THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR JOHN T. MacCURDY, M.D. LECTURER ON MEDICAL PSYCHOLOGY, CORNELL UNIVERSITY MEDICAL SCHOOL, NEW YORK NEW \ORK E. P. DUTTON & COMPANY 681 FIFTH AVENUE Copyright, 1918, by E. P. DUTTO^ & COMPANY 411 Rights Reserved Printed in the United States of America PREFACE The conduct of modern warfare demands the co-operation of practically every sci- ence. Engineering, chemistry, bacteriology and agriculture are all needed. Even the sanctity of home is invaded, and domestic economy regulated. But behind all the sci- ences stands the human factor, infinitely the most important of all. On the behaviour of the private in the trenches, the officer in his dug-out, the mechanic at his lathe, and the woman in the kitchen depends the victory. What science can explain how and why they act, or in what way their mental attitudes are altered? Again, before hos- tilities emerge, something must happen; no meteorological or terrestrial event can cause war, it must be a change in the mind of man. Are the forces which make war 5 383085 6 PREFACE and decide its issue to lie uninvestigated? Is mankind going to accept this stagger- ing burden, or attempt solution of its prob- lem merely by wishing for peace? There is a science ambitious enough to hope for an answer to each of these ques- tions. Unfortunately phychology is young amongst the sciences, and must therefore hope rather than promise. Perhaps, were it older, there might be no wars. It is with the confidence that that day of peace will be hastened by the diffusion of a psychological viewpoint that this essay has been written. There can be little claim for originality made, as its aim is to bring before the lay reader material and methods of investiga- tion that are normally not available to him. AVith this some tentative formulations are given, which it is hoped may tend to corre- late the hypotheses that are reviewed. In this essay an analogy between war and mental disease is frankly attempted. No PREFACE 7 medical treatise is complete without a dis- cussion of treatment for the ailment whose pathology and symptoms are described. Some readers may therefore be lured into perusing the following pages with the hope that, in conclusion, some panacea for war's afflictions may be offered. When one con- siders, however, that this spirit of strife has always been an intimate part of the soul of man, it will be evident that no simple formula can ever dispel it from his life. Further than that, it is essential to realise that any summary effort to purge the world of war would be pernicious. It is not an isolated phenomenon, but the product of the best and the worst in human kind. It would be a sad day for the race if man lost his hardihood and ideas of loyalty merely for the sake of peace. His psyche must be transformed, not syncopated. This change can only come from within, and only when he has learned his essential nature. The 8 PREFACE ambition of the psychologist — a fundamen- tally practical man — is, therefore, to set men thinking before they act. Whether what is found in this pamphlet be right or wrong, it will have served its purpose if it stimulates a more thoroughgoing study of war on the part of the average citizen, a more rigorous analysis of himself and his martial feelings than he has previously un- dertaken. The bulk of this essay was written in America in the summer of 1916. The chap- ter on America is essentially a postscript, added in London a few weeks after Con- gress had declared a state of war to exist. J. T. M. London, May, 1917. CONTENTS CHAP. PAGE I Introduction : The Problem and ITS Approach . . . .11 II Primitive Instincts . . .24 III Gregariousness . . . .52 IV Correlation of Primitive In- stincts with Gregariousness . 78 CHAPTER I introduction: the problem and its approach There is probably no practice to which \ man in all his history has clung more tena- ' ciously and irrationally than he has to the pursuit of war. I say irrationally because whatever may have been the incidental ben- efits to individual tribes or nations, man- kind as a whole has surely suffered by war. This statement is really not debatable, since its proof rests on arguments that are tru- isms. Yet war, with its related issues, re- mains the greatest problem man has to solve. In earlier days war was more or less chronic, and was accepted as part of the lot of man; now, with advance of knowl- edge and a growing human self-conscious- 11 12 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR ness, its irrationality is better recognised. Perhaps as a result of this there are longer intervals of peace, but warfare when it does come is so much the more bitter. What shall we do about it? Diplomacy fails to answer; education refuses to answer, pre- ferring to inculcate the spirit of war; any religion which tries to answer dies of inanition. Possibly we can turn to those who make human behaviour the object of their study, those whose work it is to begin where common sense ends, those whose task is to teach man what his instincts and ten- dencies are. With this knowledge it may be that he will see the way his footsteps tend ^and, seeing, choose or shun that course. fBy investigating the world around him, man has found that he can largely control his environment. War shows that he can- jiot control himself. The modern advance of the physical sciences has created the illu- sion that human safety, human salvation. INTRODUCTION 13 depends on his clinging to the materialisti- cally obvious. And material science has made of modern war almost a biological suicide. Is it not time to seek aid of psy- chology, the least material and most prac- tical of the sciences, and study man him- self? As chemistry grew out of alchemy, so psychology has developed from metaphys- ics. Alchemy consisted largely in the ascription of abstract qualities to material substances, and the combining of these sub- stances in order to produce other abstrac- tions. Chemistry was born when men ex- amined substances to find out what quali- ties they had — the experimental method. So long as psychology consisted of pasting la- bels on to subjective mental phenomena it worked in an arid and barren field. How- ever, at the beginning of the present cen- tury, roughly speaking, it was realised that there was an objective method possible; 14 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR namely, the observation of the mind in dis- ease. It was then discovered that beneath the apparent unity and consistency of con- sciousness there lay a complicated structure of elements, unrecognised by the subject. One combination of these elements in due proportion makes what we call a normal man, another a neurotic, a third a criminal, a lunatic, and so on. Then there came into being what is practically a new science. Dynamic Psychology. . Perhaps the most important achievement of this new study is the demonstration that transition from mental normality to abnormality is not oc- casioned by the addition of something from without, but by a change in combination or relative strengths of the forces that are already operative in "normal'' mental life. In war, without the addition of any extra- mental factor, the behaviour of society and its members is suddenly altered.^ The fact that this alteration is sometimes a most INTRODUCTION 15 profound one makes the analogy with the psychosis all the more exact. It becomes eAident why psychiatry (using the term in its widest and most correct sense) is the most promising preparation for the psycho- logical study of war. The psychiatrist of the future will be an exi)ert in the affairs of our lives, which are now most notori- ously left to chance. The program of the psychologist is, there- fore, to discover, if possible, what tenden- cies of the normal mind upset the balance which exists apparently in times of peace, and thereby produce war. That he should an- alyse the problem completely and estimate to a nicety the strength of every instinct involved is to ask too much of a new science. But if his findings give hints to the edu- cator or law-maker his work will not be in vain. The objection that any present discussion must necessarily be focussed on the Euro- 16 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR pean struggle now in progress and inevita- bly be coloured by prejudice is an argument demanding consideration. One must be an emotional ament or dement not to be swayed in his sympathy and thoughts to one side or the other. And history, we frequently hear, will tell us the true story. That she will be free from superficial prejudices is probable; but are basic prejudices likely to die? After a lapse of nearly a thousand years we hear one historian call William Wallace a patriot and another a barbarous outlaw. On the other hand, there is an urgent necessity that the problem be faced now. The will to ac- tion, to reform, to a change of national atti- tude is now present when the carnage of Europe is spread before our eyes; in ten years' time we shall have placidly grouped the War of 1914 with the Napoleonic Wars or the war between the North and the South in the United States — something that can- not happen again because the ^vorld is dif- INTRODUCTION 17 ferent and those problems have disappeared. Yet history teaches us that wars do not make war (else they would be continuous), but rather that peace makes war. This unpalatable truth can, perhaps, be put in a less paradoxical form by saying that the forces which lead to war are engendered and nourished in times of peace, to burst out when some trivial accident provides an oc- casion. To a psychiatrist accustomed to the defective make-up of his patient, the gradual accumulation of difficulties and the final psychotic explosion, the precipitating factor seems of relative insignificance and the idea of preventing the catastrophe by avoidance of the last "cause'' or by mandate is pre- posterous. One who studies war psycho- logically will probably come to a similar conclusion. An effort to avoid interna- tional quarrels and agreements to arbitrate differences would be at best palliative. What we call "peace" is, apparently, a \ 18 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR \ period during wliicli' forces both psycliic ^ and material are dammed up until