OUTLINES OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY. OUTLINES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. FOR THE USE OF STUDENTS IN THE UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH. THE FIFTH EDITION. EDINBURGH : PRINTED FOR CADELI, & COMPANY, STIRLING & KENNKY, AND JOHN FAIRBAIRN, EDINBURGH; GEORGE CLARK, ABERDEEN ; AND WHITTAKER & CO. LONDON. 1829. PREFACE. My principal object, in this Publication, is to exhibit such a view of the arrange- ment of my Lectures, as may facilitate the studies of those to whom they are addressed. In a course which employs more than five months, and which necessarily includes a great variety of disquisitions, it is difficult for a hearer to retain a steady idea of the train of thought leading from one sul)ject to another ; and, of consequence, the lec- tures, by assuming the appearance of de- tached discourses, are in danger of losing VI the advantages arising from connection and method. The following Outlines will, I hope, not only obviate this inconvenience ; but will allow me, in future, a greater la- titude of illustration and digression, than I could have indulged myself in with pro- priety, so long as my students were left to investigate the chain of my doctrines by their own reflections. In the execution of this design, I have attempted, at the same time, to state, under each head, a few fundamental principles, which I was either anxious to impress on the memory of my hearers ; or which I thought might be useful to them, by re- lieving their attention during the discussion of a long or a difficult argument. The branch of Moral Philosophy which relates to the Principles of Politics being less abstract than the others, I have con- VII tented myself with a simple enumeration of the most important articles treated of in the third part of my course. It is scarcely necessary for me to mention, that, in this enumeration, I have not aimed at any thing approaching to systematical ar- rangement ; and that, in illustrating the titles it contains, I am obliged, by the term prescribed to my academical labours, to confine myself to very general sketches. As soon as my other engagements allow me sufficient leisure for such an undertak- ing, I shall attempt a separate course of lectures on this very extensive and difficult subject. With respect to my general plan, those who are in the smallest degree conversant with ethical writers, will perceive, that, in its formation, I have been guided almost entirely by the train of my own specula- tions. In following the order which these Vlll prescribed, I was far from proceeding on the supposition, that it was likely to pos- sess, in the opinion of the public, advan- tages over the arrangements already pro- posed : but it appeared to me reasonable to think, that a plan resulting from my own habits of thought, would probably be bet- ter executed in my hands, than any one, how perfect soever, suggested by the views of another. DUGALD STEWART. College of Ej>inburgii, \ Nov. 8. 1793. I IX p. S. — Having, of late, carried into execution (at least in part) the design an- nounced in the foregoing Preface, by a separate course of Lectures on Political Economy, I have omitted, in this Edition of my Outlines, the Articles which I for- merly enumerated under that general title ; substituting in their stead a few others, calculated to illustrate the peculiar and in- timate connection between this department of Politics and the more appropriate objects of Ethics. The observations which these articles are meant to introduce, may be useful, at the same time, in preparing the minds of Students for disquisitions, the details of which can scarcely fail to appear uninviting to those, who are not aware of the important conclusions to which they are subservient. Nov. 2, 1801. CONTENTS. INTRODUCTION. Sect. Page I. Of the Object of Philosophy, and the Method of prosecuting Philosophical Inquiries, 1 II. Application of the foregoing Principles to the Philosophy of the Human Mind, - 7 III. Causes of the slow Progress of Human Know- ledge ; more particularly of the Philosophy of the Human Mind, and of the Sciences immediately connected with it, - y SUBJECT AND ARRANGEMENT OF THIS TREATISE. PART I. of the intellectual powers of man. Sect. I. Of Consciousness, - - - 18 II. Of the Powers of External Perception, - 20 Art. 1. Of the Laws of Perception in the case of our different Senses, - ib. Art. 2. Of Perception in general, - 29 Xll CONTENTS. Sect. Page III. Of Attention, . - . 36 IV. Of Conception, ... 38 V. Of Abstraction, - - - 40 VI. Of the Association of Ideas, - - 44 VII. Of Memory, - - - - 49 VIII. Of Imagination, - - - 51 IX. Of Judgment and Reasoning, - - 53 1. Of Intuitive Evidence, - 54 2. Of Deductive Evidence, - 56 X. Of Intellectual Powers and Capacities, form- ed by particular Habits of Study or of Business, - - - - 61 XI. Of certain auxiliary Faculties and Principles essential to our Intellectual Improvement, or intimately connected with it, - 67 1. Of Language, - - 68 2. Of the Principle of Imitation, 71 XII. Of the Intellectual Faculties of Man, as con- trasted with the Instincts of the Brutes, 74 PART II. OF THE ACTIVE AND OF THE MORAL POWERS OF MAN. CHAP. I. CLASSIFICATION AND ANALYSIS OF OUH ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS. Sect. I. Of the Active Powers in general, - - 80 II. Of our Appetites, - - - 82 CONTENTS. XIU Sect. Page III. Of our Desires, - - - 84 1. The Desire of Knowledge, - 85 2. The Desire of Society, - 86 3. The Desire of Esteem, - 88 4. The Desire of Power, - 90 5. The Desire of Superiority, - 94 IV. Of our Affections, ... 98 1. Of the Benevolent Affections, - hh. 2. Of the Malevolent Affections, 105 V. OfSelf-Love, - - - - 109 VI. Of the Moral Faculty, - - - 117 Art. 1. General Observations on the Mo- ral Faculty ; tending^- chiefly to shew, that it is an original Prin- ciple of our Nature, and not re- solvable into any other Principle or Principles more simple, - ib. Art. 2. Analysis of our Moral Perceptions and Emotions, - - 126 1. Of the Perception of Right and Wrong, - - 128 2. Of the Agreeable and Disa- greeable Emotions, arising from the Perception of what is E-iojht and Wrong; in Conduct, - - 141 3. Of the Perception of Merit and Demerit, - - 144 Art. 3. Of Moral Obligation, - - 148 XIV CONTENTS. Sect. Page VII. Of certain Principles which co-operate with our Moral Powers in their Influence on the Conduct, . _ - 154 1. Of Decency, or a regard to Character, 155 2. Of Sympathy, - - . 157 3. Of the Sense of the Ridiculous, 160 4. Of Taste, considered in its relation to Morals, - - - - 162 VIII. Of Man's free Agency, - - - 166 PART II. OF THE ACTIVE AND OF THE MORAL POWEKS OF MAN. CHAP. II. OF THE VARIOUS BRANCHES OF OUR DUTY. Sect. I, Of the Duties which respect the Deity, 171 [Preliminary/ Inquiry into the Principles of' Na- tural Religioni~\ - - - - 1 72 Art. 1. Of the Existence of the Deity, ib. 1. Of the Foundations of our Rea- soning from the Effect to the Cause, and of the Evidences of Active Power, exhibited in the Universe, - - - 175 2. Of the Evidence of Design exhi- bited in the Universe, - 185 CONTENTS. XV Skct. Page Art. 2. Of the Moral Attributes of the Deity, .... 203 1. Of the Evidences of Benevolent Design in the Universe, . 205 2. Of the Evidences of the Moral Government of the Deity, - 219 Art. 3. Of a Future State, - 222 1. Of the Argument for a Future State, derived from the Nature of Mind, - - - 224 2. Of the Evidences of a Future State, arising from the Human Constitution, and from the Cir- cumstances in which Man is placed, - . - 232 Continuation and Conclusion o/" Section I. 238 II. Of the Duties which respect our Fellow- Creatures, ... 242 Art. 1. Of Benevolence, - - 243 Art. 2. Of Justice, - - - 249 1. Of Candour, - - 251 2. Of Uprightness or Integrity, 255 Art. 3. Of Veracity, - - - 2G4 III. Of the Duties which respect ourselves, . 272 Art. 1. General Remarks on this Class of our Duties, - . - ih. Art. 2. Of the Duty of employing the Means we possess to promote our own Happiness, - 275 XVI CONTENTS. Sect. Page Art. 3. Of Happiness, - - 278 1. Opinions of the Ancients concerning the Sovereign Good, . - . 279 2. Additional Remarks on Happiness, - - 285 IV, Of the different Theories which have been formed concerning the Object of Moral Approbation, - - - 803 V. Of the General Definition of Virtue, 305 VI. Of an Ambiguity in the words Right and Wrong, Virtue and Vice, - - 308 VII. Of the Office and use of Reason in the Practice of Morality, - - 312 Appendix, - - - - SI 5 OUTLINES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. INTRODUCTION. SECTION I. OF THE OBJECT OF PHILOSOPHY, AND THE METHOD OF PROSECUTING PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIIIIES. 1. All the different kinds of philosophical inquiry, and all that practical knowledge which guides our conduct in life, presuppose such an established order in the succession of events, as enables us to form conjectures con- cerning the future, from the observation of the past. 2 OUTLINES OF 2. In the phenomena of the material world, and in many of the phenomena of mind, we expect, with the most perfect confidence, that in the same combinations of circumstances the same results will take place. The laws which regulate the course of human affairs are inves- tigated with much greater difficulty : But, even in this class of events, such a degree of order may frequently be traced, as furnishes general rules of great practical utility; and this order becomes the more apparent, in propor- tion as we generalize our observations. 3. Our knowledge of the laws of nature is entirely the result of observation and experi- ment ; for there is no instance in which we perceive such a necessary connection between two successive events, as might enable us to infer the one from the other by reasoning a priori. We find, from experience, that cer- tain events are invariably conjoined, so that when we see the one, we expect the other ; but our knowledge in such cases extends no farther than to the fact. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 3 4. To ascertain those established conjunc- tions of successive events, which constitute the order of the universe ; — to record the phe- nomena which it exhibits to our observation, and to refer them to their general laws, is the great business of philosophy. — Lord Bacon was the first person who was fully aware of the importance of this fundamental truth. — The ancients, considered philosophy as the science of causes ; and hence were led to many speculations, to which the human fa- culties are altogether incompetent. 5. The ultimate object of philosophical in- quiry is the same which every man of plain understanding proposes to himself, when he remarks the events which fall under his ob- servation, with a view to the future regula- tion of his conduct. The more knowledge of this kind we acquire, the better can we ac- commodate our plans to the established or- der of things, and avail ourselves of natural Powers and Agents for accomplishing our purposes. 4 OUTLINES OF 6. The knowledge of the Philosopher dif- fers from that sagacity which directs unedu- cated men in the business of life, not in kind, but in degree, and in the manner in which it is acquired. Isf, By artificial combinations of circumstances, or, in other words, by exjwri- ments, he discovers many natural conjunc- tions which would not have occurred sponta- neously to his observation, ^cUy, By investi- gating the general Laws of Nature, and by reasoning from them synthetically, he can of- ten trace an established order, where a mere observer of facts would perceive nothing but irregularity. — This last process of the mind is more peculiarly dignified with the name of Philosophy ; and the object of the rules of philosophizing is to explain in what manner it ought to be conducted. 7. The knowledge which is acquired of the course of Nature by mere observation, is ex- tremely limited, and extends only to cases in which the uniformity of the observed pheno- mena is apparent to our senses. This happens. MOKAI. PHlLOSOrHY. 5 either when one single law of nature operates separately, or when different laws are always combined together in the same manner. In most instances, however, when different laws are combined, the result varies in every parti- cular case, according to the different circum- stances of the combination ; and it is only by knowing what the laws are which are concern- ed in any expected phenomenon, and by con- sidering in what manner they modify each other's effects, that the result can be predicted. 8. Hence it follows, that the first step in the study of Philosophy is to ascertain the simple and general laws on which the com- plicated phenomena of the universe depend. Having obtained these laws, we may proceed safely to reason concerning the effect result- ing from any given combination of them. — In the former instance, we are said to carry on our inquiries in the way of Analysis ; in the latter in that of Synthesis. 9. To this method of philosophizing, (which 6 UUTLINES OF is commonly distinguished by the title of the Method of Induction,) we are indebted for the rapid progress which physical knowledge has made since the time of Lord Bacon. The pub- lication of his writings fixes one of the most important seras in the history of science. — Not that the reformation which has since taken place in the plan of philosophical inquiry is to be ascribed entirely to him : for although he did more to forward it than any other in- dividual, yet his genius and writings seem to have been powerfully influenced by the cir- cumstances and character of the age in which he lived ; and there can be little doubt that he only accelerated an event which was al- ready prepared by many concurrent causes. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. SECTION II. APPLICATION OF THE FOREGOING PRINCIPLES TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE HUMAN MIND. 10. The reformation in the plan of philoso- phical inquiry, which has taken place during the two last centuries, although not entirely- confined to physics, has not extended in the same degree to the other branches of science ; as sufficiently appears from the prevailing scepticism with respect to the principles of metaphysics and of moral philosophy. This scepticism can only be corrected by applying to these subjects the method of induction. 11. As all our knowledge of the material world rests ultimately on facts ascertained by observation, so all our knowledge of the hu- man mind rests ultimately on facts for which we have the evidence of our own conscious- ness. An attentive examination of such facts 8 OUTLINES OF will lead in time to the general principles of the human constitution, and will gradually form a science of mind not inferior in certain- ty to the science of body. Of this species of investigation, the works of Dr Reid furnish many valuable examples. 12. The objections which have been stated by some writers of the present age to the conclusions of those metaphysicians who have attempted to apply the method of induction to the science of mind, are perfectly similar to the charge which was at first brought a- gainst the Newtonian doctrine of gravitation, as being a revival of the occult qualities of the Aristotelians. In all our inquiries, whe- ther they relate to matter or to mind, the bu- siness of philosophy is confined to a reference of particular facts to other facts more gene- ral ; and our most successful researches must always terminate in the discovery of some law of nature, of which no explanation can be given. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. SECTION III. CAUSES OF THE SLOW PROGRESS OF HUMAN KNOW- LEDGE ; MORE PARTICULARLY OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE HUMAN MIND, AND OF THE SCIENCES IM- MEDIATELY CONNECTED WITH IT. 13. Some of the chief of these may be re- ferred to the following heads. (1.) The imperfections of language, both as I instrument o communication. an instrument of thought and a medium of (2.) Mistakes about the proper object of philosophy, and the method of prosecuting philosophical inquiries. (3.) A disposition to grasp at general prin- ciples, without submitting to the previous study of particular facts. 10 OUTLINES, &C. (4.) Difficulty of ascertaining facts, parti- cularly in the sciences immediately connected with the philosophy of the human mind. (5.) The great part of life which is spent in making useless literary acquisitions. (6.) Prejudices arising from a reverence for great names, and from the influence of local institutions. (7.) A predilection for singular or paradoxi- cal opinions. (8.) A disposition to unlimited scepticism. OUTLINES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. SUBJECT AND ARRANGEMENT OF THIS TREATISE. 1. The object of IVIoral Philosophy is to ascertain the general rules of a wise and vir- tuous conduct in life, in so far as these rules may be discovered by the unassisted light of nature; that is, by an examination of the principles of the human constitution, and of the circumstances in which man is placed. 2. In examining the principles of our con- stitution with this view, our inquiries may 12 OUTLINES OF be arranged under three heads ; according an they refer, (1.) To the intellectual powers of man. (2.) To his active and moral powers. And (3.) To man, considered as the member of a political body. 3. Of these articles, the two first coincide with the common division of human nature into the powers of the Understanding and those of the Will ; a division of great anti- quity, and which (abstracting from the effects of political institutions) exhausts the whole of Moral Philosophy. As man, however, ex- cepting in his rudest state, has been always found connected with a political community, the principles which lay the foundation of this species of union may be regarded as univer- sal and essential principles of our constitution ; and, without an examination of them, it is impossible for us to have a just idea of our si- MORAL I'HILOSOPHY. IS tuation in the world, and of the most import- ant duties we owe to our fellow-creatures. This last branch of the subject has, besides, a more intimate connection with the other two than might at first be apprehended : for it is in the political union, and in the gradual im- provement of which it is susceptible, that na- ture has made a provision for a gradual deve- lopement of our intellectual and moral powers, and for a proportional enlargement in our ca- pacities of enjoyment ; and it is by the par- ticular forms of their political institutions, that those opinions and habits which consti- tute the Mcmners of nations are chiefly de- termined. How intimately these are connect- ed with the progress and the happiness of the race will appear in the sequel. 4. An investigation of the Pleasures and Pains of which we are susceptible, might fur- nish the subject of a fourth view of man, con- sidered as a sensitive being. But instead of aiming at so great a degree of analytical dis- tinctness, it will be found more convenient to 14 OUTLINES, &C. incorporate this part of the Philosophy of the Human Mind with the other three which have been already defined ; connecting what- ever remarks may occur on our enjoyments or sufferings, with those intellectual or moral principles, from the exercise of which they re- spectively arise. OUTLINES OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY. PART I. OF THE INTELLECTUAL POWERS OF MAN. The most important of these are compre- hended in the following enumeration : (1.) Consciousness. (2.) Powers of external perception. (3.) Attention. (4.) Conception. 16 OUTLINES 01 (5.) Abstraction. (6.) Association of ideas. (7.) Memory. (8.) Imagination. (9-) Powers of judgment and reasoning. 5. Besides these intellectual faculties, which in some de^ee are common to the whole species, there are other more complicated powers or capacities, which are gradually- formed by particular habits of study or of business. Such are, the Power of Taste; a Genius for Poetry, for Painting, for Music, for JMathematics ; with all the various intel- lectual habits acquired in the different pro- fessions of life. To analyze such compound- ed powers into the more simple and general principles of our nature, forms one of the most interesting subjects of philosophical dis- quisition. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 17 6. To this branch of our constitution may also be referred those auxiHary faculties and principles, which are essential to our intel- lectual improvement, or very intimately con- nected with it ; in particular, the faculty of communicating our thoughts by arbitrary signs, and the principle of imitation. 18 OUTLINES OF SECTION I. CONSCIOUSNESS. 7. This word denotes the immediate know- ledge which the mind has of its sensations and thoughts, and, in general, of all its present operations. 8. Of all the present operations of the mind, Consciousness is an inseparable con- comitant. 9. The belief with which it is attended has been considered as the most irresistable of any ; insomuch that this species of evidence has never been questioned : and yet it rests on the same foundation with every other kind of be- lief to which we are determined by the con- stitution of our nature. MORAL I'HILOSOPHY. 19 10. We cannot properly be said to be con- scious of our own existence ; our knowledge of this fact being necessarily posterior, in the order of time, to the consciousness of those sensations by which it is suggested. 11. From Consciousness and Memory we acquire the notion, and are impressed with a conviction, of our own personal identity. 20 OUTLINES OF SECTION II. OF THE POWERS OF EXTERNAL PERCEPTION. ARTICLE FIRST. OF THE LAWS OF PERCEPTION IN THE CASE OF OUR DIFFERENT SENSES. 12. Our external senses are commonly reck- oned to be five in number, and the same enu- meration has been adopted by the soundest philosophers. An attempt has been made by some writers to resolve all our senses into that of feeling ; but this speculation has plainly proceeded from over-refinement, and has no tendency to illustrate the subject of inquiry. 13. Of our five senses there are two, m%. Touch and Taste, in which there must be an immediate application of the object to the MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 21 organ. In the other three, the object is per- ceived at a distance, by the intervention of a material medium. 1 4. In order to form an accurate notion of the means by which we acquire our know- ledge of things external, it is necessary to at- tend to the distinct meanings of the words Sensation and Percei:>tion, The former ex- presses merely that change in the state of the mind which is produced by an impression upon an organ of sense ; (of which change we can conceive the mind to be conscious, without any knowledge of external objects :) the lat- ter expresses the knowledge we obtain, by means of our sensations, of the qualities of matter. An indiscriminate use of these two words has introduced much confusion into philosophical disquisitions. SMELLING, TASTING, AND HEARING. 15. The qualities perceived by Smelling Tasting, and Hearing, are known to us only 22 OUTLINES OF as the causes of certain sensations ; and have therefore been contradistinguished by the name of Secondm-y Qualities^ from those of which we learn the nature directly and imme- diately from the sensations with which they are connected. Of this last kind are Exten- sion and Figure ; — to which (along with some others) Philosophers have given the title of the Primary Qualities of matter, 16. Abstracting from our other organs of perception, Smelling, Tasting, and Hearing, could give us no information concerning ex- ternal objects. 17. Any one of these senses, however, might suggest to the mind (or furnish the oc- casions of our forming) the simple ideas or no- tions of Number, Time, Causation, Existence, Personal Identity, and many others. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 23 TOUCH. 18. The sense of Touch is spread over the whole surface of the body ; but the hand is more particularly appropriated to this mode of perception ; in consequence, partly, of its ana- tomical structure, and partly of the greater de- gree of attention we give to the impressions which are made on it. 19. Some of the qualities perceived by this sense are primary, others secondary. — In all its different perceptions, however, there is one common circumstance ; that we are not only made acquainted with the existence of some quality or other, but with the particular part of the body to which the external object is applied. It is probably owing to this, that w^e refer to Touch a variety of sensations which have little or no resemblance to each other ; Heat, Itching, Pain, kc. All of these suggest to us the local situation of their excit- 24 OUTLINES OF ing causes ; and hence we refer them to the same class. 20. The hand is useful in two respects : 1. For examining the properties of bodies, and the laws of the material world ; of which pro- perties and laws none of our other senses, un- assisted by that of Touch, could convey to us any accurate knowledge. 2. For the practice of the mechanical arts. — The advantages we derive from it in these respects are so great, that some philosophers, fond of paradoxical opinions, have ascribed to it entirely our in- tellectual superiority over the brutes. 21. The importance of this organ to man sufficiently intimates the intentions of nature with respect to his ordinary posture ; and af- fords a refutation of those theories which at- tempt to class him with the quadrupeds. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 25 SIGHT. 22. The description of the Eye, and of the manner in which the pencils of rays, proceed- ing from the different points of a visible ob- ject, are collected by the refractive powers of the humours, so as to form a picture on the retina, belongs properly to optics ; but there are many questions arising from this subject, which are intimately connected with the phi- losophy of the human mind, and which op- tical writers have in vain attempted to resolve on the common principles of their science. Such are all the questions that relate to the most simple and general laws of vision. These laws are facts which the optician must assume as the groundwork of his reasoning ; not difficulties which he is called on to ex- plain. 23. Among the phenomena of vision, more immediately connected with the philosophy 26 OUTLINES OF of the human mind, the most important are those which depend on the distinction be- tween the original and the acquired percep- tions of sight. Prior to experience, all that we perceive by this sense is superficial ex- tension and figure, with varieties of colour and of illumination. In consequence, however, of a comparison between the perceptions of sight and of touch, the visible appearances of objects, together with the correspondent affections of the eye, become signs of their tangible qualities, and of the distances at v/hich they are placed from the organ. In some cases our judgment proceeds on a va- riety of these circumstances combined toge- ther ; and yet, so rapidly is the intellectual process performed, that the perception seems to be perfectly instantaneous. 