UC-NRLF Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/essaysonstudyuseOOplutrich YALE STUDIES IN ENGLISH ALBERT S. COOK, Editor XV ESSAYS ON THE STUDY AND USE OF POETRY BY PLUTARCH AND BASIL THE GREAT TRANSLATED FROM THE GREEK WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY FREDERICK MORGAN PADELFORD, Ph.D. Professor of the English Language and Literature in the University of Washington NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY 1902 YALE STUDIES IN ENGLISH ALBERT S. COOK, Editor XV ESSAYS ON THE STUDY AND USE OF POETRY BY PLUTARCH AND BASIL THE GREAT TRANSLATED FROM THE GREEK WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY FREDERICK MORGAN PADELFORD, Ph.D. Professor of the English Language and Literature in the University of Washington NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY 1902 Copyright, 1902, by Frederick Morgan Padelford, Ph.D. TO GEORGE DANA BOARDMAN PEPPER AND ADONIRAM JUDSON PADELFORD iSJ^lSb TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface, ...... Introduction, ..... Plutarch's Theory of Poetry, . The Life of St. Basil and the Address to Young Men How A Young Man Should Study Poetry, . Outline, ..... Translation, ..... Address to Young Men on the Right Use of Greek Litera ture, ...... Outline, ...... Translation, ..... Appendix, ...... Index, ...... Page 7 II 13 33 45 47 49 97 99 lOI 121 125 PREFACE The recent very general interest in poetics has led me to prepare these translations of the essays on poetry by Plu- tarch and Basil the Great, in the hope that they may prove useful to students of literature. Although they were not epoch-making, these essays are worthy of consideration, for, besides their intrinsic value, they mark interesting stages in the history of poetic criticism. The essay on How a Young Man Ought to Study Poetry was first rendered into English by Philemon Holland, who made a complete translation of the Morals, which was issued in octavo from the press of Arnold Hatfield, a London printer, in 1603. Its title reads as follows: 'The Philoso- phic, commonlie called The Morals, written by the learned Philosopher Plutarch of Chaeronea. Translated out of Greek into English, and conferred with the Latin translations and the French, by Philemon Holland of Coventrie, Doctor in Physicke. Whereunto are annexed the Summaries neces- sary to be read before every Treatise.' This version, though its archaism possesses an undeniable charm, is not alto- gether adapted to modern requirements. A second edition, *newly revised and corrected,' appeared in 1657, and this was followed not many years later by the translation of the Morals 'by Several Hands,' published in London in 1684- 1694. To this work Simon Ford contributed the version of the essay on How a Young Man Ought to Study Poetry. Ford's translation is clumsy, frequently obscure, and often wide of the Greek. In 1870 Professor Goodwin offered a corrected and revised text of this rendering of the Morals, and the fact that the sixth edition appeared in 1898 attests the usefulness of this revised version. However, of the essay under consideration much more than a revision of Preface Ford's translation is needed, if the essay is to assume its proper place in our study of poetics. There seems to have been one separate translation of Basil's homily into English, although it is not recorded in the catalogue of the British Museum. It appeared at the press of John Cawood in octavo form, and was printed in black letter. According to Ames and Herbert^ it bore the following title: 'An Homelye of Basilius Magnus, Howe Younge Men oughte to reade Poets and Oratours. Trans- lated out of Greke. Anno M. D. LVIL' Nothing seems to be known about the author. It is interesting to find that the two essays of Plutarch and Basil were associated by Archbishop Potter of Canter- bury in the first of his learned publications. In 1694, when barely twenty,^ and just after he was made a Fellow of Lincoln College, he published at Oxford an octavo volume with the following title: 'Variantes Lectiones et Notae ad Plutarchi librum de Audiendis Poetis ; et ad Basilii Magni Orationem ad Juvenes.' In 1753 a second edition of this book was issued at Glasgow. Potter, however, was not the first to associate these essays; in 1600 Martin Haynoccius published them in an Enchiridion Ethicum, and Grotius brought out an edition of the two at Paris in 1623. A German dissertation, De Fontibus Plutarchi Comment, de Audiendis Poetis et de Fortuna, written by August Schlemm, and published at Gottingen in 1894, shows the probable indebtedness of Plutarch's essay to the lost writ- ings of the Stoics and Peripatetics. I am indebted to Herr Schlemm for several of my notes, and offer his conclusions in an appendix. In the present renderings an attempt has been made to express the spirit and style of the originals, and thus to reproduce the looseness and indirectness of Plutarch's thought, as well as the conciseness and rapid movement of Basil's language. The translation of Plutarch follows the ' Typographical Antiquities, London, 1785-6-90. ^ See Diet. Nat. Biog. s. v. John Potter. Preface text of Bernardakis, and the rendering of Basil the text of Migne. Acknowledgment should be made of sugges- tions taken from the earlier English translations of Plutarch, from the German version of Basil by Kaltwasser, and from Maloney's school edition of Basil's essay. For the many quotations from the Iliad and the Odyssey, the translations by Lang, Leaf, and Myers, and by Butcher and Lang, have been adopted; wherever quotations from Plato or from Aristotle's Poetics have been embodied in the notes, the ver- sions of Jowett and of Butcher have been followed. The notes attempt to show the indebtedness of the essays to earlier Greek literature, and to furnish interesting paral- lels from the classics, but do not cite the many passages from modern writers which are similar in thought. Biographical notices are taken from Johnson's Encyclopaedia, Smith's Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology, and Miiller's Handbuch der Klassischen Alterthumswissen- schaft. Fragments from the Greek philosophers, drama- tists, and lyrists, are referred to the collections of Mullach, Nauck, Meineke, and Bergk, even when these essays furnish the sources for the fragments. A few quotations and allu- sions have escaped me, and I shall be grateful to any reader who will direct my attention to the originals. The preparation of this volume was undertaken at the suggestion of Professor Albert S. Cook, and it owes much to his interest. Professor George D. B. Pepper, ex-Presi- dent of Colby College, has read the translations with pains- taking care, and Dr. Charles Grosvenor Osgood, Jr., of Yale University, has read both translations and introduction ; to their suggestions the book, whatever its imperfections, is greatly indebted. To my colleagues, Dr. Thomas F. Kane and Dr. Arthur S. Haggett, with whom I have frequently advised, I also acknowledge my obligations. F. M. P. Seattle, Washington. August i6, 1902, INTRODUCTION PLUTARCH'S THEORY OF POETRY Unless one accepts the theory, playfully or otherwise advanced in the Ion, that the poet is but the instrument of an overmastering divinity, he is often at a loss to explain the inability of many a genius in the world of art and letters to judge of the relative excellence of his own creations. Michel Angelo eagerly dropped the brush and resumed the chisel, with the joy of one who returns to the work he loves after interruption, and yet succeeding generations have been unable to tell whether they admire more the frescoes of the Chapel or the Pieta; Wordsworth, the author of Michael, the Daffodils, and 'There Was a Boy,' with infinite self-satis- faction drew out the prolonged monotony of the Excursion as the supreme work of a lifetime ; and he whose imagination swept from the Visible darkness' of the throne of Chaos to the skirts of God, 'dark with excessive bright,' failed to see how far the intensity, sublimity, and mighty organ- tones of Paradise Lost excel the unimpassioned finish of Paradise Regained, In a similar way Plutarch misjudged his productions, for although he regarded philosophy as the ideal field for the mind's activity, he was not profound enough nor subtle enough to excel as a philosopher, so that the Morals are hardly known more than by title to the cultivated reader of to-day, while the Lives, those 'idealized ethical portraits,' as Professor Perrin calls them, have charmed generations of English readers by their freshness and spirit, and are found on many a book-shelf where poverty allows them no other companions save Shakespeare and the Bible. And yet the Morals have great value historically. No other extant writings give so complete and satisfactory a record of custom and thought in the late Greek period. 13 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry Domestic life in its many phases, affairs of government, questions of religion and ethics, the investigations of science, and the problems of art, all find a place in the pages of this multifarious collection of essays. The student of poetry, and of aesthetics in general, will find these essays fruitful or barren according to the point of view from which they are approached. If, in the essay on poetry, the reader looks for intrinsic excellence in criti- cism, he will be disappointed, and will find many pages that are distressingly pedantic, and many that are commonplace and trivial; thus, when the charming episode of Nausicaa and Odysseus is made the subject of prudish speculation, the reader is equally offended by the triteness of the thought and by the writer's pragmatism. If, however, Plutarch is regarded as an exponent of the thought and feeling of his time, the essay is full of significance, for it shows the attempts of decadent Greece to deal with an art which had been the glory of the classical period. Accordingly, the following pages will attempt an analysis of Plutarch's theory of poetry, the material furnished by the essay on poetry being supplemented by gleanings here and there from essays on other subjects. First will be consid- ered Plutarch's theory of the distinction between poetry and prose; secondly, his theory of the relation of poetry to nature and to truth ; thirdly, his theory of the end of fine art. Wherein do poetry and prose differ? Although Plutarch does not follow Aristotle in threatening the established tradition which made metrical form essential to poetry,^ he does agree with him in saying that the nature of its sub- ject largely determines whether a composition is prose or poetry.^ With playful disdain he criticizes the early Greek philosophers and naturalists for presenting didactic sub- jects metrically: 'The verses of Empedocles and Par- menides, Nicander's verses on antidotes to poisons, and the maxims of Theognis, borrowed the poetic form and dignity only as a sort of riding-carriage to avoid footing it.'^ ^ Poet. i. 5; ix. 9. ^i^jd. i. 7-8 ; ix. 2. ^See p. 53. Plutarch's Theory of Poetry This idea is more elaborately developed in the essay entitled Why the Pythian Priestess Ceases her Oracles in Verse :^ Vanity and love of display, united with a certain racial apti- tude, led men to clothe history and philosophy in verse, though these subjects, being of a grave and solid nature, and designed to teach rather than to move, demand the severity and directness of prose. Subjects of a didactic nature are purely intellectual, and demand perfect simplicity in expres- sion. Poetry, on the other hand, is the product of intellect and feeling combined, and hence, because its appeal is quite as much to the feelings as to the intellect, requires the sensu- ousness of verse. In the Symposiacs there is a discussion of why it is commonly said that love makes a man a poet, and one Sossius offers the following explanation: 'One would do well to explain it in the light of Theophrastus' dis- course on music, a book that I have just finished reading. Theophrastus holds that music has three causes, grief, joy, and inspiration, since each one of these alters the wonted tone of the voice. Grief utters its mournful lamentations in song, which explains why orators in their perorations, and actors in their lamentings, employ soft and musical cadence. Intense and excessive joy completely carries away the lighter-minded fellows, and incites them to hop about and frisk and keep their steps, even though they know nothing about dancing ; as Pindar has it, "The frenzy and shouts of those aroused, and their wild tossings of the head." But men of taste and refinement, when subject to this emotion, are incited only to sing and to give voice to verse and mel- ody. Inspiration most of all changes the customary state of body and voice. Whence the Bacchae use rhythm, and the inspired give forth their oracles in metre, and one sees few madmen who do not utter their insane ravings in poetry and song. Such being the case, if you should observe love with a critical eye and examine closely into it, you would find that no other passion is attended with more ^ 23-24. 15 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry bitter grief, more intense and excessive joy, or greater ecstasy and madness. A lover's soul looks like Sophocles' city, "At the same moment it is full of sacrifices, of paeans, and of lamentations."^ Wherefore it is not strange or sur- prising that, since love contains all the causes of music — grief, joy, and inspiration — and is also prone to talk and babble, it should be more inclined than any other passion to the making of poetry and songs. But although the poet must be a man of sensitive emotions, not every man of sensibility will be a poet. The power to express passion- ate feeling in language melodious, rhythmical, and nobly embellished is a gift to rare temperaments. Consequently, when Euripides says that "Love makes men poets who before no music knew,"^ he does not mean that love infuses music and poetry into men that were not already inclined to them, but that it warms and awakens that disposition which lay inactive and drowsy before. . . . Poetic rapture, like the raptures of love, makes use of the ability of its subject.'^ It was because this temperamental aptitude was general among the early Greeks that they produced such a wealth of poetry. A people whose civilization favored a natural and sincere play of the emotions was equipped with a genius for metrical utterance, and responded to the slightest excitation with spontaneous and melodious poetry; accordingly their banquets, where wine flowed and spirits were high, were graced with charming odes and love-songs.* But while emotion plays a large part in poetry, as already stated poetry is the product, not of feeling alone, but of intellect as well ; one must therefore not allow such a pas- sage as that quoted above, which, moreover, is dealing strictly with lyrics, to cause him to overlook the emphasis laid upon wisdom and judgment as factors in the production of poetry. Indeed, by this very word 'enthusiasm,' Plutarch does not mean that the poet's personality is lost while the ' Oed. Tyr. 4. ^ Nauck 666. ^ Why the Pythian Priestess Ceases her Oracles in Verse 23. ^Ibid. 23. 16 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry god is speaking through him, for he is too much of a rationaHst to entertain such a theory of divine possession; rather, that the god uses each poet according to the abiUty which nature and training have given him. Even the Pythian priestess, if brought up among the ignorant, must utter her oracles in prose.^ The necessity for this element of judgment in the produc- tion of works of art is considered at length in the essay On Music.^ The thought is that he is the best musician who combines the greatest amount of skill with the best judg- ment. By skill is meant the technical understanding of the different modes, such as the Dorian, the Ionian, and the Phrygian, and the ability to play or sing in any one of them without violating the laws of harmony. Judgment is an inclusive term, comprising the ability to discover the nature and genius of the poem, to choose for it the mode which is most appropriate, and to judge of the coherency of all the component parts.^ As to the importance of a knowledge of philosophy for the production, or the appreciation, of music, Plutarch does not go to the extreme of Pythagoras, who 'rejected the judging of music by the senses, affirming that the virtue of music could be appreciated only by the intel- lect,'* yet he does advise him who would be proficient in this art to acquaint himself with all sciences, and especially to make philosophy his tutor.® It is needless to enforce this point further by citing passages from the essay on poetry; suffice it to say that Plutarch thought that poetry of real excellence must be grounded in philosophy. To summarize the conclusions already reached: while prose is didactic, and appeals to the intellect, poetry is ^Ibid. 22. 