LOGIC FOR THE T. SHARPER K.NOWLSON Ex Libris C. K. OGDEN LOGIC FOR THE MILLION The Origins of Popular Superstitions, Customs and Ceremonies. By T. SHARPER KNOWLSON. Ctown 8vo, 6s. net. We meet people every day who are super- stitious, but who can give no intelligent account of the origin of those beliefs that it is dangerous, for instance, to sit thirteen at table, or to break a looking-glass. To trace a habit of thinking and of action to its source is frequently to dispel an illusion ; at any rate, the interest of the search for origin has a charm all its own, and Mr. Sharper Knowlson, working on the basis of old authorities, has brought forth a mass of attractive exposition respecting popular beliefs and customs which cannot fail to secure ihe reader's attention, By the same Author, The Education of the Will. Crown 8vo, 6s. net. Can Will-power be trained ? If so, how ? These are the two main questions before Mr. Sharper Knowlson in " The Education of the Will." As a book it covers the middle ground between the erudite studies of professors of medicine and psychology on the one hand, and the extravagant literature of many " New Thought " writers on the other hand. The author's aim is to popularise the results of re- search, apd set forth in a strictly practical manner the best known methods of developing Will-power, The volume is a vigorous attempt to combine theory with practical wisdom, T. Werner Laurie, Clifford's Inn, London. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION EDITED BY T. SHARPER KNOWLSON AUTHOR OF "The Art of Thinking," "The Education of the Will," etc. LONDON T. WERNER LAURIE CLIFFORD'S INN PREFACE. THE object of the following pages is to supply the general reader with a simple text-book on logic. There are, it is true, several elementary manuals already, but the speciality of the present one lies in its illustrations of logical principles from old and new writers, and from the political and social discussions of the period. Examples in logic are usually very uninteresting in themselves, and too brief to be attractive. In Logic for the Million these faults have been remedied, and following the lead of J. W. Gilbart, F.R.S., I have endeavoured to bring the science of reasoning out of the atmo- sphere of the class-room into the arena of daily life. 20G05G8 CONTENTS PAGE INTRODUCTION I CHAPTER I. THE SPHERE OF REASONING - 9 II. THE UTILITY OF THE LOGICAL MIND 15 III. MENTAL INDEPENDENCE 20 IV. KNOWLEDGE AND REASONING - 28 V. THE RELATION OF A SUBJECT AND ITS ATTRIBUTES 34 VI. THE RELATION OF A WHOLE AND ITS PARTS - 5 VII. THE RELATION OF GENUS AND SPECIES - 57 VIII. THE RELATION OF CAUSE AND EFFECT PHYSICAL CAUSES 75 IX. MORAL CAUSES 85 X. CONDITIONAL CAUSES 101 XI. FINAL CAUSES 1 15 XII. THE USE OF WORDS IN REASONING - - 133 XIII. ON SOCRATIC DISPUTATION - - - - 142 XIV. REASONING FROM EXAMPLES - - - - 152 XV. REASONING FROM ANALOGY - - - - l6l XVI. REASONING FROM STATISTICS - - - - 171 XVII. REASONING FROM HISTORY - - - - 178 XVIII. REASONING FROM AUTHORITIES - - - 187 XIX. A STUDY IN FALLACIES igi xx. BAILEY'S RULES FOR ANALYSING ARGUMENTS - 209 XXI. CONVERSATIONAL REASONING - - - - 213 XXII. REASONING BY SIMPLE SYLLOGISM - - 22$ XXIII. REASONING BY COMPOUND SYLLOGISM - - 234 XXIV. ARGUMENTS FOR ANALYSIS - - - - 238 INTRODUCTION. MEPHISTOPHELES indulges in some merciless criti- cism of University studies, and in regard to logic thus advises a friend : " First of all attend a course of logic. There your mind will be properly drilled and laced up in the tightest of boots, so that it may henceforth slink more circumspectly along the path of thought, and not perchance will-o'-the-wisp it hither and thither through thick and thin. Then you'll be taught for many a day that what you've been in the habit of doing in a moment, as easy as eating and drinking, must have its One, Two, Three. To be sure, the manufacture of. thought is like a masterpiece of weaving where one treadle moves a thousand threads. The shuttles fly hither and thither ; the threads flow unseen ; a single stroke strikes a . thousand combinations. Your philosopher comes up and proves to you that it can't help being so. The first was;so, the second so, and hence the third and fourth were so; and if the first and second had not been there, the third and fourth would never have come to pass. The students go into ecstasies over his explanation but none of them have become weavers." Thus 2 INTRODUCTION. Goethe. Is he right or wrong? And what have others to say in the matter ? Take the latter question first. Herbert Spencer, in a letter to Professor Brough, said: "I have at no time paid the least attention to formal logic, and hold for all practical purposes it is useless." Spencer and Mephistopheles are then of the same opinion ; and to these names could be added many others. It would indeed be no difficult thing to get up a respectable case against logic as a factor in mental education ; a case with apparent reason- ableness in all its arguments, and supported by the authority of some of the greatest names in philo- sophy and literature. Such a task is naturally outside the scope of this book, but we may do well to enquire into some of the reasons which have prompted men of weight to criticise the place of logic in modern education. The chief reason lies in its seeming inutility. This is a feature specially selected for notice by Spencer in the remark just quoted. Its short-sightedness is not a little surpris- ing, for it is as if he had said, " I have found formal logic useless ; therefore other men will find it useless " an arguing from the particular to the universal. And yet when such an opinion is bol- stered up by the testimony of others, it suggests a weakness somewhere ; and that weakness we shall find in the worship of the figures of Aristotle, a worship that reduces logic to the mere analysis of other men's arguments. Logic should teach the art of reasoning; too often it is content with argu- mentative criticism. That is why expert logicians are sometimes unable to form public opinion or to INTRODUCTION. 3 lead it in logical paths. It was with a view to the correction of this error that the original author of Logic for the Million wrote his book on popular argumentation. He set his face against mere formal analysis of syllogisms; and although quite willing to admit the result was good, by reason of the critical power it engendered, he preferred to give more attention to the illustration of simple rules. His position, stated in his own words, is as follows : " A knowledge of the art of reasoning is essential to the study of the science ; but an acquaintance with the science is not necessary to the practice of the art. Indeed it is only by the use of the art that the science can be studied. We meddle not with the science. We profess not to analyse any of the powers of the mind, nor to lay down any new rules for conducting the process of reasoning. We shall attempt only to describe those rules tfiat are already known, and to apply them correctly. And we shall consider their application chiefly with reference to those things with which people are most familiar. " If a man who understands grammar hear a per- son say, ' I speaks,' he will know, from general prac- tice, that the language is improper; but he will, moreover, quote the rule, that ' a verb should agree with its nominative case in number and person.' Now, a collection of such rules form grammar, or the art of speaking correctly. So, if a man hear a person say ' All men are liars, for a man has just told me a lie,' he will know from his own common sense that this is not sound reasoning; but if he has studied logic, he will also cite the 4 INTRODUCTION. rule, ' Universals cannot be inferred from particu- lars.' Now, a collection of all these rules form logic, or the art of reasoning correctly ; and the man who has a knowledge of these rules, and is correct and ready in applying them in practice, is called a logician. A man may reason accurately without rules. But if he can give the rules, he will have more confidence in the truth of his reason- ings. He will also be better able to perceive the incorrect reasonings of others, and to show the soundness or unsoundness of any opinions pro- pounded for his consideration. " These practical rules of reasoning collected to- gether form the art of reasoning, in the same way as a collection of rules for speaking and writing with propriety form the art of speaking and writing with propriety. The one art is called logic the other art is called grammar. These two arts are useful to each other. Thoughts are expressed in words. If we think clearly we shall speak clearly, and when we are learning to arrange our words with accuracy and order, we are leaning to think with accuracy and order. " A man who has acquired a knowledge of gram- mar will afterwards speak and write grammatically, without ever thinking of the rules of grammar. So a man who has acquired a knowledge of logic, will afterwards reason logically, without ever thinking of the rules of logic. The rules will have become so deeply fixed in his mind that he will habitually reason accurately ; and by practice he will come to reason promptly and forcibly. It is the chief business both of grammar and logic to teach us INTRODUCTION. 5 how to avoid errors. Grammar teaches us how to avoid the use of words and sentences that are con- trary to its rules. But as beautiful or powerful style of writing must arise from the constitution of our own minds, or the peculiar direction of our studies, and is not to be acquired merely by an observance of grammatical construction. So logic teaches how to know and to discard bad arguments." A second objection to formal logic arises from its supposed difficulty. This, of course, is a very flimsy objection, but nevertheless it exists, and is referred to by Lord Morley in his essay, On Culture, who no doubt had in mind the attitude of the young man anxious to learn, but afraid of, the mysteries of Barbara Celarent. One must admit that a page from a text-book on formal logic is not prepossessing : it has the appearance of being very dry and uninteresting, with its circles within circles and its endless repetition of terms. Still, it is not untrue to affirm, with Mill, that logic can be learned in a few weeks; what is not true is to affirm that logic has ever been made as attractive as it can be made not even by Lewis Carroll. Readers and private students who are unaccus- tomed to scientific figures and mathematical for- mulae seem to have an instinctive dislike for logic taught by squares and circles. Put the idea into a little explanatory prose and they will study it closely. That was one of the notions of Mr. J. W. Gilbart, F.R.S., and his success certainly lends some support to his pleas for reasoning without diagrams. The third objection to formal logic has more 6 INTRODUCTION. human nature in it than sound sense : it is that professors of logic get no nearer the truth in some things than the untrained man. A body of social- ists who listen to the arguments of a professor of logic in favour of individualism reject those argu- ments with great scorn, both for the man and his science. The popular mind argues that if twenty expert logicians entertain seriously twenty different policies for social amelioration, there cannot be much good in logic as a study ; otherwise it would inevitably bring a greater unanimity of opinion. This contention is not so absurd as some people have affirmed ; for however wrong-headed it may be, it does emphasise a real fact, namely, that we are guided in our actions more by feeling than by thought : our temperaments are more than a match for our reasoning powers. That explains why Newman's logic carried him into the Roman Church; why John Stuart Mill's logic kept him an unbeliever; why Romanes' logic caused him to turn to the Anglican Church ; why Joseph McCabe's logic compelled a journey from the Roman Catholic College to the Rationalist platform ; it explains why highly intelligent men are to be found individually supporting different kinds of political policy, thoroughly convinced theirs is the only true solution of national problems. One of the greatest of all mental arts is to be able to kill prejudices and adjust emotions; and formal logic has taken little account of this fact, mainly because it is formal and unable to help itself. Here, then, comes the opportunity for a style of text-book which shall, in addition to formal INTRODUCTION. 7 rules, give some attention to other features of reasoning processes; and instead of studying abstract propositions, shall devote its attention to concrete cases, reviewing them in the light of facts as we know them, particularly the facts of human life. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION. CHAPTER I. THE SPHERE OF REASONING. IN order to show the true sphere of logic, we shall, in this chapter, briefly consider the truths with which we become acquainted by other means than reasoning. They may be classed as the truths of the senses, of consciousness, of the intellect, and of testimony. (i) Truths of the senses: The evidence of sense consists in framing a proposi- tion according to the dictates of the senses; thus we judge that grass is green ; that a trumpet gives a pleasant sound ; that fire burns wood ; water is soft ; and iron is hard ; for we have seen, heard, or felt all these. It is upon this evidence of sense that we know and believe the daily occurrences in human life ; and almost all the histories of mankind, that are written by eye or ear- witnesses, are built upon this principle. Under the evidence of sense we do not only include that knowledge which is derived to us by our outward senses of hearing, seeing, feeling, tasting, and smelling; but that also which is derived from the inward sensations and appe- tites of hunger, thirst, ease, pleasure, pain, weariness, B io LOGIC FOR THE MILLION rest, etc., and all those things which belong to the body ', as, "hunger is a painful appetite; light is pleasant; rest is sweet to weary limbs." (2) Truths of consciousness : As we learn what belongs to the body by the evidence of the senses, so we learn what belongs to the mind by an inward consciousness, which may be called a sort of internal feeling, or spiritual sensation of what passes in the mind; as, "I think before I speak; I desire large knowledge ; I suspect my own practice ; I studied hard to-day ; my conscience bears witness to my sincerity ; fear is an uneasy passion ; long meditation on one thing is tiresome." Thus it appears that we obtain the knowledge of a multitude of propositions, as well as of single ideas, by those two principles which Locke calls sensation and reflection ; one of them is a sort of consciousness of what affects the body, and the other is a consciousness of what passes in the mind. (3) Truths of the intellect : Intellect relates chiefly to those abstract propositions which carry their own evidence with them, and admit no doubt about them. Our perception of this self- evidence in any proposition is called intelligence. It is our knowledge of those first principles of truth which are, as it were, wrought into the very nature of our minds ; they are so evident in themselves to every man who attends to them, that they need no proof. It is the prerogative and peculiar excellence of these proposi- tions, that they can scarce ever be proved or denied : they cannot easily be proved, because there is nothing supposed to be more clear or certain, from which an argument may be drawn to prove them. They cannot well be denied, because their own evidence is so con- vincing, that, as soon as the terms are understood, the LOGIC FOR THE MILLION n mind necessarily assents ; such are these, " whatsoever acted hath a being ; nothing has no properties ; a part is less than the whole; nothing can be the cause of itself." These propositions are called axioms or maxims, or first principles; these are the very founda- tions of all improved knowledge and reasonings, and on that account these have been thought to be innate propositions, or truths born with us. (4) Truths of testimony : When we derive the evidence of any proposition from the testimony of others, it is called the evidence of faith; and this is a large part of our knowledge. Ten thou- sand things there are which we believe merely upon the authority or credit of those who have spoken or written of them. It is by this evidence that we know there is such a country as China, and there was such a man as Cicero, who dwelt in Rome. It is by this that most of the transactions in human life are managed : we know our parents and our kindred by this means, we know the persons and laws of our present governors, as well as things that are at a vast distance from us in fpreign nations, or in ancient ages. According as the persons that inform us of anything are many or few, or more or less wise, and faithful, and credible, so our faith is more or less firm or wavering, and the proposi- tion believed is either certain or doubtful ; but in matters of faith, an exceeding great probability is called a moral certainty.* * Mr. Bailey observes: "In philosophical strictness, we can be said to know only these things which we perceive, or have perceived, through our organs of sense, and those states of mind or mental events of which we are or have been conscious. Other things we believe on evidence more or less cogent; that is to say, they are matters of inference." If so, the truths of testimony will have to be classed under truths of inference. But the word know is often used in a more extended sense. 12 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION The truths of reasoning are distinct from all these. They are derived from these truths, or similar truths, by natural and just methods of argumentation. As logic is the art of reasoning, it has nothing to do with those truths that are self-evident, or which are known to be true without reasoning. The positive tendency of the senses supercedes the necessity for reasoning.* If you have toothache, or gout, you want no logic to prove to you that you suffer pain. And as we know what passes without us, by the organs of hearing and seeing and what passes in our bodies, by means of our sensations so we know what passes in our minds, by means of consciousness. We know that we think that we judge that we remember. We know that we hope and we fear we love and we hate. All these, and a variety of other operations and feelings, pass within our minds; and we want no logic to convince us of their existence. There are also many other truths that are self-evident. We know that two and two make four that a part of anything is less than the whole that a cause must precede the effect and that a proposition cannot be both true and not true at the same time, and in the same respect. These are called first truths, or truths of intuition. They are wrought into our very nature, and we cannot disbelieve them if we would. If we meet a man who denies them, we do not reason with him. We conclude either that he does not understand the meaning of * Such a statement needs guarding from misapprehension, for in scientific experiments observation must be more than the mere seeing: it is observation with inference. [ED.] LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 13 the words, or that he has lost his reasoning facul- ties. As logic is merely the art of reasoning, it follows that it has nothing to do with those mental operations in which we do not reason. The mere giving or receiving of information is not reasoning. If you say to a friend, " It is a cold day," there is no logic in that. But if you say, " I think we shall have rain in the course of the day," that is a logical conclusion ; and if asked to do, you should be pre- pared to give reasons for your opinion. So the acquisition of knowledge by reading or hearing is not reasoning. You may possibly read history or biography, learn several languages, and become acquainted with botany, natural history, and several sciences, without reasoning. All this requires nothing more than a good memory. And hence it is possible to become a very learned man and yet not be a logician. But if you begin to reason about anything you learn, you immediately become a logician. Take, for illustration, a case in history. You have read the life of Napoleon Bonaparte, and you remember all the events recorded, and also the opinions of the historian. You are no logician here. But if you stop to ask if any particular event be true if you inquire whether in certain actions he evinced sagacity or courage and consider what were the effects of his course on the state of Europe as soon as you commence to discuss these or any similar questions, you become a logician. Logic has no province of its own. If you reason at all you must reason about something, and that something may belong to any one of the arts or 14 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION sciences. There is no object in nature, nor any fact in history, but what may become a subject of argument. Thus, while logic as an art has no domain of its own, it has a province in every other domain or rather, it is called in whenever necessary to settle disputes and exercise supremacy in all the other departments of human knowledge. A judge on circuit has no property in the county in which he administers justice, nor any authority over its population. But should any estates in the county become the subject of litigation, or any person become a party in a civil or criminal proceeding, then are they immediately brought under his juris- diction. So whenever any difference in opinion arises either in the arts and sciences or in ordinary life, it is the province of logic to adjust the dispute. Thus every object in nature, every feeling of the mind, and every event in history, may become connected with a logical process. CHAPTER II. THE UTILITY OF THE LOGICAL MIND. WHEN men reason about things they understand, they generally reason well. But sometimes they reason ill ; and it is the business of the art of reason- ing to show them why, and to teach them how to reason well. Such an art cannot be otherwise than useful. And when we recollect that much of our health, our success in business, our happiness, our reputation in the world, and our usefulness to others, will depend upon the soundness of our reasonings, the art will appear to us to be of very high importance. We shall point out a few respects in which it is useful 1 . (i) It assists in the formation of intelligent opinion. You talk, of course, about a great many things. You talk about yourself; about your friends and relations, and acquaintances; about your trade and profession ; about the accidents and offences you read of in the newspaper; about public measures and public men ; about France, and Russia, and America, and other nations ; about right and wrong ; justice and injustice ; wealth and poverty ; slavery and liberty ; and on Sundays, if not on other days, you will talk about religion, or at least about the 16 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION church and the parson, and about people who are supposed to be religious. Now, upon all these subjects, and a variety of others, you will probably give opinions, and most likely very correct opinions, provided you talk only of what you understand. But to guard against giving incorrect or unguarded opinions, you may as well take a lesson or two upon the right way of reasoning. You will say that you can do all this without the aid of logic. So you can. But logic will teach you how to do it better. Logic will teach you that you must form your opinions by reason alone, without any bias from your passions or feelings. Logic will teach you that you must be able to give a reason for all the opinions you entertain. Logic will teach you that you must look at both sides of the question, and examine the arguments that can be advanced against any opinion, as well as those that may be advanced in its favour; and that you must weigh these arguments, and see which side preponderates. Logic will teach you that after having done this, you must be ready to admit any new facts or arguments that may appear on either side of the question. In these various ways a knowledge of the art of reasoning will be useful to yourself. By thus examining the reasons for your opinions you will soon learn to distinguish between good reasons and bad ones. You will get into the prac- tice of using good reasons and discarding bad ones. You will acquire the habit of reasoning well, and when assailed with bad reasons you will know how to refute them. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 17 (2) The second benefit lies in the aid it renders to the powers of debate. You may have to defend your opinions against the attacks of those who hold contrary opinions. You must not hesitate to do this when the cause of truth or of justice requires it. When your own charac- ter or that of your friends, or your political or religious principles are assailed, you are bound to make resistance, and it will be useful to be able to do it well. The political and religious differences that exist among mankind are by no means to be deplored as unmingled evils. They serve to awaken the nobler feelings of the mind, and to maintain attention to principles that might otherwise be for- gotten. They stimulate the intellectual powers, and impart an energy to all the faculties and to all the operations of the mind. To engage in contro- versy does not imply that you are to vituperate the person, misrepresent the opinions, or calumniate the character of your opponents. You will be less liable to fall into these practices if you understand the art of reasoning. You will then have no occa- sion for these ignoble weapons. You will be con- scious that the force of truth and the power of logic will have much greater effect in defeating your antagonists. (3) The third benefit is also individual : it lies in the ability to control passion and prevent it from warping the judgment. In a curious but learned book on " Man's Power over Himself to prevent or control Insanity," I find the following: i8 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION " The registers of the Bicetre, for a series of years, show that even when madness affects those who belong to the educated classes, it is chiefly seen in those whose education has been imperfect or irregular, and very rarely indeed in those whose minds have been fully, equally, and systematically exercised. Priests, artists, painters, sculptors, poets, and musicians, whose professions so often appear marked in that register, are often persons of very limited or exclusive education ; their faculties have been unequally exercised ; they have com- monly given themselves up too much to imagina- tion, and have neglected comparison, and have not habitually exercised the judgment. Even of this class it is to be remembered that it is commonly those of the lowest order of the class, in point of talent, who become thus affected; whilst of natu- ralists, physicians, chemists, and geometricians, it is said not one instance occurs in these registers. If one go from individual to individual in any lunatic establishment, and investigate the character and origin of the madness of each, we shall find for every one who has become insane from the exercise of his mind, at least a hundred have become insane from the undue indulgence of their feelings. Those men who really most exercise the faculties of their minds, meaning thereby all their faculties, their attention, reflection, or comparison, as well as their imagination and memory, are least liable to insanity. An irregular and injudicious cultiva- tion of poetry and painting has often concurred to produce madness, but nothing is rarer than to find a mad mathematician ; for, as no study demands LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 19 more attenion than mathematics, so it secures the student, during a great part of his time, from the recurrence of feelings which are always the most imperious in those who are the least occupied." But there is a sense in which the benefit of a study of reasoning is not merely individual : it is social. Truth is always attainable to an approxi- mate degree not truth for the one alone, but for the many. Ought we not therefore to consider a knowledge of logic to be an acquisition, the pos- session of which we owe to the community ? If a slovenly personal appearance is a sign that we have no self-respect as well as no respect for others, surely a slovenly mental habit is alike an insult to ourselves and to society. CHAPTER III. MENTAL INDEPENDENCE. To reason well we must avoid prejudices or p re- judgments judgments formed before we begin to reason. Watts divides prejudices into four classes prejudices arising from things, from words, from ourselves, and from others. We shall follow his observations on two dispositions, which those who wish to reason well ought to cultivate. We mean the love of truth, and a spirit of mental indepen- dence. (i) The love of truth: Search for evidence of truth with diligence and honesty, and be heartily ready to receive evidence, whether for agreement or disagreement of ideas. Search with diligence; spare no labour in searching for the truth in due proportion to the importance of the proposi- tion. Read the best authors who have written on that subject ; debate the matter with your friends ; and be not unwilling to borrow hints from the meanest person, nor to receive any glimpse of light from the most illiterate. Search carefully for the evidence of truth, and dig for wisdom as for hid treasure. Above all be honest, and develop a sincere impartiality to find the truth. Watch against every temptation that might bribe your judg- ment or warp It aside. Do not indulge yourself to wish any unexamined proposition were true or false. A wish 20 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 21 often perverts the judgment, and tempts the mind strangely to believe upon slight evidence whatsoever we wish to be true or false. . . . Be ready always to hear what may be objected even against your favourite opinions, and those which have had longer possession of your assent. And if there should be any new and incontrovertible evidence brought against these old or beloved sentiments, part with any- thing for the sake of truth : remember when you over- come an error you gain truth; the victory is on your side, and the advantage is all your own. . . . Let not a party spirit, nor any passion or prejudice whatsoever, stop or avert the current of your reasoning in quest of true knowledge. When you are inquiring therefore into any subject, maintain a due regard to the arguments and objections on both sides of a question. Consider, compare, and balance them well, before you determine for one side. It is a frequent, but a very faulty prac- tice, to hunt after arguments only to make good one side of a question, and entirely to neglect and refuse those which favour the other side. If we have not given a due weight to arguments on both sides, we do but wilfully misguide our judgment and abuse our reason, by forbidding its search after truth. When we espouse opinions by a secret bias on the mind, through the in- fluences of fear, hope, honour, credit, interest, or any other prejudice, and then seek arguments only to support those opinions, we have neither done our duty to God nor to ourselves; and it is a matter of mere chance if we stumble upon truth in our way to ease and prefer- ment. (2) The spirit of mental independence. (a) Independence of mind implies a right use of the principle of authority, neither rely- ing on it blindly nor discrediting it as un- worthy of consideration. 22 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION " To believe in all things as our predecessors did, is the ready way to keep mankind in an everlasting state of infancy, and to lay an eternal bar against all the im- provements of our reason and our happiness. Had the present age of philosophers satisfied themselves with the substantial forms and occult qualities of Aristotle, with the solid spheres, eccentrics, and epicycles of Pto- n lemy, and the ancient astronomers ; then the great Lord^ ' Bacon, Copernicus, and Descartes, with the greater Sir i ^r> Isaac N e wton , Locke, and Boyle, had risen in our world ' in vain. We must have blundered on still in successive Jf^ene rations, among absurdities and thick darkness, and - x a hundred useful inventions for the happiness of human life had never been known." So Dr. Watts : and he is right for the most part. But there is another side to the question. We have dealt with it in another place. (b) Independence of mind implies exemption from the influence of the passions : The various passions or affections of the mind are numerous and endless springs of prejudice. They dis- guise every object they converse with, and put their own colours upon it, and thus lead the judgment astray from truth. It is love that makes the mother think her own child the fairest, and will sometimes persuade us that a blemish is beauty. Hope and desire make an hour of delay seem as long as two or three hours ; hope inclines us to think there is nothing too difficult to be attempted ; despair tells us that a brave attempt is mere rashness, and that every difficulty is insurmountable. Fear makes us imagine that a bush shaken with the wind has some savage beast in it, and multiplies the dangers that attend our path. . . . Sorrow and melancholy tempt us to think our circumstances much more dismal than they are, that we may have some excuse for mourning ; and envy represents the condition of our neighbour better than it is, that there may be some pretence for her own LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 23 vexation and uneasiness. Anger, and wrath, and re- venge, and all those hateful passions, excite in us far worse ideas of men than they deserve, and persuade us to believe all that is ill of them. A detail of the evil in- fluence of the affections of the mind upon our judgment, would make a large volume. (c) Independence of mind implies exemption from the influence of constitutional infirmi- ties : The credulous man is ready to receive everything for truth that has but a shadow of evidence; every new book that he reads, and every ingenious man with whom he converses, has power enough to draw him into the sentiments of the speaker or writer. He has so much complaisance in him, or weakness of soul, that he is ready to resign his own opinion to the first objection which he hears, and to receive any sentiments of another that are asserted with a positive air and much assurance. The man of contradiction is of a contrary humour, for he stands ready to oppose everything that is said : he gives a slight attention to the reasons of other men, from an inward scornful presumption that they have no strength in them. When he reads or hears a discourse different from his own sentiments, he does not give him- self leave to consider whether that discourse may be true ; but employs all his powers immediately to confute it. Your great disputers and your men of controversy, are in continual danger of this sort of prejudice : they contend often for victory, and will maintain whatsoever they have asserted, while truth is lost in the noise and tumult of reciprocal contradictions; and it frequently happens, that a debate about opinions is turned into a mutual reproach of persons. . . . Another sort of temper that is very injurious to a right judgment of things, is an inconstant, fickle, changeable spirit, and a very uneven temper of mind. When such 24 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION persons are in one humour, they pass a judgment of things agreeable to it ; when their humour changes, they reverse their first judgment, and embrace a new opinion. They have no steadiness of soul; they want firmness of mind sufficient to establish themselves in any truth, and are ready to change it for the next alluring false- hood that is agreeable to their change of humour. This fickleness is sometimes so mingled with their very con- stitution by nature, or by distemper of body, that a cloudy day and lowering sky shall strongly incline them to form an opinion both of themselves, and of persons and things round about them, quite different from what they believe when the sun shines, and the heavens are serene. This sort of people ought to judge of things and per- sons in their most sedate, peaceful, and composed hours of life, and reserve these judgments for their conduct at more unhappy seasons. (d) Independence of mind implies exemption from the influence of manner: There is another tribe of prejudices which is near akin to those of authority, and that is, when we receive a doctrine because of the manner in which it is proposed to us by others. I have already mentioned the power- ful influence that oratory and fine words have to in- sinuate a false opinion, and sometimes truth is refused, and suffers contempt in the lips of a wise man, for want of the charms of language : but there are several other manners of proposals, whereby mistaken sentiments are powerfully conveyed into the mind. Some persons are easily persuaded to believe what another dictates with a positive air, and a great degree of assurance : they feel the overbearing force of a confi- dent dictator, especially if he be of a superior rank or character to themselves. Some are quickly convinced of the truth of any doc- LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 25 trine, when he that proposes it puts on all the airs of piety, and makes solemn appeals to heaven, and protes- tations of the truth of it : the pious mind of a weaker Christian is ready to receive anything that is pronounced with such an awful solemnity. It is a prejudice near akin to this, when a humble man is frighted into any particular sentiments of religion, because a man of great name or character pronounces heresy upon the contrary sentiments, casts the disbeliever out of the church, and forbids him the gates of heaven. Others are allured into particular opinions by gentler practices on the understanding; not only the soft tempers of mankind, but even hardy and rugged souls, are sometimes led away captives to error by the soft air of address, and the sweet and engaging methods of persuasion and kind- ness. There is another manner of proposing our own opinion, or rather opposing the opinions of others, which demands a mention here, and that is when persons make a jest serve instead of an argument; when they refute what they call error by a turn of wit, and answer every objection against their own sentiments, by casting a sneer upon the objector. These scoffers practise with success upon weak and cowardly spirits : such as have not been well established in religion or morality, have been laughed out of the best principles by a confident buffoon ; they have yielded up their opinions to a witty banter. There is no way to cure these evils in such a degenerate world as we live in, but by learning to dis- tinguish well between the substance of any doctrine, and the manner of address, either in proposing, attacking, or defending it ; and then by setting a just and severe guard of reason and conscience over all the exercises of our judgment, resolving to yield to nothing but the con- vincing evidence of truth. (e) Independence of mind implies exemption from the influence of association : A court lady, born and bred up amongst pomp and c 26 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION equipage, and the vain notions of birth and quality, con- stantly joins and mixes all these with the idea of her- self, and she imagines these to be essential to her nature, and as it were necessary to her being : thence she is tempted to look upon menial servants, and the lowest rank of mankind, as another species of beings, quite dis- tinct from herself. A ploughboy, who has never tra- velled beyond his own village, and has seen nothing but thatched houses and his parish church, is naturally led to imagine that thatch belongs to the very nature of a house, and that that must be a church which is built of stone, and especially if it has a spire upon it. A child whose uncle has been excessively kind, and his school- master very severe, easily believes that kindness always belongs to uncles, and that severity is essential to mas- ters or instructors. He has seen also soldiers with red coats, or ministers with long black gowns, and there- fore he persuades himself that these garbs are essential to the characters, and that he is not a minister who has not a long black gown, nor can he be a soldier who is not dressed in red. It would be well if all such mistakes ended with childhood. . . . When we have just reason to admire a man for his virtues, we are sometimes in- clined not only to neglect his weaknesses, but even to put a good colour upon them, and to think them amiable. When we read a book that has many excellent truths in it, we are tempted to approve not only that whole book, but even all the writings of that author. When a poet, an orator, or a painter, has performed admirably in several illustrious pieces, we sometimes also admire his very errors, we mistake his blunders for beauties, and are so ignorant as to copy them. . . . This sort of prejudice is relieved by learning to distin- guish things well, and not to judge in the lump. There is scarce anything in the world of nature or art, In the world of morality or religion, that is perfectly uniform. There is a mixture of wisdom and folly, vice and virtue, good and evil, both in men and things. We should re- LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 27 member that some persons have great wit and little judg- ment; others are judicious, but not witty. Some are good-humoured without compliment ; others have all the formalities of complaisance, but no good-humour. We ought to know that one man may be vicious and learned, while another has virtue without learning. That many a man thinks admirably well, who has a poor utterance; while others have a charming manner of speech, but their thoughts are trifling and impertinent. Some are good neighbours, and courteous and charitable toward men, who have no religion ; others are truly religious, but of morose natural tempers. Some excellent sayings are found in very silly books, and some silly thoughts appear in books of value. We should neither praise nor dispraise by wholesale, but separate the good from the evil, and judge of them apart ; the accuracy of a good judgment consists much in making such distinctions. .CHAPTER IV. KNOWLEDGE AND REASONING. (i) To reason well, you must understand the sub- jects that you reason about. Go to the market-place, and listen to the con- versation between the buyers and sellers. How readily the sellers advance arguments to show that their goods are very cheap, and how promptly the buyers answer these arguments, and strongly argue on the other side. Now how is it that these unedu- cated people are enabled to argue so forcibly and so fluently? It is that they understand what they are talking about. And this must be the first step in all our reasonings. We begin, therefore, by stating clearly what is the subject of discussion, and this is called giving a definition of it : In order to form a definition of anything, we must put forth these three acts of the mind. First, Compare the thing to be defined with other things that are most like itself, and see wherein its essence or nature agrees with them : and this is called the general nature or genus in a definition : so if you would define what wine is, first compare it with other things like itself, as cider, perry, etc., and you will find it agrees essentially with them in this, that it is a sort of juice. Secondly, Consider the 28 29 most remarkable and primary attribute, property, or idea wherein this thing differs from those other things that are most like it ; and that is its essential or specific differ- ence : so wine differs from cider and perry, and all other juices, in that it is pressed from a grape. This may be called its special nature, which distinguishes it from other juices. Thirdly, Join the general and special nature together, or (which is all one) the genus and the difference, and these make up a definition. So the juice of a grape, or juice pressed from grapes, is the defini- tion of wine. So if I would define what winter is, I consider first wherein it agrees with other things which are most like it, namely, summer, spring, autumn, and I find they are all seasons of the year; therefore a season of the year is the genus. Then I observe wherein it differs from these, and that is in the shortness of the days ; for it is this which does primarily distinguish it from other sea- sons ; therefore this may be called its special nature, or its difference. Then by joining these together, 1 make a definition. Winter is that season of the year wherein the days are shortest. But everything cannot be defined in this formal manner, and we may adopt any mode of expression we please, provided it will convey to others a correct description of what we mean. Thus we may say Motion is a change of place. Swiftness is the passing over a long space in a short time. A natural day is the time of one alternate revolution of light and darkness, or it is the duration of twenty-four hours. An eclipse of the sun is a defect in the sun's transmission of light to us by the moon interposing. Snow is congealed vapour. Hail is congealed rain. An island is a piece of land rising above the surrounding water. A hill is an elevated part of the earth, and a grove is a piece of ground thick set with trees. A triangle is a figure com- 30 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION posed of three sides. A king is the chief ruler in a king- dom. Veracity is the conformity of our words to our thoughts. Murder is the unlawful killing of a man. Natural philosophy is the knowledge of the properties of bodies, and the various effects of them, or it is the know- ledge of the various appearances in nature, and their causes. (2) To reason well, you must clearly understand what is asserted about the subject. A proposition is a sentence wherein two or more ideas or terms are joined or disjoined by one affirmation or negation; as, " Plato was a philosopher: every angle is formed by two lines meeting : no man living on earth can be completely happy." When there are two or more ideas or terms in the sentence, and they are joined or disjoined merely by one single affirmation or negation, they are properly called but one proposition, though they may be resolved into several propositions which are implied therein, as will appear hereafter. There are three things which go to the nature and con- stitution of a proposition ; namely, the subject, the pre- dicate, and the copula. The subject of a proposition is that concerning which anything is affirmed or denied : So " Plato, angle, man living on earth," are the subjects of the foregoing pro- positions. The predicate is that which is affirmed or denied of the subject : so " philosopher " is the predicate of the first proposition; " formed by two lines meeting," is the predicate of the second; " capable of being completely happy," the proper predicate of the third. The subject and predicate of a proposition taken to- gether, are called the matter of it; for these are the materials of which it is made. The copula is the form of a proposition ; it represents the act of the mind affirming or denying, and it is ex- LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 31 pressed by the words, am, art, is, are, etc. ; or am not, art not, is not, are not, etc. The subject and predicate of a proposition, are not always to be known and distinguished by the placing of the words in the sentence, but by reflecting duly on the sense of the words, and on the mind or design of the speaker or writer : as if I say, " In Africa there are many lions," I mean many lions are existent in Africa : " many lions " is the subject, and " existent in Africa " is the predicate. "It is proper for a philosopher to understand geometry " : here the word " proper " is the predicate, and all the rest is the subject, except " is," the copula. But there are some propositions, wherein the terms of the subject and predicate seem to be the same ; yet the ideas are not the same ; nor can these be called pure, identical, or trifling propositions ; such as, Home is home ; that is, home is a convenient or delight- ful place ; Socrates is Socrates still : that is, the man Socrates is still a philosopher; The hero was not a hero ; that is, the hero did not show his courage ; What I have written, I have written ; that is, what I wrote I still approve and will not alter it : What is done, is done ; that is, it cannot be undone. It may be easily observed in these propositions the term is equivocal, for in the predicate it has a different idea from what it has in the subject. (3) To reason well, you must know the meanings of words and their relation to habits of thought. A separate section having been devoted to this topic (see p. 133), there is no need to deal with it here. (4) Practice is the secret of success. Accustom yourselves to clear and distinct ideas, to evident propositions, to strong and convincing argu- ments. Converse much with those friends, and those 32 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION books, and those parts of learning, where you meet with the greatest clearness of thought and force of reasoning. The mathematical sciences, and particularly arithmetic, geometry, and mechanics, abound with these advan- tages : and if there were nothing valuable in them for the uses of human life, yet the very speculative parts of this sort of learning are well worth our study ; for by per- petual examples they teach us to conceive with clear- ness, to connect our ideas and propositions in a train of dependence, to reason with strength and demonstration, and to distinguish between truth and falsehood. Some- thing of these sciences should be studied by every man who pretends to learning, and that, as Locke expresses it, not so much to make us mathematicians, as to make us reasonable creatures. We should gain such a fami- liarity with evidence of perception and force of reason- ing, and get such a habit of discerning clear truths, that the mind may be soon offended with obscurity and con- fusion : then we shall, as it were, naturally and with ease restrain our minds from rash judgment, before we attain just evidence of the proposition which is offered to us : and we shall with the same ease, and, as it were, natu- rally seize and embrace every truth that is proposed with just evidence. This habit of conceiving clearly, of judging justly, and of reasoning well, is not to be attained merely by the happiness of constitution, the brightness of genius, the best natural parts, or the best collection of logical precepts. It is custom and practice that must form and establish this habit. We must apply ourselves to it till we perform all this readily, and without reflecting on rules. A coherent thinker, and a strict reasoner, is not to be made at once by a set of rules, any more than a good painter or musician may be formed extempore, by an excellent lecture on music or painting. It is of in- finite importance, therefore, in our younger years, to be taught both the value and the practice of conceiving clearly and reasoning right ; for when we are grown up LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 33 lo the middle of life, or past it, it Is no wonder that we should not learn good reasoning any more than that an ignorant clown should not be able to learn fine lan- guage, dancing, or a courtly behaviour, when his rustic airs have grown up with him till the age of forty. CHAPTER V. THE RELATION OF A SUBJECT AND ITS ATTRIBUTES. BY attribute we mean a quality or property that can be ascribed to some person or thing; by subject we mean that to which the attribute is ascribed. Take an illustration from English grammar. A substantive or noun is the name of any person, place, or thing; and an adjective is a word added to the substantive or noun to denote its quality. Now, instead of using the words substantive and adjective, use subject and attribute, and you will get a good idea of what we have to talk about in this section. Of course, attribute has a more exten- sive meaning than adjective: every adjective denotes an attribute, but sometimes an attribute is expressed by a verb, a particle, or by several words put together. Often, too, an adjective united to a substantive will become a subject. When you say "a wily man," the word man denotes the subject, and wiliness is the attribute. But when you say "a wily man is frequently unscrupulous," the words, "wily man," become the subject, and the remaining phrase is the attribute. Whatever you talk about is a subject, and what you say about it is an attribute, real or affirmed. Some attributes are called specific. They belong to the subject, 34 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 35 and to no other subject. These are attributes chiefly that distinguish one class or species from others. Thus man is called a rational animal. Rationality is the specific attribute that dis- tinguishes him from other animals. The specific attribute is called by logicians a specific difference. Other attributes are called common. They are essential to the subject, but they belong also to other subjects. Thus, it is an attribute of gold to be yellow. If a metal is not yellow, it is not gold. But other things are yellow besides gold. The colour yellow is an attribute common to many subjects. These common attributes are called properties. Other attributes are accidental. What- ever attribute can be removed from the subject without destroying the subject, is considered to be accidental. A hat may be white, or black, or made of beaver, silk, or straw ; these are accidental attri- butes, for they all might be changed, and yet the subject remain a hat. These attributes are called accidents. This relation of subject and attribute is a very extensive one. Almost everything we see, or hear, or know, is a subject, and has some kind of attributes. The usual way in which we define or describe anything is by an enumeration of its attributes. We shall here adduce a few proposi- tions expressing this relation, and then we shall show how this relation is employed in reasoning. (a) Newman's definition of a Gentleman. Hence it is that it is almost a definition of a gentle- man to say he is one who never inflicts pain. This de- scription is both refined, and, as far as it goes, accurate. He is mainly occupied in merely removing the obstacles 36 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION which hinder the free and unembarrassed action of those about him ; and he concurs with their movements rather than takes the initiative himself. His benefits may be considered as parallel to what are called comforts or conveniences in arrangements of a personal nature : like an easy chair or a good fire, which do their part in ex- pelling cold and fatigue, though nature provides both means of rest and animal heat without them. The true gentleman, in like manner, carefully avoids whatever may cause a jar or a jolt in the minds of those with whom he is cast all clashing of opinion, or collision of feel- ing, all restraint, or suspicion, or gloom, or resentment ; his great concern being to make everyone at their ease and at home. He has his eyes on all his company, he is tender towards the bashful, gentle towards the distant, and merciful towards the absurd. (b) Herbert Spencer on " Style." The ideal is "to so present ideas that they may be apprehended with the least possible mental effort." Re- garding language as an apparatus of symbols for the conveyance of thought, we may say that as in a mechani- cal apparatus, the more simple and the better arranged its parts, the greater will be the effect produced. In either case, whatever force is absorbed by the machine is deducted from the result. A reader or listener has at each moment but a limited amount of mental power avail- able. To recognise and interpret the symbols presented to him requires part of this power : to arrange and com- bine the images suggested requires a further part : and only that part which remains can be used for realising the thought conveyed. Hence, the more time and atten- tion it takes to receive and understand each sentence, the less time and attention can be given to the central idea; and the less vividly will that idea be conceived. Turning our attention to a different class of sub- LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 37 ject, we find the sum total of attributes more exact, in the sense of being capable of proof. (c) Biology. Biology is that branch of knowledge which treats of organised beings, or animals and plants, including their morphology, physiology, origin or development, and dis- tribution. (d) Blackstone on " Law." Every law may be said to consist of several parts ; one, declaratory whereby the rights to be observed and the wrongs to be eschewed, are clearly denned and laid down; another, directory whereby the subject is in- structed and enjoined to observe those rights, and to abstain from the commission of those wrongs; a third, remedial whereby a method is pointed out to recover a man's private rights, or redress his private wrongs : to which may be added a fourth, usually termed the sanc- tion or vindicatory part of the law, whereby it is signi- fied what evil or penalty shall be incurred by such as commit any public wrongs and transgress or neglect their duty. These examples will serve to show how it is impossible to carry on even an ordinary conversa- tion without the use of attributive phrases; whilst to conduct an argument means the close and rea- soned use of such phrases. When Disraeli, in a humorous vein, desired to set out the attributes of a good novel, he said : " Take a pair of pistols and a pack of cards, a cookery book and a set of new quadrilles; mix them up with half an intrigue and a whole marriage, and divide into three equal portions."