1 1 Hi A a; ^ I j 4 I 9 i 8 I 3 I 7 i 5 i RU " maxhema flii lliiiliiiiiiiiiilli liliflliiliiiiii r 1 Ex JLi^xii. <3xan^ ^idcx Iane. angle, etc. He 2 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. then proposes Postulates'' in which he takes for granted that we can draw straight Hnes from any point to any other point, and that we can prolong any straight line in a straight direction. Finally, he adds what he calls Common Notions* which em- body some general principles of logic (of pure rea- son) specially needed in geometry, such as that things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one another; that if equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal, etc. I need not mention here perhaps, since it is a fact of no consequence, that the readings of the several manuscripts vary, and that some proposi- tions (e. g., that all right angles are equal to one another) are now missing, now counted among the postulates, and now adduced as common notions. The commentators of Euclid who did not under- stand the difference between Postulates and Com- mon Notions, spoke of both as axioms, and even to-day the term Common Notion is mostly so trans- lated. In our modern editions of Euclid we find a statement concerning parallel lines added to either the Postulates or Common Notions. Originally it appeared in Proposition 29 where it is needed to prop up the argument that would prove the equality of alternate angles in case a third straight line falls upon parallel straight lines. It is there enunciated as follows: "But those straight Hnes which, with another straight ^ aiTirttxara, * Koi.val ivvoiai. HISTORICAL SKETCH. 3 line fallinjT upon them, make the interior angles on the same side less than two right angles, do meet if continually pro- duced." Now this is exactly a point that calls for proof. Proof was then, as ever since it has remained, alto- gether lacking-. So the proposition was formulated dogmatically thus : "If a straight line meet two straight lines, so as to make the two interior angles on the same side of it taken together less than two right angles, these straight lines being con- tinually produced, shall at length meet upon that side on which are the angles which are less than two right angles." And this proposition has been transferred by the editors of Euclid to the introductory portion of the book where it now appears either as the fifth Postulate or the eleventh, twelfth, or thirteenth Common Notion. The latter is obviously the less appropriate place, for the idea of ])ara]lelism is assuredly not a Common Notion ; it is not a rule of pure reason such as would be an essential con- dition of all thinking, reasoning, or logical argu- ment. Anrl if we do not give it a place of its own, it should either be classed among the postulates, or recast so as to 1)ecome a pure definition, it is usu- ally referred to as "the axiom of i)arallels." It seems to me that no one can read ihc axiom of jxirallels as it stands in Furlid without receiving the impression that {\\v statcni'-nl was affixed by a later redactor. Even in Proposition 2(), the original place of its insertion, it comes in as an afterthought ; and if Euclid himself had considered the diffirultv 4 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. of the parallel axiom, so called, he would have placed it among the postulates in the first edition of his book, or formulated it as a definition.'^ Though the axiom of parallels must be an inter- polation, it is of classical origin, for it was known even to Proclus (410-485 A. D.), the oldest com- mentator of Euclid. By an. irony of fate, the doctrine of the parallel axiom has become more closely associated with Euclid's name than anything he has actually writ- ten, and when we now speak of Euclidean geometry we mean a system based upon that determination of parallelism. We may state here at once that all the attempts made to derive the axiom of parallels from pure reason were necessarily futile, for no one can prove the absolute straightness of lines, or the evenness of space, by logical argument. Therefore these con- cepts, including the theory concerning parallels, cannot be derived from pure reason ; they are not Common Notions and possess a character of their own. But the statement seemed thus to hang in the air, and there appeared the possibility of a geom- etry, and Qven of several geometries, in whose do- mains the parallel axiom would not hold good. This large field has been called metageometry, hyper- ^ For Professor Halsted's ingenious interpretation of the origin of the parallel theorem see The Monist, Vol. IV, No. 4, p. 487. He believes that Euclid anticipated metageometry, but it is not probable that the man who wrote the argument in Proposition 29 had the fifth Postulate before him. He would have referred to it or stated it at least approximately in the same words. But the argument in Propo- sition 29 differs considerably from the parallel axiom itself. HISTORICAL SKETCH. 5 geometry, or pangeometry, and may be regarded as due to a generalization of the space-conception involving what might be called a metaphysics of mathematics. METAGEOMETRY. Mathematics is a most conservative science. Its system is so rigid and all the details of geometrical demonstration are so complete, that the science was comrnonly regarded as a model of perfection. Thus the philosophy of mathematics remained undevel- oped almost two thousand years. Not that there were not great mathematicians, giants of thought, men like the Bernoullis. Leibnitz and Newton, Euler. and others, worthy to be named in one breath with Archimedes, Pythagoras and Euclid, but they ab- stained from entering into ])hilosophical specula- tions, and the very idea of a ])angeometry remained foreign to them. They may privately have reflected on the subject, but they dicl not give utterance to their thoughts, at least they left no records of them to posterity. It would be wrong, however, to assume that the mathematicians of former ages were not conscious of the flifficulty. They always felt that there was a flaw in the luiclidean foundation of geometry, but they were satisfied to sui)ply any need of basic l)rincii)le'^ in the shape of axioms, and it has become (|uite customary ( I might almost say ortbodox) to say that mathematics is based upon axioms. In fact, l)eople enjoyed the idea that mathematics, the most b THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. lucid of all the sciences, was at bottom as mysterious as the most mystical dogmas of religious faith. Metageometry has occupied a peculiar position among mathematicians as well as with the public at large. The mystic hailed the idea of "7Z-dimensional spaces," of "space curvature" and of other concep- tions of which we can form expressions in abstract terms but which elude all our attempts to render them concretely present to our intelligence. He relished the idea that by such conceptions mathe- matics gave promise to justify all his speculations and to give ample room for a multitude of notions that otherwise would be doomed to irrationality. In a word, metageometry has always proved attrac- tive to erratic minds. Among the professional math- ematicians, however, those who were averse to phil- osophical speculation looked upon it with deep dis- trust, and therefore either avoided it altogether or rewarded its labors with bitter sarcasm. Prominent mathematicians did not care to risk their reputation, and consequently many valuable thoughts remained unpublished. Even Gauss did not care to speak out boldly, but communicated his thoughts to his most intimate friends under the seal of secrecy, not unlike a religious teacher who fears the odor of heresy. He did not mean to suppress his thoughts, but he did not want to bring them before the public unless in mature shape. A letter to Taurinus con- cludes with the remark: "Of a man who has proved himself a thinking mathe- matician, T fear not that he will misunderstand what I say, HISTORICAL SKETCH. 7 but under all circumstances you have to regard it merely as a private communication of which in no wise public use, or one that may lead to it, is to be made. Perhaps I shall pub- lish them myself in the future if I should gain more leisure than my circumstances at present permit. "C. F. Gauss. "GoETTiNGEx, 8. November, 1824." But Gauss never did publish anything upon this topic although the seeds of his thought thereupon fell upon fertile ground and bore rich fruit in the works of his disciples, foremost in those of Riemann. PRECURSORS. The first attempt at improvement in the matter of parallelism was made by Nasir Eddin ( 1201- 1274) whose work on Euclid was printed in Arabic in 1594 in Rome. His labors were noticed by John W'allis who in 165 1 in a Latin translation com- municated Nasir Eddin's exposition of the fifth Pos- tulate to the mathematicians of the University of Oxford, and then propounded his own views in a lecture deHvered on July 11, 1663. Nasir Eddin takes his stand upon the postulate that two straight lines which cut a third straight line, the one at right angles, the other at some other angle, will converge on the side where the angle is actite and diverge where it is obtuse. Wallis, in his endeavor to prove this postulate, starts willi llu- ;mxilinrv theorem : "If a limited straight line which lies upon an un- limited straight line be prolonged in a straight direction, 8 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. its prolongation will fall upon the unlimited straight line." There is no need of entering into the details of his proof of this auxiliary theorem. We may call his theorem the proposition of the straight line and may grant to him that he proves the straightness of the straight line. In his further argument Wallis shows the close connection of the problem of paral- lels with the notion of similitude. Girolamo Saccheri, a learned Jesuit of the seven- teenth century, attacked the problem in a new way. Saccheri was born September 5, 1667, at San Remo. Having received a good education, he became a member of the Jesuit order March 24, 1685, and served as a teacher of grammar at the Jesuit College di Brera, in Milan, his mathematical colleague be- ing Tommaso Ceva (a brother of the more famous Giovanni Ceva). Later on he became Professor of Philosophy and Polemic Theology at Turin and in 1697 at Pavia. He died in the College di Brera October 25, 1733. Saccheri saw the close connection of parallelism with the right angle, and in his work on Euclid^ he examines three possibilities. Taking a quadrilateral ABCD with the angles at A and B right angles and the sides AC and BD equal, the angles at C and D are without difficulty shown to be equal each to the other. They are moreover right angles or else they are either obtuse or acute. He undertakes to ^ Euclidcs ab omni naevo vindicatus; sive conatus geometricus quo stabiliimtur prima ipsa iiniversae geometriae principia. Auctore Hieronymo Saccherio Societatis Jesu. Mediolani, 1773. HISTORICAL SKETCH. prove the absurdity of these two latter suppositions so as to leave as the only solution the sole possibility left, viz., that they must be right angles. But he finds difficulty in pointing out the contradiction to which these assumptions may lead and thus he opens a path on which Lobatchevsky (1793-1856) and Bolyai (1802-1860) followed, reaching a new view which makes three geometries possible, viz., the geometries of (i) the acute angle, (2) the obtuse angle, and (3) the right angle, the latter being the Euclidean geometry, in which the theorem of paral- lels holds. B D While Saccheri seeks the solution of the problem through the notion of the right angle, the German mathematician Lambert starts from the notion of the angle-sum of the triangle. Johann Heinrich Lambert was born August 26, 1728, in Miihlhauscn. a city which at that time was a part of Switzerland. He died in 1777. His The- ory of flic Parallel Lines, written in 1766, was not ])ublished till 1786, nine years after his death, by Bernoulli and Ilindcnburg in tlie Mai^acin fi'ir die rcine iiiid auii^cwaiidte MatJicuiatik. Lambert ])oints out that there are three possi- bilities: the sum of the angles of a triangle may be lO THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. exactly equal to, more than, or less than i8o degrees. The first will make the triangle a figure in a plane, the second renders it spherical, and the third pro- duces a geometry on the surface of an imaginary sphere. As to the last hypothesis Lambert said not without humor :'^ "This result^ possesses something attractive which easily suggests the wish that the third hypothesis might be true." He then adds:^ "But I do not wish it in spite of these advantages, be- cause there would be innumerable other inconveniences. The trigonometrical tables would become infinitely more complicated, and the similitude as well as proportionality of figures would cease altogether. No figure could be repre- sented except in its own absolute size ; and astronomy would be in a bad plight, etc.