LIBRARY 
 
 THE UNIVERSITY 
 OF CALIFORNIA 
 
 SANTA BARBARA 
 
 PRESENTED BY 
 
 ALMA WILLIAMS 
 UCSB
 
 
 ^
 
 STUDIES IN THE THEORY 
 OF HUMAN SOCIETY
 
 THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 
 NEW YORK BOSTON CHICAGO DALLAS 
 ATLANTA SAN FRANCISCO 
 
 MACMILLAN & CO.. LIMITED 
 
 LONDON BOMBAY CALCUTTA 
 MELBOURNE 
 
 THE MACMILLAN CO. OP CANADA. LTD. 
 
 TORONTO
 
 Studies in the Theory 
 of Human Society 
 
 BY 
 FRANKLIN H. GIDDINGS, LL.D. 
 
 PROFESSOR OF SOCIOLOGY AND THE HISTORY OF 
 
 CIVILIZATION IN COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY. 
 MEMBER OF THE NATIONAL INSTITUTE OF ARTS 
 
 AND LETTERS. 
 
 FELLOW OF THE AMERICAN STATISTICAL ASSO- 
 CIATION. 
 
 THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 
 1922 
 
 All rights reserved
 
 PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 
 
 COPYRIGHT, 1922, 
 BY THE MACMILLAN COMPANY. 
 
 Set up and electrotyped. Published February. 1922. 
 
 Press of 
 
 J. J. Little & Ives Company 
 New York, U. S. A.
 
 SAiSTA BAiiiiAKA 
 
 PREFACE 
 
 These consecutive studies are a book of Sociology without the 
 form or the formality of a text. The discursive manner has 
 permitted me to reiterate cardinal ideas and principles, exhibiting 
 them in many lights and relations. I have thought this important 
 in these days of loose thinking on social themes. 
 
 The theory of human society into which these ideas are or- 
 ganized is stated in Chapter XVI, as follows : 
 
 "If I can be said to have a system of sociology it is briefly this: 
 
 "i. A situation or stimulus is reacted to by more than one 
 individual; there is pluralistic as well as singularistic behavior. 
 Pluralistic behavior develops into rivalries, competitions, and con- 
 flicts, and also, into agreements, contracts, and collective enter- 
 prises. Therefore, social phenomena are products of two vari- 
 ables, namely, situation (in the psychologist's definition of the 
 word) and pluralistic behavior. 
 
 "2. When the individuals who participate in pluralistic be- 
 havior have become differentiated into behavioristic kinds or 
 types, a consciousness of kind, liking or disliking, approving or 
 disapproving one kind after another, converts gregariousness 
 into a consciously discriminative association, herd habit into so- 
 ciety; and society, by a social pressure which sometimes is con- 
 scious but more often, perhaps, is unconscious, makes life rela- 
 tively hard for kinds of character and conduct that are disap- 
 proved. 
 
 "3. Society organizes itself for collective endeavor and achieve- 
 ment if fundamental similarities of behavior and an awareness 
 of them are extensive enough to maintain social cohesion, while 
 differences of behavior and awareness of them in matters of de- 
 tail are sufficient to create a division of labor. 
 
 "4. In the long run organized society by its approvals and dis- 
 approvals, its pressures and achievements, selects and perpetuates
 
 vi PREFACE 
 
 the types of mind and character that are relatively intelligent, 
 tolerant, and helpful, that exhibit initiative, that bear their share 
 of responsibility, and that effectively play their part in collective 
 enterprise. It selects and perpetuates the adequate." 
 
 I have endeavored to bring discussion and exposition to date. 
 The nearly completed first quarter of the Twentieth Century has 
 not been marked by discoveries comparable to those that lifted 
 the second half of the Nineteenth Century above all other years 
 in the history of knowledge; but it has been a time of rectifica- 
 tion in science. Logic has abandoned absolutes for variables, 
 and pigeon hole classifications for frequency distributions. 
 Physics and chemistry have begun to build from electrons. Bi- 
 ology has become experimental and Mendelian. Psychology has 
 become experimental and objective. It has discriminated between 
 reflex and conditioning; between original nature and habit. 
 Anthropology has discovered elements of religion older than 
 ghosts, and found more variates of primitive social organization 
 than Morgan and McLennan knew. These corrections of fun- 
 damental notions and of inductions that are data of sociology 
 have made the revision of sociology obligatory. I offer here an 
 individual contribution to that formidable undertaking. A large 
 part of the content of the volume is entirely new. Materials that 
 in a cruder form have been printed in various journals and pro- 
 ceedings, and a small portion taken over from Democracy and 
 Empire now out of print, have been worked over to the extent 
 of being nearly rewritten. 
 
 The chapter on "Order and Possibility" is not strictly a part, 
 but it sets forth prolegomena (as I conceive them) of a scientific 
 theory of human society. Many students of both psychology and 
 sociology continue to worry over "determinism," and in par- 
 ticular over "mechanistic" theories of life. Just what happens 
 to their apprehensions when the discriminations of a statistical 
 way of thinking are applied to them has not, I believe, before 
 been pointed out. 
 
 I am grateful to friends and colleagues for helpful criticisms 
 and suggestions; and especially grateful to student members of 
 my research group for untiring aid in "checking up" and "trying 
 out."
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 I 
 
 HISTORICAL 
 
 CHAPTER PAGE 
 
 I. THE STRUGGLE FOR HUMAN EXISTENCE .... 3 
 
 II. THE SIGNIFICANCE OF CULTURE J 9 
 
 III. THE ECONOMIC AGES 33 
 
 IV. THE QUALITY OF CIVILIZATION 57 
 
 V. A THEORY OF HISTORY 66 
 
 VI. THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 94 
 
 II 
 ANALYTICAL 
 
 VII. ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 127 
 
 VIII. A THEORY OF SOCIAL CAUSATION 144 
 
 IX. THE MIND OF THE MANY 154 
 
 X. THE GROUP-MAKING ROLE OF IDEAS AND BELIEFS 175 
 
 XI. FOLKWAYS AND STATEWAYS 190 
 
 XII. SOCIAL SELF CONTROL 197 
 
 XIII. SOCIAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 209 
 
 XIV. THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 224 
 
 III 
 SYNTHETIC 
 
 XV. PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 249 
 
 XVI. FURTHER INQUIRIES OF SOCIOLOGY ..... 291 
 
 INDEX 303
 
 PART I 
 HISTORICAL
 
 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF 
 HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 
 THE STRUGGLE FOR HUMAN EXISTENCE 
 
 REVOLUTIONIZING as the life work of Charles Darwin was in 
 the fields of biology and psychology, one may doubt if his writings 
 disturbed the intellectual peace anywhere more profoundly than 
 in the already perturbed realms of pre-Darwinian social philos- 
 ophy. Borrowing a shocking thought from the Rev. Thomas 
 Robert Malthus, Mr. Darwin, in due course of time, gave it back 
 to Malthusians and Godwinites, to Ricardians and Ruskinites, to 
 Benthamites and Owenites, with a new and terrific voltage. 
 
 Nine years before The Origin of Species was published, 
 Herbert Spencer, in the concluding chapters of Social Statics, 
 had offered an explanation of society in terms of a progressive 
 human nature, adapting itself to changing conditions of life. 
 These chapters are the germ of that inclusive conception and 
 theory of evolution which were elaborated in the ten volumes of 
 the Synthetic Philosophy. Five years later, or four years be- 
 fore The Origin of Species saw the light, Mr. Spencer, in the 
 first edition of his Principles of Psychology, set forth an original 
 interpretation of life, including mental and social life, as a cor- 
 respondence of internal relations to external relations, initiated 
 and directed by the external relations. Finally, in April, 1857, 
 Mr. Spencer published, in The Westminster Review, the provo- 
 cative paper on "Progress : Its Law and Cause," in which a law 
 of evolution was partially formulated, and evolution was declared 
 to be the process of the universe and of all that it contains. 
 
 3
 
 4 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 Mr. Spencer thus had seen evolution comprehensively, as adap- 
 tation and differentiation. He had not yet mentally grasped the 
 universal redistribution of energy and matter, wherein every finite 
 aggregate of material units, radiating energy into surrounding 
 space, or absorbing energy therefrom, draws itself together in 
 order-making coherence, or distributes itself abroad in riotous 
 disintegration. That universal equilibration, which in fact is the 
 beginning and the end of material transformation, was the aspect 
 of the world which in thought Mr. Spencer arrived at last of all. 
 
 It is not given to any one human intellect to discover all truth, 
 and there is more in evolution than even Mr. Spencer perceived, 
 either at the beginning of his great work, or in the fulness of his 
 powers. 1 Intent upon the broader aspects of cosmic change, his 
 mind did not seize upon certain implications of rearrangement. 
 In the concrete world of living organisms, equilibration becomes 
 the relentless struggle for existence, in which the weakest go to 
 the wall. Natural selection follows. It was this intensely con- 
 crete aspect that Mr. Darwin saw, and intellectually mastered. 
 
 The distinction here indicated between evolution as a universal 
 process, comprehensively described by Spencer, and Darwinism, 
 or Mr. Darwin's account of one vitally important and concrete 
 phase of that process, has often been noted, and is usually ob- 
 served by careful writers. It is of particular importance in any 
 discussion of social evolution. One cannot hope to get far in a 
 theoretical study of human society if he does not heed the extent 
 to which our explanations of social origins, our philosophies of 
 history and of human institutions, have become not only evolution- 
 ist, in the Spencerian sense of the word, but also Darwinian. 
 
 It was not until the publication of The Descent of Man, in 
 1871, when controversy over The Origin of Species had raged 
 through twelve years of intellectual tempest, that the full signifi- 
 cance of natural selection for the doctrine of human progress was 
 apprehended by the scientific world. Mr. Spencer saw it when 
 
 1 And he did not finally reduce his general formula to its lowest terms. 
 As "universal," evolution is but a progressive emergence of order out of 
 turbulence, and therefore a progressive complication of relationships. All 
 other aspects of evolution are particularistic, for example, they are astro- 
 nomical or biological, or psychological or political, and no two of them are 
 of quite identical pattern.
 
 THE STRUGGLE FOR HUMAN EXISTENCE 5 
 
 The Origin of Species appeared. Mr. Darwin himself had per- 
 ceived that he must offer a credible explanation of the paradox 
 that a ruthless struggle for existence yields the peaceable fruits 
 of righteousness. But it was neither Mr. Spencer, nor Mr. Dar- 
 win, who first recognized the specific phase of the life struggle in 
 which the clue to the mystery might be sought. The gifted thinker 
 who made that discovery was Walter Bagehot, editor of the Lon- 
 don Economist, whose little book on Physics and Politics or 
 Thoughts on the Application of the Principles of Natural Selec- 
 tion and Inheritance to Political Society, was published first as a 
 series of articles in The Fortnightly Review, beginning in Novem- 
 ber, 1867. Mr. Darwin rightly calls these articles "remarkable." 
 Revised and put together in book form they made a volume of 
 only two hundred and twenty-three small pages in large type, but 
 no more original, brilliant or, as far as it goes, satisfactory exami- 
 nation of the deeper problems of social causation has ever been 
 offered from that day until now. It anticipated much that is most 
 valuable in later exposition. 
 
 In the Social Statics, Mr. Spencer had shown that primitive 
 man, subsisting upon inferior species and contending with them 
 for standing room and safety, necessarily developed a human 
 nature adapted to the task of slaughter, cruel, therefore, and un- 
 scrupulous ; but that triumphant posterity, inheriting a subjugated 
 world, and no longer bound to kill, might become sympathetic 
 enough to cooperate successfully in peaceful activities. The exact 
 relation, however, of this process to group formation or to the 
 collective activity of a cooperating group when formed, Mr. 
 Spencer at this time certainly did not see. For, incredible though 
 it may seem, Mr. Spencer did not at this time so much as make 
 note of the terrific struggles for control of food-getting oppor- 
 tunities that occur among individuals or between groups of the 
 same species, or variety. Conflict among men of the same cul- 
 tural attainments Mr. Spencer thought of only as prompted by 
 surviving savage instincts, engendered by predatory habits, in the 
 lawless youth of the race. 
 
 It was specifically the phenomena of group solidarity and of col- 
 lective conflict, in distinction from a merely individual struggle 
 for existence, which Mr. Bagehot selected for examination, and
 
 6 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 his mind penetrated directly to the essential conditions of the 
 problem. He said: 
 
 "The progress of man requires the cooperation of men for its develop- 
 ment. . . . The first principle of the subject is that man can only make 
 progress in 'cooperative groups'; I might say tribes and nations, but I 
 use the less common word because few people would at once see that 
 tribes and nations are cooperative groups, and that it is their being so 
 which makes their value; that unless you can make a strong cooperative 
 bond, your society will be conquered and killed out by some other society 
 which has such a bond; and the second principle is that the members of 
 such a group should be similar enough to one another to cooperate easily 
 and readily together. The cooperation in all such cases depends on a 
 felt union of heart and spirit; and this is only felt when there is a great 
 degree of real likeness in mind and feeling, however that likeness may 
 have been attained." l 
 
 Addressing himself to the question how the necessary likeness 
 in mind and feeling is produced, Mr. Bagehot answers: By one 
 of the most terrible tyrannies ever known among men, namely, 
 the authority of customary law ; and in accounting for the origin 
 and force of custom, he develops a theory of the function of imi- 
 tation which anticipates much, but by no means all, of the socio- 
 logical theory of Gabriel Tarde. Custom, however, tends to create 
 a degree of similarity among social units, and an unchanging way 
 of life, fatal to further progress. To reintroduce and to maintain 
 certain possibilities and tendencies toward variation is, as Bagehot 
 sees the process, one of the chief uses of conflict. Social evolu- 
 tion thus proceeds through the conflict of antagonistic tendencies, 
 on the one hand toward uniformity and solidarity; on the other 
 hand toward variation and individuality. In some groups, one of 
 these tendencies predominates. Contending together, group with 
 group, in the struggle for existence, those groups survive in which 
 the balancing of these tendencies secures the greatest group effi- 
 ciency. It is not too much to say that in this interpretation, Mr. 
 Bagehot arrived at conclusions which to-day we recognize as be- 
 longing to the theoretical core of a scientific sociology. 
 
 Mr. Darwin, in those chapters of The Descent of Man in 
 which he treats of the origin of social habits and the moral facul- 
 ties, adopts in substance the conclusions of Mr. Bagehot, and with 
 
 1 Physics and Politics, pp. 212, 213.
 
 THE STRUGGLE FOR HUMAN EXISTENCE 7 
 
 his keen sense for what is essential, lays emphasis upon four 
 facts, namely : ( I ) the importance of group or tribal cohesion as a 
 factor of success in intertribal struggle, (2) the importance of 
 sympathy as a factor in group cohesion, (3) the importance of 
 mutual fidelity and unselfish courage, and (4) the great part 
 played by sensitiveness to praise and blame in developing both 
 unselfish courage and fidelity. In terms of these four facts, Mr. 
 Darwin finds an answer to the question, how, within the condi- 
 tions fixed by a struggle for existence, social and moral qualities 
 could tend slowly to advance and to be diffused throughout the 
 world. 
 
 That the studies of both Mr. Bagehot and Mr. Darwin left 
 much still to be said on the subject of group feeling and coopera- 
 tive solidarity was shown when, in 1890, Prince Peter Alekseevich 
 Kropotkin published in The Nineteenth Century his fascinating 
 articles on Mutual Aid among Animals, afterwards supple- 
 mented by studies of mutual aid among savages and among bar- 
 barians. These articles contained nothing essentially new in 
 theory, but they contributed to our knowledge an imposing mass 
 of facts demonstrating how great has been the part played by 
 sympathy and helpfulness in the struggle for existence, and how 
 inadequate would be any interpretation of natural selection which 
 accounted for it wholly in terms of superior strength, cruelty and 
 cunning. 
 
 Mr. Darwin never claimed to offer an adequate explanation of 
 the variations which natural selection preserves or rejects. He 
 sometimes took them for granted, he sometimes spoke of them as 
 accidental or fortuitous. 1 He would have been the last to pretend 
 
 *It was left for the post-Darwinians, and in particular DeVries, to 
 demonstrate the distinction between "mutations" (variations large or 
 small that are inherited) and "fluctuations" (variations large or small that 
 are not inherited) and to apprehend its significance. The fact of mu- 
 tation (often large and conspicuous) ; the law of heredity discovered 
 by Mendel; the continuity of germ plasm discontinuous with somatic 
 cells and the fact that traits acquired by an individual after birth do not 
 descend in heredity, established by Weismann; have displaced both the 
 hypothesis of pangenesis and Darwin's view of the transformation of 
 species by cumulative variation ; but they have not touched essential 
 Darwinism, namely, recognition of the fact and the function of selective 
 death-rates among mutants. There is no evidence that Malthus saw, or 
 if he saw attached importance to the fact, that death-rates are selective.
 
 8 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 that he had told us all that we should like to know about the be- 
 ginnings of herd habit, of sympathy or of sensitiveness to praise 
 or blame. But, starting from herd habit, sympathy and the desire 
 for approval as traits that may actually be observed, and that 
 presumably have somehow had a natural origin, Darwin and 
 Kropotkin convincingly demonstrate that groups possessing these 
 qualities have a certain advantage in the struggle for life. 
 
 To account more fully for the origins, in distinction from the 
 natural selection of the social qualities, was the problem that John 
 Fiske attacked in his theory of the effects of prolonged infancy, 
 first published in the North American Review of October, I873, 1 
 and a year later in the Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy. Fiske 
 discriminates between "gregariousness" and "sociality," without, 
 however, sufficiently analyzing the one or the other, or quite de- 
 fining the difference. 2 By sociality he seems to mean a relatively 
 high development of sympathy, affection and loyalty to kindred 
 or comrades. He argues that sociality has its origin in small and 
 permanent family groups. These are not necessarily monogamous 
 at first. They may be polygamous or polyandrian, and may 
 broaden out into clans. But they must be more enduring than 
 matings observed in the merely gregarious herd. The cause of 
 both definiteness and permanence he finds in the prolongation of 
 infancy, necessitating a relatively long-continued parental care 
 of offspring. The relations so established among near kindred 
 have conserved and strengthened the feelings of affection and the 
 sense of solidarity. Mr. Darwin recognized Mr. Fiske's theory 
 as an important contribution to the subject. It must be said in 
 criticism, however, that Mr. Fiske did not see all the implications 
 of prolonged infancy, or develop his theory into all its possibilities. 
 Admitting that the prolongation of infancy was probably a factor 
 in the evolution of stable family relationships, and therefore 
 played a part in strengthening the social sentiments, we must re- 
 member that the collective life and solidarity of the gregarious 
 group was probably a chief cause of the prolongation of infancy 
 itself. Demanding, as it did, relatively complex habits and ad- 
 
 1 Under the title: The Progress from Brute to Man. 
 'Nevertheless, the discrimination is one of the most significant that 
 had so far been made in sociology.
 
 THE STRUGGLE FOR HUMAN EXISTENCE 9 
 
 justments, it operated to select for survival those individuals that 
 varied in the direction of high brain power and its correlated long 
 infancy. But this is to say that the collective struggle for exis- 
 tence was a factor in the evolution of man before man became a 
 factor in the evolution of society, and the fact is important. 
 
 Moreover, Mr. Fiske's theory no more explained the actual 
 origins of sympathy and cooperation than Bagehot's and Dar- 
 win's theories had done. Neither, for that matter, did Suther- 
 land's account of The Origin and Growth of the Moral In- 
 stinct? although Sutherland got somewhat further back when he 
 called attention to the reaction of parental care of offspring upon 
 the evolution of ganglia making up the sympathetic nervous 
 system. 
 
 At this stage the Darwinian interpretation of social origins had 
 arrived when, in 1894, there was published a work which had an 
 almost sensational reception. Hailed as a new gospel by minds 
 desiring above all things to find some solid ground for religious 
 convictions that had seemingly suffered violence in the course of 
 evolutionist warfare, this book was treated by scientific critics 
 with scant respect. The critics, I venture to think, were in error. 
 For, in fact, the Social Evolution of Benjamin Kidd raised a 
 profoundly important question, and gave an answer to it which, 
 while half wrong, was probably half right, and the half that was 
 right was a real and important contribution to knowledge. Stated 
 in the fewest possible words, Mr. Kidd's query was this : 
 
 Since natural selection saves the few and kills the many, why 
 does not the great majority of mankind try to curb competition 
 and put an end to progress ? Thus presented, Mr. Kidd's question 
 is the radical and fearless form of a question which socialism asks 
 in a form that, by comparison, is conservative and half-hearted. 
 And Mr. Kidd's answer, not so much as tainted with socialism, 
 is as fearless as his question. Progress has no rational sanction. 
 It is irrational and, from the standpoint of reason, absurd. Man 
 goes on multiplying, competing, fighting and making progress be- 
 cause he is not rational and has no desire to be. He lives not by 
 
 1 Published in 1898, a worthy product of Australian scholarship, which 
 its author described as largely a detailed expansion of the fourth and 
 fifth chapters of The Descent of Man.
 
 io STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 reason, but by faith. He crucifies and kills himself to improve 
 the race, not because he is scientific, but because he is religious. 
 
 Perhaps it was because Mr. Kidd's thesis was paradoxical, that 
 theologians found something tangible in it while scientific men 
 did not. It should be possible now to look back upon it without 
 prejudice. On the face of it, it is an obvious fallacy, but back of 
 fallacy lies a truth. 
 
 The fallacy consists in an unwarranted assumption that indi- 
 viduals and families marked for extermination in the struggle for 
 existence are, in their own lifetime, aware of their impending 
 doom. Let us suppose that, of one hundred families now flourish- 
 ing, ninety will become extinct in the tenth generation, their 
 places being filled by a corresponding number of new families 
 branching from the one successful line. This would be natural 
 selection at a rapid rate. Yet to maintain this rate, only ten fam- 
 ilies have to drop out in any one generation, and ten new ones 
 to appear. This means that, at any given time, a ninety per cent, 
 majority of all persons at the moment living have an expectation 
 of further life, the termination of which cannot be foreseen. The 
 large majority, therefore, at any given time existing think of 
 themselves not as the unfit that must perish, but rather as the 
 fit selected to survive. 
 
 This way of stating the problem, however, brings us face to 
 face with a peculiarly interesting truth, for the apprehension of 
 which we rightly may give generous credit to Mr. Kidd. Ob- 
 viously, while no family stock or race at any time existing can 
 certainly know, or, while it remains still vigorous, find sufficient 
 ground to believe that it is doomed to perish, neither can it cer- 
 tainly know that it is indefinitely to survive. It struggles instinc- 
 tively and it achieves not altogether by knowledge or by reason, 
 but also in part by faith. It impulsively goes forward and it 
 hopes, it expects to endure. It believes in its future. 
 
 Therefore the ongoing drive by which a race, a family, or an 
 individual lives, is not anti-rational, nor yet super- rational. It is 
 rather sub-rational or proto-rational. It is deeper and more ele- 
 mental than reason. It is the will to "carry on" sustained by 
 faith in the possibilities of life. The question, therefore, which 
 Mr. Kidd should have asked, and which we, reviewing his work,
 
 THE STRUGGLE FOR HUMAN EXISTENCE n 
 
 must ask in his stead, is this : May we identify our ongoing will 
 with what men in all lands and times have called "the soul," and 
 merge our elemental faith in the possibilities of life in the tre- 
 mendous social phenomenon of religion, which, in all the ages of 
 man's progress, has been one of his supreme interests ? Shall we 
 perhaps find that, when reduced to its lowest terms, to its essential 
 principle, religion is not, as has been supposed, so much a belief 
 in gods, or in a supernatural, in any way conceived, as an endeavor 
 to sustain and "save" the soul (i. e. to fortify the ongoing will) 
 and to nourish that primordial faith in the possibilities of life 
 which was born, and generation after generation is re-born, of 
 success in the struggle for existence; which may gather about 
 itself all manner of supplementary beliefs, including a belief in 
 spirits and in gods, but which will persist after science has 
 stripped away from it all its mystical and theological accretions ? 
 If we may and should, we can accept as a positive contribution to 
 the theory of human behavior Mr. Kidd's proposition that relig- 
 ion, a thing deeper and more elemental than reason, has been a 
 chief factor in social evolution. 
 
 The mention of socialism, when referring to the theories of 
 Benjamin Kidd, may serve to remind us of two further contribu- 
 tions to the Darwinian theory of society still to be mentioned. 
 William Hurrell Mallock's American lectures on socialism, 1 did 
 not enhance his reputation as a competent student of social phe- 
 nomena. Before passing judgment, however, one should examine 
 Mr. Mallock's Aristocracy and Evolution, a suggestive and 
 really important work, published in 1898. In this book Mr. Mai- 
 lock rises above his habit of literary trifling, and digs somewhat 
 below his prejudices, to examine not only fairly, but also cogently, 
 and with illumination, the phenomenon of personal ability as a 
 factor of social achievement. Distinguishing between a struggle 
 for existence merely, and a struggle for domination, he contends 
 that progress in any legitimate sense of the word is attributable 
 to the struggle for domination. No one, I think, can go far in 
 sociological study without seeing that this is a significant distinc- 
 tion for purposes of historical interpretation. 
 
 'Delivered in 1906; published 1907 as A Critical Examination of 
 Socialism,
 
 12 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 One need not, however, draw the conclusion that democracy is 
 necessarily antagonistic to progress, as Mr. Mallock does. He 
 says: 
 
 The human race progresses because and when the strongest human 
 powers and the highest human faculties lead it ; such powers and faculties 
 are embodied in and monopolized by a minority of exceptional men ; these 
 men enable the majority to progress, only on condition that the majority 
 submit themselves to their control. 1 
 
 No student of social evolution would be less likely to dispute 
 these propositions than Francis Galton would be if he were now 
 living. In his studies of natural inheritance and hereditary genius, 
 Galton did more than any investigator before him to establish 
 them on a broad inductive basis. Since Galton, no investigator 
 has made more valuable studies in this field than Karl Pearson, 
 and no one more unreservedly than he accepts the conclusion that 
 superiority is necessary to social advance and that personal superi- 
 ority is a fact of heredity. Yet Mr. Pearson contends that to add 
 artificial advantage to natural superiority is fatal, because su- 
 periority cannot be maintained unless the herd, as well as the 
 superior individual, is carefully looked after and improved. The 
 superiority that achieves leadership and domination is usually the 
 power to do some particular thing exceptionally well. It is ex- 
 treme individuation, and it often is purchased at the cost of race 
 vitality. It is as necessary to maintain the one as to develop the 
 other. Mr. Pearson therefore finds the socialistic program not 
 incompatible with continuing progress by selection and inheri- 
 tance. 2 
 
 "To 'wage war against natural inequality' is clearly a reductio ad 
 absurdum of the socialistic doctrine. So far as I understand the views 
 of the more active socialists of to-day, they fully recognize that the 
 better posts, the more lucrative and comfortable berths, must always go 
 to the more efficient and more productive workers, and that it is for 
 the welfare of society that it should be so. Socialists, however, propose 
 to limit within healthy bounds the rewards of natural superiority and 
 the advantages of artificial inequality. The victory of the more capable, 
 or the more fortunate, must not involve such a defeat of the less capable, 
 
 1 Aristocracy and Evolution, p. 379. 
 
 'The Chances of Death, Vol. I., pp. 112, 113. Rejecting socialism 
 myself and defending a creed of socialized individualism, I have thought 
 it worth while to quote the exact words in which Mr. Pearson summarized 
 his argument.
 
 THE STRUGGLE FOR HUMAN EXISTENCE 13 
 
 or the less fortunate, that social stability is endangered by the misery 
 produced. At the present time a failure of the harvest in Russia and 
 America simultaneously, or a war with a first-class European power, 
 would probably break up our social system altogether. We should be 
 crushed in the extra-group struggle for existence, because we have given 
 too much play to intra-group competition, because we have proceeded on 
 the assumption that it is better to have a few prize cattle among in- 
 numerable lean kine than a decently-bred and properly-fed herd with no 
 expectations at Smithfield." 
 
 From this too brief account of the applications thus far made 
 of Darwinian theory to the problems presented by social relation- 
 ships, including human institutions, we may turn to the question of 
 further scientific possibilities in this direction. It will have been 
 noted that the theories reviewed are not as they now stand entirely 
 consistent with one another, and that none of them carries ex- 
 planation back to the actual beginnings and causes of group for- 
 mation. Perhaps if we could more adequately account, in terms 
 of the struggle for existence, for actual social origins, and for 
 successive stages of social evolution, the various fragments of 
 theory which we now possess would fall into orderly correlation. 
 
 Possibly also the most promising starting point for any new 
 attempt to achieve these ends may be found in a careful scrutiny 
 of what is involved in the struggle for existence itself. Close 
 readers of The Origin of Species know that although Mr. Dar- 
 win, when employing the phrase "a struggle for existence," usu- 
 ally meant by it a struggle for subsistence, he uses it also to mean 
 a struggle with the physical conditions of life, to which an or- 
 ganism that would survive must be or must become adapted. 
 "Two canine animals in a time of dearth," he remarks, "may truly 
 be said to struggle with each other which shall get food and live. 
 But a plant on the edge of a desert is said to struggle for life 
 against the drought, though more properly it should be said to 
 be dependent on the moisture." * Also, "climate plays an impor- 
 tant part in determining the average numbers of a species, and 
 periodical seasons of extreme cold or drought seem to be the most 
 effective of all checks." 2 Yet further, "when we reach the Arctic 
 regions, or snow capped summits, or absolute deserts, the struggle 
 
 1 The Origin of Species, p. 78. 
 </., p. 84.
 
 14 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 for life is almost exclusively with the elements." * Again, Mr. 
 Darwin often means, not a struggle for food or against the ele- 
 ments, but a struggle to avoid being converted into food. "Very 
 frequently," he writes, "it is not the obtaining of food, but the 
 serving as prey to other animals, which determines the average 
 numbers of a species." 2 And some of his most fascinating pages 
 deal with the variations, such as protective markings, colorings 
 and habits, which are helpful in the mere struggle for safety. 
 Once more, in those paragraphs in The Descent of Man already 
 referred to, in which Mr. Darwin recognizes the utility of group 
 solidarity, he, by implication, takes account of a struggle on the 
 part of associating individuals to adjust their interests and their 
 activities to one another in such wise that group life may be 
 maintained. 
 
 If, then, it is legitimate to use the term, "struggle for existence," 
 "in a large and metaphorical sense," as Mr. Darwin says his prac- 
 tice is, 3 the struggle itself obviously consists of four distinct and 
 specific struggles, namely: (i) the struggle to react, to endure 
 heat and cold and storm, to draw the next breath, to crawl the 
 next yard, to hold out against fatigue and despair, to explore and 
 analyze the situation; (2) the struggle for subsistence wherewith 
 to repair the waste of reaction; (3) the struggle for adaptation 
 by every organism to the objective conditions of its life, and, (4) 
 the struggle for adjustment, by group-living individuals to one 
 another. 
 
 And this large use of the term is legitimate in fact. Mr. Dar- 
 win's only mistake was in calling it "metaphorical." For, as Karl 
 Pearson has pointed out, "the true measure of natural selection 
 is a selective death rate," 4 and any circumstance, whether it be 
 danger, or scarcity of food, or non-adaptation to physical condi- 
 tions, or mal-adjustment of associating individuals to one an- 
 other, which affects the selective death rate, is a factor in the 
 struggle for existence. 
 
 If so much be granted, a number of difficult questions get a real 
 
 1 The Origin of Species, p. 85. 
 'Ibid., p. 84. 
 'Ibid., p. 78. 
 
 * Essay on "Reproductive Selection" in The Chances of Death and 
 Other Studies in Evolution, Vol. I, p. 63.
 
 THE STRUGGLE FOR HUMAN EXISTENCE 15 
 
 illumination. What are the true relations of religious, aesthetic, 
 intellectual, economic, ethical and social phenomena to one an- 
 other, and to life in its wide inclusiveness ? What, especially, is 
 the precise point of departure of social evolution from all that 
 precedes it and prepares for it? And what is the precise dis- 
 crimination needful of things social from things merely organic 
 or psychological ? The modes and the phases of the struggle for 
 existence suggest intelligible answers. 
 
 The struggle to endure and, withstanding fatigue, to go on, to 
 keep up courage and to maintain faith, develops into religion. 
 It avails, however, only if sensitiveness to situation warns of 
 danger, and reaction to peril achieves safety. Sensitiveness to 
 electrical and chemical conditions, to temperature, pressure and 
 sound, to light and shade, to color and form (in all their objective 
 degrees and proportions, dissonances and harmonies) and alert 
 reaction to them, are the beginnings of aesthetic interest and dis- 
 crimination, which, therefore, it seems, are vital concerns; not 
 triflings with life, as stupid people assume. They are the un- 
 wearying guardians of immediate safety. For assurance of 
 safety or continuing security, yet other reactions are necessary. 
 There must be an exploration of each situation and an analysis 
 of it. This is an intellectual business, an affair of ideas and of 
 thought processes, for which only man is competent. His attempt 
 to develop it is his scientific life. 
 
 Religion, then, the aesthetic life and the scientific life, are initial 
 products of the struggle to react, to hold out and to go on. 
 
 The struggle for subsistence initiates and broadens into the 
 economic life. The struggle for adaptation becomes the ethical 
 life. For adaptation, in its beginnings a mere taking on or per- 
 fecting of useful characters, develops, in time, into self-control, 
 self-direction and self-shaping. 
 
 Between adaptation and adjustment, no distinction whatever 
 has been made by a majority of evolutionist writers. Spencer 
 uses the word "adjustment" to include all that biologists and 
 psychologists commonly mean by adaptation. Yet the two things 
 are not at all the same. The struggles which they involve are not 
 identical struggles, and, for the purposes of sociological theory, 
 the distinction is of fundamental importance.
 