24. This distinction, between the original and the acquired perceptions of sight, leads to an explanation of many curious phenomena, which had long puzzled those opticians who confined their attention to the mathematical MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 27 principles of Dioptrics. But to the student of Moral Philosophy it is interesting, chiefly as it affords a palpable and an acknowledged proof, that the mind may carry on intellect- ual processes which leave no trace in the me- mory. 25. Two other celebrated questions con- cerning vision are intimately connected with the philosophy of the mind, and furnish a fa- vourable opportunity for illustrating the li- mits wdiich nature has prescribed to our in- quiries on the subject of perception. The one relates to our seeing objects erect, by means of inverted images on the retina ; the other, to our seeing objects single with two eyes. 26. Some of the qualities perceived by sight are primary, others secondary. Exten- sion and figure belong to the former class ; colour and varieties of illumination, to the lat- ter. 28 OUTLINES OF 27. The foregoing article naturally leads the attention to the general accommodation of our animal frame to our intellectual fa- culties. Under this head the following par- ticulars may furnish matter for useful reflec- tions. (1.) The local distribution of our organs of sense. (2.) The adaptation of our perceptive powers to the properties and laws of the material world. (3.) The relation of the stature and strength of man to the physical arrangements on that planet with which he is connected. (4.) The versatility of his nature ; qualify- ing him to subsist in every variety of climate. MORAL PHILOSOHY. 29 SECTION II. OF THE POWERS OF EXTERNAL PERCEPTION. ARTICLE SECOND. OF PERCEPTION IN GENERAL. 28. Our notions both of body and of mind are merely relative ; that is, we can define the former only by the qualities perceived by our senses, and the latter by the operations of which we are conscious. 29. As the qualities of body bear no re- semblance to the operations of mind, we are unavoidably led to consider them as perfectly distinct objects of our knowledge ; each of which must be studied in its own peculiar way : The one by attention to the subjects of our Consciousness ; the other by attention to the objects of our Perceptions. — This is not a 30 OUTLINES OF hypothesis, but a fact, which is implied in the only notions of body and of mind that we are capable of forming. 30. It appears, however, from the pheno- mena of perception, and also from those of voluntary motion, that the connection be- tween body and mind is extremely intimate ; and various theories have been proposed, to explain the manner in which it is carried on. All these theories relate to a subject placed beyond the reach of our faculties ; and con- cerning which it is impossible for us to ascer- tain any thing, but the laws by which the connection is resfulated. '&' 31. According to the distinction formerly stated between the primary and the seconda- ry qualities of matter (15.), our notions of the latter are merely relative ; the sensations which correspond to them informing us of nothing; but of the existence of certain un- known causes by which they are produced. What we know of the nature of these causes MORAL PHILOSOPHY. SI is the result of subsequent philosophical in- vestigation. — The names of secondary quali- ties are in all languages ambiguous ; the same word expressing the sensation, and the un- known cause by which it is excited. Hence the origin of the Cartesian paradox with re- spect to the non-existence of heat, cold, gmell, sound, and colour. 32. The primary qualities of matter, (such, for example, as Extension and Figure,) al- though perceived in consequence of certain sensations excited in our minds, are always apprehended as external and independent ex- istences ; and the notions of them we form have in general no reference to the sensations by which they are suggested. The truth seems to be, that these sensations were intend- ed by nature to perform merely the office of signs, without attracting any notice to them- selves ; and as they are seldom accompanied either with pleasure or pain, we acquire an habitual inattention to them in early infancy, 32 OUTLINES OF which is not easily to be surmounted in our maturer years. 33. As our sensations have no resemblance to the qualities of matter, it has puzzled phi- losophers to explain in what manner our no- tions of primary qualities are acquired. It is this difficulty that has given rise to the mo- dern scepticism concerning the non-existence of matter. 34. According to the ancient theory of perception, sensible qualities are perceived by means of images or species propagated from external objects to the mind, by the or- gans of sense. These images (which since the time of Descartes have been commonly called Ideas) were supposed to be resemblances of the sensible qualities ; and, like the impres- sion of a seal on wax, to transmit their form without their matter. This hypothesis is now commonly distinguished by the title of the Ideal Theory. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 33 35. On the principles of this theory, Berke- ley demonstrated that the existence of matter is impossible : for, if we have no knowledge of any thing which does not resemble our ideas or sensations, it follows that we have no know- ledge of any thing whose existence is indepen- dent of our perceptions. 36. If the Ideal Theory be admitted, the foregoing argument against the existence of matter, is conclusive ; but the theory is un- supported by evidence, and is even inconcei- vable. That we have notions of external qualities perfectly unlike to our sensations, or to any thing of which we are immediately conscious, is 2i fact ; nor ought we to dispute the reality of what we perceive, because we cannot reconcile this fact wath our received philosophical systems. 37. Dr Reid, who first called the Ideal Theory in question, offers no argument to prove that the material world exists ; but con- siders our belief of it as an ultimate fact in our c 34 OUTLINES OF nature. — It rests on the same foundation with our belief of the reality of our sensations, which no man has disputed. 38. Beside the Ideal Theory, other attempts have been made to explain in what manner the communication between mind and matter is carried on, in the case of perception. — Leib- nitz's system of pre-established Harmony, ta- king for granted the impossibility of any im- mediate connection between two substances essentially different, represents the human mind and human body as two independent machines, adjusted, at their first formation, to an invariable correspondence with each other, like two clocks made to correspond in all their movements. — By means of the same hypothe- sis, he endeavoured to account for the pheno- mena of Voluntary Motion. 39. The following are the most important general laws of our perceptions, as far as we can infer them from acknowledged facts. '&' (1.) The object, either immediately, or by MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 35 means of some material medium, must make an impression on the organ. (2.) By means of the organ, an impression is made on the nerves. (3.) By means of the nerves, an impression is made on the brain. 40. With respect, however, to the manner in which this process is carried on, and even with respect to the nature of the changes that take place in the nerves and brain, in the case of perception, we are hitherto ignorant ; nor does there seem to be any probability that we shall ever obtain satisfactory information. Physiologists, as well as metaphysicians, have in this instance, too frequently lost sight of the just rules of philosophizing, and have proposed many conjectures which afford no explanation of the phenomena in question, and which have sometimes led to dangerous conclusions. 36 OUTLINES OF SECTION III. OF ATTKNTION. 41. It appears from the acquired percep- tions of sight, that a process of thought may be carried on by the mind, without leaving any trace in the memory ; and many facts prove, that impressions may be made on our organs of sense, and yet be forgotten next moment. In such cases, our want of recollection is as- cribed, even in ordinary conversation, to a want of attention ; so that it seems to be a principle sufficiently ascertained by common experience, that there is a certain act or exer- tion of the mind, necessary to fix in the me- mory, the thoughts and the perceptions of which we are conscious. This act is one of the simplest of all our intellectual operations, and yet it has been very little noticed by wri- ters on pneumatology. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 37 42. Having established the certainty of the general fact, by an induction of particulars, we are entitled, by all the rules of sound phi- losophizing, to employ it as a principle for the explanation of other phenomena. Many very curious ones which are commonly referred to other causes, are resolvable into this principle, in a manner equally simple and satisfactory. 38 OUTLINES OF SECTION IV OF CONCEPTION. 43. The lower animals, as far as we are able to observe, are entirely occupied with their present sensations and perceptions : but man is possessed of a faculty by which he can re- present to himself sensations of which he has been formerly conscious, and external objects which he has formerly perceived. This fa- culty may be conveniently distinguished by the name of Conception. 44. The objects of some senses are more easily conceived than those of others ; above all, the objects which are perceived by the eye. The power of conception, however, may, in the case of all our senses, be greatly improved by experience. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 39 45. It is commonly understood, that Con- ception is accompanied with no belief of the existence of its objects ; but various considera- tions render this opinion somewhat doubtful. 46. This faculty has obviously a very inti- mate connection with the body. The con- ception of a pungent taste, produces a rush of saliva into the mouth. The conception of an instrument of torture applied to any member of the body, produces a shock similar to what would be occasioned by its actual application. 40 OUTLINES OF SECTION V. OF ABSTRACTION. 47. By our perceptive powers we are made acquainted only with what is jyarticular or individual ; but this description comprehends a very small part of the subjects about which our thoughts are employed. In by far the greater number of instances, our reasonings relate to classes or genera of objects or of events. 48. The process of classification supposes a power of attending to some of the qualities, or circumstances of objects and events, and of withdrawing the attention from the rest. This power is called by logicians, Abstraction, It may be defined, in more general terms, " The Faculty by which the mind separates MORAL THILOSOrHY. 41 " the combinations which are presented to it, " in order to simplify the objects of its consi- " deration." 49. An appellative, or a generic word, is a name applicable in common to a number of individuals, which agree with each other in some particulars, and differ in others. By- means of such words, we are enabled to rea- son concerning classes of objects and classes of events, and to arrive at general conclusions, comprehending under them a multitude of particular truths. The use which is made in algebra of the letters of the alphabet, affords the best illustration of the nature of general reasoning, and of the principles on which it proceeds. These principles were long misun- derstood by philosophers, who imagined that a generic word expresses an actual existence distinct from the individuals of which the jje- nus is composed ; and that the mind has a faculty of directing its attention to this ge- neral IDEA or ESSENCE, Without the media- tion of language. Hence much of the mys- 42 OUTLINES OF tery which still prevails in the abstract sci- ences. 50. As it is by language alone that we are rendered capable of general reasoning, one of the most valuable branches of logic is that which relates to the use of words. Too little attention has hitherto been bestowed on this subject. 51. It is not, however, sufficient that we guard against error, in ascertaining the truth of our general principles. However accurate- ly just they maybe in themselves, considered as speculative maxims ; they must always be applied, in actual practice, with the utmost caution. To illustrate the advantages result- ing from the proper vise of them, and the mis- takes produced by their abuse, would form another very important article in a philosophi- cal system of logic. 52. A habit of abstract speculation, uncor- rected by experience ; and a habit of unen- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 43 lightened practice, without the aid of gene- ral principles ; are two opposite extremes, to which we are liable, in the conduct of the un- derstanding. Few men are to be found, who have not acquired, in early life, a manifest bias either to the one or to the other. 44 OUTLINES OF SECTION VI. OF THE ASSOCIATION OV IDEAS, 53. The effect of custom in connecting to- gether different thoughts, in such a manner, that the one seems spontaneously to follow the other, is one of the most obvious facts with respect to the operations of the mind. To this law of our constitution, modern philoso- phers have given the name of the Association of Ideas. — Of late, the phrase has been used in a more extensive sense, to denote the ten- dency which our thoughts have to succeed each other in a regular train ; whether the connection between them be established by custom, or arise from some other associating principle. 54. What the different circumstances are, which regulate the succession of our thoughts, it is not possible, perhaps, to enumerate com- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 45 pletely. The following are some of the most remarkable : Resemblance, Analogy, Contra- riety, Vicinity in Place, Vicinity in Time, Relation of Cause and Effect, Relation of Means and End, Relation of Premises and Conclusion. Whether some of these may not be resolvable into others, is not very material to inquire. — The most powerful of all the as- sociating principles is undoubtedly Custom ; and it is that which leads to the most import- ant inquiries of a practical nature. 55. Among the associating principles al- ready enumerated, there is an important dis- tinction. The relations on which some of them are founded are obvious ; and connect our thoughts together, when the attention is not directed particularly to any subject. Other relations are discovered only in conse- quence of efforts of meditation or study. Of the former kind are the relations of Resem- blance and Analogy, of Contrariety, of Vi- cinity in Time and Place ; of the latter, the Relations of Cause and Effect, of Means 46 OUTLINES OF and End, of Premises and Conclusion. It is owing to this distinction that transitions, which would be highly offensive in philoso- phical writing, are the most pleasing of any in poetry, 56. In so far as the train of our thoughts is regulated by the laws of Association, it de- pends on causes of the nature of which we are ignorant, and over which we have no direct or immediate controul. At the same time it is evident, that the will has some in- fluence over this part of our constitution. To ascertain the extent and the limits of this in- fluence, is a problem of equal curiosity and importance. 57. We have not a power of summoning up any particular thought, till that thought first solicit our notice. Among a crowd, how- ever, which present themselves, we can choose and reject. We can detain a particular thought, and thus check the train that would otherwise have taken place. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 47 58. The indirect influence of the will over tlie train of our thoughts is very extensive. It is exerted chiefly in two ways : 1. By an effort of attention, we can check the spon- taneous course of our ideas, and give efficacy to those associating principles which prevail in a studious and collected mind. 2. By practice, we can strengthen a particular asso- ciating principle to so great a degree, as to ac- quire a command over a particular class of our ideas. 59. The effect of habit, in subjecting to the will those intellectual processes, which are the foundation of wit, — of the mechcmical part of poetry, (or, in other words, of the powers of versification and rhyming), — of poetical fancy, — of invention in the arts and sciences ; — and, above all, its effect in forming a talent for ex- tempore elocution, furnish striking illustra- tions of this last remark. 60. Of all the different parts of our con- stitution, there is none more interesting to the 48 OUTLINES OF student of Moral Philosophy than the laws which regulate the Association of Ideas. From the intimate and almost indissoluble combina- tions, which we are thus led to form in infancy and in early youth, may be traced many of our speculative errors ; many of our most powerful principles of action ; many perver- sions of our moral judgment ; and many of those prejudices which mislead us in the con- duct of life. By means of a judicious edu- cation, this susceptibility of the infant mind might be rendered subservient not only to moral improvement, but to the enlargement and multiplication of our capacities of enjoy- ment. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 49 SECTION VII. OF MEMOllV. 61. The theories which attempt to ticcount for the phenomena of Memory, by means of impressions and traces in the braii:. nre en- tirely hypothetical ; and throw no light on the subject which they profess to explain. 62. This faculty appears, indeed, to de- pend much on the state of the body ; as may be inferred from the effects oi ii.toxication, disease, and old age. A collection of facts with respect to these effects, as they are di- versified in different instances, would form a valuable addition to our knowledge, and might lead to important conclusions. 63. On a superficial view of the subject, the original differences among men, in their capa- cities of memory, would seem to be immense. But there is reason for thinking that these dif- ]) 50 OUTLINES OF ferences are commonly overrated ; and that due allowances are not made for the diversity of appearance which the human mind must necessarily exhibit, in this respect ; in conse- quence of the various walks of observation and of study, to which mankind are led, partly by natural propensity, and partly by accidental situation. 64. Independent of any inequalities in the original capacity, there are remarkable va- rieties of memory, which lay the foundation of important distinctions among individuals in point of intellectual character. 65. These varieties arise chiefly from the different modes in which the constituent qua- lities of memory are combined in different in- stances. The perfection of memory is to unite Susceptibility, Retentiveness, and Readiness: but such an vmion is rare ; and any extraordi- nary improvement that is bestowed on one of these qualities is generally purchased at the expence of the others. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 51 SECTION VI 11. OF IMAGINATION. 66. The province of Imagination is to se- lect qualities and circumstances from a variety of different objects ; and, by combining and disposing these, to form a new creation of its own. In this appropriated sense of the word, it coincides with what some authors have called. Creative or Poetical Imagination. 67. This power is not a simple faculty, but results from the combination of several differ- ent ones. The effort, for example, of the painter, in composing an ideal landscape, im- plies conception, which enables him to repre- sent to himself those beautiful scenes in na- ture, out of which his selection is to be made ; — Abstraction, which separates the selected materials from the qualities and circumstances connected with them in the memory ; — and Judgment or Taste, which selects the mate- rials, and directs their combination. 52 OUTLINES OF 68. The nature and province of imagination are most clearly exemplified, in the arts which convey pleasure to the mind by new modifica- tions and combinations of beauties originally perceived by the eye. The operations of ima- gination, in this particular instance, serve to illustrate the intellectual processes, by which the mind deviates from the models presented to it by experience, and forms to itself new and untried objects of pursuit, in those analo- gous but less palpable cases, which fall under the consideration of the moralist. It is in con- sequence of such processes, (which, how little soever they may be attended to, are habitually passing in the thoughts of all men), that hu- man affairs exhibit so busy and various a scene; tending, in one instance, to improvement, and, in another, to decline ; according as our no- tions of excellence and of happiness are just or erroneous. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 5$ SECTION IX. OF .TUDGMENT AND REASONING. 69. Judgment is defined, by the writers on logic, to be an act of the mind, by which one thing is affirmed or denied of another ; — a de- finition, which, although not unexceptionable, is as good as the nature of the subject admits of. 70. In some cases, our judgments are form- ed as soon as the terms of the proposition are understood ; or they result so necessarily from the original constitution of the mind, that we act upon them from our earliest infancy, with- out ever making them an object of reflection. In other cases, they are formed in consequence of a process of thought, consisting of different successive steps. Hence, a distinction of Evi- dence into intuitive and deductive. 54 OUTLINES OF I. OF INTUITIVE EVIDENCE. 71. The most important, if not all the dif- ferent species of intuitive evidence, may be comprehended under the three following heads : (1.) The evidence of axioms. (2.) The evidence of consciousness, of per- ception, and of memory. (3.) The evidence of those fundamental laws of human belief, which form an essential part of our constitution ; and of which our en- tire conviction is implied, not only in all spe- culative reasonings, but in all our conduct as active beings. Of this class, is the evidence for our own personal identity ; for the exist- ence, of the material world ; for the continu- ance of those laws which have been found, in the course of our past experience, to regulate the sviccession of phenomena. Such truths no MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 55 man ever thinks of stating to himself in the form of propositions ; but all our conduct, and all our reasonings, proceed on the supposition that they are admitted. The belief of them is necessary for the preservation of our animal existence ; and it is accordingly coeval with the first operations of the intellect. 72. The attacks of modern sceptics have been chiefly directed against this last descrip- tion of intuitive truths. They have been call- ed .Principles of Cormjiofi Sense, by some late writers, who have undertaken to vindicate their authority. The conclusions of these writers are, on the whole, solid and import- ant : but the vagueness of the expression, Conwion Sense, which is generally employed, in ordinary discourse, in a sense considerably different from that in which it was at first in- troduced into this controversy, has furnished to their opponents, the means of a specious misrepresentation of the doctrine in question ; as an attempt to shelter popular prejudices from a free examination ; and to institute an 56 OUTLINES OF appeal, from the decisions of philosophy, to the voice of the multitude. II. OF DEDUCTIVE EVIDENCE. 73. Notwithstanding the commonly re- ceived doctrine concerning the radical dis- tinction between Intuition and Reasoning, it may be doubted, if the one of these powers be not implied in the other. If it be true, that a perfect demonstration is constituted by a chain of reasoning, in which all the links are connected by intuitive evidence ; it will follow, that the power of reasoning presup- poses the power of intuition. On the other hand, are not the powers of intuition and of memory suixicient to account for those pro- cesses of thought, which conduct the mind by a series of consequences, from premises to a conclusion ? 74. " When the mind (says Locke) per- " ceives the agreement or disagreement of MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 57 " two ideas immediately by themselves, with- " out the intervention of any other, its know- " ledge may be called intuitive. When it " cannot so bring its ideas together, as by " their immediate comparison, and, as it " were, juxtaposition, or application one to " another, to perceive their agreement or dis- " agreement, it is fain, by the intervention " of other ideas, (one, or more, as it hap- " pens), to discover the agreement or dis- " agreement which it searches ; and this is " what we call Reasoning.'" According to these definitions ; supposing the equality of tw o lines A and B to be perceived immediate- ly, in consequence of their coincidence ; the judgment of the mind is intuitive. Suppos- ing A to coincide with B, and B with C ; the relation between A and C is perceived by Rea- soning. « 75. This is certainly not agreeable to com- mon language. The trutli of mathematical axioms has always been supposed to be intui- tively obvious ; and the first of these, accord- 58 OUTLINES OF ing to Euclid's enumeration, affirms ; that if A be equal to C, and B to C ; A and C are equal. 76. Admitting, however, Locke's defini- tion to be just, it might easily be shewn, that the faculty which perceives the relation be- tween A and C, is the same with the faculty which perceives the relation between A and B ; and between B and C. When the rela- tion of equality between A and B has once been perceived, A and B become different names for the same thin";. "&• 77. That the power of reasoning (or, as it has been sometimes called, the Discursive Fa- culty) is implied in the powers of intuition and memory, appears also from an examina- tion of the structure of syllogisms. It is im- possible to conceive an understanding so form- ed, as to perceive the truth of the major and minor propositions, and not to perceive the truth of the conclusion. Indeed, as in this mode of stating an argument, the mind is led MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 59 from universals to particulars, the truth of the conclusion must have been known before the major proposition is formed. 78. Deductive evidence is of two kinds, Demonstrative and Probable. The former relates to necessary, the latter to contingent truths. An accurate examination and compa- rison of these, are of great consequence to all who engage in moral inquiries , But the sub- ject is too extensive to be introduced here. 79. The process of the mind, in discovering media of proof for establishing the truth of doubtful propositions ; and also the process by which we bring new truths to light, is proper- ly called Invention. In this power, remark- able inequalities are observable among differ- ent individuals. In a capacity of understand- ing the reasonings of others, all men seem to be nearly on a level. 80. The word Logic is used by modern writ- ers in two very different senses: 1. To ex- 60 OUTLINES OF press the scholastic art of syllogizing, which is commonly referred to Aristotle for its invent- or. 2. To express that branch of the philoso- phy of the human mind, which has for its ob- ject, to guard us against the various errors to which we are liable in the exercise of our rea- soning powers ; and to assist and direct the inventive faculty in the investigation of truth. The general aim of these two sorts of logic is the same ; and they differ only in the justness of the principles on which they proceed. The inutility of the former is now pretty generally acknowledged ; and it deserves our attention, chiefly, as a curious article in the history of science. The other is still in its infancy ; but many important views have already been open- ed into the subject by Lord Bacon and others. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 61 SECTION X. OF INTELLECTUAL POWERS OR CAPACITIES, FORMED BY PARTICULAR HABITS OF STUDY OR OF BUSINESS. 