Controversial Blements In Xucretius B^ (3eoroe p. Echman a^^ ^,.,^ ^^<^ — i^/y^-"'^ Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/controversialeleOOeckmrich ^ntxoi?tx0iat ^^tmrnte in Bucre^iue A THESIS FOR THE Doctorate in pbiloeopbi? BY- GEORGE P. ECKMAN APPROVED BY THE EACULTY OE THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OE THE XEW YORK CXIVERSITY, rSgy Nkw York 1899 El ^T]6ev r]\kas al twv (j.€T€(dp(ov viro\|/Cai t|v«x\ovv Kttl al irepl Gavdrov, |xir'] iroTe irpos rifids rj ti, €Ti t€ to }iT) Karavoeiv tovs opovs twv d\'YT]86va)v Kal twv eiriOv- (i,iwv, ovK dv irpocre8e6|ie8a 4>v(rio\o-Yias. 'EiriKOvpov Kvpiai A6|ai, XI. Dioi^encs La erf ins. X. 142. Printed for the author by Charles B. Jackson, New York. CONTEXTS. -3611 Table of Contents. INTRODUCTION. Ap Contemporary Interest in Epicureanism. Character of the period. Causes of the apparent neglect of Lucretius by his contemporaries. Influence of Epicureanism upon cultivated Romans. Reasons for Cicero's comparative silence regarding Lucretius. Recognition of the poet by later generations. (§) A Preliminary Question. To what extent did Lucretius pursue original investigations .' The poets devotion to Epicurus. Evidences of servile imita- tion. Marks of independent treatment of physical pheno- mena. No extreme position tenable. Divisions of the present discussion. L Philosophers With Whom Lucretius Contends Amicably. Respects for early physicists. The main contention. 7. Einpedocles. Object of Lucretius' admiration. Internal evidence that Lucretius studied the works of Empedocles. Halliers proofs. Similarity of literary style. Rhetorical imitations. Doctrinal agreement. Resemblances in explana- tions of physical phenomena. Unquestioned indebtedness of Lucretius. Hostility to Empedocles as representative physi- cist designating one or more substances primordial matter. Various points of conflict. Void and motion. Incompetent primordia. Fallibility of the senses. Mortality of the soul. Teleology. 2. Anaxagoras. Evidence of high esteem of Epicurus for Anaxagoras. Common ground occupied by Anaxagoras and Atomists. General lines of divergence. Sympathy of Lucre- tius with Anaxagoras. Instances in proof. The doctrine of the homoeorneria the real issue between Lucretius and Anaxa- goras. The theory expoundetl. Objections of Lucretius. Void ignored. Infinite divisibility of body. Defective pri- mordia. Secondary qualities in primitive matter. Minima. A pair of dilemmas. 2 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LITRETIIS. J. Democi-itus. The obligation of Epicurus to the philoso- pher of Abdera. Ingratitude of the former. The more commendable spirit of Lucretius. Eulogistic lines. Traces of the pressure of Democritus upon Lucretius'. Harmony of general principles. The doctrine of emanations. The suin- vium bonum. The sexual passion. Earthquakes. ImitJttions of Democritus. The extent of Lucretius' acquaintance with his writings. Chief doctrinal disagreement. Atomic declina- tion. Free-will. Arguments of Epicurus and Lucretius. Minor occasions of controversy. Infinity of number and shapes of atoms. Constitution of the soul. Origin of verbal designations. The rising of the Nile. The gods. II. Philosophers Toward Whom Lucretius Is Hostile. The censoriousness of Epicurus emulated by Lucretius. 1. Heraclilus. Alone denounced by name. Taunt of ob- scurity. Avowed reason for the animosity of Lucretius to- ward Heraclitus the latter's assertion that fire is the original essence from which everything has been derived. Order of Lucretius' arguments. Is the poet's treatment of Heraclitus just? Character of his elemental fire. Hypothesis of conden- sation and rarefaction. Void eliminated. Change by extinc- tion. Doctrine of the senses. Transmutation of primitive matter. Heraclitus and the Stoics. 2. The Stoics. Antagonism of Lucretius an inherited pas- sion. Mutual calumnies of the Stoics and Epicureans. Irrepressible conflict on the subject of nature. Specific points of eontroversy. Properties and accidents. Corporeal- ity and reality. Elemental fire. The structure and course • of the universe. Infinity of space and matter. Theory of centripetal force. Immortality and divinity of the world. Cosmic systems. The world as a living organism. Destrulc- tibility of the world. Theological positions. The character and functions of deity. Stoic ideas of creation and provi- dence incompatible with the supreme repose and happiness of the gods. Likewise disproved by the imperfections of creation. The desire to deliver men from the fear of divine interference the basic reason for Lucretius' argument against Providence, Only valid ground for scientific study. Final cause denied. True philosophy of the gods. Myth of Kybele. Epicureans and Stoics in relation to popular re- ligion. Stern denunciation of prevalent superstition. Ap- parent inconsistency of Lucretius. BIBLIOGRAPHY, BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE CHIEF WORKS CONSULTED IN THIS DISCUSSION. Diogenes Laertius — De Vitis /'^//oj'fl/>^fl/7/w,Tauchnitz.Leipsic, 1895. Cicero, IMarcls Tlllius — De Xatura Deonim. De Finibus, etc., Teubner, Leipsig, 1894. Ritter' et Preller — Historia Philosophiae Graecae, 7th Edition, Gothae, 1888. Mlnro, H. a. J. — 7\ Lucreti Can De Return Naiura, Text, Notes, etc., 4th Ed., Cambridge, 1893. Zeller, E. — Pre-Socratic Philosophy; Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, London, 1892. Usexer, Hermann — Epicurea, Leipsig, 1887. Teuffel, W. S. — History of Roman Literature, London, 1873. Fairbanks, Arthur — The First Philosophers of Greece, New York, 1898. Sellar, \V. Y. — Roman Poets of the Republic, 3d Edition. Ox- ford. 1889. Hallier, Aemilius — Lucreti Carmina e Fragmentis Empedoclis Adum- brata, Jena, 1857. MoMMSEN, Theodor — Historv of Rome. New York, 1875. Masson, John — The Atomic Theory of Lucretius, London, 1884. CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETH'S. CORRIGENDA. P. 8, note 2, read //«rz>7//> instead o{ plurimus; consul ere not consider e. P. 9, line 4, read Catius Insuber. P. 26, line 26, read Katroi instead of Kalrot. P. 29, line 13, read 'EiiireSoKXei; dva-yKatov for avaYKaiov. P. 30, line 3, read queunt instead of quent. P. 31, line 9, read crreCpots instead of o-Teipois. line 22, read -yvuvol instead of ^jjivvol. line 23, read ircviiTevovTa instead of ir€VT]T€vovTa. P. 32, line 22, read ^■x\{ depniare. P. 68, line 10, read pcpXois instead of pcpXiois. P. 75, line 7, read irpwrov instead of irpwTwv. P. 81, line I, read nuriquam instead o{ nemquatu ; remove p)eriod after Chtysippam. line 2, read vocabat instead of vocebal. \ P. 82, note 2, read Praefatio instead o{ Prefatio. P. 90, line 18, read tovtwv instead of tovwv, P, 103, line II, read irpdXritl/is instead of irpdXiiilJis. CDNTRDYERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. INTRODUCTION. Contemporary Interest in Epicureanism. It cannot be denied that the poem of Lucretius failed to awaken any marked interest until long after its publication. The almost unbroken silence of his contemporaries regarding him is significant of the com- parative indifference with which his production was received. The reasons for this neglect are various and not far to seek. In the first place the moment was inopportune for the appearance of such a work. "It was composed in that hapless time when the rule of the oligarchy had been overthrown and that of Caesar had not yet been established, in the sultry years during which the outbreak of the civil war was awaited with long and painful suspense." ^ The poet betrays his sol- icitude for the welfare of his country at this crisis in the introduction of his work, in which he invokes the aid of Venus in persuading Mars to command peace — Efficc ut inter ea f era moenera militiai Per maria ac terras omnis sopita quiescani '^ — and acknowledges that his attention is diverted from literary labors by the exigencies of the state : N^am neque nos agere hoc patriai tempore iniquo Possumus aequo animo nee Memmi clara propago Talibiis in rebus comrnuni desse saluti. '' Munro believes these lines were written toward the close of 695, when Caesar as consul had formed his coalition with Pompey and when there was almost a reign of terror.* The reflection of a state of 1 Monimseii, Hist. Rome, IV, p. 698 (Eng. Tr. ). ' I. 29. 30. M. 41-43- ^Muiim. Luiictiiis. II. p. 30. 6 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. tumult and peril is equally obvious in the opening verses of the second book, where the security of the contemplative life is contrasted with the turbulence of a political and military career.' Particularly signifi- cant are the lines : Si non forte tuas legiones per loca campi Fervere cum videas belli simulacra cientis, Subsidiis magnis et ecum vi constabilitas, Ornatasque armis statuas pariierque animatas, His tibi turn rebus timefactae religiones Effugiunt animo pavide ; mortisque timores Turn vacuum pectus lincunt curaque solutum, Fervere cum videas classem lateque vagari} It can readily be appreciated that a period of such fermentation and alarm would afford opportunity for philosophic study to those alone who were able to retire from political excitements to private leisure and quiet. Moreover the very characteristics of the Epicurean philosophy would recommend it chiefly to persons of this description. Participation in public life was distinctly discouraged by the school of Epicurus, who regarded the realm of politics as a world of tumult and trouble, wherein happiness — the chief end of life — was almost, if not quite, impossible. They counselled entering the arena of public affairs only as an occasional and disagreeable necessity, or as a pos- sible means of allaying the discontent of those to whom the quiet of a private life was not wholly satisfactory.'' Such instruction, though phrased in the noble hexameters of a Lucretius, was scarcely calculated to enjoy immediate popularity in the stirring epoch of a fast hurrying revolution.^ 1 Sellar, Rommi Pods of the Republic, p. 290. 2 II, 40-47. " Caesar after his consulship remained with his army for three months l)efore Rome, and was bitterly attacked by Memmius. Does Lucretius here alhide to Caesar? " Munro, II, p. 122. •^ Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, p. 491, 3, 6. * " In consequence of his mode of thought and writing lieing so averse to his own time and directed to a better future, the poet received little attention in his own age." Teuflfel, Hist. Rom. Lit. I, 201 (Eng. Tr.). "It (Epicureanism) arose in a state of society and under circumstances widely different from the social ar.d political condition of the last phase ol the Roman Republic." Sellar. Roman Poets of the Republic, p. 357. IXTRODUCTIOX. 7 A somewhat ingenious, but unsuccessful, attempt has been made to account for the indifference with which Lucretius was treated on the ground of his assault Upon the doctrine of the future life. It has been suggested that as the enmity of the Christian writers was early called down upon his head for this cause, he was likewise whelmed ' ' under a conspiracy of silence on the part of his Roman contempo- raries and successors " for the same reason. ^ But so general was the skepticism of his age on this question, that it is scarcely credible that the publication of his views could have seriously scandalized the cul- tured classes who read his lines. The same judgment will hold true with reference to the entire attitude of Lucretius toward the tra- ditional religion. It is a sufficient answer to the theory that his in- fidelity created antipathy toward him to record the fact that Julius Caesar, than whom no more pronounced free-thinker lived in his day, was, despite his skepticism, pontifex maxi'mus of the Roman common- wealth, and did not hesitate to declare in the presence of the Senate that the immortality of the soul was a vain delusion.^ That he rep- resented in these heretical opinions the position of many of the fore- most persons of the period is the testimony of contemporary literature. Shall we not find the better reason for the apparent neglect of Lucretius in the era immediately following the issue of his poem in the fact that there was no public at this juncture for the study of Greek philosophy clothed in the Latin language .? Cicero, who de- voted himself with the zeal of a patriot to the creation of a philosoph- ical literature in his native tongue, complained of the scant courtesy paid to his efforts. Xon eram nescius. Brute, cum, quae summis in- geniis exquisitaque doctrina philosophi Graecn sermone tractavisseni, ea Latinis Uteris mandaremus, fore ut hie noster labor in varias reprehen- siones incur reret. Nam qiiibusdam, et Us quidem non admodum indoctis, totum hoc displicet, philosophari. Quidam autem non tam id reprehendunt, si remissius agatur, sed tantum studium tamque muUam operant ponendam in eo non arbitrabantur. Erunt etiam, et ii quidem eruditi Graecis Utter is, contemnentes Latinas, qui se dicant in Graecis legendis operant maUe consumer e. Postremo aliquosfuturos suspicor, qui me ad aUas Utter as vocent, * This is the view advanced by R. T. Tyn-il of the University of Dublin. See his LiiUn Poc'try, p. 74, (Houjrhton, Mifflin & Co., N. Y., 1895). ^ Merivale. History of the Romans. If. p. 354. 8 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. genus hoc scribendi, etsi sit elegans, personae iamen et digtiiiatis esse negent.^ Yet this work, as he explains in his De Divinatione,'^ was undertaken with the commendable purpose of benefitting his countrymen. He anticipated with delight the advantages which would accrue to them when his researches were com- plete. Magnificum illud etiam Romanisque hominibus gloriosum, ut Graecis de philosophia litteris no?i egeant. ^ And later he reaped his re- ward in an awakened interest in the subjects of his studious inquiries. But he was compelled in the beginning to cultivate a sentiment in behalf of those investigations. Lucretius addressed himself to an un- sympathetic public, and was likewise required to wait for applause until a' more appreciative generation rose up to do him honor. Yet it must not be supposed that Epicureanism exercised a feeble influence over the thought of cultivated Romans in this period of their history. The very theme which engaged the genius of Lucretius had also employed the energies of predecessors and contemporaries. Among attempts of this character were the De Rerum Natura of Egnatius, which appeared somewhat earlier than the work of Lucretius ; the Empedoclea of Sallustius mentioned by Cicero in the much dis- cussed passage relating to Lucretius; and a metrical production en- titled De Rerum Natura by Varro.* Commentaries on the principles of Epicureanism had also been extant for some time. Chief among the authors of such compositions was Amafinius who preceded Lucretius by nearly a century. Our knowledge of him is mainly derived from Cicero, who says : C Amafijiius exstitit dicens cuius libris editis commota multitudo contulit se ad eain potissimum disciplinam} Rabirius is also mentioned by the same author as belonging to that class of writers, Qui nulla arte adhibita de rebus ante oculos positis vol- * Dc Finilnts, I, i. ^ Quaercnti mihi vmltumquc d diu cogitanti, quanotii re possem prodesse qtiam plu- rimus, ne quando intervdtterem considere reipubiicae, nulla niaior occurrebat^ quam si optimaruni artiwn vias traderevi vicis civibus; quod conpluribus iam libris me arbitror conseciiturn. . . . Quod enim munus rei publicac adferrc mains nieliusve pos- s tonus , quam si docemus at que erudimus iuveiitutem^ his praesertim in or i bus at que iemporibus, qtdbus ita prolapsa est, etc. II, I, 2. ^ De Divinatione, II, 2. ^ Sellar, Roman Poets of the Republic, p. 278. ^ Acad. I, 2, 5. INTRODUCTION. 9 gari sermone disputant.^ Rabirius indulged in a popular treatment of philosophy and covered much the same ground as Amafinius. Another contributor to the literature of Epicureanism whom Cicero records in no complimentary way is Catius — Catius insuber, Epicur- eus, quinuper est vioriuus, quae ille Gargettius et iam ante Democritus ctSuXa, hie spectra nominat. ^ The interest in this school of philosophy among Romans of the time of Lucretius is further apparent in the prominence which cer- tain Epicurean teachers attained. Conspicuous among them is Zeno the Sidonian, whose lectures Cicero in company with Atticus had at- tended on the occasion of his first visit to Athens, 79 to 78 B.C., whom he calls the prince of Epicureans in his De Natura Deorum,'^ and wliose instruction is doubtless liberally embodied in Cicero's discussions of the system of Epicureanism.* Contemporary with Zeno was Phaedrus/ who had achieved distinction in Athens and Rome, in both of which places Cicero studied under his direction. Somewhat later Philodemus^ of Gadara appeared in Rome, and is mentioned by Cicero as a learned and amiable man. The consider- able body of writings bearing his name found in the Volumina Her- culanensia'^ indicates his position among the philosophic instructors of his day. Scyro * a follower of Phaedrus, said to have been the teacher of Vergil ; Patro * the successor of Phaedrus, who taught in Athens; and Pompilius Andronicus,^" the grammarian who gave up his j)rofession for the tenets of Epicurus, were eminent also at this period. Partly as a result of the activity of these teachers of philosophy, and partly on account of the prevailing anxiety to arrive at some satis- factory scheme of life, the number of disciples of Epicurus steadily increased at this time, and included not a few illustrious names. »7>/j6. Disp., IV, 6. ■'Ad Fam.. XV, 16, 2. ^I. 21. Cf. Diogenes Laertius. X, 25. * Rilter et Preller, Hist. Phil. Graec, 447. a. -^Ad Fam., XIII, i. ^De Fin., II, 35, 119. • Ritter et Preller, Hist. Phil. Graec, 447, a. ^Ad. Fam., VI. ii. ^Ad. Fam., XIII, i. Ad Attic, V, 11. ^•^Zeller. Stoics. Fpicnreans and Sceptics, p. 414, i. lO CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. These are known to us chiefly through the writings of Cicero/ who mentions T. Albutius, Velleius, C. Cassius, the well-known conspirator against Caesar, who may himself be classed among those who had lost confidence in the gods/ C. Vibius Pansa, Galbus, L. Piso, the patron of Philodemus, and L. Manlius Torquatus. Other notable personages are apparently regarded as Epicureans by Cicero, but grave doubts have been expressed concerning their real attitude toward the school. It is barely possible that Atticus may justly be denominated an Epicurean, for he calls the followers of Epicurus nostri familiar es^ and condiscipuli.* But his eclectic spirit would seem to forbid his classification with any single system, and Zeller^ feels that neither he nor Asclepiades of Bithynia, a contemporary of Lucretius, who resided at Rome and was associated with Epicureans, can be regarded as genuine disciples of Epicurus. The discussions of the Epicurean philosophy in De Natura Deorwn, De Finibus and other works of Cicero evince the profound interest he had in the school, though his general attitude was one of unfriendli- ness. What reason, then, we may ask, can be given for his almost uninterrupted silence concerning Lucretius } The only reference we have to the poet in all Cicero's voluminous compositions occurs in a letter to his brother Quintus,* four months after the death of Lucretius, in which he says, Lucretii poemata, ut scribis ita sunt: viultis lunmiibus ingenii, viultae etiam artis; sed cum veneris virum te putabo, si Sallustii Empedoclea legeris, hominem non putabo. These words certainly imply that both Marcus and Quintus had read the poem, and many scholars accept the statement of Jerome in his additions to the Eusebian chronicle — quos Cicero emendavit — as applying to Marcus.' But if he was closely enough identified with the work of Lucretius to edit his manuscript, why in those writings wherein ample opportunity was af- forded, did not Cicero mention his labors in the field of philosophy .? ^ Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, p. 414, 3. ■^Merivale, Hist. Rom., II, pp. 352, 3. ^De Fin., V, i, 3. ^Legg., I, 7» 21. '^Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, p. 415. ^Ad Quint ton, II, II. ^ Munro (II, pp. 2-5) who discusses this question with his usual lucidity, inclines to the opinion that Jerome, following Suetonius, has indicated M. T. Cicero as the INTRODUCTION. I I This is a particularly pertinent inquiry in view of the fact that he does speak of Amafinius, Rabirius and Catius, as we have already observed, and that he devoted so much attention to the discussion of Epicur- ean principles. Munro answers this question by declaring that it was not Cicero's custom to quote from contemporaries, numerous as his citations are from the older poets and himself; that had he written on poetry as he did of philosophy and oratory, Lucretius would have undoubtedly occupied a prominent place in the work, and that more than once in his philosophical discussions Cicero unquestionably re- fers to Lucretius.