 1 6 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 Adaptation which, as it goes on, widens into and includes the 
 ethical life, at first is a mere conforming of the organism through 
 variation, selection and inheritance, to the physical conditions 
 under which it happens to live ; that is to say, to altitude, tempera- 
 ture, light or darkness, dryness or moisture, enemies, food supply, 
 and so on. Through adaptation, and because non-adaptation 
 means extinction, the individuals of any given species congregated 
 and dwelling in any given region where adequate food supplies 
 are found become increasingly alike, and the first two conditions 
 of social life, as Mr. Bagehot rightly explained it, namely, group- 
 ing and substantial resemblance, are provided. But, since they are 
 alike, individuals of the same variety or race, so brought together 
 in one habitat, necessarily want the same things, and, as often as 
 not, try in like ways to get them, reacting in one manner to any 
 stimulus that incites all of them, or to a common situation. They 
 compete in obtaining things which each is able to get by his own 
 efforts, or (unconsciously or consciously) they combine their 
 efforts to obtain things that no one could get unaided. In either 
 case their interests and activities are not altogether harmonious 
 and easily become antagonistic. Competition tends to engender 
 conflicts inimical to group cohesion; but in aggregations of ani- 
 mals or of human beings, in which individuals generally are sub- 
 stantially similar in behavior and approximately equal in strength, 
 conflicts are self-limiting in a degree. An equilibrium of "live and 
 let live" is arrived at, which makes gregarious life possible for 
 animals and conscious association possible for human beings. In 
 human communities the let live habit of noninterference becomes 
 a conscious toleration, in which adaptation passes into adjust- 
 ment, a reciprocal adaptation. It is a precarious adjustment at 
 first, because rivalries continue and conflicts recur. When, how- 
 ever, these provoke collective (i. e. group) reactions in defense 
 of the let live status, the struggle then begun is a struggle to 
 maintain adjustment and to improve it. On its success group 
 cohesion depends, and on group cohesion social evolution depends. 
 
 Or, to put the matter now in slightly different words, while the 
 struggle to react with ongoing will and discriminating intelli- 
 gence becomes differentiated into religious, aesthetic and scientific 
 activities; and while the struggle for subsistence becomes the
 
 THE STRUGGLE FOR HUMAN EXISTENCE 17 
 
 economic life, and the struggle for adaptation broadens into the 
 ethical life, the struggle of resembling creatures to adjust them- 
 selves (together with their competitions and their adaptations) to 
 one another, is the beginning and the continuing process of group 
 cohesion, the precedent condition of human society and all that it 
 signifies. 
 
 Through success in all of these struggles, and not in one or an- 
 other of them only, there results a survival of the fit, namely, 
 organisms that are so equipped with proper parts and habits that 
 on the whole they fit into and conform to the essential conditions 
 of life incident to the environment in which they are forced or 
 elect to dwell. 
 
 Only a few of the countless billions of the fit are human, and 
 human beings are not in all cases the fit. There are regions and 
 circumstances in which man is unfit to live, and doesn't. 
 
 Human qualities have been winnowed and selected in a differ- 
 ential struggle, projected from and beyond the general struggle 
 for existence. They are products of a highly definite and intense 
 struggle for human existence. 
 
 This struggle has been not only a collective effort, as the life 
 struggle of all gregarious creatures is, but also a social struggle 
 another phenomenon altogether. 
 
 Pluralistically responding (i. e. in plural numbers reacting) to 
 common stimulation, communicating and associating, acting upon 
 one another by suggestion and example, and imitating one an- 
 other in a thousand ways, individuals generate similar feelings and 
 develop closely resembling ideas. Among them are feelings and 
 ideas of liking and disliking, of trust and distrust, of approval 
 and disapproval. These are social feelings and ideas, a human 
 equipment not found full grown, if indeed in rudimentary begin- 
 nings, in the animal mind. Also an awareness of similarities of 
 behavior and of character (and of conflicting dissimilarities) be- 
 comes a consciousness of kind, or type. Social feelings and ideas, 
 (emotions and thoughts) and the consciousness of kind fuse in a 
 conscious social sentiment, a state of the human mind, to which 
 gregarious instinct (if there is a gregarious instinct) is but a 
 small contribution. Social sentiment converts herd habits into 
 those common and usual but not invariable ways of doing things,
 
 i8 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 those norms and elements of human custom, which Professor 
 Sumner has named the folkways. 
 
 Folkways and mores constrain the individual and become that 
 "most terrible of all tyrannies known to man" of which Mr. 
 Bagehot wrote. But it is a tyranny, as Bagehot demonstrated, 
 that perfects the group in cohesion and in unity of purpose. Con- 
 scious, then, of the usefulness of solidarity, the group endeavors 
 by definite policies to limit variation from type. Society thereby 
 becomes a type-conforming group of associates, endeavoring, by 
 self -instituted discipline to maintain as a type its distinctive char- 
 acteristics. Chief of selected and perpetuated traits are the dif- 
 ferential human reactions; conscious toleration, conscious sym- 
 pathy, and an intellectualized understanding. 
 
 In the three next following chapters fundamental conditions 
 and elemental processes of the struggle for human existence are 
 examined in further detail. The historic process as a whole is 
 then viewed comprehensively, and afterwards an attempt is made 
 to discover and to connect the historical factors of social theory. 
 The chapters of the second part of the volume are analytical 
 studies of determinative factors and controlling processes in 
 human society. In the third part an attempt is made to exhibit 
 their genetic and functional synthesis.
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF CULTURE 
 
 IT would help to clear up those issues which have been brought 
 forward by the economic interpretation of history, if scholars 
 generally understood the true character of certain human interests 
 which we are in the habit of grouping under the word "culture." 
 To the historian who comprehends the part which religion and 
 language, manners and amusements, art and literature have played 
 in the drama of human progress, there is something almost per- 
 verse in the proposition that all which has happened in the world 
 can be explained in economic terms. . Not only does economic 
 explanation in history savor of materialism in that sense of the 
 word which is ethical rather than scientific, but it seems to be 
 wholly inadequate. 
 
 Yet the question raised, as all will admit, is perplexing. The 
 word "economy" has become one of the most elastic in the vo- 
 cabulary of science. It means the whole system of industry and 
 business whereby a modern population sustains existence. It 
 means the production and distribution of wealth. It also means 
 the total phenomena of wants and satisfactions. Whenever the 
 economist, turned historian, discovers that he cannot account for 
 a social development in terms of property or of industrial or- 
 ganization or of "the iron law," he falls back on the most abstract 
 meaning of his words, and has no difficulty in proving that since 
 all the forms of culture are satisfactions of wants, they are 
 economic phenomena. He might demonstrate also that they are 
 cosmic phenomena, and the one "interpretation" would be as 
 illuminating as the other. Admitting that cultural products are 
 both cosmic and economic, our common sense assures us that they 
 are distinguishable from undifferentiated comet tails, and that it 
 would be interesting to know wherein their economic nature 
 differs from that of stock yards and rolling mills. The crux of 
 
 19
 
 the whole question is right here. Are the facts of culture eco- 
 nomic in some precise sense, as the facts of industry are? Is 
 culture in general an economy, of a different order from the 
 economy called industry; and if so, which economy is radical, or 
 primordial? Is culture an offshoot of industry, or has industry 
 been evolved from culture ; or are there two economies, indepen- 
 dent and coordinate from the beginning? These questions can- 
 not be answered by scientific intuition. 
 
 On the one hand we know that in modern life churches and 
 theatres, clubs and "society" are maintained from the products 
 of iron and cotton mills, coal mines and oil wells, wheat fields and 
 lumber camps. On the other hand, we know that the Ingsevones 
 and Herminones, whom Tacitus described, had neither mills nor 
 mines, nor much cultivated grain, nor marts, and yet they had 
 religion and a splendid mythology, choral song, and social festi- 
 vals. Historically, culture had a vast development before industry 
 got beyond its rudest beginnings. Industry, however, supplies us 
 with material goods, food, clothing and shelter, which minister 
 to those bodily needs that are older than the cravings of the mind. 
 Moreover savages and barbarians have had practical as well as 
 ceremonial arts. As a rule (but not always) they have obtained 
 something to eat before devoting themselves to tom-toms and 
 prayer. Altogether, antecedent and consequent in our investiga- 
 tion seem to be mixed. 
 
 In the attempt to get them into a genetic order let us first care- 
 fully recognize facts that are beyond argument. It is by directing 
 human labor and by controlling the processes of nature that mod- 
 ern industry creates vast quantities of goods, including food sup- 
 plies in excess of what nature offers freely in unsolicited bounty. 
 In achieving this end modern industry is dependent upon man's 
 acquisitions of scientific knowledge and technical skill. Knowl- 
 edge and skill have had beginning and growth in man's ceaseless 
 interrogation of nature through unnumbered generations, and in 
 his attempt to imitate her ways. These questionings and imita- 
 tions lead back into a maze of religious ceremonies and beliefs, 
 back through the world of ghosts to an earlier world of mana, 
 then further back to those earliest forms of expression and of 
 mimicry, of which language and manners were born, and at last to
 
 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF CULTURE 21 
 
 those primordial reactions of which adventure, fortitude and faith 
 were born. Modern industry, then, presupposes among its ante- 
 cedents the whole cultural history of man considered as a mental 
 preparation for his present task. 
 
 This, however, is not all. Industry presupposes certain mo- 
 tives for productive effort, and these are more than pangs of 
 hunger and cold. They include not only the demand of the body 
 for nourishment and protection, but also the demand of body 
 and of mind for exhilarating activity ; for stimulation and exalta- 
 tion ; for the pleasures of sight and of sound, of imagination and 
 of sentiment, and for the deeper satisfactions of understanding. 
 In their turn all these satisfactions are concretely embodied in 
 cultural forms handed down to us from the past. On the side of 
 motive also, therefore, modern industry presupposes the long 
 historical evolution of culture. 
 
 Thus, indirectly at least, culture has an economic function. As 
 motive and means a necessary antecedent of the whole industrial 
 scheme of the modern world it must be recognized among eco- 
 nomic causes. Has it, then, or has it had in the past an economic 
 function more immediate, an economic character less disguised? 
 Did it originate in economic effort? As a product of evolution it 
 must be regarded as in some way related to the struggle for ex- 
 istence. Did it grow and differentiate because it contributed in a 
 practical way to life maintenance, or only because it happened to 
 be correlated with useful activities, and fortunately added some- 
 thing to the variety and interest of an existence which it had no 
 power to sustain ? 
 
 The answer to this question is not doubtful. In its earliest 
 forms culture is an economy; a practical, utilitarian thing. Only 
 in its late developments does it become a diversion. To the primi- 
 tive man culture in general, like music or dancing in particular, is 
 a serious business. 
 
 Bird and beast subsist on what they find. They are not, how- 
 ever, helpless creatures of a strictly fatalistic luck. Their reflex 
 and instinct mechanisms serve them well. Without comprehen- 
 sion they strive, and without thought they discriminate. Their 
 cries and gestures, by-products of zeal and alarm, proclaim dis- 
 coveries, warn of dangers, stimulate or depress. Also, through
 
 22 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 beating the air and the bush in a random trial of this and that 
 which results now in failure and now in accidental success, they 
 recondition their instincts. They learn, and acquire habits. They 
 practice cautious approaches and unhesitating avoidances. They 
 learn concrete good and evil, what things and powers revive and 
 comfort them, what hurt and incapacitate them. Out of ap- 
 proaches and avoidances they develop play habits of mimicry, 
 which like cries and gestures serve them by way of self-stimula- 
 tion and exhilaration. These first acquisitions (not known by 
 their beneficiaries to be such) are the rudiments of culture. 
 
 Primitive man develops articulate sounds into predicative dis- 
 course, the indispensable means of communication in the higher 
 forms of aggressive and defensive cooperation. He develops 
 address and reply, approach and avoidance into manners. Ap- 
 proaches he develops into contacts and alliances through which he 
 "gets power" (mana) and so into totemism. Avoidances he de- 
 velops into taboos, interposed between himself and evil. Mimicry 
 he develops into dance and song, and for ages the supreme pur- 
 pose for which he cultivates these arts is to stimulate himself to 
 moods of "power" and then by stimulating to enchant the realms 
 of plant and animal life. Presently out of such enchantments as 
 are practiced by the native Australians whereby those children of 
 nature believe that they multiply the witchetty grubs on which 
 their uncertain life depends, and such initiation ceremonies as 
 those of the "white clay men" (the Titanes) of ancient Crete, he 
 develops drama and myth. Out of mimicries also he creates tech- 
 nical arts of carving and drawing, of weaving and building. 
 Everything that he does, and worship above all, is with practical 
 intent. Whether thinking of natural processes in terms of im- 
 personal mana he piles his altars with rice or with maize and 
 sprinkles them with water to bring down saving rain, or, at a 
 later time, having peopled the world with ghosts and then with 
 personal gods of ghost extraction he prays and propitiates, his 
 worship is as purely economic in motive as is that of the modern 
 man of affairs who puts his contribution into the plate to fortify 
 his credit at the bank. Casting bread upon the waters is an old 
 practice, in which worship and economy are as one. 
 
 Nor was this ceremonial economy of primitive man as ridicu-
 
 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF CULTURE 23 
 
 lously idle as the modern skeptic may imagine. It did in fact very 
 greatly contribute to economic security. The effect of taboo was 
 to preserve multitudes of plant and animal species from indiscrim- 
 inate destruction, and, what was equally important, to compel men, 
 forbidden to subsist on this and that, to seek other food supplies 
 and thus to diversify consumption. The significance of this latter 
 fact will again be referred to later on. 
 
 And even where mere mimicry and supplication failed to ex- 
 tort from nature that which she yields only to patient industry 
 directed by scientific knowledge, they increased man's well-being 
 in another way. Differentiated into a thousand modes of pic- 
 turesque and enlivening activity, they became habits which man 
 has continued to cherish for the immediate pleasure which they 
 afford. They multiplied his interests, expanded his ideas, dis- 
 ciplined his mind. They provided immediate satisfactions, and 
 continued to provide them for all those human needs which are 
 not merely material ; while, at the same time, taboo and ceremony 
 contributed to his material security. 
 
 Whatever, then, culture may be today, it has been in its time an 
 economic system, as truly as industry is now. It was the economy 
 of primitive man. It was the first means of differentiating and 
 of protecting the food supply, and it was the first means of dif- 
 ferentiating the immaterial needs, thereby enormously broadening 
 economic demand, and strengthening economic motive. Yet it 
 was a radically different economy from that which now maintains 
 the enormous population of the world. In the hope of discovering 
 the scientific aspect of the difference, let us submit the bare out- 
 line of facts, which has thus far been given, to a more precise 
 analysis. 
 
 In a following chapter, on "The Economic Ages," in which I 
 shall pay a more adequate attention to the psychological character 
 of phenomena that I am here but superficially describing, I shall 
 suggest reasons for recognizing four stages of economic develop- 
 ment, namely, an organic, an instinctive and habitistic, an appre- 
 hensive, an ascertaining. The economy of plant life is organic 
 only. The economy of animal life is organic, instinctive and habi- 
 tistic. The economy of human life is organic, instinctive and 
 habitistic, apprehending and credulous, and ascertaining. Man
 
 24 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 alone systematically attempts to improve his condition. His first 
 experiments, however, directed by naive conceptions of nature, 
 are with the arts of enchantment and propitiation : his apprehen- 
 sive economy is ceremonial. Not until late in his career does he 
 become a systematic worker and develop a verifiable business 
 economy. 
 
 The organic, the instinctive and the ceremonial economies have 
 an essential something in common which marks them off from 
 modern industry, and which makes their phenomena the subject 
 matter of one grand division of economic science, while the busi- 
 ness phenomena of industry belong to another grand division. If 
 this distinction can be made clear, the true significance of culture 
 as a preliminary economy, and the antecedence of cultural phe- 
 nomena to nearly everything which we nowadays call economics, 
 will be established. 
 
 We must begin with a brief reference to phenomena of wants 
 and satisfactions, which are the data of all economic theory. The 
 need for food is so far from being the only original want that in 
 fact it is coordinate with demands equally imperative, no one of 
 which, taken by itself, is antecedent to another. Life would 
 perish as quickly if the energies which are evolved by the assimila- 
 tion of food could not normally be expended, as it would through 
 starvation. Expenditure in cell division and reproduction is the 
 universal mode, and it results in that multiplicity of organisms 
 which conditions the life struggle for each one. It is supple- 
 mented in the animal creation by motor activities, and these, in 
 the higher species, are differentiated in endless complications 
 through their correlation wittt a developed nervous system. All 
 of these activities of body and mind as they appear are enlisted in 
 the food quest, in the phenomena of reproduction and race main- 
 tenance, and, finally, in determining the relations of organisms to 
 one another. Again, each mode of activity, once established, 
 creates a continuing demand in the organism for the further en- 
 joyment of such expenditures of energy. Accustomed to the 
 chase, beast or man suffers miseries if deprived of freedom. Ac- 
 customed to the functions of race maintenance, the organism that 
 is deprived of offspring finds the pleasures of its own existence 
 largely curtailed. Long used to the presence of fellow creatures
 
 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF CULTURE 25 
 
 and to activities of antagonism or of sympathy, the individual in 
 isolation begins to perish, as surely as if he were deprived of food. 
 Finally, every activity of the mind in its questioning of nature, 
 and in its practical efforts to ameliorate the conditions of life, 
 creates a craving for its own renewal. 
 
 As rapidly as activities are differentiated, the need for discharge 
 of energy in each new channel becomes a demand for a particular 
 class of satisfactions, which must not be confused with the final 
 satisfaction of actual expenditure any more than food is mistaken 
 for the pleasure of consuming it. Food is a preliminary or me- 
 diate satisfaction. Means are necessary also to the end pleas- 
 urable activity. In general they may be described as stimuli. 
 For the pleasures of the chase the stimuli of forest and game are 
 needed. For the active pleasures that young creatures have in 
 the antics of play they need the stimulus of one another's pres- 
 ence. For all of the lighter pleasures of intellectual activity we 
 need the stimulus of fellow minds. For a major part of our 
 happiest emotional activity we need the stimulus afforded by the 
 presence of those who, through long association with us, have 
 become objects of attachment. In highly evolved societies the 
 stimuli of intellectual and emotional activity have become innu- 
 merable, and to provide them is as much a part of man's foresight 
 as to provide for the production of energy and its conservation 
 by food, clothing and shelter. 
 
 The. original wants of an organism, then, are those of energy- 
 supplying substance, and of stimuli provocative of energy dis- 
 charge. The wants of the former class can be differentiated to 
 a very slight extent only. Those of the latter class can be varied 
 indefinitely. The multiplication of wants and of satisfactions is 
 mainly a multiplication of activities and of stimuli. 
 
 How are the satisfactions of each class provided? There is a 
 large number of life-sustaining substances, and there are many 
 stimuli of activity, which not only are not produced by industry, 
 but which are not even obtained through intent, or by effort. 
 They are put in the way of the creatures that enjoy them, and 
 are absorbed or reacted upon as a matter of course. The lowest 
 organisms are wholly dependent upon such resources, and the 
 highest, including human beings, are still dependent upon them
 
 26 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 largely. Sunshine and air we accept without a thought of what 
 it would mean to have to get them by effort. The infinitely 
 varied stimuli which create our pleasurable sensations in the 
 presence of nature, and the ideas of nature that are slowly or- 
 ganized in scientific knowledge, are all a part of nature's unso- 
 licited bounty. The economy which utilizes them is purely bio- 
 logical and psychological, but it may be of any stage, from the 
 merely organic economy to the rational. 
 
 By the normal evolution of the organism further objective satis- 
 factions, belonging to the class stimuli, are provided ; in the lower 
 forms of life without conscious effort, but among human beings 
 with more or less of forethought, and at much cost in economic 
 sacrifice. These are offspring and fellow-beings, with all their 
 potentialities of sympathy and of rivalry, of social intercourse and 
 of cooperation. 
 
 A third mass of satisfactions is obtained through a measure of 
 effort, which, however, consists simply in finding and taking pos- 
 session of what nature provides. It is made up of those food 
 supplies that are the dependence of most of the higher animals 
 and of primitive man, and of various materials which both ani- 
 mals and men use for nests or shelter, and men for clothing. 
 To a much greater extent than we realize the human race still 
 subsists by foraging rather than by producing. We consume 
 great quantities of wild fruits and of game, of medicinal barks 
 and herbs, of furs and feathers which are merely gathered, and 
 are not increased in supply by any process of breeding or culti- 
 vating. In a large measure our so-called extractive industries 
 are merely survivals of a primitive foraging economy. Lumber- 
 ing by the usual wasteful methods is a conspicuous example of it. 
 
 There is a fourth array of satisfactions, consisting substantially 
 of stimuli of bodily and mental activities, intellectual and emo- 
 tional, which are enjoyed only by man, and the origins of which 
 we have been describing. All have sprung from instinctive reac- 
 , tions, mimetic habits, approaches and avoidances. Originally de- 
 veloped with practical intent, they become important to man for 
 the sustenance of mind and soul rather than of body. Language 
 and manners, worship and amusements, plastic and poetic arts, 
 these involve productive intent and effort, and in the beginning
 
 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF CULTURE 27 
 
 they are regarded as productive means, as truly as capital is in 
 modern days. Nevertheless, they are in reality productive of 
 subjective satisfactions, rather than of material goods, and so are 
 not properly to be classed as agents of a productive economy. 
 
 The fifth and final array of satisfactions is that which is created 
 by modern productive industry. It comprises the great bulk of 
 our food supplies, and of our clothing, comforts and luxuries; 
 and their creation involves the production also of great quantities 
 of auxiliary goods, including tools and machinery and means of 
 transportation. 
 
 All of these satisfactions save those of the last division named, 
 are an inheritance from an almost immeasurable past. Are there 
 any categories of economic science which apply to the products 
 of that "preliminary age," as Bagehot called it, no less than 
 to the wealth of our modern world? The answer has already 
 been given by implication in what has been said of the func- 
 tions of reproduction and of culture in differentiating both wants 
 and their satisfactions. The numerical increase of a species raises 
 the life of each individual to a higher power by multiplying a 
 thousand fold the stimuli of activity. Cultural products raise it 
 to yet higher powers both by diversifying its material basis of 
 subsistence, and by almost infinitely multiplying its interests. 
 
 Now just to the extent that men have a wide variety of ma- 
 terial satisfactions, and that their interests are multiplied by 
 innumerable stimuli of activity, they have a relatively high stand- 
 ard of living. That the standard of living is a complex of cul- 
 tural facts hardly needs demonstration. What men desire and 
 expect in life is an epitome of their race history in social inter- 
 course, manners, art, amusements and religion. Here, then, in 
 identifying the preliminary economies with the evolution of a 
 standard of living we bring them within the scope of familiar 
 economic concepts. A phenomenon of the diversification of wants 
 and satisfactions, the standard of living is a fact not of produc- 
 tion primarily, but of consumption. Thus we arrive at the broad 
 economic significance of culture. The evolution of culture is the 
 evolution of a consumption economy. 1 
 
 *I take the phrase from Simon N. Patten, but he must not be held 
 responsible for the uses that I make of it.
 
 28 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 The classical economists recognized a department of their 
 science which they called the consumption of wealth ; but they 
 never knew what to make of it. Accepting the self-luminous 
 proposition that wealth cannot be consumed until it is obtained, 
 they touch upon consumption, if at all, at the end of their expo- 
 sition, and only so far as to show how the consumption of wealth 
 reacts upon its increase. This fact ought to have disclosed to 
 them the causal relation of consumption to production. Jevons 
 and the Austrian writers perceived the psychological aspect of it, 
 and by deriving from the facts of consumption the marginal 
 theory of utility and of value, they restated economic theory. 
 Marshall, broadening the treatment, identified the theory of con- 
 sumption with the theory of demand, and placed it before the 
 theory of supply, that is, of production. 
 
 The whole truth of the matter, however, is that the phenomena 
 of consumption are not only psychologically antecedent to the 
 phenomena of production, as motive to deed, but, as we have 
 seen, they are also historically antecedent. For ages there was 
 consumption before there was any production, and without grasp- 
 ing that fact man's economic and social history is not to be under- 
 stood. Like the lower animals he depended for supplies upon 
 the proffered bounty of nature. His only business was to con- 
 sume what she gave. His ideas and habits of consumption, 
 therefore, were his original economy. There was, in short, a 
 consumption economy long before there was a production 
 economy. 
 
 And that is not all. When man became convinced that he must 
 do something to increase the supplies that nature offered, he knew 
 nothing of industrial methods. He did not even suspect the im- 
 portance of differentiating his consumption. But through avoid- 
 ance and taboo, and by trying through magical stimulation and 
 religious ceremony to wheedle food from the powers of earth and 
 air, he did vary his consumption in fact, and differentiation once 
 begun was bound to continue until it became a great multiplication 
 of wants. The immediate effect of differentiation was to establish 
 a conservative and relatively advantageous use of the environ- 
 ment. Here again history confirms theory. Economists recognize 
 the indebtedness of their science to Patten's studies of the relation
 
 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF CULTURE 20 
 
 of a diversified consumption to marginal utility and to the total 
 supply of goods. Diversified consumption does not soon en- 
 counter diminishing returns. It is the simplest way to ameliorate 
 economic conditions, and it was the primitive way. 
 
 Differentiation begins with the multiplication of organisms and 
 the evolution of their relations to one another. It begins, in 
 short, in the needs and satisfactions of collective life. In relations 
 with offspring and other fellow-creatures we have the first new 
 forms of energy-expenditure which have been referred to as 
 correlative with the need for energy-supplying substances. In the 
 relation of the individual to his fellows we have the stimuli which 
 first expand his consumption. 
 
 From pluralistic behavior and relations are presently developed 
 the things of culture ; from language, manners and religion to the 
 arts of expression and of utility. Culture in turn, in its economic 
 aspect, is nothing more nor less than the diversification of con- 
 sumption. It is the expansion and perfection of the consumption 
 economy. 
 
 But we have not yet exhausted the possibilities, of the consump- 
 tion economy so nearly identical with culture. It is through the 
 diversification of consumption that man passes over into a pro- 
 duction economy, and it is in the standard of living, created and 
 measured by the diversification of culture, that we have the effi- 
 cient cause of the modern production of wealth. 
 
 Through using a large number of nature's freely offered goods 
 in new and varied ways, man slowly discerns the possibilities that 
 lie in the cultivation of roots and grains, the breeding of animals, 
 the development of instinctive arts into rude manufactures, and 
 finally exchange. Perhaps we cannot trace all the steps by which 
 magical mummeries became agriculture and herding, and imita- 
 tions of natural objects for purposes of incantation or enchant- 
 ment became practical utensils or beautiful adornments, but there 
 is no doubt that for ages the practical was not yet separated from 
 the ceremonial. And without attempting to explain just how 
 exchange began, we can say that one of its earliest forms was a 
 give and take between the community and its unseen powers. The 
 ceremonial rites of magic and religion offer services and gifts, and 
 man expects to be rewarded for them by a relative abundance.
 
 30 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 This exchange has in it also the germ of the idea of capital. 
 Closely connected with such ceremonies are those of propitiation 
 between man and man, whereby the various products found in the 
 foraging of many individuals, families and hordes, being cere- 
 monially passed from one to another, in the course of time are 
 passed for the sake of a varied consumption, until the whole 
 affair becomes a trade, and exchange is seen to be a means of 
 producing a greater sum total of satisfactions. 
 
 In the question whether the standard of living determines 
 industrial production, or industrial production determines the 
 standard of living, we come back to close quarters with the whole 
 issue over the economic interpretation of history. If the stand- 
 ard of living determines production, then the "interpretation of 
 history" runs back into that early economy which survives as 
 culture. Men cannot have more to eat and to wear, or better 
 houses or bigger churches, or handsomer theatres and clubs, or 
 choicer books and pictures, or indulge in more music or travel 
 than they can produce or find the means to pay for ; but neither 
 can they produce given quantities of these things unless they de- 
 sire them strongly enough to put forth necessary exertion, to 
 make necessary sacrifices, to undergo miscellaneous hardships, 
 and to keep their minds alert enough to bring them all to comple- 
 tion. In a word, the standard of living is not the sum and sub- 
 stance of what a population actually has. It is literally what the 
 word means the standard, the ideal of comfort and luxury which 
 a class or people is striving to realize ; not its day-dream of what 
 some fairy godmother might provide, but its sober estimate of 
 what it believes to be possible, and is determined by all reasonable 
 effort to try to secure. So defined and understood, the standard 
 of living is beyond question the cause and not the effect of pro- 
 duction. 
 
 We may now summarize our results to this point. The or- 
 ganic, instinctive and ceremonial economies, of the world of veg- 
 etation, of animal life and of primitive man, are all parts of a 
 consumption economy which is antecedent historically as well as 
 psychologically to the production economy of the modern world. 
 The consumption economy increases well-being not by producing 
 goods through cultivation, breeding or manufacture, but by so
 
 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF CULTURE 31 
 
 diversifying wants and satisfactions that the adaptation of or- 
 ganism and environment is wider in its basis and more stable 
 than it can be when consumption is simple. The diversification 
 of wants and satisfactions begins in the multiplication of organ- 
 isms through reproduction, and in the evolution of pluralistic rela- 
 tions. It is continued and perfected by the evolution of culture. 
 The consumption economy, by thus determining habits and mo- 
 tives, creates the standard of living, and the standard of living in 
 turn, when mental evolution has achieved the transition to a pro- 
 ductive economy, determines the extent of wealth production. 
 
 Certain further facts may now be conceded, and we are then in 
 a position to comprehend the full economic significance of culture, 
 because the successive steps of economic causation in history 
 will appear in their genetic order. Accepting as true that theory 
 of distribution which accounts for the share of each productive 
 factor by its marginal productivity, and, in like manner, for the 
 share of each component part of a productive factor, for ex- 
 ample, a particular group of laborers, it is clear that the social 
 distribution of wealth is determined by the productive power of 
 the various groups and classes in the population. This produc- 
 tive power is in turn determined, so far as causation lies in motive, 
 by the standard of living of the producing groups, and so far as 
 it lies in ability, by their bodily power, moral equipment, mental 
 discipline and acquisitions. Normally these factors are corre- 
 lated, and all in a large sense are products of culture. They are, 
 in a word, the cultural equipment of the respective groups. 
 Chiefly important is the extent to which primitive conceptions 
 have been superseded by scientific knowledge. 
 
 The social distribution of wealth, it may be admitted, is a true 
 cause of changes in mores and in law, while these in turn, involv- 
 ing as they do conceptions of rights and liberties, are true causes 
 of changes in political organization and policy. 
 
 Therefore, still more briefly stated, our conclusion is : A con- 
 sumption economy, the chief factors in which are pluralistic rela- 
 tions and their great objective product, culture, creates presently 
 a productive economy and the beginnings of law and government, 
 and it continues to determine the scope of the productive econ- 
 omy, while the latter, once in full operation, determines the
 
 32 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 further evolution of law and politics. Let us then have as much 
 economic interpretation of history as the facts can be made to 
 yield, provided that we know what we are talking about. An in- 
 terpretation in terms of those ideas and practices which are the 
 subject-matter of economic science, as the term is ordinarily un- 
 derstood, will carry us but a very little way. To get back to the 
 beginnings of the historical process and to true causes, we must 
 go deep into the origins of the consumption economy and follow 
 its evolution through the unfolding of culture.
 
 CHAPTER III 
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 
 
 IN those pleasantly discursive writings which Alfred Russell 
 Wallace in advancing years brought together in the volumes en- 
 titled Studies Scientific and Social, and which include, with dis- 
 cussions geological, biological and anthropological, other discus- 
 sions that are economic, political and educational, the reader finds 
 a chapter described by the headline, "The Problem of Utility." 
 Naturally, if he is familiar with those developments of economic 
 theory which interested us in the last quarter of the nineteenth 
 century, he will assume that the great English evolutionist, who 
 shares with Darwin the honor of having discovered the process of 
 organic evolution by natural selection, found time to give atten- 
 tion to the abstruse problems associated with the names of Cour- 
 not, Menger, Jevons, Walras, Von Wieser and J. B. Clark. Upon 
 turning, however, from the table of contents to Chapter XVIII 
 itself, one discovers that it is further described by the question, 
 "Are Specific Characters always or generally Useful ?" and by the 
 following quotation from an article which Mr. Wallace published 
 as early as 1867 : 
 
 Perhaps no principle has ever been announced so fertile in results as 
 that which Mr. Darwin so earnestly impresses upon us, and which is 
 indeed a necessary deduction from the theory of natural selection, namely, 
 that none of the definite facts of organic nature, no special organ, no 
 characteristic form or marking, no peculiarities of instinct or of habit, 
 no relations between species or between groups of species, can exist but 
 which must now be, or once have been, useful to the individuals or races 
 which possess them. 
 
 The principle thus described Mr. Wallace called "The Principle 
 of Utility." As thus employed, the phrase sounded strange to ears 
 that had grown familiar with such locutions as "final degree of 
 utility," "marginal utility" and "subjective utility." The late 
 
 33
 
 34 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 nineteenth century economist had ceased to think of utility apart 
 from the psychological facts of want and satisfaction. Yet none 
 would deny that Mr. Wallace's employment of the word was an 
 old and common one. Moreover, it would not be inconsistent with 
 one definition given by Jevons namely, "a circumstance of things 
 arising out of their relation to man's requirements" 1 if for the 
 phrase "man's requirements" we might substitute the words "the 
 requirements of a living organism." Such a substitution, how- 
 ever, would distort Jevons's conception and that of the whole 
 school of writers to which he belonged. For Jevons elsewhere 
 says : "Whatever can produce pleasure or prevent pain may pos- 
 sess utility." It is by the latter definition that we should interpret 
 his phrase "man's requirements." In the last analysis, according 
 to an economic calculus, man's requirements are the diminution 
 of pain and the increase of pleasure. 
 
 Thus, plainly there were and are two distinct notions of utility : 
 one a concept of utility as objective, which plays a large part in 
 the theory of biological evolution ; the other a concept of utility 
 as subjective, which became and will remain an important factor 
 in economic theory. Utility objective is a circumstance of things 
 arising out of their relations to organic life. It is a realized 
 capacity to maintain life or to develop it, and the life so served 
 may be conscious or unconscious, animal or only vegetal. Utility 
 subjective is a pleasure-producing or a pain-preventing circum- 
 stance of things, itself varying with a state of mind want or 
 satiety and consciously known or recognized as a cause of 
 conscious satisfaction. 
 
 Not only in their employment of this somewhat technical word 
 "utility" do the biologists and the economists reveal an interesting 
 divergence of thought, but also, as was intimated in Chapter II, in 
 their use of the words "economy" and "economic," as well, they 
 present a significant contrast. The economist, however deeply 
 tinged his ideas may be with the color of modern biological knowl- 
 edge, habitually thinks of economy as a practice or condition of 
 human beings who have acquired arts, and who produce wealth 
 i.e., exchangeable goods by means of industry, well regulated 
 
 1 Theory of Political Economy, ch. iii.
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 35 
 
 by "business methods.'' Inherent in this conception an almost 
 essential part of it is the notion that economy presumes a con- 
 scious being, endowed with capacity for pain and for pleasure, 
 to plan and direct the economy and to profit by it. It is a notion 
 that, after all, "economy" is only a refined form of the Greek 
 "housekeeping," which the word originally meant. 
 
 From the Greek OIKOS, however, a far more general concept 
 has been derived, and it is this which we straightway encounter 
 when we turn from the pages of the economists to those of the 
 biologists. Housekeeping is a system of activities and rela- 
 tionships that subserve the well-being of the housekeepers. 
 Hence is derived the highly general notion of "economy" as 
 any system of activities and relations which furthers the well- 
 being of any class or species of living things. This is the 
 biological meaning of the word, and we have therefore such 
 phrases as the "economy of the animal kingdom," "the economy 
 of the vegetal kingdom" and ' even the most general concept 
 of all "the economy of nature." In these notions there is no 
 implication of consciousness, of pleasure or of pain, and no pre- 
 sumption of intelligent planning or management on the part of 
 the organisms that are benefited by their economy. The thought 
 is altogether objective. 
 
 The bearing of these reflections upon our theories of society 
 and upon the cult, (for such it has become) of the economic in- 
 terpretation of history, was considered in Chapter II. It was 
 there contended that if economic phenomena imply conscious 
 intelligence, systematized industry and "business methods," even 
 if no more complex than those of the ol/cos management of old 
 Hellas, it cannot be maintained that economic phenomena are 
 antecedent to social relations, and that if on the other hand 
 economic phenomena are fundamental, it is incontestable that the 
 economic interpreters must drop the economic conception of 
 "economy" and adopt the biological. In this contention, as the 
 reader was told, there is more to be said. 
 
 The theses which I now undertake to prove are : First, that in 
 every stage of the evolution of life, from that of the lowest 
 vegetal organisms to that of the highest human consciousness, 
 economy is a function of two variables, namely, ( I ) the physical
 
 36 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 environment, (2) a plural number of living organisms or indi- 
 viduals; second, that the relation of these two variables to each 
 other, which may at any time be affected by changes occurring 
 in the physical environment, is at all times largely determined 
 by the relations which the organisms or individuals in plural 
 number sustain to one another; and, third, that economy, as thus 
 determined, is developed through four great stages or ages, which 
 I shall call, respectively, the Organic Economy, the Instinctive 
 Economy (instinctive and habitistic), the Apprehensive Economy, 
 (childishly reasoning), and the Ascertaining Economy (scientifi- 
 cally rational) ; and that for unnumbered generations economy 
 into which reasoning enters is an Apprehensive and Ceremonial 
 Economy (apprehending and credulous yet fearing) before it 
 becomes an Ascertaining (a verifying) and Business Economy. 
 An analytical description of these economic ages will constitute 
 the sufficient proof of my three propositions. 
 
 We begin, then, with the organic economy. This phrase must 
 be interpreted as an abbreviation of a longer expression namely, 
 the economy of living organisms that are without psychologically 
 functioning nervous mechanisms. It is the economy of the 
 vegetal kingdom, and of the animal kingdom in so far as nervous 
 mechanisms function physiologically only. From the standpoint 
 of evolution it is the lowest stage in the economy of living 
 things, and from the standpoint of time it is the primal economic 
 age the economy that must have prevailed before there were 
 differentiated nerve cells, or dawn of that elemental sensibility 
 which was to develop into conscious intelligence. 
 
 So understood, organic economy is a system of activities and 
 relations that subserve the well-being of merely vegetal organ- 
 isms and of all organisms in so far as they are physiological only. 
 In what, then, does that system of activities and relations con- 
 sist? The answer has been given in elaborate detail in the 
 writings of the Darwinian evolutionists. The activities include 
 alimentation, the waste and repair of tissue, and reproduction. 
 Before Darwin's day an account of these processes would have 
 been an extremely simple affair. Each would have been described 
 in terms of observations made upon single and separate organ- 
 isms, with but slight intimation that at every instant the physiolog-
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 37 
 
 ical processes were vitally conditioned by the relations of co- 
 existent organisms to one another. Darwin revolutionized the 
 description by showing that alimentation was conditioned by a 
 struggle for existence, and that metabolism and reproduction 
 were conditioned by natural selection, a result of unequal ali- 
 mentation and other consequences of the struggle for existence. 
 In short, Darwin and the Darwinians first gave us an approxi- 
 mately complete account of organic economy, and the precise 
 fact, previously ignored or misunderstood, which they brought 
 into prominence and explained the significance of, was that of 
 the varying relations of coexisting organisms to one another, 
 whereby the whole scheme of organic economy was, from point 
 to point and from generation to generation, determined. 
 
 Nor is it merely the relations of organisms of many species 
 indiscriminately mingling in the same environment that thus 
 determine the scheme of organic economy. Most important 
 of all relations are those subsisting among individual organisms 
 of the same species and, above all, of the same subspecies or 
 variety and of the same generation. Between widely unlike 
 species there may be mortal antagonism or there may be a 
 relation of mutual protection. Precisely the same is true of 
 the individuals constituting a variety, except that now the rela- 
 tion of mutual protection is more important than the relation of 
 antagonism. In the struggle for existence among the hundreds 
 of varieties of plants in any garden or field there is, indeed, a 
 continual crowding to the wall of weakly individuals by compet- 
 itors of their own kind; but in the long run it is whole kinds 
 that are crowded out, while large tracts are overrun by the 
 multiplying individuals of a single kind, whose very numbers 
 and contiguity are their chief protection against the encroach- 
 ments of any other species. Every individual stem of lichen, 
 moss or fern is protected by surrounding masses of organisms 
 like itself; every blade of grass or grain, by thousands of such 
 blades ; and every pine in the wood, by the forest of pines about 
 it. Thus in the realm of merely organic life we discover the 
 economic importance of a grouping in one place of many indi- 
 viduals of the same kind. And this grouping and mutual pro- 
 tection of individuals of like kind, while not to be described as
 
 38 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 a social fact, is yet a basis for social phenomena. It is a pre- 
 or subsocial grouping, the beginning of developmental arrange- 
 ments that may culminate in social relationships. 
 
 How organic economy shades into instinctive economy we 
 very imperfectly know. Manifestations of irritability in nervous 
 matter we can perceive. Reflex actions developing into co- 
 ordinated movements can be observed. An instinct is a combi- 
 nation (or a complex) of reflex tendencies which normally 
 complete themselves in action. Energized and stimulated it 
 "goes," as an internal combustion engine goes when it gets fuel 
 and the spark. When instinct has appeared in the organic world, 
 a new development of economy has begun. Generations, num- 
 bered probably by millions, must live and die before it can 
 become a conscious calculation and creation of utilities, but the 
 well-being of the responding organism is now furthered by 
 means vastly more complex than those which suffice for sub- 
 instinctive life. Movement from place to place by the organism 
 itself, and the ability of the organism to move things from 
 place to place, have become factors of immeasurable importance 
 in the economic scheme. 
 
 In due course irritability takes on sensitivity (psychologists 
 have too often identified these two) but sensitivity itself, and the 
 process by which it develops into sensation, into pain and pleasure, 
 and ultimately into intelligence, are facts which arise out of and 
 disappear into the unknown. 
 
 Instinctive action, then, may be accompanied by sensation, by 
 pleasure or pain, by awareness, but it is not a conscious adaptation 
 of means to ends in the sense that consciousness effects the 
 adaptation. The delicate work of the wasps and bees in making 
 their nests, the complicated labors of the nest-building fishes, the 
 weaving and sewing and clay modelling of birds, the collective 
 hunting and fishing and the collective defense against enemies 
 seen among both birds and the gregarious mammalia all these 
 are a mechanistic behavior, as truly if a small measure of "trial 
 and error" enters into them as when they are unvarying. 
 
 In short, in the whole marvelous economy of the animal king- 
 dom, from the protozoa to man, there is no certain trace of what 
 the subjective economists could by any stretch of meaning call
 
 39 
 
 economic. The welfare of the organism which is subserved 
 by adaptation includes a subjective element. Pain and pleasure 
 have appeared, and the adaptation of means to ends tends on the 
 whole to allay pain and to increase pleasure; but as yet sub- 
 jective utility that is, a circumstance of things varying with 
 subjective want or satiety, and consciously recognized as the 
 cause of an agreeable state of mind does not exist. Only the 
 elements out of which it may slowly be developed have come into 
 being. 
 
 Yet, to an extent far greater than in the sub-instinctive or 
 pre-instinctive organic world, economy has become a function 
 of the relations of individuals to one another, at every moment 
 determining the relations of each individual to the purely ma- 
 terial environment. Readers of Darwin, Wallace, Brehm, Kro- 
 potkin, and later writers too many to name, do not need to be 
 told that every food-getting and nest-building instinct, as well 
 as every protective instinct in the animal kingdom, has been 
 influenced quite as much by rivalry and combat as by quantity 
 of food, the nature of the inhabited earth or water, or the cli- 
 matic conditions which have entered as factors into the struggle 
 for existence. In a yet greater degree, perhaps, have all these 
 instincts been developed through the pluralistic like-reactions to 
 common situations, and through the interstimulations, of the 
 herd. It follows that, to an enormous degree, instinct is a 
 product of the closely related activities of creatures of the same 
 kind, living together in a common habitat. Even more than segre- 
 gation determines well-being in the vegetal kingdom does con- 
 sorting determine the well-being of an animal species. In fact, 
 ages before man appeared upon the earth, and ages before any 
 creature existed that could have entertained the concept of 
 subjective utility, economy had been developed to the stage in 
 which collective action and a division of labor counted as factors 
 of high importance. 
 
 When evolutionist doctrine became a part of the common stock 
 of ideas among knowing people, economists avowedly or tacitly 
 assumed that the economy of industrial humanity was through 
 various stages developed out of the instinctive economy of 
 animals. The "historical economists" of Germany and their
 
 40 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 American disciples before 1914 took pride in their reconstruction 
 of the process. It seems that in the beginning was a "hunting 
 stage" ; then, in the course of ages, appeared the "pastoral stage." 
 At length, after more ages, dawned the "agricultural stage," and 
 finally, in the fullness of time, came to fruition the "industrial 
 stage" the end and consummation of nature's eons of travail. 
 With all respect to laborious and learned men, I must protest 
 that this economic philosophy of history is inadequate. It fails 
 to grasp the actual facts which have marked the transition from 
 instinctive to rational conduct in the human species. Not that 
 there is anything untruthful about it as far as it goes. It is 
 true that man hunted and fished before he learned how to milk, 
 and that he probably had made some progress in the dairy busi- 
 ness before he learned how to yoke oxen to the plough, although 
 not before his squaws had learned how to tickle the earth with a 
 stick. But it is also true that historical economists too often had 
 a keener sense of chronology than of value. Their "historical" 
 scheme of economic evolution was as accurate as the multiplica- 
 tion table; but it was one from which everything of real signifi- 
 cance in economic evolution was as carefully omitted as lese 
 majeste from a chancellor's address. 
 
 The real question for which we should, if possible, find the 
 answer is this: How did the human mind, slowly developing 
 from instinct to reason, successively re-grasp the environment, 
 successively re-interpret the relations of cause and effect and 
 successively re-attempt to control the processes of nature in the 
 interest of human welfare? Primitive man caught fish and 
 killed game; but did he fish like Henry Van Dyke or hunt like 
 Theodore Roosevelt? And, what is more important, did he think 
 of man's relation to fish in the Van Dyke way, or of his relation 
 to very fierce beasts in the Roosevelt way? 
 
 It so happens that we have an overwhelming mass of evidence 
 that primitive man would have thought it absurd to the last 
 degree to go "a-fishing" with no better equipment than a beau- 
 tiful rod, a neat basket, a choice assortment of flies, a dainty 
 luncheon and a vest-pocket edition of Keats. He would confi- 
 dently have lotted on meeting an ignominious death if he had 
 gone forth to battle with the mountain lion with no better im-
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 41 
 
 plements than the "latest improved" rifle, a bowie knife, a brace 
 or two of pistols and buckskin leggings. The primitive man 
 would have made from a bit of wood as neat a carving of the 
 fish as his artistic instinct and humble tools could fashion, and 
 would have put it in the water to swim in the direction which 
 the fish usually followed. Then he would fervently and be- 
 lievingly have prayed to the fish to come; and this would have 
 caused them to arrive. When he went hunting, he would first 
 have made an ingenious trap; then he would have clothed and 
 decorated himself in the best possible imitation of the ferocious 
 beast to be caught. Buckskin leggings might, indeed, have had 
 some virtue at this stage of the procedure, but on the whole the 
 primitive man would have thought them insufficient. Having 
 completed these preparations, he would nonchalantly have strolled 
 into the woods in the direction of the trap and, quite carefully 
 failing to see it, have very carelessly fallen into it, crying out 
 in alarm that he was caught. Then, regaining his composure, he 
 would have extricated himself as best he could, and readjusted 
 the trap, knowing with certainty that the first unsuspecting beast 
 that wandered that way would be caught and done for. 
 
 These fables teach that the economy of primitive man is as 
 unlike the economy of his modern child, even when the latter re- 
 verts to the "hunting stage," as the savage theory of creation 
 is unlike Darwinism. The primitive man's economy is no longer 
 merely instinctive and habitistic. He has ideas, he consciously 
 contemplates his situation, he perceives relations which the lower 
 animals have never discriminated, and his imagination runs riot 
 in explanatory activity. And yet it never once occurs to him 
 that his well-being is to any great extent within his own control, 
 least of all that by systematic labor, directed by "business 
 methods," he could become master of his economic situation. He 
 is beginning to be rational, but he is not yet scientific. He views 
 the world as a fearsome aggregation of "creepy" objects, pos- 
 sessed of mysterious and often amazing powers for good and for 
 evil. His well-being, as he believes, depends almost entirely upon 
 his relation to those powers. 
 
 Instinct, even when overlaid by habit, is relatively unerring in 
 its action. The instinctive bee does not experiment with new
 
 42 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 geometric designs in constructing its cell. The instinctive bird 
 goes about its nest-building business with a directness that might 
 well be the envy of the human architect or contractor. There is 
 little hesitation at any point in the instinctive economy of the ani- 
 mal kingdom. But reason is never unerring, never unhesitating. 
 While instinct is correlative of the adaptation of an organism to 
 those facts of the environment which remain constant, reason is 
 correlative of that variation from old adaptations, which an or- 
 ganism must make to a changing environment or to the varying 
 features of an environment in which some features remain con- 
 stant. Reason, therefore, always means choice, and choice means 
 some hesitation, some deliberation. Accordingly, the rational 
 economies of man (the apprehensive and the ascertaining), un- 
 like the instinctive economies of the animal, are marked by per- 
 plexity, by doubt, by experimentation and the slow, painful 
 process of discovery. Inevitably, therefore, rational economies 
 develop by stages which can be understood only if we can trace 
 the progress of man's intellectual development. The "obvious" 
 stages of "hunting," "pasturage" and so on will doubtless still 
 go chiming down the ages in the Mother Goose philosophy of 
 history but, as was said, they have no scientific significance. Are 
 there, then, any indications, psychological and historical, whereby 
 we may discriminate the ages through which rational economies 
 have been evolving? 
 
 Reasoning is a trial of this and that in thought, supplementing 
 and economizing the trial of this and that ("trial and error") in 
 action. Seemingly it begins with guessing, or conjecture. All 
 authorities agree that the transition from instinct to reason is 
 seen in that warfare of "contrary impulses" which was so ad- 
 mirably described by James 1 and in the "hesitation" emphasized 
 by Marshall. 2 Circumstances having arisen, through environ- 
 mental change or otherwise, in which instinct or habit no longer 
 can guide the organism aright, the mind begins to "wobble." It 
 casts about more or less wildly for an answer to its questionings, 
 and that casting about or conjecturing we call in our everyday 
 speech merely guesswork. 
 
 1 Psychology, Vol. II, pp. 389-393- 
 
 2 Instinct and Reason, pp. 417, et seq.
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 43 
 
 Now guessing, as we all know, is the prevailing intellectual 
 method of childhood, when reason is struggling with instinct 
 for supremacy. It is the confirmed intellectual method of igno- 
 rant and undeveloped minds, in which reason is arrested at the 
 childhood stage. Guesswork, however, is extraordinarily fallible 
 as a guide to action. Sometimes it pierces the situation by a 
 happy intuition, and sometimes it hits disastrously wide of the 
 mark. Stumbling along a miry road on a dark night, the back- 
 woodsman comes to a swollen stream and "guesses" that he can 
 ford it. Plunging in, he finds it not half so deep or so violent 
 as it looked, and he emerges on the other side complacently glad 
 that he isn't the kind of fellow to be too easily scared. This 
 reflection, however, is not the only idea in his mind at the 
 moment. He is at the same time blessing his "good luck." Had 
 it turned out that the stream was more formidable than he had 
 guessed, and had he reached the farther bank barely alive and 
 mourning the loss of his outfit, he would have been found not 
 only chagrined over his bad guessing, but also energetically damn- 
 ing his bad luck. A strong belief in luck, in fine, always coexists 
 with the guesswork stage of intellectual activity. The guess hits 
 or goes astray, and luck does the rest. 
 
 Thus far the psychology of the primitive human mind as it 
 survives among ourselves. How is it with the primitive human 
 mind as it survives among savages? All observers unite in 
 testifying that the lowest savage reasoning is purely conjec- 
 tural, and that one of the strongest beliefs of the lowest sav- 
 age is his ineradicable faith in luck. The element of industry 
 enters into the economic life of the savage as largely, possibly, 
 as it does into the economy of the lower animals. The savage 
 looks for food and puts forth effort to appropriate it. He 
 sometimes constructs rude weapons and equally rude tools. He 
 sometimes builds a rude shelter and sometimes contrives a bit of 
 clothing. Yet in all this economic activity he is disturbed and 
 made doubtful of his procedure as the instinctive animal never is. 
 If the savage gets the idea into his head that luck is against a 
 particular plan of procedure in his hunting or fishing, or is 
 against a certain pattern of construction, his economic activity in 
 these directions is instantly inhibited. He then loafs about until
 
 44 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 guesswork and luck suggest a new procedure. That this is the 
 true explanation of the seemingly paradoxical fact that the prim- 
 itive man, a little higher in the scale of existence than the highest 
 quadrumana, is often less industrious and much less systematic in 
 his economic activities than many lower species are, cannot, I 
 think, be questioned by any investigator familiar with both the 
 psychology and the sociology of savage groups. The fact is not, 
 however, as paradoxical as it seems. A luck economy is the first 
 stage of a rational economy, and the very lowest sort of rational 
 economy is a degree advanced beyond the highest instinctive and 
 habitistic economy. It is precisely because the savage does hesi- 
 tate and trust to luck that he breaks down a lot of habits which 
 would have been fatal to progress and, more or less by accident, 
 adopts many new ways in which the potentiality of progress lies. 
 
 One test of any hypothesis concerning the early stages of 
 an evolutionary process is found in survivals of each early stage 
 in a later time. What was chronologically first to a great extent 
 survives as the structurally or functionally low, just as the rocks 
 old in time are in position deep down in the stratification. 
 
 Do we, then, find in civilization significant survivals of the luck 
 economy? Turn to the pages of Hesiod and read over again the 
 Works and Days, but especially the calendar of lucky and un- 
 lucky days at the end : 
 
 Mind well, too, and teach thy servants fittingly the days appointed 
 of Jove. . . . The eleventh and twelfth, both in truth are good, the one 
 for shearing sheep, the other for reaping laughing corn : but the twelfth 
 is far better than the eleventh, for on it, look you, the high hovering 
 spider spins his threads in the long summer day, when also the wise 
 ant harvests his heap. On this day, too, a woman should set up her 
 loom, and put forth her work. But on the thirteenth of the beginning 
 of the month avoid commencing your sowing; though to set plants it 
 is best. The sixteenth, however, is very unprofitable to plants. . . . Nor, 
 in truth, is the first sixth day suitable for the birth of girls, but a favor- 
 able day for cutting kids and flocks of sheep, and for enclosing a fold 
 of sheep. . . . On the eighth of the month emasculate the boar and loud 
 bellowing bull, and on the twelfth the toil-enduring mules. . . . On the 
 seventeenth watch well, and cast upon the well-rounded threshing floor 
 Demeter's holy gift; and let the woodcutter cut timbers for chamber 
 furniture, and many blocks for naval purposes, which are fit for 
 ships. . . . Now, few, again, know that the twenty-ninth of the month 
 is best both for broaching a cask, and placing a yoke on the neck of
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 45 
 
 oxen and mules and fleet-footed steeds. ... On the fourth day open 
 your cask. 1 
 
 Hesiod and the graceless agricultural brother whom he admon- 
 ished lived long ago, to be sure, yet the practical American of 
 the twentieth century need not plume himself on being much 
 less a devotee of luck than was the imaginative Greek. Give the 
 average American his choice between making a certain compe- 
 tence by diligence and good judgment or possibly making a for- 
 tune by operations in land or in stocks, he will take the gamble. 
 Endless protestations by "the moral element" have only demon- 
 strated that the love of gambling is one of the strongest of human 
 passions. Guesswork and a belief in luck, in fact, run through 
 all our business undertakings and bring to naught innumerable 
 promising enterprises. I have often wished that an ingenious 
 statistician would compute the annual average loss of property 
 and of life in the United States directly attributable to the belief 
 in luck. The railroad corporation takes its chances with wornout 
 rails and decrepit bridges and pays hundreds of thousands of 
 dollars in damages. The owners of buildings take their chances 
 with "jerry" construction and see their property disappear in 
 collapse or in smoke. The shipowner takes his chances with 
 rotten hulks on the sea, and the banker with rotten securities on 
 the street. One and all, they are devotees of luck. Even the 
 religious beliefs of this most secular and most sceptical of peoples 
 are permeated through and through with the primitive man's 
 philosophy of luck. I remember in my boyhood hearing old 
 ladies tell of finding names for babies by opening the Word of 
 God at random. 
 
 The second stage in the development of reason, following 
 close upon the guessing or conjectural, is that of reasoning 
 from analogy. The mind begins to form conclusions by assuming 
 that essential resemblance, or identity, goes with superficial like- 
 ness. Imagination is a lively coadjutor of reason at this stage, 
 and the reasoning is as likely to follow the psychological laws 
 of the blending of mental images as to obey any law of logic. 
 Yet, even so, it enormously multiplies the number of possible 
 ways in which man can experiment in his economic life. Imag- 
 
 *The translation is that of the Bohn Library.
 
 46 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 ination, however riotous, corresponds on the whole a little better 
 than conjecture to objective possibility. In other words, experi- 
 ments suggested by imagination and analogy are likely to yield 
 a larger percentage of successes than experiments suggested by 
 mere guesswork. 
 
 Now it is quite in keeping with the nature of things psycho- 
 logical that we discover, at a certain stage in the evolution of 
 savage culture, a system of thought and practice which corre- 
 sponds to the analogy-loving stage in the development of reason. 
 It is known as magic, and long was regarded by ethnologists as 
 all of a piece with ghost worship and primitive supernaturalism 
 in general. Then the suggestion was made, and too well backed 
 up by facts to be dismissed lightly, that magic, instead of being 
 the beginning of supernaturalism, is, in reality, the beginning 
 of naturalism, in a word of a natural philosophy. Ethnologists 
 like Spencer and Gillen in Central Australia, Miss Kingsley in 
 West Africa and W. W. Skeat in the Malay Peninsula, unaware 
 of each other's researches, almost simultaneously arrived at this 
 view, and discussion of it was well summed up by Frazer, in a 
 new edition of The Golden Bough. The fundamental principles 
 of magic, according to Mr. Frazer, can be reduced to two, 
 namely : 
 
 First, that like produces like, or that an effect resembles its cause; 
 and second, that things which have once been in contact but have ceased 
 to be so, continue to act on each other as if the contact still existed. 
 From the first of these principles the savage infers that he can produce 
 any desired effect by merely imitating it; from the second he concludes 
 that he can influence at pleasure and at any distance any person of 
 whom, or anything of which, he possesses a particle. 
 
 When Mr. Frazer wrote this passage the lore of "mana" and its 
 vocabulary ("orenda," "power," "virtue," "it," and so on) hardly 
 existed as a chapter in anthropology. In view of what is known 
 now it will not do to assume that the savage attributes mysterious 
 potency to imitations as such or to contacts (past or present) as 
 such. Presumably he looks upon them all as means only for 
 calling forth or for communicating this or that mana, good or 
 evil, inhering in this or that concrete thing or person. I say 
 "this or that" mana because we may be sure that the savage is 
 no pantheist. He has no abstract notion of a universal power,
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 47 
 
 indwelling in everything and everybody. He knows only specific 
 and various powers. They are migrant, however, and communi- 
 cable : they are contagious. Each mana is something that a thing 
 or a person can "catch" or impart by contact, and sometimes in 
 other ways. 
 
 These notions serve the savage mind in more ways than one. 
 They gather accretions of analogy and convert them into simple 
 classifications. Persons that have the same mana are akin, and 
 things that have the same mana are a kind. Conversely, things 
 and persons that are of a kind or a kin have the same mana, and 
 so have things that are alike. Also things or persons, even 
 things and persons can be made of a kind or a kin by exchanging 
 mana or by partaking of the same mana. This can be done by 
 contact a laying on of hands, for example, or by eating the 
 same food or drinking the same drink or by otherwise sharing 
 something. Also it can now and again be done without physical 
 contact or any sharing of material substance. The savage knows 
 that by getting excited he excites others, and that others by 
 getting excited excite him. He knows that when he mimics 
 others are likely and apt to mimic, and that when they mimic he 
 yields to an impulse to fall into like mimicry. "Power" leaps 
 through distance, from one to another. Often it goes further, 
 from men to animals and from animals to men, a common excite- 
 ment infecting all. Does it even from men and animals infect 
 vegetation and from vegetation infect animals and men? The 
 savage assumes that it does. 
 
 Satisfying the earliest craving for theory and naively practiced 
 as the first art of control over nonhuman realms, magic gives 
 plan and direction to the entire scheme of economy. Examples 
 of its application to fishing and hunting have already been given. 
 Others could be added almost without limit. When an Aleut 
 has wounded but not killed a whale he separates himself from 
 his people for three days and, abstaining from food and drink, 
 snorts in imitation of a dying cetacean. This helps the whale to 
 die. 1 The Galelareese of Halmahera an island west of New 
 Guinea when going out shooting are careful to put a bullet in 
 
 *I. Petroff, Report on the Population, Industries, and Resources of 
 Alaska, p. 154.
 
 48 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 the mouth before dropping it into the gun. By thus imitating the 
 eating of game, success in hunting is rendered certain. 1 A 
 Blackfoot Indian who has set a trap for eagles will not eat 
 rosebuds, because, if he did, when an eagle alighted near the trap 
 the rosebuds in the hunter's stomach would make the bird itch 
 and, instead of swallowing the bait, the eagle would merely sit 
 and scratch itself. 2 When a Malay has baited a trap for croco- 
 diles he is careful in eating his curry to begin by swallowing three 
 lumps of rice successively. This helps the bait to slide easily 
 down the crocodile's throat. 3 Spencer and Gillen have described 
 in minute detail the elaborate ceremonies performed by the 
 Central Australian natives for the purpose of multiplying the 
 witchetty grubs which are an important means of subsistence. 
 Men of the witchetty grub totem build a long narrow structure 
 of branches in imitation of the chrysalis case of the grub. In this 
 bower the men seat themselves and sing of the witchetty in its 
 various stages of development. At length they shuffle out in a 
 squatting posture, singing of the insect emerging from the 
 chrysalis. This insures an abundance of grubs. 4 
 
 Survivals of imitative magic are not quite so easy to identify 
 in later civilizations as are survivals of the economy of luck, 
 yet they are by no means infrequent. Many of the festivals 
 connected with agriculture among the Greeks and the Romans, and 
 similar festivals surviving until a comparatively recent period in 
 parts of Central Europe, are clearly of this nature. In nearly all 
 of these festivals a pantomimic element in the songs and dances 
 and in the processions around or back and forth across the fields 
 is associated with a sacrificial element of later origin. The panto- 
 mimic element may without much hesitation be regarded as a 
 survival of the age of magic. The myth of the burning brands 
 tied to foxes' tails, which we find in the story of Samson, and 
 again in the Fasti of Ovid, 5 is believed by Mannhardt, Frazer and 
 
 1 M. J. van Baarda, "Fabelen, verhalen en overleveringen der Gale- 
 lareezen," in Bijdragen tot de Taal-Landen Volkenkunde. van Neder- 
 landsch Indie, Vol. XLV (1895), p. 502; quoted by Frazer, Golden Bough 
 (second edition), Vol. I, p. 25. 
 ' * G. B. Grinnell, Blackfoot Lodge Tales, pp. 237, 238. 
 
 8 W. W. Skeat, Malay Magic, p. 300. 
 
 4 Spencer and Gillen, The Native Tribes of Central Australia, p. 176. 
 
 8 Vol. IV, p. 681 et seq.
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 49 
 
 others to have originated in the widely spread notion that the 
 fox's tail bears a close resemblance to the ear of wheat. Pro- 
 fessor Gubernatis * quotes a modern Italian folk tale in which a 
 fox is frightened away by chickens, each of which carries in its 
 beak an ear of millet. The fox is told that these ears are all 
 foxes' tails, and he runs. It is probable enough that, in a long- 
 forgotten past, the foxes were let loose to run over the fields, that 
 the magic influence of their tails stimulating fertility might insure 
 an abundant harvest. Presumably, however, the burning brands 
 were thought of not so much as imitative and symbolic of the 
 light and heat of the sun that would be necessary to ripen vegeta- 
 tion, as charged with and releasing the same "power" that the 
 sun gives forth. Such a use of the brand is, indeed, so obviously 
 in keeping with the "general run" of magic practice that one is 
 surprised to find Fowler, commenting upon Ovid, saying: "If 
 the foxes were corn spirits, one does not quite see why they 
 should have brands fastened to their tails." 2 The Roman festi- 
 val of the Parilia consisted very largely of imitative magic. The 
 sheepfold was decked with green boughs and a great wreath was 
 hung on the gate : 
 
 Frondibus et fixis decorentur ovilia ramis, 
 Et tegat ornatas longa corona fores. 3 
 
 This sort of decoration found throughout Europe to the present 
 day at May Day, Midsummer, Harvest and Christmas, is admit- 
 tedly a survival of primitive magical rites to influence ^vegetation. 
 The purification of the Roman sheep by sprinkling was, in like 
 manner, in form imitative and symbolic, in substance an impart- 
 ing of mana. The real purification was accomplished by burning 
 sulphur. 
 
 That many survivals of a magic economy could be found 
 in our own country I have not the slightest doubt. A few prac- 
 tices will occur to almost every one. When John Uri Lloyd in 
 Stringtown on the Pike makes Cupid turn his coat inside out in 
 order to change his luck, he describes a practice that is by no 
 means confined to negroes. Once I witnessed the magical treat- 
 
 1 Zoologvedl Mythology, Vol. II. p. 138. 
 a Roma#i Festivals, p. 78. 
 1 Ovid, Fasti, IV, 737, 738.
 
 50 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 ment of lockjaw, on a Massachusetts farm not distant from my 
 own. A nail driven into the hoof of a horse by a careless black- 
 smith was, when pulled out by the veterinary surgeon, carefully 
 greased by the owner of the horse, wrapped in flannel and kept 
 in a warm place until after the equine obsequies. 1 In out of 
 the way neighborhoods American farmers still believe that hogs 
 should not be killed in the old of the moon, because a waning 
 moon will make the pork shrink in the pot. 
 
 A higher stage of reasoning than the analogical is the deductive 
 and speculative, or dogmatic. The mind has grasped the differ- 
 ence between mere analogy and necessary implication. It has 
 acquired logic. Granted certain premises, the deductive thinker 
 can with a high degree of certainty arrive at necessary conclu- 
 sions. He begins to reconstruct the entire scheme of knowledge. 
 But, enamoured of logical method, he fixes attention almost 
 exclusively upon the successive steps of the reasoning process, 
 often to the entire neglect of the premises upon which the whole 
 superstructure rests. The premises, therefore, of the most pre- 
 tentious system may be a lot of childish beliefs fortified by age 
 and sacredness. 
 
 It is when this stage of reasoning is reached that barbarian 
 man, reconstructing his philosophy of nature, as represented 
 both in magic, and in the belief in ghosts, almost as ancient, 
 begins to people the unseen realms of the sky, of the sea and of 
 the underworld of earth with personalities of supernatural power ; 
 he begins to create the immortal gods. To his anthropomorphic 
 deities he now ascribes the function, of meting out good and 
 evil. His whole welfare he conceives is determined by their atti- 
 tude toward him as an individual or, to a yet greater extent, by 
 their attitude toward the community to which he belongs. Their 
 friendliness must at any cost be secured. They are supposed to 
 have the needs and to be subject to the passions of men. They 
 must therefore be propitiated ; they must be well fed and lavishly 
 praised. If the propitiator has reason to know that his deities 
 have arrived at "the agricultural stage," he gives them corn and 
 wine. If, however, like Cain, he reasons from false premises, he 
 comes to grief, and the blessing falls upon the Abel who has 
 
 'For a like example, see Cooper, The Spy, ch. xi.
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 51 
 
 offered meat. The entire scheme of economy is now transformed. 
 It becomes a sacrificial economy. Communities and individuals 
 prosper in their herding and their agriculture if they are faithful 
 and, above all, generous in their sacrifices. Everything that 
 happens is viewed as a special providence. Droughts, famines 
 and pestilences are punishments, to be averted, not by forestry or 
 quarantine, but by holocausts and prayer. Glorious crops and 
 riotous prosperity are rewards bestowed upon exemplary piety. 
 To recount the survivals of the sacrificial economy in civili- 
 zation would be to catalogue half of the doings of Babylonians 
 and Egyptians, of Greeks and Romans, and of later Western 
 peoples. More significant is it to observe specific survivals that 
 preserve the combination of the magic economy with the sacri- 
 ficial, as well as specific survivals of a later time which show 
 the continuing influence of the sacrificial tradition in communities 
 that have become materialistic and businesslike. Of the former 
 there is probably no better specimen than the festival of the 
 Fordicidia (April 15), one of the oldest sacrificial ceremonies in 
 the Roman religion. It consisted in the slaughter of pregnant 
 cows, one in the Capitol and one in each of the thirty curiae. 
 