their I accumulated pressure overpowers the judg- ment of mankind. Only a rigorous anal- ysis of national or racial psychology could lay bare the factors which make of peace a fool's paradise. If these were found we might have a rational hope of modifying these factors until both war and peace were terms of merely historic interest. Among the difficulties attending this study (and, properly speaking, part of the problem) are the preconceptions about war. War is a disease ; yet we hear jingoes refer to it as a normal human activity or the rem- edy for any social malaise. On the other hand, the professional pacifists talk belliger- ently about its horrors as if they could wake the public to a realisation of evils previously unrecognised, and with it all, never adduce a single essential fact unknown to society for generations. Were it not for the intense INTRODUCTION 19 gravity of the problem, one would be tempt- ed to laugh at the seriousness with which, for instance, men have solemnly proved by elaborate statistics that war involves eco- nomic losses. How would a physician be welcomed who harangued his patient on the discomfort and danger of recurrent chills in malaria? The suspicion seems justified that in these matters we share the belief of the savage in the potency of curses. In fact, we might even think that the savage is slightly more rational than we. He has his theory of disease : an evil spirit possesses the patient; the demon must be exorcised. We, on the contrary, seem to deny that there is a disease. We are asked to realize that the symptoms are unpleasant and avoid them as a child must learn to avoid fire. An attempt to discover the cause of this so- cial malady would doubtless be regarded as mawkish sentimentality by the militarists, and as immoral by the pacifists. It is not 20 THE PSYCHOLOGY OP WAR impossible that these passionate irrational- ities have their influence in the production of the apparently inevitable cycles of war and peace, and it is psychologically inter- esting that there is much in common be- tween the two types. Each party tries to solve a delicate situation by a tour de force. Th5 inilitarist sneers at diplomacy of any kind and seeks to adjust every difference by the sword, while the pacifist would change human nature by fiat. The futility of gain- ing world-wide harmony by such means must be painfully obvious. Although the student of mental disease may offer a new approach, too much should not be expected of him, for, with the intro- duction of abnormal mass action, what is practically a new field for psychiatrists is opened up. This is because we have always assumed as a standard of normality for the individual an essential agreement with the average conduct of the community. For INTKODUCTION 21 this reason the common belief of fifty or a hundred years ago may be a delusion if en- tertained to-day, when superstitions are dropping out of everyday life and out of religions. Therefore we cannot say that the exhibitions of martial lust, which any per- son may show, stamp him as insane — his neighbours applaud him. Similarly we can- not be psychiatrically exact if we speak of a nation becoming mad if it embarks on a career of self-destruction with the lure of some gain trifling in comparison with the inevitable sacrifice. This w^ould be an ac- curate term if all other peoples instinctively and automatically regarded the nation as suffering from mental disease and took ac- tion in accordance with that view. Obvi- ously we are dealing with an analogy — not an identity. Where the cases fail of identity is in the lack of any universal standard for social behaviour. With a problem of the magnitude of war before us, however, we 22 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR must remember that if analogies were iden- tities the problem would long ago have ceased to exist as such, and that our one ambition is, therefore, to compare war with other normal and abnormal phenomena, re- membering always the danger of drawing too rigid inferences and accepting hasty conclusions. This is a practical age and, particularly in these times of stress, the pragmatic value of any proposition is more apt to be ques- tioned than is its theoretic worth. It is only natural, therefore, that the reader should ask, "What guarantee does the psychiatrist offer that his study of war will prove of more than academic value?" We are attempting to establish an analogy between the phenomena of war and the symptoms of mental disease. Investigation of the latter field leads inevitably to the conclusion that prevention of insanity de- pends on education in its truest sense of INTRODUCTION 23 mind training, and it is being slowly real- ised that mental hygiene is as important for human welfare as is the care of the body. Psychiatrists are not hopeless of the day coming when, thanks to a sounder knowl- edge of himself, man may be relatively free from mental infirmities. It is only by edu- cation of this type that the race as a whole may hope to rid itself of the pest of w^ar. Expectations of individual and social health are based upon programs equally ambitious and equally practical. The two problems are probably inseparable. Success, in either case, depends no less upon willingness to learn, and zeal in self-reform, than on the investigation which must precede the teach- ing. Preventive psychiatry is beginning to show its fruits; it is therefore not illogical to entertain a hope that similar efforts may ultimately prevent war. CHAPTER II PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS / It may be convenient to consider the phe- I nomena in question as falling into two Lgroups, just as historians speak of remote and immediate causes. In times of peace we have rivalry between nations expressing itself in ways that must appear to any ob- jective view irrational. Individuals of a foreign country are, however, not consid- ered natural enemies — it is only the groups as a whole who are natural rivals. Injury to a foreigner is almost, if not quite, as re- pugnant as injury to a native citizen. This rivalry becomes more intense until with a trifling precipitating factor a totally new set of forces comes into play. What can be termed nothing less than blood-lust springs apparently out of nowhere, and upsets many 24 PEIMITIVE INSTINCTS 25 normal standards of conduct. The for- eigner becomes the scapegoat for his race: he must be killed or injured in any possible way. If there is to be a real war it is obvi- ous that this second phase has to develop, for, unless the animosity of the race be- comes individual, it would be impossible for a civilised man to deal a lethal blow, re- strained as he is by the inhibitions of gen- erations. Moreover, these inhibitions must be lifted to the point where killing gives sat- isfaction, else there will be a woeful lack of the enthusiasm necessary to outweigh personal sacrifice and sustain the war. Ob- jectively viewed, the motto of nations in time of peace seems to be, "Live, but do not let live," while in times of war the individ- ual says, "Kill, even if killed." These two factors — tribal rivalry, or more properly speaking, tribal jealousy — and the lust of violence are each held by different schools of dynamic psychology to be the chief cause 26 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR c of war. It may be well to discuss them sep- arately, and then attempt to weigh their relative importance. i Beginning with the blood-lust or cruelty iimpulse, it must be obvious that this phe- pomenon is not confined to warfare. It is an everyday observation that the behaviour of an American college student is more bru- tal in a football game than in his individual activities; he is not ashamed of it, in fact he positively enjoys it. More notorious is the violence of mobs. The statistics of lynching show with what lamentable fre- quency the innocent suffer, and how the tor- ture inflicted is often totally dispropor- tionate to the gravity of the offence. These men who assume the role of judge and exe- cutioner are, many of them, of the highest character, respected and loved for their kindliness and honour. Plainly in mass ac- y tion an opportunity is given for the devel- \ppment of justice into revenge, and revenge PKIMITIVE INSTINCTS 27 into cruelty, which becomes an end in itself. J The lyncher, again, is not ashamed of his deed, but takes a grim, if not blithe satis- faction in it.* The greatest inspired psy- chologist of all time has given a true picture of the lust which a mob can call to life in its members — a lust which has no connection with the original common impulse of the crowd. ''Third Citizen: Your name, sir, truly. Cinna: Truly, my name is Cinna. First at. : Tear him to pieces ; he's a con- spirator ! Cm.: 1 am Cinna the poet — I am Cinna the poet. Fourth at.: Tear him for his bad verses — tear him for his bad verses ! Cin.: I am not Cinna the conspirator. *This satisfaction is not confined to those taking- part in the outrage. The notorious Frank case is an instance in point. After his brutal execution men and women in Georgia eagerly bought photographs of the final scene. 