^ Munro is not alone in contending that the liter- ary relations between Lucretius and Cicero were more or less intimate. Other critics have traced to Cicero's Aratea important lines in Lucretius, while many passages in Cicero closely resemble utterances of the poet. Martha quotes several remarkable parallels between De Finibus and various lines in Lucretius.^ But it is argued on the other hand no less vigorously that didactic resemblances prove nothing, ex- cept that Lucretius and Cicero wrought from like sources their several Latinizations of Greek philosophy. And herein there is suggested a possible explanation of Cicero's ap- parent indifference to the poet, whether he did him the favor of edit- ing his verse or not. Cicero had made an earnest study of Greek philosophy long before the poem of Lucretius had been introduced to his notice. He had resorted to original authorities for informa- tion concerning Epicureanism. Zeno the Sidonian and Philodemus of Gadara, as already noted, had supplied him with much material. Everywhere in his philosophical works there is evidence that he re- garded himself a sort of pioneer in this peculiar field of investigation. editor of Lucretius, and that this was the real fact. Sellar, Roman Poets of the Republic, pp. 284-6, though suspending judgment does not deny the probability that M. T. Cicero performed this favor for Lucretius. Teuffel, Hist. Rom. Lit., I, 201, 2, while expressing doubt concerning the evidence of Cicero's connection with the poem, declares that at any rate his " part was not very important, and it might almost seem that he was afraid of publishing a work of this kind." Prof. E. G. Sihler, N. Y. University, presents an argument of great force against the prob- ability of Cicero's editorship. See Art. Lucretius and Cicero. Transactions Amer- ican Philological Association^ Vol. XXVIII, 1897. 1 Munro, II. pp. 4, 5. ^ M. Constant Martha, La: L^oeme de Lucrece, quoted in Lee's Lucretius, p. xiv, I. 12 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. and therefore deserving of the pre-eminence therein. He d()u])tlcss placed no importance upon any Latin writings beside his own which treated of this class of Greek culture. Indeed the references which he has made to persons engaged in an undertaking similar to his own are in no instance flattering. And Lucretius would only be esteemed by him a competitor in the same department of inquiry, who wrote in Latin verse instead of Latin prose. Keeping these facts in mind the comparative silence of Cicero re- garding Lucretius does not seem wholly incompatible with the theory of his editorship. He was himself an expositor of Epicurus — and that too of the hostile kind. He had " popularized the Epicurean doctrines in the bad sense of the word," and had thrown "a ludicrous color over many things which disappear when they are more seriously regarded. " ^ Yet his opposition to the tenets of Epicurus would not preclude him from friendly association with many who professed them, and if asked to lend his name to the publication of Lucretius' verses, there could be no reason for withholding it. But if his antagonism to Epicureanism would lead him to speak against the doctrines of the poem, his admiration for the literary excellences of the work, as exhibited in his willingness to stand sponsor for its issue, would deter him from adverse criticism. Silence in such a case is the best evidence of friendship. Mommsen ^ remarks that "Lucretius, although his poetical vigor as well as his art was admired by his cultivated contemporaries, yet remained — of late growth as he was — a master without scholars." But with increasing knowledge in what is best in Epicurus and a finer taste to appreciate the moral and literary virtues of Lucretius, subsequent generations gave ample recognition to the poet. Horace and Vergil were greatly influenced by him, particularly the latter, who is supposed to refer to Lucretius in the famous lines : Felix qui potuii rerum cognoscere causas\ Atque metus omnes et inexorabile fatum. Subiecit pedihus strepitumque Achernntis avari.'^ 1 Lanjje, History of Materialism. I. p. 127 (Eng. Tr.). =* Hist. Rome, IV, p. 699. ^ Georgica, II. 490 2. INTRODUCTION. I 3 Ovid pronounced words of high eulogy upon him : Carmina sublimis tunc sunt peritura Lucre tt Exitio terras cum dabit una dies. ^ The persistency of the Epicurean school of philosophy despite perse- cution and opposition down to the fourth century A. D. demon- strates its marvelous vitality and the almost deathless influence of the personality of Epicurus, whose single mind projected its grasp upon human thought throughout the whole existence of the sect. And not the least important agent in affecting this result, because of his almost idolatrous devotion to his master and the persuasive charm of his lines, was the poet Lucretius. A Preliminary Question. Before entering specifically upon an examination of the contro- versial elements in Lucretius, it will be important to inquire to what extent, if at all, the poet may be regarded an independent worker in the field he has chosen. One is impressed from the very beginning of his study of Lucretius with his profound moral earnestness. He is impelled by an absorbing passion to emancipate the human spirit from the terrors induced by the fear of death and the tyranny of super- stition The constantly recurring application of his doctrines to the soul of the convert he hopes to make leads him into frequent rep- etitions of his constant aim, and should dissuade the student of Lucretius from attaching too much significance to his iterations else- where. In the scheme of the poem Epicurus is the savior of man- kind, and Lucretius is his prophet. His entire energy seems to be devoted to the effort to render intelligible the process of Epicurean- ism in delivering men from irrational terrors. It is pertinent, there- fore, to inquire whether it is probable that a man of such missionary zeal, who is consumed with a desire to propagate the theories of his master, would go out of his way to study other systems of philosophy. Is it not natural to infer from our knowledge of his characteristics that his acquaintance with rival schools of thought would be mainly, if not exclusively, derived from a perusal of Epicurus, and that he would deal with them from the traditional Epicurean point of view } ' Amor.. I. 15. 2' 14 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. In short are there any evidences that Lucretius engaged in independ- ent research, when he undertook his exposition of philosophic doctrines ? Scholars have arrayed themselves in extreme positions on this question. Woltyer ^ of Groningen represents one leading view, and maintains that Lucretius gave himself utterly to the Latinization of Epicurus. In support of this theory there are undeniably strong declarations in the poem. The exordia of Books III, V, VI, furnish ample marks of the almost slavish devotion of Lucretius to his master, and the whole poem breathes the same spirit. He professes only to imitate the peerless Epicurus : E tenebris iantis tam clarum extollere lumen Qui primus potuisti inlustrans commoda vitae, Te sequor, o Graiae gentis decus, inque tiiis nunc Ficta pedum pono pressis vestigia signis, Non ita certandi cupidus quam propter amorem Quod te imitari aveo."^ He sees in him the highest human intelligence : Qui genus humanum ingenio super avit et omnis Restincxit, stellas exortus ut aetherius sol. ^ His glory can never fade : Cuius et extincti propter divina reperta Divolgata veius iam ad caelum gloria fertur.^ No honor can be too great for such a man : Nam si, ut ipsa petit maiestas cognita rerum, Dicendum est, deus ille/uit, deus, inclyte Memmi.^ Hence Lucretius will follow him explicitly : Cuius ego ingressus vestigia dum rationes Persequor ac doceo dictis, quo quaeque creata Foedere sint^ ^Lucretii philosophia cum fontibus comparata, Groningae, 1897. -' in, 1-5. -^ III, 1043, 4. * VI. 7. 8. ^ V, 7, 8. •'V, 55-7. INTRODUCTION. 1 5 It is apparent from the whole tenor of his production that Lucretius makes no claim to originality, his frequently avowed purpose being to disclose the method of Epicurus for the redemption of the race. Moreover such a procedure is in perfect accord with the conven- tional usages of the Epicurean school, among the disciples of which there was mere dogmatic iteration of the original propositions of Ep- icurus. The Kvpiai 8pa.^ A survey of this presentation of the Epicurean doctrines on the facts of nature reveals a feeling that Wiog. Laer., X, 139-154. •^Ib., 12, 35, 83. 85. 116. V/i., 16. ♦ Zeller, Epicureans^ Stoics and Sceptics, p. 418. 2. ^Ritter et Preller, Hist. Phil. Graec. 422-26, **Diog. Lat-r.. X. 84. sqq. 1 6 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. exact scientific knowledge is both impracticable and unnecessary. In a g-iven case a variety of reasons may be offered in explanation, and the student is at liberty to take his preference.^ Without an earnest purpose to study the facts of nature until they disclose the one and only interpretation for each phenomenon, there can be no real progress in science. The instances are not wanting in which a little deeper penetration into these facts of the universe on the part of Lucretius would have announced to the world in his day discoveries which were reserved to a much later period of time. So convinced are some critics that Lucretius made no advance upon Epicurus, but contented himself with a servile Latinization of his Greek master's productions, that they even assert he obtained his account of the plague at Athens from Epicurus and not from Thu- cydides. But from this extreme statement there seems to be reason for dissent. Would Epicurus, who was himself an Athenian resident, living but a hundred years after Thucydides, misunderstand the historian as Lucretius gives evidence of doing ? A comparison of Thucydides II, 47-54 with Lucretius VI, 1 138-1286, will show sev- eral instances in which the poet has either wilfully or ignorantly mis- represented his model. For example observe the difference between this declaration of Thucydides — twv 7c dKpwTHpiwv dvT(\ti>|/is avrov liria-f][i.aiv€' KaWo-KirirTC -Yap Is alSota Kal €s aKpas x<^P°-^ '^°-^ ir68as, Kal iroXXol o-Tcpko-Koixevoi TovTwv 8i€()>v-Yov, elo-l 8* ot KOLi T«v 6(|>6aXp,wv~ — and the verses of Lucretius on the same matter : tamen in nervos huic morbus el artus Ibat et in partis genitalis corporis ipsas. Et graviter partim metuentes limina leti Vivebant ferro privali parte virili, Et nianibus sine nonnulli pedibusque manebant In vita tamen et perdebant lumina partim : Usque adeo mortis mortus his incesserat acer. ^ In view of the intense desire of Lucretius to turn to account every opportunity to point a moral, is it not possible that he purposely ^ Compare the statements of Epicurus recorded by Diogenes Laertius, X, 91-115, witli Lucretius VI. Cf. E. G. Sihler, Transactions Am. Phil. Ass., 1898. Wc- Bfllfl Pi'lopomh'siaco. II. 40. 7. 8. Cf. Munro. II. jip. 301-401. •^ VI. 1206 12. INTRODUCTION. IJ perverted this passage from Thucydides in order to reinforce his position? The misery of the plague-stricken victims was such that suicide would seem to be reasonable and desirable ; b\it fear of death — that ever- present terror of men's lives — withheld them from this and induced them to deprive themselves of certain diseased members that life might be prolonged. There is another extreme view regarding the question under dis- cussion, which is represented by those scholars who maintain that Lucretius was a man of great independent research. These men light uncritically upon any point of doctrinal identity, particularly in Book VI, and forthwith are eager to ascribe original investigation to Lucretius.' There can be no doubt also that "he was endowed not only with the poet's susceptibility to the movement and beauty of the outside world, but also with the observing faculty and curiosity of a naturalist ; " "^ but it must be ever kept in mind that distinctive Ep- icureanism does not consist of the study of the minutiae of physical facts for the purpose of presenting a well articulated system of natural philosophy, but is practically the metaphysical employment of ob- served phenomena to demonstrate the folly of fearing the gods or death. It is necessary always to differentiate the -yvifjo-ios <()viXiav T€ ^ (riryKpCvcrai, Kal vciKos J 8iaKp(v€Tai. «^T^v»o-6«s of the latter as in some sense his poetic model. ^ The genius of Empedocles was celebrated by Aristotle, and may well have influenced the character of Lucretius' composition. *Ev 8c tcJ ircpl irotTjTav ^ryrKv, oti Kdi 'O^iipiKos 6 'EjiireSoKXfis, KOLi 8€iv^ irepl ttiv <{>pdoriv "y^-yove, |JLCTa4>opiK6s tc «v, koLi tois dXXois tois ircpl iroiT^TiKTiv liriTcv-yiJiao-i xp^^H-^vos.* In view of the fact that critics have been able to designate verses in both authors which bear a distinct Homeric ^ flavor, we may infer, perhaps, that the influence of Empedocles upon Lucretius was even more subtle than the latter ^Diog. Laer., VIII, 76. 2 1, 726-33. ^ Munro, II, p. 90. Cf. Il>., p. 32. *Diog. Laer., VIII, 57. = Sellar, Roman Poets of the Republic, p. 302, EMPEDOCLES. 23 was himself aware. But the traces of a more direct influence are abundant. The first fundamental principle, which Lucretius estab- lishes at the outset of his argument, is that nothing can be created from nothing by divine agency ; and the second is like unto it, that nothing already in existence can ever be annihilated. But the very content and form of these propositions reflect the doctrine of Empedocles. Nullam rtm e nilo gigni divinitus unquam, was evidently suggested by the lines of the older poem ircpl <|)vv(r€(i>$, both in literary style and in philosophic material. There exists, for example, a similarity of grammatical and rhetorical forms in these productions which is worthy of remark. Both poets are also given to an almost excessive use of iteration, Lucretius in particular being prone to this habit. Again, both freely employ tmesis, another indication, perhaps, of the influence of the Homeric verse upon Empedocles who studied it. Then, too, there are palpable imitations of the elder poet in the phraseology of Lucretius. Compare the following lines : avrdp l^u iroXivopcos IXcvo-Ofiai 4s iropov vp.va)v.^ Sed nunc ut repetam coeptum pertexere dictis. ^ ^ Emped., 48. 49, Sellar, Roman Poets of the Republic, p. 300. n, 159-328. '^ Lucreti Carmina e Fragrnentis Empedoclis Adumbrata, Jena, 1857, (A doctor's dissertation). * Emped., 169, Hallier. p. 13. '"> Lun-ef.. I, 418. 24 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. •yt-yvovT* avOpwiroC t€ Kal aXXwv cOvca Oriptav.^ Et genus humanum, parit omnia saecla ferarum^ Again, there are instances of the employment of identical similes by both poets : . . . Y% tSpttra OdXeuro'av.' expressus salsus de corpore sudor. ^ Munro ^ has pointed out that the lines — Nee tamen hanc possis oculorum subdere visu Nee iacere indu manus, via qua munita fidei Proxima fert humanum in pectus templaque mentis — ® are translated from this passage of Empedocles : o^K (lo-Tiv ircXdo-ourO ' ovS ' o<)>6aXp,oiikt6v *T)|MT4pois i) Xp^va irCirrci.^ But the marks of doctrinal agreement in the works of these poet- philosophers are even more significant than resemblances of compos- ition. While Empedocles and Lucretius differ on many of the questions involved in their several discussions of the nature of things, there are not a few notable points of coincidence in their writings. They are of one mind touching the eternity of matter : <|>vo'is oiScvds l(rriv &irdvTv 6vi)T«v, 6v84 Ti$ 6vXo(Uvov OavdroLO tcXcvt^, . . . ^vwv 4k -yf^s dvaSvveu 'n(ri, irplv rhv t)Xiov mpiairXMOt^vai KaV irplv T)|&4pav Kal vvKxa SiaKpi6{)vai* Sid 8< o-viip^rpCav rfjs Kpd(r<«»S rhv rov &ppcvos Kal rov 0^Xco$ ircpUxctv X^yov* a{}|ca rd kv r^ Ycurrpl Tf\S IJlVJTpaS Ji^pTJ.'' Principio genus herbarum viridemque nitoreni Terra dedit circum collis camposque per omnis, Florida fulserunt viridanti prata colore, Arbor tsque datumst variis exinde per auras Crescendi magnum inmissis certamen habenis. Ut pluma atque pili primum saetaeque creantur Quadripedum membris et corpore pennipotentum. Sic nova tum tellus herbas virgultaque primum Sustulit, inde loci mortalia saecla creavit Multa modis multis varia ratione coorta. * Lightning is explained by both as the result of fire submerged in clouds : Kalroi rivis Xfyovciv ms Iv rots yk^wxv \:>(>{iyvTOx irvp* tovto 8' 'E|jLirc8oKX{^s (i4v <|>T](riv (tvai TO {(iircpiXap.pavdiicvov tmv tov ^iXCov dKrCvwv.^ Hac etiam fit uti de causa mobilis ille Devolet in terram liquidi calor aureus ignis, Semina quod nubes ipsas permulta necessust Ignis habere; etenim cum sunt umore sine ullo, Flammeus est plerumque colos et splendidus ollis. ^Emped., 157-9, HalUer, p. 31. '^Lucret., V, 753-5. ^Plac, V, 26. 4 Dox., 438, Ritteret Preller, 136. ^Lucret., V, 783-92. ^Aristotle, Meteor. TI, 9. p. 369. B. II. quoted by I[vT»v, ovSc Yf)s Kal 6aXdTTT)$, dXXd Kal X£6ci)v dircuriv IvScXcx^s iroXXd ^vfiara Kal XOwv Kal Xa, and Lucretius has adopted the same method of accounting for sense per- ceptions, devoting a large proportion of Book IV to the considera- tion of what he denominates simulacra. Sellar* has called attention to the fact that the principle of beauty and life in the universe figures in the verses of both writers under the symbol of the goddess of love— Empedocles employing the form Kvirpi Boo-CXcta ; Lucretius, alma Venus, genetrix. Zeller draws an interesting parallel between the primitive substances of Empedocles (which are subject to no qualitative changes, and combine only through the entrance of the particles of one body into the intervals between the parts of another) and the Atoms and Void of the Democritean system.* Perhaps a similar comparison between the Empedoclean doctrine of Love and Hate and the atomistic theory of the eternal conflict and conjunction would be equally justifiable. rd |i€v (rwp,ariKd o-toix«i«- irout Wrrapa, irvp Kal d4pa Kal vSwp Kal ^f^v, di8ia )uv ^vra irX^Oci Kal oXi^drtiTi, (uraPdXXovra S« Kara tt]v Kry)>{K^\.fr\.v Kal Sidxpuriv, rds $€ KvpCcos dpxdsi v<|> ' wv Kivcirai ravra, <^kXCav Kal vckKos. 8ov Kal ^apcos olov Ava^a-yopas KarE|iire8oK\fis.-^ Hut Empedocles is himself equally plain: 1 II. 1002-4. Cf. TI. 560-80. -'1. 742-45- '/X- Caelo, TV. 2, 300. // i<). Ritter et I'lvllrr. 132 f. EMPEDOCLES. 