THE LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LOS ANGELES HISTORY OF POLITICAL ECONOMY AU right* rtitrvt* A HISTORY OF POLITICAL ECONOMY if JOHN KELLS INGRAM, LL.D. FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, DUBLIN itJ) preface PKOF. E. J. JAMES, PH.D. UNIVEBSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA Neto fJork: THE MACMILLAN COMPANY. 1902. COPYRIGHT, 1887, BY GEORGE W. DILLAWAY. Press of J. J. Little & Co. Astor Place, New York. PBEFACE. IT is with great pleasure that I embrace the opportunity afforded me by the publishers of Dr. Ingram's "History of Political Economy " to commend the book to the attention of the American public. Dr. Ingram needs no introduction to our students of economics. His work in the Encyclopaedia Britannica has attracted marked attention wherever earnest thinkers are studying the social and economic problems of our time, whether in Europe or America. The present treatise deserves especial notice, as the first serious attempt by a pro- perly qualified English writer to present a view of the progress of economic thought. The works of M'Culloch and Twiss on the same subject were of value only because there was nothing else on the same topic. They testify eloquently to the exceedingly primitive state of the history of economic thought and policy which existed in their day. The work of Blanqui, recently translated into English, is rather a history of economic systems (and a poor one even as such) than of economic theories and doctrines. Up to the time of the appearance of the nineteenth volume of the Encyclopaedia Britannica there was no essay on the subject in English which could be considered a very valuable one. We now Vave a treatise which will compare favourably with any work of similar compass in any other language. 1381036 vi PREFACE. It seems appropriate in this connection to emphasise briefly the importance of this service to our American schools and colleges. In no country, except possibly France, has there been such pure and unadulterated teaching of dogma in the realm of economics as in America. The teaching of thi? subject has been largely in the hands of clergymen or other people whose specialties, so far as they have had any, have lain in other directions. "When called upon to teach the subject they have ordinarily taken some standard text-book and taught it verbatim et literatim, adhering to the letter in a manner which would have seemed ridiculous even to the authors of the books, though they were oftentimes dogmatic enough themselves. The result was, of course, not merely superficiality, but an extreme form of doctrinaireism and a priori-ism, which even yet dominates to a large extent the public mind so far as this troubles itself with economic principles at all. The great phe- nomena of our modern industrial life do not allow themselves to be subsumed under any such simple economic forms. The result has been that in the case of those who really thought about the subject at all, and who tried to bring their practical ideas into harmony with the economic teaching which they had received, the sentiment took strong hold and found frequent expression that it is all very well to propound econo- mic doctrines, and they may be true in theory, but they will not work in practice. In the case of those who did not think of the matter at all there would be found the grossest incon- sistency between their professed economic doctrines and their actual views of public policy and economic phenomena. A change has recently taken place in the spirit and methods of teaching the subject, so that now there is scarcely a leading centre of college or university instruction in which the old PREFACE. vh plan has not been considerably modified. This is a change in the right direction, I believe, and whatever will hasten its progress deserves serious attention. To this end nothing will contribute more than a study of the history of the rise and development of economic systems and economic thought. A thoughtful study of the history of investigation and theories has valuable results in any branch of human learning, but above all in the field of moral, philosophical, and social science. The first lesson borne in upon the serious student of eco- nomic systems and economic thought is the essential relativity of economic theories, at least of all such as have been hitherto propounded. The dogmatist in the field of economics, the man who never learned anything from history, regards the whole past development of politics and theories as did Say, who looked upon the history of the science as a record of absurd and justly exploded opinions. But the man who studies them carefully in order to find out what measure of truth was in each form which prevailed and exercised a wide influence finds the conviction gradually borne in upon him that econo- mic systems and theories change with every great change in industry and in man. The axioms and theorems which apply to one form of society may have little or no application in another form, and any attempt to make such application may result in the most absurd conclusions. An explanation of the phenomena of industrial life in such a community as ancient Eome or mediaeval Europe will not serve as an explanation of the life of to-day. Nor will a theory which is adequate to the demands of an industrial state like England or America suit such a country as India or Africa. It is not, therefore, a science in which the laws and principles may be safely compared with the laws and principles of physics and chemistry, which, BO far as we know, are true in all times and placea In other tlii PREFACE. words, the science of economics must be relative and progres- sive, because the phenomena which form its subject-matter are changing all the time, not merely from age to age, but from country to country. 1 The view, therefore, expressed by Colonel Torrens over sixty years ago is, at least in the sense in which he was think- ing of it, an erroneous one. He wrote as follows : " In the progress of the human mind a period of controversy amongst the cultivators of any branch of science must necessarily precede the period of unanimity. With respect to Political Economy, the period of controversy is passing away, and that of unanimity is rapidly approaching. Twenty years hence there will scarcely be a doubt respecting any of its funda- mental principles." Mill, writing twenty years later, thought to formulate those principles on which everybody agreed, and believed confidently that on several topics, like that of value, for example, the last word had been spoken. Travers Twiss, in his lectures at Oxford in 1846, said that, while it was true that the simplest doctrines of the science were vigorously con- troverted during the earlier part of the century, yet all the great principles are now readily acquiesced in ; and he proposed to show how this had been accomplished. His attitude was significant. He proposed not to show the modicum of truth which lay in each of the great systems of economic policy and theory, but how they were all false, and how they had been gradually superseded by the pure and unadulterated system of truth as it existed in his day. Less than fifteen years after Twiss had written these words we find Professor Cairnes almost in despair over the prospects 1 The economic laws which may be discovered as the result ef a com- plete comparative view of human history and development belong, of course In A (\\fffrp.nt. rat.p.tmrv anil are ftasfrihfiri hv Dr. Inoram on D. 2Os. iaa different category, and are described by Dr. Ingram on p. PREFACE. it of the science on account of the continued agitation against what he is pleased to call its fundamental principles. He says in his first lecture delivered before the University of Dublin, in commenting upon Torrens' prophecy above quoted : " Five-and-thirty years have passed since that unlucky pro- phecy was uttered, and yet sudh questions as those respecting the laws of population, of rent, of foreign trade, the effects of different kinds of expenditure on distribution, the theory of prices all fundamental in the science are still unsettled, and must still be considered as ' open questions,' if that expression may be applied to propositions which are still vehemently debated, not merely by sciolists and smatterers who may always be expected to wrangle, but by the professed cultivators and recognised expounders of the science. So far from the period of controversy having passed, it seems hardly yet to have begun controversy, I mean, not merely respecting pro- positions of secondary importance or the practical application of scientific doctrines (for such controversy is only an evi- dence of the vitality of the science, and is a necessary con- dition of its progress), but controversy respecting fundamental principles which lie at the root of its reasonings, and which were regarded as settled when Colonel Torrens wrote." In the preface to the published lectures Professor Cairnes states it to be his purpose " to bring back the discussions of Political Economy to those tests and standards which were formerly considered the ultimate criteria of economic doctrine, but which have been completely lost sight of in many modern publications." Although he thus admits the existence of great difference of opinion, yet he also shows that he is a stead- fast believer in the ultimate truth of the old formulations, and an apologetic tone runs through his remarks, as if he needed to justify, to himself at least, his willingness to take X PREFACE. any notice of a set of men who were so blind as to deny the validity of the old system. Now, as we have noted above, a study of the history of economic systems and economic theories of society in its various industrial stages, and of the explanations offered of its industrial phenomena by contemporaneous writers, com- pletely changes such a mental attitude. The student becomes aware that every one of the great systems possessed some truth, and no one has been elaborated which contains the whole truth. He becomes aware of a still more important fact, and that is, that owing to the continual changes in the nature of the elements with which he has to deal, no uni- versal system, no system which shall be valid in all times and places, can at present, if indeed it ever can, be formu- lated. We can formulate for our time and country, for our type of society and industry, for our race and nation ; but such a formulation, even though perfectly correct, would pro- bably not hold for any other time or country or type at race, though it would, of course, hold true of them to just the extent to which they are similar to us and ours. As a result of this conviction, when a problem presents itself, the eco- nomist does not set out with a firm determination to force it at any cost into the old moulds. He recognises that there are probably new elements in the case which cannot be brought within the old formulas without changing the prob- lem to such an extent that its solution would be of no value, since it would no longer correspond to the actual problem to be solved. On the contrary, he devotes himself to a careful study of all the elements in the case, and while seeking help from all the solutions of other similar and dissimilar problems of other times and countries, recognises that after all the exist- ing problem is a new one, and that any attempt to apply the PREFACE. xi cut and dried recipes of an a priori system san only result in failure. Now, it is this mental attitude a recognition of the value of the services of the great thinkers of the past, combined with an equally full recognition that they were but creatures of their age, writing and thinking primarily for their time and society, and were circumscribed by the same limitations as hedged in their contemporaries in similar fields that every economic thinker should strive to attain. Only in this way can we do justice to the contributions of former thinkers, and at the same time keep our minds open for the reception of all new truth. Of course, there is more or less of this spirit in all the great writings on the subject of Political Economy. Mill, in particular, deserves praise for admitting to a certain extent the validity of the above view, but his knowledge of economic history was not sufficient and his " historical sense " was not sufficiently developed for him to come thoroughly under the influence of this truth. In his discussion of the theory of Distribution he acknowledged the justness of this conception, but failed to carry it into the domain of Production. He thus stamped himself as a believer in the existence of " natural laws " in economics in the Ricardian sense of that term. In developing this spirit a good text-book written from such a point of view is a great aid. We are under special obligations, therefore, to Dr. Ingram for the preparation of this convenient hand-book. It is believed that its general intro- duction into our college and university work would greatly stimulate the careful study of economic thought and policy. I may be pardoned one word in regard to the so-called " New Political Economy." It is perhaps a matter of indif- ference whether the change which has recently taken place in M PREFACE. the tendencies and methods of economic thought be dignified by a distinctive name or not. The important point is that there has been a great change, and that the valuable work in economics for the last twenty years has nearly all been done by men who are distinctly under the influence of thia new spirit, whether they profess themselves as adherents of the new school or not. The term "Historical School" has been employed to distinguish one set of writers and thinkers connected with the movement. There is much misunderstanding as to what these men have accomplished in economics, and as to what they are trying to accomplish. Their work is not limited, as many seem to think, to a study of former writers on economics. Their object is the same as that of previous investigators, viz., to find as far as possible the laws underlying the industrial progress of human society. They believe, however, that this can be done only by a care- ful study of the origin and development of human society on its industrial sides. The economic systems best adapted to further the industrial interests of society must change with every great change in social organisation, and with the gradual change in the character of man himself which is the result of advancing civilisation. It is believed that by a study of the economic systems of successful societies a clue may be dis- covered to a general law of industrial progress. By discovering and studying the essential features of many different national economies we may finally by comparison deduce (or, if you like it better, induce) a general rule of economic development which may form the basis of a general political economy. Whether this view be just or not and we must admit, I think, that the positive results in this particular direction are not all that could be desired, since they have been such as to lead some writers to give up any hope of ascertaining PREFACE. xiii any general laws of economics yet the negative results have been neither few nor unimportant. They have demonstrated beyond a doubt that some of the so-called orthodox views as to the " cosmopolitanism and perpetualism " of the natu- ral laws of Political Economy were erroneous. What were claimed to be fundamental principles of all economic theory have been proved to hold good only in a certain form of society which is to be found only on a very small portion of the earth's surface, and not even there, in the purity pre- supposed by the premises of this theory. This is a real service ; since next to offering a theory which will explain additional phenomena is the service which proves beyond a doubt that the generally accepted one does not and cannot explain known facts; for the result of such demon- stration must be a quickened zeal in discovering the true doctrine. The work of the so called Historical School has thus far, then, been primarily critical and destructive, though it has resulted in bringing to light an enormous amount of material, which must be utilised by him who would construct anew those places which have been torn down. To under- stand their work fully and this is an essential thing for every one who would comprehend the present tendencies in econo- mics a study of the history of economic theory is necessary. In this work no better guide is at present attainable for the English student than this book of Dr. Ingrain's. E. J. JAMES. UVOTRSITY or PENNSYLVANIA, PHILADELPHIA, BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE. THE reader is referred for fuller information to the following books on the history of Political Economy, all of which have been more or less, and some very largely, used in the prepara- tion of the present work : GENERAL HISTORIES. Sistoire de rficonomie Politlque en Europe depuis les anciens jusqu' a no* jours, by Jerome Adolphe Blanqui (1837- 38) ; of which there is an English translation by Emily J. Leonard (1880). Histoire de V Economic Politique, by Alban de Villeneuve- Bargemont (Brussels, 1839; Paris, 1841); written from the Catholic point of view. View of the Progress of Political Economy in Europe since the Sixteenth Utntury, by Travers Twiss, D.C.L. (1847). Die geschichtliche Entwickelung der National- Oekonomik und ihrer Literatur, by Julius Kautz (ad ed. 1860) ; a valuable work marked by philosophical breadth, and exhibiting the results of extensive research, but too declamatory in style ; the book sadly wants an index. Kritische Geschichte der National- Ckonomie und der Socialismus, by Emile Diihring (1871 ; 3d ed. 1879) ; characterised by its author's usual sagacity, but also by his usual per- verseness and depreciation of meritorious writers in his own field. Guida olio studio dell' Economia Politico,, by Luigi Cossa (1876 and 1878 ; Eng. trans. 1880). Geschichte der Nationalb'konomik, by H. Eisenhart (1881); a vigorous and original sketch. And, lastly, a brief but excellent history by H. von Scheel in the Handbuch der politischen Uekonomie (a great encyclopaedia of economic knowledge in all its extent and applications) ; edited by Gustav Schon berg (1882 ; 2d ed., enlarged and improved, 1886). To these histories proper must be added The Literature of Political Economy, by J. R. M'Culloch (1845), a book which might with advantage be re-edited, supplemented where imperfect, and continued to our own time. Some of the biographical and critical notices by Eugene Daire and others in the Collection det principaux ficonomistes will also be found useful, as well as the articles in the Dictionnaire de I' Economic Politiqvt of Coquelin and Guillaumin (1852-53; 3d ed. 1864), which is justly described by Jevons as " on the whole the best work of reference in the literature of the science." SPECIAL HISTORIES. Italy. Storia della Economia Pubblica in Italia, otsia Epilogo critico degli Economisti Italiani, by Count Giuseppe Pecchifl BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE. xv (1829), intended as an appendix to Baron Custodi'g collection of th Scrittori dassici Italiani di Economic, Politico,, 50 vols., comprising the writings of Italian economists from 1582 to 1804. There is a French translation of Pecchio's work by Leonard Gallois (1830). The book i not without value, though often superficial and rhetorical. Spain. Storia detta Economia Politico, in Espana (1863), by M. Colmeiro ; rather a history of economy than of economics of policies and institutions rather than of theories and literary works. Germany. Geschichte der Nationalokonomik in Deutschland (1874)- by Wilhelm Roscher ; a vast repertory of learning on its subject, with occa- sional side-glances at other economic literatures. Die neuere National- okonomie in ihren Hauptrichtungen, by Moritz Meyer (3d ed. 1882) : a useful handbook dealing almost exclusively with recent German specula- tion and policy. England. Zur Getchichte der Englischen VoUatoirthschafttlehre, by W. Roscher (185 1-52). The reader is also advised to consult the articles of the Encyclopaedia Britannica, ninth edition, which relate to the principal writers on political economy, especially those on Petty, Quesnay, Turgot, Smith, Say, and Ricardo. The present work, it should be stated, is for the most part a reproduction of the article " Political Economy," which appeared (1885) in yoL xix. of the Encyclopaedia Britannica. J.K.I CONTENTS. PAGE PREFACE . v BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE xiv CHAP. I. INTRODUCTORY 1 " II. ANCIENT TIMES 7 " III. THE MIDDLE AGES 34 '* IV. MODERN TIMES : Two FIRST PHASES . .. .32 " V. THIRD MODERN PHASE : SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY 55 " VI. THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL 196 " VII. CONCLUSION ........ 240 INDEX 247 OUTLINES OF THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. CHAPTER L INTRODUCTORY. IN the present condition of Political Economy, the production of new dogmatic treatises on the subject does not appear to be opportune. There are many works, accessible to every one, in which, with more or less of variation in details, what is known as the "orthodox" or "classical" system is ex- pounded. But there exists in England and other countries wide- spread dissatisfaction with that system, and much difference of opinion with respect both to the method and the doctrines of Economic Science. There is, in fact, good reason to believe that this department of social theory has entered on a transition stage, and is destined ere long to undergo a con- siderable transformation. But the new body of thought which will replace, or at leas; profoundly modify, the old, has not yet been fully elaborated. The attitude of mind which these circumstances seem to prescribe is that of pause and retrospection. It is thought that our position will be rendered clearer and our further progress facilitated by tracing historically, and from a general point of view, tb.e a POLITICAL ECONOMY. course of speculation regarding economic phenomena, and con- templating the successive forms of opinion concerning them in relation to the periods at which they were respectively evolved. And this is the task undertaken in the following pages. Such a study is in harmony with the best intellectual tendencies of our age, which is, more than anything else, characterised by the universal supremacy of the historical spirit. To such a degree has this spirit permeated all our modes of thinking, that with respect to every branch of knowledge, no less than with respect to every institution and every form of human activity, we almost instinctively ask, not merely what is its existing condition, but what were its earliest discoverable germs, and what has been the course of its development? The assertion of J. B. Say 1 that the history of Political Economy is of little value, being for the most part a record of absurd and justly exploded opinions, belongs to a system of ideas already obsolete, and requires at the present time no formal refutation. 2 It deserves notice only as reminding us that we must discriminate between history and antiquarianism : what from the first had no significance it is mere pedantry to study now. We need concern ourselves only with those modes of thinking which have prevailed largely and seriously influenced practice in the past, or in which we can discover the roots of the present and the future. When we thus place ourselves at the point of view of history, it becomes unnecessary to discuss the definition of Political Economy, or to enlarge on its method, at the outset. It will suffice to conceive it as the theory of social wealth, or to accept provisionally Say's definition, which makes it 1 " Que pourrions-nous gagner a recueillir des opinions absurdes, dea doctrines de'crie'es et qui merilent de I'Stre ? II serait a la fois inutile et fastidieux." tcvn. Pd. Pratique, IX me Partie. The "cependant" which follows doea not really modify this judgment. 8 See Roscher's (jetchichtt dcr National-cekonomik in Ueuttchland, Vorrede. INTRODUCTORY. 3 the science of the production, distribution, and consumption of wealth. Any supplementary ideas which require to be taken into account will be suggested in the progress of our survey, and the determination of the proper method of economic research will be treated as one of the principal results of the historical evolution of the science. The history of Political Economy must of course he dis- tinguished from the economic history of mankind, or of any separate portion of our race. The study of the succession of economic facts themselves is one thing; the study of the succession of theoretic ideas concerning the facts is another. And it is with the latter alone that we are here directly concerned. But these two branches of research, though dis- tinct, yet stand in the closest relation to each other. The rise and the form of economic doctrines have been largely conditioned by the practical situation, needs, and tendencies of the corresponding epochs. With each important social change new economic questions have presented themselves; and the theories prevailing in each period have owed much of their influence to the fact that they seemed to offer solutions of the urgent problems of the age. Again, every thinker, however in some respects he may stand above or before his contemporaries, is yet a child of his time, and cannot be isolated from the social medium in which he lives and moves. He will necessarily be affected by the circumstances which surround him, and in particular by the practical exigencies of which his fellows feel the strain. This connection of theory with practice has its advantages and its dangers. It tends to give a real and positive character to theoretic inquiry ; but it may also be expected to produce exaggerations in doctrine, to lend undue prominence to particular sides of the truth, and to make transitory situations or temporary expedients be re- garded as universally normal conditions. There are other relations which we must not overlook in tracing the progress of economic opinion. The several branches of the science of society are so closely connected that the 4 POLITICAL ECONOMY. history of no one of them can with perfect rationality be treated apart, though such a treatment is recommended indeed necessitated by practical utility. The movement of economic thought is constantly and powerfully affected by the prevalent mode of thinking, and even the habitual tone of sentiment, on social subjects generally. All the intellectual manifesta- tions of a period in relation to human questions have a kindred character, and bear a certain stamp of homogeneity, which is vaguely present to our minds when we speak of the spirit of the age. Social speculation again, and economic research as one branch of it, is both through its philosophic method and through its doctrine under the influence of the sciences which in the order of development precede the social, especially of the science of organic nature. It is of the highest importance to bear in mind these several relations of economic research both, to external circumstance and to other spheres of contemporary thought, because by keeping them in view we shall be led to form less absolute and therefore juster estimates of the successive phases of opinion. Instead of merely praising or blaming these accord- ing to the degrees of their accordance with a predetermined standard of doctrine, we shall view them as elements in an ordered series, to be studied mainly with respect to their filia- tion, their opportuneness, and their influences. We shall not regard each new step in this theoretic development as implying an unconditional negation of earlier views, which often had a relative justification, resting, as they did, on a real, though narrower, basis of experience, or assuming the existence of a different social order. Nor shall we consider all the theoretic positions now occupied as definitive ; for the practical system of life which they tacitly assume is itself susceptible of change, and destined, without doubt, more or less to undergo it. Within the limits-of a sketch like the present these considera- tions cannot be fully worked out ; but an effort will be made to keep them in view, and to mark the relations here indicated, wherever their influence is specially important or interesting. INTRODUCTORY. 5 The particular situation and tendencies of the several thinkers whose names are associated with economic doctrines have, of course, modified in a greater or less degree the spirit or form of those doctrines. Their relation to special prede- cessors, their native temperament, their early training, their religious prepossessions and political partialities, have all had their effects. To these we shall in some remarkable instances direct attention ; but, in the main, they are, for our present purpose, secondary and subordinate. The ensemble must pre- ponderate over the individual ; and the constructors of theories must be regarded as organs of a common intellectual and social movement. The history of economic inquiry is most naturally divided into the three great periods of (i) the ancient, (2) the mediaeval, and (3) the modern worlds. In the two former, this branch of study could exist only in a rudimentary state, jt js evident that for any considerable development of social theory-Two conditions must be fulfilled. First, the phenomena must have exhibited themselves on a sufficiently extended scale to supply adequate matter for observation, and afford a satisfactory basis for scientific generalisations ; and secondly, whilst the spectacle is thus provided, the spectator must have been trained for his task, and armed with the appropriate aids and instruments of research, that is to say, there must have been such a previous cultivation of the simpler sciences as will have both furnished the necessary data of doctrine and prepared the proper methods of investigation. Sociology requires to use for its purposes theorems which belong to the domains of physics and biology, and which it must borrow from their professors ; and, on the logical side, the methods which it has to employ deductive, observational, comparative must have been previously shaped in the cultivation of mathematics and the study of the inorganic world or of organisms less complex than the social Hence it is plain that, though some laws or tendencies of society must have been forced on men's attention in every age by practical exigencies which could not be postponed, and 6 POLITICAL ECONOMY. though the questions thus raised must have received some empirical solution, a really scientific sociology must be the product of a very advanced stage of intellectual development. And this is true of the economic, as of other branches of social theory. We shall therefore content ourselves with a general outline of the character of economic thought in antiquity and the Middle Ages, and of the conditions which detern j ./ ed that character. CHAPTER IL ANCIENT TIMES. THE earliest surviving expressions of thought on economic subjects have come down to us from the Oriental theocracies. The general spirit of the corresponding type of social life con- sisted in taking imitation for the fundamental principle of education, and consolidating nascent civilisation hy heredity of the different functions and professions, or even by a system of castes, hierarchically subordinated to each other according to the nature of their respective offices, under the common supreme direction of the sacerdotal caste. This last was charged with the traditional stock of conceptions, and their application for purposes of discipline. It sought to realise a complete regulation of human life in all its departments on the basis of this transmitted body of practical ideas. Con- servation is the principal task of this social order, and its most remarkable quality is stability, which tends to degenerate into stagnation. But there can Jbe no doubt that the useful arts were long, though slowly, progressive under this regime, from which they were inherited by the later civilisations, the system of classes or castes maintaining the degree of division of labour which had been reached in those early periods. The leading members of the corporations which presided over the theocracies without doubt gave much earnest thought to the conduct of industry, which, unlike war, did not imperil their political pre-eminence by developing a rival class. But, con- ceiving life as a whole, and making its regulation their primary aim, they naturally considered most the social reactions which 8 POLITICAL ECONOMY. industry is fitted to exercise. The moral side of economics is the one they habitually contemplate, or (what is not the same) the economic side of morals. They abound in those warnings against greed and the haste to be rich which religion and philosophy have in all ages seen to be necessary. They insist on honesty in mutual dealings, on just weights and measures, on the faithful observance of contracts. They admonish against the pride and arrogance apt to be generated by riches, against undue prodigality and self-indulgence, and enforce the duties of justice and beneficence towards servants and inferiors. Whilst, in accordance with the theological spirit, the personal acquisition of wealth is in general thesis represented as deter- mined by divine wills, its dependence on individual diligence and thrift is emphatically taught. There is indeed in the fully developed theocratic systems a tendency to carry precept, which there differs little from command, to an excessive degree of minuteness, to prescribe in detail the time, the mode, and the accompaniments of almost every act of every member of the community. This system of exaggerated surveillance is connected with the union, or rather confusion, of the spiritual and temporal powers, whence it results that many parts of the government of society are conducted by direct injunction or restraint, which at a later stage are intrusted to general intel- lectual and moral influences. The practical economic enterprises of Greek and Roman antiquity could not, even independently of any special adverse influences, have competed in magnitude of scale or variety of resource with those of modern times. (The unadvanced con- dition of physical science prevented a large application of the i less obvious natural powers to production, or the extensive use of machinery, which has acquired such an immense development as a factor in modern industry. J/ The imper- fection of geographical knowledge and of the means of com- 26 POLITICAL ECONOMY. / economic effect by transferring in many cases the possessions of the feudal chiefs to the industrious classes, whilst by *i K bringing different nations and races into contact, by enlarging 3 the horizon and widening the conceptions of the populations, 'as well as by affording a special stimulus to navigation, they tended to give a new activity to international trade. The independence of the towns and the rising importance of the burgher class supplied a counterpoise to the power of the land aristocracy; and the strength of these new social elements was increased by the corporate constitution given to the urban industries, the police of the towns being also founded on the trade guilds, as that of the country districts was on the feudal relations. The increasing demand of the towns for the products of agriculture gave to the prosecution of that art a more extended and speculative character ; and this again led to improved methods of transport and communication. But the range of commercial enterprise continued everywhere narrow, except in some favoured centres, such as the Italian republics, in which, however, the growth of the normal habits of industrial life was impeded or perverted by military ambi- tion, which was not, in the case of those communities, checked as it was elsewhere by the pressure of an aristocratic class. Every great change of opinion on the destinies of man and the guiding principles of conduct must react on the sphere of material interests ; and the Catholic religion had__a powerful influence on the economic life of the Middle Ages. Christianity Inculcates, perhaps, no more effectively than the older religions the special economic virtues of industry, thrift, fidelity to engagements, obedience to rightful authority ; but it brought out more forcibly and presented more persistently the higher aims of life, and so produced a more elevated way of viewing the different social relations. It purified domestic life, a reform which has the most important economic results. It taught the doctrine of fundamental human equality, heightened the dignity of labour, and preached with quite a new emphasis the obligations of love, compassion, and THE MIDDLE AGES. 27 forgiveness, and the claims of the poor. The constant pre- sentation to the general mind and conscience of these ideas, the dogmatic bases of which were scarcely as yet assailed by scepticism, must have had a powerful effect in moralising life. But to the influence of Christianity as a moral doctrine was added that of the Church as an organisation, charged with the application of the doctrine to men's daily transactions. Besides the teachings of the sacred books, there was a mass of ecclesiastical legislation providing specific prescriptions for the conduct of the faithful. And this legislation dealt with the economic as with other provinces of social activity. In the Corpus Juris Ganonici, which condenses the result of centuries of study and effort, along with much else is set out what wejnay call the Catholic economic theory, if we under- stand by theory, not a reasoned explanation of phenomena, but a body of ideas leading to prescriptions for the guidance of conduct. Life is here looked at from the point of view of spiritual well-being ; the aim is to establish and maintain amongst men a true kingdom of God. The canonists are friendly to the notion of a community of goods from the side of sentiment (" Dulcissima rerum possessio communis est "), though they regard the distinction of meum and tuum as an institution necessitated by the fallen state of man. In cases of need the public authority is justified in re-establishing pro hac vice the primitive community. The care of the poor is not a matter of free choice ; the relief of their necessities is debitum legate. Avaritia is idolatry ; cupiditas, even when it does not grasp at what is another's, is the root of all evil, and ought to be not merely regulated but eradicated. Agriculture and handiwork are viewed as legitimate modes of earning food and clothing ; but trade is regarded with disfavour, because it was held almost certainly to lead to fraud : of agriculture it was said, " Deo non dis- plicet ; " but of the merchant, " Deo placere non potest." The seller was bound to fix the price of his wares, not according to the market rate, as determined by supply and demand, 28 POLITICAL ECONOMY. but according to their real value (justum pretium). He must not conceal the faults of his merchandise, nor take advan- tage of the need or ignorance of the buyer to obtain from him more than the fair price. Interest on monev_jig_Jor- bidden ; the prohibition of usury is, indeed, as Roscher says, the centre of the whole canonistic system of economy, as well as the foundation of a great part of the ecclesiastical jurisdiction. The question whether a transaction was or was not usurious turning mainly on the intentions of the parties, the innocence or blameworthiness of dealings in which money was lent became rightfully a subject of determination for the Church, either by her casuists or in her courts. 1 The foregoing principles point towards a noble ideal, but by their ascetic exaggeration they worked in some directions as an impediment to industrial progress. Thus, whilst, with the increase of production, a greater division of labour and a larger employment of borrowed capital naturally followed, the laws on usury tended to hinder this expansion. Hence they were undermined by various exceptions, or evaded by fictitious 1 transactions. These laws were in fact dictated by, and adapted to, early conditions to a state of society in which money \loans were commonly sought either with a view to wasteful pleasures or for the relief of such urgent distress as ought jrather to have been the object of Christian beneficence. But they were quite unsuited to a period in which capital was y borrowed for the extension of enterprise and the employment >. of labour. The absolute theological spirit in this, as in other instances, could not admit the modification in rules of conduct demanded by a new social situation; and vulgar good sense better understood what were the fundamental conditions of \ industrial life. When the intellectual activity previously repressed by the more urgent claims of social preoccupations tended to revive towards the close of the mediaeval period, the want of 1 Roscher, Geachichte der N.O. in Deutsehland, pp. 5, sqq. THE MIDDLE AGES. yg rational appreciation of the whole of human affairs was felt, and was temporarily met by the adoption of the results of the best Greek speculation. Hence we find in the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas the political and economic doctrines of Aristotle reproduced with a partial infusion of Christian elements. His adherence to his master's point of view is strikingly shown by the fact that he accepts (at least if he is the author of the De Regimine Principum) l the Aristotelian theory of slavery, though by the action of the forces of his own time the last relics of that institution were being elimi- nated from European society. This great change the enfranchisement of the working classes was the most important practical outcome of the Middle Ages. The first step in this movement was the trans- formation of slavery, properly so called, into serfdom. The latter was, by its nature, a transitory condition. The serf was bound to the soil, had fixed domestic relations, and partici- pated in the religious life of the society ; and the tendency of all his circumstances, as well as of the opinions and sentiments of the time, was in the direction of liberation. This issue was, indeed, not so speedily reached by the rural as by the urban workman. Already in the second phase serfdom is \ abolished in the cities and towns, whilst agricultural serfdom \ does not anywhere disappear before the third. The latter revolution is attributed by Adam Smith to the operation of selfish interests, that of the proprietor on the one hand, who discovered the superior productiveness of cultivation by free tenants, and that of the sovereign on the other, who, jealous of the great lords, encouraged the encroachments of the villeins on their authority. But that the Church deserves a chare of the merit seems beyond doubt moral impulses, as often happens, conspiring with political and economic motives. The serfs were treated best on the ecclesiastical estates, and the members of the priesthood, both by their doctrine and by 1 On this question see Jourdain, " Philosophic de 8. Thomas," voL I, pp. 141-9, and 400. 30 POLITICAL ECONOMY. their situation since the Northern conquests, were constituted patrons and guardians of the oppressed or subject classes. Out of the liberation of the serfs rose the first lineaments of the hierarchical constitution of modern industry in the separation between the entrepreneurs and the workers. The personal enfranchisement of the latter, stimulating activity and developing initiative, led to accumulations, which were further promoted by the establishment . of order and good government by the civic corporations which grew out of the enfranchisement. Thus an active capitalist class came into existence. It appeared first in commerce, the inhabitants of the trading cities importing expensive luxuries from foreign countries, or the improved manufactures of richer communities, for which the great proprietors gladly exchanged the raw pro- duce of their lands. In performing the office of carriers, too, between different countries, these cities had an increasing field for commercial enterprise. At a later period, as Adam Smith has shown, commerce promoted the growth of manufactures, which were either produced for foreign sale, or made from foreign materials, or imitated from the work of foreign artificers. But the first important development of handicrafts in modern Europe belongs to the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, and the rise of manufacturing entrepreneurs is not conspicuous within the Middle Ages properly so called. Agriculture, of course, lags behind ; though the feudal lords tend to transform themselves into directors of agricultural enterprise, their habits and prejudices retard such a movement, and the advance of rural industry proceeds slowly. It does, however, proceed, partly by the stimulation arising from the desire to procure the finer objects of manufacture imported from abroad or produced by increased skill at home, partly by the expenditure on the land of capital amassed in the prosecution of urban industries. Some of the trade corporations in the cities appear to have been of great antiquity ; but it was in the thirteenth century that they rose to importance by being legally recognised and regulated. These corporations have been much too absolutely THE MIDDLE AGES. 31 condemned by most of the economists, who insist on applying to the Middle Ages the ideas of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. They were, it is true, unfitted for modern times, and it was necessary that they should disappear ; their exist- ence indeed was quite unduly prolonged. But they were at first in several respects highly beneficial. They were a valu- able rallying-point for the new industrial forces, which were strengthened by the rise of the esprit de corps which they fostered. They improved technical skill by the precautions which were taken for the solidity and finished execution of the wares produced in each locality, and it was with a view to the advancement of the industrial arts that St. Louis undertook the better organisation of the trades of Paris. The corporations also encouraged good moral habits through the sort of spontaneous surveillance which they exercised, and they tended to develop the social sentimert within the limits of each profession, in times when a larger public spirit could scarcely yet be looked for. CHAPTEK IV. MODERN TIMES- FIRST AND SECOND PHASES. THB close of the Middle Ages, as Comte has shown, must be placed at the end, not of the fifteenth but of the thirteenth century. The modern period, which then began, is filled by a development exhibiting three successive phases, and issuing in the state of things which characterises our own epoch. I. During the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries the Catholico-feudal system was breaking down by the mutual conflicts of its own official members, whilst the constituent elements of a new order were rising beneath it. On the practical side the antagonists matched against each other were the crown and the feudal chiefs ; and these rival powers sought to strengthen themselves by forming alliances with the towns and the industrial forces they represented. The movements of this phase can scarcely be said to find an echo in any contemporary economic literature. II. In the second phase of the modern period, which opens with the beginning of the sixteenth century, the spontaneous collapse of the mediaeval structure is followed by a series of systematic assaults which still further disorganise it. During this phase the central temporal power, which has made a great advance in stability and resources, lays hold of the rising elements of manufactures and commerce, and seeks, whilst satisfying the popular enthusiasm for their promotion, to use them for political ends, and make them subserve its own strength and splendour by furnishing the treasure necessary MODERN TIMES. 33 for military success. With this practical effort, and the social tendencies on which it rests, the Mercantile school of political economy, which then obtains a spontaneous ascendency, is in closeTelation. Whilst partially succeeding in the policy we have indicated, the European Governments yet on the whole necessarily fail, their origin and nature disqualifying them for the task of guiding the industrial movement ; and the dis- credit of the spiritual power, with which most of them are confederate, further weakens and undermines them. III. In the last phase, which coincides approximately with the eighteenth century, the tendency to a completely new system, both temporal and spiritual, becomes decisively pronounced, first in the philosophy and general literature of the period, and then in the great French explosion. The universal critical doctrine, which had been announced by the Protes- tantism of the previous phase, and systematised in England towards the close of that phase, is propagated and popularised, especially by French writers. The spirit of individualism inherent in the doctrine was eminently adapted to the wants of the time, and the general favour with which the dogmas of the social contract and laisser faire were received indicated a just sentiment of the conditions proper to the contemporary situation of European societies. So long as a new coherent system of thought and life could not be introduced, what was to be desired was a large and active development of personal energy under no further control of the old social powers than would suffice to prevent anarchy. Governments were there- fore rightly called on to abandon any effective direction of the social movement, and, as far as possible, to restrict their intervention to the maintenance of material order. This policy was, from its nature, of temporary application only ; but the negative school, according to its ordinary spirit, erected what was merely a transitory and exceptional necessity into a permanent and normal law. The unanimous European movement towards the liberation of effort, which sometimes rose to the height of a public passion, had various sides, o 34 POLITICAL ECONOMY. corresponding to the different aspects of thought and life j and of the economic side the French physiocrats were the first theoretic, representatives on the large scale, though the office they undertook was, both in its destructive and organic pro- vinces, more thoroughly and effectively done by Adam Smith, who ought to be regarded as continuing and completing then work. It must be admitted that with the whole modern move- ment serious moral evils were almost necessarily connected. The general discipline which the Middle Ages had sought to institute and had partially succeeded in establishing, though on precarious bases, having broken down, the sentiment of duty was weakened along with the spirit of ensemble which is its natural ally, and individualism in doctrine tended to encourage egoism in action. In the economic field this result is specially conspicuous. National selfishness and private cupidity increasingly dominate ; and the higher and lower industrial classes tend to separation and even to mutual hostility. The new elements science and industry which were gradually acquiring ascendency bore indeed in their bosom an ultimate discipline more efficacious and stable than that which had been dissolved ; but the final synthesis was long too remote, and too indeterminate in its nature, to be seen through the dispersive and seemingly incoherent growth of those elements. Now, however, that synthesis is becoming appreciable ; and it is the effort towards it, and towards the practical system to be founded on it, that gives its peculiar character to the period in which we live. And to this spon- taneous nisus of society corresponds, as we shall see, a new form of economic doctrine, in which it tends to be absorbed into general sociology and subordinated to morals. It will be the object of the following pages to verify and illustrate in detail the scheme here broadly indicated, and to point out the manner in which the respective features of the several successive modern phases find their counterpart and re- flection in the historical development of economic speculation. MODERN TIMES: FIRST PHASE. 35 FIRST MODERN PHASE. The first phase was marked, on the one hand, by the spontaneous decomposition of the mediaeval system, and, on the other, by the rise of several important elements of the new order. The spiritual power became less apt as well as less able to fulfil its moral office, and the social movement was more and more left to the irregular impulses of individual energy, often enlisted in the service of ambition and cupidity. Strong governments were formed, which served to maintain material order amidst the growing intellectual and moral disorder. The universal admission of the commons as an element in the political system showed the growing strength of the industrial forces, as did also in another way the insur- rections of the working classes. The decisive prevalence of peaceful activity was indicated by the rise of the institution of paid armies at first temporary, afterwards permanent which prevented the interruption or distraction of labour by devoting a determinate minority of the population to martial operations and exercises. Manufactures became increasingly important; and in this branch of industry the distinction between the entrepreneur and the workers was first firmly established, whilst fixed relations between these were made possible by the restriction of military training and service to a special profession. Navigation was facilitated by the use of the mariner's compass. The art of printing showed how the intellectual movement and the industrial develop- ment were destined to be brought into relation with each other and to work towards common ends. Public credit rose in Florence, Venice, and Genoa long before Holland and England attained any great financial importance. Just at the close of the phase, the discovery of America and of the new route to the East, whilst revolutionising the course of trade, prepared the way for the establishment of colonies, which contributed powerfully to the growing preponderance of industrial life, and pointed to its ultimate universality. 36 POLITICAL ECONOMY. It is doubtless due to the equivocal nature of this stage, standing between the mediaeval and the fully characterised modern period, that on the theoretic side we find nothing corresponding to such marvellous practical ferment and expan- sion. The general political doctrine of Aquinas was retained, with merely subordinate modifications. The only special economic question which seems to have received particular attention was that of the nature and functions of money, the importance of which began to be felt as payments in service or in kind were discontinued, and regular systems of taxation began to be introduced. Reseller, 1 and after him Wolowski, have called attention to Nicole Oresme, who was teacher of Charles V., King of France, and died Bishop of Lisieux in 1382. Roscher pro- nounces him a great economist. 2 His Tractatus de Origine, Natura, Jure, et Mutationibus Monetarum (reprinted by Wolowski, 1864) contains a theory of money which is almost entirely correct according to the views of the nineteenth century, and is stated with such brevity, clearness, and simplicity of language as show the work to be from the hand of a master. SECOND MODERN PHASE: MERCANTILE SYSTEM. Throughout the first modern phase the rise of the new social forces had been essentially spontaneous ; in the second "they became the object of systematic encouragement on the part of Governments, which, now that the financial methods of the Middle Ages no longer sufficed, could not further their military and political ends by any other means than increased taxation, implying augmented wealth of the community. Industry thus became a permanent interest of European Governments, and even tended to become the principal object of their policy. In natural harmony with this state of facts, 1 Comptes rtndut de V Academic des Sciencei morales et politiquei, but 435. qq- 2 Oeschickte dtr N.O. in Deutschland, p. 25. SECOND MODERN PHASE. 37 the mercantile system arose and grew, attaining its highest development about the middle of the seventeenth century. The Mercantile doctrine, stated in its most extreme form, makes wealth and money identical, and regards it therefore as the great object of a community so to conduct its dealings with other nations as to attract to itself the largest possible share of the precious metals. Each country must seek to export the utmost possible quantity of its own manufactures, and to import as little as possible of those of other countries, receiving the difference of the two values in gold and silver. This difference is called the balance of trade, and the balance is favourable when more money is received than is paid. Governments must resort to all available expedients prohibi- tion of, or high duties on, the importation of foreign wares, bounties on the export of home manufactures, restrictions on the export of the precious metals for the purpose of securing such a balance. But this statement of the doctrine, though current in the text-books, does not represent correctly the views of all who must be classed as belonging to the Mercantile school. Many of the members of that school were much too clear-sighted to entertain the belief, which the modern student feels difficulty in supposing any class of thinkers to have professed, that wealth consists exclusively of gold and silver. The mercan- tilists may be best described, as Roscher 1 has remarked, not by any deh'nite economic theorem which they held in common, but by a set of theoretic tendencies, commonly found in com- bination, though severally prevailing in different degrees in different minds. These tendencies may be enumerated as follows : (i) Towards over-estimating the importance of possessing a large amount of the precious metals ; (2) towards an undue exaltation (a) of foreign trade over domestic, and (&) of the industry which works up materials over that which provides them ; (3) towards attaching too high a value to a dense population as an element of national strength ; and (4) 1 Geschichte der N.O. in Deutschland, p. 228, sqq. 38 POLITICAL ECONOMY. towards invoking the action of the state in furthering arti ncially the attainment of the several ends thus proposed aa desirable. If we consider the contemporary position of affairs in Western Europe, we shall have no difficulty in understanding how these tendencies would inevitably arise. The discoveries in the New World had led to a large development of the European currencies. The old feudal economy, founded principally on dealings in kind, had given way before the new "money economy," and the dimensions of the latter were everywhere expanding. Circulation was becoming more rapid, distant communications more frequent, city life and movable property more important. The mercantilists were impressed by the fact that money is wealth sui generis, that it is at all times in universal demand, and that it puts into the hands of its pos- sessor the power of acquiring all other commodities. The period, again, was marked by the formation of great states, with powerful Governments at their head. These Governments required men and money for the maintenance of permanent armies, which, especially for the religious and Italian wars, were kept up on a great scale. Court expenses, too, were more lavish than ever before, and a larger number of civil officials was employed. The royal domains and dues were insufficient to meet these requirements, and taxation grew with the demands of the monarchies. Statesmen saw that for their own political ends industry must flourish. But manufactures make possible a denser population and a higher total value of exports than agriculture ; they open a less limited and more promptly extensible field to enterprise. Hence they became the object of special Governmental favour and patronage, whilst agriculture fell comparatively into the background. The growth of manufactures reacted on commerce, to which a new and mighty arena had been opened by the establishment of colonies. These were viewed simply as estates to be worked for the advantage of the mother countries, and the aim of statesmen was to make the colonial trade a new source of SECOND MODERN PHASE. 39 public revenue. Each nation, as a whole, working for its own power, and the greater ones for predominance, they entered into a competitive struggle in the economic no less than in the political field, success in the former being indeed, by the rulers, regarded as instrumental to pre-eminence in the latter. A national economic interest came to exist, of whiih the Govern- Tneht made itself the representative head. States became a sovt of artificial hothouses for the rearing of urbaw industries. Production was subjected to systematic regulation with the object of securing the goodness and cheapness of the exported articles, and so maintaining the place of the nation in foreign markets. The industrial control was exercised, in part directly by the state, but largely also through privileged corporations and trading companies. High duties on imports were resorted to, at first perhaps mainly~fbr revenue, but afterwards in the interest of national production. Commercial treaties were a principal object of diplomacy, the end in view being to exclude the competition of other nations in foreign markets, whilst in the home market as little room as possible was given for the introduction of anything but raw materials from abroad. The colonies were prohibited from trading with other European nations than the parent country, to which they supplied either the precious metals or raw produce purchased with home manufactures. It is evident that what is known as the mer- cantile doctrine was essentially the theoretic counterpart of the practical activities of the time, and that nations and Govern- ments were led to it, not by any form of scientific thought, but by the force of outward circumstance, and the observation >>f facts which lay on the surface. And yet, if we regard the question from the highest point df view of philosophic history, we must pronounce the uni- versal enthusiasm of this second modern phase for manufac- tures and commerce to have been essentially just, as leading the nations into the main avenues of general social develop- ment. If the thought of the period, instead of being impelled by contemporary circumstances, could have been guided by 40 POLITICAL ECONOMY. sociological prevision, it must have entered with zeal upon the same path which it empirically selected. The organisation of agricultural industry could not at that period make any marked progress, for the direction of its operations was still in the hands of the feudal class, which could not in general really learn the habits of industrial life, or place itself in sufficient harmony with the workers on its domains. The industry of the towns had to precede that of the country, and the latter had to be developed mainly through the indirect action of the former. And it is plain that it was in the life of the manu- facturing proletariat, whose labours are necessarily the most continuous and the most social, that a systematic discipline could at a later period be first applied, to be afterwards ex- tended to the rural populations. That the efforts of Governments for the futherance of manufactures and commerce were really effective towards that end is admitted by Adam Smith, and cannot reasonably be doubted, though free trade doctrinaires have often denied it. Technical skill must have been promoted by their encourage- ments ; whilst new forms of national production were fostered by attracting workmen from other countries, and by lightening the burden of taxation on struggling industries. Communica- tion and transport by land and sea were more rapidly improved with a view to facilitate traffic ; and, not the least important effect, the social dignity of the industrial professions was enhanced relatively to that of the classes before exclusively dominant. It has often been asked to whom the foundation of the mercantile system, in the region whether of thought or of practice, is to be attributed. But the question admits of no absolute answer. That mode of conceiving economic facts arises spontaneously in unscientific minds, and ideas suggested by it are to be found in the Greek and Latin writers. The policy which it dictates was, as we have shown, inspired by the situation of the European nations at the opening of the modern period. Such a policy had been already in some SECOND MODERN PHASE. 