28 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR Fourth at.: It is no matter, his name's Cinna ; pluck but his name out of his heart, and turn him going. Third Cit.: Tear him, tear him! Come, brands, ho! firebrands: to Brutus', to Cas- sius'; burn all: some to Decius' house, and some to Casca's, some to Tigurius': away, go!" If any one fancies that such bloodthirsty furor is manufactured by the mob and not merely called out of each member by a special stimulus, let him remember that cru- elty and bloodshed have some attraction for I every one of us. The degrees of dilution or manner of disguise may vary; it may be open enjoyment of torture, the morbid fa^ cination of melodrama or accidents (perA haps strongly coloured by horror), or mere- ly a love of the swashbuckling novel. But (in all of us there exists deep down a savage streak which evidences itself when the PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS 29 proper stimulus is applied. We are never/ coldly, judiciously neutral in reaction. / Much of contemporary interest in the psy- chology of the abnormal, and a large share of the impetus recently given to its study, is due to the growth of a school which uses a method termed "psycho-analysis/^ The nature of this technique need not be dis- cussed here, but it should be mentioned that those who use it claim to trace all mental abnormalities to unconscious wishes or, more accurately, unconscious tendencies which gain indirect and symbolic express- sion in neurotic or psychotic symptoms. These tendencies are presumed to be un\ known to the consciousness of the individ- \ ual because they are repugnant to his per- / sonality. It is this repugnance which causes" them to be repressed to the limbo of the un- conscious, where they can live on aw^ay from contact with that part of the mind which is law-abiding, altruistic and social in its aims. 30 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR Not unnautrally these unconscious tenden- cies are of a primitive, lawless and individ- ualistic type, and include such impulses of cruelty and violence as are seen in war. /The importance of these tendencies has 'been emphasised by two psycho-analysts since the beginning of the present conflict. One is an Austrian and one an Englishman, but both scrupulously avoid any partizan discussion of the war now in progress. Un- der the headings of "The Disillusionment of War," Professor Freud* treats this topic without any reference to the causation of warfare, focusing his attention rather on certain of its phenomena. His tone is pes- simistic, somewhat cynical, and not out of keeping with the general trend of the Vien- na school of psycho-analysis. He notes first a destruction of the com- mon feeling of humanity; the clearest in- *S. Freud : "Zeitgemasses iiber Krieg' und Tod." — Imago, Bd. IV, H.I. PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS 31 tellects seem distorted ; and we find Science, that should own no country, being prosti- tuted as an argument in favour of one an- tagonist and to the disparagement of an- other. We are not surprised when conflicts arise between nations or tribes of widely varying aims, such as those of savages and the civilised peoples; but had come to be- lieve that between nations with common cul- ture and common morality it was hardly to be expected. He thinks that States have demanded a high standard of honour on the part of their citizens, and that now the States themselves seem to have abolished Buch standards. Facility of travel has made many citizens of the world; our literary, artistic and scientific heroes are interna- tional. We have also grown to believe in the restriction of war to the destruction of , armies and the immunity of non-combatants. Now all these are gone as if they had been illusions, and their place is taken by bit- 32 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR terest hate of one people for another. States, he thinks, have monopolised all the wickedness that they suppress in their citi- zens. Every license which the government restricts in the individual is made use of in war by the State, which, in the meantime, demands every virtue from the subject. The States cannot be defended on the ground that virtue does not pay, for it does not pay the individual very often, and he receives no reward from society to compensate him for the sacrifice his virtue involves. The loss of international respect is naturally re- flected in individual conduct, for our inhibi- tions are largely occasioned by fear of so- ciety rather than "conscience." When this ban is removed individuals perform un- thinkable acts. The disillusionments, then, fall into two groups: first, the slight de- cency we see exhibited by nations in their reciprocal relations in contrast to the vig- our of the demands they make on their citi- •' PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS 33 zens; and, second, the general brutality of the soldier, who is such a gentleman in times of peace. He discusses the second first, and to ac- count for it recapitulates the development of the individual. Man begins with primi- tive, egoistic tendencies, which are neither good nor bad except in so far as their exhi- bitions affect society. In the process of development these assume socialised forms often appearing in the opposite form from the original, as when the unusually cruel child becomes an unduly sympathetic man. Such metamorphoses are the work of two factors. The first is the desire to be loved, which puts a premium on self-sacrifice and makes an altruistic act pleasurable. Begin- ning as love for others in the family, this spreads out to society in general and forms a genuine basis for virtuous character. The second is the artificial warping of native tendencies by education, laws, and conven- U THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR tions, which is natural and genuine only in so far as there is an hereditary predisposi- tion to such adaptation. Conduct arti- ficially determined may be superficially identical with the more genuine type but is never as stable. The person who has been affected only by education and en- vironment is naturally good only when it pays to be, and the number of such people is probably much larger than is generally supposed. This forced virtue really amounts to a kind of hypocrisy, although it is not fully conscious. Freud suggests that a cer- tain amount of hypocrisy may be necessary for the maintenance of our cultured level, which is probably higher than the average individual capacity. The shattered illusion, he therefore concludes, is the belief that the bulk of mankind ever had any true civilisa- tion. As soon as governments relax their reciprocal responsibilities, the governed get an outlet for their original impulses on the PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS 85 bodies of the foe, while the inhibitions pro-^ ceed relatively uninterrupted within the State. As to the hate existing between nations, he can only say that it seems that common world interests are not strong enough to hold national passions in check. There is apparently no "fear of society'' in this case. He admits frankly that he can offer no explanation of the phenomenon, merely remarking that it seems as if the aggrega- tion of men simply multiplied their primi- tive impulses. It is evident from the above that Freud views the atrocities of the war as more natural than the civilised behaviour of man. Although accounting for war phenom- ena alone, it would perhaps not be doing him an injustice to suggest that he would view violence as the native instinctive meth- od of settling any quarrel, a tendency that is lost only between individuals of the same 36 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR state where society has put a ban on such methods. This is equivalent to saying that the mystery to be solved is the behaviour of peace rather than the incidents of war. In passing it may be remarked that in this we have an example of a frequent type of reasoning encountered in many psycho-ana- lytic writings. A symptom is traced to some unconscious instinct, which, because it is deeply rooted and long lived, is stated to be part of the "real'' individual. A some- what similar argument would say that be- cause gill breathing is the most primitive type of respiration, because every foetus has gills, traces of which persist to adult life, and because these traces may have patho- logical development, therefore gill breath- ing is the normal respiration for man. What the individual is in the bulk of his life should constitute his true nature. In the present instance we should not forget that, no matter what man may have been pre- PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS 37 historically, and no matter what character the infant may have, the contemporary adult is by constitution a unit of society, and any purely individualistic acts he may perform must be regarded as abnormal. It is important to note, however, that Freud correlates the atrocities of war with the lifting of national ambitions. Using somewhat the same material, an- other psycho-analyst, Ernest Jones,* of London, gives a wider scope to his specu- lation. "The aim of this essay is to raise the question whether the science of Psy- chology can ever show us how to abolish war." He makes no claim that psychology can do so, but insists that its methods are essential to the study of the problem because it deals with the mental factors that de- termine all decisions. His chief argument ^ is the claim that unconscious wishes distort ^ *"Vrar and Individual Psychology," The Sociolog- ical Review, July, 1915. 38 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR rational judgment. This phenomenon is part, perhaps, of the essence of war, as an example of which he cites the difficulty of ascertaining the facts in such an apparently simple inquiry as the immediate cause of the present war. The unconscious, he claims, can only be studied by individual psychol- ogy. This term he uses to differentiate the study of the mental phenomena of a group from that of separate persons. After a dis- cussion of the different fields he dismisses social psychology as a superfluous science, accepting Trotter's* view that the reactions of the mass are the sum of the reactions of the units in the mass, and that man invari- ably reacts as a herd animal whether in a crowd or alone. All this may undoubtedly be true and still leave room for a psychology that is broader than the "Individual Psy- chology" developed in Jones' paper, for this is concerned only with impulses that arise *"IIerd Instinct," The Sociological Review, 1908. PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS 39 within the individual, whereas there must surely be other forces, or at least stimuli, that are external to him in their origin. The importance of this objection will be discussed later. He begins his argument in favour of there being deep-lying mental causes for war by suggesting that man may not be able to live for more than a certain period without war, and that he possibly prefers that form of settling disputes to peaceful means. This would be analogous to the phenomenon recognized by many novelists that an un- conscious wish of the individual may be objectively obvious but subjectively un- recognized. His suspicion of man's bias for fighting is based on the history of great wars recurring after a lapse of several gen- erations, which are marked by a revulsion towards war. This last statement should not pass without comment. Such a psychic factor as this revulsion could never pass 40 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR from one generation to tlie next if it were a force springing up within the individual and not something handed on from man to man. Here is an admission of the exist- ence of what is essentially a social factor, and if such a powerful inhibitive force can have its origin previous to a complete gen- eration, may there not similarly be social tendencies working to produce war, as well as those of the unconscious individual type of which Jones speaks? He proceeds to argue that although men act abnormally in certain "social situa- tions," where normal standards seem to be relaxed (e.g. in mob activities), there is a certain unity of aim in both his normal and abnormal behaviour. In normal develop- .