* The university professor, on the other * Referring, of course, to the three-volume novel. 38 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION hand, in true academical style, would argue the question from the broad basis of art, the function of literature, the qualities of good narrative, and a host of other items. But the capacity to deal with attributes in relation to subject is one of the first that should be developed. (1) From the presence of the subject we infer the presence of the attribute. It was said by a wise man that " a fool uttereth all his mind : but a wise man keepeth it in till afterwards." If, then, the man who rides to town with you every morning be a fool, he will utter all his mind. Generally he does, and having loqua- ciously turned his brain inside out, dropping all its secrets on the floor of the compartment for every- body to inspect, he invites you to do likewise; and when you decline, he calls you a snob, for to him no thoughts should be private property : he is an out-and-out socialist. Arguments of this kind are often expressed in a conditional form. Thus we say : If this be a magnet, it will attract iron ; if he be an honest man, he will pay his debts; if the current is on the " live " wire, it will be dangerous; if we sow wheat, we reap wheat. (2) From the presence of the specific attribute, or of all the common attributes, we infer the presence of the subject. You will observe that this rule is the reverse of the former. In the former case we said : This is LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 39 a good tree; therefore it will bear good fruit. In the present case we say : This tree bears good fruit ; therefore it is a good tree. So, if we should find a metal having all the common attributes of gold, we should know that it is gold. This prin- ciple is of great use in chemical experiments. Thus, we know that certain bodies have certain affinities for other bodies. To ascertain, therefore, whether this body be present in any compound substance, we add some body, for which the body, whose presence we wish to detect, has an affinity, or upon which it produces a known effect. There are certain chemical tests which are in constant use in such cases. Thus, the presence of the specific attribute shows the presence of the subject. So, if an auctioneer had to sell a house, he would enumerate all its attributes, in order to show that it is a most agreeable residence. The projector of a new company enumerates all its attributes, in order to show that its shares would turn out a most profitable investment. A candidate for a seat in the House of Commons states all his attributes, in order to prove that he would be a most valuable member. To enable you to infer from a single attribute the presence of the subject, that attribute must be a specific attribute; that is, it must belong to no other subject. (See p. 41.) Thus, if it be an attribute of an express train on any railway, that it does not stop at the intermediate stations, you may say: "This train does not stop at the inter- mediate stations;" therefore, "this train is an express train." Here, from the presence of the attribute, we infer the presence of the subject. But! 40 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION mind, if there are other trains besides the express trains that do not stop at the intermediate stations, this conclusion may not be correct. For then the attribute is no longer a specific attribute, but a common attribute. And from the presence of an attribute that is common to several subjects you cannot infer the presence of any particular subject. All you can do is to infer the presence of either one or other of the subjects. Thus, " The express trains and the mail trains are the only trains that do not stop at this station. The train which has just passed has not stopped at this station ; there- fore, the train which has just passed is either an express train or a mail train." But in conformity with the first rule you may always, from the presence of the subject, infer the presence of the attributes, even though the same attributes may belong to other subjects. Thus you may say : None of the express trains stops at the intermediate stations. The train that leaves at three o'clock is an express train ; therefore, it will not stop at the intermediate stations. (3) From the absence of the subject we infer the absence of its specific attribute. Here are some instances : This animal is not a human being ; therefore he is not endowed with rational intelligence. This man is not an educated man ; therefore he is not qualified to be a teacher. This man has had no military training ; therefore he is unfit to lead a large army. Jones has an impediment in his speech; therefore he is unfitted for public speaking. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 41 But although the absence of a subject shows the absence of its specific attribute, it does not prove the absence of any of its common attributes or properties. For these attributes belong also to other subjects. Thus, honesty is an item in the code of religion; but we cannot say that if a man is not a religious man he is not an honest man, for a man may be honest and yet be destitute of religion. (4) From the absence of an essential attribute we infer the absence of the subject. This rule is the reverse of the last, where the process was to say : This is not a good tree ; there- fore it will not bear good fruit. By the present rule we should say : This tree does not bear good fruit; therefore it is not a good tree. So thought is an attribute of mind; and since matter cannot think, we infer that matter is not mind. Again, it is an attribute of matter to be divisible; but mind is not divisible; hence we infer that mind is not matter. (5) If any two attributes may be ascribed to the same subject, then we may infer that these two attributes are not inconsistent with each other. Sir Isaac Newton was a great philosopher, and also a man of strong religious principle; hence we infer that philosophy is not incompatible with religion. Sir Robert Peel had a taste for the fine arts, he was also a good man of business; hence we infer that a taste for the fine arts is not incom- 42 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION patible with habits of business. Sir Thomas Powell Buxton was a very benevolent man, and yet a great sportsman ; and hence we infer that benevolent feelings are not incompatible with a fondness for field-sports. Writers on scholastic logic repeat the subject in this kind of argument so as to form two proposi- tions, which they usually place under one another, and the conclusion under them ; and these three propositions taken together they call a syllogism ; thus Sir Robert Peel had a taste for the fine arts. Sir Robert Peel was a good man of business. Therefore, a taste for the fine arts is not incom- patible with habits of business. Here are three more examples. (a) All who assist in the progress of true science deserve the respect of mankind. All who assist in the progress of true science have to contend with difficulties. Some who have to contend with difficulties deserve the respect of mankind. (b) Some distinguished poets have not escaped poverty. All distinguished poets do honour to their country. Some who do honour to their country have not escaped poverty. (c) No bombastic writers are worthy of imitation. Some bombastic writers are amusing. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 43 Some things amusing are not worthy of imita- tion.* This mode of reasoning may also be expressed in the form of example, thus: "A taste for the fine arts is not incompatible with habits of business. In proof of this we may cite the example of Sir Robert Peel." "Some who do honour to their country have not escaped poverty, which is proved by the history of some of our distinguished poets." "A very interesting book may consist chiefly of quotations. Witness DTsraeli's ' Curiosities of Literature' ' The following are instances of the same kind of argument expressed in a different form : " The example of Virgil shows that a great poet may be seduced into some faults by the prac- tice of imitation." " A man remarkable for his knowledge and policy, the wisdom of his maxims, the justness of his reasoning, and the variety, dis- tinctness, and strength of his characters, may want exactness in his diction, and be careless in the art of writing, for we find all these qualities united in Lord Clarendon." You will observe that this argument must not be pushed too far. It does not prove that either of the two attributes is the cause of the other; or that they always, or even often, accompany one another; but merely that they are not incompatible. * These examples illustrate the third figure of syllogistic reasoning: the maxim is, " When the whole of a class pos- sess a certain attribute, and the whole or part of the class possess another attribute, then some things that possess one of these attributes possess the other also." See Bailey, p. 72. 44 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION (6) If the same attribute cannot be ascribed to two specified subjects, then we may infer that those subjects are different from each other. Thus, if the soul of man can reason, and the soul of a brute cannot reason, we infer that the soul of a man is different from the soul of a brute. If all fever produces thirst, and the patient does not suffer thirst, we infer that the patient has no fever. The following examples are taken from the Port Royal Logic: No virtue is contrary to the love of truth ; There is a love of peace which is opposed to a love of truth ; Therefore there is a love of peace which is not a virtue. Every virtue is accompanied with discretion ; There is a zeal without discretion ; Therefore there is a zeal which is not a virtue.* You will observe that these conclusions are negative. We deny that one thing is another, because the attribute can be ascribed to one of these things and not to the other. (7) If a subject have certain attributes, we infer that it is adapted for the use to which those attributes are applicable. * These examples are adduced as illustrations of the second figure of syllogistic reasoning. The maxims of this figure are, " When the whole of a class possess a certain attribute, whatever does not possess the attribute does not belong to the class; " and, "When the whole of a class is excluded from the possession of an attribute, whatever pos- sesses the attribute does not belong to the class." Bailey, p. 71. 45 From the attributes of the Isle of Wight, Tor- quay, and Penzance, we infer that those places are suitable residences for people in danger of con- sumption. From the attributes of wool, we infer that a woollen garment worn next the skin is some- times good for rheumatism. From the attributes of certain medicines, w r e endeavour to learn what are the respective complaints for which they are adapted. From the attributes of bones, lime, sea- weed, and fish, we infer that they may be usefully applied as manure to certain kinds of land. So if a man have the attributes of honesty, industry, prudence, and perseverence, we infer that he will thrive in his pursuits. If a man offers himself as a Member of Parliament, excise officer, banker's clerk, or policeman, he must show that he has those attributes which will qualify him for the discharge of his official duties. The attributes of a joint-stock bank are, that it has more than six partners, that it has an amount of paid-up capital, and that on the death or retirement of any of its partners their portion of the capital is not with- drawn, but is transferred to other parties; and hence we infer that it is a safer system of banking for the public than if the partners were no more than six, and the death or retirement of any partner would cause the withdrawal of his portion of the capital. So from the attributes of the precious metals, it was inferred that they were adapted for the purposes of coin. That medium of exchange must be best which unites in itself the largest amount of the following qualities : sameness of value both as to time and place, divisibility, 46 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION durability, and facility of transportation. The metals especially gold and silver possess all these qualities in a great degree. We may have them in tons or in grains : wear is slow; fire will not destroy them; when divided, they can be fused again and re-blended ; and, except where large values are concerned, they are easily con- veyed from place to place. Because metals possess these qualities, they were early and (in civilized countries) uni- versally adopted as a medium of exchange. (8) The presence of similar attributes in two or more subjects shows the probability of their corresponding in other attributes. This is called " reasoning by analogy," which we shall discuss more at length later on. We will here give an example. It is natural to mankind to judge of things less known by some similitude, real or imaginary, between them and things more familiar or better known. And where the things compared have really a great similitude in their nature, when there is reason to think that they are sub- ject to the same laws, there may be a considerable degree of probability in conclusions drawn from analogy. Thus we may observe a very great similitude between this earth which we inhabit, and the other planets, Saturn, Jupiter, Mars, Venus, and Mercury. They all revolve round the sun, as the earth does, although at different distances and in different periods. They borrow all their light from the sun, as the earth does. Several of them are known to revolve round their axis, like the earth ; and by that means must have a like succession of day and night. Some of them have moons that serve to give them light in the absence of the sun, as our moon does to us. They are all in their motions subject to the same law of gravitation as the earth is. From all this similitude, it is not unreasonable to think that those LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 47 planets may, like our earth, be the habitation of various orders of living creatures. (9) The presence of any attribute shows the absence of a contrary attribute. This, of course, refers only to accidental attributes, for an essential attribute cannot be absent from its subject. Thus, if the weather be hot, it is not cold ; if a man be humble he is not proud ; if avaricious, he is not liberal ; if he is gouty, he is not in good health. The presence of an accidental attribute in one instance, proves the possibility of such a subject becoming united to such an attribute in any similar case. Wisdom is the accidental attribute of a man, and therefore we are justified in inferring that a man may become wise. In the same way, wealth, learning, virtue, happiness, are attributes of man, and though not essential attributes, but only acci- dental, yet they may all be acquired- Sometimes, as we have already observed, an accidental attri- bute may be united to a subject, and form a new subject, which may have other attributes. Thus we may say " A wise man will receive instruc- tion." Here the word "wise" is not viewed as an attribute, but as with " man " forming a sub- ject, and a readiness to receive instruction is an essential attribute of a wise man. In reasoning upon the relation subsisting between subject and attribute, it is always necessary to dis- tinguish between those attributes which are essen- tial, and those which are accidental. For, if we take accidental attributes, and argue upon them 48 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION as though they were essential, our reasonings will be erroneous. Thus, the poet Ovid had a large nose. This was a mere accidental circumstance, and was by no means essential to him as a poet. If, therefore, we were to meet a man in the street with a large nose, we should not be justified in inferring that he was a poet. Some men of great minds have had feeble bodies, but it does not follow that a feeble body tends to invigorate the mind. Some men of great intellectual powers have been addicted to great vices, but it does not follow that great vices are a mark of intellect. Erroneous reasonings under this head sometimes arise from our omission to take into account some one or more of the essential attributes. A tradesman may have all the attributes of a good man of business, except that he is fond of speculation. A young woman may have all the attributes of a good wife, except sweetness of temper. A house may have all the attributes of an agreeable residence, except that the chimney smokes. A man may have all the attributes of an excellent friend, except that he cannot keep' a secret. Now, in these cases, if you had from a review of the other attributes, come to the conclusion, " That tradesman is worthy of high credit"; "That young woman would make an excellent wife "; " That house is a most agreeable residence"; "That man is a most judicious friend," you would have formed erroneous conclu- sions. The tradesman may let you in for a heavy account; the young woman may bring misery upon herself and her man for the space of fifty years; your house may cost you more than if you had LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 49 rented it; and the man who was a friend turned out to be a devil in disguise. (10) It may also happen that when we have noticed all the attributes, our judgment may be kept in suspense from the conflicting character of those attributes. If we have to hire servants, those who are most skilled may be deficient in sobriety, or, if not deficient in sobriety, they may be deficient in industry, or in cleanliness. If we want a house, we cannot find one that has all the attributes we require. If we wish to emigrate, we can discover no colony exactly suited to our circumstances. In these cases we must balance the attributes one against the other. Here, a full knowledge of the subject, and plenty of common sense, are the best guides. The rules of logic, however, will teach us to decide coolly and systematically. The best way is that of Franklin. Write down on paper first, all the reasons for the affirmative, and then, all the reasons for the negative. Having all the reasons thus before your eyes, weigh them deliber- ately, and see which preponderate. CHAPTER VI. THE RELATION OF A WHOLE AND ITS PARTS. (i) The things that have parts are subjects pos- sessing attributes, but attributes themselves, or most of them, have no parts. The colours green, red, and blue; the sounds loud, sharp, and shrill; the smells pleasant and unpleasant, have no parts. But all material objects can be divided into parts : we divide an animal into head, trunk, and limbs; a tree into root, stem, branches, bark, leaves, and fruit; a day into hours, minutes and seconds; a book into pages, chapters, and lines; a mile into furlongs and furlongs into yards. Watts has some interesting remarks shewing the importance of what otherwise appears an elementary feature of all knowledge. Each part taken singly must contain less than the whole, but all the parts taken collectively must contain neither more nor less than the whole. Therefore, if in discoursing of a tree you divide it into the trunk and leaves, it is an imperfect division, because the root and the branches are needful to make up the whole. In all divisions we should first consider the larger and more immediate parts of the subject, and not divide it at once into the more minute and remote parts. It would by no means be proper to divide a kingdom first into streets, and lanes, and fields ; but it must be first divided into 50 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 51 provinces or counties, then those counties may be divided into towns, villages, fields, etc. ; and towns into streets and lanes. The several parts of a division ought to be opposite, that is, one part ought not to contain another. It would be a ridiculous division of an animal into head, limbs, body, and brains, for the brains are contained in the head. Let not subdivisions be too numerous with- out necessity : for it is better many times to distinguish more parts at once, if the subject will bear it, than to mince the discourse by excessive dividing and subdivid- ing. It is preferable, therefore, in a treatise of geo- graphy, to say, that in a city we will consider its walls, its gates, its buildings, its streets, and lanes, than to divide it formally first into the encompassing and the encompassed parts; the encompassing parts are the walls and gates ; the encompassed parts include the ways and the buildings; the ways are the streets and the lanes ; buildings consist of the foundations, and the superstructure, etc. Divide every subject according to the special design you have in view. One and the same idea or subject may be divided in very different manners, according to the different purposes we have in discoursing of it. So if a printer were to consider the several parts of a book, he must divide it into sheets, the sheets into pages, the pages into lines, and the lines into letters. But a grammarian divides a book into periods, sentences, and words, or parts of speech, as noun, pronoun, verb, etc. A logician considers a book as divided into chapters, sections, arguments, propositions, ideas; and, with the help of ontology, he divides the propositions into sub- ject, object, property, relation, action, passion, cause, and effect. But it would be very ridiculous for a logician to divide a book into sheets, pages, and lines; or for a printer to divide it into nouns and pronouns, or into pro- positions, ideas, properties, or causes. In all your divi- sions observe with greatest exactness the nature of things. 52 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION By way of illustration one may refer to the relics of the cross of Christ found in many Continental churches. If the wood so regarded were gathered together and weighed, it would be found to total an avoirdupois far in excess of that carried by the Cyrenian. Hence we infer that some of these relics cannot be genuine, in spite of the testimony of tradition and the veneration of the faithful. (2) We shall now consider this principle of the whole and its parts with reference to physical objects. By physical objects we mean objects known to the senses, such as relate to what we call science. By chemistry we ascertain what are the parts of which these objects are composed. And hence we infer the purposes to which they may be applied. Thus, we learn that certain substances may be employed as medicines; and we discover the effects of par- ticular kinds of food : (a) Of what is water composed ? Of two gases oxygen and hydrogen. In nine pounds of water, eight are oxy- gen, and one is hydrogen. Of what is atmospheric air composed ? Principally of two gases, oxygen and nitro- gen, mixed together in the proportion of one gallon of oxygen to four of nitrogen. (b) Fruits consist principally of gum, sugar, starch, and vegetable jelly, combined with different acids. They contain but little nutritious matter, though, on account of their flavour and coolness, they are very agreeable to the palate, and, therefore, much prized as an article of diet. Their use is particularly beneficial to the health. Here from a knowledge of the constituent parts 53 of these substances we infer what would be the effect of the whole. The relation between a part and a whole has sometimes furnished important evidence in cases of judicial proceedings. In a case of house-breaking, the thief had gained admission into the house by means of a penknife, which was broken in the attempt, and part left in the window-frame. The broken knife was found in the pocket of the prisoner, and perfectly corresponded with the frag- ment left. In the case of a man who had been shot by a ball, the wadding of the pistol, which stuck in the wound, was found to be part of a ballad which corresponded with another part found in the pocket of the prisoner. The relation of a whole and its parts has some- times a reference to questions in political economy. Let us now observe how the value of a commodity re- solves itself into three component parts. Take, for in- stance, a load of hay ; its price pays first the wages of the labourer who cut down the grass and made it into hay then the profits of the farmer who sells it and lastly, the rent of the field in which it grew. This, there- fore, constitutes the whole cost of production of the load of hay, and may be called its natural value. (3) We shall now consider the application of this principle to moral ideas. The word moral is not used here in its ethical sense as opposed to immoral, but as opposed to physical. We cannot divide these ideas into parts so readily as we can divide arithmetical numbers, or as we may carve a fowl. Hence we often use the 54 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION words imply or include, in order to denote the simple ideas of which they are composed. Thus we may consider independence of mind as implying or including several things. Possibly it includes several other things besides those I have mentioned. But we are able to argue from these. For if it be a duty to cherish independence of mind, then it is a duty to cherish every one of the parts or principles of which it is composed. So gratitude includes a consciousness of favours received a disposition to acknowledge them on proper occasions and a resolution to return them when an opportunity occurs. Honour includes a regard to truth in words humanity and generosity in actions can- dour and forgiveness in thought, and resentment of insult or affront. Lender this relation we may class the points of belief, or practice adopted by any public body. The following were the points of the charter con- tended for by the Chartists : i . Equal Electoral Dis- tricts. 2. Universal Suffrage. 3. Vote by Ballot. 4. Triennial Parliaments. 5. No Property Quali- fications for Members. 6. Payment of Representa- tives. The settlement of a public question will some- times turn upon this relation of a whole and its parts. The first Baron Rothschild took all the oath required from Members of Parliament, except the words, " Upon the true faith of a Christian." His friends contended that these words were not part of the oath, and that the Baron, having now taken the oath, should be allowed to take his seat. The House of Commons decided that these words LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 55 formed a part of the oath. The Baron, therefore, could not take his seat. (4) It is curious to note how false reasonings arise out of a misuse of the relation between a whole and its parts. When a public body or society, governed jointly by a number of managers, is prosperous, each manager will take to himself a high degree of credit for having caused that prosperity. Quite naturally, too. On the other hand when the society or limited company becomes involved in difficulties, each manager is anxious to show that no part of the blame belongs to him ; thus the totals of the praise or blame which each manager is willing to take to himself are more or less than the total that belongs to the whole body. It should not be for- gotten in such cases that, whether of applause or censure, the total of all the parts cannot be either more or less than the whole. In the Curtain Lectures, it will be remembered that Mr. Caudle having lent a friend five pounds, Mrs. Caudle enumerates four or five ways in which this amount might have been employed, and then concludes that the lending of this one sum of five pounds has subjected her to all those privations. You ought to be very rich, Mr. Caudle. I wonder who'd lend you five pounds? But so it is : a wife may work and may slave ! Ha, dear ! the many things that might have been done with five pounds. As if people picked up money in the street ! But you always were a fool, Mr. Caudle ! I've wanted a black satin gown these three years, and that five pounds would have pretty well 56 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION bought it. All the girls want bonnets, and where they're to come from I can't tell. Half five pounds would have bought 'em but now they must go without. Next Tuesday the fire insurance is due. I should like to know how it's to be paid. Why, it can't be paid at all. That five pounds would have just done it and now, insurance is out of the question. I did think we might go to Mar- gate this summer. There's poor little Caroline, I'm sure she wants the sea. But no, dear creature ! she must stop at home all of us must stop at home she'll go into a consumption, there's no doubt of that; yes, sweet little angel ! I've made up my mind to lose her, now. The child might have been saved ; but people can't save their children and throw away their five pounds too. Dean Swift, in his sarcastic " Advice to Ser- vants," counsels them to act on the same fallacy. The cook, the butler, the groom, the market-man, and every other servant who is concerned in the expenses of the family, should act as if his master's whole estate ought to be applied to that servant's particular business. For instance, if the cook computes his master's estate to be a thousand pounds a year, he reasonably con- cludes, that a thousand pounds a year will afford meat enough, and therefore he need not be sparing ; the butler makes the same judgment, so may the groom and the coachman ; and thus every branch of expense will be filled to vour master's honour. CHAPTER VII. THE RELATION OF GENUS AND SPECIES. THIS relation is founded upon the act of classifica- tion. Let us take a tree. There are many kinds of trees, e.g., the oak and the elm ; and there is a great number of oaks and elms. Here, then, a tree is the GENUS ; oak and elm are the species, and a par- ticular oak or elm that we may happen to see, is an individual. In all the branches of natural his- tory, classification is very generally introduced. It is a rule, that the GENUS can always be asserted of each species. Thus we can say, an oak is a tree, an elm is a tree, a vine is a tree. This shows that tree is a genus, and that oak, elm, and vine, are species under that particular genus. We may say a horse is an animal, an ox is an animal, a dog is an animal. This proves that animal is a genus, and that dog, horse, and ox, are species of that genus. Each species may again be divided into inferior species, as there are various kinds of dogs, horses, and oxen. Genus and species have a reference to moral ideas, as well as to physical ones. Thus we may say, industry is a virtue, frugality is a virtue, temperance is a virtue. This shows that virtue is a genus, and that frugality, industry, and temperance are three of its species. E 57 58 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION You will observe that, although I call this, for brevity's sake, the relation of genus and species, you must always remember that, while a genus may be divided into species, each species may again be subdivided into individuals. I use these words, genus and species, being words in common use, to express the general idea of classification. The^ word genus denotes a large class the word species a small class included in the large class. This small class may sometimes be again sub- divided into smaller classes, and an individual is a single thing forming a part of the smallest class. It is clear that any single thing included in a smaller class must be included in a larger class. This is the foundation of all our reasonings from the relation of genus and species. (i) The following are examples of classification : (a) Mountain water, as it is pure and cold to the taste, is also beneficial to the health for drinking. If it cannot be obtained, river water may be resorted to. Well water I put in the last place, although everywhere it is agree- able for its coldness. It is almost always hard, unsuit- able for dissolving soap and for cooking vegetables. The water of lakes, even although they may contain the purest waters, and appear pellucid, nevertheless become tepid from their isolation, and are flat and vapid. (b) The capital of a manufacturer is of two kinds, fixed and circulating. The fixed capital remains always in his possession, as the mills, warehouses, etc. The circulating capital is always going out of his possession, as the materials of the manufacture, the wages of the workmen, etc. So the horses that draw the plough are part of the farmer's fixed capital, the sheep and oxen he LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 59 sends to market for sale are part of his circulating capital. (c) A library of books might be arranged (i) accord- ing to their size (2) according to the language in which they are written, (3) according to the alphabetic order of their author's names, (4) according to their subjects and in various other ways.* (d) The primary distinction of rights is of Natural and Positive rights. Rights are natural, as laid in the nature of man; rights are positive, as defined in the nation. Rights are natural as immanent in the nature of man : rights are positive as immanent in the nation, f The great purpose of classification, which reduces multiplicity to unity, is that it enables us to infer of all other members of a class what we know of any one member; consequently every classification should allow the greatest possible number of general assertions to be made, and it should be appropriate to the purpose in hand. (2) The rules for dividing a genus into its species, are similar to those for dividing a whole into its parts. A species is part of a genus. Each part singly taken must contain less than the whole, but all the parts taken collectively, or together, must contain neither more nor less than the whole ; or, as logicians sometimes express it, the parts of the divi- sion ought to exhaust the whole thing which is divided. In all distributions we should first consider the larger and more immediate kinds or species, or ranks of being, and not divide a thing at once into the more minute and *Jevons' Logic, p. 278. tMulford's The Nation, 60 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION remote. The several parts of a distribution ought to be opposite; that is, one species or class of beings in the same rank of division ought not to contain or include another; so men ought not to be divided into the rich, the poor, the learned, and the tall ; for poor men may be both learned and tall, and so may the rich. Let not sub- divisions be too numerous, without necessity ; therefore I think quantity is better distinguished~at once into a line, a surface, and a solid ; than to say, as Ramus does, that quantity is either a line or a thing lined; and a thing lined is either a surface or a solid. It is to this doctrine of distribution of a genus into its several species, we must also refer the distribution of a cause according to its several effects, as some medi- cines are heating, some are cooling : or an effect, when it is distinguished by its causes; as faith is either built upon divine testimony or human. It is to this head we refer particular artificial bodies, when they are distin- guished according to the matter they are made of, as a statue is either of brass, of marble, or wood, etc. ; and any other beings, when they are distinguished accord- ing to their end and design, as the furniture of body or mind is either for ornament or use. To this head also we refer subjects, when they are divided according to their modes or accidents; as men are either merry, or grave, or sad; and modes, when they are divided by their subjects, as distempers belong to the fluid, or to the solid parts of the animal.* (3) The mode of reasoning from genus and species is merely to show that a certain species is properly classed under a certain genus, and then to affirm or deny of the species what you may affirm or deny of the genus. f * Watts' Logic. t This is the principle of the first figure of syllogistic ifasoning; or, as Mr. Bailey calls it, "class reasoning." LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 61 Thus you may say, All fruit is useful to health : the apple is a kind of fruit; therefore the apple is useful to health. I may observe that this principle of reasoning from genus to species is the only kind of reasoning in which you gain anything by placing it in the form of a syllogism. And here, mind, the argument gains nothing in point of strength, but sometimes it gains a little in point of clearness; or, at least, it gives a clearer statement of the mean- ing of the reasoner. Here are two further specimens of syllo- gisms : He that's always in fear is not happy; Covetous men are always in fear; Therefore covetous men are not happy. Nothing that must be repented of is truly desir- able; Some pleasures must be repented of; Therefore there are some pleasures which are not truly desirable. In the first syllogism, " He that's always in fear " is the genus, and "covetous man " is the species under that genius. At least, he is, or was, with Dr. Watts; with other people he would have a more happy classification, despite his ambitions. In the second syllogism, " Nothing that must be repented of " is the genus, and " Some pleasures " The maxim is, " Whatever is predicated universally of any class of thing's, may be predicated in like manner of anything comprehended in that class." See Bailey's Theory of Rea- soning, p. 64. 62 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION is the species. In natural, everyday reasoning we should not use these syllogisms. We should say : Covetous men are not happy because they are always in fear. Some pleasures are not truly desirable because they must be repented of. (4) The application of a general principle to a par- ticular case is another mode of reasoning from the relation of genus and species. Take the principle of justice by way of illustra- tion. Gilbart thus applies it to the question of the rights of employees : Be just in your appointments, and select those who are the most worthy and the best qualified for the duties they will have to discharge. Be just in the amount of your remuneration; recollect that many of the servants of public companies have greater trusts and heavier re- sponsibilities than the servants of individuals; and in this case, it is just and equal that they be rewarded accordingly. Be just in your promotions, and let not merit be supplanted by patronage or favouritism. Be just in the quantity of labour you exact. Appoint a suffi- cient number of servants to do the work easily. Do not compel them to keep late hours ; nor refuse reasonable holidays, for the purposes of health and recreation. Be just in your pensions, and let your aged and worn-out servants be treated with respect and liberality. Be just in your reproofs. Let not your censures or your punish- ments be more than proportionate to the offence ; and be as ready at all times to acknowledge the merits of your servants as to notice their defects. All complaints, and all applications for increased remuneration or privileges, LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 63 from the servants of public companies, should receive mature consideration; and all refusals should be given with kindness and courtesy.* (5) In the application of general proverbs we reason from the relation of genus and species. Thus, " Honesty is the best policy." Therefore, when a public company has sustained losses, it is the best policy to announce them in its annual report to the shareholders, as that is the most honest procedure. This is one of the numerous cases to which this maxim may be applied. Frank- lin describes several specific characters under the genus that they " paid too dear for their whistle." And in daily life we meet with people to whom is applied the maxim, that " they have too many irons in the fire " ; or that " they carry too many eggs in one basket " ; or that " they are penny wise and pound foolish." In these cases the proverb is regarded as the genus, and the particular case to which it is applied is the species. This will appear the more evident if placed in the form of a syllo- gism. It is unwise to have too many irons in the fire. The man who carries on more trades than he can attend to, has too many irons in the fire. Therefore, the man who carries on more trades than he can attend to acts unwisely. (6) Rules and examples in any art or science sus- tain the relation to each other of genus and species. * Practical Treatise on Banking. 64 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION Take the following general rule in grammar: " Two or more nouns in the singular number joined together by a copulative conjunction, expressed or understood, must have verbs, nouns, and pronouns agreeing with them in the plural number." That is the general rule. Now, when we meet with two or more nouns, joined together in the manner stated, we apply the rule, and if we find that the verbs, nouns, and pronouns agreeing with them are put in the plural number, we infer that the sentence is grammatical; but, if otherwise, we say the sentence is ungrammatical. Now then, try by this rule the following sentences: "Socrates and Plato were wise, they were the most eminent philosophers of Greece." Here the rule is observed. " And so ivas also James and John, the sons of Zebedee, who were partners with Simon." Here the rule is violated. You perceive then that the application of any general rule to a particular case, is a logical process, and forms an argument on the principle of genus and species. I may also observe, that although in teaching an art systematically, we lay down our rules first, and then give the examples, yet, in the practical operations of teaching, especially in con- versation, it is usually best to state the example first, and then state the rule as a deduction from the example. Indeed, most general rules were probably in the first instance deduced from examples. Men did not invent grammar first, and then learn to speak, but speech existed before grammar. The same remark may be applied very LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 65 extensively. Poets existed before critics, and the practical arts before the sciences. (7) Arguments from enumeration may justly be classed under genus and species, as the enumeration is either of the individuals of a species, or of the species of a genus. Sometimes we enumerate the several arguments by which an opinion may be supported. Public speakers at the close of their address often do this. And judges on the bench enumerate, or sum up, as it is called, the arguments that have been used by the advocates. Sometimes, to prove the advantages or disadvan- tages of any engagement or pursuit, we enumerate them. In order to show that there is a pleasure in science, Lord Brougham thus enumerates the pleasures that it tends to produce: It is easy to show that there is a positive gratification resulting from the study of the sciences. If it be a pleasure to gratify curiosity to know what we are ig- norant of to have our feelings of wonder called forth ; how pure a delight of this very kind does natural science hold out to its students ! Recollect some of the extra- ordinary discoveries of mechanical philosophy. Observe the extraordinary truths which optical science discloses. Chemistry is not behind in its wonders; and yet these are trifling when compared to the prodigies which astro- nomy opens to our view : the enormous masses of the heavenly bodies ; their immense distances ; their count- less numbers ; and their motions, whose swiftness mocks the uttermost efforts of the imagination. Then, if we raise our view to the structure of the heavens, we are again gratified by tracing accurate, but most unexpected 66 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION resemblances. Is it not in the highest degree interest- ing to find that the power which keeps the earth in its shape, and in its path wheeling round the sun, extends over all the other worlds that compose the universe, and gives to each its proper place and motion ; that the same power keeps the moon in her path round the earth ; that the same power causes the tides upon our earth, and the peculiar form of the earth itself; and that, after all, it is the same power which makes a stone fall to the ground ? To learn these things, and to reflect upon them, pro- duces certain, as well as pure, gratification. (8) Under this head of genus and species we may place reasoning from the definition. The genus and the specific difference, as we have already stated, are joined together to make a formal definition.