INTRODUCTORY PHILOSOPHY J. F. SOLLIER, S.T.D., Provincial S.M. Smprimatttt : ^ JOHN CARDINAL FARLEY, Archbishop of New York. February 7th, 1912. INTRODUCTORY PHILOSOPHY A TEXT-BOOK FOR COLLEGES AND HIGH SCHOOLS BY CHARLES A. DUBRAY, S.M., PH. D. PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY AT THE MARIST COLLEGE, WASHINGTON, D.C. LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. FOURTH AVENUE & 30rn STREET, NEW YORK LONDON, BOMBAY AND CALCUTTA 1912 COPYRIGHT, IQI2, BY LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO, ALL RIGHTS RESERVED THB. PLIMPTON-PRESS [ W D O ] NORWOOD. MASS'U'S'A PREFACE THE efforts which have been made in recent years to provide the beginner in philosophy with a text-book suited to his needs are justified both by the importance of the subject and by the requirements of educational method. It is obvious that an intro- duction should really introduce, in other words that it should present philosophy in such a way as to arouse the student's interest, give him a firm grasp of essentials, and encourage him to further study. But how these results are to be secured is still an open question. The books that have so far appeared have, each from its own point of view, distinct advantages either as outlining the history of philosophical problems, or as setting forth the claims of rival systems, or as explaining the principles which serve as the foundation of some special system and a basis of criticism in dis- cussing variant theories. An introduction that will combine these several utilities seems to be our present need. Dr. Dubray's aim in this volume is to lead the student by easy approaches into the field of philosophy and to show him its divisions with their several problems and the solutions which these have received. In accordance with the principles of correct method, the knowledge which the student has already acquired is made to serve as the starting-point, and from this he is led on to the con- sideration of more abstract philosophical concepts and theories. These again are presented in clear statement and orderly sequence, with sufficient indication of outstanding questions, yet without the excess of detail which sometimes destroys proportion or results in narrowness of view. At the same time, definite conclusions are presented with the evidence on which they rest, so that the student may get from his use of the book not merely a lot of vague question- ings, but a certain amount of positive knowledge and critical direction for later investigation. 247041 VI PREFACE Students of Catholic philosophy will appreciate both the form and the content of this manual. While adhering to the principles of Scholasticism, the author has kept steadily in view the develop- ment of modern philosophy and the recent advances of science. It is not possible of course to effect a conciliation all along the line where the aim is rather to open up the whole subject. But impor- tant service, can be rendered by illustrating the method by which the old and the new may be combined. This feature of the book is the more helpful because the student, working simultaneously in other departments of knowledge, is sure to come upon problems which lead up to philosophy. This is true not only of the physical and biological sciences, but also of the social and historical. In each of these, whatever be the special subject of study, there is needed a certain seasoning of philosophical principle and method in order that the student may see scientific facts, not in their first crudeness or isolation, but as parts of a larger truth. In this way he will not only give to each item of knowledge its proportionate value, but will also form the habit of philosophical thinking, which in itself is the best result that can be derived from an introductory course. In Catholic colleges, importance has always been attached to the study of philosophy both as a means of culture and as a source of information regarding the great truths which are influential in supporting Christian belief and in shaping character. It is rightly considered essential for every graduate to have a training in logic and in the fundamentals of psychology, ethics, and metaphysics. But if this training is to be successful, philosophy must be presented not as a complex of abstruse speculations on far-off inaccessible topics, but as a system of truths that enter with vital consequence into our ordinary thinking and our everyday conduct. For be- ginners especially it is not the best plan to take up first the science and art of reasoning where the formal treatment predominates. On the other hand, the study of logic itself becomes more attractive when it follows that of ethics or psychology. There is yet consider- able difference of opinion as to which of the philosophical disciplines should have precedence; but if the choice is to be made with due regard to the scientific subjects which have previously been studied, PREFACE Vll psychology would seem to have the strongest claim. The recogni- tion of the value of its empirical methods is quite compatible with the philosophical discussion of its central problems, and its own conclusions find numerous applications in other fields of research. Teachers of philosophy realize that the difficulties encountered in an introductory course can, in part at least, be overcome by the use of a suitable text-book. As it is not desirable that the student ,y should memorize a set of formulae for the purpose of recitation orr examination, it is also unwise to expand each topic in such lengthy' fulness that no margin is left for individual thinking. The con- ciseness that marked the writings of the great Schoolmen is an art that may yet be revived. It leaves the teacher scope to de- velop the text, to suggest new points of view, and to select special topics for discussion. The best features of the lecture method may in this way be added to the ordinary class exercise and the student be gradually led on to examine each statement in the light of established principles and with a single eye for the truth which is the attitude and temper of the really critical mind. Dr. Dubray has profited by his experience as a teacher, and in this volume he offers the results with the hope that they may be useful to others. He has certainly contributed his share toward encouraging the beginner in philosophy and has indicated a line of approach which is neither too steep nor too easy. If it smoothes out some of the hard places, it leaves ample room for hard thinking. EDWARD A. PACE THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA March 7, 1912 CONTENTS GENERAL INTRODUCTION I. THE NATURE OF PHILOSOPHY 3 1. What has been done already 3 2. What remains to be done 4 3. Definition of philosophy 7.* 4. Division of philosophy 9 5. Method of philosophy n II. GENERAL VIEW OF THE WORLD AND OF MAN 13 1. The self and the not-self 13 2. The not-self and its obvious characteristics . . . . . . . 15 3. Relations of the self with the external world 17 4. Obvious characteristics of the self 19 PSYCHOLOGY, OR THE EMPIRICAL STUDY OF THE MIND INTRODUCTION I. THE NATURE OF PSYCHOLOGY 22 1. Definition and subject-matter 22 2. Method of psychology . 26 3. Division of mental processes 27 II. THE GENERAL LAWS OF THE MIND 29 1. A danger to be avoided 29 2. General processes and attitudes of the mind 31 3. General laws of the mind 35 CHAPTER I KNOWLEDGE PRELIMINARY REMARKS 40 ARTICLE I. SENSE PRESENTATION I. SENSATION 44 1. Sensation in general 44 2. Internal or general sensations 46 iz X CONTENTS 3. External sensations 46 (a) Smell and taste 47 (6) Touch 49 (c) Hearing 5 1 (d) Vision 52 4. Number and comparison of the senses 53 5. Psychophysics and psychophysiology 56 II. PERCEPTION 62 1. Analysis and genesis of sense-perception 62 2. Perceptions of smell and taste 64 3. Auditory perceptions 65 4. Tactual perceptions 66 5. Visual perceptions 67 ARTICLE II. SENSE REPRESENTATION I. THE MENTAL IMAGE 71 1. Nature of the image 71 2. Properties of the image 73 3. Association and its laws 76 II. IMAGINATION 78 1. Nature of imagination 78 2. Importance of imagination 79 3. Training of the imagination 81 III. MEMORY 83 1. Nature of memory 83 2. Qualities and conditions of a good memory ....... 85 3. Culture of memory 86 4. Time-perception 88 IV. ILLUSIONS or THE SENSES 89 1. Nature of illusions and hallucinations 89 2. Main causes of illusions and hallucinations 90 ARTICLE III. CONCEPTION I. CHARACTERISTICS OF THE CONCEPT 92 1. Various terms explained 92 2. The essential characteristics of the concept 94 II. GENESIS OF THE CONCEPT 9 8 1. Various proposed systems 08 2. Discussion of the systems , . , 102 ARTICLE IV. JUDGMENT I. NATURE OF THE JUDGMENT I07 1. The psychological process I0 y 2. Various kinds of judgments IO 8 CONTENTS xi II. GENESIS OF THE JUDGMENT no 1. General no 2. Genesis of necessary judgments .112 3. Genesis of mediate judgments. Inference. Reasoning . . . 115 4. The processes of judging and reasoning in ordinary life . . . 117 ARTICLE V. LANGUAGE I. THE FUNCTION OF LANGUAGE 122 1. Signs in general. Signs of mental processes 122 2. Special signs of intellectual ideas. Language 124 II. LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT 126 1. In the speaker or writer 126 2. In the hearer or reader 128 REMARKS ON THIS CHAPTER .129 1. General conspectus of cognitive faculties 129 2. Genesis of some ideas and principles 131 3. Development of intellectual cognition 133 CHAPTER II FEELING INTRODUCTORY REMARKS 137 ARTICLE I. FEELINGS OF PLEASURE AND PAIN I. NATURE AND LAWS OF THESE FEELINGS 139 1. Nature of the feelings 139 2. Laws of feelings 140 II. IMPORTANCE OF FEELINGS .142 ARTICLE II. EMOTIONS I. SELF-REGARDING EMOTIONS 145 II. ALTRUISTIC EMOTIONS 148 ARTICLE III. SENTIMENTS I. INTELLECTUAL SENTIMENTS 153 II. ^ESTHETIC SENTIMENTS 155 III. MORAL SENTIMENTS . 157 IV. RELIGIOUS SENTIMENTS 158 CONCLUSION. IMPORTANCE AND CULTURE OF AFFECTIVE LIFE . . . 160 1. Importance of affective life 160 2. Cultivation of affective life 163 xil CONTENTS CHAPTER III ACTING AND WILLING ARTICLE I. ACTION AND MODES OF ACTION I. INTRODUCTION 166 1. Meaning of action 166 2. General modes of action 167 II. NON- VOLITIONAL ACTION 169 1. Random, automatic, and reflex movements . . . . . . . . 169 2. Impulsive and instinctive movements 171 III. VOLITIONAL ACTION 173 IV. HABIT 175 ARTICLE II. DETERMINANTS AND FREEDOM OF THE WILL 1. Determinants and motors of the will 177 2. Freedom of the will 178 CONCLUSION. CULTIVATION OF THE WILL 185 1. The qualities and defects of the will 185 2. Some principles to be used in will-culture 187 CHAPTER IV SUPPLEMENTARY SOME SPECIAL RELATIONS AND MODES OF MENTAL PROCESSES I. MIND AND ORGANISM JQO 1. Mutual relations of dependence and influence 190 2. Cerebral localization I92 II. SOME SPECIAL MENTAL CONDITIONS 194 CONCLUSION OF PSYCHOLOGY CHARACTER AND PERSONALITY ... 203 LOGIC, OR THE NORMATIVE SCIENCE OF THE INTELLECT INTRODUCTION 205 CHAPTER I REASONING ARTICLE I. THE IDEA I. NATURE OF IDEAS 2o8 i. The idea in logic 20 g CONTENTS xiii 2. Intension and extension of ideas and terms . . . . . . . 211 3. Division of ideas and terms 212 II. DEFINITION AND DIVISION 215 1. Definition 215 2. Division 217 ARTICLE II. THE JUDGMENT 1. Nature of the judgment and proposition 219 2. Division of judgments and propositions 219 3. Related propositions 222 ARTICLE III. REASONING I. THE PERFECT SYLLOGISM 226 1. Nature of the syllogism 226 2. Figures and moods of the syllogism 227 3. Rules of the syllogism 228 II. VARIOUS KINDS OF ARGUMENTS 230 III. PRINCIPLES OF THE SYLLOGISM 233 CHAPTER II METHOD OBJECT OF THIS CHAPTER 237 ARTICLE I. THE TERMINI I. THE END TO BE REACHED 238 1. The nature of science 238 2. Classification of sciences 240 II. THE STARTING-POINT . 243 ARTICLE II. THE PROGRESS I. THE VALUE OF THE ARGUMENTS 244 1. Demonstration 244 2. Probable arguments 246 II. THE Two GENERAL METHODS 250 . Induction 251 2. Deduction 254 III. OBSTACLES 256 1. Fallacies 256 2. Error 260 CONCLUSION OF LOGIC . 262 xiv CONTENTS AESTHETICS, OR THE NORMATIVE SCIENCE OF THE FEELINGS OF THE BEAUTIFUL INTRODUCTION 265 1. What is aesthetics? 265 2. The place of aesthetics 266 CHAPTER I BEAUTY 1. Subjective aspect 270 2. Objective conditions 271 CHAPTER II THE FINE ARTS 1. Nature of the fine arts 275 2. Art and nature 276 3. The production of works of art 277 4. Classification of the fine arts 279 ETHICS, OR THE NORMATIVE SCIENCE OF THE WILL INTRODUCTION I. THE MEANING OF ETHICAL SCIENCE 2 g r 1. Facts 2 gj. 2. The science of ethics 2 gx II. PSYCHOLOGICAL CONDITIONS OF MORALITY I 287 y Knowledge * 2 g 7 , - Feelings 288 \ 3- Will 28o CHAPTER I FUNDAMENTAL ETHICS ARTICLE I. THE MORAL NORMS OR LAWS i. Definition and divisions CONTENTS XV 2. Characteristics of the moral law 294 3. Existence of the moral law 295 II. CONSCIENCE 299 1. Nature of conscience 299 2. Value of conscience as the rule of actions 300 ARTICLE II. THE MORAL STANDARD I. THE QUESTION STATED 303 1. The object of the present article 303 2. Different views classified 304 II. THE QUESTION DISCUSSED 306 1. Positive determination of the moral good 306 2. Morality based on a special sentiment 309 3. Morality relative to pleasure and utility 313 4. Morality dependent on reason 319 5. The ultimate foundation of the moral law 323 6. Conclusion 326 CHAPTER II APPLIED ETHICS RIGHT AND DUTY 328 ARTICLE I. PERSONAL ETHICS OR DUTIES TOWARD ONESELF EXISTENCE OF DUTIES TOWARD ONESELF 331 I. DUTIES REFERRING CHIEFLY TO THE MIND 332 1. Personal dignity 332 2. Intelligence 333 3- Will 334 4. Conclusion 336 II. DUTIES REFERRING CHIEFLY TO THE BODY 337 1. Negative duties 337 2. Positive duties 341 ARTICLE II. SOCIAL ETHICS OR DUTIES OF MAN TOWARD OTHER MEN EXISTENCE AND NATURE OF THESE DUTIES 341 I. DUTIES TOWARD INDIVIDUAL MEN 344 1. Duties toward the person of Others 344 2. Duties toward the property of others 347 II. SOCIAL DUTIES 352 1. The family 353 2. The state 354 CONCLUSION OF ETHICS 360 XVI CONTENTS EPISTEMOLOGY, OR THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE INTRODUCTION I. THE NATURE OF EPISTEMOLOGY 362 II. FACTS AND PROBLEMS 364 1. Facts 364 2. Problems 368 III. METHOD 369 CHAPTER I IS CERTITUDE JUSTIFIED? 1. Scepticism 373 2. Agnosticism 376 3. Dogmatism 377 CHAPTER II CERTITUDES 1. Facts 380 2. Empiricism 382 3. Rationalism 383 CHAPTER III WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE? I. FACT OF KNOWLEDGE 385 II. VALUE OF THE REPRESENTATIVE ASPECT OF KNOWLEDGE . . . 386 1. In general 386 2. The external world 389 3. Ideal truths 395 4-~ Summary and corollaries 399 CHAPTER IV THE CRITERIA OF VALID KNOWLEDGE I. THE ULTIMATE CRITERION 403 i. Theories of a criterion extrinsic to both the knowing mind and the object known by this mind 403 CONTENTS Xvii 2. Theories of a subjective criterion, intrinsic to the knower, but extrinsic to the object 405 3. Theory of a criterion intrinsic to the object and, in a certain sense, also to the knower 411 II. DERIVATIVE CRITERIA 414 1. Personal faculties coming in direct contact with the known object 414 2. Indirect relation of the mind with the known object 417 CONCLUSION OF EPISTEMOLOGY 421 COSMOLOGY, OR THE METAPHYSICAL STUDY OF THE PHYSICAL WORLD INTRODUCTION 422 CHAPTER I INORGANIC SUBSTANCES I. PROPERTIES 425 II. CONSTITUTION 426 1. The question stated . 426 2. Discussion of the systems 428 CHAPTER II LIVING BEINGS I. THE CHARACTERISTICS OF LIFE 432 1. In general 432 2. Manifestations of life 434 II. NATURE OF THE LIVING BEING 436 1. Theories 436 2. Discussion 436 CHAPTER III ORIGIN AND EVOLUTION I. THE QUESTION STATED 439 II. THE INORGANIC WORLD 441 III. THE ORGANIC WORLD 441 1. The origin of life 442 2. The origin of the various forms of life 443 xviii CONTENTS CHAPTER IV THE COSMOS INTRODUCTORY 448 I. SPACE AND TIME 449 1. Space 449 2. Time 451 II. THE LAWS OF NATURE 452 1. Meaning and properties 452 B. Efficiency and teleology 454 CONCLUSION OF COSMOLOGY 457 RATIONAL PSYCHOLOGY, OR PHILOSOPHY OF THE HUMAN MIND INTRODUCTION 458 CHAPTER I SUBSTANTIALITY 1. Meaning of substantiality 460 2. Proofs of the substantiality 461 3. Phenomenalism 463 4. Multiple personality 465 CHAPTER II SPIRITUALITY 1. The question stated 469 2. The simplicity of the soul 470 SPIRITUALITY OF THE HUMAN SOUL 471 1. Specific human activities 471 2. Spirituality of the human soul 474 3. Psychological materialism 476 CHAPTER III THE UNION OF THE SOUL WITH THE BODY I. THE UNION ITSELF 480 1. The question stated . . 480 2. Man, one composite substance 483 II. CONSEQUENCES OF THE UNION 487 CONTENTS XIX CHAPTER IV ORIGIN OF THE SOUL AND OF MAN I. THE HUMAN ORGANISM 490 1. The evidence 490 2. Conclusions 491 II. THE HUMAN SOUL 492 1. The first human soul 492 2. Subsequent human souls 493 III. MANKIND 495 1. Specific unity of mankind 495 2. Antiquity of man 496 CHAPTER V IMMORTALITY OF THE SOUL I. THE QUESTION STATED 498 1. Death 498 2. The question of immortality 500 II. POSSIBILITY AND FACT OF IMMORTALITY 501 1. Possibility 501 2. Proofs of immortality 503 CONCLUSION or THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. HUMAN PERSONALITY . 509 THEODICY, OR THE STUDY OF GOD INTRODUCTION 511 CHAPTER I THE EXISTENCE AND NATURE OF GOD I. EXISTENCE OF GOD 514 1. The question stated 514 2. The argument 516 II. THE NATURE OF GOD 521 1. Distinction of God from the world 521 2. Fundamental or primary attributes 525 3. Derived or secondary attributes 528 4. Value of these conclusions 529 XX CONTENTS CHAPTER II GOD AND THE WORLD I. GOD IN RELATION TO THE WORLD 534 II. THE WORLD IN ITS RELATION TO GOD 538 1. The universe 538 2. Man 538 CONCLUSION or THEODICY 541 OUTLINES OF HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY INTRODUCTION 542 CHAPTER I ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY I. ORIENTAL PHILOSOPHY 544 II. GREEK PHILOSOPHY 548 1. Pre-Socratic schools 548 2. Socrates, Plato, Aristotle 551 3. Post- Aristotelian philosophy 555 III. GRECO-ORIENTAL PHILOSOPHY . . .557 CHAPTER II MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY TRANSITION. PATRISTIC PHILOSOPHY 559 I. FIRST PERIOD 561 1. Beginnings 561 2. The problem of universals 562 3. Mysticism and pantheism 565 4. Oriental philosophy 565 II. SECOND PERIOD 567 1. General 567 2. Philosophy in the earlier part of the thirteenth century . . . 