^rfient a primitive tendency, when denied direct expression by the repressive side of one's nature, gains outlet in a social or altruistic form which is somehow symbolic Vof the latent, more individualistic craving. PKIMITIVE INSTINCTS 41 For example, one might take the case of an unmarried woman in whom the maternal instinct can gain no direct outlet without involving anti-social behaviour, who gets a substitutive outlet through nursing, char- itable work, etc. In such a case the object of her attention receives her "maternal" care, and may stand in the unconscious level of her mind for a child. Such an outlet is termed a sublimation. The analysis of the development of so many activities has shown a similar mechanism that psycho- analysts believe all pursuits are of this type which are not obviously actuated by primi- tive instincts. These sublimations giving only indirect expression to the deeper forces are never absolutely stable, and tend to break down with a return to the more primi- tive form at all times. When such a lapse occurs the conduct of the individual is to- tally different from that of his everyday life, but as the sublimation is being replaced by 42 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR directer expression of its more primitive driving impulse there is still the unity be- tween the two of which Jones speaks. It is the same unconscious wish that is grat- ified in each case. The more normal activ- ity is an indirect, distorted, symbolic outlet, its successor is crude and direct. This ac- counts for the appalling changes of charac- ter often seen in senility or other states con- ducive to mental enfeeblement. He does not pretend to give any final explanation of the highly frequent phenom- enon (of which many examples will occur to the reader) of mass action favouring cruder expressions of primitive cravings. He does make a clever suggestion, how- ever. Sublimations, he says, are largely in- dividual developments. That is, each per- son works out his particular way of social- izing his individualistic tendencies, while the unconscious wishes, being primitive, are common to all the unite in a given group. PEIMITIVE INSTINCTS 43 The mass action proceeding, therefore, as a sum of all the individual tendencies present, is made up of over-determined ^'uncon- scious" forces, while the sublimations, being individual, tend to neutralise one another, because they are individual and may be widely different from the other. Resultant action springs from the wishes that are common to all. This argument is plausible; and it seems reasonable to suppose that this may well operate as a contributing fac- tor in mob suggestion; but, as we shall see presently, there are probably other and more important explanations of these phe- nomena. Jones says, then, as does F reud, that we should not consider the atrocities of war as due to' war iSelf, but rather that it is one of a number of conditions which favour the unleashing of tendencies always latent in civilised men. But Jone« goes further still, suggesting 44 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR that the impulse to release these tendencies may be one of the important causes of war itself. ^^The essence of war surely consists in an abrogation of standards of conduct approved of by the ethical sense of commu- nities. By this is meant that in war an attempt is made to achieve a given purpose by means which are otherwise regarded as reprehensible." An individual in such a situation is ashamed and attempts to excuse himself with all sorts of tenuous proofs of the justifiability of his actions. This is, he thinks, true of the nations now at war. Although each insists that the war was inev- itable, each is unwilling to assume respon- sibility for its actual inception. It is generally held that in war the ends justify the means, while Jones boldly suggests that perhaps it is really the means which are primary and that the ends are found to justify them. . He quotes Nietzsche quite aptly for his argument : "Ye say that it is the PKIMITIVE INSTINCTS 45 good cause which halloweth every war? I say unto you : It is the good war which hal- loweth every cause." It is interesting that each nation imputes such motives to its foes. It is easier for an enemy to see a disagree- able characteristic than it is for the pos- sessor of it. The problem may then be stated, he pro- 2eeds, as the determination of the relative mportance of the conscious and unconscious motives in the initiation of war. As con- scious motives may be all grouped under the term patriotism, he analyses this complex of feelings. The relation of the individual to his country is an outgrowth of the relation- ships existing in childhood in the home. These centre around three effective com- plexes : the relationships of the child to his mother, his father and himself. Generally the country wins in adult life the devotion originally given the mother, more rarely the state stands in a paternal position (such as 46 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR in patriarchal governments). The oppor- tunities for unconscious reinforcement of patriotic impulses with this history is ob- vious to any one familiar with psycho- analysis and is well shown in the "self relationship, where the individual identifies the country with himself, is personally inflated or depleted with its success or failure. The development of those uncon- scious forces has, probably, a great deal to do with one's attitude towards war, whether one is a pacifist or a firebrand, just as other characteristics have their unconscious deri- vation and history. But to urge that all patriotic impulses may be thus disposed of is too sweeping a generality. This is well shown by Jones' suggestion that national make-up may be the outcome of the type of family life existing in the nation. If there is a similarity in homes, it is surely self- evident that this is due to conformity to a national standard of domestic life or else the PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS 47 product of a stupendous coincidence of identical, independent development. In his endeavour to make unconscious motives responsible for everything he has succeeded in putting the cart before the horse. It is only fair to add, however, that a uniformity of home life may well act, secondarily, in reinforcing a homogenity of national con- duct and thought. But primary it can never be. Many of the conscious motives are, then, according to Jones, essentially unconscious if their history be traced far enough back. The undoubtedly unconscious motives which find an outlet in war centre around the pas- sions for cruelty, destruction, lust and loot. He claims that no army has ever been with- out one or more of these, which is probably true. He cites the orgies of destruction indulged in by Cromwell's Puritan army. That the innate desire for outlet of these passions is mainly responsible for war he 48 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR merely suggests; that, at least, they con- stantly reinforce the more conscious pa- jtriotic motiyes he confidently asserts. As to the future, he is wise enough not to offer any panacea. The few generalities offered are worthy of attention. In the first place he deprecates any attempts to abolish war by forcible repression of primitive in- stincts. Psycho-analysis tends to show that repression leads only to a temporary damming up of such forces, with later ex- plosions, unless the opportunities for sub- limated outlets be favourable. He suggests that it may be possible that the sublimating capacity of man is now at its greatest height, which, if true, would certainly mean that civilisation is maintained only by virtue of the safety valve of war, although, strange to say, he does not put forward this hypothesis as such. What he recommends is a more intelligent treatment of primitive instincts, the substitution of open-eyed study and con- PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS 49 trol of social problems rather than blind legal negations which tend to increase social unrest. As an example of what such a policy can do in preventing unrest he cites the suc- cess of the modern British colonial policy. As a corollary of this he mentions the grant- ing of outlet to these instincts in a less harm- ful form than war. Naturally he gives credit here to William James, who first made this suggestion in his essay on "The Moral Equiv- alents of War." In conclusion, with a few striking sen- tences he gives a picture of the benefits of war as a national and individual stimulus and an agency bringing man closer to the essential realities of life. He does not sug- gest that these benefits have any causal relation to war. On the whole, therefore, we can sum np Jones' contribution as an effort to establish the violent, primitive instincts of man, usually unconscious, as an important, if not the primary, cause of war. 50 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR It is striking that in this able paper no mention is made of the phenomena of inter- national hostility, the jealousy which is exhibited in times of peace. Yet it is a fact ^"hich historians constantly impress upon (their readers that prior to a warthe^ is \always a tension gradually increasing be- tween rival nations, which finally culminates fen the outbreak of hostilities. If the forces Jones