41 degree practised in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, thus preceding any formal exposition or defence of its speculative basis. At the commencement of the sixteenth century it began to exercise a widely extended influence. Charles V. adopted it, and his example contributed much to its predominance. Henry VIII. and Elizabeth conformed their measures to it. The leading states soon entered on a universal competition, in which each power brought into play all its political and financial resources for the purpose of securing to itself manu- facturing and commercial preponderance. Through almost the whole of the seventeenth century the prize, so far as commerce was concerned, remained in the possession of Holland, Italy having lost her former ascendency by the opening of the new maritime routes, and by her political misfortunes, and Spain and Germany being depressed by protracted wars and internal dissensions. The admiring envy of Holland felt by English politicians and economists appears in such writers as Raleigh, Mun, Child, and Temple ; l and how strongly the same spectacle acted on French policy is shown by a well-known letter of Colbert to M. de Pomponne, 2 ambassador to the Dutch States. Cromwell, by the Navigation Act, which destroyed the carrying trade of Holland and founded the English empire of the sea, and Colbert, by his whole economic policy, domestic and international, were the chief practical representatives of the mercantile system. From the latter great statesman the Italian publicist Mengotti gave to that system the name of Colbertismo ; but it would be an error to consider the French minister as having absolutely accepted its dogmas. He regarded his measures as temporary only, and spoke of protective duties as crutches by the help of whict manufacturers might learn to walk and then throw them away. The policy of exclusions had been previously pursued by Sully, partly with a view to the accumulation of a royal treasure, but 1 Roscher, Geschichte der N.O. in Deutschland, p. 227. * Clement, Histoire de la vie et de V administration de Colbert (1846), p. 134- 4* POLITICAL ECONOMY. chiefly from his special enthusiasm for agriculture, and hia dislike of the introduction of foreign luxuries as detrimentaV to the national character. Colbert's tariff of 1664 not merely simplified but considerably reduced the existing duties ; the tariff of 1667 indeed increased them, but that was really a political measure directed against the Dutch. It seems certain that France owed in a large measure to his policy the vast development of trade and manufactures which so much impressed the imagination of contemporary Europe, and of which we hear so much from English writers of the time of Petty. But this policy had also undeniably its dark side. Industry was forced by such systematic regulation to follow invariable courses, instead of adapting itself to changing tastes and popular demand. NOT was it free to simplify the processes of production, or to introduce increased division of labour and improved appliances. Spontaneity, initiation, and invention were repressed or discouraged, and thus ulterior sacrificed in a great measure to immediate results. The more enlightened statesmen, and Colbert in particular, endeavoured, it is true, to minimise these disadvantages by procuring, often at great expense, and communicating to the trades through inspectors nominated by the Government, information respect- ing improved processes employed elsewhere in the several arts ; but this, though in some degree a real, was certainly on the whole, and in the long run, an insufficient compensation. We must not expect from the writers of this stage any exposition of political economy as a whole ; the publications which appeared were for the most part evoked by special exigencies, and related to particular questions, usually of a practical kind, which arose out of the great movements cf the time. They were in fact of the ' nature of counsels to the Governments of states, pointing out how best they might develop the productive powers at their disposal and increase the resources of their respective countries. They are con- ceived (as List claims for them) strictly in the spirit of national economy, and cosmopolitanism is essentially foreign SECOND MODERN PHASE. 43 to them. On these monographs the mercantile theory some- times had little influence, the problems discussed not involving its tenets. But it must in most cases be taken to be the scheme of fundamental doctrine (so far as it was ever entitled to such a description) which in the last resort underlies the writer's conclusions. The rise of prices following on the discovery of the Ameri- can mines was one of the subjects which first attracted the attention of theorists. This rise brought about a great and gradually increasing disturbance of existing economic relations, and so produced much perplexity and anxiety, which were all the more felt because the cause of the change was not under- stood. To this was added the loss and inconvenience arising from the debasement of the currency often resorted to by sovereigns as well as by republican states. Italy suffered most from this latter abuse, which was multiplied by her political divisions. It was this evil which called forth the work of Count Gasparo Scaruffi (Discorso sopra le monete e della vera proportions fra I'oro e I'argento, 1582). In this he put forward the bold idea of a universal money, everywhere identical in size, shape, composition, and designation. The project was, of course, premature, and was not adopted even by ths Italian princes to whom the author specially appealed ; but the reform is one which, doubtless, the future will see realised. Gian Donato Turbolo, master of the Neapolitan "mint, in his Discorsi e Relazioni, 1629, protested against any tampering with the currency. Another treatise relating to the subject of money was that of the Florentine Bernardo Davanzati, otherwise known as the able translator of Tacitus, Lezioni delle Monete, 1588. It is a slight and somewhat superficial production, only remarkable as written with con- ciseness and elegance of style. A French writer who dealt with the question of money, but from a different point of view, was Jean Bod in. In his Reponse aux paradoxes de M. Malestroit touchant I'enclierisse- ment de toutea les choses et des moniiaies, 1568, and in his 44 POLITICAL ECONOMY. Discours sur le rehaussement et la diminution des monnaiee, 1578, he showed a more rational appreciation than many cf hia contemporaries of the causes of the revolution in prices, and the relation of the variations in money to the market values of wares in general as well as to the wages of labour. He saw that the amount of money in circulation did not constitute the wealth of the community,, and that the prohibition of the export of the precious metals was useless, because rendered inoperative by the necessities of trade. Bodin is no incon- siderable figure in the literary history of the epoch, and did not confine his attention to economic problems ; in his Six livres de la Repullique, about 1576, he studies the general conditions of the prosperity and stability of states. In har- mony with the conditions of his age, he approves of absolute Governments as the most competent to ensure the security and wellbeing of their subjects. He enters into an elaborate defence of individual property against Plato and More, rather perhaps because the scheme of his work required the treatment of that theme than because it was practically urgent in his day, when the excesses of the Anabaptists had produced a strong feeling against communistic doctrines. He is under the general influence of the mercantilist views, and approves of energetic Governmental interference in industrial matters, of high taxes on foreign manufactures and low duties on raw materials and articles of food, and attaches great importance to a dense population. But he is not a blind follower of the system ; he wishes for unlimited freedom of trade in many cases ; and he is in advance of his more eminent contemporary Montaigne l in perceiving that the gain of one nation is not necessarily the loss of another. To the public finances, which he calls the sinews of the state, he devotes much attention, and insists on the duties of the Government in respect to the right adjustment of taxation. In general he deserves the praise of steadily keeping in view the higher aims and 1 " II ne se faict aucun profit qu'au dommage d'autruy." Jb'isais, li v. I, chap. 21. SECOND MODERN PHASE. 45 interests of society in connection with the regulation and development of its material life. Correct views as to the cause of the general rise of prices are also put forward by the English writer, W. S. (William Stafford), in his Briefe Conceipte of English Policy, published in 1581, and dedicated to Queen Elizabeth. It is in the form of a dialogue, and is written with liveliness and spirit. The author seems to have been acquainted with the writings of Bodin. He has just ideas as to the nature of money, and fully understands the evils arising from a debased coinage. He describes in detail the way in which the several interests in the country had been affected by such debasement in previous reigns, as well as by the change in the value of the precious metals. The great popular grievance of his day, the conversion of arable land into pasture, he attributes chiefly to the restrictions on the export of corn, which he desires to see abolished. But in regard to manufactures he is at the same point of view with the later mercantilists, and proposes the exclusion of all foreign wares which might as well be provided at home, and the prohibition of the export of raw materials intended to be worked up abroad. Out of the question of money, too, arose the first remarkable German production on political economy which had an original national character and addressed the public in the native tongue. Duke George of the Ernestine Saxon line was in- clined (1530) to introduce a debasement of the currency. A pamphlet, Gemeine Stymmen von der Milntze, was published in opposition to this proceeding, under the auspices of the Albertine branch, whose policy was sounder in the economic sphere no less than in that of ecclesiastical affairs. A reply appeared justifying the Ernestine project. This was followed by a rejoinder from the Albertine side. The Ernestine pam- phlet is described by Roscher as ill-written, obscure, inflated, / and, as might be expected from the thesis it maintained, sophistical. But it is interesting as containing a statement of the fundamental principles of the mercantile system more than 46 POLITICAL ECONOMY. one hundred years before the publication of Mun's book, and forty-six before that of Bodin's Six livres de la Republique. The Albertine tracts, according to Koscher, exhibit such sound views of the conditions and evidences of national wealth, of the nature of money and trade, and of the rights and duties of Governments in relation to economic action, that he regards the unknown author as entitled to a place beside Raleigh and the other English " colonial-theorists " of the end of the six- teenth and beginning of the seventeenth century. In connection with the same subject of money we meet the great name of Copernicus. His treatise De monetce cudendce ratione, 1526 (first printed in 1816), was written by order of King Sigismund I., and is an exposition of the principles on which it was proposed to reform the currency of the Prussian provinces of Poland. It advocates unity of the monetary system throughout the entire state, with strict integrity in the quality of the coin, and the charge of a seigniorage sufficient to cover the exper/ses of mintage. Antonio Serra is regarded by some as the creator of modern political economy. He was a native of Cosenza in Calabria. His Breve Trattato delle cause che possono fare abbondare It regni d'oro e d'argento dove non sono miniere, 1613, was written during his imprisonment, which is believed to have been due to his having taken part in the conspiracy of Campanella for the liberation of Naples from the Spanish yoke and the establishment of a republican government. This work, long overlooked, was brought into notice in the follow- ing century by Galiani and others. Its title alone would sufficiently indicate that the author had adopted the principles of the mercantile system, and in fact in this treatise the essential doctrines of that system are expounded in a tolerably formal and consecutive manner. He strongly insists on the superiority of manufactures over agriculture as a source of national wealth, and uses in support of this view the pros- perity of Genoa, Florence, and Venice, as contrasted with the depressed condition of Naples. With larger insight than SECOND MODERN PHASE. 47 many of the mercantilists exhibit, he points out the import- ance, towards the acquisition, of wealth, not alone of favourable external conditions, but of energetic character and industrious habits in a population, as well as of a stable government and a good administration of the laws, The first systematic treatise on our science which proceeded from a French author was the Traite de VEconomie Politique, published by Montchre"tien de Watteville (or Yasteville) * in 1615. The use of the title, says Boscher, now for the first time given to the science, was in itself an important service, since even Bacon understood by " Economia " only the theory of domestic management. The general tendencies and aims of the period are seen in the fact that this treatise, notwith- standing the comprehensive name it bears, does not deal with agriculture at all, but only with the mechanical arts, navigation, commerce, and public finance. The author is filled with the then dominant enthusiasm for foreign trade and colonies. He advocates the control by princes of the industry of their subjects, and condemns the too great freedom, which, in his opinion to their own detriment, the Governments of Spain, Portugal, and Holland had given to trade. His book may be regarded as a formal exposition of the principles of the mercantile system for the use of Frenchmen. A similar office was performed in England by Thomas Mun. In his two works, A Discourse of Trade from England unto the East Indies, 2nd ed., 1621, and especially in England's Treasure by Foreign Trade, 1664 (posthumous), we have for the first time a clear and systematic statement of the theory of the balance of trade, as well as of the means by which, according to the author's view, a favourable balance could be secured for England. The great object of the economic policy of a state, according to him, should be so to manage its export 1 Montehre'tien, having fomented the rebellion in Normandy in 1621, was slain, with a few followers, by Claude Turgot, lord of Les Tourailles, who belonged to the elder branch of the noble house from which the great Turgot was descended. 4 8 POLITICAL ECONOMY. of manufactures, its direct and carrying trade, and its customi duties, as to attract to itself money from abroad. Hewaa^ however, opposed to the prohibition of the export of the precious metals in exchange for foreign wares, but on the ground, fully according with his general principles, that those wares might afterwards be re-exported and might then bring back more treasure than had been originally expended in their purchase ; the first export of money might be, as he said, the seed-time, of which the ultimate receipt of a larger amount would be the harvest. 1 He saw, too, that it is inexpedient to have too much money circulating in a country, as this enhances the prices of commodities, and so makes them leas saleable to foreigners, but he is favourable to the formation and maintenance of a state treasure. 2 One of the most remarkable of the moderate mercantilists was Sir Josiah Child (Brief Observations concerning Trade and the Interest of Money, 1668, and A Neio Discourse of Trade, 1668 and 1690). He was one of those who held up Holland as a model for the imitation of his fellow-countrymen. He is strongly impressed with the importance for national wealth and wellbeing of a low rate of interest, which he says is to commerce and agriculture what the soul is to the body, and which he held to be the " causa causans of all the other causes of the riches of the Dutch people." Instead of regarding such low rate as dependent on determinate conditions, which should be allowed to evolve themselves spontaneously, he thinks it should be created and maintained by public authority. Child, whilst adhering to the doctrine of the balance of trade, observes that a people cannot always sell to foreigners 1 On Mun's doctrines, see Smith's Wealth of Nations, Bk. iv. chap. i. 1 Writers of less importance who followed the same direction were Sir Thomas Culpeper (A Tract against the High Kate of Usury t 1623, and Useful Remark on High Interest, 1641), Sir Dudley Digges (Defence of Trade, 1615), G. Malynes (Consuetude vel Lex Mercutoria, 1622), E. Misselden (Circle of Commerce, 1623), Samuel Fortrey (England'i Interest and Improvement, 1663 and 1673), and John Pollexfen (England and India imontistent in their Manufactures, 1697). SECOND MODERN PHASE. 49 without ever buying from them, and denies that the export^ of the precious metals is necessarily detrimental. He has the ordinary mercantilist partiality for a numerous population. He advocates the reservation hy the mother country of the sole right of trade with her colonies, and, under certain limitations, the formation of privileged trading companies. A.s to the Navigation Act, he takes up a position not unlike that afterwards occupied by Adam Smith, regarding that measure much more favourably from the political than from the economic point of view. It jvill be seen that he is some- what eclectic in his opinions ; but he cannot properly be re- garded, though some have attributed to him that character, as a precursor of the free-trade school of the eighteenth century. Two other eclectics may be here mentioned, in whom just views are mingled with mercantilist prejudices Sir William Temple and Charles Davenant. The former in his Observations upon the United Provinces of the Netherlands, 1672, and his Essay on the Trade of Ireland, 1673, nas man y excellent remarks on fundamental economic principles, as on the func- tions of labour and of saving in the production of national wealth ; but he is infected with the errors of the theory of the balance of trade. He follows the lead of Raleigh and Child in urging his fellow-countrymen to imitate the example of the Dutch in their economic policy advice which in his case was founded on his observations during a lengthened residence in Holland as ambassador to the States. Davenant in his Essay on the East-India Trade, 1696-97, Essay on the Probable Ways of making the People Gainers in the Balance of Trade, 1699, &c., also takes up an eclectic position, combining some correct views on wealth and money with mercantilist notions on trade, and recommending Governmental restrictions on colonial commerce as strongly as he advocates freedom of exchange at home. JWhilst the mercantile system represented the prevalent form of economic thought in the seventeenth century, and was alone dominant in the region of practical statesmanship, there waa " D POLITICAL ECONOMY. growing up, side by side with it, a body of opinion, different aiid indeed hostile in character, which was destined ultimately to drive it from the field. The new ideas were first developed in England, though it was in France that in the following century they took hold of the public mind, and became a power in politics. That they should first show themselves here, and afterwards be extended, applied, and propagated throughout Europe by French writers, belongs to the order of things according to which the general negative doctrine in morals and politics, undoubtedly of English origin, found its chief home in France, and was thence diffused in widening circles through the civilised world. In England this move- ment of economic thought took the shape mainly of individual criticism of the prevalent doctrines, founded on a truer analysis of facts and conceptions ; in France it was penetrated with a powerful social sentiment, furnished the creed of a party, and inspired a protest against institutions and an urgent demand for practical reform. Eegarded from the theoretic side, the characteristic features of the new direction were the following. The view of at least the extreme mercantilists that national wealth depends on the accumulation of the precious metals is proved to be false, and the gifts of nature and the labour of man are shown to be its real sources. The exaggerated estimate of the importance of foreign commerce is reduced, and attention is once more turned to agriculture and the conditions of its successful prosecution. On the side of practical policy, a so-called favourable balance of trade is seen not to be the true object of a nation's or a statesman's efforts, but the procuring for the whole population in the fullest measure the enjoyment of the necessaries and conveniences of life. And what more than anything else contrasts the new system with the old the elaborate appa- ratus of prohibitions, protective duties, bounties, monopolies, and privileged corporations, which the European Governments had created in the supposed interests of manufactures and trade, is denounced or deprecated as more an impediment than SECOND MODERN PHASE. 51 furtherance, and the freedom of industry is insisted on as the one thing needful. This circle of ideas, of course, emerges only gradually, and its earliest representatives in economic literature in general apprehend it imperfectly and advocate it with reserve ; but it rises steadily in importance, being more and more favoured by the highest minds, and finding an in- creasing body of supporters amongst the intelligent public. Some occasional traits of an economic scheme in harmony with these new tendencies are to be found in the De Cive and Leviathan of Hobbes. But the efficacy of that great thinker lay rather in the general philosophic field ; and by sys- tematising, for the first time, the whole negative doctrine, he gave a powerful impulse towards the demolition of the exist- ing social order, which was destined, as we shall see, to have momentous consequences in the economic no less than in the strictly political department of things. A writer of no such extended range, but of much sagacity and good sense, was Sir William Petty, author of a number of pieces containing germs of a sound economic doctrine. A leading thought in his writings is that "labour is the father and active principle of wealth, lands are the mother." He divides a population into t\vo classes, the productive and the unproductive, according as they are or are not occupied in producing .useful material things. The value of any com- modity depends, he says, anticipating Ricardo, on the amount of labour necessary for its production. He is desirous of obtaining a universal measure of value, and chooses as his unit the average food of the cheapest kind required for a man's daily sustenance. He understands the nature of the rent of land as the excess of the price of its produce over the cost of production. He disapproves of the attempt to fix by autho- rity a maximum rate of interest, and is generally opposed to Governmental interference with the course of industry. He sees that a country requires for its exchanges a definite quantity of money and may have too much of it, and con- demns the prohibition of its exportation. He holds that one 52 POLITICAL ECONOMY. only of the precious metals must be the foundation of the currency, the other circulating as an ordinary article of mer- chandise. Petty's name is specially associated with the pro* gress of statistics, with which he was much occupied, and which he called hy the name of political arithmetic. Relying on the results of such inquiries, he set himself strongly against the opinion which was maintained by the author of Britannia Languens (1680), Fortrey, Roger Coke, and other writers, that the prosperity of England was on the decline. The most thorough-going and emphatic assertion of the free- trade doctrine against the system of prohibitions, which had gained strength by the Revolution, was contained in Sir Dudley North's Discourses upon Trade, 1691. He shows that wealth may exist independently of gold or silver, its source being human industry, applied either to the cultivation of the soil or to manufactures. The precious metals, however, arc one element of national wealth, and perform highly im- portant offices. Money may exist in excess, as well as in defect, in a country ; and the quantity of it required for the purposes of trade will vary with circumstances ; its ebb and flow will regulate themselves spontaneously. It is a mistake to suppose that stagnation of trade arises from want of money ; it must arise either from a glut of the home market, or from a disturbance of foreign commerce, or from diminished con- sumption caused by poverty. The export of money in the /~ course of traffic, instead of diminishing, increases the national wealth, trade being only an exchange of superfluities. Nation? are economically related to the world just in the same way as cities to the state or as families to the city. North emphasises more than his predecessors the value of the home trade. With respect to the interest of capital, he maintains that it depends, like the price of any commodity, on the proportion of demand and supply, and that a low rate is a result of the relative increase of capital, and cannot be brought about by arbitrary regulations, as had been proposed by Child and others. In arguing the question of free trade, he urges that individual* SECOND MODERN PHASE. 53 often take their private interest as the measure of good and evil, and would for its sake debar others from their equal right of buying and selling, but that every advantage given to one interest or branch of trade over another is injurious to the public. No trade is unprofitable to the public; if it were, it would be given up; when trades thrive, so does the public, of which they form a part. Prices must determine themselves, and cannot be fixed by law ; and all forcible interference with them does harm instead of good. No people can become rich by state regulations, only by peace, industry, freedom, and unimpeded economic activity. It will be seen how closely North's view of things approaches to that embodied some eighty years later in Adam Smith's great work. 1 Locke is represented by Koscher as, along with Petty and North, making up the "triumvirate" of eminent British economists of this period who laid the foundations of a new and more rational doctrine than that of the mercantilists. But this view of his claims seems capable of being accepted only with considerable deductions. His specially economic writings are Considerations of the lowering of Interest and raising the value of Money, 1691, and Further Considerations, 1695. Though Leibnitz declared with respect to these treatises that nothing more solid or intelligent could be said on their subject, it is difficult absolutely to adopt that verdict. Locke's spirit of sober observation and patient analysis led him indeed to some just conclusions ; and he is entitled to the credit of having energetically resisted the debasement of the currency, which was then recommended by some who were held to be eminent practical authorities. But he falls into errors which show that he had not by any means completely emancipated himself from the ideas of the mercantile system. He attaches far too much importance to money as such. He says expressly that riches consist in a plenty of gold and silver, that is, as he 1 YetM. Eugene Daire asserts (CEuvresde Turgot, i. 322) that "Hume et Tucker sont les deux premiers e"crivains qui se soient Sieve's, en Angle, terre, au-dessua des theories da systemr mercantile." 54 POLITICAL ECONOMY. explains, in having more in proportion of those metals than the rest of the world or than our neighbours. " In a country not furnished with mines, there are but two ways of growing rich, either conquest or commerce." Hence he accepts the doctrine of the balance of trade. He shows that the rate of interest can no more be fixed by law than the rent of houses or the hire of ships, and opposes Child's demand for legisla- tive interference with it. But he erroneously attributed the fall of the rate which had taken place generally in Europe to the increase of the quantity of gold and silver by the discovery of the American mines. He sets too absolute a value on a numerous population, in this point agreeing with Petty. On wages he observes that the rate must be such as to cover the indispensable wants of the labourer; when the price of sub- sistence rise?, wages must rise in a like ratio, or the working population must come on the poor rates. The fall of the rent of land he regards as a sure sign of the decline of national wealth. " Taxes, however contrived, and out of whose hands soever immediately taken, do, in a country where their great fund is in land, for the most part terminate upon land." In this last proposition we see a foreshadowing of the impdf unique of the physiocrats. Whatever may have been Locke's direct economic services, his principal importance, like that of Hobbes, lies in his general philosophic and political principles, which powerfully affected French and indeed European thought, exciting a spirit of opposition to arbitrary power, and laying the foundation of the doctrine developed in the Contrat Social. 1 1 Minor English writers who followed the new economic direction were Lewis Roberts, Treasure of Traffick, 1641 ; Rice Vaughan, DixccurM of Coin and Coinage, 1675 ; Nicholas Barbon, Discourse concerning (7cin> ing the new money lighter, 1696, in which some of Locke's errors were pointed out ; and the author of an anonymous book entitled Consider**- tions on the East India Trade, 1701. Practical questions much debated at this period were those connected with banking, on which a lengthened controversy took place, S. Lamb, W. Potter, F. Cradocke, M. Lewis, M. Godfrey, R. Murray, H. Chamberlen, and W. Paterson, founder of the Bank of England (1694). producing many pamphlets on the subject { and the management of the poor, which was treated by Locke, Sil Matthew Hale, R. Haines, T. Firmin, and others. CHAPTER V. THIRD MODERN PHASE: SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. THE changes introduced during the third phase in the in- ternal organisation of the industrial world were (i) the more complete separation of banking from general commerce, and the wider extension of its operations, especially through the system of public credit; and (2) the great development of the use of machinery in production. The latter did not become very prominent during the first half of the eighteenth century. Whilst tending to promote the dignity of the working classes by relieving them from degrading and exhausting physical labour, it widened the gulf between them and the capitalist employers. It thus became plain that for the definitive constitution of in- dustry a moral reform was the necessary preliminary condition. With respect to the political relations of industry, a remark- able inversion now showed itself. The systematic encourage- ments which the European Governments had extended to it in the preceding phase had been prompted by their desire to use it as an instrument for achieving the military superiority which was the great end of their policy. Now, on the con- trary, the military spirit subordinated itselfto the industrial, and the armies and the. diplomacy of governments were placed at the service of commerce. The wars which filled a large part of the eighteenth century were essentially Commercial wars, arising out of the effort to sustain or extend the colonial establishments founded in the previous phase, or to deprive rival nations of the industrial advantages connected with the 56 POLITICAL ECONOMY. possession of such establishments. This change of attitude, notwithstanding its deplorable tendency to foster international enmities and jealousies, marked a real and important progress by pointing to industrial activity as the one permanent practical destination of modern societies. But, whilst by this sort of action furthering the ascendency of the new forces, the ruling powers, both in England and France, betrayed the alarm they felt at the subversive ten- dencies which appeared inherent in the modern movement by taking up in their domestic policy an attitude of resistance. Reaction became triumphant in France during the latter half of the reign of Louis XIV. under the disastrous influence of Madame de Maintenon. In England, after the transaction of 1688, by which the Government was consolidated on the double basis of aristocratic power and official orthodoxy, the state policy became not so much retrograde as stationary, industrial conquest being put forward to satisfy the middle class and wean it from the pursuit of a social renovation. In both countries there was for some time a noticeable check in the intellectual development, and Eoscher and others have observed that, in economic studies particularly, the first three decades of the eighteenth century were a period of general stagnation, eclecticism for the most part taking the place of originality. The movement was, however, soon to be resumed, but with an altered and more formidable character. The negative doctrine, which had risen and taken a definite form in England, was diffused and popularised in France, where it became evident, even before the decisive explosion, that the only possible issue lay in a radical social transformation. The partial schools of Voltaire and Rousseau in different ways led up to a violent crisis, whilst taking little thought of the conditions of a system which could replace the old ; but the more complete and organic school, of which Diderot li the best representative, looked through freedom to a thorough reorganisation. Its constructive aim is shown by the design of the Encydopedie, a project, however, which could have SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 57 only & temporary success, because no real synthesis was forth- coming, and this joint production of minds often divergent could possess no more than an external unity. It was with this great school that the physiocrats were specially connected ; and, in common with its other members, whilst pushing towards an entire change of the existing system, they yet would gladly have avoided political demolition through the exercise of a royal dictatorship, or contemplated it only as the necessary condition of a new and better order of things. But, though marked off by such tendencies from the purely revo- lutionary sects, their method and fundamental ideas were negative, resting, as they did, essentially on the basis of the jus naturae. We shall follow in detail these French develop- ments in their special relation to economic science, and after- wards notice the corresponding movements in other European countries which showed themselves before the appearance of Adam Smith, or were at least unaffected by his influence. BEFORE ADAM SMITH. France. The more liberal, as well as more rational, principles put forward by the English thinkers of the new type began, early in the eighteenth century, to find an echo in France, where the clearer and more vigorous intellects were prepared for their reception by a sense of the great evils which exaggerated mercantilism, serving as instrument of political ambition, had produced in that country. The impoverished condition of the agricultural population, the oppressive weight and unequal imposition of taxation, and the unsound state of the public finances had produced a general feeling of disquiet, and led several distinguished writers to protest strongly against the policy of Colbert and to demand a complete reform. The most important amongst them was Pierre Boisguillebert, whose whole life was devoted to these controversies. In his statistical writings (Detail de la France sous le regne pres&at t 58 POLITICAL ECONOMY. 1697 ; Factum de la France, 1707), he brings out in gloomy colours the dark side of the age of Louis XIV., and in his theoretic works (Traite de la nature et du commerce dea grains; Dissertations sur la nature des richesses de V argent et des tributs ; and Essai sur la rarete de I'argent) ha appears as an earnest, even passionate, antagonist of the mer- cantile school. He insists again and again on the fact that national wealth does not consist in gold and silver, but io useful things, foremost among which are the products of agri- culture. He even goes so far as to speak of " argent criminel," which from being the slave of trade, as it ought to be, had become its tyrant. He sets the " genuinely French Sully " far above the " Italianising Colbert," and condemns all arbi- trary regulations affecting either foreign or internal commerce, especially as regards the corn trade. National wealth does not depend on Governments, whose interference does more harm than good ; the natural laws of the economic order of things cannot be violated or neglected with impunity ; the interests of the several classes of society in a system of free- dom are identical, and those of individuals coincide with that of the state. A similar solidarity exists between different nations ; in their economic dealings they are related to the world as individual towns to a nation, and not merely plenty, but peace and harmony, will result from their unfettered intercourse. Men he divides into two classes those who do nothing and enjoy everything, and those who labour from morning to night often without earning a bare subsistence ; the latter he would favour in every way. Here we catch the "breath of popular sympathy which fills the social atmosphere of the eighteenth century. He dwells with special emphasis on the claims of agriculture, which had in France fallen into un- merited neglect, and with a view to its improvement calls for a reform in taxation. He would replace indirect taxes by taxes on income, and would restore the payment of taxes in kind, with the object of securing equality of burden and eliminating every element of the arbitrary. He has some SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 59 interesting views of a general character : thus he approximates to a correct conception of agricultural rent, and he points^ tp_ the order in which human wants follow each other, those of necessity, convenience, comfort, superfluity, and ostentation succeeding in the order named, and ceasing in the inverse order to be felt as wealth decreases. The depreciating tone in which Voltaire speaks of Boisguillebert (Siecle de Louis XIV., chap. 30) is certainly not justified ; he had a great economic talent, and his writings contain important germs of truth. But he appears to have exerted little influence, theo- retical or practical, in his own time. The same general line of thought was followed by Marshal Vauhan (16331707) in his economic tracts, especially that bearing the title of Projet d'une dixme Royale, 1707, which was suppressed by the authorities, and lost for him. the favour of his sovereign, but has added lustre to his name in the judgment of posterity. He is deeply impressed with the deplorable condition of the working classes of France in his day. He urges that the aim of the Government should be the welfare of all orders of the community ; that all are entitled to like favour and furtherance ; that the often despised and wronged lower class is the basis of the social organisation ; that labour is the foundation of all wealth, and agriculture the most important species of labour; that the most essential condition of successful industry is freedom ; and that all un- necessary or excessive restrictions on manufactures and com- merce should be swept away. He protests in particular against the inequalities of taxation, and the exemptions and privileges enjoyed by the higher ranks. With the exception of some duties on consumption he would abolish all the existing taxes, and substitute for them a single tax on income and land, impartially applied to all classes, which he describes under the name of " Dixme Royale," that is to say, a tenth in kind of all agricultural produce, and a tenth of money income chargeable on manufacturers and traders. 1 1 An English translation of the Dixme Royale was published in 1 708. 60 POLITICAL ECONOMY. The liberal and humane spirit of Fenelon led him to aspira after freedom of commerce with foreign nations, and to preach the doctrine that the true superiority of one state over another lies in the number indeed, but also in the morality, in- telligence, and industrious habits of its population. The Telemaque, in which these views were presented in an attractive form, was welcomed and read amongst all ranks and classes, and was thus an effective organ for the propagation of opinion. After these writers there is a marked blank in the field of French economic thought, broken only by the Reflexions Politiques sur les Finances et le Commerce (1738) of Dutot, a pupil of Law, and the semi-mercantilist Essais Politiquet eur le Commerce (1731) of Me'lon, till we come to the great name of Montesquieu. The Esprit des Lois, so far as it deals with economic subjects, is written upon the whole from a point of view adverse to the mercantile system, especially in his treatment of money, though in his observations on colonies and elsewhere he falls in with the ideas of that system. His immortal service, however, was not rendered by any special research, but by his enforcement of the doctrine of natural laws regulating social no less than physical phenomena. There is no other thinker of importance on economic subjects in France till the appearance of the physiocrats, which marks an epoch in the history of the science. The heads of the physiocratic school were Francois Quesnay (1694-1774) and Jean Claude Marie Vincent, sieur de Gournay (1712-1759). The principles of the school had been put forward in 1755 by Richard Cantillon, a Fiench merchant of Irish extraction (Essai sur la nature du Commerce en general), whose biography Jevons has elucidated, 1 and whom he regards as the true founder of political economy j 1 " Richard Cantillon and the Nationality of Political Economy," in Contemporary Review, Jan. 1 88 1. Cantillon is qnoted in the Wealth Of Nations, bk. i. chap. 8. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 6. but it was in the hands of Quesnay and Gournay l that they acquired a systematic form, and became the creed of a united group of thinkers and practical men, bent on carrying them into action. The members of the group called themselves " les ^conomistes," but it is more convenient, because unam- biguous, to designate them by the name " physiocrates," invented by Dupont de Nemours, who was one of their number. In this name, intended to express the fundamental idea of the school, much more is implied than the subjection of the phenomena of the social, and in particular the economic, world to fixed relations of co-existence and succession. This is the positive doctrine which lies at the bottom of all true science. But the law of nature referred to in the title of the sect was something quite different. The theological dogma which represented all the movements of the universe as directed by divine wisdom and benevolence to the production of the greatest possible sum of happiness had been trans- formed in the hands of the metaphysicians into the conception of a /MS naturae, a harmonious and beneficial code established By the favourite entity of these thinkers, Nature, antecedent to human institutions, and furnishing the model to which they should be made to conform. This idea, which Buckle apparently supposes to have been an invention of Hutcheson's, had come down through Roman juridical theory from the speculations of Greece. 2 It was taken in hand by the modern negative school from Hobbes to Rousseau, and used as a power- ful weapon of assault upon the existing order of society, with which the "natural" order was perpetually contrasted as offer- ing the perfect type from which fact had deplorably diverged. The theory received different applications according to the diversity of minds or circumstances. By some it was directed against the artificial manners of the times, 'by others against 1 Gournay strongly recommended to his friends Cantillon's book M "ouvrage excellent qu'on negligeait." Mimoires de Morettet, i. 38. 2 See Cliffe Leslie's Essays in Political and Moral Philosophy, p. 62 POLITICAL ECONOMY. contemporary political institutions ; it was specially employed by the physiocrats in criticising the economic practice of European Governments. The general political doctrine is as follows. Society is composed of a numher of individuals all having the same natural rights. If all do not possess (as some members of the negative school maintained) equal capacities, each can at least best understand his own interest, and is led by nature to follow it. The social union is really a contract between these individuals, the object of which is the limitation of the natural freedom of each, just so far as it is inconsistent with the rights of the others. Government, though necessary, is a necessary evil ; and the governing power appointed by consent should be limited to the amount of interference absolutely required to secure the fulfilment of the contract. In the economic sphere, this implies the right of the individual to such natural enjoyments as he can acquire by his labour. That labour, therefore, should be undisturbed and unfettered ; and its fruits should be guaranteed to the possessor ; in other words, property should be sacred. Each citizen must be allowed to make the most of his labour ; and therefore freedom of exchange should be ensured, and competition in the market should be unrestricted, no monopolies or privileges being permitted to exist. The physiocrats then proceed with the economic analysis as follows. Only those labours are truly "productive" which add to the quantity of raw materials available for the purposes of man ; and the real annual addition to the wealth of the community consists of the excess of the mass of agricultural products (including, of course, minerals) over their cost of production. On the amount of this "produit net" depends the wellbeing of the community, and the possibility of its advance in civilisation. The manufacturer merely gives a new form to the materials extracted from the earth ; the higher value of the object, after it has passed through his hands, only represents the quantity of provisions and other materials used SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 63 and consumed in its elaboration. Commerce does nothing more than transfer the wealth already existing from one hand to another ; what the trading classes gain thereby is acquired at the cost of the nation, and it is desirable that its amount should be as small as possible. The occupations of the manufacturer and merchant, as well as the liberal professions,^ and every kind of personal service, are " useful " indeed, but they are " sterile," drawing their income, not from any fund which they themselves create, but from the superfluous earnings of the agriculturist. Perfect freedom of trade not only rests, as we have already seen, on the foundation of natural right, but is also recommended by the consideration that it makes the " produit ne/"," on which all wealth and general progress depend, as large as possible. " Laissez faire, laissez passer" should therefore be the motto of Governments. The revenue of the state, which must be derived altogether from this net product, ought to be raised in the most direct and simplest way, namely, by a single impost of the nature of a land tax. The special doctrine relating to the exclusive productiveness of agriculture arose out of a confusion between "value " on the one hand and " matter and energy" on the other. Smith and others have shown that the attempt to fix the character of " sterility " on manufactures and commerce was founded in error. And the proposal of a single impot territorial falls to the ground with the doctrine on which it was based. But such influence as the school exerted depended little, if at all, on these peculiar tenets, which indeed some of its members did not hold. The effective result of its teaching was mainly destructive. It continued in a more systematic form the efforts in favour of the freedom of industry already begun in England and France. The essential historical office of the physiocrats was to discredit radically the methods followed by the European Governments in their dealings with industry. For sucn criticism as theirs there was, indeed, ample room: the policy of Colbert, which could be only temporarily useful, 64 POLITICAL ECONOMY. had been abusively extended and intensified ; Governmental action had intruded itself into the minutest details of business, and every process of manufacture and transaction of trade was hampered by legislative restrictions. It was to be expected that the reformers should, in the spirit of the negative philo- sophy, exaggerate the vices of established systems ; and there can be no doubt that they condemned too absolutely the economic action of the state, both in principle and in its historic manifestations, and pushed the " laissez faire " doctrine beyond its just limits. But this was a necessary incident of their connection with the revolutionary movement, of which they really formed one wing. In the course of that movement, the primitive social contract, the sovereignty of the people, and other dogmas now seen to be untenable, were habitually invoked in the region of politics proper, and had a transitory utility as ready and effective instruments of warfare. And so also in the economic sphere the doctrines of natural rights of buying and selling, of the sufficiency of enlightened selfishness as a guide in mutual dealings, of the certainty that each member of the society will understand and follow his true interests, and of the coincidence of those interests with the public welfare, though they will not bear a dispassionate examination, were temporarily useful as convenient and ser- viceable weapons for the overthrow of the established order. The tendency of the school was undoubtedly to consecrate the spirit of individualism, and the state of non-government. But this tendency, which may with justice be severely condemned in economists of the present time, was then excusable because inevitable. And, whilst it now impedes the work of recon- struction which is for us the order of the day, it then aided the process of social demolition, which was the necessary, though deplorable, condition of a new organisation. These conclusions as to the revolutionary tendencies of the school are not at all affected by the fact that the form of government preferred by Quesnay and some of his chief fol- lowers was what they called a legal despotism, which should SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 5 embrace within itself both the legislative and the executive function. The reason for this preference was that an en- lightened central power could more promptly and efficaciously introduce the policy they advocated than an assembly repre- senting divergent opinions, and fettered by constitutional checks and limitations. Turgot, as we know, used the absolute power of the crown to carry into effect some of his measures for the liberation of industry, though he ultimately failed because unsustained by the requisite force of character in Louis XVI. But what the physiocratic idea with respect to the normal method of government was appears from Quesnay's advice to the dauphin, that when he became king he should " do nothing, but let the laws rule," the laws having been of course first brought into conformity with thejiis naturae. The partiality of the school for agriculture was in harmony with the sentiment in favour of " nature " and primitive simplicity which then showed itself in so many forms in France, especially in combination with the revolutionary spirit, and of which Rousseau was the most eloquent exponent. It was also asso- ciated in these writers with a just indignation at the wretched state in which the rural labourers of France had been left by the scandalous neglect of the superior orders of society a state of which the terrible picture drawn by La Bruyere is an indestructible record. The members of the physiocratic group were undoubtedly men of thorough uprightness, and inspired with a sincere desire for the public good, especially for the material and moral elevation of the working classes. Quesnay was physician to Louis XV., and resided in the palace at Versailles; but in the midst of that corrupt court he main- tained his integrity, and spoke with manly frankness what he believed to be the truth. And never did any statesman devote himself with greater singleness of purpose or more earnest endeavour to the service of his country than Turgot, who wag the principal practical representative of the school. The publications in which Quesnay expounded his system were the following : Two articles, on " Ferrniers " and OB 66 POLITICAL ECONOMY. "Grains," in the Encydopedie of Diderot and D'Alemberl (1756, 1757) ; a discourse on the law of nature in the Physio- cratie of Dupont de Nemours (1768); Maximes generates de gouvernement economique d'un royaume agricole (1758), and the simultaneously published Tableau Economique avec son explication, ou Exirait des Economies Royales de Sully (with the celebrated motto "pauvres paysans, pauvre royaume; pauvre royaume, pauvre roi"); Dialogue sur le commerce et les travaux des artisans ; and other minor pieces. The Tableau Economique, though on account of its dryness and abstract form it met with little general favour, may be considered the principal manifesto of the school. It was regarded by the followers of Quesnay as entitled to a place amongst the fore- most products of human wisdom, and is named by the elder Mirabeau, in a passage quoted by Adam Smith, 1 as one of the three great inventions which have contributed most to the stability of political societies, the other two being those of writing and of money. Its object was to exhibit by means of certain formulas the way in which the products of agriculture, which is the only source of wealth, would in a state of perfect liberty be distributed among the several classes of the com munity (namely, the productive classes of the proprietors and cultivators of land, and the unproductive class composed of manufacturers and merchants), and to represent by other for- mulas the modes of distribution which take place under system? of Governmental restraint and regulation, with the evil results arising to the whole society from different degrees of such violations of the natural order. It follows from Quesnay's theoretic views that the one thing deserving the solicitude of the practical economist and the statesman is the increase of the net product; and he infers also what Smith afterwards affirmed on not quite the same ground, that the interest of the landowner is "strictly and inseparably connected with the general interest of the society." * * Wealth of Nation*, bk. iv. chap. 9. a Ibid. bk. i., chap. II. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 67 M. de Gournay, as we have seen, was regarded as one of the founders of the school, and appears to have exercised some influence even upon the formation of Quesnay's own opinions. With the exception of translations of Culpeper and Child, 1 Gournay wrote nothing hut memoirs addressed to ministers, which have not seen the light ; but we have a full statement of his views in the Bloge dedicated to his memory hy his illustrious friend Turgot. Whilst Quesnay had spent his youth aiaidst rural scenes, and had been early familiar with the labours of the field, Gournay had been bred as a merchant, and had passed from the counting-house to the office of inten- dant of commerce. They thus approached the study of political economy from different sides, and this diversity of their ante- cedents may in part explain the amount of divergence which existed between their views. Gournay softened the rigour of Quesnay's system, and brought it nearer to the truth, by rejecting what Smith calls its "capital error" the doctrine, namely, of the unproductiveness of manufactures and com- merce. He directed his efforts to the assertion and vindica- tion of the principle of industrial liberty, and it was by him that this principle was formulated in the phrase, since so often heard for good and for evil, " Laissez faire et laissez passer." One of the earliest aud most complete adherents of the physio- cratic school, as well as an ardent and unwearied propagator of its doctrines, was Victor Mirabeau, whose sincere and inde- pendent, though somewhat perverse and whimsical, character is familiar to English readers through Carlyle's essay on his more celebrated son. He had expressed some physiocratic views earlier than Quesnay, hut owned the latter for his spiritual father, and adopted most of his opinions, the principal dif- ference being that he was favourable to the petite as opposed to the grande culture, which latter was ^referred by his chief as giving, not indeed the largest gross, but the largest 1 Gonrnay's inspiration was, without doubt, largely English. "II avait lu," says Morellet, " de bons livres Anglais d'Economie politkjue, tels qne Petty, Davenant, Gee, Child, &c." Alemoires, i. 38. 68 POLITICAL ECONOMY. net product. Mirabeau's principal writings were Ami dei Hommes, ou traite sur la population (1756, 1760), Thwrifi dt Vimpot (1760), Les J&conomiques (1769), and Philosophic rurale, ou Economic generate et politique de t Agriculture (1763). The last of these was the earliest complete expositua of the physiocratic system. Another earnest and persevering apostle of the system was Dupont de Nemours (1739-1817), known by his treatises De I'exportation et de ^importation de* grains (1764), De I'origine et des progres d'une science nouvelle (1767), Du commerce de la Compagnie des Indes (1767), and especially by his more comprehensive work Physiocratie, ou Constitution naturelle du gouvernement le plus avantageux au genre humain (1768). The title of this work gave, as has been already mentioned, a name to the school. Another formal exposition of the system, to which Adam Smith refers as the " most distinct and best connected account " of it, was produced by Mercier-Lariviere, under the title L'Ordre naturel et essentiel des societes politiques (1767), a title which is inte- resting as embodying the idea of the jus naturae. Both he and Dupont de Nemours professed to study human communities, not only in relation to their economic, but also to their political and general social aspects; but, notwithstanding these larger pretensions, their views were commonly restricted in the main to the economic sphere; at least material considerations" de- cidedly preponderated in their inquiries, as was naively indi- cated by Lariviere when he said, " Property, security, liberty these comprise the whole social order ; the right of property is a tree of which all the institutions of society are branches." The most eminent member of the group was without doubt AnrnTRobert Jacques Turgot (1727-1781). This is not the place to speak of his noble practical activity, first as intendant of Limoges, and afterwards for a brief period as finance minister, or of the circumstances which led to his removal from office, and the consequent failure of his efforts for the salvation of France. His economic views are explained in the introductions to his edicts and ordinances, in letters and SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 69 occasional papers, but especially in his Reflexions sur la forma- tion et la distribution des richesses (1766). This is a con- densed but eminently clear and attractive exposition of the fundamental principles of political economy, as they were con- ceived by the physiocrats. It embodies, indeed, the erroneous no less than the sound doctrines of that school ; but several subjects, especially the various forms of land-economy, the different employments of capital, and the legitimacy of interest, are handled in a generally just as well as striking manner ; and the mode of presentation of the ideas, and the luminous arrangement of the whole, are Turgot's own. The treatise, which contains a surprising amount of matter in pro- portion to its length, must always retain a place among the classics of the science. The physiocratic school never obtained much direct popular influence, even in its native country, though it strongly attracted many of the more gifted and earnest minds. Its members, writing on dry subjects in an austere and often heavy style, did not find acceptance with a public which demanded before all things charm of manner in those who addressed it. When Morellet, one of their number, entered the lists with Galiani, it was seen how esprit and eloquence could triumph over science, solid indeed, but clumsy in its movements. 1 The physiocratic tenets, which were in fact partially erroneous, were regarded by many as chimerical, and were ridiculed in the contemporary literature, as, for example, the impdt unique by Voltaire in his L'homme aux quarante icus, which was directed in particular against Mercier- Lariviere. It was justly objected to the group that they were 1 On Galiani's Dialogues, see page 72. Soon after the appearance of this book Turgot wrote to Mile. Lespinasse "Je crois possible de lui faire une tres bonne re"ponse ; mais cela demande bien de 1'art. Lea ^conomistes sont trop confiants pour combattre contre un si adroit ferrailleur. Pour 1'abbe 1 Morellet, il ne faut pas qu'il y pense." Morellet's work was prohibited by the Controller-General Terray; though printed in 1770, some months after Galiani's, it waa not published till 1774. 70 POLITICAL ECONOMY. too absolute in their view of things ; they supposed, as Smith remarks in speaking of Quesnay, that the body-politic could thrive only under one precise regime, that, namely, which they recommended, and thought their doctrines universally and immediately applicable in practice. 1 They did not, as theorists, sufficiently take into account national diversities, 2 or different stages in social development; nor aid they, as politicians, adequately estimate the impediments which ignor- ance, prejudice, and interested opposition present to enlightened statesmanship. It is possible that Turgot himself, as Grimm suggests, owed his failure in part to the too unbending rigour of his policy and the absence of any attempt at conciliation. Be this as it may, his defeat helped to impair the credit of his principles, which were represented as having been tried and found wanting. The physiocratic system, after guiding in some degree the policy of the Constituent Assembly, and awakening a few echoes here and there in foreign countries, soon ceased to exist as a living power ; but the good elements it com- prised were not lost to mankind, being incorporated into the Rounder and more complete construction of Adam Smith. ITALY. In Italy, as in the other European nations, there was little activity in the economic field during the first half of the eighteenth century. It was then, however, that a really remarkable man appeared, the archdeacon Salustio Antonio Bandini (1677-1760), author of the Discorso sulla Maremma Sienese, written in 1737, but not published till 1775. The 1 Hume, in a letter to M orellet, 1 769, calls them " the set of men the most chimerical and arrogant that now exist." He seems intentionally to ignore Morellet's close connection with them. 2 Turgot said, " Quiconque n'oublie pas qu'il y a des e"tats politiques se"pare"s les uns des autres et constitue's diversement, ne traitera jamaia bien aucuue question d'Economie politique. " Letter to MUe. Ltspinasse, 1770. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 71 object of the work was to raise the Maremma from the wretched condition into which it had fallen through the decay of agriculture. This decay he showed to be, at least in part, the result of the wretched fiscal system which wae in force ; and his book led to important reforms in Tuscany, where his name is held in high honour. Not only by Pecchio and other Italian writers, but by Reseller also, he is alleged to have anticipated some leading doctrines of the physiocrats, but this claim is disputed. There was a remarkable renascence of economic studies in Italy during the latter half of the century, partly due to French influence, and partly, it would appear, to improved government in the northern states. The movement at first followed the lines of the mercantile school. Thus, in Antonio Broggia's Trattati dei tributi e delle monete e del governo politico della societa (1743), and Girolamo Belloni's Dissertazione sopra il commercio (1750), which seems to have had a success and reputation much above its merits, mercantilist tendencies decidedly preponderate. But the most distinguished writer who represented that economic doctrine in Italy in the last century was Antonio Genovesi, a Neapolitan (1712-1769). He felt deeply the depressed intellectual and moral state of his fellow-countrymen, and aspired after _a revival of philosophy and reform of education as the first condition of progress and wellbeing. With the object of pro- tecting him from the theological persecutions which threatened him on account of his advanced opinions, Bartolomeo Intieri, of whom we shall hear again in relation to Galiani, founded in 1755, expressly for Genovesi, a chair of commerce and mechanics, one of the conditions of foundation being that it should never be filled by a monk. This was the first pro- . feiisorship of economics established in Europe ; the second wag ^ founded at Stockholm in 1758, and the third in Lombardy ten years later, for Beccaria. The fruit of the labours of Genovesi in this chair was his Lezioni di commercio, ossia dt economic/, civile (1769), which contained the first systematic treatment of the whole subject which had appeared in Italy. 