568 3. Thomistic philosophy 568 4. Scotistic philosophy 570 5. Other schools and philosophers 570 III. THIRD PERIOD 571 CONTE NTS XXI CHAPTER III MODERN PHILOSOPHY TRANSITION. RENAISSANCE 574 I. FIRST PERIOD 577 1. Bacon and Descartes 577 2. Development of British empiricism 579 3. Development of Cartesian rationalism 582 II. SECOND PERIOD 584 1. German philosophy 584 2. Scottish philosophy 588 3. French philosophy 589 4. Italian and Spanish philosophy 590 5. English and American philosophy 591 CONCLUSION OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 593 GENERAL CONCLUSION 1. The universe 595 2. Man 597 3- God 597 APPENDIX 601 INDEX 613 INTRODUCTORY PHILOSOPHY GENERAL INTRODUCTION I. THE NATURE OF PHILOSOPHY AS the study of philosophy takes place at the end of the college course, it will be useful to outline the relations of philosophy to the knowledge already acquired by the student. I. WHAT HAS BEEN DONE ALREADY i. Special Results. During the college years numerous studies have been pursued, and little by little the physical universe has unfolded its secrets. (a) Chemistry has reduced material substances to their finest elements and revealed the laws by which their various combina- tions are governed. Biology has manifested the special properties of living beings, and the human organism has been the special subject-matter of anatomy and physiology. The whole earth has been described in the sciences of geography and geology, while astronomy pointed to millions of other worlds which, in their con- stitution and evolution, bear a striking resemblance to the world which we inhabit. From physics we also know that, however near or distant they may be, all the beings of the universe are ruled by natural laws which all obey and which produce order and harmony in the world. (b) Mathematical and geometrical sciences deal with the prop- erties and laws of quantity; namely of numbers, surfaces, and volumes. Wherever applied, these relations, once ascertained, will always be verified. (c) Events of the past recorded in history have also been memo- rized, and from the comparison of the present with the past the mind is now able to draw useful lessons. We know the deeds of great men in war and peace, and we are able to follow the succes- 3 4 GENERAL INTRODUCTION sive steps by which nations have reached their actual standing in the world. (d) Not only knowledge has been acquired, but also the apti- tude to express it by speech and writing. The study of grammar and of the various languages and literatures enables man not only to manifest his own thoughts to others, but also to profit by the thoughts of other men and to admire the beauties found in the various forms of literature. (e) Religious science has taught us how to revere and serve God. The principles of morality are the guides of human actions and behavior. 2. More General Results. In addition to the mastering of the various sciences, another result has been attained. Gymnastic exercises do not merely develop one muscle or another; their purpose is not only to make man go through a certain series of motions, but chiefly to strengthen and develop the whole organism. So also the mental efforts made in the different studies have con- tributed to the general and harmonious growth of the mind. Mem- ory is stronger; the power of attention has been increased; habits of study and reflection have been developed. The faculties of judgment and reasoning have been strengthened. The discipline of college life, the obligation to follow a rule, the constant relations with other students, have been important factors hi the formation of character and the acquisition of social virtues. Hence if we had to summarize in a few words the mental results of college years, we might say that the mind has been furnished with a numerous array of facts grouped and classified, and that it has grown or increased in power and energy. II. WHAT REMAINS TO BE DONE Great and important as it is, the knowledge acquired so far is insufficient. Certain things have been neglected altogether and the knowledge of the others needs a complement. i. New Knowledge to be Acquired. (a) There is a whole world, as varied and as complex as the physical world, which has been left aside almost completely, or, at least, has not been the NATURE OF PHILOSOPHY 5 object of any systematic study. It is the inner world of the self, of our own mind, with its constant changes, its successive states, its growth and development, and its conditions of activity. You have learned your lessons, but what is it to learn? What is the power of acquiring knowledge with which the mind is endowed, and how is such a power exercised? How should it be exercised? What is knowledge itself? And when judgments and conclusions are called true or false, questions are suggested immediately con- cerning the nature of truth, the possibility of reaching it and of distinguishing it from error, and the method of doing this most effectively. (b) In your studies you made use of your memory, judgment, reasoning, reflection, etc., so many words which now call for further explanation, and which suggest numerous problems concerning the functions of the senses, the memory, and the intellect. Fre- quently you have relied on the testimony of others; you have learned a text-book and taken it for granted that the author was right. How could you do otherwise, for instance, for historical or geographical statements? But this method, which was the only possible one, must not now lead to an exaggerated reverence for all that is found in books or newspapers. For, how many errors are published and how many fallacies are taken for truths simply because they appear in print, or even because they are spoken in brilliant language accompanied by fine gestures. It is necessary to learn how to use one's own reason and to practise the difficult art of criticism so as to distinguish truth from falsity, and thus to become able to steer one's own mental life, to think for oneself, and no longer depend too exclusively on the thinking of others. (c) Other questions may be raised which so far have received no answer. You have made efforts and acted for the best: herein are included such notions as those of end, purpose, motive, choice, activity, habit, etc., which have to be elucidated. (d) When the working of man's organic and mental life is understood, when we know its conditions and laws, there still remain the problems of our own constitution. We speak of body and mind. What are they and what are their mutual relations? What is the origin and what will be the destiny of the human 6 GENERAL INTRODUCTION soul? What is the end of man? Even if our Christian faith has given us answers to these questions, what is the attitude of reason toward our belief? These are a few of the many problems which so far have received no solution. 2. The Knowledge already Acquired must be Completed. Even in sciences that have been mastered, there remain many incomplete conclusions. They are good as far as they go, but they do not go far enough. (a) At the very outset, when we learn to read and write, and when later we learn to express our thoughts correctly, accurately, and clearly, how many problems present themselves: the nature of thought, of correct and consistent thought; the possibility of expressing it by means of symbols and of understanding others; the general relations of body and mind, since, in speaking, writing, or making signs, bodily movements are supposed to be controlled by the mind and to represent mental processes or ideas. (b) Historical and social sciences lead to such problems as the con- ditions, motives, and value of human activity. We pass judgments on the actions of others, approve them as right or condemn them as wrong; what, then, is right and wrong? We rely on human testi- mony and historical records; what is their value as signs of truth? (c) Sciences that deal with the material world leave also many notions unexplained. The very word "matter" is an enigma, and "force" is hardly clearer. We are told of a being acting on another in a certain way and under certain conditions, and pro- ducing such or such results. Because these are everyday occur- rences which have become familiar, they seem clear, and we do not even think that they may need an explanation. And yet if we are asked to define what is meant by activity, action, and cause in general, and how action and causality are possible, we find that the task is not an easy one, and that, at every step, many obscurities and difficulties are met with. If all this were understood, there would still remain questions which are altogether beyond the reach of natural science; namely, those concerning the first origin and cause of the world, the nature and necessity of the laws that govern it. NATURE OF PHILOSOPHY 7 (d) Religion requires a basis. It does not consist in blindly believing certain things as true or following certain arbitrary practices. To reason belongs the task of proving the existence of God and of explaining his attributes as far as possible. To sum up: The task of philosophy is to complete and unify knowledge by showing how all the things which we know are related together, and by examining certain notions which have a wide range of application and cover numerous cases, such as those of substance, cause, activity, matter, mind, etc. III. DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY If we consider the name itself, we find that philosophy means the love of wisdom (<&os friend, o-o; D is ; therefore A is ." There are two special rules for the sorites: (i) Only one par- ticular premise is allowable, namely, the first; otherwise the argu- ment is against the 4th rule of the syllogism. (2) Only one negative premise is allowable, namely, the last major; otherwise PRINCIPLES OF THE SYLLOGISM 233 the argument is against the 2d rule. The student may ver- ify for himself that, if any premise except the first is particular, the middle term will be undistributed in one of the syllogisms, and, if any premise except the last is negative, the major term will have a greater extension hi one of the conclusions than in the major premise of the same syllogism. N.B. Sometimes in order to reduce an argument to a perfect syllogism it is necessary to use equivalent propositions. E.g. "Those who are not good will not be rewarded; Peter is not good; therefore Peter will not be rewarded. " Both premises are appar- ently negative, and yet the syllogism is certainly valid, because in reality the minor, as compared to the major, is affirmative. Again this syllogism contains apparently four terms: (i) "those who are not good," (2) "rewarded," (3) "Peter," (4) "good." By using equivalents, we have "Men in the class not-good will not be rewarded; Peter is in the class not-good; therefore he will not be rewarded." Again "Iron (i) is a useful metal (2); this bridge (3) is made of iron (4) ; therefore this bridge (3) is made of a useful metal (5)." Here we have apparently five terms. But it must be noticed that besides the mediate inference by reasoning, we have an immediate inference by complex conception (p. 226) and the argument is perfectly valid. This type of reasoning is used very frequently. III. PRINCIPLES OF THE SYLLOGISM i. Points of View of Extension and of Comprehension. In a syllogism, the propositions may be considered from the point of view of comprehension or from that of extension. The predi- cate may be looked upon as an idea contained in the comprehension of the subject, or as a class containing the subject. "All men are mortal," interpreted from the point of view of comprehension means "Mortal is an attribute of all men," or "Man owing to his nature is mortal." Interpreted from the point of view of exten- sion it means "Man is a sub-class of the class mortal," or "Man is one of the mortal beings." In the former case it is meant that man has a greater comprehension than mortal; in the latter, that 232 LOGIC in order to be true. But, if there are more than two members, and one member is affirmed or denied in the minor, all the others must be denied or affirmed disjunctively in the conclusion. E.g. "To-day is either Sunday, or Monday, or ... Saturday; it is Sunday; therefore it is neither Monday, nor Tuesday, nor . . . "; or, "it is not Sunday; therefore it is either Monday, or Tuesday, or ... ." The disjunctive syllogism may also be reduced to the conditional and the categorical syllogism. (d) A dilemma is a disjunctive argument in which, whichever member of the disjunction be selected, something is inferred against an adversary. E.g. "Speaking irreverently of Holy Scripture is done either in jest or in earnest; if in jest, it is not respectful; if in earnest, it is not good." Rules: (i) The disjunction must be com- plete. (2) The consequences inferred from each member must be valid. 2. Imperfect and Incomplete Syllogisms, (a) The enthymeme is an abbreviated argument, either one of the premises or the conclusion being understood. E.g. "He must be sick, for he has not come." (b) The epicheirema is an argument in which to one or both of the premises its reason or proof is added immediately. E.g. "Order requires an intelligence, for chance does not produce order; there is order in the world, otherwise it could not continue to exist as it is; therefore the world requires an intelligence." (c) The polysyllogism is a series of complete syllogisms in which the conclusion of one is assumed immediately as the major of the following. "A is B\ B is C; therefore A is C; C is Z); therefore A is D." (d) The sorites is a series of incomplete syllogisms or enthy- memes in which only one conclusion, the last, is expressed. It includes as many complete syllogisms as there are propositions minus two. To test its validity, it is useful to reduce it to com- plete syllogisms. "A is B\ B is C; C is D\ D is E\ therefore A is .E." There are two special rules for the sorites: (i) Only one par- ticular premise is allowable, namely, the first; otherwise the argu- ment is against the 4th rule of the syllogism. (2) Only one negative premise is allowable, namely, the last major; otherwise PRINCIPLES OF THE SYLLOGISM 233 the argument is against the 2d rule. The student may ver- ify for himself that, if any premise except the first is particular, the middle term will be undistributed in one of the syllogisms, and, if any premise except the last is negative, the major term will have a greater extension in one of the conclusions than in the major premise of the same syllogism. N.B. Sometimes in order to reduce an argument to a perfect syllogism it is necessary to use equivalent propositions. E.g. "Those who are not good will not be rewarded; Peter is not good; therefore Peter will not be rewarded." Both premises are appar- ently negative, and yet the syllogism is certainly valid, because in reality the minor, as compared to the major, is affirmative. Again this syllogism contains apparently four terms: (i) "those who are not good," (2) "rewarded," (3) "Peter," (4) "good." By using equivalents, we have "Men in the class not-good will not be rewarded; Peter is in the class not-good; therefore he will not be rewarded." Again "Iron (i) is a useful metal (2); this bridge (3) is made of iron (4) ; therefore this bridge (3) is made of a useful metal (5)." Here we have apparently five terms. But it must be noticed that besides the mediate inference by reasoning, we have an immediate inference by complex conception (p. 226) and the argument is perfectly valid. This type of reasoning is used very frequently. HI. PRINCIPLES OF THE SYLLOGISM i. Points of View of Extension and of Comprehension. In a syllogism, the propositions may be considered from the point of view of comprehension or from that of extension. The predi- cate may be looked upon as an idea contained in the comprehension of the subject, or as a class containing the subject. "All men are mortal," interpreted from the point of view of comprehension means "Mortal is an attribute of all men," or "Man owing to his nature is mortal." Interpreted from the point of view of exten- sion it means "Man is a sub-class of the class mortal," or "Man is one of the mortal beings." In the former case it is meant that man has a greater comprehension than mortal; in the latter, that 234 LOGIC mortal has a greater extension than man. This is in agreement with what has been mentioned concerning the relations of inten- sion and extension. 2. Principles of the Syllogism. (a) From the point of view of comprehension the eight rules of the syllogism are based on the following principle: "Quod dicitur de continente dicitur etiam de con ten to." That which is predicated affirmatively or nega- tively of that which contains must be predicated also of that which is contained. If "mortal" is contained explicitly or implicitly in the comprehension of "man," and "man" in the comprehension of "Peter," "mortal" is also contained in the comprehension of "Peter." (b) From the point of mew of extension, the principle of the syl- logism is stated briefly as "Dictum de omni " and "Dictum de nullo." Whatever is predicated affirmatively or negatively of the genus or class must also be predicated of the species, sub- classes, and individuals under this genus or class. If "man" is a sub-class of "mortal," and "Peter " is an individual man, Peter is also mortal. (c) More generally the principles of the syllogism are three, (i) Two terms agreeing with one and the same third agree with each other. (2) Two terms one of which agrees and the other disagrees with the same third disagree with each other. (3) Two terms neither of which agrees with the same third cannot be said to agree or to disagree with each other. It would be easy to show that all the rules of the syllogism are but applica- tions of these principles. N.B. It may be found useful to represent syllogistic processes by means of circles which diagrammatically show their value (see on opposite page two illustrations showing how this can be done). By applying the rules given for the quantity of the predicate, one may verify which inferences are valid, and which are invalid. 3. Quantitative Syllogisms. So far we have spoken only of the logical or qualitative syllogism. There is also a mathemat- ical or quantitative syllogism based on quantity, succession, equality of relations, etc. For instance: "A is equal to B; B is equal to C; therefore A is equal to C." "A is greater than B; PRINCIPLES OF THE SYLLOGISM 235 B is greater than C; therefore A is greater than C." "A (a musical instrument) is in tune with B; B with C. . . ." "A is a brother of B. . . ." " A lived before 5. . . ." In each of these arguments we have four terms. Yet they are valid, because they are based on quantitative self-evident relations: "Two things equal to the same third are equal to each other "; "The greater than the Point of view of extension Point of view of comprehension MP(a); SM(a); Conclusion: SP(a) MP(e); SM(i); Conclusion: SP(o) greater is greater than the great," etc. In the syllogism: "A is greater than B; B greater than C; therefore A is greater than C," if A's greatness is a, B's greatness b, and C's greatness c, we have: a = b + x; b = c -f y; therefore a = c + y + x. 4. Primary Laws of Thought. All the principles and rules of the syllogism are ultimately reducible to three primary laws of thought implied in all affirmations, negations, and processes of 236 LOGIC reasoning, (i) Law of identity: "A thing is what it is." Or logically: "Every subject is its own predicate"; "A is A." (2) Law of contradiction: "The same thing cannot at the same time and from the same point of view be and not be." Or logically: "The same predicate cannot at the same time and in the same sense be affirmed and denied of the same subject." (3) Law of excluded middle: "A thing is or is not." Or logically: "Of two contradic- tory attributes one must be affirmed and the other denied of the same subject." These laws are the basis on which the syllogism rests, and are implied in every process of thinking and judging. CHAPTER II METHOD OBJECT OF THIS CHAPTER 1. Meaning. Method (68os ftera, road or way toward) in gen- eral signifies the adaptation of means in order to do something and to reach safely a determined end. In logic, it signifies the adap- tation of means in order to reach scientific truth, i.e. the knowl- edge of things from their causes and in their relations to other things. To know, in the strict sense, is not simply to apprehend a fact or an event, but also to perceive the reasons, laws, causes, and relations of facts and events. Methodology teaches how to proceed in order to acquire science. In every syllogism there is a progress from the premises to the conclusion. Knowledge is generally acquired by a series of reasonings. Hence, although a method is required for one single reasoning, method as understood here applies to a more complex progress in which arguments of different value and from different sources are used. 2. Importance. It is important to proceed methodically, (i) Unless the road is known, one is likely to go astray, or at least to lose much time in finding the way. This will be made clear if you compare, with regard to both quantity and quality, the work of two men, one of whom proceeds methodically, and the other does not. (2) It is necessary to proceed gradually, not by jumps; precipitation is likely to mislead the mind. (3) What is acquired with method, and orderly arranged, is more easily memorized, and only such a methodical arrangement of ideas deserves the name of knowledge. Thus, whereas the first chapter of logic indicated how to make a valid formal syllogism, and as such is indispensable, there re- mains to show (i) the value of the premises used; if the form be correct, but the materials weak, the whole edifice lacks solidity; 237 238 LOGIC (2) the use to be made of the syllogism, and the mode of proceed- ing step by step from one conclusion to another; (3) the danger of fallacies which may come either from the form or the matter of the syllogism. 