ALL THINGS ARE POSSIBLE ALL THINGS ARE POSSIBLE BY LEO SHESTOV AUTHORISED TRANSLATION BY S. S. KOTELIANSKY WITH A FOREWORD BY D. H. LAWRENCE NEW YORK ROBERT M. McBRlDE ^ CO. 1920 P Cr NOTE Leo Shestov is one of the living Russians. He is about fifty years old. He was born at Kiev, and studied at the university there. His first book appeared in 1898, since which year he has gradually gained an assured position as one of the best critics and essayists in Russia. A hst of his works is as follows : — 1898. Shakespeare and his Critic, Brandes. 1900. Good in the Teaching of Dostoevsky and Nietzsche : Philosophy and Preaching. 1903. Dostoevsky and Nietzsche : The Philosophy of Tragedy. 1905. The Apotheosis of Groundlessness (here trans- lated under the title " All Things are Possible "). 1908. Beginnings and Ends. 1912. Great Vigils. 640383 FOREWORD„ In his paragraph on 7he Russian Spirit, Shestov gives us the real clue to Russian literature. European culture is a rootless thing in the Russians. With us, it is our very blood and bones, the very nerve and root of our psyche. We think in a certain fashion, we feel in a certain fashion, because our whole substance is of this fashion. Our speech and feeling are organically inevitable to us. With the Russians it is different. They have only been inoculated with the virus of European culture and ethic. The virus works in them like a disease. And the inflammation and irritation comes forth as literature. The bubbling and fizzing is almost chemical, not organic. It is an organism seething as it accepts and masters the strange virus. What 7 thg Russian is struggling zvith, crying out against, is not life itself : it is only European culture which has been introduced into his psyche^ and which hurts him. The tragedy is not so much a real soul tragedy, as a surgical one. Russian art, Russian literature after all does not stand on the same footing as European or Greek or Egyptian art. It is not spontaneous utterance. It is not the flowering of a race. It is a surgical outcry, horrifying^ or marvellous, lacerating at first; hut when we get used to it, not really so pro- found, not really ultimate, a Utile extraneous. What is valuable is the evidence against European culture, implied in the novelists^ here at last expressed. Since Peter the Great Russia has been accepting Europe, and seeth- ing Europe down in a curious process of katabolism. Russia has been expressing nothing inherently Russian. Russia's modern Christianity even was not Russian. Her genuine Christianity, Byzantine and Asiatic, is incomprehensible to us. So with her true philosophy. What she has actually uttered 8 is her own unwilling^ fantastic reproduction of European truths. What she has really to utter the coming centuries will hear. For Russia will certainly inherit the future. What we already call the greatness of Russia is only her pre-natal struggling. It seems as if she had at last absorbed and overcome the virus of old Europe. Soon her new, healthy body will begin to act in its own reality, imitative no more, protesting no more, crying no more, but full and sound and lusty in itself. Real Russia is born. She will laugh at us before long. Meanwhile she goes through the last stages of reactio?i against us, kicking away from the old womb of Europe. In Shestov one of the last kicks is given. True, he seems to be only reactionary and destructive. But he can find a little amuse- ment at last in tweaking the European nose, so he is fairly free. European idealism is anathema. But more than this, it is a little comical. We feel the new independence in his new, half-amused indi-fference. He is only tweaking the nose of European 9 idealism. He is preaching nothing : so he protests time and again. He absolutely re- futes any imputation of a central idea. He is so afraid lest it should turn out to he mother hateful hedge-stake of an ideal. " Everything is possible " — this is his really central cry. It is not nihilism. It is only a shaking free of the human psyche from old bonds. The positive central idea is that the human psyche^ or soul, really believes in its elf ^ and in nothing else. Dress this up in a little comely language^ and we have a real new ideal, that will last us for a 7iezv, long epoch. The human soul itself is the source and well-head of creative activity. In the unconscious human soul the creative prompting issues first into the universe. Open the consciousness to this prompting, away with all your old sluice-gates, locks, dams, channels. No ideal on earth is anything more than an obstruction, in the end, to the creative issue of the spontaneous soul. Away with all ideals. Let each individual act spontaneously from the forever-incalculable 10 prompting of the creative well-head within him. There is no universal law. Each being is, at his purest, a law unto himself, single, unique, a Godhead, a fountain from the unknown, 7 his is the ideal which Shestov refuses positively to state, because he is afraid it may prove in the end a trap to catch his own free spirit. So it may. But it is none the less a real, living ideal for the moment, the very salvation. When it becomes ancient, and like the old lion who lay in his cave and whined, devours all its servants, then it can be despatched. Meanwhile it is a really liberating word. Shestov' s style is puzzling at first. Having found the " ands " and " buts " and " be- causes " and " therefores " hampered him, he clips them all off deliberately and even spite- fully, so that his thought is like a ma?i zvith no buttons on his clothes, ludicrously hitching along all undone. One must be amused, not irritated. Where the armholes were a bit tight, Shestov cuts a slit. It is baffling, but II really rather piquant. The real conjunction, the real unification lies in the reader's own amusement, not in the author's unbroken logic. D. H. Lawrence. 12 PART I Zu fragmentarish ist Welt und Lehen. H. Heine. I The obscure streets of life do not oflPer the conveniences of the central thorough- fares : no electric light, no gas, not even a kerosene lamp-bracket. There are no pave- ments : the traveller has to fumble his way in the dark. If he needs a light, he must wait for a thunderbolt, or else, primitive-wise, knock a spark out of a stone. In a glimpse will appear unfamiliar outlines ; and then, what he has taken in he must try to remember, no matter whether the impression v/as right or false. For he will not easily get another light, except he run his head against a wall, and see sparks that way. What can a wretched pedestrian gather under such circumstances ? How can we expect a clear account from him whose curiosity (let us suppose his curi- osity so strong) led him to grope his way among the outskirts of life ? Why should we try to compare his records with those of the travellers through brilliant streets ? 15 2 The law of sequence in natural pheno- mena seems so plausible, so obvious, that one is tempted to look for its origin, not in the realities of actual life, but in the promptings of the human mind. This law of sequence is the most mysterious of all the natural laws. Why so much order ? Why not chaos and disorderliness ? Really, if the hypothesis of sequence had not offered such blatant advantages to the human intelligence, man would never have thought of raising it to the rank of eternal and irrefutable truth. But he saw his opportunity. Thanks to the grand hypo- thesis, man is forewarned and forearmed. Thanks to this master-key, the future is at his mercy. He knows, in order that he may foreknow : savoir pour prhoir. Here, is man, by virtue of one supreme assump- tion, dictator henceforward of all nature. The philosophers have ever bowed the knee to success. So down they went before the newly-invented law of natural sequence, they hailed it with the title of eternal truth. But even this seemed insufficient. Uappetit vient en mangeant. Like the old woman in the fairy-tale about the golden fish, they had it in their minds that the fish should i6 do their errands. But some few people at last could not stand this impudence. Some very few began to object 3 The comfortable settled man says to himself : " How could one live without being sure of the morrow ; how could one sleep without a roof over one's head ? " But misfortune turns him out of house and home. He must perforce sleep under a hedge. He cannot rest, he is full of terrors. There may be wild beasts, fellow-tramps. But in the long run he gets used to it. He will trust himself to chance, live like a tramp, and sleep his sleep in a ditch. 4 A writer, particularly a young and inex- perienced writer, feels himself under an obligation to give his reader the fullest answers to all possible questions. Con- science will not let him shut his eyes to tormenting problems, and so he begins to speak of " first and ultimate things." As he cannot say anything profitable on such subjects — for it is not the business of the young to be profoundly philosophical — he grows excited, he shouts himself to B 17 hoarseness. In the end he is silent from exhaustion. And then, if his words have had any success with the public, he is astonished to find that he has become a prophet. Whereupon, if he be an average sort of person, he is filled with an insatiable desire to preserve his influence till the end of his days. But if he be more sensitive or gifted than usual, he begins to despise the crowd for its vulgar credulity, and himself for having posed in the stupid and disgraceful character of a clown of lofty ideas. 5 How painful it is to read Plato's account of the last conversations of Socrates ! The days, even the hours of the old man are numbered, and yet he talks, talks, talks. . . . Crito comes to him in the early morning and tells him that the sacred ships will shortly return to Athens. And at once Socrates is ready to talk, to argue. ... It is possible, of course, that Plato is not altogether to be trusted. It is said that Socrates observed, of the dialogues already written down by Plato. " How much that youth has belied me ! " But then from all sources we have it, that Socrates spent the month following his verdict in incessant l8 conversations with his pupils and friends. That is what it is to be a beloved master, and to have disciples. You can't even die quietly. . . . The best death is really the one which is considered the worst : to die alone, in a foreign land, in a poor-house, or, as they say, like a dog under a hedge. Then at least one may spend one's last moments honestly, without dissembling or ostentation, preparing oneself for the dread- ful, or wonderful, event. Pascal, as his sister tells us, also talked a great deal before his death, and de Musset cried like a baby. Perhaps Socrates and Pascal talked so much, for fear they should start crying. It is a false shame ! 6 The fact that some ideas, or some series of ideas, are materially unprofitable to mankind cannot serve as a justification for their rejection. Once an idea is there, the gates must be opened to it. For if you close the gates, the thought will force a way in, or, like the fly in the fable, will sneak through unawares. Ideas have no regard for our laws of honour or morality. Take for example realism in literature. At its appearance it aroused universal indigna- 19 tion. Why need we know the dirt of life ? And honestly, there is no need. Realism could give no straightforward justification for itself. But, as it had to come through, it was ready with a lie ; it compared itself to pathology, called itself useful, beneficial, and so obtained a place. We can all see now that realism is not beneficial, but harm- ful, very harmful, and that it has nothing in common with pathology. Nevertheless, it is no longer easy to drive it from its place. The prohibition evaded, there is now the Justus titulus possessionis. 7 Count Tolstoy preached inaction. It seems he had no need. We *' inact '* remarkably. Idleness, just that idleness Tolstoy dreamed of, a free, conscious idling that despises labour, this is one of the chief characteristics of our time. Of course I speak of the higher, cultured classes, the aristocracy of spirit — " We write books, paint pictures, compose symphonies " — But is that labour ? It is only the amusement of idleness. So that Tolstoy is much more to the point when, forgetting his preaching of inaction, he bids us trudge eight hours a day at the tail of the plough. In this there is some 20 sense. Idleness spoils us. We were re- turning to the most primitive of all the states of our forefathers. Like paradisal Adam and Eve, having no need to sweat for our bread, we were trying to pilfer the fruit from the forbidden tree. Truly we received a similar punishment. Divine laws are inscrutable. In Paradise everything is permitted, except curiosity. Even labour is allowed, though it is not obligatory, as it is outside. Tolstoy realised the dangers of the paradisal state. He stooped to talk of inaction for a moment — and then he began to work. Since in regular, smooth, con- stant, rhythmical labour, whether it is efficient or whether it merely appears efficient, like Tolstoy's farming, there is peace of mind. Look at the industrious Germans, who begin and who end their day with a prayer. In Paradise, where there is no labour, and no need for long rest and heavy sleep, all temptations become dangerous. It is a peril to live there. . . . Perhaps present-day people eschew the paradisal state. They prefer work, for where there is no work there is no smoothness, no regularity, no peacefulness, no satisfaction. In Eden, even the well-informed individuals cannot tell what will come next, savoir 21 four prevoir does not answer, and ever- lasting laws are exposed to ridicule. Amongst ourselves also a few of the work-abjurors, the idlers, are beginning to question our established knowledge. But the majority of men, and particularly Germans, still defend a priori judgments, on the ground that without these, perfect knowledge would be impossible, there could be no regulation of the course of natural phenomena, and no looking ahead. 8 To escape from the grasp of contemporary ruling ideas, one should study history. The lives of other men in other lands in other ages teach us to realise that our " eternal laws " and infallible ideas are just abortions. Take a step further, imagine mankind living elsewhere than on this earth, and all our terrestial eternalities lose their charm. 9 We know nothing of the ultimate realities of our existence, nor shall we ever know anything. Let that be agreed. But it does not follow that therefore we must accept some or other dogmatic theory as a modus vivendi, no, not even positivism, 22 which has such a sceptical face on it. It only follows that man is free to change his conception of the universe as often as he changes his boots or his gloves, and that constancy of principle belongs only to one's relationships with other people, in order that they may know where and to what extent they may depend on us. Therefore, on principle man should respect order in the external world and complete chaos in the inner. And for those who find it diffi- cult to bear such a duality, some internal order might also be provided. Only, they should not pride themselves on it, but always remember that it is a sign of their weakness, pettiness, dullness. 10 The Pythagoreans assumed that the sun is motionless and that the earth turns round. What a long time the truth had to wait for recognition ! II In spite of Epicurus and his exasperation we are forced to admit that anything what- soever may result from anything whatso- ever. Which does not mean, however, that a stone ever turned into bread, or that 23 our visible universe was ever " naturallv '* formed from nebulous puffs. But from our own minds and our own experience we can deduce nothing that would serve us as a ground for setting even the smallest limit to nature's own arbitrary behaviour. If whatever happens now had chanced to happen quite differently, it would not, therefore, have seemed any the less natural to us. In other words, although there may be an element of inevitability in our human judgments concerning the natural pheno- mena, we have never been able and prob- ably never shall be able to separate the grain of inevitable from the chaff of acci- dental and casual truth. Moreover, we do not even know which is more essential and important, the inevitable or the casual. Hence we are forced to the conclusion that philosophy must give up her attempt at finding the veriiates aeternae. The business of philosophy is to teach man to live in uncertainty — man who is supremely afraid of uncertainty, and who is forever hiding himself behind this or the other dogma. More briefly, the business of philosophy is not to reassure people, but to upset them. 24 12 When man finds in himself a certain defect, of which he can by no means rid himself, there remains but to accept the so-called failing as a natural quality. The more grave and important the defect, the more urgent is the need to ennoble it. From sublime to ridiculous is only one step, and an ineradicable vice in strong men is always rechristened a virtue. On the whole, there is little to choose between metaphysics and positivism. In each there is the same horizon, but the composition and colouring are different. Positivism chooses grey, colourless paint and ordinary composition ; metaphysics prefers brilliant colouring and complicated design, and always carries the vision away into the infinite ; in which trick it often succeeds, owing to its skill in perspective. But the canvas is impervious, there is no melting through it into " the other world." Never- theless, skilful perspectives are very alluring, so that metaphysicians will still have some- thing to quarrel about with the positivists. iS The task of a writer : to go forward and share his impressions with his reader. In spite of everything to the contrary, he is not obliged to prove anytliing. But, because every step of his progress is dogged by those police agents, morality, science, logic, and so forth, he needs always to have ready some sort of argument with which to frustrate them. There is no necessity to trouble too deeply about the quality of the argumenta- tion. Why fret about being " inwardly right." It is quite enough if the reasoning which comes handiest will succeed in occupy- ing those guardians of the verbal highways whose intention it is to obstruct his passage. The Secret of Poushkin's " inner har- mony." — To Poushkin nothing was hope- less. Nay, he saw hopeful signs in every- thing. It is agreeable to sin, and it is just as delightful to repent. It is good to doubt, but it is still better to believe. It is jolly " with feet shod in steel " to skate the ice, it is pleasant to wander about with gypsies, to pray in church, to quarrel with a friend, to make peace with an enemy, to swoon on waves of harmony, to weep over 26 a passing fancy, to recall the past, to peep into the future. Poushkin could cry hot tears, and he who can weep can hope. " I want to live, so that I may think and suffer," he says ; and it seems as if the word " to suffer," which is so beautiful in the poem, just fell in accidentally, because there was no better rhyme in Russian for " to die." The later verses, which are intended to amplify to think and to su-ffer, prove this. Poushkin might repeat the words of the ancient hero : " danger is dangerous to others, but not to me." There- in lies the secret of his harmonious moods. i6 The well-trodden field of contemporary thought should be dug up. Therefore, on every possible occasion, in season and out, the generally-accepted truths must be ridi- culed to death, and paradoxes uttered in their place. Then we shall see ... What is a Weltanschauung, a world- conception, a philosophy ? As we all know, Turgenev was a realist, and from the first he tried to portray life truthfully. Although we had had no precise exponents of realism, 27 yet after Poushkin it was impossible for a Russian writer to depart too far from actuality. Even those who did not know what to do with *' real life '* had to cope with it as best they could. Hence, in order that the picture of life should not prove too depressing, the writer must provide himself in due season with a philosophy. This philosophy still plays the part of the magic wand in literature, enabling the author to turn anything he likes into anything else. Most of Turgenev's works are curious in respect of philosophy. But most curious is his Diary of a Superfluous Man. Turgenev was the first to introduce the term " a superfluous man " into Russian literature. Since then an endless amount has been written about superfluous people, although up till now nothing important has been added to what was already said fifty years ago. There are superfluous people, plenty of them. But what is to be done with them ? No one knows. There remains only to invent philosophies on their behalf. In 1850 Turgenev, then a young man, thus solved the problem. He ends the Diary — with a humorous postscript, supposed to have been scribbled by an impertinent reader on the last fly-leaf of the MS. 28 7his MS. was ready and contents thereof disapproved^ by Peter Zudotyeshin. MM. MM. Dear Sir, Peter Zudotyeshin, My dear Sir, It is obvious Turgenev felt that after a tragedy must follow a farce, and therein lies the substance of his philosophy. It is also obvious that in this feeling he has the whole of European civilisation behind him. Turgenev was the most educated, the most cultured* of all Russian writers. He spent nearly all his life abroad, and absorbed into himself all that European learning could offer. He knew this, although he never directly admitted it, owing to an exaggerated modesty which sometimes irritates us by Its obviousness. He believed profoundly that only learning, only European science could open men's eyes to life, and explain all that needed explanation. According to this belief he judges even Tolstoy. " The saddest instance of the lack of real freedom," the sixty-year-old Turgenev writes of PFar and Peace^ in his literary memoirs : " the saddest instance of the lack of real freedom, arising from the lack of real knowledge, is revealed to us in Leo Tolstoy's latest work, a work which at the same time, 29 by virtue of its creative^ poetic force, ranks almost first among all that has appeared in Russian literature since 1840. No ! with- out culture, without freedom in the widest sense, freedom within oneself, freedom from preconceived ideas, freedom with regard to one's own nation and history, without this, the real artist is unthinkable ; without this free air he cannot breathe." Listening to Turgenev one might imagine that he had learned some great secret in the West, a secret which gave him the right to bear himself cheerfully and modestly when other people despaired and lost their heads. . . . A year after the writing of the literary memoirs above quoted, Turgenev happened to be present at the execution of the notorious murderer, Tropman. His impressions are superbly rendered in a long article called " Tropman's Execution.'* The description produces a soul-shaking effect upon the reader ; for I think I shall not exaggerate if I say that the essay is one of the best, at least one of the most vigorous of Turgenev's writings. It is true that Tolstoy describes scenes of slaughter with no less vigour, and therefore the reader need not yield too much to the artist's power. Yet when Turgenev relates that, at the decisive moment, when 30 the executioners like spiders on a fly threw themselves on Tropman and bore him to the ground — " the earth quietly swam away from under my feet " — we are forced to believe him. Men respond only faintly to the horrors that take place around them, except at moments, when the savage, crying incongruity and ghastliness of our condition suddenly reveals itself vivid before our eyes, and we are forced to know what we are. Then the ground slides away from under our feet. But not for long. The horror of the sensation of groundless- ness quickly brings man to himself. He must forget everything, he must only get his feet on earth again. In this sense Turgenev proved himself in as risky a state at sixty as he was when, as a young man, he wrote his Diary of a Superfluous Man. The description of Tropman's execution ends with these words : " Who can fail to feel that the question of capital punishment is one of the urgent, immediate problems which modern humanity must settle ? I shall be satisfied ... if my story will provide even a few arguments for those who advocate the abolition, or at least the suppression of the publicity of capital punishments." Again the mountain has 31 brought forth a mouse. After a tragedy, a farce. Philosophy enters into her power, and the earth returns under one's feet. I emphasise and repeat : Turgenev is not alone responsible for his attitude. With his lips speaks the whole of European civilisation. On principle all insoluble problems are rejected. During her thousand years of experience, the old civilisation has acquired the skill which allows her children to derive satisfaction and benefit out of anything, even the blood of their neigh- bour. Even the greatest horrors, even crimes are beneficial, properly construed. Turgenev was, as we know, a soft, " humane " man, an undoubted idealist. In his youth he had been through the Hegelian school. And from Hegel he learned what an enormous value education has, and how supremely important it is for an educated man to have a complete and finished — most certainly a " finished " philosophy. i8 To praise oneself is considered improper, immodest ; to praise one's own sect, one's own philosophy, is considered the highest duty. Even the best writers have taken at 32 least as much trouble to glorify their philo- sophy as to found it, and have always had more success in the former case than in the latter. Their ideas, whether proven or not, are the dearest possession in life to them, in sorrow a consolation, in difficulty a source of counsel. Even death is not terrible to ideas ; they will follow man beyond the grave, they are the only im- perishable riches. All this the philosophers repeat, very eloquently repeat and reiterate concerning their ideas, not less skilfully than advocates plead their cases on behalf of thieves and swindlers. But nobody has ever yet called a philosopher " a hired conscience," though everybody gives the lawyer this nickname. Why this partiality ? Certain savage tribes believe that their kings need no food, neither to eat nor to drink. As a matter of fact, kings eat and drink, and even relish a good mouthful more than ordinary mortals. So, having no desire, even for the sake of form, to abstain too long, they not infrequently interrupt the long-drawn-out religious cere- monies of their tribes, in order to command refreshment for their frail bodies. But c 33 none must witness, or even be aware of this refreshing, and so while he eats the king is hidden within a purple pall. Meta- physicians remind one of these savage kings. They ^/ant everyone to believe that empiricism, which means all reality and substantial existence, is nothing to them, they need only pure ideas for their existence. In order to keep up this fiction, they appear before the world invested in a purple veil of fine words. The crowd knows perfectly well that it is all a take-in, but since it likes shows and bright colours, and since also it has no ambition to appear too knowing, it rarely betrays that it has caught the trick of the comedy. On the contrary, it loves to pretend to be fooled, knowing by instinct that actors always do their best when the audience believes im- plicitly in what happens. Only inexperi- enced youths and children, unaware of the great importance of the conventional atti- tide, now and then cry out in indignation and give the lie to the performance : like the child in Andersen's story, who so unexpectedly and inopportunely broke the general, deliberate illusion by calling out — " But the king is naked.'