THE LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA RIVERSIDE Mf<\ II LECTURES AND REMAINS RICHARD LEWIS NETTLESHIP VOL. I. ©■ 18 8 9. PHILOSOPHICAL LECTURES AND REMAINS OF RICHARD LEWIS NETTLESHIP FELLOW AND TUTOR OF BALLIOL COLLEGE, OXFORD EDITED, WITH A BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH BY A. C. BRADLEY PROFESSOR OF ENGLISH LITERATURE IN THE UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW FORMERLY FELLOW AND LECTURER OF BALLIOL COLLEGE, OXFORD AND G. R. BENSON OF BALLIOL COLLEGE, OXFORD IN TWO VOLUMES: VOL. I Pontoon MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltd. NEW YORK: THE MACMILLAN CO. 1897 \_All rights reserved] b^gf HORACE HART, PRINTER TO THE UNIVERSITY PREFACE The persons jointly responsible for the publi- cation of these volumes are the editors named on the title-page, and Professor C. E. Vaughan, of the University College of South Wales, one of the executors of Nettleship's will. For the preparation of the first volume, the form in which everything in it finally appears, and the notes contained in square brackets, Mr. Bradley is solely answerable. Mr. Benson is in like manner solely answerable in the case of the second volume. In addition to the matter here published, a considerable mass of material was prepared by Mr. Vaughan from reports of Nettleship's lectures on the history of Logic and of Moral Philosophy. But it was decided not to make use of this material, as the more original parts of the lectures could not well be separated from other parts vi PREFACE which, however well adapted to their purpose, seemed less characteristic of the author. Explanations regarding the different portions of which these volumes are composed will be found prefixed to them. The only portion which was written for publication is the essay on ' Plato's Conception of Goodness and the Good.' The ' Miscellaneous Papers and Extracts from Letters' are, almost without exception, of the nature of private and probably hurried correspondence. The remainder of the first volume, and the whole of the second, consist of redactions of lecture- notes. In regard to these, a few words are required here in addition to the remarks of the editors. Nettleship's own notes were, as a rule, very scanty, and have been of use only in occasional passages. The editors have therefore attempted to reproduce the lectures chiefly by comparison, selection, and combination of reports by pupils who heard them in various years to- wards the end of Nettleship's life. They have endeavoured, as far as possible, to preserve the original phraseology and the forms of the sen- tences; but, especially in difficult passages, they have sometimes been compelled to choose between various possible interpretations, and even occa- sionally to represent what they believed to be the author's meaning without professing to reproduce his words. They have also modified or removed, PREFACE vii where they detected them, such unguarded or ambiguous statements as naturally occur in ex- tempore lecturing. They are, of course, answer- able for the correctness of the references inserted. No one can feel more keenly than those respon- sible for the publication of these volumes how difficult was the task of determining what should be printed, and how likely they are to have erred in their choice. They will only say that they have been guided by anxious consideration of three questions, — what was most characteristic of the author, what promised to be of most use to readers, and which of the proposed selections Nettleship himself would, to the best of their judgment, have accepted or rejected. Their thanks are due to many old pupils of Nettleship, who lent their reports of the lectures ; to several friends, especially the Master of Balliol, Mr. Bernard Bosanquet, Mr. R. G. Tatton, Pro- fessor J. Cook Wilson, and Professor John Burnet, who gave advice as to the selection of lectures for publication ; to Mr. Vaughan, to Mr. George Macdonald, Lecturer in Glasgow University, to Mr. J. A. Smith, Fellow and Tutor of Balliol, and to one another, for assistance given in various ways in the preparation of these volumes. CONTENTS OF VOL. I PACK BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xi MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS AND EXTRACTS FROM LETTERS i I. Immortality (Preliminary Thoughts) ... 3 II. Pleasure (Preliminary Thoughts) . . . . n III. Spirit 20 IV. Individuality ......... 33 V. The Atonement ........ 39 VI. Florence and Athens 43 VII. Extracts from Letters 50 LECTURES ON LOGIC 109 Sect. I. Thought, Sense, and Imagination . . . .113 II. The Value of Theory ...... 122 III. Language and its Function in Knowledge . . 127 IV. Concepts as the Principles of Knowledge . 142 V. Formal Logic as the Science of the Principles of Knowledge ....... 148 VI. The Concept as Universal, Particular, Indi- vidual 153 VII. Conception and Perception. Mediate and Imme- diate Apprehension ...... 165 VIII. Conceivability and Sensation as Tests of Truth 174 IX. Concept and Thing. Subjective and Objective. Self and Not-Self . . . . . .191 X. Classification and Definition of Concepts. . 212 XI. Extension and Intension. The Generality of Concepts 2I 7 x CONTENTS PAGE Note A. Experience 225 Note B. Certitude. Law. Necessity. Uniformity . . 228 Note C. Subjective and Objective 231 PLATO'S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS AND THE GOOD 235 Introduction, chiefly on Plato's Criticism of Current Ideas 238 The Protagoras ......... 250 The Meno 258 The Laches and the Charmides ..... 264 The Euthydemus ......... 268 The Gorgias 276 The Philebus ......... 307 The Republic ......... 336 Plato's Ideas on Philosophy and Life .... 383 BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH A DETAILED biography of one whose main work was that of a College tutor will not be expected or required by the reader of the following Remains. I shall merely recount the chief events of Nettleship's outer life, and shall then attempt such a description of his mind and character as may explain in some degree the great in- fluence he exerted on his pupils and friends, and the impression of ' uncommonness ' which he almost in- variably left even on acquaintances. Lewis Nettleship (for he was called by his second name) was born on December 17, 1846. His father was Henry John Nettleship, a solicitor of Kettering in Northamptonshire ; his mother, Isabella Ann, daughter of the Rev. James Hogg, of the same town. Among his elder brothers were Henry, who became Professor of Latin at Oxford, and who died in the summer of 1893 ; John, well known as a painter ; and Edward, well known as an oculist. Lewis was educated at Uppingham School, and was deeply influenced by his head-master, Edward Thring, for whom he retained a very strong ad- miration and affection ] . He early showed unusual ability, and for some years before he left Uppingham was head 1 Some of the correspondence which passed between master and pupil during Nettleship's undergraduate years is likely to be published in Mr. G. R. Parkin's forthcoming memoir of Thring. xii BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH of the school. At this time, we are told, he appeared ' old for his age,' sober and sedate ; but he entered readily into ' all the fun,' and practised the school games, not with marked ability, but with a characteristic desire to do everything as well as he could. Those who met him as a man have often unconsciously echoed the remark made by an acquaintance in the year 1864 — ' though he was very quiet and reserved, one felt the better for being in the room with him.' Curiously characteristic, again, in turn of phrase as well as in sub- stance, are the words which he is remembered to have used in addressing the school on an occasion when Thring, according to his custom, had left it to the senior boys to bring an unknown offender to justice. Nettleship ' asked the lads to remember they were trusted, and called on them to be worthy of the trust. He ended his appeal to the sense of honour by saying, " Uppingham is a little place, and I dare say you fellows think it doesn't very much matter how we treat either our masters or one another ; but at least it shall never be said, if I can help it, that Uppingham boys are either liars or cowards. Those who agree, show their hands." And the whole school rose, and cheered their head boy to the echo. One remembers how, ever after, one seemed to look to Nettleship as a kind of impersonation of truth and bravery' 1 . Nettleship entered for the Balliol Scholarships in November, 1864, and came out head of the list. He went up to Oxford in October, 1865, and began a career of brilliant University successes. In addition to minor honours, he won the Hertford Scholarship in 1866 and the Ireland in 1867, and was generally recognized as the 1 H. D. Rawnsley, in Good Words for January, 1893. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xiii ' best man ' of his year. He was not, however, merely a ' reading man.' He rowed in the Balliol ' Torpid ' and then in the ' Eight,' and entered fully into the life of the College. His quiet manner, and the thoughtfulness, delicacy, and refinement, which were as evident in his face as in his speech, did not prevent him from being eminently companionable. He was perfectly free from conceit and priggishness, keenly enjoyed the humour and 'chaff' of undergraduate society, and was not one of those unhappy beings who never acquire nicknames. At the same time, throughout these years his nature and mind, which were not precociously developed, and which (as he afterwards thought) grew very slowly, were continu- ously deepening. His undergraduate life was at times full of intellectual and emotional struggle ; but to outward appearance he advanced steadily and calmly, and he was too thoughtful and modest to leave a record of phases and crises among his contemporaries. Doubtless the intellectual influence which he felt most strongly was that of Green, who was just then becoming famous in Oxford and bringing a ferment into the philosophical studies of the abler men. This influence Nettleship quietly absorbed, and it did much to mould both his thoughts and his character, although he was hardly so ardently excited about philosophy as were some others among Green's pupils, and it was never natural to him to regard Green's teaching as a kind of gospel which it was his mission to spread. Even at this early time, too, the individuality of his mind was as marked, if not so obvious, as its receptiveness ; and the essays which he wrote as an undergraduate bear scarcely a trace of that imitativeness in which enthusiasm for a teacher is apt to show itself at first. He owed much, also, to the kindness xiv BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH and the wise advice of Jowett, who was his tutor ; and the influence of his brother John was probably at least as powerfully felt as that of any of his elders in Oxford. His most intimate College friend was H. S. Holland, now Canon of St. Paul's. In the summer of 1869 Nettleship went in for his final examination, and astonished his teachers and fellow-students by failing to obtain a first class. This mishap, like some other startling reverses of that time, was attributed in part to the effects of Green's teaching, or, in other words, to the incapacity of certain of the examiners. Nettleship himself thought that his failure had, at any rate, additional causes, ' even including rowing.' He regretted, however, neither the teaching nor the rowing ; and therefore, though, on account of the College and Green and his old school, he was 'vexed not to have managed better' 1 , the mishap did not further trouble him, and he declined to follow the advice of a friend that he should enter for a fellowship that happened to be vacant at another College, and try to prove that he was still invincible. In the autumn of 1869 he competed for a fellowship at Balliol, and was elected. The question of his future profession had naturally been already considered. He had thought of going to the Bar, and also of becoming a schoolmaster, but had put aside both these ideas in favour of another. His love of painting, and his in- timacy with his brother John, had attracted him to the plan of preparing himself to write upon art ; and his interest in philosophy only stimulated this desire. What he meditated was a study of all the main branches of 1 These words, like most of the quotations in the present sketch, are Nettleship's own. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xv art, in their connection with religion and the history of ideas. He had thought of pursuing his design in London, where he could combine it with work among the poor, and where he hoped to find an intellectual air less irritating and more vitalizing than that of Oxford. The idea was not abandoned when, on gaining his fellowship, Nettleship began to take work for the College ; and for some little time he remained in doubt whether he should stay more than a year or two at Balliol. What chiefly decided the question was the marked success of his first lectures (on the Republic of Plato), and the value set upon his presence in the College by Jowett and Green on the one side, and by the undergraduates on the other. But he was also influ- enced by characteristic feelings. He was acutely con- scious of the immaturity of his mind and character ; the thing he most needed, he felt, was training ; and for training the Oxford work would stand him in as good stead as any other. Besides, then and always, he put a good deal of faith in the precept which bids a man do what lies nearest to his hand. Nettleship remained a tutor of the College until his death. His energies were given therefore to work which, however valuable, cannot be eventful, and could hardly be briefly described. He had gained his reputation mainly in the field of classical scholarship, and he continued for a long time to take part in the teaching of Latin and Greek composition. Even after he gave this up, he was kept in touch with the junior under- graduates through the Balliol custom of weekly essays. But from the first his chief work lay in philosophy ; and after Green's appointment to a professorship he became the principal teacher of this subject, which is studied by xvi BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH men reading for the final classical examination. In addition to his duties in the way of lecturing and dis- cussing essays with pupils, he held the post of Junior Dean, and sometimes, during a part of the year, that of Senior Dean. He continued, also, to take a lively interest in the Boat Club, was always a welcome guest at bump-suppers and College concerts, and made full use of the gift which he possessed of establishing an unconstrained and equal relationship with men younger than himself. Thus an unusually large proportion of the undergraduates felt the effect of his presence, though it was in those who studied philosophy that his influence struck deepest. Something will be said of the nature of this influence in a later part of the present sketch ; but I believe it would be agreed by most of those able to judge that, from the time of Green's retirement from tutorial work, the strongest intellectual and spiritual force felt within the College issued from Nettleship. The subjects on which he most frequently lectured were Logic and Plato's Republic, and his courses on these subjects had a high reputation in the University, and were largely attended by out-College men. He occasionally lectured also on Aristotle's Ethics, and on the history of Moral Philosophy. The greater part of the lectures on Logic was historical, dealing chiefly with Aristotle and Bacon. It will be seen, therefore, that, except in the introductory portion of that course, Nettle- ship confined himself to the interpretation of authors, if not of particular works. His practice in this matter was due quite as much to his own choice as to the character of the University examinations ; and the prominence given in those examinations to Greek philo- sophy, as compared with modern, was not distasteful BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xvii to him. Though his position in regard to the main philosophical issues was well defined, he had very little desire to propagate his own opinions ; he wished chiefly to help others to think, and to bring their minds into contact with those of great men. And for the beginner, at any rate, he thought Plato and Aristotle better than modern writers of any school, because the Greeks put their questions more simply than the moderns, and be- cause they were less apt to lead the student prematurely into controversy on burning questions. In the practice based upon these views Nettleship's teaching differed somewhat markedly from Green's. It does not follow that he estimated the achievements of modern philo- sophers less highly than Green, but he regarded the teaching of philosophy more strictly from an educational point of view, while he no more subordinated it than Green did to the exigencies of examinations 1 . When Nettleship began to teach, he wrote his lectures out at length ; but before long he abandoned this practice, and spoke from very scanty notes and without verbal preparation. This plan necessarily involved much labour ; for, instead of repeating or re-casting in any one year the material used in some preceding year, he had always to construct his lectures anew. But he thought the labour well spent ; indeed, if he borrowed from an old pupil a report of his lectures, it was principally in order to guard against saying what he had said before. And the result justified him ; for his mind continually ad- vanced instead of being hampered by its past, while his 1 He had, on the other hand, no sympatlw whatever with the idea that a teacher who pays some regard to the fact that his pupils are going to be examined must needs 'cram' them for their examination. On the question whether his own lectures were, as a matter of fact, ' good for the schools,' there seems to be a difference of opinion among his pupils. VOL. I. b xviii BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH hearers felt that every subject he discussed was fresh and living to him. The distinguished success which he achieved on this method implied a considerable gift of speech ; and that he possessed such a gift was, I believe, very evident on the few occasions when he addressed an audience outside the lecture-room. In his lectures he was able without loss of freedom to speak slowly enough to suit those who wished to take full notes. He spoke with interest but equably, seldom emphatically, and never with any attempt at impressiveness. He rarely hesitated, and was little troubled by the tendency, com- monly observed in lecturers who use but few notes, to expand unduly or to be seduced into parenthetical remarks ; indeed it seems probable that for the majority of his hearers he often expanded his ideas too little. On the other hand, his habit of returning in one lecture upon an idea introduced in another was evidently intentional. The two heaviest of the literary undertakings on which Nettleship entered were interfered with by un- foreseen interruptions, and were only accomplished in part. The first of these was historical. In the spring of 1873 he gained the Arnold Prize for an essay on the History of the Normans in Italy and Sicily. He was led to write for the Prize partly by the characteristic idea that his success might compensate the College for his failure in his final examination. His essay was very highly estimated by Professor Stubbs and the other Examiners, and they urged him to pursue the subject and to publish his results. The enterprise cost him much labour. His memory was accurate, but not particularly strong; his historical reading had been comparatively slight ; he found himself constantly driven from his immediate subject, which was large and difficult enough, BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xix into wider fields ; and the instinct of the scholar and artist made it impossible for him to work hastily or at second-hand. His vacations from 1873 to 1 879 were mainly devoted to his projected history ; and to it he gave also most of a year's holiday which the College granted him in 1875. In this year he travelled a good deal in South Italy, visiting the scenes of the events he was to narrate. He stayed for some time working at Naples, and there he made one of the most valued friendships of his life, that with B. Zumbini, now Professor of Litera- ture at Naples, and an eminent writer l . By the year 1879 he had made considerable progress with his work. Large materials had been amassed, and a part of the book- was written, when his advance was arrested by the news of Freeman's intention to write a history of Sicily, and by a proposal that he should therefore confine himself to the history of the Normans in Italy. Though the arrangement involved the surrender of the most fasci- nating part of his subject, Nettleship readily adopted it ; but naturally it checked him in his course, and for a time, as will be seen presently, he turned to philoso- phical writing. This being finished, in March, 1882, he was hoping to be able to return before long to his history ; but in that month Green died, and the work of writing a memoir and preparing for publication the lectures of his friend occupied most of Nettleship's leisure for some years. He gradually came to recog- nize that it was beyond his power to combine both philosophical and historical writing with his College 1 In Macmillan's Magazine for November, 1878, there is a paper by Nettleship entitled, 'An Italian Study of Bunyan's Pilgrim's Progress. 7 The 'Study' referred to, together with one not less admirable on Paradise Lost, will be found re-published in Prof. Zumbini's Studi di Lctterature Straniere, 1893. b 2 xx BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH work, and he therefore abandoned the enterprise on which he had spent so much time and thought, hoping that his friend and colleague, A. L. Smith, would some day be able to use his materials and carry out the design of the book. That Nettleship should give so much of his leisure to a historical work was surprising to many of his friends, who thought that his natural bent was in another direction. He himself was accustomed, more than half seriously, to deny that he had any decided natural bent ; or rather, it seemed to him that ' there were several things that he could do pretty well, and nothing at all that he could do well.' Within certain limits he was curiously indifferent as to the mode in which he should put forth his energy ; and, if the College had been mis- taken enough to wish it, I believe he would readily have consented to teach history or ' classics ' instead of philosophy. In any case, he became thoroughly in- terested in his essay-subject. The adventurous and stormy characters whom he had to describe appealed powerfully to one element in his own nature ; he loved Italy, too ; and though he had no tendency to sub- stitute reflection for narrative, or to compel the facts into the frame of a theory, many passages in his manuscript prove that his researches in history gave plenty of scope to his philosophical imagination. This manuscript shows the conciseness and the verbal felicity which marked his writing, and in addition a power of producing rapid and vivid effects for which philosophical composition offers little room ; but an unrevised historical fragment is ill fitted for separate publication, and Nettle- ship's executors, after taking the opinion of experts, decided to leave his manuscript unprinted. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xxi In the summer of 1879, when his historical work was suspended, Nettleship had written, for a volume called Hellenica and edited by his friend and colleague Evelyn Abbott, his essay on the Theory of Education in the Republic of Plato. With the purpose of the volume, which was to illustrate the undying significance of Greek thought and literature, Nettleship was in entire sympathy. Although he recognized the importance of the more purely historical and critical questions involved in the study of Greek philosophy, he was never keenly interested in them, and cared deeply only for what is permanent in that philosophy. He could not regard Plato as a fasci- nating relic of antiquity, nor could he use Plato's theories as a mere cover for the discharge of his own. In his eyes Plato was a man of extraordinary genius, to whom the world around him presented problems — among others, an educational problem — which, in spite of many differ- ences, were fundamentally identical with those that confront an Englishman in the nineteenth century; and at the same time it seemed to him that the Greek writer drove straight to the heart of those problems with a force and directness less easily attained in the rich con- fusion of modern life. Hence his first object was, by a sympathetic and almost affectionate intercourse with the mind of his author, to re-create in imagination the occasion and the mental processes which had led to the formation of Plato's theories, to ascertain, as nearly as might be, what made him feel this and that, and why this and that seemed to him so important. And then he asked himself in what manner and with what modifica- tions Plato's ideas could be applied to the changed con- ditions of our own time. In attempting to answer this question, Nettleship did not abstain from criticism ; but xxii BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH in his criticism he still held to the method of sympathetic interpretation : he did not oppose to Plato's opinion an opinion of his own, but rather tried to show how a true development of Plato's own ideas would sometimes lead to conclusions other than those which appear in his dialogues. Doubtless such a mode of treatment was not the best way of conveying to the casual reader an im- pression of brilliant originality, but it gave to Nettleship's work a truthfulness and a sureness of touch which are nothing less than invaluable to serious students. The method adopted in the essay in Hellenica was followed by Nettleship in his memoir of Green and in all his teaching. The notes of his lectures on Aristotle. on later Greek philosophy, on Bacon and other modern writers, show that he applied it indifferently to all, without regard to the degree of his own sympathy with the ideas which he was endeavouring to expound. There is no more of negative criticism in his treatment of Hobbes or Hume than in his treatment of Plato or Spinoza. He approached the works of a philosopher just as he would have approached any man of acknowledged genius whom he might have met face to face. Such a man's ideas, he thought, may be one-sided or imperfectly connected, but they are likely to represent some real and im- portant aspect of truth ; and the first thing to do, if not the last, is to get, by sympathetic study, at those parts of human experience which he realized with peculiar force, however unsatisfying the theory which he wove round them. After the completion of the essay in Hellenica, Nettle- ship took part, with Green and some of Green's old pupils, in the translation of Lotze's Logik and Metaphysik. published under the editorship of B. Bosanquet in 1884. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xxiii His share of the work was the translation of the first book of the Logik. Meanwhile, he had undertaken the second of his main literary projects. He was invited to write, for the Society for Promoting Christian Knowledge, a small book on Platonism, as a companion to Prof. Wal- lace's volume on Epicureanism and Prof. Capes's on Stoicism. A large book on Plato would have suited his way of working much better ; but he was attracted by the very modesty of the plan, and not less by its diffi- culty ; he felt that it would be more of an achievement to express himself in 250 small pages than in two or three large volumes. Although he was to write for the general public, he did not intend to avoid Plato's metaphysics ; his aim was ' to give some idea of what was in the man's mind in its original, unmitigated, form, without apology or attempt to soften it down for modern culture.' He- began his task by analyzing for his own use all the dialogues of Plato ; and by the summer of 1883 he had finished at least one of the five sections of which the book was to consist. This was a chapter on Plato's Ethics, somewhat similar in character to the Hellenica essay, though naturally less elaborate in its treatment of the various dialogues. But even before the chapter was complete, it had become evident that the proposed limits of the book were likely to be greatly exceeded ; and the publishers, who had allowed the title to be changed from L Platonism ' to ' Plato,' were unable to sanction such an extension of the plan as Nettleship now thought de- sirable. He therefore made some changes in the whole design, and began to reduce without mercy the matter already composed. But during the next five years his leisure was mainly given to a more pressing duty (to be referred to presently), and. although he continued during xxiv BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH these years to work at intervals on his ' Plato,' he made but little progress in the composition of the book. In the Long Vacation of 1889 he was able again to give it his whole attention, and he was occupied with it till the end of his life. But, as he penetrated more deeply into Plato's mind, and as his own mind grew, he was compelled once more to modify his plan ; and. although some of the notes he made for the ' Plato' after 1889 probably show his philosophical power as adequately as anything in his lectures or essays, they were merely notes for his own use, and at the time of his death but few passages of finished composition had been added to the chapter which is printed in the present volumes. The duty just alluded to arose out of the death of Green, in March, 1882. After the publication of the Prole- gomena to Ethics, which Green had left nearly finished, it was decided that a part of his remaining MSS. should be edited and published, together with a memoir. No one else could be so competent in all ways to undertake this task as Nettleship, who (so far as it was possible for any man to do so) had filled Green's place at Balliol, and for whom Green had felt an admiration as great as his affection. In his editorial duties Nettleship received help from various friends — very great help from Mrs. Green ; but there remained much laborious work, which he exe- cuted with characteristic thoroughness. The Memoir of Green was published in the third and last volume of the edition of his works in 1 888. Nettleship was better content with it than with anything else that he wrote ; he even admitted that some of it was ' rather well done.' The memoir is markedly impersonal both in tone and in substance, and it was intended to be so. Nettleship felt that the thoughts and actions in which Green had BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH XXV openly and deliberately expressed himself were the truest exhibition of his personality; and by dwelling on them he was able to give a very distinct impression of that personality without lingering on the details, or breaking- through the reserves, of private life. The remark some- times heard, that he did not succeed in making Green's philosophical ideas more easily intelligible to the general reader than their author had left them, is probably true as a statement, but it is surely unreasonable as a com- plaint. To ( popularize ' these ideas would really have been to substitute for them something which would have been nearer to the reader's everyday thoughts and, for that very reason, less valuable. So, at any rate, it seemed to Nettleship. He made no attempt, therefore, to popularize Green's teaching ; but he succeeded in simplifying it by bringing into relief the unity which pervades it, and which connects with Green's central ideas the outlying questions on which he so persistently dwelt. The Memoir of Green was Nettleship's last publication. In Oxford, where his reputation was so great, there is probably an impression that in the way of literary work- he accomplished less than might have been expected ; and he himself felt that he had ' done very little.' Whatever he had done, he would have felt this ; and if he wrote comparatively little, there were many causes besides those for which he might take himself to account. Among these, it is quite a mistake to reckon a failing which is supposed to be characteristic of gifted Oxford dons. Nettleship was by no means irresolute or over- fastidious in composition. Certainly he was not fond of second-rate work ; but his dislike of producing it was free from morbidity, and he was untroubled by the dread of xxvi BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH committing himself 1 . On the other hand, he had no strong impulse to literary composition, and took little pleasure in it ; his temperament, also, was not that of the mere student or author ; and, except when there was an obvious need for prompt action, he was perhaps somewhat deficient in the power of 'putting a thing through.' He was also impeded by a marked peculiarity of his mind. He could produce good work rapidly under pressure (for instance, his article on Green's philosophy, in the Contemporary Review for May, 1882, was written very quickly); but when he was making his greatest intellectual advances he appeared to himself to work very slowly, and at such times he certainly composed very slowly. His con- versation on philosophical subjects was then extremely interesting, but one could see that his whole mind was in ferment, and that, as he said, he was not ' fit to write.' Naturally, these times of restless progress were apt to come towards the end of the Long Vacation, when he had recovered from the effects of his College work ; and they were cut short by the return of Term. In fact, the main reason why he did not write more was that he regarded his College work as his first business, and gave himself to it so ungrudgingly that, although he was on the whole a healthy man, little troubled by pain or ailments, the bulk of his energy was exhausted in it. And, considering what he made of this work, it is not clear that we have any right to wish that he had diverted more of his force to composition. His life was ended in its prime by an accident ; but I see no reason to 1 I have often heard it said that Langham in Robeti Elsmere is a por- trait of Nettlcship. To any one who knew Nettleship the idea is merely ludicrous ; but it seems a pity that one or two tricks of speech and manner, which could hardly fail to remind Oxford men of him, should have been associated with a character so contemptibly unlike his. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xxvil doubt that, had this not been the case, his five and twenty years of teaching would have been followed by a period of philosophical authorship as concentrated and as successful. Of the events of Nettleship's life little remains to be told, and the most important can only be touched on. After the year 1880 his greatest happiness and unhappi- ness arose from a passionate attachment which was not returned, and which lasted till his death. He met the suffering it brought to him bravely and unselfishly ; and, although he was saddened, he did not allow his sympathies to be narrowed or deadened. Several in- ducements, of which the strongest was his desire to make a home for his mother, led him, in 1882, to give up his College rooms and take a house. He lived for the last ten years of his life at 7 Banbury Road, next door to his friend Mrs. Green. He saw per- haps less than he had previously done of his colleagues and of acquaintances in Oxford, and he spoke with regret of this loss ; but I do not gather x that the change diminished his influence within the College, and he found a fuller satisfaction of the need for affection in his daily life with his mother, his devotion to whom was none the less beautiful because it brought with it its own reward. The change put within his reach, too, pleasures granted only in part to the inmate of a College. Relatives, old pupils, and other friends 2 visited the house in Banbury Road. He worked in the garden regularly, and with a characteristic mixture of enjoyment and conscientious- 1 I should mention that I left Oxford at the end of 1881. 2 Among the friendships formed or strengthened during the last ten years of his life, I cannot help naming that with Mrs. G. W. Prothero, to whom every one who loved him must be grateful. xxviii BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH ncss. A Dandie Dinmont, ' Jenny,' became his constant companion. He saw more of children, of whom he was fond, and with whom he had a very taking way. And, lastly, I must mention his love of music. He had eagerly welcomed the Sunday evening recitals in Balliol Hall, which his friend, C. B. Heberden, had organized about the year 1877; and he took an equal interest in the concerts which succeeded these recitals, when Mr. Farmer came from Harrow to Balliol in 1885. He occasionally sang at the College concerts ; and at home, where his mother, while her health allowed her, used to accompany him, the singing of Beethoven, Schubert, Schumann and Brahms became a constant practice with him, which he more than once referred to as almost his 'greatest comfort.' I do not know that he cared less for painting in his later years than in his earlier, but he certainly cared more for music. For the sake of hearing great compositions he would go out of his way as he never would to see a play or any kind of spectacle, and the hearing of some music came to be for him, as he said, • almost the only reasonable form of worship ' \ When, as a young man, Nettleship thought of living in London, and of writing on art, he thought also of working among the poor ; and no doubt he would have carried out this intention after he had given up his College work. But during his Oxford life he abstained entirely and deliberately from attempting anything of the kind ; nor did he ever take any part in the civic or 1 The words were used after he had been hearing Cherubini's Requiem. I may add here that the sum subscribed by Nettleship's colleagues, pupils, and other friends for the purpose of a memorial, was used to found a scholarship by which a student of music is enabled to spend some years at Balliol College before completing his musical training or pursuing his profession. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xxix political affairs of the city. Work among the poor would probably have been congenial to him ; he had a natural feeling of equality, and was perhaps more at his ease with people below him in station than with the average person of culture, who frequently irritated him. He was also full of kindness without being at all senti- mental. On the other hand, he had no liking for ' affairs,' and not much turn for them ; and he had less than the usual interest in politics. This does not mean that he was indifferent to political or social movements, as artists and men of letters not seldom are. He sym- pathized warmly with democratic ideas, had some strong admirations (e. g. for Mazzini and for Bright), made up his mind on important questions of the day, and used his vote 1 . But the interest he took in current politics was a matter more of duty than of inclination. He had little of the spirit which makes many Englishmen open the day's paper anxiously or eagerly, and none of the spirit which makes many others rejoice in party conflicts as they do in football-matches. Nettleship never (except perhaps in boyhood) had a passion for books, and in the last fifteen years of his life he read neither very much nor very widely. As a boy and as a young man he was fond of history ; later, his favourite reading was biography and poetry, with an occasional novel. He was rather a slow reader and had a difficulty in skimming ; partly perhaps for this reason, he was less interested than most intellectual men by second-rate books, and he was intolerant of second-rate 1 So far as I know, his vote, in University and in national politics, was invariably given on what may be vaguely called the liberal side. He hesitated a good deal in 1886 about Home Rule, but ultimately decided for it. He was always inclined to what seemed to him the courageous policy. x\x BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH work in philosophy. Indeed, in the last few years of his life he read little philosophy except Plato and Spinoza, and he more than once spoke of the best poetry as the only literature that he found very much worth reading except as pastime. By this he doubtless meant that the best poetry seemed to him to contain most of the kind of new experience that he chiefly valued. His appreciation of poetry was catholic, but his favourites were few. He was fond of George Herbert, of Browning, and of Whitman, though he would not have ranked any one of them very high. Dante and Shakespeare were probably the poets most congenial to him ; but, as he had never studied Dante much, he could not turn to him with ease in odd hours, while he read Shakespeare more and more. The books he took with him on his last Swiss tour were a volume of Spinoza containing the Ethics, and the shilling selection from Browning. From early days Nettleship had been fond of travelling; and in the last ten years of his life he went once to Italy (where in earlier days he had often been), twice to Norway, several times to Switzerland or the Tyrol, and twice to Greece, on one occasion making an extremely trying and somewhat hazardous journey on foot through Albania and Thessaly. Though he seldom spoke of them, famous places and works of art were much to him, and some extracts printed in this volume record his impressions of Athens and Florence ; but he liked best of all to travel under conditions which made it natural for him to live roughly, to exert himself strenuously, and to depend upon himself; and partly from necessity, but probably quite as much from choice, he often travelled alone. He could not live without doing something ' violent,' as he called it ; he felt also BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xxxi a recurring need to get away from society, and to dis- pense with the ' swimming-belts ' of regular habits and duties, public opinion, the aid of books and friends. Contact with nature seemed almost always to revive him. He had something of an artist's enjoyment of form and colour, and when he was watching a sunlit landscape his face wore a peculiarly happy expression ; but perhaps his strongest impulse was to feel in nature ' an elemental force in whose presence man finds peace by escaping from himself' 1 ; and this impulse led him most often to moorland or mountain districts. For mountains especially he had always felt (and these were strong words for him to use) ' an intense love tinged perhaps by fear ' ; and the very fact that he was doubt- fully conscious of a mingling of fear with his love attracted him the more to mountain-climbing. In all things that which called for courage, as well as effort and skill, appealed to him most. One may even say that in Nettleship's experience all the virtues tended to appear in the shape of courage, just as to another they may all appear as forms of unselfishness ; and it was natural to him to think of most moral weaknesses as kinds of fear. To prevent misunderstanding, I may add that I never saw any sign that he was more inclined to timidity than most men. At various times he had done some climbing in the high Alps. In 1890 he went to Switzerland with two friends who were first-rate mountaineers, and he much enjoyed the necessity of attempting the utmost of which he was capable. The next year he went alone, first to Grindelwald, and afterwards to Saas Fee ; did all the work and attacked all the difficulties that lay within his 1 Memoir of Green, p. xviii. xxxii BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH powers ; and came home looking alarmingly thin, but feeling full of vigour and also of ideas. In August, 1892, he again went to Switzerland, expecting a friend to join him in a short time. Settling at the Montanvert Hotel, he engaged two Chamouny guides and made various ascents, in which, for the sake of practice, he took the place on the rope usually assigned to the first guide, and to a large extent declined the aid commonly offered in abundance to the amateur. On those who met him at the hotel he left, as he always did, the impression of helpfulness and gentleness, and of being ' uncommon.' His guides became much attached to him; he was 'si gentil, si aimable'; he treated them ' as brothers.' On an expedition, they noticed, he was generally silent in the valley, but ' as soon as they got up into the high air he seemed to be another person, so joyous and full of song and talk.' The sum he had laid aside for climbing being almost exhausted, he determined, by way of a last ascent, to go up Mont Blanc by the Aiguille and Dome du Gouter. In this expedition he lost his life. On Wednesday, August 24, his guides and he went up the Aiguille, and at midday left the top and made for the Dome. On their way they were met by a storm of wind and snow, violent and intensely cold. Their tracks were quickly effaced ; they lost their bearings ; and, as the light began to fail, they cut out with their axes a hole in the ice of the mountain-side. Here they spent the night. Nettleship acted in his last hours as his friends would have expected of him. During the night he was cheerful ; the guides were too depressed to sing, and he sang to them. In the morning he ate, and pressed them in vain to eat. After a while, as the storm showed no sign of abating, BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xxxiii he proposed to start ; some such words as, ' II faut faire quelque chose ; mourir ici ce serait mourir en laches,' were almost his last. The guides objected ; but he answered only, ' Allons,' and stepped into the storm, and they followed him. They had thought him the strongest of the three ; but it was not long before he fell and, when they ran to him, grasped them each by a hand, and died. The storm lessened an hour or two later, and the guides escaped, though one of them was in poor health for some months afterwards. Nettleship's body was buried at Chamouny. The inscription on the tomb- stone ends with the quotation, chosen by his mother, ' He maketh the storm a calm ' l . Those who saw something of Nettleship without becoming intimate with him were often at once im- pressed and puzzled ; and it was possible to know him pretty well without losing much of this feeling of bewilderment. That he was a remarkable man was quite evident ; but he belonged to no obvious type, and, while his character was transparently sincere, it united qualities so unlike that a first conception of it was liable to be greatly modified on further acquaintance. He was plainly very serious and thoughtful; quiet, self- possessed, and somewhat retiring ; courteous, frank, and simple in manner ; grave, occasionally melancholy, in expression. But to some he seemed repressed, in- 1 Fuller details regarding the expedition may be found in the English newspapers of the days following August 25, 1892, and in Mr. Rawnsley's paper in Good Words. There is no reason for dwelling on them in this slight sketch, when one has to pass without mention many incidents of Nettleship's life which would illustrate his character at least as well. The} 7 have some importance of another kind for those who are interested in mountaineering. VOL. I. C xxxiv BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH different, or even austere, while others found that he talked with interest and ease, and, if he did not often say humorous things himself, showed a quick and hearty enjoyment of humour in others. One person would say that he was a philosopher; that he regarded things — even the most ordinary things— in a strikingly original way, as though he saw them from some hidden central position of his own ; and that, taking life so seriously as he obviously did, he was probably somewhat stern and stoical in moral judgment. Another might notice that he did not use philosophical formulas, would even put them aside with a certain impatience, and would discuss anything that concerned human nature with the interest of a novelist, with almost startling frankness, and with a ready sympathy for wellnigh any kind of passion or difficulty. He would have winced to know it, but it is the fact, that he gave the impression of living on a height, and of carrying something of an ideal atmosphere into the most every-day occupations ; yet, if there was little exuberance, there was no reservation in his enjoyment of sunshine and laziness ; of eating and drinking ; of walking, rowing, bathing, games ; of singing, talking, and mirth. Few can have met him without being struck by his modesty, and even by a certain diffidence and indecision in expressing an opinion ; yet he was often decided, quick, and plain-spoken, and he could be irritable, combative, and brusque. In the years of his early manhood there was a look of quiet placidity in his face, in his latest years an expression often of hard- earned but settled peace ; but, at almost any period of his life, the marks of the strain of work, and of incessant inward struggle, would sometimes be evident even to a stranger. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH XXXV The various impressions just described answered to various aspects of Nettleship's character, and I shall do best if, at the cost of repetition, I dwell on some of these more at length. The gentler and happier side of his nature was more quickly apparent in his earlier years than afterwards ; and probably most of those who knew him only as an undergraduate or a young tutor would be surprised to hear that he ever struck any one as austere or even melancholy. Nor did contemporaries who, after a long interval, saw him again in later life, find him changed in this way, though he seemed to them to look ' lean and intense,' and less peaceful than in youth. The change that passed over him was possibly not greater than that which middle-age often brings, and a very simple circumstance made it appear greater than it really was. In the later time his dark eyes, deeply set under a projecting brow and thick eye-brows, were the most noticeable feature of his face, while his mouth was almost hidden. In earlier days, when he wore no beard and moustache, the delicate and mobile lines of his mouth, betraying every transitory touch of sympathy, pleasure or amusement, gave to his face a look of sensitiveness and a peculiar sweetness. This look was in entire harmony with the gentleness and modesty of his address, while the upper part of his face, which was rather immobile, left the impression of intellectual power and of a patient but somewhat stern sadness. His modesty was one of the most essential and beauti- ful traits of his character. It was native, and was only increased by the consciousness of intellectual power. To compare his own gifts with those of others was unnatural to him ; he was not competitive, and had hardly any temptation to be vain. He went out into the world, as c 2 xxxvi BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH Thring had bidden him, ' not as a lord and judge, but as an humble child seeking wisdom.' ' Wisdom,' philosophy, deepened in him the sense of mystery, the need of worship, and the feeling of his own littleness; and habitual intercourse with the greatest minds kept him constantly aware of the difference between their powers and his. I have heard him say many ' irreverent ' things, but I never once saw him in an irreverent state of mind. This humility towards all that was above him was the source of much of his influence over younger men, who felt it the more because it was linked to abilities and achievements far above their own. It put conceit or assumption to shame, encouraged the timid, and led Nettleship's pupils to regard him as a fellow-worker. To this modesty, which was a spring of strength alone, were joined a diffidence of nature and a disinclination to self-assertion, in which strength was mingled with weak- ness. These traits were often obvious at a glance. Nettleship's hesitation in beginning to give an opinion, his preliminary disavowals of knowledge, and his qualifi- cations of statement, amused his pupils and formed the grain of truth round which a body of College legends gathered. To a large extent they were mere unconscious tricks of manner. So far as they were more, they arose from his constant sense that his knowledge was frag- mentary and his insight limited ; from the perception that different minds, however unequal in power of vision, still catch glimpses of different sides of truth ; and from the fact that, until he began to think, he was often unaware that he had an answer to the question put to him, while it never occurred to him to suppose that it was his duty as an educator to pretend to have an opinion when he had none. His diffidence led some people to imagine BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xxxvii that he was not only in the best sense humble, but had a lower estimate of himself than of them ; and in this they were generally mistaken. If 'humility' means this kind of self- depreciation, he neither was nor, on the whole, appeared to be humble ; indeed, his readiness to treat seriously the opinion of a beginner was frequently touched with irony, and there was sometimes traceable in his manner to intellectual men of his own age his feeling that they were as far as himself from being great or wise. Still it is true, for good and for ill, that it cost him an effort to assert himself. He had little of the temperament, the gifts, and the defects, of a leader and ruler. Though he influenced men greatly, he scarcely set himself to influence them, and was not inclined to direct their lives for them. He could take and hold his own way, but he was not eager — perhaps was too little eager — to induce others to join it. He hated conflict, and was ready to sacrifice a good deal to avoid the waste caused by friction. Yet I do not know that he ever sacrificed what he thought essential ; and though the effort which it cost him to oppose or pain those whom he admired or cared for was sometimes visible in a certain roughness of manner, neither in his private nor in his more public life did he flinch from ungracious tasks. It would be misleading to describe Nettleship simply as reserved or unsociable, and he was not exactly shy. But it is true that in society he was often silent and appeared uncomfortable. The surface of social inter- course was not his element : after a short course of 'saying pleasant things to pleasant people' a feeling of unreality and futility came over him and made him dumb. This does not mean that he could only interest xxxvm BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH himself in intellectual subjects. Indeed much of what is called cultivated conversation was as unsatisfying to him as the merest gossip, and he was quite at home with people who had never heard of philosophy. If I may so put it, an intelligent or affectionate savage would have suited him, and a philosopher or poet would doubt- less have suited him better still ; but in proportion as people were further removed from one of these extremes without approaching the other, their attraction for him diminished. Thus he couH be happy with any child of nature, of whatever nationality, rank, or degree of culture ; and he would talk readily with any one keenly interested in his own experience or occupation, or in human beings, or ideas, or works of art. But in the middle region of political or literary discussion he moved with an air of forced interest or suppressed discomfort ; and, when he felt a barrier between his own mind and that of another, the feeling that conversation was useless tempted him to withdraw into himself or (more rarely) to become combative. Such dumbness or combative- ness arose almost wholly, I think, from irritation at his own inability to enjoy the good of the moment ; and he made many efforts, if not many successful ones, to master what he himself regarded as a weakness. When his society suited him, his conversation was remarkable in more ways than one. It was not brilliant, and he never attempted to make it so ; but it was original. His mind was eminently unconventional, and, unlike some unconventional minds, it had no ruts of its own. He approached a subject as if he were ignorant of the received views, and wished, by observing it steadily, to learn something of its nature ; and his ideas about it, while as far as possible from being eccentric or BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH XXXIX wrong-headed, were often surprisingly fresh and pregnant. They presupposed, however, in his fellow-talker a willing- ness to press into the matter, and also to supply con- siderations which Nettleship himself thought too obvious to be mentioned. His omission of these was sometimes a cause of bewilderment, as he appeared to be maintaining, as the whole truth, what was merely a partial view. Another marked quality of his conversation was its intellectual sympathy. He seemed not to compare an opinion of his own with the opinion of another, but o adopt the idea offered to him and to win from it new suggestions which often transformed it. His constant study of Plato's dialogues no doubt strengthened this tendency, but it was a part of his nature. He did not care for argument. To ' talk philosophy ' meant to him the attempt of two minds to arrive at new results in company, these results being something which neither of the explorers had foreseen, and in which neither could have distinguished his separate contribution. In this kind of joint search after truth I have known no one at all equal to him. It is evident from the reports of his pupils that these characteristics of his conversation reappeared in his tutorial teaching. In discussing philosophical questions he appeared to ignore the recognized views and the recognized terminology with which his pupil had probably some acquaintance ; he attacked the matter as if it were something perfectly new, into which he was making his way for the first time. At the end of two years a pupil might have heard not a sentence from him about some of the most famous controversies, yet he found himself familiar with the points really at issue. When he read his essay to Nettleship. he found his tutor xl BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH assuming that he had something of value to say, and that he meant what he said ; and this was equally taken for granted, whether he had advanced some hopelessly confused view, or some wilful paradox, or an idea which he imagined likely to be welcome, or one which he expected to hear condemned. In any case he was led into a joint attempt to examine the position stated, and to get from it nearer to the truth which he was believed to be anxious to find. He recognized, at once or after- wards, the intellectual sympathy which had enabled his tutor to conduct this process ; and indeed it may be said that Nettleship's intercourse with his pupils differed from his conversation with older men only in being deliberately adapted to an educational purpose, and, of course, in being less unrestrained. It is no exaggeration to call him a master in the art of educating able men in philo- sophical thinking. If his art ever failed him, it must have been in dealing with the less able among his pupils. He probably left some of them doubtful of his own position, possibly doubtful whether he did not regard all philosophies as equally true. The same doubts were occasionally felt by strangers of his own age, who surmised from his conversation that, with regard to theories, he was an eclectic, and that in moral judgment he was over tolerant. Neither of these im- pressions was correct ; he had not even the tendency to think all ideas equally true, or all modes of life and action equally good or bad. But no doubt his instinct was to look for the truth or goodness of everything, and to thrust nothing aside as insignificant or worthless. His mind was naturally synthetic. He had a strong feeling of the unity or continuity of human experience, and was more inclined to dwell on the presence of one BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xli principle in many manifestations than upon the defects which make any one manifestation of it imperfect. In regard to morality he did not, as a rule, use the language most familiar to Englishmen. It was natural to him to think of better and worse rather than of right and wrong ; of the attainment of an end, the fulfilment of one's possibilities, the increase of one's being, rather than of obedience to law, or conscience, or duty. Antitheses like those of duty and pleasure, or self and others, were not to his mind ; like all antitheses, they were apt to provoke him, so that he would startle a neighbour with whom he might be in substantial agreement, by declaring that every one does in the end what pleases him best, or that there is no action on earth which may not be good or may not be bad, or that for a man's self there is no difference between things called great and things called little, though there is plenty of difference between what is hard and what is easy. Thus he sometimes seemed, especially to a listener unused to philosophy, to be denying the most obvious distinctions, or perhaps to be maintaining the heresy that good and evil differ only in degree. In reality no one could have held more strongly that the difference between them is absolute ; what was alien to Nettleship's mind was the pretension to be able to separate the world into two parts called evil and good, or the attempt to restrict the manifestation of goodness to its generally recognized forms. Doubtless, he would have said, it is chiefly in these forms that human nature is able to realize its possibilities ; but that is no reason for attempting to bind it down to them. Nettleship's sympathy with almost any passion, or with any action which, however unusual, seemed to xlii BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH spring from a real conviction, was connected with this mode of thought, and also with his own inward experi- ence. There was nothing really strange in its being combined with an exceptional seriousness, patience, gentleness, and dutifulness. These traits were obvious ; the passionate aspiration and effort of his life were less evident, but not less characteristic. He struggled vehemently to attain singleness of purpose, his ' one pearl of great price,' and to make a harmony of the different elements of his nature. But these elements were very diverse. Among them were strong animal impulses, and something wild and untameable, which found no satisfaction in the limits of his habitual life, and made him feel, when he escaped from that life, that some day he should leave it for ever, although it, too, answered to a no less urgent need within him. Nor could he, like some men, flatly deny the justice of these demands of his nature, or feel that they were wholly alien to the spirit which drove him to seek for truth, and to love and serve his fellows. Hence, while he was as far as possible from undervaluing the great typical virtues which form the basis or substance of morality, he sym- pathized keenly with any strenuous effort to reach the good of life, however unlike the direction taken by it might be to the recognized order ; and when an action seemed to him to embody this effort, he could not acquiesce in hearing it condemned merely because it was not easy to apply to it one of the common terms of approval, or because it was easy to affix to it one of the common terms of blame. Let a man contend to the uttermost For his life's set prize, be it what it will ! — the spirit of these lines appealed to him. The readiness BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xliii to find good wherever there is a full pulse of the soul drew him to Browning and to Whitman, and was one of the reasons why Plato and Spinoza attracted him most among philosophers. ' He seems to me,' he wrote of Plato, ' to have more of the eternal human nature in him than any one else except Shakespeare.' It was a natural result of Nettleship's way of think- ing that the unity in his ideas and character was more easy to feel than to understand. It was felt by those who knew him that, in everything which he said or did, he was emphatically himself, that he brought into the little things of life the same spirit that appeared in his best thoughts, and that he did what was common in an uncommon way. But few of his friends would have been able to say in what centre his thoughts met, or what system they formed, or to predict with entire confidence what his view of a given question would be, or how he would feel about any particular occurrence. Thus the unity and connection so obvious in the lives and ideas of men like Mazzini or Green (I name them because of Nettleship's admiration for them) were in his case far less visible. He himself would have been the first to laugh at the comparison, and to say that the reason of the difference lay in the fact that these were much greater men than he, and knew their own minds much better. But the reason did not lie solely here. To say nothing of his never having set himself to express his ideas in writing, it lay also in the complexity of his nature, his impatience of limitations, and the continual effort, which was so characteristic of him, to bring a larger and larger experience into the focus of his inner life. Absurdly exalted as the claim would have sounded to him, there xliv BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH was in him the impulse to appropriate, what Browning, on his higher plane of genius and energy, had the impulse to express, the various experiences of the philosopher, the scholar, the artist, the man of action, the philan- thropist, the lover, and even the saint. At the same time what he longed for, and perhaps felt most hopeless of attaining, was something of the simplicity of the child or the great man. The lines most frequently on his lips were Goethe's couplet : — Nur wo du bist sei alles, immer kindlich ; So bist du alles, bist uniiberwindlich. Feeling intensely the unity of experience and the presence of the whole in every part, he was compara- tively little interested in dwelling on the connection of the parts, or in demonstrating that the aims of artist, philanthropist, and philosopher are ultimately one, while he felt that the way for a man to realize his whole self was to throw his whole heart into each thing that touched him, and to make of each thing all that it was capable of being l . Some other traits in Nettleship's character seemed to be connected with the philosophic strain in his nature ; for instance, his disposition to bring himself into positive relation with views of the most different kinds, and (if Plato was right 2 ) the habitual gentleness with which his 1 The following words, from Nettleship's discussion of the Philebus, are very characteristic of his own feeling : ' If the end of our being is to be, to be the utmost we are capable of being, then the higher the constant level at which we can live, the less the energy which we have to spend in escaping the pain of depression, the more each moment contains in itself, and the less it borrows from felt contrast with a lower past or a higher future, the more nearly do we approach the full measure, the full beauty, the full truth, in which, according to the Philebus, the principle of good is manifested.' 