* We cannot always obtain a definition of this kind, but when we can do so, we may reason from it in various ways. Commence your definition by stating the genus or general nature. Thus, in dealing with justice you would describe it as "merited reward or punishment"; therefore be- longing to the sphere of ethics. This is the genus. And then you may state wherein it differs from other branches of ethics, e.g., temperance, obedi- ence, patience, and self-love. But you must not be too precise about this matter of definition. If your opponent is disposed to cavil, he may easily find fault with any definition you can give. Even men of great talent and learning cannot agree among themselves upon this subject. The most eminent political economists give different defini- * See p. 28. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 67 tions of such plain words as capital, profit, rent, wages, words that we use in our ordinary con- versation, without fancying that there is any diffi- culty or mystery about them. Sydney Smith, the most witty man of his time, was at a loss to find a definition for wit, and at the same time is very witty upon the definitions he quotes from other writers. Dryden's definition of wit, he says, will apply to Blair's Sermons, and Pope's to the Funeral Orations of Bossuet. (9) We reason erroneously from the relation of genus and species, when we place under the genus several species that do not belong to it, and then assert of each species what may be truly asserted of the genus. Mrs. Opie, who had previously become a member of the Society of Friends, published a book en- titled, " Illustrations of Lying in all its Branches." Under the class of " practical lies," she places the practice of wearing false hair. This we think is an erroneous classification ; for if we use the word liar in the sense in which it is usually employed, the wearer of false hair is not a species of that genus. A lie implies something immoral, but we do not think it is immoral to conceal defects that are inconvenient to the party himself, or that would be unpleasant to the beholders. Mrs. Opie's argu- ment stands thus: A liar is one who wishes to deceive. She who wears false hair wishes to deceive. Therefore she who wears false hair is a liar. We may refute this argument in the following 68 ways: We may say that the words, "wishes to deceive," have not the same meaning in the first or major proposition which they have in the second or minor proposition, and hence the two proposi- tions are independent of each other, and they have no relation that can be a foundation for any reason- ing respecting them. Or, we may admit that in both propositions the words, "wishes to deceive," have the same meaning. But then they merely denote a common property not a specific difference and hence they do not prove that the two subjects are the same. Gold is yellow, and saffron is yellow, but it does not follow that saffron is gold. So in the present case, the common attribute does not prove that the two subjects are the same. Or we may reduce the conclusion to an absurdity, thus : All liars shall have their portion in the lake that burns with fire and brimstone. She who wears false hair is a liar. Therefore she who wears false hair shall have her portion in the lake that burns with fire and brimstone. Such a conclusion shows the absurdity of the classification. In actual life we often meet with erroneous classi- fications of this kind. The words, " want of courtesy," is a general term often unjustly applied to individual actions. A person goes to transact some business at a public office, and is detained much longer than he expected. He becomes irri- tated, and declares he is treated with want of courtesy; whereas the delay may have been occa- LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 69 sioned by the necessary forms of the office, or by his own ignorance of those forms. When a servant for some trifling oversight is charged with " neglect of duty," it is a fallacy of the same kind. The words, " neglect of duty," is a generic phrase that is applied only to cases of wilful or serious omis- sions. To apply it in trfling cases is to use it illogically. Whenever we wish to represent any act in its worst colours, we use generic terms of so wide a meaning as to include several species of offences of a deeper dye than that we are called upon to censure ; and, on the other hand, when we wish to extenuate, we employ generic terms that shall include only offences of a lighter hue. All these are fallacies arising from erroneous classifica- tion similar to that we have exemplified from Mrs. Opie. (10) We must also avoid the error of confounding two or more species because they belong to the same genus. Thus when we find that two species resemble each other in some respects (which of course they always must do), we should not infer that they resemble each other in all respects. For example He who says you are an animal, says what is true. He who says you are a goose says you are an animal. Therefore he that says you are a goose, says what is true. Here the two premises are true, and yet the con- clusion is absurd. It is true that you are an animal, and that a goose is an anjmal, and yet it is not 70 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION true (of course I mean literally) that you are a goose : For you and the goose belong to different species, and although you resemble each other so far as to be properly classed under the same genus (animal), yet you cannot be asserted to be each other. So, dog, horse, camel, elephant, are species of animal, but a dog is not a horse, nor is a camel an elephant. In the case of genus "animal " we are not in much danger of falling into error. But we meet with similar errors elsewhere. I have read a debate in the House of Commons in which Unitarians were called Mahometans. Both these bodies agree in disbelieving the doctrine of the Trinity. But under this generic description, they form two widely different species, and one cannot logically be confounded with the other. You will often observe this practice in party writers. They will class the party against whom they write with some other party that has a disreputable name, and confound them both together under some generic description. (11) In reasoning on this principle we should always be on our guard against mere mental classifications. I mean such as exist only in the mind, and not in the nature of the things themselves. The following para- graph explains the point fully. I may borrow a remarkable instance for my purpose almost out of every garden, which contains a variety of plants in it. Most or all plants agree in this, that they have a root, a stalk, leaves, buds, blossoms, and seeds : but the gardener ranges them under very different names, as though they were really different kinds of beings, merely because of the different use and service to which they are applied by men : as for instance, those plants whose roots are eaten, shall appropriate the name of roots to themselves; such are carrots, turnips, radishes, etc. If the leaves are of chief use to us, then we call them herbs, as sage, mint, thyme; if the leaves are eaten raw, they are termed salad, as lettuce, purslain; if boiled, they become pot-herbs, as spinach, coleworts ; and some of those plants which are pot-herbs in one family are salad in another. If the buds are made our food, they are called heads or tops ; so cabbage heads, heads of asparagus, and artichokes. If the blossom be of most importance, we call it a flower; such are daisies, tulips, and carnations, which are the mere blossoms of those plants. If the husk or seeds are eaten, they are called the fruits of the ground ; as peas, beans, straw- berries, etc. If any part of the plant be of known and common use to us in medicine, we call it a physical herb; as carduus, scurvy-grass ; but if we count no part useful, we call it a weed, and throw it out of the garden ; and yet, perhaps, our next neighbour knows some valuable property and use of it ; he plants it in his garden, and gives it the title of a herb, or a flower. Now, when things are set in this clear light, it appears how ridicu- lous it would be for two persons to contend, whether dandelion be an herb or a weed ; whether it be a pot-herb or a salad; when, by the custom or fancy of different families, this one plant obtains all these names, accord- ing to the several uses of it, and the value that is put upon it. A dispute somewhat similar to what is here inti- mated took place between M'Culloch and Malthus upon the classification of labourers into productive and unproductive. Malthus, following Adam Smith, applied the word productive to such 72 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION labourers only whose exertions directly produced material wealth. M'Culloch extended the word so as to include those also whose labour indirectly produced wealth. Hence arose the important ques- tion, whether a dancer at the opera should be styled a productive or an unproductive labourer? Some good paper and printing were expended in this wordy warfare. And, after all, it was only a dis- pute about classification, for in other respects the antagonists did not differ in opinion. This example may teach us to use caution in the choice of the words we employ to denote our classifications. The words productive and unproductive seem to convey praise and censure. Had other words been employed, Adam Smith's distinction would not probably have been thought worthy of so much reproach.* (12) In reasoning from this relation of genus and species we should carefully notice the kind of universality which is attributable to the genus ; for if the general proposition be taken in too extensive a sense, the conclusion will be erroneous. One authority thus argues the case : Universal terms may either denote a mathematical, a physical, or a moral universality. A mathematical universality, is when all the particu- lars contained under any general idea have the same * We fear Mr. Bailey has committed an error of this kind in dividing reasoning into demonstrative and contingent. In defiance of all explanation the mind will associate some degree of uncertainty with the word "contingent." LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 73 predicate belonging to them without any exception what- soever ; or when the predicate is so essential to the uni- versal subject, that it destroys the very nature of the subject to be without it ; as, All circles have a centre and circumference. A physical or natural universality, is when, according to the order and common course of nature, a predicate agrees to all the subjects of that kind, though there may be some accidental and preter- natural exceptions; as, All men use words to express their thoughts, yet dumb persons are excepted, for they cannot speak. All beasts have four feet, yet there may be some monsters with five; or maimed, who have but three. A moral universality, is when the predicate agrees to the greatest part of the particulars which are con- tained under the universal subject ; as, All men are gov- erned by affection rather than by reason : All the old Romans loved their country : and the scripture uses this language when St. Paul tells us, " The Cretes are always liars." Now it is evident, that a special or singular conclusion cannot be inferred from a moral universality, nor always and infallibly from a physical one, though it may be always inferred from a universality which is mathematical, without any danger or possibility of a mis- take. Let it be observed also, that usually we make little or no distinction in common language, between a subject that is physically or mathematically universal. You will find that some political economists lay down general propositions, and reason from them as though they possessed a mathematical univer- sality. But, from the nature of the science, this cannot be the case. It is a moral science, and its general propositions have only a moral universality. I mean that these rules have a good many excep- tions. For example; one of its principles is, that the Government should not interfere with matters F 74 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION of trade a very good rule, as a general rule; but when we are told that this rule is so inflexible that the Government must not interfere even in behalf of humanity and religion, then we contend that its advocates claim for this rule a universality to which it is not entitled In this sense we deny the sound- ness of the rule. Nay, even those political econo- mists who maintain most strongly this principle, maintain at the same time that the Government ought to pass laws for the regulation of the currency a subject with which trade has a very close affinity. It is rarely that a mathematical universality can be obtained with regard to those propositions that we usually act upon in ordinary life. We believe that all noblemen have honourable and patriotic feelings that all judges are impartial in their deci- sions that all London merchants are honest in their dealings that our friends, whose constancy we have tried, will never desert us that a man who has maintained a high reputation for thirty years will maintain it as long as he lives. But we have only moral evidence for all these propositions, and we can get no more. He who, in these and similar instances, would refuse to act until he should obtain mathematical evidence, would show a want of that wisdom and decision which are essential to the good administration of the affairs either of a family, a commercial establishment, or a political com- munity. CHAPTER VIII. THE RELATION OF CAUSE AND EFFECT PHYSICAL CAUSES. THE Relation of Cause and Effect is a principle of extensive use in the art of reasoning. But as causes are of various kinds, \ve must consider them sepa- rately in different sections; and in this section we shall confine our attention to those causes that refer to material substances, and are consequently styled physical. We shall, in the subsequent sections, consider those causes that are moral, conditional, and final. We may observe, with regard to these four kinds of causes physical, moral, conditional, and final the first has reference to the physical sciences, as botany, physiology, geography, chemistry, etc. ; the second has reference to the sciences of politics and political economy ; the third has reference to jurisprudence and the affairs of ordinary life; the fourth has reference to ethics and theology. We do not mean an exclusive refer- ence, but a general reference. (i) The first class of causes we call physical causes. To this class of causes we refer all those effects which are produced by the uniform and necessary operations of nature. Thus, it is an established law of nature that the earth should move 75 76 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION round the sun, and that the moon should move round the earth. All the phenomena which result from the revolutions of the heavenly bodies are the result of natural causes. It is a law of nature that all bodies on the earth should tend towards the centre; and that different kinds of matter, whether fluid or solid, should have certain properties, and that some of them should Have an affinity for each other. Hence, all reasonings connected with astronomy, mechanics, chemistry, and the other branches of experimental philosophy, are founded on natural causes. The reasonings founded on this class of causes amount to demonstration. The cause necessarily and invariably produces the effect. The following are examples: (a) Almost universally in nature causes are manifold and complex and none of the complex elements can be overlooked without falling into error. For example, about 1854, some excavators brought up some burnt brick and pottery from the depth of 60 and 72 feet in the valley of the Nile. Assuming that they were found where they were made, and that the alluvium had been de- posited upon them at the rate at which the Nile now makes its deposit, and that this was the only cause at work, it was calculated mathematically that the relics must be from 12,000 to 60,000 years old. One causal element omitted was the weight of the brick bats in con- nection with the fact (also causal) that all the region is a vast quagmire during the inundation which covers it with water during a large part of the year. Sir Robert Stephenson afterwards found in the delta, near Damietta, at a far greater depth, a brick, bearing the stamp of Mohammed Ali (1808). Someone said, satirically, that the main question in the first case should have been : LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 77 How long will it take a brick to sink 72 feet in a quag- mire? But, although this might be the main question, all causes should be given their due weight in reaching the correct result.* (b) It is perfectly certain that, at a comparatively recent period of the world's history the cretaceous epoch none of the great physical features which at present mark the surface of the globe existed. It is cer- tain that the Rocky Mountains were not. It is certain that the Himalaya Mountains were not. It is certain that the Alps and Pyrenees had no existence. The evi- dence is of the plainest possible character, and is simply this : We find raised up on the flanks of these moun- tains, elevated by the forces of upheaval which have given rise to them, masses of cretaceous rock which formed the bottom of the sea before these mountains ex- isted. It is, therefore, clear that the elevatory forces which gave rise to the mountains operated subsequently to the cretaceous epoch ; and that the mountains them- selves are largely made up of the materials deposited in the sea which once occupied their place, t (c) The annual overflowing of the Nile is caused by the periodical rains in Ethiopia. The river begins to rise in the latter end of June, and attains its utmost height about the middle of August, when Egypt presents the appearance of a vast sea, while the cities and towns appear like so many islands ; after this the waters gradually subside, and about the end of November the river has returned to its ordinary limits. During this period the earth, or mud, which the waters held in solu- tion, has fallen on the soil; and on the retiring of the * Practical Logic. D. S. Gregory. t Three Lectures on "Evolution. By T. H. Huxley. 78 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION waters, the whole land is covered with a rich manure; and, according to Herodotus, required so little cultiva- tion, that, in some cases, it was only necessary that the seed should be thrown upon the surface, and trodden down by pigs.* (2) There are four ways of reasoning in regard to these physical causes. First, from the existence of the cause, we may infer the existence of the effect; if the sun has arisen, we know it must be day; if the earth comes between the sun and the moon, the moon will be eclipsed : if a body, of less specific gravity than water, be thrown into water, we know it will float. If fire be applied to gun- powder, an explosion will take place ; if the colours blue and yellow be mixed together, they will pro- duce a green ; if a man has had his head cut off, \ve may infer that he is dead. The second mode of reasoning is, from the existence of the effect to infer the existence of the cause. All theories or systems are founded upon this mode of reasoning. We observe the appearances of nature, and we endeavour to ascertain the causes which have pro- duced them : if we see an abundant harvest, we may infer that the land is good. The third mode of reasoning is, from the non-existence of the cause to infer the non-existence of the effect : in the deserts of Arabia there is no rain, consequently there can be no vegetation. The fourth mode of reasoning is, from the non-existence of the effect to infer the non-existence of the cause : the streets are not wet, therefore it cannot have rained recently. *Ltctures on Ancient Commerce. By J. W. Gilbart. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 79 Watts thus expounds the principle: There is a system of beings round about us, of which we ourselves are a part, which we call the world, and in this world there is a course of nature, or a settled order of causes, effects, antecedents, concomitants, and con- sequents. Where antecedents, concomitants, and consequents, causes and effects, signs and things signified, subjects and adjuncts, are necessarily connected with each other, we may infer the causes from the effects, and effects from causes, the antecedents from the consequents, as well as consequents from antecedents, etc., and thereby be pretty certain of many things both past, present, and to come. It is by this principle that astronomers can tell what day and hour the sun and moon were eclipsed five hundred years ago, and predict all future eclipses as long as the world shall stand. They can tell precisely at what minute the sun rises or sets this day at Pekin, in China, or what altitudes the dog-star had at midnight or midnoon in Rome on the day when Julius Caesar was slain. Gardeners upon the same principle, can foretell the months when every plant will be in bloom, and the ploughman knows the weeks of harvest : we are sure, if there be a chicken, there was an egg; if there be a rain- bow, we are certain it rains not far off ; if we behold a tree growing on the earth, we know it has naturally a root under ground. Where there is a necessary connexion between causes and effects, antecedents and consequents, signs and things signified, we know also that like causes will have like effects, and proportionable causes will have propor- tionable effects, contrary causes will have contrary effects ; and observing men may form many judgments by the rules of similitude and proportion, where the causes, effects, etc., are not entirely the same. Where there is but a probable and uncertain connexion between antecedents, concomitants, and consequents, we can give but a conjecture, or a probable determination. If the 8o LOGIC FOR THE MILLION clouds gather, or the weatherglass sinks, we suppose it will rain : if a man spit blood frequently, with coughing, we suppose his lungs are diseased : if very dangerous symptoms appear, we expect his death. (3) We reason falsely when we ascribe effects to wrong causes. Thus, for many ages the appearances of the celes- tial bodies were ascribed to their motion round the earth; whereas it has since been demonstrated that these effects could not be produced by such a cause. The French philosopher, Descartes, imagined certain whirlpools in the atmosphere, by which he attempted to account for the appearances of nature. Thunder and lightning, earthquakes and volcanoes, are effects which have been ascribed to a variety of causes, according to the hypotheses of different philosophers : the flux and reflux of the tide, the origin of rivers, and the phenomena of electricity, have furnished curious specimens of false reasoning in assigning causes. I would make this matter a little plainer still by in- stances borrowed from the peripatetic philosophy, which was once taught in all the schools. The professor fancies he has assigned the true reason why all heavy bodies tend downward, why amber will draw feathers or straws, and the loadstone draw iron, when he tells you that this is done by certain gravitating and attractive qualities, which proceed from the substantial forms of those various bodies. He imagines that he has explained why the loadstone's north pole shall repel the north end of a magnetic needle, and attract the south, when he affirms that this is done by its sympathy with one end of it, and its antipathy against the other end. Whereas, in truth, all these names of sympathy, antipathy, substantial LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 81 forms, and qualities, when they are put for the causes of these effects in bodies, are but hard words, which only express a learned and pompous ignorance of the true cause of natural appearances. Writers on metaphysics have also adopted theories calculated to weaken our confidence in the relation of physical causes and effects. The most remarkable of these writers is Bishop Berkeley "Since," he asks, "the mind does not perceive physical objects, but merely the images of those objects formed in the eye, how do you know that any such objects exist ?" To this we may reply, that the representation formed in the eye, is the effect of the external objects, and is in itself a proof of their existence. When we look at an object through a telescope, we know that the object exists, though we see only the image formed by the speculum. Mill observes in his system of " Logic " : I affirm that I saw my brother at a certain hour this morning. If any proposition concerning a matter of fact would commonly be said to be known by the direct testi- mony of the senses, this surely would be so. The truth, however, is far otherwise. I only saw a certain coloured surface, or rather I had the kind of visual sensations which are usually produced by a coloured surface, and from these, as marks known to be such by previous ex- perience, I concluded that I saw my brother.* Upon this theory we should suppose, that as soon as an infant can recognise its mother, it has begun to draw conclusions, and has also had sufficient * Mill's Logic, vol. ii., p. 208. 82 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION experience in the arts to know that a human body may be represented on a coloured surface.* (4) To prove the connection between a physical cause and its effects, is not directly the province of reasoning, but of observation and experiment. Bacon said: " Alan, the Servant and Interpreter of Nature can do and understand as much as he has observed concerning the order of Nature in outward things or in the mind : more he can neither know nor do." In other words, the truth about nature and man can only be discovered by analys- ing both, using such faculties as we possess and following a strict logical method for the avoidance of error. Observations carefully and systematic- ally carried out and recorded tell us what happens in the world of Nature when we do nothing to affect the results of natural forces; experiments conducted in the same way tell us new truths, which, mere observation could not possibly yield. We do not mean that new truths do not come by observation, else we should not have Newton discovering the law of gravitation ; but no observation pure and simple, without the aid of experiment, would have put us in possession of radium. The function of reasoning in these cases is, as Mill said, to enable us "to discriminate accurately between what we * I have thought it best to let this argument stand as Gilbart wrote it. The attitude of psychologists to-day would seem to make an intellectually double life necessary, denying objective reality in one breath and affirming it the next. Christian Scientists deny the existence of matter, including dollars, but they know when they have received the wrong change. [Ed.] LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 83 really do observe and what we only infer from the facts observed. " Observation, even where supported by exact measurement, in many cases, will go very little way towards establishing the cause of a phenome- non, unless we are able to vary the concomitant circumstances, and view the cause, generate the effect, or vary in exact proportion along with it. Though there was every reason to attribute light- ning to electric agency, the fact was never con- sidered definitely made out until Franklin threw up his kite in the air at the approach of a thunder- storm, and obtained the same sparks from his cord as invariably accompanied its connection with an electric machine. As Nature is constructed for a widely different object than that of facilitating our studies, it frequently happens, indeed, that she refuses to afford the precise kind of variation needed to establish the law we are in search of, and leaves us to rack our invention, to institute a case in point, by direct experiment. Thus were it required to ascertain the principle in the atmosphere which enables it to sustain life, we should find no instance in which Nature produces either oxygen or nitrogen in a separate state, to enable us, by immersing a living animal alternately in both gases, to decide the question. We are exclusively indebted to ex- periment for the fact that respiration is supported by oxygen, and also for our knowledge of the ingre- dients of which the atmosphere is composed."* In all reasoning about physical causes it is well *Devey's Logic, p. 215. 84 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION to bear in mind Mill's canons of inductive enquiry. I. If two or more instances of the phenomenon under investigation have any one circumstance in common, the circumstance in which alone all the instances agree, is the cause (or effect) of the given phenomenon. II. If an instance in which the phenomenon under investigation occurs, and an instance in which it does not occur, have every circumstance in common save one, that one occurring only in the former; the circumstance in which alone the two instances differ is the effect or the cause or an indispensable part of the cause of the phenomenon. u. If two or more instances in which the phe- nomenon occurs have only one circumstance in common, while two or more instances in which it does not occur have nothing in common, save the absence of that circumstance : the circumstance in which alone the two sets of instances (always or invariably) differ, is the effect, or the cause, or an indispensable part of the cause of the phenomenon. CHAPTER IX. THE RELATION OF CAUSE AND EFFECT MORAL CAUSES. THE existence of moral causes can best be under- stood from examples, and some of these we hope to give as early as possible ; but it will not be amiss to occupy the opening paragraph of this chapter with a few words of explanation as to the term itself. Moral causes deal with ethical problems only as part of that great sphere of life where forces work that are not purely physical. In sciences like chemistry and physics we have to do with physical causes alone; we add nothing to them, and we take nothing from them ; they would exist and operate even if we ourselves did not exist. But in dealing with problems arising out of actions of human beings, we are face to face with a new element : and although sociology and political economy, to take two instances, cannot be said to be free from all connection or association with phy- sical causes, there is sufficient freedom from them to justify the use of another term, i.e., moral; not in the strictly ethical sense, but as opposed to physical. The reader is warned against the expectation of finding the same demonstration in the world of moral causes as he finds in the other, where in most instances no two opinions are possible. The science of physics, as far as we know it, is almost 85 86 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION as exact as mathematics; but in reasoning about human relationships of all kinds allowance must be made for the fact that it is not possible to get the same exactitude as in other spheres of investiga- tion. True, tae moral probability arising out of a study of events is frequently of a demonstrative character; but in some matters the experts have been, and always will be, at variance. In this sec- tion we shall try to reproduce those laws of moral argumentation which have proved themselves to be of the greatest worth. First, however, we give some examples of moral cases: (a) Influence. Certainly the two human beings who have had the greatest influence upon the understandings of mankind have been Aristotle and "baked. Bacon. To*bwd Bacon are indebted for an almost daily extension of our knowledge of the laws of nature in the outward world ; and the same modest and cautious spirit of inquiry, ex- tended to moral philosophy, will probably at last give us clear, intelligible ideas of our spiritual nature. Every succeeding year is an additional confirmation to us that we are travelling in the true path of knowledge ; and as it brings in fresh tributes of science for the increase of human happiness, it extorts from us fresh tributes of praise to the guide and father of true philosophy. To the understanding of Aristotle, equally vast, perhaps, and equally original, we are indebted for fifteen hundred years of quibbling and ignorance, in which the earth fell under the tyranny of words, and philosophers quar- relled with one another, like drunken men in dark rooms, who hate peace without knowing why they fight, or see- ing how to take aim.* * Sydney Smith's Moral Philosophy. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 87 (b) Political Economy. It is a doctrine of Hume, in his " Essay on Money," that an influx of the precious metals gives great en- couragement to industry, during the interval which elapses before the prices of commodities are adjusted to the increased quantity of specie. " We find," says he, " that in every kingdom into which money begins to flow in greater abundance than formerly, everything takes a new face : labour and industry gain life ; the merchant becomes more enterprising, the manufacturer more dili- gent and skilful, and even the farmer follows his plough with greater alacrity and attention. In my opinion," he continues, " it is only in this interval, or intermediate situation, between the acquisition of money and rise of prices, that the increased quantity of gold and silver is favourable to industry."* (c) Ecclesiastical Affairs. We hold that a Church Establishment is the most effective of all machines for the moral instruction of the people, and that, if once taken down, there is no other instrumentality by which it can be adequately replaced. We are aware, that it may be feebly and even corruptly administered ; but the way to rectify this, is not to demo- lish the apparatus, but to direct its movements. It is the means of turning so much unproductive into produc- tive consumption. Without a church the whole of our ecclesiastical wealth would have been in the hands of those who give no return for it. With a church, we have the return of all its usefulness its theological learn- ing the protection which it affords against a desolat- ing infidelity the service which it renders to the morality of the commonwealth and, above all, to the eternal well-being of the individual members who compose it. t * Questions on Political Economy. t Dr. Chalmers. 88 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION (2) With regard to moral causes, we may adopt the following modes of reasoning : First. From the existence of the cause we may infer the existence of the effect. Thus, if a man be industrious, we may infer that he will probably become rich. If a man be given to intoxication, we may infer that he will reduce himself to beggary. If a man exercise his intellectual faculties, we know he will improve them. Secondly. From the existence of the effect we may infer the existence of the cause. Thus, if a servant enjoy in a high degree the confidence of his master, we may infer that he has served him well. If a man be involved in debts which he is unable to pay, we may infer that he has been either imprudent or unfortunate. Thirdly. From the non-existence of the cause, we may infer the non-existence of the effect. Thus, if a man has not been unfortunate nor improvident, we may argue that he cannot be poor. Fourthly. From the non-existence of the effect we may infer the non-existence of the cause. Thus, we may say, such a person is not poor; he cannot then have been extravagant. Such a person is not an intelligent man ; he cannot, then, have spent much time in reading and study. He does not speak correctly; therefore he cannot have learned grammar. (3) In the relation of moral causes and effects, we have, generally, in the first instance, to prove by reasoning that such a relation exist. If, for instance, I contend that education produces 8 9 good morals, and hence, ask my neighbours to assists me in establishing a school for the poor, I may be asked to prove, in the first instance, that education does produce good morals; for, unless I can prove the relation of cause and effect in this case, my efforts will be unavailing. So in many of the acts of ordinary life, and in nearly all our public proceedings, whether a certain cause will produce a certain effect, is in fact the whole question in dispute. In reasoning upon moral causes, we are exposed to much difficulty from the circumstance, that one effect is often produced by a variety of causes. The greatest sophistry arises from imputing to one particular cause an effect which results from the joint operation of many causes. Thus, the ruin of an individual may be the consequence of the accidental burning of his house; of imprudent conduct ; of the treachery of friends, and of robbery by thieves. The fall of a state may be the effect of the united operation of a tyrannical government, a seditious people, the encroachments of a foreign enemy, and pestilence and famine. Now, should a person take the effect, and argue that it was pro- duced solely by one cause, he would be in error. We shall fall into error if we deny the existence of any one cause, because other causes contributed to produce the effect. Thus, it has been contended that Sir Robert Peel's Act for Regulating the Currency, passed in the year 1844, was a cause of the commercial distress that occurred in the year 1847. In reply, it was contended, that the distress of 1847 was produced by the famine in Ireland and G 90 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION the speculations in railways. Now this is no refu- tation of the former opinion ; for all the three causes may have united in producing the same effect. We should also fall into error were we to infer, that of two events one is the cause of the other, merely because it occurred first in the order of time. This fallacy is often ridiculed by a reference to the building of Tenterden steeple being the cause of the Goodwin sands. The story is told, I believe, by Bishop Latimer. There was a time when the Goodwin sands, which lie in the neighbourhood of Dover, did not exist. Some time after they had collected, Government commissioners were ap- pointed to ascertain the cause. They accordingly proceeded to the spot to examine witnesses. Among others, an old man assured them that the cause of the Goodwin sands was the building of the Tenterden steeple. They asked him how this could be. He stated, he could not tell how, but he knew it was so; for he recollected that when there was no steeple there were no sands, but soon after the building of the steeple, in came the sands. He, therefore, inferred that the building of the steeple was the cause of the sands. We shall give an example of the way in which this allusion is applied. The following argument is taken from the " Sophisms of Free Trade," by " A Barrister " : All great manufactures had their origin in the protec- tive system. Take our own, the greatest and least sickly of any. All our own manufactures took their rise in a system of protective duties, so high as to amount to prohibitions. In addition to this, owing to LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 91 the fearful hostilities that raged in Europe for nearly a quarter of a century before 1815, we enjoyed a further accidental monopoly of the manufacturing industry of the world. And this stringent protection has not only created manufactures, but created them where they would not naturally have existed, in spite of great natural disadvantages. Other nations have coal and iron ore as well as we. The United States are even richer in this respect. But other nations have, also, what we have not, they have native raw materials. It has been justly observed, that Great Britain is singularly poor in the raw materials which constitute the basis of the greater portion of her manufacturing industry. We have no cotton, no silk, no fine wool. Even our best iron for the manufacture of hardware, comes from Sweden ; our oils, gums, colours, woods, from the ends of the earth. Next to us in manufacturing industry, is France. Her manufacturing industry, though still inferior to ours, has nevertheless, since the peace, augmented in an even greater ratio, but under strict and jealous protection. The following reply is taken from " Free Trade and its so-called Sophisms " : There is no doubt that, until recently, the govern- ments of almost all countries considered that the way to establish an industry, and make it prosper, was to " protect " it; and, consequently, whenever an industry flourishes simultaneously with the existence of protec- tion, a great shout of triumph is raised, as if the former were dependent on the latter the old fallacy of post hoc, ergo propter hoc. It is only necessary to refer to the well-known case of Tenterden steeple and the Goodwin sands for an illustration. The reader will observe, that the Barrister's argument with regard to manufactures is that in several countries protection preceded prosperity; 92 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION and he infers that protection was the cause of prosperity. His opponent replies, that though protection preceded prosperity, it was not the cause of prosperity ; the two facts having no more relation to each other than Tenterden steeple and the Good- win sands. In order to prove that two events sustain the relation to each other of cause and effect, it is necessary to show, first, that the two events did actually occur; secondly, that the event which we call the cause, occurred in the order of time before the effect; and, thirdly, that there was an adaptation in the cause to produce the effect. In refutation we may state, that one or both of the two events did not occur or that they did not occur in the order of time or that there was no adaptation in the one to produce the other. We may go further, and maintain that the alleged cause, so far from being the cause, was an obstruction to the effect. The words, " in spite of," are sometimes used on such occasions. " Gentlemen, I contend that trade did not prosper in consequence of protection, but that it prospered in spite of protection." (4) Public measures are usually approved or con- demned on account of the effects they are alleged to produce. Here is a wide field for controversy. The affairs of a nation are so multifarious, so many causes are perpetually at work, that it is difficult to trace with certainty the precise effects of any one cause. Even after measures have become law, and we have had some experience of their operation, the same differ- LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 93 ence of opinion is still maintained. If a measure already adopted is applauded on account of the good effect it "has produced, we may contend in opposition to this, that the event, called the effect, has not taken place or admit that the event has taken place, but was not the effect of that cause. Or, we may go further, and admit that the event was the effect of the cause, but that the effect was a bad effect. Or, we may go still further, and admit that the effect was a good effect, and then contend that the same cause produced other effects of a different character, so that the bad conse- quences more than counterbalanced the good ones. Sometimes it is a matter of dispute, when two circumstances sustain the relation of cause and effect, which is the cause and which is the effect. Heretofore the landlords have been accused of keeping up the price of corn by demanding high rents; but Chalmers observes that there is no sounder principle in political economy than that the high prices of corn are not the effect, but the cause of high rents. The country bankers were accused of causing a general rise in prices by an excessive issue of their notes ; but they stated, in reply, that it was not the increased issue of notes that caused the high prices, but the high prices called out the notes. The error of the Ricardo system of political economy on the subject of rent, has been well characterised by Mr. T. Perronet Thomson as the fallacy of inversion. It confounds the effect with the cause. It is not be- cause of the existence of inferior soils that the superior pay a rent, but it is because the superior pay a rent that 94 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION the inferior are taken into occupation. There does not occur to us any logical term by which to denominate the fallacy that is now under consideration ; but it is not less a fallacy notwithstanding. If the effect may have been produced by several causes, and we can prove the absence of all causes except one, this fixes the effect on that one cause. Some years ago there was a serious outbreak of fever in an English town, where it began in a par- ticular street. The fact of the people in the first street mentioned having been the first victims in the great outbreak, shows that they must have been highly predisposed; and as they lived in decent houses, and were in comfortable circumstances two of the more ordinary causes of the disease over- crowding and poverty could not have operated. Those considerations can leave no doubt that the one main cause of the great severity of the attack, was the use for domestic purposes of polluted water. A series of analyses proved this to be true. In investigating the relation of cause and effect, it is sometimes advisable not to stop at the immediate causes, but to go further back, and ascertain what are the original causes of that immediate cause. It has been disputed whether the price of food has any influence on the rate of wages. It has been answered, No; for the rate of wages is regulated by the proportion between the demand for labour and the supply. Admitting the latter opinion to be correct, it does not refute the former; for the demand and the supply of labour are influenced by anterior causes, and the price of food may be one of those anterior causes. So, we are told that LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 95 the rate of interest is regulated by the proportion that may exist between the demand and the supply of capital. This throws but little light upon the matter, unless we are told at the same time what are the anterior causes that regulate this demand and this supply. If it be a matter of dispute whether two events sustain the relation of cause and effect, we may be able to solve the difficulty, if it is found that the removal of the supposed cause is followed by the removal of the supposed effect. In 1844 an Act was passed for regulating the currency, and in 1847 there was severe monetary pressure. The 1844 Act got all the blame; but it was found that when the Act was suspended in October, 1847, the pressure immediately ceased. A writer on this subject observes " It has been denied that this pressure was produced or increased by the Act. But how stand the facts? The Act was passed, and, as predicted, a pressure came the Act was continued, and the pressure increased the Act was suspended, and the pressure went away. These are not opinions they are facts." In reasoning upon moral causes and effects we should inquire whether at all times and under all circumstances the same causes will produce pre- cisely the same effects. We often meet with cases of this kind in the consideration of historical and international questions. Thus it is said the wool- len manufacture in England, and the linen manu- facture in Ireland, prospered in consequence of protective laws, and therefore the same laws would cause increased prosperity at the present time. 9 6 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION When Joint Stock Banks were first created, it was contended they were adapted only for countries having little capital and Scotland and Ireland were freely mentioned in this connection not for wealthy countries like England ! (5) We sometimes attempt to refute a doctrine by tracing the absurd consequences that must result from it. This is called by scholastic logicians a reductio ad absurdum you reduce it to an ab- surdity. It is not necessary, however, in this mode of reasoning that the deduction should be absurd in the ordinary sense of the word. It is sufficient if it shows the unsoundness of the sentiment from which it is fairly inferred. Here is one from philosophy. If the thesis is, Man is a free agent, then the antithe- sis is, Man is not a free agent. . . . The indirect proof would take some such form as this : Man is either free or he is not free. Let us assume he is not free. If he is not free he cannot, in cases of conflicting motives, choose, but must blindly follow one of the impulses. But we know from consciousness that he can decide be- tween conflicting motives ; therefore it is false that he is not free. In the following passage Professor Greenleaf is arguing on behalf of the synoptical writers and the author of the Fourth Gospel : If, on the contrary, they are supposed to have been bad men, it is incredible that such men should have chosen this form of imposture : enjoining- as it does, un- feigned repentance, the utter forsaking and abhorrence of all falsehood and of every other sin, the practice of daily self-denial, self-abasement, and self-sacrifice, the LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 97 crucifixion of the flesh with all its earthly appetites and desires, indifference to the honours and hearty contempt of the vanities of the world, and inculcating perfect purity of heart and of life, and intercourse of the soul with heaven. It is incredible that bad men should in- vent falsehoods to promote the religion of the God of Truth. The supposition is suicidal. If they did believe in a future state of retribution, a heaven and hell here- after, they took the most certain course, if false wit- nesses, to secure the latter for their portion. And if, still being bad men, they did not believe in future punish- ment, how came they to invent falsehoods, the direct and certain tendency of which was to destroy all their pros- pects of worldly honour and happiness, and to ensure their misery in this life? From these absurdities there is no escape but in the perfect conviction and admission that they were good men, testifying to that which they had carefully observed and considered, and well knew to be true.* Sometimes we meet with zealous advocates who reduce their own principles to an absurdity by deducing from them extravagant conclusions. Socialist speakers very frequently fall into this error. If an absurd conclusion can be legitimately deduced from any alleged general principle, it is sufficient proof that the principle is unsound; but in cases of this kind we should carefully investigate the logical accuracy of the deduction, for weak and unbalanced advocates will sometimes make extrava- gant deductions from even sound principles. (6) Akin to the reduction ad absurdum is an expo- sure of the fallacy called " proving too much." * From Genung's Rhetoric, p. 430. 