* Of course every- body knows without telling that the king is 34 naked : that the metaphysicians not only are unable to explain anything, but that hitherto they have not been able to present even a single hypothesis free from contra- diction. It is necessary to pretend to believe that kings eat nothing, that philo- sophers have divined the secrets of the universe, that arbitrary theories are more precious than empirical harvests, and so on. There remains only one difficulty : grown- ups may be won over to the conventional lie, but what about the children ? With them the only remedy is the Pythagorean system of upbringing, so glorified by Hegel. Children must keep silent and not raise their voice until they realise that some things may not be talked about. This is our method. With us pupils remain silent, not only for five years, as the Pythagoreans recommended, but for ten or more — until they have learned to speak like their masters. And then they are granted a freedom which is no longer any good to them. Perhaps they had wings, or might have had them, but they have crawled all their life long in imitation of their masters, so how can they now dream of flight ? To a well-informed man, who has studied much, the very thought of the possibility of tearing 35 himself away from the earth, even for a moment, is horrifying : as if he knew beforehand what the result would be. 20 The best, the most effective way of convincing a reader is to begin one's argu- ment with inoffensive, commonplace asser- tions. When suspicion has been sufficiently lulled, and a certainty has been begot that what follows will be a confirmation of the readers own accepted views — then has the moment arrived to speak one's mind openly, but still in the same easy tone, as if there were no break in the flow of truisms. The logical connection is unimportant. Conse- quence of manner and intonation is much more impressive than consequence of ideas. The thing to do is to go on, in the same suave tone, from uttering a series of banal- ities to expressing a new and dangerous thought, without any break. If you suc- ceed in this, the business is done. The reader will not forget — the new words will plague and torment him until he has accepted them. 36 21 The habit of logical thinking kills imagina- tion. Man is convinced that the only way to truth is through logic, and that any departure from this way leads to error and absurdity. The nearer we approach the ultimate questions of existence, in our departure from logicality, the more deadly becomes the state of error we fall into. The Ariadne ball has become all unwound long ago, and man is at the end of the tether. But he does not know, he holds the end of the thread firmly, and marks time with energy on the same spot, imagining his progress, and little realising the ridiculous situation into which he has fallen. How should he realise, considering the innumer- able precautions he has taken to prevent himself from losing the logical way ? He had better have stayed at home. Once he set out, once he decided to be a Theseus and kill the Minotaur, he should have given himself up, forfeited the old attachment, and been ready never to escape from the labyrinth. True, he would have risked losing Ariadne : and this is why long journeys should be undertaken only after family connections have become a burden. Such being the case, a man deliberately cuts the 37 thread which binds him to hearth and home, 80 that he may have a legitimate excuse to his conscience for not going back. Philo- sophy must have nothing in common with logic ; philosophy is an art which aims at breaking the logical continuity of argument and bringing man out on the shoreless sea of imagination, the fantastic tides where everything is equally possible and im- possible. Certainly it is difficult, given sedentary habits of life, to be a good philo- sopher. The fact that the fate of philosophy has ever lain in the hands of professors can only be explained by the reluctance of the envious gods to give omniscience to mortals. Whilst stay-at-home persons are searching for truth, the apple will stay on the tree. The business must be undertaken by homeless adventurers, born nomads, to whom ubi bene ibi patrta. It seems to me that but for his family and his do- mesticity, Count Tolstoy, who lives to such a ripe old age, might have told us a great many important and interesting things. . . . Or, perhaps, had he not married, like Nietszche he would have gone mad. "If you turn to the right, you will marry, if to the left, you will be killed." A true philosopher never chooses the middle course ; 38 lie needs no riches, he does not know what to do with money. But whether he turns to the right or to the left, nothing pleasant awaits him. 22 Scratch a Russian and you will find a Tartar. Culture is an age-long develop- ment, and sudden grafting of it upon a race rarely succeeds. To us in Russia, civili- sation came suddenly, whilst we were still savages. At once she took upon herself the responsibilities of a tamer of wild animals, first working with decoys and baits, and later, when she felt her power, with threats. We quickly submitted. In a short time we were swallowing in enormous doses those poisons which Europe had been gradually accustoming herself to, gradually assimil- ating through centuries. Thanks to which, the transplanting of civilisation into Russia turns out to be no mild affair. A Russian had only to catch a whiff of European atmosphere, and his head began to swim. He interpreted in his own way, savage-like, whatever he heard of western success. Hearing about railways, agricultural machines, schools, municipalities, his imagi- nation painted miracles : universal happi- ness, boundless freedom, paradise, wings, 39 etc. And the more impossible his dreams, the more eager he was to believe them real. How disillusioned with Europe the westerner Herzen became, after living for years on end abroad ! Yet, with all his acuteness, it did not occur to him that Europe was not in the least to blame for his disillusionment. Europe had dropped miracles ages ago ; she contented herself with ideals. It is we in Russia who will go on confusing miracles with ideals, as if the two were identical, whereas they have nothing to do with each other. As a matter of fact, just because Europe had ceased to believe in miracles, and realised that all human problems resolve down to mere arrangements here on earth, ideas and ideals had been invented. But the Russian bear crept out of his hole and strolled to Europe for the elixir of life, the flying carpet, the seven-leagued shoes, and so on, thinking in all his naivete that railways and electricity were signs which clearly proved that the old nurse never told a lie in her fairy tales. . . . All this happened just at the moment when Europe had finally made away with alchemy and astrology, and started on the positive researches resulting in chemistry and astronomy. 40 ^3 The first assumption of all metaphysics is, that by dialectic development of any concept a whole system can be evolved. Of course the initial concept, the a priori, is generally unsound, so there is no need to mention the deductions. But since it is very difficult in the realm of abstract thought to distinguish a lie from truth, metaphysical systems often have a very convincing appearance. The chief defect only appears incidentally, when the taste for dialectic play becomes blunted in man, as it did in Turgenev towards the end of his life, so that he realises the uselessness of philosophical systems. It is related that a famous mathematician, after hearing a musical symphony to the end, inquired, " What does it prove ? " Of course, it proves nothing, except that the mathema- tician had no taste for music. And to him who has no taste for dialectics, metaphysics can prove nothing, either. Therefore, those who are interested in the success of meta- physics must always encourage the opinion that a taste for dialectics is a high distinction in a man, proving the loftiness of his soul. 41 ^4 Man is used to having convictions, so there we are. We can none of us do with- out our hangers-on, though we despise them at the bottom of our souls. Socrates and Plato tried to determine under the shifting change of appearance the immutable, unchanging reality. In the Platonic " ideas " the attempt was incar- nated. The visible reality, never true to itself, assuming numberless varying forms, this is not the genuine reahty. That which is real must be constant. Hence the ideas of objects are real, and the objects them- selves are fictitious. Thus the root of the Platonic philosophy appears to be a funda- mental defect in human reasoning — a defect regarded as the highest merit. It is difficult for the philosopher to get a good grasp of this agitated, capricious life, and so he decides that it is not life at all, but a fig- ment. Dialectics is supreme only over general concepts — and the general concepts are promoted to an ideal. Since Plato and Socrates, only such philosophers have succeeded largely who have taught that the unchangeable is preferable to the change- 42 able, the eternal to the temporal. The ordinary individual, who lives unconsciously, never reckoning his spiritual credit against his spiritual debit, naturally regards the philosopher as his legitimate book-keeper, keeper of the soul's accounts. Already in Greece the Athenian youth watched with passionate interest the dexterity which Socrates displayed in his endeavour to restore by means of dialectics the lost " ultimate foundations " of human conduct. Now in book-keeping, as we are aware, not a single farthing must disappear untraceably. Socrates was trying to come up to expecta- tions. The balance between man's spiritual assets and liabilities was with him ideally established. Perhaps in this lies the secret of that strange attraction he exerted even over such volatile and unsteady natures as that of Alcibiades, drawing the young men to him so that they were attached to him with all their soul. Alcibiades had long since lost all count of his spiritual estate, and therefore from time to time he had need to recourse to Socrates, who by speeches and dissertations could bring order into chaos and harmony into the spiritual con- fusion of his young friend. Alcibiades turned to Socrates to be relieved. Of 43 course, he sought relief in order that he might begin again his riotous living : rest is so sweet to a tired man. But to conclude that because Alcibiades exhausted himself, and because rest is sweet, therefore all men must rest, this is absurd. Yet Socrates dictated this conclusion, in all his ideas. He wished that all men should rest, rest through eternity, that they should see their highest fulfilment in this resting. It is easier to judge of Socrates since we have Count Tolstoy with us. Probably the physi- ognomist Topir would say of Tolstoy as he said of Socrates, that there are many evil propensities lurking in him. Topir is not here to speak, but Tolstoy has told us himself how wicked he found his own nature, how he had to struggle with it. Tolstoy is not naturally over-courageous ; by long effort he has trained himself to be bold. How afraid of death he was in his youth And how cleverly he could conceal that fear. Later on, in mature age, it was still the fear of death which inspired him to write his confession. He was conquering that fear, and with it all other fears. For he felt that, since fear is very difficult to master in oneself, man must be a much higher being when he has learned not to be afraid 44 any more. Meanwhile, who knows ? Peir haps " cowardice," that miserable, despic- able, much-abused weakness of the under- world, is not such a vice after all. Perhaps it is even a virtue. Think of Dostoevsky and his heroes, think of Hamlet. If the underworld man in us were afraid of nothing, if Hamlet was naturally a gladiator, then we should have neither tragic poetry nor philosophy. It is a platitude, that fear of death has been the inspiration of philo- sophers. Numberless quotations could be drawn from ancient and modern writers, if they were necessary. Maybe the poetic daimon of Socrates, which made him wise, was only fear personified. Or perhaps it was his dark dreams. That which troubled him by day did not quit him by night. Even after the sentence of death Socrates dreamed that he ought to engage in the arts, so in order not to provoke the gods he began to compose verses, at the age of seventy. Tolstoy also at the age of fifty began to per- form good deeds, to which performance he had previously given not the slightest atten- tion. If it were our custom nowadays to express ourselves mythologically, w^e should no doubt hear Tolstoy telling us about his daimon or his dreams. Instead he 45 squares his accounts with science and morality, in place of gods or demons. Many a present-day Alcibiades, who laves all the week in the muddy waters of life, comes on Sundays to cleanse himself in the pure stream of Tolstoyian ideas. Book-keeping is satisfied with this modest success, and assumes that if it commands universal attention one day in the week, then obvi- ously it is the sum and essence of life, beyond which man needs nothing. On the same grounds the keepers of public baths could argue that, since so many people come to them on Saturdays, therefore cleanliness is the highest ambition of man, and during the week no one should stir at all, lest he sweat or soil himself. 26 In an old French writer, a contemporary of Pascal, I came across the following remarkable words : " L'homme est si miserable que rinconstance avec laquelle il abandonne ses desseins est, en quelque sorte, sa plus grande vertu ; parce qu'il temoigne par la qu'il y a encore en lui quelque reste de grandeur qui le porte a se degouter de choses qui ne meritent pas son amour et son estime." What a long way modern 46 thought has travelled from even the possi- bility of such an assumption. To consider inconstancy the finest human virtue ! Surely in order to get somewhere in life it is neces- sary to give the whole self, one's whole energy to the service of some one particular purpose. In order to be a virtuoso, a master of one's art and one's instrument, it is necessary with a truly angelic or asinine patience to try over and over again, dozens, hundreds, thousands of times, different ways of expressing one's ideas or moods, sparing neither labour, nor time, nor health. Everything else must take a second place. The first must be occupied by " the Art»" Goncharov, in his novel Obryv, cleverly relates how a 'cellist struggled all day, like a fish against the ice, sawing and sawing away, so that later on, in the evening, he might play super-excellently well. And that is the general idea. Objectionable, tedious, irritating labour, — this is the condi- tion of genius, which no doubt explains the reason why men so rarely achieve anything. Genius must submit to cultivate an assi within itself — the condition being so humili- ating that man will seldom take up the job. The majority prefer talent, that medium which lies between genius and mediocrity. 47 And many a time, towards the end of life, does the genius repent of his choice. " It would be better not to startle the world, but to live at one with it," says Ibsen in his last drama. Genius is a wretched, blind maniac, whose eccentricities are condoned because of what is got from him. And still we all bow to persevering talent, to the only god in whom we moderns believe, and the eulogy of inconstancy will awake very little sympathy in our hearts. Probably we shall not even regard it seriously. We very often express in a categorical form a judgment of which we do not feel assured, we even lay stress on its absolute validity. We want to see what opposition it will arouse, and this can be achieved only by stating our assumption not as a tentative suggestion, which no one will consider, but as an irrefutable, all-important truth. The greater the value an assumption has for us, the more carefully do we conceal any suggestion of its improbability. 28 Literature deals with the most difficult and important problems of existence, and, 48 therefore, litterateurs consider themselves the most important of people. A bank clerk, who is always handing money out, might just as well consider himself a millionaire. The high estimate placed upon unexplained, unsolved questions ought really to discredit writers in our eyes. And yet these literary men are so clever, so cunning at stating their own case and revealing the high importance of their mission, that in the long run they convince everybody, them- selves most of all. This last event is surely owing to their own limited intelligence. The Romans augurs had subtler, more versatile minds. In order to deceive others, they had no need to deceive themselves. In their own set they were not afraid to talk about their secrets, even to make fun of them, being fully confident that they could easily vindicate themselves before outsiders, in case of necessity, and pull a solemn face befitting the occasion. But our writers of to-day, before they can lay their improbable assertions before the public, must inevitably try to be convinced in their own minds. Otherwise they cannot begin. 49 29 " The writer is writing away, the reader is reading away " — the writer doesn't care what the reader is after, the reader doesn't care what the writer is about. Such a state of things hurt Schedrin very much. He would have liked it different ; no sooner has the writer said a word, than the reader at once scales the wall. This was his ideal. But the reader is by no means so naive as all that. He prefers to rest easy, and insists that the writer shall climb the wall for him. So those authors succeed with the public who write " with their heart's blood." Conventional tournaments, even the most brilliant, do not attract the masses any more than the connoisseurs. People rush to see a fight of gladiators, where awaits them a scent of real, hot, smoking blood, where they are going to see real, not pretended victims. Thus many writers, like gladiators, shed their blood to gratify that modern Caesar, the mob. " Salve, Caesar, morituri te salutant ! " Anton Tchekov tells the truth neither out of love or respect for the truth, nor yet because, in the Kantian manner, a high 50 duty bids him never to tell a lie, even to escape death. Neither has he the impulse which so often pushes young and fiery souls into rashness : that desire to stand erect, to keep the head high. On the contrary, Tchekhov always walks with a stoop, his head bent down, never fixing his eyes on the heavens, since he will read no signs there. If he tells the truth, it is because the most reeking lie no longer intoxicates him, even though he swallow it not in the modest doses that idealism offers, but in immoderate quantities, thousand-gallon-barrel gulps. He would taste the bitterness, but it would not make his head turn, as it does Schiller's, or Dostoevsky's, or even Socrates', whose head, as we know, could stand any quantity of wine, but went spinning with the most commonplace lie. Noblesse Oblige. — The moment of obliga- tion, compulsion, duty, that moment described by Kant as the essential, almost the only predicate of moral concepts, serves chiefly to indicate that Kant was modest in himself and in his attitude towards all whom he addressed, perceiving in all men beings subject to the ennobling effect of 51 morality. Nobles sg oblige is a motto not for the aristocracy, which recognises in its privileges its own instant duties, but for the self-made, wealthy parvenues who pant for an illustrious title. They have been accustomed to telling lies, to playing pol- troon, swindling, and meanness, and the necessity for speaking the truth impartially, for bravely facing danger, for freely giving of their fortunes scares them beyond measure. Therefore it is necessary that they should repeat it to themselves and to their children, in whose veins the lying, sneaking blood still runs, hourly, lest they forget : " You must not tell lies, you must be open, mag- nanimous." It is silly, it is incompre- hensible — but " noblesse oblige.^' Homo homini lupus is one of the most steadfast maxims of eternal morality. In each of our neighbours we fear a wolf. " This fellow is evil-minded, if he is not restrained by law he will ruin us," so we think every time a man gets out of the rut of sanctified tradition. The fear is just. We are so poor, so weak, so easily ruined and destroyed ! How can we help being afraid ! And yet, behind 52 danger and menace there is usually hidden something significant, which merits our close and sympathetic attention. But fear's eyes are big. We see danger, danger only, we build up a fabric of morality inside which as in a fortress we sit out of danger all our lives. Only poets have undertaken to praise dangerous people — Don Juans, Fausts, Tannhaiisers. But nobody takes the poets seriously. Common-sense values a com- mercial-traveller or a don much more highly than a Byron, a Goethe, or a Moliere. 33 The possibilities which open out before mankind are sufficiently limited. It is im- possible to see everything, impossible to know everything, impossible to rise too high above the earth, impossible to penetrate too deeply down. What has been is hidden away, what will be we cannot anticipate, and we know for certain that we shall never grow wings. Regularity, immutably regular succession of phenomena puts a term to our efforts, drives us into a regular, narrow, hard-beaten road of everyday life. But even on this road we may not wander from side to side. We must watch our feet, consider each step, since the 53 moment we are off our guard disaster is upon us. Another life is conceivable, how- ever : life in which the word disaster does not exist, where responsibility for one's actions, even if it be not completely abolish- ed, at least has not such a deadly and accidental weight, and where, on the other hand, there is no " regularity," but rather an infinite number of possibilities. In such a life the sense of fear — most disgraceful to us — disappears. There the virtues are not the same as ours. Fearlessness in face of danger, liberality, even lavishness are considered virtues with us, but they are respected without any grounds. Socrates was quite right when he argued that not all courage, but only the courage which measures beforehand the risks and the chances of victory, is fully justifiable. To the same extent those economical, careful people who condemn lavishness are in the right. Fearlessness and lavishness do not suit mortal men, rather it becomes them to tremble and to count every penny, seeing what a state of poverty and impotence they exist in. That is why these two virtues are so rarely met with, and when they are met, why they arouse such super- stitious reverence in the crowd. " This man 54 fears nothing and spares nothing : he is probably not a man, but a demi-god, perhaps even a god." Socrates did not believe in gods, so he wanted to justify virtue by reason. Kant also did not believe in God, and therefore he derived his morals from " Law." But if there is God, and all men are the children of God, then we should be afraid of nothing and spare nothing. And then the man who madly dissipates his own life and fortunes, and the lives and fortunes of others, is more right than the calculating philosophers who vainly seek to regulate mankind on earth. 34 Moral people are the most revengeful of mankind, they employ their morality as the best and most subtle weapon of ven- geance. They are not satisfied with simply despising and condemning their neighbour themselves, they want the condemnation to be universal and supreme : that is, that all men should rise as one against the con- demned, and that even the o-Qenier's own conscience shall he against him. Then only are they fully satisfied and reassured. Nothing on earth but morality could lead to such wonderful results. ^5 Inveterate wickedness. — Heretics were often most bitterly persecuted for their least digression from accepted belief. It was just their obstinacy in trifles that irritated the righteous to madness. " Why can they not yield on so trifling a matter ? They cannot possibly have serious cause for opposition. They only want to grieve us, to spite us." So the hatred mounted up, piles of faggots and torture machines appeared against obdurate wickedness. 36 I do not know where I came across the remark, whether in Tolstoy or Turgenev, that those who have been subjected to trial in the courts of justice always acquire a particularly noble expression of face. iUthough logic does so earnestly recommend caution in the forming of contradictory conclusions, come what may I shall for once risk a deduction : a noble expression of face is a sign that a man has been under trial — but certainly not a trial for political crime — for theft or bribe-taking. S6 37 The most important and significant revela- tions come into the world naked, without a wordy garment. To find words for them is a delicate, difficult business, a whole art. Stupidities and banalities, on the con- trary, appear at once in ready-made apparel, gaudy even if shabby. So that they are ready straight away to be presented to the public. A strange impatience has taken possession of Russian writers lately. They are all running a race after the " ultimate words." They have no doubt that the ultimate words will be attained. The question is, who will lay hold of them first. 39 The appearance of Socrates on the philosophic horizon is hailed by historians as the greatest event. Morals were begin- ning to work loose, Athens was threatened with ruin. Socrates' mission was to put an end to the violent oscillation in moral judgments which extreme individualism on the one hand and the relativism of the sophists on the other had set up. The great teacher did all he could. He gave 57 up his usual occupations and his family life, he took no thought for the morrow, he taught, taught, taught — simple people or eminent, wise or foolish, ignorant or learned. Notwithstanding, he did not save the country. Under Pericles, Athens flourished without wisdom, or at least independently of Socratic wisdom. After Pericles, in spite of the fact that the Socratic teaching found such a genius as Plato to continue it, Athens steadily declined, and Aristotle is already master to the son of Philip of Macedon. Whence it is obvious that the wisdom of Socrates had not saved the country, and as this had been its chief object, it had failed in its object, and therefore was not worthy of the exaggerated respect it received. It is necessary to find some justification for philosophy other than country-saving. This would be the easiest thing in the world. But altogether we must give up the favourite device of the philosophers, of looking to find in the well-being of society the raison (Tetre of philosophy. At the best, the trick was a risky one. As a rule, wisdom goes one way, society the other. They are artificially connected. It is public orators who have trained both the philosophers and the masses to regard as worthy of 58 attention only those considerations which have absolutely everything on their side : social utility, morality, even metaphysical wisdom. . . . Why so much ? Is it not sufficient if some new project will prove useful ? Why try to get the sanction of morality and metaphysics ? Nay, once the laws of moraHty are autonomous, and once ideas are allowed to stand above the em- pirical needs of mankind, it is impossible to balance ideas and morality with social requirements, or even with the salvation of the country from ruin. Per eat mundus, fiat philosophia. If Athens was ruined because of philosophy, philosophy is not impugned. So the autonomous thinker should hold. But de facto, a thinker does not like quarrelling with his country. When a writer has to express an idea whose foundation he has not been able to establish, and which yet is dear to his heart, so that he earnestly wishes to secure its general acceptance, as a rule he interrupts his exposition, as if to take breath, and makes a small, or at times a serious digression, during which he proves the invalidity of this or that proposition, often without 59 any reference to his real iheme. Having triumphantly exposed one or more absurdities, and thus acquired the aplomb of a solid expert, he returns to his proper task, calculating that now he will inspire his reader with greater confidence. His calculation is perfectly justified. The reader is afraid to attack such a skilled dialectician, and prefers to agree rather than to risk himself in argument. Not even the greatest intellects, particularly in philosophy, disdain such stratagems. The idealists, for example, before expounding their theories, turn and rend materialism. The materialists, we remember, at one time did the same with the idealists, and achieved a vast success. Theories of sequence and consequence are binding only upon the disciples, not upon the masters. Fathers of great ideas tend to be very careless about their progeny, giving very little heed to their future career. The offspring of one and the same philosopher frequently bear such small resemblance to one another, that it is impossible to discern the family connection. Conscientious disciples, wasting away under the arduous effort to discover that which 60 does nol exist, are brought to despair of their task. Having got an inkling of the truth concerning their difficulty, they give up the job for ever, they cease their attempt at reconciling glaring contradictions. But then they only insist the harder upon the necessity for studying the philosophers, studying them minutely, circumstantially, historically, philologically even. So the history of philosophy is born, which now is taking the place of philosophy. Certainly the history of philosophy may be an exact science, since by means of historical research it is often possible to decide what exactly a certain philosopher did mean, and in what sense he employed his peculiar terms. And seeing that there have been a fair number of philosophers, the business of clearing them all up is a respectable under- taking, and deserves the name of a science. For a good translation or a commentary on the chief works of Kant a man may be given the degree of doctor of philosophy, and henceforth recognised as one who is initiated in the profundities of the secrets of the universe. Then why ever should anybody think out new systems — or even write them ? 6i 42 The raptures of creative activity ! — empty words, invented by men who never had an opportunity of judging from their own experience, but who derive their conclusion syllogistically : " if a creation gives us such delight, what must the creator himself experience ! " Usually the creator feels only vexations. Every creation is created out of the Void. At the best, the maker finds himself confronted with a formless, meaning- less, usually obstinate and stiff matter, which yields reluctantly to form. And he does not know how to begin. Every time a new thought is gendered, so often must that new thought, which for the moment seems so brilliant and fascinating, be thrown aside as worthless. Creative activity is a continual progression from failure to failure, and the condition of the creator is usually one of uncertainty, mistrust, and shattered nerves. The more serious and original the task which a man sets himself, the more tormenting is the self-misgiving. For this reason even men of genius cannot keep up the creative activity to the last. As soon as they have acquired their technique, they begin to repeat themselves, well aware that the public willingly endures the monotony of a 6z favourite, even finds virtue in it. Every connoisseur of art is satisfied if he recognises in a new work the accepted " manner " of the artist. Few realise that the acquiring of a manner is the beginning of the end. Artists realise well enough, and would be glad to be rid of their manner, which seems to them a hackneyed affair. But this requires too great a strain on their powers, new torments, doubts, new groping. He who has once been through the creative raptures is not easily tempted to try again. He prefers to turn out work according to the pattern he has evolved, calmly and securely, assured of his results. Fortunately no one except himself knows that he is not any longer a creator. What a lot of secrets there are in the world, and how easy it is to keep one's secret safe from indiscreet glances ! 43 A writer works himself up to a pitch of ecstasy, otherwise he does not take up his pen. But ecstasy is not so easily distinguished from other kinds of excitement. And as a writer is always in haste to write, he has rarely the patience to wait, but at the first promptings of animation begins to pour himself forth. So in the name of ecstasy we 63 are oflered suc]\ quantities of banal, by no means ecstatic effusions. Particularly easy it is to confound with ecstasy that very common sort of spring-time liveliness which in our language is well-named calf-rapture. And calf-rapture is much more acceptable to the public than true inspiration or genuine transport. It is easier, more familiar. 