 The cows were offered [says Fowler], as all authorities agree, to Tellus, 
 who, as we shall see, may be an indigitation of the same earth power 
 represented by Ceres, Bona Dea, Dea Dia, and other female deities. 
 The unborn calves were torn by attendants of the virgo Vestalis Maxima 
 from the womb of the mother and burnt, and their ashes were kept by 
 the vestals for use at the Parilia a few days later. This was the first 
 ceremony in the year in which the vestals took an active part, and it 
 was the first of a series of acts, all of which are connected with the 
 fruits of the earth, their growth, ripening and harvesting. The object 
 of burning the unborn calves seems to have been to procure the fertility 
 of the corn now growing in the womb of mother earth, to whom the 
 sacrifice was offered. 1 
 
 Here we have a perfect connecting link between the magic 
 economy and the sacrificial. The burning of anything of value 
 would have been sacrifice. The selection of a product and em- 
 blem of fertility, that the corn might abundantly fructify, that 
 was the cult oi mana become magic. 
 
 One almost hesitates to speak of very modern examples of the 
 
 1 Roman Festivals, p. 71.
 
 52 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 sacrificial economy, even in a strictly scientific spirit, lest one 
 should unwittingly wound the religious feelings of people whom 
 he respects. Disclaiming all such intention, however, let me call 
 attention to the almost unparalleled intensity of the belief in 
 Providence which prevailed in New England down to the present 
 generation. Among the earliest acts of the Plymouth colony was 
 the institution of days of fasting and of thanksgiving, which were 
 no such mere holidays as we have become used to in later times. 
 Let no one imagine that these religious institutions of the Pil- 
 grims had any direct bearing upon the problem of weal or woe 
 in a future life. They were religious institutions of a strictly 
 economic order. They were supposed and expected to influence 
 well-being in this present evil world, on the shores of Plymouth 
 Bay, A.D. 1621. No one can read the writings of the Winthrops, 
 Cotton Mather, Increase Mather, Bradford, and Samuel Sewall, 
 without seeing that in the belief of those founders of our Puritan 
 statecraft in New England the people of the colonies were es- 
 pecially chosen of God to play a leading role in the outworking 
 of the divine plan of salvation, and that to such end their 
 economy would be guided and furthered by the Almighty to just 
 the extent necessary to accomplish the divine purpose. Prac- 
 tically every event that happened every change in prosperity, 
 every famine or abounding harvest was explained as essentially 
 miraculous, and as following upon the piety or the wickedness of 
 the colonists, rather than upon their shrewdness, their energy or 
 their thrift. The title of Edward Johnson's famous treatise, 
 The Wonder-Working Providence of Zion's Saviour in New* 
 England, perfectly expresses the habitual attitude of the early 
 New England mind. 
 
 Is that attitude entirely a phenomenon of the past? Surely 
 no one will venture to say so. The public fasting and prayer 
 that were observed in the Middle West late in the nineteenth 
 century when locusts were moving in devastating march across 
 the great grain belt, might be repeated any day, and generations 
 will pass before the best people will cease to believe and to say 
 that the locusts disappeared immediately after and in consequence 
 of those acts of worship.
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 53 
 
 Let me now recall my main contention that in any age the 
 system of economy then prevailing is a function not merely of 
 the relation of an individual to a purely physical environment, 
 but rather of the relation subsisting between a physical environ- 
 ment and a plural number of coexisting and resembling indi- 
 viduals, sub-social or social in their relations to one another. 
 Organic economy, I showed, was thus to a great extent a func- 
 tion of segregation that is to say, of certain groupings of 
 resembling organisms in one given place or region. Instinctive 
 economy, in like manner, I showed was largely a function of 
 gregarious relations among the lower animals. In a still higher 
 degree, it is certain, the luck economy, the magic economy and the 
 sacrificial economy, constituting the first three stages of the 
 rational economy of man, are functionally determined by the 
 social relations of men to one another in their slowly developing 
 communities. These three economies may be brought under the 
 inclusive term, Ceremonial Economy. In one and all the specific 
 conduct which is expected to bring economic well-being is the 
 performance of a ceremonial act. Labor to some extent of course 
 is necessary. Cooperation and the division of labor to some 
 extent may be found, but these purely practical and materialistic 
 factors in and of themselves would be absolutely unavailing, in 
 the belief of primitive or of barbarian man. Far more thought 
 does he bestow upon the exact performance of one or another 
 rite than upon the exact performance of his labor. Far more 
 time and wealth does he bestow upon sacrifice than upon the 
 accumulation of a fund of capital. 
 
 But ceremony, it is quite unnecessary to argue, is purely a 
 social phenomenon. It is developed by imitation and handed on 
 by tradition. Equally unnecessary is it to argue that the suc- 
 cessive developments of reason, from the conjectural stage, 
 which goes with and produces the luck economy, through the 
 imaginative and analogy-loving stage, which produces the magic 
 economy, into the deductive stage, which produces the sacrificial 
 economy, are also a product of social relations and could nowise 
 be accounted for by the direct relationship of the individual to 
 his physical environment. Reasoning presupposes conceptual
 
 54 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 thinking, and conceptual thinking presupposes language. 1 Cere- 
 monial economy is, then, from first to last, a function of the social 
 relation. 
 
 Now at length I come to a consideration of those stages of 
 economic evolution to which, and to which only, the modern 
 science of economics can be said to have an explanatory rela- 
 tion. It is not until social phenomena have become complicated 
 in a high degree that the phenomena which admit of explanation 
 in terms of modern economic concepts come into existence. The 
 phenomena of organic economy and of instinctive economy can 
 be and must be explained in terms of the useful potentialities of 
 the environment, complicated by segregation, grouping, and the 
 pluralistic behavior of gregariousness. The phenomena of the 
 first three stages of rational economy must be explained in terms 
 of the same facts, further complicated by that developing reason 
 which will presently evolve notions of subjective utility and of 
 value. These notions appear at the dawn of civilization or pos- 
 sibly just before. They certainly do not exist at a much earlier 
 time. The luck economy is roughly coincident with that stage of 
 evolution which I have elsewhere called anthropogenic associa- 
 tion. 2 Magic economy is roughly coincident with the earlier half 
 of ethnogenic association. Sacrificial economy is roughly coinci- 
 dent with the later half of ethnogenic association. Only with 
 demogenic or civic association does ceremonial economy in all its 
 forms slowly begin to give place to the business economy of the 
 modern man, the subject-matter of the studies of the political 
 economist. 
 
 Coincident with the beginning of this change is the attainment 
 of inductive reasoning which, thenceforth, is a potent factor in 
 further change. In the third stage of reasoning, as we have 
 seen, man has become logical. No longer satisfied with mere 
 analogy, much less with conjecture, he reasons deductively from 
 
 1 A clear perception of this truth has led Payne, in his admirable History 
 of the New World Called America, to break in upon his clear exposition 
 of the economic history of the civilizations of Mexico and Peru, and to 
 devote a large part of his second volume to an account of the nature 
 and evolution of the American languages. 
 
 ' Principles of Sociology.
 
 THE ECONOMIC AGES 55 
 
 accepted premises to "necessary" conclusions. The fatal weak- 
 ness of his procedure lies in the usual indifference of his mind 
 to the validity of his premises. He has not yet learned to subject 
 them to a searching criticism, and he does not learn to do so 
 until, little by little, his mind becomes in a measure inductive. 
 Now induction, strange as it may seem, is in a certain sense a 
 return to analogy. Systematic induction begins with observing 
 the resemblances of things that are alike and the differences of 
 things that are unlike, and, on the basis of resemblances and dif- 
 ferences, sorting things into classes. Strictly speaking, the great 
 difference between the analogical reasoner and the inductive 
 reasoner is the difference between a thorough, exact worker and 
 a superficial, inexact worker. Deductive reasoning, in like man- 
 ner, is a development of the conjectural or guesswork state of 
 mind. It is the careful drawing out by exact logical steps of 
 whatever may be contained in a premise taken for granted that 
 is, in nine cases out of ten, conjectured. A few pages back I 
 gave qualified assent to Frazer's proposition that magic was the 
 beginning of a natural philosophy. I may now add that belief 
 in luck was just as truly the beginning of supernaturalism. The 
 doctrine of magic was the product of minds reasoning by analogy 
 and capable, in course of time, of developing into minds inductive 
 and scientific. Belief in luck, in like manner, was the product of 
 minds reasoning conjecturally, and sure in time to develop into 
 speculative philosophers and dogmatists. 
 
 Only when the human mind had become to some extent sys- 
 tematically inductive and critically observant of premises could 
 the real relations of cause and effect in nature be discovered ; and 
 only then could man understand that his prosperity must depend 
 chiefly upon his systematic industry, his invention, his skillful 
 organization of association in short, upon the development of 
 his business habits, rather than of his ceremonial punctiliousness. 
 Then, and only then, could begin the later economic ages, namely : 
 the age of Slave Economy, or of the systematic exploitation of 
 servile labor; the age of Trade Economy, or of the exploitation of 
 situation ; and the age of Capitalistic Economy, or of the ex- 
 ploitation of the powers of nature. 
 
 Such a change in man's habits of reasoning probably could not
 
 56 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 have occurred apart from the commingling of kinsmen and 
 strangers, of native born and foreign born, which engendered a 
 dijuos ( a people) in distinction from an Wvos (a wide kindred). 
 Demogenic association brought about comparisons of traditions, 
 and of experiences, in the course of which long accepted beliefs 
 were for the first time questioned. From such a shock dogmatism 
 could not wholly recover. New categories of things and of 
 thoughts were inductively formed. 
 
 Reacting upon one another and together reacting upon tra- 
 ditional culture, demogenic association and inductive thinking 
 converted an ethnic society into a civil social order, and created 
 civilization. Successive steps of the process can be made out. 
 The consorting of ethnically heterogeneous elements assimilates 
 practices; incidental discussion correlates ideas. Consorting and 
 discussion assimilate standards of living, and thereby standardize 
 consumption. A standardized consumption and a verified knowl- 
 edge that accumulates and permeates, further assimilate. Sur- 
 vivals of the luck, the magic, and the sacrificial economies are 
 resistant to attrition, but they lose prestige.
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 
 THE QUALITY OF CIVILIZATION 
 
 ACCORDING to varying ratios in which the factors of civiliza- 
 tion just now named and others are combined, civilization de- 
 velops varying qualities. Process and product are disclosed by 
 the earliest civilizations and, as well and on a larger scale, by 
 the turbulent civilization of our own time. Having dwelt so 
 long upon primitive thoughts and doings I shall now, partly for 
 change of scene, and partly for perspective, take many of my 
 facts from American life. . 
 
 From early times men have seen a significant association be- 
 tween ethnic and social solidarity. They have associated the 
 jostling of ill-assorted elements in urban multitudes with a relative 
 failure of collective achievement. Both Greek and Roman 
 writers turned this popular wisdom to literary and to philosoph- 
 ical account. In a well-known writing, addressed to his mother 
 Helvia, Seneca, prime minister to the Emperor Nero, has de- 
 scribed the social population of Rome and incidentally has be- 
 trayed his own personal estimate of the civilization which he 
 loyally, if sometimes discreetly, served. 
 
 Behold this multitude [he exclaims] to which the habitations of a city 
 scarce suffice! It is mainly composed of people not born at Rome. 
 From country towns, from colonies, from the whole wide world, they 
 flow hither as a river. Some are spurred by ambition, others come to 
 fulfil public functions. Debauchees seek here a place where every vice 
 may be indulged. Some among us have come to satisfy their taste 
 for letters and the arts, others their craving for spectacular shows. People 
 flock hither in the wake of friends, to display their talents on a wider 
 stage. Some are here to sell their beauty, others to sell their eloquence. 
 In short, the human race foregathers here, in a city where virtues and 
 vices alike are paid at higher rates than elsewhere in the world. 1 
 
 The traits of Roman civilization are every day discovered in the 
 life of modern nations a circumstance explainable in part by the 
 
 1 Seneca, Consolation? ad Helviam, 6. 
 
 57
 
 58 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 facts, in part by the unconcealed historical scholarship of our 
 public men and predictions are freely made that America, in 
 particular, fs destined to repeat the story of imperial decline and 
 fall. Contrasting with this light readiness to interpret ourselves 
 in terms of Roman experience, is our silent admission that we are 
 not reproducing civilizations to which Rome, even as their con- 
 queror, paid the tribute of respect. 
 
 No historian has proclaimed resemblance between any modern 
 people and the creators of a civilization which for four thou- 
 sands years endured in the Valley of the Nile. Splendid and 
 imperishable, Egypt stands supreme and apart. Protected by 
 desert frontiers from recurrent invasion, and from immigration 
 on the great scale, her people, more homogeneous than any other 
 considerable population of which we have record, developed a 
 community of mind which enabled them without the harsher fea- 
 tures of despotism to combine their efforts in an amazing col- 
 lective efficiency. Intellectual and economic power, religious and 
 artistic sincerity, expressing themselves through the perfect co- 
 operation of men who spontaneously felt alike and thought alike, 
 produced an unrivaled unity and stability which stamped the 
 quality of incomparable dignity upon Egyptian civilization. 
 
 There is no other land like Egypt, and so it has happened that 
 regions bountiful enough to support dense populations have 
 attracted a multitude of ill-assorted elements. And with what 
 result? The confusion of tongues at Babylon was typical of the 
 incapacity of mixed multitudes for great cooperation, except as 
 they have been organized by external authority, or have them- 
 selves evolved the imperator. If their territory has been 
 exposed to invasion, they have fallen under the yoke of a con- 
 queror, or war has hammered them into a more or less mechan- 
 ical cohesion. In either case, they have developed a militaristic 
 empire which commonly has displayed the qualities of power and 
 splendor, but at the cost of freedom. 
 
 In regions not favorable to large military operations, like the 
 Aegean Islands, or the diversified coasts of mainland Greece, 
 mixed populations, maintaining their local liberties, have created 
 civilizations marked by intellectual expansion, but riot safe- 
 guarded by political cohesion. Too frail to hold their own in
 
 THE QUALITY OF CIVILIZATION 59 
 
 the struggle for existence, they have left their treasures of 
 thought and art a heritage to ruder but sturdier folk. 
 
 So in contrast to the strong but not inhumanly despotic, the 
 vigorously creative but not ideally free civilization of homoge- 
 neous Egypt, two original and distinct types of civilization appear 
 to have been created in the early days by mixed populations ; the 
 one harshly despotic but effective, the product of incessant war; 
 the other free and differentiated, intellectually and morally dy- 
 namic, but unstable, the product of an exuberant community life 
 under conditions of local security. 
 
 Rome, militaristic for purposes of expansion chiefly, and not 
 compelled to fight incessantly for her life with enemies nearly as 
 strong as herself, created a civilization of compromise. Imperially 
 strong, she often respected and safeguarded the local liberties of 
 her component parts, and usually protected the personal liberties 
 of her citizens. Under these conditions an individualism arose 
 which submitted itself at least conventionally to the imperial will, 
 but displayed little sense of obligation to the collective welfare. 
 It is the compromise civilization of Rome which survives in our 
 world today. 
 
 The resources of a new continent have drawn to America a 
 population as variegated as that which crowded the Euphrates 
 valley and more miscellaneous than that by the Tiber. Pro- 
 tected by ocean barriers against military invasion, and not com- 
 pelled, as Rome was, to conquer room for free expansion, the 
 American population has been working out an experiment largely 
 new. With a minimum of foreign war, and without militarism, 
 it has created a more than imperial political solidarity with rela- 
 tively little restraint until now of local or personal liberty. It 
 has created, too, an individual enterprise without parallel, but it 
 has yet to achieve the diversified and finer results of collective 
 efficiency. 
 
 For sectarian liberty and local independence the colonists of 
 New England sacrificed most other things that men have cared 
 for. In extreme contrast, it was not community life of any 
 kind, but an untrammeled individualism that fixed the ideas and 
 formed the habits of pioneer adventurers who conquered the wil- 
 derness beyond the Appalachian ranges and traversed the plains
 
 60 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 of the West. And in those environments for two generations the 
 opportunities for individual achievement were limitless and in- 
 toxicating. It is therefore not strange that men of obscure 
 origin have wielded in America a power greater than that of 
 old-world kings, not occasionally, as from time to time has hap- 
 pened in other lands, but in so many hundreds of instances that 
 no' one can recall them all. By sheer individual effort and indi- 
 vidually controlled organization, Americans have created in less 
 than three hundred years the greatest aggregation ever seen, of 
 industry and graft, of capital and wreckage, of toil and luxury, 
 of comfort and misery, of sanctification and crime. 
 
 In the domain of collective achievement we have attained no 
 corresponding eminence, although we have accomplished much 
 that has been worth while. On the executive side our central 
 government has been strong and our state governments have been 
 vigorous, because they have been products of a party system built 
 up by machine methods under boss leadership, which always, in 
 the last resort, is the unifying political agency in mixed popula- 
 tions. In matters of administrative detail, it is generally ac- 
 knowledged, we have been wasteful and incompetent, while on 
 the legislative side of political endeavor, we have conspicuously 
 shown the ineffectiveness of unlike-minded men in cooperative 
 undertakings. Our legislation has been discontinuous and un- 
 coordinated, a product largely of shameless bargaining among 
 conflicting interests. 
 
 And indisputably we have not by any happy combination of 
 public activity with individual enterprise achieved certain results 
 of collective effort which are commonly held to be distinctive of 
 genuine, not to say high, civilization. We have not effectively 
 protected life against criminal attack or against industrial acci- 
 dent, certainly not in the measure which experiment has shown 
 to be attainable. We have not as a general thing made our 
 towns safe against the elemental risk of fire, or beautiful to look 
 upon, or satisfying to the mind. 
 
 We have, however, developed national feeling and patriotism. 
 Notwithstanding the heterogeneity of our population, we ac- 
 knowledge a certain solidarity of sentiment, and it appears to be
 
 THE QUALITY OF CIVILIZATION 61 
 
 fortified and possibly is more or less guided by an increasing 
 solidarity of opinion. 
 
 We have been in the habit of attributing this measure of agree- 
 ment to example and suggestion. We have thought of it as both 
 an unconscious influence and a conscious teaching proceeding 
 from a hitherto dominant Anglo-Saxon stock. We explain so 
 much solidarity of mind and heart as now prevails as a product 
 largely of assimilation, and our faith in the American future rests 
 chiefly in our ability further to assimilate the differing minds 
 and wills of our citizens of foreign birth. 
 
 It is worth while, therefore, to ask what assimilative forces 
 have chiefly been effective so far in American life, and are likely 
 further to strengthen such community of spirit as may yet give 
 to our civilization the qualities of unity, effectiveness, and dignity, 
 without restraint of freedom. 
 
 First among these forces I think we must name a standardized 
 consumption. The immigrant discards the costume of his native 
 land and adopts American clothing. With it he demands for his 
 house and table the products that "everybody" has. This phrase 
 almost literally describes the economic satisfactions of our well- 
 to-do population. We have only to call to mind such articles of 
 universal use as the carpet or rug, wall-paper, table linen, piano 
 or phonograph, expensive clothing and jewelry, and to reflect 
 upon the aggregate investment in such costly comforts as the 
 automobile, by classes that were supposed to be unable to 
 afford them, to realize how tremendous has become the stand- 
 ardizing influence of example and imitation in this field of eco- 
 nomic consumption. As consumers of wealth we exhibit mental 
 and moral solidarity. We want the same things. We have the 
 same tastes. So far as this part at least of our life is concerned 
 we have the basis and the fact of a highly general consciousness 
 of kind. 
 
 On this fact rests the pertinent rejoinder to social theories 
 which allege that neither the consciousness of kind itself nor any 
 underlying community of thought and feeling, can henceforth be 
 the ground of social solidarity or the characteristic phenomenon 
 of the social mind. The economic operations of modern times are
 
 62 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 carried on through specialization, and the industrial system, as we 
 frankly recognize, is more and more becoming a correlation of 
 differences in a working organization. Therefore, it is contended 
 for example by Emile Durkheim that it is only the primitive 
 undifferentiated group that is held together by a consciousness of 
 kind. The modern complex group is an economic fact, and the 
 social consciousness, as Cooley explains it, is the recog- 
 nition quite as much of complementary differences as of mental 
 and moral similarities. 
 
 What actually has happened, however, in the economic evolu- 
 tion of modern populations has been, on the side of production a 
 marvelous differentiation and development of the division of 
 labor and, on the side of consumption, an equally marvelous 
 standardizing and assimilation. In the primitive community and 
 in the undeveloped rural community now, every family produces 
 many things, and each individual is to some extent a Jack-of-all- 
 trades. At the same time each individual as a consumer asserts 
 his individuality. He wears his hair long or short, according to 
 his whim, and never tires of declaiming against the manners and 
 the morals of city folk who must follow fashion at any cost. In 
 the urban community, by contrast, consumption is ruled by the 
 mode, while in the productive realm the Jack-of -all-trades and 
 master of none is ever out of a job. 
 
 Moreover, if our accepted economic philosophy is sound, it is 
 because of the standardization of consumption that we are en- 
 abled continually to differentiate the processes of production, and 
 to specialize abilities. For while, as Adam Smith demonstrated, 
 the division of labor is limited by the extent of the market, the 
 extent of the market, as perhaps Smith did not quite so clearly 
 see, is ultimately determined by the standardization of con- 
 sumption. 
 
 Therefore it seems a safe assumption that the characteristic 
 economic evolution of modern times, while producing differen- 
 tiated ability as an incident of production, is also inevitably pro- 
 ducing a remarkable uniformity of mind and habit in respect of 
 consumption, and therefore an ever-increasing consciousness of 
 kind to balance and control the consciousness of difference. 
 
 A second assimilating force is the scientific view of nature,
 
 THE QUALITY OF CIVILIZATION 63 
 
 which all mankind is being forced to adopt because of our modern 
 methods of getting a living. 
 
 For ten thousand years or more, as was shown, the human 
 race lived by belief; it will live henceforth by knowledge. Its 
 belief has been nine-tenths credulity, to one part of reasonable 
 and sustaining faith in the possibilities of life. It has believed in 
 luck and magic, in miracle and providential aid. By luck it has 
 subsisted on fish and game ; by magic it has sustained the fertility 
 of its fields ; by miracle and providential aid it has harvested its 
 crops and brought its ships to port. 
 
 The religions of luck and miracle have been a multitude of 
 faiths that no man could number. Each has united a band, a sect, 
 or a greater body of devotees, but each of these bodies has dis- 
 trusted and anathematized all others. And so long as religious 
 differences have played a vital part in life, thoroughgoing assim- 
 ilation and a universal consciousness of kind have been impossible. 
 
 But henceforth, in our own land at least, the people will not 
 get their bread by luck, nor yet by miracle. Not only our manu- 
 facturing industries and our mining operations, but also our 
 commerce and our agriculture, rest today firmly and broadly upon 
 the scientific interpretation of nature. On every farm the boy 
 learns something of chemistry and of biology, as in every shop 
 he learns something of mechanics, of thermodynamics, and of 
 electricity. And so it is coming about that millions of human 
 beings can no longer be mentally diverse in quite the same old 
 fashion. They can no longer swear by quite so many strange and 
 jealous gods. They must think and they will think the same 
 thoughts. They must view nature in the same way, and look 
 forth upon life from the same point of observation, not because 
 they have been converted by any proselyter, but because only so, 
 under modern conditions, can they obtain their daily bread. 
 
 It may be optimistic to say, but probably it is true, that democ- 
 racy, crude as it is and disappointing, is subtly an assimilating 
 influence, as it is blatantly a leveling force. 
 
 Perhaps the most remarkable and probably the most hopeful 
 development in present day political life is an increasing attention 
 to things, over against an undue attention to persons. Repre- 
 sentative government has been, all in all, the best kind of
 
 64 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 government that men have been able to get results by, and it 
 remains indispensable, even where we have also much direct 
 democracy. No one claims perfection for representation, how- 
 ever, and its chief shortcoming is betrayed by an unfortunate 
 psychological reaction. It permits men indolently to give over 
 to delegated agents the consideration of concrete questions of 
 public policy with the result, all too apparent, that political ac- 
 tivity is resolved into a struggle over candidates while we neglect 
 to grapple earnestly with questions. Direct democracy, in con- 
 trast, breaks down when it attempts to take over all legislative and 
 administrative functions ; yet it has merits, chief of which is its 
 educative efficacy. It stimulates the citizen to think, with such 
 intellectual power as he possesses, upon questions, the issues 
 themselves. It was this virtue that made the New England town 
 meeting the greatest school of political science and art that has 
 existed among men. Through experiments in direct democracy, 
 some of which work out well while many go wrong, entire peoples 
 are learning now in a large way as the New England folk gener- 
 ations ago in a small way learned to think about things as well as 
 to care about candidates ; and this thinking assimilates. 
 
 If it be contended that the quality of a civilization is most 
 affected by the physical vigor and the intellectual power of the 
 population concerned, it will be admitted, I suppose, that assimi- 
 lation is the factor significant in next degree. Assimilation, like 
 indifferent nature mechanically, and like the conscious intelligence 
 of man creatively, selects and combines. It rejects attitudes and 
 habits that do not "fit in" ; it modifies and combines those that do 
 fit in. So it creates a type, as imitation creates a style ; and style 
 and type are things of quality. The most conscious selection of 
 color values by a painter, of notes and bars by a composer, does 
 not more surely produce distinction (or vulgarity) than a select- 
 ing and converting assimilation produces a quality of behavior. 
 
 Much depends upon the amount of assimilative work to be 
 done. A population may be too heterogeneous to be civilized 
 (appreciably) by assimilation (or otherwise) until natural se- 
 lection has weeded out unassimilable elements. What is to hap- 
 pen in the Americas, North and South, prudent prophets do not 
 prophesy too confidently. The confusion of tongues has not
 
 THE QUALITY OF CIVILIZATION 65 
 
 abated in any nation of these continents, and in the United States 
 (whatever is happening elsewhere) the clamor of conflicting 
 purposes does not suBside. We are reckless and unprepared, but 
 noisily determined to be redoubtable. We are self-indulgent and 
 lawless, but resolved to make ourselves good by law. We are 
 sentimental and irresponsible, but set on efficiency. We buy 
 editions, but do not diligently read. We live "handsomely," but 
 not carefully, nor always self-respectingly. While these condi- 
 tions prevail our civilization cannot "settle"; it cannot clarify; 
 and until it runs more limpid than now it cannot temper zeal with 
 dignity, or chasten power with graciousness.
 
 CHAPTER V 
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 
 
 THERE may have been theories of history before The Book of 
 the Dead was compiled. The title itself of that cheerful Nilitic 
 document suggests that there were. Perhaps there will be 
 theories of history after the Adams family has been forgotten, 
 although this is more doubtful. That there will be comprehensive 
 (and plausible) philosophies of history after the intellectual re- 
 mains of Friedrich Hegel and Karl Marx have been cremated, is 
 highly probable. 
 
 Speculation is here piquant and more or less alluring, but 
 profitless. Turning, therefore, to the record of occurrence, one 
 remarks that the historical theories of history are nearly as 
 numerous as historians. Paradoxically, however, their histor- 
 icity lies almost wholly in the circumstance that they are facts 
 of record. So far as intellectual content goes they are phil- 
 osophy rather than history, and the outstanding ones have been 
 evolved by philosophers, not brought forth by historians. The 
 reason, of course, is simple. History primarily is factual de- 
 tail, and altogether concrete. Secondarily it ventures, timor- 
 ously, upon generalization. It depicts "situations," "general as- 
 pects," and "trends." In so doing it becomes, in modest measure, 
 philosophy or (sadly or gladly) sociology! 
 
 No fault can be found, therefore, with sociologists of the 
 shameless sort if, to conserve energy, they generalize further and 
 examine the theories of history not individually, in every instance, 
 but usually by kinds or types. 
 
 From Plato to Comte and from Comte to the Adams brothers 
 one encounters five distinct type groups of theories of history. 
 
 The first group comprises the predestinational philosophies of 
 the metaphysicians, theological and other. In the second group 
 fall the philosophies of social self-determination. Plato's view, 
 
 66
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 67 
 
 by his own account of it, was a hybrid. In part the gods arrange 
 human affairs, in part men freely plan and freely achieve. A 
 third group of interpretations goes back to geographical or "en- 
 vironmental" influence. The writings of Montesquieu remain 
 the classical example, but the painstaking researches of present- 
 day workers like Ellen C. Semple and Ellsworth Huntington are 
 building a more substantial structure. 
 
 Theories of the fourth group explain history in terms of 
 heritage (not heredity). Heritage is the total product (and 
 by-product) of human activity hitherto which we now enjoy. It 
 includes our acquired habits (in distinction from our original 
 instinctive nature), our arts, our knowledge and our property. 
 Piling up and distributing heritage, history cuts its own tortuous 
 channel, as a river does when it scours mud and gravel from one 
 bank to contribute it to the other. In their several and unlike ways 
 Comte, Buckle and Karl Marx interpret history in terms of 
 heritage. Comte sees mankind moving from a theological through 
 a metaphysical into a positive or scientific intellectual habit. 
 Buckle corrects naive resolutions of history into geography and 
 climate by calling in a secondary or cultural environment, ante- 
 cedent or contemporaneous. The Marxian "materialistic" 
 interpretation, notwithstanding the mistaken and extravagant 
 claims that have been made for it, is materialistic in a moral 
 sense of the word only. It is an attempt to account for all that 
 has happened or can happen to socially organized mankind by the 
 aggregation and functioning of property. 
 
 The working hypotheses that make up our fifth, and for the 
 time being last, group of philosophies of history, are modern. 
 They are chapters out of the book of cosmic dynamics. They 
 account for the stream of human experience as the solar system 
 or a thunder storm is accounted for, as a case of equilibration. 
 Herbert Spencer and Brooks Adams, leaving nothing to imagina- 
 tion, resolve it into a degradation of physical energy. Individual 
 biologists and bio-anthropologists, taking the degradation of 
 energy for granted, see history as heredity and natural selection. 
 Taking physics and biology both for granted, I am writing these 
 pages to intimate, and perhaps gently to argue, that human 
 history is a psychological, or behavioristic, equilibration.
 
 68 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 The premise merely, or datum, from which this intimation 
 and this argument must proceed is not new. Modern fashion 
 denies it and sneers at it. The premise is that men are not born 
 equal, and from the beginning of time never have been. Or, in 
 the language of dynamics, it is that just as heat energy is not 
 uniformly distributed in space, and therefore radiates from mole- 
 cules in lively motion upon molecules in sluggish motion ; and just 
 as physiological vitality is not uniformly distributed among stocks 
 and races, and therefore some stocks are either driven to the wall 
 or are kept alive by such as bear the infirmities of the weak ; so 
 behavioristic reaction to stimulation, whether it is an instinctive 
 or a rational reaction, impulsive or forecasting, is more alert and 
 more tireless, more ranging and more varied, more modifiable 
 and more adaptive, better correlated and better coordinated on 
 the part of some aggregations of men than it is on the part of 
 other aggregations; and, therefore, practical activity spills over 
 from alert populations, alert component groups and alert con- 
 stituent classes, upon sluggish populations, sluggish component 
 groups and sluggish classes. When the overflow began history 
 began, when it ceases history will end. 
 
 Whether a theory exploitive of this premise will prove to be, 
 as pure science, more illuminating or more clarifying than other 
 theories of history have been, I am not sure ; I hope it may. But 
 if it is true, or as far as it is true, it has a pragmatic value that 
 should obtain for it a patient hearing. The whole world at 
 present is intellectually muddled and morally bedevilled. It is 
 trying to reconstruct society upon a hypothetical equality of all 
 mankind. If it succeeds, it will destroy historic achievement 
 from the beginning, and will send mankind to perdition. 
 
 My venture, therefore, is an adventure; but before I and such 
 as will go with me set forth upon it let us linger self -indulgently 
 a moment (for it is a pleasurable thing to do) upon history in its 
 concreteness, as it appeals to imagination and our love of mere 
 narration. 
 
 History is a scenario and a play, a swiftly moving film and a 
 drama in which every human passion contends with every other, 
 brutally or intellectually, upon the stage of life. More than this,
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 69 
 
 history is also a prodigious creative effort, tremendous beyond our 
 power to conceive it, and an achievement overwhelming to our 
 finite ability to appraise. And always, whether as scenario or as 
 play or yet as achievement, history is a story, holding in every 
 generation the interest of childhood and of age. 
 
 Like all good stories it begins in medias res, that is to say, 
 when men have lived long enough and have learned enough to 
 leave written records of their doings. It begins, as far as our 
 present knowledge goes, in Egypt and in Sumer. 
 
 But also, like all good stories, when history has introduced 
 its characters it goes back, and more or less accounts for them, 
 telling us something of their previous occupations and experi- 
 ences, their interests, their associations and peregrinations, and 
 how they happened to arrive in the situation where we have 
 encountered them. This chapter in the story of history is now- 
 a-days called prehistory, and because we have no written records 
 to extract it from, it is essentially a film of scenes rather than a 
 play, in the truer sense of the word. The materials for it have 
 .been obtained from geology and biology, anthropology and 
 archaeology. 
 
 As the reel begins to move we see sluggish rivers, and tropical 
 trees alive with monkeys that have learned how to throw things 
 and so, from safe distance, to beat off dangerous enemies that 
 would make short work of them in the close-up fighting of bodily 
 contact. Then we see apes, bigger and possibly more clever than 
 the gorillas and chimpanzees that survive in our menageries. 
 They can stand almost erect and fight with clubs as well as throw 
 stones. They can build of sticks rough habitations for their young 
 and are not afraid to shuffle about on the ground. Their bones 
 are found all the way from Farther India to Southwestern 
 Europe. Presently, in tertiary Java, we see Pithecanthropus 
 Erectus, a brute so like an ape and yet so like a man that com- 
 parative anatomists hesitate to say for certain whether he is a 
 primate only or truly homo sapiens. In any case he is a "link," 
 no longer "missing," between man and his progenitors, and so 
 we leave him. 
 
 Now on the screen come bones only bones but they stimulate
 
 70 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 imagination. The Heidelberg jaw, the Piltdown skull, the 
 Neanderthal skull these are remains of man. Of this there is 
 no doubt, and as a series they exhibit our kind progressively los- 
 ing simian traits and, throughout one hundred thousand years 
 after another, becoming the human species to which we ourselves 
 belong. 
 
 From this point on we see things that early man makes, his 
 artifacts: weapons, tools and utensils, and the places where he 
 makes them and leaves them. At first, with his mate and chil- 
 dren, his sisters and brothers, and their mates and children, he 
 lives in the woods, along river margins, as numerous little sav- 
 age hordes of the lowest type live today in! the Andaman 
 Islands, in tropical Africa and in Brazil ; or they wander off in 
 the bush, as Australians and Bushmen do. They hunt and fish 
 and build habitations of boughs not much better than the gorilla's. 
 Arrowheads and spearheads they make by roughly chipping 
 flints. They weave mats of shredded bark and rude baskets of 
 osiers and reeds. 
 
 They are widely dispersed, some of them in far northern 
 parts of Asia and of Europe. With subtropical animals they 
 made their way there, we guess, in the mild weather of inter- 
 glacial time. Now the ice of a new glaciation creeping south- 
 ward overtakes them. They retreat before it. Multitudes of 
 them perish. Only the hardy and the resourceful survive. In 
 the great caverns of Southern Europe they find shelter. There 
 through thousands of years they dwell, learning to flake by pres- 
 sure the flints that before they chipped. They make axes and 
 hammers of stone, awls and needles of bone. They clothe them- 
 selves with skins. They carve ivory. They learn to draw and 
 to paint and cover the walls of their caves with realistic (and 
 beautiful) pictures of the cave bear, the sabre-toothed tiger and 
 the mastodon which they dread, and of the reindeer on which 
 they subsist. These are the greatest of the paleolithic people, the 
 remarkable men of the Old Stone Age. 
 
 Elsewhere, in Northern Africa and in Southwestern Asia, 
 paleolithic men become neolithic. They grind and polish their 
 stone implements. Experimenting with clay they fashion pottery
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 71 
 
 on which they work geometrical designs, possibly symbolic, by 
 incising lines into which they rub gypsum. Generations pass. 
 By hand labor they till patches Of ground in which they have 
 planted seeds or roots. They cut trees into logs and fashion logs 
 into posts, piles, beams and boards. They build houses to dwell 
 in, and platforms, supported by posts driven into the ground or 
 by piles driven in water, on which they enact ceremonies and 
 afterwards build houses. They make canoes and boats. Again 
 generations pass. On the grass-lands of Africa and Arabia, 
 of Western Asia and Eastern Europe, we see restless groups of 
 kinsmen caring for herds of goats and sheep and for larger herds 
 of cattle. In the oases of Africa and of Arabia and of Central 
 Asia east of the Caspian Sea we see villages built of various 
 materials, wood and stone and sunbaked clay. We see shelters for 
 cattle, ditches and moats filled with water, cisterns of water and 
 wells, storehouses of grain, fires carefully kept alive, altars and 
 secret places where ceremonies are observed. 
 
 More generations come and go. Throughout Northern Africa, 
 throughout Central and Southern Asia, throughout Central and 
 Southern Europe, men are living in villages and in little towns. 
 These are strung' like beads along the Euphrates and the Nile. 
 Against druidic backgrounds of ancient oaks and pines they hide 
 in quiet valleys among the foot-hills of mountain ranges. With 
 their backs to walls of rock they defy the storms of wind-swept 
 uplands. On platforms supported by piles, they are built above 
 the waters of Swiss and Italian lakes; or, on dry land, with 
 moats around them terramare they strangely imitate the lake 
 constructions. In all of these various situations the inhabitants 
 keep pigs and goats and cattle, and raise crops. A division of 
 status and of work is seen. The people of a community are no 
 longer in every instance of one kindred. Often the "place" is 
 in fact not one village but two adjacent villages. In the superior 
 one live kinsmen, who possess and rule the land round about. In 
 the lowlier one live "aliens," a miscellaneous assemblage of "kin 
 wrecked" folk, ruined by war or driven forth as offenders from 
 the clans of their birth. They have been taken in. They are 
 harbored and defended and allotted land to use on condition that
 
 72 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 they render prescribed services. These are the "village com- 
 munities" that economic historians used to picture as "free," 
 idyllic, communistic democracies! 
 
 Near every settlement is a burial place, a "long barrow" or a 
 "round barrow" of earth, or, now and then, a hollow cairn built 
 of stones, perhaps in imitation of the caves where paleolithic dead 
 were laid : two unhewn shafts supporting a heavy lintel above 
 are the portal. Here and there also, at intervals from the Persian 
 Gulf to Southwestern England, are more impressive megalithic 
 monuments : avenues of giant shafts or great circular enclosures 
 like Stonehenge. Presumably they have to do with festival pro- 
 cessions and athletic events. 1 
 
 With one more scene the film of prehistory ends. In moun- 
 tain gulches men dig copper, and elsewhere tin. A glare against 
 the sky by night betrays the places where they mix and smelt 
 them, in rude crucibles of clay. They are making bronze ! 
 
 The human species now has overspread the earth, and racial 
 varieties of it, both major and minor, are identified with broad 
 geographical habitats. An Australian-African major division is 
 black, kinky-haired, prognathic and usually dolichocephalic. An 
 Asian- American major division is yellow in Asia and copper- 
 hued in America, straight-haired and usually brachycephalic. A 
 European-Polynesian major division is white in Europe and in 
 Northern Asia, including Northern Japan, and brown in North- 
 ern Africa, in Southern Asia and in the South Pacific islands ; it 
 is usually wavy-haired and orthognathic, but in skull shape it is 
 anything possible, dolichocephalic, mesocephalic or brachycephalic. 
 
 The European whites, who by early differentiation (in Europe 
 or elsewhere) were of three varieties, namely, dolichocephalic 
 Mediterraneans, dolichocephalic Baltics 2 and brachycephalic 
 Caspians (a relatively late arrival), are now of four varieties, by 
 reason of the crossbreeding of Caspians with Mediterraneans 
 south of the Alpine ranges and with Baltics north of them. The 
 Mediterraneans, not tall but well built, are brunette, with black 
 breasted, Ancient Times, p. 28. 
 
 *The name "Nordic," now in fashion, should be given to the entire 
 northern blond half of the brown-white orthognathic race, whether found 
 in Europe, in Siberia or in Japan. The Baltics are a sufficiently dis- 
 tinctive (and distinguished) variety to have a name of their own.
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 73 
 
 hair and dark eyes. The Baltics, tall and angular, are blond, 
 with light hair and blue eyes. The Alpines, a Caspian-Mediter- 
 ranean hybrid, are brachycephalic, thick set and in coloring 
 variable, but usually lighter than Mediterraneans. The Danu- 
 beans, a Caspian-Baltic hybrid, are brachycephalic, tall and pow- 
 erfully built, prevailingly ruddy, with red beards and hair and 
 gray eyes. 1 
 
 The prevailing languages of the white peoples have become 
 inflectional. An Aryan tongue is spoken throughout the Asian- 
 European grass-lands. Among all peoples there are reactions 
 of excitement, including terrified avoidances or fearsome con- 
 tacts, toward innumerable natural objects, in particular, springs, 
 pools, rivers, cliffs, trees, reptiles and birds, and, in the grass- 
 lands, bulls. 
 
 After prehistory, history; intense, tumultuous, short, its mil- 
 lenniums, compared to prehistory's eons, are a dynamic instant of 
 time. Yet (such is the relativity of things) the perspective of 
 history is atmospheric, if we keep our distance. Its scenes are 
 geographically spacious, if the eye sweeps boldly. So we must 
 view them now, inattentive to detail. 
 
 At the delta of the Nile and far up its course, at the head of 
 the Persian Gulf and far up the Euphrates River, dense popula- 
 tions are distributed. There is no longer pretense that any one 
 of these is a close-knit kindred. Aliens commingle with the 
 native born, and many languages are heard. Agriculture is sys- 
 tematically followed. Industries are differentiated and special- 
 ized. Artisans of amazing skill make useful things of bronze, 
 perfect of their kind, and fashion silver and gold and precious 
 stones in patterns of beauty. Engineers build dams and reser- 
 voirs and a network of canals, to control and distribute the over- 
 
 1 The confusion of Danubeans with Alpines in current anthropological 
 literature is peculiarly annoying to the historian. The Romans discrimi- 
 nated. Caesar's Aquitani were Mediterraneans, his Celts were Alpines, 
 his Belgae were Danubeans, his Germans were Baltics. The fair-haired 
 Achaeans of Homer and the Hellenes generally were Danubeans. The 
 Picts of the British islands were Mediterraneans, the Goidelic Celts were 
 Alpines, and the Brythonic Celts were Danubeans, whose dialects now, 
 by one of the curious paradoxes of history, are spoken by brunette Welsh, 
 Cornishmen and Bretons.
 
 74 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 flow of the rivers. Architects of commanding genius build pal- 
 aces for the great, temples for the gods and the multitudes, and 
 tombs for the venerated dead. Boats ply up and down the rivers. 
 Where were towns there now are cities, turbulent with human 
 life. Merchants import and export goods by caravans that cross 
 deserts to foreign parts. Slaves breed in hovels, toil in quarries 
 and in brick yards, and die. Scribes write down dates and taxes, 
 and keep the record of dynasties. These urbanized peoples of the 
 river valleys of the Southeastern Mediterranean area are creating 
 civilization. Colonists, exiles and merchants will bear it to the 
 farthest East; merchants and armies to the frontiers of the West. 
 
 On the island of Crete, Knossos, already old, unfortified but 
 defiant, commands the Aegean Sea. Beneath it lie strata of 
 debris, as priceless as pearls, left there by neolithic makers of 
 hand-burnished pottery and by "early," "middle" and "late" Mino- 
 ans. Round about it are lesser towns, but rich and powerful, 
 which it controls. On the Aegean islands are its countless petty 
 ports, and on the coasts of Greece its colonies: Tiryns on the 
 Gulf of Argos, and Mycenae, marvelous for wealth and splendor, 
 at the mountain pass as the trail runs from Tiryns to Corinth. 
 The fabulous wealth of this maritime power, its treasures of 
 bronze and gold, have been paid for by a distinctive and highly 
 perfected art and by trade with Egypt and Asia and the coasts of 
 Western Africa and of Europe. Its ships of commerce are safe- 
 guarded as they traverse the sea, and at every port, by ships of 
 war the first sea power. 1 Against this unique resplendent civi- 
 lization of the Mid-East Mediterranean area the armies of Egypt 
 and of Asia do not aggress. 
 
 Between the Black Sea and the Mediterranean, between the 
 Taurus mountains and the Caucasus, between the Zagros moun- 
 tains and the Caspian Sea, stretch the table lands of Cappadocia 
 and Armenia, of Media and Elam, eastward to Persia and be- 
 yond. The armies of Egypt and of the Tigris-Euphrates basin 
 invade them, following caravan routes, up water courses, through 
 canons and mountain passes. Overflowing from Elam and Media 
 
 1 Egypt may first have navigated the eastern Mediterranean, though 
 strict proof is lacking; but the argument that Egypt was ever a naval 
 power is not yet convincing.
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 75 
 
 and presently from Persia, an Aryan stock repels them and swiftly 
 extends its empire. In Cappadocia and throughout Eastern Asia 
 Minor, a non-Aryan stock, the origins of which we do not see, ap- 
 pears as a military power. The Persian conquers the Euphratic, 
 and the Hittite conquers a part of the Egyptian imperial domain. 
 Each creates a civilization, in part derivative, in part original and 
 distinctive. These civilizations of the West-Asian Uplands are 
 stark and lean, but outreaching. Persia drives an Aryan influence 
 into Northwestern India. The Hittite power transmits Sumerian 
 and Semitic achievement to the Aryans of the West. 
 
 Enclosing the Aegean and Adriatic Seas three peninsulas thrust 
 into the northern waters of the Mediterranean : Asia Minor in its 
 western extension, Peloponnesian and Central Greece, and Italy. 
 Northeast, north, and northwest of them are the mystery-haunted 
 lands of the Aryan dispersion. Mountains and rugged hills hide 
 lonely valleys or guard aUuvial plains, open to the sea. On the 
 lower slopes are olive trees and grapes, and above them chestnut 
 trees and oaks. The coasts are irregular. Gulfs and deep bays 
 cut into them, but also there are long straight reaches where no 
 harbor can be found, and dangerous by reason of conflicting 
 tides. Between Greece and Asia Minor Aegean islands can be 
 seen off shore. The sea, impressionistically (since Agamemnon), 
 is purple. On hills and plains the sun at noon is white, but even- 
 ing and morning lights are violet. Beauty has taken these parts 
 for her own. And hardy men, unafraid of loneliness or of the 
 sea, sensitive to beauty and loving freedom ; shepherds, herdsmen 
 and plowmen, fisher folk and sailors ; and presently artisans and 
 merchants have taken them for their own. By comparison with 
 the peoples of the River Valleys they are a sparse population and 
 poor. Their cities, except possibly Troy, the oldest of them, 
 which in its day has rivaled Mycenae, are less splendid, and their 
 buildings are less majestic than those of Thebes and Babylon, but 
 are infinitely more appealing to intelligence. Their statues and 
 their paintings, for the first time in human achievement, attain 
 truth through freedom restrained only by mastery of modeling 
 and line. Racially they are a mixture of primitive Mediter- 
 raneans, Danubean invaders and Alpines, but slavery has limited 
 hybridizing, and (it appears) more strictly in democratic Athens
 
 76 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 than in aristocratic Sparta. 1 Their armies are small and local 
 but valorous. The Athenian navy is a formidable arm. The 
 East fails to invade European Greece ; Carthage invades Italy but 
 is expelled. These are visible features (we are not heeding now 
 the processes) of the Peninsular Civilization of the North Medi- 
 terranean area. Athens tries to make it imperial but is unsuc- 
 cessful. Macedon succeeds, but her empire is short-lived. Rome 
 builds an empire geographically coextensive with Europe south 
 of the Rhine and the Danube, with Northeastern Africa and with 
 Asia Minor. In more than a figurative sense it is "built." Ex- 
 cellent roads provide a means of internal mobilization and com- 
 munication never before equaled. The possibilities of the arch 
 are developed in bridge building and in the construction of aque- 
 ducts, by which for the first time town dwellers are supplied with 
 an abundance of pure water. This empire endures nearly half a 
 millennium. 
 
 Rome and the Romanized populations of her provinces, a partly 
 hybridized commingling of Mediterraneans, Danubeans and Al- 
 pines, are overrun by European Nordics, principally Baltics. 
 Most of them are inlanders of the forests. They build boldly of 
 timber but not of stone, and know nothing of engineering or of 
 the finer arts. As invaders they burn and raze. Establishing 
 themselves in overlordship, they roughly reorganize an existing 
 serfdom, extending it and increasing the severity of obligatory 
 services. Taught and aided by artisans of the old order, now 
 under duress and robbed of all but traditions and skill, they build 
 strongholds and presently castles of stone, from which they wage 
 wars of pillage upon one another. Converted to Romanized 
 Christianity, they build monastic houses and churches. About 
 churches and castles villages of craftsmen and laborers grow up, 
 but merchants are few, and imported goods all but unknown : 
 
 1 Greek democracy was infra- not inter-eihnic, and the argument of the 
 indiscriminatists that panmixia in Athens begot the most brilliant race of 
 men in history suffers from the militating circumstance that the premise 
 is not true. LaRue Van Hook has shown in The Classical Journal, May, 
 1919, that Athenian democracy was more than the internal equality (and 
 clique warfare) of a social "four hundred"; nevertheless, Galton's guess 
 that Greek genius was a product of early and prolonged inbreeding by 
 aristocratic clans is probably the best one ever made. In Sparta, by all 
 accounts, there was panmixia, the details of which may be left to feminist 
 literature.
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 77 
 
 orderly trade has been destroyed. Almost the only contacts with 
 the East are through missionaries from Rome and pilgrims to 
 Jerusalem. Nevertheless, in ecclesiastical establishments and in 
 guilds of artisans reminiscences of Latin civilization survive and 
 presently ameliorate somewhat the struggle for existence and the 
 manners of the time. So arises an isolated civilization of Inland 
 Western Europe, a grotesque reaction of barbarism to the Medi- 
 terranean heritage. For centuries it is politically incoherent and 
 intellectually barren until, alarmed by Saracen intrusion, it rallies 
 about Charles Martel and the way is opened for Charlemagne. 
 Horizons now are widened. The Mediterranean resurges upon 
 the Baltic, and when, at length, the daring of the North and the 
 intelligence of the South are mingled, their product is the match- 
 less beauty, the wonder and the glory of Gothic art. 
 
 Looking back for a moment upon the migrations from which 
 this unique civilization dates, we note that not literally all of 
 the participants are inlanders. A fringe of them, dwelling upon 
 dismal northwestern coasts, fog-hidden and forbidding, are fisher- 
 men and sailors. They can fashion keels as well as rafters. 
 They, too, feel the wanderlust, but from Denmark they turn their 
 faces west. The tempestuous North Sea calls them. They voy- 
 age to Iceland and the British coasts. They conquer Britain and 
 possess it. Kindred Norsemen voyage to the coasts of Gaul, 
 there to become Normans and in their turn to conquer an incom- 
 pletely Anglicized Britain. In the Mediterranean, also, sea-faring 
 traditions persist, and in the ports of Italy, of Southern France 
 and of Spain the race of sailor men is not extinct. Communica- 
 tion between East and West is slowly reestablished. The knowl- 
 edge of geography, of mathematics and of navigation, that Egyp- 
 tians, Cretans, Greeks and Romans possessed, is recovered, and 
 is disseminated among seafarers of the West. Trade with the 
 East is unsettled, its ways are changing and its possibilities are 
 multiplying. Christian crusaders take Jerusalem from the Infidel 
 but are unable to hold it, and fail to break through to the East. 
 An ocean way may be found. Voyages become longer and more 
 daring. Canaries and Azores are left behind. The Cape of Good 
 Hope is rounded. Dutch and English, French, Portuguese and 
 Spaniards become maritime peoples and discoverers. The At-
 
 78 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 lantic Ocean is crossed by an Italian backed by Spanish royal 
 power and money. The Pacific Ocean is discovered from the 
 West. The earth is circumnavigated. Europe explores and 
 colonizes a Western Hemisphere. Ocean-fronting Nations, de- 
 limiting their boundaries and organizing themselves politically, 
 create by ocean-borne commerce a civilization of the world. 
 
 In the play of History the dramatis persona are not only in- 
 dividuals ; they are also groups of individuals and* multitudes. 
 These act as units, and as characters they have moral and intel- 
 lectual unity. Yet always they are groups and multitudes. 
 
 Again, more often than not a scene in history is repeated in 
 various places and with variations before the next scene in 
 dramatic order is enacted; and always an entire act is repeated. 
 Act two (mediaeval history) is a repetition of act one (ancient 
 history), with variations. Act three (modern history) is a repe- 
 tition of act two, again with variations. This is the basis of fact 
 for the saying that "history repeats itself." 
 
 At Memphis a company of priests marches solemnly in pro- 
 cessional. They proclaim themselves Masters of Mysteries and 
 Men of Vision. They have been instructed in the wisdom of 
 the past; they foresee the future. They know what signs pres- 
 age abundance and famine, what conduct of man pollutes and 
 what cleanses the sources and streams of life. Now they warn 
 the people of impending peril. Boatmen from the south, con- 
 firming rumors that for months have passed from lip to lip, 
 have reported abominations. Dwellers up the river, corrupted 
 by too much contact with heathens beyond the Cataracts, have 
 adopted strange rites, not to be described. They have defiled 
 sacred places and killed sacred animals. Warnings have multi- 
 plied. Thousands of ibexes have died. Dead crocodiles float 
 by. The river itself has an unusual and sinister look; many 
 persons have observed it. Already, perhaps, the Valley, and 
 the Delta too, lie under a curse. Pestilences and more dreadful 
 plagues may stalk the streets tomorrow. 
 
 The people clamor for action. The King has had dreams and 
 is impressed. Soldiers are assembled and mobilized. A defensive- 
 offensive expedition sets forth. The land must be purified.
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 
 
 79 
 
 Skirmishes become battles and battles wars, which recur. 
 
 The curtain falls on United Egypt; but the priests are not 
 as happy as they were. The army has become arrogant. The 
 people never tire of cheering it, and sometimes the King defers 
 to it, instead of to the priests. 1 
 
 A later scene, perhaps a variant of this one, or it may be a 
 second, is set in Sumer. 
 
 Caravans from the Crescent bring disquieting tidings. Suc- 
 cessive droughts have parched the oases and dried wells never 
 before known to fail. Even in the wadys of the West-Arabian 
 mountains crops have failed, and cattle by thousands have died. 
 Tribes of Semites, apparently migrating, have been seen moving 
 eastward, a fierce and uncouth rabble. Companies of armed 
 strangers, a vanguard perhaps, have been in the Plain of Shinar 
 but have disappeared. They were thought to be from the desert. 
 The older camel men, however, recall that Semitic nomads have 
 been herding in Mesopotamia time out of mind, "always," some 
 say, but others deny this, asserting that all Semites were oasis 
 men once, or, more likely, wady men. Either way, they have been 
 rovers apart in petty groups, and beyond stealing cattle or looting 
 a village now and then, harmless enough. Yet nobody knows 
 how many of them could come together in a round-up, or what 
 might happen if the devil got into them. 
 
 It happens. That pillar of dust on the western sky was not 
 caravan dirt this time; but the warning was too short. Wave 
 upon wave, countless, tumultuous, the Semites come, spearmen 
 and swordsmen, frenzied as charging cattle, and as resistless. Ur 
 is theirs. Eridu falls before them. Nippur will be theirs, and 
 Babylon. 
 
 Now let us drop the figure of the play and more simply sum- 
 marize action, from this point on. 
 
 Two tremendous movements surge upon each other while 
 sweeping onward together. One is the group struggle for do- 
 minion and subsistence. The other is the class struggle for 
 
 1 The certified records on which I should have been glad to base my 
 reconstruction of this scene have unfortunately not been found ! Never- 
 theless, historical friends will grant, I hope, that my imagination has not 
 run quite wild in the suggested explanation of rudimentary political 
 integration and the beginnings of class struggle.
 
 8o STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 ascendancy and revenue. These two movements begin with 
 history. They are the action of history. 
 
 Climatic crises, 1 exhaustion of resources, diminishing returns 
 and other circumstantial pressures cause migrations, in which 
 populations clash. The issue is life or death. Groups confed- 
 erate for defense; by conquest they are consolidated. They are 
 compounded and recompounded. They integrate and are in- 
 tegrated. 
 
 Military leaders, selected and developed by war, become pow- 
 erful politicians if war continues or often recurs, and army 
 officers become a class, as "class conscious" as the priesthood. 
 They contest the ascendancy of the priests. The struggle is 
 long and bitter. The priesthood is jealous and alarmed. The 
 army is envious and aggressive. The army has booty and land 
 to divide, but it wants to be assured of supernatural sanction. 
 Above all, being new, it wants to become respectable. The 
 priesthood has traditions and form. It can make things right 
 with unseen powers, or wrong. It can confer respectability, or 
 withhold it. 
 
 The possibilities of the situation are not obscure, and when 
 priests and soldiers both grow weary of strife, an understanding 
 is arrived at which royalty, properly instructed, consents to and 
 decrees. Distinguished priests are "let in" on the ground floor 
 of the New Privilege. They receive lands and revenues. Dis- 
 tinguished soldiers are vouched for as divinely guided, and get 
 invitations thenceforth to convocations. So (historically) are 
 begotten "lords temporal" and "lords spiritual," and both kinds 
 are landlords ! 
 
 Old groups of land-owning kinsmen, and individual land own- 
 ers, if they are fortunate, become free tenants. An increasing 
 number of these, if the times favor, become merchants. Old 
 communities of dependents continue to be serfs. Artisans, if 
 fortunate, become free tenants and enjoy guild privileges. If 
 merchants prosper, they become class conscious (as the soldiers 
 
 1 Most fateful of all, short of a far-extending glaciation, has been "the 
 pulse of Asia," an alternating irrigation and dessication of regions east 
 of the Caspian Sea, as the snow-fall on the mountain systems is 
 rhythmically heavy and light; See Huntington, The Pulse of Asia,
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 81 
 
 did), and intimations of a new class struggle between merchants 
 and landlords appear. 
 
 From the morning of history in Egypt and Sumer until Jus- 
 tinian's reign, group integration is almost continuous, and the 
 class struggle is taken up by successive classes. In the Medi- 
 terranean Island area, as in the river valleys of the Southeastern 
 area, in the West-Asian uplands and in the North 'Mediterranean 
 peninsulas chieftaincies become kingdoms, and kingdoms empires. 
 Priests yield to soldiers. Priests and military adventurers, in- 
 venting the "gentlemen's agreement," become landlords. Land- 
 lords lay field to field, but the merchants, amassing wealth, prepare 
 to contest ascendancy. 
 
 Then there is a break. The empire collapses. Act one of a 
 drama has closed. Ancient history ends, and mediaeval history 
 begins. The cycle of group and class struggle starts anew. 
 
 A new religion has arisen and a new priesthood. From the 
 death of Constantine in 337 its divine authority is conceded. 
 At the birth of Charlemagne in 742 its social ascendancy is 
 complete and unquestioned. But the northward thrust of the 
 Moors and their repulsion has set going changes that will com- 
 pel it to fight for its prestige. A new militarism grows pro- 
 digiously under Charlemagne and his successors. Unwittingly 
 the Church abets it by demanding that the Holy Land, be 
 "purified" from Islam. Crusading barons become more powerful 
 than titular princes, and their followers become armies. They 
 make their own terms with bishops. The Holy Roman Empire 
 and the Bishops of Rome both assert "sovereignty," but in the 
 end the inevitable bargain is struck. A new and overpowering 
 landlordism is created. Bishops and barons become "peers." 
 
 The ablest of them, William of Normandy, with the intellectual 
 and ecclesiastical aid of Lanfranc (whom William, after quar- 
 reling with for opposing the ducal marriage to Matilda, has made 
 Archbishop of Canterbury), creates out of English chaos the first 
 politically sovereign western nation, by reorganizing the relations 
 between feudal society and monarchy and putting monarchy in- 
 disputably on top. Under his incompetent successors the barons 
 get on top and resolve society into anarchy. Henry II, instituting 
 scutage and the assize of arms and thereby making royal revenues
 
 82 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 and the army semi-independent of baronial favor, and subordinat- 
 ing ecclesiastical to civil courts, lifts monarchy from personal rule 
 to trusteeship for a nation. So begins a struggle as sharp and 
 distinctive as any struggle between group and group or between 
 class and class; a struggle, namely, between an integral group 
 the nation and whatever class is ascendant. The first clash is 
 disastrous, for again the barons get on top, and society disin- 
 tegrates. Group and class struggles revert to beginnings, and 
 mediaeval history ends. 
 
 Mediterranean Christianity came to birth among humble folk 
 inclined to communism, and was adopted by the great when they 
 saw its stupendous possibilities as an agency of social control. 
 The more carefully the origins of Northwestern Christianity, 
 otherwise Protestantism, are studied, the more nearly certain it 
 appears that these are not so much a vision or a hope of the 
 miserable, whether docile or rebellious, as an assertion of per- 
 sonal independence by men self-reliant and self-respecting, al- 
 though poor. Therefore, while in substance of theology this 
 religion of the individual conscience is not new, and as rebellion 
 against authority is schism, as reaction to life it is a new faith, 
 engendered by new actualities of the struggle for existence. That 
 fourteenth-century "Poor Richard," William Langland, the per- 
 sistent Wyclif and the fiery Huss are all, in their different ways, 
 true exponents of its spirit. And this is why, notwithstanding 
 the doings at Constance and at Basle, its ministry does not become 
 a priesthood. 
 
 Nevertheless, with this spirit, with this new faith and its min- 
 istry, modern history begins in the fourteenth century. The 
 group and the class struggles of ancient and of mediaeval history 
 are recapitulated, but, as always, with variations. A new mili- 
 tarism, developed by the Hundred Years War, uses gunpowder. 
 A new landlordism is sustained by money rents instead of by 
 feudal services, and this time the part played by religion in the 
 class struggle is new. The Protestant ministry is not yet socially 
 ascendant, and not strong enough to exact privileges. Moreover, 
 it has been recruited chiefly from commoners and the lesser gentry, 
 and its individualism is "middle-class." Therefore it allies itself 
 with the merchants and becomes a factor in the incipient class
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 83 
 
 struggle between them and the landlords. The major alliance, 
 accordingly, is between landlordism and the older ecclesiasticism, 
 and the major intra-group struggle is between this combination 
 and the nationalistic monarchy. It ends (except for brief re- 
 crudescence under Mary and again under the Stuarts) in the firm 
 establishment of nationalism and the ascendancy of Protestantism 
 under Henry VIII. 
 
 Now, at last, class struggle between merchants and landlords 
 assumes full proportions and (without violence, however) in- 
 tensity. Voyages of discovery open new and unprecedented 
 opportunities, and merchant adventurers become men of power. 
 But, like the soldiery of earlier times, they crave and demand 
 full social recognition. They can make terms, and the bargain 
 is struck. Great merchants are admitted to the peerage, and 
 by marriage (and otherwise) peers in need of revenue acquire 
 wealth. A capitalist class is created. 
 
 So modern history arrives at noon. Capitalism exploits in- 
 vention and revolutionizes industry. A wage-earning proleta- 
 riat, descended from emancipated serfs, becomes in its turn 
 "class conscious," and Karl Marx makes the epochal discovery 
 that class struggle impends in history ! 
 
 The creative efforts of history are concentrated upon one com- 
 prehensive achievement, which is, attainment of a preferred way 
 of living. The means of attainment are culture and a social 
 order. Culture includes taste, a standard of living, knowledge 
 and skill. A social order is a system of pluralistic habits, rela- 
 tionships and policies. Prehistory gropes, perceives, tries, learns 
 and with infinite patience practices. It creates the elements of 
 culture and primitive social systems. History scrutinizes, criti- 
 cizes, rejects, selects, conserves, changes, adds, combines, reforms, 
 revolutionizes and reconstructs. 1 
 
 The history of culture no less than the history of action, is a 
 story of strife. The New has fought with the Old for its life. 
 Instinct, habit, taste, sentiment and vested interests have rallied 
 
 1 The study of history as achievement (history as scenario, play and 
 story being presupposed) is the study of the History of Civilization, a 
 specialist's task, demanding among other qualifications a sociologist's 
 knowledge of social systems.
 
 about the Old. Experimental drive, cleanliness, convenience, 
 comfort, health, enterprise, prosperity have been identified with 
 the New. 
 
 The Old has not been content to conserve its own : it has tried 
 to strangle the New at birth. Therefore the conflict between the 
 two has been a war for the right of achievement to survive; to 
 live on as the Old, to be born and to carry on as the New. Civi- 
 lization exists because neither the Old nor the New has been able 
 to do its instinctive or its premeditated worst against the other. 
 
 More than those things that constitute heritage (of which 
 mention was made) has been at stake. Heredity has been at 
 stake. The intellectualized variety of man (irrespective of race) 
 has been subjected to an artificial selection as fateful as natural 
 selection. Where innovation is not permitted, experimental in- 
 tellect cannot leave posterity. 
 
 Our knowledge of the origin, structure and functioning, and 
 of the transformation of social systems, is largely a scientific in- 
 duction. 
 
 There are surviving examples of social systems that never 
 have produced and that will not leave a written history. They 
 have been much observed, fortunately, by ethnologists; and pos- 
 sibly they may so far be neglected by powerful peoples bent on 
 cleaning up dirty neighbors that they can be studied a generation 
 or so longer. Social systems now extinct were observed and 
 described in antiquity, not, indeed, with scientific precision, but 
 often shrewdly and with approximate accuracy. The social 
 systems of prehistoric men we imperfectly reconstruct from 
 archaeological and philological fragments, supplemented by folk 
 ways and folk lore that survived into historical days. This evi- 
 dence, as far as it goes, is often worth more than chronicles, since 
 it is without bias, and came into existence without conscious in- 
 tent to impress posterity. All of these systems, extinct and sur- 
 viving, that did not and do not leave written annals, we describe 
 collectively as primitive social systems. 
 
 By comparison with the highly complex social systems that we 
 know today primitive social systems are almost incredibly simple ; 
 but some of them are less simple than others. There is a sue-
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 85 
 
 cession of types, each of which is associated with a characteristic 
 situation or habitat. 
 
 First in time and simplest in structure is a social system of 
 the forest habitat and the bush. In its rudimentary form it is a 
 small horde or camp or a cluster of neighboring and more or less 
 communicating hordes, in none of which more than twenty to 
 fifty individuals, men, women and children, can be counted. This 
 group knows nothing of blood relationships, or it ignores them; 
 it coheres by instinct and habit. 
 
 Within it, however, arise ideas of mysterious influences and 
 relationships. Various things and kinds of things are believed 
 to have an uncanny power to harm or to benefit. "It," for so 
 more often than not the mysterious power is referred to, can 
 cause good or bad luck ; it can pollute ; it can cause sickness, and 
 it can kill, or it can cleanse and heal; it is contagious, passing 
 from object to object or from person to person by contact. It is 
 "mana" or "virtue"; it is demoniac power. Whatever holds 
 or imparts purifying and healing mana is sacred ; whatever holds 
 or imparts defiling and evil mana is accursed. There are ways of 
 banning evil mana and of conserving good mana. These rituals 
 as much as habits of camping and wandering together, are group 
 ways ; they are modes of pluralistic behavior in distinction from 
 individual behavior. In each group they are more or less peculiar. 
 They are, therefore, a collective interest and bond supplementing 
 mere animal gregariousness, including its reactions to cries and 
 calls. They are a distinctly human interest and bond. 
 
 Out of these ideas and practices totemism emerges, and pres- 
 ently appear more complicated relationships identified with it. 
 These get mixed up with natural relationships, which thereby 
 become distorted and conventionalized. There results a social 
 system of inclusions and exclusions, based on a recognition of 
 descent in one line only. A matrilineal and matronymic system 
 is in general more primitive than a patrilineal and patronymic 
 system. How far the cavern people of the Reindeer Age had 
 advanced in these matters we do not know. 
 
 The social system of the grass-lands has become or is becoming 
 patrilineal ; but it carries along many survivals of totemism and of
 
 86 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 matrilineal relationship. 1 Ideas of ghosts and ghost worship have 
 appeared, and out of them ancestor worship develops. Paternal 
 power and authority have superseded the authority that maternal 
 uncles exercised in matrilineal society, and the family group, 
 cohering for more than one generation, often becomes a patri- 
 archal kindred. Whether this happens or not, the patrilineal 
 system has the great advantage that the fighting men of any con- 
 siderable aggregation are of one conventional kindred, instead of 
 being, as in matrilineal society, of as many different conventional 
 kindreds as they have totemic or clan mothers. 
 