2 Nettleship was fond of the passage referred to, Rep. ii. 376. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xlv occasional irritability or brusqueness formed so odd a contrast. He was also in a remarkable degree, and in a peculiar way, ' impersonal ' in feeling and in expres- sion. I do not mean merely that he was very dis- interested and free from touchiness, personal resentment, and the like ; but it was more than usually easy to him to regard things from a general point of view, and, in speaking of them, he was accustomed to ignore their effect upon his own feelings. Even in matters where he or his friends were most deeply concerned, he maintained the attitude of a dispassionate and, one might almost say, of an indifferent spectator with an ease and a naivete which was sometimes comical as well as beautiful. He would speak of the harm done by the teaching of philosophy, of the possible decline of his College or his country, of the troubles or the death of a friend, of his own sufferings or his own shortcomings, always with seriousness, no doubt, but still as though he were a ' spectator of all time and all existence,' anxious only for the truth ; and it is easy to fancy him discussing his own death as though it did not affect him personally at all. Statements like these may give to those who did not know him a strange impression, perhaps even the ludicrously false impression that he was affected or priggish ; but the peculiarity of manner to which I refer was too characteristic to pass unmentioned. Perhaps, also, it may have led strangers to suppose that he was apathetic and likely to be too quiescent. But in reality the personal feelings which he ignored in speaking of things simply as they are, were warm enough, and he would have been the first to fight against the avoidable evils which he so quietly discussed. Balliol. for example, had not in his eyes the glamour it possesses for many of its sons, but he was as ready to xlvi BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH work for his College and as devoted to it as any of them could be. As a friend he was not only true but affec- tionate, and untiring in helpfulness. Indeed, to be helpful to those he loved, and, I may almost say, to any human being who needed him, was one of the keenest of his pleasures. Perhaps it was a pleasure all the keener because his feelings were not easily expressed in look or tone or spoken words. And if this is true of his affection for others, it is quite as true of the pleasure he took in their affection for him. He showed such pleasure less than most men, but he certainly felt it more. To be dis- liked by any one, however poor an opinion he had of the person, was painful to him. He had a longing for sympathy from those whom he liked which most of them can never have guessed ; and perhaps even those nearest to him never fully realized, while he lived, that his delight in being loved was as simple and strong as a dog's or a child's. It remains that something should be said of Nettle- ship as a student and teacher of philosophy. Readers will prefer to gather for themselves from these volumes a notion of his philosophical position, or at least of the ideas on which he dwelt mos". Of the former, I need only say that he was in substantial agreement with the idealism represented first and most powerfully in Oxford by Green. He was very sensible of the difficulties of this point of view, and did not expect to see them alto- gether removed ; but he was convinced that they were not to be avoided by falling back upon easier theories, and that their solution, so far as it lies within the power of the mind at all, must be sought not in giving up idealism but in pushing it farther. He thought also that critics were apt to forget that the question is not BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xlvii merely whether a certain theory is wholly satisfactory, but whether it does not interpret and harmonize our experience better than any other. With all his admira- tion for Green, however, his own mind was framed on another model. In his handling of questions he scarcely ever reminds one of his old tutor ; and he took excep- tion to some of Green's language, though rather because he thought it likely to mislead than from disagree- ment with what he believed it to mean. This applies especially to some of the statements in Green's works regarding nature and the difference between nature and mind. Students of philosophy will notice in these volumes 1 how frequently and emphatically Nettleship recurs to the continuity of all existence ; and an ex- tract from a letter written towards the end of his life may indicate the constant direction of his thoughts. ' I think,' he writes, ' I shall end my days as something like a Spinozist 2 . At least I get more and more to feel that there is absolutely no difference in principle between what is called physical and what is called spiritual, and that if one can understand a triangle one can understand oneself.' Many similar expressions occur in his later letters. They do not mean that he was inclined to reduce something higher to something lower, but rather that he believed himself to find more 1 Particularly in some of the Miscellaneous Papers and Extracts from Letters. However slight and hasty these may be, they seem to me to represent him more adequately than his lectures or even his essays, in which the subject, or again the predominance of an educational purpose, often prevented him from emphasizing his own view or dealing fully with the most difficult questions. 2 Some readers will perhaps object that in that case he would not have ended his days as an ' idealist.' If so, it will be safe to say that he was and remained in substantial agreement with the type of philo- sophy represented, with differences, by Plato, Spinoza, and Hegel. xlviii BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH and more of the higher in the lower. These terms, however, he would probably not have used ; he was ac- customed, rather, to distinguish between the more partial and the more complete, the more abstract and the more concrete, appearances of the whole. It may be added that, in weighing Nettleship's words, the reader will do well to remember what has been said of his tendency, in dwelling on a particular aspect of truth, to ignore as self-evident more obvious complementary aspects. Nettleship's insistance on the continuity of things may be seen in another characteristic of his philosophizing. He was deeply impressed by the truth that the answer to complicated questions lies in the understanding of simple ones, or that the only way to approach the interpretation of the highest facts of experience is to arrive at clearness about the most elementary. He writes, for instance: 'If I had to begin over again, I should like to try to master the elements of a few big things. Till I have done this, the rest is all confusion, and talking about it is beating the air. And whenever I at all understand the elements, I seldom find much difficulty in finding " applications " everywhere. Anything presents every kind of problem ' (January 1890). Again: 'These old chaps [the Greek philosophers] certainly do bring one face to face with elemental things, and that is what I want. I sometimes feel that if I could only be quite clear about such things as one and many, same and other, rest and motion, all life would be simple' (July 1891). And with this characteristic, again, was connected another. ' One always comes back to the feeling that the truth in these ultimate problems is not got by thinking (in the ordinary sense), but by living'' — so he wrote in 1880, and the words have nothing unusual about them, except perhaps the BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH xlix implication that there may be a ' thinking ' which is equivalent to ' living ' ; but in his last years Nettleship felt equally strongly the necessity of this ' living,' or of personal experience, for the real understanding not merely of ultimate problems but of the simplest facts. He writes in 1889: 'One cannot understand anything unless one can in some remote way experience it.' Again, in the same year : ' I am at work at Plato again. The endless difficulty of these big men is that one can only understand them at the rare times when one has fragmentary glimpses of their actual experience. At other times they are mere words.' And a year later : ' I have got on slowly, but, I think, fairly satisfactorily with Plato : but I am continually being pulled up by inability really to feel certain extremely elementary facts which, I am sure, meant any amount to him.' The mis- giving which most troubled Nettleship regarding his capacity to write a valuable philosophical book was, I think, the doubt whether he had sufficient ' experience.' The feeling expressed in these quotations explains in part some traits already touched on, and some others worth mention. It supplies one reason why Nettleship's interpretation of great philosophers was so exceptionally close and sympathetic, and why it sometimes advanced so slowly. It partly explains also his want of interest in much philosophical writing. He often felt that though, in a sense, he understood an author's meaning, he was unable to ' realize ' it, and that, instead of repeating and grasping an unusual experience, he was going through a mere exercise in dialectics, though it did not follow that he laid the blame on the author. He seldom read the writings of a great man's disciples, because he thought they generally made him easier by pulling VOL. I. d 1 BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH him down to their own level. He was averse to philo- sophical controversy, largely from a feeling that often the disputants were separated ultimately by inability to reach one another's experience. He thought, for instance, that to a competent ' hedonist ' the word ' pleasure ' could not denote the experience of which his opponent wrote; and although Green's arguments against hedonism seemed to him sound, the problem that really interested him was to find the central flaw in the experience which Green called pleasure, — the flaw which is the real ground of the intellectual difficulties of hedonism 1 . Two other characteristics may be mentioned in conclusion. Nettleship's own language was studiously simple, and he had a strong dislike to needlessly technical terminology ; partly, no doubt, on grounds of taste 2 , but partly because he knew how easy it is for students of philosophy to suppose that they have appropriated an author's meaning when they are really doing hardly more than repeating his phrases. He also took comparatively little interest in the working-out of ideas into detail, in their application to a wide field of instances, or in the solution of subordinate problems. His own method was to state his main idea as simply and broadly as possible, to illustrate it by one or two very familiar examples, and to leave the rest to the hearer or reader. His taste in these respects was 1 He attempted to indicate this in a few lines in his Memoir of Green, p. cxxxvii. 2 I have had no opportunity of referring to the accuracy and delicacy of Nettleship's feeling for language. This was evident in his criticisms and translations, and (I am told) in his compositions in Latin, Greek, and Italian. It is obvious in his English prose, and also in the few pieces of verse that he wrote. Green suggested to him in early days that he might approach philosophy from the side of language ; and various passages in his lectures and letters show an inclination to do so. See, for example, pp. 53-4, 86, 99, 127-141, of this volume. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH li repelled by the verbosity and repetitions of some philo- sophers. For example, though I do not suppose he underrated Kant's greatness, much of the Critiques seemed to him mere surplusage, an ocean of unnecessary words containing a few ideas, profound and far-reaching, but capable of simple statement. Some of the characteristics lately mentioned seem to account both for the striking effectiveness of his teaching, and for the few defects, real or imaginary, which I have been able to conjecture from report. To begin with the latter, a few of his hearers thought his lectures common- place, and the less able men found some of them difficult to understand. The simplicity both of his method of treatment and of his language seems to be the main source of dissatisfaction in both these cases. For those who wanted striking or piquant remarks upon Plato, instead of interpretation of Plato, Nettleship's lectures can of course have had little attraction ; and his avoidance of technicalities, of reference to controversies, and of negative criticism, as well as his reduction of every problem to its barest expression, might easily deceive a clever man who, in his ignorance of the difficulties around him, was led so simply to a result. And, though it may seem strange, these same characteristics may have been a cause of perplexity to the less able of Nettleship's pupils ; for reference to controversies, negative criticism, and even technical terms, though they may bewilder and mislead the beginner in philo- sophy, also arrest his attention, give a certain support to his mind, and sometimes open a passage from his ordinary experience to the world of thought, while a very simple positive statement on a difficult matter conveys very little to him, and therefore seems to him d 3 Hi BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH cither trivial or obscure. Nettleship himself felt that his simplicity sometimes made him hard to understand, and in one of the last of his letters alludes to the fact. He says : ' I find my mind perpetually running on certain elementary things, and at the same time I only get at anything by realizing it in very homely instances ; and I fancy the combination is embarrassing to many people. The natural way to most men seems to be to move in a sort of middle region of half-imagery, half- abstractions, which always bothers me.' To this may be added that, whatever a lecturer's powers of speech may be, a treatment of difficult questions not preceded by any verbal preparation must sometimes be hard to follow, and even wanting in lucidity. On the other side, only a few words need be added to the remarks already made under various heads : for, if the foregoing pages have conveyed to the reader any definite idea of what wa.s most characteristic of Nettle- ship as a man and a student of philosophy, he will be as well able as I to imagine the effect of his teaching and influence. His pupils felt that they were in contact with a man remarkable for intellectual strength and subtlety, but still more remarkable for the seriousness and sincerity with which he endeavoured to find and to convey to them the truth. They felt that he was careless of novelty and brilliance, and uninfluenced by partiality and antipathy ; that, sympathetic as he was to ideas from every source, and full of reverence for great men, he still valued ideas solely for their truth, and emphasized only truths which he had himself experienced ; that, greatly as he cared to help them, he did not seek to win their adherence to any doctrine, or even to elevate and inspire them, but simply told them what he saw to BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH liii be true. At the same time, they felt that the search for truth, the philosophy which it was his business to teach, was no mere intellectual employment to him, but his life ; and that the truths which he had learned and wished them to learn with him made life, in his eyes, significant and great. He founded no school, and perhaps few of his pupils could have set out in form the ideas he gave them ; but he taught them to think and to believe in thinking, and some of them are conscious that most of what they value in their own minds derives from him. He could not preach to them ; but they know from his silent witness that the only sure way of doing good to others is to try to be good oneself. How can they remember him without feeling, as he felt, that conceit is ridiculous, cowardice more painful than any pain, selfishness treason to oneself; that sloth and hardness and all forms of evil are literally a dying of the soul, and that no other death is worth a thought ? They may have guessed that his interest in them sustained him in weariness, and that to him there was ' no reward so great as the feeling that one has won the gratitude and affection of the undergraduates.' They will like to know that when, just before he left home for the last time, circumstances led to his making his will and writing other directions in case of death, he remembered many of them. ' I should like, 5 he wrote, ' to send greetings to a huge number of men whom I have known at school and college, but I could not make a complete list, and I should not like to make an incomplete one.' I have said that Nettleship could not preach to his pupils (and the word is not used in any offensive sense). Feeling so strongly that philosophy ought to be, and, at its best, can be, only the utterance of personal experience, liv BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH he was keenly conscious of the distance between his own life and the thoughts of great writers, so that he would sometimes exclaim that the more he understood what life really was, the less he lived it. Even as a young man he was half afraid to speak of his higher aims and aspirations, and when he did so would break off with such words as, ' it is no good dreaming until one has bridged over the gulfs in oneself.' It was therefore quite impossible for him to adopt the tone of a preacher, and he even shrank from lecturing on those subjects which touch most directly on life and conduct. After a single experiment in 1872, he never gave a general lecture on Moral Philosophy *, and even in his lectures on Greek Ethics or the history of Moral Philosophy he was often ill at ease and felt himself ' a solemn humbug.' It is not likely that the effect of his teaching was diminished by this feeling, but it cost him many a struggle. Chiefly for this reason, too, he would never give any- thing in the shape of a religious address. He did at one time begin to write for his pupils a paper which touched directly on the nature of religious ideas : it was studiously matter of fact in tone, but he put it aside. A good deal later, when he was invited to give an address of this kind, he declined. ' I am quite clear,' he wrote in reference to this proposal, ' that whatever religion there is in me had better come out in the only form which is natural to it. i. e. in my ordinary work. The specifically religious form of expression — preaching — seems to me 1 Almost the whole of the course given in 1872 dealt really with metaphysical and psychological foundations, not with moral philosophy itself. The lectures were written in full, but no trace of them remained among his papers. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH lv only to be right when it is one element in a specifically religious life.' His objection, it need hardly be said, had nothing to do with the fact that he was a layman ; and no one was more anxious than he that the men should hear from Green as many lay-sermons as he was able to give. But those ideas and modes of worship which are considered 'specifically religious' occupied in Green's life a place which they did not occupy in Nettle- ship's, after he had definitely broken with traditional beliefs. Though he would have accepted most of what Green wrote and said of those ideas, they ceased to be the natural channels of his religious experience, and he seldom found in the customary forms of worship the ' best moments ' on which he relied for inspiration. Yet the thoughts which ruled his life, though far too difficult and too free from the alloy of sense to form the creed of a Church, were fitted to be the medium of religious experience in a mind like his ; and assuredly they were so. If ' religion ' means the union of a man's whole being with that which he conceives as at once the source and the perfection of all that he knows, admires, and loves ; and if a man may be called ' religious ' when his deepest desire is to attain such union, and when his life is full of the effort after it — then those who knew Nettle- ship best will feel that they have scarcely known a more religious man. In his last years he had given up some of his Col- lege work, and it is most likely that before very long he would have retired and have devoted himself in London to philosophical writing. Nor is it probable that, even if his colleagues had wished him to become Master, he could have been induced to accept a position which in some respects would have been very uncongenial lvi BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH to him, and for which he considered himself in those respects unfitted. He was thought by the friends who saw most of him in these last years to look decidedly older, and at the same time to have grown more peaceful, if not happier. He had, I think, mastered the restless- ness of unsatisfied love ; and, while his sympathies were only deepened and enlarged, he seemed to have attained much of that indifference to the chances and changes of life of which religious writers speak. Alike in intellect and character, which in him seemed in a peculiar degree inseparable, he was standing, when his death came, higher than he had ever stood before. The last of his letters to me was written the night before he started for Switzerland, never to return ; it was meant to be read only if he chanced to be the first to die ; and almost its final words were these : ' Don't bother about death ; it doesn't count.' Not for him, doubtless, or for that which includes both him and all who loved him or felt his influence ; but to them, and, as they believe, to others, his death counts only too much. He lives indeed in them so long as they are true to him ; but they must feel how dim is the reflection that their memories, or even these Remains, can render of a spirit so ardent, deep, and pure l . A. C. B. 1 I have been asked to print the inscription on the memorial tablet in Balliol College Chapel. The words are as follows :■ — ' In memory of Richard Lewis Nettleship, for twenty-three years a tutor in this College. He was born at Kettering, December xvn, mdcccxlvi, and died on Mont Blanc, August xxv, mdcccxcii. He loved great things, and thought little of himself: desiring neither fame nor influence, he won the devotion of men and was a power in their lives : and, seeking no disciples, he taught to many the greatness of the world and of man's mind.' MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS AND EXTRACTS FROM LETTERS VOL I IMMORTALITY (PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS) [This paper, and the two that follow it, entitled ' Pleasure ' and ' Spirit,' were written two or three years before the author's death. They were composed, by way of experiment, for a friend who wished to discover how far the want of education in technical philosophy would be a hindrance to the understanding of some of the ideas which were occupying Nettleship's mind.] PEOPLE talk of ' personal ' immortality, and often find fault with what philosophers say on the ground that it is merely ' impersonal.' It is clear that the first thing to do is to come to some understanding as to what we are to mean by personality. It is probably the hardest of all subjects, and yet it is one upon which we are all ready to pronounce in the most easy-going way. It is worth while to bring home to oneself how extra- ordinarily vague, confused, or inadequate, many of the things are which we suppose ourselves to mean by per- sonality. B 2 4 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS To begin with, we generally assume it to be a definite, self-contained, unchanging thing, round and about which all sorts of more or less separable and changing ap- pendages confusedly float. Or it is something ' inward,' the most inward of all things, that to which we think we should come if we stripped off all the coats of circumstances, custom, education. But we soon realize, on thinking, that there is no circle to be drawn round any one, within which all is ' personal,' and without which all is ' impersonal.' We realize what may be called the continuity of things. What, for instance, is a triangle ? A space bounded by three straight lines. Where does ' it ' stop ? At the lines, of course. But these lines are merely its contact with surrounding space, and the ' personality ' of the triangle is one thing if the surrounding space be limited to the page of a book, another thing if it be extended to the room where the book is, another thing if it be carried on to include the solar system, and so on. And though for particular purposes it is necessary to define the triangle in particular ways, it is, strictly speaking, quite true that it is continuously one with the spatial universe. What is a ' person ' ? A body occupying a certain place, keeping out and otherwise acting on other bodies. What and how many other bodies? It has weight, it exerts pressure, it causes the sensations of colour, sound, smell. Each of these again is continuous with other sensations, and ultimately with universes, of weight, colour, sound, scent, &c. A man touches me with his hand, looks at me, speaks to me. All this is called 'personal ' communication. He writes a letter to me. This too would be called by some IMMORTALITY: PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS 5 ' personal/ He builds a house, makes a picture, founds an institution, passes a law : I live in his house, enjoy his picture, am maintained by his institution, am put in prison or protected by his law. Is this personal or not ? If not, why not ? Well, it will be said, you may not know ox fed that it is his house, his law, &c, whereas you must know or feel that it is his hand or voice. But what does ' his' mean? There lies the whole question. In calling the touch the touch of his hand, you mean that you know, or have reason to believe, that under certain circumstances the touch would be accom- panied by some other sensations, and those by others, and so on : and this possible continuity you call ' him.' Apply the same principle to the other things. It is only want of power that prevents me from connecting the feelings which I have when I look at the picture or am protected by the law, as continuously and as indissolubly with the ' him ' who made them. Of course it will be said, ' This want of power is just what makes the difference.' No doubt it does, but it is good to realize that it is want of power that puts the limits to our sense of personality, and that, as a matter of fact, those limits are very varying in different people, and in the same people at different times. Everybody is 'continuous' with a good deal more than (say) the space six feet round him and the time an hour on each side of him. The simplest memories, hopes, associations, imaginations, inferences, are extensions of personality far greater than we can easily realize. Every 'here' and every 'now' is the centre of practically innu- merable ' theres ' and ' thens,' and the centres are abso- lutely inseparable from their circumferences. 6 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS Loss, separation, death, is failure of continuity. A being which was (so to say) always closing up with everything would change but would not die. There is an irresistible tendency to associate, or even to identify, immortality with duration. Yet when we think of it, we see that duration, strictly speaking, plays very little part in what we really mean by immortality, so far as we mean anything by it. Take any simple fact of duration, e. g. an hour of time. What is an ' hour ' ? ' The time taken by a hand on a clock to go round a certain space and get back to the point it started from ' ; ' the time taken by a shadow to move from a certain point to another certain point,' &c. But these simple-sounding phrases are not so simple. The 'time taken by the clock-hand to move,' &c, is supposed to be a definite, absolute, thing. But it is only so by reference to. or comparison with, some other ' time taken,' e. g. a certain portion of the motion of the earth in regard to the sun. Try as hard as you like to attach a definite meaning to ' hour,' you will inevitably find yourself thinking of at least two things, which you will probably call at first ' the time ' and ' what happens in it.' Thus an hour may mean that, if you could watch the clock-hand and the sun together, a certain position of the one would coincide over and over again with a certain position of the other : i. e. they would take the same time to do a certain thing (get from here to there). Or again, ' it takes an hour to read twenty pages of a book,' ' it takes an hour to feel at home with so and so ' ; these mean that, if we could watch a clock-hand and IMMORTALITY : PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS 7 certain parts of ourselves, we should find certain acts of the clock-hand (reaching a certain point) coinciding with certain acts of our intelligence or feelings : and ulti- mately (as the position of the clock-hand means some- thing which we sec, or infer from what we see) an hour means two or more acts of consciousness compared and identified (i.e. felt to be the same in a certain respect, viz. in respect of points of beginning and ending). Accordingly 'an hour' is a very different thing accord- ingly as the experiences compared and identified are different. There is no such thing as ' absolutely long ' or 'absolutely short.' As we all know, 'an hour' (in the sense of two observed positions of a clock-hand) may be long or short according to what we do or experience in the interval. If we are simply ' waiting ' for something, ' it' will probably seem very • long.' What is the 'it' in this case ? Probably it is the observation of the clock- hand in a great many different positions, or of the pendulum making a great many beats. These are the things to which we attend, and, properly speaking, these are what we are doing or experiencing during the ' hour ' : the ' hour ' is (say) 3,600 beats heard, plus the perception that the first beat and the last coincide with a certain position of the clock-hand. Now this is a very large experience of its kind ; we go through a great deal of auditory perceptk n and attention in it ; and we express this by calling the hour very ' long,' because the per- ception in question happens to be the perception which has been chosen to measure 'length of time' (i.e. it is the experience with which we compare and, in a certain respect, identify other experiences). Now suppose the hour is not passed in ' waiting,' but in a very interesting talk. At the end we constantly say, 8 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS ' How short the time seems ! I should not have thought it was an hour.' First, then, what does an ' interesting ' talk mean ? To be ' interested ' is simply to be ' in it,' and this means that we are attending a great deal. But what does a ' great deal ' mean ? To attend to 3,6co beats of a pendulum is to attend a ' great deal ' ; so is to watch a clock-hand passing through sixty points ; so is to take in a page of a hard book, or fifty pages of an exciting novel, or a scene in a good play ; so is to perform a delicate surgical operation, to draw a delicate line, to sing an exciting or difficult song, to have a row with any one when you are really angry, and so on. These different operations may ' take very different times'; i.e. the beginnings and endings of them may coincide with very different positions of the earth with regard to the sun. If at the end of them we are inclined to say, ' How quickly the time has gone ! ' it means that we should not have expected (if we had thought about it) to find the clock-hand where it is. And this again means that we carry about with us a sort of average feeling of how long the hand takes to get through a certain space, and this average feeling represents roughly how much we should feel between certain positions of the hand, if we were ' doing nothing in particular ' (i. e. partly watching the clock, partly doing a little of fifty other things). When, then, we feel that ' the time ' has been short, we really mean that we have been going through so much in other ways that we have gone through very little measurement of time, as ' time ' is usually understood (i. e. as the observation of certain changes of position in certain bodies). On the other hand, we are just as likely to say at the end of one of the experiences mentioned above, ' What an age it IMMORTALITY : PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS 9 seems ! I seem to have lived through year?.' This is very interesting, because it makes us see the complete relativity of time-measurement. What happens in these cases (when the 'time' seems ' long ') is that we measure the motion of the clock-hand in terms (so to say) of what we have been experiencing. We have ' gone through a great deal,' ' lived a great deal,' ' put out a great deal of energy ' ; and just as the hour measured on the clock seems 'a great deal ' when we are ' waiting,' because we attend very much to the hands, so now we say it seems ' a great deal ' because we have attended very much to the reading or looking or singing. Properly speaking, it is not the ' it ' which seems a great deal (not the clock-measured hour), but it is the ' it' filled with all that we have experienced. We are surprised that so much could be ' got into an hour,' because we mean by an ' hour ' (as we said before) a rough average of what we expect generally to experi- ence when the clock-hand moves a certain distance. All this may not seem to have much to do with immortality. But it helps one to see that ' duration,' ' g om g on / & c -' have n ot the simple or definite meaning that we are apt to suppose. The truth seems to be that nobody ever wishes simply to ' go on ' ; what men really want, when they want at all, is to be or do more of what they are or are doing ; but what sort of ' more ' it is depends entirely on the particular circumstances. What is ' more ' or ' longer ' from one point of view, or on one principle of measurement, will be ' less ' or 'shorter' on another. We shall always find that, when we use the terms 'long' and 'short' in an apparently absolute way, we are applying a rough average sense, which is got at by unconsciously taking bits out of io MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS different experiences, and which does not really apply precisely to any. We may say, All that we call ' duration ' implies a comparison of two or more different experiences, any one of which may be chosen to measure the rest by. ' Absolute duration ' could only apply to a being which was all in all its experiences (not less in one and more in another). But then ' duration ' (in our sense) would not really apply to such a being; and this is just what is expressed by saying, ' With the Lord one day is as a thousand years, and a thousand years are as one day.' PLEASURE (PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS) The discussions of Greek philosophers about pleasure, the nature of it and the part which it plays for good and evil in human life, are full of interest and suggestion. Philosophy is only the concentrated and articulate- expression of the experience of certain men. an ex- perience which all people have to some degree. And in the history of philosophy, accordingly, we may be said to get a sort of quintessence of what human nature has come to find in itself, so far as that admits of expression in language. The first, and also the last, question that can be asked about anything is, 'What is it?' It is all-important to be clear what exactly this question can and ought to mean. The understanding of this is the foundation of all clear thinking, as the misunderstanding of it is the source of all confusion. Observe, firstly, that the answer to the question, 'What is x?' is never simply ' x.' Such an answer would universally be admitted to be no answer : the person giving it would, properly speaking, have said nothing. All answers that are really answers are of the form, ' x is y, z, &c.' 12 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS Now this is a very important fact. It compels us to realize that the ' being ' of anything, that which it ' is,' its ' .r-hood,' is never adequately expressed by saying, ' It is just itself and nothing else.' Or, to put the same thing another way, z/and so far as we insist that l x is just x and nothing else,' we are merely insisting that it is z';zexpressible. The instinct which we all have at times to assert this has, indeed, if rightly understood, a truth in it, which it is important to consider. We stick to it, and rightly, that ' x is x ' ; that ' whatever may be said about it by way of explanation and interpretation, the fact to which we ultimately come back is the fact from which we start, the fact that x is not anything else in the world except itself This conviction has found expression in various forms; e.g. 'the essence of anything does not admit of analysis ' ; ' no reason can be given why a thing is what it is'; 'the individuality (which = indivisibility or un- analyzableness) of anything is an ultimate fact, behind which we cannot go.' Consider in what sense these sayings are true ; and for this purpose take some simple fact of consciousness, e.g. the consciousness of the taste of a peach, or that of the roundness of a circle. In what sense can we, and in what sense can we not, say ' what these are,' or express their ' being ' ? First take the assertion that we cannot. What does it mean? It means, e.g., that the taste of a peach is not the taste of any other thing ; that it is unique ; that this is what is meant by calling it ' of a peach ' ; that, if a person had never had personal experience of it, we could never convey its nature to him at all adequately by any amount of description or analysis ; and that the PLEASURE : PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS 13 taste remains precisely the same fact of consciousness after our attempts to define it as it was before. All this is very true and very important to realize, for not realizing it leads to all sorts of delusions, and gives rise to the common feeling that, when people do what they call f explaining ' a thing, they are usually merely ' explaining it away.' But now look at the question from another side. When we rightly assert that the peach-taste is absolutely unique and individual, what exactly is it that we are asserting (for we do undoubtedly mean to assert some- thing, not nothing) ? In other words, what is uniqueness and individuality ? Or, what is it to be unique and individual ? In answering this, let us, as far as possible, put words out of our mind, and attend to that which we are con- scious of, that which we experience, in tasting the peach. Let us start by supposing that the experience comes without any premeditation (let us wake suddenly and find a peach in our mouth), and let us further suppose that we have never tasted or heard of a peach before. The first and least thing that we can say of the experience is that it is 'new' ; i.e. it stands out, so to say, from and against a vague general background (our taste-experience). If it did not at least do this, there would, strictly speak- ing, be no ' 1 V at all. This will be found to be equally true of every experience that we have ; however many times we may have had it, it is still absolutely distinct each time that we have it. It is true that what we call ' habit ' tends to diminish its distinctness. But what does this really mean? ' Habit ' is not some mysterious force (as we are too apt to suppose) which ' acts upon us ' ; it is merely the word i 4 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS expressing one particular kind of limitation in our power of experiencing. There is no necessary connexion be- tween the repetition and the loss of an experience. On the contrary, the curious thing is that it is by repetition that we gain (as well as lose) experience. Let us go back to the peach, and illustrate this. We saw that, whatever the taste is when experienced, however much or however little there is in it, it is a distinct something, and that this distinctness is (necessarily) a distinctness in, or of, or against, a something else. This distinctness is not something separate from the individuality of the experience ; it is the individuality ; the ' self-hood ' of the experience is at the same time a ' not-something-else.' Now let us see how the experience may^ww, or become an experience of more. Suppose us to wake a second and third time with a peach in our mouth. We shall be conscious of the taste, and we shall also be conscious that it is the same taste as we had before. Now in this simple statement there are three possibilities implied. We may feel inclined to say, either (i) This is the same taste, only to-day is Tuesday, and the day on which it occurred before was Monday; or (2) This is the same taste, but now I like it better or find more in it ; or (3) This is merely the same taste over again, and it doesn't interest me so much as it did the first time. In case (1) we may say that the experience is (though not precisely, yet for practical purposes) 'the same'; in (2) it is ' more ' ; in (3) it is ' less.' Consider (2). We are apt to think that the ' more-ness ' means that, while the experience itself remains the same, something else has been added to it. But this is only an imperfect way of putting the fact. The experience in (2) is just as in- dividual, just as much ' itself and nothing else,' as the PLEASURE : PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS 15 original experience, and its individuality consists in an unanalyzable consciousness. That is, though we describe it by saying, ' it is the same as the original one but also more/ we cannot by any device separate the two factors in it without making it cease to be ' it! Suppose, e. g., the increase consists in what we call ' not only new but pleasant,' ' not only sweet but piquant,' ' not only peculiar but like some other taste,' ' not only nice to me but what would be nice for a certain invalid whom I am fond of; the various elements thus combined by ' not only but also ' make up in each case a sing/r experience ; the consciousness of the combination is not a combined consciousness; if we took it to pieces, i.e. if we attended exclusively first to one, then to another of its elements, we should be experiencing, not it, but quite different its. More obvious illustrations of this truth are, e.g., such experiences as ' aesthetic impressions ' : the consciousness of a musical phrase, or of a combination of lines or colours, is one indivisible thing ; it is not made tip of the several notes, lines, or colours, but it is these in combination. In this sense all experience is unanalyzable ; it can never be divided without becoming a different experience, any more than an organism can be divided into its organs without ceasing to be an organism. On the other hand, no experience is, strictly speaking, simple; i.e. an experience is never of one thing merely, but always of a unity of two or more things. And in this sense it always admits of analysis, or rather, it always is an analysis ; i.e. it is always a consciousness of something as distinct from, a variety of, following on, connected with, but at the same time one with, something else. It does not matter whether its internal structure 16 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS can be put into words or not ; what we have to consider is the nature of the experience itself, and this will always be found to involve some, however little, ' structure.' Growth of experience, its becoming more, may thus be represented as growth of structure, or a process in which we come to be more ' constructive,' to put more together, to find more in things, to get more out of them. (All these are equivalent expressions, for our experience is ' we,' and it makes no difference whether we represent ourselves as making it or as finding it ; sometimes one and sometimes the other way of speaking comes more naturally.) Conversely, loss of experience, its becoming less, will mean that certain elements in our construction drop out and leave gaps. The less we ' get out of a thing,' or ' the less we put of ourselves into it,' the less we are, the less there is of us. If we could see right into the ex- periences of a number of persons who were all supposed to be experiencing the same thing (looking at the same picture, hearing the same tune, doing the same duty, receiving the same pleasure or pain), we should find that they all experienced different things, and that all had gaps, bigger or smaller, in different places. And it Avould be a mistake to single out the one place in them all (if there happened to be one) where there was no gap, where they all coincided, and call that the expe- rience of the thing. The thing is really all that can be possibly experienced under the given circumstances, and no human being can say beforehand what or how much this is. Different people differ in nothing more than in the different amounts which they experience under externally the same circumstances. To one, as Wordsworth puts it, PLEASURE : PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS 17 ' A primrose by a river's brim A yellow primrose was to him, And it was nothing more ' ; to another, ' The meanest flower that blows can give Thoughts that do often lie too deep for tears.' The experiences of both are perfectly real and indi- vidual ; they differ in the amount which they hold together or construct, or again in the amount of them- selves that they put into the experience. What is usually called ' taking interest ' illustrates the same thing. To be ' interested ' literally means to be 'in it ' (curious that the slang 'in it ' and ' out of it ' should have retained something of this original mean- ing). We experience a thing just in proportion as we are ' in it,' or (to use another graphic phrase) make it our own. In proportion as we ' lose interest ' we cease to experience, and, so far as that thing is concerned, we cease to be. (' Interest ' at its highest power is ' love,' and if we could take interest in all things, we should be on the way to love all things, and this means to 'be in ' all things or make all things our own, which is God. If any one wants to have a healthy sense of his limita- tions, let him ask himself, (1) how many things he is interested in ; (2) how much he gets out of those in which he would say he was interested.) As a result of all this, we may say, the self, I, per- sonality, or whatever we like to call that which ex- periences things, is one in all that it experiences : one in seeing, hearing, smelling, and in every modification of these, one in every combination of these, and in all more complex experiences as well ; it is this oneness which makes the unanalyzable self-hood of any and every VOL. I. C 18 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS experience. On the other hand, the self in all its experi- ence is one of ox in many, an experience of distinctness in innumerable senses. In a word, it is always and every- where a whole of parts, a combining and dividing activity, able to detach any part from any other part, and yet to be in them all. Another important point to clear up in any investiga- tion of pleasure is the proper meaning of the phrase ' pleasure of doing a thing.' It may mean two totally different things: (i) what would be described as, e.g., the pleasure of eating a peach apart from the act of eat- ing it. What we really do when we make this distinction is to separate mentally one part of the whole experience from another part. The pleasant part of the eating, e.g., can be separated from the consciousness of moving the teeth (which may not be pleasant). But it is very important to remember that, so far as this is done, the experience ceases to be one, and the pleasure ought not (quite strictly) to be called the pleasure of that ex- perience, but a pleasant experience in or along with a non-pleasant one. (2) Strictly speaking, the pleasure of doing or being anything is the pleasant consciousness of doing or being that thing ; not a consciousness along- side the doing or being, but the conscious doing or being itself. It is only after what we call 'reflexion,' i.e. when we are more or less ' out of the experience and ' in ' some other, that we come to analyze it into act and pleasure. Yet what most people mean by ' pleasures ' are the results of some such reflexion. They are, so to say, detached pieces of experience, retained and dwelt upon. The common maxim, ' If you want pleasure, do not think about it,' is based upon this fact ; for to ' think PLEASURE : PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS 19 about ' pleasure to most people means to detach a certain element in some experience, and then perhaps to try to get it without the rest of the experience- The dis- appointment which so often follows arises from the fact that, having thus detached the pleasure, we expect to get it in some different experience, forgetting that there are very likely new elements present which disturb or prevent the pleasure. C 2 SPIRIT i. THE history of the word ' spirit,' and of its equivalents in Greek and German, would be the history of a great bit of the human mind, and of that bit of it where perhaps its most absorbing experiences are to be found. Ilvtvixa, ' wind,' ' breath,' ' moving air ' — that is the thing to which it all goes back ; and the text which sums it all up the best is, ' The wind bloweth where it listeth, and thou hearest the sound thereof, but canst not tell whence it cometh or whither it goeth : so is every one who is born of the wind.' It seems as if the notion that lies at the root of all notions of spirit is that of freedom in some sense, whether in that cf power to dispense with means usually necessary, or of power to produce something out of material usually unproductive. Hence the mystery, the unaccountableness, which always hangs about ' spirit ' in all its senses, when it is looked at from a less ' spiritual ' point of view. Take some absurdly different instances. A ' ghost,' when it means anything, means something which in some way transcends or does without certain conditions which the person who calls it a ghost cannot SPIRIT 21 do without. It comes through a door without having to open it, speaks without having to breathe, appears without having to occupy space. &c. A ' spiritualist ' is a person who can communicate with other persons in ways unknown or unfamiliar to most people, and these ways imply the power of dispensing with certain usual means or organs. A person ' of spirit,' in English, is one who rises above certain circumstances which would depress other people. A person of Gcist, in German, is a person who gets something out of things which to most people suggest nothing. And a person of esprit, in French, is one who does the same in the somewhat lighter things of life. The ' spirit,' as opposed to the ' letter,' is the meaning got out of a formula or principle by one who sees it in many bearings, one who is very much alive, as opposed to that which is got out of it by one who can see it in only one or two bearings and is dead to the rest. The ' spirit/ as opposed to the ' flesh,' is the activity of mind which is independent of actual touch or bodily presence, as opposed to that which is tied to these for its experiences. ' God is a spirit ' ; he is not ' in this mountain ' or ' at Jerusalem ' ; wherever there is anything, there is he. He is absolutely free activity, able to ' make all things new,' and ' where the spirit of God is, there is liberty.' One great difficulty in the way of understanding spirit is the inveterate habit of supposing that ' spiritual ' activity is a single definite kind of activity, opposed to another definite kind called ' material ' or ' physical ' or ' natural.' The latter is supposed to be known and understood, the former is supposed to be ' mysterious,' ' supernatural,' and the like. 22 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS The truth seems to be that all activity or agency may truly be called spiritual, if by 'agency' is understood that which gives rise to something which was not there before. All ' things ' whatever, and all the ' properties ' of things, are ultimately forms of agency, force, energy. Things are what they do, and what they do is themselves. Motion, heat, light, magnetism, electricity, &c, are different forms of agency, i.e. they are names for various sorts of change which occur under various conditions. They are better understood than many other forms of agency only in the sense that they admit of being more precisely described. They may be called ' physical,' if this merely means that they have certain properties in common, distinguishing them from, e.g., what are called 'personal' agencies ('moral influence,' &c). But the ' physical ' forms of agency can be no more ' explained ' than the ' moral,' nor can the ' moral ' be less 'explained ' than the ' physical.' {Explanation in the scientific sense means the expression of something in terms of some- thing else, with which we are more familiar or with which we can deal more easily.) Wherever there is agency, there something is being produced different from what was there before, i. e. certain conditions are being transcended, gone beyond, in a way which could not be predicted (except by a being which was the source of all agency, the universal agent). All agency is in this sense ' mysterious,' a continual ' miracle ' or ' wonder.' But it is generally called ' mysterious ' only when it is unfamiliar to the person in question. Gunpowder is miraculous to a savage, but he sees nothing miraculous in his bow and arrows. To SPIRIT 23 a being which was all stomach, the experiences of a being which had eyes or ears would be miraculous, just as again a person of exceptional knowledge or in- sight was regarded in the middle ages as having con- nexion with the devil. ' Spiritual'' and 'physical." Two of the most important and interesting illus- trations of the various ways in which this distinction has been understood are found in the facts of eating and of love. Hardly any subject has exercised and divided people more than the Eucharist. It is worth considering how and why there has been so much controversy about it. Roughly speaking, there are two prevalent views : one, that eating the bread and drinking the wine are ' signs ' or ' symbols ' of certain ' spiritual ' acts ; the other, that the bread and