44 A school axiom : logical scepticism refutes itself, since the denial of the possibility of positive knowledge is already an aihrmation. But, in the first place, scepticism is not bound to be logical, for it has no desire whatever to gratify that dogma which raises logic to the position of law. Secondly, where is the philosophic theory which, if carried to its extreme, would not destroy itself ? There- fore, why is more demanded from scepticism than from other systems ? especially from scepticism, which honestly avows that it cannot give that which all other theories claim to give. 45. The Aristotelian logic, which forms the chief component in modern logic, arose, as we know, as a result of the permanent controversies which were such sport to the 64 Greeks. In order to argue, it is indeed necessary to have a common ground ; in other words, to agree about the rules of the game. But in our day dialectic tournaments, like all other bouts of contention, no longer attract people. Thus logic may be relegated to the background. In Gogol's Portrait, the artist despairs at the thought that he has sacrificed art for the sake of " life." In Ibsen's drama, When We Dead Awaken, there is also an artist, who has become world-famous, and who repents that he has sacrificed his life — to art. Now, choose — which of the two ways of repentance do you prefer \ Mcin is often quite indifferent to success whilst he has it. But once he loses his power over people, he begins to fret. And — vice versa. 48 . Turgenev's Insarov strikes the imagina- tion of Elena because he is a man preparing for battle. She prefers him to Shubin the painter, or to Berseniev the savant. Since s 65 ancient days women have looked with favour on warriors rather than on peaceful men. Had Turgenev invested that idea with less glamour, he would probably not have become the ideal of the young. Who does not get a thrill from Elena and her elect ? Who has not felt the fascination of Turgenev's women ! And yet all of them give themselves to the strong male. With such " superior people," as with beasts, the males fight with each other, the woman looks on, and when it is over, she submits herself the slave of the conqueror. A caterpillar is transformed into a chrysalis, and for a long time lives in a warm, quiet little world. Perhaps if it had human consciousness it would declare that that world was the best, perhaps the only one possible to live in. But there comes a time when some unknown influence causes the little creature to begin the work of destruc- tion. If other caterpillars could see it how horrified they would be, revolted to the bottom of their soul by the awful work in which the insurgent is engaged. They would call it immoral, godless, they would begin to talk about pessimism, scepticism, and so on. To destroy what has cost such labour 66 to construct ! Why, what is wrong with this complete, cosy, comfortable little world ? To keep it intact they call to their aid sacred morality and the idealistic theory of know- ledge. Nobody cares that the caterpillar has grown wings, that when it has nibbled its old nest away it will fly out into space — nobody gives a thought to this. Wings — that is mysticism ; self-nibbling —this is actuality. Those who are engaged in such actuality deserve torture and execu- tion. And there are plenty of prisons and voluntary hangmen on the bright earth. The majority of books are prisons, and great authors are not bad hangmen. Nietzsche and Dostoevsky seem to be typical " inverted simulators," if one may use the expression. They imitated spiritual sanity, although they were spiritually insane. They knew their morbidity well enough, but they exhibited their disease only to that extent where freakishness passes for originality. With the sensitiveness peculiar to all who are in constant danger, they never went beyond the limits. The axe of the guillotine of public opinion hung over them : one awkward move, and the execution 67 automatically takes place. But they knew how to avoid unwarrantable moves. . SI The so-called ultimate questions troubled mankind in the world's dawn as badly as they trouble us now. Adam and Eve wanted *' to know," and they plucked the fruit at their risk. Cain, whose sacrifice did not please God, raised his hand against his brother : and it seemed to him he committed murder in the name of justice, in vindication of his own injured rights. Nobody has ever been able to understand why God preferred Abel's sacrifice to that of Cain. In our own day Sallieri repeats Cain's vengeance and poisons his friend and benefactor Mozzart, according to the poem of Poushkin. " All say, there is no justice on earth ; but there is no justice up above : this is as clear to me as a simple scale of music." No man on earth can fail to recognise in these words his own tormenting doubts. The outcome is creative tragedy, which for some mysterious reason has been considered up till now as the highest form of human creation. Everything is being unriddled and explained. If we com- pare our knowledge with that of the ancients, we appear very wise. But we are no nearer 68 to solving the riddle of eternal justice than Cain was. Progress, civilisation, all the conquests of the human mind have brought us nothing new here. Like our ancestors, we stand still with fright and perplexity before ugliness, disease, misery, senility, death. All that the wise men have been able to do so far is to turn the earthly horrors into problems. We are told that perhaps all that is horrible only appears horrible, that perhaps at the end of the long journey some- thing new awaits us. Perhaps ! But the modern educated man, with the wisdom of all the centuries of mankind at his command, knows no more about it than the old singer who solved universal problems at his own risk. We, the children of a moribund civilisation, we, old men from our birth, in this respect are as young as the first man. They say it is impossible to set a bound between the "I" and society. Naivete! Crusoes are to be found not only on desert islands. They are there, in populous cities. It is true they are not clad in skins, they have no dark Fridays in attendance, and so nobody recognises them. But surely Friday and a fur jacket do not make a Crusoe. 69 Loneliness, desertion, a boundless, shoreless sea, on which no sail hasrisen for tens of years, — do not many of our contemporaries live in such a circumstance ? And are they not Crusoes, to whom the rest of people have become a vague reminiscence, barely dis- tinguishable from a dream ? 53 To be irremediably unhappy — this is shameful. An irremediably unhappy person is outside the laws of the earth. Any connection between him and society is severed finally. And since, sooner or later, every individual is doomed to irremediable unhappiness, the last word of philosophy is loneliness. 54 " It is better to be an unhappy man, than a happy pig." The utilitarians hoped by this golden bridge to get over the chasm which separates them from the promised land of the ideal. But psychology stepped in and rudely interrupted : ^here are no unhappy people^ the unhappy ones are all pigs. Dostoevsky's philosopher of the under- world, Raskolnikov, also Hamlet, and such- like, are not simply unhappy men whose fate might be esteemed, or even preferred 70 before sorrie happy fates ; they are simply unhappy swine. And they themselves are principally aware of it .... He that hath ears to hear, let him hear. 55 If you want people to envy you your sorrow or your shame, look as if ycu were proud of it. If you have only enough of the actor in you, rest assured, you will become the hero of the day. Since the parable of the Pharisee and the publican was uttered, what a lot of people who could not fulfil tlieir sacred duties pretended to be publicans and sinners, and so aroused sympathy, even envy. Philosophers dearly love to call their utterances '' truths," since in that guise they become binding upon us all. But each philosopher invents his own truths. Which means that he asks his pupils to deceive themselves in the way he shows, but that he reserves for himself the option of deceiving himself in his own way. Why ? Why not allow everyone to deceive him- self just as he likes ? 71 r' 57 When Xanthippe poured slops over Soc- rates, as he returned from his philosophical occupations, tradition says that he observed : " After a storm there is always rain.'* Would it not be more worthy (not of the philosopher, but of philosophy) to say : \fter one's philosophical exercise, one feels as if one had had slops emptied over one's head. And therefore Xanthippe did but give outward expression to what had taken place in Socrates' soul. Symbols are not always beautiful. S8 From the notes of an underworld man — " I read little, I write little, and, it seems to me, I think little. He who is ill-disposed towards me will say that this shows a great defect in my character, perhaps he will call me lazy, an Oblomov, and will repeat the copy-book maxim that idleness is the mother of all the vices. A friend, on the other hand, will say it is only a temporary state, that perhaps I am not quite well — in short, he will find random excuses for me, more with the idea of consoling me than of speaking the truth. But for my part, I say let us wait. If it turns out at the end 72 of my life that I have * done * not less than others — why, then — it will mean that idleness may be a virtue." Borne, a contemporary of Heine, was very much offended when his enemies insisted on explaining his misanthropic out- pourings as the result of a stomach and liver disease. It seemed to him much nobler and loftier to be indignant and angry because of the triumph of evil on earth, than because of the disorders of his own physical organs. Sentimentality apart — was he right, and is it really nobler ? 60 A real writer disdams to repeat from hearsay events which he has not witnessed. It seems to him tedious and humiliating to tell " in his own words," like a school- boy, things which he has fished out of another man's books. But there — how can we expect him to stoop to such insig- nificance ! 61 Whilst conscience stands between the educated and the lower classes, as the only possible mediator, there can be no hope for 73 mutual understanding. Conscience demands sacrifices, nothing but sacrifices. It says to the educated man : " You are happy, well-off, learned — the people are poor, un- happy, ignorant ; renounce therefore your well-being, or else soothe your conscience with suave speeches." Only he who has nothing to sacrifice, nothing to lose, having lost everything, can hope to approach the people as an equal. This is why Dostoevsky and Nietzsche were not afraid to speak in their own name, and did not feel compelled either to stretch up or to stoop down in order to be on a level with men. 62 Not to know what you want is considered a shameful weakness. To confess it is to lose for ever not only the reputation of a writer, but even of a man. None the less, " conscience " demands such a con- fession. True, in this case as in most others the demands of conscience are satisfied only when they incur no very dire conse- quences. Leaving aside the fact that people are no longer terrified of the once-so-terrible public opinion (the public has been tamed, it listens with reverence to what is told to 74 it, and never dares judge) — the admission " I do not know myself what I want " seems to offer a guarantee of something important. Those who know what they want generally want trifles, and attain to inglorious ends : riches, fame, or at the best, progress or a philosophy of their own. Even now it is sometimes not a sin to laugh at such wonders, and may-be the time is coming when a rehabilitated Hamlet will announce, not with shame but with pride : " I don't in the least know what I want." And the crowd will applaud him, for the crowd always applauds heroes and proud men. Fear of death is explained conclusively by the desire for self-preservation. But at that rate the fear should disappear in old and sick people, who ought by nature to look with indifference on death. Whereas the horror of death is present in all living things. Does not this suggest that there is still some other reason for the dread, and that even where the pangs of horror cannot save a man from his end, still it is a necessary and purposeful anguish ? The natural-scientific explanation here, as usual, 75 stops halfway, and fails to lead the human mind to the promised goal. ... ^4 Moral indignation is only a refined form of ancient vengeance. Once anger spoke with daggers, now words will do. And happy is the man who, loving and thirsting to chastise his offender, yet is appeased when the offence is punished. On account of the gratification it offers to the passions,morality^ which has replaced bloody chastisement, will not easily lose its charm. But there are offences, deep, unforgettable offences, inflicted not by people, but by "laws of nature." How are we to settle these ? Here neither dagger nor indignant word will serve. Therefore, for him who has once run foul of the laws of nature morality sinks, for ever or for a time, into subsidiary importance. Fatalism frightens people particularly in that form which holds it just to say, of anything that happens, or has happened, or will happen : be it so ! How can one acquiesce in the actuality of life, when it contains so many horrors ? But amor fati does not imply eternal acquiescence in 76 actuality. It is only a truce, for a more or less lasting period. Time is needed in which to estimate the forces and intentions of the enemy. Under the mask of friendship the old enmity persists, and an awful revenge is in preparation. 66 In the " ultimate questions of life " we are not a bit nearer the truth than our ancestors were. Everybody knows it, and yet so many go on talking about infinity, without any hope of ever saying anything. It is evident that a result — in the usual accept- ance of the word — is not necessary. In the very last resort we trust to instinct, even in the field of philosophy, where reason is supposed to reign supreme, uttering its eternal " Why ? " " Why ? " laughs at all possible " becauses." Instinct, however, does not mock. It simply ignores the whys, and leads us by impossible ways to ends that our divine reason would hold absurd, if it could only see them in time. But reason is a laggard, without much foresight, and there- fore, when we have run up to an unexpected conclusion, nothing remains but for reason to accept : or even to justify, to exalt the new event. And therefore, — *' reality is 77 reasonable," say the philosophers : reason- able, not only when they draw their philo- sophic salaries, as the socialists, and with them our philosopher \ladimir Soloviov, explain; but still reasonable even when philosophers have their maintenance taken away from them. Nay, in the latter case, particularly in the latter case, in spite of the socialists and VI. Soloviov, reality shows herself most reasonable. A philosopher persecuted, downtrodden, hungry, cold, receiving no salary, is nearly always an extreme fatalist — although this, of course, by no means hinders him from abusing the existing order. Theories of sequence and consequence, as we already know, are binding only upon disciples, whose single virtue lies in their scrupulous, logical developing of the master's idea. But masters themselves invent ideas, and, therefore, have the right to substitute one for another. The sovereign power which proclaims a law has the same power to abolish it. But the duty of the subordinate consists in the praise, in the consequential interpretation and the strict observance of the dictates of the higher will. 78 The Pharisee in the parable fulfilled all that religion demanded of him : kept his fasts, paid his tithes, etc. Had he a right to be pleased with his own piety, and to despise the erring publican ? Everybody thought so, including the Pharisee himself. 7he judg- ment of Christ came as the greatest surprise to him. He had a clear conscience. He did not merely pretend before others to be righteous, he himself believed in his own righteousness. And suddenly he turns out guilty, awfully guilty. But if the conscience of a righteous man does not help him to distinguish between good and evil, how is he to avoid sin ? What does Kant's moral law mean, that law which was as consoling as the starry sky ? Kant lived his life in profound peace of soul, he met his death quietly, in the consciousness of his own purity. But if Christ came again, he might condemn the serene philosopher for his very serenity. For the Pharisee, we repeat, was righteous, if purity of inten- tions, together with a firm readiness to fulfil everything which appears to him in the light of duty, be righteousness in a man. 79 68 We jeer and laugh at a man not because he is ridiculous, but because we want to have a laugh out of him. In the same way we are indignant, not because this or the other act is revolting to us, but because we want to let off our steam. But it does not follow from this that we ought always to be calm and smooth. Woe to him who would try to realise the ideal of justice on earth. We think with peculiar intensity during the hard moments of our life — we write when we have nothing else to do. So that a writer can only communicate something of import- ance in reproducing the past. When we are driven to think, we have unfortunately no mind to write, which accounts for the fact that books are never more than a feeble echo of what a man has gone through. 70 Tchekhov has a story called Misfortune which well illustrates the difficulty a man finds in adapting himself to a new truth, if this truth threaten the security of his condition. The Merchant Avdeyer does not believe that he is condemned, that he has 80 been brought to trial, and tried, and found guilty, for his irregularities in a public bank. He still thinks the verdict is yet to come — he still waits. In the world of learning some- thing like this is happening. The educated have become so accustomed to think them- selves not guilty, perfectly in the right, that they do not admit for a moment even now that they are brought to court. When threatening voices reach them, calling them to give an account of themselves, they only suspiciously shrug their shoulders. " All this will pass away " — they think. Well, when at last they are convinced that misfortune has befallen them, they will probably begin to justify themselves, like Avdeyer, declaring that they cannot even read printed matter sufficiently .well. As yet, they pass for respectable, wise, experienced, omniscient men. 71 If a man had come to Dostoevsky and said to him, " I am hopelessly unhappy," the great artist in human misery would probably, at the bottom of his soul, have laughed at the naivete of the poor creature. May one confess such things of oneself ? May one go to such lengths of complaint, and still expect consolation from his neighbour ? 81 Hopelessness is the most solemn and supreme moment in life. Till that point we have been assisted — now we are left to our- selves. Previously we had to do with men and human laws — now with eternity, and with the complete absence of laws. Is it not obvious ? Byelinsky, in his famous letter, accuses Gogol, among other things, that in his Correspondence with Friends ^ he, Gogol, succumbs to the fear of death, of devils, and of hell. I find the accusation just : Gogol definitely feared death, demons, and hell. The point is, whether it is not right to fear these things, and whether fearlessness would be a proof of the high development of a man's soul. Schopenhauer asserts that death inspired philosophy. All the best poetry, all the wonderful mythology of the ancients and of modern peoples have for their source the fear of death. Only modern science forbids men to fear, and insists on a tranquil attitude towards death. So we arrive at utilitarianism and the positivist philosophy. If you wish to be rid of both these creeds you must be allowed to think again of death, and without shame to fear hell and its devils. It may be there is really 8z a certain justification for concealing fears of such kind : in the abiHty to conceal one's agitation at moments of great danger there is a true beauty. But to deaden human sensitiveness and to keep the human intelli- gence within the bounds of perception, such a task can have charms only for a petty creature. Happily, mankind has no means by which to perform.on itself such monstrous castration. Persecuted Eros, it is true, has hidden himself from the eyes of his enemies, but he has never abjured himself ; and even the strictest mediaeval monks could not completely tear out their hearts from their breasts. Similarly with the aspiration towards the infinite : science persecuted it and put a veto on it. But laboratory workers themselves, sooner or later, recover their senses, and thirstily long to get out of the enclosure of positive knowledge, with that same thirsty longing that tortured the monks who wanted to get out of the enclosure of monastery walls. 73 If fate — and they say there is such a law — punishes criminals, it has its penalty also for the lovers of good. The former it throttles, the latter it spits upon. The former end in bitter torment, the latter — in ignominy. 83 74 Philosophy has always loved to occupy the position of a servant. In the Middle Ages she was the ancilla theologiie, nowadays she waits on science. At the same time she calls herself the science of sciences. 75 I wonder which more effectually makes a man rush forwards without looking back : the knowledge that behind him hovers the head of Medusa, with horrible snakes, ready to turn him into stone ; or the certainty that in the rear lies the unchangeable order laid down by the law of causality and by modern science. Judging from what we see, judging from the degree of tension which human .thought has reached to-day, it would seem that the head of Medusa is less terrible than the law of causality. In order to escape the latter, man will face anything. Rather than return to the bosom of scientific cause and effect, he embraces madness : not that fine frenzy of madness which spends itself in fiery speeches, but technical madness, for which one is stowed away in a lunatic asylum. 84 76. . *' To experience a feeling of joy or sorrow, of triumph or despair, ennui or happiness, and so on, without having sufficient cause for such feeling, is an unfailing sign of mental disease . . . ." One of the modern truths which is seeing its last days. 77 Count Tolstoy's German biographer regrets the constant misunderstanding and quarrels which took place between Tolstoy and Turgenev. He reminds us of Goethe and Schiller, and thinks that Russian literature would have gained a great deal if the two remarkable Russian writers had been more pacific, had remained on constantly friendly terms with one another, and bequeathed to posterity a couple of volumes of letters dealing with literary and philo- sophic subjects. It might have been very nice — but I refuse to imagine Tolstoy and Turgenev keeping up a long, peaceful corre- spondence, particularly on high subjects. Nearly every one of Turgenev's opinions drove Tolstoy to madness, or was capable of so driving him. Dostoevsky's dislike of Tur- genev was even stronger than Tolstoy's ; he wrote of him very spitefully and offensively, 8s libelling him rather than drawing a cari- cature. Evidently Dostoevsky, like Tolstoy, detested the " European " in their confrere. But here he was mistaken, in spite of his psychological acuteness. To Dostoevsky, it was enough that Turgenev wore European clothes and tried to appear like a westerner. He himself did the opposite : he tried to get rid of every trace of Europeanism from him- self, apparently without great success, since he failed to make clear to himself wherein lay the strength of Europe, and where her sting. Nevertheless, the late Mikhailovsky is not wrong in calling Dostoevsky a seeker of buried treasure. Surely, in the second half of his literary activity Dostoevsky no longer sought for the real fruits of life. There awoke in him the Russian, the elemental man, with a thirst for the miraculous. Compared with what he wanted, the fruits of European civilisation seemed to him trivial, flat, insipid. The agelong civilisation of his neighbours told him that there never had been a miracle, and never would be. But all his being, not yet broken-in by civilisation, craved for the stupendous unknown. There- fore, the apparently-satisfied progressivist enraged him. Tolstoy once said of Turgenev : *' I hate his democratic backside." Dostoev- 86 sky might have repeated these words . . . And now, for the gratification of the German critic, please reconcile the Russian writers and make them talk serenely on high-flown matters! Dostoevsky was within a hair's- breath of a quarrel with Tolstoy, with whom, not long before death interrupted him, he began a long controversy concerning " Anna Karenina." Even Tolstoy seemed to him too compliant, too accommodating. 78. We rarely make a display of that which is dear to us, near and dear and necessary. On the other hand, we readily exhibit that which is of no importance to us — there is nothing else to be done with it. A man takes his mistress to the theatre and sticks her in full view of ever)^body ; he prefers to remain at home with the woman he loves, or to go about with her quietly, unnoticed. So with our " Virtues." Every time we notice in ourselves some quality we do not prize we haste to make a show of it, thinking perhaps that someone would be glad of it. If it wins us approval, we are pleased — so there is some gain. To an actor, a writer, or an orator, his own anticfe, without which he can have no success with the public, are often 87 disgusting. And yet his knack of making such antics he considers a talent, a divine gift, and he would rather die than that it should be lost to the public. Talent, on the whole, is accounted a divine gift, only because it is always on show, because it serves the public in some way or other. All our. judg- ments are permeated through and through with utilitarianism, and were we to attempt to purify them from this adulteration what would remain of modern philosophy ? That is why youngish, inexperienced writers usually believe in harmonia prcestabilitata, even though they have never heard of Leibnitz. They persuade them.selves that there is no breach between egoistic and idealistic aspira- tions ; that, for instance, thirst for fame and desire to serve mankind are one and the same thing. Such a persuasion is usually very tenacious of life, and lasts long in men of vigorous and courageous mind. It seems to me that Poushkin would not have lost it, even had he lived to a prolonged old age. It was also part of Turgenev's belief — if a man of his spiritual fibre could have any belief. Tolstoy now believed, and now disbelieved, according to the work he had in hand. When he had other people's ideas to destroy he doubted the identity of egoistic 88 and idealist aspirations ; when he had his own to defend, he believed in it. Which is a line of conduct worthy of attention, and supremely worthy of imitation ; for human truths are proper exclusively for ancillary purposes . . . 79 Man is such a conservative creature that any change, even a change for the better, scares him, he prefers the bad old way to the new good one. A man who has been all his life a confirmed materialist would not consent to believe that the soul was immortal, not if it were proved to him more geometrico, and not if he were a constitutional coward, fearing death like Shakespeare's Falstaff. Then we must take human conceit into account. Men do not like to admit them- selves wrong. It is absurd, but it is so. Men, trivial, wretched creatures, proved by history and by every common event to be bunglers, yet must needs consider them- selves infallible, omniscient. What for ? Why not admit their ignorance flatly and frankly ? True, it is easier said than done. But why should slavish intellect, in spite of our desire to be straightforward, deck us out with would-be truths, of which we cannot divest ourselves even when we know their 89 flimsiness. Socrates wanted to think that he knew nothing — but he could not bring it off. He most absorbedly believed in his own knowledge ; nothing could be '' truth," except his teaching ; he accepted the decree of the oracle, and sincerely esteemed himself the wisest of men. And so it will be, as long as philosophers feel it their duty to teach and to save their neighbours. If a man wants to help people, he is bound to become a liar. We should undertake doubt seriously, not in order to return at length to established beliefs, for that would be a vicious circle. Experience shows us that such a process, certainly in the development of ultimate questions, only leads from error to error ; we should doubt so that doubt becomes a continuous creative force, inspiring the very essence of our life. For established know- ledge argues in us a condition of imperfect receptivity. The weak, flabby spirit can- not bear quick, ceaseless change. It must look round, it must have time to gather its wits, and so it must undergo the same experience time after time. It needs the support and the security of habit. But the well-grown soul despises your crutches. He is tired of crawling on his own cabbage patch, he tears himself away from his own 90 " native " soil, and takes himself off into the far distances, braving the infinitude of space. Surely everybody knows v/e are not to live in the world for ever. But cowardice prevents one straightforward admitting of it, we keep it close till there is an occasion to air it as a truism. Only when misfortune, disease, old age come upon us, then the dread fear of departure walks with us like our own skeleton. We cannot dismiss him. At length, involuntarily, we begin to examine our gruesome companion with curiosity. And then, strangely enough, we observe that he not only tortures us, but, keeping pace with us, he has begun to gnaw through all the threads that bind us to the old existence. At moments it seems as if, a few more threads gone, nothing, nothing will remain to hold us back, the eternal dream of crawling man will be fulfilled, we shall be released from the bonds, we shall betake ourselves in liberty to regions far from this damned vale of earth. ... 80 Moralists are abused because they offer us " moral consolations." This is not quite fair. Moralists would joyfully substitute palpable blessings for their abstract gifts, if they could. When he was young, Tolstoy 91 / wanted to make men happy ; when he was old, and knew he could not make them happy, he began to preach renunciation, resignation, and so forth. And how angry he got when people wouldn't have his teaching ! But if, instead of foisting his doctrines off on us as the solution of the ultimate problems, and as optimism, he had only spoken of the impossibility of finding satisfactory answers, and have offered himself as a pessimist, he would probably have obtained a much more willing hearing. Now he is annoying, because, finding himself unable to relieve his neighbours, he turns to them and insists that they shall consider themselves relieved by him, nay, even made happy by him. To which many will not agree : for why should they voluntarily renounce their rights ? Since although, God knows, the right of quarrelling with one's fate, and cursing it, is not a very grand right, still, it is a right . . . 