2 Among the Greeks music was accessory to poetry. Throughout this essay the intimate relation of poetry and music is apparent on every page, at times it being almost impossible to tell whether the writer is speaking of the one or the other. In this essay Plutarch follows the theories of Aristoxenus and Heraclides. ^Siff. ^ Ibid. 37 ; see Plato, Zaize/j ii. 659. ^ Ibid. 23. 17 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry emotional, and the product of feeling as well as of intellect. Further, poetical power is a gift, but a gift that may be refined by proper training — indeed, a gift that cannot be pos- sessed by the altogether untutored. So much for Plutarch's distinction between prose and poetry. Let us now consider his theory of the relation of poetry to nature and to truth. Does poetry copy nature or transcend it ? Is it truthful or untruthful ? Is it universal or restricted ? We shall find an answer to these questions in determining Plutarch's use of the expression 'imitation.' Imitation as applied to the arts was employed by Greek writers very generally, and widely dififering theories of its nature were held. As both Plato and Aristotle give much prominence to this term in their discussions of art, it will be helpful to examine somewhat carefully their employment of the word, in order that Plu- tarch's views may be seen against the background of earlier Greek thought. In the tenth book of the Republic,^ where the work of poet and painter is discussed, we find the following train of thought : The artist is one who turns a mirror round and round, and catches the reflection of objects — of the sun, the heavens, the earth, plants, animals, men. There is the ideal world as it exists in the mind of God, for example, the ideal plant, table, or man ; the actual world which produces plants, tables, or men imitative of the ideal ; and the world of the artist, in which are copied the appearances of the objects in the actual world. Imitative art is therefore an imitation of an imitation, and further from truth than the world of nature about us; it is three removes from God. Useful art is superior to imitative art, for the carpenter who makes a bed is better employed than the painter who repro- duces the appearance of the bed, and the general who con- ducts a campaign tlian Homer, the poet of battles.^ 1 595-607. ^ See Plutarch, Whether the Athenians were More Renowned for their Warlike Achievements or their Learning cc. vi-viii, for an elaborate argument that more honor belongs to commanders than to poets, orators, and historians. 18 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry Further light is thrown on this conception of imitation in the Third Book/ where it is defined as the assimilation of oneself to another, whose character is assumed. Pre- cisely because any such assumption of the character of another is undignified, unnatural, and insincere, because, for example, the poet, not being a cobbler, can never really act the cobbler, all imitative artists were to leave the Republic, even though the banishment included the much loved Homer. All art, however, was not excluded, for Plato implies a distinction between imitative art and true art. The best art is the sincere and direct expression of a courageous and harmonious life, not the product of the fancy of some 'pantomimically- versatile' imitator. The Republic is a return to simplicity, and that poetry alone is permissible which expresses the simplicity of a mind so nobly ordered that, whether in action or repose, it expresses the highest moral energy. The temper of this, the true artist-soul, gives char- acter to the words, and through the words to the rhythm and harmony. Rhythm and harmony, then, become formal expressions of the great virtues, bravery and temperance; they give to the senses graceful and beautiful expression of true beauty and grace, for, in Plato's very words, 'grace and harmony are the sisters and images of goodness and vir- tue.'^ Such rhythm and harmony find their way into the inmost part of the soul of the listener, and render right the form of his soul through their rightness of form.^ Such art is one with the music of the spheres; it is divine beauty and loveliness.* In the Poetics of Aristotle imitation is used in two senses. In an early chapter, where Aristotle simply wishes to show that the instinct of imitation is universal, occurs the follow- '393. '401. ^402. *In Laws vii. 817, in a less severe vein Plato is more generous to tragedy, speaking of it as above of ideal art : ' Our whole state is an imitation of the best and noblest life, which we affirm to be indeed the very truth of tragedy.' Likewise, in Laws ii. 667-669, imitative art is defined as good when it truthfully reproduces the original as to propor- tions, etc., and is beautiful. 19 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry ing statement : Toetry in general seems to have sprung from two causes, each of them lying deep in our nature. First, the instinct of imitation is implanted in man from childhood, one difference between him and other animals being that he is the most imitative of living creatures ; and through imita- tion he learns his earliest lessons; and no less universal is the pleasure felt in things imitated. We have evidence of this in the facts of experience. Objects which in them- selves we view with pain, we delight to contemplate when reproduced with minute fidelity, such as the forms of the most ignoble animals and of dead bodies. The cause of this again is, that to learn gives the liveliest pleasure, not only to philosophers, but to men in general, whose capacity of learning, however, is more limited. Thus the reason why men enjoy seeing a likeness is that in contemplating it they find themselves learning or inferring, and saying perhaps, "Ah, that is he." For if you happen not to have seen the original, the pleasure will be due not to the imitation as such, but to the execution, the coloring, or some such thing.'^ That Aristotle is speaking of imitation in general, and not of artistic imitation, is at once apparent when one reads in other chapters that ^.Poetry imitates men as they ought to be ;'2 that it 'is a more philosophical and a higher thing than history,'^ for the 'one relates what has happened, the other what may happen;'* that 'poetry tends to express the uni- versal, history the particular.'^ In essence Aristotle says that poetry is not limited to the actual deeds of men who have lived, but that, freeing itself from the trammels of the accidental, the temporary, and the local, it portrays men nobler than nature, though such men as nature's tendencies toward the ideal would produce. The poet sees through and Mv. 1-5. ^ Foet i. 5 ; see also xxv. 6 : ' Further, if it be objected that the description is not true to fact, the poet may perhaps reply, *' But the objects are as they ought to be ; " just as Sophocles said that he drew men as they ought to be drawn * Euripides as they are.' 3 Ibid. ix. 3. ''Ibid. ix. 2. ^Ibid. ix. 3. 20 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry beyond nature to the models of her workmanship. Thus, good portrait-painters, 'while reproducing the distinctive form of the original, make a likeness which is true to life, and yet more beautiful. So, too, the poet, in representing men quick or slow to anger, or with other defects of charac- ter, should preserve the type and yet ennoble it. In this way Achilles is portrayed by Agathon and Homer.'^ Further, artistic imitation does not include the portrayal of animals and of still life. The objects of aesthetic imita- tion are rj^rj, TrdOrj, and TrpaicLs, which Butcher defines as 'the characteristic moral qualities, transient emotions, and actions in their proper and inward sense,'^ meaning by the last, actions which are the inevitable expression of intellec- tual and emotional activity. Men acting, therefore, Aristotle defines as the objects imitated by the fine arts, because such actions as the artist makes use of spring from a deep source, and are but the outward manifestations of the movements of the soul. Plutarch treats the subject of imitation as follows: 'We shall still more thoroughly ground the young man, if, on introducing him to poetry, we explain to him that it is an imitative art and agent, analogous to painting. Not only must he be made acquainted with the common saying that poetry is vocal painting, and painting silent poetry, but we must teach him also that when we see a painting of a lizard, an ape, or the face of Thersites, our pleasure and surprise are occasioned, not by the beauty of the object, but by its likeness. For it is naturally impossible for the ugly to be beautiful, but it is the imitation which is praised if it reproduce to the life either an ugly or a beautiful object. On the other hand, if an ugly object is represented as beau- tiful, we deny the truthfulness or the consistency of the picture. Now there are some artists who paint uncomely actions; thus Timotheus pictured Medea killing her chil- dren ; Theon showed Orestes murdering his mother ; Parr- 1 Ibid. XV. 8. ^ Butcher, Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and Fine Art c. ii. 21 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry hasius, Odysseus counterfeiting madness; and Chaere- phanes, the unchaste converse of women with men. In such instances it is especially important that the young man come to understand that we do not praise the action which is imi- tated, but the art, provided the subject is treated accurately. Since now poetry also frequently describes base actions and depraved emotions and character, the youth must not confound their artistic admirableness and success with truth, nor rank them as beautiful, but he is to praise them only as accurate and natural likenesses of the things treated. For as we are annoyed when we hear the grunting of a hog, the noise of pulleys, the whistling of the wind, and the roaring of the seas, but are pleased if any one imitates them with naturalness, as Parmenio did the hog,^ and Theo- dorus the pulleys ; and as we avoid the unpleasant sight of an unhealthy man with festering sores, but take pleasure in witnessing the Philoctetes of Aristophon and the Jo casta of Silanion^ — which are realistic likenesses of wasting and dying ^ See Symposiacs v. i : ' For upon what account, for God's sake, from what external impression upon our organ, should men be moved to admire Parmenio's sow so much as to pass it into a proverb ? Yet it is reported, that Parmenio being very famous for imitating the grunting of a pig, some endeavored to rival and outdo him. And when the hearers, being prejudiced, cried out, " Very well indeed, but nothing comparable to Parmenio's sow ;" one took a pig under his arm and came upon the stage. And when, though they heard the very pig, they still continued, " This is nothing comparable to Parmenio's sow ;" he threw his pig amongst them, to show that they judged according to opinion and not truth.' [This translation is taken from the Goodwin edition.] See Rep. iii. 397, for Plato's condemnation of this kind of imitation : ' But another sort of character will narrate anything, and the worse he is the more unscrupulous he will be ; nothing will be beneath him : moreover he will be ready to imitate anything, not as a joke, but in right good earnest, and before a large audience. As I was just now saying, he will attempt to represent the roll of thunder, the rattle of wind and hail, or the various sounds of pulleys, of pipes, of flutes, and all sorts of instruments : also he will bark like a dog, bleat like a sheep, and crow like a cock ; his entire art will consist in imitation of voice and gesture, and there will be very little narration.' ^ Ibid. : ' And therefore, because he that is really affected with grief or anger presents us with nothing but the common bare passion, but in 22 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry persons — so when the youth reads what Thersites the buf- foon, or Sisyphus the debaucher, or Batrachus the brothel- keeper says or does, he must be taught to praise the genius and the art which imitates them, but to censure the subjects and actions with opprobrium. For the excellence of a thing and the excellence of its imitation are not the same. Fitness and naturalness constitute excellence, but to things base, the base is natural and fit.'^ To this passage two questions address themselves : What are the subjects of aesthetic imitation, and what is its nature? The first may be answered without trouble: clearly all forms of life are legitimate for artistic treatment — inferior types of animal life, such as a lizard or an ape, as well as heroic men like Achilles and Hector; and in human con- duct, immorality and obscenity, as well as self-control and heroism. In making all objects proper for artistic reproduction, Plutarch showed that, in theory at least, he was far from assigning poetry the exalted place which Aristotle had given it. Not only did Aristotle exclude all but human the imitation some dexterity and persuasiveness appears, we are nat- urally inclined to be disturbed at the former, whilst the latter delights us. It is unpleasant to see a sick man, or one that is at his last gasp ; yet with content we can look upon the picture of Philoctetes, or the statue of Jocasta, in whose face it is commonly said that the workmen mixed silver, so that the brass might represent the face and color of one ready to faint and yield up the ghost. And this, said I, the Cyre- niacs may use as a strong argument against you Epicureans, that all the sense of pleasure which arises from the working of any object on the ear or eye is not in those organs, but in the intellect itself. Thus the continued cackling of a hen or cawing of a crow is very ungrateful and disturbing ; yet he that imitates those noises well pleases the hearers. Thus to behold a consumptive man is no delightful spec- tacle ; yet with pleasure we can view the pictures and statues of such persons, because the very imitating hath something in it very agreeable to the mind, which allures and captivates its faculties.' [Goodwin ed.] ^ See pp. 58-60. See also the Symposiacs i. i, where is discussed the question of why we take delight in hearing those that represent the passions of men angry or sorrowful, and yet cannot without concern behold those who are really so aifected. 23 Plutarch's Theory of Poetry life from art, but he discriminated between the artistic excel- lence of noble and of ignoble conduct. To such subjects as Chaerephanes painted he all but denied the name of art, for they represent conduct false and temporary, and stand for nothing permanent nor structural. The nobler the types of character which the poet imitates the more will his work be artistic. Aristotle would have had little sympathy with one who 'could find matter for artistic approval in the ugly or in the immoral, however correctly delineated. We find further evidence that Plutarch did not appre- ciate Aristotle's conception of the proper subject-matter for art in his use of the terms yOr], TrdOrj, and -n-pd^eL?, since, although he employed them freely, he did not appreciate their combined idea, for he robbed the expression men act- ing of its Aristotelian significance by using epya, irpdyyia, and TT/oo^ts quite interchangeably/ Turning now to the consideration of the nature of aes- thetic imitation, we find such expressions in the above passage as likeness (oftotov), truthfulness {Ilko^) consist- ency (it pirrov) ^reproduction to the life (i. iii. 386-387: ' Well, I said, and if they are to be cour- ageous, must they not learn, besides these, other lessons also, such as will have the effect of taking away the fear of death? ... I said, we shall have to obliterate obnoxious passages, beginning with the verse, — " I would rather be a serf on the land of a poor portionless man who is 55 How to Study Poetry might disgorge the endless darkness;'^ Tast the streams of Oceanus and the White Rock . . . they sped;'^ 'The nar- row straits of Hades and the ebbing of the deeps/^ On the other hand, whenever the poets deplore death as pitiable, or the want of burial as terrible, and utter in trem- bling tones such sentiments as the following : 'Leave me not unwept and imburied as thou goest hence;'* and 'His soul, fleeting from his limbs, went down to the house of Hades, wailing its own doom, leaving manhood and youth ;'^ and 'Cut me not off untimely, for sweet it is to see the light; force me not to see the realms below ;'^ they express the convictions of men who have suffered because they have not well to do, than rule over all the dead who have come to naught," — {pdys. xi. 489.) We must also expunge the verse — " He feared lest the mansions grim and squalid which the gods abhor should be seen both by mortals and immortals." — (//. xx. 64.) Or again — " O heavens ! is there in the house of Hades soul and ghostly form but no mind?" — (//. xxiii. 103.) Again — " To him (Teiresias) alone had the gods given wisdom ; the other souls do but flit as shadows." — {Odys. x. 495.) Again — "The soul flying from the limbs had gone to Hades, lamenting her fate, leaving strength and youth." — (//. xvi. 856.) Again — "And the soul, with shrilling cry, passed like smoke beneath the earth." — (//. xxiii. 100.) And— "As bats in hollow of mystic cavern, whenever any of them dropping out of the string falls from the rock, fly shrilling and hold to one another, so did they with shrilling cry hold together as they moved." — {Odys. xxiv. 6.) ' Also we shall have to reject all the terrible and appalling names which describe the world below — Cocytus and Styx, ghosts under the earth, and sapless shades, and any other words of the same type, the very mention of which causes a shudder to pass through the inmost soul of him who hears them.' ^ Bergk, Poetae Lyrici i. 426. ^ Odys. xxiv. 11. * Nauck 246. ^ Odys. xi. 72. *//. xvi. 856. « Euripides, Jpk. Aul. 1218. 56 How to Study Poetry been prepossessed and deceived by error, and such ideas cling to us and distress us the more because we are filled to the full with the same impotent passion which gave them utterance. Now we may fortify ourselves against such ideas by bear- ing in mind from the very first that poetry is not much concerned about the truth; indeed, what the truth is in regard to these matters, even those men who give their undi- vided attention to the search for truth confess that they find it very hard to determine. Therefore let us have these words of Empedocles at hand, 'So eye hath not seen, nor ear heard, nor the mind of man comprehended these things;'^ and these of Xenophanes,^ 'No man ever lived, nor ever shall, who knows the truth about the gods and a thousand other things;'^ and especially let us remember the passage from Plato in which Socrates denies knowledge of these things.* For when young men see that these matters make the heads of philosophers swim, they will pay less heed to the poets.** * Mullach, Fr. Phil. Graec. i. 2. ^ Founder of the Eleatic School of philosophy ; flourished in the second half of the sixth century B.C. ' His epic poems have for their themes, The Founding of Colophon, and The Colonization of Elea, but his reputation rested on his didactic poem, On Nature, and on his satires, in which he attacked the doctrines of other philosophers and poets. He was a zealous upholder of monotheism.' 2 Mullach i. 103. * Phaedo 69 : 'In the number of whom (the philosophers) I have been seeking, according to my ability, to find a place during my whole life , whether I have sought in a right way or not, and whether I have suc- ceeded or not, I shall truly know in a little while, if God will, when I myself arrive in the other world : that is my belief.' 5 See Introd. pp. 24-28, for discussion of this section. 57 How to Study Poetry III We shall still more thoroughly ground the young man, if, on introducing him to poetry, we explain to him that it is an imitative art and agent,^ analogous to painting. Not only must he be made acquainted with the common saying that poetry is vocal painting, and painting, silent poetry,^ but we must also teach him that when we see a painting of a lizard, an ape, or the face of Thersites, our pleasure and surprise are occasioned, not by the beauty of the object, but by the likeness of the painting to it. For it is naturally impossible for the ugly to be beautiful, but it is the imitation which is praised, if it reproduce to the life either an ugly or a beauti- ful object. On the contrary, if an ugly object is represented as beautiful, we deny the truthfulness or the consistency of the picture. Now there are some artists who paint shameful actions: thus Timotheus^ pictured Medea killing her chil- dren ; Theon* showed Orestes murdering his mother ; Par- * See Introd. pp. 18-24. * In the essay entitled Whether the Athenians were More Renowned for their Warlike Achievements or for their Learning c. iii, Plutarch attributes this saying to Simonides : * Indeed, Simonides calls painting silent poetry, and poetry speaking painting. For those actions which painters represent as occurrent history relates as past. And what the one sets forth in colors and figures, the other relates in words and sen- tences ; only they differ in the materials and manner of imitation.' See also Horace, Art of Poetry 361 fi".: For poems are like pictures : some appear Best in the distance, others standing near ; This loves the shade, while that the light endures. Nor shuns the nicest ken of connoisseurs ; This charms for once, and then the charm is o'er. While that, the more surveyed, still charms the more. ^A statuary and sculptor who belonged to the later Attic school of the time of Scopas and Praxiteles. He was one of the artists who executed the bas-relief which adorned the frieze of the mausoleum, about 352 B.C. ^ Of Samos, a painter who flourished from the time of Philip onward to that of the successors of Alexander. The peculiar merit of Theon was his prolific fancy. 58 How to Study Poetry rhasius/ Odysseus counterfeiting madness; and Chaere- phanes,^ the unchaste converse of women with men. In such instances it is especially important that the young man come to understand that we do not praise the action imitated, but the art, provided the subject is treated accu- rately. Since now poetry also frequently describes base actions and depraved emotions and character, the youth must not confound their artistic admirableness and success with truth, nor rank them as beautiful, but is only to praise them as accurate and truthful likenesses of the things treated. For as we are annoyed when we hear the grunting of a hog, the noise of pulleys, the whistling of the wind, and the roaring of the seas, but are pleased if any one imitates them with naturalness, as Parmenio did the hog,^ and Theodorus the pulleys, and as we avoid the unpleasant sight of an unhealthy man with festering sores, but take pleasure in witnessing the Philoctetes of Aristophon* and the Jocasta of Silanion,^ which are realistic likenesses of wasting and dying persons, so when the youth reads what Thersites the fool, or Sisyphus the debaucher, or Batrachus the brothel- keeper says or does, he must be taught to praise the genius and the art which imitates, but to censure the subjects and actions with opprobrium.^ For the excellence of a thing ^ A contemporary and rival of Zeuxis, who flourished 400-380 B.C. Zeuxis deceived the birds by his painted grapes ; Parrhasius deceived Zeuxis himself by his painting of a curtain. 2 Better known as Nicophanes : Greek painter, younger contempo- rary or successor of Apelles, but inferior to him ; he chose subjects of a meretricious character for his painting. ^ See Introd. p. 22, note. ■* A painter of some distinction. See Introd. p. 22, note. °A distinguished statuary in bronze. His statues belonged to two classes, ideal and actual portraits. Of the former, the most celebrated was his dying Jocasta, in which a deadly paleness was given to the face by the mixture of silver with the bronze. His statue of Sappho, which stood in the Prytaneum at Syracuse in the time of Verres, is alluded to by Cicero in terms of the highest praise. See Introd. p. 22, note. ^ See Milton, Apology for Smectymnuus : ' By the firm settling of these persuasions, I became, to my best memory, so much a proficient, that 59 How to Study Poetry and the excellence of its imitation are not the same ; fitness and naturalness constitute excellence, but to things base the base is natural and fit. To be sure, the boots of Demonides the cripple, which, when they were lost, he wished might fit the feet of him who stole them, were sorry objects, but they fitted him. Take also the following passage, Tf one must needs do wrong, let it be for power's sake ;'^ and this, 'Gain a reputation for fair dealing, and you may do the deeds of a knave ;'^ and, 'A talent for my dowry ! Shall I not have it ? Can I live if I slight it ? Shall I meet with sleep if I chance to loose it? Will I not suffer hell's torments if I sin against a silver talent ?'^ these are false and villainous speeches, but suited to Eteocles, Ixion, and an old griping usurer. If now we suggest to young men that the poets do not commend and praise these sentiments, but assign disgusting and base words to base and disgust- ing characters, they will not get wrong notions about the poets. On the contrary, their suspicion of the character will extend to his acts and words, the assumption being that the words and acts of a base man must likewise be base.* Of such a sort is the representation of Paris stealing away from the battle to lie with Helen; for as this lascivious and adulterous fellow is the only man whom the poet represents as lying with a woman in the daytime, it is clear that he regards incontinence as a shame and a reproach.^ if I found those authors anywhere speaking unworthy things of them- selves, or unchaste of those names which before they had extolled, this effect it wrought with me — from that time forward their art I still applauded, but the men I deplored.' ^Euripides, Phoeniss 524. See Cicero, De Off. iii. 21. 82 : 'Nam si violendum est jus, regnandi gratia violandum est.' '^Nauck 652. 3 Meineke, Fragmenta Comicorum Graecorum iv. 668. * See Poet. xxv. 8. *//. iii. 380-461. See Symposiacs iii. 6. 4, for similar comment on this episode. 60 How to Study Poetry IV In such passages one must observe very carefully whether or not the poet gives any intimation that he himself is dis- pleased with these ignoble sentiments. Instance Menander in the prologue to his Thetis: *Now sing to me, goddess, of such a maid, bold, youthful, and enticing, ever sinning, ever wronging others, ever shutting her doors to men, and crav- ing ever, loving no man, though always feigning love.'^ But Homer is the most particular of all the poets in this respect, for condemnation precedes the expression of base sentiments, and commendation, of the good. Of commenda- tion, note the following: 'So straightway he spake a sweet and cunning word;'^ 'He stood by his side, and refrained him with gentle words.'^ And as for condemnation, his testimony is all but a command to us not to use nor heed disgusting and base speeches. Thus, when he is about to narrate how uncivilly Agamemnon treated the priest, he pre- mises, 'Yet the thing pleased not the heart of Agamemnon, son of Atreus, but he roughly sent him away,'* intimating that such an act is brutal, hard-hearted, and unbecoming. And when he attributes these rash words to Achilles, 'Thou heavy with wine, thou with face of dog and heart of deer,'^ he passes this judgment upon them, 'Then Peleus' son spake again with bitter words to Atreus' son, and in no wise ceased from anger,'^ for it is against reason that words spoken in such anger and bitterness should be just. In a similar way he passes comment upon actions; thus, 'He ' Meineke iv. 131. "^ Odys. vi. 148. 3//. ii. 189. ^11. i. 124. 5 See Plato, Rep. iii. 390 : * What again of this line, — •*0 heavy with wine, who hast the eyes of a dog and the heart of a stag." (//. i. 225.) And of the verses which follow? Would you say that these or any other impertinent words which private men are supposed to address to their rulers, whether in verse or prose, are well or ill spoken ? They are ill spoken.' •//. i. 223. 61 How to Study Poetry said, and devised foul entreatment of noble Hector, stretch- ing him prone in the dust beside the bier of Menoitios' son.'^ He also makes good use of the criticism which one character passes upK)n another, for registering his own opinions of actions and speeches, as when he makes the gods say of the adultery of Ares, 111 deed, ill speed ! The slow catcheth the swift.'^ And notice the intimation in Hera's resentment of the disdain and arrogance of Hector, *So spake he boastfully, and queen Hera had indignation,'^ and observe the following in the light of Pandarus' shooting, 'So spake Athene, and persuaded his fool's heart.'* Now every attentive reader will notice such condemnations, which are expressed in the very words of the text.^ But other hints are embodied in the actions. Thus Eurip- ides is said to have replied to those who found fault with his Ixion as an impious and dirty fellow, 'Nay, but I did not take him off the stage until I had fastened him to a torturing wheel.' This teaching by implication is also used by Homer, and offers helpful and subtle comment upon those very fables most often misconstrued. For some men distort these stories, and pervert them into allegories,^ or what the men of old times called hidden meanings."^ Thus they say that the real meaning of the adultery of Aphrodite and Ares, discovered by Helios,^ is that when the star called Ares comes in conjunction with Aphrodite, bastardly births are produced, and that, since the sun rises and discovers them, they are not concealed. So will they have Hera's arraying herself for Zeus and the enchantment of the girdle® to mean the purification of the air in the vicinity of fire. As if the poet had not interpreted these episodes! For in the fable of Aphrodite, he teaches the attentive student that light ^ //. xxiii. 24. '^Odys. viii. 329. ^11. viii. 198. ^//. iv. 104. 5 See Schrader, Porphyria, Quaesii. Homer. 313-315, for observations similar to these. ^ See Saintsbury, History of Crit. i. 2. 10, and Schlemm, 32-36, for a discussion of the extent and character of early allegorical interpreta- tion. Such interpretation is rejected by Plato ; see Rep. ii, and Phaedrus. ''imovoiat. ®See Odys. viii. 265-367. ^//. xiv. 152-352. 62 Hozv to Study Poetry music, wanton songs, and obscene talk make for impure characters, unmanly lives, and natures given over to luxury and effeminacy, 'changes of raiment, and the warm bath, and love, and sleep.'^ And therefore he brings in Odysseus bidding the bard, 'Come now, change thy strain, and sing of the fashioning of the horse of wood,'^ thus teaching rightly that musicians and poets should take their themes from men of reason and understanding.^ In the fable of Hera he teaches most effectively that intercourse and favors secured from men through drugs, sorcery, and cunning not only are short-lived, inconstant, and soon cloying, but are quickly turned to displeasure and loathing when once passion has spent itself. This is exemplified by the way Zeus threatens Hera, when he says to her 'that thou mayest know if it profit thee at all, the dalliance and the love wherein thou didst lie with me, when thou hadst come from among the gods and didst beguile me.''* For if the disgrace and harm to the doer is embodied in the representation and imitation of a base act, the reader is helped rather than hindered. At any rate, philosophers employ examples from history for our correction and instruction, and the poets only differ from them by inventing and presenting fictitious narratives. Be it in jest or earnest, Melanthius^ was wont to say that the salvation of Athens depended upon the dis- sensions and quarrels among the orators; for thus not all the citizens took the same view, and in this diversity was a preventive of harm. Similarly the contradictions in the poets offset one another, so that the balance cannot incline unduly toward that which is hurtful. Therefore, when a comparison of one passage with another exposes a contra- diction, we ought to adhere to the better sentiment, as in ^ Odys. viii. 249. "^ Odys. viii. 492. 3 See like comment in Schrader, 74-75. ^//. XV. 32. See J^ep. iii. 390, for Plato's comment on these episodes of Zeus and Hera and of Ares and Aphrodite. 5 An Athenian tragic poet, of whom little is known beyond the attacks made on him by Aristophanes and the other comic poets. The most important passage respecting him is in the Peace of Aristophanes (796 ff.). Several specimens of his celebrated wit are preserved by Plutarch. 63 How to Study Poetry these instances : * "Many times, my son, the gods ruin men ;" " 'Tis easy to lay blame on the gods ;" '^ and again, ' "Much wealth is thine, but they are bankrupt ;" "Accursed the rich fool ;" '^ * "What then, must you kill yourself with sacrific- ing?" "Indeed it is no hardship to reverence the gods." '^ Such contradictions need not trouble a young man, if, as I have said, we teach him to fix upon the better sentiment. But when absurd sayings are not refuted in the con- text, they are to be canceled by contradictory sentiments occurring elsewhere in the same author, and we are not to be vexed with the poet because of such absurdities, nor to judge him harshly, but to accept them as playful masquer- ading. So, if he wishes, when he hears of the gods hurling one another from heaven, wounded by mortals, and quarrel- ing and brawling,* he may say to Homer, ' "Yet thou hast it in thee to devise other sayings more excellent than this,"^ and certainly you give utterance to far better thoughts else- where, as "The gods that live at ease ;"^ "Therein the blessed gods are glad for all their days ;"^ "This is the lot the gods have spun for miserable men, that they should live in pain ; yet themselves are sorrowless." '^ For these are sound and true opinions of the gods, but those above were only feigned to cause men fear. Again, when Euripides says, 'By many an artifice the gods, who are our betters, cause us to stumble,'® it is well to return a better answer in the words of Euripides himself, 'If the gods do anything base, they are no gods.'