LIBRARY U*IVF siry OF SAN DIEGO ESSAYS ON THE ESSAYS ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF THEISM BY THE LATE WILLIAM GEORGE WARD, PH.D. SOMETIMK FELLOW OF BALLIOL COLLEGE, OXFORD AND PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY AND DOGMATIC THEOLOGY AT OLD HALL COLLEGE, WARE REPRINTED FROM THE "DUBLIN REVIEW" EDITED, WITH AN INTRODUCTION, BY WILFKID WAKD IN TWO VOLUMES VOL. I. LONDON KEGAN PAUL, TRENCH & CO., 1, PATERNOSTER SQUARE 1884 (The rights of translation and of reproduction are reserved.) TO BARON FRIEDRICH YON HUGEL. MY DEAR BARON VON HUGEL, In offering these volumes of my father's philosophical essays for your acceptance, I am doing what I believe he would himself have done had he lived to republish them. They treat for the most part of subjects which you frequently discussed with him, and on which I know he valued your opinion. But a yet stronger motive which would have led him to ask you to accept them would have been the opportunity thereby afforded him of giving expression to the great esteem in which he held the friendship enjoyed by him, during the closing years of his life, with yourself and Baroness von Hiigel. I trust that your regard for his memory will render this dedication not unacceptable to you : and I may add that it gives me great pleasure on personal grounds to be the means of offering the book to you so far as I can be said to offer that which is not my own. Believe me, dear Baron von Hiigel, Yours very sincerely, WILFRID WARD. JIarch, 1881. NOTE. THE Editor bas to offer his best thanks to the Revv. J. Connelly and E. Pennington for their kind assistance in looking through and correcting the proofs of the following essays. The analytical contents at the com- mencement of each volume are in nearly every case by the Author himself. The date given after the title of each essay is the date of its original publication in the Dublin Review. March, 1884. CONTENTS OF VOL. I. L'AOK INTRODUCTION .. ... xi ESSAY I. THE RULE AND MOTIVE OF CERTITUDE. (July, 1871.) Two schools of philosophy ... ... ... ... ... 1 Question stated as to the test of certitude ... ... ... 2 Answer given by scholastics to that question ... ... ... <> Primary truths known by the light of reason ... ... ... '.' Answer to objections ... ... ... ... ... ... 11 Propositions inconceivable are not therefore untruu ... ... 17 Doctrine of various English philosophers on our subject ... ... -'! Mr. Mill's doctrine on our subject ... ... ... ... 2<> ESSAY II. MR. MILL'S DENIAL OF NECESSARY TRUTH. (October, 1871.) Characteristics of Mr. Mill's philosophical writing ... ... ... :>:> Mathematical axioms self-evidently necessary ... ... ... i!5 Consideration of Mr. Mill's reply based on the " association " psychology 'M Consequence of Mr. Mill's admitting that mathematical axioms are cognizable by purely mental experimentation ... ... />'< Mr. Mill's argument from the " Geometry of Visiblcs" ... ... . r >7 The allegation considered that mathematical axioms are tautological .">'.) Three inferences from what ha.s preceded ... ... ... ... HO Phcnomeniatio anti-theists ... ... ... ... ... <>'.'> Three arguments against phenomenism ... ... ... ... ('"> viii Contents. ESSAY III. MR. MILL ON THE FOUNDATION OF MORALITY. (January, 1872.) PAGE Domestic controversies on this matter ... ... 77 The issue joined with Mr. Mill Moral goodness a simple idea Certain moral truths self-evidently necessary ... 85 Intuitive knowledge that all acts, morally evil, are prohibited by a Personal Being ... 91 This Being inferred to be Supreme Legislator of the universe ... 92 Mr. Mill's appeal to man's primordial faculties ... ... 98 Mr. Bain's appeal to divergences of moral judgment ... 100 Mr. Mill implicitly embraces the doctrine which he speculatively opposes 1 13 Criticism of his speculative position ... ... ... ... 116 ESSAY IV. MR. MILL'S REPLY TO THE " DUBLIN REVIEW." (July, 1873.) Prefatory remarks on the late Mr. Mill ... ... ... ... 120 Purpose of this essay ... ... ... ... ... 126 1 5 ule and motive of certitude ... ... ... ... ... 127 Mr. Mill on the motive of certitud e ... ... ... ... 133 Mr. Mill on the rule of certitude ... ... ... ... ... 146 Argumentative preliminaries on the matter ... ... ... 155 Direct controversy with Mr. Mill on the matter ... ... ... 1GO Mr. Mill's positive thesis ... ... ... ... ... 176 Some subordinate issues considered 180 ESSAY V. MR. MILL'S PHILOSOPHICAL POSITION. (January, 1874.) Mr. Mill's autobiography ... ... ... ... ... 185 His aggressive and affirmative philosophical position ... ... 205 His position examined on mathematical axioms and the rule of certitude 209 His attempted distinction between two kinds of complex ideas ... 220 Summary of the preceding argument ... ... ... ... 222 Other propositions concerning necessary truth ... ... ... 223 Can the uniformity of nature be proved by experience? ... ... 227 Mr. Mill's reply to the Dublin Review on this question ... ... 229 Contents. ix ESSAY VI. MR. MILL'S DENIAL OF FREEWILL. (April, 1874.) PAGE Mr. Mill's theory of determinism stated in detail ... ... ... 237 Great part of this theory may be accepted as true ... ... 246 Exact point at issue ... ... ... ... ... ... 247 Determinism opposed to observed facts ... ... ... 251 Determinism and fatalism ... ... ... ... ... 264 Answers to objections ... ... ... ... ... 265 Statement of two further objections ... ... ... ... 282 ESSAY VII. APPENDIX ON FREEWILL. (July, 1874.) Criticism in the Spectator ... ... ... ... ... 285 Distinction between resolve and desire ... ... ... 288 Men often act against their prevailing desire ... ... ... 289 ESSAY VllL MB. MILL ON CAUSATION. (July, 1876.) Recapitulation of former essays ... ... ... ... ... 303 Mr. Mill's sense of the word " cause "... ... ... ... 312 The universal belief of mankind in a causation different from this ... 320 In what precise sense of the word do mankind universally believe the existence of causation ... ... ... ... ... 325 The principle of causation established ... ... ... ... 326 Causation in no way depends on the uniformity of nature ... 333 The principle of causation entirely ampliative ... ... ... 334 ESSAY IX. FREEWILL. (April, 1879.) REPLY TO A REPLY OF DR. BAIN'S. Summary of our original argument ... ... ... ... 337 Dr. Hain does not once refer to our central argument ... ... 316 His first criticism ... ... ... ... ... ... 347 His second criticism ' r >0 x Contents. PA OK His proof of determinism drawn not from direct observation, but merely from analogy ... ... ... ... ... ... 352 The degree of moral evil existing on earth seems to us by far the greatest difficulty connected with our subject ... ... 35!) The relations between moral habit and anti-impulsive effort ... ... 364 CAUSATION AND FREEWILL. Having established indeterminism, our next step is to develop that truth into the full doctrine of freewill ... ... ... 369 Mill's conception of cause recognizes no influx or agency ... ... 371 Regular sequence of phenomena looked upon by the intuitionist as the result of causation ... ... ... ... ... 375 Contrast between a blind cause and an originative cause ... ... 378 The soul acts as a blind cause in generating its spontaneous impulse, as an originative cause in resisting it ... ... ... 381 Summary of what has been said on causation and freewill ... ... 382 INTEODUCTION. THE following essays, with the exception of the last four in the second volume, were written as part of a systematic course projected by the author with a double object : firstly, to point out the fundamental fallacies in the Ex- perience system of philosophy, as represented especially by the late Mr. Stuart Mill, and the absolute necessity of admitting the power of the human mind to perceive with certainty some immediately evident truths beyond the phenomena of consciousness ; and, secondly, to draw out, on the principles thus established, an argumentative train, exhibiting the various intuitions in the intellectual and moral order, truths of observation, and deductions, whereby the existence of a Personal God, with the characteristics which Theists attribute to Him, may be established. The first of these two tasks the author considered himself to have accomplished. Of the second he had barely indicated the lines, in two essays on "Ethics in its bearing on Theism" and "The Philosophy of the Thcistic Contro- versy," when he was deprived of all power of intellectual work by the illness which terminated in his death. It may be worth while to say a few words as to the exact scope and aim of the essays which are here republished, for the purpose of making clear what they do and what they do not profess to accomplish. No exhaustive review xii Introduction. is attempted of Mr. Mill's philosophical work as a whole. Such a review would have exhibited many points of agree- ment between that writer and the author,* who always considered that Mill's carefully disciplined and naturally candid and thoughtful mind had done much for the super- structure of psychology and logic, although the basis he adopted, which was substantially that of his father, and in part an inheritance from Hume, was most unsatisfactory, or rather was no basis at all. What the author did attempt was to show that the root-doctrines of the Experience School are devoid of all scientific foundation and incapable of defence, while the representatives of that school have in all the useful work they have done for philosophy been in reality acting upon those very principles of intuition which they deride as superstitious and unscientific in their opponents. If we note the consequences of this (supposing the charge to be true), we at once see the peculiar importance of the work which he undertook. If it be granted that Mill's logic is in many respects an advance upon previous works pf the same description, and that the experimental method of psychology attains to valuable and new results is, in fact, a distinct step forward in that science, there seems at first sight no escape from admitting that the methods and principles of inquiry adopted by these philosophers are really an improvement upon those which they have replaced. The writers themselves acquire all the authority which attends on success, and public opinion declares in their favour. They appeal to results as the positive proof that the first principles whence they started were sound. And the con- sequence is that people do not look closely at the real connection between their success and their avowed prin- * The Review of Mill's Logic contributed to the British Critic of October, 1843, by Mr. Ward, when fellow of Balliol, shows his very high intellectual appreciation of Mill, in spite of the severity of its criticisms. Introduction. xiii ciples. The world sees their success, and takes them at their word as to the way in which it was gained. Dr. Ward's central aim, we may say, was by a concentrated attack upon their first principles to draw attention to them, and to their absolute incompatibility with the mode of philoso- phizing of those who professed them. He singled out a few of their fundamental axioms, and insisted on holding them up to the light and examining them. " These men are conjurors," he said in effect. A conjuror who is performing feats of sleight of hand before an audience of simple villagers passes a shilling, apparently, through the table. He gives them plenty of time to examine the shilling and to mark it. They see it and touch it, and know unmistakably that there it is on one side of the table. And when it comes out on the other side, they examine it again, and recognize their own mark. But at the really critical part of the performance, he diverts their attention, and, while bidding them watch closely something unconnected with the real secret of the trick, imperceptibly passes the coin from the right hand to the left, so that when a few moments later he is pressing his right hand on the top of the table and holding a plate in his left underneath to catch the coin, as he says, when it passes through, the whole work is already done ; there is no coin in the right hand ; it is really under the table. He then explains to them that his method is simple enough. He scratches the table three times in one spot, and says, ' Presto open/ and the table opens and allows the coin to pass. The villagers listen with open mouths. They have no doubt this is the true explanation. See there, he is doing it again, to show them that this is really the secret of the matter. He scratches, pronounces the words, and they hear the coin drop in the plate beneath the table. He can do it, and so they do not doubt that lie himself gives the true account as to how he does it. So also it is i. I- xiv Introduction. with Mill and Bain. They have done a work for philosophy. They have shown up a good deal of inaccurate thinking in their predecessors, and added considerably to the analysis of mental operations. This they make clear, and take care that the world should recognize. And all the time they profess to have been philosophizing on the principles of the Experience School, and to reject the power of the mind to know immediately anything beyond its own consciousness. Here is the trick. Their readers read these principles as they state them, and study the results ; but the sleight of hand whereby the results are reached, the imperceptible insertion of intuitions into the process when nobody was looking, escapes notice. And the impossible account which they themselves give of this part of their performance is accepted, not after close scrutiny, but in virtue of the authority naturally possessed by those who have been successful in a particular department of study. Dr. Ward's work, then, was confined to the detection of this sleight of hand. He insists repeatedly on the necessity of watching this part of the process, and on the absolute impossibility of accepting their own account of the philo- sophical method they employ, which entirely eliminates intuitive perception of truth. In all their useful and careful analysis, Mill and Bain act, he says, as unmistakably on a belief in the validity of intuitions, in the mind's power to perceive directly certain objective truths, as I do or any other Christian philosopher does. They use all the authority they have gained by successful deductions from intuition, in advocating principles which are not more subversive of religious philosophy than they are of the methods they themselves have employed. The illustration which he himself pressed most con- stantly upon his opponents was the immediate and absolute trust, which is assumed in all philosophy, nay, in all coherent thought, to be rational, in the veracity of memory ; Introduction. xv or to put it in such a form as will most clearly exhibit its connection with the point at issue our trust that our present impression of what we saw or heard five minutes ago tells truly the objective fact that we did see or hear the thing in question. On this point the author had the advantage of learning from the rejoinder of Mr. Mill, and the express treatment of the subject by Mr. Huxley, that his apparent rcductio ad absurdum was not based on an overstatement of the natural consequences of the Experience view. Mr. Huxley quite accepted the position that his principles allowed of no intuitive confidence in an act of memory, and was led in his defence of his own belief therein into what must be allowed on all hands to be an amusing slip in logic. We trust our memory with good reason, he argued, because we so con- stantly experience its truthfulness. The retort was obvious. Unless Mr. Huxley begins by trusting it instinctively, how can he be sure that he ever has experienced its truthfulness ? Mr. Mill, on the other hand, admitted our belief in memory to be ultimate, because no reason can be given for it which does not presuppose its validity. This position is, as Dr. Ward pointed out, if literally accepted and carefully reflected on, most paradoxical. Dr. Ward had contended that the mind's positive declaration, if rightly analyzed, is the ultimate test of truth, and gave as an instance the act of memory. If, he said, you do not trust your mind's immediate declaration there you cannot even speak co- herently, much less give any reason for your belief that memory tells truly. This was, of course, a rcductio ad absurdnm ; but Mill replied as though the ground for the belief were the dilemma which its absence would lead to, whereas of course it would be equally true of any fahc belief that you can give no reason for it which docs not presuppose its truth indeed this would bo the special characteristic of a false belief. Some superstitious old xvi Introduction. woman tells me that she is convinced of the existence of fairies. I ask her what is her reason. " Oh," she replies, "I hear them knocking at my door in the night; and I hear them singing at Christmas time." I reply, " How do you know that the knocking is done by fairies or that the Christmas songs are not performed by the waits ? You give no reason for your belief, which does not presuppose the existence of the fairies the very thing in question." What Mr. Mill, of course, means is that the belief in the veracity of memory is plainly not derived from any prior truth, and is in that sense ultimate. But its being ultimate does not prove it to be well grounded, and it is manifestly illogical in him to regard a belief as well founded on the sole ground that his philosophy cannot get on without it. Such a mode of procedure would sanction any fanaticism that was ever devised. " All our schemes would fail, and all our faith be vain," says the follower of Mahomet, " if we did not believe Mahomet to be a prophet ; " therefore forsooth he is a prophet ! And the special case of memory presents in addition the peculiar characteristic, that reasoning in its favour from consequences is suicidal. In the act of recognizing the consequences, as in any other train of thought, the memory is used and trusted. The consequences cannot be known until the veracity of memory is established. The only possible warrant, then, for our trust in memory, and its all-sufficient warrant, is the mind's own positive declaration in the very act of remembering, that it is telling truth ; and it remained for Mr. Mill to show by what right, save that of expediency, he admitted the validity of that declaration, to save his neck, as it were, in this one instance, and refused to admit it, in the absence of similar external pressure, in others. This he never did. And seeing that he considered the intuition controversy of the last importance, and devoted a long appendix to Dr. Introduction. xvii Ward's strictures, which he said were the best which were likely to be made by any future champion, Dr. Ward held himself justified in assuming that he did not press his explanation of this particular question further, because he had some faint perception of the probable issue of a sus- tained analysis of the position he had taken up. Another instance which the author selected of the want of fidelity to his avowed principles in Mr. Mill's philosophy was his belief in nature's uniformity. This belief is, by the confession of all, at the root of induction, and induction and the inductive method is the very watchword of modern philosophy, and the field in which Mill has been above all others a successful analyst of the mind's method of pro- cedure. Dr. Ward draws out carefully, in the second and fifth essays of this collection, the impossibility of giving a reasonable ground for this belief without allowing the prin- ciple of intuition. Not that he held the belief to be itself intuitive, but it necessarily depends for its establishment on certain intuitive principles among others the principle of causation. Mr. Bain gives up this controversy and admits,* that we must assume the uniformity of nature, as we can find no other basis for physical science. And 3 r et we may remark in passing what contempt do not thinkers of his school exhibit for those who say that we must assume Theism to be true because there is no other satisfactory basis for moral science ! Mr. Mill was led, in reference to this controversy, into another curious logical blunder. He had summarized the uniformity of nature as an exhibition of what he called the lair of causation. This law, he explained, implies no more than uniform phenomenal sequence, as he refuses to allow any other meaning to the word " cause," than immediate precedence in order of time. Speaking however, later on, in reference to the question raised by Dr. Ward, he declared that a miracle would be * Poo Buiu's " Logic," pp. 27H, 271. xviii Introduction. no breach of the law of causation, as a new antecedent viz. the volition of a supernatural being is, by hypothesis, interposed in such a case. Thus, a law which was defined as the law of phenomenal uniformity in nature, and the basis on which physical science proceeds, is allowed by him to be consistent with as many interruptions of that uni- formity as might result from the constant interference (as the author puts it) of as many deities as Homer himself supposed to inhabit Olympus. A truly marvellous basis for the inductive method ! Of course such an argument is a reductio ad absurd urn, but, as Dr. Ward points out, in such a delicate matter and in treating of principles which in their legitimate issue must overthrow religious philo- sophy, one has a right to expect careful thought and accurate expression : whereas in both the instances that have been named no evidence appears of either. The author frequently pointed out, that of questions such as the veracity of memory and the general uniformity of phenomena all men have abundant evidence through the intuitive and in- ferential powers of their own mind, working in the normal way; therefore controversy in their regard is apparently sterile and unnecessary. But this is the very reason of Dr. Ward's challenge : " You trust your intuitive percep- tions," he says, " and climb by means of them to an eminence. Then you kick down the ladder by which you have climbed, and tell those who did not notice you while you were climbing, that you jumped up, and that the ladder is rotten, and would be of no use." Mr. Mill and Mr. Bain are no doubt right in trusting in memory and in nature's uniformity, but their only warrant for doing so is a process of mind involving intuition, and if they pretend to have sufficient warrant on the Experience principles let them show it. If they fail to do so, let them own that these principles are an insufficient account of the basis of their own reasoning. Dr. Ward thus expresses his view on this Introduction. xix matter, so far as nature's uniformity is concerned, in an essay which we have not here repuhlished : "Any one who observes either the language or the general tone of Phenomenistic philosophers will see clearly (we think) that they do not in fact rest their belief in the uniformity of nature on any argumentative basis whatever, which they can distinctly contemplate or defend. The truth of the doctrine is made clear to them by reasons which they do not attempt to analyze, and which they could not analyze if they did attempt to do so. The uniformity of nature is borne in upon them (if we may so express our- selves) by the e very-day experience of their active life. Every day they receive fresh proofs of it and live (as we may say) in contact with it. Accordingly, if they ever give their minds to an inquiry as to what those arguments are on which the doctrine can reasonably be based, any one may see that they pursue the examination in a spirit of languid indifference. They are already profoundly con- vinced of the doctrine, before they have even asked them- selves any question as to its reasonable basis. " Now, on this we have three remarks to make : (1) We think that their procedure is, so far, entirely reasonable. We are confident that there are several truths of vital im- portance to mankind, which are reasonably accepted as certain on implicit grounds of assurance. They are reason- ably accepted, we say, as certain, on grounds of assurance, winch have not as yet been scientifically analyzed ; nay, of which, perhaps, scientific analysis transcends the power of the human mind. See what Catholic philosophers say on the sensns communis nntnrs >- lutely necebi-ary for phenomenists to assume as a separate principle tl o validity of their inferring process Mr. Mill, indeed, apparently tines >/ >t account this necessary we would jx>int out (what will he very obvious is our essay proceeds) that no part whatever of our argument depends on th s particular statement. G The Philosophy of Theism. for human knowledge in its entireness and totality. The inquiry, then, to be instituted is this. Firstly, what characteristics must be possessed by those truths, which the thinker may legitimately accept as primary ? and secondly, on what ground does he know that the propositions are true which possess those characteristics ? Or to express the same thing in F. Kleutgen's words (n. 2G3), firstly, what is the rule of certitude ? and, secondly, what is its motive ? There never was any answer but one given to this question by Catholics, before the deplorable darkness spread abroad by Descartes over the whole region of philosophy. (1) Primary truths are those which the human intellect is necessitated by its constitution to accept with certitude, not as inferences from other truths, but on their own evidence : this is the rule of certitude. (2) These truths are known to be truths ; because a created gift called the light of reason is possessed by the soul, whereby every man, w r hile exercising his cognitive faculties accord- ing to their intrinsic law r s, is rendered infallibly certain that their avouchments correspond with objective truth : this is the motive of ceiiitude. " It is conceivable," says Professor Huxley ("Lay Sermons," p. 35G), "that some powerful and malicious being may find his pleasure in deluding us, and in making us believe the thing which is not every moment of our lives." Quite conceivable, doubt- less ; but the light of reason makes man infallibly certain that such a supposition is absolutely contradictory to fact. This is the doctrine accurately and carefully elaborated by F. Kleutgen in the 2nd, 3rd, and 4th chapters of his Third Dissertation. "It is the light of reason which makes us certain of what the sensus intimus attests" (n. 263). "Proceeding from the facts furnished by ex- perience, we advance to further knowledge by the principles of pure thought ; but the truth of these principles and the reality of those facts are not certain to the mind, except The Ride and Motive of Certitude. 7 through the light of reason which is inherent in the human mind " (n. 264). " The mind in thinking by reason has the consciousness of possessing truth, so long as it knows the agreement [which exists] between its thoughts and those principles which we call the laws of thought " (n. 274). Since the creature's " faculty of knowledge is created and therefore limited, no creature can be infallible in this sense, that by his own strength he can judge of everything with certitude. In the creature infallibility is always united with fallibility, as being is united with not- being. Yet, just as the creature's being, though finite, is nevertheless true being, so his infallibility, though limited, is nevertheless real infallibility" (n. 277). "The principles wherewith we begin, the logical laws which we follow in deduction, are infallible, as the rule whereby we judge the truth of our experimental knowledge " (n. 278).* We may be allowed to call this doctrine the doctrine of intrinsic certitude. We would so call it, in order to dis- tinguish it from those theories which rest certitude on some basis extrinsic to the mind itself; from Descartes's, e.g., who rests it on the veracity of God ; and from La- mennais's, who rests it on the consent of mankind. Accord- ing to this, which we must be allowed to call the one Catholic doctrine on the subject, the mind's intrinsic light * We should not fail, however, to quote the important elucidation which F. Kleutgen subjoins: "And that we may understand how little this pre- rogative [of partial infallibility] would justify human pride, let us observe the limits of that sphere within which [alone] it is ascribed to him. In our investigations we need experimental knowledge, not only in commencing our inquiries, but during their whole progress; especially when we would apply science to the conduct of life. Now, how many tilings arc necessary in order to our arriving at full certitude by means of personal experience and other men's observations! What calm! what attcntivcness ! what impartiality! what efforts! what perseverance ! How often it happens that a new obser- vation, a more profound examination, an unexpected discovery, have over- thrown the most accredited systems by taking from Un-m their basis! If, then, our age glorifies itself fur its progress in the experimental sciences, men should not IK; unmindful at the same time of the lesson in humility which should be learnt from that very progress," etc. 8 The Philosophy of Theism. declares the objective truth of whatever man's cognitive faculties subjectively avouch. Would we demonstrate that there are necessary verities ? Would we demonstrate that this or that particular proposition is among this number ? In either case it is requisite, and it is sufficient, to demon- strate that the human intellect, acting on the laws of its constitution, so declares. This is the foundation we wish to lay in our present essay for the controversy with Mr. Mill which is to follow. But before proceeding to vindicate its truth, we must guard against two possible misconcep- tions of our meaning. In the first place, it is abundantly possible that men may misinterpret the avouchment of their intellect ; and this, indeed, would constitute an important addition to the causes alleged by F. Kleutgen (see our preceding footnote) for their proclivity to error. Both schools of philosophy admit this. The objectivist says to his opponent, If you will only look fairly at this and that intellectual fact to which I draw your attention, you will not be able to deny that such and such is the declaration of your cognitive faculties. And the phenomenist is not slow in making a similar retort. We hope ourselves, indeed, in our next essay vigorously to illustrate this fact ; we hope to show, by appealing to this, that, and the other mental experience, that phenomenists have not a leg to stand on, when they deny that their cognitive faculties declare the existence of necessary truth. What we are maintaining in this essay is, that such is the sole legitimate controversial ground ; that the avouchment of man's cognitive faculties is his final and his infallible standard of truth. But, secondly, we appeal to the mind's positive, not its negative constitution ; or, in other words, we lay our stress on its affirmations, not on its incapacities. It does not follow, because the human mind cannot conceive a propo- sition, that such proposition may not be true ; nay, that it The Rule and Motive of Certitude. may not be most certain and inappreciably momentous. We express this qualification here, that we may distinctly explain the precise bearing of our main thesis ; but we reserve our argument on the matter to a later part of our paper. Our main thesis, then, is this. " Man's cognitive faculties, while acting on the laws of their constitution, carry with them in each particular case their own evidence of absolute trustworthiness. All human knowledge has its commencement in various truths, whether of memory* or of other kinds, which are self-evidently known as true, each by itself, under the light of reason." It would, of course, be a contradiction in terms, if we professed to adduce direct arguments for this thesis ; because such profession would imply that the self-evidence of these truths is a verity inferred from premisses, whereas the thesis itself states that the knowledge of one or other of them as self-evident is an absolutely essential preliminary to all inference whatever. But we will (1) adduce for it strong indireci argument ; and (2) (which is much more important) suggest to our readers such mental experiments as shall (we trust) satisfy them of its truth. "We state our indirect argument as follows. Every one really knows that he knows something besides his present consciousness ; that he has had this or that definite past experience ; that through this or that moral or intellectual training he has arrived at this or thnt interior result ; and the like. There are some few most singularly constituted men who, at particular moments of their life, persuade themselves that they doubt whether they * We arc amazed that both Sir W. Hamilton and Mr. Mill concur in censuring Reid for his statement that " memory is immediate knowledge of the past" ("Mill on Hamilton," p. 134). The statement seems to us not only indubitable, hut even elementary ; and we are sanctioned in this opinion by the high authority of Mr. Martineau (vol. ii. pp. 2."iS-'Jt;:!). That which I immediately think of, in remember! rr.:, is surely my past experience. But the question is wholly irrelevant to our present purpose. 10 The Philosophy of Theism. possess such knowledge, and we will presently consider their case : for the moment, however, we will put them out of account. Speaking generally, then, every one knows that he knows something besides his present consciousness. But he cannot possess that knowledge, except through the exercise (past or present) of his cognitive faculties ; and he cannot accept it as being knowledge and not delusion, except by knowing that the declarations of those faculties are true. Now, how can he know this ? By the authentication of God ? by the testimony of his fellow-men ? But it is only by trusting the declaration of his cognitive faculties that he can know or even guess the existence of God and his fellow-men ; and still more, that he can know or even guess what God and his fellow-men testify. Unless, there- fore, his cognitive faculties authenticate thcmsclces, they cannot be authenticated at all. And if they are not authenticated at all, no man on earth knows anything whatever, except his own experience of this particular moment. Than this there can be no more clenching reductio ad absurdum. Passing now to the direct establishment of our thesis, we appeal to each man's consciousness in our favour. That which his faculties indubitably declare as certain, he finds himself under an absolute necessity of infallibly knowing to be true. I experience that phenomenon of the present moment, which I thus express : I say that I remember distinctly and articulately to have been much colder a few minutes ago when I was out in the snow, than I am now when sitting by a comfortable fire. Well, in consequence of this present mental phenomenon, I find myself under the absolute necessity of knowing that a very short time ago I had that experience which I now remember. Professor Huxley may talk of " some powerful and malicious being," who " finds his pleasure in deluding me " and making me fancy what never happened; but I am abso- The Rule and Motive of Certitude. 1 1 lutely necessitated to know that I am under no such delusion in regard to this recent experience.* And so with my other intellectual operations. My faculties pronounce that my present impression of colour differs from another of which I retain a distinct idea ; or they pronounce that this trilateral figure which I distinctly image in my mind, is triangular ; or when I see two strips of wood lying in an ohlong hox close together and parallel to the sides, my faculties pronounce that the one which reaches beyond the other is nearer than that to the further end of the box. In all these cases I am necessitated to know that which my faculties declare as true. As we have already said, there are some few most singularly constituted persons who, when contemplating their own mental phenomena, become for the moment dizzy with self-inspection ; seized with vertigo, as one may say, with gazing down the abyss : and these men persuade themselves that they do possess a power of distrusting their cognitive faculties. We would thus address such a sceptic, if we could obtain his attention. We appeal from Philip drunk to Philip sober. You are giddy for the moment and beside yourself, like a man in liquor. If you would correctly appreciate your mental constitution, look back at some given period of your life, when your faculties * In a passage which we quoted in a previous note, Professor Huxley seems to say that the truth of what memory distinctly testifies is not known " with that highest decree of certainty which is given by immediate nmti-iou*- new" but is nevertheless in the very highest degree pnHmlib 1 . If we rightly understand him with very greiit respect for his usutil power and clearness of thought we must nevertheless say that this seems to us the most 1111- reagonable opinion on the subject which can possibly be held. If my memory may be trusted, those things which it distinctly testities are known with most absolute certainty; if it cannot be trtK-ted, its avouchinent does not render them even remotely probable. Indeed, what can be more violently unscientific from the standpoint of mere experimental science than t<> assume without grounds, as even probable, the very singular proposition, that mental phenomena (by some entirely unknown law) have proceeded in such a fashion that my clear impri-fi'm of the past invariably cm-responds with my past erperii nre f 1 2 The Philosophy of Theism. were braced and in full play, not paralyzed by morbid intro- spection. You were engaged in that anxious commercial speculation, or in that important lawsuit, or you were taking measures to avert imminent gout. Had you at that time the power of doubting whether you had previously entered on that speculation, or engaged in that lawsuit, or experienced premonitory symptoms of gout ? Or when your mother was at last pronounced out of danger, could you really prevent yourself from infallibly knowing that you had been anxious ? Or had you really the power of doubt- ing whether you had ever seen that sweet face before ? You will reply perhaps and indeed you are bound (we admit) in consistency to reply that you have no reason to know you ever icere in such circumstances ; that you know nothing whatever about yourself, except your present con- sciousness. In that case we will practise on you a future experiment. Employ yourself in whatever most interests you ; in studying mathematics or taking a part in glees. While you are so engaged, we will suddenly come up and seize you by the arm. Can you noiv, we will say, prevent yourself from infallibly knowing that a very short time ago you were immersed in mathematical study or engaged in singing that glee ? However, whether or no we would succeed in curing this monomaniac, is an irrelevant question : for that he is a mere monomaniac, and, moreover, that he has no real power of persevering in such scepticism, will be admitted by all our readers. For the consistent sceptic cannot possibly be a reader. He cannot understand one single sentence unless, while reading the last words, he trusts his memory for the first. Now, if he trusts his memory so far as this, he has ipso facto abandoned his sceptical position. Phenomenists, then, as we have urged, act suicidally in disparaging the light of reason ; for it is only by surrender- ing themselves to that light, and so trusting their memory, The, Rule and Motive of Certitude. 13 that they can know anything whatever about phenomena. They are very much given, however, to such disparage- ment ; and they are very fond of alleging certain supposed difficulties. I see a straight stick in the water, and my faculties (they urge) confidently pronounce that the stick is crooked ; or if a cherry is placed on my crossed fingers, my faculties confidently pronounce that my hand is touched hy two substances. It is apparently for some such reason that Mr. Mill lays so much stress on Berkeley's theory of vision. Men fancy themselves such is Berkeley's theory to see distance immediately ; but in fact that conviction of distance is an inference, and no immediate judgment whatever. Now, we do not admit this theory except for argument's sake ; and Mr. Abbott, in his little volume called " Sight and Touch," professes to disprove it.* But we cannot at all agree with the latter writer, when he says (Preface) that if Berkeley's theory were admitted, " con- sciousness " would be proved " delusive " and " doubt must reign supreme : " for on the contrary so far as the con- troversy with scepticism is concerned we consider the question one of complete indifference. All these superficial difficulties are readily solved by resorting to a philosophical consideration, which is familiar to Catholics, though (strangely enough) we do not remember to have seen it in non-Catholic works. We refer to the distinction between what may be called " undoubting " and what may be called " absolute " assent. By " absolute " assent we understand an assent so firm as to be incompatible with the co-existence of doubt : but by * The present writer has never given liis mind to it, and has no bins whatever on either side. Dr. M'Cosli ("Intuitions of the Mind," p. Ill, note) thinks Mr. Ablnitt's argument sufficient for part, not the whole, of his conclusion. Mr. Mill (p. v{00) considers tlmt Mr. Abbott has been con- clusively answered by Professor Fraser in the Xorth lirittth J{r for August, 18<>4. On the other Imnd, the lust writer on the subject, 1'rofe.isor Huxley, takes part ntjainxt Mr. Mill and Professor Frascr. Sec M acini lUm'a for June, 1871, p. 153. 14 The Philosophy of Theium. " undoubting " assent we mean no more than that with which in fa<'t doubt does not co-exist. Now, the mere undoubtingness of an assent does not at all imply any particular firmness, but arises from mere accident. For instance, a friend, coming down to me in the country, tells me that he has caught a sight of the telegrams as he passed through London, and that the Versailles government has possession of Paris. I had long expected this, and I assent to the fact without any admixture of doubt. In an hour or two, however, the morning paper comes in; and I find that my friend's cursory glance has misled him, for that the army has only arrived dose up to Paris. The extreme facility with which I dismiss my former " un- doubting " assent, shows how very far it was from being " absolute." Its true analysis, in fact, was no more than this : " there is an a priori presumption that Paris is taken." But as no particular motive for doubt happened to cross my mind, I was not led to reflect on the true character of the assent which I yielded. Now to apply this. Evidently it cannot be said that my cognitive faculties declare any proposition to be certainly true, unless they yield to that proposition "absolute" assent. But a moment's consideration will show that my assent to the crookedness of the stick or the duplicity of the cherry, may accidentally indeed have been undoubting, but was extremely far from being absolute. Its true analysis was: "there is an a priori presumption that the stick is crooked or that there are two objects touched by my fingers ; " and this declaration of my faculties indisput- ably corresponded with objective truth. A remark precisely similar may be made on my putatively immediate percep- tion of distances ; and we may bring the matter to a crucial experiment by some such supposition as the following. I am myself but youthful, whether in age or power of thought ; but 1 have a venerable friend and mentor, in The Rule and Motive of Certitude. 15 whose moral and intellectual endowments I repose perfect confidence. I fancy myself to see a crooked stick, or to feel two touching objects ; but he explains to me the physical laws which explain my delusion, and I surrender it with the most perfect facility. He further expounds and demon- strates Berkeley's theory of vision ; and here, though I have a little more trouble with myself, yet after a short con- sideration I entirely acquiesce. He proceeds, however let us suppose, for the purpose of probing the depth of my convictions to tell me that I have no reason whatever for knowing that I ever experienced a certain sensation, which my memory most distinctly declares me to have experienced a very short time ago : or again, that, as to the particular trilateral figure which I have in my thoughts, I have no reason whatever for knowing it to be triangular, and that he believes it to have five angles. Well, first of all I take for granted that I have not rightly understood him. When I find that I have rightly understood him, either I suspect him (as the truth indeed is) to be simulating, or else (if I am too great an intellectual coward for this) I am reduced to a state of hopeless perplexity and bewilderment, and on the high-road to idiocy. So great is the distinction between merely " undoubting " and " absolute " assent ; between my faculties testifying that there is an a priori presumption for some theory and their testifying that it is certainly true. Another objection, raised by phenomenists, turns on the divergence which exists among objectivists, as to what their faculties do testify. Thus many men do not think them- selves to intue any axiom of causation at all ; and of those who do allege such axiom, there are different schools, each differently analyzing it. Many, again, do not think theiu- selve to intue the intrinsic distinction between moral good and evil ; and among those who do recognize this dis- tinction, there are differences which may in some sense be 1(5 The Philosophy of Tfteism, called fundamental. This objection cannot, however, be maintained, unless its advocate first makes good a pre- liminary position. He must show that the difference, on which he insists, is a difference between what the intellect of different men declares, and not merely between what they interpret it as declaring. But we are perfectly confident that he cannot show this, for that it is not true. We shall examine the phenomena on which he relies when we come to treat the respective questions of morality and causality. A third objection has been urged against us, founded on the indubitable fact that we may not, at this rudiniental stage of our argument against phenomenists, assume the Creator's Veracity. Could not a mendacious creator, it has been asked Professor Huxley's " powerful and malicious being who finds his pleasure in deluding " mankind so have constituted the human intellect as that it should testify falsehood, and nevertheless have given men the same trust in its declarations which they now feel ? We reply easily in the negative. To say that mendacious faculties can be infallibly known as trustworthy, is a contradiction in terms. No possible creator could anymore achieve such a result than he could form a crooked straight line. We have now, then, sufficiently illustrated our funda- mental thesis, that every thinker infallibly knows each successive declaration of his faculties to be true. And we have also sufficiently illustrated the first explanation, which we appended to that thesis ; viz. that what he can ulti- mately trust is the declaration of these faculties, and not his own analysis thereof. We proceed to the second qualifica- tion which we made at starting. We appeal, we said, to the mind's positive, not its negative constitution : we cannot admit that what is inconceivable is therefore untrue. We side here with the vast majority of phenomenists,* against * Mr. Herbert Spencer is, we believe, the only exception j and that on grounds of his own which we need not here consider. The Rule aiid Motive of Certitude. 17 certain objectivists ; but we believe that our divergence from the latter is exclusively verbal. They say, e.g., that no trilateral figure is quadrangular, and that two straight lines never enclose a space, because in either case the supposition is inconceivable : but what they intend is, that such supposition contradicts what I know as true, by my very conception of a trilateral figure or a straight line. "We think it, however, a real calamity that they have used the expression which we criticize, because it permits such writers as Mr. Mill to rest contented with a most inadequate apprehension of the objectivist argument. In justice, however, to these writers, we must distinguish carefully between two different senses of this word "incon- ceivable ; " and this procedure will lead us into what our readers may at first be tempted to suppose a digression, but which they will ultimately find to be no digression at all. Sometimes the word "inconceivable" is taken to mean " unimaginable," at other times " unintelligible " or " unthinkable." Now, there is a large class of unimaginable things, which are by no means unthinkable ; and no objec- tivist ever alleged that the unimaginablencss of a proposition is incompatible with its truth. We may express the dis- tinction in Mr. Martineau's words ; though we are not aware that this most able philosopher has ever adopted the particular formula which we are criticizing, of incouceiv- ableness being conclusive against truth. Ideas, he says (vol. i. p. 193), may be clear and thinkable, which " do not come before the imaginative or representative facult} 7 ." " You may deny the idea of the ' infinite,' " he adds (p. 194), " as not clear : and clear it is not, if nothing but the mental picture of an outline deserve that word. But if a thought is clear when it sits apart without danger of being confounded icitJi another, when it can exactly keep its own in speech and reasoning with forfeit and without encroachment if, in short, logical clearness consists not in the idea of a limit VOL. I. C IS The Philosophy of Theitmi. but in the limit of the idea, then no sharpest image of any finite quantity ... is clearer than the thought of the infinite." And so at p. 205, the author contrasts an "idea of the reason " with " one of the phantasy." " It is no objec- tion," he adds (p. 238), "to either the reality or the legitimacy of a thought, that it is not of a kind to be brought before the mind's eye" So Dr. M'Cosh. " The thinking, judging, believing power of the mind is not the same as the imaging power " (" Intuitions," p. 195, note). Similarly speaks Mr. Mill from the opposite school. Take the case of some large number : suppose, e.g., it were said that over a certain tract of ground there had been counted 27,182,818 potatoes. It is simply impossible to have this number in my phantasy or imagination, so as to distinguish it from 27,182,817 and 27,182,819. Yet says Mr. Mill (p. 100), " We have a " sufficient " conception of it, when we have conceived it by some one of its modes of composition, such as that indicated by the position of its digits." This " limited conception enables us to avoid confounding the number in our calculations with any other numerical whole ; " and we can also " by means of this attribute of the number ascertain and add to our conception as many more of its properties as we please." In other words, this large number is most easily thinkable, though by no means imaginable. This distinction, between propositions imaginable and propositions only thinkable, is in some degree correspondent, though not precisely so, with a distinction made by F. Newman, between what he characterizes respectively as " real " and " notional " assent.* He adds, also, this obvious qualification, that multitudes of men, from indolence or other causes, give no more than a " notional " assent to * He thinks, however (p. 43), that men cannot have even a " notional " apprehension of a very large number, such as a hillion or a trillion. We are certainly disposed to dissent from him on this small episodical question. The Rule and Motive of Certitude. 19 propositions most easily " imaginable." And this circum- stance, as F. Newman emphatically repeats in various passages, is often a very serious moral or intellectual calamity. Now, as we have said, those objectivists against whom we are now arguing, undoubtedly used the word " incon- ceivable " to express not " unimaginable," but "unthink- able." We are led, then, to consider whether any proposi- tion can (in this sense) be truly called inconceivable, except those which actually contradict what is known by my very conception of their " subject." If there are none such, then our only quarrel with these philosophers will be, that their language understates the positivcness with which man's cognitive faculties declare certain propositions to be neces- sarily false. But we think there are propositions which may most fitly be called inconceivable and unthinkable, yet which all Theists regard as indubitably true. "We refer to religious mysteries.* Let us begin with an illustration, which has often been given by F. Newman. It is most easily supposable that there may be rational creatures to whom, as being incor- poreal themselves, the union of soul and body is a veritable mystery. If it were revealed to them or, again, if it were deducible from premisses with which they were acquainted that the soul of man is on one hand spiritual and indi- visible, while on the other hand it is integrally present throughout every particle of an extended body, such a * It is said in Goschler's " Dictionary of Catholic- Theology " (article " Mysteries "), that theologians are extremely far from accord in their acceptation of this word. F. 1'errone (" De Vera Religione," prop. )J) uses it substantially in the same sense with F. Newman, and we ourselves so adopt it in the text. F. Franzelin, however (see e.f/. "Do Deo Trino," thesis xvii.), employs the word quite otherwise ; viz. to designate thoso truths which can in no sense he intrinsically established by reason, cither before or after their revelation. But it is very diflicult indeed to find it substitute for the word, as expressing FF. Perrone's and Newman's ideii : whereas F. Franzelin may most easily express hi* by a phrase which also ho often uses, viz. " superrational verities." 20 The Philosophy of Theism. proposition would be inconceivable to them. It would be inconceivable, in what Mr. Mill calls (p. 90) " the proper sense " of the term : it would be " that which the mind is unable to put together in a representation." Their first impulse would be to think that it is a contradiction in terms.* But subsequent consideration might bring to their mind that, as F. Newman expresses it (" Grammar," p. 44), their " notion " of a thing so entirely external to their experience "may be" nay, is almost sure to be "only partially faithful to the original;" that the word "pre- sence " may have a far wider sense than any which they can ever so distantly apprehend. That their notions, there- fore, of subject and predicate are more or less mutually contradictory, is no proof whatever that there is incompati- * " The soul is not only one, and without parts, but, moreover, as if by a great contradiction even in terras, it is in every part of the body. It is nowhere, yet everywhere. . . . No part of a man's body is like a mere instrument, as a knife or a crutch might be, which he takes up and may lay down. Kvery part of it is part of himself; it is connected into one by his soul, which is one. Supposing we take stones and raise a house, the building is not really one ; it is composed of a number of .separate parts, which viewed as collected together we call one, but which are not one except in our notion of them. But the hands and feet, the head and trunk, form one body under the presence of the soul within them. Unless the soul were in every part, they would not form one body ; so that the soul is in every part, uniting it with every other, though it consists of no parts at all. I do not, of course, mean that there is any real contradiction in tho.^e opposite truths ; indeed, we know there is not, and cannot be, because they are true, because human nature is a fact before us. But it is a contradiction trhen put into icords ; we cannot so express it as not to involve an apparent contradiction ; and then, if we discriminate our terms, and make distinctions, and balance phrases, and so on, we fehall seem to be technical and artificial and speculative, and to use words without meaning. . . . What (we should ask) was the meaning of Baying that the soul had no parts, yet was in every part of the body ? what was meant by saying it was everywhere and no- where? how could it be one, and yet repeated, as it were, ten thousand times over every atom and pore of the body, which it was said to exist in? how could it be confined to the body at all? how did it act upon the body? how happened it, as was pretended, that when the soul did but will, the arm moved or the feet walked ? how can a spirit, which cannot touch anything, yet avail to move so large a ma>s of matter, and so easily, as the human body ? These are some of the questions which might be asked, partly on the ground that the alleged fact was impossible, partly that the idea was self-con- tradictory." (F. Newman's Oxford "Parochial Sermons," vol. iv. pp. 325-328.) The Rule and Motive of Certitude. 21 bility between the archetypes of those notions. And we human beings indeed, in this case, are so well aware of the ludicrous mistake which would be made by these immaterial creatures if they reasoned otherwise, that we are mightily tempted to forget how prone we are ourselves in other instances to a similar paralogism. A proposition, then, maybe called "mysterious" to some given thinker, when it would be rightly accounted by him self-contradictory, if he suppposed that the notions which it conveys to him adequately represent their arche- types. It should be carefully observed, however, that his faculties themselves convey to him an assurance of his notions being thus utterly inadequate, and of no contra- dictoriness being therefore necessarily involved in the proposition itself. And it is further worth pointing out, that such mysterious propositions may nevertheless give real possibly, therefore, vitally important information ; though it would carry us too far from our theme, if we here enlarged on this truth. Now, as the union of soul and body might be utterly inconceivable to certain immaterial creatures, however strong their evidence for the fact, so there are various propositions concerning God, rigidly demonstrable by human reason, which are nevertheless inconceivable to the human intellect. That He Who is absolutely Simple and Indivisible, is present throughout all space ; that He in Whom is no succession of time, is ever diversely energizing ; that in God there is no real distinction whatever between His Nature and His Acts ; here are propositions at once humanly demonstrable and humanly inconceivable. We should add that no mysteries added by revelation arc more inconceivable than those irresistibly authenticated by reason.* * We earnestly hope we shall not V>e understood to rlmrnrtcri/r "// propositions concerning d'od as inconceivable. Cml, in most of His u.-itccts. *2'2 Tlic Philosophy of Mr. Mill excellently explains (p. 82) why it is abundantly possible that such inconceivable propositions may be true. " The inference " that " what we are incapable of conceiving cannot exist," " would only be warrantable if we knew a priori that we must have been created capable of con- ceiving whatever is capable of existing ; that the universe of thought and that of reality must have been formed in complete accordance with each other. . . . But an assump- tion more destitute of evidence could scarcely be made ; nor can one easily imagine any evidence that would prove it, unless it were revealed from above."* We implied, a few pages back, that a proposition is necessarily false which contradicts what is known by my very conception of its "subject." We should here explain that this does not at all conflict with what we have just been saying about mysteries. The reason is this. When the archetype is apprehended by me as indefinitely transcending my conception thereof, various propositions are not " known by its very conception," which otherwise would be. We have given, then, two reasons for deeply regretting the phrase used by many objectivists, that what is incon- ceivable is necessarily false. Firstly, even if no proposi- tion could be called " inconceivable " except that which can be apprehended by man (to use the common phrase) though not com- prehended. Accordingly a great majority of the propositions concerning Him are readily conceivable, thinkable, intelligible, though not compre- hensible in all the fulness of their meaning ; while some few are inconceivable as explained in the text. Nothing e.g. in the world conveys a more intelligible and practical idea than the affirmation that God is Loving, Veracious, Omniscient, Omnipotent, Holy. The same distinction applies to retealfd propositions concerning Him. F. Newman (pp. 120-137) considers those various statements which combine to express the dogma of the Blessed Trinity ; and in a very masterly way determines which of these statements admit of " real," and which of only " notional " assent. * We were much disappointed on coming, a few pages later (p. 1 19, note), to Mr. Mill's disparagement of "mystical metaphysics" and "mystical theology ; " for there cannot be a better defence of " mystical metaphysics " than the jwissage quoted in the text. The Rule and Motive of Certitude. 23 actually contradicts what is known by my very conception of its " subject," still it was extremely to be desired that a stronger expression than " inconceivable " should be used to express this. But, secondly, the word "inconceivable " may very naturally be understood as applying to every "mystery; " and if it be so understood, all Theists know that certain " inconceivable " propositions are demon- stratively true. Here, then, we sum up. Our direct thesis has been, that whatever men's cognitive faculties indubitably declare, is thereby known to be infallibly true. To prevent mis- conception, however, we have added two explanations. (1) This infallibility appertains to what they declare, not to what they may be understood as declaring ; and (2) it appertains to their positive declarations, and not to their incapacities. Now, since Mr. Mill is to be our principal opponent in various succeeding essays, it is absolute!}' necessary, before we conclude, to see how far we are in harmony with 1dm on this preliminary question. We are hereafter to argue against him, that the existence of neces- sary truths is cognizable with certitude by mankind ; but in order to discuss this with any satisfactory result, it is extremely momentous that he and ourselves should arrive at an agreement as to what constitutes a sufficient /<.-/ of certain knowledge. And we shall be able, on our side, to make our position clearer if we begin by distinguishing it from a ground importantly different, which has been occupied by more than one English non-Catholic objectivist. Mr. Martineau, indeed whom, notwithstanding extreme theological divergence and some serious philosophical sepa- ration, we cannot but recognize as at once the ablest and most learned of these entirely agrees with ourselves (if we rightly understand him) on the question we have been discussing. " ~\\'e have entire faith," lie says (vol. i. p. '211), '2\- Tltr Philosophy of T " in the veracity and the consistency of the reports given in by our highest faculties." And he uses similar expres- sions in pp. 47, 48, 101, 282, 237. He says again, pointedly (p. 104), " be the proof what it may which authenticates the belief, it is the faculty in the last resort which authen- ticates the proof." Yet even as to Mr. Martineau, we wish he had spoken more uncompromisingly. " Our faculties," he says (p. 238), " must be either taken at their word, or dismissed as cheats." We wish he had expressly said what he evidently holds, viz. that it is physically impossible to " dismiss them as cheats "or to doubt their declaration. It is a very serious loss to metaphysical science that Mr. Martineau has never found time for writing a systematic treatise. Dr. M'Cosh, in his most valuable work on "the Intui- tions of the Mind," speaks as strongly as F. Kleutgen himself, on one part of our subject, viz. the ride of certitude. He maintains emphatically that whatever the human faculties avouch is infallibly certain as they avouch it. The capacity of cognition in the mind, he says (p. 17), " is not that of the bent mirror to reflect the object under modified forms, but of the plane mirror to reflect it in its proper shape and colour. The truth is preserved by the mind, not formed ; it is cognized, not created.'" But when question arises on the motive of certitude, he often seems to turn off into a different groove. He often partakes, in fact, the error of Descartes, and implies that my reason for knowing the veracity of my mental constitution is my previous con- viction of God's Veracity. See third edition, pp. 30, 113, 116 : see also p. 333, where his remarks are singularly un- satisfactory. In fact, we suspect that this view possesses, more or less systematically and consciously, not a few speculative minds of non-Catholic England. Yet surely never was there an error more suicidal ; and Mr. Mill in a few pregnant words utterly explodes it. We quote the The Rule and Motive of Certitude. 25 passage with a few verbal changes (pp. 161, 162), and we italicize two sentences. " If the proof of the trustworthiness of our faculties is the veracity of the Creator, on what does the Creator's veracity itself rest ? Is it not on the evidence of our faculties ? The Divine veracity can only be known in two ways : (1) By intuition, or (2) through evidence. If it is known by intuition, it is itself an immediate declaration of our faculties ; and to have ground for believing it we must assume that our faculties are trustworthy. ... If we hold that God is not known by intuition but proved by evidence, that evidence must rest in the last resort on the' immediate declaration of our faculties. Religion thus, itself resting on the evidence of our faculties, cannot be invoked to prove that our faculties ought to be believed. We must already trust our faculties before we can have any evidence of the truth of religion." We are bound in fairness to add that Dr. M'Cosh, in his "Examination of Mr. Mill's Philosophy" (p. 54), ex- presses full concurrence with this reasoning. Dean Mansel has undoubtedly conferred important benefits on philosophy, and we hope in our succeeding essays to profit largely by his labours. Yet we must frankly say that, on the matter discussed in our present essay, his doctrine differs from Dr. M'Cosh's, signally for the worse. He concurs with that writer in holding that God's Veracity is my reason for regarding my faculties as in any sense trustworthy ; but he considers that argument as availing, not for the conclusion that their declaration is always true, but only that they are not so utterly mendacious as to be the mere "instruments of deception." " We may believe, and we ought to believe," he says (" Prolegomena Logica," p. 81), " that the powers which our Creator has bestowed upon us are not given as instruments of deception. . . . But in believing this we desert the evidence of Iteason to rest on that of Faith." According to this view, I could not know or even guess that my faculties are not mere instru- 26 The Philosophy of Theism, raents of deception, except for my belief that they are given by God. But on what ground do I believe that they are given by God ? Because they by their exercise lead me to that conclusion. But how do I know that, in thus leading me, they are not mere instruments of deception ? Because they were given me by God? But how do I know that they were given me by God? And so on with a vicious circle ad infmitum. We would only add here, to prevent possible miscon- ception of our meaning, that God's Veracity is undoubtedly a most legitimate philosophical premiss for the establish- ment of any conclusion, which is not itself required as a premiss for the demonstration of God's Veracity. For our own part, we think that a consideration of God's Attributes might with advantage be much oftener employed in philo- sophical argument than is commonly the case. But this by the way. We are now, then, to consider how far we may count on Mr. Mill's agreement with ourselves, in holding that the genuine declaration of man's faculties is in every case infallibly true. It is by no means so easy to answer this question confidently as might at first be supposed. At p. 152, indeed, he seems to speak unmistakably in our sense. " The verdict of ... our immediate and intuitive conviction is admitted on all hands to be a decision without appeal." Again, in p. 166 : " As regards almost all, if not all philosophers," he says and by his very phrase he implies that he at all events is no dissentient "the questions which divided them have never turned on the veracity of consciousness."* What Sir W. Hamilton " calls the testimony of consciousness to something beyond itself, may be and is denied ; but what is denied has almost * It should }>e explained that here and elsewhere he adopts under pro- test Sir W. Hamilton's use of the word "consciousness," to express not merely " self-consciousness," but man's intuitive faculty. Ttte Rule and Motive of Certitude. 27 always been that consciousness gives the testimony, not that if given it must be believed." In the preceding page, he says that no philosopher, not even Hume or Kant, had "dreamed of saying that we are compelled by our nature to believe" error. At page 161, note, he cites with approval Mr. Stirling's excellent statement, that it is the business of man's cognitive faculties to consider carefully what it is which they themselves declare : and adds, pointedly and justly (p. 166), that "we certainly do not know by intuition what knowledge is intuitive." Yet, in p. 171, he introduces a very ominous qualification of this doctrine. Men should only accept, it seems, " what consciousness," i.e. their intellect, " told them at the time when its revelations iverc in their pristine purity." There are " mental conceptions which become so identified in thought with all our states of consciousness, that we seem and cannot but seem to receive them by direct intuition." (Ib.) Some thinkers (p. 177) " may be personally quite incapable of not holding " a fundamental error. " We have no means of interrogating consciousness," i.e. our intellect, " in the only circumstances in which it is possible for it to give a trust- worthy answer" (p. 172). "Something u-hich ice now confound with consciousness may have been altogether foreign to consciousness in its primitive state " (p. 185). lie seems really to distinguish between the primitive and the adult state of man's cognitive faculties. He seems to imply that the laws of man's mental constitution are changed during his progress from infancy to manhood ; and that it is to their earlier, not their later, declarations that we are to look for authentication of truth. We cannot believe that Mr. Mill really intends this ; and we will, therefore, for the moment content ourselves with a brief reply to his possible meaning. We will say this, then. If the laws of man's mental constitution do really change in his progress from infancy to manhood, 2S Tlir Philosophy of Theism. then never was there a philosophical proposition more preposterously unfounded than that assumed by Mr. Mill throughout, viz. that man's primitive faculties testify truth. On what ground does an adult trust his faculties? We know of no other answer than we gave in an earlier part of our essay. In eacli individual case he finds himself necessitated to know infallibly what his faculties indubitably declare as certain ; and he generalizes this by degrees into the universal proposition that they are veracious. But all this applies to his adult, not his primitive, mental constitu- tion ; and if the former in any respect contradicts the latter, his reasoning so far does not apply to the latter at all. Mr. Mill professes, as strongly as we do, that no knowledge or experience is possible, unless the thinker first trust the distinct declarations of his memory. Is it only, then, the clear declarations of man's primitive memory which Mr. Mill accounts self-evidently true ? For ourselves we cannot but entirely agree with Mr. Mill's critic, whom he mentions in his note to p. 173. We think it would be " contrary to all analogy," if man's cognoscitive faculties did not need and did not receive, as time advances, " development and education." An argument, precisely resembling the above, applies a fortiori to a view which Mr. Mill ascribes (p. 175, note) to Mr. Herbert Spencer : viz. that " our primary forms of thought " are in many cases " inherited by us from ancestors by the laws of the development of organization," and need not, therefore, correspond with objective truth. It is plain we may observe in passing that such a theory applies no less to memory than to man's other cognitive faculties ; and the view thus stated impresses us as indi- cating the lowest point of speculative degradation at which " the progress of thought " has yet arrived. We should add, however, that all readers of Mr. Spencer are unani- mous in accounting him a writer of rare subtlety and genius. Tfte Ride and Motive of Certitude. 29 Returning to Mr. Mill, we cannot persuade ourselves that he really means what he seems to say ; that he really regards man's mental constitution as undergoing a change between infancy and maturity, in such sense that its de- clarations of a later period can possibly contradict those of an earlier. Nor, again, do we interpret a singular ex- pression in his " Logic," as indicating a real difference between him and ourselves, on what has been the theme of this article. Yet we cannot refrain from adverting to that expression. He says (vol. ii. pp. 97-98, seventh edition) that " the truth of a belief " would not follow even from an "irresistible necessity" of entertaining it; and that man- kind might conceivably be " under a permanent necessity of believing what might possibly not be true." But though Mr. Mill here speaks very obscurely, we understand him as referring to a certain imaginary state of things, which might have existed; and not as denying that in fact man's reason infallibly authenticates its own authority. It seems to us, from his language in both works, that Mr. Mill has failed indeed (as we should estimate the matter) in clearly and consistently apprehending and bearing in mind the true doctrine ; but that he has never intended to advocate a different one in preference. We shall take for granted, therefore, in our next essay, unless we are admonished of being mistaken, that the controversy between him and ourselves turns in no respect on the authority of man's faculties, but exclusively on their avouchment. On the other hand, we fully admit that again and again inferences are so readily and imperceptibly drawn as to be most easily mistaken for intuitions ; and that, in arguing hereafter against Mr. Mill, we shall have no right of alleging aught as certainly a primitive truth, without prorinfi that it cannot be an opinion derived mferentially from experience. It is our strong impression that this, and no more, is what Mr. Mill intends to urge in the 30 Tln>.-riit. 50 Tlie Philosophy of (" Logic," vol. i. p. 350.) Yet (vol. ii. p. 108) " it would be folly," in his opinion, " to affirm confidently " that " in distant parts of the stellar regions, where phenomena may be entirely unlike those with which we are acquainted," "those special laws" prevail, "which we have found to hold universally in our own planet." To hold otherwise, he thinks, would be "to make a supposition without evidence, and to which it would be idle to attempt to assign any probability." "Which of these two conflicting statements represents Mr. Mill's real mind ? We can have no doubt that the second does so. It would be a blunder, of which thinkers far less clear-sighted than Mr. Mill could not be guilty with their eyes open, to say that mathematical axioms are mere "generalizations from observation" ("Logic," vol. i. p. 258), and yet that a man can know them to hold good externally to the reach of possible obser- vation. Mr. Mill then considers it impossible to know, or even to guess, whether " in the more distant parts of the stellar regions " there may not be quadrangular trilateral, and pairs of straight lines each pair inclosing a space. Yet, in the extract before us, he alleges confidently that two divergent straight lines will never meet. Let us concede that experience can tell that they will not meet within tJie reach of human observation. But what possible reason can he consistently allege for even guessing that they may not meet, after they have passed beyond human ken and entered those inaccessible " distant parts of the stellar regions " ? We believe that a careful observer would detect many more paralogisms in the extract on which we have been commenting ; but our readers will have had enough of this particular passage. The only other argument which we can call to mind, as having been adduced by Mr. Mill against the self-evident necessity of mathematical axioms, occurs in an earlier part of his volume on Sir W. Hamilton ; p. 87, note. He has Mr. Mill's Denial of Necessary Truth. 57 avowedly adopted this argument from another contemporary writer, who has pressed into his service Eeid's " Geometry of Visibles : " and the argument itself may be thus stated : " If mankind had possessed only the sense of sight and not that of touch, they would have accounted it a self-evidently necessary truth that every straight line being produced will at last return into itself, and that any two straight lines being produced will meet in two points." Consequently, such is Mr. Mill's implied inference, men's knowledge of geometrical axioms depends, not on the immediate and peremptory declaration of their cognitive faculties, but on their possessing the sense of touch. We must here say one preliminary word, on Mr. Mill's strange attempt to enlist Eeid's authority on his side. He speaks of "Eeid's conclusion that, to beings possessing only the sense of sight, the paradoxes here quoted and several others would be truths of intuition, self-evident truths." But it is quite impossible that Reid can have intended what is here implied, because notoriously he maintained that men cognize with certitude the self-evident truth of mathe- matical axioms. In p. 451 of the volume from which Mr. Mill quotes, he says (sub fineiri) that "mathematical axioms" possess "intuitive evidence;" and in p. 452 he proceeds to enumerate them among the " first principles of necessary truths." We are confident that Dr. Reid, in the passage on which Mr. Mill relies, intended the very truth which it will be our own business to set forth in opposition to our present antagonist. In order to the apprehension of Mr. Mill's argument, it is necessary to premise, that both he and Dr. Reid account differences of distance as made known to man, not really by sight at all, but exclusively by touch. They hold therefore, that, if any man possessing sight were without the sense of touch, he would account all the objects seen by him to be equidistant. We are perfectly willing to admit this doctrine 58 The Philosophy of Tlteism. for argument's sake, though we have no conviction of its truth. This being laid down, Mr. Mill in effect thus argues : Let a planet be supposed, the inhabitants of which possess the sense of sight but not that of touch ; while their mental constitution is identical with that of the human race. The objects, which the planetarian sees at any given moment, are all accounted by him as equally distant from himself ; and accordingly as ranged on the inner surface of a hollow sphere, his eye being centre of that sphere. Let a straight line be placed before his vision : it will appear to him as the arc of a great circle of that sphere. He is told, how- ever, on trustworthy authority that it is a straight line ; and he will therefore enounce, as a self-evidently necessary truth, that every straight line being produced will at last return into itself, and that any two straight lines being produced will meet in two points. Those geometrical axioms therefore such is Mr. Mill's implied conclusion which contradict these two propositions, are not known to man by his mental constitution (for the planetarian has the very same mental constitution) but by his possessing and exercising the sense of touch. When once this argument is stated, there can hardly be any need of exposing its fallacy. The truth, which this planetarian regards as self-evidently necessary, is self- evidently necessary in the judgment of all objectivists : only he has learned to clothe it in non-human language. That form, w r hich he has learned to designate by the name "straight line," is precisely that which human bcinf/s designate an " arc of a great circle of a sphere." Whether such a planetarian could conceive the idea which men call a " straight line," is a question which we shall not here discuss ; but if he do conceive that idea possessing as he does the same mental constitution with men he will cognize as self-evidently necessary, that no Mr. MiWs Denial of Necessary Truth. 59 straight line, however produced, can possibly return into itself, and that no two straight line's can intersect in more than one point. In what language he will have learnt to express this idea " straight line," we cannot of course guess. We are not aware of any other reasoning of the least importance anywhere employed by Mr. Mill, in opposition to the objectivist doctrine on mathematical axioms. It seems to us, that in every instance the only effect he has legitimately produced, is to open out some fresh line of argument, which tells with irresistible force against his own conclusion. We ought not, however, perhaps considering the ultimate purpose of these essays entirely to pass over a philosophical theory, which arrives at a goal substantially the same with Mr. Mill's, by a route precisely opposite. Our readers will remember that, towards the beginning of our essay, we drew a distinction between "tautological" and " significant " propositions. A proposition of the former class declares no more than has already been expressed in its subject. Suppose, e.g., some one were gravely to enounce, that " every square is quadrilateral : " "of course," I should reply ; " for ' quadrilateral ' is part of what is expressed by the very word ' square.' ' Such nugatory propositions are of the form "A is A : " and Mr. Mill would himself admit that they are known inde- pendently of experience; though reasonably enough he might refuse to dignify them with the name of " a priori " or " necessary." Now such a philosopher as we speak of, while admitting that mathematical axioms are cognized independently of experience, maintains that they arc " tautological ; " and consequently that no inference can reasonably be made from them to the case of " significant " propositions. He denies accordingly, that there are any " necessary " propositions of the latter class. 00. The Ph ilosopl y of Tit e i#m . As this view is fundamentally opposed to Mr. Mill's, it is no part of our present business to reason against it at any length. We will but draw attention to the whimsical character of a theory which alleges that a vast body of new truths can be syllogistically deduced from tautologies ; and we will add one single argument by way of refutation. So far is it from being true that "triangular" is part of what is expressed by the word " trilateral," that on the contrary I have comprehended the whole of what is meant by " trilateral," before I have so much as asked myself the question whether a trilateral figure has three angles or any angle at all. So far is it from being true that 3 + 8 is part of what is expressed by the words 2 + 9, that on the contrary I have comprehended the whole of what is meant by the latter before I have so much as thought of the former, consciously or unconsciously, directly or indirectly. Mr. Mill has some excellent observations on this theory, so far as regards arithmetical axioms, in his " Logic," vol. i. pp. 284-289. We now, however, return to our general argument. From what has been hitherto said three inferences may be deduced, of much importance in their respective ways. I. Mathematical axioms are not ordinarily intued at first in an universal but in an individual shape. Dr. M'Cosh has done very great service, by dwelling on this truth in the case of all intuitions ; but our present concern is with mathematical axioms. I hold 7 pebbles in one hand and 4 in the other, and then transfer one from the larger to the smaller group. I intue, as a self-evidently necessary truth, that the new 5 + 6 = the old 4 + 7 : that not even Omnipotence could make the case otherwise. On reflection I perceive that the same truth holds, not of these pebbles only, but of all pebbles ; not of pebbles only but of all numerable things. Still further, reflection enables me to intue the more general axiom, a + 6 = (a + !) + (&-!); Mr. Mill's Denial of Necessary Truth. 61 and the more general axiom still, a + b = (a + m) -f (b m) ; where a, b, and m may be any whole numbers whatever, so only, that m be not greater than b. Capability of being universalized is indubitably a characteristic of self-evidently necessary truths ; but we shall be quite mistaken, if we fancy that they are ordinarily intued as universal. The immense majority of mankind, while again and again accepting them in their individual shape, seldom if ever universalize an axiom from the beginning of their life to the end. II. There can be no need of employing words to prove the very obvious proposition, that if mathematical axioms are self-evidently necessary, the validity of syllogistic reasoning is no less so. But the whole body of mathe- matical truth is derived syllogistically from mathematical axioms ; and it follows therefore, that the whole body of mathematical truth is strictly necessary. III. Even were there no other necessary truths than those which (we trust) we have conclusively proved to be such in our present essay, let us observe what results from our argument. Entirely distinct from, entirely over and above, the experimental order, there is a body of what may be called " transcendental " truth ; truth which trans- cends human experience.* We are not able yet to decide whether all transcendental truth is necessary : but anyhow all necessary truth is transcendental ; for the knowledge of * It will conduce to clearness, if we accurately distinguish between our use of the words " transcendental " and " intuitional." We call those truths " intuitional," which the individual accepts exclusively on the ground of mental intuition ; and we call those truths " transcendental " which are neither experienced facts nor inferable from experienced facts. Thus the truths testified by memory are " intuitional," but not " transcendental : " they are facts which have been experienced, and therefore are not "trans- cendental " truths ; yet they are known to him who remembers them, exclusively on the ground of present intuition, and they are therefore " intui- tional." On the other hand, Euclid's theorems are "transcendental," but not generally "intuitional;" because they are not accepted on the ground of intuition, but of deduction from intuitive truths. 62 The Philosophy of Theism. anything as necessary Mr. Mill will be the first to admit is wholly unattainable from mere experience. Further, among these transcendental truths are to be numbered the propositions of geometry, arithmetic, algebra, the dif- ferential calculus, calculus of variations, etc. Again, all the truths of mechanics and physical astronomy are neces- sary, if understood hypothetically. Take any proposition whatever of physical astronomy : it is a necessary truth that this proposition holds, if there be in existence a certain attractive force. But still further. Scientific men have not of course taken the trouble to work out a series of necessary hypothetical propositions, except in those com- paratively few cases where the hypothesis coresponds with physical fact. But a million other hypotheses may be framed ; as e.g. that the force of gravitation varies inversely as the distance, or as the cube of the distance, etc. : and for each one of these hypotheses, a new vast series of necessary hypothetical propositions can be evolved. It is plain then that, though there were no necessary truths except mathematical, even so their number is literally unimaginable and incalculable; immeasurably more than a thousand times the number of experimental truths. All trustworthy science, says Mr. Mill, is experimental : on the contrary, the enormous majority of true scientific propositions are transcendental. This will be our best place, for explaining the exact end at which we are aiming in this series of essays. Our ultimate purpose is a philosophical establishment of Theism : i.e. of the dogma, that there exists a Personal God, Infinite in all perfections, the Creator and Moral Governor of the universe. Those who deny that this dogma is cognizable by man with certitude, may be called " anti- theists ; " i.e. opponents of Theism. Of these, comparatively few are dogmatic atheists ; men who think that reason Mr. Mill's Denial of Necessary Truth. 63 disproves the existence of a Personal Creator. A far larger number, of whom Professor Huxley may be taken as representative, are "nescients;" i.e. deny that man can know certainly, or even probably, anything whatever about the matter. Others again, far more numerous perhaps than is commonly supposed, regard it as probable that the universe had an intelligent Maker ; but are driven, by the existence of moral and physical evil, to deny that this Maker combines Infinite Power with Infinite Love. We are led by various indications to suspect that Mr. Mill himself belongs to this category. Lastly, there are "pan- theists." The pantheist holds with some emphasis the cognizableness of the "Absolute" and the "Uncondi- tioned ; " but denies the existence of a Personal God, to Whom men are responsible, Who knows their thoughts, and Who will requite them according to their works. Now we believe that pantheists certainly Hegelian pantheists hold in philosophy the objectivist doctrine : but they have no important representative in England ; * and at all events would require a totally distinct consideration. While therefore our arguments, we hope, shall be such as to hold their own against all comers, our direct contest shall be only with those antitheists who profess the phenomenal philosophy. The phenomenistic doctrine is such as this : that an ascertained truth, means a truth experienced or inferred from experience ; that he who lays stress on -supposed intuitions leaves a foundation of rock to build on the sand ; that such a thinker, instead of manfully and philosophically confronting facts, erects into a would-be oracle his own individual idiosyncrasy ; that " a priori philosophy " means simply the enthronement of prejudice and the rejection of experience. And we fully admit, or rather indeed contend, * Dr. Stirling, the loading English Hegelian, professes l>elief even in Christianity. (" Secret of Hegel." preface, p. xxi.) 64 The Philosophy of Theism. that this phenomenistic doctrine issues legitimately in pro- nounced antitheism. Our first reply to it shall be founded on the faculty of memory. " Our belief in the veracity of memory," says Mr. Mill (on Hamilton, p. 508, note), "is evidently ultimate: no reason can be given for it, which does not presuppose the belief and assume it to be well founded." In other words, according to his frank confession, when I trust my memory when I believe myself to have experienced what my memory distinctly testifies I am resting exclusively on an intuition ; I am holding most firmly a truth for which experience gives me no warrant at all.* Yet unless I hold firmly this intuitive truth, I am literally incapable of receiving any experience whatever ; I have no knowledge of any kind except my present consciousness. The whole fabric of experience then has, for its exclusive foundation, a series of those intuitions which are called acts of memory. If intuitions as such are to be distrusted, experience is an impossibility and its very notion an absurdity. Mr. Mill has laid himself open, we think, to just criticism, for his mode of making this most honourable admission. No one will doubt, either that the phenomenist school professes the general doctrine we have ascribed to it, or that Mr. Mill habitually identifies himself with that school. Yet here is a most pointed exception to the school's general doctrine ; and an exception which no phenorneiiist had made before. Surely he might reasonably have been expected not merely to state it (however explicitly and un- mistakably) in a note, but to give it a prominent position in his work. If ever there were a paradoxical position, his is one on the surface. It is most intelligible to say that * This is undeniably Mr. Mill's admission : for he says that no reason whatever whether grounded on experience or on any other basis can be given for the veracity of memory, "which does not presuppose the very thesis for which it is adduced." A reason which presupposes the very thesis for which it is adduced is undeniably no reason at all. Mr. Mill's Denial of Necessary Truth. 65 there are no trustworthy intuitions ; and it is most intelli- gible to say that there are many such : but on the surface it is the ne plus ultra of paradox, to say that there is just one such and no more. He seems to have been uncon- sciously almost ashamed of this paradox ; and instead of placing it in the foreground, has shrouded it in the obscurity of a note. Then further he was surely called on to state explicitly his reasons. He holds that there is just one intuition one and only one which carries with it its own evidence of truth. There was an imperative claim on him then, as he valued his philosophical character, to explain clearly and pointedly where the distinction lies between acts of memory and other alleged intuitions. He would have found the task very difficult, we confidently affirm ; but that only gives us more reason for complaining that he did not make the attempt. To us it seems, that various classes of intuition are more favourably circumstanced for the estab- lishment of their trustworthiness, than is that class which Mr. Mill accepts. Thus in the case of many a wicked action, it would really be easier for the criminal to believe that he had never committed it, than to doubt its necessary turpitude and detestableness. Then in the case of other intuitions, I know that the rest of mankind share them with myself; and I often know also that experience con- firms them so far as it goes : but I must confidently trust my acts of clear and distinct memory, before I can even guess what is held by other men or what is declared by experience. We think it a blot on Mr. Mill's philosophy, that he has chosen, as his only trustworthy class of in- tuitions, a class for which there is less extrinsic evidence than for that of many others. But we think it a far greater blot on his philosophy, that instead of facing the difficulty he has ignored it. This, then, is our first argument against the phcnomi'iiist VOL. i. i' 60 Tlie Philosophy of Theism. doctrine. So far from experience being a more trustworthy guide than intuition, experience is not so much as possible unless we are throughout guided by intuition. Our second argument against the same doctrine is more closely con- nected with the earlier part of this essay. Phenomenists allege, that experience affords a legitimate basis for certi- tude, and that intuition affords no such basis. On the contrary without here discussing the question of " greater" or " less " certitude at all events intuition affords a higher kind of certitude than does experience. Experience at best can but declare what happens within the reach of human observation : but intuition avouches truths eternal and immutable ; truths which necessarily hold good in every possible region of existence. But thirdly, we maintain against phenomenists, that the best grounded conclusions of experimental science are not certain at all, except in virtue of certain necessary truths known mediately or immediately by intuition. In other words we maintain, that the certainty of physical science rests in last analysis, not on the phenomenal but on the transcendental order. This is a conclusion of extreme im- portance ; and we shall devote to it the remainder of our essay. Our argument is this. All physical science depends for its existence on the fundamental truth, that the laws of nature are uniform.* By introducing transcendental considerations, Catholics are able to prove conclusively this fundamental truth. We cannot indeed enumerate and weigh these transcendental considerations, until we have reached a later stage of our argument; here we are only contending, that no basis * In saying that " the laws of nature are uniform," we mean, of course, that no physical phenomenon takes place without a corresponding physical antecedent, and that the same physical antecedent is invariably followed by the same physical consequent. Of course we hold firmly against Mr. Mill that such physical antecedents are efficient causes; but this consideration is external to our present argument. Mr. Mill's Denial of Necessary Truth. 67 adduced by consistent phenomenists can suffice for its support. This is virtually admitted by the phenomenist philosopher, who has closer philosophical connection with Mr. Mill than has any other living writer : we refer to Mr. Bain. His language is so remarkable, that we shall quote it entire, italicizing one or two sentences. Granting, however, that the belief in memory, as well as the belief in present consciousness, is a primary assumption, we next remark that it conies short of our needs. The most authentic recollection gives only what has been ; something that has ceased, and can concern us no longer. A far more perilous leap remains ; the leap to the future. All our interest is concen- trated on what has yet to be ; the present and the past are of value only as a clue to the events that are to come. Now, it is far easier to satisfy us of what has been, than of what is still to be. The postulate that we are in quest of must carry us across the gulf, from the experienced known, either present or re- membered, to the unexperienced and unknown must perform the leap of real inference. " Water has quenched our thirst in the past ; " by what assumption do we affirm that the same will happen in the future ? Experience does not teach us this ; ex- perience is only what has actually been ; and, after never so many repetitions of a thing, there still remains the peril of venturing upon the untrodden land of future possibility. The fact, generally expressed as nature's uniformity, is the guarantee, the ultimate major premise, of all induction. " What has been, will be," justifies the inference that water will assuage thirst in after times. We can give no reason, or evidence, for this uniformity ; and, therefore, the course seems to be to adopt this as the finishing postulate. And, undoubtedly, there is no other issue possible. We have a choice of modes of expressing the assumption, but, whatever be the expression, the substance is what is conveyed by the fact of uniformity. Let us word the postulate thus : " What has uniformly been in the past will be in the future." Otherwise " what has never been contradicted in any known instance (there being ample means and opportunities of search) will always be true." This assumption is an ample justification of the inductive operation, as a process of real inference. Without it, we can do nothing; with it, wo can do anything. Our only error in / CS The Philosophy of Theism. proposing to give any reason or justification of it, to treat it other- wise than as begged at the very outset. If there bo a reason, it is not theoretical, but practical. Without the assumption, wo could not take the smallest steps in practical matters ; we could not pursue any object or end in life. Unless the future is to reproduce the past, it is an enigma, a labyrinth. (" Deductive Loyic," pp. 273, 274.) We give Mr. Bain every credit for his moral candour in making the admission so repugnant to phenomenist prin- ciples that, without this a priori presumption, science would be impossible ; and yet that no " reason or justifica- tion " for the assumption can possibly be given. Still we must account the passage we have quoted discreditable to his intellectual character. In his work on " The Senses and the Intellect," Mr. Bain emphatically denies, that even mathematical axioms are intuitively known; and yet he maintains the intuitive cognizableness of such a proposition, as that " what has uniformly been in the past will be in the future." For this truly amazing assumption he gives no reason whatever, and says that no reason can be given, except that physical science could not go on without it. Yet what would he himself say to an objectivist, who should assume the intuitive cognizableness of morality, while giving no other reason for that assumption, except that Chris- tianity could not get on without it ? He would say, we suppose, "so much the worse for Christianity;" and we might similarly reply to him, if we chose to be so narrow- minded, " so much the worse for physical science." We really know not one of the " a priori fallacies " which Mr. Mill in his "Logic " so ably denounces, more extravagantly wild than Mr. Bain's. " Nature abhors a vacuum ; " " actio non datur in distans ; " * " the heavenly bodies must move * Some philosophers, even some Catholic philosophers, really consider this axiomatic. F. Franztlin, however (*' De Deo Uuo," p. 350), says that Scotus, Vasquez, Bid, Francis Lugo, Valentia, and many grave theologians either doubt or dfiij its truth. And this fact, by the way, disproves Mr. Mill's Mr. Mill's Denial of Necessary Truth. C9 in the most perfect of figures, i.e. a circle ; " there is not one of these propositions, which may not quite as plausibly be considered self-evident. Moreover, the thinkers who have advocated such axioms as those above mentioned, have at all events openly avowed themselves a priori philo- sophers ; whereas Mr. Bain, the originator of this astonish- ing tour de force, professes himself a severe and cautious disciple of experience. There are two doctrines importantly different, on the uniformity of nature. There is the Catholic doctrine, that the laws of nature are ordinarily uniform, but very often miraculously suspended ; and there is the infidel doctrine, that they are unexceptionally uniform. Mr. Bain's language throughout implies the latter. In other words, he assumes as intuitive a principle, which with one breath sweeps off the whole Christian religion, without condescending to give even one philosophical reason for his opinion.* Mr. Mill is by no means so unfaithful to his pheno- menism as Mr. Bain, in the proof which he gives for the uniformity of nature. He thus reasons : The considerations which, as I apprehend, give, at the present day, to the proof of the law of uniformity of succession as true of all phenomena without exception, this character of completeness and collusiveness, are the following : First, that we know it directly to be true of far the greatest number of statement (" Logic," vol. ii. p. 317), that so recently as " rather more than a century ago " this " was a scientific maxim disputed by no one and which no one deemed to require any proof." For ourselves we can sec no shadow of ground for the maxim. * We ought not to conceal the fact, that tho sentence immediately fol- lowing our extract runs thus: "our natural prompting is to a*#um>'. such identity [of the future with tho past] ; to believe it first and prove it after- wards ;" ami the last words may bo understood us meaning that we <-nn " prove it afterwards." Certainly the sentence is expressed with discredit- able obscurity; but Mr. Biiin had already said expressly that " experience does not prove this;" and this sentence therefore must only mean, that when the fnttin' fa-comes the prttent we shall be able to prove that it re- sembles the pant. 70 TIte Philosophy of Thtivm. phenomena ; that there are none of which we know it not to be true, the utmost that can be said being that of some we cannot positively from direct evidence affirm its truth; while pheno- menon after phenomenon, as they become better known to us, are constantly passing from the latter class into the former ; and in all cases in which that transition has not yet taken place, the absence of direct proof is accounted for by the rarity or the obscurity of the phenomena, our deficient means of observing them, or the logical difficulties arising from the complication of the circumstances in which they occur; insomuch that, not- withstanding as rigid a dependence on given conditions as exists in the case of any other phenomenon, it was not likely that we should be better acquainted with those conditions than we are. Besides this first class of considerations, there is a second, which still further corroborates the conclusion. Although there are phenomena the production and changes of which elude all our attempts to reduce them universally to any ascertained law; yet in every such case, the phenomenon, or the objects concerned in it, are found in some instances to obey the known laws of nature. The wind, for example, is the type of uncertainty and caprice, yet we find it in some cases obeying with as much constancy as any phenomenon in nature the law of the tendency of fluids to distribute themselves so as to equalize the pressure on every side of each of their particles; as in the case of the trade winds, and the monsoons. Lightning might once have been supposed to obey no laws ; but since it has been ascertained to be identical with electricity, we know that the very same phenomenon in some of its manifestations is implicitly obedient to the action of fixed causes. I do not believe that there is now one object or event in all our experience of nature, within the bounds of the solar system at least, which has not either been ascertained by direct observation to follow laws of its own, or been proved to be closely similar to objects and events which, in more familiar manifestations, or on a more limited scale, follow strict laws : our inability to trace the same laws on a larger scale and in the more recondite instances, being accounted for by the number and complication of the modifying causes, or by their inaccessibility to observation. (" Logic," vol. ii. pp. 106, 107.) Before we consider the value of this argument, a pre- liminary remark will be in place. We have already said Mr. Mill's Denial of Necessary Truth. 71 that, by help of transcendental considerations, the uni- formity of nature is conclusively established ; and we will here add, that these transcendental considerations are of such a kind as to impress their force, not on philosophers only, but on all mankind. Since then, as we consider, the mass of men are at starting most reasonably and completely convinced of the thesis which Mr. Mill desires to prove, it is only to be expected that they should receive with ready acquiescence any reasoning which is adduced for so un- deniably true a conclusion. Let it be granted, then, that the majority of Mr. Mill's readers are satisfied with his argument. Still such a fact does not at all evince the argument's real sufficiency, because the fact may so easily be accounted for by the cause which we have stated. Now Mr. Mill's reasoning amounts at best to this. If in any part of the world there existed a breach in the uniformity of nature, that breach must by this time have been dis- covered by one or other of the eminent men who have given themselves to physical experiment. But most certainly, adds Mr. Mill, none such has ever been discovered, or mankind would be sure to have heard of it : consequently, such is his conclusion, none such exists. Now, in order to estimate the force of this argument, let us suppose for a moment that the fact were as Mr. Mill represents it ; let us suppose for a moment that persons of scientific education were unanimous in holding, that there has been no well- authenticated case of a breach in the uniformity of nature. What inference could be drawn from this ? Be it observed that the number of natural agents constantly at work is incalculably large ; and that the observed cases of uni- formity in their action must be immeasurably fewer than one thousandth of the whole. Scientific men, we assume for the moment, have discovered that in a certain proportion of instances immeasurably fewer than one thousandth of the whole a certain fact has prevailed ; the fact of uni- 72 The Philosophy of Theism. forinity : and they have not found a single instance in which that fact does not prevail. Are they justified, we ask, in inferring from these premisses that the fact is universal ? Surely the question answers itself. Let us make a very grotesque supposition, in which however the conclusion would really be tried according to the arguments adduced. In some desert of Africa there is an enormous connected edifice surrounding some vast space, in which dwell certain reasonable beings who are unable to leave the enclosure. In this edifice are more than a thousand chambers, which some years ago were entirely locked up, and the keys no one knew where. By constant diligence twenty-five keys have been found, out of the whole number ; and the corre- sponding chambers, situated promiscuously throughout the edifice, have been opened. Each chamber, when examined, is found to be in the precise shape of a dodecahedron. Are the inhabitants justified on that account in holding with certitude, that the remaining 975 chambers are built on the same plan ? We cannot fancy that Mr. Mill would answer in the affirmative : yet otherwise how will his reasoning stand ? But, secondly, it is as far as possible from being true that men of scientific education are unanimous in holding that there has been no well-authenticated case of breach in the uniformity of nature. On the contrary, even to this day the majority of such persons believe in Christianity, and hold the miracles revealed in Scripture to be on the whole accurately reported. The majority of scientific men believe that, at one time, persons on whom the shadow of Peter passed were thereby freed from their infirmities ; and that, at another time, garments brought from the body of Paul expelled sickness and demoniacal possession (Acts v. 15 ; xix. 12). Will Mr. Mill allege that S. Peter's shadow, or that garments from S. Paul's body, were the physical cause of a cure, as lotions and bandages might be ? Of course Mr. Mill's Denial of Necessary Truth. 73 not. Here then is a series of physical phenomena, result- ing without physical cause; and Catholics to this day consider that breaches in the uniformity of nature are matters of every-day occurrence.* Even then if it were true it seems to us (as we have already said) most untrue that Mr. Mill's conclusion legitimately follows from his premisses, still he cannot even approximate to establishing those premisses, until he have first disproved Catholicity and next disproved the whole truth of Christianity. But the strongest objection against the sufficiency of Mr. Mill's argument still remains to be stated. " All our interest," says Mr. Bain most truly, " is concentrated on what is yet to be ; the present and the past are of value only as a clue to the events that are to come" Let us even suppose then for argument's sake, that Mr. Mill had fully proved the past and present uniformity of nature : still the main difficulty would continue ; viz. how he proposes to show that such uniformity will last one moment beyond the present. It is quite an elementary remark that, whenever a proposition is grounded on mere experience, nothing * In the following passage F. Newman does but express what is held by all thoughtful Catholics who are at all well acquainted with the facts of their religion. We italicize one or two sentences : " Putting out of the question the hypothesis of unknown laws of nature (which is an evasion from the force of any proof) I think it impossible to withstand the evidence which is brought for the liquefaction of the blood of S. Januarius at Naples, and for the motion of the eyes of the pictures of the Madonna iu the Roman States. I see no reason to doubt the material <>f the Lombard Crown at Monza ; and I do not see why the Holy Coat at Treves may not have been what it professes to be. I firmly believe that por- tions of the True Cross are at Rome and elsewhere, that the Crib of Bethle- hem is at Rome, and the bodies of S. Peter and S. Paul also. I believe tlmt ut Rome too lies S. Stephen, that S. Matthew lies at Salerno, and S. Andrew at Amalfi. I firmly believe that the relic* of the saint* arc fining innumerable, miracles and graces daily, and that it needs only for a Catholic- to show devo- tion to any saint in order to receive special benefits from his intercession. I firmly believe that saints in their lifetime have before now rained tin: dnid In life, crofted the sea without vewl*, multiplied ijrain and bread, cured in- curable diwaw*, and stopped the operation of the laws of the universe in it multitude of ways." (" lectures on Catholicism in England," p. ii'.iSJ 74 The Ph'do8ophy of Theimn, whatever can be known or even guessed concerning its truth, except within the reach of possible observation. For this very reason, Mr. Mill professes himself unable to know, or even to assign any kind of probability to the supposi- tion, that nature proceeds on uniform laws in distant stellar regions. But plainly there are conditions of time, as well as of space, which preclude the possibility of observation ; and it is as simply impossible for men to know from mere experience what will take place on earth to-morrow, as to know from mere experience what takes place in the planet Jupiter to-day. In considering the question "on what grounds we expect that the sun will rise to-morrow," Mr. Mill (" Logic," vol. ii. p. 80) falls into a mistake very unusual with him ; for he totally misapprehends the difficulty which he has to encounter. He argues we think quite successfully that there is a probability amounting to practical certainty that the sun will rise to-morrow, on the hypothesis that the uni- formity of nature so long continues. But the question he has to face is, what reason can he have for knowing, or even guessing, that the uniformity of nature will so long con- tinue ? And to this, the true question at issue, he does not so much as attempt a reply. Notwithstanding the disclaimer, with which we started, our recent course of argument may have led unwary readers to fancy, that we have been in some way disparaging the trustworthiness and certainty of physical science. So far is this from being so, that on the contrary such trust- worthiness and certainty constitute the major premiss of our syllogism. That syllogism runs as follows. The declarations of physical science are absolutely trustworthy and certain : but if there were no human knowledge inde- pendent of human experience, they would not be trustworthy and certain ; consequently it is untrue that there is no human knowledge independent of human experience. In Mr. Mill's Denial of Necessary Truth.- 75 other words, that doctrine of phenomenism, which in some sense idolizes physical science, is in real truth fatal to the object of its idolatry. Here we conclude for the present. This essay has con- sisted of two distinct portions : in the former of these we have purported to prove against Mr. Mill, on grounds of reason, the existence of certain necessary truths ; while in the latter portion we have set forth some general considera- tions, which tell importantly, as we think, against the doctrine of phenomenism. These considerations may sufficiently be summed up as follows. Phenomenism, taken in its full extent, teaches primarily, that experience is the only legitimate foundation for certitude ; and teaches secondarily, as an inference from this, that there is no necessary truth humanly cognizable as such. We have replied firstly, as to intuitional truths in general, that (by Mr. Mill's own admission) no experience is so much as possible, unless a large number of truths be assumed, which are not known by experience ; viz. truths testified by memory. And we have replied secondly, as to necessary truths in particular, that unless necessary truths were cog- nizable, experimental science could not so much as exist. Our ultimate purpose however in these essays, as we have said, is to draw out, as completely as we can, the philosophical argument for Theism. But it does not follow, because Mr. Mill's phenomenism is false, that therefore Theism is true ; on the contrary, for the full establishment of that fundamental dogma, it will be necessary to accumu- late a large number of philosophical premisses. This we hope to perform in future essays. III. MR. MILL ON THE FOUNDATION OF MORALITY.* IN our last essay we argued against Mr. Mill, that mathematical truths possess the attribute of " necessity ; " and in this we are to argue against him, that moral truths also are of the same kind. We have done im- portant service, we consider, in our previous paper, not only towards the particular conclusion there advocated, but towards the conclusion also which we are now to main- tain. The doctrine that there are truths possessing that very singular quality expressed by the term " necessary "- this doctrine is a priori both so startling, and also pregnant with consequences so momentous, that the philosopher may well require absolutely irresistible evidence before he will accept it. This was our reason for placing mathe- matical truths in the very front of our controversial position; because they afford so much less room than others for confusion and equivocalness, that their " neces- sary " character is on that account more irresistibly evident. When the philosopher is once obliged to admit that there are propositions of this character, it is a matter of com- parative detail which they are. This, therefore, is the * An Ensay in aid of a Grammar of Assent. By JOHN HENRY NEWMAN, D.D., of the Oratory. London : Burns, Gates, & Co. Dissertations and Discussions. By JOHN STUART MILL. London : J. W. Parker. Utilitarianism. By JOHN STUART MILL. London : Longmans. The Emotions and the Will. Chap. XV. : Tlie Moral Seme. By ALEXANDER BAIN, A.M. London: J. W. Parker. Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 77 position of advantage from which we approach our present theme. But from another point of view, we are less favourably circumstanced in our present than in our former under- taking. There is no difference of opinion worth mentioning as to what those propositions are which are called mathe- matical axioms : and there are only therefore two possible alternatives ; viz. whether those axioms are, or are not, self- evidently necessary. All phenomenists are on one side, and all objectivists, as a matter of course, on the other. But those who hold most strongly the "necessary" cha- racter of moral science differ nevertheless importantly from each other, as to what are those axioms on which the science is founded. Whatever theory we adopt, we must necessarily have for our opponents, not only all pheno- menists, but a large number of objectivists also. Even among Catholics there are some subordinate differences on the subject ; and before we enter on our reply to Mr. Mill, there are three little matters of domestic controversy which we must briefly consider, in order to make clear the precise position which is to be our controversial standpoint. The first of these relates to a phrase which we have more than once used. We are here assuming for the moment, what we are afterwards to defend against Mr. Mill, that there are certain moral axioms intuitively known : * and we have frequently used the phrase "moral faculty " to express that mental faculty whereby such axioms are cognized. F. Liberatore (Ethica, n. 82) under- stands this phrase to imply, that moral truths are not discerned by the intellect and reason, but assumed by blind propension and instinct. With great deference to so distinguished a writer, we must nevertheless say that this seems to us a complete misapprehension of Eeid's and * I5y the term "axioms" are hero meant " sclf-evulently necessary truths." 7S The Philosophy of Tfteism. Hutcheson's meaning ; and it is certainly removed to the greatest possible degree from our own. By the phrase "moral faculty" we mean neither more nor less (as we have said) than the power, which resides in man's intellect, of cognizing moral axioms with self-evident certitude. For various reasons, it seems to us of extreme importance that attention should be carefully fixed on this power ; and we think it very desirable, therefore, to give it a special name.* F. Newman habitually uses the word " conscience " to express substantially the same thing ; nor could any word be better adapted to the purpose, so far as regards the ordinary usage of Englishmen. Our own difficulty in so using it arises from the circumstance, that the word " con- scientia " has a theological sense, importantly different from F. Newman's, and yet not so far removed from it as to prevent real danger of one being confused with the other. The theological word " conscientia " does not commonly express an intellectual power or habit; but an existing declaration of the intellect, as to the morality (hie et nunc) of this or that particular act: and so one hears of a " correct " or an " erroneous," of a " certain " or a " doubt- ful" conscience. Then again, and more importantly, its office is the cognition, not so much of moral axioms as of moral conclusions : and the first premisses too on which it proceeds, are not merely moral axioms, but include God's positive precepts, the Church's interpretation of the Divine Law, and the Church's positive commands. We cannot, then, but think it will be more conducive to clearness if we avoid using this word in F, Newman's sense. We now proceed to our second preliminary. It is a very prominent doctrine of F. Newman's, that "con- * It may be worth while also to cite Liberatore's own statement " hominem individuum universamque societatem ad perfectionem moralem jugiter amplificandam rt naturse incitari, atque ideo typo quodam honestatis in animis insculpto gaudere, quo dijudicet quibus defectibus liberal! et quibus bonis augeri debeat." (lutroductio ad Ethicam, art. iii.) Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 79 science " testifies emphatically God's existence. And very many Catholic writers hold (as will be presently seen) that whenever reason notifies to me the intrinsic turpitude of this or that act, it thereupon notifies to me the existence of some Supreme Legislator, who forbids it. This doctrine, however, may be advocated in two essentially different senses. On the one hand, it may merely be alleged that when- ever reason notifies to me the intrinsic moral turpitude of this or that act, it further notifies, by most prompt and immediate consequence, the prohibition of that act by some Supreme Legislator. We incline to think that such is F. Newman's meaning. At all events, we ourselves heartily accept this doctrine, and are to maintain it in the course of our present article. But, on the other hand, it may be alleged that the idea itself "moral turpitude" is either identical with, or includes, that of "prohibition by a Supreme Legislator." We cannot assent to such a proposition. We accept S. Ignatius's teaching in the " Spiritual Exercises," that evil acts possess a " fceditas et nequitia " of their own, " ex natura sua, vel si prohibita non essent." We follow Suarez in holding, that they would be "mala, peccata, culpabilia," even if (per irnpossibile) there existed no law strictly so called forbidding them. We follow Vasquez, Bellarmine, Lessius, and other eminent theologians, in their use of similar expressions.* We are not here arguing * A considerable number of passages to this effect have been cited by Dr. Ward, in his " Philosophical Introduction," from the most eminent Catholic theologians and philosophers, including the expressions mentioned in the text (pp. 42D-190). Since that work was published, the phrase used in it " independent morulity '' has been adopted by some French infidels to express certain tenets, which we consider to be us philosophically de- spicable as they are morally detestable. But the phrase had imt bi-en dirtied, to his knowledge at least, when Dr. Ward used it. F. Chaste], S..1. (Dr. Ward, p. 4H1) raises the question, whether " there is n moral law iii'l>/n- 'Imtly of all Divine law," and proceeds to answer it in the iillirmativr. Juarez (ib. p. Iu3, says, " dictamina rationis natural is, in qiiibus luuc lex 80 The Philosophy of TJieism. against those excellent Catholics who think otherwise : * we are hut explaining the position we shall assume, in this part of our controversy against Mr. Mill. Thirdly, the question has been raised among Catholics, whether there can he obligation, properly so called, apart from man's knowledge of a Supreme Legislator. So far as this question is distinct from the preceding, it seems to us purely verbal. If, by saying that act A is of obligation, you only mean that its omission would be culpable and sinful, we hold (consistently with our previous remarks) that there may be true obligation, without reference to a Legislator's prohibition. So F. Chastel says, " there would still remain moral obligation, real duty, though one made abstraction of God and religion." On the other hand, if the term be understood as implying the correlative act of a Legislator who obliges, of course there can be no obligation without full means of knowing such a Legislator. Without further delay, let us set forth the precise issue which we are to join with Mr. Mill. There is a large number of cognizable truths, which may be expressed in one or other of the following shapes. "Act A is morally good ; " " act B is morally bad ; " " act C is morally better than act D." All these, it will be seen, are but different shapes, in which emerges the one fundamental idea called " moral goodness." We will call such judgments, therefore, " moral judgments ; " and the truths cognized in them " moral truths." t Our allegation against Mr. Mill is, that a certain number J of these truths are cognized as self- [naturalis] consistit, sunt intrinsece necessaria et independentia ab omui voluntate etiam Divina." * Dr. Ward has done so in his " Philosophical Introduction," pp. 78-90. t We need hardly say that a " moral judgment " may be mistaken ; and that in that case there is no corresponding " moral truth." J " ' Parentes cole;' 'Deo convenientem cultum exhibe;' 'rationem sensibus ne subjicias;' et alia innumera generis ejusdem." (Liberatore, n. 80.) Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 81 evidently necessary. These we call " moral axioms." Mr. Mill admits, of course, that moral judgments are very frequently elicited ; but, denying as he does the existence of any necessary truths, he denies inclusively that there are moral truths self-evidently necessary. The ground which he often seems to take is that no moral judgments are intuitions, but that all are inferences ; though these infer- ences, he would add, are so readily and imperceptibly drawn, as to be most naturally and almost inevitably mistaken for intuitions. That we may bring this vital question to a distinct issue, it is highly important to dwell at starting on the fundamental idea "moral goodness." There is probably no psychical fact, so pregnant with momentous con- sequences in the existing state of philosophy, as man's pos- session of this idea. Very many philosophers hold, that it is complex and resolvable accordingly into simpler elements ; we contend earnestly and confidently that it is simple. The strong bias of our opinion is, that Mr. Mill (as we shall explain in a later part of our essay) so far agrees with ourselves ; though his expression of doctrine would no doubt be importantly different. It is very possible, however, that the case may be otherwise ; and that he may regard the idea before us as consisting of simpler elements. In that case he must consistently say, that " morally good," as applied to human acts, means neither more nor less than "conducive to general enjoyment." Provisionally, therefore, we shall assume this as Mr. Mill's position. Now, this is an issue, one would think, which must admit of speedy and definite decision : for there is perhaps no one idea which so constantly meets one at every turn, whether in literature or conversation, as that of " morally good" with its correlatives. "I am bound to do what I am paid for doing;" " how conscientious a man 11 is!" 82 TJic Philosophy of TItcism. " K behaved in that matter with much more uprightness than L ; " " M is an undeniable scoundrel ; " "no praise can be too great for N's disinterested benevolence and self- sacrifice; " " whatever God commands, men of course are bound to do." At this moment we are in no way concerned with the truth or falsehood of such propositions, but ex- clusively with their meaning. Our readers will see at once, that these judgments, and a thousand others of daily occurrence, contain unmistakably the idea " morally good," under different aspects ; and if they consider the matter with any care they will further see, that this idea is as distinct from the idea " conducive to general enjoyment," as any one can possibly be from any other. This is the proposition which we now wish to illustrate and establish. Take the last instance we gave : " whatever God com- mands, a man is bound to do ; " or, in other words, " what- ever God commands, a man acts morally ill in failing to do." Does the Theist mean, by this judgment, that the_ individual's disobedience to God militates against general enjoyment ? This latter statement may or may not be true ; but it is no more equivalent to the former, than it is to a geometrical axiom. Or let us take such a case as would be most favourable to Mr. Mill's argument ; the case of one whom he would regard as amongst the greatest benefactors of his species. "How noble," Mr. Mill would say, "was the self-sacrificing generosity of Howard the philanthro- pist ! " Would he merely mean by this, that Howard's generosity conduced immensely to general enjoyment ? He would be the first indignantly to disclaim so poor an inter- pretation of his words. By the term "noble," then, "or "morally good," Mr. Mill means much more than "con- ducive to general enjoyment." But the particular idea " moral evil " deserves our especial consideration, as exhibiting in clearest light the Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 83 peculiar character of moral judgments. Take any very obvious case of wickedness. Consider, e.g., the judgment elicited by David concerning his own past course of action, when Nathan had said to him, " Thou art the man." Or suppose I had been guilty of such conduct in an exaggerated shape, as that ascribed to Lord Bacon (truly or falsely) by Lord Macaulay. A politician of high and unblemished moral character, with whose political principles I am heartily in accordance, has admitted me to his friendship and trusted me with his dearest secrets. I find, however, as time goes on, that my best chance of advancement lies in attach- ing myself to the opposite side. Filled with passionate desire for such advancement, I make political capital by disclosing my friend's confidences to his opponents ; and I embark heartily in a course of political enterprise, which has for its end his ruin. As I am about to reap the worldly fruit of my labours, I am seized with a violent illness : and in the tedious hours of slow recovery, I "enter into myself," to use the expression of ascetical writers ; I bitterly repent the past ; I judge that my suc- cessive acts have been " sinful," " wicked." I judge, as a consequence of this, that I have rendered myself worthy of punishment ; that if there be a Moral Governor of the Universe, He views my conduct with detestation ; etc. We are not at this moment alleging that these various judgments are true, but only considering their correct analysis. And surely Mr. Mill will not on reflection maintain, that when I am pondering on the moral turpitude of my past conduct, I am in fact merely thinking of its evil effects on general enjoyment. Doubtless, when I reflect on the malitia of having supported a political cause which I deem unsound, I base this malitia greatly on the evil which I have thereby tried to inflict on my country ; but I base it also in part on the concomitant judgment, that to inflict such injury is intrinsically evil. And when I reflect on the malitia of my The Philosophy of Theism. ingratitude, and of my having perfidiously violated my friend's confidence, in all probability the question does not ever so distantly present itself, whether general enjoy- ment is promoted or retarded by such practices. We are arguing against the theory which we provision- ally ascribe to Mr. Mill ; viz. that the idea " morally good " is equivalent with the idea " conducive to general enjoy- ment." But it seems to us that this whole matter may be clenched, so as to render all evasion impossible. If this theory were true, it w r ould be a simply tautologous pro- position to say, that " conduct, known by the agent as adverse to general enjoyment, is morally evil." This pro- position, we say, would be as simply tautologous, as the proposition that "two mutual friends desire each other's well-being;" or the proposition, that "a hard substance resists muscular pressure." These two latter propositions are really tautologous : for a desire of each other's well- being is expressed by the very term " mutual friends ; " and "resistance to muscular pressure" is expressed by the very term " hard substance." Now, it is an evident logical truth, that the contradictory of a tautologous proposition is simply unmeaning, because its predicate denies that very thing which its subject affirms. (See " Mill on Hamilton," p. 92.) " There are two mutual friends of my acquaintance, who do not desire each other's well-being; " " some hard substances I have met with do not resist muscular pres- sure ; " for any meaning that such propositions convey, we might even better (to use Mr. Mill's illustration) say that " every Humpty Dumpty is an Abracadabra." Let us look again, then, at the proposition, that " conduct, known by the agent as averse to general enjoyment, is morally evil." If this proposition were tautologous, its contradictory would be unmeaning; it would be simply unmeaning to say, that " some conduct, known by the agent as averse to general enjoyment, may be morally good." Will Mr. Mill him- Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 85 self say that this is unmeaning? On the contrary, the energetic protest with which he would encounter its enunciation, sufficiently evinces how clearly he apprehends its tenor. Indeed, Mr, Mill himself, in a very remarkable passage which we shall quote at length before we conclude, contra- dicts the doctrine which we are here opposing. He says in effect, that it would be morally better for all mankind to undergo eternal torment than to worship such or such a being, whom he imagines and describes. Now, most cer- tainly eternal torment, endured by all mankind, is less con- ducive to general enjoyment than would be the worship of such a being; and Mr. Mill does not therefore consider " morally good " as synonymous with " conducive to general enjoyment." Arguments entirely similar to those which we have here given would equally suffice to disprove any other analysis which might be attempted, of the idea " morally good ; " and we conclude, therefore, that this idea is simple and incapable of analysis. We are now in a position to consider satisfactorily the direct point at issue : the self-evident necessity of certain moral truths. Let us go back to the moral judgments on which we have already dwelt ; the moral judgments, elicited on his sick-bed by the recently unscrupulous politician. Take any one of their number: for instance, "my divulging what my friend told me in confidence, was morally evil." "We maintain that this judgment is the cognition of a self- evidently necessary truth. On this point let us refer to the remarks we made in our second essay, on the notes of a self-cvidently necessary truth, and let us apply them to the case before us. It is known to me by my very idea of this my act- so soon as I choose carefully to consider it that it was morally evil ; I intuc irresistibly, that in no possible sphere 1 80 The Philosophy of Theism. of existence the relevant circumstances remaining un- changed could such an act be otherwise ; that omnipotence itself could not prevent such an act from being intrinsically base and abominable.* In other words, if it be a self- evidently necessary truth (see pp. 86, 37 of .our last essay) that a trilateral figure is triangular, it is no less indubi- tably a self-evidently necessary truth, that such an act as we are considering is morally evil. How may we consider Mr. Mill to stand in reference to this argument ? He agrees with us, of course, that mankind do again and again form legitimately, and with good reason, what we have called "moral judgments: " judgments re- ducible to the type " act A is morally good; " or " act B is morally evil ; " or " act C is morally better than act D." He adds, however, what is quite true, that we have no right to consider any of these judgments intuitive, until we have clearly shown that they are not inferential : for, as he most justly observes, inferences from experience are often so obviously and spontaneously drawn, that unless we are very wary we may most easily mistake them for intuitions. We * We do not for a moment forget the power, possessed by God, of changing (as theologians express it) the " materiu " of the Natural Law ; but the existence of this power, so far from conflicting with, on the contrary coufirms, what is said in the text. The classical instance in point is the command imposed by God on Abraham, of sacrificing his son ; and what all Catholic theologians say is this. God, as the Creator of mankind, could (without disparagement of His sanctity) inflict death on Isaac or on any one else ; and it is no more repugnant to His Attributes that He should do this by human intermediation, than that He should do it directly. God's command, then, intrinsically changed the circumstances of Abraham's act, if the morality of the act was intrinsically necessary, and external to the sphere of God's Power. It would have been intrinsically wrong in Abraham, if he had refused to slay Isaac when commanded to do so as God's vicegerent; and God Himself could not make such refusal innocent. On the other hand, it would have been no less necessarily wrong to tlay Isaac on his own authority ; and God Himself could not make such slaughter innocent. It should be added, that no such " mutatio inateriaj " can affect the internal acts and dispositions of the will. For instance, God could not possibly command His reasonable creatures to hate each other ; and still less to hate Himself. Dr. Ward has stated this doctrine at length as clearly as he could, " Philosophical Introduction," pp. KJ5-1UO. Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 87 are next, therefore, to show, that there are indubitably some moral judgments, which are not inferential. Our argument runs thus. If the idea "morally good" be really simple as we consider ourselves to have now conclusively established then that idea cannot possibly be contained in the conclu- sion of any syllogism, unless it be expressly found in one of the premisses.* Take, then, any one of those moral judg- ments, which Mr. Mill admits to be legitimately formed. If he alleges that that judgment is an inference as indeed it very possibly may be he does but shift his difficulty, and in no respect lessens it. If the judgment be really the conclusion of a syllogism, then, as we have said, that syl- logism must contain some other moral judgment as one of its premisses. If this premiss be itself a conclusion, we are thrown back on an earlier moral premiss, until at length we come to some moral judgment, which is immediate and not inferential. If this primary moral premiss be not cognizable as true, then neither is the ultimate conclusion so cognizable : and this is against the hypothesis ; for Mr. Mill admits that many moral judgments are cogniz- able as true, and it is one of these which we are here considering. If, on the other hand, the primary moral premiss be cognizable as true, then a moral proposition is cognizable as true, which is not inferred from experi- ence ; and Mr. Mill is obliged to abandon the keystone of his position. It seems to us, then, that the real issue between Mr. Mill and ourselves turns on the question, whether the idea " morally good " be capable of analysis. If it means " con- ducive to general enjoyment," then no doubt all moral judgments are inferential and founded on experience ; but * If " morally pood" were a complex idea, it mif;ht lie contained. <>f course, in the conclusion of a syllogism, without appearing iu the pK'inif.-ea except in its cvnttitucnt elements. 88 TJte Philosophy of Tltcixni. if it be incapable of analysis, then a certain number of moral judgments must be intuitive. And if Mr. Mill once admits that they are intuitive, he will certainly find no difficulty in further admitting, that they are cognitions of self-evidently necessary truths. \Ve have worded our argument throughout, in harmony with the opinion which to us seems true (see our last essay, pp. 48, 49), that axioms are first intued in the individual case, though capable of being universalized. According to this view, what Catholics call " the first prin- ciples " of morality, are simply these universalized axioms. Firstly, for instance, I intue, as a self-evidently necessary truth, that my own betrayal of my friend's confidence was intrinsically wicked ; and I then further intue, as self- evidently necessary, that all such betrayal in really analogous circumstances possesses the same evil quality. Those philosophers, on the contrary, who hold that axioms are always intued in the universal, will regard every individual moral judgment as the conclusion of syllogistic reasoning, whereof some universal moral axiom has been a premiss. But their substantial argument against Mr. Mill may be precisely the same as our own. Moreover, we have assumed throughout no other datum, except the one for which we argued in the first of these essays ; viz. that whatever my cognitive faculties indubi- tably avouch, is infallibly true. The strong bias of our own opinion is, that this is the very doctrine which Mr. Mill will call in question; but most certainly he has no right to do so. On one hand, no experience is possible to me I have no knowledge whatever except of my present consciousness unless I first unreservedly believe the truth of whatever my memory distinctly declares ; while on the other hand (as we have more than once pointed out), Mr. Mill fully admits that I have no ground whatever for this belief, except the present Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 89 avouckment of my faculties. If my faculties convey to me infallible knowledge when they distinctly declare to me a certain past experience, no less must they convey to me infallible knowledge, when they declare to me (if they do declare) the self-evident necessity of certain moral truths. If I do not firmly trust them in the latter avouch- ment, I have no right firmly to trust them in the former. Nay, I have really stronger grounds for accepting the distinct declarations of my moral faculty than the distinct declara- tions of my memory. In the first place intrinsically, it would be in some sense less utterly impossible to believe that I never did betray my friend's confidence, than to believe that such betrayal is not morally detestable. And in the second place extrinsically, I find these obvious moral judg- ments confirmed by every one I meet : whereas for the trustworthiness of my memory, I can have no external warrant at all ; because my absolute trust in its testimony is a strictly requisite preliminary condition, in order that I may know or even guess what any one human being thinks or says. But we are to meet Mr. Mill in detail on this point a few pages hence. This datum, then, being assumed, we consider that we have built thereon an argument absolutely irrefragable. We consider our reasoning to have established conclusive!}', (1) that the idea " morally good " is incapable of analysis ; and (2) that various moral judgments are cognitions of self- evidently necessary truths. We may add, that if the Catholic reader desires to apprehend the relation which exists between necessary truth and the One Necessary Being, we would refer him to the Dublin Ilcvicw for July, 1809, pp. 153, 154. We there stated with hearty con- currence F. Kleutgen's doctrine, that all necessary truths are founded on God; that they are what they are, because God is what He is. Our next thesis is a very simple one ; and indeed almost 90 The Philosophy of Theism. (if not altogether) tautologous. All acts, morally good, are " admirable " and " praiseworthy ; " all acts, morally evil, are " the reverse of admirable " and " blameworthy ; " all acts are more admirable and more praiseworthy in proportion as they are morally better. But now, lastly in order to express the whole doctrine which we would place before our readers we must make a very important supplement to what has hitherto been said. Let us renew our old picture. I ain lying on a bed of illness, and looking back remorsefully on my shameful violation of my friend's confidence, and on a life of dis- honest practices directed (as I myself knew) to the detriment of my country's highest interests. Not only I intue that a large number of my past acts have been morally evil, but I further intue that they violated the command of some living Personal Being.* This is the further thesis, which we are now to advocate. The general axiom, we maintain, is cognizable, that all morally evil acts are prohibited by some living Personal Being. Now, here let us distinctly explain our meaning. We by no means say on the contrary, in an earlier part of our article we have denied that the idea " morally evil " either includes or is equivalent with the idea " forbidden by some living Personal Being." The predicate of an axiom is not commonly included in, or equivalent with, the * "Ipsa ratio natriralis . . . discernendo actiones convenientes aut repugnantes naturae humanse, prohibitionem vel imperium divinum nobis offert." (Liberatore, Ethica, n. 79.) " Hoc" dictamen rationis " sic auclitu quodam interne homo percipit, ut veie imperio aliquo se astrinpi sentiat. . . . Cui voci intrinsecus prsocipienti si quis non pareat, sic stimulis angitur ... ut ... ipsemet se accuset et arguat et pcenam a supremd quddam potestate sibi infligendum expectet" (ib. n. 80). "Semper in illis " judiciis practicis "involvitur obscurus saltern et indistinctus conceptus alicujus occultse potestalis, . . . quae objective spectata non est nisi l)eus " (ib. n. 83). On the other hand: " Divina voluutas bonitatem vel malitiam actionibus impertire non posset, nisi ante prxsumalur bouum esse et honestum Deo prsecipienti parere, turpe et illicitum reluctari. Hoc non snpposito, actio tuauebit indifferent ctiam post Dei jussum vtl prohibitionem " (ib. n. 27). Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 91 idea of its subject ; for were it so, there would be no axioms except tautologies. Take the parallel case, on which we insisted in our last essay : " all trilaterals are triangular." So far is it from being true (as we there pointed out) that triangularity is included in the idea of trilateralness, that, on the contrary, I call a figure " trilateral " in the fullest sense of that word, before I have so much as considered any question as to the number of its angles. Nevertheless the proposition is axiomatic : because, to use F. Kleutgen's expression, " by merely considering the idea of the subject and predicate, I come to see that there exists between them that relation which the proposition expresses ; " or (as we ourselves expressed the same thought) because, from my very conception of a trilateral, I know its triangularity. This, then, is what we maintain in the present instance. If after such an ill-spent life as we have supposed, while lying on my sick-bed, I ponder in anguish of soul the idea "morally evil" as truly applicable to so many of my past acts, I find myself to know, by my very conception of that attribute, that these acts have been acts of rebellion against some living personal authority, external to myself. "We make this allegation, on the sole possible and the abundantly sufficient ground of an appeal to the indubitable facts of human nature. We say, "external to myself;" because to say merely that the lower part of my nature has rebelled against the higher, is absurdly inadequate to express my deep conviction. And we say "living personal authority," because it is still more absurd to suppose that there can be rebellion against an impersonal thing ; least of all against an abstraction, which is in fact nothing at all. I intue, then, the axiom, that all morally evil acts are also forbidden me by some living personal authority external to myself. It is of vital moment here to muke manifest how com- pletely distinct are the t\vo ideas; ''morally evil " on one 92 The Philosophy of Theism. hand, and " prohibited by a Personal Being " on the other. For this purpose, let us take the following proposition : "to do what is prohibited by my Creator is to do an act morally evil." A moment's consideration will show that this proposition has an entirely distinct sense from the purely tautological one, that " what is prohibited by my Creator is prohibited by a Personal Being." The term " morally evil " expresses an idea entirely external to, over and above, the idea expressed by the term " prohibited by a Personal Being." And as, on the one hand, it is no tautology, but an axiom, that "to do what is prohibited by my Holy Creator is to do an act morally evil ; " so, on tho other hand, we are here urging that it is no tautology, but an axiom, that " all acts morally evil are prohibited by some Personal Being." But further, as Viva argues,* this Personal Being has on me such paramount claims, that though all other beings in the universe solicited me in an opposite direction, my obligation would in no degree be affected, of submitting myself unreservedly to His command. His Will, then, is more peremptorily authoritative than the united will of all existent or possible beings who are not He. Nay, further and this is put by F. Franzelin t moral laws hold good for all persons existent or possible ; all other persons, therefore, existent or possible, are as unreservedly subject to His command as I am. Consequently He is no less than Supreme Legislator of the universe. F. Kleutgen expresses substantially the same doctrine with Viva and Franzelin, where he says that, "when we vividly represent to ourselves our imperfection and dependence," " God makes Himself felt within us by His moral law, as an August Power to which we are subject." * Treating the condemned proposition on " philosophical sin." t " De Deo Uno," p. 52. Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 93 But there are further facts of human nature to which F. Newman conclusively appeals, as showing how universal and how undeniably intuitive is man's conviction, that acts morally evil are offences against a Supreme Euler. We will remind our readers indeed of what we have already said concerning F. Newman's use of the word " conscience." But we need hardly beg them to observe how singularly his remarks combine exquisite beauty of expression with strong and irresistible appeal to facts. The italics are our own. In consequence of this prerogative of dictating and command- ing, which is of its essence, Conscience has an intimate bearing on our affections and emotions, leading us to reverence and awe, hope and fear, especially fear. . . . No fear is felt by any one who recognizes that his conduct has not been beautiful, though he may be mortified at himself, if perhaps he has thereby forfeited some advantage ; but, if he has been betrayed into any kind of immorality, he has a lively sense of respon- sibility and guilt, though the act be no offence against society ; of distress and apprehension, even though it may be of present service to him ; of compunction and regret, though in itself it be most pleasurable ; of confusion of face, thouyh it may have no witnesses. These various perturbations of mind, which are characteristic of a bad conscience, and may be very considerable ; self-reproach, poignant shame, haunting remorse, chill dismay at the prospect of the future ; and their contraries, when the conscience is good, as real though less forcible, self-approval, inward peace, lightness of heart, and the like ; these emotions constitute a generic difference between conscience and our other intellectual senses ; common sense, good sense, sense of ex- pedience, taste, sense of honour, and the like. . . . Conscience always invoices the recognition of a living object, towanh which it is directed. Inanimate things cannot stir unr affections: these are correlative with persons. If, as is the case, wo feel responsibility, are ashamed, are frightened, at trans- gressing the voice of conscience, this implies that there is One to ichom we are responsible, before whom we are ashamed, whose claim upon us wo fear. If, on doing wrong, we feel the same tearful, broken-hearted sorrow which overwhelms us on hurting a mother; if, on doing right, we enjoy the same sunny serenity of 04- TJte Philosophy of Tlieism. mind, the same soothing satisfactory delight, which follows on our receiving praise from a father, we certainly have within us the image of some person, to whom our love and veneration look, in whose smile we find our happiness, for whom we yearn, towards whom we direct our pleadings, in whose anger we are troubled and waste away. These feelings in us are such as require for their exciting cause an intelligent being : we are not affectionate towards a stone, nor do we feel shame before a horse or a dog ; we have no remorse or compunction on breaking mere human law ; yet, so it is, conscience excites all these painful emotions, confusion, foreboding, self-condemnation ; and, on the other hand, it sheds upon us a deep peace, a sense of security, a resignation, and a hope, which there is no sensible, no earthly object to elicit. " The wicked flees, when no one pursueth ; " then why does he flee ? whence his terror ? Who is it that he sees in solitude, in darkness, in the hidden chambers of his heart ? If the cause of these emotions does not belong to this visible world, the Object to which his perception is directed must be Supernatural and Divine ; and thus the phenomena of Conscience, as a dictate, avail to impress the imagination with the picture of a Supreme Governor, a Judge, holy, just, powerful, all-seeing, retributive ; and is the creative principle of religion (pp. 104-7). We affirm then, as an axiom, that all acts morally evil are prohibited by some Living Person external to the agent ; and we affirm as an obvious inference, that this Person is Supreme Legislator of the Universe.* "We may sufficiently sum up what we have now main- * It seems to us (speaking with all diffidence) lhat the view expressed hy us in the text is serviceable, on two different doctrinal heads, in harmonizing Catholic writers with themselves, with each other, and with facts. Thus firstly Liberatore, Dmowski, and (we think) all modern Catholic philosophers, hold, on the one hand, that God (according to human modes of conception) cognizes any given act as intrinsically evil, antecedently to prohibiting it by the Natural Law ; and yet they hold that, in intuing its moral evil, men spontaneously and inevitably cognize the fact of its being prohibited by some Supreme Legislator. It is not easy to see how these statements can be combined, except according to the exposition which we have drawn out. Then, for another matter of doctrine. The vast majority of theologians follow S. Thomas in holding, that the existence of God is not " per se nota quoad nos ; " though they regard it as a truth, Reducible from first prin- ciples by a very obvious and immediate consequence. On the other hand, it Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 95 tained, in three propositions : (1) the idea "morally good " or " morally evil " is simple and incapable of analysis ; (2) there are various human acts self-evidently known to be morally evil; (3) such acts are further known to be prohibited by a Supreme Ruler of the Universe. If Mr. Mill admitted the two former of these propositions, he would feel no difficulty in the third : in considering, there- fore, the objections he may be expected to bring against our doctrine, we will for brevity's sake dismiss from considera- tion the last of our three above-named theses. These objections, as in other similar instances, may be of two different kinds : they may be objections against the reasoning adduced for our conclusion, or they may be objections against the conclusion itself. Of the former kind, there is only one which occurs to us as possible ; and we believe this to be the very objection on which Mr. Mill will mainly insist. Take the judgment, applied to some very obviously immoral act " act B is morally evil." Mr. Mill may probably admit, both that this judgment is immediate, and also that the idea " morally evil " is perfectly simple : yet he may allege that such an avouch- ment is not intuitive, because it would not have issued from the mind at the time when the mind's revelations were in their pristine purity . The quality of immediately* eliciting on occasion this or that moral judgment, however indubitably now possessed, may be no part (Mr. Mill will say) of the mind's original constitution , but on the contrary may result, by natural process, from various experiences, is admitted by all, that a large number of moral axioms are self-evident ami intuitively known ; while yet those very writers, who deny that God's existence is " per se nota quoad nos," say that some knowledge of God is included in the cognition of a moral axiom. According to the view given in 'our text, the knowledge of a Supreme Legislator of the Universe is an infer fnrf though a very prompt and obvious one from the self-evident truths of morality. * We need hardly say that we hero use the word " immediately " as opposed to " inferential!)-." 9G The Philosophy of Theism. through which every man has passed.* Consequently (so be will conclude) this subjective persuasion is no guarantee whatever of objective truth. Such an objection brings us back to certain expressions of Mr. Mill's, on which we animadverted in the first of these essays, and which here again require coniment.t But we must preface this com- ment by a brief exposition of terminology. We believe there is no difference whatever, among those philosophers who use the word "intuition," as to the signification of that word. Of course nothing could be known at all unless some truths were known immediately and by their own light ; and these are called " first truths." Moreover, it is absolutely indubitable, that the facts of " consciousness " properly so called the mental phenomena which I experience at the present moment are " first truths " to me. Now, the word " intuition " is used, by all who do use it, to express those other truths, over and above acts of consciousness, which are known to me immediately and by their own light. Sir W. Hamilton, however, uses the expression " acts of consciousness " to express all first truths : and we think never was there a mode of speech more exquisitely infelicitous, more singularly adapted to introduce equivocation and perplexity, and to surround the whole subject with almost impenetrable fog. Mr. Mill, while justly disapproving this use of language, yet (much to our regret) adopts it for purposes of argument with Sir W. Hamilton (" On Hamilton," p. 193 et alibi) ; and this * It should be explained that, in Mr. Mill's opinion, by a process of what lie calls " mental chemistry," some idea nuiy result from others of the past, while nevertheless in its prevent state it is simple and incapable of analysis. (See "Logic" (seventh edition), vol. ii. p. 437.) He calls such an idea indeed "complex," because (as he considers) it "results from," it has been " generated by," other ideas ; but he adds, that it does not " consist of" simpler ideas, and its true name, therefore, in its present state is surely " simple." t Since we wrote tliat article, we have again examined Mr. Mill's philo- sophical writings, with a social view to this question, and we find hia meaning much more pronounced and unmistakable than we had fancied. Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 97 fact must be remembered in looking at those passages of his, to which we shall presently refer. Let us now, there- fore, pass from this question of words to the question of things. The main thesis of the first essay in this volume, on "Certitude," was, that man's cognitive faculties infallibly testify objective truth ; and, as part of this, that I intui- tively know whatever my mind immediately avouches. "VVe admitted expressly (in full agreement so far with Mr. Mill) that inferential judgments are again and again mistaken for intuitive ones; and in our present article accordingly we have shown (we trust) conclusively, that certain moral judgments are not inferential but immediate. Mr. Mill, however, in various passages goes much further than we have here implied : he affirms that the very thing, which my faculties now immediately declare, is not thereby in- tuitively known, and that I must not accept it as self- evidently true until I can show that it was declared by my intuitive faculties, at the time "when they received their first impressions ; " " at the first beginning of my intel- lectual life;" when they were "in their state of pristine purity." See "On Hamilton," pp. 152, 160, 171, 176, 185 ; " Logic," vol. ii. p. 439. In one place (" On Hamil- ton," p. 173, n.) he repudiates the opinion that man's intuitive faculties admit of development and improvement by means of practice ; and in another (p. 172) implies that no one's intuitive faculties can be trusted, except an infant's " when he first opened his eyes to the light." Now, the answer to all this is really very obvious and conclusive. There is one class of intuitions, of which Mr. Mill heartily admits the existence ; those which arc called acts of memory. In consistency, however, he must maintain that he can trust no avouchmcnts of his memory, however clear and distinct, until he can show that that faculty, " at the first beginning of his intellectual life," VOL. I. II 98 The Philosophy of Tliewm. before it had received " development and education," nay, " when he first opened his eyes to the light," would have been capable of those avouchments. But it is indubitable that he can never prove this ; because, so soon as he attempt* to prove it, he takes for granted at every turn the very thing to be proved, viz. the trustworthiness of his present memory. So long as Mr. Mill adheres to the philosophical tenet which we are opposing, he cannot in consistency have any reasonable ground whatever for trusting his memory ; and unless he trusts his memory, he knows nothing whatever of any kind or description, except only his mental experience of this particular moment. In brief, there is no middle term whatever. Either the mind's present avouchment must be accepted as infallibly declaring objective truth, or blind, hopeless, and universal scepticism is the inevitable lot of mankind. Here, also, we must repeat a remark which we made in our essay on " Certitude." Never was there a philosophical proposition more preposterously unfounded than that which Mr. Mill makes the foundation of his whole philosophy ; viz. that the primordial avouchments of the human mind certainly correspond with objective truth. We may safely challenge him to allege so much as one colourable reason for this proposition, unless he first assumes that the mind's present avouchments are infallibly true. It is this latter proposition which is primarily certain ; and the former proposition has no other evidence whatever, except of inference from the latter. He denies that very truth which alone can supply any reasonable ground for what stands as the sole basis of his intellectual speculations. Our reason for this confident statement will be at once understood by those who have read the essay to which we refer. This is our answer to the objection which Mr. Mill will probably raise. We might have replied to it from an Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 99 entirely different point of view : for we confidently deny the psychological allegation on which it is built ; we confidently deny that men go through any series of experiences, which could by possibility have generated their present moral judgments. On this head we can refer to an unusually able article, contributed to the Macmillan of July, 1869, by Mr. R. H. Hutton, called "A Questionable Parentage of Morals." Mr. Hutton's arguments indeed are directly addressed against a theory ascribed by him to Mr. Herbert Spencer ; * but they apply a longe fortiori to Mr. Mill's. For ourselves, however, we think it better to abstain alto- gether from this psychological question. We thus abstain, in order that our readers' attention may be more un- dividedly fixed on what we consider the glaring unreason- ableness and utterly subversive tendency of that principle of Mr. Mill's, which alone could give any controversial value to such a psychological allegation. Never could we have expected so able a thinker as Mr. Mill to take up a position so relentlessly suicidal. We hold, then, that no such objection will stand for a moment or has so much as the slightest plausibility against the reasoning adduced for our two theses. And since we know of no other objection, we assume that they are conclusively established. We next, therefore, proceed to consider such objections as may be raised against our theses themselves, and no longer against the arguments which we have adduced in their behalf. There is only one of these which impresses us as presenting any even superficial difficulty ; we refer to the divergence of moral standard, which has prevailed in different times and countries. Mr. Bain lays much stress on this in the chapter which we have named at the head of our essay, and which Mr. Mill (in his " Utilitarianism ") commemorates with the warmest * Wo use this form of expression, hccuusc Mr. Spencer afterwards di.s- cliiimcd that theory. 100 The Philosophy of Theism. commendation. Mr. Bain lays stress, e.g., on such points as "the change that has come over men's sentiments on the subject of slavery " (p. 312). He lays stress, again, on the inexhaustible varieties of what may be called ritual morality : on such facts, as that the Mussulman women think it a duty to cover their faces in public (p. 300) ; the men to abstain from wine (p. 301) ; the Hindoos to venerate the cow (p. 808) ; the Buddhists to avoid animal food (ib.). How are such fundamental differences of moral judgment, he asks, consistent with any supposition that the first principles of moral truth are self-evidently known to man- kind as universally and necessarily true ? F. Harper gives the true reply to this obvious objection, in the sixth of his papers contributed to the Month on F. Newman's " Grammar." " First," he says, " I observe with Sir J. Mackintosh, that people may differ as much as they please about what is right and wrong, but they all nevertheless agree that there is something right and some- thing wrong." But further and more importantly, " we have forgotten the influence that the will has over the intellect in moral matters ; and the influence again which passion, affection, prejudice, evil education, custom, have in such subjects over both. By means of these and similar causes, the perception of right and wrong has been blunted, often choked. Still more often it is liable to be misdirected." " These varieties, therefore," he adds, " of popular or national judgment, however extensive, prove nothing against the objective evidence and certitude of moral principles ; or against the possibility of their subjective evidence and certainty, as reflected in the individual conscience when left free to its unbiassed determination and in its right balance." The question, however, is of immeasurably more prominent importance in our controversy with Mr. Mill than it was in F. Harper's criticism of F. Newman ; and we will therefore draw out, at much greater length and in our own way, what Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 101 is substantially identical alike with the doctrine of F. New- man and F. Harper. Firstly, however, we must observe, that phenomenists here are in the habit of trying most unfairly to shift the burden of proof from themselves to their opponents. We allege with confidence that we have demonstratively proved our theses. Unless, therefore, Mr. Bain demonstrates the validity of his objection, he does nothing whatever ; for great probability on one side is simply valueless against proof on the other. At the same time, however, we do not for a moment admit that our antagonists can give even probable ground for the validity of their objection. Then, further, we would point out that they appeal from what is known to what is unknown. I am most intimately aware of my own present or habitual thoughts and feelings : I am also in various degrees well acquainted with those of my friends, my compatriots, my contemporaries. Our antagonists appeal from these, to the sentiments of bar- barous tribes, separated from me most widely by time or place or both, and of whose circumstances I know next to nothing. And they make this appeal on a question in which everything depends on circumstances ; a very little divergence in these often sufficing to change an act from intrinsically evil to intrinsically good. We now proceed to give our own explanation of the facts to which Mr. Bain has appealed ; reminding our readers, however, that it is no business of ours to prove our explanation sufficient, but Mr. Bain's business to prove (if he can) that it is otherwise. We have already conclusively (we trust) established our position ; Mr. Bain has no standing in court, unless he conclusively establishes his. (1) Firstly, then, in one respect the most barbarous nations emphatically confirm our view. As F. llarprr quotes from Mackintosh, they may diiTt-r as to what is right 102 The Philosophy of Theism-. or wrong, but they all agree that there is a right and a wrong. And so it has often been said though the present writer has no such knowledge as would justify him in affirming it from his own researches that every nation, however savage, has some word in its language to express "duty," as distinct from " expediency." Mr. Bain admits throughout, that all those to whom he appeals have that very same idea of what is meant by " right," or " wrong," or "moral obligation," which is possessed by Europeans of the nineteenth century.* It is true that he explains the origin and authority of this idea in a way fundamentally different from our own. But in raising this issue, he is amenable to the court of modern and civilized experience ; and by considering the most undeniable facts of human nature as it exists around us, we are able (as we trust we have shown) conclusively to establish our own doctrine. Nay, (2) the number of moral axioms is by no means inconsiderable which are intued by all men possessing the use of reason throughout the world. In other words, men not only agree everywhere on the existence of a "right" and a " wrong," but in no inconsiderable degree on the acts to which they ascribe those respective attributes. Take the two instances on which we have ourselves insisted : the sins of David, and of the dishonest and treacherous politician. In either case there is no one, capable of under- standing such actions, who will not in his cool judgment condemn them without a moment's hesitation. We say "in his cool judgment," because it is manifest that men who are wholly absorbed and excited in the pursuit of some temporal end, refuse commonly even to consider the moral character of what they do. But otherwise, " there must be admitted to exist," says Mr. Bain himself (p. 300), "a * For instance. " Every man may have the feeling of conscience, that is the feeling of moral reprobation and moral approbation. All men agree in having these feelinrj$, though all do not agree in the matters to which they are applied " (pp. 207, 298). M r. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 103 tolerably uniform sense of the necessity of recognizing some rights of individuals : " " there are to a certain point * eternal and immutable ' moral judgments ... in the re- pudiation of the thief, the manslayer, and the rebel; " and we may add, no less, of him who becomes the wanton enemy of his benefactor, or who for private ends violates his solemn promise, or who for personal reward inflicts on his country what he knows to be a heavy injury. (3) "We shall still further see the existing amount of agreement on moral matters, by another consideration. There are several classes of actions, on which there may be indeed no universally received axiom of the form " act B is morally evil " where nevertheless all mankind agree in holding as self-evident that "act C is better than act D." Thus men everywhere will consider some course of conduct more admirable caeteris paribus, in proportion as it is more unselfish, however little they may agree as to what amount of selfishness is actually immoral. It is said, again, that the most barbarous nations regard celibacy as a higher state than marriage, while differing most widely from each other as to the limits of actual obligation in such matters. If this be true, we should be disposed to hold that the moral judgment in question is really cognized by all men as self- evidently true. For though Protestants earnestly repudiate this axiom, we should regard this as one of the not infre- quent cases in which men refuse to recognize what they really cognize ; we should say that the preternatural hatred of these Protestants for Catholicity, in this as in many other cases, prevents their explicit perception of the most obvious moral truths. But there is no need whatever of insisting on this.* * Mr. Bain, when reciting cases in which "strong antipathies" have boon arbitrarily " made into moral rules " (p. ISO'.)), has the following shameless remark: "There has been a very prevailing disposition to restrict tho indulgences of sex. Some practices are so violently abhorred, that they uro not permitted even to bo iniined " (p. 310). We must do Mr. Mill the 104 The Philosophy of Theism. (4) But no consideration perhaps so impressively shows the unanimity of moral conviction even now prevalent among mankind, as the following. All mankind, we say, are agreed in holding that justice, beneficence, veracity, fidelity to promises, gratitude, temperance, fortitude, that these, and not their opposites, are the virtuous ends of action. By this phrase we mean to express two proposi- tions. On the one hand, every act, otherwise faultless,* is accounted hy all men as good, if done for the sake of justice, beneficence, or any one of the rest ; while, on the other hand, every act is accounted by all men to be evil, if it contravene these ends. Take any one in their number say justice as standing for the rest. Many men doubtless in various times and places have thought it right to do many an act, which Catholics know to be unjust : still they have never thought it right because unjust ; they have never thought it right, for the sake of any virtuousness which they have supposed to reside in injustice ; but because of the virtuousness of beneficence, or gratitude, or the like. Similarly, many men think an act wrong because they think it unjust ; but they never think it wrong because they think it just. They regard this or that just act as wrong, because they regard it as opposed to beneficence or gratitude, but never because they regard it as required by justice. In one word, they think many an act good simply because prompted by justice ; but they never think an act good because prompted by injustice. And the same remark applies, to the other virtuous ends of action which we have named above. A "good man," in the judgment of all mankind, means " a man possessing in various degrees the justice to say, that no sentiment can be more violently opposed than this to hit way of regarding similar subjects. * We say " otherwise faultless," because it is perhaps possible that an act, known to be intrinsically evil, may be done for the virtuousuess of some good end. It is perhaps possible, e.g., that I may commit what I know to be a tueft on A, lor the virtnouaneaa of benefiting some very deserving person B. For ounelvca, however, we doubt whether this is possible. Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 105 qualities of justice, benevolence, veracity, fidelity to pro- mises, gratitude, temperance, fortitude." So much on the existing concurrence of moral judgments. Our further remarks are directed to explain the existing divergence. (5) The moral faculty, like all other faculties and perhaps more than any other, is perfected by cultivation ; and the means whereby it is cultivated is moral action.* If I only know two or three moral axioms and no others whatever, I know that there are certain acts intrinsically wrong and prohibited by the Supreme Euler ; or, in other words, I know that there is a Natural Law whether its extent be wide or narrow possessing irrefragable claims on my obedience, and strictly binding, though the whole universe solicited me to rebellion. Every other course of conduct, then, is glaringly unreasonable, except (1) to obey its precepts carefully, so far as I know them ; and (2) to use every means at my disposal by interrogating my con- sciousness, by praying for light to this Supreme Ruler, and in every other attainable way in order to discover the full extent of its enactments. In proportion as I give myself more energetically to this task and specially in proportion as I labour, not only to comply with strict obligation, but to do what is morally the better and more pleasing therefore to my Supreme Euler in that proportion two results ensue. Firstly, the utterances of my moral faculty become far more readily distinguishable from all other intellectual suggestions ; t and secondly, the number of moral axioms * Similarly F. Harper, as we have seen, holds that the perception of right and wrong has been blunted, often choked, still moro often misdirected, by passion, evil education, affection, prejudice, custom. lie adds that "the great aim of a true education must be to strengthen the principle of law, and then to direct it in a light channel." F. Newman, again, is constantly laying extreme stress on the proposition stated in the text. t There is one special means by which moral judgments become moro nml more pointedly distinguished from all others, in proportion as the agent grows in a habit of viitue ; viz. that they are ao intimately connected with 100 The Philosophy of Theism. within my cognizance is very rapidly increased. Certainly we maintain with confidence, that no man's intellect really avouches as self-evident a false moral verdict, on the case brought up to it for judgment. But nevertheless, in con- sistency with what has just been said, we have no difficulty whatever in admitting, (1) that those whose moral faculty is uncultivated may easily be mistaken as to its true utterances ; and (2) that very often indeed they will see no wickedness in many an act, which those more advanced in moral discernment will intuitively cognize to be evil. (6) We have said that no man's intellect avouches as self-evident a false moral verdict, on the case brought up to it for judgment ; and we are now to express our meaning in this qualification, on which we lay great stress. The very notion of an " axiom " as we have so often quoted from F. Kleutgen is that it exists wherever, by merely com- paring the ideas of subject and predicate, I come to see the truth of a proposition. But suppose those ideas did not correspond with objective facts : in that case of course the supposed axiom is simply delusive, as applied to these facts. A first-rate lawyer may give a faultless judgment on a case a sense of sin. Moral perception grows so far more quickly than moral nctiou, that a prevailing sense of sinfulness may be taken as an infallible measure of advance in true goodness. It is a peculiar merit of F. Newman's philosophy, to our mind, that he is ever so urgent in insisting on this. Mr. Lecky whose views, as a whole, are to us simply revolting nevertheless speaks well on this point. He criticizes (" European Morals," p. 07, note) the language, so commonly found among philosophers of either school, about the delight which is supposed to accrue to every good man from the testi- mony of his approving conscience, and the pleasure which the good man is supposed to receive from reflecting on that delight ; like " little Jack Horner," says Mr. Lecky, " who said ' what a good boy am I ' ! " And ho quotes a truly fatuous passage from Adam Smith. " The man who . . . from proper motives has performed a generous action . . . feels himself . . . the natural object ... of the esteem and approbation of all mankind [!!!]. And when he looks backward to the motive from which he acted, and surveys it in the light in which the indifferent spectator will survey it, he still con- tinues to enter into it, and applaiula himself by sympathy with the approba- tion of this supposed impartial judge. In both these points of view his con- duct appears to him in every way agreeable. Mis>ry and icretchedness can never enter the brtatt in which dwelleth complete self-satiiffaciiou." Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 107 proposed to him for consideration ; but if the case be wrongly drawn up, the judgment is valueless or mischievous. The same is true concerning moral judgments ; and we will give one obvious instance. To the uninstructed and non- Catholic reader of that unprincipled book Pascal's " Pro- vincial Letters," such a circumstance as the following will happen again and again. He will read in Pascal some propositions, advocated by illustrious Catholic casuists, and will regard it as axiomatic that they are immoral. And yet, if he comes to apprehend those very propositions as illus- trated by the context and taken in connection with the general drift of these casuists, he will entirely revoke his former judgment, and not improbably accept as self-evident the very opposite. This misstatement of the case is a most fruitful source of apparent divergences in moral judgment. Whether from prejudice and moral fault indefinitely varying in degree, or from mere intellectual inaccuracy and want of comprehen- siveness, it happens again and again that men totally misapprehend the phenomena on w r hich they judge. Wo may take an illustration from negro slavery, on which Mr. Bain twice insists (pp. 299, 812) as illustrating his theory. A and B are equally good men, and have therefore equally cultivated their moral faculty. A, however, has lived mostly among slaves, and is intimately acquainted with their cir- cumstances and character. B, on the contrary, has derived his scanty information on the subject entirely from slave- holders ; and, moreover, has never had any reason for pondering carefully on such light as the matter would receive, from the known laws of human nature. Some definite act of harshness to a slave will be cognixed by A as self-evidently wrong ; while B forms no moral judgment on it at all, axiomatic or otherwise. Mr. Bain himself admits in substance what we are now affirming. " When an abolitionist from Massachusetts," he says (p. 2Ui>) 10S The Philosophy of Theism. " denounces the institution of slavery, and a clergyman of Carolina defends it, both of them have in common the same sentiment of justice and injustice" (7) There are other instances, which are explicable by a process very familiar to Mr. Mill. This writer is con- stantly pointing out, how very easily an inference may be mistaken for an intuition ; and we have always heartily concurred in his remark. Now, many of the judgments cited by Mr. Bain, on the obligatoriness of some ritual observance, are conclusions of a syllogism. " Whatever the Supreme Euler commands is of obligation : but He commands this ; therefore this is of obligation." The only moral axiom here is the major premiss, which is indubitably true ; and it is an historian's business, not a philosopher's, to trace the origin of the minor. Moreover, although some of these ritual observances should be both intrinsically immoral, and self-evidently cognizable as such by one who has duly cultivated his moral faculty, this admission (as is obvious) does not in any way affect our argument. (8) In other cases, again, a moral judgment is the con- clusion, not of unconscious, but of explicit and prolonged reasoning. Mr. Bain seems really to speak (p. 312) as though the question, whether slavery be or be not permis- sible, could be axiomatically answered. We do not ourselves think that it is capable of any universal solution ; we think that what is permissible or even preferable in some circum- stances, is intrinsically evil in others. But however this may be, the true conclusion can only be reached by a sustained process of reasoning a process in which moral axioms doubtless play a large part, but in which a large part is also played by various psychological and social data. And the moral axioms will be precisely those premisses on which both parties in the controversy profess agreement. (9) Finally, the instances are by no means few in which mere antipathy has been mistaken by philosophers for Mr. Mill on the Foundation of Morality. 109 moral disapprobation. It by no means follows, because some body of men abhor some practice, that they regard it as morally wrong. And, most fortunately for our purpose, it happens that we have irrefragable proof of this, in facts, which to the grandfathers of living Englishmen were matters of every-day experience. We refer to the time when duelling was of social obligation. Some hundred years ago, any layman who refused to fight a duel under circumstances in which public opinion required it, was treated as a veritable Pariah : he was received into no society of gentlemen ; no gentleman would give him his daughter in marriage ; nay, to associate with him was to be socially excommunicated. From such usages as these, had they occurred in some distant and very partially known period, Mr. Bain would have confidently inferred that those who practised them accounted as morally evil the refusal to fight duels ; and yet no fact in the world is more certain than the reverse of this. These men were in general so firmly convinced of the truth of Christianity that they regarded with horror the very suspicion of infidelity. On the other hand, it is equally undeniable that they knew duelling to be forbidden by Christianity ; because for this very reason no clergyman was expected to fight.* Again, suppose one of themselves a man too of otherwise profligate life were lying on his death-bed : they would probably experience a momentary misgiving about his future lot; though they would very likely soon reassure themselves, by some blasphemous plausibilities about God's mercy. But suppose a man of spotless life were on his death-bed, who had been under their ban for his faithfulness to God and his consequent refusal to fight ; the very notion would not occur to them, that he had placed his sn in jeopardy by conduct which nevertheless they so intensely * See, in the Dublin Review for July, 1871, p. U4, Dr. H;imi>y , thut there exists Ow Necessary Person. 120 The Philosophy of Tltc ism. always been "singularly clear in statement, accessible to argument, and candid or rather generous towards oppo- nents ; " and the whole tone of his replies to the Dublin Review is in full accordance with this estimate of his con- troversial qualities. At the same time, it was his conviction no less than our own, that the highest interests of mankind are intimately involved in the prevalence of sound doctrine on the matters in debate ; while on our side we further know that these interests are inappreciable in magnitude and eternal in duration. It is our bounden duty, therefore, to do evenihing we can to expose what we consider the un- reasonableness and shallowness of those phenomenistie tenets which Mr. Mill has embraced. Of those tenets we must ever affirm with confidence that they are (as we have just implied) not unreasonable only, but incredibly shallow ; and it is of extreme moment that this characteristic of theirs be fully understood. Yet the very weakness of a cause may in some sense set forth the ability of its advocate ; and our predominant feeling towards Mr. Mill is one of surprise, that so skilful and rarely accomplished a navigator should have embarked in so frail a vessel. "Without further preamble, however, let us commence our work by entering again on the matters treated in our first essay, and by seeing where Mr. Mill stands thereon in relation to ourselves. We begin, then, with "the rule and motive of certitude." There is one truth which the extremest sceptic cannot possibly call in question, viz. that his inward conscious- ness, as experienced by him at the present moment, is what it is. To doubt this, as Mr. Mill observes, would be "to doubt that I feel what I feel." But this knowledge is utterly sterile, very far inferior to that possessed by the brutes ; and no one manifestly can possess knowledge worthy of being so called, unless he knows the phenomena, not only of his momentarily present consciousness, but also 'Nr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review." 127 (to a greater or less extent) of that consciousness which has now ceased to exist. A man cannot e.g. so much as understand the simplest sentence spoken to him, unless, while hearing the last word, he knows those words which have preceded it. We ask this question, then : what means has he of possessing this knowledge of the past ? On what grounds can he reasonably accept, as true, the clearest and distinctest avouchments of his memory ? "I am conscious of a most clear and articulate mental impression that a very short time ago I was suffering cold : " this is one judgment. " A very short time ago I was suffering cold : " this is another and totally distinct judgment. That a man knows his present impression of a past feeling, by no manner of means implies that he knows the past existence of that feel- ing. How do you know, we would have asked Mr. Mill, how do you know (on the above supposition of facts) that a very short time ago you were suffering cold ? How do you know e.g. that Professor Huxley's suggestion* is not the very truth ? How do you know, in other words, that some powerful and malicious being is not at this moment deluding you into a belief that you were cold a short time ago, when the real fact was entirely otherwise ? How do you know, in fact, that any one experience, which your memory testifies, ever really befel you at all ? It is plain, then, and most undeniable, that the philo- sopher cannot claim for men any knowledge whatever beyond that of their momentarily present consciousness, unless he establishes some theory on what scholastics call the "rule and motive of certitude." He must (1) lay down the " rule of certitude ; " or, in other words, explain what is the characteristic of those truths which men may reason- ably accept with certitude : and (2) he must lay down " the * "It i.s conceivable that some powerful and malicious being may find his pleasure in deluding UK, und in making us believe the tiling which is not every moment of our lives." (" Lay Sermons," p. l{.")0.) 128 The Philosophy of Tlmsm. motive of certitude ; " or, in other words, explain what is men's reasonable ground for accepting, as certain, those truths which possess such characteristic. It is conceivable, doubtless, that the principle he lays down may authenticate no other avouchments except those of memory ; or it is conceivable, on the contrary, that that principle may authenticate a large number of other avouchmeuts. But if he professes to be a philosopher at all, if he professes to establish any reasonable stronghold whatever against absolute and utter scepticism, some theory or other he must lay down, on the rule and motive of certitude. And such theory is, by absolute necessity, the one argumentative foundation of his whole system. We maintained in our first essay, that it is the scholastic theory on this fundamental issue which alone is conformable with reason and with facts. This theory is of course set forth by different writers, with greater or less difference of detail and of expression ; and we referred to F. Kleutgen as having enunciated it with singular clear- ness of exposition. Firstly, what is the rule of certitude ? or, in other words, what is the characteristic of those truths which I may reasonably accept as certain ? Every proposition, he replies, is known to me as a truth, which is avouched by my cognitive faculties when those faculties are exercised according to their intrinsic laws ; whether they be thus exercised in declaring primary verities, or in deriving this or that inference from those verities. Secondly, what is the motive of certitude ? or, in other words, what is my reasonable ground for accepting the above-named propositions as certainly true ? He replies, that a created gift, called the light of reason, is possessed by the soul, whereby every man, while exercising his cognitive faculties according to their intrinsic laws, is rendered infallibly certain that their avouchments corre- spond with objective truth. Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review." 1 29 In advocating this theory, however, we guarded ourselves against two possible misconceptions of its bearing. We admitted, in the first place, how abundantly possible it is, nay, how frequently it happens, that men misunder- stand the avouchment of their intellect. In fact a large part of our controversy with Mr. Mill proceeds on this very ground : we allege against him, that this, that, and the other proposition, which he denies, is really declared by the human faculties, when exercised according to their intrinsic laws. Then, secondly, we explained that our appeal is made to the mind's positive, not its negative con- stitution ; or, in other words, that we lay our stress on its affirmations, not on its incapacities. It does not at all follow, we added, because the human mind cannot conceive some given proposition, that such proposition may not be true ; nay, that it may not be most certain and inappre- ciably momentous. This statement appears to us of great importance, in regard to various controversies of the present day. But it has little or no bearing on the points directly at issue between Mr. Mill and ourselves. Such, then, is the scholastic thesis, on the rule and motive of certitude; viz. that man's cognitive faculties, while acting on the laws of their constitution, carry with them in each particular case immediate evidence of absolute trustworthiness. It would be a contradiction almost in terms if we professed to adduce direct arguments for this thesis, because the very fact of adducing arguments would imply that man's reasoning faculty can be trusted, which is part of the very conclusion to be proved. But (1) we adduced for our thesis what appears to us strong indirect argument ; and (2) (which is much more important) we suggested to the inquirer such mental experiments aa are abundantly sufficient, we consider, to satisfy him of its truth. Under the latter head we appealed to each man's consciousness in our favour. That which his faculties V(L. I. K 130 Tlte Philosophy of Theism. indubitably declare as certain, he finds himself under an absolute necessity of infallibly knowing to be true. I experience, e.g., that phenomenon of the present moment, which I thus express : I say that I remember distinctly and articulately to have been much colder a few minutes ago when I was out in the snow, than I am now when sitting by a comfortable fire. Well, in consequence of this present mental phenomenon, I find myself under the absolute necessity of knowing that a very short time ago I had that experience which I now remember. Professor Huxley suggests that "some powerful and malicious being" may possibly " find his pleasure in deluding me," and in making me fancy as past what has never really happened to me ; but I am absolutely necessitated to know that I am under no such delusion in regard to this recent experience. My act of memory is not merely known to me as a present impression, but carries with it also immediate evidence of representing a fact of my past experience. And so with my other intellectual operations, whether of reasoning or any other. The subjective operation, if performed according to the laws of my mental constitution, carries with it immediate evidence of corresponding with objective truth. All must admit that this is at least a consistent and intelligible theory ; and for several intellectually active centuries it reigned without a rival. Descartes, however, the great philosophical revolutionist of Christian times, substituted for it a strange and grotesque invention of his own. He held that each man's reason for knowing the trustworthiness of his faculties is his previous conviction of God's Existence and Veracity. Nothing can be more simply suicidal than this theory, because (as is manifest) unless I first know the trustworthiness of my cognitive faculties, I have no means of knowing as certain (or even guessing as probable) God's Existence and Veracity them- selves. We insisted on this consideration in our first essay ; Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Revieiv." 131 but as we are here in hearty concurrence with Mr. Mill, we need add no more on the present occasion. We fear that Descartes's theory possesses, more or less partially, not a few minds among the non-Catholic opponents of phenomenism. But if certain non-Catholic opponents of phenomenism have exhibited shallowness in one direction, the whole body of phenomenists * have exhibited still greater shallowness in another. They have universally assumed, as the basis of their whole philosophy, that each man knows with certitude the past existence of those experiences which his memory distinctly testifies. They admit of course that unless this certitude existed man would possess less know- ledge than the very brutes ; and yet, though its assumption is to them so absolutely vital, not one of them has so much as entertained the question, on what ground it rests. As we have already asked, how do they know, how can they reasonably even guess, that a man's present distinct impression of a supposed past experience corresponds with a past fact ? Still more emphatically how do they know that this is not only so in one instance, but in every instance ? that man is so wonderfully made and endowed, that his present impression of what he has recently ex- perienced always corresponds with what he has in fact so experienced ? They make this prodigious assumption without the slightest attempt at giving a reason for it nay, and without any apparent consciousness that a reason needs to be given. And then finally, as though to give a crowning touch of absurdity to their amazing position, they make it their special ground of invective against the opposite school of philosophy, that it arbitrarily erects, * There is only one exception with which we happen to bo acquainted, viz. that of Professor Huxley, which we presently mention in the text. By "phenomenists " (we need hardly say) we mean those philosopher* who ascribe to mankind no immediate knowledge whatever except of phenomena. 132 Tlte Philosophy of into first principles of objective truth, the mere subjective impressions of the human mind. One could not have believed it possible that such shallowness should have characterized a whole school of philosophers some of them, too, undoubtedly endowed with large knowledge and signal ability were not the facts of the case patent and undeniable. We mentioned just now, in a note, that an exception to this universality is afforded by Professor Huxley ; and there may of course be other exceptions, with which we do not happen to be acquainted. In our first essay we quoted one of the Professor's remarks, to which we here refer. " The general trustworthiness of memory," he says, " is one of those hypothetical assumptions which cannot be proved or known with that highest degree of certainty which is given by immediate consciousness ; but which, nevertheless, are of the highest practical value, inas- much as the conclusions logically drawn from them are always verified by experience." To this singular piece of reasoning we put forth an obvious reply. You tell us that you trust your present act of memory because in innumerable past instances the avouchments of memory have been true. How do you know, how can you even guess, that there has been one such instance ? Because you trust your present act of memory; no other answer can possibly be given. Never was there so audacious an instance of arguing in a circle. You know forsooth that your present act of memory can be trusted because in innumerable past instances the avouchment of memory has been true ; and you know that in innumerable past instances the avouchment of memory has been true because you trust your present act of memory. The blind man leads the blind round a " circle " incurably " vicious." Let us observe the Professor's philosophical position. It is his principle, that men know nothing with certitude Mr. Mill's Eeply to the " Dublin Review" 133 except their present consciousness. Now, on this principle, it is just as absurd to say that the facts testified by memory are probably as that they are certainly true. What can be more violently unscientific, we asked, from the stand-point of experimental science, than to assume without grounds as ever so faintly probable the very singular proposition, that mental phenomena (by some entirely un- known law) have proceeded in such a fashion that my clear impression of the past corresponds with my past experience 1 Professor Huxley possesses, no doubt, signal ability in his own line ; but surely as a metaphysician he exhibits a sorry spectacle. He busies himself in his latter capacity with diligently overthrowing the only principle on which his researches as a physicist con have value or even meaning. At present, however, our direct business is with Mr. Mill ; and we are next to inquire how his philosophy stands in reference to the rule and motive of certitude. As to the rule of certitude, he speaks (it seems to us) so ambiguously as to make it a matter of no ordinary difficulty to discover which one of two contradictory propositions he intends to affirm ; while, as to the motire of certitude, he unites with his brother phenomenists in shirking the question altogether. We shall begin with urging against him this latter allegation. We did not bring it forward by any means so strongly in our former essay,* because (as we shall explain further on) we had good reason for understanding him to admit much more in our favour than his present reply shows him to have intended. Even now we entirely concede that he (and again Dr. Bain) have made a distinct step beyond earlier writers of their school. They have advanced, we say, a little way beyond earlier writers, along the road which, if duly pursued, would have brought them * We only said, that ho"hnu failed in clearly anil consistently appre- hending and bearing in mind tin; true doctrine." 134 The Philosophy of Thelxni. into the observed presence of the question with which we are here engaged. Yet even they, we must maintain, have nowhere arrived at a distinct apprehension, that there is such a question to be considered as the motive of certitude. With Dr. Bain we are not here concerned. As to Mr. Mill, the direct basis of our allegation against him is of course negative. He admits everywhere, that men's know- ledge of their past experience is an absolutely indispensable condition for knowledge.* But we believe no one place can be mentioned throughout his works in which he so much as professes to explain, on what principle it is that men can reasonably trust their memory as authenticating their past experience. At least, we protest we have been unable to find such a passage, though our search has been minute and laborious. There is no part of his writings in which one might so reasonably have expected to find some doctrine on the motive of certitude, as in a passage on which we have before now laid some stress a passage, indeed, which (for reasons presently to be given) we originally understood in a far more favourable sense than his subsequent explana- tion permits. He had said ("On Hamilton," p. 209, note) that " our belief in the veracity of memory is evidently ultimate," because " no reason can be given for it which does not presuppose the belief and assume it to be well grounded." On this we made the following comment in our second essay : He holds that there is just one intuition one, only one which carries with it [immediate] evidence of truth. There was an imperative claim on him then, as he valued his philo- sophical character, to explain clearly and pointedly, where the distinction lies between acts of memory and other alleged in- tuitions. He would have found the task very difficult, we * For instance. " All who have attempted the explanation of the human mind by sensation, have postulated the knowledge of past sensations as well as of present." (" Ou Hamilton," p. 210, note.) Mr. Mitt's Reply to the " Dublin Review." 135 confidently affirm ; but that only gives us more reason for complaining that he did not make the attempt. To us it seems that various classes of intuition are more favourably circum- stanced for the establishment of their trustworthiness, than is that class which Mr. Mill accepts. Thus, in the case of many a wicked action, it would really be easier for the criminal to believe that he had never committed it than to doubt its necessary turpitude and detestableness. Then, in the case of other intuitions, I know that the rest of mankind share them with myself; and I often know, also, that experience confirms them as far as it goes ; but I must confidently trust my acts of clear and distinct memory, before I can even guess what is held by other men or what is declared by experience. Mr. Mill thus replies : Dr. Ward with good reason challenges me to explain where the distinction lies, between acts of memory and other alleged intuitions which I do not admit as such. The distinction is, that as all the explanations of mental phenomena presuppose memory, memory itself cannot admit of being explained. Whenever this is shown to be true of any other part of our knowledge, I shall admit that part to be intuitive. Dr. Ward thinks that there are various other intuitions more favourably circumstanced for the establishment of their trustworthiness than memory itself, and he gives as an example our conviction of the wickedness of certain acts. My reason for rejecting this as a case of intuition is, that the conviction can be explained without presupposing as part of the explanation the very fact itself, which the belief in memory cannot. Our readers, then, will observe that Mr. Mill, when expressly challenged, gives no other reason for his belief in the veracity of memory except only this. Memory, he nays, must be assumed to be veracious, because " as all the explanations of mental phenomena presuppose memory, memory itself cannot admit of being explained : " or, in other words (as he expressed the same thought somewhat more clearly in his original note), because " no reason can be given for the veracity of memory which does not pre- suppose the belief and assume it to be well grounded." 130 The Philosophy of Theism. But a moment's consideration will show that this answer implies a fundamental misconception of the point we had raised. The question which he answers is, whether my knowledge of past facts (assuming that I hare such know- ledge) is on the one hand an immediate and primary, or on the other hand a mediate and secondary, part of my know- ledge.* But the question which we asked was totally different from this. We asked, on what ground my belief of the facts testified by my memory can be accounted part of my knowledge at all. We asked, in short, on what reason- able ground can my conviction rest, that I ever experienced those sensations, emotions, thoughts, which my memory represents to me as past facts of my life ? We say that the question to which Mr. Mill has replied is fundamentally different from the question which we asked. Let it be assumed that my belief in the declarations of my memory is a real part of my knowledge, and nothing can be more pertinent than Mr. Mill's argument : he shows satisfactorily, that such belief must be an immediate and primary part of my knowledge, not a mediate and derivative part thereof. But when the very question asked is whether this belief be any part of my knowledge at all^ Mr. Mill's reply is simply destitute of meaning. For con- sider. We may truly predicate of every false belief which ever was entertained nay, of every false belief which can even be imagined that " no " satisfactory " reason can be given for it which does not presuppose the belief and assume it to be well grounded." If Mr. Mill, then, were here professing to prove the trustivorthiness of memory, his argu- ment would be this : " The declarations of memory," he would be saying, " are certainly true, because they possess one attribute which is possessed by every false belief which was ever entertained or can even be imagined." * Observe, e.g., his words : " Whenever this appears to be true of any other part of our knowledge." Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review." 137 Or we may draw out against him, in a different shape, what is substantially the same argument. Mr. Mill's first business as it is that of every philosopher was to show that philosophy is possible; or, in other words, to place before his disciples reasonable grounds for rejecting the sceptical conclusion. Now, the sceptic's argument as put, e.g. (however inconsistently), by Professor Huxley may be worded as follows : " No knowledge is possible to me, except that which I possess at any given moment of my actually present consciousness. No knowledge is possible to me, I say, beyond this, because I cannot possibly acquire more except by knowing that the declarations of my memory may be trusted. But I see no ground whatever for knowing that these may be trusted. How can I guess but that as the Professor suggests some powerful and malicious being may find his pleasure in deluding me, and making me fancy myself to remember things which never happened ? Nay, apart from that supposition, there may be ten thousand different agencies, to me unknown, which may have produced my present impression of a supposed past, not one of which agencies in any degree implies that this supposedly past experience was ever really mine." Mr. Mill, we say, was absolutely required to give reasonable ground for rejecting this view of things, under pain of forfeiting his position of " philosopher " altogether. Let us consider, then, how far the one argument which he gives for the trustworthiness of memory will enable him to oppose the sceptical view. His argument, if it can be logically expressed at all, consists of two syllogisms which we will draw out in form. SYLLOGISM I. Knowledge of much more than present consciousness i>s possible to human beings. 138 TJie Philosophy of Theism. But such knowledge would not be possible, unless they had reasonable grounds for trusting their memory. Therefore they have reasonable grounds for trusting their memory. SYLLOGISM II. Men have reasonable grounds for trusting their memory (Conclusion of First Syllogism). But they would not have such grounds, unless its veracity were immediately evident, (because "no reason can be given for it, which does not presuppose it "). Therefore the veracity of memory is immediately evident. We beg our readers, then, to observe the character of this argument. It abandons all profession of replying to the sceptic at all ; it assumes, as the very major premiss of its first syllogism, that precise proposition which the sceptic expressly and formally denies. We infer from all this, that the question which we pressed on Mr. Mill, we will not say has not been answered, but has not even been apprehended by him. With him, as with other phenomenists, "the motive of certitude" is a "missing link" of the philosophical chain. Even if the merits of his philosophical structure were far greater than we can admit, no one can deny that it is entirely destitute of & foundation ; that he has exhibited no grounds whatever on which inquirers can reasonably accept either his own conclusions or any one else's. A similar view of his position is impressed on our mind by another paragraph, in which he treats the sceptical tenet more directly, and in which he shows again that he has not even a glimpse of the sceptic's true controversial status. It will be better to give this paragraph at length ; Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review." 139 and we need only explain, by way of preface, that he uses the word " consciousness," not in the sense in which we uniformly use it, and which he himself accounts the more usual and convenient, but in a totally different sense given to it by Sir W. Hamilton. We italicize one sentence : According to all philosophers, the evidence of consciousness, if only we can obtain it pure, is conclusive. This is an obvious, but by no means a mere identical proposition. If consciousness be defined as intuitive knowledge, it is indeed an identical proposition to say, that if we intuitively know anything, we do know it, and are sure of it. But the meaning lies in the implied assertion, that we do know some things immediately or intuitively. That we must do so is evident, if we know any- thing ; for what we know mediately depends for its evidence on our previous knowledge of something else : unless, therefore, we know something immediately, we could not know anything mediately and consequently could not know anything at all. That imaginary being, a complete sceptic, might be supposed to answer, that perhaps we do not know anything at all. I shall not reply to this problematical antagonist in the usual mariner, by telling him that if he does not know anything, I do. I put to him the simplest case conceivable of immediate knowledge, and ask if we ever feel anything ? If so, then at the moment of feeling do we know that we feel ? or, if he will not call this knowledge, will he deny that when we have a feeling we have at least some sort of assurance, or conviction, of having it ? This assurance of conviction is what other people mean by knowledge. If he dislikes the word, I am willing in discussing with him to employ some other. By whatever name this assurance is called, it is the test to which we bring all our other convictions. He may say it is not certain ; but such as it may be it is our model of certainty. \Ve consider all our other assurances and con- victions as more or less certain, according as they approach the standard of this. I have a conviction that there are icebergs on the Arctic seas. I have not the evidence of my senses for it : I never saw an iceberg. Neither do I intuitively believe it by a law of my mind. My conviction is mediate, grounded on testimony, and on inferences from physical laws. When I say 1 am convinced of it, I mean that the evidence is equal to that of my senses. I am as certain of the fact as if 1 had seen it. HO TJie Philosophy of Thriwn. And on a more complete analysis, when I say that I am con- vinced of it, what I am convinced of is that if I were in the Arctic seas I should see it. We mean by knowledge, and by certainty, an assurance similar and equal to that afforded by our senses : if the evidence in any other case can be brought up to this, we desire no more. If a person is not satisfied with this evidence, it is no concern of anybody but himself, nor practically of himself, since it is admitted that this evidence is what we must, and may in full confidence, act upon. Absolute scepticism, if there be such a thing, may be dismissed from discussion as raising an irrelevant issue, for in denying all knowledge it denies none. The dogmatist may be quite satisfied if the doctrine he maintains can be attacked by no arguments, but those which apply to the evidence of our senses. If his evidence is equal to that, he needs no more ; nay, it is philosophically maintain- able that by the laws of psychology we can conceive no more, and that this is the certainty we call perfect. (" On Hamilton," pp. 157, 158.) This whole passage, as we have observed, is very significant. In the italicized sentence, Mr. Mill says that scepticism cannot be assailed by any arguments, except those which would overthrow "the evidence of the senses." Very short work would be made of this statement by a consistent follower of Professor Huxley. He would point, of course, to the undeniable fact, that men's belief in the " evidence of their senses " or in the phenomena of their consciousness at any given moment on one hand, and men's belief in anything else whatever on the other hand, that these two beliefs rest respectively on grounds funda- mentally different from each other. He would urge with irrefragable force, that the former belief is independent of the question whether their memory may or may not be trusted; whereas every other belief is destitute of so much as the hundredth part of a leg to stand on, unless the trust- worthiness of memory be in some way made known to them. Of this vital fact in the controversy with sceptics, Mr. Mill seems absolutely and utterly unaware. There is another passage of Mr. Mill's which we may Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin fiei-ieiv" HI also adduce. We referred to it in our first essay ; but now that we understand more clearly Mr. Mill's statements, we had better quote it entire : I must protest against adducing, as evidence of the truth of a fact in external nature, the disposition, however strong or however general, of the human mind to believe it. Belief is not proof, and does not dispense with the necessity of proof. I am aware, that to ask for evidence of a proposition which wo are supposed to believe instinctively is to expose one's self to the charge of rejecting the authority of the human faculties ; which of course no one can consistently do, since the human faculties are all which any one has to judge by: and inasmuch as the meaning of the word evidence is supposed to be something which when laid before the mind induces it to believe, to demand evidence when belief is ensured by the mind's own laws, is supposed to be appealing to the intellect against the intellect. But this, I apprehend, is a misunderstanding of the nature of evidence. By evidence is not meant anything and everything which produces belief. There are many things which generate belief besides evidence. A mere strong associa- tion of ideas often causes a belief so intense as to be unshakable by experience or argument. Evidence is not that which the mind does or must yield to, but that which it ought to yield to, namely, that by yielding to which its belief is kept conformable to fact. There is no appeal from the human faculties generally, but there is an appeal from one human faculty to another ; from the judging faculty to those which take cognisance of fact, the faculties of sense and consciousness. The legitimacy of this appeal is admitted whenever it is allowed that our judgments ought to be conformable to fact. To say that belief suffices for its own justification is making opinion the test of opinion ; it is denying the existence of any outward standard, the conformity of an opinion to which constitutes the truth. We call one mode of forming opinions right and another wrong, because the ono does, and the other docs not, tend to make the opinion agreo with fact to make people believe what really is, and expect what really will be. Now, a mere disposition to believe, even if supposed instinctive, is no guarantee for the truth of the thing believed. If, indeed, the belief ever amounted to an irresistiHo necessity, there would then bo no use in appealing from it, because there would be no possibility of altering it. 1'ut even 142 The Philosophy of Theism. then the truth of the belief would not follow; it would only follow that mankind were under a permanent necessity of believing what might possibly not bo true ; in other words, that a case might occur in which our senses or consciousness, if they could be appealed to, might testify one thing, and our reason believe another. (" Logic," vol. ii. pp. 96-98.) Now, to begin with the opening sentences of this para- graph. Of course we admit that, under particular circum- stances, there may be a strong disposition of the human mind to believe untrue propositions. But Mr. Mill's state- ment is very different from this. No disposition to believe, he says, " however strong or however general," can evidence a fact. A more glaringly untenable philosophical statement never was put forth. There is literally no " fact in external nature," great or small, which does not rest in last resort, for the " evidence of its truth," exclusively on " the disposi- tion of the human mind to believe it." This is absolutely undeniable ; for consider : No one fact can possibly be established, except through the past experience of human beings. Mr. Mill of all men will not deny this. But that human beings ever had this past experience is a fact to which not one with any show of reason could attach the least shred of credibility, were it not for the " disposition " of their " mind " to accept as true the declarations of their memory ; and were it not for that inward gift possessed by them, whereby they know that this acceptance is reasonable. And a comment precisely similar might so easily be made on each successive sentence of the passage, that we should be guilty of tedious impertinence if we inflicted such comment on our readers' patience. Our inference is as before, that Mr. Mill, from wholly failing to apprehend the position of sceptics, has also wholly failed to apprehend the necessity of carefully considering " the motive of certitude." We have said, however, that Mr. Mill is one of two Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review." 143 phenomenist writers, who (as we think) have advanced a little way beyond earlier writers of their school, towards discerning the existence of this question. In Mr. Mill's case, we are here specially referring to the ninth chapter of his work " On Hamilton," concerning "the interpretation of consciousness." In p. 159 he cites the distinction drawn by Sir W. Hamilton, between the authority of what is commonly called consciousness on one hand, and of what is commonly called intuition on the other; * and in pp. 162-3 he expresses hearty concurrence with this distinction.! Sir William proceeds still with Mr. Mill's full approval to derive an instance of this distinction from the faculty of memory. "I cannot deny," he says (Mill, p. 160), "the actual phenomenon " that I have that present impression which I call an act of memory, " because my denial would be suicidal : but I can without self-contradiction assert that [present] consciousness may be a false witness in regard to any former existence ; and I maintain, if I please, that the memory of the past, in consciousness, is nothing but a phenomenon, which has no reality beyond the present." Mr. Mill, then, has here got hold of the truth, that the two beliefs belief in the present existence of the act of memory, and belief in the past existence of those phenomena which memory testifies that these two beliefs rest on foundations totally different from each other. It is passing strange, that he should have let this truth slip from his mind after having once apprehended it ; that he should have failed to inquire accordingly, what is the basis on which beliefs of the latter kind reasonably rest ; and above all, that at the * All those philosophers who use the word " intuitions " at all, use it in the same sense. They use it to express those truths which are not indeed mere facts of present consciousness, but which nevertheless are immediately and primarily known with certitude. t These are Mr. Mill's words of approval: " By the conception and clear exposition of thin distinction, Sir W. Hamilton has" shown "that, whatever he the positive value of his achievements in metaphysics, he has a greater capacity for the subject than many metaphysicians of high reputation." Tlie Philosophy of Theism. beginning of this very chapter (at pp. 157-8) he should have expressed (as our readers have seen) an opinion directly contrary to that doctrine of Sir W. Hamilton's which he endorses in pp. 162-3. We consider, then, that we have established a very grave charge indeed against Mr. Mill's philosophical character. It is the very first business of a philosopher to show that he has a raison d'etre ; that philosophy can exist ; that human knowledge is possible. Those who hold that no human knowledge is possible, ground their opinion on the alleged impossibility of authenticating the avouchments of memory. Mr. Mill not only has not solved this difficulty, not only has not attempted to solve it, but has not even contemplated its existence. We are by no means implying that herein he is inferior to other phenomenists ; on the contrary we have said that he is somewhat in advance of them : but what we wish to impress on our readers, is the in- credible shallowness of the phenomenistic philosophy itself. Mr. Mill has also replied to the rest of the criticism which we expressed in our second essay, on his treatment of the memory question ; and this will be our proper place for dealing with his reply. One remark we made was, that his statement about memory constitutes " a most pointed exception to his school's general doctrine, and an exception which no phenomenist had made before." To this Mr. Mill answers ("On Hamilton," p. 210, note) that he "doubts whether we can point out any phenomenist who has not made it either expressly or by implication." We reply, that we had understood him to admit in his note and we had excellent reason for so understanding him much more than (as now appears) he ever intended. We understood him in his original note to express agreement with what was said in Dr. Ward's " Philosophical Introduction," on this particular theme.* Now, the view set forth in that * Mr. Mill said : " Our belief in the veracity of memory is evidently Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review." work was identical with the view advocated in the preceding pages. Dr. Ward maintained, not merely that " the veracity of memory" in each particular case is not known by reason- ing or by consciousness, but further that it is known with certitude by means of a gift which may be called the light of reason ; that man's belief in the veracity of memory on one hand, and of present consciousness on the other, rest on grounds fundamentally different from each other ; but that each rests on evidence abundantly sufficient. Dr. Ward, we may add, laid his main stress on the proposition, that the trustworthiness of memory, in any given case whatever, is known, not at all by consciousness, but by the mind's own inward light. We had no other notion, then, but that Mr. Mill intended to express concurrence with this opinion. And even if we had otherwise doubted this, we should have been strongly confirmed in our existing impression by that comment of Mr. Mill's on Sir W. Hamilton which we so recently quoted. How were we to guess that the same writer, who praised Sir William so warmly for his " con- ception and clear exposition of this distinction," did not himself recognize the distinction ? We consider, therefore (as we have more than once said in the preceding pages), that we had excellent reasons for considering Mr. Mill's view to be coincident with our own on the motive of certitude ; and we now can only regret our inevitable mistake. We said in our first essay, that he " failed in consistently apprehending and bearing in mind " what we regard as "the true doctrine;" but we now see that ho never in any way held it. Our readers, then, will under- stand what was the view which we inevitably (though it now appears mistakenly) ascribed to Mr. Mill : and this ultimate," etc. "This point is forcibly urged in" Dr. Ward's " Philosophical Introduction," "a book . . . showing u capacity in the writer," etc., etc. Nor did Mr. Mill give the most distant hint that he differed from Dr. Ward's view of the subject in its most essential particular. VOL. I. j, 14G The Philosophy of Theism. being so, we easily defend the criticism expressed by us in our second essay. If Mr. Mill's doctrine bad been what we supposed, it would have constituted " a most pointed exception to his school's general doctrine;" for we are certainly not aware of a single phenomenist writer, anterior to Mr. Mill, who had so much as a glimpse of it. Mr. Mill further takes exception to our remark, that " if there ever were a paradoxical position, his is one on the surface." But it will now be understood that we were speaking of the position which we inevitably mistook for his, and not of that which he really intended to assume. We understood him to concur with our doctrine, that the soul of man possesses a special gift, given for the very purpose of authenticating intuitions. On such a supposi- tion we do think it paradoxical to hold that there is just one class of intuitions and no more. But we need hardly say that the statement is of no controversial importance, and we willingly withdraw it. We confess, however, with regret one piece of careless- ness, which Mr. Mill has pointed out. We did not suffici- ently bear in mind that he had " avowedly left the question open, whether our perception of our own personality is not " another "case of the same kind ; " another case of intuition. We now pass from Mr. Mill's doctrine (or rather absence of doctrine) on the motive of certitude, to his doctrine on the rule thereof. In particular as regards primary truths : what is the characteristic, we should have liked to ask him, of those judgments which man may reasonably accept as immediately and primarily evident ? F. Kleutgen answers and we are heartily in accord that all those and only those judgments may reasonably be accepted as immediately evident which man's existing cognitive faculties imme- diately avouch as certain. Now, whether it be taken as proof of Mr. Mill's obscurity or of our own dulness, certain it is that on this point also, Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Revievj." 147 when we wrote our first essay, we considered Mr. Mill's doctrine to be far nearer our own than it really is. We were led astray by such passages as the following, which we quoted in p. 26 : " The verdict of our immediate and intuitive conviction is admitted on all hands to be a decision without appeal." " As regards almost all, if not all, philo- sophers " and by his very phrase (we said) he implies that he at all events is no dissentient "the questions which divided them have never turned on the veracity of con- sciousness : " where (as we explained) he is, by his own express avowal, using the word " consciousness " in Sir \V. Hamilton's sense of "immediate and intuitive convic- tion." What Sir W. Hamilton calls " the testimony of consciousness," so Mr. Mill proceeds, "to something beyond itself, may be and is denied ; but what is denied has almost always been that consciousness gives the testimony, not that if given it must be believed." We might have added other similar statements. Thus (p. 137) : " what con- sciousness directly reveals, together with what can be legitimately inferred from its revelations, composes by universal admission all that we know." "All agree with" Sir W. Hamilton (p. 165), "in the position itself, that a real fact of consciousness cannot be denied." These sentences, one would have thought, are most plain and unmistakable in their assertion, that whatever is declared by men's " immediate and intuitive conviction " is indubit- ably true. Then there was another reason also for crediting Mr. Mill with the same theory, viz. that, according to this interpretation of his words, he would have laid down a solid basis for his belief in the veracity of memory. If those judgments may reasonably be accepted as primarily evident, which man's existing cognitive faculties imme- diately avouch as certain, then the various declarations of memory indubitably rank among primarily evident truths. In the same essay, however, we quoted other sentences 148 The Philosophy of Theism. of Mr. Mill, -which point to quite a different indeed, a directly contradictory theory on the rule of certitude. This theory is, that no judgment c*an be reasonably ac- cepted by me as immediately evident which would not have been declared by my cognitive faculties in their earliest and primordial state.* And the sentences of Mr. Mill, which we quoted as seeming to express this theory, are such as the following. Men should only accept, he says, "what consciousness told them at the time when its revela- tions were in their pristine purity." " We have no means of interrogating consciousness in the only circumstances in which it is possible for it to give a trustworthy ansiver." And we might have added several others even stronger. That which is "a fact of our consciousness in its present artificial state " may possibly " have no claim to the title of a fact of consciousness generally, or to the unlimited credence given to what is originally consciousness" (p. 163). "We cannot study the original elements of our mind in the facts of our present consciousness " (p. 179). " Could we try the experiment of the first consciousness in any infant . . . what- ever was present in that first consciousness would be the genuine testimony of consciousness " (p. 178). And accord- ingly Mr. Mill complains, that "in all Sir W. Hamilton's writings " no " single instance can be found in which, before registering a belief as a part of our consciousness from the beginning, he thinks it necessary to ascertain that it has not grown up subsequently " (p. 181). Of course Sir W. Hamilton never dreamed of the strange tenet here taken for granted by Mr. Mill. He never dreamed of the tenet, that what he called " consciousness " i.e., as Mr. * We expressed this theory, however, somewhat incorrectly. Mr. Mill, we said, "seems to imply that the laics of man's mental constitution are changed during his progress from infancy to manhood." The theory we are criticizing has faults enough of its own to answer for, but need not be understood as involving so greut a paradox as this. Mr. Mill pointed out to us this misapprehension in a private letter. Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review!' 149 Mill himself explains, " immediate and intuitive conviction " is no rule of certitude, except as regards its primordial avouchments. This tenet, indeed we must really be allowed to say- is so transparently shallow that we were very unwilling to believe it could be Mr. Mill's. In our first essay accord- ingly we declared, " we cannot persuade ourselves that he really means what he seems to say." When, however, we looked more narrowly at Mr. Mill's language with a view to our third essay, we arrived at a different conclusion ; and "we found his meaning," as we said, "much more pronounced and unmistakable than we had fancied." We observed particularly (what had escaped our notice) that he alleges this theory in direct opposition to the other, as his reason for upholding what he calls the " psycho- logical" as contrasted with the " introspective " method of philosophizing ("On Hamilton," p. 179). This consideration is decisive. We are obliged accordingly to credit this grave writer with the theory which he so energetically professes, and to understand him as holding that no declaration of my cognitive faculties is trustworthy, unless it be a declaration which those faculties would have put forth when I was " an infant ; " when I " first opened my eyes to the light " (" On Hamilton," p. 178). Certainly he has here assumed very solid ground against necessists.* He may very safely challenge them to show, if they can, that when they were infants, first opening their eyes to the light, their faculties would have avouched as a necessary truth the triangularity of trilateral, or the divergency of two intersecting straight lines. But then he absolutely slaughters himself, by the weapon which ho raises against his opponents. We would thus address one * The word " necessarian is irretrievably appropriated to the purpose of designating those who deny /rec icill. We have coined, therefore, the word in the text, to express an idea for which some word or other ix urgently needed. lf>0 Tie Philosophy of Theism. of his disciples. You are very confident, doubtless, that you really experienced this or that fact, which you re- member to have occurred an hour or so ago ; and you will very readily admit that if such memory were not trust- worthy, experimental science would be even more utterly impossible 'than metaphysical. Yet have you any ground (even the faintest) for even conjecturing, that when you were a new-born infant or, for that matter, when you were a baby half a year old your memory could truly testify the experience of your last hour ? Of course not. When, therefore, Mr. Mill assumes the trustworthiness, whether of his own or other men's memory, he is suicidally abandon- ing the " psychological," and contenting himself with the " introspective " method. Or, in other words, that "psy- chological" method, which he regards as the one safeguard of sound philosophy, overthrows the whole possibility of experimental science. But, in fact, we are greatly understating the case. Take any one of Mr. Mill's living disciples. We have been saying that, on his own theory, the avouchments of his present memory are not primarily and immediately known by him as true. But in our third essay we have further urged, that (on his own theory) he has no means of even making the inquiry whether they be true or no. He can- not, we say, so much as begin to investigate the question whether his existing memory be trustworthy, without taking for granted that it is so ; for, unless he trust his existing memory, he cannot so much as draw the most obvious of conclusions from the simplest of premisses. But if he takes for granted that the avouchments of his present memory are true, then he is taking the present, and not the primordial, declaration of his faculties as his rule of certitude. We cannot conjecture why Mr. Mill has left wholly unanswered this very direct objection, which w T e had so clearly and definitely expressed. Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Review." 151 So far we have argued against this amazing theory from its consequences. We have maintained that, by up- holding it, Mr. Mill inflicts on himself no less a calamity than that of philosophical suicide. Let us now in turn consider the same theory as regards the evidence adducible for its truth. It is necessarily an essential part of the foundation on which Mr. Mill's whole philosophy rests ; and we have a right to expect, therefore, that it shall itself be inexpugnable. Yet was there ever, we ask, a more gratuitous and arbitrary dictum than that whatever men's faculties declared in their primordial condition, is infallibly true ? On what ground (from his point of view) could Mr. Mill even guess, that whatever a baby's memory distinctly testifies is infallibly true ? Was there ever otherwise such a basis as this attempted for a philosophical system ? such a foundation as this laid down as the one support of all human knowledge ? The whole mass of human knowledge is made utterly dependent on what is about the most gratuitous and arbitrary hypothesis which can well be imagined. Do we, then, ourselves, Mr. Mill might ask, doubt that the avouchment of men's faculties in their earlier state is infallibly true ? Speaking generally, we do not doubt this at all ; though we should be sorry to commit ourselves on Mr. Mill's case, of the new-born infant first opening his eyes to the light. But we maintain confidently that the veracity of my primordial faculties instead of being a primary truth is an inference from the veracity of my present faculties. Our position is most intelligible. What- ever my existing faculties indubitably declare I am under a necessity of infallibly knowing to be true, and I infer from this fact that I possess a special gift (called by scholastics the light of reason) which authenticates the veracity of these faculties. Of these none is more vitally essential than that of memory; and by uicuns of this 152 The Philosophy of Theism. faculty I know with infallible certainty a large number of facts in my past life. Looking back at these, I find myself to have possessed, at every period to which my memory reaches, the same light of reason which I possess now ; and I infer, therefore, that then, no less than now, my faculties were veracious. In one word, the veracity of men's faculties in their earlier state is inferred from their present veracity ; whereas Mr. Mill, by a preposterous inversion of the natural order, would authenticate the present by means of the past. Such is the contrast we would draw between the theories of what may respectively be called " primordial " and " existing " certitude. At the same time, we have been uniformly careful to urge that there may be serious mis- takes in interpreting the avouchment of men's existing faculties. Particularly, we altogether admitted in our first essay, "that again and again inferences are so readily and imperceptibly drawn as to be most easily mistaken for intuitions." In accordance with this we pro- ceeded to say, that " in arguing hereafter with Mr. Mill wo shall have no right of alleging aught as certainly a primi- tive truth without proving that it cannot be an opinion derived inferentially from experience." In our third essay we acted sedulously on this principle : we argued carefully that those moral judgments, which we were maintaining to be intuitive, could not possibly be derived from experience, however rapid and imperceptible the process of inference might be supposed to be. We have no means of knowing on what ground Mr. Mill would base his opposition to the conclusions of that essay ; but we still strongly incline to the opinion there expressed, that he would oppose it in no other way than by falling back on his own amazing theory of primordial certitude. In regard to our second essay, our impression is different. The main purpose of that essay was to establish Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Review." 153 against Mr. Mill the doctrine that the whole body of mathematical truth possesses the attribute of necessity. Now, if Mr. Mill really admitted that men's cognitive faculties in their existing state declare this doctrine, and if he denied the doctrine on no other ground than that the faculties of a new-born infant would give no such testimony, we should consider him abundantly refuted by the preceding remarks. But we still think, as we thought when we wrote the essay, that he assumes ground far stronger and more plausible than this. He alleges, we think, that necessists do not accurately analyze the declaration of their existing faculties. I consider myself e.g. to cognize, as a self- evident and necessary truth, that every trilateral figure is triangular : but Mr. Mill would reply, that experience has most unexceptionally united in my mind the two ideas of trilateralness and triangularity ; and that accordingly I mistake for intuition what is really a rapid and unconscious inference from experience. In the remaining part of our essay, then, this is the issue to be handled. And in this later part of our discussion we are far more favourably cir- cumstanced than we have been in our earlier. Hitherto we have trodden ground on which Mr. Mill can hardly be said to have entered into express controversy with us at all, because of his silence on our first essay, and on that part of our third which is connected therewith. But as to our second essay on the necessary character of mathematical truth he has encountered us explicitly, and said all which he deemed necessary for our refutation. Wo have the immense advantage, therefore, of knowing all which can be said against us by that opponent, who is (to our mind), immeasurably the ablest and most persuasive of his school. Certainly at the outset, Mr. Mill's theory on mathe- matical axioms is very startling. If 1 were asked what arc l:">4f The, Philosophy of Thcixm. those truths which are best known to me by constant and uniform experience, all the world except phenomenist philosophers would be greatly surprised by any hesitation in my reply. The truths, I should answer, best known to me by constant and uniform experience are such as these : that fire burns ; that water quenches fire ; that wood floats on water, while stones sink therein, etc. But Mr. Mill tells me, that this reply is a complete mistake ; that there is another class of truths, known to me by experience with an immeasurably greater degree of familiarity than those just mentioned. I ask in amazement to what truths he can possibly be referring ; and he tells me, to such as these : that trilateral are triangular, and that intersecting straight lines mutually diverge. This is indubitably his proposition ; for consider : I have no tendency whatever to regard the former class of truths (the effect of water upon fire, etc.) as eternal and immutable ; whereas he assures me, that my considering the latter class (the triangularity of trilaterals, etc.) to possess these attributes arises exclu- sively from their having been to me such constant matters of experience. He considers, therefore, that the triangularity of trilaterals has been to me an immeasurably more constant matter of experience than have been the most familiar and every-day properties of fire and water. And while this is indubitably Mr. Mill's thesis, no less indubit- ably at first hearing it startles me beyond expression. Ask the vast majority of Englishmen how often they have observed that fire burns or that water quenches it ; they will reply they have experienced it almost every day of their lives. Ask them, on the contrary, how often they have observed that trilaterals are triangular; they will tell you that they have never to their knowledge experi- enced it from the day they were born. Mr. Mill's statement, then, is assuredly on the surface a startling paradox ; and we are confident that closer examination will show Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Review!' 155 it to be undeniably and demonstrably erroneous. This closer examination is what we are now to undertake, and we will begin with reciting certain argumentative pre- liminaries : I. We did not in our essay attempt any analysis of the word " necessary," nor even inquire whether such analysis is possible. "Our present purpose," we said, "will lead us only to attempt such a delineation and embodiment of this idea as shall make clear the point at issue. When we call a proposition "necessary," then, we mean to say that its contradictory is an intrinsically impossible chimera ; is that which could not be found in any possible state of existence ; which even Omnipotence would be unable to effect." To this explanation of the word Mr. Mill's silence gives consent. II. Mr. Mill himself is a phenomenist, one who avowedly denies the cognizableness of necessary truth as such. If he admitted that there is so much as one science which is conversant throughout with necessary truth, he would, ipso facto, be going over bag and baggage to what is now his enemies' camp. It was well worth while, then, as we said, " to choose some special field whereon to join issue as a specimen of the rest." Now, " there is one particular class of truths, which will be generally accepted as in every respect most fitted to effect a clear and salient result." Our contention then was, that mathematical truths vast and inexhaustible as is their number are cognizable by mankind as necessary. III. But it was possible very greatly to narrow this issue. "Mr. Mill will not of course deny that, if mathe- matical axioms are necessary, the validity of syllogistic reasoning must be also a necessary verity; and that the whole body, therefore, of mathematical truth possesses the same character." Our thesis was accordingly, " that mathematical axioms (arithmetical, algebraic, geometrical) 156 Tlie Philosophy of Theism. are self-evidently necessary truths." And by the term " axioms," for the purpose of our discussion, we under- stood "those verities which mathematicians assume as indubitably true, and use as the first premisses of their science." Mr. Mill tacitly accepts all this as a fair and straightforward joining of issue. IV. We next come to a question of words. It is plain that propositions may be divided, if we please, into two classes : those which express no more than has been already expressed by the subject, and those which do express more. Now, it so happens that a distinction, sub- stantially similar to this, is of vital importance in the dis- cussion between necessists and phenomenists ; and it is very desirable, therefore, that names shall be given to the two above-named classes. All non-Catholics since Kant, of either school, have used the words " analytical " and " synthetical " for this purpose. But a Catholic cannot so use these words without risk of serious misconception, because Catholic philosophy has affixed to them quite a different sense. What Catholics mean by calling a pro- position " analytical " so F. Kleutgen explains is that " by simply considering the idea of the subject and predicate, one comes to see that there exists between them that relation which the proposition expresses." But, as we shall immediately urge, a most important class of those propo- sitions which non-Catholics call " synthetical " possess the very property mentioned by F. Kleutgen ; and these are accordingly denominated by Catholics " analytical." In our second essay, we attempted to evade this difficulty by calling these two classes respectively "tautologous " and " significant." An able writer, however, in the Spectator was reasonably led by this nomenclature to misunderstand some of our remarks ; and we cannot our- selves, on consideration, defend its appropriateness. We will adopt, therefore, the words used by Sir W. Hamilton Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Revieiv" 157 for the purpose before us, and will use the two words, " explicative," " ampliative." From this, moreover, we obtain the incidental advantage, that these two phrases are to our mind really more fitted to express the intended distinction than the other two. We will define, then, these two terms thus. " Explicative " propositions are those which declare no more than that some idea (1) is, or (2) is not, identical with or included in some other idea. If the former, they are " positively explicative ; " if the latter, " negatively" so. "Ampliative " propositions are those which declare more than this. And it may be worth while to add, that various propositions rank technically under the former head which in common parlance would not be called so much as "explicative," but are mere truisms : as " this apple is this apple," or "is an apple." V. All positively explicative propositions are at once reducible to the principle of identity " A is A." Take e.g. as one example, " all hard substances resist pressure : " there is no meaning in this proposition, except that " all hard substances are hard ; " or " all substances which resist pressure resist pressure." * VI. A second purely verbal explanation. " Self-evident " truths, in the present essay, are by no means the same thing with " primary " truths, but are only a particular class of them. All those truths are " primary," which are known to human beings immediately, and which need not to be inferred from other truths. But we call no truth "self-evident," unless it be cognized as certain by merely pondering the proposition which expresses it ; by pene- * We may be allowed a moment's digression to repeat a remark nmdo by us on a former occasion. We suggested that what have been called " the fundamental laws of thought," are but different exhibitions of the principle of identity. Thus, the principle of contradiction ; "anything which is not B is not B;" the principle of excluded middle; "anything which is not B i not B." 15cS The Philosophy of Theism. trating and comparing with each other the ideas respec- tively expressed by the proposition's subject and predicate. The fact that I was miserably cold a short time ago if it be a fact is to me a " primary" truth : nevertheless it is not a "self-evident" one, because it is known to me as certain, not by my pondering the proposition which ex- presses it, but by my consulting the attestation of my memory.* We should add, that these self-evident truths are called by scholastic writers " principles " and " axioms." The latter term is of much philosophical service ; but the word " principles " has in English so many different senses that we do not think it very well fitted to be a technical term. In our present discussion we must refrain from using even the word " axioms " in its scholastic sense, because Mr. Mill gives the name "axioms" to the first premisses of mathematical science, while denying that those premisses are self-evident. There is another expression, common in modern philosophy. Those truths are said to be " cog- nizable a priori," which may be known independently of experience, whether they be self-evident or only dcducible from self-evident premisses. Such truths are called in Catholic philosophy " metaphysically certain." VII. All self-evident truths are necessary. This follows at once from the theory of certitude. Take the proposition " every trilateral is triangular : " and let us assume for the moment that this proposition is self-evident; or in other words that it is known by me to be true, if I do but duly ponder it. But, as we urged in the earlier part of our essay, the declaration of my faculties infallibly corre- sponds with objective truth. Take therefore any trilateral which can exist in the universe which can be formed * We are well aware that we did not in our former essays preserve this distinction of meaning between "primary" and "self-evident," but we are of opinion that it will be found conducive to clearness of thought. Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review" 159 by Omnipotence itself I know infallibly of this trilateral that it is triangular. It will be seen, then, by reverting to that very explanation of the word "necessary" which we gave at starting, that the triangularity of every trilateral if it be a "self-evident" must also be a "necessary" truth. VIII. Mr. Mill nowhere, of course, dreams of denying that all explicative propositions are self-evident. And certainly though he would doubtless wish to avoid the word "necessary" we take for granted he would admit that the truth " A is A " must hold good in every possible sphere of existence.* It is not therefore absolutely accu- rate to say that he denies the cognizableness of any necessary truth, but only of any necessary truth which is not purely explicative. At the same time, we most heartily concur with him in holding that these truths " A is A," "B is B," "C is C" though they went through all the letters of a thousand alphabets are utterly sterile, and cannot by any possible mutual combination germinate into an organic whole. There can be no syllogism without a middle term. Although, therefore, it may not be strictly true to say that Mr. Mill denies all necessary truth, he does deny the possibility of any necessary science ; and denies also the cognizableness of any such necessary truths as we may call " fruitful." IX. On the other hand, he holds as firmly as we do, that mathematical axioms are ampliative and not explicative : indeed, he would consider, as we do, that this fact is suffi- ciently proved by the very existence of mathematical science. Take our ordinary instance, " all trilateral are triangular:" no one would dream of saying that the idea " triangular " * Yet we observe that even thus we tnko ton much for granted. " Whether the three so-called fundamental laws," he says ("On Hamilton," p. 491) and tho principle of identity is one of these three "are laws of our thoughts . . . inn-ly liecaiiae we perce.ioe tken to be univertally true of all obstrced plienoniena, I will not positively decide." 1 GO TJie Ph ilosopfiy of Theism. is identical with, or contained in, the idea " trilateral." * And though some able writers have maintained that the axioms of arithmetic are purely explicative, this is not the place to oppose them ; because Mr. Mill dissents from them as eagerly and as confidently as we do. We briefly referred to this question in our second essay. We are thus at last brought to the point at issue between Mr. Mill and ourselves. He denies, whereas we amrm, that various ampliative propositions are self-evident and neces- sary. And we are now to join issue on mathematical axioms, as being special and critical instances of the general class " ampliative." In general accordance with what has been expressed, we thus laid down in our second essay the immediate ground on which the discussion was to turn. "If in any case," we said, " I know by my very conception of some ens, that a certain attribute, not included in that conception, is truly predicable of that ens, such predication is a self- evident necessary proposition." These words defined with strict accuracy, as our readers will have seen, the kind of necessary truth of which Mr. Mill certainly denies the exist- ence, though they are incidentally faulty in expression, as imping that explicative propositions are not necessary. Mr. Mill himself might admit, though in different phrase- ology, that explicative propositions are self-evident and necessary ; and the controversy between him and ourselves turns on the question whether certain ampliative proposi- tions are not self-evident and necessary also. Moreover, as has been seen, (/"they are self-evident, it follows that they are necessary. Here, then, is the direct and central combat we have to * F. Kleutpen avowedly concurs with Kant's doctrine, on the cognizable- ness of " synthetical a priori propositions " as self-evident ; differing only from him on the appropriateness of this particular word " synthetical." On this particular there is no difference of doctrine, but only of words, between other writers of the s.-hola*tic following and the philosopher of Konigsberg. Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Revieu'." Ifil fight out with Mr. Mill, and we beg our readers to con- centrate on it their best attention. We take, as our pattern specimen, the judgment " all trilaterals are triangular." We maintain (1) that this judgment is ampliative : because (as is manifest) the idea "triangular" is neither identical with, nor contained in, the idea "trilateral." We maintain (2) that this judgment is self-evident : because its truth is known by duly pondering the proposition which expresses it ; because, as soon as I have apprehended it, I need not go ever so little beyond the region of my own thoughts in order to cognize its truth. Mr. Mill's reply is substantially as follows ; and we print his whole paragraph in a note, that our readers may judge for themselves whether we have misconceived him.* The proposition " all trilaterals are triangular " so Mr. Mill answers in effect is indubitably ampliative ; because the idea expressed by the predicate is not identical with, nor contained in, that expressed by the subject. But the judgment expressed by the proposition is * " It is not denied nor deniable that there are properties of things which we know to be true (as Dr. Ward expresses it) by our ' very conception ' of the thing. Hut this is 110 argument against our knowing tin m solely by ex- perience, for these are cases iu which, in the very process of forming tho conception, we have experience of the fact. It is not likely that Dr. Ward has returned to the notion (so long abandoned and even forgotten by in- tuitionists) of ideas literally innate, and thinks that we bring into the world the conception of a trilateral figure ready made. He doubtless believes that it is at least suggested by observation of objects. Now, the fact of three sides and that of three angles are so intimately linked together in external nature, that it is impossible for the conception of a three-sided figure to get into the mind without carrying into the mind with it the conception of three angles. Therefore, when we have once got the conception of a trilateral, we have no need of further experience to prove triangularity. The conception itself, which represents all our previous experience, suffices. And if the association theory be true, it must follow from it that whenever any property of external things is in the relation to the things which is required for the formation of an inseparable association, that property will got into the con- ception, and be believed without further proof. Dr. Ward will say that triangularity is not included in the conception of trilateral. Hut this is only true in the sense that triangularity is not in the connotation of the name. Many attributes, not included in the definition, :ire included in the conception. Dr. Ward cannot but see that <>n the experience h\ jMithesis, this not only may but luiiat be the case." ("On Hamilton," p. :;:!7, note.) \i>|.. |. M 102 Tic Plnlwopby of Theism. not arapliative at all, but explicative.* Why ? Because, in consequence of the singular uniformity of my past experience, I have come to include triangularity in my very idea of trilateralness ; because, through this uniformity of experience, I have acquired an inability of thinkinij of a figure as trilateral without at the same moment (implicitly, at least) thinking of it as triangular. According to Mr. Mil], then, when an adult expresses the proposition that "all trilaterals are triangular," the judgment which he elicits would be truly analyzed and expressed by a different pro- position ; by the proposition, that " all figures which have; three sides and three angles are triangular." But this proposition is of course purely explicative, and is admitted by Mr. Mill himself to be self-evident. We are so very confident of our cause, that we earnestly desire to exhibit Mr. Mill's theory at its thoroughly best advantage. We will put it, therefore, this way. The pro- position was once placed before me for the first time in a formulized shape (perhaps in some "object-lesson"), that " horses differ greatly from each other in colour." Though (by hypothesis) I have never before expressly contemplated that proposition in form, I at once recognize it as expressing a freshly familiar truth ; a truth vividly known to me by every day's experience. Now, the very same thing took place so Mr. Mill would say when the proposition was first placed before me in a formulized shape, that " all trilaterals are triangular : " I recognize it at once, as ex- pressing a freshly familiar truth, vividly known to me by * It may be asked how our ascription of this opinion to Mr. Mill is recon- cileable with our recent statement, that he regards mathematical axioms as ampliative propositions. But the answer is moot easy. According to him, my judgment that all trilaterals are triangular was ampliative when first I formed it, and indeed for a considerable time afterwards. He considers that it was first formed through my experience of external nature ; and that it became more and more familiar and intensified by the same cause until at last (as explained in the text) it became part of my mind's habitual furniture and is easilv mistaken for an intuition. Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Review." 163 every day's experience. According to Mr. Mill, the triangu- larity of trilaterals is a truth as freshly known to me by daily experience as is the fact that horses are of different colours or that wood floats on water. Nay, according to Mr. Mill, the first-named truth is known to me with in- definitely greater freshness of familiarity than are the two latter. For consider : Mr. Mill admits that all mankind are under an incapacity of conceiving that even Omni- potence could form a non-triangular trilateral ; whereas no one of cultivated mind has the slightest difficulty in con- ceiving that Omnipotence could make wood sink in the water, or could make all horses of the same colour. And it is Mr. Mill's precise allegation, that this contrast arises exclusively from the fact that experience is so very much more peremptorily uniform (if we may so express ourselves) in testifying the triangularity of trilaterals than in testifying the above-named properties of wood and of horses.* Mr. Mill's contention, then, is as follows : " The truth that all trilaterals are triangular, is known by every one with * "Dr. Ward says that mere constant and uniform experience cannot possibly account for the mind's conviction of self-evident necessity. Nor do I pretend that it does. The experience must not only be constant and uni- form, but the juxtaposition of the facts in experience must be immediate and close; as well as early, familiar, and so free from even the semblance of an exception that no counter-association could possibly arise." (" On Hamilton," p. 339, note.) "Whether the" mathematical "axiom needs con- tinuation or not, it receives confirmation in almost every instant of our lives. . Experimental proof crowds in upon us in such endless profusion, and without one instance in which there can be even a suspicion of an exception, to the rule, that we should soon have stronger ground for believing the axiom, even as an experimental truth, than we have for almost any of tins general truths which we confessedly learn from the evidence of the senses. Independently of a priori evidence, we should certainly believe it with an intensity of conviction far greater than we accord to any ordinary physical truth. . . . Where, then, is the necessity for assuming that our recognition of those truths lias a different origin from the rest of our knowledge, when its existence is perfectly accounted for by supposing its origin to be tho same? when the causes which produce belief in all other instances exist in this instance, nnd in a degree of strength ns much superior to what exists in other cases as the intensity of the belief itself is superior?" (" Logic," vol. i. p lii'.T.) 1 G4 The Ph ilotophy of Thritnn . indefinitely greater freshness of familiarit}" than the truth that wood floats upon water." This is what he affirms, and what we deny ; and it is precisely on this point that issue is joined. As politicians would say, we cannot desire a better issue than this to go the country upon. We affirm as an in- dubitable matter of fact, that Mr. Mill is here contradicted by the most obvious experience. We affirm as an indu- bitable matter of fact, that ninety-nine hundredths of man- kind not only do not know the triangularity of trilateral with this extraordinary freshness of familiarity, but do not know it at all. Those who have not studied the elements of geometry with hardly an exception if they were told that trilateral are triangular, and if they understood the statement, would as simply receive a new piece of informa- tion as they did when they w r ere first told the death of Napoleon III. Then, as to those who are beginning the study of mathematics. A youth of fifteen, we said in our second essay, is beginning to learn geometry, and his tutor points out to him that every trilateral is triangular. Does he naturally reply as he would if his tutor were telling him that horses are of different colours "of course the fact is so ; I have observed it a thousand times " ? On the contrary, in all probability the proposition will be entirely new to him ; and yet, notwithstanding its novelty, will at once commend itself as a self-evident truth.* Lastly, take those w T ho learned the elements of geometry when they were young, and are now busily engaged in * Mr. Mill does not directly reply to this allegation of ours. Nor does he notice Mr. Mahuffy's testimony, quoted by us in the note. " A mathe- matical friend," says the latter, " told me he perfectly well remembered, when a boy, being taught, without understanding it, the axiom, that two straight lines cannot enclose a space. When the fourth projwsition of Euclid was shown to him, he remembers the universality and necessity of the axiom at once flashing on him." J/r. Mill's Reply to the " DiiUin Review" 105 political, or forensic, or commercial life. If the triangularity of trilatejals were mentioned to them, they would remember, doubtless, that they had been taught in their youth to see the self-evidence of this truth ; but they would also re- member, that for years and years it had been absent from their thoughts. Is it seriously Mr. Mill would allege, that they know the triangularity of trilateral with the same freshness of familiar experience (or rather with indefinitely greater freshness of familiar experience) with which they know the tendency of fire to burn and of water to quench it ? or with which they respectively know the political events of the moment, or the practice of the courts, or the habits of the Stock Exchange ? If he did allege this in his zeal for a theory, we should confidently appeal against so eccentric a statement to the common sense and common experience of mankind. But is it not, then, Mr. Mill might ask, a matter to every man of every-day experience, that trilaterals are triangular? If by "every-day experience" he means "every day observation " and his argument requires this, we answer confidently in the negative. Even if we could not lay our finger on the precise fallacy which has misled Mr. Mill, it would be none the less certain that he has been misled. It cannot possibly be true that the triangularity of trilaterals is a matter to every man of every-day observa- tion, because (as we said just now) patently and undeniably the mass of men know nothing whatever hy of Tfieiwn. therefore any thought of that figure, either explicitly or implicitly, enters my mind. I am probably musing on matters indefinitely more interesting and exciting ; the prospects of the coming parliamentary division, or the point of law which I am going down to argue, or the symptoms of the patient whom I am on my way to visit, or the pro- bable fluctuation of the funds. The keen geometrician may see trilaterals in stocks and stones, and think of trilateral* on the slightest provocation : but what proportion of the: human race are keen geometricians ? Then, secondly still excluding these exceptional geome- tricians for a hundred times that observation might suggest to me the thought of a trilateral, not more than once perhaps will it suggest to me the triangularity of such trilateral. Mr. Mill himself will admit, we suppose, that such explicit observation is comparatively rare ; but he will urge, probably, that I implicitly observe the triangularity of every trilateral which I remark. We will make, then, a very simple sup- position, for the purpose of testing this suggestion, as well as for one or two other purposes connected with our argu- ment. We will suppose that all rose stalks within the reach of human observation had leaves of the same shape icith each other. On such supposition, the shape of its stalk-leaves would be a more obvious and obtrusive attribute of the rose than is triangularity of the trilateral ; and yet, beyond all possibility of doubt, one might very frequently observe a rose, without even implicitly noticing the shape of its stalk- leaves. The present writer can testify this at first-hand. In a life of sixty odd years, he has often enough smelt roses and handled their stalks, and yet he had not the slightest notion whether their leaves are or are not similarly shaped, until he asked the question for the very purpose of this illustration. And it is plain that if he has not observed the mutual dissimilarity of their leaves, neither would he have observed their similarity did it exist. Now, we appeal to Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review:' 1G7 our readers' common sense, whether what we said at start- ing is not undeniably true ; viz. that every ordinary person is very far more likely to observe the shape of rose-stalk leaves, than to observe the number of angles formed by the sides of a trilateral. At the same time, we fully admit that many a man may have implicitly observed the similarity of shape in rose-stalk leaves (supposing such similarity to exist) without having explicitly adverted to the fact until he heard it mentioned ; and in like manner this or that man may have implicitly observed the triangularity of various trilaterals. But such a circumstance does but give occasion to another disproof of Mr. Mill's theory. Suppose I have implicitly observed the former phenomenon. I hear the proposition stated, that the shape of all rose-stalk leaves is similar, and I set myself to test its truth by my former experience. I consult my confused remembrance of numerous instances in which I have looked at rose-stalks, and I come to assert, with more or less positiveness, that all those within my observa- tion have had similar leaves. On the other hand, I wish, let us suppose, to test the proposition that all trilaterals are triangular. If Mr. Mill's theory were true, I should proceed as in the foregoing instance ; I should contemplate my confused remembrance of numerous instances in which 1 have observed the triangularity. But the fact is most different from this. I do not consult at all my memory of past experience, but give myself to the contemplation of some imaginary trilateral, which I have summoned into my thoughts. And the impression which I receive from such contemplation is not at all that the various trilaterals / hare observed in times punt are triangular, but that in no possible world could non-triangular trilaterals exist. Observe, then, these two respective cases. My jirocexx of reason has been fundamentally different in the two ; and the imprrxxion tihi<'h I ircrirc from that process will have been funda- 1 OS Thf Pit ilo*ophy of Theism. mentally different in the two : consequently the two cases are fundamentally different, instead of being (as they would be on Mr. Mill's theory) entirely similar. Our readers will observe that we have just now twice used the word " impression," instead of such more definite terms as "cognition" or "intuition." Our reason for this is easily given. Hy the admission of Mr. Mill himself, every adult who gives his mind to the careful thought of trilateral, receives the impression that their triangularity is a necessary truth : but Mr. Mill denies that this impression is a genuine intuition, and we could not of course assume what Mr. Mill denies. Here we bring to a close the exhibition of our first argument against Mr. Mill ; an argument which we must maintain to be simply final and conclusive, even if no second were adducible. According to his theory, the triangularity of trilaterals (or any other geometrical axiom) is a pheno- menon known to all men with as great freshness of familiarity as the phenomenon that fire burns, or that water quenches it ; or rather, the former class of phenomena is known to all men with incomparably greater freshness of familiarity than the latter. But such a proposition is undeniably inconsistent with the most patent and indubitable facts. This circumstance would of course be fatal to Mr. Mill, even though we were entirely unable to account for it psychologically ; but (as we have further argued) it can be psychologically accounted for with the greatest possible ease. , A second argument has been incidentally included in our exposition of the first. The mental process, whereby I come to cognize the truth of a geometrical axiom, is funda- mentally different from the mental process, whereby I come to recognize the truth of an experienced fact ; whereas, on Mr. Mill's theory, these two processes would be simply identical. Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Revieic:' 160 There is a third and perfectly distinct line of argument, which has been urged with great cogency by modern neces- sists against the phenomenistic school. We have hitherto been advocating the necessary character of geometrical axioms, as an inferential truth ; and this is the line (we think) most in harmony with the ordinary language of Catholic philosophers. But non-Catholic necessists have powerfully advocated the same truth, as one immediately declared by the human faculties. Let us revert to our specimen instance. We have hitherto contemplated the proposition, that " all trilaterals are triangular : " we have argued that the proposition is undeniably self-evident, and from this we have inferred that it is also necessary. But we will now contemplate a different proposition ; viz. th.it " the triangularity of trilaterals is a necessary truth." We maintain, in accordance with many modern philosophers, that this propostion is immediately declared by the human faculties ; that it is self-evident ; that it is recognized as true by a mere pondering of its sense and comparison of its terms. Mr. Mill himself admits that the declaration of the human faculties is prima fade in our favour ; while wo on our side allege that pro founder self-inspection does but corroborate and intensify men's primdfacic impression. We think, indeed, that in no way will the truth of our allegation be more effectively forced on the inquirer's conviction than by his considering (as we shall now proceed to do) Mr. Mill's attempted refutation thereof. He lays very great stress on this alleged refutation, and says that the principle on which it rests is one which intuitionists ought to have specially considered, "because it is the basis of the " phenomenistic "theory." ("On Hamilton," p. 814.) We can only reply. that the phenomenistic theory in that case rests on a basis of extraordinary frailty. Mr. Mill distinctly admits that, when the human miinl contemplates mathematical axioms, there arise* in it a 17<) The Philosophy of Theism. certain " conviction of self-evident necessity : " but he con- siders that this conviction can be satisfactorily explained, without accounting it a genuine intuition. These are his words in reply to ourselves : Dr. Ward says that more uniform and constant experience cannot possibly account for the mind's conviction of Keif-evident necessity. Nor do I pretend that it does. The experience must not only be constant and uniform, but the juxtaposition of the facts in experience must be immediate and close, as well as early, familiar, and so free from even the semblance of an ex- ception, that no counter-association can possibly arise. (" On Hamilton," p, 339.) Now, we must admit at once that this reply is no after- thought of Mr. Mill's, but that, on the contrary, he had repeatedly made the same statement on earlier occasions ; and, indeed, in one passage which we actually quoted (pp. 44, 45). We must admit, therefore, that in our second essay we did not sufficiently bear in mind Mr. Mill's previous explanation ; and we must accordingly withdraw a reply to him, which we pressed with some confidence, but which he has shown in his rejoinder to labour under this fault. This, however, of course by the way, as it does not affect the merits of Mr. Mill's argument itself. That argument, it will be seen, runs thus. That " conviction," he says, " of self-evident necessity," which I receive when I contemplate a geometrical axiom, cannot be shown to be a genuine intuition, because it may be accounted for in quite a different way. In irhat way ? we ask. He replies by the following syllogism. Major. " If there be a phenomenon so circumstanced, that not only my experience of it is constant and uniform, but the juxtaposition of facts in experience is immediate and close, and so free from even the persistent * semblance of an exception that no counter-association can possibly * Our reason for inserting the word " persistent" will presently appear. Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review." 171 arise an impression will inevitably be made on my mind, that this phenomenon is a self-evidently necessary truth." Minor. " But the triangularity of trilaterals, or any other geometrical axiom, is a phenomenon thus circumstanced." The consequent is obvious. Now, plainly Mr. Mill would do nothing for his cause, if we could successfully deny either of his premisses ; but it so happens that we confidently deny both. We will begin with the minor, which is expressed somewhat more clearly and emphatically a few pages earlier. A geometrical axiom, he says (p. 334), (1) is " founded on an experience beginning from birth, and never for many minutes intermitted in our waking hours : " while on the other hand (2) no counter- association is ever formed ; because " experience affords " no " case of persistent illusion " in which such axiom has even the semblance of being contradicted. We have said that we deny both Mr. Mill's major and his minor ; and \ve now add, that we deny also both the statements contained in his minor. We deny them altogether (1) that a geometrical axiom is " founded on an experience never for many minutes intermitted in our w^aking hours." On the contrary, as regards the mass of mankind, we affirm (and have already given ample reasons for our affirmation) that the triangu- larity of trilaterals has never been to them a matter of observation at all. Of course a necessist will be the last to deny that men's experience of such triangularity has been " constant and uniform " in this sense, that they have never once experienced any phenomenon inroitnistcnt therewith : but such an admission gives no help whatever to Mr. Mill's reasoning. Then, (2) what does Mr. Mill mean, when he further says that experience affords no case of persistent illusion in which any geometrical axiom h;is oven the semblance of contradicted? That there are "illusions" of the 172 Tie Fhilum-qJ'?/ "f Tlelvm. kind he expressly admits, though denying that such illusions are " persistent ; " for he proceeds at once to mention one himself. "In the case of parallel lines," he says, "the laws of perspective do present such an illusion : they do to the eye appear to meet in both directions, and consequently to inclose a apace." Mr. Mahaffy had given another instance, viz. a straight stick, appearing bent in the water, and presenting thereby an illusion contradictory to the axiom, that a straight line is the shortest way between two points. But Mr. Mill replies, that these are not " persistent " illusions ; and explains himself to mean (p. 335, note) that their " illusory character is at once seen, from the imme- diate accessibility of the evidence which disproves them." Observe what is involved in this. There are two different classes of truths, which we may be allowed for the present purpose to call geometrical and physical axioms respectively ; * both of which Mr. Mill regards as unknown except through experience. He admits, however, that the former class produce on the mind an inevitable impression of their being necessary, while the latter produce no such impression at all. We ask him to explain how this difference arises, if both classes really rest on the same kind of evidence. He replies firstly, that geometrical axioms are known by far more unintermittent observation than physical ; and on this part of his answer we have already rejoined. He replies secondly, that no persistent illusions befall me in which geometrical axioms have even the semblance of being contradicted ; whereas in the case of all physical axioms I am exposed to such illusions. In other words, according to Mr. Mill, I am from time to time under an illusion, that fire does not burn, nor stones sink in the water without any " evidence " being " immediately accessible " to me which would correct * We here are for the moment using the word " axioms" in the inaccurate sense of " obvious anearing bent in the water. I argued that on Mr. Mill's showing, these natural objects should have been sufficient to defeat " the supposed necessity, " and that still they were not so. ... I did not nieau to maintain [as Mr. Mill's answer implies] that mankind had reason to brliw that 1 = 2, or that a bent line was the shortest way between two points; but merely that, on Mr. Mill's own showing, we had a hiiHicient amount of experience to enable us to conceive it " (Kant's "Critical Philosophy," pp. 157, 158). 17-4 Tin 1 Philosophy of Theism. declared the necessity of a geometrical axiom ; just as it is impossible to know that they would have faithfully repre- sented to me my experience of one hour back. If Mr. Mill is prepared on that account to disbelieve the distinctest declarations of his memory, he will doubtless be consistent in disbelieving, on the same ground, the necessity of geometrical axioms. But as Mr. Mill always takes the trustworthiness of memory for granted, an appeal from him to men's primordial faculties as their rule of certitude is the most glaring of inconsistencies. "We are anxious, however, throughout so confident we are of our cause to exhibit Mr. Mill's position at its greatest possible advantage : and we will take for granted, therefore, that his appeal is to men's existing faculties. His major premiss, then, will be the following : " Let there be a phenomenon so circumstanced that not only my expe- rience of it is constant and uniform, but the juxtaposition of facts in experience immediate and close, and so free from the persistent semblance of an exception that no counter- association can possibly arise. In such case (1) a super- ficial impression will inevitably be made on my mind that this phenomenon is a self-evidently necessary truth ; but (2) my faculties, if carefully and accurately consulted, will declare such impression to be unfounded. Mr. Mill's major, then, like his minor, contains two separate statements ; and in the case of his major, moreover, just as in the case of his minor, we entirely deny them both. The first of these statements, however, is so com- paratively unimportant that a very few word swill suffice for its examination. Mr. Mill alleges a supposed psychological fact, viz. that certain conditions generate in the human mind an inevitable primd facie impression that certain propositions are necessary. What evidence does he adduce of this supposed fact ? Absolutely none. He may say, perhaps, that conclusive proof is impossible from the nature Mr. Mill's Reply to the " Dublin Review." 17o of the case ; that he does not even pretend that his con- ditions apply, except to propositions which his opponents regard as really necessary. But at least he might have applied something like what he calls " the method of con- comitant variation ; " he might have shown that in propor- tion as there is a nearer approach to the fulfilment of his conditions, in that proportion there is a nearer approacli to the generation of this superficial impression. But the fact is indubitably otherwise. All men have unceasing experience of certain very obvious physical phenomena; yet no one has the faintest appreciable tendency towards doubting that Omnipotence could make fire innocuous, could make wood sink in the water, or could make stones float thereon. But at last the question is one of fact, not theory ; and its gist lies in the second of the two statements which we have included in Mr. Mill's major. The question, in fact, is simply this : what do the human faculties declare con- cerning geometrical axioms ? We have always readily conceded to Mr. Mill, that a man's self-inspection is often very defective ; and that he will again and again carelessly ascribe to his faculties some avouchment which is not really theirs. As to this, however, there is one, and only one, reasonable appeal ; viz. from a superficial to a pro- founder examination of the human consciousness. Let as many competent inquirers as possible devote themselves to this examination ; let them, by painstaking introspection, ponder on the true nature of their mind's avouchment, when they contemplate the triangularity of a trilateral. Is that avouchment such as the following : " I have never met with nor heard of a non-triangular trilateral ? " Or is is not rather : " A non-triangular trilateral is an intrin- sically impossible chimera, which Omnipotence itself could not fashion ? " There arc several arguments, we consider, any one of which may with entire collusiveness be directed 1 TiJ The PI Uosupliy of The Ism . against Mr. Mill's theory : yet we could be content (were it requisite) to abandon them all, and to rest our whole case on the issue we have just raised. In fact, Mr. Mill's silence on this matter is the most emphatic controversial support which can well be imagined. It is impossible to obtain from him a categorical statement, that the existing faculties of an adult declare the "con- tingent " * character of mathematical axioms. We say, with some confidence, that no such statement is to be found in any of his writings ; and that just where we should most expect such a statement, he seems to check himself in full career, and fall back on his amazing theory of primordial certitude. In saying, then, most confidently that the human faculties declare the necessary character of geometrical axioms, we do but say what Mr. Mill himself nowhere ventures expressly to deny. So far we have been considering Mr. Mill's negative thesis, viz. that mathematical axioms are not cognizable as necessary truths. But his positive thesis is not so easily intelligible. No one (we believe) was ever more anxious than Mr. Mill to treat his opponents with perfect fairness ; but, in fact, he has altogether failed to treat them fairly in this particular matter, because he has kept so much in the background his own actual theory, on the degree of certitude possessed by these axioms, and on the grounds which he considers sufficient to establish that certitude. He declares, indeed, again and again, that their universal truth is amply proved by uniform experience ; but we find it most difficult to understand what he means by this allegation. Revert- ing to an earlier example, let us suppose that all rose-stalks, known as within human experience, have been observed to possess leaves similar in shape, what conclusion should * By " contingent," we need hardly say, is simply meant the contradictory of " nccedsary." Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Revieiv." 177 I have a right to draw from this circumstance ? I could not know that even in Dorsetshire or Hampshire, some fresh method of planting or sowing might not be found to produce indubitable roses, growing on stalks totally different in shape from those hitherto experienced ; and I could not even guess that, in some newly-discovered country, such rose-trees should not be found abundant. In like manner we do not see how Mr. Mill could reasonably even guess but that, in some newly-discovered country, a tree may be found the wood of which shall possess the capability of being formed into quadrangular trilaterals. He says, indeed, that the truth of mathematical axioms " pervades all nature ; " but how can he reasonably even guess that this is the case ? What stronger reason can he possibly have for his opinion that trilaterals are everywhere triangular, than his ancestors had for their opinion that all swans are white, and that all metals sink in the water ? * Here, however, as in several other instances, Mr. Mill has shown himself too clear-sighted to be quite satisfied with his own position ; and he takes refuge in a thinty- disguised reproduction of that very necessist theory, which he so energetically repudiates. This fact is so very curious and characteristic, that we beg our readers to give it special attention. " That a straight line is the shortest distance between two points, we do not doubt to be true," says Mr. Mill, " even in the region of the fixed stars." (" Logic," vol. i. pp. 302-803.) What right has Mr. Mill, we asked, to hold this truth without doubt ? He regards this axiom as merely a fact known by experience. But " in distant parts of the stellar regions," he affirms (vol. ii. p. 108), "where pheno- * "Thnt nil metals sink in wator wns a uniform experience, from tho origin of the human race to the discovery of potassium in the present century by Sir Humphry Davy. That all swans (ire white was a uniform experience down to the discovery of Australia " (Mill's " Loiric," vol. i. p. 30.')). VOL. I. N 178 The Philosophy of Theism. mena may be entirely unlike those with which we are acquainted, it would be folly to affirm confidently that " those laws prevail "which we have found to hold uni- versally on our own planet." In our second essay we asked him distinctly how he could reconcile these two statements ; how he could regard a certain property of stellar straight lines as a truth known by experience, while he admitted that the stellar region is beyond the reach of experience. Mr. Mills tacitly replies by correcting the earlier sentence. " That a straight line is the shortest distance between two points we do not doubt," he had said, "to be true, even in the region of the fixed stars." But now he adds in a note a qualification. " In strictness, wherever the present constitution of space exists ; which we have ample reason to believe that it does in the region of the fixed stars." In the new note of his work on Hamilton, written with avowed reference to our criticism, he expresses the same theory more fully. We italicize a few words. Only if space itself is everywhere what we conceive it to be, can our conclusions from the conception be everywhere objectively true. The truths of geometry are valid, wherever the constitution of space agrees with what is within our means of observation. That space cannot anywhere be differently constituted, or that Almighty power could not make a different constitution of it, we know not (p. 338, note). Here is a most undeniable ampliative proposition : viz. " wherever the present constitution of space exists, a straight line is always the shortest distance between two points." Yet Mr. Mill admits that this ampliative proposition is cognizable, independently of experience, as a "conclusion from the conception " of space. It is really difficult to imagine a more explicit surrender of the whole point at issue between him and ourselves. Or we may express the same self-contradiction of Mr. Mill's in a somewhat different shape. It is impossible, Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Review." 179 Mr. Mill confesses, to know by experience that in the stellar region trilaterals are triangular, because in that region "phenomena may be totally unlike those with which we are acquainted: " yet, according to him, I may confidently " conclude " their triangularity from my " conception " of stellar " space." In like manner, therefore, as to earthly trilaterals. I need not resort to experience for my know- ledge of their triangularity ; but I may " conclude " that attribute from my very " conception " of earthly " space." This is the very proposition which hitherto we have been engaged in affirming and he in denying. Here we close our direct and central conflict with Mr. Mill. We have confined our attention to geometrical axioms, and, indeed, almost exclusively to one such axiom ; because the more closely the issue can be narrowed, the greater hope there is of arriving at a definite decision. Nor is there any inconvenience in such a course : because (1) it is very easy for inquirers to apply to other mathematical axioms what has been said of one ; and because (2) if there were so much as one ampliative judgment which Mr. Mill admitted to be necessary, by that very admission he would be a refugee from the phenomenistic to the necessist camp. On arithmetical axioms in particular, we will content ourselves with placing on record the point at issue. We gave, as our specimen instance, the axiom "2 + 9 = 3 + 8;" and Mr. Mill replies to us, in the new edition of his work on Hamilton, at p. 839. While we confidently maintain against Mr. Mill that the axiom is self-evident, we never- theless entirely agree with him that it is deducible from one still simpler ; from the axiom that " change of arrange- ment makes no difference in the number of objects." * We heartily agree with him, that this latter judgment is * Mr. Mill Fays inadvertently, "change of position ;" but we need hardly point out that arithmetical axioms apply to succession in time, or indeed, to any other aggregation, no less than to position in place. 180 Tlte Philosophy of T fie ism. ampliative, and not merely explicative. On the other hand, whereas he alleges that nian's knowledge of it is derived only from experience, we maintain, on the contrary, that the axiom is not merely self-evident, hut among the most superficially ohvious of self-evident truths. After the dis- cussion of the previous pages, we need not trouble our readers with arguments on this head. One or two subordinate points were incidentally raised in our second essay, and it will be more satisfactory not to pass entirely over Mr. Mill's replies on those issues. At the same time, our notice of those replies must necessarily be very brief ; and we may mention to our readers for their relief, that they can pass over what follows without losing any essential part of our argument. (1) Mr. Mill had argued as follows : Many persons who have been frightened in childhood can never be alone in the dark without irrepressible terrors. Many a person is unable to revisit a particular place, or to think of a particular event, without recalling acute feelings of grief or reminiscences of suffering. If the facts which created these strong associations in individual minds had been common to all mankind from their earliest infancy, and had, when the associa- tions were fully formed, been forgotten, we should have had a necessity of thought ; one of those necessities which are supposed to prove an objective law, and an a priori mental connection between ideas. We replied to this that a mere necessity of feeling has never been affirmed to prove "an a priori connection between two ideas." Mr. Mill, however, thus rejoins (" On Hamilton," p. 329, note) : If the person in whose mind a given spot is associated with terrurs, had entirely forgotten the fact by which it came to be so; and if the rest of mankind, or even only a great number of them, felt the same terror on coming to the same place, and were equally unable to account for it ; there would certainly grow up a conviction that the place had a natural quality of Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Review" 181 terribleness, which would probably fix itself in the belief that the place was under a curse, or was the abode of some invisible object of terror. Of course we entirely deny this. We would ask any disciple of Mr. Mill this simple question. Let us suppose that Mr. Mill's conditions were fulfilled : we ask, u-hat is that particular ampliative judgment which, on that suppo- sition, men would suppose themselves to cognize as self- evident ? Mr. Mill avowedly cannot answer this question. They might think it self-evident, he says, that the place was under a curse, or they might think it self-evident that the place was the abode of some terrific object ; but it is not (according to him) more than probable that they would think it either the one or the other. (2) "We further objected that Mr. Mill had used the words "necessity of thought" in two different senses: a "law of nature whereby I necessarily think ;" and "a law of nature whereby I think as necessary." Mr. Mill replies ("On Hamilton," p. 339) that the on/?/ evidence "which can be given for my thinking a thing as necessary, is my neces- sarily thinking it. But we had adduced evidence of a totally different character. Mr. Mill proceeds indeed to say, that he has refuted our arguments for this different kind of evidence ; but our preceding pages have, we trust, suffi- ciently shown that his alleged refutation is invalid. (3) Mr. Mill admits that men possess the power of cognizing mathematical axioms by means of purely mental experience. He accounts for this power by " one of tho characteristic properties of geometrical forms ; " viz. " that they can be painted in the imagination with a distinctness equal to the reality." We urged against him that, in thus speaking, he entirely leaves out of account arithmetical and algebraic axioms ; though these, equally with geometrical, can be arrived at by purely mental experimentation. He replies ("On Hamilton," p. 340) as follows: 182 The Philosophy of Theism. I do not leave them out of account, but have assigned in my Logic another and equally conclusive reason why they can be studied in our conception alone; namely, that arithmetical and algebraic axioms, being true not of any particular kind of thing but of all things whatever, any mental conceptions what- ever will adequately represent them. We fully admH that in his " Logic " (vol. i. pp. 298- 295) Mr. Mill sets forth the true doctrine, that arithmetical axioms hold good, not of any particular kind of thing, but of all things whatever. But we cannot for the life of us see that he anywhere assigns this doctrine as a "reason why they can be studied " and known to be true, by men's " conception alone." On the contrary, as it seems to us, he distinctly denies that they can be so studied. These are his words: " All who wish to carry the child's mind with them in teaching arithmetic, all who wish to teach numbers and not mere ciphers, now teach it through the evidence of the senses" (p. 296). (4) There remains to be reconsidered, a reply we gave to an argument which Mr. Mill had based on Eeid's " Geometry of Visibles." It would carry us much too far, if we attempted to make our present rejoinder under- stood by those who do not clearly bear in mind our earlier remarks. We will here, therefore, presuppose them. Mr. Mill (" On Hamilton," p. 92, note) does not attempt, on his own account, any further discussion on the point ; but contents himself with maintaining that Reid was of the same mind with Mr. Mill himself, and with referring us to Eeid's own arguments. We are still perfectly confident that it is Mr. Mill who is opposing Eeid. It is certainly not very probable that Eeid can have intended to argue against the necessary character of mathematical axioms, considering that he habitually and earnestly upheld their necessary character. And there is one sentence of his which will put the matter beyond dispute. Mr. Mill's Reply to the "Dublin Review." 183 Reid conceived certain imaginary " Idomenians," who agree with human beings in every other particular, but who possess the sense of sight without any accompanying sense of touch. The Idomenians, he says, would regard as self- evident certain strange geometrical propositions; as, e.g., that " every straight line, being sufficiently produced, will re-enter into itself." The question between Mr. Mill and ourselves is this : whether in such an opinion they would be (according to Eeid) referring to that figure which human beings call a straight line ; or, on the contrary, to some totally different figure (viz. the arc of a great circle), which they will have learned to call by the name of a straight line. Mr. Mill maintains the former alternative, and we the latter. Now let our readers observe Reid's own words, especially those which we italicize : This small specimen of the geometry of visibles is intended ... to demonstrate the truth of what we have affirmed above ; namely, that those figures and that extension which are the immediate objects of sight [and which, therefore, are those con- templated by the Idomenians] are not the figures and the ex- tension about which common geometry is employed. (Hamilton's edition, p. 148.) Surely this is final and decisive. Our second essay, however, was not exclusively devoted to the discussion of mathematical axioms, but contained in its later part various general considerations, which tell importantly (as we think) against the doctrine of pheno- menism. There are only two of these which it has naturally fallen in Mr. Mill's way to answer ; and on one of the two relating to the faculty of memory we have rejoined in the early part of this essay. The remaining one concerns the very foundation of phenomenism. The whole body of doctrine accumulated by a phenomenist depends throughout on his premiss, that " the laws of nature are uniform." Let this premiss be successfully denied, and straightway 184 The Ph iloaophy of The ism. there is no phenoinenistic philosophy. We allege that phenomenists can adduce no grounds whatever, which will reasonably be accounted sufficient to establish their fundamental premiss ; and we criticized in that sense Mr. Mill's arguments for the desired conclusion. In the new edition of his Logic, Mr. Mill replies to our criticism (vol. ii. pp. 109-111) ; though we think few readers will fail to see how unsatisfactory is his self-defence. The question, however, is one of such fundamental importance in the conflict with phenomenism, that no merely perfunctory treatment of it is permissible. In our next essay on Mr. Mill, then, we hope to elucidate the matter in more detail. One or two other questions, more or less cognate, are in our mind, which we trust also to include in our next paper. And so much having been accomplished, we have every hope of continuing in subsequent papers without further interruption and still with Mr. Mill as our representative opponent the course of argument w r hich we originally pro- jected against that poison of antitheism, which just now so widely and so profoundly infects all the higher specula- tions of non-Catholic Europe. V. MR. MILL'S PHILOSOPHICAL POSITION.* IT is impossible to pursue our controversy with Mr. Mill without some preliminary notice of the very remarkable autobiography which has appeared in this last quarter. We will not ourselves, however, make any comment on Mr. Mill's personal qualities as therein exhibited : because (1) our argument concerns his philosophy, not himself; and because (2) any attempt at subtle appreciation of character is wholly beyond the present writer's power of thought and expression. We will supply our omission, however, as best we can, by placing before our readers large part of a very able criticism which appeared in the Spectator and with which on the whole we concur : That this curious volume delineates, on the whole, a man marked by the most earnest devotion to human good, and the widest intellectual sympathies, no one who reads it with any discernment can doubt. But it is both a very melancholy book to read, and one full of moral paradoxes. It is very sad, in the first instance, to read the story of the over-tutored boy, con- stantly incurring his father's displeasure for not being able to do what by no possibility he could have done, and apparently without any one to love. Mr. James Mill, vivacious talker, and " Autobiography. By JOHN STUART MILL. London: Longmans. An Examination of i'z'r William Hamilton's Philosophy. By JOHN STCAUT Mn,i,. Fourth Edition. London : Longmans. A Si/xtcm of Logic, Jlatiocinative and Inductive. By Jons STUART MILL. Eighth Edition. London : Longmans. 186 The Philosophy of Theism, in a narrow way powerful thinker as he was, was evidently as an educator, on his son's own showing, a hard master, anxious to reap what he had not sown, and to gather what he had not strewed ; or, as that son himself puts it, expecting " effects without causes." Not that the father did not teach the child with all his might, and teach in many respects well ; but then he taught the boy far too much, and expected him to learn besides a great deal that he neither taught him nor showed him where to find. The child began Greek at three years old, read a good deal of Plato at seven, . . . began logic at twelve, went through a "complete course of political economy" at thirteen, including the most intricate points of the theory of currency. He was a constant writer for the " Westminster Eeview" at eighteen, was editing Bentham's "Theory of Evidence " and writing habitual criticisms of the Parliamentary debates at nineteen. At twenty he fell into a profound melancholy on discovering that the only objects of life for which he lived the objects of social and political reformers would, if suddenly and completely granted, give him no happiness whatever. Such a childhood and youth, lived apparently without a single strong affection for his relation to his father was one of deep respect and fear, rather than love, and he tells us frankly, in describing the melancholy to which we have alluded, that if he had loved any one well enough to confide to him, the melancholy would not have been and resulting at the age of eighteen in the production of what Mr. Mill himself says might, with as little extravagance as would ever be involved in the application of such a phrase to a human being, be called "a mere reasoning machine," are not pleasant subjects of contemplation : even though it be true, as Mr. Mill asserts, that the over-supply of study and under-supply of love did not prevent his childhood from being a happy one. Nor are the other personal incidents of the autobiography of a different cast. Nothing is more remarkable than the fewness, limited character, and apparently, BO far as close intercourse was concerned, temporary duration, of most of Mr. Mill's friendships. The one close and intimate friendship of his life, which made up to him for the insufficiency of all others, that with the married lady who, after the death of her husband, became his wife, was one which for a long time subjected him to slanders, the pain of which his sensitive nature evidently felt very keenly. And yet he must have been aware that though in his own conduct he had kept free from all stain, Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 187 his example was an exceedingly dangerous and mischievous one for others, who might be tempted by his moral authority to follow in a track in which they would not have had the strength to tread. Add to this that his married life was very brief, only seven years and a half, being unexpectedly cut short, and that his passionate reverence for his wife's memory and genius in his own words, " a religion " was one which, as he must have been perfectly sensible, he could not possibly make to appear otherwise than extravagant, not to say an hallucination, in the eyes of the rest of mankind ; and yet that he was possessed by an irresistible yearning to attempt to embody it in all the tender and enthusiastic hyperbole of which it is so pathetic to find a man who gained his fame by his "dry-light" a master; and it is impossible not to feel that the human incidents in Mr. Mill's career are very sad. True, his short service in Parliament, when he was already advanced in years, was one to bring him much intellectual consideration and a certain amount of popu- larity. But even that terminated in a defeat, and was hardly successful enough to repay him for the loss of literary pro- ductiveness which those three years of practical drudgery im- posed. In spite of the evident satisfaction and pride with which Mr. Mill saw that his school of philosophy had gained rapid ground since the publication of his "Logic," and that his large and liberal view of the science of political economy had made still more rapid way amongst all classes, the record of his life which he leaves behind him is not, even in its own tone, and still less in the effect produced on the reader, a bright and happy one. It is "sicklied o'er with the pale cast of thought," and of thought that has to do duty for much, both of feeling and of action, which usually goes to constitute the full life of a large mind. And besides the sense of sadness which the human incidents of the autobiography produce, the intellectual and moral story itself is full of paradox which weighs upon the heart as well as the mind. Mr. Mill was brought up by his father to believe that Christianity was false, and that even as regards natural religion there was no ground for faith.* But in the mean time, he is most anxious to point out that religion, in what he thinks the best sense, is possible even to one who does not beliovo in God. That best sense is the sense in which religion stands for * This is certainly an urnler-statement, as we shall show presently iu the text 188 Thf Philosophy of Theism. an ideal conception of a perfect Being to which those who have euch a conception " habitually refer as the guide of their conscience : " an ideal, he says, " far nearer to perfection than the objective Deity of those who think themselves obliged to find absolute goodness in the author of a world so crowded with suffering and so deformed by injustice as ours." Unfortunately, however, this " ideal conception of a perfect Being " is not a power on which human nature can lean. It is merely its own best thought of itself; so that it dwindles when the mind and heart contract, and vanishes just when there is most need of help. This Mr. Mill himself felt at one period of his life. At the ago of twenty he underwent a crisis, which apparently corresponded in his own opinion to the state of mind that leads to " a Wesleyan's conversion." . . . It is clear that Mr. Mill felt the deep craving for a more permanent and durable source of spiritual life, than any which the most beneficient activity spent in patching up human institutions and laboriously recasting the structure of human society could secure him ; that he himself had a suspicion that, to use the language of a book he had been taught to make light of, his soul was thirsting for God, and groping after an eternal presence, in which he lived and moved and had his being. What is strange and almost burlesque, if it were not so melan- choly, is the mode in which this moral crisis culminates. A few tears shed over Marmontel's " Memoires," and the fit passed away : " Two lines of Coleridge, in whom alone of all writers I have found a true description of what I felt, were often in my thoughts, not at this time (for I had never read them), but in a later period of the same mental malady " ' Work without hope draws nectar in a sieve, And hope without an object cannot live.' In all probability my case was by no means so peculiar as I fancied it, and I doubt not that many others have passed through a similar state; but the idiosyncrasies of my education had given to the general phenomenon a special character, which made it seem the natural effect of causes that it was hardly possible for time to remove. I frequently asked myself if I could or if I was bound to go on living, when life must be passed in this manner. I generally answered to myself that I did not think I could possibly bear it beyond a year. When, however, not more than half that duration of time had elapsed, a small ray of light broke in upon my gloom. I was reading accidentally Mnrmontel's ' Me'moires,' and came to the passage which relates his father's death, the distressed position of the family, and the sudden in- Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 189 spiration by which he, then a mere boy, felt and made them feel that he would be everything to them would supply the place of all that they had lost. A vivid conception of the scene and its feelings came over me, and I was moved to tears. From this moment my burden grew lighter. The oppression of the thought that all feeling was dead within me was gone. I was no longer hopeless ; I was not a stock or a stone. I had still, it seemed, some of the material out of which all worth of character and all capacity for happiness are made. Relieved from my ever-present sense of irremediable wretchedness, I gradually found out that the ordinary incidents of life could again give me some pleasure ; that I could again find enjoyment, not intense, but sufficient for cheerfulness, in sunshine and sky, in books, in conversation, in public affairs ; and that there was once more excitement, though of a moderate kind, in exerting myself for my opinions, and for the public good. Thus the cloud gradually drew off, and I again enjoyed life ; and though I had several relapses, some of which lasted many months, I never again was as miserable as I had been." And the only permanent instruction which this experience left behind it seems to have been curiously slight. It produced a threefold moral result : first, a grave alarm at the dangerously- undermining capacities of his own power of moral analysis which promised to unravel all those artificial moral webs of painful and pleasurable associations with injurious and useful actions respectively, which his father had so laboriously woven for him during his childhood and youth : and further, two notable practical conclusions one, that in order to attain happiness (which he " never wavered " in regarding as " the test of all rules of conduct and the end of life ") the best strategy is a kind of flank march, to aim at something else, at some ideal end, not consciously as a means to happiness, but as an end in itself, so, he held, may you have a better chance of securing happiness by the way than you can by any direct pursuit of it ; and the other, that it is most desirable to cultivate the feelings, the passive susceptibilities, as well as the reason- ing and active powers, if the utilitarian life is to be made enjoy- able. Surely a profound sense of the inadequacy of ordinary human success to the craving of the human spirit was never followed by a less radical moral change. That it resulted in a new breadth of sympathy with writers like Coleridge and Wordsworth, whose fundamental modes of thought and faith Mr. Mill entirely rejected, but for whoso mode of sentiment, after this period of his life, he somehow managed, not very intelligibly, to make room, is very true; and it is also true that this gave a new largeness of tone to his writings, and gave him a real superiority in all matters of taste to the utilitarian clique 190 The Philosophy of Tfieism. to which ho had belonged results which enormously widened the scope of his influence, and changed him from the mere ex- positor of a single school of psychology into the thoughtful critic of many different schools. But as far as we can judge, all this new breadth was gained at the cost of a certain haze, which, from this time forth, spread itself over his grasp of the first principles which he still professed to hold. Ho did not cease to be a utilitarian, but ho ceased to distinguish between the duty of promoting your own happiness and of promoting anybody else's, and never could make it clear where he found his moral obligation to sacrifice the former to the latter. He still main- tained that actions, and not sentiments, are the true objects of ethical discrimination ; but he discovered that there was a significance which he had never before suspected even in senti- ments and emotions of which he continued to maintain that the origin was artificial and arbitrary. He did not cease to declaim against the prejudices engendered by the intuitional theory of philosophy ; but he made it one of his peculiar distinctions as an experience-philosopher, that he recommended the fostering of new prepossessions, only distinguished from the prejudices he strove to dissipate by being, in his opinion, harmless, though quite as little based as those in ultimate or objective truth. He maintained as strongly as ever that the character of man is formed by circumstances, but he discovered that the will can act upon circumstances, and so modify its own future capability of willing ; and though it is in his opinion circumstances which enable or induce the will thus to act upon circumstances, he taught and thought that this makes all the difference between fatalism and the doctrine of cau.se and effect as applied to character. After his influx of new light he remained as strong a democrat as ever, but he ceased to believe in the self-interest principle as universally efficient to produce good government when applied to multitudes, and indeed qualified his democratic theory by an intellectual aristocracy of feeling, which to our minds is the essence of exclusiveness. " A person of high intellect," he writes, " should never go into unintellectual society, unless he can enter it as an apostle ; yet he is the only person with high objects who can ever enter it at all." You can hardly have exclusiveness more extreme than that, or a doctrine more strangely out of moral sympathy with the would-be universalism of the Benthamite theory. In fact, it seems to us, Mr. Mill's unquestionable breadth of philosophic treatment was Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 191 gained at the cost of a certain ambiguity which fell over the root-principles of his philosophy an ambiguity by which he gained for it a more catholic repute than it deserved. The result of the moral crisis through which Mr. Mill passed at the age of twenty may be described briefly, in our opinion, as this : that it gave him tastes far in advance of his philosophy foretastes, in fact, of a true philosophy ; and that this moral flavour of something truer and wider served him in place of the substance of anything truer and wider during the rest of his life. . . . On the whole, the book will be found, we think, even by Mr. Mill's most strenuous disciples, a dreary one. It shows that in spite of all Mr. Mill's genuine and generous compassion for human misery and his keen desire to alleviate it, his relation to concrete humanity was of a very confined and reserved kind, one brightened by few personal ties, and those few not, except in about two cases, really hearty ones. The multitude was to him an object of compassion and of genuine beneficence, but he had no pleasure in men, no delight in actual intercourse with this strange, various, homely world of motley faults and virtues. His nature was composed of a few very fine threads, but wanted a certain strength of basis, and the general effect, though one of high and even enthusiastic disinterestedness, is meagre and pallid. His tastes were refined, but there was a want of homeliness about his hopes. He was too strenuously didactic to be in sympathy with man, and too incessantly analytic to throw his burden upon God. There was something overstrained in all that was noblest in him, this excess seeming to be by way of compensation, as it were, for the number of regions of life in which he found little or nothing where other men find so much. He was strangely deficient iu humour, which, perhaps, we ought not to regret, fur had he had it, his best work would, in all probability, have been greatly hampered by such a gift. Unique in intellectual ardour and moral disinterestedness, of tender heart and fastidious tastes, though narrow in his range of practical sympathies, his name will long be famous as that of the most wide-minded and generous of political economists, the most disinterested of Utilitarian moralists, and the most accomplished and impartial of empirical philosophers. But as a man, there was in him a certain poverty of nature, in spite of the nobleness in him, a monotonous joylessness, in spite of the hectic sanguiiioiiesa of 192 TJte Philosophy of Thewn. his theoretic creed, a want of genial trust, which spurred on into an almost artificial zeal his ardour for philosophic recon- struction; and these are qualities which will probably put a well-marked limit on the future propagation of an influence such as few writers on such subjects have ever before attained within the period of their own lifetime. Our own comments on the autobiography shall be con- fined to one or two points, on which it illustrates (as we think, very instructively) Mr. Mill's habits and character, as a thinker on philosophy and religion. And firstly, the present work makes it abundantly clear that we were correct in our estimate of his opinion on religious subjects. By "deism " is commonly understood the doctrine, that an infinitely perfect Being is Author of the universe, but that this Being has made no revelation to mankind. Mr. Mill considers this doctrine no less obviously irrational and immoral than Christianity itself. His father, he said (pp. 39-40), "found it impossible to believe that a world so full of evil was the work of an Author combining infinite power with perfect goodness and righteousness. His intellect spurned the subtleties by which men attempted to blind themselves to this open contradiction." And in this passage, as our readers will have observed, Mr. Mill not only narrates as a fact his father's unbelief, but adds on his own account the statement that " Theism is an open contradiction." In p. 46 he says that " the ideal of good " framed by such thinkers as himself, " is usually far nearer to perfection than the objective Deity of those who think themselves obliged to find absolute goodness in the author of a world so crowded with suffering and so deformed with injustice as ours." And in p. 70 he laments that " those who reject revelation very generally take refuge in an optimistic deism, a worship of the order of nature and the supposed course of Providence, at least as full of contradic- tions and perverting to the moral sentiments as any of the Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 193 forms of Christianity, if only it is as completely realized." Moreover, any one who reads the volume will see that these passages express what was his own doctrine from first to last. If, then, by the term " God " be understood an "infinitely perfect Being" Omnipotence, of course, being included in "Perfection" nothing can be clearer than that Mr. Mill throughout his life confidently denied the existence of God. He implies, indeed (p. 39), that " dog- matic atheism " is absurd : but he himself was in the ordinary sense of the term a " dogmatic atheist ; " because he confidently denied the existence of any such Being as Him who is ordinarily called " God." It may be worth while to add, that he not only rejected deism as confidently as he rejected Christianity, but that he thought Christianity the less unreasonable of the two. His father "spoke with respect" of Butler's "Analogy" (p. 38), which kept him, as he said, for some considerable time, a believer in the divine authority of Christianity, by proving to him that whatever are the difficulties in believing that the Old and New Testaments proceed from, or record the acts of, a perfectly wise and good Being, the same and still greater difficulties stand in the way of the belief that a Being of such a character can have been the Maker of the universe. He considered Butler's argu- ment as conclusive against the only opponents for whom it was intended. Those who admit an omnipotent as well as perfectly just and benevolent Maker and Ruler of such a world as this, can say little against Christianity but what can, with at least equal force, be retorted against themselves (p. 39). In this last sentence, as in a former instance, the author is avowedly expressing what is his own opinion as well as his father's. In his view, then, the deistic theory is not only faulty on the same ground with the Christian, but has the additional faultiness of adducing arguments against Christianity which are equally destructive of deism itself. Further, from the very first opening of his reason to VOL. J. 104 The Philosophy of Tfieimn. the day on which this autobiography was concluded, no shade of doubt on the absolute and even obvious certainty of atheism seems to have even momentarily crossed his mind. At one critical period of his life (see pp. 182-140) he was led to question profoundly the whole basis on which he had been so carefully trained, and which he had hitherto assumed as indubitable. He was impelled by the very strongest motives to look in every possible direction for some relief ; and yet there was one direction in which he never thought of looking, viz. belief in God.* No one more heartily denounced than he all habit of passive acquiescence (as he would call it) in tenets once learned ; yet his faith in atheism seems really to have rivalled, in firmness, tenacity, undoubtingness, unfaltering persistency, the faith of Catholics in the great verities of their creed. Of every other tenet which he held, he felt it his duty again and again to re-examine the grounds : but the truth of atheism was too self-evident in his view to need re-examina- tion. Catholics, in accordance with their fundamental principles, hold the truth of Catholicity firmly and irre- spectively of inquiry ; while Mr. Mill chose, in the very teeth of his fundamental principles, to hold the truth of atheism firmly and irrespectively of inquiry. And at last what was the intellectual foundation of this blind persistency ? Strange to say of a phenomenistic philosopher, it was his absolute trust in the self-evident character of a certain alleged axiom. He had been taught from childhood to account it a self-evident contradiction in terms, that a world so abounding in evil as this can have been created by a Being infinite at once in love and in power. It is meant by the very term " Infinite in love " so he had been taught to think that such a Being imparts all the happiness He possibly can ; and it is meant * He snys in one place (p. 43), " I am one of the very few examples in this country who has not thrown off religious belief, but never had it." Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 195 by the very term " Infinite in power," that He can impart all the happiness He may wish. Looking, then, at the experienced facts of life, he held that the affirmation of God's Existence is not merely a statement open to in- numerable objections and surrounded by innumerable diffi- culties though this also he would have said but a direct contradiction in terms ; as though one spoke of a crooked straight line of a round square. We on our side maintain, not only that his thesis is indefensible, but that it will not bear a moment's consideration. We are not able, indeed, to draw out an intelligible argument on this head, until we can discuss the matter as a whole ; until we are directly engaged in that theistic controversy on which this series of essays is intended to converge. Even when we are engaged in that controversy, we are not so insane as to imagine that we can explain how it is that such a world as this can have proceeded from an infinitely loving and powerful Creator. Nay, the Catholic is not called on to show positively, that any given objection of antitheists is invalid ; because it is rather their business to prove it valid.* The Catholic begins by drawing out the direct proof of God's Existence a proof of the most urgent, immediate, irrefragable, irresistible character that can well be imagined, which penetrates the inmost depths of the human heart, and which reasonably convinces million millions of men, who would be wholly incapable of understanding its scientific analysis. Of course, on the imaginary supposition that any argument could be adduced on the opposite side, which demonstratively disproves God's Existence absolute scepticism must result ; and the Catholic philosopher is therefore required further to answer any such alleged argument. But here his obligation manifestly ends. We * So ns regards e.g. transnbstantiation. Catholic jiliilosophors ecau.e from the firxt it was the aim of his publications to promote the radical refuriu of society on seme irre- ligious basis or other. 200 The Philosophy of Theism. the present volume. We extract the passage to which we refer, italicizing one clause. Of unbelievers (so called), as well as of believers, there are many species, including almost every variety of moral type. But the best among them, as no one who has had opportunities of really knowing them will hesitate to affirm, are more genuinely religious, in the best sense of the word religion, than those who exclusively arrogate to themselves the title. The liberality of the age, or, in other words, the weakening of the obstinate prejudice which makes men unable to see what is before their eyes because it is contrary to their expectations, has caused it to be very commonly admitted that a deist may be truly religious ; but if religion stands for any graces of character, and not for mere dogma, the assertion may equally be made of many whose belief is far short of deism. Though they may think the proof incomplete that the universe is a work of design, and though they assuredly disbelieve that it can have an Author and Governor who is absolute in power as well as perfect in goodness, they have that which constitutes the principal worth of all religions whatever, an ideal conception of a Perfect Being, to which they habitually refer as the guide of their conscience; and this ideal of Good is usually far nearer to perfection than the objective Deity of those who think them- selves obliged to find absolute goodness in the author of a world so crowded with suffering and so deformed by injustice as ours (pp. 45-46). No doubt, by the word " religion," are meant certain "graces of character, and not mere dogma." But what graces ? Would Mr. Mill have used the word "religion " to express justice as such ? or benevolence as such ? or veracity as such ? or fortitude or temperance as such ? Of course there would be no sense in his doing so. What is ordinarily meant by "religion" as a grace of character is the habit of communion with God. A person is more " religious " in proportion as he more has his thoughts fixed on God's presence ; in proportion as the whole stream of his life is devoted to the end of loving and obeying God. It is most intelligible, then, to say that a deist can be Mr. MiWs Philosophical Position. 201 " religious ; " and all those indeed must think the saying true, who consider (as we do) that there may be invincible ignorance on the divine origin of Christianity. Such a saying results from faithfulness to the rules of logic, not from so-called "liberality" or "weakening of prejudice." But what can possibly be meant by an atheist being " religious " ? How can any man remember God's presence, if he do not believe that God exists ? how can he devote his life to loving and obeying God, if he thinks there is no God to be loved and obeyed ? When first we hear it, then, such language seems simply astounding : but on consideration, one comes to see what it indicates. It indicates that Mr. Mill had no notion of what it is which Christians mean, when they speak of "religiousness" or "piety." Had it not been for Mr. Mill's case, we should have said that even those who do not practise religion, know well what is meant by these terms ; but Mr. Mill, while leading a life of laborious study, remained to the end of his life profoundly ignorant of the very existence of what the whole world around him knew to be among the most widely extended and powerful springs of human conduct. And this was the man who sat in judgment, as if from an elevated pedestal, on the acts and motives of saintly persons ; who claimed superiority over the prejudices of the vulgar ; who condescendingly patronized the mediaeval Church ; who was kind enough to nee even in modern Catholicity much which he was happy to approve, though far more which he was obliged to condemn.* It may seem heartless if, while making these comments, we do not pause for a moment to bewail the hard lot of * Observe e.g. such a sentence as this : " There are men who, not dis- guising their own unbelief, have written deeper and finer thiny* in vindica- tion of what religion has done for mankind, than would have sufficed to found the reputation of some of its most admired defenders" (" Dissertations and Discusaions," vol. ii. p. 122). 202 The, Philosophy of Theism. one, by nature so teachable, loving, and sensitive, placed from his birth under the iron yoke of that bigoted and intolerant atheist his father, and indoctrinated by him so carefull}' to paganism. But (as we have already said) we are attempting no appreciation whatever of his personal character ; we are but mentioning this or that fact, which bears importantly on the value of his speculations whether in the sphere of religion or philosophy. For, indeed, even in the matter of social philosophy, how fatal to his intellectual character is what we have just mentioned ! He was ignorant (as we have said) of the very existence of what is among the most widely extended and powerful springs of human conduct. The main purpose of his life was to act directly or indirectly on the convictions and actions of his contemporaries. To do so with any hope of success, it was necessary that he should clearly understand their existing motives, impulses, instincts. And yet, in one very prominent particular, he was as ignorant of the moral world in the midst of which he passed his days as though he had never read of the past nor lived in the present. Then, again considering he claimed to take a leading position in metaphysics and psychology how noteworthy was his ignorance of what Catholics have done in that direction. For many centuries a series of men, admitted by Mr. Mill himself to be powerful thinkers, had concen- trated their intellectual energy on the work of raising an edifice of theological science, on the basis of the scholastic philosophy. "We should not have been surprised, however profoundly Mr. Mill might have differed from them : what does surprise us is, that he took no pains to know them. What would he have thought of himself, if he had written his work on Hamilton without acquiring a knowledge of Kant's philosophy ? Of course, whether Kant be or be not intellectually superior to the giants of scholasticism, is a Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 203 matter of opinion : but it is a matter of undeniable fact that the latter immeasurably surpassed him in the influence of their speculations on the whole course of thought and of society for many centuries. Yet, undeterred by this crass ignorance, Mr. Mill permitted himself very freely to criticize the intellectual characteristics of those very centuries. It will be said, perhaps, that at all events other anti- theistic philosophers of the day are no less unacquainted with Catholic theology and philosophy than Mr. Mill. We heartily endorse this remark. Their dense ignorance of Catholicity is a mark of their crooked and perverse intel- lectual habits, which can be appreciated by the most ordinarily educated Catholic. In fact, they are less ac- quainted with Catholicity, and have far less wish to be acquainted, than had Mr. Mill himself.* But, then, the latter always laid claim to exceptional large-mindedness, and honestly believed such claim to be legitimate. He accounted himself " much superior to most of his contem- poraries in willingness and ability to learn from everybody " (p. 242). He professed " great readiness and eagerness to learn from everybody, and to make room in his opinions for every new acquisition by adjusting the old and new to one another " (p. 252). He was eager to learn from every quarter, except only the Catholic Church. There are other passages in the autobiography besides those we have mentioned, which bear importantly on Mr. Mill's philosophical tenets : but (with one exception to be immediately mentioned) they will be more conveniently considered in subsequent essays, especially when we come to handle again his utilitarian tenets. We therefore proceed * Mr. Mill's autobiography has not unnaturally caused for the moment a reaction npuinBt him, even aa compared with other writers of the sumo school. Wo look forward to a reaction against this reaction. To our mind, no one of the rent approaches him cither in intellectual clearness, candour, and ability, nor, again, in zealous philanthropy. 204. Ttie Philosophy of Theism. to resume our controversy with him, at the point where we left off in the preceding essay. The principal topic with which we were occupied was a consideration of Mr. Mill's reply to the arguments we had adduced against him, on the necessary character of mathematical axioms. It might appear, on the surface, that this is somewhat a subordinate question, in its bear- ing on the very vital points at issue between Mr. Mill and ourselves : but we replied, that Mr. Mill " would have been the last to make this complaint." Our state- ment is fully borne out by the autobiography. He ac- counted the controversy between intuitionism and pheno- menism far more fundamental than any other, in matters no less of social than of strictly philosophical speculation ; and he accounted the discussion on the necessary character of mathematical axioms to be the very turning-point of this controversy. The former opinion is expressed in p. 273 ; and in p. 226 he declares, that " the chief strength " of the philosophy which he assails "in morals, politics, and religion, lies in the appeal which it is accustomed to make to the evidence of mathematics and the cognate branches of physical science." " To keep it from these," he adds, " is to drive it from its stronghold ; " and by parity of reason, if we maintain it in these, we maintain it in its stronghold. No one, then, could have a stronger conviction than Mr. Mill himself, on the vital character of the issue which we joined with him. We candidly expressed our opinion as to the utterly worthless character of his reasoning. " We are deliberately of opinion," we said, " that not one of his arguments has the slightest force, and hardly one of them the most superficial appearance of force." " The whole mass of human knowledge," we further alleged, " is made," by him, " utterly dependent on what is about the most gratuitous and arbitrary theory which can well Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 205 be imagined." And we added, that Mr. Mill's death had been to us a severe controversial disappointment. We had been eager to engage in a hand-to-hand conflict with so distinguished a champion, not on a few questions only, however fundamental, but on the whole mass of philo- sophical speculations, which leads onward to that one supreme issue, the Existence of a Personal God. We were full of confidence that a signal triumph must result to the cause of truth, if we could induce Mr. Mill to put forth his utmost strength on the other side. At the same time, we are glad to think that the keystone of his whole philosophical position lies in those very doctrines on which he lived to publish his reply to our adverse arguments. Every philosopher of the present day has his " aggressive " as well as his " affirmative " position. You understand his " aggressive " position so far as you understand what those tenets are which he desires to over- throw ; and you understand his " affirmative " position so far as you understand what those tenets are which he desires to establish in their place. Now, Mr. Mill's "aggressive" position mainly consisted, (1) in his denying the cognizableness of any necessary truths ; and (2) (as a means for that denial) in his denying the competence of men's existent faculties to avouch truth finally and without appeal. Whereas, then, he regards the very " stronghold " of necessists to be their view of mathematical axioms, we may fairly say that the keystone of his "aggressive" position consists (1) in his doctrine on mathematical axioms, and (2) in his doctrine on the rule of certitude. On the other hand, his " affirmative " position mainly consists in his claim to substitute a body of science built exclusively on experience, for a body of science purporting to be built partly on necessary truth. But no body of science can possibly be built on the exclusive basis of experience, unless the philosopher first establishes on grounds of experience 206 The Philosophy of Theism. the uniformity of nature ; or what Mr. Mill calls " the law of universal causation." Mr. Mill himself admits this as heartily as we maintain it. The keystone, then, of Mr. Mill's "affirmative" position lies in his doctrine, that the uniformity of nature can be proved by experience ; while the keystone of his " aggressive " position lies (as we have seen) in his respective doctrines, on mathematical axioms, and on the rule of certitude. And it so happens that these are the very three doctrines on which he expressly replied to our adverse arguments. In our last essay we commenced our rejoinder on that reply, and on the present occasion are to complete it. It is certainly a great matter of regret to us, for the sake of truth, that such rejoinder must now necessarily be final ; and it would have been a matter of keen interest to us to know how he would have encountered our remarks. Our last essay was much longer than we could have wished; but we were very desirous of drawing out unin- terruptedly our whole counter-argument on the necessity of mathematical axioms. To prevent our essay, however, from swelling to an absolutely intolerable length, we were obliged to omit all summary of our lengthened reasoning. And we feel this to have been so great a disadvantage, that one of our first procedures on the present occasion will be in some degree to supply that deficiency. Before commencing this, however, we shall make a little further comment on a position of Mr. Mill's, which we criticized. Our readers, on referring to our previous remarks, will see that he makes two statements. Firstly, he says that "wherever the present constitution of space exists," the axioms of geometry are cognizable to man- kind as "conclusions from that conception." Secondly, he adds, that we have ample reason to know,* that the same * His word is to " believe ; " but on looking at the context our reader will see that he certainly means " know." Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 207 " constitution of space which exists on our own planet, exists also in the region of the fixed stars." Now what does he mean by this extremely vague term " constitution of space " ? We can fancy his indignation, if one of his opponents had used so vague a term as this without ex- planation. Yet we affirm, with some confidence, that Mr. Mill has nowhere even attempted to explain what he meant by the term ; and we doubt indeed whether he ever used it, except in the two notes, replying to our own criticism, which he inserted in the latest edition of his respective works on " Logic " and on " Hamilton." There is only one meaning which we can think of as intended by this phrase. We must suppose that he accounts "the present constitution of space" as existing wherever the three dimensions length, breadth, height are predicable of all material objects. But if this were his meaning, he would hold that a man can "conclude" the truth of geometrical axioms " from his very conception " of length, breadth, and height. This, however, is the precise point at issue between him and his opponents ; and if such were his meaning, he would be saying in so many words that his opponents are in the right and he in the wrong. We would beg our readers to look back at our whole criticism in pp. 176-179. For our own part, we believe this is one of the cases far more numerous throughout Mr. Mill's works than might be supposed in which his spontaneous reason is too strong for his artificial and elaborated philosophy. We will next direct our readers' attention to a remark we made a page earlier. We observed how difficult it is to know what is Mr. Mill's positive thesis, on the cognizable- ness of mathematical axioms ; and also to know what are the grounds alleged by him for such thesis. He declares again and again, that the universal truth of these axioms, throughout the planet Terra at least, is irrefragably proved 208 Tht Philosophy of Theism. by universal experience. Yet what does he himself say on another occasion? "That all metals sink in water, was a uniform experience from the origin of the human race down to the discovery of potassium in the present century by Sir Humphry Davy. That all swans are white, was a uniform experience down to the discovery of Australia " (" Logic," vol. i. p. 805). What stronger ground, then, has he for his conviction that over the whole earth trilateral are triangular, than his ancestors had for their entirely mistaken conviction that over the whole earth swans are white and metals sink in water ? How can he even guess that in some newly-discovered country a tree may not be found which shall possess the capability of being formed into quadrangular trilateral, or into pairs of straight lines of which each pair shall enclose a space ? Mr. Mill, however, is much less anxious to state and establish his positive than his negative thesfs on mathe- matical axioms ; and unless his whole fabric of philosophy is to collapse,* he must prove that these axioms are not self-evidently necessary. We, on the contrary, as zealous impugners of his philosophy, have been bent on proving the contrary. And the general argument we have used may be thus syllogistically stated. Whatever the existent cognitive faculties of mankind testify, is instinctively f known by mankind as certainly true. * This must not be understood in too extreme a sense. In a former essay, we said that, on such a supposition, "his works might still bo admitted to contain a large quantity of valuable philosophical matter, as we think indeed they do ; but his philosophy as a whole would be at an end." This is precisely what we still think. t We had at first said " self-evidently," but in our last essay we found it more convenient to appropriate that phrase in a different sense. We think the word "instinctively" the best substitute, as expressing the irre- sistible and (as it were) piercing character of the convictions to which we refer. Let any reader consider the keen certitude with which he knows that he experienced those sensations of ten minutes back, which his memory vividly testifies. Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 209 But the existent cognitive faculties of mankind testif}', that any given mathematical axiom is self-evidently necessary. Ergo, etc. Now, it is most surprising that a writer generally so clear as Mr. Mill, should so long have left it uncertain which of these two propositions it is which he denies : see e.g. the mutually contradictory propositions which we quoted from him in our last essay. Such, however, being the case, we entered at length into the proof of both the above premisses. But after reading the autobiography, we can hardly doubt that it is the former of the two premisses against wl^ich Mr. Mill protests.* We shall not, therefore, here attempt to epitomize our argument for our minor premiss ; but we shall content ourselves on that head with referring our readers to the whole course of our remarks. We will but briefly say here, that it would certainly be a bold step to deny this premiss. Take any man of ordinary thoughtfulness and education ; and ask him whether it is within the sphere of Omnipotence to enclose a space by two straight lines, or to create a quadrangular trilateral : there can be very little doubt what his spontaneous answer will be. We here, then, assume Mr. Mill to accept our minor premiss ; we assume him to concede that, if mankind trust their existent faculties, it is impossible for them to doubt the self-evident necessity of any given mathematical axiom. Mr. Mill, then, we take it, would have argued in some such manner as this : and we confine ourselves for clear- ness' sake to geometrical axioms, because whatever is said of them may so easily be applied to arithmetical. " From the first moment when an infant begins to move his arms and legs," Mr. Mill would say, " he is beginning to acquire * See particularly a passage in pp. 22"), 220, which wo bliall (junto in ;i later part of our paper. V declare not what under imaginary circumstances they would declare which alone is known by each man to be infallibly true. Our present business is not with Mr. Herbert Spencer ; but we may mention, by the way, that (if we rightly under- stand his various statements) his distrust of the human 222 TJie Philosophy of Theism. existent faculties exceeds even Mr. Mill's. He will not even accept, as certainly true, what lie admits that his "pure" faculties would unmistakably declare, because he considers that he may inherit faculties which have been de- naturalized and artificialized by ancestral experience. Our whole answer to Mr. Mill contains a fortiori an answer to Mr. Spencer.* And it is no small testimony to the strength of Theistic philosophy, that its two ablest assailants in our time have been driven to take refuge in different phases of a theory so manifestly absurd and self-contradictory. Here, then, we close what is necessarily our final reply to Mr. Mill, on what we have called the keystone of his " aggressive " philosophical position ; viz. his respective doctrines on mathematical axioms and on the rule of certitude. In our last essay we treated these two questions in their logical order, and commenced with the latter : whereas, on the present occasion, for the sake of varying our treatment, we have proceeded inversely ; we have traced back our difference from him on mathematical axioms, to our difference from him on the rule of certitude. "We will sum up under five questions, and so (we hope) give our readers an intelligible conspectus of the whole. Question 1st. Do the existent human faculties pronounce that mathematical axioms are self-evidently necessary ? We reply most confidently in the affirmative, and Mr. Mill, if we may judge from his autobiography, does not himself venture to answer this question in the negative. Question 2nd. Can this avouchment of the human faculties have been produced by the mere agency of past experience ? We answer confidently in the negative ; Mr. Mill confidently in the affirmative. * We would refer our readers to a masterly article on Mr. Spencer in the Quarterly of October, 1874. We heartily concur with it from first to last, except, indeed, that its eulogy of Mr. Spencer's ability seems to us a little beyond the mark. Mr. Spencer's reply to it in the Fortnightly of December entirely misses its point. Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 223 Question 3rd. Supposing that the said avouchment could have been thus produced, would this circumstance afford any justification for doubting its certain truth ? Mr. Mill answers this question in the affirmative ; we in the negative. We maintain that the avouchment of each man's existent faculties is his one infallible rule of certitude ; and that a denial of this truth would degrade his knowledge to a level below that of the brutes. Question 4th. Mr. Mill implies that he accepts, as certainly true, whatever his faculties would have declared, had they not been denaturalized and artificialized by past experience. Does he give any reason for this opinion ? None whatever. He is wholly silent on the motive of certitude. Question 5th. What ground do we give for our own doctrine, that whatever any man's existent faculties avouch is known by him as certainly true ? We allege that in each separate case this is known instinctively : and we give, as our illustration of the term "instinctive," the keen and instinctive certitude with which each man knows himself to have experienced what his memory clearly and vividly testifies. We have been speaking on necessary truth in general, and on the self-evident necessity of mathematical axioms in particular. One or two further questions had better be considered before we finally turn from this matter, though Mr. Mill is not directly concerned with them. I. One of these has been suggested to us by a non- Catholic correspondent. He objects altogether to our taking mathematical axioms as a sample of what we allege about necessary truths in general. " Lines and angles," he argues, are but imagined by geometricians. No fair parallel can be made (he thinks) between such mere notions on one hand, and facts on the other hand, such c.y. as 224- The Philosophy of Theism. human actions, which have a real objective existence. Our correspondent does not deny that there are various hypo- thetically necessary truths concerning these imaginary lines and angles ; but he denies that this furnishes any kind of presumption, or even illustration, in favour of there being e.fj. a necessary morality in human actions. He is well aware that on this matter he has Mr. Mill for his opponent, no less than ourselves ; and, in fact, we could answer him at every point without going further for materials than Mr. Mill's " Logic." Mr. Mill holds, that every true proposition concerning angles and lines repre- sents real objective truth. We will not, however, here draw out Mr. Mill's (to our mind) conclusive argument for this opinion ; because to do so would carry us a great deal too far. We content ourselves with three replies, either of which by itself appears to us decisive. Firstly, we point to arithmetical truths. Let there be 16 rows of pebbles, each containing 18 : it is a necessary truth that the whole number is 288. Omnipotence could divide one pebble into two, or create new pebbles ; but it is beyond the sphere of Omnipotence to effect that, so long as there remain 1C rows of 18 pebbles each, the whole number of pebbles should be either more or less than the sum of two hundreds eight tens and eight units. Is not this an external objective fact, if there be any such in the world ? And the number of such arithmetical facts is simply in- exhaustible. Then, secondly, take the theorems inex- haustible in number of solid geometry. Omnipotence e.g. can make a perfectly accurate parallelepiped : but it cannot make one which shall not possess all the properties proved by geometricians. And, thirdly, every proposition which concerns areas may be most easily converted into a propo- sition of solid geometry.* Even then, if it were true that * Here is one instance of what we mean. Take a right-angled triangle, and erect squares on all the aides as in Euclid I. 47. Suppose this figure to Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 225 lines and angles are mere geometrical notions, there remains an inexhaustible number of mathematical pro- positions which indubitably concern objective and external facts. All these possess the attribute of necessity, and they may very fairly be made samples of other necessary truths which also concern objective external facts. II. We now pass to an objection, which may imaginably be made from an entirely different quarter, though no such objection has happened to come within our knowledge. On this, as on other occasions, we have often given, as a special explanation of the term "necessary," that the reversal of a necessary truth is external to the sphere of Omnipotence. It is possible that here and there some Catholic may have been startled by this expression, as though it implied some disparagement of God's Attributes. Now, since a very few words will suffice to remove any such misapprehension, those few words had better be inserted. On a former occasion we laid down the following propo- sition, as that for which in due time we shall contend. We contend, with FF. Kleutgen and Liberatore, that all necessary truths are founded on God's Essence ; that they are what they are, because He is what He is. Let us suppose, then, any Catholic to make the objection we suggested above. We would ask him whether there is any disparagement to God's Attributes in saying that He cannot destroy Himself; that the destruction of God is external to the sphere of Omnipotence. On the con- trary, he will answer, God's Attributes would be intoler- ably disparaged if He were not accounted Indestructible : Existence is involved in His Essence. Secondly, we would move parallelly with itself, and a solid figure is of course the result. Omui- potence can create such a solid figure with perfect accuracy ; hut Omnipo- tence cannot etlect that the portion of it generated by the square of tho hypothenuse shall IHJ either greater or less than the sum of those two portions generated by the squares of the sides. 220 The Philosophy of Theism. ask, whether there is any disparagement of God's Attributes, in saying that He cannot change His Nature ; that He cannot make Himself e.g. mendacious, unjust, unfaithful to promises. On the contrary, the Immutability of His Nature is perhaps what is in my mind more than anything else, when I speak of His Greatness. But if He cannot change His Nature, it follows that He cannot change what is founded on His Nature ; that He cannot change necessary truths. In saying, then, that the reversal of a necessary truth is external to the sphere of Omnipotence, so far from disparaging God's Attributes, we are extolling the Immutability of His Nature. III. We must preface our next inquiry by a short pre- liminary statement. It is alleged by various phenomenists, that there are no ideas in the mind, except copies in various combinations of what has been cognized by the senses.* "We need hardly say how intensely we deny this, though we are not here considering the question at any length. Take e.g. the idea " morally good." We have maintained in a former essay that it is perfectly simple ; and that perhaps no other idea can be named so constantly recurring in one or other shape. Here we may add, that there is no idea possessing more special characteristics of its own, more readily and vividly cognizable ; while most certainly it is no copy, or combination of copies, of any- thing experienced by the senses. f In a future essay we * This is not, however, Mr. Mill's opinion ; for (not to mention other ex- ceptions he would make) we have already recounted his doctrine, that many an idea is generated by " mental chemistry " from other ideas, which never- theless does not consist of those ideas, nor is now any combination of them. t The following passage from F. Kloutgen's work on the scholastic philo- sophy will illustrate our meaning. We translate it from the French trans- lation. The author is assailing the doctrine of innate ideas : " But," it will be said, " should we be able, on sight of an individual action, to conceive a maxim of morality, if we did not possess already certain notions relative to the moral order ? Assuredly no. ... But are we at liberty thence to infer that the mind finds in itself as innate those earlier ideas, or else that it must have received them from some external source [d'ailleurs] ? Not at Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 227 hope to defend a similar proposition, in regard to the idea "cause;" and in like manner the idea "necessary" is certainly no copy, or combination of copies, of anything cognized by the senses. The question for which we have been preparing the way is (as far as we see) of no practical importance ; but for the sake of clearness, it may be worth while briefly to enter on it. Is the idea " necessary " a simple or complex idea? "We suggested on a former occasion that it is complex, and that a " necessary " truth precisely means a truth " of which there is no cause." Subsequent reflection has induced us to doubt the truth of this sug- gestion ; and has inclined us to the opinion that the idea " necessary " admits no such analysis, and is, in fact, altogether simple. Take the proposition, " every necessary truth is uncaused." Is this a purely explicative proposi- tion? Does the word " uncaused " merely express what was already in my mind when I used the word " necessary ? " or, on the contrary, does it add something to the former idea ? If our reader gives the former answer, he holds the opinion which we suggested in the essay we have referred to; if he gives the latter answer, he holds the opinion to which we now rather incline. We now pass to what we have called the keystone of Mr. Mill's " affirmative " position. His whole positive doctrine from first to last depends on the proposition, that the uniformity of nature can be proved by experience. We did not deny that this uniformity could be proved by intro- ducing premisses of that kind which Mr. Mill rejects ; but we denied that it can be proved (as he is required on hi* till ; for it is sufficient that the mind possesses, besides sensibility, u higher power of knowledge, reason. . . . As we perceive in tho object, by means of the senses, those phenomena which correspond tj the nature of tin- senses ; so wo know, by the reason, that which is exclusively within the sphere of th:it faculty " (Uiss. i. n. 01:5). 228 Tlic Philosophy of Thrivm. principles to prove it) from experienced phenomena alone. In the new edition of his " Logic " Air. Mill replies to our criticisms (vol. ii. pp. 109-111) ; and what we have now to do is to rejoin on his reply. " All physical science," we said, " depends for its existence on the fundamental proposition, that the laws of nature are uniform : " by which proposition " we mean, that no physical phenomenon takes place without a corre- sponding physical antecedent, and that the same physical antecedent is invariably followed by the same physical consequent." Mr. Mill professes to establish conclu- sively, on mere grounds of experience, that such is the fact ; at all events, throughout the whole of this planet. ("Logic," book iii. chap. 21.) "His reasoning," we said, " amounts at best to this. If in any part of the world there existed a breach in the uniformity of nature, that breach must by this time have been discovered by one or other of the eminent men who have given themselves to physical experiment. But most certainly, adds Mr. Mill, none such has been discowred, or mankind would be sure to have heard of it ; consequently, such is his conclusion, none such exists." Mr. Mill tacitly admits that we have stated his argument quite correct!}'. We, then, thus pro- ceeded : Now, in order to estimate the force of this argument, let us suppose for a moment that the fact were as Mr. Mill represents it ; let us suppose for a moment that persons of scientific educa- tion were unanimous in holding that there has been no well- authenticated case of a breach in the uniformity of nature. What inference could be drawn from this? Be it observed, that the number of natural agents constantly at work is incal- culably large; and that the observed cases of uniformity in their action must be immeasurably fewer than one-thousandth of the whole. Scientific men, we assume for the moment, Lave dis- covered that in a certain proportion of instances immeasurably fewer than one-thousandth of the whole a certain fact has prevailed, the fact of uniformity; and they have not found a Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 229 single instance in which that fact does not prevail. Are they justified, we ask, in inferring from these premisses that the fact is universal ? Surely the question answers itself. Let us make a very grotesque supposition, in which, however, the conclusion would really be tried according to the arguments adduced. In some desert of Africa there is an enormous connected edifice, surrounding some vast space, in which dwell certain reasonable beings who are unable to leave the enclosure. In this edifice are more than a thousand chambers, which some years ago were entirely locked up, and the keys no one knew where. By constant diligence twenty-five keys have been found, out of the whole number; and the corresponding chambers, situated promiscuously throughout the edifice, have been opened. Each chamber, when examined, is found to be in the precise shape of a dodecahedron. Are the inhabitants justified, on that account, in holding with certitude that the remaining 975 chambers are built on the same plan ? Mr. Mill frankly replies : Not with perfect certitude, but . . . with so high a degree of probability that they would be justified in acting upon the presumption until an exception appeared. This we, of course, quite admit ; but it falls very far short of Mr. Mill's thesis, and he therefore thus proceeds : Dr. Ward's argument, however, does not touch mine as it stands in the text. My argument is grounded on the fact that the uniformity of the course of nature as a whole, is constituted by the uniform sequences of special effects from special natural agencies ; that the number of these natural agencies in the part of the universe known to us is not incalculable, nor even ex- tremely great, that we have now reason to think that at least the far greater number of them, if not separately, at least in some of the combinations into which they enter, have been made sufficiently amenable to observation, to have enabled us actually to ascertain some of their fixed laws; and that this amount of experience justifies the same degree of assurance that the course of nature is uniform throughout, which we previously had of the uniformity of sequence among the phenomena best known to us. This view of the subject, if correct, destroys the force of Dr. Ward's first argument. 230 The Philosophy of T/n'i*ni. We do not see, on the contrary, how it touches our argument ever so faintly. Mr. Mill accounts it to be proved by experience that certain "natural agencies" produce certain "special effects." We totally deny that this has been proved, or that it can be proved, on mere grounds of experience. There are none of these natural agencies which can be cited more favourably for Mr. Mill's purpose than that of gravitation. We ask, then, this simple question : How could Mr. Mill show, by mere experience, that particles throughout the earth (and universe) attract each other in that particular way which is spoken of as " the law of gravitation ? " What we said on that general truth the uniformity of nature, we say equally on that particular truth the law of gravitation. The number of particles of matter in the universe is in- calculably large, and the observed cases of their acting according to the law of gravitation must be immeasurably fewer than one-thousandth part of the whole. Scientific men have discovered that in a certain proportion of in- stances immeasurably fewer than one-thousandth of the whole a certain fact has prevailed, the fact of gravitation ; and they have not found a single instance in which that fact does not prevail. Are they justified, we ask, in in- ferring from these premisses that the fact is certainly universal? Why, Mr. Mill has already answered in the negative a question precisely equivalent. The very same reasoning which showed how impossible it is to prove by experience the uniformity of nature in general, shows equally how impossible it is to prove by experience the law of gravitation in particular. And the same remark is applicable to all the other " natural agencies " which Mr. Mill commemorates. His attempted answer only avails to exhibit, more pointedly than it might have been seen before, the extraordinary weakness of his case. Our second argument was the following: Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 231 But, secondly, it is as far as possible from being true that men of scientific education are unanimous in holding that there has been no well-authenticated case of breach in the uniformity of nature. On the contrary, even to this day the majority of such persons believe in Christianity, and hold the miracles revealed in Scripture to be on the whole accurately reported. The majority of scientific men believe that at one time persons on whom the shadow of Peter passed were thereby freed from their infirmities ; and that at another time garments brought from the body of Paul expelled sickness and demoniacal pos- session. (Acts v. 15; xix. 12.) Will Mr. Mill allege that S. Peter's shadow, or that garments from S. Paul's body, were the physical cause of a cure, as lotions and bandages might be ? Of course not. Here, then, is a series of physical phenomena, resulting without physical cause; and Catholics to this day consider that breaches in the uniformity of nature are matters of every-day occurrence. Even then, if it were true it seems to us (as we have already said) most untrue that Mr. Mill's conclusion legitimately follows from his premisses, still he cannot even approximate to establishing those premisses until he have first disproved Catholicity and next disproved the whole truth of Christianity. Mr. Mill thus replies, the italics being his own : Dr. Ward's second argument is, that many or most persons, both scientific and unscientific, believe that there arc well- authenticated cases of breach in the uniformity of nature, namely miracles. Neither does this consideration touch what I have said in the text. I admit no other uniformity in the events of nature than the law of Causation ; and (as I have explained in the chapter of this volume which treats of the Grounds of Disbelief) a miracle is no exception to that law. In every case of alleged miracle, a new antecedent is aftirmed to exist ; a counteract ing cause, namely the volition of a supernatural being. To all, therefore, to whom beings with superhuman power over nature are a vera causa, a miracle is a case of the Law of Universal Causation, not a deviation from it. AVI uit an astonishing collapse is here both of memory and of scientific intelligence ! Firstly, of memory. Nothing can be more express than Mr. Mill's words, where he is first occupied with setting forth the uniformity of nature. 232 The Philosophy of Thf'ivm. "When in the course of this inquiry," he says ("Logic," vol. i. p. 876), " I speak of the cause of any phenomenon, I do not mean a cause which is not itself a phenomenon . . . the causes with which I concern myself are not efficient but physical causes. . . . Between the phenomena which exist at any moment and the phenomena which exist at the succeeding instant there is an invariable order of succes- sion." Is a volition, then, of the Invisible God a phenomenon ? Mr. Mill laid down at starting, that he recognizes no causes which are not phenomena ; and now he tells us that God's volition may count as a cause. Secondly, what a collapse of scientific intelligence ! Mr. Mill professes to lay down a doctrine on the uniformity of nature,* which shall suffice as a reasonable basis for physical and other science. Yet what is the view he now professes? He now advocates no doctrine inconsistent with the supposition that there may be as many deities on Olympus as Homer himself believed in ; and that each one of these deities is arbitrarily interfering with the course of nature every minute of every day. In all these cases " the volition of a supernatural being" might count as " a new antecedent," a " counteracting cause : " so that every arbitrary and irregular phenomenon so brought about " is a case of the law of universal causation," as he says, and " not a deviation from it." Why, it is plain that if such constant interference took place, there would be no " course of nature," nor what he ordinarily calls " causation," at all, and physical science would vanish from the sphere of human knowledge. In other words, if we are to trust his present language, he does not profess to prove that there is any uniformity of nature whatever, or that phj'sical science can reasonably exist. f * He calls it " the law of universal causation ; " but we cannot ourselves use this term, because of the vital difference with Mr. Mill on " causation," which we are to set forth in a future essay. t It may most fairly be asked, how belief in the Christian miracles is Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 233 It is quite true (as Mr. Mill implies in the words we have quoted) that, in his comment on Hume's argument against miracles, he had made the very same blunder -which he now repeats. We have always attributed the former blunder to the same cause, to which we also attribute the one before us. Mr. Mill, we think, held so disparaging an estimate of the philosophy which admits the existence of miracles, that in dealing with it he was satisfied with the first plausible argument which came to hand ; and did not trouble himself to examine its merits very closely. We further adduced a third argument : But the strongest objection against the sufficiency of Mr. Mill's argument still remains to be stated. " All our interest," says Mr. Bain most truly, " is concentrated on ichat is yet to be ; the present and the past are of value only as a clue to the events that are to come." Let us even suppose, then, for argument's sake that Mr. Mill had fully proved the past and present uniformity of nature ; still the main difficulty would continue, viz. how he proposes to show that such uniformity will last one moment beyond the present. It is quite an elementary remark that, whenever a proposition is grounded on mere experience, nothing whatever can be known or even guessed concerning its truth, except within the reach of possible observation. For this very reason Mr. Mill professes himself unable to know, or even to assign any kind of probability to the supposition that nature proceeds on uniform laws in distant stellar regions. But plainly there are conditions of time, as well as of space, which preclude the possibility of observation ; and it is as simply impossible for men to know from mere experience what will take place on earth to-morrow, as to know from mere experience what takes place in the planet Jupiter to-day. Here is Mr. Mill's reply, with his own italics : Dr. Ward's last and, as he says, strongest argument is the familiar one of Reid, Stewart, and their followers that what- ever knowledge experience gives us of the past and present, it gives us none of the future. I confess that I see no force consistent with belief in the existence of physical science. We answered this question, however, directly nnd expressly in our essay " Science, Prayer, und Miracles," (vol. ii. of this collection). 234. Tltt Philosophy of Theism. whatever in this argument. Wherein does a future fact differ from a present or a past fact, except in their merely momentary relation to the human beings at present in existence? The answer made by Priestly, in his examination of Reid, seems to me sufficient, viz. that though we have had no experience of what is future, we have had abundant experience of what was future. The " leap in the dark " (as Professor Bain calls it) from the past to the future is exactly as much in the dark, and no more, as the leap from a past which we have personally observed to a past which we have not. I agree with Mr. Bain in the opinion that the resemblance of what we have not experienced to what we have is, by a law of our nature, pre- sumed through the mere energy of the idea before experience has proved it. This psychological truth, however, is not, as Dr. Ward, when criticizing Mr. Bain, appears to think, inconsistent with the logical truth that experience does prove it. The proof comes after the presumption, and consists in its invariable verification by experience when the experience arrives. The fact which while it was future could not be observed, having as yet no existence, is always, when it becomes present and can be observed, found conformable to the past. This rejoinder is more surprising than even the two former. Any one who attentively peruses it will see that it comes to this. We say that, on Mr. Mill's theory, no one, during the year 1874, has any solid ground whatever for supposing as even probable, that fire will burn or water will quench thirst in the year 1875. Mr. Mill replies, that at the end of 1875 he will have ground for knowing that such has been the case during that past year. Dr. Bain gays very truly, that " the present and past are of value only as a clue to " the future ; and we argued that, on Mr. Mill's theory, they are no clue whatever to the future. That is true, replies Mr. Mill ; but still what is now future will be known as soon as it shall have become past. Let us observe what comes of this. We find from his auto- biography that " the principal outward purpose of his life " (p. 67) was so to act on mankind through the laws of human nature, that various intellectual, political, and social Mr. Mill's Philosophical Position. 235 results might ensue, which he regarded as ameliorations of unspeakable moment. Nevertheless according to the very principles which he accounted to be essentially in- volved in such amelioration he had no ground whatever, at any one moment, for thinking it (we will not say certain, but) ever so faintly probable, that the laws of human nature were in future to continue the same. And yet if they did not continue the same, his whole life would have been one sustained blunder. We made one final comment on Mr. Mill's treatment of these subjects, which he has left entirely unnoticed. In considering the question " on what grounds we expect that the sun will rise to-morrow," Mr. Mill (" Logic," vol. ii. p. 80) falls into a mistake very unusual with him ; for he totally misapprehends the difficulty which he has to encounter. He argues we think quite successfully that there is a probability amounting to practical certainty that the sun will rise to- morrow, on the hypothesis that the uniformity of nature so long con- tinues. But the question he has to face is, what reason can he have for knowing, or even guessing, that the uniformity of nature will so long continue? And to this, the true question at issue, he does not so much as attempt a reply. Nothing, then, can be more conspicuous and undeniable than Mr. Mill's break-down in what is the one keystone of his " affirmative " philosophical position. He professes to build a philosophy on the exclusive basis of experience ; and he heartily admits that such construction is impossible, unless the philosopher first establishes the uniformity of nature. But if he establishes that truth on some other basis than experience, he docs not build his philosophy on the exclusive basis of experience. Mr. Mill, then, is re- quired by his principles to prove the uniformity of nature from the mere facts of experience ; and we have now seen how pitiably he fails in his attempt. We are very confident that where ho has failed no other phenomenist will succeed ; but if any one makes the attempt, we promise 23G The Philosophy of Theism. beforehand to meet him straightforwardly and publicly. Meanwhile, we consider ourselves to have shown, that nothing, at all events, can be more ignominious than Mr. Mill's philosophical position, whether on its " aggressive " side or its " affirmative." The paper of ours to which Mr. Mill replied, was followed by another on " the foundation of morality." In our next essay we hope to supplement that paper by one encountering him in full detail on that most vital theme, his denial of freewill. VI. MR. MILL'S DENIAL OF FREEWILL.* ON the present occasion our contention against Mr. Mill will be purely psychological, though connected, of course, with most important metaphysical questions, such as morality and again causation. On every question between intuitionists and phenomenists, we consider Mr. Mill by far our ablest opponent, as we have often said. But on the particular theme now before us, he is pre-eminently the most suitable champion we could assail; for "the theory of volition and of responsibility," says its advocate in the Westminster Review (Oct. 1873, p. 305), which was "first stated in this country by Hobbes," "is now asso- ciated most closely with the name of Mr. J. S. Mill." In addition, however, to the two works in which Mr. Mill treats this theme, we have also named at the head of our essay Dr. Bain's well-known treatise, which is identical in doctrine with Mr. Mill's volumes. And in our present essay we propose to join issue with Mr. Mill on a mere question of fact, in regard to experienced phenomena. He holds, "as a truth of experience," "that volitions do in fact follow determinate moral antecedents, with the same * F.fuminntion of Sir W. Hamilton's Philosophy. By JOHN STTAKT Mil, i.. Fourth Edition. London : Longmans. A f>y*trm of Logic, Raliocinative and Inductive. By JOHN STUART MILL. Kifjlith Kdition. London : Longmans. The Emotion* and the Will. By ALEXANDER BAIN. London : J. W. Parker. 23S The Philosophy of TJieiam. uniformity and the same certainty as physical effects follow their physical causes:" these moral antecedents being "desires, occasions, habits, and dispositions, combined with outward circumstances suitable to call those internal in- centives into action" (" On Hamilton," pp. 576, 577). He maintains, that if we knew any given " person thoroughly, and knew all the inducements which are acting on him, we could foretell his conduct with as much certainty as we can predict any physical event " (" Logic," vol. ii. p. 422). This doctrine has commonly been called " the doctrine of philo- sophical necessity," and we think the name a very suitable one. Mr. Mill, however, prefers the name " determinism ; " and in this he apparently accords with the great body of his fellow -thinkers : by all means, therefore, so let it be. For ourselves, as we have already implied, we shall not attempt in our present article to establish the full doctrine of Freewill; because this cannot be done until we have treated " causation," as we hope to do in the next essay of our series.* On the present occasion we shall content ourselves with disproving (as we consider) the psychical fact w r hich Mr. Mill alleges. He calls his theory "deter- minism ; " and we will call our own, therefore, by the name of " indeterminism." The full doctrine of Freewill includes, indeed, the doctrine of indeterminism ; but it includes also a certain doctrine on the causation of human acts, which we do not here profess to establish. It is always of pre-eminent importance in controversy to understand rightly the position of one's opponent, but on no other question (we think) is this so necessary as on the present. We will beg, therefore, our readers' most careful attention, while we draw out what we apprehend to * It ifl an inconvenience in philosophical controversy, that not un- frequently some particular themo has to be treated piecemeal, in order that nothing may be assumed without proof. It would have been indefinitely more inconvenient if we had attempted to treat causation before we had dealt with determinism. Mr. MiWs Denial of Freewill. 239 be Mr. Mill's theory, at a length which to them may pos- sibly appear tedious and superfluous. As we proceed, we will cite in footnotes illustrative passages from Mr. Mill himself and from Dr. Bain. The determinist, then, may be supposed to express himself as follows : "By the term ' motive ' I understand the desire of some pleasure which may be gained, or the aversion to some pain which may be prevented, by some given course of action.* For the sake of greater compendiousness, indeed, I will call the avoidance of pain a negative pleasure ; and I can then omit the second part of the above definition. When a man in a boat sees the approach of a storm, and rows to save his life, his motive is his desiring that negative pleasure, the escape from death. " If any motive at any moment acted alone, it would as a matter of course be followed by action in the in- dicated direction. But almost always conflicting motives are at work; or, in other words, the pleasure desired is seen to be unattainable, except with some concomitant pain. Even a flower cannot be plucked without the trouble of stooping. But in many cases there are power- ful conflicting motives in several different directions. If I enter on course A, I shall certainly or probably derive pleasure M; but on the other hand, I shall certainly or probably endure pain N : while at the same time, by pursuing course A, I shall be prevented from pursuing course B, or pursuing it at least with equal diligence ; which said course B offers special pleasures of its own, though these of course accompanied with its own pains, and so on indefinitely. Under these circumstances, an illustration of my position may be derived from mechanics. * u A motive, being a desire or an aversion, is proportional to the plm- santiu'ris us conceived by us of the thing desired, or the hurmfulncss of tlio thing shunned." (" On Hamilton," p. G0, r >.) 80 Dr. Bain : " Various motives [irwnt or prospective pleasures and jiaiint concur in urging us to act" (p. .WO). 24-0 Tlie Philosophy of Theism. A certain physical point, possessing certain intrinsic qualities, is solicited at this moment by several attracting forces : such being the case, it moves definitely and de- cisively ; not perhaps in the direction of any one force, but at all events in a direction resulting from the joint influence of all. The conflicting motives which act on my will are analogous to the conflicting forces which act on the physical point ; and my will commonly under these circumstances moves definitely and decisively, not perhaps in the exact direction of any one motive, but at all events in the direc- tion which results from the joint influence of them all.* From time to time, no doubt, there are pauses for delibera- tion ; and there are cases, also, in which there exists for a while much vacillation and (as one may say) vibration of the will. I will expound these cases presently. But in the enormous majority of instances even where there are powerful motives acting on some side which does not prevail there is no such vacillation at all, but one definite and decisive resultant. Take as an instance, the demeanour in battle of some brave soldier. He is stimulated by many impelling motives : by a certain savage pleasure in aggres- siveness, which is partly natural and is partly due to past habit ; by desire of his country's success ; by zeal, perhaps, for the cause in which his country is engaged ; by desire of his countrymen's and of the world's applause ; by repug- nance to the infamy which would follow a display of cowardice, etc. Yet the motives are in themselves extremely * Determinists " affirm as a truth of experience that volitions do, in point of fact, follow determinate moral antecedents, with the same uniformity and with the same certainty as physical effects follow their physical causes. These moral antecedents are desires, aversions, habits, and dispositions, com- bined with outward circumstances suited to call those internal incentives into action. All these again are effects of causes; those of them which are mental being consequences of education and of other moral and physical influences." (" On Hamilton," pp. 576, 577.) So Dr. Bain says in effect that the will's act is in every case determined by " the operation of the motive forces of pleasurable and painful sensibility, coupled with the mental spoutaneousness of the system " (p. 553). Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 241 strong which solicit him in the opposite direction. He is vividly conscious (even though implicitly) of the danger to which he is exposed ; of the fearful suffering, and death itself, which may not improbably befall him ; he remembers his wife and children whom he has left at home, and the doubt whether he shall ever be with them again ; he has seen, perhaps, his dear friend shot dead by his side, and would be glad to have some brief time for the indulgence of grief ; the whole scene around him is ghastly and repulsive in the extreme. Yet in the teeth of these repelling con- siderations, there is not one moment's faltering or hesita- tion : the antagonistic motives are as nothing when conflicting with those which stir him to action. Or take a son, passionately devoted to his mother and tending her in her old age. In vain he is solicited by this, that, and the other antagonistic gratification : the one master passion overbears all other motives, promptly and without a struggle. And so, if you look at the lives of men in general, you will find that, during very far the greater part of their existence, they are pursuing without hesitation one very definite line of conduct, though there is many a motive simultaneously present, which by itself has a very strong tendency to divert them from their course. " Here I can explain what I mean by the power of a motive : I mean its tendency to influence this or that man's conduct, at this or that particular instant, by means of the pleasure which it proposes. That assemblage of motives, which influences the heroic soldier or the passionately loving son in one direction, is indefinitely 'more powerful,' ' stronger ' or, in other words, indefinitely more suggestive of positive or negative pleasure than that which influences him in the other.* Here, however, I must make two * " Various motives present or prospective pleasures and pains concur in urging me to act : the result of the conflict shows that one group ia stronger tliiin another, and that is the whole case." (liain, p. f>o().) " It m only an identical proposition to affirm that the greatest of two pleasures, or vol.. I. K 242 The Philosophy of Theism. explanations, to prevent very serious misconception of my meaning. " Firstly. The natural difference of character among men is enormous ; and this enormous difference is enor- mously increased by difference of education and of past life. That which may be a most powerful motive to one man, will be a very weak one to another, and an actual cause of repulsion to a third. Nay, so moody and changeable is human nature, not only at different periods of his life, but even at different moments of the same day the same object is desired by the same man with very varying degrees of intensity. This is partly caused, indeed, by the fact that the nervous and muscular systems are so very differently affected at different instants ; so that the very same object is indefinitely more attractive at one instant than at another.* Nor, again, is there any more common pheno- menon than that a man's desire of some immediate gratification is indefinitely stronger at the moment than his desire of what he well knows to be far more to his permanent welfare ; or, in other words, that the thought of enjoying such gratification is at the moment far more suggestive to him of pleasure than is the thought of promoting his own permanent welfare. what appears such, sways the resulting action ; for it is the resulting notion that alone determines which is the greater." (Ibid. p. 447.) Mr. Mill is express on this point: "Those who say that the will follows the strongest motive, do not mean the motive which is strongest in relation to the icill, or, in other words, that the will follows what it does follow. They mean the motive which is strongest in relation to pain and pleasure ; since a motive, being a desire or aversion, is proportional to the pleasantness as conceived by us of the thing desired, or the painfulness of the tiling shunned." (" On Hamilton," p. 605.) There is another passage of Mr. Mill's, which may be cited as illustrating his doctrine in another point of view: "I dispute altogether that we are conscious of being able to act in opposition to the strongest present desire or aversion. The difference between a bad and a good man is not that the latter acts in opposition to his strongest desire : it is, that his desire to do right and his aversion to doing wrong are strong enough to overcome and in the case of perfect virtue to silence any other desire or aversion which may conflict with them." (Ibid. p. 585.) What is conscience, he elsewhere asks, except a desire " the desire to do right ? " (Ibid. p. 583.) * Bain, p. 442, and elsewhere. Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 243 " Secondly. Very prominently under the head of ' pain ' ranks ' difficulty : ' such difficulty, e.g., as accom- panies any attempt at breaking through a firmly established habit. Suppose, e.g., I have established a very firm habit of early rising. When the proper moment comes, very strong motives on the other side are spontaneously and at once counterbalanced by the difficulty of breaking through my habit. And similar phenomena are by no means con- fined to the case of habits. As one of a thousand instances, there is a very strong impulse with some men, to throw themselves down a precipice if they are standing close to its edge ; an impulse which it requires powerful effort to withstand. I am not, of course, taking a case where the man's head becomes so dizzy that he loses his power of remaining on the cliff. I am supposing a man with full power over his actions, but conscious of this strange and eccentric impulse. This impulse then acts as a strong motive : and yet it cannot in any obvious sense of the words be called either a desire of pleasure or an aversion of pain. In fact, however, it is the latter. There is very great difficulty i.e. 'pain' in resisting his natural tendency to throw himself down, and strong motives on the other side are required to counterbalance this difficulty.* * The following passage from Mr. Mill's " Logic " deserves very careful attention : "As we proceed in the formation of habits and beccane accustomed to will a particular act or a particular course of conduct because it is pleasurable, we at last continue to will it without any reference to its being pleasurable. Although, from some change in us or in our circumstances, we have ceased to find any pleasure in the action, or perhaps to anticipate any pleasure in con- sequence of it, we still continue to desire the action, and consequently to do it. In this manner it is that habits of hurtful excess continue to bo practised although they have ceased to be pleasurable; and in this manner also it is that the willingness to persevere in the course which he has chosen does not desert the moral hero, even when the reward, however real, which he doubtless receives from the consciousness of well-doing, is anything but an equivalent for the sufferings he may undergo or the wishes which ho may have to renounce" (vol. ii. p. 488, 489). The last clause of this sentence, if regard be had to its rhetoric, is one of the numerous passages in Mr. Mill's works which imply a theory on morals 244 The Philosophy of Theism. " I have hitherto considered that great majority of instances in which conflicting motives issue in a definite and decisive resultant. But I admitted at starting that this is not always the case. Sometimes, e.g., there occurs a pause for deliberation. But what more easity explicable than this on my theory ? The person pauses that he may more fully understand the full nature and consequences of proposed alternatives, before deciding which he prefers. You will say perhaps that he sometimes pauses in order to consider whether some action to which he is attracted be consistent with morality; and I admit this. But, then, this very fact implies that his desire of performing that action is not so strong as his desire of acting in accordance with morality.* " So much on the particular case of pausing. Other indefinitely truer and nobler than that in which lie philosophically acquiesced. But its logical meaning is made obvious by the earlier clause. " Habits of hurtful excess continue to be practised, although they have ceased to be pleasurable," simply because their abandonment is so intensely painful. In like manner, then, according to Mr. Mill, the difficulty of acting in opposi- tion to a strongly formed virtuous habit affords a motive which will often counterbalance very strong adverse solicitations. We may add that there arc passagi-s similar to the above in his work "On Hamilton," in pp. 58S, 58;), and in p. 605. As to such other impulses as those mentioned in the text, Dr. Bain draws especial attention to them (p. 433). Singularly enough, he adds that they "are cases of action where we cannot discover any connection betwt en pleasure enjoyed or pain averted, and the energy of active devotion made manifest;" a statement which seems at first sight to subvert his whole theory. He says, however, that " we must look for the explanation of this influence, which traverses the proper course of volition, in the undue or morbid persistency of certain ideas in the mind." In various parts of his works, Dr. Bain lays stress on these " fixed ideas ; " and it is by no means easy to see how he reconciles his language concerning them with his general theory. One mode of doing so is that given in the text. In some passages he seems to imply a different explanation ; viz. that these fixed ideas imply a certain mild form of quasi-insanity ; and that acts done under their influence are not properly volitions. We see no reason for pursuing further this inquiry, because our reader will see clearly, as we proceed, that it can in no way affect our own argument. * " If I elect to abstain " from murder, " in what sense am I conscious that I could have elected to commit the crime ? Only if I had desired to commit it with a desire stronger than my horror of murder ; not with one less strong." (Mill, " On Hamilton," p. 583.) Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 245 cases, again, no doubt exist, exemplifying what I have called vacillation and vibration of will. The devoted son, e.g. whom I just now mentioned, may fall in love, and there will at times be much vacillation and vibration between his respective desires of seeing the 3 r oung lady, and of solacing his mother's old age. Such cases, however, are very easily explained on my principles ; or rather, indeed, my principles would lead me a priori to be sure that there must be these cases of vacillation and vibration. Where the motives on one side are notably stronger than those on the other, there results a definite and decisive spontaneous impulse ; but where the motives are very nearly balanced, there must result (on the same principles) vacillation and vibration. During a closely balanced con- flict of motives, there is not a single instant in which there does not pass across the mind some thought which adds strength to, or takes it from, one or other of the contending powers. Some time, then, must necessarily elapse before the balance adjusts itself between forces neither of which is for any two successive instants the same ; and this time is, of course, one of vacillation and vibration.* If the relative power of the two motives is constantly changing, no wonder that the resultant is constantly changing also. " Here, then, is the simple doctrine of determinism ; which I take to be a mere interpretation of universal experience, a statement in words of what every one is internally convinced of.f Every human being at every moment is infallibly determined by the law of his nature to * The last sentence is almost verbatim Mr. Mill's ("On Hamilton," p. 584). An opponent had objected that " balancing one motive against another is not willing, but judging." Mr. Mill replies: "The state of mind I am speaking of is not an intellectual, but an emotional state. If there were any indis- pensable act of judging in this state, it would only be judging which of the two pains or pleasures was the greatest; and to regurd this as the operativu force would lie conceding the point in favour of uecessuriauiaiu." t These ure Mr. Mill's words in his '' Logic" (vol. ii. p. 1'Jli). 246 The Philosophy of Tlteism. choose that course of conduct which is apprehended by him as the more pleasurable or the less painful." Now, we are disposed to agree with by far the larger part of all this ; and here is, in fact, a hopeful augury for the discussion, because by consequence the issue is so very much narrowed. We object, indeed, entirely, as a matter of words, to using the term " motive " in its deterministic sense ; for to our mind a large share of the confusion which has so overspread the controversy has originated in the equivocal use of this term. We will adopt, therefore, the word "attraction," in a very similar sense to that which determinists express by the term "motive." We will call by the name of an "attraction" every thought, which proposes some pleasure, positive or negative, to be gained by some act or course of action ; and we will call one attraction stronger than another, if the pleasure proposed by the former is apprehended as greater is more attractive at the moment than that proposed by the latter. If the thought proposes " positive " pleasure, it will be a " positive " in the other case a " negative " attraction. This terminology being understood, it is very plain (as determinists urge) that every man, during by far the greater part of his life, is solicited by conflicting attrac- tions ; and it is further a manifest and undeniable matter of fact that, in the very large majority of such instances, a certain definite and decisive inclination or impulse of the will spontaneously ensues. Further, we are thoroughly disposed to agree with Mr. Mill, that this spontaneous inclination or impulse is due to the greater strength of attraction on the prevailing side ; or, in other words, to the greater pleasurableness (positive or negative) anticipated at the moment from one course of action as compared with the other. So strong and constant is the observed gravitation of human nature towards immediate pleasure, Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 247 that on this particular head Mr. Mill's theory seems to us thoroughly reasonable and well grounded. Nor, again, is this theory (to our mind) best refuted by dwelling on those instances of pause, or, again, of vacillation and vibration, to which reference has above been made ; although we are very far from regarding the deterministic exposition of those instances as at all sufficient. But we think that the opposition between determinism and indeterminism is by no means so clearly brought out by such cases, as it is by the far more numerous ones in which the will's spontaneous impulse is definite and decisive. The whole argument, then (in our view), should be made to turn on one most simple and intelligible issue. We beg our readers, then, to fix their attention on that definite and decisive spontaneous impulse of the will,* which is so very common a phenomenon, and to which we have so often referred. We entirely agree with Mr. Mill, as we just now said, that this spontaneous impulse of the will is infallibly determined at each particular moment, by the balance of pleasurableness as apprehended at that moment. But the whole deterministic argument rests from beginning to end on the assumption that men never resist this spontaneous impulse ; whereas we confidently affirm, as an experienced fact, that there are cases of such resistance numerous, unmistakable, nay, most striking. What we allege to be a fact of indubitable experience is this. At some given moment, my will's gravitation, as it may be called, or spontaneous impulse is in some given direction ; insomuch that if I held myself passively, if I let my will alone, it would with absolute certainty move accordingly; but, in fact, I exert myself with more or less vigour to resist such impulse, and then the action of my * It muy he better to point out that Dr. Bain winn-times (e.g. in p. 442) uses the term "spontaneoUH impulse" he nowhere, wu believe, says " spon- taneous iiuj'iilbf of the icill" in u sense fundamentally distinct from our own. 2 IS The Philosophy of Theixm. will is in a different, often an entirely opposite, direction. In other words, we would draw our readers' attention to the frequently occurring simultaneous existence of two very distinct phenomena. On the one hand (1) my will's gravi- tation or spontaneous impulse is strongly in one direction ; while, on the other hand, at the same moment (2) its actual movement is quite divergent from this. Now, that which " motives " * to use deterministic language affect, is most evidently the will's spontaneous inclination, impulse, gravitation. The determinist, then, by saying that the will's movement is infallibly determined by "motives," is obliged to say that the will never moves in opposition to its spontaneous impulse. And, in fact, he does say this. All determinists assume as a matter of course that the will never puts forth effort for the purpose of resisting its spontaneous impulse. We, on the contrary, allege that there is no mental fact more undeniable than the frequent putting forth of such effort.t And on this critical point issue is now to be joined. * For convenience sake in this paragraph wo use the word " motives " as determinists do. t As it is very important to avoid all possibility of cavil, it will be per- haps better to add one further explanation of the exact point at issue. Mr. Mill and Dr. Bain hold that in each case the spontaneous impulse or inclina- tion of the will is determined by the balance of immediate pleasure ; and (taking into account the various explanations they give of their statement) we are so far entirely in accord with them. But our own essential argument would not be affected in the slightest degree, if this theory of theirs were disproved. And it is worth while, at the risk of being thought tedious, to make this clear. The essence of determinism is the doctrine, that at any given moment the will's movement is infallibly and inevitably determined by circumstances. (1) internal and (2) external; i.e. (1) by the intrinsic constitution and dis- position of the will, and (2) by the external influences which act on it. Now, no one doubts that in every man, during far the larger portion of his waking life, there exists what we have called a definite and decisive spontaneous impulse of his will ; and determinists allege that circumstances (internal and external) determine the will's actual movement, precisdy by determining its spontaneous impulse. It is the very essence of determinism, therefore, to allege that the will's actual movement is never divergent from its spon- taneous impulse. Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 249 Before commencing our argument, however, there are one or two further questions of terminology to be settled. And, first, how shall we define the word " motive '? " Our own acceptation of it may be thus set forth. We premise the obvious truth, that some ends are aimed at for their own sake, and others only for the sake of the former class : the former we will call "absolute," the latter "relative," ends. To these two classes of ends correspond two classes of "motives." My "ultimate motive" in a course of action is my resolve of pursuing some absolute end or ends, with a view to obtaining which I begin and continue that course of action. And what an "ultimate motive" is in relation to an absolute end or ends, precisely that is an "immediate" or "intermediate" motive in relation to a relative end or ends. We say " end or ends," because it is one of the most familiar among mental phenomena that men often aim simultaneously at many ends. A youth, e.g., applies himself to study, partly for the sake of enjoying its pleasure, and partly for the sake of his future temporal advancement. Where the end is single, we may call the motive " simple ; " where there is more than one end we may call the motive " complex." But it is a different question altogether, and one entirely irrelevant to the deterministic controversy, to inquire what is the exact fixed relation which exists between circumstances on the one hand and the will's spontaneous impulse on the other. Mr. Mill and Dr. Bain adopt on this question the balance-of-pleasure theory ; and here wo agree with them. But quite imaginably philosophers might arise (though we think this very improbable) who should adduce strong arguments for some different theory on the subject. Now this, as our readers will see, is a cross-controversy altogether, and in no way affects the issue between determinism and its assailants. Wo have ourselves assumed, throughout our essay, the balance-! >f- pleasure theory as confessedly and indisputably true ; because (1) we account it the true one, anil Injcause (2) it is held by all the determinists we ever heard of; but nothing would bo easier than to mould our argument according to any dill'rrent theory which might be established. The question, between dctcr- minists and ourselves, is not at all how the will's spontaneous impulse is farmed, but exclusively whether it is ever rrsixti'd. Determinists as such say that it is never resisted, and indcterininists as such maintain the con- trary. 2:>0 The Philosophy of Tliewm. So far we are on common ground with determinists. But they hold that the " resolve of pursuing some absolute end" is simply synonymous with the "desire of some preponderating pleasure," positive or negative. For the sake, therefore, of making ourselves more intelligible to our Catholic readers, we will proceed a little further. Whatever absolute end I aim at is always either " bonum honestum " or "bonum delectabile ; " or, in other words, it is either the practising of some virtuousness or the enjoying of some pleasure. So far as this truth is needed in our future argument, we shall not fail to prove it ; here we assume it. My " ultimate motive," then, in any act or course of action, will always be either (1) my resolve of practising some virtuousness ; or (2) my resolve of enjoying or trying to enjoy some pleasure ; or (3) some combination of such resolves. In the first two cases my motive is " simple ; " in the last it is " complex." We need hardly add how often it happens that such " resolves," however real and influential, are implicit or unreflected on. So much on the word " motive ; " but now further. We have already expressed our conviction that at any given moment the will's spontaneous impulse (of which we have said so much) is infallibly determined by the preponderance of pleasure proposed. The thought of this preponderating pleasure may be called the " preponderating attraction," or " the resultant of co-existing attractions." Again, we have often to speak of the will's " spontaneous impulse ; " this we will sometimes call the will's "preponderating" impulse ; or, for brevity's sake, we may omit the adjective altogether, and speak of the will's "impulse." Resistance to this impulse may be called " anti-impulsive effort " issuing in " anti-impulsive action." The determinist, then, denies that there is any such thing in man as anti-impulsive effort, or (a fortiori) as anti -impulsive action. According to his theory, not only Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 251 the will's spontaneous impulse, but its actual movement, is at every moment infallibly determined by the balance of pleasure. He readily admits that men often put forth great efforts sometimes most intense efforts in response to their preponderating attraction of the moment ; witness the case above mentioned, of brave soldiers engaged in battle. But he alleges that such effort is always in response, and never in opposition, to their preponderating attraction ; and that this must inevitably be the case while human nature remains what it is.* On our side, if we expressed our full mind, we should say that all men in full possession of their faculties have a true moral power and by no means unfrequently exercise it of anti-impulsive action ; and that of course, therefore, they may be no less free when they yield to their will's impulse than when they resist it. In our present argument, however (as w r e have explained), the ideas of " power " and " freedom " are to be put in abeyance, and we are to speak only of experienced facts. It is our purpose, then, here to prove against the determinist that so far from anti-impulsive efforts and action being non-existent they are by no means rare ; nay, that in one particular class of men they are among the commonest and most unmistakable phenomena in the whole world. We need hardly say that, in our view, devout Theists are immeasurably the most virtuous class of human beings. Consequently, in our view, devout Theists will, with absolute certainty, immeasurably exceed other men in their anti- impulsive efforts ; for the simple reason that they im- * Wo cannot understand the determinists' objection to the word " neccs- sarianism," as expressing their doctrine. According to that doctrine, so long as my nature remains what it is, uiy volitions are infallibly determined by circumstances external and internal. On the one hand, I have no power of altering my nature; on the other hand, I have not, nor have had, any power of controlling those past and present circumstances, which in combination infallibly and inevitably determine my volition. How cau uuu imagine a more complete " necebsitutiuu " of my whole conduct? 252 The Philosophy of TJteism. measurably exceed other men in the vigilant care with which they adjust their volitions by a standard which they consider supremely authoritative. Nor have we an}' hesitation in saying that able and thoughtful men could never have even dreamed of so monstrous a theory as determinism, had the}' not been densely and crassly ignorant of the practical working of devout Theism. Here, in fact, is one of those instances, by no means few, in which a devout Christian possesses no ordinary advantage over irreligious men, in his power of investigating truth. He could as easily doubt that he experiences temptation, as that from time to time he resists it ; or, to put the thing more distinctly, he could as easily doubt that at times the preponderating impulse of his will is towards some pleasurableness which he accounts unlawful, as he could doubt that at this or that given moment he is resisting such impulse. We will not, however, begin with consider- ing the practical working, in this respect, of devout Theism ; we will begin with that great majority of mankind who are, either in theory or at least in practice, irreligious. Even such men do from time to time resist their will's prepon- derating impulse ; whether for the sake of acting virtuously, or, much more frequently, for the sake of promoting their permanent worldly interest. And as our whole appeal is, of course, necessarily to experienced facts, we must be pardoned a certain familiarity of illustration. We will begin with such a case as the following : I have for some time past been a reckless spendthrift, and am well aware that I am travelling rapidlj- along the road to ruin ; though my temperament is such that the positive attraction of present pleasure greatly preponderates over the negative attraction of escape from a direly calamitous future. One fine day, however, in my travels I come across a wretched and squalid creature, who re- counts to me his history ; and I find that its earlier part Mr. Mill's Denial of Freeivill. 253 is a precise parallel of my own. The sight of his abject and deplorable condition produces on me a profound im- pression, and the idea of him is ever haunting me. While this impression remains fresh, there is a complete reversal in the relative power of those attractions which solicit me ; and whenever the thought enters my mind of squandering money, the memory of what I have seen promptly redresses the balance, and the definite decisive impulse of my will is towards economy. Time, however, passes on, and my memory of the poor creature I met with becomes fainter, until at last, on some occasion when I am very specially drawn by some tempting indulgence, the decisive and definite impulse of my will is towards wasting money in its purchase. Is it, or is it not, infallibly certain, from the laws of human nature, that I shall yield to this impulse ? Are there, or are there not, cases in which a person so circumstanced even though in no way under the influence of religious motives by means of anti-impulsive efforts, holds back his will, and fixes his thoughts again on the ruined spendthrift he has seen ; until a lively counter- attraction has resulted, and the will's preponderating impulse has changed its direction ? Let an inquirer honestly examine his own past consciousness, and let him appeal to the testimony of others : we are very certain what the answer will be. It will be said, perhaps, that at last there is no very courageous or heroic resistance here, seeing that the will's impulse, though definite and decisive, was by no means intense. The answer, however, is easy. Firstly, if one unmistakable case of anti-impulsive effort be established, the deterministic theory is overthrown. Secondly, we are the very last to allege that any very courageous or heroic resistance to preponderating impulse will be found, except in devout Theists. Our second illustration shall be taken from a far 254 The Philosophy of Theism. humbler and more commonplace event. A, B, and C, three young brothers, go to a dentist. He tells them all the same thing : " You have not been taught the proper way of brushing your teeth. If you don't take more time over it than is now your habit, and if you don't perform the operation in the way I have just shown you, you will lose all your serviceable teeth before you pass the prime of life." The three of them accept his statement as true. A has alwaj's had a perfect horror of false teeth. The thought of such a danger is vividly present with him every night and morning, when the tooth-brush is in his hands ; and he spontaneously obeys the dentist's admonition. B, by temperament, cares little for the future ; accordingly, in a very few days he has forgotten all about the dentist, and goes on just as he did before. Neither of these cases evidently includes any phenomenon inconsistent with determinism. C's history, however, is different. For two or three weeks, indeed, his will's preponderating impulse leads him to take the requisite trouble. One morning, however, when the wind is southerly and the sky cloudy, he is in a hurry to get his breakfast over and start off hunting ; and his very decided impulse is to make his tooth-brushing a most perfunctory operation. He dis- tinctly remembers, however, the dentist's warning ; and he knows well enough that, if he once begin to neglect it, there is imminent danger of confirmation in a bad habit. These thoughts are clearly and distinctly in his mind, though not so vividly as to preponderate over the opposite attraction. Nevertheless to use an equestrian simile such as he would himself love he pulls himself up, and reins himself in ; he dwells on the thoughts which are so clearly and distinctly in his mind, until they become vivid, and the balance of attraction is changed to the opposite side. Determinists say that such a case as this never happens ; that the laws of human nature forbid it. Will any candid inquirer on reflection endorse their dictum ? Mr. MilVs Denial of Freewill. 255 We may appeal, indeed, to the universal voice of man- kind, which, on a matter of observed fact, is the most irrefragable of authorities.* It is quite proverbial, and in every one's mouth, that man has a real power of following reason where it conflicts with passion. Now, men would not surely have come to believe in such a power had they not observed numerous facts in corroboration ; especially each man within the sphere of his own intimate self- experience. Further, considering how very small a proportion of mankind can look on their own habitual conduct with satisfaction, if they choose carefully to measure it even by their own standard of right, emphatic stress may justly be laid on the universal conviction that there is such a thing as sin and guilt. There could be no sin or guilt if every one's conduct were infallibly and inevitably deter- mined by circumstances ; and what a balm, therefore, to wounded consciences is offered by the deterministic theory ! Yet so strong and ineradicable in the mass of men is their conviction of possessing a real power against temptation, that they never attempt to purchase peace of mind by disclaiming that power. But, as we have already urged, how could such a conviction have possibly come to possess them, had they not frequently experienced that power in its actual exercise ? t * Mr. Mill (" On Hamilton," p. 581, note) speaks with contempt of " accepting Hodge as a better authority in metaphysics than Locke or Kuut." But we think there is much truth iu his opponent's affirmation, "that no philosopher, unless he be one in a thousand, can see or feel anything that is inconsistent with his preconceived opinion." t Mr. Mill at times has certainly a singular way of expressing his ideas on determinism. In his work " On Hamilton " (p. 575, note), he puts this question, with an obvious implication tliat it must be answered in the negative: "If I am determined to prefer innocence to the satisfaction of a particular desire, through an estimate of the relative worth of innocence and the gratification, can this estimate, while unchanged, leave me at liberty to choose the gratification in preference to innocence?" Why plainly on Mr. Mill's principles to whatever extent I may more highly fnh'nmti' the of innocence as compared with the gratification, I am often inevitably 250 The Philosophy of Theivm. We cannot doubt, then, that even the mass of men who live mainly for this world do by no means un frequently, however languidly and falteringly, oppose themselves to the spontaneous impulse of their will. For our own part, indeed, we hold confidently that those cases of vacillation and vibration, to which we have more than once referred, are often results of this circumstance. Many of these cases, doubtless, can be explained in the way suggested by Mr. Mill ; but certainly not all. In several of them, we are confident, the fact is, that the will first languidly and falteringly resists its own spontaneous impulse, and then (for want of due energy) sinks back into acquiescence ; that another languid effort presently succeeds, to be again followed by relapse ; and so on possibly for a considerable period of time. Still though all men do, from time to time, put forth some anti-impulsive effort it follows obviously, as we have already said, from our philosophical principles, that very far the most signal illustrations of the doctrine we are defending will be found in the devout Theist's resistance to temptation. Nor has the determmist any right to ignore such facts because he himself may believe that no God is cognizable and that devout Theism is a superstition. If it be unmistakably proved that those who hold and act on a certain belief (however untrue he may consider that belief) do put forth great, or indeed any, anti- impulsive effort, he is bound in reason to abandon his theory. We will proceed, then, to exhibit, as clearly as we can, those facts to which we invite his attention. To Catholics they are familiar, and the determinist may easily, if he chooses, convince himself of their truth. Nor is driven to choose the latter in preference to the former. According to him, this result will inevitably ensue, whenever the balance of pleasurublencss is on the side of gratification. How strange that he should speak of " estimating the relative irorth " of two objects, when ho meant to express " balancing their relative pleasunibleness." He seems ashamed of his own theory, when he has to face it. Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 257 there any reason why, in stating them, we should adopt the artificial course of veiling our own hearty sympathy with piety, or our conviction that those who are not devout Theists are like poor sheep going astray. It suffices, if we carefully avoid all " petitio principii ; " if we never assume the truth of Theism as any part of our premisses ; if we state distinctly and articulately the facts which we are alleging in argument. Before we begin this task, however, we will make one or two preliminary remarks, which will enable us to accom- plish it better. Our readers, therefore, will understand that what immediate!} 7 follows is no integral part of our argument, but only an introduction thereto. And the first of these preliminary remarks is that a devout Theist thinks very far more than another of merely interior acts. He will feel it a sacred duty to contend most earnestly against his will's impulse, though solicited thereby to no other offence than an evil thought, whether it be of impurity, of anger, of impatience, of pride, of vainglory. Our second preliminary remark is, that to those who have trained themselves in habits of virtue, virtue itself supplies an attraction often an exceedingly powerful one,* and which by itself suffices to counterbalance a * What is here said in the text may at first cause a certain difficulty in the mind of some Catholics, which we had better remove. Our comment, however, will be more appropriately placed in a note, because it is so com- plete a digression from our general argument. It is held by the large majority of theologians, and appears to us in- dubitably true, that no act is virtuous which is not directed " actually " or " virtually " to " bonum houestum " to a virtuous end. Suppose, e.g., I meet a poor man, who is a singularly worthy recipient of alms. At the same time I neither know this fact nor think of inquiring about it, but I give him some money, merely to obtain his services as guide to some beautiful scenery in the neighbourhood. The act is materially most virtuous, because the man is so worthy a rrcipient ; but any one would be supremely absurd who should account it n formally virtuous act of almsgiving. The difficulty, then, in the text which may at first strike a Catholic is this : how can virtue ever supply an "attraction"? An act done merely for tho sake of pleasure is no virtuous act at all ; and if it bo nnt done for tho sake of pleasure, how in such cusos can virtue be said to supply an attraction ? Tho VOL. I. S 258 The Philosophy of Theism. large number of opposite gratifications. Acts of love towards God, of gratitude towards Christ, of zeal for God's glory, are often in a pious man extremely pleasurable ; nay, even such acts as resignation to God's will in trouble and patience under cruel insults, not unfrequently carry with them special sweetness of their own. The peace also of subdued passions and a good conscience may afford a pleasure which " passeth all understanding." At times, again, the thought of heaven is most bracing and exhila- rating. Then there are negative attractions also, which act powerfully on the side of virtue. The knowledge of that remorse, which will assuredly follow a good man's momentary lapse from virtue ; the fear of hell or of purgatory ; all these may act very strongly on the emotions. Then as our supposed determinist set forth in his ex- position of doctrine at the commencement of our essay there are negative attractions, which are very powerful without being emotional at all.* The difficulty, e.g., of answer, however, is simple. An act need not be motived by pleasure at all ; and yet a very large amount of pleasure may be aniiexed to its performance, whether by the ordinary laws of human nature or by God's special inter- vention. Take the instance above given. Suppose I had known the poor man to be a most worthy recipient of alms ; and hud given him money, not in return for any service whatever, but exclusively from my remembrance how highly our Blessed Lord praised almsgiving ; and that forasmuch as I did it to the least of His disciples, I did it to Him. No Catholic will deny that this act was most virtuous ; yet I might have derived far more pleasure from this thought of Christ than I should have obtained from the most beautiful scenery to which the poor man could have guided me. We do not, of course, at all deny that in very many cases there is a mixture of motives. Perhaps I know very well how worthy a recipient of alms is this man ; and I give him money, partly from such a reason as that just described, but partly also that I may obtaiu his services as guide. Different theologians pronounce differently on such a case, so far at least as regards their mode of expression. We are ourselves disposed to say that the integral energy of the will at any such moment should be considered as con- sisting of two different acts, one motived by virtuousness, and the other by pleasure; that the former act is simply virtuous, and the latter is simply indifferent, neither good nor bad. * A few words of psychological exposition will here be useful on these non-emotional attractions ; though our doctrine on them is entirely concur- rent with that of Mr. Mill and Dr. Bain. Let us take our illustration from Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 250 breaking through a firmly established habit is a very powerful negative attraction, though accompanied with little or no emotion. And a similar non-emotional but strong negative attraction is experienced when some good end is proposed by the intellect with unusual vividness a vividness, perhaps, very far greater than is due to the existing strength of acquired habit, because, proportionately to such vividness, there would be peculiar difficulty and pain in contravening that end. Taking all these and many similar phenomena into consideration, it is easy to account for the indubitable fact, that very frequently the spontaneous impulse of a devout Theist's will is one of high virtue. But every one well knows by experience how singularly capricious is human emotion. The very same thoughts Dr. Bain's own instance of early rising. A, B, and C agree in this, that the spontaneous impulse of their will leads them on eome given morning to rise at an hour when the counter-attractions are by no means weak which solicit them to stay in bed. A is thus influenced because it is the first of Sep- tember ; all yesterday he was thinking of the partridges, and now that the happy day has arrived he springs out of bed with a joyous heart. B fancies he hears an alarm of fire, and starts up in a panic : while C gets up in ac- cordance with his firm and established habit. A is influenced by a positive attraction, B by a negative one, both acting on their will through their emotions. But consider the attraction which acts on C ; or, in other words, the thought of pleasure or pain which influences his will. This thought is nothing else than his sense of the difficulty which opposes his resisting the impulse engendered by his habit. We see at once that this thought acts powerfully on his will in the way of suggesting pain, without exciting his emotions at all. On the other hand, there would be a strong emotion (of pain) if his impulse were thwarted ; if, e.g., he were compelled to go on for hours lying in bed, because on some bitterly cold morning he had neither clothes to put on nor means of lighting a fire. So far we are entirely at one with determinists. For the sake, however, of giving one further instance of the contrast between their theory and our own, we may add that we admit a fourth case ; that of D, whose spon- taneous impulse would load him to lie in bed, but who, for the sake of some good end, resists that impulse and gets up. The determinitjt must deny that such a case is possible so long as the laws of human nature remain what they are. Dr. Bain, in his treatment of moral habits (pp. 500-510), speaks, so far as we have observed, in entire consistency with his deterministic throry. For our own part, we hold that anti-impulsive efforts are immeasurably the most effective mount) of strengthening a good habit; but Dr. liain uowhuri; implies that there such things. 2GO The Philosophy of Theivm. which on one day or at one moment excite the keenest feeling, on another day or at another moment fail wholly of any such effect. According to the laws of hum an nature, this great emotional difference is probably far more con- siderable in the case of more susceptible and highly-strung souls than in that of ordinary mortals ; nor do we doubt that God often, for purposes of probation, intensifies by special agency the working of natural laws. Every one acquainted with saints' lives well knows the vicissitudes between spiritual rapture on one side and spiritual desola- tion on the other, which constitute one principal probation of those most highly favoured among mankind. This statement, then, brings us to the particular fact on which we lay stress in our present controversy. At some given moment, some holy man finds suddenly a strongly preponderating impulse of his will soliciting him to some act, which he regards with intense disapprobation as a grievous offence against his Creator. He still, of course, retains that very considerable negative attraction to good which is caused by his habits of virtue ; but his emotions in that direction are for the moment in abeyance, while those leading in the opposite direction are for the moment so abnormally excited as vastly to predominate over the opposite attraction. Here, then, we have a crucial test of the deterministic theory. The enormous balance of pleasurableness is on the side of yielding to the temptation ; and according to determinists, therefore, the holy man (by the very necessity of human nature) yields irresistibly thereto as irresistibly as a physical point yields to the resultant of the forces which attract it. We need hardly say how violently such a statement is opposed to the most undeniable facts. Nor, indeed, need we confine our atten- tion to persons of saintly attainment ; the case of any devout Theist will suffice. Let it once be understood what is the deterministic theory, and no one, acquainted with Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 261 the most ordinary facts of Catholic experience, can hear it advocated without amazement. For the deterministic theory comes simply to this, that resistance to predominat- ing temptation* is not so much as possible under the existing laws of human nature. There is no single Catholic, who has at any time so much as attempted to lead a devout life, who does not know the reverse of this by his own quite unmistakable self-experience. You might as well try to persuade him that he is never visited with predominating temptation as that he never resists it ; nay, you might as well try to persuade him that the rain does not wet, that the wind does not blow, that the sun does not warm. As we said before, no pious man can possibly hold deter- minism as soon as he comes to see what is meant by the term. It has been maintained, indeed, by determinists that no psychological analysis is possible of such a phenomenon as resistance to predominating temptation ; that the relation between intellect and will, as testified by experience, implies an absolute dependence of volitions on the motives intellectually proposed. When we come (in a later part of this essay) to treat objections, we will answer this in detail ; here we will but make a brief remark. There is no experienced fact in the whole world more conspicuously manifest than that pious men very frequently do resist predominant temptation. If, then, there be a psychological theory which would lead validly to the conclusion that no such resistance ever takes place, such theory is by that very circumstance shown demonstratively to be false. On the other hand, if it were really the case that the phenomena * A person may be said to be visited by " temptation " whenever lie is solicited by any attraction towards forbidden pleasures, even though such attraction be more than counterbalanced by other opposite ones. By using the term "predominant" temptation, then, we mean to express a case iu which the attractions towards forbidden pleasure preponderate over their opposes, so that the will's spontaneous impulse is fti the sinful direction. 202 TJm Philosophy of TJteism. of resistance have not yet been satisfactorily analyzed l>y scientific men, that would be no ground for disbelieving what experience so urgently testifies, but only for working at the indicated psychological problem. No explanation at all adequate has yet been discovered of the phenomena of dreams ; but men do not on that ground deny, that there are such things as dreams. However (as we shall set forth a little further on) we think ourselves that the psycho- logical explanation commonly given by indeterminists is in substance entirely sound and sufficient. There are two further facts, which we allege to bo testified by experience ; and we will here set them forth, not because we can lay any stress on them in our contro- versy with determinism, but merely for the sake of avoiding possible misconception. It is a very frequent phenomenon, we hold, that a devout man, even when his will's spontaneous impulse leads to an entirely virtuous act, proceeds nevertheless by an effort to make his act more virtuous (i.e. more efficaciously directed to the virtuous end) than it otherwise would be. On the other hand, it is not unfrequent that a man partially resists some temptation, but not with sufficient energy for the avoidance (as Catholics consider) of mortal sin. We have now set forth, sufficiently for our purpose, those broad facts of human action which make it so obviously certain that determinism is false. At the same time, our exposition will have shown how innocent we are of charges frequently brought against indeterminists, that they disparage the inestimable importance of virtuous habits and of good moral education. What can be more important for the cause of virtue than that the spontaneous impulse of men's will should be as virtuous as it can possibly be made ? And what other agency is there (on our theory) which, on the whole, tends to make that impulse virtuous, comparably with the effect produced by Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill 263 good habits and good education ? Zealous, indeed, as the Church has ever been in upholding Freewill, still more conspicuous has been her zeal for her children's moral and religious training. One further question remains to be asked. What are the motives which actuate a man when he resists his will's spontaneous impulse? In every instance, by far the easiest course is to act in response to that impulse ; and no one will take the trouble of resisting it, except for some unmistakably worthy motive, some clear dictate of reason. There are two, and two only, classes of motives which occur to our mind as adequate to the purpose. First, there is the resolve of doing what is right. We consider ourselves to have shown irrefragably in the third essay in this volume, that there are various acts, cognizable under certain cir- cumstances to be base, detestable, forbidden by a Supreme Euler; and certain others excellent, noble, approved, and counselled by this Supreme Euler. Here, then, is one most worthy motive for resisting my will's spontaneous impulse, whenever that impulse solicits me to something detestable and forbidden, or even to something less excellent than another proposed alternative. Another motive, which often suggests itself, is my desire of promoting my permanent happiness in the next world, or even in this. It happens again and again that my will's spontaneous impulse solicits me to some act which even if I consider this world alone is known by me as likely to result in misery ; or, at all events, in much less happiness than I should otherwise enjoy. Here it is a plain dictate of reason that I resist that impulse, which otherwise would load to consequences BO disastrous. It is an observed phenomenon, we contend, that men do at times resist the spontaneous impulse of their will, when induced so to do by one or other of these two classes of motives ; * but where such motives are away, * \Ve do not, of course, for a moment deny that dcterimnists include both 2G4 The Philosophy of Theism. it seems to us a matter of course that every one is always led by his predominating attraction. With one further explanation, we bring to a close our positive exposition of the doctrine we would maintain. It regards the distinction drawn by Mr. Mill, between mere " determinism " and "fatalism." We here differ (we think) from the large majority of his opponents ; for we cannot but hold that he establishes his point (see his work " On Hamilton," p. 601). Fatalists maintain that the will can exercise no influence over the character ; and Mr. Mill may earnestly deny this (as he does), without at all affirm- ing that the will has any power of resisting its own spontaneous impulse. Mr. Mill, of course, quite admits that mere determinism is as absolutely contradictory to Freewill as is fatalism itself. But the practical bearing on the point at issue is excellently expressed by him, in a note replying to an opponent, at pp. 602, 603. Suppose that a person dislikes some part of his own character, and would be glad to change it. He cannot, as he well knows, change it by a mere act of volition. He must use the means which nature gives to ourselves, as she gave to our parents and teachers, of influencing our character by appropriate circum- stances. If he is a fatalist, he will not use these means, for he will not believe in their efficacy . . . but if he is a [determiuist and] if the desire is stronger than the means are disagreeable, he will set about doing what, if done, will improve his character. We are now to consider the very numerous objections that have been raised against indeterminism : a considera- tion which, we venture to say, will at every step put in clearer light the irrefragable truth of that doctrine against the pleasurableness of virtue and the pleasurableneas of promoting a man's own permanent interest among the attractions which influence his will. But it is a matter of every-day experience that the pleasurableness of this or that immediate gratification is more attractive than these at some given moment. And what we allege is, that men not unfrequently resist such preponderating attraction for the sake of practising virtue or of promoting their own per- manent interest Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 2G5 which they are brought. It will be in various ways, how- ever, more convenient to consider these objections as brought, not merely against indeterminism, but against the full doctrine of Freewill. Nor is such a procedure in any way unfair to our opponents, but the very contrary, for it does but offer them a larger target to shoot at. Hitherto, then, we have been merely alleging, as an experienced fact, that men often do resist their will's spontaneous impulse : but in the next essay of our series we are to maintain, as a doctrine deducible from the experienced fact, that they possess the power of resistance; and that, possessing it, they act with true freedom on every relevant occasion, whether they exercise that power or no.* This is the doctrine of Freewill ; and we are now to treat the various objections which have been raised against it by determinists. It is difficult to marshal Mr. Mill's objections in due order, because he is directly answering, not our doctrine, but Sir W. Hamilton's. "We gladly give all honour to Sir W. Hamilton, for his zealous advocacy both of Theism and of Freewill ; but there are particulars on which we widely differ from him, and, indeed, we regard Reid as both a sounder and abler, though of course a very much less learned, philosopher. Indeed, we think Mr. Mill obtains unreasonable advantage on many philosophical questions by replying to Hamilton's statements and arguments rather than to Reid's. At all events, we have not ourselves to do with any of Mr. Mill's objections, except those which are relevant against our own doctrine. We will take every care, however, that no one of those objections shall fail to be distinctly stated and examined by us, either in this or in a following essay of our series ; and we will supplement them with all the others known to us, which have bc-en advanced by Dr. Bain and others of his school. 1. The first objection, we consider, shall bo that to which * This doctriuo is developed in the essay on " Freewill." Ku. 26C TJte Philosophy of TJtdsm. we have already expressly referred ; viz. that no satisfactory psychological analysis has ever been alleged, of such an act as resistance to the will's spontaneous impulse. We have already said that, if this were really the case seeing that the fact of such resistance is undeniable no other inference would be legitimate, except, perhaps, that psychologians have been wanting in perspicacity. We think, however, that the account of the matter commonly given by liber- tarians is true and sufficient; viz. that the will can for a moment suspend its movement, and then proceed to a choice of the motive on which it shall proceed to act. But perhaps it will be more satisfactory if we work the matter out with more detail. We will take, therefore, as our special instance, that of a devout Theist resisting strong predominant temptation ; because it is this which, far more vividly than any other, displays the phenomena of Free- mil, and because what we say of this can be applied without much difficulty to all other cases. We will suppose, then, a holy man resisting some pre- dominant temptation to mortal sin. Our own view of what takes place under these circumstances is such as this. In the very first instant he yields to it by necessity,* because his will has had no time whatever to collect its self-deter- mining power. In the next instant he does two things : he suspends the act of consent, and he looks up to Almighty God for strength and help. We may add that such prayer continues with great intensity (though often perhaps im- plicitly) through the whole ensuing conflict. After the second instant, as we may call it, we arrive at the critical point. Much more probably than not since he is so holy a man even before the temptation began, God was im- plicitly at least in his thoughts ; but otherwise, according * According to Catholic terminology, the very first assaults of temptation are called " motus prim5 primi ; " and to these the will consents without any sin. They are followed by " motus secundo primi ; " and even to these the will may consent without mortal sin. Mr. Mitt's Denial of Freewill. 267 to the experienced laws of Jiabit, the very presence of temptation summons into his mind some virtuous thought, distinct or confused as the case may be. From the motives which present themselves, he rapidly chooses such as seem most hopeful for success. Sometimes it may happen that such thoughts speedily excite the appropriate sensible devo- tion, and that his will's impulse at once changes its direc- tion. At other times, though very little sensible devotion may be excited, yet the good motives are so vividly set before his mind, that they constitute a very strong non- emotional attraction, and that in this case also the will's impulse is speedily changed. At other times, lastly, the force of predominant attraction long remains on the other side, and he is left to support the arduous conflict in deso- lation. Students of hagiology well know S. Catherine of Sienna's fearful probation, and her heroic demeanour for so many days.* For all that long period, so it would seem, the preponderance of attraction was strongly towards forbidden gratification, and her anti -impulsive action intense and unremitting. Such, in our view, is on the whole a true analysis of what takes place under the circumstances. Those psycho- logians who are not satisfied with it must really take on themselves the trouble of discovering a better. The broad fact of resistance remains simply undeniable. II. A second objection, raised by determinists, often takes the form of a triumphantly asked question. Can it be gravely maintained, they ask, that a man ever acts against his strongest motive ? Never was there a poorer equivocation than this " Achilles " of our opponents. What do the} 7 mean by " acting against the strongest motive " ? Do they mean " resisting the strongest attraction " ? In that case it is the negative, and not the affirmative, answer * Wo need hardly say that Catholics attribute this moral power of resist- ing grave temptation to the agency of grace. Such considerations, however, are external to the present coutroveisy. 268 Tlie Philosophy of TJiewm. to their question, which is the true paradox. Is it para- doxical to say that reason can resist predominant passion ? or to say that it can not ? The ne plus ultra of paradox, indeed, has been reached, we should think, by Mr. Fitz- james Stephen, in his work on "Liberty, Equality, Fraternity." " That any human creature," he says (p. 294), "ever under any conceivable circumstances, acted otherwise than in obedience to that which, for the time being, was his strongest wish, is to me an assertion as incredible and as unmeaning as the assertion that on a particular occasion two straight lines enclosed a space." " A man's strongest wish " must be the wish which determined the spontaneous impulse of his will. Mr. Stephen, then, is not content with saying that men have, in fact, no power of anti-impulsive effort ; but, he adds, that to affirm 'their possession of that power is an " unmeaning " statement. The only other sense in which we can understand this phrase, "the strongest motive," is "the worthiest or most reasonable motive." But to understand the determinist as meaning this, is to suppose him in a state of absolute hallucination. If all Theists acted consistently on what they hold to be the worthiest and most reasonable motive, they would lead lives of spotless virtue. III. Another argument, somewhat similar to the former, is frequently used by determinists. " When any change of will is produced," they say, "it is always effected by the agency of motives. Let it be supposed, for instance, that a man is now beginning, for the sake of his own permanent welfare, to shun some imprudent pleasure, in which he has hitherto indulged. Well, by the very statement of the case it is evident that a new motive has intervened, or, at all events, has received great additional vigour ; viz. the desire of his own permanent welfare. It is in exact accordance with our doctrine that, where there is a change in the motives, there is a change in the will's movement." Mr. Mitt's Denial of Freeivill. 269 It is this argument which, more than any other, has impressed us with a sense of the evil resulting from the equivocal use of the word " motive." Of course, in our sense of the word, under such circumstances as the above, a new "motive" has intervened; for this means neither more nor less than that a new resolve has been formed. But by "motive " they mean "the desire of some pleasure;" and this being understood, we thus rejoin. In the first place as far as our own experience and observation go it is by no means universally true that whenever a man begins to act with much greater vigour for his own permanent welfare, the thought of promoting that welfare has first become a more pleasurable and attractive thought. Often it is so, but we think that often it is not so. For argument's sake, however, we will waive this demur, and will so far accept the determinists' allegation. We proceed, then, to ask them this simple question. Do they mean that, whenever a man begins to renounce some imprudent enjoyment for the sake of his permanent welfare, the pleasure of promoting that welfare has first become greater than the pleasure of that enjoyment ? To answer this question in the negative would be to abandon their doctrine ; for it would be to say that a man sometimes acts otherwise than according to the balance of pleasurable- ness : they must, therefore, answer it in the affirmative. But if the pleasure of promoting his own permanent welfare has become greater to the agent than the pleasure of the enjoyment, then his will's spontaneous inclination, impulse, gravitation, is in favour of renouncement. The objection, then, which we are here considering, turns out at last to be nothing but the expression of that opinion with which we have credited the determinists throughout : they do but mean to say that no man ever acts in opposition to his will's spontaneous impulse. This is the very opinion against which we have been expressly arguing, and in 270 Ttw Philosophy of Tfteism. disproof of which we have adduced, as we consider, such undeniable facts. It happens again and again, we are quite confident, that a man will make efforts if he is a devout Theist, very energetic and sustained efforts towards renouncing this or that enjoyment for the sake of his per- manent welfare at times when his thought of promoting that welfare is distinctly less pleasurable than is the enjoy- ment which he strives to renounce. And, in saying this, we use the word " pleasurable " in the full sense given to it by Mr. Mill and Dr. Bain ; as including negative pleasure, and also what we have called " non-emotional attractions." The proof, of course, which we give of our allegation, is the fact on which we have so constantly insisted ; viz. that such renouncement is often begun in opposition to the will's spontaneous impulse. IV. Wonderful to say, determinists sometimes accuse their opponents of holding that men possess the power of acting without any motive. Nay, even Sir W. Hamilton (quoted by Mr. Mill in p. 572) calls a free act a " motiveless volition." This comes entirely from the equivocal use of the word " motive." V. It has often been argued by libertarians that all men are conscious of freedom, and that there is an end of the matter. Against this argument Mr. Mill raises (1) a verbal and (2) a real objection. In his verbal objection we think he is right ; in his real objection he is most certainly wrong. We begin with the former. "We are conscious," he says (" On Hamilton," p. 580), " of what is, not of what tc ill or can be:" and the word "conscious," therefore, is used improperly by libertarians to express their meaning. He admits, however (p. 582, note), on being taxed with inconsistency by an opponent, that in his " Logic " he used the word "consciousness" in the very sense to which he objects in his work " On Hamilton," as expressing " the whole of our familiar and intimate knowledge concerning Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 271 ourselves." We will use the word "self-intimacy" to express what is here spoken of. And this verbal question being disposed of, we will set forth in our own way the argument to which Mr. Mill objects, that we may consider the value of his objection. Take an obvious illustration. I am in the habit of walking out with a stick in my hand. I know, by self- intimacy, that I brandish this stick about in whatever direction I choose ; in other words, I have a confused memory of numberless instances in which I have willed to do this, and the result has followed; while I also re- member that in no single case have I willed it without the result following. In precisely the same way, I know by self-intimacy that I resist in some degree my will's spon- taneous impulse, whenever I make the attempt to do so. Then, by a certain course of reasoning, the validity of which is to be defended in the next essay of our series, I infer from this latter phenomenon that I have a poicer of resisting the impulse of my will ; or, in other words, that I am a free agent. Now, how does Mr. Mill reply to this reasoning? Surely by a most shallow sophism. When two courses are open to us, he says ("On Hamilton," p. 582), " I feel (or am convinced) that I could have chosen the other course, if I had preferred it, that is, if I had liked it better ; but not that I could have chosen one course while I preferred the other." Such a statement would not possess a moment's plausibility, were it not for Mr. Mill's ambiguous use of the terms " prefer " and " like better ; " and we will begin with exposing this equivocation. In one sense, I may "prefer" course A to course B at some given moment; viz. in this sense, that I am at the moment more attracted by the former than by the latter ; that I spontaneously gravitate to the former course, and not to the latter. And yet at the very same moment I may "prefer" immeasurably course B to course A : in this sense, that I think course B 272 The Philosophy of Tfteism. immeasurably preferable, as, e.g., being immeasurably more conducive to my permanent happiness. Whether, there- fore, I pursue course A or course B, in either case it may be truly said that I pursue the course which I " prefer " to the other ; the course which I " like better " than the other. And it is this mere equivocation on which Mr. Mill un- consciously rests for the prima facie plausibility of his argument. Passing, however, from words to things, let us look at the experienced facts of every-day life. Certainly we do not deny it to be a matter of frequent occurrence that (under such circumstances as those above described) I effectively choose course A : " video meliora proboque, deteriora sequor." But Mr. Mill has to maintain that (under such circumstances) no human being does, or ever did, effectively choose course B ; nay, and that no human being has so much as the power of choosing it, so long as the laws of human nature remain what they are. After what has been said in the earlier part of our essay, we may safely leave this question of fact to be determined by any even moderately candid inquirer. VI. Dr. Bain (p. 540) quotes Mr. Bailey with approval, who argues that all the world in practice takes determinism for granted : Men are perpetually staking pleasure and fortune and reputation, and even life itself, on the very principle [of deter- minism] which they speculatively reject. . . . Take for example the operations of a campaign. A general . . . cannot move a step, without taking for granted that the minds of the soldiers will be determined by the motives presented to them. When he directs his aide-de-camp to bear a message to an officer in another part of the field, he calculates on his obedience with os little mistrust as he reckons on the magnifying power of the telescope in his hand. When he orders his soldiers to wheel, to deploy, to form a square, is he less confident in the result than when he performs some physical operation when he draws a sword, pulls a trigger, or seals a despatch ? etc. Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 273 As regards the external act of obedience, this kind of act is precisely of the class which on our principles can be predicted beforehand with almost infallible certainty. When the general has issued a command, the spontaneous impulse of any given soldier's will is towards obedience ; if for no other reason, because he knows that he would be at once shot down were he to hesitate ; and, on the other hand, neither the motive of virtue nor the motive of permanent self-interest has any place whatever on the opposite side. Now, as our readers will remember, it is a very important part of our thesis that no human being takes the trouble of resisting the impulse of his will, unless in such resistance he is pursuing either virtue or his own permanent happiness. The facts, then, here cited by Mr. Bailey, square entirely with our own theory ; and those stated in his next paragraph are precisely of the same kind. As regards his remarks referring to Political Economy which we do not, however, think it worth while to quote we can only recommend him to read the first of Mr. Mill's "Essays on some unsettled questions of Political Economy," in order that he may see their fundamental fallacy. But the very case thus placed before his readers by Dr. Bain the case of military obedience signally illustrates what to our mind is among the greatest blots in deter- ministic morality : its confining attention to exterior acts. Certain sentries, e.g., are ordered to stay at their posts for so many hours. It may be predicted with almost infallible certainty that they will do so, because they know they will otherwise be shot ; and because, on the other hand, there is no motive of virtue or self-interest which can come into play in an opposite direction. Still, the interior act, com- manding this exterior one, varies indefinitely with dinVrent persons ; and there is no pretext whatever for saying that you can rely beforehand on this being this or that. A, .<]., is VOL. i. r 274- TJte Philosophy of actuated throughout by the simple motive of obedience to God's command ; B, in addition to this, offers up his wearisome duty as a penance for his sins ; C is animated by zeal for his country's cause ; D is influenced by strong convictions on the nobleness of military obedience ; E is kept where he is, by no other motive than his dislike of being put to death. And a similar remark may be made on numberless other instances, where men agree with each other as a matter of course in doing the external act, but differ indefinitely as to the spirit in which they do it. It is really difficult to determine how often (according to what we account sound moral doctrine) the good man's probation consists not in the external act which he has to do but in the motives for which he does it. We may safely say that during far the largest portion of his life, his growth in virtue mainly depends, either (1) on his choice of good motives for his every-day acts ; or (2) on acts altogether interior, such as patience, self-examination, humility, forgivingness, equitableness of judgment, purity, under circumstances of trial. All this is entirely external to the sphere of a determinist's thoughts. VII. Mr. Mill alleges ("On Hamilton," p. 577) that determinism is shown to be probable " by each person's observation of the voluntary actions of those with whom he comes into contact ; and by the power which every one has of foreseeing actions with a degree of exactness proportioned to his previous experience and knowledge of the agents, and with a certainty often quite equal to that with which he predicts the commonest physical events." We deny this alleged fact entirely so far as it bears on the issue between Mr. Mill and ourselves ; but we would beg our readers, in the first place, to remember what is that issue. We (1) heartily admit that in every single case every man's spontaneous impulse of will may be predicted by me (to repeat Mr. Mill's words) "with a degree of exactness Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 275 proportioned to my previous experience and knowledge of the agent ; and with a certainty often quite equal to that with which I predict the commonest physical events." We further hold (2) that no person takes the trouble of resisting this impulse with any considerable energy, except only devout Theists ; and we hold (3) that an exterior act may be predicted in the abstract with almost infallible certainty? in all those many cases in which there is no motive of duty or self-interest which can act in an opposite direction to the will's spontaneous impulse.* We are confident that no power of foreseeing men's conduct can be alleged as known by experience, which presents even the superficial appearance of implying any greater certainty and uniformity of human action than might have been fully anticipated from our own doctrine. "When we speak of Aristides as just," says Dr. Bain (p. 539), "of Socrates as a moral hero, of Nero as a monster of cruelty, and of the Czar Nicholas as grasping of territory, we take for granted a certain persistence and regularity as to the operation of certain motives, much the same as when we affirm the attributes of material bodies." We assent to this in its full extent ; substituting only, of course, for the word " motives," the word "attractions." Dr. Bain, on his side, proceeds to admit that "the number and complication of motive forces may elude our knowledge, and render prediction uncertain and precarious." But let our readers observe this. No- where has Dr. Bain, nor Mr. Mill, nor (so far as we know) any other determinist whatever, attempted to show that this " uncertainty and precariousness of prediction " is due exclusively to "the number and complication of" attrac- * By the phrase " predicted in the abstract," we mean that it could bo predicted by a, person of superhuman and adequate intelligence, who should thoroughly penetrate the antecedent facts. We say with " (iltnimt" not "quite" "infallible certainty;" because it may be true indeed that tlio exterior aet prompted by my will's spontaneous impulse is not o;jyssihlo that I shall ehso another in preference, as still better and mr>- acceptable to God. 27G The Philosophy of Theism. tions ; that it is not largely due to the freedom of men's will. Yet until they have shown this, they have shown nothing worth so much as a pin's head towards the estab- lishment of their theory. On the other hand, Mr. Mill refers very reasonably to " each person's observation of the voluntary actions of those with whom he comes into contact." Now, we are confident that the careful examination of such a case will be favourable to our doctrine rather than to his. We do not mean that any experiment can be made on another which is absolutely crucial and decisive ; * but we do say that such an experiment will be to Mr. Mill a cause of weakness rather than of strength. Suppose such an instance as this. A widowed mother, most virtuous and wise, devotes herself exclusively to the education of her only son. She sees some critical probation of him ap- proaching ; some abnormal circumstances, from under which he will assuredly 'emerge, either much better or much worse than he was before. Studying carefully (as she has so long done) his temperament, tendencies, habits, she is able to calculate with a real approach to certainty what will be the impulse of his will under these circum- stances ; though, of course, she does not intermit doing all in her power to correct and elevate that impulse. But as to how he will comport himself under the approaching crisis on this she is profoundly anxious. The impulse itself, she well knows, will be more or less in an evil direction : will he nobly resist ? or will he, reluctantly, indeed, but effectively, succumb ? She awaits with breath- less solicitude the resolution of this doubt. We maintain that such a description as this is more conformable to observed facts than is Mr. Mill's allegation ; viz. that she * We say "on another" because we have maintained that every man may make on himself an experiment which shall be absolutely decisive of the fact that he can resist his will's impulse. Mr. Mill's Denial of Free-will. 277 might be able (except for the imperfection of her knowledge and discernment) to predict beforehand her son's movement of will, just as she might predict the movement of a physical point solicited by divergent attractions. We do not, however, deny that, in proportion as men have passed through the earlier part of their probation and established firm habits of virtue, in that proportion their resistance to predominant temptation (but only within certain limits) may be predicted with much confidence. But even if the power of prediction in such cases were indefinitely greater than it is, it would in no way tend to make probable Mr. Mill's theory. For consider. The whole of Mr. Mill's position rests on the allegation that men infallibly follow the most powerful attraction of those which at the moment solicit them ; insomuch that the balance of pleasurableness (positive or negative) may be known with infallible certainty, by observing what that direction is in which the will spontaneously moves. But when any one is said to resist predominant temptation, we mean, by the very force of the term, that he acts in opposition to his spontaneous impulse ; that is (according to Mr. Mill's theory itself) in opposition to the balance of pleasure. Suppose, then, we could even predict with infallible cer- tainty that in this or that given case this or that holy man would resist predominant temptation, what could be reasonably inferred from such a circumstance ? This could reasonably be inferred from it that the said holy man will act with infallible certainty in a way directly opposite to that which determinists regard as his inevitable course. On our side, we easily explain this power of probable prediction, so far as it exists : we explain it partly on psychological, partly on theological grounds. Psycho- logically a confirmed habit of resistance to predominant temptation generates a vast increase of facility and promptitude in such resistance. Theologically he who 27s The Philosophy of Theism. faithfully corresponds with grace in the earlier part of his probation, is (by way of reward) visited with larger and more persuasive supplies thereof in his later years. But all this is, of course, external to the deterministic con- troversy. VIII. Mr. Mill argues " ad homines " from God's prescience. " The religious metaphysicians," he says ("Logic," vol. ii. p. 422), "who have asserted the freedom of the will, have always maintained it to be consistent with God's foreknowledge of our actions; and if with divine, then with any other foreknowledge." But we deny entirely that God calculates future acts of the will through their fixed connection with phenomenal antecedents, because we deny that there is any such fixed connection. According to the " religious metaphysicians " in whom w r e repose confidence, God's knowledge of future human acts supposes, as its very foundation, the will's free exercise in this or that direction. It is strictly and fully, we maintain, within my own power, that God shall have eternally foreseen me as acting in this way or in that. Or rather God does not foresee anything at all, because He is external to time.* " Nothing to Him is present, nothing past, But an Eternal Now doth ever last." IX. Determinists often imply this syllogism. " If determinism were untrue, there would be no such thing as psychological, social, historical science ; but by the con- fession of all men there is such science, therefore deter- minism is true." We replied to this argument directly and expressly in our Essay on Science, Prayer, Freewill, and Miracles, f and must refer our readers to what we * " Dei proDscientia, ex doctrin& Patrum, res libere futures supponit." " In hypothesi quod res futuraj sint, Deus eas viilere debet : coiisequenter nempe ad liberam detcrminationem. . . . Cum verum sit hominem se deter- minaturum ad talem vel talem actionem, hoc ipso diviuae notitite subest " (" Perrone de Deo," nn. 393, 400). t This essay is republished in the second volume of this collection. ED. Mr. Mill's Denial of Freewill. 279 there said. Here we will only explain that we admit the existence of psychological, social, and historical science, but deny that the existence of such science is incompatible with freewill. X. Determinists sometimes seem to imply an a priori argument in favour of their theory. " Since physical phenomena proceed on uniform laws " so they seem to reason " how incredible that psychical phenomena should proceed otherwise ! " Before entering, however, on the field of thought thus opened, we will make a very brief digression. " Naturam expellas furca : tamen usque re- curret." Antitheists, having no belief in the God who created all things, very often erect the uniformity of nature into a kind of deity. Theists would protest with horror against the very notion of change in God as being a horrible irreverence. Quite similarly, a very large proportion of antitheists reject, not with philosophical serenity, but with passionate outcry, the very notion of external interference with the course of phenomena, whether such interference be alleged as proceeding by way of freewill, or of miracles, or of God's constant action on phenomena in answer to prayer. We now proceed to the particular objection which we are here to consider. As a preliminary, however, we beg to ask determinists who nowadays are also always pheno- inenists how they came to be so certain that physical phenomena do proceed on uniform laws. In our last essay we challenged phenomenists to prove, if they could, the uniformity of nature, by mere appeals to experience ; and we answered one by one the arguments by which Mr. Mill professed so to prove it. However, we ourselves, of course, entirely admit the uniformity of physical phenomena, though wo contend that no proof of this truth can be derived from mere experience. \Vu usk, then, where is the