VC 36756 UC-NRLF M7 7Mb On the Philosophy of History ^Address Delivered to the Historical Society University of Glasgow January 8, 1909 By WILLIAM PATON KER, LL.D. Glasgow James MacLehose and Sons Publishers to the University 1909 PRICE ONE SHILLING NETT TO RICHARD LODGE On the Philosophy of History ONE of the stories in the life of Hegel tells how another philosopher asked him to ' deduce his quill pen,' i.e. to prove and justify on metaphysical grounds a particular accidental thing. The problem, it is held, was ridiculous, and showed in the other philosopher a misapprehension of the scope of philosophy. Yet when Hegel deals with history, one is reminded of this frivolous problem, and led to ask whether the Philosophy of History is not the same kind of im- possibility a deduction, a metaphysical proof, of particular contingencies, which are in their nature un- reasonable. The dilemma seems to be obvious. The philosopher in dealing with history may work out a formula of progress or development ; but to do this effectively and clearly must he not neglect the acci- dents and chances of the mortal life which is the matter of history ? Or on the other hand, if he attends to particular accidents, i.e. if he is an historian a reader and interpreter of the drama of history, of the unreasonable fluctuating human temperaments that make the tissue of history he will get into serious 5 265276 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY difficulties \yith his formula. He may be tempted to give it up altogether, to forswear philosophy and become a mere historian. Hegel does not shirk the difficulty, and it would be a mistake a mistake in history, or at any rate in biography to dismiss his work as an abstract a priori construction. He has the dramatic and imaginative interest in character, will and temper, and he makes this plain at the outset in his notes on great men, choosing Alexander, Caesar ' and Napoleon as his instances. No imaginative writer, neither Carlyle in his Heroes nor Mr. Hardy in The Dynasts, has a stronger interest than Hegel in the persons who seem to be in the most extreme contradiction to all abstract and summary formulas of history. The achievements of the men of destiny may indeed be summarised, but that sort of work, however philosophical, is not enough for Hegel. They are the instruments and vehicles of the meaning of the world, but they have an independent meaning and value of their own, besides ; Caesar is Caesar still, something different from his effect in history, and Napoleon is Napoleon, as they are known roughly to common sense, and more thoroughly to the dramatic imagination. This is one of the strong points of Hegel, an essen- tial part of his own character, that everywhere he recognises and appreciates character, in the sense which the word has for the reader of novels and plays, and THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY quite apart from any moralising judgment. What he admires in Dante is the distinct and individual impression made by everyone in the poem, the in- dependence and sufficiency of each character, whatever his place and surroundings may be : like Farinata, thinking meanly of Hell : Come avesse lo inferno in gran dispitto. He does not reduce Shakespeare to a play of ideas, and does not wish to improve him. Ancient Pistol is good enough as he is, and Hegel laughs and applauds. Sometimes one is inclined to think ' how great a critic was in Hegel lost ' : he is so inspiriting in his judgment of character, so sound in his policy towards Romance ; his sane appreciation (like Goethe's) being quite another thing from coldness. But possibly his digressions and escapades of criticism are all the better as they are, being unprofessional and unexpected. Dealing with historical characters, he is at some pains to put the moralist in his right place, and to show the irrelevance of moralising with regard to Alexander, Caesar and Napoleon. He does not want any sermons on the vanity of human wishes ; the preacher with his commonplaces about the pitiful deaths of great men seems to Hegel only to be say- ing : ' Look at me ! Take example by me ! I am not Alexander the Great ; I am not ambitious ; do not be Alexander ! I any not Julius Caesar ; he was AS 7 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY killed in the Capitol ; Brutus killed him ; do not be Caesar ! ' Hegel was a moralist himself, and those remarks of his bring out a great difference, which may be observed elsewhere, between the moralists who judge conduct, and the others who think mainly of char- acter. With the former class the heroes are frequently dismissed as bad men. The second order of judges often seem to be rather antinomian if not anarchical in their sentences. Wordsworth is one of them ; read what he says of Tarn o' Shanter in his Letter to a Friend of Robert Burns, and in the same context his appreciation of the ' clachan yill ' : ' How happily does he lead his