7 POLITICAL ECONOMY. As the model for Italian imitation he held up England, a country for which, says Pecchio, he had a predilection almost amdunting to fanaticism. He does not rise above the false economic system which England then pursued ; but he rejects some of the grosser errors of the school to which he belonged ; he advocates the freedom of the corn trade, and deprecates regulation of the interest on loans. In the spirit of his age, he denounces the relics of mediaeval institutions, such as entails and tenures in mortmain, as impediments to the national prosperity. Ferdinando Galiani was another dis- tinguished disciple of the mercantile school. Before he had completed his twenty-first year he published a work on money (Ddla tnoneta libri cinque, 1750), the principles of which are supposed to have been dictated by two experienced practical men, the Marquis Rinuccini and Bartolomeo Intieri, whose name we have already met. But his reputation was made by a book written in French and published in Paris, where he was secretary of embassy, in 1770, namely, his Dialogues sur le commerce des Hies. This work, by its light and pleasing style, and the vivacious wit with which it abounded, delighted Voltaire, who spoke of it as a book in the production of which Plato and Moliere might have been combined ! 1 The author, says Pecchio, treated his arid subject as Fontenelle did the vortices of Descartes, or Algarotti the Newtonian system of the world. The question at issue was that of the freedom of the corn trade, then much agitated, and, in particular, the policy of the royal edict of 1764, which permitted the ex- portation of grain so long as the price had not arrived at a certain height. The general principle he maintains is that the best system in regard to this trade is to have no system, "S countries differently circumstanced requiring, according to ^him, different modes of treatment. This seems a lame and impotent conclusion from the side of science; yet doubtless 1 So also Grimm : " C'est Platon avec la verve et lea gestei d'Arlequin." Diderot called the book " module de dialogues qui restera I *6ti dea lettrea de Pascal." SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 7$ the physiocrats, with whom his controversy lay, prescribed on this, as on other subjects, rules too rigid for the safe guidance of statesmen, and Galiani may have rendered a real service by protesting against their absolute solutions of practical problems. He fell, however, into some of the most serious errors of the mercantilists, holding, as indeed did also Voltaire and even Verri, that one country cannot gain with- out another losing, and in his earlier treatise going so far as to defend the action of Governments in debasing the currency. Amongst the Italian economists who were most under the influence of the modern spirit, and in closest harmony with the general movement which was impelling the Western nations towards a new social order, Cesare Beccaria (1738-1794) holds a foremost place. He is best known by his celebrated treatise Dei delitti e delle pene, by which Voltaire said he had made himself a benefactor of all Europe, and which, we are told, has been translated into twenty-two languages. The Empress Catherine having invited him to fix his residence at St. Petersburg, the Austrian Government of Lombardy, in order to keep him at home, established expressly for him a chair of political economy ; and in his Elementi di economia pubblica (1769-1771 ; not published, however, till 1804) are embodied his teachings as professor. The work is unfinished : he had divided the whole subject under the heads of agriculture, manufactures, commerce, taxation, government ; but he has treated adequately only the first two heads, and the last two not at all, having been called to take part in the councils of the state. He was in some degree under the influence of physio- cratic ideas, and holds that agriculture is the only strictly productive form of industry, whilst manufactures and artisans are a sterile class. He was strongly opposed to monopolies and privileges, and to corporations in arts and trades; in general he warmly advocated internal industrial freedom, though in regard to foreign commerce a protectionist. In the special case of the corn trade he was not, any more than Galiani, a partisan of absolute liberty. His exposition of 74 POLITICAL ECONOMY. economic principles is concise and sententious, and he often states correctly the most important considerations relating to his subject without adding the developments which would be desirable to assist comprehension and strengthen convic- tion. Thus on fixed capital (capitali fondatori), as distinct from circulating (annui), in its application to agriculture, he presents in a condensed form essentially the same explana- tions as Turgot about the same time gave ; and on the division of labour and the circumstances which cause different rates of wages in different employments, he in substance comes near to Smith, but without the fulness of illustration which is so attractive a feature of the Wealth of Nations. Pietro Verri (1728-1797), an intimate and life-long friend of Beccaria, waa for twenty-five years one of the principal directors of the administration of Lombardy, in which capacity he originated many economic and other reforms. In his Riflessioni sulle leggi vincolanti, principalmente nel commercio de' grani (written in 1769, printed in 1796), he considers the question of the regulation of the corn trade both historically and in the light of theoretic principles, and arrives at the conclusion that liberty is the best remedy against famine and against excessive fluctuations of price. He is generally opposed to Govern- mental interference with internal commerce, as well as to trade corporations, and the attempts to limit prices or fix the rate of interest, but is in favour of the protection of national industry by a judiciously framed tariff. These views are explained in his Meditazioni sulV economia politica (1771), an elementary treatise on the science, which was receivevl with favour, and translated into several foreign languages. A primary principle with him is what he calls the augmenta- tion of reproduction that is, in Smith's language, of " the annual produce of the land and labour " of a nation ; and by its tendency to promote or to restrict this augmentation, he tests every enactment and institution. Accordingly, unlike Beccaria, he prefers the petite to the grande culture, as giving a larger total produce. In dealing with taxation, SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 75 he rejects the physiocratic proposal of a single impot terri- torial. 1 Giovanni R. Carli (1720-1795), also an official pro- moter of the reforms in the government of Austrian Lombardy, besides learned and sound treatises on money, was author of Ragionamenti sopra i bilanci economici delle nazioni, in which he shows the falsify of the notion that a state gains or loses in foreign commerce according to the so-called balance of trade. In his letter to Pompeo JSTeri Sul liber o commercio de' grant (1771), he takes np a position similar to that of Galiani, regarding the question of the freedom of the corn trade as not BO much a scientific as an administrative one, to be dealt with differently under different local or other conditions. Reject- ing the physiocratic doctrine of the exclusive productiveness of agriculture, he illustrates in an interesting way the neces- sity of various economic classes in a society, and the reflex agency of manufactures in stimulating the cultivation of the soil. Giambattista Vasco (1733-1796) wrote discourses on several questions proposed by academies and sovereigns. In these he condemns trade corporations and the attempts by Governments to fix the price of bread and to limit the interest on loans. In advocating the system of a peasant proprietary, he suggests that the law should determine the minimum and maximum portions of land which a citizen should be per- mitted to possess. He also, with a view to prevent the undue accumulation of property, proposes the abolition of the right of Request, and the equal division of the inheritance amongst the children of the deceased. Gaetano Filangieri (1752-1788), one of the Italian writers of the last century whose names are most widely known throughout Europe, devoted to economic 1 J. S. Mill, in his Principles, bk. i. chap. I, takes credit to his father for having first illustrated and made prominent in relation to produc- tion what he strangely calls "a fundamental principle of Political Economy," namely, that "all that man does or can do with matter" is to " move one thing to or from another " But this is clearly put forward by Verri in his Meditazioni, sect. 3: "Accostare e separare sono gli unici element! che 1'ingegno nmano ritrova analizzando 1'idea doll* riproduzione." 76 POLITICAL ECONOMY. questions the second book of his Scienza della legislazione (5 vols., 17801785). Filled with reforming ardour and a j.'as- sionate patriotism, he employed his vehement eloquence in denouncing all the abuses of his time. Apparently without any knowledge of Adam Smith, he insists on unlimited free- dom of trade, calls for the abolition of the mediaeval institu- tions which impeded production and national wellbeing, and condemns the colonial system then followed by England, Spain, and Holland. He prophecies, as Kaynal, Turgot, and Genovesi had done before him, that all America would one day be independent, a prediction which probably helped to elicit Benjamin Franklin's tribute of admiration for his work. Bather a propagator than a discoverer, he sometimes adopted from others erroneous opinions, as, for example, when he approves the impdt unique of the physiocrats. On the whole, however, he represents the most advanced political and social tendencies of his age ; whilst strongly contrasted with Beccaria in temperament and style, he was a worthy labourer in the same cause of national and universal progress. Ludovico Kicci (1742-1799) was author of an able report Sulla riforma degli istituti pii della cittct, di Modena (1787). He treated the subject of poor relief and charitable institutions in so general a way that the work possesses a universal and permanent in- terest. He dwells on the evils of indiscriminate relief as tending to increase the misery it seeks to remove, and as lowering the moral character of a population. He exposes especially the abuses connected with lying-in and foundling hospitals. There is much in him which is akin to the views of Malthus ; like him he is opposed to any state provision for the destitute, who ought, he thinks, to be left to voluntary private beneficence. Ferdinando Paoletti (1717-1801) was an excellent and public-spirited priest, who did much for the diffusion of intelligence amongst the agricultural population of Tuscany, and for the lightening of the taxes which pressed upon them. He corresponded with Mirabeau (" Friend of Men "), and appears to hare accepted the physiocratic doc- SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 77 trines, at least in their general substance. He was author of Pensieri sopra Vagricoltura (1769), and of I veri mezzi dt render felici le societd. (1772); in the latter he advocates the freedom of the corn trade. The tract II Colbertismo (1791) by Count Francesco Mengotti is a vigorous protest against the extreme policy of prohibition and protection, which may still be read with interest. Mengotti also wrote (1791) a treatise Del commercio de' Romani, directed mainly against the ex- aggerations of Huet in his Histoire du commerce et de la navigation des anciens (1716), and useful as marking the broad difference between the ancient and modern civilisations. Here lastly may be mentioned another Italian thinker who, eminently original and even eccentric, cannot easily be classed among his contemporaries, though some Continental writers of our own century have exhibited similar modes of thought. This was Giammaria Ortes (1713-1790). He is opposed to the liberalist tendencies of his time, but does not espouse the doctrines of the mercantile system, rejecting the theory of the balance of trade, and demanding commercial freedom. It is in the Middle Ages that he finds his social and economic type. He advocates the maintenance of church property, is averse to the ascendency of the money power, and has the mediaeval dislike for interest on loans. He entertains the singular idea that the wealth of communities is always and everywhere in a fixed ratio to their population, the latter being determined by the former. Poverty, therefore, necessarily waits on wealth, and the rich, in becoming so, only gain what the poor lose. Those who are interested in the improve- ment of the condition of the people labour in vain, so long as they direct their efforts to the increase of the sum of the national wealth, which it is beyond their power to alter, instead of to the distribution of that wealth, which it is possible to modify. The true remedy for poverty lies in mitigating the gain-pursuing propensities in the rich and in men of business. Ortes studied in a separate work the subject of population; he formulates its increase as "geo- 78 POLITICAL ECONOMY. metrical," but recognises that, as a limit is set to such increase amongst the lower animals by mutual destruction, so is it in the human species by " reason " f: he " prudential restraint " of which Malthas afterwards made so much. He regards the institution of celibacy as no less necessary and advantageous than that of marriage. He enunciates what has since been known as the " law of diminishing returns to agricultural iii- dustry." He was careless as to the diffusion of his writings; and hence they remained almost unknown till they were included in the Custodi collection of Italian economists, when they attracted much attention by the combined sagacity and way- wardness which marked their author's intellectual character. SPAIN. The same breath of a new era which was in the air else- where in Europe made itself felt also in Spain. In the earlier part of the eighteenth century Geronimo Ustariz had written his Teorica y Practica del Comercio y Marina (1724; published, 1740; Eng. transl. by John Kippax, 1751 ; French by Forbonnais, 1753), in which he carries mercantile principles to their utmost extreme. The reforming spirit of the latter half of the century was best represented in that country by Pedro Ikodriguez, Count of Campomanes (17231802). He pursued with ardour the same studies and in some degree the same policy as his illus- trious contemporary Turgot, without, however, having arrived at so advanced a point of view. He was author of Respmsta fiscal sobre abolir la tasa y establecer el comercio de granos (1764), Discurso sobre el fomento de industria popolar (1774), and Discurso sobre la education de los artesanos y su fomento (1775^. By means of these writings, justly eulogised by Robertson, 1 as well as by his personal efforts as minister, he / sought to establish the freedom of the corn trade, to remove the hindrances to industry arising from mediaeval survivals, 1 Hittory of America, note 193. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 79 t'> ,-ive a large development to manufactures, and to liberate agriculture from the odious burdens to which it was subject. He saw that, notwithstanding the enlightened administration of Charles III., Spain still suffered from the evil results of ths blind confidence reposed by her people in her gold mines, an 1 enforced the lesson that the real sources of the wealth and power of his country must be sought, not in America, but in her own industry. In both Italy and Spain, as is well observed by Comte, 1 the impulse towards social change took principally the direc- tion of economic reform, because the pressure exercised by Governments prevented so large a measure of free speculation in the fields of philosophy and general politics as was possible in France. In Italy, it may be added, the traditions of the great industrial past of the northern cities of that country also tended to fix attention chiefly on the economic side of public policy and legislation. GERMANY. We have seen that in Italy and England political economy had its beginnings in the study of practical questions relating chiefly to money or to foreign commerce. In Germany it arose (as Eoscher has shown) out of the so-called cameralistic sciences. Soon after the close of the Middle Ages there existed in most German countries a council, known as the Kammer (Lat. camera), which was occupied with the management of the public domain and the guardianship of regal rights. The Kmperor Maximilian found this institution existing in Bur- gundy, and established, in imitation of it, aulic councils at Innspruck and Vienna in 1498 and 1501. Not only finance and taxation, but questions also of economic police, came to be entrusted to these bodies. A special preparation became necessary for their members, and chairs of cameralistic science 1 Philosophic Positive, voL v. p. 759. 8o POLITICAL ECONOMY. were founded in universities for the teaching of \\\e appro- priate body of doctrine. One side of the instruction thus given borrowed its materials from the sciences of external nature, dealing, as it did, with forestry, mining, general technology, and the like ; the other related to the conditions of national prosperity as depending on human relations and institutions ; and out of the latter, German political economy was at first developed. In no country had mercantilist views a stronger hold than in Germany, though in none, in the period we are now con- sidering, did the system of the balance of trade receive a less extensive practical application. All the leading German economists of the seventeenth century Bornitz, Besold, Klock, Becher, Horneck, Seckendorf, and Schroder stand on the common basis of the mercantile doctrine. And the same may be said of the writers of the first half of the eighteenth century in general, and notably of Justi (d. 1771), who was the author of the first systematic German treatise on political economy, a work which, from its currency as a text book, had much effect on the formation of opinion. Only in Zincke (1692-1769) do we find occasional expressions of a circle of ideas at variance with the dominant system, and pointing in the direction of industrial freedom. But these writers, except from the national point of view, are unimportant, not having exercised any influence on the general movement of European thought. The principles of the physiocratic system met with a certain amount of favour in Germany. Karl Friedrich, Mar- grave of Baden, wrote for the use of his sons an Abrege de principes d' Economic Politique, 1772, which is in harmony with the doctrines of that system. It possesses, however, little scientific value. Schlettwein (i 731 1802) and Mauvillon (1743-1794) were followers of the same school. Theodor Schmalz (1764-1831), who is commonly named as "the last of the physiocrats," may be here mentioned, though somewhat out of the historic order. He compares Colbertism with the SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. Si Ptolemaic system, physiocratism with the Copernican. Adam Smith he represents as the Tycho Brahe of political economy, a man of eminent powers, who could not resist the force of truth in the physiocrats, but partly could not divest himself of rooted prejudices, and partly was ambitious of the fame of a discoverer and a reconciler of divergent systems. Though Smith was now "the fashion," Schmalz could not doubt that Quesnay's doctrine was alone tr.ue, and would ere long be triumphant everywhere. Just before the appearance of Smith, as in England Steuart, and in Italy Genovesi, so in Austria Sonnenfels (17331817), the first distinguished economist of that country, sought to present the mercantile system in a modified and more enlight- ened form ; and his work (Grundsdtze der Polizei, Handlung, und Finanz, 1765 ; 8th ed., 1822), exercised even during a considerable part of the present century much influence on opinion and on policy in Austria. But the greatest German economist of the eighteenth cen- tury was, in Reseller's opinion, Justus Mb'ser (1720-1794), the author of Patriotische Phantasieen (17 74), a series of fragments, which, Goethe nevertheless declares, form "ein wahrhaftes Ganzes." The poet was much influenced by Mbser in his youth, and has eulogised in the Dichtung und Wahrheit (Bk. xiii.) his spirit, intellect, and character, and his thorough in- sight into all that goes on in the social world. Whilst others occupied themselves with larger and more .prominent public affairs and transactions, Mb'ser observed and reproduced the common daily life of his nation, and the thousand "little things " which compose the texture of popular existence. He has been compared to Franklin for the homeliness, verve, and freshness of his writings. In opinions he is akin to the Italian Ortes. He is opposed to the whole spirit of the " Aufklarung," and to the liberal and rationalistic direction of which Smith's work became afterwards the expression. He IB not merely conservative but reactionary, manifesting a preference for mediaeval institutions such as the trade guilds, w 82 POLITICAL ECONOMY. and, like Carlyle in our own time, seeing advantages even in serfdom, when compared with the sort of freedom enjoyed by the modern drudge. He has a marked antipathy for the growth, of the money power and of manufactures on the large scale, and for the highly developed division of labour. He is opposed to absolute private property in land, and would gladly see revived such a system of restrictions as in the interest of the state, the commune, and the family were imposed on mediaeval ownership. In his wayward and caustic style, he often criticises effectively the doctrinaire narrowness of his contemporaries, throws out many striking ideas, and in parti- cular sheds real light on the economic phenomena and general social conditions of the Middle Agea ADAM SMITH, WITH HIS IMMEDIATE PREDECESSORS AND HIS FOLLOWERS. England. The stagnation in economic inquiry which showed itself in England in the early part of the eighteenth century was not broken by any notable manifestation before 1735, when Bishop Berkeley put forward in his Querist, with much force and point, views opposed to those of the mercantile school on the nature of national wealth and the functions of money, though not without an admixture of grave error. But soon a more decisive advance was made. Whilst in France^ the physiocrats were working after their own fashion towards the construction of a definitive system of political economy, a Scottish thinker of the first order was elucidating, in a series of short but pregnant essays, some of the fundamental con- ceptions of the science. What had been written on these questions in the English language before his time had remained almost altogether within the limits of the directly practical sphere. With Locke, indeed, the general system of the modern critical philosophy had come into relation with economic inquiry, but only in a partial and indeterminate way. But SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 83 in Hume the most advanced form of this philosophy was represented, and his appearance in the field of economics decisively marks the tendency of the latter order of specula- tion to place itself in connection with the largest and deepest thought on human nature and general human history. Most of the essays here referred to first appeared in 1752, in a volume entitled Political Discourses, and the numher was completed in the collection of Essays and Treatises on Several Subjects, published in the following year. The most important of them are those on Commerce, on Money, on Interest, and on the Balance of Trade. Yet these should not be separated from the rest, for, notwithstanding the unconnected form of these little treatises, there runs through them a profound unity of thought, so that they indeed compose in a certain sense an economic system. They exhibit in full measure Hume's wonderful acuteness and subtlety, which indeed some- times dispose him to paradox, in combination with the breadth, the absence of prejudice, and the social sympathies which so eminently distinguish him ; and they offer, besides, the charm of his easy and natural style and his rare power of lucid exposition. In the essay on money he refutes the mercantilist error, which tended to confound it with wealth. "Men and com- modities," he says, "are the real strength of any community." " In the national stock of labour consists all real power and riches." Money is only the oil which makes the movements of the mechanism^ of commerce more smooth and easy. He *\ shows that, from the domestic as distinguished from the I international point of view, the absolute quantity of money, / supposed as of fixed amount, in a country is of no consequence, \ whilst an excessive quantity, larger, that is, than is required [ for the interchange of commodities, may be injurious as raising j prices and driving foreigners from the home markets. He goes so far, in one or two places, as to assert that the value of money is chiefly fictitious or conventional, a position which cannot be defended ; but it must not be pressed against him, 84 POLITICAL ECONOMY. as he builds nothing on it. He lias some very ingenious observations (since, however, questioned by J. S. Mill) on the effects of the increase of money in a country in stimulating industry during the interval which takes place before the additional amount is sufficiently diffused to alter the whole scale of prices. He shows that the fear of the money of an industrious community being lost to it by passing into foreign countries is groundless, and that, under a system of freedom, the distribution of the precious metals which is adapted to the requirements of trade will spontaneously establish itself. " In short, a Government has great reason to preserve with care its people and its manufactures ; its money it may safely trust to the course of human affairs without fear or jealousy." A very important service was rendered by his treatment of the rate of interest. He exposes the erroneous idea often entertained that it depends on the quantity of money in a country, and shows that the reduction of it must in general be the result of " the increase of industry and frugality, of arts and commerce," so that it may serve as a barometer, its lowness being an almost infallible sign of the flourishing condition of a people. It may be observed in passing that in the essay devoted to this subject he brings out a principle of human nature which economists too often overlook, " the constant and insatiable desire of the mind for exercise and employment," and the consequent action of ennui in prompting to exertion. With respect to commerce, he points to its natural founda- tion in what has since been called " the territorial division of labour," and proves that the prosperity of one nation, instead of being a hindrance, is a help to that of its neighbours. ''Not only as a man, but as a British subject," he says, "I pray for the flourishing commerce of Germany, Spain, Italy, and even France itself." He condemns the "numberless bars, obstructions, and imposts which all nations of Europe, and none more than England, have put upon trade." Yet on the question of protection to national industry he is not quite at SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 85 the free-trade point of view, for he approves of a tax on German linen as encouraging home manufactures) and of a. tax on brandy as increasing the sale of rurn and supporting our southern colonies. Indeed it has been justly observed A that there are in him several traces of a refined mercantilism, [ and that he represents a state of opinion in which the transi- V tion from the old to the new views is not yet completely j effected. We cannot do more than refer to the essay on taxes, in which, amongst other things, he repudiates the imp&t unique of the physiocrats, and to that on public credit, in which he criticises the "new paradox that public encumbrances are of themselves advantageous, independent of the necessity of contracting them," and objects, perhaps too absolutely, to the modern expedient of raising the money required for national enterprises by way of loan, and so shifting our burdens upon the shoulders of posterity. Tlu> characteristics of Hume, which are most important in the history of economic investigation, are (i) his practice of bringing economic facts into connection with all the weighty interests of social and political life, and (2) his tendency to introduce the historical spirit into the study of those facts. He admirably illustrates the mutual action of the several branches of industry, and the influences of progress in the arts of production and in commerce on general civilisation, exhibits the striking contrasts of the ancient and modern system of life (see especially the essay On the Populousness of Ancient Nations), and considers almost every phenomenon which comes under discussion in its relations to the con- temporary stage of social development. It cannot be doubted that Hume exercised a most important influence on Adam Smith, who in the Wealth of Nations calls him " by far the most illustrious philosopher and historian of the present age," and who esteemed his character so highly that, after a friend- ship of many years had been terminated by Hume's decease, he declared him to have "approached as nearly to the ideal 86 POLITICAL ECONOMY. of a perfectly wise and virtuous man as perhaps the nature of human frailty will permit." Josiah Tucker, dt-fr of Gloucester (d. 1799), holds a dis- tinguished place among the immediate predecessors of Smith. Most of his numerous productions had direct reference to contemporary questions, and, though marked by much sagacity and penetration, are deficient in permanent interest. In some of these he urged the impolicy of restrictions on the trade of Ireland, advocated a union of that country with England, and recommended the recognition of the independence of the United States of America. The most important of his general economic views are those relating to international commerce. He is an ardent supporter of free-trade doctrines, which he bases on the principles that there is between nations no necessary antagonism, but rather a harmony, of interests, and that their several local advantages and different aptitudes naturally prompt them to exchange. He had not, however, got quite clear of mercantilism, and favoured bounties on ex- ported manufactures and the encouragement of population by a tax on celibacy. Dupont, and after him Blanqui, represent Tucker as a follower of the physiocrats, but there seems to be no ground for this opinion except his agreement with them on the subject of the freedom of trade. Turgot translated into French (1755), under the title of Questions Importantes sur le Commerce, a tract by Tucker on The Expediency of a Law for the Naturalisation of Foreign Protestants. In 1767 was published Sir James Steuart's Inquiry into the Principles of Political Economy. This was one of the most unfortunate of books. It was the most complete and syste- matic survey of the science from the point of view of moderate mercantilism which had appeared in England. Steuart was a man of no ordinary abilities, and had prepared himself for his task by long and serious study. But the time for the mercantile doctrines was past, and the system of natural liberty was in possession of an intellectual ascendency which foreshadowed its political triumph. Nine years later the SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 87 Wealth of Nations was given to the world, a work as superior to Steuart's in attractiveness of style as in scientific soundness. Thus the latter was predestined to fail, and in fact never exercised any considerable theoretic or practical influence. Smith never quotes or mentions it ; being acquainted with Steuart, whose conversation he said was better than his book, he probably wished to keep clear of controversy with him. 1 The German economists have examined Steuart's treatise more carefully than English writers have commonly done ; and they recognise its high merits, especially in relation to the theory of value and the subject of population. They have also pointed out that, in the spirit of the best recent research, he has dwelt on the special characters which distinguish the economies proper to different nations and different grades in social progress. Coming now to the great name of Adam Smith (1723-1 790), it is of the highest importance that we should rightly under- stand his position and justly estimate his claims. It is plainly contrary to fact to represent him, as some have done, as the creator of political economy. The subject of social wealth "had always in some degree, and increasingly in recent times, engaged the attention of philosophic minds. The study had even indisputably assumed a systematic character, and, from being an assemblage of fragmentary disquisitions on particular questions of national interest, had taken the form, notably in Turgot's Reflexions, of an organised body of doctrine. The truth is, that Smith took up the science when it was already considerably advanced; and it was this very circumstance which enabled him, by the production of a classical treatise, to render most of his predecessors obsolete. But, whilst all the economic labours of the preceding centuries prepared the Way for him, they did not anticipate his work. His appear- 1 Smith says, in a letter to Pulteney ( 1772) " I have the same opinion of Sir James Stewart's book that you have. Without once mentioning it, I natter myself that any false principle in it will meet with a clear and distinct confutation in mine." 88 POLITICAL ECONOMY. ance at an earlier stagb, :>r without those previous would be inconceivable ; but he built, on the foundation which had been laid by others, much of his own that was precious and enduring. Even those who do not fall into the error of making Smith the creator of the science, often separate him too broadly from Quesnay and his followers, and represent the history of modern Economics as consisting of the successive rise and reign of three doctrines the mercantile, the physiocratic, and the Smithian. The last two are, it is true, at variance in some even important respects. But it is evident, and Smith him- self felt, that their agreements were much more fundamental than their differences ; and, if we regard them as historical forces, they must be considered as working towards identical ends. They both urged society towards the abolition of the previously prevailing industrial policy of European Govern- ments ; and their arguments against that policy rested essenti- ally on the same grounds. Whilst Smith's criticism was more searching and complete, he also analysed more correctly than the physiocrats some classes of economic phenomena, in par- ticular dispelling the illusions into which they had fallen with respect to the unproductive nature of manufactures and commerce. Their school disappeared from the scientific field, not merely because it met with a political check in the person of Turgot, but because, as we have already said, the Wealth of Nations absorbed into itself all that was valuable in their teaching, whilst it continued more effectually the impulse they had given to the necessary work of demolition. The history of economic opinion in modern times, down io the third decade of our own century, is, in fact, strictly bipartite. The first stage is filled with the mercantile system, which, as we have shown, was rather a practical policy than a speculative doctrine, and which came into existence as the spontaneous growth of social conditions acting on minds not trained to scientific habits. The second stage is occupied with the gradual rise and ultimate ascendency of anothei SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 89 system founded on the idea of the right of the individual to an unimpeded sphere for the exercise of his economic activity. "With the latter, which is best designated as the " system of natural liberty," we ought to associate the memory of the physiocrats as well as that of Smith, without, however, main taining their services to have been equal to his. The teaching of political economy was in the Scottish uni- N versities associated with that of moral philosophy. Smith, as we are told, conceived the entire subject he had to treat in his public lectures as divisible into four heads, the first of which was natural theology, the second ^thics. the third jurisprudence ; whilst in the fourth "he examined those poli- ^^^^^MMM^^^B A tical regulations which are founded upon expediency, and which are calculated to increase the riches, the power, and the p^rosperity of a state." The last two branches of inquiry are regarded as forming but a single body of doctrine in the well- known passage of the Theory of Moral Sentiments in which the author promises to give in another discourse " an account of the general principles of law and government, and of the different revolutions they have undergone in the different ages and periods of society, not only in what concerns justice, but in what concerns police, revenue, and arms, and whatever else is the subject of law." This shows how little it was Smith's habit to separate (except provisionally), in his conceptions or his researches', the economic phenomena of society from all the rest. The words above quoted have, indeed, been not unjustly described as containing " an anticipation, wonderful for his period, of general Sociology, both statical and dynami- cal, an anticipation which becomes still more remarkable when we learn from his literary executors that he had formed the plan of a connected history of the liberal sciences and elegant arts, which must have added to the branches of social study already enumerated a view of the intellectual progress of society." Though these large designs were never carried out in their integrity, as indeed at that period they could not have been adequately realised, it has resulted from them th*it, though 90 POLITICAL ECONOMY. economic phenomena form the special subject of the Wealth of Nations, Smith yet incorporated into that work much that relates to the other social aspects, incurring thereby the censure of some of his followers, who insist with pedantic narrowness on the strict isolation of the economic domain. There has been much discussion on the question What is the scientific method followed by Smith in his great work I y By some it is considered to have been purely deductive, a view which Buckle has perhaps carried to the greatest ex- treme. He asserts that in Scotland the inductive method was unknown, that the inductive philosophy exercised no influence on Scottish thinkers ; and, though Smith spent some of the most important years of his youth in England, where the inductive method was supreme, and though he was widely read in general philosophical literature, he yet thinks he adopted the deductive method because it was habitually followed in Scotland, and this though Buckle maintains that it is the only appropriate, or even possible, method in political economy, which surely would have been a sufficient reason for choosing it. That the inductive spirit exercised no influence on Scottish philosophers is certainly not true ; as will be presently shown, Montesquieu, whose method is essentially inductive, was in Smith's time studied with quite peculiar care and regarded with special veneration by Smith's ^fellow-countrymen. As to Smith himself, what may justly be said of him is that the deductive bent was certainly not the predominant character of his mind, nor did his great excellence lie in the "dialectic skill "which Buckle ascribes to him. "What strikes us most in his book is his wide and keen observation of social facts, and his perpetual tendency to dwell on these and elicit their significance, instead of drawing conclusions from abstract principles by elaborate chains of reasoning. It is this habit of his mind which gives us, in reading him, so strong and abiding a sense of being in contact with the realities of life. That Smith does, however, largely employ the deductive - SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 91 method is certain ; and that method is quite legitimate when the premises from which the deduction sets out are known universal facts of human nature and properties of external objects. Whether this mode of proceeding will carry us far may indeed well be doubted ; but its soundness cannot be disputed. But there is another vicious species of deduction which, as Cliffe Leslie has shown, seriously tainted the philosophy of Smith, in which the premises are not facts ascertained by observation, but the same a priori assumptions, half theological half metaphysical, respecting a supposed harmonious and beneficent natural order of things which we found in the physiocrats, and which, as we saw, were embodied in the name of that sect. In his view, Nature has made provision for social wellbeing by the principle of the human constitution which prompts every man to better his condition : the individual aims only at his private gain, but in doing so is " led by an invisible hand " to promote the public good, which was no part of his intention ; human institutions, by interfering with the action of this principle in the name of the public interest, defeat their own end ; but, when all systems of preference or restraint are taken away, " the obvious and simple system of natural liberty establishes itself of its own accord." This theory is, of course, not explicitly presented by Smith as a foundation of his econo- mic doctrines, but it is really the secret substratum on which they rest. Yet, whilst such latent postulates warped his view of things, they did not entirely determine his method. His native bent towards the study of things as they are pre- served him from extravagances into which many of his fol- lowers have fallen. But besides this, as Leslie has pointed out, the influence of Montesquieu tended to counterbalance the theoretic prepossessions produced by the doctrine of the jus naturce. That great thinker, though he could not, at his period, understand the historical method which is truly ap- propriate to sociological inquiry, yet founded his conclusions on induction. It is true, as Comte has remarked, that hit 92 POLITICAL ECONOMY. accumulation of facts, borrowed from the most different states of civilisation, and not subjected to philosophic criti- cism, necessarily remained on the whole sterile, or at least could not essentially advance the study of society much beyond the point at which he found it. His merit, as we have before mentioned, lay in the recognition of the subjection of all social phenomena to natural laws, not in the discovery of those laws. But this limitation was overlooked by the philosophers of the time of Smith, who were much attracted by the system he followed of tracing social facts to the special circumstances, physical or moral, of the communities in which they were observed. Leslie has shown that Lord Kaimes, Dalrymple, and Millar contemporaries of Smith, and the last his pupil were influenced by Montesquieu ; and he might have added the more eminent name of Ferguson, whose respect and admiration for the great Frenchman are expressed in striking terms in his History of Civil Society, 1 We are even informed that Smith himself in his later years was occupied in preparing a commentary on the Esprit des Lois. 2 1 " When I recollect what the President Montesquieu has written, I am at a loss to tell why I should treat of human affairs ; but I too am instigated by my reflections and my sentiments ; and I may utter them more to the comprehension of ordinary capacities, because I am more on the level of ordinary men. . . . The reader should be referred to what has been already delivered on the subject by this profound politician and amiable moralist " (Part I. sect. 10). Hume speaks of Montesquieu as an "illustrious writer," who "has established ... a system of political knowledge, which abounds in ingenious and brilliant thoughts and is not wanting in solidity " (Principles of Morals, sect. 3, and note). 2 The following paragraph appeared in the Moniteur Universel of March II, 1790: "On pretend que le celebre M. Smith, connu si avantageusement par son traite' des causes de la richesse des nations, prepare et va mettre a 1'impression un examen critique de 1'Esprit des Lois ; c'est le re'sultat de plusieurs anne'es de meditation, et Ton sait assez ce qu'on a droit d'attenclre d'une tete comme celle de M. Smith. Ce livre fera e'poque dans 1'histoire de la politique et de la philosophic , tel est du moins le jugement qu'en portent des gens instruits qui en connaissent des fragments dont ils ne parlent qu'avec an enthousiagma du plus heureux augure." SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 93 He was thus affected by two different and incongruous systems of thought, one setting out from an imaginary code of nature intended for the benefit of man, and leading to an optimistic view of the economic constitution founded on enlightened self- interest ; the other following inductive processes, and seeking to explain the several states in which human societies are found existing, as results of circumstances or institutions which have been in actual operation. And we find accordingly in his great work a combination of these two modes of treat- ment inductive inquiry on the one hand, and, on the other, a priori speculation founded on the "Mature" hypothesis. The latter vicious proceeding has in some of his followers been greatly aggravated, while the countervailing spirit of inductive investigation has fallen into the background, and indeed the necessity or utility of any such investigation in the economic field has been sometimes altogether denied. Some have represented Smith's work as of so loose a texture and so defective in arrangement that it may be justly described as consisting of a series of monographs. But this is certainly an exaggeration. The book, it is true, is not framed on a rigid mould, nor is there any parade of systematic divisions and subdivisions ; and this doubtless recommended it to men of the world and of business, for whose instruction it was, at least primarily, intended. But, as a body of exposi- tion, it has the real and pervading unity which results from a mode of thinking homogeneous throughout and the general absence of such contradictions as would arise from an imper- fect digestion of the subject. Smith sets out from the thought that the annual labour of a nation is the source from which it derives its supply of the necessaries and conveniences of life. He does not of course contemplate labour as the only factor in production ; but it has been supposed that by emphasising it at the outset he at once otrikes the note of difference between himself on the one hand and both the mercantilists and the physiocrats on the other. The improvement in the productiveness of laboui 94 POLITICAL ECONOMY. depends largely on its division ; and he proceeds accordingly / to give his unrivalled exposition of that principle, of the grounds on which it rests, and of its greater applicability to manufactures than to agriculture, in consequence of which the latter relatively Jags behind in the course of economic develop- ment. 1 The origin of the division of labour he finds in the propensity of human nature " to truck, barter, or exchange one thing for another." He shows that a certain accumulation of capital is a condition precedent of this division, and that the degree to which it can be carried is dependent on the extent of the market When the division of labour has been established, each member of the society must have recourse to the others for the supply of most of his wants ; a medium of exchange is thus found to be necessary, and money comes into use. The exchange of goods against each other or against money gives rise to the notion of value. This word has two meanings that of utility, and that of purchasing power ; the one may be called value in use, the other value in exchange. Merely mentioning the former, Smith goes on to study the latter. What, he asks, is the measure of value ? what regu- lates the amount of one thing which will be given for another ? " Labour," Smith answers, " is the real measure of the ex- changeable value of all commodities." " Equal quantities of labour, at all times and places, are of equal value to the labourer." 2 " Labour alone, therefore, never varying in its own value, is alone the ultimate and real standard by which the value of all commodities can at all times and places be estimated and compared. It is their real price ; money is their nominal price only." Money, however, is in men's actual transactions the measure of value, as well as the vehicle 1 Smith takes no account in this place of the evils which may arise from a highly developed division of labour. But see Bk. v. chap. i. 2 This sentence, which on close examination will be found to have no definite intelligible sense, affords a good example of the way in which metaphysical modes of thought obscure economic ideas. What is a "quantity of labour," the kind of labour being undetermined? And what is meant by the phrase " of equal value " I SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 95 of exchange ; and the precious metals are best suited for this function, as varying little in their own value for periods of moderate length ; for distant times, corn is a better standard of comparison. In relation to the earliest social stage, we need consider nothing but the amount of labour employed in the production of an article as determining its exchange value ; but in more advanced periods price is complex, and consists in the most general case of three elements wages, profit, and rent. Wages are the reward of labour. Profit arises as soon as stock, being accumulated in the hands of one person, is employed by him in setting others to work, and supplying them with materials and subsistence, in order to make a gain by what they produce. Rent arises as soon as the land of a country has all become private property ; " the landlords, like all other men, love to reap where they never sowed, and de- mand a rent even for its natural produce." In every improved society, then, these three elements enter more or less into the price of the far greater part of commodities. There is in every society or neighbourhood an ordinary or average rate of wages and profit in every different employment of labour and stock, regulated by principles to be explained hereafter, as also an ordinary or average rate of rent. These may be called the natural rates at the time when and the place where they pre- vail ; and the natural price of a commodity is what is sufficient to pay for the rent of the land, 1 the wages of the labour, and the profit of the stock necessary for bringing the commodity to market. The market price may rise above or fall below the amount so fixed, being determined by the proportion between the quantity brought to market and the demand of those who are willing to pay the natural price. Towards the natural price as a centre the market price, regulated by com- petition, constantly gravitates. Some commodities, however, are subject to a monopoly of production, whether from the peciiliarities of a locality or from legal privilege : their price 1 Smith's expressions on this point are lax, as will be seen when we come to examine the (so-called) Ricardian Theory of Bent. g6 POLITICAL ECONOMY. is always the highest that can be got ; the natural price of other commodities is the lowest which can be taken for any length of time together. The three component parts or factors of price vary with the circumstances of the society. The rate of wages is determined by a " dispute " or struggle of opposite interests between the employer and the workman. A minimum rate is fixed by the condition that they must be at least suffi- cient to enable a man and his wife to maintain themselves and, in general, bring up a family. The excess above this will depend on the circumstances of the country, and the con- sequent demand for labour, wages being high when national wealth is increasing, low when it is declining. The same circumstances determine the variation of profits, but in an opposite direction ; the increase of stock, which raises wages, tending to lower profit through the mutual competition of capitalists. " The whole of the advantages and disadvantages of the different employments of labour and stock must, in the same neighbourhood, be either perfectly equal or continually tending to equality ; " if one had greatly the advantage over the others, people would crowd into it, and the level would soon be restored. Yet pecuniary wages and profits are very different in different employments, either from certain cir- cumstances affecting the employments, which recommend or disparage them in men's notions, or from national policy, " which nowhere leaves things at perfect liberty." Hero follows Smith's admirable exposition of the causes which pro- duce the inequalities in wages and profits just referred to. a passage affording ample evidence of his habits of nice observa- tion of the less obvious traits in human nature, and also of the operation both of these and of social institutions on eco- nomic facts. The rent of land conies next to be considered, as the last of the three elements of price. Kent is a mono- poly price, equal, not to what the landlord could afford to take, but to what the farmer can afford to give. " Such parts only of the produce of land can commonly be brought to market, of which the ordinary price is sufficient to replace the stock SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 97 which must be employed in bringing them thither, togethel with the ordinary profits. If the ordinary price is more tha* this, the surplus part will naturally go to the rent of the land. If it is not more, though the commodity may be brought to market, it can afford no rent to the landlord. Whether the price is or is not more depends on the demand." "Rent, therefore, enters into the price of commodities in a different way from wages and profits. High or low wages and profit are the causes of high or low price ; high or low rent is the effect of it." Rent, wages, and profits, as they are the elements of price, are also the constituents of income; and the three great orders of every civilised society, from whose revenues that of every other order is ultimately derived, are the landlords, the labourers, and the capitalists. The relation of the interests of these three classes to those of society at large is different. The interest of the landlord always coincides with the general interest : whatever promotes or obstructs the one has the same effect on the other. So also does that of the labourer : when the wealth of the nation is progressive, his wages are high ; they are low when it is stationary or retrogressive. " The interest of the third order has not the same connection with the general interest of the society as that of the other two ; ... it is always in some respects different from and opposite to that of the public." The subject of the second book is " the nature, accumulation, and improvement of stock." A man's whole stock consists of two portions that which is reserved for his immediate consumption, and that which is employed so as to yield a revenue to its owner. This latter, which is his " capital," is divisible into the two classes of " fixed " and " circulating." The first is such as yields a profit without passing into other hands. The second consists of such goods, raised, manufac- tured, or purchased, as are sold for a profit and replaced by other goods ; this sort of capital is therefore constantly going from and returning to the hands of its owner. The whole 98 POLITICAL ECONOMY. capital of a society falls under the same two heads. Its fixed capital consists chiefly of (i) machines, (2) buildings which are the means of procuring a revenue, (3) agricultural improve- ments, and (4) the acquired and useful abilities of all members of the society (since sometimes known as " personal capital "). Its circulating capital is also composed of four parts (i) money, (2) provisions in the hands of the dealers, (3) materials, and (4) completed work in the hands of the manufacturer or merchant. Next comes the distinction of the gross national revenue from the net, the first being the whole produce of the land and labour of a country, the second what remains after deducting the expense of maintaining the fixed capital of the country and that part of its circulating capital which consists of money. Money, " the great wheel of circulation," is altogether different from the goods which are circulated by means of it ; it is a costly instrument by means of which all that each individual receives is distributed to him ; and the expenditure required, first to provide it, and afterwards to maintain it, is a deduction from the net revenue of the society. In development of this consideration, Smith goes on to explain the gain to the community arising from the substitution of paper money for that composed of the precious metals ; and here occurs the remarkable illustration in which the use of gold and silver money is compared to a highway on the ground, that of paper money to a waggon-way through the air. In proceeding to consider the accumulation of capital, he is led to the distinction between productive and unproductive labour, the former being that which is fixed or realised in a particular object or vendible article, the latter that which is not so realised. The former is exemplified in the labour of the manufacturing workman, the latter in that of the menial servant. A broad line of demarcation is thus drawn between the labour which results in commodities or increased value of commodities, and that which does no more than render services : the former is productive, the latter unproductive. " Productive " is by no means equivalent to " useful : " the SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 95 labours of the magistrate, the soldier, the churchman, lawyer, and physician are, in Smith's sense, unproductive. Productive labourers alone are employed out of capital ; unproductive labourers, as well as those who do not labour at all, are all maintained by revenue. In advancing industrial communities, the portion of annual produce set apart as capital bears an increasing proportion to that which is immediately destined to constitute a revenue, either as rent or as profit. Parsimony is the source of the increase of capital ; by augmenting the fund devoted to the maintenance of productive hands, it puts in motion an additional quantity of industry, which adds to the value of the annual produce. What is annually saved is as regularly consumed as what is spent, but by a different set of persons, by productive labourers instead of idlers or unpro- ductive labourers ; and the former reproduce with a profit the value of their consumption. The prodigal, encroaching on his capital, diminishes, as far as in him lies, the amount of productive labour, and so the wealth of the country; nor is this result affected by his expenditure being on home-made, as distinct from foreign, commodities. Every prodigalj there- fore, is a public enemy ; every frugal man a public benefactor. The only mode of increasing the annual produce of the land and labour is to increase either the number of productive labourers or the productive powers of those labourers. Either process will in general require additional capital, the former to maintain the new labourers, the latter to provide improved machinery or to enable the employer to introduce a more complete division of labour. In what are commonly called loans of money, it is not really the money, but the money's worth, that the borrower wants ; and the lender really assigns to him the right to a certain portion of the annual produce of the land and labour of the country. As the general capital of a country increases, so also does the particular portion of it from which the possessors wish to derive a revenue without being at the trouble of employing it themselves ; and, as the quantity of stock thus available for loans is augmented, the TOO POLITICAL ECONOMY. interest diminishes, not merely " from the general causes which make the market price of things commonly diminish as theif quantity increases," but because, with the increase of capital. " it becomes gradually more and more difficult to find within the country a profitable method of employing any new capital," whence arises a competition between different capitals, and a lowering of profits, which must diminish the price which can be paid for the use of capital, or in other words the rate of interest. It was formerly wrongly supposed, and even Locke and Montesquieu did not escape this error, that the fall in the value of the precious metals consequent on the discovery of the American mines was the real cause of the permanent lower- ing of the rate of interest in Europe. But this view, already refuted by Hume, is easily seen to be erroneous. " In some countries the interest of money has been prohibited by law. But, as something can everywhere be made by the use of money, something ought everywhere to be paid for the use of it," and will in fact be paid for it ; and the prohibition will only heighten the evil of usury by increasing the risk to the lender. The legal rate should be a very little above the lowest market rate ; sober people will then be preferred as borrowers to prodigals and projectors, who at a higher legal rate would have an advantage over them, being alone willing to offer that higher rate. 1 As to the different employments of capital, the quantity of productive labour put in motion by an equal amount varies extremely according as that amount is employed (i) in the improvement of lands, mines, or fisheries, (2) in manufactures, (3) in wholesale or (4) retail trade. In agriculture " Nature labours along with man," and not only the capital cf the farmer is reproduced with his profits, but also the rent of the landlord. It is therefore the employment of a given capital which is most advantageous to society. Next in order come manufactures; then wholesale trade first the home trade, 1 See p. 1 10, oii Beutbam. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 101 secondly the foreign trade of consumption, last the carrying- trade. All these employments of capital, however, are not only advantageous, but necessary, and will introduce them- selves in the due degree, if they are left to the spontaneous action of individual enterprise. These first two hooks contain Smith's general economic scheme; and we have stated it as fully as was consistent with the necessary brevity, because from this formulation of doctrine the English classical school set out, and round it the discussions of more recent times in different countries have in a great measure revolved. Some of the criticisms of his successors and their modifications of his doctrines will come under our notice as we proceed. The critical philosophers of the eighteenth century were often destitute of the historical spirit, which was no part of the endowment needed for their principal social office. But some of the most eminent of them, especially in Scotland, showed a marked capacity and predilection for historical studies. Smith was amongst the latter ; Knies and others justly remark on the masterly sketches of this kind which occur in the Wealth of Nations. The longest and most elaborate of these occupies the third book ; it is an account of the course followed by the nations of modern Europe in the successive development of the several forms of industry. It affords a curious example of the effect of doctrinal prepossessions in obscuring the results of historical inquiry. Whilst he correctly describes the European movement of industry, and explains it as aris- ing out of adequate social causes, he yet, in accordance with the absolute principles which tainted his philosophy, protests against it as involving an entire inversion of the "natural order of things." First agriculture, then manufactures, lastly foreign commerce; any other order jthan this he considers " unnatural and retrograde." Hume, a more purely positive thinker, simply sees the facts, accepts them, and classes them under a general law. " It is a violent method," he says, " and in most cases impracticable, to oblige the labourer to toil in ica POLITICAL ECONOMY. order to raise from the land more than what subsists himself and family. Furnish him with manufactures and commodities, and he will do it of himself." ''If we consult history, we shall find that, in most nations, foreign trade has preceded any refinement in home manufactures, and given birth to domestic luxury." The fourth book is principally devoted to the elaborate and exhaustive polemic against the mercantile system which finally drove it from the field of science, and has exercised a powerful influence on economic legislation. When protection is now advocated, it is commonly on different grounds from those which were in current use before the time of Smith. He believed that to look for the restoration of freedom of foreign trade in Great Britain would have been " as absurd as to expect that an Oceana or Utopia should be established in it ; " yet, mainly in consequence of his labours, that object has been completely attained; and it has lately been said with justice that free trade might have been more generally accepted by other nations if the patient reasoning of Smith had not been replaced by dogmatism. His teaching on the subject is not altogether unqualified; but, on the whole, with respect to exchanges of every kind, where economic motives alone enter, his voice is in favour of freedom. He has regard, however, to political as well as economic interests, and on the ground that " defence is of much more importance than opulence," pronounces the Navigation Act to have been " perhaps the wisest of all the commercial regulations of England." Whilst objecting to the prevention of the export of wool, he proposes a tax on that export as somewhat less injurious to the interest of growers than the prohibition, whilst it would " afford a sufficient advantage " to the domestic over the foreign manufacturer. This is, perhaps, his most marked deviation from the rigour of principle ; it was doubt- less a concession to popular opinion with a view to an attain- able practical improvement. The wisdom of retaliation in order to procure the repeal of high duties or prohibitions SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 103 imposed by foreign Governments depends, he says, altogether on the likelihood of its success in effecting the object aimed at, but he does not conceal his contempt for the practice of such expedients. The restoration of freedom in any manu- facture, when it has grown to considerable dimensions by means of high duties, should, he thinks, from motives of humanity, be brought about only by degrees and with cir- cumspection, though the amount of evil which would be caused by the immediate abolition of the duties is, in his opinion, commonly exaggerated. The case in which J. S. Mill would tolerate protection that, namely, in which an in- dustry well adapted to a country is kept down by the acquired ascendency of foreign producers is referred to by Smith ; but he is opposed to the admission of this exception for reasons which do not appear to be conclusive. 1 He is perhaps scarcely consistent in approving the concession of tempo- rary monopolies to joint-stock companies undertaking risky enterprises " of which the public is afterwards to reap the benefit." 2 He is less absolute in his doctrine of Governmental non- interference when he comes to consider in his fifth book the " expenses of the sovereign or the commonwealth." He recognises as coming within the functions of the state the erection and maintenance of those public institutions and public works which, though advantageous to the society, could not repay, and therefore must not be thrown upon, 1 It must, however, always be borne in mind that the adoption by a state of this sort of protection is liable to three practical dangers : (l) of en- couragement being procured through political influences for industries which could never have an independent healthy life in the country ; (2) of euch encouragement being continued beyond the term during which it might be usefully given ; (3) of a retaliatory spirit of exclusion being provoked in other communities. 2 Professor Bastable calls the author's attention to the interesting fact that the proposal of an export duty on wool and the justification ef a temporary monopoly to joint-stock companies both appear for tht first time in the edition of 1 784. io 4 POLITICAL ECONOMY. individuals or small groups of individuals. He remarks in just historical spirit that the performance of these functions requires very different degrees of expense in the different periods of society. Besides the institutions and works in- tended for public defence and the administration of justice, and those required for facilitating the commerce of the society, he considers those necessary for promoting the instruction of the people. He thinks the public at large may with propriety not only facilitate and encourage, but even impose upon almost the whole body of the people, the acquisition in youth of the most essential elements of education. He suggests as the mode of enforcing this obligation the requirement of submission to a test examination " before any one could obtain the freedom in any corporation, or be allowed to set up a trade in any village or town corporate." Similarly, he is of opinion that some probation, even in the higher and more difficult sciences, might be enforced as a condition of exercising any liberal profession, or becoming a candidate for any honourable office. The expense of the institutions for religious instruction as well as for general education, he holds, may without injustice be defrayed out of the funds of the whole society, though he would apparently prefer that it should be met by the voluntary contributions of those who think they have occasion for such education or instruction. There is much that is sound, as well as interesting and suggestive, in this fifth book, in which he shows a political instinct and a breadth of view by which he is favourably contrasted with the Manchester school. But, if we may say so without disrespect / to so great a man, there are traces in it of what is novr called Philistinism a low view of the ends of art and poetry which arose perhaps in part from personal defect, though it was common enough in even the higher minds in his century. There are also indications of a certain deadness t the lofty aims and perennial importance of religion, which was no doubt chiefly due to the influences of an age when the critical spirit was doing an indispensable work, in the SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 105 performance of which the transitory was apt to be confounded with the permanent. / For the sake of considering as a whole Smith's view of the functions of government, we have postponed noticing his treat- ment of the physiocratic system, which occupies a part of his fourth book. He had formed the acquaintance of Quesnay, Turgot, and other members of their group during his sojourn in France in 1765, and would, as he told Dugald Stewart, had the patriarch of the school lived long enough, have dedicated to him the Wealth of Nations. He declares that, with all its imperfections, the system of Quesnay is " perhaps the nearest approximation to the truth that had yet appeared on the sub- ject of political economy." Yet he seems not to be adequately conscious of the degree of coincidence between his own doc- trines and those of the physiocrats. Dupont de Nemours complained that he did not do Quesnay the justice of recognis- ing him as his spiritual father. It is, however, alleged, on the other side, that already in 1753 Smith had been teaching as professor a body of economic doctrine the same in its broad features with that contained in his great work. This is indeed said by Stewart ; and, though he gives no evidence of it, it is possibly quite true ; if so, Smith's doctrinal descent must be traced rather from Hume than from the French school. The principal error of this school, that, namely, of representing agricultural labour as alone productive, he refutes in the fourth book, though in a manner which has not always been con- sidered effective. Traces of the influence of their mistaken view appear to remain in his own work, as, for example, his assertion that in agriculture nature labours along with man, whilst in manufactures nature does nothing, man does all ; and his distinction between productive and unproductive labour, which was doubtless suggested by their use of those epithets, and which is scarcely consistent with his recognition of what is now called " personal capital." To the same source M'Culloch and others refer the origin of Smith's view, which they represent as an obvious error, that " individual advantage io6 . POLITICAL ECONOMY. is not always a true test of the public advantageousness of dif ferent employments." But that view is really quite correct, as Professor Nicholson has clearly shown. 1 That the form taken by the use of capital, profits being given, Is not indif- ferent to the working class as a whole even Ricardo admitted j and Cairnes, as we shall see, built on this consideration some of the most far-reaching conclusions in his Leading Principles. On Smith's theory of taxation in his fifth book it is not necessstry for us to dwell. The well-known canons which he lays down as prescribing the essentials of a good system have been generally accepted. They have lately been severely criticised by Professor Walker of whose objections, however, there is only one which appears to be well founded. Smith seems to favour the view that the contribution of the indi- vidual to public expenses may be regarded as payment for the services rendered to him by the state, and ought to be proportional to the extent of those services. If he held this opinion, which some of his expressions imply, lie was certainly so far wrong in principle. / V>W.^ We shall not be held to anticipate unduly if we remark here on the way in which opinion, revolted by the aberrations of some of Smith's successors, has tended to turn from the disciples to the master. A strong sense of his compara- tive freedom from the vicious tendencies of Ricardo and his followers has recently prompted the suggestion that we ought now to recur to Smith, and take up once more from him the line of the economical succession. But notwithstanding his indisputable superiority, and whilst fully recognising the great services rendered by his immortal work, we must not forget that, as has been already said, that work was, on the whole, a product, though an exceptionally eminent one, of the negative philosophy of the last century, resting largely in its ultimate foundation on metaphysical bases. The mind of Smith waa mainly occupied with the work of criticism so urgent in his 1 In the Introductory Essay to his edition of the Wealth of Nation*. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 107 time ; his principal task was to discredit and overthrow the economic system then prevalent, and to demonstrate the radical unfitness of the existing European Governments to direct the industrial movement. This office of his fell in with, and formed a part of, the general work of demolition carried on by the thinkers who gave to the eighteenth century its characteristic tone. It is to his honour that, besides this destructive operation, he contributed valuable elements to the preparation of an organic system of thought and of life. In his pecial domain he has not merely extinguished many errors and prejudices, and cleared the ground for truth, but has left us a permanent possession in the judicious analyses of economic facts and ideas, the wise practical suggestions, and the luminous indications of all kinds with which his work abounds. Be- longing to the best philosophical school of his period, that with which the names of Hume and Diderot are associated, he tended strongly towards the positive point of view. But it was not possible for him to attain it ; and the final and fully normal treatment of the economic life of societies must be constituted on other and more lasting foundations than those which underlie his imposing construction. It has been well said that of philosophic doctrines the saying " By their fruits ye shall know them " is eminently true. And it cannot be doubted that the germs of the vicious methods and false or exaggerated theories of Smith's successors are to be found in his own work, though his good sense and practical bent prevented his following out his principles to their extreme consequences. The objections of Hildebrand and others to the entire historical development of doctrine which the Germans designate as " Smithianismus " are regarded by those critics as applicable, not merely to his school as a whole, but, though in a less degree, to himself. The following are the most important of these objections. It is said (j.) Smith's con- ception of the social economy is essentially individualistic. In this he falls in with the general character of the negative philosophy of his age. That philosophy, in its most typical io8 - POLITICAL ECONOMY. forms, even, denied the natural existence of the disinterested affections, and explained the altruistic feelings as secondary results of self-love. Smith, however, like Hume, rejected these extreme views ; and hence it has been held that in tho Wealth of Nations he consciously, though tacitly, abstracted from the benevolent principles in human nature, and as a logical artifice supposed an " economic man " actuated by purely selfish motives. However this may be, he certainly places himself habitually at the point of view of the individual, whom he treats as a purely egoistic force, working uniformly in the direction of private gain, without regard to the good of others or of the community at large. (2.) He justifies this personal attitude by its consequences, presenting the optimistic view that the good of the community is best attained through the free play of individual cupidities, provided only that the law prevents the interference of one member of the society with the self-seeking action of another. He assumes with the negative school at large though he has passages which are not in harmony with these propositions that every one knows his true interest and will pursue it, and that the economic advantage of the individual coincides with that of the society. To this last conclusion he is secretly led, as we have seen, by a priori theological ideas, and also by meta- physical conceptions of a supposed system of nature, natural right, and natural liberty. (3.) By this reduction of every question to one of individual gain, he is led to a too exclusive consideration of exchange value as distinct from wealth in the proper sense. This, whilst lending a mechanical facility in arriving at conclusions, gives a superficial character to economic investigation, divorcing it from the physical and biological sciences, excluding the question of real social utility, leaving no room for a criticism of production, and leading to a denial, like J. S. Mill's, of any economic doctrine dealing with consumption in other words, with, the use of wealth. (4.) In condemning the existing industrial policy, lie tends too much towards a glorification of non-government SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 109 and a repudiation of all social intervention for the regulation of economic life. (5.) He does not keep in view the moral destination of our race, nor regard wealth as a means to the higher ends of life, and thus incurs, not altogether unjustly, the charge of materialism, in the wider sense of that word. Lastly, (6.) his whole system is too absolute in its character; it does not sufficiently recognise the fact that, in the language of Hildebrantl, inan, as a member of society, is a child of civilisation and a product of history, and that account ought to be taken of the different stages of social development as implying altered economic conditions and calling for altered economic action, or even involving a modification of the actor. Perhaps in all the respects here enumerated, certainly in some of them, and notably in the last, Smith is less open to criticism than most of the later English economists ; but it must, we think, be admitted that to the general principles which lie at the basis of his scheme the ultimate growth of these several vicious tendencies is traceable. Great expectations had been entertained respecting Smith's work by competent judges before its publication, as is shown by the language of Ferguson on the subject in his History oj Civil Society. 1 That its merits received prompt recognition is proved by the fact of six editions having been called for within the fifteen years after its apjiearance. 2 From the year 1 " The public will probably soon be furnished with a theory of national oeconomy, equal to what has ever appeared on any subject of science whatever " (Pajt III. sect. 4). 2 Five editions of the Wealth of Nations appeared during the life of the author: the second in 1779, the third in 1784, the fourth in 1786, and the fifth in 1789. After the third edition Smith made no change in the text. The principal editions containing matter added by other economists are those by William Playfair, with notes, 1805 ; by David Buchanan, with notes, 1814 ; by J. R. M'Culloch, with life of the author, introductory discourse, notes, and supplemental dissertations. 1828 (also, with numerous additions, 1839 ; since reprinted several times with fur- ther additions) ; by the author of Enyland and America (Edward Gibbon Wakefield), with a commentary, which, however, is not continued beyond the second book, 1835-9 ; by James E. Thorold Rogers, Professor of no POLITICAL ECONOMY. 1783 it was more and more quoted in Parliament. Pitt was greatly impressed by its reasonings ; Smith is reported to have said that that Minister understood the book as well as himself. Pulteney said in 1797 that Smith would persuade the then living generation and would govern the next. 1 Smith's earliest critics were Bentham and Lauderdale, who, though in general agreement with him, differed on special points. Jeremy Bentham was author of a short treatise en- titled A Manual of Political Economy and various eco- nomic monographs, the most celebrated of which was his Defence of Usury (1787). This contained (Letter xiii.) an elaborate criticism of a passage in the Wealth of Nations, already cited, in which Smith had approved of a legal maxi- mum rate of interest fixed but a very little above the lowest market rate, as tending to throw the capital of the country into the hands of sober persons, as opposed to " prodigals and projectors." Smith is said to have admitted that Bentham had made out his case. He certainly argues it with great ability ; 2 and the true doctrine no doubt is that, in a developed industrial society, it is expedient to let the rate be fixed by contract between the lender and the borrower, the law inter- fering only in case of fraud. Bentham's main significance does not belong to the economic field. But, on the one hand, what is known as Benthamism was undoubtedly, as Comte has said, 3 a derivative from poli- tical economy, and in particular from the system of natural political economy at Oxford, with biographical preface and a careful verification of all Smith's quotations and references, 1869 (26. ed., l8So) ; and by J. S. Nicholson, professor at Edinburgh, with notes referring to sources of further information on the various topics handled in the text, 1884. There is a careful Abridgment by W. P. Emerton (2d ed., 1881), founded on the earlier Analysis of Jeremiah Joyce (3d ed., 1821). 1 Parl. Hist., vol. xxxiii. p. 778. 2 It must be remembered, however, that the same doctrine had been supported with no less ability as early as 1769 by Turgot in his Mtmoirt tur lea prSts d' argent. Lettret d' A. Comte d /. S. Mill, p. 4. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. in liberty ; and, on the other, it promoted the temporary ascen- dency of that system by extending to the whole of social and moral theory the use of the principle of individual interest and the method of deduction from that interest. This alliance between political economy and the scheme of Beutham is seen in the personal group of thinkers which formed itself round him, thinkers most inaptly characterised by J. S. Mill as " profound," but certainly possessed of much acuteness and logical power, and tending, though vaguely, towards a positive sociology, which, from their want of genuinely scientific culture and their absolute modes of thought, they were incapable of founding. Lord Lauderdale, in his Inquiry into the Nature and Origin of Public Wealth (1804), a book still worth reading, pointed out curtain real weaknesses in Smith's account of value ami the measure of value, and of the productivity of labour, and threw additional light on several subjects, such as the true mode of estimating the national income, and the reaction of the distribution of wealth on its production. Smith stood just at the beginning of a great industrial revolution. The world of production and commerce in which he lived was still, as Cliffe Leslie has said, a " very early " and comparatively narrow one ; " the only steam-engine he refers to is Newcomen's," and the cotton trade is mentioned by him only once, and that incidentally. " Between the years \ 1760 and 1770," says Mr. Marshall, "Koebuck began to smelt J iron by coal, Brindley connected the rising seats of manufao- / vUres with the sea by canals, Wedgwood discovered the art of I making earthenware cheaply and well, Hargreaves invented / the spinning-jenny, Arkwright utilised Wyatt's and High's ( inventions for spinning by rollers and applied water-power to \ move them, and Watt invented the condensing steam-engine. J Crompton's mule and Cartwright's power-loom came shortly/ after." Out of this rapid evolution followed a vast expan- sion of industry, but also many deplorable results, which, had Smith been able to foresee them, might have made him a IBM - H2 POLITICAL ECONOMY. enthusiastic believer in the benefits to be wrought by the mere liberation of effort, and a less vehement denouncer of old institutions which in their day had given a partial pro- tection to labour. Alongside of these evils of the new indus- trial system, Socialism appeared as the alike inevitable and indispensable expression of the protest of the working classes and the aspiration after a better order of things ; and what we now call " the social question," that inexorable problem of modern life, rose into the place which it has ever since mnin- tained. This question was first effectually brought before the English mind by Thomas Robert Malthus (1766-1834), not, however, under the impulse of revolutionary sympathies, but in the interests of a conservative policy. The first edition of the work which achieved this result appeared anonymously in 1798 under the title An Essay on the Principle of Population, as it affects the future im- provement of Society, with remarks on the speculations oj Mr. Godwin, M. Condorcet, and other writers. This book arose out of certain private controversies of its author with his father, Daniel Malthus, who had been a friend of Rousseau, and was an ardent believer in the doctrine of human progress as preached by Condorcet and other French thinkers and by their English disciples. The most distinguished of the latter was William Godwin, whose Enquiry concerning Political Justice had been published in 1793. The views put forward in that work had been restated by its author in the Enquirer (1797), and it was on the essay in this volume entitled " Avarice and Profusion " that the discussion between the father and the son arose, " the general question of the future improvement of society " being thus raised between them the elder Malthus defending the doctrines of Godwin, and the younger assailing them. The latter " sat down with an in- tention of merely stating his thoughts on paper in a clearer manner than he thought he could do in conversation/' and the Essay on population was the result The social scheme of Godwin was founded on the idea that SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 113 the evils of society arise from the vices of human institutions. There is more than enough of wealth available for all, but it is not equally shared : one has too much, another has little or nothing. Let this wealth, as well as the labour of producing it, be equally divided ; then every one will by moderate exertion obtain sufficient for plain living ; there will be abun- dant leisure, which will be spent in intellectual and moral self-improvement; reason will determine human actions; government and every kind of force will be unnecessary ; and, in time, by the peaceful influence of truth, perfection and happiness will be established on earth. To these glowing anticipations Malthus opposes the facts of the necessity of food and the tendency of mankind to increase up to the limit of the available supply of it. In a state of universal physical wellbeing, this tendency, which in real life is held in check by the difficulty of procuring a subsistence, would operate without restraint. Scarcity would follow the increase of num- bers ; the leisure would soon cease to exist ; the old struggle for life would recommence ; and inequality would reign once more. If Godwin's ideal system, therefore, could be estab- lished, the single force of the principle of population, Malthus maintained, would suffice to break it down. It will be seen that the essay was written with a polemical object ; it was an occasional pamphlet directed against the Utopias of the day, not at all a systematic treatise on popula- tion suggested by a purely scientific interest. As a polemic, it was decidedly successful ; it was no difficult task to dispose of the scheme of equality propounded by Godwin. Already, in 1761, Dr. Kobert Wallace had published a work (which was used by Malthus in the composition of his essay) entitled Various Prospects of Mankind, Nature, and Providence, in which, after speaking of a community of goods as a remedy for the ills of society, he confessed that he saw one fatal objection to such a social organisation, namely, " the excessive population that would ensue." With Condorcet's extrava- gances, too, Malthus easily dealt. That eminent man, amidst 114 POLITICAL ECONOMY. the tempest of the French Revolution, had written, whilst in hiding from his enemies, his Esquisse d'un tableau historique de Tesprit humain. The general conception of this book makes its appearance an epoch in the history of the rise of sociology. In it, if we except some partial sketches by Turgot, 1 is for the first time explained the idea of a theory of social dynamics founded on history ; and its author is on this ground recognised by Comte as his principal immediate predecessor, But in the execution of his great project Condorcet failed. His negative metaphysics prevent his justly appreciating the past, and he indulges, at the close of his work, in vague hypotheses respecting the perfectibility of our race, and in irrational expectations of an indefinite extension of the dura- tion of human life. Malthus seems to have little sense of the nobleness of Condorcet's attitude, and no appreciation of the grandeur of his leading idea. But of his chimerical hopes he is able to make short work ; his good sense, if somewhat limited and prosaic, is at least effectual in detecting and exposing utopias. The project of a formal and detailed treatise on population was an after-thought of Malthus. The essay in which he had studied a hypothetic future led him to examine the effects of the principle he had put forward on the past and present state of society ; and he undertook an historical examination of these effects, and sought to draw such inferences in relation to the actual state of things as experience seemed to warrant. The consequence of this was such a change in the nature and composition of the essay as made it, in his own language, "a new work." The book, so altered, appeared in 1803 under the title, An Essay on the Principle of Popu- lation, or a View of its Past and Present Effects on Human Happiness ; with an Enquiry into our prospects respecting the future removal or mitigation of the evils which it occasions. 1 In his discourse at the Sorbonne (1750), Sur Its progrtt tuccessif t dt humain. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 115 In the original form of the essay he had spoken of no checks to population but those which came under the head either of vice or of misery. He now introduces the new element of the preventive check supplied by what he calls " moral restraint," and is thus enabled to " soften some of the harshest conclusions " at which he had before arrived. The treatise passed through six editions l in his lifetime, and in all of them he introduced various additions and correc- tions. That of 1817 is the last he fully revised, and presents the text substantially as it has since been reprinted. Notwithstanding the great development which he gave to his work, and the almost unprecedented amount of discussion to which it gave rise, it remains a matter of some difficulty to discover what solid contribution he has made to our know- ledge, nor is it easy to ascertain precisely what practical precepts, not already familiar, he founded on his theoretic principles. This twofold vagueness is well brought out in his celebrated correspondence with Senior, in the course of which it seems to be made apparent that his doctrine is new not so much in its essence as in the phraseology in which it is couched. He himself tells us that when, after the publication of the original essay, the main argument of which he had deduced from Hume, Wallace, Smith, and Price, he began to inquire more closely into the subject, he found that "much more had been done " upon it " than he had been aware of." It had " been treated in such a manner by some of the French economists, occasionally by Montesquieu, and, among our own writers, by Dr. Franklin, Sir James Steuart, Mr. Arthur Young, and Mr. Townsend, as to create a natural surprise that it had not excited more of the public attention." " Much, however," he thought, " remained yet to be done. The comparison between the increase of population and food had not, perhaps, been stated with sufficient force and precision," and " few inquiries had been made into the various modes by 1 Their dates are 1798, 1803, 1806, 1807, 1817, 18261 u6 POLITICAL ECONOMY. which the level " between population and the means of subsistence "is effected." The first desideratum here men- tioned the want, namely, of an accurate statement of the relation between the increase of population and food Malthus doubtless supposed to have been supplied by the celebrated proposition that " population increases in a geometrical, food in an arithmetical ratio." This proposition, however, has been conclusively shown to be erroneous, there being no such dif- ference of law between the increase of man and that of the organic beings which form his food. J. S. Mill is indignant with those who criticise Malthus's formula, which he ground- lessly describes as a mere " passing remark," because, as he thinks, though erroneous, it sufficiently suggests what is true j but it is surely important to detect unreal science, and to test strictly the foundations of beliefs. When the formula which we have cited is not used, other somewhat nebulous expressions are frequently employed, as, for example, that " population has a tendency to increase faster than food," a sentence in which both are treated as if they were spontaneous growths, and which, on account of the ambiguity of the word "tendency," is admittedly consistent with the fact asserted by Senior, that food tends to increase faster than population. It must always have been perfectly well known that popula- tion will probably (though not necessarily) increase with every augmentation of the supply of subsistence, and may, in some instances, inconveniently press upon, or even for a certain time exceed, the number properly corresponding to that supply. iJor could it ever have been doubted that war, disease, poverty the last two often the consequences of vice are causes which keep population down. In fact, the way in which abundance, increase of numbers, want, increase of deaths, succeed each other in the natural economy, when reason does not intervene, had been fully explained by the Rev. Joseph Townsend in his Dissertation on the Poor Laws (1786), which was known to Malthus. Again, it is surely plain enough that the apprehension by individuals of the evils of SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 117 poverty, or a sense of duty to their possible offspring, may retard the increase of population, and has in all civilised communities operated to a certain extent in that way. It is only when such obvious truths are clothed in the technical terminology of "positive" and "preventive checks" that they appear novel and profound ; and yet they appear to con- tain the whole message of Malthus to mankind. The labo- rious apparatus of historical and statistical facts respecting the several countries of the globe, adduced in the altered form of the essay, though it contains a good deal that is curious and interesting, establishes no general result which was not previously well known, and is accordingly ignored by James Mill and others, who rest the theory on facts patent to universal observation. Indeed, as we have seen, the entire historical inquiry was an after-thought of Malthus, who, before entering on it, had already announced his fundamental principle. It would seem, then, that 'what has been ambitiously called Malthus's theory of population, instead of being a great dis- covery, as some have represented it, or a poisonous novelty, as others have considered it, is no more than a formal enun- ciation of obvious, though sometimes neglected, facts. The pretentious language often applied to it by economists is objectionable, as being apt to make us forget that the whole subject with which it deals is as yet very imperfectly under- j stood the causes which modify the force of the sexual instinct, and those which lead to variations in fecundity, still t awaiting a complete investigation. 1 It is the law of diminishing returns from land (of which more will be said hereafter), involving as it does though only hypothetical^ the prospect of a continuously increasing difficulty in obtaining the necessary sustenance for all the members of a society, that gives the principal importance to population as an economic factor. It is, in fact, the conflu- 1 On this subject see the speculations of Mr. Herbert Spencer in nil Principles of Biology, Part VI. chaps, xii. xiii ii8 POLITICAL ECONOMY. ence of the Malthusian ideas with the theories of Ricardo, especially with the corollaries which the latter, as we shall see, deduced from the doctrine of rent (though these were not accepted by Malthus), that has led to the introduction of population as an element in the discussion of so many economic questions in recent times. Malthus had undoubtedly the great merit of having called public attention in a striking and impressive way to a subject which had neither theoretically nor practically been sufficiently considered. But he and his followers appear to have greatly exaggerated both the magnitude and the urgency of the dangers to which they pointed. 1 In their conceptions a single social imperfection assumed such portentous dimensions that it seemed to overcloud the whole heaven and threaten the world with ruin. This doubtless arose from his having at first omitted altogether from his view of the question the great counteracting agency of moral restraint. Because a force exists, capable, if unchecked, of producing certain results, it does not follow that those results are imminent or even possible in the sphere of experience. A body thrown from the hand would, under the single impulse of projection, move for ever in a straight line ; but it would not be reason- able to take special action for the prevention of this result, ignoring the fact that it will be sufficiently counteracted by the other forces which will come into play. And such other forces exist in the case we are considering. If the inherent energy of the principle of population (supposed everywhere the same) is measured by the rate at which numbers increase under the most favourable circumstances, surely the force of less favourable circumstances, acting through prudential or altruistic motives, is measured by the great difference between this maximum rate and those which are observed to prevail in most European countries. Under a rational system of insti- i Malthus himself said : " It is probable that, having found the bow bent too much one way, I was induced to bend it too much the other in order to make it straight." SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. iig tutions, the adaptation of numbers to the means available for their support is effected by the felt or anticipated pressure of circumstances and the fear of social degradation, within a tolerable degree of approximation to what is desirable. To bring the result nearer to the just standard, a higher measure of popular enlightenment and more serious habits of moral reflection ought indeed to be encouraged. But it is the duty of the individual to his actual or possible offspring, and not any vague notions as to the pressure of the national population on subsistence, that will be adequate to influence conduct The only obligation on which Malthus insists is that of abstinence from marriage so long as the necessary provision for a family has not been acquired or cannot be reasonably anticipated. The idea of post-nuptial continence, which has since been put forward by J. S. Mill and others, is foreign to his view. He even suggests that an allowance might be made from the public funds for every child in a family beyond the number of six, on the ground that, when a man marries, he cannot tell how many children he shall have, and that the relief from an unlooked-for distress afforded by such a grant would not operate as an encouragement to marriage. The duty of economic prudence in entering on the married state is ' plain ; but in the case of working men the idea of a secured provision must not be unduly pressed, and it must also be remembered that the proper age for marriage in any class de- pends on the duration of life in that class. Too early mar- riages, however, are certainly not unfrequent, and they are attended with other than material evils, so that possibly even legal measures might with advantage be resorted to for pre- venting them in all ranks by somewhat postponing the age of full civil competence. On the other hand, however, the Malthusians often speak too lightly of involuntary celibacy, not recognising sufficiently that it is a deplorable necessity. They do not adequately estimate the value of domestic life as a school of the civic virtues, and the social importance (even apart from personal happiness) of the mutual affective educa- 120 POLITICAL ECONOMY. tion arising from the relations of the sexes in a well-constituted union. Malthus further infers from his principles that states should not artificially stimulate population, and in particular that poor-laws should not he estahlished, and, where they exist, should be abolished. The first part of this proposition cannot be accepted as applying to every social phase, for it is evident that in a case like that of ancient Rome, where continuous conquest was the chief occupation of the national activity, or in other periods when protracted wars threatened the inde- pendence or security of nations, statesmen might wisely take special action of the kind deprecated by Malthus. In relation to modern industrial communities he is doubtless in general right, though the promotion of immigration in new states is similar in principle to the encouragement of population. The question of poor-laws involves other considerations. The English system of his day was, indeed, a vicious one, though acting in some degree as a corrective of other evils in our social institutions ; and efforts for its amendment tended to the public good. But the proposal of abolition is one from which statesmen have recoiled, and which general opinion has never adopted. It is difficult to believe that the present system will be permanent ; it is too mechanical and undiscriminating ; on some sides too lax, it is often unduly rigorous in the treatment of the worthy poor who are the victims of misfortune ; and, in its ordinary modes of dealing with the young, it is open to grave objection. But it would certainly be rash to abolish it ; it is one of several institutions which will more wisely be retained until the whole subject of the life of the working classes has been more thoroughly, and also more sympatheti- cally, studied. The position of Malthus with respect to the relief of destitution is subject to this general criticism, that, first proving too much, he then shrinks from the consequences of his own logic. It follows from his arguments, and is indeed explicitly stated in a celebrated passage of his original essay, that he who has brought children into the world without SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 121 adequate provision for them should be left to the punishment of Nature, that " it is a miserable ambition to wish to snatch the rod from her hand," and to defeat the action of her laws, which are the laws of God, and which " have, doomed him and his family to suffer." Though his theory leads him to this conclusion, he could not, as a Christian clergyman, main- tain the doctrine that, seeing our brother in need, we ought to shut up our bowels of compassion from him ; and thus he is involved in the radical inconsequence of admitting the law- fulness, if not the duty, of relieving distress in cases where he yet must regard the act as doing mischief to society. Buckle, who was imposed on by more than one of the exaggerations of the economists, accepts the logical inference which Malthua evaded. He alleges that the only ground on which we are justified in relieving destitution is the essentially self-regard- ing one, that by remaining deaf to the appeal of the sufferer we should probably blunt the edge of our own finer sensibilities. It can scarcely be doubted that the favour which was at once accorded to the views of Malthus in certain circles was due in part to an impression, very welcome to the higher ranks of society, that they tended to relieve the rich and powerful of responsibility for the condition of the working classes, by showing that the latter had chiefly themselves to blame, and not either the negligence of their superiors or the institutions of the country. The application of his doctrines, too, made by some of his successors had the effect of discouraging all active effort for social improvement. Thus Chalmers " reviews seriatim and gravely sets aside all the schemes usually pro- posed for the amelioration of the economic condition of the people" on the ground that an increase of comfort will lead to an increase of numbers, and so the last state of things will be worse than the first. Malthus has in more recent times derived a certain degree of reflected lustre from the rise and wide acceptance of the Darwinian hypothesis. Its author himself, in tracing its filiation, points to the phrase " struggle for existence " used by 121 POLITICAL ECONOMY. Malthus in relation to the social competition. Darwin believe* that man has advanced to his present high condition through such a struggle, consequent on his rapid multiplication. He regards, it is true, the agency of this cause for the improve- ment of our race as largely superseded by moral influences in the more advanced social stages. Yet he considers it, even in these stages, of so much importance towards that end, that notwithstanding the individual suffering arising from the struggle for life, he deprecates any great reduction in the natural, by which he seems to mean the ordinary, rate of increase. There has been of late exhibited in some quarters a ten- dency to apply the doctrine of the "survival of the fittest" to human society in such a way as to intensify the harsher features of Maltlms's exposition by encouraging the idea that whatever cannot sustain itself is fated, and must be allowed, to disappear. But what is repellent in this conception is removed by a wider view of the influence of Humanity, aa a disposing power, alike on vital and on social conditions. As in the general animal domain the supremacy of man introduces a new force consciously controlling and ultimately determining the destinies of the subordinate species, so human providence in the social sphere can intervene for the protection of the weak, modifying by its deliberate action what would otherwise be a mere contest of comparative strengths inspired by selfish instincts. 1 David Ricardo (1772-1823) is essentially of the school of Smith, whose doctrines he in the main accepts, whilst he seeks to develop them, and to correct them in certain par- 1 The Essay on Population and the Inquiry into the Nature and Pro- gressof Rent (i8i5), to be hereafter mentioned, are by far the most im- portant contributions of Malthus to the science. He was also author of Principles of Political Economy (1820), Definitions in Political Economy (1827), and other minor pieces. On these less important writings of Malthus, and on his personal history, see Malthus and his Work (i885), by James Bonar, who has also edited (1888) Ricardo's Letters to Malthus, SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 123 ticulars. But his mode of treatment is very different from Smith's. The latter aims at keeping close to the realities of _, life as he finds them, at representing the conditions and ^ relations of men and things as they are ; and, as Hume re- marked on first reading his great work, his principles are everywhere exemplified and illustrated with curious facts. Quite unlike this is the way in which Ricardo proceeds. He \U> moves in a world of abstractions. He sets out from more or less arbitrary assumptions, reasons deductively from these, and announces his conclusions as true, without allowing for the partial unreality of the conditions assumed or confronting his results with experience. When he seeks to illustrate his doctrines, it is from hypothetical cases, his favourite device being that of imagining two contracting savages, and consider- ing how they would be likely to act. He does not explain probably he had not systematically examined, perhaps was not competent to examine the appropriate method of poli- tical economy; and the theoretic defence of his mode of proceeding was left to be elaborated by J. S. Mill and Cairnes. But his example had a great effect in determining the practice of his successors. There was something highly attractive to the ambitious theorist in the sweeping march of logic which seemed in Ricardo's hands to emulate the certainty and com- prehensiveness of mathematical proof, and in the portable and pregnant formulae which were so convenient in argument, and gave a prompt, if often a more apparent than real, solution of difficult problems. Whatever there was of false or narrow in the fundamental positions of Smith had been in a great degree corrected by his practical sense and strong instinct for reality, but was brought out in its full dimensions and even exaggerated in the abstract theorems of Ricardo and his followers. The dangers inherent in his method were aggravated by the extreme looseness of his phraseology. Senior pronounces him "the most incorrect writer who ever attained philosophical eminence." His most ardent admirers find him fluctuating 124 POLITICAL ECONOMY. and uncertain in the use of words, and generally trace his errors to a confusion between the ordinary employment of a term and some special application of it which he has himself devised. The most complete exposition of his system is to be found in his Principles of Political Economy and Taxation (1817). This work is not a complete treatise on the science, but a rather loosely connected series of disquisitions on value and price, rent, wages and profits, taxes, trade, money and banking. Yet, though the connection of the parts is loose, the same fundamental ideas recur continually, and determine the character of the entire scheme. The principal problem to which he addresses himself in this work is that of distribution, that is to say, the proportions of the whole produce of the country which will be allotted to the proprietor of land, to the capitalist, and to the labourer. And it is important to observe that it is especially the varia- tions in their respective portions which take place in the pro- gress of society that he professes to study, one of the most unhistorical of writers thus indicating a sense of the necessity of a doctrine of economic dynamics a doctrine which, from his point of view, it was impossible to supply. The principle which he puts first in order, and which is indeed the key to the whole, is this that the exchange_value of any commodity the supply of which can be increased at will is regulated, under a regime of free competition, by the labour necessary for its production. Similar propositions are to be found in the Wealth of Nations, not to speak of earlier English writings. Smith had said that, " in the early and rude state of society which precedes both the accumulation of stock and the appropriation of land, the proportion between the quan- tities of labour necessary for acquiring different objects seems to be the only circumstance which can afford any rule for ex- changing them with one another." But he wavers in his con- ception, and present? as the measure of value sometimes the quantity of labour necessary for the production of the object, SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 125 sometimes the quantity of labour which the object would com- mand in the market, which would be identical only for a given time and place. The theorem requires correction for a deve- loped social system by the introduction of the consideration of capital, and takes the form in which it is elsewhere quoted from Malthus by Ricardo, that the real price of a commodity " depends on the greater or less quantity of capital and labour which must be employed to produce it." (The expression " quantity of capital " is lax, the element of time being omitted, but the meaning is obvious.) Ricardo, however, constantly takes no notice of capital, mentioning labour alone in his state- ment of this principle, and seeks to justify his practice by treating capital as "accumulated labour;" but this artificial way of viewing the facts obscures the nature of the co-opera- tion of capital in production, and by keeping the necessity of this co-operation out of sight has encouraged some socialistic errors. Ricardo does not sufficiently distinguish between the cause or determinant and the measure of value ; nor does he carry back the principle of cost of production as regulator of value to its foundation in the effect of that cost on the limita- tion of supply. It is the " natural price " of a commodity that is fixed by the theorem we have stated ; the market price will be subject to accidental and temporary variations from this standard, depending on changes in demand and supply ; but the price will, permanently and in the long run, depend on cost of production defined as above. On this basis Ricardo goes on to explain the laws according to which the produce of the land and the labour of the country is distributed amongst the several classes which take part in production. The theory of rent, with which he begins, though commonly associated with his name, and though it certainly forms the most vital part of his general economic scheme, was not really his, nor did he lay claim to it. He distinctly states in the preface to the Principles, that "in 1815 Mr Malthus, in his Inquiry into the Nature and Progress of Rent, and a fellow of University College, Oxford, in his Essay on the Application of 126 POLITICAL ECONOMY. Capital to Land, presented to the world, nearly at the sam moment, the true doctrine of rent." The second writer here referred to was Sir Edward West, afterwards a judgvj of the supreme court of Bombay. Still earlier than the time of Malthus and "West, as M'Culloch has pointed out, this doctrine had been clearly conceived and fully stated by Dr. James Anderson in his Enquiry into the Nature of Corn-Laws, pub- lished at Edinburgh in 1777.* That this tract was unknown to Malthus and West we have every reason to believe ; but the theory is certainly as distinctly enunciated and as satis- factorily supported in it as in their treatises ; and the whole way in which it is put forward by Anderson strikingly re- sembles the form in which it is presented by Eicardo. The essence of the theory is that rent, being the price paid by the cultivator to the owner of land for the use of its productive powers, is equal to the excess of the price of the produce of the land over the cost of produr.tion on that land. With the increase of population, and therefore of demand for food, inferior soils will be taken into cultivation ; and the price of the entire supply necessary for the community will be regulated by the cost of production of that portion of the supply which is produced at the greatest expense. But for the land which will barely repay the cost of cultivation no rent will be paid. Hence the rent of any quality of land will be equal to the difference between the cost of production on that land and the cost of production of that produce which is raised at the greatest expense. / The doctrine is perhaps most easily apprehended by means of the supposition here made of the coexistence in a country of a series of soils of different degrees of fertility which are successively taken into cultivation as population increases. But it would be an error to believe, though Ricardo some- times seems to imply it, that such difference is a necessary 1 Anderson's account of the origin of rent is reprinted in the Select Collection of Scarce and Valuable Economical Tracts, edited or Lord Over-stone by J. R. M'Culloch, 1859. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 127 condition of the existence of rent. If all the land of a country were of equal fertility, still if it were appropriated, and if the price of the produce were more than an equivalent for the labour and capital applied to its production, rent would be paid. This imaginary case, however, after using it to clear \ our conceptions, we may for the future leave out of account. The price of produce being, as we have said, regulated by the cost of production of that which pays no rent, it is evident that " corn is not high, because a rent is paid, but a rent is paid because corn is high," and that " no reduction would take place in the price of corn although landlords should forego the whole of their rent." Rent is, in fact, no determining element of price; it is paid, indeed, out of the price, but the price would be the same if no rent were paid, and the whole price were retained by the cultivator. It has often been doubted whether or not Adam Smith held this theory of rent. Sometimes he uses language which seems to imply it, and states propositions which, if developed, would infallibly lead to it. Thus he says, in a passage already quoted, " Such parts only of the produce of land can commonly be brought to market of which the ordinary price is sufficient to replace the stock which must be employed in bringing them thither, together with its ordinary profits. If the ordinary price is more than this, the surplus part of it will naturally go to the rent of land. If it is not more, though th > commodity can be brought to market, it can afford no rent to the landlord. Whether the price is or is not more depends on the demand." Again, in Smith's application of these con- siderations to mines, "the whole principle of rent," Ricardo tells us, " is admirably and perspicuously explained." But he had formed the opinion that there is in fact no land which does not afford a rent to the landlord ; and, strangely, he seems not to have seen that this appearance might arise from the aggregation into an economic whole of parcels of land which can and others which cannot pay rent The truth, indeed, is, that the fact, if it were a fact, that all the land 128 POLITICAL ECONOMY. in a country pays rent would be irrelevant as an argument against the Andersonian theory, for it is the same thing in substance if there be any capital employed on land already cultivated which yields a return no more than equal to ordi- nary profits. Such last-employed capital cannot afford rent at the existing rate of profit, unless the price of produce should rise. The belief which some have entertained that Smith, notwith- standing some vague or inaccurate expressions, really held the Andersonian doctrine, can scarcely be maintained when we remember that Hume, writing to him after having read for the first time the Wealth of Nations, whilst expressing general agreement with his opinions, said (apparently with reference to Bk. I. chap, vii.), "I cannot think that the rent of farms makes any part of the price of the produce, but that the price is determined altogether by the quantity and the demand." It is further noteworthy that a statement of the theory of rent is given in the same volume, published in 1777, which contains Anderson's polemic against Smith's objections to a bounty on the exportation of corn ; this volume can hardly have escaped Smith's notice, yet neither. by its contents nor by Hume's letter was he led to modify what he had said in his first edition on the subject of rent. ; It must be remembered that not merely the unequal fertilities of different soils will determine differences of rent ; the more ' or less advantageous situation of a farm in relation to markets, and therefore to roads and railways, will have a similar effect. Comparative lowness of the cost of transit will enable the pro- duce to be brought to market at a smaller expense, and will thus increase the surplus which constitutes rent. This con- sideration is indicated by Eicardo, though he does not give it prominence, but dwells mainly on the comparative produc- tiveness of soils. Kent is defined by Ricardo as the price paid for the use of "the original and indestructible powers of the soil." He thus differentiates rent, as he uses the term, from what is popularly SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 129 designated by the word ; and, when it is to be taken in hia sense, it is often qualified as the "true" or "economic" rent. Part of what is paid to the landlord is often really profit on his expenditure in preparing the farm for cultivation by the tenant. But it is to be borne in mind that wherever such improvements are " amalgamated with the land," and " add permanently to its productive powers," the return for them follows the laws, not of profit, but of rent. Hence it becomes difficult, if not. impossible, in practice to discriminate with any degree of accuracy the amount received by the landlord "for the use of the original powers of the soil" from the amount received by him as remuneration for his improve- ments or those made by his predecessors. These have raised the farm, as an instrument for producing food, from one class of productiveness to a higher, and the case is the same as if nature had originally placed the land in question in that higher class. Smith had treated it as the peculiar privilege of agriculture, as compared with other forms of production, that in it " nature labours along with man," and therefore, whilst the workmen in manufactures occasion the reproduction merely of the capital which employs them with its owner's profits, the agricultural labourer occasions the reproduction, not only of the employer's capital with profits, but also of the rent of the landlord. This last he viewed as the free gift of nature which remained " after deducting or compensating everything which can be regarded as the work of man." Kicardo justly observes in reply that " there is not a manufacture which can be mentioned in which nature does not give her assistance to man." He then goes on to quote from Buchanan the remark that "the notion of agriculture yielding a produce and a rent in consequence, because nature concurs with industry in the process of culti- vation, is a mere fancy. It is not from the produce, but from the price at which the produce is sold, that the rent is derived ; and this price is got, not because nature assists in the pro- duction, but because it is the price which suits the consump- I 130 POLITICAL ECONOMY. tion to the supply." l There is no gain to the society at large from the rise of rent; it is advantageous to the landlords alone, and their interests are thus permanently in opposition to those of all other classes. The rise of rent may be retarded, or prevented, or even temporarily changed to a fall, by agricul- tural improvements, such as the introduction of new manures or of machines or of a better organisation of labour (though there is not so much room for this last as in other branches of production), or the opening of new sources of supply in foreign countries ; but the tendency to a rise is constant so long as the population increases. The great importance of the theory of rent in Ricardo's system arises from the fact that he makes the general eco- nomic condition of the society to depend altogether on the position in which agricultural exploitation stands. This will be seen from the following statement of his theory of wages and profits. The produce of every expenditure of labour and capital being divided between the labourer and the capitalist, in proportion as one obtains more the other will neces- sarily obtain less. The productiveness of labour being given, nothing can diminish profit but a rise of wages, or increase it but a fall of wages. "Now the price of labour, being the same as its cost of production, is determined by the price of the commodities necessary for the support of the labourer. The price of such manufactured articles as he requires has a constant tendency to fall, principally by reason of the pro- gressive application of the division of labour to their produc- tion. But the cost of his maintenance essentially depends, not on the price of those articles, but on that of his food; and, as the production of food will in the progress of society 1 Senior, however, has pointed out that Smith is partly right ; whilst it is true that rent is demanded because the productive powers of nature are limited, and increased population requires a less remunerative ex- penditure in order to obtain the necessary supply ; on the other hand, it is the power which most land possesses of producing the subsistence of more persons than are required for its cultivation that supplies the fund out of which rent can be paid. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 131 and of population require the sacrifice of more and more labour, its price will rise ; money wages will consequently rise, and with the rise of wages profits will fall. Thus it is to the necessary gradual descent to inferior soils, or less pro- ductive expenditure on the same soil, that the decrease in the rate of profit which has historically taken place is to he attributed (Smith ascribed this decrease to the competition of capitalists, though in one place, Book I. chap, ix., 1 he had a glimpse of the Eicardian view). This gravitation of profits towards a minimum is happily checked at times by improve- ments of the machinery employed in the production of neces- saries, and especially by such discoveries in agriculture and other causes as reduce the cost of the prime necessary of the labourer; but here again the tendency is constant. Whilst the capitalist thus loses, the labourer does not gain ; his increased money wages only enable him to pay the increased price of his necessaries, of which he will have no greater and probably a less share than he had before. In fact,_the labourer can never for any considerable time earn more than what is required to enable the class to subsist in such a degree of comfort as custom ha& made indispensable to them, and to perpetuate their race without either increase or dimi- nution. That is the " natural " price of labour and if the market rate temporarily rises above it population will be stimulated, and the rate of wages will again fall. Thus whilst rent has a constant tendency to rise and profit to fall, the rise or fall of wages will depend on the rate of increase of the working classes. For the improvement of their con- dition Ricardo thus has to fall back on the Malthusian remedy, of the effective application of which he does not, however, seem to have much expectation. The securities against a 1 "A* the colony increases, the profits of stock gradually diminish. When the most fertile and best situated lands have been all occupied, lesa profit can be made by the cultivation of what is inferior both in soil and situation, and less interest can be afforded for the stock which U M employed." The view in question had been anticipated by Weak I3 POLITICAL ECONOMY. superabundant population to which he points are the gradual abolition of the poor-laws for their amendment would not content him and the development amongst the working classes of a taste for greater comforts and enjoyments. It will he seen that the socialists have somewhat exagge- rated in announcing, as Ricardo's " iron law " of wages, their absolute identity with the amount necessary to sustain the existence of the labourer and enable him to continue the race. He recognises the influence of a "standard of living" as limit- ing the increase of the numbers of the working classes, and so keeping their wages above the lowest point. But he also holds that, in long-settled countries, in the ordinary course of human affairs, and in the absence of special efforts restricting the growth of population, the condition of the labourer will decline as surely, and from the same causes, as that of the landlord will be improved. If we are asked whether this doctrine of rent, and the con- sequences which Bicardo deduced from it, are true, we must answer that they are hypothetically true in the most advanced industrial communities, and there only (though they have been rashly applied to the cases of India and Ireland), but that even in those communities neither safe inference nor sound action can be built upon them. As we shall see here- after, the value of most of the theorems of the classical eco- nomics is a good deal attenuated by the habitual assumptions that we are dealing with " economic men," actuated by one principle only ; that custom, as against competition, has no existence ; that there is no such thing as combination ; that there is equality of contract between the parties to each trans- action, and that there is a definite universal rate of profit and wages in a community; this last postulate implying (i) that the capital embarked in any undertaking will pass at once to another in which larger profits are for the time to be made ; (2) that a labourer, whatever his local ties of feeling, family, habit, or other engagements, will transfer himself immediately to aay place where, or employment in which, for the time, SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 133 larger wages are to be earned than those he had previously obtained ; 1 and (3) that both capitalists and labourers have * perfect knowledge of the condition and prospects of industry throughout the country, both in their own and other occupa- tions. But in Ricardo's speculations on rent and its conse- quences there is still more of abstraction. The influence of emigration, which has assumed vast dimensions since his time, is left out of account, and the amount of land at the disposal of a community is supposed limited to its own territory, whilst contemporary Europe is in fact largely fed by the western States of America. He did not adequately appreciate the degree in which the augmented productiveness of labour, whether from increased intelligence, improved organisation, introduction of machinery, or more rapid and cheaper com- munication, steadily keeps down the cost of production. To these influences must be added those of legal reforms in tenure, and fairer conditions in contracts, which operate in the same direction. As a result of all these causes, the pres- sure anticipated by Ricardo is not felt, and the cry is of the landlords over falling rents, not of the consumer over rising prices. The entire conditions are in fact so altered that Professor Nicholson, no enemy to the " orthodox " economics, when recently conducting an inquiry into the present state of the agricultural question, 2 pronounced the so-called Ricardian theory of rent "too abstract to be of practical utility." A particular economic subject on which Ricardo has thrown a useful light is the nature of the advantages derived from foreign commerce, and the conditions under which such com- merce can go on. Whilst preceding writers had represented those benefits as consisting in affording a vent for surplus produce, or enabling a portion of the national capital to re- place itself with a profit, he pointed out that they consist 1 Adam Smith says : "It appears evidently from experience that man is, of all sorts of luggage, the most difficult to be transported " ( Wealth of Nations, Bk. I. chap. viii. ). J Tenant's Gain not Landlord's Loss (1883), p. 83. 134 POLITICAL ECONOMY. " simply and solely in this, that it enables each nation t obtain, with a given amount of labour and capital, a greater quantity of all commodities taken together." This is no doubt the point of view at which we should habitually place our- selves ; though the other forms of expression employed by his predecessors, including Adam Smith, are sometimes useful as representing real considerations affecting national production, and need not be absolutely disused. Ricardo proceeds to show that what determines the purchase of any commodity from a foreign country is not the circumstance that it can be produced there with less labour and capital than at home. If we have a greater positive advantage in the production of some other article than in that of the commodity in question, even though we have an advantage in producing the latter, it may be our interest to devote ourselves to the production of that in which we have the greatest advantage, and to im- port that in producing which we should have a less, though a real, advantage. It is, in short, not absolute cost of produc- tion, but comparative cost, which determines the interchange. This remark is just and interesting, though an undue import- ance seems to be attributed to it by J. S. Mill and Cairnes, the latter of whom magniloquently describes it as " sounding the depths " of the problem of international dealings, though, as we shall see hereafter, he modifies it by the introduction of certain considerations respecting the conditions of domestic production. For the nation as a whole, according to Kicardo, it is not _ the gross produce of the land and labour, as Smith seems to assert, that is of importance, but the net income the excess, that is, of this produce over the cost of production, or, in other words, the amount of its rent and its profits ; for the wages of labour, not essentially exceeding the maintenance of the labourers, are by him considered only as a part of the " necessary expenses of production." Hence it follows, as he himself in a characteristic and often-quoted passage says, that, " provided the net real income of the nation be the same, it SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 135 is of no importance whether it consists of ten or twelve millions of inhabitants. If five millions of men could pro- duce as much food and clothing as was necessary for ten millions, food and clothing for five millions would be the net revenue. Would it be of any advantage to the country that to produce this same net revenue seven millions of men should be required, that is to say, that seven millions should be employed to produce food and clothing sufficient for twelve millions? The food and clothing of five millions would be still the net revenue. The employing a greater number of men would enable us neither to add a man to our army and navy nor to contribute one guinea more in taxes." Industry is here viewed, just as by the mercantilists, in relation to the military and political power of the state, not to the maintenance and improvement of human beings, as its end and aim. The labourer, as Held has remarked, is regarded not as a member of society, but as a means to the ends of society, on whose sustenance a part of the gross income must be expended, as another part must be spent on the sustenance of horses. We may well ask, as Sismondi did in a personal interview with Kicardo, "What! is wealth then everything? are men abso- lutely nothing ?" On the whole what seems to us true of Ricardo is this, that, whilst he had remarkable powers, they were not the powers best fitted for sociological research. Nature intended him rather for a mathematician of the second order than for a social philosopher. Nor had he the due previous preparation for social studies ; for we must decline to accept Bagehot's idea that, though " in no high sense an educated man," he had a specially apt training for such studies in his practice as an eminently successful dealer in stocks. The same writer justly notices the " anxious penetration with which he follows out rarefied minutiae." But he wanted breadth of survey, a comprehensive view of human nature and human life, and the strong social sympathies which, as the greatest minds have recognised, are a most valuable aid in this department of study. 136 POLITICAL ECONOMY. On a subject like that of money, where a few elementary pro- positions into which no moral ingredient enters have alone to be kept in view, he was well adapted to succeed ; but in the larger social field he is at fault. He had great deductive readiness and skill (though his logical accuracy, as Mr. Sidg- wick remarks, has been a good deal exaggerated). But in human affairs phenomena are so complex, and piinciples so constantly limit or even compensate one another, that rapidity and daring in deduction may be the greatest of dangers, if they are divorced from a wide and balanced appreciation of facts. Dialectic ability is, no doubt, a valuable gift, but the first condition for success in social investigation is to see things as they are. A sort of Eicardo-mythus for some time existed in eco- nomic circles. It cannot be doubted that the exaggerated estimate of his merits arose in part from a sense of the support his system gave to the manufacturers and other capitalists in their growing antagonism to the old aristocracy of landowners. The same tendency, as well as his affinity to their too abstract and unhistorical modes of thought, and their eudaemonistic doctrines, recommended him to the Benthamite group, and to the so-called Philosophical Radicals generally. Brougham said he seemed to have dropped from the skies a singular avatar, it must be owned. His real services in connection with questions of currency and banking naturally created a prepossession in favour of his more general views. But, apart from those special subjects, it does not appear that, either in the form of solid theoretic teaching or of valuable practical guidance, he has really done much for the world, whilst he admittedly misled opinion on several important questions. De Quincey's presentation of him as a great revealer of truth is now seen to be an extravagance. J. S. Mill and others speak of his "superior lights "as compared with those of Adam Smith ; but his work, as a contribution to our knowledge of human society, will not bear a moment'* comparison with the Wealth of Nations. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 137 It is interesting to observe that Malthus, though the com- bination of his doctrine of population with the principles of Ricardo composed the creed for some time professed by all the " orthodox " economists, did not himself accept the Ricardian scheme. He prophesied that " the main part of the structure would not stand." " The theory," he says, " takes a partial view of the subject, like the system of the French economists ; and, like that system, after having drawn into its vortex a great number of very clever men, it will be unable to support itself against the testimony of obvious facts, and the weight of those theories which, though less simple and captivating, are more just, on account of their embracing more of the causes which are in actual operation in all economical results." We saw that the foundations of Smith's doctrine in general philosophy were unsound, and the ethical character of his scheme in consequence injuriously affected ; but his method, consisting in a judicious combination of induction and deduc- tion, we found (so far as the statical study of economic laws is concerned) little open to objection. Mainly through the influence of Ricardo, economic method was perverted. The science was led into the mistaken course of turning its back on observation, and seeking to evolve the laws of phenomena out of a few hasty generalisations by a play of logic. The principal vices which have been in recent times not unjustly attributed to the members of the " orthodox " school were all encouraged by his example, namely, (i) the viciously abstract character of the conceptions with which they deal, (2) the abusive preponderance of deduction in their processes of re- starch, and (3) the too absolute way in which their conclu- sions are conceived and enunciated. The works of Ricardo have been collected in one volume, with a biographical notice, by J. R. M'Culloch (I846). 1 1 A sketch of Ricardo's personal history, and an account of his writ- ings on monetary questions, which could not conveniently be introduced here, will be found under his name in the Encyclopaedia ritanniea t 9th edition. 138 POLITICAL ECONOMY. After Malthus and Ricardo, the first of whom had fixed public attention irresistibly on certain aspects of society, and the second had led economic research into new, if questionable, paths, came a number of minor writers who were mainly their expositors and commentators, and whom, accordingly, the Germans, with allusion to Greek mythical history, designate as the Epigoni. By them the doctrines of Smith and hi earliest successors were thrown into more systematic shape, limited and guarded so as to be less open to criticism, couched in a more accurate terminology, modified in subordinate par- ticulars, or applied to the solution of the practical questions of their day. James Mill's Elements (1821) deserves special notice, as exhibiting the system of Ricardo with thorough-going rigour, and with a compactness of presentation, and a skill in the disposition of materials, which give to it in some degree the character of a work of art. The a priori political economy is here reduced to its simplest expression. J. R. M'Cullouh (1779-1864), author of a number of laborious statistical and" other compilations, criticised current economic legislation in the Edinburgh Review from the point of view of the Ricardian doctrine, taking up substantially the same theoretic position as was occupied at a somewhat later period by the Manchester school. He is altogether without originality, aud never exhibits any philosophic elevation or breadth. His confident dogmatism is often repellent ; he admitted in his later years that he had been too fond of novel opinions, and defended them with more heat and pertinacity than they deserved. It is noticeable that, though often spoken of in his own time both by those who agreed with his views, and those, like Sismondi, who differed from them, as one of the lights of the reigning school, his name is now tacitly dropped in the writings of the members of that school. Whatever may have been his partial usefulness in vindicating the policy of free trade, it is at least plain that for the needs of our social future he has nothing to olfer. Nassau William Senior (1790-1864), SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 139 who was professor of political economy in the university of Oxford, published, besides a number of separate lectures, a treatise on the science, which first appeared as an article in the Encyclopaedia Metropolitana. He is a writer of a high order of merit. He made considerable contributions to the elucidation of economic principles, specially studying exact- ness in nomenclature and strict accuracy in deduction. His N explanations on cost of production and the way in which it affects price, on rent, on the difference between rate of wages / and price of labour, on the relation between profit and wages j (with special reference to Ricardo's theorem on this subject, which he corrects by the substitution of proportional for / absolute amount), and on the distribution of the precious metals between different countries, are particularly valuable./- His new term " abstinence," invented to express the conduct for which interest is the remuneration, was useful, though not quite appropriate, because negative in meaning. It is on the theory of wages that Senior is least satisfactory. j^e_ makes the average rate in a country (which, we must main- tain, is not a real quantity, though the rate in a given employ- ment and neighbourhood is) to be expressed by the fraction of which the numerator is the amount of the wages fund (an unascertainable and indeed, except as actual total of wages paid, imaginary sum) and the denominator the number of the working population ; and from this he proceeds to draw the most important and far-reaching consequences, though the equation on which he founds his inferences conveys at most only an arithmetical fact, which would be true of every case of a division amongst individuals, and contains no economic element whatever. The phrase " wages fund" originated in gome expressions of Adam Smith l used only for the purpose of illustration, and never intended to be rigorously interpreted; 1 Thus, in Wealth of Nations, Bk. I. chap, viii., we have the phrases " the funds which are destined to the payment of wages," " the f uiuii destined for employing industry " " the funds destined for the mainte- nance of servants." I 4 o POLITICAL ECONOMY. and we shall see that the doctrine has been repudiated bj several members of what is regarded as the orthodox school of political economy. As regards^jnethod, Senior makes the science a purely dedmtive one, in which there is no room for any other "facts than the four fundamental propositions from which he undertakes to deduce all economic truth. And he does not regard himself as arriving at hypothetic conclu- sions ; his postulates and his inferences are alike conceived as corresponding to actual phenomena. 1 Colonel, Robert Torrens (1780-1864) was a prolific writer, partly on economic theory, but principally on its applications to financial and commercial policy. Almost the whole of the programme which was carried out in legislation by Sir Eobert Peel had been laid down in principle in the writings of Torrens. He gave sub- stantially the same theory of foreign trade which was after- wards stated by J. S. Mill in one of his Essays on Unsettled Questions? He was an early and earnest advocate of the repeal of the corn laws, but was not in favour of a general system of absolute free trade, maintaining that it is expedient to impose retaliatory duties to countervail similar duties im- posed by foreign countries, and that a lowering of import duties on the productions of countries retaining their hostile tariffs would occasion an abstraction of the precious^jii e tals, and a decline in prices, profits, and wages. His principal writings of a general character were The Economist [i.e., Physiocrat] Refuted, 1808; Essay on the Production oj Wealth, 1821 ; Essay on the External Corn-trade (eulogised by Kicardo), 3d ed., 1826 ; The Budget, a Series of Letters on Financial, Commercial, and Colonial Policy, 1841-3. Harriot Martineau (1802-1876) popularised the doctrines of Malthas and Kicardo in her Illustrations of Political Economy (1832- * See the last of his Four Introductory Lectures on Political Economy, 1852. 2 Mill, however, tells us in his Preface to those Essays that his own views on that subject had been entertained and committed to writing before the publication by Torrent) of similar opinion*. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 141 34), a series of tales, in which there is much excellent descrip- tion, but the effect of the narrative is often marred by the somewhat ponderous disquisitions here and there thrown in, usually in the form of dialogue. Other writers who ought to be named in any history of the science are Charles Babbage, On the Economy of Machinery and Manufactures (1832), chiefly descriptive, but also in part theoretic ; William Thomas Thornton, Overpopulation and its Remedy (1846), A Plea for Peasant Proprietors (1848), On Labour (1869 ; 2d ed., 1870) ; Herman Merivale, Lectures on Colonisation and Colonies (18412; new ed., 1861); T. C. Banfield, The Organisation of Industry Explained (1844; 2d ed., 1848); and Edward Gibbon Wakefield, A View of the Art of Colonisation (1849). Thomas Chalmers, well known in -4- other fields of thought, was author of The Christian and Civic Economy of Large Towns (182136), and On Political Eco- nomy in Connection with the Moral State and Moral Prospects of Society (1832); he strongly opposed any system of legai charity, and, whilst justly insisting on the primary importance of morality, industry, and thrift as conditions of popular well- being, carried the Malthusian doctrines to excess. Nor was Ireland without a share in the economic movement of the period. 1 Whately, having been second Drummond professor -4 of political economy at Oxford (in succession to Senior), and delivered in that capacity his Introductory Lectures (1831), founded in 1832, when he went to Ireland as archbishop of Dublin, a similar professorship in Trinity College, Dublin. It was first held by Mountifort Longfield, afterwards Judge of the Landed Estates Court, Ireland (d. 1884). He published 1 Samuel Crumpe, M.D., had published at Dublin in 1793 an Essay on the Best Means of Providiny Employment for the People, which obtained a prize offered by the Royal Irish Academy for the best dissertation on that subject. Thia is a meritorious work, and contains a good state- ment of some of the leading principles of Adam Smith. John Hely Hutchinson's Commercial Restraints of Ireland (i779) i 8 important foi the economic history of that country. 142 POLITICAL ECONOMY. lectures on the science generally (1834), on Poor Laws (1834), . and on Commerce and Absenteeism (1835), which were marked by independence of thought and sagacious observation. He was laudably free from many of the exaggerations of his con- temporaries; he said, in 1835, "in political economy we must not abstract too much," and protested against the assumption commonly made that " men are guided in all their conduct by a prudent regard to their own interest." James A. Lawson (afterwards Mr. Justice Lawson, d. 1887) also published some lectures (1844), delivered from the same chair, which may still be read with interest and profit; his discussion of the question of population is especially good ; he also asserted against Senior that the science is avide de faits, and that it must reason about the world and mankind as they really are. The most systematic and thorough-going of the earlier critics of the Ricardian system was Richard Jones (1790-1855), pro- fessor at Haileybury. Jones has received scant justice at the hands of his successors. J. S. Mill, whilst using his work, gave his merits but faint recognition. Even Roscher says that he did not thoroughly understand Ricardo, without giving any proof of that assertion, whilst he is silent as to the fact that much of what has been preached by the German his- torical school is found distinctly indicated in Jones's writings. He has been sometimes represented as having rejected the Andersonian doctrine of rent ; but such a statement is in- correct. Attributing the doctrine to Malthus, he says that \ that economist "showed satisfactorily that when land is culti- \ vated by capitalists living on the profits of their stock, and S able to move it at pleasure to other employments, the expense ~Y\ of tilling the worst quality of land cultivated determines the j average price of raw produce, while the difference of quality ( of the superior lands measures the rents yielded by them." What he really denied was the application of the doctrine to all cases where rent is paid ; he pointed out in his Essay on the Distribution of Wealth and on the Sources of Taxation, 1831, that, besides " farmers' rents," which, under the supposed SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. '43 conditions, conform to the above law, there aie " peasant rents," paid everywhere through the most extended periods of history, and still paid over by far the largest part of the earth's surface, which are not so regulated. Peasant rents he divided under the heads of (i) serf^(2) metayer, (3) ryot, and (4) cottier rents, a classification afterwards adopted in sub- stance by J. S. Mill ; and he showed that the contracts fixing their amount were, at least in the first three classes, deter- mined rather by custom than by competition. Passing to the superstructure of theory erected by Ricardo on the doctrine of rent which he had so unduly extended, Jones denied most of the conclusions he had deduced, especially the following : that the increase of farmers' rents is always contemporary i\ with a decrease in the productive powers of agriculture, and 2- } comes with loss and distress in its train ; that the jnterestsof 3 / landlords are always and necessarily opposed to the interests / of the state and of every other class of society; that the diminu- V tion of the_ate^ of profits is exclusively dependent on the / returns to the capital last employed on the land; and that 1 wages can, jie_only atthejsxpense of profits. J The method followed by Jones is inductive; his conclu- sions are founded on a wide observation of contemporary facts, aided by the study of history. " If," he said, " we wish to make ourselves acquainted with the economy and arrange- ments by which the different nations of the earth produce and distribute their revenues, I really know but of one way to attain our object, and that is, to look and see. We must get comprehensive views of facts, that we may arrive at principles that are truly comprehensive. If we take a different method, if we snatch at general principles, and content ourselves with confined observations, two things will happen to us. First, what we call general principles will often be found to have no generality we shall set out with declaring propositions to be universally true which, at every step of our further progress, we shall be obliged to confess are frequently false ; and, secondly, we shall miss a great mass of useful knowledge which 144 POLITICAL ECONOMY. those who advance to principles by a comprehensive examina tion of facts necessarily meet with on their road." The world he professed to study was not an imaginary world, inhabited by abstract "economic men," but the real world with the different forms which the ownership and cultivation of land, and, in general, the conditions of production and distribution, assume at different times and places. His recognition of such different systems of life in communities occupying different stages in the progress of civilisation led to his proposal of what he called a " political economy of nations." This was a protest against the practice of taking the exceptional state of facts which exists, and is indeed only partially realised, in a small corner of our planet as representing the uniform type of human societies, and ignoring the effects of the early history and special development of each community as influencing its economic phenomena. It is sometimes attempted to elude the necessity for a wider range of study by alleging a universal tendency in the social world to assume this now exceptional shape as its normal and ultimate constitution. Even if this tendency were real (which is only partially true, for the existing order amongst ourselves cannot be regarded as entirely definitive), it could not be admitted that the facts witnessed in out civilisation and those exhibited in less advanced communities are so approximate as to be capable of being represented by the same formulae. As Whewell, in editing Jones's Remains, 1859, well observed, it is true in the physical world that "all things tend to assume a form determined by the force of gravity ; the hills tend to become plains, the waterfalls to eat away their beds and disappear, the rivers to form lakes in the valleys, the glaciers to pour down in cataracts." But are we to treat these results as achieved, because forces are in operation which may ultimately bring them about ? All human questions are largely questions of time ; and the economic phenomena which really belong to the several stages of the human movement must be studied as they are, unless we are con- SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 145 tent to fall into grievous error both in our theoretic treatment of them and in the solution of the practical problems they present. Jones is remarkable for his freedom from exaggeration and one-sided statement ; thus, whilst holding Malthus in, perhaps, undue esteem, he declines to accept the proposition that atf) increase of the means of subsistence is necessarily followed byA an increase of population; and he maintains what is undoubtedly*] true, that with the growth of population, in all well-governed and prosperous states, the command over food, instead of diminishing, increases. Much of what he has left us a large part of which is un- fortunately fragmentary is akin to the labours of Cliffe Leslie at a later period. The latter, however, had the advantage of acquaintance with the sociology of Comte, which gave him a firmer grasp of method, as well as a wider view of the general movement of society ; and, whilst the voice of Jones was but little heard amidst the general applause accorded to Ricardo in the economic world of his time, Leslie wrote when disillusion had set in, and the current was beginning to turn in England against the a priori economics. Comte somewhere speaks of the "transient predilection" for political economy which had shown itself generally in western Europe. This phase of feeling was specially notice- able in England from the third to the fifth decade of the present century. "Up to the year 1818," said a writer in the Westminster Review, " the science was scarcely known or talked of beyond a small circle of philosophers ; and legislation, so far from being in conformity with its principles, was daily receding from them more and more." Mill has told us what a change took place within a few years. " Political economy," ho says, " had asserted itself with great vigour in public affairs by the petition of the merchants of London for free trade, drawn up in 1820 by Mr. Tooke and presented by Mr. Alexander Baring, 1 and by the noble exertions of Ricardo 1 Afterwards Lord Ashburton. For this Petition, see M'Cullocb'f I 146 POLITICAL ECONOMY. during the few years of his parliamentary life. Ilia writing^ following up the impulse given by the bullion controversy, and followed up in their turn by the expositions and com- ments of my father and M'Culloch (whose writings in the Edinburgh Review during those years were most valuable), had drawn general attention to the subject, making at least partial converts in the Cabinet itself ; and Huskisson, supported by Canning, had commenced that gradual demolition of the protective system which, one of their colleagues virtually completed in 1846, though the last vestiges were only swept away by Mr. Gladstone in 1860." Whilst the science was thus attracting and fixing the attention of active minds, its unsettled condition was freely admitted. The differences of opinion among its professors were a frequent subject of complaint. But it was confidently expected that these discre- pancies would soon disappear, and Colonel Torrens predicted that in twenty years there would scarcely " exist a doubt respecting any of its more fundamental principles." " The prosperity," says Mr. Sidgwick, " that followed on the aboli- tion of the corn laws gave practical men a most impressive and satisfying proof of the soundness of the abstract reasoning by which the expediency of free trade had been inferred," and when, in 1848, "a masterly expositor of thought had published a skilful statement of the chief results of the controversies of the preceding generation," with the due " explanations and qualifications " of the reigning opinions, it was for some years generally believed that political economy had " emerged from the state of polemical discussion," at least on its leading doc- trines, and that at length a sound construction had been erected on permanent bases. This expositor was John Stuart Mill (1806-73). He exercised, without doubt, a greater influence in the field of English economics than any other writer since Ricardo. His systematic treatise has been, either directly or through Literature of Political Economy, p. 57, or Senior's Lectures on the Tra*t~ mission of the Previous Metals, &c., 2d ed. , p. 78. x SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 147 manuals founded on it, especially that of Fawcett, the source from which most of our contemporaries in these countries have derived their knowledge of the science. But there are other and deeper reasons, as we shall see, which make him, in this as in other departments of knowledge, a specially interest- ing and significant figure. In 1844 he published five Essays on some Unsettled Ques- tions of Political Economy, which had been written as early as 1829 and 1830, but had, with the exception of the fifth, remained in manuscript. In these essays is contained any dogmatic contribution which he can be regarded as having made to the science. The subject of the first is the laws of interchange between nations. He shows that, when two countries trade together in two commodities, the prices of the commodities exchanged on both sides (which, as Kicardo had proved, are not determined by cost of production) will adjust themselves, through the play of reciprocal demand, in such a way that the quantities required by each country of the article which it imports from its neighbour shall be exactly sufficient tc. payfor one another. This is the law which appears, with some adcIeTTdevelopments, in his systematic treatise under the name of the "equation of international demand." He then discusses the division of the gains. The most important practical conclusion (not, however, by any means an undis- puted one) at which he arrives in this essay is, that the relaxation of duties on foreign commodities, not operating as protection but maintained solely for revenue, should be made contingent on the adoption of some corresponding degree of freedom of trade with England by thenation from which the commodities are imported. In the second essay, on the in- fluence of consumption on production, the most interesting results arrived at are the propositions (i) that absenteeism is a local, not a national, evil, and (2) that, whilst there cannot be permanent excess of production, there may be a temporary excess, not only of any one article, but of com- modities generally, this last, however, not arising from over- 148 POLITICAL ECONOMY. production, but from a want of commercial confidence. Th third essay relates to the use of the words " productive " and " unproductive " as applied to labour, to consumption, and to expenditure. The fourth deals with profits and interest, especially explaining and so justifying Kicardo's theorem that " profits depend on wages, rising as wages fall and falling as wages rise." What Eicardo meant was that profits .lepend on the cost of wages estimated in labour. Hence improve- ments in the production of articles habitually consumed by the labourer may increase profits without diminishing the real remuneration of the labourer. The last essay is on the de- finition and method of political economy, a subject later and more maturely treated in the author's System of Logic. In 1 848 Mill published his Principles of Political Economy, with some of their Applications to Social Philosophy. This title, though, as we shall see, open to criticism, indicated on the part of the author a less narrow and formal conception of the field of the science than had been common amongst his predecessors. He aimed, in fact, at producing a work which might replace in ordinary use the Wealth of Nations, which in his opinion was " in many parts obsolete and in all im- perfect." Adam Smith had invariably associated the general principles of the subject with their applications, and in treat- ing those applications had perpetually appealed to other and often far larger considerations than pure political economy affords. And in the same spirit Mill desired, whilst incor- porating all the results arrived at in the special science by Smith's successors, to exhibit purely economic phenomena in relation to the most advanced conceptions of his own time on the general philosophy of society, as Smith had done in reference to the philosophy of the eighteenth century. 1 1 Curiously, in an otherwise well-executed Abridgment of Mill's work, published in the United States (1886) by J. Laurence Laughlin, as a text-book for colleges, all that " should properly be classed under the head of Sociology " has been omitted, Mill's own conception being thus set wide, and his book made to conform to the common type. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 149 This design he certainly failed to realise. His book is fai indeed from being a " modern Adam Smith." It is an admirably lucid and even elegant exposition of the Ricardian economics, the Malthusian theory being of course incorporated with these, but, notwithstanding the introduction of many minor novelties, it is, in its scientific substance, little or nothing more. When Cliffe Leslie says that Mill so qualified and amended the doctrines of Ricardo that the latter could scarcely have recognised them, he certainly goes a great deal too far : Senior really did more in that direction. Mill's effort is usually to vindicate his master where others have censured him, and to palliate his admitted laxities of expres- sion. Already his profound esteem for Ricardo's services to economics had been manifest in his Essays, where he says of him, with some injustice to Smith, that, " having a science to create," he could not " occupy himself with more than the leading principles," and adds that " no one who has thoroughly entered into his discoveries " will find any difficulty in work- ing out " even the minutiae of the science." James Mill, too, had been essentially an expounder of Ricardo ; and the son, whilst greatly superior to his father in the attractiveness of his expository style, is, in regard to his economic doctrine, substantially at the same point of view. It is in their general philosophical conceptions and their views of social aims and ideals that the elder and younger Mill occupy quite different positions in the line of progress. The latter could not, for example, in his adult period have put forward as a theory of government the shallow sophistries which the plain good sense of Macaulay sufficed to expose in the writings of the former ; and he had a nobleness of feeling which, in relation to the higher social questions, raised him far above the ordinary coarse utilitarianism of the Benthamites. The larger and more philosophic spirit in which Mill dealt with social subjects was undoubtedly in great measure due to the influence of Comte, to whom, as Mr. Bain justly says, he was under greater obligations than he himself was disposed 150 POLITICAL ECONOMY. to admit. Had he more completely undergone that influence, we are sometimes tempted to think he might have wrought the reform in economics which still remains to he achieved, emancipating the science from the a priori system, and founding a genuine theory of industrial life on observation in the broadest sense. But probably the time was not ripe for such a construction, and it is possible that Mill's native intellectual defects might have made him unfit for the task, for, as Koscher has said, " ein historischer Kopf war er nicht. ' However this might have been, the effects of his early train- ing, in which positive were largely alloyed with metaphysical elements, sufficed in fact to prevent his attaining a perfectly normal mental attitude. He never altogether overcame the vicious direction which he had received from the teaching of his father, and the influence of the Benthamite group in which he was brought up. Hence it was that, according to the striking expression of Eoscher, his whole view of life was " zu wenig aus Einem Gusse." The incongruous mixture of the narrow dogmas of his youthful period with the larger ideas of a later stage gave a wavering and indeterminate character to his entire philosophy. He is, on every side, eminently " un-final ; " he represents tendencies to new forms of opinion, and opens new vistas in various directions, but founds scarcely anything, and remains indeed, so far as his own position is concerned, not merely incomplete but inco- herent. 1 It is, however, precisely this dubious position which seems to us to give a special interest to his career, by fitting him in a peculiar degree to prepare and facilitate transitions. What he himself thought to be " the chief merit of his treatise " was the marked distinction drawn between the theory of production and that of distribution, the laws of 1 Mr. John Morley (" Mill on Religion," in Critical Miscellanies, 2d ser., 1877) betrays something like consternation at finding in Mill's posthumous writings statements of opinion distinctly at variance with philosophic doctrines be had energetically maintained during his whole life. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 151 the former being based on unalterable natural facts, whilst the course of distribution is modified from time to time by the changing ordinances of society. This distinction, we may remark, must not be too absolutely stated, for the organisation of production changes with social growth, and, as Lauderdale long ago showed, the nature of the distribution in a community reacts on production. But there is a sub- stantial truth in the distinction, and the recognition of it tends to concentrate attention on the question How can, we im- prove the existing distribution of wealth ? The study of this problem led Mill, as he advanced in years, further and further in the direction of socialism ; and, whilst to the end of his life his book, however otherwise altered, continued to deduce the Eicardian doctrines from the principle of enlightened selfishness, he was looking forward to an order of things in which synergy should be founded on sympathy. The gradual modification of. his views in relation to the economic constitution of society is set forth in his Auto- biography. In his earlier days, he tells us, he "had seen little further than the old school " (note this significant title) "of political economy into the possibilities of funda- mental improvement in social arrangements. Private pro- perty, as now understood, and inheritance appeared the dernier mot of legislation." The notion of proceeding to any radical redress of the injustice "involved in the fact that some are born to riches and the vast majority to poverty " he had then reckoned chimerical But now his views were such as would " class him decidedly under the general designa- tion of socialist ; " he had been led to believe that the whole contemporary framework of economic life was merely tem- porary and provisional, and that a time would come when " the division of the produce of labour, instead of depending, as in so great a degree it now does, on the accident of birth, would be made by concert on an acknowledged principle of justice." "The social problem of the future" he considered to be " how to unite the greatest individual liberty of action," 152 POLITICAL ECONOMY. \vhich was often compromised in socialistic schemes, "with a common ownership in the raw material of the globe, and an equal participation in all the benefits of combined labour." These ideas, he says, were scarcely indicated in the first edition of the Political Economy, rather more clearly and fully in the second, and quite unequivocally in the third, the French Revolution of 1848 having made the public more open to the reception of novelties in opinion. Whilst thus looking forward to a new economic order, he yet thinks its advent very remote, arid believes that the inducements of private interest will in the meantime be in- dispensable. 1 On the spiritual side he maintains a similar attitude of expectancy. He anticipates the ultimate disap- pearance of theism, and the substitution of a purely human religion, but believes that the existing doctrine will long be necessary as a stimulus and a control. He thus saps existing foundations without providing anything to take their place, and maintains the necessity of conserving for indefinite periods what he has radically discredited. Nay, even whilst sowing the seeds of change in the direction of a socialistic organisation of society, he favours present or proximate arrangements which would urge the industrial world towards other issues. The system of peasant proprietorship of land is distinctly indi- vidualistic in its whole tendency ; yet he extravagantly praises it in the earlier part of his book, only receding from that laudation when he comes to the chapter on the future of the labouring classes. And the system of so-called co-operation in production which he so warmly commended in the later edi- tions of his work, and led some of his followers to preach as the one thing needful, would inevitably strengthen the principle of personal property, and, whilst professing at most to sub- stitute the competition of associations for that of individuals, would by no means exclude the latter. The elevation of the working classes he bound up too 1 8e also his Chapters on Socialism, in Fortnightly Review, 1879. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 153 exclusively with the Malthusian ethics, on which lie laid quite an extravagant stress, though, as Mr. Bain has observed, it is not easy to make out his exact views, any more than his father's, on this subject. We have no reason to think that he ever changed his opinion as to the necessity of a restriction on ' population ; yet that element seems foreign to the socialistic idea to which he increasingly leaned. It is at least difficult to see how, apart from individual responsibility for the sup- port of a family, what Malthus called moral restraint could be adequately enforced. This difficulty is indeed the fatal flaw which, in Malthus's own opinion, vitiated the scheme of Godwin. Mill's openness to new ideas and his enthusiasm for im- provement cannot be too much admired. But there appears to have been combined with these fine traits in his mental constitution a certain want of practical sense, a failure to recognise and acquiesce in the necessary conditions of human life, and a craving for "better bread than can be made of wheat." He entertained strangely exaggerated, or rather per- verted, notions of the "subjection," the capacities, and the rights of women. He encourages a spirit of revolt on the part of working men against their perpetual condemnation, as a class, to the lot of living by wages, without giving satisfactory proof that this state of things is capable of change, and with- out showing that such a lot, duly regulated by law and morality, is inconsistent with their real happiness. He also insists on the " independence " of the working class which, according to him, fard, da se in such a way as to obscure, if not to controvert, the truths that superior rank and wealth are naturally invested with social power, and are bound in duty to exercise it for the benefit of the community at large, and especially of its less favoured members. And he attaches a quite undue importance to mechanical and, indeed, illusory expedients, such as the limitation of the power of bequest and the confiscation of the " unearned increment " of rent. With respeci to economic method also, he shifted his poo- 154 POLITICAL ECONOMY. tion ; yet to the end occupied uncertain ground. In the fifth of his early essays he asserted that the method a priori is the only mode of investigation in the social sciences, and that the method a posteriori " is altogether inefficacious in those sciences, as a means of arriving at any considerable body of valuable truth," When he wrote his Logic, he had learned from Comte that the a posteriori method in the form which he chose to call "inverse deduction" was the only mode of arriving at truth in general sociology ; and his admission of this at once renders the essay obsolete. But, unwilling to relinquish the a priori method of his youth, he tries to estab- lish a distinction of two sorts of economic inquiry, one of which, though not the other, can be handled by that method. Sometimes he speaks of political economy as a department " carved out of the general body of the science of society ; " whilst on the other hand the title of his systematic work im- plies a doubt whether political economy is a part of " social philosophy'' at all, and not rather a study preparatory and auxiliary to it. Thus, on the Idgical as well as the dogmatic side, he halts between two opinions. Notwithstanding his misgivings and even disclaimers, he yet remained, as to method, a member of the old school, and never passed into the new or " historical " school, to which the future belongs. The question of economic method was also taken up by the ablest of his disciples, John Elliott Cairnes (1824-75) who devoted a volume to the subject (Logical Method of Political Economy, 1857 ; ad ed., 1875). Professor Walker has spoken of the method advocated by Cairnes as being different from that put forward by Mill, and has even represented the former as similar to, if not identical with, that of the German his- torical school. But this is certainly an error. Cairnes, not- withstanding some apparent vacillation of view and certain concessions more formal than real, maintains the utmost rigour of the deductive method ; he distinctly affirms that in political economy there is no room for induction at all, " the economist starting with a knowledge of ultimate causes," and being thus, SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 155 "at the outset of his enterprise, at the position which the physicist only attains after ages of laborious research." He does not, indeed, seem to be advanced beyond the point of view of Senior, who professed to deduce all economic truth from four elementary propositions. Whilst Mill in his Logic represents verification as an essential part of the process of demonstration of economic laws, Cairnes holds that, as they " are not assertions respecting the character or sequence of phenomena " (though what else can a scientific law be ?), " they can neither be established nor refuted by statistical or docu- mentary evidence." A proposition which affirms nothing re- specting phenomena cannot be controlled by being confronted with phenomena. Notwithstanding the unquestionable ability of his book, it appears to mark, in some respects, a retro- gression in methodology, and can for the future possess only an historical interest. Kegarded in that light, the labours of Mill and Cairnes on the method of the science, though intrinsically unsound, had an important negative effect. They let down the old political economy from its traditional position, and reduced its extra- vagant pretensions by two modifications of commonly accepted views. First, whilst Eicardo had never doubted that in all his reasonings he was dealing with human beings as they ' actually exist, they showed that the science must be regarded as a purely hypothetic one. Its deductions are based on unreal, or at least one-sided, assumptions, the most essential of which is that of the existence of the so-called " economicjtnan," a being who is influenced by two motives only, that of ac- quiring wealth and that of avoiding exertion ; and only so far as the premises framed on this conception correspond with fact ean the conclusions be depended on in practice. Senior in vain protested against such a view of the science, which, as he saw, compromised its social efficacy ; whilst Torrens, who had previously combated the doctrines of Ricardo, hailed Mill's new presentation of political economy as enabling him, whilst in one sense rejecting those doctrines, in another sense to 156 POLITICAL ECONOMY. accept them. Secondly, beside economic science, it had often been said, stands an economic art, the former ascertaining truths respecting the laws of economic phenomena, the latter prescribing the right kind of economic action ; and many had assumed that, the former being given, the latter is also in our possession that, in fact, we have only to convert theorems into precepts, and the work is done. But Mill and Cairnes made it plain that this statement could not be accepted, that action can no more in the economic world than in any other province of life be regulated by considerations borrowed from one department of things only ; that economics can suggest ideas which are to be kept in view, but that, standing alone, it cannot direct conduct an office for which a wider prospect of human affairs is required. This matter is best elucidated by a reference to Comte's classification, or rather hierarchical arrangement, of the sciences. Beginning with the least com- plex, mathematics, we rise successively to astronomy, physics, chemistry, thence to biology, and from it again to sociology. In the course of this ascent we come upon all the great laws which regulate the phenomena of the inorganic world, of organised beings, and of society. A further step, however, remains to be taken namely, to morals ; and at this point the provinces of theory and practice tend to coincide, because every element of conduct has to be considered in relation to the general good. In the final synthesis all the previous analyses have to be used as instrumental, in order to determine how every real quality of things or men may be made to converge to the welfare of Humanity. Cairnes's most important economic publication was his last, entitled Some Leading Principles of Political Economy newly Expounded, 1874. In this work, which does not profess to be a complete treatise on the science, he criticises and emends the statements which preceding writers had given of some of its principal doctrines, and treats elaborately of the limitations with which they are to be understood, and the exceptions to them which may be produced by special circumstances. Whilst SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 157 marked by great ability, it affords evidence of what has been justly observed as a weakness in Cairnes's mental constitution his " deficiency in intellectual sympathy," and consequent frequent inability to see more than one side of a truth. The three divisions of the book relate respectively to (i) value, (2) labour and capital, and (3) international trade. In the first he begins by elucidating the meaning of the word " value/' and under this head controverts the view of Jevons that the exchange value of anything depends entirely on its utility, without, perhaps, distinctly apprehending what Jevons meant by this proposition. On supply and demand he shows, as Say had done before, that these, regarded as aggregates, are not independent, but strictly connected and mutually depen- dent phenomena identical, indeed, under a system of barter, but, under a money system, conceivable as distinct. Supply and demand with respect to particular commodities must be understood to mean supply and demand at a given price ; and thus we are introduced to the ideas of market price and normal price (as, following Cherbuliez, he terms what Smith less happily called natural price). Normal price again leads to the consideration of cost of production, and here, against Mill and others, he denies that profit and wages enter into cost of pro- duction ; in other words, he asserts what Senior (whom he does not name) had said before him, though he had not con- sistently carried out the nomenclature, that cost of production is the sum of labour and abstinence necessary to production, wages and profits being the remuneration of sacrifice and not elements of it. But, it may well be asked, How can an amount of labour be added to an amount of abstinence ? Must not wages and profits be taken as " measures of cost " ? By adhering to the conception of " sacrifice," he exposes the emptiness of the assertion that " dear labour is the great obstacle to the extension of British trade " a sentence in which " British trade " means capitalists' profits. At this point we are introduced to a doctrine now first elaborated, though there are indications of it in Mill, of whose theory of 158 POLITICAL ECONOMY. international values it is* in fact an extension. In foreign trade cost of production, in Cairnes's sense, does not regu late values, because it cannot perform that function except under a re'gime of effective competition, and between different countries effective competition does not exist. But, Cairnes asks, to what extent does it exist in domestic industries? So far as capital is concerned, he thinks the condition is sufficiently fulfilled over the whole field a position, let it be said in passing, which he does not seem to make out, if we consider the practical immobility of most invested, as distinct from disposable, capital. But in the case of labour the requisite competition takes place only within certain social, or rather industrial, strata. The world of industry may be divided into a series of superposed groups, and these groups arc practically " non-competing," the disposable labour in an}' one of them being rarely capable of choosing its field in a higher. 1 The law that cost of production determines price cannot, therefore, be absolutely stated respecting domestic any more than respect- ing international exchange ; as it fails for the latter univer- sally, so it fails for the former as between non-competing groups. The law that holds between these is similar to that governing international values, which may be called the equa- tion of reciprocal demand. Such a state of relative prices will establish itself amongst the products of these groups as shall enable that portion of the products of each group which is applied to the purchase of the products of all other groups to discharge its liabilities towards those other groups. The reciprocal demand of the groups determines the " average relative level" of prices within each group; whilst cost of 1 Economists are fond of comparing the rate of profit or wages in cne nation (using this word in its economic sense) to a single fluid surface which is continually disturbed by transient influences and continually tending to recover its level. We must compare these rates in different nations to reservoirs which, not communicating with each other, stand always at different, though variable, levels. And the latter comparison will apply also to the rates (at least of wages) in different economic "groups," or strata, within the same community. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 159 production regulates the distribution of price among the individual products of each group. This theorem is perhaps of no great practical value ; but the tendency of the whole investigation is to attenuate the importance of cost of pro- duction as a regulator of normal price, and so to show that ye 4 - ^aother of the accepted doctrines of the science had been propounded in too rigid and absolute a form. As to market price, the formula by which Mill had defined it as the price which equalises demand and supply Cairnes shows to be an identical proposition, and he defines it as the price which most advantageously adjusts the existing supply to the exist- ing demand pending the coming forward of fresh supplies from the sources of production. His second part is chiefly remarkable for his defence of what is known as the wages fund doctrine, to which we adverted when speaking of Senior. Mill had given up this doctrine, having been convinced by Thornton that it was erroneous ; but Cairnes refused to follow his leader, who, as he believes, ought not to have been convinced. 1 After having given what is certainly a fallacious reply to Longe's criticism of the expression "average rate of wages," he proceeds to vindicate the doctrine in question by the consideration that, the amount of a nation's wealth devoted at any time to the payment of wages if the character of the national industries and the methods of production employed remain the same is in a definite relation to the amount of its general capital ; the latter being given, the former is also given. In illus- {fating his view of the subject, he insists on the principle (true in the main, but too absolutely formulated by Mill) that *' demand for commodities is not demand for labour." It is not necessary here to follow his investigation, for his reason- ing has not satisfied his successors, with the exception of 1 Jevons strangely says, in the Preface to his Theory of Political Economy, 2d ed., that the wage fund doctrine "has been abandoned by most English economists owing to the attacks," amongst others, "of Cairnes." Cairnes was, in truth, a supporter of iho doctrine. I6o POLITICAL ECONOMY. Fawcett, and the question of wages is now commonly treated without reference to a supposed determinate wages fund. Cairnes next studies trades-unionism in relation to wages, and arrives in substance at the conclusion that the only way in which it can affect their rate is by accelerating an advance which must ultimately have taken place independently of its action. He also takes occasion to refute Mr. (now Lord) Brassey'a supposed law of a uniform cost of labour in every part of the world. Turning to consider the material prospects of the working classes, he examines the question of the changes which may be expected in the amount and- partition of the fund out of which abstinence and labour are remunerated. He here enunciates the principle (which had been, however, stated before him by Bicardo and Senior) that the increased productiveness of industry will not affect either profit or wages unless it cheapen the commodities which the labourer con- sumes. These latter being mostly commodities of which raw produce is the only or principal element, their cost of produc- tion, notwithstanding improvements in knowledge and art, will increase unless the numbers of the labouring class be steadily kept in check ; and hence the possibility of elevating the condition of the labourer is confined within very narrow limits, if he continues to be a labourer only. The condition of any substantial and permanent improvement in his lot is that he should cease to be a mere labourer that profits should be brought to reinforce the wages fund, which has a tendency, in the course of industrial progress, to decline relatively to the general capital of a country. And hence Cairnes abandon- ing the purely theoretic attitude which he elsewhere represents as the only proper one for the economist recommends the system of so-called co-operation (that is, in fact, the abolition of the large capitalist) as offering to the working classes "the sole means of escape from a harsh and hopeless destiny," and puta aside rather contemptuously the opposition of the Positivists to this solution, which yet many besides the Positivists, as, for example, Leslie and F. A. "Walker, regard as chimerical. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 161 The third part is devoted mainly to an exposition of Ricardo's doctrine of the conditions of international trade and Mill's theory of international values. The former Cairnes modifies by introducing his idea of the partial influence of reciprocal demand, as distinguished from cost of production, on the regu- lation of domestic prices, and founds on this rectification an interesting account of the connection between the wages pre- vailing in a country and the character and course of its ex- ternal trade. He emends Mill's statement, which represented the produce of a country as exchanging for that of other coun- tries at such values " as are required in order that the whole of her exports may exactly pay for the whole of her imports " by substituting for the latter phrase the condition that each country should by means of her exports discharge all her foreign liabilities in other words, by introducing the consi- deration of the balance of debts. This idea was not new ; it had been indicated by John Leslie Foster as early as 1804,* and was touched on by Mill himself ; but Cairnes expounds it well ; and it is important as clearing away common misconcep- tions, and sometimes removing groundless alarms. 2 Passing to the question of free trade, he disposes of some often-repeated protectionist arguments, and in particular refutes the American allegation of the inability of the highly-paid labour of that country to compete with the "pauper labour" of Europe. He is not so successful in meeting the "political argument," founded on the admitted importance for civilisation of develop- ing diversified national industries ; and he meets only by one of the highly questionable commonplaces of the doctrinaire economists Mill's proposition that protection may foster nascent industries really adapted to a country till they have struck foot and are able to endure the stress of foreign competition. We have dwelt at some length on this work of Cairnes, aot only because it presents the latest forms of several accepted 1 In his Essay on the Principle of Commercial Exchanges. 