*' Lobatchevsky's geometry is an elaboration of Lambert's third hypothesis, and it has been called "imaginary geometry" because its trigonometric formulas are those of the spherical triangle if its sides are imaginary, or, as Wolfgang Bolyai has shown, if the radius of the sphere is assumed to be imaginary =(V — i)r. France has contributed least to the literature on the subject. Augustus De Morgan records the fol- lowing story concerning the efforts of her greatest mathematician to solve the Euclidean problem. La- ^ P. 351, last line in the Magazin fiir die rcinc uiid angewandte Mathematik, 1786. ' Lambert refers to the proposition that the mooted angle might be less than 90 degrees. '/fttrf., p. 352. HISTORICAL SKETCH. II grange, he says, composed at the close of his Hfe a discourse on parallel lines. He began to read it in the Academy but suddenly stopped short and said: "II faut que j'y songe encore." With these words he pocketed his papers and never recurred to the subject. Legendre's treatment of the subject appears in the third edition of his elements of Euclid, but he omitted it from later editions as too difficult for be- ginners. Like Lambert he takes his stand upon the notion of the sum of the angles of a triangle, and like Wallis he relies upon the idea of similitude, saying that "the length of the units of measurement is indifferent for proving the theorems in ques- tion."^" GAUSS. A new epoch begins \\ith Gauss, or rather with his ingenious disciple Riemann. While Gauss was rather timid about speaking openly on the subject, he did not wish his ideas to be lost to posterity. In a letter to Schumacher dated May 17, 1831, he said: "I have bc'S^iin to jot clown somcthinc^ of my own medi- tations, which are partly older than forty years, but which I have never written out, beinj^ oblijj^ed therefore to excogi- tate many things three or four times over. I do not wish them to pass away with me." The notes to whicli Gauss here refers have not been found among his posthumous papers, and it ^'' Mcmnirrs dc I'Acadcmic dcs Sciences de I'liislilut de Prance. Vol. XII, 1833. 12 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. therefore seems probable that they are lost, and our knowledge of his thoughts remains limited to the comments that are scattered through his corres- pondence with mathematical friends. Gauss wrote to Bessel (1784-1846) January 27, 1829: "T have also in my leisure hours frequently reflected upon another problem, now of nearly forty years' standing. I refer to the foundations of geometry. I do not know whether I have ever mentioned to you my views on this matter. J\Iy meditations here also have taken more definite shape, and my conviction that we cannot thoroughly demon- strate geometry a priori is, if possible, more strongly con- firmed than ever. But it will take a long time for me to bring myself to the point of working out and making public my very extensiz'e investigations on this subject, and pos- sibly this will not be done during my life, inasmuch as I stand in dread of the clamors of the Boeotians, which would be certain to arise, if I shotild ever give full expression to my views. It is curious that /;/ addition to the celebrated flaw in Euclid's Geometry, which mathematicians have hith- erto endeavored in vain to patch and never will succeed, there is still another blotch in its fabric to which, so far as I know, attention has never yet been called and which it will by no means be easy, if at all possible, to remove. This is the definition of a plane as a surface in which a straight line joining any tivo points lies wholly in that plane. This definition contains more than is requisite to the determina- tion of a surface, and tacitly involves a theorem which is in need of prior proof." Bessel in his answer to Gauss makes a distinc- tion between Euclidean geometry as practical and metageometry (the one that does not depend upon HISTORICAL SKETCH. I3 the theorem of parallel lines) as true geometry. He writes under the date of February lo, 1829: "I should regard it as a great misfortune if you were to allow yourself to be deterred by the 'clamors of the Boeo- tians' from explaining your views of geometry. From what Lambert has said and Schweikart orally communicated, it has become clear to me that our geometry is incomplete and stands in need of a correction which is hypothetical and which vanishes when the sum of the angles of a plane tri- angle is equal to 180°. This would be the true geometry and the Euclidean the practical, at least for figures on the earth." In another letter to Bessel, April 9, 1830, Gauss sums up his views as follows : "The ease with which you have assimilated my notions of geometry has been a source of genuine delight to me, espe- cially as so few possess a natural bent for them. I am pro- foundly convinced that the theory of space occupies an en- tirely different position with regard to our knowledge a priori from that ot the theory of numbers (Grossenlehre) ; that perfect conviction of the necessity and therefore the absolute truth which is characteristic of the latter is totally wanting to our knowledge of the former. We must confess in all humility that a number is solely a product of our mind. •Space, on the other hand, possesses also a reality outside of our mind, the laws of which we cannot fully prescribe a priori." Another letter of Gauss may l)e quoted here in fidl. It is a reply to Taurinus and contains an ap- preciation of his essay on the Parallel Lines. Gauss writes ivom r,r,iiino;-cn, \ov. S, i, not lying in a straight line. If the equation between these three figures be homogene- ous, the totality of all points that correspond to it will be a system of second degree. If this homogeneous equation is of the first grade, this system of second degree will be simple, viz., of a straight line; but if the equation be of a higher grade, we shall have curves for which not all llic laws of plane geometry hold good. The same considerations lead to a dis- tinction between homaloidal space and non-Euclid- ean systems.^* Being professor at a German gymnasium and not a universitw Grassniann's 1)ook remained neg- lected and ihc newness of liis methods i)revented superficial readers from ajjpreciating the sweeping significance of bis i:)rr)positions. Since there was no call whatexer for llie book, the ])ul)lishers re- turned tbe whole edition to tlie ])aper mill, and the complimentary copies which tlie author had sent "Sec Grassniann's Ausdehunu^slrhrr. 1S44, Anhanj? I. pii. 273- 274. 30 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. out to his friends are perhaps the sole portion that was saved from the general doom. Grassmann, disappointed in his mathematical labors, had in the meantime turned to other studies and gained the honorary doctorate of the Univer- sity of Tubingen in recognition of his meritorious work on the St. Petersburg Sankrit Dictionary, when Victor Schlegel called attention to the simi- larity of Hamilton's theory of vectors to Grass- mann's concept oiStrccke, both being limited straight lines of definite direction. Suddenly a demand for Grassmann's book was created in the market; but alas! no copy could be had, and the publishers deemed it advisable to reprint the destroyed edition of 1844. The satisfaction of this late recognition was the last joy that brightened the eve of Grass- mann's life. He wrote the introduction and an ap- pendix to the second edition of his Lincare Aus- dehminzdehre, but died while the forms of his book were on the press. At the present day the literature on metageo- metrical subjects has grown to such an extent that we do not venture to enter into further details. We will only mention the appearance of Professor Schoute's work on more-dimensional geometry^^ which promises to be the elaboration of the pan- geometrical ideal. "" Mehrdimensionale Gcomctrie von Dr. P. H. Schoute, Professor der Math, an d. Reichs-Universitat zii Groningen, Holland. Leipsic. Goschen. So far only the first volume, which treats of linear space, has appeared. HISTORICAL SKETCH. 3 1 EUCLID STILL UNIMPAIRED. Having briefly examined tlie chief innovations of modern times in the field of elementary geometry, it ought to be pointed out that in spite of the well- deserved fame of the metageometricians from Wal- lis to Halsted, Euclid's claim to classicism remains unshaken. The metageometrical movement is not a revolution against Euclid's authority but an at- tempt at widening our mathematical horizon. Let us hear what Halsted, one of the boldest and most iconoclastic among the champions of metageometry of the present day, has to say of Euclid. Halsted begins the Introduction to his English translation of Bolyai's Science .Ibsoliifc of Space with a terse description of the history of Euclid's great book The Elements of Geometry, the rediscovery of which is not the least factor that initiated a new epoch in the development of Europe which may be called the era of inventions, of discoveries, and of the appre- ciation as well as growth of science. Halsted says : "The immortal Elements of EucUd was already in dim antiquity a classic, regarded as al)solutely perfect, valid without restriction. "Elementary geometry was for two thousand years as stationary, as fixed, as peculiarly Greek as the Partlu-non. r)n this foundatif)n piin- science rose in Arcliinudi's. in Apollonius, in Pappus; struggled in Theon. in I lypatia ; declined in Proclus ; fell into the long decadence of the Dark- Ages. "The book that monkish Kurope could no longer under- 32 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. stand was then taught in Arabic by Saracen and Moor in the Universities of Bagdad and Cordova. "To bring the Hght, after weary, stupid centuries, to Western Christendom, an EngHshman, Adelhard of Bath, journeys, to learn Arabic, through Asia Minor, through Egypt, back to Spain. Disguised as a Mohammedan stu- dent, he got into Cordova about 1120, obtained a Moorish copy of Euclid's Elements, and made a translation from the Arabic into Latin. "The first printed edition of Euclid, published in Venice in 1482, was a Latin version from the Arabic. The trans- lation into Latin from the Greek, made by Zamberti from a manuscript of Theon's revision, was first published at Ven- ice in 1505. "Twenty-eight years later appeared the editio princeps in Greek, published at Basle in 1533 by John Hervagius, edited by Simon Grynaeus. This was for a century and three-quarters the only printed Greek text of all the books, and from it the first English translation (1570) was made by 'Henricus Billingsley,' afterward Sir Henry Billingsley, Lord Mayor of London in 1591. "And even to-day, 1895. in the vast system of examina- tions carried out by the British Government, by Oxford, and by Cambridge, no proof of a theorem in geometry will be accepted which infringes Euclid's sequence of propo- sitions. "Nor is the work unworthy of this extraordinary im- mortality. "Says Clifl^ord: 'This book has been for nearly twenty- two centuries the encouragement and guide of that scientific thought which is one thing with the progress of man from a worse to a better state. " 'The encouragement : for it contained a body of knowl- edge that was really known and could be relied on. " 'The guide ; for the aim of every student of every sub- HISTORICAL SKETCH. 33 ject was to bring his knowledge of that subject into a form as perfect as that which geometry had attained.' " Euclid's Elements of Geometry is not counted among the books of divine revelation, but trul}- it deserves to be held in religious veneration. There is a real sanctity in mathematical truth which is not sufhciently appreciated, and certainly if truth, helpfulness, and directness and simplicity of presen- tation, give a title to rank as divinely inspired litera- ture, Euclid's great work should be counted among the canonical books of mankind. * * * Is there any need of warning our readers that the foregoing sketch of the history of metageometry is both brief and popular? We have purposely avoided the discussion of technical details, limiting our exposition to the most essential points and try- ing to show them in a light that will render them interesting even to the non-mathematical reader. It is meant to serve as an introduction to the real matter in hand, viz., an examination of the founda- tions upon which geometrical truth is to be ration- ally justified. The author has purposely introduced what might be called a biographical element in these ex- positions of a subject which is commonly regarded as dry and abstruse, and endeavored to give some- thing of the lives of the men who have struggled and labored in this line of thought and have sacri- ficed their time and energy on the altar of one of the 34 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. noblest aspirations of man, the delineation of a philosophy of mathematics. He hopes thereby to relieve the dryness of the subject and to create an interest in the labor of these pioneers of intellectual progress. THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF ^lATHE- MATICS. THE PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEM. HAVING thus reviewed the history of non- EucHdean geometry, which, rightly consid- ered, is but a search for the philosophy of mathe- matics, I now turn to the problem itself and, in the conviction that I can offer some hints which con- tain its solution, I will formulate my own views in as popular language as would seem compatible with exactness. Not being a mathematician by profes- sion I have only one excuse to offer, which is this: that I have more and more come to the conclusion that the problem is not mathematical but philo- sophical ; and I hope that those who are competent to judge will correct me where I am mistaken. The problem of the philosophical foundation of mathematics is closely connected with the topics of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. It is the old quarrel between Empiricism and Transcendental- ism. Hence our method