speaks of were the only ones at work, the increasing tension would always be an internal one, an unrest from the pent-up lawless energies of the citizens which would finally seek an outlet in indiscriminate violence, not necessarily focused on one par- jticular foe. In other words, who the enemy should be would be a matter of accident. Such unconscious motives as Freud and Jones discuss could easily account for the choice of war in time of crisis, for clinical experience teaches us that in any occasion of mental stress the primitive tendency is PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS 51 most apt to be followed. We might, there- fore, leave this type of psychological ap- proach with the suggestion that unconscious impulses may more than any other influ- ences be responsible for the actual initiation of war and the abnormal behaviour of the antagonists. There remain to be discussed the psychological factors which engender the international animosities and antagonisms in times of peace. CHAPTER III GREGAEIOUSNESS ( International rivalry is, apparently, never friendly ; in fact, it seems to be invari- ably characterised by jealousy, often by bit- \ terness. Community of interest is only a phrase, and never sought in practice. If nation A develops trade in some com- mercially isolated district, the citizens of nation B do not see in this a gain for their own merchants in the opening up of a new outlet for business, but view the growth with alarm and bend their energies towards blocking the foreigner's efforts as much or more than they extend their own. Similarly a new warship or new military program is regarded with an almost paranoic suspicion by all possible military rivals. All this is 53 GREGARIOUSNESS 53 obviously irrational, and is certainly a prob- lem to be studied by psychopathologists. If the average citizen is asked why this situa- tion exists, he gives one of two answers: either, "It is silly, and we shouldn't do it any more;" or, "History teaches us that the na- tion which is not suspicious is destroyed." The first reply is a form of the pacifist's fiat that human nature be changed. The second makes a pretence of rationality. But does man listen to History? Have the yoking of force and suspicion ever led to anything but disaster, even after a short triumph? Surely here, as elsewhere, man learns what he washes to learn; some powerful instinct urges him the way he goes. War is never far from consciousness when such suspicious rivalry is in the air. What is the attitude of any nation towards war in time of peace? War, of course, is damnable, all readily agree. But this is war as an abstraction. What do the citizens of any 54 THE PSYCHOLOGY OP WAR given country think of their own ivars? All are excusable, some justifiable and some glorious. Every thinking man will admit afc least these differences, and here there /"emerges a not unimportant fact. Tjie wars) I that fire the national imagination are those | \ in which the nation's existence was threat-^^ Njened. The same is true of national heroes : no heterogeneous English gathering ever waxed enthusiastic over the name of Dar- win, nor did a German crowd applaud Goethe to the skies.* It is the military hero *It is true that a few years ago a large plebiscite, instituted by a Parisian newspaj)er, placed Pasteur first in answer to the question, "Who was the great* est Frenchman?" But the form of this question naturally calls for an objective, intellectual judgment. The voter probably put himself in the place of a for- eigner, trying to decide what Frenchman had done most for the world. Had the question been, "As a> Frenchman, whom do you admire m:Ost?" the vote •would probably have placed Napoleon first, a sim- ilar plebiscite had some years before. Emotional feelings are more dynamic than intellectual judg- m^ents, as every observer knows. It is safe to guess that many more Frenchmen to-day visit the tomb of Napoleon than the grave of Pasteur. GREGARIOUSXESS 55 who is the national hero, and here again a discrimination can be made. It is not the genius who fought in some small campaign that stirs the blood, but the man of force who saved the country or founded the empire. The point of these observations is this : The^ attitude of a people towards its wars is not a glorification of war, but rather an en- thusiasm for itself as a nation. War marks the highest level of national consciousness that is ever reached. In earlier days, when' primitive man had not known the advan- tages of herd life for very long, friction with other tribes over hunting grounds or other coveted possessions must have made strangers appear like those of another species in the struggle for existence. Ad- vance of knowledge has taught that all the members of the species Homo sapiens are men, but it is doubtful whether that knowl- edge is a vital part of our automatic mental life. It is one thing for us to recognise in 56 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR an animal identity of anatomical structure, and another to feel that he is like ourselves. Without this instinctive bond, every stranger, every member of every other group, must to a greater or less extent arouse in us the biological reaction appropriate towards a different species. We have sympathy for a dog, an animal useful to us, but we kill wolves, snakes and insects without any revulsion of feeling for the act. Interna- tional relationships are probably largely traceable to this feeling of specific differ- ences and to the deep-lying instinct for preservation of the species, distorted in this case to the preservation of what is at most only a variety. This phenomenon of group allegiance is, of course, a commonplace to sociologists. One might hazard the generality that with- out it there would be no large political or social problems. It is this instinct which cements the labour unions, maintains re- I GREGARIOUSNESS 57 ligious factions. Here we have what is, per- haps, the greatest paradox of human nature. The forgetting of self in devotion to others, altruism or loyalty, is the essence of virtue. At the same time, precisely the same type of loyalty that makes of a man a benefactor to all mankind can become the direst menace to mankind when focused on a small group. The bigot can with all sincerity and con- sciousness of high motive enslave thought and retard science for centuries. Similarly the labour leader, in his zeal to better the condition of his fellow unionists, will shake the foundations of industry. The reader will call to mind countless examples having this in common, that the small group calls forth a loyalty which is inimical to larger groups. In the case of war we have national loyalty destroying the civilisation of all mankind. There is but one psychologist who has seen the potentiality of man's gregariousness. 58 -THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR This is Wilfrid Trotter.* The substance of his claims is that one can understand many anomalies of man's conduct by regarding him as a herd animal: that is, not only an animal who lives gregariously, but one whose instinct it is to react with the herd. He is deaf to the voice of one without the herd, but infinitely suggestible to influences coming from within it. In this way herd traditions and herd thoughts are superior in their in- fluence to individual reason, and the strug- gle between these two he assigns as the cause for most human ills that are not frankly physical in origin. f He says that there are three great types of development in herd life: that of the animals, who unite for aggression as do wolves ; that of the species like sheep, whose cohesion gives protection; and finally, the highest degree of gregariousness, which he V ^Instincts of the Herd in Peace and in War. Fisher Unwin & Co., London. V'\^ GREGARIOUSNESS 59 terms the socialised type, exemplified in the society of ants, or better still by bees. Each kind of specialisation is represented in man, and has its peculiar mental make up exhib- ited both in the reactions of the mass and the individual. Each tends in human devel- opment to exclude the others and produce a type that is almost a specific variation bio- logically. This leads to lack of sympathy and, if the interests of two "herds" come into collision, a deep hostility. In his original papers,* he showed how gregariousness leads inevitably to unques- tioning acceptance of the herd dogma, and that this works strongly against that sensi- tiveness to experience — open mindedness — w^hich is necessary for progress. In bio- logical terms, the aggregation of units in the herd, which ought to facilitate variation, actually inhibits variation. He concluded, therefore, that the human race was doomed *The Sociological Review, 1908 and 190y. 60 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR to extinction unless some new factor should come into play. Hints as to the nature of this force were extremely vague. He now states that this must be an understanding of man's psychology in the biological sense, and a conscious guidance along the path of evolution on which he has entered only to halt long before the goal is reached. Both of these definite additions to his theory ap- pear prominently in his discussion of war. In this book there are no statements as to the causation of warfare in general, but only arguments about the present conflict. The author frankly admits that prejudice is un- avoidable, and claims no immunity from that vice in his discussion. He places entire responsibility for the war on Germany, giv- ing no suggestion as to how England could have had a hand in producing the situation which made war inevitable. Such criticisms as he directs against England concern only her internal politics and social constitution. GREGARIOUSNESS 61 If there be a neutral bloodless enough to qualify as an impartial critic, and if he dispute the validity of such claims, he could still profit from Trotter's work. One does not need to sympathise with his antagonism to Germany to get helpful material from his essay. It is only necessary to agree that forces such as he alleges to be operative there w^ould probably produce war, to gain a hint as to what underlies warlike impulses in general. Similarly whether English society has the inherent virtue he ascribes to it or