8i Ivanov, in Tchekhov's drama of that name, compares himself to an overstrained labourer. The labourer dies, so that all that remains to Ivanov is to die. But logic, as you know, recommends great caution in coming to conclusions by analogy. 92 Behold Tchekhov himself, who, as far as we can judge, had endured in his own soul all the tragedy, just as Ivanov had, did not die or think of dying, or even turn out a wasted man. He is doing something, he struggles, he seeks, his work seems important and considerable to us, just like other human works. Ivanov shot himself because the drama must end, while Tchekhov had not yet finished his own struggle. Our aesthetics demand that the drama must have a climax and a finale : though we have abandoned the Aristotelian unities. Given a little more time, however, dramatic writers will have got rid of this restriction also. They will frankly confess that they do not know how, or with what event to end their dramas. Stories have already learnt to dispense with an ending. 82 More of the same. — Ivanov says : *' Now, where is my salvation ? In what ? If an intelligent, educated, healthy man for no discoverable reason sets up a Lazarus lament and starts to roll down an inclined plane, then he is rolling without resisting, and there is no salvation for him." One way out would be to accept the inclined plane and the 93 gathering impetus as normal. Even further, one might find in the rolling descent a proof of one's spiritual superiority to other men. Of course in such a case one should go apart from the rest, not court young girls or fraternise with those who are living the ordinary life, but be alone. "Love is nonsense, caresses maudlin, work is meaning- less, and song and fiery speeches are banal, played-out," continued Ivanov. To young Sasha these words are horrible, — but Ivanov will be responsible for them. He is already responsible for them. That he is tottering is nothing : it is still full early for him to shoot himself. He will live whilst his creator, Tchekhov, lives. And we shall listen to the shaky, vacillating philosophy. We are so sick of symmetry and harmony and finality, sick as we are of bourgeois self-complacency, 83 It will be seen from the above that already in Ivanov^ one of his early works, Tchekhov has assumed the role of advocatus diaboli. Wherever Ivanov appears he brings ruin and destruction. It is true, Tchekhov hesitates to take his side openly, and evidently does not know what to do 94 with his hero, so that in the end he shakes him off, so to speak, he washes his hands of him in the accepted fashion : Ivanov shoots himself in the sight of everybody, has not even time to go discreetly into a corner. The only justification of Ivaiiov is that caricature of honesty, Doctor Lvov. Lvov is not a living figure — that is obvious. But this is why he is remarkable. It is remarkable that Tchekhov should deem it necessary to resurrect the forgotten Staro- doum, that utterer of truisms in Fon-Visin's comedy ; and to resurrect him no longer that people may bow their heads before the incarnation of virtue, but so that they shall jeer at him. Look at Doctor Lvov ! Is he not Starodoum alive again f He is honesty personified. From force of old habit, honesty sticks his chest out, and speaks in a loud voice, with imperious tone, and yet not one of this old loyal subjects gives a brass farthing for him. They don't even trouble to gibe at him, but spit on him and shove him through the door, as a disgusting and impudent toady. Poor honesty ! What has he sunk to ! Evidently virtues, like everything else, should not live too long on earth. Tchekhov's " Uncle Vanya " is waiting 95 to throw himself on the neck of his friend and rival, the doctor, throw himself on his neck and sob there like a little child. But he finds that the doctor himself has an unquenchable thirst for consolation and encouragement, whilst poor Sonia can bear her maiden sorrows no longer. They all go wandering round with big, lost eyes, looking for someone to relieve them from part of their woes, at least. And lo, every- body is in the same street as themselves. All are over-heavy-laden, not one can carry his own burden, let alone give a lift to another's. The last consolation is taken away. It is no use complaining : there is no sympathetic response. On all faces the same expression of hopelessness and despair. Each must bear his cross in silence. None may weep nor utter pitiful cries — it would be uncalled-for and indecent. When Uncle Vanya, who has not realised at once the extremity of his situation, begins to cry out : " My life's a waste ! " nobody wants to listen to him. " Waste, waste ! Every- body knows it's a waste ! Shut your mouth, howling won't help you : neither will pistol-shots solve anything. Everyone of us might start your cry — but we don't, neither do we shout : 96 — I'ou think ni weep ; No, ril not weep : I have full cause of weeping. But this heart shall break into a hundred thousand flaws. Or ere Pll weep ; Fool, I shall go mad.^^ Gradually there settles down a dreadful, eternal silence of the cemetery. All go mad, without words, they realise what is happening within them, and make up their minds for the last shift : to hide their grief for ever from men, and to speak in commonplace, trivial words which will be accepted as sensible, serious, and even lofty expressions. No longer will anyone cry : " Life is a waste," and intrude his feelings on his neighbours. Everybody knows that it is shameful for one's life to be a waste, and that this shame should be hidden from every eye. The last law on earth is — loneliness .... Resigne-toi, mon cceur, dors ton sommeil de brute ! Groundless assumptions. — " Based on nothing," because they seem to derive from common assumption of the reasonableness of human existence, which assumption surely is the child of our desires, and probably a « 97 bastard at that ..... In his Miserly Knight Poushkin represented a miser as a romantic figure. Gogol, with his Plyushkin, creates on the contrary a repulsive figure of a miser. Gogol was nearer to reaHty, A miser is ugly, whatever view you take of him — inward or outward. Yet Gogol ought not to teach people to preserve in their age the ideals of their youth. Once old age is upon us — it must not be improved upon, much less apologised for. It must be accepted, and its essence brought to light. Plyushkin, the vulgar, dirty maniac is disgusting — but who knows ? perhaps he is fulfilling the serious mission of his own being. He is possessed by one desire — to everything else, to all happenings in the outer world he is indifferent. It is the same to him whether he is hungry or full, warm or cold, clean or dirty. Practically no event can distract his attention from his single purpose. He is disinterestedly mean, if one may say so. He has no need for his riches. He lets them rot in a disgusting heap, and does not dream, like Poushkin's knight, of palaces and power, or of sportive nymphs. Upon what end is he concentrated ? No one has tlie time to think it out. At the sight of Plyushkin everyone recalls the 98 damage the miser has done. Everyone of course is right : Plyushkins, who heap up fortunes to let them rot, are very harmful. The social judgment is nearly always to the point. But not quite always. It won't hurt morals and social considerations if at times they have to hold their tongue — and at such times we might succeed in guessing the riddle of meanness, sordidness, old age. 86 We have sufficient grounds for taking life mistrustfully : it has defrauded us so often of our cherished expectations. But we have still stronger grounds for mistrusting reason : since if life deceived us, it was only because futile reason let herself be deceived. Per- haps reason herself invented the deception, and then to serve her own ambitious ends, thre.v the blame on life, so that life shall appear sick-headed. But if we have to choose between life and reason, we choose life, and then we no longer need try to foresee and to explain, we can wait, and accept all that is unalterable as part of the game. And thus Nietzsche, having realised that all his hopes had gradually crumbled, and that he could never get back to his former strength, but must grow worse and worse 99 every day, wrote in a private letter of May 28, 1883: ^^ Ich will es so schwer haben, wie nuT irgend ein Mensch es hat ; erst unter diesem Drucke gewinne ich das gute Gewissen dafur, etzvas zu besitzen, das wenige Menschen haben und gehabt haben : Fliigel, um im Gleichnisse zu reden.''^ In these few simple words lies the key to the philo- sophy of Nietzsche. " So long as Apollo calls him not to the sacred offering, of all the trifling children of men the most trifling perhaps is the poet." Put Poushkin's expression into plain language, and you will get a page on neuropathology. All neurasthenic indi- viduals sink from a state of extreme excita- tion to one of complete prostration. Poets too : and they are proud of it. 88 Shy people usually receive their impres- sions post-dated. During those moments when an event is taking place before their eyes, they can see nothing, only later on, having evoked from their memory a frag- ment of what happened, they make for themselves an impression of the whole scene. 100 And then, retrospectively arise in their soul feelings of pity, offence, surprise, so vivid, as if they were the flames of the instant moment, not rekindlings from the past. Thus shy people always think a great deal, and are always too late for their work. It is never too late for thought. Timid before others, they reach great heights of daring when alone. They are bad speakers — but often excellent writers. Their life is insigni- ficant and tedious, they are not noticed, — until they become famous. And by the time fame comes, they do not need popular attention any more. 89 If Tchekhov's Layevsky, in 7he Duel^ had been a writer with a literary talent, people would have said of him that he was original, and that he was engaged in the study of the " mysticism of sex," like Gabriele D'Annunzio for example ; whereas, as he stands, he is only banal. His idleness is a reproach to him : people would prefer that at least he should copy out extracts from documents. loi . 90 . From observations on children. — Egoism in a man strikes us unpleasantly because it betrays our poverty. " I cannot dole out my abundance to my neighbour, for if I do I myself shall be left with little." We should like to be able to scatter riches with a royal hand ; and, therefore, when we see someone else clutching his rags with the phrase, " property is sacred," we are hurt. What is sacred comes from the gods, and the gods have plenty of everything, they do not count and skimp, like mortals. 91 We see a man repent for his actions, and conclude that such actions should be avoided : an instance of false, but apparently irreproachable reasoning. Time passes, and we see the same man repenting again of the self-same acts. If we love logic, this will confirm us in our first conclusion. But if we do not care for logic, we shall say : man is under an equal necessity to commit these acts, and to repent of them. Sometimes, however, the first conclusion is corrected differently. Having decided that repent- ance proves that a certain course of action should be avoided, man avoids it all his 102 life ; only to realise in the end, suddenly, with extraordinary clarity, how bitter is his regret that he has not trodden the for- bidden course. But by this time a new conclusion is already useless. Life is over, and the newly-enlightened mind no longer knows how to rid itself of the superfluous light. 92 A version of one of the scenes of Tolstoy's Power of Darkness reminds us exactly of a one-act piece of Maeterlinck. There can be no question of imitation. When the Power of Darkness was written nobody had heard of Maeterlinck. Tolstoy evidently Avanted to try a new method of creating, and to get rid of his own manner, which he had evolved through tens of years of dogged labour. But the risk was too great. He preferred to cure himself of his doubts by the common expedient, manual toil and an outdoor life. So he took up the plough. Every woodcock praises its own fen ; Lermontov saw the sign of spiritual pre- eminence in dazzling white linen, and there- fore his heroes always dressed with taste. Dostoevsky, on the other hand, despised 103 show : Dmitri Karamazov wears dirty linen — and this is assigned to him as a merit, or almost a merit. 94 While he was yet young, when he wrote his story, Enough, Turgenev saw that some- thing terrible hung over his life. He saw, but did not get frightened, although he understood that in time he ought to become frightened, because life without a continual inner disturbance would have no meaning for him. 95 Napoleon is reputed to have had a profound insight into the human soul ; Shakespeare also. And their vision has nothing in common. .96. . What we call imagination, which we value so highly in great poets — is, essentially, unbridled, loose, or if you will, even per- verted mentality. In ordinary mortals we call it vice ; but to the poets everything is forgiven on account of the benefit and pleasure we derive from their works. In spite of our high-flown theories we have always been extremely practical, great 104 utilitarians. Two-and-a-half-thousand years went by before Tolstoy got up, and, in his turn, offered the poets their choice : either to be virtuous, or to stop creating and forfeit the fame of teachers. If Tolstoy did not make a laughing-stock of himself, he has to thank his grey hairs and the respect which was felt for his past. Anyhow, nobody took him seriously. Far from it ; for never yet did poets feel so free from the shackles of morality as they do now. If Schiller were writing his dramas and philo- sophic essays to-day, he would scarcely find a reader. In Tolstoy himself it is not so much his virtues as his vices which we find interesting. We begin to understand his works, not so much in the light of his striving after ideals, but from the standpoint of that incongruity which existed between the ideas he artificially imposed upon him- self, and the demands of his own non- virtuous soul, which struggled ever for liberty. Nicolenka Irtenyev, in Childhood and 2'outh, would sit for hours on the terrace, turning over in his mind his elder brother Volodya's love-making with the chamber- maids. But, although he desired it '* more than anything on earih^^ he could never bring himself to be like Volodya. The maid 105 said to the elder brother, *' Why doesn't Nicolai Petrovitch ever come here and have a lark ? " She did not know that Nicolai Petrovitch was sitting at that moment under the stairs, ready to give anything on earth to take the place of the scamp Volodya. " Everything on earth " is twice repeated. Tolstoy gives a psychological explanation of his Httle hero's conduct. " I was timid by nature," Nicolenka tells us, " but my shyness was increased by the conviction of my ugliness." Ugliness, the conscious- ness of one's ugliness, leads to shyness ! What good can there be in virtue which has such a suspicious origin ? And how can the morality of Tolstoy's heroes be trusted f Consciousness of one's ugHness begets shy- ness, shyness drives the passions inwards and allows them no natural outlet. Little by little there develops a monstrous dis- crepancy between the imagination and its desires, on the one hand, and the power to satisfy these desires, on the other. Per- manent hunger, and a contracted alimentary canal, which does not pass the food through. Hence the hatred of the imagination, with its unrealised and unrealisable cravings. . , . In our day no one has scourged love so cruelly as Tolstoy in Pozver of Darkness, io6 But the feats of the village Don Juan need not necessarily end in tragedy. " More than anything on earth," however, Tolstoy hates the Don Juans, the handsome, brave, successful, the self-confident, who spon- taneously act upon suggestion, the con- querors of women, who stretch out their hands to living statues cold as stone. As far as ever he can he has his revenge on them in his writing. 97 In the drama of the future the whole presentation will be different. First of all, the difficulties of the denouement will be set aside. The new hero has a past — reminiscent — but no present ; neither wife, nor sweetheart, nor friends, nor occupation. He is alone, he communes only with himself or with imaginary listeners. He lives a life apart. So that the stage will represent either a desert island or a room in a large densely-populated city, where among millions of inhabitants one can live alone as on a desert island. The hero must not return to people and to social ideals. He must go forward to loneliness, to absolute loneliness. Even now nobody, looking at Gogol's Plyushkin, will feel any more the slightest 107 response to the pathetic appeal for men to preserve the ideals of youth on into old age. Modern youths go to see Plyushkin, not for the sake of laughing at him or of benefiting from the warning which his terrible miserly figure offers them, but in order to see if there may not be some few little pearls there where they could be least expected, in the midst of his heap of dirt. . . . Lycurgus succeeded in fixing the Spartans like cement for some centuries — but after that came the thaw, and all their hardness melted. The last remains of the petrified Doric art are now removed to museums. ... Is something happen- ing ? If I sow not in the spring, in autumn I shall eat no bread. Every day brings troubles and worries enough for poor, weak man. He had to forget his work for a moment, and now he is lost : he will die of hunger or cold. In order merely to preserve our existence we have to strain mind and body to tne utmost : nay more, we have to think of the surrounding world exclusively with a view to gaining a liveli- hood from it. There is no time to think about truth ! This is why positivism was 108 invented, with its theory of natural develop- ment. Really, everything we see is mysterious and incomprehensible. A tiny midge and a huge elephant, a caressing breeze and a blizzard, a young tree and a rocky mountain — what are all these ? What are they, why are they ? we incessantly ask ourselves, but we may not speak out. For philosophy is ever pushed aside to make room for the daily needs. Only those think who are unable to trouble about self-preservation, or who will not trouble, or who are too careless : that is, sick, desperate, or lazy people. These return to the riddle which workaday men, confirmed in the certainty that they are right, have construed into " naturalness." 99 Kant, and after him Schopenhauer, was exceedingly fond of the epithet " disin- terested," and used it on every occasion when the supply of laudatory terms he had at his disposal was exhausted. " Disin- terested thinking," which does not pursue any practical aim, is, according to Schopen- hauer, the highest ideal towards which man can strive. This truth he considered uni- versal, an a priori. But had he chanced 109 to be brought amongst Russian peasants he would have had to change his opinion. With them thoughts about destiny and the why and wherefore of the universe and infinity and so on, would by no means be considered disinterested, particularly if the man who devoted himself to such thoughts were at the same time to announce, as becomes a philosopher, that he claimed complete freedom from physical labour. There the philosopher, were he even Plato, would be stigmatised with the disgraceful nickname, " Idle-jack." There the highest activity is interested activity, directed towards strictly practical purposes; and if the peasants could speak learnedly, they would certainly call the principle upon which their judgment is founded an a priori. Tolstoy, who draws his wisdom from the folk-sources, attacks the learned for the very fact that they do not want to work, but arc disinterestedly occupied in the search for truth. 100 It is clear to any impartial observer that practically every man changes his opinion ten times a day. Much has been said on this subject, it has served for innumerable no satires and humorous sketches. Nobodv has ever doubted that it was a vice to be unstable is one's opinions. Three-fourths of our education goes to teaching us most carefully to conceal within ourselves the changeableness of our moods and judgments. A man who cannot keep his word is the last of men : never to be trusted. Likewise, a man with no firm convictions : it is im- possible to work together with him. Morality, here as always making towards utilitarian ends, issues the " eternal " principle : thou shalt remain true to thy convictions. In cultured circles this commandment is con- sidered so unimpeachable that men are terri- fied even to appear inconstant in their own eyes. They become petrified in their beliefs, and no greater shame can happen to them than that they should be forced to admit that they have altered in their convictions. When a straightforward man like Montaigne plainly speaks of the inconstancy of his mind and his views, he is regarded as a libeller of himself. One need neither see, nor hear, nor understand what is taking place around one : once your mind is made up, you have lost your right to grow, you must remain a stock, a statue, the qualities and defects of which are known to everybody. Ill lOI Every philosophic world-conception starts from some or other solution of the general problem of human existence, and proceeds from this to direct the course of human life in some particular direction or other. We have neither the power nor the data for the solution of general problems, and consequently all our moral deductions are arbitrary, they only witness to our prejudices if we are naturally timid, or to our pro- pensities and tastes if we are self-confident. But to keep up prejudices is a miserable, unworthy business : nobody will dispute that. Therefore let us cease to grieve about our differences in opinion, let us wish that in the future there should be many more differences, and much less unanimity. There is no arbitrary truth : it remains to suppose that truth lies in changeable human tastes and desires. In so far as our common social existence demands it — let us try to come to an understanding, to agree : but not one jot more. Any agreement which does not arise out of common necessity will be a crime against the Holy Spirit. 112 102 Tchekhov was very good at expounding a system of philosophy — even several systems. We have examples in more than one of his stories, particularly in fhe Duel, where Fon-Koren speaks ex cathedra. But Tchekhov had no use for such systems, save for purely literary purposes. When you write a story, and your hero must speak clearly and consistently, a system has its value. But when you are left to yourself, can you seriously trouble your soul about philosophy ? Even a German cannot, it seems, go so far in his " idealism." Vladimir Semionovitch, the young author in Tchekhov's Nice People^ sincerely and deeply believes in his own ideas, but even of him, notwithstanding his blatantly comical limitations, we cannot say more than that his ideas were constant little views or pictures to him, which had gradually become a second natural setting to everything he saw. Certainly he did not live by ideas, Tchekhov is right when he says that the singing of Gaudeamus igitur and the writing of a humanitarian appeal were equally important to Vladimir Semionovitch. As soon as Vladimir's sister begins to think for herself, her brother's highest ideas, H 113 which she has formerly revered, become banal and objectionable to her. Her brother cannot understand her, neither her hostility to progress and humanitarianism, nor to the university spree and Gandeamus igitur. But Tchekhov does understand. Only, let us admit, the word " understand " does not carry its ordinary meaning here. So long as the child was fed on its mother's milk, everything seemed to it smooth and easy. But when it had to give up milk and take to vodka, — and this is the inevitable law of human development — the childish suckling dreams receded into the realm of the irretrievable past. 103 The summit of human existence, say the philosophers, is spiritual serenity, aeq^ianiniitas. But in that case the animals should be our ideal, for in the matter of imperturbability they leave nothing to be desired. Look at a grazing sheep, or a cow. The\' do not look before and after, and sigh for what is not. Given a good pasture, the present suffices them perfectly. 114 104 A hungry man was given a piece of bread, and a kind word. The kindness seemed more to him than the bread. But had he been given only the kind word and no bread, he would perhaps have hated nice phrases. Therefore, caution is always to be recom- mended in the drawing of conclusions : and in none more than in the conclusion that truth is more urgently required than a consoling lie. The connections of isolated phenomena can very rarely be discerned. As a rule, several causes at once produce one effect. Owing to our propensity for idealising, we always make prominent that cause which seems to us loftiest. 105 A strange anomaly ! we see thousands of human beings perish around us, yet we walk warily lest we crush a worm. The sense of compassion is strong in us, but it is adapted to the conditions of our existence. It can relieve an odd case here and there — and it raises a terrific outcry over a trifling injustice. Yet Schopenhauer wanted to make compassion the metaphysical basis of morality. 115 io6 To discard logic as an instrument, a means or aid for acquiring knowledge, would be extravagant. Why should we ? For the sake of consequentialism ? i.e. for logic's very self ? But logic, as an aim in itself, or even as the only means to know- ledge, is a different matter. Against this one must fight even if he has against him all the authorities of thought — beginning with Aristotle. 107 " When the yellowing corn-fields sway and are moved, and the fresh forest utters sound to the breeze . . . then I see happiness on earth, and God in heaven." It may be so, to the poet ; but it may be quite different. Sometimes the corn-field waves, the woods make noise in the wind, the stream whispers its best tales : and still man cannot perceive happiness, nor forget the lesson taught in childhood, that the blue heavens are only an optical illusion. But if the sky and the boundless fields do not convince, is it possible that the arguments of Kant and the commentations of his dozens of talent- less followers can do anything ? 116 io8 The greatest temptation. — In Dostoevsky^s Grand Inquisitor lurks a dreadful idea. Who can be sure, he says — metaphorically, of course — that when the crucified Christ uttered His cry : " Lord, why hast thou forsaken me ? " He did not call to mind the temptation of Satan, who for one word had offered Him dominion over the world ? And, if Jesus recollected this offer, how can we be sure that He did not repent not having taken it ? . . . One had better not be told about such temptations. 109 From the Future Opinions concerning con- temporary Europe.''^ — " Europe of the nine- teenth and twentieth centuries presented a strange picture. After Luther, Christianity degenerated into morality, and all the threads connecting man with God were cut. Together with the rationalisation of religion, all life took on a flat, rational character. Knights were replaced by a standing army, recruited on the principle of compulsory military service for all, and existing chiefly for the purpose of parades and official needs. Alchemy, which had been trying to find the philosopher's stone, was replaced by 117 chemistry, which tried to discover the best means for cheap preparation of cheap com- modities. Astrology, which had sought in the stars the destinies of men, was replaced by astronomy, which foretold the eclipses of the sun and the appearing of comets. Even the dress of the people became strangely colourless ; not only men, but women also wore uniform, monochromatic clothes. Most remarkable of all, that epoch did not notice its own insignificance, but was even proud of itself. It seemed to the man of that day that never before had the common treasury of spiritual riches been so well replenished. We, of course, may smile at their naivete, but if one of their own number had allowed himself to express an opinion disdainful of the bases of the contemporary culture he would have been declared immoral, or put away in a mad-house : a terrible punish- ment, very common in that coarse period, though now it is very difficult even to imagine what such a proceeding impHed. But in those days, to be known as immoral, or to find oneself in a mad-house, was worse than to die. One of the famous poets of the nineteenth century, Alexander Poushkin, said : ' God forbid that I should go mad. Rather let me be a starving beggar.' In ii8 those times people, on the whole, were compelled to tell lies and play the hypocrite, so that not infrequently the brightest minds, who saw through the shams of their epoch, yet pretended to believe in science and morality, only in order to escape the persecu- tion of public opinion." no JFritcrs of tragedies on Shakespeare'^ s model. — To obtain a spark, one must strike with all one's might with an iron upon a stone. Whereupon there is a loud noise, which many are inclined to believe more important than the little spark. Similarly, writers having shouted very loudly, are deeply assured that they have fulfilled their sacred mission, and are amazed that all do not share their raptures, that some even stop their ears and run away. Ill IMetamor phases. — Sense and folly arc not at all native qualities in a man. In a crisis, a stupid man becomes clever. We need not go far for an example. What a gaping simpleton Dostoevsky looks in his Injured and htsulted, not to mention Poor Folk. But in Letters from the Underworld 119 .Tud the rest of his books he is the shrewd- est and cleverest of writers. The same may be said of Nietzsche, Tolstoy, or Shakespeare. In his Birth of Tragedy Nietzsche seems just like the ordinary honest, rather simple, blue-eyed provincial German student, and in Zarathustra he reminds one of Machiavelli. Poor Shakespeare got himself into a row for his Brutus — but no man could deny the great mind in Hamlet. The best instance of all, however, is Tolstoy. Right up to to-day, whenever he likes he can be cleverer than the cleverest. Yet at times he is a schoolboy. This is the most interesting and enviable trait in him. 112 In Troilus and Cressida Thersites sa)'s : " Shall the elephant Ajax carry it thus ? He beats me, and I rail at him : worthy satisfaction ! would it were otherwise ; that I could beat him, whilst he railed at me." Dostoevsky might have said the same of his opponents. He pursued them with stings, sarcasm, abuse, and they drove him to a white heat by their quiet assurance and composure. . . . The present-day ad- mirers of Dostoevsky quietly believe in the teachings of their master. Does it not 120 mean that de facto they liave betrayed him and gone over to the side of his enemies. 