1 On this whole subject see Professor C. F. Bastable'a Theory of Inter- national Trade, 1887. L 162 POLITICAL ECONOMY. economic doctrines, but also because it is, and, we believe, will remain, the last important product of the old English school. The author at the outset expresses the hope that it will strengthen, and add consistence to, the scientific fabric " built up by the labours of Adam Smith, Malthus, Ricardo, and Mill." Whilst recognising with him the great merits of Smith, and the real abilities and services of his three successors here named, we cannot entertain the same opinion as Cairnes respecting the permanence of the fabric they con- structed. We hold that a new edifice is required, incorporating indeed many of the materials of the old, but planned on dif- ferent ideas and in some respects with a view to different ends above all, resting on different philosophic foundations, and having relation in its whole design to the more comprehensive structure of which it will form but one department, namely, the general science of society. We shall hereafter have occasion to refer to Cairnes's Essays in Political Economy, 1873. His Slave Power (1862) was the most valuable work which appeared on the subject of the great American conflict FRANCE. All the later European schools presuppose in part adopting, in part criticising the work of the English economists from Smith a to Ricardo and the Epigoni. The German school has had in a greater degree than any other a movement of its own 1 The first French translation of the Wealth of Nations, by Blavet, appeared in the Journal de V Agriculture, du Commerce, des Finances, et des Arts, 177980 ; new editions of it were published in 1781, 1788, and 1800 ; it was also printed at Amsterdam in 1784. Smith himself recom- mended it in his third edition of the original as excellent. In 1790 appeared the translation by Roucher, to which Condorcet had intended to add notes, and in 1802 that by Count Germain Gamier, executed during his exile in England, which is now considered the standard ver- siou, and has been reproduced, with notes by Say, Sismondi, Blanqui, &c. ( in the Collection des Principaux jZconomistet. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 163 following, at least in its more recent period, an original method, and tending to special and characteristic conclusions. The French school, on the other hand, if we omit the socialists, who do not here come under consideration, has in the main reproduced the doctrines of the leading English thinkers, stopping short, however, in general of the extremes of Ricardo and his disciples. In the field of exposition the French are unrivalled ; and in political economy they have produced a series of more or less remarkable systematic trea- tises, text books, and compendiums, at the head of which stands the celebrated work of J. B. Say. But the number of seminal minds which have appeared in French economic literature of writers who have contributed important truths, introduced improvements of method, or presented the phe- nomena under new lights has not been large. Sismondi, Dunoyer, and Bastiat will deserve our attention, as being the most important of those who occupy independent positions (whether permanently tenable or not), if we pass over for the present the great philosophical renovation of Auguste Comte, which comprehended actually or potentially all the branches of sociological inquiry. Before estimating the labours of Bastiat,- we shall find it desirable to examine the views of Carey, the most renowned of American economists, with which the latest teachings of the ingenious and eloquent Frenchman are, up to a certain point, in remarkable agreement. Cournot, too, must find a place among the French writers of this period, as the chief representative of the conception of a mathematical method in political economy. Of Jean Baptiste Say (1767-1832) Eicardo says "He was the first, or among the first, of Continental writers who justly appreciated and applied the principles of Smith, and has done more than all other Continental writers taken together to recommend that enlightened and beneficial system to the nations of Europe." The Wealth of Nations in the original language was placed in Say's hands by Claviere, afterwards minister, then director of the assurance society of which 164 POLITICAL ECONOMY. Say was a clerk ; and the book made a powerful impression on him. Long afterwards, when Dupont de Nemours com- plained of his injustice to the physiocrats, and claimed him as, through Smith, a spiritual grandson of Quesnay and nephew of Turgot, he replied that he had learned to read in the writings of the mercantile school, had learned to think in those of Quesnay and his followers, but that it was in Smith that he had learned to seek the causes and the effects of social phenomena in the nature of things, and to arrive at this last by a scrupulous analysis. His Traite d'tfconomie Pulitique (1803) was essentially founded on Smith's work, but he aimed at arranging the materials in a more logical and instructive order. 1 He has the French art of easy and lucid exposition, though his facility sometimes degenerates into superficiality j and hence his book became popular, both directly and through translations obtained a wide circulation, and diffused rapidly through the civilised world the doctrines of the master. Say's knowledge of common life, says Roscher, was equal to Smith's; but he falls far below him in living insight into larger political phenomena, and he carefully eschews historical and philoso- phical explanations. He is sometimes strangely shallow, aa when he says that " the best tax is that smallest in amount.' 1 He appears not to have much claim to the position of an original thinker in political economy. Kicardo, indeed, speaks of him as having " enriched the science, by several discussions, original, accurate, and profound." "What he had specially in view in using these words was what is, perhaps rather pre- tentiously, called Say's theorie des debouches, with his con- nected disproof of the possibility of a universal glut. The_ theory amounts simply to this, that buying is also selling, and that it is by producing that we are enabled to purchase the products of others. Several distinguished economists, especially 1 He grossly exaggerated Smith's faults of metho^ Thus he says "L'ouvrage de Smith n'est qu'un assemblage confus.des principes le plus sains de 1' Economic politique . . . sou livre eat un vaste chaoi d'id5es justee " (Ditcevri Preliminaire). SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 165 Malthus and Sismondi, in consequence cliiefly of a misiuter-^ pretation of the phenomena of commercial crises, maintained / that there might be general over-supply or excess of all commodities above the demand. This Say rightly denied. A particular branch of production may, it must indeed be admitted, exceed the existing capabilities of the market ; but, if we remember that supply is demand, that commodities are purchasing power, we cannot accept the doctrine of the possi- bility of a universal glut without holding that we can have too much of everything that " all men can be so fully provided with the precise articles they desire as to afford no market for each other's superfluities." Whatever services, however, Say may have rendered by original ideas on those or other subjects, his great merit is certainly that of a propa- gandist and populariser. The imperial police would not permit a second edition of his work to be issued without the introduction of changes which, with noble independence, he refused to make ; and that edition did not therefore appear till 1814. Three other editions were published during the life of the author in 1817, 1819, and 1826. In 1828 Say published a second treatise, Cours complet d' Economic Politique pratique, which contained the substance of his lectures at the Conservatoire des Arts et Metiers and at the College de France. Whilst in his earlier treatise he had kept within the narrow limits of strict econo- mics, in his later work he enlarged the sphere of discussion, introducing in particular many considerations respecting the economic influence of social institutions. Jean Charles L. Simonde de Sismondi (1773-1842), author of the Histoire des Republiques Italiennes du moyen dge, represents in the economic field a protest, founded mainly on humanitarian sentiment, against the dominant doctrines. He wrote first a treatise De la Richesse Oommerciale (1803), in which he Allowed strictly the principles of Adam Smith. But he af iei .vards came to regard these principles as insuffi- cient and requiring modification. He contributed an article on 166 POLITICAL ECONOMY. political economy to the Edinburgh Encyclopaedia, in which his new views were partially indicated. They were fully de- veloped in his principal economic work, Nouveaux Principe* d'jZconomie Politique, ou de la Richesse dans ses rapports avec la Population (1819 ; 2d ed., 1827). This work, as he tells us, was not received with favour by economists, a fact which he explains by the consideration that he had " attacked an orthodoxy an enterprise dangerous in philosophy as in reli- gion." According to his view, the science, as commonly understood, was too much of a mere chrematistic : it studied too exclusively the means of increasing wealth, and not sufficiently the use of this wealth for producing general happiness. The practical system founded on it tended, as he believed, not only to make the rich richer, but to make the poor poorer and more dependent ; and he desired to fix attention on the question of distribution as by far the most important, especially in the social circumstances of recent times. The personal union in Sismondi of three nationalities, the Italian, the French, and the Swiss, and his comprehensive historical studies, gave him a special largeness of view ; and he was filled with a noble sympathy for the suffering members of society. He stands nearer to socialism than any other French economist proper, but it is only in sentiment, not in opinion, that he approximates to it ; he does not recommend my socialistic scheme. On the contrary, he declares in a memorable passage that, whilst he sees where justice lies, he must confess himself unable to suggest the means of realising it in practice ; the division of the fruits of industry between those who are united in their production appears to him vicious ; but it is, in his judgment, almost beyond human power to conceive any system of property absolutely different from that which is known to us by experience. He goes no further than protesting, in view of the great evils which he saw around him, against the doctrine of laisser faire, and invoking, somewhat vaguely, the intervention of Governments SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 167 to " regulate the progress of wealth " and to protect the weaker members of the community. His frank confession of impotence, far wiser and more honourable than the suggestion of precipitate and dangerous remedies, or of a recurrence to outworn mediaeval institutions, has not affected the reputation of the work. A prejudice was indeed early created against it in consequence of its partial harmony of tone, though, as we have seen, not of policy, with socialism, which was then beginning to show its strength, as well as by the rude way in which his descriptions of the modern industrial system, especially as it existed in England, disturbed the complacent optimism of some members of the o-called orthodox school. These treated the book with ill- disguised contempt, and Bastiat spoke of it as preaching an economie politique cb rebours. But it has held its place in the literature of the science, and is now even more interesting than when it first appeared, because in our time there is a more general disposition, instead of denying or glossing over the serious evils of industrial society, to face and remove or at least mitigate them. The laisser faire doctrine, too, has been discredited in theory and abandoned in practice ; and we are ready to admit Sismondi's view of the State as a power not merely intrusted with the maintenance of pe-ice, but charged also with the mission of extending the benefits of the social union and of modern progress as widely as possible through all classes of the community. Yet the impression which his treatise leaves behind it is a discouraging one ; and this be- cause he regards as essentially evil many things which seem to be the necessary results of the development of industry. The growth of a wealthy capitalist class and of manufacture on the great scale, the rise of a vast body of workers who live by their labour alone, the extended application of machines, large landed properties cultivated with the aid of the most advanced appliances all these he dislikes and deprecates ; but they appear to be inevitable. The problem is, how to regulate and moralise the system they imply ; but we must 168 POLITICAL ECONOMY. surely accept it in principle, unless we aim at a thorough social revolution. Sismondi may be regarded as the precursor of the German economists known under the inexact desig- nation of " Socialists of the Chair ; " but their writings are much more hopeful and inspiring. To the subject of population he devotes special care, as of great importance for the welfare of the working classes. So far as agriculturists are concerned, he thinks the system of what he calls patriarchal exploitation, where the cultivator ia also proprietor, and is aided by his family in tilling the land a law of equal division among the natural heirs being apparently presupposed the one which is most efficacious in preventing an undue increase of the population. The father is, in such a case, able distinctly to estimate the resourcea available for his children, and to determine the stage of sub- division which would necessitate the descent of the family from the material and social position it had previously occu- pied. When children beyond this limit are born, they do not marry, or they choose amongst their number one to continue the race. This is the view which, adopted by J. S. Mill, makes so great a figure in the too favourable presentation by that writer of the system of peasant proprietors. In no French economic writer is greater force or general solidity of thought to be found than in Charles Dunoyer (1786-1862), author of La Libert^ du Travail (1845; the substance of the first volume had appeared under a different title in 1825), honourably known for his integrity and inde- pendence under the regime of the Restoration. What makes him of special importance in the history of the science ia his view of its philosophical constitution and method. With respect to method, he strikes the keynote at the very outset in the words " rechercher experimentalement," and in profes- sing to build on " les donnees de 1'observation et de I'exp&ri- ence." He shows a marked tendency to widen economics into a general science of society, expressly describing political economy as having for its province the whole order of things SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 169 which results from the exercise and development of the social '} forces. This larger study is indeed better named Sociology ; and economic studies are better regarded as forming one depart- ment of it. But the essential circumstance is that, in Duncyer's treatment of his great subject, the widest intellectual, moral, and political considerations are inseparably combined with purely economic ideas. It must not be supposed that by liberty, in the title of his work, is meant merely freedom from legal restraint or administrative interference ; he uses it to express whatever tends to give increased efficiency to labour. He is thus led to discuss all the causes of human progress, and to exhibit them in their historical working. Treating, in the first part, of the influence of external con- ditions, of race, and of culture on liberty in this wider sense, he proceeds to divide all productive effort into two great classes, according as the action is exercised on things or on men, and censures the economists for having restricted their attention to the former. He studies in his second and third parts respectively the conditions of the efficiency of these two forms of human exertion. In treating of economic life, strictly so called, he introduces his fourfold division of material industry, in part adopted by J. S. Mill, as " (i) extractive, (2) voituriere, (3) manufacturiere, (4) agricole," a division which is useful for physical economics, but will always, when the larger social aspect of things is considered, be inferior to the more commonly accepted one into agricultural, manu- facturing, and commercial industry, banking being supposed as common president and regulator. Dunoyer, having in view only action on material objects, relegates banking, as well as commerce proper, to the separate head of exchange, which, along with association and gratuitous transmission (whether inter vivos or mortis causa), he classes apart as being, not :A- dustries, in the same sense with the occupations named, but yet functions essential to the social economy. The industries which act on man he divides according as they occupy them- selves with (i) the amelioration of our physical nature, () 170 POLITICAL ECONOMY. the culture of our imagination and sentiments, (3) the edu cation of our intelligence, and (4) the improvement of oui moral habits ; and he proceeds accordingly to study the social offices of the physician, the artist, the educator, and the priest. | We meet in Dunoyer the ideas afterwards emphasised by / Bastiat that the real subjects of human exchange are services ; | that all value is due to human activity ; that the powers of nature always render a gratuitous^assistance to the labour of / noan ; and that the rent of land is really a form of interest on invested capital. Though he had disclaimed the task of a practical adviser in the often-quoted sentence " Je n'impose rien ; je ne propose meine rien ; j'expose," he finds himself, like all economists, unable to abstain from offering counsel. And his policy is opposed to any state interference with in- T dustry. Indeed he preaches in its extreme rigour the laisser ^tfaire doctrine, which he maintains principally on the ground that the spontaneous efforts of the individual for the improve- ment of his condition, by developing foresight, energy, and perseverance, are the most efficient means of social culture. But he certainly goes too far when he represents the action of Governments as normally always repressive and never directive. He was doubtless led into this exaggeration by his opposition to the artificial organisations of labour proposed by so many of his contemporaries, against which he had to vindicate the principle of competition ; but his criticism of these schemes took, as Comte remarks, too absolute a character, tending to the perpetual interdiction of a true systematisation of industry. 1 AMERICA. At this point it will be convenient to turn aside and notice the doctrines of the American economist Carey. Not much had been done before him in the science by citizens of the United States. Benjamin Franklin, otherwise of world-wide 1 The French economists are continued on page 175. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 171 renown, was author of a number of tracts, in most of which he merely enforces practical lessons of industry and thrift, but in some throws out interesting theoretic ideas. Thus, fifty years before Smith, he suggested (as Petty, however, had already done) human labour as the true measure of value (Modest Inquiry into the Nature and Necessity of a Paper Currency, 1721), and in his Observations concerning the In- c^ase of Mankind (1751) he expresses views akin to those i*f Malthus. Alexander Hamilton, secretary of the treasury, in 1791 presented in his official capacity to the House of Repre- sentatives of the United States a Report on the measures by which home manufactures could be promoted. 1 In this docu- ment he gives a critical account of the theory of the subject, represents Smith's system of free trade as possible in prac- tice only if adopted by all nations simultaneously, ascribes to manufactures a greater productiveness than to agriculture, and seelfs to refute the objections against the development of the former in America founded on the want of capital, the high rate of wages, and the low price of land. The conclusion at which he arrives is that for the creation of American manu- factures a system of moderate protective duties was necessary, and he proceeds to describe the particular features of such a system. There is some reason to believe that the German economist List, of whom we shall speak hereafter, was in- fluenced by Hamilton's work, having, during his exile from his native country, resided in the United States. Henry Charles Carey (1793-1879), son of an American citizen who had emigrated from Ireland, represents a reaction against the dispiriting character which the Smithiau doctrines had assumed in the hands of Malthus and Ricardo. His aim was, whilst adhering to the individualistic economy, to place it on a higher and surer basis, and fortify it against the assaults of socialism, to which some of the Ricardian tenets had exposed it. The most comprehensive as well as mature exposition of his views is contained in his Principles of Social 1 Hamilton's Works, edited by H. C. Lodge, vol. iii. p. 294. I7 POLITICAL ECONOMY. Science (1859). Inspired with the optimistic sentiment natural t ) a young and rising nation with abundant undeveloped resources and an unbounded outlook towards the future, 4, he seeks to show that there exists, independently of human wills, a natural system of economic laws, which is essentially beneficent, and of which the increasing prosperity of the r whole community, and especially of the working classes, ia / the spontaneous result, capable of being defeated only by the ignorance or perversity of man resisting or impeding its action. He rejects the Malthusian doctrine of population, maintaining that numbers regulate themselves sufficiently in every well-governed society, and that their pressure on sub- sistence characterises the lower, not the more advanced, stages of civilisation. He rightly denies the universal truth, for all stages of cultivation, of the law of diminishing returns from land. His fundamental theoretic position relates to the antithesis of wealth and value. Wealth had been by most economists confounded with the sum of exchange values ; even Smith, though at first distin- guishing them, afterwards allowed himself to fall into this error. Kicardo had, indeed, pointed out the difference, but only towards the end of his treatise, in the body of which value alone is considered. The later English economists had tended to regard their studies as conversant only with exchange ; so far had this proceeded that Whately had proposed for the science the name of Catallactics. When wealth is considered as what it really is, the sum of useful products, we see that it has its origin in external nature as supplying both materials and physical forces, and in human labour as appropriating and adapting those natural materials and forces. Nature gives her assistance gratuitously ; labour is the sole foundation of value. The less we can appropriate and employ natural forces in any production the higher the value of the product, but the less the addition to our wealth in proportion to the labour expended. Wealth, in its true sense of the sum of useful things, is the measure of the power we have acquired SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 173 over nature, whilst the value of an object expresses the resistance of nature which labour has tp overcome in order to produce the object. Wealth steadily increases in the course of social progress ; the exchange value of objects, on the other hand, decreases. Human intellect and faculty of social combination secure increased command over natural powers, and use them more largely in production, whilst less labour is spent in achieving each result, and the value of the product accordingly falls. The value of the article is not fixed by its cost of production in the past ; what really determines it is the cost which is necessary for its reproduction under the present conditions of knowledge and skill. The dependence of value on cost, so interpreted, Carey holds to be universally true ; whilst Ricardo maintained it only with respect to objects capable of indefinite multiplication, and in particular did not regard it as applicable to the case of land. Kicardo saw in the productive powers of land a free gift of nature which had been monopolised by a certain number of persons, and which became, with the increased demand for food, a larger and larger value in the hands of its possessors. To this value, however, as not being the result of labour, the owner, it might be maintained, had no rightful claim ; he could not justly demand a payment for what was done by the " original and indestructible powers of the soil." But Carey held that land, as we are concerned with it in industrial life, is really an instrument of production which has been formed as such by man, and that its value is due to the labour expended on it in the past, though measured, not by the sum of that labour, but by the labour necessary under existing conditions to bring new land to the same stage of productiveness. He studies the occupation and reclamation of land with peculiar advantage as an American, for whom the traditions of first settlement are living and fresh, and before whose eyes the process is indeed still going on. The difficulties of adapting a primitive soil to the work of yielding organic products for man's use can be lightly estimated only by an inhabitant of a country 174 POLITICAL ECONOMY. long under cultivation. It is, in Carey's view T the overcoming of tliese difficulties by arduous and continued effort that ontitles ) the first occupier of land to his property in the soil. Its pre- sent value forms a very small proportion of the cost expended on it, because it represents only what would be required, with the science and appliances of our time, to bring the land from its primitive into its present state. Property in land is therefore only a form of invested capital a quantity of labour or the fruits of labour permanently incorporated with the soil ; for which, like any other capitalist, the owner is compensated by a share of the produce. He is not rewarded for what is done by the powers of nature, and society is in no sense defrauded by his sole possession. The so-called Ricardian I theory of rent is a speculative fancy, contradicted by all experience. Cultivation does not in fact, as that theory supposes, begin with the best, and move downwards to the poorer soils in the order of their inferiority. 1 The light and dry higher lands are first cultivated ; and only when popula- tion has become dense and capital has accumulated, are the low-lying lands, with their greater fertility, but also with their morasses, inundations, and miasmas, attacked and brought into occupation. Rent, regarded as a proportion of the produce, . sinks, like all interest on capital, in process of time, but, as an absolute amount, increases. The share of the labourer increases, both as a proportion and an absolute amount. Arid thus the interests of these different social classes are in harmony. But, Carey proceeds to say, in order that this harmonious progress may be realised, what is taken from the land must be given back to it. All the articles derived from it are really separated parts of it, which must be restored on pain of its exhaustion. Hence the producer and the consumer must be close to each other ; the products must not be exported to a foreign country in exchange for its manufactures, and thus go to enrich as manure a foreign soil. In immediate exchange 1 It is, however, a mistake to suppose that the assumption of this historical order of descent is essential to the theory in question. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 175 value the landowner may gain by such exportation, but the productive powers of the land will suffer. And thus Carey, who had set out as an earnest advocate of free trade, arrives at the doctrine of protection : the " co-ordinating power " in society must intervene to prevent private advantage from working public mischief. 1 He attributes his conversion on the question to his observation of the effects of liberal and protective tariffs respectively on American prosperity. This observation, he says, threw him back on theory, and led him to see that the intervention referred to might be necessary to remove (as he phrases it) the obstacles to the progress of younger communities created by the action of older and wealthier nations. But it seems probable that the influence of List's writings, added to his own deep-rooted and hereditary jealousy and dislike of English predominance, had something to do with his change of attitude. The practical conclusion at which he thus arrived, though it is by no means in contradiction to the doctrine of the existence of natural economic laws, accords but ill with his optimistic scheme ; and another economist, accepting his funda- mental ideas, applied himself to remove the foreign accretion, as he regarded it, and to preach the theory of spontaneous social harmonies in relation with the practice of free trade as its legitimate outcome. 2 FRANCE (Continued). Frederic Bastiat (1801-1850), though not a profound 1 This argument seems scarcely met by Professor F. A. Walker, Political Economy, 50-52. But perhaps he is right in thinking that Carey exagge- rates the importance of the considerations on which it is founded. Mill and Leslie remark that the transportation of agricultural products from the western to the Atlantic States has the same effect as their export to Europe, so far as this so-called " land-butchery ' is concerned ; besides, tome manures are obtainable from abroad. 8 Other writings of Carey's besides his Somal Science are his Essay on the Rate of Wages (1835) '> Principles of Political Economy (1838-1840); Past, Present, and Future (1848) ; Unity of Law (1872). 176 POLITICAL ECONOMY. thinker, was a brilliant and popular writer on economic ques- tions. Though he always had an inclination for such stuclies s he was first impelled to the active propagation of his views by his earnest sympathy with the English anti-corn-law agita- tion. Naturally of an ardent temperament, he threw himself with zeal into the free-trade controversy, through which he hoped to influence French economic policy, and published in 1845 a history of the struggle under the title of Cobden et la Ligue. In 184548 appeared his Sophismes Bconomiques (Eng. trans, by P. J. Stirling, 1873), in which he exhibited his best qualities of mind. Though Cairnes goes too far in comparing this work with the Lettres Provinciates, it is cer- tainly marked by much liveliness, point, and vigour. But to expose the absurdities of the ordinary protectionism- was no difficult task ; it is only in such a form as the policy assumed in the scheme of List, as purely provisional and preparatory, that it deserves and demands consideration. After the revolu- tion of 1848, which for a time put an end to the free-trade movement in France, the efforts of Bastiat were directed against the socialists. Besides several minor pieces possessing the same sort of merit as the Sophismes, he produced, with a view to this controversy, his most ambitious as well as characteristic work, the Harmonies ficonomiques (Eng. trans, by P. J. Stirling, 1860). Only the first volume was published; it appeared in 1850, and its author died in the same year. Since then the notes and sketches which he had prepared as materials towards the production of the second volume have been given to the public in the collected edition of his writings (by Paillottet, with Life by Fontenay, 7 vols.), and we can thus gather what would have been the spirit and substance of the later portions of the book. It will always be historically interesting as the last incar- nation of thorough-going economic optimism. This optimism, recurring to its first origin, sets out from theological considera- tions, and Bastiat is commended by his English translator for treating political economy "in connection with final causes." SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 177 The spirit of the work is to represent "all principles, all motives, all springs of action, all interests, as co-operating towards a grand final result which humanity will never reach, but to which it will always increasingly tend, namely, the indefinite approximation of all classes towards a level, which steadily rises, in other words, the equalisation of individuals in the general amelioration." What claimed to be novel and peculiar in his scheme was principally his theory of value. Insisting on the idea that value does not denote anything inherent in the objects to which it is attributed, he endeavoured to show that it never signifies anything but the ratio of two " services." This view he develops with great Variety ted ielicity of illustration. Only the mutual services of human beings, according to him, possess value and can claim a retribution ; the assistance given by nature to the work of production is always purely gratui- tous, and never enters into price. Economic progress, as, for example, the improvement and larger use of machinery, tends perpetually to transfer more and more of the elements of utility from the domain of property, and therefore of value, into that of community, or of universal and unpurchased enjoyment It will be observed that this theory is substanti- ally identical with Carey's, which had been earlier propounded ; and the latter author in so many words alleges it to have been taken from him without acknowledgment. It has not perhaps been sufficiently attended to that very similar views are found in Dunoyer, of whose work Bastiat spoke as exercising a powerful influence on " the restoration of the science," and whom Fontenay, the biographer of Bastiat, tells us he recog- nised as one of his misters, Charles Comte l being the other. The mode which has just been explained of conceiving industrial action and industrial progress is interesting and 1 Charles Comte (1782-1837) was son-in-law of J. B. Say. He waa associated with Dunoyer in his political writings and, like him, distin- guished for his honourable independence. He was author of the TraM de Leyitlation, a meritorious and useful, but not a profound work. 178 POLITICAL ECONOMY. instructive so far as it is really applicable, but it was unduly generalised. Cairnes has well pointed out that Bastiat's theoretic soundness was injuriously affected by his habit of studying doctrines with a direct view to contemporary social and political controversies. He was thus predisposed to accept views which appeared to lend a sanction to legitimate and valuable institutions, and to reject those which seemed to him to lead to dangerous consequences. His constant aim is, as he himself expressed it, to " break the weapons " of anti-social reasoners " in their hands," and this preoccupation interferes with the single-minded effort towards the attainment of scientific truth. The creation or adoption of his theory of value was inspired by the wish to meet the socialistic criticism of property in land ; for the exigencies of this controversy it was desirable to be able to show that nothing is ever paid for except personal effort. His view of rent was, therefore, so to speak, foreordained, though it may have been suggested, aa indeed the editor of his posthumous fragments admits, by the writings of Carey. He held, with the American author, that rent is purely the reward of the pains and expenditure of the landlord or his predecessors in the process of converting the natural soil into & farm by clearing, draining, fencing, and the other species of permanent improvements. 1 He thus gets rid of the (so-called) Ricardian doctrine, which was accepted by the socialists, and by them used for the purpose of assailing the institution of landed property, or, at least, of supporting a claim of compensation to the community for the appropriation of the land by the concession of the " right to labour." As Cairnes has said, 2 " what Bastiat did was this : having been at infinite pains to exclude gratuitous gifts of nature from the possible elements of value, and pointedly identified " [rather, associated] " the phenomenon with ' human effort ' as its 1 M. Leroy-Beaulieu maintains ( Essai sur la Repartition des Richessei, 2d ed., 1882) that this, though not strictly, is approximately true that economic forms a very small part of actual rent. 8 Estays in Political Economy, p. 334. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 179 exclusive source, he designates human effort by the term ' service,' and then employs this term to admit as sources of value those very gratuitous natural gifts the exclusion of which in this capacity constituted the essence of his doctrine." The justice of this criticism will be apparent to any one who considers the way in which Bastiat treats the question of the value of a diamond. That what is paid for in most cases of human dealings is effort no one can dispute. But it is surely a reductio ad dbsurdum of his theory of value, regarded as a doctrine of universal application, to represent the price of a diamond which has been accidentally found as remuneration for the effort of the finder in appropriating and transmitting it. And, with respect to land, whilst a large part of rent, in the popular sense, must be explained as interest on capital, it is plain that the native powers of the soil are capable of appropriation, and that then a price can be demanded and will be paid for their use. Bastiat is weak on the philosophical side ; he is filled with the ideas of theological teleology, and is led by these ideas to form a priori opinions of what existing facts and laws must necessarily be. And the jus naturae, which, like metaphysical ideas generally, has its root in theology, is as much a postu- late with him as with the physiocrats. Thus, in his essay on Free Trade, he says : " Exchange is a natural right like property. Every citizen who has created or acquired a product ought to have the option of either applying it immediately to his own use or ceding it to whosoever on the surface of the globe consents to give him in exchange the object of his desires." Something of the same sort had been said by Turgot ; and in his time this way of regarding things was excusable, and even provisionally useful; but in the middle of the i Qth century it was time that it should be seen through and abandoned. Bastiat had a real enthusiasm for a science which he thought destined to render great services to mankind, and he seems to have believed intensely the doctrines which gave a special i8o POLITICAL ECONOMY. colour to his teaching. If his optimistic exaggerations favoured the propertied classes, they certainly were not prompted by self-interest or servility. But they are exaggerations ; and, amidst the modern conflicts of capital and labour, his per- petual assertion of social harmonies is the cry of " peace, peace," where there is no peace. The freedom of industry, which he treated as a panacea, has undoubtedly brought with it great benefits ; but a sufficient experience has shown that it is inadequate to solve the social problem. How can the advocates of economic revolution be met by assuring them that everything in the natural economy is harmonious that, in fact, all they seek for already exists ? A certain degree of spontaneous harmony does indeed exist, for society could not continue without it, but it is imperfect and precarious ; the question is, How can we give to it the maximum of complete- ness and stability ? Augustin Cournot (18011877) appears to have been the first l who, with a competent knowledge of both subjects, en- deavoured, to apply mathematics to the treatment of economic questions. His treatise entitled Recherches sur les Principes Mathematiques de la Theorie des Richesses was published in 1838. He mentions in it only one previous enterprise of the same kind (though there had in fact been others) that, namely, of Nicolas Frangois Canard, whose book, published in 1802, was crowned by the Institute, though "its principles were radically false as well as erroneously applied." Not- withstanding Cournot's just reputation as a writer on mathe- matics, the Recherches made little impression. The truth seems to be that his results are in some cases of little import- ance, in others of questionable correctness, and that, in the abstractions to which he has recourse in order to facilitate his calculations, an essential part of the real conditions of the problem is sometimes omitted. His pages abound in symbols 1 Hermann Heinrich Gossan's work, Entwickelung der Gesetze det menschlichen VerTcehrs, so highly praised by Jevous, Theory of Pol. Meon., ad ed., Pref., was published in 1854. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 181 representing unknown functions, the form of the function being left to be ascertained by observation of facts, which he does not regard as a part of his task, or only some known properties of the undetermined function being used as bases for deduction. Jevons includes in his list of works in which a mathematical treatment of economics is adopted a second treatise which Cournot published in 1863, with the title Principes de la Theorie des Richesses. But in reality, in th6 work so named, which is written with great ability, and con- tains much forcible reasoning in opposition to the exaggera- tions of the ordinary economists, the mathematical method is abandoned, and there is not an algebraical formula in the book. The author admits that the public has always shown a repug- nance to the use of mathematical symbols in economic dis- cussion, and, though he thinks they might be of service in facilitating exposition, fixing the ideas, and suggesting further developments, he acknowledges that a grave danger attends their use. The danger, according to him, consists in the probability that an undue value may be attached to the abstract hypotheses from which the investigator sets out, and which enable him to construct his formulae. And his practical conclusion is that mathematical processes should be employed only with great precaution, or even not employed at all if the public judgment is against them, for "this judgment," he says, " has its secret reasons, almost always more sure than those which determine the opinions of individuals." It is an obvious consideration that the acceptance of unsound or one- sided abstract principles as the premises of argument does not depend on the use of mathematical forms, though it is possible that the employment of the latter may by association produce an illusion in favour of the certainty of those premises. But the great objection to the use of mathematics in economic reasoning is that it is necessarily sterile. If we examine the attempts which have been made to employ it, we shall find that the fundamental conceptions on which the deductions are made to rest are vague, indeed metaphysical, in their 182 POLITICAL ECONOMY. character. Units of animal or moral satisfaction, of utility, and the like, are as foreign to positive science as a unit of dormitive faculty would be ; and a unit of value, unless we understand by value the quantity of one commodity exchange- able under given conditions for another, is an equally indefinite idea. Mathematics can indeed formulate ratios of exchange when they have once been observed ; but it cannot by any process of its own determine those ratios, for quantitative conclusions imply quantitative premises, and these are want- ing. There is then no future for this kind of study, and it is only waste of intellectual power to pursue it. But the im- portance of mathematics as an educational introduction to all the higher orders of research is not affected by this conclusion. The study of the physical medium, or environment, in which economic phenomena take place, and by which they are affected, requires mathematics as an instrument ; and nothing can ever dispense with the didactic efficacy of that science, as supplying the primordial type of rational investigation, giving the lively sentiment of decisive proof, and disinclining the mind to illusory conceptions and sophistical combinations. And a knowledge of at least the fundamental principles of mathematics is necessary to economists to keep them right in their statements of doctrine, and prevent their enunciating propositions which have no definite meaning. Even dis- tinguished writers sometimes betray a serious deficiency in this respect ; thus they assert that one quantity " varies in- versely as " another, when what is meant is that the sum (not the product) of the two is constant ; and they treat as capable of numerical estimation the amount of an aggregate of elements which, differing in kind, cannot be reduced to a common standard. As an example of the latter error, it may be mentioned that " quantity of labour," so often spoken of by Kicardo, and in fact made the basis of his /stem, includes such various species of exertion as will not admit of summa- tion or comparison. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 183 ITALY. The first Italian translation of the Wealth of NaMont appeared in 1780. The most distinguished Italian economist of the period here dealt with was, however, no disciple of Smith. This was Melchiorre Gioja, author, besides statisti- cal and other writings, of a voluminous work entitled Nuovo Prospetto delle Scienze Economiche (6 vols., 1815-17; the work was never completed), intended to be an encyclopaedia of all that had been taught by theorists, enacted by Govern- ments, or effected by populations in the field of public and private economy. It is a learned and able treatise, but so overladen with quotations and tables as to repel rather than attract readers. Gioja admired the practical economic system of England, and enlarges on the advantages of territorial proper- ties, manufactures, and mercantile enterprises on the large as opposed to the small scale. He defends a restrictive policy, and insists on the necessity of the action of the state as a guiding, supervising, and regulating power in the industrial world. But he is in full sympathy with the sentiment of his age against ecclesiastical domination and other mediaeval survivals. We can but very briefly notice Romagnosi (d. 1835), who, by his contributions to periodical literature, ami by his personal teaching, greatly influenced the course of economic thought in Italy ; Antonio Scialoja (Principii d' Economia Sociale, 1840; and Carestia e Governo, 1853), an able advocate of free trade (d. 1877); Luigi Cibrario, well known as the author of Economia Politico, del media evo (1839; 5th ed., 7861: French trans, by Barneaud, 1859), which is in fact a view of the whole social system of that period; Girolamo Boccardo (b. 1829; Trattato Teorico-pratico di Economia Politica, 1853); the brilliant controversialist Francesco Ferrara, professor at Turin from 1849 to 1858 (in whose school most of the present Italian teachers of the science were, directly or indirectly, educated), a partisan of the laisser faire doctrine in its most extreme form, and an advocate of 184 POLITICAL ECONOMV. the peculiar opinions of Carey and Bastiat on the subject of rent; and,, lastly, the Neapolitan minister Ludovico Bianchini (Prindpii della Scienza del Ben Vivere Sociale, 1845 ai 'd 1855), who is remarkable as having followed in some degree an historical direction, and asserted the principle of relativity, and who also dwelt on the relations of economics with morals, by a due attention to which the Italian economists have, indeed, in general been honourably distinguished. SPAIN. The Wealth of Nations was translated into Spanish by Ortiz in 1794. It may perhaps have influenced Caspar de Jovellanos, who in 1795 presented to the council of Castile and printed in the same year his celebrated Informe de la Sociedad Economica de Madrid en expedients de Ley Agraria, which was a powerful plea for reform, especially in taxation and the laws affecting agriculture, including those relating to the systems of entail and mortmain. An English version of this memoir is given in the translation (1809) of Laborde's Spain, voL iv. GERMANY. Roscher observes that Smith did not at first produce much impression in Germany. 1 He does not appear to have been known to Frederick the Great ; he certainly exercised no in- fluence on him. Nor did Joseph II. take notice of his work. And of the minor German princes, Karl Friedrich of Baden, as a physiocrat, would not be accessible to his doctrines. It was otherwise in the generation whose principal activity be- longs to the first decade of the igth century. The Prussian statesmen who were grouped round Stein had been formed aa 1 The first German version of the Wealth of Nations was that by Johann Friedrich Schiller, published 1776-78. The second, which is the first good one, was by Christian Garve (1794, and again 1799 and 1810). A bter one by C. W. Asher (1861) is highly commended. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 185 economists by Smith, as had also Gentz, intellectually the most important man of the Metternich regime in Austria. The first German expositors of Smith who did more than merely reproduce his opinions were Christian Jacob Kraus (1753-1807), Georg Sartorius (1766-1828), and August Ferdi- nand Luder(i 7 60-1 8 1 9). They contributed independent views ^^^^^^^ "^ from different standpoints, the first from that of the effect of Smith's doctrine on practical government, the second from that of its bearing on history, the third from that of its rela- tion to statistics. Somewhat later came Gottlieb Hufeland (i76o-i8i^)7^h ann Friedrich Eusebius Lotz (1771-1838,) and Ludwig Heinrich von Jakob (1759-1827), who, whilst essentially of the school of Smith, apply themselves to a re- vision of the fundamental conceptions of the science. These authors did not exert anything like the wide influence of Say, partly on account of the less attractive form of their writings, but chiefly because Germany had not then, like France, a European audience. Julius von Soden (1754-1831) is largely founded on Smith, whom, however, he criticises with undue severity, especially in regard to his form and arrangement ; the Wealth of Nations he describes as a series of precious fragments, and censures Smith for the absence of a comprehensive view of his whole subject, and also as one- sidedly English in his tendencies. The highest form of the Smithian doctrine in Germany is represented by four distinguished names : Karl Heinrich Eau (1792-1870), Friedrich Nebenius (1784-1857), Friedrich Benedict Wilhelm Hermann (1795-1868), and Johann Hein- rich von Thiinen (1783-1850). Raja's characteristic is " erudite thoroughness." His Lehr- buck (1826-32) is an encyclopaedia of all that up to his time had appeared in Germany under the several heads of Volks- wirthschaftslehre, Volkswirllischaftspolitik, and Finanzioissen- schaft. His book is rich in statistical observations, and is particularly instructive on the economic effects of different geographical conditions. It is well adapted for the teaching 186 POLITICAL ECONOMY. of public servants whose duties are connected with economics, and it has in fact been the source from which the German official world down to the present time has derived its know- ledge of the science. In his earlier period Eau had insisted on the necessity of a reform of economic doctrine (An&ichten der Volksmrthschaft, 1821), and had tended towards relativity and the historical method; but he afterwards conceived the mistaken notion that that method " only looked into the past without studying the means of improving the present," and became himself purely practical in the narrower sense of that word. He has the merit of having given a separate treat- ment of Unternehmergewinn, or " wages of management." The Prussian minister Nebenius, who was largely instrumental in the foundation of the Zollverein, was author of a highly esteemed monograph on public credit (1820). The Staats- loirthschaftliche Untersuclmngen (1832 ; 2d ed., 1870) of Hermann do not form a regular system, but treat a series of important special subjects. His rare technological knowledge gave him a great advantage in dealing with some economic questions. He reviewed the principal fundamental ideas of the science with great thoroughness and acuteness. " His strength," says Koscher, " lies in his clear, sharp, exhaustive distinction between the several elements of a complex con- ception, or the several steps comprehended in a complex act." For keen analytical power his German brethren compare him with Ricardo. But he avoids several one sided views of the English economist. Thus he places public spirit beside egoism as an economic motor, regards price as not measured by labour only but as a product of several factors, and habi- tually contemplates the consumption of the labourer, not as a part of the cost of production to the capitalist, but as the main practical end of economics. Von Thiinen is known principally by his remarkable work entitled Der Isolirte Stoat in Beziehung auf Landwirthschaft und Nationalokonomie (1826; 2d ed., 1842). In this treatise, which is a classic in the political economy of agriculture, there is a rare union of SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 18? exact observation with creative imagination. With a view to exhibit the natural development of agriculture, he imagines a state, isolated from the rest of the world, circular in form and of uniform fertility, without navigable rivers or canals, with a single large city at its centre, which supplies it with manu- factures and receives in exchange for them its food-products, and proceeds to study the effect of distance from this central market on the agricultural economy of the several concentric spaces which compose the territory. The method, it will be seen, is highly abstract, but, though it may not be fruit- ful, it is quite legitimate. The author is under no illusion blinding him to the unreality of the hypothetic case. The supposition is necessary, in his view^ in order to separate and consider apart one essential condition that, namely, of situation with respect to the market. It was his intention (imperfectly realised, however) to institute afterwards several different hypotheses in relation to his isolated state, for the purpose of similarly studying other conditions which in real life are found in combination or conflict. The objection to this method lies in the difficulty of the return from the abstract study to the actual facts; and this is probably an insuperable one in regard to most of its applications. The investigation, however, leads to trustworthy conclusions as to the conditions of the succession of different systems of land economy. The book abounds in calculations relating to agri- cultural expenditure and income, which diminish its interest to the general reader, though they are considered valuable to the specialist. They embody the results of the practical ex- perience of the author on his estate of Tellow in Mecklenburg- Schwerin. Von Thiinen was strongly impressed with the danger of a violent conflict between the middle class and the proletariate, and studied earnestly the question of wages, which he was one of the first to regard habitually, not merely as the price of the commodity labour, but as the means of subsistence of the mass of the community. He arrived by mathematical reasonings of some complexity at a formula 188 POLITICAL ECONOMY. which expresses the amount of " natural wages " as = where a is the necessary expenditure of the labourer for subsistence, and p is the product of his labour. To this formula he attributed so much importance that he directed it to be engraved on his tomb. It implies that wages ought to rise with the amount of the product ; and this conclusion led him to establish on his estate a system of participation by the labourers in the profits of farming, of which some account will be found in Mr. Sedley Taylor's Profit-sharing between Capital and Labour (1884). Yon Thiinen deserves more attention than he has received in England ; both as a man and as a writer he was eminently interesting and original ; and there is much in Der Isolirte Stoat and his other works that is awakening and suggestive. Roscher recognises what he calls a Germano-Russian (deutsch-russische) school of political economy, represented principally by Heinrich Storch (1766-1825). Mercantilist principles had been preached by a native (" autochthonen ") economist, Ivan Possoschkoff, in the time of Peter the Great. The new ideas of the Smithian system were introduced into Russia by Christian Von Schlb'zer (17741831) in his pro- fessorial lectures and in his Anfangsgriinde der Staatswirth- schaft, oder die Lehre von National-reichthume (18051807). Storch was instructor in economic science of the future emperor Nicholas and his brother the grand-duke Michael, and the substance of his lessons to them is contained in his Cours d'JZconomie Politique (1815). The translation of this treatise into Russian was prevented by the censorship ; Rau published a German version of it, with annotations, in 1819. It is a work of a very high order of merit. The epithet " deutsch-russisch " seems little applicable to Storch ; as Roscher himself says, he follows mainly English and French writers Say, Sismondi, Turgot, Bentham, Steuart, and Hume, but, above all, Adam Smith. His personal position (and the same is true of Schlozer) led him to consider economic doctrines in connection with a stage of culture different from SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 189 that of the Western populations amongst which they had been formulated ; this change of the point of view opened the door to relativity, and helped to prepare the Historical method. Storch's study of the economic and moral effects of serfdom is regarded as especially valuable. The general subjects with which he has particularly connected his name are (i) the doctrine of immaterial commodities (or elements of national prosperity), such as health, talent, morality, and the like ; (2) the question of "productive" and "unproductive," as characters of labour and of consumption, on which he dis- agreed with Smith and may have furnished indications to Dunoyer; and (3) the differences between the revenue of nations and that of individuals, on which he follows Lauder- dale and is opposed to Say. The latter economist having published at Paris (1823) a new edition of Storch's Cours, with criticisms sometimes offensive in tone, he published by way of reply to some of Say's strictures what is considered his ripest and scientifically most important work, Considera- tions sur la nature du Revenu National (1824 ; translated into German by the author himself, 1825). A distinct note of opposition to the Smithian economics was sounded in Germany by two writers, who, setting out from somewhat different points of view, animated by different sentiments, and favouring different practical systems, yet, so far as their criticisms are concerned, arrive at similar con- clusions ; we mean Adam Muller and Friedrich List. Adam Muller (1779-1829) was undoubtedly a man of real genius. In his principal work Elemente der Staatskunst (1809), and his other writings, he represents a movement of economic thought which was in relation with the (so-called) Eomantic literature of the period. The reaction against Smithianism of which he was the coryphaeus was founded on an attachment to the principles and social system of the Middle Ages. It is possible that the political and historical ideas which inspire him, his repugnance to contemporary liberalism, and his notions of regular organic development, igo POLITICAL ECONOMY. especially in relation to England, were in some degree imbibed from Edmund Burke, whose Reflections on the Revolution in France had been translated into German by Friedrich Gentz, the friend and teacher of Miiller. The association of his criticisms with mediaeval prepossessions ought not to prevent our recognising the elements of truth which they contain. He protests against the doctrine of Smith and against modern political economy in general on the ground that it presents a mechanical, atomistic, and purely material con- ception of society, that it reduces to nullity all moral forces and ignores the necessity of a moral order, that it is at bottom no more than a theory of private property and private interests, and takes no account of the life of the people as a whole in its national solidarity and historical continuity. Exclusive attention, he complains, is devoted to the immediate production of objects possessing exchange value and to the transitory existence of individuals ; whilst to the maintenance of the collective production for future generations, to intellectual products, powers, possessions, and enjoyments, and to the State with its higher tasks and aims, scarcely a thought is given. The truth is that nations are specialised organisms with distinct principles of life, having definite individualities which determine the course of their historical development. Each is through all time one whole ; and, as the present is the heir of the past, it ought to keep before it constantly the permanent good of the community in the future. The eco- nomic existence of a people is only one side or province of its entire activity, requiring to be kept in harmony with the higher ends of society ; and the proper organ to effect this reconciliation is the State, which, instead of being merely an apparatus for the administration of justice, represents the totality of the national life. The division of labour, Miiller holds, is imperfectly developed by Smith, who makes it to arise out of a native bent for truck or barter ; whilst its dependence on capital on the labours and accumulations of past generations is not duly emphasised, nor is the necessary SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 191 counterpoise and completion of the division of labour, in the principle of the national combination of labour, properly brought out. Smith recognises only material, not spiritual, capital ; yet the latter, represented in every nation by language, as the former by money, is a real national store of experience, wisdom, good sense, and moral feeling, transmitted with in- crease by each generation to its successor, and enables each generation to produce immensely more than by its own unaided powers it could possibly do. Again, the system of Smith is one-sidedly British ; if it is innocuous on the soil of England, it is because in her society the old foundations on which the spiritual and material life of the people can securely rest are preserved in the surviving spirit of feudalism and the inner connection of the whole social system the national capital of laws, manners, reputation, and credit, which has been handed down in its integrity in consequence of the in- sular position of the country. . For the continent of Europe a quite different system is necessary, in which, in place of the sum of the private wealth of individuals being viewed as the primary object, the real wealth of the nation and the produc- tion of national power shall be made to predominate, and along with the division of labour its national union and concentra- tion along with the physical, no less the intellectual and moral, capital shall be embraced. In these leading traits of Miiller's thought there is much which foreshadows the more recent forms of German economic and sociological speculation, especially those characteristic of the " Historical " school. Another element of opposition was represented by Friedrich List (1798-1846), a man of great intellectual vigour as well as practical energy, and notable as having powerfully contri- buted by his writings to the formation of the German Zull- verein. His principal work is entitled Das Nationals System der Politischen Oekonomie (1841 ; 6th ed., 1877 : Eng. trans., 1885). Though his practical conclusions were different from Miiller's, he was largely influenced by the general mode of thinking of that writer, and by his strictures on the doctrine 192 POLITICAL ECONOMY. of Smith. It was particularly against the cosmopolitan prin- ciple in the modern economical system that he protested, and against the absolute doctrine of free trade, which was in harmony with that principle. He gave prominence to the National idea, and insisted on the special requirements of each nation according to its circumstances and especially to the degree of its development. He refuses to Smith's system the title of the industrial, which he thinks more appropriate to the mercantile system, and designates the former as " the exchange- value system." He denies the parallelism asserted by Smith between the eco- nomic conduct proper to an individual and to a nation, and holds that the immediate private interest of the separate members of the community will not lead to the highest good of the whole. The nation is an existence, standing between the individual and Humanity, and formed into a unity by its language, manners, historical development, culture, and con* stitution. This unity is the first condition of the security, wellbeing, progress, and civilisation of the individual ; and private economic interests, like all others, must be subordi- nated to the maintenance, completion, and strengthening of the nationality. The nation having a continuous life, its true wealth consists and this is List's fundamental doctrine not in the quantity of exchange- values which it possesses, but in the full and many-sided development of its productive powers. Its economic education, if we may so speak, is more important than the immediate production of values, and it may be right that the present generation should sacrifice its gain and enjoy- ment to secure the strength and skill of the future. In the sound and normal condition of a nation which has attained economic maturity, the three productive powers of agriculture, manufactures, and commerce should be alike developed. But the two latter factors are superior in importance, as exercising a more effective and fruitful influence on the whole culture of the nation, as well as on its independence. Navigation, railways, all higher technical arts, connect themselves specially SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 193 irith these factors ; whilst in a purely agricultural state there is a tendency to stagnation, absence of enterprise, and the main- tenance of antiquated prejudices. But for the growth of the higher forms of industry all countries are not adapted only those' of the temperate zones, whilst the torrid regions have a natural monopoly in the production of certain raw materials ; end thus between these two groups of countries a division of labour and confederation of powers spontaneously takes place. List then goes on to explain his theory of the stages of econo- mic development through which the nations of the temperate zone, which are furnished with all the necessary conditions, naturally pass, in advancing to their normal economic state. These are (i) pastoral life, (2) agriculture, (3) agriculture united with manufactures; whilst in the final stage agriculture, manufactures, and commerce are combined. The economic task of the state is to bring into existence by legislative and administrative action the conditions required for the progress of the nation through these stages. Out of this view arises List's scheme of industrial politics. Every nation, according to him, should begin with free trade, stimulating and improv- ing its agriculture by intercourse with richer and more culti- vated nations, importing foreign manufactures and exporting raw products. When it is economically so far advanced that it can manufacture for itself, then a system of protection should be employed to allow the home industries to develop themselves fully, and save them from being overpowered in their earlier efforts by the competition of more matured foreign industries in the home market. When the national industriea have grown strong enough no longer to dread this competi- tion, then the highest stage of progress has been reached ; free bade should again become the rule, and the nation be thus thoroughly incorporated with the universal industrial union. In List's time, according to his view, Spain, Portugal, and Naples were purely agricultural countries; Germany and the United States of North America had arrived at the second tage, their manufactures being in process of development- M 194 POLITICAL ECONOMY. France was near the boundary of the third or highest stage, which England alone had reached. For England, therefore, as well as for the agricultural countries first-named, free trade was the right economic policy, but not for Germany or America. What a nation loses for a time in exchange-values during the protective period she much more than gains in the long run in productive power, the temporary expenditure being strictly analogous, when we place ourselves at the point of view of the life of the nation, to the cost of the industrial education of the individual. The practical conclusion which List drew for his own country was that she needed for her economic pro- gress an extended and conveniently bounded territory reaching to the sea-coast both on north and south, and a vigorous ex- pansion of manufactures and commerce, and that the way to the latter lay through judicious protective legislation with a customs union comprising all German lands, and a German marine with a Navigation Act. The national German spirit, striving after independence and power through union, and the national industry, awaking from its lethargy and eager to recover lost ground, were favourable to the success of List's book, and it produced a great sensation. He ably represented the tendencies and demands of his time in his own country ; his work had the effect of fixing the attention, not merely of the speculative and official classes, but of practical men gene- rally, on questions of Political Economy ; and he had without doubt an important influence on German industrial policy. So far as science is concerned, the emphasis he laid on the relative historical study of stages of civilisation as affecting economic questions, and his protest against absolute formulas, had a certain value ; and the preponderance given to the national development over the immediate gains of individuals was sound in principle ; though his doctrine was, both on its public and private sides, too much of a mere chrematistic, and tended in fact to set up a new form of mercantilism, rather than to aid the contemporary effort towards social reform. SYSTEM OF NATURAL LIBERTY. 