98 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION This fallacy is an argument that, if admitted to prove the point in dispute, would, if carried out to all its legitimate consequences, also prove other points that neither of the disputants admit to be true. As an example of proving too much, we may adduce all the arguments that go to prove the impropriety of closing the post- offices throughout the country on the Sunday; for if these arguments prove the point in regard to provincial towns, they also prove the propriety of opening the post-office on Sunday in London. But if the argument fails when applied to London, then, a fortiori, it must be inconclusive when applied to a country town. This argument can be resisted only by showing that there are peculiar circumstances in the country which do not apply to London. Cobden's arguments against granting loans to Russia proved too much ; for if it were immoral to lend money to the Czar because he might employ it to carry on war against the Hungarians, then by parity of reasoning it would be also immoral to have any transactions with him by which his finances might be improved. Hence all trade with Russia would cease. (7) Arguments founded on the advantages or dis- advantages that may result from any measure under consideration come under the head of reasonings from the relation of cause and effect. When I state the importance of the Colonies to this country, and the magnitude of danger hanging over this country from the present plan of maladministration LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 99 practised against them, I desire not to be understood to argue for a reciprocity of indulgence between England and America. I contend not for indulgence, but justice to America ; and I shall ever contend that the Americans justly owe obedience to us in a limited degree they owe obedience to our ordinances of trade and navigation; but let the line be skilfully drawn between the objects of those ordinances and their private internal property. . . When I urge this measure of recalling the troops from Boston, I urge it on this pressing principle, that it is necessarily preparatory to the restoration of your peace and the establishment of your prosperity.* These examples will suffice to show how moral causes, in the sense defined, are part and parcel of our daily interests. Here is a plea against early marriages, the argument being very interest- ing as a specimen of the early nineteenth century attitude : Lord Harewood, to get rid of the evil of over-crowd- ing in country villages, refuses to permit his cottage tenantry to take lodgers, or to allow a son or daughter to marry from the cottage, and continue to occupy it with the wife or husband conjointly with the parents. The first of these regulations is one with which every landlord is familiar. The offence lies in the second, which has been interpreted to mean a pro- hibition to the poor to marry : and some country newspaper talks about feudal laws, and we know not what besides. Now the regulation means nothing of the sort. It is a simple refusal on the part of Lord Hare- wood to permit persons to continue his tenants who marry without the power of having a house of their own. Now we are quite satisfied that it is the bounden duty of a landlord to put every check in his power upon the * Lord Brougham, House of Lords, 1775. ioo LOGIC FOR THE MILLION mania of the poor for headlong marriages. God forbid we should attempt to restrain them from marrying at all. But, in the name of morality and decency, let them wait till they have a chair and bed of their own. With- out question or doubt, nine-tenths of agrarian misery, pauperism, and crime, arise from the extraordinary hurry and recklessness of the poor in marrying early. It is a madness neither more nor less. A young woman in the country is never satisfied till she has got a sweet- heart. As soon as she has caught her Lubin, she must needs fix him, lest, as she says, " next time she should get a worse." And so, in one half-year, a tidy lad and decent lass become a couple of ragged, ill-looking, slovenly trampers. Let them only do as all other mem- bers of society do, from the top of the ladder down- wards, until it reaches themselves let them be patient and provident let them stay till they have bought a pot to boil their potatoes in, and a sack in advance many a couple begin life without either. The poor ob- tain a multitude of advantages by delay ; they start fair they learn carefulness they have an idea of comfort, and some notion of character; and, more than all Mal- thusian though the consideration be they will find four children much easier to bring up than fourteen. A landlord has an unquestioned right to keep bad characters from his cottages. He owes this duty to him- self and to his honester tenants. He has an equal right to exclude those who, from their circumstances, are cer- tain we use the word advisedly to become bad charac- ters. In the last case he may prevent, not the contagion alone, but the evil itself. If this right were used, cau- tiously and yet firmly, throughout the country, the vil- lages would not be what they are. CHAPTER X. THE RELATION OF CAUSE AND EFFECT CONDITIONAL CAUSES. A CONDITIONAL cause is a circumstance, or state of things, which is necessary to the production of an effect, but which does not actively produce that effect. Thus, if a man fall from his horse, it is a necessary condition that he should previously have been on his horse, otherwise he could not have fallen. If a man is hanged for forgery, the active or efficient cause of his being hanged is the com- mission of the crime; but if he had never learned to write, he could not have committed a forgery; hence his knowledge of writing is a necessary con- dition. As the condition does not thus actively, or necessarily produce the effect, we do not usually use the words "conditional cause" and "effect," but we say the "condition," and the "sign."* Thus, a physician feels the pulse of his patient, to ascertain the state of his health ; the state of health is the condition, the state of the pulse is the sign. Now, a man may be in a bad state of health, and yet his pulse may be regular : the exist- ence of the condition is no proof of the existence of the sign. But if the pulse be irregular, it shows * Or the condition and the consequent, or the antecedent and the consequent. 101 102 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION that the health is disturbed : the existence of the sign is proof of the existence of the condition. So it is a necessary condition to the performance of any act, that the man who performs it should be alive. Therefore, if a will is produced of a date some years subsequent to the death of the alleged testator, it proves that the will is a forgery. The man might have been alive without making a will, but he could not have made a will unless he had been alive. The condition must have preceded the consequent. (i) This relation of condition and sign supplies us with various modes of reasoning. From the non-existence of the condition, we infer the non-existence of the consequent. Qualifications, instruments, and opportunities are necessary conditions to the performance of any act. If we prove the absence of these we prove the non- performance of the act. If a man has committed murder, it is a necessary condition, that he should have been at the place when the murder was com- mitted, and at the time the murder was committed. Now, if he can prove an alibi (this word of course means elsewhere), that is, if he can prove that he was at a distant place at the time the murder was com- mitted, this proves that he did not commit the murder. The non-existence of the condition proves the non-existence of the sign. But you cannot reverse this rule. The existence of the condition will not of itself prove the existence of the sign ; for he might have been at the place where, and at the time when, the murder was committed, and LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 103 yet might not have committed the murder. It might have been committed by some of his com- panions. Again, from the existence of the sign we infer the existence of the condition. Take the same instance. If a man is proved to have committed a murder, it proves the condition, that he was at the place where, and at the time when, the murder was committed. But if it is proved that he did not commit the murder, that is in itself no proof that he was not present when the murder was committed. The non-existence of the sign is no proof of the non-existence of the con- dition. Sometimes it is contended in favour of a proposed measure, that it is a necessary condition, i.e., a conditional cause, to some other measure of still greater importance. Thus the Earl of Shaftesbury advocated in the House of Lords the establishment of Lodging Houses for the poor, upon the ground that domestic comfort is a necessary condition to their intellectual and moral improve- ment. Could their Lordships suppose that these physical evils produced no mischievous moral consequences ? He was sorry to have to inform them that they produced the most fatal and deadly consequences. They generated habits of drinking they led to the overthrow of decency. Every function of nature was performed in public there was no retirement for any purpose for any purpose; there was no domestic education nay education itself was useless, if children returned to their homes to un- learn by* example what they had learned elsewhere by precept. He grieved to reflect that in these dens there could be no domestic training of that description which 104 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION was more valuable than any other training the train- ing of the mother; and that the want of such domestic training could not be compensated by any system of public education which could be devised. This he saw daily. He had, as many of their lordships perhaps knew, been for some time connected with the ragged schools recently established in the metropolis. Most of the ragged children whom they saw about the streets attended those schools, and not, he trusted, without benefit. A young boy or girl received there useful lessons, but they returned to the single room, in which six families might be residing, without any regard to the restraints which were necessary for a social, moral, and religious life; and they lost, in one hour, all the decent impressions which they had gained in the pre- vious six. Until this source of evil were removed, all your hopes to improve the morals of your people, all your efforts to give them a useful and religious educa- tion, will be vain. You must stop this welling fountain of disaster, if you would carry into execution the benev- olent and provident views which you, in common with all who have property to protect, entertain towards the lower class. (2) You will observe that much erroneous reason- ing has taken place from confounding the conditional with the active cause. In cases where a number of causes, some active, and some only conditional, conspire to produce the same effect, it is not always easy to distinguish between the active and the conditional causes. This difficulty is often experienced in the investiga- tion of historical facts. Thus, it has been said that the Reformation was the cause of all the wars in Germany in the fifteenth century. The Reformation was certainly a condition, for if there had been no LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 105 Reformation, there could have been no fighting about it. But it was only the condition, the active cause of those wars was the interference of those hostile parties, who would not allow the people to follow the convictions of their own judgments. In the following argument the existence of the condition is insisted on as essential to the conse- quent. Men of excellent intentions and full of a fervent though mistaken zeal, have been, and still are, attempting to propagate their own religion among the inhabitants of barbarous countries. By strenuous and unremitting activity, and frequently by promises, and even by actual gifts, they have in many cases persuaded savage com- munities to make a profession of the Christian religion. But whoever will compare the triumphant reports of the missionaries with the long chain of evidence supplied by competent travellers will soon find that such profes- sion is only nominal, and that these ignorant tribes have adopted, indeed, the ceremonies of the new religion but have by no means adopted the religion itself. They re- ceive the externals but there they stop. They may bap- tise their children ; they may take the sacrament ; they may flock to the church. All this they may do and yet be as far removed from the spirit of Christianity as when they bowed the knee before their former idols. The rites and forms of a religion lie on the surface ; they are at once seen, they are quickly learned, easily copied by those who are unable to penetrate to that which lies beneath. It is this deeper and inward change which alone is durable ; and this the savage can never experience while he is sunk in an ignorance that levels him with the brutes by which he is surrounded. Remove the ignor- ance and then the religion may enter. This is the only course by which ultimate benefit can be effected.* * History of Civilisation, vol. i., p. 206. By H. T. Buckle. H 106 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION (3) This principle of reasoning is used very extensively in the examination of evidence adduced in our Courts of Law. Sometimes men are accused of crimes, to the perpetration of which there were no witnesses. Their guilt is inferred from the circumstances of the case. This is called "circumstantial evidence," and sometimes pre- sumptive evidence," as the guilt is presumed from the circumstances adduced. Some lawyers have maintained that circumstantial evidence is more conclusive than direct evidence, as there is no danger from the perjury of the witnesses. But others have thought differently. No certain rules can be given for circumstantial evidence. Each cause must depend upon itself. The reader will remember, that within recent years, several atro- cious criminals have been convicted upon circum- stantial evidence. The following are some general remarks on this kind of evidence: The force and effect of circumstantial evidence depend upon its incompatibility with, and incapa- bility of, explanation or solution upon any other supposition than that of the truth of the fact which it is adduced to prove ; the mode of argument resem- bling the method of demonstration by the reductio ad absurdum. These circumstances may be considered under the heads of motives to crime, declarations indi- cative of intention, preparations for the commis- sion of crime, possession of the fruits of crime, refusal to account for appearances of suspicion, or unsatisfactory explanations of such appearances, LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 107 evidence indirectly confessional, and the suppres- sion, destruction, simulation, and fabrication of evidence. The principal facts of circumstantial evidence of an external character, relate to questions of identity, (i) of person; (2) of things; (3) of hand- writing; and (4) of time; but there must necessarily be a number of isolated facts which admit of no more specific classification. Since an action without a motive would be an effect without a cause, a presumption is created in favour of innocence from the absence of all apparent inducement to the commission of the imputed offence. But the investigation of human motives is often a matter of great difficulty from their latency or remoteness; and experience shows that aggravated crimes are sometimes committed from very slight causes, and occasionally even without any apparent or discoverable motive. This par- ticular presumption would therefore seem to be applicable only to cases where the guilt of the indi- vidual is involved in doubt; and the consideration for the jury in general is rather whether upon the other parts of the evidence the party accused has committed the crime, than whether he had any adequate motive. Since falsehood, concealment, flight, and other like acts, are generally regarded as indications of conscious guilt, it naturally follows that the absence of these marks of mental emotion, and still more a voluntary surrender to justice, when the party had the opportunity of concealment or flight, must be considered as leading to the opposite presump- io8 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION tion : and these considerations are frequently urged with just effect as indicative of innocence; but the force of the latter circumstance may be weakened by the consideration that the party has been the object of diligent pursuit. It must be also remem- bered, that flight and other similar indications of fear may be referable to guilt of another and less penal character than that involved in the particular charge. If it be proved that a party charged with crime has been placed in circumstances which commonly operate as inducements to commit the act in ques- tion, that he has so far yielded to the operation of those inducements as to have manifested the disposition to commit the particular crime, that he has possessed the requisite means and opportuni- ties of effecting the object of his wishes, that recently after the commission of the act he has become possessed of the fruits or other consequen- tial advantages of the crime, if he be identified with the corpus delicti by any conclusive mechani- cal circumstances, as by the impressions of his footsteps, or the discovery of any article of his apparel or property at or near the scene of the crime, if there be relevant appearance of suspicion connected with his conduct, person, or dress, and such as he might reasonably be presumed to be able to account for, but which nevertheless he can- not or will not explain, if he be put upon his defence recently after the crime, under strong cir- cumstances of adverse presumption, and cannot show where he was at the time of its commission, if he attempt to evade the force of those circum- LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 109 stances of presumption by false or incredible pre- tences, or by endeavours to evade or pervert the course of justice by conduct inconsistent with the supposition of his innocence, the concurrence of all or of many of these cogent circumstances, unopposed by facts leading to a counter presump- tion, naturally, reasonably, and satisfactorily establishes the moral certainty of his guilt, if not with precisely the same kind of assurance as if he had been seen to commit the deed, at least with all the assurance which the nature of the case and the vast majority of human actions admit. In such circumstances we are justly warranted in adopting, without qualification or reserve, the conclusions to which, "by a broad, general, and comprehensive view of the facts, and not relying upon minute circumstances with respect to which there may be some source of terror," the mind is thus naturally and inevitably conducted, and in regarding the application of the sanctions of penal law as a mere corollary. Nor can any practice be more absurd and unjust, than that perpetuated in some modern codes, which, while they admit of proof by circum- stantial evidence, inconsistently deny to it its logical and ordinary consequences.* It may be observed that the conclusiveness of circumstantial evidence does not depend upon the force of any one circumstance, but upon the strength of the whole united. If we see a man coming out of a house, with blood on his clothes, that is no proof that he has committed murder. * Will's Principles of Circumstantial Evidence. i io LOGIC FOR THE MILLION There are many other ways in which his dress may have become bloody. But* if we enter the house, and find there a person who has the appearance of having been recently murdered, this causes the former individual to become suspected. If, again, you find the hat of this person in the house of the murdered man ; and when this person is appre- hended, he denies ever having been in the house; and, moreover, you find concealed in his dress some property proved to have belonged to the man who was murdered; now, putting these and similar circumstances together, you may have sufficient proof of the prisoner's guilt; for although you might easily assign other causes for any one of these circumstances separately, you cannot assign sufficient causes to account for them all, except on the supposition that the prisoner is the man who has committed the crime. In cases of this kind the prisoner's counsel exercises his ingenuity in assigning other causes to account for these criminating appearances. And some barristers think themselves justified in doing this, even after the prisoner has confessed his guilt. Lawyers of high standing have declared that such conduct is not, in their judgment, a violation of professional morality. It must also be observed, that if the circumstances brought in evidence against a prisoner can be accounted for on any other supposition than his guilt, he is entitled to an acquittal. The evidence must prove, not merely that he may be guilty, but that he must be guilty. The circumstances adduced must be wholly incompatible with the LOGIC FOR THE MILLION in supposition that he is innocent, and incapable of explanation upon any other hypothesis than that of his guilt. It is upon this kind of evidence that most criminals are convicted. As crimes are usually committed in secret, witnesses can rarely be obtained, and circumstantial evidence is the only evidence that can be adduced; and Providence seems always to have arranged that all great crimes shall in this way be brought to light. Plans hatched with consummate ingenuity, and in pro- found secrecy, have in their execution been attended with some slight oversight, which has supplied a thread by which the whole plot has been unravelled. True, some persons convicted upon circumstantial evidence have afterwards been proved to be inno- cent; so also persons convicted upon direct evidence have afterwards been proved to be innocent. If, on the one hand, circumstances may seem to war- rant an erroneous conclusion, on the other hand you may have mistaken or perjured witnesses. (4) Circumstantial evidence is part of the armoury of the Biblical critic. Below is a specimen of the way in which a theo- logian argues on behalf of the genuineness of an Old Testament record. Towards the end of the famine caused by this drought, Elijah is commanded by God to " get him to Zarephath, which belongeth to Zidon, and dwell there"; where a widow woman was to sustain him.* He goes : finds the woman gathering sticks near the gate of the city ; and asks her to fetch him a little water and a morsel of * i Kings xvii. 9. ii2 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION bread. She replies, " As the Lord thy God liveth, I have not a cake, but an handful of meal in a barrel, and a little oil in a cruse : and, behold, I am gathering two sticks, that I may go in and dress it for me and my son, that we may eat it, and die."' This widow-woman, then, it seems, dwelt at Zare- phath, or Sarepta, which belongeth to Zidon. Now, from a passage in the book of Joshua,! we learn that the district of Zidon, in the division of the land of Canaan, fell to the lot of Asher. Let us, then, turn to the thirty-third chapter of Deuteronomy, where Moses blesses the tribes, and see the character he gives of this part of the country : " Of Asher he said, Let Asher be blessed with children ; let him be acceptable to his breth- ren, and let him dip his foot in oil ";+ indicating the future fertility of that region, and the nature of its prin- cipal crop. It is likely, therefore, that at the end of a dearth of three years and a half, oil should be found there, if anywhere. Yet this symptom of truth occurs once mye as an ingredient in a miraculous history for the oil was made not to fail till the rain came. The inci- dent itself is a very minute one ; and minute as it is, only discovered to be a coincidence by the juxtaposition of several texts from several books of Scripture. It would require a very circumspect forger of the story to intro- duce the mention of the oil ; and when he had introduced it, not to be tempted to betray himself by throwing out some slight hint why he had done so. (5) Circumstantial evidence is employed too with reference to the affairs of ordinary life. Bankers, merchants, and traders judge by this kind of evidence of the solvency and responsibility of the parties with whom they deal. The actual * i Kings xvii. 12. t Josh. xix. 28. J Deut. xxxiii. 24. ^Undesigned Coincidences. By J. J. Blunt, B.D. amount of a man's property is probably known only to himself. His standing on the exchange or in the market will depend upon his personal character, his business habits, his conformity to established rules, and the extent to which he practises those moral virtues which are known to be the surest guide to wealth. We are told that "it is of great importance to a banker to have an ample knowledge of the means and transactions of his customers. The customer, when he opens his account, will give him some information on this subject. The banker will afterwards get information from his own books. The amount of transactions that his customer passes through his current account, will show the extent of his business. The amount of his daily balance will show if he has much ready cash. The extent and character of the bills he offers for discount, will show if he trust large amounts to individual houses, and if these are respectable. On the other hand, the bills his customer may accept to other parties, and his payments, will show the class of people with whom he deals, or who are in the habit of giving him credit."* Another banker observes that, " Next in importance to a study of his accounts, the habits and character of a client are deserving of your attentive consideration. If a man's style of living, for example, becomes extrava- gant, and he gives himself over to excess, you cannot too promptly apply the curb, however regu- lar the transactions upon his account may seem."f * Gilbart's Practical Treatise on Banking. t The Internal Management of a Country Bank. By Thomas Bullion. ii4 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION Now, this is judging from circumstantial evi- dence. By the same kind of evidence we are guided in our social adjudications. In this mode of reasoning we judge of the honesty of our servants, of the truthfulness of our children, and of many other transactions connected with social discipline. By this mode too we often judge of the sincerity of our friends, and of the character of public men. (7) Arguments are often expressed in a conditional form when they have no reference to the relation of conditional cause and effect. In these cases the relation is usually denoted by the words antecedent and consequent. The ante- cedent denotes what goes before, and the conse- quent denotes what follows after. The consequent is the result of the antecedent, or is a natural infer- ence from the antecedent. Thus, " If the sun is fixed centre of the solar system, the planets move round it." " No fire, no smoke." The truth of such propositions does not depend on the truth or falsehood of their two parts, but on the truth of the connection of them. The sun has a proper motion, and there is an appearance of smoke that does not come from fire. In many cases, indeed, we do not intend to denote any kind of condition or contingency, but adopt this form of reasoning merely because it is a more forcible way of stating the argument. Arguments from analogy, and a fortiori, as will be explained hereafter, are almost always expressed in this form, as well as those advanced in the way of objections. CHAPTER XI. THE RELATION OF CAUSE AND EFFECT FINAL CAUSES. OF late years the term " Final Cause " seems to have gone out of fashion. The design argument for the existence of a Supreme Being was subjected to a good deal of spirited criticism in the latter part of the nineteenth century, and it became almost improper to assume any kind of knowledge about the teleology of the universe i.e., the object or purpose for which it came into being, which is another way of saying what we mean by " final cause." Immediate causes become known to us in science, but as to the cause of all causes, we are pre- sumed to be entirely ignorant. In spite of our ignor- ance, however, we may still reason about the prob- lem on the basis of such small knowledge as we possess. But first, following a previous practice, we will reproduce some specimen arguments on final causes within the sphere of our more immediate knowledge, afterwards dealing at greater length with the larger issue. (i) The doctrine of final causes enters largely into the administration of the law. Sometimes this mode of reasoning is employed by the lawyers in fixing the meaning of an Act of Parliament. Our laws are-made by the legislature, but their meaning is fixed by the judges. It some- times happens that the wording is uncertain or ob- scure, and that one clause appears to contradict some other clause. In these cases the judges en- quire into the intention of the Act ; that is the inten- tion of the Legislature in passing the Act. This in- tention is sometimes called the spirit of the Act, and when a clause has two meanings the judges will decide in favour of that meaning which is most in conformity with the spirit of the Act. Take, for example, the Reform Act, passed in 1831. The in- tention of the act was to extend the privilege of voting for Members of Parliament. In case, there- fore, the meaning of any of the clauses should be doubtful, that meaning which is most favourable to the extension of the privilege of voting for Mem- bers of Parliament is most in conformity with the spirit of the act. If you watch the proceedings of the Courts of Law you will observe many cases illus- trative of this kind of reasoning. (2) In judicial cases, also, this principle of final causes is acknowledged. From the effects of any motive, the law infers the existence of the motive. If a man commits murder, the law assumes that he intended to commit mur- der. So, if a dozen persons, who never saw each other before, should join in an illegal act, they may be indicted for a conspiracy ; for their acting in con- cert will be considered as a proof of an intention to act in concert. In the case of Dr. Webster, who was hanged at Boston for the murder of Dr. Parkman, the follow- ing criticisms, in a prominent journal, aptly set forth the legal principles involved: Suppose the facts as stated in the confession had been proved by a witness present on the spot, but without the knowledge of the accused; and then apply the law as laid down by the Chief Justice, and which we see no reason to question. " In murder, to escape the imputation of malice, the prisoner must prove the provocation, the accident, or any other circumstance which goes to preclude the malice ; otherwise it is argued from the act itself. No provocation of words, however opprobious, will mitigate the motive for a mortal blow, or one intended to pro- duce death, where there is an intent to kill. If there is sufficient provocation, it is manslaughter; but words are not a sufficient provocation. Malice is implied from any deliberate, cruel act against another, however sudden. When there is a blow of a deadly weapon, with intent to do some great bodily harm, and death ensues, malice is presumed." Amongst the interstices of this net-work of distinctions, there may possibly be room to extricate the killing of Dr. Parkman from the category of murder ; but we confess the distinctions of the law seem framed to meet this very description of sudden, unjustifiable, passionate, revengeful, and reckless homicide. Were the contrary the case, few of the usual forms of murder would come within the definition. The confession of Dr. Webster may be only another link in the chain of fatali- ties which he has been forging for his own destruction. (3) Final causes form an important part of the investigation in cases of circumstantial evidence. If we show that the prisoner had a strong motive for committing the offence, such as avarice, re- ii8 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION venge, etc., or had stated beforehand a determina- tion that he would commit it, this, with other cir- cumstances, will be considered as tending to prove that he did commit it. Motives are, with relation to moral conduct, what phy- sical power is to mechanics ; and both of these kinds of impulse are equally under the influence of known laws. But in reasoning upon motives and their resulting actions, it is impracticable to obtain the same sure data as when material phenomena only are involved, since it is not possible to discover all the modifying circum- stances of human conduct, or to assign with unerring certainty the true character of the motives from which they spring. Nevertheless, we naturally, reasonably, and safely, judge of men's motives by their conduct, as we conclude from the nature of the stream the qualities of the fountain whence it proceeds. An evil motive con- stitutes in law, as in morals, the essence of guilt ; and the existence of an inducing motive for the voluntary acts of a rational agent, is assumed as naturally as secondary causes are concluded to exist for material phe- nomena. The predominant desires of the mind are in- variably followed by corresponding volitions and actions. It is therefore indispensable, in the investigation of moral actions, to look at all the surrounding circum- stances which connect the supposed actor with other persons and things, and may have influenced his motives. The usual inducements to crime, are the desire of re- venging real or fancied wrongs of obtaining some ob- ject of desire which rightfully belongs to another or of preserving reputation, either that of general character or the conventional reputation of sex or profession.* In many things which we do, we ought not only to consider the mere naked action itself, but the persons * Will's Circumstantial Evidence. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 119 who act, the persons towards whom, the time when, the place where, the manner how, the end /or which the action is done, together with the effects that must, or that may follow, and all other surrounding circum- stances : these things must necessarily be taken into our view, in order to determine whether the action, which is indifferent in itself, be either lawful or unlawful, good or evil, wise or foolish, decent or indecent, proper or improper, as it is so circumstantiated. Let me give a plain instance for the illustration of this matter. Mario kills a dog, which, considered merely in itself, seems to be an indifferent action : now the dog was Timon's, and not his own : this makes it look un- lawful. But Timon bid him do it ; this gives it an appear- ance of lawfulness again. It was done at church, and in time of divine service; these circumstances added, cast on it an air of irreligion. But the dog flew at Mario, and put him in danger of his life; this relieves the seeming impiety of the action. Yet Mario might have escaped by flying thence; therefore the action appears to be improper. But the dog was known to be mad ; this further circumstance makes it almost neces- sary that the dog should be slain, lest he might bite other people, and do much mischief. Yet again, Mario killed him with a pistol, which he happened to have in his pocket since yesterday's journey; now, hereby the whole congregation was terrified and discomposed, and divine service was broken off; this carries an appear- ance of great indecency and impropriety in it : but after all, when we consider a further circumstance, that Mario, being thus violently assaulted by a mad dog, had no way of escape, and had no other weapon about him, it seems to take away all the colours of impropriety, in- decency, or unlawfulness, and to allow that the preserva- tion of one or many lives will justify the act as wise and good. Now, all these concurrent appendices of the action ought to be surveyed, in order to pronounce with justice and truth concerning it. 120 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION (4) Under the head of final causes we may place those reasonings that are founded on the presumed object of the measures we advocate. Thus, in regard to the punishment of criminals, one party contends that the main object is the punishment of the criminal ; another contends that the main object is the reformation of the criminal ; and a third contends that the main object of punish- ment is the prevention of crime. The opinion any one may entertain as to the final cause or main object of punishment, will, of course, influence his sentiments as to the nature, duration, and severity of the punishments that ought to be inflicted. The proper end of punishment is said by some to be the satisfaction of justice; by others the prevention of crimes ; by others the reformation of the offender. The first doctrine is that which most immediately occurs to a mind beginning to reflect on the subject ; and it is often warmly defended, although it is now pretty nearly aban- doned by systematic writers on legislation. One of the last instances of a laboured defence of it, which we have met with, is to be found in a dissertation by Lord Wood- houselee, appended to his life of Lord Kames. The second opinion is supported by the generality of writers, although they by no means reject the third object, as a subordinate consideration. Of late years, a few philanthropists have argued, that the principal object of punishment should be the reformation of the offender, and that other ends are of inferior consequence. If crimes could be more effectually prevented by any one punishment than another, the tendency of that punishment to satisfy the demand for justice, or to re- form the offender, would be a secondary consideration. If the crime of murder, for example, could be more effectually prevented by the penalty of death than by a LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 121 term of imprisonment, which would give an opportunity for the reformation of the criminal, that penalty ought to be inflicted, and the reformation of the offender aban- doned, otherwise we should be showing more regard for the life of a murderer than for the lives of innocent persons. (5) Political economists sometimes argue upon this principle. They assign motives to different classes of society, and then infer that persons under the influence of such motives, would act in a cer- tain manner; and on the conduct thus assumed, they construct a theory. Thus Macculloch states that " the wish to aug- ment our fortunes comes with us from the womb, and never leaves us till we go into the grave." This may be the case generally in Scotland, but it is not so in Ireland, and it is not so universally anywhere. In all classes of society, many individuals are found who prefer present enjoyment to a future im- provement of their condition. Another erroneous assumption is, that the uninstructed classes of society, when left to themselves, will always do that which is most conducive to their own advantage. This argument has been advanced in opposition to those acts of the legislature that refer to regulating the hours of labour in the manufacturies, and to the working of women and children in mines. The reasonings of some economists, with reference to these matters, will, on examination, be found to rest on erroneous assumptions. "In tracing the progress of society, too, the econo- mists assume that mankind were originally savages, i 122 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION then became hunters, then shepherds, then agricul- turists, and at last merchants and manufacturers; and they attribute to mankind in these several stages precisely the same feelings and motives which men entertain in the highest degree of civili- sation. Such writers' theories are full of subtle fallacies. In the first place, the origins of civilisa- tion are more obscure than the origins of life itself; and in the second place, savages have no thirst for knowledge and the improvement of circumstances. But the opinion that all mankind were originally savages, is unsupported by either reason or history. Had they been created savages, they would proba- bly have remained savages for ever. They could have formed no idea of a civilisation which had never existed, nor have desired comforts, the want of which they did not feel. History does not record a single instance of a savage nation having become civilised by its own unassisted exertions. Civilisa- tion has never sprung up spontaneously from the soil ; it has always been imported from abroad. The Greeks derived their civilisation from the Egyptians ; the Romans theirs from the Greeks; the nations conquered by Rome became civilised from their in- tercourse with the Romans. But if we attempt to trace the origin of civilisation in Egypt and Baby- lon, we are at a loss; for neither history, nor even tradition, mentions any period at which these nations were not civilised. Founded in an inscrutable past, they possessed the knowledge of all the arts and sciences known to the antediluvian world. The fertility of their soils, and the extent of their plains, furnished ample provision for their population : LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 123 hence, as population increased, their civilisation in- creased. While, on the other hand, those tribes or families who wandered in quest of new settle- ments, became separated from the rest of mankind by mountains, and forests, and rivers ; and their time being wholly occupied in seeking supplies of food, they lost, in the course of a few generations, the knowledge they originally possessed, and fell into the savage state. It would thus appear, from his- tory and from reason, that the savage state was not the original state of man, but a departure from that state, arising from a want of communication through several ages with the other branches of the family of mankind." (Gilbart.) (6) As all actions result from the feelings of the mind, when we wish to induce any person to per- form certain actions, we try to produce in the mind those convictions and feelings which are the usual cause of such actions. It is the great object of logic to teach us how to select and use those arguments that have an effect upon the judgment and understanding. But some- times people are influenced more by their feelings than by their judgment. In this case, if we wish to convince or persuade them, we must adapt our arguments to their feelings. The parties who are thus influenced by their passions can hardly be said to reason ; but we who are trying to influence them may be reasoning nevertheless. We are using a means to accomplish an end ; we are selecting such arguments, and placing them in such a form, as are best adapted to produce an impression on the 124 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION mind of the individual with whom we converse. These arguments are outlined below : There is yet another rank of arguments which have Latin names; their true distinction is derived from the topics or middle terms which are used in them, though they are called an address to our judgment, our faith, our ignorance, our profession, our modesty, and our pas- sions. If an argument be taken from the nature or ex- istence of things, and addressed to the reason of man- kind, it is called argumentum ad judicium. When it is borrowed from some convincing testimony, it is argu- mentum ad fidem, an address to our faith. When it is drawn from any insufficient medium whatsoever, and yet the opposer has not skill to refute or answer it, this is argumentum ad ignorantiam, an address to our ignor- ance. When it is built upon the professed principles or opinions of the person with whom we argue, whether the opinions be true or false, it is named argumentum ad hominem, an address to our professed principles. St. Paul often uses this argument when he reasons with the Jews, and when he says, " I speak as a man." When the argument is built upon the sentiments of some wise, great, or good men, whose authority we reverence and hardly dare oppose, it is called argumentum ad vere- cundium, an address to our modesty. I add finally, When an argument is borrowed from any topics which are suited to engage the inclinations and passions of the hearers on the side of the speaker, rather than to con- vince the judgment, this is argumentum ad passiones, an address to the passions; or, if it be made publicly, it is called ad populum, or an appeal to the people. The argument called Argumentum ad hominem requires a further illustration : Sometimes we may make use of the very prejudices under which a person labours, in order to convince him of some particular truth and argue with him upon his LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 125 own professed principles as though they were true. This is called argumentum ad hominem, and is another way of dealing with the prejudices of men. Suppose a Jew lies sick of a fever, and is forbidden flesh by his physician ; but hearing that rabbits were provided for the dinner of the family, desired earnestly to eat of them; and suppose he became impatient be- cause his physician did not permit him, and he insisted upon it, that it could do him no hurt; surely, rather than let him persist in that fancy and that desire, to the danger of his life, I would tell him that these animals were strangled, which sort of food was forbidden by the Jewish law, though I myself may believe that law is now abolished. Encrates used the same means of conviction when he saw a Mahometan drink wine to excess, and heard him maintain the lawfulness and pleasure of drunkenness : Encrates reminded him that his own prophet Mahomet had utterly forbidden all wine to his followers : and the good man restrained his vicious appetite by his super- stition, when he could no otherwise convince him that drunkenness was unlawful, nor withhold him from excess ! (7) The effects of circumstances upon the disposi- tion of the mind may fairly be placed under this head, and they enter largely into our daily reason- ings. On this ground Lord Erskine advocated his bill for preventing cruelty to animals. In what I am proposing to your lordships, disin- terested virtue, as in all other cases, will have its own certain reward. The humanity you shall extend to the lower creation will come abundantly round in its conse- quences to the whole human race. The moral sense, which this law will awaken and inculcate, cannot but 126 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION have a most powerful effect upon our feelings and sym- pathies for one another. The violences and outrages committed by the lower orders of the people, are offences more owing to want of thought and reflection than to any malignant principle; and whatever, therefore, sets them a-thinking upon the duties of humanity, more especially where they have no rivalries nor resentments, and where there is a peculiar generosity in forbearance and compassion, has an evident tendency to soften their natures, and to moderate their passions in their deal- ings with one another. The effect of laws, which pro- mulgate a sound moral principle, is incalculable ; I have traced it in a thousand instances, and it is impossible to describe its value. In conformity with this principle, if a man has received a good education, we expect to find him well informed; if he has mixed in good society, we presume his manners are courteous ; if he has held certain positions in society, we infer that he has the excellencies, and probably the defects, con- nected with that position ; and if we are wise, we shall consider the peculiar temptations to which our own circumstances expose us, and endeavour to guard our minds against them. Different employments, and different conditions of life, beget in us a tendency to our different passions. Those who are exalted above others in their daily stations, and especially if they have to do with many persons under them, and in many affairs, are too often tempted to the haughty, the morose, the surly, and the more unfriendly ruffles and disturbances of nature, unless they watch against them with daily care. The commanders in armies and navies, the governors of workhouses, the masters of public schools, or those who have a great number of servants under them, and a multitude of cares LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 127 and concerns in human life, should continually set a guard upon themselves, lest they get a habit of affected superiority, pride, and vanity of mind, of fretfulness, impatience, and criminal anger. Upon this ground, we avoid the dangerous social element, because we instinctively prefer a suitable environment. And here I would advise you to have no dealings with a man who is known to be a rogue, even though he should offer a bargain that may, in that instance, be for your advantage to accept. To avoid him is your duty, on the ground of morality; but it is, moreover, your in- terest in a pecuniary point of view : for, depend upon it, although he may let you get money by him at first, he will contrive to cheat you in the end. An additional reason is, that your own reputation, and even your moral sensibilities, may be endangered by the contact. If you get money by a rogue, there is a danger that you will feel disposed to apologize for his rogueries; and, when you have once become an apologist for roguery, you will probably, on the first temptation become a rogue yourself. (8) The doctrine of final causes also enters largely into our reasonings on the nature and character of the human mind, and on the circumstances by which we are surrounded. From the properties, or qualities, or faculties of the mind, we infer the existence of a corresponding design. Alan has a capacity for being happy we infer he was designed to be happy. Man has a capacity for acquiring knowledge we infer he was designed to acquire knowledge. Man has feelings 4^ L* 128 and capacities adapted for society we infer he was designed to live in society. (9) In the same way, from the attributes, quali- ties, and capacities of the animal creation, we infer the design or final cause of their creation. All the wonderful instincts of animals, which, in my humble opinion, are proved beyond a doubt, and the belief in which has not decreased with the increase of science and investigation all these instincts are given them only for the combination or preservation of their species. If they had not these instincts, they would be swept off the earth in an instant. This bee, that under- stands architecture so well, is as stupid as a pebble- stone, out of his own particular business of making honey; and, with all his talents, he only exists that boys may eat his labours, and poets sing about them. Ut pueris placeas et declamatio fias. A peasant girl of ten years old puts the whole republic to death with a little smoke; their palaces are turned into candles, and every clergyman's wife makes mead-wine of the honey; and there is an end of the glory and wisdom of the bees ! Whereas, man has talents that have no sort of reference to his existence; and without which, his species might remain upon earth in the same safety as if they had them not. The bee works at that particular angle which saves most time and labour ; and the boasted edifice he is con- structing is only for his egg : but Somerset House, and Blenheim, and the Louvre, have nothing to do with breeding. Epic poems, and Apollo Belvideres, and Venus de Medicis, have nothing to do with living and eating. We might have discovered pig-nuts without the Royal Society, and gathered acorns without reasoning about curves of the ninth order. The immense super- fluity of talent given to man, which has no bearing upon animal life, which has nothing to do with the mere pre- servation of existence, is one very distinguishing circum- LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 129 stance in this comparison. There is no other animal but man to whom mind appears to be given for any other purpose than the preservation of body.