wine ai'e in some way ' spiritual ' substances, the body and blood of Christ, in which the communicant in the act of eating and drinking partici- pates. Neither view seems to represent the deepest truth. In the first place, we must ask what is a sign or symbol! To say that A is a symbol of B implies, of course, that A is something different from B, but (and this is often forgotten) it also implies that it is in some respect the same as B. The most remote, far-fetched symbol in the world must have something in common with that which it symbolizes ; i. e. the person to whom it has the symbolic meaning must have some (however little it may be) of the same feeling or experience when he experiences the symbol, as he has when he experiences 24 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS that which it symbolizes. In other words, there are such things as symbols just because the most different things in the world have something in common. From this elementary fact spring all the controversies and complications about symbols. One party says, ' It is only a symbol, it is not the real thing ' ; and they are partly right, for in order to be a symbol a thing must be partly different from something else, and this something else which is symbolized must be more than the symbol. The other party says, ' It is the real thing, this which you call a mere symbol ' ; and they too are partly right, for in order to be a symbol at all, a thing must be partly the same as that which it symbolizes. Take the case of the Eucharist. What is the act (the ' physical ' act, as it is usually called) of eating? It is an act in virtue of which a certain material comes into contact with a certain other material, and thereupon arises another material endowed with fresh properties. It would be much better to speak of ' agencies ' through- out. Bread, for instance, is a certain agent, capable of acting and being acted on in various ways. The palate, tongue, throat, stomach, blood, &c, are other similar agents. Bread in the various processes of chewing, swallowing, digesting, &c, becomes a new agent, does new things, is an element in a new whole, contributes to new results ; some of these results have got names ; e. g. ' taste,' ' satisfaction of hunger,' ' refreshment,' w strength,' ' health; If we chose, we could follow the bread through a still wider circle of transformations ; e. g. we could see it becoming an element in an ' artistic ' or a ' moral ' or a 'spiritual ' result ; i.e. we could see the agency or force which it has (or, rather, which it is) becoming an agency or force in the production of a picture, the doing of SPIRIT 25 a brave act, the overcoming a temptation or difficulty. The great mistake which we usually make is that we follow the bread as far, say, as the digestive process, and then stop and draw a line ; on the one side of the line we put what we call the f physical ' agency of bread, on the other we put what we sometimes call the agency of a • mysterious ' moral or intellectual or spiritual agent (quite separate from bread). But the truth is (however absurd it may sound at first) that there is no one thing, ' bread,' beginning to be ' bread ' at a certain point and ceasing to be ' bread ' at a certain other point. The properties (i.e. forces or agencies) which make 'bread' as it is in the loaf, become quite different when ' bread ' is in a stomach, and quite different again when it is blood and muscle and nerve, and quite different again when it is feeling and thought and emotion of various kinds. And there is absolute continuity in all these changes, though the agency at any given moment is quite different from what it is at any other given moment. Now it is what we may call this continuity of agency which makes symbolism possible. Bread, in all its various phases of existence, is an agent which enters into and contributes to the total agency which we may call human life. If we like to call it ' a symbol of life- producing agency,' we ought to mean that it has (really, not only fancifully) something in common with all life- giving agency. It (so to say) points beyond what it is in any given phase, to the infinite other phases into which it is capable of entering and into which it eventually does enter, just as conversely the agencies of those other phases point back to (because they are really continuous with) the elementary agency of bread. It is they pro- spectively, they are it retrospectively. i6 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS It might be asked, why then should we not call moral or artistic agency 'symbolic of digestive agency? I suppose to an omniscient mind everything would be equally symbolic of everything else ; or, more accu- rately, such a mind would see everything in everything ; whereas to us with our limited and unequally active minds one thing only ' suggests ' or ' is like ' or ' recalls ' or ' contrasts with ' another. And the principle upon which we go is, apparently, to call A a "symbol of B when, from the point of view at which we are at the moment, B means more of the same kind of thing that A means. Digestive agency is much, but the agency of growing is more, the agency of moving about is more still, the agency of making clothes, houses, machines, is more still, the agency of making schools, laws, govern- ment, art, science, religion, is more still, and so on. But in all there will be found certain identical features ; in all there is what we may call ' assimilation ' of one thing by another, the assimilation resulting in an agency different from either of the agents assimilated. In this way it is literally true to say that human society is an ' organism ' ; only it should be remembered that its organic life or agency is incomparably more complicated than that of an animal or plant, and there- fore incomparably more difficult to set out in detail. To return to the Eucharist. We saw that in reality ' bread ' is an element or factor in a continuous agency. But the name 'bread' (like all names) is intended to mark off a more or less definite bit of this continuous agency, and enable us to treat it as if it were a thing by itself. What particular bit is marked off by this or any other name, is impossible to say precisely, because different people mark off different bits according to their SPIRIT 27 different views and interests. Still there is a sort of average meaning for 'bread,' which it is the business of a dictionary-maker to ascertain and define. Starting from this (which he would call its ' proper ' meaning) the dictionary-maker goes on to notice various other meanings which he calls ' derivative/ ' metaphorical,' and the like (all of which arise from the same fact as that which gives rise to symbols). Taking ' bread,' then, in its average or dictionary sense, as that which is ' physically ' assimilated and transformed in the Eucharist, it is obvious that it is not what is ordinarily understood as a spiritual agent, ' the body of Christ.' It is ' only ' a symbol. But now suppose a person to eat this bread, and in the act of eating it to realize (not of course completely, but very much more than is usually done) the immensity of the act ; to realize as one thing (for it really is one thing) the chewing and digesting, the increase of muscular strength, the doing of acts or making of things, in fact the whole of himself into which the bread is now enter- ing. Or suppose more than this ; suppose that not only once now and then, under special circumstances which help the act of realization, in church on Sunday, &c, but whenever he eats or drinks, he has this comparatively full consciousness of what he is doing. To such a person it would be true to say that ' every meal is a sacrament.' To such a person ' grace before meat ' would be no almost meaningless formula, but the true expression of a feeling that God, the omnipotent and omnipresent agent, was really present here and now, in this partial agent of bread or water. Such a person might properly be said to have a com- paratively ' spiritual ' mind, or to realize more than most c8 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS people the 'spiritual' significance of the act of eating. But it is all-important to see that this 'spiritual' con- sciousness of the nature of the act is not got at the expense of, or by leaving beliind, the consciousness of the ' physical ' nature of the act. The person in question, for instance, would not help himself to be spiritual in eating if he were to practise being indifferent to what his food tasted like, or to how it was cooked, or to whether it was digestible. On the contrary, these properties or agencies of food are part of its spiritual property or agency. Food does not become an agent in the highest life of man by giving up its niceness and digestibility, but by means of these. It is quite true that the niceness and digestibility of food may, under certain circumstances, have to be ignored in consideration of more important things. That is to say, the thing we call ' food ' may (so to say) be called upon to do a different thing, to contribute a different factor, in the total agency of life. This illus- trates from a new point of view what we said before about the relativity of things or agents. No agent stands alone or has its agency all to itself. It is always an element in a continuous larger agency. And to beings like ourselves, beings that are never the whole but that may always realize that there is a whole, this larger or largest agency must always present itself as an infinite possibility, a something of which we can never predict the demands it may make on us, a ' wind ' that may change its direction at any moment, and of which all that we can hope to feel or know is that its direction is good, that we are better in proportion as we can surrender ourselves to it, that it is a more of something which we already are. Thus, for instance, ' food ' cannot say, ' I am SPIRIT 29 food, with such and such powers and rights, which I will exercise and keep, but in my own way and at my own pleasure.' In proportion as it says this, it is lost. If it consistently said this and acted on it, it would not be food at all. It can only be food, even in the most elementary sense of the word, by entering into some- thing else, assimilating and being assimilated. The more it ' loses itself (what it begins by being) the more it ' finds itself.' This is no fancy, but a plain fact. The whole truth about ' selfishness ' hangs on this con- sideration. There is no act which may not be selfish, or which may not be unselfish. An agent or act is selfish in proportion as it tries to make itself the whole, instead of feeling that it is part of the whole. But it does not really save itself by trying to make itself the whole, nor does it really lose itself by realizing that it is only part of the whole. The pleasantness of wine is not made more by trying to concentrate all our powers upon the experience of it (meaning by this, we will say, a certain sensation in the palate) ; it would soon be made less, and the other powers would be made less too. On the other hand, it would not be less, but infinitely more, to a being which could feel it along with, or as an element in, all the delight to which it is capable of ministering. (By way of a simple illustration take, e.g., the enjoy- ment of wine by the solitary depressed drinker, its enjoyment in delightful company, its enjoyment by a person in whom it almost immediately became a poem, and its enjoyment by a so-called ' mystical ' person in the Eucharist. Some people would say it was 'blasphemous' to put the last enjoyment along with the others ; but it can only be so, if we allow ourselves to pull it down to a lower level. No doubt most of us are pretty sure 3 o MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS to do this, because we are so limited in our 'spiritual ' capacity, and we are apt to help ourselves out of our limitations by giving what we call a ' tangible ' interpreta- tion to experiences which we cannot understand.) Agency, then, is not ' spiritualized ' by becoming less, but by becoming more. This gives us the right point of view from which to look at ' asceticism ' and everything of that kind. There is, e.g., no virtue in 'giving up' wine, any more than there is any virtue in drinking wine without enjoying it. All true ' asceticism ' means simply the acquisition of some greater power by practice. Everybody who has any ambition of any kind whatever ' asceticizes ' a little, i. e. gives itp something to get some- thing more. But a person who says 'wine in itself is bad ' is as wrong as one who says ' wine in itself is good.' The prejudice (sometimes right and sometimes wrong) against ' asceticism.' ' spirituality,' and the like, seems to arise mostly from the fact that men must recognize a sort of average experience and express it in a sort of average language and habits. The most really l spiritual' people are, I suppose, the people who talk least about it. A person to whom every meal was a sacrament would be the last to say it to his neighbours at a dinner-party, for he would know that his words would not convey what he meant, and would convey something that he did not mean. A person who really felt that he was ' training for an immortal prize ' would not go about saying so, for he would know that what is ordinarily understood by ' training ' and ' prize ' is only a fragment of what he understands. On the other hand, it must be insisted that the ' average ' meaning of words (and this is the average level of ex- perience) has no right whatever to call itself the ' true ' SPIRIT 31 meaning. ' Philistinism ' in all its forms is the refusal to admit that things can mean more than I, the Philistine, choose that they shall mean. John the Baptist comes neither eating nor drinking, and the Philistines settle him by saying ' he has a devil.' Jesus comes eating and drinking, and the same Philistines settle him as a free liver, who keeps company with vulgar men and loose women. But ' wisdom is justified of all her children ' ; the world, if we would only open our eyes, wants them all, is the better for them all ; and the publicans and harlots often go into the kingdom of heaven before the Pharisee. As the Philistine tends to interpret ' spirituality ' by pulling it down, calling it ' cant ' or ' madness' or ' eccen- tricity ' or 'radicalism' or 'vapouring' (and he can always produce lots of instances where so-called spiritu- ality is not spirituality at all), so many well-meaning people interpret it by calling it ' miraculous,' which is really another way of pulling it down. Take the Eucharist again. The feeling (true and justifiable in itself) that every act has ' a spiritual meaning,' ' an eternal significance/ ' infinite consequences,' and the like, unable to maintain itself at its height, helps itself by saying, ' This bit of bread is being transformed into divine flesh ' ; and in saying this, it thinks, not of the real wonder (that bread is really an agency in the whole agency of human life, and so in the life of the world and God), but of a sort of nondescript process by which ' bread ' (in the average sense) is somehow converted into ' flesh ' (not indeed ' flesh ' in the average sense, but still in some similar sense). Then comes the angry ' man of science ' and proves triumphantly that bread is bread and nothing else, while 32 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS the ' man of religion ' goes racking his brains to find a way by which the ' physical ' laws of bread may be superseded, and yet the bread may still be bread. The cure for a wrong or spurious ' mysticism ' is to realize ' the facts ' : but ' the facts ' must not be taken to mean (as they generally are) either certain particular facts (of chemistry, for instance, or physiology), or certain particular aspects of facts to which I happen to be ac- customed. The fact is the whole fact, neither more nor less. True mysticism is the consciousness that everything which we experience, every ' fact,' is an element and only an element in ' the fact ' ; i. e. that, in being what it is, it is significant or symbolic of more. INDIVIDUALITY [Remarks on a pupil's essay which there was no opportunity of discussing orally. About 1889.] A STONE ' does not distinguish itself from its environ- ment.' Doesn't it, just so far as 'stone' means anything? Any of what are called its ' properties ' seem to be exertions of force, actions and reactions. E. g. it occupies a certain space (keeps other things out and is kept in by them), has a certain weight (presses on other things and is pressed on by them). Of course a plant does and suffers a great many more things than a stone, but both, so far as they are anything distinct from anything else, are so because they act on and are acted on by an environment. The question is, What is environment ? Where does it begin ? What is it that is environed ? It is the old problem of ' circumstance ' (of which I suppose environ- ment is only a modern translation). If you say the environment of the stone is the adjacent spaces, then the it of the stone is occupation of a certain space. If you say its environment is the bodies upon which it presses, then it is pressure. So with the plant : where does ' it ' begin or end ? To what distance, for VOL. I. D 34 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS instance, is the surrounding air or soil affected by its absorbing surface ? At what point do they become part of it, and when ought ' they ' to be said to act upon ' it ' and ' it ' upon ' them ' ? One is inclined to say that the plant is what you could take away and put somewhere else without its being changed, and that you could do this without carrying the air and soil with it. But it couldn't be taken away without some air, or transplanted into no soil. An 'individual ' is properly 'something that cannot be divided.' This seems to give one some clue. The indi- viduality of a thing is just the amount of things which make one — from which none can be taken away without the unity ceasing. A heap of stones, we say, has little individuality, because we can take away a good many stones and still call it a heap. But it isn't the same heap, and does not really retain its individuality. Any two things that can't do without each other seem to make an individual, and the more things there arc in this condition the greater the individuality. A complete individual would therefore apparently have no ' environment ' ; or, environment begins where individuality ends. To any two contiguous stones in a heap the rest of the heap is environment ; to any two notes in a tune the rest of the tune is environment ; and when you add some more notes and make a phrase, what was before 'environment and individuality ' has become all individuality. Thus too it seems difficult to distinguish between 'taking in ' and 'giving out.' The two notes of a tune are exactly what they take in and what they give out : they are affected by the notes on each side of them exactly as much as they affect them : if you alter them you alter the tune, and if you alter the tune you alter INDIVIDUALITY 35 them. No doubt they have an individuality out of the tune, and one is inclined to call this their own individuality. But it is no more their own than what they had in the tune ; or rather, ' their ' is now a different ' their ' and has a different environment (the particular circumstances under which they happen to be heard). If it be said they can exist and have individuality without any en- vironment, I suppose one would have to ask whether two notes could be one thing (have an individuality) except to a consciousness which was more than they. Anyhow, they could only be without environment if they were the universe (or fancied themselves such). Thus, for everything except the absolute, individuality implies limitation (i.e. environment), and the great differ- ence in the associations which the word has seems to come from the double fact that, while every individuality is measured by the amount which it holds together (i. e. by the amount of what would otherwise be environment that it converts into itself), it is also measured against what still remains environment, what it excludes, asserts itself against. ' Individualism ' and all that goes with it, isolation, selfishness, jealousy, fear, represent this side of the thing. A ' great individuality,' such as you say Shakespeare was, represents the other side. You say that the attempt to take in without giving out results in death. I suppose this is quite true, only it seems that one must say the same of the attempt to give out without taking in. The trouble is that each of these phrases (' taking in,' &c.) only expresses one mode of activity or being, and it is impossible not to be affected by the metaphor which is necessarily present in any such partial account of a thing. When a person makes a box, or a tune, or a law, does he take in or give out the most ? D 2 ^6 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS It seems impossible to make any distinction. You say indifferently, ' he puts himself into the wood,' or ' he takes the wood into himself.' At any given point in the process you can analyze it into ' wood ' and ' him,' but it is only your analysis ; the fact is indivisible, and that fact is just individuality. If he says indignantly, ' I am not box,' that is only because he is aware that he is other things as well. Ultimately one seems to have to say, the greatest indi- viduality is that which produces most, or out of which the most is produced. It does not seem really to matter which you say, though it sounds as if it did. One might compare individuality to centre of gravity. Every material body has a centre of gravity, i. e. is an individual or indivisible system in respect of motion. On the other hand, each centre of gravity is determined by those about it, and ultimately by the centre of the earth (to go no further). If one thinks of other properties besides motion, it seems to be the same. E. g. any person has one centre of gravity at each moment regarded as a body merely, another regarded as an organic body, another regarded as a healthy body, another regarded as a legal ' person,' another regarded as a character, and so on. And as in the original sense the centre of gravity is continually changing, and the body is continually becom- ing a different individual and getting into different en- vironments, so with the other senses. And one can imagine a stone refusing to admit that it had any other centre of gravity than that which it had in a particular place and position, and being very much distressed or offended when it found itself topsy-turvy, and putting the blame upon its environment which would not conform or which it could not assimilate, whereas all the time the INDIVIDUALITY 37 environment was conforming beautifully, and in fact there was no environment at all, for the world of bodies was individual. A person who, as you put it, ' knows a great deal ' without being a great individuality, does not, I suppose, really know a great deal. What one means is that a great many pieces of information make a kind of unity in him (in what is called his memory), but that the unity that they make is not as close or organic as we can conceive it might be. We see, for instance, that there are other bits of the ' he ' which seem to stand quite apart from ' his knowledge.' It seems very important to recognize, as you do to- wards the end, that the problem of individuality is raised in different ways to different people. As you say, it may be ' people ' or it may be ' things ' that ' refuse to come right.' What one is perpetually doing is to stereo- type oneself — to fix one or two experiences as the centres and try to keep these and make everything else into circumference. There are two lines of Goethe which always stick in my head about this : Nur wo du bist sei alles, immer kindlich, So bist du alles, bist unuberwindlich. I suppose both self-depreciation and self-assertion arc equally wrong kinds of this 'centralization.' In both one allows oneself to be divided into a more or less hostile self and not-self ; only in the one case one shrinks from the not-self, in the other one threatens it. The people who have, in various phraseology, represented love as the reality of things, have I suppose felt this, for love is the only thing that is perfectly fearless and yet per- fectly kind. The difficulty is to keep between the two extremes, as 28 MISCELLANEOUS PAPERS Aristotle might say, that of being nothing because one has only one centre, and that of being nothing because one has no centre ; death by stagnation and death by dissipation. The ideal would be to be the centre of every circumference. Practically the important thing seems to be that one should try to be the growing centre of a growing circumference, so that while one is always ready to change one's individuality without fear of losing it, one should always carry the individuality that one has so far made into each new environment, so that the old should become young and the young old and thus death be impossible. THE ATONEMENT [The following rough notes, evidently written merely for himself, seem, from comparison with the ideas con- tained in Nettleship's letters, to belong to 1886.] The ' Christian ' doctrine says, God so loved the world that he gave his only-begotten Son to save it, i. e. to make it one with himself again. This assumes that the ' world ' is estranged from God ; that this estrangement is the fact of ' sin ' ; that the effect of sin is death — perishableness ; that by ' atonement ' the world regains ' life.' What is the relation of these conceptions to the patent facts of life ? We see that everything perishes : iravra pet. Yet we equally see that nothing perishes ; everything becomes something else : life is only possible through consumption (death) : life is the process of transmutation. On what ground do we distinguish life from death, yeWo-is from L\ei(r6ai as well as of $i\/;tu) and ' doing ' fall more or less apart, and more or less succeed one another, THE VALUE OF THEORY 123 and to a certain extent each can go on independently ; and it is to this imperfect understanding and this im- perfect action that we commonly appropriate the names of theory and action. We may illustrate this by considering, first, cases of manifestly imperfect action. For instance, a person who is said to be able to do a thing without understanding it generally does the thing, as we say, ' empirically ' or 'mechanically.' One sign that he does it 'empirically'" is that, if the circumstances are changed, he is at sea. He cannot do the thing, because his acquaintance with it is bound up with certain circumstances, and, these being changed, the ' thing ' is changed to him. But this really means that his doing of the thing is imperfect, or that what he does is not the thing but only a fragment of it, — that this ' it ' in its truth involves the new circum- stances. In the same way the ' mechanical ' doing of a thing is not, in the full sense, the doing of that thing, but a partial doing of it, or (if one pleases) not the doing of it. For example, we should all admit that a man who does his duty mechanically does not, in the full sense, do his duty. Now, in the second place, take the other phrase, ' I know it theoretically, but I can't do it.' Here the ' it ' in the first clause has not the same sense as the ' it ' in the second. It is true that the man cannot do the whole thing, but no more does he know the whole thing : he really has the theory of a mere fragment of it. ' Theory ' in common parlance always means such partial knowledge, though in the case of certain subjects the ' theory ' spoken of is much more partial than in the case of others, and therefore is spoken of with contempt. It is curious that OtujjLa with Aristotle meant just the 124 LECTURES ON LOGIC opposite of this partial knowledge ; it meant the full consciousness of the object. Again, what is really meant by the phrase, ' That is true in theory, but it won't hold practically ' ? It seems to imply two different standards of truth, but in reality the 'theory' here again is a merely partial knowledge. When it is said of a statement in Political Economy that it is true in theory, this means that it is true if certain conditions only are considered ; and when it is said that the statement will not hold in practice, this means that it would have to be modified if all the conditions were considered. (2) To come to the antithesis of theory and fact, let us consider the saying, 'All theory is based upon, and derived from, facts '.* This naturally suggests that there is something, called ' the facts,' which we are supposed to know at starting, and that by reflexion or thought we reproduce these facts in a weaker form. If so, it is natural to ask what the value of the theory can be, since it was already contained in the known facts and is only a feeble reproduction of them. The whole fabric of developed knowledge, on this view, would be based on facts more true than itself; and the more we thought, the further we should get from reality. Whereas, in truth, the thought or reflexion which is here mistaken for a continually weaker reproduction, is a progressive activity, advancing from the more limited and isolated to the more connected and full. It is, no doubt, the case that in English we often do give the name of ' thought ' or ' reflexion ' to something which does not deserve the name — to the otiose re- production of parts of some previous experience ; just as 1 [See further, pp. 168-9.] THE VALUE OF THEORY 125 we give the name of imagination to the retention or recovery of some part of a sense-perception. And this ' thought ' or ' reflexion ' certainly has no value : it is the ' pale cast ' of this ' thought ' that ' sicklies o'er the native hue of resolution ' ; and it is this kind of thought that we have in mind when we say, ' Don't think about the thing, but do it.' Yet we admit that imagination — the ima- gination of a poet, for example — is not merely repro- ductive, but productive ; and in the same way genuine thought is productive, originative. It is the gradual discovery of the truth about a fact, the coming to realize the fact more and more. The fact at starting is hardly a fact to us at all ; it becomes more and more a fact as we think ; and it is this genuine ' thought ' that we have in mind when we say, ' Think about the thing, and you will do it.' To study the theory of a thing, then, ought to mean to rethink the thing, and in so doing to recreate it for our- selves ; which is the only way in which the fact can become really the fact for us. To study the theory of knowledge should mean, accordingly, to realize gradually what the fact called knowledge means. The use of lan- guage ; discovery, observation, experimentation ; reason- ing, judging, proof ; force, space, time ; causation, subject, object — these are all facts, parts (to speak roughly) of the great fact called knowledge. For a man to realize something of what is implied in this fact assuredly has its value or ' use.' It means that he is so far better off, has more in him, is more in contact with reality. And as reality is one, and all truths are ultimately connected, a person who is in a truer state of mind about one part of reality, is so far in a more favourable position for understanding any other part. 126 LECTURES ON LOGIC ' Philosophiren,' says Novalis, ' ist clephlegmatisiren, vivificiren ' ; to philosophize is to get rid of one's phlegm, to acquire a vivid consciousness of some aspect of reality. This is the value of theory or thinking ; but thinking which is not also producing, thinking which leaves experience what it was before, has no value 1 . 1 There is in our use of 'conscious' and 'consciously' an ambiguity somewhat similar to the ambiguity of the words 'thought' or 'reflexion.' It is said that the more unconsciously we do a thing, the better we do it. What is really meant is not that we do the thing better, the more unconscious we are of it; but that we do it better, the more unconscious we are of certain other things which are not it, — e. g. of certain feelings that accompany it, or of other persons looking at us. Or again : we do not do the thing worse for being conscious of it, but because we are only partially conscious of it, exclusively conscious of some limited step in it or aspect of it. SECTION III LANGUAGE AND ITS FUNCTION IN KNOWLEDGE In the widest sense of the term, language (of which word-language is only one form) is anything by which man expresses or ' means ' something. What then is im- plied in ' meaning ' ? That which ' means ' ( r^atVei) is always a sign (a-f/^euu') ; and a sign is something which stands for something else. If there is to be ' meaning/ one thing must suggest, signify, be related to another thing. Man is a creature for whom things have meanings ; his whole world is a world of meanings. No experience or sensation of his, we hear it said, is devoid of meaning. That is, no human experience is isolated, and all human experience is ultimately a kind of language or symbolism. This fact may be put in opposite ways. Man, on the one hand, is privileged to use symbols — a privilege from which spring incalculable consequences, of which litera- ture is only one. He is, on the other hand, compelled to use symbols; and this compulsion is a limitation. All that he is conscious of comes to him through certain ' media,' which are not what they mean. All his think- ing is ' representative ' or ' discursive ' ; one point leads to another ; he gets at everything through something else. While, then, the world to man is a world of language in which nothing is meaningless ; and while his experience 128 LECTURES ON LOGIC is the reading of this world, or the interpretation of this language ; he is yet obliged to approach the meaning by interpreting symbols, he never gets to the end of it, and (in a sense) he never sees things as they are. Language in the narrower sense, then, — language pro- per — being one kind of symbolism, we have to ask, what are its peculiar properties ? A word, as such, is simply a sound or a sight. It is a certain kind of sensation (of sound, colour, shape). To say, therefore, that words have a meaning is to say that certain sounds or sights have come to suggest, firstly, certain other sounds, sights, smells, and the like ; and, secondly, certain further images and thoughts, with ever-growing complexity. So far, a word is on the same level with a flag. Speech has its origin in an instinctive action, but, as soon as it can properly be called speech, it is a conscious action. In varying degrees we exert intelligence and will in using words. Language is thus always being made. We are unfortunately apt to speak as if it were a fixed set of symbols which we have simply to use ; but the use of language is really a recreating of it, and every one modifies his native language a little, or creates a little new meaning ; great authors create a great deal. The question sometimes asked, ' Is it possible to think without language ? ' may mean two very different things. It may mean, (i) 'Is it possible to think without symbols of any kind? ' or (2) 'What should we lose if we had not the particular form of symbolism called speech ? ' The answer to the first question must apparently be, No. To think without symbols would be to think directly, ' intuitively.' It would not be what we call thinking, and would imply that we were always and immediately one with things. All articulate human consciousness is LANGUAGE AND ITS FUNCTION IN KNOWLEDGE 129 consciousness of something through something else. If our experience were literally unsymbolic, if it were what it means, it would not be what we call human consciousness. The second question is a difficult one, but admits of reasonable discussion. We should pro- bably find that people differ more than is supposed in the amount they do with different kinds of symbols. An individual highly organized in a certain direction may be habitually conscious through other symbols than speech, e. g. through music ; and, though we may quarrel as to the sense in which we can apply the word ' thought ' to music, man would be partially dumb without it. There is also the language of gesture, and the expression of thought in action. Speech is the most widely spread form of symbolism, and has the most important practical consequences ; but it does not follow that people who are deficient in the use of it are inarticulate. The Function of Language in Knoivledge. Language may be conveniently considered as an in- strument (1) of expression, (2) of distinction, (3) of communication. For example, we may regard the elementary function of naming from these three points of view. (1) The phenomenon of expression may be observed in a very simple form in an interjection. Physiologically, this, like any other mode of speech, is describable as a reaction on a stimulus. A feeling affects certain nerves, and through them certain muscles, and so issues in a sound. This sound would generally be called the ' expression ' of the feeling. The phrase is however misleading, because it separates the feeling from its VOL. I. K 130 LECTURES ON LOGIC expression in sound, and suggests that we first have the feeling and then express it. It would be truer to say that the expression is the completed feeling ; for the feeling is not fully felt till it is expressed, and in being expressed it is still felt, but in a different way. What the act of expression does is to fix and distinguish it finally ; it then, and then only, becomes a determinate feeling. In the same way the consciousness which we express when we have found the ' right word ' is not the same as our consciousness before we found it ; so that it is not strictly correct to call the word the expression of what we meant before we found it. This remains true of more developed forms of expression ; and, following it out, we may say that what is absolutely unexpressed and inexpressible is nothing. We can only describe it po- tentially and by anticipation. It cannot enter into human life until it has become articulate in some way, though not necessarily in words. What is meant, then, by the contrast between expres- sion and the unexpressed, and by our complaint that language is so imperfectly articulate, and that we mean much moie than we can say? These phrases seem all to indicate the fact that thought is progressive. As soon as consciousness is expressed in a word, that word becomes a fixed sign and enters into the web of human experience. As it is used again and again, it acquires new meaning by entering as an element into new con- texts. Through this extension, by metaphor, simile, and the like, the original consciousness goes on becoming a consciousness of more : but still the word which expresses this enlarged consciousness has, at any given time, a meaning more or less fixed. When then we say that we cannot find words for our meaning, unless this implies LANGUAGE AND ITS FUNCTION IN KNOWLEDGE 131 that our consciousness is too undeveloped to be expressed, it indicates the fact that the words at our command are so fixed in meaning that they would have to be re- created to express our present consciousness, or (to vary the phrase) that this consciousness is potentially more than will go into the known forms of expression. In such a case a word may (very rarely) be invented, or a word may be used in a new sense, or a new combination of words may be found. Our inarticulateness, the in- adequacy of words, thus means here simply the pro- gressiveness of thought and of language, and it would be just as right to blame one's thought for it as to blame one's language 1 . (As there are persons who feel more than they can say, so there are others who say more than they feel, and use sham rhetoric and the like. That is, they use words which, if taken in their full sense, mean more than is present in the consciousness of the persons using them. This phenomenon, like the other, arises from the contrast between the fixity of language and the fluctuation of human consciousness.) We are sometimes told that language becomes less expressive as it becomes more civilized. This is true if it means that what primitive language expresses is very simple, elementary, ?nd obvious, and that therefore primitive language bears its meaning on its face. But the language of a great writer is in reality infinitely more expressive than primitive language ; the amount ex- pressed by it is infinitely greater. Compare, for instance, the ' original ' meaning of ' spirit ' with the meaning of the word as it is used by a religious genius or a great philosopher. The true reason why ' civilized ' words 1 [For, as the preceding sentence implies, the extension of conscious- ness is expressible through a modification of language.] K 3 132 LECTURES ON LOGIC are inexpressive to us is, generally, that we are unable to realize the fullness of their complex meanings. It is often said, again, that the highest truths are in- expressible, or perhaps that they are unknowable, and inaccessible to reason, though not to ' faith.' Doubtless to every thoughtful man the consciousness is always present that his utmost reach of thought is limited ; and we may say in this sense that there is always a truth beyond us and inexpressible by us, at which we have to try to get. But we are apt to treat this truth as if it were expressible, and indeed actually expressed as a truth of ' faith,' and then to contrast it with some other expressed truth. This has often happened in the history of thought. It is dangerous to imply that there is some virtue in being inexpressible ; the corollary would be that the less we think definitely, the better. Inarticulateness often comes from indolence : we will not take the trouble to mean what we might. In so far as words are really expressive, they are con- sciousness in a certain form which we call articulate, and do not need to be contrasted with anything of which they are the expression. We are not definitely conscious till we use the words. But language is always ceasing to be expressive, in various degrees, ceasing, that is, to mean all that it ought to mean. We should try to recover its expressiveness. The most civilized language should be as direct an expression of consciousness as the simplest interjection ; but it is only to great writers and speakers that it is so. (2) A second main function of language is that of distinction. To distinguish is to be distinctly conscious. We are apt to suppose that first there is a certain con- sciousness, and that then we distinguish it. But this LANGUAGE AND ITS FUNCTION IN KNOWLEDGE 133 is not so: in the act of distinguishing something we are for the first time distinctly conscious of it. The act of distinguishing has also been represented as the act of arresting the flux of consciousness, or as an act of attention ; but, here again, we must not suppose that first there is x, and then we attend to it : x exists for the first time in the act of attention. If we say then that naming is distinguishing or attending (though it is of course possible to distinguish without naming), we must beware of thinking that we first have the consciousness and then name it. This is true, indeed, in the sense that any particular act of naming is preceded by un-named or differently named consciousnesses ; but the consciousness which is now named is this consciousness, which reaches its specific character in the act of being named. The man who first names a thing may be said, there- fore, to give that thing its first existence in the human world. Such first naming is found now in comparatively rare instances ; for example, in science, when the new name implies that a new fact has been experienced. But to a certain extent we all make names in learning them. For, when we learn what a thing is called, what is it that we really do ? We fix a certain consciousness in a certain other consciousness (a sound) ; and with this the con- sciousness has passed into a different stage. How is this stage different? What has happened to the consciousness, the thing, in being named? In the first place we have given it a more permanent position in our experience, and have made it more easily recognizable. Secondly, each time it is recognized it takes a fresh meaning, gets more ' distinct.' It stands out more dis- tinctly from a certain background of consciousness, of which it is a modification ; as, for instance, the distinct 134 LECTURES ON LOGIC consciousness of straightness implies a more general consciousness of direction, of which straightness is one distinct form. It is thus, again, more and more com- pared with and differentiated from other things. That is, thirdly, it gets more ' classified.' All classification is a development of the elementary act of distinction, and every name is the germ of a classification. For all classification is arranging experiences according as< they exhibit a certain identity in various ways ; and to name is to identify. As in regard to expression, so in regard to the function of distinction, reproaches are constantly brought against language. On the one hand it is said, ' How poor lan- guage is ! How very few distinctions it recognizes ! ' On the other hand it is said, ' How superficial, needless, and merely verbal, are many of the distinctions expressed in language ! ' As to these complaints we may remark, first, that the poverty of language is our fault, not the fault of language. Words are symbols made by us, but we come to look upon them as mysterious agencies, under whose power we are. If a man says he is conscious of a thousand distinctions unrecognized by language, let him prove it by giving names to them. (Not that the number of words in a language or in a book is more than a very partial guide to the wealth or poverty of the nation's or the individual's experience.) Secondly, as to ' verbal distinctions,' it may be observed that these are not mere distinctions of words, for the only distinctions of words as such are distinctions of sound or shape. By ' verbal ' or by ' mere words ' we mean really that the words are being used in partial meanings instead of in their full meanings. One should beware of the antithesis of words and things ; it really is a distinction between LANGUAGE AND ITS FUNCTION IN KNOWLEDGE 135 the less full and the more full meanings of words. If wc all tend to become the 'victims of words,' the corollary is that we should mean something by our words, and know what we mean. Wc cannot get over the difficulty by blaming language or declining to use it. (3) Language, thirdly, is an instrument or medium of communication. ' Communication ' implies two beings, otherwise different, which meet or identify themselves in a certain respect (the ' medium ' of communication). Ap- plying this to language, we must observe that the two beings need not be two different people. There is no real difference between language, as a means of com- munication with self, and language as a means of communication with others. Plato's description of thought as a 'dialogue of the soul with itself is not fanciful. The act of naming, for example, may be re- presented as a saying to oneself, ' This shall mean that,' * I understand that by this,' ' When this recurs, I (being then partly a different I) shall understand myself in using this word, or again shall find myself in what is different.' If there is a mystery in two people under- standing one another, there is the same mystery in ' I ' being the same at two different times and understanding itself. And, if language is ' conventional ' or dependent on a mutual understanding (Kara as dis- tinguished, for example, from the special laws of spatial thought or economic thought ? The answers to these questions should give us something that is involved in all objects and all thought, that type of objectivity and of thinking which will be the same everywhere. And these questions will be equivalent to the question, What is a concept as such? if we bear in mind that this is FORMAL LOGIC 149 to mean for us, What is the simplest form of experience regarded as a self-contained, independent unity ? To our question many answers have been given. (a) Greek philosophy answers, Everything is a one in many ; this is the simplest and most abstract formulation of being ; whatever else being may involve, it involves at least this. (J?) It is much the same when a modern philosopher answers, The most elementary consciousness which can possibly become knowledge is a consciousness of identity in difference or of differentiated identity. It is difficult to realize a consciousness so abstract, but a concrete example may help us. If we take an act of attention, we shall agree that it involves a double con- sciousness, a consciousness of having changed from some- thing to something. The moment I am conscious of A I am conscious of it as a change from B, my previous consciousness (or unconsciousness, for it makes no dif- ference to the point) ; B has become^, or rather BA ; or I am conscious of A as the same as B with a difference. Definite consciousness is always a consciousness of change ; an absolutely uniform consciousness would be no con- sciousness ; all consciousness is consciousness of dif- ferentiated identity, or of a many in one. (e) Another way of formulating the activity of thought is to say that all thought implies synthesis. In the most elementary consciousness there is a holding together of two things at least — of myself as I was then, and myself as I am now. It is evident that these three answers to our question are merely different ways of stating the same fact. And it is worth while to observe that a famous conclusion from the fact thus variously stated is the principle that everything is what it is in and through its difference from another ; that not-being or ' otherness ' (Plato's Sophist) is the 150 LECTURES ON LOGIC inseparable concomitant of being ; that ' omnis determi- natio est negatio,' or everything is determined by the exclusion of something else (Spinoza) ; that therefore everything is and is not at the same moment. These considerations will help us to see the true signifi- cance of Formal Logic, and of those ' laws of thought' of which it speaks. Formal logic, as a science, has for its subject-matter being (or consciousness) where it is at its minimum. It takes account of things simply in so far as we can predicate of them ' being ' and ' not-being,' ' all ' and ' some.' Its question is : Suppose I know no more than that a thing is what it is and not something else, and that ' all ' is more than ' some,' what can I infer from this knowledge ? Formal logic is therefore the most abstract of all sciences ; it is more abstract even than arithmetic, for arithmetic considers also the ' count- ability ' of things, while geometry goes further still. In the same way, the laws of thought considered in formal logic are the most abstract laws possible : they are the ways in which the mind must act if it is to think at all. For instance, the law of Identity means that, if I am to be definitely conscious of anything, I must at least be able to identify, to say that A is A. The law of Contradiction, which is only the other side of this law, means that human experience would fall to the ground, unless we could say, If A is A, A is not not-^L The law of Excluded Middle, which says that, if I have thought of the world simply as A and not- A, everything I am con- scious of is one or the other, is not a third law, but a corollary of these. By using the word ' laws ' we do not imply that they are something externally imposed on the mind ; but we imply that these are the ways in which the mind acts, and must act, if it is to be a mind. FORMAL LOGIC 151 These laws are usually called by formal logicians laws of pure thought ; but the expression is objectionable, for it suggests the false idea that there is some difference of kind between ' pure ' thought and thought as it enters, for example, into chemistry. In reality, ' pure ' thought differs from other thinking in being the most elementary thinking possible, and it differs in no other way ; all thinking is some kind of identification of differences or differentiation of identities. It is quite true that the results of this elementary thinking have extreme certitude, and the reason is that elementary thinking is extremely simple, while every fresh condition brings a fresh pos- sibility of error ; the reason is not that the elementary thinking is ' pure,' while other thinking involves an appeal to 'experience.' It is sometimes said that, as soon as a proposition is set forth which involves nothing but the laws of Identity and Contradiction, its truth is self-evident and does not depend on ' experience,' by which is meant something outside the particular pro- position. But every truth, so far as it is seen to be true, is so far self-evident ; and in another sense of 'experience,' the simplest truths imply an appeal to experience just as much as any others. A man who follows the reasoning of Euclid reasons, in one sense, without appealing to experience ; but he is, all the time, ' experiencing ' a certain thing called space, and each new step in the reasoning is a new experience of space. The experience of space is so simple and universal, and we get it so easily, that we are apt to speak as if it were different from other kinds of experience, and as if the truths of geometry had some different ground of belief from other truths. But, while the truths of geometry are not derived from any other experience than that of space, they 152 LECTURES ON LOGIC express the experience of space ; and this differs from certain other kinds of experience merely in its simplicity. In the same way the laws of Identity and Contradic- tion express an experience, though an experience of a still more simple kind ; and they are truths of ex- perience just as much as are the truths of chemistry. Certainly they are not ' derived from experience ' in the sense of being derived from some other experience ; for to say that is to say something quite unmeaning, since without experience of identity and difference there is no experience at all. To say, as some formal logicians do, that the results of formal logic involve no appeal to experience is either false or tautologous \ The subject-matter of formal logic, then, is experience, or the nature of things, at its minimum. Its thinking, therefore, is in the highest degree abstract, and for this reason formal logic is well fitted to be a mental gymnastic, and to hold a place like that of algebra in education. No doubt the text-books of formal logic are apt to speak of it as though it were ' mere ' thinking and not connected with things at all ; but it is really a statement of what is most elementary in objects, and therefore the laws of thought are, so far, also laws of things. 1 [On experience, see Note A.] SECTION VI THE CONCEPT AS UNIVERSAL, PARTICULAR, INDIVIDUAL We have seen that the analysis of knowledge brings us, if we consider the matter on the ' objective ' side, to being as such, and that this involves identity and difference ; and, again, that if we consider knowledge on the ' subjective ' side we reach an activity of thought which consists in identifying and distinguishing. In con- nexion with this account of the simplest experience, or of conception as such, we may enquire into the meaning of the terms universal, particular, and individual. The simplest conception we can possibly form may be described by the word ' something.' We should identify it by calling it 'this.' In identifying it thus we ipso facto distinguish it from ' that ' ; it is ' this not that.' The con- ception ' this not that ' further implies something in which both ' this ' and ' that ' partake, the medium in which they both are and of which they are different forms. Here we have the germs of universal, particular, and individual. The universal is the medium or common nature in which both ' this ' and ' that ' partake, and of which they are distinct forms. ' This ' is a particular ; it is this medium in a partial form ; partial, because it excludes ' that,' which is another partial form of the common element. Thirdly, if we wish to know fully what ' this ' is, we can only do so by discovering all 154 LECTURES ON LOGIC its differences from, and resemblances to, ' that ' : here we should have the individuality of 'this.' Such seems to be the simplest and truest meaning of the three words. Every concept, as a one of (or in) many, is universal, particular, and individual. For ex- ample, take the concept of triangle. It is universal *, for it may assume a number of different forms (equilateral, isosceles, &c), or is capable of further specification. It is particular, for it is a specific form of something more genera] (figure) and excludes other specific forms of it. It is individual, for it is this unique form of figure re- garded as complete and self-contained, its individuality being its whole nature, or what would be described in a true definition of it. Thus the same thing is at once uni- versal, particular, and individual. Every concept admits of further specification, and therefore is universal ; every concept is the specification of something more general, and therefore is particular ; every concept is exactly what it is, and therefore is individual. These properties do not exclude each other, but each implies the others. Universal and Particular. We may now consider certain important ways in which the relations of the universal and particular have been regarded. i . The universal, or the concept as universal, has been regarded as the capability or potentiality of assuming certain particular forms. Thus Aristotle sometimes re- presents the universal as the potentiality or v\^ of its particulars, the yevos as the ' matter ' of the species. This 1 'The universal triangle,' or, better, 'the triangle regarded univer- sally,' is not the same as ' the universal of triangle.' ' The universal of triangle ' is figure, just as triangle is ' the universal of isosceles triangle. CONCEPT UNIVERSAL, PARTICULAR, INDIVIDUAL 155 expresses the important truth that a universal is the universal of some particular, and a particular the par- ticular of some universal, i.e. that there must be a real continuity between the two. Thus a red triangle may be offered as an instance of a particular triangle, but in strictness it is not a particular triangle ; for redness is not a differentiation of triangularity, but of something else. The truth expressed in this phrase of Aristotle's is of special importance in regard to classification. 2. The universal has been called the kolvov of the particulars, that which is common to them all and enters into them all. This phrase suggests the idea that the universal is arrived at by leaving out the particularity of the particulars ; and with this idea is connected the doctrine that universal conceptions are obtained by abstraction. There is in this both truth and untruth. In what sense is it true that we leave out the particu- larities in order to arrive at the universal? If we take our former instance, particular triangles will be equi- lateral, isosceles, scalene triangles. Now, in order to arrive at the concept of triangle as such, we cannot absolutely leave otit the particular properties of equi- lateral, isosceles, and scalene triangles ; for if we did we should be left not with triangularity, but with nothing at all ; the equilaterality of an equilateral triangle is in- separable from its triangularity. But we can attend exclusively to the fact of triangularity, the fact of space contained in three straight lines ; a fact which may exist under various conditions (equilateral, &c), and which never exists except under certain conditions. To this we can attend, and this we can retain as something ' com- mon ' to all particular triangles. Every triangle is par- ticular ; but triangularity, the ( common ' or universal, 156 LECTURES ON LOGIC is not a mere abstraction, it is something which exists in all particulars. Like ' our common humanity ' it is that in which all its particulars meet ; they are absolutely inseparable from it, and it from them. 3. The universal is said to express what is essential in the particulars. This again may be taken in a true sense or in a false. Mill protests against an ' exploded realism ' which insists on certain ' essences ' as the sole matter of importance, and opposes to them as unessential all the characteristic properties of things. And, if this doctrine was ever really held, Mill's protest would certainly be right. But, when the universal is said to be or to express the essential, what is regarded as unessential is that which is irrelevant, e.g. the redness of a triangle. So again with ' our common humanity ' : to realize this, one must disregard many things usually associated with humanity. For example, in discussions about slavery, it is rightly urged that it does not matter whether a man is black or white, but that the essential thing is, perhaps, the pos- session of reason, or the capacity of forming a society. This essence is the universal, compared with which certain differences are irrelevant ; and, although people will always differ more or less as to what is essential and what irrelevant, the distinction itself is a sound one. It is a misunderstanding of it that leads to that idea of an 'essence 5 from which everything really characteristic is omitted. 