29 oiSi Ti Tov iravT^ kcvc^v ir^Xci ov8< ircpuro'6vJ This position Lucretius rightfully regards as incongruous. Indeed, as already indicated, the Empedoclean doctrine of primitive sub- stances and their method of combination leads logically and almost inevitably to something very much akin to the atomistic hypothesis. For atoms minute particles of matter are substituted, and for void we have pores or interstices Combination is effected according to a certain elective affinity, like particles being attracted by like and dissimilar particles being mutually repellent. Notwithstanding the palpable resemblances thus exhibited, Empedocles rejects the funda- mental principles of the atomists, an inconsistency which Aristotle was quick to discover. (TXcSov 8c Kttl 'E|iirc8oKXci dvaYKaiov X^civ, «*viirp6ar(i)ira Kal dp.<|>iarTcpv' I4>vovto, ^u\k\.y^liva Ti] |i,€v dir ' dvSpwv, Txi 8c YV^<'^^Ko4>vii, OTTcipois f|arKT](icva •yviois.^ With this declaration of Empedocles may be compared a passage from Lucretius too lengthy for quotation in this place, but equally explicit on the same theory.^ But Lucretius condemns centaurs and other beings of a two-fold nature as impossible/ though Empedocles does not hesitate to affirm his credence in them : Pov-ycvTi dvSpoirpwpa, rd 8* cfiiroXiv 4|avCTc\Xov dv8po<|>ufi PovKpava.' Lucretius likewise dissents entirely from the doctrine that primary bodies worked teleologically, an idea which Empedocles embraces with enthusiasm, and the promulgation of which constitutes him ac- cording to Zeller "the earliest precursor of Darwin." * iQ iroXXal ficv Kopo-ai dvavxcvcs ^pXdo-rqarav, ^v^vol 8' cirXd^ovTO Ppax^ovcs cvvi8cs wfiwv, op-fiara 8 ' ol ' cirXavdro ir€VT]TCv)OVTa (iCTwircav. But Love — ^'A<|»po8iTT] — fashioned these together into comely and ap- propriate unions. avrdp ^ircl Kara (uttov cp-icrycro 8aCp.ovi 8aCfi,uv, ravrd tc (rvfiirCirTco-Kov oirr| (ruvcKvpo-cv iKCurra, dXXa TC irpos tois iroXXd 8it]vcki^ cIc-yevovTO.' ^Emped., 384, 85. Fairbanks, p. 206. Diog. Laer., VIII, 76. ^Emped., 257. 259, 260. Fairbanks, p. 19O. =^V. 837-54. ♦ IV, 878-924. Cf. Munro. II, pp. 328-9. '^Empt'd., 258. 59. Fairbanks, p. 190. ^Pi-e-Socratic Philosophy. II, p. 206. ''Emped.. 244-46, 254-56. Fairbanks, pp. 188-90. Cf. Munro, II, p. 326. 32 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. So Empedocles expresses himself, while Lucretius vehemently de- nounces the doctrine of final causes in a passage * which is directed, as we shall see hereafter, primarily against the Stoics. Faculties and functions were not created for predestined ends, but finding himself possessed of powers and appliances man uses them for his advantage. Nil ideo quoniam naiumst in corpore ut uti Possemus, sed quod natumst id procreat usum^ It was the habit of the Epicurean school to include Empedocles in the catalogue of philosophers to be derided and condemned, as Cicero and Plutarch testify,* but Lucretius commends the author as much as he combats him, and discloses in his lines an indebted- ness to Empedocles which he is not averse from paying. 2. Anaxagoras. Nunc et Anaxagorae scrutemur homoeomerian Quam Grai memorant nee nostra dicere lingua Concedit nobis patrii sermonis egestas, Sed iamen ipsam rem facilest exponere verbis.^ With these words Lucretius introduces a philosopher for whom he has a degree of personal esteem, and with whom the Epicurean school had some natural affiliation. The opinion which Epicurus held concerning Anaxagoras was singularly high. MdXio-ra 8' dircS^x^'^^^' ^l^l*^^ ^*'<^* rwv dpxaCttv 'Avola-y^pav, KaCroicv ruriv &VTCipi]K«l>S avTw.^ In addition to this evidence of his warm regard Epicurus, it has been conjectured, furnishes further proof in the freedom with which in his letter to Pythocles he employs the views of ' IV, 823-57. nv, 834-5- ^ Usener, Epicurea, pp. 175. 10 ; 187. 19. * I, 830-32. '^Diog. I^er., X, 12. AXAXAGORAS. 33 Anaxagoras in settini,^ forth a variety of explanations for remarkable physical phenomena. A comparison of the extant fragments of An- axagoras and the records of his opinions in other writings with cer- tain statements of Epicurus in the document referred to has led to this conviction. Attention has been especially directed by Usener ' to the causes assigned for the rising and setting of the sun, moon and stars ; the intertropical movement of the sun and moon ; the successive phases of the moon ; the apparition of a face in the orb of the moon ; the eclipses of the sun and moon ; and the phenom- ena of lightning, earthquakes and hail.- Moreover there is a general sense in which Anaxagoras occupies a common ground with Empedocles, Leucippus and Democntus.^ On the proposition of Parmenides that generation and destruction in the ordinary meaning of those terms are impossible Anaxagoras is in agreement with the Atomists and the Epicureans. With them also he proceeds upon the supposition that there are certain original and immutable substances, out of which were evolved all things by combination and separation in space. There is this fundamental dift'erence, however, between- Anaxagoras and the contemporaneous philosophers with whom he contended: The latter conceived prim- itive matter without the qualities of things in being. Empedocles names four elements distinct in quality. Democritus designates atoms unlimited in form and multitude and alike in quality as primordial matter. Anaxagoras, on the other hand, regards original and elementary substances as possessing all the qualities anti differ- ences of thmgs derived, and conceives them infinite in number and. kind, a theory which creates a radical divergence between himself and the Atomists. There is another position which separates Anaxagoras from the systems named. They explain motion, which is the cause of all combination, separation and order in the universe, by forces in- herent in matter; Empedocles by the mythical contrivance of Love and Hate, the Atomists by the force of gravity. But Anaxagoras asserts that motion must be attributed to the operation of immaterial '^Epicuvc'a. p. 400. -Diog. Liwr.. X. q2-()6. ioi, 105. 106. •'•Zeller. IW-Socra/ic Philosophy. II. p. 330. 34 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN Ll'CRETIUS. energy, and places Mind — vovs — in opposition to matter as the origin of motion and order. In support of the statement that Anaxagoras, like Epicurus, regard- ed generation and destruction as in reality only combination (o-v-yKpwris) and separation (Sidxpio-is), we have the affirmation of the philosopher himself: TO Sc yivea-dai Kttl dir6X.Xvo-0ai owk opOus vop.i^ovds CTc'pas d-Tr€8£i|€v. ' In a similar vein are the lines oi' Lucretius alread\- cited : Xec sic i7iteremit mors res ut material Corpora conficiat, sed coetum dissupai o//is, Inde aliis aliud coniungH. •^ ^Fr. 17 Schorn., Ritter et Preller, iiq. -Pre-Socratic Philosophy. II, p. 331. i. MI. p. 167. ^Phys., I. 4, 187 a, 26. in Ritter et Preller. 120 a. '""Piac. V. If), Dox. 430 a. in Ritter et Preller. IIQ l>. «II. 1002-4. ANAXAGORAS. 35 On the same grounds which enable him to declare against gen- eration and destruction, Anaxagoras asserts his belief in the unchangeableness of the sum of matter. TOVTwv Sc ovToi SiaK€Kpi)j.€vcov -yivcGo-Kciv XPT> '^'^*' "f^^vra ovdikv 4Xd(r iv Kal Gewv YCVCTup, f| 8' v-ypo^oXovs o-Ta'yovas votiovs irapa8c|a|jL€vT] TiKTti GvaTOvs, tCkt€i 8e ^opdv, <|>vXd t€ 6t]p»v oOcv ovK d8iKa)s p'flTT^p irdvTctfv vevopio-Tai. X,(i>p€i 8* oirio-w Td p€v Ik -yaias <|>vvT els "yaiav, Td 8' dir' aldcpCov pXao-TOvTa -yovtis els ovpdviov iroXov TJX9« irdXiv Ovrjo-Kci 8' ov8ev Twv -yi-yvopevwv, 8iaKpiv6pcvov 8 ' dXXo irpos dXXov p,op4>T)v l8Cav dir^Scilc/ 1 Fr. 14 in Ritter et Preller, ico. '■Dio^. Laer.. X. 39. ^W, 294-307. See p. 25. ^Eiiripidis Fras^rut'tita. IVai^mr Ed.. Paris. 1878. Cf. Munro. II. p. 166. 36 rON'IKOVKKSIAI. KI.F.MKNTS IX LICKKIIIS. The passacp6v ev6dSe o-vc^wpiicrtv €v0a vvv [ti'V^il'To 8c dpaiov Kal to Ocppiov Kal to |i]pov [Kal to Xa|iirp6v] 4|cxwpi^- (Tcv els TO irp6o-o) Tov alBcpos. ' Quippe rtenini primum terrai corpora quaeque, Propterea quod erant gravia et perplexa, coibant In medio atque imas capiebant omnia sedes. * ' II, 001-1004. -^ Munro 11. p. 166. •* Fr. 8. in Fairhunk's Finl IViilosoplu-rs of Cviurc. p. 242. CI". iMunro II. p. 306. *V,. 449-5 1. AXAXAGORAS, 11 The immediate occasion of conflict between Lucretius and An- axagoras is the doctrine of the homoeomeria (ojioionepeta) or the theory that the parts of a body are altogether similar to the whole, and that^these homeogeneous parts are original and elementary substances, infinite in number and variety.. The account of this doctrine which Lu'cretius gives is comparatively brief, but is fair in the main and sufficiently exact for his purpose: Principw, rerum quom dicii homoeomerian, Ossa videlicet e pauxillis atque viiiiidis Ossibus hie et de pauxillis atque viinutis Visceribus viscus gigni sa?iguenque creari Sanguifiis inter se inultis coeuntibu guttis Ex aurique putat micis consistere posse A u?'um et de terris terram concrescere parvis, Ignibus ex ignis, umorem umoribus esse. Cetera consimili fingit ratione putatque. '^ The argument which Lucretius makes against this doctrine will be considered after some examination of the actual teaching of Anaxagoras on this subject, as revealed in the most reliable extant sources of information. The word homoeomeria (ofioioncpcCa) does not appear in the frag- ments of Anaxagoras which have been preserved to us. Is there any ground for supposing that he ever employed the term.'* On this ques- tion scholars are divided. Lucretius plainly asserts that Anaxagoras uses the word. Plutarch affirms the same: — '0(ioio|ji€p€£as avrds IkoXco-c^ Sim})licius makes a like declaration: — "On 8c 'Ava^a-yopas €| cvos p.i-Yp.aT09 aireipa tw irX'^Oei 6p,oiop,cp{) diroKpCvcorOaC <|>T]T](ri (rv-yKpC- ^ Munro, II p. 98. ■^ Zeller, Pre-Socratic Philosophy^ II. pp. 334, 35. V^., p. 334. ANAXAGORAS. 39 T]v Kal Twv dXXcov (rireppkaroiv iravruvclvai -yAp CKdrcpov avrcov l| dopdrwv 6|ioio- op,ep»v irdvTftJv T|6poi€pov Kal -y-qs iroXXfis ^vcovo-qs Kal trirepjJLdTwv dTrcipwv irX-^Sovs ov8€v coikotcdv dW-^Xots . ov8€ -ydp T&V dXXwV Ov8£V €01K« TO '^TCpOV TtO lT€pw.'-' TOVTwv 8€ ovT«s Ix^^*^'*"* XP^ 8oK€iv Ivcivai TToXXd T€ Kttl iravTOia cv irdo-t Tois (TvyKpivoixe'vois Kal o-ir^p|xaTa irdvTwv \pr\ii.a.T(av Kal ISt'as TravToCas e'xovTa Kttl xpoi-^S Kal TjSovds.' The objections which Lucretius brings against Anaxagoras are characteristic. There is, of course, the fundamental difference between them at the very begmning, that the Epicureans posit one primitive matter, from which all things are derived by an in- finite variety of combinations, while Anaxagoras maintains an un- limited number of primordial. germs of every conceivable difference and quality. Out of this fundamental disagreement spring in the main the occasions of Lucretius' hostility. The first count 'in the indictment against Anaxagoras is that he does not recognize void in his calculations of the process of com- bination and separation. Aristotle bears witness on this point as follows: — ol p,€v ovv 8€iKvvvat TTCipdiJLCvoi OTi ovK '^o-Ttv (t6 k€v6v) ovx o jSovXovTai Xiy- €iv Ol dvOpwtrpi K€v6v, tovt c^eX^-yx^^*'"''^ °'^^' o-ixapTdvovTes Xc'-yovo-iv, cio-irep *Av- a^a-yopas Kal ol tovtov tov Tpoirov eXc-yxovTcs, l-rriSciKvvovo-i "ydp oti €o-ti ti 6 d^p -. 15, Fairbanks, pp. 242, 44. Cf. Zeller. Pre-Socratic Philosophy. II p. 341, 3. ANAXAGORAS. 4 1 Quare in utraque inihi par iter ratione videtur Err are aique illi, supra quos diximus ante. ^ Again, primordia of the character ascribed to them by Anaxagoras will be too feeble in the judgment of Lucretius to withstand the shocks of antagonistic influences, and will ultimately perish. Adde quod inhecilla nimis primordia fing it ; Si primordia sunt, simili quae praedita constant Natura atque ipsae res sunt aequeque laborani Et pereunt neque ab exitio res ulla refrenat. Nam quid in oppressu valido durabit eorum, Ut mortem effugiat, leti sub dentibus ipsis? Ignis an umor an aura? quid horump sanguen an ossaP Nil, ut opinor, ubi ex aequo res funditus omnis Tam mortalis erit quam quae manifesta videmus Ex oculis nostris aliqua vi victa perire. Such an obvious violation of the first principles of his philosophy cannot be tolerated by so earnest an Epicurean as Lucretius, who says: — At neque reccidere ad nilum res posse neque autem Crescere de nilo testor res ante probatas. '^ Moreover, the fact that Anaxagoras attributes secondary qualities to his primitive particles is enough in the estimation of Lucretius to condemn the whole system. In his second book he labors ingen- iously to demonstrate the impossibility that such qualities should belong to original matter. As these qualities are themselves de- structible, he believes that the atoms possessing them would necessar- ily be perishable also.^ Again, Epicurus and his school argued that the atoms, though indivisible, consist of parts inseparable and undistinguishable, which have existed in the atoms from eternity. These are called by Epi- curus IXdxwTToi and by Lucretius minima, 1 I, 845-6. 2 I, 847-58. 3 IL 730-865. 42 CONTROVERSAL ELEMENTS IN' LUCRETIUS. t6 t€ IXAxhttov to cv t^ alcrG'^o-ci Set Karavoeiv on ovt€ roiovr6v Icnv oiov to Tds (JL€Tapdo-€ts €X°*' o^T€ irdvT'j] irdvTws dv6pLOiov,d\X' €\ov ji^v Tiva Koivdrr^ra t«v (jLCTaPaTuv, 8id\T^\)/iv 8e \upS>v ovk €xov dW 8Tav 8id tt)v ttis KOtv6TT]TOS irpoo-e^i- <|>€p€iav olT)6o)p,cv 8ia\'q\{/€o-0a{ ti avTOv, to \uv ciriTdSc, to 8e lirCKCiva, to ta*ov t])jliv 8€i irpoo-irCiTTetv. k^r[s t€ de&>pov)i€v TavTa diro tov irpwTOv KaTapxo^cvoi Kal ovk Iv Tip avTw, ovSe p.€peo-i (icpuv. dirTdjicv", dW i] 4v t]] l8i6rr]Tt t^ tavr&v ra. (ic-y^Oi] KaTapt€TpowvTa, Td irXciw irXetov Kal Td IXdTTco e\aTTOv. TavT^ t-^ iivaXoyia vo\xi€p€i TOV KaTd TTjv a\:o-0ii6Tepa dtrEipa Idvra • Tavra -ydp n^-yiorTa €V€s tw iravrl Sid to 6p<^v OTiovv \% OTOvovv •yi'yvofJLtvcv • €VT€V06V ■ydp €OiK€ Kal ofiov iroT€ irdvra yj^-i\^fx.TtJk (}>dvai ctvai, olov -qSt tj o-dp^ Kal t68€ to ostovv Kal ovt«s otiovv • Kal irdvTa dpa. 1 I, 867-74. 2 I, 875-79. 2 Fr. I in Ritter et Preller. 120, 44 CONTROVERSAL ELEMENTS IX LUCRETIUS. Kttl &)JLa ToCwv • dpxT] -Yap ov |ji6vov kv CKdo-TO) la-r\ -ri^s 8iaKpC(rco>s, dXXd Kal irdvTwv K, T. X. ^ If, therefore, a thing seems to possess some single quality to the exclusion of others, it is simply because there is an excess of the substance indicated. The truth is that each thing has substances of every kind in it, but it derives its name from the predominating con- stituents, or as Munro puts it, "each individual thing is what it is by having in it the greatest number of 6|ioio|jL€pfi o-rotxcia." ^ Lucretius disposes of this theory quite summarily by answering that if it were true, corn, water, clods, wood etc., would when ana- lyzed reveal vestiges of blood, milk, fire etc. ; in other words when sufficiently divided they would exhibit traces of the substances fed to make them or produced from them. It is obvious that this is not the case, and we must conclude, decides Lucretius, that various things have certain elements in common. His antagonist, he conjectures, may offer as an illustration of the opposite view the fact that tree-tops frequently catch fire by rubbing together under the action of the wind. But this simply demonstrates what he has already asserted, that there are many seeds of things which trees and heat possess in common. If there were fully formed particles of fire in trees or anything else they might burst into flame at any moment. It is all a matter of the arrangement and order of the primordia whether they form one thing or another. Finally, Lucretius makes his favorite appeal to common sense, and closes his argument with a reducHo ad absurdum which he evidently believes is unanswerable: Denique iam quaecumque in rebus cernis apertis Si fieri mm posse putas, quin viateriai Corpora consimili natura praedita fingas, Hac ratione tibi pereunt primordia rerum: Fiet uti risu tremulo concussa cachinnent Et lacrimis salsis U7nectent ora genasque. ^ ^ Aristotle, Phys. Ill, 4, 203 a 23. Zeller Pre-Socratic Phil. II, 339, i. 2 II, p. lOI. 3 I, 915-20. ANAXAGORAS. 4 5 In the same vein are the verses of Lucretius in the second book (973-90), where he combats the idea that the atoms must be similar in quaHty to the whole, by showing that upon this supposition the atoms of men must be able to laugh and cry and moralize on their own constituent particles, and concludes, Quod si delira haec furiosaque cernimus esse Et rider e potest non ex ridentibti f actus Et sapere et doctis rationem reddere dictis Non ex seminibus sapientibus atque disertis, Qui minu's esse queant ea quae sentire videmus Seminibus per mixta carentibus undique sensup It has been remarked that there is a striking similarity between Lucretius' treatment of this portion of his argument against Anax- agoras, and the discussion on Empedocles in Book I, 803-29, both in language and matter. The reason for this is apparent. The par- ticles of Anaxagoras seem to Lucretius to be open to the same criticism as the four elements of Empedocles. Both possess those secondary qualities which are the concomitants of things derived.^ In order to avoid blind Chance and eternal Necessity, Anaxagoras assumes Mind (voOs) as the world-forming energy, an immaterial es- sence which is the cause of all motion and order in the universe. This places him inevitably in opposition to the Epicurean doctrine of the fortuitous concourse of atoms, but as this speculation does not figure as a point of actual contention in the poem of Lucretius, we may properly leave it without treatment here. 3. Democritus. It is natural to expect that Lucretius will treat Democritus with great gentleness and consideration on account of the unquestioned indebtedness of the Epicurean school to this philosopher. Epicurus can scarcely be said to have had any scientific attainments of his own, ^Munro, II, p. 102. 46 CONTROVERSAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. though he indulged in a superficial study of nature, and even ventured to publish the results of his investigations.^ It is none the less true, however, that he would have looked with contempt upon all scientific observation but for the practical advantages which such study af- forded him in his attempt to destroy the baneful influences of super- stition on the human mind.^ For any other purpose the labor in- volved would have been esteemed superfluous by him. Science, therefore, Epicurus held to be subsidiary to ethics. Let the searcher after truth take whatever explanation of physical phenomena he will — only in the name of reason and for the sake of human comfort let him not attribute them to the interference of divine hands — is the doctrine of Epicurus. Some general mechanical theory, however, is necessary to account for the world and its activities, in order to banish this delusion of the human race. Now, the atomic theory of Leucippus and Democritus best serves Epicurus in this regard, and he adopts it without making any contribution to it except in a single instance, which will be men- tioned hereafter. ' The dependence of Epicurus upon Democritus did not escape the keen scrutiny of Cicero, who says: Quid est in physicis Epicuri non a Democrito ? Nam etsi quaedam comviutauit ut quod paullo ante de in- clinatione atomorum dixi, tamen pleraque dicit eadem, atomos inane im- agines, infinitatem locorum innumerabilitatemque mundorum, eorum orius interitus, omnia fere quibus naturae ratio continetur.^ In physicis, quibus maxime gloriatur, primumi totus est alienus {Epicurus). Democritea dicit perpauca mutans, sed ita ut ea quae corrigere uolt, mihi quidem depruare uideatur . . . ita quae mutat ea corrumpit, quae sequiiur sunt tota Democriti . . . quae etsi mihi nullo probantur, tamen Democritum laudatum a ceteris ab hoc, qui eum unum secutus esset, 1 Thirty-seven books entitled ircpl <)>v(r€(i>s, mentioned by Diogenes Laertius, X, 27. 2 ct ^y\Vkv T)}ias al t«v |iET6(&p(i>v viro\|/Cai t|V(&x\ovv Kal at irtpl Oavdrov, fi^ irort irpos t)H>6i£ t) "^^i <^Ti Tc TO fiTj Karavoeiv tovs v(rioXoYCas. -Diog. Laer. X, 142, Usener, Epicurea, p. 74. ^ De Natura Deorum, I, 26, 72. DEMOCRITUS. 