reader into that tract of sensations ! * Principal Shairp, with the other standard, makes a different sort of estimate, and is pained by The Jolly Beggars. In the writings of Mr. Holmes, the Police Court Missionary, there is a standard of judgment which is nearer to that of Wordsworth, and which finds an infinite variety in human beings, apart from the record of their vices. Another instance was given me lately by a friend of mine who is both historian and moralist ; the difference of opinion about that wonderful piece of Diderot's which Goethe translated, Le Ne-veu de Rameau. Rameau's nephew is a black- guard musician of genius, without a rag of decent conduct (something like the goliardeis in Piers Plow- man), who is taken by Diderot to confound all THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY respectability and pedantry by the miracle of his lively spirit. The God of the old Comedy has had few more glorious triumphs in modern times. But Lord Morley of Blackburn, who also has translated Ra- meaus Nephew in his Diderot, can hardly endure him, and takes the value of the piece to lie in its exposure of that corrupt world, which (in the words of a classical translator) so soon was to meet * the severe, the very severe chill of a hostile public executioner/ Or, in another figure, to quote exactly : c We see the rotten material which the purifying flame of Jacobin- ism was soon to consume out of the land with fiery swiftness/ History has often been turned into a Mirror for Magistrates, or Gesta Romanorum, a stock of instances, and illustrations with the edifying conclusion : c And this, my friends, ought to teach us ! ' No doubt the study of history has flourished, in a way, through this moral application of it ; the preachers give it a recog- nised and appreciable value. It is not a thing to be scoffed at or condemned ; many a one would be glad to know as much history as Montaigne, to read and remember Plutarch in Plutarch's own spirit; to enjoy, on any terms whatever, such acquaintance with the lives of famous Greeks and Romans as was common in the easy old-fashioned days. But at the same time it can hardly be denied that the moralising use of history, while it may have 9 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY encouraged the study of history in one way, also tended to make it distasteful in another. It is easily degraded into mechanical rhetoric, and those who have used it best Juvenal and Dr. Johnson have seen this most clearly. The moral historian is too closely related to the sophist, the tutor who teaches the art of essay writing with the proper number of heads, the right openings and amplifications. History of this sort is parasitic, with no proper root of its own. One of the most notable events or changes in the eighteenth century was the abandonment of this old-fashioned way in favour of genuine history. We know Dr. Johnson's views. A conversation is re- ported, at dinner in Mr. Cambridge's house at Twickenham, April 18, 1775 : 4 The common remark as to the utility of reading history being made : Johnson. " We must consider how very little real history there is ; I mean real authentic history. That certain kings reigned and certain battles were fought we can depend upon as true, but all the colouring, all the philosophy of history is conjecture." Boswell. " Then, Sir, you would reduce all history to no better than an almanac, a mere chronological series of remarkable events." Mr. Gibbon, who must at that time have been employed upon his history, of which he pub- lished the first volume in the following year, was present, but did not step forth in defence of that 10 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY species of writing. He probably did not like to trust himself with Johnson/ Before this (in the spring of 1772) Johnson had said : ' There is but a shallow stream of thought in history.' BoswelL ' But surely, Sir, an historian has reflection.' Johnson. c Why, yes, Sir, and so has a cat when she catches a mouse for her kitten.' He never desired to hear of the Punic War while he lived. Mrs. Thrale asked him about ' the conver- sation powers ' of one of their acquaintance. ' He talked to me at club one day/ replies our Doctor, 4 concerning Catiline's Conspiracy ; so I withdrew my attention and thought about Tom Thumb/ His use of history in the old-fashioned way is splendidly seen in the well-known passages of The Vanity of Human Wishes ; Wolsey and Charles XII. of Sweden : His fall was destin'd to a barren strand, A petty fortress and a dubious hand ; He left the name at which the world grew pale, To point a moral, or adorn a tale. It is true that there is much more history in Dr. Johnson than is commonly supposed. In spite of his disparaging remarks he was willing to give advice about the reading of history. His depreciation means that he is tired of historical rhetoric and has a better ideal in his mind, and he, himself, is the author of one of the