195 Most of the writers at home or abroad hitherto mentioned continued the traditions of the school of Smith, only develop- ing his doctrine in particular directions, sometimes not without one-sidedness or exaggeration, or correcting minor rrors into which he had fallen, or seeking to give to tne exposition of his principles more of order and lucidity. Some assailed the abuse of abstraction by Smith's successors, objected to the con- clusions of Kicardo and his followers their non-accordance with the actual facts of human life, or protested against the anti- social consequences which seemed to result from the application of the (so-called) orthodox formulas. A few challenged Smith's fundamental ideas, and insisted on the necessity of altering the basis of general philosophy on which his economics ultimately rest. But, notwithstanding various premonitory indications, nothing substantial, at least nothing effective, was done, within the field we have as yet surveyed, towards the establishment of a really new order of thinking, or new mode of proceeding, in this branch of inquiry. Now, however, we have to describe a great and growing movement, which has already considerably changed the whole character of the study in the conceptions of many, and which promises to exercise a still more potent influence in the future. We mean the rise of the Historical School, which we regard as marking the third epoch in the modern development of economic science. CHAPTER VI. THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. THE negative movement which filled the eighteenth century had for its watchword on the economic side the liberation of industrial effort from both feudal survivals and Governmental fetters. But in all the aspects of that movement, the economic as well as the rest, the process of demolition was historically only the necessary preliminary condition of a total renova- tion, towards which Western Europe was energetically tending, though with but an indistinct conception of its precise nature. The disorganisation of the body of opinion which underlay the old system outran the progress towards the establishment of new principles adequate to form a guidance in the future. The critical philosophy which had wrought the disorganisation could only repeat its formulas of absolute liberty, but was powerless for reconstruction. And hence there was seen throughout the West, after the French explosion, the remark- able spectacle of a continuous oscillation between the tendency to recur to outworn ideas and a vague impulse towards a new order in social thought and life, this impulse often taking an anarchical character. From this state of oscillation, which has given to our century its equivocal and transitional aspect, the only possible issue was in the foundation of a scientific social doctrine which should supply a basis for the gradual convergence of opinion on human questions. The foundation of such a doctrine is the immortal service for which the world is indebted to Auguste Comte (1798-1857). THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 197 The leading features of Sociology, as he conceived it, are the following: (i) it is essentially one science, in which all the elements of a social state are studied in their relations and mutual actions ; (2) it includes a dynamical as well as a statical theory of society ; (3) it thus eliminates the absolute, substi- tuting for an imagined fixity the conception of ordered change ; (4) its principal method, though others are not excluded, is that of historical comparison ; (5) it is pervaded by moral ideas, by notions of social duty, as opposed to the individual rights which were derived as corollaries from the jus natures ; and (6) in its spirit and practical consequences it tends to the realisation of all the great ends which compose " the popular cause " ; yet (7) it aims at this through peaceful means, re- placing revolution by evolution. 1 The several characteristics we have enumerated are not independent ; they may be shown to be vitally connected with each other. Several of these features must now be more fully described; the others will meet us before the close of the present survey. In the masterly exposition of sociological method which is contained in the fourth volume of the Philosophic Positive (i839), 2 Comte marks out the broad division between social statics and social dynamics the former studying the laws of social coexistence, the latter those of social development. The fundamental principle of the former is the general consensus 1 It would be a grave error to suppose that the subjection of social phenomena to natural laws affords any encouragement to a spirit of fatal- istic quietism. On the contrary, it is the existence of such laws that is the necessary basis of all systematic action for the improvement either of our condition or of our nature, as may be seen by considering the parallel case of hygienic and therapeutic agencies. And, since the dif- ferent orders of phenomena are more modifiable in proportion to their greater complexity, the social field admits of more extensive and effica- cious human intervention than the inorganic or vital domain. In rela- tion to the dynamical side of Sociology, whilst the direction and essential character of the evolution are predetermined, its rate and secondary features are capable of modification. 2 He had already in 1822 stated his fundamental principles in an opuscule which is reproduced in the Appendix to his Politiqut Positive. 198 POLITICAL ECONOMY. between the several social organs and functions, which, without unduly pressing a useful analogy, we may regard as resembling that which exists between the several organs and functions of an animal body. The study of dynamical is different from, and necessarily subordinated to, that of statical sociology, pro- gress being in fact the development of order, just as the study of evolution in biology is different from, and subordinated to, that of the structures and functions which are exhibited by evolution as they exist at the several points of an ascending scale. The laws of social coexistence and movement are as much subjects for observation as the corresponding phenomena in the life of an individual organism. For the study of development in particular, a modification of the comparative method familiar to biologists will be the appropriate mode of research. The several successive stages of society will have to be systematically compared, in order to discover their laws of sequence, and to determine the filiation of their charac- teristic features. Though we must take care that both in our statical and dynamical studies we do not ignore or contradict the funda- mental properties of human nature, the project of deducing either species of laws fr<3m those properties independently of direct observation is one which cannot be realised. Neither the general structure of human society nor the march of its development could be so predicted. This is especially evident with respect to dynamical laws, because, in the passage of society from one phase to another, the pre- ponderating agency is the accumulated influence of past generations, which is much too complex to be investigated deductively a conclusion which it is important to keep steadily before us now that some of the (so-called) anthro- pologists are seeking to make the science of society a mere annex and derivative of biology. The principles of biology unquestionably lie at the foundation of the social science, but the latter has, and must always have, a field of research and a method of inquiry peculiar to itself. The field is history in THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 199 the largest sense, including contemporary fact ; and the prin- cipal, though not exclusive, method is, as we have said, that process of sociological comparison which is most conveniently called "the historical method." These general principles affect the economic no less than other branches of social speculation ; and with respect to that department of inquiry they lead to important results. They show that the idea of forming a true theory of the economic frame and working of society apart from its other sides is illusory. Such study is indeed provisionally indispensable, but no rational theory of the economic organs and functions of society can be constructed if they are considered as isolated from the rest. In other words, a separate economic science is, strictly speaking, an impossibility, as representing only one portion of a complex organism, all whose parts and their actions are in a constant relation of correspondence and reciprocal modification. Hence, too, it will follow that, whatever useful indications may be derived from our general knowledge of individual human nature, the economic structure of society and its mode of development cannot be deductively foreseen, but must be ascertained by direct historical investi- gation. We have said " its mode of development " ; for it is obvious that, as of every social element, so of the economic factor in human affairs, there must be a dynamical doctrine, a theory of the successive phases of the economic condition ol society ; yet in the accepted systems this was a desideratum, nothing but some partial and fragmentary notions on this whole side of the subject being yet extant. 1 And, further, the economic structure and working of one historic stage being different from those of another, we must abandon the idea of an absolute system possessing universal validity, and substitute that of a series of such systems, in which, however, 1 Under the influence of these views of Comte, J. S. Mill attempted in Book IV. of his Political Economy a treatment of Economic Dynamics ; but that appears to us one of the least satisfactory portions of hut work. 200 POLITICAL ECONOMY. the succession is not at all arbitrary, but is itself regulated by law. Though Comte's enterprise was a constructive one, his aim being the foundation of a scientific theory of society, he could not avoid criticising the labours of those who before him ha.l treated several branches of social inquiry. Amongst them the economists were necessarily considered ; and he urged or im- plied, in various places of his above-named work, as well as of his Politique Positive, objections to their general ideas and methods of procedure essentially the same with those which we stated in speaking of Ricardo and his followers. J. S. Mill shows himself much irritated by these comments, and remarks on them as showing "how extremely superficial M. Conite " (whom he yet regards as a thinker quite comparable with Descartes and Leibnitz) " could sometimes be," an un- fortunate observation, which he would scarcely have made if he could have foreseen the subsequent march of Euro- pean thought, and the large degree in which the main points of Comte's criticism have been accepted or independently reproduced. GERMANY. The second manifestation of this new movement in economic science was the appearance of the German historical school The views of this school do not appear to have arisen, like Comte's theory of sociological method, out of general philo- sophic ideas ; they seem rather to have been suggested by an extension to the economic field of the conceptions of the his- torical school of jurisprudence of which Savigny was the most eminent representative. The juristic system is not a fixed social phenomenon, but is variable from one stage in the progress of society to another ; it is in vital relation with the other coexistent social factors ; and what is, in the jural sphere, adapted to one period of development, is often unfit for another. These ideas were seen to be applicable to the THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 201 economic system also; the relative point of view was thus reached, and the absolute attitude was found to be untenable. Cosmopolitanism in theory, or the assumption of a system equally true of every country, and what has been called per- petualism, or the assumption of a system applicable to every social stage, were alike discredited. And so the German historical school appears to have taken its rise. Omitting preparatory indications and undeveloped germs of doctrine, we must trace the origin of the school to Wilhelm Roscher. Its fundamental principles are stated, though with some hesitation, and with an unfortunate contrast of the his- torical with the " philosophical " method, 1 in his Grundriss zu Vorlemngen uber die Staatswirthschaft nach geschiclitlicher Methods (1843). The following are the leading heads in- sisted on in the preface to that work. "The historical method exhibits itself not merely in the external form of a treatment of phenomena according to their chronological succession, but in the following fundamental ideas, (i.) The aim is to represent what nations have thought, willed, and discovered in the economic field, what they have striven after and attained, and why they have attained it. (2.) A people is not merely the mass of individuals now living ; it will not suffice to observe contemporary facts. (3.) All the peoples of whom we can learn anything must be studied and compared from the economic point of view, especially the ancient peoples, whose development lies before us in its totality. (4.) We must not simply praise or blame economic institutions ; few of them have been salutary or detrimental to all peoples and at all stages of culture ; rather it is a principal task of science to show how and why, out of what was once reasonable and beneficent, the unwise and inexpedient has often gradually arisen." Of the principles enunciated in this paraphrase of Reseller's words a portion 1 This phraseology was probably borrowed from the controversy on the method of jurisprudence between Thibaut on the one band and Suvigny and Hugo on the other. 202 POLITICAL ECONOMY. of the third alone seems open to objection ; the economy ol ancient peoples is not a more important subject of study than that of the moderns; indeed, the question of the relative im- portance of the two is one that ought not to be raised. For the essential condition of all sound sociological inquiry is the comparative consideration of the entire series of the most complete evolution known to history that, namely, of the group of nations forming what is known as the Occidental Commonwealth, or, more briefly, "the West." The reasons for choosing this social series, and for provisionally restricting our studies almost altogether to it, have been stated with unanswerable force by Comte in the Philosophic Positive. Greece and Rome are, indeed, elements in the series ; but it is the development as a whole, not any special portions of it, that Sociology must keep in view in order to determine the laws of the movement, just as, in the study of biological evolution, no one stage of an organism can be considered as of preponderating importance, the entire succession of changes being the object of research. Of Roscher's further eminent services we shall speak hereafter ; he is now mentioned only in relation to the origin of the new school. In 1848 Bruno Hildebrand published the first volume of a work, which, though he lived for many years after (d. 1878), he never continued, entitled Die NationaloTconomie der Gegen- wart und Zukunft. Hildebrand was a thinker of a really high order; it may be doubted whether amongst German economists there has been any endowed with a more profound and searching intellect. He is quite free from the wordiness and obscurity which too often characterise German writers, and traces broad outlines with a sure and powerful hand. His book contains a masterly criticism of the economic systems which preceded, or belonged to, his time, including those of Smith, Miiller, List, and the socialists. But it is interesting to us at present mainly from the general position he takes up, and his conception of the real nature of political economy. The object of his work, he tells us, is to open a way in the THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 203 economic domain to a thorough historical direction and method, and to transform the science into a doctrine of the laws of the economic development of nations. It is interesting to observe that the type which he sets before him in his proposed reform of political economy is not that of historical jurisprudence, but of the science of language as it has been reconstructed in the present century, a selection which indicates the compara- tive method as the one which he considered appropriate. In both sciences we have the presence of an ordered variation in time, and the consequent substitution of the relative for the absolute. In 1853 appeared the work of Karl Knies, entitled Die Politische Oekonomie vom Standpunkte der geschichtliclien Methods. This is an elaborate exposition and defence of the historical method in its application to economic science, and is the most systematic and complete manifesto of the new school, at least on the logical side. The fundamental propositions are that the economic constitution of society at any epoch on the one hand, and on the other the contemporary theoretic conception of economic science, are results of a definite his- torical development; that they are both in vital connection with the whole social organism of the period, having grown up along with it and under the same conditions of time, place, and nationality ; that the economic system must therefore be regarded as passing through a series of phases correlative with the successive stages of civilisation, and can at no point of this movement be considered to have attained an entirely definitive form; that no more the present than,any previous economic organisation of society is to be regarded as absolutely good and right, but only as a phase in a continuous historical evolution ; and that in like manner the now prevalent economic doctrine is not to be viewed as complete and final, but only as representing a certain stage in the unfolding or progressive manifestation of the truth. The theme of the book is handled with, perhaps, an undue degree of expansion and detail. The author exhibits much *>4 POLITICAL ECONOMY. sagacity as well as learning, and criticises effectively the errors, inconsistencies, and exaggerations of his predecessors. But in characterising and vindicating the historical method he has added nothing to Comte. A second edition of his treatise was published in 1883, and in this he makes the singular confes- sion that, when he wrote in 1852, the Philosophic Positive, the six volumes of which had appeared from 1830 to 1842, was entirely unknown to him and, he adds, probably to all German economists. This is not to the credit of their open- mindedness or literary vigilance, if we remember that Mill was already in correspondence with Comte in 1841, and that his eulogistic notice of him in the Logic appeared in 1843. When, however, Knies at a later period examined Comte's work, he was, he tells us, surprised at finding in it so many anticipations of, or "parallelisms" with, his own conclusions. And well he might; for all that is really valuable in his methodology is to be found in Comte, applied on a larger scale, and designed with the broad and commanding power which marks the dii majores of philosophy. There are two points which seem to be open to criticism in the position taken by some German economists of the historical school. i. Knies and some other writers, in maintaining the principle of relativity in economic theory, appear not to preserve the due balance in one particular. The two forms of absolutism in doctrine, cosmopolitanism and what Knies calls perpetualism, he seems to place on exactly the same footing; in other words, he considers- the error of overlooking varieties of local ciicum- stances and nationality to be quite as serious as that of neglect- ing differences in the stage of historical development. But this is certainly not so. In every branch of Sociology the latter is much the graver error, vitiating radically, wherever it is found, the whole of our investigations. If we ignore the fact, or mistake the direction, of the social movement, we are wrong in the most fundamental point of all a point, too, which is involved in every question. But the variations de- THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 205 pending on difference of race, as affecting bodily and mental endowment, or on diversity of external situation, are secondary phenomena only ; they must be postponed in studying the general theory of social development, and taken into account afterwards when we come to examine the modifications in the character of the development arising out of peculiar conditions. And, though the physical nature of a territory is a condition which is likely to operate with special force on economic phe- nomena, it is rather on the technical forms and comparative extension of the several branches of industry that it will act than on the social conduct of each branch, or the co-ordination and relative action of all, which latter are the proper subjects of the inquiries of the economist. 2. Some members of the school appear, in their anxiety to assert the relativity of the science, to fall into the error of denying economic laws altogether; they are at least unwilling to speak of "natural laws" in relation to the economic world. From a too exclusive consideration of law in the inorganic sphere, they regard this phraseology as binding them to the notion of fixity and of an invariable system of practical economy. But, if we turn our attention rather to the organic sciences, which are more kindred to the social, we shall see that the term "natural law" carries with it no such implica- tion. As we have more than once indicated, an essential part of the idea of life is that of development, in other words, of "ordered change." And that such a development takes place in the constitution and working of society in all its elements is a fact which cannot be doubted, and which these writers themselves emphatically assert. That there exist between the several social elements such relations as make the change of one element involve or determine the change of another is equally plain ; and why the name of natural laws should be denied to such constant relations of coexistence and succession it is not easy to see. These laws, being universal, admit of the construction of an abstract theory of economic develop- ment ; whilst a part of the German historical school tends to 206 POLITICAL ECONOMY. substitute for such a theory a mere description of different national economies, introducing prematurely as we hav pointed out the action of special territorial or ethnological conditions, instead of reserving this as the ground of later modifications, in concrete cases, of the primary general laws deduced from a study of the common human evolution. To the three writers above named, Roscher, Hildebrand, and Knies, the foundation of the German historical school of political economy belongs. It does not appear that Roscher in his own subsequent labours has been much under the in- fluence of the method which he has in so many places admir- ably characterised. In his System der Voiles wirthschaft (vol. i., Grundlagen der Nationalokonomie, 1854; 1 6th ed., 1883 : Eng. transl. by J. J. Lalor, 1878; vol. ii., N. 0. des Ackerbaues, 1860; loth ed., 1882 ; vol. iii., N. 0. des Handels und Gewerbfleisses, 4th ed., 1883) the dogmatic and the historical matter are rather juxtaposed than vitally combined. It is true that he has most usefully applied his vast learning to special historical studies, in relation especially to the progress of the science itself. Hia treatise Ueber das Verhdltniss der Nationdldkonomie zum dag- sischen Alterthume (1849), n ^ s ^ur Gtschiclde der Englischen Volkswirthschaftslehre (Leipsic, 1851-2), and, above all, that marvellous monument of erudition and industry, his Geschichte der National-Oekonomik in Deutschland (1874), to which lie is said to have devoted fifteen years of study, are among the most valuable extant works of this kind, though the last by its accumulation of detail is unfitted for general study out- side of Germany itself. Several interesting and useful mono- graphs are collected in his Ansichten der Volkswirtliscliaft vom gescMchtlichen Standpunkte (3d ed., 1878). His systematic treatise, too, above referred to, abounds in historical notices of the rise and development of the several doctrines of the science. But it cannot be alleged that he has done much towards the transformation of political economy which his earliest labours seemed to announce ; and Cossa appears to be right in saying that his dogmatic work has not effected THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 207 any substantial modification of the principles of Hermann and Rau. The historical method has exhibited its essential features more fully in the hands of the younger generation of scientific economists in Germany, amongst whom may be reckoned Lujo Brentano, Adolf Held, Erwin Nasse, Gustav Schmoller, II. Rosier, Albert Schaffle, Hans von Scheel, Gustav Schon- l>erg, and Adolf Wagner. Besides the general principle of an historical treatment of the science, the leading ideas which have been most strongly insisted on by this school are the following. I. The necessity of accentuating the moral element in economic study. This consideration has been urged with special emphasis by Schmoller in his Grundfragen (1875) and by Schaffle in his Das gesellschaftliche System der mensclilichen Wirthschaft ($& ed., 1873). G. Kries (d. 1858) appears also to have handled the subject well in a review of J. S. Mill According to the most advanced organs of the school, three principles of organisation are at work in practical economy ; and, corresponding with these, there are three different systems or spheres of activity. The latter are (i) private economy ; (2) the compulsory public economy ; (3) the " caritative * sphere. In the first alone personal interest predominates ; in the second the general interest of the society ; in the third the benevolent impulses. Even in the first, however, the action of private interest cannot be unlimited ; not to speak here of the intervention of the public power, the excesses and abuses of the fundamental principle in this department must be checked and controlled by an economic morality, which can never be left out of account in theory any more than in practical applications. In the third region above named, moral influences are of course supreme. II. The close relation which necessarily exists between economics and jurisprudence. This has been brought out by L. von Stein and H. Rosier, but ia most systematically established by Wagner who is, without doubt, one of the most eminent of living German economists especially in his Grundleyung, now forming part of th 208 POLITICAL ECONOMY. comprehensive Lehrbuch der politischen Oekonomie published by him and Professor Nasse jointly. The doctrine of the jus naturae, on which the physiocrats, as we have seen, reared their economic structure, has lost its hold on belief, and the old a priori and absolute conceptions of personal freedom and property have given way along with it. It is seen that the economic position of the individual, instead of depending merely on so-called natural rights or even on his natural powers, is conditioned by the contemporary juristic system, which is itself an historical product. The above-named con- ceptions, therefore, half economic half juristic, of freedom and property require a fresh examination. It is principally from this point of view that Wagner approaches economic studies. The point, as he says, on which all turns is the old question of the relation of the individual to the community. Whoever with the older juristic and political philosophy and national economy places the individual in the centre comes necessarily to the untenable results which, in the economic field, the physiocratic and Smithian school of free competition has set up. Wagner on the contrary investigates, before anything else, the conditions of the economic life of the com- munity, and, in subordination to this, determines the sphere of the economic freedom of the individual. IIL A different conception of the functions of the State from that entertained by the school of Smith. The latter school has in general followed the view of Rousseau and Kant that the sole office of the state is the protection of the members of the community from violence and fraud. This doctrine, which was in harmony with those of the jus naturae and the social contract, waa temporarily useful for the demolition of the old economic system with its complicated apparatus of fetters and restric- tions. But it could not stand against a rational historical criticism, and still less against the growing practical demands of modern civilisation. In fact, the abolition of the impolitic and discredited system of European Governments, by bringing to the surface the evils arising from unlimited competition. THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 209 irresistibly demonstrated the necessity of public action accord- ing to new and more enlightened methods. The German historical school recognises the State as not merely an insti- tution for the maintenance of order, but as the organ of the nation for all ends which cannot be adequately effected by voluntary individual effort. Whenever social aims can be attained only or most advantageously through its action, that action is justified. 1 The cases in which it can properly inter- fere must be determined separately on their own merits and in relation to the stage of national development. It ought certainly to promote intellectual and aesthetic culture. It ought to enforce provisions for public health and regulations for the proper conduct of production and transport. It ought to protect the weaker members of society, especially women, children, the aged, and the destitute, at least in the absence of family maintenance and guardianship. It ought to secure the labourer against the worst consequences of personal injury not due to his own negligence, to assist through legal recogni- tion and supervision the efforts of the working classes for joint no less than individual self-help, and to guarantee the safety of their earnings, when intrusted to its care. A special influence which has worked on this more recent group is that of theoretic socialism; we shall see hereafter that socialism as a party organisation has also affected their practical politics. With such writers as St. Simon, Fourier, and Proudhon, Lassalle, Marx, Engels, Mario, and Kodbertus (who, notwithstanding a recent denial, seems rightly described as a socialist) we do not deal in the present treatise ; but we must recognise them as having powerfully stimulated the younger German economists (in the strict sense of this last word). They have even modified the scientific conclusions of the latter, especially through criticism of the so-called orthodox system. Sch'affle and Wagner may be especially named as having given a large space and a respectful attention 1 It will in each case be necessary to examine whether the action can belt be taken by the central, or by the local, government. O 2io POLITICAL ECONOMY. to their arguments. In particular, the important consideration, to which we have already referred, that the economic position of the individual depends on the existing legal system, and notably on the existing organisation of property, was first insisted on by the socialists. They had also pointed out that the present institutions of society in relation to property, in- heritance, contract, and the like, are (to use Lassalle's phrase) "historical categories which have changed, and are subject to further change," whilst in the orthodox economy they are generally assumed as a fixed order of things on the basis of which the individual creates his own position. J. S. Mill, as we have seen, called attention to the fact of the distribution of wealth depending, unlike its production, not on natural laws alone, but on the ordinances of society, but it is some of the German economists of the younger historical school who have most strongly emphasised this view. To rectify and complete the conception, however, we must bear in mind that those ordinances themselves are not arbitrarily change- able, but are conditioned by the stage of general social development. In economic politics these writers have taken up a position between the German free-trade (or, as it is sometimes with questionable propriety called, the Manchester) party and the democratic socialists. The latter invoke the omnipotence of the State to transform radically and immediately the present economic constitution of society in the interest of the pro- letariate. The free-traders seek to minimise state action for any end except that of maintaining public order, and securing the safety and freedom of the individual. The members of the school of which we are now speaking, when intervening in the discussion of practical questions, have occupied an inter- mediate standpoint. They are opposed alike to social revolu- tion and to rigid laisser faire. Whilst rejecting the socialistic programme, they call for the intervention of the State in accordance with the theoretic principles already mentioned, for the purpose of mitigating the pressure of the modern 211 industrial system on its weaker members, and extending in greater measure to the working classes the benefits of advanc- ing civilisation. Schaffle in his Capitalismus und Socidlismus (1870; now absorbed into a larger work), Wagner in his Rede iiber die sociale Frage (1871), and Schdnberg in his Arbeit- sdmter: eine Aufgabe des deutschen Reichs (1871) advocated this policy in relation to the question of the labourer. These expressions of opinion, with which most of the German professors of political economy sympathised, were violently assailed by the organs of the free-trade party, who found in them " a new form of socialism." Out of this arose a lively controversy ; and the necessity of a closer union and a prac- tical political organisation being felt amongst the partisans of the new direction, a congress was held at Eisenach in October 1872, for the consideration of "the social question." It was attended by almost all the professors of economic science in the German universities, by representatives of the several political parties, by leaders of the working men, and by some of the large capitalists. At this meeting the principles above explained were formulated. Those who adopted them obtained from their opponents the appellation of " Katheder-Socialisten," or " socialists of the (professorial) chair," a nickname invented by H. B. Oppenheim, and which those to whom it was applied were not unwilling to accept. Since 1873 ^is g r up has been united in the " Verein fiir Socialpolitik," in which, as the con- troversy became mitigated, free-traders also have taken part. Within the Verein a division has shown itself. The left wing has favoured a systematic gradual modification of the law of property in such a direction as would tend to the fulfilment of the socialistic aspirations, so far as these are legitimate, whilst the majority advocate reform through state action on the basis of existing jural institutions. Schaffle goes so far as to maintain that the present " capitalistic" regime will be replaced by a socialistic organisation ; but, like J. S. Mill, he adjourns this change to a more or less remote future, and expects it as the result of a natural development, or process of " social 212 POLITICAL ECONOMY. election ; " l he repudiates any immediate or violent revolution, and rejects any system of life which would set up " abstract equality " against the claims of individual service and merit. The further the investigations of the German historical school have been carried, in the several lines of inquiry it has opened, the more clearly it has .come to light that the one thing needful is not merely a reform of political economy, but its fusion in a complete science of society. This is the view long since insisted on by Auguste Comte ; and its justness is daily becoming more apparent. The best economists of Germany now tend strongly in this direction. Schaffle, who is largely under the influence of Comte and Herbert Spencer, has actually attempted the enterprise of widening economic into social studies. In his most important work, which had been prepared by previous publications, Ban und Leben des gocialen Korpers (187578; new ed., 1881^, he proposes to give a comprehensive plan of an anatomy, physiology, and psychology of human society. He considers social processes as analogous to those of organic bodies; and, sound and suggestive as the idea of this analogy, already used by Comtt., undoubtedly is, he carries it, perhaps, to an undue degree of detail and elaboration. The same conception is adopted by P. von Lilienfeld in his Gedariken iiber die Socialwissenschaft der Zukunft (1873-79). A tendency to the fusion of economic science in Sociology is also found in Adolph Samter'sSozial-lehre (1875) though the economic aspect of society is there speci- ally studied and in Schmoller's treatise Ueber einige Grund- fragen des Rechts und der Volkswirthschaftslehre (1875) ; and the necessity of such a transformation is energetically asserted by H. von Scheel in the preface to his German version (1879) of an English tract 1 On the present Position and Prospects of Political Economy. 1 This should be remembered by readers of M. Leroy-Beaulieu's work on Collectivism (1884), in which he treats Schaffle as the principal theo- retic representative of that form of socialism. 2 By the present writer ; being an Address to the Section of Economic Science and Statistics of the British Association at its meeting in Dublin in 1878. THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 213 The name "Realistic," which has sometimes been given to the historical school, especially in its more recent form, appears to be injudiciously chosen. It is intended to mark the contrast with the "abstract" complexion of the orthodox economics. But the error of these economics lies, not in the use, but in the abuse of abstraction. All science implies abstraction, seeking, as it does, for unity in variety ; the question in every branch is as to the right constitution of the abstract theory in relation to the concrete facts. Nor is the new school quite correctly distinguished as " inductive." Deduction doubtless unduly preponderates in the investiga- tions of the older economists; but it must be remembered that it is a legitimate process, when it sets out, not from a priori assumptions, but from proved generalisations. And the appropriate method of economics, as of all sociology, is not so much induction as the specialised form of induction known as comparison, especially the comparative study of " social series " (to use Mill's phrase), which is properly desig- nated as the " historical " method. If the denominations here criticised were allowed to prevail, there would be a danger 'of the school assuming an unscientific character. It might occupy itself too exclusively with statistical inquiry, and forget in the detailed examination of particular provinces of economic life the necessity of large philosophic ideas and of a systematic co-ordination of principles. So long as economics remain a separate branch of study, and until they are absorbed into Sociology, the thinkers who follow the new direction will do wisely in retaking their original designation of the his- torical school. The members of this and the other German schools have pro- duced many valuable works besides those which there has been occasion to mention above. Ample notices of their contribu- tions to the several brandies of the science (including its appli- cations) will be found dispersed through Wagner and Nasse's Lehrbuch and the comprehensive Handbuch edited by Schon- berg. The following list, which does not pretend to approach to 214 POLITICAL ECONOMY. completeness, is given for the purpose of directing the student to a certain number of books which ought not to be over- looked in the study of the subjects to which they respectively refer : Knies, Die Eiseribahnen und Hire Wirkunyen (1853), Der Telegraph (1857), Geld und Credit (1873-76-79) ; Rosier, Zur Kritik der Lehre vom Arbeitslohn, (1861) ; Schmoller, Zur Geschichte der deutschen Kleinge- werbe im 19 Jahrh. (1870) ; Schaffle, Theorie der ausschliessenden Absatz- verhdltnisse (1867), Quintesscnz des Socialismus (6th ed., 1878), Grundsatze der Steuerpolitik 1 1 880) ; Nasse, Mittelalterliche Feldgemeinschaft in Engla nd, (1869) ; Brentano, On the History and Development of Gilds, prefixed to Toulmin Smith's English Gilds (1870), Die Arbeitergilden der Gegcnwart (1871-72), Das Arbeitsverhdltniss gemass dem heutiyen Rrcht (1877), Die Arbeitsversicherung gemass der heutigen Wirthschaftsordnung (1879), Der Arbeitsversicherungszwang (1881); Held (born 1844, accidentally drowned in the Lake of Thun, 1880), Die Kinkommensteuer (1872), Die deutsche Arbeiterpresse der Gegenwart (1873), Sozialismus, Sozialdemok- ratie und Sozialpolitik (1878), Grwndriss fur Vorlcswigen iiber National- okonomie (2d ed., 1878) ; Zwei Bilcher zur socialen Geschichte Englands (posthumously published, 1881) ; Von Scheel (born 1839), Die Theorie der socialen Frage (1871), Unsere social-politischen Parteien (1878). To these may be added L. von Stein, Die Verwaltungslehre (1876-79), Lehr- buch der Finanzwissen>ichaft (4th ed., 1878). E. Diihring is the ablest of the few German followers of Carey ; we have already mentioned (Bibl. ' Note) his History of the Science. To the Russian-German school belongs the work of T. von Bernhardi, which is written from the histori- cal point of view, Versuch einer Kritik der Griinde wdche fur grosses und kleines Grundeiyenthum angefiihrt werden 1848. The free-trade school of Germany is recognised as having rendered great practical services in that country, especially by its systematic warfare against antiquated privileges and restrictions. Cobden has furnished the model of its political action, whilst, on the side of theory, it is founded chiefly on Say and Bastiat. The members of this school whose names have been most frequently heard by the English public are those of J. Prince Smith (d. 1874), who may be regarded as having been its head ; H. von Treitschke, author of Der Socialismus und seine Conner, 1875 (directed against the Katheder- Sucialisteu) ; V. Bohmert, who has advocated the participation of work- men in profits (Die Gewinnbetheiligung, 1878)1 A. Emminghaus, author of Das Armenwesen vn Europaischen Staaten, 1870, part of which has been translated in E. B. Eastwick's Poor Relief in Different Parts of Europe, 1873 ; and J. H. Schultze-Delitzsch, well known as the founder of the German popular banks, and a strenuous supporter of the system of " co-operation. " The socialist writers, as has been already mentioned, are THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 215 not included in the present historical survey, nor do we in general notice writings of the economists (properly so called) having relation to the history of socialism or the controversy with it. 1 The movement which created the new school in Germany, with the developments which have grown out of it, have without doubt given to that country at the present time the primacy in economic studies. German influence has been felt in the modification of opinion in other countries most strongly, perhaps, in Italy, and least so in France. In England it has been steadily making way, though retarded by the insular indifference to the currents of foreign thought which has eminently marked our dominant school. Alongside of the influence thus exerted, a general distaste for the " orthodox " system has been spontaneously growing, partly from a sus- picion that its method was unsound, partly from a profound dissatisfaction with the practice it inspired, and the detected hollowness of the policy of mere laisser faire. Hence every- where a mode of thinking and a species of research have shown themselves, and come into favour, which are in harmony with the systematic conceptions of the historical economists. Thus a dualism has established itself in the economic world, a younger school advancing towards predominance, whilst the old school still defends its position, though its adherents tend more and more to modify their attitude and to admit the value of the new lights. ITALY. It is to be regretted that but little is known in England and America of the writings of the recent Italian economists. 1 The most important economic work which has appeared in Germany since the above paragraph was written is undoubtedly the System der Nationaloekonomie of G. Cohn, of which vol. i. (1885) only has yet been published. A movement of reaction in favour of the older school is represented by C. Menger ( Untcrsuchungen ilber die Methode der Social- vnssenschaften, 1883), H. Dietzel (Beitrage zur Methode der Wirthschaftt- wissenchaft, 1884), and E. Sax (Das Wesen und die Aufgabe der National' oekonomie, 1884, and Grundleyung der theoretischenStaatttcirthachaft, 1887)1 216 POLITICAL ECONOMY. Luigi Cossa's Ouida, which was translated at the suggestion of Jevons. 1 has given us some notion of the character and importance of their labours. The urgency of questions of finance in Italy since its political renascence has turned their researches for the most part into practical channels, and they have produced numerous monographs on statistical and ad- ministrative questions. But they have also dealt ahly with the general doctrines of the science. Cossa pronounces Angelo Messedaglia (b. 1820), professor at Padua, to be the foremost of contemporary Italian economists ; he has written on public loans (1850) and on population (1858), and is regarded aa a master of the subjects of money and credit. His pupil Fedele Lampertico (b. 1833) * s author of many writings, among which the most systematic and complete is his Economia del popoli e degli stati (1874-1 884). Marco Minghetti ( 1 8 1 8- 1886), distinguished as a minister, was author, besides other writings, of Economia pubbUca e le sue attinenze colla morale e col diritto (1859). Luigi Luzzati, also known as an able administrator, has by several publications sought to prepare the way for reforms. The Sicilians Vito Cusumano and Giuseppe Kicca Salerno have produced excellent works : the former on the history of political economy in the Middle Ages (1876), and the economic schools of Germany in their rela- tion to the social question (1875); the latter on the theories of capital, wages, and public loans (1877-8-9). G. Toniolo, E. Nazzani, and A. Loria have also ably discussed the theories of rent and profit, as well as some of the most important practical questions of the day. Cossa, to whom we are in- debted for most of these particulars, is himself author of several works which have established for him a high reputa- tion, as his Scienza delle Finanze (1875 ; 4th ed., 1887), an< i his Primi Elementi di Economia Politica (1875; 8th ed., 1888), which latter has been translated into several European languages. 1 Guide to the Study of Political Economy, 1880. See also the Eiblio. graphical matter in his Primi Elementi di E. P., vol. i , 8th ed, 1888. THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 217 Of greater interest than such an imperfect catalogue of writers is the fact of the appearance in Italy of the economic dualism to which we have referred as characterising our time. There also the two schools the old or so-called orthodox and the new or historical with their respective modified forms, are found face to face. Cossa tells us that the instructors of the younger economists in northern Italy were publicly denounced in 1874 as Germanists, socialists, and corrupters of the Italian youth. In reply to this charge Luzzati, Lam- pertico, and Scialoja convoked in Milan the first congress of economists (1875) with the object of proclaiming their resistance to the idea which was sought to be imposed on them " that the science was born and died with Adam Smith and his commentators." M. lmile de Laveleye's interesting Lettres d' Italic (1878-79) throw light on the state of eco- nomic studies in that country in still more recent years. Min- ghetti, presiding at the banquet at which M. de Laveleye was entertained by his Italian brethren, spoke of the "two tendencies " which had manifested themselves, and implied his own inclination to the new views. Carlo Ferraris, a pupil of Wagner, follows the same direction. Formal expositions and defences of the historical method have been produced by Schiattarella (Del metodo in Economia Sociale, 1875) and Cognetti de Martiis (Delle attinenze tra V Economia Socials e la Storia, 1865). A large measure of acceptance has also been given to the historical method in learned and judicious monographs by Ricca Salerno (see especially his essay Del metodo in Econ. Pol., 1878). Luzzati and Forti for some time edited a periodical, the Giornale degli Economisti, which was the organ of the new school, but which, when Cossa wrote, had ceased to appear. Cossa himself, whilst refusing his adhesion to this school on the ground that it reduces political economy to a mere narrative of facts, an observation which, we must be permitted to say, betrays an entire misconception of its true principles, admits that it has been most useful in several ways, and especially as having given the signal for 218 POLITICAL ECONOMY. a salutary, though, as he thinks, an excessive, reaction against the doctrinaire exaggerations of the older theorists. FKANCE. In France the historical school has not made so strong an impression, partly, no doubt, because the extreme doctrines of the Ricardian system never obtained much hold there. It was by his recognition of its freedom from those exaggerations that Jevons was led to declare that " the truth is with the French school," whilst he pronounced our English economists to have been "living in a fool's paradise." National preju- dice may also have contributed to the result referred to, the ordinary Frenchman being at present disposed to ask whether any good thing can come out of Germany. But, as we have shown, the philosophic doctrines on which the whole proceed- ing of the historical school is founded were first enunciated by a great French thinker, to whose splendid services most of his fellow-countrymen are singularly dead. Perhaps another determining cause is to be looked for in official influences, which in France, by their action on the higher education, impede the free movement of independent con- viction, as was seen notably in the temporary e"clat they gave on the wider philosophic stage to the shallow eclecticism of Cousin. The tendency to the historical point of view has appeared in France, as elsewhere ; but it has shown itself not so much in modifying general doctrine as in leading to a more careful study of the economic opinions and institutions of the past. Much useful work has been done by Frenchmen (with whom Belgians may here be associated) in the history of political economy, regarded either as a body of theory or as a system or series of systems of policy. Blanqui's history (1837-38) is not, indeed, entitled to a very high rank, but it was serviceable as a first general draught. That of Villeneuve- Bargemont (1839) was also interesting and useful, ae present* THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 219 ing the Catholic view of the development and tendencies oi the science. C. Perm's Les doctrines economiques depuis un siecle (1880) is written from the same point of view. A number of valuable monographs on particular statesmen or thinkers has also been produced by Frenchmen, as, for example, that of A. Batbie on Turgot (Turgot Philosophe, Economists, et Administrates, 1861); of A. Neymarck on the same statesman (Turgot et ses doctrines, 1885) ; of Pierre Clement on Colbert (Histoire de Colbert et de son Administra- tion, 2d ed., 1875); of H. Baudrillart on Bodin (/. Bodin et son Temps ; Tableau des Theories politiques et des Idees econo- miques au 16* siecle, 1853); of L^once de Lavergne on the physiocrats (Les ficonomistes Francais du 18* sidcle^ 1870). Works, too, of real importance have been produced on parti- cular aspects of the industrial development, as those of L. de Lavergne on the rural economy of France (1857), and of England, Scotland, and Ireland (1854). The treatise of M. de Laveleye, De la Propriety et de ses formes primitives (1874 ; Eng. trans, by G. K. Marriott, 1878), is specially worthy of notice, not merely for its array of facts respecting the early forms of property, but because it co-operates strongly with the tendency of the new school to regard each stage of economic life from the relative point of view, as resulting from an his- toric past, harmonising with the entire body of contemporary social conditions, and bearing in its bosom the germs of a future, predetermined in its essential character, though modifi- able in its secondary dispositions. M. de Laveleye has done much to call attention to the general principles of the historical school, acting in this way most usefully as an interpreter between Germany and France. But he appears in his most recent manifesto (Les Lois natu- relles et lobjet de I'jZconomie Politique, 1883) to separate him- self from the best members of that school, and to fall into positive error, when he refuses to economics the character of a true science (or department of a science) as distinguished from an art, and denies the existence of economic laws or 220 POLITICAL ECONOMY. tendencies independent of individual wills. Such a denial seems to involve that of social laws generally, which is a sin- gularly retrograde attitude for a thinker of our time to take up, and one which cannot be excused since the appearance of the Philosophie Positive. The use of the metaphysical phrase "necessary laws" obscures the question; it suffices to speak of laws which do in fact prevail. M. de Laveleye relies on morals as supplying a parallel case, where we deal, not with natural laws, but with " imperative prescriptions," as if these prescriptions did not imply, as their basis, observed coexist- ences and sequences, and as if there were no such thing as moral evolution. He seems to be as far from the right point of view in one direction as his opponents of the old school in another. All that his arguments have really any tendency to prove is the proposition, undoubtedly a true one, that economic facts cannot be explained by a theory which leaves out of account the other social aspects, arid therefore that our studies and expositions of economic phenomena must be kept in close relation with the conclusions of the larger science of society. We cannot do more than notice in a general way some of the expository treatises of which there has been an almost continuous series from the time of Say downwards, or indeed from the date of Germain Garnier's Abrege des Principes de V Economic Politique (1796). That of Destutt de Tracy forms a portion of his Elements d'Ideologie (1823). Droz brought out especially the relations of economics to morals and of wealth to human happiness (Economie Politique, 1829). Pelle- grino Rossi, an Italian, formed, however, as an economist by studies in Switzerland, professing the science in Paris, and writing in French (Court d' Economic Politique, 1838-54), gave in classic form an exposition of the doctrines of Say, Malthus, and Eicardo. Michel Chevalier (1806-1879), speci- ally known in England by his tract, translated by Cobden, on the fall in the value of gold (La Baisse d?0r, 1858), gives in his Gours d Economie Politique (1845-50) particularly valu- able matter on the most recent industrial phenomena, and THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 221 on money and the production of the precious metals. Henri Baudrillart, author of Lea Rapports de la Morale et de t 'Economic Politique (1860 ; 2d ed., 1883), and of Histoire du Luxe (1878), published in 1857 a Manuel d'J^conomie Politique (3d ed., 1872), which Cossa calls an " admirable compendium." Joseph Gamier (Traite de VBconomie Politique, 1860 ; 8th ed., 1880) in some respects follows Dunoyer. J. G. Courcelle- Seneuil, the translator of J. S. Mill, whom Prof. F. A. Walker calls " perhaps the ablest economist writing in the French language since J. B. Say," besides a Traite theorique et pratique des operations de Banque and Theorie des Enterprises Industrielles (1856), wrote a Traite d' Economic Politique (1858-59; 2d ed., 1867), which is held in much esteem. Finally, the Genevese, Antoine FJise Cherbuliez (d. 1869), was author of what Cossa pronounces to be the best treatise on the science in the French language (Precis de la Science JJlconomique, 1862). L. Walras, in Elements d'^Jconomie Politique pure (1874-77), and Theorie Mathematique de la Richesse Sociale (1883), has followed the example of Cournot n attempting a mathematical treatment of the subject ENGLAND. Sacrificing the strict chronological order of the history of economics to deeper considerations, we have already spoken of Cairnes, describing him as the last original English writer who was an adherent of the old school pure and simple. Both in method and doctrine he was essentially Ricardian ; though professing and really feeling profound respect for Mill, he was disposed to go behind him and attach himself rather to their common master. Mr. Sidgwick is doubtless right in be- lieving that his Leading Principles did much to shake " the unique prestige which Mill's exposition had enjoyed for nearly half a generation," and in this, as in some other ways, Cairnes may have been a dissolving force, and tended towards radical change ; but, if he exercised this influence, he did so uucon- S22 POLITICAL ECONOMY. aciously and involuntarily. Many influences had, however, for some time been silently sapping the foundations of the old system. The students of Comte had seen that its method was an erroneous one. The elevated moral teaching of Carlyle had disgusted the best minds with the low maxims of the Manchester school. Ruskin had not merely protested against the egoistic spirit of the prevalent doctrine, but had pointed to some of its real weaknesses as a scientific theory. 1 It began to be felt, and even its warmest partisans sometimes admitted. that it had done all the work, mainly a destructive one, of which it was capable. Cairnes himself declared that, whilst most educated people believed it doomed to sterility for the future, some energetic minds thought it likely to be a positive obstruction in the way of useful reform. Miss Martineau, who had in earlier life been a thorough Ricardian, came to think that political economy, as it had been elaborated by her contemporaries, was, strictly speaking, no science at all, and must undergo such essential change that future generations would owe little to it beyond the establishment of the exist- ence of general laws in one department of human affairs. 2 The instinctive repugnance of the working classes had continued, in spite of the efforts of their superiors to recommend its lessons to them efforts which were perhaps not unfrequently dictated rather by class interest than by public spirit. All the symptoms boded impending change, but they were visible rather in general literature and in the atmosphere of social opinion than within the economic circle. 3 But when it be- came known that a great movement had taken place, especially in Germany, on new and more hopeful lines, the English econo- mists themselves began to recognise the necessity of a reform 1 The remarkable book Money and Morals, by John Lalor, 1852, wag written partly under the influence of Carlyle. There is a good mono- graph entitled John Ruskin, Economist, by P. Geddes, 1884. 2 See her Autobiography, 2d ed., vol. ii. p. 244. 