ON THE 
 
 .ETHICS OF NATURALISM 
 
 BY 
 
 W. E. SOELEY, M.A. 
 
 FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE ; AND EXAMINER IN 
 PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH 
 
 WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS 
 
 EDINBURGH AND LONDON 
 
 MDCCCLXXXY 
 
PBEFATOKY NOTE. 
 
 THE Deed of Foundation of the Shaw Fellowship pro- 
 vides that " it shall be in the power of the Senatus 
 Academicus of the University of Edinburgh to re- 
 quire the holder of the Shaw T Philosophical Fellow- 
 ship, during the fourth or fifth year of his tenure of 
 it, to deliver in the University of Edinburgh a course 
 of Lectures, not exceeding four, on any of the subjects 
 for the encouragement of the study of which the Fel- 
 lowship has been founded." The following pages 
 consist of four lectures delivered in the University of 
 Edinburgh, in accordance with this provision, in the 
 month of January 1884. 
 
 Since their delivery, the argument of the lectures 
 has been revised, and in some places enlarged. I have 
 also thought it better to modify their original form by 
 dividing the discussion into chapters. 
 
 W. K. S. 
 
CONTENTS. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 1. Connection of ethics with theoretical philosophy, . . 1 
 
 (a) Dependence of ethical on theoretical points of view, . 1 
 
 (b) Ethics necessary to complete philosophy, . . 3 
 
 2. The inquiry into the ethical end, .... 5 
 
 (a) Fundamental, ...... 5 
 
 (&) Implies a new point of view, .... 7 
 
 (c) Distinct from other ethical questions, ... 9 
 
 (a) From the inquiry into the methods of ethics, . 10 
 
 () From moral psychology and sociology, . . 13 
 
 3. Scope of the present inquiry, . . . . 14 
 
 PAET I. 
 
 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEOEY. 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 EGOISM. 
 
 Definition of Naturalism, . . . . .20 
 
 Pyschological hedonism, . . . . .21 
 
Vlll CONTENTS. 
 
 1. Its theory of action ambiguous, . . . .22 
 
 Eef erring to 
 
 (a) Actual consequences of action, . . .23 
 
 (b) Or its expected consequences, . . .23 
 
 (c) Or its present characteristics, . . .24 
 
 2. Ethical inferences from this theory, . .25 
 
 3. Transition from psychological to ethical hedonism, . 31 
 
 4. Possible objections considered, . . . .37 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 
 
 1. Difference of the standpoints of individual and State, . 41 
 
 2. Connection between egoism and utilitarianism according to 
 
 Bentham, ...... 45 
 
 (a) Utilitarianism not a political duty, . . .46 
 
 (b) Nor a moral duty, ..... 47 
 
 (c) Nor insisted on as a religious duty, . . .49 
 
 (d) Nor sufficiently motived in private ethics, . . 50 
 
 3. Exhaustive character of Bentham' s treatment from his point 
 
 of view, ....... 51 
 
 (a) The religious sanction (Paley), . . .53 
 
 (b) Limits of the political sanction, . . .54 
 
 (c) Uncertainty of the social sanction, . . .55 
 (d} And of the internal sanction so far as a result of the 
 
 social, ....... 56 
 
 4. Mill's logical defence of utilitarianism, . . .57 
 
 (a) Distinction of kinds of pleasure, . . .58 
 
 (b} Ambiguities in his proof, . . . .60 
 
 5. Actual transition to utilitarianism, . . . .62 
 
 (a) Recognition of sympathy, . . . .64 
 
 (b) The idea of equality, ..... 69 
 
 6. The two sides of utilitarian theory without logical connec- 
 
 tion, ....... 73 
 
 7. Summary of the ethical consequences of psychological 
 
 hedonism, ...... 75 
 
CONTENTS. ix 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 MORAL SENTIMENT. 
 
 1. A uniform psychological theory not supplied by the oppo- 
 
 nents of ethical hedonism, . . . .78 
 
 2. The non-hedonistic theory of action, . . .84 
 
 3. Ethics made to depend on the moral sense, . . .89 
 
 (a) As harmony of impulses, . . . .90 
 
 (b) As a separate sensitive faculty, . . .92 
 
 (c) As an internal law, . . . . .100 
 
 4. The ethics of moral sentiment a mediating theory, . .105 
 
 PAET II. 
 THE THEOEY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION AND THE DEVELOPMENT 
 OF MORALITY. 
 
 1. General characteristics of the theory of evolution, . .107 
 
 An assertion of the unity of life, . . . .109 
 
 Primarily historical, but capable of ethical application, . 110 
 
 2. The development of morality, . . . .116 
 
 (a) Historical psychology, . . . . .116 
 
 Its difficulties, . . . . .117 
 
 Its result, ...... 123 
 
 (b) Development of society, . . . .124 
 
 CHAPTER VI. 
 
 t 
 
 EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 
 
 Bearing of the theory of evolution, . . . .126 
 
 1. On theories depending on moral sentiment or intuition, . 127 
 
X CONTENTS. 
 
 (a) Ethical value of moral sentiments affected by their 
 
 origin, ...... 130 
 
 (b) Organic character of moral sentiments, . .132 
 
 Resultant attitude of evolutionism to intuitionism, . 133 
 
 2. On egoism : relation of egoism to altruism, . . .134 
 
 (a) Social nature of the individual, . . . 135 
 
 (b) Limits to conciliation of egoism and altruism, . 141 
 
 (a) Continued existence of competition, . .142 
 
 ()8) Different and conflicting degrees of altruism, . 143 
 
 (7) Altruism of interest and altruism of motive, . 143 
 
 (5) Weakness of altruistic feelings, . . .146 
 
 (c) Tendency of evolution opposed to egoism, . .148 
 
 Evolution not the basis of psychological hedonism, . 148 
 
 Nor of ethical hedonism, . . . .150 
 
 3. On utilitarianism, . . . . . .152 
 
 Modification of the utilitarian method, . . .153 
 
 And of its principle, . . . . . .155 
 
 Evolutionist objections to utilitarianism, . . 155 
 
 (a) As prescribing an unprogressive ideal, . . 156 
 
 (6) As a theory of consequences, . . .160 
 
 (c) As related solely to sensibility, . . .161 
 
 CHAPTER VII. 
 
 HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 
 
 1. Alliance of evolutionism and hedonism, . . .164 
 
 (a) From interpreting greatest happiness by the laws 
 
 of life, ...... 164 
 
 (b) From interpreting life by pleasure, . . .165 
 
 2. Evolutionist argument for concomitance of life and 
 
 pleasure, . . . . . .167 
 
 3. Objections to this argument, . . . .168 
 
 (a) That life cannot bring more pleasure than pain,. . 169 
 
 (a) From the negative nature of pleasure, . . 171 
 
 (j8) From the facts of human life, . . .172 
 
 (b) That the evolution of life does not uniformly tend to 
 
 pleasure, . . . . . .172 
 
CONTENTS. xi 
 
 (a) Incompleteness of the evolutionist argument, . 173 
 
 (0) The pessimist doctrine that life tends to/ 
 
 misery, . . . . . .175 
 
 (aa) The hypothesis of the unconscious, . . 176 
 
 (66) The nature of volition, . . .177 
 
 (cc) The facts of human progress, . . .179 
 
 Individual progress, . . . .179 
 
 Social progress, . . . .181 
 
 The psychological analysis of pleasure and pain in relation 
 
 to evolutionist ethics, . . . . .186 
 
 (a) The subjective nature of pleasure and pain, . . 187 
 
 (b) The conditions of pleasure and pain, . . .190 
 
 (c) Application of the theory of evolution, . .197 
 
 CHAPTER VIII. 
 
 THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 
 
 Necessity of inquiring into the ethical end suggested by 
 
 the theory of evolution, ..... 201 
 
 1. Adaptation to environment, . . . .203 
 
 (a) As the end for present conduct, . . . 207 
 Opposed to progress, . . . .207 
 Does not fully represent evolution, . . . 209 
 
 (b) As describing the ultimate condition of life, . 210 
 Resultant absolute code, . . . .211 
 
 (a) Abstract principles of social relation, . * . 212 
 
 () Personal end only denned as adaptation, . 213 
 
 (7) Cannot be shown to lead to happiness, . 213 
 
 (c) Insufficiency of adaptation as evolutionist end, . 217 
 
 2. End suggested by the tendency to variation, . . 221 
 
 (a) Prescribes self - development rather than self- 
 
 preservation, . . . . .222 
 
 (b) Standard for measuring development found in com- 
 
 plexity of act and motive, .... 227 
 (a) Antinomy between social and individual ends, 231 
 (j8) Psychological defects, . . . .232 
 
 3. Development or increase of life as the end, . . 236 
 
Xil CONTENTS. 
 
 (a] Subjective standard: most persistent impulses, . 242 
 Cannot define life without an objective standard, . 244 
 
 (b) Objective standard : defined in two ways, . . 247 
 
 (a) Conformity to the type, . . . 248 
 
 Which can be reduced to 
 
 ($) Abundance and variety of vital power, . 251 
 
 That is, to the subjective standard, . . 253 
 
 Summary as to the evolutionist end, . . . .256 
 
 (a) Difficulty of reconciling individual and social ends, . 256 
 
 (b) Hedonistic interpretation of evolution not possible, . 257 
 
 (c) No independent ethical ideal, . . . .259 
 
 CHAPTER IX. 
 
 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 1. Principles involved in theory of evolution, . . . 263 
 
 2. Unsuccessful application of these principles to ethics, . 264 
 
 (a) The principles being treated empirically, . . 265 
 
 (b) No logical transition having been effected from 
 
 efficient to final cause, . . . .267 
 
 3. Difference between causality and teleology, . . .269 
 
 4. Reference to self -consciousness implied in evolution, , 277 
 
 (a) Attempt to trace the genesis of self -consciousness, . 278 
 
 (b) Attempt to trace morality from reflex action, . 283 
 
 5. The unity of self -consciousness, .... 284 
 
 (a) As making possible the transition from knowledge 
 
 to morality, ...... 284 
 
 (6) As determining the character of the ethical end, . 286 
 
 (c) As showing that the realisation of the end must be 
 
 progressive, ...... 291 
 
1TY 
 
 . 
 
 THE ETHICS OF NATUEALTSM, 
 
 CHAPTEE I. 
 
 ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 
 
 IT is a common remark that a writer's ethical i. connec- 
 doctrine is throughout conditioned by his attitude with theo- 
 to the problems of theoretical philosophy. The 
 main lines of dispute in questions of ethics may 
 be regarded as prolongations of the controversies 
 which arise in metaphysics and psychology. The 
 Eealism or Idealism which marks a speculative 
 system reappears in its ethics, whilst differences 
 in the psychological analysis of mental states, or 
 concerning the relation of pleasure to desire, are 
 grounds of distinction between schools of moralists. 
 And not only are the special controversies of ethics 
 decided in different ways, but the scope of the (a) 
 whole science is differently conceived, as the spec- ethtomion 
 ulative standpoint changes. Thus, not for one JJJJJJfJf 
 school only, but for a whole period in the history view 
 
 A 
 
"2 ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 
 
 (a)teieoio- of reflection, ethics was regarded as an inquiry 
 into the highest human good. Opposed schools 
 agreed in looking from this point of view, however 
 much they might differ from one another in defining 
 the nature of that highest good. At other times, 
 
 (&)jurai, according to the prevailing view, to investigate and 
 systematise the rules of conduct has exhausted 
 the scope of ethics controversies being carried 
 on as to the nature of those rules, and their source 
 in external authority or in the internal revelation 
 of conscience. Again, ethical inquiry has been 
 
 (c> empir- apparently identified with the analysis and history 
 of the moral affections and sentiments ; while a 
 purely external point of view seems to be some- 
 times adopted, and ethics held to be an investiga- 
 tion of the historical results of action, and of the 
 forms, customary and institutional, in which those 
 results find permanent expression. 
 
 These different ways of looking at the whole 
 subject proceed from points of view whose effects 
 are not confined to ethics, but may be followed 
 out in other lines of investigation. They corre- 
 spond to ideas which dominate different types of 
 thought and form different philosophical stand- 
 points. The first starts from a teleological con- 
 ception of human nature, as an organism con- 
 sciously striving towards its end. The second 
 assimilates ethics to a system of legal enactments, 
 and is connected with the jural conceptions of 
 
ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 3 
 
 theology and law. The two last are concerned 
 to show that the subject-matter of ethics are facts 
 which have to be treated by the ordinary inductive 
 and historical methods. These different points of 
 view, however, are to be regarded as complement- 
 ary rather than as conflicting, although their com- to be con- 
 
 . nected by 
 
 plete synthesis must be worked out in the region philosophy, 
 of general philosophy, and not on purely ethical 
 ground. Philosophy has thus to deal with the 
 notions which determine the scope and character 
 of ethical thought ; and in this way it must neces- 
 sarily pass from the purely speculative to the 
 practical point of view. If it is the business of 
 philosophy to bring into rational order the material 
 supplied by experience, cosmical and anthropo- 
 logical, it cannot be without bearing on the func- 
 tion of man as a source of action in the world. 
 The question, What are the ends man is naturally 
 fitted to attain ? or if we prefer so to express it 
 What are the ends he ought to pursue ? is not 
 merely as natural as the question, What can a man 
 know of the world and of himself ? But the two 
 questions are inseparably connected. To know 
 man is to know him not only as a thinking but 
 also as an active being ; while to solve the problem 
 of the ends of man implies knowledge both of his 
 nature and of the sphere of his activity. 
 
 Much distrust is often expressed of metaphysics. (&> Ethics 
 But it is not denied that the philosophy whether n< 
 
4 ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 
 
 to complete metaphysical or not in which our most compre- 
 hensive view of the world finds its reasoned ex- 
 pression, cannot neglect that aspect of things in 
 which man is related to his surroundings as a 
 source of action. Eecent ethical literature is itself 
 a proof of this fact. In its speculative develop- 
 ments, both realistic and idealistic, the philosophy 
 of the present day has made the endeavour to con- 
 nect its conceptions of the world of thought and 
 nature with the ends contemplated as to be realised 
 in the realm of action. Whatever difficulties may 
 be involved in the transition from the " is " to the 
 " ought to be," it is yet implied that the transition 
 requires to be made, not merely in order that 
 human activity may be shown to be rational, but 
 that reason itself may be justified by leaving 
 nothing outside its sphere. 
 
 We must make no attempt, therefore, to draw 
 a line of absolute separation between the first two 
 of the three questions in which, as Kant says, 1 all 
 the interests of our reason centre. The "What 
 ought I to do ? " of ethics is for ever falling back 
 on the " What can I know ? " of metaphysics. The 
 question of practice must accordingly be treated 
 throughout in connection with the question of 
 knowledge, If we use Kant's distinction between 
 speculative and practical reason, we must always 
 bear in mind that it is the same reason which is 
 
 1 Werke, ed. Hartenstein (1867), iii. 532. 
 
ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 5 
 
 in one reference speculative, in another practical. 1 
 We are not at liberty to assume with Butler 2 that 
 "morality . . . must be somewhat plain and 
 easy to be understood : it must appeal to what we 
 call common-sense." Nor may we presuppose, as 
 Hutcheson did, 3 that it is a subject "about which 
 a little reflection will discover the truth." The 
 question must be looked upon not so much as one 
 of immediate practical as of scientific interest, and 
 reason is to be regarded as the only court of 
 appeal. 
 
 The form just quoted, in which Kant states the 2. The in- 
 problem, is not altogether free from ambiguity. tLethfcai 
 "What ought I to do?" may be taken to signify, end 
 What means should I adopt for the attainment of 
 some end presupposed, perhaps unconsciously, as 
 the end to be sought ? But it is evident, not only 
 that this is not what Kant himself meant by the 
 question, but that, as thus put, it necessarily im- 
 plies a further and deeper question. Not the di 
 covery of the means, but the determination of the 
 end itself the end which cannot be interpreted 
 as a mere means to some further end is the (a) funda- 
 fundamental question of ethics. It is only by m 
 misconception that this can be thought to be a 
 trivial question. To say, as a recent scientific 
 
 1 Cf. Kant, Werke, iv. 237. 
 
 2 Sermons, v., towards the end. 
 
 3 Essay on the Passions and Affections, p. iv. 
 
6 ETHICS AND ITS PKOBLEMS. 
 
 writer does, 1 " that happiness in one disguise or 
 another is the end of human life is common ground 
 for all the schools/' is either to ignore what the 
 schools have taught, 2 or else to use the word 
 "happiness" merely as another name for the 
 highest good. But, even were it still the case, as 
 it was in the time of Aristotle, that nearly all men 
 were agreed as to the name of the highest good, 
 and that the common people and the cultured alike 
 called it happiness, the difference as to what they 
 meant by the term would still remain. To say 
 that the ethical end is happiness is, to use Locke's 
 terminology, a " trifling proposition " ; for in so 
 doing we merely give it a name 3 and one which 
 the controversies of philosophy have surrounded 
 with confusion. That the end is happiness in any 
 definite sense, for example, as the greatest balance 
 of pleasure over pain, may be perfectly true, but 
 stands very much in need of proof. That happi- 
 
 1 W. H. Rolph, Biologische Probleme, zugleich als Versuch zur 
 Entwicklung einer rationellen Ethik, 2d ed., p. 21. 
 
 2 Not to mention Kant, the consistent opponent of every 
 eudsemonistic principle, or the doctrines of a political idealist 
 such as Mazzini (see Life and Writings (1867), iv. 223), reference 
 may be made to a writer like W. K. Clifford, who looks from the 
 scientific point of view, and yet holds that " happiness is not to 
 be desired for its own sake." Lectures and Essays (1879), ii. 
 121, 173. 
 
 3 "Auch dieser Begriff [Gliickseligkeit] ist an sich ein bloss 
 formaler, der jede beliebige materiale Bestimmung zulasst." 
 Zeller, Ueber Begriff und Begriindung der sittlichen Gesetze 
 (1883), p. 23. 
 
ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 7 
 
 ness is the highest ethical end can be assumed as 
 true only when " happiness " is nothing more than an 
 abbreviated expression for " the highest ethical end." 
 
 A difficulty of a more radical kind meets us, at (&) implies a 
 
 ,1 P . , -, -, . , . . . , new point of 
 
 the very outset of our inquiry, in the distinctively vieWj 
 ethical notion expressed by the word "ought." 
 Various attempts have been made to surmount or 
 circumvent this difficulty ; and some of these will 
 come under consideration in the sequel.. The very 
 notion of conscious activity contains the idea of 
 bringing about something which does not yet exist. 
 It involves a purpose or end. The notion " ought," 
 it is true, means more than this: it implies an 
 obligation to pursue a definite end or conform to 
 definite rules, regarded generally as coming from 
 an authoritative source. In this clear and full 
 sense, "oughtness" or duty is a comparatively 
 recent notion, foreign to the classical period of 
 Greek ethics. The force and defmiteness belong- 
 ing to the modern conception of it are due to the 
 juridical aspect which the Stoic philosophy, Eoman 
 law, and Christian theology combined to impress 
 upon morality. But even the notion of purpose or 
 end implies a " preference " of the end sought : the 
 state to be realised is looked upon as " better " or 
 " more to be desired " than the existing state. We 
 may ask for the reason of this superior desirable- 
 ness ; but the answer must soon fall back upon the 
 assertion of something held to be desirable in it- 
 
8 ETHICS AND ITS PKOBLEMS. 
 
 self. The question which we are always asking, 
 and cannot help asking, " Why is such and such an 
 end to be pursued by me ? " or " Why ought I to 
 follow such and such a course of conduct ? " must 
 soon lead to the assertion of an ultimate end. 
 the transi- This end, therefore, must not be sought for some 
 req^irel^- 11 ulterior end, nor desired as a means to satisfy any 
 vestigation; O ther desire. But it is still necessary to inquire 
 into the way in which the end, held to be ultimate 
 in a practical regard, stands related to the con- 
 stitution of man and his environment. And the 
 question to which I would draw attention, as the 
 fundamental problem of ethics, is, What is that 
 which men have variously called happiness, the 
 highest good, the ethical end ? or, more precisely, 
 How can a transition be made from the notions of 
 theoretical philosophy to the determination of that 
 ethical end ? No assumption is made, at starting, 
 as to the nature of this end, or the manner of 
 arriving at it. It may be a transient state of feel- 
 ing, or a permanent type of character; or it may 
 by its very nature defy exact definition, the idea 
 itself being perfected as its realisation is progres- 
 sively approached. In any case it requires to be 
 brought into connection with the ultimate concep- 
 tions of thought and existence. 
 
 This question of the ethical end or highest good 
 is thus fundamental in ethical science, and upon it 
 all other questions in ethics finally depend. But 
 
\ 
 V 
 
 ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 9 
 
 it is easy to see that it does not cover the whole 
 field, and that the other points of view already 
 referred to have a legitimate application. Ethics 
 has not only to determine the end, but to apply it 
 to practice, and so to decide as to what is right or 
 wrong in particular actions, and virtuous or vicious 
 in character. And, in addition to the two questions 
 thus implied the question as to the ethical end, 
 and that as to the application of it to practical 
 affairs there is another department of inquiry 
 which has had a place assigned to it in most ethi- 
 cal systems, and which has a right to be regarded 
 as belonging to ethics. We may investigate the 
 place, in the individual and the community respec- 
 tively, both of the sentiments and ideas and of the 
 social institutions and customs through which mor- 
 ality is manifested; and this inquiry covers the 
 twofold ground of what may be called moral psy- 
 chology and moral sociology. 
 
 Of these three questions, the first forms the sub- (c) distinct 
 
 . . , ,, T from other 
 
 ject oi inquiry in the following pages. It seems to ethical 
 me that a great part of the obscurity which sur- que ' 
 rounds ethical argument is due to confounding these 
 different questions. It is true that no one of them 
 is without bearing on the others ; but it is none the 
 less necessary, in discussing any one of them, to 
 keep its distinctness from those others well in view. 
 In inquiring into the foundation on which the ethi- 
 cal end is based, I do not intend to develop a code 
 
10 
 
 ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 
 
 of ethics. 
 
 of rules for practical conduct or a theory of human 
 virtue ; nor shall I attempt to trace the origin and 
 nature of moral sentiments and ideas, or of the 
 social institutions and customs connected with mor- 
 ality. If these subjects have to be introduced at all, 
 it will be only in so far as they may be thought to 
 decide, or tend to decide, the question more imme- 
 diately in view. 
 
 (a) from in- Thus it forms no part of the present inquiry to 
 th^methods follow u ^ the application to conduct of different 
 ethical ends, or to exhibit the different practical 
 systems to which different ends naturally lead. It 
 might seem indeed, at first sight, as if the develop- 
 ment of their practical consequences might solve 
 the question as to the nature of the ends them- 
 selves. If we assume certain possible and primd 
 facie reasonable ethical ends, and then see what 
 codes of morality they will yield, surely (it may be 
 thought) that one which affords the most consist- 
 ent and harmonious code for the guidance of life 
 will be the end to be sought in preference to 
 all others. But in order that the criticism of what 
 Professor Sidgwick has called the methods of ethics 
 may be able to answer the question as to the end 
 or principle of ethics, certain conditions must first 
 be complied with. In the first place, it is necessary 
 ^at the ends or principles whose applications to 
 conduct are to be examined must not be uncritic- 
 ally accepted from the fluctuating morality of com- 
 
 Limitation 
 inquiry 
 
 from 
 
 ing an log- 
 
 ical alter- 
 natives, 
 
ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 11 
 
 mon- sense nor from the commonplaces of the 
 schools, but must be shown to be "alternatives 
 between which the human mind" is "necessarily 
 forced to choose when it attempts to frame a com- 
 plete synthesis of practical maxims, and to act in a 
 perfectly rational manner." 1 
 
 But although this requisite is complied with, it (66) from 
 will still remain possible, in the second place, that ^TLif-con- 
 two or more of the assumed principles may yield Jjj|*J* co< 
 systems of practical rules perfectly self-consistent, possible, 
 and yet inconsistent with one another. 2 It would 
 be very hard indeed to show that both the theory 
 of Egoistic Hedonism, and what is generally called 
 Utilitarianism, do not succeed in doing so : and thus 
 the examination of methods is not of itself suffi- 
 cient to settle the question of the end of conduct. 
 And since to quote Mr Sidgwick 3 it is " a fun- 
 damental postulate of ethics that either these 
 methods must be reconciled and harmonised, or all 
 but one of them rejected," it follows that the criti- 
 cism of methods leads naturally up to an indepen- 
 dent criticism of principles, unless indeed it can be 
 shown that one method only yields a consistent 
 code of practical rules. 
 
 1 Methods of Ethics, book i. chap. i. 5, 3d ed., p. 11. 
 
 2 " The rule, * Let every one care for me,' is quite as simple, 
 and, in a logical point of view, defines conduct as consistently and 
 reasonably as the rule, * Love your neighbour as yourself.' " 
 Leslie Stephen, Science of Ethics (1882), p. 73. 
 
 3 Methods of Ethics, I. i. 3, p. 6. 
 
12 ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 
 
 (cc) from its Even in this case, however, if it led to the adop- 
 
 assumption , 
 
 that the true tion or the end in question, it must be borne in 
 gtfe pe?* min(i tnat th 6 postulate would be implied that the 
 fectiycon- ^rue ethical end must be able to yield a consistent 
 
 sistent rules. 
 
 and harmonious system of rules for practical life. 
 "Without altogether denying this postulate, it yet 
 seems to me that it stands in need of qualification. 
 For in different circumstances, and at different 
 stages of individual and social development, the 
 application of the same ethical end may naturally 
 produce different and conflicting courses of conduct. 
 We must not start with any such assumption as 
 that the rationality of the end consists in some sort 
 of mathematical equality which ignores alike the 
 different environment with which one age and an- 
 other surround different generations, and the differ- 
 ent functions which one individual and another 
 have to perform in the social whole. We must 
 leave open the possibility that what is right now 
 may be wrong in another age ; we must remember 
 that everybody may not count for one, and that 
 some people may count for more than one; we 
 must admit that we may have sometimes to do to 
 others what we would not that others should do 
 to us. The only consistency we have a right to 
 demand must leave room for such a variety of differ- 
 ent conditions as to be, by itself, a very insecure 
 guide. 
 
 From the difficulty of complying with the above 
 
ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 13 
 
 * 
 
 conditions, it seems practically impossible for the 
 criticism of ethical methods to decide the question 
 of the ethical end. Even if the application to con- 
 duct of every important end has been taken account 
 of, we are met with the difficulty that two or more 
 mutually antagonistic though self-consistent prac- 
 tical codes may probably have been developed, 
 while we are not even justified in assuming that 
 inability to yield a system which will fit the com- 
 plex circumstances of life in a perfectly harmonious 
 manner is sufficient ground for rejecting an end 
 shown in some other way to be reasonable. 
 
 The last department of ethics referred to that (/s) distinct 
 
 .,-.., from moral 
 
 which has to do with the origin and nature ot moral psychology 
 sentiments and social customs has a bearing on 
 the question of the end of conduct in some respects 
 more important than the investigation of ethical 
 methods. For, whereas the latter expressly assumes 
 certain ends as primd facie reasonable, the former 
 inquiry, on the contrary, is now frequently under- 
 stood to be able, without presupposing any ethical 
 relations whatever, to trace the way in which, from 
 primitive feelings and customs, morality itself has 
 been evolved. The psychological side of ethical 
 inquiry has always had an important place with 
 English moralists. At times, indeed, the ques- 
 tion of the " moral faculty " has excited so much 
 interest as to divert attention from the nature of 
 morality itself. Moral truth has been supposed to 
 
14 ETHICS AND ITS PKOBLEMS. 
 
 be something known and indisputable, the only 
 question being how we came to know it. But the 
 psychology of ethics, reinforced by the knowledge 
 sociology gives of the development of morality, 
 rises now to larger issues. It attempts to show 
 the genesis of the moral from the non-moral, to 
 account thus for the origin of ethical ideas, and 
 even to determine what kinds of ends are to be 
 striven after. In this way, a theory of the origin 
 and growth of moral sentiments and institutions is 
 made to render important help to more than one 
 of the theories which will fall to be considered in 
 the sequel. 
 
 3. Present The present Essay has to inquire into the way in 
 limited which we may determine what the end of human 
 conduct is, into the basis of ethics, therefore. But 
 I do not propose to offer an exhaustive investiga- 
 tion of all the theories which have been or may be 
 started in solution of the problem. On the con- 
 trary, I will begin by excluding from the inquiry 
 all theories which seek the basis of ethics in some- 
 thing outside the constitution of man as a feeling 
 and reasoning agent : l not because I contend that all 
 
 1 The difference between Aristotle and Kant in ethics is some- 
 times expressed (see Trendelenburg, Hist. Beitrage zur Phil., 
 iii. 171 ff.) as if it consisted in the fact that the former in- 
 vestigated human nature in order to find its re'Aos, whereas the 
 latter sought the standard of action in a transcendental ground. 
 There is reason for this distinction in Kant's manner of state- 
 ment. But both may be regarded as investigating human nature. 
 
ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 15 
 
 such theories are primd facie unreasonable, but be- 
 cause it is at any rate the more obvious course to to theorie 
 seek to determine the function of an organism by on P the dmi 
 studying its inner constitution, than by having re- JSSnu 1 
 gard to something which is external to it, and does 
 not act upon and modify it as a necessary part of 
 its environment. It is only when this method has 
 been tried and has failed that we should seek out- 
 side us for some guide as to the part we ought to 
 play in the universe. Tor this reason I shall not 
 take into consideration the views of the basis of 
 ethics which find it in positive law either divine 
 or human, except in so far as they are shown to 
 follow from the nature of man. It is not necessary 
 for me to deny that the source of all moral obliga- 
 tion may be the will of God, or the commands of 
 the sovereign, or the opinion of society, and that 
 the highest moral ideal may be obedience to such a 
 rule. But theories of this kind make ethics merely 
 an application of positive theology, or of legislation, 
 or of social sentiment, and seem only to have an 
 
 Their difference rather consists in the different position and func- 
 tion assigned to reason in man. It is because Kant is for the 
 moment looking upon reason as something distinct from human 
 nature that he says that " the ground of obligation is to be sought, 
 not in the nature of man or in the circumstances in the world in 
 which he is placed, but cu priori simply in the notions of pure 
 reason" (Werke, iv. 237). His "metaphysical" view of ethics, 
 however, follows from the rational constitution of the human 
 subject and his experience, and does not depend on any source 
 that really " transcends " the reason of man. 
 
16 ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 
 
 appropriate place when we have failed to find an 
 independent basis for action. 
 
 The question which remains to be put may be 
 expressed in these terms : Can we find in human 
 nature (taken either alone or in connection with its 
 environment) any indications of the end of human 
 conduct, or, in other words, of the principle on 
 which human beings " ought " to act ? and if so, in 
 what direction do these indications point, and what 
 is their significance ? The answer to this question 
 will thus necessarily depend on the view we take 
 of the constitution of man and his relation to his 
 environment. And I purpose to bring this dis- 
 cussion within the necessary limits by consider- 
 ing the ethical consequences of one only of the 
 two views into which philosophical opinion is 
 divided. 
 
 and here to Now the fundamental principle of division in 
 Naturalism, philosophical opinion lies in the place assigned to 
 reason in human nature. 1 According to one theory, 
 man is essentially a sensitive subject, though able 
 to reason about his sensations that is, to associate, 
 compound, and compare them. He is supposed to 
 be built up of sense-presentations associated with 
 feelings of pleasure and pain. Recipient of external 
 impressions which persist in idea and are accom- 
 
 1 Opinion is also divided according to the place assigned to 
 reason in the world, this principle of division corresponding 
 almost exactly with the former. 
 
ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 17 
 
 panied by pleasure or pain on his part, and thus 
 followed by other ideas and impressions, man's 
 mental constitution is explained without attrib- 
 uting to reason any spontaneous or productive 
 function. 1 The other view differs from this in as distm- 
 attributing spontaneity to reason making it, in ? r u m Ration- 
 one way or another, the source of forms of thought, al ethics> 
 principles, or ideas. The former may be called the 
 Naturalistic, the latter the Eationalistic view of 
 man : from that follows a Naturalistic or Natural 
 ethics, from this a Eationalistic or Eational ethics. 
 Into both these theories, in a theoretical as well as 
 in an ethical aspect, the historical turn of thought 
 which has characterised recent inquiry has intro- 
 duced a profound modification. On the basis of Naturalism 
 Naturalism, we may either look "upon man as an vIduTiiTtic 
 individual distinct from other individuals, as was 
 done by Epicurus and Hobbes and the materialists 
 of the eighteenth century, or we may consider the 
 race as itself an organism, apart from which the orhistoricai. 
 individual is unintelligible, and look upon human 
 nature as having become what it now is through a 
 long process of interaction between organism and 
 environment, in which social as well as psychical 
 and physical facts have influenced the result. This 
 is the view to the elaboration of which Comte and 
 
 1 Thus it is the object of Helve'tius's first discours " De 1'es- 
 prit " to prove that physical sensibility and memory are the only 
 productive causes of our ideas. 
 
 B 
 
18 ETHICS AND ITS PKOBLEMS. 
 
 Darwin and Spencer have in different ways con- 
 tributed. 1 What makes the historical method of 
 importance philosophically, is not the mere fact 
 that it traces a sequence of events in time, but the 
 fact that, by doing so, it is able to look upon each 
 link in the chain of events as necessarily con- 
 nected with every other, and thus to regard as 
 a system or, rather, as an organism what pre- 
 vious empirical theories had left without any 
 principle of unity. 
 
 Rationalism A similar movement of thought has introduced 
 viduSiBtic" a like modification into the nationalistic theory. 
 According to older doctrines, the individual rea- 
 son is mysteriously charged with certain a priori 
 principles which are to us laws of knowledge and 
 of action ; whereas the form of Eationalism which 
 is now in the ascendant resembles the theory of 
 natural evolution in this, that as the latter finds 
 the race more real than the individual, and the 
 individual to exist only in the race, so the former 
 or universal- looks upon the individual reason as but a finite 
 manifestation of the universal reason, and attempts 
 to show the principles or constitutive elements of 
 this universal reason or consciousness in their 
 logical or necessary connection leaving open to 
 empirical investigation the way in which they 
 have gradually disclosed themselves in the in- 
 
 1 Comte, by connecting ethics with biology ; Darwin and Spen- 
 cer, by the doctrine of evolution. 
 
ETHICS AND ITS PROBLEMS. 19 
 
 dividual human subject, and in the expression of 
 the collective life of the race. Thus, as Natural 
 Ethics is divided into an individualistic and an 
 historical view, a similar distinction might be 
 made in Eational Ethics, though in this case it 
 would be more difficult to follow out the dis- 
 tinction in detail; and many ethical systems can- 
 not be said to have kept consistently either to one 
 side of it or to the other. 
 
 In the following discussion I shall investigate 
 the ethical theory which is founded on the basis of 
 Naturalism working out and criticising in some- 
 what greater detail that form of the theory which, 
 from the agreement it lays claim to with the results 
 of modern science, plays so important a part in 
 contemporary philosophical thought. 
 
20 
 
 PAET I. 
 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEOKY, 
 
 CHAPTEE II. 
 
 EGOISM. 
 
 Definition of IT is difficult to give an exact definition or even 
 description of what I have called the " natural " 
 view of man. Perhaps it may be best defined, 
 negatively, as the view which denies to reason any 
 spontaneous or creative function in the human 
 constitution. For this definition, if it still leaves 
 the positive description wanting, will at least 
 make the classification into " natural " and " ra- 
 tional" exhaustive and mutually exclusive. At 
 the same time it is to be noted that, on the theory 
 of Naturalism, reason is not supposed to be ex- 
 cluded from all share in determining questions of 
 conduct or the choice of ends. It would, indeed, 
 
EGOISM. 21 
 
 be impossible to have even the pretence of an 
 ethical theory without a certain use of reason. 
 But its function, in this case, is limited to the 
 merely formal one of bringing different presenta- 
 tions (or objects) and feelings into connection, 
 and comparing the different states of mind thus 
 formed with one another, not with a reason-given 
 standard. 
 
 Since the function of reason is thus restricted, 
 and its competency to supply an end for, or prin- 
 ciple of, action is denied, we must seek this end 
 either in the feelings of pleasure and pain which 
 accompany both sensory and motor presentations, 
 perceptions, that is to say, and actions, or in the 
 more complex, or apparently more complex, emo- 
 tions of the mind. And the latter may either be 
 themselves reducible to feelings of pleasure or pain 
 accompanying presentations directly pleasurable or 
 painful, and thence transferred by association to 
 other presentations, or they may be regarded as 
 somehow motives to action which may be or ought 
 to be followed on their own account. The Indi- 
 vidualistic Theory, therefore, is not necessarily 
 hedonistic. It admits of a twofold view of the 
 " natural " man : one which looks upon him as in 
 essence a pleasure-seeking, pain-avoiding animal; 
 another which regards him as having a variety of 
 impulses, some of which are not directed to his own 
 pleasure or avoidance of pain. 
 
22 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 i. its theory The former view psychological hedonism, as it 
 is called claims to be an exhaustive analysis of 
 the motives of human conduct, perfectly general 
 indeed, but yet valid for every case of action. It 
 denies the possibility of a man acting from any 
 other principle than desire of pleasure or aversion 
 from pain. The theory is, that it is a psychological 
 law that action is motived by pleasure and pain, 
 and that nothing else has motive-power over it. 
 If, then, one pleasure (or avoidance of pain) is 
 chosen in preference to another, it must be either 
 by chance, an alternative which has no ethical 
 significance no significance, that is, for the guid- 
 ance of voluntary conduct, or because the one 
 course promises, or seems to promise, th6 attain- 
 ment of a greater balance of pleasure than the 
 other, or is actually at the time more pleasant than 
 that other. Thus the view that pleasure is the 
 only motive of human action is really identical, for 
 ethical purposes, with the theory loosely expressed 
 in the law that action follows the greatest pleasure. 1 
 
 ambiguous, I say " loosely expressed"; for the law as thus 
 stated really admits of three quite different in- 
 
 1 Meaning by " greatest pleasure," greatest balance of pleasure 
 over pain, and thus inclusive of the meaning "least pain." It is 
 the expression in terms of feeling of the statement sometimes 
 preferred, that " action follows the line of least resistance " a 
 statement to which no exception can be taken, nor any import- 
 ance allowed, till it be translated into definite psychological 
 language. 
 
EGOISM. 23 
 
 terpretations, not always distinguished with the referring to 
 precision which such subjects require. 
 
 (a) In the first place, the law might mean that (a) actual 
 action always follows the course which, as a matter quences of 
 of fact, will in the long-run bring the greatest actlon> 
 balance of pleasure to the agent. It is evident 
 that there is no ground in psychology for main- 
 taining this view. Yet it is a fair interpreta- 
 tion of the "law" of psychological hedonism, as 
 commonly stated ; and it is at least an admissible 
 supposition that this meaning of the phrase has 
 not been without effect upon the uses to which 
 the law has been put by some of its upholders. 
 The second interpretation of the law namely (5), or (&> its ex- 
 that action is always in the direction which seems sequences) 
 to the agent most likely to bring him the greatest 
 balance of pleasure, whether it actually brings it or 
 not is the sense in which it appears to have been 
 most commonly taken when expressed with any 
 degree of accuracy. It is in this sense that in 
 language which ascribes greater consistency to 
 men's conduct than it usually displays " interest " 
 is asserted by the author of the 'Syt&me de la 
 nature ' to be " the sole motive of human action." l 
 
 1 " Ainsi lorsque nous disons que Vinteret est I 'unique mobile 
 des actions humaines, nous voulons indiquer par la que chaque 
 homme travaille a sa maniere a son propre bonheur, qu'il place 
 dans quelqu'objet soit visible, soit cache", soit re"el, soit imagin- 
 aire, et que tout le systeme de sa conduite tend a 1'obtenir." 
 Systeme de la nature (1781), i. 268. 
 
 
24 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 The same view is adopted by Bentham ; l and both 
 James Mill and John Stuart Mill identify desire 
 with pleasure, or an " idea " of pleasure, in terms 
 which are sufficiently sweeping, if not very care- 
 fully weighed ; 2 while the will is said to follow 
 desire, or only to pass out of its power when 
 coming under the sway of habit. 3 Still another 
 meaning may, however, be given to the " law " of 
 psychological hedonism, according to which the 
 doubtful reference to the manifold pleasures and 
 pains, contemplated as resulting from an action, is 
 or (c) its got rid of, and (c) the agent is asserted always to 
 
 1 " On the occasion of every act he exercises, every human 
 being is led to pursue that line of conduct which, according to his 
 view of the case taken by him at the moment, will be in the 
 highest degree contributory to his own greatest happiness." 
 Constitutional Code, book i. 2 ; Works, ix. 5. The continued 
 existence of the species is, Bentham thinks, a conclusive proof of 
 this proposition. 
 
 2 Thus, according to James Mill, " the terms ' idea of pleasure ' 
 and * desire ' are but two names ; the thing named, the state of 
 consciousness is one and the same. The word Desire is com- 
 monly used to mark the idea of a pleasurable sensation when the 
 future is associated with it." Analysis of the Phenomena of the 
 Human Mind, J. S. Mill's edit., ii. 192 ; cf. Fragment on Mac- 
 kintosh (1835), p. 389 f. To the same effect J. S. Mill says : 
 " Desiring a thing and finding it pleasant, aversion to it and 
 thinking of it as painful, are phenomena entirely inseparable, or 
 rather two parts of the same phenomenon ; in strictness of lan- 
 guage, two different modes of naming the same psychological fact." 
 Utilitarianism, 7th ed., p. 58. 
 
 3 " Will is the child of desire, and passes out of the dominion 
 of its parent only to come under that of habit." Utilitarianism, 
 p. 60. 
 
EGOISM. 25 
 
 choose that action or forbearance which is actually present 
 most pleasant, or least painful, to him at the time istics. 
 taking account, of course, of imaginative pleasures 
 and pains, as well as of those which are imme- 
 diately connected with the senses. It is in this 
 interpretation of its law that psychological hedonism 
 seems to be most capable of defence, and in this 
 sense it has been more than once stated and 
 defended. 1 
 
 The ethics of the form of Naturalism which is 2. Ethical 
 
 inferences 
 
 now under examination must be inferred from the from this 
 " law " that human action follows the greatest 
 
 1 Thus Jonathan Edwards says : " When I say that the Will is 
 as the greatest apparent good, or (as I have explained it) that 
 volition has always for its object the thing which appears most 
 agreeable, it must be carefully observed, to avoid confusion and 
 needless objection, that I speak of the direct and immediate 
 object of the act of volition, and not some object to which the 
 act of will has only an indirect and remote respect. " On the 
 Freedom of the Will, part i. 2 ; Works, i. 133. The matter 
 is put still more clearly by the late Alfred Barratt : " Action 
 does not always follow knowledge. Of course not : but the doc- 
 trine [Hedonism] does not require that ib should ; for it says, not 
 that we follow what is our greatest possible pleasure, or what we 
 know or ' think ' to be so, but what at the moment of action 
 is most desired." Mind, vol. ii. 173 ; cf. Physical Ethics, p. 52 ff. 
 So Mr Stephen, Science of Ethics, p. 47 : " It is more accurate 
 to say that my conduct is determined by the pleasantest judg- 
 ment, than to say that it is determined by my judgment of what 
 is pleasantest." The negative side of the same view was ex- 
 pressed by Locke in his doctrine that action is moved by the 
 most pressing uneasiness (Essay, II. xxi. 29, 31), and distinguished 
 by him from the former view (b), that the " greater visible good " 
 is the motive (II. xxi. 35, 44). 
 
26 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 pleasure, in one or other of the above meanings 
 which that law admits of. The law is the datum or 
 premiss from which we are to advance to an ethical 
 conclusion. The "right" is to be evolved from 
 the pleasurable ; and the pleasurable, consequently, 
 cannot be made to depend upon the right. It is 
 certainly true of the conduct of most men, "that 
 our prospect of pleasure resulting from any course 
 of conduct may largely depend on our conception 
 of it as right or otherwise." x But this presupposes 
 that there is a right independent of one's own 
 pleasure, and therefore does not apply to an ethics 
 based on the simple theory of human nature put 
 forward by psychological hedonism. - 
 (a) m its first It is scarcely necessary to discuss the first alter- 
 
 meaning, , / \ i-i-j 11 i 
 
 native (a), as no psychologist would seriously main- 
 tain it. A society composed of men constituted 
 in the way it supposes men to be constituted, would 
 be a collection of rational egoists, omniscient in 
 all that concerned the results of action, and each 
 adopting unerringly at every moment the course 
 of conduct which would increase his own pleasure 
 the most. The conduct of any member of such a 
 society could only be modified when and would 
 always be modified when the modified conduct 
 actually brought pleasurable results to the agent : 
 never so as to make him prefer the public good 
 (6) in its to his own. The second alternative (b) admits of 
 
 1 Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, 3d ed., p. 40. 
 
EGOISM. 27 
 
 such modification taking place only when it seems second 
 to the individual that this modified action will m 
 produce a greater balance of pleasure or smaller 
 balance of pain than any other course of action. 
 Under this theory an individual might indeed 
 prefer the public good or another man's good to 
 his own, but only through his being deceived as to 
 the actual results of his course of action. Ethics 
 as determining an end for conduct is put out of 
 court ; though the statesman or the educator may 
 modify the actions of others by providing appro- 
 priate motives. If the " two sovereign masters, 
 pain and pleasure," " determine what we shall do," 
 it is hardly necessary for them also " to point out 
 what we ought to do." l The end is already given 
 in the nature of action, though an enlightened 
 understanding will teach men how the greatest 
 
 1 Bentham, Principles of Morals and Legislation, chap, i., Works, 
 i. 1. With this statement may be compared the assertion of 
 Helve'tius : " II semble que, dans 1'univers moral comme dans 
 1'univers physique, Dieu n'est mis qu'un seul principe dans tous 
 ce qui a e'te'. ... II semble qu'il ait dit pareillement a 
 Thomme : . . . Je te mets sous la garde du plaisir et de la 
 douleur : 1'un et 1'autre veilleront a tes pense'es, a tes actions ; 
 engendrerpnb tes passions, exciteront tes aversions, tes amities, 
 tes tendresses, tes fureurs ; allumeront tes de'sirs, tes craintes, tes 
 espeYances, te de'voileront des ve'rite's ; te plongeront dans des 
 erreurs ; et apres t' avoir fait enfanter mille systemes absurdes et 
 diffe'rens de morale et de legislation, te decouvriront un jour les 
 principes simples, au deVeloppement desquels est attache* 1'ordre 
 et le bonheur du monde moral." De 1'esprit, III. ix, QEuvres 
 (ed. of 1818), i. 293. 
 
28 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 balance of pleasure may be obtained. We can 
 only get at a rule prescribing an end by changing 
 our point of view from the individual to the state. 
 It is best for the state that each individual should 
 aim at the common happiness ; but, when we talk 
 of this as a moral duty for the individual, all we 
 can mean is that the state will punish a breach of 
 it. In the words of Helvetius, 1 " pain and pleasure 
 are the bonds by which we can always unite per- 
 sonal interest to the interest of the nation. . . . 
 The sciences of morals and legislation can be only 
 deductions from this simple principle." According 
 to Bentham's psychology, a man is necessitated by 
 his mental and physical nature to pursue at every 
 moment, not the greatest happiness of the greatest 
 number, but what seems to him his own greatest 
 happiness. And what the legislator has to do is, 
 by judiciously imposed rewards and punishments, 
 especially the latter, to make it for the greatest 
 happiness of each to pursue the greatest happiness 
 of all. 2 As distinguished from this " art of legisla- 
 tion," " private ethics " consists only of prudential 
 rules prescribing the best means to an end pre- 
 determined by nature as the only possible end of 
 human action : it " teaches how each man may 
 
 1 De 1'homme, concl. gn., GEuvres, ii. 608. 
 
 2 Cf. Systeme de la nature, i. 120: "La politique devrait etre 
 1'art de rgler les passions des hommes et de les diriger vers le 
 bien de la socie'te'." 
 
EGOISM. 29 
 
 dispose himself to pursue the course most conducive 
 to his own happiness." l The consequences to the 
 theory of action of the third alternative (c) are ( C ) in its 
 similar: it only states the law with more appear- fining. 
 ance of psychological accuracy. If a man always 
 follows that course of action which will give him 
 at the time the greatest (real and imaginative) 
 satisfaction, it is impossible for us to infer from his 
 nature an ethical law prescribing some other end, 
 without admitting a fundamental contradiction in 
 human nature ; while to say that he ought to seek 
 the end he always does and cannot help seeking, 
 is unnecessary and even unmeaning. Modification 
 of character may of course be still brought about, 
 since the kinds of action in which an individual 
 takes pleasure may be varied almost indefinitely. 
 But the motive made use of in this educative pro- 
 cess must be personal pleasure ; and the end the 
 legislator has in view in his work must be the 
 same, 2 though it is often quietly assumed that 
 for him personal pleasure has become identified 
 with the wider interests of the community. 
 
 The different significations of which it admits Result of 
 show that the psychological law that action follows 
 the greatest pleasure is by no means so clear as it 
 may at first sight appear. Probably it is the very 
 
 1 Bentham, op. cit., chap. xix. (xvii. in the reprint of 1879), 
 20; Works,i. 148. 
 
 2 Cf. Bentham, Works, ix. 5. 
 
30 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 ambiguity of the law that has made it appear to 
 provide a basis for an ethical system. When it is 
 said that greatest pleasure is the moral end of 
 action, this " greatest pleasure " is looked upon as 
 the greatest possible balance of pleasurable over 
 painful states for the probable duration of life : on 
 the egoistic theory, of the life of the individual ; 
 on the utilitarian theory, of the aggregate lives of 
 all men or even of all sentient beings. But when 
 it is said that greatest pleasure is, as a matter of 
 fact, always the motive of action, it is obvious that 
 "greatest pleasure" has changed its signification. 
 For if the same meaning were kept to, not only 
 would the psychological law as thus' stated be 
 openly at variance with facts, but its validity 
 would render the moral precept unnecessary. It 
 is even unmeaning to say that a man " ought " to 
 do that which he always does and cannot help 
 doing. 1 On the other hand, if the double meaning 
 of the phrase had been clearly stated, we should at 
 ethical once have seen the hiatus in the proof of egoistic 
 hedonism the gap between the present (or appa- 
 rent) pleasure for which one does act, and the great- 
 est pleasure of a lifetime for which one ought to act 
 as well as the additional difficulty of passing 
 
 1 Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, I. iv. 1, 3d ed., p. 41 ; cf. 
 Green, Prolegomena to Ethics, p. 9 : "To a being who is simply 
 a result of natural forces, an injunction to conform to their laws 
 is unmeaning." 
 