of dealing with it will nat- urally be philosophical, not typically mathematical. The proper solution can be attained only by analysing the fundamental concepts of mathematics 36 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. and by tracing them to their origin. Thus alone can we know their nature as w^ell as the field of their applicability. We shall see that the data of mathematics are not without their premises; they are not, as the Germans say, voraiissetBun gslos ] and though math- ematics is built up from nothing, the mathematician does not start with nothing. He uses mental im- plements, and it is they that give character to his science. Obviously the theorem of parallel lines is one instance only of a difficulty that betrays itself every- where in various forms; it is not the disease of geometry, but a symptom of the disease. The the- orem that the sum of the angles in a triangle is equal to 180 degrees; the ideas of the evenness or homaloidality of space, of the rectangularity of the square, and more remotely even the irrationality of TT and of e, are all interconnected. It is not the author's intention to show their interconnection, nor to prove their interdependence. That task is the work of the mathematician. The present in- vestigation shall be limited to the philosophical side of the problem for the sake of determining the na- ture of our notions of evenness, which determines both parallelism and rectangularity. At the bottom of the difficulty there lurks the old problem of apriority, proposed by Kant and decided by him in a way which promised to give to mathe- matics a solid foundation in the realm of transcen- dental thought. And yet the transcendental method THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 37 finally sent geometry away from home in search of a new domicile in the wide domain of empiricism. Riemann, a disciple of Kant, is a transcendental- ist. He starts with general notions and his arguments are deductive, leading him from the abstract down to concrete instances; but when stepping from the ethereal height of the absolute into the region of definite space-relations, he fails to find the necessary connection that characterizes all a priori reasoning ; and so he swerves into the domain of the a posteriori and declares that the nature of the specific features of space must be determined by experience. The very idea seems strange to those who have been reared in traditions of the old school. An un- sophisticated man, when he speaks of a straight line, means that straightness is implied thereby; and if he is told that space may be such as to render all straightest lines crooked, he will naturally be "bewildered. If his metageometrical friend, with much learnedness and in sober earnest, tells him that when he sends out a ray as a straight line in a for- ward direction it will imperceptibly deviate and finally turn back upon his occiput, he will naturally become suspicious of the mental soundness of his company. Would not many of us dismiss such ideas with a shrug if there were not geniuses of the very first rank who subscribe to the same? So in all modesty we ha\-e to defer our judgment until com- petent study and mature reflection have enabled us to understand the difficulty which they encounter and then judge their solution. One thing is sure, 38 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. however: if there is anything wrong with meta- geometry, the fault Hes not in its mathematical portion but must be sought for in its philosophical foundation, and it is this problem to which the present treatise is devoted. While we propose to attack the problem as a philosophical question, we hope that the solution will prove acceptable to mathematicians. TRANSCENDENTALISM AND EMPIRICISM. In philosophy we have the old contrast between the empiricist and transcendentalist school. The former derive everything from experience, the latter insist that experience depends upon notions not de- rived from experience, called transcendental, and these notions are a priori. The former found their representative thinkers in Locke, Hume, and John Stuart Mill, the latter was perfected by Kant. Kanf establishes the existence of notions of the a priori on a solid basis asserting their universality and necessity, but he no longer identified the a priori with innate ideas. He granted that much to em- piricism, stating that all knowledge begins with ex- perience and that experience rouses in our mind the a priori which is characteristic of mind. Mill went so far as to deny altogether necessity and uni- versality, claiming that on some other planet 2X2 might be 5. French positivism, represented by Comte and Littre, follows the lead of Mill and thus they end in agnosticism, and the same result was THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 39 reached in England on grounds somewhat different by Herbert Spencer. The way which we propose to take may be char- acterized as the New Positivism. We take our stand upon the facts of experience and estabhsh upon tiie systematized formal features of our experience a new conception of the a priori, recognizing the uni- versality and necessity of formal laws but rejecting Kant's transcendental idealism. The a priori is not deducible from the sensorv elements of our sen- sations, but we trace it in the formal features of experience. It is the result of abstraction and sys- tematization. Thus we establish a method of dealing with experience (commonly called Pure Reason) which is possessed of universal validity, implying logical necessity. The New Positivism is a further development of philosophic thought which combines the merits of both schools, the Transcendentalists and Empiri- cists, in a higher unity, discarding at the same time their aberrations. In this way it becomes possible to gain a firm basis upon the secure ground of facts, according to the principle of positivism, and yet to preserve a method established by a study of the purely formal, which will not end in nescience (the ideal of agnosticism) 1)Ut justify science, and thus establishes the philosophy of science.^ 'We have treated the pliilosonhic.-il problem of tlie a fi'iori at full length in a discussion of Kant s Prolegomena. See the author's Kant's Prolegomena, edited in English, with an essay on Kant's Phi- losophy and other .Supplementary Material for the study of Kant, pp. 167-240. Cf. Fundamental Prnblems,. the chapters "Form and 40 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. It is from this standpoint of the philosophy of science that we propose to investigate the problem of the foundation of geometry. THE A PRIORI AND THE PURELY FORMAL. The bulk of our knowledge is from experience, i. e., we know things after having become acquainted with them . Our knowledge of things is a posteriori. If we want to know whether sugar is sweet, we must taste it. If we had not done so, and if no one had tasted it, we could not know it. However, there is another kind of knowledge which we do not find out by experience, but by reflection. If I want to know how much is 3X3, or {a-\-hY or the angles in a regular polygon, I must compute the answer in my own mind. I need make no experiments but must perform the calculation in my own thoughts. This knowledge which is the result of pure thought is a priori; \nz., it is generally applicable and holds good even before we tried it. \\'hen we begin to make experiments, we presuppose that all our a priori arguments, logic, arithmetic, and mathemat- ics, will hold good. Kant declared that the law of causation is of the same nature as arithmetical and logical truths, and that, accordingly, it will have to be regarded as a priori. Before we make experiments, we know that every cause has its effects, and wherever there Formal Thought," pp. 26-60, and "The Old and the New Mathemat- ics," pp. 61-73; and Primer of Philosophy, pp. 51-103. THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 4I is an effect we look for its cause. Causation is not proved by, but justified through, experience. The doctrine of the a priori has been much mis- interpreted, especially in England. Kant calls that which transcends or goes beyond experience in the sense that it is the condition of experience "tran- scendental," and comes to the conclusion that the a priori is transcendental. Our a priori notions are not derived from experience but are products of pure reflection and they constitute the conditions of experience. By experience Kant understands sense-impressions, and the sense-impressions of the outer world (which of course are a posteriori) are reduced to system by our transcendental notions; and thus knowledge is the product of the a priori and the a posteriori. A sense-impression becomes a perception by be- ing regarded as the effect of a cause. The idea of causation is a transcendental notion. A\'ithout it experience would be impossil)le. An astronomer measures angles and determines the distance of the moon and of the sun. Experience furnishes the data, they are a posteriori: l)ut his mathematical methods, the number system, and all arithmetical functions are a priori. He knows them before he collects the details of his investigation; and in so far as they are the condition without which his sense - impressions could not be transformed into knowledge, they are called transcendental. Note here Kant's use of the word transcendental which denotes the clearest and most reliable knowl- 42 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. edge in our economy of thought, pure logic, arith- metic, geometry, etc. But transcendental is fre- quently (though erroneously) identified with "tran- scendent," which denotes that which transcends our knowledge and accordingly means "unknowable." Whatever is transcendental is, in Kantian terminol- ogy, never transcendent. That much will suffice for an explanation of the historical meaning of the word transcendental. We must now explain the nature of the a priori and its source. The a priori is identical with the purely formal which originates in our mind by abstraction. When we limit our attention to the purely relational, drop- ping all other features out of sight, we produce a field of abstraction in which we can construct purely formal combinations, such as numbers, or the ideas of types and species. Thus we create a world of pure thought which has the advantage of being applicable to any purely formal consideration of conditions, and we work out systems of numbers which, when counting, we can use as standards of reference for our experiences in practical life. But if the sciences of pure form are built upon an abstraction from which all concrete features are omitted, are they not empty and useless verbiage? Empty they are, that is true enough, but for all that they are of paramount significance, because they introduce us into the sanctum sanctissimum of the world, the intrinsic necessity of relations, and thus they become the key to all the riddles of the THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 43 universe. They are in need of being supplemented by observation, by experience, by experiment; but while the mind of the investigator builds up purely formal systeuLS of reference (such as numbers) and purely formal space-relations (such as geometry), the essential features of facts (of the objective world) are in their turn, too, purely formal, and they make things such as they are. The suchness of the world is purely formal, and its suchness alone is of importance. In studying the processes of nature we watch transformations, and all we can do is to trace the changes of form. Matter and energy are words which in their abstract significance have little value; tliey merely denote actuality in general, the one of being, the other of doing. \Miat interests us most are the forms of matter and energy, how they change by transformation ; and it is obvious that the famous law of the conservation of matter and energy is merely the reverse of the truth that cau- sation is transformation. Tn its elements which in their totality are called matter and energy, the ele- ments of existence remain the same, but the forms in which they combine cliange. The sum-total of the mass anrl the sum-total of the forces of the world ran be neither increased nor diminished; they re- main the same to-day that they have ahvavs been and as they w ill remain forever. All a pnslcr'wri cognition is concrete and par- ticular, while all a priori cognition is abstract and general. 