4. The universal is said to contain or include its par- ticulars. This, of course, is a spatial metaphor, and we always have to guard against the influence of spatial associations. But the metaphor helps some minds to realize the truth, and it is convenient as bringing out the fact that particulars, while excluding one another, also CONCEPT UNIVERSAL, PARTICULAR, INDIVIDUAL 157 make up, or arc included in, one whole. To say, for example, that humanity includes all men may help one to realize the truth that, though men exclude one another, they still form a unity. This formula is connected with that which represents the universal as the whole, of which the particulars are parts. ' Universal ' is /ca0' oKov, that which is true of something as a whole. To nad' 6'Aou is ' universum,' a thing taken in its totality. And so 'particular' is to Kara /me'pos or kv ixipzi, a thing taken in a partial sense. The whole is more than the part; and so the universal (e.g. tri- angularity, or triangle as universal) is said to be more, or to have more in it, than the particular (e.g. isosceles triangle). This is so, or is not so, according as you understand 'triangle' and 'isosceles triangle.' If you mean by 'triangle' simply and solely the conception of a space included in three straight lines, clearly there is less in ' triangle ' than in ' isosceles triangle,' and every particularity assumed by ' triangle' adds something to its concreteness. But, if you mean by ' triangle ' the conception, or holding together in the mind, of all the possibilities implied in a space included in three straight lines, there is more in 'tri- angle' than in ' isosceles triangle,' for the latter is 'triangle ' under limitations, or in a partial sense. This is what Aristotle meant by h> /ue'pei ; and if we guard against quantitative associations this is an instructive point of view. To repeat, any whole may be regarded either in its full meaning as containing all its parts, or as a sort of outline waiting to be filled up. In the latter sense we speak of ' triangle ' as a universal containing less than any of its particulars (an ' abstract universal '). So, again, 158 LECTURES ON LOGIC any part of a whole may be regarded either as implying all the other parts, and therefore implying, ultimately, the whole ; or, in an abstract way, as excluding the other parts. In the latter sense a particular triangle is only part of the whole 'triangle,' or is triangle under limitations. General Concepts and Generalization. From the point of view we have taken, there would seem to be no reason for talking of universal or general concepts as if they were a separate class, and of particular and individual concepts as if they were two other separate classes. Every concept is general, particular, and in- dividual. Every concept is general because it may apply to other cases besides the one you happen to have in mind. Still, ' general concepts ' are constantly spoken of, in implied contrast with concepts that are not general. And, further, 'general' and 'generality' are often used in a bad sense, as when it is said, ' That is a mere generality,' or ' So and so deals in vague generalities.' This de- preciatory remark cannot mean merely that the person says what is true in a great variety of circumstances, and that his concept is very general in this sense. It means that he realizes the concept only to a small extent, that he does not realize nearly all of the circumstances to which it applies, but lumps together under it things which are quite distinct ; that he has not thought out the meaning of the concept. A concept being the result of an act or acts of thought, the generality of a concept will be simply that in it which is due to the act of generalization. To generalize means, in the simplest sense, to see that A is true in other CONCEPT UNIVERSAL, PARTICULAR, INDIVIDUAL 159 cases than the present case, in B, C, and D. To put it technically, all generalization is, ultimately, seeing a cer- tain identity running through certain differences ; and a concept is general in so far as it is the result of this generalization. A good generalize r is one who sees identities under differences which disguise them from most people ; he is Plato's (tvvotttlkos. But we may generalize badly. We may see, for instance, that A holds good in B, C, D, but may overlook important differences in B, C, D. In such a case our generalization will be rash ; though true as far as it goes, it will be false because, from the differences being overlooked, identities will be inferred where they do not exist. But it is impossible to think at all without generalizing; merely to judge 'this is a case of that ' is to generalize ; and to generalize is to use a general concept, which is capable of particular varieties. Individual and Individuality. ' Individuum ' is the translation of amixov, ' indivisible,' a word habitually used in legic by Aristotle to express a certain point of view. Any generic nature — anything considered universally — may be regarded as admitting of particularization. This process of differentiating a uni- versal was represented by Plato and Aristotle as a dividing or cutting up (iqiveiv), so that Plato in the Pliaedrns compares the differentiation of a universal to the organization of a physical body, and a bad reasoner to an unskilful cook who divides the body across the joints. Supposing the process to be carried as far as it can be in a given direction, something will be reached which may be called to 6.toijlov } that which admits of no 160 LECTURES ON LOGIC further division ; that which is not the possibility of several ; that of which there is only one. Where this point is reached — where in the process something is arrived at which, for the purpose in question, is fully differentiated and therefore individual, depends upon the purpose in question ; and therefore the word individual is extremely ambiguous. Thus the universal ' figure ' may be differentiated into rectilinear and curvi- linear, and the triangle, as the simplest form of recti- linear figure, may be taken as individual. But this individual again for another purpose may be divided into equilateral, isosceles, and scalene. That is, you may ' in- dividualize ' any concept in various degrees. All we can say in the abstract is that a concept is individual when it is, or is regarded as being, incapable of further dif- ferentiation, or as the complete differentiation (for the purpose in question) of a certain universal. Thus, if we start with the idea of the universal as that which contains its differences merely implicitly, any individual of this abstract universal will contain more than it, and that which is most individual in the series will be the fully developed or realized universal. In this sense we often use ' individuality.' The ' indivi- duality ' of a thing is that which makes it what it is, its complete nature, that which you would state if you were able to define it. A ' great individuality ' is a person in whom the universal humanity has reached a very high degree of development or differentiation ; one who concentrates in himself a great deal of human nature; a person therefore of many sides, who is very ' represen- tative ' and touches others at innumerable points. On the other hand the word ' individual ' has also associations of the very opposite kind. If we look at the CONCEPT UNIVERSAL, PARTICULAR, INDIVIDUAL 161 universal as a whole formed by the composition of ele- ments, and if we break it up into these elements, we arrive at last at elements incapable of further division, or arofia. These ultimate atoms are, in this sense, in- dividuals ; but, instead of being- the universal as most fully qualified, these individuals contain the minimum of qualification or character. The individuality of an ' atom ' is the least individuality we can speak of. And so we say of a person who has no individuality, 'he is a mere atom ' ; and ' a mere individual ' is one whose personality is supposed to be reduced to the fact that he is just one in a crowd, only a unit, which is next to being a cipher. Thus the word ' individual ' is applied at opposite poles, and signifies both the greatest and the least amount of character or 'individuality.' The reason of this, and of the confusion that arises from it, is that the process of differentiating or individualizing may be conducted to any point we like, and may be considered to stop at any point we like. Different people individualize up to different stages, and the associations we connect with the word individual depend en the point at which the process is generally understood to stop. It may stop at the first differentiation of the simplest universal: 'something' becomes ' this,' and attains a little individuality, the individuality of ' this ' consisting in being ' not that.' Advance a step and localize ' this ' in space, and it be- comes 'this here'; it is somewhat more individualized, for it is ' not that there.' To express this low degree of individuality we might coin an Aristotelian formula robe tI t.ov kclI vvv; and, again, the individuality implied by our English phrase ' mere individual ' is the smallest amount that will serve to distinguish one from another. VOL. I. M i62 LECTURES ON LOGIC Still this may be considered an individuality ; that is, we may stop the process of individualization at this point. Just as the process may be stopped at various points, so it may be conducted on various principles ; and thus again the individuality of an object will be said by different people to consist in different things. Human nature, for example, is so complicated that perhaps no two persons would exactly agree as to that in which the individuality of man consists. Still more would two of us differ about the individuality of some particular man whom we both happened to know, because each of us would consider a different thing in the man the most important and interesting thing about him. And in the same way ' the individual ' in logic books has various senses, according as various properties are regarded as constituting individuality. We may bring out still further in the following way the opposite senses which attach to the words ' individual ' and 'individuality.' If we insist on asking the question, What is the true individuality of a thing? we must answer, All that the generic nature in question has in it to become in that particular form. The true individuality of man is everything of which human nature is capable. But no man, no ' individual,' is, in this sense of the word K truly individual. ' Individual ' accordingly comes to be used in the sense of ' particular.' In calling a man ' in- dividual ' we imply his limitations, and think as much of what he excludes as of what he includes. ' Individualism' again has come to be the regular word to designate the attitude of men in their mutual exclusiveness ; an ' in- dividualistic ' theory is one which regards men as mutually exclusive atoms, and endeavours to explain society by showing it to result from a combination of such atoms. CONCEPT UNIVERSAL, PARTICULAR, INDIVIDUAL 163 No antithesis is more common than that between the community and the individual. Yet if it is true that the community is nothing but a collection of individuals, and that the individual is merely that which goes to make up a community, it seems strange that the antithesis should be able to arise, and that controversies should be waged regarding the respective rights of the two. The main reason is that, as we have seen, different people ' in- dividualize ' up to such different stages and on such different principles. A person who upholds the ' rights of the individual ' probably does not mean the rights which attach to the merest individuality possible to man, but the rights of a considerably differentiated human being ; and a person who speaks of the community does not mean a collection or whole in the abstract, but a certain body of persons representing definite interests. There is no such thing as an abstract individual ; a person with the minimum of qualification must mean a person who has some standing-ground common to himself and others. And a community, again, is not a com- munity unless it is a one in many, something in which there is a commune quid. So long as the controversy is debated in the abstract, it is a mere beating of the air. It ought always to be made concrete. That is, we ought always to ask what is meant by the ' individual ' spoken of, what amount of individuality he is taken to possess ; and what is the particular commune quid we mean when we talk of the community. It is possible then to com- pare this commune quid with the rights in question, and to ask whether it is of such value that it ought, or ought not, to be paramount. To sum up : individuality, as such, is any determinate character which any generic nature has assumed, this M 2 164 LECTURES ON LOGIC character being the point at which you choose to stop in the process of differentiation. Hence, in logic, indi- viduality may be, and has been, used in two chief ways, to express either (i) the minimum of differentiation, what is just enough to distinguish one from another ; or (2) the maximum of qualification, the most differentiated nature, what is contained in the full definition of a thing, the to tC i]v thai, which is also the ovala of a thing l . 1 [Compare the remarks entitled ' Individuality ' in the Miscellaneous Papers.'] SECTION VII CONCEPTION AND PERCEPTION, MEDIATE AND IMMEDIATE APPREHENSION So far we have used ' concept ' to mean any definite matter of consciousness ; any consciousness of ' this ' as a form of 'that,' and as, therefore, partly the same as ' that.' But the terms ' conception,' ' concept,' ' conceive,' are also used in specific senses and in contrast with other terms. Before we proceed with our discussion of con- ception in its wider meaning, it will be well to glance at some of these antitheses. Concept and Percept. What is the point of the distinction often made between conception and perception ? Every act of perception is really also an act of conception, in the sense we have hitherto given to the latter word, for a perception is, a holding together in the mind. But, if we wish to assign the two words to different modes of 'holding together,' the name perception may be given to any distinct con- sciousness of objects which involves the action of one or more of the senses, whereas conception would stand for that distinct consciousness of objects which excludes, or at least does not imply, any direct action of the senses. Thus, in the case of any object, part of the nature of which is to be sensible, we may talk of perception and con- ception as distinct. The perception of a tree, for example, 166 LECTURES ON LOGIC will be our consciousness of the tree when we are actually in its presence and see it. The conception of it will be our consciousness of the tree when we go away and think of it. This conception may be complete or incomplete in various degrees. It is possible that a person, in thinking of a tree, might realize its sensible qualities as vividly as in actually looking at it ; and in that case there would be no assignable or ' practical ' difference between the con- ception and the perception of the tree. Doubtless in most cases where we are said to think of a thing we leave out elements which are present in perception. (We are of course aware of this ; if we are not aware of it, we are the victims of illusion.) Still a full conception of a thing means realizing the whole thing ; and as, in the case of the tree, reflexion shows that the experience of it implies visibility, tangibility, and the like, a reflecting person includes in his conception of the tree the fact that under certain conditions he would see it and touch it. In the same way a man with unusual powers of conception is one who has a great power of realizing what he would experience under certain circumstances, while most of us have to refresh our conceptions constantly. Thus there is no absolute line between perception and conception. A full conception of a perceptible thing, in the sense of a thoroughly definite consciousness of it, would imply its perceptibility, as well as a great deal besides. This truth is obscured by the meaning often given to conception. Many people understand by the word a partial and faded idea of a thing, and this is what they contrast with perception. In the same way we find it stated that thoughts or conceptions are reproduced sen- sations ; sensations which have lost their original fresh- CONCEPTION AND PERCEPTION 167 ness and force 1 i but have been retained by memory, reproduced by imagination, recombined by thought. There is obviously some truth in this account, but it is not an adequate or instructive account ; for to call con- ception a fainter or less clear reproduction of sensation or perception is to omit its differentia. It would be more instructive to say that an experience becomes more a con- ception, and less a mere perception, the wider, the more complex, and the more connected it becomes. In con- ception perceptions are not eliminated, but are carried on into ever-widening contexts. Conception, one may say, is perception connected with other perceptions. If this were not so, in passing from perception to conception we should be like a man who, in order to understand a 1 [Some remarks were made at this point on the idea that a concep- tion has less force or intensity than a sensation or sense-perception. These remarks seem to be rather of the nature of a note made in passing ; but their drift would appear to be somewhat as follows : — There is no doubt of the fact that what I feel (my -naOos) when I see or hear something is often much more intense than what I feel when I realize an abstract truth. But we must not confuse intensity of sensitive affection with degree of reality or truth. Our impressibility is no gauge of truth (though doubtless it is important as far as possible to make ourselves impressionable by the truest truth). The man who sees an illuminated turnip and takes it for a ghost may die of fright ; and that proves the intensity of his naOos, but it does not prove the truth of his perception. We might, indeed, if we chose, speak of an intensity of thought, conception, knowledge, just as we do of an intensity of feeling; and there is this analogy between them, that the intensity in either case can only be measured by that which, in the one case, it enables a man to do, and in the other case moves him to do. But then the intensity of feeling and the intensity of thought may be in inverse ratio. A person may, and often does, realize a truth intensely without feeling at all intensely ; and, though a relatively simple sensation may move intensely at the moment, its intensity with respect to truth or knowledge is trifling ; i. e. the knowledge got through it would enable a man to do extremely little. Observe also that intensity of conviction is not intensity of thought nor any test of truth; a madman's conviction may be most intense.] i68 LECTURES ON LOGIC chapter, forgets all the particular ideas in it. And no doubt what are often called our ' general conceptions ' are very much of the nature of that general meaning of a book which we say we retain, though we remember hardly any of the details. This general meaning is cnly a fragment of the meaning of the book, and to complete it we should have to retraverse the details. In like manner our ' general conceptions,' so called, are but fragmentary and sketchy pieces of experience, which have to be revivified by recourse to sensation. If we choose (as many writers do) to confine the word ' con- ception ' to such faded fragments, there is no objection to this use. In that case, however, we must remember that the word is not equivalent to ' conception ' in the sense we attach to it in these lectures, as the holding together of many particulars of experience. (The antithesis of conception and perception, as gene- rally used, corresponds to some extent with the wider antithesis of theory and fact, already touched on in an earlier lecture. In one sense there can be no antithesis of theory and fact. If a theory is the expression of any truth, it corresponds to some fact ; and there is no fact which does not imply a theory, simple or complicated. In a certain sense, however, ' mere theory ' and ' mere fact,' a ' mere theorist ' and a ' mere empiricist,' may be contrasted. A ' mere theory ' is never the expression of a non- entity. The wildest theories express some facts, or they would not do the mischief they do. When anyone speaks of a mere theory he will always be found to mean a par- tial statement of something which he knows more fully, or thinks capable of being known and treated more fully. It is a conception of a partial fact, awaiting further THEORY AND FACT 169 experience, like a hypothesis, which also is never abso- lutely baseless. A ' mere empiricist,' again, is never a person without any theory ; every one must connect his facts a little. A mere empiricist is a man who, comparatively, sees little connexion between the facts he knows. His facts, one may say, are like isolated words, which have little meaning ; and he is like a man who knows by heart a great many words out of a dictionary, but who cannot make a sentence. A ' mere fact ' then is one in which you assume there is more meaning, more ' conception,' than is seen in it by the person to whom it is a mere fact. A common way of attempting to express the difference between theory and fact is to say that a theory only exists in somebody's mind. The meaning intended is that facts are true independently of the whims and fancies of this or that person ; but the expression is most un- fortunate, since it suggests that a fact is a fact because it exists in nobody's mind. In that case it would be a fact for nobody. As a thing becomes more true, it does not withdraw itself from people's minds ; rather, the more it becomes an essential and inseparable part of people's minds, the more true it is. Between theory and fact one can make no distinction other than that of less and greater connectedness and completeness.) Intuition and Conception. Immediate and Mediate. Presentative and Representative. These are other forms of the antithesis which we have been considering. ' Intuition ' means literally the act of looking at something. The word is used in two important ways in philosophy. It is used (a) as the equivalent of 170 LECTURES ON LOGIC AnscJiauwig, as employed by Kant ; and in this sense it ought to mean a consciousness of which the form is either spatial or temporal or both, as contrasted with any consciousness of which the form is neither spatial nor temporal. Though ' intuition ' is the more literal trans- lation of Anschauung, the meaning of the latter term is, on the whole, better rendered by ' perception.' (b) More generally, ' intuition ' is used to signify a direct or im- mediate apprehension. To see intuitively that a thing is true does not, indeed, mean — as it is sometimes supposed to do — that I see it instantaneously or by a mere glance of the mind ; but it means that I see its truth without being able to give any reason for it, or that my per- ception is ' immediate.' Let us consider more fully what ' immediate ' and ' mediate ' can signify. An immediate consciousness would be one that is not held through the medium of some other consciousness. If I think A is A because it is B, B is a medium between my mind and A : I get at A through B. Any reason for a truth is a medium, a ixeaw, between something and something else ; and, the more media are implied in a consciousness, the more mediate is it. Can any perception or other consciousness, then, be immediate in the sense of absolutely simple? We must answer, No. However simple a sensation is, of however little it is the sensation, it is the sensation of something. If we call it A, it is felt through, or as, something else, B. Every sensation which is an element in experience refers to something else, from which it is distinct, or of which it is a particular form ; it is symbolic, it means something besides itself; and therefore it is mediate. There is, indeed, a sense in which we can speak of a sensation as though it had no meaning, no reference MEDIATE AND IMMEDIATE APPREHENSION 171 beyond itself. We can describe it as an occurrence which comes and goes, and we can speak of the mind as a series of such occurrences. But in speaking thus we do not speak of the sensation as an element in in- telligent experience. In experience, consciousnesses do not simply come and go, they come and go for me ; and it is impossible for them in such experience to be dis- connected units. The moment a sensation is fixed, it has some connexion, some meaning, and is therefore to some extent mediate. There is then no absolutely immediate apprehension. The distinction of immediate and mediate is a relative one. A very immediate sensation should mean a sensa- tion very little mediate, one very little connected with anything else. As the sensation enters as an element into wider and wider wholes, it becomes more mediate. To the ignorant person who stands before the fire and says he feels hot, the consciousness of heat is very much more ' immediate ' than it is to the man of science, to whom heat is an element in an immense body of connexions, and whose mind in grasping the conception of heat goes through a very large number of media. If we use the word ' intuition,' then, in contrast with conception, ' in- tuition' should only mean to us a relatively immediate apprehension, a less mediate as compared with a more mediate. There is, however, one sense in which not simple sensa- tions only, but every definite piece of consciousness, may truly be called immediate or intuitive — in the sense that it is what it is, and cannot be explained by, or analyzed into, anything which does not contain it. If, for example, a man is told that his perception or conception of ' right ' is derivable from and analyzable into certain quite 172 LECTURES ON LOGIC different conceptions, which have preceded it in the history of his mind or other people's minds, he may in that sense truly answer that his consciousness of right is intuitive. And this is true of any definite consciousness, e.g. his consciousness of ' red.' His consciousness of right or of red may be ' explained ' by tracing its history and showing (truly) that it would not be what it is if certain other consciousnesses had not preceded it ; but he will justly maintain that it is what it is, that it cannot be analyzed into those preceding consciousnesses, and that, after the ' explanation,' both they and it remain what they were before. In this sense his consciousness of right is intuitive ; but then this does not mean anything mysterious, or that everybody is born with this con- sciousness, or that it can be got without effort, practice, or experience. The antithesis of presentative and representative con- sciousness is only another way, and a metaphorical way, of putting the contrast of immediate and mediate. By a presentative consciousness is meant one in which the object is actually present to me, by a representative consciousness one in which an object once present is reproduced. All reproduction implies a medium, and therefore all representative consciousness is mediate. This distinction, again, though convenient, is merely relative. There is no experience in which what is pre- sent is absolutely simple ; but, the further knowledge advances, the more representative consciousness becomes. These antitheses are parallel to those which were formulated by Locke and Hume respectively between sensation and reflexion, and between impression and idea. It would seem to be the case that these dis- tinctions cannot be absolute. It is incorrect to speak SENSATION AND REFLEXION 173 as if there were first a number of disconnected and simple feelings, and as if then thought or reflexion took these and combined them in various ways. There is really a continuous process going on, from the beginning of experience, in which sensation becomes more and more thought, and is more and more modified ; but at no point do we experience a sensation which is absolutely un- related, nor is there any thought of which the elements do not eventually imply a sensitive organism. Hume's language conveys the notion that the most simple ex- periences are somehow more real than what is derived from them ; and this idea, if pressed to its conclusion, implies that, the more we think, the further we get from truth. If, on the other hand, we get at truth more by thinking more, we must say that what is given in sensa- tion is less real, has less of reality in it, than the results of developed thinking. No doubt the prevalent idea that what are called conceptions are comparatively unreal arises from the true observation that most of our ' con- ceptions ' are not the results of developed thinking, but are what Hume represented all thought as being, weaker and more faded reminiscences of fuller ex- periences. But the right corollary of this truth is not that we should take refuge in the most meagre of our experiences and hope to find reality there, but that we should endeavour to realize, to think out, those empty forms which we carry about in our minds under the name of general conceptions. SECTION VIII CONCEIVABILITY AND SENSATION AS TESTS OF TRUTH Conceivability. The import of the word ' conceive ' is that in all rational experience there is a holding together [concipere) of certain elements, a synthesis of elements in a unity ; and every object of experience implies such a synthesis. If we begin with the most elementary conception possible, ' being ' implies at least the synthesis, the distinguishing and holding together, of ' this ' and ' that.' Space implies at least something outside something else, that is, a synthesis of the two ; and time implies the synthesis of ' before ' and ' after.' Leaving such elementary con- ceptions as these, and coming to more concrete things, we find objects commonly analyzed into their properties. A thing, we are told, is the sum of its properties ; at any rate it is the unity of a certain manifold. Now the condition of anything being a unity is that its elements should be compatible or consistent with one another ; and, following this out, we come to the much- disputed principle that conceivability, i.e. the capacity of being held together as a unity of elements, is a test of truth, — that the true is the conceivable. To take simple instances, it would be agreed that it is inconceivable that ' before ' and ' after ' should be the same, or that there should be a time in which there was CONCEIVABILITY AS TEST OF TRUTH 175 no before and after ; or that two straight lines should enclose a space. In these cases it is implied that the thing conceived (time or space) has a definite nature, which includes certain things and excludes other things. Philosophers who have made conceivability a test of truth mean that, the conception of a thing being the clear apprehension of this definite nature, anything inconsistent with this nature, and therefore inconceivable, is impossible, just as anything that can be thought together with this is possible. Thus the question, Is this spatially possible ? must come back to the question, Can I think this con- sistently with what I know of space ? The same test is really applied in more concrete cases, e.g. in the question of the credibility of an asserted fact in history. After all our investigation of evidence we come to the question, Can I think this fact consistently with all that I know of the matter in hand ? The distrust of the idea that con- ceivability is a test of truth is largely due to misunder- standing, and to a failure to realize that the conceivability of a thing is ultimately equivalent to its consistency with the sum of experience. In order to discuss more fully whether the conceivable and the objective are to be identified, let us ask the question, What is the minimum concipibile, the least possible conceivable? and then let us enquire whether this is the same as the least possible object. If so, con- ceivability and objectivity will be found to coincide, at least in the simplest instance. Can we then conceive A to be both A and not-A ? No, we cannot ; and therefore the least conceivable pos- sible may be said to be something which is the same with itself and different from something else. Try to conceive something which does not submit to this condition, and 176 LECTURES ON LOGIC you find that your mind is a blank, and that you are not performing an act of thought at all. If then this is the least conceivable, what is the least objectivity, the least that would make a thing a thing ? Would anything be anything if it were in no two consecutive moments the same with itself, and if it were not different from every- thing else ? No, it would be nothing. (This is the germ of the conception of substance.) At this stage, then, it would seem that the thinkable and the objective cannot be dis- tinguished. They are subject to one and the same condition or law, and must conform to it. The law of Identity is the expression of this condition ; or rather it is the condition of there being any thought at all, and of there being any thing at all. Again, we cannot conceive or have an experience unless there is some continuity in our experiences ; we cannot conceive A as absolutely independent of B, and yet con- ceive A and B as both objects. And to say that an object that stood in no relation to anything else would be no object, would be nothing, is simply to say this in other words. The principle of causality is the developed ex- pression of this truth, and therefore there is no difference between saying that it is a law or condition of experience or conceivability, and saying that it is a law or con- dition of objectivity. Thus we must beware of supposing that first there are things identical in difference, and that then we conceive them ; to conceive or think is to identify in difference, and a thing is a determinate matter of consciousness or it is nothing. So with causality ; there are not first causes and effects, and then our conceptions of them ; to think causally is to connect things as somehow affecting one another and forming one world. All experience — CONCEIVABILITY AS TEST OF TRUTH 177 conceivability at its least, and objectivity at its least — implies a certain synthesis of diverse elements. Going further, taking thought or the world in more developed stages, we have seen that space and time also imply syntheses of parts. And it makes no difference whether we say that each of these objects has a certain nature of its own and therefore certain laws of its own, or whether we say that we cannot conceive of space or of time except in certain ways ; so that, instead of saying that we think or conceive of space or time, we might just as accurately talk of our thinking spatially or temporally. The conditions of space and time are not one thing for the world and another thing for our minds. To say that it is a law of space that two straight lines cannot enclose a space, is exactly the same as saying that we cannot think of two straight lines as enclosing a space. To say that the nature of space imposes this inability on our minds is only to restate the fact more metaphorically. The laws of space are equally laws of thought, though they are not commonly called so. The same thing is true when we advance to the objects with which the physicist, or the chemist, or the biologist, deals. These objects involve further syntheses beyond that of space, or certain laws in addition to the laws of space. These laws again are simply the expression of the natures of the objects ; but we might just as well call them the laws of thought as it is concerned with those objects, the laws of thinking physically or chemically or biologically. Going still further, we may take the world as it is for aesthetic or for moral science. Objects here are qualified in still more complex ways, or involve many new syntheses. Take a line as it enters first into a triangle, VOL. I. N 178 LECTURES ON LOGIC then into a crystal, and then into a picture, and you see that at each stage it belongs to an object more complex than the last. Each of these objects, however, has a nature and laws of its own to which the line must con- form. And here again the laws of the aesthetic object are equally laws of our thinking aesthetically ; or there is, as we say, a logic of art, as also of morality. For instance, when we say that it is inconceivable that the same act should be perfectly honourable and perfectly dishonourable, i.e. that we cannot hold the two things together in the mind, we imply that morality has prin- ciples or laws which are alike laws of its nature and of conceivability. It may be answered that the inconceiv- ability would not be the same to a person who had not our moral experience, but it is equally true that it is only to a person who has our experience of space that our spatial conceivabilities and inconceivabilities would be conceivable and inconceivable. Or take the case of art : an artist might say, 'These two colours, or these two lines, cannot be thus combined, for they contradict one another ' ; and this expresses a principle the same in kind as that expressed in the statement that two straight lines cannot enclose a space. No doubt the principles in the two cases are extremely different ; and about the one there may be much controversy, whereas there is little about the other. But any one who assumes the existence of laws in anything, or who speaks of a ' right ' and a ' wrong ' in regard to it, really commits himself to the principle that the right in that sphere is equivalent to the conceivable. To say that a combination of two tones is musically wrong is to say, ' I cannot, consistently with the laws or principles of musical thinking, conceive or hold together those two tones.' To sum up, then, each CONCEIVABILITY AS TEST OF TRUTH 179 sort of object has its own laws, and every such law is a law of conception. Every one admits some laws of conceivability and applies them to objects. Every one, in other words, admits in some cases that the conceivable is identical with the empirically possible. But different people draw the line differently. What is conceivable to one person or age may be inconceivable to another, and what is con- ceivable to a person at one time may be inconceivable to him at another. What can be conceived by a person is ultimately determined by his experience ; his con- ception of an object is proportionate to his experience of it (' experience ' being taken in the widest sense, as equivalent to what he has been, or thinks he might be, conscious of). And the same thing is true of any age. Take the case of the antipodes, which were once incon- ceivable. They were inconceivable at a time when certain conceptions of motion, &c, were held ; and the people of that time might justifiably deny that they existed. The facts from which those people argued were facts of observation, and they remain so ; but they were to those people more limited facts than they are to us, and what we call the same facts are the same with great additions. If we take the phrase 'the sun rises,' it means very different things at different times. It remains always true that the sun occupies a higher position relative to me at noon than at ten o'clock ; but some people have interpreted this fact by the idea that a chariot and horses were being driven up a steep road, and others by the conception of the body called the sun actually moving up the sky. The different conceptions which different people have expressed by the word ' sun ' depend on the other conceptions with which this conception ' sun ' is N 1 180 LECTURES ON LOGIC connected in their minds, and on the ways in which it is connected. It remains at this day quite conceivable that the sun goes round the earth, if that means that one yellow body goes round another ; but an astronomer would say that it is inconceivable that the sun goes round the earth, i.e. that if you realized mentally all the conditions involved in the conception you would find it self-contradictory. In the same way, as we have seen, there is no difficulty in conceiving a centaur, so long as your conception is merely spatial ; but a biologist would say that if you saw all that is involved in a centaur you would pronounce it inconceivable. When, then, is a man justified in saying that a thing is inconceivable ? When, and in so far as, he has reason to believe that he has exhausted the conditions of the phenomenon in question. Otherwise his logical course is to suspend his judgment. And towards most things this is obviously our proper attitude ; they are neither conceivable nor inconceivable ; in regard to them we are aware of our limitations. There is no surer sign of a really educated mind than the power of pronouncing and of suspending judgment at the right times. The more educated we arc, i.e. the wider our intelligent experience is, the more things are inconceivable to us, and (we must add) the more things are conceivable. It is not ignorance which has the widest possibilities. If by ' conceivable ' we mean ' able to be held together so as to be coherent,' the true is also the conceivable. But ' conceivable ' ought not to be understood in the narrow and superficial sense commonly attached to it ; it does not mean ' able to be pictured.' ' Can you conceive a thing ? ' ought to mean, ' Can you think it completely out?' Really to do this is, of course, TEST OF TRUTH 181 impossible ; but when a man comes to the point where he can conscientiously say, ' If this is true, or if that is not true, then the whole of the rest of my experience falls to the ground,' then he is justified in pronouncing the one thing to be inconceivable, and the other to be conceivable. Test of Truth. The point in speaking of conceivability as a test of truth is that everything is experienced as an element in or of something else, as something related in a more or less determinate way to something else in one world. The conceivable is that which admits of being thought along with certain other things according to certain prin- ciples of union or synthesis. To apply to anything the test of conceivability is to try whether it fulfils this con- dition. It will be worth while to look more closely at the meaning of ' test.' In the first place, ' testing ' clearly implies that the test we employ is something different from the thing tested ; we cannot in strictness speak of testing a thing by itself. To ask whether a thing is really what I take it to be, whether y4 is really A, is to ask whether A is related to other possible experiences B, C, as I suppose it to be. To test an experience A is to try to actualize some other possible experience B which we expect to accompany it, — which we have reason to believe ought to be present if A is really A. For example, I go into a dark room, and, touching something, I ask if it is really a table. This question does not mean, Is the sensation of touch really a sensation of touch? It means, If a candle w< re lighted, should I see something of a certain colour and shape ? If I lifted this something, should I have a certain 182 LECTURES ON LOGIC impression of weight ? and so on. Every question I ask about experience A, the sensation of touch, expects for its answer other experiences, B, C, D, which I have come to hold together with A in the conception of table. In other words, ' table ' stands for a synthesis or principle, according to which I expect certain experiences to be connected in certain ways. Again, even supposing I ask the question, Is A, the sensation of touch, really a sensa- tion of touch ? this question, if it means anything, requires for its answer a reference to something beyond A. It may mean, for instance, Am I interpreting the sensation rightly, or am I under an illusion such as is possible, in a morbid condition of the organism, regarding the simplest sensation ? And this means, in other words, Am I right in assuming that, along with the sensation, something else is present (a certain modification of the nerves of my skin, for example) which would be present if the sensation were a sensation of touch ? About a literally simple feeling there can be no question raised, for such a feeling is not a constituent of our experience. Every feeling we are conscious of is felt as a modification of another feeling, or in contrast with another, or in some way which compels us to regard it as a related feeling. By no possibility can we raise the question whether a feeling is real without going beyond the feeling itself, and, in effect, asking whether something else is there. Thus to ' test ' any experience is, literally, to ' try ' it, to experiment with it. And all experimentation, the most ignorant and the most scientific, means, ultimately, trying to experience the same thing over again in a different context. It means either trying whether something else which we expect to accompany the thing does accompany TEST OF TRUTH 183 it, or trying whether the thing remains the same when the circumstances are altered. I test my incipient judg- ment that this is a table by adding a fresh clement, a visual sensation, or another sensation of touch. The experiment is very simple and comes to an end very soon ; but the most difficult and prolonged experimenta- tion is, in principle, the same process. All progress in knowledge is, in this wide sense, a gradual process of experimentation. Every judgment is the expression of a hypothesis which waits to be confirmed, or not, by experiment. Or, to put it otherwise, in every significant judgment we state that something of which we have had experience is now being experienced under different circumstances, that the thing in question is the same thing with a difference. And to test the judgment is to try whether the thing is the same. Every concept, in the same way, may be said to be a certain form of synthesis waiting to be filled up. The ultimate postulate of all experience is that of a self which is the centre and unity of all experiences, or (it is the same thing) of a world which is one through all its changes. This is the most elementary concept or form of synthesis, that which I bring to all experience, and which I expect every experience to fill up. Every specific concept is a specific form of synthesis ; and the question of what kind are the other elements B, C, D, which we expect to coexist with A, depends on the question what is the specific form of synthesis concerned. Space, for instance, is such a specific form, which we bring to the world, and under which the world shows itself to us in a certain aspect. If we take the judgment, ' That is two feet off,' a judgment of spatial distance, ' two feet ' is the concept which awaits experience, and the other element 184 LECTURES ON LOGIC in the synthesis by which I roughly test it may be a certain amount of the stretch of my arm. The concept of space is gradually filled up, the nature of space is gradually discovered, by all sorts of more elaborate experiments. A geometer in reasoning is perpetually constructing new cases of something of which he has already a general conception. Geometrical reasoning may be said to consist in wondering whether a thing is possible and then trying it by experiment ; and the good experimenter in any science is the man who sees how to make a good test of the possibility he has in his mind. Every experiment, then, is governed by the conception we bring to it ; and every conception is a certain ex- pectancy or form of synthesis, waiting to be tested and filled up. The most elementary or general of these expectancies has been described above, but it is also often described as the conception or principle of the uniformity of nature. This means simply that there would be no experience, no world, for us unless we expected things to retain their identity or to behave in certain permanent ways. If this expectancy were not fulfilled there would be no things at all. The prin- ciple of the uniformity of nature is simply the principle of identity in difference. If you never had two ex- periences in some sense identical, you could have no experience ; and any two experiences in any way iden- tical are experiences of the uniformity of nature. The phrase does not mean that nature continually repeats herself; in one sense nature never repeats herself; every identity we observe is accompanied by difference. The phrase does not imply monotony or exclude variety. It means, { A is always A, though it may occur with the SENSATION AS TEST OF TRUTH 185 differences B, C, D . . .' All problems of testing or verification resolve themselves into the question, Is this, which I suppose to be A, really A ? Sensation as Test of Truth. We have seen that testing anything implies that some- thing else is in some way related to the thing in question, and related to it according to some determinate rule or principle. In ordinary practice we test only to a limited point ; and there are certain conventional tests agreed on, which differ according to the field of knowledge concerned. Such a conventional test, for example, is tangibility, which seems as a rule to have the prerogative even over visibility, probably because touch is the earliest vehicle of experience and the most continuously present. We may, however, raise the question, What is the ultimate test, and what is the point at which we should stop in the process of verification ? In the abstract we can only answer, The ultimate test is that about which there can be the least possible doubt ; that in which I am most directly conscious of being what I judge myself to be ; and verification should stop at the point at which I am obliged to say that, if this is not what I judge it to be, I am not at all. The question, however, would still remain, In what form then do I realize my own existence most fully ? When, where, how, does the certainty of it most come home to me? And to this question most people would probably answer that some form of sense-perception is the mode in which we most directly realize our own existence. Hence it is sometimes said that the ultimate test of all truth is the possibility of sensation ; a statement which sounds like the opposite of the doctrine that the test 186 LECTURES ON LOGIC of truth is conceivability. What then does this state- ment mean? It can hardly mean that the most real reality is visibility or tangibility. No one would assert that these properties of the world are more real than any others ; no one would say, to take a very crude instance, that the reality of God depends upon whether you can touch him or not. The statement must ultimately mean that, we being what we are, and getting all our experience, as we do, through sensitive organs, nothing is real which does not admit of affecting us at least in the way of sensation. As simple sensible qualities are the beginnings, the apxai, of all experience, the centre from which we perpetually advance, so, however far afield we go in discovery, they remain the limitations of human ex- perience. This is obviously the case with the physical world. It is, indeed, perfectly true that, in one sense, the solar system and its laws are not sensible objects ; that no one can touch the laws of motion ; that the conception of motion is one obtained by very great effort of thought, and that almost all statements made about moving bodies are complicated inferences. Still the truth of a theory of motion does include the pos- sibility of experiencing certain sensations ; and a man of science, like Newton, would admit that, unless under certain circumstances he could experience certain sensa- tions of sight, his theory of motion would fall to the ground. In this sense the possibility of experiencing such sensations is a test of theory ; or, to put it other- wise, suppose the theory to be absolutely verified, then among other elements in this verification one would be certain sensations. Certainly there would be no ground for saying that this element is more a test of truth than SENSATION AS TEST OF TRUTH 187 others. Visual and other sensations get their prominence merely from their simplicity, and because they are a test which every one can apply. But it remains true that in all human experience some relation to a sensitive or- ganism is a necessary element, and that a conception which ignores this is so far untrue. 'In all human experience ' ; for the statement holds good beyond physical experience. Duty, for example, is a human experience, an experience of beings with a sensitive organization. Duty is not sensible ; but we cannot ex- perience it, cannot do an act of duty, without at the same time having certain sensitive experiences. A con- ception of duty, therefore, which did not ultimately include the human body in it would be illusory ; there would be no object answering to it in human experience. If it is true in this sense that sensation is a necessary element in every conception, and is thus a test of truth, how is it that sensation is also spoken of as the most illusory thing in the world ? How is it that we find such opposite things said of it, and of its importance in knowledge ? When we say that any experience is illusory, we really mean that it is wrongly interpreted, we never mean that it has no existence. We often talk as though there were something of which we can speak and think, and which yet is unreal ; but an unreal thing is simply nothing, and what we call illusory is not unreal. If a person sees what he takes to be a ghost, while it is really a turnip with a candle in it, he is under an illusion. But his visual sensations are not unreal ; they are as real as his alarm ; his illusion consists in going beyond them and interpreting them into a supernatural phenomenon. All falsehood is of the nature of misinterpretation. Just as 188 LECTURES ON LOGIC a true experience means one that is rightly connected with others, so a false or illusory experience is one that is wrongly connected with others. And, as we have seen, there is no way of testing the truth or falsehood of an experience except by going beyond it, and seeing whether it is connected with certain other experiences in certain ways. Accordingly, when we say that sensation is illusory, what we mean is not that it is unreal, but that it enables us to go with safety only a very little way beyond itself, and that it gives very wide opportunities for misinter- pretation. Visual sensation, for example, is extremely un- trustworthy, in the sense that, if we confined ourselves to what we can strictly be said to see, we should be confined within a very narrow circle, and should make all kinds of mistakes. The more nearly sensation approaches to mere sensation, the more isolated is it, the less extensive and connected is the experience of which it forms a part, and therefore the more opportunity is there for illusion ; it is likely to be taken to mean the wrong thing because it may mean so many things. Conversely, as we have already seen, the wider the context in which a thing becomes an element, the more conceivable it becomes ; and every fresh connexion makes it more conceivable or true. The truest and most tested truths are, therefore, those which express the widest uniformities, are the same in the greatest number of differences, hold good in the largest contexts ; and the truths least true, least tested, and most liable to misinterpretation, are the most limited, those that hold good in the narrowest contexts. Such are the judgments based most directly on sensation ; and this is the ground of the polemic against sensation. The old comparison of the process of acquiring know- SENSATION AS TEST OF TRUTH 189 ledge to the reading of a book may illustrate the truth about sensation. If we take a single word at random out of the book, how much truth or meaning has it ? Apart from its sentence, paragraph, chapter, its meaning is reduced to a minimum. So it is with a simple sensation. Some meaning the word has (for it would not be itself if it did not suppose some context), but its meaning is as little as it can be ; and so it is again with a sensation, which would be nothing if it did not tell us of something else. Again, as long as you consider merely the isolated word, you may interpret it in many ways, and all of them may be wrong ; but with every extension of the context of the word its meaning becomes more certain ; and this also holds of a sensation. On the other hand, the whole meaning of the sentence, and, in a sense, the whole meaning of the book, may be said to depend on the understanding of a single word x ; and so it may be said that a given piece of truth is not true to me unless it comes home to me through some simple sensation, and unless I experience that element of it ; and its truth may be said to depend on the possibility of its being thus experienced. Hence the progress of knowledge and truth consists in the gradual widening of experience ; that is, in our con- tinually experiencing the same things in fresh contexts. And we must remember that every bit of truth, in being tested, also tests. I find out what this word means by comparing it with the same word in other passages ; and in the process it not only receives meaning but gives it. It is not merely the case that every new experience adds 1 Or rather, to interpret the book, you must know at least the minimum of the meaning of the language, and, if the book does not at least mean that, it will mean nothing to you. 190 LECTURES ON LOGIC something to previous knowledge ; it affects and modifies that knowledge. Knowledge is not a process of mere accretion. This is seen in a startling way in the effect of a great discovery or a new idea ; it may revolutionize the whole mind of a generation ; it does not merely add to the circumference of knowledge, it penetrates to the centre and rearranges the whole body of ideas. Hence, again, it follows from the nature of the progress of experience that no concept, no ' meaning,' can be final. If you ask at a given time what is the conception of a certain thing, the answer may attempt to fix the experience of mankind for the moment, and to define it by drawing imaginary limits ; but this can be only for the moment. SECTION IX CONCEPT AND THING. SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE. SELF AND NOT-SELF l We have considered certain antitheses in which con- ception is contrasted with perception, or a mediate and representative mode of apprehension with an intuitive or presentative. We pass now to another set of antitheses, which appear to place conception or thought, as some- thing ' subjective,' in opposition to things, or reality, or what is ' objective.' I. What is meant by the antithesis of Concept and Thing ? A concept is sometimes contrasted with a thing on the ground that it is merely something ' in my mind.' But, if ' concept ' has the meaning we have assigned to it, there can be no ultimate contrast of this kind. The thing ' tree ' is my various experiences of it in presence of it and in thinking of it ; and every word that I use in describing this thing expresses, and must express, my consciousness or experience. The tree ' outside ' my consciousness of it is simply nothing to me. In the same way a triangle, i.e. the space contained between three straight lines, is an object of consciousness, and there can be no ultimate contrast between this concept and the thing triangle or the fact of triangularity. What sense then can we give to the distinction ? 1 [Compare Note C] 192 LECTURES ON LOGIC (a) I can distinguish between the fact of triangularity and my concept of triangularity if I mean by the latter my experience of triangularity as accompanied by other experiences, feelings, &c. ; and if I mean by the former my experience of triangularity, regarded as disconnected from these other irrelevant experiences. Again (b), in another way my concept may be distinguished from the thing or fact. My concept of triangularity may well be an inadequate concept : it is so, for instance, if a triangle means to me nothing more than a space contained be- tween three straight lines. A man who knew more would say that my conception was a long way off the fact, and he would be right. But that which he calls the 'fact' would not be different in kind from my conception ; it would be my conception very much extended. The contrast here, then, between concept and fact is really the contrast between a less complete and a more com- plete conception. In the same way a scientific conception is said to be much nearer to the ' fact ' than a popular conception, not because it is composed of elements dif- ferent in kind from those which form the popular con- ception, but because it contains more elements, and because these elements are better arranged. And though the most scientific conception falls short of the fact, and is only ' nearer ' to it, this ' fact ' is still nothing but an extension of the experience contained in the conception. If a man could experience the whole fact, he would not cease to conceive it, he would conceive it more. Concepts, then, are not mysterious somethings which intervene between us and things, the ' concepts ' to which Mill objects as misleading superfluities added to names and things. A concept is a certain experience held together in the mind. My experience of a thing is what SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE 193 I am conscious of about it, and this is my conception of it. II. Subjective and Objective. With the antithesis of concept and thing is connected that of subject and object, and that of subjective and objective. As to the usage of the words subjective and objective, it is curious that the sense they commonly bear now is just the opposite of their original meaning. ' Sub- jectivum,' in the writings of the Schoolmen, where it first appears, applies to the real subject of attributes, the viroKeCfjiei'op of which they are predicated. ' Objectivum' is used of anything regarded as an object to us (avTiKei\j.evov) or ' idealiter,' i. e. from the point of view of our idea of it. Gradually ' subjectum ' came to be appropriated to one particular subject of attributes, namely, the human mind or self. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries the modern usage was becoming tolerably fixed ; but Berkeley still employs ' objective ' in the old sense ; for instance, when he says that, as the esse of things is percipi, ' their real and objective nature is the same.' As used now, the words are strictly correlative terms, the one being taken to imply a contrast with the other. It is difficult to detach from the chaos of their meanings a few round which the rest may be grouped ; but the antithesis is used to convey the following principal contrasts : — 1. Between the experience of this or that individual, and the experience of mankind, or of some group of individuals, or of scientific men. 2. Between human experience in general, and the world as it may be supposed to appear to some other being or beings. VOL. I. O i 9 | LECTURES ON LOGIC 3. Between that which is in consciousness or exists for a mind, and that which is outside consciousness or un- related to a mind. There is, we must first observe, an implication com- mon to all three antitheses. When people contrast any experience, as ' subjective,' with something described as ' objective/ they mean to convey that the former is less true or real than the latter. For example, in think- ing of heat, we are told to put aside heat in the 'sub- jective' sense, i.e. anybody's particular susceptibility to heat, the implication being that this has little to do with the real or objective nature of heat. And so in the sphere of art or of morality what is called ' subjective ' is understood to be less true than what is called ' ob- jective.' Now this distinction of degrees of truth or reality is one that we want to make and must make ; but it is unfortunate that the words ' subjective ' and 'objective' should be chosen to convey it. For a 'merely subjective ' idea is just as much an ' object ' as anything else in the world, and my particular feeling of heat just as much an object as the ' objective ' heat of the physicist. And conversely the ' objective,' however true or real it may be, is just as much an object of mind as the merest whim or fancy. Unfortunately, however, ' subjective' and ' objective ' are apt to suggest the antithesis of ' in the mind ' and ' outside the mind ' ; and therefore we must be on our guard against the influence of that antithesis if we choose to use 'subjective' and 'objective' to convey the perfectly justifiable distinction of degrees of truth or reality. 1. Bearing this in mind, we may say that, in the first usage of the words which we have to consider, ' subjective ' generally means the experience of random SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE 195 individuals, ' objective ' the experience of mankind (or sometimes of educated mankind) ; the one is to ibiov, the other to kolvoi: Now of course numbers, as such, can be no criterion of truth ; and yet on certain subjects (for in this matter there is a great difference between different subjects) to naai bonovr, universal consent (which is never really universal), is important to ascertain, and the agree- ment of many minds in one view gives a certain prob- ability in favour of its truth. But the reason lies not in the number as such, but in the diversity of opinions, feelings, circumstances, through which the view persists. The Ihiov has, in comparison, the less probability of truth, because it belongs only to a limited area of human nature; the koivov has the greater probability, because it holds through a larger area of differences. We may observe that the truth is koivov, also, in the sense that it unites : different people are united in so far as they all see the same thing to be true ; it is ignorance and prejudice that isolate. The distinction of ' subjective ' and ' objective,' in this sense, is a relative distinction. Probably there is no truth which is merely true in one place, at one moment, and for one person. Nor is there any truth in which all the people in the world would agree. But the progress of knowledge, or the increase of truth, means that the irrelevant elements in each man, those which do not affect the thing in question, are more and more put aside, and the essential elements more and more recog- nized and agreed upon; and we may, if we choose, call this an increase of the ' objective ' at the expense of the 'subjective.' 2. Secondly, 'subjective' may be extended to mean that which is true for man, and ' objective ' may be O 2 196 LECTURES ON LOGIC taken to mean some truer truth — the world as it may be conceived to be to some higher and fuller intelligence. If \vc use the words thus, we must remember that it is we men who use them and for whom the antithesis exists. To talk of anything outside human experience is, ipso facto, to bring it into human experience. How, then, can we men speak, with any sense, of the subjective as that which is for man, and of the objective as that which is for some higher intelligence? We must answer that the contrast, whatever it means, cannot be one between a reality which implies consciousness, and a reality which implies none. If the 'objective' is to signify a more real world than the world as it is for us, we can only attach a meaning to the ' objective ' by thinking of the world as it is for us modified in some way. If I contrast my ' subjective ' view with the ' objective ' view of a man who knows better than I, I do not suppose an absolute break between my mind and his ; the difference is one of degree, and the two views are connected. And in the same way, if I contrast the knowledge of mankind with a more perfect knowledge, this ' objective ' knowledge must be a continuation and completion of the ' sub- jective ' knowledge. Otherwise the ' objective ' is a mere blank, and it is idle to speak of it. In this sense, again, we may speak of an ' unknowable/ and may represent the unknowable as the objective ; only we must remember that in so speaking of the unknowable we are knowing- it — knowing it as the ' beyond ' of the known. If it be said that this is a contradiction in terms, we can only answer that it is the fact : man is conscious at one and the same time of knowing and not knowing 1 . If we 1 [Compare Note A.] SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE 197 like, then, to use 'subjective' for the determinatcly known, and the correlative 'objective ' for the ' beyond ' of that — the 'beyond' which is always present — well and good ; only the distinction will not be one between that which is matter of conscious experience and that which is not. 1 It is well to insist on this because of the constant association of the word ' objective ' with the idea of an existence out of relation with consciousness. There is a notion, for example, that we should come to such an 'objective reality' if we could analyze the world back into its simplest constituents. Thus some popularized views of science convey the impression that, if every- thing could be shown to be some form of matter and motion, matter and motion would be the objectively real, compared with which everything else would have only a subjective reality. And this corresponds with the earliest formulation of the antithesis of subjective and objective in the saying of Democritus, vop.co yXvKv /cat vop.w VLKpov, I'OjKi) depfxov, vop.u> \j/vxp6v, vofxco xpon] ' (Tefj 5e arofxa /cat k€v6v. Now it is quite true that it may rightly be considered a great achievement of science to show that all phenomena are forms of motion. But why should this be an ideal of science? Why should it be thought to explain the world ? In one sense it is true to say that such a discovery would leave everything as it was before ; all the differences of phenomena — of sound, heat, electricity— are not done away with by it. But it puts them in a new light. It gives us a language by 1 [This paragraph has been left in its place, although it does not deal with the second of the three contrasts of 'subjective' and ' objective.' It represents remarks made at the end of a lecture, when Nettleship probably did not care to begin the discussion of the third contrast.] 198 LECTURES ON LOGIC which they can all be expressed in terms of one thing, and this a thing the nature of which is, comparatively, accurately known. It enables us to measure them and compare them. It not merely increases our practical power, but heightens our sense of the intelligibility and the unity of things. Accordingly we may, if we choose, speak of motion as ' objective,' if we mean that we understand it more exactly than we do most things ; and, in this sense, the simpler the elements we have to consider, the more objective they will be. But if we mean that they — that time and space and motion, for example — are objective in the sense of being outside the mind, or of having a reality different in kind from that of other objects of human experience, that is a distinction which cannot be maintained. 3. We have now to consider this distinction further. The objective, in the two senses hitherto discussed, has been seen to be nothing ' outside ' consciousness. The further question is whether we can give a sense to the antithesis of the subjective, as ' a mere idea ' or that which is ' in the mind,' and the objective, as that which is ' outside the mind.' 1 Let us take the old instance. The idea of .£100 is said to be a very different thing from the real or objec- tive fact of .£100. What then is the idea of ;£ioo? As soon as we reflect we find that the idea has no fixed meaning, that its meaning varies more or less with the 1 [The following discussion repeats and develops the previous state- ment of this Section, that the distinction of concept and thing is really the distinction of less complete and more complete concept. It is not denied, therefore, that an idea (concept) of jCioo differs from the fact of £100 ; but it is insisted that both alike are objects to subjects, that both are real, and that the superior reality of the second object lies in its content, not in its supposed independence of a subject.] SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE 199 various persons who use the words, and that the idea, the matter of consciousness, has in each case its own appropriate reality. A child's idea of £100, what £100 means to a child, may be a hundred round yellow things of a certain size. This idea has its own reality ; a hun- dred, yellowness, roundness, &c, are all facts. If you call it a ' mere ' idea, you do not mean that they are not facts, but that the real .£100 is more than the idea. To the child the reality of ;£ioo, the objective fact, is exactly the content of its idea ; and the objective fact to you is not different in kind from this, but contains something more, which, for reasons good or bad, is considered more important and real. What is the economist's idea of £100? Most of the contents of the child's idea find no place in it, or have taken a subordinate place. The economist's idea of ^100 is a certain value, or purchasing power ; and this is also the objective fact to him. This value is the power to do something which implies various persons maintaining a certain understanding with one another. If anything is ' inside ' the mind, such an understanding is ; and the economist's ' objective reality ' would simply disappear if there were not persons who were capable of that under- standing, and to whom things had value. Suppose sovereigns to go out of circulation and to become very scarce ; what will be the coin-collector's idea of^ico? It will differ from the two former conceptions, though it will combine elements of each. ;£ico will mean still an object of value, but of ' fancy' value. This 'fancy' value is perfectly 'real' or objective; but it, and the real £100 of the collector, would disappear if there were no one who cared about the age, historical associations, and artistic interest of coins. 200 LECTURES ON LOGIC Suppose, again, there were persons who could ap- preciate neither the economic nor the fancy value, nor even the engraving on a sovereign, what would remain of the ;£ioo to them? We should say that a sovereign, as such, did not exist for them. There would only exist weight, shape, colour, hardness, and the like ; and all these imply a feeling subject. These considerations by no means show that ;£ioo is a mere fancy, but they show that its reality, though we talk as if it were perfectly fixed, is purely relative ; so that if its reality is its objectivity, its objectivity depends on the subject to which it is an object, and seems to have no sense out of this relation. Thus, when it is said that, the idea of ,£ico is different from the reality, we have to remember (i) that the real ;£ioo, whatever it is, is still ideas ; that all the words we use about it imply conscious subjects, and their feelings, views, desires, and the like ; and (2) conversely, that, though we talk of the idea of ;£ioo being merely in the mind, it is no more so than the objective fact ; it is itself a perfectly real fact, the object of a subject, with its own reality, which we can characterize. The phrases ' inside the mind ' and ' outside the mind ' are responsible for a great deal of confusion. We forget that 'inside' and 'outside' refer in strictness to nothing but objects in space, and that the use of them in reference to anything else is metaphorical. We conventionally fix ' reality' to mean some sort of ' outsideness,' and ' subjec- tivity ' to mean some kind of insideness' ; and we forget that there is no 'outside' without an 'inside.' Let us take another instance of object and subject — the table and me. (a) In what sense is the table outside me ? In the same sense as it is outside a chair, and in no other SUBJECTIVE AND OBJECTIVE 201 sense : that is, ' mc ' is here my body. Are the table and I in this sense object and subject? Certainly not. The table and I (my body) are two correlatives, and object and subject are two correlatives, but object and subject are correlatives of a totally different nature from two things spatially external to one another. If the table becomes an object to me, its spatial externality to ' me ' (my body), and its metaphorical externality (the fact that it is an object) to me, have nothing in common but the characteristic that each is a correlative to something else. (/;) Suppose now that the table becomes an object to mc, what is its correlative ' me,' the subject to which it is object? Not my body, but something to which my body and the table are both objects. In thinking of the table as simply an external object, I think of it as out- side my body (and other things) ; the table is not outside my mind, but its externality to my body and other things is an object to my mind. (c) Again, suppose the table is an object to me in the sense of being my property, then ' I,' the subject, am something capable of owning property, and that is the only ' I ' to which the table belongs, (d) Again, if I want the table, if the table is an object of desire to me, then the subject is only the desiring ' I.' There is no abstract ' I ' to which the table is object ; the object and the subject vary together ; if its objectivity is its externality, then the subject is a consciousness capable of spatial expe- rience ; and so on. The question is constantly asked, What is the evidence for the existence of an 'external world'? This question means, in strictness, not what the questioner generally intends, but, 'What is the evidence for there being spatiality?' And as soon as we leave this sense of it 202 LECTURES ON LOGIC we fall into ambiguities, for we do not know with what metaphorical meaning the question is being asked. It may, no doubt, be pleaded that any metaphorical use of a word must have something in common with the original meaning. But then the conclusion is that, when a person talks of an 'external' world, he must have in mind some ' internal ' to which the external is cor- relative ; whereas the questioner, in using ' external,' generally wishes to mean something which is not a corre- lative. Spatial externality has become a symbol of dis- connected ness, of one thing having nothing to do with another ; and yet, if the questioner dwells upon this spatial externality itself, he will find that to conceive one thing as outside another is to conceive it as closely bound up with another. A person who talks of an external world has already, by this very word, internalized it. As soon as anything of this kind is urged, it is supposed to mean that the real world is a collection of ' subjective feelings.' But this confusion again is due to a certain conventional usage of the words which describe our minds, consciousness, feelings, &c. As ' external ' misleads people into supposing the real to be that which is out of relation to mind, so such a phrase as ' in the mind ' misleads them into supposing that to call something an idea or ideas is to deny or diminish its reality. Hence the impression produced on most people by Berkeley was that he held the ordinary things to which we ascribe reality to be illusions. But all the things we call most real are, when we reflect on them, recognized to be ideas or states of mind or consciousness ; and there is nothing whatever in these phrases to exclude reality. To speak of a thing as ' my consciousness ' or ' a state of my mind' is, it is true, to imply some want of reality. But SELF AND NOT-SELF 203 the difference indicated by the phrase is an assignable and describable one, for it is / who contrast ' my mind ' with ' mind,' or what is in my mind with what is objec- tive ; and, instead of using the phrase vaguely to convey the notion of unreality, one ought to reflect on the difference that it indicates. So, again, ' consciousness ' is commonly used in one or two narrow and restricted senses, and conveys only these senses. ' Consciousness of tooth- ache is the actual feeling, not the idea of it,' some will say, as if ' consciousness ' meant only physical feeling. So again, to say that a thing is a fact of consciousness means, to many people, to do away with its reality. Strictly, however, consciousness is co-extensive with experience. III. Self and Not-self . It appears, then, that in everything called human experience there is present self-consciousness, i.e. consciousness analyzable into a self and a not-self 1 . Whatever piece of experience we take, we see that, whether we describe it as ideas or feelings, or again as an object or a thing, we have at length to say that, if it is a feeling, it is felt by something ; if it is an idea, it is entertained by something ; if it is an object, it is object to a subject. Ideas, states of mind, as experiences, are not things which pass over a surface ; if they are really states of consciousness, there is something which is conscious of them. Consciousness, conversely, is not consciousness unless it is consciousness of something. We can, and we must, analyze any and every experi- ence into two correlative factors ; we must say ' we 1 [Not necessarily consciousness of a self as against a not-self. For this meaning of self-consciousness see what follows.] 204 LECTURES ON LOGIC experience' and 'we experience something 1 ; and this is what is meant by saying that the ultimate fact in ex- perience is self-consciousness, the simultaneous con- sciousness of a subject and an object. These correlative factors never have any independent existence ; the reality is the inseparable union of the two. And in actual experience no one thinks of separating him- self from that which he experiences. It is all one to say ' toothache exists ' and ' I experience toothache ' ; to say ' colour is a fact ' and ' I see colour' ; to say ' the equality of the angles of a triangle to two right angles is a fact ' and ' I understand it ' ; to say ' duty is a reality ' and ' I am conscious of an obligation to act.' When these things are really being experienced, the last thing we think of doing is to separate ourselves from the fact or the fact from ourselves. Again, the more we experience, the more are we able to say, indifferently, that we are more, there is more of us, or that the world is more, there is more of the world. The growth of experience, that is, is describable indifferently as the growth of our- selves or as the growth of the world. But, if this is so, how is it that we so habitually divide experience into self, the subject, the inward, on the one side, and the not-self, the object, the outward, on the other ; so that experience seems to fall into two dis- connected and independent halves? It may help us if we consider, first, some cases where the consciousness of self, as separate from not-self and opposed to it, is most vividly present, (i) 'Self-con- sciousness,' in the ordinary English sense of the word (altogether different from the philosophical use), is an instance. In the kind of shyness called self-conscious- ness, what is it of which we are conscious ? It may be SELF AND NOT-SELF 205 perhaps some peculiarity in our dress, or the fact that someone is looking at us. That is, we really for the time being consider that the self is contained in these extremely trivial particulars. And that they really do absorb the self may be demonstrated by the fact that a person intensely ' self-conscious ' in that way may be quite incapable of thinking of anything but them. (2) Other instances would be egotism, in the sense of the consciousness of self, as excluding, or limited by, or competing with, other selves ; or, again, fear, in which we are intensely conscious of ourselves, and desirous of self-preservation, and in which the self of which we are aware is exclusive of, and painfully contrasted with, a not-self from which we wish to get away. Or (3) take an intellectual instance, the consciousness of difficulty or strangeness in something which we are trying to learn. The thing may interest us, but it stands over against us and shuts us out, and we are uncomfort- ably conscious of ourselves as limited, and wish to be different. In all these cases we should generally be said to be intensely conscious of ourselves, but what is really true is that we are conscious of ourselves as limited and exclusive, and it is this consciousness of self that is the differentia of such experience. With such experience we contrast conditions in which we are totally free from ' self-consciousness,' such as the state of being intensely interested in anything ; and we say, perhaps, ' I was entirely absorbed (or lost) in the thing.' And yet it is at these very times that a man's self is most conscious ; just as it is not less active, but much more active, when, an intellectual difficulty being overcome, the man understands, and is no longer conscious of ' himself as 206 LECTURES ON LOGIC excluded. In all these cases, then, the use of self and 'self-conscious' is most misleading. If we turn now to the other correlative, the not-self or object, it would be easy to find corresponding misleading uses of ' object ' or ' objective,' which again suggest that the world falls into two disconnected halves, and that an object is an object to nobody. A typical instance of what we call objective reality would be matter, by which most of us mean at any rate what occupies space. This may be taken as a type of something into which we, as self-conscious selves, do not enter at all, and we think it absurd to call the spatial world a state of consciousness. Yet when we try to characterize spatiality, to say what it consists in, we at once use terms which imply conscious- ness just as much as the terms by which we describe pain or colour. We say, for example, that distance is the space traversed between two points — the space, that is, moved through by us or by some other body. But this is to imply consciousness at once ; and, if we say that, even if there were no conscious being, distance would still exist, we shall find that what we then mean by distance existing is that, under certain given circumstances, there would be that conscious experience which we describe as the experience of distance. But, if every experience really implies the two cor- relative factors, how is it that, as we have just seen, one part of experience seems so very unlike another ? Why does space seem to be different in kind from an ' inner ' experience? Why do an intense feeling of shyness, and the clear apprehension of the distance between two points, seem to be so far apart from one another ? The fact is that, though self-consciousness in its true sense means an experience in which self and object are one and SELF AND NOT-SELF 207 the same thing, or two in one, yet this experience is con- stantly, so to say, fading or falling away from itself; and, as it does so, the mutually implicated elements or factors, which have really no independent existence, seem to fall asunder and to receive such an existence, and our world is perpetually getting falsely broken up into separate parts. It is only comparatively seldom that we really and fully experience what we say we experience ; and our ordinary language and thought represent but a very partial and faded consciousness. This partiality may be a partiality or defectiveness on the one side or on the other. We may fail to realize either the subjective or the objective element 1 , (a) If we take the case of space or the material world, we are so used to this from childhood that it is only by an effort we can realize that we enter into it at all. We talk of it as if it were outride us, half meaning that we experience it with- out an effort of our own. Yet the most elementary facts of space only exist in so far as they are facts of ex- perience, or acts of our own ; and we understand this perhaps when, as we pass beyond them, the subjectivity of 1 [The following, largely in the words of Nettleship's own notes (which are here very much fuller than usual), gives his meaning briefly, and may be useful : — In actual experience we never separate ourselves from that which we experience. But, out of the given experience, we still talk of ' I ' as the subject of it, and of it as an object. What is this ' I ' in general, which I distinguish from, say, colour or duty, and which I yet distinguish as subject from them as objects ? It is a subject to which they are still partly objects, or, rather, it is a subject which is conscious of part of what 'colour' and 'duty' mean; and 'the object' (colour or duty) with which I contrast it is really just as much another subject as another object. The truth is, we have a vague (but fixed"; conventional general- ized set of experiences which we call I. subject, oneself; and another set which we call objects. Really, these objects are objects to its all the time, but we do not call them such until their objectivity and our subjectivity reach a certain height above the average.] 208 LECTURES ON LOGIC space is brought home to us, and we realize that there is no difference between the existence of triangularity and that which we understand (or, if you prefer it, that which is understood) by triangularity. It is just that part of our experience of which, for various reasons, we partly lose our hold that we speak of as the objective world. But this world is not out of our consciousness, and its ob- jectivity is exactly correlative to the amount of subjective activity in the person who speaks of it. Ask a man what space is, and, though he may think he is speaking of something ' external,' he must talk of his own experience, and will enable you to measure his subjectivity, (b) Con- versely, a great part of the world is conventionally described as ' our own experience,' ' ourselves/ the ' inner' or 'subjective world.' But, if we reflect, we find nothing to correspond with this language ; we do not find that the consciousness thus described is the consciousness of a self to the exclusion of a not-self. Take the most ' subjective ' experience, and it is still consciousness of self and not-self. The more we keep within ' ourselves ' (as in the uncomfortable ' inward ' states described before), the more we are conscious of something else shutting us out. Self-consciousness, in the proper sense, is con- sciousness of self in not-self, and of not-self as self. The more it is self-consciousness, the greater the conscious- ness of duplicity and of unity. The less it is self- consciousness, the more one or the other element domi- nates, and the world of experience falls into two halves, oneself and the objective world. Then ' self-conscious- ness' (as opposed to the objective world) comes to mean certain fixed things in which we are most conscious of self against not-self; i.e. in which we are most intensely conscious of our exclusion and limitation. SELF AND NOT-SELF 209 The current distinctions, then, of subjective and objec- tive, subject and object, self and not-self, have no precise meaning, nor in our conventional states of mind do they express to us what they ought to express. It is only occasionally that we rise from these states to anything like a true perception of our experience. It is on these moments, when we understand and are active, that we ought to dwell if we wish to arrive at truth. [At this point some remarks were made on the mis- understanding by which the doctrine of the correlativity of subject and object is supposed to imply that the world ceases to exist when we cease to experience it. These remarks were made at the end of a lecture and were probably hurried, and it is not possible to re- produce them satisfactorily from the reports. The same misunderstanding was, however, touched upon in the course on Logic begun in October, 1886 ; and the follow- ing is an attempt to give, only partly in the original words, the substance of what was said on these two occasions : — ' It does not follow from the doctrine of the implica- tion of subject and object in all experience that " colour ceases to exist when it ceases to be seen," or that " if the human race perished, the world would no longer exist." Statements like these betray, and are partly due to, the confusion which arises from our habit of taking words to stand for a mere fraction of the facts or experiences they signify when understood in their full sense. " Colour," for example, stands for a complex fact, having various aspects and involving many conditions. One of these aspects is its visibility, and one of these conditions is (to speak roughly) a certain affection of the eye; and it is VOL. I. P 210 LECTURES ON LOGIC really this one aspect or part of the fact " colour " that we have in mind when we say that, according to the doctrine impugned, colour would cease to exist when it ceased to be seen ; we mean that colour as seen would cease to exist. And this is perfectly true ; for that part of the fact "colour" called its visibility depends upon a certain sensitive affection, and we have supposed this condition of its existence to be removed. If then we assert that colour, as seen, would continue to be real after all human beings (putting the lower animals out of account) had ceased to exist, what can we mean by the statement ? We must mean either (a) that, if there were a subject sensitive in a particular way, it would see colour [i.e. the reality of colour as seen would be a conditional reality], or (b) that in some way or other there is eternally a sensitive subject which experiences colour as seen. That is, in either case we should still be affirming the correlativity of object and subject. On the other hand, it is perfectly true that with the disappearance of the human race colour would become a very different fact from what it is now ; for everything in it which implies a merely human experience, and everything which it contributes to human life, would have ceased to exist. ' The same considerations, taken in reversed order, may be applied to the case of the laws of motion. These laws would still be true if all men died, but the meaning of their " truth " would be seriously changed. For the laws of motion are not something altogether apart from the detailed facts of motion ; and the sum of motion, if the human race disappeared, would be different from what it is now. That is, motion would be exactly what it is now, minus those modifications of it which are due to human intelligence and the applications of human SUBJECT AND OBJECT 211 intelligence ; the reality of motion, in other words, would differ according to the intelligence of which it was the object. If, again, we say that all the laws of motion and their possible consequences are true, whether they are discovered by man or not, this means nothing unless we suppose a mind to which they are true.' It seems evident that Nettleship's purpose was solely to point out (i) that the idea of the world without man, supposed to be denied by the doctrine of subject-object, really implies it ; (2) that, on the other hand, the dis- appearance of humanity (and indeed the birth and death of any individual) must make a difference to the world. What he said implies further a positive opinion that human beings are not the only subjects in the universe. But it seems clear that in his restricted treatment of the matter he did not intend to express any view on the questions it suggests as to an ' eternal subject,' or the relation of that subject to finite intelligence, or the like. Nor can the illustration from colour be safely taken to imply that motion, or any other of the physical con- ditions of colour, involves no reference to sensibility (see pp. 186-7, I 9^> 200).] P 2 SECTION X CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION OF CONCEPTS A CONCEPT, in the wide sense in which we have understood the word, is any definite content of conscious- ness (a percept being, if we please, distinguished from a concept as a definite content of consciousness implying present sensation). Now, as we also saw, every definite content of consciousness is experienced as a modification of something else. It is something attended to, and in the act of attention distinguished, defined, particularized. Every sensation is experienced as a modification of more general sensibility, the particular sensations of sound as modifications of the general sense of sound. Every figure is experienced as a modification of general spatiality, every virtue as a modification of general excellence, and everything as a modification of conscious- ness in general. That is, consciousness — or, as the Greeks said, being — is the ultimate genus, of which all experiences or things are specific forms. In accordance with this terminology, the name genus may be applied, in any given case, to that ' something else,' as a modifica- tion of which any experience is experienced. And so every concept is what it is (individual), as being a par- ticular modification of something which admits of other CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION OF CONCEPTS 213 modifications, and which is therefore called general or universal. Hence every concept is the germ of a classification. In all thinking or conceiving we may be said to classify. For to classify, in the simplest sense, is to assign to a given thing its place in the world of our experience ; to discover and point out what other experience it is a modification of, and what particular modification of that experience it is. For instance, to classify a triangle is to discover of what kind of thing it is a particular case or form. And this is the same as to conceive a triangle. For, when you conceive a triangle as a three-sided figure, this means that you realize that it is a modification of the experience which is called ' figure,' and which admits of other forms or modifications. And the more definitely we conceive, the more we classify; for each fresh characterization is a fresh modifi- cation of something less characterized. If, for example, you enumerate the properties of a table, and say that it is wooden, square, heavy, a dining-table, each of these properties classifies it, each of them at once identifies it with, and distinguishes it from, something else. ' Wooden ' identifies it with other wooden things (from which it is also distinguished), and again distinguishes its material from other possible materials of a table : and so with each of its qualifications (which are the ' marks ' of the concept). Everything which we conceive may be classified on various principles, which will differ in value. There is, indeed, no abstract ' best ' classification of anything ; the best is that which best serves the purpose in view. A dictionary is an instance of a very artificial classification, but the classification is excellent for its purpose; it 214 LECTURES ON LOGIC enables you to find words easily. The arrangement of some etymological dictionaries, in which words are classified according to their roots, is different because its purpose is different. The latter classification would, however, be called more ' natural.' And this means, speaking roughly, that, as compared with the ' artificial ' classification, it includes more of the nature of the thing classified ; just as a classification of plants according to colours might be called an artificial classification, because the colour of a plant, though essential to it, tells us so little about it, or is so ' insignificant ' a mark of it. An ideal classification would be one which, as soon as you knew how a thing was classified, enabled you to know all about the thing. Accordingly a classification may be called better or worse (apart from special purposes) in proportion as it enables you to know more or less about the things classified. And the distinction of ' natural ' and ' artificial ' ought to have this meaning. What is implied in saying that an ideal classification would tell one all about the thing classified ? It is implied that one would understand each thing in the world to be a modification of some one universal or substance, and that one would understand exactly what modification it is. If this were so, we should know pre- cisely how one thing was related to all other things. The aim of scientific classification is to accomplish some- thing like this for one section of the world ; it aims at finding a property or quality, of which the various forms of the subject-matter in question can be shown to be modifications. But so far as, in conceiving a thing more and more definitely, we see more and more what it is a modification of, and what modification it is, all advance in conception is an advance in classification. CLASSIFICATION AND DEFINITION OF CONCEPTS 215 Definition seems at first sight very different from classification. A modern reader of Greek philosophy is struck by the prominent part played in it by opLo-fxas : for with us ' definition ' has come to signify generally the more or less arbitrary fixing of the meaning of a word, so that 6 pianos reminds us, for example, of the definitions of a dictionary-maker. We must banish this notion if we wish to understand what is meant by definition in the theory of science. To define is really to conceive or experience definitely ; the expression in speech or writing is an after-thing. When we are told that Socrates spent his whole life in trying to define certain things, this seems to us absurd, because we take the word in an external and limited sense, whereas the effort of Socrates was to make himself and others realize fully and definitely the meaning of the experiences de- noted by moral terms. How do we define, in this sense? How do" we realize the meaning of an idea or experience? The more we think of the experience, the more we find that it is a modification of some other experience, and what modifi- cation it is. This is an untechnical way of saying that definition is 'per genus et differentiam ' ; to be definitely conscious of anything you must see what modification it is of what more generic thing. Hence we see how near together classification and definition really are. We are often told that the ideal of ancient science was definition, while that of modern science is classification ; but the essence of the two things is the same. Definition 'per genus et differentiam' assigns to a thing its position in a genus relatively to other things which are also modifications of the generic nature ; and to do this is to classify the thing. It is quite true that a great deal of 216 LECTURES ON LOGIC what we call definition is not definition ; it consists in substituting one word for another, moving about (so to say) the pieces on the board of cultivated people's minds. Hence the prejudice against ' definition.' But, in the proper sense of the word, our whole business in thinking may be said to be definition ; for it consists in conceiving more and more definitely what we experience. SECTION XI EXTENSION AND INTENSION. THE GENERALITY OF CONCEPTS I. Extension and Intension of Concepts. The content of a concept may be described equally well as the ' marks ' or ' notes ' by which it is known, or as the elements which are united in it. The sum of these elements or marks is sometimes called the intension or comprehension or connotation of the concept, and with this is contrasted its extension or denotation. Triangularity, for example, that which makes a triangle a triangle, that which would be verbally expressed in a perfect definition, is the meaning or intension of the concept triangle. Triangles, i. e. instances in which this is found, are said to be the extension of the concept. It is common to say that the intension of a concept is the attributes connoted by the name, and the extension is the ' things ' in which these attributes are found. But what is the sense of this antithesis ? On what ground do I contrast triangularity with this, that, and the other triangle, calling the latter emphatically ' things ' in con- trast with the former ? What constitutes the ' thing-hood ' of the particular triangles? It is that in them which has nothing to do with triangularity, the mere circumstances of triangularity ; for instance, the 'here-ncss' of the parti- cular triangle, or its woodenness, or brazenncss. What we mean, then, by the ' things ' in which triangularity is 218 LECTURES ON LOGIC found is a number of attributes x which are unessential to triangularity, though they are found united with it. l A triangle ' is constituted by the fact of triangularity plus the facts of ' here-ness,' woodenness, and the like ; and the extension of the concept triangle is its intension plus the consideration that this co-exists with a number of other intensions. But we must observe that, in this sense, the extension is just not the extension of the in- tension, for the intension is exactly the same, however many the instances of it ; we call these ' things ' particular triangles, but they are not particular triangles. On the other hand, if we really mean by extension the extension of the concept, then intension and extension coincide. The fact of triangularity is not, and cannot be, separated from the various forms of isosceles, scalene, &c. ; it is in them, just as life cannot be apart from, but is in, the various forms of life. We may, however, give a meaning to the distinction in the following way. We may, for convenience' sake, mentally hold apart a certain fraction of the fact ; for instance, the minimum of meaning which justifies us in using the word 'triangularity.' We may call this the generic triangle, and distinguish it from particular forms of triangle. We may go on to say that the content of triangularity is less than that which is contained in all possible triangles ; and we may call this content the intension of the concept triangle, and distinguish it from the extension. But in reality trian- gularity cannot be separated from its particular forms ; and the intension of the concept, i.e. its full meaning, is therefore the same as its extension. 1 That is, every such ' thing,' or element of the ' thing,' has in its turn intension, of whose extension triangularity is a part. Woodenness is the intension ; the wooden thing is woodenness + triangularity + . . . . THE GENERALITY OF CONCEPTS 219 II. TJic Generality of Concepts. The discussion of extension and intension recalls the statement that general conceptions are got by abstraction from things — a statement in which ' things ' is used in the same unsatisfactory way as in the extension and intension formula. That conceptions are got by abstrac- tion merely means, in its simplest sense, that, as conscious experience is one and continuous, any particular bit of it, in order to be clearly realized, must be attended to ex- clusively ; the act of attention, that is, implies an act of abstraction. Hence we are rightly told that the power to abstract is essential to thinking, that to ' think ' a thing we must free ourselves from certain contexts in which it appears. But it is misleading to say, on the strength of this, that conceptions are abstracted from things ; for this is apt to suggest that the ' things ' from which the conceptions are abstracted have some other kind of reality than that which belongs to the conceptions ab- stracted from them ; whereas in truth that from which we abstract in order to think clearly a given conception (say, that of triangle) consists of other actual or possible experiences or elements of consciousness. No doubt, if we like to give the name of ' thing ' to any group of properties supposed to be coherent, there is no objection to saying that every property which is clearly conceived is abstracted from a thing ; only we must be on our guard against the notion that the conception (the pro- perty clearly conceived) has one kind of reality, and the thing (the group of properties) another. Again, we are told that a concept is general, but a thing (or existence) particular ; and that general con- cepts are got by abstraction from particular things. 220 LECTURES ON LOGIC What, then, is the generality of a concept ? A concept is general in so far as we are conscious of it as common to, shared in by, diverse elements — as entering into, and entered into by, other concepts. To conceive colour in general is to be conscious of a certain experience, and, in that act, to be conscious of it as capable of being experienced in a variety of forms, such as red, blue, green. When I conceive virtue in general, I am con- scious of an excellence of a certain kind, which may assume and be present in various shapes. Taking the generality of a concept in this sense, we cannot properly say that the general concept is 'got by abstraction,' for the concept is not made general by being abstracted, its generality means its capability of being abstracted- Nor can we properly say that it is abstracted from particulars ; for its generality does not exclude, but implies, particularity. Consider, again, the meaning of the verb 'to generalize.' To generalize is to conceive something as general (in the sense explained) ; to conceive it as actually or possibly an identity in differences. It is to see mentally that ' this ' is also true of ' that ' and ' that ' and ' that ' ; that this thing or experience would also be true under other circumstances. We talk of generalizing an experience, and this means seeing that we should have it under various conditions. In this sense of ' generalization ' we could have no experience at all without generalizing. The simple judgment, ' this here and now is that there and then,' is an act of generalization. It implies that I am conscious of a certain identity which I carry on through the difference of time and place. I have in ' now ' and ' then ' two particulars of a general, and their identity ; and this implies power to see through the THE GENERALITY OF CONCEPTS 221 differences to the identity (power of ' abstraction '). Take, again, at the other end of the scale, a great act of scientific generalization. Newton, according to the story, generalized from a falling apple to a truth about motion. Supposing this to be so, it would mean that he mentally saw in the falling apple an clement of identity with all moving bodies on the earth, and with all the bodies of the solar system. That is, he saw this identity through a mass of differences which to any ordinary mind would have been insuperable. But this act of generalization was in principle the same that a child performs in identifying any two things. The result of this act is a generality or general concept, and in this sense all concepts are general. The concept of motion is general, not in the sense of being vague, but because it is conceived as realized in, or admitting of, many forms, applications, modes. Its generality (to repeat) does not exclude, but implies its particularity. The more we know about anything the more we generalize and particularize, and the widest generalization ' explains ' the greatest number of par- ticulars. The power to generalize implies fur titer, and incidentally, the power to distinguish the fact from irrele- vant conditions of experience, from things with which it is found, but which it is not ; and the more we generalize, the greater is the number of these irrelevant things from which we abstract. It is these irrelevant conditions which are sometimes described as the ' particular things ' from which a ' general concept is got by abstraction.' But it is essential to recognize clearly that these particulars are not the particulars of the general. You may call the falling apple a particular case of motion, but it is not the whole apple that is so ; as falling it is so, but as rosy it 222 LECTURES ON LOGIC is a particular case of colour. It is perfectly true, how- ever, that the power of thinking or generalizing implies not only the power of particularizing in the strict sense, but also the power of ' abstraction,' or of seeing the fact through the mass of circumstances, the so-called ' particulars,' with which it co-exists. The generality of truth, in this sense, means its independence of irrelevant conditions. We may take as an illustration of what has been said the experience of heat, (i) Let us begin with an elementary form of this experience, the state in which we are conscious of ' feeling hot,' and are conscious of almost nothing besides. We should here know the mini- mum about heat. We should hardly have generalized heat at all ; it would be nearly an isolated fact. And the proof of this is that an alteration of the circum- stances would seriously modify our consciousness of heat. (2) Next let us take a stage at which we feel hot and refer the feeling to an object outside. Here we have a great advance. I am conscious of a certain identity (expressed by 'hot' or ' heat') in a context which includes my body and an external body. I have generalized heat more ; and advance in the same direction might lead to the ' generalizations ' that there is heat wherever there is fire, or alike where there is sunlight and where there is fire. And then (3) we may suppose that we have some- how found that heat goes with expansion. This would enable us to carry on heat into new and wider contexts, to connect the phenomenon with a great number of other phenomena, to pursue an identity through many more differences, to increase greatly the generality of heat. From this point of view it is doubtless true that a concept, in advancing, gets further and further from THE GENERALITY OF CONCEPTS 223 c sense.' In the case of heat, for example, at each step the particular circumstances of time and place become less and less important. The experience is more and more disengaged from the local and temporary circum- stances in which it is embedded. The merest act of memory, in which an element is simply retained, is an act of disengagement from sense ; and this disengage- ment from sense (in this meaning of the words 1 ) goes on increasing in recollection and imagination and the further processes of thought. In this sense, again, but only in this sense, it is true that conceptions, as they become more true, become more abstract ; that is, more independent of bodily, local, temporal conditions. And so, the better we understand anything, the less we need instances ; and, the less we understand anything, the more we need them. What are usually called ' general ' ideas (often in a dis- paraging way) are just not true generalities. They are conceptions which are supposed to represent a certain definite identity in certain definite differences, but which really represent neither the one nor the other. They will not hold or apply in particular instances, just because they are not the generals of the particulars. If a man acts upon his ' general idea ' of motion, in this sense, he may find that it is not true ; but the reason is that it is not the true general idea of motion, for that carries with it the consciousness of its possible modifi- cations. A mere 'general idea' of motion is usually a generalized image ; that is, a congeries of certain pieces, often incongruous, of different moving objects with which the person is familiar, some of these pieces being irrelevant to the fact of motion. In like manner a 1 [The parenthesis is doubtless meant to guard against the notion that the full conception would contain no reference to sensation. See pp. 186-7.] £24 LECTURES ON LOGIC ' general idea ' of human nature is often a mere congeries of elements abstracted from a few human beings. It is inevitable that such general ideas should fail when they are applied. So, again, what is commonly called generalizing means carrying a certain quality, perhaps quite superficial, into all kinds of new circumstances, where perhaps it does not apply at all, and then basing upon it all kinds of unjustifiable inferences. Thus the most ignorant are the rashest generalizers ; and this is also true of classification and definition. It may almost be said that, the less we know of a thing, the readier we are to classify and define it. We all carry about with us a number of ready-made concepts, each of which gives the basis for generalization, classification, definition ; and according to the greatness of our ignorance we need to restrain ourselves the more. The polemic, then, against what are called 'general ideas ' is valuable and true. But it is not the generality of a general idea that makes it vicious, but its imperfect generality, which is also imperfect particularity. Every- body, who thinks at all, generalizes ; and all concepts are general. If ' general ' means ' vague ' and ' confused,' that is because the true generality of the concept is not realized. Finally, when we say that all concepts are general, we must add that no concept is ' general ' if this means that it is not individual. The most general concept in the world has its own unique individuality. Truth does not become less individual as it becomes more general. The individuality of a truth is proportionate to the clear- ness and fullness with which it is conceived ; and every new application of it increases both its generality and its individuality. NOTE A. Experience l . Some light may be thrown upon discussions about an ' a priori element in experience,' the ' derivation of knowledge from experience,' and the like, by considering one or two senses in which we use the word ' experience.' i. We sometimes qualify the term by the adjective ' per- sonal.' We say that we have a personal experience of a pain, or of a feeling of heat ; we hear of a personal experience of ' salvation.' In such phrases ' experience ' seems to mean what- ever we refer to ourselves, whatever we are conscious of as happening to us or being done by us. . . . With this ' experi- ence ' in particular cases we contrast what we know about only through hearsay, or in theory, or the like. We say, for example, that we have some knowledge, through descriptions, of what is meant by an earthquake, though we have no experi- ence of earthquakes. But it is evident that this distinction is not really one between experience and something of a different kind, but merely a distinction between different grades or strata of experience, between a fuller experience and a less full. What we experience through hearsay and the like, we still experience ; it is something we are conscious of as happening to us. For our present purpose we may evidently dismiss this use of the word. Knowledge is experience — the fullest experience of anything. There would be no meaning, therefore, in asking whether knowledge is derived from experience. 2. In the second place we contrast experience, in the sense of that which we actually know, with that which is merely 1 [From the course given in October, 1887.] VOL. T. Q 2 :6 LECTURES ON LOGIC possible ; and we speak of the latter as being beyond, or out- side, experience. We say, for instance, ' So far as experience goes, A or B is certain.' Experience, in this sense, means the sum of what is known, the best-established knowledge so far. There can be no objection to this use of the term. Only we must observe that, wherever we take this ' experience,' we find that it points beyond itself, and suggests something which it is not as yet. Nor is it separate from the unknown which it suggests, or which we interpret it to mean. Thus it may be said with perfect truth that we are always in advance of our ' experience ' ; and that the progress of experience means that fresh interpretation, or analysis, or application, of experience by which suggested possibilities are confirmed or refuted 1 . From this point of view we may best understand what has been meant by references to an element in experience which is not itself matter of experience. For example, the essence of Plato's doctrine of avafiv^cns (as found in the Phaedo) is that the soul is aware of something which it has never ' experienced.' We have the notion of equality, for example ; we know what we mean by the word ; and yet we have never seen perfectly equal things. The two things which we call equal are never really equal ; they do but imper- fectly realize, or partly exhibit, the idea of equality. So that our ' experience ' of so-called equal things is at the same time a knowledge of an equality which is not in the things. We cannot therefore learn the idea of equality from our experience of things ; we only ' recover ' it, as Plato says ; or, in other phraseology, the idea would seem to be an element in our experience which is not matter of ' experience,' in that sense of the word which we are considering at present. From the same fundamental characteristic of our knowledge arises the difficulty discussed in the Meno. We advance in knowledge : we learn. Learning means coming to something which we do not yet know. But, if we do not know it, how can we look for it ? Learning must be a coming of the soul to itself— a. process never complete under human conditions. In the same way, to Aristotle learning is the actualizing of something potential, a coming of the soul to itself which is at 1 [Cf. ix. 2, Test of Truth, and Note C, p. 234.] NOTE A 227 the same time a coming of it to things (17 ^v\q fa ivra 7ra>? tart ttcivto), for what is gradually actualized bj' us must be eternally actualized somewhere. The doctrine of innate ideas, originated by Descartes and developed by his followers, was really an attempt to bring out the same fact. It did not imply that people are born in pos- session of fully developed ideas and ultimate truths. It meant that the very fact of our getting these ideas implies an activity which is not derivable from anything else, and which is always in advance of its experience. Kant's doctrine of a priori forms of perception and under- standing is substantially the same idea. The real point of the phrase a priori is that the modes of our experience, the ways in which we experience what we do experience, are always in advance of what at any given moment we hav^ experienced. The truth pointed to by such theories as these, and by the misleading phrase about an element in experience which is not given by experience, is that all experience is a double fact. In experiencing anything, we are aware that we do not experience the whole of what we say we experience. In other words, experience itself, the concrete fact, is the union of two dis- tinguishable but inseparable elements, actual and possible. It is a yiyvofievov, a coming to be. One ought not, in strictness, to say that experience suggests something beyond itself, for experience is the suggestion of something by something which is not yet it ; just as any growing thing does not merely suggest something beyond itself, but is at any moment beyond itself. For example, we say that we have experience of causal con- nexion ; but we never experience all that we mean by causal connexion. We never find a case where it is quite true that two things are absolutely and necessarily implied in each other, for we can never exclude the possibility of some unknown element. Causation remains an idea not fully realized in ex- perience, though it is of the essence of experience ; and it is just this that makes science advance. 