47 nollem uituperatum} . . Democritus, uir magnus in pn'mis, cuius fontibus Epicurus hortulos suos inrigauit. '^ In the same vein is the testimony of Plutarch:' Ati(jlokp(tov koXoL Kai irp^irovTa 8i8ai\oa-0(j>Cav 4l^*-^ Usener has pointed out many positive imitations of Democritus in the writings of Epicurus.^ Notwithstanding these palpable evidences of the heavy indebtedness of Epicurus, he was very slow to acknowl- edge that he was under obligation to any teacher. He loved to herald himself as untaught.® He refrained from praising even those from whom he had undoubtedly derived instruction. Cicero, refer- ring to the custom of Socrates to eulogize other philosophers, says: Decet hoc nescio qw) modo ilium, nee Epicuro, qui id reprehendil, as- sentior.'^ Diogenes Laertius also remarks: dXX' ovSc AcvKiirirdv riva -ye-yevficrOaC (jtTjo'i <{>iX6o-0(j>ov,ovT€ avros o{;T€''£jp|iapx- OS) ov €vi.o{ <}>curi Kal 'Airo\\(S8cDpos 6 'ETTiKOvpcios 8i8d(rKaXov ArKiOKpCrov "ycycv- fjo-eai .^ This fully justifies Cicero's accusation of ingratitude.' At the ^ame time Epicurus somewhat reluctantly gave an occasional ac- knowledgment of his association with the Democritean school. Ka( TOi iroXvv xpovov avros lauTov avTi-yopcve Ar||iOKpCT€iov 6 'EiriKOvpoSiWS aX- Xot T€ Xc'-yovo-i Kttl AeovTtvs, tls Tciiv €Tr' OLKpov 'EiriKOvpov p.a6i]Tc!)v^ TTpos Avk6- c|>pova 7pd4>(«)v Tip,d6apTovis. Mt^Bcv T€ Ik tov jjtti ovTOs "ytv€(r0ai, jiriSe els to [it] 5v 9€(p€^pc(r0ai 8' Iv tw b\a> 8ivovp.evas . Kal ovro) irdvTa rd o-vyKpCfiaTa "yevv^v, irvp, v8€p(ov o-yKcov o-vyKCKpio-6ai, Kal TTjv ^vxTjv o^oCcos* TjvKal vovv TavTov elvai. 'Op8cv irpoo-iovTwv • p.TfScvl •ydp liriPdXXttv p.T]8€T£pav xt^p'^S tov irpoo-iriirTOVTOS el8wXov. r/ac: IV, 8. Box. 395 in Hitter et Preller, 155. ^ Zeller, Pre-Socratic Philosophy^ II, pp. 265-72. ^ Cf. Dio^eHi'S Lcit-rtius X, 46-53, with Litcrctius. IV. 50 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. surface of all bodies infinitesimal particles are streaming every moment. These particles take the figure of the objects from which they proceed, and thus form images or idola of the things they leave. These emanations are spontaneously generated, they are in- cessantly streaming, they move with almost inconceivable rapidity, and should they cease at any time we should at once lose sight, smell and hearing. By reason of this perpetual evaporation of mat- ter a never-ending waste is going on, which explains the theory of Lucretius that the world is continually being fed with fresh matter from without. Moreover, on account of the porosity of matter, these simulacra constantly pass through them in all directions. Thus all bodies are to a greater or less degree interpenetrated with other matter. Somewhat more obscurely, but none the less truly, does Lucretius state the Empedoclean notion of pores differing from or resembling in shape the atoms which proceed by this streaming pro- cess from all bodies.^ To these emanations we are indebted for dreams, apparitions and many other strange phenomena. Our con- ceptions of the deities, for example, have their origin in these images. But while Democritus distrusts the evidences of the senses, Lu- cretius, as we have already seen, maintains the absolute correctness of the presentations of these organs of perception. If misconceptions are formed from the testimony of the senses, it must be the mind which errs in the inferences made.^ There is a striking similarity in the views expressed by Lucretius and Democritus on the question of the summum bonum, although there is an unimpoVtant difference in the terms employed. TeXos 8« €lvai ttiv cvOvfiCav, oil tt]v avt^v odo-av r^ t)8ovtj, 6Pov, r\ 8eiori8a(.)JkOv(as, r] dWov tivos irdOovs. KaXci 8* avrriv Kal €v- fO-To), Kttl iroWots dWois 6v6|ia(ri. ^ If we compare this declaration with all that has been preserved as the doctrine of Epicurus upon the same subject, we shall find that the difference between the two is virtually nothing. In the recorded sayings of Epicurus there is surely as refined a conception of the * Masson, Atomic Theory of Lucretius, p. 46. ''■Lucretius, IV, 379-86. '^Dio.genes LMerfius, IX, 45. DEMOCRITUS. 5 1 meaning and function of pleasure as has been anywhere expressed by Democritus so far as our knowledge of his sentiments enables us to judge. ^ Lucretius, who follows Epicurus faithfully here as elsewhere, ex- presses himself with equal dignity and forcefulness: O miseras hominum mentes, O pectora caeca ! Qualibus in tenebris vitae quantisque periclis Degitur hoc aevt quodcumquest ! nonne videre Nil aliud sibi naturam latrare, nisi ut qui Cor pore seiunctus dolor absit, mente fruatur lucundo sensu cur a semota metuque? Ergo corpoream ad naturam pauca videmus Esse opus omnino, quae demant cumque dolorem. Delicias quoque uti multas substernere possint Gratius interdum, neque natura ipsa requirit, Si non aurea sunt iuvenum simulacra per aedes Lampadas igniferas manibus retinentia dextris, Lu7nina nocturnis epulis ut suppeditentur , Nee domus argento fulget auroque renidet Nee citharae reboant laqueata aurataque tecta, Cum tamen inter se prostrati in gr amine mo Hi Propter aquae rivum sub ramis arboris altae Non magnis opibus iucunde corpora curant, Praesertim cum tempestas adridet et anni Tempora conspergunt viridantis Jloribus herbas. Nee calidae cititis decedunt corpore febres, Textilibus si in picturis ostroque rubenti lacteris, quam si in plebeia veste cubandum est. Quapropter quoniam nil nostro in corpore gazae Pruficiunt neque nobilitas nee gloria regni Quod super est, animo quoque nil prodesse putandum.^ In this connection we may also note the similarity of attitude which Democritus and Lucretius take with reference to the passion of love. For sexual enjoyment they both have a certain contempt," ^Diogeftes Laertius, X. 1 28-132, 140. Usener. Epicurea^ pp. 62-64. 72. ' 11. ,14-39. 52 CONTROVERSAL ELEMENTS IX LUCRETIUS. which in Democritus amounts to positive hatred, because in the per- suit of such pleasure the man gives himself over to the degrading charm of the senses.^ The intense earnestness of Lucretius in deal- ing with this subject in the fourth book of his poem, seems almost like a commentary on the creed of Democritus in this regard. An illustration of the characteristic Epicurean method of account- ing for physical phenomena is afforded in the passage on earthquakes in the sixth book, where Lucretius, following his master, is in accord with Democritus in assigning these disturbances to a variety of causes. Epicurus, after specifying certain reasons for earthquakes, naivel}' Savs: kuI Kar aWovs Si trktiovs Tpdirous rds kiv^o-cis ravras Tfjs "yfis -yCveo-Gai . ^ We are indebted to Seneca for what Munro calls a better illustra- tion of Lucretius in this connection than the extant writings of Epi- curus himself provide, since the larger works of the latter, which Lucretius had no means of consulting, were available to Seneca, who says: J^em'amus nunc ad eos qui omnia ista quae rettuli in causa esse dix- erunt aut ex his plura. Demncritus plura putat. Ait enim motum ali- quando spiritu fieri, aliquando aqua, aliquando utroque. . . . 0?/i- nes is/as posse esse causas Epicurus ait pluresque alias temptat et alios qui aliquid unum ex istis esse adfirmaverunt corripit, etc. [Xat. Quaest. VI, 20.)^ Attention has already been called to the fact that palpable imitations of Democritus have been attributed to Epicurus. It has also been maintained that Lucretius made liberal use of the same authorit}'. The words ordo, positura, figurae, which appear in the same succession and with the same technical significance in I, 685 and II, 102 1, have been traced to Democritus, by whom their Greek equivalents were employed according to the testimony of two author- ities. Aristotle says: AT](jLOKpiTb> }i€v ovv Tpcis 8ia<|>opds €OiK€v olop.€vu> ctvai * TO jJL€v "yotp VirOKeifl€VOV o-w|ia TTjv vXt)v €v Kal TavTOv, 8ia<)>6p€iv Be r\ pv(r(itp o Io-ti o-xfipta, r\ Tpoirti & Io-ti 64o-is, 11 SiaOt-Y-g '6 iarri Td|ts . * 1 Zeller, Pre-Socratic P/iitosop/iy, II, p. 285. '^Diogenes Laeriius X, 105, 106. ^ Munro, II, p. 370. ^Metap/i., VIII, 2, p. 1042, b. ii. Munro, II, p. 87. DEMOCRITUS. 53 Simplicius, referring to the doctrines of Democritus, says : Tp€is 84 tlo-iv avrai pvc Kara Td|iv ovrcos «vcis ova(ri, t« Sc clvai riva ^apvrcpa llwOovficva rd K0V({>6T€pa {iir' avroiv v4>i^av6vT^p€(r6ai * xal ovto) Xe-yovo-iv ovroi Sokciv rd fxcv KoO()>a cl- vai rd %\ Pape'a . Simplicius in Ritter et Preller, 149 e. DEMOCRITUS. 55 Aeque ponderibus non acquis concita ferri. Haud igitur poterunt levioribus incidere umquam Ex super graviora neque ictus gignere per se Qui varient motus per quos natura gerat res. * In arguing the equal rapidity of the atoms through space and the consequent impossibility of atom overtaking atom in the eternal de- scent, and thus rendering generation and combination inconceivable without some variation of the downward sweep or the interference of the divine will, which he distinctly disavows, Lucretius follows Ep- icurus, who says : Kal y.y\v Kal lo-oraxcts dvaYKaiov rds drdfiovs elvai, Srav 8id rov kcvov ct(r<|>^p- a»v, orav -yt St| p,T]8ev diravrj^ avTOis * ovt€ rd p.iKpd [PpaSvrcpov] T«v jiry- dXwv, irdvTa iropov o-v)x.|JLeTpov exovra, orav |jlt]6€v fit^Sc CKcCvoi^ dvTiK6irrg .' To account for the collision of the atoms and the resultant com- bination .of matter and the formation of the worlds and their contents, Lucretius and Epicurus adopt an mgenious expedient. Corpora cum deorsum rectum per inane feruniur Ponderibus propriis, se incerto tempore fer me Incertisque locis spatio depellere paulum, Tantum quod mo men mutatufn dicer e possis. Quod nisi declinare solerent, omnia deorsum, Imbris uti guttae, caderent per inane pro/undum. Sec for et offensus natus nee plaga creata Principiis : ita nil umquam natura creasset.^ Lucretius seems to have realized how dangerous a thing it was to introduce this physical contrivance into his system, for he attempts to guard his readers from the error of supposing that the atoms can travel downward in oblique lines, as would be the case if the swerve were more than the slightest conceivable variation from the perpen- dicular. UI, 225-42. ''Diogeiws Laertius X, 61. This objection, it is asserted, was borrowed from Aristotle. Cf. Zeller, Stoics. Epicureans ami Sceptics, p. 445. 5. Masson Atomic Theory of Lucretius, p. 48. MI. 217 24. 56 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. Quare eiiam atque etiam paulum inclinare necessest Corpora; nee plus quam minimum, ne fifigere motus Obliquos videamur et id res vera refutet.. Namque hoc in promptu manifestumque esse videmus, Pondera, quantum in sest, non posse ohliqua meare, Ex supero cum praecipitant, quod cernere possis; Sed nil omnino recta regione viai Declinare quis est qui possit cernere seseP ' It also seems apparent from the phraseology employed that Lucre- tius conceived his atoms as swerving from their own inner impulse, the words se depellere especially pointing to this conclusion.'' The testimony of Cicero as a student of Epicureanism, though he ridicules the expedient, is valuable in this connection as to the belief of that school in the necessity of using the swerve to account for combination and generation, and also as to their faith in the inherent tendency of the atoms to diverge almost imperceptibly by their own impulse: Epicurus autem in quibus sequitur Democritum, non fere labilur . . . illae Epicuri propriae ruinae censet: enim eadem ilia indiuidua et solida corpora ferri deorsum suo ponder e ad lineam, hum: natural em esse om- nium corporum motum. Deinde ibidem homo acutus, cum illud occurreret, si omnia deorsus e regione f err entur et ut dixi ad lineam, nunquam fore ut atomus altera alteram posset attingere itaque . . attulit rem com- menticiam; declinare dixit atomum perpaullum, quo nihil posset Jieri min- us; ita effici conplexioiies et copulationes et adhaesiones atomorum inter se, ex quo efficeretur mundus omnesque partes mundi quaeque in eo essent. Quae cum res tola ficta sit pueriliter, tum ne efficit quidem, quod vult. Nam et ipsa declinatio ad libidine?n fingitur {ait eniju declinare aiomuju sine causa; quo nihil turpius physico, quam fieri quicqua?n sine causa dicer e), et ilium motum naturalem o??inium ponder um, ut ipse constituit, e regione inferiorem locum petentium sine causa eripuit atomis nee tamen id, cuius causa haec finxerat, assecutus est. Nam si omnes atomi declin- abunt, nullae umquam cohaerescent, sive aliae declinabunt, aliae suo nutu recte fer entur, primum erit hoc quasi provincias atomis dare, quae recte, » TI, 243-50. 2 Munn), II, p. 132. DEMOCRITIS. 57 quae oblique ferantur, deinde eadern ilia alomorum, in quo eiiani Democ- ritus haeret, turbulenia coficursio hunc mundi ornatum effi-cere non poterit. ' But not only does the doctrine of the swerve enable Lucretius to explain the contact of the atoms in space, but it also servesa far more important purpose. It affords a rational basis for the doctrine of free will, which the Epicureans maintained against the Stoics, the early Atomists and other schools of thought. If the atoms had no power to decline, neither would men, constructed by a fortuitous concourse of these atoms, have the ability to move at will. The power of dec- lination in the atoms corresponds to free action in animals and men, and according to Lucretius* the former is the cause of the latter. It has been conjectured that had not Lucretius required this theory to ex- plain the mystery of free will, he would have left his whirling atoms to take care of themselves, nor bothered his soul over the process of world formation. But the desire to avoid the doctrine of eternal ne- cessity or fate im{)elled him to invent this method of accounting for the freedom of the will.^ Here Lucretius again followed his master, Kpicurus, who — cum viderel, si atomi ferrentur in locum inferior em suopte pondere, nihil /ore in nostra potestate, quod esset earum motus cer- ttis et necessarius, invenit quo modo necessitatem effugeret, quod videlicet Democritum fugerat; ait atomuvi, cum pofidere et gravitate derecto deor- sus /'eratur, declinare paullulum.^ . . . Epicurus declinatione atomi vitari necessitatem fati putat. Itaque tertius quidam motus oritur ex- tra pondus et plagam, cum declinat atomus intervallo minimo — id appellat 4\dxio-Tov — ; quam declinationem sine causa fieri si minus verbis, re cog- itur confiteri. . . . Hanc Epicurus rationem induxit ob eam rem, quod veritus est ne si semper atomus gravitate ferretur naturali ac necessaria, nihil liberum nobis esset, cum ita moveretur aftimus, ut atomorum motu cog- eretur. Id Democritus auctor atomortim accipere maluit. necessitate omnia fieri, quam a corporibus individuis naturalis motus avellere. * Kpicurus doubtless did adopt the hypothesis of the declination or swerve — as Cicero declares — in tjrder to avoid the Democritean ' Cicero. De Finibus, I, 6, 18-20. ■^ Munro, II, p. 136. '•* Cicero, De Natura Drorum, 1, 25, 69. * Cicero, De Fato. 10, 22, 23. 58 CONTROVERSAL ELEMENTS IX LUCRETIl'S. doctrine of eternal necessity. He has emphatically denounced this teaching in his famous letter to Menaeceus, and despite his purpose to remove the gods from all participation in human affairs, he says: KpciTTOv r\v rta ir€pl Oewv (ivOto KaraKoXovOetv r\ rri rtav <|>v(riKci)v clfiap^cvg 8ov- \cveiv . ^ This conviction Lucretius seems to share. The adoption of the swerve is from the standpoint of Cicero a thoroughly absurd, if not dishonest, proceeding. He cannot admit that the conceit, is rational. Declinat, inquit, atomus. Prim urn cur? A Ham ekim quandam vim motus habebant a^ Democrito inpuhionis, quam plagam ille appellat, a te. Epicure, gravitatis et ponderis. Quae ergo nova causa in natura est qua dec line i atomus? Aut num sortiuntur ' inter se, quae declinet, quae non? Aut cur minimo declinent ititervallo, maiore non ? A ut'Cur declinetit uno minimo, non declinent duobus aut t rib us ? Optare hoc quidem est, non disputare. Nam neque extrinsecus inpulsam atomum loco moveri et declinare dicis, neque in illo inani, per quod fera- tur atotnus, quicquam fuisse causae, cur ea non e regione ferreiur, ncr in ipsa atomo mutationis aliquid factum est, quam ob rem naturalcni mo- tum sui ponder is non teneret. fta cum attulisset nuUim causa m, quae is- lam declinationem efficeret, tamen aliquid sibi dicerr vidctur, cum id dical quod ojnniiun mentes aspernentur ac respuant. '^ Nee . . . est causa cur Epicurus fatum extimescat et ab atomis petal praesiditim easque de via deducat et uno tempore suscipiat res duas inenodabiles, U7iam, ut sine causa fiat aliquid — ex quo existet ut de nihilo quippiam fiat . . . , alteram, ut cum duo individua per inanitalem ferantur, alterum e regione moveatur, alterum declinet.'' Of course in this asumption of the doctrine of free will Lucretius antagonizes the Stoics, of whom Plutarch says in this relation: 'EliriKovp({> (JLCv ^dp ov8' dKap€S l-yKXivai, tt)v aropiov crvyxupova-iv ( 01 StwikoI ) cl>S dvaiTiov lir€i(rd'yovTi KCvt]ao'i, ravTO, 8 aireipa Kal to ir\fi0os etvai Kal rds p.op()>ds, aira 8c -n-pos avrd 8ia<{>cp€iv TOVT013 «^ wv €lv Kal p.copttS €k twv avToiiv opais ov\ dirXws dircipoi dXXd jjlovov direpiirXirirTOi . * Lucretius adheres to his master in that he states; and argues that the number of atoms is finite, but he does not, like F4)icurus, admit that the number ^is incalculably great. He refrains from declaring whether it is small or large. But he adduces cogent reasons tor his belief. In order to haVe an infinite number of shapes of atoms, it would be necessary to have atoms infinite in magnitude. For sup- pose an atom has a limited number of least parts: their permutations will only give a limited number of shapes. To secure an infinite number of shapes, therefore, it would be necessary to keep adding parts to infinity, and thus we should eventually have atoms of infinite size, which has been demonstrated to be an impossibility. Again, were the shapes of atoms infinite in number, there would be no limit to the beauty of color and sound, or to that which is olTensivc. But * Zeller, Fre-Socratic Philosophy, II, p. 223. V/;., p. 224, I. MX, 44. ^Diogenes Laertius, X, 42. 64 CONTROVERSAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS, we know there is a limit to all this, as also to the heat and cold of the year, summer's heat and winter's cold being two points between which various degrees of temperature proceed in their order. ^ Lucretius mentions Democritus by name when he combats, as he feels compelled to do, this philosopher's theory of the formation of the soul; but, while he deprecates his doctrine, he alludes to its author in terms of compliment. Illud in his rebus nequaqiiam sumere possis, Democriti quod sancta viri sententia ponii, Corporis atque animi primordia singula privis Adposita alterriis variare, ac necitre memlra.''- To say that between every pair of atoms which compose the body there is a finer atom of the soul, is to Lucretius a wholly groundless statement. In his judgment the atoms of the body are many times as numerous as those of the soul, and therefore distributed at much wider intervals than Democritus supposed. Nayn cum viiiHo sunt animae elementa minora Quam quibus e corpus nobis ft viscera constant. Turn numero quoque coTicedunt et rara per artus Dissita sunt dumtaxat; ut hoc promittere possis, C'uatitula prima queant nobis iniecta ciere^ Corpora sensiferos 7?iotus in corpore, tanta Intervalla tenere exordia prima animai. Nam neque pulveris interdum sentimus adhaesum Corpore nee membris incussam sidere cretam, Nee nebulam noctu neque aranei tenvia fila Obvia sentimus, quando obretimur euntes. Nee supera caput eiusdem cecidisse vietam Vestem nee plumas avium papposque volantis Qui nimia levitate cadiuit plerumque gravatim, Nee repentis itum cuiusviscumque animantis Sentimus nee priva pedum vestigia quaeque, Corpore quae ifi nostro culices et cetera poitunt, 111,478-521. 2 III, 370-3. DEMOCRITUS. 6 5 Usque adeo prius est in nobis multa ciendum, Qua?n primordia sentiscant coficussa animai Semina corporibus nosiris inmixta per artus, Et quam in his intervallis tuditantia possint Concur sare coire et dissultare vicissim. * This point of difference between Epicurus and Democritus Munro declares we should never have known but /or this passage in Lucre- tius, for in many particulars the two were in accord on the question of the constitution of the soul as well as other subjects connected with the atomistic philosophy.^ On the origin of verbal designations, the teaching of Epicurus and Lucretius seems to have been at variance with the doctrine of Democritus. In his letter to Herodotus Epicurus says: TO, ovofxara c| o-PX'HS H-^ Oeo-ei 'Ycv€varcis twv dvOpMirwv Ka9' 'iKO.fna. e6vT] \!Sia irao-xovcras irdOr] Kal \!8ia Xa}iPavovavTd' tKdTTwv Toiv iraOwv Kal twv <}>avTa(rfidTa>v, d>s dv TTOTe Kal r\ irapd tovs tottovs twv IOvuv 8ia(|>opd rj • {'cTipov Si KOivdis KaO' ^k- aora (.%vr\ to. tSia TeSfivai irpos to rds 8r|\(0(r£is t^ttov d}i4>iP6Xovs -Ycvco-Gai dXX^- Xots Kal £tv Iv avrais dWois ts Kal Nau(ri4>dv€i [ra. irXcio-ra], Ka av»T|] Xc'^ei 4>d(rKEiv outcos 'AXX' 'inoa-av • il\i yap Ikcivos wSivwv tt]v aTro tov trro- (xaros Kavx.'HO'iv tt^v croa-Y6vTa ttjv irarpwav ovcrCav (rTpaT€ii£opfio(t>6pov re Xlpwra-yopav Kal 'Ypa<}>ea A-qfiiOKpiTOv Kal Iv K(iop,ais 'ypdp.jxara SiSdo-Kciv * 'HpdK- XeiTOV TC KVKTJTTJV * Kal Al^JlOKpiTOV ATJpOKpiTOV ' Kal 'AvTlSwpOV DavVlSwpOV • TOVS T6 KvviKOvs Ix^povs TTis 'EXXdSos' Kal TOVS SioXcKTiKovs 7roXv96pous' Ilvppctfva 8€ dfjiadf] Kal d'irai6€VT0v. ^ The most notable thing in this passage, of course, is the fact that even Democritus, to whom Epicurus was so much indebted, comes in for his share of obloquy. Cicero confirms in a large degree the reports preserved by Diogenes Laertius. Aa??i Phaedro nihil elegantiiis, nihil humaniiis; sed stomachabatur senex, si quid asperitis dixerani, ctan Epicurus Arislolelein vexarii co?i- lumeliosissiine, Phaedoni Socratico iurpissivie male dixc?it, JMelrodori, sodalis stti, fratrem, Pimocralen, quia nescio quid in philosophia dis- * Diogenes Laertius, X, 7, 8. HERACLITUS. 69 sentiret, totis voluminibus conciderii, in Democritum ipsum, quern secutus est, fuerit ingratus, Nausiphanen, magistrum suum, a quo {non) nihil di- dicerat, tarn male acceperit. ^ With such traditions before him and filled with an idolatrous ven- eration for his master, it is not strange that Lucretius exhibited some severity in the treatment of his controversial antagonists, albeit his language is mild compared with that of Epicurus. I. Heraclitus. Of the persons referred to by Lucretius in his poem, Heraclitus alone is severely denounced by name. It is interesting to note that this philosopher was himself abusive in his manner toward his com- petitors and contemporaries. Such honored names as Hesiod, Pyth- agoras. Xenophanes and Homer fell under the ban of his reprobation. )jL€-YaX6((>p(i>v %\ yiyovi irap* ovTivaovv, Kal vircp6irn]S' a)S Kal Ik tov a-vyypa\i.\i.m- ro$ avTov Sf^Xov, ev tJ 4>T)(ri,IIoXv(i.a6iT] voov ov 8i8d(rK€i. 'HcioSov 'ydp av 4Si8ok|c Kal nvOa-yop-qv, avOCs t€ ^«vopov 4ir- icurKCv a|iov 6K Twv d-ywvwv CK^dXXco-Oai Kal pairi^ccrOai, Kal 'ApxCXoxov ofioCws*^ At the same time, as has been pointed out by scholars, Heraclitus was influenced by some of the teachers whom he antagonized, nota- bly by Xenophanes, with whose views of the heavenly bodies he un- doubtedly sympathized.' The avowed reason for the animosity of Lucretius toward Herac- litus, as exhibited in the passage now to be considered, is that he is the leader of those philosophers who assert that fire is the original essence from which everything has been derived. The Epicurean physics is arrayed against all systems that ascribe primordial matter to one, two or any limited number of substances. This of itself would be sufficient to bring the condemnation of Lucretius down ^De Nat. Deor., I, 93. ^ Diogenes Laertiiis, IX, I. ' Ueberweg, Hisi. Phil., I, 39. 70 CONTROVERSAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. upon the head of Heraclitus. But when the element chosen to stand for all matter is fire, the whole Stoic school seems to be in- volved, and the virulence of the Epicurean poet is largely explained, as will become more apparent later by the deathless hostility existing between the "porch" and the ''garden." It is a truly Epicurean and natural temper which displays itself in the lines with which Lu- cretius begins the attack upon Heraclitus. Heraclitus mil quorum dux proelia primus, Clarus ob obscuram linguam magis inler inanis Quamde gravis inler Graios qui vera requirunl. Omnia enim slolidi magis admiranlur amanlque, Inversis quae sub verbis lalilantia cernunl, Veraque consliluunl quae belle langere possunt Auris el lepido quae sunt fucata sonar e.^ The taunt of obscurity contained in these lines originated as much from the reputation given Heraclitus by several writers of antiquity, as from any personal conviction which possessed Lucretius. The title 6 i6voxr\.v iv avr^J t«v jiiv iroXaiuv 'HpaKXcirds tc 6 s \i.{v rivts, liriTTj8«v^p6v« TjTov ctt). TOVTOv Sc Kttl 6 T£)i,(i)v viTO'Ypditxi, Xcyt^v. Tois 8' €vi K0KKVO-T1]? ox^oXoiSopos 'HpdicXctTOf aCviKTT)s dv6pov(rc.^ In the letter from Darius, the son of Hystaspes, to Heraclitus we have further evidence of the recondite character of the Ephesian phil- osopher's writings. T«v 8c irX«CorTo>v lirox^v exovra* &6ai irapd a>s IkPoXXji, wotc Kal tov vvAiv Barov p(;i8i(ds -yvuvai Kal 8iap(ta <)/v\iis XaP^iv i) ^pa^vTi^s Kal to ^dpos t{)s fp- )iT)v€Cas do-v-yKpiTov.^ ^ Diog. Laer., IX, 6. '^Ib., IX, 13. » Ritter et Preller, 2T,a * Diog. Laer., IX, 7. 72 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. He himself compared his gravity with the seriousness of oracles when correctly interpreted. 6 ava| (ov to piavTctdv Io-ti to) iv AcX4>ois oUrt \iyti oUrt KpvirTCi, dXXd aii\]t.aivu. o-CPvXXa Sc )j,aivop,^v(^ o-T6fiaTi d-yeXao-Ta Kal dKoXXwirio-Ta Kal d|xvpio-Ta <)>OiY- yo\iAvr\ \i\U»v iritav ^^iKv^Tai tq 4>a>v^ 8id tov 6c6v.' There are a few persons who doubtless will agree with Prof. Fer- rier that Heraclitus is "the deepest probably, if also the darkest, of all the thinkers of antiquity.^ The argument of Lucretius against Heraclitus betrays perhaps more clearly than any other controversial passage in his poem how difficult it is for him to argue from any standpoint except his own. His reasoning is neither as cogent nor as fair in this instance as in Some other portions of his work. Accepting his own premises and proceeding from his own point of view, his argument is weighty enough; but there are evidences of either a wilful attempt to mis- represent the opinions of Heraclitus, or a disposition to allow the prejudices of his school against the Stoics, with whom he identifies Heraclitus, to obscure the real teaching of the Kphesian. On the supposition that the fire out of which the universe is evolved accord- ing to Heraclitus is the same as the fire which he pictures to his own consciousness, Lucretius presents his objections in this order: 1. It is impossible to obtain such a variety of things from fire. 2. Condensation and rarefaction are insufficient to account for this variety, because they effect no qualitative change. 3. Heraclitus denies void in things, without which condensation and rarefaction are inconceivable. 4. When he declares that changes occur by the extinction of the fire he is at fault, for that would mean annihilation, and things would then need to be produced from nothing, which is contrary to the first principle of true philosophy. 5. To assert that fire is the only real existence, all other things being only apparent is to deny the infallibility of the senses, a funda- mental doctrine of Epicureanism.' ' Fr. II, 12, in Fairbanks, First Philosophers of Greece, p. 26. ^Masson, /^/<7ot;V Theory of Lucretius, p. 27, 3. » I, 645-764. HERACLITUS. IZ The question suggested by an examination of the argument thus outlined is: To what extent does Lucretius represent the actual posi- tion of Heraclitus? What, for example, is the precise significance of the fire which the latter employs to indicate primitive matter? That Heraclitus has adopted fire as the primordial sole element from which all things have been derived, is certified in the most unequivo- cal manner. Ik irvpos to, irAvra p* 'TrT]'Yvv}uvov Be TO v8(i)p, els •YT]v Tp€ir€o-6ai* Kal TavTtjv 686v cirl to KdTot civai. irdXiv tc avTr^v TTiv 'Y'nv xcio-6ai, k\ y\% to v8ci>p ■y^veo-Oai' Ik 8^ tovtov Td Xotird ar)(.686v irdvTa, lirl Tf]v dvaOv^iao-iv dvd-ywv ttjv diro ttjs OaXdTrrjs. avn] 8€ Io-tiv tj lirl to av« 686s. ^ But was the fire of Heraclitus that of Lucretius? The poet would have us think so, and the words of Cicero already cited seem to claim as much. Lucretius apparently has before his mind constantly the visible flame, the process of combustion, and other phenomena which appeal to the senses. But no student of the fragments of Her- aclitus can be persuaded that he was tied to any such narrow con- ceptions. Grote admits that the Lucretian interpretation is coun- tenanced by some striking passages from Heraclitus, but maintains that from the whole mass of his works, in as far as we possess them, "it appears that his main doctrine was not physical but metaphys- ical or ontological; that the want of general adequate terms induced him to clothe it in a multitude of symbolical illustrations, among which fire was only one, though the most prominent and significant." ^ The latter part of this sta;tement would seem to be scarcely accurate, since Heraclitus evidently regarded fire, not simply as one of several symbols which could serve as illustrations of his doctrine, but as the one inclusive symbol, which in a special sense answered the require- ments of ever-changing nature. With this modification Zeller would be in substantial harmony with Grote's view. The former says in ef- fect, that with the doctrine that all things are in constant flux as the 1 Diogenes Laertius, IX. 7, 8, 9. 'HpdKXeiTos <|>no-lv diravTa -ylvco-Oai. ttotc irvp. Aristotle, Fhys. Ill, 5, 205^, 3. Ritter et Preller, iga. 2 Grote, Plato, I, 27. 74 CONTROVERSAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. fundamental principle of his philosophy, fire seems to Heraclitus to be the living, moving element in nature. The foundation of this theory, lies in the fact that fire seems to the philosopher to be the sub- stance which least of all has a permanent consistency or allows it in another; and he consequently understands by his fire not merely flame, but warmth in general, for which reason he also designates it as vapor or breath — t|n>x^. His reason for adopting fire as the material of the universe was "in order to express the absolute life of nature, and to make the restless alternation of phenomena comprehensible. Fire is not to him an unvarying substance out of which things de- rived were compounded, but which in this union remains qualitat- ively unchanged, like the elements of Empedocles or the primitive substances of Anaxagoras; "it is the essence which ceaselessly passes into all elements, the universal nourishing matter which, in its eternal circulation, permeates all parts of the cosmos, assumes in each a different constitution, produces individual existences, and again resolves itself; and by its absolute motion causes the restless beating of the pulse of nature. ^ Heraclitus has left a statement which harmonizes with this phrase- ology, and serves to elucidate his meaning in the use of fire: TTupos &.vra\ui^rai iravra Kal irvp &irdvT»v, tSo-ircp xpvoroii xp^^ara Kal xp-p- ftdruv x^o-os . ^ Brandis, commenting upon this, as quoted by Munro,''' says that fire "is that for which all things are exchanged as wares for gold; but it changes itself as little into the things, as gold changes into these wares. ' But Zeller* puts a somewhat different construction on the pa.ssage when he says: " Herein he gives us to understand that the derived arises out of the primitive matter, not merely by com- bination and separation, but by transformation, by qualitative change; for in the barter of wares for gold, the substance does not remain, but only the worth of it." Another pertinent inquiry in this connection is this: Does Lucre- tius correctly represent Heraclitus in attributing to him the hypothesis 1 Zeller, Fre-Socratic Philosophy, II, 23. 2 Fr., 22, in Fairbanks, First Phil. Greece, p. 30. MI, 85. * Fre-Socratic Philosophy, II, 28. HERACLITUS. 75 of condensation and rarefaction to account for the derivation of things? There is undoubtedly on the surface of much that is cred- ited to Heraclitus an indication of this theory. The passage already quoted from Diogenes Laertius ' certainly bears this construction. Other testimony is equally direct and definite. 'HpdKXciTos . . . apX'lv ''''**' &X«v to irOp . . tovtov 8c Karoo-pcvvupivov KO(r)u>- iroicicOai TcL ircLvTa. irpwTwv p,€v ■ydp to iraxvixcp^o-TaTOv avTOv cts avTO o-uv(rc(i>s ti^S WoKCk|x4vT]s' irupos^dp d)ioiPT]v ctvat 4>T|o'iv 'HpdKXciTos irdvTa.^ But this interpretation of Heraclitus, which is made by later writers exclusively, is irreconcilable with the fundamental principle of his philosophy, which is that all things are in perpetual flux — there is nothing permanent. It is inevitable that when fire passes into moisture and thence into earth, condensation occurs, and when this process is reversed, rarefaction just as certainly takes place. But these are results, and not causes of a change of substance. The phraseology employed by Heraclitus is foreign to the notion of con- densation and rarefaction, and combination and separation of sub- stances. His terms are transmutation, kindling and extinguishing, life and death. Moreover, the idea of one immutable primitive sub- stance is utterly incongruous with the underlying principle of his philosophy. Though fire was in his view the essence from which all things .were evolved, it was not so in the sense in which Thales or Anaximenes made water or rain the original element. The early physicists regarded their elements as abiding without change in the midst of the constant mutations of things derived. The fire of Her- aclitus, on the other hand, is that element which by its perpetual transmutation efi"ects these changes.* But Lucretius contends that without void in matter, the existence ^ IX, 8, 9. '^Plutarch, Ptac, I, 3, 25, in Zeller, Pre-Socratic Philosophy, II. 28, 2. ^ Simplicius, Phys., 6r, 23, 33Z) in Ritter et Preller, 2gc. ♦Zeller, Pre-Soc. Phil., 11,28-30. 76 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. of which Heraclitus denies, there could be no such processes as rare- faction and condensation; and hence, even if they were sufficient to account for the variety in nature produced from fire as the sole orig- inal element, on his opponent's own theory, they are not to be con- sidered. Id quoque, si faciant admixtum rebus inane, Denseri poterunt ignes rarique relinqui. Sed quia multa sibi cernunt contraria nasci Et fugitant in rebus inane relinquere purum, Ardua dum metuunt, amittunt vera viai. Nee rursum cernunt exempto rebus inani Omnia denseri fierique ex omnibus unum Corpus, nil ab se quod pos sit mittere raptim; Aestifer ignis uti lumen iacit atque vapor em, Ut videas nan e stipatis partibus esse. ^ Again, bearing in mind the terminology of Heraclitus referred to above, which apparently involves the ideas of death and extinction, Lucretius fancies he has hit upon an argument calculated utterly to destroy his adversary, when he declares that the extinguishing of the primordial fire to produce the changes of nature would signify that things were constantly being produced out of nothing, which is con- trary to the first principle of rational philosophy. Quod si forte alia credunt ratione potesse Ignis in coetu stingui mutareque corpus. Scilicet ex nulla facer e id si parte reparcent, Occidet ad nilum nimirum funditus ardor Omnis et e nilo fient quaecumque creantur. * But when Heraclitus conceives of his fire as extinguished, it is cer- tainly not in the sense in which Lucretius fancies he does, for he plainly declares that his fire is never destroyed. The lightning flash passes away, but the essential warmth is still in existence. The sun goes down and darkness follows, but Helios is not quenched. The ' 1, 655-64. 2 1 665-69. HERACLITUS. 77 fire of Heraclitus "is not like sunlight, connected with a particular and therefore changing phenomenon, but is the universal essence, which is contained in all things as their substance."' The remarkable approach which Heraclitus thus makes to the nebular hypothesis of modern science imparts to his doctrines an exceedingly vital interest. An examination of the Heraclitean doctrine of the senses, sug- gested by the criticism of Lucretius, presents another difficulty of interpretation. Had Lucretius some better knowledge of the opinions of Heraclitus than we possess in order to enable him to make the assertions regarding his views contained in the following lines? is a problem propounded by Munro:'^ Dicer e porro igtiem res omnis esse neque ullam Rem veram in numero rerum constare nisi ignem. Quod facit hie idem, perdelirum esse vide fur. Xam contra sensus ab sensibus ipse repugnat Et labefactat eos iinde omnia credita pendent, Unde hie cognitus est ipsi quem nominat ignem; Credit enim sensus ignem cognoscere vere, Cetera non credit, quae nilo clara minus sunt} There can be no doubt that Heraclitus did distrust the senses. KaKol pidprvpcs dv9pwTroi9a\|iol Kal wra, pap^dpovs \|/vxds i\6vTiov^ T^v T€ otrio-tv, icpdv v6vTd tc Kal ^wa Kal rd aXXa 76VTJ . The' opposition of Lucretius to the doctrine of transmutation, con- tained in the passage under discussion, is that primordia cannot thus change, but must be distinct and unchangeable, otherwise they would be annihilated; for, according to his view, whenever a thing changes and deserts its own limitations, immediately the death of ' I, 698-700. 2 1, 782-802. ^ Munro, II, 95. ♦ Lucrefi Carmina e Fragmcntis Enipedoclis Adumbrata, p. 20. HERACLITIS. 79 that which was ensues. Hence, if the elements, which the philoso- phers under consideration have described, are not formed out of things themselves immutable, we should have things returning to nothing, and again defy the first principle, of all true philosophy. Quin potius tali naiiira praedita quaedam Corpora constituas, igfiern si forte crearint, Posse eadem demptis paucis paucisque tributis, Or dine mutato et motu, facer e aeris avras. Sic alias aliis rebus mutarier onmisp^ — exclaims Lucretius, who in this as ail other instances, argues from his own standpoint exclusively. It may serve to mitigate in our judgment the severity of Lucretius' assault upon Heraclitus to remember that he is principally actuated by his hostility to the Stoics, who adopted very largely the physical theory of the origin of the universe taught by Heraclitus, as the Epi- cureans employed that of Leucippus and Democritus for their pur- pose. Munro feels that the use of plural subjects and verbs in the section under survey (I, 645-89), undoubtedly points to the Stoic school.^ 2. The Stoics. The antagonism of Lucretius toward the Stoic school was one of the inevitable consequences of his absolute confidence in -Epicurus. Trusting him with unquestioning devotion, he could not avoid being intolerant of that system of philosophy which, at the time he wrote, was the only successful rival of Epicureanism. Though Lucretius never mentions the Stoics or their chief teachers, Zeno, Chrysippus and Cleanthes by name, there are repeated allusions to them in his verses, which betray an intensity of feeling not always manifest in other polemical passages. Twice in Book I (641, 106 8)- he con- temptuously calls the Stoics stolidi, a word containing more bitterness » 1, 798-802. "^ Munro. II, p. 83. 