not, is for our present jjurposes immaterial. In the type of herd he describes as British would certainly be found a people whose power could only be a blessing to the world. In 1908 Trotter wrote as follows — "The solutions [of the problem of recon- ciling individual desires or experience with herd suggestion] by indifference and by rationalisation, or by a mixture of these two processes, are characteristic of the great 62 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR class of normal, sensible, reliable middle age, with its definite views, its resiliency to the depressing influence of facts, and its gift for forming the backbone of the State. In them herd suggestion shows its capacity to triumph over experience, to delay the evolu- tion of altruism, and to obscure the existence and falsify the results of the contest between personal and social desires. That it is able to do so has the advantage of establishing society with great firmness, but it has also the consequence of entrusting the conduct of the State and the attitude of it towards life to a class which their very stability shows to possess a certain relative incapacity to take experience seriously, a certain relative insensibility to the value of feeling and to suffering, and a decided preference for herd tradition over all other sources of conduct. "Early in history the bulk of mankind must have been of this type, because ex- perience, being still relatively simple, would GREGARIOUSNESS 63 have but little suggestive force, and would therefore readily be suppressed by herd sug- gestion. There would be little or no mental conflict, and such as there was would be readily stilled by comparatively simple rationalisations. The average man would then be happy, active, and possessed of an inexhaustible fund of motive and energy, capable of intense patriotism and even of self-immolation for the herd. The nation consequently, in an appropriate environ- ment, would be an expanding one and rend- ered ruthless and formidable by an intense, unshakable conviction of its divine mission. Its blindness towards the new in experience would keep its patriots narrow and fierce, its priests bigoted and bloodthirsty, its rulers arrogant, reactionary and overconfi- dent. Should chance ordain that there arose no great environmental change, rendering necessary great modifications, such a nation would have a brilliant career of conquest, as 64 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR has been so often demonstrated by history. "Among the first-class Powers to-day the mentally stable are still the directing class, and their characteristic tone is discernible in national attitudes towards experience, in national ideals and religions, and in national morality. It is this possession of the power of directing national opinion by a class which is in essence relatively insensitive towards new combinations of experience; this persistence of a mental type, which may have been adequate in the simpler past, into a world where environments are daily be- coming more complex — it is this survival, so to say, of the wagoner upon the footplate of the express engine, which has made the modern history of nations a series of such breathless adventures and hairbreadth escapes. To those who are able to view national affairs from an objective stand- point, it is obvious that each of these escapes might very easily have been a disaster, and GREGARIOUSNESS 65 that sooner or later one of them must be such." In his later work Trotter ascribes these- primitive characteristics more specifically to the aggressive or wolf gregariousness and, needless to say, he finds them highly devel- oped in the Germans. This race, he thinks, demonstrate the validity of his claim that great development can be obtained by con- scious direction of what is the evolutionary tendency, although, of course, he looks on lupine gregariousness as inimical to civiliza- tion as a whole, and therefore bound to fail in the end. It may seem grotesque to attempt an analogy between the society of the wolf and that of any group of men, and it would probably be impossible to present Trotter's arguments sympathetically without quota- tion in extenso. Assuming this risk, how- ever, what he considers to be the lupine characteristics in man may be enumerated. Wolves band themselves together purely 66 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR for the sake of the advantages the pack enjoys over the individual in hunting. Wolf gregariousness is, therefore, founded on aggression. Trotter notes that the Germans are constantly taking as their ideal the civilisations which in the past were built on aggression. Not unnaturally he points to the fact that peoples of the "socialised" (the bee) type, such as Italians and Americans, have not been impressed by German propa- ganda, while the bloodthirsty Turks and Bulgarians have espoused the Teutonic cause. ^ He finds as a national characteristic, pervading all classes, a naive arrogance usually displayed in florid and banal meta- phors. The simple, honest conviction of being God's chosen people furnishes a great stimulus in attack. He claims they are incapable of grasping the idea that other people may be differently constituted from themselves; that they are incredulous of altruism ever being a real motive, and rely GREGARIOUSNESS 67 on intimidation rather than understanding in their relations with other nations. It is to these tendencies that he ascribes the series of diplomatic blunders which resulted in Germany facing a coalition of tremendous strength. Xot unusually he views the ap- parent determination of the General Staff to keep constantly on the offensive as an evidence of aggression being the keynote of their union. He even risks the prediction that there will be a collapse so soon as offence is no longer possible. There are certain traits shown in their internal rela- tionships which Trotter regards as distinc- tive of the lupine type. He speaks first of the flagrant cruelty and harshness exhibited by the individual German in times of peace as well as in war. The same habit he observes in the treatment of their colonies. As a corollary to this the individual German shows a subserviency to his superior and a favourable reaction to rigorous, even phys- 68 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR ical discipline, that would to other peoples be intolerable. This is likened to the behaviour of the dog, who reacts so much more satisfactorily to a whipping than does a horse, for instance. Finally, Trotter makes much of the German tendency to adopt war cries and shibboleths {e.g. "Gott strafe Eng- land'' ) , any attempt to implant which on the English meets with failure. This successful bolstering up of the national morale with catch phrases he cosiders directly anal- ogous to the howl of wolf pack, which inspirits and unites it in hunting. From a scientific rather than a national standpoint it is regrettable that Trotter writes with this partisanship, for it tends, a priori, to prejudice the validity of his arguments. Before speaking of England and Germany explicitly, he mentions that it is open to man to develop his gregariousness along either the wolf, the sheep, or the bee plan. Man, then, is potentially capable of GKEGARIOUSNESS 69 all three types and, it is safe to assume, has all three latent in him. We can get much from Trotter if we accept his aggressive type as expressing those elements in the gregariousness of man which tend towards war. Sheep never fight, bees sting merely to repel attacks. It is only in the develop- ment of the bee type that mankind can progress. The swarm has the focus of the hive, in which all interest is centred, and the co-ordination of function is such that no individualism is possible. What Trotter terms "intercommunication" among the units is developed to its highest point. This he aptly compares to the cell colony that develops into the metazoic type of animal. No one thinks of the welfare of the indi- vidual cell in a multi-cellular animal. The advance of the bee-hive is not determined by subjugation of other hives or species, but by more effective industry. This would make an ideal national type. 70 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR It is now a fairly well recognised fact that in the study of psychopathic states the observation of the conduct and utterances of the patient will betray much of his innate mental constitution, and also show what was the underlying personal significance of the events which disturbed his balance. Our material on the psychology of war is, there- fore, not complete until we have made more of a survey of the phenomena of war. These are, of course, legion, and only a few can be considered here and, at that, in generalities. The external changes in the life of the mass and of the individual do not demand com- ment — ^that is the sphere of the economist. Our problem is to discover the mental changes of the nation and the citizen. Of the national changes the added cohe- siveness and unity is a commonplace. What has been a vague conception of flag or king becomes a living entity. The herd crowds closer together. All the departments of GKEGARIOUSNESS 71 Government become more co-ordinate; the claims of smaller groups, such as labour, capital, and political parties are allowed to lapse in the presence of the need of the large groups. A much-needed reform, long blocked by the obstinacy of some small class, can be instituted without opposition. In short, internal problems almost cease to exist, not merely in relation to the magni- tude of the external problems, but abso- lutely. The factors of sectional rivalry and jealousy have disappeared, or, at least, tend to do so. National conscience is both quick- ened and perverted. The action of the enemy or of individual enemy citizens is judged to be wicked regardless of the merits of the case, while individual frivolities and indiscretions of fellow-citizens come to be looked on almost as treason. The people press a debt of the individual whose payment is never expected in times of peace. Trotter observed in England some less obvious signs 72 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR pf a quickening of the herd instinct. The first reaction was of vague fear. This did not necessarily confine