^® And when in a very bitter and provoking way Pindar says, 'We must stop at nothing that will enfeeble our enemy, once our friend,'^^ we shall answer, 'But you yourself say that "Unrighteous pleasure awaits the bitterest end." '^^ So when Sophocles says, 'Sweet is the gain which falsehood brings,'^^ we shall rejoin, 'But we have heard you say that "False words produce no fruit." '^* 1 Nauck 345. ^ Ibid 542. ^ Nauck 694. 4 See Plato, Rep. ii. 378 ; iii. 390 ; and pp. 104-105. ^11. vii. 358. 6//. vi. 138. '^ Odys. vi. 46. « //. xxii. 525. » Nauck 519. ^0 Ibid. 355. See Plutarch, The Contradictions of the Stoics jj. 11 Isthm. iv. 48. 12 Ibid. vii. 47. ^^ Nauck 246. 1* Ibid. 246. 64 How to Study Poetry Again, to what the same author says of riches, 'The inaccessible and the accessible alike open up to wealth, while nowhere may the man who earns his daily bread compass his heart's desire, even by entreaty; riches truly make the unshapely body fair to see, and cause the ineloquent man to speak with skilful tongue,'^ may be opposed many of his own words, such as these : 'From honor, poverty doth not debar ','^ 'Poverty is no reproach to him whose thoughts are noble ;'^ 'Wherein are a multitude of fine things a boon, if the fool's anxiety is the price paid for blessed wealth?'* Menander undoubtedly stirred up and inflamed the love of pleasure by the following amorous and burning lines, 'Everything that has life and with us beholds the common sun is the slave of pleasure ;'^ but at another time he pursues a different course and inclines us to virtue, checking the rage of lust, when he says, 'An infamous life is a reproach, however sweet it be.'® These lines are contrary to the former, and both better and more profitable. Accordingly, such comparison and critical examination of passages either inclines one to the better, or at least destroys one's confidence in the worse. But if any of the poets do not themselves offer an escape from those things which they have said amiss, it is well to employ the contrary sentiments of other famous men, so that the better may outbalance the worse. Thus, when Alexis'^ tempts people with these words, 'The wise man must needs heap up pleasures, and three there are which have the power to make life fully and finally complete: to eat, to drink, to follow after wanton sports ; and if other pleasures be added to these, they are to be counted over-measure,'^ we must remember that Socrates, in far different strain, says that 'Bad men live that they may eat and drink, but good men eat and drink that they may live.' And to offset the » Ibid. ii8. 2 Ibid. 247. 3 Ibid. 247. * Ibid. 207. 5 Meineke iv. 266. ^ Ibid. iv. 282. ' Comic poet ; b. B.C. 392. ' One of the most important and prolific writers of the Middle Attic Comedy, yet living as he did to the age of 106, he reached far into the period of the New Attic Comedy. The part of the parasite was considered his special invention.' ^ Meineke iii. 518. 65 How to Study Poetry sentiment of the man who wrote, 'Against the knave, knav- ery itself is no bad tool' — as it were commending us to be- come like the knave — we are to use the words of Diogenes,^ who, being asked how a man might revenge himself upon an enemy, said, 'by being an honest and upright man him- self.' Diogenes may also be cited against Sophocles, who caused utter despair to multitudes of men when he wrote thus about the mysteries: 'Thrice happy mortals they who behold these mysteries ere the journey to Hades; to them alone is it given there to enjoy life's vigor; on others all ills attend.' For when Diogenes heard some such thing, 'What then,' says he, 'shall Pataecion the thief enjoy a better lot than Epaminondas,^ simply because he was initiated?' And when Timotheus* in the theatre was extolling Artemis, calling her 'mad, inspired, possessed, frenzied,'^ Cinesias® straightway shouted back, 'May thy daughter be such a one.' Similarly, when Theognis^ said, 'Naught may he say or do who bears the yoke of poverty ; his tongue is bound,'^ Bion^ cleverly replied, 'How comes it then that thou thyself, being so poor, so copiously pratest and chatterest in this manner ?'^^ ^ See pp. 117. "^ Nauck 247. 3 Statesman and general ; b. at Thebes about 418 B.C. Epaminondas was the successful leader of the Thebans in their wars with the Spartans, showing remarkable military genius. ' He left a pure and exalted repu- tation as a patriot, a statesman, and a sage, and is universally admitted to have been one of the greatest captains of antiquity. Cicero expressed the opinion that Epaminondas was the greatest man that Greece had produced.' * The most admired Greek musician of his day ; flourished towards the close of the fourth century, B.C. His innovation consisted in the use of a chorus in rendering the so-called Nome, and in the employ- ment of mimetic action to enliven the delivery. ^ Bergk 3. 620. « Probably the dithyrambic poet ridiculed by Aristophanes. ' See p. 54. ^ 177. ^ A Cyreniac philosopher of the third cen- tury B.C., noted for his sharp sayings. ^^ Schlemm attributes the ridicule of allegory in this chapter, and the moral interpretation of Homer, to the influence of lost Peripatetic writings, the discussion of the contradictions in the poets to the Stoics, and the chronologically impossible anecdotes in the last paragraph to Plutarch's ingenious association of the famous words of poets and philosophers. 66 How to Study Poetry Nor is the context to be ignored as a factor in correct interpretation. Just as physicians believe that, although the cantharides is deadly, its feet and wings are efficacious in nullifying the effect of the poison,^ so in poetry if any noun or verb in the context can make a better case out for a pas- sage, it should be eagerly taken up with and noted. This method should be employed in the following verses, 'Lo this is now the only due we pay to miserable men, to cut the hair and let the tear fall from the cheek ;'2 'This is the lot the gods have spun for miserable men, that they should live in pain.'^ For Homer does not say that for absolutely every man the gods have woven a painful life, but for those who are foolish and unreasonable, whom, because wicked- ness has made them such, he is wont to call wretched and pitiable.* VI We shall be further helped in our efforts to put the best interpretation upon doubtful passages by observing whether or not a word is used in its ordinary sense f in this a young man should be better trained than in the study of dialects. Thus it is a point in philology, and rather an interesting one too, that ptyeSavo? {making one shudder) means an evil death, for the Macedonians use Sapos as a synonym for death. The Aeolians call victory won through endurance and persistency Ka/A/Aovoy/ {a staying behind), and the Dry- opians call divinities 7ro7rot(0 strange ones!). Further, if we wish to be helped rather than hindered by the poets, it is both profitable and necessary to know how they use the names of gods, as also the terms for evil and ^ See Dioscorides i. 66. '^Odys. iv. 197. "^ li. xxiv. 526. * See Aristotle, Poet. xxv. 8-20, for similar suggestions. ^ Poet. xxv. 8-20. * Ep. for Karanovi], explained by Schol. r] ek KaTafiovrjg vUrj. 67 Hozv to Study Poetry good, what they mean by Tv^^ and Motpa {Fortune and Fate), and whether, as in the case of a number of other words, they use these in one or in many senses. For oticos {house, abode) sometimes means a material house, as, 'into his high-roofed home,'^ and sometimes an estate, as, * My property' is being devoured/^ Similarly, ^tbro? {life) means life, as, 'But Poseidon of the dark locks made his shaft of no avail, grudging him the life/* but also wealth, as, 'that others may consume his livelihood/^ Again dXvctv {mental wandering) is also used instead of the terms for sore vexation and perplexity respectively, as * So spake he, and she departed in amaze and was sore troubled,'^ and the same word also signifies boasting and rejoicing, as, 'Art thou beside thyself for joy, because thou hast beaten the beggar Irus?''^ Likewise Boaiuv {to move quickly) means to move, as in Euripides, 'the whale rush- ing beyond the Atlantic deeps,'^ and again, to sit down and to remain seated, as in Sophocles, 'Why sit ye here, your hands thus wreathed with the suppliant's boughs?'® It is also in good taste, as the grammarians teach, to, adapt words to the matter in hand, by construing them from their customary meanings, as in this passage, vq oXCyrjv atvcif/, /xcyoXT/ 8* m opr(a OicrBca {a fresh pittance courteously to decline, but to store up goods in abundance) ,'^^ for here aivctv {to tell or speak of) has the meaning of liraivtXv (to approve, praise, in the sense of to decline courteously) , and * Odys. V. 42 : oIkov kg vipdpotpov. ^ B. and L. read dwelling. ^ Odys. iv. 318: eadisTai fioL olKog. '^ II. xiii. 562 : afievTjvuaev di oi alxfiijv Kvavoxcura Roaeidduv, fSiSroio fiey^pag. ^ Odys. xiii. 419: f3ioTov 6e fiot h7i7[,oi edovoi. • //. V. 352 : £>g la&, f/ ^ akvovcf dnefiijaeTo, reipero 6' alvag. ' Odys. xviii. 332: ^ dTiveig brt Ipov kviKTjGaq tov akijTTfv. 8 Nauck 523: laJTOQ Bodrov k^ ' ArTiavriK^g d^6g. » Oed. Tyr. 2 : rivag tz6& edpag rdade fioi Bodl^ere iKTf/pioig KlddoLGiv e^eaTS/ifievoi. Hermann interprets the word as meaning, come in haste to this suppliant posture, or sit in earnest supplication. '0 Hesiod, W. and D. 641. 68 How to Study Poetry cTratvctv in turn is used instead of napaiT€La-6aL (to beg off). Similarly, in familiar intercourse we say KoXm exuv (to be well), and we bid a thing x^P^*-^ (farewell), when we do not care for it nor wish to receive it. So in the expression iirawj] ll€p(Te7yos {oak). So when a young man reads such passages as these, 'Then the Danaans by their virtue brake the battalions ;'® 'If death is the common lot of man- kind let men die nobly, merging life in virtue ;'^ he should at once appreciate that the poet is speaking of that best and most divine state which we deem to be rightness of reason, excellence of the rational nature, and a normal condition of the soul.^ But when he reads, 'But for virtue, Zeus increaseth it in men or minisheth it;'^ and 'Virtue and * //. xxiv. 527. See p. 55, note. ^11. vii. 69. ^Odys. viii. 81. ^11. xi. 540. ^ Hesiod, W. andD. 289. *//. xi. 90. L. L. and M. read valour. ' For similar definitions after Zeno, Chrysippus, and Cleanthes compare Diogenes Laertius vii. 89 ; Cicero, Tusculanae Disputationes iv. 34 ; Stobaeus, Anthologium ii. ^ Nauck 529. ^11. XX. 242. L. L. and M. read valour. 71 Hoiv to Study Poetry honour upon wealth attend ;'^ let him not sit down in gaping admiration of rich men, as if their silver straightway could purchase virtue, nor let him think that Fortune may increase or lessen his wisdom, but rather let him conceive that the poet used virtue as a synonym for reputation, power, prosperity, or some such word. Also, at one time the poet makes KaKon^s {evil) stand for a wicked and vicious heart, as in Hesiod, 'For evil is at hand in great abundance,'^ and at another for some misfortune or ill-luck, as in Homer, Tor men quickly age in evil fortune.'^ Then any one would be sadly deceived who thought that the poets, like phil- osophers, use the word evSaufiovui (happiness) to denote a perfect habitual enjoyment of all good things, or the completeness of life in accordance with nature, and that they do not frequently misuse the word by calling the rich man happy, and power and reputation happiness. Homer, indeed, uses these words correctly. Thus look you, I have no joy of my lordship among these my possessions,'* and Menander as well, 'For my much possessions I am called rich by all, but happy by none.'^ But if, as said above, one does not attend to the metaphorical uses and misuses of the words, Euripides causes much misunderstanding and confusion when he writes, 'Let not a life of weal become a life of woe to me ;'® or, 'Why honorest thou tyranny, injus- tice triumphant?'^ But enough has been said upon this point. VII Another principle that must be reiterated in teaching young men is, that while poetry is based upon imitation, and employs embellishment and richness of diction suited to the actions and characters in hand,^ it does not resign * fV. andD. 313. ^ ly^ ^^^ j) 287. ^ Odys. xix. 360. * Odys. iv. 93. ^ Meineke iv. 266. ^ Medea Sg^- '^ Phoeniss. 549. ® Poet. vi. 2-3 : ' Tragedy, then, is an imitation of an action that is serious, complete, and of a certain magnitude ; in language embellished with each kind of artistic ornament, the several kinds being found in separate parts of the play. ... By " language embellished," I mean 72 How to Study Poetry the likeness of the truth, since the charm of imitation is probability.^ Wherefore such imitation as does not wholly ignore the truth weaves a mixture of virtue and vice into the action. This is done in the poetry of Homer, which completely renounces the principles of the Stoics, who hold that nothing bad can be where virtue is, and nothing good where vice is, but that the ignorant man is ever in error, and the cultured man always right. Such stuff we hear in the schools. But in the life and affairs of the mass of mankind, according to the judgment of Euripides, 'Virtue and vice are never found alone, but blended, as it were.' Now since poetry does not keep strictly to truth, it makes much use of variety and transitions.^ For reversals of for- tune furnish plots with emotional disturbance, with the unex- pected and surprising, upon which deep emotion and delight best attend. But the uncomplicated is not fitted to stir emotion and serve as fiction. Wherefore the poets do not make their characters uniformly victorious, successful, or happy, nor when the gods engage in human affairs are they represented as free from passion and error, lest, through language into which rhythm, "harmony," and song enter. By "the several kinds in separate parts," I mean that some parts are rendered through the medium of verse alone, others again with the aid of song.' ^ See p. 22, note 2. 2 Poet, x-xiii : ' Plots are either Simple or Complicated. . . . An action which is one and continuous, . . I call Simple, when the turning point is reached without Reversal of Fortune, or Recognition ; Compli- cated, when it is reached with Reversal of Fortune or Recognition, or both. ... A Reversal of Fortune is, as we have said, a change by which a train of action produces the opposite of the effect intended ; and that, according to our rule of probability or necessity. ... A Recognition ... is a change from ignorance to knowledge, producing love or hate between the persons destined by the poet for good or bad fortune. ... A perfect tragedy should be arranged, not on the simple, but on the complicated plan. ... It follows plainly, in the first place, that the change of fortune presented must not be the spectacle of a perfectly good man brought from prosperity to adversity : for this moves neither pity nor fear ; it simply shocks us. Nor, again, that of a bad man passing from adversity to prosperity ; ... it neither satis- fies the moral sense, nor calls forth pity or fear.' 73 How to Study Poetry absence of peril and conflict, the poem should fail to excite and astonish.^ VIII Since this is true, we should so guide a youth in his early study of poetry that reverence for names may not lead him to esteem the fair and stalwart heroes as men of wisdom and justice, the perfection of princes, and the standard of all excellence and virtue. For he will suffer harm if he thinks all their acts astonishingly great, and is quite unwil- ling to disapprove of them himself, or to accept criticism from others, even if it be of those who act and speak as follows : 'For would, O father Zeus, and Athene, and Apollo, would that not one of all the Trojans might escape death, nor one of the Argives, but that we twain might avoid destruction, that alone we might undo the sacred coronal of Troy ;'^ and, 'Most pitiful of all that I heard was the voice of the daughter of Priam, of Cassandra, whom hard by me the crafty Clytemnestra slew;'^ and, 'So she besought me continually by my knees to go in first unto the concubine, that the old man might be hateful to her;'* and, 'Father Zeus, surely none of the gods is cruder than thou.'^ A young man should not get into the way of praising any such sentiment, nor of showing his clever powers of persua- sion in finding excuses and inventing plausible misinterpre- tations for bad passages; rather let him keep in mind that poetry is an imitation of character and life, and of men who are not wholly perfect, pure, and blameless, but in some degree subject to passion, error, and ignorance, who, how- ^ See Plutarch's essay Concerning Music i6 : 'The mixed Lydian moves the affections, and is fit for tragedies. This mood, as Aristoxe- nus alleges, was invented by Sappho, from whom the tragedians learned it and joined it with the Doric. The one becomes a majestic, lofty style, the other mollifies and stirs to pity, both which are the properties of tragedy.' 