81. The varieties of intellectual character among men, result from the various possible combinations and modifications of faculties, which, in greater or less degrees, are common to the whole species. Supposing these facul- ties to be originally the same in every indivi- dual ; infinite diversities of genius would ne- cessarily arise, from the different situations into which men are thrown by the accidents of human life. 82. The intellectual habits that are formed by the pursuits of science or of literature, are widely different from those which are produ- ced by the active engagements of business. 62 OUTLINES OF There are other peculiarities of a more delicate nature, which originate from particular studies, and which distinguish the different classes of literary men from each other. The metaphy- sician, the mathematician, the antiquary, the poet, the critic, strengthen, by their respective pursuits, particular faculties and principles : while they suffer others to remain without due cultivation. 83. An examination of the effects produced on the understanding, by different sciences, and by different active professions, would sug- gest many important rules for the improve- ment and enlargement of the mind, and for preserving all its various powers in that just proportion to each other, which constitutes the perfection of our intellectual nature. 84. Quickness ; Acuteness ; Penetration ; Presence of Mind ; Good Sense ; Sagacity ; Comprehension ; Profoundness ; — all express particular characteristics of intellect by which individuals are distinguished from each other ; MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 63 and which present a subject of observation and study, not more interesting to the philosopher, than to those who take an active concern in the business of the workl. — The mental de- fects to which these qualities are respectively opposed, are no less deserving of attention. 85. Nearly connected with these last specu- lations, are those philosophical inquiries which have for their object, to analyze, into their con- stituent principles, the different kinds of in- tellectual ability, which are displayed in the different sciences and arts. Such inquiries not only open a curious and interesting field of disquisition, but have an obvious tendency to lessen that blind admiration of original genius, which is one of the chief obstacles to the im- provement of the arts, and to the progress of knowledge. 64 OUTLINES OF 86. Among the intellectual powers, gra- dually formed by a particular application of our original faculties, the power of Taste is one of the most important. It was formerly treated by metaphysicans as a simple and uncompounded principle of our constitution ; and, notwithstanding the ingenious attempts lately made to analyze it into its competent elements, it continues still to be considered by some as an ultimate fact in the constitu- tion of the human mind. The extensive in- fluence it possesses in such a state of society as ours, not only over the pursuits of those who devote themselves to the study of Litera- ture and of the Fine Arts, but over the en- joyments of every individual who partakes of the general refinement of manners, might jus- tify the allotment of a separate article to an illustration of the intellectual process, by which it is formed. Sucli a digression, how- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 65 ever, would necessarily encroach on other dis- cussions still more closely connected with the object of this First Part of the Course ; and the intimate relation between the Power of Taste and our Moral Principles will furnish another and a more convenient opportunity of resuming the speculation. 87. It is sufficient, at present, to remark, That although the ground-work of Taste must be laid in the original qualities of the mind, yet this power is the slow result of ex- perience, habitually and attentively conver- sant with a particular class of agreeable ob- jects. The instantaneous rapidity of its de- cisions gives it sometimes the appearance of an immediate perception ; — and hence the name which it has borrowed, in the languages of modern Europe, from one of the external senses. The use made in the French tongue of the word Tact, to denote that delicate sense of propriety which enables a man to feel his ivay in the difficult intercourse of po- 66 OUTLINES OF lished society, seems to have been suggested by similar considerations. This power, as well as the other, is evidently an acquired one ; and a comparison of the two might be useful for illustrating the nature and genesis of both. ;moiial philosophy. 67 SECTION XI. OF CERTAIN AUXILIARY FACULTIES AXD PRINCIPLES, ESSENTIAL TO OUR INTELLECTUAL IMPROVEMENT, OR INTIMATELY CONNECTED WITH IT. 88. The form and posture of the human body, and its various organs of perception, have an obvious reference to Man's rational nature ; and are beautifully fitted to encou- rage and facilitate his intellectual improve- ment. A similar remark may be extended to many other parts of our constitution, both external and internal: but there are two, which more particularly claim our attention ; the power of expressing our thoughts by Lan- guage ; and the princip/p of Imitation. 68 OUTLINES OF I. OF LANGUAGE. 89. The connection of this subject with that of the foregoing sections is sufficiently obvi- ous. It is to the use of artificial signs, (§ 49.) that we are indebted for all our general con- clusions; and without it, our knowledge would have been entirely limited to indivi- duals. It is also to the use of artificial signs, that we are indebted for all that part of our information, which is not the immediate re- sult of our own personal experience : and for that transmission of intellectual acquisitions from one race to another, which lays the foun- dation of the progressive improvement of the species. 90. The formation of an artificial lan- guage, (as Dr Reid has remarked), presup- poses the use of natural signs. These con- sist in certain expressions of the countenance, certain gestures of the body, and certain tones of the voice. MORAL I'HILOSOPHY. 69 91. There seems to be, in man, a power of interpreting instinctively some of these ex- pressions. This, indeed, has been disputed of late ; but various considerations might be mentioned, which justify the common opinion upon the subject, when stated with certain corrections and limitations. 92. As ideas multiply, the imperfections of natural language are felt ; and men find it necessary to invent artificial signs, of which the meaning is fixed by m\itual agreement. In proportion as artificial language improves, the language of nature declines ; insomuch, that in such a state of society as ours, it re- quires a great deal of reflection and study to recover the use of it. This study is in a con- siderable degree the foundation of the arts both of the actor and of the orator. 93. Artificial signs may be divided, into those which are addressed to the eye, and those which are addressed to the ear. The latter have formed, among all nations, the ordinary medium of intellectual communication. 70 OUTLINES OF 94. As we have no record of the steps, by which any of the languages spoken among men have arisen ; some writers have employ- ed their ingenuity, in tracing, from the facul- ties of the mind, the origin of the different parts of speech ; and, in illustrating the gra- dual progress of language, resulting from the general progress of society. — Such conjectu- ral speculations concerning the natural ad- vances of the Species, in any particular line of improvement, may be distinguished by the title of Theoretical Histories. 95. The imperfections of those languages, which have originated from popular use, have suggested, to some philosophers, the idea of a language expressly calculated for the pur- poses of science. The failure of the at- tempts hitherto made on this subject, are not decisive against the practicability of such a project. 96. The art of Writing is an important step in the history of language ; and a power- MORAL PHILOSOPHY 71 ful aid to the intellectual progress of the species. 97. The advantages with which it is ac- companied, are wonderfully extended by the art of Printing, which may be justly regard- ed, not only as the happiest of all expedients, for facilitating the intellectual commerce of mankind, but as one of the most important events that have occurred in the history of human affairs. II. OF THE PRINCIPLE OP" IMITATION. 98. Whenever we see any expression, or, in general, any change, in the countenance of another person ; we have a tendency to assume the same expression, or the same change, in our own countenance. Every man is sensible of this, when he looks at an- other in a rage, in a fit of laughter, or in a deep melancholy. Kor is it the visible appearance alone of others, that we have a disposition to imitate. We copy instinctively 72 OUTLINES or the voices of our companions, their tones, their accents, and their modes of pronuncia- tion. 99. This tendency in our nature to imi- tation is attended with important advantages. It seems to be by means of it, that children acquire the use of speech ; and that they learn insensibly, to model their habits, on the appearance and manners of those with whom they are familiarly conversant. 100. As it is in early life, that the principle of imitation is of greatest use to us, so it is in infancy that we have the strongest tendency to indulge it. — It is of this natural tendency, which all men have in some degree, that mi- mics avail themselves ; till, by repeated ef- forts, they acquire a power of carrying it far- ther than they could have done originally : or, rather, perhaps, they only contrive to re- tain through life, a faculty, which, in the case of most men, disappears after the period of childhood. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 73 101. The contagious nature of insanity, of convulsions, of hysteric disorders, of panics, and of all the different kinds of enthusiasm, seems to have an intimate connection with the principle of imitation. To this class of facts, an important addition has lately been made in the course of the philosophical in- quiries which took rise at Paris, in conse- quence of the cures pretended to be effected by means of animal magnetism. TJf OUTLINES OF SECTION XII. OF THE IXTELLECTUAL FACUT.TIES OF MAN, AS CON- TRASTED WITH THE INSTINCTS OF THE BliUTES. 102. That the brutes are under the more immediate guidance of nature, while man is left to regulate, to a great degree, his own destiny, by the exercise of his reason ; is a fact too obvious to admit of dispute. In what manner, indeed, nature operates, in this in- stance, we are perfectly ignorant : but no- thing can be more certain than this, that it is not by a deliberate choice, analgous to what we experience in ourselves, that the lower animals are determined to the pursuit of particular ends ; nor by any process analo- gous to our reason, that they combine means in order to attain them. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 75 103. To that unknown principle, which guides the operations of the brutes, we give the name of Instinct. It is distinguished from Reason by two circumstances: 1. By the uniformity with which it proceeds, in all individuals of the same species ; and, 2. By the unerring certainty with which it performs its office, prior to all experience. 104. But although we do not, in such cases, ascribe reason or art to the brutes, the opera- tions of instinct plainly indicate intelligence in that being by whom they were formed ; and who, by adapting their constitutions so beautifully to the laws of the material world, has evinced an unity of design, which proves that all the different parts of the universe, animate and inanimate, are the workmanship of the same Author. 105. The wisdom of nature, as displayed in the instincts of animals, is more particu- larly conspicuous in those tribes which asso- 76 OUTLINES OF date in political communities ; — as the bee, and the beaver. Here we see animals, who, considered individually, discover but a small degree of sagacity, conspiring together, under the guidance of a blind impulse, in the ac- complishment of effects, astonishing by their magnitude, and by the complicated ingenuity they exhibit. 106. Animals, however, are left to make some small acquisitions, by experience ; as sufficiently appears, in certain tribes, from the sagacity of the old, when contrasted with the ignorance of the young ; and from the effects which may be produced on many of them, by discipline and education. 107. In what, then, does the difference be- tween man and the brutes consist ? Do their faculties differ from each other in degree only ; or is there an essential distinction, be- tween the rational and the animal natures ? MORAL rniLOSOPHY. 77 108. The French philosophers of the Car- tesian school adopted the latter opinion ; and even carried it so far, as to consider the brutes as mere machines. Their successors have, in general, gone into the opposite extreme ; and have employed their ingenuity, in attempting to account for the boasted superiority of man, by accidental circumstances in his bodily or- ganization, or in his external condition. 109. In opposition to these doctrines of mo- dern Materialists, a great variety of consider- ations prove ; that, in respect of our intellect- ual and moral principles, our nature does not admit of comparison with that of any other inhabitant of this globe; the difference be- tween our constitution and theirs, being a dif- ference, not in degree, but in kind. Perhaps, this is the single instance, in which that regu- lar gradation which we, every where else, ob- serve in the universe, fails entirely. — The subject is by far too extensive to be treated in these OufUnes. OUTLINES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. PAPvT II. OF THE ACTIVE AND OF THE MORAL POWERS OF MAN. 110. This part of the subject naturally divides itself into two Chapters : The first re- lates to the Classification and Analysis of our Active and Moral Powers. The second, to the various branches of our Duty. 80 OUTLINES OF CHAP. I. CLASSIFICATION AND ANALYSIS OF OUR ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS. SECTION I. OF THE ACTIVE POWERS IN GENERAL. 111. The word Action is properly applied to those exertions which are consequent on volition ; whether the exertion be made on external objects, or be confined to our mental operations. Thus, we say the mind is active, when engaged in study. In ordinary dis- course, indeed, we are apt to confound toge- ther action and motion. As the operations in the minds of other men escape our notice, we can judge of their activity, only from the sensi- ble effects it produces ; and hence we are led to MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 81 apply the character of iVctivity, to those whose bodily activity is the most remarkable ; and to distinguish mankind into two classes, the Active and the Speculative. — In the pre- sent instance the word Activity is used in its most extensive signification, as applicable to every voluntary exertion. 112. The primary sources of our activity, therefore, are the circumstances that influence the will. Of these, there are some which make a part of our constitution, and which, on that account are called Active principles. Such are. Hunger, Thirst, Curiosity, Ambi- tion, Pity, Resentment. The most important principles of this kind may be referred to the following heads. (1.) Appetites. (2.) Desires. (3.) Affections. (4.) Self-Love. (5.) The Moral Faculty. 82 OUTLINES OF SECTION II. OF OUR ArirETITES. 113. This class of our active principles is distinguished by the following circumstances. (1.) They take their rise from the body, and are common to us with the brutes. (2.) The are not constant but occasional. (3.) They are accompanied with an uneasy sensation, which is strong or weak, in propor- tion to the strength or weakness of the appe- tite. 114. Our appetites are three in number ; Hunger, Thirst, and the appetite of Sex. Of these, two were intended for the preservation of the individual ; the third, for the continu- ance of the species ; and without them, rea- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 83 son would have been insufficient for these im- portant purposes. 115. Our appetites can, with no propriety, be called selfish, for they are directed to their respective objects, as ultimate ends ; and they must all have operated, in the first instance, prior to any experience of the pleasure arising from their gratification. — Self-love, too, is of- ten sacrificed to appetite, when we indulge ourselves in an immediate enjoyment, which we know is likely to be attended with hurtful consequences. 116. Beside our natural appetites, we have many acquired ones. — Such are, an appetite for tobacco, for opium, and for intoxicating li- quors. In general, every thing that stimulates the nervous system, produces a subsequent lan- guor, which gives rise to a desire of repetition. 117- Our occasional propensities to action and to repose are, in many respects, analogous to oiu' appetites. 84 OUTLINES OF SECTION III. OF OUR DESIRES. 118. These are distinguished from our ap- petites by the following circumstances. (1.) They do not take rise from the body. (2.) They do not operate periodically, after certain intervals : and they do not cease upon the attainment of a particular object. 119. The most remarkable active principles belonging to this class are ; (1.) The Desire of Knowledge, or the Prin- ciple of Curiosity. (2.) The Desire of Society. MORAL PHILOSOrHY. 85 (3.) The Desire of Esteem. (4.) The Desire of Power ; or the Principle of Ambition. (5.) The Desire of Superiority ; or the Principle of Emulation. I. THE DESIUE OF KNOWLEDGE. 120. The principle of Curiosity appears, in children, at a very early period, and is commonly proportioned to the degree of ca- pacity they possess. The direction too which it takes, is regulated by nature, according to the order of our wants and necessities ; being confined, in the first instance, exclusively to those properties of material objects, and those laws of the material world, an acquaintance with which is essential to the preservation of our animal existence. In more advanced years, it displays itself, in one way or another, in every individual ; and gives rise to an in- 86 OUTLINES OF finite diversity in their pursuits. Whether this diversity be owing to natural predisposi- tion, or to early education, it is of little con- sequence to determine ; as upon either suppo- sition, a preparation is made for it in the ori- ginal constitution of the mind, combined with the circumstances of our external situation. Its final cause is also sufficiently obvious ; as it is this which gives rise, in the case of indi- viduals, to a limitation of attention and study ; and lays the foundation of all the advantages, which society derives, from the division and subdivision of intellectual labour. 121. The desire of knowledge is not a self- ish principle. As the object of hunger is not happiness, but food ; so the object of curiosity is not happiness, but knowledge. II. THE DESIRE OF SOCIETY. 122. Abstracting from those affections which interest us in the happiness of others. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 87 and from all the advantages which we our- selves derive from the social union, we are led by a natural and instinctive desire, to asso- ciate with our own species. This principle is easily discernible in the minds of children ; and it is common to man with many of the brutes. 123. After experiencing, indeed, the plea- sures of social life ; the influence of habit, and a knowledge of the comforts inseparable from society, contribute greatly to strengthen the instinctive desire : and hence some authors have been induced to display their ingenuity, by disputing its existence. Whatever opi- nion we form on this speculative question, the desire of society is equally entitled to be rank- ed among the natural and universal principles of our constitution. 124. How very powerfully this principle of action operates, appears from the effects of solitude upon the mind. We feel ourselves in an unnatural state ; and, by making compa- 88 OUTLINES OF nions of the lower animals, or by attaching ourselves to inanimate objects, strive to fill up the void of which we are conscious. 125. The connection between the Desire of Society and the Desire of Knowledge is very remarkable. The last of these principles is al- ways accompanied with a wish to impart our information to others ; — insomuch, that it has been doubted, if any man's curiosity would be sufficient to engage him in a course of perse- vering study, if he were entirely cut off from the prospect of social intercourse. In this manner, a beautiful provision is made for a mutual communication, among mankind, of their intellectual attainments. III. THE DESIRE OF ESTEEM. 126. This principle discovers itself, at a very early period, in infants ; who, long be- fore they are able to reflect on the advanta- ges resulting from the good opinion of others. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 89 and even before they acquire the use of speech, are sensibly mortified by any expression of neglect or contempt. It seems, therefore, to be an original principle in our nature ; that is, it does not appear to be resolvable into rea- son and experience, or into any other prin- ciple more general than itself. An additional proof of this is, the very powerful influence it has over the mind ; — an influence more strik- ing than that of any other active principle whatever. Even the love of life daily gives way to the desire of esteem ; and of an esteem, which, as it is only to affect our me- mories, cannot be supposed to interest our self-love. — In what manner, the association of ideas should manufacture, out of the other principles of our constitution, a new prin- ciple stronger than them all, it is difficult to conceive. 127. As our appetites of Hunger and Thirst, though not selfish principles, are yet immediately subservient to the preservation of the individual ; so the desire of Esteem, 90 OUTLINES OF though not a social or benevolent principle, is yet immediately subservient to the good of society. IV. THE DESIKE OF POWER. 128. Whenever we are led to consider ourselves as the authors of any effect, we feel a sensible pride of exultation, in the consci- ousness of Power ; and the pleasure is, in ge- neral, proportioned to the greatness of the ef- fect, compared to the smallness of our exer- tion. 129. The infant, while still on the breast, delights in exerting its little strength upon every object it meets with ; and is mortified, when any accident convinces it of its own imbecillity. The pastimes of the boy are, almost without exception, such as suggest to him the idea of his power : — and the same remark may be extended to the active sports, MORAL THILOSOPHY. 91 and the athletic exercises, of youth and of manhood. 130. As we advance in years, and as our animal powers lose their activity and vigour, we gradually aim at extending our influence over others, by the superiority of fortune and of situation, or by the still more flattering superiority of intellectual endowments : — by the force of our understanding ; by the ex- tent of our information ; by the arts of per- suasion, or the accomplishments of address. What but the idea of power pleases the ora- tor, in the consciousness of his eloquence; when he silences the reason of others by su- perior ingenuity ; bends to his purposes their desires and passions ; and, without the aid of force, or the splendour of rank, becomes the arbiter of the fate of nations ? 131. To the same principle we may trace, in part, the pleasure arising from the disco- very of general theorems. Every such dis- covery puts us in possession of innumerable 92 OUTLINES OF particular truths, or particular facts ; and gives us a ready command of a great stock of knowledge to which we had not access be- fore. The desire of pow^er, therefore, comes, in the progress of reason and experience, to act as an auxiliary to our instinctive desire of knowledge. 132. The idea of power is, partly at least, the foundation of our attachment to property. It is not enough for us to have the use of an object. We desire to have it completely at our owii disposal ; without being responsible to any person whatever. 133. Avarice is a particular modification of the desire of power ; arising from the va- rious functions of money in a commercial country. Its influence as an active principle is much strengthened by habit and associa- tion. 134. The love of liberty proceeds, in part, from the same source ; from a desire of being MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 93 able to do whatever is agreeable to our own inclination. Slavery mortifies us, because it limits our power. 135. Even the love of tranquillity and re- tirement has been resolved by Cicero into the same principle. " Multi autem et sunt, et " fuerunt, qui eam, quam dico, Tranquillita- " tem expetentes, a negotiis publicis se re- " moverint, ad otiumque perfugerint. His " idem propositum fuit, quod regibus ; ut ne " qua re egerunt, ne cui parerent, libertate " uterentur ; cujus proprium est, sic vivere, " ut velis. Quare, cum hoc commune sit po- " tentiae cupidorum cum iis, quos dixi, otio- " sis ; alteri se adipisci id posse arbitrantur, " si opes magnas habeant ; alteri, si content! " sint et suo, et parvo." 136. The idea of power is also, in some degree, the foundation of the pleasure of Vir- tue. We love to be at liberty to follow our own inclinations, without being subjected to the controul of a superior ; but this alone is 94 OUTLINES OF not sufficient to our happiness. When we are led, by vicious habits, or by the force of passion, to do what reason disapproves, we are sensible of a mortifying subjection to the in- ferior principles of our nature, and feel our 'own littleness and weakness. A sense of free- dom and independence, elevation of mind, and the pride of virtue, are the natural senti- ments of the man, who is conscious of being able, at all times, to calm the tumults of pas- sion, and to obey the cool suggestions of duty and honour. V. THE DESIRE OF SUPERIORITY. 137. Emulation has been sometimes class- ed with the Affections : but it seems more properly to fall under the definition of our Desires. It is, indeed, frequently accompa- nied with ill-will towards our rivals : but it is the desire of superiority which is the active principle ; and the malevolent affection is only a concomitant circumstance. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 95 138. A malevolent affection is not even a 7iecessary concomitant of the desire of supe- riority. It is possible, surely, to conceive (al- though the case may happen but rarely,) that Emulation may take place betv/een men, who are united by the most cordial friendship ; and without a single sentiment of ill-will disturb- ing their harmony. 139. When Emulation is accompanied with malevolent affection, it assumes the name of Envy. The distinction between these two principles of action is accurately stated by Dr Butler. " Emulation is merely the desire of " superiority over others with whom we com- " pare ourselves. To desire the attainment " of this superiority, by the particular means " of others being brought down below our " own level, is the distinct notion of Envy. " From whence it is easy to see, that the real " end, which the natural passion, Emulation, " and which the unlawful one, Envy, aims at, " is exactly the same ; and, consequently, that " to do mischief is not the end of Envy, but 96 OUTLINES OF " merely the means it makes use of to attain " its end." 140. Some faint symptoms of Emulation may be remarked among the lower animals ; but the effects it produces among them are perfectly insignificant. In our own race, it operates in an infinite variety of directions, and is one of the principal springs of human improvement. 