3. Division of this Chapter. Method being a progress supposes two extremes: one, the starting-point; the other, the end to be reached. As the direction of any movement or progress is derived from the term to which it tends, "motus specificatur a ter- mino " we must begin with the end to be reached, for it is from this end that the process derives its orientation. As to the proc- ess itself from the starting-point to the terminus, it supposes that we know the value of the instruments to be used, the various kinds of methods, and the wrong ways, fallacies or errors. Hence our division: (i) The extremes; (a) the terminus ad quern, or end to be reached, (b) the terminus a quo, or starting-point. (2) The progress itself; (a) the value of the arguments, (b) the two main general methods, (c) the obstacles. ARTICLE I. THE TERMINI I. THE END TO BE REACHED Man's intelligence strives after science, that is, a certain mode of knowledge to which his innate curiosity instinctively impels him. Man not only wants to see things and events, but he is anxious to know their "how" and "why" two words which are frequently used by both the child and the adult. I. THE NATURE OF SCIENCE The term "science" is used with both a subjective and an objective meaning. It signifies the knowledge and the object of knowledge, and we speak of the science which a man possesses, and of the various sciences which he studies. i. Characteristics of Scientific Knowledge. Science is always knowledge, but knowledge in its broad sense is not always sci- ence, (i) Sense-perception, of itself, is not scientific knowledge. (2) Things known directly and immediately by the intellect, i.e. SCIENCE 239 self-evident principles, are not said to be known scientifically, but are the bases of science. Scientific knowledge is essentially the knowledge of things through their causes and their common prin- ciples. It possesses the three following characteristics: (a) // is certain. It starts from something certain, and uses valid inferences that lead to certitude. This certitude is based on rea- sons and justified by proofs. Unscientific knowledge is frequently doubtful and accepted without proof. (b) It is general. The fact or individual as such is not the object of science. Science has for its object the causes common to several happenings, the types common to several beings, the laws com- mon to several phenomena. To know that a man died is not sci- ence; to know that he died on account of his swallowing a certain poison which, under the same circumstances, is capable of killing not only this man, but any other man, because it has such or such effects on the organism, is scientific. To see a dog is not science; to know its nature and essential features belongs to sci- ence. To perceive that the stone thrown up in the air falls down is not science; the law of gravitation gives a scientific explanation of the fact. (c) It is systematic. Facts are only the materials of science. They are not science itself any more than the materials of a house are a house. The materials become a house by their adjustment according to certain relations. So also facts become science only when their connections and relations are perceived, and when they are reduced to common principles and laws. 2. Two Meanings of Science. (a) If stress is laid on the knowl- edge of causes and on certitude , it may be insisted that such causes give necessary conclusions, i.e. conclusions which, under existing circumstances, the mind conceives as incapable of being otherwise. Mathematical sciences are the best types of this meaning of science. (b) If stress is laid on the element of systematization, the limits of science are widened and may be made to include not only con- clusions that are certain, but also others that are more or less conjectural and hypothetical. These, it is true, do not consti- tute science in the strict sense; they are called scientific because 240 LOGIC they are obtained methodically, connected with strictly ascer- tained conclusions, and, for the present, offer a plausible explana- tion of facts. Many such conclusions are found in empirical sciences. 3. Advantages of Scientific Knowledge. From the charac- teristics of scientific knowledge its advantages are easily derived. (a) It enables the mind to understand and explain things; to know not only what happens, but also why it happens. (b) It makes it possible to foresee the future, so that measures may be taken accordingly. Certain events, like an eclipse of the sun or an explosion of dynamite, may be foreseen and predicted with certitude. Others, like a storm, human actions, political events, etc., can be foreseen only with varying degrees of prob- ability. Besides freedom which is found in human actions, the reason of this difference is the complexity of the causes that con- tribute to produce a given phenomenon, and the difficulty of knowing them all in their various relations. (c) It increases our power over nature, for, when the causes that produce a thing are known, they may be brought about, or avoided, or combined in a thousand ways, so as to give rise to intended results. Machinery is an obvious instance. It is the adaptation of many causes, laws, and principles for certain purposes. To know the cause of a disease is the first step toward curing it. To know the character of a man is of great importance in dealing with him. II. CLASSIFICATION OF SCIENCES i. Distinction and Subordination. (a) Sciences are distin- guished and classified according to their formal objects, that is, not according to the object itself of which they treat considered in its totality (material object), but according to the special point of view which they take of it (formal object). Thus many sciences have the human body for their material object : anatomy, physiol- ogy, pathology, histology, hygiene, etc. . They are distinct sciences because they do not study the human body under the same aspect. SCIENCE 241 (b) Sciences may be subordinated in several ways, (i) // we consider their objects, some are more general, and the knowledge of them is supposed by the more special. Thus ethics supposes psychology; trigonometry supposes geometry, etc. This does not mean that the higher sciences must always be studied first; some- times the inferior and more special sciences may be a necessary means toward the superior. (2) // we consider their utility, some sciences are speculative, and others more immediately practical. As a rule practical sciences are based on theoretical sciences. (3) // we consider their origin, empirical sciences come or should come first, since psychologically experience comes before general- ization. (4) // we consider their excellence, the higher the object, the nobler the science. Thus the knowledge of God and of the human soul is higher than that of nature. 2. Classification. It is difficult, not to say impossible, to give a satisfactory classification of sciences, (i) In fact, scien- tists do not agree in all details. (2) The number of distinct sciences increases with experience, and mere chapters of former sciences little by little become special sciences. (3) The limits separating distinct sciences are largely artificial. Since all the objects of nature, and all aspects of these objects, are in close con- nection, it is not possible for any science to be independent; it must necessarily go beyond its own limits into the domain of other sciences. Without stopping to consider the merits of other classifications, the following seems sufficiently complete and satisfactory. Gen- eric sciences alone will be mentioned, and these again may be subdivided. I. Physical and natural sciences, i.e. sciences of the material world. i. Inorganic (a) General properties of matter, Physics Nature, composition, and special properties of elements and compounds, Chemistry (c) Minerals, Mineralogy (d) Description of the earth, Physical Geography (e) Constitution of the earth, Geology (/) Other mundane bodies, Astronomy, Cosmogony, etc 242 LOGIC 2. Organic (a) Life in general, (b) Plant life, (c) Animal life, Biology Botany Zoology N.B. Both botany and zoology are subdivided into the study of (a) General structure of organisms, (&) Minute structure, (c) Functions, (J) Diseases, (e) Early development, (/) Fossil remains, Anatomy Histology, Cystology Physiology Pathology Embryology Paleontology truth, duty, beauty, Psychology Logic and Episte- mology Ethics Msthetics II. Sciences of man considered as intelligent, free, and social, either as an individual or in his social relations. :. Individual (a) Conscious processes, (6) Normative sciences of 2. Social (a) Language, Philology (b) Wealth, Political Economy (c) Social ethics and politics, Law and Jurisprudence (d) Description of States, Political Geography (e) Past events, History and Historical Sciences, e.g. Epigraphy, Archeology, etc. (/) Early human development, Anthropology (g) Human races, Ethnology III. Mathematical sciences, i.e. sciences of abstract quantity. 1. Of numbers, 2. Of extension, |3. Of movement and force, Arithmetic, Algebra Geometry, Trigonometry Mechanics IV. Metaphysical sciences, i.e. higher constitution and nature, 1. Of material substances, 2. Of the human soul, 3. Of God, Cosmology Philosophy of mind Theodicy THE STARTING-POINT 243 II. THE STARTING POINT 1. Doubt. Any question and any desire for learning suppose in the mind both knowledge and doubt; namely, the knowledge, however vague and imperfect, of something concerning the object we want to study, for, if man were altogether ignorant of it, he would not even suspect that any question may be asked about it; and a doubt with regard to the special points to be examined and the answer to the questions proposed. This doubt, however, bears on a special point. It is not universal, for, if everything, including sense-experience, the value of the faculties of knowledge, and the first principles be doubted, it becomes absolutely impos- sible ever to reach anything certain. Since they are primary, self-evident facts and principles cannot be reconstructed out of anything else. Descartes began by a universal doubt, but did not reach certi- tude except through inconsistencies, implicitly admitting later on what he had formerly rejected as doubtful. He warns us him- self that his example is not to be followed indiscriminately. Log- ically, certitude can come only from certitude, universal doubt can beget only doubt, since the conclusion must be contained in the premises. Moreover, it is impossible to demonstrate everything, for, if a proposition M be demonstrated by L, L by K, K by /, and so on, without ever reaching a proposition standing by itself and on its own merits, no certitude can ever be obtained. 2. Positive Data. The process may be analytical or synthet- ical. In the former case, the positive starting-point will be a fact or a series of facts; in the latter, it will be self-evident and indemon- strable principles. Facts will be gathered from internal or external experience. Principles will be either general, or special to each science. Thus the principle of sufficient reason is general; the axioms and definitions of geometry are more special. In all these are contained implicitly or explicitly the fact of the subject's existence, which is implied in every conscious process; the subject's power to know which is implied in the act itself of knowledge; the primary laws of thought identity, contra- 244 LOGIC diction, and excluded middle without which consistent thinking is an impossibility. ARTICLE II. THE PROGRESS I. THE VALUE OF THE ARGUMENTS Method is the way to make progress from the known to the unknown, or from the better known to the less known. Hence the importance of knowing the value of inferences and reasonings. These may be (i) certain, i.e. start from premises that are certain, and lead to conclusions that are also certain; (2) more or less prob- able and worthy of assent; (3) false, either because the premises are false, or because the rules of the syllogism are not observed. Only the first two classes belong here as instruments of science, and as yielding scientific results, permanent or provisional. The last class, on the contrary, is an obstacle to science, and will be considered later. I. DEMONSTRATION 1. Nature of Demonstration. Demonstration is a process of reasoning in which from premises known to be certain a conclu- sion which is also certain is inferred. Hence two conditions are required: (i) The formal validity of the process of reasoning; (2) the certainty of the premises, either because they are self-evi- dent, or because they are ultimately reducible to self-evident facts and principles, since, as was said above, the process of demon- stration requires indemonstrable principles. Thus the last the- orems of Euclidean geometry are based on the preceding ones, and ultimately on principles, axioms, and definitions. 2. Various Kinds of Demonstration. A demonstration is: (a) (i) Direct, when it proceeds by positive arguments, and shows positively that the predicate does or does not belong to the sub- ject. (2) Indirect, when it shows the falsity of the contradic- tory or of opposite propositions. To prove the freedom of the will from consciousness is to proceed directly; to prove it from the consequences of determinism is to proceed indirectly. (b) (i) A priori, synthetic, or deductive, when it proceeds from VALUE OF ARGUMENTS 245 that which is in reality prior, namely, from the cause to the effect, from the essence to the property, from the law to the phenomenon. (2) A posteriori^ analytic, or inductive, when it proceeds from that which is in reality posterior, namely, from the effect to the cause, from the property to the essence, from the phenomenon to the law. To prove the immortality of the soul from the soul's spirituality is to proceed a priori; to prove the existence of God from the world is to proceed a posteriori. In natural sciences, these two methods are generally combined. We proceed first from the effects to the cause, and the knowledge of the cause leads again to the knowledge of other effects. N.B. Prioriness and posterioriness here are taken in the natural, not in the logical, order, since logically the premises, whatever be their natural relation to the conclusion, are always prior to the conclusion. In the a posteriori demonstration, the fact is better known than, or logically prior to, the law, although in the natural order it is but an application of the existing law. (c) (i) Perfect propter quid, 8m, "why" when it gives the necessary, proximate, special, and adequate reasons or prin- ciples of the conclusion. Hence it is always a priori. (2) Imper- fect quia, on, "that " when it shows simply the existence of a thing, or does not give its intrinsic, special, or proximate reasons. N.B. Causes and reasons are necessary when they make it impossible for the conclusion to be otherwise; proximate and spe- cial when there is no link omitted between the conclusion and its premises; adequate when they give the complete reason of the conclusion. The perfect demonstration is possible chiefly in math- ematics, logic, and metaphysics, where it can start from the axioms of quantity, and from self-evident principles considered either as laws of thought or as principles of being and existence. (d) (i) Absolute when the premises are true in themselves and for all men. (2) Relative, or ad hominem, when the premises are admitted by an adversary, although they may not be certain. The former is valid for all, not the latter. To base a demonstra- tion on principles or facts which are admitted by an opponent, but known to be false by the one who uses them, is a lack of intel- lectual honesty. Probabilities are frequently used in this way. 246 LOGIC II. PROBABLE ARGUMENTS i. Nature of Probable Arguments. (a) Probable arguments are those in which one of the premises is, or both premises are, probable, and lead to a probable conclusion. Probability means likelihood, approach to truth, or greater force of argument. It refers to the object, and produces in the mind the state of opin- ion, that is, an assent without the firmness of certitude. Degrees of probability are numberless, and the corresponding states of opinion are more or less firm, nearer to, or farther from, doubt and certitude. In fact, doubt and certitude exist only in one point, at each extreme of the line of mental assent; doubt is the absence of assent; certitude is full, complete, and unrestricted assent. Opinion with its various degrees occupies the whole range between these two extremes. Probability is much more frequent than certitude, especially in practical matters, in historical, moral, social, political, and even natural sciences. But in many cases, as explained in psychology, subjective motives are added to objec- tive evidence, and make one consider as certain that which pru- dently and logically should be considered only as probable (p. 117 ff.). (b) The general rule of probable arguments is that the conclu- sion cannot have a greater probability than the weaker premise. We must understand in this sense also the general rules: "Latius hos quam . . . ." and: "Peiorem sequitur semper. ..." If in a series of arguments, or in the same argument, two or several prop- ositions are only probable, the conclusion represents their combined weakness. A mathematical example will illustrate this: In toss- ing a coin, the chances of turning tails are ^; the chances of turning tails twice in succession are i X i, i.e. , for there are four chances in all, two for tails and two for heads. In the same way probabil- ity means a chance for truth. If to this be added another chance, the probability of both chances coinciding with truth is smaller than it would be if only one proposition were probable. However, probabilities, when independent, form a cumulative evidence, and may produce certitude. Thus a coincidence of inde- pendent facts, each one only probable in itself, may show the guilt VALUE OF ARGUMENTS 247 of an accused person, because his guilt is the only sufficient reason of this coincidence. Cumulative evidence is frequently used in all sciences. The main probable arguments are analogy and example, statis- tics, hypothesis, and authority. 