3. If we still ask whether knowledge is derived from ex- perience, we are probably meaning by 'experience' what is really simply a very elementary experience. We are taking a certain layer of experience and giving it the privilege of being called experience par excellence. But there is no reason for such a use of the term. Q 2 228 LECTURES ON LOGIC NOTE B. Certitude, Law, Necessity, Uniformity l . The progress of knowledge consists in the widening of elementary experiences of substance and cause. Suppose, for example, a simple sensation of colour, red. The least I could say about it would be a judgment expressing the fact that when I saw it I recognized it. The amount of certitude here, the amount that I am certain of, is very small : how does it grow ? Suppose I say, ' Red is a sensation,' meaning by ' sen- sation ; at least something that I experience through my ears, eyes, &c. I have now established a connexion between red and certain other experiences, which modifies my knowledge both of it and of them. If I then say, ' Red is a colour,' I have connected it with other colours. If I say, ' Red is a modification of light,' or ' Red enters into this or that artistic effect,' I have connected it with an immense number of other things in my experience. Something of this kind is what is continually happening as knowledge grows. When we find an element in different contexts, it acquires new meanings for itself, and it gives new meanings to the elements in these contexts. The element remains in a sense the same, for it is clearly essential that I should be able to recognize it when I have it again ; but it is also continually changing with every new connexion into which it is brought. The progress of knowledge may therefore be represented as the pursuing of identities through ever- increasing differences. And just as the 'substance' red re- mains the same, and yet changes and increases, so do also the ' cause ' and ' effect ' red. The more I know of the connexions of red with other elements, the more I know of its causes and effects ; and the progress of knowledge is therefore a pro- gress in the perception of the coherence of things. At each step in the expansion of experience we put a new interpretation on old data. It is quite true that we constantly 1 [This passage, condensed from the lectures of October, 1886, follows an account (similar to that on pp. 175 f.) of the minimum cognoscibile as expressed in the judgment, 'This is this, not that,' or, 'This is that as well as this.' The self-identity and relation to other implied here were pointed to as the germs of the conceptions of substance and cause.] NOTE B 229 'test' our inferences by going back to the original fact. But what this means is that we ascertain whether we have really got the original fact A — e.g. the sensation 'red' — in the new context to which it gives, and from which it receives, a new meaning. Our 'going back' does not mean that we simply repeat the original experience, or that this contained in it our later experience ; but at each step the ultimate ground of certi- tude is the identity of the phenomenon with itself: i.e. we argue, ' If this is really a case of A, then B is true of it.' The expression of A's nature we call its laws. A universal law about A means, what is true of A as A, neither more nor less. It means that wherever A is found, and under whatever circumstances, A will behave in such and such a way. The universality of a law does not mean that the law ' holds ' in an enormous number of cases, or wherever we have observed A ; its universality depends not on the number of cases in which we have observed A, but on the degree to which we are able to be sure that we have observed A, and nothing but A, in those cases. And the impossibility of ' absolute certitude ' is due to the impossibility of absolutely isolating an}' element from the rest of the world. Hence arises the contrast between theoretical and actual certi- tude, laws and facts. The law says, Wherever A is found, it will behave in such and such a way. The difficulty is to be sure that we have found A, neither more nor less. Hence any actual phenomenon, however simple it appears, presents an insoluble problem if we pursue it far enough ; for to isolate A absolutely would mean that we knew fully, not only A, but the whole context of which it is a part. Hence also all scientific truth is ' abstract ' or fragmentary ; or, that of which we are certain is always a very limited part of what we have ex- perienced. It is a certain truth that the angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles, but any ' actual ' triangle is partly triangle and partly something else. The practical application of the law is therefore modified. We may say that, of the two ultimate sceptical questions, one, ' Is a triangle really a triangle ? ' is no question, it is nonsense ; the other, ' Is this triangle really a triangle ? ' is always a question. The great difference between the sciences with regard to certitude depends on the comparative simplicity or complexity of their subject-matter. The simpler the conditions in any 230 LECTURES ON LOGIC matter, the surer we can be that we know what we have got, and nothing more nor less. The mathematical sciences are peculiarly exact, because the experiences called numerical and spatial are very simple (so that, if we had no others, we should know very little of the world). Sociology is as yet no science, because the simplest object here involves so many conditions. The exactness of a science depends on its abstractness, i. e. on the number of conditions it is able to ignore. The degrees of necessity correspond to the degrees of certi- tude. To say that logical necessity is higher than mathematical, and mathematical than physical, does not mean that one kind of existence is more 'subject to law' than another. Mathe- matics has a high degree of necessity because, its subject-matter being very simple, it is comparatively easy to see how one thing involves another. Logical necessity is higher because, for example, the experience expressed by the law of contradic- tion is still more simple and elementary. A contingent truth, again, does not mean a truth about something not subject to law, but a truth about something comparatively little known. ' Contingency ' means dependence on conditions over and above the known conditions. ' Chance ' is a high degree of contin- gency. ' Necessity ' means that there is no such dependence, — that the conditions are exhausted. The statement that 'all certitude is hypothetical ' is true if it means that all certitude is dependent upon our knowing the conditions of the problem in question ; i. e., if we are justified in saying that we have exhausted the conditions, the thing is certain. The principle of the uniformity of nature (which does not mean that the future will resemble the past) is a particular application of the logical principle of identity. It is implied as soon as anything is experienced as the same under different conditions, and it means that the same thing under the same conditions will always behave in the same way. The question ' How far does this uniformity reach ? ' does not mean, ' How many things are capricious ? ' but, ' How much of the world is not merely theoretically (in anticipation) but actually (in ex- perience) uniform ? ' or, ' Over how much of the world are we able to realize uniformity ? ' The Greeks recognized the prin- ciple, but were able to realize it only over a comparatively narrow field ; and there are still enormous tracts over which we cannot realize it. But the imperfection of our knowledge does NOTE C 231 not, as people say, leave a loophole for ' chance '■ or the ' miracu- lous.' These words ought merely to mean, ' what we cannot yet explain.' NOTE C. Subjective and Objective 1 . The antithesis of subjective and objective elements in ex- perience or knowledge has various senses. 1. ' Subjective ' denotes all the elements in ' me ' and ' you ' except the knowledge itself; e.g. our feelings about it, and our ways of reaching it, are ' subjective.' ' It ' is independent of these elements ; and it is for this reason that they are ' sub- jective,' and not because they are present in subjects. ' It,' the fact, is for us, for subjects ; to know it is to ' make it our own '; and when we are in the most perfect state of intelligence the distinction between 'us' and 'it' disappears, just as in a per- fect sympathy or ' understanding ' two persons become one. ' Subjective,' then, in this sense means everything up to the point of intelligence. 2. ' Subjective ' denotes part of the fact as contrasted with the whole : e. g. a subjective visual experience is one in which the whole fact of sight is not present ; certain conditions are absent. If these conditions are judged to be present, there is ' illusion'; i. e. misinterpretation. In such a case the absent conditions alone are sometimes called ' objective.' What these particular conditions are, depends on the person who is speaking : one means solidity, another physiological concomitants, another conformity to some law or principle, and so on. That is, there is in each case a certain form of existence which has a ' pre- rogative ' of objectivity or reality; and the question to be asked always is, What are the characteristics, or tests, of that particular form of being ? It is in this connexion that so many people identify ' objective ' with what they call ' external ' reality ; but of course the objective is no more outside the 1 [The following is an abstract of the lectures on this subject given in October, 1886. It covers nearly the same ground as Section IX. printed above. Much is omitted as needless to the reader of that section, but what is given is almost entirely in the words of Nettleship's notes, or of the reports of the lectures.] 232 LECTURES ON LOGIC mind than the subjective ; we understand the objective con- ditions of sensation as well as the sensation itself. So far, 'subjective' and 'objective' denote different sets of elements in experience, of which the second are understood to be the more important or universal. They are not corre- lative ; they co-exist, but they may exist separately. 3. We now come, however, to a third distinction, and in this the two terms subjective and objective, or subject and object, are strictly correlative. And this distinction, which amounts to saying that all experience is presented (objectum), is one inherent in consciousness. This distinction is one particular form of a universal law or principle, which may be called the principle of relativity. That principle holds good for all being whatever : in self-conscious- ness 1 it assumes a special form, that in which the related elements are self or subject, and not-self or object. The fact of relativity means that everything is what it is through its relation to other things ; or that, as Plato says, being implies not-being or ' otherness.' For example, every number is one of a series, and its nature or meaning is determined by its place in the series, i. e. ultimately by all the other numbers (and so with any series). Any figure, or piece of space, is determined by the surrounding spaces. So with force ; there is no action without re-action ; the fact may be analyzed into these two, but they are not separable. Again, the attributes of a thing are its modes of acting on, and being acted on by, other things ; and you cannot separate the thing from them ; if you try to, you leave nothing. Then we come to the mode of existence called consciousness (in the widest sense 2 ) ; we find that, as we say, certain bodies feel. Here again every feeling is determined, either by other definite feelings, or by the general surrounding medium of feeling. Lastly, in self- consciousness, the related elements are self and not-self, or subject and object. Here then the object in general is the 'other' of self, but its special meaning will depend on the special kind of self, and will differ according as the self is, for example, sensitive, per- ceptive, intelligent, appetitive, willing. And the distinction of 1 [Apparently = ' consciousness ' in the preceding paragraph.] 2 [A wider sense than that of ' consciousness ' in the last paragraph but one.] NOTE C 233 self and other is perpetually being done away with, and per- petually reappearing. Thus (a) in desire we have to distin- guish between the desiring subject and the desired object. But each is only in relation to the other ; the object is an object only so far as desired, the subject a subject only so far as it conceives of itself as possibly obtaining the object. And in the attainment of desire, when the distinction disappears or becomes implicit, the object, which is s^-satisfaction, ceases to be an ' other,' and the subject, which goes out of itself in desiring, identifies itself with the object. So again (b) in sympathy a person is said to feel himself one with another, or the sense of separation is said to disappear ; and what is implied in these phrases is that the concrete fact, analyzable into two selves, is really the unity of the two. And so (c) with knowledge. In all perceptive consciousness there is one fact analyzable into two aspects. We can only separate subject and object in this sense if we mean b}' subject the possible percipient, and by object the possible perceivable ; and we must do so, because we are aware that our knowledge is imperfect. In truth the dis- tinction disappears (so that truth may be described indifferently as an object or a subject), but it disappears only to re-appear. Finally, pursuing the enquiry, we come to the proposition that ' in the absolute all distinction between subject and object vanishes.' That is, if we start with the idea that everything is in relation to another, and follow this out to the whole of being, we see that, if the ' thing ' were fully determined, its relativity would cease. The sum of relativities would be that which has no 'other' beyond it, or is self-related. Hence Aristotle's description of the divine mind, the ideal of know- ledge, as thought which is its own object (vorjais vor}s). [Then follows the illustration of the ' table ' and ' I,' to show how the meanings of ' object ' and ' subject 'vary together. See p. 200 f.] The 'relativity' of which the correlation of subject and object is one form is not to be confused with the ' relativity of know- ledge,' as expressed in such a phrase as, ' we only know phenomena.' Such a phrase may point to a truth, but it is most misleading. Taken strictly, it must mean either (a) that all we call truth is mere appearance or illusion ; but in that case it is we who draw the distinction of apparent and real, and we are using our knowledge of the real in asserting that we have no 234 LECTURES ON LOGIC knowledge of the real. Or (b) it means that all knowledge is analyzable into a presented (to (^cuvo^vuv) and something to which it is presented (w fyaivcrai) ; i. e. all knowledge is a form of self-consciousness. But generally the phrase in question con- veys in a confused way two notions, (a) that all our knowledge is limited, has a ' beyond ' ; (b) that this ' beyond,' the ideal of truth, though unknowable, is more real than anything which we know. ' Unknowable ' here must mean, not ' unintelligible,' but that ' beyond ' of our present knowledge which implies a subject beyond our present subject. All knowledge involves the consciousness of an unknown in this sense ; this conscious- ness is the other side of knowledge, and the two are inseparable. It is often said that in Greek philosophy the problem of knowledge is regarded objectively, and in modern philosophy subjectively. There is only a partial truth in this statement. In the analysis of perception or thought the Greeks started from the side of the object, the uIo-Stjtov or votjtov : but they regarded the object as strictly correlative to a subject. The distinction of subject and object, which is said to be absent from Greek philosophy, appears without a name in the De Anima, where the process of knowledge is described as a gradual appropriation of the world by the human soul, or as the gradual development of the human soul, from a possible to an actual state of knowledge, under the influence of the world. That is, the distinction appears here as that of the potentially intelligent and the actually intelligible ; and the subject is said to be in a sense the object (17 ^vx^ ra 6Wa nws eVxt iravru) : i. e. in the act of knowledge the distinction ceases to exist, or becomes that of the concave and convex sides of a curve. Conversely, while it is true that conspicuous modern philosophers have started from the side of the subject, and have regarded the conditions of experience as expressions of the self or Ego, it must be re- membered that this subject, self, or Ego has been to them that to which the world is an object, or that which some call the universal subject. It is not true that in modern philosophy the sense of the objectivity of the world has decreased ; it has grown enor- mously, so that we even tend to say that the Greeks had no sense of the uniformity of nature. In modern philosophy, again, as in Greek, we have the idea of something in which the distinction disappears ; and in each it is expressed by a personal term, vovs, or the subject which has itself for object. PLATO'S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS AND THE GOOD PLATO'S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS AND THE GOOD [In the Biographical Sketch some account is given of the book on Plato which Nettleship engaged to write for the Society for Promoting Christian Knowledge. The following Essay is one of the five chapters into which, according to his original plan, the book was to be divided. It was composed about the year 1H81 or 1882. When it became evident that the chapter was much too long for the proposed scale of the volume he began to cut it down, and in the end it would probably have been reduced to less than a half of its original length. Con- sidering the reason of these excisions, it has seemed best to restore almost all the excised passages. A few cor- rections have also been made, some references have been added, and some of the paragraphs have been divided. Otherwise the Essay is printed as the author left it. In the opening paragraph, as originally written, the more specifically ethical of Plato's writings were divided into two groups, according as they deal mainly with the nature of goodness, or with the nature of the good or the end of life ; although, it was remarked, these two subjects touch at many points and ultimately unite. To the first group were assigned the Protagoras, Metio, Laches, 238 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS Charmidcs, and Euthydemus ; to the second the Gorgias, Philebus, and Republic; and these are the dialogues dis- cussed in the Ess?y. In revising it the author determined to prefix a ' general account of Plato's ideas about morality.' The first paragraph, as it now stands, is evidently a mere list of headings for this ' general account,' which does not appear to have been written.] Some of the characteristic ideas of Plato's moral philosophy may be stated in the following proposi- tions : — (1) Goodness is a state of soul, or of the inner man; it means good life. (2) To live well is to live for the right end : the soul is its own end : the end of life is to live well : the best life is that in which the soul is at its best. (3) The condition of living well is clear insight into what the good of the soul means and requires. It is best to have this insight oneself; next best, to follow or be ruled by some one else who has it. (4) The soul of man is so constituted that he can only live well in community with other souls. The perfect life would be a life of perfect communion with other souls and with the soul which animates the universe. These ideas are seldom entirely absent from any of the ethical dialogues, but they are present in very dif- ferent proportions, and are developed with different degrees of emphasis. They are moreover usually de- veloped in contrast with other prevalent ideas which to Plato seemed mistaken ; the idea, for instance, that virtue plato's criticism of current ideas 239 is an external accomplishment, the idea that the end of life is an external possession, the idea that living well is a matter of chance or inspiration or custom, or the idea that individual self-assertion is th^ glory of life. Thus Plato's enquiries are coi^jrned with two main objects. The first is to show what the best life is; that is to say, what is its true essence and definition, irre- spectively of the tendencies in actual human nature which prevent or impede its attainment. This is a question for logical analysis. The second is to show how, human nature being what it is, that life is to be attained. This is a question of social and political construction. Any critical enquiry into the nature of moral quali- ties or principles must be primarily an enquiry into the meaning of certain words and phrases. Every civilized society has a current phraseology, in which its feelings about right and wrong, about what it admires and what it dislikes, are embodied. Under the apparent fixity of this current language is concealed an indefinite variety and inconsistency of meaning, according to the character, education, and circumstances of those who employ it. Such a fluid mass of opinion, solidified at the surface into words, was the material with which Plato started in his ethical enquiries ; and the questions with which at various points he probed the mind of Greek society were practically two : What do you really mean by this or that expression ? and, What do you think you ought to mean by it ? The Greek word dper?/, the most comprehensive term for admirable qualities of character, is usually rendered by ' virtue.' It is unfortunate that the English word has undergone the process of attenuation and decay, so 240 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS familiar in the history of language, by which any special meaning which it had has shrunk into equivalence with chastity, while the general approbation which it expresses has evaporated into a praise so faint that it almost damns. Under these circumstances, ' goodness ' is often a better translation of apeTij : for we too can speak of a good dog or a good ship, a good painter or a good citizen, a good friend or a good man, with many various shades of meaning, but with the common implication that the object which we call 'good' has an intrinsic worth, and that we admire it. The Greek word apery has at least as wide a range, and as welcome associa- tions ; the English word ' virtue ' has neither the one nor the other. The difficulty felt, in rendering the Greek term for excellence of character in general, is increased when we come to specific forms of excellence. We still sum up our admiration of a man in the word ' good,' but we do not so naturally speak of the 'justice,' the 'tem- perance,' the ' wisdom,' the ' piety,' or even the ' courage/ of our friends, when we wish to note the qualities which most strike or attract us. We use the words, indeed, but in senses sometimes more narrow or more shallow, sometimes more emphatic or more remote, than the Greeks of Plato's time, seldom with the same associa- tions or under the same circumstances. Their place has been taken by a new list, of mixed extraction, Jewish, Greek, Latin, and Teutonic. Humility and purity, duty and honour, Christian and gentleman, honesty and con- sistency — such are some of the words which a modern Plato would have to examine if he wished to sift the moral consciousness of English society. The above reflexion upon the greater comprehensive- PLATO S CRITICISM OF CURRENT IDEAS 241 ness, and, if we may say so, ' solidarity,' of the Greek conception of virtue suggests another which is of equal importance for the understanding of Plato. It has become a commonplace of modern criticism that the Greeks ' confounded ethics and politics.' The remark expresses about as much of the truth as would be ex- pressed by saying that to the modern world the ideas of legal, moral, and religious obligation are absolutely separate. It is doubtless true that, so far as there has been progress in the theory of human conduct, it has been marked by growing ' differentiation ' of ideas ; but the progress has not been progress unless it has also brought with it a corresponding ' integration.' The synthesis which the rudimentary organization of Greek life made comparatively easy now requires a grasp and a penetration of mind as much greater as a modern nation is greater than a Greek town. But it has equally to be made, and we have only to look below the sur- face to see that modern thought is in labour with its execution. Plato's method of examining the moral ideas which he found in vogue may be described as that of making the ideas criticize themselves. This he does by pressing them to their logical consequences, by assuming given words to have at least some definite moral meaning, and by asking what follows if that meaning be strictly adhered to. The ultimate appeal is to the conscience of ordinary people ; if you grant that one thing is better than another, if you recognize a distinction between some- thing right and something wrong, if you feel this conduct to be admirable and that repulsive, then you must also grant that such and such is an inadequate or false or confused account of what is good, right, or admirable. VOL. I. R 242 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS This is the critical side of the enquiry. But the enquiry is not only critical ; it is conducted, as all such enquiries must be, in tacit accordance with certain positive and constructive ideas in the mind of the writer, which, though often indicated rather than expressed, grow in- creasingly clear and prominent with the growth of his own moral experience and purpose. In asking, What is virtue? or, What is this or that virtue ? Plato was asking for a definition ; and the significance of the question depends first upon the formal requirements which he expected the definition to satisfy — in a word, on the import which he attached to ' is.' This import will best be brought out by considering what kind of answers he thought formally or logically unsatisfactory, and on what grounds. The tolerably well-defined group of such answers which we meet with in the dialogues called Protagoras, Meno, Laches, Charmides, and Eutkydemus, represents a comparatively rudimentary stage of experience and reflexion. They are put in the mouths of a brave but uncultivated soldier, an honest but ignorant and pretentious prophet, an indolently curious young nobleman, a modest and ingenuous schoolboy. That which naturally occurs first to an unreflecting mind, when asked to give an account of its morality, is to mention some obvious instance of what it considers to be moral. The soldier, asked what courage is, replies, 1 Not to run away in battle ' ; but it is easily shown that it may be an act of courage to run away as one fights (like the Scythians), or to run away in order to fight at an advantage (as the Lacedaemonians at Plataea) ; so that running away and not running away are not, in themselves, of the essence of courage. A similar criticism applies if, substituting for a single act or circumstance PLATO S CRITICISM OF CURRENT IDEAS 2^3 a single general quality, we define courage as 'endurance,' or temperance as 'quietness in behaviour' ; for by courage and temperance we mean something admirable, and there are many cases in which to yield is more admirable than to endure, and where quickness and energy are more admirable than quietness. A second and equally common form in which we hold and express our moral conceptions is illustrated by Meno, when to the question, What is virtue ? he answers, ' Virtue in a man is to be able in the conduct of public affairs, virtue in a woman is to manage her house well and obey her husband ; and so on with the various actions and times of life — there is a virtue proper to each.' This, as Socrates objects, is to tell us, not what virtue is, but how it differs in different circumstances. If we want to know what a bee is, it is of no use to be told that there are all sorts of bees ; one bee may be bigger or handsomer than another, but, in so far as they are all bees, they are all the same. A strong or a healthy man is different from a strong or a healthy woman, but strength is strength, and health is health, wherever they are found. What we want to know is, what makes virtue to be virtue and nothing else. A third error to which in our ordinary state of mind we are liable is that of confusing a principle with its results or accidents, as when, for instance, we define holiness as ' that which the gods love ' ; for, though this may be true of holiness, it appears that it is not the being loved by the gods which makes holiness holy, but the fact of its being holiness which makes them love it. This is part of the general principle that, whenever a thing takes place or is affected in a certain way, the cause is found, not in the fact of its so taking place or R 2 244 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS being affected, but in its own quality or nature. Such a definition of holiness, then, does not give us what holiness is, but what happens to it. These instances will be enough to show what Plato was looking for when he asked the question, What is goodness ? He was looking for something which should be, not good at one time or place and bad at another, but good under all circumstances ; for something which should be realized by the mind, not as a disconnected series of different instances, but as something one and the same, pervading them all ; for something which should be the centre and source of its attributes, not one possible attribute amongst many. He has various ways of describing this something: it is the 'being' or ' essence ' or ' what is,' as contrasted with the ' affection ' or ' what happens to it l ': it is ' that in which all cases of it are the same,' or ' that which remains the same with itself in all,' as contrasted with that in which they differ 2 : it is that which ' makes them all to be what they are,' and it is the ' pattern ' or type to which we must refer in judging of them ourselves or in explaining their nature to others 3 . The one term which he chose to express these various conceptions, the term which more than any other has become associated with his name, was ' idea,' a Greek word which has been naturalized in English, and of which the literal meaning is ' form.' The fuller consideration of Plato's use of this word is best combined with that of his theory of knowledge 4 ; it is enough here to note that from an apparently early period he appro- 1 Euthyphro, 1 1 A. 2 Meno, 72 C ; Euthyphro, 5 D ; Laches, 191 E. 3 Meno, 72 C ; Euthyphro, 6 E. 4 [On which a chapter was to have been written. On the meaning of idea' in Plato see Hellenica, pp. 146-7, and vol. ii.] PLATO S CRITICISM OF CURRENT IDEAS 245 priated it to express the substance of morality, under- standing by the ' form ' of virtue that which is essential, identical, and typical in our moral principles, that which we really mean, believe in, and have in our minds' eye, when we express those principles in words. From the above instances we also see what Plato regarded as the defect or weakness in the moral con- ceptions which they illustrate. The defect is twofold ; either they confound the moral attributes in question with other attributes, which, though they accompany them in experience, have nothing to do with their morality ; or they mistake the moral principle itself for the transitory conditions under which it is manifested. The corrective to the former is found in the habit of clear thinking, in the power to see and pursue a single thread of meaning through the tangled maze of circum- stances, to keep in the mind the thing, the whole thing, and nothing but the thing, which we are considering. The latter defect implies a failure to realize what is in- volved in a moral principle, namely, that, though it can only be exemplified in a series of particular cases, it cannot be identified with any or all of its cases, except by surrendering its claim to be a principle at all. From these imperfect and rudimentary conceptions of goodness we now pass to a more advanced and ambitious level of thought, of which the exponents are men like the cultivated general Nicias or the literary statesman Critias, Protagoras the great sophist, or even Socrates himself. The theories of morality put into the mouths of these speakers, differing as they do in details and in the criticism to which they are subjected, agree in this, that they make virtue, in some sense and to some degree, a matter of knowledge. It is in connexion with this 246 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS view that thre3 cognate questions come into promin- ence: (i) How is virtue produced? for if it is knowledge it seems to follow that it must admit of being explained, understood, communicated — in a word, taught ; (2) How are the different specific virtues related to each other and to virtue as a whole ? for, if there is no goodness without knowledge, the different kinds of goodness must be in some sense one; (3) What is the object of the know- ledge which is the condition of goodness? for, whatever analogy it may have to various branches of knowledge ordinarily so called, it is clearly not identical with any one or with all of them. The insistence upon knowledge as the condition of morality was not peculiar to Plato, or even to Socrates, with whom it is generally associated. Education, under- stood in its widest sense, so as to include all that we mean by the diffusing of ideas, was an object of the keenest interest in Greek society at this time. It meant indeed very different things to different minds. With representatives of culture and enlightenment the question was, how the new ideas of advancing civilization could be best communicated to the rising generation ; the politicians and men of business cared mainly to know how their sons could be fitted for public life or private enterprise ; while the friends of the good old times, or the critics of modern degeneracy, were asking anxiously how the youth might be made upright and gentlemanly, or how the decay of native genius and virtue might be met by better methods and greater application. The supply of instruction was as various as the demand, and ranged from manual accomplishments to the whole duty of a householder and a citizen. ' Love of wisdom ' or ' philosophy ' was the term in vogue for almost any sort PLATO S CRITICISM OF CURRENT IDEAS 247 of higher intellectual interest, any desire for information or attainments above the ordinary traditional level. The ' masters of wisdom ' or ' sophists ' were the persons who made it their business to provide for the satisfaction of the general want. To ' be wise ' and to ' make wise,' wise in literature, science, and art, wise in domestic and social life, wise in war, in law, in politics, these were the dominant ambitions of the rising generation and their teachers in Athens at the end of the fifth century B. c. 1 And, when to this special demand for culture and accom- plishments, whether as an ornament or as a practical engine of success, we add the general intellectual endow- ment of the Greek race, it is easy to understand how a theory which made morality a kind of knowledge should find a soil to spring from and an atmosphere to grow in. To a people which brought artistic and scien- tific faculties to bear so conspicuously, not only upon art and science proper, but upon every branch of life, it was natural that the cunning of the craftsman should furnish the typical illustration of the practical importance of knowledge. Nobody could help seeing that a musician, a surgeon, or a shoemaker must understand his profession if he would succeed in it : why should a man expect to succeed any more as a general, a statesman, a master of a house, unless he has acquired the theory of his business? And, if the former crafts can be taught and learnt, why not the latter ? Socrates, then, was on common ground with the ordinary intelligence of his age when he asserted that the general management of ourselves and our lives, in which morality consists, implies knowledge, study, skill, 1 For illustrations in Plato see Laches, 179 B-D ; Euthydemus, 306 D, fl". ; Protagoras, 310 A, ff. 248 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS in other words a theory and a principle, just as much as the management of any particular branch of life. Where he went beyond and offended public opinion, enlightened as well as unenlightened, was in putting a more ideal construction upon a requirement which, up to a certain point and in a certain sense, every one admitted. The conception of knowledge which he tried to awaken was not only that of a practical mastery in one's business, nor did it merely mean seeing the nature and bearing of a principle of conduct as clearly and certainly as those of a technical or scientific principle ; it required, besides and before these, that self-knowledge which is the know- ledge of our own ignorance, and which is at once the spur to moral progress and the evidence of the inexhaustibility of moral truth. This conception Plato embraced and assimilated in all, and more than all, its original signifi- cance ; and the synthetic tendency of his mind naturally led him to seek a systematic expression for what Socrates had put forth as occasion served or required. But, in his first attempts to define the knowledge upon which he, with his master, believed human goodness and well- being to depend, he was as much concerned to see what it was not, and how it differed from other kinds of know- ledge, as to see what it was and how it resembled them. And thus in the dialogues with which we are now dealing, while the idea of a life according to knowledge is perpetually recurring, and is indeed the idea which dominates them all, we find ourselves being reminded scarcely less often of the difficulties which the idea in- volves, and are sometimes almost encouraged to question its tenability. The points which Plato urges in his criticism fall mainly under two heads. Firstly, if morality has prin- PLATO S CRITICISM OF CURRENT IDEAS 249 ciples and can be taught, it must be morality of a dif- ferent kind from anything now to be found either in society at large or in its professed leaders and teachers, for that certainly is not based upon principles. Secondly, if the good of man depends upon knowledge, it must be knowledge of a different kind from any of the existing arts and sciences, for no amount cf knowledge such as they convey will necessarily make human life better. As regards the first point l , we are forcibly reminded how much of Plato's philosophy was developed by antagonism. A true disciple of Socrates in his thirst for truth and his impatience of half-truths, he must have welcomed eagerly the new lights which had risen or were rising upon his intellectual horizon. ' If happiness means the dealing rightly with circumstances, and if it is knowledge which enables us to do this, surely every man ought to set to work in every possible way to make himself as wise as he can.' - And yet almost in the same breath we find him doubting whether it is possible to be ' made wise/ whether wisdom can be ' learnt ' at all ; and, when the professors of wisdom or their disciples come forward with offers to teach it, he receives them with doubt, criticism, or contemptuous irony. It would seem, indeed, that the word ' wisdom ' was as much a bone of contention in Plato's time as 'culture' is in our own. Genuine scientific attainments, and pretentious sciolism ; speculative interest in language and thought, and mercenary juggling with words ; honest search for deeper moral principles, and rules of thumb for getting on in life, such were some of the diverse elements covered 1 [The reader will sec that the Protagoras and the Me no are considered under the first head, the Laches and the Channides under the second.] 2 Euthydemus, 282 A. 250 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS by the common title '• love of wisdom' or ' philosophy.' Plato's conception of what philosophy ought to mean developed gradually, and in its earlier stages we can gather it mainly from his criticism of rival claimants to the title. He found men professing to be in advance of ordinary views of life, professing to have a real theory of conduct and to teach men how to live ; and yet, when he interrogated their theories, he found in them little more depth, little more unity, little more consistency, than in the popular opinion which they claimed to en- lighten. But it was not only with the professed repre- sentatives of enlightenment that Plato felt himself in antagonism. He, like them, demanded more light ; he, like them, started with criticism of commonly received ideas ; the difference was that his light was more intense and searching than theirs, his criticism more subtle and more uncompromising. And so, like some other philo- sophers, he found himself the enemy, not only of the men of ideas, of culture, and of science, but also of the professional men and practical politicians. The latter class probably regarded him as a variety of the former, that specially dangerous variety to which philosophical radicals and conservative free-thinkers are supposed to belong. The former probably interpreted his unsecta- rianism as trimming, while they hated his hauteur and winced under his sarcasm. In the two dialogues called Protagoras and Meno, which in whole or in part we have now to consider, this double-faced antagonism, the antagonism to society at large and the antagonism to its accredited leaders, begins to show itself. Prota- The Protagoras is a humorous apotheosis of the sophists. In Athens, ' the hearth and home of wisdom,' goras. THE PROTAGORAS 251 in the house of the Athenian who has spent more money upon wisdom than any other living man, the wisest of the Greeks are met together, Hippias, Prodicus, and, greatest of all, Protagoras. Each of the distinguished strangers has brought his circle of admirers ; the elite of Athenian society also is there ; the whole house is pos- sessed with culture, and the porter has lost his temper at the number of callers. Round a bed extemporized in the counting-house Prodicus is holding a literary seance ; in one of the vestibules Hippias is lecturing on physics and astronomy ; in another, Protagoras walks up and down discoursing to a chorus of disciples, who follow the movements of their master with a reverential dexterity which Socrates cannot sufficiently admire 1 . He has called to introduce his young friend Hippocrates to the great sophist ; the youth had come to wake him before it was light with the news that Protagoras was in Athens ; so eager is he to be made wise 2 . Protagoras receives them with the air of a man who is conscious of having been a leader of thought for forty years. Unlike some members of his profession, he is not ashamed of being a sophist, though fully aware of the invidiousness of the title. He knows that many other men distinguished in letters, art, and science, who are practically sophists, have tried to veil the fact for fear of what the political world might think of them ; but they arc always found out sooner or later, and the best policy is to be quite outspoken : as to the opinion of the general public, he makes no account of that ; the general public takes its cue from its leaders 3 . Such is the tone of the great teacher. 1 Protag. 314C-316A, 337 D; cp. Apol. 20 A. 2 Protag. 309A-314C. 3 lb. 316B-317C; cp. 353A-B. 252 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS In the manner in which Socrates is made to behave to him there is the deference of a younger to an older and more distinguished man, touched with the irony of one who has seen through and beyond him. The discussion is conducted without bitterness, and the two disputants part with expressions of mutual respect. Protagoras undertakes to teach a young man, who wishes to become distinguished, ' how best to manage his own affairs, and how to speak and act with the greatest effect in public life '—in a word, to teach ' the art of politics' and to 'make a man a good citizen.' But can these things be taught ? Socrates is inclined to doubt it, and public opinion seems to go with him ; for in the popular assembly at Athens, when any technical question arises, about building, for instance, or ships, nobody is listened to but the architects and shipwrights ; but on a political question any one who likes may get up and speak, and no one asks where he got his knowledge. The Athenian people, then, at any rate, do not consider that politics can be taught or learnt. And apparently the great statesmen themselves feel the same ; for, though they get their children taught everything for which they can find a master, they do not teach them their own virtue of statesmanship 1 . Protagoras does not agree that these facts prove, either that political virtue cannot be taught, or that it is not taught. For, firstly, the art of good citizenship is not, like other arts, the property of a few professional men ; it is present, and is assumed to be present, in a greater or less degree in everybody who is capable of living in a civilized community. This explains and justifies the conduct of the public assembly. Secondly, the fact that 1 Protag. 317E-320B. THE PROTAGORAS 253 society punishes us for doing wrong shows that it re- gards morality, not as a gift of chance or nature, but as a thing which can be acquired and learnt ; for the true purpose of punishment is not to avenge what is past, but to deter for the future. Thirdly, so far from morality not being taught as a matter of fact, we are learning it all our lives. The lesson begins with our nurses and parents ; it goes on at school, where even more attention is given to discipline than to accomplishments, and where the poetry and music taught are specially selected with the view of inculcating virtue ; and, when we leave school, the state takes us in hand, and makes us learn the laws and live by them, and if we transgress them it punishes us. What is all this but teaching virtue? Lastly, we need not wonder if the sons of great and good men are not always great and good. Every civilized man has some morality (a great deal, indeed, if you compare him with a savage) ; it is like speaking our own language ; we think that nobody learns or teaches it, just because to a certain extent everybody does so ; but some people are born with better natural capacities than others, and some people (Protagoras himself, for instance) are better teachers than others \ Such is the position of the professed instructor of public opinion, as regards the nature of his instruction. It is really the position of public opinion itself, put at its best. Society assumes a certain amount of moral knowledge in all its members, and it is right to do so. Society makes every one responsible for his morality up to a certain point, thus implying that it can be acquired and taught. And society itself teaches it in a variety of ways, but of course nature goes for a good deal. All, 1 Protag. 320 C-328 D. 254 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS then, that the professed teacher can be expected to do is to teach a little better than the rest of the world. But Plato expects more from him than this, and in the person of Socrates continues to examine him, not as to the fact of his teaching, but as to what it is that he teaches. If virtue can be taught, what is it ? Protagoras had spoken of justice, temperance, piety, courage, wisdom, indiscriminately as virtue : are they five different names for one thing, or five different parts of the same thing ? Suppose we say with Protagoras that they are parts, and heterogeneous parts, as the mouth, eyes, and nose are parts of the face ; yet is it not hard to maintain that piety, for instance, has not something of the quality of justice ? And how can wisdom and temperance be both opposites of foolishness, without being in some sense one? Or, once more, if temperance may be combined with injustice, will not this imply that injustice is some- thing good ? l If it be still maintained that, however much the other virtues may have in common, courage at any rate is quite distinct (for we find men who are very unjust, licentious, irreligious, and unwise, who yet are very brave), we must ask, Can a man who is a fool be really brave ? Is not confidence an element in all courage, and is it not just the addition of intelligence that makes confidence into something better than mere confidence, which may be the result of rage or madness? This, it may be said, only shows that wisdom makes confidence into courage, but not that wisdom makes courage what it is. We must then again ask, What is it which con- stitutes the excellence, the virtuousness, of courage ? In 1 Protag. 329 B-334 C. Then follows a long interlude (334 C-348 C), after which the question is taken up again where it had been left. THE PROTAGORAS 255 a word, what is the meaning of the distinction between good and evil in human life ? Are they identical with pleasure and pain? If, with Protagoras, we decline to admit this, and equally decline to identify good with knowledge, how are we to conceive the relation between pleasure and knowledge? Is knowledge the strongest and ruling principle in man, so that, when we know what is good, it is impossible to do what is bad ? Or is the common opinion true, that knowledge is the mere slave of pleasure and pain, passion and fear ; so that we may know what is good, and yet do what is bad ? x Now, though Socrates and Protagoras may disagree with and despise common opinion, it is worth while to examine it. When then people say that a thing is bad but pleasant, or good but painful, what do they mean by bad and good? They do not mean that the thing is bad because it is pleasant, or good because it is painful, but that it is bad or good because, though pleasant or painful now, it deprives them of greater pleasure or pain in the future. Pleasure and pain, then, are the real objects of pursuit and avoidance, the things which people- have in view when they call one thing good and another bad. But, if this is so, the common saying that we do what is bad, knowing it to be bad, under the influence of pleasure, is absurd ; it is like saying, we do what is bad, knowing it to be so, under the influence of what is good ; or again, we do what is less pleasant, knowing it to be so, under the influence of what is more pleasant. It may be said, indeed, that there is a great difference between pleasure or pain in the present and in the future ; but it still remains that the difference is only one of pleasure or pain, for we have agreed that these arc the only standard 1 Proiag. 349A-352D. 256 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS of comparison ; it is a question of weighing one amount against the other. Now we know that the same objects appear larger or more numerous when seen near than when seen far off. Suppose then that human welfare had depended upon our choosing the larger magnitudes or numbers, and avoiding the smaller ; in that case we should not have allowed ourselves to be governed by- appearances, but by the sciences of measure and number. Similarly with pleasures and pains : human welfare lies in the right choice of them, and this can mean nothing but right measurement, and this means art and science. What the science is, is a further question ; all that we now assert is that it is a science, and that it is the want of it, that is, ignorance, which produces the evil supposed to come from the victory of pleasure over knowledge. And from this it follows that it is not in human nature to do what is bad, that is, what is really less pleasant, knowingly or voluntarily ; every one goes into evil through not knowing what is good \ Let us now return to our former subject, the re- lation of courage to the rest of virtue. Fear may be defined as expectation of evil, and danger as coming evil. The brave man, then, when he faces danger, does so because he knows that it is not really evil, but good, noble, pleasant ; and the coward does not face it, because he does not know this. And again, when the brave man is afraid of a thing, he is so because he knows that it is really evil, while the fool and the madman are not afraid of it because they do not know this. Courage, therefore, so far from being compatible with the greatest ignorance, would seem to be a kind of knowledge, — knowledge of what is, and what is not, to be feared 2 . 1 Protag. 352 E-358 D. 2 lb. 358 D-360 E. THE PROTAGORAS 257 Such is the conclusion of our argument ; and, as Socrates remarks, it may well ' laugh at us.' For here is Socrates, who denied that virtue could be taught, now trying all he can to prove that it is knowledge ; and, if knowledge cannot be taught, what can be ? And here is Protagoras, who assumed that it was teachable, now anxious to show that it is anything rather than know- ledge. One thing is plain to Socrates, that they must try to clear up this confusion, and enquire what virtue is before they ask whether it can be taught 1 . None of Plato's dialogues has more of the character of a philosophical drama than the Protagoras. This applies not only to the form and setting, but also in a great measure to the substance, of the work. The treatment of the main question is inlaid with more than the usual wealth of subordinate incident and illustration ; and the centre of unity lies, not in any single moral problem or principle, but in the development of the far-reaching opposition between two modes of thought, between the spirits of speculative and popular philosophy, the critical and the professional, the uncompromising and the accommodating, the self-examining and the self- satisfied. We are made to feel throughout the dialogue that the professor of social and political enlightenment has not reckoned with his subject. Much that he says is true, and its truth is not questioned by Socrates ; but he has not thought out what is involved in the phrase ' to teach morality.' With all his contempt for popular opinion, and profession that he has something better to offer, he has really accepted the popular moral distinctions with- out enquiring into their meaning and justification. He 1 Protag. 360 E-362 A. VOL. I. S 258 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS sees that the various virtues must have something in common, but he cannot say what it is. He feels that all pleasant things are not good, but he has not asked himself why. He believes that knowledge is moral power, but he has not tried to explain the wide-spread belief in its impotence, or considered what sort of knowledge he is thinking of. Plato's criticism does more to clear the ground for advance than to make the advance itself. It shows that, if morality is to be put upon an enlightened basis, we must begin with an analysis of what morality really is, for as ordinarily practised and understood it is certainly not enlightened. It further suggests the direc- tion that analysis must take, that, namely, of discovering the central and essential point from which the confused distinctions of the popular code can be explained, justi- fied, or rejected. And, lastly, it indicates that this point will be found in a true conception or knowledge of man's real good or interest, by which the illusory appearances of feeling and emotion may be measured and reduced to their true proportions. Meno. The Protagoras, starting with the assumption that morality can be taught, shows that neither its professed teachers nor society at large are in a position to teach it, and yet that it is in its very essence knowledge. The contribution of the Meno to the question of the nature of morality is in many respects the same as that of the Protagoras, but the conception of knowledge is made more definite by contrast, and the various aspects of the antagonism latent in the latter dialogue have assumed a more emphatic expression. On the one hand Anytus, the representative of the successful politicians and men of the world, gives utterance with unmitigated violence to the prejudice against the sophists which Protagoras THE MENO 259 had thought to meet by out-spokenness ! ; and Socrates, though he suspects the quarter from which the prejudice comes, hardly conceals his sympathy with it ~. On the other hand, the hostility felt by Anytus to the sophists is extended by him, though less openly, to Socrates him- self 3 , and we already see the beginning of that breach between philosophy and the world which Plato, when he wrote the Gorgzas, felt to be impassable. The pri- mary object of criticism in the Protagoras was the pretension of the professed teacher ; only through him, and secondarily, was reference made to the actual morality of public life, which he undertetok to instruct. But in the Meno the professed teachers arc dismissed summarily, and the main interest centres in the great citizens and statesmen who arc appealed to as the practical illustrations of virtue. Meno is a young Thessalian nobleman, a disciple of Gorgias, with enough intellectual curiosity to make him raise questions, but with too little mind to appreciate their real difficulties and too little seriousness to face them. The question which he has asked Socrates con- cerns the acquisition of virtue ; is it got by teaching, or by practice, or does it come by nature 4 ? And, though, as Socrates is so fond of pointing out 5 , it is impossible really to discuss the attributes of a thing until we know what the thing is, he yields to Meno's indolence so far as to put the question in this hypothetical form : What sort of thing must virtue be, supposing that it is got by teaching? It is clear that in that case it must be knowledge ; for knowledge is the only thing that is 1 Meno, 91 C-92 C. 2 lb. 92 D, koX taws ri \tyus : cp. 96 A. 3 lb. 94E-95A, 99 E, 100 B. * lb. 70 A. 5 lb. 71 B, 86D-E, 100 B. S % 260 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS taught. Is it, then, knowledge ? Virtue, we shall admit, is something good ; is there, then, any good thing which is not embraced by knowledge? All good things are useful ; and the utility of a thing depends on whether it is used rightly, and rightly means wisely. This is true of things of the body, such as health, strength, beauty, and wealth. And the same is the case w r ith things of the soul ; moral and intellectual gifts, if guided by intelligence, are useful ; if not, they do harm. Such things, then, are in themselves neither good nor bad ; they are made good or bad by the way in which they are used ; the things of the body depend for their goodness on the soul, and the things of the soul upon wisdom. If then virtue is something good and useful, it must be, in whole or in part, wisdom. And from this it follows that it cannot come by nature : indeed, if it did, we should certainly have taken steps to find out the naturally good amongst us, and shut them up out of reach of corruption until they were of age to serve the state. It would seem, then, that virtue is got by teaching 1 . But here a difficulty presents itself. When we say that a thing is got by teaching, we imply that there are persons who teach and persons who learn it. Now Socrates, with all his efforts, has never yet been able to find any one who could teach virtue. Let us consult Anytus : he ought to be able to help us, for his father was both rich and wise, and gave him a good education ; so at least the Athenians seem to think, for they elect him to the most important offices of state. Supposing then that we wanted to make Meno a shoemaker or a doctor or a flute-player, we should of course send him to the persons who professed to teach those crafts and 1 Meno, 86E-89C. THE MENO 261 were paid for so doing. Meno wants to learn the duties of a citizen, the best way of administering public and domestic affairs, of behaving to parents, of entertaining fellow-citizens and strangers ; to whom is he to go to learn this virtue? The persons who profess to teach it, and are paid for doing so, are the sophists. But Anytus declares that the sophists are the ruin of all who go near them ; and, though it is hard to understand, if this be so, how men like Protagoras should have made such fortunes, perhaps Anytus is right. But to whom then are we to go ? ' Go to any Athenian gentle- man,' says Anytus. And who, we ask, taught the Athenian gentlemen? 