2//. xvi. 97. 3 Odys. xi. 421. *//. ix. 452. ^11. iii. 365. How to Study Poetry ever, through strength of character are often changed for the better.^ For if his mind is thus prepared, a young man will receive no harm from his reading, for while he will be delighted and inspired by wise words and acts, he will not entertain, but dislike, those which are bad. On the other hand, the man who admires indiscriminately and accepts everything, whose judgment is enslaved by his esteem for the names of heroes, like those who affect Plato's humpback and the lisping of Aristotle, will take up with much that is bad before he realizes it.^ So a youth must not be timid, nor, like superstitious people in a temple, prostrate himself in holy awe of everything, but must form the habit of pronouncing his judgment with con- fidence, as, 'This was right and proper ;' 'That was not well/ For example, chafing at the delays in the campaign, because he was extremely desirous of winning distinction in arms, Achilles called together an assembly of the soldiers while they were suffering from an epidemic. But being a physi- cian, and noting that the decisive ninth day of the malady was passed, he perceived that the sickness was not an ordi- nary one nor produced by usual causes, and hence, on rising to speak, he did not harangue the crowd, but counseled the King, 'Son of Atreus, now deem I that we shall return wandering home again ;'^ and he spake well and with due moderation. But when the soothsayer professed fear of the anger of the chief of the Greeks, observing neither wis- dom nor moderation, Achilles swore that while he himself were alive no one should lay hands on the old man, 'not even if thou mean Agamemnon.'* Here he showed con- tempt and disdain for his commander. And when he was provoked still more, he unsheathed his sword, thinking to kill the king, which was neither right nor expedient. But straightway he repented and 'thrust the great sword back into the sheath, and was not disobedient to the saying of Athene.'^ And this last act was right and noble, for ^ See Butcher, c. viii, on The Ideal Tragic Hero. 'The attitude taken is Peripatetic ; see Ps.-T>lutarch, Of the Life ana Poetry of Homer 135. ^Il.\. 59. '*//• i. 90. ^ //. i. 220. 75 How to Study Poetry although he was not able wholly to quiet his anger, he yet made it obey the restraints of reason before it was too late. Again, Agamemnon made a fool of himself by his actions and words in the assembly, but in the Chryseis affair acted more as a dignified prince should ; for though Achilles Svept anon, and sat him down apart,'^ when Briseis was taken away from him, Agamemnon put on board ship, gave to the care of others, and sent away the woman, who, a little before, he declared was dearer to him than his lawful wife. Simi- larly, when Phoenix was cursed by his father because of the concubine, he said. Then took I counsel to slay him with the keen sword ; but some immortal stayed mine anger, bringing to my mind the people's voice and all the reproaches of men, lest I should be called a father-slayer amid the Achaians.'^ Aristarchus^ was fearful of the effect of this passage, and omitted it; but it served a legitimate purpose, for Phoenix was trying to show Achilles what a thing is wrath, and what men do in anger, heeding neither reason nor advice. The poet also introduces Meleager at first highly wroth with the citizens, and later pacified.* Thus by rightly disparaging, he encourages one not to yield to anger, and by praising repentance as right and expedient, encourages one to battle against passion and hold sway over it. But where it is no easy matter to pass judgment, we are to help the young man to distinguish as follows : If when Nausicaa beheld the strange Odysseus she felt the passion of Calypso for him, and because she was passionate and ripe for marriage made such light talk as this to her maidens, 'Would that such an one might be called my husband, dwelling here, and that it »//. i. 349. 2//ix. 458. 3 Grammarian and critic ; 222-150 B.C. ' His special excellence lay in textual criticism, in which he showed great acumen, rare powers of divination, and soundness of method. His leading principle of exe- gesis was the explanation of the author out of himself. He published a large number of corrected texts, with critical signs. The Homeric scholia derive much of their value from the preservation of the criticisms of Aristarchus.' •* See //. ix. 527-605. 76 How to Study Poetry might please him here to abide/^ then her boldness and incontinence were blameworthy. But if, because she recog- nized his breeding by his language and was charmed by his intelligent address, she wished to marry him in prefer- ence to a dancing fop or seaman of her own people, she was to be commended.^ Again, Odysseus was pleased that Penelope conversed in a free and easy way with the suitors, and that they presented to her robes and other ornaments; now if his pleasure sprang from covetousness and greed, 'because she drew from them gifts, and beguiled their souls with soothing words,'^ he was a worse panderer than Polia- ger, the character in the comedy, 'Happy Poliager, who has as paramour a gold-bringing Capricorn/* On the contrary, if he thought that the hopes which Penelope held forth, by making the suitors over-confident and blinded to the real issue, would put them more within his power, his pleasure and good spirits were quite proper. Again, after the Phaea- cians had set him ashore with his treasure and departed, if by counting it over in such a lonely place, where he was ignorant of the inhabitants, he showed anxiety for his goods, 'lest the men be gone, and have taken back of their gifts upon their hollow ship,'** his covetousness deserves to be pitied, or rather, I should say, to be abhorred. But if, as some think, he was doubtful whether or not the land were Ithaca, and thought that to find his goods intact would be proof of the sincerity of the Phaeacians — for, if dishonest, they would not set him down on a strange shore free of charge and leave him there with his fKDSsessions untouched — then he used a lawful test, and deserves to be commended for his good sense. Others find fault with his being put ashore while asleep, if indeed the incident really happened, and say that the Tuscans preserve a tradition that he was naturally a sleepy-head, and not liked on that account. But if the sleep was not genuine, but was feigned to relieve him ^ Odys. vi. 254. ' See p. 107, for St. Basil's comment on this episode. ' 2 Odys. xviii. 282. * Meineke iv. 667. ^ Odys. xiii. 216. 77 How to Study Poetry from embarrassment — for he was ashamed to dismiss the Phaeacians without gifts and feasting, yet knew that such festivity would discover him to his enemies — they approve of the episode.^ If then we explain this principle of judgment to young men, and without hesitation censure some things and praise others, we shall preserve their characters from corruption, and arouse their emulation of what is good. And especially should we do this in the case of all those tragedies in which actions ignoble and wicked are accompanied by persuasive and subtle words. For there is not much truth in the say- ing of Sophocles, 'From acts not good, good words may ne'er proceed.'^ Indeed he himself was wont to connect pleasing speeches and philanthropic motives with base char- acters and irrational actions. And in a fellow-author you may see Phaedra laying on Theseus the blame of her inter- course with Hippolytus, on the ground of his maltreatment of her.^ Also in The Trojan Dames he allows Helen the same license of speech against Hecuba, who, as Helen thinks, ought to be punished more than herself, because she gave birth to her seducer.* Now the young man should not get into the way of thinking anything of this sort clever and shrewd, nor of approving such sophistry, but he should dis- like such words more than the licentious deeds they excuse. IX Above all it will be of advantage to inquire the reason why each idea is expressed. For while Cato was yet a mere child, though he always minded his tutor, he yet asked the cause and reason of the commands. To be sure, the poets are not to be obeyed as tutors and lawgivers, unless their thought is based on reason. But it will be so based if it is morally good, and, if bad, its utter emptiness will be apparent. Now the average man questions sharply the ' Porphyrio offers similar interpretations; see Schrader 117-118 ; Schlemm proposes a common Peripatetic source. ^ Nauck 247. 2 Nauck, Eurip. Fr. 430^. 113. '*9I9- 78 Hozv to Study Poetry reasonableness of such words as the following: 'Never at drinking-bouts should we place the ladle upon the mixing- bowl;'^ and, 'Whensoever a warrior from the place of his own car can come at a chariot of the foe, let him thrust forth with his spear ;'^ while he accepts without question even worse sentiments, such, for example, as the following: 'The consciousness of a father's or a mother's wrong-doing makes a slave of any man, be he ever so daring;'^ and, 'He whom fortune has opposed must needs think meanly of himself.'* And yet these last sentiments affect character and injure a man by debasing his judgment and begetting sordid ideas, unless he is accustomed to ask in reply, 'Why now must he needs think meanly of himself whom fortune has opposed? Why not rather resist it and rise unhumbled? And why, if I am a good and wise son of a parent who is foolish and bad, should I not rather respect myself for my vir- tue than be dejected and cast down because of his stupidity?'^ He who can thus stand firm against all such sayings, and not, as it were, surrender himself to every wind of doctrine, and who can recognize the truth of the proverb, 'The dolt loves to fee a thrill at every speech,'^ will reject such judg- ments as neither truthful nor profitable. These suggestions will render harmless the study of poetry.'^ ^ Hesiod, W. and B. 744. ^11. iv. 306. ^ Euripides, Hippol. 424. ^ Nauck 695. ' See Of the Training of Children ii, where Plutarch reasons very differently from this same passage of Euripides : ' For the spirits of men who are alloyed and counterfeit in their birth are naturally enfeebled and debased ; as rightly said the poet again, — A bold and daring spirit is often daunted, When with the guilt of parents' crimes 'tis haunted.' [This translation is from the Goodwin edition.] * Mullach I. 326. ' This style of criticism follows Bion, who attacks this same line from Euripides ; see Diogenes Laertius iv. 51, and Schlemm's comment, 65. 79 How to Study Poetry X As on a vine the leaves and branches frequently cover up and conceal the ripe fruit, so the diction of poetry and its profusion of fictitious narrative conceal many useful and helpful things from the attention of a young man. Now he ought not to be thus led astray, but rather to give himself wholly to those things which make for virtue and exert a powerful influence upon character. I shall therefore develop this thought, though briefly and only in outline, leaving it to more ostentatious writers to verify and illustrate my ideas. First then, let the youth, knowing well the good and bad respectively in manners and men, turn his attention to the words and deeds which the poet attributes to his several characters. Though he is speaking in anger, Achilles says to Agamemnon, 'Never win I meed like unto thine, when the Achaians sack any populous citadel of Trojan men,'^ but Thersites addresses him abusively, 'Surely thy huts are full of bronze and many women are in thy huts, the chosen spoils that we Achaians give thee first of all, whene'er we take a town.'^ Again, Achilles says, If ever Zeus grant us to sack some well-walled town of Troy-land,'^ but Ther- sites, 'whom I perchance or some other Achaian have led captive.'* At another time, when Agamemnon, inspecting the army, speaks abusively to Diomedes, the latter makes no reply, 'but had respect to the chiding of the king revered,'^ but Sthenelus, a fellow of no account, says, 'Atreides, utter not falsehood, seeing thou knowest how to speak truly. We avow ourselves to be better men by far than our fathers were.'® If such differences are not overlooked they will teach a youth to regard modesty and moderation as the marks of gentility, but to shun boasting and bragging as vulgar. It is worth while, in this connection to notice the conduct of Agamemnon ; for he passes Sthenelus by without 1//. i. 163. 2//. ii. 226. ^//. i. 128. *//. ii. 231. **//. iv. 402. •//. iv. 404. 80 How to Study Poetry noticing him, yet he does not neglect Odysseus, but answers him, 'seeing how he was wroth, and took back his saying/* Had he apologized to all, he would have appeared undigni- fied and servile, and had he disdained all, arrogant and unreasonable. Best of all is the conduct of Diomedes, for during the battle he bears in silence the king's abuse, but after the battle deals plainly with him, saying, 'My valour didst thou blame in chief amid the Danaans.'^ It is also a good idea to take notice of the difference between the ways in which a discreet man and a pompous soothsayer addresses a crowd. Thus Calchas, since he lacks a sense of the fitness of things, scruples not to denounce the King in public as accountable for the plague. But when Nestor would conciliate Achilles, in order that before the multitude he may not seem to accuse the king of erroneous passion, he advises, 'Spread thou a feast for the councilors ; that is thy place, and seemly for thee. ... In the gathering of many shalt thou listen to him that deviseth the most excellent counsel ;'^ accordingly, after the meal he sends out the elders. This last course tends to correct the mistake, but the other was an insulting accusation. One should notice as well the differences in racial char- acteristics. For example, the Trojans rush ferociously to battle with savage cries, but the Greeks 'in silence feared their captains;'* for to fear officers in the presence of the enemy is the mark of heroism and obedience. Wherefore Plato was wont to fear reproach and shame more than pains and perils, and Cato said that he liked men who blush better than those who blanch. Then too, a promise has its own *//. iv. 357. ^11. ix. 34. Compare comments of Porphyrio, Schrader 75. 4 ; Ps.-Plutarch 168. ^11. ix. 70. * II. iv. 431. See Rep. iii. 389 : 'Then would you praise or blame the injunction of Diomedes in Homer — , "Friends, sit still and obey my word (//. iv. 412)," and the verses which follow — "The Greeks marched breathing prowess (//. iii. 8.)," " In silent awe of their leaders (//. iv. 431)," and other sentiments of the same kind ? They are good.' 81 How to Study Poetry peculiar worth; Dolon promises, 'I will go straight to the camp, until I may come to the ship of Agamemnon,'^ but Diomedes makes no promise, and only says that he will fear the less if a companion be sent with him. Hence fore- sight is Grecian and civil ; rashness, barbaric and rude ; the one to be emulated, the other to be avoided.^ It is also not unprofitable to notice the state of mind of the Trojans and of Hector, when he and Ajax are about to engage in single combat. When a great cry went up because one of the boxers in the Isthmian games received a blow in the face, Aeschylus said, 'See what training does for one; the spectators cry out, but the man who was struck says not a word !' Likewise, when the poet says that the Greeks rejoiced when they saw Ajax approaching resplendent with armor, but that 'sore trembling came upon the Trojans, on the limbs of every man, and Hector's own heart beat within his breast,'^ who does not wonder at the difference? The heart of him who risks himself only beats inwardly, as of one engaging in a wrestling-match, or rather in running a race, while the bodies of the spectators tremble and shake in apprehension for the safety of their beloved prince.* In the same poet one may observe the difference between a very brave man and the worst of knaves, for Thersites 'was hateful to Achilles above all and to Odys- seus,'^ but Ajax, ever friendly to Achilles, says of him to Hector, 'Now verily shalt thou well know, man to man, what manner of princes the Danaans likewise have among them, even after Achilles, render of men, the lion-hearted.'® This is a veritable panegyric of Achilles, and is followed by hearty commendation of the soldiers in general, 'Yet are we such as to face thee, yea, and many of us ;'^ here Ajax does not say that he is the best and only champion, but one of many able to do battle.^ 1//. X. 325. * Almost the same words occur in Ps. -Plutarch 149. 3//. vii. 215. ** Compare Ps. -Plutarch 135. ^ II. n. 220. ^11. vii. 226. '//. vii. 231. 8 This sentence closely resembles he scholium of Aristarchus. 82 Hozv to Study Poetry Enough now as to this matter of contrasts, unless we wish to add that many a Trojan was taken alive, but not a single Greek, and that some of the Trojans begged for mercy, as, for example, Adrastus, the sons of Antimachus, and Lycaon, and that even Hector besought Achilles for burial, but that no one of the Greeks did such a thing; showing that it is characteristic of barbarians to bow the suppliant knee on the field, but of Greeks to conquer or die. XI As in pastures the bee seeks the flower, the goat seeks the bud, the hog the root, and other creatures the fruit and seed, so in reading poetry one man culls the flowers of history, another dwells upon the beauty and the arrange- ment of words, as Aristophanes, who says of Euripides, T delight in his imposing rhetoric,'^ and still others — ^and to this class I am now addressing myself — are concerned with those ideas which strengthen character. Such must be made to see how deplorable it is that the lover of fiction should allow nothing of novelty and extravagance in narra- tive to escape him, and the philologist notice the rhetorical purity of every sentence, but the devotee of honor and virtue, who studies poetry for instruction rather than for pleasure, read with careless indifference writings which commend man- liness, temperance, and justice. Take for example the fol- lowing : 'Tydeus' son, what ails us that we forget our impet- uous valor? Nay, come hither, friend, and take thy stand by me, for verily it will be shame if Hector of the gleaming helm take the ships. '^ For to see a man of preeminent wisdom in danger of utter defeat anp6v7j(TK) is the most divine and kingly quality, and that therein consists the supreme preeminence of Zeus, since it is the source of all the other virtues. A young man should also become accustomed to give vigilant heed to such sentiments as these: 'And he will not lie to thee, for he is very wise ;'2 ' Antilochus, who once wert wise, what thing is this thou hast done? Thou hast shamed my skill and made my horses fail ;'^ 'Glaukos, where- fore hath such an one as thou spoken thus over measure? Out on it, I verily thought that thou in wisdom wert above all others.'* For a wise man does not lie, nor take an unfair advantage in athletic contests, nor bring false accusations against another man. And when the poet says that Pan- darus was led by his folly to violate the truce, it is evident that he believes that a man of wisdom would not do an unjust act. The like is also taught of self-control in such passages as the following, 'Now Proitos' wife, goodly Anteia, lusted after him, to have converse in secret love, but no whit pre- vailed she, for the uprightness of his heart, on wise Bellero- phon;'^ 'Verily at the first she would none of the foul deed, the fair Clytemnestra, for she had a good understanding;'^ for in these the poet represents self-control as resulting from wisdom. And when in the instances of hortatory addresses during battles he says, 'Shame, ye Lykians, 1//. xiii. 354. "^ Odys. iii. 20. ^11. xxiii. 570. *//. xvii. 170. ^11. vi. 160. ^Odvs. iii. 265. 86 How to Study Poetry whither do ye flee ? Now be ye strong ;'^ and 'But let each man conceive shame in his heart, and indignation, for verily great is the strife that hath arisen ;'2 he declares that the man of self-control is the brave man, because he is ashamed to do a base act, and is able to ignore pleasure, and to encounter dangers. In line with this, in the Persae Timo- theus spiritedly and well exhorts the Greeks, 'Respect honor as the soldier's ally/^ Aeschylus also, in writing of Amphi- araus, places it to one's credit not to be puffed up and arrogant, nor to lose one's head at the plaudits of the multi- tude, 'For his desire is not to seem the bravest, but to be, and he reaps in thought the deep furrow, whence grows the fruit of good counsel.'* For it is the part of a wise man to feel confidence in himself and in his own true worth. Since, then, all excellencies are reducible to wisdom, it fol- lows that every kind of virtue is a product of reason and education. XII As the bee instinctively gathers the smoothest and sweet- est honey from the most bitter blossoms and the sharpest thistles, so, if trained rightly in the poets, boys will learn in one way or another to gather something useful and profitable from suspiciously vulgar and irrational passages. For example, it certainly looks very much as if Agamemnon were bribed when he dismisses from the army the rich man who presented Aethe to him: 'Her unto Agamemnon did Anchises' son Echepolos give in fee, that he might escape from following him to windy Ilios and take his pleasure at home; for great wealth had Zeus given him.'^ Yet, as Aristotle observes,^ he did right in preferring a good mare to such a man, because a coward weakling, effem- inate through wealth and luxury, is of less worth than ^11. xvi, 422. *//. xiii. 121. ^Bergk 3. 622. ^ Sept. 579. The translation is after Verrall. ^ //. xxiii. 297. ® Probably in the Homeric Questions. 87 How to Study Poetry 2l dog, yea, or even an ass. Again it seems most shame- ful in Thetis to encourage her son in pleasure, and to remind him of the delights of love. But, on the other hand, it is well to compare the self-control of Achilles, for, though he loves Briseis, who has come back to him, yet because he knows that his days here are numbered, he does not hasten to the fruition of pleasure ; further he does not mourn for his friend by inactivity and neglect of duty, as other men are wont, for though in his sorrow he refrains from pleasure, he yet busies himself with the affairs of the army. Again, Archilochus is not praised because he tries by drinking and carousing to dispel his grief for a brother-in-law who had been drowned in the sea ; yet he offers a plausible excuse : *My grief will cure no ill, nor will my pleasure and feasting make matters worse. '^ Now if he thought he did no harm in following after pleasure and feasting, how shall we do worse if we study philosophy, or conduct public affairs, or visit the market, or descend to the Academy, or engage in husbandry? Wherefore the corrections of Cleanthes and Antisthenes^ are not without value. For, seeing the Athe- nians in an uproar in the theatre because of these words, 'What is base save to those who take it so?'^ Antisthenes straightway objected, ^The base is base, seem it so or not;' and Cleanthes, hearing this of wealth, 'To give to one's friends and to save one's body when diseased,'* altered it to read, *To give to harlots and to inflame one's body when diseased.' Zeno also amended the following of Sophocles, 'Whoever journeys to a tyrant's house becomes his slave, e'en though he entered free,'^ to 'Nay, not a slave, if really free on entering,' meaning by free independent, high-minded, and self-respecting. ^ Bergk 2. 387. ^ Eminent Cynic philosopher ; pupil and friend of Socrates, and the teacher of Diogenes. ' Antisthenes was simple in life, despised riches and sensual pleasure, and emphasized practical morality.' ^ Nauck 293 ; Eurip. Frag. 19. ^Eurip. Electra 428. ^ Nauck 253. 88 How to Study Poetry Now what hinders us also from making similar emenda- tions, in order to influence young men for the better? Thus, why not change such a passage as this, 'That man is to be envied, who so aims as to hit his wish,'^ to read, 'who so aims as to hit his advantage?' for to get and have things wrongly desired merits pity, not envy. When we read this passage, 'Not to all good without a taste of ill did Atreus beget thee, Agamemnon; but thou art destined both to joy and to grieve,'^ let us much rather say, Tt must be thine to rejoice, but not to grieve, if moderate thy means, because, "Not to all good, without a taste of ill, did Atreus beget thee." ' The poet says, 'Alas ! 'tis a curse sent by the gods on man, to behold the good but accept it not;'^ rather, 'It is a brutal, unreasonable, and deplorable thing for one who appreciates the better part to be led away to the worse through incontinence and effeminacy.' Again, 'A speaker influences by character, not by speech;'* nay, 'by both character and speech,' or better, 'by character through speech,' as does a horseman by the bridle and a pilot by the rudder, since virtue has no other instrument so pleasing to people as speech nor so fitted by nature to influ- ence mankind. This passage, ' "Inclines he more to man or woman?" "To each alike, when beauty is present;'"*^ should be altered to read, 'To each alike, when good sense is present,' as indicating a finely-balanced nature; for the man so greatly influenced by pleasure and youthful beauty is weak and unstable. This sentiment, 'The gods cause men to fear,'^ is by no means true, but rather, 'The gods give courage to men,' and fear only to those who are senseless, unreasonable, and ungrateful, who are sus- picious lest that power which is the origin and first princi- ple of every good be injurious. Such then is the character of emendation. ^ Nauck 695. ^Eurip. Iph. Aul. 29. ^ Nauck 449. * Meineke iv. 209. ^ Nauck 288. ^ Ibid. 695. 89 How to Study Poetry XIII A further use to which poetry may be put is well explained by Chrysippus, namely, classification or generali- zation. For, in saying, 'An ox would not be killed unless its neighbor were bad,'^ Hesiod says the same of a dog, an ass, or any other animal liable to be lost in the same way. Also, the saying of Euripides, 'Who then is a slave if he be indifferent to death ?'^ may be applied to toil or to sickness. As when physicians discover the efficacy of a drug in curing a case, they assign the drug to all other cases of the same disease, so a universally applicable gen- eralization is not to be confined to the one specific thing to which it was at first applied, but is to be transferred to all other members of the same category,^ and young men should become accustomed to recognize the affinities between things, and to make such transfers of application with insight, exercising and training their perceptive pow- ers by constant practice. Thus when Menander says 'Blessed is he who being and wisdom hath,'* they should recognize that the like may be said of reputation, of authority, and of eloquence. Also, it should be appre- ciated that the reproof which Odysseus administers to Achilles seated amidst the Scyrian maids, 'Dost thou destroy the splendor of thy birth by carding wool, thou, sprung from a father noblest of the Greeks?'^ could be applied to the profligate man, the covetous, the heedless, or the ignorant; thus, 'Art thou drunken, thou, sprung from a father noblest of the Greeks?' or, 'Dost thou play at dice, or strike at quail, or drive a petty trade, or practise sordid usury, with no thought for those high things worthy 1 W. and D. 348. 2 Nauck 523. ^ Such illustrations were much employed by the Stoics ; see Cicero, Tusculanae Disputationes iv. 10. 23 : * Hoc loco nimium operae con- sumitur a Stoicis, maxime a Chrysippo, dum morbis corporum com paratur morborum animi similitudo.' See also Zeller, Gesch. d. Gr. Ph. ii. I. 285. * Meineke iv. 103. ^ Nauck 653. 90 How to Study Poetry of thy good birth?' When young men read these words: 'Talk not of wealth; I reverence not a god which even the worst of men easily obtains/^ they may infer that popular esteem is not to be praised, nor physical beauty, nor military cloaks, nor sacerdotal crowns, all of which we see to be the possessions of the worst of men. Thus when they read, 'Cowardice begets base children,'^ they may say, 'Very true, but so does intemperance, super- stition, envy, and every other disease/ When Homer, using the word best in two connections, says, 'Evil Paris, best in form,^ and, 'Hector, best in form,'* he is teach- ing that one who has in him nothing good save physical beauty is worthy of blame and reproach. This sentiment should be transferred to like faults, to restrain those who are boastful of fictitious excellencies, and to teach youth that such expressions as, 'O thou that excellest in wealth,' 'O thou that excellest in feasting,' 'O thou that excellest in servants and flocks,' and, yea, 'O thou that excellest' — in everything to the end of the list, imply censure and reproach; for one should seek preeminence in good deeds and words, to be first in those things which are first, and great in those things which are greatest, since reputation gained from things small and mean is inglorious and dis- honorable. Careful observation of instances of censure and praise, especially in the works of Homer, will impress this upon us, for he is at pains to show that he esteems lightly the advan- tages of form and fortune. First of all, in meetings and salutations, men do not accost one another as fair, or rich, or strong, but use such expressions of esteem as 'Heaven- sprung son of Laertes, Odysseus of many devices ;'^ 'Hector son of Priam, peer of Zeus in counsel;'® 'O Achilles, Peleus' son, mightest of Achaians far;^ 'Noble son of ^ Nauck 294 ; Eurip. Aeolus. Frag. 20. ^ Nauck 695. 3//. iii. 39 : this rendering and the following are not taken from L., L., and M. ^11. xvii. 142. 5//. ii. 173. ^11. vii. 47. '//. xix. 216. 91 How to Study Poetry Menoitios, dear to my heart.'^ And when men censure one another, they do not call attention to physical defects, but direct their reproaches at errors, as. Thou heavy with wine, thou with face of dog and heart of deer;'^ 'Ajax, master of railing, ill-counseled;^ 'Idomeneus, why art thou a braggart of old? ... It beseemeth thee not to be a braggart;'* 'Ajax, thou blundering boaster;'^ and, lastly, Thersites is not reviled by Odysseus for his lameness, nor baldness, nor hunched back, but for his reckless babble, while the indulgent mother of Hephaestus accosts her son by referring to his lameness, 'Rise, lame god, O my son.'^ Thus Homer ridicules those who are ashamed of being lame or blind, maintaining that nothing is an object of reproach which is not in itself disgraceful, and that nothing is disgraceful which is not our own doing, but the gift of fortune. Hence two great benefits accrue to the careful student of poetry: the one, equanimity, that is, the power to keep from unreasonably and viciously casting a man's misfortunes in his teeth; the other, magnanimity, that is, the power to resist being cast down or disquieted when fortune deals harshly with us, but rather with meekness to endure suffering, reproach, and ridicule. This last it is very easy to do if one has in mind the saying of Philemon,'^ There is no surer proof of a gentle and harmonious spirit than the power to endure a railer.'^ But if one appear to deserve rebuke, let him be attacked for his own errors and passions, as Adrastus, the tragic character, who, when accosted by Alcmaeon with, Thy sister killed her husband,' replied, 'Yes, and thou with thine own hand slew the mother who bore thee.'^ For just as those who lash a man's garments do not touch his body, so those who abuse a man for his ill fortune or low birth, vainly and foolishly 1//. xi. 608. 2// i 225. 3//. xxiii. 483. *//. xxiii. 474-479. 5//. xiii. 824. ^//. xxi. 331. ''Comic poet, born about 361 B.C. Philemon was a successful rival of Menander, and exerted much influence upon Latin comedy. ^ Meineke iv. g. ^ Nauck 695. 92 How to Study Poetry work themselves up over mere externalities, without touch- ing the soul or those things which really need a sarcastic reproof. XIV Moreover, just as it is explained above that we should thwart and check confidence in coarse and hurtful poems by contrasting with them the maxims and sayings of men of esteem and of public service, so all refined and helpful sen- timents we should nurture and strengthen by examples and testimony from philosophy, giving to it the credit of their origination.^ This is right and profitable, for one's confi- dence in the poems and regard for them is strengthened when he discovers that the doctrines of Pythagoras and of Plato agree with the words spoken on the stage, or sung to the harp, or studied in school, and that the precepts of Chilo^ and Bias^ accord with the books which children read. Wherefore it is of prime importance to teach young men that such thoughts as these, which are met with in the poets, 'Not unto thee, my child, are given the works of war, but follow thou after the loving tasks of wedlock;'* and. Tor Zeus would have been wroth with him, if he fought with a better man than himself;'^ differ not from the precept, 'Know thyself,'^ but express the same thought. And these again, 'Witless ones, not knowing how much the half is greater than the whole ;'^ and, 'Bad counsel is worst of all for him who gives it ;'^ accord with the maxims which Plato expresses in the Gorgias and the Republic, namely^ ' See Introd. p. 30, on this section. 2 A Spartan enumerated among the Seven Wise Men of Greece. He became one of the ephori of Sparta in 556 B.C. Among the maxims ascribed to him is, ' Know thyself.' 3 Another of the Seven Wise Men, living about 560 B.C. He was dis- tinguished for eloquence as well as wisdom. One of his witty sayings was, ' I carry all my goods (or riches) with me.' *//. V. 428. 