 On the grass-lands appears also in the course of time a new 
 social system as distinctive as systems based on conventionalized 
 kinship are, or as the earliest ritualistic system was by comparison 
 with an animal herd. It is based on an understanding between a 
 luckless individual needing protection and a man powerful enough 
 to protect him. In primitive society men get "kin wrecked" in 
 many ways. Because of their own misdeeds they are banished 
 from clan or village, or the groups in which they were born are 
 plundered and broken in war. Other men, a smaller number, 
 become powerful as successful leaders in war or when, in recog- 
 nition of one or another service to the group, they are permitted 
 to possess an exceptionally large share of booty or otherwise to 
 become rich. 2 In the grass-lands ruined men take service and 
 receive protection as cowboys under cattle owners strong and 
 self-assertive enough to break folkway rules and override the 
 rights of fellow tribesmen. In the Brehon Laws of Ireland, where 
 the grass-land life survived until comparatively late times, we have 
 the picture of a society organized partly as a holdover tribal 
 system and partly as allegiance and service rendered to a pro- 
 tecting chieftain. 3 
 
 The social system of primitive agricultural communities is a 
 medley and compromise of survivals rather than a new type. 
 
 1 Robertson Smith, Kinship and Marriage in Early Arabia. 
 
 ' The evidences brought together by Robert Lowie in Primitive Society 
 that private property and inequalities of private property exist in primitive 
 societies of every cultural grade and in every part of the world have 
 disposed of a long controversy, to the lasting discomfiture of propagandist 
 vendors of primitive communism. 
 
 1 Henry Sumner Maine, Lectures on the Early History of Institutions.
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 87 
 
 Kinship is cognatic as far as recognition of relationship by both 
 mother and father goes, but is usually patronymic. A kindred 
 may cohere as a local group and hold land as an undivided pos- 
 session for four generations, and, as was mentioned on a fore- 
 going page, it may stand in the relation of protector to a hetero- 
 geneous group of dependents. Within the kindred itself inequali- 
 ties of rank and of condition exist and are recognized; among 
 the dependents they are not permitted. 1 
 
 Survivals of all primitive systems, namely, those based on re- 
 ligious solidarity and ritual, those based on a conventionalized 
 kinship and those based on beneficium et commendatio, are numer- 
 ous in present-day societies. The most interesting ones, perhaps, 
 are found in such laws of nationality as the jus sanguinis and the 
 sacramentum fidelitatis, whereby a claim to citizenship rests, in 
 one case, on the citizenship of a parent, and, in another case, on 
 an oath of allegiance to a sovereign. 
 
 All the social systems of civilized peoples, whether ancient or 
 modern, are variants of a fourth general type. Indeed, in the 
 strict etymological meaning of the word, civilization is the super- 
 seding of tribal by civil society. Within the city aliens congregate 
 and prosper until it becomes necessary to admit them to privileges 
 and to impose upon them such fundamental obligations as tax 
 paying and military service. After much experimenting they are 
 naturalized, that is to say, by a legal fiction they are made of one 
 kindred with the older stock. 2 The basis of this system is mutu- 
 ality of opportunity and of obligation. 
 
 The historical variates of this general type are familiar and 
 need not detain us longer than is necessary to make essential 
 discriminations and to point out their relation to group and class 
 struggles. 
 
 Society is an aristocracy as long as opportunity, although 
 shared, is not equalized, and control is retained by a privileged 
 class, qualified by ability and experience to govern in the ad- 
 ministrative sense of the word, but not by unselfishness to rule 
 
 1 Frederic Seebohm, The Tribal System in Wales; and Hugh Seebohm, 
 The Structure of Greek Tribal Society. 
 
 2 The Constitution of Athens , discovered by Dr. Budge and by him 
 attributed to Aristotle.
 
 88 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 arbitrarily over fellow men. Society is a plutocracy as long as 
 opportunity, although shared, is not equalized, and control is 
 held by a capitalist class. Society is a kakistocracy as long as 
 opportunity, although proclaimed to all, is not equalized in fact, 
 and control is exercised by a dictating minority, undisciplined and 
 ignorant, that has seized power by revolutionary violence. So- 
 ciety is a democracy if opportunity is equalized and control, 
 although not equalized (a thing impossible), is shared. Democ- 
 racy is communistic if property is equalized and occupation is 
 prescribed. Democracy is socialistic if property in major part is 
 held collectively and occupation is prescribed. Democracy is 
 individualistic if property in major part is held individually but 
 is subject to prescribed obligations and limitations, and if occupa- 
 tion is freely chosen by individuals but, like property, is subject 
 to prescribed obligations and limitations. The distinction be- 
 tween democracy and all other social systems is radical. In a 
 democracy control is participated in although never equally exer- 
 cised by all members of society instead of being monopolized by 
 any group or calling, and, consequently, integral society dominates 
 over all its component groups, constituent classes, callings, fac- 
 tions, parties and miscellaneous minorities. 
 
 Without specialized callings and segregations, differentially 
 functioning, society is primitive and negligible; it can achieve 
 nothing; and yet from the moment that differentiation of a popu- 
 lation into variously functioning callings or segregations begins, 
 class struggle rages. A dominant minority or majority rules as 
 nearly absolutely as it can. Revolution overthrows it, destroying 
 in its leveling violence so much of the functioning social organiza- 
 tion that prosperity cannot return, or achievement proceed, until 
 differentially functioning fractions, specialized and unequal, are 
 recreated. Democracy is an attempt to equilibrate energies in a 
 less costly way. Communistic and socialistic democracies err by 
 equalizing too much and restraining too much. Anarchistic in- 
 dividualism errs by permitting excessive inequalities and restrain- 
 ing too little. Between these extremes are possibilities of a more 
 delicate equilibration in a Socialized Individualism acting through 
 unstable majorities subject at every instant to possible disintegra- 
 tion and reformation.
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 89 
 
 It is time to get back to theory. I promised to intimate and 
 perhaps gently to argue an interpretative hypothesis or, if the 
 phrase is not presumptuous, a scientific explanation of history. 
 If any reader has followed me so far, he has already received 
 and apprehended the intimation. My argument will be a gen- 
 eralization (without contention) from the materials that have 
 been exhibited. 
 
 Here let me anticipate and answer a question. Are these 
 materials history? No and yes. Quantitatively they are in- 
 finitesimal, but qualitatively they are bits picked out of history 
 by a scientific test, namely, significance. They have indicative 
 quality and therefore scientific value. They are signatures of 
 history. 
 
 More and more our inductive science accumulates priceless 
 knowledge of things (and events) in themselves inaccessible, by 
 examining their marks or signatures. The astronomer knows 
 the chemical composition of suns unimaginably distant because 
 they have made their "mark" in lines of the spectrum. No 
 physicist has seen an atom, but every physicist reads in atomic 
 signatures that it is composed of positive and negative electrons, 
 and that the electrical charge of a positive electron may be numeri- 
 cally equal to the electrical charge of a negative electron, al- 
 though its mass is nearly two thousand times greater while its 
 diameter is only one two thousandths as great. 1 The materials 
 from which I am generalizing now are finger-prints of history 
 on the smoked glass of time. 
 
 The geographical theory of history is true, as far as it goes. 
 Civilization arose in regions that could sustain and energize dense 
 populations. It has never made headway except in regions that 
 could sustain and energize urban populations. Throughout the 
 first nine-tenths or more of total historical time the action of 
 history was confined to the Mediterranean Basin. That basin 
 is made up of characteristic areas. In each a distinctive civiliza- 
 tion arose. In each the action and the achievements of history 
 have been distinctive. So long, however, as physical environment 
 has remained stafic nothing has happened. Only when environ- 
 mental change has created a circumstantial pressure of calamities, 
 
 1 MacMillan, Science, July 23, 1920.
 
 90 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 hardships, contacts, conflicts and rivalries, has there been col- 
 lective human action and with it integrations, differentiations, 
 cultural progress and social evolution. 
 
 The biological theory of history is true, as far as it goes. The 
 historical peoples have been stocks capable of persistent multipli- 
 cation and at the same time of variation and longevity. In other 
 words, they have been dynamic stocks. In a struggle for exis- 
 tence that has been terrible and remorseless they have held their 
 own by vitality and by adaptability. Also, to an extent not ade- 
 quately apprehended, they have been, unconsciously, eugenic 
 breeders. By taboos and conventions, by pride and arrogance 
 born of success, and by the social exclusiveness of dominant 
 classes, they have restricted hybridization and effectually pre- 
 vented that miscellaneous and general amalgamation which the 
 biologists call panmixia. Natural selection, therefore, has had 
 not only individuals but also relatively pure stirps to work on, 
 with the inevitable consequence that, through an elimination of 
 biologically inferior stirps as such, energy, character and intelli- 
 gence have been conserved for generations. Whether a subse- 
 quent indiscriminateness has now and then caused national decline, 
 is a question more difficult to answer. The one certainty is that, 
 irrespective of theories, the instinct of persistently vigorous peo- 
 ples has been against it, as it is now in England, Canada, Aus- 
 tralia and the United States. 
 
 True also, as far as it goes, is a psychological theory of his- 
 tory that has never yet been well formulated. It is not well 
 described as a theory of collective self-determination, although 
 that phrase is not wholly inaccurate. The historical peoples 
 have been capable of imagination and of persistent exaltation. 
 They have seen visions and dreamed dreams. They have been 
 aroused by enthusiasms. Much that they have seen has been 
 hallucination, and often their enthusiasm has gotten out of hand, 
 but among their visions have been discoveries and inventions, 
 and among their exaltations have been heroic devotions. Su- 
 preme among these, as a factor in human achievement, has been 
 the devotion of a few peoples, of whom the Greeks were first in 
 time and in degree, to an intellectualized civilization. 
 
 An anthropological theory of history that of late has been a
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 91 
 
 factor in world politics has most mischievously confounded bi- 
 ological, psychological and cultural facts. Baltic stocks have 
 displayed conquering energy and dominating will, but their culture 
 has been derivative. Wherever they have gone they have mingled 
 with populations of predominantly Mediterranean characteristics 
 and have assimilated a Mediterranean culture. It is preposterous 
 to argue that the predominant part which composite populations 
 so originating have played in history should or can be accounted 
 for by hybridizing or by Baltic culture or by Baltic domination. 
 It can be accounted for only as an exploitation of Mediterranean 
 culture by Baltic energy civilized by the Mediterranean culture. 
 Achievement is the historic work of races capable of ascendancy 
 through culture. 
 
 A sociological theory of history might be formulated but has 
 not been. The historical peoples most distinguished for achieve- 
 ment have somehow been able more successfully than others to 
 balance integral against partial interests, and individualism against 
 collectivism. 
 
 All of these theories of history are true, as far as they go, 
 but not one of them accounts for history! One and all they ac- 
 count for conditions that have shaped history, or, at best, have 
 made it possible. Not one of them tells us why it has been 
 actual. 
 
 For, when all is said, history is human behavior. It is a stream 
 of behavior, rising obscurely in time, making for itself a devious 
 channel, fed by countless tributaries of collective action, and 
 broadly flowing now into the mist that hides an unexplored 
 hereafter. 
 
 In part the historic behavior of men moving on together by 
 thousands and by millions has been blindly instinctive. In part 
 it has been a conscious but errant experimentation. Also in part 
 (and increasingly) it has been an attempted and often a successful 
 carrying-out of premeditated policies. These have been made by 
 no one man, and for this reason, rather than for any "determin- 
 istic" reason, the great-man theory of history breaks down. They 
 have arisen as visions in the minds of the men of vision and have 
 then been taken over, with or without acknowledgment, by men 
 of action. To convert them into collective behavior the men of
 
 92 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 action have "interested" and enlisted effective members of 
 groups, classes, factions, parties, minorities and majorities, prom- 
 ising them substantial advantages. The combination has been a 
 dynamic plurel:* a "gang," "ring," or "junto" bent on "going 
 somewhere" or "doing something." Inasmuch as it has accom- 
 plished, first and last, infinitely more good than evil, let us give it 
 a dignified and suitable name. It has been a Composite Protago- 
 nist. To an appreciable extent it has "made" history, proceeding 
 deliberately, and by every art of persuasion, temptation, bullying 
 and coercion known to man. It has started wars and class strug- 
 gles. It has been self-renewing until supplanted by a rival, 
 destroyed by failure, subjected by conquest or deposed by revo- 
 lution. 
 
 As participants in the behavior that is history the instinctive 
 multitudes, the errant experimenters, the clear-eyed and far- 
 seeing protagonists of premeditated policies have had in com- 
 mon one trait besides their elemental human nature; or has it 
 veritably been their human nature itself ? Either way, they have 
 been of one inclusive kind. All have been adventurers. All 
 have felt an urge and responded to it. They have dared and 
 gone forth. They have listened to pipings and followed lures. 
 They have dug for pots of gold ; climbed purple mountains. They 
 have fared on pilgrimages "to meet with joy" in any "sweet 
 Jerusalem." They have trekked and voyaged; have fought, and 
 plundered and avenged. They have fashioned empires and dis- 
 membered them. With infinite toil they have created social order, 
 and in drunken deviltry have destroyed it. They have read the 
 stars and rent the atom. 
 
 History, then, is adventure, and the urge to adventure is the 
 cause of history. This proposition is the kernel of my theory. 
 
 Enfolding and sustaining it is the coefficient truth that some 
 men, the daimones of our race, react to the urge promptly, abun- 
 dantly, persistently, effectively, and in doing so pour or radiate a 
 secondary or converted urge upon more sluggish men until they 
 too react effectively. Paradoxically and amusingly this one 
 specific affirmation of inequality among men is not denied by 
 
 *Our English derivative from pluralis has in usage an adjective value 
 only. Needing a noun, I fall back upon this pleasing old French form.
 
 A THEORY OF HISTORY 93 
 
 egalitarians. The wildest social lunatic has never imagined, or 
 liar for a holy cause averred, that as adventurers men are equal. 
 On the contrary, each is more sure than of anything else in life, 
 that he at least, is an adventurer of parts, destined at some time 
 to lead a multitude of small adventurers somewhere ! 
 
 In sum, and to be severely scientific (as scientific as Mr. Adams 
 is) equilibration of the urge to adventure and of reaction to it is 
 the historically behavioristic mode of the degradation of energy. 
 
 As far as I can see there is one sufficient reason for being so 
 accurate, and abbreviate. It is the short way to get back to his- 
 tory as reality, concrete and alive. As reality history is theme 
 and story. The theme is actuality, the story what we make it. 
 Scholarship a kind of morality has corrected our story of 
 history in point of veracity, and (so all things work together for 
 good to such as love truth) amazingly enriched it. Science has 
 discovered and revealed actuality. Unspoiled by knowledge and 
 unharmed by understanding, actuality is what it was to Odysseus 
 and to Columbus; story is what it was to Herodotus and to 
 Froissart. As actuality history has been and is, Adventure; as 
 story it was and is, and to the end of time will be, the Great 
 Romance. 1 
 
 1 This chapter was in type for publication in The Political Science 
 Quarterly, before the publication of Mr. Wells's The Outline of History.
 
 CHAPTER VI 
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 
 
 NEARLY two and a half thousand years ago Clinias the Cretan, 
 Megillus of Lacedaemon, and their Athenian friend, who, we 
 surmise, wrote The Republic and The Laws, sauntered along 
 the way that led from Knossos to the cavern temple of Zeus. 
 Loitering from time to time in the groves of cypress trees, they 
 discoursed upon the question whether from the gods, or from 
 the merely finite minds of mortal though gifted men, have pro- 
 ceeded chiefly those customs, rules, or laws which are the foun- 
 dations of moral order in the state. As their dialogue flowed on, 
 it revealed a sophisticated knowledge of affairs and a nicely 
 graduated caution in generalization which proclaimed each one 
 of the three to be that rarest and most excellent of beings, the 
 philosopher who is also a man of the world. The vulgar view 
 that laws are a gift from the gods they well understood ; and that 
 in a sense it could be accepted as true they acknowledged. The 
 not less vulgar view that the mortal lawgiver has on the whole 
 improved upon the lawmaking of the gods, they likewise under- 
 stood; and that this view also in a sense is true, they acknowl- 
 edged no less freely. But as they themselves viewed the compli- 
 cated relations of man to his fellowman, his passions and his 
 reasoned purposes, his manifold deeds of evil and of good, and 
 called to mind the varied plans of social organization which they 
 had observed in the city states of their own Grecian world, they 
 for themselves interpreted the divine lawgiving not as a proclama- 
 tion from the throne of Zeus, but rather as a certain objective 
 conditioning of individual and collective life by a thousand for- 
 tuitous forces to which man must accommodate his conduct. 
 And the lawmaking of man they viewed as essentially the art of 
 perfecting this accommodation of human conduct to objective 
 facts and relations. 
 
 94
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 95 
 
 Their phrasing of this naturalistic philosophy was simple and 
 straightforward, and admitted of no misunderstanding: "I was 
 about to say," remarked the Athenian, "that no man is ever a 
 legislator ; but that fortune and all kinds of accidents happening 
 in all kinds of ways, are our legislators. For either a war by 
 violence has overturned polities and changed laws, or the want 
 of means arising from severe poverty. Many innovations, too, 
 diseases compel men to make, through pestilences falling upon 
 them, and unfavorable seasons through many years. He, then, 
 who foresees all this, will be eager to exclaim, as I just now did, 
 that no mortal man was ever a legislator, but that nearly all 
 human affairs are accidents. . . . On the other hand, it is equally 
 possible for the person to speak correctly on these points who 
 says . . . that although a god, and, together with a god, fortune 
 and opportunity, govern all human affairs; nevertheless it is 
 necessary to admit that art, a somewhat milder power, follows 
 them." 1 
 
 Thus, in the land of the Gortynian law, where civilization 
 millenniums old had begun perhaps as early as in Egypt or on 
 the Babylonian plain, was stated the profoundest problem of 
 social philosophy may I not say of all philosophy the problem 
 of the interplay of human purpose with that external fate which 
 we moderns call the reign of natural law, the question how far the 
 collective life of man is inexorably determined by the one, how 
 far from time to time it may be shaped anew by his own clear- 
 seeing reason and indomitable will. 
 
 Before we take up the question how far the solution of this 
 problem which satisfied those men of Crete, of Athens, and of 
 Lacedsemon, can suffice for us, whose intellectual standards have 
 been both shattered and recreated by the new-born science of our 
 later world, let us linger yet a moment more on certain further 
 words in which they set their meaning forth. So strongly did 
 they hold that man by constructive reason may create institutions 
 potent to perfect his life, that they themselves were then devising 
 a body of laws for an ideal commonwealth. And yet they held 
 steadily before their minds the truth that their dreamed-of repub- 
 lic, if it were in fact to exist, must be composed of certain nat- 
 
 1 Plato, The Laws, IV, 4.
 
 96 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 urally coherent elements, and must conform to unalterable objec- 
 tive requirements. Once more I quote, and again it is the Athe- 
 nian who speaks : 
 
 "For when a colony is of one race, and has the same language 
 and the same laws, it possesses a kind of friendship as being a 
 partaker in the same holy rites, and everything else of a similar 
 kind, nor does it easily endure other laws, and a polity foreign to 
 what it had at home. . . . But, on the other hand, a colony, com- 
 posed of all kinds of people flowing together to the same point, 
 will perhaps be more willingly obedient to certain new laws ; but 
 to conspire together, and, like a pair of horses, to froth together, 
 as the saying is, individually to the same point, is the work of a 
 long time and very difficult." 1 
 
 In no later writing that I know do we find in so few words 
 so many cardinal generalizations as these lines contain upon the 
 nature and behavior of human society. They tell us, first, that 
 of two familiar groupings of human beings, namely, groupings 
 of kindred, and groupings of "all kinds of people flowing together 
 to the same point," the second or miscellaneous grouping is no 
 less spontaneous, no less natural, than the first. Secondly, they 
 tell us that in the ethnically homogeneous group there is a psy- 
 chological as well as a physical unity, a sympathy and under- 
 standing not to be looked for in the heterogeneous group. Never- 
 theless, as thirdly, they aver, not only in the homogeneous but 
 also in the heterogeneous group, notwithstanding its defective 
 mental unity, there is a collective behavior, which, however, 
 and this is generalization fourth is more slowly and with greater 
 difficulty in the miscellaneous group raised to the practical work- 
 ing level of collective action for the attainment of a common end. 
 Fifthly, and finally, they declare that innovation any voluntary 
 breaking away from an old order of things to experiment with a 
 new is more likely to occur in the heterogeneous than in the 
 homogeneous group. 
 
 Two thousand years of so-called progress have enriched and 
 broadened knowledge. They also have multiplied the absolute 
 number, possibly the relative number, of well-informed persons. 
 They have multiplied, further, the relative as well as the absolute 
 
 1 Plato, The Laws, IV, 4.
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 97 
 
 number of scientifically trained minds. That they have evolved 
 individual intellects of greater power or of higher quality than 
 were the best minds of Greece cannot be demonstrated. That 
 they have multiplied the absolute number of men of genius is 
 probable. That they have multiplied the relative number of gifted 
 intellects is possible, but not certain. The civilization of Greece, 
 in fine, was like some marvelous mutation in the realm of organic 
 life, the advent of a new and glorious creation. Modern civiliza- 
 tion is but the multiplication of its offspring. There has not yet 
 appeared a nobler type. 
 
 Our one undeniable superiority, then, is a fact not of inherent 
 quality, but of acquisition merely. It is our fuller and more ac- 
 curate knowledge and, underlying our knowledge, our more com- 
 plex, our more rigorous methods of investigation. It is, in a 
 word, our science. 
 
 In the light of our fuller knowledge it may be of interest now 
 to reexamine the Grecian conceptions of collective life, of the 
 nature, the origins and the uses of society, as the men of natural 
 science, on their part, have reexamined, corrected and restated 
 the Greek conceptions of the material world and of individual 
 living things. Applying our stricter canons of scientific method, 
 let us raise anew the questions of which Plato and his friends 
 discoursed. 
 
 The continuity of all phenomena, within the limits at least of 
 finite space and of finite time, is the master conception of our 
 modern thought. There is no drifting molecule of dust that does 
 not beat with impulse from solar systems very far away. There 
 is no living thing that is not related in bonds of kinship to every 
 other living thing. There is no conscious thought that has not a 
 history which, if told, would be the story of all existence from 
 eternity. There can be no theory, then, of any thing, or group of 
 things, of any change, or series of changes, which is not a coordi- 
 nate part of universal theory. Each science must not only be 
 compatible with every other science, but, inseparable from every 
 other, it must with them complete the unity of knowledge. More- 
 over, in every science the verdict of reason must accord with the 
 verdict of sense perception. This accord, indeed, is the very
 
 98 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 substance of science, the innermost essence of verification. 
 Science cannot identify or measure truth by standards of utility. 
 It can only declare that this observation, or that generalization, 
 accords with, or stands in conflict with, other observations, other 
 generalizations. It may make for pleasure. We believe that in 
 the end it will. For the moment it may contribute only pain. 
 With either result the scientific man as such has no concern. 
 
 Accepting this conception of scientific knowledge as the basic 
 standard from which to judge the pretensions of any explanation 
 or theory of collective life, we expect to find, and we do in fact 
 find, that many sciences have something to contribute to the sys- 
 tematic analysis and interpretation of human society. 
 
 The natural groupings of human beings which are the bases of 
 their community life are in no important sense unique. From 
 botany and from zoology we learn that these groupings are com- 
 mon to all living things. The patches of lichen, the beds of moss, 
 the forests of pine or of oak, the swarms of bees, the hills of ants, 
 the shoals of fishes, the flocks of birds, the bands of squirrels, 
 the colonies of beavers, the villages of prairie dogs, the herds of 
 wild sheep, of antelope, of wild horses and wild cattle, the bands 
 of monkeys, the tribes and nations of men, form an unbroken 
 series of aggregations. In like manner, collective behavior is a 
 phenomenon not peculiar to the human species. Comparative 
 psychology assures us that from such simple beginnings as the 
 simultaneous reaction of protozoons to mechanical pressure, to 
 heat, to light, to electricity, or to chemical action, up through the 
 subinstinctive mutual aid of the ants, the sympathetically con- 
 certed action of pelicans in fishing or of wolves in hunting, to the 
 deliberate cooperation of Australian savages in corroboree, or of 
 Tammany braves in a political campaign, there is no point at 
 which we can draw a line and with certainty say : Here mere phys- 
 ical response of irritable matter to a stimulus passes into coopera- 
 tive instinct or here cooperative instinct, in its turn, passes over 
 into a reasoned cooperation. 
 
 The race of man, however, is more highly differentiated than 
 any other species of living things, and the wide range of human 
 variation, both physical and mental, which anthropology describes, 
 has determined a marvelous diversity of kind and of degree in the
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 99 
 
 social groupings of human beings. Between the feeble hordes 
 the shifting camp-fire groupings of primitive savagery, and those 
 great aggregations of men in the Mediterranean Basin who, with 
 infinite toil, laid the prehistoric foundations of civilization, archae- 
 ology reveals endless gradations, while the peoples who upon these 
 foundations have builded with political art the empires whose 
 story the historian repeats, have played the drama of collective 
 life with endless variations. 
 
 And throughout these gradations, this range of variation, there 
 is order the genetic order of evolutional change, the balanced 
 order of correlation. The presumption which biology establishes 
 that the reign of natural law extends to every realm of the world 
 of life is confirmed by the sciences of social phenomena. The 
 economist, the student of comparative jurisprudence, the investi- 
 gator of comparative politics, one and all assure us that the collec- 
 tive conduct of men is not fortuitous. The values of the market- 
 place rise and fall, the activities of commerce ebb and flow as the 
 tides of the sea. Law proceeds from law with the regularity of 
 a birthrate. Parties and policies arise, flourish, and are lost in 
 new issues with the sweep of a geometric curve. 
 
 There is, then, we must conclude, no branch of modern science 
 which does not contribute something to the theory of man's social 
 relations, and there is no aspect of these relations which may not 
 be illuminated by any scientific discovery. Obviously, it is not 
 only the structures and the functions of living things regarded as 
 individuals that have awakened scientific curiosity, but, as well, 
 the groupings of individuals and their collective behavior have 
 fixed the attention of observers in many domains of inquiry. 
 Under systematic scrutiny they have been revealed as legitimate 
 scientific data, admitting of examination by scientific methods. 
 
 Quite as certainly, however, the possibilities of the scientific 
 study of society have not been exhausted by any of the sciences 
 thus far named. Beyond the questions 4hat have been raised by 
 biologist and historian, by economist and student of politics, there 
 are fundamental ones that thrust themselves upon attention. 
 
 What, for example, is the process of group formation? What 
 are its conditions? What, if any, are its limits? What types or 
 kinds of groups or of groupings arise? Similar questions we are
 
 loo STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 compelled to ask about pluralistic behavior. How does it begin ? 
 What are its causes? What types or kinds of pluralistic behavior 
 are there ? How does it develop into collective behavior and then 
 into concerted action for the achievement of a purpose? How 
 far, under given conditions, does it take the place of individual 
 action? To what extent does it become or does it create a con- 
 straining pressure upon the individual, in some degree controlling 
 him and setting bounds to his liberty? 
 
 Again, when combined or collective action is long continued 
 does it establish certain enduring relations among the individual 
 actors participating in it, and are these relations that complex 
 something which we call social organization? If so, what types 
 or kinds of social organization may we discriminate? What are 
 the stages of their genesis ? What are their respective limitations ? 
 Do they tend to become fixed or rigid, or may they remain plastic, 
 with a mobile and shifting membership? 
 
 Such questions provoke others. What consequences or re- 
 actions proceed from natural groupings and from collective be- 
 havior? It is commonly assumed that they create artificial con- 
 ditions of security and opportunity. What, then, is their effect 
 upon the process of evolutionary selection? What on the sur- 
 vival of any given race or stock? What upon the amplitude and 
 the richness of individual life? What upon the character of the 
 individual and of the race ? In a word, does the character of the 
 mass determine the character of the individual, or is individual 
 character fixed and determinative of the mass ? Or yet, perhaps, 
 within ascertainable limits, does each determine the other ? 
 
 Finally, there is a profound question of interpretation, the 
 ultimate question of causation. From the political sciences we 
 have derived conceptions of teleological causation. We have been 
 led to think of man as a creator, fashioning his social relations as 
 he would have them for the achievement of ends which he has 
 visualized. From biology we have derived the conception of an 
 ecological explanation. Life proceeds through an adaptation of 
 organism to environment. Environment moulds the organism, 
 provokes and directs its activities, and determines its fate. Is 
 social evolution, in like manner, an ecological adaptation ? Grant- 
 ing that it is, is it also an idealistic striving ? How far, then, may
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 101 
 
 our interpretation of social relations legitimately be idealistic, how 
 far must it be ecological ? 
 
 Under careful examination these radical inquiries about social 
 phenomena are seen to be closely clustered and correlated. Aris- 
 ing within a well-defined field of research, they are the problems 
 of a logically organized science. Presupposing general psychol- 
 ogy, presupposing also anthropology conceived as a special and 
 concrete psychology of the racial varieties of mankind, and 
 presupposing, finally, archaeology and history, sociology the 
 general science of society is the true scientific foundation 
 of such special sciences as political economy, jurisprudence and 
 politics. As such, it has little in common with that portentous 
 science of all social things, good and bad, but especially bad, 
 which has been invented for the sociologist by untethered intel- 
 lects that live by describing things which the non- journalistic eye 
 has not seen and defining things which have not entered into 
 the merely academic mind to conceive. The sociology with which 
 we are here concerned may be defined in the simple terms already 
 used and repeated as the science of the natural groupings and 
 the collective behavior of living things, including human beings. 
 
 Social philosophy grappled in its youth with its most difficult 
 questions, those, namely, of personal causation and of the action 
 of society upon the individual character. This was not because 
 systematic inquiry into the nature of society was a legacy from 
 anthropomorphic ages. On the contrary, it was because it arose 
 in that Grecian world where, for the first time, man had become 
 in the true sense of the word a citizen, and had experimentally 
 demonstrated that, through a free and plastic social organization, 
 he could in a measure control his own economic and moral destiny. 
 In Egypt and in Babylonia political integration, hastened and 
 hardened by empire-making militarism, had brought all the eastern 
 lands under a remorseless despotism. Peoples once free and 
 happy had been so crushed by exploitation that hope itself had 
 almost died within them. Despairing of redress at the hands of 
 any earthly power, and distrustful of themselves, they could only 
 create and embrace, according to their temperaments, the relig- 
 ions of resignation, or those of apocalyptic vision. In the Aegean
 
 102 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 Grecian world geography and race had conspired to prevent a too 
 rapid centralization of power. The city states were still free and 
 proud. Man still believed in himself and respected his fellow man. 
 Rejoicing in political as in artistic creation, loyal to the state which 
 his own thought had fashioned, he believed that he could make it 
 perfect, and thereby perfect himself. Therefore it is that the 
 first comprehensive work on the nature and possibilities of hu- 
 man society which has come down to us from the past was the 
 Utopian Republic of Plato. 
 
 The imperishable contribution which this work makes to our 
 reasoned knowledge of human society is found not in its com- 
 munistic plan of life, but rather in its analysis and its correlation 
 of moral and social forces ; above all, in its actual solution of the 
 problem of social reaction upon individual character. Assuming 
 that man as a personal cause can in fact mould the commonwealth 
 to his will, assuming also that the final end of endeavor is the 
 attainment of a good life which should consist substantially of 
 those kinds and degrees of pleasurable activity that reason can 
 approve of The Republic demonstrates that the "good life," 
 so conceived, after all depends upon a certain objective condition 
 which reason and the human will may create, and which is called 
 "justice." Moreover, reason and will cannot create justice directly. 
 They can establish it only through the fine adjustments of a social 
 order. Thus, in the thought of Plato, the "good life" is a func- 
 tion of "justice," and to maintain justice is the function of social 
 organization. 
 
 It was but too obvious, however, to the men of Athens in its 
 Periclean Age, as it is to us to-day, that not all society establishes 
 justice, and that not all so-called justice yields the fruitage of 
 good life. It was inevitable to ask whether the failure is wholly 
 attributable to man's fault or weakness, or is caused in part by 
 those vicissitudes of fortune which, as Plato himself admitted, 
 finally govern all human affairs. It is to this problem that 
 Aristotle turns in The Politics, in some respects the most mas- 
 terful treatise upon human relations that has yet proceeded from 
 either the ancient or the modern mind. Based upon an inductive 
 study of one hundred and fifty-eight Grecian constitutions, it 
 analyzes the nature and functions of the state, it classifies and
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 103 
 
 critically compares the forms of government, it exposes both the 
 inherent and the adventitious limitations of each, and reveals the 
 causes of political change, including revolution, that lie deep in 
 human nature, in historical experience, in geography, climate and 
 soil, and in other circumstances of external fact. Thus, while 
 fully recognizing the creative part of conscious purpose, Aristotle 
 carries explanation back to impersonal causation. He lays the 
 foundation for an ecological interpretation. Inductive also in 
 his method, where Plato is speculative only, his work is more 
 strictly a scientific study of society. 
 
 While Plato was interested chiefly in problems of the social 
 welfare, and Aristotle chiefly in the antecedent problems of social 
 organization, they did not quite neglect a multitude of facts that 
 are dynamically antecedent to association, as organization is 
 functionally antecedent to welfare. Aristotle, especially, was 
 curious about the nature of those bonds of feeling and purpose 
 which hold men together in agreeable or useful organization, and 
 in his chapters on Friendship, in the Nicomachean Ethics, he 
 recognizes the importance of that sense of similarity, which, long 
 before his day, had been expressed in the proverb that "birds of a 
 feather flock together," and by Empedocles in the saying that 
 "like desires like." Perceiving that this social sense is instinctive, 
 he built the argument of The Politics upon the postulate that 
 man is a political animal. 
 
 This simple theory of the social mind was both broadened and 
 deepened by the disciples of Zeno. Alexander's conquests brought 
 into one political system Thracian and Athenian, Asiatic and 
 Egyptian. In the cosmopolitan atmosphere of the Macedonian 
 Empire the brotherhood of man became for the first time a prac- 
 tically important fact, and stoic philosophy, reflecting upon the 
 moral consciousness common to barbarian and Greek, explained 
 it as the conformity of human reason to a universal reason imma- 
 nent in nature. This interpretation goes to the bottom of things, 
 for it is equivalent to the proposition that resemblances and sym- 
 pathies have their origins in like adaptations of otherwise differ- 
 ing men to the same objective fact or universal law. 
 