141. As we have artificial appetites, so we have also artificial desires. Whatever con- duces to the attainment of any object of na- tural desire, is itself desired on account of its subserviency to this end ; and frequently comes, in process of time, to acquire, in our estimation, an intrinsic value. It is thus, that wealth becomes, with many, an ultimate ob- ject of pursuit ; although it is undoubtedly valued at first, merely as the means of attaining other objects. In like manner, men are led MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 97 to desire dress, equipage, retinue, furniture, on account of the estimation in which they are supposed to be held by the public. Such desires have been called, by Dr Hutcheson, Secondary Desires. Their origin is easily ex- plicable, on the principle of Association. G 98 OUTLINES OF SECTION IV. OF OUR AlFECTIONS. 142. Under this title are comprehended all those active principles, whose direct and ultimate object is the communication either of enjoyment or of suffering, to any of our fellow-creatures. According to this defini- tion, Resentment, Hevenge, Hatred, belong to the class of our affections, as well as Gra--^ titude or Pity. Hence a distinction of the af- fections into Benevolent and IMalevolent. I. OF THP; BENEVOLENT AFFECTIONS. 143. Our Eenevolent affections are various; and it would not, perhaps, be easy to enu- merate them completely. The Parental MORAL THILOSOPHY. 99 and the Filial affections, — the affections of Kindred, — Love, — Friendship, — Patriotism. —Universal Benevolence, — G ratitude, — Pity to the distressed,— are some of the most im- portant. Besides these, there are peculiar benevolent affections, excited by those moral qualities in other men, which render them either amiable, or respectable, or objects of admiration. 144. In the foregoing enumeration, it is not to be understood, that all the benevolent affections particularly specified, are stated as original principles, or ultimate facts in our constitution. On the contrary, there can be little doubt, that several of them may be analyzed into the same general principle dif- ferently modified, according to the circum- stances in which it operates. This, however, (notwithstanding the stress which has been sometimes laid upon it), is chiefly a question of arrangement. Whether we suppose these principles to be all ultimate facts, or some of them to be resolvable into other facts more 100 OUTLINES OF general ; they are equally to be regarded as constituent parts of human nature ; and, up- on either supposition, we have equal reason to admire the wisdom with which that na- ture is adapted to the situation in which it is placed. — The laws which regulate the ac- quired perceptions of Sight, are surely as much a part of our frame, as those which re- gulate any of our original perceptions ; and, although they require, for their develope- ment, a certain degree of experience and ob- servation, in the individual ; the uniformity of the result shews, that there is nothing ar- bitrary nor accidental in their origin. 145. The question, indeed, concerning the origin of our different affections, leads to some curious disquisitions ; but is of very subordi- nate importance to those inquiries, which re- late to their nature, and laws, and uses. In many philosophical systems, however, it seems to have been considered as the most interest- ing subject of discussion connected with this part of the human constitution. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 101 146. To treat, in detail, of the nature, laws, and uses of our benevolent affections, is obviously inconsistent with the brevity of a treatise, confined by its plan, to a statement of definitions and divisions, and of such re- marks as are necessary for explaining the arrangement on which it proceeds. The enumeration already mentioned, (§ 143.), suggests an order according to which this subject may be treated in a course of lec- tures on JMoral Philosophy. What follows is equally applicable to all the various prin- ciples which come under the general descrip- tion. 147. The exercise of all our kind affections is accompanied with an agreeable feeling or emotion. So much indeed, of our happi- ness is derived from this source, that those authors, whose object is to furnish amuse- ment to the mind, avail themselves of these affections as one of the chief vehicles of plea- sure. Hence, the principal charm of trage- 102 OUTLINES OF dy, and of every other species of pathetic composition. How far it is of use, to sepa- rate, in this manner, " the luxury of pity" from the opportunities of active exertion, may perhaps be doubted. 148. The pleasures of kind affection are not confined to the virtuous. They mingle also with our criminal indulgences ; and often mislead the young and thoughtless, by the charms they impart to vice and to folly. 149. Even when these affections are dis- appointed in the attainment of their objects, there is a degree of pleasure mixed with the pain : — and sometimes the pleasure greatly predominates. 150. The final cause of the agreeable emo- tion connected with the exercise of Benevo- lence, in all its various modes, was evidently to induce us to cultivate, with peculiar care. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 103 a class of our active principles so immediate- ly subservient to the happiness of human so- ciety. 151. Notwithstanding, however, the plea- sure arising from the indulgence of the bene- volent affections ; these affections have no- thing selfish in their origin — as has been fully demonstrated by different writers. This conclusion, although contrary to the systems of many philosophers, both ancient and mo- dern, is not only agreeable to the obvious ap- pearance of the fact ; but is strongly confirm- ed by the analogy of the other active powers already considered. 152. We have found, that the preservation of the individual, and tlie continuation of the species, are not intrusted to Self-love and Reason alone ; but that w^e are endowed with various appetites, which, w^ithout any reflection on our part, impel us .to tlieir re- spective objects. We have also found, witli 104 OUTLINES OF ~ respect to the acquisition of knowledge, (on which the perfection of the individual, and the improvement of the species, essentially depend) ; that it is not entrusted solely to Self-love and Benevolence ; but that we are prompted to it by the implanted principle of Curiosity. It farther appeared, that, in ad- dition to our sense of duty, another incentive to v/orthy conduct is provided in the desire of Esteem, which is not only one of our most powerful principles of action, but continues to operate in full force, to the last moment of our being. Now, as men were plainly intended to live in society, and as the social union could not subsist, without a mutual in- terchange of good offices ; would it not be reasonable to expect, agreeably to the ana- logy of our nature, that so important an end would not be intrusted solely to tlie slow de- ductions of Reason, or to the metaphysical refinements of Self-love ; but that some provi- sion would be made for it in a particular class of active principles, which might operate, MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 105 like our appetites and desires, independently of our reflection ? To say this of Parental Af- fection or of Pity, is saying nothing more in their favour, than what was affirmed of Hun- ger and Thirst ; that they prompt us to par- ticular objects, without any reference to our own enjoyment. II. OF THE MALEVOLENT AFFECTIONS. 153. The names which are given to these, in common discourse, are various ; Hatred, Jealousy, Envy, Revenge, Misanthropy ; — but it may be doubted, if there be any prin- ciple of this kind, implanted by nature, in the mind, excepting the principle of Resentment ; the others being grafted on this stock, by our erroneous opinions and criminal habits. 154. Resentment has been distinguished into Instinctive and Deliberate. The former operates, in man, exactly as in the lower ani- 106 OUTLINES OF mals ; and was plainly intended to guard us against sudden violence, in cases where reason would come too late to our assistance. This species of Resentment subsides, as soon as we are satisfied that no injury was intended. 155. Deliberate Resentment is excited only by intentional injury ; and, therefore, im- plies a sense of justice, or of moral good and evil. 156. The Resentment excited by an injury offered to anotlier person, is properly called Indignation. In both cases the principle of action seems to be fundamentally the same ; and to have for its object, not the communi- cation of suffering to a sensitive being, but the punishment of injustice and cruelty. 157. As all the benevolent affections are ac- companied with pleasant emotions ; so all the malevolent affections are sources of pain and disquiet. This is true even of Resentment ; MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 107 how justly soever it may be roused by the injurious conduct of others. 158. In the foregoing review of our active powers, no mention has been made of our Pas- sions. The truth is, that this word does not, in strict propriety, belong exclusively to any one class of these principles ; but is applicable to all of them, when they are suffered to pass the bounds of moderation. In such cases, a sensible agitation or commotion of the body is produced ; our reason is disturbed ; we lose, in some measure, the power of self-command, and are hurried to action by an almost irresist- ible impulse. Ambition, the desire of Fame, Avarice, Compassion, Love, Gratitude, Re- sentment, Indignation ; may all, in certain circumstances, be entitled to this appellation. When we speak of ^j«*.s«o?2 in general, we com- monly mean the passion of Resentment ; pro- 108 OUTLINES OF bably because this affection disturbs the rea- son more, and leaves us less the power of self- government, than any other active principle of our nature. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 109 SECTION V. OF SELF-LOVE. 159. The constitution of man, if it were composed merely of the active principles hi- therto mentioned, would be analogous to that of the brutes. His reason, however, renders his nature and condition, on the whole, essen- tially different from theirs. 160. They are incapable of looking for- ward to consequences, or of comparing toge- ther the different gratifications of which they are susceptible ; and accordingly, as far as we are able to perceive, they yield to every present impulse. But man is able to take a comprehensive survey of his various prin- ciples of action ; and to form a plan of con- duct for the attainment of his favourite ob- 110 OUTLINES OF jects. Every such plan implies a power of refusing occasionally to particular active prin- ciples, the gratification which they demand. 161, According to the particular active principle which influences habitually a man's conduct, his character receives its denomina- tion of Covetous, Ambitious, Studious, or Voluptuous ; and his conduct is more or less systematical, as he adheres to his general plan with steadiness or inconstancy. 162. A systematical steadiness in the pur- suit of a particular end, while it is necessary for the complete gratification of our ruling pas- sion, is far more favourable to the general im- provement of the mind, than the dissipation of attention resulting from an undecided choice, among the various pursuits which human life presents to us. Even the systematical volup- tuary is able to command a much greater va- riety of sensual indulgences, and to continue them to a much more advanced age, than the MORAL PHILOSOPHY. Ill thoughtless profligate ; and, how low soever the objects may be which occupy his thoughts, they seldom fail, by engaging them habi- tually in one direction, to give a certain de- gree of cultivation to his intellectual facul- ties. 163. The only exception, perhaps, which can be mentioned to the last remark, is in the case of those men Vv^hose leading principle of action is Vanity ; and who, as their rule of conduct is borrowed from without, must, in consequence of this very circumstance, be per- petually wavering and inconsistent in their pursuits. — Accordingly, it will be found, that such men, although they have frequently per- formed splendid actions, have seldom risen to eminence in any one particular career ; unless, when, by a rare concurrence of accidental cir- cumstances, this career has been steadily pointed out to them through the whole of their lives, by public opinion. 112 OUTLINES OF 164. A systematical conduct in life, inva- riably directed to certain objects, is more fa- vourable to happiness, than one which is influ- enced merely by occasional inclination and appetite. Even the man who is decidedly and uniformly unprincipled, is free of much of the disquiet which disturbs the tranquillity of those, whose characters are more mixed, and more inconsistent. 165. There is another, and very import- ant respect, in which the nature of man dif- fers from that of the brutes. He is able to avail himself of his past experience, in avoid- ing those enjoyments, which he knows will be succeeded by suffering ; and in submit- ting to lesser evils, which he knows are to be instrumental in procuring him a greater ac- cession of good. He is able, in a word, to form the general notion of Happiness, and to deliberate about the most effectual means of attaining it. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 113 166. It is implied in the very idea of Hap- piness, that it is a desirable object ; and there- fore, Self-love is an active principle very dif- ferent from those which have been hitherto considered. These, for aught we know, may be the effect of arbitrary appointment ; and they have, accordingly, been called implanted principles. The desire of happiness may be called a ratio7ial principle of action ; being peculiar to a rational nature, and inseparably connected with it. 167. In prefixing to this section the title of Self-love, the ordinary language of modern philosophy has been followed. The expres- sion, however, is exceptionable ; as it sug- gests an analogy (where there is none in fact) between that regard, which every rational be- ing must necessarily have to his own happi- ness, and those benevolent affections which attach us to our fellow-creatures. — The simi- larity, too, between the words. Self-love and Selfishness, has introduced much confusion into ethical disquisitions. II 114 OUTLINES OF 168. The word Selfishness, is always used in an unfavourable sense ; and hence, some authors have been led to suppose, that vice consists in an excessive regard to our own happiness. It is remarkable, however, that, although we apply the epithet selfish to ava- rice, and to low and private sensuality, we never apply it to the desire of knowledge, or to the pursuits of virtue, which are certainly sources of more exquisite pleasure than Riches or Sensuality can bestow. 169. The truth will probably be found, upon examination, to be this ; that the word Selfishness, when applied to a pursuit, has no reference to the motive from which the pursuit proceeds, but to the effect it has on the conduct. Neither our animal appetites, nor avarice, nor curiosity, nor the desire of moral improvement, arise from Self-love : but some of these active principles disconnect us with society more than others ; and conse- quently, though they do not indicate a great- er regard for our own happiness, they betray MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 115 a greater unconcern for the happiness of our neighbours. The pursuits of the miser have no mixture whatever of the social affections : On the contrary, they continually lead him to state his own interest in opposition to that of other men. The enjoyments of the sen- sualist all expire within his own person : and, therefore, whoever is habitually occupied in the search of them, must of necessity neglect the duties which he owes to mankind. It is otherwise with the desire of knowledge, which is always accompanied with a strong- desire of social communication ; and with the love of moral excellence, which, in its practi- cal tendency, coincides so remarkably with Benevolence, that many authors have at- tempted to resolve the one principle into the other. 170. That the word Selfishness is by no means synonymous with a regard to our own happiness, appears farther from this, that the blame we bestow on those pursuits which are commonly called selfish, is founded, partlyy 116 OUTLINES OF on the sacrifice they imply of our true inte- rest, to the inferior principles of our nature. When we see, for example, a man enslaved by his animal appetites ; so far from consider- ing him as under the influence of an exces- sive self-love, we pity and despise him for neglecting the higher enjoyments which are placed within his reach. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 117 SECTION VI. OF THE MORAL FACULTY. ARTICLE FIRST. OKNERAL OBSERVATIONS ON THE MORAL FACULTY ; TEND- ING CHIEFLY TO SHEW, THAT IT IS AN ORIGINAL PRIN- CIPLE OF OUR NATURE, AND NOT RESOLVABLE INTO ANY OTHER PRINCIPLE OR PRINCIPLES MORE SIMPLE. 171. The facts alluded to in the last pa- ragraph of the foregoing section, have led some philosophers to conclude, that Virtue is merely a matter of prudence, and that a sense of duty is but another name for a ra- tional self-love. This view of the subject was far from being unnatural : for we find, that these tv, o principles, in general, lead to the same course of action ; and we have every reason to believe, that if our know- 118 OUTLINES OF ledge of the universe were more extensive, they would be found to do so, in all instances whatever. 172. That we have, however, a sense of duty, which is not resolvable into a regard to our happiness, appears from various consider- ations. (1.) There are, in all languages, words equivalent to Duty and to Interest, which men have constantly distinguished in their signification. They coincide, in general, in their applications ; but they convey very dif- ferent ideas. (2.) The emotions arising from the con- templation of what is right or wi'ong in con- duct, are different, both in degree and in kind, from those which are produced by a calm regard to our own happiness. This is particularly remarkable in the emotions ex- cited by the moral conduct of others ; for such is the influence of self-deceit, that few MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 119 men judge with perfect fairness of their own actions. The emotions excited by charac- ters exhibited in histories and in novels, are sometimes still more powerful than what we experience from similar qualities displayed in the circle of our acquaintance ; because the judgment is less apt to be warped by partiality or by prejudice. The representa- tions of the stage, however, afford the most favourable of all opportunities for observing their effects. As every species of Enthu- siasm operates most forcibly when men are collected in a crowd, our moral feelings are exhibited on a larger scale in the theatre than in the closet. And accordingly, the slightest hint suggested by the poet, raises to transport the passions of the audience ; and forces involuntary tears from men of the greatest reserve, and the most correct sense of propriety. (3.) Although philosophers have shewn, that a sense of duty, and an enlightened re- gard to our own happiness, conspire, in most 120 OUTLINES OF instances, to give the same direction to our conduct, so as to put it beyond a doubt, that, even in this world, a virtuous life is true wis- dom, yet this is a truth by no means obvious to the common sense of mankind, but deduced from an extensive view of human affairs, and an accurate investigation of the remote conse- quences of our different actions. It is from experience and reflection, therefore, that we learn the tendency of virtue to advance our worldly prosperity ; and, consequently, the great lessons of morality, which are obvious to the capacity of all mankind, cannot have been suggested to them merely by a regard to their own interest. (4.) The same conclusion is strongly con- firmed by the early period of life at which our moral judgments make their appearance ; — long before children are able to form the general notion of happiness, and indeed in the very infancy of their reason. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 121 173. In order to elude the force of some of the foregoing arguments, it has been sup- posed, that the rules of morality were, in the first instance, brought to light by the saga- city of philosophers and politicians ; and that it is only in consequence of the influence of education, that they appear to form an origi- nal part of the human constitution. — The di- versity of opinions among different nations, with respect to the morality of particular ac- tions, has been considered as a strong confir- mation of this doctrine. 174. But the power of education, although great, is confined within certain limits ; for it is by co-operating with the natural prin- ciples of the mind, that it produces it effects. Nay, this very susceptibility of education, which is acknowledged to belong universally to the race, presupposes the existence of cer- tain principles which are common to all man- kind. 122 OUTLINES OF 175. The influence of education, in diver- sifying the appearances which human nature exhibits, depends on that law of our constitu- tion, which was formerly called the Associa- tion of Ideas : And this law supposes, in every instance, that there are opinions and feelings essential to the human frame, by a combina- tion with which, external circumstances lay hold of the mind, and adapt it to its accident- al situation. 176. Education may vary, in particular cases, the opinions of individuals with respect to the beautiful and the sublime. But educa- tion could not create our notions of Beauty or Deformity, of Grandeur or Meanness. In like manner, education may vary our senti- ments with respect to particular actions ; but could not create our notions of llight and Wrong, of Merit and Demerit. 177. The historical facts which have been alleged to prove, that the moral judgments of mankind are entirely factitious, will be MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 123 found, upon examination, to be either the effects of misrepresentation ; or to lead to a concUision directly the reverse of what has been drawn from them :— proper allowance being made, 1*/ For the different circumstan- ces of mankind in different periods of society ; — 2f//y, For the diversity of their speculative opinions ; — and, Sclly, For the different moral import of the same action, under different systems of external behaviour. 178. All these doctrines, how erroneous so- ever, have been maintained by writers not unfriendly to the interests of morality. But some licentious moralists have gone much far- ther, and have attempted to shew, that the motives of all men are fundamentally the same ; and that what we commonly call Vir- tue is mere Hypocrisy. 179. The disagreeable impression, which such representations of human nature leave on the mind, affords a sufficient refutation of their truth. If there be really no essential 124 OUTLINES OF distinction between virtue and vice, whence is it, that we conceive one class of qualities to be more excellent and meritorious than ano- ther ? Why do we consider Pride, or Vanity, or Selfishness, to be less worthy motives for our conduct, than disinterested Patriotism, or Friendship, or a determined adherence to what we believe to be our duty ? Why does our species appear to us less amiable in one set of philosophical systems than in ano- ther ? 180. It has been a common error among licentious moralists, to confound the question concerning the actual attainments of man- kind, with the question concerning the rea- lity of moral distinctions ; and to substitute a satire on vice and folly, instead of a philoso- phical account of the principles of our con- stitution. Admitting the picture which has been sometimes drawn of the real depravity of the world to be a just one ; the gloom and dissatisfaction which it leaves on the mind, are sufficient to demonstrate, that we are form- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 125 ed with the love and admiration of moral excellence, and that this is enjoined to us, as the law of our nature. " Hypocrisy it- " self," (as Rochefoucault has remarked), " is " an homage which vice renders to virtue." 1^6 OUTLINES OF SECTION VI. OF THE MORAL FACULTY. ARTICLE SECOND. ANALYSIS OF OUR MORAL PERCEPTIONS AND EMOTIONS. 181. After establishing the universality of moral perception, as an essential part of the human constitution, the next question that occurs, is, how our notions of Right and Wrong are formed ? Are we to refer them to a particular principle in our nature, appro- priated to the perception of these qualities, as our external senses are appropriated to the perception of the qualities of matter ? — or are they perceived by the same intellectual power which discovers truth in the abstract sciences ? — or are they resolvable into otlier MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 127 notions still more simple and general than themselves ? All these opinions have been maintained by authors of eminence. In order to form a judgment on the point in dispute, it is necessary to analyze the state of our minds, when we are spectators of any good or bad ac- tion performed by another person ; or when we reflect on the actions performed by our- selves. On such occasions, we are conscious of three different things. (1.) The perception of an action as Kight or Wrong. (2.) An emotion of pleasure or of pain ; varying in its degree, according to the acute- ness of our moral sensibility. (3.) A perception of the merit or demerit of the agent. 128 OUTLINES OF I. OF THE PERCEPTION OF RIGHT AND WRONG. 182. The controversy concerning the origin of our moral ideas, took its rise in modern times in consequence of the writings of Mr Hobbes. According to him, we approve of virtuous ac- tions, or of actions beneficial to society, from self-love; as we know, that whatever promotes theinterest of society, has, on that very account, an indirect tendency to promote our own. — He farther taught, that, as it is to the institution of government we are indebted for all the com- forts and the confidence of social life, the laws which the civil magistrate enjoins are the ul- timate standards of morality. 183. Dr Cudworth, who, in opposition to the system of JMr Hobbes, first shewed in a satisfactory manner, that our ideas of Right and AVrong are not derived from positive law ; referred the origin of these ideas to MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 129 the power which distinguishes truth from falsehood : and it became, for some time, the fashionable language among moralists to say, that virtue consisted, not in obedience to the law of a superior, but in a conduct conformable to Reason. 184. At the time that Cudworth wrote, no accurate classification had been attempted, of the principles of the human mind. His account of the office of reason, accordingly, in enabling us to perceive the distinction be- tween right and wrong, passed without cen- sure, and was understood merely to imply, that there is an eternal and immutable dis- tinction between right and wrong, no less than between truth and falsehood ; and that both these distinctions are perceived by our rational powers, or by those powers which raise us above the brutes. , 185. The publication of I^ocke's Essay introduced into this part of science, a preci- 130 OUTLINES OF sion of expression unknown before ; and taught philosophers to distinguish a variety of powers which liad formerly been very generally confounded. With these great merits, however, his work has capital defects ; and, perhaps, in no part of it are these de- fects more important, than in the attempt he has made to deduce the origin of our know- ledge entirely from sensation and reflection. These, according to him, are the sources of all our simple ideas ; and the only power that the mind possesses, is to perform certain operations of Analysis, Combination, Compa- rison, &c. on the materials with which it is thus supplied. 186. This system led Mr Locke to some dangerous opinions, concerning the nature of moral distinctions ; which he seems to have considered as the offspring of Educa- tion and Fashion. Indeed, if the words Right and Wrong neither express simple ideas, nor relations discoverable by reason, it MORAI, PHILOSOrHY. 131 will not be found easy to avoid adopting this conclusion. 187. In order to reconcile Locke's account of the origin of our ideas, with the immutabi- lity of moral distinctions, different theories were proposed concerning the nature of vir- tue. According to one, for example, it was said to consist in a conduct conformable to the Fitness of things : According to another, in a conduct conformable to Truth. — The great object of all these theories may be con- sidered as the same ; — to remove Right and Wrong from the class of simple ideas, and to resolve moral rectitude, into a conformity with some relation perceived by reason or the understanding. 188. Dr Hutcheson saw clearly the va- nity of these attempts ; and hence he was led, in compliance with the language of Locke's philosophy, to refer the origin of our moral ideas to a particular power of ])erception, to which he gave the name of 132 OUTLINES OF the Moral Sense. " All the ideas, (says he), " or the materials of our reasoning or judging, " are received by some immediate powers of " perception, internal or external, which we " may call senses. Reasoning or intellect " seems to raise no new species of ideas, but " to discover or discern the relations of those *' received." 189- According to this system, as it has been commonly explained, our perceptions of right and wrong are impressions, which our minds are made to receive from particular actions ; similar to the relishes and aversions given us for particular objects of the external or internal senses. 190. From the hypothesis of a moral sense, various sceptical conclusions have been de- duced by later writers. The words Right and Wrong, it has been alleged, signify nothing in the objects themselves to which they are applied, any more than the words sweet and bitter, pleasant and painful ; but MO UAL PHiLOSOPHV. 133 only certain effects in the mind of the spec- tator. As it is improper, therefore, (accord- ing to the doctrines of modern philosophy), to say of an object of taste that it is sweet ; or of heat, that it is in the fire ; so it is equal- ly improper, to say of actions, that they are right or wrong. It is absurd to speak of mo- rality as a thing independent and unchange- able : inasmuch as it arises from an arbitrary relation between our constitution and particu- lar objects. 191. In order to avoid these supposed con- sequences of Dr Hutcheson's philosophy, an attempt has been made by some later writers, in particular by Dr Price, to revive the doc- trines of Dr Cudworth, and to prove, that moral distinctions, being perceived by reason or the understanding, are equally immutable Avith all other kinds of truth. 192. This is the most important question that can be stated, with respect to the theory of morals. The obscurity in which it is in- 134 OUTLINES OF volved arises chiefly from the use of indefinite and ambiguous terms. 193. That moral distinctions are perceived by a sense, is implied in the definition of a sense which Dr Hutcheson has given, (§ 188.): provided it be granted, (as Dr Price has done explicitly), that the words Right and Wrong express simple ideas, or ideas incapable of analysis. 194. It may be farther observed, in justi- fication of Dr Hutcheson, that the sceptical consequences deduced from his supposition of a moral sense, do not necessarily result from it. Unfortunately, most of his illustra- tions were taken from the secondary quali- ties of matter, which, since the time of Des Cartes, philosophers have been, in general, accustomed to refer to the mind, and not to the external object. But if we suppose our perceptior of Right and Wrong to be analo- gous to the perception of Extension and Fi- gure, and other primary qualities ; the reality iMOKAL I'HILOSOrHY. 135 and immutability of moral distinction seems to be placed on a foundation, sufficiently satis- factory to a candid inquirer, (§ 31. and 32.) 195. The definition, however, of a sense, which Hutcheson has given, is, by far, too ge- neral, and was plainly suggested to him by Locke's account of the origin of our ideas, (§ 185.) The words Cause and Effect, Du- ration, Number, Equality, Identity, and ma- ny others, express simple ideas, as well as the words Right and Wrong ; and yet it would surely be absurd to ascribe each of them to a particular power of perception. — Notwithstanding this circumstance, as the expression Moi'al Sense has now the sanction of use, and as, when properly explained, it cannot lead to any bad consequences, it may be still retained, without inconvenience, in ethical disquisitions. 196. To what part of our constitution, then, shall we ascribe the origin of the ideas of Right and Wrong ? Price says, — to the Un- 136 OUTLINES OF derstanding ; and endeavours to shew, in op- position to Locke and his followers, that "the " power which understands, or the faculty " that discerns truth, is a source of new " ideas." 197. This controversy turns chiefly on the meaning of words. The origin of our ideas of right and wrong, is manifestly the same with that of the other simple ideas already mentioned ; and whether it be referred to the understanding or not, seems to be a matter of mere arrangement ; provided it be granted, that the words Right and Wrong express qualities of actions, and not merely a power of exciting certain agreeable or disagreeable emotions in our minds. 198. It may perhaps obviate some objec- tions against the language of Cudworth and Price, to remark, that the word Reason is used in senses which are extremely different. Sometimes to express the whole of those powers which elevate man above the brutes. MORAL PHILOSOrHV. 137 and constitute his rational nature ; — more especially, perhaps, his intellectual powers. Sometimes to express the power of deduc- tion or argumentation. The former is the sense in which the word is used in common discourse ; and it is in this sense that it seems to be employed by those writers wiio refer to it the origin of our moral ideas. Their antagonists, on the other hand, under- stand, in general, by Reason, the power of de- duction or argumentation ; an use of the word which is not unnatural, from the simi- larity between the words Reason and Rea- soning, but w^hich is not agreeable to its or- dinary meaning. " No hypothesis (says JDr " Campbell) hitherto invented, hath shewn " that, by means of the discursive faculty, " without the aid of any other mental power, ** we could ever obtain a notion of either the " beautiful or the good*." The remark is undoubtedly true ; and may be applied to ' Philosophy of Rhetoric, vol. i. page 201. 138 OUTLINES OF all tiiose systems which ascribe to Reason the origin of our moral ideas, if the expres- sions, Reason and Discursive Faculty, be used as synonymous. But if the word Reason be used in a more general sense, to denote mere- ly our rational and intellectual nature ; there does not seem to be much impropriety in a- scribing to it the origin of those simple no- tions, which are not excited in the mind by the immediate operation of the senses ; but which arise in consequence of the exercise of the intellectual powers upon their various ob- jects. 199- A variety of intuitive judgments might be mentioned, involving simple ideas, which it is impossible to trace to any origin, but to the power which enables us to form these judgments. Thus, it is surely an intui- tive truth, that the sensations of which I am conscious, and all those I remember, belong to one and the same being, which I call myself. Here is an intuitive judgment involving the simple idea of Identity.-— In like manner, the MORAL rniLOSOPHY. 139 changes which I perceive in the universe im- press me with a conviction that some cause must have operated to produce them. Here is an intuitive judgment, involving the simple idea of Causation. — When we consider the ad- jacent angles made by a straight line standing upon another, and perceive that their sum is equal to two right angles, the judgment we form involves the simple idea of Equality. — To say, therefore, that Keason or the Under- standing is a source of new ideas, is not so exceptionable a mode of speaking as has been sometimes supposed. According to Locke, Sense furnishes our ideas, and Reason perceives their agreements or disagreements. But the truth is, that these agreements and disagreements are, in many instances, simple ideas, of which no analysis can be given ; and of which the origin must therefore be refer- red to Reason, according to Locke's own doc- trine. 200. The opinion 'we form, however, on this point, is of little moment, provided it be 140 OUTLINES OF granted, that tlie words Right and Wrong- express qualities of actions. When I say of an act of justice that it is right ; do I mean merely that the act excites pleasure in my mind, as a particular colour pleases my eye, in consequence of a relation which it bears to my organ ; or do I mean to assert a truth which is as independent of my constitution, as the equality of the three angles of a tri- angle to two right angles ? Scepticism may be indulged in both cases, about mathemati- cal and about moral truth : but in neither case, does it admit of a refutation by argu- ment. 201. The immutability of moral distinc- tions has been called in question, not only by sceptical writers ; but by some philoso- phers who have adopted their doctrine, with the pious design of magnifying the perfec- tions of the Deity. Such authors certainly do not recollect, that what they add to his power and majesty, they take away from his mo- MOllAL PHILOSOPHY. 141 ral attributes ; for if moral distinctions be not immutable and eternal, it is absurd to speak of the goodness or of the justice of God. II. OF THE AGREEABLK AND DISAGREEABLE EMOTIONS ARISIXG FROM THE PERCEI'TION OF WHAT IS RIGHT AND Wr.ONG IN' CONDUCT. 202. It impossible to behold a good ac- tion, without being conscious of a benevolent affection, either of love or of respect, to- wards the agent ; and consequently, as all our benevolent affections include an affreeable feeling, every good action must be a source of pleasure to the spectator. Beside this, other agreeable feelings, of order, of utility, of peace of mind, &c. come, in process of time, to be associated with the general idea of virtuous conduct. 203. Tliose qualities in good actions, which excite agreeable feelings in the mind of the 14)2 OUTLINES OF spectator, form Avliat some moralists have call- ed the Beauty of virtue. 204. All this may be applied, mntatifi mu- tandis, to explain what is meant by the De- formity of Vice. 205. Our perception of moral beauty and deformity is plainly distinguishable from our perception of actions as right or wrong : But the distinction has been too little attended to by philosophers. — Among the moderns, in particular, some have confined their atten- tion almost solely to our perception of actions as right or wrong ; and have thereby render- ed their works abstract and uninteresting. Others, by dwelling exclusively on our per- ception of Moral Beauty and Deformity, have been led into enthusiasm and declamation, and have furnished licentious moralists with a pretext for questioning the immutability of moral distinctions. 206. The emotions of pleasure and of pain MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 14-3 arising from the contemplation of moral beau- ty and deformity, are so much more exquisite than any that are produced by the percep- tion of material forms, that some philosophers have held, that the words Beauty and Subli- mity express, in their literal signification, the qualities of mind ; and that material objects affect us only by means of the moral ideas they suggest. This was a favourite doctrine of the Socratic school, and has been support- ed with great ingenuity by several modern writers. 207. Whatever opinion we adopt on this speculative question, there can be no dispute about the fact, that good actions and virtuous characters form the most delightful of all ob- jects to the human mind ; and that there are no charms in the external universe so power- ful as those which recommend to us the cul- tivation of the qualities, that constitute the perfection and happiness of our nature. 144 OUTLINES OF 208. It was a leading object of the ancient moralists, to establish such an union between philosophy and the fine arts, as might add to the natural beauty of virtue every attraction which the imagination could impart. The effect which might be produced in this way maybe easily conceived, from the examples we daily see of the influence of association in con- cealing the meanness and deformitv of fashion- able vices. III. OF THE PERCEPTION OF MEUIT AND DEMERIT. 209. The virtuous actions performed by other men, not only excite in our minds a benevolent affection towards them, or a dis- position to promote their happiness ; but impress us with a sense of the merit of the agents. We perceive them to be the proper objects of love and esteem, and that it is morally right that they should receive their reward. We feel ourselves called on, to make their worth known to the world, MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 145 ill order to procure them the favour and re- spect they deserve ; and if we allow it to remain secret, we are conscious of injustice, in suppressing the natural language of the heart. 210. On the other hand, when we are wit- nesses of an act of selfishness, of cruelty, or of oppression ; whether we ourselves are the sufferers or not ; we are not only inspired with aversion and hatred tovv'ards the delinquent, but find it difficult to restrain our indifvna- tion from breaking loose against him. By this natural impulse of the mind, a check is imposed on the bad passions of individuals ; and a provision is made, even before the esta- blishment of positive laws, for the good order of society. 211. In our own case; when we are con- scious of doing well, we feel that we are en- titled to the esteem and attachment of our fellow-creatures ; and we know, with the evi- dence of a perception, that we enjoy the ap- 146 OUTLINES OF probation of the invisible witness of our con- duct. Hence it is, that we have not only a sense of merit, but an anticipation of reward, and look forwards to the future with increased confidence and hope. 212. The feelings of remorse which accom- pany the consciousness of guilt, involve, in like manner, a sense of ill-desert, and an anticipa- tion of future punishment. 213. Although, however, our sense of Me- rit and Demerit, must convince the philoso- pher of the connection which the Deity has established between virtue and happiness, he does not proceed on the supposition, that, on particular occasions, miraculous interpositions are to be made in his favour. That virtue is, even in this world, the most direct road to hap- piness, he sees to be a fact ; but he knows that the Deity governs by general laws ; and when he feels himself disappointed in the attainment of his wishes, he acquiesces in his lot, and consoles himself with the pro- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 147 spect of futurity. It is an error of the vul- gar to expect, that good or bad fortune are al- ways to be connected, in particular instances, with good or bad actions ; — a prejudice which is a source of much disappointment in human life, but of which the prevalence in all ages and countries, affords a striking illustration of the natural connection between the ideas of virtue and of merit. 148 OUTLINES OF SECTION VI. OF THE MORAL FACULTY. ARTICLE THIRD. OF MORAL OBLIGATION. 214. According to some systems, moral obligation is founded entirely on our belief, that virtue is enjoined by the command of God. But how, it may be asked, does this belief impose an obligation ? Only one of two answers can be given. Either, that there is a moral fitness that we should con- form our will to that of the Author and the Governor of the universe ; or that a ra- tional self-love should induce us, out of pru- dence, to study every means of rendering ourselves acceptable to the almighty Arbiter MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 149 of happiness and misery. On the first sup- position, we reason in a circle. We resolve our sense of moral obligation into our sense of religion ; and the sense of religion into that of moral obligation. 215. The other system which makes vir- tue a mere matter of prudence, although not so obviously unsatisfactory, leads to conse- quences which sufficiently shew that it is erroneous. Among others, it leads us to con- clude, 1. That the disbelief of a future state absolves from all moral obligation, excepting in so far as we find virtue to be conducive to our present interest : — 2. That a being inde- pendently and completely happy, cannot have any moral perceptions, or any moral attri- butes. 216. But farther ; the notions of reward and punishment presuppose the notions of right and wrong. They are sanctions of vir- tue, or additional motives to the practice of 150 OUTl.lNES OF it ; but they suppose the existence of some previous obligation. 217. In the last place ; if moral obligation be constituted by a regard to our situation in another life, how shall the existence of a fu- ture state be proved by the light of nature ? or hovv^ shall we discover what conduct is ac- ceptable to the Deity ? The truth is, that the strongest argument for such a state is deduced from our natural notions of right and wrong, of merit and demerit ; and from a comparison between these and the general course of hu- man affairs. 218. It is absurd, therefore, to ask, why we are bound to practice virtue ? The very notion of virtue implies the notion of obli- gation. Every being, who is conscious of the distinction between Right and Wrong, carries about with him a law which he is bound to observe ; notwithstanding he may be in total ignorance of a future state. " What " renders obnoxious to punishment, is not MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 151 " the foreknowledge of it, but merely the " violating a known obligation*." 219. From what has been stated, it follows, that the moral Faculty, considered as an ac- tive power of the mind, differs essentially from all the others hitherto enumerated. The least violation of its authority fills us with remorse. On the contrary, the greater the sacrifices we make, in obedience to its sug- gestions, the greater are our satisfaction and triumph. 220. The supreme authority of conscience, although beautifully described by many of the ancient moralists, was not sufficiently at- tended to by modern writers, as a fundamental principle in the science of ethics, till the time of Dr Butler. Too little stress is laid on it by Lord Shaftesbury ; and the omission is the chief defect of his philosophy. Butler, 152! OUTLINES OF 221. If this distinction between the moral faculty and our other active powers, be ac- knowledged, it is of the less consequence what particular theory we adopt concerning the origin of our moral ideas : and accord- ingly Mr Smith, though he resolves moral approbation ultimately into a feeling of the mind, represents the supremacy of conscience as a principle which is equally essential to all the different systems that have been proposed on the subject. " Upon whatever we suppose ' our moral faculties to be founded, whe- ' ther upon a certain modification of reason, ' upon an original instinct, called a moral ' sense, or upon some other principle of our ' nature, it cannot be doubted that they were ' given us for the direction of our conduct ' in this life. They carry along with them ' the most evident badges of this authority, ' which denote that they were set up within ' us to be the supreme arbiters of all our ac- ' tions, to superintend all our senses, passions, ' and appetites, and to judge how far each of MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 153 " them was either to be indulged or restrain- " ed. — It is the peculiar office of these facul- " ties to judge, to bestow censure or applause " upon all the other principles of our nature." 154 OUTLINES OF SECTION VII. OF CERTAIN PRINCIPLES WHICH C0-0PB:RATE WITH OUR MORAL POWERS IN THEIR INFLUENCE ON THE CON- DUCT. 222. In order to secure still more com- pletely the good order of society, and to faci- litate the acquisition of virtuous habits, nature has superadded to our moral constitution a va- riety of auxiliary principles, which sometimes give rise to a conduct agreeable to the rules of morality, and highly useful to mankind ; where the merit of the individual considered as a moral agent is extremly inconsiderable. Hence, some of them have been confounded with our moral powers, or even supposed to be of themselves sufficient to account for the phenomena of moral perception, by authors whose views of human nature have not been sufficiently comprehensive. — The most im- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 155 portant principles of this description are, 1. A regard to Character. 2. Sympathy. 3, The sense of the Ridiculous. And, 4. Taste. — The principle of Self-love (which was treated of in a former section) co-operates powerfully to the same purposes. I. OF DECENCY, OR A REGARD TO CHARACTER. 223. It was before observed (126.), that the desire of esteem operates in children be- fore they have a capacity of distinguishing right from wrong ; and that the former prin- ciple of action continues for a long time to be much more powerful than the latter. Hence, it furnishes a most useful and effectual engine in the business of education ; more particular- ly, by training us early to exertions of self- command and self-denial. It teaches us, for example, to restrain our appetites within those bounds which decency prescribes, and thus forms us to habits of moderation and temper- ance. And, although our conduct cannot be denominated virtuous, so long as a regard to 156 OUTLINES OF the opinion of others is our only motive, yet the habits we thus acquire in infancy and childhood render it more easy for us, as we advance to maturity, to subject our passions to the authority of reason and conscience. 224. That our sense of duty is not resolv- able into a desire of obtaining the good opi- nion of our fellow-creatures, may be inferred from the following considerations. 1. The desire of esteem can only be effec- tually gratified by the actual possession of those qualities for which we wish to be esteemed. 2. The merit of a virtuous action is always enhanced in the opinion of mankind, when it is discovered in those situations of life, where the individual cannot be suspected of any view to the applauses of the world. 3. When a competition takes place between our sense of duty and a regard to public opi- nion ; if we sacrifice the former to the latter, MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 157 we are filled with remorse and self-condem- nation ; and the applauses of the multitude afford us but an empty and unsatisfactory re- compence; whereas a steady adherence to the Hight never fails to be its own reward, even when it exposes us to calumny and mis- representation. II. OF SYMPATHY. 225. That there is an exquisite pleasure an- nexed to the sympathy or fellow-feeling of other men, with our joys and sorrows, and even with our opinions, tastes and humours, is a fact obvious to vulgar observation. It is no less evi- dent, that we feel a disposition to accommodate the state of our own minds to that of our com- panions, wherever we feel a benevolent affec- tion towards them ; and that this accommoda- ting temper is in proportion to the strength of our affection. In such cases, sympathy would appear to be grafted on benevolence ; and per- haps it might be found, on an accurate ana- lysis, that the greater part of the pleasures 158 OUTLINES OF which it yields, is resolvable into those which arise from the exercise of kindness, and from the consciousness of being beloved. 226. The same word sympathy is applied in a loose and popular sense, to various phe- nomena in the Animal Economy ; to the correspondence, for example, in the motions of the eyes ; and to the connection which exists between different organs of the body, in re- spect of health, or of disease. It is also ap- plied to those contagious bodily affections which one person is apt to catch from another ; such as yawning ; stammering ; squinting ; sore eyes ; and the disorders commonly dis- tinguished by the name of Hysterical. 227. In all these different instances, there is, no doubt, a certain degree of analogy ; such as completely accounts for their being- comprehended, in ordinary discourse, under one general name ; but, where philosophical precision is aimed at, there is ground for many- distinctions. Hence the necessity of limiting, MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 159 by an accurate definition, the sense in which this very vague and equivocal word is to be understood, when it is introduced into any scientific discussion. 228. The facts generally referred to sym- pathy, have appeared to Mr Smith so import- ant and so curiously connected, that he has been led to attempt an explanation, from this single principle, of all the phenomena of mo- ral perception. 229. The large mixture of valuable truth contained in this most ingenious Theory, and the light which it throws on a part of our frame, formerly very little attended to by Philosophers, entitle the Author to the high- est rank among Systematical Moralists ; but, on a closer examination of the subject, it will be found, that he has been misled, like many other eminent writers, by an excessive love of simplicity ; mistaking a subordinate principle in our moral constitution (or rather a principle superadded to our moral constitu- 1 60 OUTLINES OF tion, as an auxiliary to the sense of duty) for that Faculty, which distinguishes Right from Wrong ; and which (by what name soever we may choose to distinguish it) recurs on us constantly, in all our ethical disquisitions, as an ultimate fact in the nature of man. III. OF THE SENSK OF THE RIDICULOUS. 230. The natural and proper object of Ri- dicule, is those smaller improprieties in cha- racter and manners which do not rouse our feelings of moral indignation, nor impress us with a melancholy view of human depravity. 231. While this part of our constitution enlarges the fund of our enjoyment, by ren- dering the more trifling imperfections of our fellow -creatures a source of amusement to their neighbours, it excites the exertions of every individual to correct those imperfec- tions by which the ridicule of others is likely to be provoked. As our eagerness, too, to MORAL PHILOSOPHY. l6l correct these imperfections may be presumed to be weak in proportion as we apprehend them to be, in a moral view, of trifling mo- ment, we are so formed, that the painful feel- ings produced by ridicule, are often more poignant than those arising from the con- sciousness of having rendered ourselves the objects of resentment or of hatred. 232. The sense of the Ridiculous, although it has a manifest reference to such a scene of imperfection as we are placed in at present, is one of the most strikino- characteristics of the human constitution, as distinguished from that of the lower animals ; and has an intimate connection with its highest and noblest prin- ciples. In the education of youth, nothing requires more serious attention, than its proper regulation. 162 OUTLINES OF IV. OF TASTE, CONSIDEllED IN ITS RELATION TO MOKALS. 