'The gentlemen before them. Surely there have been plenty of them.' Yes, there have been plenty, and there are still ; but the question is this, Have these excellent men been able to impart their excellences to others? What are the facts about The- mistocles, Aristides, Pericles, or Thucydides ? Is it not notorious that, while they had their sons taught all sorts of accomplishments, such as riding, shooting, wrestling, playing, they never taught them their own virtues? And yet surely they would have done so, if they had been able. So much, in any case, is clear, that if the professed teachers of virtue are admitted to know nothing about it, while those who possess it cannot agree whether it can be taught or not, there cannot be said to be any teachers of it in the proper sense of the word, nor there- fore any learners. Virtue, therefore, cannot be taught 1 . Are there, then, no good men? And, if there are, how do they become good ? The truth is that we made an absurd mistake before. We said before that nothing is good without right guidance, and this is true. But we 1 Meno, 89 C-96 C. 262 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS also said that right guidance implies knowledge, and this is not true ; for in particular cases right opinion will serve as well as knowledge ; a man whose opinion about a road is right is as good a guide as a man who knows the road. This is the case with our good statesmen ; their virtue is that of opinion, not of knowledge. Is there, then, no difference between the two ? Certainly ; a difference in point of permanence. Right opinions are excellent things as long as they remain in the soul, but they soon run away unless they are made fast ; and the way to make them fast is to see the reason of them : this converts them into knowledge. It is in this per- manence that the superior value of knowledge lies ; but, for this or that particular act, true opinion serves the purpose just as well \ Now neither knowledge nor right opinion comes by nature : goodness, therefore, is not natural. But neither does it come by teaching, for, as we have seen, there are no teachers of it. Yet we allow that it is something good and useful, and that the condition of goodness and usefulness is right guidance, and that the only right guides for man are knowledge and right opinion ; and, as virtue is not taught, it cannot be knowledge ; it remains, then, that it is right opinion. This is why our good statesmen are not able to make others like themselves; their goodness comes from opinion, not from know- ledge. Their intelligence is thus on the same level with that of prophets and poets, who say many true and great things, but do not understand what they say. Their success is due to a sort of inspiration ; as women and Lacedaemonians say of people whom they admire, they are 'divine' men. If we have been right in our reason- 1 Meno, 96D-98C. THE MENO 263 ing, then, the conclusion is this : virtue would seem to come neither by nature nor by teaching, but by the grace of heaven, and reason has nothing to do with it. Unless indeed there were found a statesman who could make others statesmen ; the virtue of such a man would be to that of the rest of the world as the substance to a shadow 1 . The Protagoras had shown the want of depth and consistency in the moral theory of society and its pro- fessed instructors, and had indicated that the remedy was to be found in a knowledge which should give unity to the virtues and supply a standard of moral measure- ment. The knowledge similarly required in the Meno is conceived as a principle, not of measurement but of guidance, and it is further characterized by a formal contrast with opinion. The guiding or ruling function here assigned to reason connects closely with the idea (afterwards more fully developed by Plato) of an ultimate end, to which alone it ' profits ' to attain, and the refer- ence to which alone makes all means and instruments 'good.' The distinction between knowledge and opinion plays a vital part in Plato's general theory of knowledge. But what is of importance here to observe is Plato's growing feeling of the imperative necessity of principle or a reasoned morality in private, and still more in public, life. He has not yet reached the point of accusing the great statesmen of actual failure, as he does in the Gorgias. He admits their success, such as it is ; but it is a success of guess-work, unable to give an account of itself, incommunicable to others, forming no permanent element in the intelligence of mankind. There is some- thing ' divine ' in it, just because it is unaccountable ; but 1 Meno, 98C-100 A. 264 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS it would be better if a man could possess it instead of being possessed by it, and share it with humanity instead of letting it die with him. The definition of goodness as knowledge, as examined in the Protagoras and the Me/io, had the result of draw- ing attention to defects in existing moral theory and practice, which must be remedied if the definition is to answer to facts. The same definition in the Laches and the Charmides is made to lead to the conclusion that the knowledge in question must be further specified as to its nature and object if it is to hold as an account of goodness. Each of these dialogues deals, not with virtue, but with a particular virtue, courage in the one case, temperance in the other. Laches. The point of departure in the Laches is a definition of courage almost identical with that arrived at in the Protagoras \ as knowledge of what is to be feared, and what is not to be feared. This is interpreted to mean, not what is to be feared under certain special circum- stances (in disease, for instance, or in agriculture, where the knowledge in question would be that of the doctor or the farmer), but what is to be feared or not to be feared altogether and as such ; in fact, ' what it is better or not better for a man to experience.' This clearly makes courage a rare and difficult thing ; it must be quite different from mere confidence, rashness, daring, and the like, and must be denied, not only to brutes, but to a great many human beings to whom it is usually ascribed 2 . But here a difficulty arises. Fear may be defined as expectation of coming evil. Now a man who has knowledge of coming evil must also have knowledge of 1 See above, p. 256. 2 Ladies, 194 D-197 B. mules THE LACHES AND THE CHARMIDES 265 evil present and past ; in fact, of evil as such or ' under all circumstances ' ; for the time in which the object of knowledge exists makes no difference to knowledge ; a thing once known is known whenever it may happen to occur. Courage, then, on this view would be co- extensive with all virtue, for what more can be wanting to a perfectly good man than that he should have knowledge of all good and evil ? And yet it has been assumed from the first that courage is one among many parts of virtue \ The subject of the Charmides is ' temperance.' ' Tern- Cha perance ' is the accepted, and perhaps the least mis- leading, translation of poii< i i- 1 || H | i »i tiOODNI ' ■■ • |m i >| i|< '-. i hiii . h in I. i I hi in ini I I i ii "hni; ' il I h> in i . I 1 1< % In i HI I In ll In' I ' .1 > In WOllld 111 III' I 'l I 'I 111 i I in uv 1 1 1 I II •• in I 111 ii \\"il mi. Hi lliul, to dill i\v I In Hi || I n| w .1 j in whlcll I' 1 W i llll 1 1 I I tO II I 'I I il . Ik u , ml, | him i I! ( il I In \ w ■ ■! i h I [)l*l 'ini II ii"l I" I in h I I , in] in i i 1 1 n hi w il h < I' mi. i I ' I 1 .1 \ in- lllOWIl in llll iiii. w i \ iin I I >\ lln inn iii i in Mi' ftft '■■■'. tlml 1 1 L loci i I lull , .1 III' , III | " ' ' 'I u hn II U , Il II' I . Il'l i l ll It . . . iii || I il\ " I i i I il .1 . I In \ ll ' WCll, I. I w I •' l\ , ii i 1 1 nn I I h 1 1 wind I In i ' Ii in lln OIK I'Owll) \\ I .mil i ii ii .ii >ii 1 1 1 1 1 1 ' • in i in world , ! Ii '• with m i|i,,|i,i'\ hn In. iiiiiIiim .illiiii|h\ . I " ■■■■' . I iin brothers I I lo show CI whul 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 ni 1 1 sort ol wlsd i Is which will uiul« h iiirii 1 1 . 1 1 1| iy nn I 'I I Moll) ii ii Ii 'i H ■, i' ' "i i Ini" l\ . h i\ ni- hil i , . i I i nn i I I h i I I I nil i .' Ii n in I . w i l i i | I n u i h ni' K I in i" I" ' omi w le, proved to them Ihal I In j will wl hui" In ilnl.il n ni I, || I In \ w i In , I hnn In , , i i In nn' w hit In WAS I I' nn i •' Ii n ml < I, ,i|.| ni , w i u 1 1 in .i II \ iiii \ il I In 1 1 1 1 1 > ■ 1 1 1 1 in. I .in I I >i"ii , I hiil. nn I ' "iii i .it In I. ■ I him I iul I in in ■ " It l| n .1 r,l i il' tl lO Ini" I I' il hni' nn I ' "ni i i' In I il I tni to ii 'i' lln former, bci nisi ll i ■ Impi issll ill to i) | h. I hill" I h il i ii"l lln I il I i i hi i ni . il [WO | II i llll I ,, 1 1 J ii nil I In i nn I hui . il In i I In \ i \ il . .nn I I In n I h' \ i i I In \ 1 1 1 i j il nn I I In ii lln \ .inii"l ,1, , ,, . .,1 ,.n, n il nn' I In "lln i .1... . iml, in. I lln n ll.- ii WOl'd lift! I il i,.ii I.. . .it h .-I In i .il ill ' ' il . wilt) ' ii' ' ' I till old Ii n in I 111 I In lll'gll mi ni |", mi' 'i "Hi ih ii ii inti only upsi I ' ill Otlll i ' / ,.,', ■;, II l-ji I /,'■ ,,M I ..'I Q ■ /,'. II , l> .III , I! rin i : ru\ • ai 'Miuw nt ., but itsclt too It false speech iuu! id i thought in.l « 1 1 . >i .ii>- .ill impossible, it is impossibh to tench Anything uiul Impossible to refute Anything, And the professions ol il\.- brothers come to nothing ll> howevci was persuaded that thej wen still playing with theii audience, And, like L*rotcus, concealing theit n il shapes Phc only thine was to hold tight to thi m until they revealed what thej I'callj mcanti Mcautimi hi would Again giv< thi in .1 sample "i what he would wish 1 licit revelation to be ' Wi got so fat 1 11 ton n • ti 1 idmlt the necessity ol knowledge i" happiw What K in iw |i 1 !■•.■ is ii i»> be? It w ould be no gooi I, foi example, to know whi n to find And how to maki ol 1 01 i\i 11 to know how to mak< oui n lv< • immortal unli 11 we alio knew how to usi gold anil Immortality What 1 inn. 1 1 Hi. 1 11. »w Ii dge 1 hat bot It maki mil ui 1 ? 1 ii 1 h. torii ' No j for, admii nbli as <>m 1 hi tori< Iaii u ■ 1 ii. \ often cannot delivei 1 1" speeches which thej com Indeed thcii urt is a somewhat Infi rioi branch ol 1 lit- charmer s urt j the channel charms vipers And spiders and scorpions, and thi rhetorician charms coui'1 <»i law •iii thi dlulectleiaii 1'crhaps stuti man ship ' 11 I ui" [ship is the ai I foi w hii h wi An Ii 11 il Ing 11 ii 1 in . w in. ii Mi-, .ii iiir helm oi Mi. tate, incl a1! thi othci .ui. hand ovi 1 thcii producti to It to be utlli ed But 1 1" H thi quest ii mi .11 Isi , wii.ii r. 1 In good w hii i> thii sov< n Ign art 11 11 11 produi ca? It produces, wi maj 1 / m/A U61J UU U 272 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS say, wealth, peace, freedom ; but we agreed before that such things are not good in themselves apart from wisdom. If then the sovereign art is to do any real good, it must make men wise. But wise in what? Wise, we are compelled to say, in making others wise. And then the same question recurs again, and we are brought round once more to the point with which we started, What is the knowledge which will make men happy? 1 In this sea of difficulty Socrates called upon the Dioscuri to come to the rescue. Euthydcmus heard the prayer and came. He offered either to teach Socrates the knowledge for which he was looking, or to prove to him that he had already got it. Socrates chose the latter, and the proof was as follows. ' You know something : therefore you know : therefore you know everything ; for, if there were anything that you did not know, you would not know.' Socrates humbly asked the brothers whether they too knew everything, and they said that they did. 'What! Everything?' asked Ctesippus. 'Yes,' they said, 'everything.' The harder they were pressed, and the more outrageous the ques- tions, the more daringly they answered, like wild boars at bay, and when they could not find answers they retorted with questions of their own. By insisting on having unqualified answers to qualified questions, they proved the most miraculous things ; that, for instance, as once a father is always a father, everybody's father is everybody else's father ; that, as gold is good and you cannot have too much of a good thing, perfect happiness would be to have gold in your stomach, your brain, and your eyes ; and that, as the presence of beauty makes things beautiful, the presence of Dionysodorus makes 1 Euth. 288 D-292 E. THE EUTHYDEMUS 273 Socrates into Dionysodorus. The climax was reached when Ctesippus, who was getting more and more excited in the game, exclaimed at one of their proofs, ' Bravo ! Hercules ! That is a beauty ! ' When Dionysodorus asked whether bravo was Hercules, or Hercules bravo, it was too much, and Ctesippus acknowledged that the brothers were invincible. A storm of applause followed from the audience, and the very pillars of the building shook with delight *. Before parting, Socrates said a few complimentary words to the brothers. He envied them, he said, the genius which could make such an acquisition in so short a time. Three points in it particularly excited his admiration. One was the magnificent disregard which they showed for the opinion of every one except the few who were like themselves ; setting these aside, the rest of the world would be more ashamed of victory than of defeat with such weapons. Then again he was charmed with the thoroughly liberal spirit of their method ; when they had proved that black was white, and sewed up everybody's mouth, they were kind enough to do the same for themselves, so that nobody could complain. But the greatest proof of the scientific character of their discovery was the rapidity with which it could be learnt, as Ctesippus had shown. This was a great advantage to them as teachers, but on the other hand it should make them careful how they displayed their knowledge, or they might lose the monopoly. 'Water,' as Pindar says, ' is the best thing in the world ' ; but it is very cheap 2 . Socrates told the story to his old friend Crito, who had already heard an account of the meeting, and who 1 Eulh. 293 A-303 B. 2 lb. 303 B-304 B. VOL. I. T 274 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF GOODNESS wondered that Socrates was not ashamed to take part in such an exhibition. No doubt education is the one thing needful, but, if these are the professors of it and this is ' philosophy,' how can we urge our sons to apply themselves to it? Socrates would say to Crito : 'Do not throw over philosophy because many or most of those who pursue it are good for nothing ; this is the case with many walks of life. The only way is, not to think about the persons, but to examine the thing itself: if it is bad, have nothing to do with it ; if it is what I believe it to be, follow it and practise it, yourself and your children.' 1 The conception of the knowledge necessary to human welfare in the EittJiydemus resembles that of the Meno in the using and guiding function which it implies ; and the attempt to identify it with the science of kingship or statesmanship anticipates the leading idea of the Republic. On the other hand the difficulty of assigning a precise product to this knowledge recalls the final dilemma of the Charmides. There it is asked, What would the fullest consciousness of the nature and limits of all knowledge profit us, unless it involved the consciousness of ' the good ' of knowledge ? Here it is asked, What would a science to which all other sciences were sub- ordinate profit us, unless it added to them the knowledge how to use them ? We have thus far been dealing with dialogues, the subjects of which are formulated in the question, What is goodness, and how is it got ? The investigation of the question has led to two principal results. It has shown, firstly, that the meaning or essence of a moral principle 1 Enth. 304 B-307 C. THE GORGIAS, PHILEBUS, AND REPUBLIC 275 is not realized or known so long as it is confused, either with the various extraneous elements with which it is combined in experience, or with the accidental circum- stances in which it is manifested or to which it gives rise : it must be understood as what it is and nothing else, if it is to be really understood. Secondly, it has shown that the conception of goodness as knowledge, that is, as rational insight and conviction, while it is one to which w r e are led by converging lines of thought, points beyond itself to the further conception of an ultimate good, which is the one thing worth living for ; a conception which would supply a standard of measure- ment for pleasure and pain, would give unity to the diversity of moral qualities and a principle to moral practice, and would assign to the sciences and arts their several places in the economy of human life. We have now to pass to dialogues in which this further conception is itself the central object of enquiry. ' What we really want to know,' says Socrates in the Gorgias 1 , 'is, who is happy and who is not,' or, ' what sort of men we ought to be and how we ought to live.' ' What we want to find,' we are told in the PJiilcbus 2 , ' is a condition of soul which can make the life of all mankind happy,' or ' what is the best thing that a man can possess.' And, in the Republic, the first formulation of the question, ' What is justice ? ' is soon exchanged for the second, ' How is a man to live his life so as to live it most profitably 3 ?' Besides this similarity in the questions which these dialogues propound, they also resemble one another in developing their answers 1 Gorg. 472 C and 500 B-C ; cp. ib. 487 E, 492 D. * Phil. 11 D and 19 C. 3 Rep. i. 344 E. T 2 276 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD polemically, though the objects of the polemic, and the method and tone in which it is conducted, differ widely. In the Gorgias the antithesis is between the claims of power and pleasure, on the one side, and those of truth and goodness on the other, to be the true end of life ; and the method employed is to show that the consistent denial of all moral distinctions makes any such end in- conceivable. In the Pliilebus the rival claims are those of pleasure and reason to be respectively the whole or chief constituents of human well-being, and a meta- physical and psychological analysis leads to the con- clusion that feeling as such is the mere negation of what is real, and only gets substance and meaning through the formative energy of mind. The Republic, starting from the opposition between the worth of morality as an inward principle and its external results or concomitants, shows that virtue, so far from being another name for material advantages, is the very principle of the soul's life and health ; that the right external organization of society is the expression of that life and health ; and that such organization is only possible so far as society is ruled by knowledge of the laws of the world and of man's position in it. Indications of this idea, by which human life is brought into connexion with a universal order, are found in the Gorgias and still more in the Philebus ; it receives a further development in the Phaedo, where the good is identified with the sustaining cause of nature, and again in the Timaeus, where it is personified in the creative God. Gorgias. We come now to the several dialogues in detail. The Gorgias opens with the question, What is rhetoric ? and closes with a picture of the last judgment. What is the order of ideas which connects points apparently so THE GORGIAS 277 remote ? Plato has made rhetoric the special subject of two dialogues, the Gorgias and the Phacdrus-, in the latter he treats it from its literary and logical, in the former from its ethical and political, side. In the former dialogue it is brought before us as the typical instrument of human power, the art of swaying men and so doing what we please. On this ground it is maintained by the rhetorician to be the greatest of all arts. Thus the issue is raised, Is the mere power to satisfy desire, and the mere pleasure accompanying such satisfaction, the greatest good ? Socrates denies it, and denies it on the ground that neither power in itself nor pleasure in itself con- stitutes a good or end at all, and that we only make them such by introducing into them a quite different principle, which is already the germ of morality ; in other words, that a consistently non-moral theory of life is logically self-destructive. We here come upon the most fundamental and characteristic idea in Plato's philosophy of life, and the one also which, to the modern mind, it is most difficult to seize, the idea which may be most shortly expressed by saying that the moral is the rational. The constant appeal to the arts and sciences which we are struck with in the Gorgias and other ethical dialogues is not merely illustrative ; it expresses Plato's conviction that all life exhibits reason, and that morality is simply the recognition of this reason in a particular sphere. It is the more important to insist upon this feature in the Gorgias, because of all Plato's dialogues it is that in which he most combines the tone of the prophet and the preacher with that of the philo- sopher. Nowhere else are we so vividly reminded of the Biblical antithesis between sin and righteousness, the flesh and the spirit ; nowhere else does the ' love of 278 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD wisdom' seem to come so near to the 'love of God.' Yet nowhere else is Plato more himself. The opposition of his enemy is not drowned in denunciatory thunders, or absorbed in a personal assurance of salvation ; the concentrated eloquence and relentless logic with which he upholds the cause of right and truth are met by the champion of pleasure and power with language as forcible and conviction as unbending ; and under their expressions of irony or contempt there are not wanting gleams of mutual admiration and pity. And while the philosopher defiantly proclaims his isolation from the world, while he refuses to count heads or to admit witnesses, and relies only upon consistency with himself and the evidence of his own soul, it is still the unquench- able desire for the good of men which sustains him ; the same Socrates who will not allow that any Athenian politician has realized his own ideal is proud to claim for himself the almost solitary glory of truly serving the state. The problem of the Gorgias is developed in three stages, in which the antithesis, implicit from the first, becomes gradually more explicit, and the rival solutions more radical. Gorgias, the famous master of rhetoric, with whom in the first part of the dialogue Socrates is confronted, is represented as a man of honesty and prin- ciple, but quite unaware of the inconsistency which is latent in the theory of his art. He is treated by Socrates with elaborate but unyielding courtesy, and retires from his untenable position to make room for Polus 1 i the wild ' colt ' of his school, who prances into the field to the defence of his master. Polus sees that the inconsistency proved against Gorgias arose from his making a certain 1 UmXos (Polus) is the Greek for ' colt.' THE GORGIAS 279 concession to public opinion, and boldly proclaims his own emancipation from moral prejudices ; but, as he still retains the feeling that there is something ' disgraceful ' in doing injustice, he is gradually reduced to a dilemma from which the only escape is by denying any but a ' conventional ' validity to all moral distinctions, and asserting as the ' law of nature ' the right of every one to do what he pleases as far as he has the power. This final step is taken by Callicles, the brilliant and cultivated politician and man of the world, who sticks at nothing, believes in nothing, and fears nothing. The tone of Socrates, who has managed the sprawling impetuosity of Polus with high-handed but playful contempt, changes, as the struggle deepens in the third part, into that of set resolve and incisive earnestness, as of a man certain of death but certain also of victory. The argument opens as follows. Gorgias, the great rhetorician, asked by Socrates what is the nature of his art, defines it as the art of producing persuasion by the use of words, asserting at the same time that it confers upon its possessor the greatest of goods, freedom for himself and power over others. When further asked to distinguish it from arts like arithmetic, which also pro- duce persuasion, he explains that the subject-matter of rhetorical persuasion is justice and injustice, and its sphere the courts of law and other large assemblies, while the conviction which it produces is not that of knowledge (which is necessarily true), but that of belief (which may or may not be true) : in fact, rhetoric only ' persuades,' it does not also ' teach.' — It would appear, then, to Socrates that when the popular assembly has to be advised upon any technical matter, such as health, ship-building, war, the persons to advise will be those who have the technical 280 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD knowledge in question, not the rhetorician. — But Gorgias points out that it was Themistocles and Pericles, not the architects, by whose advice the ports and walls of Athens were built ; that it is the orators who carry the elections of generals ; that he himself has often induced a patient to submit to treatment when the doctors had failed ; in fact, that there is no subject on which a good rhetorician could not carry a mass of people with him against a man of technical knowledge ; so that the rhetorical faculty may be said to have all other faculties under its single control. On the other hand, though it is so powerful, this is no reason why the rhetorician should depreciate the men of technical knowledge, or why the public should hate or banish the teachers of rhetoric. The power may be unjustly used, of course, like the power of boxing; but this is not the fault of the power itself, or of those who impart it. — It seems to Socrates that there is an inconsistency in this position. Gorgias undertakes to make a man a good rhetorician, that is, to enable a man who has no technical knowledge of a subject to speak to a crowd, that is, to persons who also have no technical knowledge, more persuasively than a man who knows the subject. The speaker, then, may be ignorant of what he is speaking about, but he must be able to produce the appearance to other ignorant people of knowing more than those who know. Now what Socrates wishes to be told is, whether the relation of rhetoric to moral matters is the same as to technical matters ; whether it is enough for the good speaker to appear to ignorant people to know about justice and injustice, or whether he must have really learnt them before he can be a good speaker. — Gorgias thinks that he must have really learnt them. — But this implies that THE GORGIAS 281 the good speaker must be a just man ; for a man who has learnt justice is just, as a man who has learnt music is a musician. And yet Gorgias spoke before of a pos- sible unjust use of rhetoric ! . The position of Gorgias is that of an honourable but unphilosophical man, who regards his art as an instrument or faculty, but has an instinctive feeling that its pos- session ought to go along with its right use. What Socrates does is to press into relief the two inconsistent ideas which coexist comfortably in his mind. If rhetoric is a mere faculty which admits of being used well or ill, then the teacher of it must not assume an operative knowledge of moral principles as part of his stock-in- trade. He must consent to divorce his art from morality, and regard it as the method of making anything look plausible. This is just what a great master of the art recoils from. He knows that his power is most con- spicuously exercised in connexion with questions of right and wrong, not with technical questions ; he knows that he can dispense to a great extent with technical know- ledge, and yet be successful ; and he shrinks from admit- ting that his hold upon morality may be as superficial as his hold upon medicine or navigation. Thus, while he professes to regard the power which his art confers as in itself the greatest of goods, he silently imports into his conception of mere power an additional element of moral principle, and saves his conscience at the expense of his consistency. Polus sees this clearly, and attributes it to a concession to custom. Everybody, he explains, would of course say that a rhetorician must have learnt justice, but it is mere philistinism to base arguments upon such admissions. 1 Gorgias, 449C-461 A. 282 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD And now he would like to know what sort of art Socrates himself considers rhetoric to be. Socrates replies that he does not consider it an ' art ' at all. Rhetoric, as he understands it, is an ' empirical,' not a ' technical ' ac- complishment : it requires ' a good eye, and courage, and natural ability in dealing with men,' but it cannot give an account of its processes or assign their causes, and therefore is not an art, for no ' unaccountable ' thing deserves the name of art. The object of this empirical accomplishment is to produce pleasure ; in other words, to flatter. If we start with the distinction between soul and body, we may divide flattery into four parts, as follows. The body and the soul may be in a really good, or in an apparently good, condition, and there are certain arts which cultivate the real good of each ; those which cultivate that of the soul are the legislative and judicial arts (two branches of the political art), and those which cultivate that of the body are gymnastic and medicine. Answering to these four genuine arts there are four counterfeits, which do not know but guess, and which aim, not at the good, but at the pleasure, of their subjects. The counterfeit of medicine is the art of confectionary, that of gymnastic the tiring art 1 , that of the legislative art is sophistic, and that of the judicial art rhetoric ; and, as the judicial and legislative arts have much in common from their common subject-matter, so rhetoric and so- phistic get mixed up with one another and are often very hard to distinguish. Each of these species of flattery professes to know what is best for its subject, but really aims at nothing but what happens to be pleasantest at 1 KofJifxajriKT) is the whole art of 'getting oneself up': the art of ' encasing oneself in a spurious beauty by shaping and colouring and smoothing and dressing.' — Gorg. 465 B. THE GORGIAS 283 the moment. Rhetoric, then, does for the soul what confectionery docs for the body l . Polus is surprised that Socrates should think so little of rhetoric ; surely the rhetoricians have great power in the state ; ' do they not put to death whom they wish, and plunder and banish just as they fancy, like tyrants? ' But Socrates distinguishes : it is one thing to do ' what one wishes,' another to do ' what one fancies 2 ' ; the tyrant and the rhetorician do the second, but not the first. For let us consider. When we do a thing, which is in itself neither good nor bad, for the sake of something good, it is the latter thing, not the former, that we really wish. Now the tyrant or the rhetorician in ques- tion kills or plunders or banishes for the sake of some- thing good, that is, because he thinks it is better for him. But suppose that it happens not to be better for him ; then he may be said to do what he fancies, but he cannot be said to do what he wishes. If, then, ' having great power ' means something good, the fact that the rheto- rician can kill, plunder, and banish whom he fancies does not imply that he has great power, or that he does what he wishes 3 . Nay, further, Socrates is ready to prove that, except under certain conditions, both he and Polus would decline such a power as the rhetorician possesses. Polus would decline it, for instance, unless he could exercise it with im- punity ; Socrates, unless he could exercise it justly. Both, therefore, mean by ' having great power,' not the mere power to do certain things, but the power to do them in a way which is good for themselves ; otherwise we should 1 Go rgias, 461 B-466 A. 2 Tlouiv a @ov\ovtcu, noitiv a doicti avrots. lb. 466 E. 3 lb. 466 A-468 E. 284 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD all think power, not a great and good, but a little and bad, thing to have. The only question is, When are things good for us, when bad ? Socrates maintains they are good when done justly, bad when done unjustly. — Polus thinks that any child could confute Socrates. Look at Archelaus, the new ruler of Macedonia ; he cut the throats of his uncle and cousin, drowned his brother, and usurped the throne. Is he the most miserable man in Macedonia ? Who would not like to be Archelaus ? — This is not what Socrates understands by being confuted. It is the way of the rhetoricians in the law-courts : they produce a number of distinguished men to witness to the truth of what they say, and, if their opponent produces few or none, they think their case is proved. No doubt Polus could find plenty of witnesses among the great men of Athens ; but no amount of false evidence will ' drive a man out of the reality and the truth.' One witness, and one only, Socrates engages to have on his side before he has done, and that is Polus himself; and he cares to have no more. What, then, are the points at issue between them ? They involve no less a question than that of the nature of human happiness. Polus maintains that it is possible for an unjust man to be happy, Socrates maintains that it is impossible. Polus holds that an unjust man is happy if he goes unpunished ; Socrates holds that he is miserable in any case, but less miserable if he is punished, more miserable if he is unpunished. Polus would like to know, then, whether an unjust aspirant to tyranny is happier if he is caught, racked, mutilated, blinded, crucified, or impaled, than if he succeeds and has a glorious reign. Ask any of the audience. To Socrates this seems mere ' bogey ' talk ; and, as to putting it to THE GORGIAS 285 the vote of the audience, he does not know enough of politics to do that ; there is only one person whose vote he knows how to ask for, and that is the person with whom he is arguing 1 . Let us take, then, the first question first. While main- taining that to suffer injustice is more ' evil ' than to do it, Polus admits that to do injustice is the more ' ugly ' : he distinguishes between ' evil ' and ' ugly,' ' good ' and ' beautiful.' He further admits that things are beautiful in virtue either of some use which they serve, or of some pleasure which they give, or of both. The beautiful, then, is definable as either the good or the pleasant, or both ; the ugly is either the evil or the painful, or both ; and this applies equally to such things as the human form and works of art, and to such things as laws and institutions. If then to do injustice is more ugly than to suffer it, it must exceed the latter either in pain or in evil, or in both ; clearly it does not exceed it in pain, and therefore not in both ; it must therefore exceed it in evil, and be worse. And, as no one can prefer the worse to the better, no one can prefer doing injustice to suffering it 2 . And now for the second point at issue. Which is the greater evil, to do injustice and be justly punished for it, or to do it with impunity? Punishment implies an agent and a patient, and wherever this relation exists we find that, in whatever way the agent acts, in that way the patient is acted upon. If, then, punishment be justly in- flicted, the recipient receives what is just ; and what is just is allowed by Polus to be also beautiful ; the person who is justly punished, then, must receive benefit from the punishment (for he clearly does not receive pleasure, 1 Gorgias, 468 E-474 A. 2 lb. 474 B-475 E. 286 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD and we agreed that the beautiful might be defined as either the beneficial or the pleasant). The particular benefit which he receives is riddance of evil in his soul, that is, vice, which of all kinds of evil Polus admits to be the ugliest, and therefore the worst (for it is clearly not the most painful). Justice then does for the soul what medicine does for the body, and economy for wealth ; and, as the ugliness of vice is greater than that of disease or poverty, so the beauty of justice is greater than that of medicine or economy. The happiest man, then, is he who has no evil in his soul ; the next happiest he who gets rid of it, that is, who is justly punished ; and those who fly from the pain of justice are like children who are afraid of the doctor. The most miserable of all are those who do injustice and are not punished, and the second in misery are those who do injustice under any circum- stances and with whatever result. What, then, can be the use of rhetoric ? None at all for defending ourselves or our friends when we have done wrong ; it might possibly be of some use in bringing ourselves to justice ; on the other hand, if we wished to do anybody all the harm in our power, we might use rhetoric to save him from a punishment which he deserved \ In this second part of the dialogue the real nature of the argument begins to emerge. Gorgias had admitted, firstly, that rhetoric did not imply knowledge, though he inconsistently maintained that it did imply moral knowledge ; and, secondly, he had claimed for it the production of the greatest good, freedom and power, though he assumed that the power might be wrongly, and ought to be rightly, used. Polus holds that the admission of a moral principle by Gorgias was a mere 1 Gorgias, 476 A-481 B. THE GORGIAS 287 concession ; that the power which rhetoric confers is simply the power to do what one likes, right or wrong ; and that this is the true object of human desire. Socrates correspondingly denies that rhetoric, so under- stood, is an art at all ; that the power so conferred is what men mean by power ; and that it is a real object of desire. Thus the abandonment of moral principle is treated by Plato as the abandonment of all principle ; life becomes irrational in proportion as it becomes immoral. f The good,' wherever it is found, means principle ; it is that which gives aim, order, coherence. Pleasure is opposed to it just because it has no principle, but is the chance feeling of the moment. In the highest things and in the lowest there is a right and a wrong ; the right always means that the thing in question is recognized to have a reason, the wrong that it is re- cognized to have none. The test, alike of the truth and the goodness of a principle, is, how much it will explain, how far it radiates, what amount of diverse elements it correlates. The confectioner's art as compared with that of the doctor is ' empirical,' because it has no object but to please the palate, and the mere pleasure of the palate compared with the health of the whole body carries us very little way in the economy of physical life. So far as it does carry us, it will be found to be not pleasure as such, but some particular kinds of plea- sure, which give the principle on which the confectioner works ; and what these particular kinds are will be determined by something else than pleasure, which something will be the real ground of the principle. The same point is illustrated by the distinction which Plato here draws between ' doing what we wish ' and ' doing what we fancy.' Just as it is not any mere 288 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD pleasure of any mere moment which is the real object of desire, so it is not the power to do whatever seems good at any moment which we really mean when we think of power as a thing worth having. We unconsciously import into it some condition, and make it the power to do something with a certain motive ; not the fancy of the moment because it is the fancy of the moment, but the fancy of the moment because it is felt to be good for us, is the real substance of our wish. And, as soon as we have said this, we have put ourselves upon something like a principle, something which can be tested, com- pared, argued upon, an element in an order of things from which we cannot escape, and to which we may refuse to conform, but only at the cost of bringing discord into our lives. Some such principle is still recognized by Polus, though he professes to make no concessions to what he regards as moral prejudices. He still has a feeling that, though to do wrong is not ' worse ' than to suffer it, it is yet somehow or other more foul, more disgraceful, more ' ugly.' The last term and its opposite ' beautiful ' are the most literal equivalents for the untranslatable Greek words, alaxpov and Kakop. The analysis of beauty into utility and pleasure, goodness and charm, and the indis- criminate application of it to natural, artistic, and ethical objects, will be better considered in another place. The important point here is the effect assigned to the vague feeling of disapprobation which Polus still retains for wrong-doing. That effect is to give another blow to the claim of pleasure to be the principle of goodness. It draws attention to the fact that, as long as any sort of distinction is felt between right and wrong, the feel- ing of the distinction cannot be resolved into one of mere pleasure or pain, for there is no necessary pain in THE GORGIAS 289 doing wrong ; any sense of its undesirablcness which we may have must be a sense that it is in some way worse for us, and this again commits us to the conception of a life determined by some end, a life of which the ulti- mate postulate is that it must be reasonable. We have already partially anticipated the develop- ment of the third and last section of the dialogue. Callicles begins by asking whether Socrates is really in earnest ; for, if what he has been saying is true, the whole of life is turned upside down, and we are all doing the very opposite of what we ought to do. Socrates can explain to Callicles how it is that he says these strange things. He is in love with philosophy, as Callicles is in love with the Athenian populace ; and lovers tend to say the same as their beloved. When Callicles speaks in the popular assembly, Socrates observes that, if the people disagree with him, he has to come round to what they wish. And so it is with Socrates ; it is philosophy, his beloved, who is always saying these things to him, and always the same things ; and, if Callicles does not like them, he must stop the mouth of philosophy, and prove that what she says is false. If he cannot do that, his whole life will be a discord ; and that is the worst of all discords ; for it is better to have your lyre or your chorus out of tune than to be out of tune with your own self 1 . What Socrates says seems to Callicles nothing but vulgar rant. The reason why he was able to silence Gorgias and Polus was only that they were ashamed to say what they thought. First, Gorgias admitted that he should teach his pupils morality if they had not learnt it when they came to him ; and then Polus admitted that to do wrong was more ugly than to suffer it ; and so 1 Gorgias, 481 B-482 C. VOL. I. U 290 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD they were both made to contradict themselves. But these are mere vulgar commonplaces to which Socrates appealed, based upon law, not upon nature, which is generally the opposite of law. Socrates took advantage of their hesitating to violate certain conventional ideas, and then silently substituted the natural for the con- ventional meaning of the ideas. Thus when Polus admitted that it was more foul or base to do than to suffer injustice, meaning ' conventionally more base/ Socrates pressed the admission in the sense of ' naturally more base ' ; whereas ' naturally ' it is baser to suffer injustice, and no one but a helpless slave would endure it. The truth is that the laws are made by the weaker majority of mankind, who, in order to protect themselves and to frighten the stronger, proclaim that it is unjust and disgraceful for one man to have more than another. But what nature herself declares to be just is that the better should have more than the worse, the stronger than the weaker ; this is ' the real law of nature,' and it comes out clearly enough in the doings both of men and the other animals. The law which we make, indeed, and with which we confine our noblest youth, like lions, in a charmed slavery, says that justice means equality ; but, when a man is born great enough, he breaks the spell and tramples on all our parchment laws, and stands up our master instead of our slave, and the justice of nature shines out in its strength. This is what Pindar meant when he sang of ' Law, the universal king.' And this is what Socrates would see to be the truth, if he would leave philosophy and take to higher things. Philosophy is all very well up to a ceitain point. As a part of the education of the young it is a graceful accomplishment, and no gentleman can dispense with it. But if pursued THE GORGIAS 291 into later life it is the ruin of a man, even though he have great natural gifts ; it makes him ignorant of the laws of his country, of the language of public life and society, of the pleasures and desires of the world, and of human nature in general ; and, when he has to do any- thing practical, he is ridiculous, as ridiculous as politicians probably are when they try to talk philosophy. The right way is to have some of both : philosophy when one is a boy, real life when one is grown up. A grown man who goes on with philosophy is as contemptible as one who goes on lisping like a child, and he deserves to be beaten. He will never be able to show his face in public, in ' the arena of fame ' as the poet calls it, but will pass his life in a corner whispering his wisdom to three or four schoolboys. Callicles has a regard for Socrates, and would put it to him, as a friend, whether so noble a soul ought to show itself in so childish a figure ; whether it is not disgraceful that he and others who go deep into philosophy should be, as they are, at the mercy of any scoundrel who might choose to bring them before a court of justice ; whether there can be much wisdom in an art which so incapacitates its most gifted devotees from protecting themselves or others that a man may slap them in the face with impunity. Surely it would be better to give up this ingenious nonsense, and take to the culture of life and action 1 . Socrates congratulates himself on having found in Callicles a real ' touchstone ' by which to test his theory. Callicles has all the three requisites, wisdom, frankness, and goodwill. If he can be got to agree with Socrates, it will not be from deficiency in ability ; it certainly will not be from excess of modesty ; nor will it be with the 1 Gorgias, 482 C-486 D. U 2 292 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD intention of deceiving. If the theory will stand such a test, it needs no other proof of its truth. What, then, is the question at issue between them ? It is the great question, what a man ought to be and what he ought to pursue all his life long. Callicles, in answering the ques- tions of Socrates, maintains natural justice to be that the better, superior, and stronger should rule over, and have more than, the worse, inferior, and weaker. And by this he does not mean the numerically or physically ' stronger,' or those who are ' superior ' in certain par- ticular kinds of knowledge, but he means (for he will speak out) that the right and natural principle of life is for a man to let his appetites be as great as possible, and to have the wisdom and the courage to satisfy them. Most people cannot do this, and so they abuse those who can ; but, for a man who had the power, nothing could be baser than continence. The truth is (and Socrates professes to seek truth) that luxury, licence, and freedom are virtue and happiness ; all this other finery, this unnatural conventionality, is worthless non- sense of man's invention 1 . Socrates is glad that Callicles has spoken out. The ideal man, then, is he who has the greatest appetites and can satisfy them ; to call a man happy who had no wants would seem to Callicles as reasonable as to call a stone or a corpse happy. But suppose the truth were, as Euripides says, that death is life, and that it is we who are really the dead ? There is an old philosophical allegory which says that the body is a tomb in which the soul is buried out of sight ; the soul of the unwise (the ' uninitiated,' this allegory calls them) is like a sieve, because it retains nothing ; and the appetitive part of 1 Gorgias, 486 D-492 C. THE GORGIAS 293 the soul is like a pitcher with a hole in it, because it is never filled, and its opinions are always going up and down ; and in the unseen world the life of the uninitiated is of all the most miserable, for they are always carrying water in a leaking sieve to fill their leaking pitcher. If this quaint conceit does not convince Callicles that the life of order and contentment is better than that of insatiate licence, here is another image from the same school. Suppose two men with a number of pitchers for wine, honey, milk, and other liquors, and that the liquors are very scarce and hard to get ; suppose that the one man's pitchers are sound and full, and he has no more to think about, while those of the other are rotten and leaky, and he has to keep filling them night and day, or suffer torments of thirst : which is the happier life ? Callicles still holds that the first of the two is the life of a stone ; the more there is to flow in, the greater the pleasure. Yes, is the answer, but the more there flows in, the more there must flow out ; such a life is the life of a cormorant 1 . But what appetites does Callicles refer to ? To be consistent, he is ready to include all, even the foulest ; he will say that the good and the pleasant are absolutely identical. But can this be? For, firstly, Callicles will admit courage and knowledge to be not identical either with each other or with pleasure ; how then can he main- tain good to be identical with pleasure ? Secondly, he will admit that well-faring and ill-faring, good and evil, happiness and unhappiness, are as opposite to each other as health and disease, strength and weakness, quickness and slowness ; and that it is as impossible for any one to fare well and ill simultaneously, or to cease faring well 1 Gorgias, 492 D-494 B. 294 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD and ill simultaneously, as it is to be healthy and diseased, or to cease being healthy and diseased, simultaneously ; yet a person who is thirsty and drinks feels pain and pleasure simultaneously, and ceases to feel them simul- taneously. Thirdly, he will admit that what he calls ' good ' men are made good by the presence of good things, as it is the presence of beauty which makes beautiful things beautiful ; and he does not call cowards and fools good men ; yet cowards and fools, as he allows, experience at least as much pleasure and pain as the brave and wise ; if, then, pleasure and pain are good and evil, and the presence of them makes those who feel them good or bad, we shall have to say that bad men are as good and as bad as good men 1 . Callicles, who has only been answering such petti- fogging questions to please Gorgias and to satisfy Socrates' childish love of argument, now announces that of course he, like everybody else, thinks some pleasures better than others. There are, then, Socrates pursues, good and bad pleasures, that is, pleasures which do good and pleasures which do harm ; and so with pains. And this good which they do is what makes us choose and do pleasant and painful things ; that is, we choose pleasure for the sake of good, not good for the sake of pleasure. Now this choosing is clearly not a thing in the power of every one ; it requires a man who has the art. And this brings us back to the distinction made before between the empiricism of the confectioner, for instance, and the art of the physician. To this distinction Socrates begs Callicles to attend seriously, for, unless they agree about it, they cannot settle the question at issue — the question, which life they ought to try to live, the political life of 1 Gorgias, 494 B-499 B. THE GORGIAS 295 Callicles or the philosophic life of Socrates. The ground of the distinction, then, is this. There are two methods of treating the soul ; the one, which aims at what is best for the soul, investigates the nature of its subject-matter, and can give an account of its own processes ; the other, which aims only at giving pleasure, that is, at flattery, has never investigated the nature and cause of pleasure, or attempted to classify it into better and worse ; it is a mere rule of thumb, based upon memory of what usually occurs. Instances of the second kind of method are, in Socrates' opinion, all such arts as those of public players and singers, of dithyrambic and even of tragic poets ; since tragedy, for all its grand air, never declines to say what pleases the populace on the ground that it is bad for them, and, if divested of melody, rhythm, and metre, is only a sort of mob-oratory and rhetoric. And what are we to say of rhetoric proper ? To which method does it belong ? l Callicles would make a distinction ; some rhetoricians, he thinks, have no care for the good of the citizens in what they say, but there are some who do care. He can- not indeed mention any such now living, but from what he hears he believes that Themistocles, Cimon, Miltiades, and Pericles were good men, and made the Athenians better. Socrates cannot think so, unless goodness means indiscriminate satisfaction of appetite ; otherwise, which of these men answers to the requirements of a good rhetorician? A man who in speaking aims at what is best will not speak at random, but with something in view. This is true of all artists — painters, architects, shipbuilders, and the rest ; they do not put their materials together at random, but in a certain order, compelling 1 Gorgias, 499 B-502 E. 296 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD one piece to fit with another so that their work may have a definite form. And in the same way trainers and physicians, in treating the body, try to organize it and put it in order. It is this presence of order which distinguishes a good ship or house from a bad one, and if we are consistent we must say the same of the soul. Health is the name given to order in the body ; law, resulting in justice and temperance, to that in the soul. To produce this order, then, will be the aim of the ' good and artistic ' speaker in all that he says and does ; and, if the soul which he addresses be in a bad state, he will only indulge those appetites which are good for it, and will restrain the others, just as the physician does with the diseased body. Restraint, there- fore, must be better for the soul than the absolute licence which Callicles considered happiness 1 . First, then (since Callicles here declines to answer any more, and advises Socrates to finish his argument by himself), let us recapitulate our results. The good and the pleasant are not the same, and the pleasant must be done for the sake of the good. Everything, natural and artificial, soul and body, is made good by the presence of its own virtue, and is given by this virtue its proper order, Tightness, art. The good soul is that which has this order, that is, which is temperate. Such a soul will behave in the right way to men, gods, and circumstances, and will therefore be just, religious, and brave. This is perfect goodness, and goodness is well-being, and well- being is happiness. Temperance, therefore, is the mark at which a man must aim if he would be happy, and licence is what he must fly from. The robber's life of unrestrained appetite makes communion, and therefore 1 Gorgias, 503 A-505 B. • THE GORGIAS 297 friendship, impossible, either with gods or men 1 . It is friendship, orderliness, temperance, and justice which, as wise men tell us, hold together heaven and earth and men and gods, and this is why they call the universe 'order' (cosmos); Callicles has not sufficiently realized the ' power of geometrical equality.' And, if these things are true, it follows that the paradoxes of Socrates, and the concessions forced from Gorgias and Polus, are true also, and the helplessness to resist injustice, which Callicles called so shameful, is not so shameful as the doing of the injustice. These consequences seem to Socrates to be ' riveted with reasons of iron and adamant'; he only knows that he has never yet found anybody who could ' undo ' them. And, if this is so, of all kinds of helplessness the most shameful is to be unable to help ourselves or our friends not to do injustice 2 . There are, then, two evils, doing injustice and suffering it ; and the first is the greater. By what means can we protect ourselves against them ? It clearly is not enough merely to ' wish ' not to suffer injustice ; and, as we saw in the argument with Polus, nobody ' wishes ' to do it ; the avoidance of both evils, therefore, implies some power or art. The way to avoid suffering injustice is either to rule in the state ourselves, or to be the friends of those who rule. And to be their friends we must be as like them as possible : if we are much better than they, they will fear us ; if much worse, they will despise us. But the way to escape doing injustice will be the opposite of this : imitation of those in power would be the very way to do the most of it, and to ruin one's soul. Socrates does not want telling that the man who 1 Cp. Republic, i. 351 B-352 B. 2 Gorgias, 505C-509C. 298 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD takes the second way will be at the mercy of the man who takes the first ; but what of that ? Is it our sole business to keep ourselves alive as long as possible ? If Callicles thinks so much of rhetoric, why does he think so little of such arts as swimming, navigation, or military engineering? Do they not save life, and in some cases a great deal more than life? The pilot brings us all the way from Egypt to Athens for two drachmae, and does not give himself airs in consequence. How, indeed, can he be sure that it would not have been better for us if he had left us in the sea ? The engineer does not preach to us all to become engineers, and yet he saves the lives of a whole city. Why does Callicles despise him, and refuse to marry his daughter ? ' Because Callicles is a better man, and better born.' But, if good- ness consists in keeping life alive at all costs, how is Callicles better? The truth is, no one who is really a man thinks about how long he is to live ; he leaves that to God, knowing, as women say, that ' we must all die some time' ; what he thinks about is, how he can best spend the time that is given him. Shall we then get power at the peril of our souls, and make ourselves as like the Athenian people as we can? For assuredly there is no other art or device by which a man can succeed as a politician and rhetorician, as Callicles understands success x . Let us recall what we said before about the two methods of treating souls, the one aiming at giving them pleasure, the other at making them better. Clearly the latter must be the method of the true politician ; for what is the good of giving people wealth or power before their minds are in a good condition? Now, supposing 1 Gorgias, 509 C-513 C. THE GORGIAS 299 we were trying for the place of architect or physician to the state, we should ask ourselves, firstly, Have wc learnt architecture or medicine ? and secondly, What buildings have wc produced, or what patients have we treated, and are the buildings good or bad, the patients better or worse ? So with politics, which Callicles is just taking up himself, and exhorts Socrates to take up ; must wc not ask, Is there any one in Athens who was bad before — unjust, licentious, foolish, — and whom Callicles has made good ? Let us apply this test to the men whom he mentioned as instances of good citizens, Pericles, Cimon, Miltiades, Themistocles. Were the Athenians better at the end of Pericles' career than at the beginning ? Socrates has been told that they were worse ; that Pericles, by his system of public payments, made them idlers, cowards, babblers, money-lovers. And, if this is a conservative calumny, it is at any rate a fact that, while Pericles began by being popular, towards the end of his life he was condemned for embezzlement and nearly put to death. Surely, if he had been a good statesman, he ought to have made the creatures under his management more tame and just instead of more wild and unjust ; at least, that is what we should expect from a man who had to manage asses or horses or oxen. The same thing is shown by the ostracism of Cimon, the banishment of Themistocles, the condemnation of Miltiades ; it is not the good driver who waits to be upset until he has had a long time for improving himself and his horses 1 . We may repeat, therefore, that 'we know of no one in this state who has been a good statesman,' and of the men whom Callicles instanced we must say that, 1 Gorgias, 513C-516E. 300 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD if they were rhetoricians, they understood neither true rhetoric nor the rhetoric of flattery. No doubt, as Callicles urges, they achieved greater things than any living statesman ; but this only means that they were better ' ministers ' to the state — that is, to the pas- sions and appetites of its members ; in controlling and directing such appetites they were no better. They were men who seem to Socrates to have done for the state much what our great cooks and bakers and wine- dealers do for our bodies ; they add flesh to them, but at the expense of the flesh we had before ; and when we get ill long afterwards, instead of blaming them, we blame those who happen to be advising us at the moment. So with the state. The men who fed it up and made it great with trash like harbours, docks, walls, and revenues, with no virtue in them, are glorified by the present generation, who do not see that it is swollen and festering ; and, when the crisis of the disease comes, they will continue to praise Themistocles, and Cimon, and Pericles, who are the causes of the evil, and they will lay hands on men like Callicles and Alcibiades, who are partly perhaps, but not wholly, responsible for it \ Nor have public men any right to complain so bitterly as they do of the injustice with which they are treated by their country, to which they claim to have done so much good. They are as unreasonable as the sophists, who profess to teach virtue, and then accuse their pupils of wronging them by their ingratitude. If they have put justice into them, how can it issue in injustice? And, though Callicles objects to putting statesmen and rhetoricians on the same level with sophists, Socrates can see scarcely any difference between them ; indeed, he 1 Go?