 With cosmopolitanism, however, came individualism, and with 
 it the final word of Greek philosophy upon the social relations.
 
 104 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 Epicureanism, with its emphasis upon individual initiative and 
 individual happiness, contended that the society is best which 
 imposes minimum restraints upon the individual will. From this 
 doctrine as a premise, the conclusion was inevitably reached that 
 social and legal relations rest wholly upon individual self-interest, 
 and the desire of each to secure himself against injury. The true 
 origin of society was therefore to be sought in contract or consent. 
 So the teaching of Plato and of Aristotle was turned about. The 
 assumption that society creates and moulds the individual became 
 the dogma that individuals, for individualistic ends, create society. 
 
 In the further development of social philosophy from these 
 Greek beginnings, the historical evolution of society itself con- 
 tinued to be the chief formative cause. To the Roman mind, with 
 its genius for political organization, the problems of organization 
 in general made strong appeal. But the great achievement of 
 Roman intellect was its analysis and correlation of the facts from 
 which organization proceeds. The conflicts of mind provoked by 
 conflicts of interest, the meeting or concert of minds, the emer- 
 gence therefrom of contract, and the ultimate expression in law 
 of the collective reason and final decision of the community 
 these phenomena were more completely understood and more 
 accurately described by the Roman legal writers than by the 
 Greek philosophers. While The Republic and The Laws of 
 Plato tell us what laws ought to be, The Republic and The 
 Laws of Cicero tell us what laws are and how they came to be. 
 The Romans, moreover, by their conquest, incorporation and 
 assimilation of many diverse peoples, acquired a knowledge never 
 before attained of the ethnic composition and other physical 
 phenomena of a social population that are determinative of the 
 social mind, and to this day there are no better descriptive studies 
 of some aspects of ethnic character and influence than Caesar's 
 Gallic War and the Germania of Tacitus. 
 
 The rise of the Christian Church and the extension of its 
 authority from Rome to the remotest frontier of the secular 
 empire offered to contemplation a new and magnificent social 
 order. It presented new ideals of human well-being and a com- 
 prehensive organization. Claiming to be in truth that City of 
 God which Augustine portrayed, it demanded recognition from.
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 105 
 
 kings no less than from people as a universal society within which 
 the secular state must henceforth take a subordinate place. To 
 vindicate not only the historical, but also the rational claim of 
 the secular empire over the ecclesiastical power, was the purpose 
 of Dante's De Monarchic*. 
 
 It was not chiefly by argument, however, that the conflicting 
 claims of secular and ecclesiastical authority were adjusted. The 
 secular state established its dominion by force, and thereby 
 brought again into the foreground of consciousness the questions 
 of social psychology. For political force is something more than 
 the vis viva of a physical body. It is the conquering power of a 
 political body, the cohesion and self-directing quality of which are 
 not accounted for by instinct and sympathy only. It is a com- 
 manding because it is a commanded group. A chieftain speaks 
 and followers obey. A prince rules and subjects render service. 
 With amazing precision, Nicolo Machiavelli analyzed the psychol- 
 ogy of this relation as it had never been analyzed before. The 
 leader obtains obedience through his power to browbeat lesser 
 men, to inspire and to awe. He is feared and revered not so 
 much for his physical strength alone, as for his nerve, his re- 
 sourcefulness and craft; because he is the fearless man in the 
 midst of men who fear. Collectively they could make an end of 
 him, but that is the last thing they would wish to do. For, deeper 
 and more overmastering than their fear of him is their fear of a 
 hostile world environing them and forever threatening their ex- 
 istence, and they have discovered that their man of iron is able 
 to make that outer world fear him as they also fear. Loyally and 
 without question obeying him, they are safe. They conquer and 
 make their way, they build the state and extend its domain. The 
 alternative is servitude or extermination. Therefore, the supreme 
 duty of the prince is to maintain his authority. The supreme duty 
 of the state, whether principality or republic, is to maintain its 
 dominion and its vital quality of growth. Greek civilization was 
 overwhelmed because the Greek ideal was a static perfection. 
 Rome, expanding, became mistress of the world. Consequently, 
 to the conduct of the prince and to the policy of the state, pro- 
 founder standards than those of ordinary morals apply. Self- 
 preservation through adequate power and ceaseless growth, is the
 
 106 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 supreme law. The social order may not rightfully be permitted, 
 for moral reasons, to disintegrate, as the Queen of Siam was left 
 to drown because it would have been sacrilege to lay hands upon 
 her sacred person. Machiavelli did not see in the struggle for 
 existence all that Darwin was to discover in it, but he did grasp 
 the tremendous truth that out of it springs social life, to be for- 
 ever conditioned by it, and that no system of state-craft or of 
 ethics which is constructed in lofty disregard of it can be other 
 than childish. 
 
 After Machiavelli, it was easy for the political theorists, Bodin 
 and Althusius, to construct their concepts of sovereignty and the 
 state. Society, as Bodin taught, arises from instinct and is devel- 
 oped by experiences of the pleasure and utility of association. 
 Within the bosom of society the state is created by force, and 
 sovereignty is supreme political power "over citizens and subjects 
 unrestricted by the laws." This conception was more simple than 
 the facts, some of which Althusius more clearly perceived. De- 
 fining sovereignty as the supereminent power of doing what per- 
 tains to the spiritual and bodily welfare of the members of the 
 state, Althusius argued that it inheres in the totality of the people 
 and cannot be alienated or delegated. So conceived, sovereignty 
 is the supreme form and expression of a social will, and as such 
 it is the focal phenomenon of the social mind. 
 
 Demonstration, finally, that society and the state, a social will, 
 rightful authority, and political power, have all one common and 
 inevitable origin, was the achievement that Thomas Hobbes es- 
 sayed. Writing in an age when royal absolutism was striving to 
 maintain itself against popular revolt, Hobbes derived both society 
 and sovereignty from a covenant whereby men in a state of nature 
 escape from intolerable ills. Freely and gladly yielding their 
 individual wills, men alienate their natural sovereignty, and the 
 monarch or the parliament so obtaining authority rightfully rules 
 absolutely, wielding force to any necessary extent. If any one 
 has refused to join in the covenant, he has elected to remain in a 
 state of nature which is a state of war. He therefore cannot com- 
 plain if force is used against him. If, however, the titular sover- 
 eign fails to maintain his authority, society is resolved back into 
 anarchy, and the social covenant must be re-made. Therefore
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 107 
 
 the revolution that succeeds is right. There is probably not in 
 all literature, outside of the exact sciences, so complete an ex- 
 ample of remorseless logic as De Corpore Politico is. 
 
 Its one vulnerable point, namely the premise, was perceived by 
 Locke. Denying that the state of nature is one of war, or for any 
 reason intolerable, since men of one blood and kindly disposed 
 spontaneously aid one another, Locke contends that the people 
 never alienate their natural sovereignty. A natural society, they 
 forever are the state, the source and real wielder of power, al- 
 though artificially by covenant creating institutions for utilitarian 
 ends and delegating a limited authority to governments. 
 
 Like history, social theory had now repeated itself. From new 
 Utopias and the doctrine that the scope and character of social 
 organization determine the quality of individual life, it had re- 
 turned to the conclusion of Epicurus that individuals in a purely 
 rationalistic way create society for individualistic ends. 
 
 Throughout this long development and in all the various phases 
 that it had assumed from Plato to Locke, social theory, while not 
 neglecting observation or ignoring external cause, had been on 
 the whole speculative, or, to use Karl Pearson's word, "ideologi- 
 cal," and its interpretations had been chiefly in terms of subjective 
 causes, namely, motives and reasons. But from ideological be- 
 ginnings, science, as Pearson contends, becomes in the second 
 stage of its evolution observational, and, finally, in a third stage, 
 metrical or quantitative and in a strict sense of the word 
 inductive. 
 
 In Montesquieu's Esprit des Lois the speculative methods 
 of the social philosophers are frankly abandoned. The work is 
 descriptive and its conclusions stand or fall with the accuracy and 
 sufficiency of concrete facts, from which the conclusions are 
 derived by generalization. That this work, as judged by modern 
 standards, is elementary and crude should not prevent our recog- 
 nition of the service it rendered in turning attention to inductive 
 method, in awakening interest in purely objective interpretations 
 of social phenomena, and in stimulating by suggestion and ex- 
 ample those researches which have accumulated for the use of 
 scholars today an enormous mass of ethnographic and other
 
 io8 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 descriptive sociological material. Montesquieu converted social 
 philosophy into descriptive social science. 
 
 Meanwhile, the beginnings of quantitative investigation had 
 been made. Ancient states enumerated their populations for 
 purposes of taxation and military service. The Roman census 
 was taken at five-year intervals, and there were probably at least 
 seventy such enumerations. The mediaeval church kept records 
 of marriages, births and deaths, primarily for the purpose of de- 
 ciding disputed cases of kinship-degree barring sacramental mar- 
 riage. The Domesday survey of England, ordered by William of 
 Normandy, is an admirable document of descriptive sociology. 
 Manorial records in many instances are accurate and detailed de- 
 scriptions of local communities. 
 
 Masses of figures, as such, however, are descriptive only. They 
 may be profoundly significant, but they yield their meaning only 
 to interpretative analyses that involve the use of somewhat refined 
 mathematical methods. The first step in this direction was taken 
 by the astronomer, Edmund Halley, in 1693. John Graunt had 
 compiled interesting tables of mortality, but had not derived from 
 them any important induction. Halley drew up a life table from 
 observations in Dresden, from which he demonstrated what pro- 
 portion of all persons born in any given year would die or survive 
 in each succeeding year. This was the first true inductive gen- 
 eralization of law in the realm of social phenomena. To the in- 
 fluence of another great mathematician and astronomer, Laplace, 
 the subsequent developments of quantitative method in sociological 
 research must in large measure be attributed. Laplace's marvel- 
 ous mind ranged over the whole field of human knowledge. He 
 drew about him the original and interesting men of his time. 
 Among these was the younger mathematician, Jean Baptiste 
 Fourier, whose monographic studies of the city of Paris revealed 
 the possibilities of scientific inference from statistics of aggrega- 
 tion, of births and deaths, and of distributions of population by 
 age and sex. The Belgian statistician, Quetelet, whose Physique 
 sociale and Sur I'Homme were the first serious attempts to 
 extend statistical methods to a study of the mental and moral 
 phenomena of society, acknowledged his indebtedness to Fourier 
 and through him to Laplace.
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 109 
 
 It is well to linger a moment upon the specific and important 
 contribution that Quetelet made to a quantitative method in social 
 science. It consisted in certain applications of the theory of 
 probability. Things that happen by chance reveal in their group- 
 ing or arrangement a remarkable uniformity. When a cartload of 
 bricks is dropped upon the ground, the individual bricks scatter 
 in every direction, but more of them fall closely about a central 
 point than elsewhere, and the aggregate is a roughly rounded pile. 
 If hundreds of bushels of wheat comprising millions of individual 
 grains fall from a shute to a floor below, the rounded pile presents 
 an exceedingly accurate symmetry. This means that the greater 
 the number of chance distributions of any given kind, the more 
 precise is the regularity of their distribution. Mathematically it 
 is represented by a curve, known as the probability curve, or- the 
 curve of error. 
 
 This term, "curve of error," has also an interesting significance. 
 If a hundred different men should measure the distance between 
 two points, their results, however carefully they did their work, 
 would not precisely agree. The measuring rod or line might 
 undergo slight changes, and men differ in manual dexterity and 
 in accuracy of sight. Assuming that there is a true value or 
 measure of distance, actual measurements differ from it by cer- 
 tain "errors" or "deviations." If these errors have been made 
 by chance only, their distribution corresponds to the probability 
 curve. If, however, they have been subject to a disturbing cause 
 or bias, their curve is unlike the probability curve. Here, then, 
 is a principle which can be and has long been used to determine 
 the accuracy of scientific observation and measurement, both for 
 theoretical purposes, as in astronomy, and for practical purposes, 
 as in engineering. 
 
 But, obviously, the principle has a more profound meaning also. 
 Any distribution of a great many numerical items which notice- 
 ably differs from the curve of probability reveals specific causa- 
 tion. It tells us at once that we have to look for a cause which 
 is creating effects different from those that might happen by 
 chance, and by its form it may give us some hint of what the cause 
 is or where to look for it. 
 
 And even this meaning is not quite all. The curve of proba-
 
 1 10 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 bility gives us the only precise meaning of the term "scientific 
 knowledge." We have seen that human observations and meas- 
 urements are never precisely accurate. Generalizations, in like 
 manner, are never precisely true. The formulation of a law of 
 nature can never be made absolutely exact. Scientific knowledge, 
 therefore, is not that absolutely exact and certain knowledge 
 which the popular mind assumes it to be. It is certainty or exact- 
 ness within a range of error, and to diminish that range is the 
 object of scientific endeavor. When, therefore, we are told that 
 recent work in astronomy demonstrates that the Newtonian laws 
 of motion and the law of gravitation, as Newton formulated it, 
 have been corrected by a decimal or two, we are not told that these 
 laws are invalid and that science, after making a splurge in the 
 world, has arrived at bankruptcy, as M. Brunetiere dogmatically 
 proclaimed ; we are told only what any modest scientific gentleman 
 of fair mathematical attainments could very positively have 
 foretold. 
 
 That the ideas and the methods of Laplace greatly influenced 
 the thought of Auguste Comte, we have abundant evidence. Al- 
 though he was a teacher of mathematics, Comte did not develop 
 his own generalizations by mathematical methods. But he did 
 grasp and exploit the notion that science differs from speculative 
 philosophy in virture of its limited range no less than by reason 
 of its practice of verification. Science can tell us how things are 
 distributed in orderly coexistence and in orderly sequence, and it 
 can discover with what other distributions any given distribution 
 is most closely correlated. The various sciences themselves, 
 Comte contended, are related to one another in a sequence at once 
 genetic and logical, and to the complete body of knowledge which 
 they collectively present he gave the name Philosophic positive. 
 In his hierarchy, mathematics is the initial, the most abstract, 
 and the most general science. The science of society is most 
 concrete and special, and it is the final science to which all sciences 
 that go before it are tributary. To distinguish the comprehensive 
 social science from all fragmentary studies of society, dealing in 
 their various ways with more or less definite divisions of social 
 phenomena, and to mark it off as a body of pure knowledge from 
 all programs of social reform, he called the social science "La
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY in 
 
 Sociologie." As Comte conceived it, sociology should exclude 
 theological and metaphysical explanations, and keep itself distinct 
 from ethical applications. Above all, it should keep itself free 
 from the revolutionary spirit. In his youth Comte had been a 
 disciple of Saint Simon, but he had wearied of revolutionary 
 reform, and had come to believe that enduring social reconstruc- 
 tion must stand on firm and broad foundations of scientific 
 knowledge. 
 
 Comte predicted sociology; he did not himself create it. The 
 first strictly sociological treatise was the Social Statics of Her- 
 bert Spencer, published in 1850. Without either accepting or 
 rejecting that comparison of Spencer to the great intellects of 
 Greece, which his more ardent disciples have made, it may at 
 once be acknowledged that the Social Statics challenges com- 
 parison to an extent that perhaps no other writing does, with both 
 The Republic of Plato and The Politics of Aristotle. It 
 propounds the same problems which they discuss, and it offers 
 solutions which, though not identical with theirs, are closely 
 parallel to them. The object of human effort for Spencer is hap- 
 piness : and as he conceives of happiness, it does not greatly differ 
 from the joy of rational activity which was the "good life" for 
 Plato. Happiness depends upon external conditions, which are, 
 namely, liberty and justice. Justice, however, for Mr. Spencer, 
 is that limitation of liberty which equalizes it among men, whereas 
 for Plato it was that specialization of work and opportunity which 
 enables every man to do what he can do best, and to be what he 
 can be perfectly. Both writers agree that to establish justice is 
 the proximate purpose, or function, of society. 
 
 So far there is nothing essentially new in the Social Statics. 
 But at the end of the book there is a discussion of the dynamics 
 of society, the originality of which no well-informed critic has 
 ventured to call in question. Society obviously is not at present 
 in the perfect equilibrium of equalized liberty. Are social tensions 
 and pressures, then, tending, Mr. Spencer asks, toward equilib- 
 rium ? Have they been tending toward it from the beginning, and 
 if so, to what causes may the progressive recomposition of forces 
 be attributed? 
 
 Mr. Spencer resolves these questions into the problem of human
 
 ii2 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 nature. 1 No mere social mechanism will ever maintain the justice 
 of equalized liberty in a community of men whose supreme desire 
 is to exploit the imperfections of the law. The equilibrium of 
 conflicting interests must be established in the human heart, as 
 in outward relations. The assumption of political science, as of 
 theology, had been that human nature is unchanging until con- 
 verted by supernatural agency. Political science, influenced and 
 colored by theology, had pictured unchanging human nature as 
 essentially evil, self-seeking and ruthless. The eighteenth century, 
 reviving Epicurean individualism, reaffirmed also the doctrine 
 that human nature is essentially good. The apparently inter- 
 mediate position of Platonism and of Stoicism that man as a 
 composite being is neither wholly good nor wholly bad, and that 
 he is modifiable by adjustment to an objective law or condition, 
 had reappeared in the teaching of Montesquieu and of Condorcet 
 which culminated in the historical philosophy of Buckle that 
 the human mind is directly or indirectly moulded by the topog- 
 raphy, soil and climate of its physical environment. These writ- 
 ers, however, did not go so far as to assume that "inner moral 
 nature" or "basic personality" which theology proclaims sinful, 
 is regenerated by material causes. They argued only that man's 
 temperament and dominant emotions, his ideas and beliefs, his 
 superstition and his rationalism, are affected by physical condi- 
 tions. The proposition that human nature at the beginning of a 
 long evolutionary process was wicked, and that, under the action 
 of natural causes which can be identified and formulated, it tends 
 to become good, is Spencerian, and is new. 
 
 Accepting as he did the generalization, which Lamarck had 
 made familiar in biology, that living things are ceaselessly trans- 
 
 1 1 use this phrase and I think we should continue to use it as it has 
 been employed for generations to denote the concrete synthesis of "origi- 
 nal nature" and "second nature." "Original nature" (Thorndike's phrase) 
 is hereditary. It is made up of instincts. "Second nature" is not heredi- 
 tary, and therefore is not truly "nature" at all. It is made up of "recon- 
 ditionings" of instincts (by education and otherwise) and of habits. 
 Discrimination of these two natures followed upon the general acceptance 
 of Weismann's contention that "acquired" traits are not hereditary. To 
 "original nature" Spencer's argument does not apply unless in five thousand 
 generations or so instincts have been modified by mutation and selection. 
 They have not been modified by use and disuse. To "second nature" the 
 argument applies in full force.
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 113 
 
 formed through a continuing adaptation of organism to environ- 
 ment, Mr. Spencer perceived an overlooked significance of 
 political integration. At the beginning of human progress, small 
 social groups were so situated in relation to a common food sup- 
 ply that they were almost continuously engaged in warfare, but 
 when, through successive conquests, small groups had been united 
 in great states or national federations it became possible for a 
 majority of men to give up military pursuits and to devote them- 
 selves to arts of peace. Herein, as Mr. Spencer argued, lay not 
 only the possibility, but also the certainty, that primitive human 
 nature, a product of the adaptation of primitive man to the condi- 
 tions of his existence, must be as brutal and cruel and treacherous 
 as theology had pictured the unregenerate human soul, but that 
 developed man, under widely different conditions must necessarily 
 be transformed into the kindly and helpful being who can live on 
 good terms with his neighbors, and in cooperation with all man- 
 kind. 
 
 In this thesis of the concluding pages of Social Statics we 
 have the germ of Mr. Spencer's rounded doctrine of evolution. 
 Explicitly, or by implication, it contains all the cardinal proposi- 
 tions of the Synthetic Philosophy: that equilibration is the 
 primary cosmic process; that integration and differentiation are 
 necessary consequences ; that life is a correspondence of internal 
 to external changes ; that mental evolution is the extension of ad- 
 justment in space and in time; that social evolution is progress 
 from militarism to industrialism; that moral evolution is the 
 conciliation of egoistic and altruistic impulses. 
 
 Mr. Spencer's sociological books are many and voluminous. 
 We nowhere find in them a compact and logical summary of his 
 sociological system. The following scheme of propositions was 
 not made by him, but it received his endorsement :* 
 
 Societies are organisms, or they are super-organic aggregates. 
 
 Between societies and environing bodies, as between other finite 
 aggregates in nature, there is an equilibration of energy. There 
 is equilibration between society and society, between one social 
 group and another, between one social class and another. 
 
 Equilibration between society and society, between societies 
 
 1 In a letter to the author, December 7, 1900.
 
 H4 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 and their environment, takes the form of a struggle for existence 
 among societies. Conflict becomes an habitual activity of society. 
 
 In this struggle for existence fear of the living and of the dead 
 arises. Fear of the living, supplementing conflict, becomes the 
 root of political control. Fear of the dead becomes the root of 
 religious control. 
 
 Organized and directed by political and religious control, ha- 
 bitual conflict becomes militarism. Militarism moulds character 
 and conduct and social organization into fitness for habitual 
 warfare. 
 
 Militarism combines small social groups into larger ones, these 
 into larger and yet larger ones. It achieves social integration. 
 This process widens the area within which an increasingly large 
 proportion of the population is habitually at peace and industrially 
 employed. 
 
 Habitual peace and industry mould character, conduct and social 
 organization into fitness for peaceful, friendly, sympathetic life. 
 
 In the peaceful type of society coercion diminishes, spontaneity 
 and individual initiative increase. Social organization becomes 
 plastic, and individuals moving freely from place to place change 
 their social relations without destroying social cohesion, the ele- 
 ments of which are sympathy and knowledge in place of primitive 
 force. 
 
 The change from militarism to industrialism depends upon the 
 extent of the equilibration of energy between any given society 
 and its neighboring societies, between the societies of any given 
 race and those of other races, between society in general and its 
 physical environment. Peaceful industrialism cannot finally be 
 established until the equilibrium of nations and of races is estab- 
 lished. 
 
 In society, as in other finite aggregates, the extent of differen- 
 tiation and the total complexity of all the evolutionary processes 
 depend upon the rate at which integration proceeds. The slower 
 the rate the more complete and satisfactory is the evolution. 
 
 Mr. Spencer organized sociology as a science, and he demon- 
 strated principles which must always hold a central place in 
 sociological theory, whatever its further development may be. But
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 115 
 
 his analyses are by no means always exhaustive, and he raised 
 many questions which he left unanswered. 
 
 The most fundamental question that his exposition left open, 
 and over which dispute soon arose, is that of the true nature of 
 the social aggregate. Is it, strictly speaking, an organism, or is it 
 more accurately described by Spencer's alternative phrase a 
 super-organic aggregate? The notion propounded by Spencer 
 that a typical society, consisting of individuals both dwelling and 
 working together, is as truly an organism as is the animal or the 
 vegetal body composed of cells and differentiated into mutually 
 dependent tissues and organs, was exploited by Schaffle, 1 and 
 Spencer himself took it seriously enough to draw from it the 
 classifications followed in his Descriptive Sociology. Nothing 
 came of it, however, and the alternative conception has prevailed. 
 Herd habit, social sentiment and society are psychological phe- 
 nomena. They are products of behavior, and social bonds no less 
 than collective performances are common activities and inter- 
 activities of individual minds. 
 
 When this assumption is made, the further question arises: 
 What definite mode of mental action or of behavior is the ele- 
 mentary social fact ? There are four possibilities, namely, reason, 
 impression, imitation, and pluralistic response to common stimu- 
 lation. 
 
 The Platonic and the social contract theories assume that men 
 perceive the utility of association and with conscious purpose 
 endeavor to perfect it. The social bond, therefore, is reason. 
 Machiavelli and the writers on sovereignty discovered the social 
 role of that mental phenomenon which modern psychologists call 
 impression, the power, namely, of the strong personality to awe 
 or inspire the many, the power of the mass to overawe the indi- 
 vidual. Durkheim with great ability maintained that this phe- 
 nomenon is the distinctly social or society-creating activity of the 
 mind. In // Convito, Dante descriptively analyzes the familiar 
 fact of imitation. The passage is of curious interest, because it 
 pictures imitations as subject to refraction by media the copy not 
 being quite like the example as spreading in a geometrical pro- 
 
 1 Bau und Leben des sodden Korpers.
 
 n6 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 gression, and as setting up contradictions or duels among them- 
 selves. There is no evidence that Gabriel Tarde derived the 
 theses of his brilliant Les Lois de limitation from // Convito, 
 but it would not matter if he did. Nor does it matter whether M. 
 Tarde derived much or little from the acute discussion of imita- 
 tion by Walter Bagehot in the Physics and Politics. Tarde 
 examined imitation and all that can be shown to proceed from it 
 with thoroughness and penetration. He gave to the word a pre- 
 cise and characteristic meaning, that of the action at a distance 
 of one mind upon another, whether consciously willed or not 
 willed, passive or active. If it were possible to demonstrate that 
 society is but a tissue of imitations defined as intermental actions, 
 it would be difficult to add much of interest or value to Tarde's 
 argument. 
 
 It is demonstrable, however, that neither imitation nor impres- 
 sion is the most elementary social fact. It long ago became un- 
 necessary to argue that reason is not. When an audience springs 
 to its feet at the cry of fire, its initial action is not imitation. 
 Example and imitation enter as complicating factors the instant 
 that movement toward the doors begins. The power of impres- 
 sion of a cool and fearless man to overawe and quell may 
 then, by some rare good fortune, intervene to prevent panic, until 
 reason can direct an orderly dispersion. The initial action is 
 merely a pluralistic response (i.e. a reaction by more than one 
 individual) to a common stimulation. In terms of like or of 
 unlike, of prompt or of slow, of persistent or of intermittent 
 response, all the phenomena of natural grouping and of collective 
 behavior can be stated and interpreted. Intermental action is 
 interstimulation and response. Like-response, complicated by 
 intermental action, may become competition or may become con- 
 certed volition. It may become solidarity. Unlike-response dif- 
 ferentiates and individualizes; it may disintegrate. 
 
 If some such explanation of the social process is tenable, it goes 
 far to resolve the difficulties that are presented by an apparent 
 dualism of social causation. The regional environment of a 
 population sustains and energizes it, constrains and depletes it, 
 and with infinite variety of provocation stimulates it. Through a 
 medium of circumstances, including happenings of every descrip-
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 117 
 
 tion, environmental influence affects behavior. These are the 
 original causes of society and of social evolution. The products 
 of response, including personal influence, conscious motives and 
 ideas, and the historical tradition, reacting as secondary stimuli, 
 are real and immediate, although in a strict sense secondary, causes 
 of social change. Both groups of causes, the primary and the 
 secondary, act upon brain and nerve cells in the same way, by 
 constraint and by provocation. 
 
 By means of this conception of social causation, the present 
 correlation and coordination of sociological problems is effected. 
 To environmental influence and circumstantial pressure response 
 is pluralistic. Animals dwell together in swarms and in herds, 
 and in regional aggregations. Men dwell together in wandering 
 bands or in populations. The struggle for existence becomes a 
 collective as well as an individual affair. From areas where the 
 struggle is most severe or becoming intolerable men and animals 
 move, if they can, to more favorable regions. Out of the rivalries 
 and conflicts of migrating or colonizing aggregations develop new 
 circumstantial pressures and new stimulations. 
 
 Under the action of these forces, populations assume varying 
 degrees of density and of composition. According to their density 
 and composition they react with more or less unity to a multiply- 
 ing number of common stimuli, thereby becoming more or less 
 alike in behavior, more or less homogeneous in feeling, thought 
 and purpose. Through ever increasing intermental activity, they 
 become increasingly conscious of their differences and resem- 
 blances. A consciousness of behavioristic kinds, combining with 
 and supplementing like-response to stimulation, converts instinc- 
 tive consorting and consorting by unthinking habit into a con- 
 sciously preferential association, and thereby converts a herd into 
 society. Also, combining with and supplementing like-response 
 to stimulation, the consciousness of kind converts a merely in- 
 stinctive cooperation into concerted action. 
 
 Concerted action modifies the relation of organism to environ- 
 ment and enhances well-being. It shields or removes individuals 
 from destructive environmental influences. It multiplies contacts 
 with stimuli. Above all, it so extensively recombines natural ele- 
 ments and forces, and so effectively directs their discharge through
 
 1 1 8 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 new channels, that the environment itself, as far as its specific 
 relation to man is concerned, is profoundly altered. Its adverse 
 pressure upon him is diminished, its positive contribution to him 
 and its stimulation of him are increased. 
 
 Individual differences of opinion and of ability may raise co- 
 operation to a maximum effectiveness, while certain differences 
 of attitude or of conduct may diminish its effectiveness or even 
 destroy it. Human societies, perceiving these complications, be- 
 come sensitive to the practical bearing of ethnic unity and of 
 moral solidarity. Differences of blood and of speech, of creed and 
 of conduct arrest attention and awaken distrust. Unconsciously in 
 part, but consciously also in a measure, a great deal of collective 
 action is directed upon the task of stamping out various differ- 
 ences among men. Such collective action is a true social pressure, 
 a constraining power of the social mass upon the social units. 
 Its understood purpose and its actual function are to increase the 
 practical effectiveness of society as an instrumentality for the pro- 
 tection and improvement of life. Exterminating or restraining 
 the anti-social, it selects for survival and encouragement the sym- 
 pathetic, the intelligent, and the self-controlled, thereby converting 
 the biological survival of the fit into a survival of the better for 
 human purposes. Nevertheless, being repressive and destructive, 
 social pressure curtails variation ; it limits differentiation ; it checks 
 spontaneity; it sets bounds to individuality, and tends to create 
 rigidity of social organization. It is of maximum utility, there- 
 fore, when it is just strong enough to control and to eliminate the 
 elements that obstruct cooperation, without limiting the free activ- 
 ity of elements that already are adapted to social life. The social 
 pressure that exceeds this degree is injurious and is justifiable only 
 when it is the substitution of a less repression from within for a 
 greater threatened repression from without. That society best 
 fulfils its purpose which maintains a highly organized and effective 
 cooperation with the least social pressure. 
 
 That social pressure tends to increase when circumstantial pres- 
 sure increases, is a conclusion suggested by history and by current 
 observation. Not only does the struggle of the nations to obtain 
 room for their multiplying millions create coercive policies, as Mr.
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 119 
 
 Spencer explained, but so also do impending dangers and insuffer- 
 able disorders. 
 
 To the extent that society protects man and, multiplying the 
 stimuli that act upon him positively, enables him to improve and 
 enrich himself, it converts a generic evolution into the specific 
 thing progress. Integration and differentiation, correlation and 
 coordination, fill out the formula of evolution, but they are not 
 necessarily a betterment of conscious existence. Evolution is also 
 progress when each unit of the integrated mass or group becomes 
 an end as well as a means. In the evolution of vegetal and of 
 animal life there has been much ruthless sacrificing of the in- 
 dividual to the race. In human evolution the race has been main- 
 tained and differentiated at a diminishing cost to the Individual. 
 This has been accomplished by and through society. In the higher 
 types of civilization, individual freedom and well-being are con- 
 tinually increased without necessary injury to the race. Race 
 maintenance and evolution with diminishing cost of individual life, 
 with increasing freedom, power and happiness of the individual 
 person, is progress. 
 
 So far, sociology at its best has been a logically organized body 
 of observations and categorical inferences. Through an increas- 
 ing use of statistical methods, it may take on the quantitative char- 
 acter. 
 
 To make the possibility clear, it is necessary to call attention to 
 the significance which that very simple numerical term, the arith- 
 metic average, has come to have in the theory of evolution. 
 
 If there is a struggle for existence in which certain organisms 
 perish, while others survive, it is plain that the survivors tend, 
 under given environmental conditions, to become alike, since all 
 must possess those structural peculiarities and those habits which 
 give advantage over competitors. The more specific the condi- 
 tions and fierce the struggle, the more surely is an individual 
 marked for destruction if he varies greatly from the successful 
 type or norm. Now most peculiarities of organic structure and 
 activity admit of measuring like height, or of counting like the 
 number of veins in a leaf. The measures or other numbers relat- 
 ing to thousands of individuals may be brought together in col-
 
 izo STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 umns or tables. Their averages may be obtained, and the differ- 
 ence between each number and the average of all numbers of the 
 same class may be found. Then, if the numbers, as shown by 
 their deviations, have a wide dispersion from the average, we 
 know that the individuals to which they relate have not for a long 
 time been subjected to a relatively intense struggle for existence. 
 It has been possible for them to vary within wide limits, and yet 
 to survive. If, on the other hand, the numbers cluster closely 
 about their average, we know that the individuals to which they 
 refer have been subjected to a severe unifying pressure. They 
 have ceased to vary because such as strayed from type lost their 
 hold on life. 
 
 Applications of this principle developed by Galton, Karl Pear- 
 son, and others, have proved to be of great value in biology, in 
 psychology, and in anthropology. There is reason to believe that 
 in sociology they will be not less valuable, especially as in all 
 statistical operations the possibilities of error diminish as the 
 number of numerical items of any given class, and happening to 
 be available for analysis, increases. Sociology will preeminently 
 enjoy this advantage. 
 
 The first attempt to make a statistical statement of the greatest 
 possible number of sociological problems, and to indicate their 
 statistical solutions, we owe to Mayo-Smith. It was possible 
 when he wrote to give precision to statistical studies of population 
 at one end of the series of social phenomena, to studies of or- 
 ganization and welfare at the other end. The intermediate and 
 crucial problems of mental type and variability, of selective social 
 choice, and of social pressure could not then be handled by statisti- 
 cal methods. It is becoming possible now to state and solve them 
 quantitatively by employing various new methodical devices. For 
 example, Rodolfo Benini, of Pavia, 1 has demonstrated that it is 
 a comparatively simple matter to measure a phenomenon seem- 
 ingly so elusive as the consciousness of kind. Tabulating the 
 Italian statistics of marriage, he ascertains how many bachelors 
 would marry maidens, how many widowers would marry widows, 
 how many men of a given age class would marry women of the 
 same age class, how many men of a given nationality would marry 
 
 *Principii di Demografia.
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 121 
 
 women of the same nationality, how many Catholics would marry 
 Catholics, how many men following a given occupation would 
 marry women whose fathers followed the same occupation, if 
 all of these combinations happened strictly by chance. Compar- 
 ing the probable numbers with the actual selections, he obtains 
 index numbers of selective choice or preference, thereby deter- 
 mining the intensity with which, as Empedocles remarked, "like 
 desires like." This method is applicable to a wide range of social 
 choices. 
 