most original historical works in the language A Journey to the Western Islands of Scot- ii THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY land. In ordinary history he felt the want of evi- dence, the uncertainty. See what he says about Robertson : 4 Robertson paints ; but the misfortune is, you are sure he does not know the people whom he paints ; so you cannot suppose a likeness.' But when he gets his chance in the Journey, he shows himself a true historian. His account of the economic and social condition of the Highlands, the change from Status to Contract, from the patriarchal system to competition and the cash nexus, brings to mind the description of a similar change at the beginning of More's Utopia, and anticipates Coleridge's Lay Sermon and Carlyle's Past and Present. This historical work of Johnson, penetrating and illuminating, is carried out in no pretentious form. The method is that of Herodotus ; it is history in the old sense of curious enquiry; it is 'Natural and Civil History,' a subject of which there was formerly a Chair in the University of St. Andrews. Herodotus and Dr. Johnson under- stood history in that comprehensive and miscellaneous way : ' One of the birds that frequent this rock has, as we were told, its body not larger than a duck's, and yet lays eggs as large as those of a goose. This bird is by the inhabitants named a coot. That which is called coot in England is here a cooter.' ' Mr. Boswell caught a cuddy. The cuddy is a fish of which I know not the philosophical name.' 12 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY So Herodotus could leave the World's Debate between Europe and Asia in order to stalk the cro- codile or the phoenix, and take notes about the sources of the Nile. It is pleasant to see how Dr. Johnson in the Journey feels the want of that minute accuracy which in Rasse/as he had treated as unnecessary for the poet : ' The business of a poet,' said Imlac, c is to examine not the individual but the species ; to remark general properties and large appearances : he does not number the streaks of the tulip, or describe the different shades in the verdure of the forest/ But in the Journey the explorer wishes he could remember things more clearly. ' He who has not made the experiment, or who is not accustomed to require rigorous accuracy from himself, will scarcely believe how much a few hours take from certainty of knowledge and distinctness of imagery ; how the succession of objects will be broken, how separate parts will be confused, and how ' many particular features and discriminations will be compressed and conglobated into one gross and general idea/ And it was the despiser of history who wrote the famous passage on historical associations : the patriotism of Marathon, the piety of lona. Johnson's Journey is a proof that the historical instinct and genius may be latent and unsuspected, 13 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY and may be brought out almost accidentally, by the mere impulse of curiosity, the old wanderer's motive, to see new lands and learn the manners of other men. Dr. Johnson's historical raid is a thing that makes the pomp of methodical historians ridiculous. This picture of the meeting of two ages in the Highlands the old traditional clan system and the economics of the nineteenth century is drawn appar- ently by a casual observer untrained in any historical school. But we know Dr. Johnson's own Spanish proverb : ' He who would bring home the wealth of the Indies must carry the wealth of the Indies with him ' ; and we see that he had been storing up all his life for this adventure. Ne fait pas ce tour qui veut. The moral seems to be that history needs no justification, and that Herodotus is never out of date;, the motive of history is that impulse, stronger than prudence, which takes Ulysses and his companions out through the pillars of Hercules : < Our eyes are wakeful only for a little space ; let us win for them a sight of the unpeopled world > South of the Sun.' * 1 O frati, dissi, che per cento milia Perigli siete giunti all' occidente, A questa tanto picciola vigilia De' vostri sensi ch' e del rimanente Non vogliate negar 1' esperienza Diretro al sol del mondo senza gente. Dante, Inf. xxvi. 1 1 2 14 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY If one is to make a fair estimate of Johnson's talent for history, his political essays should not be forgotten, with their scornful insight : ' how is it that we hear the loudest yelps for liberty among the drivers of negroes ? ' And his latest work is historical: the Lives of the Poets. All these things are a long way from the moral application of history, the examples of the vanity of human wishes. But they do not efface the difference between Johnson and Gibbon. Johnson's good sense, his keenness and curiosity, may be turned to history, as we have seen ; but he has not the frame of history as it disclosed itself to Gibbon or to Burke, the idea, more or less vague, of a general continuous life, of historical progress. It is this new fashion of regarding history that makes the second half of the eighteenth century so different from the first. There is an implicit philosophy of history in every modern historian, even when like Gibbon or Macaulay he may seem for the time to have no interest beyond the narrative. At any rate it may be said that the idea of a continuous impersonal life is necessary to the story of the Roman Empire or of England, and this vague conception is on the way to become philosophical ; it calls for philosophical criticism to determine what is implied, in such terms as ' national life ' or the ' spirit of the age/ Historians are naturally inclined to be suspicious 15 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY or unrespectful about the philosophy of history. They regard it as an amateurish and, at the same time, pretentious way of cutting the difficulties. What there is good in it is history ; what is not history in it is superfluous. This opinion is not unreasonable. The short cuts in history are many of them deceptive and unprofitable. Taine 'deduced' the English genius from the English mutton ; and therefore is thought by some to have had a philosophy of history. Hegel is full of historical good things, like his description of the Middle Ages ; but is their goodness beyond the reach of the historian, does it need philosophy ? As in his remarks on heroes, already quoted, Hegel seems often to be working as a man of letters, using imagination and common sense, without any meta- physics at all. In many of his lectures, especially on the Philosophy of Art, he appears to be escaping from metaphysics, and giving his hearers criticism and history ; the results of his reading in the Nibel- ungen or the ballads of the Cid, his impressions of Shakespeare or Cervantes. In this place, I remember how Edward Caird seemed to be glad when he came to the Papacy and the Empire in the notes which, in my time, in the Moral Philosophy Class, followed the lectures on Greek Philosophy and led on to the moderns, Descartes and Spinoza. Those historical notes were a surprise to many of his hearers, a new sort of interest ; and 16 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY I imagine that Hegel also was unscrupulous, and gave his people a good deal of history because he liked it, without trying too hard at every point to insist on the philosophy. The Philosophy of History has the same place in his works as the Critias of Plato, after the Republic and T'imaeus. The Theory of Justice and the Theory of Nature are followed by the story which shows the adventures of Justice in space and time. There are many things besides philosophy in Plato's story of Atlantis, and the same sort of freedom may be allowed to Hegel. One might ask whether Hegel's scheme of history is a thing beyond the reach of ordinary historical method, whether it really needs metaphysics to invent or explain it. The conception of Freedom as the end of all historical progress can be made intelligible without the heavy philosophic apparatus ; and the shifting of the historical centre from Greece to Rome, from the Empire to the modern national state (e.g. Prussia) so far from being new or para- doxical belongs to the oldest type of historical commonplaces, such, for instance, as is explained in Sir David Lyndsay's Monarche, the succession of empires, Chaldee, Persian, Greek and Roman the theory derived from the book of Daniel, which is, as Dr. Driver describes it, ' a religious philosophy of history/ If Prussia, with Hegel, takes the place of the Fifth Monarchy, we may note the fact and 17 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY perhaps draw inferences, without obscuring the like- ness of the younger to the older doctrine. The Philosophy of History may be a work of mixed origin ; partly philosophy and partly the native genius of a great improviser. But there is another set of Hegel's lectures where he proves himself philosopher and historian in one. About the historic value of Hegel's History of Philosophy there can be no question. No one who has read those lectures can ever fall back into the state of mind that was possible before they were delivered. Here is history, ' the record of change ' ; and here the change is a movement of thought under its own laws ; the historical succession is a process of logic. Now if the merely human and temporal relation of Plato and Aristotle, of Spinoza and Leibnitz, can be truly represented in another sphere by the logical sequence of their theories in the history of philosophy, it is at least possible that the much more complex and accidental fabric of ordinary history may be explicable as a process of thought ; and this will be the Philosophy of History. An ideal explanation is not necessarily bad science. Goethe explained the metamorphosis of Plants by reference to a sort of Platonic idea