113 . The opinion has gained ground that Turgenev's ideal women — Natalie, Elena, Marianna — are created in the image and likeness of Poushkin's Tatyana. The critics have been misled by external appearances. To Poushkin his Tatyana appears as a vestal guarding the sacred flame of high morality — because such a job is not fitting for a male. The Pretender in Boris Godunov says to the old monk Pimen, who preaches meekness and submission : " But you fought under the walls of Kazan, etc." That is a man's work. But in the hours of peace and leisure the fighter needs his own hearth- side, he must feel assured that at home his rights are safely guarded. This is the point of Tatyana's last words : " I belong to another, and shall remain forever true to him." But in Turgenev woman appears as the judge and the reward, sometimes even the inspirer of victorious man. There is a great difference. 121 114 trom a German I ntroduciion to Philosophy. — " We shall maintain the opinion that meta- physics, as the crown of the particular sciences, is possible and desirable, and that to it falls the task intermediate between theor}- and practice, experiment and anticipa- tion, mind and feeling, the task of weighing probabilities, balancing arguments, and reconciling difficulties." Thus metaphysics is a weighing of probabilities. Ergo — further than probable conclusions it cannot go. Thus why do metaphysicians pretend to universal and obligatory, established and eternal judgments ? They go beyond them- selves. In the domain of metaphysics there cannot and must not be any established behefs. The word established loses all its sense in the connection. It is reasonable to speak of eternal hesitation and temporality of thought. 115 From another Introduction to Philosophy, also German. " Compared with the delusion of the materiaHsts ... the wretchedest worshipper of idols seems to us a being capable of apprehending to a certain degree the great meaning and essence of things." .. Perhaps this thought strayed in accidentally 122 among the huge herd of the other thoughts of the professor, soHttle does it resemble the rest. But even so, it loses none of its interest. If the materialists here spoken of, those of the nineteenth century, Biichner, Vogt, Mole- schot, all of them men who stood on the pinnacle of natural science, were capable of proving in the realm of philosophy more uninformed than the nakedest savage, then it follows, not only that science has nothing in common with philosophy, but that the two are even hostile. Therefore we ought to go to the savages, not to civilise them, hut even to learn philosophy from them. A Papuan or a Tierra del Fuegan delivering a lecture in philosophy to the professors of the Berlin University — Friedrich Paulsen, for example — is a curious sight. I say to Friedrich Paulsen, and not to Biichner or Moleschot, because Paulsen is also an educated person, and therefore his philosophic sensibility may have suffered from contact with science, even if not so badly as that of the materialists. He needs the assistance of a red-skin. :t" • master. Why have German professors so little daring or enterprise ? Why should not Paulsen, on his own in- itiative, go to Patagonia lo perfect himself in philosophy ? — or at least send his pupils 123 there, and preach broadcast the new pil- grimage. And now lo and behold he has hatched an original and fertile idea, so he will stick in a corner with it, so that even if you wanted you could not get a good look at it. The idea is important and weighty : our philosophers would lose nothing by sitting at the feet of the savages. ii6 From a History of Ethics. — " Doubts concerning the existence or the possibility of discovering a moral norm have, of course (I underline it), proved a stimulus to a new speculative establishing of ethics, just as the denial of the possibility of knowledge led to the discovery of the condition of knowledge." With this proposition the author does not play hide-and-seek, as Paulsen with his. He places it in a con- spicuous position, in a conspicuous section of his book, and accompanies it with the trumpeting herald " of course." But only one thing is clear : namely, that the majority share the opinion of Professor Yodl, to whom the quoted words belong. So that the first assumption of ethics has as its foundation the consensus sapientium. It is enough. 124 "7 " The normative theory," which has taken such hold in Germany and Russia, bears the stamp of that free and easy self-assurance which characterises the state of content- ment, and which does not desire, even for the sake of theoretical perfection, to take into consideration the divided state of soul which usually accompanies discontent. Windelband (Pradudien, p. 313) is evidence of this. He exposes himself with the naive frankness almost of an irrational creature, and is not only unashamed, but even proud of his part. " Philosophic research," he says, *' is possible only to those who are convinced that the norm of the universal imperative is supreme above individual activities, and that such a norm is discover- able." Not every witness will give evidence so honestly. It amounts to this : that philosophic research is not a search after truth, but a conspiracy amongst people who dethrone truth and exalt instead the all-binding norm. The task is truly ethical : morality always was and always will be utilitarian and bullying. Its active principle is : He who is not with us, is against us. 125 Ii8 " Ifj besides the reality which is evident to us, we were susceptible to another form of reality, chaotic, lawless, then this latter could not be the subject of thought." (Riehl — Philosophie der Gegenzvart.) This is one of the a priori of critical philosophy — one of the unproved first assumptions, evi- dently. It is only an expression in other words of Windelband's assertion quoted above, concerning the ethical basis of the law of causation. Thus, the a priori of contemporary thought convince us more and more that Nietzsche's instinct was not at fault. The root of all our philosophies lies, not in our objective observations, but in the demands of our own heart, in the subjective, moral will, and therefore science cannot be uprooted except we first destroy morality. 119 One of the lofty truisms — " The philoso- pher conquers passion by perceiving it, the artist by bodying it forth." In German it sounds still more lofty : but does not for that reason approach any nearer to the truth. " Der Philosoph iiherzvindet die Leidenschaft, indem er sie begreift — der 126 Kiinstler, indem er sie darsfeJIt.^^ (Windel- band, Praehidien, p. 198.) 120 The Germans always try to get at Allgemeingultigkeit . Well, if the problem of knowledge is to fathom all the depths of actual life, then experience, in so far as it repeats itself, is uninteresting, or at least has a limit of interest. It is necessary, however, to know what nobody yet knows, and therefore we must walk, not on the common road of AllgemeingiiltigkeiL, but on new tracks, which have never yet seen human feet. Thus rnorality, which lays down definite rules and thereby guards life for a time from any surprise, exists only by convention, and in the end collapses before the non-moral surging-up of individual human aspirations. Laws — all of them — have only a regulating value, and are neces- sary only to those who want rest and security. But the first and essential con- dition of life is lawlessness. Laws are a refreshing sleep — lawlessness is creative activity. 127 121 A =3 A. — They say that logic does not need this postulate, and could easily develop it by deduction. I think not. On the contrary, in my opinion, logic could not exist without this premiss. Meanwhile it has a purely empirical origin. In the realm of fact, A is always more or less equal to A. But it might be otherwise. The uni- verse might be so constituted as to admit of the most fantastic metamorphoses. That which now equals A would successively equal B and then C, and so on. At present a stone remains long enough a stone, a plant a plant, an animal an animal. But it might be that a stone changed into a plant before our eyes, and the plant into an animal. That there is nothing unthinkable in such a supposition is proved by the theory of evolution. This theory only puts cen- turies in place of seconds. So that, in spite of the risk to which I expose myself from the admirers of the famous Epicurean system, I am compelled to repeat once more that anything you please may come from anything you please, that A may not equal A, and that consequently logic is dependent, for its soundness, on the empirically-derived law of the unchangeableness of the external 128 world. Admit the possibility of super- natural interference — and logic will lose that certitude and inevitability of its conclusions which at present is so attractive to us. 122 The effort to understand people, life, the universe prevents us from getting to know them at all. Since "to know" and "to understand" are two concepts which are not only non-identical, but just the opposite of one another in meaning ; in spite of their being in constant use as synonyms. We think we have understood a phenomenon if we have included it in a list of others, previously known to us. And, since all our mental aspiration reduces itself to under- standing the universe, we refuse to know a great deal which will not adapt itself to the plane .urface of the contemporary world- conceptions. For instance the Leibnitz question, put by Kant into the basis of the critique of reason i " How can we know a thing outside us, if it does not enter into us ? " It is non-understandable ; that is, it does not agree with our notion of under- standing. Hence it follows that it must be squeezed out of the field of view — which is exactly what Kant attempted to do. To I 129 us it seems, on the contrary, that in the interests of knowing we should sacrifice, and gladly, understanding, since under- standing in any case is a secondary affair. — Zu fragmentarish ist Welt und Leben / . . . 1 30 PART II Nur fur Schwindeljreie. (From Alpine Recollections.) I Light reveals to us beauty — but also ugli- ness. Throw vitriol in the face of a beautiful woman, and the beauty is gone, no power on earth will enable us to look upon her with the same rapture as before. Could even the sincerest, deepest love endure the change ? True, the idealists will hasten to say that love overcomes all things. But idealism needs be prompt, for if she leaves us one single moment in which to see^ we shall see such things as are not easily explained away. That is why idealists stick so tight so logic. In the twinkling of an eye logic will convey us to the remotest con- clusions and forecasts. Reality could never overtake her. Love is eternal, and conse- quently a disfigured face will seem as lovely to us as a fresh one. This is, of course, a lie, but it helps to preserve old tastes and obscures danger. Real danger, however, was never dispelled by words. In spite of Schiller and eternal love, in the long run 133 vitriol triumphs, and the agreeable young man is forced to abandon his beloved and acknowledge himself a fraud. Light, the source of his life and hope, has now destroyed hope and life for him. He will not return to idealism, and he will hate logic : light, that seemed to him so beautiful, will have become hideous. He will turn to darkness, where logic and its binding conclusions have no power, but where the fancy is free for all her vagaries. Without light we should never have known that vitriol ruins beauty. No science, nor any art can give us what darkness gives. It is true, in our young days when all was new, light brought us great happiness and joy. Let us, there- fore, remember it with gratitude, as a benefactor we no longer need. Do after all let us dispense with gratitude, for it belongs to the calculating, bourgeois virtues. Do ut des. Let us forget light, and gratitude, and the qualms of self-important idealism, let us go bravely to meet the coming night. She promises us great power over reality. Is it worth while to give up our old tastes and lofty convictions ? Love and light have not availed against vitriol. What a horror would have seized us at the thought, once upon a time ! That short phrase 134 can annul all Schiller. We have shut our eyes and stopped our ears, we have built huge philosophic systems to shield us from this tiny thought. And now — now it seems we have no more feeling for Schiller and the great systems, we have no pity on our past beliefs. We now are seeking for words with which to sing the praises of our former enemy. Night, the dark, deaf, impenetrable night, peopled with horrors — does she not now loom before us, infinitely beautiful ? Does she not draw us with her still, mysteri- ous, fathomless beauty, far more powerfully than noisy, narrow day ? It seems as if, in a short while, man will feel that the same incomprehensible, cherishing power which threw us out into the universe and set us, like plants, to reach to the light, is now gradually transferring us to a new direction, where a new life awaits us with all its stores. Fata volentem ducunt, nolentem trahunt. And perhaps the time is near when the impassioned poet, casting a last look to his past, will boldly and gladly cry : Hide thy s elf y sun ! darkness ^ be welcome ! 135 2 Psychology at last leads us to conclude that the most generous human impulses spring from a root of egoism. Tolstoy's " love to one's neighbour," for example, proves to be a branch of the old self-love. The same may be said of Kant's idealism, and even of Plato's. Though they glorify the service of the idea, in practice they succeed in getting out of the -vicious circle of egoism no better than the ordinary mortal, who is neither a genius nor a flower of culture. In my eyes this is " almost " an absolute truth. (It is never wrong to add the retractive " almost " ; truth is too much inclined to exaggerate its own import- ance, and one must guard oneself against its despotic authority.) Thus — all men are egoists. Hence follows a great deal. I even think this proposition might provide better grounds for metaphysical conclusions than the doubtful capacity for compassion and love for one's neighbour which has been so tempting to dogma. For some reason men have imagined that love for oneself is more natural and comprehensible than love for another. Why ? Love for others is only a little rarer, less widely diffused than love to oneself. But then hippopotami 136 and rhinoceros, even in their own tropical regions, are less frequent than horses and mules. Does it follow that they are less natural and transcendental ? Positivism is not incumbent upon blood-thirsty savages. Nay, as we know, many of them are less positive-minded than our learned men. For instance, a future life is to them such an infallible reality that they even enter into contracts, part of which is to be fulfilled in the next world. A German metaphy- sician won't go as far as that. Hence it follows that the way to know the other world is not by any means through love, sympathy, and self-denial, as Schopenhauer taught. On the contrary, it appears as if love for others were only an impediment to metaphysical flights. Love and sympathy chain the eye to the misery of this earth, where such a wide field for active charity opens out. The materialists were mostly very good men — a fact which bothered the historians of philosophy. They preached Matter, believed in nothing, and were ready to perform all kinds of sacrifices for their neighbours. How is this ? It is a case of clearest logical consequence : man loves his neighbour, he sees that heaven is indifferent to misery, therefore he takes upon himself the role of Providence. Were he indifferent to the sufferings of others, he would easily become an idealist and leave his neighbours to their fate. Love and compassion kill belief, and make a man a positivist and a materialist in his philo- sophical outlook. If he feels the misery of others, he leaves off meditating and wants to act. Man only thinks properly when he realises he has nothing to do, his hands arc tied. That is why any profound thought must arise from despair. Optimism, on the other hand, the readiness to jump hastily from one conclusion to another, may be regarded as an inevitable sign of narrow self-sufficiency, which dreads doubt and is consequently always superficial. If a man offers you a solution of eternal questions, it shows he has not even begun to think about them. He has only " acted." Perhaps it is not necessary to think — who can say how we ought or ought not to live ? And how could we be brought to live " as we ought," when our own nature is and always will be an incalculable mystery. There is no mis- take about it, nobody wants to think. I do not speak here of logical thinking. That, like any other natural function, gives man great pleasure. For this reason 138 philosophical systems, however complicated, arouse real and permanent interest in the public provided they only require from man the logical exercise of the mind, and nothing else. But to think — really to think — surely this means a relinquishing of logic. It means living a new life. It means a permanent sacrifice of the dearest habits, tastes, attachments, without even the assur- ance that the sacrifice will bring any com- pensation. Artists and philosophers like to imagine the thinker with a stern face, a profound look which penetrates into the unseen, and a noble bearing — an eagle preparing for flight. Not at all. A think- ing man is one who has lost his balance, in the vulgar, not in the tragic sense. Hands raking the air, feet flying, face scared and bewildered, he is a caricature of help- lessness and pitiable perplexity. Look at the aged Turgenev, his Poems in Prose and his letter to Tolstoy. Maupassant thus tells of his meeting with Turgenev : " There entered a giant with a silvery head." Quite so ! The majestic patriarch and master, of course ! The myth of giants with silver locks is firmly established in the heart of man. Then suddenly enters Turgenev in his Prose Poems — pale, pitiful, fluttering 139 f like a bird that has been " winged." Tur- genev, who has taught us everything — how can he be so fluttered and bewildered ? How could he write his letter to Tolstoy ? Did he not know that Tolstoy was finished, the source of his creative activity dried up, that he must seek other activities. Of course he knew — and still he wrote that letter. But it was not for Tolstoy, nor even for Russian literature, which, of course, is not kept going by the death-bed letters and covenants of its giants. In the dreadful moments of the end, Turgenev, in spite of his noble size and silver locks, did not know what to say or where to look for support and consolation. So he turned to literature, to which he had given his life. . . . He yearned that she, whom he had served so long and loyally, should just once help him, save him from the horrible and thrice sense- less nightmare. He stretched out his withered, numbing hands to the printed sheets which still preserve the traces of the soul of a living, suffering man. He addressed his late enemy Tolstoy with the most flattering name : *' Great writer of the Russian land " ; recollected that he was his contemporary, that he himself was a great writer of the Russian land. But this he 140 did not express aloud. He only said, " I can no longer " He praised a strict school of literary and general education. To the last he tried to preserve his bearing of a giant with silv.ery locks. And we were gratified. The same persons who are indig- nant at Gogol's correspondence, quote Tur- genev's letter with reverence. The attitude is everything. Turgenev knew how to pose passably well, and this is ascribed to him as his greatest merit. Mundus vult decipi, ergo decipiatur. But Gogol and Turgenev felt substantially the same. Had Turgenev burnt his own manuscripts and talked of himself instead of Tolstoy, before death, he would have been accounted mad. Moral- ists would have reproached him for his display of extreme egoism. . . . And Phil- osophy ? Philosophy seems to be getting rid of certain prejudices. At the moment when men are least likely to play the hypocrite and lie to themselves Turgenev and Gogol placed their personal fate higher than the destinies of Russian literature. Does not this betray a " secret " to us ? Ought we not to see in absolute egoism an inalienable and great, yes, very great quality of human nature 2 Psychology, ignoring the threats of morality, has led us to a new knowledge. 141 Yet still, in spite of the instances we have given, the mass of people will, as usual, see nothing but malice in every attempt to reveal the human impulses that underlie " lofty " motives. To be merely men seems humiliating to men. So now malice will also be detected in my interpretation of Turgenev's letter, no matter what assurance I offer to the contrary. 3 On Method. — A certain naturalist made the following experiment : A glass jar was divided into two halves by a perfectly transparent glass partition. On the one side of the partition he placed a pike, on the other a number of small fishes such as form the prey of the pike. The pike did not notice the partition, and hurled itself on its prey, with, of course, the result only of a bruised nose. The same happened many times, and always the same result. At last, seeing all its efforts ended so pain- fully, the pike abandoned the hunt, so that in a few days, when the partition had been removed it continued to swim about among the small fry without daring to attack them. . . . Does not the same happen with us ? Perhaps the limits between " this 142 world " and " the other world " are also essentially of an experimental origin, neither rooted in the nature of things, as was thought before Kant, or in the nature of our reason, as was thought after Kant. Perhaps indeed a partition does exist, and make vain all attempts to cross over. But perhaps there comes a moment when the partition is removed. In our minds, however, the con- viction is firmly rooted that it is impossible to pass certain limits, and painful to try : a conviction founded on experience. But in this case we should recall the old scepticism of Hume, which idealist philosophy has regarded as mere subtle mind-play, value- less after Kant's critique. The most lasting and varied experience cannot lead to any binding and universal conclusion. Nay, all our a priori, which are so useful for a certain time, become sooner or later extremely harmful. A philosopher should not be afraid of scepticism, but should go on bruising his jaw. Perhaps the failure of metaphysics lies in the caution and timidity of metaphysicians, who seem ostensibly so brave. They have sought for rest — which thev describe as the hiehest boon. Whereas they should have valued more than anything restlessness, aimlessness, even 143 purposelessness. How can you tell when the partition will be removed ? Perhaps at the very moment when man ceased his painful pursuit, settled all his questions and rested on his laurels, inert, he could with one strong push have swept through the pernicious fence which separated him from the unknowable. There is no need for man to move according to a carefully- considered plan. This is a purely sesthetic demand which need not bind us. Let man senselessly and deliriously knock his head against the wall — if the wall go down at last, will he value his triumph any the Ie?s ? Unfortunately for us the illusion has been established in us that plan and purpose are the best guarantee of' success. What a delusion it is ! The opposite is true,, The best of all that genius has revealed to us has been revealed as the resiJt of fantastic, erratic, apparently ridiculous and useless, but relentlessly ytubbom seeking. Columbus, tired of sitting on the same spot, sailed west to look for India. And genius, in spite of vulgar conception, is a condition of chaos and unutterable restlessness, Not for nothing has genius been counted kin to madness. Genius flings itself hitner and thither because it has not the Sitzfleisch 144 necessary for industrious success in medio- crity. We may be sure that earth has seen much more genius than history has recorded ; since genius is acknowledged only when it has been serviceable. When the tossing-about has led to no useful issue — which is the case in the majority of instances — it arouses only a feeling of disgust and abomination in all witnesses. " He can't rest and he can't let others rest." If Lermontov and Dostoevsky had lived in times when there was no demand for books, nobody would have noticed them. Ler- montov*s early death would have passed unregretted. Perhaps some settled and virtuous citizen would have remarked, weary of the young man's eternal and dangerous freaks : " For a dog a dog's death." The same of Gogol, Tolstoy, Poushkin. Now they are praised because they left interesting books. . . . And so we need pay no atten- tion to the cry about the futility and worth- lessness of scepticism, even scepticism pure and unadulterated, scepticism which has no ulterior motive of clearing the way for a new creed. To knock one's head against the wall out of hatred for the wall : to beat against established and obstructive ideas, because one detests them : is it not K 145 an attractive proposition ? And then, to see ahead uncertainly and limitless possi- bilities, instead of up-to-date " ideals," is not this too fascinating ? The highest good is rest ! I shall not argue : de gustibus aut nihil aut bene. . . . By the way, isn't it a superb principle ? And this superb principle has been arrived at perfectly by chance, unfortunately not by me, but by one of the comical characters in Tchek- hov's Seagull. He mixed up two Latin proverbs, and the result was a splendid maxim which, in order to become an a priori, awaits only universal acceptance. 4 Metaphysicians praise the transcendental, and carefully avoid it. Nietzsche hated metaphysics, he praised the earth — bleib nur der Erde treu, meine Bruder — and always lived in the realm of the transcen- dental. Of course the metaphysicians be- have better : this is indisputable. He who would be a teacher must proclaim the meta- physical point of view, and he may become a hero without ever smelling powder. In these anxious days, when positivism seems to fall short, one cannot do better than turn to metaphysics. Then the young man need 146 not any more envy Alexander the Mace- donian. With the assistance of a few books not only earthly states are conquered, but the whole mysterious universe. Metaphysics is the great art of swerving round dangerous experience. So metaphysicians should be called the positivists far excellence. They do not despise all experience, as they assert, but only the dangerous experiences. They adapt the safest of all methods of self- defence, what the English call protective mimicry. Let us repeat to all students — professors know it already : he who v\ould be a sincere metaphysician must avoid risky experience. Schiller once asked : How can tragedy give delight ? The answer — to put it in our own words — was : If we are to obtain delight from tragedy, it must be seen only upon the stage. — In order to love the transcendental it also should be known only from the stage, or from books of the philosophers. This is called idealism, the nicest word ever invented by philoso- phising men. 5 Poetae nascuntur. — Wonderful is man. Knowing nothing about it, he asserts the existence of an objective impossibility. Even a little while ago, before the invention of H7 the telephone and telegraph, men would have declared it impossible for Europe to converse with America. Now it is possible. We cannot produce poets, therefore we say they are born. Certainly we cannot make a child a poet by forcing him to study literary models, from the most ancient to the most modern. Neither will anybody hear us in America no matter how loud we shout here. To make a poet of a man, he must not be developed along ordinary lines. Perhaps books should be kept from him. Perhaps it is necessary to perform some apparently dangerous operation on him : fracture his skull or throw him out of a fourth-storey window. I will refrain from recommending these methods as a substitute for paedagogy. But that is not the point. Look at the great men, and the poets. Except John Stuart Mill and a couple of other positivist thinkers, who had learned fathers and virtuous mothers, none of the great men can boast of, or better, complain of, a proper upbringing. In their lives nearly always the decisive part was played by accident, accident which reason would dub meaninglessness, if reason ever dared raise its voice against obvious success. Something like a broken 148 skull or a fall from the fourth floor— not metaphorically, but often absolutely literally — has proved the commencement, usually concealed but occasionally avowed, of the activity of genius. But we repeat auto- matically : poetae nascuntur, and are deeply convinced that this extraordinary truth is so lofty it needs no verification. 