'I'he concrete is (at least in its relation 44 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. to the thinking subject) incidental, casual, and indi- vidual, but the abstract is universal and can be used as a general rule under which all special cases may be subsumed. The a priori is a mental construction, or, as Kant says, it is ideal, viz., it consists of the stuff that ideas are made of, it is mind-made. While we grant that the purely formal is ideal we insist that it is made in the domain of abstract thought, and its fundamental notions have been abstracted from ex- perience by concentrating our attention upon the purely formal. It is, not directly but indirectly and ultimately, derived from experience. It is not de- rived from sense-experience but from a considera- tion of the relational (the purely formal) of ex- perience. Thus it is a subjective reconstruction of certain objective features of experience and this reconstruction is made in such a way as to drop every thing incidental and particular and retain only the general and essential features ; and we gain the unspeakable advantage of creating rules or for- mulas which, though abstract and mind-made, apply to any case that can be classified in the same cate- gory. Kant made the mistake of identifying the term "ideal" with "subjective," and thus his transcen- dental idealism was warped by the conclusion that our purely formal laws were not objective, but were imposed by our mind upon the objective world. Our mind (Kant said) is so constituted as to interpret all facts of experience in terms of form, as appear- THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 45 ing in space and time, and as being subject to the law of cause and effect; but what things are in them- selves we cannot know. We object to Kant's sub- jectivizing the purely formal and look upon form as an essential and inalienable feature of objective existence. The thinking subject is to other thinking subjects an object moving about in the objective world . E\'en when contemplating our own exist- ence we must grant (to speak with Schopenhauer) that our bodily actualization is our own object; i. e., we (each one of us as a real living creature) are as much objects as are all the other objects in the world. It is the objectified part of our self that in its inner experience abstracts from sense-experience the interrelational features of things, such as rioht and left, top and bottom, shape and figure and struc- ture, succession, connection, etc. The formal ad- heres to the object and not to the subject, and every object (as soon as it develops in the natural way of evolution first into a feeling creature and then into a thinking being) will be a1)le to build up a /^riori from the abstract notion of form in general the sev- eral systems of formal thought: arithmetic, geom- etry, algebra, logic, and the conceptions of time, space, and causalitv. Accordingly, all formal tliought, although we grant its idcdity, is fashioned from niatcrinls ab- stracted from the oljjective world, and it is tlu-reforc a matter of course that they are applicable to the objectix'c world. Tliey belong to the object and, when we thinking subjects beget them from our own 46 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. minds, we are able to do so only because we are ob- jects that live and move and have our being in the objective world. ANYNESS AND ITS UNIVERSALITY. We know that facts are incidental and hap- hazard, and appear to be arbitrary; but we must not rest satisfied with single incidents. We must gather enough single cases to make abstractions. Abstrac- tions are products of the mind; they are subjective; but they have been derived from experience, and they are built up of elements that have objective significance. The most important abstractions ever made by man are those that are purely relational. Every- thing from which the sensory element is entirely omitted, where the material is disregarded, is called "pure form," and the relational being a considera- tion neither of matter nor of force or energy, but of number, of position, of shape, of size, of form, of relation, is called "the purely formal." The no- tion of the purely formal has been gained by ab- straction, viz., by abstracting, i. e., singling out and retaining, the formal, and by thinking away, by can- celling, by omitting, by leaving out, all the features which have anything to do with the concrete sensory element of experience. And what is the result ? We retain the formal element alone which is void of all concreteness, void of all materialitv, void THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 47 of all particularity. It is a mere nothing and a non-entity. It is emptiness. But one thing is left, — position or relation. Actuality is replaced by mere potentiality, viz., the possible conditions of any kind of being that is possessed of form. The word "any" denotes a simple idea, and yet it contains a good deal of thought. Mathematics builds up its constructions to suit any condition. "Any" implies universality, and universality in- cludes necessity in the Kantian sense of the term. In every concrete instance of an experience the subject-matter is the main thing with which we are concerned; but the purely formal aspect is after all the essential feature, because form determines the character of things, and thus the formal (on account of its anyness) is the key to their comprehension. The rise of man above the animal is due to his ability to utilize the purely formal, as it revealed itself to him especially in types for classifying things, as genera and species, in tracing transformations which present themselves as effects of causes and re- ducing them to shapes of measurable relations. The abstraction of the formal is made through the in- strumentality of language and the result is reason, — the faculty of abstract thought. Man can see the universal in the particular; in the single experiences he can trace the laws that are generally applicable to cases of the same class; he observes some in- stances and can describe them in a general formula so as to cover an\- other instance of the same kind, and thus he becomes master of the situation; he learns 48 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. to separate in thought the essential from the acci- dental, and so instead of remaining the prey of cir- cumstance he gains the power to adapt circum- stances to himself. Form pervades all nature as an essential constit- uent thereof. If form were not an objective feature of the w^orld in which we live, formal thought would never without a miracle, or, at least, not without the mystery of mysticism, have originated accord- ing to natural law, and man could never have arisen. But form being an objective feature of all existence, it impresses itself in such a way upon living crea- tures that rational beings will naturally develop among animals whose organs of speech are per- fected as soon as social conditions produce that de- mand for communication that will result in the crea- tion of language. The marvelous advantages of reason dawned upon man like a revelation from on high, for he did not invent reason, he discovered it; and the senti- ment that its blessings came to him from above, from heaven, from that power which sways the des- tiny of the whole universe, from the gods or from God, is as natural as it is true. The anthropoid did not seek reason : reason came to him and so he be- came man. Man became man by the grace of God, by gradually imbibing the Logos that was with God in the beginning ; and in the dawn of human evolu- tion we can plainly see the landmark of mathemat- ics, for the first grand step in the development of THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 49 man as distinguished from the transitional forms of the anthropoid is the abihty to count. Man's distinctive characteristic remains, even to-day, reason, the faculty of purely formal thought ; and the characteristic of reason is its general appli- cation. All its verdicts are universal and involve apriority or beforehand knowledge so that man can foresee events and adapt means to ends. APRIORITY OF DIFFERENT DEGREES. Kant has pointed out the kinship of all purely formal notions. The validity of mathematics and logic assures us of the validity of the categories including the conception of causation; and yet ge- ometry cannot be derived from pure reason alone, hut contains an additional element which imparts to its fundamental conceptions an arbitrary appear- ance if we attempt to treat its deductions as rigidly a priori. Why should there be straight lines at all? Why is it possible that by quartering the circle we should have right angles with all their peculiarities? All these and similar notions can not be sul)sumed under a general formula of pure reason from which we could derive it with logical necessity. When dealing with lines we observe their exten- tion in one direction, when dealing with planes we have two dimensions, when measuring solids we have three. Whv can we not rr)ntinue and construct bodies that extend in t'our (Hmensions? 'Hie hmit set us by space as it jK)sitively presents itself to us 50 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. seems arbitrary, and while transcendental truths are undeniable and obvious, the fundamental no- tions of geometry seem as stubborn as the facts of our concrete existence. Space, generally granted to be elbow-room for motion in all directions, after all appears to be a definite magnitude as much as a stone wall which shuts us in like a prison, allowing us to proceed in such a way only as is permissible by those co-ordinates and no more. We can by no resort break through this limitation. Verily we might more easily shatter a rock that impedes our progress than break into the fourth dimension. The boundary line is inexorable in its adamantine rigor. Considering all these unquestionable statements, is there not a great probability that space is a con- crete fact as positive as the existence of material things, and not a mere form, not a mere potentiality of a general nature ? Certainly Euclidean geometry contains some such arbitrary elements as we should expect to meet in the realm of the a posteriori. No wonder that Gauss expressed "the desire that the Euclidean geometry should not be the true geom- etry," because "in that event we should have an ab- solute measure a priori.''' Are we thus driven to the conclusion that our space-conception is not a priori; and if, indeed, it is not a priori, it must be a posteriori ! What else can it be? Tertium non datitr. If we enter more deeply into the nature of the a priori, we shall learn that there are different kinds THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 5I of apriority, and there is a difference between the logical a priori and the geometrical a priori. Kant never investigated the source of the a pri- ori. He discovered it in the mind and seemed satis- fied with the notion that it is the nature of the mind to be possessed of time and space and the categories. He w^ent no further. He never asked, how did mind originate? Had Kant inquired into the origin of mind, he would have found that the a priori is woven into the texture of mind by the uniformities of experi- ence. The uniformities of experience teach us the laws of form, and the purely formal applies not to one case only but to any case of the same kind, and so it involves "anyness," that is to say. it is (/ priori. Mind is the product of memory, and we may briertv describe its oriijin as follows: Contact with the outer world produces impres- sions in sentient substance. The traces of these impressions arc preserved (a condition which is called "memory") and they can be revived (which state is called "recollection"). Sense-impressions are different in kind and leave dift'erent traces, but those which are the same in kind, or similar, leave traces the forms of which are the same or similar; and sense-impressions of the same kind are regis- tered in the traces haxing the same form. As a note of a definite pitch makes chords of the same i)itch vibrate while it passes all others by; so new sense- impressions revive those traces only into wliich they fit. and therebv announce themselves as beiuLr the 52 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. same in kind. Thus all sense-impressions are sys- tematized according to their forms, and the result is an orderly arrangement of memories which is called "mind."2 Thus mind develops through uniformities in sen- sation according to the laws of form. Whenever a new sense-perception registers itself mechanically and automatically in the trace to which it belongs, the event is tantamount to a logical judgment which declares that the object represented by the sense- impression belongs to the same class of objects ^^•hich produced the memory traces with which it is registered. If we abstract the interrelation of all memory- traces, omitting their contents, we have a pure sys- tem of genera and species, or the a priori idea of "classes and subclasses." The a priori, though mind-made, is constructed of chips taken from the objective world, but our several a priori notions are by no means of one and the same nature and rigidity. On the contrary, there are different degrees of apriority. The emp- tiest forms of pure thought are the categories, and the most rigid truths are the logical theorems, which can be represented diagrammatically so as to be a de- nt onst ratio ad oculos. If all bs are B and if /Sis a b, then yS is a B. If all dogs are quadrupeds and if all terriers are dogs, then terriers are quadrupeds. It is the most rigid ' For a more detailed exposition see the author's Soul of Man ; also his Whence and Whither. THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 53 kind of argument, and its statements are practically tautologies. The case is different with causation. The class of abstract notions of which causation is an instance is much more complicated. No one doubts that everv effect must have had its cause, but one of the keenest thinkers was in deep earnest when he doubted the possibility of proving this obvious state- ment. And Kant, seeing its kinship with geometry and algebra, accepted it as a pviori and treated it as being on equal terms with mathematical axioms. Yet there is an additional element in the formula of causation which somehow disguises its a priori origin, and the reason is that it is not as rigidly a priori as are the norms of pure logic. What is this additional element that somehow savors of the a posteriori? If we contemplate the interrelation of genera and species and su1)species, we find that the cate- gories with \\hich we operate are at rest. They stand before us like a well arranged cabinet with several di\isions and drawers, and these drawers have sulxlivisions and in these subdivisions we keep boxes. The cabinet is our (/ priori system of classi- fication and we store in it our a posteriori impres- sions. If a thing is in box /8, we seek for it in drawer b which is a sul)division of the dei)artment B. How different is causation! While in logic everything is al rest, causation is not conceivable without mot inn. The norms of pure reason are static, the law of cause and effect is dynamic; and 54 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. thus we have in the conception of cause and effect an additional element which is mobility. Causation is the law of transformation. We have a definite system of interrelated items in which we observe a change of place. The original situation and all detailed circumstances are the conditions; the motion that produces the change is the cause; the result or new arrangement of the parts of the whole system is the effect. Thus it appears that cau- sation is only another version of the law of the con- servation of matter and energy. The concrete items of the whole remain, in their constitutional elements, the same. No energy is lost; no particle of matter is annihilated; and the change that takes place is mere transformation.