2. Analogy and Example. (a) Analogy applies to an object what is known to apply to another object having with the former one or several points of resemblance. From certain features known to be common certain other features are inferred to be also common. Example and analogy are closely related, and these terms are frequently used for each other. Strictly speaking, however, analogy argues from one instance to another by passing through a general law; it is inductive and deductive. Example goes directly and conjecturally from one instance to another. Thus, knowing that a certain disease is produced by micro-organ- isms, I infer by analogy that another disease having some similar symptoms is also due to a similar cause. Here is implied the gen- eral principle that the same symptoms are due to the same cause. To deter a man from excess in drinking, I may point out to him the example of this or that man who is an habitual drunkard. (b) Analogy and example are of frequent use in all sciences and in daily life. They are the starting-point of many discoveries, by suggesting solutions which later on may be proved true. Their value depends on the number and character of the observed re- semblances, and thus ranges anywhere from certitude to zero. Hence extreme caution is necessary in using and admitting these arguments. They are sources of metaphors and allegories which must not be taken as true beyond the legitimate value of the inference. Points of resemblance must not cause one to over- look the differences. 3. Statistics consist in noting the absolute and relative fre- quency of certain happenings. All happenings of a certain nature and within a certain period are numbered, and averages are taken and compared with various circumstances which are conjectured to be the causes of these happenings. Thus I may note the number of divorces for a whole nation or for a certain class of people dur- ing a certain period of time, compare their increasing or decreas- 248 LOGIC ing rate with changes in social, political, and religious conditions, and thus find out the causes which influence their frequency. Statistics are of frequent use in social sciences, for mortality, births, diseases, crimes, accidents, suicides, etc., and also in many other sciences, e.g. for harvests, money circulation, mineral and agricultural products, etc. Statistics are very useful because ob- served coincidences help to find the causes of phenomena, or at least the various influences under which they happen. But they are difficult both to make and to interpret correctly because the causes and influences of events may be very complex and varied. There is danger of mistaking a mere fortuitous coinci- dence for the true cause, and of overlooking some important factors. 4. Hypothesis (Greek, "placing under") in general consists in supposing (Latin, sub-positio) or presuming the solution looked for, and dealing with it as if it were known. It is, therefore, a tentative explanation to be verified. (a) When a fact or a series of facts has been observed, we may not know its law immediately. Or even if the law is known in its generality, we may not know all its determinations. A hypothesis consists in supposing the law to be true, and in working on this assumption so as to ascertain whether it is true and justi- fied. The principle which impels to frame hypotheses is the prin- ciple of sufficient reason which applies to all phenomena. The faculty that frames them is the imagination under the guidance of reason. (b) The main utilities of hypotheses are, (i) to offer a more or less probable solution of a problem which perhaps cannot be solved definitively, or which has not yet received a satisfactory solution; (2) to coordinate and group results already obtained, and to sys- tematize them into a class that will be more or less permanent; (3) to incite to work in a certain direction in order to ascertain if the hypothesis is verifiable; (4) to throw many side-lights on the problem, even if the hypothesis is disproved, and to point the way to a true solution. (c) The conditions of a scientific hypothesis are the following: (i) It must not be taken as an end, but as a means; not as a prop- VALUE OF ARGUMENTS 249 osition to be proved, but as a proposition to be tested. (2) It must not contradict any well-ascertained facts, conclusions, or principles, but sometimes may overthrow conclusions hitherto accepted as certain. (3) It must not be gratuitous, but based on facts. (4) It must be adequate, i.e. applicable to all the observed phenomena, and assign to them what is, or seems to be, a sufficient explana- tion. A hypothesis which certainly contradicts one fact which is certain, ceases to be valid. (5) It must be capable of some veri- fication or disproof, for its value consists chiefly in the hope of testing it. 5. Authority. Historical sciences are based on human author- ity. In all other sciences, as well as in daily life, men frequently rely on the authority of others. Few are the beliefs and actions prompted exclusively, and even principally, by personal reflec- tion, when compared with the number of those prompted by the authority of others, common opinion, education, individual ad- vice and suggestion. (a) In general it may be said that the value of human author- ity as such ordinarily does not go beyond probability, for any man may be deceived or be a deceiver. Yet there may be found such guarantees in one single witness or in several independent wit- nesses cumulative probability as to give a moral certitude. On questions of facts, especially of facts that are easily observable, it is possible in many cases to reach certitude, but in other cases probability alone can be obtained. On questions of doctrine and systems, a competent man has greater authority; yet none is infallible, and for a man who can appreciate and weigh the reasons that are given, an authority is worth these reasons. (b) Hence two extremes must be avoided: (i) Making of sci- ence a mere study and repetition of the opinions of others. This does not give a scientific knowledge; it is a lazy process dis- pensing with private research and progress. (2) Neglecting completely what others have said. We may profit by their discoveries and discussions, avoid doing the same work twice, proceed more safely where they have groped and, perhaps, lost their way, appropriate the conclusions of science already acquired. 250 LOGIC II. THE TWO GENERAL METHODS 1. Induction and Deduction. The two general methods are induction and deduction. Induction goes from the particular to the universal, from the effect to the cause, from the phenomenon to the law. It tries to generalize, to find uniformities and general truths. Deduction follows the reverse process. Hence, consid- ering the real order of things, induction is regressive; deduc- tion, progressive. The cause is prior to the effect, but the effect may be known better than the cause (cf. p. 116.). The chief instrument of induction is analysis; of deduction, synthesis. 2. Analysis and Synthesis. By analysis (re-solutio) is meant a decomposing, a passing from the more complex to the simpler. By synthesis (com-positio) is meant a putting together, a passing from the simpler to the more complex. The whole which is decom- posed by analysis, and the parts that are put together by synthesis, are to be understood, not according to extension, but according to comprehension. Thus the human organism is more complex than a single organ, since it includes this organ, and others besides. The fact is more complex than the law, since it is a concrete appli- cation of the law, i.e. it is the law plus some individual determina- tions. In general, analysis proceeds from the conditioned to the condition; synthesis, from the condition to the conditioned. (a) In the case of facts or of concrete realities, analysis reduces the whole to its parts or components; either really, as, for instance, water to oxygen and hydrogen; white light to the colors of the spectrum; the organism, plant or animal, to its organs, tissues, etc.; or mentally, as, for instance, in psychology we have tried to analyze the complex mental states into their elements which do not exist separately as simple. Synthesis proceeds in the opposite direction. (b) In the case of ideas or mental truths, e.g. in mathematics, analysis proceeds from a more complex to a more simple statement until known principles are reached. Synthesis starts from the principles, and deduces consequences from them. Thus when I consider the theorem "The sum of the angles of a triangle is equal to two right angles," I may ascend from it to simpler principles INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 251 (analysis), or, as is commonly done in learning geometry, descend toward it from the simpler principles (synthesis). I. INDUCTION We do not speak here of complete induction, or induction per enumerationem simplicem, which consists in affirming of the whole in the conclusion that which has been affirmed of all the parts enumerated separately in the premises. E.g. "It rained Sunday, Monday, Tuesday . . . and Saturday; but these are all the days of the week; therefore it rained every day of the week." "Peter, Paul, John ... are under thirty; but Peter, Paul, John . . . are all the men here present; therefore . . . ." Such an induction is not scientific, and leads to no new result. It is a mere process of addition based on the principle that the total- ity equals the sum of its parts. We speak only of incomplete in- duction, e.g. "This water is composed of oxygen and hydrogen; therefore all water is composed of oxygen and hydrogen." i. Description of the Inductive Process. The inductive proc- ess includes three steps: knowledge of individual facts, generaliza- tion, verification. (a) The knowledge of facts, internal or external, is acquired by observation and experiment. Experiment is a special mode of, and includes, observation. To observe is to watch attentively phenomena as they occur in nature when it is left to itself. To experiment is to question nature. It consists in varying and con- trolling circumstances so as to see what results will follow. When- ever possible, experiment is superior to simple observation, because it creates circumstances, and consequently results which other- wise might never occur. I may simply observe the behavior of an animal, or experiment with drugs to see how the animal's be- havior will be affected by them. Observation and experiment are very important. If the facts are not observed correctly, the theory based on them cannot fail to be weak for lack of sufficient foundation. The qualities required are: (i) On the object's side (a) precision as to the circumstances; (b) the variation of these circumstances in a precise manner; (c) the isolation, as far as possible, of the 252 LOGIC phenomenon under observation from other phenomena. (2) On the observer's side, (a) physiological and physical conditions: health and normal state of organs; use of good instruments; (b) intellectual: attention to all circumstances and to analogies; desire to know; (c) moral: patience, impartiality, carefulness to discriminate accu- rately between what is observed and what is inferred, between what is really perceived and what is imagined. (b) When a fact or a sufficient number of facts have been ob- served, their uniformities are noted, and their laws assigned, first generally in a tentative way. (c) The theory must be verified by new observations and exper- iments. 2. Methods of Induction. Observation ?.nd experiment are made according to four methods known as the four inductive methods. All inductions, both in science and in daily life, depend on the use of one or several of these methods by which experience is interpreted. (a) Method of agreement. When a phenomenon occurs in two or several cases which agree only in one circumstance, this circum- stance is probably the cause of, or at least causally related to, the phenomenon. In other words, if, in several instances where a phenomenon occurs, there is only one common antecedent, this antecedent is the cause. The value of the conclusion depends on the constancy and multiplicity of coincidences under varying circumstances. Thus, if after eating a certain food whatever other food I may also take with it I invariably feel sick, this article of food is very likely the cause of my sickness. (b) Method of difference. Two or several instances are observed, one in which the phenomenon occurs, and the others in which it does not. If all the circumstances except one are the same in all cases, this one circumstance is probably the cause. In other words, the one difference in the antecedent is the cause of the dif- ference in the result. Thus sickness or death is ascribed to a cer- tain poison because, everything else being identical, the taking of the poison is followed by ackness or death. N.B. The joint method of agreement and difference combines these two methods. INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 253 (c) Method of residues. It is a modification of the method of difference. When in a group of consequents, a, b t c, d, some, for instance, a, b, c, are known to be due to certain antecedents A, B, C, the residual consequent d is probably caused by a residual antecedent D. If I have bought three articles, a, b, c, and know how much I have spent in all and how much a and b cost, I can find the cost of c. Knowing what effects are due to the presence of certain elements in a compound, a new effect is ascribed to the presence of a new element. (d) Method of concomitant variations. If variations of a phe- nomenon occur simultaneously with variations in the antecedent, it is probable that these two variations are causally related. Thus the concomitant variations of the number of vibrations with the pitch of a sound, or of the thermometer with the temperature, show that these phenomena are causally related. N.B. As much as possible these methods must be used to- gether to test, correct, verify, and strengthen one another. The experiments in each must be varied and multiplied according to the nature of the case. 3. The Principle of Induction. (a) In induction, the conclu- sion has a greater extension than the premises, since from observed particular instances a general conclusion is drawn applying to un- observed instances. If the process is valid, there must be some principle that makes this passage legitimate. Observation and experiment are always limited to few cases, and, by themselves, justify only the affirmation of the facts observed. Nor is the association of ideas sufficient to justify this passage. According to associationists, as mentioned in Psychology (p. 113), because several times a man has observed that the same ante- cedents were followed by the same consequents, he is led to expect this succession in every case. Little by little these associations and partial uniformities lead to the formation by the mind of the general principle of the uniformity of the laws of nature: "Nature always acts in the same manner under the same circumstances." In addition to its psychological difficulties, this view is open to the following objections: (i) This principle would have only a subjective and relative value; it could be changed by subsequent 254 LOGIC experiences and habits. (2) A law is frequently discovered after one observation, or very few observations, and hence not through constant associations. On the contrary, sometimes induction corrects long-standing prejudices due to associations and habits of thought. (3) The number of cases in which constant uniform- ities are perceived by the senses is very small when compared to the number of cases in which they are not observed. (b) Some other criterion is needed since experience can never account for the universality and necessity of knowledge. In fact, the principle of induction is the principle of the uniformity of nature: "The same causes produce the same effects," or "Causal relations are constant," or "Nature is governed by constant laws." This principle is not derived from mere sense association, but rests imme- diately on the principle of sufficient reason, which in turn is but an application of the principle of contradiction. Not only does every single fact require a sufficient reason without which it could not occur, but a series of coincidences, or harmonious and constant occurrences, must be assigned an adequate reason. A single fact requires a proportionate cause. The recurrence of the same fact requires the sameness of natural inclination and of energy, which alone can explain the observed uniformities, and from which we are led to know future and unobserved uniformities. Wherever there is the same nature, i.e. the same source of activity, there also the same effects will necessarily occur. II. DEDUCTION i. Description of the Deductive Process. (a) Deduction starts from principles, and goes to their special applications. These principles may either be self-evident, like the axioms and defini- tions of geometry, or result from a previous inductive process, like the various laws of natural sciences. Deduction is used especially in abstract sciences, the best types of which are mathematics and geometry. In physical sciences it is used to demonstrate that which has been found to be the truth. The professor may some- tunes proceed deductively in proving what he has discovered by induction. Generally speaking, however, the method of demon- stration should be essentially the same as the method of invention. INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 255 (b) Deduction includes three steps: (i) Definition, i.e. the unfold- ing of the intension of the terms, and the indication of the exact meaning in which they are used. (2) Division, i.e. the unfolding of the extension of the terms, and classification. (3) Proof, i.e. the assigning of the reasons, or demonstration proper. 2. Utility of Deduction. Two main objections are raised by Stuart Mill against the usefulness of the deductive syllogism. (a) It is sterile, and teaches nothing new, since the major already contains the conclusion. In the following syllogism, "All men are mortal; Socrates is a man; therefore Socrates is mortal," in order to be able to affirm the major, I must already be certain of the conclu- sion, for, the major would not be true if Socrates were not mortal. Answer: (i) The conclusion may be contained only virtually and implicitly in the premises. The syllogistic process makes it explicit. Who can say that deduction is sterile in geometry, and that he who knows the principles knows also all the theorems which these principles serve to prove? (2) Deduction teaches the reason why the conclusion is true. I might know that Socrates was mortal because in fact he died, that the number 275 is divisible by 5 because I have tried the division, and that the square built on the hypothenuse of a right-angled triangle is equal to the sum of the squares built on both its sides because I have measured them. But demonstration will give me the reason of these truths, show not only that they are so, but why they are so, and why they are universal. (b) The syllogism is a petitio principii; in affirming the major we already suppose the truth of the conclusion. Answer, (i) In the example given by Mill, the major is not taken extensively, but comprehensively. "All men are mortal" does not mean primarily "All men numerically are mortal," but "mortal" belongs to the comprehension of "man," or "Human nature implies mortality," an assertion which is based on the knowledge of human nature acquired by an inductive process. (2) Hence induction does not require the complete enumeration of all cases. (c) Mill also says that, in fact, we do not argue from the general to the individual, but from the individual to the individual. For 256 LOGIC instance, a matron unhesitatingly prescribes a remedy for her neighbor's child simply because it has cured her own child. Answer. Universal principles are implied here; that the same symptoms are signs of the same disease; and that what has cured the disease in one case is likely to cure it in all cases. The matron would give the same advice to anybody else, thus showing that, in the case of her neighbor's child, she only applies a general principle. 