6 " Until Apollo calls him to the sacrifice, ignobly the poet is plunged in the cares of this shoddy world ; silent is his lyre, cold sleeps his soul, of all the petty children of earth most petty it seems is he." Pisaryev, the critic, was exasperated by these verses. Presumably, if they had not belonged to Poushkin, all the critics along with Pisaryev would have condemned them and their author to oblivion. Suspicious verse ! Before Apollo calls to him — the poet is the most insignificant of mortals ! In his free hours, the ordinary man finds some more or less distinguished distraction for himself : he hunts, attends exhibitions of pictures, or the theatre, and finally rests in the bosom of his family. But the poet is incapable of normal existence. Im- mediately he has finished with Apollo, 149 forgetting all about altars and sacrifices, he proceeds to occupy himself with unworthy objects. Or he abandons himself to the dolce far niente, the customary pastime of all favourites of the Muses. Let us here remark that not only all poets, blit all writers and artists- in general are inclined to lead bad lives. Think what Tolstoy tells us, in Confession and elsewhere, of the best representatives of literature in the fifties. On the whole it is just as Poushkin says in his verses. Whilst he is engaged in composition, an author is a creature of some consequence : apart from this, he is nothing. Why are Apollo and the Muses so remiss ? Why do they draw to themselves wayward or vicious votaries, instead of rewarding virtue ? We dare not suspect the gods, even the de- throned, of bad intentions. Apollo loved virtuous persons — and yet virtuous persons are evidently mediocre and unfit for the sacred offices. If any man is overcome with a great desire to serve the god of song, let him get rid of his virtues at once. Curious that this truth is so completely unknown to men. They think that through virtue they can truly deserve the favour and choice of Apollo. And since industry is 150 the first virtue, they peg away, morning, noon, and night. Of course, the more they work the less they do. Which really puzzles and annoys them. They even fling aside the sacred arts, and all the labours of a devotee ; they give themselves up to idleness and other bad habits. And sometimes it so happens, that just as a man decides that it is all no good, the Muses suddenly visit him. So it was with Dostoevsky and others. Schiller alone managed to get round Apollo. But perhaps it was only his biographers he got round. Germans are so trustful, so easy to deceive. The biographers saw nothing unusual in Schiller's habit of keeping his feet in cold water whilst he worked. No doubt they felt that if the divine poet had lived in the Sahara, where water is precious as gold, and the inspired cannot take a footbath every day, then the speeches of the Marquis of Pola would have lacked half their noble- ness, at least. And apparently Schiller was not so wonderfully chaste, if he needed such artificial resources in the composition of his fine speeches. In a word, we must believe Poushkin. A poet is, on the one hand, among the elect; on the other hand, he is one of the most insignificant of mortals. Hence we can draw a very consoling con- clusion : the most insignificant of men are not altogether so worthless as we imagine^ They may not be fit to occupy government positions or professorial chairs, but they are often extremely at home on Parnassus and such high places. Apollo rewards vice, and virtue, as everybody knows, is so satisfied with herself she needs no reward. Then why do the pessimists lament ? Leibnitz was quite right : we live in the best possible of worlds. I would even suggest that we leave out the modification ** possible." It is Das Ewig fVeibltche, with Russian writers. Poushkin and Lermontov loved women and were not afraid of them. Poush- kin, who trusted his own nature, was often in love, and always sang his love of the moment. When infatuated with a bacchante, he glorified bacchantes. When he married, he warbled of a modest, nun- like beauty, his wife. A synthesising mind would probably not know what to do with all Poushkin's sorts of love. Nor is Lermon- tov any better. He abused women, but, as Byelinsky observed after meeting him, he loved women more than anything in 152 the world. And again, not women of one mould only : any and all attractive females : the wild Bella, the lovely Mary, Thamar ; one and all, no matter of what race or condition. Every time Lermontov is in love, he assures us his love is so deep and ardent and even moral, that we cannot judge him without conpunction. Vladimir Soloviov alone was not afraid to condemn him. He brought Poushkin as well as Lermontov to account for their moral irregularities, and he even went so far as to say that it was not he himself who judged them, but Fate, in whose service he acted as public denouncer. Lermontov and Poush- kin, both dying young, had deserved death for their frivolities. But there was nobody else besides Vladimir Soloviov to darken the memories of the two poets. It is true Tolstoy cannot forgive Poushkin's dissolute life, but he does not apply to Fate for a verdict. According to Tolstoy morality can cope even with a Titan like Poushkin. In Tolstoy's view morality grows stronger the harder the job it has to tackle. It pardons the weak offenders without waste of words, but it never forgives pride and self-confi- dence. If Tolstoy's edicts had been executed, all memorials to Poushkin would have 153 disappeared; chiefly because of the poet's addiction to the eternal female. In such a case Tolstoy is implacable. He admits the the kind of love whose object is the establish- ing of a family, but no more. Don Juan is a hateful transgressor. Think of Levin, and his attitude to prostitutes. He is exasper- ated, indignant, even forgets the need for compassion, and calls them " beasts." In the eternal female Tolstoy sees temptation, seduction, sin, great danger. Therefore it is necessary to keep quite away from the danger. But surely danper is the dragon which guards every treasure on caith. And again, no matter what his precautions, a man will meet his fate sooner or later, and come into conflict with the dragon. Surely this is an axiom. Pous'hkin and Lermontov loved danger, and therefore sought women. They paid a heavy price, but while they lived they lived freely and lightly. If they had cared to peep in the book of destinies, they might have averted or avoided their sad end. But they pre- ferred to trust their star — lucky or unlucky. Tolstoy was the first among us — we cannot speak of Gogol — who began to fear life. He was the first to start open moralising. In so far as public opinion and personal IS4 dignity demand it, he did go to meet his dangers : but not a step further. So he avoided women, art, and philosophy. Love per se, that is, love which does not lead to a family, like wisdom per se, which is wisdom that has no utilitarian motive, and like art for art^s sake, seemed to him the worst of temptations, leading to the destruction of the soul. When he plunged too deep in thinking, he was seized with panic. *' It seemed to me I was going mad, so I went away to the Bashkirs for koumiss." Such confessions are common in his works. And surely there is no other way with temptations, than to cut short, at once, before it is too late. Tolstoy preserved himself on account of his inborn instinct for departing betimes from a dangerous situation. Save for this cautious prompting he would probably have ended like Ler- montov or Poushkin. True, he might have gone deeper into nature, and revealed us rare secrets, instead of preaching at us abstinence, humility, simplicity and so on. But such luck fell to the fate of Dostoevsky. Dostoevsky had very muddled relations with morality. He was too racked by disease and circum- stance to get much profit out of the rules of morality. The hygiene of the soul, 155 like that of the body, is beneficial only to healthy men. To the sick it is simply harmful. The more Dostoevsky engaged himself with high morality, the more in- extricably entangled he became. He wanted to respect the personality in a woman, and only the personality, and so he came to the point where he could not look on any woman, however ugly, with indifference. The elder Karamazov and his affair with Elizabeth Smerdyascha (Stinking Lizzie) — in what other imagination could such a union have been contemplated ? Dostoevsky, of course, reprimands Karamazov, andthanks to the standards of modern criticism, such a reprimand is accounted sufficient to exonerate our author. But there are other standards. If a writer sets out to tell you that no drab could be so loathsome that her ugliness would make you forget she was woman; and if for illustration of this novel idea we are told the history of Fiodov Karamazov with the deformed, repulsive idiot. Stinking Lizzie ; then, in face of such '' imaginative art " it is surely out of place to preserve the usual confidence in that writer. We do not speak of the interest and appreciation of Dostoevsky's tastes and ideas. Not for one moment Vv'ill 156 I assert that those who with Poushkin and Lermontov can see the Eternal Female only in young and charming women, have any advantage over Dostoevsky. Of course, we are not forbidden to live according to our tastes, and we may, like Tolstoy, call certain women " beasts." But who has given us the right to assert that we arc higher or better than Dostoevsky ? Judging " objectively," all the points go to show that Dostoevsky is better — at any rate he saw further, deeper. He could find an original interest, he could discover das etvig Weihliche where we should see nothing of attraction at all, where Goethe would avert his face. Stinking Lizzie is not a beast, as Levin would say, but a woman who is able, if even for a moment, to arouse a feeling of love in a man. And we thought she was worse than nothing, since she roused in us only disgust. Dostoevsky made a dis- covery, we with our refined feelings missed it. His distorted, abnormal sense showed a greater sensitiveness, in which our high morality was deficient. . . . And the road to the great truth this time, as ever, is through deformity. Idealists will not agree. They are quite justly afraid that one may not reach the truth, but may get stuck in 157 the mud. Idealists are careful men, and not nearly so stupid as their ideals would lead us to suppose. 8 New ideas, even our own, do not quickly conquer our sympathies. We must first get accustomed to them. 9 :A point of view. — Every writer, thinker — even every educated person thinks it necessary to have a permanent point of view. He climbs up some elevation and never climbs down again all his days. What- ever he sees from this point of view, he believes to be reality, truth, justice, good — and what he does not see he excludes from existence. Man is not much to blame for this. Surely there is no very great joy in moving from point of view to point of view, shifting one's camp from peak to peak. We have no wings, and " a winged thought " is only a nice metaphor — unless, of course, it refers to logical thinking. There to be sure great volatility is usual, a lightness which comes from perfect naivete, if not ignorance. He who really wishes to know something, and not merely to have 158 a philosophy, does not rely on logic and is not allured by reason. He must clamber from summit to summit, and, if necessary, hibernate in the dales. For a wide horizon leads to illusions, and in order to familiarise oneself with any object, it is essential to go close up to it, touch it, feel it, examine it from top to bottom and on every side. One must be ready, should this be impossible otherwise, to sacrifice the customary position of the body : to wriggle, to He flat, to stand on one's head, in a word, to assume the most unnatural of attitudes. Can there be any question of a permanent point of view ? The more mobility and elasticity a man has, the less he values the ordinary equilibrium of his body ; the oftener he changes his outlook, the more he will take in. If, on the other hand, he imagines that from this or the other pinnacle he has the most comfortable survey of the world and life, leave him alone ; he will never know anything. Nay, he does not want to know, he cares more about his personal convenience than about the quality of his work. No doubt he will attain to fame and success, and thus brilliantly justify his " point of view." 159 10 Fame. — " A thread from everyone, and the naked will have a shirt." There is no beggar but has his thread of cotton, and he will not grudge it to a naked man — no, nor even to a fully dressed one ; but will bestow it on the first comer. The poor, who want to forget their poverty, are very ready with their threads. Moreover, they prefer to give them to the rich, rather than to a fellow-tramp. To load the rich with benefits, must not one be very rich indeed ? That is why fame is so easily got. An ambitious person asks admiration and respect from the crowd, and is rarely denied. The mob feel that their throats are their own, and their arms are strong. Why not voci- ferate and clap, seeing that you can turn the head not only of a beggar like yourself, but of a future hero, God knows how almighty a person. The humiliated citizen who has hitherto been hauled off to the police station if he shouted, suddenly feels that his throat has acquired a new value. Never before has anyone given a rap for his worth- less opinion, and now seven cities are ready to quarrel for it, as for the right to claim Homer. The citizen is delighted, he shouts at the top of his voice, and is ready to throw i6o all his possessions after his shouts. So the hero is satisfied. The greater the shout, the deeper his belief in himself and his mission. What will a hero not believe ! For he forgets so soon the elements of which his fame and riches are made. Heroes usually are convinced that they set out on their noble career, not to beg shouts from beggars, but to heap blessings on mankind. If they could only call to mind with what beating hearts they awaited their first applause, their first alms, how timidly they curried favour with ragged beggars, perhaps they would speak less assuredly of their own merits. But our memory is fully acquainted with Herbert Spencer and his law of adaptability, and thus many a worthy man goes gaily on in full belief in his own stupendous virtue. II In defence of righteousness. — Inexperienced and ingenuous people see in righteousness merely a burden which lofty people have assumed out of respect for law or for some other high and inexplicable reason. But a righteous man has not only duties but rights. True, sometimes, when the law is against him, he has to compromise. Yet how rarely does the law desert him ! No L i6i cruelty matters in him, so long as he does not infringe the statutes. Nay, he will ascribe his cruelty as a merit to himself, since he acts out of no personal considera- tions, but in the name of sacred justice. No matter what he may do, once he is sanctioned he sees in his actions only merit, merit, merit. Modesty forbids him to say too much — but if he were to let go, what a luxurious panegyric he might deliver to himself ! Remembering his works, he praises himself at all times ; not aloud, but in- wardly. The nature of virtue demands it : man must rejoice in his morality and ever keep it in mind. And after that, people declare that it is hard to be righteous. Whatever the other virtues may be, certainly righteousness has its selfish side. As a rule it is decidedly worth while to make con- siderable sacrifices in order later on to enjoy in calm confidence all that surety and those rights bestowed on a man by morality and public approval. Look at a German who has paid his contribution to a society for the assistance of the indigent. Not one stray farthing will he give, not to a poor wretch who is starving before his eyes. And in this he feels right. This is righteousness out and out : pay your tax and enjoy the 162 privileges of a high-principled man. So righteousness is much in vogue with cul- tured, commercial nations. Russians have not quite got there. They are afraid of the exactions of righteousness, not guessing the enormous advantages derived. A Rus- sian has a permanent relationship with his conscience, which costs him far more than the most moral German, or even Englishman, has to pay for his righteous- ness. 12 The best way of getting rid of tedious, played-out truths is to stop paying them the tribute of respect and to treat them with a touch of easy familiarity and derision. To put into brackets, as Dostoevsky did, such words as good, self-sacrifice, progress, and so on, will alone achieve you much more than many brilliant arguments would do. Whilst you still contest a certain truth, you still believe in it, and this even the least penetrating individual will perceive. But if you favour it with no serious attention, and only throw out a scornful remark now and then, the result is different. It is evident you have ceased to be afraid of the old truth, you no longer respect it. And this sets people thinking. 163 13 . . Four zvalls. — Arm-chair philosophy is being condemned — rightly. An arm-chair thinker is busy deciding on everything that is taking place in the world : the state of the world market, the existence of a world- soul, wireless telegraphy and the life after death, the cave dweller and thie perfecti- bility of man, and so on and so on. His chief business is so to select his statements that there shall be no internal contradiction ; and this will give an appearance of truth. Such work, which is quite amusing and even interesting, leads at last to very poor results. Surely verisimilitudes of truth are not truth : nor have necessarily anything in common with truth. Again, a man who undertakes to talk of everything probably knows noth- ing. Thus a swan can fly, and walk, and swim. But it flies indifferently, walks badly, and swims poorly. An arm-chair philo- sopher, enclosed by four walls, sees nothing but those four walls, and yet of these pre- cisely he does not choose to speak. If by accident he suddenly realised them and spoke of them his philosophy might acquire an enormous value. This may happen when a study is converted into a prison : the same four walls, but impossible not to 164 think of them ! Whatever the • prisoner turns his mind to — Homer, the Greek- Persian wars, the future world-peace, the bygone geological cataclysms — still the four walls enclose it all. The calm of the study supplanted by the pathos of imprisonment. The prisoner has no more contact with the world, and no less. But now he no longer slumbers and has grayish dreams called world-conceptions. He is wide awake and strenuously living. His philosophy is worth hearing. But man is not distinguished for his powers of discrimination. He sees soli- tude and four walls, and says : a study. He dreams of the market-place, where there is noise and jostling, physical bustle, and decides that there alone life is to be met. He is wrong as usual. In the market- place, among the crowd, do not men sleep their deadest sleep ? And is not the keenest spiritual activity taking place in seclusion ? H The Spartans made their helots drunk as an example and warning to their noble youths. A good method, no doubt, but what are we of the twentieth century to do ? Whom shall we make drunk ? We have no slaves, so we have instituted a higher 165 literature. Novels and stories describe drunken, dissolute men, and paint them in such horrid colours that every reader feels all his desire for vice depart from him. Unfortunately only our Russians are either too conscientious or not sufficiently recti- linear in their minds. Instead of showing the drunken helot as an object of repugnance, as the Spartans did, they try to describe vice truthfully. Realism has taken hold. Indeed, why make a fuss ? What does it matter if the writer's description is a little more or less ugly than the event ? Was justice invented that everything, even evil, should be kept intact ? Surely evil must be simply rooted out, banned, placed outside the pale. The Spartans did not stand on ceremony with living men, and yet our novelists are afraid of being unjust to imaginary drunken helots. And, so to speak, out of humane feeling too. . . . How naive one must be to accept such a justifica- tion ! Yet everybody accepts it. Tolstoy alone, towards the end, guessed that humani- tarianism is only a pretext in this case, and that we Russians have described vice not only for the purpose of scaring our readers. In modern masters the word vice arouses not disgust, but insatiable curiosity. i66 Perhaps the wicked thing has been per- secuted in vain, like so many other good things. Perhaps it should have been studied, perhaps it held mysteries. . . . On the strength of this " perhaps '* morality was gradually abandoned, and Tolstoy remained almost alone in his indignation. Realism reigns, and a drunken helot arouses envy in timid readers who do not know where to put their trust, whether in the traditional rules or in the appeal of the master. A drunken helot an ideal ! What have we come to ? Were it not better to have stuck to Lycurgus ? Have we not paid too dearly for our progress ? Many people think we have paid too dearly — not to mention Tolstoy, who is now no longer taken quite seriously, though still accounted a great man. Any mediocre journalist enjoys greater influence than this master-writer of the Russian land. It is inevitable. Tolstoy insists on think- ing about things which are nobody's concern. He has long since abandoned this world — > and does he continue to exist in any other ? Difficult question ! " Tolstoy writes books and letters, therefore he exists." This inference, once so convincing, now has hardly any effect on us : particularly if we 167 take into account wKat it is that Tolstoy writes. In several of his last letters he expresses opinions which surely have no meaning for an ordinary man. They can be summed up in a few words. Tolstoy pro- fesses an extreme egoism, sollipsism, solus- ipse-ism. That is, in his old age, after infinite attempts to love his neighbour, he comes to the conclusion that not only is it impossible to love one's neighbour, but tha: there is no neighbour, that in all the world Tolstoy alone exists, that there is even no world, but only Tolstoy : a view so obviously absurd, that it is not worth refuting. By the way, there is also no possibility of refuting it, unless you admit that logical inferences are non-binding. Sollipsism dogged Tolstoy already in early youth, but at that time he did not know what to do with the impertinent, oppres- sive idea, so he ignored it. Finally, he came to it. The older a man becomes, the more he learns how to make use of imper- tinent ideas. Fairly recently Tolstoy could pronounce such a dictum : '* Christ taught men not to do stupid things." Who but Tolstoy could have ventured on such an interpretation of the gospels ? Why have we all held — all of us but Tolstoy — that these i68 words contained the greatest blasphemy on Christ and His teaching ? But it was Tolstoy's last desperate attempt to save himself from sollipsism, without at the same time flying in the face of logic : even Christ appeared among men only to teach them common sense. Whence follows that " mad " thoughts may be rejected with an easy conscience, and the advantage, as usual, remains with the wholesome, reasonable, sensible thoughts. There is room for good and for reason. Good is self-understood; it need not be explained. If only good existed in the world, there would exist no questions, neither simple nor ultimate. This is why youth never questions. What indeed should it question : the song of the night- ingale, the morning of May, happy laughter, all the predicates of youth ? Do these need interpretation ? On the contrary, any explanation is reduced to these The proper questions arise only on contact with evil. A hawk struck a nightingale, flowers withered, Boreas froze laughing youth — and in terror our questions arose. '^ That is evil. The ancients were right. Not in vain is our earth called a vale of tears and sorrow." And once questions are started, it is im- possible and unseemly to hurry the answers, 169 still less anticipate the questions. Tfie nightingale is dead and will sing no longer, the listener is frozen to death and can hear no more songs. The situation is so palp- ably absurd that only with the intention of getting rid of the question at any cost wull one strive for a sensible answer. The answer must be absurd — if you don't want it, don't question. But if you must question, then be ready beforehand to reconcile yourself with something like sollipsism or modern realism. Thought is in a dilemma, and dare not take the leap to get out. We laugh at philosophy, and, as long as possible, avoid evil. But nearly all men feel the intolerable cramp of such a situation, and each at his risk ventui:es to swim to shore on some more or less witty theory. A few courageous ones speak the truth — but they are neither understood nor respected. When a man's words show the depth of the pain through which he has passed, he is not, indeed, condemned, but the world begins to talk of his tragic state of soul, and to take on a mournful look fitting to the occasion. Others more scrupu- lous feel that phrases and mournful looks are unfitting, yet they cannot dwell at length on the tragedies of outsiders, so they 170 take on an exaggeratedly stern bearing, as if to say, " We feel deeply, but we do not wish to show our feeling." They really feel nothing, only want to make others beheve how sensitive and modest they are. At times this leads to curious results, even in writers of the first order of renown. Thus Anatole France, the inventor of that most charming smile which is intended to con- vince men that he feels everything and under- stands everything, but does not cry out, because that would not be fitting, in one of his novels takes upon himself the noble role of advocate of the victims of a crime, against the criminal. *"' Our time," he says, " out of pity to the criminal forgets the sufferings of his victim." This, I repeat, is one of the most curious misrepresentations of modern endeavour. It is true we in Russia talk a good deal about compassion, particu- larly to criminals, and Anatole France is by no means the only man who thinks that our distinguishing characteristic is extreme sensitiveness and tender-heartedness. But as a matter of fact the modern man who thinks for himself is not drawn to the crim- inal by a sense of compassion, which would incontestably be better applied to the victim, but by curiosity, or if you like, inquisitive- ness. For thousands of years man has sought to solve the great mystery of Hfe through a God-conception — with theodicy and metaphysical theories as a result, both of which deny the possibility of a mystery. Theodicy has long ago wearied us. The mechanistic theories, which contend that there is nothing special in life, that its appear- ance and disappearance depend on the same laws as those of the conservation of energy and the indestructibility of matter, these look more plausible at first sight, but people do not take to them. And no theory can survive men's reluctance to believe in it. In a word, good has not justified the expectations placed on it. Reason has done no better. So overwrought mankind has turned from its old idols and enthroned madness and evil. The smiling Anatole argues, and proves — proves excel- lently. But who does not know what his proofs amount to ? — and who wants them ? It may be our children will take fright at the task we have undertaken, will call us " squandering parents," and will set them- selves again to heaping up treasures, spiritual and material. Again they will believe in ideals, progress, and such like. For my own part, I have hardly any doubt of it. 172 Solllpsism and the cult of groundlessness are not lasting, and, most of all, they are not to be handed down. The final triumph, in life as in old comedies, rests with goodness and common sense. History has known many epochs like ours, and gone through with them. Degeneration follows on the heels of immoderate curiosity, and sweeps away all refined and exaggerately well- informed individuals. Men of genius have no posterity — or their children are idiots. Not for nothing is nature so majestically serene : she has hidden her secrets well enough. Which is not surprising, consid- ering how unscrupulous she is. No despot, not the greatest villain on earth, has ever wielded power with the cruelty and heart- lessness of nature. The least violation of her laws — and the severest punishment follows. Disease, deformity, madness, death — what has not our common mother con- trived to keep us in subjection .? True, certain optimists think that nature does not punish us, but educates us. So Tolstoy sees it. " Death and sufferings, like ani- mated scarecrows, boo at man and drive him into the one way of life open to him : for life is subject to its own law of reason." Not a bad method of upbringing. Exactly m like using wolves and bears. Unfortunate man, bolting from one booing monster, is not always able in time to dodge into the one correct way, and dashes straight into the maw of another beast of prey. Then what ? And this often happens. With- out disparagement of the optimists, we may say that sooner or later it happens to every man. After which no more running. You won't tear yourself out of the claws of madness or disease. Only one thing is left : in spite of traditions, theodicy, wiseacres, and most of all in spite of oneself, to go on praising mother nature and her great goodness. Let future generations re- ject us, let history stigmatise our names, as the names of traitors to the human cause — still we will compose hymns to deformity, destruction, madness, chaos, darkness. And after that — let the grass grow. ^5 Astrology and alchemy lived their day and died a natural death. But they left a posterity — chemistry inventing dyes, and astronomy accumulating formulae. So it is. Geniuses beget idiots : especially when the mothers are very virtuous, as in this case, 174 when their virtue is extraordinary. For the mothers are pubHc utility and morality. The alchemists wasted their time seeking the philosopher's stone ; the astrologers, swindled people telling fortunes by the stars. Wedded to utility these two fathers have begotten the chemists and astronomers. . . . Nobody will dispute the genealogy. Perhaps even none will dispute that; from idiotic children one may, with a measure of probability, infer genius in the parents. There are certain indications that this is so — though of course one may not go beyond supposition. But supposition is enough. There are more arguments in store. For instance — our day is so convinced of the absolute nonsense and uselessness of alchemy and astrology that no one dreams of verifying the conviction. We know there were many charlatans and liars amongst alchemists and astrologers. But what does this prove ? In every department there are the same mediocre creatures who specu- late on human credulity. However positive our science of medicine is, there are many fraudulent doctors who rob their patients. The alchemists and astrologers were, in all probability, the most remarkable men of their time. I will go further : in spite of 175 dye-stuffs and formulae, even In our nine- teenth century, which was so famous for its inventions and discoveries, the most eminent, talented men still sought the philosopher's stone and forecast the destinies of man. And those among them who were possessed of a poetic gift won universal attention. In the old days, consensu sapientium, a poet was allowed all kinds of liberties : he might speak of fate, miracles, spirits, the life beyond — indeed of anything, provided he was interesting. That was enough. The nineteenth century paid its tribute to restlessness. Never were there so many disturbing, throbbing writers as during the epoch of telephones and tele- graphs. It was held indecent to speak in plain language of the vexed and troubled aspirations of the human spirit. Those guilty of the indecency were even dosed with bromides and treated with shower-baths and concentrated foods. But all this is external, it belongs to a history of " fashions " and cannot interest us here. The point is that alchemy and astrology did not die, they