of the absolute plant ; he saw in the light of this idea that the Flower and all the parts of the Flower are modifi- 18 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY cations of the Leaf. I understand that this meta- physical theory is still accepted by positive botanists. And in history the power of ideas is not to be denied merely because it is difficult to explain the operation of large impersonal causes. It is possible, of course, to make large and imposing formulas do the duty of explanation. This easy process of fallacy is not to be encouraged. But it is another thing to say that because the ' Spirit of the Age ' and such branches of learning are sometimes unlawfully invoked, therefore there is to be a law, a statute of Praemunire, against all recourse to ideal explanations. Every age has its own fashion, and this is deter- mined by habits of thought, which can be shown to follow their own law. The movement of the world, the progress of thought from one age to another, may be proved and tested often as thoroughly as the history of individual lives. The histories of literature and art are sometimes depreciated by political historians c poor despised trades,' as the plumber said to the schoolmaster. Those who take Seeley's view now prevalent in the schools that the business of history is politics, will, of course, regard those other histories as at best merely subsidiary ancillary sciences, Hulfswissen- schaften. But as their matter is itself intellectual, so the changes which they record (one would suppose) must be under some laws of intelligence, and if 19 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY the changes of literary or artistic fashion correspond to political changes, then the political changes the matter of ordinary history must be to some extent under the same intellectual law. The history of art the history of literature may be included in it or taken along with it has one great disadvantage which may partly account for the low opinion held of it by most regular historians. The ordinary historian is not so much exposed to be confronted and outfaced by his subject. His subject is all in the past, and much of his matter is only half articulate. But the historian of art is / dealing with things present and alive, and things whose nature it is to be intelligible. Statesmen and generals are past and gone, and cannot resent their treatment by the historian ; but when the historian is talking about Rembrandt and Milton, he can never be quite safe. Rembrandt and Milton may walk in at any moment, and put out his little light. Without attempting to explain them, I mention some things that are made definite by the history of literature, with some bearing on political history. ; The Teutonic ' wandering of the peoples,' the migrations and conquests of Goths, Burgundians, Franks, and Northmen are seen in literature to be accompanied, in the tumult of the Dark Ages and through all the confusion of Greek, Latin, Hebrew and Teutonic elements, by the progress of a distinctly 20 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY Northern type of civilisation, the proof of which is in the scanty remains of old Teutonic poetry so different in their peculiar elaborate art from that which follows in the next great mediaeval period, when the new Latin languages French and Provensal first are the instruments of the ruling fashion in Christendom. The change is about uoo, the time of the first Crusade ; it coincides with a change in the type of the Teutonic languages, from the c Old ' to the c Middle ' stage, so called, and with a general submission of the Teutonic literatures High and Low Dutch, English, Danish to the sway of the Romance dictators. This, and not the classical renaissance, is the beginning of modern poetry ; there is an unbroken succession from the early Proven9al to the first Italian poets, then to Dante and Petrarch, and so to Ariosto, Ronsard and Spenser the new Renaissance ideas taking up and carrying on what had begun before i TOO, before the first extant Proven9al songs. That is a rough summary of part of the literary history which, at least, gives clearness to one's view of the difference between the earlier and the later Middle Ages, and security against the common prejudice of the Renaissance. Without this, the perspective of mediaeval history will go wrong ; for there is little in the political record to bring out that wonderful early Teutonic growth and culmination, that Homeric age of the North. It is through literature, also, that 21 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY the Irish get their proper place in relation to the rest of Europe. More in detail, many things might be brought out by a comparison of literary and political history. One of the most difficult of all periods is the fifteenth century : the Middle Ages were an uncon- scionable time in dying, and the spectacle is tedious. The exhaustion of the Middle Ages is described