EGOISM. 31 
 
 from egoism to utilitarianism. If greatest appa- 
 rent pleasure or greatest present pleasure is by 
 an inexorable law of human nature always sought, 
 how can it be shown that we ought to sacrifice the 
 apparent to the real the present pleasure that is 
 small to the greater future pleasure? If the in- 
 dividual necessarily pursues his own pleasure, how 
 can we show that he ought to subordinate it to 
 the pleasures of the " greatest number " ? 
 
 It is a matter of fact, however, that the psychol- 3. Transition 
 ogists who maintain that action follows the great- logSaTto 
 est pleasure meaning by that, greatest apparent f e ^| sm 
 or greatest present pleasure have in their ethics Right action 
 
 will imply 
 
 made the transition to an enlightened Egoism, or 
 even to Utilitarianism. The nature of the transi- 
 tion thus requires to be more clearly pointed out. 
 If the former interpretation of the law of psycho- 
 logical hedonism could be accepted, and a man's 
 motive for action were always what seemed to 
 him likely to bring him the greatest pleasure on 
 the whole, ethics what Bentham calls private 
 ethics could be reduced (as Bentham finally re- 
 duces it) to certain maxims of prudence. To be 
 fully acquainted with the sources of pleasure and (a) correct 
 
 . estimate of 
 
 pain, and to estimate them correctly, would imply conse- 
 possession of the highest (egoistic) morality. If action!" ( 
 men could be made to think rightly as to what 
 their greatest pleasure consisted in, then right 
 action on their part that is to say, the pursuit of 
 
32 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 their greatest pleasure would (according to Ben- 
 tham's psychology) follow as a matter of course. 
 :t Eight conduct, however, is not so purely an affair 
 of the intellect as this would make it. Indeed, 
 Bentham's psychological assumption requires only 
 to be plainly stated for its inconsistency with the 
 facts of human action to become apparent. The 
 " video meliora proboque, deteriora sequor " ex- 
 presses too common an experience to be so easily 
 explained away. The impulses by which action is. 
 governed are not always in accordance with what 
 the intellect decides to be best on a survey of the 
 whole life and its varied chances. In judging the 
 consequences of action, a future good ' is compared 
 with a present, regardless of the mere difference of 
 (6) and cor- time by which they are separated. But the springs 
 Itrength^ which move the will are often at variance with the 
 feeling. decisions of the understanding ; and many men are 
 unable to resist the strength of the impulse to act 
 for the pleasure of the moment, though they fore- 
 see that a greater future satisfaction would follow 
 from present self-denial. 
 
 It would seem, then, that the facts of experience 
 are sufficient to show that a man's conduct does not 
 always follow the course which he thinks likely 
 to bring him the greatest pleasure on the whole. 
 But the view that a man always acts for what is 
 most pleasant or least painful at the time can- 
 not be dismissed so easily. It is not enough simply 
 
EGOISM. 33 
 
 to point to the facts of human action in order to 
 show that this hypothesis is inconsistent with 
 them. If we instanced the self -restraint in which 
 so many pass their lives from day to day, it might 
 perhaps be answered that there is a persistent idea 
 of duty, or love of reputation, or fear of social 
 stigma, the repression of which would be more 
 painful than the restraint it puts upon other im- 
 pulses. Even the martyr who deliberately parts 
 with life itself for the sake of an ideal, may be said 
 to choose death as the least painful course open to 
 him at the time. It should be borne in mind, 
 however, that Professor Bain, the most thorough 
 psychologist of Bentham's school, refuses to admit 
 this line of defence for psychological hedonism, 
 and holds that, in actions such as those referred to, 
 men are really carried out of the circle of their 
 self-regarding desires. 1 But my present purpose is 
 not to discuss the merits of any such psychological 
 theory, but rather to investigate its ethical conse- 
 quences. And for this purpose the question re- 
 quires to be put, how a passage is effected from 
 psychological hedonism to an egoistic and even 
 to a utilitarian theory of ethics. 
 
 If a man always acts for his greatest present Thepostu- 
 
 , , , . . ., late that 
 
 pleasure, real and imaginary, it seems a far step to ac tio n can 
 say that he " ought " to act or in any way to J e tiona1 ' 
 expect that he will act at each moment for the 
 
 1 Cf. The Emotions and the Will, 3d ed., p. 293 ff. 
 C 
 
34 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 greatest sum of pleasure attainable in the probable 
 duration of his life. But on reflection, this may 
 turn out to follow if we postulate that conduct 
 can be rationalised. What is meant by this ego- 
 istic " ought " may be said to be simply that to 
 the eye of reason the pleasure of any one moment 
 cannot be regarded as more valuable than the 
 equal pleasure of any other moment, if it is equally 
 involves certain ; and that therefore to act as if it were is to 
 
 these con- . 
 
 ditions, act unreasonably. Man tails in acting up to rea- 
 son in this sense, because his action is not motived 
 by reason, but directly by pleasure and pain ; and 
 not by a mere estimate of pleasure and pain, but 
 by pleasure and pain themselves. The psycho- 
 logical hedonist must maintain that the estimates 
 of future pleasure and pain only become motives 
 by being not merely recognised (intellectually) but 
 felt (emotionally) that is, by themselves becoming 
 pleasurable or painful. If the Egoist calls any 
 action irrational, it cannot be because the motive 
 which produced it was not the greatest pleasure 
 in consciousness at the time. It can only be on 
 the ground that the greatest pleasure in conscious- 
 ness at the time is likely to lead to a sacrifice of 
 greater pleasure in the future ; and this must be 
 due either to intellectual misapprehension or to 
 the imagined fruition of future pleasure not being 
 strong enough to outweigh the pleasure which 
 comes from a present stimulus, and to the imagined 
 
EGOISM. 35 
 
 
 fruition of the more distant being weaker than that 
 of the less distant pleasure. It is owing to a 
 defect of the imagination on a man's part that 
 even with complete information he does not act 
 " up to his lights " irrational action being partly 
 a consequence of insufficient acquaintance with the 
 normal results of conduct, partly due to defective 
 imagination. Were a man's imagination of future 
 pleasure and pain as strong as his experience of 
 present pleasure and pain, and did he correctly 
 appreciate the results of his conduct, then his 
 action would, of psychological necessity, harmo- 
 nise with the precepts of egoistic hedonism. 
 
 Egoistic hedonism may therefore, in a certain 
 sense, be said to be a " reasonable " end of conduct 
 on the theory of psychological hedonism ; it is the 
 end which will be made his own by that ideally 
 perfect man whose intellect can clearly see the 
 issues of conduct, and whose imagination of the 
 future causes of sensibility is so vivid that the 
 pleasure or pain got from anticipating them is as 
 great as if they were present, or only less lively in 
 proportion as there is a risk of their not being 
 realised. Conversely it would seem that only that 
 man can act " reasonably " in whom imagination of the latter of 
 pleasure (or of pain) is already of equal strength 
 with the actual experience of it. But, if the " pleas- 
 ures of the imagination " are as strong as those of 
 sense or of reality, the latter obviously become 
 
36 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 superfluous ; and it follows that the ideally perfect 
 man is left without any motive to aim at the real 
 thing, since he can obtain as much pleasure by 
 imagining it. The cultured hedonist must, it would 
 seem, be able to 
 
 " Hold a fire in his hand 
 By thinking on the frosty Caucasus, 
 Or cloy the hungry edge of appetite 
 By bare imagination of a feast." 
 
 is inconsist- So far as feeling or motive to action goes, no differ- 
 ent with . . 
 
 the nature encc must exist for mm between reality and ima- 
 ary gination. And thus, although we may admit that, 
 on this psychological basis, conduct when ration- 
 alised agrees with that prescribed by egoistic 
 hedonism, yet it can only be rationalised by a 
 development of the strength of the imagination, 
 which would make the feeling which it brings with 
 it as strong as that which accompanies a real object, 
 and hence take away the motive for the pursuit of 
 the latter. The discrepancy between representa- 
 tion and presentation which is necessary for the 
 state of desire, 1 is no longer present. Hedonism 
 vindicates its rationality only on conditions which 
 imply the futility of action altogether. It is not 
 merely that the attainment of the hedonistic end in 
 practical conduct implies a strength of imagination 
 of which no one is capable, but the conditions of 
 
 1 Cf. Sully, Outlines of Psychology, p. 577. 
 
EGOISM. 37 
 
 acting both rationally and hedonistically, are condi- 
 tions which would paralyse all activity. 
 
 The foregoing argument may perhaps be ob- 4. possible 
 jected to on two grounds. On the one hand, it may to^pre^Sng 
 be said that it ignores the vast complexity of hu- ar g*ment: 
 man motive, and treats action as if it were a simple 
 and abstract thing. On the other hand, we may be 
 reminded of the fact that, while all men act for 
 pleasure, the moral quality of their conduct does 
 not depend on this fact, but on the kind of things 
 in which they take pleasure. 
 
 So far as the first objection is concerned, it seems (a) compiex- 
 to me that the fault belongs to the psychological tive but it 
 
 theory of human action, the ethical consequences of 
 which are under investigation. It is this theory aonism 
 
 J which ig- 
 
 which asserts that, however interwoven the threads nores this. 
 of impulse, aversion, and habit may be, their most 
 complex relations can be reduced to the formula, 
 " greatest pleasure, or least pain, prevails." It is 
 not necessary, indeed, that every action should be 
 the conscious pursuit of a pleasurable object already 
 before the mind in idea. But the theory, if con- 
 sistently carried out, implies that the action which 
 follows in the line of a previously formed habit, 
 does so because the discomfort or pain of breaking 
 through the habit would be sufficient to counter- 
 balance any satisfaction that might result. The ob- 
 jection, therefore, of excessive simplicity or-"ab- 
 stractness," is one which cannot have greater force 
 
38 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 than when urged against the theory of psychologi- 
 
 cal hedonism. 
 
 (6) differ- Further and this is the second objection the 
 ofpieasur- above analysis may be considered by some not to 
 awe objects; ^^ taken su ffi cient account O f the difference in 
 
 the objects in which a human being can take pleas- 
 ure, and of the fact that the moral quality of men 
 differs, not according as they act for pleasure or 
 not, but according to the kind of actions and suf- 
 ferances in which they find pleasure. There can be 
 no doubt of the importance of this distinction for 
 questions of practical morals. The man in whom 
 " selfishness takes the shape of benevolence," as it 
 did in Bentham, is infinitely better than the man 
 in whom it retains the form of selfishness. But 
 the consideration is important just because it goes 
 on the implied assumption that the hedonistic is 
 not the chief aspect of conduct, and that there is a 
 difference between courses of action more fundamen- 
 tal than the pleasurable or painful feeling attend- 
 but this in- ant on them. If the principles on which the objec- 
 Ire^ce to^ ti n i g founded were consistently adhered to and 
 something followed out, they would make not pleasure, but 
 
 else than J 
 
 pleasure, something else that, namely, by which pleasures 
 differ from one another in kind the ethical stand- 
 ard. But if, in ultimate analysis, it is the pleasure 
 felt or expected that moves to action, it would seem 
 that there is no way in which the conclusion of the 
 preceding argument can be avoided. If pleasure is 
 
EGOISM. 39 
 
 the motive, it must be qud pleasure that is to say, 
 either the greatest apparent pleasure, or the great- 
 est present pleasure, is the motive. If difference of 
 quality be admitted, we are introducing a determin- 
 ing factor other than pleasure. Certain kinds of 
 pleasure may be better than others for the race or 
 for the state. But these differences must be reducible which psy- 
 
 . -, i chological 
 
 to terms of individual pleasure admitting of purely hedonism 
 quantitative comparisons, before they become mo- admit^f. 
 tives to action. 1 From the point of view of the 
 whole, we may say that one action leads to a greater 
 sum of pleasure than another. But, in judging the 
 action of individuals, all that we can say of it is, 
 that to one man one class of actions gives pleasure, 
 to another another : each man is equally following 
 the course of action which either (a) will bring, or 
 (6) seems to him likely to bring, the greatest pleas- 
 ure, or (c) is actually most pleasant at the time. 
 From the nature of the individual we can evolve no 
 end beyond egoistic hedonism. And even this end 
 can only be made his at each occurrence of action 
 (assuming the first alternative (a) to be incorrect) 
 by enlightening his intellect so that (6) will corre- 
 spond with the actual greatest pleasure, or by also 
 
 1 Cf. J. Grote, ' Utilitarian Philosophy,' p. 20, note : " One 
 kind of pleasure may be, systematically, to be preferred to 
 another, but it must be because the pleasures classified under it 
 generally exceed those under the other in intensity, or some other 
 of the elements of value." 
 
40 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 enlivening his imagination of future pleasures and 
 pains so that (c) will correspond with it ; and this, 
 as has been shown, could only be effected under 
 conditions which are inconsistent with the prin- 
 ciples of human action. 
 
41 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 THE TEANSITION TO UTILITAEIANISM. 
 
 IT still remains possible, of course, to fix an ethical i. Different 
 
 end in some other way than by studying individual onndfvT^uai 
 
 human nature. We may, for instance, looking from and state 
 
 the point of view of the community, fix its greatest 
 
 happiness, instead of his own, as the individual's 
 
 end. But the difficulty then arises of persuading 
 
 the individual or, indeed, making it possible for 
 
 him to regard this impersonal goal as the end of 
 
 his conduct. For this purpose, Bentham seemed to 
 
 look to the exercise of administrative control which, 
 
 by a system of rewards and punishments, will make 
 
 the greatest happiness of the individual coincide so 
 
 far as possible with that of the community. 1 J. S. 
 
 Mill, on the other hand, with his eyes turned to the 
 
 1 Professor Bain distinguishes with greater clearness than his 
 predecessors, first, legal duty, or that the contravention of which 
 is punished by the ministers of the state ; secondly, moral duty, 
 enforced by the unofficial punishment of social disapprobation ; 
 and thirdly, the conduct which society leaves to individual choice, 
 without censuring either its commission or omission. Moral duty 
 is further distinguished by him from the meritorious, or conduct 
 
42 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 subjective springs of action, saw in the gradual 
 growth of sympathetic pleasures and pains the 
 means by which an individual's desires would cease 
 to conflict with those of his neighbours. 
 
 It is in some such way that the transition is 
 made from Egoism to Utilitarianism. The transi- 
 tion is made : Bentham and his school are an evi- 
 dence of the fact. But it is not therefore logical. 
 It is, indeed, important to notice that we only pass 
 from the one theory to the other by changing our 
 original individualistic point of view. Having al- 
 ready fixed an end for conduct regardless of the 
 difference between the individual at the time of 
 acting and at subsequent times, we proceed to take 
 the much longer step of ignoring the difference be- 
 tween the agent and other individuals. The ques- 
 tion is no longer, What is good or desirable for the 
 person who is acting ? but, What is best on the 
 whole for all those whom his action may affect- 
 that is to say, for the community ? 
 
 cannot be But while it is comparatively easy to see how 
 connected tins transition is effected as a matter of fact, it is 
 difficult to establish any logical connection between 
 its different stages, or to offer any considerations 
 fitted to convince the individual that it is reason- 
 able for him to seek the happiness of the commu- 
 nity rather than his own. Only that conduct, it 
 
 which society encourages by approval, without censuring its 
 omission. 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 43 
 
 may seem, can be reasonable which directs and per- 
 fects the natural striving of each organism towards 
 its own pleasure. We may, of course, let our point through 
 of view shift from the individual to the social " or- state to L 
 ganism." And in this case, if the " natural " end diyidua1 ' 
 of each human being is his own greatest pleasure, 
 the end of the community, or organised body of 
 pleasure-seekers, will naturally be concluded to be 
 the greatest aggregate pleasure of its members. 
 Thus, if we can hypostatise the community, and 
 treat it as an individual with magnified but human 
 wants and satisfactions, then, for this leviathan, the 
 ethical end will correspond to what is called Utili- 
 tarianism or Universalistic Hedonism. But, when Difference 
 we remember that the community is made up of ^Town 
 units distinct from one another in feeling and action, {^rTasure 
 the difficulty arises of establishing it as the natural of others 
 end, or as a reasonable end, for each of these units 
 to strive after the greatest pleasure of all. Tor it 
 is evident that the pursuit of the greatest aggregate 
 pleasure may often interfere with the attainment 
 by the individual of his own greatest pleasure, j On 
 the other hand, the self-seeking action of the indi- 
 vidual may no doubt lead to a loss of pleasure on 
 the whole ; \ but then it is not his own pleasure that 
 is lost, only other people's. To the outsider as 
 to the community it may seem irrational that a 
 small increase in the pleasure of one unit should 
 be allowed at the expense of a loss of greater pleas- 
 
44 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEOKY. 
 
 ure on the part of other units. But it seems irra- 
 tional only because the outsider naturally puts him- 
 self in the place of the community ; and neither 
 takes account of the fact that to the individual agent 
 there is a fundamental difference between his own 
 pleasure and any one else's pleasure : for him the 
 former is, and the latter is not, pleasure at all. 1 
 overlooked This fundamental difference seems to be over- 
 argumg j 00 ^ e( j w j ien the attempt is made to argue logically 
 
 1 Mr Gurney's attempt (Mind, vii. 349 ff.) to rationalise 
 the utilitarian " ought " depends upon the assumption that the 
 individual feels a desire (not only for his own, but) for other 
 people's pleasure (p. 352). From the point of view of the psy- 
 chological hedonist, however, this desire is only secondary and 
 derivative, depending upon the fact that it increases the pleasure 
 of the subject. "Your pleasure," the psychological hedonist 
 would say, " is desired by me qud my pleasure." If, on the other 
 hand, it is admitted that the individual has other ends than his 
 own pleasure, there seems no ground in psychological fact for 
 limiting these ends to something aimed at because pleasurable to 
 others. From this point of view the first step in the establish- 
 ment of an ethical theory would be an attempt to find a principle 
 of unity in the various ends actually aimed at by individuals, and 
 recognised by them as "good." This is made by Professor Sidg- 
 wick, who, while allowing that " it is possible to hold that the 
 objective relations of conscious minds which we call cognition of 
 Truth, contemplation of Beauty, Freedom of action, &c. , are good, 
 independently of the pleasures that we derive from them," main- 
 tains that " we can only justify to ourselves the importance that we 
 attach to any of these objects by considering its conduciveness, in 
 one way or another, to the happiness of conscious (or sentient) 
 beings" (Methods of Ethics, iii. xiv. 3, 3d ed., p. 398). But 
 Mr Sidgwick's Utilitarianism depends on a Rational view of 
 human nature which is beyond the scope of the present discus- 
 sion. See below, p. 74. 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 45 
 
 from egoistic psychology (or even from egoistic from egoism 
 ethics) to utilitarianism. Indeed, the hiatus in an^m. 1 
 logical proof is often only concealed by a confusion 
 of standpoints ; and J. S. Mill, while emphasising 
 the distinction between modern Utilitarianism and 
 the older \Epicureanisrnj has even allowed his 
 official " proof " of utilitarianism such proof, 
 that is, as he thinks the principle of Utility to be 
 susceptible of to rest on the ambiguity between 
 individual and social happiness. 
 
 This ambiguity does not seem to have been con- 2. connec- 
 sistently avoided even by Bentham. For the most egoism and 
 
 part, indeed, nothing can exceed the clearness with 
 which he recognises the twofold and possibly con- i n 
 flicting interests involved in almost every action. 
 There is the interest of the agent, and the interest 
 of others whom his action may affect. And he 
 also holds that, in the case of divergence of interests, 
 the individual will act for his own. I^The happi- 
 ness of the individuals," he says, 1 "of whom a 
 community is composed, that is, their pleasures 
 and their security, is the end, and the sole end, 
 which the legislator ought to have in view the 
 sole standard in conformity to which each indi- 
 vidual ought, as far as depends upon the legislator, 
 to be made to fashion his conduct. But whether 
 it be this or anything else that is to be done, there 
 
 1 Principles of Morals and Legislation, chap. iii. 1 ; Works, 
 i. 14. 
 
46 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 is nothing by which a man can ultimately be made 
 to do it, but either pain or pleasure/* that is, of 
 course, his own pain or pleasure. fHere, then, 
 ethical Utilitarianism and psychological Egoism 
 are both plainly involved. A man, it is said, can 
 only pursue general happiness by its being identical 
 with his own happiness. And as it is evident, and 
 admitted, that these two happinesses often diverge 
 in the courses of action naturally leading to them, 
 a man can only be beneficent, rather than selfish, 
 through some artificial arrangement which makes 
 beneficence to be for his interest: 1 in plain lan- 
 guage (since rewards are only of exceptional ap- 
 plicability), through his being punished for not 
 (a) utmtari- being beneficent. 2 But, as Bentham clearly shows, 
 poiitoi a many cases of action cannot be safely touched by 
 duty ' the legislator's art. Such cases u unmeet for 
 punishment" include not only the actions which 
 are beneficial or neutral in their results, but also 
 actions hurtful to the community, though they 
 may elude such vigilance as the state can contrive, 
 or their restraint by punishment inflicted by the 
 
 1 As Paley put it, with characteristic plainness of statement, 
 " We can be obliged to nothing, but what we ourselves are to gain 
 or lose something by." Moral and Political Philosophy, book ii. 
 chap. ii. 
 
 2 Cf. Bain, Emotions, p. 264 : " I consider that the proper 
 meaning or import of these terms [Morality, Duty, Obligation, or 
 Right] refers to the class of actions enforced by the sanction of 
 punishment." 
 
THE TKANSITION TO UTILITAKIANISM. 47 
 
 state may constitute a greater evil than the 
 offence. 1 Probity may be exacted by the " persons 
 stated and certain" who happen to be political 
 superiors : except in rare instances, positive benefi- 
 cence can not. Utilitarian conduct, therefore, is 
 not a "political duty," because it is not fully 
 enforced by definite punishment. The " art of 
 legislation" is indeed said to teach "how a mul- 
 titude of men, composing a community, may be 
 disposed to pursue that course which upon the 
 whole is the most conducive to the happiness of 
 the whole community, by means of motives to be 
 applied by the legislator." 2 But the means here 
 indicated are such as cannot fully compass the 
 attainment of the end. For the motives applied 
 by the legislator either cannot reach a large part 
 of the extra-regarding conduct of individuals, or 
 could only reach it by entailing greater evils than 
 those they would be used to prevent. 
 
 But if utilitarian conduct is not a political duty, (&> nor a 
 it may seem evident that it is at least a moral m 
 duty. Now a moral duty is said by Bentham 3 to 
 
 1 Bentham, Principles of Morals and Legislation, chap, xix, 
 (xvii.), 9 ff ; Works, i. 144 ff. 
 
 3 Ibid., 20, p. 148. 
 
 3 Fragment on Government, chap. v. ; Works, i. 293. Cf. 
 Principles of Morals and Legislation, ch. iii. 5, p. 14, where 
 the Moral Sanction is said to proceed from " such chance persons 
 in the community as the person in question may happen in the 
 course of his life to have concerns with." 
 
48 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 be " created by a kind of motive which, from the 
 %7icertainty of the persons to apply it, and of the 
 species and degree in which it will be applied, has 
 hardly yet got the name of punishment : by various 
 mortifications resulting from the ill-will of persons 
 fcmcertain and variable, the community in general ; 
 that is, such individuals of that community as he 
 whose duty is in question shall happen to be con- 
 nected with." In plain language, then, moral duty 
 simply means the ill-will of a man's neighbours 
 which follows his conduct in so far as that conduct 
 affects them disagreeably. Such ill-will on the 
 part of a man's neighbours may result from success 
 or from failure on his part, from a breach of eti- 
 quette, from refusal to sacrifice to the caprice of 
 those neighbours the wider good of the society 
 whom his conduct affects (but to whom it may be 
 unknown), from deception or from telling the truth. 
 In a word, the duty that is, the punishment is 
 entirely uncertain : not only as regards the persons 
 applying it, its nature and its amount, but also as 
 regards the kind of actions to which it applies. 
 They will be actions unpleasant to the people who 
 inflict the punishment, but not necessarily hurtful 
 to the common weal: since the immediate effects 
 of an action are easily recognised, while its wider 
 and more lasting consequences are neither so ap- 
 parent nor appeal so surely to the interest of those 
 who are cognisant of the action and immediately 
 
THE TKANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 49 
 
 affected by it. Moral duty, therefore, as Bentham 
 defines it, depending on, or rather identical with, 
 the ill-will of one's neighbours, is indefinite and 
 limited in its nature, and can command or sanction 
 no such definite and wide-reaching rule for conduct 
 as that a man should always act for the greatest 
 happiness of the greatest number of people whom 
 his action may affect. Utilitarian conduct, there- 
 fore, is neither a political duty nor a moral duty ; \ 
 nor does Bentham follow Paley in insisting upon (c) nor in- 
 
 ,.. i . .-IT i i sisted on as 
 
 it as a religious duty " created by punishment ; by a religious 
 punishment expected at the hands of a person duty ' 
 certain the Supreme Being." And " if he persists 
 in asserting it to be a duty but without meaning 
 it to be understood that it is on any one of these 
 three accounts that he looks upon it as such all 
 he then asserts is his own internal sentiment ; all 
 he means then is that he feels himself pleased or 
 displeased at the thoughts of the point of conduct 
 in question, but without being able to tell why. In 
 this case he should e'en say so ; and not seek to 
 give an undue influence to his own single suffrage, 
 by delivering it in terms that purport to declare 
 the voice either of God, or of the law, or of the 
 people." x 
 
 This plain piece of advice which Bentham gives 
 to Blackstone is not often neglected by himself. 
 The motive, he once said, of his own exceptional 
 
 1 Bentham, Fragment on Government, loc. cit. 
 D 
 
50 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 devotion to the interests of the community was 
 that it pleased him. " I am a selfish man/' he wrote, 
 " as selfish as any man can be. But in me, somehow 
 or other, so it happens, selfishness has taken the 
 shape of benevolence." l But when the matter is 
 thus brought back from the regions of political, 
 (d) nor sum- moral, and religious duty, to the individual ground 
 motived in of " private ethics," we have still to refer to Ben- 
 tham's own discussion of the question, " What mo- 
 tives (independent of such as legislation and reli- 
 gion may chance to furnish) can one man have to 
 consult the happiness of another ? " 2 Bentham at 
 once replies and indeed the answer on his princi- 
 ples is obvious enough that there is no motive 
 which always continues adequate. But yet there 
 are, he says, " no occasions in which a man has not 
 some motives for consulting the happiness of other 
 men." Such are " the purely-social motive of sym- 
 pathy or benevolence," and " the semi-social motives 
 of love of amity and love of reputation." A man 
 is directly moved to promote the happiness of 
 others through the sympathetic feelings which 
 make the happiness of others in some degree pleas- 
 urable to himself; and he is indirectly moved to 
 promote their happiness through his desire of their 
 friendship and good opinion. So far, therefore, it 
 is quite true that " private ethics " or what Ben- 
 
 1 Works, xi. 95 ; cf. J. Grote, Utilitarian Philosophy, p. 137. 
 
 2 Principles of Morals and Legislation, ch. xix. (xvii.), 7 ff. 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 51 
 
 tham regards as such " concerns every member 
 that is, the happiness and the actions of every ' 
 member of any community that can be proposed." l 
 It certainly concerns their happiness, but only in 
 so far as this is a means to the happiness of the 
 agent. So that when Bentham says that "there 
 is no case in which a private man ought not to 
 direct his own conduct to the production of his 
 own happiness and of that of his fellow-creatures," 
 he should rather say that a man will 2 only direct 
 his conduct to the happiness of his fellow- creatures 
 in so far as such action leads to his own happiness. 
 Private ethics, therefore, has to do with the happi- which can 
 ness of others only so far as this reacts on the topm- 
 happiness of self ; or, as Bentham ultimately defines dence * 
 it, in terms to which no exception can be taken : 
 " Private ethics teaches how each man may dispose 
 himself to pursue the course most conducive to his 
 own happiness by means of such motives as offer 
 of themselves." 3 
 
 Under Bentham's hands " private ethics " is thus 3. Ben- 
 
 -. , .. . tham's treat- 
 
 reduced to prudence, at the same time that the me nt ex- 
 author has failed to show why the general happi- haustlve 
 
 1 Loc. cit., 8, p. 144. 
 
 2 " Ought " is inappropriate here according to Bentham's prin- 
 ciples, since there is no question of punishment inflicted by a po- 
 litical or social or religious superior. 
 
 3 Loc. cit., 20, p. 148. 
 
52 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 from his ness is to be aimed at by the individual as a reli- 
 Stew. gious or political or moral duty. Nor is this failure 
 due to any lack of skill in following out the con- 
 sequences which his premisses involved. The argu- 
 ments used against him have thus an equally valid 
 application to all who adopt the same general line 
 of thought. For Bentham appears to have seen as 
 clearly as any of his disciples the difficulty of bring- 
 ing the egoistic basis of his theory of human nature 
 into harmony with the universal reference required 
 by his ethics. And the criticism already offered of 
 the way in which Bentham attempts to bring about 
 this connection may be shown not to be restricted 
 to his special way of putting the case. 
 
 It is necessary to remember that throughout this 
 chapter we are looking from the individual's point 
 of view, and inquiring how far it is possible to work 
 from it in the direction of utilitarianism. Now it 
 is admitted that, in pursuing his own happiness, 
 he is sometimes led, and may be led on the whole, 
 to neglect the general happiness. A sufficient 
 reason for following the latter or an obligation to 
 do it can therefore only come either from the 
 supreme power or from one's fellow-men, and from 
 the latter either as organised in the State, and ex- 
 pressing themselves by its constituted authorities, 
 or else by the vaguer method of social praise and 
 blame. Bentham's classification of the possible 
 sources or kinds of duty into religious, political, 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 53 
 
 and moral [or social], is therefore a natural conse- 
 quence of the individualistic system. 
 
 The first of these possible sources of duty is in- ( a > The re- 
 deed only mentioned by Bentham, and then passed ^ us 
 by. And yet it might seem that the religious sanc- 
 tion is a more efficient motive - power than the 
 social, while it applies to regions of conduct which 
 legal enactment cannot reach. Without question, 
 the operation of such a motive is capable of bringing 
 egoistic conduct into harmony with utilitarianism, 
 or with any other principle of action to which the 
 sanction may be attached. " Private happiness is relied on by 
 our motive, and the will of God our rule," says 
 Paley ; l and in this case such conduct will be 
 obligatory as the rule may arbitrarily determine ; 
 while, whatever it may be, there will be a strong 
 enough motive to follow it. The whole fabric of a 
 moral philosophy such as Paley's, therefore, rests 
 on two theological propositions that God has or- 
 dained the general happiness as the rule of human 
 conduct, and that He will punish in another life 
 those who disregard that rule. The basis of mor- 
 ality is laid in a divine command enforced by a 
 divine threat. Perhaps it will be generally agreed 
 that Bentham acted wisely in not laying stress on 
 this application of the " religious sanction." Even 
 those least inclined to theological agnosticism would 
 reject any such rough-and-ready solution of the 
 
 1 Moral and Political Philosophy, book ii. chap. iii. 
 
54 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 inverts the problem which deals with the relation of morality 
 tween ethics to the divine nature. Paley's method of treatment, 
 io gy> e they would say, inverts the relation in which the- 
 ism stands to morality. The divine will cannot be 
 thus arbitrarily connected with the moral law. It 
 can be conceived to approve and sanction such an 
 object as the happiness of mankind only when God 
 is first of all regarded as a moral being, and the hap- 
 piness of mankind as an obj ect of moral action. If any 
 relation of consequence can be asserted between them, 
 the general happiness is to be regarded as a moral 
 duty first, and only afterwards as a religious duty. 
 (&) Limits of When he comes to the political sanction, Ben- 
 sanction, tham's treatment wants nothing in respect of ful- 
 ness, and even those who do not agree with his esti- 
 mate of the infelicific character of many existing 
 institutions and enactments will admit that even the 
 best-intentioned legislator cannot make utilitarian 
 conduct a political duty. We must bear in mind 
 here, also, the effect which individual desires and 
 opinions have not only on social judgments, but also 
 on statute-law. In arguing on the relation of the 
 individual to the State, we are too ready to forget 
 that the State is represented by a legislator or body 
 of legislators, and that we can never assume that 
 in their cases private interest has already become 
 identified with the larger interests of the com- 
 munity. 1 For were this the case, the accusation 
 
 1 This is clearly recognised by Bentham : " The actual end [as 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 55 
 
 of class-legislation or private interest would not be 
 heard so often as it is. 
 
 A modern disciple of Bentham would thus be 
 compelled, just as Bentham himself was, to make social sane- 6 
 utilitarianism neither a political nor religious but tlon> 
 a " moral " duty, enforced by and founded on the 
 shifting and uncertain punishments or sanctions of 
 society what Professor Bain describes as "the 
 unofficial expressions of disapprobation and the 
 exclusion from social good offices." 1 But as a 
 logical proof of utilitarianism, this means is, if 
 possible, weaker than the preceding : for social 
 opinion, though of somewhat wider applicability 
 than legal enactment, has probably been, for the 
 most part, in even less exact correspondence than 
 it with the general happiness. The social sanction 
 is strict on indifferent points of etiquette, does not 
 consult the general interests of mankind on points 
 of honour, and is lenient towards acts that the 
 utilitarian moralist condemns. 2 
 
 distinguished from the right and proper end] of government is," 
 he says, " in every political community, the greatest happiness of 
 those, whether one or many, by whom the powers of government 
 are exercised." Constitutional Code, booki., Introd., 2 ; Works, 
 ix. 5. 
 
 1 The Emotions and the Will, p. 264. 
 
 2 Cf. Bain, The Emotions and the Will, p. 287. Professor 
 Bain says (Emotions, p. 276 n.), "we ought to have a written 
 code of public morality, or of the duties imposed by society, over 
 and above what parliament imposes, and this should not be a 
 loosely written moral treatise, but a strict enumeration of what 
 
56 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 (d) and of Prof essor Bain, however, advances from the ex- 
 
 the internal 
 
 sanction so temal disapprobation to an internal sanction 
 
 far as a re- T T . . . , , . , 
 
 suit of the looking upon conscience as one ot the powers which 
 inflicts punishment, and lies at the source of the 
 feeling of obligation. But if conscience is only " an 
 ideal resemblance of public authority, growing up 
 in the same individual mind, and working to the 
 same end," it can, as little as its archetype, point 
 to the maxim of utilitarianism. According to 
 Professor Bain, it is through this sentiment at 
 first a mere imitation of external authority that 
 the individual becomes a law to himself, on recog- 
 nising the utilities that led to the imposition of the 
 law. 1 But on this theory, in so far as conscience 
 continues to point to the conduct impressed upon 
 it by its external pattern, it fails to correspond 
 with the utilitarian maxim. If, on the other hand, 
 it is modified by the comprehensive and unselfish 
 view of the effects of conduct which utilitarianism 
 demands, it must be at the expense of correcting 
 
 society requires under pain of punishment by excommunication 
 or otherwise, the genuine offences that are not passed over." 
 This would certainly be very desirable, were it not from the 
 nature of the case impracticable. Popular judgment as to a 
 man's conduct, what society imposes, is one of the things most 
 difficult to predict : it is under the influence of most hetero- 
 geneous causes, personal, industrial, religious, political, &c. I do 
 not think, for instance, that any one could safely undertake to 
 describe exactly the kind of actions which will infallibly call forth 
 the censure of British public opinion, or that of the smaller and 
 intersecting groups into which society is divided. 
 1 Emotions, p. 288. 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 57 
 
 its original edicts, and so far discrediting its author- 
 itative claims. 
 
 The "social sanction" would be of much greater vaiueofthe 
 service if used to show how a solidarity is brought S* * 
 about between the interests and feelings of the 
 individual and those of his neighbours, from which 
 the utilitarian maxim may be arrived at by a gen- 
 eralisation of his principle of conduct as modified 
 by the social impulse. But this would not consti- apart from 
 tute a logical justification of utilitarianism : it would f^tmtari- 
 show how the principle has been arrived at, but amsm * 
 without giving a sufficient reason to the individual 
 for adopting it. And this is really the tendency of 
 much recent discussion of Professor Bain's theory 
 of conscience as a reflex of the external order, of 
 George Grote's analysis of the moral sentiment, 
 and of Mill's doctrine of the progressive identifica- 
 tion of the individual's feelings with those of his 
 neighbours through the gradual increase of sym- 
 pathetic pleasures and pains: for it was to this 
 source that Mill looked for the practical solution 
 of the antinomy between his psychological and 
 ethical theories, though he himself tried to pass 
 from one position to the other by means of 
 the " highway in the air " constructed by his own 
 logic. 
 
 Mill's attempt to pass by a logical method from 4. MQI-S 
 psychological hedonism to utilitarianism is an in- logical d< 
 
 ' 
 
 
58 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 fence of structive commentary on the difficulties which 
 ism: beset the transition. His work may be described 
 
 as a vindication of the utilitarian morality, first, 
 from the charge of sensualism ; and secondly, from 
 that of selfishness. And it is largely owing to his 
 polemic that utilitarianism is no longer looked 
 upon as either a sensual or a selfish theory. It 
 is not sensual, unless, indeed, the pleasures of most 
 men are of a sensual kind. So far from being 
 selfish, it is almost stoical in the subordination of 
 individual desires it enjoins. But Mill wished to 
 do more than clear the character of utilitarian 
 ethics. He wished to show a logical reason for 
 utilitarians pursuing elevated pleasures rather than 
 base ones, and to demonstrate the connection of his 
 moral imperative with the principles which the 
 school he belonged to laid down for human motives. 
 In both these respects his failure is conspicuous, 
 (a) distinc- In the former endeavour, he went against Ben- 
 
 tion of kinds ., , ,. ^ T , j -1-1 
 
 of pleasure, tham by attempting to draw a distinction in kind 
 amongst pleasures a distinction not reducible to 
 quantitative measurement. A higher degree of 
 quality in the pleasure sought was to outweigh any 
 difference in its amount or quantity. With this 
 modification, utilitarianism is made to require a 
 subordination of the lower or sensuous nature to 
 the higher or intellectual nature. Pleasure, indeed, 
 is still the end ; but the " higher " pleasure takes 
 precedence over the "lower," irrespective of the 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 59 
 
 amount of pleasant feeling that results. Pleasure 
 is still the standard, but not the ultimate standard ; 
 for a further appeal has to be made to the criterion 
 that distinguishes one pleasure from another, not 
 as merely greater or less, but as higher or lower. 
 As is well known, Mill did not look either to the 
 action or to the feeling itself for this criterion. To 
 have done so would have implied an acknowledg- 
 ment that pleasure was no longer regarded as the 
 
 ultimate standard. He found the criterion of determined 
 ., 1 ,1 T by author- 
 
 superiority simply in the opinion people of ex- i ty , 
 
 perience have about the relative desirability of 
 various sorts of pleasure. But such a criterion 
 'only pushes the final question of the standard one 
 step farther back. Those people of experience to 
 whom Mill refers who have tried both kinds of 
 pleasure, and prefer one of them l can they give 
 no reason for, no account of, their preference ? If 
 so, to trust them is to appeal to blind authority, 
 and to relinquish anything like a science of ethics. 
 But, if Mill's authorities can reflect on their feelings, 
 as well as feel, they can only tell us one or other 
 of two things. Either the so-called " higher " pleas- 
 ure is actually, as pleasure, so preferable to that 
 called " lower," that the smallest amount of the one 
 would be more pleasurable than the largest amount 
 
 1 I have spoken, for simplicity's sake, as if there were two kinds 
 of pleasure easily distinguishable. But the question is really 
 much more complicated. 
 
60 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 of the other ; or else the higher is called higher, 
 
 and is to be preferred to the lower even although 
 
 the latter may be greater as pleasure because of a 
 
 quality belonging to it over and above its character 
 
 either can as pleasant feeling. The former verdict would be 
 
 to difference ^ n tne ^ rst P^ ace paradoxical, and, in the second 
 
 of quantity, place, would give up Mill's case, by reducing 
 
 or leads to r ' J 
 
 non-hedon- quality to a quantitative standard. Besides, it 
 ard ; would be no valid ground of preference for men in 
 
 general ; since the pleasure of various actions and 
 states differs according to the susceptibility of the 
 subject. According to the latter verdict, the char- 
 acteristic upon which the distinction of quality 
 depends, and not pleasure itself, becomes the 
 ethical standard. 
 
 (&)ambigui- In respect of his main contention, that utilitarian- 
 proofof 18 i sm * s a theory of beneficence, and not of prudence 
 utilitarian. or O f selfishness, Mill emphasised even more strongly 
 than Bentham had done the distinction between 
 the egoism which seeks its own things, and the 
 utilitarianism according to which everybody counts 
 for one, and nobody for more than one. But when 
 he attempted to connect this doctrine logically with 
 the psychological postulates of his school, he com- 
 mitted a double error. In the first place, he con- 
 fused the purely psychological question of the mo- 
 tives that influence human conduct with the ethical 
 question of the end to which conduct ought to be 
 directed ; and, in the second place, he disregarded 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 61 
 
 the difference of end there may be for society as a 
 collective whole, and for each member of the society 
 individually. " There is in reality," he says, 1 " noth- 
 ing desired except happiness ; " and this psycholog- 
 ical theory is too hastily identified with the ethical 
 principle that happiness alone is desirable, or what 
 ought to be desired and pursued. Moreover, " no 
 reason," he says, "can be given why the general 
 happiness is desirable, except that each person, so 
 far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his 
 own happiness." And this admission, which seems 
 as good as saying that no reason at all can be given 
 why the individual should desire the general hap- 
 piness, is only held to be a sufficient reason for it, 
 through assuming that what is good for all as an 
 aggregate is good for each member of the aggregate : 
 "That each person's happiness is a good to that 
 person, and the general happiness, therefore, a good 
 to the aggregate of all persons." 2 
 
 It may appear strange to offer the preceding as the imperfect 
 logical basis of an ethical principle which has had of ethical 6 
 so wide and, on the whole, beneficial an influence JJ 
 as utilitarianism. The explanation is to be found o 
 in the want of full coherence which often exists, 
 and is nowhere commoner than in English ethics, 
 between an author's practical view of life and the 
 foundation of psychology or metaphysics with which 
 
 1 Utilitarianism, p. 57. 2 Ibid., p. 53. 
 
62 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 it is connected. It would certainly be wrong to 
 imagine that Bentham's self-denying labours rested 
 on a confusion of standpoints, or that Mill's moral 
 enthusiasm had no other support than a logical 
 quibble. To both of them, and to many others, 
 utilitarianism was an ethical creed influencing their 
 lives, which was scarcely connected with the at- 
 tempt to justify it logically. Such reasons in its 
 favour as they adduced were rather after-thoughts 
 for the defence of their creed than the foundations 
 on which it was built. 
 5. Actual The formula of utilitarianism cannot be expressed 
 
 transition to . 
 
 utilitarian- as the conclusion or a syllogism or or an inductive 
 inference. It seems rather to have been arrived at 
 by the production or the recognition of a sympa- 
 thetic or " altruistic " sentiment, which was made 
 to yield a general principle for the guidance of con- 
 duct. This process involves two steps, which are 
 consecutive and complementary, although the posi- 
 tions they connect are not necessarily related. The 
 first step is to overcome the selfish principle of 
 action in the individual ; the second to generalise 
 it, and obtain a principle for the non-selfish action 
 that results. Mill seems to be the only recent 
 writer who, in making this transition, adheres 
 strictly to the psychological hedonism distinctive 
 of his school. He looks to the influence of educa- 
 tion in increasing the feeling of unity between one 
 man and his neighbours, till individual action be- 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 63 
 
 comes merged in altruistic or social action. " The 
 social state," he says, a is at once so natural, so 
 necessary, and so habitual to man, that, except in 
 some unusual circumstances, or by an effort of 
 voluntary abstraction, he never conceives himself 
 otherwise than as a member of a body." l This is 
 perfectly true, but does not imply a sublation of 
 selfishness. A man " never conceives himself other- 
 wise than as a member of a body ; " but it does not 
 follow from this that he will subordinate his own 
 interests to the interests of the other members when 
 the two clash. In cases of conflict the individual 
 often tends to sacrifice the good of his neighbours 
 to his own good ; and he may do so although he 
 fully recognises the social consequences of action, 
 just because he still remains at the ethical stand- 
 point which treats private good as superior to public. 
 It is true, as Mill contends, that, " in an improving 
 state of the human mind, the influences are constant- 
 ly on the increase, which tend to generate in each 
 individual a feeling of unity with all the rest ; which 
 feeling, if perfect, would make him never think of, 
 or desire, any beneficial condition for himself, in 
 the benefits of which they are not included." 2 But 
 this is not sufficient, to connect the two antagonistic 
 
 1 Utilitarianism, p. 46. But no statement of the sociality of 
 man could be more explicit or satisfactory than that of Butler, 
 Sermons, i. 
 
 2 Utilitarianism, p. 48. 
 
64 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 poles of Mill's system. It starts with assuming the 
 notion of an "improving state/' of the human mind, as 
 determined according to an ethical standard not yet 
 arrived at ; and it gives no valid account of the means 
 by which the improvement is to be brought about. 
 It is prophetic of a time when the motives of human 
 nature will have been so modified that the antagon- 
 ism between self and others will be no longer felt ; 
 but it offers no practical solution of the antinomy 
 suited to present circumstances, 
 (a) recogni- The basis of the ethical sentiment by which the 
 
 tionofSym- . 
 
 pathy desires and actions of a man are to be brought into 
 harmony with those of his fellows is investigated 
 in a more thorough manner by Professor Bain and 
 by George Grote. But both of these writers stand 
 on a somewhat different platform from the strict 
 psychological hedonism which Mill never relin- 
 quished. Thus Grote enumerates as " elementary 
 tendencies of the mind," which ethical sentiment 
 presupposes, and out of which it is compounded, 
 self-regarding tendencies, sympathetic tendencies, 
 benevolent affections, malevolent affections, and 
 (though in a smaller degree) love and hatred of 
 those who cause pleasure and pain to others ; l and 
 this without interpreting sympathy, in the way that 
 Mill does, as having for its end the pleasures which 
 come with the gratification of the sympathetic 
 impulse, or the removal of the pain caused by its 
 
 1 Fragments on Ethical Subjects (1876), p. 6. 
 
THE TRANSITION" TO UTILITARIANISM. 65 
 
 restraint. As Professor Bain argues, this position 
 of Mill's " is tenable only on the ground that the 
 omission of a disinterested act that we are inclined 
 to, would give us so much pain that it is on the 
 whole for our comfort that we should make the 
 requisite sacrifice. There is plausibility in this 
 supposition." But " the doctrine breaks down 
 when we try it upon extreme cases. . . . All 
 that people usually suffer from stifling a generous 
 impulse is too slight and transient to be placed 
 against any important sacrifice." 1 In recognising as 
 sympathy as a " purely disinterested " impulse, 2 Mr Bam,' 
 Bain breaks loose at an important point from the 
 psychology of Bentham. He is indeed only kept 
 from a complete break with it by the position he 
 ascribes to sympathy as outside of the ordinary 
 sphere of voluntary action. Above all things, it 
 would seem to be necessary that nothing should 
 conflict with "our character as rational beings, 
 which is to desire everything exactly according 
 to its pleasure-value." 3 But sympathy obviously 
 " clashes with the regular outgoings of the will 
 in favour of our pleasures ; " so that it ought to 
 be placed outside voluntary action, and regarded 
 
 1 The Emotions and the Will, 3d ed., p. 295. 
 
 2 Ibid., p. Ill ; cf. Mind, viii. 55 : "The important exceptions 
 to the law of Pleasure and Pain are (1) Fixed Ideas, (2) Habits, 
 and (3) Disinterested action for others. " 
 
 3 Emotions, p. 438. 
 
 E 
 
66 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 simply as " a remarkable and crowning instance 
 of the Fixed Idea." 1 
 
 without be- It is owing to its exclusion, as a fixed idea, from 
 tJfdetermtae the sphere of voluntary conduct, that sympathetic 
 the ethical a pp r0 p r i a tion of the feelings of others has little or 
 no place assigned it by Professor Bain, when he goes 
 on 2 to describe the way in which the moral opinions 
 of men have actually originated. They have, he 
 holds, a twofold source the one arising from the 
 necessity for public security, the other being of 
 sentimental origin. The former makes society 
 ordain those acts and services required for its own 
 preservation. The latter leads to the confusion of 
 this necessary element of morality with the senti- 
 mental likes and dislikes which may be character- 
 istic of different people. These are " mixed up in 
 one code with the imperative duties that hold 
 society together;" and it is only when "we dis- 
 entangle this complication, and refer each class of 
 duties to their proper origin," that we can " obtain 
 a clear insight into the foundations of morality." 3 
 Morality, therefore, is that which is imposed by 
 society for its own preservation and security, and 
 which is sanctioned by the punishments of society 
 either in its "public judicial acts," or "by the 
 unofficial expressions of disapprobation and the 
 exclusion from social good offices." 4 Of this ex- 
 
 1 Emotions, p. 121. 2 Ibid., p. 271 ff. 
 
 3 Ibid., p. 273. 4 Ibid., p. 264. 
 
THE TKANSITION TO UTILITAEIANISM. 67 
 
 ternal law the moral sense or conscience is merely 
 a subjective mirror or copy. The duty of unselfish- 
 ness is not connected with the disinterested impulse 
 of sympathy, but is traced to the external order of 
 society, which has found it necessary to restrain 
 the self-seeking action of individuals a restraint 
 which has come to be transferred to the consciences 
 of the members of the society. 
 