-gias, 517 A-519 B. THE GORGIAS 301 puts sophistic above rhetoric, as he puts the legislative art above the judicial, and gymnastic above medicine. Surely public speakers and sophists are just the persons who cannot blame those whom they educate, without at the same time condemning their own incompetence. They are also the only persons who ought to be able to dispense with a fixed charge for their services ; for, if they succeed in removing injustice, there is no fear of their not being justly requited. This seems to be the reason why the only advice for which it is thought dishonour- able to demand money is advice how to be a good man and citizen : it is the only form of benefit which must make the recipient wish to return it ; and, if he does not, it is a sign that the benefit has not been conferred l . And now which method of treatment does Callicles advise Socrates to adopt — that of fighting with the Athenians to make them as good as possible, or that of ministering to their pleasures ? Callicles still advises the second ; he wonders that Socrates is so confident and does not see that he is at the mercy of any scoundrel who likes to accuse him. Socrates, comes the answer, is wise enough to know that in Athens anything may happen to anybody ; nevertheless, he knows that he is innocent, and that no good man would accuse him. But, indeed, he would not be surprised if he were put to death, for ' he believes himself to be almost, if not quite, the only man in Athens who attempts the true art of politics' ; and so, if he is brought before a court of justice, he will be like a physician put on his trial by a confectioner before a court of children ; he will not be able to say that he has provided them with pleasures, and if he says the truth, that all his questionings and harsh criticisms were 1 Gorgias, 519 B-520 E. 302 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD for their good, who will listen to him? Still, whatever Callicles may think, this is not the helplessness of which a man need be ashamed ; the only help worth having is that which comes from having lived righteously ; to die for want of that help would indeed be grievous, but to die for want of flattering rhetoric is nothing. No one can fear death itself, unless he be utterly unthinking and unmanly ; but to go to the other world with his soul loaded with injustice, that is what every one must fear 1 . Listen to a story of these things (Callicles will think it only a story, but it is true nevertheless). In the reign of Cronos it was the law of the gods, as it still is, that those men who have lived righteously should go to the islands of the blessed and live in happiness, and those, who have lived unrighteously, to Tartarus, the prison- house of punishment. Formerly men used to be judged alive, and on the day on which they were to die ; and the judges also were alive. The consequence was that the wrong persons often went to the wrong place ; for those who came for judgment came clothed in their bodies and riches and rank, and there were witnesses with them to witness to their good lives ; the judges too had to judge through the veil of their eyes and ears and bodies. Hearing this, Zeus first made Prometheus take away from men the power of foreseeing their deaths ; and then he ordained that, when they came to be judged, they should be dead, naked, and alone, and that the judges also should be dead and naked, so that soul might see into soul. From this story we may draw the following conclusions. Death is nothing but the separa- tion of soul and body ; and when they are separated each retains the characteristics which it had during life ; if 1 Gorgias, 520 E-522 E. THE GORGIAS 303 the body was large or stout or scarred or maimed in life, it remains so for a time after death; and in the same way the soul, when stripped of the body, shows all the marks of its nature and habits. The judge, then, when it comes before him, does not know whose soul it is ; it may be that of the Great King himself; but, when he looks at it. he sees perhaps that it is full of scars and crookedness and disproportion, where perjury and in- justice, falsehood and conceit, wantonness and licence, have left their marks ; and he sends it away in dis- honour to be punished. Punishment has two ends, to improve and to warn. Those who are punished for their good are those whose sins are curable, though only by suffering both in this world and the next ; for suffering is the only way of getting rid of injustice. Incurable sinners are punished, not for their own good, but for that of others, to whom they are ' hung up in Hades as warnings,' suffering torments for ever. Most of them have been tyrants, kings or rulers, for they, having the greatest power, commit the greatest sins. Not but that there have been and will be good rulers and kings, and these deserve all our admiration, for it is hard for a man to live uprightly when he has great power to do wrong ; Aristides is one famous instance of a man who was able to deal justly with whatever was put into his hands. When, then, the judge sees a wicked soul, all that he knows is that it is wicked, and he marks it as curable or incurable and sends it to Tartarus ; and when he finds a soul that has lived a righteous life, the life perhaps of a single-minded philosopher, he sends it with admiration to the islands of the blessed 1 . Socrates is persuaded of the truth of these sayings, 1 Gorgias, 522 E-526 D. 304 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD and is seeking how he may present his soul to the judge as healthy as possible. With this end he puts aside the honours of the world, and strives, by looking for the truth, to live and die as good a man as he can. This is the prize which he would call Callicles and the rest of mankind to live for ; it is worth all other prizes ; and it will be shame to Callicles if he is helpless when he comes before the judge, and stands as dizzy and gaping there as Socrates would do here. This may all seem to him an old wives' tale, but have we found anything better? Three of the wisest living men in Greece — Gorgias, Polus, and Callicles — have been unable to prove that any life is worth living but that which profits hereafter. And, of all the theories which we have heard, the only one which has not been shaken is this : that to do injustice is worse than to suffer it ; that the best thing is to be just, and the next best thing to be made just by punishment ; that we must fly from all flattery of ourselves and of others, and that we must use rhetoric, and everything else that we touch, in the service of justice. This, if Callicles will believe it, is the only road to happiness, both in life and after death. If he will follow this with Socrates, he need not fear being despised and insulted, for nothing will be able to hurt him. And, when they have com- pleted their training in virtue, then it will be time to think of taking to politics and offering advice ; at present they have so neglected their education that on the greatest subjects they never think the same thing twice. The best life is to live and die in the practice of virtue: let this principle be our light and guide, not the principle in which Callicles put his trust, for that is worth nothing 1 . As a masterpiece of writing, the Gorgias must speak 1 Gorgias, 526 D-527 E. THE GORGIAS 305 for itself; its effect can only be weakened by comment. All that is necessary here is to draw attention to the logic of its conclusion, which is liable to be obscured by the very force with which it is expressed. The issue in which the dialogue culminates is that between the life of 'philosophy' and the life of 'politics.' The antithesis thus stated suggests to modern ears that between specu- lation and action, or (still more misleadingly) that between theory and practice. But consideration shows that Plato is not here opposing the scientific investiga- tor of politics to the working statesman, still less the academic to the parliamentary politician. The true modern equivalent to the opposition which he has in his mind is that between principle and no principle. The question which he puts to the various advocates of power and pleasure is this : ' When you say that power and pleasure are the best things, the things most worth having, do you really mean power and pleasure as such, the mere capacity to do anything and everything, the mere sensibility to any and every pleasant feeling ; or do you mean power to do and feel something which (for whatever reason) you consider good ? If the latter (and the latter is what you must mean), then you have admitted some other principle of life than the mere capacity of feeling or doing what pleases you.' The fact that there is some other principle than this, or rather that the only possible principle is something other than this, is to Plato the central fact, which alone makes life and the world intelligible. Wherever he looks, to the work of the artist, the doctor, the mechanic, to the constitution of human society, to the operations of nature, he finds that success, excellence, well-being, depend upon, or rather are identical with, the observance VOL. I. X 306 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD of a certain order or law. What the particular order is, and what the particular excellence of which it is the condition, depends on the nature of the thing in ques- tion ; bodily health and moral goodness, beauty and utility, are different excellences expressing different orders ; the all-important point to Plato is that they do express an order, and that only so far as they express it are they good. If this is the ultimate truth of things, and if 'philosophy ' is simply the operative love of truth, the ' philosophic ' life will be the life lived in the continual and growing consciousness of this truth ; in the consciousness that, whatever we have to deal with, be it a house or a living body, the physical universe or human society, we shall deal with it successfully just in proportion as we recognize that it has a principle of its own, and deal with it upon that principle. The ' philosophic ' statesman, then, is not the man who spends his time in dreaming of Utopias, but the man who takes for his aim, not to please, but to make men better, and who realizes that, while the former aim consistently carried out must dissipate itself in an aimless empiricism, the latter, starting with the re- cognition of reason as the primary factor in things, leads to greater and greater concentration of all effort in a more and more comprehensive end. In such a con- ception there is not necessarily involved any antagonism to active political life ; the antagonism is to a political rule of thumb, which regards, not the permanent interests of the people at large, but a transitory fragment of their nervous susceptibilities. It is true that Plato, when he wrote the Gorgias, was convinced that nearly all the great Athenian statesmen had failed of his ideal ; and he no doubt regarded the execution of Socrates as a crown- THE PH1LEBUS 307 ing proof of the triumph of that evil spirit in politics vhich seemed to him to have been silently gathering strength since the days of Miltiadcs and Themistocles. Tr> philosophers, as to other men, theories are the inter- pretation of their experience ; and, however true a prin- ciple of interpretation may be, the interpretation itself will always have a strong personal colouring. We are here concerned, not to judge Plato's judgment of Pericles in the Gorgias, but to understand the conception of statesmanship, and of human life generally, upon which his judgment was formed. That conception receives new light and development Phikbus. from the Philebus, a dialogue in most ways so unlike the Gorgias that the agreement of the two in certain im- portant points is the more striking. The Philebus is almost as remarkable for the absence, as the Gorgias is for the presence, of moral inspiration and dramatic power. The style seldom escapes from a cumbrous obscurity, and only here and there are the claims of pleasure to be the end of life combated with vehemence. The practical consequences of the doctrine are kept in the background, and the argument moves in a region of metaphysical and psychological analysis, the bearing of which upon the original question is often dubious or remote. Yet, under these differences of tone and treat- ment, the ground upon which the issue is decided is substantially the same as in the Gorgias. If the latter dialogue insists that life implies principle, and that power and pleasure as such cannot be made to yield a principle, the Philebus shows that the good cannot be found in mere feeling, because mere feeling is, strictly speaking, nothing, and gets whatever form or quality it X % 308 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD has from something other than feeling. And again, as in the Gorgias the evidence of reason in the world and human life is found in a certain order or law which determines otherwise random elements, so in the Philebus reality in general, and human consciousness in particular, are represented as an unquantified and unqualified matter which is continually taking definite character under the formative action of mind. Lastly, the conclusion sug- gested by the Gorgias, that the goodness of a thing is identical with its realized end or full reality, is explicitly developed in the Philebus, where it is finally affirmed that the divine good in the world is manifested under the triple form of measure, beauty, and truth. The question asked in the Philebus is one with which we are already familiar, What is the ' condition of soul which can make human life happy'? or, What is the ' best thing that a man can have,' in other words, 1 the good ' ? But the particular manner in which this question is treated will seem strange, and perhaps un- instructive, to a modern reader. The whole dialogue is dominated by an idea peculiarly Greek, and foreign, at least in this form, to the mind of Northern Europe. It has become almost a commonplace of modern culture to contrast the Greek view of life with its love of perfect attainment, and our own with its unsatisfied aspiration. ' To-day's brief passion limits their range ; It seethes with the morrow for us, and more. They are perfect — how else ? they shall never change : We are faulty — why not ? we have time in store.' There is truth in this contrast ; but it would be very misleading to suppose that, because the Greeks chose words like ' measure,' ' limit,' ' mean,' to express per- fection, they were devoid of what we call a 'sense of THE PHILEBUS 309 the infinite.' Assuredly the philosopher who wrote the Phaedrtis and the Symposium, who could speak of the longing of the soul to fly away and be at rest in its lost ' heaven ' of truth, or to abandon itself to the ' great sea ' of beauty, cannot have been the victim of a self-satisfied formalism. Much confusion would be avoided if it were remembered that ' limit ' may mean either that to which we are always getting, or that beyond which we never get ; in the first sense it is the condition of progress, in the second its negation. To the Greeks it meant primarily the first, to us it means primarily the second. The leading idea of the Philebus, divested of its peculiar phraseology, is as follows. All existence, human life and the life of nature alike, is a continual process or move- ment ; but it is a process which is being continually arrested. The formless and timeless stream of being, which we can only conceive as the negation of all that we know, is for ever taking shape, and becoming a describable and comprehensible world of things and events. The blank monotony differentiates itself, the chaotic multiplicity falls asunder into groups ; sound becomes rhythmical, speech articulate, time is measured, temperance is graduated ; human life, physical, intel- lectual, and moral, rises and falls according to laws of its own, which the doctor calls health, the philosopher truth, the moralist virtue. From such a point of view existence may be described as a perpetual resultant of two factors, a negative and a positive, that which is never anything in particular, and that which is ever making it something. Take any object or event, and try to characterize it ; each new quality which it exhibits gives it a fresh hold in the surrounding void ; on this side and on that, before and behind, welters a dim space which 310 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD becomes ever dimmer with distance; but here, at this point, there is fixity and limit, here the potential emerges into actuality, here the nothing has come to be some- thing. The productive, formative force, which is the source of the positive and characteristic element in things, Plato calls reason or mind. The rationality of the world seems to him to lie in its being measurable, rhythmical, articulate ; to understand any part of it is to find its unit of measurement or to trace the lines of its structure, and each new discovery is the reduction of a new piece of chaos to order. The idea of measure has to him something of the power and charm which invest the modern idea of law. The measure of a thing is its reality, its true self ; that which has no measure is neither anything itself, nor can it be brought into any relation with other things ; to fulfil its own measure, to be entirely what it is meant to be, and neither to exceed nor fall short of its place in the great whole of which ' God is the measure * ' — this is to obey the law of its existence both for itself and for others. In the particular sphere of human life the indeterminate and negative element of existence is the stream of feeling, so far as we can conceive it as absolutely devoid of order, direction, or result. So conceived it is, indeed, a mere abstraction, for no named or nameable feeling is of this utterly characterless nature ; it is always feeling of or about something, and this something is what qualifies it. The two feelings called pleasure and pain are, according to Plato's view, feelings which accompany the restoration and the disintegration of the normal harmony or balance of the animal organism ; pleasure is the sense of rising to a higher grade of vitality, pain the sense of falling 1 Laws, iv. 716 C. THE PHILEBUS 31 r from a grade to which we had risen. The character of both is given to them by the points between which they move. If they were consciousness of mere process, from nothing and to nothing, they would not, strictly speaking, be states of consciousness at all ; if, on the other hand, life were not a process, if we were not always coming to be or ceasing to be, wc should not have the specific feelings of pleasure and pain, we should have the sense of continual being, which now we can only have at moments. The contrast between Plato and the modern mind may be expressed by saying that the former loves to dwell upon the sense of attainment in life, the latter upon the sense of movement. The one says, ' Be your true self ; the other, ' Be better than you are.' The latter abhors a dead level, the former a motiveless change. We, like Callicles in the Gorgias 1 , are inclined to ask whether a life without either pleasure or pain is life at all, because we instinctively think of it as a compromise between the two, not as something above both. To enjoy the sense of rising is doubtless better than never to wish to rise, but to live permanently at the height is better than either, and only does not seem so because we are so incapable of experiencing it. And if it be asked, What is the thing most worth having in the world ? we can only answer in terms which give the priority, not to mere pleasurable feeling of process, but to that which we come to be in the process. If the end of our being is to be, to be the utmost we are capable of being, then the higher the constant level at which we can live, the less the energy which we have to spend in escaping the pain of depression, the more each moment contains in itself, and the less it borrows from felt contrast with 1 Above, pp. 292-3. 312 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD a lower past or a higher future, the more nearly do we approach the full measure, the full beauty, the full truth, in which, according to the Philebus, the principle of good is manifested. The dialogue opens by asking what is 'the best thing that a man can have.' Three alternatives are first suggested. Is it the sense of pleasure, or is it intellectual truth, or is it something better than either of these x ? We must begin by investigating the nature of pleasure. For, though it sounds such a simple thing, it is really most complex ; the licentious and the temperate, the fool and the wise, severally feel pleasure, but no reasonable person would hold that their pleasures are similar. It maybe said, indeed, that though they arise from opposite things they all resemble each other in being pleasure. But it is only very young or very incompetent reasoners who press such resemblances to the denial of all differ- ence ; and, if we would not drive logic into illogicality, we must admit that both in knowledge and pleasure there are differences, and that each, though one, is also many. Indeed, the truth is that this coexistence of unity and multiplicity, though a standing crux of logic, is an inherent attribute of all reality. Everything of which we say 'it is ' will be found to be both one and many, and to have in it a determining and an indeterminate element. To understand a thing is to see, not merely that it is one or that it is indefinitely manifold, but that its unity falls into two or more other unities, and each of these again into others, and so on until no further articulations can be detected ; or, again, to see that its indefinite multiplicity falls into definite groups, and each group into other groups, until we arrive at 1 Philebus ) n A-12 B, and 19C-20C. THE PHILEBUS 313 units forming the groups. And so, before we can answer the question whether pleasure or knowledge is the good, we should be able to classify their kinds, and say into how many forms the indeterminate unity of each is determined 1 . On reflexion, however, it appears that ' the good ' cannot be either pleasure or knowledge, but must be something other and better than either. For by ' the good ' we all understand something complete and sufficing, something which all desire to have, and without which they care to have nothing. Now neither a life of pleasure alone nor a life of intelligence alone satisfies these re- quirements. A life of pleasure entirely without intelli- gence would be the life of an oyster, not of a man ; we should neither know, conceive, remember, nor anticipate our pleasure. On the other hand, no one would choose the possession of all intelligence without any feelings of pleasure and pain. Every one would prefer to either life a life which combined both. The good, therefore, cannot be identical either with pleasure or with reason (not at least with human reason, for with the divine reason it may be otherwise) ; and the only question can be, which of the two contributes more to the good which is realized in their combination ? Neither can have the first prize ; which is to have the second ? 2 Now, human life is a form of being : what is being ? Everything of which we say ' it is ' will be found to be a resultant of ' the indeterminate ' or ' limitless ' and 'determination' or 'limit.' The 'indeterminate' may be described as that which has no quantitative limit, but is in continual process of increase and decrease, always a ' more ' or a ' less,' never a ' so much.' Examples of 1 Philebus, 12B-19B. - lb. 20 B-22 D. 3 i4 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD ' determination ' are number and measure, and everything which puts a stop to the difference of opposites, such as more and less, and makes them measurable and com- parable. Wherever these two elements combine, the result is a third form of being different from either ; and the indeterminate process now comes to be a determinate something. Thus it is the introduction of determination into indeterminate tone and time which produces music ; and from similar combinations result the temperature of the seasons, the health, beauty, and strength of the body, law and order in the soul, and innumerable other good things. Lastly, whatever comes into being must have a cause — in other words, must be produced by something ; and it is in the nature of things that that which produces is prior to that which is produced ; the former leads, the latter obeys. We must therefore distinguish cause as a fourth element from the other three 1 . Let us now apply this analysis to the question at issue. The life of combined pleasure and reason in which we have placed the good must, like all other complex forms of existence, involve determination of an indeterminate element. Of its two constituent factors pleasure clearly belongs to the indeterminate, for it is something which, in itself and as such, has neither beginning, middle, nor end. If it be said that its indeterminateness is just what makes it good, it must be answered that it is the same indeterminateness which makes pain evil ; therefore what- ever good there may be in pleasure must come from some other source 2 . Reason, on the other hand, would seem to be of the nature of cause. It is an old theory of some philosophers that mind is the king of heaven and earth, and it seems impossible to suppose that the universe is 1 Philebus, 23 B-27 C. 2 Cp. ib. 31 A and 32 B. THE PHILEDUS 315 regulated by irrational chance. Moreover, when we compare the elements of body (fire, water, air, and earth), as they exist in us, with these same elements as they exist in the universe, we see that the former are very much poorer in amount and force than the latter, by which they are produced, sustained, and controlled. The same is true of body as a whole ; our body depends on the body of the universe, not that of the universe on ours. Our body, again, is endowed with soul ; and must not the same considerations apply to that? Whence could we get it, unless the body of the universe were endowed with soul, as good as ours and better ? Surely we cannot suppose that the cause which works in us under the name of wisdom, keeping our body alive and in health and harmony, is not also working on a corre- spondingly grander scale in the grander field of the universe. We may say, then, that the determining and indeterminate elements are present all through the world, and we may call the mighty cause which orders them the sovereign mind, residing in the sovereign soul of Zeus. Reason in man, then, would seem to be es- sentially causative, and akin to the divine reason which creates and sustains the world l . Having thus determined the generic character of reason and pleasure in themselves, let us go on to examine the sphere and occasions of their occurrence in human life. Pleasure and pain (to take them first) occur in connexion with the third form of being of which we spoke, that in which determination combines with an indeterminate. In all living things there is a natural harmony, implying, like all harmony, a certain determination of an inde- terminate ; when this harmony is being broken up, pain 1 Philebus, 27 C-31 A. 316 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD takes place ; when it is being restored, pleasure. If there were neither restoration nor disintegration going on, the animal would feel neither pleasure nor pain, and that is just the condition which we described above as the life of pure reason : we may find eventually that this is the most divine life of all ; anyhow, we cannot without im- propriety think of the gods as feeling pleasure or the reverse 1 . One form of pleasure and pain, then, is that which accompanies the processes of bodily restoration and disintegration ; a second form is that which ac- companies the anticipation of such processes by the soul itself without the body. This takes place through memory: the soul retains the sensation of something which it experienced with the body, and recovers it with- out the body. This is the explanation of appetite, which is really a thing of the soul, not of the body ; for appetite is an impulse towards a state the opposite of that in which the body is at the moment, and this is only possible through memory 2 . A third form is that in which pain of body is accompanied by pleasure of soul, that is, by a memory of pleasant things which would relieve the pain 3 . So much for the circumstances under which pleasure and pain occur : let us now apply these observations to determine the relative truth or falsity of the pleasures and pains which we have been describing. And, first, we must ask in what senses we can speak of things like pain and pleasure, fear and hope, being false. We conceive, indeed, that in dreams or madness a person may think that he feels pleasure and yet not do so ; but are we right in this ? Let us compare pleasure with thought. 1 Philebus, 31 B-33 C. 2 lb. 33 C-35 D. ■ lb. 35D-36B. THE PHILEBUS 317 There is that which thinks and that which is thought, and there is that which feels pleasure and that at which the pleasure is felt; and as the thinking subject really thinks, whether it thinks rightly or not, so the pleased subject is really pleased, whether the pleasure be rightly felt or not. If, then, truth and falsity are attributes of thought, why should they not be equally attributes of pleasure, in spite of the fact that all pleasure is in a sense real? Or is it the case that pleasure and pain do not admit of qualification at all, but are simply what they are ? Clearly not, for we speak of them as great, small, or intense; we admit that the addition of badness makes them bad ; and we cannot deny that a mistaken opinion as to their object makes them mistaken. If it still be maintained that in the last case it is the opinion which is false, not the pleasure, it must at least be allowed that there is a great difference between pleasure accompanied by right opinion or knowledge, and pleasure accompanied by false opinion or ignorance ; the difference is that, while in both cases the pleasure is really felt, in the former it is felt at a real, in the latter at an unreal, object. We may exemplify opinion thus. We see something, ask ourselves what it is, and say to ourselves, ' It is so and so.' The soul may here be compared to a book, on which a present sensation, coalescing with a remembered sensation, writes certain words. This act of writing is followed (to use another metaphor) by an act of picturing, whereby the objects of the opinion are detached from the original sensations, and their images transferred to the soul. If what is thus written in the soul represents the truth, the opinion is true, and, if the opinion is true, the corresponding images are true. Now these psychical affections relate to future things as well as to present and 318 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD past, and there are corresponding pleasures and pains of anticipation ; a man, for instance, may enjoy the picture of himself enjoying a future pleasure. Human life is thronged with such pictures of hope ; if a man is good and beloved by the gods, his pictures are probably true ; if not, false. This, then, is one sense in which pleasure and pain (and similarly fear, anger, and other feelings), though really felt, may be untrue ; we may express it by saying that the truth or falsity of opinion infects feeling. Whether falsity in pleasure is equivalent to badness, as it is in opinion, is a question which we need not discuss at present 1 . A second form in which we may experience false pleasures is that in which feeling infects opinion. We saw above that when we feel appetite we may feel pain and pleasure simultaneously, pain from the present bodily affection, pleasure from the remembered and expected relief. We also saw that pleasure and pain are essentially indeterminate. Suppose then that we wish, as we often do in such cases, to judge which is the greater, a pleasure or a pain, how are we to do it ? We find that their magnitude, like that of objects of sight, appears to vary with their position ; they seem greater when looked at nearer, less when further off, and greater again when looked at side by side with each other. If then, we cut off from each the apparent excess or defect, we must say that both the appearance and the corresponding amount of feeling are wrong and untrue 2 . Following out this idea of the relativity of pleasure and pain to one another, we find that they admit of still greater degrees of falsity, so much so, indeed, that some 1 Philebits, 36C-41 A. 2 lb. 41 A-42A. Cp. Protagoras, 352D-357A. THE PHILEBUS 319 philosophers have been led to deny the reality of pleasure altogether. They maintain that what is called pleasure is a mere illusion, being really nothing but the sense of relief from pain. The antipathy of these philosophers to pleasure is based, not upon knowledge, but upon a sort of instinct, a noble instinct, which makes them distrust pleasure in every form. Without agreeing with them, we may use their theory to illustrate the possible falsity of pleasure. What they say is this. If we wanted to know the real nature of anything, of hardness for instance, we should examine the hardest things that we could find ; and we must do the same with pleasure. Now the greatest (i. e. the intensest) pleasures are those of the body ; and these are greater in proportion as the appetites which precede them are greater ; that is, they are greater in diseased than in healthy bodies, and in intemperate than temperate souls. Now what makes us call them the ' greatest ' pleasures is the fact that they are mixed with pain. Such mixtures of feeling may be in the body itself, or in the soul itself, or in both together. An instance of the first kind is itching ; of the second, the feelings which we have in seeing tragedy or comedy acted ; and of the third, the cases in which a sense of want coexists with a prospect of satisfaction. In such combinations as come under the first head, the pain may be greater than the pleasure, as when an itch is deep- seated and can only be partially removed by rubbing ; or it may be less, in which case the pleasure gives rise to the most ungovernable effects in colour, gesture, and voice, and makes us say that we are ' almost dying ' of delight. The more witless and licentious a man is, the more he pursues such pleasures l . 1 Philebus, 42 C-47 C. 320 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD So much for mixed pleasures of the body : we have already spoken l of the cases in which body and soul are oppositely affected : it remains to consider the mixture within the soul itself. Anger, fear, regret, grief, love, envy, jealousy and the like, are pains of the soul ; yet we find them often accompanied by great pleasure. ' Wrath,' says Achilles, ' is sweeter than honey,' and in seeing a tragedy acted we feel pleasure at the same moment that we weep. The pleasure of comedy, too, is similarly, though less obviously, mixed ; what we laugh at as comic is the harm- less conceit of our neighbours arising from their self- ignorance, which makes them think themselves richer, handsomer, or cleverer, than they really are ; in the jealous irritation which we feel at this conceit we are pained, but in laughing at it we are pleased. The same applies to 'the whole tragedy and comedy of real life'; and a similar mixture might be shown in the other emotions which we mentioned 2 . We have seen that many so-called pleasures are not really pleasures at all, while others appear greater than they are through being mixed with pains. We do not however agree with the theory that all pleasure is cessa- tion from pain ; there are also true or unmixed pleasures, and to these we now pass. Pure pleasures, then, are such as accompany the satisfaction of wants of which we are not conscious, or not painfully conscious. Such are the pleasures associated with beautiful colours and forms, sounds and scents. By beauty of form we are not to understand beauty of living things or their copies, but that of straight lines and curves, and the planes and solids formed from them ; these are beautiful, not rela- tively, but in themselves, and the corresponding pleasures 1 Philebus, 35 D-36 C. 2 lb. 47 D-50 E. THE PHIL E BUS 321 are pleasant in themselves. The same is true of smooth clear sounds of one pure tone, and of the analogous colours. The pleasures of smell are ' less divine ' than these, but resemble them in not necessarily implying pain. To these we must add the pleasures of knowledge, for neither the getting nor the losing of knowledge is accompanied by a painful sense of want, except as a result of reflexion 1 . We have thus got a division of pleasures into pure and impure. The latter or intense kind is obviously of the nature of the indeterminate and unmeasured, the former of the measured ; while, as regards their comparative truth, we see that, as a little pure white is whiter, truer, and more beautiful of its kind than a great deal which is impure, so a little unmixed pleasure will be pleasanter, truer, and more beautiful than much mixed 2 . As to the identification of pleasure with the good, we may thank- fully apply the theory of those ingenious persons who hold that pleasure has no ' being ' but is always ' coming to be.' Things may be divided into those which are self- related and self-contained, and those which relate to, and are in need of, other things ; the former are those for which something else exists, the latter those which exist for something else. Being comes under the former, be- coming under the latter, head. All things of the nature of remedies, instruments, and material, exist for, and have their end in, something which is coming to be; and all things which are coming to be exist for, and have their end in, something which is. Now that in which things have their end lies in the sphere of the good ; that which has its end in something else lies elsewhere. Pleasure, therefore, if it is a process of becoming, has its 1 Philebus, 50 E-52 B. a lb. 52 C-53 C. VOL. I. V 322 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD end in something else and cannot be of the nature of the good ; and those who hold that life is not worth having without hunger, thirst, and similar appetites, the relief of which is such a process, prefer an existence of continual coming and ceasing to be, to one in which there is neither pleasure nor pain, but the purest possible exercise of reason. The absurdity of identifying the good with pleasure appears still further when we consider that it compels us to deny goodness of everything except the soul, and of everything in the soul except pleasure, and moreover to hold a person good and bad in proportion as, and at the times when, he feels and does not feel pleased 1 . Having thus sifted pleasure, we must not spare reason and knowledge, but must free them also from alloy as far as possible, so that when we come to judge between the claimants we may have before us the truest elements of each. What kinds of knowledge, then, are the purest? Knowledge may be divided into professional and educa- tional. Of the professional arts we see that those are the more exact in which there is more numbering, measuring, weighing ; the less of these there is, the more does the art sink into guesswork and empiricism. Thus such arts as carpentry, shipbuilding, and architecture, owing to the numerous instruments which they can use, are more exact than those of music, medicine, agriculture, navigation, and war. Again, there is a difference in clearness and exactness according as the arts of number, measure, and weight are pursued by ordinary people or by philosophers ; the former, for example, count with unequal units (two armies, two oxen), while the latter insist that every unit must be equal to every other. 1 Philebus, 53 C-55 C. THE PHILEBUS 323 These arts, however, even when philosophically pursued, are not the most exact and clear forms of knowledge ; the first place must be given to philosophy, the universal science, which is concerned with being as such, in its real and unchangeable nature. Other arts (rhetoric, for in- stance) may be greater, more popular, more profitable ; but, having regard to the love of truth for its own sake, we must consider philosophy to be the purest exercise of reason. Most of the other arts are concerned with the mere opinions of men ; even those which investigate nature confine themselves to the processes of the sensible universe, and these, being in perpetual change, do not admit of the truest knowledge. Consistency, truth, and purity, then, must be assigned in the first degree to the thought which is exercised upon things unchangeable or things most akin to these, and can be assigned only in lower degrees to other forms of thought l . And now reason and pleasure may be said to lie before us, like material ready for the craftsman to work with. Neither of them alone, as we have seen, satisfies the requirements of the good ; the good must be looked for in the mixed life, and presumably in the well-mixed. How then shall we mix them, the honey of pleasure, and the austere water of reason ? We shall begin most safely by mixing the truest parts of each ; but will these suffice to make a perfect life? No; clearly it is not enough to have the ' divine ' knowledge of things as they really are ; we must have the every-day ' human ' know- ledge as well, otherwise we shall not be able to find the way to our own houses. Nor can we dispense with music, unscientific though it is ; life would not be life without it. In fact we need not be afraid to admit all 1 Philebus, 55 C-59 D. Y 1 324 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD forms of knowledge, pure and impure alike. But it will be otherwise with pleasures ; when we have taken the true kinds, and have added, as in the case of knowledge, those which are necessary to life, we must stop. For, while pleasure must be the better for having any know- ledge for a companion, especially knowledge of itself, it is only true and pure, healthy and temperate, pleasures which are consistent with the exercise of reason ; the pleasures of folly and vice only impede and corrupt it. Moreover, truth is indispensable to the combination ; nothing would be real without it x . And now, assuming our materials to be combined into one organic whole, we may suppose ourselves to be standing before the house where the Good dwells ; and we have to ask, Which is the highest element in the combination, and the chief cause of its being universally desirable ; and is this element more akin to reason or to pleasure ? It is clear that what makes any mixture good is measure and proportion ; without these indeed there could be no mixture at all, but only an unmixed conglomerate. Proportion always gives rise to beauty ; and truth, we remember, is already an essential element in the combination. Thus the good, which escapes us when we try to grasp it in a single form, is apprehensible under the triple form of measure, beauty, and truth ; and these three in one are what make the combination good. There is now no difficulty in answering the second part of our question. Pleasure is the most lying thing in the world, while reason, if not identical with truth, is of all things the most like it. Pleasure, again, is the most unmeasured, mind and knowledge the most measured; of things. And lastly, while no one ever saw 1 Phikbus, 59 D-64 B. THE PHILEBUS 325 or conceived any ugliness in reason, the sight of some of the greatest pleasures is cither ridiculous or disgusting l . We may now, therefore, proclaim to the world that pleasure is not the first of possessions, or the second either. First come measure and all things of the same eternal nature as measure ; second, proportion, beauty, perfection, and the like ; third, mind and understanding ; fourth (to come to the goods of the soul itself), sciences, arts, right opinions ; fifth, pure or painless pleasures ; and there the list stops. It remains to sum up our judgment once more. Neither pleasure nor reason has the self-sufficingness and perfection which we require in the good ; the good is something higher than either of them. But reason is infinitely more akin to it than pleasure. Pleasure is fifth in the list, and we will not put it first for all the horses and oxen in the world ; it is to these that men go for their oracles when they judge pleasure to be the chief thing in life; 'they believe in the loves of the brutes instead of in the inspired words of the muse of philosophy' 2 Some attempt has been already made to interpret the general idea which underlies the argument of the PJiile- bus ; but the practical bearing of the dialogue still requires some notice. It proposes to answer the ques- tion, What is the true end of human life ? and at the conclusion we are tempted to ask impatiently, What does the answer mean? Does it mean that we are to aim in our lives at mathematical precision, or at statuesque repose, or at logical consistency ? And what is the connexion of these elaborate analyses of existence and consciousness with the somewhat obvious precept, to get as much knowledge as we can and to cultivate only the 1 Philebus, 64 B-66 A. ' lb. 66 A-end. 326 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD higher pleasures ? Part of our embarrassment, in the case of this as of some other dialogues of Plato, arises no doubt from the length and rapidity of his mental stride, and the comparatively unoccupied state of the ground which he had to traverse. It would take a modern philosopher much more time and trouble to pass from an analysis of heat or of itching to the conception of a divine mind or an absolute good. But the chief stumbling-block lies in the fusion (to some it will seem the confusion), already noticed in the Gorgias, of the scientific and moral aspects of life. We are accustomed to regard science as having to do with an objective world which goes its own way and has its own laws, unaffected by, and indifferent to, human good and evil. Morality on the other hand seems to us peculiarly a personal matter, a something which we make and un- make for ourselves, and in which, rightly or wrongly, we emphatically distinguish ourselves from what we call nature. There have not indeed been wanting modern attempts to bridge over this distinction, but they have mostly taken the direction, not of relating the moral and the natural through the medium of some third and higher element, but of making the first disappear in the second. Thus, when we find Plato, in an ethical dialogue, treating pleasure and pain under the same head, and on the same principles, as cold and heat, we are inclined to say : ' Let us distinguish ; pleasure and pain may be dealt with as physical processes, but, so dealt with, they are not matter for the moralist ; or again, cold and heat, as personal feelings, may acquire an ethical interest, but in that case they have passed out of the sphere of physical science. Ultimately, no doubt, we only know " pheno- mena," that is, our own feelings, and so far pleasure and THE PHILEBUS 327 heat may be ranged together ; but the standards which we apply to these feelings are quite disparate. Both standards are, if you will, conventional; scientific man- kind fixes that of heat, moral mankind that of pleasure, each for certain purposes of its own ; but there is no connexion between the two standards, nor any reason to suppose that they can be reduced to one. Rightness in physics is one thing, another thing in ethics.' Perhaps we shall not be misinterpreting the Philebus if we elicit from it an answer somewhat as follows: ' The rightness both of natural processes and of human conduct, so far as there is a rightness in cither, is due to the working of a single principle. You say that there is no objectively right feeling of heat ; that heat is either what it is to this or that individual — that is, entirely indeterminate, — or else what it is to science, entirely conventional. But really there is no such thing as an en- tirely indeterminate feeling; the vaguest and most capri- cious feeling in the world must be measurable to some extent, or it would be nothing. What are called the ar- bitrary measures of science are only a purer and more exact form of the measure inherent in different degrees in all feeling and all existence. The minimum of feeling and existence is the minimum of measurableness. As feeling acquires more content, and existence becomes fuller, they become more determinate. New limits emerge in the limitless ; gradations, elements, parts, kinds, arc felt, where before there was monotony ; and each new limit supplies a new standard of measurement. The increase of measure is not an arbitrary external addition, but the recognition of an inherent development. And it is in morality as in science. The moral standard is not a rule mechanically applied to circumstances ; it is the 328 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD measure inherent in the circumstances, and giving them their character. The moral organization responds to the moral fact, as the physical to the physical fact ; the finer the organization, the more delicate its measurement, and the fuller therefore its experience. Laws and institutions fix certain units of measurement ; they are rough moral thermometers. The more feeling has been morally measured by an individual or a society, the higher their moral condition. Each new step in moral consciousness is consciousness of a new limit, not a new limit to ex- perience, but a limit which is itself a new experience. Here, too, reality grows with the growth of measure.' ' But,' it will be said, ' if reality is measure, each dif- ferent kind of reality has its own measure : the essences of motion and heat, temperance and pity, may exhibit them- selves as various measures, but what is the common mea- sure of them all ? It may be possible to express them all in terms of some common factor, but the expression so obtained will only express what is common to all, not what is specific in each ; heat will remain heat, and pity, pity.' But there is no reason to suppose that when Plato puts together, as he does in the Philebus, the various phenomena of temperature, rhythm, health, and virtue, as expressions of the principle of measure, he is think- ing of a possible reduction of them all to forms of one element, such as motion. His conception of the ultimate measure, the measure which he places first of the three forms of the good, is made clear to us when we consider his conception of the second of these forms, ' symmetry ' or proportion. Symmetry or commensurableness is in- deed, as he himself indicates 1 , only another aspect of 1 Philebus, 26 A epipeTpov /cat ap.a ovpp.tTpov : and 64 D. In 65 A, cvuptTpia occurs where we should expect {AfTptoTijTt, for in the final list, THE PHIL E BUS 3-9 measurableness. In becoming measurable itself, a thing becomes commensurable with all other things of the same kind. The difference is that, while in measun w< think primarily of the thing itself, in symmetry we think of its relation to other things, and ultimately to a whole of which it is a part. It is in this whole that we must look for the law or principle or measure which deter- mines that relation. Thus the same measure becomes differently symmetrical as it enters into different wholes. A second of time obeys different laws of proportion according as it is an element in an hour, in a musical phrase, or in an act of forbearance, respectively. In Plato's language, it gets more ' determined ' at each ste] 1 ; it remains the same itself, but it acquires new significance, and is linked to larger issues. And, if we follow out this line of thought, we are led with Plato to the idea of a perfect whole, or ' cosmos,' in which each form of existence finds its measure assigned to it, and in fulfilling that measure fulfils itself. This brings us to the third aspect of the good in the Philebus, truth. If the truth of a thing is the thing realized, neither more nor less, it easily passes into measure on the one side (for its measure- is its full self), and into symmetry on the other (for its true nature is determined by its position in a whole). In substituting, as he afterwards does 1 , 'mind and in- telligence' for 'truth,' Plato must be supposed to be speaking of what he has before* called the 'divine mind,' a mind which is all that it is conscious of, and is 66A-B, av/xixiTpov, not fxirpiov, is identified with koXvv. The passage from the Politicus (283C-285A), referred to below, p. 343, bears directly upon this point. 1 Cp. Philebus, 65 A and 66 B ; also 65 D. 2 lb. 22 C, where it is implied that the divine mind is the good. 3SO PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD conscious of all that is, a mind in which the distinction of subject and object disappears. It is this mind to which he had ascribed a life of pure being x , above the flow and ebb of human consciousness, and which he had identified with the causative force which creates a deter- minate universe out of indeterminate nothing. It is, in fact, the good, conceived, not as a principle or a con- dition, but as an activity. Thus, starting from the idea that the minimum of being implies determinateness, and that in reaching its proper limit each thing attains both its being and its well-being, its truth and its good, we have been led, as a logical consequence, to the idea of an absolutely deter- mined being or cosmos, by relation to which each particle of being is what it is, and in which is realized, by the sustaining energy of mind, the perfect measure, beauty, and truth of things. Plato has expressed the same idea in religious language, and with a directly moral bearing, in a passage in the Laws' 2 , which may be quoted as a complement to the abstractions of the PJiilebus. ' God, as the old saying is, holding in his hand the beginning and end and middle of all things, goes straight to his purpose by the long ways of nature, and justice ever follows him, to punish all shortcomings of the divine law. He who would fare well follows close behind her, in lowliness and moderation ; but if any man is lifted up in his heart by riches or honour or beauty, and in the fire of youthful insolence and folly thinks that he needs no ruler or guide, but can himself be a guide to others, he is deserted by God ; and so deserted he takes to himself others like him, and prances through the world spreading confusion as he goes ; and to many 1 Phikbus, 33 B. 2 Laws, iv. 715E-716C. THE PIULEDUS 331 he seems to be somebody, but in no long time he pays a righteous penalty to justice, and makes ruin of himself, his house, and his state. In the face of this order of things, how must the wise man bear himself? Surely he must make up his mind to follow after God. And how must he act so as to be the friend and follower of God? There is only one way of acting, and one principle, the old principle that the measured is the friend of the measured, but the unmeasured is the friend neither of the measured nor of the unmeasured. Now God, and not, as some say, man, is the real measure of all things, and he who would be the friend of God must be such as God is.' It would seem, then, that the first three in the list of goods with which the Philebus concludes represent different aspects under which the divine perfection may be apprehended. The last two, (1) truth of science, art, and opinion, and (2) unmixed pleasures, are distinguished as ' of the soul itself,' and constitute in their combination the highest good realizable in human life. - Man, Plato implies, can never transcend the conditions of time and process ; only the divine being is, all else only comes to be or ceases to be. But the divine good is the cause or condition of the human ; the latter is only good as it approximates to the former, as it rises out of becoming into being. In the measure, beauty, and truth, realizable by us in intellect and emotion, we catch something of the reality. The universe lies about us, composed of the same elements, endowed with the same life, ordered by the same reason, as ourselves. We have to learn to know it in order to take our part in it. From the crude counting of the unlettered man or child up to the pure; 1 abstractions of mathematics and physics, and on again 332 PLATO S CONCEPTION OF THE GOOD to the philosophical analysis of the very nature of being. the mind is gradually coming to find the measure, the proportion, the truth, of things. And in learning their limits it is also learning its own, learning to correct the phantasmagoria of its senses and to distinguish their confusion, to direct the currents of its prejudices and the momentum of its logical impulses, to feel the clear outlines of reality and to delight in responding to their pressure, to see things as they are, and to be itself at one with them. This is why truth, alike in its lowest and its highest forms, is to be welcomed as an unmixed good. But man not only knows, he also feels ; and, if he is to be truly himself, his emotions as well as his intellect must be true. And this brings us to the last point to be noticed in the PJiilcbtis, the distinction between true and false pleasures. The question in what sense we can speak of feelings being true or untrue must, as Plato himself was aware, always be a difficult one. We are inclined to say with Protarchus 1 , there may be untrue opinion, but how can there be untrue pleasure? We feel what we feel, and what other canon of truth is there ? To appreciate Plato's answer we must first appreciate his mode of representing the mental activities in general. In his view the various acts of thinking, reasoning, desiring, are not temporary exercises of faculty by a soul which still remains in the background with a separable life of its own ; they are its very life and being, and as such they are the modes in which it takes its part in the life and being of the world. The truth which is appre- hended in knowledge is thus the ' sustenance 2 ' of the 1 Philcbus, 36 C, 38 A. a Rep. vi. 490 B. Cp., in this connexion, Rep. vi. 500 C ; Phaedo, 79 C-D ; Timaeus, 42 E-44 D, 47 B-C ; Phaedrus, 248 B. THE PHILEBUS 333 soul, that upon which it lives, that which it assimilates, and in assimilating which it is itself assimilated. And analogously ignorance, fbrgetfulncss, illusion, arc not mere states passing over the surface of the soul ; they mean that it is dropping out of the life of the world. dying of inanition, or growing diseased and maimed ; it not only sees things as they are not, it is itself failing to be its true self. Now pain and pleasure, as we have seen, are de- scribed by Plato as the feelings of the disintegration and restoration of harmony in the organism, of the fall and rise of the vital energies, of the emptying and re- filling of capacity. They are not external additions to the life of the soul with a character of their own ; they are part and parcel of the life itself, and get their character from it ; they are the soul in certain phases of its being. The question is, What are these phases ? What is the soul in pleasure and pain ? Plato answers, In pleasure, strictly speaking, the soul does not attain being at all, but is only coming to be ; for pleasure is just the sense of transition from a lower to a higher state of being. A perfect being, in which there was no want and no dissolution, would have no pleasure ; its con- sciousness would be of some higher kind, but it would not be what we mean by pleasure 1 . All pleasure, then, is so far a form of unrealized, imperfect, being ; and it cannot therefore be consistently conceived as the good of life, as that in which life finds its fullest expression. Only as determined and realized in various forms of thought, as conceived, remembered, anticipated, and the like, can it be a constituent in the end or true being of man. 1 Cp. Sympos. 203 E, OecDi' oiiSets <£iAo<7oe? ov8' imOv^u croc/>