itself to fears for the safety of the country as a whole, but was transferred to ridiculous, petty anxieties. With this was an intolerance of isolation. Men could not bear to be alone, and, follow- ing the instinct for members of the herd to ( be in actual contact, class barriers were \j3roken down. Most interesting was the wild- fire spread and credulity of rumours, that form of mental contagion which owes its existence to herd suggestion. Finally, every foreign-looking person was looked on with suspicion. This last, coupled with the open hatred of individual foes, gives us a beautiful analogy with the psychosis. The uncon- scious idea that the foreigner belongs to a rival species becomes a conscious belief that he is a pestiferous type of animal. All the above, with the exception of rumour, fear, and senseless suspicion, are GREGARIOUSNESS 73 gains for the nation as siicli. National con- sciousness is a large part of that vision with- out which the people perish, and it is quite possible that the essential victory rests with that people whose national morale emerges intact from the war. I once had occasion to meet one of the most noteworthy of the Boer generals, and took the opi)ortunity to ask him why the Boers had not yielded to the British demands instead of attempting the impossible. He replied that they all knew their relative impotence, but that to have capitulated would have meant the for- feiture of their national self-respect, so they chose to fight against impossible odds. We can now begin to see the result of this de- cision. Their individual losses were enor- mous, but nationally they are probably better off. They have as good a Government or better; they are part of a larger civilisa- tion (to which they owe ready allegiance) ; they are not a subject race in fact or feeling. 74 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR One thing is altered: the Vierkleur is re- placed by the Union Jack. But that of which the flag was a symbol has not been destroyed. In fact, it has probably grown. Had the two States capitulated a Boer would not now, in the eyes of Europe and America, be a citi- zen of the world, but only a semi-savage frontiersman. Did the Boers really lose the war? The effects of war on the nation as a whole have still more interesting results on the mental reactions of the individual. We are accustomed to think of energy being largely a product of personal ambition. The in- dividual in war time couples self-abnegation with unwonted energ}^ His interests change : his pride tends to be centred less on the eminence of himself and family, but more on what he and they can do for the country. A man no longer strives to outwit his neigh- bour in business, but rather to outdo him in patriotism. An exhibition of generosity or GEEGARIOUSNESS 75 altruism that merits a sneer from many quarters in times of peace becomes an incen- tive, an example to copy. Herd suggestion constantly reinforces the spirit of self-sacri- fice in the interests of the herd. These statements must not, of course, be taken as indicating constant results. If all the citi- zens of any country responded to the full along these lines, the concerted energy of that herd would probably make it infinitely stronger than any other nation. As in all psychological matters, we can only consider tendencies. It is frequently stated that war awakens a feeling for the essential realities of life. In the face of the astounding per- versions of truth which characterise every war, this statement must be delimited. More accurately one could say that a vaguely felt standard of conduct — to act in best inter- ests of the herd — becomes a vital, conscious rule of life, and keener criticism is directed by each individual to see if his conduct fol- 76 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR lows this rule. As a corollary to this, self- deceptions may tend to disappear. The more or less conscious delusions of grandeur which actuate so many people are apt to fail in the emergency of war. Probably the more fundamental of such ideas — the im- portance of one's individual life — is the one that is most conspicuously shattered. In ^-^e article by Freud, already quoted, there is considerable discussion of our attitude towards death. He shows that normally we are continually handicapped by our insin- cerities about death and fears of it in our- selves and others. There is no more beautiful proof that a nation at war acts as a species struggling for existence than the fact that individual deaths do not matter either to the mass or to the individual himself. Trotter's comparison to the multicellular animal is peculiarly apt in this connection. If we find ourselves in a situation of danger we are not conscious of any fear for hand or eye or GREGARIOUSNESS 77 body, but for ourselves as a whole. Neither the wolf in the pack nor the bee in the swarm has thought for its own safety. As Trotter points out, mass formation gains psycho- logically perhaps more than it does tacti- cally. It seems to me not impossible that the success of military training consists es- sentially in the acquisition of the herd spirit, the gain of a feeling that the herd is always present, even if it be only in imagina- tion. When this is accomplished the prodi- gies of devotion and self-immolation, which are a commonplace of mass formation, can become possible individually. The essen- tial victory in war rests with that nation which has the largest number of citizens unconsciously and constantly aware of the presence of the herd, fighting or travailling alone, perhaps, but hearing always the voice of their choir invisible. CHAPTER IV CORRELATION OF PRIMITIVE INSTINCTS WITH GREGARIOUSNESS We are now in a position to recapitulate. In so far as one can generalise about such a protean affair as war, there are two great groups of phenomena. In the first come vio- lence in the form of killing fellow beings, purposeful destruction of property, injury to the rival trade and deception of the enemy. These are all "legitimate'' in war. With these there always occur "atrocities" in the form of wanton destruction, loot, and the indulgence of brutal passion on the bod- ies of the enemy combatant and non-com- batant alike, phenomena more apt to pre- ponderate in one country but probably pres- ent in all armies. The latter are openly or 78 COKRELATION 79 tacitly encouraged or, at least, condoned by each belligerent. On the other hand, there is a group of phenomena evidencing a stim- ulus to the nation at war, causing greater cohesiveness, greater energy, marvellous self-abnegation on the part of individuals, extinction of all that is a sham in life, but with it all a loss of capacity to sympathise with a foreign view-point that amounts to an intellectual stultification. There are, also, two schools of dynamic psychology that attempt answers to this rid- dle. One says that primitive, anti-social human instincts still exist unconsciously in the make-up of all "civilised'' beings, that they are constantly striving for an outlet which the conditions of war allow. The second school say that man is by instinct a herd animal, and that as such he forms groups to which he owes a blind allegiance, more complete than is generally thought and always including an instinctive hostility to 80 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR that which is outside the national group. / When the group develops an aggressive type (of gregariousness war is imminent. Signifi- cantly, each school in its argument leaves one set of phenomena severely alone. As far as each goes, the argument seems sound ; can they be reconciled, or are they mutually ex- clusive? To answer this we must leave the question of war for a moment and turn to a considera- tion of the fundamentals of dynamic psy- chology. Freud and Trotter are probably the only two psychologists who have initi- ated hypotheses that are not essentially tautological, so only psycho-analysis and herd instinct need be seriously considered. The teaching of Freud is that civilisation has forced upon man a "repression'' of primi- tive instincts whose operation is unconscious but always the dominant, dynamic prin- ciple of life. Trotter, on the other hand, insists that man is by nature gregarious, CORRELATION 81 and impelled by instinct to serve the herd and assimilate his conduct and thought with that of his fellows. The irrationalities and mental disabilities of man he ascribes to the conflict between his actual experience and / what the herd bids him believe. In short, one may say that psycho-analysis deals with individualistic motivation, while herd in- stinct is a study of social instinct. From our studies of the psychoses and the wealth of psycho-analytic material that appears there- in it has become increasingly plain that what psycho-analysis terms "repression" is the work of an instinct (or group of in- stincts) only part of whose work is repres- sion. The other task of this instinctive force is to augment the individualistic un- conscious instinct when it is symbolised in a form that is socially acceptable. This is the essence of the dynamic structure of a "sub- limation.'' The proof of this cannot be given here, but I might mention that the 82 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR elation and energy of the manic state seem to be regularly accompanied by ideas that represent a fusion of individualistic and social tendencies. As I pointed out in re- viewing Trotter's original papers,* his herd instinct is probably nothing more or less than the force behind the psycho-analytic "repressions.'