 Mr Bain's theory falls back in this way upon 
 external authority, just as Bentham's did ; and, for 
 the same reasons, they are neither of them able to 
 prescribe the utilitarian principle of conduct. But, 
 in his assertion of the disinterested nature of sym- 
 pathy, Mr Bain has introduced though he has not 
 himself utilised a fruitful principle, by means of 
 which a basis of moral sentiment may be found 
 by means of which it is possible to escape from 
 ethical as well as psychological egoism. 
 
 This element of sympathy is most fully recog- and by 
 nised in the instructive analysis of ethical sentiment 
 by the late George Grote. At the same time, Grote 
 does not, like Adam Smith, for instance, attempt to 
 evolve the material characteristics of approbation 
 and disapprobation from this source. The mere 
 putting of one's self in the place of a spectator or 
 in that of the patient instead of that of the agent, 
 is only a formal change, which will modify our 
 judgments or feelings without accounting for their 
 actual content. But a uniform formal element 
 
68 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 in all ethical sentiment is, according to Grote, a 
 man's " constant habit of viewing and judging of 
 circumstances around him," both from the point of 
 view of the agent and from that of the patient. 1 
 This twofold position is occupied by every indivi- 
 dual. He is an agent, and in that position his own 
 interests and feelings are separate from, and often 
 at variance with, those of others. But he is also a 
 patient in respect of the actions of others, and in 
 that position his interests and his feelings are com- 
 monly in unison with those of the majority. Hence 
 a man is led constantly to adopt ideally the point 
 of view which is not actually his own at the time, 
 so that " the idea of the judgment which others will 
 form becomes constantly and indissolubly associ- 
 ated with the idea of action in the mind of every 
 agent." In every community, certain actions are 
 visited with the admiration, esteem, and protection 
 of the society ; certain other actions with the oppo- 
 site feelings and results : so that there arises " an 
 association in my mind of a certain line of conduct 
 on the part both of myself and of any other indivi- 
 dual agent, with a certain sentiment resulting from 
 such conduct, and excited by it, in the minds of the 
 general public around us. It is a sentiment of 
 regulated social reciprocity as between the agent 
 and the society amongst which he lives." And 
 this sentiment, when enforced by a sanction, 
 
 1 Fragments on Ethical Subjects, p. 8 f. 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 69 
 
 constitutes the complete form of ethical senti- 
 ment. 
 
 As a complete explanation of the moral senti- 
 ments and judgments of men, this theory does not 
 seem to be above criticism. It requires not only 
 an association between every personal action and 
 the feelings sympathetically imagined by the 
 agent with which the action will be regarded by 
 others, but it also implies that this association has 
 become so inseparable that the feeling appears as 
 an individual or personal one, distinguished by the 
 subject from other sentiments which he has on con- 
 sciously imagining himself in the position of others. 
 But it is referred to here as illustrating what we 
 find in Mill, and, in a different way, in Professor 
 Bain, that the first real step towards the utilitarian 
 standard is to make the individual pass somehow 
 or other to a standpoint outside his own nature. 
 In Mill this is done mainly by the assertion of the 
 social nature of man, in Grote by showing how a 
 moral sentiment may be arrived at by the com- 
 bined action of sympathy and association. 
 
 The further influence required in the transition (&) The idea 
 to utilitarianism is the idea of equality. The best 
 expression of utilitarian doctrine followed soon after 
 the assertion of the equal rights of men which 
 signalised the politics of the end of last century 
 in 'the French and American revolutions. Bentham 
 was permeated by the spirit of this movement, 
 
70 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 however far he might be fron accepting its ab- 
 stractions about natural rights. In his hands, too, 
 utilitarianism was a political rather than an ethical 
 doctrine. " Everybody to count for one and nobody 
 for more than one" follows naturally from the 
 phrase, "the greatest happiness of the greatest 
 yto number." Without this assertion of the necessity 
 sympathy; of an equal distribution, there is no safeguard 
 against sympathy being restricted and partial in 
 its operation. Indeed the feeling of sympathy in 
 itself is naturally strongest towards those with 
 whom one is in most frequent relation, or con- 
 nected by numerous associative ties ; and if left to 
 itself, it might therefore be expected to give rise to 
 the extended selfishness of class or family interest, 
 only relieved by a spasmodic humanitarianism. 
 This tendency is corrected by the dogma of human 
 equality, which had been formulated as a juridical 
 maxim in the Eoman Jus Gentium, but afterwards 
 passed into a political creed, and found vent in the 
 literature of the eighteenth century and in the 
 public events which marked its close. 
 
 The change which this notion of human equality 
 passed through has been traced by Sir Henry 
 Maine. " Where the Eoman jurisconsult had 
 written ' aequales sunt/ meaning exactly what he 
 said, the modern civilian wrote ' all men are 
 equal ' in the sense of ' all men ought to be equal.' 
 The peculiar Eoman idea that natural law co- 
 
THE TKANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 71 
 
 existed with civi 1 law and gradually absorbed it, 
 had evidently been lost sight of, or had become 
 unintelligible, and the words that had at most 
 conveyed a theory concerning the origin, composi- 
 tion, and development of human institutions, were 
 beginning to express the sense of a great standing 
 wrong suffered by mankind." l Now Bentham, influence of 
 however far he may have been from trusting to 
 the system of 'natural law,' 2 was certainly not 
 beyond the influence of the idea of human equality 
 which it carried in its train ; and, from his own 
 point of view, he laboured to defend it. In assimi- 
 lating this idea, utilitarianism has preserved one 
 of the best results of the old . " law of nature," 
 without the ambiguity with which it had formerly 
 been used, 3 if in a sense which admits of a some- 
 what narrow and abstract interpretation. 
 
 1 Ancient Law, 8th ed., p. 93. 
 
 2 Principles of Morals and Legislation, chap. ii. 14 n. 
 
 3 The ambiguity of the phrase is explained in an interesting 
 way in Sir H. Maine's account of the change from its juridical to 
 a political or ethical meaning. In some writers it seems to have 
 a third and still different signification. We must thus distinguish 
 (1) the juridical meaning, originating in the Roman " law common 
 to all nations," which had arisen through the " constant levelling 
 or removal of irregularities which went on wherever the praetorian 
 system was applied to the cases of foreign litigants," modified 
 subsequently by the Greek conception of iVdrojs. (2) The 
 political meaning, that all men ought to be equal, arose from 
 the preceding. But its notion of " ought " seems often to depend 
 on an idea of the constitution of nature according to which all 
 men are actually born equal not only in rights, soon to be 
 obscured by human convention, but also in power or faculty, 
 
72 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 It is true that this does not give exactly the 
 result which is usually described as utilitarianism. 
 I have spoken of the notion of equality as the 
 regulator of sympathy a canon in accordance with 
 which the sympathetic impulse is to be guided. 
 Sympathy impels us to relieve the pains and in- 
 crease the pleasures of our fellow-men. The prin- 
 ciple of equality dictates that this sympathetic 
 activity is to be directed to the happiness of all 
 men equally. Every one whom our conduct may 
 be made to affect is to count as a unit, and a unit 
 only. The distribution is not to be according to 
 kinship of blood or social ties, though it is so much 
 
 afterwards unequally developed by education. Hence (3) the 
 natural meaning. The doctrines of evolution and heredity have 
 made this view seem as strange to us now as it would have done 
 to the Komans from whom it was illegitimately derived. Yet at 
 one time it seems to have been assumed, almost without question, 
 that there is but little difference in the natural endowments of 
 different men. This assumption lay at the basis of Hobbes's 
 political theory Leviathan, I. xiii. p. 60, was stated in a more 
 guarded form by Locke On Education, 1 ; Works, ed. of 
 1824, i. 6, and adopted almost without qualification by Hel- 
 vetius, who, carrying out Locke's metaphor of the soul as, at 
 birth, a " tabula rasa," afterwards written over with the pen of 
 experience, says : " Quintilien, Locke, et moi, disons : L'ine'galite' 
 des esprits est 1'efifet d'une cause connue, et cette cause est la 
 difference de 1'education " the causes of the existing inequality 
 being afterwards stated as twofold : first, the difference of environ- 
 ment, which may be called chance ; and secondly, the difference 
 of strength in the desire for instruction. De 1'homme, II. i., III. 
 i., IV. xxii. ; (Euvres, ii. 71, 91, 280. (Quintilian's statement, 
 however, is even more guarded than Locke's. Cf. Opera, ed. 
 Spalding, i. 47.) 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 73 
 
 more in our power to promote the happiness of 
 those closely connected with us, that it may fairly 
 occupy a larger share of our thought and energy 
 than the happiness of other people does. Utili- 
 tarianism carries the application of the principle 
 of equality still farther, by looking upon self as a 
 unit whose happiness is to be regarded as of exactly 
 equal value with that of any one else. "With every 
 individual reduced to the same ethical worth, 
 happiness is declared to be the end of moral action, 
 and equality of distribution the rule for deciding 
 between the claims of competing individuals. 
 
 It seems to me, therefore, that utilitarianism is 6. The two 
 a theory compounded out of two quite different ele- utilitarian 
 ments. On the one side the basis of the theory has gMy 0t 
 been laid by Bentham and Mill in a naturalistic connected, 
 psychology which looks upon pleasure as the only 
 object of desire. To this there is superadded the 
 idea of equality, which is the distinctively ethical 
 element in the theory. But it is only by confusion 
 that the idea of equality which Bentham expresses 
 by the proposition that the happiness of one man 
 is to count for no more than the happiness of 
 another can be supposed to be derived from the 
 same theory of human nature as that which iden- 
 tifies pleasure and desire. Utilitarianism only 
 becomes a practicable end for individual conduct 
 when psychological hedonism has been given up. 
 It is futile to say that one ought to pursue the 
 
74 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 greatest happiness of the greatest number, unless 
 it is possible for the individual to act for some- 
 thing else than his own pleasure that is, for an 
 end which is for him not pleasure at all. In a 
 word, utilitarianism, while maintaining that the 
 only thing worth desiring is pleasure, must at the 
 same time admit that pleasure is not the only 
 object that can be or is desired : otherwise, it can 
 never advance from the egoistic to the universal- 
 istic form. 
 
 This view receives confirmation from the way in 
 which utilitarianism is held by the most eminent 
 of living moralists. In the 'Methods of Ethics/ 
 the tradition of Bentham is expressly united with 
 the doctrines of Butler and Clarke. Professor 
 Sidgwick agrees with Bentham, and the long line 
 of moralists from Epicurus downwards, in main- 
 taining the doctrine of ethical hedonism, that 
 pleasure is the only thing ultimately desirable ; 
 but, with Butler, he rejects the psychological 
 hedonism, according to which pleasure is the only 
 object of desire. So far from these two positions 
 being inconsistent, it is only through the second 
 that the first can be held in its universalistic form. 
 The problem is, however, how to unite them. In 
 Professor Sidgwick's theory, they are connected by 
 the application of the ethical maxims of benev- 
 olence and equity, which an exhaustive exami- 
 nation of ethical intuitions has left standing as 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 75 
 
 axioms of the practical reason. Though utilitari- 
 anism, therefore, is still adhered to, it is on an 
 expressly Eational ground, not on the basis of 
 Naturalism. 
 
 In this and the previous chapter, I have looked 7. summary 
 at human nature from the point of view of psycho- conseqwn- 
 logical hedonism, and have endeavoured to show 2hdS2i" 
 what ethical principles that theory leads to, or is hedonism : 
 consistent with. The theory does not deny that 
 there is a great diversity of capacities and interests 
 in man. But it holds that, so far as concerns 
 conduct, they admit of being brought under one 
 general law that every action is subject to the 
 rule of the " two sovereign masters, pleasure and 
 pain." It is evident, therefore, that if ethics is 
 to be connected at all with psychology if what 
 ought to be done is in any degree what can be 
 done the end of conduct must be hedonistic. 
 The psychological fact cannot indeed be without 
 more ado turned into a moral imperative. Yet 
 this much may be admitted, that if this interpre- 
 tation of action leaves room for ethics at all, the 
 end prescribed can be nothing else than pleasure, 
 or the avoidance of pain. 
 
 The question, therefore, was how to determine (a)noiogi- 
 the pleasure which is to be sought ? And I have tfon^tiT 
 tried to show, in the chapter just concluded, that ^ hta 
 utilitarianism does not admit of being logically 
 
76 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 arrived at from this point of view. It may indeed, 
 under certain circumstances, 1 be the guide of politi- 
 cal or social enactments; but these can only be 
 made to bear upon the conduct of individuals 
 by the sanctions which the State or Society has 
 at its command. The individual can have as his 
 maxim of conduct an end which corresponds with 
 utilitarianism in two events only: when he is 
 so constituted as to find his pleasure in the great- 
 est aggregate pleasure of mankind, or when the 
 political and social sanctions are so complete and 
 searching as to make his individual interest and 
 the collective interest coincide. The former event 
 is unfortunately too rare to be taken into account 
 in establishing a theory ; the latter would imply 
 an interference with individual liberty so impracti- 
 cable that it is not contemplated even in the most 
 comprehensive of socialistic schemes. 
 
 Hedonism in psychology, therefore, means egoism 
 in ethics. But even this theory, as the previous 
 chapter has shown, has its own difficulties to meet. 
 The antagonism of individual and universal has not 
 yet been got rid of. The difficulty is no longer 
 caused by the conflict between one man and his 
 neighbours : it is the difference between the feeling 
 
 1 That is, when (1) the legislature accurately expresses the 
 average feeling of all the members of the State ; or (2) the legis- 
 lators happen to be fully intelligent people in whom " selfishness " 
 has taken the shape of benevolence. 
 
THE TRANSITION TO UTILITARIANISM. 77 
 
 and action of a moment, and the sum of feelings and 
 actions which makes up a lifetime. It is true that, 
 if we admit that pleasure is the only thing worth 
 pursuing, and that by .." pleasure" a man means 
 " his own pleasure," there is so far no reason for 
 preferring the pleasure of one moment to that of 
 another, except as more certain or of greater 
 amount or degree ; l but this is to start with ascrib- 
 ing a value to pleasure, and not with the simple 
 fact that pleasure is desired. If psychological 
 hedonism is our starting-point and we give to the 
 theory the interpretation that has the greatest 
 verisimilitude it is the greatest present pleasure 
 that rules. And, although the man of reflection only under 
 will no doubt attempt to estimate the future pleas- cS 
 ure at its true value in comparison with the 
 pleasure actually present, this can never have full 
 effect upon his will. It has been shown, indeed, 
 that the realisation of egoistic hedonism is not 
 merely unattainable from the point of view of 
 psychological hedonism, but that it would involve 
 conditions inconsistent with the nature of desire. 
 
 1 Although, as is well known, propinquity was held by Ben- 
 tham to be an independent ground of distinction and preference. 
 Principles of Morals and Legislation, chap. iv. sect. 2. 
 
78 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 MORAL SENTIMENT. 
 
 i. A uni- PSYCHOLOGICAL hedonism possesses the merit of 
 such asps7- ff erm g a simple and uniform theory of mental 
 ac ti n It m ay admit conflicting accounts of the 
 kinds of action and sufferance which actually give 
 men pleasure and pain, a point on which, for 
 example, Hobbes and J. S. Mill differ widely. 
 But it has one general formula for the relation of 
 feeling to action, which has been precise and clear 
 enough to attract many psychologists. The ethical 
 consequences of the theory have, indeed, turned 
 out if the argument of the preceding chapters 
 is valid to be neither so obvious nor so satisfac- 
 tory as its adherents have commonly supposed. 
 But it must nevertheless be admitted that, if 
 psychology shows pleasure to be, as a matter of 
 fact, the constant end of action, it will be useless 
 even if it is not impossible for ethics to prescribe 
 any other end. 
 
MOKAL SENTIMENT. 79 
 
 The opponents of ethical hedonism have thus not supplied 
 uniformly insisted that the theory which makes pon^ts of 
 pleasure the end and motive of all conscious activity f hical he ~ 
 
 domsm, 
 
 is imperfect ; and this psychological question has 
 been the battle-field of many of the controversies, 
 at any rate, of English ethics. Psychological he- 
 donism has not, however, been confronted by the 
 English moralists with an opposed theory of equal 
 simplicity, nor can the controversy be said to 
 have led to a thorough analysis of action. The 
 psychological investigation has, in most cases, been 
 carried no farther than the ethical interests at 
 stake seemed to require ; and the predominance 
 of these interests has perhaps prevented the in- 
 quiry from being carried out with complete free- 
 dom from preconception on either side. 
 
 A uniform theory under which our various par- 
 ticular desires might be brought may, indeed, be 
 said to have been suggested by Butler. He meets 
 the hedonistic proposition that all desire is for 
 personal pleasure, by the doctrine that no particu- 
 lar desire has pleasure as its end, since all pleas- 
 ure presupposes a previous desire in the satisfac- 
 tion of which it consists. 1 This theory, which may 
 have been derived from Plato, 2 and was afterwards 
 
 1 " The very idea of an interested pursuit necessarily presup- 
 poses particular passions or appetites ; since the very idea of 
 interest or happiness consists in this, that an appetite or affection 
 enjoys its object." Sermons, Pref. ; cf. Serm. xi. 
 
 2 Phil., 31 ff. ; cf. Gorg., 495 f. ; Rep., ix. 585. 
 
80 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 used by Schopenhauer to prove the negative nature 
 of pleasure and consequent worthlessness of life, 
 is, however, a generalisation which cannot be made 
 to include the whole facts to be taken account of. 1 
 Many pleasures occur independently of any pre- 
 cedent desire. And what Butler had to show 
 and was really concerned to show was that desire 
 was not exclusively directed to objects thus inde- 
 pendently found to be pleasurable : the contra- 
 dictory, that is to say, and not the contrary, of 
 psychological hedonism. 
 
 in maintain- For this purpose Butler pointed to the whole 
 Sftyofnon- c ^ ass ^ affections which, although they may also 
 hedonistic en( j ^ p r i va t e interest, have an immediate refer- 
 
 activity. 
 
 ence to the good of others; and, in addition to 
 these, he contended for an original principle of 
 benevolence towards others in human nature, as 
 well as of self-love or care for one's own interests 
 and happiness. This latter, he held, so far from 
 being the sole principle of action, implied the exist- 
 ence of a number of particular passions and affec- 
 tions, directed immediately to external objects the 
 satisfaction of these desires giving pleasure, though 
 pleasure was not the end they aimed at. Volun- 
 tary action is thus not brought under any common 
 rubric ; for, at the same time that the calm prin- 
 ciple of self-love is directed to the agent's greatest 
 pleasure, the object of hunger, for example, is said 
 
 1 Cf. Sidgwick. Methods of Ethics, I. iv. 2, 3d ed., p. 44. 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 81 
 
 to be not pleasure but food, that of benevolence 
 not personal pleasure but the good of others. 
 
 The attempt to give unity to the non-hedonistic 
 view of desire has come from a different quarter. 
 Uninfluenced by the exigencies of ethical contro- by Herbart > 
 versy, which formed the entire motive of Butler's 
 investigation, Herbart and his school have worked 
 out a theory of desire, which has many points of 
 comparison with that of Butler. However much 
 they may differ from the English moralist of 
 whose existence they are mostly ignorant they 
 are at one with him in rejecting the maxim of 
 psychological hedonism, nihil appetimus nisi sub 
 specie loni ; and their differences from him are 
 largely due to their having gone further in their 
 analysis of the facts, and endeavoured to bring them 
 under a general principle. 
 
 Butler's view of the object of desire is distin- 
 guished from the Herbartian chiefly in two respects. 
 In the first place, he identifies that object with the 
 external or real thing, whereas Herbart is careful 
 to point out that it is a presentation or idea. In 
 the second place, while Butler is content to pos- 
 tulate an original tendency of our nature towards 
 certain objects, Herbart attempts to get behind this 
 tendency, and explain the phenomena of striving 
 from the interaction of presentations. Over and 
 above the ordinary hypothesis of natural realism, 
 Butler's theory implies a sort of pre-established 
 
 F 
 
82 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 harmony between our active tendencies and things 
 outside the mind, in virtue of which some of these 
 things do, and some do not, attract our desires, 
 from the Herbart, on the other hand, attempts nothing less 
 ideas to aeif- than a complete genetic account of mental phen- 
 ion. omena ^ explaining the facts of presentation, desire, 
 and feeling through " the persistence of presenta- 
 tion in consciousness and their rise into clearer 
 consciousness." 1 The phenomena of desire and 
 feeling are both accounted for by this mechanism 
 of impelling and inhibiting forces. 2 
 
 It would be beyond the scope of this Essay to 
 examine the above view of the active side of mental 
 phenomena. For present purposes it is enough to 
 draw attention to the fact that the common de- 
 duction of the phenomena of desire and will from 
 the feelings of pleasure and pain is not the only 
 " scientific " theory of human action, and that it 
 is rejected on its merits by writers who have no 
 hankering after what the psychological hedonist 
 would call the mystical element of free-will. It 
 is of interest to note, too, that Professor Bain, in 
 
 1 Herbart, Psychologic als Wissenschaft, 104, Werke, vi. 74 ; 
 cf. Waitz, Lehrbuch der Psychologie als Naturwissenschaft, 40, 
 p. 418 : " It is not difficult to recognise the basis of desire in the 
 presentations brought forward by reproduction, and, at the same 
 time, held back by an inhibition." 
 
 2 With Herbart's doctrine may be compared Mr H. Spencer's 
 view of the genesis of feeling and voluntary action, Principles of 
 Psychology, 2d ed., part iv. chaps, viii. and ix. 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 83 
 
 whose works the traditions of psychological hedon- 
 ism find their most careful expression, has modified 
 the doctrine so as to allow of desire of pleasure and 
 avoidance of pain explaining less than had been 
 formerly required of them. Outside the circle of This ten 
 hedonistically -determined motives, he recognises the 
 influence of the presentation or idea as a self-realis- 
 ing element in the individual consciousness, apart 
 from its pleasurable or painful characteristics. 1 
 Those "fixed ideas,' 7 as Mr Bain calls them, 
 tend both to persist in the mind, and to project 
 themselves into action, independently of pleasure 
 and pain or at least with a force which is out of 
 proportion to the pleasure they bring. As has been 
 already seen, it is by means of this doctrine that he 
 explains " the great fact of our nature denominated 
 sympathy, fellow-feeling, pity, compassion, disinter- 
 estedness." 2 To the same category belongs " much 
 of the ambition and the aspirations of human 
 beings. ... A certain notion say of power, 
 wealth, grandeur has fixed itself in our mind and 
 keeps a persistent hold there." It is asserted, in- 
 deed, that the action of such fixed ideas " perverts 
 the regular operation of the will which would lead 
 us to renounce whatever is hopeless or not worth 
 the cost." And, certainly, their admission among 
 
 1 Cf. note to James Mill's Analysis, ii. 383 f. 
 
 2 The Senses and the Intellect, 3d ed., p. 344 ; cf. Mental and 
 Moral Science, pp. 90, 91 . 
 
84 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 mental phenomena seems to imply the superposition 
 of a new theory of action upon the old theory of psy- 
 chological hedonism. There is no disguising the im- 
 portance of the modification thus introduced. The 
 name " fixed idea " is misleading if it be taken to 
 imply that persistency and tendency to action are 
 properties belonging to a certain class of ideas only. 
 Mr Bain's doctrine is founded on the hypothesis of 
 the identity of the nervous centres which function 
 in representation and in sensation, and is therefore 
 valid of all representations or ideas. The char- 
 acteristics of persistency, and of tendency to action, 
 are therefore normal characteristics of presentations, 
 though they may belong in an unusual degree to 
 some ideas from the relation these hold to the 
 dominant cluster of ideas in the individual con- 
 sciousness. And if we thus attribute to all ideas 
 without exception the tendency to self-realisation, 
 and recognise as we must the relation of mutual 
 assistance or inhibition which ideas bear to one 
 another in virtue of their being " presented " to the 
 same subject, we have granted the material out of 
 which, in Herbart's skilful " Mechanik des Geistes," 
 the phenomena of feeling and desire are woven. 
 
 2. The non- The view of individual human nature, which 
 
 thto iS of C nolds tnat a11 its desires are not directed to per- 
 
 action. sonal pleasure, thus claims consideration. With 
 
 its less restricted theory of action, this doctrine 
 
MOEAL SENTIMENT. 85 
 
 may seem to offer a larger means of determining 
 the appropriate end of human conduct. In par- 
 ticular, the suggestion naturally occurs that the 
 ethical end will, on this theory, be something else 
 than pleasure. 1 But there is, nevertheless, no con- 
 tradiction in holding as Mr Sidgwick does that 
 although other objects than pleasure are actually 
 desired, there is nothing else which can be held to 
 be ultimately desirable, or the tendency to which 
 can be said to have moral worth. 
 
 The ethical barrenness of psychological hedonism Difficulty of 
 has been seen to result from its narrow and inflex- vSk^ g im he 
 ible view of human nature. But theories such as ? uls , QS {i 
 
 implies, 
 
 those now to be considered have, in an ethical 
 regard, to overcome a difficulty of another kind in 
 the variety of impulses which they admit upon the 
 stage. The " objects " to which these impulses or 
 desires relate have as yet received no further charac- 
 terisation than that they are objects of desire. And 
 the difficulty of finding a principle by which some 
 order of precedence or value amongst them may be 
 determined is just, in other words, the difficulty of 
 obtaining a moral standard. 
 
 The question does not ordinarily arise in the 
 
 1 " If there be any principles or affections in the mind of man 
 distinct from self-love, that the things those principles tend 
 towards, or the objects of those affections are, each of them in 
 themselves eligible to be pursued upon its own account, and to be 
 rested in as an end, is implied in the very idea of such principle 
 or affection." Butler, Sermons, Pref. 
 
86 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 above form, because the moral standard is com- 
 monly taken for granted, and the various impulses, 
 affections, and dispositions are made to derive their 
 ethical rank from their relation to that standard. 
 But this method is obviously inappropriate when 
 the standard is still to be ascertained, its determina- 
 tion being the object of inquiry. And it may seem 
 that the constitution of man contains in itself a 
 means of distinguishing the moral value of its vari- 
 ous elements, or of the actions to which they lead, 
 so as to de- and thus furnishing a moral standard or end for 
 standard* conduct. This purpose seems to have been to some 
 for action. ex fc en ^ though not quite clearly, kept in view by 
 the writers who, in last century, contended against 
 the selfish theory which had been so crudely enun- 
 ciated by Hobbes. They attempted to show that 
 selfishness was not the only, nor even the most 
 prominent, principle of action ; and, from the 
 system of diverse principles which they found 
 implanted in human nature, they endeavoured to 
 work out a theory of conduct. 
 
 This at- Especially amongst the later English moralists 
 
 the English Adam Smith, for instance the question of the 
 
 moralists, en( j Qr s t an( j ar (i came almost to drop out of sight 
 
 in the midst of the controversy regarding the 
 
 nature of the " moral sense " or " moral faculty " 
 
 the way, that is, in which we become aware of 
 
 the difference between right and wrong. But in 
 
 Shaftesbury, Butler, and Hutcheson the writers 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 87 
 
 who formulated this doctrine of the moral sense 
 the attempt is made to connect a theory of the 
 criterion of morality with the source of our know- 
 ledge of it. Shaftesbury and Hutcheson both but along 
 looked upon social welfare or the general happiness tartan cri- 
 as the end of moral conduct, and the criterion in t lon> 
 accordance with which moral character is ascribed 
 to actions ; at the same time that their main con- 
 tention was for the immediateness of the " sense " 
 by which we perceive these moral qualities. And 
 they sought to establish the connection of the two 
 doctrines by means of the benevolent feelings 
 which they held to be original and independent of 
 private interest and their immediate approval by 
 the reflex or moral sense of the individual man. 
 Similar ideas appear in Butler, at the same time 
 that he tended to make conscience or the moral 
 sense the standard of morality, as well as the 
 source of our knowledge of it. They, as well as 
 he, however, found it necessary to come back from 
 the social or political to the individual point of 
 view. Even if their conception of " the good " was 
 not evolved from the nature of the individual man, 
 their philosophical standpoint required them to 
 leave broader ground, and show it to be the in- 
 dividual's natural goal. And in doing this, their and with 
 constant tendency is to revert to egoistic argu- 
 ments demonstrating the complete harmony of 
 virtue and interest, or attempting to prove to the 
 
88 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 individual that his own happiness consists in the 
 exercise of the social affections. Thus Shaftesbury 
 tries to show, by an empirical collection of results, 
 that to have the " natural " (or social) affections too 
 weak, or the private affections too strong, is a source 
 of misery, 1 as well as the chief source of vice ; and 
 that, largely owing to the pleasure of virtuous 
 action, it is " to the private interest and good of 
 every one to work to the general good." 2 Hutche- 
 son, again, devotes a large portion of his most 
 mature work to allay the suspicion " that in follow- 
 ing the impulse of our kind affections and the 
 moral faculty we are counteracting our interests, 
 and abandoning what may be of more consequence 
 to our happiness than either this self -approbation 
 or the applauses of others ; " 3 while Butler, re- 
 ferring to virtuous conduct, says, in a well-known 
 passage, that " when we sit down in a cool hour we 
 can neither justify to ourselves this or any other 
 pursuit, till we are convinced that it will be for our 
 happiness, or at least not contrary to it." 4 Opposed 
 as the whole school were to the selfish theory of 
 human action, they never spoke of any sacrifice 
 of private happiness as a thing to be looked for, or 
 in any way taken into account, in conduct which is 
 the result of calm deliberation. It is difficult, there- 
 
 1 Inquiry concerning Virtue, II. i. 3. 
 
 2 Ibid., II. ii., conclusion. 
 
 3 System of Moral Philosophy, i. 99. 4 Sermons, xi. 
 
UN] 
 
 MOKAL SENTIMENT. 
 
 fore, to avoid the judgment passed upon them by 
 Schleiermacher, that " the English school of Shaftes- 
 bury, with all their talk about virtue, are really 
 given up to pleasure." l 
 
 At the same time, their writings constantly sug- 3. Ethics 
 gest a theory of morals which is neither obliged to 
 adopt off-hand a utilitarian criterion of virtue, nor 
 forced to fall back upon the egoistic sanctions of 
 personal pleasure and pain. Their psychological 
 theory points to an ethical doctrine in which 
 pleasure is neither the sole end of action, nor its 
 sole motive. They do not, indeed, make quite clear 
 the transition from the psychological to the ethical 
 point of view ; and critics are still fond of confront- 
 ing Butler with the objection he anticipated Why 
 ought I to obey my conscience ? The apparent 
 petitio principii of Butler's answer, Because it is 
 the law of your nature, is due to the way in which 
 the teleological standpoint is introduced. The pur- 
 pose of which (according to Butler) man is the 
 vehicle or realising organism is spoken of as a law 
 externally imposed, and deriving its authority, not 
 from its own nature, but from the nature of its 
 origin. 
 
 There would seem to be one way only to sur- 
 mount the difficulty arising from the variety of 
 impulses of which the nature of man is made up, 
 and that is by consistently following out the teleo- 
 
 1 Kritik der bisherigen Sittenlehre (1803), p. 54. 
 
90 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 logical point of view. But what, the question is, 
 
 is the final or comprehensive end to which human 
 
 nature points amidst this diversity of objects of 
 
 striving ? The doctrine of the " moral sense " 
 
 Different attempts to answer the question. Now this moral 
 
 n^ e of tbe sense may either be regarded as not itself a separate 
 
 the moral f acu lty, but simply an expression for the harmony 
 
 of human tendencies ; or it may be looked upon as 
 
 a separate and superior capacity, which, again, may 
 
 either be interpreted in terms of sense, or of the 
 
 understanding the former interpretation leading 
 
 to its identification with pleasure, the latter to its 
 
 being conceived as law. 
 
 (a) The bar- These different methods were attempted by the 
 i^puisfs. English moralists the first, however, to a less 
 shaftes- extent than the others. But it inspired much of 
 
 bury s 
 
 theory. Shaftesbury's work, though it cannot be said to 
 have been consistently developed by him. The 
 conflict of impulses in man was too obvious a fact 
 not to be apparent even in Shaftesbury's roseate 
 view of life. He recognised, indeed, not only 
 private or self-affections, promoting the good of 
 the individual, and " natural " or social affections, 
 which led to the public good, but also " unnatural 
 affections," which tended to no good whatever. 1 
 The reference to consequences is thus made pro- 
 minent at once. The last class of affections is 
 
 1 Inquiry, II. i. 3. 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 91 
 
 condemned outright because of its infelicific re- 
 sults; while an attempt is made to prove from 
 experience that the courses of conduct to which 
 the two former lead coincide. Shaftesbury con- 
 tended for a real organic union between the indi- 
 vidual and society ; but, when he came to establish 
 its nature, he made it consist in an asserted har- 
 mony of interests, while the obligation to virtue 
 was allowed to rest on its conduciveness to personal 
 pleasure. He sometimes spoke of virtue as identical 
 with the harmonious development of the affections of 
 the individual man ; * but he expressly defined it as 
 consisting in the individual " having all his inclina- 
 tions and affections . . . agreeing with the good of 
 his kind or of that system in which he is included, 
 and of which he constitutes a part." 2 And the 
 two views can only be connected by proving that 
 the harmonious development of an individual's 
 affections will lead to the good of the species : the 
 proof of this depending on a one-sided summation 
 of consequences. Shaftesbury does, indeed, throw 
 out the idea that both the self -affections and the 
 " natural " or social affections become self-destruc- 
 tive when carried out so as to interfere with one 
 another. But this, again, has only the previous 
 calculus of the results of conduct to support it. He 
 cannot show that the contradiction in the conception 
 of a completely solitary being belongs also to the con- 
 
 1 Inquiry, II. i. 3 ; II. ii. 2. 2 Ibid., II. i. 1. 
 
92 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 ception of a judiciously selfish being. The latter 
 being loses the pleasures of virtuous action; but 
 perhaps he may gain greater pleasures in their room. 
 He does not develop his whole nature ; but if that na- 
 ture contains totally infelicific passions, the develop- 
 ment of the whole nature is not to be recommended. 
 Thus Shaftesbury is unable to reach a conception 
 of man's nature as a harmony of impulses just on 
 account of the external point of view which makes 
 him treat it as an aggregate, though he contends 
 that it is an organism. His ingenious and subtle 
 account of the relations between the individual 
 and society does not really go to the root of the 
 matter, because, after all, it remains a calculus of 
 the results of action, not an analysis of its nature. 
 And his view of the affections constituting the 
 individual system leaves them wanting in the 
 unity of organic connection. An effort is made, 
 however, to supply this defect by means of the 
 reflex affections called the " moral sense/' to which 
 he ascribes an oversight over the other affections 
 and their resultant actions. In what way, then, 
 must we regard the nature of this faculty and the 
 important functions assigned to it ? 
 
 It was left to Shaftesbury's disciple, Francis 
 Hutcheson, to elaborate with thoroughness this 
 conception of the moral sense as a separate faculty. 
 Hutcheson did not make any important addition 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 93 
 
 to the ideas of Shaftesbury and Butler. But he 
 worked them out more systematically ; and in his 
 last work, the ' System of Moral Philosophy/ the 
 protest against the egoism of Hobbes has found 
 expression in a complete theory of human nature, 
 in which the " moral sense " is supreme, and the 
 ends of conduct independent of self - interest. 
 Hutcheson, too, keeps more closely than either 
 of his immediate predecessors to the way of look- 
 ing at human nature which is spoken of in this 
 volume as " naturalistic." He rejects even more 
 decidedly than Shaftesbury much more so than 
 Butler any creative function of reason in deter- 
 mining the constitution and direction of the moral 
 sense. 1 The questions thus arise (a) What is the TWO ques- 
 moral sense when not regarded as a rational deter- ingTt?^ 
 mination of the ends of conduct ? and (&) To what 
 determination of ends or other distinction between 
 right and wrong in action does it lead ? On both 
 these points there is a difference between his early 
 ' Inquiry into the Original of our Ideas of Beauty 
 and Virtue ' (1725), and the more mature ' System/ 
 published in 1755, eight years after his death. 
 
 " What is Reason but that sagacity we have in prosecuting 
 any end ? The ultimate end proposed by the common moralists 
 is the happiness of the agent himself, and this certainly he is 
 determined to pursue from instinct. Now may not another 
 instinct towards the public, or the good of others, be as proper 
 a principle of virtue as the instinct toward private happiness ? " 
 Hutcheson, Inquiry, p. 115. 
 
94 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 () Nature of Hutcheson is in earnest with the rejection of 
 
 this faculty: 
 
 not reason; reason as a creative force. I he moral sense is not, 
 he says, a source of new ideas. Its objects are 
 received in the ordinary ways by which, through 
 "sensation and reflection," we come by our know- 
 ledge. 1 But just as we have a sense of beauty in 
 the forms of sensible objects, so there is a moral 
 sense given us from which, in the contemplation of 
 our actions, we derive " still nobler pleasures " than 
 at first de- those of physical sensation. This moral sense is 
 ing of lima- " a determination of our minds to receive amiable 
 or pam, OY disagreeable ideas of actions." 2 So far, there- 
 fore, it seems to be simply a pleasure in the con- 
 templation of certain actions which, we say, have 
 " an immediate goodness." " By a superior sense," 
 says Hutcheson, " which I call a moral one, we 
 perceive pleasure in the contemplation of such 
 actions in others, and are determined to love the 
 agent (and much more do we perceive pleasure in 
 being conscious of having done such actions our- 
 selves) without any view of further natural advan- 
 tage from them." 3 The significance of this posi- 
 tion' is easily seen. It is not only meant to give a 
 criterion of moral action ; it is also a short cut to 
 the conclusion that virtue is for our private in- 
 terest. The disquieting suspicion that morality 
 may involve a sacrifice of individual happiness 
 
 1 Cf. System, i. 97 ; Inquiry, p. 124. 2 Inquiry, p. 124. 
 
 3 Ibid., p. 106. 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 95 
 
 " must be entirely removed, if we have a moral 
 sense and public affections, whose gratifications are 
 constituted bvnature our most intense and durable 
 pleasures." 1 {JTEe elaborate analysis of conduct and 
 enumeration of the pleasures which various affec- 
 tions and actions bring in their train, which 
 Hutcheson gave in his latest work, were thus 
 unnecessary as long as the position was maintained 
 that the moral sense is emphatically a pleasure or 
 pain, and that the pleasures it gives are the most 
 intense and durable we have. 
 
 There was only an apparent contradiction in this 
 theory which placed the test of morality in a pleas- 
 ure consequent upon moral action, and yet held 
 that such actions were not performed from inter- 
 ested motives. In the spirit of Butler's psychology, 
 Hutcheson contends 2 that virtue is pleasant only 
 because we have a natural and immediate tendency 
 towards virtuous action ; our true motive is " some 
 determination of our nature to study the good of 
 others ; " and this, although not always immediately 
 pleasant in itself, is yet succeeded by the calm 
 satisfaction of the moral sense. The real weakness 
 of Hutcheson's position is the fatal one that he 
 cannot show that it corresponds with facts; that 
 the pleasures incidental to the moral sense out- 
 
 1 Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affec- 
 tions, with Illustrations on the Moral Sense (1728), p. xix. 
 
 2 Cf. Inquiry, p. 140 ff. 
 
96 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 weigh all others. Indeed, he defends his opinion 
 in their favour only, in a way which reminds one 
 of Mill's method in the ' Utilitarianism/ by making 
 every juror stand aside unless he has pledged him- 
 self to morality. 1 It is open to any one, however, 
 to hold that the pleasures of benevolent action and 
 the " relish " of the moral sense are not of sufficient 
 hedonistic value to make up for the restraints they 
 put upon conduct and the enjoyments they oblige 
 one to forego. Even if this position be not correct, 
 it is merely a mistake in estimating doubtful quan- 
 tities. The man who chooses the smaller pleasure 
 will be the loser by his mistake ; but we cannot 
 say that the selfish man is to blame for not being 
 benevolent, because the pleasures of benevolence 
 and the moral sense are greatest, any more than 
 we could blame the benevolent man for not being 
 selfish, if selfishness should turn out on the whole 
 to leave a greater hedonistic balance at the indi- 
 vidual's credit. 
 
 afterwards A more objective determination of the nioral 
 , 8 sense is afterwards given by Hutcheson. Without 
 professedly changing ground, he ceases to speak of 
 it as a mere feeling of pleasure, and calls it a judg- 
 ment of approbation or disapprobation. " It is," he 
 he says, 2 " a natural and immediate determination 
 
 1 Introduction to Moral Philosophy, translated from the Latin, 
 2d ed., 1753, p. 43 ; cf. Essay on the Passions and Affections, 
 &c., p. 128. 2 System,!. 58. 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 97 
 
 to approve certain affections and actions consequent 
 upon them ; or a natural sense of immediate excel- 
 lence in them, not referred to any other quality 
 perceivable by our other senses or by reasoning." 
 Nor is this judgment of approbation consequent 
 upon the feeling of pleasure the affection or action 
 produces in us. The action is not "judged good 
 because it gains to the agent the pleasure of self- 
 approbation, but it gains to him this pleasure be- 
 cause it was antecedently good, or had that quality 
 which, by the constitution of this sense, we must 
 approve." l But, in attempting to make clear the but this 
 nature of this judgment, Hutcheson seems to re- In ^dt 
 turn, though not in so many words, to his earlier f^^* 10 
 position. To seek a basis for the judgment in reason 
 would have been to make the " moral sense " what 
 Kant afterwards made it, simply practical reason. 
 This, however, would have been a "metaphysic 
 of ethics" inconsistent with Hutcheson's whole 
 position. He had always opposed the narrowly 
 intellectual view of morality in Clarke and Wollas- 
 ton, and he had no conception of the function of 
 reason which would admit of an interpretation of 
 the judgment of approbation by an appeal to a 
 rational determination, depending upon an idea 
 conceived as inherent in the human constitution, 
 and to be realised in action. The judgment, there- 
 fore, is referred to a " taste or relish " 2 for certain 
 
 1 System, i. 53. 2 Ibid., i. 59. 
 
98 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 affections and actions, and this he takes no pains 
 to distinguish from pleasure. 
 
 The analogy he seeks to draw between the moral 
 sense and our other powers does not really favour 
 a distinction of it from pleasure. " To each of our 
 powers," he says, " we seem to have a corresponding 
 taste or sense, recommending the proper use of it 
 to the agent, and making him relish or value the 
 like exercise of it by another. This we see as to 
 the powers of voice, of imitation, designing, or 
 machinery, motion, reasoning ; there is a sense 
 discerning or recommending the proper exercise 
 of them." 1 That is to say, besides the sense of 
 hearing, which has to do with sounds, there must 
 needs be another sense which has to do with our 
 way of hearing sounds ; besides the sense of sight, 
 which has to do with form and colour, there must 
 needs be another sense which has to do with our 
 way of perceiving form and colour ; and so with 
 every other activity, especially those which proceed 
 from our " highest powers." A doctrine such as this 
 sets no limits to the manufacture of additional senses. 
 The whole view of human nature upon which it pro- 
 ceeds is one of meaningless complexity, which serves 
 the one good purpose only of showing how -much 
 ethics has suffered from a defective psychology. 
 
 The mental objects or presentations which are 
 distinguished from one another by the difference 
 
 1 System, i. 59. 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 99 
 
 of their characteristic qualities, and which we 
 therefore call colours, or sounds, or movements, 
 are accompanied by varying degrees of pleasurable 
 or painful feeling ; and it is possible to hold that 
 the moral sense is a name for such feelings following 
 in the train of those complexes of presentations 
 to which we give the name of actions, or of those 
 other recurring complexes we call affections. This, 
 practically, was the position with which Hutcheson 
 started in the c Inquiry/ Benevolence pleased us 
 and selfishness pained us; just as the taste of 
 sugar was pleasant, and that of wormwood dis- 
 agreeable. Perhaps Hutcheson departed from this 
 theory, because he saw that if conduct was made a 
 matter of taste, there would be no sufficient reason 
 for condemning selfishness any more than an un- 
 usual taste. He therefore relinquished, or seems to 
 have relinquished, the view of the moral sense as a 
 feeling of pleasure or pain ; and under the influence, 
 no doubt, of Butler, spoke of it as a judgment of 
 approbation or disapprobation. But he fell back on 
 his original theory by making this judgment depend 
 on " a taste or relish," which only lends itself to 
 interpretation as a peculiar feeling of pleasure. 
 
 The reflex nature of the moral sense is brought ($ The ot>- 
 out more distinctly in the 'System' than in the 
 ' Inquiry/ In his earlier work, Hutcheson had I 
 spoken of it as directly related to actions. But 
 it was more consistent with his maturer thought 
 
100 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 afterwards to regard it as having to do with mental powers 
 tions ; or " affections " in the first instance, and with 
 actions only indirectly or mediately. " The object 
 of this sense," he says, 1 " is not any external motion 
 or action, but the inward affections or dispositions ; " 
 and this is made by him to account for the dis- 
 crepancy which the deliverances of the moral sense 
 show in regard to actions. It " seems ever to 
 approve and condemn uniformly the same imme- 
 diate objects, the same affections and dispositions ; 
 though we reason very differently about the actions 
 which evidence certain dispositions or their con- 
 traries." This distinction is applied with unlimited 
 confidence in its efficacy. By means of it he would 
 explain the most fundamental differences in the 
 moral code of men and nations. Thus people un- 
 acquainted with the industrial improvements which 
 give the character of permanence to property, may 
 " see no harm in depriving men of their artificial 
 acquisitions and stores beyond their present use," 
 that is to say, " no evil may appear in theft." 2 
 
 But it is more important in another respect ; for 
 it enables the author to avoid the difficulty of 
 finding any principle according to which the moral 
 sense may be related to the empirical content of 
 action. As long as the moral sense was simply 
 spoken of as a feeling of pleasure, it could be 
 conveniently regarded as the consequent of ex- 
 
 1 System, i. 97. 2 System, i. 93. 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 101 
 
 ternal actions. But if it is an internal sense 
 distinct from pleasure, it is easier to relate it to 
 what he calls our internal powers or affections 
 than to action. The moral sense, then, is to be 
 the regulator of all our powers ; and by means of 
 it Hutcheson attempts to reduce human nature to 
 a scale of morality. 
 
 It is to be noted that, in the classification he but its 
 offers, 1 what are commonly called the virtues of preference 
 candour, veracity, &c., are not accounted virtues 
 at all, but only immediately connected with virtuous 
 affections : these are identified with the " kind " or 
 benevolent affections, directed to the happiness of 
 sentient beings. Within the latter there are two 
 grounds of preference : the deliberate affections are 
 preferred to the passionate ; those which are more 
 extensive in the range of their objects to the less 
 extensive. With regard to the former ground of 
 preference, the " moral sense " of the community has 
 perhaps undergone some modification since Hut- 
 cheson's time, and looks upon enthusiasm with less 
 suspicion than it formerly did. The other ground 
 of preference ascribed to the moral sense refers not 
 so much to the affection itself which is the direct 
 or immediate object of the moral sense as to the 
 way in which the affection is applied, the number mainly de- 
 of the objects to which it is directed. The affec- p< 
 
 1 System, i. 68 ff. With this may be compared the elaborate 
 classification of motives, according to their moral quality, in Dr 
 Martineau's ' Types of Ethical Theory,' ii. 176 ff. 
 
102 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEOKY. 
 
 the nature tion of benevolence is the same in nature whether 
 
 of the affec- . . 
 
 tion, but on its object be wide or restricted; though difference 
 objects. .^ ^ig respect profoundly influences the actions to 
 which it leads. The object approved or most ap- 
 proved by the moral sense is therefore, according 
 to Hutcheson, utilitarian conduct, or rather, as he 
 would say, the calm disposition leading thereto. 1 In 
 this way he obtains a principle for determining the 
 morality of actions ; but only through the arbitrary 
 assertion that this principle is immediately ap- 
 proved by the moral sense/ The connection of the 
 moral sense with an object such as universal bene- 
 volence could only be made out by showing a 
 rational, or at any rate an organic union between 
 individual sentiment and social wellbeing ; and 
 Hutcheson, like Shaftesbury, has no conception of 
 attempting this in any other way than the tradi- 
 tional one of exhibiting the personal advantages of 
 benevolent conduct, and the disadvantages that 
 accompany selfishness. 
 
 (c) Third Both Shaftesbury and Hutcheson were often led 
 moral sense, astray by a tendency to interpret facts as they 
 
 wished them to be, rather than as they were. 
 
 Their view of the consequences of action was 
 Butler. coloured by their optimism. Butler, too, in spite 
 
 of the difference in his general attitude to the 
 
 value of human life, was not altogether free from 
 
 1 System, i. 50. 
 
MORAL SENTIMENT. 103 
 
 a similar error. He thinks that Shaftesbury " has 
 shown beyond all contradiction that virtue is natur- 
 ally the interest or happiness, and vice the misery 
 of such a creature as man." l But, in view of par- 
 ticular exceptions, or of any one not being con- 
 vinced of "this happy tendency of virtue," he 
 thinks it necessary to emphasise the "natural conscience 
 authority of the principle of reflection." Con- tatireUw," 
 science is, he holds, a part of our inward nature ; 
 but it differs from the other parts of our nature 
 inasmuch as it is not related immediately to an 
 external object, but to the actions dealing with 
 such objects, and to the dispositions leading to 
 those actions. It is a principle of "reflex appro- 
 bation or disapprobation," which is said to have 
 equal respect to both public and private good. 
 This tendency, however, would seem to be ascer- 
 tained empirically. The deliverances of conscience 
 are immediate judgments as to the morality of 
 actions and affections (for Butler speaks of it as 
 referring to both equally) ; and its reference to 
 the ends which those actions or the exercise of 
 these affections may ultimately tend to would, 
 therefore, seem to be indirect. 2 Butler was care- 
 ful, moreover, not to speak of it as an aesthetic 
 
 1 Sermons, Pref. 
 
 2 Although it is not "at all doubtful in the general, what 
 course of action this faculty or practical discerning power within 
 us, approves. ... It is ... justice, veracity, and regard to the 
 common good." Dissertation on Virtue. 
 