5//. xi. 543, The same comparisons exist in the scholia of Codex B on these passages. ® See note 2. ' W. and D. 40. See also Rep, v. 466 ; Laws 3. 690. ^ Ibid. 265. 93 How to Study Poetry that, To be unjust is worse than to suffer injustice;'^ and, *To harm is more harmful than to be harmed.'^ One must admit also that the following words of Aeschylus, 'Be of good cheer, intense pain does not last,'^ express but the famous and oft-quoted maxim of Epicurus, Tain if great is brief; if lasting, slight;' and that the one idea is stated explicitly by Aeschylus, while the other is only its corollary; for if great and intense pain does not last, the pain which does last is not great nor hard to bear. And wherein do these words of Thespis,* 'Thou seest that Zeus is supreme among the gods, because no falsehood, no boastful or idle jesting, comes from his lips, and he alone knows not pleasure,'^ differ from the saying of Plato, 'The divine nature is seated far from both joy and grief.'^ Again, this saying of Bacchylides,'^ 'Virtue keeps its lustre untarnished, but wealth associates with worthless men;'^ and this of Euripides to the same effect, 'I deem nothing superior to self-control, since its abiding-place is ever with good men;'^ and this, 'Should you strive for honor, and seek to acquire virtue through riches, among good men you would be rated as good for nothing ;'^*^ do they not confirm what the philosophers say of wealth and external goods, that, unless virtue is present, they are useless and unprofitable ? For thus to unite and wed poetry to the doctrines of philosophy relieves it of its fictitious and illusive quality, ^ Gorgias 473. ^ See Wyttenbach, Lexicon Plutarcheum. ^ Nauck 83. "* ' Inventor of the Greek tragedy, since he introduced between the dithyrambic chorals at the festival of Dionysus an interlocutor, who now in monologues, now in dialogues with the leader of the chorus, narrated, or gave a mimetic representation of, the incidents to which the songs referred.' See Horace, Art of Poetry 276, for a curious pic- ture of Thespis strolling from place to place and giving shows from his wagon. s Nauck 647. ^ Epist. iii. 315. ' One of the nine canonical Greek lyric poets, about 470 B.C. Bacchylides was a graceful writer, and a rival of Pindar. 8 Bergk 3. 580. * Nauck 523. ^'^ Ibid. 523- 94 How to Study Poetry and invests with seriousness its useful passages. More- over, it prepares and predisposes the young man's mind to the teachings of philosophy, so that he comes to it not utterly without taste for it or without knowledge of its teachings, not full of the confused notions which he has been wont to receive from his mother and his nurse, yea, and likely enough from his father and his tutor as well,^ esteeming the rich happy and worshipful, dreading death and suffering, and holding virtue without riches and fame to be unenviable and a mere nothing. For when young men brought up in this way hear from the philosophers senti- ments contradictory to these, they are alarmed, confused, and bewildered, and they do not accept or test them, unless, like men accustoming themselves to see the sun on com- ing out of great darkness, they become accustomed, in an artificial light whose rays blend truth with fiction, to see such truths without dislike or repugnance. For having heard or read such things as this in poetry, 'Lament for him who is born to the ills of life, but him who has died and ended his pain count happy, sending him hence with congratulations;'^ or this, 'What needs have mortals save two alone, the earth for grain, the spring for water ?'^ or this, 'O tyranny, dear to savage men;'* or this, The welfare of mortals consists in having the fewest possible causes of grief ;'^ I say, if such thoughts are known to them, they are less disturbed and annoyed when they hear from philosophers that, 'Death is nothing to us ;' that, 'Nature's wealth is limited ;' and that, 'Happiness and good fortune do not consist in the abundance of riches, in the pretentiousness of one's employment, in sovereignty and power, but in freedom from grief, in equanimity, and in a mind disposed to conform itself to nature.' Wherefore, for these reasons, as well as for the others mentioned above, a young man needs to be carefully guided in his reading, in order that he may not beforehand be 1 See Rep. ii. 381. ^ Nauck 395. ^ Ibid. 507. 4 Ibid. 696. 5 Ibid. 696. 95 How to Study Poetry prejudiced against philosophy, but rather somewhat in- structed in it, and so, by his study of poetry, may be advanced to the study of philosophy, in a gracious, friendly, and congenial spirit. 96 c ADDRESS TO YOUNG MEN ON THE RIGHT USE OF GREEK LITERATURE OUTLINE I. Introduction: Out of the abundance of his experience the author will advise young men as to the pagan literature, showing them what to accept, and what to reject. II. To the Christian the life eternal is the supreme goal, and the guide to this life is the Holy Scriptures ; but since young men cannot appreciate the deep thoughts contained therein, they are to study the profane writings, in which truth appears as in a mirror. III. Profane learning should ornament the mind, as foliage graces the fruit-bearing tree. IV. In studying pagan lore one must discriminate between the helpful and the injurious, accepting the one, but closing one's ears to the siren song of the other. V. Since the life to come is to be attained through virtue, chief attention must be paid to those passages in which virtue is praised; such may be found, for example, in Hesiod, Homer, Solon, Theognis, and Prodicus. VI. Indeed, almost all eminent philosophers have ex- tolled virtue. The words of such men should meet with more than mere theoretical acceptance, for one must try to realize them in his life, remembering that to seem to be good when one is not so is the height of injustice. VII. But in the pagan literature virtue is lauded in deeds as well as in words, wherefore one should study those acts of noble men which coincide with the teachings of the Scriptures. VIII. To return to the original thought, young men must distinguish between helpful and injurious knowledge, keeping clearly in mind the Christian's purpose in life. So, like the athlete or the musician, they must bend every energy to one task, the winning of the heavenly crown. IX. This end is to be compassed by holding the body 99 The Right Use of Greek Literature under, by scorning riches and fame, and by subordinating all else to virtue. X. While this ideal will be matured later by the study of the Scriptures, it is at present to be fostered by the study of the pagan writers ; from them should be stored up knowl- edge for the future. Conclusion: The above are some of the more important precepts; others the writer will continue to explain from time to time, trusting that no young man will make the fatal error of disregarding them. ADDRESS TO YOUNG MEN ON THE RIGHT USE OF GREEK LITERATURE Many considerations, young men, prompt me to recom- mend to you the principles which I deem most desirable, and which I believe will be of use to you if you will adopt them. For my time of life, my many-sided train- ing", yea, my adequate experience in those vicissitudes of life which teach their lessons at every turn,^ have so familiarized me with human affairs, that I am able to map out the safest course for those just starting upon their careers. By nature's common bond I stand in the same relationship to you as your parents, so that I am no whit behind them in my concern for you. Indeed, if I do not misinterpret your feelings, you no longer crave your parents when you come to me. Now if you should receive my words with gladness, you would be in the second class of those who, according to Hesiod, merit praise; if not, I should say nothing disparaging, but no doubt you your- selves would remember the passage in which that poet says : 'He is best who, of himself, recognizes what is his duty, and he also is good who follows the course marked out by others, but he who does neither of these things is of no use under the sun.'^ Do not be surprised if to you, who go to school every day, and who, through their writings, associate with the learned men of old,^ I say that out of my own experience I have ^ See Newman, Historical Sketches, vol. ii. chaps, i. and ii, for an account of the trials and labors of St. Basil. Also see Fialon, Bio- graphie de St. Basile, and Wace and SchafF, Select Library of Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, vol. viii, Prolegomena. » W. and D. 285 flf. 2 See Introd. p. 28, on the education of Greek youth. lOI The Right Use of Greek Literature evolved something more useful. Now this is my counsel, that you should not unqualifiedly give over your minds to these men, as a ship is surrendered to the rudder, to follow whither they list, but that, while receiving whatever of value they have to offer, you yet recognize what it is wise to ignore. Accordingly, from this point on I shall take up and discuss the pagan writings, and how we are to discriminate among them. II We Christians, young men, hold that this human life is not a supremely precious thing, nor do we recognize any- thing as unconditionally a blessing which benefits us in this life only.^ Neither pride of ancestry, nor bodily strength, nor beauty, nor greatness, nor the esteem of all men, nor kingly authority, nor, indeed, whatever of human affairs may be called great, do we consider worthy of desire, or the possessors of them as objects of envy; but we place our hopes upon the things which are beyond, and in preparation for the life eternal do all things that we do. Accordingly, whatever helps us towards this we say that we must love and follow after with all our might, but those things which have no bearing upon it should be held as naught. But to explain what this life is, and in what way and manner we shall live it, requires more time than is at our command, and more mature hearers than you. And yet, in saying thus much, perhaps I have made it suf- ficiently clear to you that if one should estimate and gather together all earthly weal from the creation of the world, he would not find it comparable to the smallest part of the possessions of heaven; rather, that all the precious things in this life fall further short of the least good in the other than the shadow or the dream fails of the reality. Or rather, to avail myself of a still more natural comparison, by ^ See Col. iii. 2 : ' Set your affections on things above, not on things on the earth.' 102 The Right Use of Greek Literature as much as the soul is superior to the body in all things, by so much is one of these lives superior to the other.^ Into the life eternal the Holy Scriptures lead us, which teach us through divine words. But so long as our immaturity forbids our understanding their deep thought, we exercise our spiritual perceptions upon profane writ- ings, which are not altogether different, and in which we perceive the truth as it were in shadows and in mir- rors. Thus we imitate those who perform the exercises of military practice, for they acquire skill in gymnastics and in dancing, and then in battle reap the reward of their training. We must needs believe that the greatest of all battles lies before us, in preparation for which we must do and suffer all things to gain power. Consequently we must be conversant with poets, with historians, with orators, indeed with all men who may further our soul's salvation. Just as dyers prepare the cloth before they apply the dye, be it purple or any other color, so indeed must we also, if we would preserve indelible the idea of the true virtue, become first initiated in the pagan lore, then at length give special heed to the sacred and divine teachings, even as we first accustom ourselves to the sun's reflection in the water, and then become able to turn our eyes upon the very sun itself.^ Ill If, then, there is any affinity between the two literatures, a knowledge of them should be useful to us in our search for truth; if not, the comparison, by emphasizing the con- trast, will be of no small service in strengthening our regard for the better one. With what now may we compare these two kinds of education to obtain a simile? Just as it is the chief mission of the tree to bear its fruit in its season, ^ See Rep. x. 614 : ' And yet, I said, all these things are as nothing, either in number or greatness, in comparison with those other recom- penses which await both just and unjust after death, which are more and greater far.' ^See p. 95. • 103 The Right Use of Greek Literature though at the same time it puts forth for ornament the leaves which quiver on its boughs, even so the real fruit of the soul is truth, yet it is not without advantage for it to embrace the pagan wisdom, as also leaves offer shelter to the fruit, and an appearance not untimely. That Moses, whose name is a synonym for wisdom, severely trained his mind in the learning of the Egyptians,^ and thus became able to appreciate their deity.^ Similarly, in later days, the wise Daniel is said to have studied the lore of the Chaldaeans while in Babylon,"^ and after that to have taken up the sacred teachings. IV Perhaps it is sufficiently demonstrated that such heathen learning is not unprofitable for the soul; I shall then dis- cuss next the extent to which one may pursue it. To begin with the poets, since their writings are of all degrees of excellence, you should not study all of their poems without omitting a single word. When they recount the words and deeds of good men, you should both love and imitate them, earnestly emulating such conduct. But when they portray base conduct, you must flee from them and stop up your ears, as Odysseus is said to have fled past the song of the sirens,* for familiarity with evil writings paves the way for evil deeds. Therefore the soul must be guarded with great care, lest through our love for letters it receive some contamination unawares, as men drink in poison with honey. We shall not praise the poets when they scoff and rail, when they represent fornicators and winebibbers, when they define blissfulness by groaning tables and wanton songs. Least of all shall we listen to them when they tell us of their gods, and especially when they represent them as being many, and not at one among themselves.^ For, among these gods, at one time brother is at variance with brother, or the father with his children; at another, ^Actsvii.22. ' ovTO) irpoaeWeiv ry Seuplgi, rov'Ovrog. ^Daniel i. 3 fF. ^See p. 51; Ba^l, £j>isf. i. ^ See p. 64, and notes. 104 The Right Use of Greek Literature the children engage in truceless war against their parents. The adulteries of the gods and their amours, and especially those of the one whom they call Zeus, chief of all and most high, things of which one cannot speak, even in connection with brutes, without blushing, we shall leave to the stage. I have the same words for the historians, and especially when they make up stories for the amusement of their hearers. And certainly we shall not follow the example of the rhetoricians in the art of lying. For neither in the courts of justice nor in other business affairs will falsehood be of any help to us Christians, who, having chosen the straight and true path of life, are forbidden by the gospel to go to law. But on the other hand we shall receive gladly those passages in which they praise virtue or condemn vice. For just as bees know how to extract honey from flowers, which to men are agreeable only for their fragrance and color, even so here also those who look for something more than pleasure and enjoyment in such writers may derive profit for their souls. Now, then, altogether after the manner of bees must we use these writings, for the bees do not visit all the flowers without discrimination, nor indeed do they seek to carry away entire those upon which they light, but rather, having taken so much as is adapted to their needs, they let the rest go. So we, if wise, shall take from heathen books whatever befits us and is allied to the truth, and shall pass over the rest. And just as in culling roses we avoid the thorns, from such writings as these we will gather everything useful, and guard against the noxious.^ So, from the very beginning, we must examine each of their teachings, to harmonize it with our ultimate purpose, according to the Doric proverb, 'test- ing each stone by the measuring-line.'