^ The law of causation is otherwise in the same predicament as the norms of logic. It can never be satisfactorily proved by experience. Experience justifies the a priori and verifies its tenets in single instances which prove true, but single instances can never demonstrate the universal and necessary va- lidity of any a priori statement. The logical a priori is rigidly a priori; it is the a priori of pure reason. But there is another kind of a priori which admits the use of that other ab- stract notion, mobility, and mobility as much as form is part and parcel of the thinking mind. Our conception of caiise and efifect is just as ideal as our conception of genera and species. It is just as much * See the author's Ursachc, Grund unci Zzvcck. Dresden, 1883; also his Fundamental Problems. THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 55 mind-made as they are, and its intrinsic necessity and universal validity are the same. Its apriority cannot be doubted ; but it is not rigidly a priori, and we will call it purely a priori. We may classify all a priori notions under two headings and both ar-t transcendental (viz., con- ditions of knowledge in their special fields) : one is the a priori of being, the other of doing. The rigid a priori is passive anyness, the less rigid a priori is active anyness. Geometry belongs to the latter. Its fundamental concept of space is a product of ac- tive apriority; and thus we cannot derive its laws from pure logic alone. The main difficulty of the parallel theorem and the straight line consists in our space-conception which is not derived from rationality in general, but results from our contemplation of motion. Our space-conception accordingly is not an idea of pure reason, but the product of pure activity. Kant felt the difference and distinguished be- tween pure reason and pure intuition or Anschau- iiHi^. He did not expressly say so, but his treatment suggests the idea that we ought to distinguish be- tween two different kinds of a priori. Transcen- dental logic, and with it all common notions of Euclid, are mere applications of the law of consist- ency; they are "rigidly a priori."' lUit our ])urc space-conception presupposes, in addition to j)urc reason, our own .activity, the potentiality of moving about in any kind of a field, and thus it admits another factor which cannot be derived from pure 56 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. reason alone. Hence all attempts at proving the theorem on rigidly a priori grounds have proved failures. SPACE AS A SPREAD OF MOTION. Mathematicians mean to start from nothingness, so they think away everything, but they retain their own mentality. Though even their mind is stripped of all particular notions, they retain their principles of reasoning and the privilege of moving about, and from these two sources geometry can be con- structed. The idea of causation goes one step further: it admits the notions of matter and energy, emptied of all particularity, in their form of pure'generali- zations. It is still a priori, but considerably more complicated than pure reason. The field in which the geometrician starts is pure nothingness ; but we shall learn later on that noth- ingness is possessed of positive qualifications. We must therefore be on our guard, and we had better inquire into the nature and origin of our nothing- ness. The geometrician cancels in thought all positive existence except his own mental activity and starts moving about as a mere nothing. In other words, we establish by abstraction a domain of monotonous sameness, which possesses the advantage of "any- ness," i. e., an absence of particularity involving universal validity. In this field of motion we pro- ceed to produce geometrical constructions. THE PHILOSOPHICx\L BASIS. 57 The geometrician's activity is pure motion, which means that it is mere progression ; the ideas of a force exerted in moving and also of resistance to be overcome are absokitely excluded. We start moving, but whither? Before us are infinite possibilities of direction. The inexhaus- tibility of chances is part of the indifference as to definiteness of determining the mode of motion (be it straight or curved). Let us start at once in all possible directions which are infinite, (a propo- sition which, in a way, is realized by the light), and having proceeded an infinitesimal way from the starting-point A to the points B, Bi,, B2, B3, B4, . . . . B ; we continue to move in infinite directions at each of these stations, reaching from B the points C, Ci, C2, Cj, C4, . . . . C.^. From Bi we would switch off to the points C\\ Cf , Cf , Cf Cl\ etc. until we reach from B^ the points C^", Cf», Cf«, Cf*, . . . -C^", thus exhausting all the points which clus- ter around every Bi, B2, B:-, B4 B^. Thus, by moving after the fashion of the light, spreading again and again from each new ])oint in all direc- tions, in a medium that offers no resistance what- ever, we obtain a uniform spread of light whose intensity in every j)oint is in liie inverse square of its distance from its source. Every lighted s])ot be- comes a center of its own from which light travels on in all directions. But among these infinite direc- tions there are rays, A, B, C, Ai, Bi. d,. . . ., A2, B2, C2 etc.. th.'it is lo '^ay. lines of motion that pursue the original direct ion and are j^aths of 58 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. maximum intensity. Each of these rays, thus ide- ally constructed, is a representation of the straight line which being the shortest path between the start- ing-point A and any other point, is the climax of directness : it is the upper limit of effectiveness and its final boundary, a non plus ultra. It is a maxi- mum because there is no loss of efficacy. The straight line represents a climax of economy, viz., the greatest intensity on the shortest path that is reached among infinite possibilities of progression by uniformly following up all. In every ray the maximum of intensity is attained by a minimum of progression. Our construction of motion in all directions after the fashion of light is practically pure space; but to avoid the forestalling of further implications we will call it simply the spread of motion in all direc- tions. The path of highest intensity in a spread of motion in all directions corresponds to the ray in an ideal conception of a spread of light, and it is equiv- alent to the straight line in geometry. We purposely modify our reference to light in our construction of straight lines, for we are well aware of the fact that the notion of a ray of light as a straight line is an ideal which describes the progression of light only as it appears, not as it is. The physicist represents light as rays only when measuring its effects in reflection, etc., but when considering the nature of light, he looks upon rays as transversal oscillations of the ether. The notion THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 59 of light as rays is at bottom as much an a priori construction as is Newton's formula of gravitation. The construction of space as a spread of motion in all directions after the analogy of light is a sum- mary creation of the scope of motion, and we call it "ideal space." Everything that moves about, if it develops into a thinking subject, when it forms the abstract idea of mobility, will inevitably create out of the data of its own existence the ideal "scope of motion," which is space. When the geometrician starts to construct his figures, drawing lines and determining the position of points, etc., he tacitly presupposes the existence of a spread of motion, such as we have described. Motility is part of his equipment, and motility pre- supposes a field of motion, \'iz., space. Space is the possibility of motion, and by ideally moving about in all possible directions the number of which is inexhaustible, we construct our notion of pure space. 1 f we speak of space wc mean this construction of our mobility. It is an a priori con- struction and is as unique as logic or arithmetic. There is but one space, and all spaces are but por- tions of this one construction. The prol)lem of tri- dimensionality will be considered later on. Here we insist only on the objective validity of our a priori construction, wliich is the same as the ob- jective validity of all our a priori constructions — of iDgic and arithmetic and causality, and it rests upon the same foundation. Our mathematical space omits all particularity and serves our purpose of 6o THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. universal application: it is founded on "anyness," and thus, within the limits of its abstraction, it holds good everywhere and under all conditions. There is no need to find out by experience in the domain of the a posteriori whether pure space is curved. Anvness has no particular qualities; we create this anyness by abstraction, and it is a matter of course that in the field of our abstraction, space will be the same throughout, unless by another act of our creative imagination we appropriate partic- ular qualities to different regions of space. The fabric of which the purely formal is woven is an absence of concreteness. It is (so far as mat- ter is concerned) nothing. Yet this airy nothing is a pretty tough material, just on account of its indifferent "any"-ness. Being void of particularity, it is universal ; it is the same throughout, and if we proceed to build our air-castles in the domain of anyness, we shall find that considering the absence of all particularity the same construction will be the same, w^herever and whenever it mav be conceived. Professor Clifford says :^ ''We assume that two lengths which are equal to the same length are equal to each other." But there is no "assumption" about it. The atmosphere in which our mathemat- ical creations are begotten is sameness. Therefore the same construction is the same wherever and whenever it may be made. We consider form only; we think away all other concrete properties, both * Loc. cit., p. 53. THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 6l of matter and energy, mass, weight, intensity, and qualities of any kind. UNIQUENESS OF PURE SPACE. Our thought-forms, constructed in the realm of empty abstraction, serve as models or as systems of reference for any of our observations in the real world of sense-experience. The laws of form are as well illustrated in our models as in real things, and can be derived from either; but the models of our thought-forms are always ready at hand while the real things are mostly inaccessible. The any- ness of pure form explains the parallelism that ob- tains between our models and actual experience, which was puzzling to Kant. And truly at first sight it is mystifying that a pure thought-construc- tion can reveal to us some of the most im])ortant and deepest secrets of objective nature ; but the sim- ple solution of the mystery consists in this, that the actions of nature are determined by the same con- ditions of possible motions wilh which pure thought is confronted in its efforts to construct its models. Here as well as there we have consistency, that is to say, a thing done is uiii(|ucly determined, and, in pure thought as well as in reality, it is such as it has been made l)v construction . Our constructions are made in anyness and apply to all possible instances of tlic kind; and thus we may as well define si)ace as the potentiality of meas- uring, which presU]iposes moving about. Mobility 62 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. granted, we can construct space as the scope of our motion in anyness. Of course we must bear in mind that our motion is in thou£>-ht only and we have dropped all notions of particularity so as to leave an utter absence of force and resistance. The motor element, qua energy, is not taken into consideration, but we contemplate only the products of progres- sion. Since in the realm of pure form, thus created by abstraction, we move