104 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 or sensitive faculty, but as a judgment. It is not 
 a feeling of pleasure, but the revelation of law. 
 and the The approval of conscience is thus made the 
 
 of'moraiity. criterion of morality. But a difficulty arises as 
 to the way in which we are to regard the author- 
 ity which conscience is said to carry along with 
 it. Butler's utterances here commonly imply a 
 teleological reference to an end implanted in human 
 nature, and to be discovered by observing that 
 nature the realisation of the end being obliga- 
 tory, because it is shown to be the purpose which 
 the author of nature had in view in making man 
 as he is. 1 The authority of conscience thus seems 
 to be derived from the divine purpose which it 
 displays. It carries within itself a claim to obedi- 
 ence ; but the justification of this claim depends 
 on a theological basis. And hence the question 
 of the nature and origin of conscience is at once 
 raised, in order to determine the legitimacy of its 
 claim to be, rather than any other part of our 
 constitution, a divinely-implanted guide. 
 Teieoiogicai But more than one current of thought runs 
 rtewsnot through Butler's ethical treatise. The theological 
 Tfimy d ' reference is sometimes so used as to make the 
 developed, obligation to morality, and even the nature of 
 morality, depend on the will of God : though 
 hardly according to Paley's crude method of seek- 
 ing in the external revelation of the divine com- 
 
 1 Sermons, ii. iii. 
 
MOKAL SENTIMENT. 105 
 
 mand a means of uniting the divergent interests 
 of the individual and of society. In general, 
 Butler's ruling idea is the idea of the system or 
 unity of human nature, for which he was largely 
 indebted to Shaftesbury's revival of the Platonic 
 conception. Conscience is regarded by him as the 
 expression of this unity. But its nature is never 
 more deeply probed. Its deliverances are justified 
 now by its supernatural mission, and now by the 
 more prosaic fact that it leads to our individual 
 interest 1 at any rate, " if we take in the future " 
 while it could not be recommended as a guide 
 if it did not. 2 On one side, therefore, Butler tends 
 to a form of theological utilitarianism, such as was 
 common in his own day, and was afterwards formu- 
 lated by Paley. 3 On the other hand, his ethics 
 more naturally allies itself with a different theory, 
 in which the moral law is conceived as having its 
 source in practical reason, and the naturalistic basis 
 of ethics is definitely abandoned. 
 
 On the whole, it would appear that the psycho- 4. The ethics 
 logical ethics worked out by Shaftesbury and his timenta 86 
 school occupies an insecure position between the ^^^ 
 view discussed in the two preceding chapters and 
 that which ascribes to reason a function in the 
 formation of objects of desire. Shaftesbury and 
 his followers tried to strike out a middle course 
 
 1 Sermons, iii. v. 2 Ibid., xi. 
 
 3 Cf. Jodl, Geschichte der Ethik, i. 192. 
 
106 THE INDIVIDUALISTIC THEORY. 
 
 between the theory that ends of action may be 
 determined by reason, and that which looks upon 
 all desires as being desires for objects as pleasur- 
 able. They made the attempt to found a system 
 of ethics on human nature, and they held that 
 that nature could not be accounted for by the 
 simple psychological analysis of the Epicurean 
 school as then represented by Hobbes. On the 
 other hand, they did not see their way to adopt 
 the " rational " ethics only known to them in the 
 abstract form it had received at the hands of 
 Clarke and Wollaston. But their own theory of 
 human nature requires a principle of harmony and 
 co-ordination among the various impulses which 
 they were unable to give a satisfactory account 
 explanation of. It may seem, however, that the idea of the 
 attempted development of man with which we are now 
 evomuon f f am ili ar > ma 7 enable us to overcome the diffi- 
 culties which formerly appeared insurmountable 
 showing the unity of human nature, and the ten- 
 dency of its activity. The general course of evolu- 
 tion, to which all life has been subject, is thought 
 to have brought about a harmony between indi- 
 vidual and social feelings, as well as between 
 individual and social interests, and thus to have 
 removed the obstacles in the way of founding 
 morality on the basis of Naturalism. It is, there- 
 fore, of importance to examine with care the ethical 
 bearings of the theory of evolution. 
 
107 
 
 PAKT II. 
 THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 CHAPTEE Y. 
 
 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION AND THE DEVELOPMENT 
 OF MORALITY. 
 
 To relinquish the individualistic theory of ethics i- General 
 
 . characteris- 
 
 does not necessarily imply a recourse to evolution, tics of the 
 It may still be possible to rest the foundation of evoiut 
 ethics on the state, without that view of the 
 growth of the community and of its connection 
 with the individual which the theory of evolution 
 involves. This, as has already been pointed out, 
 was, in part, what Bentham did ; while an attempt 
 in some respects more elaborate still to deduce 
 morality from society was made by Hobbes. The 
 theory of Bentham, and of his successor Professor 
 Bain, is indeed partly individualistic, partly social. 1 
 
 1 The social basis of ethics is emphasised by Professor Bain 
 
108 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 Iii the former reference, ethics becomes a theory of 
 prudence ; in the latter, a part of legislation. With 
 Hobbes, on the other hand, the identification of 
 individual and social interests is supposed to be 
 brought about by the absolute necessity, in order 
 to personal security, of a supreme political power, 
 into the hands of which all men have agreed to 
 transfer their rights to all things. But both 
 Hobbes and Professor Bain might have avoided 
 obvious difficulties had they had the theory of 
 evolution to assist them, and had they thought 
 themselves justified in making use of it. 1 For 
 want of it the former has to explain morality and 
 its binding force by means of the fiction of an 
 " original contract " ; while the latter has to ac- 
 count by the associations of a few years for the 
 harmony of feeling between the individual and the 
 whole, and for the good of the community coming 
 to be so faithfully reflected in the consciences of its 
 
 in his Practical Essays (1884), p. 155 : " ' How is society to be 
 held together ? ' is the first consideration ; and the sociologist 
 as constitution-builder, administrator, judge is the person to 
 grapple with the problem. It is with him that law, obligation, 
 right, command, obedience, sanction, have their origin and their 
 explanation. Ethics is an important supplement to social or 
 political law. But it is still a department of law. In any other 
 view it is a maze, a mystery, a hopeless embroilment." 
 
 1 Without denying that it is possible to apply the theory of 
 evolution to mind, Professor Bain holds that, as a fact, moral 
 sentiment has not become organic and hereditary " that there 
 are no moral instincts properly so called." The Emotions and 
 the Will, 3d ed., p. 56. 
 
THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 109 
 
 members. The theory of evolution, by its doctrine 
 of the hereditary transmission of acquired modifi- 
 cations, gives a scientific basis for this existing 
 solidarity between man and society. 
 
 The great consensus of opinion amongst those 
 who are best qualified to judge amongst those 
 who alone are qualified to judge may be regarded 
 as having established the claim of the theory of 
 evolution to give the most satisfactory account of 
 all forms of natural life. And it may seem only 
 advancing the theory a step further, or only de- 
 veloping one of its applications, to make it yield a 
 complete explanation of human nature, mental as 
 well as physical. If ethics, then, is to be founded 
 on a " natural " basis, no theory would seem to be 
 complete which leaves evolution out of account. 
 
 In general, the theory of evolution is an assertion an assertion 
 of the unity of life, or, in its widest form, of the ofiife; Um 
 unity of existence. Progressive modifications and 
 hereditary transmission of such modifications are, 
 it is contended, sufficient to explain the different 
 forms and species which life now manifests. The 
 assumption is specially discarded that there are 
 fixed differences between kinds of living things 
 making it impossible for them all to have developed 
 from simple germs, originally of like constitution, 
 which have, in the course of time, become more 
 heterogeneous and complex, and so given rise to 
 the wealth of organic life. But this general doc- 
 
110 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 trine, held (wholly or in part) in modern times by 
 Kant, Wolff, and Lamarck, needed to be supple- 
 mented by a definite view of the way in which the 
 progressive modifications took place ; and this re- 
 quired to be established as a really operative 
 cause, before evolution could receive scientific' 
 proof. This more special element of the theory 
 was Darwin's contribution to the subject. Evolu- 
 tion, he showed, and herein consists his theoret- 
 ical advance on Lamarck, has taken place by the 
 " natural selection " of organisms, so modified as to 
 fit them for survival in the struggle for existence. 
 Organisms in which advantageous modifications 
 have been produced tend to survive, and to trans- 
 mit their modified structure to descendants, while 
 organisms in which such modifications have not 
 been produced, are less able to preserve their life 
 and to hand it on to successors. Older types, it is 
 true, remain, but only in circumstances in which 
 their continued existence does not seriously inter- 
 fere with the organisms which, in the struggle for 
 life, have developed a structure better suited to 
 their environment: when more perfect and less 
 perfect forms cannot exist together, only the better 
 adapted survive. 
 
 in first in-/' The theory of evolution is thus primarily the 
 history of an order of sequent facts and relations. 
 It is an account of the origin or growth of things, 
 which attempts to explain their nature and consti- 
 
THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. Ill 
 
 tution by showing how they have come to be what 
 they are. But, in so doing, it naturally reveals the 
 method and tendency of this order. And it is by but impli 
 means of this its teleological aspect that we see how ca^aspe 
 it may be possible for it not merely to trace the de- ^ 
 velopment of historical facts, such as the feelings conse - 
 
 quences. 
 
 and customs of men, but at the same time to make 
 a more real contribution to ethics by pointing out 
 the course of action to which human nature is 
 adapted. It does not, like the old teleology, at- ^J 
 tempt to show that each thing has been formed 
 with the design of subserving some particular 
 purpose. On the contrary, it reverses this way of 
 looking at things. The fitness of an organism to 
 fulfil any definite end comes to be regarded as the 
 result not of a conscious design, independent of the 
 environment, but of the modifications produced on 
 the organism through the necessity laid upon it by 
 its surroundings of adapting itself to them or else 
 disappearing. What the theory does show is, that 
 adaptation to environment is necessary for life, and 
 that organisms unable to adapt themselves pass 
 away. Adaptation to environment will thus be 
 implied in, or be an essential means towards, self- 
 preservation and race -preservation, self -develop- 
 ment and race-development. And should this pre- 
 servation or development be looked upon as the end 
 of conduct, the adaptation to environment it im- 
 plies may help to define and characterise the end. 
 
112 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 Again : when an organism adapts itself to its en- 
 vironment, it does so by some modification being 
 produced in its structure corresponding to the modi- 
 fied function required by the conditions of life. In 
 this way, one organism increases in complexity in a 
 certain direction, while another organism, in differ- 
 ent circumstances, also develops a more compli- 
 cated structure, though one of a different kind. 
 Thus organisms, alike to begin with, become heter- 
 ogeneous in nature through exposure to different 
 surroundings. At the same time, by constant in- 
 teraction with their environments, they become 
 more definite and coherent in structure. Incipient 
 modifications are developed and defined in different 
 ways by different circumstances, and the parts of a 
 living being are brought into closer reciprocal rela- 
 tions, and thus welded into a coherent organic 
 whole. This is what Mr Spencer means when he 
 says that evolution implies a transition from " an 
 indefinite incoherent homogeneity to a definite co- 
 herent heterogeneity " : 1 the whole process being 
 interconnected in such a way that these different 
 aspects of it definiteness, coherence, heterogeneity 
 increase together and imply one another. By 
 this the inference would appear to be suggested 
 that, if conduct is to harmonise with the conditions 
 of evolution, this characteristic feature of it must 
 be recognised in the ethical end. 
 
 1 First Principles, 4th ed., p. 380. 
 
THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 113 
 
 In saying this, I am perhaps anticipating results. Distinction 
 But it is well to show at the outset how the essen- 
 
 tially historical inquiry carried out by the evolu- ethical 
 
 aspects. 
 
 tionists may suggest conclusions which are ethical 
 in their nature. To some, indeed, it will appear 
 superfluous to have spent even a sentence in suggest- 
 ing a primd facie case for the ethical importance 
 of evolution. If there is one subject more than 
 another, it may be thought, which has secured a 
 place for itself in the scientific consciousness of the 
 day, it is the evolution-theory of ethics.<-Without 
 question, the phrase has been received into the 
 scientific vocabulary ; but there is a good deal, even 
 in the official literature on the question, to make 
 one doubt whether it is always used with a distinct 
 conception of its meaning. When reference is made 
 to the " ethics of evolution," no more is sometimes 
 meant though a great deal more should be meant 
 than an historical account of the growth of moral 
 ideas and customs, which may provide (as Mr 
 Stephen expresses it) " a new armoury wherewith 
 to encounter certain plausible objections of the 
 so-called Intuitionists." This, however, would only 
 affect the ethical psychology of an opposed school. 
 The profounder question still remains, What bear- 
 ing has the theory of evolution, or its historical 
 psychology and sociology, on the nature of the ethical 
 end, or on the standard for distinguishing right and 
 wrong in conduct? The answer to this question 
 
 H 
 
114 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 will be the " reconstruction " and " deeper change " 
 which Mr Stephen holds to be necessary. 1 It is 
 the ambiguity of the subject or rather its twofold 
 range which has made the application of evolution 
 to ethics look so obvious, and made a discussion of 
 the easier question frequently do duty for a solution 
 of the more difficult. The ethical writings of the 
 evolutionists, indeed, often confuse the problems of 
 history and theory in a way which presents the 
 same difficulty to the critic as the works of the cor- 
 responding school in -jurisprudence. In both, the 
 writers seem disinclined fairly to put to themselves 
 the question as to the kind of subjects to which so 
 fruitful a method as that which has fallen into their 
 hands is appropriate : what its conditions are, and 
 whether it has any limits at all. Every one is now 
 familiar with the evils of hypothetical history, and 
 with the iniquity of the proverbial philosophic 
 offence of constructing facts out of one's inner con- 
 sciousness. The historical jurists deserve no little 
 credit for the thoroughness with which this has 
 been enforced by them ; perhaps, too, the same les- 
 son may be learned from the facts of the develop- 
 ment of morality. But it may be questioned whether 
 we are not at the present time more apt to confuse 
 fact and theory in the opposite way : whether the 
 science of law is not sometimes lost sight of in the 
 history of legal institutions, and ethics in danger 
 
 1 Science of Ethics, p. vi. 
 
THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 115 
 
 of being identified with the development of moral 
 sentiments and customs. 
 
 We may naturally expect the theory of evolution 
 to throw light on such questions as the growth of 
 moral feelings and ideas, and of the customs and 
 institutions in which morality is expressed and 
 embodied. But to show the process morality has 
 passed through in the individual mind and in society 
 still leaves the question as to the end of conduct 
 unanswered. It is necessary, therefore, to keep 
 clearly before us the distinction between the histo- 
 rical and the ethical problem, if we would success- 
 fully attack the subject of the bearing of the theory 
 of evolution on this fundamental question of ethics. 
 To the theory of evolution we are indebted for the 
 opening up of a new field of investigation the his- 
 torical treatment of conduct. But it is one thing 
 to describe the way in which men have acted in the 
 past : to determine the end for their action now is 
 quite a different problem ; and there is no reason why 
 the distinction should be overlooked. The interest 
 which belongs to the history of morality is not 
 solely nor mainly due to its bearing on questions 
 beyond the historical sphere. That its results will 
 not be without relation and that of an important 
 kind to questions of theory may well be expected. 
 But it can only tend to confusion if we treat the 
 development of morality, in the human mind and 
 in society, from a preconceived attitude dogmatic 
 
116 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 or agnostic towards the central problem of 
 ethics. 
 
 2. The de- The way in which the theory of evolution is ap- 
 ofmoramy: P^ e( ^ to ethical psychology is easy enough to under- 
 
 (a) historical s fc an( j j n principle, though complex and obscure in 
 
 psychology. 
 
 many of its details. We have only to postulate 
 that mental as well as bodily traits admit of modi- 
 fication, and that modifications once produced can 
 be transmitted to descendants, 1 and it 1 at once fol- 
 lows that sentiments and -ideas leading to actions 
 which promote life will be encouraged and devel- 
 oped by natural selection. Thus parental and filial 
 feelings, once originated, may have been developed 
 through those families and tribes in which they 
 were strongest, presenting a more united, and 
 therefore stronger, front against hostile influences. 
 The feelings of tribal sympathy and patriotism, too, 
 may have had a similar history. Those races in 
 which they were strongest would, other things 
 being equal, obtain the mastery over and extermi- 
 nate other races in which they were relatively weak. 
 The compactness of the community would even be 
 promoted by that fear of the political and of the 
 
 1 It would seem that the transmission of mental qualities only 
 takes place in the form of modified physical structure (cf. Gr. H. 
 Lewes, Problems of Life and Mind, 1st series, i. 164). But, if we 
 regard it as established that every mental change has a structural 
 modification corresponding to it, the possibility of mental evolu- 
 tion and inheritance presents no new difficulty^ 
 
THE DEVELOPMENT OF MORALITY. 117 
 
 religious control in which the feeling of obligation 
 is said to have had its root. In general, benevo- 
 lence and sympathy amongst a people give it a soli- 
 darity from which it derives a stronger position, so 
 that in turn the benevolent and sympathetic feel- 
 ings gain free scope to develop and expand. 
 
 But the working out of this theory is not with- its difficui- 
 out its own difficulties. In the first place, the factor origin of 
 in the theory of evolution which can be most w s fe( 
 clearly traced the principle of natural selection 
 is not itself a source of change or of the production 
 of new results. It is only the means by which 
 advantageous changes are preserved and disadvan- 
 tageous changes passed by. The initiative in these 
 changes comes either from the unequal pressure of 
 the environment or from some tendency to vary in 
 the organism itself. Now, if we suppose certain 
 moral relations and the feelings corresponding to 
 them to exist in a society, and to tend to greater 
 certainty and' fulness of life on the part of those 
 who possess them, such relations and feelings will 
 be favoured by the operation of natural selection, 
 and will gradually be assimilated into the tissue of 
 the social organism. But this does not account for 
 the origin of morality generally nor of any par- ^ 
 ticular moral relation ; it merely shows how, having 
 been somehow originated, it has naturally come to 
 persist. There are thus really two points to be 
 considered in tracing the development of moral 
 
118 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 ideas the question of origin and the question of 
 persistence. The latter is accounted for by natural 
 selection; the former must be brought under the 
 obscure laws of variation, laws so obscure that 
 variations in nature are frequently spoken of as if 
 they took place by chance. These two questions 
 are involved at each stage in the progress of 
 morality. But it is at the initial stage that the 
 and of the question of origin is of greatest importance: when 
 sdousness"- ^ e a ^tempt is made to show how, in the course of 
 time, and by the aid of purely physical and biolo- 
 gical laws, feelings and conduct, from being merely 
 natural and reflex, have acquired a moral character 
 when, in a word, the moral is being evolved out 
 of the non-moral. A difficulty comes to the front 
 here which scarcely arises when we are simply 
 tracing the various phases through which the moral 
 consciousness has passed, and the various forms in 
 which moral conduct and feelings have expressed 
 and embodied themselves. The latter subject is 
 obviously within the scope of the theory of evo- 
 lution, if that theory applies to the processes of 
 the human mind and society as well as to those of 
 external nature. And, although each stage involves 
 a modification to be accounted for not by natural 
 selection, but by the laws of variation, yet the 
 variation is within facts of the same order, and 
 creates no more difficulty than the successive modi- 
 fications of living tissue which have been implied 
 
THE DEVELOPMENT OF MOKALITY. 119 
 
 in the evolution of organic nature. But the transi- 
 tion from the non-moral to the moral is a transition 
 to a different order of facts or perhaps we should 
 rather say to a different way of looking at facts, 
 and should not be assumed to be a process of the 
 same kind and explicable by the same method of 
 investigation as the passage from one fact to the 
 similar fact which immediately follows it. It may 
 be compared, perhaps, to the transition from the 
 sphere of inorganic matter to that of life. At the 
 same time, it is frequently maintained that we 
 unduly limit the application of the law of evolution 
 if we deny its power to show how morality has 
 developed out of customs and institutions whose 
 origin can be traced to purely natural or non- 
 moral causes. And, for present purposes, it is 
 sufficient to have pointed out that this does not 
 necessarily follow from the admission that evolution 
 applies to mental and social processes as well as 
 to the facts of external nature. It is not my object 
 to criticise any doctrine of the development of mor- 
 ality ; but, starting with the position taken up with 
 regard to it by the theory of evolution, to inquire 
 what conclusions it may lead to as to the end of 
 action. 
 
 A further difficulty has to be met by the theory thedeveiop- 
 
 n, ini ,., ,.,.. ment of feel- 
 
 oi the development or morality, which is in a sense i llgs apart 
 complementary of the initial difficulty encountered 
 in differentiating the moral from the non-moral. 
 
120 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 This further difficulty awaits it at a subsequent 
 stage of development when the extension and re- 
 finement of moral feeling seem to have gone on in 
 circumstances where there is no room for natural 
 selection to work. Thus it has been admitted that 
 the feeling of sympathy, and the habitual exercise 
 of mutual good offices among members of a com- 
 munity, strengthen that society, and make it fit 
 to prevail in the struggle for existence over other 
 similar societies, the members of which are not so 
 much at one amongst themselves in feeling and 
 in act. 
 
 But as benevolence and sympathy widen, and 
 become less closely connected with a definite 
 association of individuals, such as the family or 
 tribe, and there ceases to be a particular body to 
 the welfare of which these social feelings contri- 
 bute, the operation of the law of natural selection 
 becomes less certain. This law only tends to con- 
 serve and perfect the feelings in question, in virtue 
 of the fact that the associations to whose good they 
 lead are successful in the struggle for life over 
 other associations the members of which are not 
 animated by like feelings. The one association 
 lives and expands, while the others are unable to 
 maintain themselves against the encroachments of 
 their neighbours, and thus fall to pieces. The law 
 of natural selection, therefore, comes into play only 
 when there are competing organisms struggling 
 
THE DEVELOPMENT OF MORALITY. 121 
 
 against one another for the means of subsistence 
 and development. Not only is it the case, therefore, 
 that the sympathy which aids the weak who are 
 unable to take care of themselves, does not seem to 
 be of the kind that would contribute to success in 
 the struggle for existence; but the more general 
 and catholic our sympathies are, the less will the 
 law of evolution help to preserve and develop 
 them because the less will they tend to promote 
 the welfare of one rival association rather than 
 that of another. Thus the growth of really un- 
 restricted sympathy with men as men cannot have 
 been promoted in this way. The " enthusiasm of 
 humanity" which animated the early Christians, 
 the self-renouncing brotherhood of Buddha, the 
 <}>i\av6 /owTi-ia attributed to men like Xenocrates 1 who 
 had freed themselves from the aristocratic pre- 
 judices of Athens, the " caritas generis humani " of 
 the Stoics, such feelings as these could not have 
 been encouraged, any more than they could have 
 been produced, by the operation of natural selection. 
 For, however much they tend to elevate the human 
 character, and to promote human happiness, they 
 do not advance the welfare of one body of men to 
 the exclusion of some other competitor in the 
 struggle for existence. 2 
 
 1 ^Elian, V. H., xiii. 30. 
 
 2 If conscience has no other function than that assigned to it 
 by Clifford, Lectures and Essay, ii. 169, "the preservation of 
 
122 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 But, although the law of natural evolution can- 
 not account, by survival of the fittest, for any 
 progress made by universal benevolence, yet it may 
 explain the value ascribed to the feeling of benev- 
 olence, when its object is the family or the com- 
 munity. Besides as has already been pointed 
 out natural selection always implies an initiative 
 got from elsewhere : it does not itself produce 
 modifications ; it only chooses out favourable ones 
 and adds them together when produced. It always 
 implies an independent modification of the organ- 
 ism; its part is to select the modifications best 
 fitted to promote life. Hence the mere fact of 
 benevolence being universalised is not in itself an 
 anomaly on the theory of natural selection, any 
 more than is the fact of its being extended from 
 the family to the tribe. Only, the latter extension 
 is one which it perpetuates, the former is not. No 
 aspect of the theory of evolution seems able to 
 account for an extension of the feeling of universal 
 benevolence among different people or throughout 
 different societies. This feeling has neither tended 
 to promote the welfare of the race animated by it 
 to the exclusion of other competing races for 
 there are no competing races whom it could 
 affect nor can it be shown that it makes the 
 individuals possessing it fitter to wage successful 
 
 society in the struggle for existence," then it can never reach 
 universal benevolence or prescribe " duties towards all mankind." 
 
THE DEVELOPMENT OF MORALITY. 123 
 
 war against opposing forces, than other individ- 
 uals. 1 
 
 Apart from such special difficulties, however, its result: 
 comparative psychology has shed a new light on the LcMnatu 
 mental structure of the individual. The facts it ^ indl 
 brings forward show that the nature of the individual 
 man cannot be explained without taking into account 
 the relations in which he stands to society by birth, 
 education, and business. He is, from the first, sur- 
 rounded by, and dependent upon, other individuals, 
 and by a set of established usages and institutions 
 which modify his life; and he is connected with 
 these in such a way that it is impossible to consider 
 him as merely acted upon by them and influencing 
 them in turn. He has been produced by, and has 
 become a part of them. His physical and mental 
 structure bears the marks of the same influences as 
 those by which his so-called environment has been 
 
 1 A difficulty of another kind is suggested by Professor Bain, 
 who holds that the " pleasure of malevolence " is not only a real 
 element in the human constitution, but greater than would be 
 naturally called forth by the conditions and course of develop- 
 ment. " It is remarked by Mr Spencer." he says ; " that it was 
 necessary for the progress of the race that destructive activity 
 should not be painful, but on the whole pleasurable. In point of 
 fact, however, the pleasure of destruction has gone much beyond 
 what these words express, and much beyond what is advantageous 
 to the collective interest of animals and of human beings alike. 
 The positive delight in suffering has been at all stages too great." 
 The Emotions and the Will, p. 66. So far from adopting this 
 argument, however, I must confess myself still amongst the un- 
 convinced regarding the " pleasure of malevolence." 
 
124 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 formed. He is cell in the " tissue " of which the body 
 social is composed. This was partly recognised, it 
 is true, before the theory of evolution had been 
 elaborated. But the organic nature of the social 
 union is confirmed by that theory, and erected into 
 a scientific view of human life. 
 
 (&) Develop- Now the various sentiments which bring one man 
 locLy. i^o mental union with others act with greatest 
 facility when men are connected with one another 
 by some definite mutual bond such as that which 
 forms the family, the clan, or the nation. The 
 individual's feeling of sympathy with his neighbours 
 both promotes this social union and depends upon 
 it. But it is characteristic of the theory of evolu- 
 tion to put the external aspect first the social cus- 
 toms and institutions and to evolve from them the 
 corresponding sentiments and ideas. Not word or 
 thought or power, it holds, is to be regarded as the 
 origin of morality : " Im Anfang war die That." The 
 whole composed of these units bound together by 
 reciprocity of feeling and function is termed the 
 " social organism " ; and what has been called moral 
 sociology shows the way in which the outward forms 
 which express and. embody morality have grown up 
 and become part of it. 
 
 In this connection, the theory of natural evolution 
 traces the process by which, from the rudimentary 
 beginnings of society, the members composing it 
 have gradually become more coherent amongst one 
 another, related in definite ways instead of merely 
 
THE DEVELOPMENT OF MORALITY. 125 
 
 by chance, and more differentiated in function. 
 Certain rudimentary forms such as the family 
 (in its rudest structure) and the corresponding 
 instincts are presupposed. And from this basis the 
 origin of institutions and customs, political, reli- 
 gious, and industrial, is traced. In developing these 
 various customs and institutions, along with the 
 corresponding sentiments, the course of social evolu- 
 tion has had the effect of gradually bringing out and 
 cultivating those feelings and tendencies in the indi- 
 vidual which promote the welfare of the organism, 
 while other individual tendencies, hostile to social 
 welfare, have been repressed. Not sympathy and 
 benevolence only, but honesty, temperance, justice, 
 and all the ordinary social and personal virtues, may 
 have their natural history traced in this way by 
 showing how they have contributed to the life of the 
 individual, or of the society, or of both. 1 Through 
 the operation of purely natural laws, the wicked are 
 " cut off from the earth," while the "perfect remain in 
 it" and leave their possessions to their children. This 
 is an obvious result of natural selection. For those 
 communities are always fittest to survive in which 
 each member, in feeling and in act, is most at one 
 with the whole. The tendency of evolution seems to 
 be to produce not merely an ideal but an actual iden- 
 tification of individual and social interests, in which 
 each man finds his own good in that of the state. 
 
 1 This subject is carefully discussed in Mr Stephen's ' Science 
 of Ethics.' 
 
126 
 
 CHAPTEE VI. 
 
 EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 
 
 Bearing of BEFORE going on to inquire into the positive con- 
 of evoStton tributions to ethics which the theory of evolution 
 
 nas to offer, it is necessary to consider the relation 
 theories. ft bears to the preceding individualistic systems of 
 morals. It was by way of investigations in psy- 
 chology and in the theory of society, that it first 
 began to influence ethical thought. And, at first; 
 sight, it appeared to come as a natural ally of 
 one of the opposed schools, dreaded by the side 
 it opposed, 1 welcomed with open arms by that 
 favoured with its friendship. But since the first 
 shock of pained and pleased surprise, there have 
 been rumours of dissension in the allies' camp ; 
 and the distribution of parties has now become a 
 matter of difficulty. The doctrine of evolution, 
 first seized upon for rebutting the arguments of the 
 intuitional moralists, has been found to transform 
 
 1 Cf . Miss Cobbe, in ' Darwinism in Morals, and other Essays ' 
 (1872), p. 5. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 127 
 
 rather than to destroy their system ; and the utili- 
 tarianism in whose interests the new controversial 
 weapon was employed, seems to have been subjected 
 to a parallel process of transformation. The bearing 
 of evolution on egoism may appear to be even more 
 fundamental. For the inheritance by an individual 
 of the qualities acquired by his ancestors may be 
 thought to establish scientifically the theory of the 
 unity of the race, and, in doing so, to make the 
 selfish system of conduct an anachronism. 
 
 It is not necessary to examine at any length the i. on theo- 
 application of evolution to the theories which con- in^onmoni 
 struct ethical principles on the basis of moral senti- 
 ment, because these theories have been found either 
 to resolve themselves into a subtle form of egoistic 
 hedonism, or else to rest their ethical system on 
 a teleological conception^ which transcends the 
 " naturalistic " view of man. Evolution has its own 
 explanation to give of the seemingly intuitive char- 
 acter of moral ideas showing how their immediate 
 necessity for the individual of the present day may 
 be reconciled with their empirical origin in the 
 mental history of the race. It attempts thus to 
 supplant both egoism and intuitionism by the same 
 doctrine of the organic union between individuals. 
 
 The phenomena of conscience and the moral 
 sentiments had been brought forward to show 
 that the origin of morality was independent of the 
 experience of the pleasurable or painful results of 
 
128 
 
 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 Origin and 
 history of 
 moral senti- 
 ments and 
 intuitions 
 traced by 
 evolution. 
 
 action : that certain actions and traits of character 
 were immediately approved and pronounced to be 
 right by the individual conscience, and certain 
 others as inexplicably but infallibly disapproved 
 and pronounced to be wrong. This phenomenon of 
 moral approbation or disapprobation had indeed 
 been thought by some as has been already seen 
 to be only a special feeling of pleasure or pain. 
 Even as such, however, it pointed to a peculiar 
 harmony or sympathy between the feelings of the 
 individual and the fortunes of society. For the 
 pleasure or pain of the individual was seen to be 
 excited by actions and dispositions which might be 
 shown to involve the common interests, but were 
 without relation to his own. 
 
 Even on the " empirical " interpretation of them, 
 such facts of the individual mind were in need of 
 explanation ; and the theory of evolution has taken 
 in hand to show how the pre - established har- 
 mony grew up. The results of this explanation 
 are, of course, not put forward as explaining the 
 facts away, or depriving them of reality, but as 
 enabling us to see their true place and bearing in 
 the economy of human nature. In tracing the 
 origin and history of the " altruistic " and >" moral " 
 sentiments of the individual, the theory of evolution 
 has this end in view. It offers so it is often said 
 terms of compromise between the " intuitional " 
 and the " empirical " psychology of morals. It will 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 129 
 
 admit the immediate and intuitive character in the 
 individual of the sentiments which older empiricism 
 had tried to make out to be composite, growing up 
 in each person out of the materials afforded by his 
 environment, and the experiences to which he was 
 subjected. The theory of evolution contends for 
 an empiricism on a larger scale, which will more 
 closely connect the individual with the race, and 
 both with their environment. 
 
 The question thus arises, What bearing has this Bearing of 
 
 . . . . , , , this on their 
 
 psychological or psycnogomcal theory on the validity : 
 ethical validity of moral intuitions and sentiments ? 
 It certainly does not follow that they are of no 
 moral value, merely because their origin can be 
 traced to simpler elements of experience. They 
 would lose ethical importance only if it were first 
 of all shown that their validity depended on their 
 not being derived from, or compounded out of, 
 other elements. As Professor Sidgwick says, " Those 
 who dispute the authority of moral or other in- 
 tuitions on the ground of their derivation, must be 
 required to show, not merely that they are the 
 effects of certain causes, but that these causes are 
 of a kind that tend to produce invalid belief." l 
 
 But what the theory of evolution has to de- 
 termine with regard to moral intuitions or sen- 
 sibilities would seem to be not so much their 
 ethical validity or invalidity, as the range and 
 ] Methods of Ethics, III. i. 4, 3d ed., p. 211. 
 I 
 
130 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 manner of their ethical application. It attempts 
 to show that particular moral beliefs or feel- 
 ings have been originated and formed by certain 
 external customs belonging to the conditions of 
 social or family life. These customs have im- 
 pressed themselves upon the mental structure, and 
 reappear in the individual in the shape of organic 
 tendencies to certain actions, or classes of actions, 
 and of aversion to other actions, accompanied by 
 a corresponding mental sentiment or judgment 
 of approbation or disapprobation. Thus the indivi- 
 dual comes instinctively to feel or to judge, " A 
 ought to be done," " B ought not to be done." Now 
 the evolutionist, as I conceive, does not proceed to 
 infer that such judgments are invalid because he 
 has shown how they originated does not conclude 
 (to use Mr Sidgwick's words) that " all propositions 
 of the form ' X is right ' or ' good/ are untrust- 
 worthy ; " but he does ask in what way the history 
 of these judgments affects their application. 1 
 (a) different (a) He recognises, in the first place, that all such 
 judgments are the natural result of a certain social 
 con( lition, and that there is, therefore, some pro- 
 resulted, bability that the same kind of social state could 
 not continue to exist were those moral judgments 
 
 1 Cf. Professor F. Pollock, "Evolution and Ethics "Mind, 
 i. pp. 335 ff. Apart from the bearing of a utilitarian test on 
 inherited instincts, to which Mr Pollock refers, I have tried to 
 show what meaning they will have for the evolutionist who judges 
 them solely from the point of view of his theory. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 131 
 
 habitually disregarded in conduct. They have re- 
 sulted from a certain state of society, and have 
 been assumed after insufficient experience, per- 
 haps to be required for the stability of that state, 
 so that every action opposed to these moral judg- 
 ments will probably tend to weaken social bonds. 
 But the evolutionist's conclusions are not restricted 
 to such generalities. He may show that certain 
 moral judgments or sentiments have had their 
 origin from the habits of union between individuals, 
 and of respect for the rights of property, which 
 have obtained in every relatively permanent society, 
 and which may therefore be inferred to be pro- 
 bably necessary for the continued existence of any 
 community ; that certain other sentiments or in- 
 tuitions have descended to present individuals from 
 customs which have not been so universal in the 
 history of societies, although the communities pos- 
 sessing them have shown greater power of vitality 
 than those in which they were absent ; while others, 
 again, may be traced to institutions which, from 
 their occasional and unprogressive character, may 
 be shown to be neither necessary nor beneficial. 
 
 The evolutionist will therefore contend that and conse 
 different degrees of value for the regulation of 
 conduct belong to different moral intuitions or valuef r 
 
 conduct ; 
 
 classes of them. If one class is habitually dis- 
 regarded, he may assert that historical evidence 
 goes to show that society will fall to pieces, and 
 
132 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 the life of man become, in the expressive words of 
 Hobbes, " solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short." 
 The disregard of another class will probably lead 
 to a more precarious existence, or one less filled 
 with the experiences which make up life ; while 
 opposition to a third .class, so far from being hurt- 
 ful or dangerous, may remove unnecessary restric- 
 tions, and aid the development both of the individual 
 and of society. 
 
 (6) their (&) There is a second point which will also be 
 
 character, recognised by the evolutionist. Although these 
 intuitions have been derived, they are now organic, 
 and their disappearance from the human mind as 
 instinctive tendencies towards or against action can 
 only be slow and painful. The process must involve 
 a certain amount of loss : at the same time, it is 
 not a process that can be easily avoided. As soon 
 as the reason of the instinctive tendency is inquired 
 into, it is weakened as instinct. We pass 'from the 
 action itself to the end it is fitted to subserve ; and, 
 if the instinctive action is not the most appropriate, 
 or has hurtful results, we have already reached the 
 stage in which the instinct is checked, and begins 
 to yield to action directed by a principle. Yet it 
 dies out only gradually, and, so to speak, after a 
 struggle. JSTor does it seem possible to assert with 
 confidence, as mitigating this struggle, that the 
 strongest impulses will always be those which are 
 necessary or advantageous to the existence of 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 133 
 
 society. For it is a common experience that the 
 moral intuitions which lead to conduct that has 
 ceased to serve a purpose, and the internal sanctions 
 which follow disregard of them, are often even 
 more powerful than those which protect such vir- 
 tues as justice or veracity. 
 
 From the preceding argument it follows that it Resultant 
 cannot be held that moral intuitions are invalid evoiution- 
 because evolved. The evolutionist will certainly ^ n * m intui ' 
 go very far wrong, as Mr Sidgwick points out, if he 
 maintains that a " general demonstration of the 
 derivedness or developedness of our moral faculty 
 is an adequate ground for distrusting it." Instead 
 of holding that, if we succeed in tracing the origin 
 of an intuition, it is thereby discredited, he will 
 admit that the mere fact of our possessing any 
 moral intuition shows that the habits of action 
 from which it was derived have been permanent 
 enough to leave their traces on the mental struc- 
 ture, and that the conduct to which it leads, like 
 the custom from which it came, will not destroy 
 society, but, on the contrary, will probably tend to 
 its permanence. The general attitude of the evolu- 
 tion-theory to moral intuitions is therefore, after 
 all, very similar to that which Mr Sidgwick has 
 reached as a result of his elaborate examination of 
 the maxims of common-sense. It is an attitude of 
 trust modified by criticism. In both an appeal 
 is made from the axioms themselves : in the one 
 
134 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 case, to their historical genesis and the facts in 
 which they originated ; in the other, to the search- 
 ing test of logical consistency, and their capability 
 of being applied to conduct. But the theory of 
 evolution, if it succeeds in tracing the origin of our 
 moral intuitions, does seem to involve the abandon- 
 ment of the old intuitional method which accepted 
 them as rules of conduct from which no appeal 
 could be taken. 
 
 2. Bearing The theory of evolution transforms intuitionism 
 ofevoiuttoif by the way in which it connects the individual 
 
 on egoism. w ^ ^ race> jj. g g rgt e p ec ^ U p 0n egoism is similar. 
 The nature of the individual man as now exhibited 
 is widely different from that which the older indivi- 
 dualistic theory used to deal with. The latter is 
 typified by the marble statue to which Condillac l 
 compares the percipient subject, as yet unaffected 
 by sense-impressions. The variety of mental life 
 which is actually met with is accounted for by the 
 different kinds of experiences different men pass 
 through ; and the consequent difference in the 
 sources of pleasure and pain accounts for the 
 diverse lines of activity which human beings follow 
 out. But the theory of evolution shows that human 
 nature is infinitely varied, not only through the 
 variety of circumstances, but through the variety 
 of inherited dispositions. One individual is not 
 
 1 Traite des sensations, (Euvres (1798), vol. iii. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 135 
 
 merely connected with others through considerable 
 similarity of experience built upon an equally 
 characterless basis; but he is organically related 
 to all the members of the race, not only bone of 
 their bone and flesh of their flesh, but mind of their 
 mind. He is connected with others by a thousand 
 subtly interwoven threads of emotion which enter 
 into his life, and unite his desires and activities 
 with the functions of the larger organism of which 
 he is a member. 
 
 The theory of evolution has thus an important Relation of 
 contribution to make to the question of the relation altruism 
 between egoism and altruism. It has remained for Jl^ 6 * 8 
 it to show historically how the individual is so con- ( a) nature of 
 
 the individ- 
 
 nected with the community that the good, or the ual s ciai, 
 pleasure, of the one cannot be considered apart from 
 that of the other. From the non-evolutionist point 
 of view it was always open to show how the indi- 
 vidual depended on society, how his wants could 
 only be supplied by it, and how the security and 
 happiness of every one were bound up with those 
 of his fellows. The individualistic theory was thus 
 able to give all sorts of egoistic reasons why people 
 should indulge in what is now called altruistic 
 conduct. Self was seen to be " a poor centre for 
 a man's actions," and only chosen by the short- 
 sighted person, who thereby missed both the good 
 to himself that followed from his neighbours' well- 
 being, and the peculiar pleasure of sympathy and 
 
136 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 benevolent action. But the theory of evolution 
 has shown how the two things have developed 
 together in the race : first, the actual solidarity be- 
 tween the individual and the whole ; and secondly, 
 the subjective reflection of the same fact, sympathy 
 with the feelings of others. When we ask, there- 
 fore, whether it is our own pleasure (or good) or 
 that of others that we ought to aim at, we are 
 pointed to the gradual obliteration of the distinc- 
 tion between the interest and feelings of the in- 
 dividual and those of the ' whole. Were this com- 
 pletely accomplished, there need be no more ques- 
 tion about the matter. If conduct with an egoistic 
 motive or aim always resulted in altruistic equally 
 with egoistic effects, and if altruistic conduct had 
 always egoistic equally with altruistic consequen- 
 ces, it would even then be little more than vain 
 subtlety to ask whether egoism or altruism was 
 to be the 'real end of conduct. But if, in addi- 
 tion to the identity of interests, there were also 
 an identity of motive or feeling, 1 the question 
 would be no longer in place at all. For there 
 would cease to be either a subjective distinction 
 in motive between egoism and altruism, or an 
 objective distinction in the courses of conduct to 
 but not which they led. And it is just because this 
 identification is manifestly incomplete because 
 
 1 It is to a condition of this sort that a phrase such as Clifford's 
 "tribal self " (Lectures and Essays, ii. Ill) would apply. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 137 
 
 neither the interests nor the desires of the indi- social. 
 vidual harmonise with any degree of exactness 
 with those of his fellows that we must examine 
 how far the conception of the social organism is 
 a true expression for the connection of individuals. 
 
 At most, the theory of organic evolution can make Difference 
 out that there is a tendency towards the identifica- in e d ^u a i 
 tion of the interests of the individual with those andsocial 
 
 organisms 
 
 of society. It cannot demonstrate a complete iden- 
 tification. The community has indeed been called 
 an organism, and the individual spoken of as a 
 cell in the tissue of which it is composed; but 
 we must avoid pressing this analogy to the point 
 of breaking. Among so many points of similarity 
 between society and an individual organism, there 
 is one essential distinction, the social organism 
 has no feelings and thoughts but those of its in- 
 dividual members the conscious centre is in the 
 unit, not in the whole ; whereas, when we regard 
 the individual organism and its constituent mem- 
 bers, consciousness is seen to exist only in the 
 whole, not in each several unit. The absence of 
 a " social sensorium " l should, therefore, make us 
 hesitate to identify the ends of individual with 
 those of collective action. Every cell in the in- 
 dividual body has a life-history of its own, besides 
 partaking of the life of the organism ; and, did it 
 possess the reason which " looks before and after/' 
 
 1 Cf. Spencer, Principles of Sociology, i. 479. 
 
138 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 it might probably adopt an egoistic attitude, and 
 object to the subordination of its private interests 
 to the good of the whole. In the same way, the 
 many individual lives which make up the social 
 organism since each of them possesses a separate 
 consciousness are apt to disregard the life of the 
 larger whole whose members they are. Now what 
 the theory of utilitarianism requires is, that the 
 happiness or pleasurable consciousness of the com- 
 munity or of the race, not that of the individual, 
 be made the end ; and those who make egoism the 
 end of ethics, commonly maintain that the general 
 happiness is the end of politics. 1 The individual 
 is not indeed required to be entirely unselfish or 
 " altruistic " in action. He is not altogether for- 
 bidden to seek his own things, nor enjoined to 
 seek only the things of others ; and evolutionist 
 utilitarianism, indeed, would tell him to seek his 
 own happiness in the happiness of the community. 
 But the obvious remark must be borne in mind, 
 that society, the social organism, cannot experience 
 happiness. However it may resemble the indi- 
 vidual organism in the manner of its growth, the 
 modes of its activity, and even its relation to its 
 component members, yet it cannot feel pleasure or 
 pain as an individual does. The "happiness of 
 the community " does not mean the happiness of 
 the social organism, but is only a concise formula 
 
 i Cf . Barratt, " Ethics and Politics "Mind, ii. 453 ff. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 139 
 
 for the aggregate happinesses of the individuals 
 composing it. 
 
 When it is said, therefore either as a political in respect 
 or an ethical theory that the happiness of society 
 is the end for conduct, the end prescribed is altru- 
 istic rather than social. Its object is not an organ- 
 ism, but an aggregate of individuals. A certain 
 organisation of society may lead to an increase in 
 this aggregate happiness, and so be necessary for 
 the attainment of the end ; but if the end is hap- 
 piness, the social organism and its wellbeing are 
 no longer the thing cared for, but the greatest 
 aggregate of pleasures on the part of its members. 
 
 So long, therefore, as the end is pleasure, it must 
 have reference to individuals. The utilitarian may 
 try to persuade the agent to seek the pleasures 
 of others as if they were his own requiring him 
 thus to seek his end out of himself, and the circle 
 of his own pleasures. And, while we continue to 
 hold pleasure to be the end, the evolution-theory^ 
 can go no further than this. It seemed to have made 
 out an organic unity between different individuals, 
 through which it might be possible to effect a 
 reconciliation between the rival ethical principles of 
 egoism and altruism. But the feeling of pleasure 
 is just the point where individualism is strongest, 
 and in regard to which mankind, instead of being an 
 organism in which each part but subserves the pur- 
 poses of the whole, must rather be regarded as a col- 
 
140 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 lection of competing and co-operating units. It is 
 true that the social factor in the individual life is 
 brought into scientific cognisance by the theory of 
 evolution. It shows the way in which his interests 
 and feelings depend upon others. And if, through 
 the influence of a political standpoint, or of some 
 intuition of reason, a universalistic ethics has been 
 already arrived at, it can bring forward the organic 
 union of individual and society as a means of en- 
 forcing the social end upon the individual agent. 
 Theory of In this way the theory of evolution makes a 
 
 obligation ., . ,, . .. . 
 
 simplified, contribution to ethics at a critical point where 
 istJce V nT al " the individualist theory failed. For ethics must 
 arrived at. no res t content with pointing out an end for con- 
 duct or standard of morality, without giving a 
 reason to the individual why he should make this 
 end his own that is, developing a doctrine of obli- 
 gation. In many current theories, notably in the 
 common forms of utilitarianism, the two things are 
 not necessarily connected, since the standard is 
 fixed from the point of view of the whole, and obli- 
 gation has reference to the individual. The devel- 
 opment of morality may appear to show how the 
 two standpoints can be connected. If it could be 
 made out that the happiness of the community and 
 of the individual are identical, a standard of moral- 
 ity which made the aggregate happiness the end 
 might be regarded as carrying its own obligation 
 within itself: politics and ethics would (on the 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEOKIES. 141 
 
 hedonistic theory) be harmonised. And, in so far 
 as evolution has brought the individual and society 
 into closer reciprocal dependence, it has lessened 
 the practical difficulty of bringing about this con- 
 ciliation, or to speak with the utilitarians of 
 making the standard of morality supply a doctrine 
 of obligation. At present, however, the course of 
 human development is far from having reached the 
 point at which actual harmony between the race 
 and each member of it is established ; and it would 
 therefore still be a subject for inquiry whether the 
 theory of evolution could provide a basis for moral 
 obligation, even were the moral standard or the end 
 for conduct satisfactorily established. But, in deter- 
 mining this latter question, we find that the above 
 psychological and sociological investigations have 
 no longer the same degree of value as before. In 
 the theory of obligation, every fact brought for- 
 ward by evolution to show the harmony of indi- 
 vidual and social welfare makes the way easier 
 for establishing the reasonableness of the pursuit 
 of social ends by the individual. But from these 
 facts of past development we have also to deter- 
 mine an end for present and future action. And 
 this question cannot be solved merely by showing 
 how morality has developed, though that develop- 
 ment may form an important part of the evidence 
 from which our conclusions are to be drawn. 
 
 The harmony of interests and the harmony of oo Limits to 
 
142 THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 complete feelings required for the empirical reconciliation 
 of egoism of egoism and altruism is a condition which needs 
 and aitm- on jy to ^ Q s t a ted to show how far it is from being 
 
 ism : J 
 
 realised in present circumstances. The constant 
 struggle involved in the course of evolution throws 
 doubt even on its ultimate attainment. The rule 
 has always been that the better-equipped organism 
 asserts and maintains its supremacy only by van- 
 quishing the organisms which are not so well 
 (a) con- equipped. Conflict and competition have been 
 ence of com" constant f actors in development. The present cir- 
 petition; cumstances of the individual have been deter- 
 mined for him by the war of hostile interests 
 between different communities, and between differ- 
 ent members of the same community; and his 
 mental inheritance has been largely formed by the 
 emotions corresponding to this rivalry. Perhaps 
 the necessity for conflict has diminished with the 
 advance of evolution; but it is still sufficiently 
 great to make competition one of the chief forma- 
 tive influences in industrial and political life. And 
 the causes from which the struggle of interests arises 
 are so constant the multiplication of desires and 
 of desiring individuals keeps so well in advance of 
 the means of satisfying desires that it is doubtful 
 whether the course of evolution is fitted to bring 
 about complete harmony between different individ- 
 uals. It would almost seem that the " moving 
 equilibrium " in human conduct, in which there is 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 143 
 
 no clash of diverse interests, cannot be expected to 
 be brought about much before the time when the 
 physical factors of the universe have reached the 
 stage in which evolution ends. 
 