by Gaston Paris in the introductory part of his little book on Villon ; the emptiness of the classical renaissance is shown in a few pages (Reflexions sur le Quattrocento] by one of his most eminent scholars, Mr. Alfred Jeanroy ; and those two complementary essays, if one takes them together, will not be without their effect on the political history of France and Italy. How much of the history of the world is included in Rabelais, the hope, the freedom of the new age, the ambition, the glory, the triumph of the Will ! and attending on Rabelais, the narrow clear mind of George Buchanan, with his unshaken faith in Latin verse, and at the same time the utter want of chivalry which was one common effect of the classic revival. For it is not every great clerk who is worthy to be admitted to the Abbey of Thelema, where the rule is freedom, and freedom means honour. To take some other examples, does not Mr. Saints- bury's History of Criticism do something to explain the history of the world at large if it were only by 22 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY showing how vast an amount of time and labour has been spent by the human race in the cultivation of formal rhetoric ? And Rutherford's Chapter in the History of Annotation has the same sort of effect, in its anatomy and physiology of the Commentator. The history of ways of thinking not only of philosophy, but of criticism and commentary is a key to political history as well. The great objection to philosophies of history is that they seem to differ little from summaries of his- tory, which may be better made by the historian than the philosopher. On the other hand, summaries well made, like Freeman's General Sketch or Gardiner's outline of English History, may have great philo- sophical value merely because they are synoptic, and keep in view the continuous life of Europe or of England as if it were one person. But the summary, however philosophical, is un- satisfying. It chooses certain things countries and heroes and tendencies and aspects for promotion, and leaves out others. Many things are interesting and important for the historian and the humanities which are not in the main line of march. The most philosophical of modern histories Sars's Norway describes the life of a country which lost its rank among the nations in October 1263. Iceland never was a State at all, in the strict sense of the term. Yet the early history of Norway and Iceland, on 23 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY account of the genius of the people, is valuable out of all proportion to the place of these countries in the political community of Europe. The Orkneys in the twelfth century, just because the story of the Earls (Jar/a Saga, Orkneyinga Saga] was written by some person of spirit and imagination, are still to be seen and understood in a light that seldom falls on any of the more important lands. The other day Mr. Nicholson's Literary History of the Arabs achieved what most people would have thought impossible, capturing readers who understand nothing of Arabic, and making them interested in the lives of writers whom they can never know, and the fortunes of a nation with which they have never been concerned. In ways like these, the historians make their appeal in the name of the humanities against the formula of progress. Progress, whatever it may be, does not refute or disannul what once has been, so long as the historian has a chance of recovering and interpreting it. History is ' the record of change'; it is also something more. It is the province of one of the Muses, and of Mnemosyne, their mother, in whose presence it is not becoming to speak of the utility of history. Discussion of the advantages to be found in noble things is seldom edifying or cheerful. The practical uses of history may be proved, no doubt, but not its true value : For nothing worthy proving can be proven. 24 THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY If ever the philosophy of history were complete, the historian would still be undismayed. There are other things for him to do ; he might perhaps attend to the history of Ireland, which has probably escaped the notice of the philosopher. The justification of history, if it wants any, may be found in the Journey to the Western Islands, and in the last voyage of Ulysses- Considerate la vostra semenza : Fatti non foste a viver come i bruti, Ma per seguir virtute e conoscenza. Adventure is the motive. And if we may judge from the freedom of some of his casual remarks, the adventurers will find Hegel ready to be of their company and to join in all fresh discoveries. He had faith in the real world. THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW AN INITIAL FINE OP 25 CENTS WILL BE ASSESSED FOR FAILURE TO RETURN THIS BOOK ON THE DATE DUE. THE PENALTY WILL INCREASE TO SO CENTS ON THE FOURTH DAY AND TO $1.OO ON THE SEVENTH DAY OVERDUE. 8 13Apr'58A 1 . APR 2 7 '64 -11 LD 21-100m-7, '40 (6936s)