only shammed death and left the stage for a time. Now, apparently, they are tired of seclusion and are coming forward again, having pushed their unsuccessful children into the 176 background. Well, so be it. A la honne he lire / . . . i6 Man comes to the pass where all experi- ence seems exhausted. Wherever he go, whatever he see, all is old and wearyingly familiar. Most people explain this by say- ing that they really knov/ everything, and that from what they have experienced they can infer all experience. This phase of the exhaustion of life usually comes to a man between thirty-five and forty — the best period, according to Karamzin. Not seeing anything new, the individual assumes he is completely matured and has the right to judge of everything. Knowing what has been he can forecast what will be. But Karamzin was mistaken about the best period, and the " mature " people are mistaken about the " nothing new can happen." The fact of spiritual stagnation should not be made the ground for judging all life's possibilities from known possibilities. On the contrary, such stag- nation should prove that however rich and multifarious the past may have been, it has not exhausted a tittle of the whole possi- biHties. From that which has been it is impossible to infer what will be. Moreover, •M 177 it is unnecessary — except, perhaps, to give us a sense of our full maturity and let us enjoy all the charms of the best period of life, so eloquently described by Karamzin. The temptation is not overwhelming. So that, if man is under the necessity of endur- ing a period of arrest and stagnation, and until such time as life re-starts is doomed to meditation, would it not be better to use this meditating interregnum for a directly oppo- site purpose from the one indicated : that is to say, for the purpose of finding in our past signs which tell us that the future has every right to be anything whatsoever, like or utterly unlike the past. Such signs, given a good will to find them, may be seen in plenty. At times one comes to the conclusion that the natural connection of phenomena, as hitherto observed, is not at all inevitable for the future, and that miracles which so far have seemed impossible, may come to seem possible, even natural, far more natural than that loathsome law of sequence, the law of the regularity of phenomena. We are bored stiff with regu- larity and sequence — confess it, you also, you men of science. At the mere thought that, however we may think, we can get no further than the acknowledgment of 178 the old regularity, an invincible disgust to any kind of mental work overcomes us. To discover another law — still another — when already we have far more than we can do with ! Surely if there is any will- to-think left in us, it is estabHshed in the supposition that the mind cannot and must not have any bounds, any limits ; and that the theory of knowledge, which is based on the history of knowledge and on a few very doubtful assumptions, is only a piece of property belonging to a certain caste, and has nothing to do with us others — und die Natur zuletzt sich doch ergrunde. What a mad impatience seizes us at times when w^e realise that we shall never fathom the great mystery ! Every individual in the world must have felt at one time the mad desire to unriddle the universe. Even the stodgy philosophers who invented the theory of knowledge have at times made surreptitious sorties, hoping to open a path to the unknown, in spite of their own fat, senseless books that demonstrate the advan- tages of scientific knowledge. Man either lives in continuous experience, or he frees himself from conclusions imposed by limited experience. All the rest is the devil. From the devil come the blandishments with 179 which Karamzin charmed himself and his readers. ... Or is it the contrary r Who will answer ! Once again, as usual, at the end of a pathetic speech one is left with a conjecture. Let every man please himself. But what about those who would like to live according to Karamzin, but cannot ? I cannot speak for them. Schiller recom- mended hope. Will it do ? To be frank, hardly. He who has once lost his peace of mind will never find it again. Ever since Kant succeeded in convincing the learned that the world of phenomena is quite other than the world of true reality, and that even our own existence is not our real existence, but only the visible mani- festation of a mysterious, unknown sub- stance (substantia) — philosophy has been stuck in a new rut, and cannot move a single millimetre out of the track laid out by the great Konigsbergian. Backward or forward it can go, but necessarily in the Kantian rut. For how can you get out of the counterposing of the phenomenon against the thing-in-itself ? This proposition, this counterposing seems inalterable, so there is nothing left but to stick your head in the 180 heavy draught-collar of the theory of know- ledge. Which most philosophers do, even with a glad smile, which inevitably rouses a suspicion that they have got what they wanted, and their " metaphysical need " was nothing more than a need for a harness. Otherwise they would have kicked at the sight of the collar. Surely the contra- position between the world of phenomena and the thing-in-itself is an invention of the reasoning mind, as is the theory of knowledge deduced from this contraposing. Therefore the freedom-loving spirit could reject it in the very beginning — and basta I With the devil one must be very cautious. We know quite well that if he only gets hold of the tip of your ear he will carry off your whole body. So it is with Reason. Grant it one single assumption, admit but one proposition — and finita la commedia. You are in the toils. Metaphysics cannot exist side-by-side with reason. Everything meta- physical is absurd, everything reasonable is — positive. So we come upon a dilemma. The fundamental predicate of metaphysics is absurdity : and yet surely many positive assertions can- lay legitimate claim to that self-same, highly-respectable predicate. What then ? Is there means of distin- i8i guishing a metaphysical absurdity from a perfectly ordinary one ? May one have recourse to criteria ? Will not the very criterion prove a pitfall wherein cunning reason will catch the poor man who was rushing out to freedom ? There can be no two answers to this question. All services rendered by reason must be paid for sooner or later at the exorbitant price of self- renunciation. Whether you accept the assist- ance in the noble form of the theory of knowledge, or merely as a humble criterion, at last you will be driven forth into the streets of positivism. This happens all the time to young, inexperienced minds. They break the bridle and dash forward into space, to find themselves rushing into the same old Rome, whither, as we know, all roads lead : or, to use more lofty language, rushing into the stable whither also all roads lead. The only way to guard against positivism — granting, of course, that positivism no longer attracts your sympathies — is to cease to fear any absurdities, whether rational or metaphysical, and systematically to reject all the services of reason. Such behaviour has been known in philosophy ; and I make bold to recommend it. Credo quia absurduvL comes from the Middle Ages. Modern 182 instances are Nietzsche and Schopenhauer. Both present noble examples of indifference to logic and common-sense : particularly Schopenhauer, who, a Kantian, even in the name of Kant made such daring sallies against reason, driving her into confusion and shame. That astounding Kantian even went so far, in the master's name still, as to attempt the overthrow of the space and time notions. He admitted clairvoyance — and to this day the learned are bothered whether to class that admission among the metaphysical or the ordinary absurdities. Really, I can't advise them, A very clever man insists on an enormous absurdity, so I am satisfied. Schopenhauer's whole cam- .paign against intellect is very comforting. It is evident that, though he set out from the Kantian stable, he soon got sick of hauling along down the cart-ruts, and having broken the shafts, he trotted jauntily into a jungle of irreconcilable contradictions, without reflecting in the least where he was making for. The primate of will over reason; and music as the expression of our deepest essence ; are not these assertions sufficient to show us how dexterously he wriggled out from the harness of synthetic judgments a priori which Kant had placed 183 upon every thinker. There Is indeed much more music than logic in the philosophy of Schopenhauer. Not for nothing is he excluded from the universities. But of course one may speak of him in the open ; not of his ideas, naturally, but of his music. The European market is glutted with ideas. How neat and nicely-finished and logically well-turned-out those ideas are. Schopenhauer had no such goods. But what lively and splendid contradictions he boldly spreads on his stall, often even without suspicion that he ought to hide them from the police. Schopenhauer cries and laughs and gets furious or glad, without ever realising that this is forbidden to a philosopher. " Do not speak, but sing," said Zarathustra, and Schopenhauer really fulfilled the command in great measure. Philosophy may be music — though it doesn't follow that music may be called philosophy. When a man has done his work, and gives himself up to looking and listening and pleasantly accepting everything, hiding noth- ing from himself, then he begins to " philo- sophise." What good are abstract formulae to him ? Why should he ask himself, before he begins to think : " What can I think about, what are the limits of 184 thought ? " He will think, and those who like can do the summing up and the build- ing of theories of knowledge. What is the earthly use of talking about beauty ? Beautiful things must be created. Not one single aesthetic theory has so far been able to guess what direction the artists' mind will next take, or what are the limits to his creative activity. The same with the theory of knowledge. It may arrest the work of a man of learning, if he be him- self afraid that he is going too far, but it is powerless to pre-determine human thought. Even Kant's counterposing of things-in- themselves to the world of phenomena cannot finally clip the wings of human curiosity. There will come a time when this unshakeable foundation of positivism will be shaken. All gnosiological disputes as to what thought can or cannot achieve will seem to our posterity just as amusing as the disputes of the schoolmen seem to us. *' Why did they argue about the nature of truth, when they might have gone out and looked for truth itself ? " the future histor- ians will ask. Let us have an answer ready for them. Our contemporaries do not want to go out and seek, so they make a great deal of talk about a theory of knowledge. 185 i8 " Trust not thyself, young dreamer." — However sincerely you may long for truth, whatever sufferings and horrors you may have surpassed, do not believe your own self, young dreamer. What you are looking for, you won't find. At the utmost, if you have a gift for writing you will bring out a nice original book. Even — do not be offended — you may be satisfied with such a result. In Nietzsche's letters relating to the year 1888, the year when Brandes dis- covered him, you will find a sad confirma- tion of the above. Had not Nietzsche struggled, sought, suffered ? — and behold, towards the end of his life, when it would have seemed that all mundane rewards had become trivial to him, he threw himself with rapture on the tidings of first fame, and rushed to share his joy with all his friends, far and near. He does not tire of telling in dozens of letters and in varying forms the story of how Brandes first began his lectures on him, Nietzsche, how the audience con- sisted of three hundred people, and he even quotes Brandes' placard announcement in the original Danish. Fame just threw him a smile, and forgotten are all the horrible experiences of former days. The loneliness, 186 the desertedness, the cave in the mountain, the man into whose mouth the serpent dimbed — all forgotten, every thought turned to the ordinary, easily-comprehensible good. Such is man. Mit gier'ger Hand nach Schdtzen grdbt Und froh ist zcenn er Regenzvurmer findet. When a man is young he writes because it seems to him he has discovered a new almighty truth which he must make haste to impart to forlorn mankind. Later, be- coming more modest, he begins to doubt his truths : and then he writes to convince himself. A few more years go by, and he knows he was mistaken all round, so there is no need to convince himself. Neverthe- less he continues to write, because he is not fit for any other work, and to be accounted a " superfluous " man is so horrible. 20 A very original man is often a banal writer, and vice versa. We tend so often to write not about what is going on in us, but of our pia desideria. Thus restless, sleepless men sing the glory of sleep and rest, which 187 have long been sung to death. x\nd those who sleep ten hours on end and are always up to the mark must perforce dream about adventures and storms and dangers, and even extol everything problematical. 21 When one reads the books of long-dead men, a strange sensation comes over one. These men who lived two hundred, three hundred, three thousand years ago are so far off now from this writing which they have left on earth. Yet we look for eternal truths in their works. 22 The truth which I have the right to announce so solemnly to-day, even to the first among men, will probably be a stale old lie on my lips to-morrow. So I will deprive myself of the right of calling such a truth my own. Probably I shall deprive no one but myself : others will go on loving and praising the self-same truth, living with it. 23 A writer who cannot lie with inspiration — and that is a great art, which few may accomplish — loves to make an exhibition 188 of honesty and frankness. Nothing else Is left him to do. 24 The source of originality. — A man who has lost all hope of rooting out of himself a certain radical defect of character, or even of hiding the flaw from others, turns round and tries to find in his defect a certain merit. If he succeeds in convincing his acquaint- ances, he achieves a double gain : first, he quiets his conscience, and then he acquires a reputation for being original. .25 Men begin to strive towards great ends when they feel they cannot cope with the little tasks of life. They often have their measure of success. 26 A belch interrupts the loftiest meditation. You may draw a conclusion if you like : if you don't like, you needn't. 27 . A woman of conviction. — We forgive a man his " convictions," however unwillingly. It goes without saying that we balk at any individual who believes in his own 189 infallibility, but one must' reconcile oneself with necessity. It is ugly and preposterous to have corns on one's hands, but still, J they can't be avoided in this unparadisal earth of sweat and labour. But why see an ideal in callosities ? In practical life, particularly in the social political life to j which we are doomed, convictions are a I necessity. Unity is strength, and unity ' is possible only among people who think alike. Again, a deep conviction is in itself a strong force, far more powerful than the most logical argumentation. Sometimes one has only to pronounce in a full, round, vibrating chest voice, such as is peculiar to people of conviction, some trifling sentence, and an audience hitherto unconvinced is carried away. Truth is often dumb, particularly a new truth, which is most shy of people, and which has a feeble, hoarse voice. But in certain situations that which will influence the crowd is more important than that which is genuine truth. Convictions are necessary to a public man : but he who is too clever to believe in himself entirely, and is not enough of an actor to look as if he believed, he had best give up public work altogether. At the same time he will realise that lack of 190 convictions is not profitable, and will look with more indulgence on such as are bound to keep themselves well supplied. Yet all the more will he dislike those men who without any necessity disfigure themselves with the coarse tattoo marks. And particularly he will object to such women. What can be more intolerable than a woman of conviction. She lives in a family, without having to grind for her daily bread — why disfigure herself ? Why wilfully rub her hands into corns, when she might keep them clean and pretty ! Women, moreover, usually pick up their convictions ready- made from the man who interests them most at the moment. And never do they do this so vigorously as when the man himself seems incapable of paving the way to his ideas ! They are full of feeling for him; they rush to the last extremities of resource. Will not their feeble little fists help him ? It may be touching, but in the end it is intolerable. So it is much pleasanter to meet a woman who believes in her husband and does not consider it necessary to help him. She can then dispense with convictions. 191 28 Emancipation of women. — The one and only way of mastering an enemy is to learn the use of his weapons. Starting from this, modern woman, weary of being the slave of man, tries to learn all his tricks. Hard is slavery, wonderful is freedom ! Slavery at last is so unendurable that a human being will sacrifice everything for freedom. Of what use are his virtues to a prisoner languishing in prison ? He has one aim, one object — to get out of prison, and he values only such qualities in himself as will assist his escape. If it is necessary to break an iron grating by physical force, then strong muscles will seem to the prisoner the most desirable of all things. If cunning will help him, cunning is the finest thing on earth. Something the same happens with woman. She became convinced that man owed his priority chiefly to education and a trained mind, so she threw herself on books and universities. Learning that promises freedom is light, everything else darkness. Of course, it is a delusion, but you could never convince her of it, for that Vv'ould mean the collapse of her best hopes of freedom. So that in the end woman will be as v/ell-informed ashman, she will furnish 192 herself with broad views and unshakeable convictions, with a philosophy also — and in the end she may even learn to think logically. Then, probably, the many mis- understandings between the sexes will cease. But heavens, how tedious it will be ! Men will argue, women will argue, children will probably be born fully instructed, under- standing everything. With what pain will the men of the future view our women, capricious, frivolous, uninformed creatures, understanding nothing and desiring to under- stand nothing. A whole half of the human race neither would nor could have any understanding ! But the hope lies there. Maybe we can do without understanding. Perhaps a logical mind is not an attribute, but a curse. In the struggle for existence, however, and the survival of the fittest, not a few of the best human qualities have perished. Obviously woman's illogicality is also destined to disappear. It is a thou- sand pities. All kinds of literature are good, except the tedious, said Voltaire. We may en- large the idea. All men and all activities are good, except the tedious. Whatever your failings and your vices, if you are N 193 only amusing or interesting all is forgiven you. Accordingly, frankness and natural- ness are quite rightly considered doubtful virtues. If people say that frankness and naturalness arc virtues, always take it cum grano salts. Sometimes it is per- missible and even opportune to fire off truth of all sorts. Sometimes one may stretch oneself like a log across the road. But God forbid that such sincere practices should be raised into a principle. To out with the truth at all times, always to reveal oneself entirely, besides being impossible to accomplish, never having been accom- plished even in the confessions of the greatest men, is moreover a far more risky business than it seems. I can confidently assert that if any man tried to tell the whole truth about himself, not metaphorically, for every metaphor is a covering ornament, but in plain bare words, that man would ruin himself for ever, for he would lose all interest in the eyes of his neighbours, and even in his own eyes. Each of us bears in his soul a heavy wound, and knows it, yet carries himself, must carry himself as if he were aware of nothing, while all around keep up the pretence. Remember Ler- montov : 194 Look ! around, you, playfully The crowd, moves on the usual road. Scarce a mark of trouble on the festive faces. Not one indecent tear ! And yet is barely one amongst them Bui is crushed by heavy torture. Or has gathered the wrinkles of young age Save from crime or loss. These words are horribly true — and the really horrible should be concealed, it frightens one off. I admit, Byron and Lermontov could make it alluring. But all that is alluring depends on vagueness, remoteness. Any monster may be beautiful in the distance. And no man can be interest- ing unless he keep a certain distance between himself and people. Women do not under- stand this. If they like a man, they try to come utterly near to him, and are sur- prised that he does not meet their frankness with frankness, and admit them to his holy of holies. But in the innermost sanctuary the only beauty is inaccessibility. As a rule it is not a sanctuary but a lair where the wounded beast in man has run to lick his wounds. And shaH this be done in public ? People generally, and women particularly, ought to be given something positive. In 195 books one may still sing the praise of wounds, hopelessness, and despair — whatever you like, for books are still literature, a conven- tionality. But to strip one's anguish in the open market, to confess an incurable disease to others, this is to kill one's soul, not to relieve it. All, even the best men, have some aversion for you. Perhaps in the interest of order and decorum they will grant you a not-too-important place in their philosophy of life. For in a philosophy of life, as in a cemetery, a place is prepared for each and all, and everyone is welcome. There also are enclosures where rubbish is dumped to rot. But for those who have as yet no desire to be fitted into a world- philosophy, I would advise them to keep their tongue between their teeth, or like Nietzsche and Dostoevsky, take to literature. To a writer, in books and only in books, all is permitted provided he has talent. But in actual living even a writer must not let loose too much, lest people should guess that in his books he is telling the truth. 30 Poushkin asserts that the poet himself can and must be the judge of his own work. " Are you content, exacting artist ? Con- 196 tent, then let the mob revile." It is need- less to argue against this, for how could you prove that the supreme verdict belongs not to the poet himself, but to public opinion? Nor, for that matter, can we prove Poushkin right. We must agree or disagree, as we like. But we cannot reject the evidence. Whether you like it or not, Poushkin was evidently satisfied with his own work, and did not need his reader's sanction. Happy man ! And it seems to me he owed his happiness exclusively to his inability to pass beyond certain limits. I doubt if all poets would agree to repeat Poushkin's verse quoted above. I decidedly refuse to believe that Shakespeare, for instance, after finishing Hamlet or King Lear could have said to himself : " I, who judge my work more strictly than any other can judge, am satisfied." I do not think he can even have thought for a moment of the merits of his works, Hamlet or Ki7ig Lear. To Shakespeare, after Hamlet, the word " satis- fied " must have lost all its meaning, and if he used it, it was only by force of habit, as we sometimes call to a dead person. His own works must have seemed to him imper- fect, mean, pitiful, like the sob of a child or the moaning of a sick man. He gave 197 them to the theatre, and most probably was surprised that they had any success. Per- haps he was glad that his tears were of some use, if only for amusing and instructing people. And probably in this sense the verdict of the crowd was dearer to him than his own verdict. He could not help accusing his own offspring — thank heaven, other people acquitted it. True, they acquitted it because they did not understand, or understood imperfectly, but this did not matter. " Use every man after his desert, and who should 'scape a whipping ? " asked Hamlet. Shakespeare knew that a strict tribunal would reject his works : for they contain so many terrible questions, and not one perfect answer. Could anyone be " satisfied " at that rate ? Perhaps with Comedy of Errors, Twelfth Night, or even Richard III. — but after Hamlet a man may find rest only in his grave. To speak the whole truth, I doubt if Poushkin himself maintained the view we have quoted till the end of his days, or even if he spoke all he felt when he wrote the poem in 1830. Possibly he felt how little a poet can be satisfied with his work, but pride prevented his admitting it, and he tried to console himself with his superiority over the crowd. 198 Which is undeniably a right thing to do. Insults — and Poushkin had to endure many — are answered with contempt ; and woe to the poor wretch who feels impelled to justify his contempt by his own merits, according to the stern voice of conscience. Such niceness is dangerous and unnecessary. If a man would preserve his strength and his confidence he must give up magnanimity, he must learn to despise people, and even if he cannot despise them he must have the air of one who would not give a pin's head for anybody. He must appear always con- tent. . . . Poushkin was a clever man and a deep nature. Metaphysics against their zcill. — It often occurs to us that evil is not altogether so unnecessary, after all. Diseases, humilia- tions, miseries, deformity, failure, and all the rest of those plants which flourish with such truly tropical luxuriance on our planet, are probably essential to man. Poets sing plentifully of sorrow. " Nous sommes les apprentis, la douleur est notre mattre,^^ said de Musset. On this subject everybody can bring forth a quota- tion, not only from the philosophers, who are a cold, heartless tribe, but from tender, 199 gentle, or sentimental poets. Doubtless one knows many instances where suffering has profited a man. True also, one knows many cases of the direct opposite. And these are all cases of profound, earnest, outrageous, incredibly outrageous suffering. Look at Tchekhov's men and women — plainly drawn from life, or at any rate, exceedingly life- like. Uncle Vanya, an old man of fifty, cries beside himself all over the stage, " My life is done for, my life is done for," and senselessly shoots at a harmless pro- fessor. The hero in A Tedious Story^as a quiet, happy man engaged in work of real importance, when suddenly a horrible disease stole upon him, not killing him, but taking him between its loathsome jaws. But what for ? Then Tchekhov's girls and women ! They are mostly young, innocent, fascinating. And always there lies in wait for them round every corner a meaningless, rude, ugly misery which murders even the most modest hopes. They sob bitterly, but fate takes no notice. How explain such horrors ? Tchekhov is silent. He does not weep himself — he left off long ago, and besides it is a humiliating thing for a grown- up person to do. Setting one's teeth, it is necessary either to keep silent or — to explain. 200 Well, metaphysicsundertakes the explanation. Where common sense stops, metaphysics must take another stride. " We have seen," it says, ^' many instances where at first glance suffering seemed absurd and needless, but where later on a profound significance was revealed. Thus it may be that what we cannot explain may find its explanation in time. ' Life is lost,' cries Uncle Vanya, * Life is done for,' repeat the voices of girls innocently perishing — yet nothing is lost. The very horror which a drowning man experiences goes to show that the drowning is nothing final. It is only the beginning of greater events. The less a man has fulfilled in experience, the more in him remains of unsatisfied passion and desire, the greater are the grounds for think- ing that his essence cannot be destroyed, but must manifest itself somehow or other in the universe. Voluntary asceticism and self-denial, such common human phenomena, help to solve the riddle. Nobody compels a man, he imposes suffering and abstinence on himself. It is an incomprehensible in- stinct, but still an instinct which, rooted in the depths of our nature, prompts us to a decision repugnant to reason : renounce life, save yourself. The majority of men 201 do not hear or do not heed the prompting. And then nature, which cannot rely on our sensibility, has recourse to violence. She shows glimpses of Paradise to us in our youth, awakens hopes and impossible desires, and at the moment of our supreme expecta- tion she shows us the hollowness of our hope. Nearly every life can be summed up in a few words : man was shown heaven — and thrown into the mud. We are all ascetics — voluntary or involuntary. Here on earth dreams and hopes are only awakened, not fulfilled. And he who has endured most suffering, most privation, will awaken in the afterwards most keenly alive." Such long speeches metaphysics whispers to us. And we repeat them, often leaving out the " it may be." Sometimes we believe them, and forge our philosophies from them. Even we go so far as to assert that had we the power we would change nothing, abso- lutely nothing in the world. And yet, if by some miracle such power came into our hands, how triumphantly we would send to the devil all philosophies and lofty world- conceptions, all ideals and metaphysics, and plainly and simply, without reflection, abolish sufferings, deformities, failures, all those things to which we attach such a high 202 educational value, abolish them from the face of the earth. We are fed up, oh, how fed up we are with carrying on our studies. But it can't be helped. Faute de mieux, let us keep on inventing systems, thinking them out. But let us agree not to be cross with those who don't want to have anything to do with our systems. Really, they have a perfect right. 