 Besides, it does not do to speak as if the only 03) different 
 
 and conflict- 
 alternative to egoism were a comprehensive altru- ing degrees 
 
 ism. Man is a member of a family, a tribe, a Ol 
 nation, the race. His altruism, therefore, may take 
 the narrow form of family feeling, or it may extend 
 to tribal feeling, or to patriotism, or even rise to 
 devotion to humanity. And these do not merely 
 supplement one another : they are often conflicting 
 principles of conduct. Action for the sake of the 
 family may frequently be most unsocial ; the keen 
 patriot ignores the rights of other peoples ; the 
 " citizen of the world " is too often a stranger 
 to the national spirit. Further, when civilisation 
 grows complex, the same man is a member of many 
 intersecting societies a church, a trade, a party 
 organisation l and has to balance the claims which 
 each of these has upon him. The sublation of 
 egoism would still leave to be determined the 
 different shares which these various social wholes 
 have in a man's sympathies, and their different 
 claims upon his conduct. 
 
 Any theory of society will show how the good ( y ) the aitm- 
 of the individual is not merely a part of the good estandthe* 
 of the whole, but reacts in various ways upon the ^ of 
 
 1 Cf. Stephen, Science of Ethics, p. 113. 
 
144 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 organism of which he is a member. But, in the 
 case of any one individual, the results of acts done 
 for his own good (or pleasure), and the results 
 of those done for the good (or pleasure) of the 
 whole, do not correspond with any exactness, and 
 often widely diverge. If, then, the individual is 
 consciously aiming at his own good (or pleasure), 
 it is if we look from the point of view of indi- 
 vidualistic ethics only an incidental and fortui- 
 tous result of the action when it promotes the 
 common good. When we recognise the social factor 
 in the individual, this judgment must be modified. 
 The evolution-theory shows how he has become 
 so constituted that much that pleases him indi- 
 vidually, must of necessity benefit society at large. 
 But there are obvious limits to the harmony. The 
 pleasure or interest of the individual is often the 
 reverse of advantageous to society. It may be 
 the case that in seeking his own private ends, he 
 is yet, to use the words of Adam Smith, " led by 
 an invisible hand to promote an end which was 
 no part of his intention/' 1 But, if so, the end 
 is invisible as well as the hand that points to it. 
 And the good of society can be said to be the 
 natural and uniform consequence of the individ- 
 ual's action, only when he consciously makes it 
 his end. In a word, the true altruism or, as we 
 might call it, using a word appropriated to another 
 
 1 Wealth of Nations, book iv. ch. ii. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 145 
 
 purpose the true socialism is when the good of 
 others or of society is pursued for its own sake ; 
 and this is to be distinguished from the false or 
 imperfect altruism, in which the same outward 
 result is aimed at, because it is seen to be the 
 most prudent way of promoting one's own good. 
 Thus Mr Spencer's elaborate argument 1 to show 
 that conduct of purely egoistic tendency, equally 
 with conduct of purely altruistic tendency, is in- 
 sufficient and self-destructive, does not reach be- 
 yond the external results of action, and leaves 
 it possible for both end and motive to be still 
 egoistic. If "morality is internal/' 2 the discus- 
 sion proves no ethical proposition at all. The 
 egoism of external prudence may indeed be tran- 
 scended by recognising that the pleasures and 
 pains of others are sources of sympathetic feel- 
 ing in ourselves. But a subjective or emotional 
 egoism remains. And if the fact that we " receive 
 pleasure from the pleasure of another man " 3 is 
 our reason for seeking his pleasure, we shall cease 
 to seek it when a means of greater pleasure offers. 
 In human life as at present constituted, no secure 
 principle of conduct can be based on the agree- 
 ment of individual with social good ; for, if they 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, chap. xiii. 
 
 2 Stephen, Science of Ethics, p. 155 ; cf. Spencer, Data of 
 Ethics, p. 120. 
 
 3 Stephen, Science of Ethics, p. 226. 
 
 K 
 
146 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 diverge, as they often do, there is no standard left 
 for determining their competing claims. 
 ) altruistic It will not do to divide all men, as Mr Stephen 
 eakf 8 seems to do, 1 into two classes, typified by the 
 reasonable and therefore sympathetic man who 
 has struck a bargain with society to take " common 
 stock of pains and pleasures," and the systematic- 
 ally selfish man who " must be an idiot." For most 
 men belong to neither of those two classes : their 
 bargain with society has not been fully completed, 
 and can be withdrawn ' from temporarily when 
 circumstances make withdrawal convenient, though 
 this process cannot be carried on indefinitely with- 
 out greatly weakening the sympathetic feelings. 
 The majority of men are neither entirely sympa- 
 thetic nor yet "systematically selfish": they are 
 unsystematically sympathetic and unsystematically 
 selfish. Such men have the sensibilities that give 
 "leverage" to the moralist. 2 But it is futile to 
 tell them to be more sympathetic, or entirely sym- 
 pathetic. For sympathetic feelings cannot be pro- 
 duced at will : they can only come with that slow 
 modification of the character brought about by 
 conduct. Shall we then say that a man should 
 in all cases of conduct prefer the pleasure of the 
 whole or of others to his own pleasure ? If a man 
 were to do so, then perhaps, by consistent self- 
 abnegation, altruism might become pleasant, and 
 
 1 Science of Ethics, p. 263. 2 Cf. Ibid., p. 442. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 147 
 
 both the man himself and his descendants become 
 more sympathetically constituted ? This perfection 
 of altruistic sympathies is looked forward to by 
 Mr Spencer as characteristic of a subsequent 
 the final stage of evolution. When that period 
 comes, men will compete with one another for the 
 few remaining opportunities of self-sacrifice. 1 At 
 present, Mr Spencer argues, pure altruism is suicidal. 
 The individual whose sympathetic nature is un- 
 developed may, however, go further, and ask what 
 right we have to say that "the moral law" is 
 " conformity to the conditions of social welfare," 2 
 rather than to those of individual welfare ? Evo- 
 lution, it would seem, does not suffice to prove 
 this proposition, which appears, on the contrary, to 
 be a survival of the social or political way of look- 
 ing at things inherited from the utilitarian theory. 
 But the point to be proved is why I ought to adopt 
 this standpoint when considering what the end of 
 my action is to be. And this point stands in need 
 of proof here as much as in utilitarianism, and 
 seems almost equally destitute of it. 
 
 Feelings leading to altruistic conduct are un- and may be 
 doubtedly possessed by the average man at his b^reflTc- 
 present stage of development. Yet the being who tlou> 
 is able to reflect on the feelings possessed by him, 
 and compare the characteristics of different emo- 
 tional states, and the activities following from 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, p. 253. 2 Science of Ethics, p. 349. 
 
148 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION". 
 
 them, has already before him the possibility of 
 
 transcending them. He is able to estimate their 
 
 value in terms of simpler or of other feelings; 
 
 and the man who rigorously does so by the test of 
 
 personal pleasure and pain manifests the spirit of 
 
 the egoistic hedonist a spirit which the theory of 
 
 empirical evolution does not seem able to exorcise. 
 
 ( c ) Tendency At the same time the tendency of the evolution- 
 
 to supplant theory is not to support but to supplant egoism. 
 
 egoism Neither the basis of psychological hedonism on 
 
 Evolution r J 
 
 not the basis which egoism is usually made to rest, nor the 
 
 of psycholo- 
 gical hedon- independent arguments which have been urged 
 
 for its ethical theory, are drawn from the facts of 
 development. The theory of evolution may, in- 
 deed, be made to suggest that non-hedonistic action 
 has arisen out of hedonistic: "That all affections 
 are generated by association with experienced 
 pleasure only that the association is mainly an- 
 cestral in the case of c affections ' proper. The 
 dim remembrance of ancestral pleasures, the force 
 of ancestral habit, produces that propension of 
 which Butler speaks, disproportionate to (distinct) 
 expectation and (personal) experience of pleasure." l 
 But this view will be rejected by the pure egoist, 2 
 who must maintain that the pain of acting con- 
 trary to ancestral habit would in every case be 
 
 1 F. Y. Edgeworth, Old and New Methods of Ethics (1877), 
 p. 11. 
 
 2 Cf. A. Barratt, Mind, iii. 280. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 149 
 
 greater than the expected pleasure foregone by 
 following it. According to the view suggested, 
 all deliberate volition would still be regarded as 
 hedonistically determined, though other motives 
 than pleasure may affect action through having 
 been inherited from cases of ancestral conduct in 
 which they tended to personal pleasure. Even 
 were it shown, however, that altruistic conduct has 
 been developed out of egoistic, the fact of its devel- 
 opment would not alter its present characteristic. 
 If action now is not always moved by pleasure 
 and pain alone, it becomes a question of merely 
 historical interest to trace its genesis to conduct 
 to which our ancestors were hedonistically im- 
 pelled. The fact remains that the original sim- 
 plicity of motive has been broken into, and some- 
 thing else than personal pleasure admitted to have 
 sway. But it does not seem to have been made 
 out that action in the early stages of human life 
 was completely egoistic, any more than that it is 
 so now. " From first to last," as Mr Spencer puts 
 it, 1 self-sacrifice seems to have been involved in 
 the preservation of each successive generation of 
 individuals. We inherit propensities to action 
 which have been evolved from an initial stage in 
 which there was no conscious distinction between 
 egoism and altruism, though both tendencies were 
 present and were necessary for the continued exist- 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, chap. xii. 
 
150 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 ence of the species. The feelings inherited by the 
 egoistic hedonist are assessed by him at their pleas- 
 ure-value. But such feelings would never have been 
 acquired by his ancestors, had they tested each ger- 
 minal emotion in the same way, and so restrained 
 self-sacrifice for offspring and fellow-men. Perhaps 
 they did not clearly see or realise what their pleas- 
 ure consisted in, or accurately distinguish it from 
 family or tribal welfare ; but, through this defi- 
 ciency of imagination, the feelings were able to 
 grow and perpetuate themselves, which have tended 
 to the preservation and consolidation of society, 
 nor of Nor can we gather from evolution any ethical 
 
 htd'onism. argument leading to egoism as the principle or end 
 for conduct; and it is worthy of remark that the 
 proof attempted by the late Mr Barratt is un- 
 affected by his recognition of the theory of evolu- 
 tion as applied to mind, depending on definitions 
 and axioms which hold (if at all) for the individual 
 man. Pleasure is defined by him as "that state 
 of consciousness which follows upon the unimpeded 
 performance (as such) of its function by one or 
 more of the parts of our organism ; " 1 and the 
 good is forthwith identified with pleasure, by its 
 being shown that it is a " state of consciousness," 
 and that it " results from the due performance of 
 function (as such)." 2 But the " due 3 performance 
 
 1 Physical Ethics, p. 12. 2 Ibid., p. 17. 
 
 3 In the word " due" an idea of worth is involved. Probably 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 151 
 
 of function " is itself a state or states of conscious- 
 ness ; and in it, not in any sequent or concomitant 
 circumstances, the good may consist. The good, 
 we may say, is not pleasure, but the evepyaa of 
 which pleasure is only the consequent or comple- 
 tion. This is not a mere question of words. For 
 " due performance of function " cannot be measured 
 by the resultant or accompanying feeling of pleas- 
 ure : the most perfect functioning, just because it 
 has become habitual, has often the slightest accom- 
 paniment of pleasant feeling. The way in which 
 the argument is put in ' Physical Ethics ' is thus 
 well fitted to bring out the fundamental antithesis 
 between ethical systems according as they place 
 the good in the active element of function, or in 
 the passive element of pleasurable feeling which 
 accompanies functioning. The theory of evolution 
 seems to have led many of the writers who have 
 applied it to ethics to the other side of the anti- 
 thesis than that adhered to by Mr Barratt. They 
 recognise ethical value as belonging to a due per- 
 formance of function," rather than to the pleased 
 states of consciousness which follow ; and in this 
 way their theory leads them beyond hedonistic ethics. 1 
 
 Mr Barratt meant by "due performance" one which made the 
 faculty correspond with its medium (cf. Physical Ethics, p. 9) ; 
 but this introduces a new standard of value. 
 
 1 The transition involved in passing from " pleasure " to " per- 
 formance of function" or "life" as the end of conduct, may be 
 illustrated by the following passage from Mr Pater's 'Marius 
 
anism 
 
 152 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 3. Bearing It has been argued that the theory of evolution 
 
 ofthetheory . . , ., ., ... . . , 
 
 of evolution 1S > in tendency, hostile to the egoistic principle. 
 Had egoism been consistently recognised and acted 
 upon during the course of human development, the 
 features of social life which most promote co- 
 operation and progress would never have become 
 persistent. But the same objection cannot be 
 urged against universalistic hedonism. It is true 
 that this has not been the end consistently aimed 
 at in the past. Those from whom our social 
 instincts are inherited cannot be credited with 
 having had either the general happiness or social 
 evolution in view. Society and institutions further- 
 ing the common good were not the work of primitive 
 utilitarians plotting for the greatest happiness of 
 the greatest number. They have come down to 
 
 the Epicurean' (1885, i. 163): "Really, to the phase of reflec- 
 tion through which Marius was then passing, the charge of 
 ( hedonism/ whatever its real weight might be, was not properly 
 applicable at all. Not pleasure, but fulness of life, and ' insight ' 
 as conducting to that fulness energy, choice and variety of 
 experience including noble pain and sorrow even loves such as 
 those in the exquisite old story of Apuleius ; such sincere and 
 strenuous forms of the moral life, as Seneca and Epictetus 
 whatever form of human life, in short, was impassioned and 
 ideal: it was from this that the 'new Cyrenaicism' of Marius 
 took its criterion of values. It was a theory, indeed, which 
 might rightly be regarded as in a great degree coincident with 
 the main principle of the Stoics themselves, and a version of the 
 precept ' Whatsoever thy hand findeth to do, do it with all thy 
 might ' a doctrine so widely applicable among the nobler spirits 
 of that time ; and as with that its mistaken tendency would lie 
 in the direction of a kind of idolatry of mere life, or natural gift 
 or strength Vidoldtrie des talents." 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 153 
 
 us from times when social organisation was forced 
 upon men by the rude logic of facts which exter- 
 minated tribes in which the bond of union was 
 weak; and they have been gradually modified by 
 the pressure of external circumstances and the 
 growing influence of mental conceptions of what 
 is best. But the adoption of general happiness as 
 the end of action would not have had the same 
 effect on social evolution, as the adoption of per- 
 sonal happiness as the end would have had. It 
 would have aided and not have hindered the growth 
 of the feeling of unity among the members of a 
 tribe or state, as well as have led to the recogni- 
 tion of the individual as subordinate to the social 
 organism. It may thus seem quite natural to look 
 to utilitarianism as giving the end for reflective 
 action, and yet to hold along with it what is loosely 
 called the ethics of evolution. 
 
 But this first attitude of evolution to utilitarian- has led to 
 ism was not fitted to be permanent ; and the catton 1 
 " start " l Mr Spencer got on being classed with 
 anti-utilitarians must have been repeated in the 
 experience of other moralists as they found them- 
 selves drifting from their ancient moorings. Mr 
 Spencer's difference from the utilitarians is not 
 such as to lead him to reject or modify their 
 
 1 " The note in question greatly startled me by implicitly class- 
 ing me with anti-utilitarians. I have never regarded myself as an 
 anti-utilitarian." Mr Spencer's letter to J. S. Mill, printed in 
 Bain's Mental and Moral Science, p. 721. 
 
154 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 principle. He maintains, as strongly as they do, 
 that " the ultimately supreme end " is " happiness 
 special and general." l But he disagrees with them 
 in method, in method, holding that, owing to the incommen- 
 surability of a man's different pleasures and pains, 
 and to the incommensurability of the pleasures and 
 pains of one man with those of others, coupled with 
 the indeterminateness of the means required to 
 reach so indeterminate an end, happiness is not 
 fitted to be the immediate aim of conduct. 2 But 
 another method is open to us. For " since evolu- 
 tion has been, and is still, working towards the 
 highest life, it follows that conforming to those 
 principles by which the highest life is achieved, is 
 furthering that end." 3 It is possible " to deduce, 
 from the laws of life and the conditions of exist- 
 ence, what kinds of action necessarily tend to pro- 
 duce happiness, and what kinds to produce un- 
 happiness." 4 Greatest pleasure, that is to say, is 
 the end. But it is so impossible to compare dif- 
 ferent kinds of pleasure, different people's pleasure, 
 and different means for obtaining a maximum of it, 
 that it is not a practical end for aiming at. No 
 doubt is expressed that greatest happiness is the 
 ultimate end; although no good reason is given 
 for holding that it is. But it is an indeterminate 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, p. 173 ; cf. p. 30. 
 
 2 Ibid., pp. 154, 155. 3 Ibid>? p< 171 
 4 Letter to J. S. Mill, in Data of Ethics, p. 57. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 155 
 
 end, and needs to be interpreted by the course of 
 evolution which is held to tend to it. It is not 
 too much to say, therefore, that Mr Spencer is only 
 nominally a utilitarian. His ethical principles are 
 not arrived at by an estimate of the consequences 
 of action, but by deduction from the laws of that 
 " highest life " which is now in process of evolu- 
 tion. This alliance between evolutionism and hed- 
 onism will be examined in the following chapter. 
 At present it is necessary to consider the reasons 
 which have led other evolutionists to look upon 
 the new morality as superseding the utilitarian 
 end. 
 
 Mr Spencer's " dissent from the doctrine of 
 utility, as commonly understood, concerns," he tells 
 us, 1 " not the object to be reached by men, but the 
 method of reaching it." In other writers, however, 
 the theory of evolution has not only supplanted 
 the method of utilitarianism, but also led to a 
 modification of its principle. The objections they andm 
 have taken to it may perhaps be summed up by pl 
 saying that they consider utilitarianism to look 
 upon conduct from a mechanical, instead of from 
 an organic point of view. It prescribed conduct 
 to a man as if he were a machine with a certain 
 kind and quantity of work to turn out. His nature 
 was looked upon by it as fixed, and his social con- 
 
 1 Letter to J. S. Mill, in Bain's Mental and Moral Science, p. 
 721. 
 
156 THE TIIEOEY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 (a) ideal of ditioHS as unvarying ; and the ideal set before him 
 ism objected was therefore unprogressive something that he 
 gressive Pr " was to ^ or to g et > not something that he was 
 to become. " If consistently applied," it has been 
 recently argued, " utilitarianism seems irrevocably 
 committed to a stereotyped and unprogressive 
 ideal." l According to Mr Stephen, it " considers 
 society to be formed of an aggregate of similar 
 human beings. The character of each molecule 
 is regarded as constant." It can, therefore, give 
 a test which is " approximately accurate " only, 
 which does not allow for the variation of character 
 and of social relations. 2 - To the same effect Miss 
 Simcox maintains that it "might pass muster in 
 a theory of social statics, but it breaks down alto- 
 gether if we seek its help to construct a theory of 
 social dynamics/' 3 These writers do not seem to 
 have made it quite clear, however, in what way 
 utilitarianism assumes a stationary condition of 
 human nature, and so formulates conduct in a 
 way unsuited to a progressive state. To say simply 
 that the greatest happiness of the greatest number 
 is the end, is not in itself inconsistent with a pro- 
 gressive state of human nature. It is true that, in 
 all the enthusiasm for and belief in progress to be 
 seen in a writer such as J. S. Mill, there is a con- 
 
 1 J. T. Punnet, "Ethical Alternatives" Mind, x. 95. 
 
 2 Science of Ethics, p. 363. 
 
 3 Natural Law ; An Essay in Ethics (1877), p. 101. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 157 
 
 stant goal always set to it in the possible maximum 
 of pleasant feeling. It would not have been incon- 
 sistent for him, however, to look upon human 
 nature as capable of developing new susceptibili- 
 ties for pleasure. Progress is made by increasing 
 the amount of pleasure actually got. And so far, 
 the ideal itself is certainly fixed, while progress 
 consists in its gradual realisation. But there is 
 no special virtue in having an ideal which is itself 
 progressive. A progressive ideal simply means an 
 ideal which is incompletely comprehended, and the 
 comprehension of which proceeds gradually with 
 its realisation. At any time the definition of such 
 an ideal can only be tentative: with the actual 
 assimilation of character to it, the intellect comes 
 to grasp its nature with increasing clearness. I 
 do not myself think that we can expect to have 
 more than such a tentative and progressive com- 
 prehension of the moral ideal of humanity. But 
 we must not take objection to a theory because 
 it gives at once a clear and definite view of the 
 final end of conduct : though we must not refrain 
 from inquiring how the end is known. 
 
 But the bearing of the objection to utilitarianism Force of the 
 becomes apparent when we try to give some definite ^en 1 
 meaning to the end greatest happiness. If we are 
 
 101 
 
 content to receive it as simply a very general or interpret 
 
 greatest 
 
 rather abstract expression for our ideal, nothing happiness, 
 need be said, except to put the question, which has 
 
158 THE THEOEY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 been already asked, How we came by such an ideal ? 
 
 The difficulty arises when we attempt to apply the 
 
 by showing ideal to practice. With men of fixed character in 
 
 the way in . . , 
 
 which men an unchanging society, our way might be compara- 
 tively clear. But, when both character and social 
 relations vary, and their variation extends to sus- 
 ceptibility to pleasure and pain, and depends on the 
 actions adopted to obtain the end, utilitarianism 
 may well appear to be without a principle by which 
 to determine between different kinds of conduct. 
 To an objection similar to this, but taken from the 
 old point of view, that we have no time before acting 
 to sum up the pleasurable and painful consequences 
 of our actions, Mill replied that there had been 
 " ample time namely, the whole past duration of 
 the human species " l in which to estimate the f eli- 
 cific results of conduct. The variability of faculty 
 and function makes this answer lack convincing 
 power. Yet, perhaps, we are apt at present to dis- 
 regard the real value of this collective experience of 
 the race. True, human nature is not a constant ; 
 yet certain of its qualities are persistent and con- 
 stant enough not to leave us in doubt as to whether, 
 say, murder and theft are beneficial or injurious 
 to happiness. There are at least certain actions, 
 and, still more, certain abstentions, upon which 
 human security the basis of happiness depends. 
 But it would seem that those " secondary laws " 
 
 1 Utilitarianism, p. 34. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 159 
 
 may be more properly regarded as conditions of life 
 than means to pleasure. 
 
 The difficulty, however, comes most clearly to andamax 
 the front when we attempt to define the maxi- m 
 mum, and that not for an indiyidual or genera- 
 tion only, but for the race. It/ is not happiness 
 merely, but greatest happiness, that is the utili- 
 tarian end. Is there any way, then, of deter- 
 mining how the maximum of happiness is to be 
 obtained for generations whose characters, though 
 inherited from present individuals, may be modified 
 almost indefinitely ? The very existence and num- 
 bers of these future generations are problematic ; and 
 Mill, as is well known, spent much of his energy 
 in trying to convince the present generation to re- 
 strict the numbers of the next. Even on the funda- 
 mental question as to whether happiness is to be 
 obtained by the restriction of desires or by the satis- 
 faction which leads to their recurrence and increase, 
 no principle can be extracted from utilitarian ethics. 
 The theory of evolution has shown how desires may 
 be uprooted in the character of the race, though 
 they remain to the end in the present individuals ; 
 but in each case utilitarianism would require us to 
 sum up and estimate the relative advantages of re- 
 nunciation and satisfaction, a problem which the 
 modifiability of human character seems to make 
 impracticable. Thus, even if certain rules of living 
 may be ascertained, and justified by the utilitarian 
 
160 
 
 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 (6) Objection 
 to utilitari- 
 anism as a 
 theory of 
 conse- 
 quences ; 
 
 principle, it would seem that the end of greatest 
 happiness for the race of man, or the sentient crea- 
 tion generally, must remain " abstract." There 
 seems no principle through which it may be ap- 
 plied to conduct no hope of an accurate esti- 
 mate of results when the variability of the 
 individual and of social relations is taken into 
 account. 
 
 Connected with this is the assertion that moral- 
 ity must have an inward, not an external standard. 
 The evolutionists are inclined to condemn utilitari- 
 anism as a theory of consequences, dealing solely 
 with work produced. According to Mill, " utili- 
 tarian moralists have gone beyond almost all others 
 in affirming that the motive has nothing to do with 
 the morality of the action, though much with the 
 worth of the agent/' l And this seems to be just 
 what evolutionism objects to. Even the worth of 
 the agent is, according to utilitarianism, only a 
 tendency to perform the actions called moral : " a 
 good or a bad disposition" is said to be "a bent 
 of character from which useful or from which hurt- 
 ful actions are likely to arise." 2 Against this view 
 Mr Stephen maintains that " the attempt to secure 
 an absolute and immutable moral law in its exter- 
 nal shape must be illusory. The moral law can be 
 stated unconditionally when it is stated in the form 
 ' Be this/ but not when it is stated in the form ' Do 
 
 1 Utilitarianism, p. 26. 2 Ibid., p. 27 n. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 161 
 
 this.' " l This, however, appears to express the matter 
 in a way not free from difficulty. The organic view 
 of conduct will object not only to considering action 
 apart from character, but also to considering char- 
 acter apart from action. We must treat conduct as 
 a whole : and, in order to do so, we must treat it as 
 both arising out of and forming character ; and we 
 must treat character not as mere potentiality, but 
 as it realises itself in conduct. The weakness of 
 the utilitarian theory is its method of treating 
 actions merely in respect of their results : the evo- 
 lutionist must show how results are connected with 
 motives, how character and conduct are different 
 aspects of a whole. 
 
 The difference of the evolutionist view from utili- (c) and as re- 
 tarianism comes out at another point. The latter to s 
 places the standard and test of conduct in its effects lty ' 
 on the sensibility. The best is that which brings 
 most pleasure. Utilitarians are now, for the most 
 part, ready to admit that, to be in earnest with their 
 theory, they must reject Mill's attempt to distin- 
 guish qualities among pleasures. " If morality is to 
 be defined by happiness, we must, of course, allow 
 all kinds of happiness to count, and to count equally 
 so far as they are actually equal. We must reckon 
 the pleasures of malevolence as well as those of 
 benevolence." 2 Of his own pleasures of the rela- 
 tive amounts of pleasure he gets from various sources 
 
 1 Stephen, Science of Ethics, p. 385. 2 Ibid., p. 361. 
 
 L 
 
162 
 
 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 of which 
 there is no 
 common 
 
 measure. 
 
 each man is the final judge. One man prefers 
 "push-pin" to poetry, another poetry to "push- 
 pin "; and neither has a right to call the other mis- 
 taken. If we are to aim at the greatest maximum 
 pleasure, therefore, we must not strive for what 
 are commonly called " high " pleasures rather than 
 " low " pleasures, except as greater in intensity. If 
 we must have a standard, the judgment of the <po- 
 VI/AOS for which Mill contended must be superseded 
 by the judgment of the average man. If pleasure 
 is the only end, and satisfaction is simply another 
 name for it, then it is plainly incorrect to say that 
 " it is better to be a human being dissatisfied than 
 a pig satisfied ; better to be Socrates dissatisfied 
 than a fool satisfied." 1 As has been urged from 
 the evolutionist point of view, " there is no common 
 measure of happiness to enable us to say that the 
 more perfect being enjoys more of it than the less." 2 
 There seems one way only in which utilitarianism 
 can bring its moral ideal into harmony with the 
 upward tendency claimed for itself by evolution- 
 ist ethics and that is, by maintaining that the 
 pleasures incident to what are regarded as the 
 higher functions are the pleasures which excel 
 others in respect of " fecundity " : they are the 
 source of future pleasures, and are frequently inex- 
 clusive even in their present enjoyment. The dif- 
 ficulty in making this assertion is just that these 
 
 1 Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 14. 2 Simcox, Natural Law, p. 101. 
 
EVOLUTION AND ETHICAL THEORIES. 163 
 
 " higher " pleasures are but slightly appreciated by 
 the majority of men, and can hardly be said to be 
 pleasures for them at all. But here the theory of 
 evolution, whose adherents have been acting the 
 part of the candid friend to utilitarianism, must 
 come to its aid, and admit that human nature may 
 be so modified in the future as to allow of the " high- 
 est " becoming also the " greatest " of pleasures. The 
 argument in the mouth of the utilitarian is perhaps 
 a somewhat arbitrary one, since it could be applied 
 equally well to any class of pleasures. The notion 
 of " higher," as applied either to conduct or to pleas- 
 ure, has been accepted from current moral opinion. 
 But the theory of evolution has set itself to explain 
 this notion, and to develop a theory of morality in 
 harmony with its own scientific positions, and free 
 from the defects which it has found in other sys- 
 tems. How far it contributes to the determination 
 of the ethical_end will form the subject of investi- 
 gation in the following chapters. 
 
164 
 
 CHAPTER VII. 
 
 HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 
 
 i. Alliance THE alliance between Evolutionism and Hedonism 
 
 tionlsm and may be arrived at from either of the two points of 
 
 effected v ^ ew which are being brought into connection : may 
 
 two ways : j^ either an attempt to bring the hedonistic end into 
 
 the definite region of law revealed by the evolution 
 
 of life ; or may result from the endeavour to give 
 
 clearness and persuasiveness to an ethical end which 
 
 evolution itself seems to point to. 
 
 (a) greatest The former point of view is represented in Mr 
 be P o?tSn S e d Spencer's rejection of empirical utilitarianism, and 
 L y g C to n iawT substitution for it of a practical end which is not 
 of life or of enunciated in terms of pleasure. Happiness is still 
 
 evolution ; 
 
 regarded by him as the supreme end ; but the tend- 
 ency to it is not to be adopted as the end in practical 
 morality. There are certain conditions to social 
 equilibrium which " must be fulfilled before complete 
 life that is, greatest happiness can be obtained in 
 any society." l Thus the form of " rational utilitari- 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, p. 171. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 165 
 
 anism " which he endeavours to establish " does not 
 take welfare for its immediate object of pursuit," 
 but " conformity to certain principles which, in the 
 nature of things, causally determine welfare." 1 Hav- 
 ing deduced " from the laws of life and the conditions 
 of existence what kinds of action necessarily tend 
 to produce happiness, and what kinds to produce 
 unhappiness," we are to recognise these deductions 
 "as laws of conduct . . . irrespective of a direct 
 estimation of happiness or misery." 2 The assump- 
 tion is thus distinctly made that the tendency of 
 life is to happiness, and that the laws of its evolu- 
 tion yield practical principles by following out which 
 the greatest happiness may be obtained, without 
 attempting the impossible task of estimating directly 
 the felicific and infelicific results of conduct. 
 
 Starting with the evolutionist point of view, but (&) ethical 
 with an opposite estimate of the relative value for evolution 
 practice of the ends supplied by evolutionism and 
 by hedonism, a like identification of them might 
 seem advisable. The "increase of life" to which 
 evolution tends may be regarded as not merely an 
 account of the actual process of existence, but as a 
 principle of action for a conscious being. In this 
 way some such ethical imperative as "Be a self- 
 conscious agent in the evolution of the universe " 3 
 may be formulated. Yet as the " evolution of the 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, p. 162. ' 2 Ibid., p. 57. 
 
 3 Cf. A. Barratt, in Mind, ii. 172 n. 
 
166 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 universe " is a somewhat large conception, and its 
 laws are not clear to every one, it may seem neces- 
 sary that the end should be explained by translation 
 into better-known terms. And this may .be done if 
 the conduct which promotes life most is, at the same 
 time, the conduct which increases pleasure most. In 
 this way, although the ultimate end is life, or, in 
 vaster phrase, " the evolution of the universe," the 
 practical end is pleasure. The moral value of con- 
 duct will depend on its tendency to increase the 
 balance of pleasure over pain. The ethics of evolu- 
 tion will be reduced to hedonism. 
 
 This way of determining the evolutionist end is 
 put forward as a logical possibility rather than as 
 representing the views of any party. The contri- 
 bution which the theory of evolution has to offer 
 towards the determination of the ethical end, has 
 not yet received that definite expression which 
 would justify our passing by any logical interpreta- 
 tion of it, on the ground of its not being actually 
 adopted by ethical writers. Yet it would seem that 
 the above point of view is not altogether foreign to 
 evolutionist morality. The preservation or develop- 
 ment of the individual or of the race which is 
 put forward as an expression both for the actual 
 course of evolution and the subjective impulse cor- 
 responding to it, is often assumed to agree at each 
 step with the desire for pleasure, and, when the 
 stage of reflective consciousness is reached, to be 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 167 
 
 identical with the pursuit of a maximum of pleasure. 1 
 In this way it is assumed that the preservation and 
 development of life tend always to pleasure, and 
 that the end or tendency of evolution is being ful- 
 filled when the greatest pleasure is wisely sought. 
 It is therefore necessary to inquire how far the 
 correspondence between life and pleasure, or between 
 development and pleasure, actually holds, that we 
 may see whether it is possible for the one to take 
 the place of the other in determining the end for 
 conduct. 
 
 Now it is argued, from the point of view of 2. 
 evolution, that, taking for granted that pleasure me 
 motives action, the organisms in which pleasurable 
 acts coincided with life-preserving or health-pro- and P leas - 
 moting acts must have survived in the struggle for 
 
 1 As illustrating this I may refer to G. v. Gizycki, Philosophische 
 Consequenzen der Lamarck-Darwin'schen Entwicklungstheorie 
 (1876), p. 27 : "Wir haben oben die Erhaltung und Forderuug 
 des Lebens des Individuums und der Gattung als das eine Ziel der 
 Einrichtung des geistigen Organismus gekennzeichnet." P. 58 : 
 "Auf das Streben nach in sich befriedigtem psychischen Leben 
 [that is to say, pleasure] sind alle animalen Organismen angelegt." 
 In his popular essay, 'Grundziige der Moral' (1883), Dr Gizycki' s 
 principle and method are utilitarian. With the above may be 
 compared Guyau, Esquisse d'une morale sans obligation ni sanction 
 (1885), p. 15 : " L'action sort naturellement du fonctionnement de 
 la vie, en grande partie inconscient ; elle entre aussitot dans le 
 doinaine de la conscience et de la jouissance, mais elle n'en vient 
 pas. La tendance de 1'etre a perse' ve'rer dans 1'etre est le fond de 
 tout de'sir sans constituer elle-meme un de'sir determine'." 
 
168 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 existence at the expense of those organisms whose 
 pleasurable activity tended to their destruction or 
 to the hindrance of their efficiency. 1 The assump- 
 tion in this argument, in addition to the constant 
 postulate of natural selection, is simply that pleas- 
 ure is a chief motive of action ; the conclusion to 
 which it leads is, that there is a broad correspond- 
 ence between life-preserving and pleasurable acts 
 that the preservation and development of life are 
 pleasurable. It is necessary to examine with care 
 the validity of this important argument with refer- 
 ence to the attacks that may be made on it from 
 the pessimist point of view ; and, if its doctrine 
 of the correspondence of life and pleasure is not 
 entirely erroneous, to inquire further whether this 
 correspondence can be made to establish an end for 
 conduct, in accordance with the theory of evolution, 
 by measuring life in terms of pleasure, 
 objec- What then is to be said of the supposed " conflict 
 between Eudaemonism [Hedonism] and Evolution- 
 ism " which v. Hartmann 2 opposes to the optimist 
 doctrine that evolution has tended to make life and 
 pleasure coincide ? 
 
 1 Spencer, Data of Ethics, p. 82 f ; Principles of Psychology, 
 125, 3d ed., i. 280 ; Stephen, Science of Ethics, p. 83. The 
 simplicity of this argument will be appreciated if we consider 
 the difficulty Comte experienced in trying to reach a similar con- 
 clusion. See Positive Philosophy, Miss Martineau's translation, 
 ii. 87 ff. 
 
 2 Cf. Phanomenologie des sittlichen Bewusstseins, pp. 701, 
 708. 
 
* 
 
 HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 169 
 
 The problem of Pessimism resolves itself into 
 two questions which admit of being kept distinct : 
 
 (a) The first is, Does life on the whole give, or can 
 it give, a balance of pleasure ? This is the funda- 
 mental question of the value of life as put by those, 
 whether optimists or pessimists, who assume that 
 " value " means " pleasure-value." If it be answered 
 in the negative, the hedonistic ideal must be the re- 
 duction of the adverse balance to the zero-point of 
 feeling striven after by Eastern ascetics, but, to all 
 appearance, obtained only and most easily by death. 1 
 
 (b) The second question is, Does the evolution of life 
 lead to an increase of pleasure and diminution of 
 pain ? This is the question brought into promin- 
 ence in recent discussions, and of most importance 
 for the present inquiry; and upon an affirmative 
 answer to it Evolutionist Hedonism is plainly de- 
 pendent. To both questions v. Hartmann gives an 
 answer in the negative. 
 
 (a) If the pessimist view of life is correct, Mr (a) that life 
 Spencer holds, 2 then " the ending of an undesirable 
 existence being the thing to be wished, that which 
 causes the ending of it must be applauded." And 
 this is so far true, though not necessarily true in 
 the way Mr Spencer thinks. Eor this undesirable 
 existence cannot, perhaps, be brought to a final con- 
 clusion merely by ending the individual life : this 
 
 1 Cf. Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, 3d ed., p. 127. 
 
 2 Data of Ethics, p. 26. 
 
170 THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 would only leave room for other individuals to fill 
 the vacant places. Annihilation is the end not 
 directly for the individual, but for the race. Not 
 life itself, according to Schopenhauer, but the will 
 to live, is to be killed in the individual man. Even 
 this code of morals, Hartmann thinks, is a remnant 
 of the false, pre - evolutionist individualism, and 
 would hinder the course of the universe, by leaving 
 the game to be played out by the remaining indi- 
 viduals whose wills were not strong enough to curb 
 or kill themselves. It is a mistake to think that 
 the will to live which pulses through all existence 
 can be annihilated by the phenomenal individual. 
 The individual's duty is not to seek for himself the 
 painlessness of annihilation or passionless Nirwana, 
 but to join in the ceaseless painful striving of 
 nature, and, by contributing to the development of 
 life, to hasten its arrival once more at the goal of 
 unconsciousness. The self-destruction, not of the 
 individual will, but of the cosmic or universal will, 
 is the final end of action. 
 
 Apart from the metaphysical view of things with 
 which this estimate of the value of life is connected, 
 and which may be regarded perhaps as its conse- 
 quent rather than its cause, 1 the pessimist doctrine 
 has a double foundation, in psychology and in the 
 facts of life. 
 
 1 Cf. Vaihinger, Hartmann, Diihring und Lange (1876), p. 
 124. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 171 
 
 Psychologically, it seems to be best supported ( a ) from the 
 by Schopenhauer's doctrine of will or desire as an nature^ 
 incessant painful striving, pleasure being merely P leasure 
 the negative of this pain, and always coming short 
 of completely satisfying it. But this position in- 
 volves a double error in psychological analysis, and 
 is relinquished even by Hartmarm, though he still 
 regards pleasure as in all cases satisfaction of desire. 
 Desire is itself merely a secondary or derived fact 
 in human nature, consequent on the inhibition of 
 volitional energy. 1 The pleasures we call passive 
 are independent of it ; and those which attend upon 
 activity, but are not themselves part of the end of 
 action, are also enjoyed without being striven after 
 in order to satisfy a want. Further, it is a mistake 
 to look upon the pleasure of attainment as a mere 
 negation of the pain of desire. The painful element 
 in desire comes from the inhibition of the attempted 
 realisation of an ideal object. In unsatisfied de- 
 sires, it is true, the pain is in proportion to the 
 strength of the restrained longing. But, if the 
 inhibition is overcome, the pain is not equal to the 
 strength of the desire, but only to the amount of 
 opposition that has to be conquered in satisfying 
 it. Hence, not only are there other pleasures than 
 those of satisfied desire, but even the pleasure got 
 from such satisfaction is something more than a mere 
 recompense for the pain accompanying the desire. 
 
 1 Cf. Sully, Pessimism, p. 216. 
 
172 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 0> from the The support got by pessimism from the facts of 
 man 8 life ; U human life is more difficult to estimate at its true 
 value. It is obvious that pleasure and pain are 
 intermingled in almost every experience ; and the 
 proportion in which they are mixed varies greatly 
 in different circumstances and according to the 
 susceptibilities of different persons. If we ask a 
 number of people whether life is on the whole 
 pleasant to them, not only do we receive a variety 
 of answers which it is hard to sum up and average, 
 but the answers we get are apt to reflect the feeling 
 of the moment rather than to represent an impartial 
 estimate of the pleasure and pain of a lifetime. 
 Thus experience seems unable to give us a trust- 
 worthy answer as to the average pleasure-value of 
 life ; but, if its verdict is correct, that to some life 
 is pleasant, though to many painful, this shows 
 that a surplus of pain does not follow from the 
 nature of life, and thus destroys the position of 
 thoroughgoing pessimism, which looks upon this as 
 the worst of all possible worlds. 
 
 (&) that the (&) It may still be maintained, however and 
 t this is the position which chiefly concerns us here 
 
 tend to that the course of evolution does not tend to in- 
 
 pleasure. 
 
 crease the pleasure in life at the expense of the pain 
 in it, and that, therefore, even although pleasure and 
 evolution may both of them be possible ends of con- 
 duct, they are ends which point in different direc- 
 tions and lead to different courses of action. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 173 
 
 It is necessary for the evolutionist who holds (a) incom- 
 that the development of life does not tend to theevoiu- 
 increased pleasure, to meet the argument already j^f argu " 
 adduced l to show their correspondence. Nor does 
 that argument seem to be altogether beyond criti- 
 cism. To compare progress or development with 
 pleasure, we ought to know exactly what is meant 
 by both terms. Yet it is impossible to have a clear 
 notion of progress without an idea of the end to 
 which it tends, and this has not yet been obtained. 
 It is largely on account of the difficulty of ob- 
 taining such an idea that some evolutionists seem 
 to have been driven to measure progress in terms 
 of pleasure, just as, owing to the difficulty of esti- 
 mating and summing up pleasures, some hedonists 
 have been induced to measure them by the progress 
 of evolution. What we have now to see is whether 
 the correspondence assumed between progress and 
 pleasure actually exists. And, to avoid the tauto- 
 logy of saying that progress is increase of life, we 
 must judge of it simply by empirical observation of 
 the nature of human activity and of the course of 
 human affairs. 
 
 Now the attempted identification of pleasurable 
 and life-promoting activities rests on an incomplete 
 account of the motives and results of action. For, 
 in the first place, even admitting that pleasure and 
 avoidance of pain are the only motives to action, 
 
 1 See above, p. 167 f. 
 
174 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 the influence of natural selection has not prevented 
 actions hurtful to life being sometimes accom- 
 panied by pleasant sensations. Its tendency to do 
 so has been much more effective in the lower 
 orders of animal life than in the higher. The 
 latter, especially man, possess the power of repre- 
 senting ideal states in the imagination, and are 
 thus able to avoid actions hurtful to life, although 
 these actions are pleasant at the time. For the 
 hurtful consequences - of the action may be so 
 vividly represented in idea as to outweigh the in- 
 fluence of the present pleasure which could be got 
 from its enjoyment. 1 
 
 And further, the analysis of volition involved in 
 the argument seems to be insufficient. For there 
 are other springs of action to be taken account 
 of than pleasure and its opposite. Habit, imita- 
 tion, and interests of a more comprehensive kind 
 than desire of pleasant feeling, are all motives to 
 action. It is true that pleasure is always felt in 
 the successful performance of an action, and it is 
 also true that the inhibition of will is always 
 painful ; but it is none the less incorrect to look 
 either upon the pleasure that follows from the 
 action, or the pain that would be the result of its 
 inhibition as, in ordinary cases, the motive. It is 
 motives of a different kind than pleasure, such as 
 
 1 Cf. Fiske, Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy (1874), ii. 
 332 f. 
 
 

 HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 175 
 
 imitation 1 and the influence of ideal ends, which 
 most often lead to progress. And the progress 
 that is due to such motives cannot be measured 
 by its effect in increasing pleasure, nor assumed to 
 make pleasure and life correspond. Other activ- 
 ities less advantageous in nature in all respects 
 but this, might, so far as the reasoning goes, lead 
 to equal or to more pleasurable consequences. At 
 the best, therefore, the above argument only proves 
 a general tendency towards the coincidence of 
 pleasurable actions with actions which promote 
 life ; it does not show that the increase of life 
 can be accurately measured by pleasure. The pro- 
 cess of natural selection might kill off all organisms 
 whose desires led them normally to action hurtful' 
 to life. But sufficient evidence has not been 
 brought forward to show that it is fitted to pro- 
 duce an exact proportion between progress and 
 pleasure. 
 
 Hartmann, however, attempts to strike a more OB) The pes- 
 
 i % ' i sinrist doc- 
 
 iundamental blow than this at the presupposition trine that 
 involved in the argument for evolutionist hedon- 
 ism. For he contends that, throughout all life, the 
 
 1 " Imitation," according to Kant (Grundlegung zur Met. d. 
 Sitten, Werke, iv. 257), " has no place at all in morals ; " and this 
 is true if the naked law of duty or respect for it is the sole 
 ethical motive. But if morality consists in the attainment of 
 an ideal which is being gradually realised in man, moral value 
 will not be denied to the motive which leads the individual to 
 fashion his own nature after that in which morality has attained 
 more complete realisation. 
 
176 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 (<m) the hy- great pulse of progress is neither, on the one hand, 
 
 pothesis of . , , . 
 
 theuncon- desire lor pleasure, nor, on the other, the more 
 scious; complex and varied motives just referred to, but 
 that it is the incessant striving towards fulness of 
 life by a universal unconscious will, which is mani- 
 fested in all things, and which is for ever pressing 
 onwards towards conscious realisation, regardless 
 of the increase of pain which the course of evolu- 
 tion implies. But this hypothesis of unconscious 
 will is not a justifiable metaphysical principle got 
 at by the analysis of experience, and necessary for 
 its explanation, though lying beyond it. It is a 
 " meternpirical," or rather mythical, cause inter- 
 polated into the processes of experience. Hence 
 the antagonism in which it stands to psychological 
 fact : its disregard of the effect of pleasure as a 
 powerful motive in volition ; and its neglect of the 
 obvious truth that function so reacts upon organ 
 that all actions have simply by continuance a 
 tendency to be performed with greater ease, and 
 therefore to yield in their performance increase 
 of pleasure. The smoothness and precision with 
 which it works may, indeed, lead to a function 
 being performed unconsciously, and thus without 
 either pain or pleasure. But the normal exercise 
 of conscious activity is uniformly pleasurable. 1 
 
 While giving up Schopenhauer's doctrine of the 
 merely negative character of pleasure, Hartmann 
 
 1 See the concluding pages of this chapter. 
 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 177 
 
 yet contends that " eternal limits " are set by the (&&) the na- 
 very nature of volition, which make it impossible tl^n; 
 to have a world with more pleasure in it than 
 pain. But his arguments * come very far short 
 of proving his case. For, in the first place, to say 
 that the stimulation and wearying of the nerves 
 imply the necessity of a cessation of pleasure as 
 well as of pain, is to confuse complete states of 
 consciousness with the subjective feeling which 
 accompanies each state. It is not true that one 
 ever becomes weary of pleasure : to talk as if there 
 were one class of nerves for pleasure, and another 
 for pain, is absurd. But every mental state, how- 
 ever pleasurable to start with, tends to become 
 monotonous, wearisome, or painful. Pleasure thus 
 requires a change from one mental state to another : 
 to say that it requires a change from pleasure to 
 something else is a contradiction in terms. It is 
 the objects or activity that require to be varied, 
 not the feeling of pleasure. Again, in the second 
 place, it is true that pleasure is to be regarded as 
 indirect in so far as it is entirely due to the 
 cessation of a pain, and not to instantaneous satis- 
 faction of will. But it does not do to regard the 
 pleasure as altogether indirect when, although the 
 cessation of a pain is necessary for its production, 
 it is itself something more than this cessation. 
 The inhibition of will often prevents the realisa- 
 
 1 Philosophic des Unbewussten, 6th ed., p. 660 ff. 
 M 
 
178 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 tion of an object which is very much more than a 
 recompense in pleasurable quality for the pain of 
 the restraint ; and although the pleasure only arises 
 from the removal of this painful state of inhibi- 
 tion, there is a direct and positive gain over and 
 above the gratification of having pain removed. 
 In the third place, Hartmann argues that the 
 satisfaction of will is often unconscious, whereas 
 pain is eo ipso conscious. But, even admitting the 
 reality of unconscious will or desire, which this 
 argument involves, it does not follow that pleas- 
 ure and pain are differently affected in regard to 
 it. If pain is eo ipso conscious, so also is pleasure ; 
 if the satisfaction of unconscious desire gives no 
 pleasure, neither does the absence of such satis- 
 faction give pain. 1 It is true, as Hartmann adds 
 in the fourth place, that desire is often long and 
 the joy of satisfaction fleeting ; but this refers not 
 so much to mental pleasures as to those connected 
 with physical appetite. Of them it is true that 
 
 " These violent delights have violent ends, 
 And in their triumph die." 
 
 But in the higher pleasures with more permanent 
 objects of pursuit, although the desire may be long- 
 continued, the pleasure does not disappear in the 
 moment of gratification. 
 