^ ' The general attitude taken here toward selectiveness in reading is Platonic ; see, for instance, frequent passages in the Laws ii, iii, and vii, and the Republic iii. ^ rhv XlOov Trbrl rav OTrdprov ayovrag. Maloney notes that St. Gregory Nazianzen cites this proverb in Letter xxxviii, and St. John Chrysostom in Homily xxv. I05 The Right Use of Greek Literature V Since we must needs attain to the life to come through virtue, our attention is to be chiefly fastened upon those many passages from the poets, from the historians, and especially from the philosophers, in which virtue itself is praised. For it is of no small advantage that virtue become a habit with a youth,^ for the lessons of youth make a deep impression, because the soul is then plastic, and there- fore they are likely to be indelible. If not to incite youth to virtue, pray what meaning may we suppose that Hesiod had in those universally admired lines,^ of which the senti- ment is as follows: 'Rough is the start and hard, and the way steep, and full of labor and pain, that leads toward virtue. Wherefore, on account of the steepness, it is not granted to every man to set out, nor, to the one having set out, easily to reach the summit. But when he has reached the top, he sees that the way is smooth and fair, easy and light to the foot, and more pleasing than the other, which leads to wickedness,' — of which the same poet said that one may find it all around him in great abundance.^ Now it seems to me that he had no other purpose in saying these things than so to exhort us to virtue, and so to incite us to bravery, that we may not weaken our efforts before we reach the goal. And certainly if any other man praises virtue in a like strain, we will receive his words with pleas- ure, since our aim is a common one. Now as I have heard from one skilful in interpreting the mind of a poet,* all the poetry of Homer is a praise of ^ Plato frequently touches upon the value of habit in the Laws vii, and the Republic ii, ' W. and D. 285 ff. Plato refers to this same passage in the Repub- lic ii. 364. ^ Ibid. 287. ^Libanius, b. at Antioch in 314 ; studied at Athens, but acquired his education principally by private study of the old Greek writers, whom he often imitated with success, and for whom he always showed great enthusiasm. During the first part of his career as a teacher at Constan- >i tinople, he was very popular, and St. Basil was then among his stu- 106 The Right Use of Greek Literature virtue, and with him all that is not merely accessory tends to this end. There is a notable instance of this where Homer first made the princess reverence the leader of the Cephallenians, though he appeared naked, shipwrecked, and alone, and. then made Odysseus as completely lack embarrass- ment, though seen naked and alone, since virtue served him as a garment. And next he made Odysseus so much esteemed by the other Phaeacians that, abandoning the luxury in which they lived, all admired and emulated him, and there was not one of them who longed for anything else except to be Odysseus, even to the enduring of shipwreck.^ The interpreter of the poetic mind argued that, in this episode, Homer very plainly says : 'Be virtue your con- cern, O men, which both swims to shore with the ship- wrecked man, and makes him, when he comes naked to the strand, more honored than the prosperous Phaeacians.' And, indeed, this is the truth, for other possessions belong to the owner no more than to another, and, as when men are dicing, fall now to this one, now to that. But virtue is the only possession that is sure, and that remains with us whether living or dead. Wherefore it seems to me that Solon- had the rich in mind when he said: 'We will not exchange our virtue for their gold, for virtue is an ever- lasting possession, while riches are ever changing owners.' Similarly Theognis^ said that the god, whatever he might dents. ' His idol was Greek style, and for his time he had rare success in mastering the secrets of Greek expression. A pagan born and bred, he was an ardent admirer of the Emperor Julian, but his devotion to the Apostate did not prevent him from associating on terms of affectionate intimacy with St. Chrysostom and St. Basil ; for he was above all a rhetorician, and his tolerant attitude toward Christianity, so far as it did not interfere with the study of the Greek classics and the attainment of excellence in Greek composition, may be explained by his shallow cleverness as well as b}'^ his easy temper.' See p. 34. ^ See Odys. vi. and vii., and also p. 76, for Plutarch's comment on this episode. ^ The great Athenian law-giver. In the tract. How One may Profit by Ones Enemies, Plutarch attributes these lines to Solon, but they occur among the Gnomes of Theognis, 316-318. See also Plutarch, Life of Solon. 2 See p. 54. 107 The Right Use of Greek Literature mean by the god, inclines the balances for men, now this way, now that, giving to some riches, and to others poverty.^ Also Prodicus, the sophist of Ceos,^ whose opinion we must respect, for he is a man not to be slighted, somewhere in his writings expressed similar ideas about virtue and vice. I do not remember the exact words, but as far as I recollect the sentiment, in plain prose it ran somewhat as follows: While Hercules was yet a youth, being about your age, as he was debating which path he should choose, the one lead- ing through toil to virtue, or its easier alternate, two women appeared before him, who proved to be Virtue and Vice. Though they said not a word, the difference between them was at once apparent from their mien. The one had arranged herself to please the eye, while she exhaled charms, and a multitude of delights swarmed in her train. With such a display, and promising still more, she sought to allure Hercules to her side. The other, wasted and squalid, looked fixedly at him, and bespoke quite another thing. For she promised nothing easy or engaging, but rather infinite toils and hardships, and perils in every land and on every sea. As a reward for these trials, he was to become a god, so our author has it. The latter, Hercules at length followed.^ VI Almost all who have written upon the subject of wisdom have more or less, in proportion to their several abilities, extolled virtue in their writings. Such men must one obey, and must try to realize their words in his life. For he, who by his works exemplifies the wisdom which with others is ^ Gnomes 157-158. ' 'A celebrated sophist of the fifth century, B.C. He was accustomed to travel through Greece, delivering lectures for money. He paid special attention to the correct use of words. Although severely criti- cised by the other sophists, he is mentioned with respect by Xenophon and Plato, the former of whom has preserved, in The Choice of Her- cules, the story here used by St. Basil.' ^ See Xenophon, Memorab. ii. I. 22 ; Cicero, De Off. i. 32 ; Chrysostom, Regnum ; Lucian, Somnium. 108 The Right Use of Greek Literature a matter of theory alone, 'breathes ; all others flutter about like shadows.'^ I think it is as if a painter should represent some marvel of manly beauty, and the subject should actually be such a man as the artist pictures on the canvas. To praise virtue in public with brilliant words and with long drawn out speeches, while in private preferring pleas- ures to temperance, and self-interest to justice, finds an analogy on the stage, for the players frequently appear as kings and rulers, though they are neither, nor perhaps even genuinely free men. A musician would hardly put up with a lyre which was out of tune, nor a choregus with a chorus not singing in perfect harmony. But every man is divided against himself who does not make his life conform to his words, but who says with Euripides, The mouth indeed hath sworn, but the heart knows no oath.'^ Such a man will seek the appearance of virtue rather than the reality. ^i'/\ But to seem to be good when one is not so, is, if we are to respect the opinion of Plato^ at all, the very height of injustice. VII After this wise, then, are we to receive those words from the pagan authors which contain suggestions of the virtues. But since also the renowned deeds of the men of old either are preserved for us by tradition, or are cherished in the pages of poet or historian, we must not fail to profit by them. A fellow of the street rabble once kept taunting Pericles, but he, meanwhile, gave no heed; and they held out all day, the fellow deluging him with reproaches, but he, for his part, not caring. Then when it was evening and dusk, and the fellow still clung to him, Pericles escorted him with a light, in order that he might not fail in the 1 Odys. X. 495. ^ Hippo lytus 612; see Cicero, De Off. 3. 29. 108: 'Juravi lingua, mentem injuratam gero.' ^ Rep. ii, 361 ; see Cicero, De Off. 1. 13. 41 : 'Totius autem injustitiae nulla capitalior est quam eorum qui quum maxime fallunt, id agunt, ut viri boni esse videantur;' Plutarch, Flatterer and Friend ^. 109 \ The Right Use of Greek Literature practice of philosophy.^ Again, a man in a passion threat- ened and vowed death to Euclid of Megara,^ but he in turn vowed that the man should surely be appeased, and cease from his hostility to him. How invaluable it is to have such examples in mind when a man is seized with anger ! On the other hand, one must altogether ignore the tragedy which says in so many words : 'Anger arms the hand against the enemy ;'^ for it is much better not to give way to anger at all. But if such restraint is not easy, we shall at least curb our anger by reflection, so as not to give it too much rein. But let us bring our discussion back again to the exam- ples of noble deeds. A certain man once kept striking Socrates, the son of Sophroniscus, in the face, yet he did not resent it, but allowed full play to the ruffian's anger, so that his face was swollen and bruised from the blows. Then when he stopped striking him, Socrates did nothing more than write on his forehead, as an artisan on a statue, who did it, and thus took out his revenge. Since these examples almost coincide with our teachings, I hold that such men are worthy of emulation. For this conduct of Socrates is akin to the precept that to him who smites you upon the one cheek, you shall turn the other also* — thus much may you be avenged; the conduct of Pericles and of Euclid also conforms to the precept: 'Submit to those who persecute you, and endure their wrath with meekness ;'^ and to the other : 'Pray for your enemies and curse them not.'^ One who has been instructed in the pagan examples will no longer hold the Christian precepts impracticable. But I will not overlook the conduct of Alexander, who, on taking captive the daughters of Darius, who were reputed to be of surpassing beauty, would not even look at them, for he deemed it unworthy of one who was a conqueror of men ' See Plutarch, Li/e of Pericles v, from which the story is taken. 'See Plutarch, Concerning the Cure of Anger 14. ' Sommer notes that St. Basil has not quoted Euripides correctly ; St. Basil reads : ''ElTf ex^povg Ov/xbg bnlil^EL x^po^', but Euripides: 'AnTiOvg ett ixOpolg onXiCeiv x^pa- ^Matt. v, 39. ^ Ibid. v. 44. ^Ibid. The Right Use of Greek Literature to be a slave to women.^ This is of a piece with the state- ment that he who looks upon a woman to lust after her, even though he does not commit the act of adultery, is not free from its guilt, since he has entertained impure thoughts.^ It is hard to believe that the action of Cleinias,^ one of the disciples of Pythagoras, was in accidental conformity to our teachings, and not designed imitation of them. What, then, was this act of his? By taking an oath he could have avoided a fine of three talents, yet rather than do so he paid the fine, though he could have sworn truthfully. I am in- clined to think that he had heard of the precept which for- bids us to swear.* VIII But let us return to the same thought with which we started, namely, that we should not accept everything with- out discrimination, but only what is useful. For it would be shameful should we reject injurious foods, yet should take no thought about the studies which nourish our souls, but as a torrent should sweep along all that came near our path and appropriate it. If the helmsman does not blindly abandon his ship to the winds, but guides it toward the anchorage ; if the archer shoots at his mark ; if also the metal-worker or the carpenter seeks to produce the objects for which his craft exists, would there be rime or reason in our being outclassed by these men, mere artisans as they are, in quick appreciation of our interests? For is there not some end in the artisan's work, is there not a goal in human life, which the one who would not wholly resemble unrea- soning animals must keep before him in all his words and deeds? If there were no intelligence sitting at the tiller of our souls, like boats without ballast we should be borne hither and thither through life, without plan or purpose. An analogy may be found in the athletic contests, or, if ^ See Plutarch, Of the Fortune or Virtue of Alexander the Great ii. 6 and 12 ; Life of Alexander ; Arrian, Exped, of Alex. ii. 12. The same story is told of Cyrus in the Cyropaedia. See p. 84. ' Matt. V. 28. 3 A contemporary and friend of Plato. "♦Lev. xix. 12, or Deut. v. 11. The Right Use of Greek Literature you will, in the musical contests; for the contestants pre- pare themselves by a preliminary training for those events in which wreaths of victory are offered, and no one by training for wrestling or for the pancratium would get ready to play the lyre or the flute. At least Polydamas^ would not, for before the Olympic games he was wont to bring the rushing chariot to a halt, and thus hardened himself. Then Milo^ could not be thrust from his smeared shield, but, shoved as he was, clung to it as firmly as statues soldered by lead. In a word, by their training they prepared themselves for the contests. If they had meddled with the airs of Marsyas or of Olympus, the Phrygians,^ abandoning dust and exer- cise, would they have won ready laurels or crowns, or would they have escaped being laughed at for their bodily incaj>acity? On the other hand, certainly Timotheus the musician* did not spend his time in the schools for wrest- ling, for then it would not have been his to excel all in music, he who was so skilled in his art that at his pleasure he could arouse the passions of men by his harsh and vehement strains, and then by gentle ones, quiet and soothe them. By this art, when once he played Phrygian airs on the flute to Alexander, he is said to have incited the general to arms in the midst of feasting, and then, by milder music, to have restored him to his carousing friends.^ Such power to compass one's end, either in music or in athletic contests, is developed by practice. I have called to mind the wreaths and the fighters. These ' ' Of Scotussa, conquered in the Pancratium at the Olympic games in 01. 93, B.C. 408. His size was immense, and the most marvelous stories are related of his strength, how he killed without arms a huge and fierce lion on Mount Olympus, etc' See Pausanias vi. 5 ; Persius i. 4. * Of Crotona. He was six times victor in wrestling at the Olympic games, and as often at the Pythian. He is said to have carried a four- year-old heifer on his shoulders through the stadium at Olympia, and then to have eaten the whole of it in a single day. See Pausanias vi. 14. ^ Olympus was the pupil of Marsyas, Schol. in Aristoph Eq. 9 ; see also Plutarch, Concerning Music 11; Arist., Pol. viii. 5. 6. "* A celebrated flute-player of Thebes. ^ See Plutarch, Of the Fortune or Virtue of Alexander the Great ii. 2; Cicero, Legg. 2. 12; Dryden, Alexander's Feast. The Right Use of Greek Literature men endure hardships beyond number, they use every means to increase their strength, they sweat ceaselessly at their training, they accept many blows from the master, they adopt the mode of life which he prescribes, though it is most unpleasant, and, in a word, they so rule all their conduct that their whole life before the contest is prepara- tory to it. Then they strip themselves for the arena, and endure all and risk all, to receive the crown of olive, or of parsley, or some other branch, and to be announced by the herald as vict^.^ Will it then be possible for us, to whom are held out rewards so wondrous in number and in splendor that tongue can not recount them, while we are fast asleep and leading care-free lives, to make these our own by half-hearted efforts ? Surely, were an idle life a very commendable thing, Sardana- palus^ would take the first prize, or Margites^ if you will, whom Homer, if indeed the poem is by Homer, put down as neither a farmer, nor a vine-dresser, nor anything else that is useful. Is there not rather truth in the maxim of Pitta- cus* which says, 'It is hard to be good ?'^ For after we have * See I Cor. ix. 24-27. ^ 'According to an inaccurate classical tradition, the last king of Assy- ria. He was noted for effeminacy and voluptuousness, and in order to escape falling into the hands of the besiegers of Nineveh, ended his worthless life by burning himself in his palace. It seems certain that the original of Sardanapalus is Asshurbanipal, King of Assyria, 668- 626 B.C.' ^ The Margites, a poem which is lost, and which ridiculed a man who was said to know many things, and who knew all badly, was frequently ascribed by the ancients to Homer, but is of later date. According to St. Clement of Alexandria, these are the verses of which St. Basil speaks : Tov S" ovT ap GKanffipa deol deaav, ovt' dpoTTJpa. OvT aX2.o)^ Tt Go