3. Induction and Deduction Compared. In conclusion we may briefly compare the uses of induction and of deduction. (a) Induction gives to deduction many of its principles. It is the main method of the sciences of nature. But with the progress of sciences, more laws are discovered, and deduction of particular instances from these known laws is more frequent. (b) Deduction is necessary even in the inductive process. It is by deduction that hypotheses are verified, and laws applied to particular cases. (c) Some sciences are chiefly deductive; others, chiefly induc- tive; others, like politics, political economy, ethics, make frequent use of both processes. Thus I may demonstrate the advantages of a certain form of government either from facts or from principles. N.B. Find concrete applications of these methods hi the sciences which you have studied. III. OBSTACLES Besides the difficulties inherent in the problems themselves, the main obstacles met with in an investigation are fallacies, which, together with other causes to be mentioned later, are sources of error. As to controversy, contradiction, and discussion, they may also be obstacles, or may become great helps, according to the use which is made of them. I. FALLACIES i. Nature of Fallacies. (a) A fallacy (fallacia, fallere, to deceive) is an erroneous argument, or a reasoning which, for some reason, fails to lead to a valid conclusion. The term "fallacy" is more general than the terms "paralogism" and "sophism." A OBSTACLES 257 paralogism supposes in the logical form of the reasoning a defect which is apt to deceive the reasoner himself. As generally used, the term sophism, and its derivatives, have an ethical implication, namely, that the reasoner is aware of the weakness of the argu- ment, but nevertheless uses it with an intention to deceive. (b) It is difficult to give a satisfactory classification of fallacies. The following, though imperfect, is sufficient for the present prac- tical purpose. Fallacy (i) of simple inspection, or a priori (2) of inference (a) logical or formal purely logical and formal semilogical, verbal, or in dic- tione (&) real or material, or extra dictionem (c) special fallacies of induction 2. Fallacies of Simple Inspection, or a priori fallacies, in general consist in the acceptance of certain principles, maxims, and generalizations without sufficient evidence. By some these fallacies are said to be wholly a priori, i.e. accepted without any reasoning. It seems truer, at least in most cases, to say that such principles are accepted on the strength of an implicit reason- ing, hasty and insufficient induction, or common acceptance and authority. They are looked upon as self-evident and as requiring no proof, and many inferences are based on them. Many are popular, like omens, the interpretation of dreams, prognostics, superstitions, lucky or unlucky days or numbers, prejudices, etc. They are found in the most ordinary assents of daily life, and in the highest pursuits like religion and morality. Others have a higher character in science, philosophy, and religion, like such ambiguous principles as: "All men are born equal;" "Progress and evolution are the law of nature"; "Man is essen- tially truthful"; "Nature and the supernatural cannot meet"; "All religions are equally good"; "It is enough for man to live honestly"; and a multitude of other maxims either admitted almost universally or special to a certain region or class of men. To avoid them it is necessary to exercise constant watchfulness. Because they are common to all or to many, and because they 18 258 LOGIC are habitual, they attract no attention. Yet they need to be explained, tested, and verified. Observe the conversation of certain persons, and see how many principles of this kind are appealed to. (Cf. p. 118 ff.) 3. The Formal or Purely Logical Fallacies are those which result from violating any of the logical rules of propositions and reasonings. The most frequent are: (i) In immediate inferences: the confusion of contrary and contradictory terms and proposi- tions; the violation of the rules of opposition, conversion, and contraposition. (2) In mediate inferences: the fallacy of four terms, of undistributed middle, of the illicit process or undue extension of either the major or the minor term, of negative premises, and of the consequent, i.e. the violation of the rules of hypothetical syllogisms. 4. Verbal Fallacies fallacies in dictione, or fallacies of language arise from the use of terms. They include a defect in the form of the syllogism, and consequently a violation of its rules, but this defect comes from the matter, that is, from the terms which are used. Hence they are also called semilogical fallacies. The most important are: (a) Amphibology, or the use of ambiguous grammatical struct- ures and sentences, e.g. "The noble hound the wolf hath slain," or this sign at the entrance of a store: "Why go elsewhere to be cheated? Come in here." (b) Equivocation, or the use of a term more frequently of the middle term in two senses, so that the syllogism has really four terms: "What produces intoxication is evil, and should be prohibited; the use of alcoholic liquors produces intoxication; therefore it should be prohibited." Distinctions should be made between the various alcoholic beverages, their various uses, and the various circumstances in which they may be used. (c) Composition, or affirming of the totality that which is true only of the parts taken distributively; "All the angles of a triangle are less than two right angles " is true of any angle taken separately, not of their sum. (d) Division, or affirming of the parts distributively that which is true only of the totality. "All the angles of a triangle are equal OBSTACLES 259 to two right angles " is true of the totality, not of any one angle. From the collective vote, i.e. the vote of the majority of Congress, or from the verdict of a jury, I cannot infer the votes of the various members taken individually. (e) Accent, or the ambiguity arising from the difference in the stress laid on a particular syllable of a word, or on a special word in the sentence. 5. Real Fallacies fallacies extra dictionem, or material fal- lacies depend not so much on the form as on the matter of the syllogism. Hence they suppose the knowledge, not only of the rules of syllogism, but also of the subject with which the syllogism deals. (a) The fallacy of accident a dicto simpliciter ad dictum secundum quid consists in the erroneous inference of a special or conditional statement from a general and unconditional state- ment. " In a republican government, subjects have the right to vote; criminals are subjects; therefore they have the right to vote." (6) The converse fallacy of accident a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter is the reverse of the preceding. "We must avoid intoxication; wine produces intoxication ; therefore we must not drink wine." Only a certain use, or rather abuse, of wine produces intoxication. (c) Begging the question petitio principii is a fallacy in which the truth of the conclusion itself is presupposed in the premises, that which is to be proved being assumed as the very ground of proof. This occurs frequently when the principle of proof is a popular axiom accepted a priori and without question- ing. "Nothing exists but what the senses can perceive; the senses cannot perceive God; therefore God does not exist." The major cannot be true unless we already suppose the conclusion that an invisible God does not exist. This fallacy is also called circulus in probando, vicious circle, or argument in a circle. The really identical propositions are generally separated by several intermediate steps, and expressed in different forms, so that the fallacy is not always easy to detect. (d) Irrelevant reasoning, or evading the question ignoratio elenchi consists in arguing perhaps validly to the wrong 260 LOGIC point; in proving a conclusion which was not in question, in such a way that the right conclusion seems to have been proved. If a man is accused before the court, the lawyer may praise his family, his moral and civic virtues and qualities, or appeal to feelings, instead of proving that he is not guilty of the offence for which he is tried. It is the great resource of those who have a weak cause to defend, and is used in many ways. 6. Special Fallacies of Induction. (a) Referring to observa- tion, (i) Non-observation of instances. We are inclined to notice affirmative rather than negative instances, coincidences rather than their absence, especially when they suit a preconceived theory. Or certain relevant facts or groups of facts may be over- looked. (2) Non-observation of circumstances. One may neglect the circumstance which is the true cause, or which is important for the explanation of a fact. (3) Mai-observation, either because of the imperfection of the senses and instruments, or because of intellectual dispositions which make man see what he is anxious to find, and prevent him from seeing what he does not want to find. This leads to the fallacy of the false cause non causa pro causa, post hoc ergo propter hoc which considers as the true cause a fact or circumstance which is a mere accidental coinci- dence. One must always be careful to distinguish between what is really perceived or observed, and what is inferred from such observations. (b) False analogy and example, or the exaggeration of the points of likeness or difference, as " Ab uno disce omnes. )y (c) The wrong application of inductive methods; hastiness; the exaggeration of the value of theories and hypotheses. II. ERROR i. Causes. Error is a false judgment. Its mam causes may be assigned as follows: (a) External causes, (i) In the object: The difficulty and complexity of the object under investigation. Hence the neces- sity of a long, complex, and manifold process of inference at any step of which error may creep in and vitiate all subsequent results. (2) In the means used to reach the object: The reliance on incompe- OBSTACLES 261 tent authority and on customary views; language, which may be ambiguous, and hence a source of many misunderstandings; the impossibility of reaching the same certitude and of using the same methods in all sciences. (b) Internal or subjective causes (see Psychology), (i) Intel- lectual: (a) In general, the weakness and fallibility of the human mind; its dependence on organic conditions; preconceived ideas, prejudices, and intellectual surroundings; education and the result- ing habits of thought, (b) In a more special manner, the senses and imagination which should be, but are not always, guided by the understanding; the defects of memory, forgetfulness and inaccurate memory; the lack of attention and of the power of observation and inference; irreflection and hastiness in judging things and persons. (2) Moral: In general, the passions, which prevent us from seeing things in their true light; especially pride and exaggerated self-confidence, which cause a man to affirm or deny rashly, and make him loath to abandon a position once he has taken it; love and hatred, that make him exaggerate or mini- mize; the will, in things that are practical; the desire to prove instead of investigating, owing to which the value of reasons is overestimated, and facts are adapted so as to fit in with a pre- conceived theory. 2. Remedies. The main remedies of error are easily inferred from what has just been outlined concerning its causes, (i) Try to apply the rules of logic, both of induction and deduction. Use definitions and divisions. (2) Pay attention to the validity of every step you take. (3) Without falling into scepticism, be careful in receiving information from others, and be not always ready to swear by it. In matters where proofs are possible and where you can appreciate them, ask for them. Always examine the value of a testimony before you accept it. (4) Acquire habits of reflection, calmness of judgment, steadiness and seriousness of study. They are indispensable to success. (5) Endeavor to develop intellectual feelings, especially a great disinterestedness and a sincere love of truth. CONCLUSION Main Rules to be Observed in Controversies and Discussions. Discussions arise from the diversity of opinions. They are very useful when carried on with the proper spirit and disposition. But in many cases, a discussion becomes a dispute and an intolerant altercation, in which the purpose is not so much to find the truth or inculcate it as to triumph over and to down an opponent, cost what may, and even should the truth suffer thereby. In some cases, on certain subjects, or with certain persons, it will be much more profitable to avoid any discussion, because it is sure to be useless, and may be harmful. Some rules will be stated to be followed before, during, and after a written or oral discussion. i. Before. "Id faciam quod in principio fieri in omnibus disputationibus oportere censeo, ut quid illud sit de quo disputa- tur explanetur, ne vagari et errare cogatur oratio, si ii qui inter se dissenserint non idem esse illud de quo agitur intelligant" (Cicero, De Oratore, I, c. 48). This precept is very prudent, and, if it were always followed, many discussions would become need- less. It often happens that, for lack of previous understanding, two bitter opponents come to find out, at the end, that they fight for almost the same ideas. Hence (i) Ascertain the meaning of the terms, especially of those that are vague and ambiguous. (2) Ascertain the meaning of the propositions on both sides. See whether they are universal or particular, or restricted in any manner, etc. (3) To avoid the ignoratio elenchi and the petitio principii, see to what school of science, philosophy, religion, etc., the adversary belongs, so as to start from principles admitted on both sides. Against an atheist I cannot suppose the existence of God. Against a rationalist I may suppose the existence of God, but I cannot argue from divine revelation, and so on with other classes of men. No discussion is possible unless it is based on principles common to both parties. 262 RULES OF DISCUSSION 263 2. During. Logical and moral rules are to be observed. (a) Logical, (i) Take care that all the rules of logic are ob- served on both sides. Keep a close watch on all the facts brought forward and on all the principles used. Examine whether they are clear and certain. (2) Frequently facts and personal inter- pretation of facts are presented together as one. Keep them distinct. (3) Keep yourself and your opponent to the point at issue. A man who feels the weakness of his position frequently will tend to shift the problem to some other point, and drift away from the main question. (4) Avoid, and make your opponent avoid, verbosity, that is, an abundant flow of words making up for the paucity of ideas. Hence, after a long presentation, sum up the ideas expressed, and reduce them to stricter forms of syllo- gism in order to test their value more easily. See also that the same terms are always used in the same sense. (5) When con- tending against a view, beware of the common tendency to go too far, to fall into the opposite extreme, and to try to prove too much. (6) While following the preceding recommendations, avoid the ridicule of rigid formalism that wants to use none but perfect syllogisms, and affects pedantry. (b) Moral, (i) Practise moderation. Avoid the anxiety to make your opinion prevail. Look for light, not for triumph. (2) Avoid anger and impatience. To abuse an adversary is not to prove the truth of one's contention; on the contrary, it is frequently a sign of weakness. Truth stands in no need of in- jurious and ungentlemanly remarks and abusive epithets. More- over, passion has for its effect to blind the mind and prevent it from seeing things in their true light. (3) Avoid intolerance. All men are fallible. Practise the great principle: "In dubiis libertas." Do not try to impose your view simply because it is yours, but because you are convinced that it is true. (4) Honesty and fairness must be practised all the time. It is always dis- honest knowingly to use inaccurate statements or distorted facts in order to prove one's contention. It is the more so when arguing against uneducated persons, who cannot see the falsity of such assumptions, and are more easily misled. 3. After. (a) If victorious, practise modesty. Nothing is 264 LOGIC more cowardly than to abuse a defeated opponent. Arrogance is a sign of conceit, and indicates that a man loves his own satis- faction more than the truth, (b) Be not depressed by defeat, and be honest enough to accept the truth. Always remember Cicero's maxim: "Cuiusvis hominis est errare, nullius nisi insipi- entis in errore perseverare " (Philipp. XII, c. 2). AESTHETICS OR THE NORMATIVE SCIENCE OF THE FEELINGS OF THE BEAUTIFUL INTRODUCTION I. WHAT is ^ESTHETICS? 1. The term "^Esthetics." Etymologically, "aesthetics" (cu'sflijTiKi}, from alMvofjMi , to perceive) is an adjective form now used substantively, and indicates that which has reference to sensation or perception. Its meaning has been narrowed down to a special kind of feelings or sentiments, namely those originating from the perception of beauty. As an adjective, " aesthetic " has either a subjective or an objective meaning. We speak of an aesthetic taste, i.e. a just and keen appreciation or judgment of beauty; and we also speak of a thing as being more or less aesthetic. As a substantive, "aesthetic," or more frequently "aesthetics," is objective, and includes the science of beauty, the rules of taste and of art. It is the normative science of the cesthetic feelings. 2. ^Esthetic Feelings. If we examine the whole group of mental states known as feelings or the affective life, we find that the feelings proper pleasure and pain cannot be assigned any special norm. Experience and association manifest which things or uses of things are pleasurable, and which are painful. All that can be done is to seek the former and avoid the latter. To a great extent emotions are also subjective. In so far as they can be controlled and governed, they fall under the rules of morality, politeness, decency, sociability, etc. Besides these general norms, 265 266 AESTHETICS no other can be assigned to either self-regarding or altruistic emo- tions. The will to subdue them if they are wrong or excessive, and the will to acquire them if they are good and lacking; in every case, the will to control them as explained in psychology - is about the only rule that can be given for this class of feelings. Intellectual, moral, and religious sentiments must be governed in accordance with the principles of logic, ethics, and religion. There remain therefore the aesthetic feelings which require a special treatment here, but which can be allowed but a few pages in this elementary course. 