* The following argument, from the relation of final cause and effect, has been advanced in favour of sporting : As Nature, with a liberal but not lavish hand, has bestowed on her offspring those powers and propensities only, which their own necessities, or the general order and economy of the system require; the gifts of scent to the hound, swiftness to the greyhound, and sagacity to the pointer, denote the use which she intended man to make of these animals ; and, therefore, the diversions in question are justifiable, as fulfilling the intentions of Nature herself. (10) It is a principle of ethics that the final cause, or motive, of an action decides its essentially moral quality. There can be no doubt that motive is of the essence of morality, but an ethical idea, to be com- plete, must eventuate in some form of expression, otherwise it can only be judged as an idea. This admission implies a higher tribunal of judgment than that which takes note of actions and the motives that caused them. For there are people who intend to murder other people in the spirit of revenge, and yet never have the chance of carrying out their evil designs. A citizen may harbour the worst thoughts in the world, and yet so long as he does not act them he is regarded as a model citizen. Similarly another citizen may have the best thoughts and intentions and yet have no oppor- * Sydney Smith's Sketches of Moral Philosophy. 130 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION tunity of putting the most altruistic of them into practice. Further, a third citizen may follow the principle of doing evil that good may come. Per- haps he lands himself and others in disaster. Here the motive, the final cause, is weighed and the result is judged accordingly. The person who " means well " may be a most unpleasant and un- profitable person, but occasional specimens of his type do not invalidate the doctrine that motive is of the essence of morality. The great question in all conduct is : Why do we act as we do ? (11) In regard to the Universe and its purpose, modern thought readily confesses its inability to say what that purpose is : the real question for us, how- ever, is whether logic can be used to discuss the existence or non-existence of a purpose. It is difficult to see how such a discussion can be legitimately refused, for if we ask " the reason why " of a part of the Universe, such as the cause of a solar system, it follows that we may ask ourselves why the Universe exists at all what is its object and what is its destiny. Here are some arguments for and against. (a) That the world displays Intelligence and is Intelligible. I allow you to doubt all things if you wish till you come to the point where doubt denies itself. Doubt is an act of intelligence; only an intelligent agent can doubt. It as much demands intellect to doubt as it does to believe to deny as it does to affirm. Universal doubt, therefore, is an impossibility, for doubt cannot, if it would, doubt the intelligence that doubts, since to doubt that would be to doubt itself. You cannot doubt that you doubt, and then, if you doubt, you know that LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 131 you doubt, and there is one thing at least you do not doubt, namely, that you doubt. To doubt the intelli- gence that doubts would be to doubt that you doubt, for without intelligence there can be no more doubt than belief. Intelligence then, you must assert, for without intelligence you cannot even deny intelligence, and denial of intelligence by intelligence contradicts itself and affirms intelligence in the very act of denying it. Doubt then as much as you will, you must still affirm intelli- gence as the condition of doubting or of asserting the possibility of doubt, for what is not, cannot act. . . . Intelligence is inconceivable without the intelligence or some object capable of being known. The intelligence is, therefore, something which is, is being, real being too, not merely abstract or possible being, for without the real there is and can be no possible or abstract. The intelligible must be asserted as real, not as abstract or merely possible being. The real being thus asserted is either necessary and eternal being, being in itself, sub- sisting by and from itself or it is contingent and there- fore created being. Whatever is, is either necessary and eternal, or contingent and created, is either being in itself, absolute being, or existence dependent on another for its being and, therefore, is not without the necessary and eternal on which it depends. If you say it is necessary and eternal being you say it is God; if you say it is contingent being, you still assert the neces- sary and eternal, therefore God, because the contingent is neither possible nor intelligible without the necessary and eternal. From this it follows that in every act of intelligence God is asserted.* (b) That the morality of the Universe is not our morality : and that its design, if it has one, is inhuman. When you tell me God is good you can only mean he * Notes on Ingersoll. L. A. Lambert. 132 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION is good as I understand goodness. Very well, then, ex- amine the goodness of the universe from the human sense of what is good and bad : what follows ? Simply this, that from time immemorial men have condemned the morality of Nature, " red in tooth and claw." Even civilisation, part of Nature's development, allows the evil to overcome the good. These things turned men into pessimists, and Buddhism is a religion of sorrow, arising out of the troubles and griefs of this mortal life. So intense has become the criticism of man on his sur- roundings that modern science now says Nature is un- moral : it is neither good nor bad. Whatever it may be essentially, from our point of view it is a strange mix- ture of good and bad ; and we cannot think that God is half as kind as a really kind-hearted man, or he would have made a world in which virtue was easier and vice more difficult, where justice would have reigned supreme, and where there would be no premium on might as right. It is useless to tell me the Why of the Universe will be revealed in a later life. By that time this life will be over. What is the good of a key to unlock a mystery that no longer exists? The whole scheme is inhuman. Teleology, the science of final causes, is still where Kant left it. Probably it will remain there, for the best we can do is to regard the world as in- telligently and morally well based, at least in prac- tical life, for otherwise action loses much of its significance. On the other hand its purpose in- vites our discussion, and theoretically that purpose may be held to be either insoluble, or good, or evil, or both. CHAPTER XII. THE USE OF WORDS IN REASONING. THE novice in the art of reasoning will not have gone far ere he discovers the importance of defining words; at any rate, to the extent of giving them the same meaning as does his opponent. It is at once humorous and annoying to find at the end of an hour's argument that the two words which con- stitute the real bone of contention have been used with two totally different meanings; and disputants with a keen sense of the value of time are not likely on a second occasion to give themselves the dubious pleasure of wasted breath. Watts affirms that, " As we are led into the knowledge of things by words, so we are oftentimes led into error, or mis- take, by the use or abuse of words. And in order to guard against such mistakes, as well as to pro- mote our improvements in knowledge, it is neces- sary to acquaint ourselves a little with words and terms. Words, whether spoken or written, have no natural connexion with the ideas they are designed to signify, nor with the things which are represented in those ideas. There is no manner of affinity between the sounds white in English, or blanc in French, and the colour which we call by that name ; nor have the letters, of which these words 133 134 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION are composed, any natural aptness to signify that colour rather than red or green. Words and names therefore are mere arbitrary signs invented by men to communicate their thoughts or ideas to one another. Words and terms are either univocal or equi- vocal. Univocal words are such as signify but one idea, or at least but one sort of thing; equivocal words are such as signify two or more different ideas, or different sorts of objects. The words book, bible, fish, house, elephant, may be called univocal words; for I know not that they signify anything else but those ideas to which they are generally affixed ; but head is an equivocal word, for it signifies the head of a nail, or of a pin, as well as of an animal : nail is an equivocal word, it is used for the nail of the hand, or foot, and for an iron nail to fasten anything. Post is equivocal, it is a piece of timber, or a swift messenger. A church is a religious assembly, or the large fair building where they meet; and sometimes the same word means a synod of bishops, or of presbyters; and in some places it is the pope and a general council. Here let it be noted, that when two or more words signify the same thing, as wave and billow, mead and meadow, they are usually called synonymous words ; but it seems very strange that words, which are directly contrary to each other, should some- times represent almost the same ideas; yet thus it is in some few instances : a valuable or an invalu- able blessing; a shameful, or a shameless villain; a thick skull, or a thin-skulled fellow a mere paper LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 135 skull ; a man of a large conscience, little conscience, or no conscience; a famous rascal, or an infamous one. So uncertain a thing is human language, whose foundation and support is custom. As words signifying the same thing are called synonymous, so equivocal words, or those which signify several things, are called homonymous, or ambiguous; and when persons use such ambiguous words with a design to deceive, it is called equivo- cation. In your own studies, as well as in the communication of your thoughts to others merely for their information, avoid ambiguous and equi- vocal terms as much as possible. Do not use such words as have two or three definitions of the name belonging to them ; that is, such words as have two or three senses, where there is any danger of mis- take. Where your chief business is to inform the judgment, and to explain a matter, rather than to persuade or affect, don't express yourself in figura- tive language, when there are any proper words that signify the same idea in their literal sense. When we communicate our notions to others, merely with a design to inform and improve their knowledge, let us, at the outset, take care to adjust the definition of names, where necessary; that is, to determine plainly what we mean by the chief words; and be sure always to keep the same ideas whensoever we use the same words, unless we give due notice of the change. This will secure others and ourselves from confusion and mistake ; for even writers and speakers, for want of due watchfulness, are ready to affix different ideas to their own words, in different parts of their discourses, and thereby 136 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION bring perplexity into their own reasonings, and confound their hearers. In communicating your notions, use every word as near as possible in the same sense in which mankind commonly use it; or which writers who have written before you have usually affixed to it, upon condition that it is free from ambiguity. Though names are in their original merely arbi- trary, yet we should always keep to the established meaning of them, unless great necessity requires the alteration ; for when any word has been used to signify an idea, that old idea will recur in the mind when the word is heard or read, rather than any new idea which we may fasten to it. And this is one reason why the received definition of names should be changed as little as possible." We will take an instance : The word " classic " is generally used to denote, according as the object refers to languages or books, those of the highest excellence. Thus when we speak of the classical languages we refer exclusively to the Greek and Latin, because these tongues have always been considered by Europeans as exemplars after which they might approve their own. In like manner we refer to the works of Milton or Dryden, Racine or Boileau, as English and French classics, the productions of these authors being ranked as the best of their kind by the general body of their countrymen. Nevertheless, the canon of what is classic utterance in literature is not even yet a transparent fact; and St. Beuve tried to solve the problem in his essay, entitled: "What is a classic? '- There are professors who are quite sure LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 137 certain books are classical performances, and other professors who are equally sure they are not. But the less important words of the language are open to the same objection. " Common speech is a quicksand," to use the expression of Minto. " In geometry we learn the definitions of the words used point, line, parallel, etc. before we proceed to use them. But in common speech we learn words first in their application to individual cases. No- body ever defined good to us, or fair, or kind, or highly educated. We hear the words applied to individual objects : we utter them in the same con- nexion : we extend them to other objects that strike us without knowing the precise points of likeness that the convention of common speech includes.* Nowadays few words have a more extensive vogue than Socialism. Everybody uses it, and yet it has not the same meaning even among the socialists themselves. This disadvantage it shares with many other political terms, and it was to provide a remedy that Sir George Cornewall Lewis wrote his Use and Abuse of Political Terms and Methods of Observation and Reasoning in Politics. A few examples from the former treatise will suit- ably illustrate this chapter. Take the word tyranny. To the socialist, capi- talism is a great tyranny : to the capitalist there could be no worse tyranny than that of strictly democratic rule, with uninstructed men occupying the chief places. Now, although these two men may agree on one issue, namely, that an absolute * Logic, Inductive and Deductive. K 138 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION monarchy is, or may be, the source of most cruel oppression, they probably are not agreed as to the advantage of a limited monarchy ; the socialist is for a real republic, the capitalist votes for a heredi- tary ruler. But both of them have an undefined belief that tyranny is less associated with free government than with autocratic government. And yet facts do not confirm that view. Burke said that "free governments have committed more flagrant acts of tyranny than the most perfect despotic governments which we have ever known." Locke said: "It is a mistake to think this fault [viz., tyranny] is proper only to monarchies; other forms of government are liable to it as well as that : for wherever the power is put in any hands for the government of the people and the preservation of their properties, is applied to other ends, and made use of to impoverish, harass, or subdue them to the arbitrary and irreguW commands of those that have it; there it presently becomes tyranny whether those that use it are one or many." The fallacy underlying the common use of the word is twofold : that tyranny is the oppression of one man, or one class ; and that free institutions can prevent it. Take another word : Nature. The number of uses to which this word is put is almost bewilder- ing, and, of course, the same remark applies to its cognates. " Women have a natural right to the vote," we hear it said. Here are two important words natural and right. On this point Lewis says: "The phrase, natural right, takes its origin from the doctrine of a state of nature. ... It LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 139 appears to signify a claim recommended by natural law, or by those rules which were recognised by common consent when mankind were in a state of nature." Hence woman, whatever rights they may claim politically, have no natural right to exercise a vote : what they mean is an indefeasible right, one that already is theirs, but which they are not allowed to use. But "an indefeasible right is a right which man enjoyed in a state of nature, and which he only surrendered conditionally at the making of the social compact." Therefore, since woman, as a sex, never enjoyed the political posi- tion to which they aspire, no political wrong is being done to them by withholding the vote; that is to say, their rights are neither natural nor inde- feasible : they must be argued on other grounds altogether. Lewis devotes many pages to the analysis of this word right. He quotes from Boswell, who recorded a conversation by Johnson : " Every man has a right to liberty of conscience, and with that the magistrate cannot interfere. People confound liberty of thinking with liberty of talking; nay, with liberty of preaching. Every man has a physical right to think as he pleases; for it cannot be dis- covered how he thinks. He has not a moral right, for he ought to inform himself and think justly." Here physical right (argues Lewis) must mean po-wer; moral right appears to mean legal right, for Johnson never could have intended to say that a man is in conscience bound to conceal opinions which he thinks true. On another occasion he said that " There seems to be in authors a stronger right 140 of property than that by occupancy ; a metaphysical right, a right, ac it were, of creation, which should from its nature be perpetual." This expression is manifestly founded on the erroneous supposition that a right to a tangible is more corporeal than a right to an intangible object; but elsewhere he uses a more common epithet when, speaking of government, he says that " if the abuse be enor- mous, Nature will rise up, and, claiming her original rights, overturn a corrupt political sys- tem." It is, however, a contradiction to speak of original rights, if by original is meant anterior to government, for . . . the notion that right is ' alto- gether an abstract thing which is independent of human laws and institutions ' is not only not true, but the direct contrary of the truth."* The reader who may perchance have given this matter but little consideration will now see that it is not a mere question of abstruse philology, worthy of the attention of scholars alone, but a really practical issue, one that he will be called upon to face when reading his lawyer's agreements, when trying to decide whether to vote for free trade or tariff reform, or when dealing with the affairs of his business. Edward Johnson, a lively critic of the last century, says: "If the legislators of a country would but first settle among themselves what is to be uniformly understood by such words as right, wrong, good, bad, better, justice, im- provement, reform, honour, dishonour, law, prin- ciple, etc., I think it is clear that much sound * Use and Abuse of Political Terms, p. 32. knowledge would take the place of much ridiculous opinion, that good argument would succeed to a mere noisy jargon, and confusion and much misery be superseded by good order and an increase of human happiness. It would no longer happen, as it does now, that the morality of one man is heinous in the eyes of another that the right of to-day is the wrong of to-morrow that what one man considers improvement another believes to be deterioration that justice often becomes injustice honour, dishonour principle, no principle at all and law itself unlawful."* If our political quar- rels are wordy, and about words (for they are all aiming at the " best interests of the nation "), so are our quarrels in theology, in philosophy, in ethics, in practical sociology, and a host of other matters. The lesson is simple, but difficult : simple to understand, difficult to carry out. It is this always define your terms. If more attention were given to definitions at the beginning of an article or a speech, there would be less trouble, fewer disagreements, and a vast saving of time. * Nuces Philosophies ; or, the Philosophy of Things as developed -from the study of the Philosophy of Words. CHAPTER XIII. ON SOCRATIC DISPUTATION. WHEN Socrates argued with his friends it was not after the manner of a modern disputant who defends a position against all comers; it was by means of cross examination. He asked his friends what they meant by the words used to set forth their ideas ; he tested their opinions by analysing the component parts and by showing their lack of harmony with other opinions expressed previously : he generally proved to his friends that they did not see through the veil of language to the clear idea ; or, if they did, that the idea itself could not be justified. His method was to put every alleged truth into the wit- ness box. A good example is to be found in the dia- logue called Menon. The characters are Socrates, Menon, and his son Anytus. The opening question is addressed to Socrates: "Can you tell me, So- crates, whether virtue can or cannot be taught, or is only acquired by practice, or in neither way, but comes to men naturally?" Socrates begs Menon to tell what virtue is. Menon declares that a man's virtue is fitness for political business and causing yourself or your friends to do well and your enemies ill; while a woman's virtue is taking care of her household, her husband, and her children. Socrates 142 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 143 considers himself in luck in having lighted on a swarm of virtues, but what he wants to know is, what is the essence of virtue? He asks, "Is it possible to administer a state or family well, if not doing it wisely or justly ? He must point out the generic idea, not the concrete example of figure, colour, and limit." Menexenus questions Socrates and is rallied by him as not willing "to tell what Georgias sa>s about virtue, and on his agreeable outside, while he thinks little of Socrates' personal recommendations. He is asked if he believes in the effluxes and pores of Empedocles, what vision is, hearing and smell, all which Menon professes to be able to explain. Socrates begs him to tell about virtue as a whole. Menon says it is a joying in beautiful things and the being able to procure a supply. Socrates asks, Do not all men desire good ? Menon thinks not, but that some desire evil. Can they do this knowing them to be evil. Do people wish to be wretched ? Again Socrates presses to be told what virtue is as a whole. On this Menon complains that Socrates, as he has before heard, is always doubting and causing others to doubt; that he is befooling and drugging and benumbing him like a flat fish, the torpedo, and asserts he has avoided foreign travel with reason. Socrates who a second time twits Menon on the score of personal vanity, asserts that he does not make others doubt when himself not in perplexity, but because he is really in doubt and does not know. "But how," asks Menon, "will you know, when you light on a result, that this is what you did not know?" The danger of this 144 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION argument is alluded to. Socrates declares that he has heard from men and women about divine things, and then introduces the subject of the soul's immortality and his doctrine of reminiscence ex- planatory of his desire to investigate with Menon what virtue is. Socrates will not be led to contra- dict himself by any craft of Menon's. Hereupon he summons one of the attendants of the latter to put his doctrine to the proof. The examination of the boy is continued, and the infer- ences to be drawn from the latent knowledge elicited are stated. It is proved that the boy has in him right opinions : that if he did not gain this know- ledge in this life, it was in an antecedent time. This remembrance must be stirred in us; we shall be the better for seeking to know what we do not know. Socrates thinks that before we seek whether virtue can be taught, we should strive to know what it is. Here occurs a geometrical puzzle. If virtue is knowledge, it can be taught. What other than virtue shall we declare good to be ? What are the things of use to us? Are they not health, strength, beauty, and money ? And yet we talk sometimes of these as beautiful ! Is it not the right use of these that is profitable? Does not fortitude sometimes become rashness ? It is phronesis that makes virtue of advantage. This being so, men cannot be good by nature. If it were so, we should have had connoisseurs of virtue who would have put a stamp on the genuine article. If virtue is to be taught, must there not be teachers ? Here Anytus drops in. Should we not go and fee the sophists? But Anytus protests against this. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 145 Socrates asks if he is to believe that Protagoras, who has got together what Phidias and ten of the best statuaries have not earned, cannot teach virtue, and declare it a sham that a man should have been duping people for forty years when a cobbler or old-clothes man would have been detected and punished. Anytus says that it is not the sophists who are mad, but the fools who give them money, and is asked by Socrates whether they have ever injured him that he inveigfcs so against them. How is he to know if he has had no intercourse with them ? Any one, Anytus declares, can make a pupil good, better than the sophists. Socrates on this asks whether any of the great and good men referred to are such spontaneously or from teaching. No doubt there have been, and still are, such in the state. But have these men received it from others, and can they transmit it? Take the case of Themistocles : you know he taught his son Cleophantus all that could be taught, but did you ever hear that he was his father's equal or superior ? Again, take Aristides, son of Lysimachus, or Paralus and Xanthus, the two sons of Pericles- That you may not think the failure was in the case of inferior persons, take the case of Thucydides and his two sons, Melesias and Stephanus. Surely Thucydides, with all the advantages of wealth and rank, would have succeeded if any one could ; but no virtue is not to be taught. Socrates again turns to Menon, and asks whether in his city the nobles teach youth virtue? Menon admires Georgias because he does not promise to make his pupils virtuous only smart. 146 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION Passing on, we get to another turn in the dis- cussion on the value of right opinion as hardly inferior to knowledge as a ground of action ; true opinions, when chained by the runaway statues of Daedalus becoming permanent, and not differing from knowledge except in the matter of chain. Right opinions are good as long as they last, but they run from the soul like fugitive slaves. The explanation of true opinion is still carried on, but it is still denied that virtue can be taught. Socrates asserts that Themistocles and others did not govern the state as being wise, nor through perfect know- ledge, but by correct opinion. They differ nothing from oracle chaunters, but are divinely inspired, gifted men, who, apart from knowledge, direct successfully many and great affairs under a guid- ance not their own. Virtue really comes to us by a divine allotment, not inherited by nature, not acquired by teaching. A statesman who could make others statesmen, would be among the living what Homer says Tiresias was among the dead a true substance among shadows. But though virtue comes by divine allotment, we shall never know how it comes to be present among men till we know what it is absolutely in itself.* In this much condensed outline the reader who is not already familiar with Plato's dialogues will obtain a fair notion of the method employed and of the results obtained. It was employed largely by the late St. George Mivart in his Philosophical * Davy's Summary of Plato, p. 133. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 147 Catechism and Nature and Thotight. From the former book I select the following: Self-Evident Truths. Can everything be proved? Manifestly not. However long may be our argu- ments, we must ultimately come to the statements which must be taken for granted. Must we then found our arguments on proposi- tions which we believe blindly ? By no means; for the truth of such propositions is self-evident, and if it is not blind to believe what is evident to us by means of something else, it must be much less blind to believe that which is directly evident in and by itself. Give me some examples of self-evident truths. My own existence ; that the whole is greater than its part; that things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one another; that nothing can be and not be at the same time; and the conclusion of every logically drawn deduction every valid syllogism. Is not syllogistic reasoning fallacious its con- clusions being a mere repetition of part of the major premiss ? Certainly not : its conclusion imparts knowledge, which is brought to the mind by the explicit recog- nition of a truth implicitly contained in the minor premiss. This is done by recognising the fact that an object has certain characters inasmuch as it belongs to a certain class. But if any one knows a truth in which others 148 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION are contained implicity, does he not know these latter also ? Not at all, otherwise a man by knowing the definitions and axioms of Euclid would thereby also know all the propositions relating to circles and triangles which are implicitly contained in those definitions and axioms. Have you any reason to urge ? Yes. It sometimes happens that a general prin- ciple is more evident than a particular example which comes under it, and our judgment as to the latter may be much aided by viewing it in the light of the former. Can you explain how it is that many persons think that to believe anything on its own evidence is to believe it blindly? In this way. Most of this knowledge is gained by inference, and therefore persons have come to associate the "inferred" with the "not blind," and so think that everything we believe without proof must be believed by us blindly, while that which conies to us as the result of a reasoning process is not believed blindly. Are not, however, our senses what we must appeal to in the last resort as the supreme tests of truth? No, for it is by our intellect that we know we have and do employ our senses, and it is our intel- lect which must judge when different sense impres- sions conflict. Thus self-conscious reflective thought, and not sense, is our ultimate and absolute criterion. We may call this ultimate act of intel- lectual perception "intellectual intuition." LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 149 Do you then distrust your own senses? Not at all : I firmly believe that the certainty of which I obtain through my sense. Nevertheless, certainty is not in sensation, but belongs only to thought. Is our inability to conceive the negation of any- thing an adequate test of the truth of that thing? No. Such mere passive inability may be nothing more than a mental impotence. Only when we actively see that the negation of anything is posi- tively impossible because its affirmation is unneces- sarily true have we such a guarantee for truth. How do you name things thus manifestly true ? I call them " evident." Do you then build merely upon what is but a purely internal feeling of the individual ? Certainly not. When I say "evident," I refer to a property of things in themselves, as they exist independently of us, or, as it is called, "objec- tively," as well as to corresponding affections which exist in us, or, as it is called, " subjectively." That is to say, I refer not only to their subjective evidence, but also to their corresponding external condition of objective evidence. When anything is evident both objectively and subjectively I call it completely or simply evident. How can we be sure we know anything external or objective ? That we must be able so to do is made clear to us by our faculty of memory. This shows us that we do really know existences and condftions which are not ours now, and which are external and objective to our present being. 150 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION How does this character of the faculty of memory affect the truth of this principle of evidence ? It shows that we can know objective as well as subjective conditions, and that therefore there is no impossibility in our knowing that real quality or objective evidence in a thing itself which is a cause of its being evident to our minds, and so gives it subjective evidence. Can you give an instance of this perception of ours of such concordance between objective and subjective relations? Yes, such a concordance is implied in every proposition about external things known to us. Thus, when I say "a negro is black," I affirm a conformity between the external thing, "a negro," and the external quality, blackness. I also affirm a conformity between those two external entities and any two corresponding internal concepts that is to say, I affirm that there is really an external thing corresponding to the term negro and an external quality corresponding to the term black. Besides these assertions, I also implicitly affirm a correspondence between my mental judgments and the corresponding objective co-existence. Of course, St. George Mivart's methods are open to the objection that the question and answer repre- sent the work of one mind. This is true, but the same criticism in some measure applies to Plato. The point, however, lies in the real use of Socratic disputation as distinct from an arranged argument on paper. The advantages of such a system of cross-examination has frequently been stated. Watts thus quaintly sums up: LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 151 " Now the advantages of this method are very considerable. It represents the form of a dialogue, or common conversation, which is much more easy, more pleasant, and a more sprightly way of in- struction, and more fit to excite the attention, and sharpen the penetration of the learner, than solitary reading, or silent attention to a lecture. Man being a sociable creature, delights more in conversation, and learns better this way, if it could always be wisely and happily practised. This method hath something very obliging in it, and carries a very humble and condescending air, when he that in- structs seems to be the inquirer, and seeks informa- tion from him who learns. It leads the learner into the knowledge of truth as it were by his own invention, which is a very pleasing thing to human nature; and by questions pertinently and artificially proposed, it draws him on to discover his own mistakes, which he is much more easily persuaded to relinquish when he seems to have discovered them himself. It is managed in a great measure in the form of the most easy reasoning, always arising from something asserted or known in the foregoing answer, and so proceeding to inquire something unknown in the following question, which again makes way for the next answer. Now such an exercise is very alluring and entertaining to the understanding, while its own reasoning powers are all along employed, and that without labour or difficulty, because the querist finds out and proposes all the intermediate ideas or middle terms." CHAPTER XIV. REASONING FROM EXAMPLES. IN the previous sections of this book we have considered those principles of reasoning which have a direct relation to the subject itself; we took the subject and considered its attributes, its parts, its causes, and its effects. In this section we shall consider the subject in its relation to other things. We will call the principles already discussed the internal principles of reasoning; and those we are now to discuss the external principles. In reasoning from examples we adduce examples in proof of the propositions we desire to establish. Here are two specimens: (a) It would be an extremely profitable thing to draw up a short and well-authenticated account of the habits of study of the most celebrated writers with whose style of literary industry we happen to be most acquainted. It would go very far to destroy the absurd and pernicious association of genius and idleness, by showing them that the greatest poets, orators, statesmen, and historians men of the most brilliant and imposing talents have actually laboured as hard as the makers of dictionaries and the arrangers of indexes ; and that the most obvious reason why they have been superior to other men is, that they have taken more pains than other men. Gibbon was in his study every morning, winter and summer, at 152 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 153 six o'clock; Mr. Burke was the most laborious and in- defatigable of human beings; Leibnitz was never out of his library; Pascal killed himself by study; Cicero narrowly escaped death by the same cause ; Milton was at his books with as much regularity as a merchant or an attorney he had mastered all the knowledge of his time; so had Homer. Raffaelle lived but thirty-seven jears ; and in that short space carried the art so far beyond what it had before reached, that he appears to stand alone as a model to his successors. There are instances to the contrary; but, generally speaking, the life of all truly great men has been a life of intense and incessant labour.* (b) If then we consider the perpetual conflicts of savage tribes, the frequent wars of the rival republics of Greece with each other, and with their common enemies; if we remember that the temple of Janus at Rome, always open in the time of war, was never closed during five centuries, till the end of the second Punic war, and then only for a short time; if we advert to the desolation caused by the Scythians, Goths, Vandals, Tartars, and the destruction of about two millions of human beings in the Crusades, it seems to be evident that wars were anciently, and before the general use of firearms and cannon, more frequent, protracted, destructive, and cruel than they are noio.-f- (2) This mode of reasoning from examples is called by scholastic logicians induction, and is opposed to deduction. We will, then, illustrate the difference between reasoning by induction and reasoning by deduction. You have observed an individual come to poverty by a dishonest course of action, and another arrive * Sydney Smith's Moral Philosophy. t Aiken's On War. 154 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION at wealth by a life of rectitude ; and you remark, " Honesty is the best policy." Here you reason by induction. From these individual cases you gather a proof of the general maxim, " Honesty is the best policy." But suppose a person should ask your advice how to act in a case wherein strict integrity might appear to be less advantageous than a more crooked procedure, and you observe to him, "Honesty is the best policy"; here you reason by deduction. You apply the general principle to an individual case; you reason on the principle of genus and species. These two kinds of reason- ing are just the reverse of each other. When from one or more examples you infer a general principle, that is called induction, or reasoning from examples. When from the general principle you infer an individual case, that is called deduction, or reasoning from genus and species. Induction is reasoning from particulars to generals, and deduction is reasoning from generals to particulars. But you ask, How can I infer a general proposi- tion from a small number of examples? Is it not a rule, that " generals cannot be inferred from particulars"? Very true. You cannot infer generals from particulars, unless you have reason to believe that all the particulars are alike. Our reasoning here must depend upon the uniformity of the laws of nature. When the law is uniform, we can infer generals from particulars, because we know that all particulars are in fact generals. This is the case most frequently in the physical sciences. All animals of the same species are alike. I see that a horse has four legs : I may assert, then, LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 155 that every horse in the world has four legs, though I have not seen them all. I decompose a glass of water, and find it is formed of oxygen and hydro- gen : I therefore assert that all water, everywhere, is composed of oxygen and hydrogen. But when this constant uniformity does not exist, I cannot reason so conclusively ; and my reasonings will be weaker and weaker in proportion to this want of uniformity ; and hence we shall have to descend from certain reasonings, to probable reasonings, and then lower, to doubtful reasonings, until at last our examples may be so few or so conflicting, that we may have no foundation for any reasoning at all respecting the matter in dispute.* Don't erect general theories from a few peculiar ob- servations, appearances, or experiments. This is what the logicians call a false induction. When general ob- servations are drawn from so many particulars as to become certain and indubitable, these are jewels of knowledge, comprehending great treasure in a little room : but they are, therefore, to be made with the greater care and caution, lest errors become large and diffusive, if we should mistake in these general notions. Some writers make a distinction between reason- ing from example and reasoning from induction, the example is one, induction is more than one. * " When the grounds for believing anything are slight, we term the mental act or state induced, a conjecture ; when they are strong, we term it an inference or conclusion. In- crease the evidence for a conjecture, it becomes a conclu- sion ; diminish the evidence for a conclusion, it passes into a conjecture. The process which ends in a conclusion, and the process which ends in a conjecture, are thus essentially the same, and differ only in degree, or in the force of the evidence." Bailey, p. 31. 156 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION But there seems no ground for this distinction. The mode of reasoning is the same : the only differ- ence is in the degree of proof. The greater the number of examples, of course, the greater is the amount of evidence in proof of the general proposi- tion.* In reasoning then from genus and species, we infer, you perceive, individual cases from universal rules. In reasoning from examples, we reverse our mode of reasoning; and from one or more examples we prove the general rule. We use the inductive method in regard to the physical sciences, such as astronomy, chemistry, etc. We see several instances in which fire melts lead ; we infer it will always do so, and when we are satisfied that this is the case, we call it a law of nature. It was also by this method that philo- sophers have discovered the laws of astronomy. By the same rule we discover the laws of medicine : if a medicine cures in a great number of cases, we infer that it will always cure in similar cases. In the science of morals, we also observe that certain vices lead to misery ; and we infer that vice will always lead to misery, and virtue to happiness. In politics, we observe in the history of the world what institutions and what laws have conduced to the happiness of the people ; we gather together these instances, and thus form maxims for the "It is obvious that whether we can draw an inference from a single fact, or whether it is needful to have a collec- tion of facts, depends altogether on what is requisite for establishing a similarity in the influential circumstances of each case, and does not affect the character of the reason- ing." Bailey, p. 10. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 157 government of nations. In political economy we observe, or should observe, the same practice But political economists have too often wandered into other paths. Instead of deducing their principles from facts, they have first formed their theories, and then made facts bend to their theories. Hence we have theories of population, theories of rent, theories of the currency, and theories of taxation, advanced and supported in a way more in accord- ance with the Aristotelian than with the Baconian system of philosophy. (3) The following explanation of the nature of induction is taken from Hill's Logic: An induction in which every individual case is enu- merated is a perfect demonstration. And in general, the more nearly we approach to the entire enumeration, the higher is the degree of probability attained by the in- duction : provided, at least, that no facts of an oppo- site tendency are discoverable ; or that if they occur, they are satisfactorily shown r >t to be really inconsistent with the principle deduced. The great error in induc- tion is too great haste in drawing a conclusion without having premised a sufficient number of individual cases. Many, for example, if they have met with or heard of one or two dishonest lawyers, or observed a comet in a warm summer, think themselves authorised to draw the sweeping inference, that all lawyers are dishonest, or all comets occasion a warm season. The difference between deduction and induction may be illustrated by the methods of proving that the interior of the earth is in a molten condition. From the volcanic phenomena, i.e., from the fact that the earth is in a molten condition under Mount Vesuvius, Mount Hecla, Mount Etna, and others, 158 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION it is inferred inductively that the whole interior is in such condition. From the process of the earth's formation by the condensation of intensely heated material (an origin probable on astronomic grounds), it is inferred deductively that the interior is in a molten condition. The one process starts from facts; the other from a general principle. They are usually thrown into syllogistic form as follows : * INDUCTIVE PROCESS. DEDUCTIVE PROCESS. The interior of the earth The interior of the earth is is molten ; molten ; For, it is molten under For the Solar system was Vesuvius, etc. ; formed by condensation ; And Vesuvius, etc., fairly And the earth is a part of represents the whole. the Solar system. In order to reason correctly on inductive lines it is necessary to obey two rules, which, although apparently simple in themselves, are not always easy to keep. First Rule. Observe, analyse, and classify the facts to be generalised and explained, in order to ascertain their reality and their various elements and relations. This rule guards against two common sources of error in induction. The first is that of assuming to be fact what is not fact. Charles II. propounded a problem to the Royal Society. He asked : Why does a live fish in water increase the weight, while a dead fish does not ? The Society took the matter seriously, and gravely thought out scientific * Gregory's Practical Logic, p. 136. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 159 explanations. If they had asked, " Is it a fact? " they would have saved themselves the trouble of trying to solve an imaginary problem. The second is the error from getting only a partial view of the facts, or from failure to get them in their rela- tions. This is illustrated in Stahl's method of accounting for combustion by the extrication of a substance supposed to be contained in all com- bustible matter called phlogiston, which went up in the flame. Combustion results in the visible residue of ashes and the invisible phlogiston, which passes off. The error was in the non-observation of an important part of the actual residue the gaseous products of combustion. When these were at last taken into account, it was found that the gases, with the ashes, weighed much more than the substance burned, so that there was no room for phlogiston. Second Rule. Correctly interpret the facts, i.e., seek to find the appropriate cause for the facts and basis for the generalisation. By cause, in induction, is meant operating power, or more strictly "power which in operating originates new forms of being." It is anything which has efficiency, and exerts it in producing change; and hence is often called efficient cause. It should be distinguished from law, which has no efficiency, but is merely an expression of an estab- lished sequence of facts, or the regular order in which a cause operates.* * Gregory's Practical Logic, p. 137. 