 It would seem, therefore, that the pessimist psy- 
 chology, in treating pleasure in a different way from 
 
 1 Cf. Sully, Pessimism, p. 226 n. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 179 
 
 pain, mistakes the true nature of both as simply 
 " polar extremes " l of feeling, and prevents the 
 argument being faced which has been brought 
 forward to show the increasing correspondence 
 of pleasure and life. 
 
 The failure of the psychological argument makes ( CC ) the facts 
 the whole burden of the proof of pessimism rest props': 
 upon the argument from historical facts. And the 
 attempt has been definitely made to show, from 
 observation of the course of human affairs, that 
 the progress of the world tends to misery. It 
 is necessary, therefore, to ask whether it can be 
 established that the facts included under the vague 
 term " human progress " have a normal tendency 
 either to increase pleasure or to act in the opposite 
 way. Now progress is a characteristic both of the 
 individual and of society ; but pleasure only be- 
 longs to the former, so that an answer to the 
 question whether individual progress tends to in- 
 crease the surplus of pleasure over pain, still leaves 
 unsettled the question as to the effect of social 
 progress. 
 
 It seems evident that both the physical and individual 
 mental development of the individual imply greater pl 
 adaptability to, and correspondence with, the exter- 
 nal world, and that, on account of this develop- 
 
 1 Cf. J. Ward, Journal of Speculative Philosophy, xvi. (1882), 
 377. 
 
180 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 ment, there is less unpleasant friction between 
 outer and inner relations, and means are at hand 
 for obtaining objects of desire with less exertion 
 than formerly. But, at the same time, the increase 
 of knowledge and of skill always implies not merely 
 the means of satisfying old wants, but the creation 
 of new ones : we see more of the evil in the world 
 than our forefathers did, and there are more avenues 
 by which it can approach us, if we have also more 
 effective means for avoiding what we dislike. And, 
 although knowledge brings with it not only the 
 pleasure of gratified curiosity, but that recognition 
 of a universal order which frees the mind from the 
 evils bred by a belief in the fickleness of nature, 
 yet this all-pervading sense of law has so regulated 
 our beliefs and methods of research that science 
 itself may seem to have lost the peculiar freshness 
 of interest that belonged to its earlier stages ; while 
 the feelings called forth by a vision of the divine 
 presence in the world, find but a poor substitute in 
 the sublime region of " cosmic emotion." Further, 
 the widening of the sympathetic feelings and their 
 consequent activities, and the refinement of the 
 whole sensitive nature by which it responds more 
 quickly and accurately to emotional stimuli, have 
 made the present generation more susceptible to 
 both pain and pleasure than its predecessors. But 
 Hartmann's argument that the duller nervous sys- 
 tem of the savage races (Naturvolker) makes them 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 181 
 
 happier than the civilised (Culturvolker), 1 leaves out 
 of sight the new sources of pleasure as well as pain 
 that are opened up to a refined sensibility. Accord- 
 ing to Hartmann, the aesthetic sensibilities may be 
 a source of painless pleasure: yet even their cul- 
 tivation cannot be said to be matter of pure gain 
 to their possessors; for the pain of discord is to 
 be set against in his opinion, it outweighs the 
 pleasure of harmony. On the whole, then, it would 
 appear that the evolution of the individual leads to 
 greater possibilities both of pleasure and of pain. 
 The refinement of the intellectual and emotional 
 nature opens up wider ranges of both kinds of 
 feeling ; and we are driven to look mainly to the 
 improvement of the social environment for the 
 means of increasing pleasure and diminishing 
 pain. 
 
 But to estimate the hedonistic value of social social pro. 
 progress is a still more difficult task than the pre- & 
 ceding. For the march of affairs has often little 
 regard to its effect on the happiness of the greater 
 number of people concerned. Industrially, it may industrial, 
 be thought that the increase in the amount of 
 wealth produced affords a vastly greater means of 
 comfort and luxury. Yet, it is doubtful whether 
 this increase has always been sufficient to keep 
 pace with the growth of population ; and it is cer- 
 tain that every society whose territory is limited, 
 1 Phil. d. Unbewussten, p. 747. 
 
182 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 must, when its numbers have increased beyond 
 a certain point, begin to experience the diminishing 
 returns which nature yields for the labour expended 
 upon it. Indeed, the tendency to an excess in the 
 rate of increase of population over that of means of 
 subsistence is one of the chief causes which make 
 it so difficult to assert that civilisation tends to 
 greater happiness. But, even although the average 
 quantity of wealth be greater now than before, it 
 must be remembered that wealth is measured by 
 its amount, whereas happiness depends on the 
 equality with which that amount is distributed. 1 
 Yet the present industrial regime tends to the 
 accumulation of immense wealth in a few hands, 
 rather than to its proportionate increase throughout 
 the community. The industrial progress which 
 increases the wealth of the rich, has little to recom- 
 mend it if it leaves the "labouring poor" at a 
 starvation-wage. 
 
 1 Bentham, Theory of Legislation (by Dumont, 1876), p^ 
 103 ff. Wundt, Physiologische Psychologic, 2d ed., p. 469, finds 
 in this an instance of Weber's law. Thus, the man with 100 
 receives the same pleasure on receipt of 1, as the possessor of 
 1000 does on receiving 10. As Wundt remarks, however, this 
 is only true within certain limits. Sixpence may give more 
 pleasure to a beggar who is never far from the starvation-point, 
 than the clearing of a million to Baron Eothschild. Further than 
 this, the law only states an "abstract" truth. For the suscepti- 
 bility to pleasure is not only very different in different individuals, 
 but this difference depends on many other circumstances than the 
 amount of wealth already in possession, such as original emotional 
 susceptibility, &c. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 183 
 
 " And what if Trade sow cities 
 Like shells along the shore, 
 And thatch with towns the prairie broad 
 With railways ironed o'er," 
 
 if the population can be divided into plutocrats 
 and proletariate ? Moreover, the very nature of 
 economic production seems to imply an opposition 
 between social progress and individual wellbeing. 
 For the former, in demanding the greatest possible 
 amount of produce, requires an excessive and 
 increasing specialisation of labour. Each worker 
 must perform that operation only to which he has 
 been specially trained, or which he can do best. 
 And in this way industrialism tends to occupy the 
 greater part of the waking hours of an increasing 
 proportion of human lives in the repetition of a 
 short series of mechanical movements which call 
 out a bare minimum of the faculties of the worker, 
 dwarf his nature, and reduce his life to a mere 
 succession of the same monotonous sensation. 1 In 
 spite, therefore, of immense improvements in the 
 general conditions of wellbeing, it is still difficult 
 to say that the happiness of the average human life 
 has been much increased by the march of industrial 
 progress. 
 
 A more hopeful view may, perhaps, be taken of and poiiti- 
 the effect of political progress. The increase of & 
 popular government gratifies the desire for power, 
 
 1 Cf. Comte, Positive Philosophy, ii. 144. 
 
184 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 and, in some cases, even tends to a more efficient 
 management of affairs. Still more important in its 
 effect on happiness is the greater security for life 
 and property which the gradual consolidation of 
 political control has brought about. It would seem, 
 too, that the harsher features of the struggle by 
 which this advance takes place have been modified ; 
 and that the war of politics has abated in fury more 
 than the war of trade. On the whole, therefore, 
 the tendency of modern political rule appears to 
 be towards an almost unmixed gain in respect of 
 happiness, by the security it affords for life and 
 property, by its wide distribution of political power, 
 and by the room it gives for individual freedom. 
 Yet the last of these results in the laissez-faire 
 system of industrialism to which it has led, and 
 which, in spite of many modifications, is still in the 
 ascendant has effects of a more doubtful character. 
 This mere reference to one or two of the leading 
 features of progress would not be sufficient to sup- 
 port a thesis either as to its beneficial or baneful 
 tendency. But evidence enough has been led to 
 show that the effects on pleasure of individual and 
 social development are of a mixed kind, that 
 culture and civilisation have neither the tendency 
 to misery which Hartmann follows Eousseau in 
 attributing to them, 1 nor, on the other hand, that 
 steady correspondence with increasing pleasure 
 
 1 Phan. d. s. B., p. 640. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 185 
 
 which would be required to establish the position 
 of evolutionist hedonism. 
 
 It follows, therefore, that, without adopting a Necessity of 
 
 . . , . , .,-, , . choosing 
 
 pessimist view, we must still make our choice between 
 between evolutionism and hedonism. The course ^and* 1 * 
 of evolution so far as experience helps us to hedonism - 
 understand it cannot be measured by increase of 
 pleasure. Nothing is said here to show that it 
 is not perfectly consistent to hold that the moral 
 feelings and ideas, the customs to which they have 
 given rise, and the institutions in which they are 
 embodied, have been produced by the ordinary laws 
 of evolution, and yet to maintain that the moral end 
 for reflective beings is the hedonistic or utilitarian 
 end. It may be possible, that is to say, to be an 
 evolutionist in psychology and sociology, at the 
 same time that one is a hedonist in ethics. But it 
 is not allowable to adopt pleasure as the end, and 
 yet speak of it as determined by evolution. Evolu- 
 tion can determine no such end until it be shown 
 that the progress it connotes implies a proportionate 
 increase of pleasure. 
 
 Such is the conclusion to which we are led by a 
 consideration of the bearings of evolution upon the 
 increase of pleasure and pain. But this argument 
 requires to be supplemented by the more satisfac- 
 tory method of an independent analysis of pleasure 
 in relation to the development of human nature; 
 and from this analysis we may hope to discover 
 
 
186 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 how far the theory of evolution is consistent with 
 the ethics of hedonism. 
 
 4. The psy- The relative and transient nature of pleasure has 
 analysis rf b een urged as an objection against any form of 
 hedonism by man 7 philosophers since the time of 
 
 lationtothe Plato. And the argument has of late years been 
 
 ethics of 
 
 evolution, brought forward in a way which shows that the 
 calculus of "pleasures" and "pains" which Ben- 
 tham's ethics implies is much less certain and easy 
 than its author supposed. This has been made 
 clear both by the subtle analysis carried out by the 
 late Professor Green, and by Professor Sidgwick's 
 examination of the difficulties which beset the 
 "hedonistic calculus." It does not appear, how- 
 ever, to have been made out that the nature of 
 pleasure proves hedonism to be impossible as the 
 end of conduct. But it may, perhaps, appear that 
 the case is altered when we consider the matter in 
 the light of the evolutionist form of hedonism now 
 under examination, and estimate from this point 
 of view the ethical bearings of the psychological 
 analysis of feeling. 
 
 The difficulty of denning pleasure or pain is not 
 the same as the difficulty or impossibility of denning 
 any elementary sensation. Tor the latter is con- 
 nected in definite ways with other similar sensations, 
 can be compared and associated with them, and by 
 such association go to make up an object or thing. 
 

 HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 187 
 
 But pleasure and pain are neither objects nor parts 
 of objects : they cannot be distinguished from or nature of 1 ' 
 associated with the impressions of the senses so as ple * 
 to constitute an object. They can only be spoken 
 of as an affection of the percipient and active sub- 
 ject, different in kind both from the objects it knows 
 and the acts it performs : each can only be denned 
 as the opposite of the other. Pleasure and pain 
 are not real phenomena with a distinguishable 
 existence of their own, like sensations, conceptions, 
 or actions ; they have no trace of objectivity what- 
 ever, but are, as Hamilton puts it, 1 "subjectively 
 subjective " : " pleasure is not a fact, nor is pain a 
 fact, but one fact is pleasurable, another painful." 2 
 Pleasure, therefore, is a mere feeling of the subject, 
 concomitant with the sensory or motor presenta- its connec- 
 tions which, by reason of their presence to conscious- objective 
 ness, we call objects or actions. It is not something 
 
 1 Lectures on Metaphysics, ii. 432. 
 
 2 L. Dumont, Theorie scientifique de la sensibility 2d ed., p. 
 83 ; cf. F. Bouillier, Du plaisir et de la douleur, 2d ed., p. 29 ff. 
 Reference may also be made to the leading psychological text- 
 book. " Das Gefiihl," says Volkmann (Lehrbuch der Psychologic, 
 127, 3d ed., ii. 300), " ist namlich keine eigene Vorstellung neben 
 den anderen (es gibt keine eigenen 'Gefiihlsvorstellungen'), ja 
 iiberhaupt gar keine Vorstellung." Professor Bain's view is 
 different, but does not altogether prevent him from acknowledg- 
 ing the subjectivity of feeling : " Without intellectual images 
 clearly recollected, we do not remember feelings ; the reproduction 
 of feeling is an intellectual fact, and the groundwork is intellec- 
 tual imagery." Emotions, p. 63. 
 
ma; 
 the 
 conduct. 
 
 188 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 by itself which we can choose rather than something 
 else, as we may select a peach instead of an apple, 
 through It can only be made the end of conduct in an 
 ,y be made indirect way. We must aim not at pleasure per se, 
 but at objects which we have reason to believe will 
 be accompanied by pleasurable feeling. Pleasure 
 and pain, as it has been urged, 1 are not quantities 
 that can be added and subtracted. It is not the 
 pleasurable or painful feeling, but the perceptional 
 or cognitive elements in the mental state of which 
 it is an element, that admit of plurality and 
 measurement. But we may foresee that one mental 
 state will be accompanied by pleasurable, another 
 by painful feeling, and, on that account, we may 
 choose the former. In a great number of cases we 
 are further able to make a quantitative estimate, 
 and to say that the pleasurable feeling accompany- 
 ing one object or action is more intense than that 
 accompanying another, and thus to choose one ob- 
 ject rather than another, not merely because one 
 is pleasurable while the other is painful, but (in 
 cases where both are pleasurable) because it is sup- 
 posed that the one will yield more intense or more 
 prolonged pleasure than the other. If this be true, 
 the purely subjective nature of pleasure does not 
 make it impossible for it to be taken as the prac- 
 tical end of conduct for the individual however 
 inexact and tentative many of its estimates must be 
 
 1 Cf. Green, Introduction to Hume, ii. 7. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 189 
 
 though it will shortly appear that its nature un- 
 fits it to be the end on the theory of evolution. 
 
 The difficulty arises when we attempt to inter- 
 pret, by means of pleasure, the increase and de- 
 velopment of life to which the course of evolution 
 tends, and which is sometimes put forward as the 
 end which the evolution-theory prescribes for con- 
 duct. And the difficulty also meets us when we 
 seek to explain the conception of a maximum of 
 pleasures as the end, by means of the conception 
 of evolution. 
 
 As long as we are content to look upon human 
 nature as consisting of constant sources of activity 
 and enjoyment, and having fixed susceptibilities for 
 pleasure and pain, it is easy to adopt the increase 
 of pleasure and diminution of pain as our aim. 
 But the case is altered when we take into consider- 
 ation the fact that man's actions and sensibilities 
 are subject to indefinite modification. Pleasure, as 
 we have seen, is a feeling of the subject dependent 
 upon the objects, sensory and motor, present at any 
 time to consciousness. These objects alone can be 
 our end ; but we may aim at certain of them rather 
 than others, simply on account of their pleasurable 
 accompaniment. It may happen, however, that an 
 object or action at one time pleasurable becomes 
 painful at another time, and that what is now pain- 
 ful ceases to be so and becomes pleasurable. In 
 this case our course of action, if motived by pleasure, 
 
190 THE THEOEY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 would have to be entirely changed, our practical 
 ethics revised and reversed. And, although no 
 sudden alteration such as this ever takes place, the 
 theory of evolution shows that a gradual modifica- 
 tion of the kind is going on. 
 
 (6) The con- The conditions of pleasure and pain, physiolo- 
 pfeunreand gi a l an( J psychological, are matter of dispute ; and 
 the dispute is complicated by the confusion of the 
 physiological with the psychological problem. It 
 will be evident, however, if only we keep differ- 
 ent things clear of each other, that both kinds of 
 explanation are possible, and that they are distinct 
 from one another. The question of the nervous 
 antecedents and concomitants of feeling is one 
 thing, and quite distinct from the question which 
 now arises of the mental antecedents or concomi- 
 tants of feeling. And here the theories which 
 have attempted a generalisation of the phenomena 
 are, in the light of recent inquiry, mainly two : 
 the theory that pleasure follows, or is the sense of, 
 increase of life, and that which holds it to be the 
 concomitant of unimpeded conscious functioning or 
 of medium activities. 
 
 (a) Pleasure The former theory l might be put forward as in- 
 abie as the dicating how it is possible to institute a connection 
 
 1 Cf. Spinoza, Ethica, iii. 11, schol. ; Hobbes, Leviathan, i. 6, 
 p. 25 ; Bain, The Senses and the Intellect, p. 283. Professor 
 Bain's statement is carefully guarded : " A very considerable 
 number of the facts may be brought under the following prin- 
 ciplenamely, that states of pleasure are connected with an in- 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 191 
 
 between pleasure and evolution. But it has been sense of 
 already shown that neither the actual facts of life, ^taSty 
 nor the tendencies to action, can be so interpreted 
 as to make their nature and development corre- 
 spond, with any degree of exactness, with pleasure 
 and its increase. 1 Nor is it possible to make out 
 that every pain corresponds to a loss of vitality, 
 every pleasure heightens it. On the contrary, the 
 assertion that pleasure-giving actions and life-pre- 
 serving actions coincide, is due to a hasty general- 
 isation which cannot include all the facts. That it 
 holds throughout a considerable extent is true. 
 Pleasure is, at any rate, a usual accompaniment 
 of the normal processes of the development of 
 life; and pain reaches its climax in death. But 
 yet there is a broad margin of experience for 
 which the generalisation is incorrect. There are 
 numerous cases of painful and pleasurable sensa- 
 tions which cannot be shown to be, respectively, 
 destructive of, and beneficial to* vitality. As 
 Mr Bain, who always keeps the facts in view, 
 admits, with regard to the feelings connected with 
 the five senses, " we cannot contend that the de- 
 crease, and states of pain with an abatement, of some, or all, of 
 the vital functions." 
 
 1 As Mr Spencer allows, Psychology, 126, i. 284: "In the 
 case of mankind, then, there has arisen, and must long continue, 
 a deep and involved derangement of the natural connections be- 
 tween pleasures and beneficial actions, and between pains and 
 detrimental actions." 
 
192 
 
 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 O) may be 
 * 
 
 tioning. 
 
 gree of augmented vital energy corresponds always 
 with the degree of the pleasure." l The same discrep- 
 ancy may be observed in more complex experiences. 
 The effort after a fuller life, whether physical or 
 mental, even when its ultimate success is not 
 doubtful, may bring more pain than pleasure; 
 while the life which never strains its powers 
 towards the limits of endurance, may experience 
 almost uninterrupted pleasure: but such pleasure 
 is the sure herald of the process of degeneration. 
 
 The theory that pleasure follows increased vital- 
 ity, and pain decreased vitality, is supplemented or 
 PP se d in modern psychology by the theory that 
 feeling depends on function: that pleasure is the 
 concomitant of medium activities, 2 or of conscious 
 functioning, which is unimpeded and not over- 
 strained 3 pain accompanying the opposite con- 
 dition. The objection urged against this view, 
 
 1 The Senses and the Intellect, p. 286. The Law of Conser- 
 vation is incomplete, Mr Bain holds, and must be supplemented 
 by the Law of Stimulation (p. 294). 
 
 8 Spencer, Psychology, 123, i. 277 : " Generally speaking, 
 then, pleasures are the concomitants of medium activities, where 
 the activities are of kinds liable to be in excess or in defect ; and 
 where they are of kinds not liable to be excessive, pleasure in- 
 creases as the activity increases, except where the activity is 
 either constant or involuntary." 
 
 3 Hamilton, Lectures, ii. 440 : " Pleasure is the reflex of the 
 spontaneous and unimpeded exertion of a power of whose ener- 
 gies we are conscious. Pain, a reflex of the overstrained or re- 
 pressed exertion of such a power." Cf. Aristotle, Eth. N., vii. 
 12, p. 1153 a 14, x. 4, p. 1174 b 20. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 193 
 
 that it leaves the so-called " passive pleasures " 
 out of account, seems to be made without sufficient 
 consideration of what is meant by attributing pas- 
 sivity to pleasure. All that such an expression 
 can denote, would appear to be that, in the pleas- 
 urable experience referred to, no exercise of the 
 muscles is implied, not that such an experience can 
 take place without any conscious activity on the 
 part of the subject. At the same time, the theory 
 that pleasure in all cases depends upon function, 
 must be admitted to be obliged to call in the aid of 
 hypothesis in order to explain all the facts. If the 
 generalisation required by the theory can be made 
 out, it must be by emphasising the fact that feeling 
 is never properly regarded as purely passive, but 
 implies subjective reaction ; and by supposing that 
 the variation of feeling between pleasure and pain 
 depends on a difference in the character of this 
 subjective reaction. At the same time, the com- 
 plete accuracy of this generalisation is not of vital 
 importance here, as it is mainly with the feeling 
 which manifestly results from activity or function- 
 ing that we are concerned. 
 
 Whether pleasure depends upon increase of vital Modification 
 energy, or upon unimpeded or medium function- 
 ing, it must be subject to modification along with ^ 
 the conditions under which life may continue and 
 increase, or the modes of activity which may be 
 carried on without opposition and in moderation. 
 
 N 
 
194 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 This constant modification of the objects in which 
 one takes pleasure, or which give one pain, is, in- 
 deed, a fact which must be admitted by any theory 
 of feeling. A state of mind may be at first pleas- 
 urable; but, if it be long-continued, the pleasure 
 will give way to the pain of monotony. The same 
 is true of a painful state of mind : its continuance 
 does not prolong the same intensity of painful con- 
 sciousness, but the sensibility becomes dulled and 
 the pain diminishes. The transition is still more 
 striking in the case of motor activities. In learning 
 to walk, or to ride, or to play any instrument, the 
 first experiences are those of painful effort. Gra- 
 dually, however, the co-ordinations of movement 
 required entail less and less pain, till the feeling 
 passes over into its opposite, and we have a pleas- 
 urable sense of successful effort and well-adapted 
 functioning. But, just as pain gave way to pleasure, 
 so pleasure itself subsides, the action becomes 
 merely reflex and passes out of consciousness al- 
 together, unless it be so long continued as to pro- 
 duce fatigue that is, pain. Habit, as Dumont 
 remarks, 1 intensifies perceptions, but weakens pleas- 
 ure and pain. 
 
 suggests These are psychological facts not mere theories 
 
 which hold true even of the individual experience. 
 
 objective J> U th e y naye l e( J psychologists to the theory, SUp- 
 intensity. 
 
 ported by a vast amount of direct experiment, that 
 
 1 Thdorie scientifique, p. 78. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 195 
 
 there is no object or action which can be said to be 
 absolutely and in itself either pleasant or painful. 1 
 The feeling of pleasure or pain accompanying the 
 object is a function of its intensity in relation to the 
 subject. This proposition cannot, indeed, be fully 
 demonstrated regarding each simple sensation: to 
 the emotions into which intricate relations of per- 
 ceptions enter, it does not apply, till their complexity 
 has been reduced. Some sensations and perceptions 
 are certainly felt as painful in any intensity in which 
 they are distinctly present to consciousness. But, 
 although this is a real difficulty, it does not seem 
 insuperable. The instances which Mill cites 2 to 
 throw doubt on the generalisation that quality of 
 feeling depends on intensity are unfortunately chosen 
 for his purpose. For to take his example the 
 taste of rhubarb is to many not painful but pleasant; 
 and, indeed, every case of acquired taste shows that 
 pleasure and pain can be modified through habit and 
 custom, and suggests that, even in the case of those 
 sensations which are painful in any form we have 
 been able to experience them, there is a degree of 
 intensity below which they would, if experienced, 
 be pleasant. Experiment has proved of the majority 
 even of sensible qualities, and analogy leads us to 
 conclude of all, that there is a degree in which each 
 
 1 Cf. Wundt, Physiol. Psych., p. 470 ; Fechner, Vorschule 
 der Aesthetik, ii. 243 f. 
 
 2 Exam, of Hamilton's Philosophy, 5th ed. 3 p. 559. 
 
196 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 may be pleasant, and a degree in which each may 
 be painful, and, between them, a real or imaginary 
 zero-point of feeling, where there is neither plea- 
 sure nor pain. This must, it is true, be received as 
 a hypothesis only; but it is a hypothesis which is 
 suggested by a wide range of facts, and which is 
 able to include even those facts with which it is 
 seemingly inconsistent, by supposing that could 
 their intensity be indefinitely diminished without 
 their passing out of consciousness, these sensations 
 would reach a point after which they would be felt 
 as pleasant and not as painful. Further, experiment 
 shows that this dividing-point which separates the 
 two poles of feeling is not always placed at the same 
 degree of intensity, that it differs not only for every 
 object, but for each individual subject as well, and 
 that it undergoes modification in the course of the 
 subject's development. 1 
 
 What is true of sense-perception is still more 
 evident regarding those experiences in which the 
 activity of the subject is more obviously involved. 
 As any function may, if carried beyond a certain 
 degree of intensity, be painful, so any function con- 
 sistent with life may be a source of pleasure. 
 
 From the preceding discussion two things may be 
 inferred: first, the dependence of pleasure and pain 
 on the subject-activity, whether the activity be that 
 
 1 See Fechner, loc. cit. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 197 
 
 of perception or of what is specifically called action ; 
 and secondly, the modification of pleasure and pain, 
 and transition from one to the other, along with the 
 modification of that subject-activity. To the appli- 
 cation of both these conclusions there may be limits; 
 but their general accuracy does not seem doubtful. 
 What the doctrine of evolution adds to this is its (<0 
 
 tion of the 
 
 proof of the indefinite modifiability of human f unc- theory of 
 
 T , ' i i i < i * n *- evolution : 
 
 tion. " It is an essential principle or lite, Mr 
 Spencer wrote, 1 before he had arrived at his general 
 theory of evolution, " that a faculty to which circum- 
 stances do not allow full exercise diminishes ; and 
 that a faculty on which circumstances make exces- 
 sive demands increases ; " and to this we must now 
 add, " that, supposing it consistent with maintenance 
 of life, there is no kind of activity which will not 
 become a source of pleasure if continued ; and that 
 therefore pleasure will eventually accompany every 
 mode of action demanded by social conditions." 2 
 It is, he holds, a " biological truth," that " everywhere 
 faculties adjust themselves to the conditions of exist- 
 ence in such wise that the activities those conditions 
 require become pleasurable." 3 The vast periods of 
 time over which evolution stretches are scarcely 
 needed to show how pleasure may be made to follow 
 from almost any course of action consistent with the 
 continuance of life. The change of habits which 
 
 1 Social Statics, p. 79. 2 Data of Ethics, p. 186. 
 
 3 Mind, vi. 85. 
 
198 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 often takes place in the history of a nation, and even 
 in the life of an individual, makes this sufficiently 
 obvious. But, if we still think of making attainment 
 of pleasure the end of conduct, the doctrine of evolu- 
 tion must give us pause. It has been already argued 
 that, given certain sources of, and susceptibilities for, 
 pleasure, the course of evolution has not been such 
 as to produce an exact coincidence between them 
 any conduct and the actions which further life. But it would 
 
 consistent .-, . -. , . . . . i i , 
 
 with condi- seem that, given habits or acting which are consist- 
 
 e conditions f life> an ^ which are system- 
 be pieasur- atically carried out, these will not fail to grow plea- 
 
 a Die j 
 
 sant as the organism becomes adapted to them. At 
 the best, it is difficult enough to say, even for the 
 individual, whether one imagined object or course of 
 action will exceed another in pleasurable feeling or 
 not. But, when we remember that function and 
 feeling may be modified indefinitely, it is impossible 
 to say what course of conduct will produce the 
 greatest amount of pleasure for the race. Taking 
 in all its effects, we cannot say that one way of 
 seeking pleasure is better that is, will bring more 
 pleasure than another. Bearing in mind the modi- 
 fications which evolution produces, it seems impos- 
 sible to guide the active tendencies of mankind 
 towards the goal of greatest pleasure, except by 
 saying that the greatest pleasure will be got from 
 the greatest amount of successful, or of unrestrained, 
 or of medium activity. 
 
HEDONISM AND EVOLUTIONISM. 199 
 
 If, then, we have been seeking to define the evolu- maximum 
 tionist end by interpreting it in terms of pleasure, 
 it appears that we have only succeeded in making 
 the round of a circle : pleasure as the end is seen to 
 be only definable as life or activity, although it was 
 adopted as the end in order that by its help we might 
 discover what life or activity meant as the end for 
 conduct. We may, perhaps, still be able to hold to 
 a form of hedonism, if we turn our attention from 
 the race to a small portion of present mankind. In 
 spite of the modifiability of function and its parasite 
 feeling, we may still be able to say that such and 
 such a course of action is likely to bring most 
 pleasure to the individual or even to the family. 
 But we cannot extend such a means of interpreting 
 the ethics of evolution to the race, where the possi- 
 bility of modification is indefinitely great, and the 
 pain incurred in initiating a change counts for little 
 in comparison with its subsequent results. If we 
 continue to look from the evolutionist point of view, 
 the question, What conduct will on the whole bring 
 most pleasure ? can only be answered by saying 
 that it is the conduct which will most promote life 
 an answer which might have been more satis- 
 factory had it not been to give meaning to this end 
 " promotion of life " that it was interpreted in terms 
 of greatest pleasure. The evolution-theory of ethics 
 is thus seen to oscillate from the theory which looks 
 upon the summum bonum as pleasure, to that which 
 
200 THE THEOEY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 finds it in activity. It contains elements which 
 make it impossible for it to adhere to the former 
 alternative. The comprehensiveness of its view of 
 life makes it unable to adopt pleasure as the end, 
 since pleasure changes with every modification of 
 function. And it has now to be seen whether the 
 empirical method of interpretation to which it 
 adheres will allow of its notion of life or activity 
 affording a satisfactory end for conduct. 
 
201 
 
 CHAPTER VIII. 
 
 THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 
 
 IN showing the important bearing which evolution wantofhar- 
 has on the causes of pleasure, the argument of the tweenevoiu- 
 preceding chapter has also made clear that the ends 
 of evolutionism and of hedonism cannot be made to 
 explain one another. The theory which starts with 
 a maximum of pleasure as the ultimate end, but 
 points to the course of evolution as showing how 
 that end is to be realised, is confronted by the fact 
 that the development of life does not always tend 
 to increased pleasure, and that the laws of its 
 development cannot therefore be safely adopted as 
 maxims for the attainment of pleasure. The same 
 objection may be taken to the method of interpret- 
 ing the evolutionist end by means of the pleasurable 
 results of conduct. The two do not correspond with 
 that exactness which would admit of one doing duty 
 for the other as a practical guide. And a further 
 difficulty has been shown to stand in the way of 
 
202 THE THEOEY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 this method. IJor, on coming to analyse pleasure, 
 we find that it may, by habituation, arise from any 
 or almost any course of conduct which the con- 
 ditions of existence admit of. The evolutionist, 
 therefore, can have no surer idea of greatest pleas- 
 ure even although this may not be a very sure 
 one than that it will follow in the train of the 
 greatest or most varied activity which harmonises 
 with the laws of life. 
 Necessity of We must therefore forsake the method of eclec- 
 
 investigat- 
 
 ing indepen- ticism, and inquire whether the theory of evolution 
 tionisTend". can niake any independent contribution towards 
 determining an end for conduct. We are frequently 
 told that it prescribes as the end " preservation," or 
 " development," or " the health of the society." But 
 to obtain a clear meaning for such notions, we must 
 see what definite content the theory of evolution 
 can give them, without considering, at present, the 
 grounds for transforming them into ethical pre- 
 cepts. Now, it may be thought and the sugges- 
 tion deserves careful examination that we may 
 find in the characteristics of evolution itself l an 
 indication of the end which organisms produced 
 by and subject to evolution are naturally fitted to 
 attain. These characteristics must therefore be 
 
 1 Taking evolution in its widest sense, since the theory of 
 evolution does not " imply some intrinsic proclivity in every 
 species towards a higher form." Spencer, First Principles, App. 
 p. 574 ; Principles of Sociology, i. 106. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 203 
 
 passed under review, that their ethical bearings 
 may be seen. 
 
 1. The first condition of development, and even i. Adapta- 
 of life, is correspondence between an organism and vironment : 
 its environment. The waste implied in the pro- 
 cesses which constitute the life of an organised 
 body has to be supplied by nutriment got from 
 surrounding objects. It requires food, air, light, 
 and heat in due proportions in order that its various 
 organs may do their work. When these circum- 
 stances change, either it adapts itself to the new 
 conditions or death ensues. Thus "we find that 
 every animal is limited to a certain range of cli- 
 mate ; every plant to certain zones of latitude and 
 elevation," 1 though nothing differs more among 
 different species than the extent of an organism's 
 adaptability to varying conditions. A definite or- 
 ganism and a medium suitable to it are called by 
 Comte the two " fundamental correlative conditions 
 of life " ; according to Mr Spencer they constitute 
 life. " Conformity " is absolutely necessary between 
 " the vital functions of any organism and the con- 
 ditions in which it is placed." In this conformity 
 there are varying degrees, and "the completeness 
 of the life will be proportionate to the completeness 
 of the correspondence." 2 Even when life is not 
 altogether extinguished, it is impeded by imperfect 
 
 1 Spencer, Principles of Biology, i. 73. 2 Ibid., i. 82. 
 
204 THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 adaptation. Where external circumstances make 
 the attainment of nourishment difficult and pre- 
 carious, life is shortened in extent, and, within its 
 limits, more occupied with simply maintaining its 
 necessary functions less full, varied, and active. 
 The same holds good whether the external circum- 
 stances are natural or social, applies equally to 
 those whose energies are exhausted in the produc- 
 tion of a bare livelihood from a niggard soil and 
 unpropitious climate, and to those who, under 
 changed conditions, feel the hardship of adapting 
 themselves to a new social medium, 
 spoken of as Shall we say, then, that the end of human conduct 
 
 the ethical , .. . , m1 . , 
 
 end; 1S adaptation to environment? Inis seems to be 
 
 the position taken up by some evolutionists. In 
 the language of von Baer, 1 "the end of ends is 
 always that the organic body be adapted to the 
 conditions of the earth, its elements and means of 
 nutriment;" and Mr Spencer holds "that all evil 
 results from the non-adaptation of constitution to 
 condition/' 2 The hedonism which Mr Spencer 
 definitely accepts as his ethical principle prevents 
 him, indeed, from fully adopting the theory of 
 human action which von Baer seems to regard as 
 the result of the doctrine of evolution. Yet com- 
 plete adaptation of constitution to condition is held 
 by him to be characteristic of that perfect form of 
 life to which evolution tends, and the laws of which 
 
 1 Reden (1876), ii. 332. 2 Social Statics (1850), p. 77. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 205 
 
 are to be our guides in our present imperfect social 
 condition. In working out his theory of ethics, he 
 describes acts as "good or bad according as they 
 are well or ill adjusted to ends/' identifying the 
 good with " the conduct furthering self-preserva- 
 tion," and the bad with "the conduct tending to 
 self-destruction." l The notion of self-preservation 
 thus introduced is na-turally suggested as the end 
 subserved by the activity of an organism being 
 adjusted to surrounding conditions. Self-preserva- defines the 
 tion, therefore, rather than adaptation to environ- seif-preser- 
 ment, will be regarded as the end, with which adap- vatlon * 
 tation will be connected as the essential means. 
 
 This notion of self-preservation has played a 
 remarkable part in ethical and psychological dis- 
 cussion since the time of the Stoics. It withdraws 
 attention from the relative and transient feeling of 
 pleasure to the permanence of the living being. 
 Thus, with the Stoics, the notion of self-preserva- 
 tion was accompanied by an ethics hostile to in- 
 dulgence in pleasure ; while, on the other hand, in 
 Spinoza and in Hobbes, pleasure was recognised 
 as the natural consequence of self -preserving acts 
 the former defining it as a transition from less to 
 greater perfection, the latter as the sense of what 
 helps the vital functions. The theory of evolution 
 has, of course, not only its distinctive contribution 
 to make to the connection between self-preservation 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, p. 25. 
 
206 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 and pleasure a subject already referred to, but 
 also shows how an increasing harmony has been 
 produced between acts which tend to self-preserva- 
 tion and those which tend to social-preservation. 
 With Mr Spencer these two points are united. His 
 doctrine that the " conduct which furthers race- 
 maintenance evolves hand-in-hand with the con- 
 duct which furthers self - maintenance " l is pre- 
 liminary^to the establishment of the proposition that 
 the highest life is one in which egoistic and " altru- 
 istic" acts harmonise with one another and with 
 external conditions : "the life called moral is one in 
 which this moving equilibrium reaches completeness 
 or approaches most nearly to completeness." 2 
 - As has been already pointed out, 3 it is not the 
 case, in the present state of human life, that egoistic 
 servation. ^^ altruistic tendencies, even when properly under- 
 stood, always lead to the same course of conduct ; 
 and even the theory of evolution does not do away 
 with the necessity for a " compromise " between 
 them. But, even had the theory of evolution' over- 
 come the opposition between the individual and 
 social standpoints, much would still remain to 
 be done for the purpose of constructing a system 
 of ethics, or determining the ethical end. It seems 
 better, therefore, to pass over at present the con- 
 flict of competing interests. According to Pascal, 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, p. 16. 2 Ibid., p. 71. 
 
 3 See above, chap. vi. p. 137 ff. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 207 
 
 " the entire succession of men, the whole courses, of 
 ages, is to be regarded as one man always living 
 and always learning/ 1 And this is a suggestion 
 which the theory of evolution only states more 
 definitely, though it cannot completely vindicate 
 it. On this supposition, self-preservation is social- 
 preservation, and the possibly divergent interests 
 of the individual and the whole are left out of 
 account. The end for the race then is, according 
 to the theory most explicitly stated by von Baer, 
 a state of " moving equilibrium " : and to this state 
 of affairs we are at least, Mr Spencer holds, indu- 
 bitably tending. In the final stage of human devel- 
 opment, man will be perfectly adapted to the con- 
 ditions of his environment, so that, to each change 
 without, there will be an answering organic change. 
 The ideal which seems to be held up to us is that 
 of a time in which there will be no more irksome 
 fretting in the machinery of life, and circumstances 
 will never be unpropitious, because the organism 
 will never be wanting in correspondence with them. 
 
 If this adaptation be adopted as the practical (a) AS the 
 end for conduct under present conditions, and not pr ese nt 
 merely as describing a far-off ideal to which we l; ^^ 
 are supposed to be tending, man may continue to progress; 
 manifest a law of progress, but its initiation will 
 be from external conditions. If " adaptation to en- 
 vironment" is consistently made the end, activity 
 will have to be restricted to suiting one's powers 
 
208 THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 to an external order of nature, and desire will have 
 to be curbed when it does not bring the means 
 of satisfaction along with it. " Bene latere " will 
 again be an equivalent for " bene vivere," and hap- 
 piness will have to be sought in withdrawal from the 
 distractions of political life, and in the restriction 
 of desire. It is strange to see the theory which 
 is supposed to be based upon and to account for 
 progress, returning in this way to an ideal similar 
 to that in which the post-Aristotelian schools took 
 refuge amid the decline of political and intellectual 
 life in Greece. The end which Stoic and Epicurean 
 alike sought in complete emancipation from the 
 conditions of the external world, 1 is now, in more 
 scientific phrase, made to consist in complete har- 
 mony with these conditions. But, in their practical 
 results, the two theories would seem scarcely to 
 differ. It is not astonishing, therefore, if this gos- 
 pel of renunciation finds little favour among prac- 
 tical men in our day. It is seen that, if a man 
 has not wants, he will make no efforts, and that, 
 if he make no efforts, his condition can never be 
 bettered. Thus social reformers have often found 
 that the classes they have tried to elevate did not 
 feel the evil of their lot as their benefactors saw it, 
 and they have had to create wants before attempt- 
 ing to satisfy them. 2 And the practical tendency 
 
 1 Zeller, Phil. d. Griechen, 3d ed., III. i. 454, 470. 
 
 2 Lassalle's tirade against the " verdammte Bediirfnisslosigkeit " 
 of the German workman is a case in point. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 209 
 
 finds its counterpart in speculative opinion, so that, 
 whereas Epicurus placed happiness in freedom 
 from wants, modern hedonism usually considers a 
 man the happier the more wants he has and is able 
 to supply. 1 
 
 This practical tendency brings out the truth that does not 
 it is not only by the subordination of self to cir- sen t the 
 cumstances, and the restriction of desire to present evolution. 
 means of satisfaction, that the required harmony 
 between outer and inner relations can be brought 
 about. The other alternative is open : circum- 
 stances may be subordinated to self. For this lat- 
 ter alternative the theory of evolution seems really 
 to leave room as much as for the former. It is ex- 
 cluded only when a one-sided emphasis is laid on 
 the necessity of adaptation to environment. For 
 evolution implies a gradually increasing heterogen- 
 eity of structure as the prelude to perfect agree- 
 ment with circumstances : " the limit of heterogen- 
 eity towards which every aggregate progresses is 
 the formation of as many specialisations and com- 
 binations of parts as there are specialised and com- 
 bined forces to be met." 2 The end of evolution is a 
 correspondence between inner and outer which is 
 not produced by the easy method of both being very 
 simple, but which is consistent with, and indeed 
 requires, the complexity and heterogeneity pro- 
 
 1 Lange, Gesch. d. Materialismus, 2d ed., ii. 458. 
 
 2 Spencer, First Principles, p. 490. 
 
 
 
210 THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 duced in both by constant interaction. 1 The greater 
 this complexity, the more filled with sensation, 
 emotion, and thought life is, the greater is what Mr 
 Spencer calls its " breadth." But, if " adaptation " 
 is still regarded as expressing the end, then, the 
 more perfect this adaptation is, the less room seems 
 left for progress, and the end of human conduct is 
 placed in a state of moving equilibrium in which 
 action takes place without a jar and without dis- 
 turbing the play of external conditions. 2 
 
 (6) AS <ie- This end of " adaptation " is looked upon by Mr 
 uitimTte e Spencer not as representing the conduct prescribed 
 ufe, !t f by morality in present circumstances, but as describ- 
 ing the ultimate condition of human life. As such, 
 it is the foundation of his Absolute Ethics that 
 " final permanent code " which " alone admits of 
 being definitely formulated, and so constituting 
 ethics as a science in contrast with empirical 
 ethics." 3 The " philosophical moralist," he tells us, 
 " treats solely of the straight man. He determines 
 the properties of the straight man ; describes how 
 the straight man comports himself ; shows in what 
 relationship he stands to other straight men ; shows 
 how a community of straight men is constituted. 
 
 1 An aspect of Mr Spencer's ethical theory which will be con- 
 sidered in the sequel : p. 228 ff. 
 
 2 Cf. A. Barratt, Physical Ethics, p. 294, where morality is 
 placed in "reasonable obedience to the physical laws of nature." 
 
 3 Data of Ethics, p. 148. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 211 
 
 Any deviation from strict rectitude he is obliged 
 wholly to ignore. It cannot be admitted into his 
 premisses without vitiating all his conclusions. A 
 problem in which a crooked man forms one of the 
 elements is insoluble by him." 1 
 
 How, then, are we to conceive the nature or con- complete 
 duct of the " straight man " ? To begin with, it is SSeeirttfa 
 made clear that his dealings are only with straight ^l r " 
 men ; for there are no " crooked men " in the ideal 
 community. " The coexistence of a perfect man 
 and an imperfect society is impossible ; and could 
 the two coexist the resulting conduct would not 
 furnish the ethical standard sought." 2 "The ulti- 
 mate man is one in whom this process [of adapta- 
 tion to the social state] has gone so far as to produce 
 a correspondence between all the promptings of his 
 nature and all the requirements of his life as car- 
 ried on in society. If so, it is a necessary implica- 
 tion that there exists an ideal code of conduct for- 
 mulating the behaviour of the completely-adapted 
 man in the completely-evolved society." This is Resultant 
 the code of Absolute Ethics, whose injunctions alone code of 6 
 are " absolutely right," and which, " as a system of ethlcs 
 ideal conduct, is to serve as a standard for our guid- 
 ance in solving, as well as we can, the problems of 
 real conduct." 3 At the outset, we were required to 
 " interpret the more developed by the less devel- 
 
 1 Social Statics, quoted in Data of Ethics, p. 271. 
 
 2 Data of Ethics, p. 279. 3 Ibid., p. 275. 
 
212 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 oped;" 1 the conclusion sets forth that the less de- 
 veloped is to be guided by the more developed, the 
 real by the ideal. Now, ethics " includes all con- 
 duct which furthers or hinders, in either direct or 
 indirect ways, the welfare of self or others." 2 Thus 
 Absolute Ethics, like Eelative Ethics, has two divi- 
 (a)iays sions, personal and social. As to the latter, Mr 
 Bte$iin- Spencer formulates certain principles of justice, 
 retetkmof negative beneficence, and positive beneficence, 3 which 
 individual describe the harmonious co-operation of ideal men 
 
 to society ; 
 
 in the ideal state. These principles may perhaps 
 be capable of a modified application to the present 
 state of society, in which there is a conflict of in- 
 terests: although Mr Spencer's representation of 
 them which is still, however, incomplete suggests 
 the belief that they are not so much guides which 
 the ideal gives to the real, as suggestions for the 
 construction of a Utopia gathered from the require- 
 ments of present social life. But, supposing the 
 "harmonious co-operation" of individuals to be 
 thus provided for, what is the personal end ? 
 and what, it might be added, is the social end, if 
 society has any further function than regulating 
 the relation of its units to one another ? Absolute 
 ethics does not seem to be able to give much guid- 
 
 i Data of Ethics, p. 7. 2 Ibid., p. 281. 
 
 3 These are examined by Mr F. W. Maitland, in an incisive 
 criticism of " Mr H. Spencer's Theory of Society," Mind, viii. 354 
 ff., 506 ff. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 213 
 
 ance here. " A code of perfect personal conduct," 0) further 
 we are told, " can never be made definite." 1 There ^dofoon- 
 are various types of activities, all of which may be- adaptation 
 long to lives " complete after their kinds." But yet 
 " perfection of individual life " does imply " certain 
 modes of action which are approximately alike in 
 all cases, and which, therefore, become part of the 
 subject-matter of ethics." We cannot lay down 
 " precise rules for private conduct," but only " gen- 
 eral requirements." And these are : to maintain 
 the balance between waste and nutrition, to observe 
 a relation between activity and rest, to marry and 
 have children. 2 This is " how the straight man com- 
 ports himself." Apart, therefore, from the sugges- 
 tion thrown out that a man's function may be the 
 realisation of a type of activity complete after its 
 kind a suggestion to be considered in the sequel 
 all that we can say of the " completely-adapted 
 man " would seem to be that he will be adapted to 
 his circumstances. 
 
 "We have a right to demur if the pleasures of the oO cannot 
 final condition of equilibrium be held up to our 1( ^ ^ 
 imagination as a reason for aiming at it. That it ha PP mess - 
 is " the establishment of the greatest perfection 
 and most complete happiness," 3 seems an unwar- 
 rantable assumption. Yet it is through this as- 
 sumption that an apparent harmony between Mr 
 
 i Data of Ethics, p. 282. 2 Ibid., p. 283. 
 
 3 First Principles, p. 517. 
 
214 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 Spencer's hedonistic ethics and his view of the 
 tendency of evolution is brought about. It is not 
 at all certain that the result of perfectly adapted 
 function is great increase of pleasure. It is true 
 that all the pains of disharmony between inner 
 desire or feeling and outer circumstances would, 
 in such a case, disappear ; but with them also there 
 would be lost the varied pleasures of pursuit and 
 successful struggle. It cannot even be assumed 
 that other pleasures would continue as intense as 
 before. For, as acts are performed more easily, 
 and thus with less conscious volition, they gradu- 
 ally pass into the background of consciousness, or 
 out of consciousness altogether ; and the pleasure 
 accompanying them fades gradually away as they 
 cease to occupy the attention. "Where action is 
 perfectly automatic, feeling does not exist." l The 
 so-called passive pleasures might still remain. But 
 the fact of effort being no longer necessary for the 
 adjustment of inner to outer relations might have 
 the effect of making the "moving equilibrium" 
 still called " life " automatic in every detail. 
 Indeed, if the suggestions of the ' First Principles ' 
 are to be carried out, it would seem that the 
 moving equilibrium is " a transitional state on the 
 way to complete equilibrium," 2 which is another 
 
 1 Spencer, Psychology, 212, i. 478. 
 
 2 First Principles, p. 489. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 215 
 
 name for death. 1 So far, therefore, from heightened 
 pleasure being the result of completely perfect 
 adjustment of inner to outer relations, this adjust- 
 ment would seem to reach its natural goal in un- 
 consciousness a conclusion which may commend 
 itself to those of Mr Spencer's disciples who take 
 a less optimist view of life than their master. 
 
 It seems evident, therefore, that to take adapta- 
 tion to environment, or self-preservation as inter- 
 preted by adaptation, as the end of conduct, is to 
 adopt an end which cannot be shown to be desirable 
 on the ground of yielding a maximum of happiness 
 or pleasure. And it is almost with a feeling of 
 relief that one finds Mr Spencer's confidence in 
 the tendency of evolution so far shaken as to admit 
 of his saying that " however near to completeness 
 the adaptation of human nature to the conditions 
 of existence at large, physical and social, may be- 
 come, it can never reach completeness." 2 " Adap- 
 tation to environment " must, at any rate, be kept 
 quite distinct from any theory of ethics which 
 takes pleasure as the end of life; and it cannot 
 consistently determine any result as of ethical 
 value on account of its pleasurable consequences. 
 The goal it sets before us, and in which human 
 progress ends, is conformity with an external order. 
 
 1 " A complete equilibrium of the aggregate is without life, 
 and a moving equilibrium of the aggregate is living." Principles 
 of Sociology, i. 106. 2 Data of Ethics, p. 254. 
 