32 Old age must be respected — so all say, even the old. And the young willingly meet the demand. But in such spontaneous, even often emphatic respect, is there not something insulting to old age. Every young man, by his voluntary deference, seems to say : " And still the rising star shines brighter than the setting." And the old, accepting the respect, are well aware that they can count on nothing more. The young are attentive and respectful to the old only upon the express condition that the latter shall behave like old people, and stand aside from life. Let a real man try to follow Faust's example, and what a shindy there will be ! The old, being as a rule helpless, are compelled to bow to public opinion and behave as if their only interests 203 were the interests of righteousness, good name, and such-like Platonic attributes. Only a few go against the convention, and these are monsters and degenerates. We do not wish old men to have desires, so that life is arranged as if old men desired nothing. This, of course, is no great matter : even the young are compelled to be satisfied with less than nothing, in our system. We are not out to meddle with human rights. Our point is that science and philosophy take enforced appearances for reality. Grey hair is supposed to be a sure sign of victory over the passions. Hence, seeing that we must all come to grey hairs, therefore the ultimate business of man is to overcome the passions. . . . On this granite foundation whole systems of philosophy are built. It is not worth while quarrelling with a custom — let us continue to pay respect to old age. But let us look in other directions for philosophic bases. It is time to open a free road to the passions even in the province of metaphysics. 33 Dostoevsky — advocatus diaboh. — Dos- toevsky, like Nietzsche, disliked Protest- antism, and tried every means of degrading 204 it in the eyes of the world. As normally he was not over scrupulous, it is probable he never took the trouble to acquaint him- self with Luther's teaching. His flair did not deceive him : the Protestant religion and morality was most unsuitable to him and his kind. But does this mean that it was to be calumniated, and judged, as Dostoevsky judged it, merely by the etymo- logical meaning of a word ? Protestant — a protester, one who only protests and has no positive content. A child's text-book of history will show the absurdity of the defini- tion. Protestantism is, on the whole, the most positive, assertive creed of all the Christian religions. It certainly protested against Catholicism, but against the de- structive tendencies in the latter, and in the name of positive ideals. Catholicism relied too much on its power and its spell, and most of all on the infallibility of its dogmas to which it offered millions of victims. To maim and mutilate a man ad majorem gloriam Dei was considered a perfectly proper thing in the Middle Ages, the period of bloom for Catholicism. At the risk of appearing paradoxical, I venture to assert that ideas have been invented only for the purpose of giving the right to mutilate 205 people. The Middle Ages nourished a myster- ious, incomprehensible hatred for everything normal, self-satisfied, complete. A young, healthy, handsome man, at peace with himself, aroused suspicion and hostility in a believing Catholic. His very appearance offended religion and confuted dogma. It was not necessary to examine him. Even though he went to church, and gave no sign of doubt, either in deed or word, yet he must be a heretic, to be converted at all cost. And we know the Catholic cost: privation, asceticism, mortification of the flesh. The most normal person, kept on a monastic regime, will lose his spiritual balance, and all those virtues which belong to a healthy spirit and a healthy body. This was all Catholicism needed. It tried to obtain from people the extreme endeavour of their whole being. Ordinary, natural love, which found its satisfaction — this was sinful. Monks and priests were condemned to celibacy — hence monstrous and abnormal passions developed. Poverty was preached, and the most unheard-of greed appeared in the world, the more secret the stronger it became. Humility was essential — and out of bare-footed monks sprang despots who had no limits to their ambitions. 206 Luther was the last man to understand the meaning and value of the tasks which CathoHcism had set itself. What he saw in Rome was not the accidental outcome of this or the other historical circumstance, but a result of the age-long effort of genera- tions that had striven to attribute to life as alarming and dangerous a nature as possible. The sincere, direct, rustic German monk was too simple-minded to make out what was going on in Rome. He thought there existed one truth, and that the essence of Catholicism lay in what seemed to him an exemplary, virtuous life. He went direct to his aim ? What meaning can monastic- ism have ? Why deprive a priest of family happiness ? How accept the licentiousness of the pope's capital ? The common sense of the normal German revolted against the absurdity of such a state of things — and Luther neither could nor would see any good where common sense was utterly forgotten. The violent oscillation of life resulting from the continuous quick passage from asceticism and blind faith to unbelief and freedom of the passions aroused a mystic horror in the honest monk and released the enormous powers in him necessary to start the great struggle. How could he help protesting ? 207 And who was the denier, Luther, or the Rome which passed on from the keeping of the Divine Word to the arbitrary ordain- ing of all the mysteries of life ? Luther might have forgiven the monks had they confined themselves to sophistries. But mediaeval monks had nothing in common with our philosophers. They did not look for world-conceptions in books, and logical tournaments amused them only moderately. They threw themselves into the deeps of life, they experimented on themselves and their neighbours. They passed from morti- fication to licentious bacchanalia. They feared nothing, spared nothing. In a word, the Rome against which Luther arose had undertaken to build Babylon again, not with stones, but with human souls. Luther, horrified, withdrew, and with him half Europe was withdrawn. That is his positive merit. And Dostoevsky attacked Luther- anism, and pitied the old Catholicism and the breathless heights to which its " spiritual " children had risen. Wholesome morality and its support is not enough for Dostoevsky. All this is not " positive," it is only " pro- test." Whether I am believed or not, I will repeat that Vladimir Soloviov, who held that Dostoevsky was a prophet, is 208 wrong, and that N. K. Mikhailovsky, who calls him a cruel talent and a grubber after buried treasure, is right. Dostoevsky grubs after buried treasure — no doubt about that. And, therefore, it would be more becoming in the younger generation that still marches under the flag of pious idealism if, instead of choosing him as a spiritual leader, they avoided the old sorcerer, in whom only those gifted with great short- sightedness or lack of experience in life could fail to see the dangerous man. .34 It is boring and difficult to convince people, and after all, not necessary. It would be much better if every individual kept his own opinions. Unfortunately, it cannot be. Whether you like it or not, you have to admit the law of gravitation. Some people find it necessary to admit the origin of man from the monkey. In the empirical realm, however humiliating it may be, there are certain real, binding, universal truths against which no rebellion will avail. With what pleasure would we declare to a representative of science that fire does not burn, that rattlesnakes are not poisonous, that a fall from a high tower is perfectly 209 agreeable, etc., etc., supposing he were obliged to prove to us the contrary. Un- luckily the scientific person is free from the burden of proof : nature proves, and thor- oughly. If nature, like metaphysics, set out to compel us through syllogisms or sermons to believe in her, how little she would get out of us. She is much more sagacious. Morality and logic she has left to Hegel and Spinoza, for herself she has taken a cudgel. Now then, try to argue against this ! You will give in against your will. The cleverest of all the metaphysi- cians, Catholic inquisitors, imitated nature. They rarely tried the word, and trusted to the fire of faggots rather than of the heart. Had they only had more power, it would not be possible to find two people in the whole world disbelieving in the infallibility of the Pope. Metaphysical ideas, dreamily expecting to conquer tlie world by reasoned exposition, will never attain dominion. If they are bent on success, let them try more effective methods of convincing. 35 Evolution. — In recent years we see more and more change in the philosophies of writers and even of non-literary people. 210 The old men are beside themselves — such shiftiness seems indecent. After all, con- victions are not gloves. But the young carelessly pass on from one idea to another. Irresolute men are somewhat timid, and although they abandon their former con- victions they do not declare the change openly. Others, however, plainly announce, as if it were nothing, how far they now are from the beliefs they held six months ago. One even publishes whole volumes relating how he passed on from one philosophy to another, and then to a third. People see nothing alarming in that kind of *' evolu- tion." They believe it is in the ordering of things. But not so at all ! The readiness to leave off one set of convictions in order to assume another set shows complete indifference to convictions altogether. Not for nothing do the old sound the alarm. But to us who have fought so long against all kinds of constancy, the levity of the young is a pleasant sight. They will don materialism, positivism, Kantianism, spirit- ualism, and so on, one after the other, till they realise that all theories, ideas and ideals are as of little consequence as the hoop- skirts and crinolines of our grandmothers. Then they will begin to live without ideals 211 and pre-arranged purposes, without fore- sight, relying on chance and their own ready- wit. This way, too, must be tried. Perhaps we shall do better by it. . . . Anyhow, it will be more fun. Strength of zvill. — Weakness and paralysis of the will, a very dangerous disease in our times, and in most other times, consists not in the absolute loss of desire, such as takes place in the very old, but in the loss of the capacity to translate desire into deed. A diseased will is "often met in violently passionate men, so that the proverb — " Say I will not, not I cannot " — does not always hold good. Man often would, but cannot. And then the force of desire instead of moving to outward creation, works inwardly. This is justly considered the most dangerous effect of the weakening of the will. For inward working is destructive working. Man does not only, to put it scientifically, fail to adapt nature to his needs, but he loses his own power of adaptability to outward circumstances. The most ordinary doctor, or even anybody, decides that he has before him a pathological case which must be treated with care. The patient is 212 of the same opinion, whilst he still hopes. But when the treatment has had no resuhs, the doctor draws back and speaks of the inadequacy of his science. Then what is the patient to retire upon ? It is disgusting to speak of an incurable disease. So he begins to think, think, think — all the time about things of which nobody thinks. He is gradually forgotten, and gradually he forgets everything — but first of all, that widespread truth which asserts that no judgments are valid save those that are accepted and universal. Not that he disputes the truth : he forgets it, and there is none to remind him. To him all his judgments seem valid and important. Of course he cannot advance the principle : let all men turn from the external world into themselves. But why advance a principle at all ? One can simply say : I am indifferent to the destinies of the external world. I do not want to move mountains or turn rivers aside or rearrange the map of Europe. I don't even want to go to the tobacconist to buy cigarettes. I don't want to do anything. I want to think that my inaction is the most important thing on earth, that any " disease " is better than health, and so on and so on without end. To what 213 thoughts will not a man abandoned by medicine and doctors sink down ! His judgments are not binding on us, that is as clear as day. But are they uninteresting ? And is that paralysis, that weakness of will, a disease only f 37 Death and metaphysics. — A superficial observer knows that the best things in life are hard to attain. Some psychologists even consider that the chief beauty of the highest things consists in their unattain- ability. This is surely not true — yet there is a grain in it. The roads to good things are dangerous to travel. Is it because nature is so much poorer than we imagine, so she must lock up her blessings, or is there some greater meaning in it, that we have not guessed ? For the fact is, the more alluring an end we have in view, the more risks and horrors we must undertake to get there. May we not also make a contrary suggestion : that behind every danger something good is hidden, and that therefore danger serves as an indication, a mark to guide us onwards, not as a warning, as we are taught tc believe. To decide this would be to decide that bcliind death, the greatest of dangers must lie the most promising things. It is as well not to speculate further. We had best stop lest we quarrel even with meta- physics. Traditional metaphysics has always been able to illumine our temporal existence with the reflected beams of eternity. Let us follow the example. Let us make no attempt to know the absolute. If you have discovered a comforting hypo- thesis, even in the upper transcendental air, drag it quickly to earth where labouring men forever await even an imaginary relief from their lot. We must make use of everything, even of death, to serve the ends of this life of ours. 7he future. — A clever, reasonable boy, accustomed to trust his common sense, read in a book for children a description of a shipwreck which occurred just as the pas- sengers were eating their sweets at dessert. He was astonished to learn that everyone, women and children as well, who could give no assistance whatever in saving the ship, left their dessert and rushed on deck with wailing and tears. Why wail, why rush about, why be stupidly agitated ? The crew knew their business and would do 215 all that could be done. If you are going to perish, perish you will, no matter how you scream. It seemed to the boy that if he had been on the ship he would just have gone on eating his sweets to the last moment. Justice should be done to this judicious and irreproachable opinion. There remained only a few minutes to live — would it not have been better to enjoy them ? The logic is perfect, worthy of Aristotle. And it was found impossible to prove to the boy that he would have left his sweets, even his favourite sweets, under the same circumstances, and rushed and screamed with the rest. Hence a moral — do not decide about the future. To-day common sense is uppermost, and sweets are your highest law. But to-morrow you will get rid of normality and sense, you will link on with nonsense and absurdity, and prob- ably you will even get a taste for bitters. What do you think .? 39 A priori synthetic judgments. — Kant, as we know, found in mathematics and the natural sciences a priori synthetic judg- ments. Was he right or wrong ? Are the judgments he indicated a priori or a 216 posteriori ? Anyhow, one thing is certain : they are not accepted as absolutely, but only as relatively indisputable. In metaphysics, where the only curious and important truths are hidden, the case is different. Kant was compelled to admit that just where metaphysics begin the capacity of our human reason to judge a priori ends. But since we cannot dispense with meta- physical judgments, he proposed to substi- tute for them postulates. At the same time he admitted the optimistic presupposition that in the domain of the transcendental we shall find all that we miss in the world of phenomena. So that, because he could not invent a truly scientific metaphysics, he contrived to present us with a non- scientific sort. Which is to say, after many round-about journeys he brings his readers along the opposite way right back to the very spot from which he led them off. Surely non-scientific metaphysics existed before Kant : the mediaeval philosophers had plenty of phantasies and speculations, all supported by " moral " proofs. If Kant wanted to reform metaphysics, he should have got rid of its favourite method of obtaining truths through inferential " con- clusions." Men are greedy, they want to 217 learn mucli, and get their knowledge cheap. So they think that every truth they have paid for with experience and loss of energy entitles them to a few more truths gratis : or, in philosophic language, a priori, by deduction. They are not ashamed to specu- late with a gift that has been given them. Instead of looking, listening, touching, seeking, they want to infer and conclude. Certainly if they could wring any secret out of nature, no matter by what means, cunning, impudence, fraud, we would forgive them — conquerors are not judged. But nothing comes of their " conclusions " save meta- physical systems and empty prattle. It is surely time to give up conclusions, and get truth a -posteriori^ as did Shakspeare, Goethe, Dostoevsky; that is, every time you want to know anything, go and look and find out. And if one is lazy, or horrified at a new experiment, let him train himself to look on ultimate questions with indifference, as the positivists do. But moral, ontological and such like arguments ! — really, it is disgusting to talk about them. Every new experiment is interesting; but our conclusions, /. :> their time between extravagant amusement and State service, or peasants whose drudgery- left them no time for idle curiosity. Such being the case, how can we know whether human knowledge has any limits ? And if we don't know, it seems to us it is only because we haven't tried to find out. Other people's experience is not ours. We are not bmmd by their conclusions. Indeed, what do we know of the experience of others, save what we gather, very vaguely and fragmentarily and unreliably, from books ? It is natural for us to believe the best, till the contrary is proved to us. Any attempt to deprive us of our belief meets with the most energetic resistance. The most sceptical Russian hides a hope at the bottom of his soul. Hence our fearlessness of the truth, realistic truth which so stunned European critics. Realism was invented in the West, established there as a theory. But in the West, to counteract it, were invented numberless other palli- ating theories whose business it was to soften down the disconsolate conclusions of Realism. There in Europe they have the etre supreme, the deus sive natura, Hegel's absolute, Kant's postulates, English utili- tarianism, progress, humanitarianism, 234 hundreds of philosophic and sociologicar theories in which even extreme realists can so cleverly dish up what they call life, that life, or realism, ceases to be life or reality altogether. The Westerner is self-reliant. He knows that if he doesn't help himself nobody will help him. So he directs all his thoughts to making the best of his opportunities. A limited time is granted him. If he can't get to the end of his song within the time- limit, the song must remain unsung. Fate will not give him one minute's grace for the unbeaten bars. Therefore as an experi- enced musician he adapts himself superbly. Not a second is wasted. The tempo must not drag for an instant, or he is lost. The ternpo is everything, and it exacts facility and quickness of movement. During a few short beats the artist must produce many notes, and produce them so as to leave the impression that he was not hurried, that he had all the time in the world at his disposal. Moreover, each note must be complete, accomplished, have its fulness and its value. Native talent alone will not suffice for this. Experience is necessary, tradition, training, and inherited instinct. Carpe diem — the European has been living up to the motto for 235 two thousand years. But if we Russians are convinced of anything, it is that we have time enough and to spare. To. count days, much less hours and minutes — find me the Russian who could demean himself to such a bourgeois occupation. We look round, we stretch ourselves, we rub our eyes, we want first of all to decide what we shall do, and how we shall do it, before we can begin to live in earnest. We don't choose to decide anyhow, nor at second- hand, from fragments of other people's information. It must be from our own experience, with our own brains, that we judge. We admit no traditions. In no literature has there been such a determined struggle with tradition as in ours. We have wanted to re-examine everything, re-state everything. I won't deny that our courage is drawn from our quite uncultured confidence in our own powers. Byelinsky, a half- baked undergraduate, deriving his know- ledge of European philosophy at third hand, began a quarrel with the universe over the long-forgotten victims of Philip II. and the Inquisition. In that quarrel is the sense and essence of all creative Russian literature. Dostoevsky, towards his end, raised the same storm and the same 236 question over the little tear of an unfor- tunate child. A Russian believes he can do anything, hence he is afraid of nothing. He paints life in the gloomiest colours — and were you to ask him : How can you accept such a life ? how can you reconcile yourself with such horrors of reality as have been described by all your writers, from Poushkin to Tchekhov ? he would answer in the words of Dmitri Karamazov : / do not accept life. This answer seems at first sight absurd. Since life is here, impossible not to accept it. But there is a sub-meaning in the reply, a lingering belief in the possibility of a final triumph over " evil." In the strength of this belief the Russian goes forth to meet his enemy — he does not hide from him. Our sectarians immolate themselves. Tol- stoyans and votaries . of the various sects that crop up so plentifully in Russia go in among the people, they go, God knows to what lengths, destroying their own lives and the lives of others. Writers do not lag behind sectarians. They, too, refuse to be prudent, to count the cost or the hours. Minutes, seconds, time-beats, all this is so insignificant as to be invisible to the naked eye. We wish to draw with a generous 237 hand from fathomless eternity, and all that is limited we leave to European bourgeoisie. With few exceptions Russian writers really despise the pettiness of the West. Even those who have admired Europe most have done so because they failed most completely to understand her. They did not want to understand her. That is why we have always taken over European ideas in such fantastic forms. Take the sixties for example. With its loud ideas of sobriety and modest outlook, it was a most drunken period. Those who awaited the New Mes- siah and the Second Advent read Darwin and dissected frogs. It is the same to-da}-. We allow ourselves the greatest luxury that man can dream of — sincerity, truthfulness — as if we were spiritual Croesuses, as if we had plenty of everything, could afford to let everything be seen, ashamed of nothing. But even Croesuses, the greatest sove- reigns of the world, did not consider they had the right to tell the truth at all times. Even kings have to pretend — think of diplomacy. Whereas, we think we may speak the truth, and the truth only, that any lie which obscures our true substance is a crime ; since our true substance is the world's finest treasure, its finest reality. . . . 238 Tell this to a European, and it will seem a joke to him, even if he can grasp it at all. A European uses all his powers of intellect and talent, all his knowledge and his art for the purpose of concealing his real self and all that really affects him : — for that the natural is ugly and repulsive, no one in Europe will dispute for a moment. Not only the fine arts, but science and philosophy in Europe tell lies instinctively, by lying they justify their existence. First and last, a European student presents you with a finished theoty. Well, and what does all the " finish " and the completeness signify ? It merely means that none of our western neighbours will end his speech before the last reassuring word is said ; he will never let nature have the last word ; so he rounds off his synthesis. With him, ornament and rhetoric is a sine qua non of creative utterance, the only remedy against all ills. In philosophy reigns theodicy, in science, the law of sequence. Even Kant could not avoid declamation, even with him the last word is '* moral necessity." Thus there lies before us the choice between the artistic and accomplished lie of old, cultured Europe, a lie which is the outcome of a thousand years of hard and bitter effort, and the 239 artless, sincere simplicity of young, uncul- tured Russia. They are nearer the end, we are nearer the beginning. And which is nearer the truth ? And can there be a question of voluntary, free choice ? Probably neither the old age of Europe nor the youth of Russia can give us the truth we seek. But does such a thing as ultimate' truth exist ? Is not the very conception of truth, the very assumption of the possibility of truth, merely an outcome of our limited experience, a fruit of limita- tion ? We decide a -priori that one thing must be possible, another impossible, and from our arbitrary assumptions we proceed to deduce the body of truth. Each one judges in his own way, according to his powers and the conditions of his existence. The timid, scared man worries after order, that will give him a day of peace and quiet, youth dreams of beauty and brilliance, old age doesn't want to think of anything, having lost the faculty for hope. And so it goes on, ad infinitum. And this is called truth, truths ! Every man thinks that his own experience covers the whole range of life. And, therefore, the only men who turn out to be at all in the right are empiricists and positivists. There can be no question 24c of truth once we tear ourselves away from the actual conditions of life. Our confident truthfulness, like European rhetoric, turns out to be " beyond truth and falsehood." The young East and the old West alike suffer from the restrictions imposed by truth — but the former ignores the restrictions, whilst the latter adapts itself to them. After all, it comes to pretty much the same in the end. Is not clever rhetoric as delightful as truthfulness ? Each is equally life. Only we find unendurable a rhetoric which poses as truth, and a truth- fulness which would appear cultured. Such a masquerade would try to make us believe that truth, which is only limitedness, has a real objective existence. Which is offen- sive. Until the contrary is proved, we need to think that only one assertion has or can have any objective reality : that nothing on earth is impossible. Every time somebodv wants to force us to admit that there are other, more limited and limiting truths, we must resist with every means we can lay hands on. We do not hesitate even to make use of morality and logic, both of which we have abused so often. But why not use them ! When a man is at his last resources, 241 he does not care what weapons he picks up. Nur fur Schwtndelfreie. — To be proper, I ought to finish with a moral. I ought to say to the reader that in spite of all I have said, or perhaps because of all I have said — for in conclusions, as you are aware, *' in spite of " is always interchangeable with " because of," particularly if the con- clusion be drawn from many scattered data — well then, because of all I have said, hope is not lost. Every destruction leads to construction, sweet rest follows labour, dawn follows the darkest hour, and so on and so on and so on — all the banalities with which a writer reconciles his reader. But it is never too late for reconciliation, and it is often too early. So why not postpone the moral for a few years — even a few dozen years, God granting us the length of life ? Why make the inevitable *' conclusion " at the end of every book ? I am almost certain that sooner or later I can promise the reader all his heart desires. But not yet. He may, of course, dispense with my consolations. What do promises matter, anyhow ? especially when neither reader nor writer can fulfil them. But if there is no 242 escape, if a writer is finally obliged to admit in everybody's hearing that the secret desires of poor mankind may yet be realised, let us at least give the wretched writer a respite, let him postpone his confession till old age — usque ad infinitum. . . . Mean- while our motto " Nur fur Schwindelfreie^ There are in the Alps narrow, precipitous paths where only mountaineers may go, who feel no giddiness. Giddy-free ! " Only for the giddy-free," it says on the notice- board. He who is subject to giddiness takes a broad, safe road, or sits away below and admires the snowy summits. Is it inevitably necessary to mount up ? Beyond the snow-line are no fat pastures nor gold- fields. They say that up there is to be found the clue to the eternal mystery — but they say so many things. We can't believe everything. He who is tired of the valleys, loves climbing, and is not afraid to look down a precipice, and, most of all, has nothing left in life but the " meta- physical craving," he will certainly climb to the summits without asking what awaits him there. He does not fear, he longs for giddiness. But he will hardly call people after him : he doesn't want just anybody for a companion. In such a case 243 companions are not wanted at all, much less those tender-footed ones who are used to every convenience, roads, street lamps, guide-posts, careful maps which mark every change in the road ahead. They will not help, only hinder. They will prove super- fluous, heavy ballast, which may not be thrown overboard. Fuss over them, console them, promise them ! Who would be bothered ? Is it not better to go one's way alone, and not only to refrain fyom enticing others to follow, but frighten them off as much as possible, exaggerate every danger and difficulty ? In order that conscience may not prick too hard — we who love high altitudes love a quiet conscience — let us find a justification for their inactivity. Let us tell them they are the best, the worthiest of people, really the salt of the earth. Let us pay them every possible mark of respect. But since they are subject to giddiness, they had better stay down. The upper Alpine ways, as any guide will tell you, are nur fiir Schwindelfreie. (fiS?^"^ UNrVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY Los Angeles This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. QL Oil 315 UC SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY AA 000 623 303 5