233. From the explanation formerly given (202, 203, 204.) of the import of the phrases Moral JBeauty, and Moral Deformity, it may be easily conceived, in what manner the cha- racter and the conduct of our fellow-creatures may become subservient to the gratification of Taste. The use which the Poet makes of this class of our intellectual pleasures, is en- tirely analogous to the resources which he borrows from the charms of external nature. 234. The power of moral taste, like that which has for its object the beauty of mate- rial forms, and the various productions of the fine arts, requires much exercise for its de- velopment and culture. The one species of taste also, as well as the other, is susceptible of a false refinement, injurious to our own happiness, and to our usefulness as members of society. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 163 235. Considered as a principle of action, a cultivated moral taste, while it provides an effectual security against the grossness neces- sarily connected with many vices, cherishes a temper of mind friendly to all that is amiable, or generous, or elevated in our nature. When separated, however, as it sometimes is, from a strong sense of duty, it can scarcely fail to prove a fallacious guide; the influence of fashion, and of other casual associations, tending perpetually to lead it astray. This is more particularly re- markable in men to whom the gratifications of Tasle in general form the principal object of pursuit ; and whose habits of life encourage them to look no higlier for their rule of judg- ment, than the way of the world. 236. The language employed by some of the Greek Philosophers in their speculations concerning the nature of virtue, seems, on a superficial view, to imply, that they supposed the moral faculty to be wholly resolvable into a sense of the Beautiful. And hence, Lord Shaftesbury and others, have been led to adopt 164 OUTLINES OF a phraseology which has the appearance of substituting Taste, in contradistinction to Rea- son and Conscience, as the ultimate standard of Right and Wrong. 237. From each of the four principles now enumerated, unfortunate consequences result, wherever it prevails in the character, as the leading motive to action. Where they all main- tain their due place, in subordination to the moral faculty, they tend, at once, to fortify virtuous habits ; and to recommend them, by the influence of amiable example, to the imi- tation of others. 238. A partial consideration of the phenome- na of moral perception, connected with one or other of these principles, has suggested some of the most popular theories concerningtheorigin of our moral ideas. An attention to the moral faculty alone, without regard to the principles which were intended to operate as its auxilia- ries, and which contribute, in fact, so power- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 165 fully to the good order of society, has led a few Philosophers into an opposite extreme ; — less dangerous, undoubtedly, in its practical ten- dency, but less calculated, perhaps, to recom- mend ethical disquisitions to the notice of those who are engrossed with the active con- cerns of life. 166 OUTLINES OF SECTION VIII. OF man's free agency. 239. All the foregoing inquiries concerning the moral constitution of man, proceed on the supposition, that he has a freedom of choice between good and evil ; and that when he de- liberately performs an action wiiich he knows to be wrong, he renders himself justly obnoxi- ous to punishment. That this supposition is agreeable to the common apprehensions of mankind, will not be disputed. 240. From very early ages, indeed, the truth of the supposition has been called in question by a few speculative men, who have contended, that the actions we perform are the necessary result of the constitutions of our minds, operat- ed on by the circumstances of our external si- tuation ; and that what we commonlv call mo- MORAL PHILOSOPHY, l67 ral delinquencies are as much a part of our des- tiny, as the corporeal or intellectual qualities we have received from nature. — The argument in support of this doctrine has been proposed in various forms, and has been frequently urg- ed with the confidence of demonstration. 241. Among those, however, who hold the language of Necessitarians, an important dis- tinction must be made ; as some of them not only admit the reality of moral distinctions, but insist, that it is on their hypothesis alone, that these distinctions are conceivable. With such men, the scheme of necessity may be a harmless opinion ; and there is ground even for suspecting, that it might be found to differ from that of their antagonists, more in appear- ance than in reality, if due pains were taken to fix the meaning of the indefinite and am- biguous terms, which have been employed on both sides of the argument. 242. By otlier philosophers, the consequences which are generally supposed to be connected with this system, have been admitted in all 168 OUTJ.INES OF their extent ; or rather, the system has been in- culcated, with a view to establish these conse- quences. When proposed in this form, it fur- nishes the most interesting subject of discus- sion which can employ human ingenuity ; and upon which our speculative opinions can hard- ly fail to affect very materially both our con- duct and our happiness. 243. Dr Cudworth, who wrote towards the end of the seventeenth century, observes, that " the scepticism which flourished in his time, " grew up from the doctrine of the fatal ne- " cessity of all actions and events, as from its " proper root." The same remark will be found to apply to the sceptical philosophy of the present age. 244. It is sufficient, in these Outlines, to mark the place which the question seems na- turally to occupy in the order of study. De- tached hints would throw but little additional light on a controversy, which has been industri- ously darkened by all the powers of sophistry. OUTLINES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. PART II. OF THE ACTIVE AND OF THE MORAL POWERS OF MAN. CHAP. 11. OF THE VARIOUS BRANCHES OF OUR DUTY. 245. The different theories which luive been proposed concerning the nature and es- sence of Virtue, have arisen chiefly from at- tempts to trace all the branches of our duty to one principle of action ; such as a rational 170 OUTLINES OF Self-love, Benevolence, Justice, or a disposi- tion to obey the will of God. 246. In order to avoid those partial views of the subject, which naturally take their rise from an undue love of system, the fol- lowing inquiries proceed upon an arrange- ment, which has, in all ages, recommended itself to the good sense of mankind. This arrangement is founded on the different ob- jects to which our duties relate. 1. The Deity. 2. Our Fellow-creatures. And, 3. Ourselves. MOKAI, rilll.OSOPHY. 171 SECTION I. OF THE DUTIES WHICH RESPECT THE DEITY. 247. As our duties to God, (so far as they are discoverable by the light of nature), must be inferred from the relation in which we stand to him as the Author and the Governor of the Universe, an examination of the prin- ciples of Natural Religion forms a necessary introduction into this section. Such an exami- nation, besides, being the reasonable conse- quence of those impressions which his works produce on every attentive and well-disposed mind, may be itself regarded, both as one of the duties we owe to Him, and as the expres- sion of a moral temper sincerely devoted to truth, and alive to the subliinest emotions of gratitude and of benevolence. 17^ OUTLINES OF PRBI.IMINAHV INQUIRY INTO THE PRINCIPLES OF NATURAL RELIGION. ARTICLE FIRST. OF THK EXISTENCE OF THE DEITY. 248. On this subject two modes of reason- ing have been employed, which are common- ly distinguished by the titles of the Argu- ments a priori and a posteriori ; the former, founded on certain metaphysical propositions which are assumed as axioms ; the latter ap- pealing to that systematical order, and those combinations of means to ends which are every where conspicuous in Nature. 249. The argument a priori has been enfor- ced wdth singular ingenuity by Dr Clarke, whose particular manner of stating it seems to have been suggested to him by the fol- lowing passage in Newton's Principia : " M- " tenuis est et infinitus, omnipotens et om- " nisciens ; id est, durat ab geterno in ater- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 173 " num, et adest ab infinite in infinitum. — " Non est aeternitas et infinitas, sed geternus " et infinitus ; non est duratio et spatium, " sed durat et adest. Durat semper, et " adest ubiqiie ; et existendo semper et ubi- " que, durationem et spatium constituit *." Proceeding on the same principles, Dr Clarke argues, that " space and time are only ab- " stract conceptions of an immensity and e- " ternity, which force themselves into our be- " lief; and, as immensity and eternity are not " substances, they must be the attributes of a " Being who is necessarily immense and eter- « nal." " These (says Dr Reid) are the " speculations of men of superior genius ; but " whether they be as solid as they are sub- " lime ; or whether they be the wanderings " of imagination in a region beyond the li- " mits of human understanding, I am unable " to determine." 250. Without calling in question the soli- * Newton, Princ. Scholiiun jrenerale. 174 OUTLINES OF clity of Clarke's demonstration, we may be allowed to say, that the argument a posteriori is more level to the comprehension of ordina- ry men, and more satisfactory to the philo- sopher himself. Indeed, in inquiries of this sort, the presumption is strongly in favour of that mode of reasoning which is the most simple and obvious, — " Quicquid nos vel me- " liores vel beatiores facturum est, aut in a- " perto, aut in proximo, posuit natura." 251. The existence of a Deity, however, does not seem to be an intuitive truth. It re- quires the exercise of our reasoning powers to present it, in its full force, to the mind. But the process of reasoning consists only of a single step ; and the premises belong to that class of first principles, which form an essential part of the human constitution, (§ 71. (3.). These premises are two in num- ber. The one is, That every thing which begins to exist must have a cause. The other. That a combination of means conspiring to a particular end, implies intelligence. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 175 I. OF THE FOLMDATION3 OF OUR REASONING FROM THE EFFECT TO THE CAUSE, AND OF THE EVIDENCES OF ACTIVE POWER P:XHIB1TED IN THE UNIVERSE. 252. It was before observed, (Introd. § 3.) that our knowledge of the course of nature is entirely the result of observation and experi- ment ; and that there is no instance in which we perceive such a connection between two successive events, as might enable us to infer the one from the other as a necessary conse- quence. 253. From this principle, which is now very generally admitted by philosophers, Mr Hume has deduced an objection to the ar- gument a posteriori for the existence of the Deity. After having proved that we cannot get tlie idea of necessary connection, from examining the conjunction between any two events ; he takes for granted, that we have no other idea of Cause and Effect, than of 176 OUTLINES OF two successive events which are invariably conjoined ; that we have therefore no reason to think, that any one event in nature is ne- cessarily connected with another, or to infer the operation of power from the changes which we observe in the universe. 254. To perceive the connexion between Mr Hume's premises and his conclusion, it is necessary to recollect, that, according to his system, " all our ideas are nothing but copies " of our impressions ; or, in other words, " that it is impossible for us to tliinh of any " thing, w^hich we have not antecedently ^^ felt, either by our external or internal " senses." Having proved, therefore, that external objects, as they appear to our senses, give us no idea of power or of necessary con- nection, and also that this idea cannot be co- pied from any internal impression, (that is, cannot be derived from reflection on the ope- rations of our own minds), he thinks him- self warranted to conclude, that we have no MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 177 such idea. " One event (says lie) follows " another, but we never observe any tie be- " tween them. They seem conjoined, but " never connected. And as we can have no " idea of any thing, which never appeared " to our outward sense or inward sentiment, " the necessary conclusion seems to be. That " we have no idea of connection or power at " all ; and that these words are absolutely " without any meaning, when employed ei- " ther in philosophical reasonings or common « life." 255. Are we, therefore, to reject as per- fectly unintelligible, a word which is to be found in all languages ; merely because it ex- presses an idea, for the origin of which we cannot account upon a particular philosophi- cal system ? Would it not be more reasonable to suspect, that the system was not perfectly complete, than that all mankind should have agreed in employing a word which conveyed no meaning ? M 178 OUTLINES OF 256. With respect to Mr Hume's tlieory concerning the origin of our ideas, it is the less necessary to enter into particular discus- sions, that it coincides, in the main, with the doctrine of Locke, to which some objections, which appear to be insurmountable, were for- merly stated, (§ 199.) Upon neither theory is it possible to explain the origin of those simple notions, which are not received im- mediately by any external sense, nor derived immediately from our own consciousness ; but which are necessarily formed by the mind, while we are exercising our intellectual powers upon their proper objects. 257. These very slight hints are sufficient to shew, that we are not entitled to dispute the reality of our idea of power, because we cannot trace it to any of our senses. The on- ly question is, If it be certain, that we annex any idea to the word power, dijtferent from that of mere succession ? The following con- siderations, among many others, prove, that MOllAI. PHILOSOPHY. 179 the import of these two expressions is by no means the same. (1.) If we have no idea of cause and effect different from that of mere succession, it would appear to us no less absurd to suppose two events disjoined, which we have constant- ly seen connected, than to suppose a change to take place without a cause. The former supposition, however, is easy in all cases what- ever. The latter may be safely pronounced to be impossible. (2.) Our experience of the established con- nections of physical events is by far too nar- row a foundation for our belief, that every change must have a cause. Mr Hume him- self has observed, that " the vulgar always " include the idea of Contiguity in place in " the idea of causation ;" or, in other words, that they conceive matter to produce its ef- fects by impulse alone. If, therefore, every change which had fallen under our notice, had been preceded by apparent impulse, ex- 180 OUTLINES OF perience might have taught us to conclude, from observing a change, that a previous im- pulse had been given ; or, according to Mr Hume's notion of a cause ^ that a cause had operated to produce this effect. Of the changes, however, which we see, how small a number is produced by apparent impulse ? And yet, in the case of every change, without exception, we have an irresistible conviction of the operation of some cause. How shall we explain, on Mr Hume's principles, the foundation of this conviction, in cases in which impulse has apparently no share. 258. The question, however, still recurs ; In w^hat manner do we acquire the idea of Causation, Power, or Efficiency ? — But this question, if the foregoing observations be ad- mitted, is comparatively of little consequence; as the doubts which may arise on the subject, tend only (without affecting the reality of the idea or notion) to expose the defects of particular philosophical systems. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 181 ^59. The most probable account of the matter seems to be, that the idea of causation, or of power, necessarily accompanies the per- ception of change, in a way somewhat analo- gous to that in which sensation implies a being who feels, and thought, a being who tliinks. A power of beginning motion, for example, is an attribute of mind, no less than sensation or thought ; and wherever motion commences, we have evidence that mind has operated. 260. Are we therefore to conclude, that the divine power is constantly exerted to pro- duce the phenomena of the material world, and to suppose, that one and the same cause produces that infinite multiplicity of effects which are every moment taking place in the universe ? 261. In order to avoid this conclusion, which has been thought, by many, too ab- surd to deserve a serious examination, various hypotheses have been proposed. The most 182 OUTLINES OF important of these may be referred to the fol- lowing heads. (1.) That the phenomena of nature are the result of certain active powers essentially in- herent in matter. This doctrine is common- ly called Materialism. (2.) That they result from certain active powers communicated to matter at its first formation. (3.) That they take place in consequence of general laws established by the Deity. (4.) That they are produced by " a vital " and spiritual, but unintelligent and neces- " sary agent, created by the Deity for the " execution of his purposes *." 5. That they are produced by minds con- nected with the particles of matter. * Cud worth. MORAL PHILOSOrHY. 183 (6.) That the universe is a machine formed and put in motion by the Deity ; and that the multiplicity of effects which take place, may perhaps have all proceeded from one single act of his power. 262. These different hypotheses, (some of which will be found, on examination, to re- solve into unmeaning or unintelligible pro- positions, and all of which are liable to in- surmountable objections), have been adopted by ingenious men, in preference to the simple and sublime doctrine, w^hich supposes the or- der of the universe to be not only at first esta- blished, but every moment maintained, by the incessant agency of One Supreme Mind ; — a doctrine, against which no objection can be stated, but what is founded on prejudices re- sulting from our own imperfections. — This doctrine does not exclude the possibility of the Deity's acting occasionally by subordinate agents or instruments. 184 OUTLINES OF 263. The observations, indeed, hitherto made, are not sufficient of themselves to autho- rise us to form any conclusion with respect to the unity of God ; but when properly illustra- ted, they will be found to warrant fully the following inference : That the phenomena of the universe indicate the constant agency of power which cannot belong to matter ; or, in other words, that they indicate the con- stant agency of Mind. AVhether these pheno- mena, when compared together, bear marks of a diversity or of an unity of design ; and, of consequence, whether they suggest the Go- vernment of one almighty Ruler, or of a plu- rality of independent divinites, are inquiries which belong to the next head of our argu- ment. MORAI- PHILOSOPHY. 185 II. OF THE EVIDENCES OF DESIGN EXHIBITED IN THE UNIVERSE. 264. The proof of the existence of God, drawn from the Order of the universe, is com- monly called the argument from Final Causes. The expression (which was first introduced by Aristotle) is far from being proper ; but is retained in this treatise, in compliance with established use. 265. It is justly remarked by Dr Reid, that the argument from Final Causes, when reduced to a syllogism, contains two pro- positions. The major is, That Design may be traced from its effects : The minor. That there are appearances of Design in the uni- verse. The antient sceptics, he says, granted the first, but denied the second. The mo- derns (in consequence of the discoveries in 18G OUTLINES OF natural philosophy) have been obliged to aban- don the ground which their predecessors main- tained, and have disputed the major proposi- tion. 266. Amonp- those who have denied the possibility of tracing design from its effects, Mr Hume is the most eminent. According to him, all such inferences are inconclusive, be- ing neither demonstrable by reasoning, nor deducible from experience. 267. In examining Mr Hume's argument on this subject, Dr Heid admits, that the in- ferences we make of design from its effects, are not the result of reasoning, or of experi- ence : but still he contends, that such infe- rences may be made with a degree of cer- tainty, equal to what the human mind is able to attain in any instance whatever. The opi- nions we form of the talents of other men, nay, our belief that other men are intelligent beings, are founded on this very inference of design from its effects. Intelligence and de- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 187 sign are not objects of our senses, and yet we judge of them every moment from external conduct and behaviour, with as little hesita- tion as we pronounce on the existence of what we immediately perceive. 268. Other philosophers have opposed the major proposition of the syllogism, by an ar- gument somewhat different. — In order to judge of the wisdom of any design, it is ne- cessary (they observe) to know, first, what end the artist proposes to himself, and then, to examine the means which he has employ- ed to accomplish it. But in the universe all we see is, that certain things are accomplish- ed, without having an opportunity of com- paring them with a plan previously proposed. — A stone thrown at random must necessarily hit one object or another. When we see, therefore, such an effect produced, we are not entitled, independently of other infor- mation, to praise the dexterity of the marks- man. 188 OUTLINES OF 269. Among a great variety of considera- tions, which might be urged in reply to this objection, the following seem to deserve par- ticular attention. (1.) Although from a single effect, we may not be entitled to infer intelligence in the cause, yet the case is different, when we see a number of causes conspiring to 07ie end. We here see not only that an effect takes place, but have an intuitive conviction, that this was the very effect intended. From see- ing a single stone strike an object, we may not be authorised to conclude that this was the object aimed at. But what conclusion should we draw, if we saw the same object invariably hit by a number of stones thrown in succession ? (2.) A multiplicity of cases might be men- tioned, in which we have really an opportu- nity of comparing the wisdom of nature with the ends to which it is directed. Of this, many remarkable examples occur in the eco- MORAI- PHILOSOPHY. 189 nomy of the human body. When any acci- dent or disease injures our frame, it is well known that the body possesses within itself a power of alleviating or remedying the evil. In such instances, we not only see an effect produced ; but we see the operation of na- tural causes directed to the particular pur- pose of restoring the healthful state of the system. (3.) There are many cases, particularly in the animal economy, in which the same ef- fect is produced in different instances, by very different means ; and in which, of con- sequence, we have an opportunity of compa- ring the wisdom of nature with the ends she has in view. " Art and means (says Baxter) " are designedly multiplied, that we might " not take it for the effect of chance : and " in some cases, the method itself is different, " that we might see it is not the effect of " surd necessity." — The science of compa- rative anatomy, furnishes beautiful confir- mations of the foregoing doctrine. From ob- 190 OUTLINES OF serving the effect produced by a particular organ in the case of any one animal, we might not perhaps be v/arranted to conclude, that it was in order to produce this effect, that the organ was contrived. But when, in the case of different species of animals, we see the same effect brought about by means extreme- ly different, it is impossible for us to doubt, that it was this common end which, in all these instances. Nature had in view. — Nor is this all. In comparing the anatomy of dif- ferent tribes of animals, we find that the differences observable in their structure have a reference to their way of life, and the ha- bits for which they are destined ; so that, from knowing the latter, we might be able, in particular cases, to frame conjectures a priori concerning the former. 270. From the foregoing hints, it suffi- ciently appears, that design may be inferred from its effects ; and, also, that design may be traced in various parts of the universe, from an actual examination of the means em- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 191 ployed to accomplish particular ends. — Ano- ther inquiry, however, and a still more im- portant, remains, — to consider the characters of this design, as it is displayed in the uni- verse ; or, in other words, to consider, how far the design seems to indicate Wisdom ; and whether it seems to operate in conformity to One uniform plan. The first investigation is useful, by its tendency to elevate our concep- tions of the Supreme Being ; and the second is necessary for the demonstration of his Unity. 271. The study of philosophy, in all its various branches, both natural and moral, af- fords, at every step, a new illustration of the subject to which these investigations relate ; insomuch that the truths of natural religion gain an accession of evidence, from every addition that is made to the stock of human knowledge. Hence, in the case of those in- dividuals who devote themselves, with fair and candid minds, to the pursuits of science, there is a gradual progress of light and con- viction, keeping pace with the enlargement of their information and of their views ; and 192 OUTLINES OF hence, a strong presumption that the influ- ence which these truths have, even in the present state of society, on the minds of the multitude, will continually increase, in pro- portion as the order of the material universe shall be more fully displayed by the discove- ries of philosophy, and as the plan of Provi- dence in the administration of human affairs, shall be more completely unfolded in the fu- ture history of our species. 272. In considering the universe, with a view to the illustration of the wisdom and unity of God, it is, in a peculiar degree, satis- factory to trace the relations which different parts of it bear to each other, and to remark the concurrence of things apparently uncon- nected and even remote, in promoting the same benevolent purposes. The following hints may be of vise in suggesting reflections on this subject. (1.) The adaptation of the bodies and of the instincts of animals to the laws of the ma- MOUAL PHILOSOPHY. 193 terial world : — Of tlie organs of respiration, for example, and of the instinct of suction, to the properties of the atmosphere ; — of the momentum of light to the sensibility of the re- tina ; — of the fabric of the eye to the laws of refraction ; — of the size and strength of ani- mals and vegetables to the laws of gravitation and of cohesion. (2.) The adaptation of the bodies, and of the instincts of animals, to those particular climates and districts of tlie earth, for which they are destined. (3.) The relations subsisting between parti- cular animals and particular vegetables ; the latter furnishing to the former, salutary food in their healthful state, and useful remedies in the case of disease. (4.) The connection which appears, from the pneumatical discoveries of modern che- mistry, to exist between the processes of nature in the animal and in the vegetable kingdoms. N 194 OUTLINES OF (5.) The relations which different tribes of animals bear to each other ; one tribe be- ing the natural prey of another ; and each of them having their instruments of offence or defence provided accordingly. (6.) The relations which the periodical in- stincts of migrating animals bear to the state of the season, and to the vegetable produc- tions, of distant parts of the globe. 