216 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 The modification of these external conditions by 
 human effort is to be justified ethically by the 
 opportunity it gives for bringing about a fuller 
 agreement between the individual or race and its 
 environment. The result is a stationary state of 
 human conduct, corresponding with, or a part of, 
 that general " equilibration " to which, according to 
 Mr Spencer, all evolution tends. But this theory, 
 which places the goal of conduct in what seems to 
 be the actual tendency of evolution, gains no real 
 support from this apparent harmony of ethics with 
 general philosophy. It may be granted that the 
 evidence of physical laws goes to show that the 
 evolution of the solar, or even stellar, system is 
 towards a condition in which the " moving equili- 
 brium" will at last pass into a form in which 
 there is no further sensible motion, and the con- 
 centration of matter is complete. But to infer 
 from this that the theory which places the end 
 of conduct in a similar equilibrium shows the 
 harmony of morality with the tendency of exist- 
 ence in general, would really involve a confusion 
 of the two different meanings of " end." The end 
 or termination of all things may be equilibrium, 
 motionlessness, or dissolution, but this is no reason 
 why the end or aim of conduct should be a similar 
 equilibrium. 
 
 Indeed, to say that we ought to promote the end 
 of evolution, and that this end is annihilation, is 
 

 THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 
 
 inconsistent with the postulate always implied by 
 the ethics of evolution the postulate that con- 
 duct should promote evolution because life is de- 
 sirable, 1 and increase of life comes with the progress 
 of evolution. Nor is it of any assistance to reply 
 to this by saying that the dissolution in which 
 evolution ends may be only the prelude to another 
 process of evolution in which life will gradually 
 progress till it again reaches equilibrium. For, in 
 the first place, this is only a problematical sug- 
 gestion is not, to speak in Mr Spencer's language, 
 " demonstrable a priori by deduction from the per- 
 sistence of force," as the tendency of present evolu- 
 tion to equilibrium is held to be ; and secondly, 
 the new process, if it were to come about, would 
 have to begin again the slow ascent from the low- 
 est rung of the ladder of existence : so that, in aid- 
 ing evolution towards the goal of equilibrium, we 
 should be only guiding it to the old starting-point 
 which has now, after many a painful struggle, been 
 left far behind. 
 
 But further, it would seem that the theory of 
 evolution itself is not fairly represented by a view adaptation 
 which emphasises the fact of adaptation to environ- 
 ment to the exclusion of that of variation. The 
 latter is as necessary to progressive development 
 as the former. Adaptation to environment might 
 
 1 Spencer, Data of Ethics, p. 26. 
 
218 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 seem to be most nearly complete when organism 
 and environment were both so simple as to be 
 hardly separate. The polype, which is scarcely 
 different from the sea -water it inhabits, might 
 seem by correspondence with its medium to be 
 near the maximum of adaptation, though at the 
 very beginning of life. It may be solely because 
 the environment is subject to numerous changes 
 that the organism of simple structure cannot main- 
 tain life. But it is only through its own inherent 
 power of variation that progress in organic life is 
 possible. Perfect correspondence with the environ- 
 ment was not reached by simple organisms, not 
 only on account of the want of uniformity in their 
 tendency to surroundings, but also because there is in every 
 IiTorgan- in organism a tendency to variation through which 
 isms, fa Q modifications are produced which natural selec- 
 tion takes hold of. Did organisms not tend to vary 
 in function and structure, no progressive modifica- 
 tion would be possible. Those fittest to live would 
 be selected once for all, and all but those adapted 
 to the environment weeded out. 
 
 It is not necessary for our present purpose to 
 have any definite theory of the obscure laws by 
 which this variability is governed. 1 It is enough 
 that natural selection requires the striking out of 
 new modifications as well as the transmission of 
 
 1 Darwin, Origin of Species (1859), pp. 43, 131, 466. 
 
 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 219 
 
 those already produced. 1 It may be the fact that 
 variation is, in the last resort, due to changes in 
 surrounding circumstances, to the unequal inci- 
 dence of external forces upon a finite aggregate. 2 
 But, with living bodies as now constituted, it has, 
 at any rate as proximate cause, a twofold source. 
 It may be due to the direct effect of external forces, 
 or it may be caused by the energy stored up in the 
 organism in growth. 3 
 
 In man the outgo of this force is conscious ; and, consciously 
 by means of his conscious or intelligent volition, 
 governed by interests of various kinds, he can 
 anticipate and modify the action of natural 
 selection. The law that the fittest organism sur- 
 vives may perhaps work in man as in the lower 
 animals, if only we give a wide enough meaning 
 to " fittest," so as to admit even of the weak being 
 made fit through the sympathy and help of the 
 strong. Natural selection becomes dependent upon 
 variations of a kind different from those in the 
 merely animal world, so that its practical effect 
 may be in some cases apparently reversed. We 
 thus see how it is that even Darwin holds that in 
 moralised societies "natural selection apparently 
 effects but little," 4 at the same time that we may 
 
 1 Spencer, Biology, i. 257. 2 First Principles, p, 404 f, 
 
 3 Cf. Clifford, Lectures and Essays, i. 101. 
 
 4 Descent of Man, 2d ed., p. 137, cf. pp. 198, 618 ; cf. A. R. 
 Wallace, Contributions (1870), p. 330. 
 
220 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 not be inclined to deny the truth of Schaffle's con- 
 tention 1 that, although circumstances differ, the 
 law of action remains the same. Schaffle points 
 out how, as we rise in the scale of life, especially 
 as it is manifested in human society, the organisa- 
 tion becomes more delicate, and other than merely 
 natural facts have to be taken account of, so that 
 the fittest to live in the new social and intellectual 
 environment is no longer the man of greatest 
 physical strength and skill. 
 
 The theory of natural selection as applied to the 
 ordinary spheres of plant and animal life, may per- 
 haps, for some purposes, neglect consideration of 
 the fact that it presupposes a tendency to variation 
 in the organisms whose growth it describes. But, 
 when the variation in the behaviour of the organ- 
 ism becomes conscious and designed, there is thereby 
 produced a preliminary indication or determination 
 of the lines on which natural selection is to work. 
 And, before the theory of evolution can give a full 
 account of the ethical in man, it must distinguish 
 consciously-determined from merely natural action, 
 and give an analysis of what is implied in the 
 former. We must bear in mind that it may be the 
 case that the ground and possibility of progress 
 and of the efficiency of ideal ends in human con- 
 duct which " adaptation to environment " has been 
 unable logically to explain or leave room for are 
 
 1 Vierteljahrsschrift f. wiss. Phil., i. (1877), 543 ff. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 221 
 
 to be found in this differentiating fact of conscious 
 activity. But we must first of all see whether, 
 from the empirical characteristics of variation, we 
 can extract an ethical end or any guide for 
 conduct. 
 
 2. " The lower animals," says a writer on biology, 2. End sug- 
 " are just as well organised for the purposes of their thifttnd- 
 life as the higher are for theirs. The tape-worm is ency * 
 
 variation 
 
 relatively quite as perfect as the man, and dis- 
 tinguished from him by many superior capabili- 
 ties." l It is incorrect to look upon the evolution 
 of animal life as working upon one line, so that the 
 different kinds of living beings can be arranged, as 
 it were, in an order of merit, in which the organ- 
 isation of the higher animal plainly excels that of 
 the lower. The conditions of life are manifold and 
 various enough to permit of the existence of many 
 species equally perfect in relation to their environ- 
 ments. The fact that we are still able to speak of 
 one species or one animal as higher than another, 
 is not owing to the one being better adapted to its 
 environment than the other, but is supposed rather 
 to be due to the higher forms having " their organs 
 more distinctly specialised for different functions." 2 
 Even Mr Spencer, for whom equilibrium is the goal 
 of life, implicitly admits that " adaptation " alone is 
 
 1 Rolph, Biol. Probl., p. 33. 
 
 2 Darwin, Origin of Species, p. 336. 
 
222 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 not the end of human action, by his doctrine that 
 the degree of evolution may be measured by the 
 complexity of the adjustments it effects between 
 organism and environment. The end, therefore, it 
 
 scribes self- . . 
 
 development may be said, is no longer the mere " selt-preserva- 
 
 " f ound in adaptation to environment, but the 
 self-development " which implies temporary dis- 
 harmony between organism and surroundings. 
 
 For " self-preservation " and " self-development," 
 though frequently spoken of *as identical, are really 
 distinct and often opposed notions the former de- 
 noting a tendency to persist in one's present state 
 of being, while the latter implies more or less 
 change. It may be held, however, that for an 
 organism such as man to persist in his state of 
 being, implies modification of his faculties, and that 
 this modification involves development. For any 
 organism to exist apart from change is, of course, 
 impossible. Life is only known to us as a series of 
 changes. But that change does not necessarily 
 mean development or "change to a higher condi- 
 tion." Degradation is as well known a fact as 
 development ; and between the two, there is room 
 for a state of existence of which it is difficult to 
 say whether it improves or deteriorates. And 
 whatever may be intended by the phrase, " self- 
 preservation " points to a state of this kind rather 
 than to an improving condition. The notion of 
 " self -development " has therefore a richer content 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 223 
 
 than that of " self-preservation " ; but just on this 
 account it cannot be explained by a reference to 
 the nature of things as they are. 
 
 It is true that self-development can only go on thus taking 
 
 , .. P T i j , account of 
 
 by a continuous process or adjustment ; but it is variability 
 also necessary for it that this tendency to adapta- 
 tion should be continually hindered from becoming 
 complete or lapsing into equilibrium. It is here 
 that the function of variation comes in. On the 
 one side there is this tendency to vary after a 
 fashion often without any apparent regard to ex- 
 ternal conditions; on the other side, there is the 
 action of the external conditions selecting and 
 favouring those variations which bring the organ- 
 ism into closer correspondence with them. The 
 wide range over which the theory of natural selec- 
 tion applies is due to the fact that the environment 
 is never uniform and never constant, so that modifi- 
 cations on the part of the organism have a chance 
 of suiting its varied and changing character. Its 
 changes, moreover, are often the result not so much 
 of any absolute alteration in external circumstances, 
 as of a new relation between them and living beings 
 having been brought about. For the enormous re- 
 productive faculty of most organisms makes them 
 multiply so rapidly as to press ever more and more 
 closely against the limit of subsistence, and thus 
 to produce competition for the means of living. 
 Hence the fresh lines of development originated 
 
224 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 by each organism have to be tested by their cor- 
 respondence with a constantly changing medium. 
 The altered circumstances give the modifications 
 which organisms are for ever striking out an 
 opportunity of perpetuating themselves, 
 which com- By each new variation the existing relation 
 
 plicatesthe , . . L-J-I.-UJ 
 
 tendency to between organism and environment is disturbed, 
 de^ce with ^ ne var iation may, however, prove its utility at 
 environ- once ^y a more exact correspondence than before 
 
 ment, 
 
 with the requirements of external conditions. But, 
 in what are called the higher grades of life, varia- 
 tions from the type are sometimes not immediately 
 useful, although they may ultimately become most 
 advantageous. 1 Were it not for the remarkable 
 power of persistence possessed by the higher 
 animals, the modified organism would be unable 
 to hold its own. The great majority of such 
 eccentric or extraordinary variations do, as a 
 
 1 Thus Darwin, Descent of Man, p. 51, speaking of the " advan- 
 tage to man " it must have been " to become a biped," says : 
 " The hands and arms could hardly have become perfect enough 
 to have manufactured weapons, or to have hurled stones and 
 spears with a true aim, as long as they were habitually used for 
 locomotion and for supporting the whole weight of the body ; or, 
 as before remarked, as long as they were especially fitted for 
 climbing trees." The hands had to lose their dexterity for the 
 latter purposes before they could acquire the more delicate ad- 
 justments necessary for skill in the former. The transition was 
 of course a gradual one ; but the initial variations required would 
 seem to have been at first unfavourable to man's chances in the 
 struggle for existence, though it was through them that he rose 
 to his place at the summit of the organic scale. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 225 
 
 matter of fact, soon disappear, because unable to 
 prove their utility. But others of them, either by 
 the power they give the organism to mould circum- 
 stances to itself, or by their appropriateness to the 
 greater complexity which conies with the increased 
 number of living organisms, and the more delicate 
 readjustment it requires, prove themselves to be 
 fitter to live than if no variation had taken place 
 and the preceding state of relative equilibrium 
 had been maintained. The higher adjustment of 
 life to its surroundings, which marks each stage of 
 advancing evolution, had its beginning in the rup- 
 ture of the original simpler harmony that previously 
 existed. 
 
 If we compare human conduct with that of especially 
 animals lower in the organic scale, it becomes conduct. 11 
 evident that there is a broad difference between 
 the two in this, that actions in the former are 
 purposed, performed with a definite end in view ; 
 whereas, in the latter, they seem 'to be the blind 
 result of impulse, and there are slight, if any, 
 traces of purpose. In activity of the latter kind, 
 natural selection works in the ordinary way by 
 choosing for survival the animals which behave so 
 as best to suit their environment. But actions 
 done with a view to an end may anticipate the 
 verdict of this natural law. The agent may see 
 that conduct of a particular kind would conduce 
 to the promotion of life, while conduct of a differ- 
 
 p 
 
226 THE THEOEY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 ent kind would render him less fit to live ; and, 
 as a consequence, the former action may be chosen. 
 In this way development may be anticipated, and 
 the present order of affairs may be disturbed, more 
 or less forcibly, in order to bring about a foreseen 
 better state of things. 
 
 We are thus able to see more clearly how it is 
 that the theory of evolution may be thought to 
 give rise to two different ethical ends. The first 
 of these is the theory already criticised, " adaptation 
 to environment," which corresponds to the notion 
 of self-preservation. But this end, as we have 
 seen, only takes one side of the theory of evolution 
 into consideration neglects the tendency to varia- 
 tion which evolution postulates, and which, in the 
 higher organisms, becomes purposed. The other 
 end which seems to be suggested by the theory of 
 evolution takes account of this tendency to varia- 
 tion, and may be said to correspond to the notion 
 of self-development ; but this end it is harder to 
 define. Adaptation we can easily understand by 
 a reference to the environment to which life is 
 to be adapted. This involves a knowledge of the 
 conditions of the environment, but nothing more. 
 Development can be measured by no such standard. 
 On the one hand it implies an independent, or 
 relatively independent, tendency to variation. On 
 the other hand, however, it is necessary that the 
 disharmony with environment, in which this tend- 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 227 
 
 ency to variation may begin, should not be exces- 
 sive and should not be permanent ; for without a 
 certain amount of adaptation to environment no 
 organism can live. The extent of initial dishar- 
 mony which is possible, or is useful, varies accord- 
 ing to the versatility of the faculties of each indi- 
 vidual organism, and to its place in the scale of 
 being ; but throughout all existence it is true that 
 want of adaptation beyond a certain varying degree 
 is fatal : " a mode of action entirely alien to the 
 prevailing modes of action, cannot be successfully 
 persisted in must eventuate in death of self, or 
 posterity, or both." l 
 
 By what standard, then, can we measure develop- (&) standard 
 ment ? We have already seen, from the " formula," i ng develop- 
 as it is called, or definition, of evolution, that it m 
 implies an advance to a state of increased coherence, 
 definiteness, and heterogeneity, by the double process 
 of differentiation of parts, and integration of these 
 parts into a whole by the formation of definite 
 relations to one another. The notions of coherence 
 amongst parts and of increased definiteness of 
 function and structure are easily understood. But 
 the heterogeneity postulated is a more complex 
 notion, has, in the first place, a double reference, 
 " is at the same time a differentiation of the parts 
 from each other and a differentiation of the con- 
 
 1 Spencer, Data of Ethics, p. 280. 
 
 
228 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 solidatecl whole from the environment ; " 1 and sec- 
 ondly, is manifested in living beings in increased 
 complexity of every kind of structure, form, 
 chemical composition, specific gravity, temperature, 
 and self-mobility. 2 Can we then apply this at 
 once to ethics, and say that the most developed 
 that is, the most moral conduct is that which is 
 most definite, coherent, and heterogeneous ? This 
 doctrine has at least the merit of not leaving out 
 of sight so fundamental a characteristic of evolution 
 as the tendency to variation ; and, without being 
 consistently held to, it is the burden of much of 
 Mr Spencer's ' Data of Ethics/ where it is illustrated 
 and defended with great ingenuity. 
 
 round in That moral conduct is distinguished by definite- 
 
 complexity ness and coherence that it works towards a de- 
 motive and terminate end, and that its various actions are in 
 agreement with one another and parts of a whole 
 may be admitted. But this is at most a merely 
 formal description of what is meant by morality in 
 conduct. To say that conduct must be a coherent 
 whole, and must seek a determinate end by appro- 
 priate means, leaves unsettled the question as to 
 what this end should be, or what means are best 
 fitted to attain it. But, when we go on to say that 
 as conduct is more varied in act, 3 more heterogene- 
 
 1 Spencer, Biology, i. 149. 2 Ibid., i. 144. 
 
 3 Spencer, Data of Ethics, p. 71 : " Briefly, then, if the con- 
 duct is the best possible on every occasion, it follows that as the 
 occasions are endlessly varied the acts will be endlessly varied to 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 229 
 
 ous in motive, 1 it is higher in the moral scale, we 
 seem to have got hold of something which may 
 be a guide for determining the ethical end. The 
 mark of what is higher in evolution, and conse- 
 quently in morality, will be greater heterogeneity 
 or complexity. 2 
 
 This conclusion follows from an attempt not 
 merely to treat "moral phenomena as phenomena 
 of evolution," but also to find the " ultimate in- 
 terpretations " of ethics " only in those fundamen- 
 tal truths which are common to all " the sciences, 
 physical, biological, psychological, sociological. 3 
 Now the fundamental truths which these sciences 
 have in common are those only which are most 
 abstract. But as we pass from mere relations be- Difficulties 
 tween matter and motion to life, and from life theory: 
 to self -consciousness, we have something different 
 from these fundamental truths with the addition 
 of certain others not fundamental: we find that 
 things are not merely more complex, but are 
 changed in aspect and nature. Even though it 
 be true that the new phenomena may still admit 
 
 suit the heterogeneity in the combination of motions will be 
 extreme." 
 
 1 Spencer, Data of Ethics, p. 106 : " The acts characterised 
 by the more complex motives and the more involved thoughts, 
 have all along been of higher authority for guidance." 
 
 2 Cf. Clifford, Lectures and Essays, i. 94 f., where a similar 
 definition is given in answer to the question, " What is the mean- 
 ing of better ? ' ' 
 
 3 Spencer, Data of Ethics, p. 63. 
 
230 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 of analysis into the old simpler terms, and that 
 life, mind, and society may be interpreted as redis- 
 tributions of matter and motion, 1 it must yet at 
 least be admitted that the change passed through 
 is one similar to those which Mill compared to 
 chemical composition: the new compound differs 
 fundamentally in mode of action from the elements 
 out of which it was formed. Now, in saying that 
 the most complex adjustments of acts to ends are 
 the highest kinds of conduct, and that we should 
 be guided by the more complex in preference to 
 simpler motives, this obvious difficulty is passed 
 over. It is true that Mr Spencer, in chapters rich 
 in suggestion, and filled with skilfully chosen 
 illustrations, has passed in review the various 
 aspects of conduct according as we look at it from 
 the point of view of the physical environment, 
 of life, of mind, or of society. But when these 
 different aspects are brought together and com- 
 pared, it becomes clear that the attempt to judge 
 conduct by reference to the " fundamental truth " 
 that evolution implies an advance towards greater 
 complexity, must necessarily end in failure. 2 
 
 1 Cf. Spencer, First Principles, p. 566. 
 
 2 So far as the following criticism may appear to apply to Mr 
 Spencer, and not merely to a possible way of denning moral con- 
 duct, it is necessary to bear in mind the words of his preface to 
 the ' Data of Ethics ' : " With a view to clearness, I have treated 
 separately some correlative aspects of conduct, drawing conclu- 
 sions either of which becomes untrue if divorced from the 
 other." 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 231 
 
 In the first place, there is a notable discrep- ( a ) antinomy 
 ancy between the biological and the sociological ^between y 
 aspect. For the complete development of the ^ 8 i ^ 1 
 individual life implies that every function should v *<iuaiends; 
 be fulfilled, and that its fulfilment should interfere 
 with the performance of no other function. " The 
 performance of every function is, in a sense, a moral 
 obligation." " The ideally moral man ... is one 
 in whom the functions of all kinds are duly ful- 
 filled," that is to say, " discharged in degrees duly 
 adjusted to the conditions of existence." l A fully 
 evolved life is marked by multiplicity and complex- 
 ity of function. And, if from the individual we 
 pass to the social organism, we find that the same 
 truth holds. The state, or organised body of in- 
 dividuals, has many functions to perform ; but it 
 can only perform them in the most efficient way 
 through the functions of its individual members 
 being specialised. From the social point of view, 
 therefore, the greatest possible division of labour is 
 a mark of the most evolved and perfect community. 
 And this division of labour implies that each in- 
 dividual, instead of performing every function of 
 which he is capable, should be made to restrict 
 himself to that at which he is best, so that the 
 community may be the gainer from the time and 
 exertion that are saved, and the skill that is pro- 
 duced, by the most economic expenditure of indi- 
 
 1 Spencer, Data of Ethics, p. 75 f. 
 
232 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 vidual talent. Thus social perfection appears to 
 imply a condition of things inconsistent with that 
 development of one's whole nature which, from the 
 biological point of view, has just been denned as a 
 characteristic of the ideally moral man. It seems, 
 indeed, inevitable that any such abstract prelimin- 
 ary notion of development as that which would 
 test it by increase of complexity must fail in such a 
 case as this where there is no question between the 
 competing claims of two phenomena on the same 
 level, but where harmony is wanted between the 
 different aspects the same phenomena present when 
 looked at from the point of view of the individual 
 and from the point of view of the whole. 
 O)itspsy- There is still greater difficulty in applying this 
 aspect' 1 Ca criterion, when we come to the psychological aspect 
 of morality the aspect most prominent in mod- 
 ern philosophy from the revival of independent 
 ethical speculation till the time of Kant. Accord- 
 ing to Mr Spencer, " the acts characterised by the 
 more complex motives and the more involved 
 thoughts, have all along been of higher authority 
 for guidance." l But the later or more advanced 
 in mental evolution is not always more complex in 
 structure; for it is a characteristic of mental develop- 
 ment that the processes by which a result has been 
 arrived at gradually disappear on account of the dim- 
 inished attention they receive, so that there remains 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, p. 106. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 233 
 
 what is, so far as psychical structure is concerned, a 
 simple mental state. Complexity of structure and confounds 
 
 . . -M T np , complexity 
 
 indirectness of origin are thus really two different of structure 
 characteristics of states of mind, which frequently JJJJiliof 
 go together, but frequently part company. 1 When ori s in > 
 Mr Spencer, accordingly, goes on to say 2 that " for 
 the better preservation of life the primitive simple 
 presentative feelings must be controlled by the 
 later-evolved compound and representative feel- 
 ings," he is really passing to a different standard 
 without giving up the former. The sympathy with 
 injured Zulus or Afghans which would be approved 
 by Mr Spencer 3 may be a more indirect, represen- 
 tative, or re-representative feeling, than the senti- 
 ments which led to British invasion, and, as such, 
 may be more to be commended. But it would be 
 rash to say that sympathy with the " British in- 
 terests " supposed to be at stake interests of com- 
 merce, and of the balance of jpolitical power, as 
 well as those arising from the subtle effect of 
 national prestige is less complex than the feeling 
 of sympathy with a people dispossessed of its ter- 
 ritory. The latter feeling may be more indirect or 
 representative, as implying an imaginative appro- 
 
 1 Although Mr Spencer holds that representativeness varies as 
 definiteness, and measures complexity, including that complexity 
 implied by increasing heterogeneity. Principles of Psychology, 
 ii. 516 f. 
 
 2 Data of Ethics, p. 113. 
 
 3 Cf . Principles of Sociology, ii. 725. 
 
234 
 
 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 neither of 
 which can 
 serve as an 
 ethical 
 standard. 
 
 priation of the circumstances of another community ; 
 but, so far as structure is concerned, it is composed 
 of far fewer and simpler component elements than 
 the feeling for British interests. 
 
 Nor, on the other hand, can we allow ourselves 
 to take refuge in the conclusion that, if the more 
 complex emotion cannot be held to be better 
 morally, then that which is later in evolution may 
 at least be regarded as of higher authority than the 
 earlier evolved feeling. According to Mr Spencer, 
 the man who obtains by fraud the money to support 
 his family is to be condemned, because, although we 
 admit the claim his family have upon him, " we 
 regard as of superior authority the feelings which 
 respond to men's proprietary claims feelings which 
 are re-representative in a higher degree and refer 
 to more remote diffused consequences." x But were 
 this the ground of distinction, we ought also to 
 regard the feelings^ prompting a man to distribute 
 his fortune in any foolish enterprise " as of superior 
 authority " to those which prompt him to support 
 his family, if only the former are " re-representative 
 in a higher degree," and their consequences more 
 " remote " and " diffused." Many of the greatest 
 evils which infect social life and warp the moral 
 feelings of men, are evils which are only possible 
 as the result of a highly advanced civilisation and 
 a refined and delicate organisation of the mind. 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, p. 123. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 235 
 
 The factitious sentiments raised by a subtle casu- 
 istry with the effect of confusing the ordinary dis- 
 tinctions of right and wrong are, in almost all cases, 
 more indirect and re-representative than the feelings 
 in harmony with the moral consciousness of the 
 community which they set aside in the individual 
 conscience. So obvious, indeed, are objections of 
 this kind objections, that is to say, taken from 
 the impossibility of so applying the criterion as 
 to construct a workable system of morals that 
 Mr Spencer virtually relinquishes his own theory, 
 talking of it as true only " on the average," 1 and 
 even allowing that it is in some cases suicidal. 2 
 
 As it cannot be held that the more complex in 
 evolution is of greater authority than the less 
 complex, nor that the later in evolution has such 
 authority over the earlier, we must admit that the 
 so-called " fundamental characteristics " of evolu- 
 tion, which find a place in its definition or "for- 
 mula," are unable to determine its value in an 
 ethical regard. The richness of life, physical, in- 
 tellectual, and social, has indeed been produced 
 only as the result of a long course of development, 
 and by the assimilation of many various elements 
 into a complex organisation ; but its value cannot 
 be measured either by the test of mechanical com- 
 plexity, or by the length of time it has taken to 
 evolve. We must therefore seek some other 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, pp. 107, 129. 2 Ibid., p. 110. 
 
236 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 method of giving a meaning to evolution in the 
 region of moral values ; and we find Mr Spencer 
 himself really falling back in his discussion on the 
 more general answer to our question, that the end 
 of evolution is life : " evolution becomes the highest 
 possible when the conduct simultaneously achieves 
 the greatest totality of life in self, offspring, and 
 fellow-men." 1 Since it appears, then, that the char- 
 acteristic of complexity or variety is as unsatis- 
 factory a criterion of morality, as the notion of 
 " adaptation to environment " was found to be, we 
 must ask for some further interpretation of the 
 notion of " development " or " increase of life " 
 when regarded as the end of conduct. 
 
 3. Further 
 
 vel . have as yet found it has always proceeded on the 
 assumption that life is desirable, and that it has 
 
 life as the a y a l ue which makes its pursuit and promotion 
 a reasonable moral end. How this fundamental 
 ethical assumption 2 is to be justified, I do not at 
 present inquire. But the question must now be 
 faced What is meant by " life " when we say 
 
 1 Data of Ethics, p. 25; cf. Lange, Ges. d. Mat., ii. 247. 
 Lange's statement is noteworthy : " Die menschliche Vernunft 
 kennt kein anderes Ideal, als die moglichste Erhaltung und Ver- 
 vollkommnung des Lebens, welches einmal begonnen hat, verbun- 
 den mit der Einschrankung von Geburt und Tod." 
 
 2 The " endeavour to further evolution, especially that of the 
 human race," is put forward as a " new duty" by Mr F. Galton, 
 Inquiries into Human Faculty and its Development (1883), p. 337. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 237 
 
 that its " increase " or " development " is the moral 
 end, and speak of its " greatest totality " in a 
 way that implies that it admits of quantitative 
 measurement ? The biological definition of life is Biological 
 
 definition of 
 
 itself matter of dispute. But, even were such a de- 
 finition as that proposed by Mr Spencer agreed to, C1 
 it would be insufficient to provide a standard for 
 human conduct. The very generality which may 
 make it fit to stand as a definition, or at least 
 abstract description, of life, renders it at the same 
 time incapable of serving as a criterion by which 
 the various modes of the manifestation of life may 
 be judged. One point, however, generally empha- 
 sised by the theory of evolution, may be admitted. 
 The life which human conduct " ought " to increase 
 is not merely that of one individual man, but the 
 whole life of the community " self, offspring, and 
 fellow-men " with which the individual life is 
 bound up. Evolution has shown how the growth 
 of the individual has been so dependent upon that 
 of the whole body of society that it is impossible 
 to separate their interests. At the same time, no 
 complete identity has been brought about, and it 
 remains one of the greatest difficulties of any em- 
 pirical theory to harmonise their competing claims. 
 For argument's sake, however, and to admit of the 
 quality of the end being investigated apart from 
 considerations as to the method of distribution, the 
 question may be discussed as if natural selection 
 
238 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 had produced complete solidarity between the life 
 of the individual and that of the race. 
 
 "What criterion have we, then, of the development 
 of human nature or life ? The answer at once sug- 
 gests itself that the higher evolution of life can be 
 accurately measured by the amount of pleasure got 
 by living beings. But this view has been examined 
 in the preceding chapter, and found to be unsup- 
 ported by sufficient evidence ; so that we are driven 
 to seek for some non-hedonistic criterion that will 
 give meaning to the phrase " development " or 
 "increase of life," when prescribed as. the ethical 
 end. 
 
 Health as Nor is the matter made any clearer by saying that 
 either used the " health" of society is the end we ought to pro- 
 rnote. 1 Tnis nas been P ut forward as an interpre- 
 tation of the hedonistic principle, which brings that 
 principle into accord with the theory of evolution. 
 As such, however, it seems open to fatal objections. 
 Given as an explanation of " pleasure," it falls back 
 upon the notion of "life"; for health can only be 
 
 1 Darwin, Descent of Man, p. 121 ; Stephen, Science of Ethics, 
 p. 366. Earlier than either of these writers, Dr Hutchison Stir- 
 ling suggested Health as a practical principle to be set against the 
 anarchy of individualism. But with him, it is not an empirical 
 generalisation of the tendency of evolution. It is as " the out- 
 ward sign of freedom, the realisation of the universal will," that 
 " health may be set at once as sign and as goal of the harmonious 
 operation of the whole system as sign and as goal of a realisation 
 of life." Secret of Hegel, ii. 554. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 239 
 
 defined as that which conduces to continued and 
 energetic life. Further than this, there is a special 
 difficulty in adopting health as the proximate end 
 where pleasure is the ultimate end. Even if we 
 could assert that health always leads to pleasure, it 
 is not evident that it is better known, or more 
 easily made the end, than pleasure. For of present 
 pleasure we have a standard in our own conscious- 
 ness from which there is no appeal. And, although 
 the value of a series of pleasures is much harder to 
 estimate, there is also no slight difficulty in saying 
 what will promote the efficiency or health of an 
 organism. Besides, the question arises whether 
 health really corresponds with pleasure; and this 
 is, in another form, the question which has been 
 already answered in the negative, whether life 
 can be measured by pleasure. 
 
 On the other hand, if " health " is to be taken or fails back 
 not as an explanation of or means to pleasure, but as notion of 
 a substitute for the notion of " life," then we hardly llfe - 
 get beyond our original terms. " Health " must be 
 interpreted simply as that which leads to strong 
 and continued life : so that the only information to 
 be got from the new term is that the life we are to 
 promote must be vigorous and long ; and this was 
 already implied in saying that it is the increase or 
 development of life that is the end. It will not do 
 to identify the notion with the mere balance of 
 physiological functions which, in common language, 
 
240 THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 appropriates to itself the term " health." We must 
 include the health of the soul as well as the health 
 of the body, and the health of society as well as the 
 health of the soul. The balance of mental and 
 social, as well as of physiological, functions, is im- 
 plied in the complex life of whose evolution we 
 form a part. To say that we are to promote this 
 balance of various functions, is to say nothing more 
 than that we are to promote the life into which 
 physical and mental and social factors enter. The 
 attempt to arrive at an end for conduct, by consid- 
 eration of the characteristics of evolution, has been 
 made without success. It has been found, too, that 
 " development " or " increase of life " does not admit 
 of translation into the language of hedonism : and 
 the question thus arises, how we are to define this 
 end, which we are unable to interpret in terms of 
 pleasure. 
 
 ways of What meaning can be given to the notion " in- 
 
 crease of life " as the end of conduct, without inter- 
 P r eting life in terms of pleasure ? Can we, the 
 question may be put, reach a " natural " good as dis- 
 tinct from " sensible good " or pleasure ? We must 
 discard at the outset any such " rational " view of 
 nature as gave colour to the Stoic doctrine by iden- 
 tifying nature with the universal reason. And we 
 must equally avoid the doctrine that reason regulative 
 of conduct is manifested in the constitution of man 
 either in a distinct faculty, such as " conscience," or 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 241 
 
 in the due regulation of the various impulses. Tren- 
 delenburg's teleological conception of human na- 
 ture, for instance, implies a rational element which 
 could not be got from the causal sequence traced by 
 evolution. 1 For he determines the essence of man 
 by reference to the inner end of his constitution, 
 and postulates an organic unity of impulses which, 
 in the form of conscience, protests against self- 
 seeking action on the . part of any single impulse. 
 But no other hierarchy of motives can be admitted 
 here than that produced by the natural law of evo- 
 lution; and this law can only show how one im- 
 pulse, or class of impulses, has become more author- 
 itative, by showing how it has become stronger or 
 more persistent : the other methods of evolving this 
 authority on the basis of naturalism, do so by means 
 of the pleasurable or painful consequences of motives 
 and actions. 
 
 There are two ways in which, on most or all either sub- 
 ethical theories, the attempt may be made to dis- i^^S*. 
 tinguish "good" from "bad" conduct. We may 
 either look to a subjective motive or impulse as 
 giving the means of distinction, or we may test 
 conduct by its conformity with an objective stand- 
 ard. If we like to make use of the terms self-pre- 
 servation and self-development, then these may refer 
 either to the subjective impulse which urges man 
 to preserve or develop his life, or to some objective 
 
 1 Naturrecht auf dem Grunde der Ethik, 2d ed., 1868. 
 
 Q 
 
242 THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 standard for estimating actions according as they 
 actually tend to prolong life or enrich it. Both 
 these possibilities are open to the theory of evolu- 
 tion. Although the subjective impulse is, of course, 
 a property of the individual, it may be the result 
 of the whole course of social development, and thus 
 take in others as well as self in the range of its 
 application. It is therefore necessary to examine 
 both methods of determination with some care, 
 especially as we are in no little danger of reaching 
 an illusory appearance of conclusiveness by allow- 
 ing the subjective standard to rest on the objective, 
 and the objective, in turn, on the subjective. 
 
 To begin with the subjective side. It may be 
 ard : most thought that we can point to some impulse, tendency, 
 Impulses* motive, or class of motives in the individual mind by 
 folio wing which the evolution of life will be promoted, 
 and that we are thus able to solve the question of 
 practical ethics, though our conception of what the 
 evolution of life connotes may still be in want of 
 exact definition. As already pointed out, such an 
 impulse (unless it depends on an objective standard) 
 must carry its own authority with it by its strength 
 or persistency. The case would, of course, be per- 
 fectly simple, if we could assert that the carrying 
 out of all impulses in one's nature was to be ap- 
 proved as tending to the development of life. Could 
 this assertion be made, there might be no difficulty 
 in ethics, or rather, there might be no ethics at all, 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 243 
 
 because there would be no difficulty in conduct. It 
 is obvious, however, that the development of one 
 natural tendency often conflicts with that of another 
 in the same individual, as well as with the tendencies 
 of other individuals. The course of evolution has 
 no doubt tended to modify, though it has not rooted 
 out, the impulses which are most prejudicial to in- 
 dividual and social welfare. But the increase of 
 wants as well as satisfactions which it has brought 
 about in human nature, makes it doubtful whether 
 it has on the whole tended to diminish the conflict 
 of motives. 
 
 Again, when it is said that a man should " be implies dis- 
 himself," or that this is his " strongest tendency," l tween per- 
 there is an implicit reference to a distinction between 
 a permanent and a transient, or a better and a worse self 
 self, and it seems to be imagined that this distinction 
 can be reduced to difference in degrees of strength. 
 But evolution has not enabled us to obviate Butler's 
 objection to taking the "strongest tendency" 
 meaning by this the tendency which is at any time 
 strongest as representing "nature." For it is an 
 undeniable fact that the tendency which for a time 
 is the strongest it may even be that which is 
 strongest throughout an individual life frequently 
 leads to a diminution of vital power on the part of 
 the agent, as well as to interference with the free 
 exercise of the vital powers of others. Some advan- 
 
 1 Cf. E. Simcox, Natural Law, p. 97. 
 
244 THE THEOEY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 tage is gained, perhaps, by substituting for " strong- 
 est " the nearly equivalent phrase " most persistent " 
 tendency. All those impulses which have in the 
 past served to promote life have been chosen out 
 and stored up as a sort of permanent basis for the 
 human fabric ; whereas other impulses, not so ad- 
 vantageous in their effects, have a less permanent 
 influence, though they are not less real. The more 
 regular or persistent class of impulses may, there- 
 fore, (the idea is) be taken as representing the 
 course of the evolution by which they have been 
 produced. 
 
 but includes To a large extent this distinction of two classes 
 iinpiiiseTin ^ impulses is justified. There seems no doubt that 
 the former, j.] ie soc j a ^ an( j wna t are usually termed moral, 
 feelings have a tendency to return into consciousness 
 after any temporary depression or exclusion, which 
 is not shared by some of the feelings with which 
 they most commonly conflict. Other impulses, not 
 usually classed as moral, no doubt share this char- 
 acteristic of persistency or recurrence. " The wish 
 for another man's property," says Darwin, "is as 
 persistent a desire as any that can be named/' The 
 selfish feelings have obviously this persistent char- 
 acter. But an evolutionist may perhaps maintain 
 that it is one of the defects of ordinary moral opinion 
 that it depreciates the necessity and value for life 
 of the selfish feelings, just because they are so strong 
 as to stand in need of no encouragement. And it is 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 245 
 
 not necessary that the evolutionist morality should 
 agree at all points with ordinary moral opinion or 
 moral intuition. It recognises, or ought to recognise 
 the agency of immoral as well as moral forces, ad- 
 mitting that it is by the action of both of these that 
 man as he is at present has been produced, although 
 the principle of the survival of the fittest has tended, 
 though by no means uniformly, towards the elimina- 
 tion of the immoral factor. We may admit, therefore, 
 that there is a pressure on the will of the average 
 individual towards certain kinds of conduct rather 
 than others, or, put more precisely, that while all 
 acts are performed in consequence of pressure on 
 the will, the pressure towards certain kinds of acts 
 is a permanent force which, although overcome for 
 the time, always tends to reassert itself, while the 
 tendency towards other acts inconsistent with these 
 is more intermittent and variable, and does not re- 
 assert itself in the same way. But this subjective 
 experience is so limited in accuracy and extent as 
 to be an unfit test of morality. 
 
 In the first place, selfish conduct is as necessary 
 for the preservation and development of man as 
 " altruistic " conduct, and must therefore have given 
 rise to an equally great and persistent pressure on 
 the will : so that the subjective criterion of persist- 
 ency leaves untouched what is often regarded as the 
 most difficult question of morals, the balance of social 
 and individual claims. In the second place, this 
 
246 
 
 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 define 
 nature of 
 morality. 
 
 is restricted subjective tendency is only a recurrence of antece- 
 hawts of dent advantageous characteristics, and does not lead 
 ' tmg ' us beyond the status quo, so that, if any progress is to 
 be made in the future, it will be only possible through 
 the pressure of new external conditions : no function 
 is left for any ethical ideal which points beyond 
 and cannot past and present habits of action. In the third place, 
 subjective tendency only enables us to say generally 
 that some acts or tendencies are more persistent 
 than others, without giving any further description 
 of what sort of acts these are. Were these tend- 
 encies or impulses a perfect guide to conduct, this 
 defect would be of little practical consequence. It 
 would prevent our having a definite ethical theory 
 only in circumstances in which no ethical theory 
 would be likely to be asked for. But the line be- 
 tween the more and less persistent motives is a 
 narrow and shifting one. The impulses which are 
 the residua of advantageous ancestral actions are 
 counteracted by other impulses, residua of actions 
 which would not be counted as moral, though we 
 inherit tendencies to them because they formed a 
 real part of our ancestral activity. We therefore 
 stand in need of some characteristic by which to 
 distinguish the one class of tendencies from the 
 other. And as the only subjective characteristic is 
 that of strength or persistency, and this has been 
 found insufficient, an objective standard is shown 
 to be necessary. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 247 
 
 The impossibility of the subjective test doing Thus sub- 
 duty alone without support from some objective Standard 
 criterion, is practically acknowledged by the writer ^ n e d w t " 
 who has discussed this part of the subject with depend on 
 greater penetration than any other investigator on 
 the same lines. "The average man," it is said, 
 " feels the pressure upon his own individual will 
 of all the unknown natural sequence of motive 
 which caused his ancestors to do on the whole 
 more often the right thing than the wrong " 1 or, 
 as we must read it without objective assumption, 
 " to do on the whole more often one class of acts 
 than another." The right must be defined simply 
 as that to which this " special feeling in the sub- 
 ject is directed," and it therefore becomes necessary 
 " to discover what descriptions of acts inspire this 
 feeling." 2 Thus, with greater facility than would 
 be permitted to a critic, we are made to pass 
 from the subjective to the objective method of 
 determination. 
 
 The question, What is right? is thus relinquished (6) objective 
 for the question, What is good ? Good is said to s 
 be of three kinds natural, sensible, and moral. 
 But as by sensible good is meant pleasure, 3 and 
 pleasure is not the end, and as by moral good 
 is meant "the pursuit of natural good under dif- 
 ficulties," 4 it follows that natural good is the 
 
 1 Simcox, Natural Law, p. 86. 2 Ibid., p. 87. 
 
 3 Ibid., p. 90. 4 Ibid., p. 99. 
 
248 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 end we seek. We have thus to determine, as 
 exactly as may be, this objective standard called 
 natural good. It is interpreted in two ways, which, 
 however, may be " not necessarily inconsistent " : 
 (a) "the perfection of the type as it is," and (/3) 
 " the absolute abundance and variety of vital 
 power." l 
 
 (a) confer- This phrase, "the perfection of the type as 
 type. it is," is somewhat misleading. When "the per- 
 fection of the type " is said to be the end, we 
 naturally regard the type as something that needs 
 to be brought to perfection, and ex Jiypothesi is not 
 perfect at present, or " as it is." But if " the per- 
 fection of the type as it is " is the standard, this 
 implies, unless the standard itself is faulty, that 
 the type is already perfect, and, therefore, that the 
 perfection spoken of is the characteristic of a thing 
 which conforms to the type, and not something to 
 which the type has to conform. This interpreta- 
 tion is confirmed by the fact that imperfection is 
 defined as " only departure from the class type." 2 
 Plainly, then, the objective standard meant is con- 
 formity to the type. What, then, is the type ? 
 Concerning things made by art the answer is easy. 
 The type, as Mr Stephen puts it, represents the 
 The type maximum of efficiency," 3 or, as we may say, is 
 
 defined as . 
 
 what that which most fully realises the purpose for 
 
 1 Simcox, Natural Law, p. 104. 2 Ibid., p. 87. 
 
 3 Science of Ethics, p. 76. 
 
X"' 
 
 i 
 
 THE EVOLUTIONIST END. ^49 
 
 >^L 
 
 which the thing was formed. The best bow is best serves 
 that which shoots truest and farthest with a lt] 
 relatively small expenditure of strength by the 
 archer ; that which best realises the purpose of a 
 bow is the typical bow. A similar explanation of 
 types may be given regarding animals modified by 
 artificial selection. The typical pointer or hunter 
 can be defined from this teleological point of 
 view ; and, as long as people lived in the belief 
 that all things were made for man, it was natural 
 to fix the type of each class by reference to the 
 human purpose it could best subserve. So also, 
 as long as people think that, whether all things 
 were made for man or not, all things may be 
 made use of by him, there will be a tendency 
 towards the same anthropomorphic interpretation 
 of types. If, then, the typical products of art, and, 
 to a large extent, the typical products of nature, 
 are those which best serve human purposes, or 
 best correspond with human ideals, how shall we 
 define the typical man himself the type which 
 it is our perfection to conform to ? " Every 
 reasoning agent," it may perhaps be allowed, 1 
 " represents a certain type ; " but the type can no 
 longer be defined merely as " maximum of effici- 
 ency," for it is the end or purpose of this efficiency 
 which now requires determination. In defining the 
 typical man, we must have no idea of final cause 
 
 1 Science of Ethics, p. 74. 
 
250 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 or purpose which is not rooted in the nature of 
 his organism. 
 
 How, then, shall we now determine the type in 
 conformity to which perfection consists ? 1 
 or as the The first answer to this seems to be, that the 
 type is what is normal, " what we have learned 
 to regard as the normal development of objects 
 belonging to " the class. 2 But the normal may 
 have either of two meanings it may, in the first 
 place, mean the usual or customary. This, how- 
 ever, would make the typical man mean the ordi- 
 nary or average man ; and the ideal of conformity 
 to the type would be reduced to doing the cus- 
 tomary thing, and not trying to be better than 
 one's neighbours. But it is evident that this sta- 
 tionary morality does not represent properly what 
 is fundamental in the theory of evolution : " what- 
 ever other duties men may acknowledge, they do 
 not look upon it as a duty to preserve the species 
 in statu quo. 1 ' 3 If natural science teaches one 
 thing more clearly than another, it is that the type, 
 like the individual, is not permanent, but the sub- 
 ject of gradual modifications. If the type is what 
 is normal, we must mean by " normal " something 
 
 1 Even were we to succeed in getting a satisfactory view of the 
 type, we should still have to leave room for the individuality of 
 each person, which is such that his function must differ in a 
 manner corresponding to his peculiar nature and surroundings 
 (cf. Lotze, Grundziige der praktischen Phil., p. 13 f.) 
 
 2 Simcox, Natural Law, p, 88. 3 Ibid., p. 100. 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 251 
 
 else than customary. But the only other meaning O r as what 
 of the word seems to imply a reference to a rule ^t vitality 
 either a rule imposed from without, or an inner or l aids de ' 
 
 velopment, 
 
 constitution or order. If the former alternative is that is, 
 adopted, then we may use another definition of 
 Mr Stephen's, and say that " the typical organism 
 is ... that organism which is best fitted for 
 all the conditions of life, or, in other words, 
 which has the strongest vitality ; " 1 and thus 
 have to fall back either on the notion of " adapta- 
 tion to environment," or on that of " strongest 
 vitality " the notion we are seeking to interpret. 
 If the other meaning, which the reference to a 
 rule may convey, be adopted, then we are met by 
 the fact that the inner order or constitution which 
 is to be our guide, can (from our present empirical 
 point of view) mean nothing different from the line 
 of development. And as we have already seen that 
 it is unsatisfactory to interpret this as equivalent 
 to adaptation to environment, or to increase of 
 definiteness, coherence, and heterogeneity, this prin- 
 ciple of conformity to the type is reduced to the 
 general principle which we have been attempting 
 to define more exactly increase of life. 
 
 Thus the first "determination of natural good os)Abun- 
 
 . dance and 
 
 as " perfection of the type is seen to reduce variety of 
 itself to the second, " absolute abundance and V1 
 variety of vital power." For the additional state- 
 
 1 Science of Ethics, p. 120. 
 
252 THE THEOKY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 ment, which, makes the highest excellence consist 
 in "conformity to the type as it is going to be, 
 but as, except in a few chosen specimens, it is 
 not yet discernible to be," l is unsatisfactory. For 
 to those " few chosen specimens " the end would 
 seem to be simply to remain as they are a con- 
 clusion which is hardly consistent for a writer 
 who regards morality as a continual progress to- 
 wards a higher life, a process of " climbing." 2 
 And, for the generality of men, there must be 
 some standard for determining what is " going to 
 be," and for certifying that the " few chosen speci- 
 mens " have realised this state in its perfect form. 
 Thus " conformity to the type as it is going to be," 
 equally with " perfection of [conformity to] the 
 type as it is," seems to be but another way of 
 saying " abundance and variety of vital power," or, 
 more fully stated, " the possession of abundant 
 faculties, active and passive, fully developed, and 
 in regular and equal exercise." 3 The question 
 thus comes to be how we are to determine this 
 " abundance of faculties." We cannot do so by 
 reference to such characteristics as increase in the 
 number and complexity of these faculties ; for a 
 criterion of this kind, as we have seen, is of no 
 
 1 Simcox, Natural Law, p. 104. 2 Ibid., p. 103. 
 
 3 Ibid., p. 89 ; cf . J. T. Punnet, Mind, x. 91 : " What the 
 progress -principle makes its aim and end is not complexity, but 
 the highest and choicest fruits of complexity the harmonious 
 unfolding of all the latent capacities of man." 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 253 
 
 assistance in deciding the most fundamental ethical 
 questions. To say that these faculties must be 
 " regular and equal " in their exercise, is to give 
 a merely formal canon. For how the equality 
 and regularity are to be brought about, which 
 faculties are to be supreme and which subordin- 
 ate what meaning equality can have in view of 
 the admitted diversity in a man's nature, are 
 questions left altogether undetermined. And to 
 describe the ideal or perfect universe as one in 
 which there is no conflict or collision, 1 is to give 
 a description which is negative as well as merely 
 formal. We are thus obliged to fall back on which fails 
 a subjective criterion, and say that the abundant subjective 6 
 life which it is the end of conduct to promote standard - 
 is a man's strongest tendencies, or the greatest 
 number of these. Natural good is determined by 
 " preferring out of all the rudimentary possibilities 
 existing in nature, the combination that harmon- 
 ises the greatest number of the strongest tenden- 
 cies." 2 We set out, be it remembered, to obtain a 
 characterisation of those acts to which the most 
 persistent tendencies of human nature lead us ; 
 and the conclusion we have arrived at is, that they 
 are the acts which harmonise the greatest number 
 of the strongest tendencies. The objective stand- 
 
 Iu 0f real tendencies" Natural Law, p. 98. But what 
 tendencies are not real ? 
 2 Natural Law, p. 98. 
 