160 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION To employ these rules intelligently it is necessary to invent hypotheses for the provisional work of interpretation. If I found that a certain plant grew better in darkness than in light, I should have to observe and experiment with other plants until I came to some sort of conclusion as to why this plant was so different from its fellow plants. The conclusion may be a wrong one, but still it renders good service as a working hypothesis; it enables me to study the subject more methodically, and, as often happens, it may ultimately lead me to the real truth. The habit of hypothesis formation is a sound intellectual habit, and can as easily be applied to economics, politics, ethics, trade, as to natural science. The danger to be guarded against is the inherent attractiveness of a new hypothesis. A man looks upon it as the child of his imagination, and he fosters it as tenderly as the child of his body with the result that hard facts which refute it altogether meet with a grudg- ing welcome, sometimes with unscientific hostility. CHAPTER XV. REASONING FROM ANALOGY COMPARISON AND CONTRAST. BY reasoning from analogy we mean reasoning about one thing from its resemblance to another thing; consequently any mal-observation in com- parison and contrast between the two things under investigation will vitiate the conclusion ; for the argument in this case is not based upon an iden- tity, but upon a relation. Before discussing fully the nature, limitations, and fallacies of this form of reasoning, we will give a selected list of such arguments. They are reproduced here not because we believe them to be models and free from all error, but because they are representative in quality and variety. (i) From Sydney Smith : It would be a very curious question to agitate, how far understanding is transmitted from parent to child; and within what limits it can be improved by culture : whether all men are born equal with respect to their understanding ; or whether there is an original diversity antecedent to all imitation and instruction. The analogy of animals is in favour of the transmissibility of mind. Some ill-tempered horses constantly breed ill-tempered colts ; and the foal never has seen the sire therefore, in this, there can be no imitation. If the eggs of a wild 161 1 62 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION duck are hatched under a tame duck, the young brood will be much wilder than any common brood of poultry : if they are kept all their lives in a farm-yard, and treated kindly, and fed well, their eggs hatched under another bird produce a much tamer race. (2) From William Paley : I suppose it will be allowed, that, to advance a direct falsehood, in recommendation of our wares, by ascrib- ing to them some quality which we know that they have not, is dishonest. Now, compare with this the designed concealment of some fault, which we know that they have ; the motive in these two cases is the same, and the prejudice to the buyer is also the same. The practice of passing bad money is sometimes defended by a vulgar excuse, that we have taken the money for good, and must therefore get rid of it. Which excuse is much the same as if one who had been robbed on the highway, should imagine he had a right to reimburse himself out of the pocket of the first traveller he met. (3) From Edmund Burke: I confess to you freely that the sufferings and dis- tresses of the people of America in this cruel war have at times affected me more deeply than I can express. I felt every gazette of triumph as a blow upon my heart, which has a hundred times sunk and fainted within me at all the mischiefs brought upon those who bear the whole brunt of war in the heart of their country. Yet the Americans are utter strangers to me; a nation among whom I am not sure that I have a single acquaintance. Was I to suffer my mind to be so unaccountably warped, was I to keep such iniquitous weights and measures of temper and reason as to sympathise with those who are in open rebellion against an authority which I respect, at war with a country which by every title ought to be and is most dear to me and yet to have no feeling at all for the hardships and indignities suffered by men who LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 163 by their very vicinity are bound up in a nearer relation to us, who contribute their share, and more than their share, to the common prosperity, who perform the common offices of social life, and who obey the laws to the full, as well as I do. [Burke advocates sympathy for the Irish Roman Catholics as more natural for the English than sympathy with the Americans.] (4) From Cardinal Newman : You will see what I mean by the parallel of bodily health. Health is a good thing in itself, though nothing came of it, and is especially worth seeking and cherish- ing; yet, after all, the blessings which attend its presence are so great, while they are so close to it, and so redound back upon it and encircle it, that we never think of it except as useful as well as good, and praise and prize it for what it does as well as for w r hat it is, though, at the same time, we cannot point out any definite and distinct work or production which it can be said to effect. And so as regards intellectual culture, I am far from denying utility in this large sense as the end of Education, when I lay it down that the culture of the intellect is good in itself and its own end. I do not exclude from the idea of intellectual culture what it cannot but be from the very nature of things; I only deny that we must be able to point out before we have any right to call it useful, some art or business, or pro- fession, or trade, or work, as resulting from it, and as its real or complete end. The parallel is exact : As the body may be sacrificed to some manual or other toil, whether moderate or oppressive, so may the intellect be devoted to some particular profession ; and I do not call this the culture of the intellect. Again, as some member or organ of the body may be inordinately used or developed, so may memory, or imagination, or the reasoning faculty ; and this again is not intellectual cul- ture. On the other hand, as the body may be tended, 164 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION cherished, and exercised with a simple view to its general health, so may the intellect also be generally exercised in order to its perfect state; and this is its cultivation. (5) From Professor Jevons: We may rely upon it that indefinite and to us incon- ceivable advances will be made by the human intellect, in the absence of any unforeseen catastrophe to the species or the globe. Almost within historical periods we can trace the rise of mathematical science from its simplest genus. We can prove our descent from ances- tors who counted only on their fingers, but how almost infinitely is a Newton or a Laplace above all simple savages. Pythagoras is said to have sacrificed a heca- tomb when he discovered the 47th proposition of Euclid, and the occasion was worthy of the sacrifice. Archimedes was beside himself when he first perceived his beautiful mode of determining specific gravities. Yet these great discoveries are the simplest elements of our school-boy knowledge. Step by step we can trace upwards the acquirement of new mental powers. What could be more wonderful and unexpected than Napier's discovery of logarithms, a wholly new mode of calculation, which has multiplied perhaps a hundredfold the working powers of every computer and, indeed, has rendered easy calculations which were before almost impracticable. Since the time of Newton and Leibnitz whole worlds of problems have been solved which before were hardly conceived as matters of enquiry. In our own day ex- tended methods of mathematical reasoning, such as the system of quaternions, have been brought into existence. What intelligent man will doubt that the recondite speculations of a Cayley or a Sylvester may possibly lead to some new methods, at the simplicity and power of which a future age will wonder, and yet wonder more, that to us they were so dark and difficult. [Argument from past examples to future truths.] LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 165 These specimens are sufficiently varied to show the extent of reasoning by analogy in our everyday thought as well as our more serious attempts in reflective moments ; for as Jevons points out in his Logic, analogical reasoning is the type of all reasoning: "Two things resemble each other in one or more respects; a certain proposition is true of the one; therefore it is true of the other. In science, ethics, politics, political economy, trade in no sphere is reasoning by analogy an absent quantity, unless it be in the gospels of social dreamers, who, having no past model to guide them, draw pictures of an Elysian state from the realms of imagination. Even a caricature in Punch is founded on the principle of analogy. The pro- rogation of Parliament in 1850 was represented by " Lord John Russell shutting up shop " ; and when William II. dismissed Bismarck, Sir John Tenniel's cartoon represented the Emperor as " Dropping the Pilot." Dean Swift's satires on the political and religious disagreements of his day have a similar basis in the use of analogy. The political parties were distinguished from each other by the high and low heels of their shoes. The heir-apparent (afterwards George II.) wore one heel higher than the other, which gave him a hobble in his gait he was evidently halting between two opinions. The religious parties were styled the Big-endians and the Little-endians; the former always broke their eggs before they ate them on the big end, the latter on the little end. The words of their prophet were, " Let all true believers break their eggs on the most convenient end." A few 166 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION statesmen thought this meant " that every true believer should break his egg on that end which seemed to him to be the most convenient." But this construction was not generally admitted, and many hundred large volumes had been published on the controversy. In his " Tale of a Tub " the Dean has, in the supposed adventures of three brothers, Peter, Martin, and Jack, given what he deems a representation of the Catholic, Lutheran, and Calvinistic Churches. But it must be admitted that in cases of this kind analogy is used more by way of exposition than of argument, although the latter element is never absent. Exposition and the argument that lies latent in it is developed by comparison and con- trast, two words that young students frequently confuse. Comparison takes note of similarities; contrast takes note of differences. The following passage from the indictment of Guy Fawkes pro- ceeds on the basis of comparison, and is a good specimen of what is known as argumentum a fortiori. The matter that is now to be offered to you, my Lords the Commissioners, and to the trial of you the knights and gentlemen of the jury, is matter of treason ; but of such horror and monstrous nature, that before now the tongue of man never delivered, the ear of man never heard, the heart of man never conceited, nor the malice of hellish or earthly devil ever practised. For if it be abominable to murder the least; if to touch God's anointed be to oppose themselves against God; if (by blood) to subvert princes, states, and kingdoms, be hate- ful to God and man, as all true Christians must acknow- ledge; then how much more than too monstrous shall LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 167 all Christian hearts judge the horror of this treason, to murder and subvert such a king, such a queen, such a prince, such a progeny, such a state, such a govern- ment, so complete and absolute ; that God approves : the world admires : all true English hearts honour and reverence : the Pope and his disciples only envy and malign. Here is a further specimen from the United States Congress at a time when they were discussing the Fugitive Slaves Bill. The Hon. J. R. Giddings said : Thus, fellow-citizens, you and I are liable at any hour to be called upon to pursue the flying bondman as he hastens towards a land of freedom. We have become a nation of slave-hunters, and slave-catchers. The man who shall seize a slave upon the African coast, is by our law consigned to the gallows, and deemed unworthy of an existence among civilised, and even barbarous people ; but how much greater must be the guilt of him who seizes the enlightened and intelligent Christian, one who holds the same religion, and trusts in the same salvation as himself, and riveting the cold iron upon his trembling limbs, sends him back to bondage and suffer- ing. We know that the benighted African is uncon- scious of his rights, and incapable of appreciating his degradation : yet we hang the man who arrests and con- signs him to slavery. This we regard as just : but what penalty can be regarded as commensurate with the crime of seizing upon our fellow-man, whose mind has been enlightened, who knows the rights with which God has endowed him, who comprehends the crime com- mitted against him, and of sending him back to a land of chains, and whips, and suffering? In my opinion, such crime far transcends that of the ordinary pirate. Indeed, I think the thief or the pirate far more entitled to our friendship, than he who under such circumstances i68 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION will lend himself to the commission of the crimes which the law requires us to perpetrate. The argument by contrast, that is, the noting of differences and the inferences to be drawn there- from, are well set forth in the following passage. It was written many years ago, and will afford the reader an opportunity of finding out what state- ments no longer hold good, and how far they invalidate the argument. The United States are, singularly enough, taken by both the advocates and the opponents of universal suffrage as a conclusive example for and against the same system ; and it is not the least curious part of the paradox that the principal cause of the facts which are pleaded and exaggerated by both parties lies out of the sphere of politics altogether. It is to the prodigious amount of fertile soil, compared with the smallness of the population, and to the consequent cheapness of land and dearness of labour, that North America owes, in a great measure, the prosperity, morality, and content- ment of her people, and the comparative security of life and property. And it is to the same cause that we should attribute the major part of that spirit of specula- tion, that rabid thirst for wealth, that inferiority in arts and literature, that absence of refinement, that selfish kimboing, jostling race through life, of which brother Jonathan is sometimes justly, and oftener unjustly, accused : the United States are, and must long remain, a country of material production, with its advantages and its disadvantages. It follows, that the conditions under which complete consistent democracy has been tried on the other side of the Atlantic are so unlike those of Europe, that we cannot infer, with any certainty, from the success of the institutions of the former, that they would succeed on our more crowded shores. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 169 The contrast between Protestant and Catholic states is thus described by Mr. Macaulay : From the time when the barbarians overran the Western Empire, to the time of the revival of letters, the influence of the Church of Rome had been generally favourable to science, to civilisation, and to good government. But during the last three centuries, to stunt the growth of the human mind has been her chief object. Throughout Christendom, whatever advance has been made in knowledge, in freedom, in wealth, and in the arts of life, has been made in spite of her, and has everywhere been in inverse proportion to her power. The loveliest and most fertile provinces of Europe have, under her rule, been sunk in poverty, in political servi- tude, and in intellectual torpor, while Protestant coun- tries, once proverbial for sterility and barbarism, have been turned by skill and industry into gardens, and can boast of a long list of heroes and statesmen, philoso- phers and poets. Whoever, knowing what Italy and Scotland naturally are, and what four hundred years ago they actually w^ere, shall now compare the country round Rome with the country round Edinburgh, will be able to form some judgment as to the tendency of Papal domination. The descent of Spain, once the first among monarchies, to the lowest depths of degradation; the elevation of Holland, in spite of many natural disadvan- tages, to a position such as no commonwealth so small has ever reached, teach the same lesson. Whoever passes in Germany from a Roman Catholic to a Protes- tant principality ; in Switzerland from a Roman Catholic to a Protestant canton ; in Ireland from a Roman Catho- lic to a Protestant country, finds that he has passed from a lower to a higher grade of civilisation. On the other side of the Atlantic the same law prevails. The Protestants of the United States have left far behind them the Roman Catholics of Mexico, Peru, and Brazil. The Roman Catholics of Canada remain inert, while the M 170 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION whole continent round them is in a ferment with Protes- tant activity and enterprise.* In the scientific world, indeed in almost every department of knowledge, analogy and contrast are great aids to discovery. The analogy of logic and algebra was the basis of the discoveries made in logic by Professor Boole. The detection of differ- ence or likeness of things discovered by comparison with things already known is essential to successful research. This is as true for a business man as for a man of science. Many Americans have falsely reasoned that because a certain product sold well in the States, it would sell well here. They made the mistake of dwelling on points of analogy be- tween English conditions and American conditions ignoring the contrasts and differences. * As the argument is based on material conditions, how far is it invalidated by the present state of Canada and South America, to say nothing of the United States? CHAPTER XVI. REASONING FROM STATISTICS. THE place which figures occupy in arguments that relate to politics, trade, and sociology is so impor- tant that it has been considered almost necessary to devote a section to the study of first principles. Few people know how to approach a table of figures showing the state of labour, or the comparative number of births, or any other facts that can be put in numerical form. The truths stated are sup- posed to be as evident as those in a profit and loss account, needing no minute analysis, and contain- ing no features that may eventuate in subtle fal- lacies. If statistics were so simple as is often imagined, we should not have the accusing picture of free traders and tariff reformers brewing their own dogmatic conclusions from the same sets of figures ; for over and over again the free trader has examined a government blue-book only to find astounding confirmation of his views, and the tariff reformer has pondered the same tables of returns without receiving a shock to his tariff convictions. The necessary complexity and subtlety of statistics is one of the first lessons to be learned. I mean, of course, statistics referring to a huge aggregate of people or commodities. There is not much room for differences of opinion about a balance-sheet : it is either good or bad, or, at any rate, promising or unpromising ; whilst the profit or loss is revealed 171 i;2 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION in the presence or absence of dividends. But the state of the trade of the nation as revealed in a big Return is quite a different matter, partly because of the vast number of facts tabulated, and partly because there are some things which can never be embodied in figures. Professor Bowley says : "We cannot measure health, poverty, or crime: we can only measure the death-rate and count the number of persons who seek public relief, and the number of convictions. In such cases the measurements can only be used as indications, and their relation to the more important quantity must be constantly criticised, while other indications should be obtained wherever possible to check the impressions formed."* (i) In arguments based on statistics the first enquiry should be directed towards the origin of the figures. Who tabulated them ? If they are the figures of a first-rate authority, they are worthy of consideration ; but if he uses them to prove a much-debated issue, they should be carefully com- pared with figures published by authorities on the other side, or, better still, use some authority quite independent. In the case of the national balance- sheet this is easily possible, for all government returns are unprejudiced at any rate, they contain as little political prejudice as any other publications mostly no prejudice at all. The debater who quotes statistics glibly is many a time brought up abruptly by being asked his authority. Thus the oft-repeated statement that there are 13,000,000 of * Elementary Manual of Statistics, p. 4. 173 people in this country on the verge of starvation falls a ready prey to the questioner. Who is the authority for the statement ? Those to whom it is a weapon of warfare. (2) The next item is the need to know exactly what is contained in the tables before you. Sup- pose those tables tell you the number of cattle in Great Britain during a certain period of years. That sounds very simple, but it is not so simple as it looks, for, as Professor Bowley remarks, What is a cow ? is a standard question in agri- cultural statistics. Similarly, in an account of registered births, it is not inopportune to inquire what is understood by a registered birth. There are many fallacies abroad which could be disposed of at once by a little keen analysis of what lies behind the formidable array of figures. (3) Professor Bowley, in his section on Rules for using published Statistics, has a useful suggestion on what he called homogeneity : are the persons or things referred to similar? do they form a homo- geneous group? For instance, there has been a serious decrease in the number of agricultural labourers in this country during the last half cen- tury. Before placing too much stress on that fact, is it not wise to enquire whether fifty years ago the same class of people were called agricultural labourers, or whether in the later tables dairymen are included who were not included previously? (4) Statistics to be really serviceable should be allowed to tell their own story. Too often men form a theory, and then go out in search of figures 174 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION to bolster it up. If the figures point the other way, they either let them alone or doctor them to suit the theory. Hence the sneer: "You can prove anything from statistics." I will now reproduce two specimen arguments based on figures, not as being necessarily true arguments, but as being the work of an authority, and as showing some of the characteristics required in such forms of reasoning. The quotations are from An Enquiry into the Economic Condition of the Country (1904), by R. H. Inglis Palgrave, F.R.S. The produce of the income tax and the progress of the deposits in the Post Office Savings Banks are often quoted as proofs of our prosperity. I will put those figures also before you, and you shall judge for your- selves what they mean. TABLE II. Income Tax, 1843-1901. Years. Produce per i,'. in the of the Income Tax. Proportion to First Year 1843=100. Produce per Head of the Population in Pence. Difference in this + or in each Decade. % d. a. 1843 772,166 100 6-93 1851 786,886 I O2 6-90 - -03 1861 1,122,258 145 9-30 + 2-40 1871 1,587,596 206 12-10 + 2-80 1881 1,915,683 248 13-17 + 1-07 1891 2,238,130 290 14-23 + 1-06 1901 2,531,462 328 14-65 + -42 These figures show the produce of a penny in the of the income tax for every ten years since the tax was first levied. It has been levied at very different rates in different years, but the amount raised by each penny of the tax supplies a very good basis of comparison from LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 175 one year to another. The years chosen are those of the Census Returns, for reasons which I will shortly ex- plain. A census of the population of these islands is taken every ten years. The first year when the income tax was levied was 1843. There was no census in that year, and, therefore, the produce of the tax in 1843 is compared with the numbers of the population in 1841. After that date the figures referring to the income tax follow the exact years of the census. We usually find that people quote the figures of the yield of the penny in the of the income tax exactly as they stand. You will see that every penny in the yielded over three times as much in 1901 as it had done in 1843. The figures run from 772,000 in 1843 up to ^2,531,000 in 1901. Hence the yield in 1901 was over three times as large as it had been when the tax was first imposed. According to this computation the country would appear to be more than three times as wealthy now as it was in 1843. But is it the right method of interpretation, to take these figures singly by themselves, separate from all other elements of progress in the country ? Are there no other points which we ought to consider? Ought not the numbers of the population also to be brought into account? If those who pay the tax become twice as many in number, the produce of the tax would exactly be doubled, while each individual would, on average, be no better off than he was before. Surely the numbers of the people ought to be taken into account, and we ought to divide the amount of the tax by the numbers of the people at the time the tax was paid. When in- vestigated thus the result is shown to be very different from what it seems to be when the tax alone is con- sidered. . . . There have been some considerable abate- ments off the income tax in recent years, but allowing for these, the general lesson to be learnt from the figures remains unchanged. One main lesson is to be learnt from them. This is that the yield in the tax increases more slowly now than formerly. This shows in plain 176 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION words that the country is not prospering as much now as some years ago. Further evidence to this effect is found in the returns of the Post Office Savings Bank from 1896 onwards. Now, it is never pleasant to people to show them that they are not getting on so well as they had done, and the point is one which may touch us all very closely. But my readers must bear with me while I put the facts before them. TABLE III. POST OFFICE SAVINGS BANKS, 1896-1902. Details of Deposits and Investments in Public Funds. V*arc Excess of Interest Amount of Money Withdrawals. Depositors. Invested in Public Funds. 1806 . 7,769,000 2,461,000 10,230,000 1,065,000 1897 . 5,132,000 2,666,000 7,798,000 1,079,000 1898 . 4,409,000 2,838,000 7,247,000 1,304,000 1899 . 3,951,000 3,024,000 6,973,000 1,770,000 1900 . 2,285,000 3,146,000 5,431,000 2,830,000 1901 . 1,562,000 3,281,000 4,843,000 3,065,000 1902 . 821,000 3,391,000 4,212,000 2,593,000 These figures show that the new money paid in by depositors described in the table as the excess of deposits over withdrawals which was nearly ;8, 000,000 in 1896, diminished to little over ;8oo,ooo in 1902, barely one-tenth of what it had been but seven years before. I have looked through the annual reports of the Postmaster-General, and I find that the net amount deposited in 1902 was actually the smallest recorded since the Post Office Savings Bank commenced operations in 1861. It is true that the investments in the public funds made through the medium of the Post Office, which are shown in the last column of the table, more than doubled during the period 1896-1902. But these LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 177 investments had fallen off in 1902 from the amount they had reached in 1901, and they by no means make up for the diminution in the deposits. The figures for 1903 have not yet been published completely, but they appear to indicate an actual decrease in the deposits of the Post Office Savings Banks. A similar diminution has been noticed elsewhere. Thus the Lord Provost of Glasgow, speaking at the 68th annual meeting of the Glasgow Savings Bank, held 24th December, 1903, stated that the withdrawals of money during the year exceeded the deposits by some ^50,000 at that institu- tion. The Glasgow Savings Bank is a large one, with deposits of nearly ten millions. It is true that the In- dustrial Insurance offices, such offices as the Refuge and the Prudential, and similar institutions which receive weekly payments of premiums for life policies, have recently been very active. I am glad that these offices are active, and that they induce more people to save, but the additions to the funds in the savings banks ought, according to the precedents of former yearSj to have been far larger than they were in the years from 1899 to 1902. The falling off in them indicates that the working classes are not doing so well as in years past. This indication of their want of means coincides with the diminished occupation in several important branches of our industries shown by recent returns of the Board of Trade. We have thus examined roughly into the condition of two great classes in the community, those who pay income tax and who are customers of the banks of the country, and those who place their savings in the Post Office Savings Bank. Neither appears to be prospering so much as formerly. We do not affirm this argument can be sub- stantiated : it may, or it may not. Our present purpose is to use it as a model of careful analysis and equally careful reasoning. CHAPTER XVII. REASONING FROM HISTORY. THERE are two problems before the historian : he has to discover what events actually took place, no light task in some instances where the evidence is confused and the testimony conflicting; and he has then to interpret the facts, showing their true inwardness in relation to the times in which they occurred, and their significance for the future. His qualifications require to be extensive and intensive : he must not only know many things, but some of them he must know intimately, in the manner of an expert. A keen knowledge of the sources of history, of the innate mind of races, of the influ- ence of geographical position, of the method of weighing evidence, and of a host of other items, go to make up the capacity for writing history, and the work involved demands as full a use of logic as that of the geologist or chemist. But as this book is addressed to general readers who never expect to become historians, it is needless to pursue this thought further; our object in referring to the matter at all was to show that we may expect as much difference in the views of the writers of history as we do in the views of any other class of men who have attempted to interpret fact. We will 178 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 179 therefore adduce a number of passages showing the historian at work. (i)The first pasage is from Buckle, who argues that history is an exact science. Rejecting then the metaphysical dogma of free will and the theological dogma of predestined events, we are driven to the conclusion that the actions of men being determined solely by their antecedents, must have a character of uniformity, that is to say must, under pre- cisely the same circumstances, always issue in precisely the same results. And as all antecedents are in the mind or out of it, we clearly see that all the variations in the results, in other words, all the changes of which history is full, all the vicissitudes of the human race, their progress or their decay, their happiness or their misery, must be the fruit of a double action; an action of external phenomena upon the mind and another action of the mind upon phenomena. These are the materials out of which a philosophic history can alone be con- structed. On the one hand, we have the human mind obeying the laws of its own existence, and, when uncontrolled by external agents, developing itself according to the conditions of its organisation. On the other hand we have what is called Nature, obeying like- wise its laws ; but incessantly coming into contact with the minds of men, exciting their passions, stimulating their intellect and, therefore, giving to their actions a direction which they would not have taken without such disturbance. Thus we have man modifying nature and nature modifying man ; while out of this reciprocal modi- fication all events must necessarily spring. (2) The second passage is from Professor Heeren's Political History of Ancient Greece. It is somewhat interesting by reason of the fact that Heeren is a writer of nearly one hundred years i8o LOGIC FOR THE MILLION ago, and his arguments in the light of recent demo- cratic developments among Asiatic peoples offer an inviting study to the reader. To the student of the history of man there is hardly a phenomenon more important in itself, or more difficult of explanation, than the superiority of Europe over the other parts of our earth. With whatever justice other lands and nations may be estimated, it cannot be denied that the noblest and best of everything which man has produced, sprung up, or at least ripened, on European soil. In the multitude, variety, and beauty of their natural productions, Asia and Africa far surpass Europe; but in everything which is the work of man, the nations of Europe stand far above those of the other continents. It was among them, that, by making mar- riage the union of but two individuals, domestic society obtained that form, without which so many parts of our nature could never have been ennobled ; and if slavery was once established among them, they alone abolished it, because they recognised its injustice. It was chiefly and almost exclusively among them that such constitu- tions were framed, as are suited to nations who have become conscious of their rights. While Asia, during all the changes in its extensive empires, shows only the continued reproduction of despotism, it was in Europe that the germ of political freedom unfolded itself, and under the most various forms, in so many parts of the same soil, bore the noblest fruits ; which again were transplanted from thence to other parts of the world. The simplest inventions of the mechanical arts may perhaps belong in part to the east ; but how have they all been perfected by Europeans ! What an advance from the hand-loom of the Hindoo to the power-loom worked by steam ; from the sundial to the chronometer ; from the bark of the North American savage to the British man-of-war. And if we direct our attention to those nobler arts, which, as it were, raise human nature above LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 181 itself, what a distance between the Jupiter of Phidias and an Indian idol; between the Transfiguration of Raphael and the works of a Chinese painter. The east had its annalists, but never produced a Tacitus, or a Gibbon; it had its poets, but never advanced to criti- cism ; it had its sages, who not unfrequently produced a powerful effect on their nations by means of their doctrines ; but still a Plato or a Kant could never flourish on the banks of the Ganges and the Hoangho. (3) The third passage is from Carlyle's Oliver Cromwell, wherein he endeavours to illustrate two common errors in interpreting history, more par- ticularly the leaders of men. There are two errors, widely prevalent, which pervert to the very basis our judgments formed about such men as Cromwell, about their " ambition," " falsity," and such like. The first is what I might call substituting the goal of their career for the course and starting point of it. The vulgar historian of a Cromwell fancies that he Had determined on being Protector of England at the time when he was plowing the marshlands of Cam- bridgeshire. His career lay all mapped out : a pro- gramme of the whole drama. . . . This is a radical perversion ; all but universal in such cases. And think for an instant how different the fact is. How much does one of us foresee of his own life? Short way ahead of us it is all dim. . . . But a second error refers to this same ambition itself. We exaggerate the ambition of great men ; we mistake what the nature of it is. Great men are not ambitious in that sense ; he is a small, poor man that is ambitious so. Examine the man who lives in misery because he does not shine above other men. Such a creature is among the wretchedest sights seen under the sun. . . . Your Cromwell, what good could it do him to be " noticed" by noisy crowds of people? God, his maker, already noticed him. 1 82 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION (4) The fourth passage is from Bigland's Letters on History, and is a specimen of how deductions are drawn in favour of the science of politics. Much has been said by many writers against the per- nicious effects of extensive empire, but many arguments may also be adduced in its favour. The union of a numerous mass of people in one political system is one of the surest preventives of war, as the division of coun- tries into a greater number of independent states is a never-failing source of predatory hostilities, of blood- shed, rapine, and anarchy. Wherever a country is thus divided, such a multiplicity of jarring interests arise, and so many objects of ambition present themselves, as cannot fail of producing continual scenes of contention, originating in the ambition, the avarice, and the jarring interests of the rulers or the subjects, which involve the people in all sorts of calamities. Instances without number might be adduced, but a glance at the state of England during the time of the Heptarchy will suffice to exemplify the propriety of this observation. In an extensive monarchy there is only one great political interest, and the objects of ambition, however splendid and attractive, are fewer, and consequently within the reach of a smaller number of persons ; in such a state all tends to one central point, instead of deviating to different centres. The vast collective mass of the people is united in one political system, and in one general interest, and the different provinces which compose the empire enjoy the advantages of a free and uninterrupted commerce ; a circumstance of incalculable benefit, both to individuals and to the whole community. Supposing even an extensive monarchy to be despotic, and the monarch himself a sanguinary and unfeeling tyrant, yet, by reason of the extent of his dominions, only a few individuals, who most of them voluntarily bring them- selves into contact with him, feel the effects of his cruelty and despotism. Those who, from motives of LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 183 ambition or interest, approach his person, and serve him as the instruments of his tyrrany, are the persons who principally feel the heavy hand of the tyrant. The great mass of the people feel its pressure in a much lighter degree. Distance of situation, and the great multitude of subjects, cause individuals to escape his notice. The reverse is the case in petty states, where the eye of the tyrant is always upon the individuals of his contracted dominions ; and a tyrant at the distance of a thousand miles, is infinitely preferable to a tyrant at home, at our very doors. The history of mankind affords a multiplicity of proofs, that extensive monar- chies are more conducive to the tranquillity of the world, and the general interests of humanity, than petty states. (5) The fifth passage deals with the operating cause of history as to whether events occur by blind Chance, by Law, or by Providence. It is taken from Wall's Theories of History. The conclusion at which we have arrived is that there is nothing in life and history which can justly be called chance, and that however obscure may be the connec- tion of events and however imperfect our knowledge of their sequences they are all linked together in the indis- soluble bonds of law, that is, in a mutual interdepen- dence of cause and effect. Here arises a new question, the precise bearing of which must be carefully discrimi- nated. In the preceding sections the question was between chance and law : Do events happen without connection? Or, do they occur consecutively? If events happen without connection, no other question remains to be solved; no other question can be raised. In knowing this we know all that can be known ; nothing remains to be known. Let it be taken for granted that chance is proved, and there is thenceforth no question between chance and any other theory of the universe. Science, philosophy, history, theism, are all disproved by the proof of chance. But they are not disproved by 184 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION the proof of law. On the contrary, a foundation is laid on which alone they can all be securely built. If events occur consecutively, that is, according to law, then one of the first questions that arise is this : Is law the highest conception of the human mind, the sole bond of the universe and expressing itself by law? This is the ques- tion not between chance and law, which is here assumed to be settled in favour of the latter, but between law and theism; and it is to be carefully noted that while in the former case the two theories mutually negative each other, in the latter this mutual negation does not take place. It will be observed that three of these passages are concerned with history as a science, one with the possible errors of interpretation, and one with the political lessons of history the last mentioned showing that it is a form of reasoning from examples. This is the use which the general reader makes of the history he reads : he wishes to derive instruction from it to help him in deciding a course of action in reference to the problems of the present. If he is persuaded that the story of civilised nations shows the inimical influence of private property, he will become a socialist of pronounced opinions. Very possibly his next-door neighbour, who has covered the same ground in the reading of history, arrives at the opposite conclusion. Now this divergence of opinion need not come as a surprise : it is the natural colouring which temperament gives to all our reasoning. " Josephus interprets history as the theocratic Jew; Aristotle as a Greek who has seen the bloom of Athens; Polybius as a Greek who has seen the bloom of Athens fade before the fateful power of Rome; St. Augustine living in the age of the decadence of Rome and the weakness of the Church interprets events in the light of another and more enduring world; the mystics of the thirteenth century who saw Europe emerging into a quickening life, hap- pier and freer^than any the world had seen before, seize upon a new view of history and see in the Kingdom of the Holy Spirit a promise for the earth itself of a New Jerusalem. After men broke with authority in the age of the Reformation, and learned to use their own eyes and their own minds on many things, they applied the method to history as well, and began to perceive in it some natural laws. This scientific point of view has dominated the leading thinkers in this field until our own day; and yet these modern men have seen these laws differently, according to their own point of view. Thus the sceptics of the eighteenth century looked to natural laws alone, and were inclined to ignore the interference of incalculable human choice; the biologists seize upon the struggle for existence as the only key to the situation ; the socialists see in history only the play of the laws of production, leading to the inevitable goal of the dominion of the proletariat."* There are so many factors conspiring together to make us see in history what we want to see that the real truth is easily obscured. What, then, are we to do ? The story of Sedan will be appreciably different in a German history from a French his- tory, not only in the account of the battle, but of * Method in History. By M. S. Barnes. 186 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION the events leading up to it ; and the reader naturally asks: Whom am I to believe? Which writer has stated the facts and drawn the inferences correctly ? To give what may be termed an absolute answer to such questions is impossible, but one or two considerations may bring us relatively nearer the truth. The first is that the historical account of Sedan by a third party, say an English or an American writer, is likely to be more impartial than an account written by a member of either of the interested countries, that is, France or Germany. The second is that there are certain facts which all parties admit, e.g., the battle of Sedan was won by Germany because of its superior military power and the morale of its army. Here, then, are two important rules for reasoning correctly from his- tory. One is to discover the facts which every historian of merit acknowledges, and the other is to follow the account of that writer who by reason of his position is likely to be disinterested. CHAPTER XVIII- REASONING FROM AUTHORITIES. IT frequently happens that when a number of men are arguing the pros and cons of a subject, they try to secure the verdict for themselves by quoting the opinion of eminent authorities. Let the subject be the origin of life. Outside the class of experts there is nobody who can argue this question on the basis of personal experiments. We are all of us guided by what the authorities say. But there is a more subtle guide at work : our temperaments, our prejudices, and our previous conclusions act as if they were a single entity. If we are Christians and believe that a Divine Person interfered with the order of nature, creating the organic out of the inorganic, no experiments or inferences of Bastian or Haeckel will have any weight with us : the words we seek for are those of scientists who believe that life never came from death. To increase our confidence we draw up a comparative statement of great names : we put Haeckel, Bastian, and the rest in one column; Lodge, Wallace, Dallinger, and the others in another column. Then we count, and the addition is finished. The argument is decided by a little sum in arithmetic. The rational- ists perform the same mathematical manoeuvre, and 187 1 88 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION there follows a quarrel about the rights and wrongs of including certain names. The basis of the argument is this: " Life had a natural origin because the best equipped men of science say it had." So says the rationalist. The Christian says: " Life had a supernatural origin because the best equipped men of science say natural forces are inadequate for the production of the phenomenon." Now it is certainly reasonable to mass together the names of authorities in this way; and it is inevitable, if unfortunate, that quarrels should ensue about certain men whose opinions are in doubt. But the dominant fact is the effect which a natural or supernatural theory will have on pre-arranged knowledge. If natural forces unaided are not able to produce life, the rationalists' scheme of the universe falls to the ground; and if, on the other hand, life came from dead matter, the Christian will have to revise one of the most important items in his creed. Thus we come to the power of prejudice once again ; the prejudice which made Huxley want to believe in spontaneous generation, and which made Bishop Wilberforce want to disbelieve in the natural evolu- tion of man because the Bible declared man to be a special creation. Theology, however, is only one sphere in which we argue from the names of authorities. Take law as another sphere. A judge will have to decide a case involving, perhaps, the evidence of three experts on each side. Three engineers affirm the fallen bridge was properly built, and three affirm the contrary. In the Thaw case there were 1 89 almost as many lunacy experts who said he was sane as those who said he was not. What line of reasoning can bring us to an intelligent conclusion in matters where we cannot form an expert opinion ourselves, and where experts themselves are in equally divided camps ? First, we must decide on the relative merits of the authorities themselves. In the Thaw case the prosecutor, cross-examining an alleged expert, asked him what he knew of a certain disease, naming a disease which did not exist, but which had been invented to ensnare the witness. That individual fell into the trap, and at once discredited himself by assuming he knew something about this imaginary disease. There are experts and experts; and not all of them can go successfully through the small sieve. Next, the opinions of the best authorities should be carefully compared and contrasted. Very often partisans who want to strengthen the case for their own side do not give sufficient attention to the delicate task of weighing evidence conveyed in chosen words. Sometimes an authority is unable to express a definite opinion on some point of great importance : he prefers to suspend his judgment. Occasionally even the reasons for suspended judg- ment are construed by partisan speakers and writers into negative or positive affirmations. There is usually about conflicting expert evidence a drift in one definite direction. In the case of telepathy the drift seems to be, on the whole, "in favour of" rather than " against " the theory. Where there does not appear to be any such tendency it may LOGIC FOR THE MILLION safely be assumed that the real truth lies in recon- ciliation ; in other words, both sides have half the truth, and the office of the conciliator is to bring them together. The origin of life has been referred to, and we have authorities who are certain the organic came out of the inorganic, the living from the dead. Other authorities, in the absence of proof, prefer to believe that life must have come to the planet in some other way. The tendency is springing up to regard the terms life and non-life as too harsh : that in some sense the matter which we call dead must be living. Should sound developments follow from this line of investigation, it will be evident that once more the meaning of words has been at the bottom of centuries of acrimonious debate- To recapitulate : (1) Where authorities disagree in anything like equal proportions, some attempt must be made to determine the relative value of such authorities. (2) The testimonies of such authorities should be critically examined; and a note must be taken of other authorities who prefer to suspend an expression of opinion. (3) Endeavour to ascertain whether there is not a possibility of discovering the truth by a union of the two principles which are in debate. CHAPTER XIX. A STUDY IN FALLACIES. I. Fallacies arising from not understanding the question. (a) Proving a different question from that in dispute : The first sophism is called ignoratio elenchi, i.e., " Ignoring the refutation." Watts provides an illustration after telling us what this fallacy is. ' When something else is proved, which has neither any necessary connexion or consistency with the thing inquired, and consequently gives no determination to the inquiry, though it may seem at first sight to determine the question : as, if any should conclude that St. Paul was not a native Jew, by proving that he was born a Roman ; or if they should pretend to determine that he was neither a Roman nor Jew, by proving that he was born at Tarsus in Cilicia : these sophisms are refuted by showing that all these three may be true; for he was born of Jewish parents in the city of Tarsus, and by some peculiar privilege granted to his parents, or his native city, he was born a citizen of Rome. Thus there is neither of these three characters of the apostle inconsistent with each other, and therefore the proving of them true does not refute the others." 