273. This view of the subject is peculiarly striking, when we consider the relations which subsist between the nature of man, and the circumstances of his external situation. An examination, of his perceptive faculties, in particular, and of his intellectual powers, as they are adapted to the structure and to the laws of the material world, opens a wide field of curious speculation. 274. The accommodation of the objects around him to his appetites, to his physical wants, and to his capacities of enjoyment, is no less wonderful : and exceeds so far what MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 195 we observe in the case of other animals, as to authorise us to conclude, that it was chiefly with a view to his happiness and improve- ment, that the arrangements of this lower world was made. 275. There is another view of nature which tends remarkably to illustrate that unity of design, which is the foundation of our belief of the unity of God ; — to trace the analogies which are observable between the different departments of the universe which fall under our notice. — Of such analogies many instances may be derived from a comparative examina- tion ; 1. Of the structures of different tribes of animals ; 2. Of the animal and of the ve- getable kingdoms ; And, 3. Of the various laws which regulate the phenomena of the material world. 276. It is pleasing to consider, that this uniform and regular plan has been found to extend to the remotest limits to which the inquiries of philosopliers have reached. The ancients, in general, supposed, that the phe- 196 OUTLINES OK nomena of the heavens were reguhited by laws perfectly unlike those which obtain with- in the circle of our experience. The mo- dern discoveries have shewn how widely they were mistaken ; and indeed it was a conjec- ture a priori, that their ideas on this subject might perhaps be erroneous, which led the way to the theory of gravitation. Every subse- quent discovery has confirmed the conjecture. 277. Nor is it only the more general laws of terrestrial bodies, which extend to the re- mote parts of the universe. There is some ground for suspecting, that the particular ar- rangements of things, on the surfaces of the different planets, are not wholly unlike those which we observe on our own. 278. Amusing and interesting as these physical speculations may be, it is still more delighful to trace the uniformity of de- sign which is displayed in the moral world ; — to compare the instincts of men with those of the brutes, and the instincts of the different tribes of brutes, with each other ; MORAL THILOSOPHY. 197 and to remark, amidst the astonishing variety of means which are employed to accomplish the same ends, a certain analogy characterize them all ; — or to observe, in the minds of dif- ferent individuals of our own species, the workings of the same affections and passions, and to trace the uniformity of their operation in men of different ages and countries. — It is this which gives the great charm to what v/e call nature in epic and dramatic composi- tion ; when the poet speaks a language to which every heart is an echo ; and which, a- midst all the effects of education and fashion, in modifying and disguising the principles of our constitution, reminds all the various clas- ses of readers or of spectators, of the exist- ence of those moral ties which unite us to each other, and to our common Parent. 279- Before leaving this subject, it is pro- j)er to remark, that the metaphysical reason- ings which have been occasionally employed in the illustration of it, ought not to be con- sidered as forming any part of the argument for the existence of God ; which (as was alrca- 198 OUTLINES OF dy observed) is an immediate and necessary consequence of the two principles formerly mentioned (§ 251.) The scope of these rea- sonings is not to confirm the truth of the pro- position, but to obviate the sceptical cavils which have been urged against it. 280. Reasoning and reflection are indeed necessary to raise the mind to worthy con- ceptions of the Divine attributes, and to cure it of those prejudices which arise from limited and erroneous views of nature. While men confine their attention to detached and insu- lated appearances. Polytheism offers itself as the most natural creed ; and it is only by slow and gradual steps that philosophy discovers to us those magnificent views of the universe which connect together all events, both phy- sical and moral, as parts of one system, and conspiring to one end. 281. Beside the sceptical objections, al- ready mentioned, to the speculation concern- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 199 ing Final Causes, some others have been proposed with very different views. Des Cartes, in particular, taking for granted the existence of God, as sufficiently established by other proofs, has rejected altogether this speculation from philosophy, as an impious and absurd attempt to penetrate into the designs of Providence. Some observations, much to the same purpose, occur in the works of INIaupertuis and of Buffon. — To this class of objections against Final Causes, a satisfac- tory answer is given by Mr Boyle, in an essay written expressly on the subject. 282. The authority of Lord Bacon has been frequently quoted in support of the opi- nion of these French philosophers. But if his writings be carefully examined, it will be found, that the censures he bestows on Aris- totle and his followers, for their conjectures concerning the ends and intentions of Nature, are applicable only to the abuse of this doc- trine in the Peripatetic scliool. It is a doc- trine, according to him, which belongs pro- 200 OUTLINES OF perly to metaphysics or to natural theology, and not to natural philosophy ; and which contributed much to mislead the Peripatetics in their physical inquiries. In a work, of which it was the principal aim to explain the true plan of philosophical investigation, it was necessary to point out the absurdity of blending physical and final causes together, and of substituting conjectures concerning the intentions of nature for an account of her operations. Perhaps it was prudent even to recommend the total exclusion of such con- jectures from physics, in an age when the just rules of inquiry were so imperfectly vmder- stood. — That Bacon did not mean to censure the speculation about Final Causes, when con- fined to its proper place, and applied to its proper purpose, appears clearly from a va- riety of particular passages, as well as from the general strain and tendency of his writ- ings, 283. In the present age, when the true method of philosophizing in physics is pretty MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 201 generally understood, it does not seem to be so necessary as formerly to banish Final Causes from that branch of science } provided always they be kept distinct from Physical Causes, with which there is now but little danger of their being unw^arily confounded. If this caution be attended to, the considera- tion of Final Causes, so far from leading us astray, may frequently be of use in guid- ing our researches. — It is, in fact, a mode of reasoning familiar to every philosopher, what- ever his speculative opinions on the subject of natural religion may be. Thus, in the stu- dy of anatomy, every man proceeds on the maxim, that nothins; in the bodv of an ani- mal was made in vain ; and when he meets with a part of which the use is not obvious, he feels himself dissatisfied, till he discovers some, at least, of the purposes to which it is subservient. " I remember (says Mr Boyle) " that, when I asked our famous Harvey " what were the things that induced him to '* think of a circulation of the blood ? he an- " swered me, that when he took notice that 202 OUTLINES OF *' the valves in the veins of so many parts of " the body were so placed, that they gave a ** free passage to the blood towards the heart, " but opposed the passage of the venal blood " the contrary way ; he was invited to ima- " gine, that so provident a cause as Nature *' had not placed so many valves without de- *' sign ; and no design seemed more probable, " than that, since the blood could not well, " because of the interposing valves, be sent " by the veins to the limbs, it should be sent " through the arteries, and return through " the veins, whose valves did not oppose its " course that way." 284. An explanation of the use and abuse of the speculation concerning Final Causes, in the study of natural philosophy, is still a desideratum in science, and would form an important addition to that branch of logic, which professes to state the rules of philoso- phical investigation. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 203 SECTION I. OF THE DUTIES WHICH RESPECT THE DEITY. PRELIMINARY INQUIRY INTO THE PRINCIPLES OF NATURAL RELIGION. ARTICLE SECOND. OF THE MORAL ATTRIBUTES OF THE DEITY. 285. The observations made in the last Article contain some of the principal heads of the argument for the existence of God ; and also for his unity, for his power, and for his wisdom. Of the two last of these attri- butes, we justly say that they are infinite; that is, that our imagination can set no bounds to them, and that our conceptions of tliem 204 OUTLINES OF always rise, in proportion as our faculties are cultivated, and as our knowledge of the uni- verse becomes more extensive. The writers on Natural Religion commonly give a parti- cular enumeration of attributes, which they divide into the natural, the intellectual, and the moral ; and of which they treat at length in a systematical manner. This view of the subject, whatever may be its advantages, could not be adopted with propriety here. The remarks which follow are confined to the evidences of the Divine goodness and jus- tice; — those attributes which constitute the moral perfection of the Deity, and which render him a proper object of religious wor- ship. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 205 I. OF THE EVIDEKCES OF BENEVOI-ENT DESIGN IN THlC UNIVERSE. 286. Our ideas of the moral attributes of God must be derived from our own moral perceptions. It is only by attending to these, that we can form a conception of what his at- tributes are ; and it is in this way we are fur- nished with the strongest proofs that they really belong to him. 287. The peculiar sentiment of approba- tion with which we regard the virtue of be- neficence in others, and the peculiar satis- faction with which we reflect on such of our own actions as have contributed to the hap- piness of mankind ; to which we may add the exquisite pleasure accompanying the ex- ercise of all the kind affections, naturally lead us to consider benevolence or goodness ^206 OUTLINES OF as the supreme attribute of the Deity. — It is difficult, indeed, to conceive what other mo- tive could have induced a Being, completely and independently happy, to have called his creatures into existence. 288. In this manner, without any exami- nation of the fact, we have a strong presump- tion for the goodness of the Deity ; and it is only after establishing this presumption a prio- ri, that we can proceed to examine the fact with safety. It is true, indeed, that, inde- pendently of this presumption, the disorders we see would not demonstrate ill intention in the Author of the universe ; as it would be still possible that these might contribute to the happiness and the perfection of the whole system. — But the contrary supposition would be equally possible ; that there is nothing ab- solutely good in the universe, and that the communication of suffering is the ultimate end of the laws by which it is governed. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 207 289. The argument for the goodness of God, derived from our own moral constitu- tion, and strengthened by the consideration of our ignorance of the plans of Providence, affords an answer to all the objections which have been urged against this attribute of the Deity. — And the answer is conclusive, what- ever the state of the fact may be with re- spect to the magnitude of the evils of which we complain. 290. But although this answer miglit si- lence our objections, something more is re- quisite, on a subject so momentous, to sup- port our confidence, and to animate our hopes. If no account could be given of the evils of life, but that they may possibly be good relatively to the whole universe ; — still more, if it should appear, that the sufferings of life overbalance its enjoyments ; it could hardly be expected, that any speculative rea- soning would have much effect in banishing the melancholy suggestions of scepticism. — 208 OUTLINES OF We are therefore naturally led, in the first place, to inquire, whether some explanation may not be given of the origin of evil, from a consideration of the facts which fall under our notice ? and, secondly, to compare toge- ther the happiness and the misery which the world exhibits. 291. The question concerning the origin of evil, has, from the earliest times, employed the ingenuity of speculative men : and va- rious theories have been proposed to solve the difficulty. The most celebrated of these are the foUowins;. '&• (1.) The doctrine of Pre-existence. (2.) The doctrine of the Manicheans. (3.) The doctrine of Optimism. 292. According to the first hypothesis, the evils we suffer at present are punishments MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 209 and expiations of moral delinquencies, com- mitted in a former stage of our being. — This hypothesis, it is obvious, (to mention no other objection,) only removes the difficulty a little out of sight, without affording any explana- tion of it. 293. The Manicheans account for the mix- ture of good and evil in the universe, by the opposite agencies of two co-eternal and inde- pendent principles. Their doctrine has been examined and refuted by many authors, by reasonings a jjriori ; but the most satisfactory of all refutations, is its obvious inconsistency with that unity of design which is every where conspicuous in nature. 294. The fundamental principle of the Op- timists is, that all events are ordered for the best ; and that the evils which we suffer, are parts of a great system conducted by almighty power, under the direction of infinite wisdom and goodness. o 210 OUTLINES OF 295. Under this general title, however, are comprehended two very different descriptions of Philosophers ; those who admit, and those who deny, the freedom of human actions. The former only contend, that every thing is right, so far as it is the woi'k of God ; and endeavour to show, that the creation of be- ings endowed with free-will, and consequent- ly liable to moral delinquency, — and the government of the world by general laws, from which occasional evils must result, — furnish no solid objection to the perfection of the universe. But they hold, at the same time, that, although the permission of moral evil does not detract from the goodness of God, it is nevertheless imputable to man as a fault, and renders him justly obnoxious to punishment. This was the system of Plato, and of the best of the ancient philosophers, who, in most instances, state their doctrine in a manner perfectly consistent with man's free- will and moral agency. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 211 296. By some modern authors, the scheme of Optimism has been proposed in a form inconsistent with these suppositions, and which leads to a justification of moral evil, even with respect to the delinquent. 297. It is of great importance, to attend to the distinction between these two systems ; because it is customary among sceptical wri- ters to confound them studiously together, in order to extend to both, that ridicule to which the latter is justly entitled. — The scope of the argument, as stated in the for- mer system, may be collected from the follow- ing hints. 298. All the different subjects of human complaint may be reduced to two classes ; Moral and Physical evils. The former com- prehends those which arise from the abuse of Free-will ; the latter those which result from the established laws of nature, and which man cannot prevent by his own efforts. 212 OUTLINES OF 299. According to the definition now gi- ven of moral evil, the question, with respect to its permission, is reduced to this ; Why was man made a free agent ? A question to which it seems to be a sufficient reply : That perhaps the object of the Deity, in the go- vernment of the world, is not merely to communicate happiness, but to form his creatures to moral excellence; — or that the enjoyment of high degrees of happiness may perhaps necessarily require the previous ac- quisition of virtuous habits. 300. The sufferings produced by vice are, on this supposition, instances of the goodness of God, no less than the happiness resulting from virtue. 301. These observations justify Providence, not only for the permission of moral evil, but for the permission of many things which we commonly complain of as physical evils. — How great is the proportion of these, which are the obvious consequences of our vices and our MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 213 prejudices; and which, so far from being a necessary part of the order of nature, seem intended to operate in the progress of human affairs, as a gradual remedy against the causes which produce them ! 802. Some of our other complaints with respect to the lot of humanity will be found, on examination, to arise from partial views of the constitution of man, and from a want of attention to the circumstances which constitute his happiness, or promote his improvement. 303. Still, however, many evils remain, to which the foregoing principles do not apply. Such are those produced by what we com- monly call the accidents of life : — accidents from which no state of society, how perfect soever, can possibly be exempted ; and which, if they be subservient to any benevolent pur- poses, contribute to none within the sphere of our knowledge. 304. Of this class of pliysical evils, the ex- 214 OUTLINES OF planation must be derived from the general laws by which the government of the Deity appears to be conducted. The tendency of these laws will be found, in every instance, favourable to order and to happiness ; and it is one of the noblest employments of philoso- phy to investigate the beneficent purposes to which they are subservient. — In a world, however, which is thus governed, and where the inhabitants are free agents, occasional in- conveniencies and misfortunes must unavoid- ably be incurred. 305. In the mean time, from this influence of " Time and Chance," on human affairs, salutary effects arise. Virtue is rendered dis- interested, and the cliaracters of men are more completely displayed. 306. Many of our moral qualities, too, are the result of habits which imply the exist- ence of physical evils. Patience, Fortitude, Humanity, all suppose a scene, in which suf- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 215 ferings are to be endured, in our own case ; or relieved, in the case of others. 307. Thus it appears, not only that partial evils mmj he good with respect to the whole system ; but that their tendency is beneficial on the whole, even to that small part of it which we see. 308. The argument for the goodness of God, which arises from the foregoing considera- tions, will be much strengthened, if it shall appear farther, that the sum of happiness in human life far exceeds the sum of misery. 309. In opposition to this conclusion, the prevalence of moral evil over moral good, in the characters of men, has been insisted on by many writers ; and in proof of it, an ap- peal has been made to the catalogue of crimes which sully the history of past ages. 310. Whatever opinion we may adopt, with respect to the state of the fact, in this parti- 216 OUTLINES OF cular instance ; no objection can be drawn from it to the foregoing reasonings ; for moral evil is alone imputable to the being by whom it is committed. There is, however, no neces- sity for having recourse to this evasion. Cor- rupted as mankind are, the proportion of human life which is spent in vice, is inconsi- derable when compared with the whole of its extent. — History itself is a proof of this ; for the events it records are chiefly those w4iich are calculated, by their singularity, to engage the curiosity, and to interest the passions of the reader. — In computing, be- sides, the moral demerit of mankind, from their external actions, a large allowance ought to be made for erroneous speculative opi- nions ; for false conceptions of facts ; for pre- judices inspired by the influence of prevail- ing: manners ; and for habits contracted in- sensibly in early infancy. 311. With respect to the balance of phy- sical evil and physical good, the argument is still clearer; if it be acknowledged, {§ 304.), MORAL PHILOSOrHV. 217 that the general laws of nature are beneficent in their tendency, and that the inconveniencies which arise from them are only occasional. 312. Of these occasional evils, too, no in- considerable part may be traced to the obsta- cles, which human institutions oppose to the order of things recommended by nature. — How chimerical soever the speculations of philosophers concerning the perfection of le- gislation may be, they are useful, at least, in illustrating the wisdom and goodness of the Divine government. 313. Nor is it only in those laws which re- gulate the more essential interests of mankind, that a beneficent intention may be traced. What a rich provision is made for our enjoy- ment in the pleasures of the understanding, of the imagination, and of the heart ; and how little do they depend on the caprice of fortune ! — The positive accommodation of our sensitive powers to the scene we occupy, is still more wonderful : — Of the organ of smell, 218 OUTLINES OK for example to the perfumes of the vegetable world : of the taste, to the endless profusion of luxuries which the earth, the air, and the waters afford ; of the ear, to the melodies of the birds ; of the eye, to all the beauties and glories of the visible creation. 314. Among these marks of beneficence in the frame of man, the constitution of his mind, with respect to Habits, must not be o- mitted. So great is their influence, that there is hardly any situation to which his wishes may not be gradually reconciled ; nay, where he will not find himself, in time, more com- fortable, than in those which are looked up to with envy by the bulk of mankind. By this power of accommodation to external cir- cumstances, a remedy is, in part, provided for the occasional evils resulting from the opera- tion of general laws. 315. In judging of the feelings of those who are placed in situations very different from our own, due allowances are seldom made MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 219 for the effects of habit ; and, of consequence, our estimates of the happiness of life fall short greatly of the truth. II. OK THE EVIDENCES OF THE MORAL GOVERNMENT OF THE DEITY. 316. It was before remarked (§ 286.), that, as our first ideas of the moral attributes of God are derived from our own moral perceptions, so it is from the consideration of these, that the strongest proofs of his attributes arise. 317. The distinction between Right and Wrong, as was formely observed (§ 200.), is apprehended by the mind to be eternal and immutable, no less than the distinction between mathematical Truth and Falsehood. To argue, therefore, from our own moral judgments, to the administration of the Deity, cannot be justly censured as a rash extension, to the Divine nature, of suggestions resulting 220 OUTLINES OF from the arbitary constitution of our own minds. 318. The power we have of conceiving this distinction, is one of the most remarkable of those which raise us above the brutes ; and the sense of obligation which it involves, pos- sesses a distinguished pre-eminence over all our other principles of action, (§ 219.)- I'o act in conformity to our sense of rectitude, is plainly the highest excellence which our na- ture is capable of attaining ; nor can we avoid extendinp- the same rule of estimation to all intelligent beings whatever. 319. Besides these conclusions, with respect to the divine attributes, (which seem to be im- plied in our very perception of moral distinc- tions), there are others perfectly agreeable to them, which continually force themselves on the mind, in the exercise of our moral judg- ments, both with respect to our own conduct and that of other men. The reverence, whicli we feel to be due to the admonitions of Con- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 221 science ; the sense of merit and demerit, which accompanies our good and bad actions ; the warm interest we take in the fortunes of the virtuous ; the indignation we feel at the occa- sional triumphs of successful villany ; — all im- ply a secret conviction of the moral adminis- tration of the universe. 320. An examination of the ordinary course of human affairs adds to the force of these considerations ; and furnishes a proof from the fact, that, notwithstanding the seemingly pro- miscuous distribution of happiness and misery in this life, the reward of virtue, and the pu- nishment of vice, are the great objects of all the general laws by which the world is go- verned. The disorders, in the mean time, which, in such a world as ours, cannot fail to arise in particular instances ; when they are compared with our natural sense of good and of ill desert, afford a presumption, that in a fu- ture state, the moral government, whicli we see begun here, will be carried into complete execution. 222 OUTLINES OF SECTION I. OF THE DUTIES WHICH RESPECT THE DEITY. PRELIMINARY INQUIRY INTO THE PRINCIPLES OF NATURAL RELIGION. ARTICLE THIRD. OF A FUTURE STATE. 321. The consideration of the Divine at- tributes naturally leads our thoughts to the sequel of that plan of moral administration, which may be traced distinctly amidst all the apparent disorders of our present condition ; and which, our own moral constitution, joined to our conclusions concerning the perfections of God, afford us the strongest intimations, will be more completely unfolded in some sub- sequent stage of our being. The doctrine, in- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 223 deed, of a future state, seems to be, in a great measure, implied in every system of religious belief; for why were we rendered capable of elevating our thoughts to the Deity, if all our hopes are to terminate here ; or why were we furnished with powers which range through the infinity of space and of time, if our lot is to be the same with that of the beasts which perish? — But although the doctrine of a future state be implied in every scheme of religion ; the truths of religion are not necessarily im- plied in the doctrine of a future state. Even absolute Atheism does not destroy all the argu- ments for the immortality of the soul. Whe- ther it be owing to an over-ruling intelligence or not, it is 2ifact which no man can deny, that there are general laws which regulate the course of human affairs, and that, even in this world, we see manifest indications of a con- nection between virtue and happiness. — Why may not necessity continue that existence it at first gave birth to ; and why may not the con- nection between virtue and happiness subsist for ever ? 