3. The Science of Esthetics. ^Esthetics is the science which tries to determine the conditions of beauty, to analyze the elements that constitute it and enable it to produce aesthetic feelings. Beauty may be natural or artificial; aesthetics deals with both. Because tastes and appreciations differ, it has been said that aesthetics cannot be a science, and that no rules Can be given for aesthetic feelings. But the fact that, notwithstanding many divergences, there are certain objects which practically all men agree in finding beautiful, and others which all agree in finding ugly, shows that there must be some reason in the subject, or in the object, or in both, for this uniformity. Moreover, without considering how other individuals are affected, I find different types of beauty, and I may ask in what respect those different objects a piece of music, a statue, a building, a person, a poem, etc. agree so as to deserve the common adjective "beautiful" which I apply to them. Undoubtedly there is a science of the beautiful. Even if conclusions are not always clear and cogent, there are reasons accounting for the aesthetic feeling. Esthetics is not a strict science like mathematics or even like physics. The rules of art cannot compare with the laws of chemical combina- tion. Yet certain principles must be observed, although they may be applied differently, and much is left to individual con- ception and interpretation. II. THE PLACE OF ^ESTHETICS The object of logic is the true, that of ethics, the moral good, that of aesthetics, the beautiful. Logic is the normative science NATURE OF .ESTHETICS 267 of the intellect, ethics, of the will, aesthetics, of the feelings of the beautiful. This leads us to inquire into the relations of the beau- tiful with the true and the good. i. Relations Between Beauty and Truth. (a) Beauty can- not be identified with truth. Some beautiful things, like poetry, romance ... are not true, but fictitious. Others, without being fictitious, cannot be called true, e.g. music. On the other hand, some truths are not beautiful, or may be positively ugly. We do not find any beauty in the truths "four and four are eight "; "the straight line is the shortest distance between two points"; "it rained yesterday "; "John Smith died last week," etc. (b) Yet there are relations between the true and the beautiful, (i) That which is false, unlikely, and unnatural is not beautiful. A picture in which the proportions are not kept, a novel in which events appear impossible or unlikely, produce a disagreeable im- pression. A statue or drawing with certain defects and depart- ures from nature will be pronounced ugly, etc. (2) Many truths of the intellectual order, when taken together systematically, are beautiful for those who can understand and penetrate them. There may be no beauty in a geometrical axiom, yet the science of geometry, with its numerous deductions, is not without beauty. There may be no beauty in a single physical conclusion, e.g. that heat expands metals, or that matter attracts matter in direct ratio to its mass, and in inverse ratio to the square of the distances. But certainly physical sciences reveal the beauty and harmony of the material world, either in the largest bodies (like astronomy), or in the smallest (like the science of radio- activity). (3) The effort, success, and power of certain minds in grasping the truth, in passing from truth to truth and in perceiving rela- tions, is also worthy of admiration. (4) The perceived beauty of a science is an incentive to its pursuit. The man who^ admires the laws of nature, the marvellous structures of living organisms, etc., will become more enthusiastic for the study of physical and biological sciences, because every new step discovers some new harmony and some new beauty. (5) However, even where the true and the beautiful coincide, 268 ESTHETICS the formal reason of the true and the formal reason of the beauti- ful are not identical, and the effects produced on the mind by these two aspects are not the same. I may perceive the truth without admiring the beauty, or admire the beauty without reference to the truth. 2. Relations Between Beauty and Goodness. Good means (i) agreeable, (2) useful, (3) conformable to the rules of morality. (a) The sentiment of beauty is always pleasant and agreeable, but many things are agreeable without being beautiful. The taste of an apple, a walk in the country, the smell of a rose, rest after fatigue, etc., are agreeable, yet not beautiful. Beauty is one special source of pleasure. An object is not beautiful because it is agreeable; it may be agreeable because it is beautiful. (b) The useful is not always beautiful; instruments, tools, clothes, etc., are useful; they frequently are not beautiful. On the other hand, many beautiful things have no practical use in themselves besides satisfying man's aesthetic taste or giving him some recreation, e.g. a statue, a picture, a flower-bed, etc. Or they may be useful indirectly by reminding one of noble examples, and inciting to follow them. It may even happen that the beauty of a thing seems to make it less useful, as certain architectural ornaments, or the hart's antlers which hinder him. Even where the two coincide in the same thing, the reason why it is beautiful is not the same as that for which it is useful. Beauty is an end in which the mind rests without looking beyond. The feeling of beauty is disinterested and stops at the contemplation and enjoy- ment of its object. Utility is essentially the quality of a means. A thing is not useful purely and simply; it is useful for this or that end. A plain dress, a simple house may be as useful as, and even more useful than, other dresses and residences which are much more beautiful. Where beauty and utility are combined, beauty is added as something distinct from utility. (c) Not all actions morally good are beautiful. To speak the truth, to return a lost article to its owner, to respect one's parents, to give alms, are good actions which, under ordinary circumstances, excite in us no feelings of admiration. On the contrary, certain hideous characters in a novel or a drama, moral monsters, may NATURE OF AESTHETICS 269 contribute by contrast to foster the total aesthetic satisfaction. But immorality as such cannot be beautiful either in real life or in works of art. The close relations of beauty and morals were emphasized by the Greeks, who frequently put together the beautiful and the good. They speak of KoXos K&ya06s, or even in one word KoAoKayatfos. To/caXov is frequently moral beauty or virtue, and in fact the Stoics identified the two. Without going to this extreme, the influence of artistic beauty on morals cannot be denied. The beautiful, being agreeable and attractive, is a spring of action. To represent the immoral as beautiful and attractive is therefore morally wrong. Art may be of great service in moral- izing, as is clear from experience, and from the principles laid down in psychology concerning the influence of imagination and feelings on the passions, the will, and the character. Art need not always be at the service of morals, and all works of art need not be under- taken for the purpose of teaching lessons. (But at least art must never be immoral, nor represent that which is wrong under the aspect of beauty, j By way of comparison and elimination, the preceding considera- tions have already given some ideas concerning the nature of beauty. We shall now proceed to a more positive analysis. CHAPTER I BEAUTY Whatever is agreeable is not thereby beautiful. Yet the aes- thetic feeling is one of the forms of agreeable feelings. What are its special characteristics? Both a subjective and an objective analysis will help in finding them. I. SUBJECTIVE ASPECT We shall recall and complete what has been said in psychology on the aesthetic feeling (p. 155). i. Several Mental Factors contribute to produce aesthetic feelings. (a) The senses through which the beautiful object is perceived. They are sight and hearing. (b) The imagination and, with it, the association of ideas and suggestion. The perceived object arouses in the mind images of objects already perceived or constructed by the imagination, and ideals formed by the higher mental powers. All these give a certain coloring to the actual perception. Hence the feeling of beauty is the combined result of the actual perception and of the images and ideals which the object recalls or suggests. (c) The intellect. The object must not only be perceived, but, to some extent, understood. Its elements must be known in their mutual relations. The harmonies of the world are beautiful only for those who understand them. The intellectual element appears also in the absolute judgment which every man, rightly or wrongly, has a tendency to pass on the aesthetic qualities of an object. When perceived, beauty seems to have such a character of evi- dence that one is inclined to suffer no contradiction on this point. (d) Activity. What is so simple and obvious as to leave no room for personal activity produces no feeling of beauty. This 270 BEAUTY 271 feeling is greater when the beauty is discovered little by little, and when it requires a certain application to perceive it. If we are almost exclusively passive, to glance rapidly at a painting, or to listen distractedly to a musical composition, will produce little or no aesthetic feeling. A man must work his own way into the object in order to grasp its inner beauty. 2. Essential Factor. From the preceding remarks we infer that the feeling of beauty results from the harmonious activity of several mental faculties. However, the fundamental, or rather essential, process seems to be the understanding of the object, which depends on natural endowments and on aesthetic education. Why is it possible for children, and even for a number of adults, to find the music of the street-organ as beautiful as perhaps more beautiful than the first-class performance of a master- piece? Undoubtedly because they cannot understand the latter. In the same way some will derive more aesthetic satisfaction from a ten-cent picture with glaring colors than from a real work of art. The aesthetic feeling is greater in proportion as the object is under- stood better and as the relations of its parts among themselves and with the totality are grasped and mastered more completely. 3. Diversity of Esthetic Judgments. The diversity of these individual factors in different persons accounts for the diversity of aesthetic judgments. Appreciations vary with individuals, countries, races, degrees of civilization, and periods of time. With- out referring to the caprice of fashion in dress and ornamentation, it is otherwise evident that tastes vary. The source of this diver- sity is to be found in the complexity of mental factors that influ- ence the feeling of beauty. Every individual has his own ideals to which he refers objects, and his own images with their different associations. As a consequence, actual perception will arouse various ideas and images in the mind. Education, surroundings, character, habit, novelty, etc., will also exercise a marked influence on the aesthetic judgment. II. OBJECTIVE CONDITIONS Besides these subjective factors, objective elements must admitted. Certain things are beautiful for all men and at all 272 AESTHETICS times, although their beauty may not always be fully appreciated. Moreover, men are agreed that there is a good and a bad taste. The possibility of developing the aesthetic taste means again that there are some rules for the beautiful. It was said above that the chief source of aesthetic pleasure is the understanding; but the understanding of what? Not of the truth of the object, since the beautiful is not to be identified with the true. There are therefore other aspects in the object which account for the sub- jective feeling. To these we now pass. / i. Three Conditions are Required in the Object: (i) Ful- lness, perfection, and completeness, (2) unity amid variety, (3) \splendor and clearness. (a) To be beautiful, an object must not lack any of its essential parts, functions, or elements. // must possess a certain perfection, completeness, energy, and life, varying of course with the type to which it belongs. Incompleteness and deformity are always ugly and displeasing. The application of this is clear in the natural order. See why one horse is pronounced beautiful, and another not; why a fertile cornfield, or a forest with abundant vege- tation, or a high mountain, etc., are beautiful, whereas the field with brambles or a few corn-stalks, the small elevation and hill, produce no such impression. We rather call pretty (not to say cute) that which is of small proportions. The elements or aspects of the whole object may be considered apart, and found beautiful, e.g. the facade of an edifice, the face of a hunchback, etc., but then they are considered as complete in themselves. Again, and for the same reason, an ugly person may perform a beautiful action; in an ordinary composition there may be found beautiful passages, etc. What is true of material objects is true also of intellectual and moral beauty. It requires some perfection, power, or special greatness. (b) Variety means a multiplicity of parts, or a successive change. There is variety in an edifice because it has several parts, several ornaments, windows, doors, columns, etc. There is variety in poetry or in a novel because different ideas, events, circumstances ... are evolved successively. There is variety in music because there is at the same time a multiplicity of combined sounds, and BEAUTY 273 successive changes of sounds, tempo, rhythm, etc. Generally, monotony, sameness, and lack of change are tedious and disagree- able. The variety and number of parts must be in proportion to the nature of the object, and must not be exaggerated. Too many parts, too many successive changes, a superfluity of orna- ments, decorations, and colors are also opposed to beauty, because generally they are obstacles to the unity which is also required. It is not enough to have many elements, they must harmonize together in some unity. Many disparate things, unconnected parts and incoherent details, are not beautiful; there must be symmetry, proportion, order, and adaptation. A common centre, a unity of action and of plan are required to prevent the attention from being diffused. This harmony must be found not only between the parts of the object, but also between the object and its surround- ings. A statue or ornament will produce a different effect accord- ing to the objects found around it. High-flown eloquence is out of place in conversation. A beautiful frame may not be adapted to a certain painting, etc. (c) Finally, a certain splendor, neatness, or clearness is required. The qualities mentioned above must be sufficiently apparent. There must be enough light to see a picture or a drawing; its lines and colors must be visible without too much strain, etc. The unity amid variety should be perceived without too great an effort and tension. 2. There are Various Types of Beauty. (a) Ideal beauty is a type or, as the word itself indicates, an ideal according to which beautiful concrete objects are judged, or which the artist strives to realize and express. Real beauty is that which is found in existing objects. It is more or less perfect according as it realizes more or less completely the conceived ideal. (b) Beauty is natural or artificial according as it is found in nature without man's intervention, or, on the contrary, is the work of man. The sea, mountains, animals, the songs or colors of birds, are natural. Statues, buildings, music . . . are artificial. Man may embellish nature, and the result is partly natural and partly artificial. (c) Physical beauty is expressed in matter; intellectual beauty 19 274 AESTHETICS results from the exercise of reason; moral beauty depends on the mode of exercise of free activities. (d) Finally, we mention again the distinction already explained in psychology between the simply beautiful, the sublime, and the pretty (p. 156). We need not discuss the question whether these objects produce more or less intensive forms of the same feeling, or specifically distinct feelings. CHAPTER II THE FINE ARTS I. NATURE or THE FINE ARTS 1. Meaning of Art. In general, art means a collection of rules or of activities necessary for the skilful production of certain works. Art is frequently contrasted with nature ,and artificial with natural. The former is produced by human activity, the latter without it. Art is also opposed to science. The fundamental difference between them is that science refers to knowledge; art, to practice. Hence arise two other points of difference, (i) True science is based on universal laws, and is valid for all men and at all times. Art is more personal, and more changeable according to times and places. (2) Science is acquired by study; art, chiefly by practice. Science also, it is true, may have a practical purpose, and in fact certain sciences, e.g. logic, medicine, etc., may also be arts, but the formal difference remains. As sciences they deal with what is, with the truth, and with the reasons of things. As arts they deal with the production of what does not yet exist, with the practice and the action. A man may have the com- plete science of medicine without ever applying it. He knows the causes and remedies of diseases without using this knowledge. On the contrary, a man may possess only the art of medicine. His own experience or that of others may have taught him the value of certain plants or remedies which he may use to good effect without knowing the reasons why they are beneficial. 