^ Trotter, in a sympathetic critique of psycho-analysis in his book, comes to the same conclusion. Presumably, therefore, the two theories supplement one another. Psycho-analysts (at least the Viennese school) have always seen in con- vention and education the influences that cause repression, but have denied any dyna- mic value to them. Trotter shows conclu- sively, however, that man accepts tradition, convention and ethical education because he is instinctively forced so to do by his grega- rious nature. There are, perhaps, some moral repugnances that are common to all ^Psychiatric Bulletin, Vol. I, No. 1 COKEELATION 83 mankind, but the majority of them are es- sentially tribal in origin. As Stevenson says : ^'The canting moralist tells us of right and wrong; and we look abroad, even on the face of our small earth, and find them change with every climate, and no country where some action is not honoured as a virtue and none where it is not branded as a vice ; and we look in our experience and find no vital congruity in the wisest rules, but at the best a municipal fitness." This "municipal fitness'^ determines (with all its accidents) the moral standard. It may be a law at which our intellect rebels, but we obey it, because obedience to its mandates is what keeps the herd together. What there is of the "brotherhood of man'' in us determines the fundamental consistency of moral standards the civilised world over. One's adherence to the standard of conduct of ideal civilisation, national advantage, or union expedience will depend on the relative 84 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR appeal each makes to tlie gregariousness in the man. One's conscience is, then, not a stable thing, but as variable as the exigencies of the group to which allegiance is auto- matically given. It is hardly necessary to state that the man of real moral greatness is he who is loyal to mankind as a whole, rather than to some smaller group. We are finally in a position to summarise what suggestions can be made as to the psy- chology of war. It is the natural outcome of fundamental human tendencies. Man by his gregarious nature is doomed to split up into groups, and these groups behave bio- logically as if they were separate species struggling for existence. Thanks to his herd instinct, which makes man accept the opinions of those immediately around him — herd, or "mob," suggestion — only that seems to be right which is done by his group, and an abnormal suspicion of the acts of other groups develops. Thus a state of antagon- COHRELATION 85 ism develops which is much augmenteds^b^, the aggressive tendency latent in human ^" gregariousness. The antagonism is cumula- tive, so that sooner or later a state of ex- treme tension is reached. At this point. \ when action of some sort seems imperative, the primitive, unconscious instincts of man assert themselves (as they constantly t-end to do), and the herd, finding in this a ready weapon, relaxes its ban, making of blood lust a virtue. Suddenly the individualistic and social tendencies find themselves worfe^ ing hand in hand — essentially a sublimation ^ i — and war with its tremendous energy is un- leashed. The behaviour of both the mass and the individual then demonstrates that the herd is playing the role of a species struggling for existence., It cannot be ob- jected that war is merely the business of soldiers. Every citizen, male or female, has a share in the spirit of war. All suffer a diminution of egoism, with an added con- 86 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR sciousness of the state, and all feel the satis- faction of a blood lust, whether it be gained by jabbing a bayonet or devouring descrip- tions of carnage in the enemy's trenches. It must not be thought that the repression of these primitive tendencies is easily lifted. There is a feeling of horror quite different from fear when a nation is on the brink of war, although with it, some thoughtful in- trospectionists admit, can be detected a "something" which seems to hope that war will come. This "something," like the fas- cination of a horrible spectacle, is, of course, the unconscious wish. When it has come as close to consciousness as this, its shadow, as it were, being seen, war is truly imminent, for now the herd antagonism is mightily augmented by the primitive pas- sion for violence. The repressing force which colours war with horror, makes it dif- ficult to kill the first man, and keeps the citi- zen at home from relishing the tales of car- COKRELATION 87 nage until he is "used to it" — this force can probably be related to that loyalty we have to the larger herd, all mankind. At such a time as this, with almost the whole w^orld w^eltering in blood, it seems hard to believe in the strength of this wider allegiance. Yet it asserts itself with greater strength at the close of every great war, as the revulsion from bloodshed lasting through generations bears witness.* *An application of this principle of "sublimation" in war may turn out to be of prime importance from. a military standpoint. It is a psycho-analj^ic truism that before every neurosis develops some sublimation is broken dovi^n or its outlet denied by external cir- cumstance. The intense strain of modern warfare is an ideal agency for wearing down the natural stability of a man, and so favouring the development of a neurosis. To counteract this strain there must "be a satisfaction in the work to act as a stimulus. The sensitive individual who cannot develop pleasure in killing — to put the matter brutally — is bound to "be the victim of a double strain, and quickly devel- ops an unconquerable hatred of his task that will soon lead to fear. Once fear appears, surrender or illness is the only escape. Before either refuge is Bought, however, the soldier is not only inefficient 88 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR What of the future? As this essay shows, psychology can give suggestions as to what seem to be the factors underlying the phe- nomena of war, and these only in generali- ties. Naturally, then, more caution is neces- sary in discussing remedies, and they can only be given in vague hints. It is a doctrine of a psychology, as it is of common sense, that things exist for the good there is in them, not for the bad. Thera- peutics must always take this into consider- ation. Rational treatment aims at estab- lishing stability by satisfying with substi- himself , but serves as a focus of contagion ; infecting his fellows with fear and breaking down the morale of his group. A comparatively brief examination by a competent psychiatrist of any soldier complaining- of initial difficulties would often be sufficient to dis- cover the measure of adaptability of the man to his task. If that were thought to be limited, frequent reliefs from active duty would enable him to continue as a soldier indefinitely. It is a much easier matter to prevent a neurosis of this type than to cure it- By such means as these a psychologist can be of ines- timable value to an army, for there is nothing more vital than its morale. CORRELATION 89 tutes the need to which the baneful dis- turbance was an answer. As far as man's primitive cravings are concerned, the sug- gestions of James, made more specific by Jones, seem excellent. Our social constitu- tions must be made more elastic, so as to give more outlet to individualistic impulses, in order that the latter may not be dammed up and form a reservoir of potential vio- lence always ready to burst its floodgates. In times of peace we revert to the illusions that hold individual lives to be supremely valuable, and it is not impossible that hazard is too far removed from us for permanent national health. A national conscription for the undertaking of dangerous engineer- ing feats would probably never be instituted by any democracy, yet the scores of lives lost in such a way would be cheap in comparison with the devastations of war. In approaching the question of the future of international relationships apart from 90 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR actual war, certain possibilities must be kept in mind. If war is a struggle for exist- ence between what are essentially rival species, the preservation of what is most vital to a nation — national morale — is the correct criterion of success or failure in the war. In comparison with the loss of this, physical impoverishment may be almost dis- regarded. Much antagonism to war on the part of fervid "patriots" is the individual fear or horror of personal loss or injury, and, of course, in this case the imagination of the horror is the potent factor. From the standpoint of the nation, as such, war is pos- sibly often a good thing. Some nations, e.g, the German Empire, or the United States, were born of war. We certainly know of no other stimulus which can so vivify and cement a nation. From the standpoint of common humanity, however, war is an un- mitigated scourge. The question, then, should, perhaps, be put: "Do we want CORRELATION 91 nations?'' rather than, "Do we want to abolish war?" It could be well argued that there is little cohesiveness in any large modern nation beyond the wars both pres- ent, potential and in tradition. In the face of man's inveterate tendency to form into herds it seems folly to talk of a reconstruc- tion of human society without national di- yisions. A working conception of common humanity to which loyalty could be devoted is certainly too ambitious a program for the human mind at its present development. If nations were abolished by common con- sent they would reappear with another name, just as, if armaments were abol- ished, people would probably fight with clubs and stones. If nations are, then, to exist, and not be a menace to all mankind, some substitute for war must be found which will give cohesiveness to the herd, but at the same time not detract from the ley- 2 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF WAR alty of its citizens to that larger group, the human race. It must be obvious from all that has been said that war is an outcome of the deepest ^' lying of human forces, and therefore some- thing which cannot be altered by legislation nor agreement any more than a man can be kept sane either by force or by promise. In- stinct is stronger than reason. And war is not an isolated phenomenon unrelated to other human tendencies.. It is the habit of amateur statesmen to offer, by preference, remedies for the largest problems. When lynch law, class hatred, strikes with violence and lockouts with starvation are things of the past, then, and then only, may w^e hope that man is becoming a peace-loving animal. In the meantime, psychology can offer one ray of hope. Instincts triumph over reason, but largely because instincts act uncon- sciously. When man is so educated as to know himself and recognise the forces that CORRELATION 93 are within him, lie will be in a position to see the way his footsteps lead, and change his path — if he wills.