224 OUTLINES OF I. OF THE ARGUMENT FOR A FUTURE STATE DERIVED FROM THE NATURE OF MIND. 322. In collecting the various evidences which the light of nature affords for a future state, too much stress has commonly been laid upon the soul's Immateriality. The proper use of that doctrine is not to demonstrate that the soul is physically and necessarily immortal ; but to refute the objections which have been urged against the possibility of its existing in a separate state from the body. Although our knowledge of the nature of Mind may not be sufficient to afford us any positive ar- gument on this subject ; yet, even if it can be shewn, that the dissolution of the body does not necessarily infer the extinction of the soul; and still more, if it can be shewn, that the pre- sumption is in favour of the contrary supposi- tion, the moral proofs of a future retribution will meet with a more easy reception, when MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 225 the doctrine is freed from the metaphysical difficulties which it has been apprehended to involve. 323. It was before remarked (§ 28.), that our notions both of body and mind are mere- ly relative ; that we know the one only by its sensible qualities, and the other by the opera- tions of which we are conscious. — To say, therefore, of Mind, that it is not material, is to affirm a proposition, the truth of which is involved in the only conceptions of Matter and of Mind that we are capable of forming. 324. The doubts that have been suggested, with respect to the essential distinction be- tween Matter and Mind, derive all their plau- sibility from the habits of inattention we ac- quire in early infancy to our mental opera- tions. It was plainly the intention of Nature, that our thoughts should be habitually direct- ed to things external ; and, accordingly, the bulk of mankind are not only indisposed to study the intellectual phenomena, but are inca- 226 OUTLINES OF pable of that degree of reflection which is ne- cessary for their examination. Hence it is, that when we begin to analyze our own inter- nal constitution, we find the facts it presents to us so very intimately associated in our con- ceptions with the qualities of Matter, that it is impossible for us to draw distinctly and stea- dily the line between them ; and that when Mind and Matter are concerned in the same event, the former is either entirely overlooked, or is regarded only as an accessory principle, dependent for its existence on the latter. — The tendency which all men have to refer the sen- sation of colour to the objects by which it is excited, may serve to illustrate the manner in which the qualities of mind and body come to be blended in our apprehensions. 325. If these remarks be well founded, the prejudices which give support to the scheme of Materialism, are not likely to be cu- red by any metaphysical reasonings, how clear and conclusive soever, so long as the judg- ment continues to be warped by such obsti- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 227 nate associations as have just been mentioned. A habit of reflecting on the laws of thought, as they are to be collected from our own con- sciousness, together with a habit of resisting those illusions of the fancy, which lead super- fical inquirers to substitute analogies for facts, will gradually enable us to make the pheno- mena of Matter and those of Mind distinct objects of attention ; and, as soon as this hap- pens, the absurdity of Materialism must ap- pear intuitively obvious. 326. It is entirely owing to our early fa- miliarity with material objects, and our early habits of inattention to what passes within us, that Materialism is apt to appear at first sight, to be less absurd than the opposite sys- tem, which represents Mind as the only exist- ence in the universe. Of the two doctrines, that of Berkeley is at once the safest and the most philosophical ; not only as it contradicts merely the suggestions of our perceptions, while the other contradicts the suggestions of our consciousness ; but as various plausible 228 OUTLINES OF arguments may be urged in its favour, from the phenomena of dreaming ; whereas no in- stance can be mentioned, in which sensation and intelligence appear to result from any combination of the particles of Matter. 327- Besides the evidences for the exist- ence of Mind, which our own conscious- ness affords, and those which are exhibit- ed by other men, and by the lower ani- mals, there are many presented to us by every part of the material world. We are so constituted, that every change in it we see suggests to us the notion of an efficient cause ; — and every combination of means conspiring to an end suggests to us the notion of intelligence. And accordingly, the various changes which take place in nature, and the order and beauty of the universe, have, in every age, been regarded as the effects of power and wisdom ; that is, of the operation of Mind. In the material world, there- fore, as well as in the case of animated na- ture, we are led to conceive Body as a pas- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 229 sive subject, and Mind as the moving and go- verning agent. And it deserves attention, that, in the former class of phenomena, Mind appears to move and arrange the parts of mat- ter, vi^ithout being united with it as in the case of animal life. 328. There are various circumstances which render it highly probable, that the union between soul and body, which takes place in our present state, so far from being essential to the exercise of our powers and faculties, was intended to limit the sphere of our infor- mation ; and to prevent us from acquiring, in this early stage of our being, too clear a view of the constitution and government of the uni- verse. Indeed, when we reflect on the diffe- rence between the operations of Mind and the qualities of Matter, it appears much more wonderful, that the two substances should be so intimately united, as we find them actually to be, than to suppose that the former may exist in a conscious and intelligent state when separated from the latter. 230 OUTLINES or 329. The most plausible objections, never- theless, to the doctrine of a future state, have been drawn from the intimacy of this union. From the effects of intoxication, madness, and other diseases, it appears that a certain condi- tion of the body is necessary to the intellec- tual operations ; and, in the case of old men, it is generally found that a decline of the fa- culties keeps pace M'ith the decay of bodily health and vigour. The few exceptions that occur to the universality of this fact only prove, that there are some diseases fatal to life, which do not injure those parts of the body with which the intellectual operations are more immediately connected. 330. The reply which Cicero has made to these objections is equally ingenious and solid. " Suppose a person to have been educated, " from his infancy, in a chamber where he " enjoyed no opportunity of seeing external " objects, but through a small chink in the " window-shutter ; would he not be apt to " consider this chink as essential to his vision ; MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 231 " and would it not be difficult to persuade *' him that his prospects would be enlarged " by demolishing the walls of his prison ?" Admitting that this analogy is founded mere- ly on fancy ; yet if it be granted that there is no absurdity in the supposition, it furnishes a sufficient answer to all the reasonings which have been stated against the possibility of the soul's separate existence, from the considera- tion of its present union with the body. 331. In support of the foregoing conclu- sions, many strong arguments might be de- rived from an accurate examination and ana- lysis of our ideas of Matter and its qualities. But such speculations could not be rendered intelligible, without a previous explanation of some principles too abstruse to be introdu- ced here. 232 OUTLINES OF II. OF THE EVIDENCES FOR A FUTURE STATE, ARISING FROM THE HUMAN CONSTITUTION, AND FROM THE CIRCUMSTANCES IN WHICH MAN IS PLACED. 332. The great extent of this subject ne- cessarily confines the following remarks to an enumeration of the principal heads of the ar- gument. These are stated without any illus- tration. (1.) The natural desire of immortality ; and the anticipations of futurity inspired by hope. (2.) The natural apprehensions of the mind when under the influence of remorse. (3.) The exact accommodation of the con- dition of the lower animals to their instincts and to their sensitive powers ; — contrasted with the unsuitableness of the present state of things to the intellectual faculties of man, — to his capacities of enjoyment, — and to the MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 233 conceptions of happiness and of ])erfection, which he is able to form. (4.) The foundation which is laid in the principles of our constitution for a progressive and an unlimited improvement. (5.) The information we are rendered ca- pable of acquiring, concerning the more re- mote parts of the universe ; the unlimited range, which is opened to the human ima- gination through the immensity of space and of time ; and the ideas, however imperfect, which philosophy affords us of the existence and attributes of an over-ruling Mind : — Ac- quisitions, for which an obvious final cause may be traced, on the supposition of a future state ; but which, if that supposition be reject- ed, could have no other effect than to make the business of life appear unworthy of our regard. (6.) The tendency of the infirmities of age and of the pains of disease, to strengthen and confirm our moral habits ; and the dif- 234 OUTLINES OF liciilty of accounting, upon the hypothesis of annihilation, for those sufferings which com- monly put a period to the existence of man. (7.) The discordance between our moral judgments and feelings, and the course of hu- man affairs. (8.) The analogy of the material world ; in some parts of which the most complete and the most systematical order may be traced ; and of which our views always become the more satisfactory, the wider our knowledge extends. It is the supposition of a future state alone, that can furnish a key to the present disorders of the moral world ; and without it, many of the most striking phenomena of hu- man life must remain for ever inexplicable. (9.) The inconsistency of supposing, that the moral laws which regulate the course of human affairs have no reference to any thing beyond the limits of the present scene ; when all the bodies which compose the visible uni- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 235 verse appear to be related to each other, as parts of one great physical system. 333. Of the different considerations now mentioned, there is not one, perhaps, which, taken singly, would be sufficient to establish the truth they are brought to prove ; but ta- ken in conjunction, their force appears irre- sistible. They not only all terminate in the same conclusion, but they mutually reflect light on each other ; and they have that sort of consistency and connection among them- selves, which could hardly be supposed to take place among a series of false propositions. 334. The same remark may be extended to the other principles of Natural Religion. They all hang together in such a manner, that, if one of them be granted, it facilitates the way for the reception of the rest. 3S5. Nor is it merely with each other that these principles are connected. They have a relation to all the other principles of Moral Philosophy ; — insomuch, that a person who 236 OUTLINES OF entertains just views of the one, never fails to entertain also just views of the other. Per- haps it would not be going too far to assert, that they have a relation to almost all the truths we know, in the moral, the intellectual, and the material worlds. One thing is cer- tain, that, in proportion as our knowledge ex- tends, our doubts and objections disappear ; new light continually breaks in upon us from every quarter, and more of order and system, appears in the universe. 336. It is a strong confirmation of these remarks, that the most important discoveries, both in moral and physical science, have been made by men friendly to the principles of natural religion ; and that those writers, who have affected to be sceptical on this last sub- ject, have in general been paradoxical and sophistical in their other inquiries. — This consideration, while it illustrates the connec- tion which different classes of truth have with each other, proves, that it is to a mind well fitted for the discovery and reception of truth MORAL rHILOSOPHY. 237 in general, that the evidences of Religion are the most satisfactory. 337. The influence which the belief of a future state has on the conduct and on the enjoyments of mankind, also tends to con- firm its credibility. This is so remarkable, that it has led some to consider it merely as an invention of politicians, to preserve the good order of society, and to support the feeble mind under the sufferings of human life. But if it be allowed that it has really such a tendency. Can it be supposed that the Author of the universe should have left con- sequences so very momentous, to depend on the belief of a chimera, which was in time to vanish before the light of philosophy ? Is it not more probable, that the enlargement of our knowledge, to which we are so power- fully prompted by the principle of curiosity, will tend to increase, and not to diminish, the virtue and the happiness of mankind ; and instead of spreading a gloom over creation, and cxthiguishing the hopes which nature 238 OUTLINES OF inspires, will gradually unfold to us, in the moral world, the same order and beauty we admire in the material ? 338. After the view which has been given of the principles of Natural Religion, little remains to be added concerning the duties which respect the Deity. To employ our fa- culties in studying those evidences of power, of wisdom, and of goodness, which he has displayed in his works ; as it is the founda- tion, in other instances, of our sense of reli- gious obligation ; so it is, in itself, a duty in- cumbent on us, as reasonable and moral be- ings, capable of recognizing the existence of an Almighty cause, and of feeling corres- ponding sentiments of devotion. By those who entertain just opinions on this most im- portant of all subjects, the following practical consequences, which comprehend some of the chief effects of religion on the temper and MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 239 conduct, will be readily admitted as self-evi- dent propositions. 339. In the first place : If the Deity be possessed of infinite moral excellence, we must feel towards him, in an infinite degree, all those affections of love, gratitude, and confidence, which are excited by the imper- fect worth we observe among our fellow-crea- tures ; for it is by conceiving all that is bene- volent and amiable in man, raised to the high- est perfection, that we can alone form some faint notion of the Divine nature. — To culti- vate, therefore, an habitual love and reverence of the Supreme Being, may be justly consi- dered as the first great branch of morality ; nor is the virtue of that man complete, or even consistent with itself, in whose mind these sentiments of piety are wanting. 340. Secondly : Although lleligion can, with no propriety, be considered as the sole foundation of morality, yet, when we are convinced that God is infinitely good, and 240 OUTLINES OF that he is the friend and protector of virtue, this belief affords the most powerfid induce- ments to the practice of every branch of our duty. It leads us to consider conscience as the vicegerent of God, and to attend to its suggestions, as to the commands of that Being from whom we have received our existence, and the great object of whose government is to promote the happiness and the perfection of his whole creation. 341. Thirdly : A regard to our own hap- piness in the future stages of our being (which will be afterwards shown to constitute a mo- ral obligation) ought to conspire with the o- ther motives already mentioned, in stimulat- ing our virtuous exertions. The moral per- ceptions we have received from God, more particularly our sense of merit and demerit, may be considered as clear indications of fu- ture rewards and punishments, which, in due time, he will not fail to distribute. Religion is therefore a species of authoritative law, en- forced by the most awful sanctions, and ex- :M01iAL PHILOSOPHY. 241 tending not merely to our actions, but to our thoughts. — In the case of tlie lower orders of men, who are incapable of abstract specula- tion, and whose moral feelings cannot be sup- posed to have received much cultivation ; it is chiefly this view of Religion, which is ad- dressed to their hopes and fears, that secures a faithful discharge of their social duties. 342. In the last place : A sense of Religion, where it is sincere, will necessarily be attend- ed with a complete resignation of our own will to that of the Deity ; as it teaches us to regard every event, even the most afflicting, as calculated to promote beneficent purposes which we are unable to comprehend ; and to promote finally the perfection and happiness of our own nature. Q 242 OUTLINES OF SECTION II. OF THE DUTIES WHICH RESPECT OUR FEL LOW-CREATURES. 343. Under this title, it is not proposed to give a complete enumeration of our social duties, but only to point out some of the most important ; chiefly with a view to shew the imperfection of those systems of morals, which attempt to resolve the whole of virtue into one particular principle. Among these, that which resolves virtue into Benevolence is undoubtedly the most amiable ; but even this system will appear, from the following re- marks, to be not only inconsistent with truth, but to lead to dangerous consequences. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 24:^ ARTICLE FIRST. OF BENEVOLENCE. 344. It has been supposed by some moral- ists, that benevolence is the only immediate object of moral approbation ; and that the ob- ligation of all our moral duties arises entirely from their apprehended tendency to promote the happiness of society. 345. Notwithstanding the various appear- ances in human nature, which seem at first view to favour this theory, it is liable to in- surmountable objections. If the merit of an action depended on no other circumstance, than the quantity of good intended by the agent, it would follow, that the rectitude of an action could be, in no case, influenced by the mutual relations of the parties ; — a con- clusion directly contrary to the universal judg- ments of mankind, Avith respect to the obliga- tions of Gratitude, of \''cracity, and of Jus- tice. 244 . OUTLINES OF 346. Unless we admit these duties to be immediately obligatory, we must admit the maxim, that a good end may sanctify what- ever means are necessary for its accomplish- ment ; or, in other words, that it would be lawful for us to dispense Avith the obligations of gratitude, of veracity, and of justice, when- ever, by doing so, we had a prospect of pro- moting any of the essential interests of society. 347. It may perhaps be urged, that a regard to utility would lead, in such cases, to an in- variable adherence to general rules; because in this way more good is produced, on the whole, than could be obtained by any occasional de- viations from them ; — that it is this idea of utility which first leads us to approve of the different virtues, and that afterwards habit, and the association of ideas, make us observe their rules, without thinking of consequences. But is not this to adopt that mode of reason- ing, whicli the patrons of the Benevolent sys- tem have censured so severely in those philoso- phers who have attempted to deduce all our MORAL PHILOSOPHY. . 245 actions from Self-love ; and may not the ar- guments they have employed against their adversaries be retorted upon themselves ? 348. That the practice of veracity and jus- tice, and of all our other duties, is useful to mankind, is acknowledged by moralists of all descriptions ; and there is good reason for be- lieving, that if a person saw all the conse- quences of his actions, he would perceive that an adherence to their rules is useful and ad- vantageous on the whole, even in those cases in which his limited views incline him to think otherwise. It \s2y0ssihle, that in the Deity, be- nevolence, or a regard to utility, may be the sole principle of action ; and that the ultimate end for which he enjoined to his creatures the duties of veracity and justice, was to secure their own happiness ; but still with respect to man, they are indispensable laws ; for he has an immediate perception of their rectitude. And, indeed, if he had not ; but were left to deduce their rectitude from the consequences Avhich they have a tendency to produce, it may 246 OUTLINES OF be doubted if there would be enough of virtue left in the world to hold society together. 349. These remarks are applicable to a con- siderable variety of moral systems, which have been offered to the world under very different forms ; but which agree with each other, in deriving the practical rules of vir- tuous conduct, from considerations of Utility. All of these systems are but modifications of the old doctrine, which resolves the whole of virtue into Benevolence. 350. But although Benevolence does not constitute the whole of our duty, it must be acknowledged to be, not only one of its most important branches, but the object of a very peculiar and enthusiastic admiration. The plausibility of the systems, to which the pre- ceding observations relate, is a sufficient proof of the rank it is universally understood to hold among the virtues. 351. It may be proper to add, that the MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 247 Benevolence which is an object of moral ap- probation, is a fixed and settled disposition to promote the happiness of our fellow-crea- tures. It is peculiar to a rational nature, and is not to be confounded with those kind af- fections, which are common to us with the brutes. These are subsidiary, in fact, to the principle of Benevolence; and they are always amiable qualities in a character : but, so far as they are constitutional, they are certainly in no respect meritorious. Where they are possessed in an eminent degree, we may perhaps consider them as a ground of moral esteem ; because they indicate the })ains which have been bestowed on their cul- tivation, and a course of active virtue in which they have been exercised and strength- ened. A person, on the contrary, who wants them, is always an object of horror ; — chiefly because we know, that they are only to be eradicated by long habits of profligacy ; and partly in consequence of the uneasiness we feel, when we see tlie ordinary covu'se of na- ture violated in any of her productions. 248 OUTLINES OF 352. Some of the writers who resolve vir- tue into Benevolence, have not attended suf- ficiently to this consideration. They fre- quently speak of virtuous and vicious affec- tions ; whereas these epithets belong, not to affections, but to actions ; or, still more pro- perly, to the dispositions and purposes from which actions proceed. 353. Where a rational and settled Bene- volence forms a part of a character, it will ren- ,der the conduct perfectly uniform, and will exclude the possibility of those inconsistencies that are frequently observable in individuals, who give themselves up to the guidance of particular affections, either private or public. In truth, all those offices, whether apparently trifling or important, by which the happiness of other men is affected ; Civility, Gentleness, Kindness, Humanity, Patriotism, Universal Benevolence ; are only diversified expressions of the same disposition, according to the cir- cumstances in which it operates, and the rela- tions wliich the agent bears to others. ilOllAI. i'HILOSOPHY. 249 ARTICLE SECOND. OF JUSTICE 354. The word Justice, in its most exten- sive signification, denotes that disposition, which leads us, in cases where our own tem- per, or passions, or interest, are concerned, to determine and to act, without being biassed by partial considerations. 355. In order to free our minds from the influence of these, experience teaches us ei- ther to recollect the judgments we have for- merly passed in similar circumstances, on the conduct of others ; or to state cases to our- selves, in which We, and all our personal con- cerns, are left entirely out of the question. 356. But although expedients of this sort are necessary to the best of men, for correcting their moral judgments upon questions in which 250 OUTLINES OF they tiiemselves are parties, it will not there- fore foilov/, (as some have supposed,*) that our only ideas of right and wrong, with re- spect to our own conduct, are derived from our sentiments with respect to the conduct of others. The intention of such expedients is merely to obtain a just and fair view of the circumstances ; and after this view has been obtained, the question still remains, what con- stitutes the obligation upon us to act in a par- ticular manner? For it is of great conse- quence to remark, that when we have once satisfied ourselves with respect to the conduct which an impartial judge would approve of, we feel that this conduct is right for us, and that we are under a moral obligation to act accordingly. If we had had recourse to no expedient for correcting our first judgment, we should still have formed some judgment or other, of a particular conduct, as right, wrong, or indifferent ; and the only difference See Mr Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments. MOllAL PHILOSOPHY. 251 would have been, that we should probably have decided erroneously, from a false or a partial view of the case. 857. As it vv^ould be endless to attempt to point out all the various forms in which the disposition of Justice may display itself in life, it is necessary to confine our attention to a few of its more important effects. These may be arranged under two heads ; according as it operates, — 1*^, in restraining the partialities of the temper and of the passions ; and, 2Iii the Sciences Of the Orio-in and Proi>Tess of the Arts and MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 317 Article VII. Of the Origin and Progress of Commerce. Article VIII. Of the Origin and Progress of Government, Rank, and Subordination. Article IX. Of the Origin and Progress of Municipal Systems of Jurisprudence. Article X. Of Diversities in the History of the Species, arising from the influence of Climate and Si- tuation. CHAP. II. OF THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF LEGIS- LATION AND GOVERNMENT. SECT. I. OF political (ECONOMY. Article I. Of the Writings of Grotkis and his Succes- sors, on Natural Jurisprudence, and their in- 318 OUTLINES OF fliience in suggesting the Modern Speculations concerning Political Economy. Article II. Of the Objects of Political Economy, and the more important general Conclusions to which the Study of it has lead. Article III. Of the Coincidence of the Principles of Justice and of Expediency, in the Political Conclusions to which they lead. Article IV. Of the Connection between just Views of Political Economy, and the Intellectual and Moral Improvement of Mankind. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 319 CHAP. II. SECT. II. OF THE DIFFERENT FUNCTIONS OF GOVERN- MENT ; AND OF THE VARIOUS FORMS IN WHICH THEY ARE COMBINED IN THE CON- STITUTIONS OF DIFFERENT STATES. Article I. Of the Legislative, Judicial, and Executive Powers. Article II. Of the Simple Forms of Government, ac- cording to the definitions of speculative Po- liticians ; and of the Uses to whicli this theo- retical view of the subject is subservient, in the examination of actual Constitutions. Article HI. Of Mixed Governments. Article IV. Of the English Constitution. 320 OUTLINES OF Article V. Of the Influence of Forms of Government on National Character and Manners. Article VI. Of the Duties arising from the Political Union. Article VII. Of the Political Relations of different States to each other ; and of the Laws of Morality as applicable to Nations. FINIS. AUCHIE, PRINTER, EDINBURGH. UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY Los Angeles This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. ::4 3|t ivri\j_ J X39d V- fEB23l99S 3^ ^'- QJL "(§§■? i 6- IS95 ^%-- ^ 0CT03i9