254 
 
 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 Strongest 
 tendencies 
 the result 
 of past 
 activities, 
 
 ard is thus reduced to the subjective standard, 
 which it was brought in to explain and support. 
 
 Now these strongest tendencies, in the harmoni- 
 ous play of which natural good or perfection is said 
 to consist, are themselves the result of the courses 
 of conduct which have been most vigorous and suc- 
 cessful in ancestral organisms, and they may there- 
 fore, perhaps, be taken as a survival and index of 
 the antecedent state of human nature. The realis- 
 ation or, rather, continuation of human nature 
 as it has been and is, seems thus to be the ideal 
 which empirical evolution is able to set before 
 conduct, with this formal modification, that, while 
 the various impulses are, so far as possible, to have 
 free play given them, they should be developed in 
 a harmonious manner. It seems doubtful how far 
 this tendency towards harmony is properly suggested 
 by, or consistent with, evolution, which has implied 
 a ceaseless struggle of opposing forces. At any 
 rate, evolution does not seem competent to give 
 any principle of relative subordination between the 
 various impulses, such as might add reality to the 
 formal principle of harmony. But what it is 
 essential to lay stress on here is, that the only 
 end which empirical evolution seems able to estab- 
 lish is conformity to human nature as it is the 
 tendencies in it which are strongest and most 
 persistent. 
 
 We thus see that the attempt to explain on 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 255 
 
 empirical grounds what is meant by positing " life," 
 or "increase and variety of life," as the end of 
 action, is practically reduced to making the most 
 persistent impulses of human nature the guide of 
 conduct. But these impulses, it has been shown, 
 are only the survival or remnant of past stages in 
 the course of development, not anticipations of 
 future stages : so that evolution is in this way and thus 
 
 i i P -IIP i T give no ideal 
 
 incapable or giving an ideal or progress as the end for p rogr ess. 
 for conduct, and the last word it seems able to give 
 us as a guide for action is that we should tread in 
 the places where the footprints of ancestral conduct 
 have left the deepest impress. The ideal of such 
 a system is summed up in the new Beatitude, 
 "Blessed is he that continueth where he is." It 
 is probably just because the empirical aspect of 
 evolution seems so little able to yield an end for 
 human conduct corresponding to the actual course 
 of evolution which has been progress that no 
 thorough attempt has been made to develop a 
 system of morals from the principle just reached. 
 It is true that systems have been worked out by 
 moralists who have taken human nature as their 
 standard, and that Trendelenburg, at any rate, 
 expressly includes historical development in his 
 conception of man. But both Trendelenburg and 
 a moralist like Butler (who has as yet no conception 
 of the gradual modifications of human character 
 and tendencies produced by evolution) have a view 
 
256 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 of human nature essentially distinct from that 
 which has been called the " naturalistic " view. 1 
 For both assume a definite rational organisation of 
 impulses similar to that taught in Plato's analogy 
 between the individual man and a political consti- 
 tution, so that the whole nature, or human nature 
 as a whole, cannot be identified with the impulses 
 which strength at any time makes most persistent, 
 but depends upon the rational allotment of function 
 and measure to each. 
 
 summary. In summing up the argument of the preceding 
 chapters, it is necessary to refer again to the dis- 
 cussion carried on in chapter vi. on the relation 
 between egoism and altruism as affected by the 
 Difficulty of theory of evolution. This discussion was not in- 
 indivixiuTf serted in order to throw an additional obstacle in 
 
 and social fa Q wa y obtaining an ethical end from the em- 
 ends. J 
 
 pirical theory of evolution. It is an integral part 
 of an attempt to estimate the ethical value of the 
 evolution -theory. The antinomy between the in- 
 dividual and social standpoints cannot be solved 
 by a theory of morality which does not recognise 
 that the individual, in his rational nature, is not 
 
 i Cf. Trendelenburg, Naturrecht, p. 45 : " Von der philoso- 
 phischen Seite kann es kein anderes Princip der Ethik geben als 
 das menschliche Wesen an sich, d. h., das menschliche Wesen in 
 der Tiefe seiner Idee und im Reichthum seiner historischen 
 Entwickelung. Beides gehort zusammen. Denn das nur His- 
 torische wiirde blind und das nur Ideale leer." 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 257 
 
 opposed to other individuals, but in reality one with 
 them. The theory of evolution certainly seems to 
 go a long way towards establishing the unity of the 
 individual with the race, and in substituting an 
 organic connection between them, in place of the 
 almost contingent reciprocal relations spoken of in 
 earlier empirical theories. But when we come to 
 inquire into this unity of organic connection, at- 
 tempting still to keep to the purely empirical point 
 of view, we find that the old difficulties return, that 
 it must be recognised that the connection is em- 
 pirically incomplete, and that it gives way at 
 the very places where a firm basis for the theory 
 of morals is required. It was in this way that, 
 quite apart from this opposition between the in- 
 dividual and the whole, the empirical character 
 of the theory prevented our getting from it any 
 clear and consistent notion of the ethical end it 
 leads to. 
 
 It appeared at first that the ethics of evolution, Hedonistic 
 when interpreted empirically, might be easily re- tfonof evoi- 
 conciled with the older theory of hedonism, by 
 identifying life with pleasure holding that the 
 highest or most evolved life is that which contains 
 most pleasure, and that increase of pleasure is 
 therefore the end of conduct. In this way the end 
 of evolutionism would be reduced to the end of 
 utilitarianism. Some utilitarians, on the other hand, 
 sought to get rid of the difficulties of their calculus, 
 
 B 
 
258 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 by the assumption that the greatest pleasure would be 
 found by following the direction of evolution. But, 
 around both points of view, and the correspondence 
 they assumed to exist between pleasure and evolu- 
 tion, special difficulties were seen to gather. Any 
 hedonistic theory might be met by the assertion 
 that life is essentially a painful experience, and 
 pleasure unattainable ; and although the grounds 
 on which this assertion was made seemed to be 
 distinctly erroneous, and hedonism did not appear 
 to be an impossible theory of conduct, yet a similar 
 objection told with greater force against the com- 
 bination of evolutionism and hedonism. For it 
 holds the double position that the end is to pro- 
 mote life, and that life is to be promoted by adding 
 to pleasure ; or else, that the end is pleasure, but 
 that pleasure is to be got by following evolution. 
 It postulates, therefore, that the progress of life 
 tends, and tends even in a proportionate degree, to 
 the increase of pleasure. Yet we could obtain no 
 proof that this progress does, as a matter of fact, 
 increase pleasure in any regular way. On the con- 
 trary, the facts of experience seemed to show that 
 life and pleasure do not advance proportionately, 
 nor even always concomitantly. But a still more 
 important and fundamental objection to the hedon- 
 istic form of evolutionism was deduced from the 
 nature of pleasure itself; for it can be modified 
 indefinitely, and always follows in the wake of 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 259 
 
 function. Thus the sole intelligible account we 
 can give of what conduct will bring the greatest 
 pleasure is, that it is the conduct which calls forth 
 the greatest amount of successful energising, that 
 which employs the greatest number and the strong- 
 est of the human faculties. Hence, instead of being 
 able to measure life by pleasure, we were driven to 
 interpret pleasure in terms of life. 
 
 And perhaps at first sight it seemed that the NO indepen- 
 dent ethical 
 theory of evolution could lead us beyond the pleas- ideal afford- 
 
 ure- basis of older Naturalism. But, when the theory of 
 matter was examined more closely, without depart- evolution - 
 ing from the empirical point of view, it was found 
 that the notions put forward were unsatisfactory, - 
 that they did not represent the progressive nature 
 of the course of evolution, and that their apparent 
 force fell away before logical analysis. It became 
 evident, in the first place, that no appropriate end 
 of human conduct could be derived from the nature 
 of evolution in general. It is true that adaptation 
 to environment is necessary for life ; but to put for- 
 ward such adaptation as the end for action, is to set 
 up a practical goal which corresponds but ill with 
 the facts from which it professes to be taken,, mak- 
 ing the theory which is supposed to account for 
 progress establish no end by pursuit of which pro- 
 gress becomes possible for human action. Further 
 than this, it neglects a factor in evolution as neces- 
 sary to it as is adaptation to environment the ele- 
 
260 THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION. 
 
 ment, namely, of variation. A theory which took 
 the latter as well as the former of these factors into 
 account seemed, in the next place, to be given by 
 those general characteristics which are said to mark 
 all progress increase of definiteness, coherence, 
 and heterogeneity. But from these, again, it was 
 found impossible to elicit a coherent and consistent 
 rule for determining right and wrong in conduct, or 
 a definite end for action: they were too abstract 
 and mechanical to suit the living organism of hu- 
 man conduct ; and we were thus driven back on the 
 more general statement that " life " or the " increase 
 of life " is the end after which we should strive. 
 In inquiring into the meaning which could be given 
 to this end, without interpreting it as pleasure, it 
 was found, after tracing it through various forms of 
 expression, that it reduced itself to making a man's 
 strongest and most persistent impulses both stand- 
 ard and end. And this proved to be not only an 
 uncertain and shifting guide for conduct, but an 
 imperfect representation of what was to be expect- 
 ed from a progressive, because evolutionist, ethics. 
 For these persistent impulses could only be re- 
 garded as the survival of past activities, and conse- 
 quently, contained no ideal beyond that of continu- 
 ing in the old paths, and re-treading an already 
 well-beaten course. Just as from the external end 
 of adaptation to environment, so from this internal 
 
THE EVOLUTIONIST END. 261 
 
 or subjective principle, no ideal for progress, ^or 
 any definite end of action, could be obtained. 
 
 It would appear, therefore, that the theory of 
 evolution however great its achievements in 
 the realm of natural science is almost resultless 
 in ethics. It only remains now to inquire whether 
 this want of competency to determine practical 
 ends may not be due to the superficiality of the 
 ordinary empirical interpretation of evolution, which 
 has hitherto been adhered to. 
 
262 
 
 CHAPTER IX. 
 
 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 THE peculiarity of the conclusion we have reached 
 is, that the theory which is used to explain the 
 nature of progress, seems unable to give any canon 
 or end for conduct which points out the way for 
 progressive advance. The view of human nature 
 became unsatisfactory just at the critical point 
 when we attempted to get at a knowledge of its end 
 or final cause, which would give unity and purpose 
 to action. To say that the end is increase of life 
 or function appeared a merely formal notion unless 
 we defined life as pleasure, while pleasure itself 
 was found to be unintelligible except as perform- 
 ance of function. This uncertainty seems to indi- 
 cate a certain superficiality in the ordinary empiri- 
 cal way of looking at evolution. 1 
 
 1 The empirical interpretation of evolution is that adopted by 
 the majority of evolutionists, but is not essential to the truth of 
 the theory. A protest against it is entered by Mr Wallace, though 
 in the somewhat crude form of postulating supernatural inter- 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 2G3 
 
 The principles involved in the theory of evolution i. principles 
 are, in brief, as follows. In the first place, it shows th* theory of 
 that there is a tendency, brought about by natural evolution - 
 selection, for organisms to harmonise with or be- 
 come adapted to their environment a tendency, 
 that is to say, towards unity of organism and envi- 
 ronment, and, in so far as external conditions are 
 uniform, towards a general unity of life. In the 
 second place, the theory implies variation in 
 organisms, produced either by the unequal in- 
 cidence of external forces, or by the spontane- 
 ous action of the organism, or by both causes 
 combined. The mere increase in the number 
 of living organisms leads to a modification of the 
 conditions of life by which new variations are 
 encouraged. And this tendency to variation in 
 organisms not merely the diversity of external 
 environment is perpetually complicating the con- 
 ditions which the former tendency, that towards 
 unity, helps to bring into harmony. It thus hap- 
 pens that there is, in the third place, a continual 
 process of readjustment and oscillation between 
 the tendency towards unity and that towards va- 
 riety, which, through opposition and conciliation, 
 produces continuity in nature. Each newly formed 
 
 ference for the production of certain classes of phenomena (cf. 
 Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection, p. 359), at the 
 same time that his conception of nature does not seem to differ 
 otherwise from that of Hiickel. 
 
264 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 unity between organism and environment is broken 
 by a new variation of the organism or of the envi- 
 ronment, which further complicates the problem to 
 be solved by the unifying process, and gives scope 
 for a more intricate and more comprehensive re- 
 adjustment. Unity, Variety, and Continuity are 
 thus the three principles implied in the theory of 
 evolution. 1 
 
 2. unsucces- It is from these principles that the attempt has 
 tioiTofthese been made to show the ethical bearing of evolution. 
 
 toS?! The first of them > Unit y> is represented in the 
 theory that would make adaptation to environment 
 the end of conduct ; and the second is represented 
 ethically in the doctrine suggested by Mr Spencer, 
 that the degree of morality depends on the de- 
 gree of complexity in act and motive. But both 
 of these views are obviously one-sided, even from 
 the point of view of empirical evolution. Taken 
 together, the principles on which they depend make 
 up that law of continuous and progressive advance 
 which may be regarded as expressing the essential 
 characteristic of the theory. And from this more 
 general and accurate expression of it, we might 
 have expected to have been able to elicit the contri- 
 bution which evolution has to make to the deter- 
 mination of the ethical end. But after examin- 
 
 1 The reference in the above to Kant, Werke, iii. 438 ff. , is obvi- 
 ous ; but it is nevertheless a true account of the principles in- 
 volved in the theory of evolution. 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 265 
 
 ing the various forms which it may take, we have 
 been unable to obtain from it a principle of action. 
 In inquiring into the reason which has made 
 the theory of evolution seemingly so barren in its 
 ethical consequences, the first point which requires 
 attention is that the characteristics of Unity, Vari- 
 ety, and Continuity are treated by it not as princi- 
 ples involved in development, but as theories in- 
 ferred from, or superinduced upon, the facts of 
 development. We are led by facts to suppose 
 certain hypothetical laws namely, that organisms 
 tend to harmony with their environment, but that 
 there are certain causes promoting variation, and, 
 consequently, that the history of all life is that of 
 a continuous process towards more comprehensive 
 uniformities, passing always into more intricate 
 variations. Additional facts are compared with 
 these hypothetical causes, and, by their ability to 
 explain such facts, the hypotheses are raised to the 
 position of laws of nature, and are confidently ap- 
 plied to account for new phenomena of the same 
 kind. But when we pass beyond facts lying imme- 
 diately on the plane of those from which our laws 
 have been gathered, it is to follow an insufficient 
 analogy if we interpret them by theories only shown 
 to belong to the former order. And this becomes 
 still more obvious when the change is not merely 
 to a different order of facts, but to a different way 
 of looking at facts, as is the case in the transition 
 
 
266 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 from the point of view of knowledge to that of 
 action. 
 
 notasde- But there is another way in which the principles 
 Tprinc?!.^ of Unity, Variety, and Continuity may be regarded, 
 ^perien^e; Instead of being simply generalisations gathered 
 from experience and depending upon it, they may 
 be founded on a principle which is itself the basis 
 of the possibility of experience. Of course, no one 
 would think of denying that it is to the accumulated 
 mass of experienced facts that these laws owe their 
 prominence in modern scientific opinion, and their 
 acceptance by the judgment of the best scientists. 
 But the process by which a man has been led to lay 
 hold of such principles is one thing ; their logical 
 position in relation to experience quite another. 
 Our definite recognition of the laws may very well 
 be the result of experience, at the same time that 
 the principle of Continuity is presupposed in our 
 having experience at all. As long as we kept to the 
 ground from which we started, and did not attempt 
 to get beyond the categories of causality and reci- 
 procity, our progress might seem to be easy enough. 
 Although their logical relations may be misconceived, 
 the laws are, of course, actually there, in experience : 
 their application to the successive phenomena of 
 nature remains the same, and may be duly appre- 
 hended. The extension of facts into laws is ex- 
 plained by the scientific imagination, and we do not 
 stay to inquire into the conditions on which the 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 267 
 
 scientific imagination works and has applicability 
 to experience. But, when we try to pass from effi- 
 cient cause to the notion of purpose or of morality, 
 we find ourselves driven back on the fundamental 
 constitution of knowledge, and see that it is only 
 through the unifying and relating action of a self- 
 conscious subject that knowledge is possible or things 
 exist for us at all. And this is the reason why we 
 are able to say that the Unity or Continuity of 
 nature is a principle or law of experience. 1 Were 
 that principle not involved in knowledge, there 
 would be no world of nature for us at all. The 
 empirical interpretation of evolution, which has 
 been hitherto adopted, has made the negative side 
 of this truth sufficiently evident : it has shown that 
 we cannot, on empirical ground, reach the end or 
 purpose of human nature. The question thus arises, 
 whether what may be called the " metaphysical " or 
 "transcendental" interpretation of evolution can 
 show the reason of this defect and suggest a 
 remedy. 
 
 The insufficiency of the empirical way of look- (&) no logical 
 ing at things is seen most clearly when we at- 
 
 tempt to make the transition just referred to, and ^^0^ 
 determine an end for conduct. It seems often to tinal cause - 
 
 1 Cf. Stirling, Secret of Hegel, ii. 615 : " One grand system, 
 unity of type, all this must be postulated from the very constitu- 
 tion of human reason ; but from the very constitution of experi- 
 ence as well, it can never be realised in experience. " 
 
268 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 be thought that, in pointing out the tendency of 
 affairs, we are, at the same time, prescribing the 
 end towards which human endeavour ought to be 
 directed. Now, it is very difficult to say how far an 
 empirical method enables us to anticipate tendencies 
 of this kind at all. Even from the historical point 
 of view the conditioning circumstances are so com- 
 plicated that it is by no means easy to predict the 
 result of their combination. It is argued, however, 
 by Schaffle, 1 that we are at least able to see as far 
 as the next stage in the series of historical progress, 
 and this is thought to lead to the conclusion that 
 we should make this next stage of development our 
 end : further than it we cannot see, and therefore 
 need not provide. If, then, we have no ultimate end 
 for conduct, at least we need never be without a 
 proximate end and one which is always changing 
 with the course of events. Instead, therefore, of 
 saying that we should take no thought for the 
 morrow, the contention would seem to be that we 
 should live for the morrow but take no thought for 
 the day after. But here the altered point of view 
 is scarcely concealed. From the discussion of effi- 
 cient causes we proceed all at once to decide upon 
 ends or final causes. We have shown (let it be 
 granted) that, taking account of the present position 
 and mode of action of the forces we are able to 
 examine, they will modify the present state of affairs 
 
 1 Bau und Leben des socialen Korpers, ii. 68. 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 269 
 
 in a certain known manner. To-day we are in state 
 A ; to-morrow we shall be in, or well on the way 
 towards, state Ab ; therefore, runs the conclusion, 
 implied or expressed, we ought to make Ab our end. 
 But this is more than a fallacy due to the confusion 
 of the two meanings of " end." The conclusion to 
 which it leads is inconsistent with, or at least shows 
 the one-sidedness of, the premisses from which it was 
 drawn. For, if Ab is really the next term in the 
 series of historical progress, our making it our end 
 can neither help nor hinder its realisation. If, on 
 the other hand, there is really a meaning in our 
 making the world-end our own, then we cannot 
 bring that end, the realisation of which is conceived 
 as still in the future, under the category of efficient 
 causality, and say with confidence that it is the next 
 stage in the course of events. 
 
 The idea does not work itself out in the same way 3. Difference 
 as an efficient cause works in the processes of nature. 
 
 "We might indeed speak perhaps with some intel- ^ o d tele * 
 ligible meaning of the tendency of evolution be- 
 coming conscious in man, and then working towards 
 its own realisation as a fixed idea. So far as the 
 simpler representations are concerned, this mode of 
 action has been clearly illustrated in Mr Bain's 
 writings ; and the characteristic is not limited to 
 the less complex kinds of mental objects. The idea 
 is, in its own nature, a force tending both to exist 
 in consciousness and to realise itself through the 
 
270 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 motor energies. 1 Consciousness of an end is a motive 
 to action. Thus the notion of final cause includes 
 that of efficient cause ; but the two are not convert- 
 ible. The idea of an end, being conceived by reason, 
 cannot be described simply as a tendency become 
 conscious. It has passed into the region in which 
 various conceptions are, or may be, competing against 
 one another, and the resultant is decided on upon 
 grounds which may be called subjective since they 
 proceed from conscious determination. However 
 the laws of this conscious determination may be ex- 
 pressed, they are not to be identified with the natural 
 sequence of events as it may be conceived to exist 
 independently of the individual consciousness. What 
 seems the tendency of things may be altered or 
 modified upon some ground of preference by the 
 conscious subject. In passing therefore to the work- 
 ing out of a rational or mental idea such as is im- 
 plied in the conception of an end we can no longer 
 fully represent our notions by means of the deter- 
 mined temporal succession called causality. 
 These no- Thus the empirical standpoint leaves the case 
 nectedby incomplete. A man might quite reasonably' ask 
 empiricism, ^y ^ Q s } lou i ( j a( j pt as maxims of conduct the laws 
 seen to operate in nature. The end, in this way, is 
 not made to follow from the natural function of man. 
 It is simply a mode in which the events of the world 
 
 1 Cf. Fouille'e, Critique des systemes de morale contemporains, 
 p. 13 ff. 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 271 
 
 occur ; and we must, therefore, give a reason why it 
 should be adopted as his end by the individual agent. 
 To him there may be no sufficient grounds of induce- 
 ment to become " a self-conscious agent in the evolu- 
 tion of the universe." From the purely evolutionist 
 point of view, no definite attempt has been made 
 to solve the difficulty. It seems really to go no 
 deeper than Dr Johnson's reply to Boswell, when 
 the latter plagued him to give a reason for action : 
 " ' Sir,' said he, in an animated tone, ' it is driving 
 on the system of life/" 1 When any further an- 
 swer is attempted now to the question, it appears to 
 be on hedonistic grounds. 
 
 But it is not certain that the next stage of even with 
 development will bring more pleasure along with anceTf 8 " 
 it than the present. Enough has already been hedonism - 
 said of the difficulties and uncertainties which 
 surround any attempt to interpret evolution as 
 tending constantly to increased pleasure. It may 
 be thought, however, that, if neither optimism nor 
 pessimism is the conclusion to which we are led, 
 the modified doctrine of what is called Meliorism 
 may be accepted. And this theory which holds 
 that the world is improving, that the balance of 
 good over evil, or that of pleasure over pain, is 
 on the increase might seem to form a convenient 
 support to the present doctrine. Tor it may ap- 
 pear to follow from it that, if the next stage in 
 
 1 Boswell's Life of Johnson, chap. liv. 
 
272 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 the world-process that towards which evolution 
 is tending is known, then we should make it 
 our end to accelerate this stage, as it will be one 
 which brings with it a better state of affairs than 
 the present. But not even the most enthusiastic 
 " meliorist " has tried to show anything more than 
 that his doctrine holds true in general, and that, 
 although progress has many receding waves, the 
 tide of human happiness is rising. But we cannot 
 tell how great these receding waves may be ; nor 
 may we say that our action can have no power 
 to check them. It follows, therefore, that, in 
 judging of any special and temporary movement 
 of events (and it is not pretended that our antici- 
 patory knowledge of the future can extend far), 
 we cannot assume that the second stage will be 
 better than the first, or that voluntary modifica- 
 tion of it if that be possible might not improve 
 both the immediate result and its later conse- 
 quences. It becomes necessary, therefore, to com- 
 pare the value of the two by the directly pleasurable 
 effects they may be expected to have, so that we 
 are driven back to test the course of evolution 
 by reference to some other principle. The further 
 we go in examining an empirical theory, the clearer 
 does it become that it can make no nearer approach 
 to the discovery of an ethical end, than to point 
 out what courses of action are likely to be the 
 pleasantest, or what tendencies to action the strong- 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 273 
 
 est: while this can only be done within certain 
 limits. The doctrine of evolution itself, when 
 added to empirical morality, only widens our view 
 of the old landscape does not enable us to pass 
 from "is" to "ought," or from efficient to final 
 cause, any more than the telescope can point 
 beyond the sphere of spatial quantity. 
 
 We are endeavouring to get at the idea or end New point 
 of human nature in an impossible way when we tro 
 attempt to reach it on purely empirical lines, and teleol sy 
 think that, if we work long enough on them, we 
 are sure to come to it. In the same way it was 
 formerly thought by physiologists that, if we thor- 
 oughly examined the brain with microscope and 
 scalpel, we should come upon the seat of the soul 
 at last, while psychologists were fain to believe 
 that, in addition to all our presentations of ob- 
 jects, we had also a presentation of the subject or 
 thinking being. The mistake of both was in 
 imagining that the soul was a thing amongst other 
 things, or a presentation amongst other presenta- 
 tions, instead of the subject and condition of there 
 being either things or thoughts at all. Of a similar 
 character is the attempt to get at an end or final 
 cause without leaving the point of view of efficient 
 causality. Were it successful, it would reduce final 
 cause to mechanism. To look upon man or upon 
 nature as manifesting an end implies an idea or 
 notion of the object as a whole, over and above 
 
 s 
 
274 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 the mutual determination of its various parts, and 
 thus necessitates the contemplation of it " as though 
 an understanding contained the ground of the unity 
 of the multiplicity of its empirical laws/' 1 It is 
 the attempt to get at an external purpose for 
 objects of experience that has made teleology be 
 looked upon askance by men of science. A con- 
 ception of this kind went far to vitiate physics in 
 the middle ages, till it was, with justice, strictly 
 excluded from the scientific interpretation of nature 
 by the leaders of modern philosophy. 2 But tele- 
 ology does not stand or fall with this external form 
 of it, which takes its illustrations from the products 
 of the factory, not from the manifestations of life, 3 
 and which is really only mechanism misunderstood, 
 necessary in The conception of an end is forced upon us in 
 me, 81 ' considering life, because then it is necessary to take 
 account of the being as organised, and therefore as 
 a whole. In the investigation of nature, on the 
 other hand, things may be apprehended without 
 relation to the conception of the whole ; and tele- 
 ology, therefore, seems to be unnecessary. The 
 notion of purpose, it is often said, is essential 
 to biology, but out of place in physical science. 
 But when we look on the world as a whole, the 
 
 1 Kant, Werke, v. 187 (Kr. d. Urt., Einl. iv.) 
 
 2 Descartes, Princ. pliil., iii. 3, i. 28 ; Bacon. De augm., iii. 5, 
 Novum organum, ii. 2. 
 
 3 Cf. Kant, Werke, v. 387 (Kr. d. Urt., 65). 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 275 
 
 notion of end or purpose is introduced, and the 
 functions of its various parts conceived from a new 
 point of view. And the end of an organism can 
 only be partially understood, when that organism 
 is conceived as a whole apart from its environment. 
 It is only a partial manifestation or example of the 
 more perfect reality in which things are to be 
 regarded as not merely conditioned and condition- 
 ing, but as revelations of purpose. But, although 
 the notion of purpose cannot be dispensed with in 
 considering organic nature, the teleological notions 
 we form of living things are imperfect and "ab- 
 stract." Thus the organism is often, more or less 
 explicitly, judged by its utility for some human 
 purpose. In these cases the end is clearly 'an 
 external and dependent one. And, when the 
 adaptation of its parts is spoken of in relation to 
 its type or perfect form, a conception is involved 
 over and above what can be inferred from the 
 nature of the organism in itself. The notion of the 
 end depends upon a rational ideal, which passes 
 beyond the causal interrelation of parts to the 
 conception of the organism as a whole, whose 
 function is necessarily related to its environment. 
 
 Our knowledge of the ends of the lower animals and lif 
 is really much more imperfect than our knowledge 
 of the human end. For the only life we really 
 know is self-conscious life, and that we are unable 
 to attribute to them. We know their life only 
 
276 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 by conjecture, our knowledge of it being but an 
 abstraction from our own consciousness. The 
 ethical, as Trendelenburg puts it, 1 is the higher 
 stage of the process, a lower stage of which is the 
 organic. The purpose, which is conceived as blind 
 or unconscious in nature, becomes conscious and 
 voluntary in man. But our notion of the former 
 is simply an abstraction from the free and con- 
 scious purpose which characterises our own activity. 
 The conception of life is only known to us as is 
 only an element or moment in our own self- 
 consciousness. And life which is not self-con- 
 scious can only be judged in relation to the self- 
 consciousness which contains in itself the explana- 
 tion both of life and of nature. The germ of truth 
 in the old mechanical teleology may perhaps be 
 seen in this way. For it had right on its side in 
 so far as it referred everything to the self -con- 
 sciousness manifested in man ; it was mistaken 
 only in so far as it made things relative to his 
 needs and desires. The teleological anthropomor- 
 phism which judges all things according to their 
 correspondence with human purposes, must be tran- 
 scended, equally with the speculative anthropo- 
 morphism which frames the unseen world in the 
 likeness of the phenomena of our present experi- 
 ence. But to attempt to escape from what is some- 
 times called anthropomorphism the reference of 
 
 1 Historische Beitriige zur Philosophic, iii. 165. 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 277 
 
 the nature and purpose of things to self -conscious- 
 ness, as expressive of the ultimate reality is to 
 attempt to escape from thought itself, and makes 
 one's thinking from the beginning void and con- 
 tradictory. 
 
 Now this reference to self has been omitted in 4. Reference 
 
 . . T , ,. ^ Tr , toself-con- 
 
 our consideration of empirical evolution. We nave SC i usness 
 taken the purely objective ground of science, and % 
 we have admitted what science has told us of how 
 all sorts of things came to be, how man appeared 
 on the earth, gradually adapted himself to his sur- 
 roundings and modified them how sentiments ex- 
 panded, customs grew, and one institution developed 
 out of another. But science shows us all this only 
 as an external process of events in space and time 
 a process in which the preceding determines each 
 succeeding state, and all parts are united together. 
 It does not show us the process from the inside. 
 And, in the end, it can do no more than point to- 
 wards, without reaching, the comprehensive idea of 
 a whole, by reference to which idea all the members 
 of the whole are determined, in such a way that it 
 is insufficient to look upon one as causing another, 
 and with the others making up the aggregate ; since 
 each member only exists for the sake of the whole, 
 and the idea of the whole precedes the parts which 
 constitute it. 1 The teleological conception thus 
 necessarily leads us beyond the ordinary categories 
 
 1 Cf. Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik, iii. 228. 
 
278 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 of science, by which all things are conceived as con- 
 nected causally in space and time. But the scien- 
 tific theories that we have been discussing do not 
 recognise this altered point of view ; and, without 
 giving any justification for the change of stand- 
 point, lay down the moral law that we ought to 
 aim at the realisation of something which can only 
 be described as a mental conception or idea. Here 
 a double change in point of view is involved. We 
 are no longer considering a process going on outside 
 us, in which the reference to self may be fairly 
 ignored, but we put ourselves in relation to this 
 external order : and we do so, not merely as cogni- 
 tive, but as active as the potential source of actions 
 which we say " ought " to be performed by us. 
 (a) made The assumption involved in the former change is 
 attempt^ 6 tna ^ m &de by comparative or evolutionist psycho- 
 
 > w ^ en tt attempts to play the part of a theory 
 peif-con- of knowledge. The development of impressions 
 
 sciousness. 
 
 and ideas is made to pass upwards to more compli- 
 cated stages, till it reaches the point at which the 
 individual, conceived as determined by external 
 forces and reacting upon them, becomes conscious 
 of itself as a subject of knowledge and source of 
 action. This transition from the category of caus- 
 ality to self - consciousness is, in some systems 
 that of Mr Spencer, for example either concealed 
 or held to with no firm grasp. Throughout his 
 objective treatment of psychology, it would seem 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 279 
 
 that Mr Spencer is evolving mind or self-conscious- 
 ness out of the process in which simple relations of 
 matter and motion form the lowest stage, and reflex 
 action is that which approaches most nearly to hav- 
 ing mental characteristics. And, from this objective 
 point of view, he speaks of his philosophy as an 
 interpretation of "the detailed phenomena of life, 
 mind, and society, in terms of matter, motion, and 
 force." l But when he discusses the subjective side, 
 he admits that it is entirely unique and sui generis? 
 and adopts what is known as the "two aspects" 
 theory the theory that mind cannot be accounted 
 for as derived from matter, any more than matter 
 can be accounted for as derived from mind, but that 
 they are both phases of one ultimate and unknown 
 reality. 3 This admission involves a practical acknow- 
 ledgment that it is impossible to arrive at conscious- 
 ness or at subjectivity by a process of natural devel- 
 opment. We must, it affirms, postulate two aspects 
 or phases of existence, or two lines of development, 
 connected probably in their ultimate reality, but, as 
 known to us, distinct from one another, and without 
 mutual influence. 
 
 The doctrine that a reference to self-conscious- Reference 
 
 i . . . i -i i to self-con- 
 
 neSS is implied in experience, may perhaps be made SC i usness, 
 
 clearer by considering a criticism to which it has 
 
 1 First Principles, 194, p. 556. 
 
 2 Principles of Psychology, 56, i. 140. 
 
 3 Ibid., 272, 273, i. 624 ff. 
 
280 OX THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 recently been subjected by an able psychological 
 writer. Professor W. James writes as follows : 
 
 " The doctrine of the post-Kan tians, that all knowledge is 
 also self-knowledge, seems to flow from this confusion [be- 
 tween the psychologist's standpoint and the standpoint of 
 the feeling upon which he is supposed to be making his re- 
 port]. Empirically, of course, an awareness of self accom- 
 panies most of our thinking. But that it should be needed 
 to make that thinking ' objective ' is quite another matter. 
 4 Green-after-red-and- other- than-it ' is an absolutely complete 
 object of thought, ideally considered, and needs no added 
 element. The fallacy seems to arise from some such reflec- 
 tion as this, that since the feeling is what it feels itself to be, 
 so it must feel itself to be what it is namely, related to each 
 of its objects. That the last is covers much more ground 
 than the first, the philosopher here does not notice. The 
 first is signifies only the feeling's inward quality ; the last is 
 covers all possible facts about the feeling, relational facts, 
 which can only be known from outside points of view, like 
 that of the philosopher himself." l 
 
 Now it seems to me that the real confusion here 
 
 is between the point of view of experience, and the 
 
 point of view of reflection on experience, and that it 
 
 is not the " post-Kantians " who confuse the two 
 
 points of view. The "post-Kantians" by whom 
 
 Professor James means T. H. Green and the 
 
 writers commonly associated with him habitu- 
 
 thoughnot ally occupy the latter standpoint. They do not 
 
 of expert?* holcl that " all knowledge is also self-knowledge," in 
 
 ence ' the sense that " an awareness of self accompanies 
 
 most [or all] of our thinking." When we have this 
 
 1 Mind, ix. 21. 
 
x^ 
 
 ff " 
 
 ff UNI\ 
 
 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 281 
 
 ^^ 
 
 empirical " awareness of self," our object is the 
 more or less distinct contents of perception, &c., 
 which make up the empirical ego. But this know- 
 ledge of the empirical ego, equally with knowledge 
 of external nature, implies logically the action of logically 
 self -consciousness. When we reflect upon experi- e " 
 ence, one constant element is seen to be implied in 
 it the reference to a subject of knowledge and 
 feeling. Certainly " post-Kantians " do not imagine 
 as Professor James seems himself to imagine and 
 to think they do that a feeling feels itself, or an 
 object knows itself. " Green-after-red-and-other- 
 than-it " is for them, as for him, if not " an abso- 
 lutely complete object of thought," yet relatively 
 complete. It may be apprehended alone as a part 
 of experience. But reflection on experience shows 
 that it, like any other object of thought, depends 
 upon a knowing subject. The " post-Kantians " do 
 not assert that knowing an object involves for the 
 individual knower actual consciousness of what his 
 knowledge implies, any more than they would say 
 that the "plain man" is already a metaphysician. 
 But they hold that reflection on experience shows 
 that self-reference, or reference to a subject, is a 
 logical condition of there being experience at all. 
 So far from confusing the two standpoints, they 
 require carefully to emphasise their difference, lest 
 the actual content of a state of consciousness in the 
 individual man be held to be equivalent to the 
 
282 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 grounds or conditions of that state of conscious- 
 ness. 
 
 The reason why there is even an apparent plausi- 
 bility in the attempt to get at a natural develop- 
 ment of self-consciousness, is that the reference to 
 self is, from the outset, implicitly, but logically, 
 assurfted in tracing the sequence of events which 
 forms the subject-matter of the theory of evolution, 
 while the course of development does nothing more 
 than render its implication explicit. Self-conscious- 
 ness is not something that exists apart from the 
 world of known and knowable objects, any more 
 than it is itself a special department of this world 
 of objects distinguishable from, and determined by, 
 its surroundings. It is, on the contrary, the supreme 
 condition of the world of objects having any exist- 
 ence whatever. It is only through objects being 
 brought into relation with the identical and per- 
 manent subject of knowledge, that there is unity in 
 nature, or, in other words, that there is a known 
 world of nature or experience at all. The evolution 
 of mind or self-consciousness out of experience is, 
 therefore, not merely to be rejected as a problem 
 too intricate for psychological analysis. It is a 
 mistake to think that it is a possible problem at all ; 
 for it attempts to make experience account for and 
 originate the principles on w r hich its own possibility 
 depends. 
 (&> made But it is the second change in point of view 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 283 
 
 which needs special emphasis here the change clear in the 
 from the point of view of science to that of moral- 
 
 ity. Taken in its bare form, this is perhaps little reflexaction. 
 more than a confusion of thought. The fact of 
 things being of a certain constitution, and of their 
 progress tending in a certain direction, cannot of 
 itself supply a law for the exercise of our activity. 
 But the view is associated with a theory of the 
 nature of human action which seeks to bring it into 
 the strict line of natural development. Just as 
 empirical psychology attempted to treat self -con- 
 sciousness as a stage in the evolution of experience 
 or knowledge, so the empirical theory of morality, 
 aided by the doctrine of evolution, tries to show 
 how the action which is called moral has been de- 
 veloped out of purely physical or reflex action. But 
 this theory of the development of moral action is 
 really open to the same objection as that which was 
 urged against the theory which evolves self-con- 
 sciousness from the unconscious. The objection to 
 the latter was, that experience, itself constituted by 
 consciousness, is made to produce the condition of 
 its own possibility ; and a similar confusion is in- 
 volved in attempting to develop moral action out of 
 merely physical or reflex action. The only case of 
 true psychical or conscious action is that in which 
 there is a conscious determination of end and means ; 
 and action of this kind implies the same relation to 
 self -consciousness as that by which knowledge is 
 
284 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 constituted. The relation is, however, manifested 
 in a different way : it is not an apprehension of the 
 manifold of impression into the unity of conscious- 
 ness, but the externalisation of self-consciousness 
 in realising a conceived end or idea. Now, in so 
 far as physical and psychical facts are phenomena 
 of experience and they have no other existence, at 
 least none that can have any intelligible meaning 
 given to it they presuppose self-consciousness ; for 
 it is only in relation to it that experience is pos- 
 sible. That is to say, their existence logically im- 
 plies a reference to a subject whose active external- 
 ising manifestation is the determination of means 
 and end which constitutes moral (as distinguished 
 from merely natural) action. So far, therefore, 
 from our being able to trace the development of 
 moral action from the simpler phenomena of natural 
 action, we find that these, in their most rudimen- 
 tary form, by virtue of their being phenomena of 
 experience, imply and receive their reality from 
 the self-consciousness which is the ^differentiating 
 quality both of knowledge and of moral action. 
 5. The unity From this it follows that, although, empirically, 
 sciousups": ^ e change from the point of view of science to that 
 of morality is a transition to a different order of 
 facts, yet the passage may be possible transcenden- 
 (a) as mak- tally through self-consciousness. For in self-con- 
 the transi- 6 sciousness we reach the element of identity between 
 tion from k now i ec [g e an( j action. It is, therefore, of import- 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 285 
 
 ance to understand the nature of this self-conscious knowledge 
 activity in relation to knowledge and to action. If tc 
 the fundamental characteristic of knowledge is the 
 bringing into relation to consciousness, then all 
 conscious action has this characteristic ; for it de- 
 termines self towards some particular line of activ- 
 ity that is to say, towards an object or end which 
 is thereby related to consciousness. Action there- 
 fore, we may say, is knowledge. And in the same 
 way, on the other hand, since the relating to con- 
 sciousness which constitutes knowledge can only be 
 regarded as originated by the subject, it follows, 
 conversely, that knowledge is action. 1 " We act," 
 says Spinoza, " only in so far as we know or under- 
 stand/' Action is but one aspect or manifestation 
 of that which, in another aspect or manifestation, is 
 knowledge. But the aspect of self-consciousness 
 we call knowledge and that we call action are dif- 
 ferent from one another. In the former the relat- 
 ing to consciousness in the definite forms of thought 
 and perception is the prominent thing. In the lat- 
 ter it is the realising energy of the self-conscious 
 
 1 From "action "in this its ultimate meaning as equivalent 
 to origination by the subject, it is necessary to distinguish 
 "action " as a phenomenon in the external world. The latter is 
 one of the modes in which the relation of objects is known to us, 
 the former a characteristic of knowing. The active nature of 
 knowledge is worked out in an interesting way in Professor S. S. 
 Laurie's ' Metaphysica nova et vetusta,' by " Scotus Novanticus " 
 (1884). 
 
286 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 subject. The ordinary distinction between know- 
 ledge and action is therefore correct, if not pushed 
 to the extent of making an absolute separation 
 between them : in the former we idealise the real, 
 in the latter we realise the ideal. But they are at 
 one in this, that both involve self-conscious activity. 
 (&) as deter- The self-consciousness which in one relation is 
 SiTractCTof knowledge, in another action, is thus the fundamen- 
 the ethical ^ act O f h uman nature i and on it, therefore, the 
 
 end, 
 
 ethical end must be based, if that end can be dis- 
 closed by the nature of man, and is to express what 
 is most fundamental in his nature. Now, as know- 
 ledge finds its completion when all things are con- 
 nected with one another and the subject in a defi- 
 nite system of relations, the end of completed self- 
 conscious activity cannot be different. In their 
 final perfection, as in their fundamental 'nature, 
 the two are at one. As Kant puts it, 1 the specu- 
 lative and the practical reason are reconciled in the 
 notion of end. However virtue may differ from 
 knowledge in the processes of ordinary experience, 
 the distinction only belongs to their finite realisa- 
 tion. An intuitive understanding, or understand- 
 ing which, in knowing, creates the objects of know- 
 ledge, is the highest conception of reason. Yet the 
 very notion of a finite self implies that neither 
 such knowledge nor such activity belongs to it. In 
 knowledge and action, as properties of the ultimate 
 
 1 Werke, iii. 538 ; cf. Adamson, Philosophy of Kant, p. 138. 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS, 287 
 
 self-consciousness, human beings only participate. 
 It is only by means of the laborious methods of 
 observation and inference that they approach the 
 intuition of all things as a unity in which perfect 
 knowledge consists ; and, in the same way, it is 
 only by the gradual volitional adaptation of means 
 to end that they are able, in some measure, to con- 
 tribute to the realisation of self-consciousness in the 
 world. 
 
 An end can only be made our own when con- as seif-reaii- 
 ceived as necessary for realising or completing our 
 idea of self. Conscious volition only follows a 
 conceived want, or recognition that the self as 
 imagined the ideal self is not realised in the 
 actual self. The action is towards a fuller working 
 out of the idea of self ; and the end may therefore, 
 in all cases of conscious action, be said to be self- 
 realisation, though the nature of this end differs 
 according to each man's conception of self. This 
 may be expressed, as Green expresses it, by saying 
 that " self -satisfaction is the form of every object 
 willed; but . . . it is on the specific difference 
 of the objects willed under the general form of 
 self-satisfaction that the quality of the will must 
 depend." l It appears to me, however, that this 
 statement requires to be guarded by an explanation. 
 The self-satisfaction sought must not be looked ^ 
 upon as a feeling, for if it is, it can only be 
 
 1 Prolegomena to Ethics, p. 161. 
 
288 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 ! interpreted psychologically as pleasure but as 
 simply conscious self-realisation. And this self- 
 realisation is the objective consciousness of an 
 attained end, which is accompanied by, but is not 
 \ the same as, the feeling of pleasure. Self-realisa- 
 tion is the end, not the pleasurable feeling which 
 follows it ; self-satisfaction, not the " pleasure of 
 self-satisfaction." In this way, the common ex- 
 perience " that the objects with which we seek 
 to satisfy ourselves do not turn out capable of 
 satisfying us," 1 might be expressed by saying that 
 the method adopted for the realisation of self is 
 often found in its result to lead to incomplete, or 
 even to illusory, self-realisation. 
 
 The question thus arises, What is the true self 
 that is to be realised, and what is meant by the 
 realisation of it? The will that wills itself is as 
 bare a notion in ethics, as the thought that thinks 
 itself is in metaphysics. The "good will," which 
 Kant rightly held to be the only ultimate good, 
 never altogether escaped this formality in Kant's 
 own treatment of it. His idea of humanity as a 
 realm of ends was limited by his formal conception 
 of the function of reason, though it suggests the 
 way by which the mere tautology of will may be 
 transcended. It is of the essence of a finite will 
 that its end is different from the realisation of the 
 end. But the rationality of the will implies that it 
 
 1 Prolegomena to Ethics, p. 165. 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 289 
 
 must aim at nothing less than the harmonious arti- 
 culation of its whole activity in the unity of self- 
 consciousness. 
 
 It has been argued above that both knowledge butastrans- 
 and morality are expressions of self-conscious 
 activity: in it these different manifestations find 
 an element of fundamental identity. But it may 
 be maintained, further, that this "unity of self- 
 consciousness" is not merely the unity of the 
 different states of an individual, but that it is an 
 element which transcends the difference by which 
 concrete individuals are distinguished from one 
 another. If this view can be carried out, it seems 
 to lead us to attribute to other men something more 
 than a " similar consciousness " x to our own, and 
 to make us look on all self-conscious beings as 
 sharing in, or manifesting, in various imperfect 
 ways, one identical self -consciousness. From this 
 point of view, self-realisation would be established 
 as no mere individual end. The first law of morality 
 would be not the " natural " impulse for each to 
 take care of himself in the struggle for life, but, 
 on the contrary, the sublation of that distinction 
 between the particular ego and other individuals 
 which would admit of the one using the others 
 as mere means to his own advancement. His true 
 end is the same as theirs: the realisation of the 
 self-consciousness in which both partake its realis- 
 
 1 Sidgwick, "Green's Ethics," Mind, ix. 180. 
 T 
 
290 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 ation, that is to say, not in one individual only, but 
 wherever it is manifested. 1 This is the rationale 
 of what the empirical theory of evolution tries to 
 establish by pointing to the growing harmony in 
 feeling and interest between the individual and 
 society. What evolution really shows is the gradual 
 manifestation in actual volition of the identity of 
 nature in all men. 2 I do not say that this funda- 
 mental identity of nature does away with all conflict 
 between self-realisation in one's self and in others ; 
 but it does much, if it establishes the principle that 
 the realisation of one's own nature involves the 
 realisation of that of others. As Schaffle says, 
 " the moral law is the direction of the will to the 
 genuinely human as humanity ; " and " this is a 
 transcendental element embedded in the hearts of 
 all men though in its basis only, for it is developed 
 and ripened in the course of history." 3 And the 
 more fully self-consciousness is realised, the clearer 
 does it become that its complete realisation implies 
 that "kingdom of ends" spoken of by Kant, in 
 which all self-conscious beings are at once subjects 
 and sovereign. 
 
 1 This is implied in Hegel's well-known imperative, " Be a per- 
 son and respect others as persons." Phil. d. Rechts, p. 73. 
 
 2 Thus Hoffding maintains that " the highest ethical idea " is 
 "the idea of the human race as a realm of personalities." Grund- 
 lage der humanen Ethik (aus dem danischen), p. 74. 
 
 3 Bau und Leben des socialen Korpers, i. 173. 
 
ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 291 
 
 Further, self-realisation in both its aspects as ( C > as show. 
 
 ,..,,-, . , . .-, . ing that the 
 
 individual and as social is necessarily progressive, realisation 
 It is only at the highest stage of its development *^* d 
 that nature becomes the organ of intelligence and progressive. 
 morality. 1 And, just as knowledge expresses 
 itself through the forms of space and time, and, 
 therefore, by gradual colligations of facts, so the 
 conscious determination of activity is manifested 
 in the world in an order of consecutive acts, and is 
 therefore subject, in its manifestation, to the laws 
 ^of temporal succession. It is the part of a system 
 of metaphysics at any rate, it does not belong to 
 the present inquiry to show how reason manifests 
 itself in space and time, and how, through the 
 rationality of this manifestation, everything in 
 space is and acts only in relation to its environ- 
 ment, and through it, to the rest of the world, and 
 how each event in time is the result of preced- 
 ing events, and determines those which follow it. 
 What it thus shows the necessity of is the process 
 of evolution ; and it is because this process is deter- 
 mined by reason that the world is the object of 
 knowledge and the sphere of moral action. Evolu- 
 tion is thus not the foundation of morality, but the 
 manifestation of the principle on which it depends. 
 Morality cannot be explained by means of its own 
 development, without reference to the self-consci- 
 
 1 Cf. H. Siebeck, Philosophische Monatshefte, xx. 340. 
 
292 ON THE BASIS OF ETHICS. 
 
 ousness which makes that development possible. 
 However valuable may be the information we get 
 from experience as to the gradual evolution of 
 conduct, its nature and end can only be explained 
 by a principle that transcends experience. 
 
 THE END. 
 
 PRINTED BY WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS. 
 
THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE 
 STAMPED BELOW 
 
 AN INITIAL FINE~OF 25 CENTS 
 
 '5 f 
 
 / I 1 W 
 
 _J_ 
 
 8flec'&H L: 
 

 / u 
 
 s 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY