Ex Libris C. K. OGDEX r See aho Catalogue at end of this Volume. VALUABLE LAW WORKS PUBLISHED BT STEVENS AND SONS (LATE STEVENS AND NORTON), 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. MAttr.TT 7 ised itutes Esq., f 8ro. ady.) 368. ar-at- ady.) rks itable with [nner Price idy.) mont, ctorj, lerons citorf js. Twelfth Mention. iZmo. 1878. Price 12s. 6d. cloth. (Just ready.) Smith's (Josiah W,) Manual of Common Law; for Prac- titioners and Students. Comprising the Fundamental Principles and the Points most usally occurring in Daily Life and Practice. By JOSIAH W. SMITH, B.C.L., Q.C., Judge of County Courts. Eighth Edition. 12mo. 1878. Price 14s. cloth. (Just ready.) All Standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindingt. %* See also Catalogue at end of this Volume. STEVENS AND SONS, 119, CHANCERY LANE, W.C. Wilson's Supreme Court of Judicature Acts, Apellate Jurisdiction Act, 1876, Rules of Court and Forms, with other Acts, Orders, Rules, and Regulations relating to the Supreme Court of Justice, with Practical Notes. Second Edition. By ARTHUR WILSON, of the Inner Temple, Barrister-at-Law. Assisted by HARRY GREENWOOD, of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister-at-Law, and JOHN BIDDLE, of the Master of the Rolls Chambers. Royal 12mo. 1878. Price 18s. cloth (or limp leather for the pocket. Price 22s. 6d.) (Now ready.) *" A Large Paper Edition of the above (for Marginal Notes), Royal 8vo. Price 11. 5s. cloth (calf or limp leather, price 30s.) (Now ready.) Sebastian on the Law of Trade Marks, The Law of Trade Marks and their Registration, and matters connected therewith, including a chapter on Goodwill. Together with Appendices containing Precedents of Injunctions, &c.; The Trade Marks Registration Acts, 18757, and the Rules and Instructions there- under; the Merchandise Marks Act, 1862, and other Statutory enactments; The United States Statute, 1870, the Treaty with the United States, 1877; and the New Rules and Instructions February, 1878, With a copious Index. By LEWIS BOYD SEBASTIAN, B.C.L., M.A., of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Demy 8vo. 1878. Price 14s. cloth. (Justieady.) Russell's Treatise on the Duty and Power of an Arbitrator, and the Law of Submissions and Awards ; with an Appendix of Forms and of the Sta- tutes relating to Arbitration. By FRANCIS RUSSELL, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Fifth Edition. Royal Bvo. 1878. Price II. 16s. cloth. (Just ready.) Millar's Bills of Sale. A Treatise on Bills of Sale, with an Appendix containing the Acts for the Registration of Bills of Sale, Precedents, &c. (Being the Fourth Edition of Millar and Collier's " Treatise on Bills of Sale.") By F. C. J. MILLAR, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 12mo. 1877. Price 12s. cloth. (Just ready.) Middleton's Settled Estates Act, 1877, with Introduction, Notes, Forms, and Summary of Practice. By JAMES W. MIDDLETON, B.A., Barrister-at-Law. 12mo. 1878. Price 3s. 6d. cloth. Theobald on Wills A Concise Treatise on the Construction of Wills, with Table of Cases and full Index. By H. S. THEOBALD, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, and Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford. Demy Bvo. 1876. Price 11. cloth. "This is a book of great ability and value. It bears on every page traces of care and sound judgment. It is certain to prove of great practical usefulness, for it supplies a want which was beginning to be distinctly felt." Solicitors' Journal, February 24, 1877. Russell's Treatise on Crimes and Misdemeanours. Fifth Edition. By SAMUEL PRENTICE, Esq., one of Her Majesty's Counsel. 3 vols. Royal 8vo. 1877. Price 51. 15s. 6d. cloth. " We may safely assert that the fifth edition of ' Russell on Crimes' has, under the careful hand of Mr. Prentice, fully reached the standard attained to by the preceding editions." Law Journal, January 27, 1877. "No more trustworthy authority, or more exhaustive expositor than 'Russell' can be consulted," Law Magazine, February, 1877. "We are amazed at the patience, industry and skill which are exhibited in the collection and arrangement of all this mass of learning." The Timet, Uecember 26, 1876. Smith's Mercantile Law. A Compendium of Mercantile Law. By the late JOHN WILLIAM SMITH, Esq. Ninth Edition. By G. M. DO WDESWELL, of the Inner Temple, Esq., one of Her Majesty's Counsel. Royal 8vo. 1877. Price 11. l&s. cloth. Arnould on the Law of Marine Insurance. Fifth Edition. By DAVID MACLACHLAN, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 2 *ofc. Royal 8vo. 1877. Price 31. cloth. Palmer's Company Precedents. Conveyancing and other Forms and Precedents relating to Companies incorporated under the Companies Acts, 1862 and 1867. Arranged as follows: Agreements, Memoranda of Association, Articles of Association, Resolutions, Notices, Certificates, Provisional Orders of Board of Trade, Debentures, Reconitruction, Amalgamation, Petitions, Orders. With Copious Notes. By FRANCIS BEA.UFORT PALMER, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Demy 8vo. 1877. Price 11. 5s. cloth. ' i'o those concerned in getting up companies, the assistance given by Mr. Palmer must be very valuable, because he does uot confine himself to bare precedents, but by intelligent and learned commentaiy lights up, as it were, each step that he takes. There is an elaborate index, and the worit is one which must commend itself to the profession." Late Times, June 9, 1877. ' \* AU Standard Law Workt are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings. ON UNIVERSAL PUBLIC LAW, BY GEOKGE BOWYEK, ESQ., M,P,, D.C.L, BARRISTER-AT-LAW, AUTHOR OF "COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF ENGLAND,' " COMMENTARIES ON THE MODERN CIVIL LAW," " READINGS BEFORE THE HONOURABLE SOCIETY OF THE MIDDLE TEMPLE," ETC. LONDON : V. & R. STEVENS AND G. S. NORTON, ILato Ijoofesrllrrs anti Uutltsfirrs, 26, BELL YARD, LINCOLN'S INN. JAMES RIDGWAY, 169, PICCADILLY. LONDON: PlttMID UV C. ROWORTH AND SONS, BJLL YARD, TEMPLE BAR. TO THE CLEE&Y AND PEOPLE OF D U N D A L K, AMONG WHOM THE CONTENTS OF THE FOLLOWING PAGES WEBB PLANNED AND PARTLY WRITTEN, Otommentarteg ARE, WITH FEELINGS OF MOST SINCERE RESPECT, GRATITUDE AND ATTACHMENT, DEDICATED AND INSCRIBED. EXPLANATION REFERENCES TO THE CORPUS JURIS CIVILIS. The Pandects are indicated by the letters ff. The letter L. means Law, and the mark means Section of the Law. The words after the letters ff. give the rubric or heading of the title or chapter. Thus for instance, L. 49, 1, ff. De Act. Empt. signifies Law 49, parag. 1, in the Pandects: title, De Actione Empti. To find the passage referred to, look in the table of contents or headings, which is in every edition of the Pandects, alphabetically arranged. You will there find the page where the particular title is. Then the number of the law will show you the particular law that you seek. The references to the headings are usually abbreviated thus : De hered. instit. for De heredibus instituendis. But any one can readily find what title the abbreviations indicate, by running his eye down the index or table of headings of the titles in the Pandects ; and then the number in the table shows the page. This is the most usual mode of referring to the Pandects, and that which I have followed. There are other ways of referring to the Pandects. Some writers give the first words of the law which they cite. Another mode of reference is thus : D. dejure dotium, L. profectitia, si pater, meaning Digest (which is the same as the Pandects), title Dejure Dotium, the law commencing with the word profectitia, and the paragraph commencing with the words si pater. In some writers the letters Pand. are used instead of ff., or D., or Dig., all of which signify Justinian's Pandects. Sometimes the letter or letters indicating the Pandects are placed last thus: L. profectitia, si pater, D. Dejure Dot. Or the numbers of the law and paragraph are given instead of their initial words thus : L. 5, G, Dejure Dotium. The law cited is sometimes indicated by the letters Fr. instead of L. It is not unusual to cite the Pandects by the numbers of the book, title, law, and paragraph thus : D. (or Pand. or ff.) 25. 3. 5. 6., or Lib. 25. tit. 3, L. 5, 6. The three books in the Pandects, Be Legatis et Fideicomnrissis, are cited by their numbers and their heading. THE CODE. The Code of Justinian is cited in the same way as the Pandects and indicated by the letters Cod. or C. And some writers use the letters Constit.(Constilutio) instead of L. b VI EXPLANATION OF REFERENCES. THE INSTITUTES. Justinian's Institutes are indicated by the letters Inst. or Instit. or I. They are cited by the number of the paragraph, followed by the rubric or heading of the title thus : 3, Inst. De Nuptiis. The title is easily found by referring to the table of rubrics. Sometimes the reference is made^by the numbers of the paragraph, book, or title thus : 3, Inst 1. 10. The letters princ.,pr. or princip. indicate the commencing paragraph of a title, as the numbering commences with the second. The Novels, or later Constitutions in the Corpus Juris, are indicated by the words Nov. or Novel. GaOTIUS AND PUFENDORF. Grotius and Pufendorf are cited from Barbeyrac's translations, because those trans- lations are the books generally in use ; and his notes on both, and his references from Grotius to Pufendorf, make the two works together one Corpus of the Law of Nations which has not yet been equalled in extent, learning, richness of illustration, and acu- men. Like Co. Litt. these translations have superseded the original for practical and scientific purposes. So PufendorPs little book De Officio Hominis el Civis is cited from Barbeyrac's translation, on account of his notes and references, which add much to its value. TABLE OF CONTENTS, CHAPTER I. INTRODUCTION ........... Page 1 CHAPTER II. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW ..... 14 CHAPTER III. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW ....... .22 CHAPTER IV. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY NATURAL LAW ............. 32 CHAPTER V. THE Two BRANCHES OF NATURAL LAW PRIMARY AND SECONDARY FURTHER CONSIDERED ACCORDING TO THE JURISTS ....... 44 CHAPTER VI. GENERAL PLAN AND NATURE OF HUMAN SOCIETY ON THE FOUNDATION OF THE Two PRIMARY LAWS .......... 52 CHAPTER VII. ON THE NATURE AND SPIRIT OF LAWS. IMMUTABLE LAWS .... 63 CHAPTER VIII. ON THE NATURE AND SPIRIT OF LAWS. OF ARBITRARY OR POSITIVE LAWS, AND THE LEGISLATIVE POWER ......... 79 CHAPTER IX. ON THE NATURE AND SPIRIT OF LAWS. OF ARBITRARY OR POSITIVE LAWS . 86 CHAPTER X. THE NATURE AND SPIRIT OF L\ws. OF ARBITRARY OR POSITIVE LAWS . 91 CHAPTER XL ON THE NATURE AND SPIRIT OF LAWS. REFLECTIONS ON THE SCIENTIFIC Use AND DIVERSITIES OF NATURAL AND ARBITRARY LAWS .... 101 Vlll CONTENTS. CHAPTER XII. THE NATURE OF PUBLIC LAW, TEMPORAL AND SPIRITUAL . . Page 107 CHAPTER XIII. REFLECTIONS ON THE END OF HUMAN SOCIETY AND THE RELATIVE USES OF THE SPIRITRAL AND TEMPORAL LAWS. THE DIVISION OF MANKIND INTO STATES AND NATIONS. LEGAL CHARACTER OF THAT INSTITUTION. CONSEQUENCES WITH RE- FERENCE. TO POLITICS AND ECONOMIC SCIENCE .... 118 CHAPTER XIV. THE DIVISION OF THE WORLD INTO STATES AND NATIONS CONSIDERED WITH REFERENCE TO ECCLESIASTICAL PUBLIC LAW. The Anglican Church The Greek (separated) Church The Roman Catholic Church Its Construction Superiority and Obedience, or Subordination The Hierarchies of Order and Jurisdiction The Four Elements of Human Society Relation of Society to Ecclesiastical Public Law Ecclesiastical Public Law independent of the Divisions of the World into Civil States But that Division not neglected by Eccle- siastical Public Law Contact of Ecclesiastical Public Law with the Political Divisions of the Earth, and Temporal Laws How it operates with them . . 127 CHAPTER XV. OF THE DIVERSITY OF LAWS AND POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS IN DIFFERENT COUNTRIES, AND OF THE CONFLICT OF LAWS. Examination of the Diversity of Municipal Laws Diversity of Forms of Govern- ment Dispute as to the best Form of Government Difference of Opinions Abso- lute Monarchy Opinion of Mariana and St. Thomas Aquinas Doctrine of the Deposition of Tyrants Divine Right of Kings Indivisibility of the Jus Majestatis Other Classes of arbitrary Matters Analogies between the Roman and the Hindu and Muhammadan Laws The Conflict of Laws First Principles The Comity of Nations, and the Spirit of the Conflict of Laws ..." 138 CHAPTER XVI. THE CONFLICT OF LAWS. Personal Laws as contradistinguished from Territorial Laws Laws of British India Concurrent Systems of Jurisprudence Municipal Conflict of Laws General Rules regarding the Conflict of Laws Real and Personal Statutes The Comity of Na- tions Lex Loci Rei Sitae Domicil Rule as to Movables Jurisprudence as to Personal Statutes Status Conflict of Laws regarding Marriage, and its Conse- quences Divorce Effects of Marriage as to Property Conflict of Laws regarding the Jurisdiction of Courts and Legal Remedies Foreigners . . . 156 CHAPTER XVII. OF THE CONFLICT OF LAWS REGARDING CRIMES AND OFFENCES. EXTRADITION. REFUGEES. GENERAL REFLECTIONS ON THE CONFLICT OF LAWS. . , 179 CONTENTS. IX CHAPTER XVIII. OF THE LEGAL ORIGIN AND NATURE OF CIVIL SOCIETIES OR STATES. The Three Parts or Orders of Human Society Matters of Public and of Private Law Detail of the Matters of Public Law, and Construction of Civil Society Neces- sity of Civil Government, and its Divine Right The Doctrine of the Social Com- pact Doctrine of Hooker, Blackstone, Pufendorf, Hobbes, Grotius, Zallinger, Locke, and Barbeyrac The true Origin of Civil Societies Savigny's Doctrine on the Sub- ject . . . . . . . . Page 194 CHAPTER XIX. OF THE SOVEREIGN POWER IN CIVIL SOCIETY OR STATES. The Civil Power Principle of Subordination Authority of a Majority Perfect and imperfect Societies Necessity of the governing Power in Civil Societies Analysis of the Civil Power by Grotius The Sovereign Power Doctrine of the Sovereignty of the People . . . . . . . .206 CHAPTER XX. OF THE PARTS OR BRANCHES OF THE SOVEREIGN POWER. The Three Parts of the Civil Power Jura Majestatis Merum et Miitum Imperium and Merum Imperium Jurisdiction The Legislative Power Place and Effect of Legislation in the Formation of Municipal Law Customary Law Political and Legal Character of the Legislative Power The Executive Power Power of inflict- ing Punishments Its Nature and Objects Fundamental Principles of Criminal Law Power of Pardoning The Appointment of Magistrates and Officers, and their Uses and Functions Right of War and Peace Negociations with Foreign States Power of assembling and arming Forces Revenue Jus Eminens and Do- minium Eminens True Foundation of the Right of Taxation The Interference of the State with Private Property for the Public Use Equality of Taxation re- quired. ......... 215 CHAPTER XXI. OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. Legal Nature and Necessity of the Judicial Power Private War Cases in which the Use of Force by Private Individuals is still lawful in Civil Society Right of Self- defence Jurisdiction Notio Proper or ordinary, and delegated Jurisdiction Civil and Criminal Jurisdiction Distinction between Public and Private Wrongs Effect of Judicial Decisions Res judicata Degrees of Jurisdiction and Appeals. . 231 CHAPTER XXII. THE CONNEXION o? THE JURA MAJESTATIS WITH EACH OTHER. Difficulties arising from the Union of equal Powers by a Convention only Union by means of Civil Government Historical Illustrations Chief Defect of several Fe- deral Constitutions The United States of America Pufendorf 's Argument regarding the Division of the Jura Majestatis or Parts of the Sovereign Power Necessity of X CONTENTS. Unity in the Sovereign Power Historical Illustrations The same Proposition de- monstrated Principles on which the Sovereign Power may be divided Consti- tutional Balance of Power Insufficiency of Laws alone to preserve it . Page 239 CHAPTER XXIII. THE FORMS OF CIVIL GOVERNMENTS. REGULAR STATES OR GOVERNMENTS. REGULAR REPUBLICS. The Constitution of a State Equality of Sovereign States The Place of Political Constitutions in the Scheme of Universal Human Society Character of Organic Laws of States General Classification of P'orms of Government Regular or Simple States or Governments Democracy Aristocracy Monarchy Oligarchy Causes of peculiar Municipal Institutions The Republican Form of Polity Nature of a Republic Mixed Governments True Definition of a Republic The Representa- tion of the People examined By what Constituency the Representatives should be chosen Universal Suffrage considered Constituent Assemblies and Conventions Authority of a Majority Secret Voting or Vote by Ballot Indirect Election. 247 CHAPTER XXIV. OF REGULAR STATES. SIMPLE OR REGULAR MONARCHY. HEREDITARY AND ELECTIVE MONARCHY. Monarchy Tyranny Limited Monarchy of two sorts Montesquieu's Distinction between Monarchy and Despotism General Principles of Monarchical Government Effect of intermediate Powers Influence of the Church Absolute Power and limited Power The different sorts of Laws that modify the Royal Authority Pro- mises and Oaths of Sovereigns Distinction between Sovereign and Absolute Power The Commissary Clause or Clause of Forfeiture The two Classes of Fundamental Laws limiting the Royal Authority Power to change Fundamental Laws and the Constitution of a State In what Sense an Absolute Monarch is above the Law Hereditary and Elective Monarchy considered Agnatic and Cognatic Succession The Salic Law Different Modes of Election Interregnum Death of a heredi- tary King, leaving his Widow with Child Precedents in History . . 264 CHAPTER XXV. ON MIXED GOVERNMENTS, AND THE DIVISION OF THE SOVEREIGN POWER AND THE THREE GREAT DEPARTMENTS OF GOVERNMENT. Nature of irregular or mixed Governments Division of the Sovereign Power Ba- lance of Powers in a State How the Government of the United States of America is a limited and mixed Government Distinction between the Distribution of Powers and the mere Division of Departments Reasons of the Division of Departments, and of the Distribution of Powers -Principles of mixed Governments The Utility of those Governments in particular Cases Examination of the Nature of Liberty, Natural and Civil Definition of Liberty by Florentinus Liberty considered with reference to its Degree or Extent Use of the Balance of Powers with reference to Liberty Political Liberty Principles on which mixed Governments are constructed Theory of Montesquieu Principles of Blackstone and Story How the Division of the Three Powers of Government is rendered consistent with the Unity of Go- vernment Doctrine of Madison on this Subject Difficulty of preventing the En- CONTENTS. XI croachments of the Three Powers on each other Government constructed on the Principle of combining Monarchy, Aristocracy and Democracy The Three Ingre- dients of this sort of Government examined Maxim that the King can do no wrong The hereditary Peerage Privileges of the Peers Impeachments The De- mocratic Part of a mixed Constitution ..... Page 282 CHAPTER XXVI. THE DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, AND THE MEANS OF MAINTAINING THAT BALANCE. General Principles exemplified by English and American Constitutional Law Com- parison of the Three Branches of Government with reference to their relative Strength and means of Self-protection Preponderating Power of the Legislative Branch, and difficulty of restraining it Weakness of the Judicial Power Appeals to the People in Convention suggested as a Remedy against the Encroachments of the Legis- lative Power Inconveniences and insufficiency of this Remedy The Constitutional Balance of Power explained Doctrines of Madison, Story and Blackstone Con- sideration of the Subject with reference to each of the Three Branches of Govern- ment The Legislature Use and Importance of dividing this Department The Negative of the President of the United States Comparison of this Provision with the Legislative Prerogative of the Crown in England Double Legislative Assemblies considered and compared with a single Assembly Duration of Representative As- semblies Executive Department Its Unity The Civil List Responsibility of Ministers The Judicial Department Permanency of the Judges Mode of appoint- ing them Connexion of the Judicial with the Executive and Legislative Depart- ments Trial by Jury ....... 303 CHAPTER XXVII. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. Provinces Colonies and Colonial Policy States united by having one King in com- mon States joined by Confederation Mode of deciding Questions among Con- federates Dissolution of Confederations Mixed Federal States exemplified by the Constitution of the United States of America. , 325 CHAPTER XXVIII. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. Double Aspect of the Law of Things Distinction between the Public and Private Law of Things The Four Classes of Things not Private, according to Justinian Domat's general View of the Public Law of Things Things common to all Men Common Right over Rivers The Common Rights of Mankind over the High Seas, and the Freedom of the Seas Appropriation of Parts of the Sea Jurisdiction over Ships, and Right of Search Public Things Rivers, Ports, Shores of the Sea, and Banks of Rivers Territories of a State Uninhabited and partly inhabited Countries and Land Hunting Ground of Savage Tribes Effect of the Change of the Course of Rivers which are Boundaries Law regarding Alluvion or Alluvial Accretions Lakes Acquisition of Territories by Occupancy Analysis of the Property of a Nation Public Property Imposts and Taxes Dominium eminens Res universi- tatis The Property of Bodies Corporate Res nullius Ecclesiastical Things Conclusion. ...... ... 347 3, STONE BUILDINGS, LINCOLN'S INN, w.c., October, 1876. DEAR SIR GEORGE BOWYER, I have now read with great interest your valuable work, which might well have been styled an introduction to the effectual reform of the Law of England. To me it is a great pleasure, perhaps a selfish one, to find an original thinker with views so nearly corresponding to my own. I have long thought the placing of the legal estate in a mortgagee one of the most crying evils of our system (p. 39). I quite agree that grants and contracts ought to do all that is wanted (p. 50). I would abolish all terms of years in trustees (p. 51). I would have a register of deeds, not of title (p. 61), and have them printed (p. 63) with separate registers for hypothecs and leases. I sincerely hope that under your leadership, reforms which I have long desired and done my best to advocate, though with little effect, may ultimately be carried through. Believe me, Dear Sir George Bowyer, Yours faithfully, JOSHUA WILLIAMS. COMMENTARIES UNIVERSAL PUBLIC LAW. CHAPTER I. INTRODUCTION. THOSE who have thoughtfully observed the events of our own time, especially during the last six years, may apprehend, not without some show of reason, that in a great part of the world permanent govern- ment on any fixed principles of Public Law is becoming extremely difficult, if not impossible. On the conclusion of the Treaty of Vienna, it seemed strange that the French Revolution and the conquests of Napoleon should have produced such small tangible results. One single new dynasty, that of Sweden, remained ; the constitution of Germany was remodelled ; and two republics were extinguished. But a transition in the history of Europe had commenced. The minds of men had been unsettled by a period of anarchy denying everything and spurning the very idea of obedience ; and then came a time of military despotism, the very type of power, the majestas of government unmitigated by any checks or restraints. We see in our time a reproduction of those phenomena, but with very peculiar and curious circumstances. The revolution which overthrew the house of Orleans was effected not so much by its own power as by the unsoundness of the system which it destroyed. That revolution was grounded on no principle and on no definite want; consequently, the results came by a sort of chance. The very leaders of the movement were unprepared to com- mence any new system, because they were not at the head of any party in the country contending for a practical object, such as the 2 INTRODUCTION. redress of a given grievance, or the attainment of some specific improvement in the economy or government of the nation. Paris and France fell into the hands of a successful orator and a knot of worth- less adventurers; and then commenced a strange caricature upon statesmanship, showing very strikingly with how little wisdom a great nation can be governed, even during a time of the highest civilization. In this uncertain state, when France had accidentally got a republic which she did not want, and no one could say for what purpose the monarchy had been overturned, it was imagined that in the midst of the despotism of the Provisional Government, the nation was to determine its future Civil Polity, by means of a Sovereign Constituent Assembly chosen by universal suffrage. The revolution itself being without any practical public object, it followed that the Constituent Assembly had no basis of Public Law to work upon. It had to invent everything; not only to erect a new edifice, but to discover a new style of architecture, and new purposes or uses for the building, pointed out by no previous want. The result was an absurdity. Whereas all statesmen and public lawyers had thought that a republic should be cunningly devised so as to afford checks and counterpoises to the different powers of government, keeping them in their right places and preventing all irregular action, it was on the contrary determined that the nation should be governed on an opposite principle. The theory was propounded, that, to prevent any violence or convulsion, all resistance or restraint must be removed. The nation was to be treated like a dangerous lunatic, who is placed at liberty in a room covered with soft cushions, where he may give vent to every impulse without injury. But we will not enter into a criticism of that absurd creation of Monsieur de Lamartine and his colleagues. Our object must be to consider the nature of the means by which the Republic was erected, namely, the Constituent Assembly. When these events took place, a disposition had been manifested by the governments of Italy and Germany to accord what are called liberal institutions to their subjects. A good deal of enthusiasm had been raised. Perhaps neither the sovereigns nor the subjects saw very clearly what results they were coming to. The principles of Public Law were little understood, and men did not clearly see what practical objects they themselves had in view, or how these were to benefit the community. Liberty was worshipped as an unknown goddess, or a beautiful myth, to which every man attached whatever ideas were most agreeable to his wishes or his fancy. In short, nothing could be more different from the material epochs of our own constitutional history, in which we always see clearly defined objects INTRODUCTION. o contended for, and definite principles of Public Law asserted and disputed on either side. One important characteristic of that time was, that there existed comparatively little commanding talent on the continent of Europe. There was a want of those great and powerful minds which seem to control the course of human events. In Italy especially, public opinion was deified. No statesman had the power to direct public opinion ; and those who seemed to lead it, such as Gioberti, were in reality only its organs and its flatterers. And indeed, the fact that so shallow and vague a writer obtained a very great share of popularity and power, in itself characterises the times. Under this state of circumstances, almost every country on the continent fell into a more or less servile imitation of France. The mob of the capital assumed supreme authority over the nation, and decreed that their sovereign had ceased to reign. Louis Philippe had laid it down that no king could continue on the throne who had fired on his people; but the converse of that proposition has been established by subsequent experience. The only question everywhere was, whether the troops would act, and could act effectually ? Day by day it was solemnly announced to the world, that tranquillity reigns in this or that capital, which meant that the city was in the possession of the mob and the sovereign a fugitive. Then was the period of Provisional Governments, and, in imitation of France, a general cry for Constituent Assemblies followed. The king of Sardinia had given free institutions to his own subjects, and had marched to assist the Lombard insurrection. The spirit of servile imitation was so strong, that it was determined by the Piedmontese Par- liament that, on the successful termination of the invasion, a Consti- tuent Assembly, elected by universal suffrage by Piedmont and Lom- bardy, should determine the future constitution of both. It is evident that if this had been effected, the only resource of the king would have been to rely on his victorious army against the Republic created in the very bosom of his monarchy. But it seemed an established prin- ciple of Public Law that no form of civil polity, however well adapted to the purposes of government, could be lawful unless it had been invented and agreed to by a Constituent Assembly. In the midst of all this confusion an attempt was made in Germany and in Italy to solve the difficult problem of a federal democratic con- stitution ; but, here again, instead of resorting to America, where it had been already tried instead of going to Kent and Story and the Federalist, they fell into a servile imitation of the French method of making constitutions, by means of provisional governments and con- stituent assemblies. From this, however, posterity may derive some u2 4 INTRODUCTION. benefit (if it be true that nations learn by experience), for the utter ab- surdity of those assemblies has been established by the experiments tried within the last few years all over Europe. But to this subject I shall return. Much may be learned by a careful study of events since the year 1848, for they present an extraordinary variety of political and legal phenomena. Yet we must admit that the attempts made during the period in question to establish constitutions, wherein, as Fortescue says, the sovereign power is restrained by political laws, 8 were at- tended by many unfavourable circumstances. And, accordingly, only two of those constitutions those of Sardinia and Hanover survive. The former was probably saved by the failure of the two invasions of Lombardy, and by the good sense with \vhich the government declined to join the Italian constituent assembly. Among the unfavourable circumstances of the times, none was more powerful than the existence of the Socialist and Red Republican party, to whom the French Revolution of 1848 had given great power and activity. We will not attempt any analysis of the different opinions comprehended within those general denominations ; suffice it to say, that they are either hostile to or incompatible with the existence of any government, and strike at the very root of the Secondary Natural Law ; but they are recommended to the discontented multitude, who, as Hooker observes " Know the manifold defects whereunto every kind of regiment is subject; but the secret lets and difficulties, which in public proceedings are innumerable and inevitable, they have not ordinarily the judgment to consider." 6 These opinions have no doubt been em- braced by considerable bodies of men on the Continent, and are pro- pagated with much zeal and ability by their leaders. Even in this country the tenets of Socialism are not unknown, and some of the peculiar terms and phrases, at least, of the sect, have been adopted by well-meaning persons, who, perhaps, do not see the danger of being led further by notions which are adorned with a fair show of Christian philanthropy. That the existence of the Socialist party in Europe is, and must be, more and more one of the chief difficulties of civil government, can scarcely be doubted. That party strives for a total alteration of civil society, and the other institutions from whence Secondary Natural Law arises, and for the subversion of any government not based on certain impracticable doctrines. And all this is clothed with pretences of philanthropy, and the greater welfare of the greatest number, a Fortesc. de Laud. chap. 9. b Hooker, Eccles. Polit. book 1, 1. INTRODUCTION. 5 highly attractive to the minds of many, especially the large classes, who, in all countries and at all times, are more or less suffering. The effect of all these things on the minds of the better educated classes those who have property, and whose welfare depends on the stability of laws and civil power is very important. They feel the want of that certainty of duration, without which municipal govern- ment cannot be said to fulfil adequately the very first objects of its in- stitution. They desiderate above all things a powerful government a sovereign power, able at all times to protect them. And thus there is now, among those who are called the party of order on the Continent, a tendency, more or less strong, towards despotism. Those who are in possession of power feel naturally loath to part with it : and so it comes to pass, that the distinctive feature of the system prevailing in the greater part of Europe is, government by means of standing armies, with a ready appeal to Martial Law, or what is technically called the state of siege. Acts of state are no longer judged according to the ordinary rules of Public Law. Policy, real or supposed or pretended, overrides Law. A coup-d'etat is no longer held anything very extraordinary. Salus populi suprema lex esto, seems to have become an ordinary maxim of government, rather than an exceptional principle, to be kept among the arcana of state for rare cases of emergency. The state of those affairs which appertain to the international branch of Public Law has of late years been equally remarkable. We have seen diplomacy turned to purposes beyond the recognized scope of diplomatic functions involving something very like what has been called political propagandisrn, and dealings with parties or factions for the purpose of producing political changes in the internal government of countries. We have seen a revolutionary government in Italy suppressed by a foreign invasion, unauthorized by any treaty, or by any request of the lawful Sovereign. And then the invading power has been recommended and pressed not to permit that Sovereign to return to his dominions, except under conditions regarding the internal management of his government and the exercise of his undoubted prerogative. Of the policy of these things I say nothing ; I only look at and refer to them as facts material with reference to the present practice of International Law. The inference drawn by some from all the various circumstances referred to and the present aspect of public affairs is, that Public Law must now be treated as a thing obsolete and cast aside by the common consent of European statesmen. And it may indeed seem, that in our times those who are entrusted with government in the greater part of 6 INTRODUCTION. Europe, can scarcely be expected to do more than meet, by energetic action and commanding force, the dangers or difficulties which from time to time arise ; and that vigilance and power must take the place of law, and even of justice. And so the uncertainty of governments renders the practice of International Law, in many cases, subordinate to state craft. But this notion, which would throw back European civilization in one of its highest branches for many centuries, seems to me both shallow and unsound. The reader will remember that fine passage in Grotius, where he laments the readiness with which nations went to war on the smallest pretences, and the lawless manner in which they carried it on when once the sword was unsheathed. He does not draw the conclusion from thence, that, because, as Cicero says, Silent leges inter arma, because nations seemed bent upon referring everything to the tribunal offeree and blood, therefore the jus gentium was a mere dream or a philosophical hypothesis, useless to practical men. On the contrary, he tells us that this, which he calls horrible barbarism, was one of his chief inducements to write his glorious book on the Laws of War and Peace. And of all times, perhaps, in modern history, the present is that in which especially it behoves thoughtful men to investigate the science of Public Law. When society and property, and that due subordina- tion of persons without which neither can exist, are perseveringly and ingeniously attacked, it becomes important to know scientifically the grounds and reasons of those institutions from whence spring the great branches of Secondary Natural Law, and to see the consequences to which they lead. When the insecurity of human government in a great part of the civilized world seems to make political institutions as changeable as the scenes of a theatre, and drives men to throw themselves into the arms of any power that appears to promise pro- tection from perpetual revolutions, it is surely interesting and useful to study the laws on which the different forms of political society are constructed, and the reasons of those laws. And when the mutability of governments and constitutions, and the sense of danger in most countries felt, renders the practice of International Law irregular and uncertain ; then especially the grounds of that law and the legal prin- ciples on which the relations of different human societies with each other should be regulated, ought to be learned and studiously con- sidered. And, indeed, as in a time of general sickness the cultivation of medicine is particularly important, so at a period of political dis- tempers it is most useful to investigate those principles whereby they may be cured or prevented. c Grot, de Jur. Belli et Pads Proem. 29, 30. INTRODUCTION. 7 Another circumstance of the present time renders the study of Public Law especially important. Many things concur to show that European society is in a state of transition. Opinions are singularly undefined and variable. And yet there are forces arrayed against each other so powerfully, that it is difficult to say which will in the end prevail. A multitude of experiments in government have been tried within the short space of three years, of which very few can be said to have met with any success whatever. Aristocratic institutions, which have hitherto been so great an element of stability, by support- ing the executive and influencing the democracy, are everywhere giving way or perishing. In France, the aristocracy, which might have been like piles driven into a quicksand, has succumbed to the operation of a despotic and luxurious court an emigration a military tyranny, and three revolutions. The spirit of hostility to aristocracy has vibrated from thence throughout Europe. The Roman Catholic Church alone presents an extraordinary spectacle of the stability denied to human institutions. Her form of polity is the most ancient in the world. The Venetian republic boasted the singu- lar honour of a constitution which had lasted a thousand years ; but Venice has perished while the constitution of the Church remains intact and vigorous, after the lapse of eighteen centuries, during which it has undergone no organic change. Its divine origin and authority, and the truth of the faith which it teaches, sufficiently account for this immunity from the common lot of other institutions. We are here to consider only its effect upon political communities, regarding its institutions and laws as part of the Public Law of Europe. Giving the sanction of religious teaching to morals and natural law, and the principle of authority and obedience; exercising a strong influence over intellectual civilization and all the relations of life, and presenting to the eyes of men a regular society, governed by a complete system of machinery, complicated yet simple, and tried by the experience of ages, the Church must be the strongest support to human government. And belonging exclusively to no one country, but everywhere formed in the same mould, regulated by the same laws, and imbued with the same principles, the Church must also be the strongest bond of union common to the whole human family on earth, and the universal vincu- lum of human society. The Church was not intended to supersede the civil magistrate and temporal government : each has its proper province in the system whereby the world is governed : but if every human government were extinguished, the Church would supply a form of external polity capable at least of keeping human society from dissolution and ruin. The operation of this great power upon the present state of man- 8 INTRODUCTION. kind is one of the most important problems of Politics and Public Law. I however now only refer to it in order to show fully that which has been described as a state of transition, in which it seems to be the only permanent element, while all the rest is constantly changing and moving on to some distant unknown point. What I have said applies chiefly to foreign countries; for a variety of causes have rendered the civil polity of this kingdom the most striking exception to that constant series of fundamental changes which characterize the legal and political history of our times. Yet when we consider how the events and institutions of one country act more and more on those of others, we must feel how important the various matters to which we have referred must be for ourselves, even where their more immediate bearing is on other nations. And changes in foreign states, but especially in France, naturally suggest speculations and opinions regarding laws and institutions here, raising the hopes and fears, and unsettling the minds of men. Hence it becomes in our times more and more useful for English lawyers and statesmen, and others engaged in public affairs, to make themselves acquainted with the principles and reasons on which human society, with its innumerable consequences, are based. The whole system of the external government of mankind depends on those principles and reasons. The very institution of property, from whence springs the greater part of private law, is based upon them. And so Hermogenianus, in the Pandects, d refers to one origin (the Jus Gen- tium) a variety of things, some appertaining to public and others to private law, such as the distinction of men into nations, the founda- tion of kingdoms, the limitation of boundaries to lands, dealings between men, contracts, and obligations. What is called the progress of laws and institutions must be go- verned by the reasons and principles to which I have referred, or it will violate some law of the immutable class and produce evil. And at a time like the present, when civil government seems so precarious in a great part of Europe, and the institutions of human society are every- where ingeniously and inclefatigably misrepresented for revolutionary purposes, it behoves all those who have any share in making or ad- ministering laws, to be well grounded in the soundest doctrines of Public Law, whereby they may meet this mischief and prevent the success- ful diffusion of those dangerous theories, and at the same time discern changes which may be safely and advantageously made. To lawyers the study of Universal Public Law must be especially and deeply im- portant. A slight knowledge of the Reports suffices to show how d L. 5, ff. De Just, et Jur. And see the comment of Cujacius thereon, torn. 7, col. 30. Edit. Venet. Mutin. INTRODUCTION. 9 often the Law of Nations, and other branches of Public Law, are resorted to in the administration of justice. I refer to the Common Law and Equity Reports, for it is superfluous to say anything of the Admiralty Reports, and especially of Lord Stowell's decisions. In Conn v. Blackburn, Dougl. 619, Mr. Law, afterwards Lord Ellenborough, arguing in an action of assumpsit, before Lord Mans- field, cites Grotius, and refers to the question agitated by Quintilian and commented on by Pufendorf, regarding the instrument of obliga- tion from the Thebans to the Thessalians, found by Alexander the Great upon taking Thebes. In the case of the Duke of Brunswick v. The King of Hanover (6 Beav.), the most abstruse doctrines of Public Law regarding the immunities of a sovereign prince in a foreign country were considered. And in the older books, the case of Monopolies (11 Rep. 85) is discussed on grounds of Public Law. And so Calvin s case (7 Rep. 1) is full of points of Public Lavy, as, for instance, when it is held that the highest and the lowest dignities are universal ; for, if a king of a foreign nation come into England by leave of the king of this realm, he shall sue and be sued by the name of a king, for he is a kino- here, whereas a foreign duke or other nobleman has no such privilege, but is a commoner here. The multitude of cases wherein this kind of learning has been used in the Courts of Common Law and Equity, renders any further re- ference to them unnecessary here. With regard to our treatises and text books, Fortescue, in his work De Laudibus Legum Anglice, enters, especially in the tenth and fol- lowing chapters, into disquisitions on the first origin of kingdoms and nations and other questions of Public Law, citing St. Thomas Aquinas, De Regimine Principum, and St. Augustine, De Civitate Dei. And Blackstone's Commentaries are full of luminous discussions of the same nature. Lord Hale, in the tenth chapter of his Pleas of the Crown, expounds the Law of Allegiance, not only with English authorities, but referring also to the Law of Nations. And I need scarcely remind the reader of Butler's note to Co. Litt. 261 a, on the Jus Maris, where he learnedly discusses the celebrated dispute of Selden and Grotius on the liberty of the seas, and Bynkershoek's treatise on the Rhodian Law. In the face of these authorities, and the many others that might be added, it is impossible to deny that Public Law ought to be part of legal education here. The present prospects of the legal profession render this proposition still clearer. What will be the ultimate effect of the New County Courts on the administration of justice, and what the precise result of the changes which they are directly or indirectly bringing about, it 10 INTRODUCTION. may at present be difficult to say with much confidence. But this new form of judicial polity must in all probability not only break that system of concentrating the bar in London, which was believed to conduce so much to its dignity and importance, but in divers ways diminish its emoluments. That this is a severe trial to the legal pro- fession, not only individually but as a body, no one can deny. Super- ficial observers may perhaps say, that this is of no consequence to any one but to lawyers, and that the change must be one of unmixed ad- vantage to the nation at large. But whoever considers that the great leading principle of our constitution is government according to law, and that "the Common Law is the greatest inheritance that the king and the subject have," must perceive how deeply important is the maintenance of that body from whom the judges of the land are selected, and who with them are entrusted with the administration of the law. It is impossible to doubt the value of those reforms having for their object the cheap and speedy administration of justice; but, like other inventions of human wisdom, they are not unaccompanied with certain dangers of inconvenience. And those dangers must be met, not only for the sake of the legal profession, but for the love of our country. If ever a time should come when the bar of England has fallen into a vulgar mediocrity, with no more learning than is necessary to earn a daily subsistence, unadorned by great legal science, dignity and in- dependence, then the constitution of this country will be in imminent peril. And this may come to pass, unless care be taken to provide a remedy against the circumstances of the times just adverted to, by raising as high as possible the standard of legal education. Barristers will probably not in future make very great and rapid fortunes, and so be the founders of powerful families among the landed aristocracy. But this need not necessarily lead to the decay of our order. In the first of the celebrated letters of Camus on the Pro- fession of an Advocate, he tells the young candidate that the exercise of that profession leads rather to honour than to fortune ; and yet at the time when he wrote, the French bar was in a high state of im- portance ; and this shows that the diminution of professional emolu- ments need not necessarily be prejudicial to the status and public utility of the bar. But that diminution must be counterbalanced by an increase of learning. In future lawyers must fit themselves, not merely to earn their bread by the practice of the law in the particular branch which they especially follow, but they must apply themselves to the general study of the law in all its branches with a more comprehensive spirit, and thereby not only enlarge their professional sphere of knowledge, but INTRODUCTION. 1 1 also qualify themselves to perform the duties of legal statesmen in parliament, and in the general business of the country. For this pur- pose they must extend their learning, so as to embrace the whole range of the legal science ; and such is the wonderful harmony of Universal Jurisprudence, and the connection of all its parts, that they will find even their special cultivation of certain branches of law facilitated by the study of the science as a whole. But these Commentaries are designed not only for lawyers by pro- fession, but for all who have any concern in the administration of public affairs. For our reflections on the political events of late years show clearly how much the practice of Public Law has lately been left to chance ; and how principles have been neglected or violated by a blind following of what has been called public opinion, which has brought about the necessary result of government by force of arms and vigor- ous measures of repression. And these remedies have been received with acquiescence, if not with thankfulness, by people who feared an overthrow of all government and the dissolution of human society. Although the science of politics, based on experience and prudence, is distinct from that of law, yet we shall see ho\v the two sciences are linked together, and that the same spirit of justice must preside over both, so as to cause a harmony and unity in the scheme or system whereby mankind are governed under Divine Providence. If it were otherwise, we must embrace the false doctrines of the Manicheans, who recognised two powers, one good and the other evil, dividing between them the government of the world. It follows, that as the administration of human affairs is conducted by both those sciences, and as they must have the same end by Divine appointment, so their principles must be consistent, and the rules of one of them cannot be violated without injury to the other, and prejudice to the interests of mankind. These reflections show how necessary Public Law is to politics and statesmanship. For as St. Thomas Aquinas says, " the government of particular states must be modelled on that of the world." And there- fore the rules of practical government are derived from principles be- longing to the original design of human society, and from natural law, which points out the state prescribed by the nature of man and the will of the Creator. From thence springs the whole science of Public Law. These observations will give an idea of the plan of our Commentaries on Universal Public Law. But some further explanation may be re- quisite to show their scope and use. Public Law, in its widest sense, includes International Law. But the latter is so vast and complicated, that it requires to be treated as a 12 INTRODUCTION. distinct branch of jurisprudence. In these Commentaries it is often adverted to, but not fully and professedly explained. International Law is founded on the great principles of jurisprudence, and the laws on which human society is constructed ; and it can never be fully understood, without a knowledge of the juridical nature of the commu- nities called nations, or states, with their essential organic laws, and their relation to the government of mankind. These Commentaries, therefore, contain the sources of the Law of Nations, and the doctrines from whence its most important parts are deduced. But we have here chiefly in view, Public Law in the more confined sense of the term, that is to say, without International Law. The object of these Commentaries is to explain the origin and struc- ture of universal human society, and of the different kinds of commu- nities into which it is divided, in order to show the system by which the world is governed, and the principles on which that government is grounded, and whereby it is regulated. This investigation will facili- tate the solution of many difficulties in the sciences of jurisprudence and government, and refute errors and false doctrines prejudicial to the peace and welfare of society. The leading practical idea in the science of universal Public Law, is to view mankind as governed by laws and obligations. It regards mankind as an aggregate divided into particular communities, or bodies politic, and forming an universal system in this world, regulated and governed by an infinite variety of laws, which, notwithstanding their great diversities, are capable of being classified and arranged so as to show how the different sorts of laws work, and what principles in them are essential or useful, or prejudicial to the interests of society ; and these laws are connected, in a multiplicity of ways, with religion and morality, and with politics and those different sciences which relate to the intercourse of mankind, and the uses of all things in the world. Such is the general spirit of this book. It is entitled, Commentaries on Universal Public Law, because it is not confined to the Public Law of any particular country, but embraces that of human society in general throughout the world, including the foundations of International Law. This vast subject is here treated on a method of development from fundamental principles. Thus we have commenced with an exposition of the origin and foundations of law, and then proceeded to show the plan of society on the foundation of those two great primary laws on which all others depend. Then follows a full explanation of the nature and spirit of laws and their different kinds. And as the laws of man are the rules of his conduct, and that conduct consists of the steps INTRODUCTION. 13 which he takes towards his end, 6 which is also the ultimate end of human society; this investigation includes the most essential parts of the government of mankind. And it also shows the connection of Public Law with all the other parts of universal jurisprudence. We then proceed to the detail of Public Law, the elements or parts of human government, and the different forms of civil polity, with the legal reasons and principles belonging to them. Such is the general scheme of these Commentaries. On every material point abundant references to authorities are provided. Thus the reader will be able to prosecute his inquiries by tracing our pro- positions and arguments to their sources, and at the same time to judge in doubtful questions on which side the weight of authority preponderates. The author is encouraged by the circumstance, that there does not exist in the English language any treatise on this the highest and most abstruse part of temporal jurisprudence; and therefore the novelty of the undertaking may recommend it, and also be some excuse for its imperfect execution. The reader need not be deterred for want of previous legal know- ledge from using these Commentaries. They are written not only for lawyers but for all persons interested in government and public affairs. Therefore everything is here explained in simple language, avoiding technical terms as much as possible : and the elementary parts are sufficiently complete to render the remainder easy. And indeed those elementary portions of the work may serve as an introduction to other branches of law : for they contain the fundamental principles on which all jurisprudence is built. Care has been taken to avoid partizanship and political bias. All questions have been considered legally and philosophically on their own merits. Yet reference is freely made to events of our own time wherever they seemed calculated to illustrate the matter in hand, and give a practical character to theories and arguments. Much use is made in the following pages of the great constitutional legal writers of that wonderful Republic, to which we are bound by so many ties both of race and interest. They are not known in this country so generally as their learning, profound reasoning, and wisdom deserve : and some of their most valuable arguments and opinions have therefore been transferred verbatim to this book. It has also been endeavoured to take as wide a range as possible in choosing the materials of this work. Civilians, canonists, jurists, theologians and political writers, ancient and modern, have been freely used, that the reader might be e Domat, Loix Civiles, Trait des Loix, ch. 1, 3. 14 INTRODUCTION. furnished with abundance of authority, and introduced to many sources of learning. Three years of constant labour have been con- sumed in the composition of these Commentaries, which I now pre- sent to the public, in the hope that so new and difficult an undertaking will be indulgently received as a zealous effort for the advancement of knowledge. CHAPTER II. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. THESE Commentaries have commenced with a general consideration of the relation which Universal Public Law that branch of juris- prudence which contains the laws whereby human society is formed and governed bears to the history of our own times and the present state of European affairs. Before we proceed to a nearer inspection of this part of general juris- prudence, some investigation of the nature and properties of laws will be necessary. The reason is, that the science of universal jurisprudence comprises all those rules of conduct or laws, whereby the human race is under Divine Providence governed ; and if laws be considered in this light, that is to say, not as establishing or defining certain specific legal relations, and so constituting the rights of individuals, but as rules of human government, all laws come within the sphere of Universal Public Law. And this is one link between Public Law and every other branch of jurisprudence. And thus Savigny/ after saying that law is divisible into two branches, Public and Private, goes on to say : " The former has for its object the state, that is, the organic manifestation of the people ; the latter embraces the legal relations between individuals, and is the rule or expression of those relations. But those two sorts of law have many points both of resemblance and of contrast. Thus the constitution of the family, the authority of the father, and the obedience of the children, bear a striking analogy to the constitution of the state ; g and many corporate bodies have nearly the same legal condition as individuals. But what distinguishes public from private law is, that the former relates to the aggregate of society, and con- 1 Trait^ du Droit Rom. torn. 1, chap. 2, 9. Trad, par Guenoux, 1840. t St. Thomas Aquinas makes the same observation. Opusc. De Regimine Prin- cipum, lib. 1, cap. 1, in fin. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. 15 siders individuals in a secondary light ; while the latter is directed to the individual exclusively, and concerns itself with his existence and his different legal states." These profound observations of the great German civilian, which form a good commentary on the celebrated law of Ulpian in the Pandects distinguishing public from private law, h show that if a law be considered in its relation to the commonwealth, that is to say, simply as a law, it has an aspect relating to public juris- prudence, though its object be private. And thus Papinian describes law as follows : " Lex est commune prceceptum" ****** " Communis reipubliccB sponsio " 1 Such is the light in which I intend to contemplate and explain the nature of laws. This preliminary disquisition will not only lead to a clearer knowledge of Public Law, but also enforce the great principle, that universal jurisprudence, comprehending all laws, is one science composed of branches intimately connected one with the other, though to the superficial observer quite separate and unconnected. Our chief guide will be Domat, of whom the Chancellor D'Aguesseau k said, that no one had ever given a better plan of human society and the origin and nature of laws. He has, indeed, been blamed by Pro- fessor Lerminier, and other modern writers, for mingling law with Religion. But the following observation of the great canonist Zallinger 1 shows that criticism to be unsound and shallow. He says, that some writers on natural jurisprudence fall into error at the very outset of the science, by taking a maimed and imperfect view of the nature of man, and referring all that man ought to regard in the observance of natural laws to this temporary life only, and to its interests; and so they deem themselves more philosophical, in proportion as they separate Religion from Natural Law. Domat commences his argument thus, " We cannot take a more simple or a surer way for discovering the first principles of laws, than by laying down two primary truths, which are only bare definitions. One is, that the laws of man are the rules of his conduct, and the other, that his conduct is nothing else but the steps which a man takes towards the end for which he was created." m And we find the same principles in Pufendorf, where he says, that h L. 1, 2, ff. De Just, et Jur. And see Bracton, De Legib. lib. 1, c. 1, 2, 3. 1 L. 1 , ff. De Legib. et Senatusc. k D'Aguesseau, CEuvres, torn. 1, p. 273. The chancellor mentions that the work was composed under his own eyes. 1 Zallinger, Instit Jur. Eccles. in Decretal. Prolog, cap. 2, 7, p. 8. m Domat, Loix Civiles, Traite des Loix, chap. 1, $ 3. 16 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. the dignity and excellence of man require that he should conform his actions to a certain rule, and that our soul is given to us whereby we know the rule, not merely to animate the body, and preserve it from corruption, but in order that, by the good use of our faculties, we may serve our Creator, and also render ourselves happy." Now these first notions of law show that it is impossible to separate the fundamental doctrines of jurisprudence from Religion, unless you throw out of your consideration the more excellent part of man and the only permanent existence of which his nature is capable. To do so would be a radical error, for as Zallinger truly observes, nothing is more important in teaching the fundamental principles of law than to consider the nature of man both correctly and completely. It follows, as Domat teaches, that in order to discover the founda- tion of the laws of man, it is necessary to know what is his end ; be- cause his destination to that end will be the first rule of the way which leads him to it, and consequently his first law, and the foundation of all the others. This, which we may call the directive aspect of law, is to be found in the celebrated definition of St. Thomas Aquinas. Lex est qucedam regula et mensura secundum quam inducitur quis ad agendum, vel ab agenda retrahitur. Suarez observes that this definition includes not only men but animals and inanimate things. And so it is, because those creatures are governed by rules directing them to their end, which is the purpose for which they are made. p And those rules may be called laws, if (as Hooker says) we apply the word law not to that only rule of working, which a superior authority imposes by way of obligation, but in the more enlarged sense in which any kind of rule or canon, whereby actions are framed, is called a law. Both kinds of rules have this in common, that they direct things or persons towards the end for which they are created. Before we learn from Domat how the two fundamental laws given to us in the Gospel are derived from the end of man's creation, it will be useful to see how Pufendorf and Grotius have deduced the origin of law from the nature of man. The former examines very judiciously the question, whether it would be consistent with the nature of man to live without any law. q The question arises thus. As God has given free will to men, that is to say, the faculty of bringing their minds, by an interior movement, n Pufend. Dr. des Gens, trad, par Barbeyrac, Liv. 2, ch. 1, 5. Suarez, De Leg. lib. 1, cap. 1, $ 1. And see Hooker, Eccles. Polit. book 1,^3. P Suarez, ubi supr. et lib. 2, cap. 3, 12. J Pufend. Dr. des Gens, 1. 2, ch. 1 ; per tot. Grot. D. de la G. & de la P. 1. 1, Disc. Prelim. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. 17 to whatever they approve, and rejecting the contrary, it has been doubted whether it would not have been conformable to the goodness of the Creator to leave them in the full enjoyment of their liberty of will. Man is gifted with a greater power of free will than any other animals possess, and yet he is fettered on all sides by obligations, and is therefore less free than they. The answer to this difficulty is in the proposition, that liberty with- out limit would be not only useless, but also pernicious to human nature ; and that therefore our own interest requires that our freedom should be restricted by some law. This principle is also important as giving a clue to the question, how far free-will may reasonably be left without bridle. Suarez r accordingly shows that law is necessary. He argues that law is not absolutely necessary in itself, because God does not require law, and a law supposes something created, to be governed thereby. And a law, properly so called, supposes the existence of a rational crea- ture, because it must be imposed on free will and free acts. But he .concludes, that assuming the creation of rational beings, a law is not only useful but necessary to direct them to good and restrain them from evil, and that they may live in a manner conformable to their nature. Man is an intellectual creature and has a Superior, under whose providence and rule he is placed, and being intelligent, he is capable of moral government; therefore, Suarez argues, he must be subject to the will of that superior whereby he is governed by law. With regard to animals, their condition is very inferior to that of man, and they can be subject to no law, properly so called, in their relations with each other or with man, and thus they have liberty independent of law. The reason is, that they have not souls capable of perceiving and knowing right or obligation. 5 There is, however, a law of Ulpian in the Pandects where he speaks of a natural law common to men and all animals : " Jus naturale est quod natura omnia animalia docuit. Nam jus istud non humani generis proprium sed omnium animalium quce in terra, quce in mari nascuntur, avium quoque commune est. Hinc descendit maris atque ' fcemince conjunctio quam nos matrimonium appellamus: hinc liberorum procreatio, hinc educatio : vidimus etenim castera quoque animalia feras etiam istius juris peritia censeri." ' And he then goes on to say that the jus gentium differs from natural law, because it is exclusively belonging to mankind ; that jus gentium is the true natural law. This celebrated text of the Pandects requires some explanation here. r Suarez, De Leg. lib. 1, cap. 3. Pufend. lib. 2, cli. 1, 4. ' L. 1, 3, ft'. De Just, et Jar. 18 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. Savigny observes," that, in the writings of the Roman jurisconsult!, we find two great divisions of law considered with reference to its origin. The first is bipartite. It is this: 1st. Jus civile the law peculiar to the Romans. 2ndly. The Jus gentium, or, Jus naturale which is common to all men. The second division is tripartite, that is to say: 1st. Jus civile the law belonging to the Romans. 2ndly. Jus gentium the law common to all nations; and 3rdly. Jus naturale the law common to men and to animals. The learned writer is of opinion that the first of these two classifications is the only rational one, expressing the true doctrine of the Roman Law, while the latter is an attempt at a more extensive classification, which has not been generally recognized, and has had no influence on the doctrines of the Roman Law. The Institutes of Gajus throw light on this subject. He represents the jus gentium as the primitive and most ancient law founded on natu- ralis ratio." He also calls it jus naturale; and when he speaks of the natural modes of acquiring property, or the ownership of things, he re- fers them indiscriminately to jus naturale and to naturalis ratio. y And the principle laid down by him, (which is also in the English Law), that the property of the soil carries with it that of the buildings, rests both on the jus civile and on the jus naturale. And Gajus calls agnation and cognation " Civilia et naturalia jura." z Thus it appears that Gajus clearly lays down the bipartite division of law. It is also fol- lowed by Modestinus, Paulus, Marcian, Florentinus, and Licimus Rufus, as Savigny shows. a The tripartite division is explicitly taught by Ulpian, Tryphoninus, and Hermogeniamis. Savigny is of opinion that it rests on the fol- lowing hypothesis. There was a time when the mutual relations of men were only those which exist among animals. Then came the period when civil government, slavery, private property, and obliga- tions were uniformly established among men. Later still, the modifi- cations of general law ; and new institutions formed in each state peculiar laws. This hypothesis is evidently not founded in fact, at least so far as regards the first period, and it is useful only to explain the legal doc- * trine of Ulpian. Donellus says that Ulpian speaks by way of figure of speech, meaning, not that there can be any law among beasts (who * Savigny, Traite du Droit Rom. torn. 1, Appendice 1. * Gajus, 1, 1 ; 1. 9, ff. De Just et Jur. ; I. 1, ff. De Adquir. rer. domin. y L. 1, ff. De Adquir. rer. domin. ; Gajus, 2, ^ 65, 73. * L. 2, ff. De Superfic.; Gajus, 1, 158. a Savigny, ubi sup. p. 407. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. 19 are incapable of obligations), but that there is among them a similitude of law in the relations which are governed by instinct and natural im- pulses, and so resemble those of mankind. Savigny defends Ulpian in the same manner. He lays it down that every legal relation has for its basis some fact on which it arises, and to which the law applies. In most legal relations, the given matter, that is to say, the fact, such as ownership and contracts, is not so necessary that the human species could not subsist without it. But with regard to those relations which are common to mankind and to animals, it is different, for they are necessary to the continuance of the human race. Therefore those legal relations are common to men and to animals in a certain sense. This view of Ulpian's doctrine gives it its true use and value. Savigny observes that the Roman jurisconsulti were no doubt led to this notion by seeing that certain institutions belonging in common to all nations must be regarded as more or less natural. But he rejects the tripartite division as a mere individual theory of Ulpian, while that of Gajus is the true principle of Roman Law. In substance Cujacius does not differ from Savigny. He says that many things which men do under the guidance of reason, and obeying an obligation of natural law, are done by animals by instinct and natural impulse, and that in this sense there is a law common to men and beasts. The same doctrine is taught by the great canonist Reif- fenstuel. d And, indeed, Cujacius carries the doctrine rather further by citing an observation of Polybius, that even monarchy (which is a part of ihe jus gentium) is common to men and some beasts, 6 for many animals have their leaders whom they obey. f This explanation of Ulpian's doctrine respecting natural law is im- portant, not only because the subject has been much considered by the learned, but as illustrating the value of the method introduced by Cujacius, who is not satisfied with taking the body of civil law com- piled by Justinian as a whole, but investigates the separate texts of which the Pandects are composed, and so discovers the opinions held at different times by the Roman jurisconsulti. And we shall thereby be assisted in the exposition of the origin of law, to which I now re- turn. St. Thomas Aquinas teaches us that, though the ultimate end of the Divine government of the world is exterior to the world, yet its irame- f Donelli Comment, lib. 1, cap. 6, 6. d Reiffenst. Jus Can. Univ. proem, parag. (chapter) 1, num. 11. And see Scbmatz- grueber, Jus Eccles. Univ. torn. 1, proem. ^ 2, num. 46. e L. 5, ff. De Just, et Jur. 1 Cujac. Op. torn. 7, col. 16, 17. See the same idea in St. Thomas Aquin. De Regim. Princip. 1. 1, cap. 12. c2 20 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. diate object is the order of things therein; from whence, indeed, he argues that there must be a Divine Providence. And he observes that inanimate things are governed without their exercising judgment, that is to say, by natural causes and effects ; and brutes, though they have a species of judgment, are governed by natural instinct. But mankind have judgment and free-will, liberum arbitrium; and their actions, per- formed in the exercise thereof, are good when directed to the true end of man according to reason. g Pufendorf accordingly argues that the dignity of man, above other animals, requires that he should conform his actions to a certain rule, without which there would be no order or fitness in mankind. 11 In fact, man would be an exception to the general principle laid down by St. Thomas as to the immediate end of the Divine government, for neither physical causes and effects nor instinct could suffice to regulate his actions. This is evident from the mental and physical powers of doing evil, in which man surpasses all other animals the number of his passions the versatility of his mind and the prodigious variety of character and disposition among men, which must cause horrible confusion unless brought to a certain harmony by laws : and that variety itself, duly regulated and controlled, becomes both beneficial and ornamentaj to human society.' These considerations show the necessity of laws as a portion of the Divine Polity, from whence we must infer that law, in its most ex- tended sense, including both lex and jus, springs from the design and will of the Creator ; and this Hooker has learnedly and splendidly shown with other things in the first book of his Ecclesiastical Polity. But here we must take care not to fall into the errors of which Savigny writes as follows : " In order that free creatures placed together in the world may mutually assist and not injure each other in the development of their action, a line of demarcation must circumscribe limits within which the parallel development of individuals may find independence and secu- rity. The rule which fixes those limits and preserves that freedom of action is right or law" " Some writers endeavour to reach the idea of law by an inverse process, and place its fundamental basis in injustice. According to them injustice is the violation of freedom by an extraneous power, which is an obstacle to the development of man and the evil which requires a remedy ; and, in their opinion, law is that remedy. Some * Div. Thomas Summa, quaest. ciii. art. 1, 2; quaest. Ixxiii. art. 1. h Pufend. Droit des Gens, 1. 11, ch. 1, 5. 1 Pufend. ibid. ^ 6, 7. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. 21 make it derived from a reasonable agreement of individuals who sacri- O fice a part of their liberty to secure the rest. Others deduce it from an exterior force alone able to restrain the will of individuals naturally inclined to a state of war. These writers base their doctrines on a negation, as if disease ought to be the point of departure for studying the laws of life. According to them, the State is a coercive power which might be dispensed with if the will of all men were regulated by justice. But, in my opinion, the State would, under such a con- dition of things, shine with augmented grandeur and power." k Thus Hooker shows that the angels are in perfect obedience to the Divine Law, 1 and this St. Thomas Aquinas assumes throughout his disquisitions on their nature and attributes. The reasoning of Savigny is confirmed by Pufendorf 's doctrine, that the weakness of the indi- vidual man with reference to his wants shows the necessity of law. No animal perhaps is so miserable as an insulated man in what has sometimes erroneously been called a state of nature that is to say, a savage state. And even if we suppose a family living together in that state, their condition would evidently be more disadvantageous than that of animals, because their wants are greater, and their means of satisfying those wants quite insufficient ; m and, indeed, this shows that such a condition is not the natural state of man, that is to say, it is not a state in conformity with his nature. That nature evidently requires what is called the social state, because the nature of man, as a reasonable creature with an immortal soul, points it out as the state for which he was intended by his Creator. 11 In this state alone can mankind satisfy all the wants which arise from the dignity of their nature. Now, unless we suppose the human race to consist of insulated individuals, which is absurd, men must be placed in various relations with each other ; and those relations generate obli- gations regulated by law or right; and in the social state those rela- tions, and the rules governing them, must be exceedingly complicated and numerous, including the duties of the man and the citizen. It is indeed impossible to conceive the social state fully accomplishing all the purposes for which it is intended, unless the actions of individuals are directed by rules of conduct which constitute law. Therefore, k Savigny, Traite de Droit Rom. torn. 1, pp. 326. 327; liv. 2, ch. 1, 52. 1 Hooker, Eccles. Polit. b. 1, 4. m Pufend. Droit des Gens, I. 11, c. 1, 8. And see St. Thomas Aquinas, Opusc. De Regimine Principum, lib. 1, cap. 1. n See my Readings at the Temple, p. 7. St. Thomas Aquinas says, " Videtur autem ultimus finis esse multitudinis congregatse, vivere secundum virtutem. Ad hoc enim homines congregantur ut simul bene vivant, quod consequi non posset unus- quisque singulariter vivens. Bona autem vita est secundum virtutem. Virtuosa igitur vita est congregations humanse finis." De Regim. Princip. lib. 1, cap. 14. 22 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. Hermogenianus, in the Pandects, describes civil society and the necessary transactions among men, as springing from jus gentium, by which he means natural law; which, in the words of Gajus natu- ralis ratio inter omnes homines constitute? Law is not intended merely to restrain man from injustice and war, but to direct human society to the common welfare ; and its origin and use are to be found in the very nature of man impressed upon him by his Creator. Law is not merely delictorum coercitio, but commune proeceptum, virorum prudentium consultum.^ So Cardinal Contarini, in his work on the Constitution of Venice, says, that the commonwealth should be governed by something more excellent than the will of man, that its objects may be obtained, and therefore, by Divine council, the government of men is committed to laws/ CHAPTER III. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. SOME may perhaps think, that instead of commencing with the foun- dations of legal philosophy, we should have proceeded in these Com- mentaries at once to the practical part of Public Law, giving a sum- mary of rules and authorities applicable to different events and affairs, with reasons and consequences. The course which we have adopted requires some explanation. Even in mathematics, axioms are laid down as first principles from whence truths are demonstrated. But the use of first principles is as important in the study of moral sciences, such as ethics and law, as in mathematics. Burke observes, that the excellence of mathematics is to have but one thing before you, but he forms the best judgment in all moral disquisitions who has the greatest number and variety of considerations in one view before him, and can take them in with the best possible consideration of the mesne results of all. a It follows that those sciences are necessarily of a very complicated nature, and every proposition that is not a primary truth depends on reasoning L. 5, ff. De Just, et Jure. P L. 9, ibi. * L. 1, ff. De Legibus. r Delia Repub. e Magistr. di Venetia del Card. Contarini, lib. 1, pp. 22, 23. Burke, Speech in the House of Commons, May 8th, 1780. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. 23 which connects it with a multitude of rules and doctrines derived from fundamental principles which are the basis of the entire science : and, indeed, the moral sciences are so intimately connected together that it is often difficult to show their various points of contact and separation. Law must be considered as one single science, though it has many different branches, because they are all connected together, and all depend directly or indirectly on certain principles from whence the vast multiplicity of laws, rules and doctrines are deduced. It follows from these characteristics of moral science; and law espe- cially, that what is commonly called the practical ought to be inse- parable from the theoretical part ; and it is difficult to obtain a masterly knowledge of any considerable branch of law, or to arrive at a tolerable proficiency in general jurisprudence, without a careful in- vestigation of fundamental principles and doctrines which are the primordia of law. So the Chancellor D'Aguesseau advises his son to go to the very first principles of law, and examine the grounds of natural law. " You perhaps thought," says the Chancellor, " that when you finished the study of philosophy you had taken leave of metaphysical investiga- tions. But you will return to them when you examine the origin of natural law and its consequences, and all those matters which may be called the metaphysics of jurisprudence. I should not, however, advise you to devote your time to that subject, if its study were calculated more to adorn the mind than to form it. But you will find that almost all the principles of the most venerable laws, that is to say those which are universal and immutable, depend thereon, as so many natural consequences derived from that original justice of which God is the source, and the first notions whereof He has engraven in our very existence. You must, therefore, make the metaphysics of law a study preliminary to every other study of jurisprudence. And I advise you for that purpose to read the first book of Cicero de Legibus, where he examines the first principles of all laws." b And then the Chancellor particularly recommends the careful and profound study of Domat's Treatise on Laws. This is the opinion, not of a professor or a mere writer on law, but of a great judge and statesman actually engaged in the administration of justice, who knew by experience the importance of combining prac- tical with theoretical science. And Savigny, in his History of the Roman Law, c shows that this combination caused the success of the first school of civilians the Glossators. He observes that the dis- tinction between legal theory and practice may be traced to those b D'Aguesseau, CEuvres, torn, i, pp. 270, 271, Prem. Instruct. c Savigny, Hist, du Droit Rom. torn. 3, ch. xli. 24 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. times, and that the life or death of both depends on the spirit govern- ing the partition of those two branches of science. Considered in a purely theoretical point of view the glossators might have derived nothing from their labours beyond exercise of the mind, but the active part which they took in judicial and political affairs saved them from that danger. When in the middle of the thirteenth century the sci- entific spirit of legal studies was extinguished, the progress of science became impossible, and it fell into a sterile condition. This shows how important the science of law must be to its practice. To every branch of public law these observations apply with very great force. Public is of a more generalizing nature than private law, because it regards wider interests and rights, including what relates to the common welfare of the state and of society ; and these matters flow from certain principles to which the social state and human go- vernment, and the various institutions and laws arising therefrom, may be traced. The reasons of all these things cannot be clearly understood, unless the fundamental doctrines from whence they di- rectly or indirectly spring are first studied. Therefore the doctrines regarding the origin and nature of law are material to the science of Public Law, and indeed they are the very root of all jurisprudence. They will give us a broad view of legal science, without which its details cannot be so completely or easily mastered. We have seen, as St. Thomas Aquinas teaches, that the eternal law directs all things towards their proper end. And thus Domat lays it down, that to discover the first principles of laws, two primary truths should be laid down ; first, that the laws of man, that is to say, those whereby he is governed, are the rules of his conduct ; and, secondly, that his conduct, directed by those rules, consists of the steps which he takes towards the end for which he was created. d And here we find a connection between law and theology ; because, as man has an immortal intelligent soul, his end cannot have reference solely to his existence here, but must relate to his moral nature and immortality. Domat, whose words derive additional authority from the fact that they were written under the advice of the Chancellor D'Aguesseau, continues thus : " Among the objects which offer themselves to man in the whole world, even including his fellow creatures, none of them is worthy to be his end. With regard to himself, so far will he be from finding his happiness there, that he will see nothing but the seeds of misery and death. And round about him, if we go over d Domat, Traitd dea Loix, chap. 1, 3. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. 25 the whole creation, we shall find nothing there that is fit to be given as an end either to his mind or to his heart. And the things which we see are so far from being our end, that we are theirs, since they are made for us. e And we see plainly that everything there is so little worthy both of our mind and of our heart, that as for the mind, God has hidden from it the knowledge even of creatures beyond what regards the ways of using them. And the sciences which apply to the knowledge of their nature, discover nothing further in them than what may be of use to us, and grow darker and less intel- ligible the more they attempt to penetrate into that which is not required for our use/ And as for the heart, the whole world is not capable of filling it, and it was never able to make any one happy. In short we must learn from Him who has made man, that it is He alone who is both the beginning and the end of man, g and God only can fill the infinite vacuity of that mind which he has made for Himself." " It is therefore for God himself that God has made man. It is that he may know Him that He has given him understanding. That he may love God, He has given him a will. And it is by the ties of this knowledge and of this love that He would have men unite them- selves to Him, that they may in Him find their true life and their only happiness." h We find the same doctrine briefly stated by St. Thomas Aquinas in his treatise De Regimine Principum, where he says, that all things are ordained to a certain end ; and so man has an end to which all his life and all his actions are directed, because he is an intelligent agent, and therefore capable of working out his own end. 1 From this argument, Domat deduces the first Law of Man, which is laid down in the Gospel as the first and great commandment, that is to say, the Love of God. k This, he says, is the first law, which is the foundation and first prin- ciple of all others. For this law, which commands men to search after and to love the Sovereign Goou, being common to all mankind, it implies a second law which obliges them to unity among themselves, and to the love of one another. But, he observes, there is no law com- manding man to love himself, because no one can better love himself than by keeping the first law and regulating his life thereby. e Deut. iv. 19. f Eccles. iii. 22. z Rev. xxii. ; Isai. xli. 4. h Prov. xvi. 4 ; Isai. xliii. 7 ; Deut. xxvi. 19. ' Div. Thorn. Aquin. Opusc. De Regimine Principum, lib. 1, cap. 1. k Domat, Tr. des Loix, cap. 1, 6. 26 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. " It is by the spirit of these two laws," continues the learned civilian, " that God designing to unite mankind in the possession of their com- mon end, bound them together in the use of the means conducting them thereto, and then has made this union, which is to be their hap- piness, to depend on their use of the first law which is to form their society." That is to say, their union in the love of God is the source and principle of their union among themselves. And in order to unite them in this society or social state, God has made it essential to their nature. And as we see in the nature of man his destination to the Sovereign Good, we also discover in it his des- O ' tination to society, and the several ties which on all sides engage him in it; and we see that these ties, which are consequences of the desti- nation of man to the exercise of the two primary ^laws, are at the same time the foundation of the particular rules of all his duties, and the fountain of all laws. 1 Domat notices the objection, that society, though it ought to be grounded on those two primary laws, does nevertheless subsist, not- withstanding that their spirit has apparently little influence over it. He very judiciously answers, that though men have violated these fundamental laws, and though society be in a state different from that which ought to be raised on them, yet it is nevertheless true that these Divine Laws, which are essential to the nature of man, remain immu- table and have never ceased to be obligatory. And it is likewise certain, as will be shown hereafter, that all the laws which govern society, even in its actual condition, are consequences of the two pri- mary laws. And therefore it was necessary to establish these first principles. There is a remarkable agreement between the two primary laws laid down by Domat, and the three prcecepta of Ulpian, which we must now examine. Ulpian thus lays down three primary laws : Juris prcecepta sunt hac: honeste vivere, dlterum non Itedere, suum cuique tribuere. Savigny, commenting on this law, says, that honeste vivere is the maintenance of the moral rectitude of the individual, neminem Icedere is the observance due to other men, and suum cuique tribuere is the recognition of the rights vested in others. These, he observes, are not properly rules of law, but principles of morals proper to found rules of law. Thus the third precept, suum cuique tribuere, is evi- dently the moral law of justice. And many of the most important laws are derived from the second precept, neminem Icedere. And the first precept, honeste vivere, is also the source of more than one rule of 1 Domat, ubi sup. 8. And see Zallinger, Instit. Jur. Natur. et Eccles. 1. 1, c. 20, 22. > L. 10, 1, ff. De Just, et Jur. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. 27 law, and is therefore a real juris prceceptum in the sense understood by Ulpian. From it flow the laws protecting morals, such as those whereby contracts are rendered void by an immoral consideration. With the same principle are also connected the numerous rules of law requiring sincerity and honesty in contracts, and also the extensive in- fluence exercised by the law regarding fraud over matters of private law. Thus the three prsecepta of Ulpian are not rules of law, but general principles calculated to form categories of rules of law. " If," says Savigny, "the three praecepta are to be classified accord- ing to their essence, the first must be placed at the head of them, as the most profound, and as containing the germ of the two others. The second has an exterior character still more visible in the third. Thus, the two latter may be obeyed without reference to the morality of the agent. But if they be considered with reference to their legal importance, the result is opposite. The third is the most fertile source of rules, then comes the second, and lastly the first. This arises from the nature of law, which is required to regulate the outward rela- tions of common life." Now the first precept, honeste vivere, bears an analogy to the first law laid down by Domat, the love of God, which includes specially all those obligations which do not directly regard other men. That pre- cept may be considered as the pagan version of the Christian doc- trine, which makes duty to God the root of all law. But, as it does not directly regard obligations towards other men, it produces fewer legal results than the other two. They are included in Domat's second primary law, which comprises man's duty to his neighbour. But, as Savigny judiciously observes, the first precept contains the germ of the other two ; and from the first law of Domat, the obligatory force of the others and of all laws is derived. This is well shown in a cele- brated letter of Barbeyrac to Leibnitz, and, indeed, it appears from the description of natural law given by Grotius, who says, that it con- sists of certain principles of right reason, which enable us to know that a certain action is right or wrong according to its congruity or in- congruity with the reasonable and social nature of man, and conse- quently that God, who is the author of nature, commands or forbids that action. Grotius thus reduces the obligation of natural law to the will of and duty to God. Barbeyrac argues thus: Either the obligatory force of the rules of justice among men is absolutely independent of the divinity and founded solely on the nature of things, like principles of arithmetic 11 Savigny, Traite du Droit Rom. torn. 1, p. 4024. Grot. Droit de la G. liv. 1, cli. 1, 10. 28 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. and geometry, or it is not founded on the nature of things. p ' Now the nature of things cannot by itself impose on us an obligation pro- perly so called. If there be a given relation of equality and propor- tion, of fitness or unfitness in the nature of things, that only obliges us to recognise such relation. Something more is requisite to restrain our freedom, to oblige us to regulate our actions in a certain way. Reason considered by itself, and independently of the Creator who has given it to us, cannot place us under the moral necessity of follow- ing those principles, though it may approve of them as founded on the nature of things. For our passions oppose those abstract prin- ciples, by offering to us objects which, if less in conformity with fit- ness, are more attractive to our feelings ; and apart from an exterior power, a being above us, there is nothing obliging us to resist them. Reason, it will be argued, shows us clearly that by observing the rules arising from fitness founded on the nature of things, we shall act in a manner more conformable to our interests than we should do by being guided by our passions. But the question is one not of utility, but of duty and obligation. No doubt our interests require, upon the whole, that we should follow the dictates of reason. But is not every one at liberty to renounce an advantage, provided there be nothing to prevent him from doing so ? Thus by not conforming to fitness founded on the nature of. things, a man would only act impru- dently, and imprudence is not here opposed to any duty, for we have to discover whether there be any duty. But it is moreover very material to observe, that our reason, con- sidered apart from all dependence on its Creator, from whom we hold it, is in substance nothing but ourselves. Now no one can impose upon himself an obligation towards himself, obliging him to act or not to act in a particular manner. Hence the common maxim of law debitum et creditum non possunt concurrere in eadem persona. And in the civil law a debt is extinguished by confusion when this concurrence takes place. Nemo potest sibi debere ; and therefore the concurrence of right and obligation in the same person extinguishes both. q The same legal doctrine may be seen in Littleton, sects. 222, 223, 224, &c., where he treats of the extinction of rents and services. Its reason is that no necessity to do or not to do any act can exist, if it be subject to the will of persons affected by such supposed necessity. Now Justinian correctly defines an obligation as vinculum juris quo neces- P Jugement d'un Anonyme, etc., printed with Pufendorf 's Devoir de 1'Homme et du Cit., translated by Barbeyrac. And see Grot. Droit de la Guerre, 1. 1, ch. 1, 10, note 4, by Barbeyrac : and Barbeyrac 's Pref. to Pufendorf, Dr. des Gens, 5. Voet. ad Pand. lib. 46, tit. 3, 18; Bowyer, Com. on the Modern Civil Law, 260. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. 29 sitate adstringimurJ And if the person on whom that necessity is imposed be the imponent, he will be able to relieve himself from it whenever he pleases. Barbeyrac concludes that even the maxims of reason are not by themselves obligatory, however agreeable they may be to the nature of things, until we discover the author of the existence and nature of all things. The question remains to be considered, whence comes obligation ? Is it from the will of God, or from any other thing in Him? It is, in the first place, impossible to form a just idea of God with- out recognizing his right to limit at pleasure the faculties which He has given to us. And it is clearly God's will that men should follow the light of reason, as that which is most excellent in them, and can lead them to their natural destination. And in His will we find all that is requisite to constitute an obligation, since it is the will of the Master of all mankind, and a will ever in accordance with the percep- tion of the divine nature. Why then seek any other principle than this, which is comprehensible to all men, and so naturally arises from the relation between the Creator and the creature ? Choose any other attribute of the Divinity and view it apart from His will. You will not find in it a more solid foundation for obliga- tions than in the nature of things. If, for example, it were possible to conceive, after the fashion of the Epicureans, a God indifferent whether men act or no according to the nature of things and their own nature, the contemplation of such a Divinity with all infinite perfections would only furnish an example which does not by itself produce a necessity to imitate it. And if it be not the will of God that all His rational creatures should follow the rules of justice with each other, how can we conceive the existence of divine justice ? Can we believe the Creator to be just, if it be indifferent to Him whether men are so, and if He do not impose on them the obligation of observing justice. And the divine will cannot be made a mere accessory to an already existing independent obligation. If this were so, the supreme autho- rity of God would be restricted to things in themselves indifferent. And thus no more force would be attributed to the will of God with regard to the rules of justice than to that of a prince, a father, a master, or any other human superior, who wishes his dependents to be honest men. Moreover, we commonly find the practice of duty and virtue described in Holy Writ as doing the will of God.* With these arguments, Barbeyrac very conclusively establishes the origin and nature of the obligatory force of natural law, and shows r Instit. lib. 3, tit. 14, pr. Matt. v. 48 ; Luke, vi. 36. 30 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. how law derives its obligation the vinculum juris from the primary fundamental law of the Gospel prescribing our duty to God. We come now to a part of the subject in which the difficulty arises that our language does not contain any word answering to the Latin word jus, as contradistinguished from lex. That distinction is, how- ever, quite necessary for comprehending the civilians and jurists. St. Thomas Aquinas says, jus non est lex, sedpotius id quod leye prce- scribitur, seu mensuratur. Law lex is a rule of conduct prescribed by the will of a superior, whereby he imposes on those who are subject to him, the obligation of acting in a particular way, which he pre- scribes to them.* Thus lex is the law looked upon as a rule prescribed, that is to say, extrinsically, and jus is the law considered as a prin- ciple, and intrinsically, with reference to what it prescribes, and what particular obligations it creates. And therefore the word jus is also used (as Grotius shows) to signify a moral quality belonging to a per- son, by virtue of which he may lawfully have or do certain things, that is to say, a right." We must now consider the foundations of law, taken in the sense of the word jus. Grotius lays it down that natural law consists in certain principles of right reason, which teach us that an action is morally right or wrong, according to its necessary conformity with, or repugnance to, a rational and social nature, and that consequently God, who is the author of nature, commands or forbids that action. 1 We have to investigate the first part of this definition, the principle on which the distinction between those two classes of actions rests, that is to sayjws the law viewed intrinsically, apart from the com- mand of a superior, whereby it is made obligatory. Gajus agrees with Grotius in holding that natural law consists of principles of reason. y He lays it down in a very celebrated law in the Pandects, that all nations, governed by laws and morals, make use partly of their own peculiar laws, and partly of laws common to all men. For, he continues, the law which each nation constitutes for itself is proper to that city, and is called jus civile. But that which natural reason has constituted among all men is observed everywhere, and is called jus gentium, because all nations use it. We shall see, hereafter, the relation between civil and natural law, when we come to the distinction between arbitrary and immutable laws. Grotius cites a passage of Carneades and of Horace, calling utility, 1 Pufendorf, Devoir de 1'Homme et du Cit. 1. 1, ch. 11, 11, not. Barbeyrac. * Grot. Dr. de la G. 1. 1, ch. 1, 4. * Ibid. 10. * L. 9, ff. De Just, et Jur. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. 31 as it were, the mother of justice and equity. And he observes, that this is not strictly correct, for human nature itself is the mother of natural law, because it would lead us to seek intercourse with our fellow creatures, even if we were in want of nothing. And even civil or municipal law draws its obligatory force from natural law, because the duty of obeying municipal laws is essential to the existence of civil society, which is an institution prescribed by natural law. The truth is (as Grotius observes), that utility accompanies natural law, because the Author of nature has ordained that each individual shall be weak by himself, and shall be in need of many things, in order that we may be induced to maintain the social state. And so the prin- ciple of utility has given occasion to civil laws ; for the association of men in civil society, and their submission to a common authority, were originally commenced with a view to some advantage. Grotius accordingly thus distinguishes between the sciences of poli- tics and law. " I have abstained from touching what belongs to another subject, i. e. giving the rules of what is expedient, for that belongs to a peculiar science, namely, politics. Aristotle correctly treats that subject by itself, unmixed with any other, instead of which Bodinus often confounds it with the science of law." z And Barbeyrac observes, on this passage, that though sound policy sanctions nothing but what is just, yet justice and utility are two separate and distinct things, even in politics. Thus, to undertake war legally, there must be a just cause of war. But however just the cause, it may be highly injurious to engage in war, and to do so would be an error in politics. This doctrine is not inconsistent with the maxim of Cicero. Eadem utilitatisque honestatis est regula* for his real meaning is, that nothing is truly and solidly useful except what is just. And so far from sanc- tioning the views of those who hold utility to be the test of justice, he maintains that justice and morality are the real test of utility. Thus he establishes one rule, namely, that of right and wrong, so far at least, that nothing is to be done on the plea of utility contrary to the dictates of justice and morality. Cujacius, in commenting on the law, Omnes populi, b which we have just cited, says, that Epicurus did not, likeGajus, deduce the law com- mon to all men from nature, but drew it from the principle of utility or advantage. And he adds, " We follow the Stoics, who derive that law from nature, and deduce the law proper to each city, that is to say, civil or municipal law, from common utility ; that is to say, what is useful and advantageous to the community." z Grot. Dr. de la G. Disc. Prelim. 59. 8 Cic. De Offic. lib. iii. c. 18. b Cujac. Op. torn. 7, col. 48 ; Donelli Comment, lib. 1, cap. 6, 10. 32 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. Thus Donellus teaches, that naturalis ratio, of which Gajus speaks, is the Law of God written, as St. Paul says, in our hearts; and that this is evident from the mere fact that all men bear witness to this law; for when they offend against it themselves their conscience accuses them, and they always condemn others so offending and hold them deserving punishment. 11 It would indeed be absurd to say, that whereas the Creator gave us reason and a sense of right and wrong, requiring of us the performance of certain duties towards Himself and to our fellow men, yet we are unable to perceive those duties by the use of our reason. Thus we know that certain acts are wrong, not merely because they are contrary to the rules of utility, but because they are violations of naturalis ratio, that Law of God written, as St. Paul says, in our hearts. All these legal doctrines will become clearer when we pursue our examination of Domat, who looks upon them from a somewhat differ- ent point of view to that of Grotius and Pufendorf. We have examined them hitherto principally with reference to cer- tain questions which have obtained much celebrity among the learned. And in doing so we have noticed several famous laws in the Pandects, on which much has been written. In the next chapter, the systematic explanation of the way in which different classes of laws are deduced from the two primary laws will be continued. CHAPTER IV. THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY NATURAL LAW. WE have shown the origin of the first principles of law from the two prime truths, that the laws of man are the rules of his conduct, and that his conduct is nothing else but the steps which he takes towards his end. And then, after demonstrating the true end of man by taking a view of his nature, we have laid down, under the guidance of Domat and'the Chancellor D'Aguesseau, the two primary laws, taken c Rom. ii. 14, 15. d Donelli Comment, lib. 1, cap. 7, ^ 2. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY NATURAL LAW. 33 from the Gospel, prescribing the duty of man to God and to his neigh- bour, from whence hang all laws. 6 This system agrees with divers texts in the title of the Pandects De justitia ct jure, and with the doctrines of commentators and jurists, who have nevertheless looked on the origin of law from a somewhat different point of view. So we have seen that Ulpian, in the tenth law of the title just referred to, lays down three precepts, which bear an analogy to Domat's two primary laws. And Grotius and Pufen- dorf both confirm the doctrines of Domat, though they do not trace the origin of law quite so high as he does, because they do not derive it from primary laws springing immediately out of the will of God mani- fested in the Creation, and written, as St. Paul says, in the heart of man. In St. Thomas Aquinas we find a more direct confirmation of Domat's principle, since he distinctly teaches, that all things are or- dained to an end, and that so man has an end to which his whole life and all his acts are directed, because he is an intelligent ao'ent. to whom * O ^J * it is proper to work out his end. And then St. Thomas establishes the social nature and destination of man, calling him animal sociale et polilicum. And he shows the true scope of that nature and destina- tion to be something beyond temporal utility and convenience. f Now the laws of mankind, whereby they are under Divine Providence governed, are evidently the rule of their conduct with reference to their end or ultimate destination. In this sense we may accept the defini- tion of Ulpian Jurisprudentia est divinarum atque humanarum rerum notitia ; justi atque injusti sciential Thus Cujacius, commenting on this celebrated text, shows it to mean, that jurisprudence is that wisdom, which by the investigation of things both human and divine determines the rules of justice. 11 It is true that Voet interprets this text, as referring in part to the public law of the Romans ; which, as Ulpian says, regards ecclesias- tical as well as civil matters. Jus publicum in sacerdotibus, in sacris, in magistratibus consistit. 1 But it must also be understood as teach- ing that jurisprudence, even temporal, is derived not only from human nature and human affairs by themselves, but from the relation which they bear to things divine. And we have accordingly shown that the obligatory force of natural law springs from the Divine Will. And here we see the connexion between jurisprudence and theology, and the impossibility of entirely separating those sciences two truths e Domat, Traite des Loix, 3. f Div. Thorn. Aquin. De llegim. Princip. 1. 1, cc. 1, 14. 8 L. 10, ^2, De Just, et Jur. h Cujac. Op. torn. 7, col. 54. 1 Voet ad Pand. lib. 1, tit. 1, 4, 7; 1. 1, 2, ff. De Just, et Jur. D 34 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. on which the soundest jurist*, but especially the canonists, strongly insist. The canon law furnishes a remarkable example of the principle re- ferring law to an ultimate end, which is its essential and fundamental rule. The canon law is thus defined : Est igitur jus canonicum quod civium acliones ad finem sterna beatitudinis diriyit.^ Now the canon law, which is the body of rules provided for the government and adminis- tration of the Catholic Church, has two objects, an immediate object, and an ultimate object. The former is the due performance of Divine Worship and the fulfilment of the other exterior functions and duties belonging to the Church. The latter is that described in the passage just cited, namely, the end of the Church itself. And this end or ulti- mate purpose of the canon law only differs from that whence Domat deduces the two primary laws, inasmuch as it is more definite and specific. And the canon as well as the temporal law hangs on those two primary fundamental laws. So do we see the beautiful harmony of the parts of universal juris- prudence, and the way in which they conjoin together for the regula- tion of human affairs. This indeed is no cause for astonishment, because man is brought into the world for one end or purpose, as Domat shows ; and since laws are those rules of conduct whereby he is directed to that end, they must (though appertaining to different parts or aspects of human life) partake of the unity of the end itself. And we cannot conceive the scheme of Divine government apart from unity of purpose, without forming a notion inconsistent with Divine perfection, which seems to imply consistency and harmony, generated by that unity. This idea becomes a very important subject of medita- tion if we take a comprehensive view of universal jurisprudence as the aggregate of all those rules and principles whereby mankind are externally governed under Divine Providence. When we come to examine the classification of laws, this view of universal jurisprudence will be clearer. It is sufficient to say here that every law, whatever it may be, either bears or is supposed and ought to bear some relation, however indirect, to the fulfilment of the purposes of human society, and to the ultimate end of that society. The reasons on which dif- ferent kinds of laws are founded are various. 1 But though municipal laws may be more or less adapted to the end for which they ought to be framed ; yet such is the nature which the Creator has given to man, that all municipal laws not inconsistent with that nature must be con- sequences, direct or indirect, of the two primary laws. And so Suarez k Lancelot. Instil Jur. Can. lib. 1, tit.l, 1 ; Reiffenstuel, Jus Canon. Univ. proem. iii. num. 36 ; Barbosa, Collectanea Doctorum, torn. 5, p. 16, in part 1 Decreti Distinc. iii. c. 1. 1 See my Readings at the Middle Temple, Reading X. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY NATURAL LAW. 35 lays it down that all human laws are originally derived, in some way or other, from divine law, and he cites this fine passage of St. Augus- tine : Conditor legum temporalium, si vir bonus est et sapiens, legem aternam consulit, ut secundum ejus immutabiles regulas, quid sit pro temporejubendum vetandumque discernat. m It is on this principle that simply human laws are in general bind- ing on men's consciences, as Blackstone says. We cannot break a human law without violating a part of the secondary natural law, which requires us to obey lawful authority, for the maintenance of human society and the attainment of its ultimate objects. And thus we find the duty of obedience to the civil magistrate repeatedly laid down in Holy Writ. This obedience is, no doubt, a general duty, though it has exceptions in certain extreme cases, where the civil power com- mands things repugnant to the two primary laws, or forbids acts com- manded by divine law. We have now to consider the plan of civil society drawn by Domat and sanctioned by the high authority of the Chancellor d'Aguesseau." In the first place civil society is founded on the two primary laws. We have seen in St. Thomas Aquinas that the social state is designed to enable man to fulfil his end, that is to say, the purpose of his creation, more completely than he could do living in a solitary condi- tion. And in order to unite men in society, God has made it essential to their nature. "As we see," says Domat, " in the nature of man, his destination to the Sovereign Good, so we shall also discover several ties which on all sides bind him in it ; and these ties, which are consequences of the destination of man to the exercise of the two first laws, are at the same time the foundation of the particular rules of his duties, and the foundation of all laws." " But before we proceed any further to show the connection which links all the laws with the two first, it is necessary to obviate the re- flection, that though society ought to be founded on the two first laws, it does nevertheless subsist though their spirit has but little influence on it, so that it seems to maintain itself by other principles. How- ever, although men have violated these fundamental laws, and although society be in a state strangely different from that which ought to be raised on these foundations and cemented by this union, it is still true that these divine laws, which are essential to the nature of man, remain immutable and never cease to be binding on mankind. And it is likewise certain, as will hereafter appear, that all laws which govern m Suarez, De Leg. lib. 1, c. 3, 17 ; Div. August. De Vera Relig. c. 31 ; Reiffen- stuel, Jus Can. Univ. proem. 13. n D'Aguesseau, GEuvres, torn. 1, p. 273. D 2 36 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. society, even in its present condition, are consequences of these first laws. Thus it was necessary to establish these first principles; and besides, it is not possible to comprehend rightly the manner in which we see society subsist at present without knowing the natural state in which it ought to be ; and considering in it the union which the divi- sions of mankind have broken, and the order which they have dis- turbed." " For the purpose therefore of judging of the spirit and use of the laws which maintain society in its present condition, it is necessary to draw a plan of this society on the foundation of the two primary laws, to the intent that we may discover therein the order of all the other laws, and the connection which they have with the two first. And then we shall see what method God has taken to make society subsist in the state in which it is, and among those persons who, not govern- ing themselves in it according to the spirit of the fundamental laws, ruin the foundations which He has laid for it." This passage points out very well the province of jurisprudence to determine the principles from whence laws are derived, and the way in which society is founded thereon, though different causes disturb the effect of the two primary laws, and thereby alter in divers ways the plan which would otherwise result from them. One great object of government is to meet and counteract those causes, and this shows the importance of studying the philosophical part of jurisprudence, which teaches the true system of laws with reference to the fulfilment of God's ordinances and the constitution of human society. Moreover, though those true principles are often disregarded and violated, yet in the main all society, and the whole system on which the world is governed, are founded on them, and can be maintained only by their observance, so that any violation of them necessarily produces incon- venience more or less prejudicial to the body politic. So St. Augustine, in his treatise De Civitate Dei, p says: ubi non est vera justitia, juris consensu sociatus ccetus hominum non potest esse. And he explains that a commonwealth (Respublica) cannot be without justice, because the very idea of a commonwealth implies an association of men for the common advantage, which cannot exist without law and justice. Thus Cicero says, Non modo falsum esse istud sine injuria non posse, sed hoc verissimum, sine summa justitia rempublicam regi non posse. The relation which the state of man in this life bears to the first of the two primary laws is simple. He is not in possession of the sove- reign good, but placed here to attain it. And his understanding and his free will enable him to pursue that object which is the end of his Domat, Loix Civiles ; Traite des Loix, ch. 1, 8. P Div. August, de Civit. Dei, lib. 19, cap. 21. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY NATURAL LAW. 37 creation. And for this purpose his conduct must be in conformity with the first law commanding the love of God, from whence the obligation of all other laws is derived. We need not enter here into any explanation of the truths of religion. It suffices (as Domat ob- serves) to assume those truths, for the purpose of giving an idea of the plan of society, because we are considering law as a rule of men's outward actions. That rule is not however sufficient in itself for the government of mankind. This is so not only because the government of men's minds, which are the most excellent part of them, is ne- cessary even for the purpose of regulating their outward acts, but also because, as I have already shown, man must be considered with re- ference to the immortality of his soul even in regard to human govern- ment. If this be neglected, an imperfect view will be taken of the scheme whereby Divine Providence intended that the world should be governed, and the result must be an imperfect plan of social polity. The truths of religion have an immediate connection with the first law, which we are considering, and spring from the same source as all law. But religion regards the interior forum primarily, and looks on men in their relation to a future existence; whereas the province of law is the regulation of outward acts in this world, since law is a rule of conduct, and not of the interior movements of the soul. Though Ecclesiastical Law regards men as members of the Universal Church, or in their relation to it, yet the same principle applies that it is a rule of external conduct. q Thus the common maxim declares Ecclesia nonjudicat de occultis. And the canonists show that the canon law is a rule of civil conduct, that is, a rule to direct the actions or conduct of the citizens of that commonwealth (civitas) of which it is the law, namely, the Church/ It follows, therefore, that we are here to regard the first law in its relation to the rules of conduct, that is to say, the laws of the outward acts of men, whereof it is the source, though it is also a fundamental principle of religion. There is no difficulty in seeing why law and religion have that first principle in common. It is because they have a common object, which is the end for which man was created. We come now to the second primary law. The various reasons which have already been explained, showing man's destination for the social state, lead him to observe that second law. That state is called by the soundest jurists the natural state of man, because it is the only condition in conformity with his nature, having regard to his destina- tion here on earth. And Domat very judiciously observes, that, "As "> Suarez, De Leg lib. 4, cap. 12, 13 ; Decret. Gratian. Tract. De Pcenit. cc. 14, 31 ; Can. et Decret. Concil. Trident, sess. xxiv. div. inform, matrim. c. 1. T Lancelot. Instit. Jur. Can. 1. 1, tit. 1, 1 ; ReifFenstuel, Jus Can. proem 3. 38 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. to the second law, God has so arranged men among themselves and adapted the creation to mankind, that the same objects which ought to excite in them the love of the Sovereign Good, engage them like- wise to society and a mutual love of one another. For we see no- thing," he adds, " and we know nothing either within or without man, but what points out his destination to society." "Thus, exteriorly to man the heavens, the stars, the light, the air, are objects which present themselves to mankind as benefits common to them all, and of which every person has the entire use. And the things which the earth and the waters bear or bring forth are for the use of man, but in such wise that no one of them passes to our use but by the labour of several persons, and thus renders men necessary one to the other, and forms among them different unions or con- nections for the purposes of agriculture, commerce, arts, sciences, and all the other communications which the various wants of life may require." This remarkable passage of Domat bears an analogy to the cele- brated law of Hermogenianus in the Pandects, where he says that from the jus gentium (which must be understood to mean natural law) are derived the separation of mankind into nations, the institution of pro- perty, dealings and commerce among men, and a variety of other things and obligations except those which were introduced by civil luw. s All these things arise from the social nature of man, and are governed by rules deduced from the second of the two primary laws. " Thus," continues Domat, " within man we see that God has formed him by an incomprehensible conjunction of spirit and matter ; and has created him by the union of a soul and a body, in order to render that conjoined soul and body and that divine structure of senses and members, the instrument of two uses essential to society. " The first of these uses is to bind the minds and hearts of men together by the communication of their thoughts and sentiments. The second use of the body is that of applying men to all the different works which God has made necessary for their wants, because it is for work that God has given us senses and members. And though it be true that the labours which occupy men are a punishment inflicted on them, yet it is certain that man is so naturally destined to work, that it was enjoined to him even in his state of innocence. 1 But one of the differences between the labours of that first state of man and those of the present consists in this, that the labour of man in his state of innocence was an agreeable occupation to him, without pain, without disgust and without weariness ; whereas our labour is im- L. 5, ff. De Just, et Jur. * Gen. ii. 15. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY NATURAL LAW. 39 posed on us by way of penalty." Thus the law enjoining labour is essential both to the nature of man and to the condition to which his fall has reduced him ; and this law is also a natural consequence of the two primary laws. By placing man in society they engage him to labour, which is a bond thereof, and appoint to each his particular work, distinguishing by its diversity the different employments and conditions which should compose society. " It is thus that God having destined mankind for society has con- stituted the ties which engage him to it ; and as the general ties which He makes among all men by their nature and by their destination to the same end, under the same laws, are common to the whole of mankind, and they do not constitute in each individual any singular relation which connects him more with one person than with others, He adds to these general and common ties, other ties and engagements O ' O D of divers sorts. By these He unites men more closely among them- selves, and determines every one to exercise towards some particular persons the duties which no one can exercise towards all mankind in general. So that these engagements are to each as it were particular laws, defining what the second law requires of him, and which conse- quently regulate his duties. For the duties of men towards each other are the effects of that which is prescribed to them by the second law, according to the engagements under which every man happens to be. " These particular engagements are of two sorts. The first is of those which are constituted by the natural ties of marriage between man and woman, and of birth between parents and children ; and this kind of engagements comprehends the engagements or obligations of relationships and alliances which are consequences of marriage and birth. " The second kind of engagements comprehends all the other sorts of engagements, which draw all manner of persons nearer to one an- other. They are constituted differently, either in the several commu- nications of work, or labour or industry, and different sorts of offices, services, and other aids which pass among men, or in the relations regarding the use of things. Herein are comprehended all the divers uses of arts, employments and professions of all kinds, and all that can connect men together according to the several wants of life, either by gratuitous or by commercial communication. " It is by all these engagements of two classes that God forms the order of the society of mankind, to link them together in the exercise of the second law ; and as He marks in such engagement that which is prescribed therein, so we discover in the characters of the various Gen. iii. 19. 40 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. sorts of engagements, the foundations of the different rules of that O O ' which justice and equity require of each person according to the con- junctures in which his particular engagements place him." This masterly classification of the engagements on which human society is constructed, requires some further investigation before we proceed with the famous plan drawn by Domat and the Chancellor d'Aguesseau. Zallinger deduces natural law, like Domat, from the two primary laws or precepts of the Gospel Diliges Dominum Deum tuum ex toto corde tuo, et in totd anima tud, et in tola mente tud ; hoc est maximum et primum mandatum. Secundum autem simile est huic, diliges prox- imum tuum sicut teipsum." He observes, that not only external acts, but even the internal movements of the will, are subject to natural laws. x This is the reason why intention is material to the legal effect of human actions ; and hence we see the connexion between natural jurisprudence and ethics. But the science of ethics is more extensive than that of natural jurisprudence, because it comprehends the whole range of morality, and treats of all virtues and vices, and the principles by which moral men are governed ; whereas natural law has regard chiefly to duties and rights considered as a rule of external conduct for man, regarded as a social responsible being bound to procure, as far as in him lies, the welfare of society. This explains how it is that Domat deduces from the two primary laws which are addressed to the soul of man and intended, in the first instance, to govern his mind the ties or engagements on which human society is built, and to which men are led by the nature of things. Domat's classification of those engagements will be further ex- plained and rendered more useful by examining the distinction between absolute and conditional or hypothetical rights and obligations, whereby natural law is divided into two parts or branches primary and se- condary natural law. . This distinction is a most important point in the science of jurisprudence, without which the works of the civilians and jurists cannot be understood. The civilians hold that there is a sort of jus gentium innate in man from the very beginning, and another sort engendered subsequently by human wants. The former they call primary, or primaeval, and the latter secondary . y The primary jus gentium comprises man's duty to God, and to other n Matt. xxii. 3739. 1 Zallinger, Instil. Jur. Natur. et Ecclesiastic! Publ. lib. ], c. 4, 22. y Donelli Comment, lib. 1, cap. 7, 8, 9 ; Reiffenstuel, Jus Canon. Univers. proem. 2, num. 3133. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY NATURAL LAW. 41 men in the common relations of human nature, without more. Such are the three heads enumerated by Pomponius religious duty to God, and the obligation to our parents, and to the community in which we live. 2 There may, it is true, be some doubt as to the third head, because duty to the community pre-supposes an institution. Yet that institution, which Pomponius calls patria, may be held so necessary a part of human being that it is matter of primary law. And so Cuja- cius, commenting on this text, says that duty to our country should have been placed before filial duty." Again, the precept alterum non Icedere belongs to the primary jus gentium. The secondary jus gentium in the civil law is that which, though flowing from natural reason, arises from certain things instituted to meet human wants. Examples are given by Ulpian and Hermoge- nianus in the Pandects. b The former begins by laying it down that the manumission of slaves is juris gentium. And he explains that by natural law all men are born free, and that by the usage of mankind which he here calls jus gentium slavery was introduced, and then came the benefit of manumission. Thus, manumission is matter of natural law, arising from the institution of slavery, which Florentinus describes as contrary to nature. Hermogenianus, in the celebrated text often referred to before, enumerates a variety of heads of law arising from the introduction of the rights of property, and other institutions generated by the wants and interests of mankind. Donellus, commenting on this law, observes that the heads mentioned therein are somewhat confused, and it does not show how they are distinguished from the former branch of jus gentium. And then he proceeds to the exposition of the text, arguing that in the beginning of the world, when men were few, it was not necessary that things should be appropriated to individuals, but after- wards the institution of property became requisite to prevent strife and confusion, and for the better enjoyment of things, and for other purposes of society. Hence that great head of the secondary jus gentium which comprises the laws of property. And from the same source came the different contracts, and commerce, and dealings among men regarding property, all of which are referred to by Her- mogenianus. To secure these things, and for other purposes of life, bodies of men came together, and buildings were collected, constituting towns and cities. By those means men, being congregated together, were better 1 L. 2, ff. De Just, et Jur. Cujac. Op. torn. 7, col. 23, E. b L. 4, 5, ff. De Just, et Jur.; Grotius, Droit de la G. 1. 1, ch. 1, 9, num. 7. c L. 4, 1, ff. De Statu Horn. 42 THE ORIGIN AND FOUNDATION OF LAW. able to secure and defend themselves, and to combine in the duties, and for the ends, of civilized life. Then for the government of aggregations of men kingdoms were constituted, and different sorts of commonwealths created : and cities and kingdoms having been formed, wars arose, and thence sprung the laws of war. Such is the law regarding captures in war. And so Grotius says that the maxim silent leges inter arma applies only to the civil and ordinary laws which belong to times and affairs of peace. a Donellus observes that the things enumerated in the second branch of jus gentium are not so clearly belonging to natural law as those in the first. Thus no one can deny religious duty to God, and the obligations between parent and child, to be of natural law. But it may be doubted whether this is so with regard to the distribution of property, and to contracts, and the laws of war. These are part, not of the natural law innate in man, but of that which was by the guid- ance of nature afterwards introduced. They arose out of what Gajus calls naturalis ratio. b And they are matters of natural law, because natural reason shows them to be requisite for the purposes of human society. On this principle, and in accordance with the famous law of Her- mogenianus, which we have been considering, Suarez holds that the political power of government, considered per se, is of divine right. d We must now briefly compare these important doctrines of the civil law with those laid down by Domat. The general ties which God constitutes among men by their nature, and by their destination to the same end under the same laws, are evidently part of the first branch of the jus gentium. It is the same with regard to the first of the two kinds of particular engagements which, according to Domat, determine men to exercise towards some particular persons duties which cannot be performed towards all mankind. These are the bonds of marriage and those of blood and affinity. The second kind of particular engagements is much more extensive, for we have seen that it comprehends all the other sorts of engage- ments arising from the intercommunion of men in the affairs and interests of social life. This class includes all the matters mentioned by Hermogenianus, and also those which he refers to by the last words of the text exceptis quibusdam qui a jure civili introductce sunt. Grot. Droit de la G., Disc. Prelim. 27. b L. 9, ff. De Just, et Jur. c Donelli Comment, lib. 1, cap. 7, ^ 16. d Suarez, De Leg. lib. 3, cap. 4, 5. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY NATURAL LAW. 43 These words regard a multitude of matters not part of the jus gentium, but instituted by municipal positive law, which is that described by Gajus Nam quod quisque populus ipse sibi jus constitute id ipsius civitatis proprium est: vocaturque jus civile, quasi jus proprium ipsius civitatis* With this exception the second kind of particular engagements belongs to the secondary jus gentium of the civil law. Domat's classification is more comprehensive than that which we have been investigating in the civil law, because he draws the plan of human society regarded with reference to all the obligations and engagements which constitute and perpetuate it. And he gives that plan, on the foundation of the two first laws, in order to show how all that multi- plicity of laws whereby mankind are governed flow from the two primary laws which are pointed out to man by his reason, and taught to him by positive revelation in the Gospel. And here we see how the Christian Religion, by teaching man beyond doubt the real end of his creation, has given him a clearer view of law, which is the rule of his conduct, directing him towards that end. And as the end of his creation is contained in the first of the two laws, out of which the second flows, so must all laws be in some way derived from them. All laws are either immediate results of the two first, or else bear a relation to the order of society which is founded on them, and are consequences of some law derived directly from those two primary laws. But all this will appear more clearly in the further prosecution of our inquiries. The next chapter will explain the doctrines of the jurists respecting the division of natural law into parts, and compare it with the classifi- cation of Domat. e L. 9, ff. De Just. et'Jur. 44 THE TWO BRANCHES OF NATURAL LAW. CHAPTER V. THE TWO BRANCHES OF NATURAL LAW PRIMARY AND SECONDARY FURTHER CONSIDERED ACCORDING TO THE JURISTS. THE doctrines of the Civil Law regarding the two branches of Natural Law have now been explained. We must consider the same subject according to the jurists who have taken a more extended view of it than the commentators on Justinian. The object in view is to give an account of a portion of legal science necessary for the useful study of jurisprudence ; and also to compare Domat's masterly scheme with other systems. We shall subsequently find that by thus establishing fundamental classifications and principles on a broad and sure basis, we are able to attain a far more easy and complete initiation into the mysteries of Public Law than would be possible by more abrupt method. We must now go on to consider the way in which the jurists have divided natural law, and compare it with the classification of ties or engagements springing from the two first laws, on which Domat has constructed his plan of society. Zallinger thus describes the rights and obligations belonging to primary natural law. Innate rights and obligations (jura connata) are those which are based on the nature of man and of things; and as the nature of man is the same in each individual, so these rights and obligations are the same in like manner, and thus they are universal. 8 The first of them is a certain legal equality among men considered simply as such, whereby whatever is legally due to any one that is to say, is just towards him is in like manner just towards everyone else. There is not by the law of nature any legal prerogative of one man considered .simply as such over another, whatever may be their difference in mental and physical powers. From this doctrine many important doctrines of public law are derived. Vattel has thus shown the source from whence they flow as regards international law : " As men are naturally equal, and their rights and obligations are the same, as equally proceeding from nature, so nations composed of men, and considered as free persons living together in a state of nature, are naturally equal, and have from nature the same rights and the same obligations. Power and weak- Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Natur et Eccles. lib. 1, 15 ; Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 2, ch. 3, 24. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY ACCORDING TO THE JURISTS. 45 ness produce no difference in this respect. A dwarf is as much a man as a giant ; and a little republic is as much a sovereign state as the most puissant kingdom." " A necessary consequence of this equality is that whatever is lawful for a nation is so also lawful to others, and vice versa" "A nation is therefore mistress of her own actions, provided they do not affect the proper and perfect rights of another " Nations being free, independent and equal, and each being bound to judge for herself what she ought to do for the performance of her duties, the effect of this is to cause, at least externally and among mankind, a perfect equality of rights among nations in the administra- tion of their affairs and the result of their claims, irrespective of the intrinsic justice of their conduct, of which others have no right to judge definitively. Thus, what is lawful to one is lawful also to another, and they must be considered in human society as having equal rights." 5 Pufendorf has devoted a chapter to the consideration of this natural equality of men. c He observes that the better to comprehend it, the doctrines of Hobbes should be examined. That writer reduces it to a mere equality of natural powers and faculties observable among grown-up men, from whence he infers that they all naturally have cause to fear each other. For he says, though one man be weaker than another, yet by the use of skill or stratagem, or by weapons, he can kill the stronger man, so that any full grown man can inflict on another, however strong he may be, the greatest of natural evils. d Thus, those who have to fear from each other similar evils, being equal between themselves, and as those who can cause to each other the greatest evils can inflict on each other lesser ones, it follows that all men are naturally equal. Hobbes adds, that the inequality now existing among men owes its origin to civil laws. But Pufendorf observes, that that inequality derived from civil laws regards only the states and condition of men, and not their natural powers. Therefore, it is not correct reasoning to juxtapose the inequality introduced by civil laws to the natural equality of human powers. And he also disapproves of the position which Hobbes endeavours ingeniously to maintain, that there is more equality in the faculties of the mind than in the strength of the body among men. Hobbes advances, that prudence proceeds solely from experience, and nature gives that quality in an equal space of time to all those who apply to anything b Vattel, Droit des Gens, Prelim. 18, 19. c Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 3, ch. 2 ; Devoir de 1'Homme et du Cit. I. 1, ch. 6. d Hobbes, Leviathan, chap. 13. 46 THE TWO BRANCHES OF NATURAL LAW. with the same degree of application. But this is not so "in general, as every day's experience shows, though in certain ordinary matters all men may be in some respects on a par. And though everyone is ready to resent being treated as below the usual level of human under- standing, and disposed to dislike those who profess to be wiser than their fellows, yet it does not follow that no one will acknowledge another to be superior in skill or parts to himself. But no one has a right to require that those who are less wise and less able than him- self should on that account submit to his rule without their consent, especially if they are satisfied with whatever capacity nature has given them. The equality which we are considering is of another nature than that of which Hobbes writes. As Pufendorf observes, its recognition is very important to mankind, for without it a well-regulated harmony cannot be maintained in that great variety of degrees in which nature dispenses to men the advantages of the body and of the mind. As in a well-regulated commonwealth every citizen enjoys liberty equally, though one be more wealthy and more highly considered than another; thus whatever advantages an individual may have over others in respect of the natural qualities of the body and the mind, he is never- theless bound to practise towards them the rules of Natural Law which they are bound to observe towards him. And he has no more right to injure them than they to hurt him. On the other hand even those who are most ill-treated by fortune and by nature are entitled to the full and peaceful enjoyment of the rights common to all men. In short, cceteris paribus there is no one of whatever condition who has not a right to require at the hands of others what they require from him. And to this principle is applicable that maxim of the Pandects, which says, Quod quisque juris in alterum statuerit, ut ipse eodemjure utatur.* And so Seneca says, Prima pars cequitatis est cequalitas. This equality of right, or legal equality, is founded on the principle that as the duties of sociability and the social state are necessary consequences of the constitution of human nature considered as such, they impose on all men in common an equally powerful and indispen- sable obligation. And this equality of law requires that as those who have advantages should not injure or insult those who are less for- tunate, so the latter should abstain from envying or dispoiling the former or disturbing them in the enjoyment of those advantages. Pufendorf also calls this natural equality of men, equality of power, or of liberty. It consists, he says, in this. No one (with an exception which will be mentioned presently) has any authority over any one else irrespectively of some human act or institution or convention. This equality is susperseded by the establishment of civil societies, e Pand. lib. 2, tit. 2. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY ACCORDING TO THE JURISTS. 47 wherein one or more persons have power to govern and command the others, who are bound to obey, whereby great inequality of persons has resulted, and the distinction between subjects and sovereigns. The exception referred to regards the status of fathers and mothers of families, and the relation between husband and wife, which produce an inequality of persons anterior to civil societies. But that inequality does not interfere with the natural equality which I have shown to exist between man and man considered simply as such. The relations between father and son, and husband and wife, are something super- added to that between man and man, and they do not indeed super- sede that equality of rights which results from primary natural law. But to this subject we shall return. As for the other inequalities existing in civil societies, they, as Pufendorf observes, clearly proceed from the will of the sovereign power. The inequalities among citizens after the institutions of sove- reign power, proceeds either from the administration of the government, which requires that certain persons be entrusted by the sovereign to exercise over others a portion of the supreme authority, or from some privilege granted by the sovereign. The relative diversity of fortunes produces by itself no real inequalities among citizens. Great wealth indeed gives the means of injuring or benefiting others, and so is a source of influence. But even real civil inequalities do not destroy the legal consequences of the natural equality of men/ The doctrine of natural equality is very important, not only as a fun- damental principle of Natural Law, but because it establishes as it were a plane surface on which divers rights and obligations are built. If it were otherwise, if men were created not with equal primary natural rights and obligations, but in different conditions or status simply as men, it would follow that there must be a different natural law for dif- ferent classes or kinds of men, and this would alter the whole science of jurisprudence. Thus Pufendorf combats the opinion which existed among the Greeks, that some men were naturally slaves, contrary to that of Ulpian, who says, that all men are by natural law born free. 8 There are, it is true, men who seem more fit to be slaves than to enjoy free- dom. But a natural adaptation to a particular state or condition does not suffice to place a person in that state. And it is clear that the distinction between free men and slaves is not by natural law. So Florentinus says, that slavery is an institution of the jus gentium, whereby a man is subjected to the dominion of another, contrary to f See on this subject, D'Aguesseau, Essai sur 1'Etat des Personnes, D'Aguesseau, CEuvres, torn. 5, p. 416. e L. 4, ff. De Just, et Jur. 48 THE TWO BRANCHES OF NATURAL LAW. nature?" He means that slavery is an institution of the arbitrary jus gentium, that is to say, a custom of nations arising out of war. And when Gajus says that the chief division in the law of persons classi- fies them as free men and slaves, 1 he refers to the classification of men not by natural law but by the Civil Law of Rome. We may here observe how it is that this doctrine of the natural equality of men has been perverted and made the source of false theo- ries. This has arisen from not seeing that the doctrine in question belongs only to primary natural law, or innate rights and obliga- tions (jura connata) which arise from the nature of man simply considered, that is to say, the relation between men merely as such, without more. And all that is to be found on the subject in the writ- ings of the great civilians jurists and theologians shows this. They all confine the doctrine of equality to the common rights of mankind, exclusive of the rights and obligations which arise from various pecu- liar relations which men bear to each other regarding the rights of persons and of things. Thus we have seen that Domat k speaks of the general ties which God makes among men by their nature and their destination to one and the same end under the same laws. But it is manifest, as he shows, that other particular ties must exist as well as those general ties with regard to which all men are equal. Primary natural law is evidently insufficient for the purposes of hu- man society. And indeed the relations of father and child and husband and wife cause a natural inequality. And natural equality and the rights arising therefrom are, as we have seen, so far from being incompatible with the various inequalities of power, arising from the wants of human society, that they actually confirm the rights springing from those inequalities. And such ine- qualities do not supersede or destroy the equality of men according to the primary natural law. We must now pursue the subject of absolute or innate rights and obligations. From the doctrine of the equality in law of all men con- sidered simply as such, it results that they have the same abso- lute rights. And thence it follows that no one should injure or infringe the absolute rights of another. The duties of a man with reference to other men are of two classes. The first consists of those which are solely founded on the mutual obligations which the Creator imposes on men in common, simply as h L. 4, 1, ff. De Statu Horn. 1 L. 3, ff. De Statu Horn. And see Somerset v. Stuart, Lofft. 1 ; Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Nat. et-Eccl. lib. 1, 15; Montesq. Esprit des Loix, lib. 15, ch. 7. k Domat, Trait^ des Loix, ch. 2, 3. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY ACCORDING TO THE JURISTS. 49 such, and the other class supposes some human establishment, either instituted or adopted by men, or an adventitious or accessary state such as that of father and son, master and servant, &c. The former must be practised by and towards all men, whereas the latter are obli- gatory only with reference to certain persons. This classification, taken from Zallinger and Pufendorf, very clearly shows the two branches into which the jurists divide Natural Law. 1 The absolute or innate duties of man with reference to other men are ranged by Pufendorf under three heads. The first consists of the general duty of doing no harm or injury to any one. This is the second of the three precepts of Ulpian, namely, alterum non Icedere, A consequence thereof is the obligation of making reparation or com- pensation for any injury or damage which you have done to any one. Zallinger observes, that this is not properly itself an absolute obliga- tion and right, because it arises from an act done. But it is neverthe- less correctly placed by Pufendorf, because it is a necessary conse- quence of the rule of law alterum non Icedere, and included therein. The second head comprises all the rights and obligations arising from the natural equality of men. The third includes what are called the common duties of humanity. "The third general duty," says Pufendorf, " whereby you are bound towards all other persons, considered simply as members of the human race, is, that each ought to contribute, so far as he conveniently can, to the benefit and advantage of others." n The duties included under this general head are those which have been called of imperfect obligation. They are comprehended in uni- versal justice, which requires the performance of all duties towards others : whereas particular justice regards only those which, because they are necessary for the preservation of mankind and the maintenance of human society in general, may be enforced by human authority and power. These duties of imperfect obligation are virtues belonging to the province of morality and religion. And yet they also appertain to natural law, because even the mere outward fulfilment of those obliga- tions is highly beneficial to the peace and welfare of society. And so Pothier observes, in a note on the first precept of Ulpian, honeste vivere, that it forbids not only what is forbidden by express laws, but 1 Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Nat. et Eccles. Publ. lib. 1, 15 ; Pufend. Devoir de 1'Homme et du Cit. 1.1, ch. 4, 1 ; Pufend. Droit des Gens, 1. 2, ch. 3, 24. m L. 10, 1, ff. De Just, et Jur. n Pufend. Devoir de 1'Homme et du Cit. ch. 8. Pufend. ibi, 1. 1, ch. 2, 14, n. 1, Barbeyrac ; and see Pufend. Droit des Gens, 1. 1, c. 7, 7, 8. The same doctrine is less clearly expressed by Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Nat. et Eccles. Publ. lib. 1, 17. E 50 THE TWO BRANCHES OF NATURAL LAW. everything against good morals, piety and honour. p And Papinian, in a celebrated law in the Pandects, says, defining legal impossibility, Qua facia verecundiam, officium, pietatem nostrum l&dunt, et generaliter contra bonos mores sunt, nee facere nos posse dicendum est.^ And so St. Thomas Aquinas includes in natural law, not only precepts, but counsels/ This general view of the obligations called innate, and belonging to primary natural law, shows that they do not suffice by themselves, because they look on each man, apart from any dealing or engage- ment with other men, and from any of those establishments or institu- tions, such as civil government and property, which are requisite for human society. And this. observation leads us to hypothetical or con- ditional obligations, with their correlative rights. They are matter of secondary natural law. Zallinger defines them to be those rights and obligations which cannot exist except on the hypothesis of some previous act, or adven- titious status, and circumstances of place and time. According to him hypothetical rights and obligations are of three classes ; as they arise from agreement or pact, from the abolition of the community of things, that is to say, the introduction of exclusive property, and from social states or conditions. 8 So we have seen that Domat teaches, that be- sides those general and common ties which God has constituted among men by their nature and their destination to the same end under the same laws, He has added other particular engagements. And these are of two kinds, namely, those which are formed by the natural ties of marriage and birth, comprising consanguinity and affinity ; and in the second place, those which arise from other sorts of engagements among men. 4 The right which men have of binding themselves, by their consent, is an original or innate or absolute right. And so Savigny, treating of re- lations of law, that is to say, legal obligations and rights arising between individuals, starts from the free will of man to act within certain limits of right. He shows that that will may be applied to things or to per- sons. And by virtue of it we may have dominion over things, or over some act or acts of another person. In the former case the result is property in its simplest form, and in the latter, what is designated as obligation, that is to say, the relation of law, whereby we control a P Pothier, Pand. Justin, lib. 50, tit. 17, sect. 1, art. 2, 1. 18. ) L. 15, ff. De Condition. Instit. r Suarez, De Leg. lib. 2, cap. 8, $11. 8 Zallinger, ubi sup. lib. 1, cap. 3, 16. The first class here added by Zallinger seems grounded on a too subtle distinction. Pufeud. Droit des Gens, I. 2, ch. 3, 24. 1 Domat, Loix Civ. Traitd des Loix, ch. 2, 3. PRIMARY AND SECONDARY ACCORDING TO THE JURISTS. 51 determined act or acts -of a person." This obligation may resolve itself into a sum of money or some other thing, that is to say, transfer property to us. And the greater number of obligations have for their object the absolute acquisition or the temporary enjoyment of property. The aggregate of the relations which thus extend the power of an indi- vidual over things, is called his property (bona), and the institutions which regulate them are called the law of things* The obligations and rights thus described and classified by Savigny are what the jurists call hypothetical, or conditional, and they belong to secondary natural law, so far as they are not regulated by positive law. They are called hypothetical or conditional, because they pre- suppose an act of human will, and the institution of property ; that is to say, exclusive rights over things. Zallinger observes that the greater number of hypothetical obligations spring from the introduc- tion of dominium, or the right of property. Taken in its widest sense, it includes both dominion over the thing itself, irrespective of right as against any particular person, and right to a thing by virtue of an obli- gation of a person, arising either from consent, or from the law without such consent, but in consequence of some fact. The former is called jus in re or dominium, in the strict acceptation of the term, and the latter jus ad rernJ The social state and its consequences are also the causes of a multi- tude of hypothetical or conditional rights and obligations, which, except so far as they belong to positive law, are also part of the secondary natural law. All these heads of hypothetical or conditional obligations are among those particular ties, as contradistinguished from the general ties, which, according to Domat, unite men among themselves. And they are originally grounded on the two primary laws, for as God has di- rected man to accomplish those laws, and for that purpose has des- tined him for society, so He has ordained those rights and obligations which are the ties uniting men in that state, and rendering it capable of accomplishing the object for which it was instituted. We have now sufficiently examined the distinction between the two chief branches of natural law, as taught by the civilians and jurists, and we have shown the bearing of their doctrines on the plan drawn by Domat in his treatise of laws. The full value of this will appear, when we come to consider the various sorts of laws by which society is governed, and the ways in which they accomplish their object. Savigny, Trait du Droit Rom. torn. 1, ch. 1, p. 328 333, 53. * Ibi, pp. 333, 334. > Zallinger, ubi supra, 16, 3. E2 52 GENERAL PLAN AND NATURE OF HUMAN SOCIETY CHAPTER VI. GENERAL PLAN AND NATURE OF HUMAN SOCIETY ON THE FOUNDATION OF THE TWO PRIMARY LAWS. WE have examined the general character of the two branches of natural law, and their connection with the two primary laws on which Domat has founded his plan of human society. That investigation shows how the distinction between primary and secondary natural law bears upon the classification given by Domat of the ties which unite men in the association to which they are destined, for the exer- cise and accomplishment of the two great fundamental or primary laws prescribing man's duty to God and to his neighbour. Thus the general ties which God has constituted among men by their nature, and their destination to the same end under the same laws, belong to primary natural law. a But those general ties are not sufficient, and the particular engagements which bind men together in the exercise of the second of the two great primary laws, constitute particular laws prescribing to every man what that law requires of him. These, for the most part, belong to secondary natural law, because they pre-suppose some act done, such as a contract, or some institution, such as property and civil society. I say for the most part, because among the particular ties are those which arise from the relation between the two sexes, which are so necessary a part of human nature that they must be considered as matters of primary natural law. It will appear more and more, as we proceed, that these distinctions and classifications are valuable both for scientific and for practical purposes. We will now see how Domat works out his plan of human society on the foundation of the two fundamental or primary laws command- ing love of God and of our neighbour. He first lays it down that God forms the order of human society, by the ties of both sorts, to bind men together in the exercise of the second law. And because each engagement shows what it prescribes to those whom He has bound by it, we may see in the characteristics of the different sorts of engagements, the foundations of the rules of that Florentinus says, " Inter nos cognitionem quamdatn natura constituit;'' 1. 3, ff. De Just, et Jur. ON THE FOUNDATION OF THE TWO PRIMARY LAWS. 53 which justice and equity require of each person according as he is placed. Domat then proceeds to the first sort of those particular engage- ments among mankind those which marriage constitutes with all its consequences. Marriage and the birth of children constitute a particular society in each family, which has been held to be the germ of all others. In a law of Ulpian we find both the conjunction which among man- kind is called marriage, and the care and rearing of the young, included among the things regulated by that supposed natural law common to man and other animals. b And Pomponius holds the obligations between children and parents to be of primary natural law. c Thus Domat, placing the engagement of marriage first among the particular ties which unite men in society, teaches that not only all the laws regulating the duties of husband and wife, but also the laws of the Church, and the civil laws regarding marriage, are founded on the mode in which God instituted that engagement at the creation of man. The bond of marriage is followed by that of birth, which unites the parents with their children, and is the foundation of all the duties arising from that relation. Thus children are made dependent on their parents in their infancy, and the parents on their children in age and infirmity ; and a strong mutual affection is implanted in the breasts of both by the Creator. Thence comes all that civil laws have regulated regarding the reciprocal duties of parent and child such as the paternal power over the persons and property of children, and the right of parents to receive aliment from them. And on the same ordinance of God, whereby children receive life from their parents, are grounded the laws which give the property of the parents at their death to their children. The reason is, that property is given to men for the different wants of life. Therefore, on the death of their parents, the inheritance should devolve on the surviving issue as an accessory of life derived from their progenitors. Marriage and birth also constitute two other sorts of natural ties, which are consequences following them. The first is that of colla- terals, called consanguinity or agnation, and the latter is that of alliance, or affinity or cognation. Consanguinity unites collaterals, that is to say, those whose birth originates from a common ascendant or ancestor, and hence is derived the relationship which unites them. This connexion is the foundation b L. l,ff. De Just, et Jur. c L. 2, ff. De Just, et Jur. And see Suarez, De Leg. lib. 3, ch. 1, \. 54 GENERAL PLAN AND NATURE OP HUMAN SOCIETY of divers civil laws in different countries such as those which forbid marriages among near relatives, give inheritances and guardianships, and exclude witnesses and judges related to a party to a suit. Alliance or affinity is the connexion which marriage constitutes between the husband and his wife's relations, and the wife and her husband's relations. It is grounded on the close union between the husband and the wife, whereby those who are bound by relationship to either of them, are also bound to the other. And it is the reason of many laws analogous to those just mentioned. d This sketch will suffice to show the nature of the first sort of ties which unite men together, and whereby God has bound them in order to the formation of civil society. We now proceed to the second kind of engagements or ties ; and this is, perhaps, the most masterly part of Domat's celebrated plan. 6 As the engagements of marriage and birth, and the ties resulting from them, are limited between particular persons with regard to each other, and God has placed men in society to exercise generally the second of the two primary laws, He has rendered necessary in society another sort of engagements, which bind together indifferently persons of all kinds. It is to constitute this sort of engagements that God multiplies the wants of men, and makes them necessary to each other for all those wants. And in two ways they are placed in the order of engagements to which they are destined. The first of these ways is the arrangement of persons in society, where each has his place assigned to him, indicating the relations which bind him to others, and the duties proper to that place. And this is effected by birth, by education, by disposition or inclination, and by the other effects of his conduct, which cause the arrangement or placing of men in the community to which they belong. By this first means God constitutes to all men the general engagements of conditions, professions, and employments, and places every person in some certain condition of life of which particular engagements are to be the consequences. The second way is the disposal of events and conjunctures which lead each man to particular engagements, according to the occasions and circumstances in which he finds himself. All these sorts of engagements of this second kind are either volun- tary or not voluntary ; that is to say, they arise from consent, or are constituted independently of the consent of the party bound. For as man is free there are engagements into which he enters by his will ; and as he is dependent on the Divine order, so there are engagements d Domat, Loix Civ. Traite des Loix, ch. 3. e Ibi, cli. 4. ON THE FOUNDATION OF THE TWO PRIMARY LA.WS. 55 in which God places him without his own choice. But whether the engagements originate from, or independently of, his consent, it is by his free will that man acts in them. And every part of his conduct bears these two characteristics that is to say, dependence on God, whose ordinance he ought to follow, and his free will, which should lead him to that obedience. Thus all these kinds of engagements are proportioned both to the nature of man and to his condition during this life. The voluntary engagements are of two kinds. Some are mutually formed among two or more persons, who by their will bind and engage themselves reciprocally one to another. And others are constituted by the will of one person, who engages himself to another person or per- sons without their treating with him. Domat gives the following examples of these two kinds of engage- ments. As an illustration of the first kind, he observes, that for the different purposes for which men require to communicate one with an- other their work and industry, and for the different commerce in all sorts of things, they form associations or partnerships, buy and sell, let and hire, borrow and lend, exchange, and enter into other sorts of mutual contracts. And to explain the second kind of engagements, Domat refers to that of an heir, who becomes liable, according to the civil law, to the debts of the deceased. For by the civil law an heir (whether testa- mentary or legal) is una eademque persona cum defuncto* arid, there- fore, is liable for all his debts that are not extinguished by his death. The old civil law was modified in this respect, for Justinian granted to heirs the benefit of inventory, that is to say, the power to provide an authentic inventory of the estate and effects, and thereby discharge themselves from all liability to his debts beyond the value of the in- heritance. 5 But still the principle of hereditary representation remains part of the civil law. And it is evident that the engagement of the heir to the creditors of the deceased, arises without any agreement or dealing between him and them. Another instance of this sort is to be found in the civil law quasi contract, called negotiorum gestorum. It is thus explained by Justinian : " When any one has transacted the business of an absent man (negotia absentis gesserit) there arise mutual actions between them, which are called actions negotiorum gestorum." The person who received the service has the actio directa, and the other the actio contraria. These actions spring from no contract, for they obtain where any one spontaneously undertakes business or the f See my Commentaries on the Modern Civil Law, p. 299. E Instit. lib. 2, tit. 12, De Heredum Qualitate, 5. And see Cod. lib. 6, tit. 30, De Jure Deliberandi, L. ult. 56 GENERAL PLAN AND NATURE OF HUMAN SOCIETY management of the property of another, without any mandate or au- thority. This law was received by reason of its utility, that the busi- ness of those who are absent may not be neglected : for no one would take this care upon himself unless he had an action to recover what he had expended." h A further example of this nature is to be found in divers offices or employments, the acceptance of which produces an obligation to fulfil the engagements that are the consequences thereof. The person accepting such office or employment is bound to those in- terested in its duties, though there is no agreement or dealing between him and them. We come now to involuntary engagements. They are those in which men are placed without their own will and choice. Thus there are municipal and legal offices or duties, such as that of sheriff and jurymen, which some persons are not permitted to decline without law- ful excuse. So it is with the office of guardian in the civil law. And when the business of an absent man has been done v without his know- ledge and authority, the civil law requires him to repay what has been reasonably expended and to ratify what has been well done. 1 He whose merchandise has been saved in a storm by the ship being dis- charged of goods thrown into the sea to lighten it, is bound to bear his share of the loss in proportion to what is saved for him. k The condition of those without means and incapable of working for their subsistence ingenders an engagement on the part of the others to ex- ercise towards them the second of the two fundamental laws which prescribes our duty to our neighbours, by enabling them to live. And on this principle the poor law is founded as Blackstone shows. And so Domat lays it down that every man being a member of society has a right to live therein; and what is necessary for those who have nothing and cannot earn their livelihood is consequently in the hands of the others, who cannot therefore refuse them relief. On the same principle, in times of public necessity individuals are compelled, even by legal authority, to assist the poor according to their wants. 1 And so the condition of persons suffering from injustice and oppression or unlawful wrong causes an engagement on the part of those who are invested with offices of justice and good government to protect them. m To these examples may be added the various obligations incumbent on every man as a member of human society, which are independent h Instit. lib. 3, tit. 28, 1. 1 Ibi; and see the French Civil Code, art. 1372. k Pandect, lib. 14, tit 2, ad Leg. Rhodiam ; Voet ad Pand. lib. 14, tit. 2, and the authors cited there ; French Code Civ. 415. 1 Domat, Trait6 des Loix, ch. 4, ^ 4. m See Magna Chart. Nulli negabitnus, &c. ON THE FOUNDATION OF THE TWO PRIMARY LAWS. 57 of his own act or consent, because he cannot refuse to fulfil those obligations without violating secondary natural law. And that law arises from the ordinance of God and not from the will of man. This theory of obligations, arising without the act and consent of the party bound, is a very important part of Public Law, which we shall have occasion to examine further hereafter. The false doctrines of Rousseau, in his Contrat Social, may be traced to ignorance of this sub- ject. His system is based on the false notion that all obligations and engagements must arise from consent of the party bound." That notion is partly countenanced by the error of Trebonian, who, in the Institutes, entitles obligations arising neither from a contract nor from a wrong, by the denomination of obligations quasi fx contractu. And this some civilians have explained by deducing those obligations arising without consent, from tacit or presumed or feigned consent. But the correct doctrine is that they are independent of consent and have therefore nothing in common with contracts, but they arise from the law. Obligations arising thus from the law without consent or agreement are of two classes. First, those which spring from the law alone, without any act of the person on whom the obligation is imposed. Secondly, those which arise from the law, on the occasion of an act of the person obliged, or of an act of the person to whom he becomes bound, or of a fortuitous occurrence. 1 " The obligations whereby every man is bound to pay taxes and perform certain public duties in the community to which he belongs, are instances of obliga- tions springing from the law alone. Obligations of the first class arise immediately, as those of the second spring mediately from the law, for every obligation must pro- ceed from the law, either natural or municipal. Obligations arising mediately from the law are brought into exist- ence by the law on the occasion of some act. Thus the obligation of a thief to restore the goods which he has stolen, arises from the law of property to which he has rendered himself amenable by his own act. The act of the person to be bound thus precedes the obligation, and is a condition precedent to the existence of the obligation ; but the obligation springs from the law on the occasion of the act. That act may be either lawful or unlawful. Of the first descrip- tion are those obligations which Trebonian in Justinian's Institutes derives quasi ex contractu, and of the second are those which he deduces ex delicto and quasi ex delicto.* n Rousseau, Contrat Social, ch. 4. See my Commentaries on the Modern Civil Law, ch. 11, where the subject is fully explained. P Ibi, p. 236. Ibi, pp. 236, 237. 58 GENERAL PLAN AND NATURE OF HUMAN SOCIETY All these various classes and descriptions of engagements bind man- kind together in a multitude of different ways in that social condition for which they are intended. And it is evident, as Domat tells us, that God constitutes them and places men under them for the purpose of uniting mankind together in the exercise of the second fundamental low, commanding us to love our neighbour/ And all the duties prescribed by those engagements are the effects which that law ought to produce according to the different conjunctures and circumstances. Thus the rules which prescribe to render to every man what is due to him, to wrong no one, and to observe faithfulness to promises, and sincerity, 8 are included in the second law. And the same may be said of the duties of a guardian to his ward, and of persons holding offices and employments, and indeed of the duties required by all other en- gagements among men. Domat gives as an example the case of a man who has in his possession the sword of a madman, or of a person inflamed with violent passion. He is bound by virtue of the second law not to restore the weapon to its owner until he is in a condition to make no bad use of it. And that great jurist adds, that his object is to show that as the second fundamental law is the spirit and principle of all those which regulate engagements among mankind, it is not sufficient to know, as even barbarians do, that we ought to render to every man that which is his, and to wrong no one, and to observe good faith, and similar rules ; but it is necessary also to regard the spirit of those rules and the source of their truth in the second law, in order to give them all the effect and extent which they ought to have. And he observes, that for want of this doctrine judges sometimes look upon those rules simply as political laws, without understanding their spirit, which requires a more abundant justice, and therefore do not give them the extensive effect which they ought to have, but tolerate breaches of faith and injustice which judges would repress if the spirit of the second law were their principle. Domat further observes, that engagements require the use of a government to keep every one in the order of their obligations. It is for the purposes of government that God has established the authority of powers requisite to maintain society. And it is necessary to add here with regard to engagements and government, that there are some constituted through the order of that government, such as those between princes and subjects, and between persons in public dignities and offices and private persons, and others of that nature. r Domat, Loix Civ. Traite des Loix, ch. 4, 5. L. ff. De Just, et Jur. ON THE FOUNDATION OF THE TWO PRIMARY LAWS. 59 One great feature of this general plan, drawn by the masterly hand of Domat under the immediate advice of the Chancellor D'Aguesseau, is, that it is based not on any imaginary system or hypothesis such as the social compact, or that state of hostility among men invented by Hobbes, but on the different classes of ties or obligations which actually unite men together in the social state, and are all deduced from the two primary laws laid down in the Gospel as the foundation of all law. Domat constructs his system by analysis of human society, showing the means whereby Divine Providence has led mankind to, and main- tains them in the social state, according to the principles of the law of nature. In order to complete the plan of society, it is now necessary to give an idea of the succession which perpetuates it ; and we shall next see how God causes it to subsist in its present state. The order of successions is grounded on the necessity of continuing and transmitting the state of society from the passing generation to that which follows. And this is done imperceptibly, by causing certain persons to succeed in the place of those who die, to enter into their rights, their duties, and those relations and engagements which are of a nature to pass to successors. It would be out of place to enter here into the different modes of succession or inheritance by the natural order and that of municipal laws, and by the will of persons appointing those who are to succeed them. It is sufficient to observe here, that successions must be distinguished from the engagements hitherto considered. For though succession constitutes an engagement into which those persons enter who succeed to others, yet successions ought not to be considered under this aspect. They should be looked upon with reference to the change by which property, rights, and obligations, pass from those who die to their successors. 1 According to the civil law, which makes the heir, or the coheirs, the representative of the deceased, this view of successions is obvious. And even in the English and Scotch laws, which make a distinction between real and personal, or heritable and personal estate, it is correct. For the executor or administrator must be considered as the temporary successor of the deceased in his personal property, which is vested in him until he has fully administered the estate. But with reference to Public Law the heir is the principal successor, because he succeeds to real property and hereditary dignities and offices, and takes the place in the community which was occupied by the deceased. And legatees maybe looked upon as successors of the deceased, so far as regards the legacy which is transmitted from him. ' Domat, Loix Civ. Trait des Loix, ch. 7. 60 GENERAL PLAN AND NATURE OF HUMAN SOCIETY A legal capacity also belongs to certain fictitious beings, called juridical persons, which exist only for certain legal purposes. Their legal character appertains, as Savigny observes, principally to private law having reference to property," but they cannot be omitted in a plan of human society. With respect to these corporate bodies, called in the civil law universitates, which are considered in law in the light of persons/ they have no successors, for they are invested with a sort of legal privilege of immortality. Yet there is a succession within them whereby new members are put in the place of those who die, or cease to be members. This succession is regulated according to the con- stitution of each corporate body. Although the parts composing these bodies be constantly changed, yet the identity of the whole remains. y And persons succeed others in various offices and employments by different ways, such as appointment and election. By all these means society is perpetuated and handed down from one generation to another, with the various modifications which from time to time it undergoes. We have now to consider the condition of society after the fall of man, and how God makes it subsist in the condition to which that fall reduced it. Domat teaches, that everything we see in society contrary to order is a natural consequence of disobedience to the first law, which com- mands the love of God ; for as that law is the foundation of the second, which commands men to love each other, man could not violate the first without falling at the same time into a condition which made him break the second also, and consequently disturb society. The first law (continues the great civilian) should have united men in the possession of the Supreme Good, and they would have found therein two perfections which would have made them happy in com- mon, one that it may be possessed by all, and the other that it can form the entire happiness of each. But man, having broken the first law, and having forsaken that true happiness which he could only find in God, sought it in material temporal things, in which he found two defects, one that those things cannot be possessed by all, and the other that they cannot make any one perfectly happy. Thence divisions and discord necessarily arose, because those who place their happiness in the possession of things of that nature, must clash in their pursuit Savigny, Traite" de Droit Remain, torn. 2, pp. 234, 236. * Voet, Comm. ad Pand. lib. 3, tit. 4, 1 ; Pand. lib. 46, tit. 1, De Fidejussoribus, 1. 22. And see Domat, Droit Publ. liv. 1, tit. 15. y Pand. lib. 5, tit. 1, De Judiciis, 1. 76; Pand. lib. 3, tit. 4, Quod cujusque Uni- versitatis nomine, 1. 7, 2. ON THE FOUNDATION OF THE TWO PRIMARY LAWS. 61 of the same objects, and they violate all kinds of obligations and engagements, according to the dictates of their desire for the things which they seek to obtain. 2 But out of that principle of selfishness, contrary to the mutual good will which is the foundation of society, God has devised a remedy which causes it to subsist. For that principle of division among men becomes a bond which unites them in a thousand ways, and maintains the greater part of their engagements. The following reasons will show the truth of this position. The fall of man multiplied his wants and augmented the necessity of labour and commerce, and also of engagements and ties among men ; for as no one can alone suffice to himself, the diversity of wants engages men to an infinite diversity of ties or connections without which they could not live. This condition of mankind leads those who act only on selfish mo- tives, to submit themselves to labour and engage in commerce and obligations which their wants render necessary. And in order to render those things useful to themselves, they are obliged, for the sake of their credit reputation and interest, to observe good faith and ho- nesty. Thus selfishness adapts itself to circumstances, and knows so well how to regulate the means according to the end in view, that it even imitates all the virtues. Self-love therefore, that principle of evil, is in the present state of society a cause of many effects which, being in themselves good, ought to have a better origin ; and thus that poison of society may be re- garded as a remedy provided by God to sustain it. The other causes whereby God sustains society are of a different nature, because they are not evils out of which good is produced, but they are the natural foundations of order. Domat divides them into four different sorts, comprehending all that maintains society. The first is Religion, which causes all that is regulated by the spirit of the two primary laws. The second is the secret providence of God over society in the whole world. The third is the authority which God gives to powers. The fourth is that light retained by man after his fall, which teaches him the natural rules of right and wrong. It is that light of reason which, showing to all men the common rules of justice and equity binding upon them by the Divine Will, is a law to them; a and it has remained in their minds in spite of the z Domat, Loix Civ. Traite des Loix, ch. 9, 1. 8 Rom. ii. 14; L. 7, ff. De bon. damn. ; Schmalzgrueber, Jus Eccles. Univers. ; Dis- sert, proem. ^ ii. 54 ; Suarez, De Leg. lib. 1, c. 6, n. 13. 62 GENERAL PLAN AND NATURE OF HUMAN SOCIETY darkness which self-love has spread there. Thus all men bear in their minds the impression of the truth and authority of these natural laws, that they ought to wrong no man, that they should render to every one what belongs to him, that they are bound to be honest in en- gagements, and faithful to execute promises, and other similar rules of justice; for the knowledge of these rules is inseparable from reason, and indeed reason itself is their knowledge and use. And, as Domat truly observes, though this light of reason giving a perception of those truths to men ignorant of their first principles, does not reign over every one in such wise as to make him regulate his conduct thereby, yet it so far prevails, that even the most unjust, love justice enough to condemn and hate injustice in others ; and each man being interested in the observance of those rules towards himself, the greater number compel obedience on the part of those who resist their precepts and commit wrong against others. This shows that God has engraven on the minds of all men, that sort of knowledge and love of justice without which society could not subsist. And by means of that knowledge of natural laws, even nations ignorant of religion have maintained their society. But this would not suffice to be the foundation of society without the government which God exercises over mankind, and the order which is preserved in human society by Divine Providence. Thereby the earth is divided among the human species; nations are distinguished one from the other with the diversity of kingdoms, republics, and other kinds of states ; their extent and duration are determined by the course of events, and society is sustained in each state by the distinction of persons to fill different stations, employments, and places. And the same Providence, to maintain society, establishes therein two kinds of powers calculated to keep men in the order of their engagements. The first consists in natural'powers regarding natural engagements, such as the authority which marriage gives to a husband over his wife, and birth to parents over their children. But as this sort of authority is restricted within the limits of families, God has ordained another kind of authority extending over the universal order of all sorts of engagements and all that regards society. And He gives this power differently in kingdoms, republics and other states, to kings, princes, and other persons raised into authority by birth, by election, and by other means. And for the same order the exercise of that authority is communicated to and distributed among different persons, with vari- ous sorts of degrees and power. We have now a sketch of the nature of human society, showing its derivation from the two primary laws, by means of the ties which con- stitute and maintain it. ON THE FOUNDATION OF THE TWO PRIMARY LAWS. 63 We must next examine the nature and spirit of the various sorts of laws which govern mankind, and which are all derived from those two primary fundamental Divine Laws. CHAPTER VII. ON THE NATURE AND SPIRIT OF LAWS. IMMUTABLE LAWS. IN the last chapter a plan of society has been drawn on the foun- dation of the two great first Laws, by showing the relation which the state of man in this life has to each of them, and the way in which God having destined man to society has constituted the ties which engage him in that state. We have seen that it is by those ties or engagements that God forms the order of the society of mankind to link them together in the exer- cise of the second Law. And as God marks in every engagement what He enjoins to those who are bound by it, so the characters of the different sorts of engagements show the foundations of the several rules prescribing that which justice and equity require of every person according to the conjunctures in which his particular engagements place him. We have seen how ties or engagements imply and require the use and advantage of a civil government to restrain every one within the order of those that belong to him. And we have seen also that there are four foundations of the order of society in its present state, that is to say, the general knowledge of justice or right and wrong, the government of God over society, the authority which God gives to supreme powers, and true religion, which includes and explains the three first. And in a former chapter I have shown the origin and necessity of laws, whereby the actions of men are regulated in all the relations and engagements in which they are placed on earth ; and this according to the definition of St. Thomas Aquinas, who says, Lex est qucedam regula et mensura secundum quam inducitur aliquis ad agendum vel non agendum. We must now proceed to examine the nature and spirit of laws and their different kinds. Suarez first divides laws into Eternal and Temporal Laws. By the former he means (following St. Augustine) what Plato calls Divine Law, that is to say, a law existing in God himself and the same with the rea- son of Divine Providence. The latter differs from it as that which is created differs from that which is uncreated. It includes that kind of 64 ON THE NATURE AND SPIRIT OF LAWS. Divine Law, which God creates, as it were, extraneously to himself, as well as all other laws that are not eternal. Suarez then gives the distinction recognised by all the theologians, and frequently used in the works of the Saints, that is to say, that of natural from positive law. b It is also to be found in the Pandects. This distinction is the basis of the system of Domat, to which we will principally direct our attention. Domat begins by laying it down that every sort of laws may be reduced to two kinds, which comprehend all laws of whatever nature. One is, of the laws which are immutable, and the other of those that are arbitrary. These two characters are the most essential part of the nature of all laws. The former class of laws include those which the theologians com- prise under the term Lex tsterna. St. Augustine says, Legem ceternam esse summam raiionem in Deo existentem cui obtemperandum est. A The latter words show that he means natural law, considered as a rule of conduct applied to men, and this remarkable passage agrees with the definition of St. Thomas Aquinas. Lex naturalis nihil aliud est quam participatio legis ceternce in rationali creatura.* But this part of the subject should be fully explained before we proceed, because it is important to establish fundamental doctrines as clearly as possible. St. Thomas Aquinas discusses the question whether it can properly be said that the attribute of justice belongs to God, and, according to his usual method, he states divers objections, the chief point of which consists in the difficulty of supposing justice where there is perfect freedom of will, and no duty or obligation. He answers that there are two species of justice. One consists in mutual obligations or giving and accepting, such for instance as buying and selling, and other communications or commutations of like nature, which is called commutative justice. And this cannot be an attribute of God. The other species consists in distribution, and is called dis- tributive justice, according to which a governor gives to each in pro- portion to his deserts/ Grotius explains the same distinction, and says, that distributive justice, considered as a rule of human actions, is the companion of the virtues which tend solely to the advantage of others, such as liberality, compassion and wise conduct in the govern- ment of a state.* 5 b Suarez, De Leg. lib. 1, cap. 3, ^ 6, 7. c Pand. lib. 1, tit. 1, 1. 9. d L. 1, De liber. Arbitr. c. 6. e 1, 2, qusest. 91, art. 2. f Div. Thorn. Summa Theol. par. 1, quaest 21, art.l. Grot. Dr. de la G. 1. 1, ch. 1, $ 8 ; Pufend. Dr. de la N. et des Gens, 1. 1 , cb. 7, $ 1 1 . IMMUTABLE LAWS. 65 St. Thomas continues, " As therefore the fitting and due govern- ment of a family, or of any multitude, shows this sort of justice in their ruler, so the order of the universe, which appears both in natural things and in voluntary things, shows the justice of God." "Asa right apprehended by the intellect is the object of will, it is impossible that God should will anything except that which is according to the rule of his wisdom. Hence he does justly according to his will, as we do justly what we do according to the law. But we act according to the law of a superior, whilst God is a law to himself." St. Thomas goes on to show that in one sense things may be due from the Divine will. For it is due to things created that they should have that to which they are ordained, and so God works justice by giving to each that which is due to it according to the principles of its nature and condition as Divine wisdom has ordained. So that God's justice con- sists in the fulfilment of His wisdom. On the other hand it is due of right to God that his wisdom and his will should be fulfilled. Debitum est Deo ut impleatur in rebus id quod ejus sapientia et voluntas habet et quod suam bonitatem manifestat : et secundum hoc justitia Dei re- spicit decentiam ipsius secundum quam reddit sibi quod sibi debetur. h From these doctrines several important consequences may be de- duced. They explain the celebrated dispute between Barbeyrac and Leibnitz respecting the efficient cause of natural law. 1 Leibnitz charged Pufendorf with seeking that efficient cause, not in the nature of things and the maxims of right reason conformable thereto, and which emanate from the Divine mind, but simply in the will of a su- perior. Barbeyrac, however, shows that Pufendorf admits, in accord- ance with St. Thomas, a natural law, founded on the nature of things, which the Divine will could not contravene without being inconsistent with itself. k And then he continues thus : " Our author does not pre- tend that all that is called right or justice emanates from the arbitrary will of a superior. He speaks of right and justice which are fitting for independent beings. And he seeks for the rule of human actions. He says that God is supremely just and follows inviolably the rules of justice, which are in conformity with His infinite perfections ; so that He cannot act otherwise, but also, no one can require Him to act in a particular manner. And Pufendorf holds that with regard to men, though they are entirely dependant on the Creator, yet God has not made right and justice by an arbitrary will ; and that God could not, h Div. Thorn. Summa Theol. par. 1, qusest. 21, art. 1. And see Grotius, Dr. de la G. 1. 1, ch. 1, 10, num. 5. 1 Jugement d'un Anonyme, p. 406, printed with the Devoir de 1'Homme et du Citoyen, edit. Amsterdam, 1735. k Pufend. Droit de la Nat. et des Gens, 1. 1, ch. 2, 5, 6. F 66 ON THE NATURE AND SPIRIT OF LAWS. without inconsistency with his own perfections, prescribe to men any other rules than those of justice. But our writer maintains, notwith- standing, that the will of God, who, as their sovereign master, has full right to restrain their freedom as he thinks fit, is the proper and direct reason why men are obliged, and under a moral necessity, to obey the rules of justice." The doctrine of St. Thomas respecting the nature of Divine justice, and Barbeyrac's explanation of Pufendorf's meaning, show that the idea of justice is not necessarily connected with that of a superior, if justice be regarded abstractedly. But if considered as a law for man- kind, that is to say, as a rule of human actions, its obligatory force must emanate from a superior. Thus Grotius defines natural law to be principles of right reason which enable us to know that a certain action is right or wrong, according to its congruity or incongruity with the reasonable and social nature of man, and, consequently, that God, who is the author of nature, commands or forbids the action. 1 And with this definition the canonists agree. And we have seen in the pre- ceding chapter, that the light retained by man after his fall, which teaches him the natural rules of right and wrong, is one of the causes whereby God sustains society, and one of the natural foundations of order therein. The doctrines of St. Thomas regarding Divine justice also show why it is that natural law is immutable. For, as it is impossible to suppose that God can prescribe to men any rules of conduct inconsis- tent with the Divine justice, so those rules must be immutable with the justice from which they emanate. We have now to discover the root of those immutable laws. Domat tells us that they are called immutable, because they are naturally so just, always and everywhere, that no authority can change or abolish them, whereas arbitrary laws are those which a lawful authority can establish, change, and abolish, according to circumstances. And he continues thus " These immutable or natural laws are all those which are necessary consequences of the two primary laws, and so es- sential to the engagements which form the order of society, that they could not be altered without injuring or destroying the foundations of that order. But arbitrary laws are those which may be differently established, changed, or even abolished, without violating the spirit of the two primary laws, and without wounding the principles of the order of society." I Grot. Dr. de la G. 1. 1, ch. 1, 10. "Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Nat. et Eccles. lib. 1, c. 2, 8, 11 ; Reiffenstuel, Jus Canon, proem. 14. II Zallinger, ubi sup. 10; Suarez, De Leg. lib. 2, c. 13. Domat, Traitc des Loix, c. 11, 1. IMMUTABLE LAWS. f>7 Grotius was somewhat misled by this idea of universality attached to natural law. He says that a thing may be proved to be of natural law in two ways, either a priori or a posteriori. The first method is in substance that of Domat. It consists in showing the conformity or inconsistency of a given act with the reasonable and social nature of man. The second concludes that anything is of natural law, because it is held to be so among all nations, at least the most civi- lized. For as an universal effect presupposes an universal cause, such general consent of mankind can scarcely be attributed to anything but to what is called common sense. p Without going so far as Hobbes, who argues that an appeal to the consent of mankind would require ab- solute unanimity, it must be admitted, that Pufendorf and Barbeyrac rightly reject this argument a posteriori, as unsafe and surrounded by a multitude of difficulties. q Grotius has overloaded his pages with quotations and references, for the purpose of showing that consent. Equally unsound is his position that there is a jus gentium or law of nations, which has acquired force by the consent of all nations, or at least of several/ The consent of all is not to be found, as Pu- fendorf justly remarks. 3 And indeed this voluntary jus gentium, distinct from natural law, is shown by Pufendorf and Barbeyrac to have no ex- istence. For in the first place, the name of law cannot correctly be given to that, the obligation of which springs, not from the authority of a superior, but from consent ; and as all independent nations are naturally equal, no one nation can impose a law on others, nor can they together prescribe laws to themselves. 4 The rights of ambassadors are placed by Grotius among the things which belong to this supposed customary law of nations. But the sacredness of these persons springs, as Pufendorf observes, from natural law, because it is necessary for procuring, preserving, and confirming peace among nations, and cannot without injustice be denied to persons employed for such purposes." And so it is with other things which have been attributed to this voluntary or arbitrary law of nations. They for the most part rest on natural law. There are indeed certain arbitrary customs used among civilized nations. But if a sovereign think fit to give full and due notice that he does not intend to observe them, he can only be blamed at most for a want of courtesy and liberality, provided he do not violate any P Grot. Dr. de la G. 1. 1, ch. ], 12. Montesquieu, Esprit des Loix, lib. 3, ch. 5. * L. 9, ff. De Just, et Jur. * So killing and wounding, and other injuries to persons, are offences against primary natural law. L. 10, ^ 1, ff. De Just, et Jur. And theft is against secondary natural law. L. 1, 3, ff. De Furtis. 1 L. 3, ff. De Just, et Jur. B L. 1, 3, ff. De Legibus. 186 CONFLICT OF LAWS REGARDING CRIMES AND OFFENCES. to defeat the criminal laws of another state by screening criminals from punishment. Humanity prescribes that an asylum should be granted to foreigners who, having committed no crime, driven out of their own country, seek a retreat elsewhere, provided they obey the laws of the country which receives them, and do nothing that can cause any disturbance." But the greater number of moralists hold that each state has a right to judge whether or no it be prudent or expedient to permit foreigners to enter its territories, who are not driven there by necessity, or by some cause which entitles them to compassion/ And though, as Pu- fendorf observes, it would be inhuman to refuse hospitality to a small number of strangers exiled from their own country for no crime/ 5 it is clear that every state may, without incurring the charge of cruelty, close its frontiers against all who have committed offences elsewhere, and who fly from trial or from punishment. And this course is pru- dent and politic with reference both to the foreign relations and the internal order of the country. Grotius argues, that though the establishment of civil societies gave to the government of each state the right of punishing or not punishing, as might be most convenient, the offences of its subjects against the laws of the community of which they are members, yet that institution did not vest in such governments so absolute and unlimited a discre- tion regarding crimes which in some measure affect human society in general. For other states have a right to prosecute such crimes, on the same principle that the laws of a particular state give to all private individuals the right of prosecuting in certain cases. 3 And a fortiori, foreign states have this right when the crimes in question are offences especially against themselves, and which they are entitled to punish for the maintenance of their safety or their honour. Grotius concludes that a state having within its territories a foreign offender ought not to throw any obstacle in the way of a foreign government which has a right to punish him. b He adds that a state does not ordinarily allow any foreign power to use armed force within its territories, a practice which would be subject to serious inconveniences. Therefore a state in whose country there is an offender convicted by a foreign court ought either to punish him itself, or to deliver him up on demand to the other state * Grotius, Droit de la Guerre, 1. 2, ch. 2, 16 ; Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 3, ch. 3, 10. y Pufend. Droit des Gens, 1. 3, ch. 3, 9 ; Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 2, ch. 7, 94. * Pufend. ibi, ^ 10. * Grot. Droit de la Guerre, 1.2, c. 21, 3 ; Pand. lib. 47, tit. 23. b Grot. ibi. CONFLICT OF LAWS REGARDING CRIMES AND OFFENCES. 187 to whose jurisdiction he is amenable. Grotius deduces his opinion from the doctrine, that a civil society, as any other body politic, may become responsible for the act of an individual/ 1 on the principle that any one cognizant of a crime and who could have prevented it, and ought to have prevented it, and does not do so, is himself guilty." And he argues that as this doctrine is of natural law, it is applicable to the liability of a state for the acts of its subjects. And that in like manner a state is also liable if it afford a retreat to an offender and so prevent his being punished/ Every state is bound to protect its sub- jects against injury; and whoever injures them, offends against their country, which is bound to punish the offender, and oblige him, if pos- sible, to compensate the injured man. g On the other hand, every stale is obliged not to permit its subjects to injure those of foreign coun- tries. 11 But a state is not responsible for the act of its subject unless it in some way approve or ratify that act, in which case it becomes liable. Therefore if the offender return home, justice should be de- manded from his sovereign, who is bound, if possible, to repair the damage committed or to punish him, or else to deliver him up to the injured state. 1 And a sovereign who refuses to make compensation for the injury done by his subject, or to punish the offender, or to deliver him up, becomes in some manner an accomplice to the injury, and is responsible for it. k Vattel judiciously adds, that a nation is also responsible for the offences of its members when its customs, and the principles of its government, accustom and allow its subjects to indulge in common pillage and piracy, as was the case with the Usbecks and the Barbary Powers. 1 These doctrines have a bearing on the law of extradition of foreign criminals. The arguments of Grotius, and the reflections which I have made above on the way in which the jurisdictions of separate states concur for the general government of human society, and are thus part of the scheme by which the world is governed, show that his position regarding extradition is generally the correct rule of Public Law. But it is liable to some modifications, which we will now consider. The arguments of Grotius chiefly apply to an offence committed by a subject of one state against another state, or its subjects, in which c Grot, ibi, 4. And see note 1 of Barbeyrac. d Ibi, 2. e Ibi, num. 2. And see the authorities cited. ' Ibi, 3. e Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 2, ch. 6, 71. h Ibi, | 72 ; Blackst. Com. b. 4, ch. 5, p. 67. 1 Vattel, ibi, 7375. k Ibi, 76. 1 Ibi, 77; Burlamaqui, Droit des Gens, edit. Dupin, torn. 4, p. 448, part 3, ch. 2, 3,8. 188 CONFLICT OF LAWS REGARDING CRIMES AND OFFENCES. case he shows that by screening the offender, and refusing redress, the whole body politic may become responsible for the act of one of its members. But with regard to the extradition of foreign convicted criminals by a state in whose dominions they have taken refuge, Grotius does not carry his argument so far, though he says that the offender ought to be delivered up or punished. The duty of delivering up such criminals is not in general one which can be enforced by a declaration of war. 1 " It is not a common and indispensable obligation, except by virtue of some treaty, or where the refugee is engaged within the territory in which he has found a refuge in some hostile design against the country from which he escaped." For actions punishable in one country may be innocent, or even praiseworthy, by the laws of another, and we have seen that each state may judge for itself what foreign laws it will act upon or reject within its territories. And the laws of evidence and criminal proce- dure in different countries vary greatly, so that a trial and conviction perfectly conclusive and satisfactory in the country where the Court sat, may be held entirely the contrary in another. Therefore, admit- ting the right of demanding extradition, it would be impossible to define, practically, the limits of that right, except by treaty. Kent holds that it is the duty of the government to surrender fugitives upon demand of a foreign state, after the civil magistrate shall have ascer- tained the existence of reasonable grounds for the charge, and suffi- cient to put the accused on his trial. But he adds that the difficulty, in the absence of positive agreement, consists in drawing the line between the class of offences to which the usage of nations does, and to which it does not, apply ; inasmuch as it is understood, in practice, to apply only to crimes of great atrocity, or deeply affecting the public safety. We may conclude that in general the extradition of offenders rests, not on strict right, but on the comity of nations, excepting where it is secured by treaty. p Cases may, however, occur in which the duty of delivering up or punishing, or at least of not sheltering a foreign criminal, may be absolutely and strictly binding. Thus a state giving hospitality and protection to a foreigner who has attempted the life of a foreign sove- reign, or of any other person sacred by Public Law, might be justly called to account by the injured nation. To a case of this description the opinion of Kent regarding atrocious crimes would apply. So we m Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 8, ch. 6, 12 ; P. Voet, De Statutis, 2, c. 1, n. 6. n Pufend. ibi. Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 2, p. 37. P See the authorities cited by Story, Conflict of Laws, 628. On the subject of extra- dition, see Hansard, Parl. Deb. 1852, vol. 122, 3rd series, col. 192, &c., 498, &c., 561, 1278. CONFLICT OF LAWS REGARDING CRIMES AND OFFENCES. 189 have seen that Pufendorf, while he holds that the right of requiring extradition of foreign criminals is not based on indispensable obliga- tion, excepts the case of refugees who abuse the hospitality accorded to them, by hostile designs against the country which they have left. No country can give an asylum for conspiracy, or the preparation of hostilities, against another state, without violating the law of nations.i The reason of this is easily perceived. The establishment of civil societies has deprived individuals of the right of war, and vested it in sovereign powers alone : r and individuals or societies not sovereign can, where civil society exists, use force in those cases only in which " the public authority cannot protect them. 3 Without this restriction, peace, which is one of the chief ends of civil society, could not be maintained ; and as Natural Law allows an appeal to violent means only where force is necessary for the defence and the maintenance of rights, 1 it follows that wherever civil society has rendered the use of force unnecessary for those purposes, it is also unlawful. Therefore any one not invested with sovereignty who commits or designs and prepares any act of hostility against any state, is guilty of an offence against the Law of Nations, unless he be authorized to do so by a sovereign power." Now it follows from the axiom that the authority of each sovereign power is exclusive, within its territories, of every other temporal sovereignty, that no state can authorize any act of hostility, or the preparation of any such act, against a third party, in the territories of an independent state, without the permission of the latter. And on the other hand, a government permitting, even by neglect, a breach of the Law of Nations to be committed within its territories, is itself liable for the offence, because a body politic is responsible for any act of individuals which it ought to prevent, and might have prevented. 1 And a state is, prima facie, responsible for whatever is done within its jurisdiction, for that jurisdiction is pre- sumed to be capable of preventing or punishing offences there. This indeed is necessary for the maintenance of the peace of the world, in which all states ought to concur. These arguments apply with pecu- liar force to the case of refugees who escape from the violated laws of their own country, and conspire against it in that which has given <> See the opinions of Lord Aberdeen and Lord Lyndhurst, in the House of Lords, Hansard, Parl. Deb. vol. 115, col. 628, 3rd series, 1851. r Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 3, ch. 1, 4 ; Pufend. liv. 8, ch. 6, 8. Ibi, 1. 156, ff. De Reg. Jur. ; 1. 13, ff. Quod Metus Causa; Gravina, Histor. de Ortu et Progress. Jur. Civ. c. 91. ' Vattel, ubi sup. u L. 24, ff. De Captiv. et Postlimin. ; 1. 168, ff. De Verbor. Signif. x Grotius, Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 2 1 , 2 ; Decree of Gratian, caus. 23, quaest. 3 can. 11 ; Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 5, ult. ; 1. 50, ff. De Reg. Jur. 190 CONFLICT OF LAWS REGARDING CRIMES AND OFFENCES. them hospitality. For, by the comity of nations, an asylum would be denied to them; and therefore they are peculiarly bound to commit no abuse of the hospitality given as a matter of humanity, which indeed demands that favour only for persons driven from their own country without having broken its laws. y With regard to political offenders, that part of the comity of nations which we have been discussing presents peculiar difficulties. On the one hand it is for the common peace of the world that offences against the security of existing governments should be prevented or punished, and revolutions repressed ; while on the other, the policy and opinions of nations vary so greatly regarding civil government and administra- tion, that a man may be pursued as a traitor in one country, and wel- comed as a patriot or a loyal subject in another. Each state, there- fore, deals with these cases according to its own policy, and with reference to its own internal constitution and security. Thus the United States of America could scarcely reject an exiled republican ; and Austria would receive with honour a partizan of the elder branch of the house of Bourbon. The principle of England is to close her ports to no political refugee. The dethroned monarch, the usurper in misfortune, and the unsuccessful demagogue, nay, even the fanatical enemy of all authority, alike find peace and safety on our shores. The present condition of Europe, as well as recent experience, seem to preclude foreign governments from complaining of a common sanc- tuary, which the uncertainty of political events renders by no means matter of indifference to the public men of all countries, none of whom can be sure that they may not, at some time or other, rejoice to claim its protection. Whatever general reasons exist against sanctuaries or asylums for offenders, may, to some extent, be urged against the rejec- tion of the comity of nations respecting the extradition of foreign offenders. The same principles are applicable to both cases. In both the impunity of crime is procured, and the efficacy of laws weakened. Treaties for the extradition or punishment of foreign criminals are therefore highly favourable to good order and civili- zation. Kent informs us, that the European nations, in early periods of mo- dern history, made provision, by treaty, for the mutual surrender of criminals seeking refuge from justice. Treaties of this kind were made between England and Scotland in 1 174, and England and France in 1308, and France and Savoy in 1385, and the last treaty made special provisions for the surrender of criminals, though they should happen to be subjects of the state to which they had fled. One treaty between Great Britain and the United States, concluded in 1795, con- y Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 3, ch. 3, 10. GENERAL REFLECTIONS ON THE CONFLICT OF LAWS. 191 tained an agreement for the mutual surrender of persons charged with murder or forgery. That treaty expired, on this point, after twelve years. The legislature of the kingdom of Belgium, by a law of the 1st of October, 1833, authorized the surrender of the fugitives from foreign countries upon the charge of murder, rape, arson, counterfeit- ing the current coin, or forging public bank paper, perjury, robbery, theft, peculation by trustees, and fraudulent bankrupts, but with a proviso that the law of foreign countries be reciprocal in the case, and that the judgment or judicial accusation be duly authenticated, and the demand be made within the time of limitation prescribed by the Belgian Law. 2 We have now examined the whole range of the Conflict of Laws in its public aspect, that is to say, not so much affording rules for the decision of questions of private right, as showing the way in which the municipal laws of different countries operate in the government of society where they come in contact with each other. Some general reflections are now required. The investigation of the nature and spirit of laws led us to see the plan of society on the foundation of the two primary laws, and the relation which the state of man in this life has to the exercise of those laws. We also examined the two sorts of engagements by which God forms the order of society, and unites mankind together therein.* And thus it was shown that the whole scheme and system of human society and government is constructed of laws, and obligations arising from laws. If we analyze human society, commencing with its first element, the family, and then proceeding to the state or nation (civitas) and then the world or mankind in general, we shall find at each step difficulty and danger increase, and they are greatest at the last. b St. Augustine speaks of the diversity of language among men, and the separation of nations, as the great obstacles to the peace of mankind ; and he observes, that when several nations are subjugated by a more powerful one, that union frequently produces civil wars and seditions instead of peace. Now the laws of which the system of human so- ciety and government is constructed are, for practical purposes, muni- cipal laws either in substance or in form. For however ready men may be to acknowledge the intrinsic authority of natural or immutable laws, yet, for the most part, the form in which those laws are obeyed 1 Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 2, pp. 37, 38. And see stat. 6 & 7 Viet. c. 75, regarding France ; and 6 & 7 Viet. c. 76, regarding America ; and stat. 8 & 9 Viet. c. 120, for facilitating the execution of treaties with France and America for the appre- hension of certain offenders. Domat, Loix Civiles, Traite des Loix, ch. 2. b Div. August. De Civ. Dei, lib. 19, cap. 7. c lbi. 192 GENERAL REFLECTIONS ON THE CONFLICT OF LAWS. or enforced is that of municipal laws ; and obedience to them is secured by means of the sovereign power in each state or nation, through the medium of divers magistrates and officers. And the other class mutable or arbitrary laws (those alluded to in the Pandects by Gajus, as peculiar to each people)* 1 are, in substance as well as form, municipal, deriving their authority from the civil power. Those mu- cipal laws of both kinds constitute in each country the basis of the social and civil polity on which the peace of the world depends, although that polity in its essential parts is of natural law. But muni- cipal laws, considered as such, do not extend beyond the territorial jurisdiction of the state to which they belong. And here we perceive a difficulty in the system of human polity considered as a whole em- bracing all mankind. For not only states and those who represent their sovereignty are not subject to any common legislative or judicial authority on earth, but, as we have seen, the laws of different countries frequently clash in such a way that either certain matters must be regulated by no law at all, or the law of one country must give way to that of another. Before civilization had developed a mode of dimi- nishing, if not of solving these difficulties, they caused a great part of the wars and dissensions of which we read in history. This is easy to understand. The same reasons by which Suarez proves the necessity of a legislative power and municipal laws in a civil community, 6 also show by implication the evils which arise for want of the same insti- tutions to regulate and govern the general community of mankind. And the equality and independence of nations render their legal rela- tions like those of individuals in a state anterior to civil society, that is to say, in an imperfect association greatly inferior to that of civil so- ciety, especially with reference to the great requisites of peace and the security of rights. Yet the division of the world into states and nations is an institution introduced jure gentium* And it is a great feature of the constitution of the world. But this subject has already been considered, and it is adverted to here only for the purpose of showing the general object and spirit of the branch of jurisprudence which gives effect to municipal laws in cases of conflict. The jurispru- dence of the conflict of laws does not seek to be a common law over- riding the conflicting municipal laws. Such a law would interfere with the peculiarities of municipal laws which make them adapted to the circumstances of the places where they prevail. And it would be at variance with the distinctions of nations and states, each of which has d L. 9, ff. De Just, et Jur. e Suarez, De Legib. lib. 3, cap. 1. 1 Ex hoc jure (gentium) . . . discretes gentes, regna condita .... Het- mogenianus, 1. 5, ff. De Just, et Jur. GENERAL REFLECTIONS ON THE CONFLICT OF LAWS. 193 laws, usages and institutions more or less adapted to its own wants and the character of its people. But this jurisprudence shows, wherever there is a conflict, which of the inconsistent laws is to govern a given state of facts. It thus allows due effect to municipal laws, and yet prevents their peculiarities from forming an impediment to the free intercourse of mankind for all the purposes of commerce and civilized life. And it applies to the municipal laws of different states, where they come in contact with each other, a system of rules in accordance with the general scheme whereby the world is governed. These obser- vations easily indicate the connection between those rules and the two primary fundamental laws. For they all have a principle of justice either belonging to immutable law or else arising from an adaptation to the order of society, which is constructed upon those two primary laws. And they have reference to the ultimate end of all laws, which is that for which man was created. Thus the rule, that where a con- tract is entered into in one country, and the performance or fulfilment is intended to be in another, such performance must be according to the law of the latter place, is matter of immutable law, because good faith requires that the manifest intentions of the parties should be car- ried into effect, and they contemplated the law of that place. And the rule, that a marriage celebrated according to the lex loci contractus, is valid everywhere, rests on a principle of the order of society, as we have seen. And so it is with the rule which gives effect to the judg- ments or decrees in rem of foreign courts having jurisdiction over the subject matter. These rules all belong to the terrestrial order and peace of which St. Augustine speaks, where he says, that the portion of the Celestial City which is here on earth, though it has no concern with the diversity of languages, laws, customs and nations, yet uses that peace, referring it to the ultimate end or civitas Dei. ? And the same passage applies particularly to International Law, as it does generally to the whole science of jurisprudence. For the innumerable multitude of rules which govern mankind all bear some relation to the two primary laws, and are the laws of man's conduct, which consists of the steps which he makes towards the end of his creation. 11 A few observations on the subject-matter of laws will further ex- plain the spirit of this head of jurisprudence. Laws may be divided under two heads, i. e. obligations and successions. The first comprises the legal relations of persons, and the second the mode in which those relations are perpetuated by transmission from one generation to another. Any one who examines the practical operation of these two heads of law, even within his own personal observation, will perceive f Div. August. De Civ. Dei, lib. 19, cap. 17. h Domat, Loix Civiles, Traite des Loix, ch. 1, 3. O 194 GENERAL REFLECTIONS ON THE CONFLICT OF LAWS. that they constitute a vast complication of details, forming a sort of network, which extends throughout the whole of human society. And he will also see that the unbroken continuity of that network, notwith- standing the political and geographical divisions of the earth, is ne- cessary for the entire fulfilment of all the purposes of civilized society. And this object could not be obtained without the comity of nations, which gives effect to laws beyond their own proper territory, in cases where such comity is required by the interests of society. These reflections show the province and the spirit of the comity of nations regarding the conflict of laws, and the effects which it is intended to produce in the scheme of terrestrial government. The foregoing chapters do not pretend to contain a complete treatise on this head of jurisprudence. They only give so much of the rules and cases as seemed necessary to afford a full view of the subject, which is an essential part of Public Law. CHAPTER XVIII. OF THE LEGAL ORIGIN AND NATURE OF CIVIL SOCIETIES OR STATES. The Three Parts or Orders of Human Society Matters of Public and of Private Law Detail of the Matters of Public Law, and Construction of Civil Society Neces- sity of Civil Government, and its Divine Right The Doctrine of the Social Com- pact Doctrine of Hooker, Blackstone, Pufendorf, Hobbes, Grotius, Zallinger, Locke, and Barbeyrac The true Origin of Civil Societies Savigny's Doctrine on the Subject. THE preceding chapters have shown the first principles and foundations of the order of society, and the general nature and spirit of the laws constituting and regulating that order. A plan of society has been drawn on that foundation of the two primary laws. 1 We have seen that God forms the order thereof by means of the ties which eng-ao-e / O ~ men in society to bind them together in the exercise of the second law. We have shown how these ties or engagements imply and require the use and advantage of civil government to restrain every one within the order of those which belong to him. And we have also seen that there are four foundations of the order of society in its present state, that is to say, the authority of true Religion, the government of God over society, the general knowledge of justice in men, and the autho- 1 See Chap. VI. LEGAL ORIGIN AND NATURE OF CIVIL SOCIETIES OR STATES. 195 rity which God gives to supreme civil powers. In the course of these disquisitions, some of the chief doctrines regarding the origin and nature of civil communities or states have necessarily appeared, be- cause the explanation of the way in which society is constructed and maintained, and of its objects, that are the design of God in uniting men together in society according to the spirit of the two primary laws, naturally shows what civil or politic societies are, and what they are intended to accomplish in the world. For, as Burlamaqui justly says, civil society is natural society so modified as to have a sovereign power which commands, and from the will of which all that regards the happiness of society depends in the last resort, so that by such means men may more surely obtain the happiness which they naturally seek. k But this subject must now be more fully explained. Domat lays it down in the Preface to his great work on Public Law, that God has made the universal society of mankind to subsist by three ties, which distinguish it into three parts, according to so many ways in which the Divine system appointed for the world ope- rates. The first of these is Religion, the spirit of which embraces all people, and tends to bring all nations into the bosom of the Catholic Church. The second is that humanity, or common human nature, which ought to unite all mankind, notwithstanding differences of religion. The third is that constituted in each state, by the order which unites all the families composing it under the same government, whatever religion they may profess. And as these three different parts of uni- versal society have their different relations to the common good, and to the different engagements and duties of men, so the subject-matter of their laws, and also those laws themselves, have their diversities adapted to their uses. 1 The first of these parts or orders comprehends all the matters relating to the good order of society with respect to Divine worship. The subject-matter of the laws contained in the second part of society, which is constituted and supported among na- tions by humanity and natural justice, common to all mankind, is, the use of commerce, and the several communications and intercourse between nations and the subjects of one state with those of another, the liberty of passing from one country to another, the freedom of navigation, honesty in international commerce, hospitality, and other things of that nature. They have rendered necessary negociations, treaties between nations, embassies, and the privileges of ambassadors and other diplomatic envoys. And even in war there are laws of huma- nity and justice. Such are those which regard the manner of declaring k Burlamaqui, Droit des Gens, vol. 4, p. 15, edit. Dupin. 1 Domat, Droit Publ. Preface. o 2 196 OF THE LEGAL ORIGIN AND NATURE and making war, the rights of hostages, humanity towards prisoners, moderation in acts of hostility, the observance of treaties of peace, truces and suspensions of arms, the use of reprisals, and the like. Domat distinguishes, as to what relates to these international matters, between Christian nations and others. For the latter have for laws, common to them all, the rules of humanity and justice which compose the Law of Nations, besides treaties and established usages. But those who know the Christian religion have, besides natural equity and treaties and international usages, the laws of Religion also, which comprehends within its bounds all duties of every nature; and which not only contains rules more perfect than those barely derived from the law of nature, but also secures a more strict and religious observance of the rules of the law of nature themselves. As to the third part or order of society, which is confined to the persons united in one state under one government, Dornat distin- guishes the matters arising from it into two sorts. The first is of the matters which concern the general order of the state, such as those relating to the government; the authority of the sovereign and the obedience due by subjects or citizens; the force necessary to preserve public tranquillity ; the management of the revenue ; the order of the administration of justice; the punishment of crimes; the functions of different sorts of offices, employments and professions which the public service requires ; the public policy for the use of the seas, of rivers, of highways, of mines, of forests, of game and fishing, of the government of towns and other places; the distinctions of the different orders of persons, and other matters of like nature. The second sort of matters of this third order of society is of those which relate to what is transacted between persons in their private capacity, their several engagements, whether by contracts, such as sales, exchanges, hiring and letting, loans, deposits, partnership, dona- tion, compromises, and the like; or without contract, such as guardi- anships, prescription, successions, wills, entails and others. The first sort of matters, having relation to the public order of the state, belong to Public Law ; and those of the second sort, respecting only what passes among particular persons, are the matters of the other part of the law which is called private law. n Having drawn a general plan of society, Domat proceeds thus to notice the detail of the matters of Public Law. " In order to give a view of the matters of Public Law, it is necessary to observe in ge- neral, that as Public Law is a system of rules respecting the order of the government and policy of a state, the first object presented by the m Domat, Droit Publ. Preface. n Ibi. And see above, Chap. XII. of these Commentaries. OF CIVIL SOCIETIES OR STATES. 197 system consists of such order and policy. And it is necessary to see in the first place what are their necessity and use, for the rules of Public Law are built on that foundation. " The design of God in uniting men together in society for the pur- pose of uniting them by the spirit of the two primary laws, as has been explained in the Treatise of Laws, implies the necessity of a subordination among them which should place some of them above the others. For this society constitutes a body of which every one is a member; and as the body is composed of different members, so there is a subordination, not only of all the members under the head, but also of the members among themselves, according as the functions of one depend on those of others. Thus as the body of the (civil) so- ciety is compounded of an infinite number of different conditions and professions necessary for the common good ; it is essential to that so- ciety, that there should be a subordination of all conditions and pro- fessions under one power intended to maintain the order of the whole society ; and that those conditions and professions should be subordi- nated one to the other according as the functions of one may depend upon or have relation to another. And the necessity of this order implies that of government, especially in the condition in which we are, under so strong an influence of self-love impelling us to serve our own interests and gratify our passions, which would destroy the order of society if the authority of government did not moderate and curb them by inflicting punishment on those who attempt to disturb that order." " But even if we could suppose a society of men without self-love, yet the subordination of some of them to others would be necessary for the things which they would have to transact together. And the necessity of assembling, of proposing matters, of deliberating and of executing what is resolved on, would require an order of subordination among them, placing some in authority over the others, whether it were by reason of the nature of their functions, or by the difference of age or capacity, or the majority of votes, or other reasons." Domat here defines that part of municipal law which is called In- ternal Public Law, to be the system of rules regarding the order and of government and the polity of a state. And he lays it down that all the rules of Public Law are built on the necessity and use of that ge- neral law. Thereby he indicates the true origin of civil societies or states. The division of mankind into distinct communities called nations, states, kingdoms or countries, is, as we have seen, one of that class of laws called by the civilians jus necessarium, or, in the words Domat, Droit Publ. Preface. 198 OF THE LEGAL ORIGIN AND NATURE of Modestimus, jus quod necessitas constitute? It arose out of the nature of things and the exigencies of mankind, though hastened in its first commencement by a peculiar dispensation. The social state could not exist without civil government, which requires and implies the institution of civil societies, that is to say, the introduction of a sovereign power into natural society, and the partition of mankind into separate bodies politic for the purposes of government. Thus Her- mogenianus refers the division of nations and the foundation of king- doms to the jus gentium, or natural law. Ex hoc jure gentium .... discretes gentes; regna condita.* He mentions first the division of man- kind into nations, and then the institution of governments, showing the former to have been required for the latter, both springing from the same source, the Law of Nature, which he, after the manner of his time, calls jus gentium. We shall find this view of the origin of civil states confirmed by fur- ther examination. Suarez, in that part of his work which relates to the sovereign power of making laws, argues that this supreme legislative authority, which is the great feature of sovereignty, does not spring from the will of men, but is of Divine right. For it is a necessary part of a state or civil community. It is an essential incident of civil society/ He goes on to say, that the civil power of government is of natural law, if viewed abstractedly, but the mode or form of exercising it may be determined by the particular community in which it is in the first instance vested. That power looked upon per se is just, and in conformity with the Divine Will; and supposing it vested in a given person or persons, the obligation of obeying him or them is of Divine right. The same principles apply to every form of civil polity. 5 Thus Covarruvias, citing St. Thomas Aquinas and others, argues that muni- cipal laws, as such, are binding in conscience, because the power of making laws is of natural law.* And Pufendorf, though he holds so- vereignty to result immediately from contract or agreement, maintains that the authority of sovereign power is both of Divine and of human right. Since the increase of mankind, he says, reason has shown be- yond contradiction, that the establishment of civil societies is absolutely necessary for the order, the peace and the preservation of the human species. Therefore God, as the author of the Law of Nature, must also be looked upon as the founder of civil societies, and consequently of sovereign power, without which they cannot exist. For, he conti- P L. 4, ff. De Legib. ; 1. 2, ff. De Orig. Jur. ; and see my Readings, p. 125. i L. 5, ff. De Legib. T Suarez, De Legib. lib. 3, cap. 3. Ibi, cap. 10. ' Covarruvias, Op. torn. 1, p. 199. OF CIVIL SOCIETIES OR STATES. 199 nues, we must refer to a Divine origin, not only the establishments made directly by God's order, and without the intervention of any human act, but also those which men themselves have invented by the light of reason, according as circumstances of time and place required it, in order to acquit themselves of obligations imposed by some Divine Law. Therefore, as the duties of natural law could not be con- veniently performed, since the great multiplication of mankind, with- out civil government, it is clear that God, who has prescribed that law to men, has thereby commanded them to form civil societies. And we see that in the sacred Scriptures He formally approves the autho- rity of sovereigns, and shows that it proceeds from Himself. But it is not certain that God has commanded the establishment of this or that particular society." Civil societies are an institution differing from other human establishments invented by the light of reason, but not shown by reason to be necessary for the order of society and the preservation of mankind. For God has here declared His will by means of reason, proving to men that without the establishment of civil societies, order and peace, which are immediate objects of natural law, could not be maintained in the world. And when Grotius says that men were not led to form civil societies by any command of God, we must understand him to mean only that there is no express Divine command to that effect, for he adds, that men found the insufficiency of separate families, and therefore they established civil societies. Reason produced this result. And he observes, that St. Paul treats them as Divine establishments, because God approved them as salu- tary to mankind/ These results agree with the principles of Domat regarding the dis- tinction between arbitrary and immutable laws. For all the laws regarding the conduct of men among themselves are the rules of the social state in which God has placed them. Those laws differ accord- ing to their relation to the order of society ; and whatever be their object with regard to that order, they are consequences of the two primary laws, as I have already shown. The laws which are a necessary consequence of the two primary laws, prescribing our duty to God and to our neighbour, are essential to the order of society, and immu- table. Now the institution of civil states and civil governments evidently fall under that class of laws. Those establishments have a direct relation to the end of man, to which his conduct is directed by the two primary laws. Thus we have seen that the power which God has given to civil governments, is one of the three ties by which uni- versal society is maintained, and constitutes one of three parts or orders composing that society. So St. Augustine deduces the whole u Pufendorf, Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 3, 2. * Grot. Droit de la G. liv. 1, ch. 4, 7, num. 3 ; Rom. xii. 1. 200 OF THE LEGAL, ORIGIN AND NATURE order of society from the two primary laws ; x and St. Thomas Aquinas argues that, as the end for which man is designed makes him a social and politic animal, and it is natural for man to live with a number of other men, it must therefore follow that there is necessarily something in man to govern a multitude. For a body of men could no more be kept together without some power to direct and govern individual wills, than a physical body could remain without a cohesive and directing power for the common welfare of all its members. 7 And he says, that the object of a multitude of men being formed into a body politic is, that they may be directed to their ultimate end, and that civil govern- ment is so much the more excellent in proportion as it is adapted to that end. 2 We may sum up all these doctrines and reflections by saying, that the object of civil societies and governments is the same as that of natural law; and the arguments which we have given to show the origin and necessity of natural law and the social state, also prove those of civil societies and governments. These things have here been fully established and explained, because they constitute the foun- dation on which the internal Public Law of states is built, and they dispose of some theories which have produced a pernicious effect in politics. The most remarkable of these is the opinion that civil states and governments are based upon, and derive their origin and force from, contract or agreement. The principal English advocates of this theory are Hooker and Locke. They derive the origin of government, both in right and in fact, from a primary contract, without which they say there was no reason that one man should be a superior to govern or judge another. " The lawful power," says Hooker, whose theory coincides with that of Locke, " of making laws to command whole politic societies of men, belongeth so properly unto the same entire societies, that for any prince or potentate of what kind soever upon earth, to exercise the same of himself, and not either by express com- mission, immediately and personally received from God, or else by authority received at first from their consent, upon whose persons they impose law, it is no better than mere tyranny. Laws they are not, therefore, which public approbation hath not made so. But approba- tion not only they give who personally declare their assent by voice, sign or act; but also when others do it in their names, by right originally, at least, derived from them."' * Div. August. De Civ. Dei, lib. 19, cap. 14. y Div. Thorn. Aquin. Opusc. De Regira. Princip. lib. 1, cap. 1. 1 Ibi, cap. 14. Hallam, Constit. Hist. vol. 1, p. 296, 297; Story, Comment, on the Constit. of the United States, vol. 1, ch. 3, 325, and notes. OF CIVIL SOCIETIES OR STATES. 201 Pufendorf holds a theory founded on the same principles, though, as we have seen, his work contains the true grounds of Public Law on this important matter. He maintains that, for the regular formation of a state, there must be two conventions or compacts, and a general ordinance. For, he argues, when a multitude forsake the independ- ence of the natural state, to form a civil society, each person, in the first place, binds himself to the others, to unite together for ever in one body, and to regulate by common consent whatever regards their preservation and common security. All in general, and each in par- ticular, must enter into this primitive engagement, and those who are not parties to it are excluded from the new society. Then a general ordinance must be made, whereby the form of the government is established, without which no secure measures could be taken for the public welfare. Then there must be another compact, whereby, after one or more persons have been chosen, to whom the power of governing the society is given, those who are invested with that supreme authority engage to watch over the common safety and welfare, and the others at the same time promise obedience to them. This comprehends a submission of the power and will of each, so far as the public interests require, to the will of the elected chief or chiefs. The state thus formed (continues our author) is conceived under the idea of a person distinct from all the individuals composing it, which has its name, its rights, and its own property, nothing of which any citizen, or many or even all of them, have any claim to, for they belong to the sovereign. He then defines the state to be a compound moral person, the will of which, formed of the united wills of persons united by their compacts, is reputed the will of all in general, and authorized, therefore, to use the power and faculties of each individual, in order to procure the common peace and security. 11 The opinion of Hobbes resembles that of Pufendorf, but he admits of only one compact, that of each individual, with the rest, removing a portion of his free will or liberty, and so submitting to the supreme power of the state. Grotius defines the state in a manner compatible with these opinions, which, however, he does not sanction. The state, he says, is a perfect body of free persons, who have united together for the purpose of peaceably enjoying their rights, and for their common advantage.* 3 He defines it as composed of free persons, to exclude slaves, who are not persons in contemplation of law, and he uses the adjective perfect, according to the meaning of Aristotle, adopted by the civilians and canonists, to designate a society having within itself b Pufend. Devoir de 1'Homme et du Citoyen, liv. 2, cap. 6, 710 ; Pufend. Droit des Gens, lib. 7, ch. 2, 7, 8. c Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Nat. et Eccles. Publ. lib. 3, cap. 1, 19(5. d Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 1, ch. 1, 14, and note by Barbeyrac. 202 OF THE LEGAL ORIGIN AND NATURE every legal power necessary for its end. We will now examine the grounds of these political theories. Zallinger, who adopts the notion of an original compact, admits that these contracts are nowhere to be found, and he therefore reduces it to a tacit compact. Blackstone's view is substantially the same. d Barbeyrac, in a note to Pufendorf, 6 quotes a passage from Buddeus, where he says, that though philosophy teaches that the origin of states was by compact, yet there is scarcely an instance of the sort in history, and Barbeyrac concludes that, even where such a contract existed, it was simply tacit. Pufendorf supposes a state of circumstances which never existed in point of fact, as a basis of his theory. It is, indeed, not difficult to show that the original compacts if they be taken as the source of the obligations which keep civil society to- gether and support civil government, and therefore as the origin of states are a mere legal fiction or hypothesis/ War and usurpation, and the power of a majority, have been the most frequent origin of governments, and no instance has yet been shown of a multitude, who, after living in a state of nature, entered into compacts to form a civil state. The opinion concerning a tacit original compact arises partly from the erroneous doctrine of Trebonian, which I have already refuted, g that obligations not springing from a contract, nor from a wrong, arise quasi ex contractu* that is, from a constructive, implied or presumed contract. I have shown that the real source of this class of obligations is the law without any consent, express, implied or pre- sumed, of the party bound, and therefore without any sort of contract. The error in question was exaggerated by Rousseau, who maintains that all obligations must arise from consent. 1 And on this false pro- position his pernicious system is based. Suarez holds, on the authority of the common opinion of the civilians and canonists and of St. Thomas Aquinas, that the civil power of go- vernment is primarily and immediately vested in the community or commonwealth, and derived thence by kings and other sovereign go- vernors. 15 And so Ulpian holds in the celebrated law quod Principi placuit. 1 But this does not confirm the opinion that states and govern- ments derive their origin from an original compact For the fact of a nation submitting to the authority of a given person does not neces- e Zallinger, ubi sup. d Blackst. Com. b. 1, p. 47. e Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 2, ^ 8, note 2. f Story, Comment, on the Constit. of the United States, vol. 1, ch. 3, 327, 328. f Chap. VI. h See my Commentaries on the Modern Civil Law, ch. 11. 1 Contrat Social, chap. 4. k Suarez, De Legib. lib. 3, cap. 4, 2. 1 L. I, ff. De Constitut. Princip. OF CIVIL SOCIETIES OR STATES. sarily constitute a compact. And I have already shown, that whatever peculiar arrangements may have occurred in some instances, the essen- tial nature of civil communities and governments is derived from natural law, and they are an intrinsic part of the order of universal human society appointed by God. The true natural state of man is a state of association or society, because it is in conformity with his na- ture and the obligations arising therefrom. And as those obligations bind him without his consent being necessary, so he is bound, without his consent, to live in civil or politic association and submit to civil government of some sort. He cannot do otherwise without acting contrary to the law of nature, and therefore his consent is superfluous, for the power to consent must imply that of dissenting. And the obligation of each man to perform the duties of the civil state and submit to civil government arises not from his consent, express or im- plied, but from natural law. It is a necessary consequence of the two primary laws and essential to the order of human society constructed upon them. This general doctrine is entirely compatible with the fact that in certain instances a man may bind himself by his free will to the observance of some particular laws or obedience to a given magistrate, or become voluntarily a member of a certain civil state. And* it is the same when a number or a body of men enter into such political en- gagements. These are facts which have no effect on the general rules and principles of Public Law, though they belong to the municipal or internal Public Law of the particular state to which they relate. Savigny treats the subject of the origin of states in a very philoso- phical manner. Speaking of the influence of the state on private law, he says, that if it be possible to conceive private law as an ab- straction extraneous to the state, and founded on a community of ideas and manners, it is the establishment of the judicial power, which, within the state, gives to private law reality and life. But he adds, that we must not believe that there is in history a time anterior to the founda- tion of the state, and in which private law had an incomplete existence, that is to say, the state of nature. " For each people, as soon as it gives signs of life, is already constituted into a state or politic community. That natural condition of man, or state of nature, is a hypothesis created by the imagination, looking on the people abstractedly from the state."" After some further reflections, Savigny thus proceeds to consider the opinions on the formation of the state. " The preceding theory on the nature and origin of the state has not been generally admitted. Assemblies of men have often been sup- posed, undefined and independent of national unity. But this opinion m L. 3, 4, ff. De Reg. Jur. n Savigny, Trait de Droit Rom. torn. 1, p. 23, edit. Guenoux, Paris, 1840. 204 OF THE LEGAL ORIGIN AND NATURE falls to the ground before the fact, that at all periods nations constitute states, and everywhere we find a people constituting the basis of the state. It has been attempted in the Slave States of America, for ex- ample, to unite great masses of men without regard to their origin. But these attempts have had bad consequences, and the constitution of the state has met with insurmountable obstacles. I therefore say in answer to those who support this opinion, that originally, and accord- ing to the nature of things, all states were formed in the nation or people, by the people and for the people." " Others represent the creation of the state as an act of individual wills, as the effect of a contract ; a system, the consequences of which are as pernicious as they are false. Thus it is supposed, that if the individuals have thought fit to form a state, they might equally not have formed it at all, or have incorporated themselves in another state, or adopted another constitution. Without repeating what I have said of the natural unity of nations, and its necessary consequences, I will only observe that in every case in which such a compact is possible, the state infallibly exists already both in fact and in law ; and from that time the matter in question would be, not as to its composition, but as t& its decomposition. This erroneous system rests on a double error. The numerous varieties presented by the constitution of states, that is to say the individual and historical elements, have been looked upon as so many arbitrary acts of the human will. Then the divers significations of the generic term people have been confounded toge- ther. Thus this term signifies 1st, that natural unity in which the state receives its birth, and is perpetuated from generation to genera- tion ; 2ndly, the union of persons existing contemporaneously, which the state comprises at a determined time; 3rdly, the assemblage of persons not invested with power, that is to say, the governed without the governors ; 4thly, in republics (ancient Rome for example), the assembly of citizens in whom, by the constitution, the sovereign power resided. The confusion of all these ideas has led to the error of attri- buting to the body of the governed, both the abstract right of the people, considered as a natural unity, and the privilege of the Roman populus, and thus placing the sovereignty in the hands of the subjects. If, indeed, without the last step, the sovereignty is attributed to the body of all the contemporaneous individuals, both governors and governed, a more correct result is not obtained. In the first place the state is not composed of all the individuals taken per capita, but of cer- tain orders or classes created by its constitution. For the total number of individuals do not exercise political will or acts. And as you must necessarily subtract the greater number women and minors you are reduced to the fiction of representation. And the assemblage of all OF CIVIL SOCIETIES OR STATES. 205 the contemporaneous individuals would still not constitute the people, for a people considered under this point of view continues in futurity, and has an imperishable existence." " But the opinion which I combat has an element of truth. Accident and the arbitrary will of men exercise their influence over the forma- tion of states : conquest has often changed natural frontiers, dismem- bered nations, and broken their unity. Often, also, the state assimi- lates to itself a foreign element. But that assimilation operates gradually, and according to certain natural laws. Such events, though frequent in history, are nevertheless anomalies. The people and its organic development still remain as the basis and the natural and regular origin of the state. If in the midst of that operation, external events bring to it a foreign element, a healthy and vigorous people is able to absorb that element by its moral energy. If not, the result of the struggle is a diseased condition of the body politic. This explains how that which was, in its origin, injustice and violence, may, sub- mitted to that power of assimilation, become a legitimate element of the state. But to present these anomalies these trials which moral power undergoes as the true origin of states, to fall back on this adventurous opinion as a sole refuge from the dangerous doctrine of a social compact, this must be absolutely rejected, for it is difficult to say whether the remedy be not worse than the evil." The doctrines of Domat and Savigny show clearly that the supposed original contract is an unnecessary legal fiction. For the real legal origin of states, considered philosophically, is the origin of the obliga- tions by which they are constituted or formed. And those obligations are the different ties which unite men together in society; and their origin is derived from the two primary laws which direct the conduct of man towards his end. Thus Savigny says, that the state derives its birth from an internal force, a superior necessity which impresses upon it a character of individuality ; p this necessity engenders the state, developing it out of the universal human society of which politic or civil society is a natural consequence. And whatever may be the political events which have caused the association of men in any given case under a particular government, the legal nature of the state is to be found in the ties and obligations which are conse- quences of the two primary laws, and part of the secondary Natural Law. The doctrine of an original contract between the crown and people was asserted by the Convention Parliament in that famous resolution which declared the vacancy of the crown after the flight of King Savigny, Traite de Droit Rom. torn. 1, p. 2731. P Ibi, p. 20. 206 LEGAL ORIGIN AND NATURE OF CIVIL SOCIETIES OR STATES. James the Second. q That position was, indeed, as Hallam observes, rather too theoretical/ and no record of any such contract is to be found in the history of England. It was no doubt resorted to for the purpose of denying the divine right of monarchy, from which the arbi- trary and indefeasible right of the crown was plausibly derived. But such a fiction was obviously unnecessary. For the rights of the people as well as those of the crown clearly rest not on contract but on laws. And so we find it in Fortescue, whose learned annotator rejects the theories of Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau regarding the institution of government. 5 In the case of federal constitutions, such as that of the United States of America, there is indeed a fundamental law, the origin of which partakes of the nature of that of a treaty or contract ; l but this is not an original contract in the sense in which the term is used by Locke and Rousseau, nor a compact. It is a constitution of govern- ment, a modification of civil or political society previously existing, by the union of several bodies politic in a form of constitution." And such federal fundamental laws are what the civilians call anomalous laws, which have no effect upon the general doctrines or jurispru- dence of Public Law. CHAPTER XIX. OF THE SOVEREIGN POWER IN CIVIL SOCIETY OR STATES. The Civil Power Principle of Subordination Authority of a Majority Perfect and imperfect Societies Necessity of the governing Power in Civil Societies Analysis of the Civil Power by Grotius The Sovereign Power Doctrine of the Sovereignty of the People. CIVIL society may be described as a modification of natural society, whereby the sovereign power is created having authority to command, i Black. Com. b. 1, ch. 3, p. 211 ; Story, Comment, on the Constit. of the United States, vol. 2, book 3, ch. 3, 341344. * Hallam, Constit. Hist. vol. 3, ch. 14, p. 349. * Fortesc. De Laudibus Legum Angliae, by Amos, cb. 14, and note. And see Story, ubi sup. 349. * Story, ubi sup. 350, &c. We shall return to this subject in Chap. XXVII. Story, ibi, 372. THE SOVEREIGN POWER IN CIVIL SOCIETY OR STATES. 207 and from the will of which depends, in the last resort, all that regards the temporal happiness and welfare of society/ And, as we have seen, the institution of civil society and political sovereignty is a natural result of the principles on which all human society is based. For the purpose and design of God in linking men together in the social state, to unite them by the spirit of the two primary laws, necessarily implies a subordination among them, or a subjection to authority whereby some are placed over others. That authority is called by Grotius the civil power, or the moral power of governing a state," when it exists in civil society. That this principle of subordination to authority is matter of Natural Law is shown by the reflection of Domat, that it is necessary in all conjunctions of several persons together which exist among men. Thus, in marriage, the man is the head of the wife, and by birth children are subjected to the authority of their parents ; and when the increase of mankind required another regimen, God established chiefs or princes over many families/ And in conjunctions of persons having equal legal rights, as members of some body, the majority expresses the will of the body, to which the individual members must submit. Savigny, in considering the constitution of judicial persons or corporate bodies, examines this subject. He says that the rule of law making the will of the majority that of the body in its corporate capacity, is founded on Natural Law. For to require unanimity would be to impede the acts and the will of the body corporate ; and the rule is preserved in the Roman Law, and adopted by the Canon Law/ Unanimity is not impossible in a deliberating assembly, and it is required for the verdict of an English jury, but it is so difficult to obtain, and subject to so many contingencies, that it would be an obstacle to the movements and the life of the assembly. And the principle of the power of a majority once admitted, the right of being acknowledged as the will of the whole body is naturally attributed to a simple majority, that is to say, half the votes, plus one. And every other proportion, such for instance as two-thirds, or six-sevenths, has a character of arbitrary or positive law/ We see here, again, an example of the way in which a rule of natural law arises from an Burlamaqui, Droit des Gens, vol. 4, p. 15, edit. Dupin. * Grot. Droit de la Gens, liv. 1, ch. 3, 6. y Domat, Droit Publ. Preface. L. 160, ^ 1, ff. De Reg. Jur. ; 1. 19, ff. ad Municipalem, 30; Decretal. Tit. De his quae fiunt a majore parte Capituli. And see Faebeus, De Reg. Jur. Canon, p. 176, who explains the distinction between things affecting the rights of the individuals as such, and those which regard the corporate body. Commentary on rule 29 in Quinto Decretal. (De Reg. Jur.) Savigny, Trait^ du Droit Rom. torn. 2, pp. 329, 330. 208 THE SOVEREIGN POWER.IN CIVIL SOCIETY OR STATES. institution of arbitrary law. But these doctrines of Savigny are cited for the purpose of showing a natural principle of authority and government, even in aggregations of persons who are all equal. For in these bodies, the individuals composing them are subject to the authority of the majority; and that majority usually delegates powers more or less extensive to certain persons, who represent the aggregate for divers purposes of internal government and administration. Sa- vigny examines the legal question arising between two propositions, one requiring unanimity, and the other holding a majority of a body sufficient. He looks upon them chiefly with reference to Private Law, which regards an aggregate body as persona, a person in con- templation of law. But he gives us the principle of Public Law, that the authority of the majority is the most simple and natural expression of the life and will of a body politic or assembly of men. The evils resulting from neglect of this principle are illustrated in the history of Poland, by the absurd institution of the liberum veto. b An artificial constitution may create different modifications of that expression. And the learned writer argues that it is naturally limited as to power, because the corporate body in its nature includes the future, as well as the present, represented by all the members living at one time. But this investigation presents to us a natural element of government inci- dent to aggregates of men, and which is to be found in one form or another throughout political systems, and even in associations belong- ing exclusively to Private Law. And this confirms the position that the subordination of persons, on which civil government is founded, is part of the order established by God for the government of the world, and that men may be united in the spirit of the two primary laws. Suarez distinguishes two sorts of associations of men. One is im- perfect, that is to say, the family : and the other is perfect, that is to say, political society, or the state. The former commences with the association of husband and wife, and this is completed by that of parent and child, to which aggregates are added the accessory rela- tions of master and servant, for divers purposes. From these three conjunctions arises the first association of men, which is called imperfect with reference to the state or political civil society, because the family is not sufficient to itself for the wants of man and human society, though it is perfect as far as regards domestic economy. In the nature of things, politic or civil society is therefore necessary, as we have already shown, and this is according to the will of God for Cicero truly says : Nihil Principi Deo in rebus humanis esse gratius, quam homines habere inter se societatem ordinatam et perfectam, quce civitas b Wheaton, Hist, of the Law of Nations, p. 269. THE SOVEREIGN POWER IN CIVIL SOCIETY OR STATES. 209 dicitur. And a perfect community or civitas necessarily requires a power to govern it. c St. Thomas Aquinas proves this last proposition in a manner which points out very well the nature of the civil power of government. He argues it a priori by saying that no body can subsist without some prin- ciple, whose province it is to procure and compass the common good of such body. As it is in natural bodies, experience shows the same to be regarding politic bodies. d The reason is clear, says Suarez, for each member looks to his own welfare or interest, which may sometimes be contrary to the common good. And many things are for the common good which do not affect individuals, or do not so affect them that they will forward those things, except so far as touches themselves. There- fore in a perfect community there must be necessarily a public power to which belongs the duty of promoting and procuring the common good. Hence, he concludes, the justice and necessity of a civil magis- trate is to be inferred. For that institution is nothing more than a man, or several or many men, invested with that power of govern- ing a perfect community. And it is clear that this power must exist in men ; for mankind are not naturally politically governed by angels, nor immediately by God himself, who, according to his ordinary law, acts by means of sufficient secondary causes. Therefore, it follows that civil polities are governed by men. 6 This disquisition may perhaps appear subtile and metaphysical, but it is useful to show the nature of human government, considered as such, and its connexion with Divine government, which ordinarily is carried on through the medium of secondary causes. And so we may remember that Domat, in drawing his general plan of human society, includes among the four foundations of the order of society in its present state, the government exercised by God over it. The great civilian says : " It is by God's universal providence over mankind, that He divides the earth among men, and distinguishes nations by the diversity of empires, kingdoms, republics and other states ; that He regulates the bounds and duration* of them by the events which give them their rise, their increase and their fall ; and that in the midst of all these changes, He forms and maintains civil society in every state by the distinctions of persons to fill employments and other places, and by the other ways in which He regulates and governs everything/ These reflections refute the error of those who have looked on human government as so different from Divine government, as to be opposed to it. c Suarez, De Legib. lib. 3, cap. 1, 3. d Div. Thorn. Aquin. Opusc. De Regim. Princip. lib. 1, cap. 1. e Suarez, ubi sup. 5. f Domat, Loix Civiles, Traite Pufend. ibi ; Heineccii Praelectiones in Pufendorf; De Offic. Horn, et Civ. lib. 2, cap. 7, 3. r See beginning of Chap. XVII. 224 OF THE PARTS OR BRANCHES In relation to private law the province of the legal power of punish- ment is the protection of private rights where they are not sufficiently protected by the civil remedies, whereby the rights of dominion or pro- perty and the obligations arising either from consent or without con- sent, are protected and enforced. Thus, for example, the right of dominion or ownership would not be sufficiently protected by the civil remedy of restitution in cases of theft. 8 But in relation to Public Law, the province of the legal power of punishing is more extensive. We have seen that Domat defines Public Law to be a system of rules which regard the general order of a state. And he shows that the power of restraining by punishments persons who violate those rules, and disturb that order, is necessary to the existence of human society. The exigencies of human society in highly civilized countries have engendered an infinite variety of those rules, and caused the detail of that order to become very complicated and extensive. Hence that great number of penalties or punishments which we find in the laws of our own and other countries, having for their object to enforce obedience to their enactments. And viewed in this light, criminal law may be considered as a branch of Public Law. Its fundamental principle is contained in the words of Cujacius with regard to municipal law, strictly so called, that is to say, positive or arbitrary municipal law : Utilitas peperit jus civile. Hac autem utilitas CBquitas est, et quidquid reipub. utile et conducibile est, bonum et cequum est. And so Grotius lays it down that the true object of human punishment is not vengeance but some utility, some advantage to be derived from its infliction. 1 It is not only because the offender morally deserves punishment that he is punished, but he is punished with a view to utility, to produce some useful result. And so, as Grotius and Pufendorf agree, every punishment ought to have for its object the correction of the offender, the security of those interested in the offence not being again committed, or the welfare of the community or mankind at large." The chief and essential object of punishments is to deter others, by example, from offending. 51 This is the only object of capital punish- ments. Another great object of punishments is the amendment of the offender. It is the infliction of some pain, with a view to deter the See my Readings at the Middle Temple, p. 139. 1 Cujac. Recit. Solemn, ad lib. 1 Digest, tit. De Just, et Jur. ; Cujac. Op. torn. 7, col. 9, edit. Venet. Mutin. ; Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv.2, c. 15, 4; Cremani, De Jur. Crim. lib. 1, pars 2, ch. 4, vol. 1, p 124. u Pufend. Devoir de 1'Homme et du Cit. liv. 2, ch. 13, 6, 7; Grot, ubi sup. 8, p. 128; Devoti, Inst. Canon, lib. 4, tit. 1, 1. x Cremani, De Jur. Crim. ubi sup. 8. OF THE SOVEREIGN POWER. 225 offender from breaking the law again ; and it should be accompanied with what Lord Coke calls preventing justice, which consists partly in religious and moral instruction.* Of the corrective character all punish- ments ought to partake, except that of death, which operates only by way of example. Such are the general objects of punishments. But the degree of moral guilt of the offence must not be neglected in deter- mining the severity with which it should be punished. 2 And utility being the object of punishments, severity ought never to be carried beyond what that object demands. Therefore it is necessary that there should be vested in the sovereign power of the state an authority to pardon offences or mitigate punishments, in cases in which peculiar circumstances require an exception to the general rules of criminal law, or where clemency is more for the public good than a strict adherence to the law. a The legislative power and that of enforcing the laws would suffice, with the judicial power, to secure men from wrongful acts of others, but other things are also necessary for the order and welfare of a state and to attain the objects of civil society. As public affairs, in times both of peace and of war, could not be managed or administered by the sovereign or the sovereign power itself, without the assistance of ministers, officers, and magistrates, it is necessary that there should be in every state a power of establishing persons to hear and determine the differences of the citizens, to levy and manage the revenue and finances, to discipline and command forces, and perform various other duties in the public administration and economy. 15 This is one of the powers generally included in the exe- cutive branch. And whatever be the mode in which public officers and magistrates are appointed or elected, their authority is part of the civil power of government, and emanates from the sovereign power of the state. And thus Blackstone says, that the most universal public rela- tion by which men are connected together is that of government; namely, as governors and governed, or, in other words, as magistrates and people. And of magistrates some are supreme, in whom the sove- reign power of the state resides ; others are subordinate, deriving their authority from the supreme magistrate, and acting in a subordinate sphere. The functions and duties of those public officers are of various descriptions : some judicial, others executive ; some ministerial and * Coke, 3rd Inst. Epilogue. z Grot, ubi sup. 28. * Lampredi, Diritto Publ. Univers. lorn. 3, p. 74. b Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 4, 6; Heineccii Praelectiones in Pufend. De Offic. Horn, et Civ. lib. 2, cap. 7, $ 6. c Blackst. Com. b. 1, ch. 2, p. 146. Q 226 OF THE PARTS OR BRANCHES others discretionary, and others again consisting in advising and deli- berating : and their various offices and gradations, and the way in which they perform different parts of the public service, their rights, their ob- ligations, and responsibilities, constitute the greater part of the internal Public Law of every state. These matters are governed by an infinite variety of rules, some of natural or immutable, and others of positive law ; but all bearing some relation to the order of society and to the two primary laws on which that order is constructed. For the body of society is composed of an infinite number of different conditions and professions and employments necessary for the common good. And it is essential to society that there should not only be a subordination of them all under one power, but also a systematic subordination among themselves according as their functions depend upon each other, for the purpose of uniting the whole body politic together by the spirit of the two primary laws. And thus we have seen that the power of civil government is one of the bonds or ties by which universal human society is made to subsist. We have also seen that another tie by which God maintains human society is that of the common humanity uniting men together, though belonging to different states. It has for its subject the use of commerce and of the several sorts of intercourse and communications which one nation holds with another, and the subjects of one state with those of another. And hence arises the necessity of negociations, embassies, and treaties among nations. And as there is no common power having authority over nations to maintain the observance of those laws which ought to govern them in their intercourse with each other, and punish offences against them, wars have become necessary, with a variety of things arising from that mode of settling the differences of nations. Treaties, negociations, wars, the conclusion of peace, and the various matters arising therefrom, are therefore a necessary branch of the sovereign power. d It naturally belongs to the executive. Though the right of declaring war is vested by the constitution of the United States of America in the legislature, 6 that of carrying it on belongs to the Pre- sident/ And, for the most part, this prerogative is given by the Public Law of different countries to the executive. And though treaties have o a force and effect analogous to laws, yet they are not laws, but con- tracts. With regard to negociations, it is important to observe that in a state where the legislative authority is vested in one or more assem- blies, they must be confided to the executive branch of the government, d Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 8, ch. 6, 10; Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 3, ch. 1, 4; liv. 4, ch. 2, 10. e Kent, Comment, vol. 1, part 1, lect. 3, p. 52. 1 Ibi, part 2, lect. 13, p. 282. OF THE SOVEREIGN POWER. 227 which usually possesses the necessary requisites of unity, secrecy and despatch. And for this reason ministers in this country frequently decline to communicate information to Parliament regarding negocia- tions which are not concluded. The internal peace of the community would not suffice without pro- tection against external injuries and attacks. For this purpose the citizens must unite their forces for their common security and the maintenance of their common rights. And thus there must be in the State a power of assembling and arming forces on land, and, in some cases, on the sea also. g Such forces are also required in time of peace, for the maintenance of the public tranquillity, and the protec- tion of commerce ; and external security can hardly be enjoyed by any nation that is not prepared for the event of war. This can only be accomplished by keeping some permanent military establishment, the care of which is an important department of executive govern- ment. Public administration and government, both in war and peace, require considerable resources and expenditure. Therefore the sove- reign authority must have power to make the subjects contribute to the expenses necessary for the State. 1 ' The State has rights over the citizens who compose it, and their property, so far as the public welfare necessarily requires. This right is the chief part of what is commonly called jus eminens, or superior right. It is that right which the entire body has over the members and whatever belongs to them, and which being for the common good is superior to the private rights of individuals belonging to their private interest. 1 This jus eminens is called by writers on Public Law dominium eminens, when it regards property. k It is the right of the State or the sove- reign power over property within it when necessity or the public good requires. 1 This is the true, foundation of the right of taxation. That right has indeed been placed by some writers on the ground of consent of individuals to part with a portion of their property for the public good. But this theory is an instance of the error which attributes to consent or contract, obligations which arise from natural equity. The doctrine that every man consents (in some forms of polity) to be taxed by his representatives, rests on a fiction, for every system of represen- tation leaves many, frequently the majority, unrepresented, who never- * Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 4, 5. h Pufend. Devoir de 1'Homme et du Citoyen, liv. 2, ch. 7, 7. 1 Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 1, ch. 1, 6. k Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Nat. et Publ. Eccl. torn. 1, lib. 3, cap. 4, 214; Lampredi, Diritto Publ. Univers. torn. 3, parte 2, cap. 3, 21 ; Grot. Droit de la G. liv. 1, ch. 3, 6. 1 Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 20, 244. Q2 228 OF THE PARTS OR BRANCHES theless pay taxes." 1 And here a celebrated rule of the canon law is applicable quod omnes tangit ab omnibus debet approbari. n The meaning of the rule is, that though the corporate acts of a body, such as a chapter, are valid with the consent of the majority, the consent of all is necessary for the purpose of affecting the private individual rights of the members of the body. So the consent of a majority would not per se suffice on sound principles of jurisprudence to affect the private individual rights of property of the minority of the citizens, without an obligation making it the duty of the minority to submit to the decision of such majority. But if an obligation to contribute to the burthens of the State be shown, then it will follow that the powers of imposing taxes and other duties lawfully belongs to that person or those persons in whom it is vested by the fundamental or organic laws of the State. That obligation is similar to the other obligations of secondary natural law, resulting, as consequences, from the insti- tution of civil society ; and so it is held by the highest authorities on Public Law. q For all the members of a body ought to perform their duties in it, that the body may subsist in the good order in which it ought to be for the common welfare ; therefore it is both necessary and just that those who compose a state should consider it their duty to do what is required of them for this common good, which is their own good. This truth, which comprehends all duties to the public, particularly regards the duty of those who compose a state, to contri- bute towards the expenses which the public service requires, whether for its internal order and administration, or for defending; it against * o o external enemies since, without this assistance, the state would perish by injustice, violence, divisions, and sedition, and would be left an easy prey to its enemies. q The same principles prove that it is sometimes just that a person be deprived of his property for the public advantage, as is the case when railroads, canals and other public works are constructed on private property. But in that case the person whose rights are affected has a right to compensation ; for the charges of the public service ought to be distributed equally and in a just proportion, and no one (as far as may be) should be burthened beyond his just share. This principle is analogous to the case of goods thrown out to lighten a vessel : for the owner of the property is entitled to compensation from the others who ni Savigny speaks of " the fiction of representation" in this sense. Traits' du Droit Rom. vol. 1, p. 30. n Reg. 29, tit. De Reg. Juris, in Quinto Decretalium. Faebeus, De Regul. Jur. Canon, p. 175, &c. P Zallinger, Instil. Jur. Nat. et Eccles. Publ. torn. 1, lib. 3, cap. 7. 4 Domat, Droit Publ. liv. 1, tit. 5. OF THE SOVEREIGN POWER. 229 have derived advantage, by the safety of their goods, from his loss/ Compensation to persons whose property is taken or injured for public advantage should be given either by the State or by the persons pro- moting or more immediately benefited by the works. Such are the chief principles of Public Law regarding a public re- venue. They are in accordance with the doctrine of Adam Smith, that " the subjects of every state ought to contribute to the support of the government, as nearly as possible in proportion to their re- spective abilities; that is, in proportion to the revenue which they enjoy respectively under the protection of the State. In the obser- vation or neglect of this maxim consists what is called the equality or inequality of taxation." 5 And so another high authority says : " For what reason ought equality to be the rule in matters of tax- ation ? For the reason that it ought to be so in all the affairs of government, as a government ought to make no distinction of persons or classes in the strength of their claims on it: whatever sacrifices it requires from them should be made to bear as nearly as possible with the same pressure on all, which, it must be observed, is the mode by which least sacrifice is occasioned on the whole. If any one bears less than his fair share of the burthen, some other person must suffer more than his share, and the alleviation to the one is not, ctsteris paribus, so great a good to him, as the increased pressure on the other is an evil. Equality of taxation, therefore, as a maxim of politics, means equality of sacrifice. It means apportioning the contribution of each person towards the expenses of the govern- ment, so that he shall feel neither more nor less inconvenience from his share of the payment than every other person experiences from his. This standard, like other standards of perfection, cannot be completely realized ; but the first object in every practical discussion should be to know what perfection is." 1 It is curious to find some- thing analogous to those principles in the laws of Manou." The charges of the public service are partly defrayed in most countries by public property vested in the sovereign power of the state, for the benefit of the community. And the administration of r Grot. Droit de la G. liv. 3, ch. 20, 7; Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 8, cb. 5, 7; Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 20, 244; Pandect, lib. 14, tit. 2, De Lege Rhodia ; Elukemore v. Glamorganshire Canal Company, 1 Mylne & K. 162 ; 1 Blackst. Com. 139; 1 Stephen, Com. 133, 134, 154; Simpson v. Lord Howden, 1 Keen, 598, 599; Lister v. Lobley, 7 Ad. & El. 124; Entick v. Carrington, 19 Howell, State Trials, 1066. 9 Adam Smith, Wealth of Nations, b. 5, ch. 2, part 2. And see Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 8, ch. 5, 6. Mill, Polit. Econ. vol. 2, b. 5, ch. 2, 2, p. 350. Loix de Manou, liv. 7, 128, 129 ; and see Pufend. Droit des Gens, 1. 8, ch.5, 5. 230 OF THE PARTS OR BRANCHES OF THE SOVEREIGN POWER. such property is for the most part entrusted to the executive power, though subject to legislative regulations. 35 Such, in this country, are the crown lands or demesne lands which form part of the ordinary revenue of the crown. y This species of property must be distinguished from the private patrimony of the prince, which belongs to him other- wise than by the title of his quality as sovereign. 2 There is some doubt whether the raising of revenue naturally belongs to the legislative or to the executive branch of government. Grotius, Pufendorf and Burlamaqui, agree in placing it under a separate head. a But a distinction will easily solve the difficulty. The establishment of a permanent tax must naturally be by the enactment of a law by the legislative power, for this is a general regulation prescribed by the sovereign power of the state. But it does not follow that because in countries where there is a representa- tive assembly, the consent of that assembly is required for the impo- sition of taxation; therefore, that act of sovereignty is necessarily legislative. Thus, where supplies are raised in the form of a contri- bution, to be paid once, it is not necessarily an act of legislation, though it may be so in point of form, according to the municipal law of the country. And the actual levying and management of revenue is essentially an executive function, especially where it consists of carry- ing the law into execution, by receiving and administering a permanent tax. The doctrine that raising a revenue belongs to the legislative power is more political than legal, and it is grounded on unanswerable reasons of policy, whenever the form of government is mixed. We may conclude that the power of taxing the community for the public wants is of an anomalous nature, though frequently exercised by the enactment of laws ; but the actual levying of imposts and their ma- nagement properly belongs, on legal principles, to the executive. With regard to interference with the rights of property by the State for the public advantage, as in the case of roads, canals and railways, and other public works, it would seem that where this involves a per- manent alienation of private property secured by the municipal law, without the consent of the owner, it ought to emanate from the autho- rity of the legislative power; but the actual administration of this function is executive. * Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 20, 244. y Blackst. Com. b. 1, ch. 8, pp. 245, 246. 1 L. 2, Cod. De Offic. com. rer. priv. ; 1. ult. Cod. De Agricol. et Mancip. Domin. ; 1. 6, ff. De Jure Fisci ; Domat, Droit Publ. liv. 1, tit. 6, 8. * See my Comment, on the Constit. Law of England, p. 61 ; Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. I, ch. 3, 6, num. 4 ; Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 8, ch. 5, 4; Bur- lamaqui, Droit des Gens, vol. 4, part 2, ch. 13, 6, p. 415, edit. Dupin ; Martens, Droit des Gens, liv. 3, ch. 3, 88. OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. 231 CHAPTER XXI. OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. Legal Nature and Necessity of the Judicial Power Private War Cases in which the Use of Force by Private Individuals is still lawful in Civil Society Right of Self- defence Jurisdiction Notio Proper or ordinary and delegated Jurisdiction Civil and Criminal Jurisdiction Distinction between Public and Private Wrongs Effect of Judicial Decisions Res judicata Degrees of Jurisdiction and Appeals. WE have seen that Grotius, in dividing the sovereign power, refers to the judicial branch as the function of the sovereignty which regulates particular private matters, considered as having a relation to the public good. It may, perhaps, here be objected, that the judicial power, which decides doubtful questions regarding the application of laws, frequently pronounces on public as well as on private matters. This is true; but the judicial power never decides a naked proposition. It decides differences which arise in the case of individuals acting in their public or private capacity, or bodies acting as persons in law. Thus, in the trial of a minister of state, or other public functionary, for a state offence, the direct question which the court has to decide, is the guilt or innocence of the accused, though that decision has a relation to and may affect the constitution and welfare of the state. In this respect, Grotius speaks of things under the judicial power, as particular matters, directly or immediately private. The judicial power is one of the three great branches of the civil power of government, and necessary for the maintenance of civil society. Its legal nature must now be examined as a fundamental part of Public Law. The legislator constructs the law by discovering the organic nature of the institution or matter which he has to regulate, and drawing from it an abstract rule. But the judge, by an inverse operation, recomposes that which has been decomposed, and of which the law presents a single aspect. 6 Laws cannot by the utmost skill of a human legislator be so con- structed as to exclude all doubts as to their application ; therefore, disputes must arise touching their application to particular cases, and b Savigny, Traite du Droit Rom. torn. 1, ch. 2, 13, p. 42; 1. 3, ff. De Legib. 1. 8, ibi. 232 OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. it is frequently necessary to examine into a multitude of circumstances, where actions are alleged to be at variance with the law. c And before the effect of the law in a particular case can be determined, it is neces- sary to ascertain the facts. But questions of fact are, as Neratius says, liable to greater doubts and difficulties than questions of law. d Now these questions of law and fact must be settled when they arise, other- wise the law would be altogether disobeyed in all such cases, and would take effect only where both its meaning and its application were undisputed. And thus the laws on which the whole system and the order of civil society depend, would be rendered of no effect, for laws would cease to be general rules of conduct. Especially criminal laws would be useless, since offenders would scarcely ever admit their own guilt. Mere natural society presents no sufficient solution of these dif- ficulties, for as it has no sovereign power, every man must be left to vindicate his own rights and those of the persons in whom he is inte- rested or whom he is bound to protect. This method has been called private war, concerning which Grotius says, that the law of sociability, which is in the nature of man, does not forbid all use of force, but only violence contrary to society, that is to say, that which is contrary to the rights of others. For a chief object of society is that each person may enjoy peaceably all that belongs to him, with the assistance of the power of the whole body. 6 Therefore the law of society cannot justly prevent a man from defending and enforcing his own rights, unless society will undertake that task for him. But on the other hand, the right of private war, which makes every man judge in his own cause, and gives an undue advantage to the strong over the weak, is liable to the most serious evils/ Civil society furnishes the remedy, and indeed it is by its very nature and objects incompatible with the existence of a system leaving each man to determine and enforce his own rights. For as Domat says, the different engagements or obligations by which man is destined to society on the foundation of the two primary laws, re- quire the use of a government to restrain every one within the order of those which bind him. And for this God has established the authority of the powers which are necessary to maintain society. 5 It is, more- over, contrary to natural reason that any man should be judge in his own cause. h c Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 4, 4. d L. 2, flT. De Jur. et Fact, ignor. e Grotius, Droit de la Guerre, liv. 1, ch. 2, ^ 1, num. 6. f Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Nat. et Eccles. Pub. torn. 1, lib. 3, cap. 9, 140. 6 Domat, Loix Civiles, Traite des Loix, cb. 4, 6. h Cod. lib. 3, tit. 5, Ne quis in sua causa ; Hob. Rep. 87 ; Voet ad Pand. lib. 2, tit. 2, $50. OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. 233 From these reasons springs the fundamental doctrine of Public Law laid down by Antoninus Pius, Callistratus, and Paulus, that no man is permitted to take the law into his own hands, and to do himself that which the civil magistrate is instituted to do, when the civil power is able and ready to maintain his rights. 1 It follows that under the civil state, the civil power of government must administer justice, by de- ciding in each disputed case, whether the facts are within the meaning of the law and what the law commands thereon, and for this purpose deciding, where there is dispute or doubt, what are the true facts which are to be subjected to the rules of the law. And for this purpose, judges and magistrates of divers sorts and orders are instituted in every civil comrmmity. For as the law of nature does not give any man authority to judge over his fellows, the creation of judges belongs, as we have seen, to the sovereign power, which cannot itself perform those functions in person, though it sometimes reserves a supreme judi- cature by way of appeal.* Thus the institution of civil society has taken away the right of private war from individuals. But this proposition must not be received without limitations. For those cases must be excepted in which, as Grotius says, the recourse to civil justice is not open to the citizen, 1 and the right of self-defence therefore remains. Every man has a right to defend himself or his property, or even to defend others, where there is not time or opportunity to call the aid of the civil power. The reason is obvious; for if it were not so, men would find themselves in a worse condition in those cases, under civil government, than they would be in if they were living in mere natural society without any civil govern- ment. Therefore, Paulus specifies that it is not allowed for private persons to do for themselves that which the magistrate is able to do for them by his authority, otherwise great disorders would ensue. These reflections show that the judicial power is of secondary natural law, like the other parts of the civil power of government, necessary for the maintenance of society and the fulfilment of the two primary laws whereon society is constructed. And indeed it may be questioned whether some sort of judicature be not more necessary to the mainte- nance of civil society than municipal laws themselves. The exercise of the judicial power is called jurisdiction. That term in its wider acceptation means every species of authority over persons or over things with reference to persons which is not a mere right of 1 L. 13, ff. Quod metus causa ; 1. 176, ff. De Reg. Jur. k Devoti, Inst. Jur. Canon, lib. 3, tit. 1, ^1,3. 1 Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 1, ch. 3, 3. m L. 176, ff. De Regul. Jur. 234 OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. property." But in the stricter sense, jurisdiction is the public power of deciding causes, civil and criminal ; or the cognizance and decision of disputes which arise among men ; the examination of accusations, and the punishment of the guilty according to law. p Jurisdiction is exer- cised by the interpretation of the law, that is to say, by the declaration of the judge that the particular fact in dispute before his tribunal is or is not comprised in the law; q or by the decision of the judge as to the truth of alleged facts, and his declaration that the state of facts so found to be true is or is not within the meaning of some particular law or principle of law. Thus Marcian speaks of the decisions of the Praetor as the living voice of the civil law ; and Cicero says, that the magistrate is a speaking law, and the law a silent magistrate/ We have already seen the distinction between merum imperium and jurisdiction, 5 which includes the power of executing or ordering the execution of that which is decided. 1 There is also the simple power of deciding, which is called by the civilians notio y as contradistinguished from jurisdiction. It consists of the mere power of cognition and de- ciding, so that the execution of what is decided remains for another authority having jurisdiction. 11 Such was the authority of masters in chancery. Jurisdiction may be either proper or delegated. The former is that which the judge exercises by virtue of his own office, and not by the authority of any other person ; and the latter is a jurisdiction held and exercised in the name and instead of some other person who granted it.* This distinction is especially in use among the canonists, who designate proper jurisdiction by the name of ordinary jurisdiction, and divide all judges into ordinary judges and delegates, or judges delegated There are other legal distinctions regarding jurisdiction, but these are for the most part either peculiar to the civil and canon law, or have their use and application chiefly with reference to private law. We will, therefore, confine ourselves to those which belong to Public Law. The most remarkable is that which divides jurisdiction into two branches, civil and criminal. They are thus defined. a Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 4, ch. 4, 14. Voet ad Pand. 1. 2, tit. 1, De Jurisdic. 1. P Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 4, 4. And see Coke, 4th Inst. proem. 1 Lampredi, Jur. Pub. Univ. par. 2, c. 3, 17. 1 L. 8, ff. De Just, et Jur. ; Cicero, De Legib. lib. 3, 1. Chap. XX. Voet ad Pand. lib. 2, tit. 1, 1. Ibi, 2 ; 1. 15, ff. De re judic. * Voet, ibi, ^ 7. y Devoti, Inst. Canon, torn. 2, p. 33, lib. 2, tit. 2, 1 ; Decretal, lib. 1, tit. 29 ; ibi, tit. 31. OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. 235 Criminal jurisdiction is the public power of taking cognizance of crimes, and imposing punishments for the public welfare f or, as it is defined by Pufendorf, the power of examining accusations, and com- manding the punishment of the guilty, according to law. Civil jurisdiction is that which has for its object the application of laws not intended for the punishment of offenders, but declaring, de- fining or creating natural or civil, immutable or positive rights. Some writers have sought the principle which distinguishes these two branches of jurisdiction from each other in the difference between private and public wrongs, and have held that the former are redressed by the civil, and the latter are vindicated by the criminal jurisdiction. But this does not solve the difficulty. Some unlawful acts, that is to say, acts or omissions at variance with the law, tend directly to injure the commonwealth, while others are immediately injurious to the rights of individuals or bodies considered as such. a But no general invariable rule determines, on an abstract principle, the boun- dary between public and private wrongs. Eveiy violation of a private right of an individual is a disturbance of the order of society, and an offence against the community, which is established for the protection of men's rights and the welfare of all its members. Viewed under this aspect, it is a public wrong. We have seen that man is destined to society, founded on the two primary laws, by two classes of engage- ments, which include all the legal relations that exist among men, whether springing from the natural ties of marriage, or from the infi- nite variety of engagements formed by the several communications which pass among men of their labour and industry, and all kinds of services and assistances, and those that relate to the use of things. And this comprehends all that may link persons together according to the different wants of life, by gratuitous communications or by com- merce. And by all these engagements of both kinds God forms the order of society of mankind, to link them together in the exercise of the second law. b The breach of any of the obligations, and the viola- tion of any of the rights constituting that complicated network of innumerable and various engagements which pervade human society, is a disturbance of its order, and a wrong against the commonwealth. There are, indeed, offences directly affecting the community alone ; and others, which, by reason of their pernicious nature, are injuries inflicted on society, as well as directly hurtful to some of its members. But these are particular sorts of cases which do not afford a general x Boehmerus, Jur. Crim. 1, cap. 3, | 60 ; Carmignani, Elem. Jur. Crira. vol. 1 , pp. 212, 113 ; Renazzi, Jurispr. Crim. lib. 3, c. 2, 2, n. 2. * Vinnius ad Instit. Paratit. ad tit. 1, lib. 4. b Dotnat, Loix Civiles, Traite des Loix, chap. 2. 236 OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. rule. And it may often occur that what is treated by the law as a private wrong, is not less injurious to the community than another offence, which is, nevertheless, placed under the head of public wrongs. Thus, for instance, it cannot be said that a petty theft is more perni- cious to society than the wrongful and fraudulent detaining of an estate, or the refusal to pay a just debt ; or that a trifling assault is more prejudicial to the community than the seduction of the daughter or wife of a citizen. Yet, by the law of England, the former is an indictable offence, and the latter only the subject of a civil action. Blackstone c defines private wrongs or civil injuries as an infringement or privation of the civil rights of individuals, considered merely as indi- viduals. But theft comes within that description, and yet it is treated as a public wrong. Blackstone seems to have felt this objection, for in exemplifying the distinction between public and private wrongs, he enumerates as public wrongs a number of instances all consisting of an offence either against the State as a body, or directly against the public peace, or including a violation of the rights of the community. The learned commentator perceived the true reason of the distinction which we are examining, for he says, " the law has a double view, namely, not only to redress the party injured, but also to secure to the public the benefit of society by preventing or punishing every breach of those laws which the sovereign power has established for the tran- quillity and government of the whole." He gives here a description of the general objects of government. We may deduce therefrom that when the wrong is sufficiently redressed, and the wrong-doer suffi- ciently discouraged by the reparation which he is forced to make to the injured person, the wrong may be treated as a private wrong, and left to the civil remedy. But where the nature of the wrong is such that any reparation must be impossible or inadequate, and where the enforcement of the obligation to make reparation is ineffectual for deterring the wrong-doer and others, society is bound, for the protec- tion of its members, to threaten and execute punishment in such cases, as well as in those wherein the grave nature, or the object of the crime, render it public as being an evident injury to the community in its cor- porate or politic capacity. We must conclude that, except in cases of the latter description, the distinction between civil and criminal law and jurisdiction is matter of public policy, and may vary according to the circumstances of times and places. For instance, an illegal refusal to pay a debt legally due is a private wrong, and sufficiently repaired by civil remedies. But if there were an illegal and unjust general refusal to pay any important class of debts all over a country, the 'Blackst. Com. b. 4, c. 1, 1. OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. 237 number of private wrongs might become so serious in its effect that the civil remedy might be insufficient, and then the legislature might properly add a public prosecution and penalty to the insufficient power of the civil laws, though each of the refractory debtors might be actu- ated by no design against the commonwealth. And on the same principle it is held in the law of England, that the generality of an illegal act may alter the nature of the offence, so that, for instance, to levy a force or multitude of men to pull down a particular enclosure is a riot, but the same thing done to pull down all enclosures is levying war against the king and high treason.* 1 The question for the legis- lator to consider is, how a sufficient remedy can be provided to enforce the law, and secure the order of society. Thus, theft would evidently be very inadequately discouraged by the mere civil remedy of restitu- tion. Therefore, thieves must be punished by the criminal laws, though theft is a private wrong, considered in itself. These doctrines are confirmed by the reflection that, though offences against Muni- cipal Law are also for the most part violations of Natural Law also, yet the definitions of offences, where the Natural Law does not clearly define them, and the appointment of punishments, belong to arbitrary mutable law, which has its justice in its relation to the order of society, and the particular advantage found in enacting it, according as the times and places and other circumstances may require. 6 And every body of Criminal Law contains both sorts of arbitrary laws, those which are consequences of natural laws, and those which regu- late invented artificial matters. We have now to consider the effect of decisions of the judicial power, on legal rights and obligations, with reference to Public Law. The nature of judicial functions implies necessarily that every suit or prosecution should have a solution, and that solution should be exe- cuted even against the will of the unsuccessful party/ It follows, that whether the judgment be right or wrong, it declares and defines the rights of the parties conclusively, if it be final. Hence the maxim of the civil law Resjudicataproveritate accipitur. It is founded on the principle of Paulus Singulis controversiis singulas actiones, unumque judicati finem sufficere probabili ratione placuit ; ne aliter modus litium multiplicatus summam atque inexplicabilem facial diffi- cultatem ; maxime si diver sa pronunciarentur. K This principle of public policy leads to a further consequence, namely, that not only a final judgment is conclusive in that suit between the parties, but it is d Hale, Pleas of the Crown, vol. 1, pp. 133, 134 ; Foster, Crown L. 215 ; Keiling, 70. e Domat, Lois Civiles, Traite des Loix, ch. 11, 20. f Savigny, Traite" de Droit Rom. torn. 6, p. 264, ch. 4, 280. e L. 6, ff. De except, rei judic. 238 OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. conclusive between them in every other suit. It may, as Savigny observes, seem natural, that when the justice of a decision comes in question in a new judicial proceeding, it ought to be examined over again, because if there be error, equity demands that it be rectified. But, on the other hand, the evils pointed out by Paulus would arise from this conclusion, which would produce a perpetual uncertainty of legal rights. We have to choose between two dangers. The question is, which of the two involves less injury to society. This is a question of Public Law. h Long experience, and the law of different nations, show that the uncertainty of law has been looked upon as the greater evil and as an intolerable one, and to prevent it recourse has been had to an institution of positive law. The danger of unjust or erro- neous judgments arising therefrom has been diminished by the esta- blishment of degrees of jurisdiction and appeals. The important positive institution intended to accomplish the end above mentioned may be generally defined as the authority of res judicata, that is to say, a fiction of truth which protects final judg- ments from being impeached or modified. 1 This fiction or absolute presumption of truth gives to a matter of judicial procedure a powerful effect on legal rights themselves ; for it may engender a right which did not previously exist, or destroy or restrict an existing right, or modify that which it contains. But the real practical value of this institution, as well as its object and spirit, are to maintain just and correct judgments. For legal rights are often uncertain and doubtful, and the means of proof vary at different times with regard to the same facts. Therefore, the second judge may decide erroneously a case rightly decided by the first; and a final decision is better for the parties than perpetual uncertainty. k We find here a remarkable instance of the way in which institutions of positive law contribute to the machinery and government of civil society, and also the peculiar equity belonging to them, which consists in their relation to and use in the order of society. In this peculiar equity their spirit is to be found and their relation to the two primary laws on which society is constructed. We come now to degrees of jurisdiction and appeals. This institu- tion seems at first sight inconsistent with what has been said re- garding the importance of settling every litigation by a final decision. But it is not so ; for this institution only makes the suit pass through different degrees or stages, to arrive at a final solution. Its advantages to prevent erroneous judgments are thus shown by Savigny. In the h Savigny, ubi sup. p. 265. Ibi, p. 266. k Ibi, pp. 268, 269. OF THE JUDICIAL POWER. 239 first place, the revision of a decision is a powerful means both for the parties and the judge to study and thoroughly master the questions in dispute. It is a still greater advantage to submit the final decision to a greater number of judges selected with much care. The new exa- mination may however take place before the same court. 1 These considerations are doubly important in criminal cases, especially where the punishment is very severe. For, as Carpezovius says, the salutary remedy of appeal is more especially to be allowed where the question in dispute involves, not a mere civil and perhaps trifling right, but the life of a man and an irreparable evil. Therefore, the civil law gives the prisoner (except in certain cases wherein the public safety will not admit any delay in the punishment of a notorious offender) a general right of appeal, and allows any byestander to appeal for him even against his will." Such is the spirit of the institution of appeals, of which, however, Ulpian says nonnunquam bene latas sententias in pejus reformat. And thus we see the importance and difficulty of so framing and regulating institutions according to their spirit, as to attain, as far as the imperfection of human means will allow, the end which that spirit points out. CHAPTER XXII. THE CONNEXION OF THE JURA MAJE8TATIS WITH EACH OTHER. Difficulties arising from the Union of equal Powers by a Convention only Union by means of Civil Government Historical Illustrations Chief Defect of several Fe- deral Constitutions The United States of America Pufendorf 's Argument regarding the Division of the Jura Majestatis or Parts of the Sovereign Power Necessity of Unity in the Sovereign Power Historical Illustrations The same Proposition de- monstratedPrinciples on whidi the Sovereign Power may be divided Consti- tutional Balance of Power Insufficiency of Laws alone to preserve it. PUFENDORF examines somewhat fully the connexion between the branches or parts of the civil power of government ; and though the conclusion to which he arrives is not unanswerable, his arguments 1 Savigny, ibS, ^ 284, pp. 291, 295. m Carpezov. Pract. Rer. Crim. pars 3, quaest. 139, num. 7. Mathseus, De Criminibus, p. 744; 1. 6, ff. De Appell. ; 1. 29, Cod. eod. tit.; 1. 2, ult. ff. Quando appellandum est. L. 1, ff. De appell. 240 OF THE CONNEXION OF THE deserve consideration, because they illustrate many important things in Public Law, showing certain difficulties which arise whenever those parts are separated and vested in different persons or bodies. There is, says the learned jurist, such an indissoluble connexion between the parts of sovereignty, that if it be supposed that they are in the hands of different persons, so that each may exercise his func- tions independently of the others, the result is an irregular state. For there are two principal ties which may unite the will of several persons or assemblies, namely, conventions or agreements, and government. Those who are united by agreements only, without subjection to a common government, are bound to the performance of their engage- ments by natural law ; but in other respects they remain equal, as all men are by nature. If either of the parties break natural law by violating his agreement, there remains no remedy in case of his obsti- nate refusal to do what justice requires, except the use of force, that is, the right of war. Thus concord can exist among those who are united simply by convention between equals only so long as each party executes what he has engaged ; and a breach of the contract leads to terminate the alliance and causes war. Hence it appears that conventions alone are not by themselves a sufficiently strong bond to keep several persons long united in a body politic, especially as it is sometimes the more powerful of the parties who violates the compact ; and even if the compact provide that whenever any one of the parties violates his engagements, the others shall unite against him, that clause would be useless when several of them simultaneously break the treaty. It would be necessary that the parties should at least constitute a sort of common government ; otherwise another convention would be re- quisite, regulating in what way those should be dealt with who refuse to lend their assistance against the violators of the alliance, and an- other convention to support the former, and so on ad injinitum. But civil government forms a far more powerful union : for those who are subjects of the same sovereign authority do not remain the equals of the person or body in whom that authority is vested. For the sove- reign has the power of commanding, and punishing those who disobey. Thus the citizens are placed under a greater necessity of conforming to his orders than if they were united by a simple convention, leaving to each a perfect equality, and full power to act according to his will.P These reflections of Pufendorf are illustrated by the constitution of the United States of America, under the articles of Confederation of 1777. For though by that constitution all the federal authority of P Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 4, 9. JURA MAJESTATIS WITH EACH OTHER. 241 the nation was vested in the federal council or congress, the arti- cles of confederation carried the decrees of that assembly to the states in their sovereign or collective capacity. Thus disobedience to the laws of the union must have been submitted to by the govern- ment, or those laws enforced by war. 1 " Kent furnishes another ex- ample from the history of Switzerland. By one of the laws of the Helvetic alliance, the cantons were bound to submit any difference that might arise between them to arbitrators. In the year 1440, a dispute arose between Zurich on the one side, and the cantons of Schweitz and Glaris on the other, respecting some territorial claims. Zurich refused to submit to a decision against her, and the contending parties resorted to arms. All Switzerland was of course armed against Zurich, the refractory member. She sought protection from her ancient enemy, the House of Austria, and the controversy was not terminated in favour of the federal decree until after six years of furious and de- structive war. 1 " The great defect of all former federal governments, such as the Amphyctionic, the Achaean and Lycian confederacies, in ancient Greece; and the Germanic, the Helvetic, the Hanseatic, and the Dutch republics, in modern history, is, that they were sovereignties over sovereigns, and legislations, not for private individuals, but for communities in their political capacity. The only coercion for disobe- dience was physical force, instead of the decree and the pacific power of the civil magistrate. The inevitable consequence, in every case in which a member of such a confederacy chooses to be disobedient, is either a civil war or the annihilation of national authority.* This defect in the political system of the United States of America was, in a great degree, remedied by the General Convention of 1787, which agreed to the plan of government now forming the constitution of that country. That constitution leaves, indeed, the residuary sovereignty of the States, but it grants specifically, and by necessary implication, powers to the union sufficient for a government, whose authority extends over every person within the entire federation. And thus the power of a civil government was made effectual to unite all the members of the body politic together. Pufendorf goes on to argue, that it is easy to see that there is so great a connexion between the parts of sovereignty that no one of them can be separated from the others without producing an irre- gular government, wherein the union of the parts of the government <> Kent, Comment, vol. 1, part 2, sect. 10, pp. 213, 214; Story, Comment, on the Constitution of the United States, vol. 1, ^ 248, 251 ; The Federalist, No. 15. ' Ibi. Ibi, p. 217. R 242 OF THE CONNEXION OF THE is formed by a convention, the effect of which is unsafe. Let us sup- pose, for example, that one person or assembly has originally and independently the legislative power, while another holds, in the same manner, the coactive or executive power. In that case, either the former must be useless and ineffectual, or the other must be its minis- terial servant. For of what use would it be to make laws without the power of enforcing or executing them ? And if the executive be invested with the power of taking cognizance of, and deciding whether the decrees of the legislature are to be executed, the legislative power vanishes. Pufendorf concludes that they must both depend on the same will. So he argues that the power of making peace and war cannot be separated from that of establishing taxes and other imposts. For how could the citizens be bound to take up arms for the defence of the country, or to contribute from their property towards the neces- sary expenses of the state, in peace and war, unless those who refuse to contribute can be lawfully compelled ? It would also, he says, be absurd to give the power of making treaties and alliances regarding peace and war, to any person who has not also the direction of the affairs of peace and war. To explain more fully the necessary connexion of the parts of sovereignty or jura mojestatis, Pufendorf thus examines the different ways in which they may be conceived to be separate. Let us suppose the power of making peace and war to be vested in a prince, the legis- lative and judicial power in the hands of a senate, and the power of establishing taxes in those of an assembly of the people. If the king order the citizens to place themselves under arms, and they refuse to obey, either he has the power of compelling them to obedience him- self, or he must have them judged by the senate. In the former case, it seems that not having the judicial power, he could not have that of ordering the punishment of the refractory citizens who refuse to be enrolled. But if the king must bring them before the senate, that body will decide whether the king had sufficient cause to levy troops, and whether the war ought to be undertaken, and so his power would be reduced to nothing. For we have supposed the senate to have an independent sovereign authority, not emanating from the prince, and therefore it would not be restricted to merely enforcing his commands. The same sort of result arises from comparing the right of the king with that of the people. For the power of making war is nugatory without that of raising supplies. And the assembly of the people will grant none, unless they are satisfied that the war is right and politic. Our author concludes that, if the parts of sovereignty be separated, an irregular body will be produced, the members of which will not be JURA MAJESTATIS WITH EACH OTHER. 243 united by a common government, but by conventions or contracts with each other. 1 These reflections show the difficulty of separating the jura majes- tatis, and the reason why so many mixt or constitutional governments have produced unsatisfactory results, or been of brief duration. This has arisen from a want of unity in the spirit and action of the separate parts of the sovereign power of the state, in consequence of which they do not tend to one common object, but encroach upon each until they fall into mutual hostility. And then, as there is no power to settle the contest, and so restore the equilibrium of the state, either one branch of the government usurps the power of the others, or else an external force, that of the people, or a successful usurper, effects a revolution. The revolution may either overthrow the whole form of government, as was the case with that which destroyed the English monarchy under Charles I.; or it may decide and terminate the con- test between the powers of the state, as occurred on the dethronement of James II., when the Parliament obtained a decided advantage over the Crown. The last French Revolution is another example. There the contest was between the executive and the legislature. The as- sembly of the people was the sovereign. The president was not the officer of the assembly, but the chief magistrate of the people, by whom he was elected directly. The legislative and executive branches of the government were thus separate and co-ordinate. An irrecon- cilable difference arose between them ; and the result was a state of war, in which the president, having the army and a great part of the people, who longed for a strong government, on his side, obtained the victory, and the Republic was soon overthrown." These events were in accordance with the doctrines of Public Law explained by Pufen- dorf; and they show that wherever the parts of the sovereignty of the state are separated, there ought to be some principle of unity direct- ing them to the common object pointed out by the spirit of the par- ticular form of polity, and by the requirements of man and the end of civil society. For, as Grotius says, sovereignty is something simple and indivisible in itself, or an assemblage of divers parts closely bound together. * And this explains the following passage of St. Thomas Aqui- nas: Bonum et salus consociata multitudinis est ut ejus unitas conser- vetur qua, dicitur pax, qua remota, socialis mice perit utilitas, quinimmo multitude dissentiens sibi ipsi sit onerosa Quanta igitur re- Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 4, 9, 11, 12. As Pomponius says, Evenit ut necesse esset Reipublica per unum Consult. L. 2, 11, ff. De Orig. Jur. x Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 1, ch. 3, 17. R2 244 OF THE CONNEXION OF THE gimen efficacius fuerit ad vnitatcm pads servandam, tanto erit utiliusJ Now this unity of peace cannot be preserved without a unity in the sove- reign power. For we have seen, in examining the plan of society founded on the two primary laws, that the end of all government is that of society itself, and civil government is more perfect in proportion as it is adapted to the attainment of that end. 2 The sovereign power is the great and essential feature of civil society. That power is, as Grotius says, com- posed of divers potential parts. 3 But they differ only in the mode of their operation, having one and the same ultimate end or object, 5 which is that of civil or politic society itself. The end of civil society is attained, or sought to be attained, in different ways, by means of different forms of civil polity, each of which has its peculiar spirit and laws. And all the parts of the sovereign power in each state, that is to say, the different operations of that power, must be directed accord- ing to that spirit, to the end of the civil society which it governs. This principle constitutes the unity of the sovereign power and the necessary and indissoluble connexion of its parts. The effect of that unity is to preserve one sovereign will in the state, which is essential to the maintenance and duration of a civil polity. Some writers have used this principle of unity to argue that the entire sovereign power should be vested in one person or body of persons. But the reflections made above show that this is not a ne- cessary conclusion. No doubt the unity of power is most perfect when its parts are thus concentrated;* 1 and cases may occur in which that condensation of authority may be necessary to preserve the state. The Roman Dictatorship, created ne quid respublica detrimenti capiat, is an example of this. And so when in the year 1776, the progress of the British arms excited the most alarming apprehensions for the safety of the American Republic, the Congress transferred to Wash- ington, for the term of six months, complete dictatorial power over the liberty and property of the citizens of the United States. 6 This instance strikingly illustrates the principle of Public Law under consideration, which affords the key to the strongest arguments of those who maintain despotic governments to be best. But there is nothing in Public Law to forbid that the parts of the sovereign power be separated and distributed y Div. Thorn. Aquin. De Regim. Princip. lib. 1, cap. 2. 1 Ibi, cap. 14. Non est ergo ultimus finis multitudinis congregatae vivere secundum virtutem, sed per virtuosam vitam pervenire ad fruitionem divinam .... Tanlo uutem est regimen sublimius, quanta ad Jinem ulteriorem ordinatur. Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 1, ch. 3, 17. b Barbeyrac, note 1, Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 4, 1. c Heineccius, Prselect. ad Pufend. de Offic. Horn, et Civ. lib. 2, cap. 7, fj 8. d Div. Thorn. Aquin. De Regim. Princip. lib. 1, cap. 2. Kent, Comment, vol. 1, part 2, lect. 10, p. 212. JURA MAJESTATIS WITH EACH OTHER. 245 among different persons and assemblies, provided there be such a dis- tribution and combination of authority as to preserve the unity of sovereignty, so that the different powers may act, each according to its nature, with one general will and intent, so as to produce the same result as regards unity as if they were all vested in the same person or body/ Thus if in the British Constitution the crown had no part of the legislative power, it would be entirely at the mercy of the two houses of parliament. 5 The crown having the whole execu- tive, and the two houses of parliament the whole legislative power, the sovereign power would be severed and its unity destroyed. So if supplies could be raised by the crown alone, the public revenues might be used against the authority of parliament. And if, on the other hand, the resources of the state were at the disposal of the two houses of parliament without the concurrence of the crown, those assemblies could raise forces and pay officers and magistrates de- pending entirely on their resolutions, and so the executive branch of the sovereign power would be reduced to insignificance, and the balance of the Constitution destroyed. Therefore, not only all sup- plies are granted by parliament to the crown, but the House of Com- mons votes no money except on the application or with the assent of the crown. h And the House will not even receive any petition praying for a grant of money, unless it be recommended by the crown.' These examples show how the common will of the branches of government is preserved, and the unity of the sovereign power thereby secured. In a well-constructed constitution they mutually check each other, leaving to each its proper attributions, and the freedom neces- sary for the due performance of its particular functions. And so a balance of political power is obtained, and the liberties of the citizens preserved from the arbitrary and unrestrained exercise of civil authority. It must, however, be admitted, notwithstanding the theories of consti- tutional lawyers and statesmen, that the unity of the sovereign power can be absolutely secured only when it is not distributed, but vested in one person or body of persons. For no laws can prevent contests be- tween separated branches of the sovereign power, which, if pushed to extremities, destroy that unity, and so cause convulsions, and some- times the overthrow of the constitution. The reason of this we have already seen. And in every state, such as our own country, in which a powerful popular assembly is invested with the chief control over the national resources, the permanency of its political institutions must f Burlamaqui, Droit des Gens, vol. 4, par. 2, chap. 1, 6. 5 Blackst. Com. b. 1, pp. 154, 155. 11 Hats. Preced. vol. 3, pp. 194, 195, 196. 1 Ibi, p. 242. 246 OF THE CONNEXION OF THE JURA MAJESTATIS. depend in a very great measure on the good sense and moderation of the body of citizens entrusted, with the political franchise. No laws can provide for the want of these qualities in the people, because no laws can restrain the will of a branch of the legislature, and give a remedy against its want of wisdom, without destroying its independ- ence ; and a legislative assembly, supported by the body of the nation, and having the principal part in raising and managing the public revenue, must ultimately prevail in a struggle with the other branches of the sovereign power. This is one reason why new constitutions, apparently calculated to be durable, have nevertheless been overturned, either by a popular revolution, or an appeal to military force on the part of the executive. But, on the other hand, where the legislative assembly or assemblies have not the confidence and support of the nation, or where the military force is sufficient to overawe the people, and the executive can rely on the army, even against the law, a struggle will have a different termination, and probably end in des- potism. Therefore, though the British constitution gives to the crown the command of the army, that force is ipso facto disbanded at the expiration of every year, unless continued by parliament, which also has the sole power of raising the necessary supplies for their mainte- nance. So great is the danger of a state of war arising between the branches of the sovereign power. And even these legal precautions would not suffice in times of internal discord, under a popular, able, and ambitious prince, with a victorious army, if the great body of the nation were not determined to support the law and constitution of the kingdom. THE FORMS OF CIVIL GOVERNMENTS. 247 CHAPTER XXIII. THE FORMS OF CIVIL GOVERNMENTS. REGULAR STATES OR GOVERN- MENTS. REGULAR REPUBLICS. The Constitution of a State Equality of Sovereign States The Place of Political Constitutions in the Scheme of Universal Human Society Character of Organic Laws of States General Classification of Forms of Government Regular or Simple States or Governments Democracy Aristocracy Monarchy Oligarchy Causes of peculiar Municipal Institutions The Republican Form of Polity Nature of a Republic Mixed Governments True Definition of a Republic The Representa- tion of the People examined By what Constituency the Representatives should be chosen Universal Suffrage considered Constituent Assemblies and Conventions Authority of a Majority Secret Voting or Vote by Ballot Indirect Election. WE have seen that Grotius, though he denies that sovereignty always belongs to the people, holds that the common subject of sovereignty is the State, and the proper subject is one or more persons according to the laws and customs of the country. Such person or persons is or are the sovereign* Thus the sovereign power may be vested in one person, or in a small number of persons, or in the general body of the citizens. From these diversities arise the different forms of govern- ment which we are now to consider. 1 The constitution of a state is the law determining the way in which the public authority is to be exercised. That constitution shows the form under which the nation acts as a body politic, how and by whom the people are governed, and the rights and duties of those who govern. The constitution is the establishment of the order according to which the nation proceeds in common to obtain the advantages for which civil or politic society is established ; m and those laws which determine the form of the government, and the manner in which the public power is exercised, are sometimes called organic or fundamental laws." There is this common to all states or civil societies, that the general order is maintained by a superior or sovereign power, whether it reside in one or in many persons. And this is an immutable rule of Public Law, because it is essential to the maintenance of society founded on the two primary laws, and to the order which God has k Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 1, ch. 3, 7. 1 Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 5, 1. m Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 3, 27. - Ibi, 29. 248 THE FORMS OF CIVIL GOVERNMENTS. established in the world. But there is no immutable law pointing out in whom that sovereign power should be vested, and by what machinery it is to be exercised, or, in other words, the form of civil governments. That problem is solved in different ways; and history presents an infinite variety of examples of constitutions or forms of government engendered by the force of events and the circumstances of times, places and persons. All these forms have certain characteristics which distinguish them from each other ; and an analysis of such charac- teristics has enabled writers on Public Law to reduce them to a few principal classes, each of which, however, comprises constitutions differing according to the laws and usages of the countries to which they belong, and more or less adapted to the wants and interests of those countries. These diversities of form do not affect the essential characteristics of sovereign states as such. Thus every nation, every sovereign state, is a member of the great society of mankind, and independent of all civil authority on earth. The sovereign represents the nation and its majesty, and is bound to maintain its interests and dignity. All sovereign states are therefore legally equal, whatever may be their form of government, their power or their weakness. These important principles of Public Law belong to the very institu- tion of separate civil societies, and are therefore of p secondary natural law. Another preliminary observation is here necessary. We have seen that God makes the society of mankind throughout the universe to subsist by three several kinds of ties, which distinguish it into three parts or three orders, according to so many different modes of the Divine conduct towards man. The first is that of Religion ; the second of common humanity ; and the third is formed in every state by the order which unites all the families composing it under one govern- ment. The first extends over the whole universe, if not in fact, at least in spirit ; for though the Catholic Religion is not known in all places, yet it is essential to the spirit of the Christian Church to embrace all nations. The second sort of ties made by the natural rules of humanity and equity, ought naturally to have its extent all over the world, and prevails everywhere in some degree ; but in many places it is violated in divers ways according to the force of interest or passion. These ties are the foundation of the law of nations : for this second order or part of society has for its subject the use of commerce, and the several communications and intercourse of nations with each other and the subjects of one state with those of another ; and divers matters, such as the use of the seas, regarding; the ' ' O O general interests and wants of mankind. The third tie, which is made Vattel, Droitdes Gens, Prelimiii. 18 j ibi, liv. 2, ch. 3. 3538. P L. 5, ff. De Just, et Jur. THE FORMS OF CIVIL GOVERNMENTS. 249 in every state by the union of the persons who compose it under the same government, is confined within each state. Thus there are as many ties of this sort as there are states, which are distinguished by different governments. The diversity of forms of government, of which we are going to treat, is a matter regarding only the third sort of ties, and the third order or part of human society which those ties constitute. Thus we see the place which political constitutions or forms of civil government hold in the scheme of universal human society. They are consequences of the division of mankind into states or nations, which we have shown to be an institution of Public Law arising from necessity -jus quod necessitas constituit. q They belong, moreover, to one part of municipal law, that is to say, public, as con- tradistinguished from private municipal law. For though the in- . fluence of political institutions shows itself in the private law of countries, especially the arbitrary part, or else the same causes which produce certain political institutions also engender private laws go- verned by the same spirit ; yet it is necessary to distinguish matters of laws having relation to the form of the government and the general order of the state, from the private law, both immutable and arbitrary. These reflections show the character of the organic laws forming the political constitution of states. They for the most part belong to the second class of arbitrary laws, that which regulates artificial arbitrary matters. For natural law does not determine the specific form of civil societies and civil crovernment. But though these matters have O D been invented by men, and it may seem that they ought to be regu- lated wholly by arbitrary laws, yet they have many immutable laws relating to them. The reason of this is to be found in the causes O which render civil government necessary, and in its uses. These are, to maintain the public order in the whole extent of the parts whereof it consists, to keep the subjects in peace, and to punish the attempts of those who disturb the peace and tranquillity of society ; to procure the administration of justice ; and to take care of all that is requisite for the common good of the state. And those rules which are neces- sary for the purposes of civil society are direct consequences of the two primary laws, and immutable, so that they cannot anywhere be violated without a disturbance of the order and uses of that society. Thus, as government is necessary for the public good, and established by God himself, it is consequently necessary that those who live under its jurisdiction be subject- and obedient to it/ And in every form of civil government this principle must be immutably observed. So the Ibi; Story, Com. on the Constit. of the United States, vol. 2, eh. 7, 529. TUB POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 305 having an influence over the people whom it represents, and suffi- ciently numerous to feel all the passions that actuate a multitude, yet not so numerous as to be unable to pursue its objects, and therefore exposed to the intrigues of the executive, the danger to be guarded against proceeds from the preponderating power of this department/ We have indeed seen, in examining the different parts of the sove- reign power, that the legislative branch is in its very nature peculiarly difficult to keep within any practical limits. In the United States of America, the legislative power is partly vested in the States, and partly in the Union. Yet Story makes the following valuable reflexions on the danger of its encroaching on the other parts of the government, or on the liberties of the people. 3 He remarks that, in point of theory, it is almost impracticable, if not impossible, that each of the three de- partments should possess equally, and in the same degree, the means of self-protection ; and that in point of fact, those means in the differ- ent departments are immeasurably disproportionate. " The judi- ciary," he continues, " is incomparably the weakest of either, and must for ever, in a considerable measure, be subject to the legislative power. 1 And the latter has, and must have, a controlling influence over the executive power, since it holds, at its own command, all the resources by which a chief magistrate could make himself formidable. It possesses the power over the purse of the nation and the property of the people. It can grant or withhold supplies; it can levy or withdraw taxes ; it can unnerve the power of the sword, by striking down the arm that wields it." " De Lolme has said, with great emphasis ' It is, without doubt, absolutely necessary for securing the constitution of a state, to restrain the executive power; but it is still more necessary to restrain the legis- lative. What the former can duly do by successive steps (I mean, subvert the laws), and through a longer or a shorter train of enter- prizes, the latter does in a moment. As its bare will can give being to the laws, so its bare will can also annihilate them; and if I may be permitted the expression, the legislative power can change the consti- tution, as God created the light. In order, therefore, to insure stability to the constitution of a state, it is indispensably necessary to restrain the legislative authority. But here we must observe a difference be- tween the legislative and executive powers. The latter may be con- fined, and even is more easily so, when undivided. The legislative, on the contrary, in order to its being restrained, should absolutely be r Federalist, ibi, p. 269. 8 Story, Comment, on the Constit. of the United States, vol. 2, 530, p. 14, &c. r See Federalist, num. 78. 306 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF divided.'" The truth is, that the legislative power is the great and overruling power in every free government. It has been remarked, with equal force and sagacity, that the legislative power is everywhere extending the sphere of its activity, and drawing all power into its im- petuous vortex. The founders of our republics, wise as they were, under the influence and the dread of the royal prerogative, which was pressing upon them, never for a moment seem to have turned their eyes from the immediate danger to liberty from that source, combined as it was with an hereditary authority, and an hereditary peerage to support it. They seem never to have recollected the danger from legis- lative usurpation, which, by ultimately assembling all power in the same hands, must lead to the same tyranny as is threatened by ex- ecutive usurpations. The representatives of the people will watch with jealousy every encroachment of the executive magistrate, for it trenches upon their own authority. But who shall watch the encroachment of these representatives themselves? Will they be as jealous of the exer- cise of power by themselves, as by others ? In a representative re- public, where the executive magistracy is carefully limited, both in the extent and duration of its power, and where the legislative power is exercised by an assembly, which is inspired by a supposed influence over the people, with an intrepid confidence in its own strength; which is sufficiently numerous to feel all the passions which actuate the mul- titude; yet not so numerous as to be incapable of pursuing the objects of its passions by means which reason prescribes; it is easy to see that the tendency to the usurpation of power is, if not constant, at least probable; and that it is against the enterprising ambition of this department, that the people may well indulge all their jealousy, and exhaust all their precautions. 1 There are many reasons which may be assigned for the engrossing influence of the legislative department. In the first place, its constitutional powers are more extensive, and less capable of being brought within precise limits, than those of either of the other departments. The bounds of the executive authority are easily marked out and defined. It reaches few objects, and those are known. It cannot transcend them without being brought in contact with the other departments. Laws may check and restrain, and bound its exercise. The same remarks apply with still greater force to the judiciary. The jurisdiction is, or may be, bounded to a few objects or persons; for, however general and unlimited, its operations are neces- sarily confined to the mere administration of private and public justice. It cannot punish without law. It cannot create controversies to act De Lolme, b. 2, ch. 3. * Federalist, num. 48, 49. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 307 upon. It can decide only upon rights and cases, as they are brought by others before it. It can do nothing for itself. y It must do every- thing for others. It must obey the laws, and if it corruptly administers them, it is subjected to the power of impeachment. On the other hand, the legislative power, except in the few cases of constitutional prohibition, is unlimited. It is for ever varying its means and its ends. It governs the institutions and laws and public policy of the country. It regulates all its vast interests. It disposes of all its property. Look but at the exercise of two or three branches of its ordinary powers. It levies all taxes ; it directs and appropriates all supplies ; it gives the rules for the descent, distribution, and devises of all property held by individuals. It controls the sources and the resources of wealth. It changes at its will the whole fabric of the laws. It moulds at its pleasure almost all the institutions which give strength and comfort and dignity to society. In the next place, it is the direct, visible representative of the will of the people in all the changes of times and circumstances. It has the pride as well as the power of numbers. 2 It is easily moved, and steadily moved by the strong impulses of popular feeling and popular odium. It obeys, without reluctance, the wishes and the will of the majority for the time being. The path to public favour lies open by such obedience ; and it finds not only support, but impunity, in whatever measures the majority advises, even though they transcend the constitutional limits. It has no motive, therefore, to be jealous, or scrupulous in its own use of power ; and it finds its ambition stimulated, and its arm strengthened, by the countenance and the courage of numbers. These views are not alone those of men who O look with apprehension upon the fate of republics, but they are also freely admitted by some of the strongest advocates for popular rights, and the permanency of republican institutions. 8 Our domestic history furnishes abundant examples to verify these suggestions. 1 " If, then, the legislative power possesses a decided preponderance of influence over either or both of the others, and if, in its own separate structure, it furnishes no effectual security for the others, or for its own abstinence from usurpations, it will not be sufficient to rely upon a mere constitu- tional division of the powers to insure our liberties. What remedy, * And see the Federalist, num. 78. 1 " Numerous assemblies," says Mr. Turgot, " are swayed in their debates by the smallest motives." See Mr. Jefferson's very striking remarks in his notes on Virginia, pp. 195 197, 248. In December 1776, and again June 1781, the legislature of Virginia, under a great pressure, were near passing an act appointing a dictator. B. 1, p. 207. b Federalist, num. 48, 49. c See Jefferson's Notes on Virginia, p. 195 197. x2 308 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OP then, can be proposed adequate for the exigency ? It has been sug- gested that an appeal to the people, at stated times, might redress any inconveniences of this sort. But if these be frequent, it will have a tendency to lessen that respect for, and confidence in, the stability of our constitutions, which is so essential to their salutary influence. If it be true that all governments rest on opinion, it is no less true that the strength of opinion in each individual, and its practical influence on his conduct, depend much upon the number which he supposes to have entertained the same opinion. 6 There is, too, no small danger in disturbing the public tranquillity by a frequent recurrence to questions respecting the fundamental principles of government. 6 Whoever has been present in any assembly, convened for such a purpose, must have perceived the great diversities of opinion upon the most vital questions ; and the extreme difficulty in bringing a majority to concur in the long- sighted wisdom of the soundest provisions. Temporary feelings and excitements, popular prejudices, an ardent love of theory, an enthusi- astic temperament, inexperience, and ignorance, as well as preconceived opinions, operate wonderfully to blind the judgment and seduce the understanding. It will probably be found, in the history of most con- ventions of this sort, that the best and soundest parts of the constitu- tion those which give it permanent value, as well as safe and steady operation are precisely those which have enjoyed the least of the public favour at the moment, or were least estimated by the framers. A lucky hit or a strong figure has not unfrequently overturned the best reasoned plan. Thus Dr. Franklin's remark, that a legislature with two branches was a wagon, drawn by a horse before, and a horse behind, in opposite directions, is understood to have been decisive in inducing Pennsylvania, in her original constitution, to invest all the legislative power in a single body/ In her present constitution that error has been fortunately corrected. It is not believed that the clause in the constitution of Vermont, providing for a septennial council of censors to inquire into the infractions of her constitution during the last septenary, and to recommend suitable measures to the legislature, and to call, if they see fit, a convention to amend the constitution, has been of any practical advantage in that state, in securing it against legislative or other usurpations, beyond the security possessed by other states having no such provision. 8 On the other hand, if an appeal to d Federalist, num. 48. e Ibi, num. 48, 50. f Adams, American Constitution, 105, 106. * The history of the former constitution of Pennsylvania, and the report of its council of censors, shows the little value of provisions of this sort in a strong light. Federalist, num. 48, 50. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 309 the people, or a convention, is to be called only at great distances of time, it will afford no redress for the most pressing mischiefs. And if the measures, which are supposed to be infractions of the constitution, enjoy popular favour, or combine extensive private interests, or have taken root in the habit of the government, it is obvious that the chances of any effectual redress will be essentially diminished. 11 But a more conclusive objection is, that the decisions upon all such appeals would not answer the purpose of maintaining or restoring the consti- tutional equilibrium of the government. The remarks of the Federalist on this subject are so striking that they scarcely admit of abridgement without impairing their force : ' We have seen that the tendency of republican governments is to aggrandizement of the legislature at the expense of the other departments. The appeals to the people, there- fore, would usually be made by the executive and judiciary depart- ments. But, whether made by one or the other, would each side enjoy equal advantages on the trial ? Let us view their different situations. The members of the executive and judiciary departments are few in number, and can be personally known to a small part only of the people. The latter, by the mode of their appointment, as well as by the nature and permanency of it, are too far removed from the people to share much in their professions. The former are generally objects of jealousy; and their administration is always liable to be discoloured and rendered unpopular. The members of the legislative department, on the other hand, are numerous. Tfeey are distributed and dwell among the people at large. Their connexions of blood, of friendship, and of acquaintance, embrace a great proportion of the most influential part of the society. The nature of their public trust implies a personal weight with the people, and that they are more immediately the con- fidential guardians of their rights and liberties. With these advantages it can hardly be supposed that the adverse party would have an equal chance of a favourable issue. But the legislative party would not only be able to plead their case most successfully with the people; they would probably be constituted themselves the judges. The same influence which had gained them an election into the legislature would gain them a seat in the convention. If this should not be the case O with all, it would probably be the case with many, and pretty certainly with those leading characters on whom everything depends in such bodies. The conventions, in short, would be composed chiefly of men who had been, or who actually were, or who expected to be, members of the department, whose conduct was arraigned. They would conse- quently be parties to the very question to be decided by them.' " h Federalist, num. 50. 1 Federalist, num. 49. The truth of this reasoning, as well as the utter inefficiency 310 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF If, then, occasional or periodical appeals to the people would not afford a sufficient protection against encroachments of the legislature on the other departments of the government, it is manifest that resort must be had to such a construction of the government as shall, by mutual checks of one department upon another, preserve their consti- tutional power and functions in relation to each other. And we must further observe, that the appeals to the people in convention, men- tioned by the Federalist and Story, though practicable in a republic, would be dangerous, and perhaps fatal, in a constitutional monarchy. It is evident, in the first place, that the very doctrine of the separa- tion of departments requires that each department should have a will of its own. And therefore, they should be so constituted that the members of each should have as little agency as possible in the appointment of the others. But it might be inexpedient to insist rigorously on this last rule with regard to the judicial department, because there the primary consideration ought to be to select that mode of choice which best secures the requisite qualifications in the persons to be appointed ; and the permanent tenure by which the offices are held in that department must soon destroy the sense of dependence on the authority conferring them. k It is equally evident that the members of each department should be as little dependent as possible on those of the others for the emoluments of office. Were the executive magistrate, or the judges, not independent of the legis- lature in this particular, their*independence in every other would be merely nominal. 1 But the great security for the constitutional division of the depart- ments consists in giving to those who administer each department the necessary constitutional means and personal motives to resist encroach- ments of the others. Thus, ambition would be made to counteract ambition ; the desire of power to check power ; and the pressure of interest to balance an opposing interest. The policy of supplying by opposite and rival interests the defect of better motives in men, might be traced through the whole system of human affairs, private as well as public. We see it especially in all the subordinate distributions of power, where the constant aim is to divide and arrange the several officers in such a manner as that each may be a check on the other." 1 of any such periodical conventions, is abundantly established by the history of Penn- sylvania under her former constitution. Federalist, num. 50. See 2 Pitkin's Hist. pp. 305, 306. k Federalist, num. 51, p. 280. Ibi. Ibi, p. 281. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 311 "There seems," says Story, "no adequate method of producing this result, but by a partial participation of each in the power of the other; and by introducing into every operation of the government, in all its branches, a system of checks and balances, on which the safety of free institutions has ever been found essentially to depend. Thus, for instance, a guard against rashness and violence in legislation has often been formed by distributing the power among different branches, each having a negative check upon the other. A guard against the inroads of the legislative power upon the executive has been, in like manner, applied, by giving the latter a qualified negative upon the former; and a guard against executive influence and patronage, or unlawful exer- cise of authority, by requiring the concurrence of a select council, or a branch of the legislature, in appointments to office, and in the dis- charge of other high functions, as well as by placing the command of the revenue in other hands." n "The usual guard applied for the security of the judicial depart- ment has been in the tenure of office of the judges, who are to hold office during good behaviour. But this is obviously an inadequate provision, while the legislature is entrusted with a complete power over the salaries of the judges, and over the jurisdiction of the courts, so that they can alter or diminish them at pleasure. Indeed, the judiciary is naturally, and almost necessarily, as has been already said, the weakest department. It would seem, therefore, that some additional guards would, under such circumstances, be necessary to protect this department from the absolute dominion of the others. Yet rarely have any such guards been applied, and every attempt to introduce them has been resisted with a pertinacity which demonstrates how slow popular leaders are to introduce checks upon their own power, and how slow the people are to believe that the judiciary is the real bulwark of their liberties. In some of the states the judicial department is partially combined with some branches of the executive and legislative departments; and it is believed, that in those cases, it has been found no unimportant auxiliary in preserving a wholesome vigour in the laws, as well as a wholesome administration of public justice." p The danger of this combination of the judicial with some branches of the executive and legislative departments is, that it has a tendency to bring the judges within the sphere of political and party influences; but we must admit the force of the observations of Story on the insuf- n Story, Comment, vol. 2, ch. 7, 540. Montesq. Esprit des Loix, liv. 11, ch. 6 ; Federalist, num. 78, pp. 419, 420; num. 79. P Story, ibi, 541. 312 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF ficiency of the protection which mere permanency of office gives to the judicial department. Having seen the opinions of Madison and Story on the way of keeping the three departments of government in their due places, it will be interesting to turn to the doctrine of Blackstone on the same subject, thus juxtaposing the words of the great republican jurists to those of our own most eminent constitutional writer. After laying it down that the king's majesty and the three estates of the kingdom, the lords spiritual, the lords temporal, and the commons, are the con- stituent parts of the parliament, and that the crown and these three estates together form the great corporation or body politic of the king- dom, 11 (of which the king is said to be caput, principium et finis, be- cause, unless he meets them, either in person or by representation, on their coming together, there can be no beginning of a parlia- ment/ and he alone has the power of dissolving them,) Blackstone continues thus : " It is highly necessary for preserving the balance of the constitution, that the executive power should be a branch, though not the whole, of the legislative. The total union of them, we have seen, would be productive of tyranny; the total disjunction of them, for the present, would in the end produce the same effects, by causing that union against which it seems to provide. The legislature would soon become tyrannical, by making continual encroachments, and gradually assuming to itself the rights of the executive power. Thus the long parliament of Charles the First, while it acted in a constitu- tional manner with the royal concurrence, redressed many heavy grievances, and established many salutary laws : but when the two houses assumed the power of legislation, in exclusion of the royal authority, they soon after assumed likewise the reins of administration, and, in consequence of these united powers, overturned both Church and State, and established a worse oppression than any they pretended to remedy. To hinder, therefore, any such encroachments, the king is himself a part of the parliament ; and this is the reason of his being so. Very properly, therefore, the share of legislation which the constitution has placed in the crown, consists in the power of rejecting rather than resolving, this being sufficient to answer the end proposed. For we may apply to the royal negative in this instance, what Cicero observes of the negative of the Roman tribunes, that the crown has not any power of doing wrong, but merely of preventing wrong from being done. 8 The crown cannot begin of itself any alterations in the present i 4 Inst. 2 ; stat. Eliz. c. 3 ; Hale, Of Parl. 1. T 4 Inst. 6. Sulla tribunis plebis sua lege injurite Jaciendte potestatem ademlt, auxilii forendi reliqtiit. De Leg. 3, 9. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 313 established law, but it may approve or disapprove of the alterations suggested and consented to by the two houses. The legislative, therefore, cannot abridge the executive power of any rights which it now has by law, without its own consent, since the law must perpe- tually stand as it now does, unless all the powers will agree to alter it. And herein, indeed, consists the true excellence of the English govern- ment, that all the parts of it form a mutual check upon each other. In the legislature the people are a check upon the nobility, and the nobility a check upon the people, by the mutual privilege of rejecting what the other has resolved ; while the king is a check upon both, which preserves the executive power from encroachments. And this very executive power is again checked and kept within due bounds by the two houses, through the privilege they have of inquiring into, impeaching, and punishing the conduct, not indeed of the king/ which would destroy his constitutional independence, but, which is more beneficial to the public, of his evil and pernicious counsellors. Thus, every branch of our civil polity supports and is supported, regulates and is regulated, by the rest ; for the two houses, naturally drawing in two directions of opposite interest, and the prerogative in another still different from them both, they mutually keep each other from exceed- ing their proper limits ; while the whole is prevented from separation, and artificially connected together, by the mixed nature of the crown, which is a part of the legislative, and the sole executive magistrate. Like three distinct powers in mechanics, they jointly impel the machine of government in a direction different from what either, O ' acting by itself, would have done ; but, at the same time, in a direc- tion partaking of each, and formed out of all; a direction which con- stitutes the true line of the liberty and happiness of the community." 11 In this masterly sketch we see that the English constitution pre- sents not only the mutual checks of departments on each other, but also that balance which arises from the combination of monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, in one government. No law can be made without the concurrence of those three powers. And on the other hand, the commons have the chief control of the public revenue and supplies, while the crown, the supreme executive magistrate, is also the fountain of justice, the source of all judicial power in the state ; and that branch of the legislature which constitutes the aristo- cratic part of this mixed government, is also the court for the trial of impeachments, and the supreme court of appeal. But the house of commons, though it is the grand inquest of the nation, is so far excluded from the exercise of judicial power in the ordinary adminis- 1 Stat. 12 Car. II. c. 30. " 1 Blackst. Com. ch. 2, pp. 154, 155. 314 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF tration of justice, that that assembly have never claimed, much less exercised, the right of administering an oath to witnesses, not even in cases of privilege, or of controverted elections, where their right of judicature was acknowledged, and on questions upon which they were admitted to be the sole court competent to determine." And this power of administering an oath is exercised in election proceed- ings only by virtue of a particular act of parliament, for the trial of controverted elections, under which the House of Commons act as a court administering the statute law. y Thus the commons, the most powerful branch of the legislature, are restrained from the exercise of the judicial power, except where it is necessary for their own indepen- dence; while the constitution entrusts the judicial department to the crown and the lords. But though the crown is the fountain of justice, the royal prerogative cannot, except by authority of parliament, erect or empower any court to proceed otherwise than according to the forms and principles of the common law. z And the sovereign cannot administer justice, except by the mouth of the judges, or by the advice of one of the constitutional councils of the crown. a Having now shown the general principles of that adjustment and combination by which the due separation and balance of the three powers or departments of government are preserved, we must proceed to the further consideration of the same subject, with more immediate reference to each of those departments. And we will commence with the legislative, as the most important of the three. Madison observes that the remedy for the preponderance of the legislative authority in republics is to divide the legislature into diffe- rent branches, and to render them, by different modes of election, and different principles of action, as little connected with each other as the nature of their common functions, and their common dependence on society, will admit. b And De Lolme has truly said, that the executive power may be confined, and even is, more easily so, when undivided, but the legislative, on the contrary, in order to its being restrained, should absolutely be divided. The reason of this diversity may be that the executive power can .be restrained by laws, but the checks x Hatsell, Preced. vol. 2, p. 158. y May, Priv. of Parl. pp. 345, 363. z See my Comment, on the Constit. Law of England, p. 170172; Hob. 63; 12 Co. Rep. 114; 1 Woodes. 188190; stat. 53 Geo. III. c. 24 ; Com. Dig. tit. Prerogative, D. 28 ; tit. Chancery, A. 3. a Com. Dig. tit. Courts, A ; Fortesc. De Landibus, by Amos, ch. 8, n. B. b Federalist, num. 51, p. 281, c De Lolme, b. 2, ch. 3. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 315 and restraints on the legislative must come chiefly from itself and its own construction, because it can make and repeal laws. So we have seen that in the English constitution the executive magistrate is pro- tected from encroachments of the legislature by being made an essen- tial part of parliament. And in that assembly monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, mutually check each other, though, it must be ad- mitted, with very unequal power. In the constitution of the United States all legislative powers thereby granted are vested in the Congress, which consists of a senate and house of representatives. 11 The president, therefore, is not part of the legislature, though he has a qualified negative upon its acts. But the principle .of this provision is the same as that which, in our own country, makes the crown one of the three estates constituting the parliament. And it seems better calculated to be useful and practi- cally effectual in a republic than an absolute veto would be. " An absolute negative on the legislature appears," says Madison, " at first view, to be the natural defence with which the executive magistrate should be armed. But perhaps it would be neither altogether safe, nor alone sufficient. On ordinary occasions it might not be exercised with the requisite firmness, and on extraordinary occasions it might be perfidiously abused." e Therefore the constitution provides that if the president disapproves of a bill that has passed the Congress, he may return it, with his objections, to the house in which it originated, and that house enters the objections at large on their Journals, and proceeds to reconsider the bill. If, after such re-consideration, two- thirds of the house should agree to pass the bill, it is sent, together with the objections, to the other house, by which it is likewise recon- sidered, and, if approved by two-thirds of that house, it becomes law. But in all such cases the votes of both houses are determined by yeas and nays, and the names of the persons voting for and against the bill are entered on the Journals/ Kent observes that this qua- lified negative answers all the salutary purposes of an absolute one, and it is not to be presumed that two-thirds of both houses of Con- gress, on reconsideration, with the reasoning of the president in oppo- sition to the bill spread at large upon their Journals, will ever concur in any unconstitutional measure. " In the English constitution," he continues, "the king has an absolute negative; but it has not been necessary to exercise it since the reign of William III. The influence of the crown has been exerted in a more gentle manner, to destroy any obnoxious measure in its progress through the two houses of a Constitution of the United States, art. 1, sect. 1. e Federalist, num. 51, p. 282. f Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 11, p. 239. 316 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF Parliament." g Story, however, conjectures that the fact that this negative of the crown has not been exercised since 1692 may be attri- buted either to the reason given by Kent, or to the danger of exer- cising it, except in the most pressing emergencies ; and he even suggests the question whether a qualified negative may not hereafter, in England, become a more efficient protection to the crown, than an absolute negative, which makes no appeal to the other legislative bodies, and consequently compels the crown to bear the exclusive odium of a rejection. 11 The operation of parliamentary government, by means of respon- sible ministers, has also mainly contributed to render the exercise of this power unnecessary, except in some rare emergency. . And the House of Lords will generally support the prerogative of the crown, by rejecting a measure repugnant to the sovereign : and a knowledge of this may enable the minister to defeat it in the House of Commons, a result which the constitutional influence of the crown and the House of Lords in the lower house may assist in producing, so as to avoid a collision between the branches of the legislature. 1 In the United States, the legislature is, as we have seen, divided into two assemblies, the Senate and the House of Representatives, and in our own country it is divided into three branches, the crown and two separate assemblies. We have now to consider the reasons of Public Law, on which the institution of double legislative assem- blies is grounded. This subject is exhausted by the American consti- tutional writers, the Federalist, Kent, Adams and Story, and they are unanimously in favour of two houses or chambers. " One great object," says Chancellor Kent, " of the separation of the legislature into two houses, acting separately, and with co-ordinate powers, is to destroy the evil effects of sudden and strong excitement, and of precipitate measures, springing from passion, caprice, prejudice, personal influence and party intrigue, which have been found by sad experience to exercise a potent and dangerous sway in single assem- blies. A hasty decision is not so likely to arrive to the solemnities of a law, when it is to be arrested in its course, and made to undergo the deliberation and probably the jealous and critical revision of another and a rival body of men, sitting in a different place, and under better advantages to avoid the prepossessions and correct the errors of the other branch. The legislatures of the Pennsylvania and Georgia con- sisted originally of a single house. The instability and passion which marked their proceedings were very visible at the time, and the subject *Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 11, pp. 140, 141. h Story, Comment, vol. 2, ch. 13, 879; Federalist, num. 51, 73. 1 See my Comment, on the Constit. Law of England, p. 165. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 317 of much public animadversion; and in the subsequent reform of their constitutions, the people were so sensible of this defect, and of the inconvenience they had suffered from it, that in both states a senate was introduced. No portion of the political history of mankind is more full of instructive lessons on this subject, or contains more striking proof of faction, instability, and misery of states, under the dominion of a single unchecked assembly, than that of the Italian republics of the middle ages ; and which arose in great numbers, and with dazzling but transient splendour, in the interval between the fall of the western and the eastern empire of the Romans. They were all alike ill constituted, with a single unbalanced assembly. They were alike miserable, and all ended in similar disgrace." k About the commencement of the French revolution, many specula- tive writers were struck with the simplicity of a legislature with a single assembly, and concluded that more than one house was useless and expensive. Milton, Turgot, Franklin and Mackintosh, are but few of those who have professedly entertained and discussed the ques- tion. 1 The elder President Adams, in his great work entitled " A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States," vindicates the necessity of the division of the legislature into two assemblies. And Mr. Hamilton argues in the Federalist, that the organization of Congress under the confederation which vested the whole legislative power of the Union in a single assembly, was im- proper for the exercise of those powers which were to be necessarily deposited in the Union by the constitution. " A single assembly," he says, " may be a proper receptacle of those slender, or rather fettered, authorities which have been heretofore delegated to the federal head ; but it would be inconsistent with all the principles of good govern- ment to entrust it with those additional powers, which the more moderate and rational adversaries of the proposed constitution admit ought to reside in the United States."" 1 The doctrine of a single house of legislature was adopted in the French constitution of 1791. The very nature of things, said the politicians of the national assembly, was adverse to every division of the legislative body; and as the nation which was represented was one, so the representative body ought to be one also. The will of the nation was indivisible, and so ought to be the voice that pronounced it. If there were two chambers, with a veto upon the acts of each other, in some cases they would be reduced to perfect inaction. By k Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 11, pp. 121, 122; and see pp. 226, 227; Adams, Defence of the American Constit. vol. 3, p. 502. 1 Story, Comment, vol. 2, ch. 8, 548. m Federalist, num. 22, p. 19. 318 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF this reasoning, the national assembly was induced to reject the pro- posal of constituting an upper house. A single assembly was likewise established in the plan of government published by the French Con- vention in 1793. And Kent observes, that the instability and violent measures of that Convention tended to display the miseries of a single single unchecked legislative assembly. He gives his opinion that, if the proposition of Lally Tolendal, to constitute a senate or upper house, composed of members chosen for life, had prevailed, the consti- tution would have had much more stability, and would probably have been much better able to preserve the nation in order and tranquillity ; and, he adds, that their own sufferings taught the French people to listen to wisdom and experience. No people, said Boissy D'Anglas, in 1795, can testify to the world, with more truth and sincerity than the French can do, the dangers inherent in a single legislative assem- bly, and the point to which factions may mislead an assembly, with- out reins or counterpoise. We accordingly find that, in the constitution of 1795, there was a division of the legislature, and a council of ancients was introduced to give stability and moderation to the govern- ment. 11 Chancellor Kent concludes by saying, that this idea was never afterwards abandoned. And yet, as if to show that nations profit little by experience, the same crude and shallow arguments, used in the national assembly in 1791, were repeated in 1848; and the French republic was constituted with a single legislative assembly. The absurdity and disgrace of that body, and the utter failure of the re- public, add confirmation to the opinion of Kent, President Adams and Story. We must now proceed to another mode of moderating the power of legislative assemblies. We have seen that the branches of the legis- lature should be rendered by different modes of election or appoint- ment, and different principles of action, sufficiently unconnected with and independent of each other to act as a mutual check. Thus in our own country we have a hereditary prince and Upper House, and an elected House of Commons. So, in the United States, the House of Representatives is chosen biennially by the people, and the senate is elected by the legislatures of the different States, and one-third of the senators are elected in every second year.? The principles of a republic require that both branches of the legislature should be elected directly or indirectly by the people ; and the tenure of a seat in the legislature for life seems inconsistent with a democracy. But even in a mixed monarchy it is necessary that the members of one at least of n Kent, Comment, vol. 2, lect. 1 1, pp. 222, 223. Federalist, num. 51, p. 281. P Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 11, p. 224228. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 319 the legislative assemblies should not hold their seats permanently for life, but be subject to re-election, and so brought under the control of the public judgment of the nation.* 1 On this point Chancellor Kent gives us the following sound doctrines of Public Law : " The term for which a representative is to serve ought not to be so short as to prevent him from obtaining a comprehensive acquaintance with the business to which he is deputed ; nor so long as to make him forget the transitory nature of his seat, and his state of dependence on the approbation of his constituents. It ought also to be considered as a fact deeply interesting to the character and utility of representative republics, that very frequent elections have a tendency to render the office less important than it ought to be deemed, and the people inat- tentive in the exercise of their right, or else to nourish restlessness, instability and factions; whilst, on the other hand, long intervals between the elections are apt to make them produce too much excite- ment, and consequently to render the periods of their return a time of too much competition and conflict for the public tranquillity." 1 " The prerogative of the crown in mixed monarchies, to dissolve the legis- lative body at any time, and send the representatives of the people to their constituents, is necessary to protect the royal authority from the power of parliamentary parties and factions, and give it a due influence in the legislature. And the fact that every representative must at certain periods either surrender his trust altogether, or give an account of his public conduct in parliament and solicit re-election, is an essen- tial restraint upon those who would otherwise pursue their own private views and interest at the expense of the liberty and welfare of the people, and exercise their power in an arbitrary manner. It is impos- sible to lay down any universal rule determining how frequent elections should be. This in every country is matter of arbitrary law depending on a great variety of circumstances. 8 We have, therefore, given only the general principles by which this important matter of constitutional law is governed. We will now proceed from the legislative to the executive depart- ment. The essential character of this department is unity ; for, as Chancellor Kent says, " the characteristic qualities required in the executive department are promptitude, decision and force ; and these qualities are most likely to exist when the executive authority is limited to a single person, moving by the unity of a single will." ' This principle is carried into effect where, in a republic, the executive i Blackst. Com. vol. 1, pp. 188, 189; Montesq. Esprit des Loix, liv. 11, ch. 6. r Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 11, p. 229; Story, Comment, vol. 2, $ 586, 587. 1 See Story, ibi, 589. And see Hallam, Constit. Hist. vol. 4, pp. 52, 53. ' Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 13, pp. 271, 272. And see the Federalist, num. 70. 320 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF department is entrusted to a single responsible magistrate not subject to the control of councillors." Under a mixed monarchy, where the king acts by the adviee of responsible ministers, it is maintained on a somewhat qualified form by the unity of the regal office." In both cases the executive department cannot be divided into branches with- out injuring its useful efficiency. Its powers and functions should be united and defined by laws, the interpretation of which is committed to the judicial department. But those laws should not deprive the executive of that extent of discretionary power which the public service may require. Thus the prerogative of the crown is defined by Lord Mansfield to be " a discretionary power lodged in the crown for the common benefit of the kingdom and the king's subjects;" and Locke and Blackstone hold that it consists in the discretionary power of acting for the public good, where positive laws are silent. y But this discretionary power of the executive department is subject to an indirect restraint wherever it cannot be effectually exerted without pecuniary supplies, which can neither be raised nor applied, except by the authority of the legislature. 2 If this were not so, the executive would be enabled to encroach on the legislative branch of government. On the other hand, the executive department could not preserve its due independence and energy if a permanent provision were not made for its support and sustenance. Blackstone, after some reflections on the diminution of the royal power and the impoverishment of the crown, stripped of the greater part of its hereditary revenues, suggests that it may be thought that the executive magistrate has neither inde- pendence nor power enough left to form a check on the lords and commons. But he considers that the permanent endowment called the Civil List, which is settled on every king by the first parliament after his accession, restores to him that constitutional independence which on his ascending the throne must be owned to be wanting.* C* O The same principle is followed in the United States of America, where a provision in the constitution declares that the president shall at stated times receive for his services a compensation, which shall neither be increased nor diminished during the period for which he shall have been elected ; and he shall not receive within that time any other emolument from the United States, or any of them. b u Federalist, ibi, p. 379. * Blackst. Com. vol. 1, ch. 7, pp. 249, 250. y See my Comment, on the Constit. Law of England, p. 493; Locke on Gov. vol. 2, 166 ; Blackst. Com. vol. 1, ch. 7, p. 252. z De Lolme, b. 1, ch. 6. " Blackst. Com. vol. 1, ch. 8, pp. 334, 335. b Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 13, pp. 280, 281. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 321 In a republic the chief executive magistrate may also be restrained from encroaching on the other departments, by the limited duration of his office, and by responsibility. Thus the President of the United States holds office for four years. He is re-eligible for successive terms, but in practice no president has ever consented to be a candi- date for a third election. And as in a republic every magistrate ought to be personally responsible for his behaviour in office/ 1 the president is directly amenable by law for maladministration. 6 And this responsibility would perhaps suffice to prevent his disturbing the balance of power by enterprizes or encroachments on the other departments of government. In a monarchy, however, this responsibility of the chief magistrate cannot be admitted without subverting the fundamental principle of mixed monarchical government, which, as we have seen, makes the Prince a part of the supreme power, and consequently amenable to no human jurisdiction/ Therefore it is wise, under that form of govern- ment, to annex to the king a constitutional council responsible to the nation for the advice that they give. Without this, there would be no responsibility in the executive department an idea inadmissible in a free government. But even there the king is not bound by the advice of his ministers, though they are answerable for such advice. 5 He is the master of his own conduct in office, and may change his advisers whenever he thinks fit : though, on the other hand, as the ministers of the crown are obliged to give an account in parliament of the measures of the government, they cannot remain in office unless they have the confidence of that assembly. If a ministry retain office after they have ceased to be supported by a majority of the House of Commons (which, as representing the body of the nation, and having the chief control over the public resources, must naturally possess the greatest power over the state administration), some vote will follow, either directly or impliedly, censuring them, and perhaps an address to the crown praying their removal ; and the next step will be a refusal of the supplies. The defeated ministers may however advise the crown to dissolve parliament, and thereby appeal to the country ; but the decision on that appeal should be final. Thus, both in a republic and in a mixed monarchy, though the executive and the legislative departments are divided from each other, the legislative assembly or assemblies may exercise a control over even c Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 13, p. 280. d Federalist, num. 70, p. 384. e Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 13, pp. 288, 289. f Blackst. Com. vol. 1, ch. 7, pp. 244, 245. * Federalist, ubi sup. p. 384. 322 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF that part of the executive administration which is discretionary and not defined by law, without depriving that department of its constitu- tional freedom of action. And so the legislative and executive branches of the sovereign power are prevented from clashing, by a mutual control which keeps each in its proper place, and maintains a unity in their action. And here the reader must be reminded, that though this country cannot be taxed except by authority of parliament, which also appro- priates the supplies to each service, the management and application of the public revenue is entrusted to the crown. And indeed the House of Commons will receive no petition for any sum of money relating to the public service but what is recommended by the crown. h This is necessary to prevent the Houses of Parliament from drawing to themselves what essentially belongs to the executive branch of the sovereign power, and thus destroying the distribution of powers which constitutes the balance of the constitution. We have now to examine how the judicial department is subjected to wholesome restraint, and protected against the encroachments of the other two. We have already seen that this is the weakest of the three departments ; yet its due administration is necessary for the maintenance of the laws upon which the whole system of the state and of civil society depend. And so it has been declared by high autho- rity, that without justice there can be no commonwealth, and that justice is the end of government. 1 This doctrine, indeed, is matter of immutable law, a direct consequence of the two fundamental laws on which human society is constructed, though it must be confessed that in all countries there are many things in the municipal laws very different from the spirit of those two Divine laws. In monarchical governments the independence of the judicial office is essential to guard the rights of the subject from arbitrary or undue exercise of the power of the crown : but in republics it is equally salutary to protect the constitution and laws from the encroachments and the tyranny of faction, 1 and from arbitrary acts of the executive. It is necessary (as we have already observed) for that independence, that the tenure of judicial office should be permanent and its emolu- ments secure. The judges should, therefore, hold office for life, subject to removal only in case of misconduct; and their salaries h Hatsell, Preced. vol. 3, p. 194196 ; May, Law of Parl. p. 335. See the sub- ject of Supply further explained in my Comment, on the Constit. Law of England, pp. 204, 205. ' Div. August. De Civ. Dei, lib. 19, cap. 21 ; Federalist, num. 51, p. 283. k Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 14, pp. 293, 294. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 323 should depend upon no annual vote, but be settled and secured by a permanent law. 1 The power to remove a judge from office should be placed in hands worthy of so great a trust. Thus in our own country the concurrence of the crown and both Houses of Parliament is required for this purpose : and by the constitution of the United States the judges can only be removed by impeachment of the House of Repre- sentatives and judgment of the senate." 1 The mode of appointing the judges is very important with reference to the independence of the judicial department and its due weight in the constitution. Kent shows, that even in a democracy, the judges ought not to be elected by the people. The fittest men, he observes, would probably have too much reservedness of manners and severity of morals to secure an election resting on universal suffrage. Nor can the mode of appointment by a large deliberative assembly be entitled to unqualified approbation. There are, he adds, too many occasions and too much temptation for intrigue, party prejudice, and local in- terests, to permit such a body of men to act, in respect of such appoint- ments, with sufficiently single and steady regard to the general welfare." And a judge so appointed would constantly be suspected of remembering in the discharge of his duties the votes given for or against him, and the influences used at his election. The constitution of the United States has wisely entrusted the appointment of the judges to the president, with the advice and consent of the senate. That connexion with the executive and the most dignified branch of the legislature secures to the judicial department the support of those great powers of the state ; augmenting, at the same time, its weight with the nation by the high guarantees which this mode of appoint- ment affords. The British constitution also connects the legislative and executive with the judicial department. For the crown is both a branch of the legislature, and the fountain of justice, which is administered in the Queen's name by her judges. In this distinct and separate existence of the judicial power in a peculiar body of men, appointed indeed, but not removable at pleasure by the crown, consists one main preserva- tive of public liberty, which cannot subsist long in any state, unless the administration of common justice be in some degree separated both from the legislative and also from the executive power.? Thus, 1 Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 14, pp. 291, 292, 294; Story, Com. vol. 2, ch. 7, 541 ; Blackst. Com. vol. 1, ch. 7, pp. 267, 268; Federalist, num. 78, pp. 419, 420. m Blackst. Com. ubi sup. ; Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 14, p. 295. n Kent, ubi sup. p. 291. Ibi. P Blackst. Com. vol. 1, ch. 7, p. 269. Y2 324 DISTRIBUTION AND BALANCE OF while the judges are independent of the crown, the judicial office emanates from the regal dignity, and is supported by the influence and majesty of the sovereign. To this influence we must add that of the House of Lords, which is not only the highest legislative assembly, but the supreme court of appeal, and therefore part of the judicial branch of government. And in the performance of their judicial duties the lords are frequently assisted by the judges of the superior courts of law, some of whom are moreover from time to time raised to the peerage ; and the Lord Chancellor, the highest judicial magistrate of the kingdom, is ex qfficio the speaker of that assembly, both in its legislative and its judicial functions. All these things tend to secure the dignity and independence of the judicial department of the state. We must now briefly consider the most important restraint on the judicial power, namely, its division between judges and juries. Trial by jury has exercised a valuable influence on jurisprudence by bringing the doctrine of juridical proofs to its true and natural principles, as contradistinguished from the artificial theory of evidence : but it may be doubted whether this institution affords the best method of deter- mining disputed questions of fact. We are, however, to view it here only as a means of maintaining the balance of power in a constitutional state by restraining the judicial department, and so securing the liberties of the people. Under this aspect its chief value is in criminal cases, though matters involving the most important rights of the citizens may be decided in civil actions. And it is necessary to observe, that a very large proportion of the civil administration of justice in this country, and part even of the administration of the criminal law, is carried on without the intervention of juries. If the judicial power were entrusted exclusively either to the per- manent judges or to the people, there would be danger of giving too much power in the former instance to the executive, towards which those magistrates are likely to lean, and in the latter, to the democracy, whose decisions would be capricious and unsafe. And it has been remarked, that the existence in any community of a standing body of functionaries, invested with the sole power of deciding upon accusa- tions involving the liberty and life of their fellow citizens, must en- danger liberty." 1 And the same principle applies in a modified sense to civil cases. Therefore, the judicial power is divided between the judges and the people : and juries have been called the commons of the judicial order. In a country where a strong aristocratic element forms part of the constitution, this division is also useful as a protec- tion to the people against the power and influence of the aristocracy, * Montesq. Esprit des Loix, liv. 11, ch. 6. THE POWERS OF GOVERNMENT, ETC. 325 with whom the judges may naturally have some community of feelings and interests. Trial by jury, therefore, preserves in the hands of the people that share which they ought to have in the administration of public justice, and prevents the encroachments of the more powerful and wealthy citizens. And thus a distribution of the judicial power obviates the danger of a union between the judicial department and the executive, or with the nobles and the executive, which would destroy the balance of a mixed constitution. CHAPTER XXVII. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. Provinces Colonies and Colonial Policy States united by having one King in com- mon States joined by Confederation Mode of deciding Questions among Con- federates Dissolution of Confederations Mixed Federal States exemplified by the Constitution of the United States of America. ONE important class of mixed governments remains to be considered. The term mixed is here applied to states of this sort in a sense some- what different from that in which we have hitherto used it. And the more correct denomination is that of compound or irregular states. I refer to federal governments or constitutions. The plan of human society given by Domat, founded on the two great primary laws, and constructed by means of the various ties which unite men together, shows the first principle on which polities of this kind are created. We have seen that, according to Domat, God makes the society of mankind to subsist by three several kinds of ties, which distinguish it into three parts or orders, according to so many manners of His conduct towards mankind. The first of these ties, and the second, that is to say Religion, and common humanity or human nature, are universal ; and the third, which is formed in every state, by the order which unites all the families whereof it is composed under one government, is restricted within the territories of each -state/ The second order or part of universal society, which is formed and maintained among nations by humanity and natural equity common to all mankind, gives rise to the use of a variety of treaties or conven- r Domat, Droit Publ. Preface. 326 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OP STATES. tions which connect or unite nations with each other in a multitude of different ways, and for different purposes. Domat shows that man is destined to society by two kinds of engagements the general ties which God makes among all men by their nature and their destination to the same end under the same laws, and the particular ties binding men towards specified persons, which include all sorts of contracts and agreements formed differently, either by the several communica- tions which pass among men of their labour and industry, and all sorts of offices, services, and other assistances, or by those which relate to the use of things. 3 The treaties or conventions among nations are analogous to this second kind of engagements among individuals, for nations stand towards each other in the relation in which men are placed to one another by universal human society, which occasions the use of various dealings and communication among them. And as individuals may form different associations and bodies politic or cor- porate among themselves, so may nations unite themselves one with another, dividing and moulding the institrtion of sovereignty so as to maintain their union, and yet not extinguish their particular corpo- rate individuality and rights.* This takes place by conventions grounded on the interests and wants of nations, or in consequence of a war, by which a country loses part only of its sovereignty and separate independent existence, and that part is incorporated with the government of another country. We shall, however, see that though the principle of agreement and convention belongs to this class of governments, yet there is a sort of federal constitution which unites all the members of the community in the last of the three ties, and brings them together in the third of the orders into which Domat divides human society. In this case the federal constitution has all the qualities of a fundamental law, and is to be considered as such, and not as a compact or treaty." Pufendorf describes compound states (systemata civitatuurri) to be an assemblage of several states, closely bound together by some parti- cular tie, so that they appear to form one body, though each preserves sovereignty in itself independent of the others. 1 " It follows," says the same writer, " from this definition, that we must not, as Hobbes does, y rank among compound states those which simply include several subordinate bodies, nor those that have aggrandized themselves by swallowing up other states which they have incorporated with their Domat, Loix Civiles, Trait des Loix, ch. 2, 3. 1 Story, Com. on Constit. of the United States, vol. 1, ch. 3, 311. " Story, ubi sup. 352. * Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 5, 16. T Leviath. c. 22. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 327 former dominions. This takes place in two principal ways. One is when a conqueror removes the conquered people into his own domi- nions, or gives to them the same laws and privileges enjoyed by his former subjects; and the other way is when, leaving the conquered nation in their country, he abolishes their government, so that they remain purely and simply subjects of their conqueror. In both these cases, the conquered people ceases to be a state; but in the former the new subjects are on an equality with the old, while in the latter the conquered are reduced to a more disadvantageous position, and rendered a mere province. Nevertheless, the conquered people are frequently allowed to retain part of their laws and privileges, however different they may be from those of the conquerors. 2 For the unity of a state does not necessarily require that all the country belonging to it should be governed by the same positive laws, nor that all the subjects should be in an equally advantageous condition. It suffices that all be under a common sovereign power. And it is often a measure of policy to change nothing of the ancient customs of the conquered, or at least to leave them to a certain extent untouched. As for conquered provinces, Hobbes maintains that Judaea, under its Roman governors, was neither a democracy nor an aristocracy, because public affairs were not in the hands of an assembly of Jews. He then asks whether it was not a monarchy ; for he says that the Roman government was an aristocracy or a democracy with regard to the Roman citizens, but that does not preclude it from being a monarchy with regard to the Jews ; for the sovereignty of a state over other states is as much a monarchy as that of a single person over a multitude of men. Thus Hobbes seems to regard as monar- chies, provinces subject to an aristocratic or democratic state. But though provinces, as he shows elsewhere at length, 8 are usually governed by a single person rather than by an assembly ; it is, in my opinion, useless to debate the question what is the form of the govern- ment of provinces. For every province, which no longer has in itself a sovereignty of its own, ceases to be a state, and becomes a depen- dency of another state. And whether such province obey a governor or an assembly, that is not material to the form of the government, for they both have but a subordinate power. Thus the sovereignty exercised over provinces, or dependencies of a state, is always of the same nature, and cannot, except improperly, be called aristocracy or monarchy ; for this distinction of forms of government is applicable * Hobbes, Leviath. c. 26. a Ibi, c. 22. 328 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. only to states properly so called, which have a sovereignty of their own." b We must here observe, that Pufendorf uses the term province, not in its ordinary sense, as contradistinguished from the capital, city, or principal seat of government, but as signifying a dependency, such, for instance, as a colony. These cannot constitute, with the mother country or the state on which they depend, a compound state, because they are not in themselves states. Thus all the colonies and plantations of the British empire are equally subject to the supreme authority of the Imperial Parliament, whatever may be the form of the provincial government ; and they have no reserved or proper sovereignty of their own. The famous Declaratory Act, 18 Geo. III. c. 12, has been held not to limit the right of parliament to legislate for the colonies. It declares, " that from and after the passing of this act, the king and parliament of Great Britain will not impose any duty, tax or assess- ment whatever payable in any of his majesty's colonies, provinces or plantations, in North America or the West Indies, except only such duties as it may be expedient to impose for the regulation of com- merce ; the net produce of such duties to be always paid and applied to and for the use of the colony, province or plantation in which the same shall be respectively levied, in such manner as other duties col- lected by the authority of the respective general courts or general assemblies of such colonies, provinces or plantations, are ordinarily paid and applied." This act contains no abandonment of right. Its recitals set forth only the inexpediency of the taxation of the colonies by parliament, and then the statute declares that parliament will no longer exercise this right. Thus, we may conclude, that no part of the jura majestatis is reserved to the colonies in a sovereign capacity, for whatever is done by their provincial governments, even with the con- currence of the crown, may be annulled by parliament. 11 It is however necessary to observe, that these principles of our Public Law are modified in practice. For the spirit of recent colonial policy has been to leave to the colonies the management of their internal affairs ; extending to them the privileges of self-government, as far as their circumstances will admit, having regard to their own interests and those of the empire at large. The most important practical point of this policy is the introduction of responsible parliamentary govern- b Pufend. ubi sup. 16. c See the Speech of Lord Chancellor Brougham, Aug. 12th, 1833, Hansard, vol. 20, 3rd ser. cols. 521, 522. The Declaratory Act is held to apply only to those colonies which have legislative assemblies. Ibi. d See the definition of sovereign power by Grotius, Droit de la Guerre, liv. 1, ch. 3, 7. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 329 ment into the colonies themselves. It was urged by the late Earl of Durham, in his report on the affairs of Canada, 6 that the government there could not be conducted with ease or harmony, excepting by the advice of persons having the confidence of the house of assembly. " If," he said, " colonial legislatures have frequently stopped the sup- plies, if they have harassed public servants by unjust or harsh im- peachments, it was because the removal of an unpopular administration could not be effected in the colonies by those milder indications of a want of confidence, which have always sufficed to attain the end in the mother country." He urged that the governor should be instructed to secure the co-operation of the assembly in his policy, by entrusting it to such men as could command a majority in the assembly or colo- nial parliament, and that it should be made necessary for the official acts of the governor to be countersigned by some public functionary ; and that changes of administration ought to take place in the colonies on the same principles on which they occur at home. The difficulty of the system consists in this, that it places the government of the colonies under two sets of ministers, one responsible to the colonial, and the other to the imperial parliament. And the governor of the colony is himself responsible to the crown, to parlia- ment, and to the colonial legislature, who may at any time address the Queen to remove him. Thus, the government at home may compel the colonial governor to take a course rendering it impossible for him to form an administration possessing the confidence of the provincial parliament. And so the whole government of the colony may be brought to a stand. The remedy against this danger is to be found in the wisdom and moderation of parliament, and the responsible ser- vants of the crown at home ; and in a prudent discrimination between matters of imperial and of provincial government or policy. This method of managing dependencies gives, in practice, a federal cha- racter to our colonial system, without violating the principles of Public Law, on which the unity of the empire depends ; and it is calculated to prolong: the connexion of the colonies with the mother country. The federal element of the system will probably develop itself, and become a constitutional law, securing a wholesome independence to the colonies, in all that does not involve the integrity and general interests of the empire. And at the same time, its natural effect is to prepare for the useful enjoyment of complete independence, or to become integral portions of other states, such colonies as their own domestic interests and the course of events may hereafter separate e Earl of Durham's Report, 1839, pp. 100, 101. 330 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. from the mother country. This last consideration is not pleasing to our feelings of national pride and patriotism ; but it is grounded on principles of true statesmanship. For, as we have shown/ the division of mankind into nations and states is a subordinate or subsidiary institution of Public Law ; and the boundaries of states are matter of arbitrary law, subject to be varied and modified by political events, in accordance with the welfare and prosperity of particular communi- ties, and the general good government of mankind. This position may seem a truism, and yet its neglect has caused much bloodshed, and retarded the progress of civilized society. For princes and nations have often imagined, that to secure or retain a certain territory was a sacred duty which could not be neglected without guilt and disgrace, and must therefore be performed, whatever might be the consequences, though in direct violation of the principles on which mankind are divided into political communities, for the purposes of civil society, founded on the two great primary laws. And so history presents many instances of conquests injurious alike to the conqueror and the con- quered, obstinately retained with the sacrifice of much human life and happiness ; and provinces or dependencies converted into bitter ene- mies, which by a wise and timely emancipation would have become valuable allies of the mother country. Pufendorf divides compound states (or systemata civitatuuni) into two sorts : one is where two or more distinct states have but one king ; and the other is where two or more confederated states form together but one body politic. With regard to the first sort, he observes, that there is no reason why several politic bodies should not have one common head. This sort of compound state may be produced in several ways. The most usual are the marriage of princes and the right of succession. Thus, if a princess, sovereign in her own right, marry a foreign sovereign, the two states will be connected, or united, at least in the children of that marriage ; for it is not in that case necessary that the princess and her dominions should be subject to her husband. The heir to a kingdom may be the sovereign of another state, and thus the two states may be united. The same thing occurs when a nation choose for their kins; a o O prince already sovereign of or heir to another state. Two or more nations may agree together to elect the same king, without ceasing to be distinct kingdoms, and without establishing a general assembly for deliberation on all their public affairs in common. And a compound state is formed when a king, established by the free consent of his ' Chap. XIII. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 331 subjects, subjugates another nation in his own particular and proper name, at his own risk and peril, and at his own expense, without the act or assistance of his subjects. 8 But one person may be king of two or more states without their forming a compound state. For their fundamental laws may keep the several crowns entirely distinct and unconnected. And so it was with the kingdom of Hanover and the united kingdom of Great Britain and Ireland. " As for any foreign dominions," says Black- stone, " which may belong to the person of the king by hereditary descent, by purchase or other acquisition, as the territory of Hanover and his majesty's other property in Germany; as these do not in any- wise appertain to the crown of these kingdoms, they are entirely unconnected with the laws of England, and do not communicate with this nation in any respect whatsoever." 11 As the union of this sort of compound states is solely founded on the person of a common prince, or at the utmost on the royal family, it is clear that when that family is entirely extinct, the body formed by the connexion of the states is dissolved, and each nation may create a king for itself, or introduce any other form of government, without the con- currence of any external person. This would be so, assuming that those kingdoms were united solely by their dependence on a common king. Thus, if a prince already in possession of a hereditary state, has become the sovereign of another by election, the union of those states ends on his death, and the elective state is not bound to choose his son to succeed him. But when two or more kingdoms are joined into one body by a confederation between them, if one of those states violate the principal articles, at least, of the treaty, the others who are injured thereby are entitled to break the alliance. Pufendorf, however, draws a distinction between the obligation of each confederated nation to- wards their common king, and their obligations towards each other. For, he says, a king once elected, to whom an oath of fidelity has been taken, cannot be deposed for every sort of wrongful act, even though committed contrary to his engagements, so long as he does not act as a declared enemy of the nation, unless the convention giving him the sovereign authority contains a commissary clause or clause of for- feiture, 1 making the obedience of his subjects depend on the observance of all and each of the articles of the contract. In that case the breach of any of them will deprive him of his crown, and so dissolve the body united in his person. But as regards the reciprocal obligation of the s Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 5, 17. h Blackst. Com. vol. 1, p. 110; stat. 12 & 13 Will. 3, c. 2 ; Heineccii Prselect. in Pufend. De Offic. Horn, et Civ. lib. 2, cap. 8, 13. 1 Grotius, Droit de la Guerre, liv. 1, ch. 3, 16. 332 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. nations joined under the same prince, that nation to whose prejudice the laws of the confederation have been violated, may separate itself, though the injury be not very considerable, provided the other nations concurred in the wrongful act, or if it be produced and turned to their profit. Thus, on the death of their common prince, the injured nations may separate themselves from the others, and afterwards act against the authors of or accomplices in the wrong, to obtain reparation, or to recover what has been taken from it. If several states are conjoined by virtue of a marriage making a Prince the heir to them all, and the order of succession of the crown be differently regulated in them, there the union is dissolved when the same person cannot succeed to all those kingdoms according to their fundamental laws. This would be when in one of two kingdoms so joined, the agnatic or male, and in the other, the cognatic or female succession prevails, and the reigning sovereign dies without male issue: for then the former kingdom will devolve on the next male heir, while the latter will descend to the daughter of the deceased sovereign. But if an union of states, originally formed by marriage or descent, be confirmed and rendered perpetual by confederation or by a law binding on them all, the diver- sity of their several laws of succession must be held to be thereby abolished ; and in such case that law of succession must be followed which is expressly provided in the treaty or law of union, or that which is known to be most conformable to the will of the author of the union, or the most natural or most advantageous to the united kingdoms. But when a kingdom becomes a province of another, there is no confederation, for the two states then become one. k We come now to the second sort of compound states, or, as Martens calls them, systems of confederated states. 1 These are, as Pufendorf tells us, formed by the perpetual confederation of several states, which usually originates from the fact that they desire to preserve the liberty of governing themselves, each according to its own laws, and yet do not feel strong enough singly to defend themselves against common enemies. " States so united," he continues, " engage with each other to exercise in common some part of the sovereign power. For the principal difference between this sort of perpetual confederation which joins nations in one body, and the alliances usually made by nations with each other, is, that in the latter each ally determines by his own judgment to do certain things agreed upon among the allies, but without making the exercise of that part of the sovereign power, to which those engagements relate, depend on the k Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 5, 1 7. 1 Martens, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 3, 29. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 333 consent of the others ; and without giving up anything of the full and absolute rights of the government of the particular state. Besides, mere alliances usually have for their object some particular advantage of each ally, and are only for a certain time. But this sort of confe- deration of which we are treating consists in this that several nations, without ceasing to be distinct states, unite together with a view to their preservation and mutual defence, making, for this purpose, the exercise of certain parts of sovereignty to depend on their common consent. Thus there is a great difference between saying ' / bind myself to aid you in this or that war, and to deliberate with you as to the way of acting against the enemy ; and agreeing thus : ' that neither of us shall make war or peace except by mutual consent.' I have said that in these confederations constituting compound states, the parties subject only some parts of the sovereign power to be exercised by common consent. For the interests of the confederates can scarcely be so united together as to make it advantageous to all in general, and each in particular, to exercise no portion of sovereignty except in common. And if this were so, they would far better be united in a single state than bound together by a mere confederation. Each con- federated state must reserve to itself full power to do as it thinks proper all that belongs to those parts of sovereignty which are of such a nature that the other united states have little or no interest, at least directly, in the way of their exercise. Such, for instance, are treaties of commerce; the establishment of the imposts necessary for the indi- vidual wants of the particular state ; the creation of magistrates ; the laws ; the right of life and death over its own citizens ; its power in ecclesiastical affairs, and the like ; with regard to which, however, each state should be careful to do nothing calculated to disturb the union. The same must be the case regarding ordinary affairs, or those which do not leave time to consult the other confederates. But as for those regarding the welfare of the whole body, they must be decided in a common assembly. Such are especially war, both offen- sive and defensive, and peace whereby it is terminated. And if any difference arise among any of the members of a compound state, the others who are disinterested ought in the first instance to intervene as mediators, and prevent the disputants from proceeding to hostilities. If follows from what we have said, that each of the confederated states has full liberty to exercise as it thinks proper all those parts of the sovereign power which are not mentioned in the treaty of confede- ration as powers to be exercised in common."" 1 Pufendorf proposes the question, whether the decision of the "Pufend. ubi sup. 18. See Bynkershoek, De modis conc'diandi dissentientes pro- vincias. Quaest. Jur. Publ. lib. 2, cap. 24. 334 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. common affairs of the confederation depends on the unanimous con- sent of all the confederates, or whether the opinion of the majority must be binding on all. He holds that the latter practice may be followed in an irregular compound state, which is in the nature of a simple state, that is to say, when several states form a single state : but that it could not be admitted in a regular body of confederated states. For, he says, as the liberty of a state is the power of deciding in the last resort on all matters touching its own preservation, a state cannot be conceived to be free when another can with authority compel it to do certain things. The confederates have, it is true, agreed to exercise in common certain parts of the sovereign power. But there is a distinction between this and the power of a majority to compel the others to do that which is not stipulated in the treaty of confederation. He further explains this point by observing, that the engagement of several persons to have but one will, proceeds either from a mere convention or agreement, or from the subjection of the will of one to that of the other. " The indispensable concurrence of several wills, which is grounded on a mere convention or agreement, does not infringe the liberty of which we speak. For either the mode in which certain affairs are to be administered conjointly has been beforehand regulated by common consent : or else, if something after- wards arise to be decided, each party claims to be only bound to give way to good and sufficient reasons. But when we submit our will to that of another, and he has thereby obtained an authority over us, he may oblige us even to things which are displeasing to us." n Pufen- dorf argues that the rule which gives authority to the plurality of votes is not here applicable. For it refers to assemblies already con- stituted, that is to say, simple bodies and not confederations. But he adds, that if one of the confederates refused with bad faith to agree to the opinion of the others, and showed unreasonable obstinacy, to the betrayal of the common cause, it would be lawful to use against him the means allowed by natural law against violators of treaties and alliances : or that inconvenient member who troubled the peace of the society, and who acts so as to ruin it, may be banished from it. Except in such cases, he adds, there may be great injustice in follow- ing the rule of the plurality of votes ; as, for example, where some of the confederated states are more powerful than the others, and thus they contribute unequally to the public defence. For though they each contribute in proportion to their means, and thus there is a sort of equality of contribution, yet it may happen often that the weaker state is more willing to expose its contingent than the stronger. Thus, 11 Pufend. ubi sup. 20. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 335 supposing that one of the states brings to the support of the common interests as much as all the others together, would it be just that they, without the consent of that state and against its will, should undertake any enterprise or other matter, the great expense and burthen of which would fall on the dissentient ? But, on the other hand, if the number of votes of each state in the confederation be in proportion to its con- tribution to the common welfare, this will give to a state so superior in power an authority over the other confederates. Pufendorf concludes that if in an assembly of confederated states, affairs are absolutely decided by plurality of votes, it is not a regular compound state, but an irregular body, or even one single simple state, and not a confede- ration. The doctrine of Pufendorf is, that when in a compound state of this sort anything is to be decided that has not been settled by the instrument of confederation, the decision must be, not that of a ma- jority, but unanimous. " Compound states are dissolved," continues the same writer, " when some of the confederates detach themselves to govern their affairs separately. And this usually happens/ because they think the union more burthensome than useful to themselves. Intestine wars, also, among the confederates break up the union, unless the confederation be renewed on the conclusion of peace. As for wars with foreign powers, when the confederated states have been unsuccessful, the victor sometimes, as a measure of policy, separates them, and compels them to remain disunited, each q governed according to its own laws, as the Romans did with regard to the people of Achaia. Hereupon it is necessary to remark, that when the common enemy has taken possession of one of the confederated states, he does not thereby acquire a right over the others ; and he cannot claim to make them his conquest, nor even to be received into the confederation, by virtue of the place occupied therein by the conquered state. He can only be admitted by a new treaty or convention, as we see in the case of King Philip of Macedon, who was admitted into the assembly of the Amphyctions in the place of the Phocians/ in consequence of a deci- sion of the whole body. For though the union of several states seems to be by a real, as contradistinguished from a personal confederation, that is to say, a treaty with the body of the state itself, and not merely with the sovereign, 5 and a nation, the form of whose government is changed, does not lose its identity on that account : yet, as the confe- Pufend. ubi sup. 20. P Livy, lib. 38, cc. 31, 32. 1 Zenophon, lib. 4, Hellenic, ch. 8, 14, et seq. ; lib. 5, cap. 1, 16, edit Ox. r Diod. Sicul. lib. 16, cap. 61. See Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 8, ch. 9, 6. 336 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. deration was made between the nations, considered precisely as so many distinct states, it follows that when one of them is subjugated, or becomes a dependency of another state, the confederation no longer subsists with regard to it. Even if it be stipulated in the treaty that a change in the form of the government of one of the confederated states shall not exclude it from the body, such stipulation must be understood to refer to changes made in a lawful manner, as by the free consent of the people.* Thus neither an usurper in the nation itself, nor a foreign conqueror, can claim a place in the general assembly of the confederated states. A compound state, or system of states, also becomes a simple state, if all the confederates submit themselves to the sovereign authority of one man or one assembly ; or if one of the states, by superiority of power, reduce the others to the condition of provinces, which usually occurs when the weaker states confer on the stronger one some permanent pre-eminence, and they enter into an unequal u confederation, or the same result is produced if one of the confederates becomes master of the others, by the favour of the army or the people, or by cabals." x These reflections on simple confederations or systems of states, forming together compound states, show that their corporate character and action are necessarily restricted to certain specified parts of the sovereign power, which, by their federal constitution, they are to exercise in common in their sovereign capacity. And these compound states differ from simple ones, in being societies depending for their union on contract or convention, and not constituted by means of a sovereign power, supreme over every member of the body politic. We have already considered this matter in explaining the connexion of the jura majestatis with each other; y but it will not be superfluous to add here the following arguments of Mr. Hamilton, showing the defects of the confederation of the United States of America, 2 which was superseded by the constitution. "The great and radical vice in the construction of the existing confederation is in the principle of legislation for states or govern- ments, in their corporate or collective capacities, and as contradistin- guished from the individuals of whom they consist. Though this 1 The expression used by Pufendorf may seem to imply that no change in the form of government can lawfully be made except by the free consent of the people. But this is not so, for the organic laws of states differ greatly in this respect. Thus, an absolute monarchy may be converted into an aristocracy, and vice versa, without the concurrence of the people. u Grotius, 1.1, c. 3, 21, num. 10. * Pufend. Droit dea Gens, liv. 7, chap. 5, | 21. y Chap. XXII. 1 Federalist, num. 15, p. 7880. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 337 principle does not run through all the powers delegated to the union; yet it pervades and governs those on which the efficacy of the rest depends. Except as to the rule of appointment the United States have an infinite discretion to make requisitions for men and money, but they have no authority to raise either by regulations extending; to the individual citizens of America. The consequence of this is, that though in theory their resolutions concerning those objects are laws, constitutionally binding on the members of the Union, yet, in practice, they are mere recommendations, which the states observe or disregard at their option. It is a singular instance of the capriciousness of the human mind, that, after all the admonitions we have had from expe- rience on this head, there should still be found men who object to the new constitution, for deviating from a principle which has been found the bane of the old, and which is in itself evidently incompatible with the idea of a government; a principle, in short, which, if it is to be executed at all, must substitute the violent and sanguinary agency of the sword, to the mild influence of the magistracy. There is nothing- absurd or impracticable in the idea of a league or alliance between independent nations, for certain defined purposes precisely stated in a treaty, regulating all the details of time, place, circumstance, and quantity, leaving nothing to future discretion, and depending for its execution on the good faith of the parties. Compacts of this kind exist among all civilized nations, subject to the usual vicissitudes of peace and war, of observance and non-observance, as the interests or passions of the contracting powers dictate. In the early part of the present century there was an epidemical rage in Europe for this species of compact, from which the politicians of the times fondly hoped for benefits which were never realized. With a view to establishing the equilibrium of power, and the peace of that part of the world, all the resources of negotiation were exhausted, and triple and quadruple alliances were formed, but they were scarcely formed before they were broken, giving an instructive but afflicting lesson to mankind, how little dependence is to be placed on treaties which have no other sanction than the obligations of good faith, and which oppose general considerations of peace and justice to the impulse of any immediate interest of passions. If the particular states in this country are dis- posed to stand in a similar relation to each other, and to drop the project of a general discretionary superintendence, the scheme would indeed be pernicious, and would entail upon us all the mischiefs which have been enumerated under the first head ; but it would have the merit of being at least consistent and practicable. Abandoning all views towards a confederate government, this would bring us to a simple alliance, offensive and defensive, and would place us in a situa- z 338 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. tion to be alternately friends and enemies of each other, as our mutual jealousies and rivalships, nourished by the intrigues of foreign nations, should prescribe to us. But if we are unwilling to be placed in this perilous situation, if we still adhere to the design of a national govern- ment, or, which is the same thing, of a superintending power, under the direction of a common council, we must resolve to incorporate into our plan those ingredients which may be considered as forming the characteristic difference between a league and a government ; we must extend the authority of the union to the persons of the citizens, the only proper objects of government. Government implies the power of making laws. It is essential to the idea of a law that it be attended with a sanction, or, in other words, a. penalty or punishment for dis- obedience. If there be no penalty annexed to disobedience, the reso- lution or commands which pretend to be laws, will in fact amount to nothing more than advice or recommendation. This penalty, what- ever it may be, can only be inflicted in two ways, by the agency of the courts and ministers of justice, or by military force, by the coercion of the magistracy, or by the coercion of arms. The first kind can evidently apply only to men ; the last kind must of necessity be employed against bodies politic, or communities or states. It is evident that there is no process of a court by which their observance of the laws can, in the last resort, be enforced. Sentences may be denounced against them for violations of their duty, but these sen- tences can only be carried into execution by the sword. In an asso- ciation where the general authority is confined to the collective bodies of the communities that compose it, every breach of the laws must involve a state of war, and military execution must become the only instrument of civil obedience. Such a state of things can certainly not deserve the name of government, nor would any prudent man choose to commit his happiness to it." These arguments of the American statesman are in accordance with the principles of Pufendorf, explained above, and they show the dif- ference between a system of confederated states, and a federal govern- ment. The latter species of constitution we must now examine. Mr. Hamilton 5 comments on the opinion of Montesquieu, recom- mending a small extent of territory for republics; and he observes, that that opinion is not opposed to the enlargement of the orbit within which popular systems of civil government are to revolve, by the con- solidation of several smaller states into a great confederacy. And he cites the following passage of Montesquieu, explicitly treating of a confederate republic, as an expedient for extending the sphere of popu- * Federalist, num. 9, pp. 45, &c. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 339 lar government, and reconciling the advantages of monarchy with those of republicanism. " It is very probable that mankind would have been obliged at length to live constantly under the government of a single person, had they not contrived a kind of constitution which has all the internal advantages of a republican, together with the external force of a monarchical government. I mean a confederate republic. This form of government is a convention, by which several smaller states agree to become members of a larger one, which they intend to form. It is a kind of assemblage of societies that constitutes a new one, capable of increasing by means of new associations, till they arrive to such a degree of power as to be able to provide for the security of the united body. A republic of this kind, able to with- stand an external force, may support itself without any internal corrup- tion. The form of this society prevents all manner of inconveniences. If a single member should attempt to usurp the supreme authority, he could not be supposed to have equal authority and credit in all the confederate states. Were he to have too great influence over one, this would alarm the rest. Were he to subdue a part, that which would remain free might oppose him with forces, independent of those which he had usurped, and overpower him before he could be settled in his usurpation. Should a popular insurrection happen in one of the confederated states, the others would be able to quell it. Should abuses creep into one part, they are reformed by those that remain sound. The state may be destroyed on one side, and not on the other ; the confederacy may be dissolved, and the confederates preserve their sovereignty. As this government is composed of small republics, it enjoys the internal happiness of each, and with respect to its external situation, it is possessed, by means of the association, of all the ad- vantages of large monarchies." b These objects of federal government can only be attained by com- bining the federal principle with that of simple national government and unity. We must now see how this may be contrived, by refer- ring to the solution of the problem in the United States of America. The constitution of that country would, as we have already observed, be an unlimited democracy, if the sovereign power were not divided between the States and the Union, which distribution causes a balance of power. Madison, commenting on this mixed character of the then proposed American constitution, makes the following observations. He shows that the act establishing the constitution was a federal, not a national act. For though the constitution was founded on the assent b Montesq. Esprit des Loix, liv. 9, ch. 1 ; Story, Comment, on the Constit. of the United States, vol. 1, ^ 473. Federalist, numb. 39, pp. 206, &c. z 2 340 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. and ratification of the people of America, given by their deputies, yet such assent and ratification was given by the people, not as individuals, composing one entire nation, but as composing the distinct and inde- pendent states to which they respectively belonged. And it was the result, not of the decision of a majority of the States, but of their unanimous assent. Here we find the principle laid down by Pufen- dorf, that a federal act should be unanimous, and should not be merely that of a majority of the confederates or their representatives. And Madison accordingly holds, that were the people regarded in that transaction as forming one nation, the will of the majority of the people, or of the States, as evidence of the will of the people, would bind the minority. But, on the contrary, each State, in ratifying the constitution, was considered as a sovereign body, independent of all others, and only bound by its own act. d But though this was the nature of the original act of establishing the constitution, Story shows, at great length, that the constitution, considered in itself, is not a com- pact or confederation, but a fundamental law. 6 And in this sense, as Mr. Webster has said, the constitution declares that it is ordained by the people of the United States, that is to say, established by the people of the United States in the aggregate and taken collectively. f If it were otherwise, the constitution would be, not a law, or as it is emphatically called, the supreme law of the land, but a compact or treaty, like the confederation which it superseded. Madison next regards the constitution, in relation to the sources from which the ordinary powers of government are derived. And herein we principally see its mixed character. The House of Repre- sentatives derives its powers from the people of America, and the people are represented in the same proportion as to numbers, and on the same principle, as they are in the legislature of each particular state. 8 So far the government is national, not federal. The senate, on the other hand, the members of which are elected by the legis- latures of the states, derives its powers from the states as political and co-equal societies; and each state is represented without re- ference to population, by the same number of senators, i. e. two, on the principle of equality. So far the government is federal, not national. 11 And this equal representation of the states in the senate is a protection to the residuary sovereignty of the smaller states, who have fewer representatives in the other branch of the legislature. We come now to the executive power. The immediate part of the d Federalist, num. 39, p. 207. e Story, Comment, on the Constit. of the United States, book 3, ch. 3. f Ibi, 363; Webster, Speeches, 1830, p. 431 ; Elliot, Debates, vol. 4, p. 326. K Kent, Comment, vol. 1, part 2, lect. 11, pp. 229, 230. 11 Federalist, p. 207 ; Kent, Comment, vol. 1, part 2, lect. 11, pp. 224, 225. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OV STATES. 341 election of the President, that is to say, the choice of those who are to elect him, is made by the states in their political characters. For the electors are chosen in each state under the direction of the lesris- O lature, and their number must be equal to the whole number of senators and representatives which the state is entitled to send to Congress ; and so, under the apportionment of Congress, in 1832, the number of electors was 28 1. 1 The eventual election of the President is made by that branch of the legislature which consists of the national represen- tatives ; but in this particular act they are thrown into the form of individual delegations, from so many distinct and co-equal bodies politic. k For the person having the greatest number of votes of the electors for President, is President, if such number be a majority of the whole number of electors appointed. But in the event of no person having such majority, then from the persons having the highest number, not exceeding three, on the list of those voted for as Presi- dent, the House of Representatives choose immediately (or before the 4th of March following), by ballot, the President. But in the choosing the President, the votes of the members of the House of Representatives are taken by states, the representation from each state having but one vote. 1 In this case, therefore, the election is partly federal. If the United States constitution be viewed with reference to the operation of the government, it is not federal, but national. For the powers of the government, in its ordinary and most essential proceed- ings, operate, not as was the case under the confederation, on the political bodies composing the confederacy, but on the individual citizens composing the nation in their individual capacity." 1 In some cases, however, arid particularly in the trial of controversies, to which the states may be parties, they must be viewed and proceeded against in their collective and political capacities." " But," continues Madison, " if the government be national, with regard to the operation of its powers, it changes its aspect again, when we contemplate it in relation to the extent of its powers. The idea of a national government involves in it, not only an authority over the individual citizens, but an indefinite supremacy over all persons and things, so far as they are objects of lawful government. Among a people consolidated into one nation, this supremacy is completely vested in the national legislature. Among communities united for 1 Federalist, ibi ; Kent, Comment, ibi, pp. 274, 275. k Federalist, p. 207. 1 Kent, Comment, ibi, lect. 14, pp. 276, 277. m Federalist, p. 208; Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 10, p. 213217. D Federalist, pp. 208, 209. 342 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. particular purposes, it is vested partly in the general, and partly in the municipal legislatures. In the former case, all local authorities are subordinate to the supreme, and may be controlled, directed, or abo- lished by it at pleasure. In the latter, the local or municipal authori- ties form distinct and independent portions of the supremacy, no more subject, within their respective spheres, to the general authority, than the general authority is subject to them within its own sphere. In this relation, then, the proposed government cannot be deemed a national one; since its jurisdiction extends to certain enumerated ob- jects only, and leaves to the several states a residuary and inviolable sovereignty over all other objects. It is true, that, in controversies relating to boundary between the two jurisdictions, the tribunal which is ultimately to decide, is to be established under the general govern- ment. But this does not change the principle of the case. The decision is to be impartially made, according to the rules of the con- stitution, and all the usual and most effectual precautions are taken to secure this impartiality. Some such tribunal is clearly essential to prevent an appeal to the sword, and a dissolution of the compact ; and that it ought to be established under the general, rather than under the local governments; or, to speak more properly, that it could be safely established under the first alone, is a position not likely to be com- bated." " If we try the constitution by its last relation to the authority by which amendments are to be made, we find it neither wholly national nor wholly federal. Were it wholly national, the supreme and ultimate authority would reside in the people of the Union ; and this authority would be competent at all times, like the majority of any national society, to alter or abolish its established government. Were it wholly federal, on the other hand, the concurrence of each state in the Union would be essential to every alteration that would be binding on all. The mode provided by the plan of the convention is not founded on either of these principles. In requiring more than a majority, and The fifth article of the Constitution respects the mode of making amendments to it. It is in these words: " The Congress, whenever two-thirds of both houses shall deem it necessary, shall propose amendments to this Constitution, or, on the applicatidh of the legislatures of two-thirds of the several states, shall call a convention for proposing amendments, which, in either case, shall he valid to all intents and purposes as part of this Constitution, when ratified by the legislatures of three-fourths of the several states, or by conventions in three-fourths thereof, as the one or the other mode of ratification may be proposed by the Congress ; provided that no amendment which may be made prior to the year one thousand eight hundred and eight, shall in any manner affect the first and fourth clauses in the ninth section of the first article ; and that no state, with- out its consent, shall be deprived of its equal suffrage in the senate." Story, Comment, vol. 3, 1820. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 343 particularly in computing the proportion by states, not by citizens, it departs from the national and advances towards the federal character; in rendering the concurrence of less than the whole number of states sufficient, it loses again the federal and partakes of the national cha- racter." "The proposed constitution, therefore, even when tested by the rules laid down by its antagonists, is, in strictness, neither a na- tional nor a federal constitution, but a composition of both. In its foundation it is federal, not national ; in the sources from which the ordinary powers of the government are drawn, it is partly federal and partly national ; in the operation of these powers, it is national, not federal ; in the extent of them again, it is federal, not national ; and finally, in the authoritative mode of introducing amendments, it is neither wholly federal nor wholly national." The federal character of the United States constitution depends on the residuary sovereignty of the states, which is not vested in the Union. For the constitution of the United States is an instrument containing the grant of specific powers, and the government of the Union cannot claim any powers but what are contained in the grant, and given either expressly or by necessary implication. The powers vested in the state governments by their respective constitu- tions, or remaining with the people of the several states, prior to the establishment of the constitution of the United States, continue un- altered and unimpaired, except so far as they are granted to the United States. The people of the United States have declared the constitu- tion to be the supreme law of the land, and it is entitled to universal and implicit obedience. Every act of Congress, and every act of the legislatures of the states, and every part of the constitution of any state, which is repugnant to the constitution of the United States, is void. The judicial power of the Union is declared to extend to all cases in law and equity, arising under the constitution ; and to the judicial power it belongs, whenever a case is judicially before it, to determine what is the law of the land. The determination of the supreme court of the United States, in every such case, must be final and conclusive, because the constitution gives to that tribunal the power to decide, and gives no appeal from that decision.? This right of the courts to pronounce legislative acts void, because contrary to the constitution, may seem at first to imply a superiority of the judicial to the legislative power, because in general the authority which can declare the acts of another void must be superior to the one whose acts are declared void. q But limitations of the power of a legislative body or magistrate can in practice be preserved in no other P Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 15, pp. 312, 313. i Federalist, num. 78, p. 420. 344 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. way than by means of the courts of justice. And this doctrine is strictly in accordance with the principles of Public Law. The act of a delegated authority, contrary to the commission or beyond the commission under which it is exercised, is void. There- fore no legislative act, contrary to the constitution, can be valid. Dilig enter fines mandati custodiendi sunt ; nam qui excedit, aliud quid facere videturJ Now the judicial power can declare void the acts of the legislative power, where those acts are beyond the powers delegated to the legislature, and therefore in reality not legislative acts, except in form only. Thus the judicial is not placed above the legislative power, because the former must obey the valid acts of the latter. The power of the people is superior to both ; and where the will of the legislature, declared in its statutes, stands in opposition to that of the people, declared in the constitution, the judges ought to be governed by the latter rather than the former. They ought to regulate their decisions by the fundamental laws, rather than by those which are not fundamental. 3 As the constitution is the supreme law of the land, in a conflict between that and the laws, either of Congress or of the States, it becomes the duty of the judiciary to follow that only which is of paramount obligation. 1 It was urged, when the constitution was under discussion, that the legislative body were themselves the constitutional judges of their own powers. But this doctrine is at variance with the spirit of a constitu- tion granting specific powers, and thereby limiting the authority of the legislature. For that body would not be fitting tribunal to judge of restrictions on itself; and it would have a natural tendency to enlarge its own power and narrow that of the state legislatures. It is far more reasonable that the courts should be an intermediate body between the people and the legislature, in order, among other things, to keep the latter within the limits assigned to their authority. Be- sides, the interpretation of the laws is the proper and peculiar province of the courts ; and a constitution is in fact, and must be regarded by the judges as, a fundamental law. The principle of Public Law, regarding' the power of the United States government, is thus laid down by Mr. Hamilton : " A govern- ment ought to contain in itself every power requisite to the full accomplishment of the objects committed to its care, and the complete execution of the trusts for which it is responsible ; free from every other control, but a regard to the public good and to the sense of the 1 L. 5, ff. Mandati; Voet ad Pand. lib. 17, tit. 1, 11. Federalist, p. 422. 1 Story, Comment, vol. 3, 1570; Federalist, num. 78, 80-82; Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch, 137. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 345 people."" Therefore, the powers of Congress extend generally to all subjects of a national nature. Congress are authorized " to provide for the common defence and general welfare, and for that purpose, among other express grants, they are authorized to lay and collect taxes, duties, imposts and excises ; to borrow money on the credit of the United States ; to regulate commerce with foreign nations, and among the several states, and with the Indian tribes; to declare war and define offences against the law of nations ; to raise, maintain and govern armies, and a navy ; to organize, discipline and arm the militia; and to give efficacy to all the powers contained in the constitution. Some of these powers, as the levying of taxes, duties and excises, are con- current with similar powers of the several states, but in most cases these powers are exclusive, because the concurrent exercise of them by the states separately would disturb the general harmony and peace, and because they would be apt to be repugnant to each other in prac- tice, and tend to dangerous collisions."-" A concurrent jurisdiction in the article of taxation is the only admissible substitute for an entire subordination, in respect to this branch of power, of state authority to that of the Union/ But the constitution provides that no state "shall enter into any treaty, alliance or confederation; grant letters of marque or reprisal ; coin money; emit bills of credit; make anything but gold and silver coin a tender in payment of debts ; pass any bill of attain- der, ex post facto law, or law impairing the obligation of contracts; or grant any title of nobility. No state shall, without the consent of Congress, lay any imposts or duties on imports or exports, except what may be absolutely necessary for executing its inspection laws, nor lay any duty on tonnage, keep troops or ships of war in time of peace, enter into any agreement or compact with another state, or with a foreign power, or engage in war, unless actually invaded, or in such imminent danger as will not admit of delay.*" With regard to the President, his chief powers are these; he is commander in chief of the army and navy of the United States, and of the militia of the several states when called into the service of the Union. a He has the power, by and with the advice and consent of the senate, to make treaties, provided two-thirds of the senators present concur. b He is the effi- cient power in the appointment of the officers of the government. He is to nominate, and, with the advice and consent of the senate, to Federalist, num. 31, pp. 159, 160. x Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 11, p. 237. >" Federalist, numb. 34, p. 175 ; and see numb. 30, 31. L Constitution, art. 1, sect. 10; Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 19, p. 407. Constitution, art. 2, sect. 2. b Art. 2, sect. 2. 346 OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OP STATES. appoint ambassadors, or public ministers and consuls, the judges of the supreme court, and all other officers whose appointments are not otherwise provided for in the constitution ; but Congress may vest the appointment of inferior officers in the President alone, in the courts of law, or in the heads of departments. And, as I have already ex- plained, the President has a qualified negative on the acts of the Con- gress. 11 As for the judicial power of the Union, its extent is in ac- cordance with the political axiom laid down by Kent that " the judi- cial power of every well constituted government must be co-extensive with the legislative power, and must be capable of deciding every ju- dicial question which grows out of the constitution and laws. 6 " It would be beyond the scope of these Commentaries to examine the reasons of the provisions of the American constitution thus briefly stated. We have dwelt chiefly on those portions which show how a form of polity partly federal and partly national or simple is con- structed. That sort of constitution is peculiarly adapted to a country the vast extent of which renders something more than a provincial government requisite for the parts distant from the capital, or seat of central power, and composed of communities originally separate, and having a strong feeling of corporate individuality and local patriotism. And it affords remarkable facilities for the acquisition of territory by the annexation of new states. For these are more willing to join in a confederation leaving to them a residuary sovereignty, with all the privileges of citizenship in a great nation, than they would be to become provinces, in any sense of the word, of a kingdom or republic. Yet this form of civil polity is liable to the defects arising from the complex nature of its machinery, and it has not that vigour and energy in the executive department which can only be secured by unity and simplicity, and which an American statesman has pronounced to be a leading character in the definition of good government/ These inconveniences arise from principles of public law already explained. The executive power divided between the President and the chief magistrates of the States, especially presents a difficulty in the struc- ture of this government. And this shows the still greater and perhaps insurmountable difficulty of a mixed confederate government com- posed of monarchical states. For the very nature of the regal office would cause a spirit of independence of, or opposition to, the autho- rity of the Union, and destroy the harmony of the system, so as .to paralyze its action. And indeed it is questionable whether this form c Art. 2, sect. 2. d Art. 1, sect. 7. And see above, pp. 315, 316. e Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 15, p. 328. ' Federalist, pp. 378, 379. OF COMPOUND STATES OR SYSTEMS OF STATES. 347 of government can be constructed on any other than republican prin- ciples. The steam engine and the electric telegraph tend to diminish the use and value of federalism, by facilitating intercourse, and connecting different places and communities together; and these means, as well as the progress of civilization, naturally diminish or extinguish local pride, and exclusive national or municipal feelings, which are the great obstacles to a central authority. And, indeed, the tendency of our times is often too strongly towards what is called centralization, which if carried beyond what the unity and vigour of government, and the benefits of uniformity, regularity, and economy require, is liable to many grave inconveniences. CHAPTER XXVIII. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. Double Aspect of the Law of Things Distinction between the Public and Private Law of Things The Four Classes of Things not Private, according to Justinian Domat's general View of the Public Law of Things Things common to all Men Common Right over Rivers The Common Rights of Mankind over the High Seas, and the Freedom of the Seas Appropriation of Parts of the Sea Jurisdiction over Ships, and Right of Search Public Things Rivers, Ports, Shores of the Sea, and Banks of Rivers Territories of a State Uninhabited and partly inhabited Countries and Land Hunting Ground of Savage Tribes Effect of the Change of the Course of Rivers which are Boundaries Law regarding Alluvion or Alluvial Accretions Lakes Acquisition of Territories by Occupancy Analysis of the Property of a Nation Public Property Imposts and Taxes Dominium eminens Res unitersi- tatis The Property of Bodies Corporate Res nullius Ecclesiastical Things Conclusion. THE use of all things in the world has some relation to the order and economy, or interests of society and the commonwealth ; and if the second of the three great divisions of law, that is to say, the law of things, be regarded under this aspect, the whole of it may seem to be within the scope of Public Law, both universal and municipal. Thus, as we have seen, there are many laws in different countries regulating private property, settlements, wills, and successions, which have a direct relation to the political laws of the state and the form of the civil polity. And judicial decisions on questions of private right are 348 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. sometimes grounded on reasons of public policy. 5 A bad law regard- ing private property may diminish the wealth and power of the whole community, or affect its peace, morality, and good order. And though every citizen has a right to manage and dispose of his property as he thinks fit, yet this right is subject to such regulations and laws as the public welfare requires. But, on the other hand, care should be taken not to restrain the people unnecessarily in the management of their affairs, as this would be contrary to the public good and the just liberty of the citizen. h These reflections on the double aspect of laws and their relation to society in general and the commonwealth, even when their direct object is of a private nature, are not without impor- tance in the science of legislation. The reason of this connexion between public and private law is, that all laws are, as we have shown, or ought to be, consequences, either direct or indirect, of the two fun- damental laws on which society is built; those of the former sort being immutable rules of equity necessary for the order of society, while the laws of the latter kind are positive laws, the justice of which depends on their fitness and adaptation to that order and the particular circum- stances of the commonwealth to which they belong. Thus the spirit of the whole law of things has this public element, because of the relation which their use bears to society, and the way in which the laws regulating them spring from the two fundamental laws of society. And we have seen that the second of the two classes of engagements by which man is destined to society, includes all those engagements which connect persons together, and are formed in divers ways by the several communications which pass among men of their labour, of their industry, and of all sorts of offices, services, and other assistances, or by those which relate to the use of things. And this includes all the different uses of arts, of employments, and of profes- sions of all kinds, and everything else that may link persons together, according to the several wants of life, whether by free and gratuitous J / O communications, or by commerce. 1 So the use of things is one of the foundations of society. And the law regarding that use chiefly belongs to secondary natural law. k We must now show the distinc- tion between public and private law in the law of things. 8 2 Barn. & Aid. 287; 5 Barn. & Aid. 287; 3 Barn. & Cress. 156; 3 Bing. 538; 5 Bing. 169; Cas. temp. Talb. 142; 3 P. W. 393, 394 ; 1 Atk. 352; 2 Atk. 136 ; Ambl. 235 ; 2 Anstr. 539;- 4 Bro. C. C. 124; 3 Madd. 114; 1 Sch. & Lef. 312; 2 Ball & B. 478 ; Lawton v. Lawlon, 3 Atk. 16 ; Egerton v. Brownlow, 4 House of Lords Cas. 1. h Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, cli. 20, 254, 255 ; Inst. lib. 1, tit. 8, 2. 1 Domat, Loix Civiles, Traite des Loix, ch. 2, 3. k L. 5, ff. De Just, et Jur. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 349 Justinian thus classifies things with reference to the nature of their appropriation. " They are either in the patrimony of some one (in nostro patrimonio), or not in the patrimony of any one (extra patri- monium nostrum}. For some things are common to all men by natural law, some are public, some belong to corporate or politic bodies (res universitatis), some belong to no one (res nullius}, many to individuals, and those are acquired in divers ways." ' We must apply to this classification of things the principle of the law of Ulpian describing public law. Publicum jus est, quod ad statum rei Romanae special: privatum quod ad singulorum utilitatem : sunt enim qucedam publice utilia, quadam privatim. Publicum jus in sacris, in sacerdotibus, in magistratibus consistit. m Four classes of things are, as appears from the extract given above, mentioned by Justinian as not private property, or extra nostrum patrimonium, that is to say I. Res jure naturali communia omnium: II. Res publica : III. Res universitatis : and IV. Res nullius. Hav- ing given this outline of the subject, and before entering into the explanation of these heads, we will see how Domat takes a general and comprehensive view of the law of things in Public Law. " Having explained in the preceding titles that which relates to the general order of the government, we shall explain in this the general policy of certain things which are of common use to this society, and which it is necessary to distinguish from those which every person may consume for his own private use. In order to distinguish these sorts of things from all others, and to understand rightly the policy of their use, it is necessary first to observe that there is nothing in the world which God has not created for the use of man, and that every thing in it is proportioned to his nature, and to his wants; so that we see in the structure of the world, and in the order and beauty of every thing contained in the earth and in the heavens, the dignity of man, for whom all these things have been made, and the relation which all this great fabric of the universe hath to his use, and to his wants. And in this infinite multitude of things of all kinds, with which we are environed in this world, it is necessary to distinguish two different sorts of them, and two different manners of the use which God gives us of them. The first of these two sorts of things is of those which are so necessary that no body can live without having a free and continual use of them, such as the air and light; and it is because of 1 Instit. lib. 2, tit. 1, princip. ; Voet ad Pand. lib. 1, tit. 8, 1. m L. 1, 2, ff. De Just, et Jur. " Deut. iv. 19; Psalm viii. ; Gen. i. 26; Heb. ii. 7. See Domat, Treatise of Laws, ch. 1, num. 3. 350 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. this necessity that the air encompasses the whole earth, which is the habitation of mankind, and that it is penetrated by the light which comes from the heavens, so that nobody can be deprived of the use of the air, and of the light, unless condemned to lose his life. And as to the manner of this use, as it is of a continual necessity it is likewise so easily to be had, that it does not require any industry or labour ; and every one has his proper use of these things, independently of the will of all others. Thus the government has nothing to regulate in this matter. It can only take precautions to keep the air pure, and forbid the throwing out or exposing anything in the public places which may infect it and render it unwholesome. The second sort of things is of those which are necessary to men for food, raiment, for habitation, and all other sorts of wants, which takes in the earth, the waters, and every thing they bear and bring forth, grain, fruits, plants, animals, metals, minerals, and all other things. And as for the manner of using all these things, it is distinguished from the manner of using the air and light, in that all those other things come to our use only by the means of some labour and industry, either in procuring them or in fitting them for the use that is to be made of them. It is for this use of this second kind of things, that seeing they are all necessary in the society of mankind, and cannot be had and put to any use, except by ways which demand different ties and intercourses among mankind, not only from one part of a kingdom to another, but from one country to another, and between nations that lie the most remote from one another, God has taken care by the order of nature, and men by the civil policy, to facilitate the said intercourses. Thus it is by nature, that one of the uses which God has given to the seas, and to rivers, is that of opening ways of communication with all the countries in the world by navigation. And it is by means of the civil policy that towns and other places have been built, where men assemble together, and have intercourse with one another by means of streets, market places, and other public places proper for that purpose ; and that the inhabit- ants of every town, every province, every kingdom, may have inter- course with all other persons, of what country soever, by the means of highways. Thus, for all these intercourses by land and water, it has been necessary to establish rules by this policy; and these rules shall make a part of the subject-matter of this title. As for the other rules of this title, it is to be remarked, that, besides this use of the seas and rivers, for the intercourse of men, they have another use, which is like- wise naturally common to all men, that of fishing. The surface of the earth gives likewise naturally to men the use of hunting, especially in the woods and forests, which have, moreover, another use of much THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 351 greater importance for the common good, by the great advantage the public draws from the use of timber for building houses and ships, for warlike engines, for the artillery, for bridges, for the construction of public edifices, churches, palaces, and others. It is because of these uses that the ordinances in France have established a policy, not only in relation to the king's forests, and those belonging to churches, and to all sorts of communities, but also to those which belong to private persons, that they may be preserved for the said uses as occasion shall offer. And as to what concerns the use of hunting and fishing, in which the liberty granted by the Roman Law was much greater than is allowed by ours; seeing this liberty, given to all persons without distinction, would be attended with many inconveniences, whether it were by diverting people from their occupation, and encouraging idle- ness, or by occasioning quarrels between those who should hunt or fish in the same place, or because of the damage that would accrue to the public by fishing and hunting in certain seasons of the year, or with certain tackle and in certain manners which would destroy the wild animals and the fish, it has been thought reasonable to provide against them ; and the civil policy in France has set bounds to this liberty by several ordinances, which regulate to whom the liberty of hunting and fishing is permitted ; which prohibit the use of it in certain manners and certain seasons, and give other particular directions therein."? Some portions of this extract refer to the internal Public Law of France before the first revolution ; but it gives a good general view of the connexion of the various matters which are the subject of the Pub- lic Law of things, and their different uses, which show the spirit of the laws regarding them. Those laws are of two sorts, that is to say, arbitrary laws, of which the municipal law of all countries presents a vast extent and detail; and others, coming within a narrower compass, and which are part of the law of nature, and contain the principles of all the rest. q We may gather from these reflections of Domat, that those things are the subject matter of Public Law, the uses of which have a direct reference to the service or advantage of society in general, or of some particular civil community. And this is in accordance with the law of Ulpian already cited, where he says, sunt enim qucedam publice ntilia, qucedam privatim. Yet we shall see that many of those L. 13, 7, ff. De injur. ; Instil. 2, Ue rerum divis. ; 1. 1, 1, ff. De acquir. rer. domin.; Instit. 12, De rer. divis.; 1. 1, 1, ff. De acquir. vel amitt. possess.; 1. 3, 55, ff. De acquir. rer. dom. ; 1. 2, 9, ff. Ne quid in loco publ. ; 1. 13, 7, ff. De injur. P Domat, Droit Publ. liv. 1, tit. 8. I have given Dr. Strahan's translation, 1722. 1 Domat, ibi. 352 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. things are devoted to the public service and advantage, so that their use is for the benefit of private persons also/ We will now consider the four heads under which Justinian places things extra patrimonium. And, first, of things common to all men. Both Grotius and Pufendorf deduce the appropriation of things which must have been originally common to all men, from the very constitution and organic laws and necessities of the social state ; and such appropriation is, as we have already observed, necessary, not only for the use and enjoyment of things, but for the peace of society, and the very existence of arts, agriculture, and every branch of industry. 8 But it follows from these very principles, that those things, the exclu- sive appropriation of which, either to a portion of mankind or to cer- tain individuals or exclusive purposes, is unnecessary for the objects of the social state, and the purposes above referred to, must remain by natural law common to all men, as they are evidently intended to be. Thus light and air cannot be brought under the exclusive power of any one person, for their use is common to all, and no kind of exclusive appropriation is requisite for their full enjoyment. They are, therefore, not divided among a number of owners as other things are. On the same principles, the Roman Law holds running waters to be common to all men. 1 But this decision does not apply to waters, the exclusive appropriation of which is necessary for certain purposes, such as water inclosed in a pipe or vessel for some particular use. The common right to running water, therefore, exists only in those cases where the quantity of water is so great that its entire exclusive appro- priation is not necessary, having regard to the general objects of the institution of property." In such cases as these, to prevent any man from using and appropriating to himself portions of the water without injuring the common right and enjoyment of others r would be contrary to natural law. x Grotius, however, holds that rivers are capable of being subject to a qualified right of property. He argues that liquids have no boun- daries of their own nature, for a liquid must be limited in its extent by something differing from it in nature, that is to say, some solid. y Now r Donelli Comment. De Jur. Civ. lib. 5, cap. 5, 13. * Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 2, 2 ; Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 4, ch. 4 ; M'Culloch, Princip.of Polit. Econ. ch. 2, 2, pp. 82, 90. 4 Instil, lib. 2, tit. 1, 1. u Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 2, 3. And see the whole of Chap. V. of the 6th book of Pufend. Droit des Gens, with Barbeyrac's notes. * Grot, ibi, 12. y See Co. Litt. 4 a; Blackst. Com. b. 2, ch. 2, p. 18, edit. Coleridge. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 353 a river is bounded in its breadth, though not in its length, for the water flows between its banks. Therefore, though it may be con- sidered as one body of moving water, yet the particles of which that body is composed remain the property of whoever is owner of the banks and bed only while they are within those bounds. 2 This is what in the English law and the writings of jurists is called transient or qualified property. It is also qualified regarding the matter in question by the rule of natural law, that no man can without injus- tice prevent another from using that which is of such a nature that all men may use it without injury to each other and with equal advantage to each. 3 Thus the owner of a river or part of it could not justly forbid persons navigating it or being lawfully on its banks, from drinking and otherwise using portions of the water without any injury to his rights and enjoyment of the stream. The same principles explain the rule cujus est solum, ejus est usque ad cesium, adopted by the English from the civil law. b It was observed by Lord Ellen- borough, that if it were trespass to interfere with a column of air superincumbent on a close, an action of trespass might be brought against an aeronaut by the owner of every field over which he passed in his balloon. Barbeyrac, in his notes on Grotius, shows that air is susceptible of being subjected to a qualified right of property analogous to that over running water, so far as exclusive appropriation is essential to the enjoyment of rights over other things.' 1 The same doctrines hold good as to light, portions of which may be subjected to a transient right of property as accessory to the enjoyment of other property. These principles will assist us to comprehend the great and celebrated question of the nature of the common rights of mankind over the high seas. The following passage from Vattel gives so good a view of the subject that its length will not be regretted. " The open sea is not of such a nature as to admit the holding pos- session of it, since no settlement can be formed on it so as to hinder others from passing. But a nation powerful at sea may forbid others to fish in it and to navigate it, declaring that she appropriates to herself the dominion over it, and that she will destroy the vessels that 1 Grot, ubi sup. ; and see 1. 2, ch. 3, 7, &c. ; Vinnii Comment, ad Instit. lib. 2, tit. 1, 2, num. 2. Grot, ibi, liv. 2, ch. 2. 11. b L. 21, 2, ff. Quod vi aut clam. c Pickering v. Rudd, 4 Campb. 219. d Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 2, 3, note 3,4; Pufend. Devoir de I'Homme et du Cit. liv. 1, ch. 12, 6, Barbeyrac; and 4, note 2. A A 354 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. shall dare to appear in it without her permission. Let us see whether she has right to do this." " It is manifest that the use of the open sea, which consists in navi- gation and fishing, is innocent and inexhaustible ; that is to say, he who navigates or fishes in the open sea, does no injury to any one, and the sea, in these two respects, is sufficient for all mankind. Now nature does not give to man a right of appropriating to himself things that may be innocently used, and that are inexhaustible and sufficient for all. For since those things, while common to all, are sufficient to supply the wants of each, whoever should, to the exclusion of all par- ticipants, attempt to render himself sole proprietor of them, would unreasonably wrest the bounteous gifts of nature from the parties excluded. The earth no longer furnishing without culture the things necessary or useful to the human race, who were extremely multiplied, it became necessary to introduce the right of property, in order that each might apply himself with more success to the cultivation of what had fallen to his share, and multiply by his labour the necessaries and conveniences of life. It is for this reason the law of nature approves the rights of dominion and property, which put an end to the primitive manners of living in common. But this reason cannot apply to things which are in themselves inexhaustible ; and consequently it cannot furnish any just grounds for seizing the exclusive possession of them. If the free and common use of a thing of this nature were prejudicial or dangerous to a nation, the care of their own safety would authorize them to reduce that thing under their own dominion, if possible, in order to restrict the use of it by such precautions as prudence might dictate to them. But this is not the case with the open sea, on which people may sail and fish without the least prejudice to any person whatsoever, and without putting any one in danger. No nation, there- fore has a right to take possession of the open sea, or claim the sole use of it, to the exclusion of other nations. The kings of Portugal formerly arrogated to themselves the empire of the seas of Guinea and the East Indies,* but the other maritime powers gave themselves little trouble about such a pretension." " The right of navigating and fishing in the open sea being then a right common to all men, the nation that attempts to exclude another from that advantage does her.an injury, and furnishes her with suffi- cient grounds for commencing hostilities, since nature authorizes a nation to repel an injury, that is, to make use of force against whoever would deprive her of her rights." e See Grotius, Mare Liberum, and Selden, Mare Clausum, lib. 1, cap. 17. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 355 " Nay, more, a nation which, without a legitimate claim, would arrogate to itself an exclusive right to the sea, and support its preten- sions by force, does an injury to all nations ; it infringes their common right ; and they are justifiable in forming a general combination against it, in order to repress such an attempt. Nations have the greatest interest in causing the law of nations, which is the basis of their tran- quillity, to be universally respected. If any one openly tramples it under foot, they all may and ought to rise up against him ; and, by uniting their forces to chastise the common enemy, they will discharge their duty towards themselves and towards human society, of which they are members (Prelim, s. 22). However, as every one is at liberty to renounce his right, a nation may acquire exclusive rights of naviga- tion and fishing, by treaties, in which other nations renounce, in its favour, the rights they derive from nature. The latter are obliged to observe their treaties; and the nation they have favoured has a right to maintain by force the possession of its advantages. Thus the House of Austria has renounced, in favour of England and Holland, the right of sending vessels from the Netherlands to the East Indies. In Grotius, De Jure Belli et Pacis, lib. 2, cap. 3, s. 15, may be found many instances of similar treaties." f " As the rights of navigation and of fishing, and other rights which may be exercised on the sea, belong to the class of those rights of mere ability (jura merce facultatis) which are imprescriptible (s. 95), they cannot be lost for want of use. Consequently, although a nation should happen to have been from time immemorial in sole possession of the navigation or fishery in certain seas, it cannot, on this founda- tion, claim an exclusive right to those advantages. For though others have not made use of their common right to navigation and fishery in those seas, it does not thence follow that they have had any intention to renounce it ; and they are entitled to exert it whenever they think proper." " But it may happen that the non-usage of the right may assume the nature of a consent or tacit agreement, and thus become a title in favour of one nation against another. When a nation that is in pos- session of the navigation and fishery in certain tracts of sea, claims an exclusive right to them, and forbids all participation on the part of other nations, if the others obey that prohibition with sufficient marks of acquiescence, they tacitly renounce their own right in favour of that nation, and establish a new right, which she may afterwards law- fully maintain against them, especially when it is confirmed by long use." f See Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 3, 15 ; and see the notes by Barbeyrac. A A2 356 THE PUBLIC LAW OP THINGS. " The various uses of the sea near the coasts render it very suscep- tible of property. It furnishes fish, shells, pearls, amber, &c. Now, in all these respects its use is not inexhaustible ; wherefore the nation to whom the coast belongs may appropriate to themselves, and convert to their own profit, an advantage which nature has so placed within their reach as to enable them conveniently to take possession of it, in the same manner as they possessed themselves of the dominion of the land they inhabit. Who can doubt that the pearl fisheries of Bahrem and Ceylon may lawfully become property; and though, where the catching of fish is the only object, the fishery appears less liable to be exhausted ; yet if a nation have on their coast a particular fishery of a profitable nature, and of which they may become masters, shall they not be permitted to appropriate to themselves that bounteous gift of nature, as an appendage to the country they possess, and to reserve to themselves the great advantages which their commerce may thence derive in case there be sufficient abundance of fish to furnish the neighbouring nations. But if, so far from taking possession of it, the nation has once acknowledged the common right of other nations to come and fish there, it can no longer exclude them from it; it has left that fishery in its primitive freedom, at least with respect to those who have been accustomed to take advantage of it. The English not having originally taken exclusive possession of the herring fishery on their coasts, it is become common to them with other nations. "A nation may appropriate to herself those things of which the free and common use would be prejudicial or dangerous to her. This is a second reason for which governments extend their dominion over the sea along their coasts, as far as they are able to protect their right. It is of considerable importance to the safety and welfare of the state, that a general liberty be not allowed to all comers to approach so near their possessions, especially with ships of war, as to hinder the ap- proach of trading nations, and molest their navigation. During the war between Spain and the united provinces, James I., king of England, marked out, along his coasts, certain boundaries within which he declared that he would not suffer any of the powers at war to pursue their enemies, nor even allow their armed vessels to stop and observe the ships that should enter or sail out of the ports. 8 These parts of the sea, thus subject to a nation, are comprehended in her territory, nor must any one navigate them without her consent. But to vessels that are not liable to suspicion, she cannot, without a breach of duty, refuse permission to approach for harmless purposes, since it is a duty incumbent on every proprietor to allow to strangers a free pas- * Selden's Mare Clausum, lib. 2. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 357 sage, even by land, when it may be done without damage or danger. It is true, that the state itself is sole judge of what is proper to be done in every particular case that occurs; and if it judge amiss it is to blame; but the others are bound to submit. It is otherwise, how- ever, in case of necessity ; as, for instance, where a vessel is obliged to enter a road which belongs to you, in order to shelter herself from a tempest. In this case, the right of entering wherever we can, pro- vided we cause no damage, or that we repair any damage done, is, as we shall show more at large, a remnant of the primitive freedom, of which no man can be supposed to have divested himself, and the vessel may lawfully enter in spite of you, if you unjustly refuse her permission." " It is not easy to determine to what distance a nation may extend its rights over the sea by which it is surrounded. Bodinus h pretends that, according to the common right of all maritime nations, the prince's dominion extends to the distance of thirty leagues from the coast. But this exact determination can only be founded on a general consent of nations, which it would be difficult to prove. Each state may, on this head, make what regulations it pleases, so far as respects the transactions of the citizens with each other, or their concerns with the sovereign; but between nation and nation, all that can rea- sonably be said is, that in general the dominion of the state over the neighbouring- sea extends as far as her safety renders it necessary, and her power is able to assert it; since, on the one hand she cannot appro- priate to herself a thing that is common to all mankind, such as the sea, except so far as she has need of it for some lawful end ( 281), and, on the other, it would be a vain and ridiculous pretension to claim a right which she were wholly unable to assert. The fleets of England have given room to her kings to claim the empire of the seas which surround that island, even as far as the opposite coasts. 1 Selden relates a solemn act, j by which it appears that, in the time of Edward I. that empire was acknowledged by the greatest part of the maritime nations of Europe; and the Republic of the United Provinces acknowledged it, in some measure, by the treaty of Breda, in 1667, at least so far as related to the honour of the flag. But solidly to establish a right of such extent, it were necessary to prove very clearly the ex- press or tacit consent of all the powers concerned. The French have h In his Republic, book 1, cli. 10; Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 3, 10, num. 2 ; Wolf, Jus Gent. $ 129132. Lord Stowell held, that for the sea out of reach of cannon shot, common use is presumed. The Twee Gebroeders, 3 Rob. Rep. 336; Kent, Com. vol. 1, lect. 2, p. 29. 1 See Selden 's Mare Clausum. i Ibi, lib. 2, cap. 28. 358 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. never agreed to this pretension of England, and in that very treaty of Breda just mentioned, Louis XIV. would not even suffer the channel to be called the English Channel or the British Sea. The Republic of Venice claims the empire of the Adriatic; and every body knows the ceremony annually performed upon that account. In confirmation of this right, we are referred to the examples of Uladislaus, king of Naples, of the emperor Frederic III., and of some of the kings of Hungary, who asked permission of the Venetians for their vessels to pass through that sea. k That the empire of the Adriatic belongs to the Republic to a certain distance from her own coasts, in the places of which she can keep possession, and of which the possession is im- portant to her own safety, appears to me incontestable; but I doubt very much whether any power is at present disposed to acknow- ledge her sovereignty over the whole Adriatic sea. Such pretensions to empire are respected as long as the nation that makes them is able to assert them by force ; but they vanish of course on the decline of her power. At present the whole space of the sea within cannon shot of the coast is considered as making a part of the territory; and for that reason, a vessel taken under the cannon of a neutral fortress is not a lawful prize." " The shores of the sea incontestably belong to the nation that pos- sesses the country of which they are a part, and they belong to the class of public things. If civilians have set them down as things common to all mankind (res communes), it is only in regard to their use ; and we are not thence to conclude that they considered them as independent of the empire. The very contrary appears from a great number of laws. Ports and harbours are manifestly an appendage to and even a part of the country, and consequently are the property of the nation. Whatever is said of the land itself will equally apply to them, so far as respects the consequences of the domain and of the empire." "All we have said of the parts of the sea near the coast may be said more particularly, and with much greater reason, of roads, bays, and straits, as still more capable of being possessed, and of greater import- ance to the safety of the country. 1 But I speak of bays and straits of small extent, and not of those great tracts of sea to which these names ' ~ are sometimes given, as Hudson's Bay and the Straits of Magellan, over which empire cannot extend, and still less can a right of property. "A bay whose entrance can be defended maybe possessed, and ren- dered subject to the laws of the sovereign; and it is of importance that it should be so, since the country might be much more easily insulted k See ibi, lib. 1, cap. 16. 1 See the Treaty of the Dardanelles, 1841 ; Wheaton, Hist, of the Law of Nations, p. 585. And see Martens, Droit des Gens, liv. 2, ch. 1, 42. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 359 in such a place than on a coast that lies exposed to the winds and the impetuosity of the waves." " It must be remarked with regard to straits, that when they serve for a communication between two seas, the navigation of which is common to all or several nations, the nation which possesses the strait cannot refuse the other a passage through it, provided that passage be innocent, and attended with no danger to herself. By refusing it without just reasons, she would deprive those nations of an advantage granted them by nature ; and, indeed, the right to such a passage is a remnant of the primitive liberty enjoyed by all mankind. Nothing but the care of his own safety can authorize the owner of the strait to make use of certain precautions, and to require certain formalities, commonly established by the customs of nations. He has a right to levy a moderate tax on the vessels that pass, partly on account of the inconvenience they give him by obliging him to be on his guard ; partly as a return for the safety he procures them, by pro- tecting them from their enemies, by keeping pirates at a distance, and by defraying the expense attendant on the support of lighthouses, sea- marks, and other things necessary to the safety of mariners." 1 Thus the king of Denmark requires a custom at the straits of the Sound. Such right ought to be founded on the same reasons, and subject to the same rules, as the tolls established on land or on a river. ( 103 and 104.)" " It is necessary to mention the right to wrecks a right which was the wretched offspring of barbarism, and which has almost everywhere, fortunately, disappeared with its parent. Justice and humanity cannot allow of it, except in those cases only where the proprietor of the effects saved from a wreck cannot possibly be discovered. In such cases those effects belong to the person who is the first to take pos- session of them, or to the sovereign, if the law reserves them for him." " If a sea is entirely inclosed by the territories of a nation, and has no other communication with the ocean than by a channel, of which that nation may take possession, it appears that such a sea is no less capable of being occupied, and becoming property, than the land-; and it ought to follow the fate of the country that surrounds it. The Mediterranean in former times was absolutely inclosed within the terri- tories of the Romans; and that people, by rendering- themselves masters of the straits which joins it to the ocean, might subject the Mediter- ranean to their empire, and assume the dominion over it. They did not by such procedure injure the rights of other nations; a particular sea being manifestly designed by nature for the use of the countries n> And see Wolf, Jus Gent. 214; Grot. Droit de la Guerre, 1. 2, tit. 3, 14; Vinnii Comm. ad Inst. lib. 2, tit. 1, 1. 360 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. and nations that surround it. Besides, by barring the entrance of the Mediterranean against all suspected vessels, the Romans, by one single stroke, secured the immense extent of their coasts; and this reason was sufficient to authorize them to take possession of it. And as it had no communication but with the states which belonged to them, they were at liberty to permit or prohibit the entrance into it, in the same manner as into any of their towns or provinces." " When a nation takes possession of certain parts of the sea, it takes possession of the empire over them, as well as of the domain, on the same principle which we advanced in treating of the land. ( 205.) These parts of the sea are within the jurisdiction of the nation, and a part of its territory. The sovereign commands there; he makes laws, and may punish those who violate them : in a word, he has the same right there as on land, and in general every right which the law of the state allow him." " It is, however, true that the empire and the domain, or property, are not inseparable in their own nature, even in a sovereign state." As a nation may possess the domain or property of a tract of land or sea, without having the sovereignty of it, so it may likewise happen that she shall possess the sovereignty of a place of which the property or the domain, with respect to use, belongs to some other nation. But it is always presumed that when a nation possesses the useful domain (dominium vtile) of any place whatsoever, she has also the higher domain and empire, or the sovereignty. (205.) We cannot, however, from the possession of the empire, infer with equal probability a co- existent possession of the useful domain ; for a nation may have good reasons for claiming the empire over a country, and particularly over a tract of sea, without pretending to have any property in it, or any useful domain. The English have never claimed the property of all the seas over which they have claimed the empire." Ulpian and Celsus distinctly hold the seas to be common to all man- kind ; and the celebrated declaration of the Emperor Antoninus, that " though he was the lord of the world, the law only was the ruler of the sea," has been held to convey the same doctrine. p The contrary was powerfully maintained by Selden; while the freedom and community of the seas were vindicated by Grotius in his treatise De Mare n See book 2, 83. And see Grotius, liv. 2, ch. 3, and n. 13, by Barbeyrac. Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 23. PL. 13, ff. Communia praediorum ; 1. 3, 1, ff. Ne quid in loc. publ. ; 1. 9, ff. ad Leg. Rhodiam ; Gothofredus, in his Opusc. De Imperio Maris, explains this law somewhat differently. > The treatises of these two great men are entitled Mare Clausum and De Mare Libero. Wheaton, Hist, of the Law of Nations, pp. 152, 153 ; Kent, Com. vol. 1, p. 27. And see Bynkershoek, De Domin. Maris Dissertatio. See also Hargrave, Law Tracts, 10 ; Co. Litt. 440, note 1 ; Martens, Droit des Gens, 1. 2, ch. 1, 43. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 361 Pufendorf concurs in the views of Grotius/ which are also adopted by Kent. 3 " It is difficult," says the latter, " to draw any precise or determinate conclusion, amidst the variety of opinions, as to the distance to which a state may lawfully extend its exclusive do- minion over the sea adjoining its territories, and beyond those portions of the sea which are embraced by harbours, gulfs, bays and estuaries, and over which its jurisdiction unquestionably extends.' All that can reasonably be asserted is, that the dominion of the sovereign of the shore over the contiguous sea extends as far as is requisite for his safety and for some lawful end. A more extended dominion must rest entirely on force and maritime supremacy. According to the current of modern authority, the general territorial jurisdiction extends into the sea as far as a cannon shot will reach, and no further ; and this is generally calculated to be a marine league : and the Congress of the United States have recognized this limitation, by authorizing the dis- trict courts to take cognizance of all captures made within a marine league of the American shores."" The same authority holds that no nation has any right of jurisdiction at sea, except it be over the per- sons of its own subjects, in its own public and private vessels ; and so far territorial jurisdiction may be considered as preserved, for the vessels of a nation are in many respects considered as part of its terri- tory, and persons on board are protected and governed by the law of the country to which the vessel belongs. They may be punished for offences against the municipal laws of the state committed on board its public and private vessels at sea, and on board its public vessels in foreign ports." This jurisdiction is confined to the ship; and no one ship has a right to prohibit the approach of another at sea, or to draw round her a line of territorial jurisdiction within which no other is at liberty to intrude. Every vessel in time of peace has a right to con- sult its own safety and convenience, and to pursue its own course and business, without being disturbed when it does not violate the rights of others." " It was declared," as we are informed by Kent, in the case of Le Louis* that " maritime states claim, upon a principle just in itself and T Pufend. Droit des Geus, liv. 4, ch. 5. Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 2, p. 2631. 1 Azuni, On Mark. Law, vol. 1, p. 206. Kent, ibi, p. 29; Bynkerskoek, Quaest. Jur. Publ. c. 8; Vattel, 1. 1, c. 23, 289; Act of Congress, June 5th, 1794, c. 50; 3 Rob. Rep. 336. * Grotius, b. 2, c. 3, 10, 13; Rutterford, b. 2, c. 9; Vattel, b. 1, c. 19, 216; Forbes v. Cochrane, 1 Barn. & Cress. 418 ; Wheaton, Elem. of International Law, 110. Kent, ibi, pp. 26, 27 ; The Mariana Flora, Wheaton, 38. 1 Dodson, Adm. Rep. 245. 362 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. temperately applied, a right of visitation and inquiry within those parts of the ocean adjoining to their shores. They were to be considered as parts of the territory for various domestic purposes, and the right was admitted by the courtesy of nations. The English hovering laws were founded on that right. The stat. 9 Geo. II. c. 35, prohibited foreign goods to be transhipped within four leagues of the coast without pay- ment of duties; and the act of Congress of March 2, 1779, c. 128, sees. 2628, contained the same prohibition; and the exercise of jurisdiction to that distance, for the safety and protection of the reve- nue laws, was declared by the Supreme Court, in Church v. Hubbard* to be conformable to the laws and usages of nations." b We will now proceed to the second head of things, that is to say, things public. The civil law gives the denomination of res publiccs to things which belong to a commonwealth, so that the citizens and all men have a public common right to the use of them. Such are rivers, ports, and shores of the sea and banks of rivers. Therefore, by the Roman law, all men have a common right of fishing in rivers and ports. d The same principle applies to the shore of the sea, which is defined by Justinian to extend quatenus hybernus fluctus maximus excurrit* Thus Justinian lays it down that the use of the shores of the sea is public and common to all men as the sea itself is ; therefore it is lawful for men to build there, and to dry nets, as well as to draw up anything from the sea upon the shore. But the property of the shore may be understood to be in no one, and so partaking of the same legal nature as the sea, and the soil or sand under it. f So he holds that the use of the banks of a river is public, jure gentium, as the river is. Thus vessels may touch there, and any one may tie ropes to the trees that grow there, and put down burthens, but the property of the banks is vested in those who are proprietors of the land whereof they form part; for which reason the trees growing upon the banks belong to those proprietors. 5 These general rules of Justinian regarding the sea shore are subject to some qualifications. Thus ScaBVola says, that it is lawful to build on the sea shore so far as the public utility will permit, and Celsus declares that the shores of the Roman territory belong to the Roman a 2 Cranch, 187. b Kent, Comment, vol. 1, p. 31. c Voet ad Pand. lib. 1, tit. 8, 8; Vinnii Com. ad Instit. lib. 1, tit. 2, 2. d Instit. lib. 1, tit. 2, 2. e Ibi, 3. f Ibi, 5. And see stat. 1 Jac. c. 23 ; 10 Car. I. Sess. 2, c. 24. The principle of the former statute was probably derived from the civil law. f Ibi, 4. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 363 people. 11 But by the Roman law the sea shore is not vested in the state, as in the Feudal and English law, which place the shores inter jura regalia. 1 The English law, however, gives a common public right of fishing to the people of England in the sea and its creeks or arms. J Such are the doctrines of the Roman law regarding things of this class, which are useful to be known because they are frequently used in questions of public law. The territories or country of a state have some legal analogy to the public things of the civil law. For though the land is, for the most part, divided among different owners, and subject to various rights of property, yet the people, as such, have a general right of habitation, use, and enjoyment of the country. On this principle a whole country is said to belong to a nation, and individuals are restrained by a variety of municipal laws from so using their private rights of ownership over land, and water, and buildings, as to injure the public rights of society in general ; and they are even compelled to part with their private property, on adequate compensation, when the benefit of the public requires this sacrifice. k Practically, however, this general right of the community is chiefly confined to public places, which are public in such wise that indivi- duals have the use of them, subject to their doing nothing to injure the rights of the community. 1 Such are public squares, streets, roads, and the like, which are within the province of public law. m These reflections are well confirmed by Vattel. He observes that the earth was given by God to mankind in general. But their multi- plication made it impossible for the land to be possessed by all in common. It therefore became necessary for nations to settle in parti- cular places, and appropriate to themselves certain portions of the earth and cultivate them." Hence came rights of property, and domi- nion over land. " The country," he continues, " which a nation inhabits that country is the settlement of the nation, and it has an exclusive and peculiar right over it. This right compre- hends two things I. the Domain (dominium), by virtue of which the nation alone may use this country for the supply of its necessities, may dispose of it as it thinks proper, and derive from it every advantage it h L. 4, ff. Ne quid in loco publico ; ibi, 1. 3. 1 Liber Feudorum, lib. 2, tit. 56; Co. Litt. 440, note 1. J Co. Litt. p. 261 a; Lord Hale, De Jure Maris, p. 11 ; and see stat. 59 Geo. III. c. 109, s. 38. k On the latter subject, see Bynkershoek, Quaest. Jur. Publ. lib. 2, cap. 15. 1 Donelli Comment. De Jur. Civ. lib. 2, c. 5, 12; 1. 2, ff. Ne quid in loc. publ. " Donelli, ibi, 13. n And see Hermogenianus, 1. 5, ff. De Just, et Jur. Ex hoc jure gentium . . discrete gentes ; regna condita ; dominia distincta ; agris termini positi .... 364 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. is capable of yielding; II. The Empire (imperium), or right of sove- reign command, by which the nation directs and regulates at its plea- sure everything that passes in the country." This last position must however be understood subject to the divers modifications of the sove- reign power arising from the constitution, or fundamental laws of each particular state. "When a nation," continues our author, "takes possession of a country to which no prior owner can lay claim, it is considered as acquiring the empire, or sovereignty of it, at the same time with the domain. For since the nation is free and independent, it can have no intention, in settling in a country, to leave to others the right of command, or any of those rights that constitute sovereignty. The whole space over which a nation extends its government is called its territory." "If a number of free families, scattered over an independent country, come to unite for the purpose of forming a nation or state, they all together acquire the sovereignty over the whole country they inhabit ; for they were previously in possession of the domain, a proportional share of it belonging to each individual family ; and since they are willing to form together a political society, and establish a public authority, which every member of the society shall be bound to obey, it is evidently their intention to attribute to that public authority the right of command over the whole country. All mankind have an equal right to things that have not yet fallen into the possession of any one, and those things belong to the person who first takes possession of them. When, therefore, a nation finds a country uninhabited and without an owner, it may lawfully take possession of it, and after it has sufficiently made known its will in this respect, it cannot be deprived of it by another nation. Thus navigators going on voyages of discovery, furnished with a commission from their sovereign, and meeting with islands or other lands in a desert state, have taken pos- session of them in the name of their nation, and this title has been usually respected, provided it was soon after followed by a real possession." " But it is questioned whether a nation can, by the bare act of taking possession, appropriate to itself countries which it does not really occupy, and thus engross a much greater extent of territory than it is able to people or cultivate. It is not difficult to determine that such a pretension would be an absolute infringement of the natural rights of men, and repugnant to the views of nature, which, having destined the whole earth to supply the wants of mankind in general, gives no nation a right to appropriate to itself a country, except for the purpose of making use of it, and not of hindering others from deriving advan- Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 18. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 365 tage from it. The law of nations will therefore not acknowledge the o o property and sovereignty of a nation over any uninhabited countries, except those of which it has really taken actual possession, in which it has formed settlements, or of which it makes actual use. In effect, when navigators have met with desert countries in which those of other nations had, in their transient visits, erected some monument to show their having taken possession of them, they have paid little regard to that empty ceremony There is another cele- brated question, to which the discovery of the new world has princi- pally given rise. It is asked whether a nation may lawfully take possession of some part of a vast country, in which there are none but erratic nations, whose scanty population is incapable of occupying the whole. We have already observed (. 81), in establishing the obliga- tion to cultivate the earth, that those nations cannot exclusively appro- priate to themselves more land than they have occasion for, or more than they are able to settle and cultivate. Their unsettled habitation in those immense regions cannot be accounted a true and legal pos- session; and the people of Europe, too closely pent up at home, finding land of which the savages stood in no particular need, and of which they made no actual and constant use, were lawfully entitled to take possession of it, and settle it with colonies. The earth, as we have already observed, belongs to mankind in general, and was designed to furnish them with subsistence ; if each nation had from the begin- ning resolved to appropriate to itself a vast country, that the people might live only by hunting, fishing, and wild fruits, our globe would not be sufficient to maintain a tenth part of its present inhabitants." " We do not therefore deviate from the views of nature, in confining the Indians within narrower limits. p However, we cannot help praising the moderation of the English Puritans, who first settled in New England ; who, notwithstanding their being furnished with a charter from their sovereign, purchased of the Indians the lands of which they intended to take possession.* 1 This laudable example was followed by William Penn, and the colony of Quakers that he conducted to Penn- sylvania. " When a nation takes possession of a distant country, and settle a colony there, that country, though separated from the principal esta- blishment, or mother country, naturally becomes a part of the state, equally with its ancient possessions. Whenever, therefore, the political laws or treaties make no distinction between them, every thing said of the territory of a nation must also extend to its colonies." 1 " P See as to Indian lands, Kent, Comment, vol. 1, p. 257, &c. i History of the English Colonies in North America. r Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 18. 366 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. The occupation of territories by nations, considered as bodies politic and juridical persons, rests on the principles of natural law, regarding the acquisition of vacant things belonging to no one, by the original title of occupation ; s which, in countries already occupied, may be qualified and restricted by municipal laws ;* but, among independent nations, rests on the law of nature, because they have no common municipal laws. And many questions in the law of nations, regarding or arising out of the occupation of territories, may be decided or eluci- dated by means of the civil law." Grotius examines the question whether, when rivers change their course, they at the same time change the boundaries of states, and whether that which a river adds to its banks, augments the territory of the state on the side on which the addition takes place. He divides lands, with reference to the nature of their boundaries, into three classes. I. Lands specifically assigned by measurement and artificial boundaries, and metes and bounds, which Florentinus denominates limited (agri limitati).* II. Those which are assigned in gross, that is to say, limited in extent, as to so many acres, but without specific boundaries and landmarks. 7 III. Lands bounded by natural limits, and called agri arcifinii. 2 Barbeyrac, in his notes on Grotius and Pufendorf, expresses an opinion that they did not correctly give the meaning of the ancient writers who furnish this classification ; but he admits that the principle derived from the distinction, between lands defined by artificial limits or measurements, and the agri arcifinii, is correct. With regard to the lands of the two first classes, the change of the course of a river does not alter the boundaries, and whatever is added by alluvion is vacant, and belongs, by the law of nations, to whoever occupies or takes possession of it, because the extent and limits of the land are fixed and determined.* With regard to the third class of lands, i. e. agri arcifinii, a river 8 Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Nat. et Eccles. Publ. torn. 1, lib. 4, ch. 3, 279, 284; Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 3, and notes by Barbeyrac. Quod ante nullius est, id naturali ratione occupanti conceditur. Instit. lib. 2, tit. 1, 12 ; 1. 3, ff. De acqui- rendo rerum dominio. 1 Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 3, 5 ; Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 4, ch. 6, | 3, and note by Barbeyrac. Instit. lib. 2, tit. 1, 1 1 17 ; and see the Comment of Vinnius ; Pandect, lib. 41, tit. 1, De acquirendo rerum dominio; and see the Comment of Voet, 1. 41, t. 1. * L, 16, ff. De aquir. rerum domin. And see Litt. sect. 36. 1 See Litt. sect 44. 1 Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 3, 16 ; Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 4, ch. 7, 1, and Barbeyrac 's notes; Zallinger, Inst. Jur. Nat. et Eccles. Publ. vol. 1, lib. 4, cap. 3, 274. Ibi. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 367 which bounds them, changes the boundaries of the territory and juris- diction, by gradually altering its course; and, whatever it adds on one side, belongs to the territory on that side, because the two states between which the river flows are presumed to have origirially taken the center of the river as their natural boundary. b This is so where the change of the course of the river is gradual. For there the change of its parts does not destroy its identity, but leaves it the same. But it is otherwise when the change is sudden and entire, for in that case, if the people into whose country the river has gone do not consent to lose part of their land, for the purpose of retaining the natural limits of the waters, the boundary is presumed to be the middle of the bed which the river has left. d If the river flow between two states, and belong entirely to one of them, the islands formed therein belong entirely to that state; but the better opinion is, that the alluvion on the other side appertains to the state on that side. 8 If, on the other hand, the river belongs to neither state, the islands and alluvions formed there are vacant, and will belong to whoever occupies them. But the state nearest to a new island, and that to whose land an alluvial addi- tion grows, must be presumed to take possession rather than the other state/ And if the boundary be in the middle of the river, and an island be formed in the middle, it will belong to both states in equal shares ; but if it be nearest to one bank, the greater part or the whole will belong to the state on that side. 8 If a river divide into branches in one place, and those branches join in another, the land thus enclosed, which becomes a sort of island, remains the property of its former owner. h It is not lawful to make on a river any works calculated to alter the course of the water, and throw it on the opposite bank. But each party may protect his own property, and prevent the current from carrying away his ground. In general, no works can be constructed on a river, or elsewhere, prejudicial to the rights of others. If a river belong- to a nation, and another have an undoubted right of navigating it, the former must not construct dykes or mills which would cause the river b Pufend. liv. 4, ch. 7, 11. c Quapropter cujns rei species eadem consistent, rem quoque eandem esse existimari. L. 76, ff. De Judiciis. d Pufend. ibi. e Ibi. f Ibi. e Instit. lib. 2, tit. 1, 22, and the Comment of Vinnius ; 1. 7, 3, ff. De acquir. rerum domin.; 1. 1, 6,4, ff. De Fluminibus; ibi, 10; Voet ad Pand. lib. 41, tit. 1, 14. h Instit. ibi, 368 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS.. to be no longer navigable. Its right is in this case a limited owner- ship, so that such right can only be exercised without prejudice to the rights of others. 1 Alluvion is thus defined in the civil law. Est alluvio incrementum latens, quo quid ita paulatim agro adjicitur ut intelligi nequeat quantum quoquo temporis momenta accedat. k It is a mode of acquisition by natural law, called accession, which is a species of occupancy. For occupancy is either simple or consequent. The former is, where a man takes possession, a's proprietor, of any thing which is the property of no one. It becomes his by right of occupancy, for, as Justinian says, Quod ante nullius est, id naturali ratione occupanti conceditur} The latter occurs, 1st, where any one's property produces fruit; and 2ndly, when anything adheres to or acceeds to and becomes part of the pro- perty of any one, for there the addition or increase is acquired by him as an accession to his property. And we have seen that alluvion is a means of acquiring territory to states," as well as simple occupancy. With regard to lakes, Vattel gives us the following principles of Public Law, " What we have said of rivers and streams may be easily applied to lakes. Every lake, entirely included in a country, belongs to the nation that is the proprietor of that country; for, in taking pos- session of a territory, a nation is considered as having appropriated to itself everything included in it; and as it seldom happens that the pro- perty of a lake of any considerable extent falls to the share of jndivi- duals, it remains common to the nation. If this lake is situated between two states, it is presumed to be divided between them at the middle, while there is no title, no constant and manifest custom, to de- termine otherwise." " What has been said of the right of alluvion, in speaking of rivers, is also to be understood as applying to lakes. When a lake, which bounds a state, belongs entirely to it, every increase in the extent of that lake falls under the same predicament as the lake itself; but it is necessary that the increase should be insensible, as that of land in alluvion, and moreover, that it be real, constant, and complete. To explain myself more fully, I speak of insensible increase; this is the reverse of alluvion ; the question here relates to the increase of a lake, 1 Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 22, 171, 172. k Voet ad Pand. lib. 41, tit. 1, 15; Instit. lib. 2, tit. 1, $ 20; 1. 7, 1, ff. De acquir. rerum domin. 1 Instit. lib. 2, tit. 1, ^12. m Vinnii Com. ad Instit. et not. Heineccii, lib. 2, tit. 1, ^ 2, num. 4. n Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 4, ch. 7, 11 ; Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 22. Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 18, 207; Martens, Droit des Gens, liv. 2, ch. 1. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 369 as in the other case to an increase of soil. If this increase be not insen- sible, if the lake, overflowing its banks, inundates a large tract of land, this new portion of the lake, this tract thus covered with water, still belongs to its former owner. Upon what principles can we found the acquisition of it in behalf of the owner of the lake. The space is very easily identified, though it has changed its nature ; and it is too considerable to admit a presumption that the owner had no inten- tion to preserve it to himself, notwithstanding the changes that might happen to it." " 2. But if the lake insensibly undermines a part of the opposite territory, destroys it, and renders it impossible to be known, by fixing itself there, and adding it to its bed, that part of the territory is lost to its former owner, it no longer exists, and the whole of the lake thus increased still belongs to the same state as before." " 3. If some of the lands bordering on the lake are only overflowed at high water, this transient accident cannot produce any change in their dependence. The reason why the soil, which the lake invades by little and little, belongs to the owner of the lake, and is lost to its former proprietor, is because the proprietor has no other boundary than the lake, nor any other marks than its banks, to ascertain how far his possession extend. If the water advances insensibly, he loses; if it retires in like manner, he gains; such must have been the inten- tion of the nations who have respectively appropriated to themselves the lake and the adjacent lands; it can scarcely be supposed that they had any other intention. But, a territory overflowed for a time is not confounded with the rest of the lake ; it can still be recognized ; and the owner may still retain his right of property in it. Were it otherwise, a town overflowed by a lake would become subject to a different government during the inundation, and return to its former sovereign as soon as the waters were dried up." u 4. For the same reasons, if the waters of the lake, penetrating by an opening into the neighbouring country, there form a bay, or new lake, joined to the first by a canal, this new body of water and the canal, belong to the owner of the country in which they are formed. For the boundaries are easily ascertained ; and we are not to presume an intention of relinquishing so considerable a tract of land in case of its happening to be invaded by the waters of an adjoining lake." " It must be observed, that we here treat the question as arising between two states ; it is to be decided by other principles when it relates to proprietors who are members of the same state. In the latter case, it is not merely the bounds of the soil, but also its nature and use, that determine the possession of it. An individual, who pos- sesses a field on the borders of a lake, cannot enjoy it as a field when B B 370 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. it is overflowed; and a person who has, for instance, the right offish- ing in the lake, may exert his right in this new extent ; if the waters retire, the field is restored to the use of its former owner. If the lake penetrates by an opening into the low lands in its neighbourhood, and there forms a permanent inundation, this new lake belongs to the public, because all lakes belong to the public." " The same principles show, that if the lake insensibly form an ac- cession of lands on its banks, either by retiring or in any other manner, this increase of land belongs to the country which it joins, when that country has no other boundary than the lake. It is the same thing as alluvion on the banks of a river." " But if the lake happened to be suddenly dried up, either totally or in a great part of it, the bed would remain in the possession of the so- vereign of the lake; the nature of the soil, so easily known, sufficiently marking out the limits." "The empire or jurisdiction over lakes and rivers is subject to the same rules as the property of them, in all the cases which we have examined. Each state naturally possesses it over the whole or the part of which it possesses the domain. We have seen ( 245) that the nation, or its sovereign, commands in all places in its possession."? With regard to acquisition by simple occupancy, we must observe that the law of nations agrees with the Roman law in the following respect : The occupation of vacant territories and jurisdiction by states, is grounded on the same principles as the acquisition of private property by occupancy. And territory is not acquired in this way by a state unless the possession has, in fact, taken place, and the act of taking possession has concurred with the manifest intention of appropriating the thing : r and so, by the Civil Law, the acquisition of things by occupancy must be made corpore et animo, that is to say, by an out- ward act, signifying an intention to possess, 3 though the outward act of possession need not be by act of physical contact, such as taking into the hand with respect to movables, or treading with the feet with respect to land ; for any species of possession, or, as the ancients express it, custodia, or some physical act importing ownership, is a sufficient appropriation. 1 These principles show that a state may take, by occupancy, an entire vacant country, without actual custody i> Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 22, 274278. r Martens, Droit des Gens, liv. 2, ch. 1, 37. s L. 3, 1, ff. De acquirenda et omit. Possess.; Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch.4, 3. 1 Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 2, ch. 8, 2; Instil, lib. 2, tit. 2, 12; Grot, liv. 2, ch. 3, 1 ; Savigny, Treatise on Possession (translated by Sir Erskine Perry), book 2, sect. 14, 15, &c. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 37 1 of each part of it. This is not contrary to the opinion of Vattel given above, that a nation cannot appropriate to herself, by mere taking pos- session, a country which she does not really occupy where she has formed no establishment and far too extensive for her to be able to people and cultivate." This would be taking from other nations that which is no benefit to herself, contrary to natural law. " All things," says Vattel, " susceptible of being property, are con- sidered as belonging to the nation which occupies the country, and constitute the total or mass of its possessions. But the nation does not possess all in the same manner. Those things which are not divided among communities or municipal bodies politic, or individuals of the nation, are called public property r . Some of these are reserved for the use of the state, and are the property of the crown, or the common- wealth ; while others remain common to all the citizens who use them, each according to his wants, or according to the laws which regulate their use; and these things are called common things. There are others which belong to some body or community ; they are called pro- perty of a community, res universitatis, and they are for the particular body, what public property is for the whole nation. As the nation may be looked upon as a great community, the property belonging to it so that all the citizens may use it, and that possessed by bodies or communities, may be called common property. The same rules apply to both. And the things belonging to individuals are called private property, res singulorum" x The public property may be acquired by the state, either by original reservation, or by other means, such as by gift or other transfer/ And it naturally belongs to the sove- reign power to dispose of the public property, but this rule must be understood subject to the diversities of municipal laws and regu- lations existing in different countries. 2 " Where the revenues of the public property do not suffice, the state supplies the deficiency by taxes and other imposts, which ought to be regulated so that all the citizens may pay their share according to their means, and the advantages which they derive from the state. And all the members of the civil society are bound to contribute according to their power to its welfare and safety; and they cannot refuse to furnish the necessary subsidies required by legitimate autho- rity." a These imposts are a salary which private persons pay to 11 Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch. 18, 208. * Ibi, ch. 20, 235. Ibi, 238. 1 Ibi, 237239. * Ibi, $ 240 ; Blackst. Com. b. 1, c. 8, p. 307; Domat, Droit Publ. liv. 1, tit. 5. B B2 372 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. the state for the defence of their life and property, and a contribution absolutely necessary for the expenses required by the government. 11 And we have already seen, that by the right called dominium eminens, (which is a part of the sovereign authority, and one of the jura majes- tatis,} the state has a power over all property within it, in cases of ne- cessity, and where such power is required for the public welfare; but where, in the exercise of this power, private property is taken or injured, compensation must be made by the state or otherwise. We come now to the property of bodies politic or corporate, called, in the civil law, res universitatis. This class of things were, as Jus- tinian informs us, sometimes called public, as contradistinguished from the property of individuals; for Ulpian says, nothing is public but what belongs to the Roman people. d They belong to the body as an aggregate person, but are used by the individuals composing it. Such were the theatres, basilica?, porticos, public baths, and the like, which belonged to a city or other municipal body, for the use of the citizens. 8 Nothing is said in the civil law, under this head, of the patrimony of cities and other aggregate bodies ; for, as Gajus informs us, cities (and other communities or bodies corporate) are, in contemplation of law, private persons/ 'though they are by the municipal laws of all countries, subject to various regulations according to their purposes in the commonwealth. The use of the several sorts of communities and corporations was, as Domat remarks, natural in the society of mankind, and had the same origin and foundation as the union of many families and of many nations under one and the same government of a monarchy, or of a republic. For as it is the multitude of the wants of men, and the necessity that every one has of the assistance of many others, that has been the occasion of forming monarchies and common- wealths, so the same necessities and wants have required and produced still more close and particular conjunctions of persons together, form- ing companies and corporations destined to different uses for the pub- lic good. g By the Civil Law, no communities could be established, except by legal permission. 11 The power of erecting a corporation is incident b Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 8, ch. 5, 3. c Vattel, Droit des Gens, liv. 1, ch 20, 244 ; Bynkershoek, Qtisest. Jur. Publ. lib. 2, ch. 15. d Instit. lib. 2, tit. 1, 6. e Virinii Comment, ad Instit. lib. 2, tit. 1, 6. 1 L. 16, ff. De Verbor. Signif. ; 1. 22, ff. De Fidejussoribus ; 1. 20, ff. De rebus dubiis. g Domat, Droit Publ. liv. 1, tit. 15. h L. 1, 2, ff. De Colleg. et Corpor. ; 1. 3, 1, ibi; 1. 1, ff. Quod cujus. Universit. nomine; 1. 5, 12, De Jur. immunit. TUB PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 373 to a sovereign power;' and no association can become a legal per- son except by the authority of the state; and this important rule is quite independent of the innocent or prejudicial nature of the society. k The essential character of a corporate body or corpora- tion is, that its rights rest, not on the members considered individu- ally, nor even on all the individuals together, but on an ideal whole. An important consequence of this is, that the partial, or even entire change of members, does not affect the essence, nor the unity, of the corporation. 1 This is what in our Jaw is called perpetual suc- cession. 1 " Corporations are sometimes called juridical persons, because they exist for juridical purposes. " The artificial legal capacity of these persons," says Savigny, " applies to relations of private law. Often the Public Law of the state requires that certain powers be exercised by an assembly or collective unity. But to con- sider such an unity, such as a college or court of judges, as a juridical person, would be a confusion of ideas ; for the essential character of the institution, the legal capacity to possess property, does not belong to most of these assemblies, though some of them, apart from their judicial functions, may have acquired the character of juridical per- sons. It is also erroneous to regard the uninterrupted succession of sovereigns in a hereditary monarchy as a juridical person." These collective powers of the Public Law must have been familiar to the Romans, who for so many centuries had a republican government; and in this sense they speak of a college of consuls or of tribunes of the people. Thus they said that the decemviri of a town constituted a unity, and their office was deemed to be exercised by one person. Even when all \\iQJudices appointed to decide a case were successively replaced by others, the judicium was not thereby changed. 15 But these expressions and principles were applied only to Public Law, or procedure, and entirely distinguished from the private law regarding juridical persons a distinction in conformity with the nature of things, and which modern writers have not sufficiently observed. The 1 Kent, Comment, vol. 1, lect. 12, p. 250. k Savigny, Traite du Droit Rom. torn. 2, p. 158. 1 Ibi, p. 241 ; 1. 7, 2, ff. Quod cujus. Univers.; 1. 76, ff. De Judiciis ; Grot. Droit de la Guerre, liv. 3, ch. 9, ^ 1. And see the Classification of Bodies, by Pomponius ; 1. 30, ff. De Usurp, et Usucap. m Kyd on Corporations, vol. 1, Introduction, p. 3; Madox, Firma Burgi, c. 2, 17, p. 50. n Hasse, Archiv, vol. 5, p. 67. It is so in our law ; Co. Litt. 43 ; 10 Rep. 29 b ; Plowd. Com. 213. L. 25, ff. Ad Municip. Magistratus mumcipales cum union magistratum adininis- trent, etiam unius hominis vicem sustinent. P L. 76, ff. De Judic. ; Novell. 134, cap. 6. 374 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. classes, centuriae, and tribes, were also important political unities ; but they do not appear ever to have been considered as juridical persons ; that is to say, as capable of possessing property in common.* 1 .... But while we restrict within the domain of private law, and especially the law of things, the legal capacity of juridical persons, I do not mean to say that in reality their capacity is their exclusive or even dominant characteristic. They, on the contrary, have special purposes often very superior to their capacity in private law, and of which the latter is merely an instrument. But all the characters of juridical persons, other than the power of holding property, are foreign to private law/" To this subject we shall return. There are also private associations for various purposes, not incor- porated ; but the law looks upon them as mere assemblies of indivi- duals having no juridical character of unity. 8 These doctrines of Savigny show the legal nature of the things constituting the patrimony of bodies corporate, and the reason why with reference to that property they are considered by the civil law in the light of private persons. The goods and rights of a corporate body belong to it in such a manner that none of the particular persons who are members of it have any right or property in them, or can dispose of them. 1 The management of the property of temporal cor- porate bodies ought to be regulated and restricted by the public law of the state, because experience shows that the members of those bodies are apt to prefer their own interests to those of the body and to the objects for which it was created. As for ecclesiastical bodies, they are regulated by the laws and principles of the Church. The fourth and last class of things, not private, remains to be con- sidered ; that is to say, res nullius. They are thus described by Jus- tinian. " Those things are the property of no one (res nullius) which are consecrated, or religious, or sacred : for things that are of divine right belong to no one." u This classification of things is important, from its analogy to the classification of things by the canon law. Things ecclesiastical are generally divided by the canonists into : I. Things spiritual, which belong immediately to divine worship or eccle- siastical functions. II. Things temporal, which are requisite for the sustenance of the churches and clergy. Things spiritual are subdi- vided into incorporeal things, such as virtues and gifts of grace, faith, hope, and charity, which belong to theology, and the sacraments ; i Savigny, Trait du Droit Rom. torn. 2, p. 234 236. r Ibi, p. 238. Pufend. Droit des Gens, liv. 7, ch. 2, 21. ' Doraat, Droit Publ. liv. 1, tit. 15, sect. 2, ^ 8. Instil, lib. 2, tit. 1, 7 ; 1. 23, 1, ff. De Rei Vindicatione ; 1. 43, ibi. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 375 and also rights, exemptions, advantages and privileges, and other things of like nature ; and things corporeal, such as altars and sacred utensils/ The remaining number of the first and general division, that is to say, things temporal, is subject to the same classifications as temporal property. Corporeal things are subdivided into two classes, things consecrated, sacred or sacrosanctec, and things religious religiosce. The former are dedicated to the exercise of external divine worship, such as churches, altars, and the like ; and as they are made inviolable, they are called sacred and holy sacra et sanctce. The latter, i.e., things reli- gious (religiosce) are those which have a connexion with Divine rites, or the duties and functions of the clergy, such as cemeteries, tombs, and houses of refuge for the aged, the sick, and the poor, and other objects of charity, which may be under the government of the Church. y All these things belong or bear a relation to Ecclesiastical Public Law, by which the government and public administration of the Church are regulated. Ecclesiastical things temporal are also affected, in divers ways, by the temporal laws of the state. And it is the same with things sacred and religious, so far as they partake of a temporal nature. This matter depends on the circumstances under which the Ca- tholic Church is placed in different countries, and on the particular muni- cipal laws existing in each state. Thus in countries where the Catholic Church is not established, but looked upon by the temporal govern- ment as a voluntary society ; its canons can only take effect in law, as the internal regulations of such society, not contrary to the law of the land. For the temporal courts will only regard them in this light, and thus ecclesiastical things, so far as they have a temporal nature, are brought de facto, although not by the will of the Church, under the regulation of the temporal laws. In some states restraints are placed on the acquisition of property for ecclesiastical and charitable purposes, by laws commonly known under the name of laws of Mort- main. 2 And the temporal laws have sometimes assisted the canons to prevent the impoverishment of the Church, by restricting the aliena- tion of ecclesiastical property. 3 So in explaining the nature of mixed laws we have seen that many ecclesiastical matters are partly regu- lated by temporal laws confirming those of the Church, or grounded on the double relation which those matters have to the Church and the civil community. And on the other hand many temporal matters 31 Devoti, Instit. Jur. Canon. Tabulae Synopt. tab. 34 ; Lancelotti, Inst. Jur. Canon, lib. 2, tit. 1, 50. >' Devoti, Tabulae Synopt. ubi sup. ; Devoti, Inst. Canon, lib. 2, tit. 1, 1. * Nardi, Diritto Eccles. torn. 1, 261. a Ibi, 263. 376 THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. are partly regulated by laws of the Church, because of their relation to Religion, or to the duties and functions of the Church and ecclesias- tical persons. 6 Divers privileges have been granted by the Holy See to particular princes and states by concordats and otherwise, whereby they enjoy rights of patronage and protection regarding ecclesiastical things ; such, for instance, as that of proposing persons for bishoprics, and appointing to ecclesiastical benefices, dignities and offices. The doctrine of the Roman Law regarding res nullim contains a principle important both in Private and in Public Law. It is this, that a thing may be actually appropriated, and yet be the property of no person. Savigny observes that in the early times of Roman history, the need to constitute a juridical person was little felt, because the important thing in the divers associations of priests and artisans and the like, was community of action, and the political position and the capacity of the body to hold property, was matter of secondary interest. For the expenses of the public worship of the Romans were defrayed by the state; and to make a foundation for this purpose, it was sufficient to have the property intended to be given, consecrated. By consecra- tion the thing given was withdrawn from commerce, without becoming the property either of the temple or of ,the priests. Subsequently, when the state increased in extent, the idea of the corporate character or juridical person applied in an important and clear manner to the municipal communities or towns, to the municipia and the colonies. For they required to possess and acquire property, and their dependant situation rendered them amenable to and suitors before the courts. And the idea of the juridical person once introduced, it extended itself to other cases. Thus it was applied to the ancient confraternities of priests and artisans, and then to the state itself, under the name of the Fisc, which was treated as a person, and subject to a jurisdiction ; and afterwards it was extended to subjects of an ideal character, such as the gods and the temples. The latter application received great and numerous extensions under the rule of Christianity. Among the Germanic nations the institution was preserved and still more developed, for it found the bonds of government relaxed, and the minds of men inclined to form free asso- ciations of all sorts. In modern times, the centralization of authority has reacted on corporate bodies, and diminished their importance, without changing anything of the essential characteristics of juridical persons/ 1 These observations of Savigny are the more interesting from b Domat, Loix Civiles, Traile des Loix, ch. 10. c Savigny, Trait du Droit Rom. torn. 2, 87, p. 213245. d Ibi, p. 245. THE PUBLIC LAW OF THINGS. 377 their application to the history of corporations in our own country. For charters of incorporation granted to cities and towns in England did not commence until the reign of Henry VI. ; and the technical cor- porate character was introduced chiefly with reference to the acqui- sition and tenure of property. 6 We may conclude that the juridical person is in reality a fiction. Thus a corporation has been called a " mere metaphysical being a mere ens rationis," and has been said to " rest only in intendment and consideration of law." f It follows, that the true principle is that involved in the doctrine of the Roman law regarding res nullius, that is to say, that things may be devoted and appropriated to a public purpose, without being vested in any person or persons. It is the purpose of a foundation or other appropriation that must be looked upon as the real owner. So we find Fleta distinguishing between the persons constituting a body, and the object for which property was given to it : " In colleges and chapters there always remains the same body, although they all successively die ; as it may be said of a flock of sheep, where there is always the same flock, although the sheep successively die off. 8 Nor does either of them succeed to the other by right of succession, so that the right should descend hereditarily from one to the other ; because the right always remains to the Church, and the Church always remains" h So, notwithstanding the jealous eye with which our common law looks upon the suspension or abey- ance of the freehold, Littleton says, " If a parson of a church dieth, now the freehold of the glebe of the parsonage is in none during the time that the parsonage is void, but is in abeyance." 1 Thus, during the interval, it is res nullius, or not vested in any person, and yet it is property. And by the English law, the property which the parson has in the church is of a different nature from his right over his private property, and even that which he has over the parsonage-house. The property of the parson in the church and churchyard is only for the technical purpose of enabling him to bring actions for injuries to them. k Here, again, is to be seen the principle of the Roman law regarding res nullius. e Merewether & Stephens, Hist, of Boroughs and Municipal Corporations, Introduc. per tot. and pp. 29, 31, 33. And see Manning, Serviens ad Legem, p. 230. f 10 Co. Rep. 32 ; Treby, Arg. in Quo Warranto case. It has also been called persona politica. Com. Dig. Franchise, F. 1. s This illustration is evidently from the Roman Law (Pomponius); 1. 30, fF. De Usurp, et Usucap. ; and Paulus, 1. 23, ^ 5, ff. De Rei Vindicatione. h Fleta, lib. 6, ch. 18. i Litt. 647; Co. Litt. 12, 18b. * Blackst. Com. b. 1, ch. 11, ^5, 7. 378 CONCLUSION. We have now reached the conclusion of these Commentaries. They commenced with a disquisition on the origin and foundation of laws : for the leading idea throughout the whole work is, that, under Divine Providence, the world is governed, and human society constituted, by laws and obligations. That idea applies to society, both in its uni- versality, and also viewed as a great aggregate composed of a number of political communities, in various forms, but all having certain fun- damental principles in common. We have shown the way in which laws are consequences, direct or remote, flowing from the two great fundamental laws laid down in the Gospel, on which society is con- structed ; and this has enabled us to see the unity of Universal Juris- prudence, and the different sorts or classes of laws or rules which it contains. The uses of those various kinds of laws enabled us to perceive the constitution of society and governments : and these inves- tigations have shown the necessity of the Spiritual Law, and that with- out it jurisprudence would be incomplete, because it would belong to one part only of the nature of man, and would not contain all the laws which are consequences of the two primary laws on which society is constructed by Divine Providence ; and it would be therefore in- adequate to regulate the conduct of mankind, that is, the steps which they take towards the end of their creation. And thus we have seen the effect of the Catholic Church in the economy of general terrestrial government, and the operation of its laws considered as a portion of that government. We have explained both the unity and the diversity of temporal and Spiritual Jurisprudence, and the way in which the latter preserves the great principle of the universality of human society. So, from the first principles showing the origin and nature and spirit of laws, we have proceeded to the constitution and forms of civil governments, with the organic laws that regulate them. And we have considered municipal laws and governments, both as govern- ing the particular states to which they belong, and also in their relation to the general government of mankind. The exposition of the principles on which human society is formed, and of the nature and uses of civil communities, has shown us the fundamental doctrines of international law. This comprehensive system of Universal Public Law has direct connexion with every part of political and legal science. For all poli- tical science must be in harmony and accordance with the laws on which human society is constructed and governed ; and though juris- prudence and politics are distinct sciences, yet they form part of one scheme of terrestrial government. And, as we have seen, all laws are derived from the two primary laws, on the foundation of which CONCLUSION. 379 society is constituted, and bear relation to the order and the various uses of that society, according to the principles and reasons on which they are grounded. Thus the reader has seen what use may be derived from Universal Public Law in every branch of legislation and public affairs, and the arguments which it affords to combat the theories which, especially in our times, threaten the foundations of society and property, and all the institutions of secondary natural law. Those theories, wild and absurd as they are in the eyes of practical and judicious men, have enough pf speciousness to be dangerous; and they must be met by reasons which are to be found in the science of Public Law. Such are the general views with which these Commentaries have been written. The vast extent and difficulty of their subject ren- dered the task most arduous : and I must add, that there does not exist a treatise similar to this, either in the English or in any other language. Whether I have justly deserved even forgiveness of the apparent presumption involved in so great and novel an undertaking, time will show. I can now only plead, that it has been accomplished after years of preparation, and with much labour, research, and medi- tation; and I offer to the world these Commentaries on Universal Public Law, trusting to that indulgence which is seldom refused to a zealous effort for the advancement of learning. INDEX. Absolute monarchy, 265, 266. Absolute monarchy, its principles, 266, &c. Absolute power, 267, 268. Accession, 368. Affinity, 54. Agnatic succession, 279, 332. Allegiance, nemo potest e.ruere patriam, 152. Allegiance, divided, 181, 182. Alluvion, 366, &c. Ambassadors, 67, 174. America. See United States. Angels, their obedience to law, 21. Animals, supposed law common to them and men, 17, 18. Annexation, 346. Antoninus, his declaration regarding the sea, 360. Appeals, 238, 239. Arcifinite lands, 366. Aristocracy in mixed governments, 300 302. Army, 226, 227, 246. Artificial, or arbitrary matters, 97, 98. Artificial, or arbitrary matters, diversity of laws regarding, 141, &c. Assemblies. See Legislative. Balance of powers in a slate, 245, 246, 303, &c., 310, &c. Ballot, 261, 262, 341. Banks of a river, 362. Bar, prospects of the, 9, 10. Bays and straits, 358, 359, 361. Bills, proposed board for preparing and revising, 149. Bishop's see, 135. Bishoprics, nomination to, 136. Blackstone, his theory of the constitutional balance of powers, 312, 313. Bodies, classification of, 373, n. '. Boundaries changed by rivers, 366, &c. Boundaries of lands, the three sorts' of, 366. Canon Law, defined, 34, 69, 70. Catholic Church. See Roman. Centralization, 347. Chambers. See Houses. Church, Anglican and Greek, 127, 128. Churches, established, 80, 127, &c. Cicero on mixed government. See Ta- citus. Civil and Criminal Law, 235, &c. Civil liberty, 290. Civil list, 320. Civil power, analysed, 210, 211. Coasts, to what distance from them do- minion extends, 356, 357. Codes, observation of Savigny on, 148. Codification, 148. Cognatic succession, 279, 332. Colonies and Colonial policy, 328 330. Comity of nations, 151, 155. Comniissory clause, 271, 272, 331. Commons, great power of the House of, 321. Commons, their power of voting supplies, 322. Compact, doctrine of the social, 200, &c., 261. Comproniissum, elections per, 262. Confederacies, defects of, 240, 241, 337. Confederation, defects of the American, 336, &c. Confederations, 325, &c. Confederations, their dissolution, 335,336. Conflict of laws, 138, &c. Conflict of laws, first principles of the, 150, &c. Congress, in America, its power, 345. Conquered people, two ways of dealing with them, 327. 382 INDEX. Consanguinity, 53. Constituent assemblies, 2, 3, 261 . Constitution of a state defined, 247, 344. Constitution of the United States, 343. Conterini, Cardinal, his reflections on laws, 84, 85. Conventions of the people, 309,318. Corporate bodies, 60, 272, &c., 376, 377. Courts, conflict of laws regarding jurisdic- tion of, 172, &c. Courts, power of the Crown to erect, 314. Crime, committed in one country and punished in another, 182, 183. Crimes and offences, conflict of laws re- garding, 179, &c. Criminal Law, 184, &c. Cujus est solum, the rule, 353. Customs among nations, 67, 68. Dardanelles, 358, and note. D'Aguesseau, his advice to his son, 23. Declaratory Act, the, 328. Decretals, 113. Defence, right of self, 232, 233. Delegated jurisdiction, 234. Delegated power, 344. Delivery of criminals. See Extradition. Democracy, 252254, 285, 303, 318. Departments, separation of, 285,286,310. Desert territories, 364. Despotism, 266. Dissolution of confederations, or compound states, 335, 336. Divine law, 64. Divine right of civil government, 198, 199. Divine right of kings. See Kings. Divorce, foreign, 171, 172, 176. Domain and sovereignty, distinction be- tween, 360, 363, 364. Domicil, 166. Dominium eminens, 227, 228,363,372. Duties or obligations, conditional or hy- pothetical, 50, &c. Duties or obligations, absolute and innate, 49. Duties of imperfect obligation, 49, 50. Duty of sovereigns, 276. * Note. See on the subject of double do- micil, Somerville v. Somermlle, 5 Ves. jun. ; Forbes v. Forbes, Wood, V. C., 9th Feb. 1854. Ecclesiastical Public Law, 133, &c. Ecclesiastical Public Law, its contact with the political divisions of the world, 137. Ecclesiastical Public Law, its Universality, 137. Ecclesiastical things, 375, 376. Elected senators or peers, 301. Elections, frequency of, 319. Elections. See Representation. Elections, indirect, 262, 263, 362, 363, 341. Elective monarchy, 278, 279. Emigration, 273, and see Refugees. Emperor, the Roman, was legibus solutim, 222. Engagements in society, 39, 40. Engagements, voluntary and otherwise, 55, &c. England, Constitution of, 293, 295, 312, 313. Epicureans, their doctrine, 29, 31. Equality of men, doctrine of the, 44 48. Equality of states or nations, 45, 248. Equity, amalgamation of law and, 148. Eiceptio reijudicata, 177. Executive power, 222, &c., 319, &c. Executive power, compared with legis- lative, 306. Exterritoriality of sovereigns, 174. Extradition, 185, &c. Factories, marriages in, 169. Federal government, 338, &c. Federations, defects of, 241. Fisheries, 351, 355, &c. Fishing, common right of, 363. Foreigners, 173, 174, and see Refugees. Foreign judgments in criminal cases, 1 83, 184. Foreign sovereigns, 174. Forfeiture of the Crown, 272. Forms of government, classified, 250. France. See Revolution. Franchise, elective, 258260. Franklin, his remark on legislatures in two branches or chambers, 308. Fundamental Laws, limiting the sovereign's power, 267, &c. Fundamental Laws, power of changing them, 273275. INDEX. 383 Fundamental Laws, their legal character, 248, 249. Fundamental Laws, supreme, 344. Game, Roman laws regarding, 351, n. . Game. See Hunting and Fishing. Genoa, mode of election there, 263. Germany, attempted federal constitution there, 3, 4. German)-, contradictions of the sources of law there, 160, 161. Glossators, the, 23, 24. Good, the sovereign, 25, 26, 35. Gospel, the two great laws in the, 25, 26. Government, difference between, and a league, 338. Government, dispute as to the best form of, 141, 142. See Divine Right. Government, mixed, 142, 253. Government, use of, 58. Greece, confederations in, 241. Grotius, on the origin of Civil States, 201, 202. Guardians to minors, 95. Hanover, its former position regarding the United Kingdom, 331. Heirship in the Civil Law, 55. Hereditary monarchy, 277, &c., 299, 300, and see Peerage. Hierarchy, 114, 130, 131. Hindu Laws, their analogy to the Roman, 147. Hobbes, his definition of the law of na- tions, 68. Hobbes on the origin of Civil States, 201. Hooker on the origin of Civil States, 200. Houses, doctrine of two, for legislation, 317. Humanity, the tie of, 195. Hunting and fishing, laws regarding, 351. Hunting ground, 365. Impeachments, 302, 313. Imperium merum et mixtum, 217. India, personal laws there, 158, 159. Indian lands, 365. International Law, late events considered with reference to, 5. International Law, 68, 195, 196, on what it is founded, 1 2. Interregnum, 279, 280. Involuntary engagements, 56. Islands, 367. Italy, political changes in, 23. James II., his flight, 205, 206. Judges, mode of appointing, 323. Judges, their tenure of office and salaries, 311, 323. Judgments, conflict of laws regarding, 175178. Judgments, effect of, 237, 238. Judicial department, 322, &c. Judicial power, 231, &c. Judicial power, its weakness, 305. Judicial power, its extent, 346. Judicial power, declaring legislative acts void, 343, 344. Junius, his error regarding the power of parliament, 274, n. *. Juridical persons, 376, 377. Jurisdiction, 217,233235. Jurisdiction, civil and criminal, 235, &c. Jurisdiction over ships at sea, 361. Jurisdiction over the sea adjoining a coun- try, 357,361. Jurisprudence, 33. Jurisprudence, harmony of its parts, 34. Jury, trial by, 324. Jus eminens, 227. Jus gentium, 18. Jus gentium, primary and secondary, 40 42. Jus in re, and jus ad ran, 51. Jus sacrum, of the Romans, 74. Justice, the Crown the fountain of, 314. Justinian, his fifty decisions, 219. King, 273. King, the, can do no wrong, 299, 312, and see Ministers. King, the title of, 264. King. See Monarchy. Kingdoms, connected by the person of their sovereign, 330, 331. Kings, doctrine of the Divine right of, 143, 144. Lakes, 368370. Lapse of benefices, 96. Law, its origin and foundations, 14, &c. Law, its division into two branches, public and private, 14, 15. 384 INDEX. Law, its first principles, 15, 16. Law, its connexion with religion, 16, 37, 43. Law, its necessity, 16, 17. Law of nations described, 68. Law of nations, supposed, created by con- sent, 67. Law of Nations. See Natural Law. Laws, analogies of those of different countries, 146, 147. Laws, arbitrary and natural, their use and diversities, 101, &c. Laws, arbitrary or positive, 86, &c. Laws of the Church, their necessity, 70, 119. Laws, immutable, 63, &c. Laws, mixed, 8082. Laws, the two great fundamental, 25, 26, 40. Laws, their obligatory force, 27, &c. Lawyers, use of public law to them, 8 10. Legatees, 59. Legislation, 2 1 8, &c. Legislative assemblies, whether they should be single or double, 317, &c. Legislative department, remedies against its too great .preponderance, 314, &c. Legislative power, 217, &c., 305, &c. Liberty, 288, &c. Lighthouses and seamarks, 359. Limited monarchy, 265, 266. Locke, on the origin of Civil States, 200. Love of God and our neighbour, 25, 26. Mackenzie, his doctrine regarding mo- narchy, 144. Magistrates and public officers, 225, 226. Magistrate, necessity of the civil, 209. Mahometan Laws, analogy with the Ro- man, 147. Majestatis jura, 217. Majestatis jura, connexion of, 239, &c. Majoritas et obedientia, 129. Majority, authority of a, 207, 208, 228, 261, 334, 340. Malta, election of the Grand Master of, 263. Marriage, 53. Marriage, conflict of laws regarding, 168, &c., 176, &c. Marriage, Sacrament of, 163. Mathematics, compared by Burke with moral sciences, 22. Middle ages, personal laws during the, 157, 158. Ministers. See Responsibility. Mixed governments, 282, &c. Monarchy, 142, 143, 264, &c. Montesquieu, his constitutional theory, 293,295. Montesquieu, his opinion as to federal republics, 339. Movables, regulated by law of domicil, 165. Municipal laws, diversity of, 138, &c. Nationality, abuse of, 125. Nationality, held indelible, 152. Nation, possessions of a, 371. Nations, division of mankind into, 124, &c. Nations, division of the world into, con- sidered with reference to ecclesiastical public law, 127, &c., 132, &c. Nations, should maintain the law of na- tions, 355. Nations, supposed voluntary law of, 67.68. Natural law, 17, 18, 6567, 126. Natural law, how the civilians have di- vided it, 40, 41. Natural law, how the jurists divide it, 44, &c. Natural law, its efficient cause, 65, 66. Natural reason, 32. Navigation Laws, mistaken spirit of the, 126. Necessity and source of laws, 123, 124. Negative of the President of the United States, 315, 316. Negative of the Crown in England, 312, 315,316. Negotiorum gestorum, the contract, 55,56. Neutral fortress, 358. Nobility, how they affect a monarchy, 267. Nobility in a mixed government, 300 302. Notio, 234. Oath, coronation, 270. Oaths and promises of sovereigns, 269, 270. INDEX. 385 Oaths, the House of Commons cannot administer, 314. Obedience and superiority, 129. Obligation of laws, 2730, 98. Obligations, ex contmctu, and quasi e.r contractu, and er delicto, and quasi ex j deliclo, 57. Obligations. See Duties. Occupancy, 370, 371. Occupancy, acquisition of territories and lands by, 364, &c. Occupancy, simple and consequent, 368. Omnes populi, the law, 30, 31. Omnipotence of Parliament, 275. Order, hierarchy of, 131. Ordinary jurisdiction, 234. Original contract, 205, 206. Orleans, overthrow of the house of, 1 , 2. Parliament, 275, 312. Parliament, the Convention, 205. Peace and war, 226, 227. Peerage bill, its rejection, 391, note. Peerage, elective, 301. Peerage, hereditary, 298, 800, 301. People, sovereignty of the, 212, &c. People, the term, 204, 205. People. See Representation. Perfect and imperfect associations, 208, 209,211. Personal laws, 156, &c. Persons, juridical, 60. Police, 145, 146. Pope, election of the, 261. Pope, his temporal power, 81, 82,280, note . Pope. See Unity. Political liberty, 292. Politics, distinction between, and jurispru- dence, 31, 89. Ports and harbours, 358. Posthumous heir to the crown, 280. Power, balance of, 292, 303, &c. Prerogative defined, 320. Prescription, 93, 94, 95, 355. Prescription considered with reference to International Law, 93, 94. Prescription, its nature, 93, 95. President of the United States, 341, 345. Press, liberty of the, 291. Property of the state, 229, 230. Property, institution of, 89, 3o2. Property, private, taken for public pur- poses, 228. Providence, 62. Provinces, 328. Public and private ecclesiastical law, 111, 112. Public and private law, connexion be- tween, 348. Public law, 14, 15, 74. Public law, its use at the present time, 5, 6. Public law, meanings of the term, 110. Public law, temporal and spiritual, its use, 107, fcc. Public law, universal, 11, 12. Public policy regarded by judges, 348. Pufendorf on the origin of civil societies, 201. Punishments, power of, 223, 224, 225. Quasi contracts, 57, 269. Real and personal estate, distinction be- tween, as to successions, 59. Reason, 31, 62. Reason and grace, 69. Refugees, foreign, 185, 186, &c. Regent, 280,281. Religion, 61, 195, 248. Representation of the people, 228. n. m , 254, &c. Representation, the fiction of, 228. Representatives, house of, in America, 340. Republic, 251, &c. Republic, French, 2, 318. Res judicata, 237, 238. Responsibility of ministers, 299, 316, 320, 321. Revenue, public, 227. Revenues of a state, 371, 372. Revolution in France, 1, 243. Rivers, 352, &c., 362. Rivers, change of the course of, 366, &c. Rivers, works constructed upon, 367. Roman Catholic Church, its influence on law and government, 121, 122. Roman Catholic Church, its legislative authority, 77. 386 INDEX. Roman Catholic Church, its public law, 111, &c., 128, &c. Roman Catholic Church, its relation to the division of the world into states, 128, &c. Roman Catholic Church, its stability and social effects, 7, 8. Roman Catholic Church, not within any State, 78. Rolls of Parliament, 149. Rousseau, bis false doctrines, 57. Sardinia, late events in the kingdom of, 3,4. Savage tribes, their territories, 365. Savigny, on the origin of civil states, 203, &c. Scrutinium, election per, 262. Sea,dominion over neighbouring, 357, 361. Sea, liberty of the, 125, 126, 353, &c. Search, right of, 362. Senate in America, 340. Senates, 301. And see Upper House. Shores, 358, 362. Slavery, 47. Socialist party, 4, 5. Social state, 21, 26. Society, civil legal origin of, 1 94, &c. Society, end of, 104, 200. Society, plan of, 35, &c., 52, &c. Society, the three parts of, 195, 196. Sovereign power, 206, &c., 211,270,271. Sovereignty, residuary, 343. Spiritual public law, 107, &c. Spirit of laws defined, 149, 150. State, connexion of, with the Church, 115. States, legal origin of, 194, &c. Status, 106, 107. Statutes, real and personal, 163, 164. Subjects of more than one country, 181, 182. Substitutions, 101, 102. Successions, 59, 60, 277. Suffrage, laws regulating the, 257. Suffrage, the, 257, &c. Suffrage, universal, 258, 259, 260. Supreme law, 343. Sussex peerage case, 158. Tacitus, his and Cicero's idea of mixed government, 298. Taxation, justice in, 229. Taxation, the right of, 227,371, 372. Taxes, laws establishing, 96. Temporal and spiritual laws, 80, &c. Temporal and spiritual laws, conflict be- tween them, 13G. Temporal and spiritual powers, 79, 80. Temporal law, how it affects ecclesiasti- cal things, 82, 136, 375, 376. Territorial laws, 156. Territories of a state, 363, &c. Things common to all men, 352, &c. Things consecrated, 374, 375. Things public, 362, &c. Things spiritual, 374. Tilings, the law of, 347, &c. Treasury, its power of regulation, 223. Treaties, in what sense part of the law of nations, 68. Treaties, tacit clause in, 142, 272. Trebonian, his error concerning obliga- gations quasi ex contractu, 57, 147, 202, 269. Trent, council of, decrees regarding mar- riage, 168, 171. Tyranny, 265. Ulpian, his three precepts, 26, 27. Unam sanctum, the decretal, 79. Unanimity of assemblies, 207. Unanimity required among confederates, 334, 340, 343. Uninhabited countries, 364, 365. United States, conflict of laws there, 161, 162. United States, constitution of the, 338, &c. Unity of government, 243, 244, &c., 295, &c. Unity of the Church, 130, 135. Universality of the law of the Church, 132, &c. Universal suffrage, 258, &c. Upper house or senate, use of a, 318. Usage. See Custom. Usucapion. See Prescription. Utilitarian theory, 30, 31. Utility, producing laws, 224. Venice, her claim over the Adriatic, 358. Venice, mode of electing the Doge of, 263. INDEX. 387 Vessels at sea, 361. Veto. See Negative. Voting, secret, 261, 262. Voting, the right of, 258, &c. War, private, abolished, 233. Washington, his dictatorship, 244. Waters, running, 352. Women, their exclusion from political suffrage, 259. Wrecks, 359. Wrongs, distinction between public and private, 235, 236. Zallinger on the origin of civil states, 202. LONDON: PRINTED BY C. ROWORTH AND SONS, BELL YARD, TEMPLE BAR. Februciry, 1878. .A. LAW WORKS, PUBLISHED BY S.TEVENS AND SONS, (LATE STEVENS AND NORTON), 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C., (Formerly of Bell Yard, Lincoln's Inn). Law Books Purchased or Valued. ACTS OF PARLIAMENT. Public and Local Acts from an early date, may be had of the Publishers of this Catalogue, who have also on sale the largest collection of Private Acts, relating to Estates, Enclosures, Railways, Roads, &c., &c. ACTION AT LAW. Prentice's Proceedings in an Action in the Queen's Bench, Common Pleas, and Exchequer Divisions of the High Court of Justice. By SAMUEL PRENTICE, of the Middle Temple, Esq., one of Her Majesty's Counsel. Editor of " Archbold's Prac- tice," "Russell on Crimes," &c. Demy 8vo. 1877. 10*. 6d. " The book can be safely lecoramended to students and practitioners .... The recent cases appear to be rally noticed." Law Timet, Nov. 10, 1877. ' ' Whether for the student or practitioner, we can cordially recommend the work." Monthly Law Tracts, December, 1877. Smith's Elementary View of the Proceedings in an Action at Law. Twelfth Edition, adapted to the practice of the Supreme Court. By W. D. I. FOULKES, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 12mo. 1S76. 10s. 6d. " The student will find in ' Smith's Action ' a manual, by the Btudy of which he may easily acquire a general knowledge of the mode of procedure in the various stage? of an action in the several divisions of the High Court of Justice." Law Times, September 2. 1870. ADM IRALTY.-Boy d. Vide Shipping." Lowndes. Vide "Collisions." Pritchard's Admiralty Digest. With Notes from Text Writers, and the Scotch, Irish, and American Keports. Second Edition. By ROBERT A. PRITCHARD, D.C.L., Barrister-at-Law, and WILLIAM TARN PRITCHARD. With Notes of Cases from French Maritime Law. By ALGERNON JONES, Avocat a la Cour Imperiale de Paris. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1865. 3/. Stuart's Cases heard and determined in the Vice-Admiralty Court at Quebec, 1836-75. Edited by GEORGE OKILL STUART, Esq., Q.C. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1858-75. Xet, 51. ** All standard Law Workt are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings. 2 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. AGENCY. Petg rave's Principal and Agent. A Manual of the Law of Principal and Agent. By E. C. PETGRAVE, Solicitor. 12mo. 1857. 7s. 6d. Petgrave's Code of the Law of Principal and Agent, with a Preface. By E. C. PETGRAVE, Solicitor Demy 12mo. 1876. Net, 2s. "Rogers. Vide "Elections." Russell's Treatise on Mercantile Agency. Second Edition. 8vo. 1873. 14*. AGRICULTURAL LAW. Addison's Practical Guide to the Agricultural Holdings (England) Act, 1875 (38 & 39 Vic. c. 92), and Treatise thereon, shewing the Alterations in the Law, and containing many useful Hints and Suggestions as to the carrying out of the Provisions of the Act; with Handy Forms and a Carefully Prepared Index. Designed chiefly for the use of Agricultural Landlords and Tenants. By ALBERT ADDISON, Solicitor of the Supreme Court of Judicature. 1 2mo. 1876. Net, 2s. 6d. Cooke on Agricultural Law. The Law and Practice of Agricultural Tenancies, with Numerous Precedents of Tenancy Agreements and Farming Leases, &c., &c. By G. WINGROVE COOKE, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 8vo. 1851. 18*. Dixon's Farm. Vide "Farm." ARBITRATION. Russell's Treatise on the Duty and Power of an Arbitrator, and the Law of Submissions and Awards ; with an Appendix of Forms, and of the Statutes relating to Arbitration. By FRANCIS RUSSELL, Esq., M.A., Barrister-at-Law. Fifth Edition. Royal 8vo. 1878. (Just ready.) II. 16s. ARTICLED CLERKS. Butlin's New and Complete Examination Guide and Introduction to the Law ; for the use of Articled Clerks and those who contemplate entering the legal profession, comprising Courses of Reading for the Preliminary and Intermediate Examinations and for Honours, or a Pass at the Final, with Statute, Case, and Judicature (Time) Tables, Sets of Examination Papers, &c., &c. By JOHN FRANCIS BUTLIN, Solicitor, &c. 8vo. 1877. 18*. A sensible and useful guide for the legal tyro." Solicitors' Journal, April 21, 1877. "In supplying law students with materials for preparing themselves for examination, Mr. Buttin, we think, has distanced all competitors. The volume before ns contains hints on reading, a very neat summary of law, which the best read practitioner need not despise. There are time tables under the Judicature Act, and an excellent tabular arrangement ol leading cases, which will be found of great service .... Tuition of this kind will do much to remove obstacles which present themselves to commencing students, and when examinations are over the book is one which may be usefully kept close at hand, and will well repay 'noting up.' " Lcae Times, February 24, 1877. Head. Vide "Statutes." Rubinstein and "Ward's Articled Clerks' Hand- book. Being a Concise and Practical Guide to all the Steps Necessary for Entering into Articles of Clerkship, passing the Preliminary, Intermediate and Final Examinations, obtaining Admission and Certificate to Practise, with Notes of Cases affecting Articled Clerks, and Suggestions as to Mode of Reading and Books to be read during Articles. By J. S. RUBINSTEIN and S. WARD, Solicitors. Demy 12mo. 1877. 3*. "No articled clerk should be without it." -Law Time*, February 17, 1877. " Will serve as a simple and practical guide to all the steps necessary for entering into articles of clerkship to solicitors, for passing the several examinations, and for pro- curing admission on the Roll." Lav: Time*, February 24, 1877. * ,* All standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law caff and other bindings. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. ARTICLED Wharton's Articled Clerk's Manual. A Manual for Articled Clerks : being a comprehensive Guide to their successful Examination, Admission, and Practice as Attorneys and Solicitors of the Superior Courts. Ninth Edition. Greatly enlarged. By CHARLES HENRY ANDERSON, Senior Prizeman of the Incor- porated Law Society, &c. Royal 12mo. 1864. 18*. ARTICLES OF ASSOCIATION. Palmer. Fide "Conveyancing." ATTORNEYS. Falling's Law of Attorneys, General and Special, Attorneys-at-Law, Solicitors, Notaries, Proctors, Convey- ancers, Scriveners, Land Agents, House Agents, &c. , and the Offices and Appointments usually held by them. Their several Qualifica- tions and legitimate Province, Rights, Duties, Privileges, Exemptions, Disabilities, and Liabilities in the General Practice of the Law, in Legal Proceedings, in Legal Negotiations, and Legal Formalities. And the Law of Costs as between Party and Party and Attorney and Client. By ALEXANDER PULLING, Serjeant-at-Law. Third Edition. 8vo. 1862. 18*. " It is a laborious work, a careful work, the work of a lawyer, and, beyond comparison, the beat that has ever been produced upon this subject." Law Times. Smith. The Lawyer and his Profession. A Series of Letters to a Solicitor commencing Business. By J. ORTON SMITH. 12mo. 1860. 4*. AVERAGE Hopkins' Hand-Book on Average. Third Edition. 8vo. 1868. 18*. Lowndes' Law of General Average. English and Foreign. Third Edition. By RICHARD LOWNDES, Author of " The Admiralty Law of Collisions at Sea." (In preparation.) BAILMENTS. Jones on the Law of Bailments. Fourth Edition. By W. THEOBALD. 8vo. 1834. Net, 5*. BALLOT. FitzGerald's Ballot Act. With an INTRODUCTION. Forming a Guide to the Procedure at Parliamentary and Municipal Elections. Second Edition. Enlarged, and containing the Municipal Elections Act, 1875, and the Parliamentary Elections (Returning Officers) Acr, 1875. By GERALD A. R. FITZGERALD, M. A., of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Fcap. 8vo. 1876. 5*. Qd. "A useful guide to all concerned in Parliamentary and Municipal Elections." Law Uagarim, February, 1877. " We should strongly advise any person connected with elections, whether acting as candidate, agent, or in any other capacity, to become possessed ot this manual." Novem- ber 26, 1S76. BANKING. Walker's Treatise on Banking Law. In- cluding the Crossed Checks Act, 1876, with dissertations thereon, also references to some American Cases, and full Index. By J. DOUGLAS WALKER, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Demy 8vo. 1877. 14*. " Persons who are interested in banking law may be guided out of many a difficulty by consulting Mr. Walker's volume." Law Timet, May 19, 1877. BANKRUPTCY. Bedford's Final Examination Guide to Bankruptcy. Third Edition. 12mo. 1877. 6*. Lynch's Tabular Analysis of Proceedings in Bankruptcy, for the use of Students for the Incorporated Law Society's Examinations. Second Edition. 8vo. 1874. Jfet, It. Scott's Costs in Bankruptcy. Fide "Costs." %* A tt standard Law WorJcs are kept in Stock, in lain calf and other Undinrjs. A 2 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. Smith's Manual of Bankruptcy. A Manual relating to Bankruptcy, Insolvency, and Imprisonment for Debt ; comprising the New Statute Law verbatim, in a consolidated and readable form. With the Rules, a Copious Index, and a Supplement of Decisions. By JOSIAH W. SMITH, Esq., B.C.L., Q.C., Judge of County Courts. 12mo. 1873. 10*. ** The Supplement may be had separately, net, 2s. Gd. Williams' Law and Practice in Bankruptcy, comprising the Bankruptcy Act, the Debtors Act, and the Bankruptcy Repeal and Insolvent Court Act of 1869, and the Rules and Forms made under those Acts. Second Edition. By ROLAND VAUGHAN WILLIAMS, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., and WALTER VAUGHAN WILLIAMS, of the Inner Temple, Esq., assisted by FRANCIS HALLETT HABDCASTLE, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barristers- at- Law. 8vo. 1876. II. 8s. " ' Williams on Bankruptcy' is quite satisfactory, the more so, perhaps, as the authors have wisely 'not attempted to give all the old authorities, even where the law seems uu- changed, but rather the result of those authorities.'" Law Magazine, November, 1S76. "The present edition is a great improvement." Solicitors' Journal. " It would be difficult to speak in terms of undue praise of the present work. . . : The present edition brings down the law to May, 1876, and the profession has now not only the most recent, but certainly one of the best, if not the best, treatise on the Law of Bankruptcy." Public Opinion. BILLS OF EXCHANGE. Chitty on Bills of Exchange and Promissory Notes. Eleventh Edition. By JOHN A. RUSSELL, one of Her Majesty's Counsel, and Judge of County Courts. (In the press.) Eddis' Rule of Ex parte Waring. By A. C. EDDIS, B.A.,of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister-at Law. Post 8vo. 1876. Net, 2s.6d. BILLS OF SALE Millar's Bills of Sale. A Treatise on Bills of Sale, with an Appendix containing the Acts for the Registration of Bills of Sale, Precedents, &c. (being the Fourth Edition of Millar and Collier's Treatise on Bills of Sale). By F. C. J. MILLAR, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 12mo. 1877. 12^ BOOK-KEEPING. Bedford's Intermediate Examina- tion Guide to Book-keeping. Second Edition. 12mo. 1875. Net, 2s. 6d. BUILDING ACTS.-Woolrych. Vide "Metropolis Building Acts." CANAL TRAFFIC ACT. Lely's Railway and Canal Traf- fic Act, 187S. And other Railway and Canal Statutes ; with the General Orders, Forms, and Table of Fees. Post 8vo. 1873. 8s. CARRIERS. Browne on Carriers. A Treatise on the Law of Carriers of Goods and Passengers by Land and Water. With References to the most recent American Decisions. By J. H. BALFOUR BROWNE, of the Middle Temple, Esq., Barrister-at- Law, Registrar to the Railway Commission. 8vo. 1873. 18s. CHANCERY and Vide " EQUITY." Daniell's Chancery Practice. The Practice of the High Court of Chancery, with some observations on the Pleadings in that Court. By the late EDMUND ROBERT DANIELL, Barrister-at- Law. Fifth Edition, by LEONARD FIELD and EDWARD CLENNELL DUNN, Barristers-at-Law ; with the assistance of JOHN BIDDLE, of the Master of the Rolls' Chambers. 2 vols. 8vo. 1871. 41. 4s. %* All standard Law Works are kept in StocJc, in law talf and other bindings. 119, CHANCERY LAXE, LONDON, W.C. CHANCERY- Continued. The Practice of the High Court of Chancery and the Court of Chan- cery (Funds) Act, 1872, together with Appendices containing the Act, and the Rules and Orders thereunder, and a Collection of Forms. By LEONARD FIELD and EDWARD CLENNELL DUNN, Barristers-at-Law. 8vo. 1873. 8*. 6d. "It is the merit of Mr. Daniell's 'Practice' that it takes nothing as known. The reader is minutely instructed what he is to do and hotf he is to do it, and if he closely follows his guide he cannot go wrong. " Law Timet. Daniell's Chancery Forms. Forms and Precedents of Pleadings and Proceedings in the High Court of Chancery, with Practical Notes and Observations, and References to the Fourth Edition of Daniell's Chancery Practice ; and incorporating the Forms in Braithwaite's Record and Writ Practice. By LEONARD FIELD and EDWARD CLENNELL DUNN, Barristers-at-Law, and JOHN BIDDLE, of the Master of the Rolls' Chambers. Third Edition. By W. H. UPJOHN. (In the press.) Morgan's Acts and Orders, Fifth Edition. 1876. The Statutes, General Orders, and Rules of Court relating to the Practice, Pleading, and Jurisdiction of the Supreme Court of Judi- cature, particularly with reference to the Chancery Division, and the Actions assigned thereto. With copious Notes. Fifth Edition. Carefully revised and adapted to the new Practice by GEORGE OSBORNE MORGAN, M.P., one of Her Majesty's Counsel, and CHALONER W. CHUTE, of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister- at -Law, and late Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford. In 1 vol. Deuiy 8vo. 1876. II. 10*. "A most valuable feature is the annotation of the Kules of Court, which give all the recent cases, and is as useful as a new edition cf any of the works on Judicature Acts only. This edition of Mr. Morgan's treatise must, we believe, be the most popular with the profession." Law Tinus, Decembers, 1876. " Jn the shape in which it now appears we have no donbt this edition will meet with a very favourable reception by the professions, and will exceed in demand any of its pre- decessors. "--Law Journal, December 30, 1876. "The practitioner will find iu the present edition, a lucid and compendi ius statement of the substance of the Consolidated and other Orders of the Court of Chancery, which, though not expressly incorporated in the new enactments, are, by implication, left un- touched by them, placed side by side with the Judicature Acts and Rules of Court. .... This new edition will maintain and enhance the high reputation deservedly gained by the original work."-iau> Magatine and Review, February, 187'. Morgan arid Davey's Chancery Costs. Vide "Costs." Orders and Rules of the High Court of Justice, Chancery Division. Published by authority, as issued. CHURCH AND CLERGY. Phillimore. ^"EcclesiasticalLaw." Stephen's Laws relating to the Clergy. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1848. 21. 18. CIVIL LAW. Bowyer's Commentaries on the Modern Civil Law. By Sir GEORGE BOWYER. D.C.L., Royal 8vo. 1848. 18*. Bowyer's Introduction to the Study and Use of the Civil Law. By Sir GEORGE BOWYER, D.C.L. Royal 8vo. 1874. 5*. Cumin's Manual of Civil Law. A Manual of (Jivil Law, containing a Translation of, and Commentary on, the Fragments of the XII. Tables, and the Institutes of Justinian ; the Text of the Institutes of Gains and Justinian arranged in parallel columns ; and the Text of the Fragments of Ulpian, and of Selec- tions from Paul's Receptae Sententiae. By P. CUMIN, M.A., Barrister-at-Law. Second Edition. Medixuu 8vo. 1 865. 1 8*. Greene. Vide "Roman Law." ** All standard Law Wvrki are kept in Stuck, in law calf and other lindingt. 6 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. CIVIL \_^\N -Continued. Mears. Vide "Roman Law." Vpet Commentarius ad Pandectas, Translated into English. Parti. The Contract of Sale. (Book xviii.) By SIR ROLAND KNYVET WILSON, Bart., of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister-at-Law. Royal 8vo. 1876. Net II. Is. COLLISIONS. Lowndes' Admiralty Law of Collisions at Sea. 8vo. 1867. 7s. 6rf. COLONIAL LAW. Clark's Colonial Law. A Summary of Colonial Law and Practice of Appeals from the Plantations. 8vo. 1834. 11. 4. Vanderlinden. Vide "Dutch Law." COMMENTARIES ON THE LAWS OF ENGLAND. Bowyer. Vide " Constitutional Law." Broom and Hadley's Commentaries on the Laws of England. By HERBERT BROOM, LL.D., of the Inner Temple, Barrister-at-Law ; Reader in Common Law to the Inns of Court : Author of " A Selection of Legal Maxims," &c. ; and EDWARD A. HADLEY, M.A., of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister-at-Law ; late Eellow of Trinity Coll., Cambridge. 4 vols. 8vo. 1869. 3Z. 3. " Messrs. Broom and Hadley have been unsparing in their editorial labours. There are abundant reference notes, so that the diligent student can consult the authorities if he is so disposed. Besides the table of contents, there are an appendix and a copious index tc each volume. Nothing that eoulH be done to m-ike the work useful and handy has been left undone." Law Journal, November 19, 1K69. COMMERCIAL LAW. Levi's International Commercial Law. Being the Principles of Mercantile Law of the following and other Countries viz. : England, Scotland, Ireland, British India, British Colonies, Austria, Belgium, Brazil, Buenos Ayres, Den- mark, France, Germany, Greece, Hans Towns, Italy, Netherlands, Norway, Portugal, Prussia, Russia, Spain, Sweden. Switzerland, United States, and Wiirtemburg. By LEONE LEY I, Esq., P.S.A., F.S.S., of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister-at-Law, Professor of the Principles and Practice of Commerce at King's College, London, &c. Second Edition. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1863. II 15a. Smith. Vide "Mercantile Law." COMMON LAW. Braithwaite. Vide "Oaths." Fisher. Vide " Digests." Orders and Rules of the High Court of Justice, Common Law Divisions. Published by Authority, as issued. Prentice. Vide "Action." Smith's Manual of Common Law. A Manual of Common Law, comprising the fundamental principles and the points most usually occurring in daily life and practice ; for the Prac- titioner, Student, and General Reader. By JOSIAH W. SMITH, B.C.L., Q.C., Judge of County Courts. Eighth Edition. (In the press.) " Admirably conceived and executed Eminently lucid and concise . . . . . A pocket-book of pith and essence of common law." Leguleian. " Mr. .] osial i Smith possesses, in an eminent degree, that kind of logical skill which exhibits itself in the simple arrangement, but exhaustive division, of wide and complicated subjects, and is, moreover, gifted with the rare power of accurate condensation." Solicitors' Journal. " To more advanced students, and to the practitioner, whether barrister or attorney, we think the ' Manual of Common Law ' a most useful and convenient companion It is compiled with the scrupulous care and the ability which distinguish Mr. Smith's previous works." Juritt. ' Smith's .Manuals of Common Law nnd Equity must be resorted to as the open sesames to the learning requisite in the Final Examination of the Incorporated Law Society." From Dr. HOLLIT'S ^Lecture, p. 1 1. ** AH ttandard Law Works arekept in Stock, in law calf and ot/ter bindings. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. COMMONS AND INCLOSURES. Chambers' Digest of the Law relating to Commons and Open Spaces. Including Public Parks and Recreation Grounds ; with Official Documents, Bye-Laws, Statutes and Cases. By GEORGE F. CHAMBERS, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Im- perial 8vo. 1877. 6s. 6d. Cooke on Inelosures. The Acts for facilitating the In- closure of Commons in England and Wales ; with a Treatise on the Law of Rights of Commons, in reference to these Acts, &c., &c. With Forms as settled by the Inclosure Commissioners. By G. WINGROVE COOKE, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Fourth Edition. 12mo. 1864. 16*. COMPANY LAW. Fide "Joint Stocks." COMPANIES, LIABILITIES OF PROMOTERS OF. Finlason's Report of the Case of Twycross v. Grant, in the Court of Common Pleas and the Court of Appeal, with the Judg- ments, as revised by the Judges, And an Introduction and Notes, containing notices of the previous cases on the subject. By W. F. FIXLASON, of the Middle Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 8vo. 1877. Net, 2s. 6d. COMPANY PRECEDENTS. Paloier. F; Tiinet "Woolryeh. Vide "Lights." ECCLESIASTICAL. Finlason's Folkestone Ritual Case. The Judgment of the Judicial Committee in the Folkestone Ritual Case, with an Historical Introduction and brief Notes. By W. F. FINLASON, of the Middle Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 8vo. 1877. Net, 2s. 6d. Phillimore's (Sir R.) Ecclesiastical Law. The Ecclesiastical Law of the Church of England. With Supplement, containing the Statutes and Decisions to end of 1875. By SIB ROBERT PHILLIMORE, D.C.L., Official Principal of the Arches Court of Canterbury ; Member of Her Majesty's Most Honourable Privy Council. 2 vols. 8vo. 1873-76. 31. 7s. 6d. %* The Supplement may be had separately, price 4s. 6d., sewed. Stephens. Vide " Church and Clergy." ELECTIONS. FitzGerald. Fide "Ballot." Rogers on Elections, Registration, and Election Agency. With an Appendix of Statutes and Forms. Twelfth Edition. By F. S. P. WOLFERSTAN, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 12mo. 1876. 11. 10*. "The book maintains its reputation as a well arranged magazine of all the authorities on the subject."* Lav; Journal, August 19, 1876. "Mr. Wolferstan has added a new chapter on election agency, which contains a care- fnl and valuable digest of the decisions and dicta on this thorny subject." Solicitor*' Journal, October 28, 1876. %* AUttandard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings. 14 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. ENGLAND, LAWS OF, Bowyer. Vide "Constitutional Law." Broom and Hadley. Vide " Commentaries." Syms' Code of English Law (Principles and Practice) for handy reference in a Solicitor's office. ByF. R. SYMS, Solicitor. 12mo. 1870. 16s. EQUITY, ad Vide CHANCERY. Seton's Forms of Decrees, Judgments, and Orders in the High Court of Justice and Courts of Appeal, having especial reference to the Chancery Division, vith Practical Notes. Fourth Edition. By R. H. LEACH, Esq., Senior Registrar of the Court of Chancery ; P. G-. A. WILLIAMS, of the Inner Temple, Esq. ; and H. W. MAY, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barristers-at-Law. In 2 vols. Vol. I. Royal 8 vo. 1877. II. 10s. "This Volume contains Judgment by Default and at Trial; Motion for Judgment ; Transfer and Payment of Funds into and out of Court ; Proceedings in Chambers: Dis- covery and Production; Injunctions; Stop Orders and Charging Orders; Jffe Exeoi Attachment of Debts; Transfer and Consolidation of Actions; Prohibition Patents; Interpleader ; Issues ; Referees and Arbitration Receivers ; Trustees (including Trustees Act) ; Charities ; Orders affecting Solicitors ; and Taxation of Bills of Costs, ,fec., &c. " Cannot fail to commend itself to practitioners. Nothing need be said as to the value of the work, which is one of settled authority, and we have only to congratulate the profession upon the fact that this edition comes out uuder circumstances peculiarly calculated to enhance its value." Law Times, February 24, 1877. ' The impre.wion derived from our perusal of the book is that it represents the result of conscientious and intelligent labour on the part of the editors, and we think it deserves, and will obtain, the confidence of the profession." Solicitor? Journal, April 7, 1877. (Vol. H. in the pi-ess.) Smith's Manual of Equity Jurisprudence. A Manual of Equity Jurisprudence for Practitioner and Students, founded on the Works of Story, Spence, and other writers, and on more than a thousand subsequent cases, comprising the Fundamental Principles and the points of Equity usually occurring in General Practice. By JOSIAH W. SMITH, B.C.L., Q.C., Judge of County Courts. Twelfth Edition. 12mo. 1878. (Nearly ready.) 12s. 6d. "To sum up all in a word, for the student and the jurisconsult, the Manual is the nearest approach to an equity code that the present literature of the law is able to furnish "Law Timet. "It will be found as useful to the practitioner as to the student." Solicitors Journal. " Mr. Smith's Manual has fairly won for itself the position of a standard work." Jurist. " It retains and that deservedly, the reverence of both examiners and students." Dr. EOLLIT'S Lecture on a Course of Reading. " There is no disguising the truth ; the proper mode to use this book is to learn its pages by heart." Law Magazine and Review. Smith's (Sidney) Principles of Equity. 8vo. 1856, II. 5s. EVIDENCE. Archbold. Frde Criminal." Roseoe. Vide "Criminal" Roscoe. Vide " Nisi Prius." EXAMINATION GUIDES Bedford's Guide to the Preli- minary Examination for Solicitors. Fourth Edition. 12mo. 1874. Net, Bs. Bedford's Digest of the Preliminary Examina- tion Questions-on English and Latin, Grammar, Geography, History, French Grammar, and Arithmetic, with the Answers. 8vo. 1875. 18s. Bedford's Preliminary Guide to Latin Gram- mar. 12mo. 1872. Net, 3s. Bedford's Intermediate Examination Guide to Bookkeeping. Second Edition. 12mo. 1875. Net, 2s. 6d. Bedford's Final Examination Guide to Bank- ruptcy. Third Edition. 12mo. 1877. 6. %* All standard Law Worlot are kept vn Stock, in law calf and other bindings. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. 15 EXAMINATION GUIDES -Continued. The following are published the day after each Examination : Bedford's Preliminary. Containing the Questions of the Preliminary Examinations. Edited by E. H. BEDFORD, Soli- citor. Sewed. Net, Is. Bedford's Intermediate. Containing the Questions and Answers at the Intermediate Examinations. Edited by E. H. BEDFORD, Solicitor. Michaelmas Term. 1877. No. 36. Sewed. Net. 1*. %* Nos. 1 to 34. 6d. each. No. 35. Is. Bedford's Final. Containing the Questions and Answers at the Final Examinations. Edited by E. H. BEDFORD, Solicitor. Michaelmas Term. 1877. No. 35. Sewed. Net, Is. %* Nos. 1 to 33. 6d. each. No. 34. Is. Butlin. Vide "Articled Clerks." Head. Vide "Statutes." Lynch and Smith. Vide " Judicature Acts. " Rubinstein and "Ward. Vide " Articled Clerks." EXECUTORS. Williams' Law of Executors and Ad- ministrators. A Treatise on the Law of Executors and Ad- ministrators. Seventh Edition. By the Rt. Hon. Sir EDWARD VAUGHAN WILLIAMS, late one of the Judges of Her Majesty's Court of Common Pleas, and WALTER VAUGHAN WILLIAMS, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1873. 31. 16s. FACTORY ACTS. Notcutt's Factory and Workshop Acts. Comprising all the Laws now in force (including the Act of 1874) for the regulation of Labour in Factories and Workshops, with Introduction, Explanatory Notes, and Notes of decided cases, by GEORGE JARVIS NOTCUTT, of the Middle Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 12mo. 1874. 9s. FARM, LAW OF. Addison ; Cooke. Vide "Agricultural Law." Dixon's Law of the Farm A Treatise on the Law of the Farm. Fourth Edition. By HENRY PERKINS, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. (In the press.) FIXTURES. -Amos and Ferard on Fixtures. Second Edition. Royal 8vo. 1847. 16*. Woodfall. See "Landlord and Tenant." FORMS Chitty's Forms. Eleventh Edition. By THOS. CHITTY and THOS. WILLES CHITTY, Esqre. (In preparation.) Corner's Forms of Writs and other Pro- ceedings on the Crown side of the Court of Queen's Bench. 8vo. 1844. 7s. 6d Dailiell's Chancery Forms. Forms and Precedents of Pleadings and Proceedings in the High Court of Chancery, with Practical Notes and Observations, and References to the Fourth Edition of Daniell's Chancery Practice ; and incorporating the Forms in Braithwaite's Record and Writ Practice. By LEONARD FIELD and EDWARD CLENNELL DUNN, Barristers-at-Law, and JOHN BIDDLE, of the Master of the Rolls' Chambers Third Edition. By W. H. UPJOHN. (In the press.) Moore's Solicitor's Book of Practical Forms. 12mo. 1852. 7s. 6d. HIGHWAYS. Bateman's General Highway Acts. Second Edition. With a Supplement containing the Highway Act of 1864, &c. With Notes by C. MANLEY SMITH, Esq., one of the Masters of the Queen's Bench. 12mo. 1865. 10s. 6d. %* All standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law coif and other bindings. 16 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. H I GHW AY S .-Confined. Shelford's Law of Highways. The Law of Highways ; including the General Highway Acts for England and Wales, and other Statutes, with copious Notes of the Decisions thereon ; with Forms. Third Edition. With Supplement by C. MANLEY SMITH, Esq., one of the Masters of the Queen's Bench. 12mo. 1865. 15*. %* The Supplement may be had separately, price 3s. sewed. INCLOSURES. Vide "Commons." INDIAN LAW. Montriou; the Hindu Will of Bengal With an Introductory Essay, &c. Royal 8vo. 18*70. Net, II. 10s* Norton's Leading Cases on the Hindu Law^ of Inheritance. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1870-71. Net, 21. 10s. INFANTS. Ebsworth's Law of Infants. A Handy Book of the Law of Infants. By JOHN EBSWORTH, Esq., Solicitor. 12mo. 1861. 3. Forsyth's Law relating to the Custody of Infants in Cases of difference between Parents or Guardians. 8vo. 1850. 8s. INJUNCTIONS. Seton. Vide " Equity." INSURANCE. Arnould on the Law of Marine Insu- rance. Fifth Edition. By DAVID MACLACHLAN, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1877. 3Z. " As a text book, Arnould is now all the practitioner can want, and we congratulate, the editor upon the skill with which he has incorporated the new decisions. Law Time*, Oct. 6th, 1877. Hopkins' Manual of Marine Insurance. 8vo. 1867. 18s. Lowndes. Vide "Average." INTERNATIONAL LAW Amos' Lectures on Inter- national Law\ Delivered in the Middle Temple Hall to the Students of the Inns of Court, by SHELDON AMOS, M.A., of the Inner Temple, Barrister-at-Law ; Professor of Jurisprudence (including International Law) to the Inns of Court ; Professor of Jurisprudence in University College, London. Royal 8vo. 1874. 10s. 6d Kent's International Law. Kent's Commentary on International Law. Edited by J. T. ABDY, LL.D., Judge of County Courts. Second Edition. Revised and brought down to the present time. Crown 8vo. 1878. (Just ready.) 10s. 6d. "Dr. Abdy has done all Law Students a great service in presenting that portion ol Kent's Commentaries which relates to public international Law in a single volume, neithet large, diffuse, nor expensive." " Altogether Dr. Abdy has performed his task in a manner worthy of his reputation His book will be useful not only to Lawyers and Law Students, for whom it was primaril) intended, but also for laymen. It is well worth the study of every member of an enlighteneo and civilized community." Solicitors' Journal. Levi's International Commercial Law. Being the Principles of Mercantile Law of the following and other Countries viz. : England, Ireland, Scotland, British India, British Colonies, Austria, Belgium, Brazil, Buenos Ayres, Denmark, France, Germany, Greece, Hans Towns, Italy, Netherlands, Norway, Portugal, Prussia. Russia, Spam, Sweden, Switzerland, United States, and Wiirtemberg. By LEONE LEVI, Esq., F.S.A., F.S.S., of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister- at-Law, Professor of the Principles and Practice of Commerce at King's College, London, &c. Second Edition. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1863. U. 15s. %* All standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. 17 INTERNATIONAL LAW -Continued. Prize Essays on International Law By A. P. SPKAGUE, Esq., Counsellor of Law in the United States, and 11. PAUL LACOMBE, Advocate in France. With an Introduc- tion by His Excellency DON ARTURO DE MARCOARTU, Ex-Deputy to the Cortes. Royal 8vo. 1876. 7s. 6d. Vattel's Law of Nations. By JOSEPH CHITTY, Esq. Royal 8vo. 1834. II. Is. Wildman's International Law. Institutes of Inter- national Law, in Time of Peace and Time of War. By RICHARD WILDMAN, Barrister-at-Law. 2 vols. 8vo. 1849-50. II. 2s. 6d. INTESTATE SUCCESSIONS Colin's Essay on Intestate Successions. According to the French Code. By BAR- THELEMY HARDY COLIN, of the Middle Temple. 12mo 1876. 6s. "A very intelligent essay." Late Time*, February 24, 1877. JOINT STOCKS. Jordan's Joint Stock Companies. A Handy Book of Practical Instructions for the Formation and Management of Joint Stock Companies. Fifth Edition. 12mo. 1875. Net, 2s. 6d. Palmer Vide "Conveyancing." Thring's (Sir H.) Joint Stock Companies' Law. The Law and Practice of Joint Stock and other Public Companies, in- cluding the Statutes, with Notes, and the Forms required in Making, Administering, and Winding-up a Company, with a Supplement containing the Companies' Act, 1867, and Notes of Recent Decisions. By SIB HENRY THRING, K.C.B., The Parliamentary Counsel Third Edition. By GERALD A. R. FITZGERALD, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, and Fellow of St. John's College, Oxford. 12mo. 1875. II. 'This, as the work of the original draughtsman of the Companies Act of 1862, and well-known Parliamentary counsel, Sir Henry Thring, is naturally the highest authority on the subject." The Times, April 21, 1876. JUDGMENTS. Pask's Judgments, Executions, and Crown Debts. The Judgments Law Amendment Acts relating to Real Property, 22 & 23 Viet., c. 35, and 23 & 24 Viet., c. 38, 23 & 24 Viet. c. 115, and 27 & 28 Viet. c. 112. With Notes, References to Cases, and Index : forming an Appendix to " The Practice of Registering," &c. By JAMES PASK, Chief Clerk to the Registrar to the Court of Common Pleas, Westminster. Third Edition. 12mo. 1866. Sewed. Net, 2*. Seton. Vide " Equity." JUDICATURE ACTS. Braithwaite. Vide "Oaths." Clowes' Compendious Index to the Supreme Court Of Judicature Acts, and to the Orders and Rules issued thereunder. By W. CLOWES, Esq., one of the Registrars of the Court of Chancery. Second Edition, revised and enlarged (Uniform in size with the Queen's Printer's Edition of the Acts and Rides.) 1875. Half bound. 10s Qd. %* THE ABOVE, with the Acts and Rules (Authorized Edition), Orders in Council, and additional rules, court fees, &c., COMPLETE IN ONK VOLUME, bound in limp leather. 11. 5s. %* All standard Law Works are kept in Stock in law calf and other bindings. 18 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. JUDICATURE ACTS -Continued. Leys' Complete Time-Table to the Rules under the SupremeCourtof Judicature Act, 187S. Show- ing all the periods fixed by the Rules within or after which any proceed- ings may be taken. By JOHN KIRKWOOD LEYS, M. A., of the Middle Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. RoyalSvo. 1875. Net, Is. 6d. Lynch and Smith's Introduction to the Final Examination. Being a collection of the questions set by the Incorporated Law Society, with the answers adapted to meet the recent extensive alterations made by the JUDICATURE ACT, 1873. By H. FOULKS LYNCH, Solicitor, and ERNEST AUGUSTUS SMITH, Solicitor, Clifford's Inn, Prizeman ; Senior Prizeman of the Incorporated Law Society, and Brodrip Gold Medalist, 1872. Vol. I. The Principles of the Law. Post 8 vo. 1874. 12s. Lynch's Epitome of Practice in the Supreme Court of Judicature in England. With References to Acts, Rules, and Orders. For the Use of Students. Royal 8vo. Third Edition. Incorporating the Appellate Jurisdiction Act, 1876, and the Rules of the Supreme Court, December, 1875, and June, 1876. 1876. Net, 1*. Morgan. Vide "Chancery." Scott. Vide " Costs." Stephen's Judicature Acts 1873, 1874, and 1875, consolidated. With Notes and an Index. By Sir JAMES STEPHEN, one of Her Majesty's Counsel. 12mo. 1875. 4s. 6d. Wilson's JudieatureActs,Rules and Forms. With Notes and a copious Index, and additional Rules, forming a COM- PLETE GUIDE TO THE NEW PRACTICE. By ARTHUR WILSON, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Royal 12mo. 1875. 18s. %* A LARGE PAPER EDITION OF THE ABOVE (for marginal notes), with Additional Rules. Royal 8vo. 1875. 11. 5s. (A Second Edition of the above is in active preparation.) "The references are ample, and the description of the matter referred to is clear. The result of a very careful examination of Mr. Wilson's book is that it is executed with great care and thoroughness, and that it will be of the utmost value to all those on whom the task falls, whether as practitioners or as administrators of the law, of applying and adapting the new practice and procedure." Solicitors' Journal, October 23, 3875. " We have nothing but praise to bestow upon the annotating ot the rules. We have no doubt it will maintain a position in the front rank of the works upon the all-engrossing subject with which it deals." Late Times, October 16, 1875. " Mr. Wilson has appended to the Acts and Kules, especially the latter, a valuable body of notes, which we are sure will be found useful." Law Journal, Oct. 30, 1875. " Mr. Arthur Wilson, as might have been expected, is particularly successful in deal- ing with the Rules of Court, to which, indeed, his notes are an almost indispensable accompaniment." Late Magazine, November 1875. JURISPRUDENCE. Amos, Law as a Science and as an Art. An Introductory Lecture delivered at University College at the commencement of the session 1874-5. By SHELDON AMOS, Esq., M.A., Barrister-at-Law. 8vo. 1874. Net, 1. 6d. Phillimore's (J. G.) Jurisprudence. An Inaugural Lecture on Jurisprudence, and a Lecture on Canon Law, delivered at the Hall of the Inner Temple, Hilary Term, 1851. By J. G. PHILLIMORE, Esq., Q.C. 8vo. 1851. Sewed. 3s. 6d. ** All standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. 19 JUSTICE OF THE PEACE. Arnold's Summary of the Duties of a Justice of the Peace out of Sessions. Summary Convictions. By Sir T. J. ARNOLD, Chief Metropolitan Police Magistrate. 8vo. 1860. II. Gs. Burn's Justice of the Peace and Parish Officer. Edited by the following Barristers, under the General Superinten- dence of JOHN BLOSSETT MAULE, Esq., Q.C., Recorder of Leeds. The Thirtieth Edition. VoL I. containing titles "Abatement" to " Dwellings for Artizans;" byTHOS. SIRRELL PRITCHARD, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Recorder of Wenlock. Vol. II. containing titles " Easter Offering " to " Hundred ;" by SAML. BOTELER BRISTOWE, Q.C., M.P., of the Inner Temple, Esq. Vol. III. containing titles " Indictment " to " Promissory Notes ;" by LEWIS W. CAVE, Q.C., of the Inner Temple, Esq., Recorder of Lincoln. VoL IV. containing the whole title " Poor ;" by JAMES EDWD. DAVIS, Esq., Stipendiary Magistrate for Stoke-upon-Trent. (Sold separately, price 11. 11s. 6d.) VoL V. con- taining titles "QuoWarranto" to "Wreck;" by JOHN BLOSSETT MAULE, Esq., Q.C., Recorder of Leeds. Five vols. 8vo. 1869. n. 7s Since the publication in 1845 of the former Edition of Bum'i Justice of the Peace and Parish Officer the whole range of the Law which Magistrates had to administer has undergone more or less alteration, and, indeed, the time which has elapsed since that publication appeared has doubtless worked as great a change in the Magistrates them- selves : so that to very many of the Gentlemen now composing the body of Justices the Encyclopedic Work of Burn must be, if not entirely unknown, at least unfamiliar as a book of reference. Paley. Vide "Convictions." Stone. Vide " Petty Sessions." JUSTINIAN, INSTITUTES OF .-Cumin. Fide "Civil Law." Greene. Vide "Roman Law." Mears. Vide "Roman Law." Voet. Vide "Civil Law." LAND DRAINAGE. Thring's Land Drainage Act. With an Introduction, Practical Notes, an Appendix of Statutes relating to Drainage, and Forms. By THEODORE THRING, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 12mo. 1861. 7. LAND TAX Bourdin's Land Tax. An Exposition of the Land Tax ; its Assessment and Collection, with a statement of the rights conferred by the Redemption Acts. By MARK A. BOUR- DIN, of the Inland Revenue Office, Somerset House (late Registrar of Land Tax). Second Edition. Crown 8vo. 1870. 4s. LANDLORD AND TENANT. Woodfall's Law of Landlord and Tenant. A Practical Treatise on the Law of Landlord and Tenant, with a full Collection of Precedents and Forms of Procedure. Eleventh Edition. Containing an Abstract of Leading Propositions, and Tables of certain Customs of the Country. By J. M. LELY, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Royal 8vo. 1877. (Just ready.) 11. 16s. LAW, GUIDE TO. A Guide to the Law for General Use. By a Barrister. Twenty-first Edition. 1877. Net, 2s. 6d. "There may be many students of both branches of the profession who will find the following pages au assistance to them in the couise of their reading, not in substitution of but together with, or preliminary to, the voluminous and highly technical works which they have necessarily to examine." %* All standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf andol/ier bindings. 20 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS/ LAW LIST. Law List (The). Comprising the Judges and Officers of the different Courts of Justice, Counsel, Special Pleaders, Draftsmen, Conveyancers, Attorneys, Notaries, &c., in England and Wales ; to which are added the Circuits, Judges, Treasurers, Registrars, and High Bailiffs of the County Courts, District Registries and Registrars under the Probate Act, Lords Lieu- tenant of Counties, Recorders, Clerks of the Peace, Town Clerks, Coroners, Colonial Judges, and Colonial Lawyers having English Agents, Metropolitan Police Magistrates, Law Agents, Law and Public Officers, Circuits of the Judges and Counsel attending Circuit and Sessions, List of Sheriffs and Agents, London Commis- sioners to Administer Oaths in the Supreme Court of Judicature in England, Conveyancers Practising in England under Certificates obtained in Scotland, &c., &c., and a variety of other useful matters so far as relates to Special Pleaders, Draftsmen, Conveyancers, Attorneys, Solicitors, Proctors and Notaries. Compiled by WILLIAM HENRY COUSINS, of the Inland Revenue Office, Somerset House, Registrar of Stamped Certificates, and of Joint Stock Companies. Published annually. By authority. 1877. Net, 10s. 6d. LAW REPORTS. Fide pages 29-30. LAWYER'S COMPANION. Fide "Diary." LEGACIES. Roper's Treatise on the Law of Lega- cies. Fourth Edition. By H. H. WHITE. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1847. 37. 3s. LEXICON Vide "Dictionary." LICENSING. Lely and Foulkes' Licensing Acts, 1828, 1869, 1872, and 1874; Containing the Law of the Sale of Liquors by Retail and the Management of Licensed Houses ; with Notes to the Acts, a Summary of the Law, and an Appendix of Forms. Second Edition. By J. M. LELY and W. D. I. FOULKES, Esqrs., Barristers-at-Law. Royal 12mo. 1874. 8s. " Messrs. Lely and Fpulkes's plan is to print in full the principal Acts, and to inter- polate between the sections of each of these statutes all subsidiary enactments, distin- guishing them by brackets and marginal notes .... These notes are usually sensible and to the point and give evidence both of care and knowledge of the subject." Solicitors' Journal. LIEN. Cross' Treatise on the Law of Lien and Stoppage in Transitu. 8vo. 1840. 15s. LIGHTS Woolryeh's Practical Treatise on the Law of Window Lights. Second Edition. 12mo. 1864. 6s. LOCAL GOVERNMENT. Vide "Public Health." LUNACY. Elmer's Practice in Lunacy. The Practice in Lunacy under Commissions and Inqusitions, with Notes of Cases and Recent Decisions, the Statutes and General Orders, Forms and Costs of Proceedings in Lunacy, an Index and Schedule of Cases. Sixth Edition. By JOSEPH' ELMER, of the Office of the Masters in Lunacy. 8vo. 1877. 21s. MAGISTERIAL LAW. Burn. Fide "Justice of Peace." Leeming and Cross. Vide " Quarter Sessions." Paley. Vide "Convictions." Pritchard. Vide " Quarter Sessions." Stone. Vide "Petty Sessions." *+*AU standard Law Workt are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindinyt. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. 21 MAINTENANCE AND CHAMPERTY. Tapp on Main- tenance and Champerty. An Inquiry into the present state of the Law of Maintenance and Champerty, principally as affecting Contracts. By WM. JOHN TAPP, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 12mo. 1861. is. 6d. MANDAMUS. Tapping on Mandamus. The Law and Practice of the High Prerogative Writ of Mandamus as it obtains both in England and Ireland Royal Svo. 1848. II. Is. MARINE INSURANCE Vide " Insurance." MARTIAL LAW. Finlason's Treatise on Martial Law, as allowed by the Law of England in time of Rebellion ; with Practical Illustrations drawn from the Official Documents in the Jamaica Case, and the Evidence taken by the Royal Commission of Enquiry, with Comments Constitutional and Legal. By W. F. FINLASON, Esq.. Barrister-at-Law. Svo. 1866. 12*. MERCANTILE LAW Boyd. Vide "Shipping." Brooke. Vide "Notary." Russell. Vide "Agency." Smith's Mercantile Law. A Compendium of Mercantile Law. By the late JOHN WILLIAM SMITH, Esq. Ninth Edition. By G. M. DOWDESWELL, of the Inner Temple, Esq., one of Her Majesty's Counsel. Royal Svo. 1877. 1?. 18s. "We can safely say that, to the practising Solicitor, few books will be found more useful than the ninth edition of ' Smith's Mercantile Law.'" Late Magazine, Nov. 1877. Tudor's Selection of Leading Cases on Mercan- tile and Maritime Law. With Notes. By 0. D. TUDOR, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Second Edition. Royal Svo. 1868. II 18s. METROPOLIS BUILDING ACTS -Woolrych's Metropolis Building Acts, together with such Clauses of the Metropolis Management Acts, 1855 and 1862, and other Acts, as more par- ticularly relate to the Buildings Acts, with Notes, Explanatory of the Sections and of the Architectural Terms contained therein. Second Edition. By NOEL H. PATERSON, M. A, of the Middle Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 12mo. 1877. 8s. 6d. MINES. Rogers' Law relating to Mines, Minerals, and Quarries in Great Britain and Ireland; with a Summary of the Laws of Foreign States and Practical Directions for obtaining Government Grants to work Foreign Mines. Second Edition Enlarged. By ARUNDEL ROGERS, Esq., Bar- rister-at-Law. Svo. 1876. II. Us. 6d. "Most comprehensive and complete." Law Times, June 17, 1876. "Although issued as a Second Edition, the work appears to have been almost entirely re-written and very muca improved. ... I he volume will prove invaluable as a work of legal reference." The MiniiiQ Journal, May 13, 1876. MORTGAGE. Coote's Treatise on the Law of Mort- gage. Third Edition. Royal Svo. 1850. Net, II. MORTMAIN. Rawlinson's Notes on the Mortmain Acts ; shewing their operation on Gifts, Devises and Bequests for Charitable Uses. Designed for the Use of Solicitors in Adminstra- tion Suits in the Chancery Division of the High Court of Justice. By JAMES RAWLINSON, Solicitor. Demy Svo. 1877. Inter- leaved. Net, 2s. 6d. ** All standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindinys. 22 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. MUNICIPAL ELECTIONS.- Vide "Ballot." NAVY. Thring's Criminal Law of the Navy, with an Introductory Chapter on the Early State and Discipline of the Navy, the Rules of Evidence, and an Appendix comprising the Naval Discipline Act and Practical Forms. Second Edition. By Theodore Thring, of the Middle Temple, Barrister at-Law, late Commissioner of Bankruptcy at Liverpool, and C. E. Gifford, Assistant- Pay master, Royal Navy. 12mo. 1877. (Just ready.) ' 12s. Qd. "In the new edition, the procedure, naval regulations, forms, and all matters con- nected with the practical administration of the law have been classified and arranged by Mr. Oifford, so that the work is in every way useful, complete, and up to date." Naval and Military Gazette, December 12, 1877. NISI PRIUS. Roseoe's Digest of the Law of Evidence on the Trial of Actions at Nisi Prius. Thirteenth Edition. By JOHN DAY, one of Her Majesty's Counsel, and MAURICE POWELL, Barrister-at-Law. Royal 12mo. 1875. (Bound in one thick volume calf or circuit, 5s. Qd., or in two convenient vols. coif or circuit, 10s. net, extra.) " The work Itself has long ago won a position altogether unique, and in the hands of its present editors there is no fear that the position will be lost." Law Journal, July 10, 1875 Selwyn's Abridgment of the Law of Nisi Prius. Thirteenth Edition. By DAVID KEANE, Q.C., Recorder of Bedford, and CHARLES T. SMITH, M.A., one of the Judges of the Supreme Court of the Cape of Good Hope. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1869. (Published at 21. 16s.) Net, II. NOT ANOA. Vide "Digests." NOTARY. Brooke's Treatise on the Office and Prac- tice of a Notary of England. With a full collection of Precedents. Fourth Edition. By LEONE LEVI, Esq., P.S.A. of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister-at-Law. 8vo. 1876. II. 4s. NUISANCES. FitzGerald. Vide "Public Health." OATHS. Braithwaite's Oaths in the Supreme Court of Judicature. A Manual for the use of Commissioners to Administer Oaths in the Supreme Court of Judicature in England. Part I. containing practical information respecting their Appoint- ment, Designation, Jurisdiction, and Powers ; Part II. comprising a collection of officially recognised Forms of Jurats and Oaths, with Explanatory Observations. By T. W. BRAITHWAITE, of the Record and Writ Clerks' Office. Fcap. 8vo. 1876. 4s. 6d. "Specially useful to Commissioners." Law Magazine, February, 1877. " The work will, we doubt not, become the recognized guide of commissioners to ad- minister oaths." Solicitors' Journal, May 6, 1876. PARTNERSHIP. Pollock's Digest of the Law of Part- nership. By FREDERICK POLLOCK, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Author of " Principles of Contract-at-Law and in Equity." Demy 8vo. 1877. 8s. Qd. %* The object of this work is to give the substance of the Law of Partnership (excluding Companies) in a concise and definite form. " Mr. Pollock's work appears eminently satisfactory . . . the b >ok is praiseworthy in design, scholarly and complete in execution." Saturday Review, May 6, 1877. " Mr. Pollock is most accurate in his law, which is a matter of much importance, in a book whose contents may almost be got by heart by a hard-working student." The Spectator, May 12, 1H77. " A few more books written as carefully as the ' Digest of the Law of Partnership,' will, perhaps, remove some drawbacks, and render English law a pleasanier and easier subject to study than it is at present." The Examiner, March 31, 1877. PATENTS. Hiudmarch's Treatise on the Law rela- ting to Patents. 8vo. 1846. ll. is. Seton. Vide "Equity." ** All standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. 28 PERSONAL PROPERTY. Smith's Real and Personal Property. A Compendium of the Law of Real and Personal Property Primarily Connected with Conveyancing ; Designed as a Second Book for Students, and as a Digest of the most useful Learning for Practitioners. By JOSIAH W. SMITH, B.C.L., Q.C., Judge of County Courts. Fifth Edition. 2 vols. Demy 8vo. 1877. (Just ready.) 21. 2s. PETITIONS. Palmer. Vide " Conveyancing." PETTY SESSIONS. Stone's Practice for Justices of the Peace, Justices' Clerks and Solicitors at Petty and Special Sessions, in Summary Matters and Indictable Offences, with a List of Summary Convictions and of Matters not Criminal. With Forms. Eighth Edition. By THOMAS SIRRELL PRITCHARD, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, Recorder of Wenlock. In 1 vol. DemySvo. 1877. (Just ready.) 11. 10s. " The design of the present Edition has been developed with a view to offer to Magis- trates :uid Practitioner*, in one volume of moderate size, a complete general account of the Procedure at t'etty Sessions in Summary Matters and Indictable Offences, in such a consecutive fjrm, according to the usual order of events, as to render easily attainable information on any poiut of procedure as it may arise at any given period of the pro. ceedings." Extract from Preface. "In clearness of exposition, in choice of matter, and, above all, in orderliness of arrangement, the book leaves little to be desired The book, as a whole, is thoroughly satisfactory, and, having gone carefully through it, we can recommend it with confidence to the numerous bi>dy of our readers who are daily interested in the subjects to which it relates." Solicitors' Journal, Dec. 8th, 1877. PLEADING. Archbold. Firfe "Criminal" POOR LAW. Davis' Treatise on the Poor Laws. Being VoL IV. of Burn's Justice of the Peace. 8vo. 1869. II. Us. 6d. POWERS. Farwell on Powers. A Concise Treatise on Powers. By GEORGE FARWELL, B.A, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 8vo. 1874. II. Is. " We recommend Mr. Farwedl's book as containing within a small compass what would otherwise have to be sought out in the pages of hundreds of confusing reports. * The Law November, 1874. PRECEDENTS. Vide " Conveyancing." PRINCIPAL AND AGENT. Petgrave's Principal and Agent. A Manual of the Law of Principal and Agent. By E. C. PETGRAVE, Solicitor. 12mo. 1857. 7s. 6d. Petgrave's Code of the Law of Principal and Agent, with a Preface. By E. C. PETGRAVE, Solicitor. Demy 12mo. 1876. Net, sewed, 2s. PRIVY COUNCIL. Lattey's Handy Book on the Prac- tice and Procedure before the Privy Council. By ROBERT THOMAS LATTEY, Attorney of the Court of Queen's Bench, and of the High Court of Bengal ; and Advocate of the Courts of British Burmah. 12mo. 1869. 6*. PROBATE. Browne's Probate Practice: a Treatise on the Principles and Practice of the Court of Probate, in Contentious and Non-Contentious Business, with the Statutes, Rules, Fees, and Forms relating thereto. By GEORGE BROWNE, Esq., Barrister- at-Law, Recorder of Ludlow. 8vo. 1873. II. 1*. " A cursory glance through Mr. Browne's work shows that it has been compiled with more than ordinary care and intelligence. We should consult it with every confidence, Md consequently recommend it to those who require an instructor in Probate Court prac- tice." lava times, June 21, 1873. PUBLIC HEALTH. Chambers' Exhaustive Index to the Public Health Act, 1875 ; with the full Text of the Act, and of most of the Incorporated Acts. By GEO. F. CHAMBERS, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Imp. 8vo. 1877. 4s. 6d. ** All standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings. 24 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. PUBLIC HEALTH.-Omned. Chambers' Digest of the Law relating to Public Health and Local Government. With notes of 1073 leading Cases. Various official documents ; precedents of By-laws and Regulations. The Statutes in full. A Table of Offences and Punishments, and a Copious Index. Seventh Edition, enlarged and revised, with SUPPLEMENT containing newLocal Govern- ment Board By-Laws in full. Imperial 8vo. 1875-7. 28s. %* The SUPPLEMENT may be had separately, price 9s. Chambers' Popular Summary of Public Health and Local Government Law. Imperial 8vo. 1875. Net, Is. 6d. FitzGerald's Public Health and Rivers Pol- lution Prevention Acts. The Law relating to Public Health and Local Government, as contained in the Public Health Act, 1875, with Introduction and Notes, showing all the alterations in the Existing Law, with reference to the Cases, &c.; together with a Sup- plement containing "The Rivers Pollution Prevention Act, 1876." With Explanatory Introduction, Notes, Cases, and Index. By G. A. R. FITZGERALD, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Royal Svo. 1876. II. Is. " A copious and well-executed analytical index completes the work which we can confidently recommend to the officers and members of sanitary authorities, and all interested in the subject matter of the new Act.'' Law Magazine and Review, February, 1877. "Mr. FitzGerald's treatise is well adapted for the professional advisers of sanitary boards." Public Health. December 1, 1876. " Mr. FitzGerald comes forward with a special qualification for the task, for he was employed by the Government in the preparation of the Act of 1875; and, as he himself says, has necessarily, for some time past, devoted attention to the Law relating to public health and local government. 1 ' Law Journal, April 22, 1876. PUBLIC LAW t Bowyer's Commentaries on Uni- versal Public Law. By Sir GEORGE BOWYER, D.C.L. Royal 8vo. 1854. 12. 1*. QUARTER SESSIONS. Leeming & Cross's General and Quarter Sessions of the Peace. Their Jurisdiction and Practice in other than Criminal matters. Second Edition. By HORATIO LLOYD, Esq., Recorder of Chester, Judge of County Courts, and Deputy-Chairman of Quarter Sessions, and H. F. THURLOW, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 8vo. 1876. II. Is. " The present editors appear to have taken the utmost pains to make the volume com- plete, and, from our examination of it, we can thoroughly recommend it to all interested in the practice of quarter sessions." Luw Time*, March 18, 1876. Pritchard's Quarter Sessions. The Jurisdiction, Prac- tice and Procedure of the Quarter Sessions in Criminal, Civil, and Appellate Matters. By THOS. SIRRELL PRITCHARD, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, Recorder of Wenlock. Svo. 1875. 11. 2s. "We can confidently say that it is written throughout with clearness and intelligence, and that both in legislation and in case law it is carefully brought down to the most recent date." Solicitors' Journal, May 1, 1875. RAILWAYS. Browne. Vide " Carriers." Lely's Railway and Canal Traffic Act, 1873. And other Railway and Canal Statutes ; with the General Orders, Forms, and Table of Fees. By J. M. LELY, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Post Svo. 1873. 8s. %,* All standard Law Worki are Icept in Stock, in law talfand other bindings. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. 2> Simon's Law relating to Railway Accidents, in- cluding an Outline of the Liabilities of Railway Companies as Carriers generally, concisely Discussed and Explained. 12mo. 1862. ' 3s. REAL PROPERTY. Dart. Fide "Vendors and Purchasers." Leake's Elementary Digest of the Law of Pro- ' perty in Land. Containing : Introduction. Part I. The Sources of the Law. Part II. Estates in Land. By STEPHEN MARTIN LEAKE, Barrister-at-Law. 8vo. 1874. II. 2s. \* The above forms a complete Introduction to the Study of the Law of Real Property. Shelford's Real Property Statutes. Eighth Edition. By T. H. CARSON, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq. 8vo. 1874. II. 10* Smith's Real and Personal Property. A Com- pendium of the Law of Real and Personal Property, primarily connected with Conveyancing. Designed as a second book for Students, and as a digest of the most useful learning for Practi- tioners. By JOSIAH W. SMITH, B.C.L., Q.C., Judge of County Courts. Fifth Edition. 2 vols. Demy 8vo. 1877. 11. 2s. "As a refresher to the memory, and a repository of information that is wanted in dailj practice, it will be found of great value." Jurist. . . . "He has given to the student a book which he may read over and over again with profit and pleasure." Law Times. "The work before us will, we think, be found of very great service to the practitioner.' Solicitor^ Journal. ..." I know of no volume which so entirely fulfils the requirements of a student' tcit book." From Dn. ROLLIT'S Lecture. RECEIVERS. Seton. Vide Equity." REGISTRATION. Rogers. Fide "Elections." REGISTRATION CASES. Hop wood and Coltman's Registration Cases. Vol. I. (1868-1872). Net,'2l.lSs. Calf Vol. II. Parti. (IS73). Net, 10*.; Part II. (1874). Net, 10*. 6d; Part III. (1875). Net, 4*. (id,; Part. IV. (1876). Net, 4s. Part V. (1877). Net, 3*. sewed. REPORTS. Vide pages 29-30. RIVERS POLLUTION PREVENTION. FitzGerald's Rivers Pollution Prevention Act, 1873. With Explanatory Introduction, Notes, Cases, and Index. Royal 8vo. 1876. 3s. 6d. "A. well-timed addition to the author's previous work on Sanitary Law." Law Magazine, February, 1877. ROMAN LAW. Cumin. Fide "Civil." Greene's Outlines of Roman Law. Consisting chiefly of an Analysis and Summary of the Institutes. For the use of Students. By T. WHITCO.MBE GREENE, B.C.L., of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister-at-Law. Third Edition. Foolscap 8vo. 1875. 7s. 6d. Mears' Student's Ortolan. An Analysis of M. Ortolan's Institutes of Justinian, including the History and Generalization of ROMAN LAW. By T. LAMBERT MEARS, M.A., LL.D. Lond., of the Inner Temple, Barrister-at-Law. Piiblishedby permission of the late M. Ortolan. PostSvo. 1876. 12*. 6d. " We have no doubt that this book is intended to meet a real demand. Nor have we any reason to doubt that the work has been well and faithfully executed . . . However, frith Law Times, December 30. 1876. %* All standard Law Worlct are kept in Stock, in law caff and other Undingt. 2 STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. SALE. The Contract of Sale -with a View to its Codification. By ARTHUR COHEN, one of Her Majesty's Counsel, FREDERIC THOMPSON, of Lincoln's Inn, and H. D. WARR, of the Middle Temple, Barristers-at-Law. (In preparation.) SAUNDERS' REPORTS. Williams' (Sir E. V.) Notes to Saunders' Reports. By the late Serjeant WILLIAMS. Continued to the present time by the Right Hon. Sir EDWARD VAUGHAN WILLIAMS. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1871. 21. 10*. SHIPPING, and vide " Admiralty." Boyd's Merchant Shipping Laws ; being a Consolida- tion of all the Merchant Shipping and Passenger Acts from 1854 to 1876, inclusive ; with Notes of all the leading English and American Cases on the subjects affected by Legislation, and an Appendix containing the New Rules issued in October, 1876 ; forming a com- plete Treatise on Maritime Law. By A. C. BOYD, LL.B., of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, and Midland Circuit. 8vo. 1876. II. 5s. " Mr. Boyd confines himself to short, and as far as we can jndge correct, statements of the effect of actual decisions." Solicitors' Journal. January 20. 1877. " The great desideratum is obviously a good index, and this Mr. Boyd has taken par- ticular care to supply. We can recommend the work as a very useful compendium of shipping law." Law Time*, December 30, 1876. SPECIAL SESSIONS PRACTICE. Stone. Vide "Petty Sessions. " STAMP LAWS. Tilsley's Stamp Laws. A Treatise on the Stamp Laws, being an Analytical Digest of all the Statutes and Cases relating to Stamp Duties, with practical remarks thereon. Third Edition. With Tables of all the Stamp Duties payable in the United Kingdom after the 1st January, 1871, and of Former Duties, &c., &c. By EDWARD HUGH TILSLEY, of the Inland Revenue Office. 8vo. 1871. 18*. STATUTES, and vide " Acts of Parliament." Biddle's Table of Statutes. A Table of References to unrepealed Public General Acts, arranged in the Alphabetical Order of their Short or Popular Titles. Second Edition, including Refer- ences to all the Acts in Chitty's Collection of Statutes. Royal 8vo. 1870. (Published at 9s. 6d.) Net, 2. 6d. Chitty's Collection of Statutes, with Supple- ments, to 1877. A Collection of Statutes of Practical Utility ; with notes thereon. The Third Edition, containing all the Statutes of Practical Utility in the Civil and Criminal Administration of Justice to the Present Time. By W. N. WELSBY and EDWARD BEAVAN, Esqrs., Barristers-at-Law. In 4 very thick vols. Royal 8vo. 1865. 12J. 12*. With Supplemental Volume to the above, comprising the Statutes 186572. By HORATIO LLOYD, Esq., Judge of County Courts, and Deputy-Chairman of Quarter Sessions for Cheshire. Together 5 vols. Royal 8vo. 186572. 15/. 16a. Vol. II., Part I., 1873, 7s. 6d. Part II., 1874, 6s. Part III., 1875, 16s. Part IV., 1876, 6s. 6d. Part V., 1877, 4s. 6d., sewed. %* Continued Annually. " When he (Lord Campbell) was upon the Bench lie always had this work by him, and ne statutes were ever referred to by the Bar, which be could not find in it." Head's Statutes by Heart; being a System of Memoria Technica, applied to Statutes, and embracing Common Law, Chan- cery, Bankruptcy, Criminal Law, Probate and Divorce, and Convey- ancing. By FREDERICK WILLIAM HEAD, of the Inner Temple, Student- at-Law. Demy 8vo. 1877. Net, Is. Qd. %* All standard La:o Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other binding*. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. 27 Lyneh's Statute Law of 187O, for the use of Students for the Incorporated Law Society's Examinations. 8vo. Sewed. Net, Is. 1872, Net, Is. ; 1873, Is. 6d. ; 1874, 1*. ; 1875, Is. ; 1876, Is. sewed. 'Public General Statutes, royal 8vo, issued in parts and in complete volumes, and supplied by the Publishers of this Catalogue immediately on publication. *The Revised Edition of the Statutes, prepared under the direction of the Statute Law Committee, and published by the authority of Her Majesty's Government. Imperial 8vo. Vol. 1. Henry III. to James II., ' 1235-1685 . II. 1*. Od. 2. Will. & Mary to 10 Geo. III., 1688-1770 .100 3. 11 Geo. III. to 41 Geo. III., 1770-1800 . 17 4. 41 Geo. III. to 51 Geo. III., 1801-1811 . 18 5. 52 Geo. III. to 4 Geo. IV., 1812-1823 .150 6. 5 Geo. IV. to 1 & 2 Will. IV., 1824-1831 .160 7. 2 & 3 Will. IV. to 6 & 7 Will IV., 1831-1836 . 1 10 8. 7 Will. IV. & 1 Viet, to 5 & 6 Viet., 1837-1842 . 1 12 6 9. 6 & 7 Viet, to 9 & 10 Viet., 1843-1846 . 1 11 6 10. 10 & 11 Viet, to 13 & 14 Viet., 1847-1850 .176 11. 14 & 15 Viet, to 16 & 17 Viet., 1851-1853 .140 12. 17 & 18 Viet, to 19 & 20 Viet., 1854-1856 .160 13. 20 Viet, to 24 & 25 Viet. 1857-1861 . 1 10 %* Volume XIV. in preparation. 'Chronological Table of and Index to the Statutes to the end of the Session of 1874. Third Edition, imperial 8vo. II. 5s. * Printed by Her Majesty's Printers, and Sold by STEVENS & SONS. TORTS. Addison on Wrongs and their Remedies. Being a Treatise on the Law of Torts. By C. G. ADDISON, Esq., Author of " The Law of Contracts." Fourth Edition. By F. S. P. WOLFERSTAN,Esq.,Barrister-at-Law. Royal 8vo. 1873. II. 18*. TRADE MARKS. Rules under the Trade Marks' Re- gistration Act, 187S (by Authority). Sewed. Net, Is. Mozley's Trade Marks Registration. A Concise View of the Law and Practice of Registration of Trade Marks, as altered by the Trade Marks Registration Act, 1875, and Amended Act, 1876, and the Decisions thereon. With an Appendix con- taining a copy of the above Acts and Rules, with Directions for Registration, &c. Also the Merchandise Marks Act, 1862. By LIONEL B. MOZLEY, Solicitor of the Supreme Court. Crown 8vo. 1877. 3s. 6d. " Mr. Mozley has done his work well, and his book furnishes a very intelligible guide to a very abstruse subject." Sebastian on the Law of Trade Marks. The Law of Trade Marks aud their Registration, and matters connected there- with, including a chapter on Goodwill. Together with Appendices containing Precedents of Injunctions, &c. ; The Trade Marks Regis- tration Acts, 1875 7, and the Rules and Instructions thereunder; The Merchandise Marks Act, 1862, and other Statutory enact- ments; and The United States Statute, 1870, and the Treaty with the United States, 1877 ; With a copious Index. By LEWIS BOYD SEBASTIAN, B.C.L., M.A., of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 8vo. 1878. (Juatreaiiy.) 14s. Trade Marks' Journal. 4to. Sewed. (Issued weekly.) Nos. 1 to 120 are now ready. Net, each Is. Index to Vol. I. (Nos. 147.) Net, 3s. Ditto, VoL II. (Nos. 4897.) Net, 3s. \* All standard Law Works arckept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings. STEVENS AND SONS' LAW PUBLICATIONS. TRADE Wood's Law Of Trade Marks. Containing the Mer- chandise Marks' Act, 1862, and the Trade Marks' Registration Act, 1875 ; with the Rules thereunder, and Practical Directions for obtaining Registration ; with Notes, full Table of Cases and Index. By J. BIGLAND WOOD, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at- Law. 12mo. 1876. 5s. "Mr. Wood's 'Table of Cases' is noTel and ingenious, each case being distinguished by a concise description in a parallel column." The Athenceum, June 24, 1876. TRAMWAYS. Sutton's Tramway Acts. The Tramway Acts of the United Kingdom, with Notes on the Law and Practice, and an Appendix containing the Standing Orders of Parliament, Rules of the Board of Trade relating to Tramways, and Decisions of the Referees with respect to Locus Standi. By HENRY SUTTON, B.A., of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister-at-Law. Post 8vo. 1874. 12s. USES Jones (W. Hanbury) on Uses. 8vo. 1862. 7s. VENDORS AND PURCHASERS. Dart's Vendors and Pur- chasers. A Treatise on the Law and Practice relating to Ven- dors and Purchasers of Real Estate. By J. HENKY DART, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq.. one of the Six Conveyancing Counsel of the High Court of Justice, Chancery Division. Fifth Edition. By the AUTHOR and WILLIAM BARBER, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 1876. 31. 13s. 6rf. " A standard work like Mr. Dart's is beyond all praise." The Law Journal, February 12, 18T6. VICE. Amos (Professor Sheldon) on the Laws for the Regulation of Vice. A comparative Survey of Laws in Force, for the Prohibition, Regulation, and Licensing of Vice in England and other Countries. With an Appendix giving the text of Laws and Police Regulations as they now exist in England, in British Dependencies, in the chief towns of Continental Europe, and in other parts of the world ; a precise narrative of the passing of the English Statutes ; and an Historical Account of English Law and Legislation on the subject from the earliest times to the present day. By SHELDON AMOS, M.A., Barrister-at-Law and Professor of Jurisprudence in University College, London. 8vo. 1877. 18s. WATERS. Woolrych on the Law of Waters. Including Rights in the Sea, Rivers, Canals, &c. Second Edition. 8vo. 1851. Goddard. Vide " Easements." Net > 10 - WILLS. Montriou. Vide " Indian Law.'' Rawlinson's Guide to Solicitors on taking In- structions for Wills. 8vo. 1874. 4s. Theobald's Concise Treatise on the Construc- tion Of Wills. With Table of Cases and Full Index. By H. S. THEOBALD, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, and Fellow of Wadham College, Oxford. 8vo. 1876. II. "Mr. Theobald has certainly given evidence of extensive investigation, conscientious labour, and clear exposition." Law Magazine, May, 1877. "We desire to record our decided impression, after a somewhat careful examination, that this is a book of great ability and value. It bears on every page traces of care and sound judgment. It is certain to prove of great practical usefulness, for it supplies a Want which was beginning to be distinctly felt." Solicitors' Journal, February 24, 1877. "His arrangement being good, and his statement of the effect of the decisions being clear, his work cannot fail to be of practical utility, and as such we can commend it to the attention of the profession." Law Times, December Zi. Itfl. " It is remarkably well arranged, and its contents embrace all the principal heads ou the subject." Law Journal, Februarys, 1877. "Williams. Vide " Executors." WINDOW LIGHTS. Woolryeh. Vide "Lights." W RONGS. Vide "Torts." \* All standard Law Worlct are Icept in Stock, in law calf and other lindingt. 119, CHANCERY LANE, LONDON, W.C. 2 REPORTS. STEVENS AND SONS HOLD THE QUIRE STOCK OF THE FOLLOWING, AND HAVE A LARGE STOCK OF SECOND- HAND REPORTS. -PRICES ON APPLICATION Adolphus and Ellis, Queen's Bench, 12 vols., 1834-40. N. S. 15 vols., 1841-50. Barnewall and Adolphus, King's Bench, 5 vols., 1830-34. Alderson, 5 vols., 1817-22. Cress-well, 10 vols., 1822-30. Barren and Austin, Election Cases, 1 voL, 1842. Barren and Arnold, 1 voL, 1843-46. Beavan, Rolls Court, 1838-66. Bell, Crown Cases, 1 voL, 1858-60. Calthrop, King's Bench, 1 voL, 1609-18. Gary, Chancery, 1 vol., 1557-1604. Central Criminal Court Sessions Papers (pub- lished after every Session). Clark and Finnelly, House of Lords, 12 vols., 1831-46. Craig and Phillips, Chancery, 1 voL, 1841. Common Bench Reports, vols. 1 to 8, 1845-9. Cooper temp. Cottenham, Chancery, 2 vols., 1834-48. temp. Eldon, Chancery, 1 voL, 1815. Dearsley, Crown Cases, 1 voL, 1852-56. and Bell, Crown Cases, 1 voL, 1856-58. De Gex, Macnaghten and Gordon. Chancery, 8 vols., 1851-57 and Jones, 4 vols., 1857-60. Fisher and Jones, 4 vols., 1860-62. Jones and Smith, 4 vols., 1862-66. De Gex, Bankruptcy Appeals, 1 voL, 1845-48. Fisher and Jones, 1 part, 1860. Jones and Smith, 1 voL, 1862-65. Denison, Crown Cases. 2 vols., 1844 52. Dow and Clark, House of Lords, 2 vols., 1827-32. D rewry, 4 vols. 185259. Drewry and Smale, Chancery, 2 vols., 1860-65. Exchequer Reports, (Welsby, Hurlstone and Gordon,) 11 vols., 1847-56. Foster and Finlason, Nisi Prius, 4 vols., 1858-67. Haggard, Consistory, 2 vols., 1789-1821. Ecclesiastical, 3 vols. and voL 4, parts 1 and 2, 1827-33. Harrison and Rutherford, Common Pleas, lvoL,1866 68. \* All Law Reports are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindinyt. NEW WORKS AND IBW EDITIONS. Archbold's Practice in the Queen's Bench, Com- mon Pleas, and Exchequer Divisions of the High Court of Justice. Thirteenth Edition. Chalmers' Digest of the Law of Bills of Exchange, Promissory Notes, Cheeks, &c. By M. D. E. S. Chalmers, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Chitty on Bills of Exchange and Promissory Notes. Eleventh Edition. By /. A. Russell, Esq., Q.C., Judge of County Courts. (In the Press.) Chitty's Forms. Eleventh Edition. By Thomas Chitty and Thomas Willes Chitty, Esqrs. Daniell's Chancery Practice. Sixth Edition. DanielJ's Chancery Forms. Third Edition. (In the Press.) Dixon's Law of the Farm. Fourth Edition. By Henry Perkins, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Lowndes' Law of General Average. English and Foreign. Third Edition. By Richard Lowndes. Author of " The Admiralty Law of Collisions at Sea." (In the Press.) Middleton's Settled Estates Act, 1877. With Introduc- tion, Notes and Forms. By James W. Middleton, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq. , Barrister-at-Law. (In the Press.) Pitt -Lewis' County Court Practice. A complete Practice of the County Courts, including Admiralty and Bank- ruptcy, embodying the Act, Rules, Forms, and Costs, with Table of Cases and full Index. By 0. Pitt-Lewis, of the Middle Temple and Western Circuit, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, sometime Holder of the Studentships of the Four Inns of Court. Roscoe's Treatise on the Jurisdiction and Practice of the Admiralty Division of the High Court of Justice, and on Appeals therefrom. With a Chapter on the Admiralty Jurisdiction of the Inferior Courts and the Vice- Ad- miralty Courts. With an Appendix containing Statutes, Rules as to Fees and Costs, Forms, Precedents of Pleadings and Bills of Costs. By Edward Stanley Poscoe, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, author of " Outlines of Civil Procedure." (In the Press.) Sale, The Contract of, with a View to its Codifica- tion. By Arthur Cohen, Q.C., Frederic Thompson, of Lincoln's Inn, and H. D. Warr, of the Middle Temple, Esqs., Barristers-at-Law. Seton's Forms of Decrees, Judgments, and Orders in the High Court of Justice and Courts of Appeal, having especial reference to the Chancery Division. Fourth Edition. With Practical Notes. By R. H. Leach, Esq., Senior Registrar of the Chancery Division of the High Court of Justice, F. G. A. Williams, of the Inner Temple, Esq., and H. W. May, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barristers-at-Law. In 2vols., royal 8vo. ( Vol. II. in the Press.) Smith's Manual of Common Law. Eighth Edition. By Josiak W. Smith, B.C.L., Q.C., Judge of County Courts. (In the press.) Wilson's Judicature Acts, Rules, and Forms. Second Edition. Revised and Enlarged by Arthur Wilson of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. (Nearly ready.) "STEVENS~& SONS, 119, OHANCEEY LANE, LONDON, W.cT See also Catalogue, at end of this Volume. . STEVENS AND SONS, 119, CHANCERY LANE, W.C. Goddard's Treatise on the Law of Easements. Second Edition. By JOHN LEYBOURN GODDARD, of the Middle Temple, Esq , Bar- rister-at-Law. Demy 8vo. 1877. Price 16s. cloth. "Nowhere has the subject been treated so exhaustively, and wo may add, so scientifically as by Mr. Goddard. We recommend it to the most careful study of the law Btudent as well as to the library of the Practitioner." Law Times. Pollock's Digest of the Law of Partnership By FREDERICK POLLOCK, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Author of " Principles of Contract at Law and in Equity." Demy 8vo. 1877. PriceSs. Gd. cloth. " Mr. Pollock's work appears eminently satisfactory ... the book is praiseworthy in design, scholarly and complete in execution." Saturday Review, May 5, 1877 Morgan's Acts and Orders, 1876. The Statutes, General Orders, and Rules of Court relating to the Practice, Pleading, and Jurisdiction of the Supreme Court of Judicature, particularly with reference to the Chancery Division and the Actions assigned thereto. With Copious Notes. Fifth Edition. Carefully revised and adapted to the new Practice. By GEORGE OSBORNE MORGAN, M.P., one of Her Majesty's Counsel, and CHALONER WILLIAM CHUTE, of Lincoln's Inn, Barrister-at-Law, and late Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford. Demy 8vo. 1876. Price II. 10s. cloth. " This new edition will maintain and enhance the high reputation deservedly gained by the original work." Law Magazine, February, 1877. " We have no doubt this edition will meet with a very favourable reception by the profession, and will exceed in demand any of its predecessors." Law Journal, December 30, 1876. " This edition of Mr. Morgan's treatise must, we believe, be the most popular with the profession." Law Times, December 9, 1876. Williams' Law and Practice in Bankruptcy Comprising the Bankruptcy Act, the Debtors Act, and the Bankruptcy Repeal and Insolvent Court Act of 1869, and the Rules and Forms made under those Acts. Second Edition. By ROLAND VAUGHAN WILLIAMS, of Lincoln's Inn, and WALTER VAUGHAN WILLIAMS, of the Inner Temple, assisted by FRANCIS HALLETT HARDCASTLE, of the Inner Temple, Esqrs., Barristers-at-Law. Demy 8vo. 1876. Price U. 8s. cloth. " It would be difficult to speak in terms of undue praise of the present work The profession has now one of the best, if not the best, treatise on the Law of Bankruptcy." Walker's Treatise on Banking Law. Including the Crossed Checks Act, 1876, with Dissertations thereon ; also references to some American Cases and full Index. By J. DOUGLAS WALKER, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Demy 8vo. 1877. Price 14s. cloth. " Persons who are interested in banking law may be guided out of many a difficulty by consulting Mr. Walker's volume." Law Times, May 19, 1877. Wharton's Law Lexicon, or Dictionary of Jurisprudence, Explaining the Technical Words and Phrases employed in the several Departments of English Law ; including the various Legal Terms used in Commercial Business ; with an Explanatory as well as Literal translation of the Latin Maxims contained in the Writings of the Ancient and Modern Commentators. Sixth Edition. Revised in accordance with the Judicature Acts, by J. SHIRE SS WILL, of the Middle Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. Super-royal 8vo. 1876. Price 21. 2s. cloth. " As a work of reference for the library, the handsome and elaborate edition of ' Wharton's Law Lexicon ' which Mr. Shiress Will has produced, must supersede all former issues of that well- known work." Law Magazine and Review, August, 1876. FitzGerald's Puhlic Health and Rivers Pollution Prevention Acts. The Law relating to Public Health and Local Government, as contained in the Public Health Act, 1875. With Introduction and Notes showing all the Alterations in the Existing Law ; with References to all the Cases Decided on Sections of Former Acts, which are re-enacted in this Act, together with a Supplement containing "THE RIVEBS POLLUTION PREVENTION ACT, 1876." With Explanatory Introduction, Notes, Cases, and Index. By GERALD A. R. FITZGERALD, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at- Law. Royal 8vo. 1876. Price II. Is. cloth. *#* The Supplement, containing " THE RIVERS PoLLimoN PREVENTION ACT, 1876," may be had separately. Price 3s. 6d. cloth. " Mr. G. A. B. FitzGerald was employed by the Government in the preparation of the Act of 1875, and is therefore specially well fitted to comment upon its provisions and discuss the judicial decisions which have been engrafted on the older statutes incorporated in it." Pall Mall Gazette, April 3, 1*76. Pritchard's Quarter Sessions. The Jurisdiction, Practice, and Procedure of the Quarter Sessions in Criminal, Civil, and Appellate Matters. By THOMAS SIRRELL PRITCHARD, of the Inner Temple, Barrister-at-Law, Recorder of Wenlock. Thick 8vo. 1875. Price 21. 2s. cloth. " We congratulate Mr. Pritchard on the state of order he has produced out of the chaotic mass he has dealt with, and we think much credit is due to him for his evident painstaking." Law Journal, April 24, 1875. \* All Standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings. A 000412193 5 ** Sec also Catalogue at end of this Volume. STEVENS AND SONS, 119, CHANCERY LANE, W.C. Greenwood's Manual of Conveyancing. A Manual of the Practice of Conveyancing, showing the present Practice relating to the daily routine of Conveyancing in Solicitors' Offices. To which are added Concise Common Forms and Precedents in Conveyancing, Conditions of Sale, Conveyances, and all other Assurances in constant use. Fifth Edition. By H. N. CAPEL, B.A., LL.B., Solicitor. Demy Svo. 1877. Price 15s. cloth. " The information under these heads is just of that ordinary practical kind which is learned from experience, and is not to be gathered trom treatises. A careful study of these pages would probably arm a diligent clerk with as much useful knowledge as he might otherwise take years of desultory questioning and observing to acquire." Solicitors' Journal. Boyd's Merchant Shipping Laws ; being a consolidation of all the Merchant Shipping and Passenger Acts from 1854 to 1876 inclusive ; with Notes of all the leading English and American Cases on the subjects affected by Legislation, and an Appendix containing the New Rules issued in October, 1876 ; forming a complete Treatise on Maritime Law. By A. C. BOYD, LL.B., of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, and Midland Circuit. Demy Svo. 1876. Price II. 5s. cloth. "The great desideratum la obviously a good Index, and this Mr. Boyd has taken particular care to supply. We can recommend the work as a very useful compendium of shipping law." Law Tiniin, December 80, 1876. Kent's Commentary on International Law. Edited by J. T. ABDY, LL.D., Judge of County Courts. Second Edition. Revised, and brought down to the present time. Crown Svo. 1878. Price 10s. 6d. cloth. (Just ready .) " Dr. Abdy has done all Law Students a great service in presenting that portion of Kent's Commentaries which relates to public international Law in a single volume, neither large, diffuse, nor expensive." Addison on Contracts. Being a Treatise on the Law of Contracts. By C. G. ADDISON, Esq., Author of the " Law of Torts." Seventh Edition. By L. "W. CAVE, of the Inner Temple, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, Recorder of Lincoln. Royal Svo. 1875. Price II. 18s. cloth. " At present this is by far the best book upon the Law of Contrast possessed by the profession ; and it is a thoroughly practical book. 1 * Law Tima. Rogers' Elections, Registration, and Election Agency, with an Appendix of Statutes and Forms. Twelfth Edition. By F. S. P. WOLFERSTAN, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. I2mo. 1876. Price II. 10s. cloth. " The book maintains its reputation as a well arranged magazine of all the authorities on the subject" Law Journal, August 19, 1876. Braithwaite's Oaths in the Supreme Court of Judicature. A Manual for the Use of Commissioners to Administer Oaths in the Supreme Court of Judicature in England. Part I. containing practical information respecting their Appointment, Designation, Jurisdiction, and Powers. Part II. comprising a collec- tion of officially recognised Forms of Jurats and Oaths, with Explanatory Observa- tions. By T. W. BRA1THWAITE, of the Record and Writ Clerks' Office. Fcap. 8ro. 1876. Price 4s. &d. cloth. "The work will, we doubt not, become the recognized guide of Commissioners to administer oaths." Sol icitorf Journal, May 6, 1876. Dart's Vendors and Purchasers. A Treatise on the Law and Practice relating to Vendors and Purchasers of Real Estate. By J. HENRY DART, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, one of the Six Conveyancing Counsel of the High Court of Chancery. Fifth Edition. By the AUTHOR and WILLIAM BARBER, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law. 2 vols. Royal Svo. 1876. Price 31. 13s. 6d. cloth. "A standard work like Mr. Dart's is beyond all praise." Law Journal, February 12, 1876. Thring's (Sir H.) Joint Stock Companies Law. The Law and Practice of Joint Stock and other Public Companies, including all the Statutes, with Notes, a Collection of Precedents of Memoranda and Articles of Association, and all the other Forms required in Making, Administering, and Winding-up Companies. By SIR HENRY THRING, K.C.B., the Parliamentary Counsel. Third Edition, considerably enlarged, with all the Cases brought down to the present time. By GERALD A. R. FITZGERALD, of Lincoln's Inn, Esq., Barrister-at-Law, and Fellow of St. John's College, Oxford. 12mo. 1875. Price It. cloth. " This, as the work of the original draughtsman of the Companies Act of 1862. aud well-known Parliamentary counsel, Sir Henry Thring, is naturally the highest authority on the subject." The Timei, April 21, 1876. %* All Standard Law Works are kept in Stock, in law calf and other bindings.