1 A vigorous attack on the received system was made by David Syme IB his Outlines of an Industrial Science, 1876. THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 223 and even to further its advent. The principal agencies of this kind, in marshalling the way to a renovation of the science, have heen those of Bagehot, Leslie, and Jevong, the first limiting the sphere of the dominant system, while seeking to conserve it within narrower bounds ; the second directly assail- ing it and setting up the new method as the rival and destined successor of the old ; and the third acknowledging the collapse of the hitherto reigning dynasty, proclaiming the necessity of an altered re'gime, and admitting the younger claimant as joint possessor in the future. Thus, in England too, the dualism which exists on the Continent has been established ; and there is reason to expect that here more speedily and decisively than in France or Italy the historical school will displace its an- tagonist. It is certainly in England next after Germany that the preaching of the new views has been most vigorously and effectively begun. Walter Bagehot (1826-1877) was author of an excellent work on the English money market and the circumstance which have determined its peculiar character (Lombard Street 1873 ; 7th ed., 1878), and of several monographs on particular monetary questions, which his practical experience, combined with his scientific habits of thought, eminently fitted him to handle. On the general principles of economics he wrote some highly important essays collected in Economic Studies (edited by K. H. Hutton, 1880), the object of which was to show that the traditional system of political economy the system of Ricardo and J. S. Mill rested on certain funda- mental assumptions, which, instead of being universally true in fact, were only realised within very narrow limits of time and space. Instead of being applicable to all states of society, it holds only in relation to those "in which commerce has largely developed, and where it has taken the form of develop- ment, or something like the form, which it has taken in England." It is "the science of business such as business is in large and trading communities an analysis of the great commerce by which England has become rich." But more 224 POLITICAL ECONOMY. than this it is not ; it will not explain the economic life of earlier times, nor even of other communities in our own time ; and for the latter reason it has remained insular ; it has never been fully accepted in other countries as it has been at home. It is, in fact, a sort of ready reckoner, enabling us to calculate roughly what will happen under given conditions in Lombard Street, on the Stock Exchange, and in the great markets of the world. It is a " convenient series of deductions from assumed axioms which are never quite true, which in many times and countries would be utterly imtrue, but which are sufficiently near to the principal conditions of the modern " English " world to make it useful to consider them by themselves." Mill and Cairnes had already shown that the science they taught was a hypothetic one, in the sense that it dealt not with real but with imaginary men " economic men " who were conceived as simply " money-making animals." But Bagehot went further : he showed what those writers, though they may have indicated, had not clearly brought out, 1 that the world in which these men were supposed to act is also "a very limited and peculiar world." What marks off this special world, he tells us, is the promptness of transfer of capital and labour from one employment to another, as deter- mined by differences in the remuneration of those several employments a promptness about the actual existence of which in the contemporary English world he fluctuates a good deal, but which on the whole he recognises as substantially realised. Bagehot described himself as "the last man of the ante- Mill period," having learned his economics from Ricardo; and the latter writer he appears to have to the end greatly over-estimated. But he lived long enough to gain some know- ledge of the historical method, and with it he had " no quarrej but rather much sympathy." "Rightly conceived," he said, 1 Jones, whose writings were apparently unknown to Bagehot, bad, s we have Been, in some degree anticipated him in this exposition. THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 225 "it is no rival to the abstract method rightly conceived." We will not stop to criticise a second time the term " abstract method " here applied to that of the old school, or to insist on the truth that all science is necessarily abstract, the only question that can arise being as to the just degree of abstraction, or, in general, as to the right constitution of the relation between the abstract and the concrete. It is more apposite to remark that Bagehot's view of the reconciliation of the two methods is quite different from that of most " orthodox " economists. They commonly treat the historical method with a sort of patronising toleration as affording useful exemplifications or illustrations of their theorems. But, according to him, the two methods are applicable in quite different fields. For what he calls the " abstract " method he reserves the narrow, but most immediately interesting, province of modern advanced industrial life, and hands over to the historical the economic phenomena of all the human past and all the rest of the human present. He himself exhibits much capacity for such historical research, and in particular has thrown real light on the less-noticed economic and social effects of the institu- tion of money, and on the creation of capital in the earlier stages of society. But his principal efficacy has been in reducing, by the considerations we have mentioned, still further than his predecessors had done, our conceptions of the work which the a priori metho'dcan do. He in fact dispelled the idea that it can ever supply the branch of general Sociology which deals with wealth. As to the relations of economics to the other sides of Sociology, he holds that the " abstract " science rightly ignores them. It does not consider the differences of human wants, or the social results of their several gratifications, except so far as these affect the pro- duction of wealth. In its view " a pot of beer and a picture a book of religion and a pack of cards are equally worthy of regard." It therefore leaves the ground open for a science which will, on the one hand, study wealth as a social fact in all its successive forms and phases, and, on the other, will p 2*6 POLITICAL ECONOMY. regard it in its true light as an instrument for the conservation and evolution moral as well as material of human societies. Though it will involve a slight digression, it is desirable here to notice a further attenuation of the functions of the deductive method, which is well pointed out in Mr. Sidgwick's recent remarkable work on political economy. He observes that, whilst J. S. Mill declares that the method a priori is the true method of the science, and that " it has been so under- stood and taught by all its most distinguished teachers," he yet himself in the treatment of production followed an in- ductive method (or at least one essentially different from the deductive), obtaining his results by "merely analysing and systematising our common empirical knowledge of the facts of industry." To explain this characteristic inconsistency, Mr. Sidgwick suggests that Mill, in making his general statement as to method, had in contemplation only the statics of distri- bution and exchange. And in this latter field Mr. Sidgwick holds that the a priori method, if it be pursued with caution, if the simplified premises be well devised and the conclusions " modified by a rough conjectural allowance " for the elements omitted in the premises, is not, for the case of a developed industrial society, " essentially false or misleading. " Its con- clusions are hypothetically valid, though "its utility as a means of interpreting and explaining concrete facts depends on its being used with as full a knowledge as possible of the results of observation and induction." We do not think this statement need be objected to, though we should prefer to regard deduction from hypothesis as a useful occasional logical artifice, and, as such, perfectly legitimate in this as in other fields of inquiry, rather than as the main form of method iu any department of economics. Mr. Sidgwick, by his limita- tion of deduction in distributional questions to "a state of things taken as the type to which civilised society generally appioximates," seems to agree with Bagehot that for times and places which do not correspond to this type the historical method must be used a method which, be it observed, does THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 227 not exclude, but positively implies, "reflective analysis" of the facts, and their interpretation from " the motives of human agents " as well as from other determining conditions. In the dynamical study of wealth of the changes in its distribution no less than its production Mr. Sidgwick admits that the method a priori "can occupy but a very subordinate place." We should say that here also, though to a less extent, as a logi- cal artifice it may sometimes be useful, though the hypotheses assumed ought not to be the same that are adapted to a mature industrial stage. But the essential organ must be the historical method, studying comparatively the different phases of social evolution. Connected with the theory of modern industry is one sub- ject which Bagehot treated, though only in an incidental way, much more satisfactorily than his predecessors, namely, the function of the entrepreneur, who in Mill and Cairnes is scarcely recognised except as the owner of capital. It is quite singular how little, in the Leading Principles of the latter, his active co-operation is taken into account. Bagehot objects to the phrase "wages of superintendence," commonly used to express his " reward," as suggesting altogether erroneous ideas of the nature of his work, and well describes the large and varied range of his activity and usefulness, and the rare com- bination of gifts and acquirements which go to make up the perfection of his equipment. It can scarcely be doubted that a foregone conclusion in favour of the system of (so-called) co- operation has sometimes led economists to keep these important considerations in the background. They have been brought into due prominence of late in the treatises of Profs. Marshall and F. A. Walker, who, however, have scarcely made clear, and certainly have not justified, the principle on which the amount of the remuneration of the entrepreneur is determined. We have seen that Jones had in his dogmatic teaching anticipated in some degree the attitude of the new school ; important works had also been produced, notably by Thomas Tooke and William Newmarch (History of Prices, 1838-1857), 2*8 POLITICAL ECONOMY. and by James E. Thorold Kogers (History of Agricultm 5 and Prices in England, 1866-82), l on the course of English econo- mic history. But the first systematic statement by an English writer of the philosophic foundation of the historical method, as the appropriate organ of economic research, is to be found in an essay by T. E. Cliffe Leslie (printed in the Dublin University periodical, Hermathena, 1876 ; since included in his Essays Moral and Political, 1879). This essay was the most important publication on the logical aspect of economic science which had appeared since Mill's essay in his Unsettled Ques- tions ; though Cairnes had expanded and illustrated the views of Mill, he had really added little to their substance. Leslie takes up a position directly opposed to theirs. He criticises with much force and verve the principles and practice of the " orthodox " school. Those who are acquainted with what has been written on this subject by Knies and other Germans will appreciate the freshness and originality of Leslie's treat- ment. He points out the loose and vague character of the principle to which the classical economists profess to trace back all the phenomena with which they deal namely, the "desire of wealth." This phrase really stands for a variety of wants, desires, and sentiments, widely different in their nature and economic effects, and undergoing important changes (as, indeed, the component elements of wealth itself also do) in the several successive stages of the social movement. The truth is that there are many different economic motors, altru- istic as well as egoistic ; and they cannot all be lumped to- gether by such a coarse generalisation. The a priori and purely deductive method cannot yield an explanation of the causes which regulate either the nature or the amount of wealth, nor of the varieties of distribution in different social systems, as, for example, in those of France and England. "The whole economy of every nation is the result of a long evolution in which there has been both continuity and change, i Mr. Rogers has since continued this work, and has also published The First Nine Years f the Bank of England, 1887. THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 229 and of winch the economical side is only a particular aspect. And the laws of which it is the result must be sought in history and the general laws of society and social evolution." The intellectual, moral, legal, political, and economic sides of social progress are indissolubly connected. Thus, juridical facts relating to property, occupation, and trade, thrown up by the social movement, are also economic facts. And, more generally, " the economic condition of English " or any other " society at this day is the outcome of the entire movement which has evolved the political constitution, the structure of the family, the forms of religion, the learned professions, the arts and sciences, the state of agriculture, manufactures, and commerce." To understand existing economic relations we must trace their historical evolution ; and " the philosophical method of political economy must be one which expounds that evolution." This essay was a distinct challenge addressed to the ideas of the old school on method, and, though its conclu- sions have been protested against, the arguments on which they are founded have never been answered. With respect to the dogmatic generalisations of the " ortho- dox" economists, Leslie thought some of them were false, and all of them required careful limitation. Early in his career he had shown the hollowness of the wage-fund theory, though he was not the first to repudiate it. 1 The doctrine of an average rate of wages and an average rate of profits he rejected except under the restrictions stated by Adam Smith, which imply a " simple and almost stationary condition " of the industrial world. He thought the glib assumption of an average rate of wages, as well as of a wage-fund, had done much harm " by hiding the real rates of wages, the real causes which govern them, and the real sources from which wages proceed." The facts, which he laboriously collected, he found 1 That service was due to F. D. Longe (Refutation of the Wage-Fund Theory of Modern Political Economy, 1866). Leslie's treatment of the subject was contained in an article of Fraser't Magazine for July 1868, reprinted as an appendix to his Land-Systems and Industrial Economy of Ireland, England, and Continental Countries, 18701 2jo POLITICAL ECONOMY. to be everywhere against the theory. In every country there is really " a great number of rates ; and the real problem is, What are the causes which produce these different rates?" As to profits, he denies that there are any means of knowing the gains and prospects of all the investments of capital, and declares it to be a mere fiction that any capitalist surveys the whole field. Bagehot, as we saw, gave up the doctrine of a national level of wages and profits except in the peculiar case of an industrial society of the contemporary English type ; Leslie denies it even for such a society. With this doctrine, that of cost of production as determining price collapses, and the principle emerges that it is not cost of production, but demand and supply, on, which domestic, no less than inter- national, values depend, though this formula will require much interpretation before it can be used safely and with advantage. Thus Leslie extends to the whole of the national industry the partial negation of the older dogma introduced by Cairnes through the idea of non-competing groups. He does not, of course, dispute the real operation of cost of pro- duction on price in the limited area within which rates of profit and wages are determinate and known ; but he main- tains that its action oh the large scale is too remote and un- certain to justify our treating it as regulator of price. Now, if this be so, the entire edifice which Kicardo reared on the basis of the identity of cost of production and price, with its apparent but unreal simplicity, symmetry, and completeness, disappears ; and the ground is cleared for the new structure which must take its place. Leslie predicts that, if political economy, under that name, does not bend itself to the task of rearing such a structure, the office will speedily be taken out of its hands by Sociology. Leslie was a successful student of several special economic subjects of agricultural economy, of taxation, of the distribu- tion of the precious metals and the history of prices, and, as has been indicated, of the movements of wages. But it is in relation to the method and fundamental doctrines of the THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 231 science that he did the most important, because the most opportune and needful work. And, though his course was closed too early for the interests of knowledge, and much of what he produced was merely occasional and fragmentary, his services will be found to have been greater than those of many who have left behind them more systematic, elaborate, and pretentious writings. One of the most original of recent English writers on Poli- tical Economy was W. Stanley Jevons (1835-1882). The combination which he presented of a predilection and aptitude for exact statistical inquiry with sagacity and ingenuity in the interpretation of the results was such as might remind us of Petty. He tended strongly to bring economics into close re- lation with physical science. He made a marked impression on the public mind by his attempt to take stock of our re- sources in the article of coal. His -idea of a relation between the recurrences of commercial crises and the period of the sun- spots gave evidence of a fertile and bold scientific imagination, though he cannot be said to have succeeded in establishing such a relation. He was author of an excellent treatise on Money and the Mechanism of Exchange (1875), an( ^ f various essays on currency and finance, which have been collected since his death, and contain vigorous discussions on subjects of this nature, as on bimetallism (with a decided tendency in favour of the single gold standard), and several valuable sug^ gestions, as with respect to the most perfect system of currency, domestic and international, and in particular the extension oi the paper currency in England to smaller amounts. He pro- posed in other writings (collected in Methods of Social Reform, 1883) a variety of measures, only partly economic in their character, directed especially to the elevation of the working classes, one of the most important being in relation to the conditions of the labour of married women in factories. This was one of several instances in which he repudiated the laisser jfaire principle, which indeed, in his book on The State in Relation to Labour (1882), he refuted in the clearest and 232 POLITICAL ECONOMY. most convincing way, without changing the position he had always maintained as an advocate of free trade. Towards the end of his career, which was prematurely terminated, he was more and more throwing off "the incubus of metaphysical ideas and expressions " which still impeded the recognition or confused the appreciation of social facts. He was, in his own words, ever more distinctly coming to the conclusion "that the only hope of attaining a true system of economics is to fling aside, once and for ever, the mazy and preposterous as- sumptions of the Ricardian school." With respect to method, though he declares it to be his aim to " investigate inductively the intricate phenomena of trade and industry," his views had not perhaps assumed a definitive shape. The editor of some of his remains declines to undertake the determination of his exact position with respect to the historical school. The fullest indications we possess on that subject are to be found in a lecture of 1876, On the Future of Political Economy, He saw the importance and necessity in economics of historical investigation, a line of study which he himself was led by native bent to prosecute in some directions. But he scarcely apprehended the full meaning of the historical method, which he erroneously contrasted with the "theoretical," and appa- rently supposed to be concerned only with verifying and illus- trating certain abstract doctrines resting on independent bases. Hence, whilst he declared himself in favour of " thorough re- form and reconstruction," he sought to preserve the a priori mode of proceeding alongside of, and concurrently with, the historical. Political economy, in fact, he thought was breaking up and falling into several, probably into many, different branches of inquiry, prominent amongst which would be the "theory" as it had descended from his best predecessors, especially those of the French school, whilst another would be the " historical study," as it was followed in England by Jones, Kogers, and others, and as it had been proclaimed in general principle by his contemporary Clifle Leslie. This waa on* of those eclectic views which have no permanent validity, THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 233 but are useful in facilitating a transition. The two methods will doubtless for a time coexist, but the historical will inevi- tably supplant its rival. What Jevons meant as the " theory " he wished to treat by mathematical methods (see his Theory of Political Economy, 1871 ; 2ded., 1879). This project had, as we have seen, been entertained and partially carried into effect by others before him, though he unduly multiplies the number of such earlier essays when, for example, he mentions Ricardo and J. S. Mill as writing mathematically because they some- times illustrated the meaning of their propositions by dealing with definite arithmetical quantities. Such illustrations, of which a specimen is supplied by Mill's treatment of the sub- ject of international trade, have really nothing to do with the use of mathematics as an instrument for economic research, or even for the co-ordination of economic truths. We have already, in speaking of Cournot, explained why, as it seems to us, the application of mathematics in the higher sense to economics must necessarily fail, and we do not think that it succeeded in Jevons's hands. His conception of " final utility " is ingenious. But it is no more than a mode of presenting the notion of price in the case of commodities homogeneous in quality and admitting of increase by infinitesimal additions ; and the expectation of being able by means of it to subject economic doctrine to a mathematical method will be found illusory. He offers 1 as the result of a hundred pages of mathematical reasoning what he calls a "curious conclusion," 2 in which " the keystone of the whole theory of exchange and of the principal problems of economics lies." This is the pro- position that "the ratio of exchange of any two commodities will be the reciprocal of the ratio of the final degrees of utility of the quantities of commodity available for consumption after the exchange is completed." Now as long as we remain in the region of the metaphysical entities termed utilities, this theorem is unverifiable and indeed unintelligible, because we 1 Theory of Political Economy, 2d ed., p. 103. ' Fortnightly Review for November 1876, p. 6 If* 234 POLITICAL ECONOMY. have no means of estimating quantitatively the mental impres- sion of final, or any other, utility. But when we translate it into the language of real life, measuring the " utility " of any- thing to a man by what he will give for it, the proposition is at once seen to be a truism. What Jevons calls " final utility '' being simply the price per unit of quantity, the theorem states that, in an act of exchange, the product of the quantity of the commodity given by its price per unit of quantity (estimated in a third article) is the same as the corresponding product for the commodity received a truth so obvious as to require no application of the higher mathematics to discover it. If we cannot look for results more substantial than this, there is not much encouragement to pursue such researches, which will in fact never be anything more than academic playthings, and which involve the very real evil of restoring the " metaphysical ideas and expressions " previously discarded. The reputation of Jevons as an acute and vigorous thinker, inspired with noble popular sympathies, is sufficiently established. But the attempt to represent him, in spite of himself, as a follower and continuator of Kicardo, and as one of the principal authors of the development of economic theory (meaning by " theory " the old a priori doctrine) can only lower him in estimation by placing his services on grounds which will not bear criticism. His name will survive in connection, not with new theoretical constructions, but with his treatment of practical problems, his fresh and lively expositions, and, as we have shown, his energetic tendency to a renovation of economic method. Arnold Toynbee (1852-1883), who left behind him a beautiful memory, filled as he was with the love of truth and an ardent and active zeal for the public good, was author of some fragmentary or unfinished pieces, which yet well deserve attention both for their intrinsic merit and as indicating the present drift of all the highest natures, especially amongst our younger men, in the treatment of .economic questions. 1 He 1 See his Lecturet on the Industrial Revolution in England, with Memoir by the Master of Balliol, 1884 ; ad ed., 1887. THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 235 had a belief in the organising power of democracy which it is not easy to share, and some strange ideas due to youthful enthusiasm, such as, for example, that Mazzini is "the true teacher of our age;" and he fluctuates considerably in his opinion of the Ricardian political economy, in one place declaring it to be a detected " intellectual imposture," whilst elsewhere, apparently under the influence of Bagehot, he speaks of it as having been in recent times " only corrected, re-stated, and put into the proper relation to the science of life," meaning apparently, by this last, general sociology. He saw, however, that our great help in the future must come, as much had already come, from the historical method, to which in his own researches he gave preponderant weight. Its true character, too, he understood better than many even of those who have commended it ; for he perceived that it not merely explains the action of special local or temporary conditions or economic phenomena, but seeks, by comparing the stages o> social development in different countries and times, to " dis- cover laws of universal application." If, as we are told, there exists at Oxford a rising group of men who occupy a position in regard to economic thought substantially identical with that of Toynbee, the fact is one of good omen for the future of the science. AMERICA. For a long time, as we have already observed, little was done by America in the field of Economics. The most obvious explanation of this fact, which holds with respect to philo- sophical studies generally, is the absorption of the energies of the nation in practical pursuits. Further reasons are suggested in two instructive Essays one by Professor Charles F. Dunbar in the North American Review, 1876, the other by Cliffo Leslie in the Fortnightly Review for October 1880. We have already referred to the Report on Manufactures by Alexander Hamilton ; and the memorial drawn up by Albert Gallatin (1832), and presented to Congress from the 236 POLITICAL ECONOMY. Philadelphia Convention in favour of Tariff reform, deserves to be mentioned as an able statement of the arguments against protection. Three editions of the Wealth of Nations appeared in America, in 1789, 1811, and 1818, and Ricardo's principal work was reprinted there in 1819. The treatises of Daniel Raymond (1820), Thomas Cooper (1826), Willard Phillips (1828), Francis Wayland (1837), and Henry Vethake (1838) made known the principles arrived at by Adam Smith and some of his successors. Rae, a Scotchman settled in Canada, pub- lished (1834) a book entitled New Principles of Political Economy, which has been highly praised by J. S. Mill (bk. i. chap. 1 1), especially for its treatment of the causes which deter- mine the accumulation of capital. The principal works which afterwards appeared down to the time of the Civil War were Francis Bo wen's Principles of Political Economy, 1856, after- wards entitled American Political Economy, 1870 ; John Bas- com's Political Economy, 1859 ; and Stephen ColwelFs Ways and Means of Payment, 1859. In the period including and following the war appeared Amasa Walker's Science of Wealth, 1866; 1 8th ed., 1883, and A L. Peny's Elements of Political Economy, 1866. A. Walker and Perry are free-traders ; Perry is a disciple of Bastiat. Of Carey we have" already spoken at some length ; his American followers are E. Peshine Smith (A Manual of Political Economy, 1853), William Elder (Questions of the Day, 1871), and Robert E. Thompson (Social Science, 1875). The name of no American economist stands higher than that of General Francis A. Walker (son of Amasa Walker), author of special works on the Wages Question (1876) and on Money (1878), as well as of an excellent general treatise on Political Economy (1883 ; 2d ed. 1887). The principal works on American economic history are those of A. S. Bolles, entitled Industrial History of Hie United States (1878), and Financial History of the United States, 1774-1885, published in 1879 an( ^ ^ a ^ er years. The deeper and more comprehensive study of the subject which has of late years prevailed in America, added to THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL, 237 influences from abroad, has given rise, there also, to a division of economists into two schools an old and a new similar to those which we have found confronting each other else- where. A meeting was held at Saratoga in September 1885, at which a society was founded, called the American Eco- nomic Association. The object of this movement was to oppose the idea that the field of economic research was closed, and to promote a larger and more fruitful study of economic questions. The same spirit has led to the estab- lishment of the Quarterly Journal of Economics, published at Boston for Harvard University, which promises to do excellent work. The first article in this Journal is by C. F. Dunbar, whose review of a Century of American Poli- tical Economy we have already noticed ; and in this article he sets out, in the interest of conciliation, the tendencies of the two schools. This division of opinion has been manifested in a striking way by a discussion on the method and fundamental princi- ples of Economics, which was conducted in the pages of the periodical entitled Science, and has since been reproduced in a separate form (Science Economic Discussion, New York, 1886). In this controversy the views of the new school were expounded and advocated with great ability. The true nature of economic method, the relativity both of economic institu- tions and of economic thought, arising from their dependence on varying social conditions, the close connection of economic doctrine with contemporary jurisprudence, the necessity of keeping economics in harmony with social ethics, and the importance of a study of consumption (denied by J. S. Mill and others) were all exhibited with remarkable clearness and force. 1 There is every reason to believe with Leslie that 1 The contributors on the side of the new school were Dr. Edwin R. A. Seligman, Professor E. J. James, Professor Richard T. Ely, Henry C. Adams, Richmond Mayo Smith, and Simon N. Patten. The representatives of the old school were Professor Simon Newcoinb, F. W. Taussig, and Arthur T. Hadley. t3 POLITICAL ECONOMY. America will take an active part both in bringing to light the economic problems of the future and in working out their solution. Contemporary English Economists. It is no part of our plan to pass judgment on the works ol contemporary English authors, a judgment which could not in general be final, and which would be subject to the imputa- tion of bias in a greater degree than estimates of living writers in foreign countries. But, for the information of the student, some opinions may be expressed which scarcely any competent person would dispute. The best brief exposition of political economy, substantially in accordance with Mill's treatise, is to be found in Fawcett's Manual (6th ed., 1884). But those who admit in part the claims of the new school will prefer Mr. and Mrs. Marshall's Economics of Industry (2d ed., 1881). Better, in some respects, than either is the Political Economy oi the American writer, Francis A. Walker, to which we have already referred. Other meritorious works are J. E. T Eogers's Manual of Political Economy, 1870; John Macdonell's Sur- vey of Political Economy, 1871 ; and John L. Shad well's System of Political Economy, 1877. Professor W. E. Hearn's Plutology (1864) contains one of the ablest extant treatment? of the subject of production. Mr. Goschen's is the best work on the foreign exchanges (loth ed., 1879). Mr. Macleod, though his general economic scheme has met with no accept- ance, is recognised as supplying much that is useful on the sub- ject of banking. Professor Rogers's Six Centuries of Work and Wages (1884) is the most trustworthy book on the economic history of England during the period with which he deals. W. Cunningham's Growth of English Industry and Commerce (1882) is instructive on the mercantile system. Dr. W. Neilson Hancock has shown in a multitude of papers a most extensive and accurate knowledge of the social economy oi Ireland, THE HISTORICAL SCHOOL. 239 We cannot here overlook a work like that of Mr. Sidgwick (1883), to which we have already referred on a special point. It is impossible not to respect and admire the conscientious and penetrating criticism which he applies to the a priori system of economics in its most mature form. But it is open to question whether the task was wisely undertaken. It cannot be permanently our business to go on amending and limiting the Ricardian doctrines, and asking by what special interpretations of phrases or additional qualifications they may still be admitted as having a certain value. The time for a new construction has arrived ; and it is to this, or at least to the study of its conditions, that competent thinkers with the due scientific preparation should now devote themselves. It is to be feared that Mr. Sidgwick's treatise, instead of, as he hopes, " eliminating unnecessary controversy," will tend to revive the steriles contestations and oiseuses disputes de mots, which Comte censured in the earlier economists. It is in- teresting to observe that the part of the work which is, and has been recognised as, the most valuable is that in which, shaking off the fictions of the old school, he examines inde- pendently by the light of observation and analysis the question of the industrial action of Governments. CHAPTER VII CONCLUSION. LET us briefly consider in conclusion, by the light of the preceding historical survey, what appear to be the steps in the direction of a renovation of economic science which are now at once practicable and urgent. I. Economic investigation has hitherto fallen for the most part into the hands of lawyers and men of letters, not into those of a genuinely scientific class. Nor have its cultivators in general had that sound preparation in the sciences of inorganic and vital nature which is necessary whether as supplying bases of doctrine or as furnishing lessons of method. Their education has usually been of a metaphysical kind. Hence political economy has retained much of the form and spirit which belonged to it in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, instead of advancing with the times, and assuming a truly positive character. It is homogeneous with the school logic, with the abstract unhistorical jurisprudence, with the a priori ethics and politics, and other similar antiquated sys- tems of thought ; and it will be found that those who insist most strongly on the maintenance of its traditional character have derived their habitual mental pabulum from those regions of obsolete speculation. We can thus understand the attitude of true men of science towards this branch of study, which they regard with ill-disguised contempt, and to whose pro- fessors they either refuse or very reluctantly concede a place in theii brotherhood. CONCLUSION. 241 The radical vice of this unscientific character of political economy seems to lie in the too individual and subjective aspect under which it has been treated. Wealth having been conceived as what satisfies desires, the definitely determi liable qualities possessed by some objects of supplying physical energy, and improving the physiological constitution, are left out of account. Everything is gauged by the standard of sub- jective notions and desires. All desires are viewed as equally legitimate, and all that satisfies our desires as equally wealth. Value being regarded as the result of a purely mental appre- ciation, the social value of things in the sense of their objec- tive utility, which is often scientifically measurable, is passed over, and ratio of exchange is exclusively considered. The truth is, that at the bottom of all economic investigation must lie the idea of the destination of wealth for the mainte- nance and evolution of a society. And, if we overlook this, our economics will become a play of logic or a manual for the market, rather than a contribution to social science; whilst wearing an air of completeness, they will be in truth one-sided and superficial. Economic science is something far larger than the Catallactics to which some have wished to reduce it. A special merit of the physiocrats seems to have lain in their vague perception of the close relation of their study to that of external nature ; and, so far, we must recur to their point of view, basing our economics on physics and biology as developed in our own time. 1 Further, the science must be cleared of all the theologico-metaphysical elements or tendencies which still encumber and deform it Teleology and optimism on the one hand, and the jargon of "natural liberty" and "indefeasible rights" on the other, must be finally abandoned. Nor can we assume as universal premises, from which economic truths can be deductively derived, the convenient 1 This aspect of the subject has been ably treated in papers contributed to the Proceedings of the Royal Society of Edinburgh on several occasions during and since 1881 by Mr. P. Geddes, well known as a biologist. 142 POLITICAL ECONOMY. formulas which have been habitually employed, such as that all men desire wealth and dislike exertion. These vague propositions, which profess to anticipate and supersede social experience, and which necessarily introduce the absolute where relativity should reign, must be laid aside. The laws of wealth (to reverse a phrase of Buckle's) must be inferred from the facts of wealth, not from the postulate of human selfish- ness. We must bend ourselves to a serious direct study of the way in which society has actually addressed itself and now addresses itself to its own conservation and evolution through the supply of its material wants. What organs it has developed for this purpose, how they operate, how they are affected by the medium in which they act and by the coexistent organs directed to other ends, how in their turn they react on those latter, how they and their functions are progressively modi- fied in process of time these problems, whether statical or dynamical, are all questions of fact, as capable of being studied through observation and history as the nature and progress of human language or religion, or any other group of social phenomena Such study will of course require a continued " reflective analysis " of the results of observation ; and, whilst eliminating all premature assumptions, we shall use ascertained truths respecting human nature as guides in the inquiry and aids towards the interpretation of facts. And the employment of deliberately instituted hypotheses will be legitimate, but only as an occasional logical artifice. II. Economics must be constantly regarded as forming only one department of the larger science of Sociology, in vital connection with its other departments, and with the moral syn thesis which is the crown of the whole intellectual system. We have already sufficiently explained the philosophical grounds for the conclusion that the economic phenomena of society cannot be isolated, except provisionally, from the rest, that, in fact, all the primary social elements should be habi- tually regarded with respect to their mutual dependence and reciprocal actions. Especially must we keep in view the high CONCLUSION. 343 moral issues to which the economic movement is subservient, and in the absence of which it could never in any great degree attract the interest or fix the attention either of eminent thinkers or of right-minded men. The individual point of view will have to be subordinated to the social ; each agent will have to be regarded as an organ of the society to which he belongs and of the larger society of the race. The con- sideration of interests, as George Eliot has well said, must give place to that of functions. The old doctrine of right, which lay at the basis of the system of " natural liberty," has done its temporary work ; a doctrine of duty will have to be substituted, fixing on positive grounds the nature of the social co-operation of each class and each member of the community, and the rules which must regulate its just and beneficial exercise. Turning now from the question of the theoretic constitu- tion of economics, and viewing the science with respect to its influence on public policy, we need not at the present day waste words in repudiating the idea that "non-government" in the economic sphere is the normal order of things. The laisser faire doctrine, coming down to us from the system of natural liberty, was long the great watchword of economic orthodoxy. It had a special acceptance and persistence in England in consequence of the political struggle for the repeal of the corn laws, which made economic discussion in this country turn almost altogether on free trade a state of things which was continued by the effort to procure a modifi- cation of the protective policy of foreign nations. But it has now for some time lost the sacrosanct character with which it was formerly invested. This is a result not so much of scientific thought as of the pressure of practical needs a cause which has modified the successive forms of economic opinion more than theorists are willing to acknowledge. Social exi- gencies will force the hands of statesmen, whatever their attachment to abstract formulas ; and politicians have practi- cally turned their backs on laisser faire. The State has with 244 POLITICAL ECONOMY. excellent effect proceeded a considerable way in the direction of controlling, for ends of social equity or public utility, the operations of individual interest. The economists themselves have for the most part been converted on the question; amongst theorists Mr. Herbert Spencer finds himself almost a vox clamantie in deserto in protesting against what he calls the " new slavery " of Governmental interference. He will protest in vain, so far as he seeks to rehabilitate the old absolute doctrine of the economic passivity of the State. But it is certainly possible that even by virtue of the force of the reaction against that doctrine there may be an excessive or precipitate tendency in the opposite direction. With the course of production or exchange considered in itself there will probably be in England little disposition to meddle. But the dangers and inconveniences which arise from the unsettled condition of the world of labour will doubtless from time to time here, as elsewhere, prompt to premature attempts at regulation. Apart, however, from the removal of evils which threaten the public peace, and from temporary palliations to ease off social pressure, the right policy of the State in this sphere will for the present be one of abstention. It is indeed certain that industrial society will not permanently remain without a systematic organisa- tion. The mere conflict of private interests will never pro- duce a well-ordered commonwealth of labour. Freiheit ist keine Losung. Freedom is for society, as for the individual, the necessary condition precedent of the solution of practical problems, both as allowing natural forces to develop themselves and as exhibiting their spontaneous tendencies ; but it is not in itself the solution. Whilst, however, an organisation of the industrial world may with certainty be expected to arise in process of time, it would be a great error to attempt to improvise one. We are now in a period of transition. Our ruling powers have still an equivocal character ; they are not in real harmony with industrial life, and are in all respects imperfectly imbued with the modern spirit. Besides, the CONCLUSION. 245 conditions of the new order are not yet sufficiently understood. The institutions of the future must be founded on sentiments and habits, and these must be the slow growth of thought and experience. The solution, indeed, must be at all times largely a moral one ; it is the spiritual rather than the tem- poral power that is the natural agency for redressing or mitigating most of the evils associated with industrial life. 1 In fact, if there is a tendency and we may admit that such a tendency is real or imminent to push the State towards an extension of the normal limits of its action for the maintenance of social equity, this is doubtless in some measure due to the fact that the growing dissidence on religious questions in the most advanced communities has weakened the authority of the Churches, and deprived their influence of social universality. What is now most urgent is not legislative interference on any large scale with the industrial relations, but the formation, in both the higher and lower regions of the industrial world, of profound convictions as to social duties, and some more effective mode than at present exists of diffusing, maintaining, and applying those convictions. This is a subject into which we cannot enter here. But it may at least be said that the only parties in contemporary public life which seem rightly to conceive or adequately to appreciate the necessities of the situation are those that aim, on the one hand, at the restora- tion of the old spiritual power, or, on the other, at the forma- tion of a new one. And this leads to the conclusion that there is one sort of Governmental interference which the advocates of laisaer faire have not always discountenanced, and which yet, more than any other, tends to prevent the gradual and peaceful rise of a new industrial and social 1 The neglect of this consideration, and the consequent undue exalta- tion of State action, which, though quite legitimate, is altogether in- sufficient, appears to be the principal danger to which the contemporary German school of economists is exposed. When Schmoller says, " The State is the grandest existing ethical institution for the education of the human race," he transfers to it the functions of the Church. The educa- tional action of the State must be, in the main, only indirect. 246 POLITICAL ECONOMY. system, namely, the interference with spiritual liberty by setting up official types of philosophical doctrine, and imposing restrictions on the expression and discussion of opinions. It will be seen that our principal conclusion respecting economic action harmonises with that relating to the theoretic study of economic phenomena. For, as we held that the latter could not be successfully pursued except as a duly subordinated branch of the wider science of Sociology, so in practical human affairs we believe that no partial synthesis is possible, but that an economic reorganisation of society implies a universal renovation, intellectual and moral no less than material. The industrial reformation for which western Europe groans and travails, and the advent of which is in- dicated by so many symptoms (though it will come only as the fruit of faithful and sustained effort), will be no isolated fact, but will form part of an applied art of life, modifying our whole environment, affecting our whole culture, and regulating our whole conduct in a word, directing all our resources to the one great end of the conservation and de- velopment of Humanity. INDEX. ANDERSON, 126 Aristotle, 15, zy, aa, 09 B ABB AGE, I^ I Bacon, 47 Baden, Karl Friedrich von, 80 Bagehot, 135, 223-227 Bain, 149, 153 Bandini, 70 Banfield, 141 Bnstahle, 103, 161 Bastiat, 167, 170, 175-180 Batbie, 219 Baudrillart, 219, 221 Beccaria, 71, 73, 74 Belloni, 71 Bentham, no, in Bernbardi, 214 Berkeley, 82 Biauchiui, 184 Blanqui, xiv., 86, 218 Bocoardo, 183 Bodin, 43, 44, 46 Bohmert, von, 214 BoisguUlebert, 57, 59 Bolles, 236 Bonar, 122 Bowen, 236 Brassey, 160 Breutano, 207, 214 Broggia, 71 Buchanan, 109, 129 Buckle, 61, 90, 242 Burke, 190 CAIRNKS, 106, 123, 134, 54-162, 178, 224 Campanella, 46 Campomanes, 78 Canning, 146 Cantillon, 60, 61 Carey, 171-175 Carli, 21, 75 Carlyle, 67, 8a Cato, 20, 22 Chalmers, 121, 141 Charles V., 41 Cherbuliez, 157, 221 Chevalier, 220 Child, 41, 48, 49, 52, 54, 6f Cibrario, 183 Cicero, 19, 20, 22 Clement, 41, 219 Coguetti de Hartiis, 217 Cohn, 215 Coke, 52 Colbert, 41, 42, 57, 63 Colmeiro, xv. Columella, 20, 21, 22 Comte, Auguste, 196-200, and patsim Comte, Charles, 177 Condorcet, 112-114 Copernicus, 46 Coquelin et Guillaumin, xiv. Cossa, xiv., 216. 217 Courcelle-Seneuil, 221 Couruot, 180-182 Cousin, 218 Cromwell, 41 Crumpe, 141 Culpeper, 48, 67 Cunningham, 238 Custodi, xv., 78 Cusumano, 216 DAIRK, xiv., 53 D'Alembert, 66 Dalrymple, 92 Darwin, 121 Daviinzati, 43 Davenant, 49, 67 De Quincey, 136 Diderot, 56, 66, 107 INDEX. Dietzel, axs Digges, 48 Droz, 220 Dub ring, xiv., 22, 214 Dunbar, 235, 237 Dunoyer, 168-170 Dupont de Nemours, 61, 66, 68, 86, 105, 164 Dutot, 60 ElSENHART, xiv. Eliot, George, 243 Elizabeth, Queen, 41 Emerton, no Emminghaus, 214 FAWCETT, 147, 160, 238 Feuelon, 60 Ferguson, 92, 109 Ferrara, 183 Ferraris, 217 Filangieri, 75 Fontenay, 176, 177 Forbonnais, 78 Forti, 217 Fortrey, 48, 52 Foster, 161 Franklin, 76, 81, 115, 170 GALIANI, 46, 69, 72, 73. 75 Garnier, Germain, 162, 22C Gamier, Joseph, 221 Garve, 184 Geddes, 222, 241 Gee, 67 Genovesi, 71, 76, 81 Gentz, 185, 190 Gioja, 183 Gladstone, 146 Godwin, 112, 113 Goethe, 81 . Goschen, 238 Gossen, 180 Gournay, 60, 61, 66, 67 Grimm, 70, 72 HAMILTON, 171 Hancock, 238 Hearn, 238 Held, 135, 207, 214 Henry VIH., 41 Hermann, 185, 186 Hesiod, ii Hildebrand, 107, 202 Hobbes, 51, 54, 61 Huet, 77 Hufeland, 185 Hugo, 201 Hume, 53, 70, 83, 85, 100, roi, 135, 107, 108, 115, 123, 128 Huskisson, 146 Hutcheson, 61 Hutchinson, 141 INTIEHI, 71, 72 JAKOB, von, 185 Jevons, 60, 159, 180, 331-434 Jones, 142-145, 224 Jourdain, 29 Jovellanos, 184 Joyce, no Justi, 80 Justinian, az KAIMES, 92 Kautz, xiv. Knies, 101, 203-205, 914 Kraus, 185 Kries, 207 LA BBDYiRE, 65 Lalor, 222 Lampertico, 216, 217 Lassalle, 210 Lauderdale, no, in, 151 Laughlin, 148 Laveleye, De, 217, 219, 220 Lavergne, 219 Law, 60 Lawson, 142 Leibnitz, 53 Leroy-Beaulieu, 178, 212 Leslie, T. E. Cliffe, 6r, 91, 90, III, 149, 160, 175, 228-231 Lilienfield, 212 List, 171, 175, 176, 191-194 Livy, 19 Locke, 53, 54, 82, 100 Longe, 159, 229 Longtield, 141 Loria, 216 Lotz, 185 Luder, 185 Luzzati, 216, 317 MACAULAT, 149 M'Culloch, xiv., 105, 109, ia6, 13^ 146 INDEX. 249 Macdonell, 938 Macleod, 238 Males troit, 43 Malthus, 76, 78, 1 12-122, 125, 137, 142 Malynes, 48 Marshal], Alfred, in, 227, 238 Marshall, Mary P., 238 Martineau, Harriet, 140, 233 Melon, 60 Menger, 215 Mengotti, 41, 77 Mercier-Lariviere, 68, 69 Merivale, 141 Messediiglia, 216 Meyer, xv. Mill, James, 117, 138, 149 Mill, John Stuart, 146-154, and passim Millar, 92 Minghetti, 216 Mirabeau, 66-68, 76 Misselden, 48 Moser, 81 Montaigne, 44 Montcln etien, 47 Montesquieu, 60, 90-92, I.TX 11=; More, 44 Morellet, 69, 70 Morley, 150 Miiller, 189-191 Mun, 41, 46, 47 NASSB, 207, 208, 914 Nazzani, 216 Nebenius, 185 Neri, 21, 75 Newmarch, 237 Neyraarck, 219 Nicholson, 106, no, 133 North, 52, S3 OPPKNHEIM, an Oresme, 36 Ortes, 77, 81 PAGNINI, 21 Paillottet, 176 Paoletti, 76 Pecchio, xiv., 71, 78 Peel, 140 Perin, 219 Petty, Si, S3, 67 Pitt, no Plato, 12-14, 32, 44 Way fair, iog Pliny, 19, 20 Pollexfen, 48 Price, 115 Prince-Smith, 214 Pulteney, no QUESNAY, 60, 61, 64-67, 70, 88, 105 RAE. 236 Raleigh, 41, 49 Rau, 185 Raynal, 76 Ricanlo, 106, 122-137, J 43 *4S Ricca-Salerno, 216, 217 Ricci, 76 Rinuccini, 72 Robertson, 78 Rogers, 109, 228, 238 Romagnosi, 183 Roscher, xiv., 201, 202, 206, and passim Rosier, 207, 214 Rossi, 220 Rousseau, 20, 56, 6l Ruskiu, 223 SAMTER, 313 Sartorius, 185 Savigny, 200, 201 Say, J. B., 2, 163-165, 189 Sax, 215 Scaruffi, 43 Schiiffle, 207, 209, 211, 212, 214 Sell eel, von, xiv., 207, 212, 214 Schiattarella, 217 Schlozer, 188 Schmalz, 80 Schmoller, 207, 214, 245 Schonberg, xiv., 207, 211, 213 Schulze-Delitzsch, 214 Scialoja, 183 Seneca, 20, 22 Senior, 115, 116, 123, 130, 138-140 Serra, 46 Shad well, 238 Sidgwick, 146, 221, 226, 239 Sismondi, 14, 135, 165-168 Smith, Adam, 87-110, and pauim Soden, 185 Sonnenfels, 81 Spencer, 117, 212 Stafford, 45 Stein, von, 207, 214 Steuart, 81, 86, 87, 115 Stewart^ 105 Stirling, 176 INDEX. Storoh, 188, 189 Syme, 233 TAOITOS, 19 Taylor, 188 Temple, 41, 49 Terray, 69 Thomas Aquinas, St., 29 Thornton, "W. T., 141, 159 Thiinen, von, 185, 186-188 Tooke, 145, 227 Torrens, 140, 146 Townsend, 115, 116 Toy n bee, 234 Tracy, 220 Treitschke, von, 214 Tucker, 53, 86 Turbolo, 43 Twiss, DSTABU, 78 VABBO, ao Vasco, 75 Vauban, 59 Jerri, 73, 74, 75 Villeneuve-Bargemont, iiy. Voltaire, 56, 59, 69, 73 WAGNER, 207-209, 211 Wakefield, 109, 141 Walker, Amasa, 236 Walker, Francis A., 106, 154, Wallace, iia, nc Trr i ** Walras, 221 West, 126, 131 Whately, 141, 173 Whewell, 144 Wolowski, 36 XBNOPHOW, 14 Tooso, 115 cm DID. WORKS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY Published, by THE MACMILLAN COMPANY. BASTABLE (C. F.) Public Finance. By C. F. BASTABLE. Professor of Political Economy at Trinity College, Dublin, 8vo. $4.00. "Is likely to be a standard work. Its literary merit, its divisions and general scope, its comprehensiveness and avoidance of undue regard to the controversies which are only of to-day, are but the secondary though essen- tial features of such a work. The higher qualities of a philosophical and practical method of treatment, and a transparent willingness to adjust the balance of evidence, are not wanting. It will be welcomed by students of political science everywhere, and not a few men more or less prominent in political or municipal life will find instruction and warning in its pages." Scotsman. BLUNTSCHLI (B. H.) The Theory of the State. English Translation by R. Lodge, M. A. Newand cheaper Edition. $3.00. BOHM-BAWERK Capital and Interest. A Critical History of Economical Theory. By EUGEN V. BOHM-BAWERK, Professor of Political Economy in the University of Innsbruck. Trans- lated, with a Preface and Analysis, by WILLIAM SMART, Lecturer on Political Economy in Queen Margaret College, Glasgow. 8vo. $4.00. " We have read the volume with increasing interest from the first page io the last. Although it consists almost wholly of destructive criticism, it is very necessary work. We recall nothing of the kind equal to it. Even though he may not have said the last word on the particular subject of his inquiry, he has said enough to fix his place in the front rank of the world's economists." Evening Post- The Positive Theory of Capital. By ETJGEN V. BOHM- BAWEKK, author of "Capital and Interest," etc. Translated by WILLIAM SMART, Lecturer on Political Economy in Queen Margaret College, Glasgow. 8vo. $4.00. BOISSEVAIN The Monetary Problem. By G. M. BOISSEVAIN. Translated from the French by G. TOWNSEND WARNER, B.A., Fellow of Jesus College, Cambridge. 8vo. $1.00. This essay gained the prize of one hundred pounds offered by Sir H. Meysey Thompson in the interests of bi-metallism. The author is a banker at Amsterdam, having close relations with English commerce ; and his work is likely to have considerable interest for those who are investigating currency problems. BOOTH (CHARLES) A Picture of Pauperism, with some remarks on the Endowment of Old Age. By CHARLES BOOTH. Crown 8vo. $1.25. Life and Labour of the People in London. Vol. I. East Central and South London. 8vo. $1.50. CANNAN (E.) Elementary Political Economy. 16mo. Stiff cover. 25 cents. COSSA (D. L.) Guide to the Study of Political Economy. With Preface by W. Stanley Jevons, F.R.S. $2.60 THE MACMILLAN COMPANY, NEW YORK. WORKS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY. FAWCETT. Works by the late RT. HON. HENRY FAWCETT M.P., F.R.S. Manual of Political Economy. Sixth Edition. Revised, with a Chapter " On State Socialism and Nationalization of the Land," and an Index. 12mo. $2.60. Free-Trade and Protection. An Enquiry into the Causes which have retarded the general adoption of Free Trade since its introduction into England. Sixth Edition. 12mo. $1.26, FAWCETT (Mrs.) Political Economy for Beginners, with Questions. Sixth Edition. 18mo. 75 cents. GIFFEN (R.> The Growth of Capital. By ROBERT GIFFEN. LL.D., F.S.S. Contents : Introduction The Valuation of 1885 The Recent Progress Distribution between England, Scot- land, and Ireland Historical Retrospect Accumulations of Capital in Foreign Countries The Use of National Values. In 1 vol. 8vo. $2.00. "A very valuable contribution to a branch of economic and political knowledge which has hitherto been too much neglected." Saturday Review. " Mr. Giffen's calculations cannot fail to be of the highest value to the politician and the economist." National Observer. Essays in Finance. FIRST SERIES. Fifth Edition, revised. 8vo. $3.00. " It is impossible to read a page of these essays without being struck by the careful and conscientious character of the work displayed in them. We feel that we are dealing with a man who is giving us the fruit of honest labor. Every problem he attacks is fairly considered on everv side." The Times. SECOND SERIES. Third Edition. 8vo. $4.00. The Case Against Bimetallism. 12mo. $2.00. " This book is timely, and the arguments pertinent and conclusive in their bearing on the present condition and drift of our national finances. . . . This able work should be studied by every legislator, or would-be legislator, throughout the United States." Boston Daily Advertiser. "Mr. Giffen is probably the highest living authority on questions rela- ting to currency and finance in general. What he has written on these subjects is in no respect academic but is the result of long familiarity with the practical questions of everyday business and financial methods. Taken throughout, the work is a very valuable contribution to pending controver- sies on the financial questions involved." The Chicago Tribune. GROSS The Gild Merchant. A Contribution to British Municipal History. By CHARLES GROSS, Professor of History, Harvard University. 2 vols. 8vo. $6.00. " These two volumes, in fine, with their apparatus of notes, bibliography, glossary and index form a monograph of the highest value, and exhibit the modern critical study of institutions at its best. Dr. Gross is eminently sober and cautious, he has no vagaries, his position is based on and defended by contemporary documents, and he demands the same vigorous proofs from others." Nation. HORTON (S. Dana) The Silver Pound and England's Monetary Policy since the Restoration. 8vo. $4.00. " A work of original historical investigation, and considering the dryness of the subject to all but experts, written in a style remarkably interesting, and even picturesque, as well as vigorous." -Westminister Review. "The most authoritative book on the subject ever written." Graphic* THE MACMILLAN COMPANY, NEW YORK. WORKS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY. HORTON. Silver in Europe. 12mo. $1.50. " Mr. Morton's name is one that carries with it an amount of authority attaching to but few writers on monetary science." St. Louis Times. HO WELL G. The Conflicts of Capital and Labour. Historically and Economically Considered. Being a History and a Review of the Trade Unions of Great Britain, showing their Origin, Progress, Constitution and Objects in their Varied Poll-, tical. Social, Economical and Industrial Aspects. By GEORGE HOWELL, M.P., author of "The Handy Book of the Labour Laws," etc. 12mo. $2.50. " There is certainly a mass of information within its pages which no one wrestling with the labor problems of to-day can afford to ignore." Christ- ian at Work. " Written with thorough knowledge and striking candor." Chicago Times. "Able and thorough . . . It will be useful and even necessary to all special students of the subject everywhere." Critic. INGRAM ( J. K. A History of Political Economy. With Preface by Prof. E. J. JAMES, Ph.D. 12mo. $1.50. JEVONS. Works by W. STANLEY JEVONS, LL.D., F.R.S. The Theory of Political Economy. Second Edition, with New Preface, etc. 8vo. $2.50. Investigations in Currency and Finance. Edited, with an Introduction, by H. S. FOXWELL, M.A. Illustrated by 20 Diagrams. 8vo. $7.50. The State in Relation to Labour. English Citizen Series. 12mo. $1.00. KE YNES. The Scope and Method of Political Economy. By JOHN NEVILLE KEYNES, M.A. 12mo. $2.25. MARSHALL. Works by ALFRED MARSHALL, M.A., Professor of Political Economy in the University of Cambridge ; Fellow of St. John's College, Cambridge. Principles of Economics. Vol. I., Second Edition, Revised. 8vo. $3.00. " To call it the greatest systematic work since Mill is to speak far within the truth, for the only other book to which it can be compared is "The Wealth of Nations." It gathers and sifts the store of economic knowledge, it reconstructs the whole body of doctrine on broader grounds, and in that new spirit, at once more liberal and more severely scientific, that has charac- terized every department of thought in these later years. . . . His com- prehensiveness and reasonableness broaden every issue he touches." Annals of the American Academy. The Economics of Industry. $1.00. This book, which is practically an abridgment of Prof. Marshall's "Principles of Economics, ' takes the place of a new edition of the " Economics of Industry," already well known as a leading elementary text- book of Political Economy. THE MACMILLAN COMPANY, NEW YORK. WORKS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY. PALGRAVE (R. H. I.) Dictionary of Political Economy. The object of the Dictionary is to give a statement of the posi- tion of Political Economy at the present time, together with such references to history, law and commerce as may be of use both in economic and in general reading. In paper covers, each part, $1.00. To be complete in about twelve parts, issued at intervals of about three months. Now ready, Parts I. -VI. The first volume containing parts one to six, eight hundred pages, can also be supplied, bound in Irish linen. 8vo. $6.50, net. Covers for this volume can also be obtained by those who have purchased the numbers as issued in paper covers and desire to have them bound, at 40 cents, net. PRICE (L. F. R.) Industrial Peace. Its Advantages, Methods, and Difficulties. By L. F. R. PRICE. With a Preface by Prof. A. MARSHALL. 8vo. $1.50. RICARDO. Letters of David Ricardo to Robert Malthus. 1810-1823. Edited by J. BONAR, M.A. 8vo. $2.75. On the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation. Edited by E. C. K. GONNER, M.A. $1.50. SIDGWICK. Works by HENRY SIDGWICK, Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of Cambridge. The Principles of Political Economy. Second Edition, Revised. 8vo. $4.00. The Elements of Politics. 8vo. $4.00. "... But aside from controverted matters, the book is of the high- est merit as containing a profound, exhaustive, and systematic examination of the whole field of politics." - Evening Post, New York. SMART. An Introduction to the Theory of Value. On the lines of Menger, Wieser, and Bohm-Bawerk. By WILLIAM SMART, M.A. 12mo. $1.25. SMITH (ADAM.) The Wealth of Nations. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of. Edited by E. BELFORT BAX. 2 vols. $2.00. A New Edition. With Notes by J. E. THOROLD ROGERS, M.A. 2 vols. 8vo. $5.25. THOMPSON (H. M.) The Theory of Wages and Its Application to the Eight Hours Question and Other Labour Problems. By HERBERT M. THOMPSON, M.A. Cr. 8vo. $1.00. WICKSTEED (P. H.) The Alphabet of Economic Science. Part I. Globe 8vo. 60c. THE MACMILLAN COMPANY, Publishers, 66 Fifth Avenue. New York.