191 192 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION This type of fallacy has several subdivisions, and we proceed to enumerate them, taking as a guide the sections found in Gregory's Practical Logic: The argumentutn ad jtidicium is based upon the common judgments of mankind. Its maxim is " What all men everywhere and always believe, is true." . . . The argument has great force when it is really based on the common judgment of mankind. The danger of appealing to this principle without sufficient grounds is, however, very great. Under the confident assertions, " Everybody says," " No one pretends to think," the greatest fallacies are often covered. The argument may be illustrated as follows : The material world is a reality and our perception of it is immediate, because all men everywhere and always have so believed. (That is how Galileo's uninstructed accusers argued when he said the earth revolved round the sun as against the testimony of " all men everywhere.") The argumentum ad populum is based on an appeal to public opinion, or to passion or prejudice rather than intelligence. It is often employed because no really good arguments are to be found, or because it is easier to appeal to the passions and prejudices of the masses than to their intelligence. It often puts forward as its major premise the false maxim, Vox populi, vox Dei, " The voice of the people is the voice of God." The argumentum ad vericundiam is an appeal to the feelings of reverence for certain persons or objects, in- stead of proceeding to prove the point in hand. The scholastics used as a standing major premise the maxim, "It is foolish to affirm Aristotle erred." The argumentutn ad ignorantiam is addressed to the ignorance of men. It sometimes consists in assuming that a position is correct because an adversary cannot show the contrary ; sometimes in taking advantage of men's ignorance to impose upon them by some shallow sophism, false statement, or confident assertion. Under LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 193 this may be included the fallacy of interrogation in which a question is so put as to be equivalent to a con- fident assertion of some error. The demand for " an adequate conception," or description, often made by a brow-beating lawyer upon a witness in court, is of the same character. Only a few experts can give anything more than a clear notion of the handwriting, features, or dress of the most intimate friend. The argumentum ad hominem -is an appeal to the practice, principles, or professions of an opponent as confirming our own position or destructive to his. An opponent may thus be silenced since the argument is good against him, even though it be not good against the views he advocates. Christ used this method to silence the cavils of the Jews. Matt, xxi., 41-45. One of the most glaring examples of this kind of irrelevant conclusion occurred in the debate on the institution of a commission of enquiry into the state of the universities. The principal opponent of the Ministerial proposition took up the ground that Government had no right to enquire into the state of municipal or corporate bodies; a principle of which no one can dispute the justice so long as the movements of those societies do not interfere with the interests of the commonwealth, or impede the progress of the community matters, of course, over which the Government have complete control. The defender of the universities, however, neglected so to restrict it, and the Minister threw ridicule on his opponent by representing many cases in which a wise Government could not abstain from interfering with corporate societies. The onus which lay on the Minister of proving that the universities presented a case for public interference 194 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION was lost sight of, in the feelings excited by the confutation of the principle in the sense to which its propounder did not intend it to apply.* (b) Assuming as true the question in dispute. This is called petitio principii, or " begging the question," or "arguing in a circle." Thus: John Knox and John Witherspoon were excel- lent men because they belonged to an excellent church, the Presbyterian Church : and the Pres- byterian Church is an excellent one because it has contained such good men. The combination of the ignoratio elenchi and the petitio principii is very common in Parliamen- tary debates, and Canning's speeches afford several instances of their employment and detection. One of the most striking of the latter will be found in his reply to the member who referred to the con- tinuance of our triumphs in the Peninsula and our conflicts with Napoleon as a reason for perpetuating an exclusive paper currency. Canning said, " I will not pay my right honourable friend so ill a compliment as to suppose that he is not himself perfectly aware that in thus shaping his argument he has, in fact, rather assumed or omitted the question in dispute. The question is not whether we shall continue the war In the Peninsula with all our heart. Who doubts, who dissuades that deter- mination? That point might have been assumed without hazard of contradiction. But my right honourable friend argues that point as if it were *Devey's Logic, p. 334. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 195 disputed, and assumes without argument that which was necessary for him to prove, viz., that to the continuance of the war and our success in the Peninsula it is essential that the present system of currency should remain unchanged. Just as fairly might I assume without argument that a change in our currency is necessary to this same purpose of continuing the war, and then retort upon my right honourable friend his own expostulations against fettering the energies and cramping the exertions of the country. In either case the point which is alone in dispute remains to be decided."* (c) Abusing the ambiguity of words a practice which may be carried out in different ways, some of them very amusing in character. When the words or phrases are plainly equivocal, they are called sophisms of equivocation; as, if we should argue thus : " He that sends forth a book into the light, desires it to be read ; he that throws a book into the fire, sends it into the light ; therefore, he that throws a book into the fire, desires it to be read." This sophism, as well as the foregoing, and all of the like nature, are solved by showing the different senses of the words, terms, or phrases. Here light in the major proposition signifies the public view of the world ; in the minor it signifies the brightness of flame and fire; and therefore, the syllogism has four terms, or rather it has no middle term, and proves nothing. But where such gross equivocations and ambiguities appear in argu- mentSj there is little danger of imposing upon ourselves or others. The greatest danger, and which we are per- petually exposed to in reasoning, is, where the two * Devey's Logic, p. 336. 196 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION senses or significations of one term are near akin, and not plainly distinguished, and yet they are really suffi- ciently different in their sense to lead us into great mis- takes, if we are not watchful. And, indeed, the greatest part of controversies in political or civil life, arise Irom the different senses that are put upon words, and the different ideas which are included in them. As an additional instance of this class we may cite the use of the word representative, which . . . " is taken not infrequently to mean, in the case of a member of a legislative assembly, a person who is bound to represent the exact opinions of a majority of his constituents on all points, and never to act on his own responsibility ; whereas law and usage have defined the term to mean one who is chosen to represent the interests of a certain constituency according to the best dictates of his own judgment, and unbiassed by any undue extraneous influence. Such a person may consult the opinions of his constituents before making up his mind on a ques- tion that may concern them, but he is not bound to be either their spokesman or resign his seat, though he may pursue the latter course from motives of delicacy."* II. Fallacies connected with the relation of sub- ject and object. (a) Judging a thing by that which belongs to it only accidentally. This is called fallacia-accidentis, or a sophism wherein we pronounce concerning the nature and essential pro- * Devey's Logic, p. 310. 197 perties of any subject according to something which is merely accidental to it. This is akin to the former, and is also very frequent in debate. So if opium or the Peruvian bark has been used imprudently, or unsuc- cessfully, whereby the patient has received injury, some weaker people absolutely pronounce against the use of the bark or opium upon all occasions whatsoever, and are ready to call them poison. So wine has been the accidental occasion of drunkenness and quarrels ; learn- ing and printing may have been the accidental cause of sedition in a state ; the reading of the Bible, by acci- dent, has been abused to promote heresies or destructive errors; and for these reasons they have all been pro- nounced evil things. Of a similar kind is the fallacy of the Epicureans who concluded that gods must have human form because among all creatures in the world men alone had the use of reason. The gods, said these philosophers, are very happy; none can be happy without virtue; there is no virtue without reason ; and reason is found nowhere except in the human form ; it must be avowed, therefore, that the gods have human form. Reason, however, is not essential to the human form, but only accidentally connected with it ; it was, therefore, puerile to conclude that because the gods were endowed with mind they must also have hands, feet, and other human appur- tenances. (b) Passing from what is true in some respects to what is true absolutely : The next sophism borders upon the former : and that is, when we argue from that which is true in particular circumstances, to prove the same thing true absolutely, simply, and abstracted from all circumstances : this is called in the schools a sophism, a dicto secundum quid 1 98 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION ad dictum simpliciter; as, That which is bought in the shambles is eaten for dinner ; raw meat is bought in the shambles ; therefore raw meat is eaten for dinner. Or thus : Livy writes fables and improbabilities when he describes prodigies and omens ; therefore Livy's Roman History is never to be believed in anything. This sort of sophism has its reverse also ; as when we argue from that which is true simply and absolutely, to prove the same thing true in all particular circumstances whatso- ever; as if a traitor should argue from the sixth com- mandment, " Thou shalt not kill a man," to prove that Ke himself ought not to be hanged : or if a madman should tell me, " I ought not to withhold his sword from him, because no man ought to withhold the pro- perty of another." These two last species of sophisms are easily solved, by showing the difference betwixt things in their absolute nature, and the same thing sur- rounded with peculiar circumstances, and considered in regard to special times, places, persons, and occasions ; or by showing the difference between a moral and a metaphysical universality, and that the proposition will hold good in one case, but not in the other. (c) The two errors in reasoning to which scholas- tic logicians give the names of " Undistributed Middle," and " Illicit Process," may be classed under this head. The " undistributed middle " is when we argue that because two things have a common attribute, therefore they are the same thing; as, " Gold is yellow, and saffron is yellow therefore saffron is gold." The " illicit process " is when, two things are not the same thing, we infer they have not a common attribute; as, "Gold is yellow; saffron is not gold: therefore, saffron is not yellow." We sometimes meet with strange fallacies of this description in the con- LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 199 troversy respecting religious education. Thus, " Religion produces morality; education produces morality; therefore, education is religion "; and, on the other side, "Religion produces morality; education is not religion ; therefore, education does not produce morality." III. Fallacies connected with the relation of a whole and its parts. The sophisms of composition and division come next to be mentioned. The sophism of composition is when we infer anything concerning ideas in a compounded sense, which is only true in a divided sense. As if any one should argue thus : Two and three are even and odd ; five are two and three ; therefore five are even and odd. Here that is very falsely inferred concerning two and three in union, which is only true of them divided. The sophism of division is when we infer the same thing concerning ideas in a divided sense, which is only true in a compounded sense; as, if we should pretend to prove that every soldier in the Grecian army put a hundred thousand Persians to flight, because the Grecian soldiers did so. Or if a man should argue thus : Five is one number; two and three are five; therefore two and three are one number. IV. Fallacies connected with the relation of genus and species. v a) Misapplication of general principles from Mill's Logic. A third example is the opposition sometimes made to legitimate interferences of government in the economi- cal affairs of society, grounded upon a misapplication of 2OO the maxim, that an individual is a better judge than the government of what is for his own pecuniary interest. This objection was urged to Mr. Wakefield's system of colonisation, one of the greatest practical improve- ments in public affairs which have been made in our time. Mr. Wakefield's principle, as most people are now aware, is the artificial concentration of the settlers, by fixing such a price upon unoccupied land as may pre- serve the most desirable proportion between the quan- tity of land in culture and the labouring population. Against this it was argued, that if individuals found it for their advantage to occupy extensive tracts of land, they, being better judges of their own interest than the legislature (which can only proceed on general rules), ought not to be restrained from doing so. But in this argument it was forgotten that the fact of a man's taking a large tract of land is evidence only that it is his interest to take as much as other people, but not that it might not be for his interest to content himself with less, if he could be assured that other people would do so too; an assurance which nothing but a govern- ment regulation can give. If all other people took much, and he only a little, he would reap none of the advantages derived from the concentration of the popu- lation and the consequent possibility of procuring labour for hire, but would have placed himself, without equiva- lent, in a situation of voluntary inferiority. The pro- position, therefore, that the quantity of land which people will take when left to themselves is that which it is most for their interest to take, is true only secundum quid : it is only their interest while they have no guarantee for the conduct of one another. But the argu- ment disregards the limitation, and takes the proposi- tion for true simpliciter. Under the same head of fallacy (d dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter) might be placed all the errors which are vulgarly called misapplications of abstract truths : that is, where a principle, true (as the common expression is) in the LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 201 abstract, that is, all modifying causes being supposed absent, is reasoned upon as if it were true absolutely, and no modifying circumstances could ever by possi- bility exist. (b) Reasoning from loose definitions: Those who are familiar with the writings of Madame de Stael, know how constantly it was the practice of that acute and plausible writer, to have recourse to what may be called the fallacy of definition, which consists in giving an arbitrary meaning to some well-known expression, sufficiently large to include, or sufficiently narrow to exclude, the subject under discussion. V. Fallacies connected with the relation of cause and effect, whether the cause be physical, moral, conditional, or final. Taking for a cause that which is not a cause : The next kind of sophism is called non causa pro causa, or the assignation of a false cause. This the peri- patetic philosophers were guilty of continually, when they told us that certain beings, which they called sub- stantial forms, were the springs of colour, motion, vege- tation, and the various operations of natural beings in the animate and inanimate world; when they inform us that nature was terribly afraid of a vacuum; and that this was the cause why the water would not fall out of a long tube if it was turned upside down : the moderns, as well as the ancients, fall often into this fallacy, when they positively assign the reasons of natural appearances, without sufficient experiments to prove them. When comets, and eclipses of the sun and moon, are construed to signify the fate of princes, the revolution of states, famine, wars, and calamities of all kinds, it is a fallacy that belongs to this rank of sophisms. O 202 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION There is scarce anything more common in human life than this sort of deceitful argument. If any two acci- dental events happen to concur, one is presently made the cause of the other. If Titus wronged his neighbour of a guinea, and six months after he fell down and broke his leg, weak men will impute it to the Divine vengeance on Titus for his former injustice. VI. Fallacies connected with reasoning from examples. Drawing a general conclusion from a defective induction : (a) There is, after all these, another sort of sophism, which is wont to be called an imperfect Enumeration or a False Induction, when from a few experiments or observations men infer general theorems and universal propositions. Nivio in his youth observed, that on three Christmas days together there fell a good quantity of snow, and now hath writ it down in his almanack as a part of his wise remarks on the weather, that it will always snow at Christmas. Huron, a young lad, took notice ten times, that there was a sharp frost when the wind was in the north-east; therefore, in the middle of last July he almost expected it should freeze, because the weathercocks showed him a north-east wind; and he was still more disappointed, when he found it a very sultry season. It is the same hasty judgment that hath thrown scandal on a whole nation for the sake of some culpable characters belonging to several particular natives of that country ; whereas all the Frenchmen are not gay and airy; all the Italians are not jealous and revengeful ; nor all the English overrun with the spleen. (Watts.) (b) I have already said that the mode of Simple Enume- ration is still the common and received method of Induc- tion in whatever relates to man and society. Of this a LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 203 very few instances, more by way of memento than of instruction, may suffice. What, for example, is to be thought of all the " common-sense " maxims for which the following may serve as the universal formula? " Whatsoever has never been, will never be." As for example : Negroes have never been as civilised as whites sometimes are, therefore it is impossible they should be so. Women, as a class, have not hitherto equalled men as a class, in intellectual energy and comprehensiveness, therefore they are necessarily inferior. Society cannot prosper without this or the other institution; e.g. in Aristotle's time, without slavery; in later times, without an established priesthood, without artificial distinctions of ranks, etc. One working man in a thousand, edu- cated, while the nine hundred and ninety-nine remain uneducated, has usually aimed at raising himself out of his class, therefore education makes people dissatisfied with their condition in life. Bookish men, taken from speculative pursuits, and set to work on something they know nothing about, have generally been found or thought to do it ill ; therefore, philosophers are unfit for business, etc., etc. All these are inductions by simple enumeration.* VII. Fallacies connected with the relation of analogy, comparison, and contrast. But this is only one of the modes of error in the employment of arguments of analogy. There is another, more properly deserving the name of fallacy; namely, when resemblance in one point is inferred from resem- blance in another point, although there is not only no evidence to connect the two circumstances by way of causation, but the evidence tends positively to discon- nect them. This is properly the Fallacy of False Analo- gies. As a first instance, we may cite that favourite * Mill's Logic. 204 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION argument in defence of absolute power, drawn from the analogy of paternal government in a family, which government is not, and by universal admission ought not to be, controlled by (though it sometimes ought to be controlled for) the children. Paternal government, in a family, works well ; therefore, says the argument, despotic government in a state will work well : implying that the beneficial working of parental government depends, in the family, upon the only point which it has in common with political despotism, namely, irrespon- sibility. Whereas it does not depend upon that, but upon two other attributes of parental government, the affection of the parent for the children, and the superiority of the parent in wisdom and experience; neither of which properties can be reckoned upon, or are at all likely to exist, between a political despot and his subjects; and when either of these circumstances fails, even in the family, and the influence of the irresponsibility is allowed to work uncorrected, the result is anything but good government. This, therefore, is a false analogy. Another example is the not uncommon dictum, that bodies politic have youth, maturity, old age, and death, like bodies natural : that after a certain duration of prosperity they tend spontaneously to decay. This also is a false analogy, because the decay of the vital powers in an animated body can be distinctly traced to the natural progress of those very changes of structure which, in their earlier stages, constitute its growth to maturity ; while in the body politic, the progress of those changes cannot, generally speaking, have any effect but the still further continuance of growth ; it is the stoppage of that progress and the commencement of retrogression that alone could constitute decay. Bodies politic die, but it is of disease or violent death : they have no old age.* * Mill's Logic. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 205 VIII. Miscellaneous fallacies. (1) Verbal quibbles. Here is an amusing speci- men : Franklin had no taste for verbal criticism. On one occasion, when the Senate of Pennsylvania were engaged in a long discussion upon the wording of a resolution, he retired to one of the back seats, and engaged in con- versation with a friend on this subject. He said : " When I was a journeyman printer, a young trades- man, named John Owen, who was about to set up busi- ness as a ropemaker, came into the printing-office, and asked us what writing he should place over his shop window. The foreman immediately wrote on a board, ' John Owen, Ropemaker, makes and sells ropes ' ; with a coil of rope at the end. One man objected to the word ropemaker, as superfluous; for if he made ropes he was certainly a ropemaker. This word was accord- ingly struck out. Another objected to makes. He said, 4 Your workmen make the ropes, not you, and if you sell good ropes, people won't care whether you make them or not. ' The sentence then stood ' John Owen sells ropes.' 'John Owen sells ropes!' exclaimed another ; ' why, who would suppose that you intended to give them away ? what do you open a shop for but to sell them?' The word sells was then struck out, and ropes followed of course. Nothing then remained but ' John Owen,' and a coil of rope." (2) Historical evidence. In reproducing a long quotation from Whateley's famous Historic Doubts relative to Napoleon Buona- parte, it should be remembered that the argument from history as a species of reasoning is necessarily very much to the fore; and although Whateley tries to prove too much, his method is that on which many critics still rely. 206 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION I suppose it will not be denied that the three follow- ing are among the most important points to be ascer- tained, in deciding on the credibility of witnesses; first, whether they have the means of gaining correct informa- tion; secondly, whether they have any interest in con- cealing truth, or propagating falsehood; and, thirdly, whether they agree in their testimony. Let us examine the present witnesses upon all these points. First, what means have the editors of newspapers for gaining correct information? We know not, except from their own satements. Besides what is copied from other journals, foreign or British (which is usually more than three-fourths of the news published), they profess to refer to the authority of certain " private correspondents " abroad; who these correspondents are, what means they have of obtaining information, or whether they exist at all, we have no way of ascertaining. We find ourselves in the condition of the Hindoos, who are told by their priests that the earth stands on an elephant, and the elephant on a tortoise ; but are left to find out for themselves what the tortoise stands on, or whether it stands on anything at all. So much for our clear knowledge of the means of information possessed by these witnesses ; next, for the grounds on which we are to cauculate on their veracity. Have they not a manifest interest in circulating the wonderful accounts of Napoleon Buonaparte and his achievements, whether true or false? Few would read newspapers if they did not sometimes find wonderful or important news in them ; and we may safely say that no subject was ever found so inexhaustibly interesting as the present. Still it will be said, that unless we suppose a regularly preconcerted plan, we must at least expect to find great discrepancies in the accounts published. Though they might adopt the general outline of facts one from another, they would have to fill up the detail for themselves; and in this, therefore, we should meet with infinite and irreconcileable variety. 207 Now this is precisely the point I am tending to; for the fact exactly accords with the above supposition ; the discordance and mutual contradictions of these wit- nesses being such as would alone throw a considerable shade of doubt over their testimony. It is not in minute circumstances alone that the discrepancy appears, such as might be expected to appear in a narrative substan- tially true; but in very great and leading transactions, and such as are very intimately connected with the sup- posed hero. For instance, it is by no means agreed whether Buonaparte led in person the celebrated charge over the bridge of Lodi (for celebrated it certainly is, as well as the siege of Troy, whether either event ever really took place or no), or was safe in the rear, while Augereau performed the exploit. The same doubt hangs over the charge of the French cavalry at Waterloo. The peasant Lacoste, who professed to have been Buona- parte's guide on the day of battle, and who earned a fortune by detailing over and over again to visitors all the particulars of what the great man said and did up to the moment of flight this same Lacoste has been sus- pected by others, besides me, of having never even been near the great man, and having fabricated the whole story for the sake of making a gain of the credulity of travellers. It appears, then, that those on whose testimony the existence and actions of Buonaparte are generally believed, fail in ALL the most essential points on which the credulity of witnesses depends : first, we have no assurance that they have access to correct information ; secondly, they have an apparent interest in propagating falsehood ; and, thirdly, they palpably contradict each other in the most important points. But what shall we say to the testimony of those many respectable persons who went to Plymouth on purpose, and saw Buonaparte with their own eyes? must they not trust their senses? I would not disparage either the eyesight or the vera- city of these gentlemen. I am ready to allow that they 208 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION went to Plymouth for the purpose of seeing Buonaparte ; nay, more, that they actually rowed out into the harbour in a boat, and came alongside of a man-of-war, on whose deck they saw a man in a cocked hat, who, they were told, was Buonaparte. This is the utmost point to which their testimony goes; how they ascertained that this man in the cocked hat had gone through all the marvellous and romantic adventures with which we have so long been amused, we are not told. There is one more circumstance which I cannot forbear mention- ing, because it so much adds to the air of fiction which pervades every part of this marvellous tale; and that is the nationality of it. Buonaparte prevailed over all the hostile states in turn except England; in the zenith of his power, his fleets were swept from the sea, by England; his troops always defeat an equal, and frequently even a superior number of those of any other nation, except the English; and with them it is just the reverse; twice, and twice only, he is personally engaged against an English com- mander, and both times he is totally defeated ; at Acre, and at Waterloo; and to crown all, England finally crushes this tremendous power, which had so long kept the continent in subjection or in alarm; and to the English he surrenders himself prisoner ! Thoroughly national, to be sure! It may be all very true; but I would only ask, if a story had been fabricated for the express purpose of amusing the English nation, could it have been contrived more ingeniously?" CHAPTER XX. BAILEY'S RULES FOR ANALYSING ARGUMENTS. SAMUEL BAILEY, in his Theory of Reasoning, drew up what may be called a list of rules for testing arguments, and as they are much to the point (especially in view of a popular audience), I venture to reproduce them in full. Suppose, therefore, the student has before him a political speech, or an ethical pamphlet, which he wishes to analyse with an eye to its logic. He should first (1) Find the exact conclusion sought to be estab- lished by the writer, and state it as briefly, but as nearly as possible in his own language. (2) If the conclusion is obscure or ambiguous, endeavour to find out what the author meant ; and, if it is doubtful which of two or more propositions he intended to maintain, examine the argument, as suggested in the following rules, first on the assumption of one, and then on that of the other, or others. (3) Next find the reason or reasons assigned, and state them as the writer has done, and as nearly as possible in his own language, stripping them, how- ever, of redundant expressions and irrelevant matter. 209 210 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION (4) Examine the nature of the argument. (a) If it is direct contingent reasoning, consider well whether the facts alleged are sufficient to war- rant the general law, or, as the case may be, the particular inference : if not sufficient, it is needless to proceed further. (b) If the reasoning is ostensibly demonstrative, and in the form of enthymemes, it may be well to make it syllogistic by supplying what is called the missing or suppressed premise, since even should the last turn out to be needless, you will at all events have all the possible propositions before you ; and although needless, it must be true if the enthymeme is valid. When the argument has thus been brought into a definite form, examine the validity of the syllogism; and if it is fallacious, in consequence of confusion or ambiguity in the language or other cause, mark the fallacy, and your task is ended. (5) In both the above cases (a and b), since the premises are insufficient to prove the conclusion deduced from them, it will be well to consider whether a modified inference may not be drawn from the facts as stated. The facts do not bear out the asserted conclusion, but they may bear out something short of it : what conclusion do they enable us to deduce ? (6) Suppose, however, the inference to be valid, the next step, whether the argument belongs to direct contingent reasoning or to demonstrative reasoning, is to examine the truth of the premises, LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 211 or, in other words, of the facts asserted in them. The conclusion is warranted by the premises : but are the premises themselves to be relied upon ? (7) In this investigation of the truth of the pre- mises, you may possibly find that although the propositons, as stated by the author, are inadmis- sible, yet the substance of them is true, or, at least, susceptible of being put into a less objectionable shape. In such cases, as your object is not to take advantage of mere errors in form, but to come at the truth, whatever it may be, throw the argu- ment into the most forcible shape in which it can be exhibited, and then re-examine the whole. (8) If you satisfy yourself that the premises are erroneous, and can point out the circumstances which make them so, it will be useful to trace the source of the error in the mind of the writer. Nothing seems to give us a greater command of a subject than to be able, not only to see the mis- takes which have been made regarding it, but to ascend to their origin. (9) Recollect that in many cases, although you can show an argument to be fallacious, the conclu- sion may still be true, and all that you have done is simply to have placed it in the position of being improved. (10) In order to guard against the obscurity, vagueness, confusion, and ambiguity incident to language, endeavour to conceive, when practicable, the actual things represented by words; and when 212 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION the terms are complex, decompose their meaning into its constituent parts. (11) When the definition of an important word on which any of the reasoning turns has been given, make it a practice, in all obscure or dubious .pas- sages of the composition where it is employed, to substitute the definition for the term. If the writer under examination has furnished no definition of such a term, form one for yourself, and use it in the same manner. (12) When abstract general terms are used in any proposition, translate the proposition into concrete language, and try how the argument in which the proposition is employed will be affected by the change. CHAPTER XXI. CONVERSATIONAL REASONING. BY conversational reasoning, I mean, of course, that reasoning which is employed chiefly in conversa- tion. I say chiefly, for there is no kind of reason- ing that is employed exclusively in conversation, nor is conversational reasoning confined to only one kind. But all kinds of reasoning, when employed in conversation, are employed in a differ- ent manner as to the form or mode of expression from that employed in books or in speeches. It is impossible to describe all these forms. Every man will express his reasons in conversation in a way of his own, according to his constitutional tempera- ment, his education, his temper at the time, the occasion, or the manners of the society in which he is accustomed to move. (i) The language and form of conversational rea- soning. This is chiefly by enthymemes. I wish I had a good English word to substitute for the Greek word enthymeme it signifies, from the mind. Reasoning by enthymemes, therefore, means rea- soning from the mind : reasoning as you think, or talk, or write, in the ordinary affairs of life. .You 213 214 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION have heard of a character in a French play, who was surprised to learn that he had been talking prose for fifty years without knowing it. He might have made the same observation respecting enthy- memes. Whenever you have given a reason, you have spoken an enthymeme. If you observe to a friend, "It is a fine day," that is a description. If you ask, "Is it going to be wet?" that is an interrogation. If you say, " I shall take my um- brella, for I think it will rain," that is an enthy- meme. Enthymemes are treated of largely in Aristotle's Rhetoric. The following is the substance of his doctrine respecting them. An enthymeme bears the same relation to rhetoric as a syllogism to logic. It is composed of a sentence and a reason. A sentence is a general proposition concerning those things which are to be desired, or avoided, and it bears the same relation to an enthymeme as any proposition to a syllogism. And therefore a sen- tence, if a reason be rendered, becomes a conclu- sion, and both together make an enthymeme. The following is an example given by Aristotle: "To be over-learned produces effeminacy and envy. Therefore, he that is wise, will not suffer his children to be over-learned." The form of this enthymeme may be reversed thus : "A wise man will not suffer his children to be over-learned, because too much learning produces effeminacy and envy." Minto, in his Logic, Inductive and Deductive, refers to Hamilton's threefold division of enthy- memes. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 215 The first order has the major premiss under- stood : Caius is a coward; for Caius is a liar. The second order has the minor premiss under- stood : Caius is a coward : for all liars are cowards. The third order has the conclusion understood : All liars are cowards, and Caius is a liar. Huyshe quotes several examples: The enthymeme is a defective syllogism, which con- sists of one premiss and a conclusion; e.g. Diamonds are jewels, they are therefore valuable. God is a spirit ; therefore he is eternal. An enthymeme may easily be reduced to a regular syllogistic form ; for since the conclusion and one premiss are given, the three terms may be known, and the omitted premiss may be supplied : thus, in the above example, the major, " All jewels are valuable," is omitted, and, if supplied, the syllogism will be regular, thus : All jewels are valuable; Diamonds are jewels ; therefore, Diamonds are valuable. Again : Every spirit is eternal; God is a spirit; therefore, God is eternal. In both these examples, the major premiss is sup- pressed ; for, as was before observed, the major premiss is, generally speaking, some universal and incontro- 216 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION vertible principle, which is so evident that it is left to the hearer's judgment; but the minor premiss is most commonly expressed, because it has more particular reference to the question which is to be proved. In common discourse the usual mode of expressing an argument is by means of the enthymeme; it being unnecessary to adduce both the premises when one is so evident that it may very fairly be left to the hearer's judgment; e.g. When we find a book quoted, or referred to by an ancient author, we are entitled to conclude that it was read and received in the age and country in which that author lived. This sentence is an enthymeme, in which the major premiss is suppressed, but which may easily be supplied as follows : " Every book quoted, or referred to by an ancient author, must have been read and received in the age and country in which that author lived." The sentence may thus be reduced to a regular syllogism in Barbara : this may be effected in most enthy- memes without much difficulty, whether their conclu- sions be negative or affirmative. Although the major premiss is generally suppressed in most enthymemes, yet there are some enthymemes in which the minor premiss is found to be omitted : this may happen when the minor premiss is very evident, or when much stress is meant to be laid upon the major; e.g. "Every tyrannical king deserves to be deposed by his subjects ; therefore Nero deserved to be deposed by the Romans." The minor premiss, which is suppressed, may be thus supplied : Nero was a tyrannical king : and thus the argument is reduced to the regular syllo- gistic form. An enthymeme is sometimes condensed into one sen- tence, which is called an enthymematic sentence: viz., LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 217 when the premiss is united in one proposition with the conclusion; e.g. " All machines, being of human manufacture, are liable to imperfections." This argu- ment may be thus expanded into a regular syllogism : All things of human manufacture are liable to imperfections ; All machines are of human manufacture; therefore, They are liable to imperfections. The following are further examples of enthy- memes : We enjoy a greater degree of political liberty than any civilised people on earth, and therefore have no excuse for a seditious disposition. The power of ridicule is a dangerous faculty, since it tempts its possessor to find fault unjustly, and to dis- tress some for the gratification of others. The study of mathematics is essential to a complete course of education, because it induces a habit of close and regular reasoning. Hard substances may be elastic, for ivory is both hard and elastic. The example of Virgil shows that even a great poet may be seduced into some faults by the practice of imitation. The apparent insufficiency of every individual to his own happiness or safety, compels us to seek from one another assistance and support. Real learning is too valuable a thing to be within the grasp of the idle. You will observe that although an enthymeme is called by scholastic logicians a defective syllo- gism, yet the syllogism is formed from the enthy- meme, not the enthymeme from the syllogism. The enthymeme is the natural mode of reasoning; P 218 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION the syllogism is the artificial mode. The argument first occurs to our mind in the form of an enthy- meme, but when we wish to make it clearer, we extend it to a syllogism. You will remember that the occurrence of " for," "because," "therefore," or any similar word, either in conversation or in reading, usually denotes an enthymeme; in other words, denotes a reason or argument expressed naturally, without the for- mality of scholastic logic. (2) The principles of reasoning most in use in con- versation. We refer not here to that communication which takes place on occasion of buying and selling, or in any other of the business transactions of life. .We speak of that kind of conversation which takes place in the hours of social intercourse. Into this circle, formal logical definitions, and processes of syllogistic reasoning, are never introduced. Nor do we witness any pitched battles of controversy nor systematic discussions of any one topic nor captious objections nor triumphant boastings. Every principle of reasoning may be introduced into conversation, but I think those most frequently employed are the relation of cause and effect, of example and of analogy. You call on a friend, and find he has taken cold. You inquire the cause. It may be he rode in an omnibus with the windows open ; he was caught in a shower without an umbrella, or he got his feet wet, and did not change his boots; or perhaps his female relations LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 219 will tell you that it was all his own fault, as lie never takes proper care of himself. Here you will have an interesting discussion upon the relation of cause and effect. But you observe, you had previously called on half a dozen of your friends, and they all had colds. You infer it is a very unhealthy season. Here you reason from example, and you arrive at your conclusion by induction. But you think the situation of your friend's house is a very exposed one, and you make a comparison between that and other situations which are more sheltered. The language of conversational reason- ing will be, as we have stated, enthymemical. Descriptions, when introduced, will be short, unless one of the party is describing an object which the others may have not seen, as Klondyke, or the Argentine. Interrogative reasoning is sometimes employed, but chiefly in the form of inquiry : "How do you account for this?" And in this mode it is sometimes prefixed to an argument from analogy. The form of dilemma a form to be hereafter described is also often used in conversa- tion. By a little observation on those conversa- tions that come under your notice, you will soon be able to discover the principles and forms of reasoning that enter into their composition. (3) Under the heading of " Rules usually observed in Conversational Reasoning," Gilbart wanders somewhat from the object he has in view; instead of dealing with logic in conversation, he dabbles in its ethics, quoting from a quaint old book with the title, " The Art of Conversation, 220 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION with Remarks on Fashion and Dress," by Captain Orlando Sabertash. I reproduce a section : As to subjects for conversation, what difficulty can there be about them ? Will not books, balls, bonnets, and metaphysics furnish pleasant topics of discourse? Can you not speak of the " Philosophy and science, and the springs Of wonder, and the wisdom of the world?" Are flirtation, travelling, love, and speech making at an end; is St. Stephen's shut up; or is the great globe itself and the weather on its surface so perfectly stationary that you can find nothing to say about them ? No, no, let us not deceive ourselves : we never want subjects of conversation; but we often want the know- ledge how to treat them; above all, how to bring them forward in a graceful and pleasing manner. There is, I am sorry to say, a great deal of servility in the very best society : a needless meanness, seen through at once; for you may be pleasant, courteous, and well-bred, without cringing to the wit or opinions of others. All that is expected, or can be expected from you, is, that you are not to shock the unsuccessful wit by exposing his stupidity, however glaring it may be, nor mark dissent from opinions in which you may not coincide, in such a manner as to bring on an argument or dis- cussion. Any pleasant, passing, and good-humoured jest will free you from noticing the wit, if particularly forced upon your attention; even as an easy, playful dissent from objectionable opinions will relieve you from the necessity of disputing or submitting to them. Franklin says, that you must never contradict in con- versation, nor correct facts if wrongly stated. This is going much too far : you must never contradict in a short, direct, or positive tone : but with politeness, you may easily, when necessary, express a difference of opinion in a graceful and even complimentary manner. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 221 And I would almost say, that the art of conversation consists in knowing how to contradict, and when to be silent; for, as to constantly acting a fawning and meanly deferential part in society, it is offensive to all persons of good sense and good feeling. In regard to facts wrongly stated, no well-bred man ever thinks of correcting them, merely to show his wisdom in trifles; but with politeness, it is perfectly easy to rectify an error, when the nature of the conversation demands the explanation. Whenever the lady or gentleman with whom you are discussing a point, whether of love, war, science, or politics, begins to sophisticate, drop the subject instantly. Your adversary either wants the ability to maintain his opinion and then it would be uncivil to press it or he wants the still more useful ability to yield the point with unaffected grace and good humour; or, what is also possible, his vanity is in some way engaged in defending views on which he may probably have acted, so that to demolish his opinions is perhaps to reprove his conduct, and no well-bred man goes into society for the purpose of sermonising. (4) Some of the most interesting examples of conversational reasoning are found in Boswell's Johnson. I praised the accuracy of an account-book of a lady whom I mentioned. JOHNSON : " Keeping accounts, Sir, is of no use when a man is spending his own money, and has nobody to whom he is to account. You won't eat less beef to-day because you have written down what it cost yesterday." I mentioned another lady who thought as he did, so that her husband could not get her to keep an account of the expense of the family, as she thought it enough that she never exceeded the sum allowed her. JOHNSON: " Sir, it is fit she should keep an account, because her husband wishes it; but I do not see its use." I maintained that keeping an account has this advan- 222 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION tage, that it satisfies a man that his money has not been lost or stolen, which he might sometimes be apt to imagine, were there no written state of his expense : and, besides, a calculation of economy, so as not to exceed one's income, cannot be made without a view of the different articles in figures, that one may see how to retrench in some particulars less necessary than others. This he did not attempt to answer. Mr. Walker, the celebrated master of elocution, came in, and then we went up stairs into the study. I asked him if he had taught many clergymen. JOHNSON : " I hope not." WALKER : " I have taught only one, and he is the best reader I ever heard, not by my teaching, but by his own natural talents." JOHNSON : " Were he the best reader in the world, I would not have it told that he was taught." Here was one of his peculiar prejudices. Could it be any disadvantage to the clergy- man to have it known that he was taught an easy and graceful delivery? Bos WELL : " Will you not allow, Sir, that a man may be taught to read well?" JOHN- SON: " Why, Sir, so far as to read better than he might do without being taught, yes. Formerly it was supposed that there was no difference in reading, but that one read as well as another." Bos WELL : "It is wonderful to see old Sheridan as enthusiastic about oratory as ever." WALKER : " His enthusiasm as to what oratory will do, may be too great : but he reads well." JOHNSON: " He reads well, but he reads low; and you know it is much easier to read low than to read high; for when you read high you are much more limited, your loudest note can be but one, and so the variety is less in proportion to the loudness. Now some people have occasion to speak to an extensive audience, and must speak loud to be heard." WALKER : " The art is to read strong, though low." Talking of the origin of language : JOHNSON : " It must have come by inspiration. A thousand, nay a million of children could not invent a language. While LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 223 the organs are pliable, there is not understanding enough to form a language; by the time that there is under- standing enough the organs are become stiff. We know that after a certain age we cannot learn to pronounce a new language. No foreigner who comes to England when advanced in life ever pronounces English tolerably well; at least, such instances are very rare. When I maintain that language must have come by inspiration, I do not mean that inspiration is required for rhetoric, and all the beauties of language; for when once man has language, we can conceive that he may gradually form modifications of it. I mean only that inspiration seems to me to be necessary to give man the faculty of speech ; to inform him that he may have speech ; which I think he could no more find out without inspiration than cows or hogs would think of such a faculty." WALKER : " Do you think, Sir, that there are any perfect synonymes in any language?" JOHXSON* : " Originally there were not; but by using words negligently, or in poetry, one word comes to be confounded with another." (5) After the above examples of conversational reasoning, I will conclude this section with an example of a conversation without reasoning^. It is taken from Miss Austen's description of "The Voluble Lady": My dear sir, you are too obliging. Is there nobody you would not rather? I am not helpless. Sir, you are most kind. Upon my word, Jane on one arm, and me on the other ! Stop, stop, let us stand a little back, Mrs. Elton is going; dear Mrs. Elton, how elegant she looks beautiful lace ! Now we all follow in her train. Quite the queen of the evening ! Well, here we are at the passage. Two steps, Jane, take care of the two steps. Oh ! no, there is but one. Well, I was per- suaded there were two. How very odd ! I was con- vinced there were two, and there is but one. I never 224 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION saw anything equal to the comfort and style candles everywhere. I was telling you of your grandmamma, Jane there was a little disappointment. The baked apples and biscuits, excellent in their way, you know; but there was a delicate fricassee of sweetbread and some asparagus brought in at first, and good Mr. Woodhouse, not thinking the asaparagus boiled enough, sent it all out again. Now there is nothing grand- mamma loves better than sweetbread and asparagus so she was rather disappointed; but we agreed we would not speak of it to anybody, for fear of its getting round to dear Miss Woodhouse, who would be so very much concerned. Well, this is brilliant ! I am all amaze- ment could not have supposed anything such ele- gance and profusion ! I have seen nothing like it since Well, where shall we sit? Where shall we sit? Any- where, so that Jane is not in a draught. Where / sit is of no consequence. Oh ! do you recommend this side? Well, I am sure, Mr. Churchill only it seems too good but just as you please. What you direct in this house cannot be wrong. Dear Jane, how shall we ever recol- lect half the dishes for grandmamma? Soup too ! Bless me ! I should not be helped so soon, but it smells most excellent, and I cannot help beginning. CHAPTER XXII. REASONING BY SINGLE SYLLOGISM. IF the mere perception and comparison of two ideas would always show us whether they agree or disagree, then all rational propositions would be matters of intelligence, or first principles, and there would be no use in reasoning, or drawing any con- sequences. It is the narrowness of the human mind which introduces the necessity of reasoning. When we are unable to judge of the truth or false- hood of a proposition in an immediate manner, by the mere contemplation of its subject and predicate, we are then constrained to use a medium, and to compare each of them with some third idea, that by seeing how far they agree or disagree with it, we may be able to judge how far they agree or disagree among themselves : as if there are two lines, A and B, and I know not whether they are equal or no, I take a third line c, or an inch, and apply it to each of them ; if it agree with them both, then I infer that A and B are equal : but if it agree with one and not with the other, then I conclude A and B are unequal : if it agree with neither of them, there can be no comparison. If I say that some taxes ought not to be paid, a friend will argue thus : All taxes levied by Government must be paid. 225 226 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION The tax on Incomes is levied by Government. Therefore Income tax must be paid. Thus it appears what is the strict and just notion of a syllogism : it is a sentence or argument made up of three propositions, so disposed as that the last is necessarily inferred from those which go before, as in the instances which have been just mentioned. The three terms are named the major, the minor, and the middle. The predicate of the conclusion is called the major term, because it is generally of a larger extension than the minor term, or the subject. The major and minor terms are called the extremes. The middle term is the third idea, invented and disposed in two propositions, in such a manner as to show the connexion between the major and minor term in the conclusion ; for which reason the middle term itself is sometimes called the argument. That proposition which contains the predicate of the conclusion, connected with the middle term, is usually called the major proposition, whereas the minor proposition connects the middle term with the subject of the conclusion, and is sometimes called the assumption. This exact distinction of the several parts of a syllogism, and of the major and minor terms connected with the middle term in the major and minor propositions, does chiefly belong to simple or categorical syllogisms, though all syllogisms whatsoever have something ana- logical to it. Single syllogisms are made up of three propositions: compound syllogisms contain more than three propositions, and may be formed into two or more syllogisms., LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 227 Single syllogisms, for distinction's sake, may be divided into simple, complex, and conjunctive. I. SIMPLE SYLLOGISM. Those are properly called simple or categorical syllogisms, which are made up of three plain, single, or categorical propositions, wherein the middle term is evidently and regularly joined with one part of the question in the major proposition, and with the other in the minor, whence there flows a plain single conclusion ; as " Every human virtue is to be sought with diligence ; prudence is a human virtue; therefore, prudence is to be sought with diligence." II. COMPLEX SYLLOGISM. Those are properly called complex syllogisms, in which the middle term is not connected with the whole subject, or the whole predicate in two distinct propositions, but is intermingled and com- pared with them by parts, or in a more confused manner, in different forms of speech ; as, " The sun is a senseless being; The Persians worshipped the sun ; Therefore, the Persians worshipped a sense- less being." Here the predicate of the conclusion is, " wor- shipped a senseless being," part of which is joined with the middle term, " sun," in the major proposi- tion, and the other part in the minor. Though this sort of argument is confessed to be entangled or confused, and irregular, if examined by the rules 228 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION of simple syllogisms, yet there is a great variety of arguments used in books of learning, and in common life, whose consequence is strong and evident, and which must be ranked under this head ; as, None but physicians came to the consultation ; the nurse is no physician ; therefore, the nurse came not to the consultation. The fogs vanish as the sun rises; but the fogs have not yet begun to vanish; therefore, the sun is not yet risen. It is necessary that a general understand the art of war; but Caius does not understand the art of war; therefore, it is necessary Caius should not be a general. A total eclipse of the sun would cause darkness at noon ; it is possible that the moon at that time may totally eclipse the sun ; therefore, it is possible that the moon may cause darkness at noon. Now the force of all these arguments is so evident and conclusive, that though the form of the syl- logism be never so irregular, yet we are sure the inferences are just and true; for the premises, according to the reason of things, do really contain the conclusion that is deduced from them, which is a never-failing test of a true syllogism. III. CONJUNCTIVE SYLLOGISM. Those are called conjunctive syllogisms, wherein one of the premises, namely the major, has distinct parts, which are joined by a conjunction, or some LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 229 such particle of speech. Most times the major or minor, or both, are explicitly compound proposi- tions arid generally the major proposition is made up of two distinct parts or propositions, in such a manner, as that by the assertion of one in the minor, the other is either asserted or denied in the conclusion : or, by the denial of one in the minor, the other is either asserted or denied in the con- clusion. It is hardly possible indeed to fit any short definition to include all the kinds of them ; but the chief amongst them are conditional syllo- gism, the disjunctive, the relative, and the con- nexive. (1) The conditional or hypothetical syllogism, is that whose major or minor, or both, are conditional propositions; e.g. If such an administration had involved the country in war it would have been a bad administra- tion. But it did not involve the country in war; Therefore it was not a bad administration. Take Cicero's defence of Mura?na : " I could then only be accused with justice of acting contrary to my law, if I maintained that Muraena purchased the votes and was justified in doing so. But I maintain that he did not buy the votes, therefore I do nothing contrary to the law." (2) A disjunctive syllogism is when the major proposition is disjunctive; as, The earth moves in 230 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION a circle or an ellipsis; but it does not move in a circle; therefore it moves in an ellipsis. Again : Those who have slain Caesar are either parricides or defenders of liberty ; They are not parricides; Therefore they are defenders of liberty. All sciences are either pure, inductive, or mixed sciences ; But astronomy is not a pure or an inductive science ; It is therefore a mixed science. Mahomet was either an enthusiast or an impostor ; But he was an enthusiast; Therefore he was not an impostor. (3) A relative syllogism requires the major proposition to be relative; as, "As is the captain, so are his soldiers; but the captain is a coward; therefore his soldiers are cowards too." Arguments that relate to the doctrine of pro- portion must be referred to this head; as, As two are to four, so are three to six; but two make the half of four; therefore, three make the half of six. (4) A connexive syllogism requires that two or more ideas be so connected, either in the complex subject or predicate of the major, that if one of them be affirmed or denied in the minor, common sense will naturally show us what will be the conse- quence. LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 231 For example : A Government cannot be at the same time despotic and the licenser of a free press ; But the English Government permits a free press ; Therefore the English Government is not despotic. Reasoning by means of syllogisms has been a thorny subject of debate among logicians for many years past. Minto remarks that " there have been heaps and mazes of discussion about the use of the syllogism, much of it being profitable as a warning against the neglect of formal logic. Again and again it has been demonstrated that the syllogism is useless for certain purposes and from this it has been concluded that the syllogism is of no use at all."* The truth seems to be that it is a form of reasoning, but not adapted for arguments founded on induction, analogy, or on mere probability. The conclusion of a syllogism should be a certainty and a certain deduction from the premises. Let us take Mill's example: All men are mortal : The Duke of Wellington is a man ; Therefore the Duke of Wellington is mortal. Here you will observe it is essential to the validity of this argument that the first proposition should be universally true. Had it been said, " All men (except one) are mortal ; the Duke of Wellington is a man;" we could not have inferred that the * Logic, Inductive and Deductive, p. 209. 232 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION Duke of Wellington is mortal, for that excepted one might, for aught we know, be the Duke of Wellington. It would appear from this example, that the syllogism is not adapted for probable arguments, however high the degree of probability may be. Hence, as in the moral sciences, and in the ordinary affairs of life, we cannot always have more than a high degree of probability, it seems to follow that in these sciences and in these affairs we cannot always employ the syllogism. The chief principle of reasoning for which the syllogism appears to be adapted, is that of genus and species, and here chiefly when the relation of genus and species is founded in nature. When we try to form this relation mentally, by simply chang- ing the mode of expression, we may weaken our reasoning. In similar cases we can rarely form a major proposition, capable of being proved to be universally true. We place ourselves by syllogism under the necessity of proving a universal, when the argument requires us to prove only a particular. And we attempt to prove by reasoning a proposi- tion that cannot be proved but by observation and experience. Although an argument legitimately founded on any other relation than genus and species, such as the relation of subject and attribute, cause and effect, can seldom be so well expressed by syllo- gism, yet, when an argument is legitimately founded on the relation of genus and species, and that a natural, not an artificial relation, the syllo- gism will sometimes afford the means of expressing the argument with superior clearness. Perhaps LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 233 this is the case in the example we have noticed. Were we to say, " As the Duke of Wellington is a man, he must be mortal " ; or, " As all men are mortal, the Duke of Wellington must be mortal, for he is only a man " ; or any similar mode of expression, we should not, perchance, express our meaning with as much clearness as in the above syllogism. While we are thus ready to admit that the syllogism is sometimes a useful form of reason- ing, we do not admit that an argument derives greater strength from being put into this form. In fact, no argument obtains increased strength by being expressed in one form more than in another. The advantage gained is in point of clearness, or in adaptation to the party to whom the argument may be addressed. The same form is not suitable for all occasions. The form which gives clearness and adaptation in one case may in another case be attended with obscurity and unsuitableness. The case in which syllogisms may be used with advan- tage is, as we have said, in natural relations of genus and species. In many other cases we think them unsuitable, and in some, probably injurious. CHAPTER XXIII. REASONING BY COMPOUND SYLLOGISM. WE properly call those compound syllogisms, which are made of two or more single syllogisms, and may be resolved into them. The chief kinds are these : epichirema, dilemma, prosyllogisms, and sorites. I. Epichirema is a syllogism which contains the proof of the major or minor, or both, before it draws the conclusion. This is often used in writing, in public speeches, and in common conversation; that so each part of the dis- course may be confirmed and put out of doubt, as it moves on toward the conclusion which was chiefly designed. Take the instance in Cicero's oration in defence of Milo, who had slain Clodius. His major pro- position is, that " it is lawful for one man to kill another who lies in wait to kill him, which he proves from the custom of nations, from natural equity, examples, etc. His minor is, that Clodius " laid wait for Milo " ; wJiich he proves by his arms, guards, etc. ; and then infers the conclusion, that " it was lawful for Milo to kill Clodius." II. A Dilemma is an argument which divides the whole into all its parts or members by a dis- junctive proposition, and then infers something 234 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 235 concerning each part which is finally inferred con- cerning the whole. Instances of this are frequent; as, In this life we must either obey our vicious inclinations, or resist them : to obey them will bring sin and sorrow; to resist them is laborious and painful : therefore, we cannot be per- fectly free from sorrow or pain in this life. A dilemma becomes faulty or ineffectual three ways : First, when the members of the division are not well opposed, or not fully enumerated ; for then the major is false. Secondly, when what is asserted concerning each part is not just ; for then the minor is not true. Thirdly, when it may be retorted with equal force upon him who utters it. There was a famous ancient instance of this case, wherein a dilemma was retorted. Euathlus promised Protagoras a reward when he had taught him the art of pleading; and it was to be paid the first day that he gained any cause in the court. After a considerable time Protagoras goes to law with Euathlus for the reward, and uses this dilemma : " Either the cause will go on my side, or on yours : if the cause goes on my side, you must pay me, according to the sentence of the judge; if the cause goes on your side, you must pay me according to your bargain ; therefore, whether the cause goes for me or against me, you must pay me the reward." But Euathlus retorted this dilemma thus: " Either I shall gain the cause, or lose it : if I gain the cause, then nothing will be due to you, according to the sentence of the judge; but if I lose the cause, nothing will be due to you, according to my bargain; therefore, whether I lose or gain the cause, I will not pay you, for nothing will be due to you." The attempt to provide artificial dilemmas is a trick of the debater. Bradlaugh is said on one occasion to have asked an opponent for an answer, " Yes," or " No," to a specific question. The debater said the question could not be answered in the direct affirmative 236 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION or negative. Bradlaugh said every question could be so answered. Whereupon his opponent asked him : " Mr. Bradlaugh, have you ceased beating your wife?" To say " Yes," or " No," implied a serious admission, and, of course, Mr. Bradlaugh did not beat his wife. III. A Prosy llogism is when two or more syllo- gisms are so connected together, that the conclusion of the former is the major or the minor of the following : Example Blood cannot think ; but the soul of man thinks ; there- fore, the soul of man is not blood : but the soul of a brute is his blood, according to the Scripture; therefore, the soul of man is different from the soul of a brute. Happiness is the result of certain habits; Man has the power of acquiring those habits; Therefore, man has the power of making himself happy. Man has the power of making himself happy; Every wise man uses this power; Therefore, every wise man is a happy man. IV. A sorites is when several middle terms are chosen to connect one another successively in several propositions till the last proposition con- nects its predicate with the first subject. For example I may say A is B. C is D. D is E. Therefore A is E. A good illustration is given by Lord Eldon on the occasion of Laurence's injunction concerning LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 237 the pirated edition of his book on The Natural History of Man. " I have a rational doubt whether some portion of this book do not lean to mate- rialism ; what leans to materialism is inconsistent with the immortality of the soul ; what is incon- sistent with the immortality of the soul is contrary to Scripture; but as that which contradicts Scrip- ture does not come under the protection of the law, I have a rational doubt whether the injunction can be maintained; therefore the injunction is dis- solved."* The sorites is, of course, much used in mathe- matical demonstrations. * Devey's Logic, p. 139. CHAPTER XXIV. ARGUMENTS FOR ANALYSIS. THE object of the following selection is to offer some facilities for examining real arguments, or what pass as arguments, as distinct from the dull and dry specimens found in some text-books of logic. I am indebted to Lateur's Illustrations of Logic for a few of the following examples : I would encourage parents to carry their daugh- ters early and much into company; for what harm can be done before so many witnesses ? Solitude is the surest nurse of all prurient passions; and a girl in the hurry of preparation, or tumult of gaiety, has neither inclination nor leisure to let tender expressions soften or sink into her heart. The ball, the show, are not the dangerous places : no, it is the private friend, the kind consoler, the companion of the easy, vacant hour, whose compliance with her opinions can flatter her vanity, and whose con^ejfvfetion can first soothe, without ever shielding her mind that is the lover to be feared. He who buzzes in her ear at Court, or at the opera, must be contented to buzz in vain. Dr. Johnson. So you object, with old Hobbes, that I do good actions for the pleasure of a good conscience; and 238 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 239 so, after all, I am only a refined sensualist. Heaven bless you, and men your logic ! Don't you see that if conscience, which is in its nature a consequence, were thus anticipated and made an antecedent a party instead of a judge it would dishonour your draft upon it it would not pay on demand ? Don't you see that, in truth, the very fact of acting with this motive properly and logic- ally destroys all claims upon conscience to give you any pain at all ? S. T. Coleridge. The entire difference between enlightened politi- cians and the advocates of violent measures may be exemplified by the difference in the signification of the singular and the plural of the word reform. A man who uses this term in the singular, exclaim- ing, " I am for reform," is a revolutionist, and an advocate of every kind of violent change which would suit his selfish ends or his vague, conceited notions of things; but the term reform means the sanitary removal of certain impediments to the welfare of society, which powerful minds, after a thorough investigation and consideration of cir- cumstances, have found to be such ; therefore every enlightened politician may pronounce himself to be an advocate of reforms. Prince Metternich. Education is all paint : it does not alter the nature of the wood that is under it, it only improves its appearance a little. Why I dislike education so much is, that it makes all people alike, until you have examined into them; and it is sometimes so long before you get to see under the varnish ! 240 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION Education, beyond reading, writing, and arith- metic, is of no use to persons who have shops to attend to, household duties to perform, and, indeed, in all the ordinary occupations of life. Lady Stanhope. No story ought to be well constructed or prob- able, in the ordinary sense of the word. If you relate only common events and ascribe actions to such motives only as would produce them in com- mon characters, what materials have you for a romance? The drama is a picture of life, where the objects represented are real, though the group- ing is such as the ordinary business of mankind does not exhibit. Byron. What has love to do with the intellect? We love a young woman for everything but her intel- lect for her beauty, her youth, her seductiveness, her candour, her faults, her caprices, and heaven knows for what other inexpressible things but we don't love her for her intellect. We may esteem her for intellect, if she is clever; and a young girl gains much in our sight by being clever. Intellect may enslave us if we are predisposed to like it; but intellect cannot warm us or inspire us with passion. Goethe. The best of us being unfit to die, what an inex- pressible absurdity to put the worst to death ! Hawthorne. Capital punishment is a violation of natural justice. No society has a right to deprive the LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 241 individual of that which he has not obtained from society. Argument of a Portuguese in defence of the abolition of capital punishment in his country. We have been saying in thousands of treatises on Logic, All men are mortal : Socrates is a man, therefore Socrates is mortal. The elephant reasons : All boys are bun-giving animals; that biped is a boy; therefore I will hold out my trunk to him. A philosopher says, The barometer is rising, and therefore we shall have fine weather ; his dogs says, My master is putting on his hat, and therefore I am going to have a walk. A dog equals a detective in the sharpness with which he infers general objec- tionableness from ragged clothes. A clever dog draws more refined inferences. If he is not up to enough simple arithmetic to count seven, he can at least say, Everybody is looking so gloomy, that it must be Sunday morning. Leslie Stephen/. I hold that a long poem does not exist. I main- tain that the phrase, "A long poem," is simply a flat contradiction in terms. I need scarcely observe that a poem deserves its title only inasmuch as it excites, by elevating the soul. The value of the poem is in the ratio of this elevating excitement. But all excitements are, through a psychal neces- sity, transient. That degree of excitement which would entitle a poem to be called so at all, cannot be sustained throughout the composition of any great length. After the lapse of half an hour at the very utmost, it flags fails a revulsion ensues 242 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION and then the poem is in effect, and in fact, no longer such. Edgar Allan Poc. The deductive inquirer . . . will argue thus : Poetry appeals to the imagination, mathematics to the understanding. To work the imagination is more exciting than to work the understanding, and what is habitually exciting is usually unhealthy. But what is usually unhealthy will tend to shorten life; therefore poetry tends more than mathematics to shorten life; therefore, on the w r hole, poets will die sooner than mathematicians. Henry Thomas Buckle. All living, in the first place, however common-' place its aims, however accidental its ideals, in- volves a deep paradox. We long to live. Very well, then, we long to be active. For life means activity; and activity, that again means longing, striving, suffering, lack, hoping for the end of the activity in which we are immediately engaged- . . . Life is will ; and every will aims at its own com- pletion, that is, at its own cessation. I will to be wiser than I am. Well, then, I will that my present foolishness shall cease. I will to get some- body's love; and that means that I will the cessa- tion of my unloved condition. Every will aims at the attainment of its desire; and attainment is the death of just this desire, and so of just this act of will. And yet, on the whole, I will to live. /. Royce. Haeckel seeks to get out of a difficulty by assum- ing that the principle of life has its origin in the LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 243 physical and chemical properties of albuminous bodies. And how are these albuminous bodies formed ? By the tendency of carbon towards mani- fold combinations with other elements. And what is the cause of this tendency and also of all other chemical properties of bodies? " I do not know," answers Haeckel. " Then," it may be replied, " if your hypothesis is sound, you have done nothing more than remove the mystery a little farther, and if the cause of your vital principle springs in its turn from an unknown cause, your explanation is reduced to this : The original cause of life is equal to x." Antonio Fogaszaro. I am a finite being, God is infinite : I am im- perfect and defective. God is perfect and without defects. It is, therefore, impossible for me to be the cause of this idea. Either I cannot have such a conception at all, or its cause must be a being of like reality; i.e., God Himself. But I have the idea of God; and, in this case, to have it is equiva- lent to having received it. Every conception, as every phenomenon, has its cause. If I clearly and distinctly perceive that I cannot be this cause, I know just as clearly and distinctly that it must be without me ; that there is, therefore, a being without me. Kuno Fischer. You know what Pericles said of his son's dog Azor : Azor rules my boy, my boy rules his mother, his mother rules me, I rule Athens, Athens rules Greece, and Greece rules the world, where- fore Azor is the ruler of the world. Same remark 244 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION applies to Mdlle. Mimi Triboulette's dog, Bichon. Bichon governs Mdlle. Mimi, Mimi governs the Parisian public, the Parisian public governs Europe, Europe governs the two hemispheres; ergo, Bichon is the governor of the universe. E. C. Grenville Murray. What distinguishes one being from another is its organisation. That is what distinguishes a plant from a mineral, an animal in one species from one in another. Every being has therefore its own nature; and because of having its own nature, it is predestined by that nature to a certain end. If the end (purpose) of the bee, for example, is not that of the lion, and that of the lion again not identical with that of man, the reason of it can be found nowhere but in the difference of their respective natures. Every being is therefore organised in view of a certain end, so that, if one only knew its nature completely, one could deduce therefrom its intention or end. The end of a being is what we call its good. There is consequently an absolute identity between the good of a being and its end. Its good is to compass its end, to travel to the limit of the purpose for which it has been organised. Jouffroy. Make the necessaries of life too expensive for the poor to reach them, and you will save their money. If they buy but few candles, they will pay but little tax; and if they buy none, the tax, as to them, will be annihilated. Coivper. 245 People really do not know what they mean by complaining that vice is happy and virtue unhappy in this world. ... It is manifestly proved that ills of every sort rain down on the human race like bullets on an army, without any distinction of persons. Now, if the good man does not suffer because he is good, and if the wicked does not prosper because he is wicked, the objection dis- appears and common sense has triumphed. Joseph De Maistre. If no man has a right to political power, then neither Jew nor Gentile has such a right. The whole foundation of government is taken away. But if government be taken away, the property and the persons of men are insecure ; and it is acknowledged that men have a right to their property and to personal security. If it be right that the property of men should be protected, and if this can only be done by means of government, then it must be right that government should exist. Now there cannot be government unless some person or persons possess political power. There- fore, it is right that some person or persons should possess political power. That is to say, some person or persons must have a right to political power. Macaulay. Why does the murdered deserve death ? The answer will be, because he has deliberately taken human life. Then, of course, the same guilt is perpetrated, and the same penalty incurred, when the law deliberately takes human life in return. For wherein is there a difference ? Both acts of 246 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION homicide are perpetrated wilfully, and to our mind the homicide of the law is worse than the homicide of the assassin, inasmuch as it is committed in cold blood, and in the sight of day. Eclectic Review, July, Suicide is indeed one of those acts which may be condemned by moralists as a sin, but which, in modern times at least, cannot be regarded as within the legitimate sphere of law; for a society which accords to its members perfect liberty of emigration, cannot reasonably pronounce the simple renunciation of life to be an offence against itself. W. E. H. Lecky. David said in his wrath, All men are liars. Therefore, David w T as a liar. Therefore, what David said was not true. Therefore, David was not a liar. But if David was not a liar, what he said was true namely, that all men are liars. Those men who set up Nature as a standard of action do not intend a merely verbal exposition ; they do not mean that the standard, whatever it be, should be called Nature ; they think they are giving some information as to what the standard of action really is. They who say that we ought to act according to Nature, do not mean the mere identical proposition that we ought to do what we ought to do. They think that the word Nature affords some external criterion of what we should do; and if they lay down as a rule for what ought LOGIC FOR THE MILLION 247 to be, a word which in its proper signification denotes what is, they do so because they have a notion, either clearly or confusedly, that what is, constitutes the rule and standard of what ought to be. y. 5. Mill. How (it has been asked) does a child come to form the very abstract and metaphysical idea expressed by the pronoun I or moi? In answer to this question, I have only to observe that when we set about the explanation of a phenomenon, we must proceed on the supposition that it is pos- sible to resolve it into some more general law or laws with which we are already acquainted. But in the case before us, how can this be expected, by those who consider that all our knowledge of mind is derived from the exercise of reflection ; and that every act of this power implies a conviction of our own existence as reflecting and intelligent beings? Every theory, therefore, which pretends to account for this conviction, must necessarily involve that sort of paralogism which logicians call a petitio principii; inasmuch as it must resolve the thing to be explained into some law or laws, the evidence of which rests ultimately on the assumption in question. Dugald Stewart. It is a matter of infinite difficulty, but, for- tunately, of comparative indifference, to determine what a man's motive may have been for this or that particular action. Rather seek to learn what his objects in general are what does he habitually wish, habitually pursue ? and thence deduce his impulses, which are commonly the true efficient 248 LOGIC FOR THE MILLION causes of men's conduct, and without which the motive itself would not have become a motive. S. T. Coleridge. Men are by nature unequal. It is vain therefore to treat them as if they were equal. Froude. There is nothing strictly immortal but immor- tality. Whatever hath no beginning may be con- fident of no end. Sir Thomas Browne. Good laws are for good people. It is useless to offer good laws to bad people. H. R. Haweis. Gambling with canis, or dice, or stocks, is all one thing it is getting money without giving an equivalent for it. H. W. Beecher. He who bears arms at the command of the magistrate does what is lawful for a Christian ; the Swiss in the French service, and the British in the American service, bore arms at the command of a magistrate; therefore they did what was lawful for a Christian. Whateley. Improbable events happen almost every day; but what happens almost every day is a very probable event; therefore very improbable events are very probable events. Whateley. I boasted the other day I was in good health : the next day I fell ill; therefore my boasting was the cause of the illness, and I will never boast again, unless I "touch wood." INDEX. A. PAGE Accidental attributes ... 47 Active cause 104 Analogy, reasoning- by 46, 161 Analysing arguments, rules for 209 Argumentum ad judicium 124 ,, ad ignorantiam 124 ,, hominem 124 ,, verecundiam 124 ,, ,, passiones 124 >, populam 124 Argument by contrast ... 168 Arguments from enumera- tion ... 65 ,, ,, general principles 62 ,, proverbs 63 ,, ,, definitions 66 Association, influence of 25 Attributes and Subject ... 34 Authority 21 Authorities, reasoning from 187 B. 37 Blackstone on " Law " Berkeley's theory of matter 81 Biology 37 Bowley on Statistics ... 173 C. PAGE 75 .. 115 Cause and effect Causes, final Circumstantial evidence i 06, 107 Classic, what is a 136 Classification, instances of 58 Constitutional infirmities 23 Common attributes 38 Contrary attributes ... 47 Conditional causes 101 Contrast, argument by ... 168 Conversational Reasoning 213 Complex Syllogism 227 Conjunctive Syllogism ... 228 Compound Syllogism ... 234 D. Design argument 127 Deduction 153 Dilemma 234 E. 116, Effects of motives Enthymemes Epichirema Equivocal terms Essential attributes Ethics and final causes ... Experiment and observa- tion Evidence, circumstantial 106, 107 118 213 234 134 47 129 82 INDEX Continued. F. PAGE Fallacies 191 Fallacia-accidentis 196 Final Causes ... 115, 130 G. Genus and species 57 Goethe, on logic ... i , 2 Goodwin Sands and Ten- terden Steeple go Grammar and logic ... 3 H. Hill on Induction 157 Historical evidence 205 I. Ignoratio elenchi 191 Illicit process 198 Intelligence and the Intel- ligible 130 Induction 153 K. Knowledge and Reasoning 28 L. Logic not difficult 5 Logic : its alleged inutility 6 Logic and debate 17 Logic and insanity 18 Love of truth 20 M. Manner, influence of ... 24 Mathematical Universality 73 Mental independence 20 to 27 Methods of Observation 137 Moral ideas 53 Moral Universality 73 Moral causes 85 Motives, effects of 116, 118 Morality of the Universe 131 N. PAGE Nature, what is? 138 Newman's " gentleman " 35 Non causa pro causa ... 201 O. Observation and Experi- ment 82 Object of punishment ... 120 Origin of civilisation ... 122 Origin of Life 187 P. Palgrave on Statistics ... 174 Passions, influence of ... 22 Petitio Principii 194 Physical Universality ... 73 Physical causes 75 Prosyllogism 236 "Proving too much" ... 97 Punishment, object of ... 120 R. Reductio ad absurdum ... 96 Reasoning from examples 153 Reasoning from analogy 161 Reasoning from Statistics 171 Reasoning from History 178 Reasoning from Authori- ties 187 " Rights " explained ... 139 Rules for induction 158 Rules for analysing argu- ments 2OQ S. Self-Evident Truths Science and Logic .. Single Syllogism .. Spencer on Logic .. Spencer on Style .. Specific attributes .. Species v. genus Sorites INDEX Continued. PAGE Socratic Disputation ... 142 Statistics, reasoning' from 171 Syllogisms ... 61, 227, 228 Subject and attributes ... 34 T. Teleology 132 Tenterden Steeple and Goodwin Sands ... 90 Truths of the senses ... 9 ,, consciousness 10 ,, ,, intellect 10 ,, testimony ... n ,, ,, reasoning ... 12 "Tyranny" explained ... 137 U. Univocal terms . . . 134 PAGE Undistributed Middle ... 198 Universality, mathematical 72 physical ... 73 moral 73 Use and abuse of terms ... 137 Utility of logical mind ... 15 V. Verbal quibbles 205 Virtue, what is? 142 W. Wall's Theories of History 183 What is a classic? 136 Whole and its parts 50 Words in Reasoning ... 133 Walter Watts 6* Co., Ltd., Printers, Walnut Street, Leicester. N OTABLE NEW BOOKS New Book by the Author of " The Opal Sea." Studies in Pictures. An introduction to the famous Galleries. By John C. Van Dyke. Forty-two illustrations. Crown 8vo, 6s. net. The aim of the book is well shown by the chapter heading's, which cover such subjects as "Old Blasters Out of Place," "Pictures Ruined, Restored tnd Re- paired," "False Attributions, Copies and Forgeries," "Fig-ure Pictures," "Portraiture," "Genre Painting," "Landscape and Marines," etc. Essays on Glass, China, Silver, etc. In connexion with the Willet-Holthuysen Museum Collection, Amsterdam. By Frans Coenen, Conservator of the Museum. With thirty-two illustrations. Crown 4to, 6s. net. The Prisoner at the Bar. Side-rights on the Administration of Criminal Justice. By Arthur Train, Assistant District Attorney in New York County. Demy 8vo, 8s. 6d. Good stories and r*cy anecdotes, with much valu- able information in regard to the practices of criminal law. Where Shakespeare Set His Stage. By Elsie Lathrop. With numerous full-page Illustrations. Demy 8vo, cloth, 8s. 6d. net. T. WERNER LAURIE, Clifford's Inn, London NOTABLE RECENT BOOKS The Building of a Book. A series of p radical articles by experts in the various depart* ments of book making and selling. With an introduction by Theodore L. De Vinne. Edited by Frederick H. Hitchcock. Crown 8vo., 6s. net. My Motor Log-Book. A Handy Record for recording dates, runs, time, distances, weather, roads, cost of repairs, petrol, entertaining, etc. Crown 8vo, cloth, as. 6d. net. Leather, full gilt, 45. 6d. net. The Queen's Progress, and other Eliza- bethan Sketches. By Felix E. Schelling. With six photogravure portraits. Decorative cover. Crown 8vo, los. net. "We will go so far as to say that in his ten short chapters within the compass of this beautifully printed book may be tasted the flavour of the Elizabethan period with more pleasure than in any other work of recent times." Daily Graph tc. Modern Medicine for the Home. By Ernest Walker, M.R.C.S.,L;R.C. P. (Lond.) Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, as. 6d. Notes from my South Sea Log. By Louis Becke, author of "By Reef and Palm." Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, 6s. net. An account of Mr Becke's sporting and fishing adventures whilst supercargo in the South Seas, to- gether with many notes on the habits and supersti- tions of the Islanders. T. WERNER LAURIE, Clifford'* Inn, Londo. NOTABLE RECENT BOOKS Sketches in Normandy. By Louis Becke. Author of "By Reef and Palm." Illustrated, 6s. It is quite a new departure for Mr Louis Becke to take as his theme stories of Normandy life, but his three years' wanderings along the coasts of Nor- mandy and Brittany, and among the fisher-folk, has resulted in his giving us some charming and amusing pictures. Letters to a Daughter. By Hubert Bland (' Hubert " of The Sunday Chronicle}. Crown 8vo, illustrated frontispiece, 35. 6d. net. With the Eyes of a Man. By Hubert Bland (" Hubert " of The Sunday Chronicle}. Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, 35. 6d. Jungle Trails and Jungle People. Travels, Adventures and Observations in the Far East. By Caspar Whitney. With many full-page plates. Medium 8vo, cloth gilt, i as. net. This book is of special interest in view of the Prince of Wales's visit to India. Mr Whitney is an experienced big game hunter, with a facile pen, and his adventures while wild ele- phant hunting and pig sticking are of thrillinginterest. He is a keen observer and gives much entertaining information about the natives and their varied modes of life. Nearly all the illustrations are from photo- graphs taken by the author, and altogether form a unique pictorial record of a novel enterprise. T. WERNER LAURIE, Clifford'! Inn, London NOTABLE RECENT BOOKS Classic Myths in Art. By Julia Addison. Illustrated with forty plate reproductions from famous Painters. Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, 6s. net. An interesting account of Greek myths, illustrated from the works of great artists. The most interesting myths of literature are represented and illustrated from the works of ancient sculptors or more modern paintings. The Artists' Life and other Essays. By John Oliver Hobbes, author of "Some Emotions and a Moral," "The School for Saints," etc. With frontispiece and a cover design by Charles E. Dawson. Crown 8vo, as. 6d. net. Pictures in Umbria. By Katharine S. Mac- quoid, author of "In the Ardennes," "About Yorkshire," etc. With fifty original illustrations by Thomas R. Macquoid, R.I. (Uniform with "The Cathedral Series.") Price 6s. net. Man and His Future. By Lt-Col. William Sedgwick, author of " Man's Position in the Universe. " Demy 8vo, cloth gilt, 75. 6d. net. Biography for Beginners. Being a Collec- tion of Miscellaneous Examples for the Us of Upper Forms. A new nonsense book. Edited by E. Clerihew, B.A., and with forty Diagrams by G. K. Chesterton. Medium 4to, 6s. net. T. WERNER LAURIE, Clifford's Inn, London NOTABLE RECENT BOOKS Confessions of a Young Man. By George Moore, author of " Esther Waters," "The Mummer's Wife," "Evelyn Innes," etc. A new edition, revised, and with a new foreword. Crown 8vo, cloth, 6s. " It is difficult to convey a sense of the book's brilliance in a brief review. His style has the delicious freshness of youth. His paragraphs reveal blossom after blossom, with a promise of a rarer beauty yet to come at each full stop." Manchester Guardian. The Night Side of London. By Robert Machray. With ninety-five pictures by Tom Browne, R.I., R.B.A. 2s. net, cloth; is. net, paper. The Wild Irishman. By T. W. H. Cros- land, author of "The Unspeakable Scot," "Lovely Woman," etc. Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, 5S. CONTENTS: Distressful The Shillelagh Blarney Whiskey The Patriot Orangemen The Low Scotch Priestcraft Morals Pretty Women The London Irish Tom Moore Mr W. B. Yeats Wit and Humour More Wit and Humour Dirt The Tourist Potatoes Pigs Emigration. The Opal Sea. By John C. Van Dyke. With Photogravure Frontispiece. Crown 8vo, 6s. net. Describing Ocean- Plains, Sea-Depths, Currents, Swirls, Whirlpools, Shoals, Coasts, Beaches, Winds, Wave Forms, Water Wear, Sea Gardens, Fishes and Birds. T. WERNER LAURIE, Clifford's Inn, London NOTABLE RECENT BOOKS THIRD PRINTING "Tht Semiramis of the North." VOLTAIRE. The Courtships of Catherine the Great. By Philip W. Sergeant, B.A. (late Scholar of Trinity College, Oxford). Illustrated. Demy 8vo, cloth gilt, IDS. 6d. net. "Extremely interesting: and pleasant reading." Saturday Review. "A valuable addition to the scanty English litera- ture upon the subject." Leeds Mercury, Classical Library. Vol. I The Works of Virgil. Translated into English by C. Davidson. With notes and a memoir. With photogravure frontispiece. Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, 23. 6d. net. Classical Library. Vol. II The Works of Horace. Translated into English by C. Smart. With notes and a memoir. With photogravure frontispiece. Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, as. 6d. net. T. WERNER LAURIE, diffonPt Inn, London Literary London By ELSIE M. LANG Many Illustrations, uniform with Cathedral Series Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, 6s. net object of this book is to add A interest to rambles in London by a careful alphabetical record of the homes and haunts of distinguished literary men and women. In many cases, as is duly noted, the houses themselves are still standing; in others the sites are definitely pointed out, and short extracts are given from biographies, showing with what particular events in the lives of their oc- cupants these residences are identified. London is full of literary memories, and this volume is an ideal guide book to its literary landmarks. T. WERNER LAURIE, Clifford's Inn, London THE LIBRARY OF SPORTS Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, with diagram and Illustrations m 2s. 6d. net Vol. I. The Complete Bridge Player. By Edwyn Anthony ("Cut Cavendish"). Crown 8vo, 244 pages. INTRODUCTIpN A Vocabulary of Bridge-How to Play the Game A First Lesson in Bridge The Declaration in No Trumps The Play in No Trumps A Red Suit Declaration A Black Suit Declaration The Play to a Suit Declaration The Double and Redouble The Original Lead The Finesse and the Discard The Play of the Hand Some Bridge Maxims Penal- ties, and When to Enforce Them Etiquette of the Game English and American Codes The New Laws of Bridge Dummy Bridge Cut Throat Bridge Auction Bridge Progressive Bridge- Duplicate Bridge Specimen Hands Misery Bridge. Vol. II. The Complete Fisherman. By W. M. Gallichan. Illustrated. THE Author of " Fishing in Wales," "Fishing in Derbyshire," etc., is an enthusiastic fisherman of life-long experience, and his book is of a practical character, and contains in- structions for old and young anglers. The intricate art of dry fly-fishing, the methods of fly-fishing for various freshwater fish besides trout and salmon, the practice of spinning for pike and other fish, the latest devices for luring roach, and the newest tackle are all freshly and concisely described in this handbook. Vol. III. The Golfer's Manual. T By W. Meredith Butler. With an Introduction by Dr Macnamara. Illustrated. HIS work is an exposition of the elementary principles ot the game for beginners in a simple and direct way so as to prevent the adoption of wrong methods at the outset. T. WERNER LAURIE, Clifford's Inn, London THE CATHEDRAL SERIES Each Volume very fully illustrated and tastefully printed y bound. The Standard Series Crown 8vo, cloth gilt, 6s. each net THIS Series is probably the most artistic, scholarly, complete, and cheap set of books yet published. Infinite pains have been expended on every branch of reproduction employed. The Daily Ne-ws said of The Cathedrals of Northern France: "In paper, print, binding and reproduction this record is a joy to the reader." " We question if there is anything about any of our Cathedrals of which Mr Bumpus is ignorant. He is a delightful companion in exploring these great churches. His 'Cathedrals' ought to become a standard book." Morning Post. LIST OF SERIES 1. The Cathedrals of Northern France. By Francis Miltoun. With 80 illustrations. 6s. net. 2. The Cathedrals of Southern France. By Francis Miltoun. Cloth gilt, 6s. net. 3, 4, 5. The Cathedrals of England and Wales. By T. Francis Bumpus. 3 vols. 6s. net each. *6. The Cathedrals of Northern Germany and the Rhine. By T. Francis Bumpus. With plates. 6s. net. 7. The Cathedrals of Northern Spain. By Charles Rudy. Many illustrations. 6s. net. * These volumes are also issued in leather binding- at IDS. 6d. each net. T. WERNER LAURIE, Clifford's Inn, London I nnHELEATHER BOOKLETS Exquisitely printed with many illustrations specially drawn for the volumes, gilt top, and full leather binding, stamped in gold. Size 4f x 3. Price 2S. 6d. each net (by post, it. 8d.) For cover de- sign see back of cover. OLD ENGLISH INNS. By G. T. Burrows. 24 Illustrations. THE CASTLES OF ENGLAND. By E. B. D'Auvergne. 30 Illustrations. COME OLD LONDON MEMO- O RIALS. By W. J. Roberts. With 25 photo- graphs by the Author. SOME OLD ENGLISH ABBEYS. By Elsie Lang. Illustrated. THE POCKET CATHEDRAL GUIDE. By W. J. Roberts. 30 Illustrations. IN PREPARATION OLD TOWN HALLS. OXFORD COLLEGES. CAMBRIDGE COLLEGES. OLD ENGLISH HOUSES, etc. READ "THE ADVENTURES OF JOHN JOHNS" PRICE 2/6 NET NOTE TEN LARGE EDITIONS HAVE ALREADY BEEN SOLD OF THIS BOOK A BRILLIANT MODERN NOVEL. PRICE Six SHILLINGS A clever and fearless Story skilfully and originally treated THE WILD WIDOW By GERTIE DE S. WENTWORTH-JAMES MANY heroines in fiction have trodden dangerous paths in the pursuance of their main desire, but the paths trodden by " The Wild Widow " are more than usually overgrown with insidious perils. She is poor she becomes rich she marries a man under perhaps more extraordinary circumstances than any " widow " has ever married before ; while her friend (a girl whose girlhood has been spent in un- consciously waiting for a desperate passionate love) affords example of that mingled ardour and caution which dominates the natures of so many modern women. Many social and moral questions are discussed in the book, the situations are poignant, and a most astounding surprise is revealed in the last chapter. , T. WERNER LAURIE, Clifford's Inn, London MUSIC LOVERS' LIBRARY A CHARMING SET OF VOLUMES IN DECORATIVE BINDING, PRETTILY ILLUSTRATED Crown 8vo, Cloth gilt, 35. 6d. per Vol. net (sold separately) Vol. I. CHATS ON VIOLINS. By Olgra Racster. Fully illustrated. A SERIES of pleasant chats telling the early history ot the violin, and also dealing- with all the better known forms of the violin. All the great makers, from Caspar di Salo, Maggine, Amati, to Stradavarius are described, the whole being interspersed with many anecdotes about makers and players, and useful chapters on violin music and playing. Thr pictures are de- lightfully uncommon. Vols II fc? III. STORIES FROM THE OPERAS. By Gladys Davidson. A CHARMING series ot tales arranged from the Grand Operas. Few people seem to know the actual stories con- tained in the great music dramas of Wagner and others. Most of them are very beautiful and interesting, and these vo- lumes contain the more popular tales, simply written, and in ac- cordance with the libretto. Vol. IV. CHATS WITH MUSIC LOVERS. By Dodkor Annie W. Patterson. HO W to Enjoy Music How to Practise How to Sing How to Compose How to Read Text Books How to Prepare for Examinations How to Get Engagements How to Ap- pear in Public How to Conduct How to Preside at the Organ How to Teach How to Organize Musical Entertainments How to Publish Music. I Vol. V. CHATS ON THE VIOLON- CELLO. By Olga Racster. Fully illustrated A 000096310 8