80 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS L\ LUCRETIUS. than he evinces in the case of any other school. This hostility of Lucretius to the philosophers of the "porch," one might almost call an inherited passion. Reference has already been made to the unfriendliness with which Epicurus spoke of competitors for philo- sophic honors.' Diogenes Laertius endeavors to refute these reports of harshness on' the part of Epicurus toward his rivals, insisting that they are calumnies, and citing evidences of his kindness and affability. \ie\ii\vaa-i 8' ovtoi. tw ■ydp dvSpl (idprvpcs iKavol ttjs dvvireppX'^TOv irpos irdvros ev-yvwfjLOo-vviis t^ rt irarpls xo^^ais elKocri Tin"^S K'n^' ""^ irdXco-iv oXais |j^Tp€i(rdai Svvacrdai, oi re yvo\js €V- iroiCa, irpos rt rovs oUc'ras Tip.€p«5rTjs, . • KaOoXov re t) irpos irdvras avrov 4>iXav- BpcoirCa. rtis fiev ^ydp irpos 6eov»s oa-idrryros Kal irpos irarp(8a (f>iX(as aXcKros tj 8id- Geo-is. ^ But an attitude of friendliness toward disciples and admirers is certainly not inconsistent with injustice and hatred toward philo- sophic opponents. Moreover, the defence which Diogenes Laertius makes is not wholly disinterested, since if not a disciple himself, he was at least a warm friend of the Epicureans.^ The spirit of hostil- ity which Epicurus exhibited toward the champions of other philo- sophic schemes he transmitted to his followers, whose most conspic- uous characteristic, as we have seen, was their servile devotion to their master's instruction. It was natural that a contention which had ensued for two hundred years should suffer no diminution with the lapse of time. In agreement with this probability we find Zeno, the Sidonian, a o-xoXdpxrjs, who wrote in the time of Lucretius, in- dulging in positive scurrility when he mentions the older philoso- ophers as well as his contemporaries. Cicero* declares: Zefio quidem non eos solum, qui turn erant, Apollodoi'um, Sihwi, ceteros, figebat mal- ediciis, sed Socraten ipsum, parenfem philosophiae, Latino verbo utens ^ Diogenes Laertius, X. 7, 8. ^ Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans atid Sceptics (Eng. Tr.), p. 416, * De Nat. Deor., I, 93. THE STOICS. 8 1 scurram Atticum fuisse dicebat Chrysippum nemquam nisi Chrysippam} vocebat. Such contumelious treatment was sure to be resented. The Stoics of earlier days did not hesitate to heap the foulest abuse upon Epicurus "^ in return for his strictures upon their philosophy ; and their successors were not slow to emulate them in this respect when they came to consider the later Epicureans. But the Stoic charges of gross immorality have never been proven against Epicurus and his immediate disciples. It is very natural that a company of persons who assert that pleasure is the highest good should be open to the suspicion of sensuality. And this likelihood was increased in the case of Epicurus bv the admission of women, some of whom were of easy virtue, to the garden where his philosophy was taught. Such conduct, however, was not extraordinary in the state of Greek soci- ety at that time. And in all justice it must be confessed that the idolatrous veneration of his adherents for Epicurus is difficult of ex- planation on the supposition that he was a man of impure character. Moreover, his letters here and there give evidence of a righteousness almost Puritanic in some particulars. That he subsisted on frugal fare, and refrained from excesses of every sort, is the testimony not only of his friends,^ but also of those who ridiculed his abstemious- ness.* Great writers subsequent to Lucretius, such as Seneca, Ju- venal and Lucian, vindicate the name of Epicurus from the dishonor ^ Or, Chesipptan. -AiOTifios 8 6 Stwikos 8v€'pwv irevTTiKovTa do-cX-yeiS <«)S 'ETrtKovpov Kal 6 rd els Xpvitrnrirov dv. a()>€p6}i€va lirio-ToXia ws 'EiriKovpov T](rl 8ls avrov rifs T^ficpas l)J.€iv d-TTo Tpv(|>fis. - - (Twcivai re avrw re Kal MTjrpoScopo) IraCpas Kal aX- Xas, Ma(ip.dpiov Kal 'HSciav Kal 'Epwriov Kal NiKiSiov. — Diog. Laer., X, 3-7. Usener, Epicurea, pp. 360-2. ^AiokXt^s 8c €v t^ TpiTT) rr\'i liri8pop.fis T]crtv - fvTcXeo-Tara Kal Xirdrara 8iaiTc&- (jkcvoi* kot-uXt) -yovv, 4>T]T]o-l Kv6pi8iov, IV* orav ^vXiOfiat iroXvTcX€v(jt,ai. lb., X. X. II. C/.. 130 144, 146. * James Baldwin Brown. Stoics and Saints, p. 17 (Mac Millan & Co.). 82 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. which is attached to it through the perversion of his doctrines. * At the same time it must be confessed that there is nothing in his principles or system of philosophy to restrain those who espouse his teaching from a life of self-indulgence. That a convivialist will adopt such a scheme of doctrines to justify lascivious and effeminate conduct, is not only a natural inference, but a fact of history. Usener, speaking of the opponents of the Epicureans, refers to the never-ending hostility of the Stoics in the following language: Omnium longe acerb issimi et gravissimi Stoici. Quorum sectae cum a principio Epicuri philosophia omnis repugnaret, etiavi magis contraria facta est, postquam Persaeus unam Stoicorum doctrinam servanda regno et civiiati utilem esse Antigono regi persuasit et ad regni commoda philos- ophiam revocavit. Prodiit Clean thes adversarius ut Arisiarchus Saniius expertus est, acer vehemensque, qui nnn solum atomos inpugnaret sed eti~ am i?iiaginem vividam exornando Virtutum ancillantium miserationem, odium Voluptatis dominantis commoveret. lam magis magisque coeptum est odiis irisque diniicari. Ad infainandum Epicurum fuere qui epislulas inpudicas tamquam ab illo scriptas publicarent. Severissima plebiscita in Epicureox a Messeniis Lyctiis Phalannaeis facta multitudinis superstiti- osae odio Stoicorum calumniis exciiato. '^ The Epicureans on their part were, of course, no less bitter in their criticisms upon the followers of Zeno. Philodemus, a close con- temporary of Lucretius, brings serious charges of impiety against the Stoics. Erom the Volumina Herculanensia Usener makes this extract: irdvTcs ovv ol diro Z('^)v<«)vos el Kal dir6\(€i)irov to 8ai|i6viov, cScrir(€)p ot jtev ovK air(€)\ciirov, (ot) 8' ^v tktIv ovk d'ir€'(X€t)irov, Siva (0€)6v \€'"yov(aa*lv ol Ilav^Xrivcs dXXd Kal irXciovas etvai XcYdvTwv.* •Sellar, Roman Poets of the Republic, p. 299. Seneca, Vit. Be., 13, I. Ep, 33, 2. Cf., Cic. Fin., II, 25, 81. Zeller, Stoics. Epicureans and Sceptics, p. 487, 3- 2 Epic urea. Prefatio, LXXI. LXXII. ' irepl Ivore^cCas, in Epicurea, Praefatio, LXXIII. THE STOICS. 83 Cicero refers to the master of the Epicurean school as Epicurum, quern hebetem et rudeni dicere solent Stoici. ' Knowing the animosity of some of the belligerents in the contests of the Stoics and the Epicureans, we easily conjecture the manner in which those treated one another, of whom we have no accurate record. Formerly, we are told,^ there were extant many volumes of the controversial writings of Chrysippus bearing upon Epicurus, but we have now only an imperfect, though valuable, index of the pro- ductions of the famous Stoic, those treating of Epicurean tenets be- ing as follows: ircpl Tov KoXov Kal Tfjs TiSovfis, diroScC^cis irpos to jjlt] etvai ttjv t)Sovi]v t^os, 4- iroStt^tis irpos TO ftt] ctvai rtiv tiSovtjv d-yaOov."^ The- hostility of Lucretius toward Stoicism, however, cannot be adequately accounted for on the mere ground of the traditional en- mity existing between the two schools. Not only do irreconcilable differences occur immediately the systems are brought to the solution of the same fundamental problems, but there are remarkable points of agreement between them, which alone would be sufficient to beget an ungenerous rivalry. Epicureans and Stoics alike were in quest of the same desideratum — rest of soul (dTapa^Ca). They both employed in this pursuit a philosophy thoroughly materialistic, and assigned to practical questions a supremacy over matters of pure speculation. The perceptions of the senses were by both regarded as the only standard by which truth could be measured. They were both agreed that accurate knowledge is attainable, otherwise there could be no positive action. Even in the consideration of the summum bonum, where it would be natural to expect the widest breach, it has been shown that the grounds of contentment and spiritual repose in both were exceedingly similar.* It has been truthfully asserted "that the ^ De Divinatione. II, 50, 103. 2 Usener, Epicurea Praefatio, LXXIII. ' Diogenes Laertius, VII, 202. * "According to Zeno virtue, according to Epicurus pleasure, is the highest and only good ; but the former in making virtue consist essentially in withdrawal from the senses or insensibility ; the latter in seeking pleasure in repose of mmd or in- perturbability, are expressing the same bt-lief. Man can only find unconditional and enduring satisfaction, when by means of knowledge he attains to a condition 84 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. tones of Lucretius might in many places be mistaken for those of a Stoic, rather than an Epicurean. In their resistance to the com- mon forms of evil these systems were at one. Perhaps, too, in the positive good at which he aimed, the spirit of Lucretius was more that of a Stoic than he imagined."^ Furthermore, both Epicureans and Stoics are devoid of any permanent interest in social life, and both would divorce the wise man from public and political activity. The very likeness ^ of these several approaches to the main question at issue was calculated to engender enmity and rancour. In addi- tion to which there v/as an irrepressible conflict between the two schools in the detailed development of their materialistic views. Speaking broadly, the occasions of this contention may be best de- scribed in the language of another: "These divergencies appear particularly on the subject of nature, the Stoic regarding nature as a system of design, the Epicureans explaining it as a mechanical prod- uct. Whilst the Stoics adhered to fatalism, and saw God every- where, the Epicureans held the theory of atoms and the theory of necessity. Whilst the Stoics were speculatively orthodox, the Epi- cureans were irreligious free-thinkers."' Hence it was inevitable that the author of De Rerum Natura should give large place to contro- versy witli his master's chief antagonists. Particular instances of conflict between Lucretius and the Stoic school appear early in "the poem. The passage in which properties and accidents [eventa et conjuncta) are discussed * is directly opposed to the teaching of the rival philosophy which regards all states, qualities, virtues, emotions, etc., as corporeal. of mind at rest with itself, and also to an independence of external attractions and misfortunes. . , . Neither the Stoic can separate happiness from virtue, nor the Epicurean separate virtue irom happiness." — Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans and Scep- tics^ pp. 505, 6. ^ Sellar, Roman Poets of the Republic, p. 363. '^ " The united weight of all these points of resemblance is sufficient to warrant the assertion that, notwithstanding their difference, the Stoics and Epicureans stand on the same footing, and that the sharpness of contrast between them is ow- ing to their laying hold of opposite sides of one and the same principle." Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, p. 506. ^Jb.y p. 505. * I, 430-82. THE STOICS. 85 The Stoics and Epicureans were agreed that reality could only be ascribed to material objects. ^ They argued in almost identical terms that whatever affects anything, or is in turn affected by anything, is bodily substance. Cicero^ says: Discrepahat etiam ab iisdem {superi- or ibus ZeTio), quod nullo mode arbitrabatur quidquam effici posse ab ea (natura), quae expers esset corporis — nee vero aut quod efficeret aliquid aiit quod efficeretur posse esse non corpus. Plutarch says: ^vra "ydp |jt6va TO. (rp.dTu> o-wfia dXXd o-wpia o-t&piaTi • o-v|iirdo-x€i 8€ T| xj/vxT] tw (r(op.aTi voo-ovvti Kal Tep,vop,cv(p Kal to (rci))xa t-q \|/vxii ' alcxwo^tevT^S 'yovv cpvOpov 'yivcTai Kal <}>oPovp,4vi]s itX[>6v. orup,a apa t| ^vx*^* ^ Other Stoic authorities are equally pronounced in this view. ^Acad., I, 39. 2 Comm. Notit. 30, 2 in Ritter et Preller 396<7. ^ Diogenes Laertius, X. 67. *1. 440-8. » Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, 210, i. 86 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN H'CRETirS. The Epicurean position on this question coincides with that of the Stoics, as the accompanying quotations sufficiently prove. ot X^-yovTCS 6i.T€ ir&a-xiiv, cl tJv rouavrr]' vvv 8* ivayn^ d}jL6Tcpa ravra a-v\i^aivt\, wtpl t^v ^vxt]v TO, dvai Kcto-Oai. . . ol 8* ov fjiovov rds dperds Kal rds KaK- (as X,(ao, ctvai X^-youo-tv, ovh\ rd irdOr] |x6vov, op-yds Kal <})06vous Kal Xviras Kal €iri- XaipcKaKias. ov8e KaTaX'^\(rei$ Kal (|>avTa TTjv o-KVTOTop,iK'<]v TTjv xo-Xkotuttik'/iv, dXXd iTpos TOVTOis tTi Kal rds Ivep-yeCas crcop.- ara Kal X^iaa iroiovo-i, tov irtpCiraTOv 5«ov, ttjv Spxiio-iv, it^v virdOco-iv, Tt]v irp- oo-aYopcvo-iv, Tt]v Xoi8op(av.^ The Good was also regarded by the Stoics as in the same category. Seneca sa\s: Quaeris, bonum an corpus sit. Bonum facit, prodest enim; quod facit corpus est. Bonum agitat animum et quodam modo format ef c on tine t, quae propria sunt corporis. Quae corporis bona sunt, corpora sunt ergo; et quae animi sunt; nam et hie corpus est. .... Non puto te dubitaturum an adfectus corpora sint, — tanquam ira, amor, tristitia. Si dubitas, vide an voltum nobis mutent, an frontem adstringant, an faciem diffundant, an rubor em evocent, an fugent sanguinem. Quid ergo, tarn manifestas notas corpori credis imprimi nisi a corpore.'^ Si adfectus ^ Diogenes Laertins, X, 67. 2 III, 161-6. '^Plutarch, Com. Not., 45, 2, in Ritter et Preller, 396^. THE STOICS. 87 corpora sunt, et morbi animorum, et avaritia, crudeliias, induraia viiia ei' in statum inemendabilem adducta; ergo et malitia et species eius omnes, . maiignitas, invidia, superbia. Ergo et bona, prinium quia contraria istis sunt, deinde quia eadeju tibi indicia praestabunt. ^ Truth is likewise placed in the same classification, the significance of truth being the knowledge which the soul possesses in itself TT]v 8c dX^Ociav otovrai tivcs, Kal fidXio-ra ot diri ttjs StooLs, 8ia4>6p€iv rdXriOovs Kara rpcts rpoirovs, ovao'(v tovtI |X€v -ydp d^ico^d cctti, to St d|C(U(jLa X€Kt6v, to h\ \€kt6v d(r(6p,aTOv. dvdiraXiv %\ tj d\-f|6eia o-d)p,d €o-ti irapdcov Ittio-t^- (iTj irdvTwv d\t]0(ov diroavTiKTj 8ok€i Tv-yxdveiv, trdo-a 8c lirio-T-^fiT] irais €xov ia-rXv ■f^'Ycp.oviKdv TO Se Tj-ycfioviKOv o-co|xa KaTd tovtovs viirfipxcv. -' Against these and other similar claims of the Stoics, Lucretius op- poses his doctrine that there are but two conceivable things in the universe, atoms and the void, materies et inane, dTojia Kal k«v6v. All other things are not distinct entities, but properties and accidents of things, having no material existence apart from the bodies with which they are identified, Xafn quaecumque cluent, aut his coniuncta duabus Rebus ea invenies aut horum eventa videbis. Coniunctuju est id quod nusquam sine permitiali Discidio potis est seiungi seque gregari, Pondus uti saxist, calor ignis, liquor aquai. Tactus corporibus cimctis intactus inani Servitium contra paupertas divitiaeque, Libertas bellum concordia, cetera quorum Adventu manet incolumis natura abituque, Haec soliti sumus, ut par est, eventa vocare} Starting with the principle that existence alone belongs to that which is material, the Stoics had great difficulty in assigning time and space to their proper category. While they could not describe these as corporeal, they did speak of day and night, months and years and seasons, as bodies, though it is evident that those who did '^ Epistotaf, 106, 3, in Ritter et Preller, 396C. '^ Sext. Math.. VII. 38, in Ritter et Preller. 396^9. 3 I. 449-59- 00 CONTROVERSIAL ELF.MF.NTS IX LUCRETH'S. SO v'irtually meant that these divisions of time answered to certain material states; the heat of the sun, for example, being responsible for summer, and the other seasons being regulated duly by the ap- proach and retirement of this planet. T«v 8c Iv dc'pt yivo\kiv(av, \ti\i.Mva jiev ctvai a(rl tov virep yi\s i^pa KaT€\|ru'Yp.^vov 8id TTiv TOV TjXCov irpoo-w a(|>o8ov cap 8c, ttiv cvKpacrCav tov d^pos, kutu ttiv irpos T)(ids iropc(av. ' CTi 8^ Kal TOV \p6vov do'<»|xaTOv, 8kd(rTT]pLa Svra tt^s tov K6o*p.ov Kivt\s ti^v a{iTi|v ova-iav exov tw l8i(op,aTi tovtw (Kal-ydp tovto iroiovcrt tiv^s)j dWd \i6vov w o-vp.ir\^KOp,€v to I'Siov tovto Kal irapapicTpovficv, fidXicTa iTriXo-yio-T^ov. Kal -ydp tovto ovk d7ro8€i|€(tfs irpoo-SciTai dXX' ^irtXo-yio-p.ov, oti Tais Tjp,4pais Kal Tais vv|l orvfiirXcKOfiev Kal tois tovtwv ptep- >oriv, wo'avTws 8c Kal TOis irdOco'i Kal Tais diraOcCais, Kal Kiv-^o-eo-i Kal o-Tao-co'iVy t8i6v Ti cru)j,TrTta>|ia ircpl TavTa irdvTa avTo tovto Ivvoovvtcs, Ka9' 6 ^povov ovo- (id^ojicv. ^ This more consistent view is well expressed by Lucretius: Tempus item per se non est, sed rebus ab ipsis Consequitur sensus, transactum quid sit aevo. Turn quae res instet, quid porro deinde sequatur. Nee per se quemquam tempus sentire fatendumst Semotum ab rerum motu placidaque quiete. Perspicere ut possis res gestas funditus omnis Non ita uti corpus per se constare neque esse, Nee ratione cluere eadem qua constet inane, Sed magis ut merito possis eventa vocare Corporis atque loci, res in quo quaeque gerantur,.* '^ Diogenes Laertius, VII, 15 1. '^Ib., 141, Cf., Sext. Math., X, 218, in Ritter et Preller, 399^^. ^Diogenes Laertius, X, 72. 73. n, 459-63; 478-82. THE STOICS. 89 The point of conflict between the two schools in this matter is this, — the Stoics strove very Jiard to assign corporeality to what the Epicureans described not as being itself, but as modes of being. In our discussion of Heraclitus we have already adverted to the physical basis with which this philosopher provides the Stoic school by his doctrine of primordial fire. We have also noted the dif- ference of opinion held by critics regarding the real object of Lucre- tius' attack in the following lines: ^ Quin etiam repetunt a caelo atque ignibus eius, Et primum faciunt ignem se verier e in auras A en's, hinc inibrem gigni, terravique creari Ex imbri, relroqtie a terra cuncta reverti, Umorem primum, post aera, deinde calorem, Nee cessare haec inter se mutare, meare A caelo ad terram, de terra ad sideya mundi. Quod facer e haud ullo debent primordia pacta. Immutabile enim quiddam superare necessest, Ne res ad nilum redigantur fundifus omnes: Nam quodcumque suis mutatum finibus exit, Continuo hoc mors est illius qvod fuit ante. Qu.ipropter quonijm qu:ie paulo diximus ante In commutatum veniunt, constare necessest Ex aliis ea, quae nequeatit convertier usquam, Ne tibi res redeant ad nilum funditus omnes. Quin potius tali natura praedita quaedam Corpora constituas, ignem si forte crearint Posse eadem, demplis paucis paucisque tributis, Ordine mutato et motu, facere aeris auras. Sic alias aliis rebus mutarier omnisj^ Whatever we may determine to have been the actual occasion of this passage, it certainly doas not misrepresent the position of the Stoics, if aimed at them. For, observing that warmth supplies nourishment, motion and life to matter, and that heat is existent in all things, they ascribed the origin and preservation of the world to ^p. 78. 2 1, 782-802. 