in a domain void of par- ticularity, it is not an assumption (as Riemann declares in his famous inaugural dissertation), but a matter of course which follows with logical ne- cessity, that lines are independent of position; they are the same anywhere. In actual space, position is by no means a negli- gible quantity. A real pyramid consisting of actual material is possessed of dififerent qualities according to position, and the line AB, representing a path from the top of a mountain to the valley is very different from the line BA, which is the path from the valley to the top of the mountain. In Euclidean geometry AB=BA. Riemann attempts to identify the mathematical space of a triple manifold with actual space and ex- pects a proof from experience, but, properly speak- ing, they are radically different. In real space po- sition is not a negligible factor, and would necessi- tate a fourth co-ordinate which has a definite rela- tion to the plumb-line; and this fourth co-ordinate (which we may call a fourth dimension) suffers a THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 63 constant modification of increase in inverse propor- tion to the scjuare of the distance from the center of this planet of ours. It is rectiHnear, yet all the plumb- lines are converging toward an inaccessible center; accordingly, they are by no means of equal value in their different parts. How different is mathemat- ical space ! It is homogeneous throughout. And it is so because we made it so by abstraction. Pure form is a feature which is by no means a mere nonentity. Having emptied existence of all concrete actuality, and having thought away every- thing, we are confronted by an absolute vacancy — a zero of existence: but the zero has positive char- acteristics and there is this peculiarity about the zero that it is the mother of infinitude. The thought is so true in mathematics that it is trite. Let any number be divided by nought, the result is the in- finitely great ; and let nought be divided by any number, the result is the infinitely small. In think- ing away everything concrete we retain with our nothingness potentiality. Potentiality is the empire of purely formal constructions, in the dim back- ground of which lurks the phantom of infinitude. MATHEMATICAL SPACE AND I' 1 1 YSIOLOGICAL SPACE. If we admit to our conception of space the qual- ities of bodies such as mass, our conception of real space will become more comj)licaled still. What we gain in concrete definitencss we lose from uni- x'ersality. and we can return tn the general ap])li 64 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. cability of a priori conditions only by dropping all concrete features and limiting our geometrical constructions to the abstract domain of pure form. Mathematical space with its straight lines, planes, and right angles is an ideal construction. It exists in our mind only just as much as do logic and arithmetic. In the external world there are no numbers, no mathematical lines, no logarithms, no sines, tangents, nor secants. The same is true of all the formal sciences. There are no genera and species, no syllogisms, neither inductions nor deduc- tions, running about in the world, but only concrete individuals and a concatenation of events. There are no laws that govern the motions of stars or mol- ecules ; yet there are things acting in a definite way, and their actions depend on changes in relational conditions which can be expressed in formulas. All the generalized notions of the formal sciences are mental contrivances which comprise relational fea- tures in general rules. The formulas as such are purely ideal, but the relational features which they describe are o1)jectively real. Thus, the space-conception of the mathematician is an ideal construction ; but the ideal has objective significance. Ideal and subjective are by no means synonyms. With the help of an ideal space-con- ception we can acquire knowledge concerning the real space of the objective world. Here the New- tonian law may be cited as a conspicuous example. How can the thinking subject know a priori any- thing about the object? Simply because the subject THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 05 is an object moving about among other objects. Mobility is a qualification of the object, and I, the thinking subject, become conscious of the general rules of motion only, because I also am an object endowed with mobility. My ''scope of motion" can- not be derived from the abstract idea of myself as a thinking subject, but is the product of a conside- ration of my mobility, generalized from my activities as an object by omitting all particularities. Mathematical space is a priori in the Kantian sense. However, it is not ready-made in our mind, it is not an innate idea, but the product of much toil and careful thought. Nor will its construction be possible, except at a maturer age after a long development. Physiological space is the direct and unsophisti- cated space-conception of our senses. It originates through experience, and is, in its way, a truer pic- ture of actual or physical space than mathematical space. The latter is more general, the former more concrete. In physiological space position is not in- different, for high and low, right and left, and up and down are of great importance. Geometrically congruent figures produce (as Mach has shown) remarkably different impressions if they i)resent themselves to the eyes in different positions. In a geometrical plane the figures can be shoved about without suffering a change of form. If they are flopped, their inner relations remain the same, as, e.g., helices of opposite directions arc, mathe- matically considered, congruent, while in actual life 66 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. they would always remain mere symmetrical coun- terparts. So the right and the left hands considered as mere mathematical bodies are congruent, while in reality neither can take the place of the other. A glove which we may treat as a two-dimensional thing can be turned inside out, but we would need a fourth dimension to flop the hand, a three-dimen- sional body, into its inverted counterpart. So long- as we have no fourth dimension, the latter being a mere logical fiction, this cannot be done. Yet mathe- matically considered, the two hands are congruent. Why? Not because they are actually of the same shape, but because in our mathematics the quali- fications of position are excluded ; the relational alone counts, and the relational is the same in both cases. Mathematical space being an ideal construction, it is a matter of course that all mathematical prob- lems must be settled by a priori operations of pure thought, and cannot be decided by external experi- ment or by reference to a posteriori information. HOMOGENEITY OF SPACE DUE TO ABSTRACTION. When moving about, we change our place and pass by different objects. These objects too are moving; and thus our scope of motion tallies so exactly with theirs that one can be used for the com- putation of the other. All scopes of motion are pos- sessed of the same anyness. Space as we find it in experience is best defined THE PHILOSOPHICAL DASIS. 67 as the juxtaposition of things. If there is need of distinguishing it from our ideal space-conception which is the scope of our mobihty, we may call the former pure objective space, the latter pure sub- jective space, but, our subjective ideas being rooted in our mobility, which is a constitutional feature of our objective existence, for many practical pur- poses the two are the same. But though pure space, whether its conception be established objectively or subjectively, must be accepted as the same, are we not driven to the con- clusion that there are after all two different kinds of space: mathematical space, which is ideal, and physiological space, which is real? And if they are different, must we not assume them to be indepen- dent of each other ^ \Miat is their mutual relation? The two spaces, the ideal construction of mathe- matical space and the reconstruction in our senses of the juxtaposition of things surrounding us, are different solely because they have been 1)uilt up upon two different planes of abstraction ; physiological space includes, and mathematical space excludes, the sensory data of juxtaposition. T"*hysiological space admits concrete facts, — man's own upright position, gravity, perspective, etc. Matliematical space is purely formal, and to lay its foundation we have dug down to the bed-rock of our formal knowl- edge, which is "anyness," Mathematical space is a priori, albeit the a priori of motion. At present it is sufficient to state that the homo- geneity of a mathematical space is its anyness, and 68 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. its anyness is due to our construction of it in the domain of pure form, involving universality and excluding everything concrete and particular. The idea of homogeneity in our space-conception is the tacit condition for the theorems of similarity and proportion, and also of free mobility without change, viz., that figures can be shifted about with- out suffering distortion either by shrinkage or by expanse. The principle of homogeneity being ad- mitted, we can shove figures about on any surface the curvature of which is either constant or zero. This produces either the non-Euclidean geometries of spherical, pseudo-spherical, and elliptic surfaces, or the plane geometry of Euclid — all of them a priori constructions made without reference to real- ity. Our a priori constructions serve an important purpose. We use them as systems of reference. We construct a priori a number system, making a simple progression through a series of units which we denominate from the starting-point o, as i, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, etc. These numbers are purely ideal con- structions, but with their help we can count and measure and weigh the several objects of reality that confront experience ; and in all cases we fall back upon our ideal number system, saying, the table has four legs ; it is two and a half feet high, it weighs fifty pounds, etc. We call these modes of determination quantitative. The element of quantitative measurement is the ideal construction of units, all of which are assumed THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 69 to be discrete and equivalent. The equivalence of numbers as much as the homogeneity of space, is due to abstraction. In reality equivalent units do not exist any more than different parts of real space may be regarded as homogeneous. Both construc- tions have been made to create a domain of anyness, for the purpose of standards of reference. EVEN BOUNDARIES AS STANDARDS OF MEASUREMENT. Standards of reference are useful only when they are unique, and thus we cannot use any path of our spread of motion in all directions, but must select one that admits of no equivocation. The only line that possesses this quality is the ray, viz., the straight line or the path of greatest intensity. The straight line is one instance only of a whole class of similar constructions which with one name may be called "even boundaries," and by even I mean congruent with itself. They remain the same in any position and no change originates however they may be turned. Clifford, starting from objective space, con- structs the plane by polishing three surfaces, A, B, and C, until they fit one another, which means until they are congruent.^ Tlis proposition leads to the same result as ours, but the essential ihing is not so much fas Clifford has it ) that the three ])lanes are congruent, each to the two others, but that each plane is congruent with its own inversion. Thus, ' Common Sense of the Exact Sciences, Applcton & Co., p. 66. 70 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. under all conditions, each one is congruent with itself. Each plane partitions the whole infinite space into two congruent halves. Having divided space so as to make the boun- dary surface congruent with itself (viz., a plane), we now divide the plane (we will call it P) in the same way, — a process best exemplified in the fold- ing of a sheet of paper stretched flat on the table. The crease represents a boundary congruent with itself. In contrast to curved lines, which cannot be flopped or shoved or turned without involving a change in our construction, we speak of a straight line as an even boundary. A circle can be flopped upon itself, but it is not an even boundary congruent with itself, because the inside contents and the outside surroundings are dififerent. If we take a plane, represented by a piece of paper that has been evenly divided by the crease AB, and divide it again crosswise, say in the point O, by another crease CD, into two equal parts, M^e establish in the four angles round O a new kind of even boundary. The bipartition results in a division of each half plane into two portions which again are congruent the one to the other ; and the line in the crease CD, constituting, together with the first crease, AB, two angles, is (like the straight line and the plane) nothing more nor less than an even boundary con- struction. The right angle originates by the pro- THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 71 cess of halving the straight Une conceived as an angle. Let us now consider the significance of even boundaries. A point being a mere locus in space, has no ex- tension whatever: it is congruent with itself on account of its want of any discriminating parts. If it rotates in any direction, it makes no difference. There is no mystery about a point's being con- gruent with itself in any position. It results from our conception of a point in agreement with the ab- straction we have made; but when we are con- fronted witli lines or surfaces that are congruent with themselves we believe ourselves nonplussed; yet the mystery of a straight line is not greater than that of a point. A line which when flopped or turned in its direc- tion remains congruent with itself is called straight, and a surface which when flopped or turned round on itself remains congruent with itself is called plane or flat. The straight lines and the flat surfaces are, among all possible boundaries, of special imi)or- tance, for a similar reason that the abstraction of ])ure form is so useful. In the domain of pure form we get rid of all particularity and thus establish a norm fit for universal application. In geometry straight lines and |)lane surfaces are the climax of simplicity; they are void of any particularity that needs further description, or would complicate the situation, and this absence of complications in ^22 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. their construction is their greatest recommendation. The most important point, however, is their quaUty of being unique by being even. It renders them specially available for purposes of reference. We can construct a priori different surfaces that are homogeneous, yielding as many different sys- tems of geometry. Euclidean geometry is neither more nor less true than spherical or elliptic geom- etry; all of them are purely formal constructions, they are a priori, being each one on its own premises irrefutable by experience; but plane geometry is more practical for general purposes. The question in geometry is not, as some meta- geometricians would have it, "Is objective space flat or curved?" but, 'Ts it possible to make con- structions that shall be unique so as to be service- able as standards of reference?'' The former ques- tion is due to a misconception of the nature of math- ematics ; the latter must be answered in the affirma- tive. All even boundaries are unique and can there- fore be used as standards of reference. THE STRAIGHT LINE INDISPENSABLE. Straight lines do not exist in reality. How rough are the edges of the straightest rulers, and how rugged are the straightest lines drawn with instruments of precision, if measured by the stan- dard of mathematical straightness ! And if we con- sider the paths of motion, be they of chemical atoms or terrestrial or celestial bodies, we shall always THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. ^^ find them to be curves of high conii)lexity. Never- theless the idea of the straight hne is justified by experience in so far as it helps us to analyze the complex curves into their elementary factors, no one of which is truly straight; but each one of which, when we ^o to the end of our analysis, can be represented as a straight line. Judging from the experience we have of moving bodies, we cannot doubt that if the sun's attraction of the earth (as well as that of all other celestial bodies) could be annihilated, the earth would fly off into space in a straight line. Thus the mud on carriage wheels, when spurting off, and the pebbles that are thrown with a sling, are flying in a tangential direction which would be absolutely straight w^re it not for the interference of the gravity of the earth, which is constantly asserting itself and modifies the straightest line into a curve. Our idea of a straight line is suggested to us by experience when we attempt to resolve compound forces into their constituents, but it is not traceable in experience. It is a product of our method of measurement. It is a creation of our own doings, yet it is justified by the success which attends its employment. The great question in geometry is not, whether straight lines are real but whether their construc- tion is not an indispensable ref|uisite for any pos- sible system of space measurement, and further, what is the nature of straight lines and planes and right angles; how does their conception originate 74 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. and why are they of paramount importance in ge- ometry. \\> can of course posit that space should be filled up with a medium such as would deflect every ray of light so that straight rays would be impos- sible. For all we know ether may in an extremely slight degree operate in that way. But there w^ould be nothing in that that could dispose of the think- ability of a line absolutely straight in the Euclidean sense with all that the same involves, so that Eu- clidean geometry would not thereby be invalidated. Now the fact that the straight line (as a purely mental construction) is possible cannot be denied: we use it and that should be sufficient for all prac- tical purposes. That we can construct curves also does not invalidate the existence of straight lines. So again while a geometry based upon the idea of homaloidal space wall remain what it has ever been, the other geometries are not made thereby il- legitimate. Euclid disposes as little of Lobachevsky and Bolyai as they do of Euclid. As to the nature of the straight line and all the other notions connected therewith, we shall always be able to determine them as concepts of boundary, either reaching the utmost limit of a certain func- tion, be it of the highest (such as » ) or lowest meas- ure (such as o) ; or dividing a whole into two con- gruent parts. The utility of such boundary concepts becomes apparent when we are in need of standards for measurement. An even boundary being the utmost THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 75 limit is unique. There are innumerable curves, but there is only one kind of straight line. Accordingly, if we need a standard for measuring curves, we must naturally fall back upon the straight line and determine its curvature by its deviation from the straight line which represents a zero of curvature. The straight line is the simplest of all boundary concepts. Hence its indispensableness. If we measure a curvature we resolve the curve into infinitesimal pieces of straight lines, and then determine their change of direction. Thus we use the straight line as a reference in our measurement of curves. The simplest curve is the circle, and its curvature is expressed by the reciprocal of the ra- dius; but the radius is a straight line. It seems that we cannot escape straightness anywhere in geometry; for it is the simplest instrument for meas- uring distance. \\'e may replace metric geometry by projective geometry, but what could projective geometricians do if they had not straight lines for their projections? Without them they would be in a strait indeed! But suppose we renounced with Lobatchevsky the conventional method of even boundary concep- tions, especially straightness of line, and were satis- fied with straightest lines, what would be the result? He does not at the same time, surrender either the principle of consistency or tlie assumption of the homogeneity of space, and thus he builds up a ge- ometry independent of the theorem of parallel lines, which would be applical^lc to two systems, the Eu- /G THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. clidean of straight lines and the non-Eudidean of curved space. But the latter needs the straight line as much as the former and finds its natural limit in a sphere whose radius is infinite and whose curva- ture is zero. He can measure no spheric curvature without the radius, and after all he reaches the straight line in the limit of curvature. Yet it is noteworthy that in the Euclidean system the straight line is definite and rr irrational, while in the non- Euclidean, TT is a definite number according to the measure of curvature and the straight line becomes irrational. THE SUPERREAL. We said in a former chapter (p. 48), "man did not invent reason, he discovered it," which means that the nature of reason is definite, unalterable, and therefore valid. The same is true of all any- ness of all formal thought, of pure logic, of mathe- matics, and generally of anything that with truth can be stated a priori. Though the norms of any- ness are woven of pure nothingness, the flimsiest material imaginable, they are the factors which de- termine the course of events in the entire sweep of actual existence and in this sense they are real. They are not real in the sense of materiality; they are real only in being efficient and in distinction to the reality of corporeal things we may call them superreal. On the one hand it is true that mathematics is THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. y"] a mental construction ; it is purely ideal, which means it is \vo\'en of thought. On the other hand we must grant that the nature of this construction is fore- determined in its minutest detail and in this sense all its theorems must be discovered. A\ e erant that there are no sines, and cosines, no tangents and cotangents, no logarithms, no number tt, nor even lines, in nature, but there are relations in nature which correspond to these notions and sug- gest the invention of symbols for the sake of de- termining them with exactness. These relations possess a normative value. Stones are real in the sense of offering resistance in a special place, but these norms are superreal because they are efficient factors everywhere. The reality of mathematics is well set forth in these words of Prof. Cassius Jackson Keyser, of Columbia University: "Phrase it as you will, there is a world that is peopled with ideas, ensembles, propositions, relations, and implica- tions, in endless variety and multiplicity, in structure ran- ging- from the very simple to the endlessly intricate and com- plicate. That world is not the product but the object, not the creature but the quarry of thought, the entities compos- ing it — propositions, for example, — being no more identical with thinking them than wine is identical with the drinking of it. Mind or no mind, that world exists as an extra- l)ersonal affair, — pragmatism to llu' contrary notwithstand- ing." While llie relational possesses objective signifi- cance, the method of describing it is subjective and of course the symbols arc arbitrarv. 78 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. In this connection we wish to call attention to a most important point, which is the necessity of cre- ating fixed units for counting. As there are no logarithms in nature, so there are no numbers; there are only objects or things sufficiently equal which for a certain purpose may be considered equivalent, so that we can ignore these differences, and assuming them to be the same, count them. DISCRETE UNITS AND THE CONTINUUM. Nature is a continuum ; there are no boundaries among things, and all events that happen proceed in an uninterrupted flow of continuous transforma- tions. For the sake of creating order in this flux which would seem to be a chaos to us, we must distinguish and mark off individual objects with definite boundaries. This method may be seen in all branches of knowledge, and is most in evidence in arithmetic. When counting we start in the domain of nothingness and build up the entire structure of arithmetic with the products of our own making. We ought to know that whatever we do, we must first of all take a definite stand for ourselves. When we start doing anything, we must have a starting- point, and even though the world may be a constant flux we must for the sake of definiteness regard our starting-point as fixed. It need not be fixed in real- ity, but if it is to serve as a point of reference we must regard it as fixed and look upon all the rest as movable; otherwise the world would be an in- THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 79 determinable tangle. Here we have the first rule of mental activity. There may be no rest in the world vet we must create the fiction of a rest as a Sos jxoL TTov crT(o aud wheuevcr we take any step we must repeat this fictitious process of laying down definite points. All the things which are observed around us are compounds of qualities which are only temporarily combined. To call them things as if they were separate beings existing without reference to the rest is a fiction, but it is part of our method of classification, and without this fictitious comprehen- sion of certain groups of qualities under definite names and treating them as units, we could make no headway in this world of constant flux, and all events of life would swim 1)efore our mental eye. Our method in arithmetic is similar. We count as if units existed, yet the idea of a unit is a fiction. We count our fingers or the l^eads of an abacus or any other set of things as if they were equal. W^e count the feet which we measure off in a certain line as if each one were cfjuivalent to all the rest. For all we know they may be different, but for our pur])ose of measuring they possess the same signifi- cance. This is neither an hypothesis nor an assump- tion nor a fiction, but a postulate needed for a definite purpose. For our purpose and according to the method emi)]oyed they are the same. We postulate their sameness. We have made them the same, we treat them as equal. Their sameness de- 8o THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. pends upon the conditions from which we start and on the purpose which we have in view. There are theorems which are true in arithmetic but which do not hold true in practical life. I will only mention the theorem 2+3+4 = 4+3+2 = 4+2+3 etc. In real life the order in which things are pieced together is sometimes very essential, but in pure arithmetic, when we have started in the domain of nothingness and build with the products of our own counting which are ciphers absolutely equivalent to each other, the rule holds good and it will be serviceable for us to know it and to utilize its significance. The positing of units which appears to be an indispensable step in the construction of arithmetic is also of great importance in actual psychology and becomes most apparent in the mechanism of vision. Consider the fact that the kinematoscope has become possible only through an artificial separation of the successive pictures which are again fused together into a new continuum. The film which passes before the lens consists of a series of little pictures, and each one is singly presented, halting a moment and being separated from the next by a rotating fan which covers it at the moment when it is exchanged for the succeeding picture. If the moving figures on the screen did not consist of a definite number of pictures fused into one by our eye which is incapable of distinguishing their quick succession the whole sight would be blurred and we THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS. 8l could see nothing but an indiscriminate and un- analyzable perpetual flux. This method of our mind which produces units in a continuum may possess a still deeper signifi- cance, for it may mark the very beginning of the real world. For all we know the formation of the chemical atoms in the evolution of stellar nebulas may be nothing but an analogy to this process. The manifestation of life too begins with the creation of individuals — of definite living creatures which develop dift'erently under dififerent conditions and again the soul becomes possible by the definiteness of single sense-impressions which can be distin- guished as units from others of a dififerent tvpe. Thus the contrast between the continuum and the atomic formation appears to be fundamental and gives rise to many problems which have be- come especially troublesome in mathematics. But if we bear in mind that the method, so to speak, of atomic division is indispensable to change a world of continuous flux into a system that can be com- puted and determined wMth at least approximate accuracy, we will be apt to appreciate thai the atomic fiction in arithmetic is an indispensable part of the method by whicii the whole science is created. MATHEMATICS AND METAGEOMETRY. DIFFERENT GEOMETRICAL SYSTEMS. STRAIGHTNESS, flatness, and rectangularity are qualities which cannot (like numbers) be determined in purely quantitative terms; but they are determined nevertheless by the conditions under which our constructions must be made. A right angle is not an arbitrary amount of ninety degrees, but a quarter of a circle, and even the nature of angles and degrees is not derivable either from arithmetic or from pure reason. They are not purely quantitative magnitudes. They contain a qualita- tive element which cannot be expressed in numbers alone. A plane is not zero, but a zero of curvature in a boundary between two solids ; and its qualita- tive element is determined, as Kant would express it, by Anschaunng, or as we prefer to say, by pure motility, i. e., it belongs to the domain of the a priori of doing. For Kant's term Anschaunng has the disadvantage of suggesting the passive sense denoted by the word "contemplation,'' while it is important to bear in mind that the thinking subject by its own activities creates the conditions that de- termine the qualities above mentioned. MATHEMATICS AND METAGEOAIETRY. ^3 Our method of creating by construction the straight Hue, the plane, and the right angle, does not exclude the possibility of other methods of space-measurement, the standards of which would not be even boundaries, such as straight lines, but lines possessed of either a positive curvature like the sphere or a negative curvature rendering their surface pseudo-spherical. Spheres are well known and do not stand in need of description. Their curvature which is posi- tive is determined by the reciprocal of their radius. A A B Fig. I. Fig. 2. Pseudo-s])heres are surfaces of negative curva- ture, and pseudo-spherical surfaces are saddle- shaped. Only limited pieces can be connectedly rci)resented, and wc reproduce from Hclmholtz,' two instances. If arc ah in figure i revolves round an axis AR, it will describe a concave-convex sur- face like that of the inside of a wedding-ring; and in the same way, if either of the curves of figure 2 revolve round their axis of symmetry, it will de- scribe one half of a jiseudosphcrical surface rescm- ' Loc. cit., p. 42. 84 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. bling the shape of a morning-glory whose tapering stem is infinitely prolonged. Helmholtz compares the former to an anchor-ring, the latter to a cham- pagne glass of the old style. The sum of the angles of triangles on spheres always exceeds i8o°, and the larger the sphere the more will their triangles resemble the triangle in the plane. On the other hand, the smii of the angles of triangles on the pseudosphere will always be somewhat less than i8o°. If we define the right angle as the fourth part of a whole circuit, it will be seen that analogously the right angle in the plane dififers from the right angles on the sphere as well as the pseudosphere. We may add that while in spherical space sev- eral shortest lines are possible, in pseudospherical space w^e can draw one shortest line only. Both sur- faces, however, are homogeneous (i. e., figures can be moved in it without suffering a change in dimen- sions), but the parallel lines which do not meet are impossible in either. Wt may further construct surfaces in which changes of place involve either expansion or con- traction, but it is obvious that they would be less serviceable as systems of space-measurement the more irregular they grow. TRIDIMEXSIONALITY. Space is usually regarded as tridimensional, but there are some people who, following Kant, express MATHEMATICS AND METAGEOMETRY. 85 themselves with reserve, saying that the mind of man may be buik up in such a way as to conceive of objects in terms of three dimensions. Others think that the actual and real thing that is called space may be quite different from our tridimensional conception of it and may in point of fact be four, or five, or /z-dimensional. Let us ask first what "dimension" means. Does dimension mean direction ? Obviously not, for we have seen that the possibilities of direction in space are infinite. Dimension is only a popular term for co-ordi- nate. In space there are no dimensions laid down, but in a space of infinite directions three co-ordinates are needed to determine from a given point of ref- erence the position of any other point. In a former section on "Even Boundaries as Standards of Measurement," we have halved space and produced a plane Pi as an e\en boundary be- tween the two halves; we have halved the plane Pi by turning the plane so upon itself, that like a crease in a folded sheet of paper the straight line AB was produced on the plane. We then halved the straight line, the even boundary between the two half-planes, by again turning the plane U])on itself so that the line AB covered its own prolongation. It is as if our folded sheet of paper were folded a second time upon itself so that the crease would be foldcfl upon itself and rtne part of the same fall exactly upon and cover the other ])art. On opening the sheet we have a second crease crossing the first 86 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. one making- the perpendicular CD, in the point O, thus producing right angles on the straight line AB, represented in the cross-creases of the twice folded sheet of paper. Here the method of producing even boundaries by halving comes to a natural end. So far our products are the plane, the straight line, the point and as an incidental but valuable by- product, the right angle. We may now venture on a synthesis of our ma- terials. We lay two planes, Po and P?., through the two creases at right angles on the original plane Pi, represented by the sheet of paper, and it becomes apparent that the two new planes Po and P3 will intersect at O, producing a line EF common to both planes P2 and P3, and they will bear the same rela- tion to each as each one does to the original plane Pi, that is to say: the whole system is congruent with itself. If we make the planes change places. Pi may as well take the place of P2 and Po of P3 and P3 of P2 or Pi of P3, etc., or vice versa, and all the internal relations would remain absolutely the same. Accordingly we have here in this system of the three planes at right angles (the result of repeated halving), a composition of even boundaries which, as the simplest and least complicated construction of its kind, recomends itself for a standard of meas- urement of the whole spread of motility. The most significant feature of our construction consists in this, that we thereby produce a con- venient system of reference for determining every MATHEMATICS AND METAGEOMETRY. 87 possible point in co-ordinates of straight lines stand- ing at right angles to the three planes. If we start from the ready conception of objec- tive space (the juxtaposition of things) we can refer the several distances to analogous loci in our system of the three planes, mutually perpendicular, each to the others, \\'e cut space in two equal halves by the horizontal plane Pi. We repeat the cutting so as to let the two halves of the first cut in their angu- lar relation to the new cut (in P2) be congruent with each other, a procedure which is possible only if we make use of the even boundary concept with which we have become acquainted. Accordingly, the second cut should stand at right angles on the first cut. The two planes Pi and P2 have one line in common, EF, and any plane placed at right an- gles to EF (in the point O) will again satisfy the demand of dividing space, including the two planes Pi and P2, into two congruent halves. The two new lines, produced by the cut of the third plane P.i through the two former planes Pi and Po. stand both at right angles to EF. Should we continue our method of cutting space at rigjit angles in O on cither of these lines, we would produce a plane coincident with P,, which is to say, that the possi- 1)ilities of the system arc exhausted. This implies that in any system of pure space three co-ordinates are suflicient for the determina- tion of any place from a given reference point. 88 THE FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS. THREE A CONCEPT OF BOUNDARY. The niiml^er three is a concept of boundary as much as the straight line. Under specially compli- cated conditions we might need more than three co-ordinates to calculate the place of a point, but in empty space the number three, the lowest number that is really and truly a number, is sufficient. If space is to be empty space from which the notion of all concrete things is excluded, a kind of model constructed for the purpose of determining juxta- position, three co-ordinates are sufficient, because our system of reference consists of three planes, and we have seen above that there is no possibility of introducing a fourth plane without destroying its character of being congruent with itself, which imparts to it the simplicity and uniqueness that render it available for a standard of measurement. Three is a peculiar number which is of great significance. It is the first real number, being the simplest multiplex. One and two and also zero are of course numbers if we consider them as mem- bers of the number-system in its entirety, but singly regarded they are not yet numbers in the full sense of the word. One is the unit, two is a couple or a pair, but three is the smallest amount of a genuine plurality. Savages who can distinguish only be- tween one and two have not yet evolved the notion of number; and the transition to the next higher stage involving the knowledge of "three" passes through a mental condition in which there exists MATHEMATICS AND METAGEOMETRY. 8g only the notion one, two, and plurality of any kind. When the idea of three is once definitely recognized, the naming of all other numbers can follow in rapid succession. In this connection we may incidentally call at- tention to the significance of the grammatical dual number as seen in the Semitic and Greek languages. It is a siirviving relic and token of a period during which the unit, the pair, and the uncounted plural- ity constituted the entire gamut of human arith- metic. The dual form of grammatical number by the development of the number-system became re- dundant and cumbersome, being retained only for a while to express the idea of a couple, a pair that naturally belong together. Certainly, the origin of the notion three has its germ in the nature of abstract anyness. Nor is it an accident that in order to construct the simplest figure which is a real figure, at least three lines are needed. The importance of the triangle, which becomes most prominent in trigonometry, is due to its being the simplest possible figure wliich accord- ingly possesses the intrinsic worth of economy. The number three j)lays also a significant part in logic, and in llie l)ranclu's of ihe a])])lied sciences, and thus we need not l)e astonishe