2. Meaning of Fine Arts. Arts are divided into useful or mechanical, and aesthetic or fine arts. The former tend to the production of something useful; the latter to the production of something beautiful. The artisan will select materials such as wood, steel, or stone in order to make something useful, a table, 275 276 AESTHETICS a saw, or a house. This object itself is destined to serve a purpose; it is a means to something else, not an end in itself. The artist tries to produce something which is an end in itself, and not simply a means. It is often difficult to draw the line between the two because the beautiful is also frequently useful, e.g. a building; but, as already indicated, the two aspects must be distinguished. From what precedes it may be inferred that eloquence is not, strictly speaking, one of the fine arts, for it aims at persuading others. The same is true of the history of heroic deeds, and the lives of the saints, which are written for the purpose of instruction. However, these may become arts if the grace of the gestures, the harmony of vocal inflections, the charms of the style and composi- tion, etc., are intended. Fine arts tend primarily to the produc- tion of beautiful works without regard to any other purpose except the satisfaction of the mind's aspirations toward beauty. II. ART AND NATURE i. Realism and Idealism. Beauty is found both in nature independently of human intervention, and in art, that is, in works which are intentionally produced by man. Moreover, we have said that beauty always supposes two elements, one sensible and real, the other ideal and intelligible. Hence the questions: Must artificial beauty be a simple imitation of natural beauty? Must it reproduce the real and the sensible of nature as closely as possi- ble? Or, on the contrary, must the artist overlook nature so as to form higher and independent ideals? Realism chooses the first alternative; idealism, the second. In their extreme forms, both are to be rejected, and the true answer is found between them. Works of art must be based on nature and inspired from it. Yet they must not be mere imitations or copies, but idealized repre- sentations. (a) Art borrows its materials sounds, colors, etc. from nature. Moreover, what is against nature is never beautiful, e.g. a statue without due proportions. Finally, pure idealism tends to abstraction, i.e. to the absence of reality and life, and therefore has less power to arouse aesthetic feelings. (b) But art cannot be a sterile imitation of nature, (i) Music THEFINEARTS 277 is not a mere imitation of natural sounds; nor architecture, of natural forms. Painting and sculpture are not the same as photo- graphing and casting. (2) Nor can art, if it merely imitates nature, be as beautiful as nature, for, in many cases, it is incapable of repre- senting the details, greatness, life, and movement that are found in nature. It represents only some of the realities of nature. (3) Not everything in nature is beautiful; nor is any object per- fectly beautiful, for none realizes completely the type of beauty of the class to which it belongs. (c) Art, therefore, must borrow its materials and objects from nature, but also idealize, purify, and refine them, making abstrac- tion of certain features and emphasizing others. 2. Advantages of Art over Nature. Art cannot reproduce all the realities of nature. Thus sculpture reproduces forms, but not colors. Art, however, has several advantages. (a) It is not subject to the same laws of space and time that are found in nature. A landscape covering in reality many square miles, which cannot be embraced at a single glance, may be repre- sented on a small canvas where its harmonious beauty will be grasped at once. A multitude of events which would require a long period of time may be condensed in a theatrical play. The deterioration which occurs in nature, especially in living organ- isms, is avoided in art, etc. (b) Art is not subject to the physical laws which prevent nature from realizing a complete and perfect type. Art supposes abstrac- tion, and represents only certain features which it idealizes. III. THE PRODUCTION OF WORKS OF ART We shall examine the conditions required in the work itself and the processes by which the artist produces it. i. Qualities Required in the Work. The object must be one, true and good, and, in general, have the qualities of the beautiful. (a) We have already spoken of unity in variety as one of the conditions of beauty. Thus, in an edifice we require the unity of style and architecture, and the proportion of the various parts, for if the style is not the same, or if the parts are out of proportion, the result is not harmonious. In a play or a novel we require the 278 AESTHETICS unity of composition one plot around which other events are centred. In a picture we require things that are not disparate, but can associate together to form one complete whole. In a volume of essays we do not expect one unit, but several. We expect a sequence throughout a novel. (b) Truth does not mean that the work of art must be a mere imitation of nature, for art idealizes nature. Yet it must be what we generally call natural or likely. Thus a personage supposed to be gifted with a certain quality, to have a certain character, or to be subject to a certain passion, must be made to speak and act naturally, i.e. in conformity with these endowments. To fail in this, or to exaggerate beyond measure, shocks the aesthetic feelings. The statue or painting of a man need not represent any man who exists or ever existed, but it must represent a human form with all its essential features. (c) Vice and immorality as such cannot be beautiful. If they cause pleasure, it is either on account of the skill of the artist, or because of the passions of those who perceive such works. It is not allowable to represent as beautiful and worthy of admiration that which is in opposition to the rules of morality. But, with due caution, it may be represented as an object of aversion which, by contrast, makes virtue more beautiful. 2. The Realization of Beauty. The artist must form an ideal, find the means of expressing it, and use these. (a) The conception of an ideal is based on the study of nature. Before applying the colors to the canvas, the painter must have in his mind the representation of the figure or the objects which he wants to paint. Before starting to write, the poet, novelist, or playwright must know what human passion he will describe, what plot he will unravel, and what circumstances he will represent. This ideal is higher or lower according to the artist's power to understand the beauties of nature, rise above them, and abstract the beautiful features from the common, insignificant, or ugly features with which they are mixed. The nature and loftiness of the ideals and interpretations will vary with the personal qualities of the artist. In their relation to nature, the artist and the scientist have an THE FINE ARTS 279 altogether different attitude. The scientist's aim is to know what is, and his mind must, as far as possible, grasp the whole reality in all its complex details. He must express his knowledge accu- rately, neglecting nothing, and describing facts, events, and things in their various aspects. In scientific books, illustrations are not necessarily beautiful, they may even be positively repugnant, for instance in books on medicine, but they must be true to nature. The artist selects only what suits his purpose, and is free to change and adapt the materials found in nature. He is original, and supplies something out of his own mind. In this process of con- ception, imagination, sensibility, and artistic taste are the most prominent factors. (b) The artist must find the means and materials best adapted to express his ideal. He follows general rules already mentioned, and more special rules like those of concord and discord, rhythm and tempo in music; unity, rhythm, and rhyme in poetry, etc. In this process of finding and choosing the means, the main faculties necessary are imagination and memory, association, attention, sensibility, and the aesthetic taste which directs the selection. (c) Execution is the expression itself of the ideal. To a great extent it is a question of practice and of the proper use of instru- ments. The artist's purpose is to reproduce in matter that which he has conceived in his mind, and the perception of which will produce in others the same emotions and arouse the same ideals. Hence, as far as possible, the work of art must be animated, resplendent, and have a soul that reveals itself through sense- perception. IV. CLASSIFICATION OF THE FINE ARTS i. General. (a) It is difficult to give a satisfactory classi- fication of the fine arts; difficult also, and even impossible, to give a complete enumeration of them, for it is not always possible to establish a clear distinction between several minor subdivisions; nor is it always possible to determine whether a given art should be counted among the fine arts. (b) It is generally admitted that there are five principal fine arts : architecture, sculpture, painting, music, and poetry. Among 280 ESTHETICS the secondary or auxiliary fine arts, mention may be made of dancing, which is subordinate to, though widely different from, music; acting, which is auxiliary to poetry; embroidery, pottery, jewelry, gardening, park-making, dress-making, house-ornament- ing, cabinet-making, etc., which are subsidiary to painting, sculpt- ure, and architecture. We shall not attempt to give any definition of these several arts, still less their special technical rules. Their mutual relations will be shown best by indicating the most impor- tant principles of classification which have been proposed. 2. Principles of Classification. (a) The first and most com- mon distinction is derived from the senses by which the work of art is perceived. These are vision and hearing. Hence there are: (i) Visual arts sculpture, architecture, and painting. (2) Auditory arts music and poetry. Acting and dancing are visual and also auditory, since they are subsidiary to music and poetry. (b) In a similar way are distinguished: (i) The arts of repose, plastic or formative, in which all the parts may be perceived simul- taneously. (2) The arts of motion and speech, in which the parts are successive and can be perceived only after one another. The former have reference chiefly to space; the latter, to tune. (c) Considered in their relation to nature, arts are either imita- tive (representative), or non-imitative (presentative), according as they imitate natural objects painting, sculpture, poetry, drama; or are in a stricter sense creative music and architecture. (d) We have seen above that beauty is essentially distinct from utility. Yet, although the special point of view of beauty is always different from that of utility, the two may be combined in the same object. A new principle of classification may be derived from this fact. Architecture is generally serviceable. Even if there are exceptions for certain monuments, its object is generally to build that which is both useful and beautiful. The other principal arts are primarily non-serviceable. Of the minor arts, many are serviceable, like pottery, embroidery, jewelry, glass- making, dancing, and many others which tend to produce or ornament objects which have a practical use. ETHICS OR THE NORMATIVE SCIENCE OF THE WILL INTRODUCTION I. THE MEANING OF ETHICAL SCIENCE I. FACTS Certain facts of internal and external experience with which ethics is concerned must first be mentioned. i. The Ethical Aspect of Human Actions. (a) Besides their psychological aspect, i.e. their nature as processes and the mode of their actual production, human actions have other important aspects or relations. Besides the manner in which they are per- formed and actually take place, there is the manner in which they should take place in order to reach certain ends, and to have certain qualities that are considered as good or advantageous. In other words, there are rules or norms of action. In the ball player, it is not so much the psychological or physio- logical processes that are of interest as their special adaptation to the end in view, which is to score or help team-mates to score runs, and to prevent the opposing team from scoring, according to the rules of the game. The value of the complex actions performed on the diamond is judged by this standard. We speak, not only of what is done, but of what should be or should have been done. Again, to be successful, the merchant must act according to certain principles. We call men good or bad in their respective occu- pations, fit or unfit for their business, prudent or imprudent in their transactions, when we compare what they do with what they ought to do, and when we examine their action to see whether it is adapted to the end which they have in view. 281 282 ETHICS (b) There is another sense the ethical or moral sense in which actions are called good or bad, right or wrong, praiseworthy or blameworthy. Whatever this may mean a question to be examined later on it does not appear at first sight to have an immediate reference to utility or advantage, at least not in the same sense as the actions mentioned above. However useful it may hap- pen to be for an individual, stealing is wrong, and helping those who are in need is right, even if giving alms imposes some sacrifice. I do not consider in the same light the failure to avail myself of a good business opportunity, and the failure to keep my contract made with, or even my word given to, my fellowman. (c) All actions which, considering all circumstances, are wrong must always be omitted. I must never commit perjury or act unjustly. But all right actions do not appear obligatory. Some, it is true, seem to impose themselves on man in such a way that to omit them is to fail in one's duty. Others, on the contrary, seem to be optional; to perform them is good; to omit them is not wrong. Thus, even if I do not comply with the obligation, I consider myself obliged to restore that which is clearly somebody else's property, and to abide by my valid contract. I do not feel obliged in all cases to give alms to every poor man whom I meet on the street, or, if I have the means, to endow hospitals or educational institutions, although all this is good. (d) The question here is not: Which actions are good, and which are bad; which are obligatory, and which are free? The standards vary with the different degrees of culture and with differ- ent classes of persons. History also shows that there has been a great diversity in the past. The question is: Are some actions morally good, and others morally bad? The fact is universally true that man, everywhere and at all times, recognizes the distinc- tion of right and wrong, and has a sense of duty. The consequence of this sense of obligation is the feeling of re- morse or satisfaction which is experienced according as one has acted wrongly or rightly, and the bestowing of blame or praise on other men. 2. Moral Law. From what precedes, the common notions of good, obligation, and duty are sufficiently clear as facts. Now NATURE OF ETHICS 283 there is no obligation without a principle of obligation, without a law , and consequently without a lawgiver. At this point, if asked for an explanation, the ordinary man, and very frequently even the most learned, will hardly be able to give a satisfactory answer. Of course it is wrong to exceed the speed limit with your motor car and to sell certain articles without a license. But wrongness here means rather imprudence and liability to the penalty pro- vided by the law in such cases. I do not mean the same when I say that it is morally wrong for me to set fire to my neighbor's house, or to steal his purse. Hence what is commonly called the law, namely the civil law, is not always assumed and accepted as the standard of moral obligation. Who then is the judge of this moral obligation? What is its standard? And when you tell another man: You must not do this, it is morally wrong; or when you accuse him of being unjust, on what authority do you pronounce? How do you know that it is so? What is your standard? And is your standard necessarily the same as his, or any other man's? Is it universal and must it be accepted by all? In a word, what is the supreme court that is to decide on the question of right and wrong? This is an important problem suggested by obvious facts. 3. Conscience. It is clear that, in order to make its deci- sions known, the law or supreme tribunal, whatever it may be ultimately, must do so through the human mind. When applied to human actions, the decision must always appear in human consciousness in the form of a judgment. This is what we call conscience, the application to a concrete action of the general principles concerning its moral character. Conscience is the actual judgment regarding the morality of actions, and every indi- vidual man has his own conscience just as he has his own under- standing. In the same way that, if I do not see, I may rely on, and be guided by, those who do, and that my eyes may be treated by the oculist, and my errors corrected by others or by my own deeper study and reflection, so my moral judgment may be based on another man's authority, changed, improved, and corrected; but I can no more judge with another man's conscience than I can see with his eyes. 284 ETHICS 4. Meaning of Morality. The special relation of an action to the rules of right and wrong is what we call its morality. "Moral" comes from the Latin "mos" (plural, "mores"), which signifies habit. Applied to actions, it means, (i) that which has relation to the rules of duty and obligation, (2) that which is in conformity with these rules. (a) In the first sense, moral is opposed to non-moral, that is, to that which has no reference whatever to any rules of right and wrong. Only human actions are called moral. A stone or bullet that kills a man is not blamed, but the man who wilfully threw the stone or fired the pistol is considered as having done wrong. Morality supposes some psychological conditions which are not found in beings inferior to man. Nor are all human actions moral, but only those of which man is truly the cause and the free agent, and which he commits with sufficient knowledge and freedom. The man who is under coercion, and, for instance, is carried to a certain place against his will, is not the real agent; the action is not his, and, for him, is not moral. (Cf. p. 167 ff.) There is no morality in the actions of a man who accidentally falls and kills himself, or who speaks and walks in his sleep. Such actions are non-moral. (b) In the second sense, moral is opposed to immoral, that is, to that which is in opposition to the rules of morality and therefore is bad and wrong. In order to be moral in the second sense, or immoral, it is clear that an action must be moral in the first sense. II. THE SCIENCE OF ETHICS i. Nature of Ethical Science. (a) Ethics (from i}0os, character) means the same as moral science, namely, the science of right and wrong, or the science of right conduct. It endeavors to account for the facts which have been indicated above, and to explain their nature, origin, and bearings. It also endeavors to direct human actions, to find the general moral laws by which they should be governed, and to apply these laws to the various cir- cumstances of life. Hence ethics includes two parts, or has two functions; one is essentially practical, and tries to determine what NATURE OF ETHICS 285 we should do and avoid; the other is more speculative, and tries to determine why ultimately we should do or avoid it. (b) From this it follows that, as a whole, ethics is a normative science. It deals with human actions, to find out, not how they are actually performed, but whether and how they should be per- formed. History and psychology are not directly normative sciences. They simply state what takes or took place, and how events or processes occur or occurred. Ethics passes a judgment on the moral value of these actions and determines whether they are right or wrong. (c) The term "law" does not apply to human actions and to physical events in the same sense. Physical laws are abstractions for the facts; they are not rules to which events ought to conform, but to which we see that events do in fact conform. And when what was thought to be a law is found to conflict with facts that are certain, the law has to be abandoned or modified. Not so with moral laws. They are ideals to which human actions do not necessarily conform, but to which they should conform in order to be good. 2. Importance of Ethics. From the scope of ethics its impor- tance may be inferred. In order to live well, perform his duty, and shape his conduct aright, man must first know in what these consist. It is true that there is innate in every man a certain moral sense which tells him his duty, but, on many points, it is vague, and, even where it is clear, one must examine whether and why its dictates are legitimate. It is not enough to feel that an action is right or wrong, one must know that it is so. Moreover, the moral feeling, precisely because it is a feeling, is often uncertain and mis- leading. It has to be interpreted, justified, and directed. Although knowledge is insufficient for good conduct, one may know the good and fail to practise it it is an essential condition of morality. 3. The Relations of Ethics to Other Sciences will now be understood easily. (a) Physical sciences have only a remote relation to ethics, inasmuch as the knowledge or ignorance of physical laws may change the morality of an action by modifying the intention, motives, and foresight of the agent. Thus, according as one is, 286 ETHICS or is not, aware of the poisonous nature of a certain substance, the morality of giving it to a fellowman to swallow will differ. Bio- logical sciences also are indirectly connected with ethics. Many obligations refer to human life and health, but generally they may be known and discussed without any detailed physiological knowl- edge. (b) Psychology is much more closely related to ethics, and for this reason a few pages will be devoted to the psychological implica- tions of morality. At present we shall limit ourselves to pointing out the difference between psychology and ethics. The psychol- ogist studies human actions as processes, to find out how mental functions are related. The moralist tries to regulate human actions. Psychology gives to ethics its materials, but ethics does not place the same value upon all. The psychologist is like the botanist who studies the growth, nature, and characteristics of all plants. The moralist is more like the gardener who arranges certain plants according to an order, cultivates some and carefully excludes others. No action is moral which is not also in some way psychological. (c) Pedagogy and ethics should also be kept in close contact. A complete education trains the whole man, and moral character is essential to man. Man must be accustomed not only to think consistently, but also to act rightly. (d) ^Esthetics and logic, although different from ethics, agree with it in being normative sciences, or in dealing with ideals and standards, the first with the ideals of beauty, the second of truth, the third of moral goodness. Frequently terms are transferred from one science to another. A man who is true to himself is one who acts according to his principles; a beautiful soul or character is one that includes certain moral characteristics, etc. (e) Sociology is also related to ethics, since it considers man in his social aspect, which is the source of many duties. Society is an important factor in the morality of individuals on account of the laws by which it is ruled and of the mere fact of men associating with one another. N.B. We shall see later that ethics is also related to meta- physics and religion. CONDITIONS OF MORALITY 287 4. Division of This Treatise. Ethics will be divided into two parts; the first more speculative and more formal, dealing with duty in general, its nature and conditions; the other more practi- cal, more detailed, and dealing with the various duties and obliga- tions. Before passing to these, however, it is necessary to indicate the main psychological conditions of moral life. II. PSYCHOLOGICAL CONDITIONS OF MORALITY Psychological conditions and influences may be grouped under the three headings of knowledge, feeling, and will. I. KNOWLEDGE 1. Knowledge Necessary to Morality. In general, from what was said above and in Psychology on the relations of intellect and will, it is evident that knowledge is a condition without which an action cannot be voluntary. A man cannot be morally bound by an obligation unless this obligation is known to him. It is impossible to conceive that a man should be responsible for failing in a duty of which he has no knowledge. Moreover, a man must be aware of what he is doing. For instance, he is not responsible for an action performed automatically during sleep. The killing of a man by the accidental discharge of a pistol which was thought to be unloaded may be the result of imprudence, but, as such, it is not morally imputable. Hence a twofold knowledge is required, (i) of what one is doing, (2) of the relations of this action to the rules of morality. These general principles need a little further explanation. 2. Effects of Ignorance. (a) Ignorance may be involuntary or voluntary. It may be unsuspected and unavoidable, when sufficient care has been taken to know one's duty; or it may, to some extent, be due to negligence in investigating one's duty when there was a suspicion of it, or, worse still, when the investigation was omitted precisely in order to act more freely and without restraint. The action due to involuntary ignorance is itself invol- untary, and the will has no share in it. The action due to volun- tary ignorance is not voluntary in itself, yet the will has a share in 288 ETHICS it inasmuch as the ignorance from which it proceeds was voluntary. Hence such an action is called voluntary in its cause. Thus the physician who is aware of his incapacity and incompetence, either in general or in special cases, is accountable for the lives he loses since he knows that he lacks the sufficient knowledge of his art. It is clear that the amount of diligence to be used depends on the importance of the interests in question, the time at one's disposal, the qualifications and opportunities for investigating, the urgency of the action to be performed, and so on. (b) The effects of ignorance are the same whether it affects the nature and consequences of an action, or the existence of a law which commands or prohibits it. I may speak an untruth in good faith thinking that it is the truth ignorantia facti or may fail to see that in the present circumstances lying is wrong ignorantia iuris. (c) In order to prevent possible confusion, it must be noted that we, speak here of the moral obligation, and not merely of the obligation to obey the civil law in any concrete case. When duly promulgated, the civil law is supposed to be known by all the citizens for whom it is intended. Hence a penalty may be inflicted on a man for breaking a law of which he was bona fide ignorant. But if the ignorance is involuntary, there is no moral wrong, although the civil law may be the source of a moral obligation and bind in conscience. II. FEELINGS Feelings exercise a great influence on the intellect and the will. Among them the most important in the present question seem to be love, fear, and anger. A great love or passion blinds the mind more or less completely. The fear of losing that which one loves, or the anger caused by a sense of injury, frequently influences man to take a certain course of action. This action is less voluntary than it would be if performed coolly and deliberately. It will perhaps be performed with greater vehemence and stronger incli- nation, but this inclination proceeds from feeling, not from reason. In the case of the fear of an impending danger, however, a man may freely and deliberately choose a less evil, e.g. promise a liberal CONDITIONS OF MORALITY 289 reward to his rescuer, although he would not otherwise do so. How far, in concrete instances, responsibility is lessened by passions and emotions is frequently impossible to determine exactly. Their influence varies from the slightest, and even imperceptible, im- pulse to a complete blinding of the mind, absence of mastery over oneself, and consequently of freedom and responsibility. III. WILL 1. Coercion. An action may be due to violence or coercion. Instead of proceeding from the command of the will, it may pro- ceed from some external power opposed to the will. Such an action is therefore involuntary. The real agent is the external power, and if this be a person, he alone incurs the responsibility. Thus a man may be dragged to a forbidden place, or compelled to per- form unjust actions. Provided of course that he resists as much as the nature of the case allows, the action cannot be attributed to him. The gravity of the obligation to offer resistance varies with the nature and circumstances of the case, the chances of success in overcoming the violence, and the necessity of showing one's opposition and reluctance. If the possible resistance is not offered, the action is voluntary to some extent, and the responsi- bility remains in varying degrees. The physical violence of which we speak here is actual, and must not be understood in the sense of a mere fear referring to the future, which, as said above, generally leaves the action voluntary. 2. Habit. (a) As explained in Psychology (p. 175 ff.), habit produces uniformity of action, facility and pleasure in acting. Hence it lessens the control of the will, both because the action proceeding from a habit is frequently performed without conscious- ness, or at least without distinct consciousness, and because, even if there is distinct consciousness, the impulse toward the action is greater, and consequently more difficult to overcome, in proportion as the habit is stronger and more inveterate. The influence exercised by habit varies in nature and intensity accord- ing to the nature, origin, and strength of the habit. (b) A habit may be (i) acquired and preserved wilfully; (2) acquired wilfully and preserved unwilfully, when one is making 20 2QO ETHICS serious efforts to overcome it; (3) acquired and preserved unwil- fully. The "wilfulness" in all these cases is itself more or less perfect. In the first instance the morality of the habitual action is not diminished by the fact itself of habit. "Qui vult causam vult et effectum"; the actions due to habit are rightly attributed to the man who consents to the good or bad habit from which they pro- ceed. In the second, the morality is lessened in various degrees according to the strength of the habit, the actual consciousness and consent, and the amount of effort made to resist and uproot it. In the third, the morality is still more reduced, and may even be totally destroyed. The liquor habit may be given as an illus- tration of these various cases. A man may acquire this habit knowingly and freely, and indulge in it although he realizes that it is bad. Or he may acquire it almost without noticing it, owing to physiological conditions, to circumstances, to the presence of alcohol in medicine which he had to use, etc. As soon, however, as he becomes aware of it, he is under the obligation of resisting it and of taking the proper means to overcome it. (c) Habit is a very complex factor in human actions, and it is frequently impossible to trace back all its antecedents in all their details and ramifications. A habit may be so strong as to be almost invincible. But generally it can be overcome by good resolutions and the use of proper means. Even when the individual declares it invincible, in most cases his "I cannot" is to be inter- preted as meaning "I do not want to." The man who is not willing to try seriously and use his best effort shows that, in reality, he consents to the habit. 3. Freedom is an indispensable condition of the moral char- acter of human actions. This has been indicated already in Psychology (p. 180 ff.), and only a few considerations will be added here. (a) At all ages and in all places mankind has recognized two distinct orders of facts. Some are necessary and worthy of neither blame nor praise. Others are free, and their agents are held account- able for them. A man is not blamed for being sick or for acci- dentally hurting himself. He is blamed for wilfully killing his CONDITIONS OF MORALITY 291 fellowman, stealing his neighbor's property, indulging in vices which caused the disease or accident. (b) Obligation supposes the power to do or omit the obligatory action, and hence postulates freedom. There can be no obliga- tion if human actions are necessarily determined and are ruled by laws as necessary as those which are found in the physical world. Obligation is an absurdity if man is not the master of his own actions, and if all are strictly and necessarily determined. (c) The same consideration applies to the notions of right and duty as correlative. A man has a right when he can exact some- thing from his fellowman; he has a duty when he ought to give that which is exacted. The right to exact and the duty to give suppose the actual power to give what is exacted. (d) Responsibility, merit, virtue or vice, self-satisfaction and remorse suppose freedom. (e) Hence freedom is at the very basis of the essential factors of morality. Without it, the terms "obligation," "responsibility," "right" and "wrong," are meaningless, and every action takes place with the same necessity with which the stone falls to the earth and obeys the law of gravitation. Such actions can neither be pre- scribed nor forbidden; they are neither right nor wrong, and deserve neither blame nor praise. It is true that some actions performed by man are necessary, but neither does he feel himself responsible, nor is he held responsible for them. If they are bad, he regrets them as he would regret an unavoidable misfortune or bodily deformity, not in the same way that he is sorry for an action known to be wrong, and yet freely committed. On this point the practice of determinists agrees with the practice of those who admit freedom. The inconsistency of the former is a sign of the connection which exists between the fact of freedom and the facts and elements of morality. CHAPTER I FUNDAMENTAL ETHICS The object of this chapter is to indicate the bases on which morality rests, and to discuss briefly the problems suggested by the obvious facts mentioned above. Although this chapter is rather theoretical, its practical importance is evident, since, hi order to be effective, the rules of morality must rest on secure foundations. ARTICLE I. THE MORAL NORMS OR LAWS The idea of obligation supposes that of a law to which actions should conform, and of a rule which they should follow. This rule may be considered in its external reality, as a law properly so called, and in its internal application or conscience. I. LAW I. DEFINITION AND DIVISIONS i. Meaning of Law. In general, law signifies a constant or uniform rule according to which actions take place. A distinc- tion is to be made between physical, civil, and ethical laws. The first apply only to material beings, the second and third to men as intelligent and free agents. (a) Physical laws are abstract expressions or formulae for the constant, necessary, and uniform mode of happening of phenomena; thus the laws of gravitation, attraction, chemical affinity, etc. Ethical laws do not express what necessarily and constantly hap- pens, but what should happen. They are not indicative, but imperative formulae. (b) When asked why I have certain documents signed before 2Q2 THEMORALLAW 293 a notary public, or why I do not build a house without a permit from the city authorities, I answer that it is the law, and that its violation would make me liable to a penalty. This answer refers to what is called the civil law, i.e. a set of rules promulgated by competent authorities, varying with different countries and govern- ments, and the violation of which is punished in different ways. Were I in another state or country, or at another time, I would not have on this point the same obligations under which I am now. (c) If asked why I do not steal my neighbor's property, or kill my innocent fellowman, I may also answer: Because the law for- bids it. But I feel that the meaning is not the same as above, that the obligation is of a higher character, that it would follow me everywhere and at all times, and that it would continue to exist even did the civil code make no mention of it and inflict no penalty for its transgression. It is based on human nature itself, and for that reason called natural law. (d) The civil law supposes the natural law. In certain cases it is only the expression or enforcement of what human reason it- self dictates, as when it forbids to kill. In other cases, it is reason again that requires obedience to any just command of the civil power, and to any law enacted by the proper authority for the welfare of the subjects. 2. The Natural or Moral Law in the strict sense is that which imposes a universal and strict obligation. It indicates an ideal to be realized, and, although one may fail to submit to its com- mands, yet, in failure, one always has the consciousness of a dis- order and of a lack of harmony between what is done and what should be done. As the term indicates, the natural law is derived from our rational nature itself; it is based on man's essential rela- tions to other beings, and manifested by the light of reason. Some of its fundamental and general precepts are self-evident, like: "Do good and avoid evil; " "Do unto others as you would like to have others do to you." Others are less general and already touch upon something concrete like: " Honor thy father and thy mqther "; " Thou shalt not kill " ; " Thou shalt not bear false witness." Other points, finally, are very complex, and, in many concrete cases, 2Q4 ETHICS their morality may seem doubtful, e.g. lying to procure a great advantage; committing suicide to avoid shame, etc. Natural law and moral law have almost the same meaning, yet the latter term seems to have a greater extension, for civil laws may also impose a strict moral obligation. But, even here, this obligation is based on the natural law commanding to obey superiors when they give just orders. The civil law rules only on matters that refer to the public material welfare. The moral law reaches a number of other actions, even internal feelings like hypocrisy, dissimulation, and evil desire; and some external actions like ingratitude, egoism, gluttony, which the civil law does not consider. What follows applies strictly to the natural law. II. CHARACTERISTICS OF THE MORAL LAW The moral law is given in consciousness with the following characteristics. 1. Obligation. The moral law is not, like physical laws, the expression of what happens fatally and unavoidably, not merely a generalized fact. It is a rule which does not register a fact, but commands, although, even when acknowledging this rule, man may depart from it and disobey. Obligation is distinct both from the determinism of the laws of nature, and from a mere attraction, desirability, or counsel, which does not command strictly in the form of a "Thou shalt . . . ." In a word, it is an imper- ative. 2. Absoluteness. The moral law is a categorical, not a hypothetical, imperative. A law is conditional when it enjoins a certain means to reach an end. It is absolute when it enjoins a thing as an end in itself independently of any condition. In the former case the obligation may be shirked by renouncing the con- ditioning end. In the latter, the obligation, even if not complied with, is unavoidable. Thus, "Thou shalt not steal," "Thou shalt not kill," are absolute commands. But if I say: "You must work in order to preserve your health, or to become rich," or "Avoid defrau