90 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. fire. Since it is a law of nature that primary being shall transmute itself into specific things, fire passes into air, water, earth; and through the distribution and combination of these elements the world is produced. After describing what, in the Stoic terminology, an element (o-Toixetov) signifies, and explaining that Zeno and his fol- lowers regarded fire, air, water, earth, as equally essential matter, without any distinctive quality, Diogenes Laertius continues: dvcDTdra) jacv ovv clvai to irvp, o St] alO^pa KaXeio-Gai, iv w irpc&Tqv ttiv t vwv cr4>aCpav ^cvvdcrSai, clra tt]v twv irXavcDpicvwv* (Jie8' t^v rov d^pa' ctra to vSwp' (nroo-TdOjJiTjv 8c irdvTwv ttjv -yf^v, p.^o-i)v dirdvTwv ovo-av. ^ He also asserts this to be their view of nature: 80K6I $€ avTots TT)v \uv <)>vo-iv ctvai irvp TCXvtK6v, 68(0 PaOt^ov el$ ^^vco'iv, ^trcp ^o-tI irvcvfia irupociScs Kal tcxvo€i86s. ^ Again on the interchange of the elements, he records the Stoic doctrine as follows: yLvtarQai hi rov K6o-p.ov, 8Tav 4k irup6s tj ovcCa Tpair^ 81' d^pos ds vyp6v, ilra. t6 iraxv|jL€p6S avTOV o-vorTdv diroTeXco-O]} y9\, to hi \€irT0|jLcp€S l^apaiwO-g Kal tovt lirl irX^ov XciTTvvOcv irvp airoyiwf\^ Natura Deorum coincides with the testimony herewith presented: Sic enim res habei, ut omnia, quae alantur et quae crescant, contineant in se vim caloris, sine qua neque ali possent nee crescere. Nam o??ine, quod est calidum el igneum, cietur et agitur motu suo. ^ Quod quidem Cleanthes his etiam argumentis docet, quanta vis insit 1 VII, 137. 2/^., 156. »/^., 142. ^Chrysipp. Ap. Plut. Stoic, Rep. 41, 3, p. 1053. in Ritter et Preller, 405^. '11. 9» 23. THE STOICS. 91 caloris in omni corpore: negat enim esse uUum cibum tarn gravem, quin is node et die concoquatur ; cuius etiam in reliquiis inest calor iis, quas natura respuerit. . . . Omne igitw, quod vivil, sive animal sive terra editum, id vivit propter inclusum in eo colorem. Ex quo iniellegi debet earn caloris naturam vim habere in se vitalem per omnem mundum pertiftentem. ^ Et cum quattuor genera sint corporum, vicissitudine eorum mundi con- tinuata natura est. Nam ex terra aqua, ex aqua oritur aer, ex aere aether^ deinde retrorsum vicissim ex aethere aer, inde aqua, ex aqua terra infima. Sic naturis his, ex quibus omnia constant sursus deorsus, ultra citro commeantibus mundi par tium coniunctio continetur.^ The resemblance between the opinions of Heraclitus already noted and the views of the Stoics herein expressed is so close as to imply that whatever Lucretius urges against the doctrine of elemental fire of the one he intends to be valid against the similar doctrine of the other. Both were doubtless in mind as he wrote the passage under consideration. Moreover, whatever he directs against the four ele- ments of Empedocles has a purposed bearing on the physical theories of the Stoics as well. Lucretius takes issue with the Stoics on the structure and course of the universe no less than on its constituent elements. Having controverted the doctrine of primordial fire, he proceeds to discuss the method by which the universal order came into existence, and finds himself again in conflict with the hereditary foe. Accident, and not design, is responsible for the production of the world. The eternal whirl of the atoms, with their perpetual collisions and attempts at combination, at length succeeded in begetting the present constitu- tion of things. This proposition Lucretius announces repeatedly in the progress of his poem, but never more elaborately than in the fol- lowing lines : A^am certe neque consilio primordia rerum Ordine se suo quaeque sagaci mente locarunt Nee quos quaeque darent motus pepigere prq/ecto, Sed quia multa modis multis primordia rerum ^ Cicero. De Natura Deorttm. II, 9, 24. 2 /<^., II, 33, 84. 92 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. Ex infinito iam ternpore percita plagis Ponder ibusque suis consuerunt concita ferri Omnimodisque coire aique omnia pertempiare. Quae cumque inter se possent congressa creare, Propter ea fit uti magnum volgata per aevom Omne genus coetus et motus experiundo Tandem conveniant ea quae convecta repent e Magnarum rerum fiunt exordia semper, Terrai maris et caeli generis que animantum. * Such a process of world-formation necessarily involves infinity of matter and of space. Lucretius introduces his argument for this doctrine by a declaration that the universe is infinite, which he illus- trates and enforces at some length. Omne quod est igitur nulla regione viarum Finitumst; namque extremum debebat habere, etc. ' In this he follows Epicurus with remarkable fidelity, both in ideas and phraseology. TO irdv aircipdv € ov. cl' re "ydp r\v ro kcvov dircipov, rd 8e o-idfiara wpi(r|JL€va, ovSaixov dv ep.evc rd (TMiiara, dX.\* c<{>epeTO Kard to dircipov kcvov 8kco"irap(jL€va, ovk c^ovTa Td vircpcCSov- Ta Kal orTcXXovTa Kard rds dvaKoirds. tt t€ to kcvov -qv b)piaipoci8€s . . c^- «9€v 8* auTOv ircpiKexv|i^vov clvai to K€v6v aireipov, oirep dt|o-iv *A'n-o\X68(«)pos) o8* rt Kocfios, Kal Ka0* eVcpov Tpoirov TO €K ToO K6(rp.ov Kttl Tov c^cuOcv Kcvov, (rva-Tr\\ia. 6 fxev oZv K6., » 143- ■' ih. . 150. *i, 1052-9. THE STOICS. 95 De Natiira Deorum, elaborates the exact theory which Lucretius thus condemns. Omnes enini partes ems undique medium locum capessenles nitujitur aequaliter. Maxime autem corpora inter se iuficta permanent, cum quasi quodam vi?iculo circumdato coltiga?itur; quod facit ea natura, quae per omnem mundum o??inia mente et ratione conficiens funditur et ad medium rapit et convertit extrema. . . . Eademque ratione mare, cum supra terram sit, medium tamen terrae locum expetens conglobatur undique aequabiliter neque redundat umquam neque effunditur. * Stobaeus attributes this theory to Zeno. iravra rd n^prj tov Koo-piov IttI to (le'o-ov tov koo-jiov ttjv (}>opdv exciv, (idXio-a 8c ToL pdpos €XOVTa.^ To Lucretius the conception is absurd, and the existence of the antipodes is ridiculed as the dream of fools. Ut per aquas quae nunc rerum simulacra videmus, Adsi?nili ratione animalia suppa vagari Contendtint, neque posse e terris in loca caeli Reccidere inferiora magis quam corpora nostra SpoTite sua possint in caeli templa volare Illi cum videant solem, nos sidera noctis Cernere, et alternis nobiscum tempora caeli Divider e et nodes parilis agitare diebus, Sed vanus stolidis haec [error somnia finxit].' The inadequacy of the arguments adduced by the Stoics in sup- port of the theory of centripetal force is clearly shown by Lucretius, who denies that infinite space can have any center, and asserts that if it were possible, nothing could come to a rest at this point, since space will always yield to heavy bodies, which cannot lose their weight, in whatever direction they move.* The inconsistency of the Stoics in asserting that only the heavy elements, earth and water, press to the center, while air and fire '11.45,113, 116. '^ Munro, II, p. 1 14. =^I, 1060-8. ♦I, 1069-82. 96 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. mount upward, is expressed not only in this connection, but in a subsequent passage, in which Lucretius refutes the Aristotelian notion of an upward centrifugal force. ^ The language of Lucretius is full of force, and justly represents the views of his antagonists. Praeterea quoniam non omnia corpora fingunt In medium niti, sed terrarum atque liquoris, Et quasi terreno quae corpore contineantur, Umorem ponti magnasque e montibus undas, At contra tenuis exponunt aeris auras Et calidos simul a medio differrier ignis, Atque ideo totum circum tremere aether a signis Et solis flammam per caeli caerula pasci Quod calor a medio fugiens se ibi conligat omnis, Nee pr or sum arboribus summos frondescere ramos Posse, nisi a terris paulatim cuique cibatum, etc. ^ The teaching of Zeno, as we have sufficient evidence, confirms the charge of incongruity which Lucretius here makes against his followers: oti iravTCDS 8e xrSt^a, pdpos ^\l^^v, d\X* dpapfj elvai dc'pa Kal xup* •yC-yvfo-Oai 8c Kal Tavrd irws lirl to ttjs oXt]s ciCpas tov K6€pciav avTov iroi€io-6ai k.tA.^ In has been observed by Munro that ''had Epicurus, while retain- ing his conceptions of infinite space and matter and innumerable worlds and systems, seen fit to adopt this Stoical doctrine of things tending to a center, and so to make his atoms rush from all sides of space alike towards a center, he might have anticipated the doctrine of universal gravity."* But he did not possess interest enough in the problems of physical science to pursue them beyond their imme- diate and obvious relation to ethical questions, nor was his know- ledge of mathematics sufficient to lead him toward the discovery which has made the name of Newton immortal. Lucretius, though ^11, 184-215. 21, 1083-93. '^ Stobaeus, Eclogue, in Munro, II. p. 114. *I, p. 114. THE STOICS. 97 exhibiting keener powers of scientific observation than Epicurus evinces in any fragments of his writings which have been preserved, is in this instance, as in many others, l)ut the echo of his idoHzed master. Omnis enini locus ac spatium, quod in [ane vocamus], Per medium, per non medium, concedere [debet] Aeque ponderibus, motus qua cumque feruntur. Nee quisquam locus est, quo corpora cuni venerunf, Ponderis amissa vi possint stare in inani: Nee quod inane autem est ulli subsistere debet, Quin, sua quod natura petit, concedere pergat. Haud igitur possunt tali ratione teneri Res in concilium medii cuppedine vinctae. ' Having shown his hostility to the Stoic conceptions of the origin, constitution and maintenance of the universe, it is natural that Lucretius should oppose the doctrine of the immortality and divinity of the world as held by the followers of Zeno. This he does in the following vigorous protest; Multa tibi expediam doctis solacia dictis; Religione re/renatus ne forte rear is Terras et solem et caelum, mare sidera lunam, Corpore divino debere aeterna manere, Proptereaque pules ritu par esse Gigantum Pender e eos poenas inmani pro seek re om?iis. Qui ratione sua disturbent moenia mundi Praeclar unique velint caeli restinguere solem, Inmortalia mortali sermone notantes; Quae procul usque adeo divino a numine distent, Inque deum numero quae sint indigna videri, Notitiaju potius praebere ut posse putentur Qtiid sit vital i motu sensuque remotum.'^ While there was apparently some diversity of opinion among the Stoic leaders regarding portions of the doctrine herein assailed. ^ I. 1074-82. Cf. Diogenes Laertius, X, 43, 61. n\ 113-25. 98 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. there was perfect unanimity touching the identification of the creative energy inherent in primordial fire with deity. The all- pervading essence which was responsible for the world and its phen- omena, they argued, could only be defined as the highest reason, operative in matter as the soul is in man. The unity and perfection of the world could only be accounted for on this theory. Nor, with- out a rational principle acting upon formless matter, could reason- ing creatures be produced out of the world. This rational essence, this anima mundi, is God. But since, according to the Stoics, deity could only attain reality when clothed with material forms, it was in- evitable that the universe and its parts should be regarded as bodying forth divinity, and that ultimatelv the distinction between the ex- ternal manifestation and the inner spirit of being should be so obscured as to be practically lost, and the divinity of the world be acknowledged. And this pantheistic conception seems to have i)re- vailed among all the great Stoics except Boethus, who insisted on a separation between God and the world. ^ Cicero has presented the Stoic view of the divinity of the universe and its parts, and the arguments by which this proposition was sus- tained with great fulness, as the accompanying excerpts from his elaborate discussion will sufficiently show. To Zeno he attributes these sentiments: Quod ratione utitiir, id melius est quam id, quod raiione no?! ufi/ur; nihil autem viundo melius; raiione igitur mtindus utitur. Nullius sensu carentis pars aliqua potest esse sentiens; vnmdi autetn partes sentientes sunt; Tion igitur caret sensu mundus. Nihil quod aninii quodque rationis est expers, id gen- erare ex se potest animantem conpotemque rationis; mundus autein generat animantis conpotesque rationis; animans est igitur mundus com- posque rationis. . . . Cur igitur mundus nan animans sapiensque iudicetur, cum ev se procreet animantis atque sapientis ?'■ Natura est igitur, quae contineat ?nundum omnem etimque tueatur, et ea quidem non sine sensu atque ratione; omnem enim naturam necesse est, quae non solitaria sit neque si?nplex, sed cu?n alio iuncta atque conexa, • Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans and Sa-pfics, pp. 1 44- 160. "^ De Natura Deo7-u7u, II, 21, 22. THE STOICS. 99 habere aliguem in se principattim. . . . Principatum auiem id dico, quod Graeci t|^€|iovik6v vocani, quo nihil in quoque genere nee potest nee debet esse praestantius. Ita necesseest illud etia??i, in quo sit totius naturae principatus, esse omnium optimum omniumque rerum potestate dominatuque dignissimum. Videmus autem in partibus mundi {nihil est enim in omni mundo, quod non pars universi sit) inesse sensum atque rationem. In ea parte igitur, in qua mundi inest principatus, haec inesse necesse est, et acriora quidem atque maiora. Quodcirca sapient em esse mundum necesse est, naturanique cam, quae res omnes conplexa teneat, perfectione ration- is excellere, eoque deum esse mundum, omnemque vim mundi natura di- vina contineri. ^ In arguing for the eternal wisdom and virtue of the workl the Stoic advocate says: Si rationis particeps sit nee sit tanien a principio sapiens, 7ion sit deter- ior mundi potius quam humana condicio; homo enim sapiens fieri potest, mundus autem si in aeterno praeteriti temporis spatio fuit insipiens, nun- quam profecto sapientiam consequetur; ita erit homine deterior. Quod quoniam absurdum est, et sapiens a principio mundus et deus habendus est. Est autem nihil mundo per/ectius, nihil virtute melius ; igitur mundi est propria virtus. Nee vero hominis natura perfecta est, et ef- ficitur tamen in homine virtus; quanto igitur in mundo facilius. Est ergo in eo virtus; sapiens est igitur et propter ea deus. ^ Diogenes Laertius, in specifying the opinions of Zeno's disciples on the subject under discussion, has the following: Xc-yovo-i 8e Kdorfiov rpixus, avrdv re tov Oeov tov Ik ird6apT6s 6v«v iroids ircpioSovs dvaXicKuv els cavrov tt]v airourav ovcriav Kal irdXiv e^ eavrov 9€ov 8*, elvat 5«ov dddvarov, Xo-YkKOVyTeXciov, y\ vocpov ev cv8aip.ovC(ji, KaKov irav- TOS dv€iri8€KT0V irpOVOT^TlKOV KOCTfiOV T€ Kal T»V €V KOOrpifa)' Jit] clvai [JtCVTOt dvOptuiTO- ^op<|>ov. etvai 8c rov |i€v, 8t]}iiovp'yov tmv SXwv, Kal we-ircp iraWpa irdvTwv* koivws T€ Kal TO (Upos avTOv TO 8i'nK0v 8id irdvTwv, o iroXXais irpo(rr)'YopCais irpotrovoud- JeTai Kara tus 8vvd(i€ic.* * De Natura Deorum, II, 29, 30. 2/^., 36-39. ' Diogenes Laertius. VII. 137. *//;., 147. lOO CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. ova£vovTak . . Ocovs 8c Kal rov K66apTa, Kal vircvatn'ias i\iiv tovtw ^ovX'^- ccis SL\La. Kal irpd|€is Kal alrias/^ Though Lucretius denies the divinity of the world, he is not so far apart from his philosophic rivals on the question of the world's de- structibility as on first observation would appear to be the case. The difference between the Stoic and the Epicurean positions on this subject was due chiefly to the divergence of their respective concep- tions of the universe. Zeno and many of his disciples held the theory of recurrent cycles in the career of the world. As matter had in the process of creation been separated from primary being, so eventually it would return to primary being at the end of the present course of things, when a general conflagration would dissolve everything into its ])rimitive elemental condition. As soon as this dissolution had occurred, however, there would begin the formation of a new world exactly conforming in every particular to the preceding one, the identical persons, things and events completing the new cycle which existed in the previous aeon. dpc'cKCi 8 * avTois Kal i|>6apT6v ctvai t6v Koo-p-o v, are y€vt]t6v tw X6'Ya> t»v 8i* aUr6^- 9apTd, ia-ri Kal to oXov Td Si p^'pt] Toii Koo-pov (}>6apTd, €is dXXT]Xa •ydp pcTa^dXXci* <|>6apT6s dpa 6 Koo-pos. Kal ei ti €iri8€KTiK6v Ictti ttjs lirl TO x*^pov ptTaPoXfjs, 4>0apT6v €o-ti' Kal 6 Kocpos dpa* c^avxpovrai ^dp Kal €^v8aTovTai.^ Xpvo-iiriros . . . <|>Y]v\r] ov \(i>pLlfrai pcv av^cTai Se o-vv€X"S P^'XP*-? ^^ *^S avTr^v (|avaXwo-T| tt^v vXt]v, ov piyriov diro6W)avTCuriwv otcrai rovs dv6pwTrovs cvvoi- av co-iraKCvai 6€0v* (ic-ydXtav -ydp clSwXwv, «|>T)wv Kard rovs virvovs irpoo'iri'TrTovTwv vircXapov Kal rats dXT|6eiais iiirdp\civ rivds toiovtovs Ocovs dydpftiirofiop^jovs.'^ Cicero's Epicurean advocate suggests the same: Nam a natura habemus omnes omnium gentium speciem nullam aliam nisi hurnanam deorum; quae enim forma alia occurrit umquam aut vigil- anti cuiquam aut dortnienti ? Sed ne omnia revocentur ad primas noti- ones: ratio hoc idem ipsa dechirat.* Lucretius expresses the same theory: de cor pore quae sane to simulacra feruntur In mentes hojuinum divinae mintia formae} Quippe eienim iam tum divofu mortalia saecla Egregias animo fades vigilante videbant, Et magis in sonmis mirando corporis auctu. ^ Cicero. De Xatiira Dc'orum, I, 43. 0€ol jicv ^dp clp, d^pa, "ytiv.' ACa }i€v "ydp (}>a(ri, 81 6v ra iravTa* Zf)va %\ KaXovo-i, irap &s 8e Kal Tds dXXas irpoo-ij-Yop- Cas, ex'^P'*^^^ Tivos olKeioT-qTOS, dir^Soo-av.^ IV, 1169-82. '^ Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, p. 466. =» Diogenes Laertius, VII. 137. quoted p. 99. ^ lb., VII, 134. ^ lb., 135, 136. «//.., 147. THE STOICS. 105 It is obvious from these declarations that, while the Stoics in strict consistency assigned the name of Deity in its original significance only to the sole primary Being, "they did not hesitate to apply it in a limited and derivative sense to all those objects by means of which the divine power is especially manifested."* The Epicureans, on the other hand, derided the very idea of the directing presence of deity in the creation, preservation and guidance of the world. The prime purpose of Lucretius, announced at the beginning of his poem and reiterated many times in its progress, is to demonstrate et unde queat res quaeque creart Et quo quaeque viodo fiant opera sine divom. ^ Velleius, Cicero's exponent of Epicurean principles, ridicules the doctrine of the creation of the world through divine agency, and charges the Stoics with resorting to the hypothesis of gods for lack of any rational method of accounting for the phenomena of nature. Docuit enim nos idem, qui cetera, natura effectum esse mundum, nihil opus fuisse fabrica, tamque earn rem esse facilem, quam vos effici negatis sine divina posse solertia, ut innumerabilis natura mundos effeciura sit, efficiat, effecerit. Quod quia quern ad modum natura efficere si?ie aliqua viente possit non videtis, ut tragici poetae, cum explicare argwnenti exitum tioti potestis, confugitis ad deum. "' The gods of the Epicureans are beings like men, but of a more re- fined essence. The cCSwXa of the gods which are presented to our minds, whether asleep or awake, take the figure of men. Moreover, the human form is the most admirable that can be conceived of for rational and happy beings. But divine bodies are not tangible to mortals. Hominis esse specie deos confitendiim est. Nee tamen ea species cor- pus est, sed quasi corpus, nee habet sanguinem, sed quasi sanguinem. * Zel!er. Stoics. Epiciivc-ans and Sceptics, p. 347. n. 157.8. '' Dc- Xatura Dc-orum. I. 53. I06 COXTROVERSIAI. ELEMENTS IN H'CRETIl'S, Epicurus autem, qui res occultas et penitus abditas non modi) viderit animo, sed eiiam sic tractet, ut manu, docet eani esse vim ef natur- ani deortwi, ut primum non sensu, sed mente cernatur ; nee soliditaie quadam nee ad numerum, ut ea, quae ille propter firmitatem o-rcpcVvia ap- pellat, sed imagimbus similitudine et transitione perceptis. ^ Tenvis enim natura deum longeque remota Sensibus ab nostris atiimi vix mente videtur ; Quae quoniam manuum tactum suffugit et icium, Tactile nil nobis quod sit contingere debet. Tangere enim non quit quod tangi non licet ipsum. ^ Now, these deities, which are innumerable, are immortal and per- . fectly happy. vptoTOv ficv rhv 6c6v ^6aprov Kal |jiaKdpiov vopiC^wv, b>s f| koivt) rov Ocov voTjoris v'rrc'Ypd4>T], p,T]6ev (I'^rc Tf]s d()>6ap(rCas dWdrpiov ^"(yn rf)s p,aKapi6Tr|ros dvolKciov avTw irp6o-airT€* irdv Be to vXdTT€iv avrov Svvd^ievov tt]v (X€Td d4>0ap- cCas p,aKapi6TT]Ta ircpl avrov 8d^a^<.^ rh fiaKdpiov Kal d4>6apTOv ofirc avro irpd'Yiiara txt\. ovt€ dXXio iraptxti, «povTi8cs Kal op-yal Kal xdpircs fiaKapid- TT]Ti, dW €v do-6cveia Kal <{>6P(i> Kal irpoo-Sc-fja-ct t«v irXT^o-iov ravra -yiveTai.^ Kal T] Oeia 4>v(ris irpos ravra p.T)8a|jk'^ irpo* r\\i tov Aia Kal tov Kocrjiov, t]] 8c ^^Xfi ""1^ irpdvoiav orav ovv CK-n-vpwo-is "y€'vT]Ta«., (lovov a<{>6apT0v ovTa tov A£a T»v Oediv dvaxopctv lirl tt^v irpovoiav, dra. ouoC -ycvofACvovs lirl (iias xf^s tov alQi- pos ovo-ias 8iaT€Xciv dp,<{>OTcpovs.''' The Stoic Balbus presents the arguments of his school in defence of the doctrine of the providence of the gods in a three-fold arrange- ment, as follows: First, if we admit the existence of gods, we must grant that they govern the world, otherwise they would not deserve the title of deities; for the very conception of gods implies that they are independent of all power other than their own, and that they work together harmoniously and wisely for the noblest end, which is nothing less than the government of the world. Second, the order and unity of the universe mdicate that all its parts are under the control of a force working intelligently and skillfully, which we de- nominate Nature. But it is impossible for a thinking man to exam- ine this orderly course of the world without being convinced that it is under the direction of a wise mind. Third, the regularity, har- mony and beauty of the heavenly bodies; the constitution, endow- ments and wondrous adaptations of plants and animals; antl the various productions of the earth, suited so remarkably to the need of living creatures, all unite to confirm the wise man in his belief in a divine providence." Based on the most reliable extant authorities, Zeller has formulated the Stoic arguments for this doctrine in this order: (i) From the general conviction of mankind. (2) From the perfection of God. (3) From the theory of necessity. (4) From the foreknowledge of God. (5) From the existence of dixiniation.* ' Diogenes Laertius, VII, 138, 139. ■^ Plutarch, De Comm. iVofif..- T^b. 5. p. 1077. in Ritter et Preller. 401 li. " De Nati.ra Dear urn, 11. 75-15 '• * Stoics. Epicureans and Sceptics, pp. 173-75. THE STOICS. 109 Perhaps the finest expression of the Stoic belief in the guidance of God which has been preserved for us is contained in the famous Hymn to Zeus by Cleanthes, a portion of which we quote. KvSko-r' dOavdrwv, iroXv(0W|ji€, Tra-yKpaTcs aUC, Zcv, (|>v(r€(i)S dp\T]'Y^, v6|JLOv {jLc'ra iravra Kv^cpvuv, Xaip€' (re "ydp irdvTeo-o-i 6^p.is 0vi^Tot^KT], irupoevra, del Jwovra Kcpavvdv, TOV -ydp viro ttXii'ytJs €WpTjo-iv dvoiais. dXXd v^} Kal Td irtpio-o-d €irio-Tao-ai dpTia Ocivai, Kal Koo-p,€is Td dKoo-|jLa, Kal ov (|>iXa crol iXa Io-tCv. w8€ -ydp €ls «v diravTa o-vv-^p|jLOKas €o-6Xd KaKoto-iv, W0-9 ' €va -Yi-yvco-Oai trdvTwv Xd^ov aUv Iovtu.* The whole teaching of these noble verses is utterly repugnant to the theology of the Epicureans, who not only deem the labor of rul- ing the world incompatible with the unquestioned happiness of the gods, but who profess to see nothing in the adjustments of nature or the experience of men to justify a belief in the providence of the gods. One of the chief reasons for the Stoic confidence in the ex- istence and guardianship of the gods lies in the perfection of the world which they allege, but which the Epicureans strenuously deny. Quid autem est ifiscitius quam eajn naturam, quae omnis res sit con- plexa, non optumam did. . . . Neque enim est quicquam aliud praeter nuindum, cui nihil absit, quodque undique aptum atque perfectum expletumque sit omnibus suis numeris et partibus.^ ^ Stobaeus Eclogue.^ I, p. 30. ^ Cicero, De Natura Deorum, II, 36, 37. no CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. Lucretius can discover no warrant in nature for such a view. On the contrary, he finds such palpable imperfections in creation that if he were totally ignorant of the true philosophy of the universe he would still never hesitate to condemn the notion that the world was constructed by divine power. Nam quamvis rerum igttorem primordia quae sint, Hoc tamen ex ipsis caeli raiionibus ausim Confirmare aliisque ex rebus reddere viulits, Nequaquam nobis divinitus esse creatam Naturam mundi: ianta stat praedita culpa} The argument by which Lucretius sustains his opinion is inter- esting, if not convincing. The defect of nature is apparent in the im- mense waste of the world as compared with its productive portions. Even where tillage is possible with almost incredible labor, the toil of the husbandman is frequently thrown away, for thorns infest the soil, and burning heat, chilling blasts and destructive hurricanes de- feat the projects of the farmer. Again, man himself is beset with constant perils. Ferocious beasts roam abroad. Disease and death walk in the train of the seasons. Helpless infancy is dependent on the care of elders, while the young of animals flourish attended only by the bounty of nature.^ There is an uncertainty and capriciousness also about the opera- tion of some of the forces of nature, not to speak of the impossibil- ity that any personal agency should control these forms of energy, which prevents him from believing the gods maintain any active in- terest in the progress of human affairs. Quae bene cogniia si teneas, natura videiur Libera continuo, dominis privaia superbis, Ipsa sua per se sponte omnia dis agere expers. Nam pro, sancta deiim tranquilla pectora pace Quae placidum degunt aevom viiamque serenam, Quis regere immensi surnmam, quis habere prof imdi Indu manu validas potis est moderanter habenas, ^11, 177-81. 2V, 195-234. THE STOICS. Ill Quis pariier caelos omnis convertere et omnis Ignibus aetheriis terras suffire feracis. Omnibus inve locis esse 07?mi tempore praesto, Nubibus ut tenebras faciat caelique serena Concutiat sonitu, turn fulmina mittat et aedis Saepe suas disturbet et in deserta recedens Saeviat, exercens teliim, quod saepe nocentes Praeterit exanimatqtie indignos inqiie merentes P^ The real animus of the Epicurean eagerness to disprove the prov- idence of the gods lies, of course, in the purpose to deliver men from the fear of deity, which Lucretius and his school felt to be in- cident to a belief in this doctrine. Nam et praestans deorum natura hominum pietate coleretur, cum et aeterna esset et beatissima {habet enim venerationem iustam, quicquid ex- cellit), et metus omnis a vi atque ira deorum pulsus esset; i?itellegitur enim a beata injuortalique natura et iram et gratiam segregari; quibus re- motis nullos a superis impendere metus.'^ The supreme inspiration of Lucretius' philosophical inquiries is the desire to deliver men from the dread of divine malevolence. His passion for the redemption of mankind from irrational terrors is ex- ceedingly impressive. He bewails the puerile credulity of the race. Nam veluti pueri trepidant atque omnia caecis In tenebris metuunt, sic nos in luce timemus Interdum, nilo quae sunt metuenda magis quam Quae pueri in tenebris pavitant finguntque futura} He would dispel such groundless forebodings by means of the rev- elations of true science. Hunc igitur terrorem animi tenebrasque necessest Non radii solis neque lucida tela diei Discutiant, sed naturae species ratioque. * ni, 1090-1104. '^ De Natura Deoruvi, I, 45. =« 11, 55-58. *V, 1211-17. ri2 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. It is lack of knowledge which betrays men into misinterpretations of the phenomena of nature, and impels them to cringe before the gods as if they were the relentless enemies of mankind. We ob- serve the wondrous movements of the celestial bodies, and are in- capable of solving the problems of their regularity and persistence, and profound misgivings are awakened. Temptat enim dubiam me tit em rationis egesias, Ecquaenam fuerit mundi genitalis origo, Et simul ecquae sit finis, quoad moenia mundi Solliciti motus hunc possint /erre laborem, An divinitus aeterna donata salute Pei'petuo possifit aevi labentia tractu Immensi validas aevi contemnere viris. * The vivid lightnings and the noisy thunder terrify monarchs and people with the expectation of merited retribution. The tempestu- ous sea mocks the skill and defies the prayers of the mariner. The mysterious earthquake tumbles down the proudest works of man, while he, unable to account for these disasters on natural grounds, at- tributes them to the wrath of the godg.'' O genus infelix humanuvi, talia divis Cum tribuit facta atque iras adiunxit acerhas! Quantos turn gemitus ipsi sibi, quantaque nobis Volnera, quas lacrimas peperere minoribu nostris!^ A better philosophy, Lucretius believes, would emancipate human- ity from the grasp of such a foolish trepidation; and with this in view he devotes the entire sixth book of his poem to the consider- ation of the physical phenomena which appall the senses. When men, for the want of the true reason of things, assign fear-inducing operations of nature to the activity of the gods, Lucretius feels that they are stultifying both themselves and the deities whom they seek to propitiate. IV, 1211-17. «V, 1218-40. =»V, 1194-97. THE STOICS. 113 Nam bene qui didicere deos sectirum agere aevo?fi, Si iamen inter eamira?iiur qua ra/ione Quaeque geri possint, praesertim rebus in illis Quae supera caput aetheriis cernuntur ift oris, Rursus in antiquas re/eruntur religiofiis, Et doniinos acris adsciscunt, omnia posse Quos niiseri credunt, ignari quid queat esse. Quid fiequeat, finita potestas denique cuique Quanam sit ratione atque alte termitius haerens; Quo magis err antes caeca ratione feruntur. Quae nisi respuis ex animo iongeque remittis Dis indigna putare alienaque pads eorum, Delibata deum per te tibi fiumina sancta Saepe oberunt; non quo violari summa deum vis Possit, ut ex ira poenas peter e inbibat acris, Sed quia tute tibi placida cum pace quietos Constitues magnos irarum volvere fluctus, Nee delubra deum placido cum pectore adibis. Nee de cor pore quae sane to simulacra feruntur In mentes homitium divinae nuntia formae, Suseipere haec animi tranquilla pace valebis. Inde videre licet qualis iam vita sequatur. ' Almost the only occasion for scientific study which Lucretius would deem legitimate is the necessity of showing by this kind of research that the things which terrify man in the external universe have a natural rather than a divine origin. And this is the reason which Epicurus himself gives for his investigations in the realm of physics. Men can never realize even approximate happiness until their bondage to superstition has been broken, a result which an inquiry into the processes of nature will achieve. cl fiT|6cv T]p.ds ai Twv ^CT6(opci)v vito^lax TJv(0\Xovv Kal ai ircpl Oavdrov, ^'i\ irorc irpos T|fjids TJ Tt, €Ti T€ TO fii] KaTttvociv Tovs opous T«v aX-ytiSovcuv Kal T«V €iri6v|jii- «v, ovK dv 7rpocrc8e6(i€da 4>vi\(as ciXcktos t) 8id6€(ris.^ His followers did not disdain to engage in religious ceremonies, and Cicero declares that, while Epicureans were hostile to traditional religion in theory, they were in repeated instances distinctly super- stitious. Aovt ego Epicureos omnia sigilla venerantes; quamquam video non nuUis videri Epicurtwi, tie in offensionem Atheniensium caderet, verbis reliqtiisse deos, re sus/u/isse. ^ In the elaborate and truly poetic phrasing of the myth of Kybele Lucretius appears to lend some countenance to the popular religion. But he is not a sincere expositor of the theology of the people, but a satirist, parodying the mode of accommodating physical facts to the traditional mythology of the ancient Greeks adopted by the Stoics. This is apparent from the declaration at the end of the passage : 1 Diogenes Laertins, X, 10. 2 De N^ahira Deoruni, I, 85. We have trustworthy evidence that Cicero, who has so fully presented the Epicurean case against the Stoics, derived his materials directly from Philodemus. From the legible remnants of this teacher found in the Volutnina Herculaiumsia, it becomes quite apparent 'that Cicero took the body of 4»iXo8-njiOv ircpl €vo-cP€ias, and appropriated it to his own uses. Mayor {De Natttra Deonini. Introduction, pp. XLIII, LIII, ) has given a strong putting of the case, from which we abridge the following points of resemblance between Cicero and Philodemus: i. Particular citations from the writings ot opponents, such as Xen- ophon, Antisthenes, Aristotle, Chrysippus, Diogenes of Babylon. 2. Divisions of the two documents, [a) Criticism of popular mythology, ib) Criticism of the older philosophers, ic) Exposition of Epicurean theology. 3. Similar lists in Cicero and Philodemus of philosophers, following much the same order. These are arrange! in parallel columns by Diels DoxograpJii Graeci, pp. SS^So), and afford a striking confirmation of the theory that Cicero used Philodemus freely. Il8 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. Hie siquis mare Neptunum Cereremque voeare Constituit friiges et Baechi nomine almti Mavolt quavi laticis proprium prof err e vocamen, Concedamus ut hie terrarum dictitet orbem Esse deum matrem, dum vera re tamen ipse Religione ajiimum turpi contingere par cat. ^ The true animus of Lucretius is seen in the lines immediately pre- ceding, in which he proclaims the doctrine of the happiness and supreme repose of the gods, who rest in blissful security unmoved by /the prayers and miseries of mankind.'^ The absurd length to which the Stoics carried their method of allegorical interpretation, an am- ple illustration of which we have in Cicero's exposition of the sub- ject,' justified the warmth of Lucretius' satire. For with an elasticity, which to a man as earnest as Lucretius seemed insincerity, the Stoics in a derivative sense invested with the prerogatives of deity stars, years, months, seasons, air, earth, fire, water, fruits, wine, etc., then great heroes, and finally the very qualities which dignify spirit- ual beings, hope, truth, freedom, honor, virtue, justice, love, etc. With marvellous facility, therefore, Stoicism could assimilate to itself the conceptions of conventional polytheism. The Epicurean, on the other hand, was willing to give a poetic interpretation to the an- thropomorphic ideas of the people, and by reason of his assumption of innumerable gods, was*able to bring himself into sympathetic rela- tions with persons adhering, to the traditional cult, while at the same time he successfully undermined the whole scheme of the popular religion by his rationalistic explanations. Lucretius consents to call the earth the mother of the gods, and, as we have seen, permits the names Neptune, Ceres, Bacchus, to be employed for the sea, corn and wine. But h& emphatically asserts that Epicurus, whose philos- ophy emancipates men from superstition, is more deserving of divine honors than Ceres, Liber and Hercules, the last mentioned being especially revered by the Stoics.* Ill, 652-7. 211, 646-51. ^ De Natura Dcorum, 11, 40-44 ; 59-70. *V. 1-54. THE STOICS. I 19 The popular faith was supported by the Stoics on account of its practical value. It constituted in their judgment an effective check to the evil passions of humanity. But Epicureans regarded the tra- ditional religion as vicious in its influence upon character. The pernicious ethical results of the prevalent superstition touching the gods evoked the bitterest hostility of Lucretius. The cowardice, sycophancy and crime which the fear of deity engendered were suf- ficient, he felt, to condemn the accepted theology. With a passion- ate earnestness which is born of his enthusiasm for humanity he smites with terrific energy the false-hearted zeal which would destroy innocent life to appease the wrath of jealous gods. The tragic story of the sacrifice of Iphigeneia rouses him to a fury of denunciation.^ It is impossible not to sympathize with his hatred of a religion that could engender such wrongs. Impiety does not consist, as he de- clares, in rejecting but in respecting such a faith. Nee pietas ullast velalum saepe videi'i Vertier ad lapidem atque omnis accedere ad aras. Nee prociunhere humi prostratuni et pandere palmas Ante deum dehibra, nee aj'as sanguine multo Spargere quadrupedum, nee votis neetere vota, Sed mage paeaia posse omnia mente tueri. ^ And this sentiment Epicurus expresses with great clearness: do-ePT]s 8€ ovx 6 tovs twv ttoXXuv Ocovs dvaiptov, dW 6 rds twv iroXXwv 86|as 6eots irpoo-diTTwv.-^ It may not be amiss, however, to observe that the invocation of a popular deity at the beginning of his poem* by one who so fiercely assails conventional religion is an apparent incongruity, to explain which has taxed the ingenuity of the acutest critics. The ethical purpose of the Stoic was practically identical with that of the Epicurean. Consequently Lucretius finds little occasion of conflict with his chief philosophic rivals on this score. He does, 1 1, 80-101. 2V, II96-'20I. ' '^ Diogetu's Laertius, X. 123. ♦ I. 1-40. I20 CONTROVERSIAL ELEMENTS IN LUCRETIUS. however, arraign the followers of Zeno somewhat sharply on the ground of their doctrine of the apathy .of the wise man. Stoicism required the utter suppression of the emotions for the attainment of virtue. Ideally the wise man is devoid of anger, fear, envy, shame, care, pity; he is exempt from all passions, appetites, enthusiasms. Emotions are perturbations of mental equilibrium. If permitted to continue they finally develop into incurable diseases of the soul.* The wise man, therefore, must be simply emotionless. Virtue is apathy. «j>acrl Si Kal diraOfi €tvai tov a-o^ov, 8id to dvc'niTTajTOv.^ Right reason, which is another name for philosophy, will enable men to reach this estate. With such teaching Lucretius takes issue. Reason, he admits, will achieve much, but it will never altogether obliterate a man's distinctive characteristics. Sic homintun genus esi. Quamvis doctrina poliios Constituai pariter quosdam, tainen ilia reli7iquii Naturae cuiusque animi vestigia prima. Nee radicitus evelli mala posse putandumst, Quin proclivius hie iras decurrat ad aeris, Ille metu citius paulo temptetur, at ille Tertius accipiat quaedam cle??ientius aequo. Inque aliis rebus multis differe necessest Naturas hominum varias moresque sequacis; Quorum ego nunc nequeo caecas exponere causas. Nee r e per ir e figur alum tot nomina quot sunt Principiis, unde haec oritur variantia rerum.^ At the same time a life truly god-like is possible to the philos- opher. So taught P2picurus, the master. TavTtt ovv Kttl TO, TOVTOts s Oeos ev dvOpwirois. ovOcv "ydp eoiK€ 9vt]T(u ^b>a> ^uv dvOpcoTros kv dOavdrois d-yaOois.* ^ Diogenes Laertius^ VII, 1 1 2/^., 117. 3111,307-18. * Diogenes La ertins, X, 135. THE STOICS. 12 I So believed Lucretius the disciple. Illud in his rebus. videor firniare potesse. Usque adeo naiurai'utn vestigia liiKjui Parvola, quae nequeat ratio depellere nobis, Ut nil inpediat dignavi dis degere vitam. ' THE END. Ill, 319-22. YC 31499 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY BERKELEY Return to desk from which borrowed. This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. 7Jan'52WKA 90ec'5lLU i} ^^ <,%\X •55^^^ %-^VA5 .^'SlVi* '^ 20Apr'59A; REC'D LD •PR 17 1959 UBRARYUSE JUN 1 1 19S0 REC'D LD FEB 1 8 1952 REC'D t-D DEC 19 197f; RECCitt QIC? 13^9 LD 21-95TO-11/50 (2877816)476