 By a procedure not very different we could measure social 
 pressure. In modern times social pressure is definitely distributed 
 through provisions of statute law, and these admit of tabulations 
 from which index numbers could be obtained. By mears of vary- 
 ing index numbers, therefore, we could measure the varying 
 degrees of social pressure as we measure changes in the purchas- 
 ing power of gold. It is hardly too much to say that all of the 
 chief theorems of sociology probably admit of quantitative state- 
 ment, solution and correlation. 
 
 In this all too hasty survey of sociological problems and meth- 
 ods, certain provisional conclusions have been indicated. But for 
 the moment they seem to involve us in new difficulties. Ap- 
 parently, they present curious contradictions. Mr. Spencer tells 
 us that in society, as in aggregates of inorganic things, the char- 
 acter of the units determines the character of the mass, and daily 
 observation affords many seeming confirmations of this view. 
 The collective behavior and the agreeing purpose of a thousand 
 German-born, or Italian-born Americans, are not altogether like 
 the collective behavior and the agreeing purpose of an equal num- 
 ber of descendants of New England Puritans under like circum- 
 stances and in the same environment. On the other hand, Plato 
 and a long line of later philosophers assumed without question 
 that the character of the mass determines the quality and the 
 conduct of its component units. This assumption is borne out by 
 the biological conclusion that environment moulds the organism, 
 and it is the postulate of both our educational policy and our 
 legislation. That each proposition is true within limits we may 
 perhaps infer from parallel phenomena in the physical world.
 
 122 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 The geologist tells us that rock which is so highly crystalline that 
 it inexorably determines the character of any structure built of 
 it, may, nevertheless, become wax-like under pressure. In like 
 manner, the harshly individualistic character of the frontiersman 
 determines the scope and the quality of the elementary social rela- 
 tions which are sufficient for his need; while in the dense human 
 mass of a great metropolis, with its traditions and conventions, 
 its municipal ordinances and its highly organized police power, the 
 individual becomes plastic and conformable. Some traits of in- 
 dividuality are lost, and the traits of a type, or class, appear. 
 
 The causation is obvious. As social evolution transforms the 
 frontier into villages and towns, and draws population from these 
 to the metropolis, it converts circumstantial into social pressure, 
 which compels the human units of the community to conform 
 their characters and their lives to a social norm. But now another 
 antinomy appears. Sociology confirms the teaching of biology 
 that individuation is a function of liberty, of freedom and occa- 
 sion to vary from type ; and society constrains. Yet society, not- 
 withstanding its constraining power, on the whole diminishes the 
 sacrifice of the individual to the race, enlarges liberty and height- 
 ens individual life. 
 
 The problem again is one of limits, but in this case it is one of 
 new factors also. While circumstantial pressure tends always to 
 increase social pressure, the relation is not unvarying. The physi- 
 cal and the mental composition of the population affect the ratio. 
 Homogeneous communities are normally democratic. Highly 
 heterogeneous communities, until they attain a very high level of 
 moral and intellectual development, normally evolve coercive 
 authority. The Quaker congregation needs not even a priest. 
 The Roman Catholic communion, embracing all sorts and condi- 
 tions of men, is governed by the Hierarchy. The New England 
 town can manage its affairs in town meeting. New York City 
 is ruled by Tammany Hall. 
 
 In this relation of demotic composition to social pressure lies 
 the real importance of those practical questions pertaining to 
 immigration and its restriction which now interest the American 
 people. Homogeneity need not disappear, and social pressure 
 need not increase to the point of despotism if assimilation rapidly
 
 THE HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY 123 
 
 transforms the heterogeneous invaders. Liberty can be preserved 
 and extended even under an increasing circumstantial pressure, 
 as long as society continues to be creative not only of social pres- 
 sure, but also of its strictly characteristic product a people in 
 the sociological sense of the word. 
 
 As the sociologist views it, a people is not merely a middle class, 
 or a lower class, in an economic stratification of the population. 
 Much less is it that rabble of the ignorant and the lawless which 
 bulks in the aristocrat's imagination. A people is a psychological 
 middle class between the arrogant and self-sufficient at one ex- 
 treme, the rude and vulgar at the other extreme. A people is 
 composed of the considerate, which is to say, of those who have 
 both manners and ideas. It is that part of a population which 
 can lay some claim to mental and moral unity, which can do things 
 collectively, which has, in a word, common purposes backed by 
 social instincts and habits. Cicero defined it perfectly. By a 
 people, we are to understand, he said, "not every group of human 
 beings, however brought together, but a multitude united by a 
 common sense of right and by a community of interest." 1 
 
 We are not at the end, however, of complications and of seem- 
 ing contradiction. The nation that should adopt the policy of 
 absolute exclusion of alien elements might lose thereby more than 
 it could gain. We have observed that stimuli are multiplied by 
 social contacts. Who would venture to estimate the amount of 
 well-being that has come to this American nation by reason of 
 that broadened outlook upon the world, that swift play of mind 
 upon mind, and that true understanding of man by man which 
 are ours because our gates have been held open to our kindred 
 of all lands? 
 
 Once more, then, our problem is seen to be one of limits, within 
 which a given effect of social forces may be anticipated. And 
 because this is the nature also of those practical problems with 
 which statecraft has to do, we discover the possible practical 
 value of theoretical sociology as a scientific criticism of public 
 policy. Sociology has been ridiculed as a science which formu- 
 lates in forbidding terminology the obvious conclusions of com- 
 mon sense. The jibe is an old one, and each science in its day has 
 
 *De Republica, I, 25,
 
 124 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 inherited it. By common sense men could build a bridge that 
 would sustain a given load, but they would waste material. Com- 
 mon sense does not tell the engineer what cross-section his girders 
 must have both to carry the load desired and to insure his reten- 
 tion as a fit adviser to an economical corporation. Under the 
 pressure of external forces, either military or economic, nations 
 adopt policies of unification, which often are extreme and unneces- 
 sarily costly in many ways. Reacting from these, they relax the 
 social pressure not only on the socialized and self-controlled, but 
 also on the unscrupulous exploiter and the predatory criminal. It 
 will be possible to subject these empirical policies to a rational 
 criticism when sociology has provided us with approximately ac- 
 curate measures of social forces, and of the correlation between 
 social pressure and both the concentration and the composition 
 of the population. Upon the success or failure of our attempt to 
 obtain these will depend the possibility of knowing certainly what 
 policies under given conditions further human progress, and what 
 retard.
 
 PART II 
 ANALYTICAL
 
 CHAPTER VII 
 
 ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 
 
 To the scientific mind the universe is order; to the practical 
 mind it is possibility. Both minds, however, know that order and 
 possibility are compatible ; it is only the mind that is neither prac- 
 tical nor scientific which imagines that they are not. Therefore, 
 the scientific mind is under logical obligation to show hov order 
 accommodates possibility, and the practical mind, if wise, will 
 wish to know what bounds are set to possibility by order. These 
 intellectual requirements bear particularly upon those specialized 
 investigators who undertake to find an order, admitting of descrip- 
 tion in categories of cause and law, in the practical activities them- 
 selves of all sorts and conditions of men. If they proclaim a 
 science of society they must themselves understand, and they must 
 make clear to others, what they mean by "cause" when they talk 
 about social causation, and what they mean by "law" when they 
 set forth sociological laws. They must know what "order" is and 
 what "possibility" is. 
 
 At the general session of the German Association of Naturalists 
 and Physicians, held at Vienna in September, 1894, an Austrian 
 physicist, Ernst Mach, delivered an address which every scientific 
 inquirer should know. It was entitled, "On the Principle of Com- 
 parison in Physics." In substance it was a lucid analysis of the 
 nature of scientific thought, and incidentally of the true nature 
 of science itself. Dr. Mach began by recalling a definition of 
 mechanics which had been given twenty years before by Kirch- 
 hoff. Mechanics, Kirchhoff had said, is "the description, in com- 
 plete and very simple terms, of the motions occurring in nature." 
 This definition had agitated scientific circles. It contained no 
 mention of explanation or of prediction as functions of science, no 
 allusion to universal or cosmic law, no hint of any search for 
 
 127
 
 128 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 first principles or causes. The scientific mind was perturbed. 
 Was science, the supreme achievement of the nineteenth century, 
 about to abandon its chief pretensions? Mechanics is of all 
 sciences the most exact and the most advanced. If, then, me- 
 chanics is nothing but description, no other branch of knowledge 
 can claim to be more. To demonstrate that this is the simple and 
 practically helpful truth was the task that Dr. Mach essayed. 
 
 I shall not attempt to repeat the demonstration in detail. It 
 consisted in showing that description is a putting together of facts 
 in a coherent system or continuum, which accurately corresponds 
 to the coherent system or continuum of reality ; and that explana- 
 tion, prediction, the formulation of laws, are nothing more and 
 nothing less. When, for example, the physicist formulates the 
 law of gravitation, as an attraction of bodies for one another 
 which varies directly with their masses, and inversely with the 
 squares of their distances, and predicts that an unsupported body 
 will fall toward or rise away from the surface of the earth ac- 
 cording as its specific gravity is greater or less -than that of the 
 atmospheric envelope, he merely puts together, in a single con- 
 densed expression, a large number of observed coherences of 
 fact. 
 
 What, however, are observed facts ? Is the "attraction" which 
 the formula alleges one of them? Yes or no, according to our 
 definition of the word. Shall we say that it is the "pull" of a 
 "force"? Has any human being ever seen, handled, or otherwise 
 perceived a force ? Certainly not. And what, moreover, does any 
 human being know of a "pull" ? Nothing whatever beyond cer- 
 tain sensations of muscular tension or of political fatigue. All, 
 then, that can actually be observed of attraction is a certain num- 
 ber of changes in the successive positions of material objects, and 
 a certain number of changes in the degrees of rapidity with which 
 the changes of position take place. All that we can really experi- 
 ment with is a number of volumes, densities, positions, distances, 
 accelerations, and retardations. And our formula or law, there- 
 fore, is nothing more than an accurate description of the way in 
 which these observed facts cohere in an objective series or system 
 of reality. The object of science is to extend description, in this 
 sense of the word, until it includes all knowable facts of matter,
 
 ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 129 
 
 life, mind, and society, and places each fact in its proper place 
 in the complete system. 
 
 This conception of science, the only one which a critical exami- 
 nation of the nature of our knowledge permits us to entertain, 
 discloses practical values. As science approaches perfection, the 
 description of the cosmos becomes continuous. We discover that 
 every known fact has, in coexistence and in sequence, points of 
 contact with other known facts. The lines and colors in our 
 chart of the universe are not drawn or splashed at random ; they 
 lie before the mental vision in an order of gradations, proportions, 
 series, and systems. Facts in any part of the chart are seen to be 
 related to all facts in every other part. So we arrive at the con- 
 ception of nature as a system of interdependent facts. This con- 
 ception once reached, we perceive what really we mean when we 
 say that science enables us to predict combinations of facts not 
 hitherto observed. Convinced by what we already know, that 
 further description of nature will not derange the system already 
 apparent, we expect that further knowledge will continue the 
 curves already partly drawn, without changing their equations, 
 fill in unknown terms of series without changing their formulas, 
 and supply shades of color that will not disturb the scheme al- 
 ready apparent. In this way science enables us to anticipate facts 
 not yet actually observed. If, then, we admit that science is de- 
 scription, and that description both reveals and presupposes the 
 interdependence of the descriptive elements, we can accept the 
 theoretical and practical conclusion at which Dr. Mach arrives, 
 that science completes in thought facts that are only partly given. 
 
 So understood, scientific description, it is plain, is both concrete 
 and abstract. It not only depicts, pictorially, in colors, shapes, 
 and perspectives as we perceive them, but also it factorizes, re- 
 solving concretes into sorts, sizes, positions, sequences, arrange- 
 ments, proportions, correlations and coordinations, as we conceive 
 them. 
 
 Therefore after all, science does explain, in a certain logical, 
 non-mystical, sense of the word. Resolving perceived or concrete 
 wholes into conceptual or abstract factors which, in turn, forecast 
 new concrete wholes that when looked for at the right time and 
 place will be perceivable, scientific description discovers the pos-
 
 130 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 sibilities of interchangeability between perceptions and concep- 
 tions. 1 
 
 Now to forecast from abstract factors or concepts (organized 
 into a theory) new concrete wholes that turn out to be perceivable, 
 is to predict ; and to perceive new concrete wholes that have been 
 predicted is to verify the conceptual theory. Precisely this is 
 what the scientific man means by explanation. Whatever else 
 passes for explanation is either a pretense, falling short of ex- 
 planation or missing it, or it is a metaphysical leap into the un- 
 known, and is unverifiable. 
 
 So it comes to this, that scientific explanation is description in 
 conceptual terms carried to the limits within which verification by 
 perception is possible, and that conceptual description verifiable 
 and verified by perception, is explanation. 
 
 The notion "causation'' like the notion "explanation" has had 
 a past of which the less said the better. It has kept company with 
 metaphysics. But that is no reason why it should not usefully be 
 employed in science, under a watchful eye. If we talk about 
 "explanation," we must talk about "causation" because, as will 
 appear, explanation is a discovery of causation. 
 
 Observe what happens. When we explain a thing or happening 
 we factorize it. The process goes on in our minds. The thing 
 or happening itself is an object outside of the mental process of 
 explaining it. Whether or not it is also outside of our minds or 
 of any and all minds is another question. Objectively it is the 
 perfect integration of its factors. If any factor be lacking the 
 thing does not exist, or the happening does not happen. There- 
 fore the perfect integration of its factors is the cause (in any 
 possible scientific meaning of the word) of the thing or happen- 
 ing. Factorizing brings to light the integration, and explanation 
 by factorizing, consequently, is a discovery of causation. 
 
 Loosely we speak of a dominant factor (outranging guns, over- 
 whelming numbers), or of a last contributed factor (the lighted 
 match applied to the fuel), or to a factor to which responsibility 
 attaches (a casting vote) as a cause, or as the cause of something. 
 This is rhetoric only, but it is harmless and convenient. 2 
 
 'On this subject compare Karl Pearson, The Grammar of Science, 
 and Bertrand Russell, Mysticism and Logic. 
 ' The conception of causation as the integration of factors is substan-
 
 ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 131 
 
 As the scientific description which is also explanation is a dis- 
 covery of causation, so also is it a discovery and formulation of 
 law. Any persisting relation (correlation, superordination, co- 
 ordination, or subordination) of factors is a reality which is or 
 may be formulated as a scientific generalization or as a scientific 
 law. 1 
 
 It is now necessary to observe that while law and cause are 
 categories of order to which science undertakes to reduce the 
 description of its results, they are not, as a rule, the categories 
 used in obtaining results. 
 
 Research begins, as the unconscious acquisition of knowledge 
 begins, with the simplicities of discrimination and counting; and 
 the categories, therefore, that we first use in factorizing are num- 
 ber (count of discriminated items) ; qualitative difference and 
 qualitative resemblance ; and quantitative difference, or inequality. 
 After these, the categories chiefly available in discovery are corre- 
 lation (comprising all degrees of association, concurrence and con- 
 tingency) ; composition ; coordination (together with superordina- 
 tion and subordination) ; and mechanistic reaction. 
 
 tially identical with the more loosely defined conceptions of Mill's Logic 
 and Jevons's Principles of Science, long accepted as the last word on 
 the subject. The "necessary antecedent" of an effect, which Mill called 
 a "condition," is simply any one factor ; and the "sufficient antecedent," 
 which he tagged as "cause," is the integration of all factors, and cannot 
 conceivably be anything else. 
 
 1 When it is worth while to be precise we must discriminate between 
 a constant relation of a static phenomenon to a static, and a constant 
 relation of a kinetic phenomenon to a kinetic. It is therefore convenient 
 to associate the word "generalization" with the one, and the word "law" 
 with the other. 
 
 "A generalization, in the scientific sense of the word, is an affirmation 
 that a constant relation exists between an unvarying class of facts and 
 some unvarying fact not in the class, or between one unvarying class of 
 facts and some other unvarying class. . . . Kepler's law ... is a gen- 
 eralization." 
 
 "A law, in the scientific sense of the word, is an affirmation of a 
 constant relation between a fact of variation and some other fact of 
 variation, or between a fact of variation and a class of variations, or 
 between a class of variations and some other class of variations. . . . The 
 law of gravitation. . . ." 
 
 "A class, in the scientific sense of the word, is a plural number of 
 facts that resemble one another in some given point or number of points." 
 
 "A fact, in the scientific sense of the word, is the close agreement of 
 many observations or measurements of the same phenomenon." Giddings, 
 Inductive Sociology, pp. 13, 14.
 
 132 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 Of correlation, two great subcategories are recognized for 
 practical purposes, namely, perfect correlation, or "one to one 
 correspondence," and imperfect correlation. Mathematically they 
 are merely differences of degree. 
 
 Within the limits of our experience a designated thing or hap- 
 pening may invariably be associated with another designated thing 
 or happening, and the ratio of one to the other throughout any 
 succession of quantitative changes may so nearly be constant that 
 our best instruments of precision do not enable us to detect a 
 deviation which philosophical or mathematical theories of rela- 
 tivity presume to be possible. The acceleration of a falling body 
 in a unit of time, the pressure of a gas at a given temperature, the 
 ratio of a degree of heat to a gravitational foot pound, are ex- 
 amples. In finite experience these are substantially one to one 
 correspondences : there is always so much of one to so much of 
 the other, point by point. They are one hundred per cent, or 
 "perfect," correlations. They are the so-called "immutable" laws 
 of nature. Conceivable deviations from them, if there are such, 
 are infinitesimal, and for human purposes negligible. 
 
 Correlations of the other subcategory are imperfect. A desig- 
 nated thing or happening is associated or is concurrent with an- 
 other designated thing or happening in less than one hundred 
 percent of all cases known or taken, or the ratio of one to the 
 other is variable. If, however, variation is within assignable 
 limits, and the percentage number of instances of association 
 whether large or small is constant, we have in the phenomena an 
 order on which we can rely. Indeed, for the purposes of every- 
 day life we rely on it as confidently as on one to one correspon- 
 dences. We sow expecting to reap. We plan journeys expecting 
 that trains and boats will run by time tables and predetermined 
 dates. We make business and professional engagements expect- 
 ing that parties of the other part will keep appointments. We buy 
 and sell commodities and securities expecting that price fluctua- 
 tions will range within familiar limits. We bring up and educate 
 children knowing that they have an ascertainable "expectation" 
 of life. 
 
 Perfect correlations are "certainties" in a finite meaning of the 
 word. Imperfect correlations are "probabilities" ; either positive,
 
 ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 133 
 
 ranging from o to I, or negative, ranging from o to I. To 
 the extent that a science measures "chances" above or below 
 "fifty-fifty," it is a science of probability. If it discovers and 
 demonstrates one to one correspondences it is, so far, exact. Me- 
 chanics, thermo-dynamics, and chemistry, are exact sciences. 
 Biology, psychology, and sociology, are sciences of probability in 
 the main, but exact in detail here and there. 
 
 Perfect correlation while it persists sets limits to possibility and 
 makes it determinate. Imperfect correlation leaves it indetermi- 
 nate. The crop may fail or be "a bumper," stocks may go down 
 or go up, beyond precedent. 
 
 And as a concrete phenomenon a particular correlation whether 
 perfect or imperfect, is not necessarily persistent : when a falling 
 body hits the ground the correlation of acceleration wuh time 
 ceases as far as this instance is concerned. The happening, or 
 the evolution, or the making of correlations determines possi- 
 bility; the termination of correlations removes or sets back 
 bounds, and restores indeterminateness. 
 
 In attending to associations of things, or of happenings, that 
 are liable to dissociation and recombination we pass from simple 
 correlation to multiple correlation, or composition. Here also 
 possibility is determined and limited at any given time by an ex- 
 isting order ; nevertheless, it is unimaginably great. The items of 
 which the universe consists are combined, and the combinations 
 are compounded: electrons in atoms, atoms in molecules, inor- 
 ganic molecules in inorganic masses, protoplasmic molecules in 
 organic cells, cells in complex living bodies, and these in groups or 
 populations; reactions in acts, acts in complex behavior, and be- 
 havior in competitions and cooperations, customs and institutions, 
 movements and policies that constitute society and history. 
 
 Some of these compounds are homogeneous, their component 
 items are of one kind ; others are heterogeneous, their component 
 items are of various kinds. Some of them, atoms above all, are 
 stable and long enduring; others, the nitrogenous compounds con- 
 spicuously, are unstable, easily, and often quickly, broken up ; yet 
 others, organic bodies, simultaneously break up and build up, by 
 continually eliminating outworn components and replacing them 
 with new. The relation of possibility to composition turns upon
 
 134 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 these differences. The greater its heterogeneity, the greater its 
 instability, the more rapid its metabolism, the quicker its reaction 
 of release or of inhibition, the more indeterminate is possibility: 
 the greater is the number of possible happenings constructive or 
 destructive, good or bad, to, in or by a composite body : the greater 
 is what the untutored man and the philosopher (without col- 
 lusion) call its "freedom" or its "liberty," or, perhaps, its "self- 
 determination." 
 
 Component bodies may not only be different in kind but also be 
 unequal, in age, size, energy, attribute or condition. If numerous, 
 some of them may be equal among themselves, while superior or 
 inferior to others. Equals are said to be coordinate, superiors 
 to be superordinate (a super order) and inferiors subordinate (a 
 sub order). Planets are approximately coordinate; suns by com- 
 parison with planets are superordinate, and satellites, by com- 
 parison with planets are subordinate. These distinctions may be 
 categorical only, or they may appear in a concrete arrangement, 
 a hierarchy of ranks. The solar system is such an arrangement, 
 so is the hierarchy of living bodies, from bacteria to man. For 
 brevity, hierarchical arrangement is called "coordination," super- 
 ordination and subordination being assumed. In human society 
 throughout history coordination has been a phenomenon of com- 
 manding importance. Hierarchies of priests, bishops, and arch- 
 bishops; of private soldiers, officers and commanders; of serfs, 
 freemen and nobles; of wage earners, capitalists and magnates, 
 have ordered and determined human life. 
 
 The sciences, as Comte discerned and contended, are hierarchi- 
 cally related. The progress of knowledge, however, has neces- 
 sitated a revision of the order that he set down, and new designa- 
 tions. The series as it now stands is: mechanics, electro-physics 
 and electro-chemistry, chemistry, thermo-dynamics, astronomy 
 and geology (these two are complexes of the preceding four), 
 biology, psychology, anthropology, ethnology, archaeology, history, 
 and sociology. 
 
 It is unnecessary to offer evidence that coordination determines 
 and limits possibility. The proposition is obvious, and vivid to 
 human experience. 
 
 So far we have looked at static order, and its determination of
 
 ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 135 
 
 possibility. When we turn to observe the happening that we call 
 mechanistic reaction, we concern ourselves with kinetic order. 
 
 Every reaction that can be identified and measured by organs 
 of sense is mechanistic. If anywhere in the material universe 
 there is a going on, or creative evolution, that is not mechanistic, 
 it belongs to a realm of things not seen except through Alice's (or 
 other philosophers') looking-glass. Conceding the perspicacity of 
 Alice, and' admitting that explanation of brain functioning, or 
 even of digestion, in mechanistic terms has not yet been achieved 
 completely, the scientific inquirer asks people who make them- 
 selves responsible for theories of human behavior not to pro- 
 nounce achievement impossible and not to accept the revelations 
 of the speculative glass until they have taken the trouble to learn 
 what "mechanistic terms" are (and are not) and whether the 
 explanatory possibilities of mechanistic hypothesis have been 
 exhausted. 
 
 To begin then with terms, or conceptions, what is the order 
 that we call mechanistic? Concisely, it is a system of equivalent 
 sensible changes. And what is it not, or not necessarily or al- 
 ways ? Concisely, a mechanistic phenomenon is never a change of 
 nothing into something or of something into nothing; and a mech- 
 anistic system is not necessarily or always machinistic; more 
 often than not it is merely ballistic. 
 
 A sensible change is a change that we become aware of through 
 any one of our organs of sense, or through any combination of 
 them. It is more tangible than a change of mind. Sensible 
 change is motion, and every motion is equivalent to motion out 
 of which it came, and to motion into which it goes. The changing 
 modes or kinds of motion may be different or various ; electronic, 
 atomic, molecular, molar, but the rule of equivalence holds. The 
 mechanistic order of the material universe therefore is a system 
 of equivalent motions. 
 
 This proposition means the same thing that the so-called New- 
 tonian laws of motion mean, namely that reaction is equal to 
 action and opposite to it in direction; that a body (or particle) 
 at rest remains at rest, and a body (or particle) in motion con- 
 tinues in motion until impelled, drawn or impeded from without ; 
 and that a body in motion moves in a straight line until deflected
 
 136 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 from without. The proposition is equivalent therefore to Spen- 
 cer's affirmation of the persistence of force. It is equivalent also 
 to the law of the so-called degradation of energy, of which more 
 will be said presently. 
 
 But it does not follow from the laws of motion that all motion 
 is machinistic, or that the mechanistic order of a material universe 
 is a machine. The billiard balls on a table where men are playing 
 are not a machine, and their motions, while strictly mechanistic, 
 are never machinistic. The material universe as a whole is not a 
 machine ; parts of it only are machines, other parts are in process 
 of becoming machines, and yet other parts remain wild turbu- 
 lences. Neglect or inability to apprehend the distinction here 
 made accounts, I am convinced, for most of the antagonism of 
 "vitalistic" biologists and "idealistic" or "spiritual" sociologists to 
 mechanistic explanations of the life processes and the behavior 
 of material organisms. A few further words of amplification 
 and illustration may, therefore, be helpful. 
 
 A machine is a system of parts so tied or linked together, or so 
 coupled or geared, or otherwise so correlated that their motions 
 are one to one correspondences, or correspondences within limits 
 of error that are negligible in prediction : they are definitely mech- 
 anistic. In contrast, a turbulence (for example a swirl of dust, 
 a tornado, or a torrent) is an assemblage of particles or larger 
 units that move freely in any direction : their motions are indefi- 
 nitely mechanistic. A solar system is a machine; a flaming gas 
 is a turbulence ; a nebula is a turbulence that is becoming or may 
 become, a machine. A germ cell, a brain, a politically organized 
 community, is half turbulence and half machine. 
 
 In a system that has become a machine possibility is limited 
 and determined ; in a turbulence it is indeterminate. 
 
 The extent to which mechanistic order limits possibility in 
 particular cases, and the ways or modes of determination, are of 
 cardinal importance to students of social theory. Much social 
 theorizing has been futile because of neglect to master them. 
 
 Pretentious social philosophies could be cited (they are taught 
 in colleges), the makers and builders of which unconsciously and 
 in all innocence postulate something from nothing or nothing
 
 ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 137 
 
 from something, because, appalled by the complexities, they will 
 not take the trouble to understand the simplicities of the degrada- 
 tion of energy. 
 
 This expression is an abbreviation for: the dynamic degrada- 
 tion of a concrete body of matter. It means that energy "does 
 something" (it "works") only when a delimited portion of the 
 "matter" that in final analysis perhaps is energy, or that "carries" 
 energy, or is charged with it, falls from a higher to a lower gravi- 
 tational level, like water from a dam ; or from a higher to a lower 
 tension, like an uncoiling watch spring; or from a higher to a 
 lower temperature, like expanding steam back of a piston head ; 
 or from a higher to a lower magnetic state, like the reacting arma- 
 ture of a dynamo; or from a more to a less unstable equilibrium, 
 like an exploding mixture. 
 
 The energy content of matter not yet dynamically degraded is 
 rightly called "potential." It is unexpended, and ready to do 
 something. Energy doing something is called kinetic. The por- 
 tion of matter that carried it is losing it, and so is undergoing 
 dynamic degradation. The energy content of matter that at pres- 
 ent can undergo no further dynamic degradation is wrongly called 
 "potential," apparently for no better reason than that it is not 
 kinetic. It has become, in fact, impotential. 
 
 It has become impotential, and the portion of matter now car- 
 rying it can undergo no further dynamic degradation, because the 
 energy content of that particular body of matter is now in equilib- 
 rium with the energy content of matter round about it. Equi- 
 librium is inertness. 
 
 So, it turns out, the degradation of energy is "the equilibration 
 of energy." This expression also is an abbreviation. It means: 
 the equilibration of the energy content of bodies of matter so 
 placed in relation to one another that energy (molar motion, or 
 molecular motion, or atomic motion, or electronic motion) can 
 and does flow from the more highly charged to the less highly 
 charged body. 
 
 Inasmuch as this process is finite and relative, it follows that 
 when we say of a delimited portion of matter a that it can un- 
 dergo no further dynamic degradation, we mean that a can suffer 
 no such further degradation under existing states of environing
 
 i 3 8 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 matter b. If the energy content of b at any time suffers depletion, 
 a in contact with b can be further degraded, and its contained 
 energy will then become potential or kinetic. Furthermore, a 
 dynamically degraded material body or "closed system" of matter 
 can be recharged with potential energy from without, if energy 
 from supercharged bodies hitherto shut off from it can be trans- 
 mitted to it and suitably transformed. The mill can grind again 
 with water thai has passed if sun energy lifts it to the clouds to 
 fall in rain above the dam. The watch spring can be wound, and 
 the exhausted steam can be passed again through the boiler. 
 
 In this process, however, further rules of order are encoun- 
 tered which set new limits to possibility. In transformation and 
 transmission energy is lost, not out of the universe, but out of 
 concrete material bodies, the charging or supercharging of which 
 is work. The ratio of work to loss (i.e. to waste) increases up to 
 a point experimentally ascertained. It then diminishes until, 
 presently, waste increases faster than work. These differential 
 ratios of loss, waste, or "cost" to work accomplished, are en- 
 countered throughout natural phenomena and human industry, 
 and are known as laws of increasing and diminishing return. 
 They were first brought to attention by economists, and all scien- 
 tific economy is founded on them. Economists of the paradoxical 
 school who deny them do not know their elementary physics and 
 talk nonsense. Economists who acknowledge these laws but 
 teach that they are unimportant to "up-to-date" man' because 
 invention diminishes waste, and discovery from time to time finds 
 new sources of potential energy, never squarely face the real 
 dilemma, which is, that inventions which diminish waste and tap 
 hitherto unknown stores of potential energy call for the use of 
 very special substances, for example high grade steels, fine cop- 
 per, nickel, platinum, and so on to uranium and radium, all of 
 which as our present knowledge goes, are of limited supply, and 
 some of which are excessively rare. 
 
 Whether the future will bring reassurance no one can predict. 
 At present mankind is wastefully using up and wantonly de- 
 stroying available sources of potential energy : coal, oil, gas, for- 
 ests, and entire species of plant and animal life that are the con- 
 verters of sunlight and sun heat into foods on which the human
 
 ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 139 
 
 race can subsist. To conserve them is becoming the most im- 
 perative of obligations. 
 
 While the equilibration of energy limits possibility quantita- 
 tively, it also determines the modes and forms of possibility, and 
 this qualitative process is evolution. 
 
 When a delimited aggregation of matter (gaseous, liquid or 
 solid) is losing molecular motion (radiating heat into environing 
 matter of a lower temperature, as molten metal does in cooling), 
 it condenses or, using Mr. Spencer's term, it "integrates." At 
 the same time, different parts of it become unlike one another in 
 various ways, because radiation proceeds at unequal rates from 
 different surface areas and from the surface and the interior of 
 the mass ; and because different areas and interior parts are vari- 
 ously played upon by energies from without. The cooling metal 
 wrinkles, and may twist or crack. The influences that bring about 
 "differentiation" bring about also sortings and assimilations of 
 molecules and their compounds. Units of like weight and shape 
 get thrown together, as stones do in one place, pebbles in another 
 place and sand in another place along the roadside during a rain. 
 This assorting Mr. Spencer called "segregation." It is supple- 
 mented by a deeper change which he failed to name in his formula. 
 Just as units differently reacting to incidental energies become 
 increasingly different, so do units similarly reacting become in- 
 creasingly alike they are assimilated and this phase of the evo- 
 lutionary process is important in the phenomena of life and be- 
 havior. It is especially significant for the student of social 
 theory. 
 
 These four consequences of the equilibration of molecular 
 energy, namely integration, differentiation, segregation and as- 
 similation, make up mechanistic evolution in its simple or primary 
 phase. Mr. Spencer, who first apprehended and described it, 
 described also a secondary phase, or compound evolution, which 
 occurs when the integrating aggregate is taking in molecular mo- 
 tion from without while losing it from within, as the earth, for 
 example, gets heat from the sun while radiating it into space, 
 and as living bodies while expending their energies take in fresh 
 stores, in the foods on which they subsist. The total loss of 
 energy in these cases exceeds the total intake (when the ratio is
 
 140 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 reversed dissolution begins) but evolution is slowed down, and 
 secondary differentiations and segregations are multiplied through 
 internal redistributions of energy. 
 
 All of these changes conform quantitatively to the laws of in- 
 creasing and diminishing return, which, therefore, in the strict 
 sense of the word are the laws, as distinguished from the general 
 description or formula, of mechanistic evolution. 1 
 
 Yet another phase of evolution not described, or named, by 
 Mr. Spencer, is even more important for biology, psychology and 
 sociology than assimilation is. 
 
 The equilibration of molecular motion with which mechanistic 
 evolution begins is an extra or an inter equilibration. It occurs, 
 as has been said, between a delimited aggregation of material 
 units and matter extraneous. There is also, however, from the 
 first, an infra equilibration: an equalizing of molecular motion 
 between each differentiated part and every other part, between 
 each group of segregated units and every other group, within the 
 aggregate. 
 
 Mr. Spencer saw and was at pains to explain the redistributions 
 of internal motion that go on step by step with the integration of 
 matter and the differentiation of its groupings, and the conse- 
 quent multiplication of effects ; and he insisted on the importance 
 of adequate time for the completion of redistribution as a factor 
 in the evolution of high types of structure and function. He did 
 not discover that among multiplying effects intra equilibration 
 creates a mechanism and sustains a process of internal control of 
 evolution, that is quite as important as external controls. In 
 living matter, in nervous systems, and in political society it is 
 often more important. 
 
 The equilibration of energy between the sun and the planets 
 more directly and more intensively than equilibration between the 
 solar system as a whole and whatever fills the spaces beyond it 
 has controlled the development of planetary surfaces, of hydro- 
 graphic and atmospheric changes, and the evolution of life. 
 Equilibration within the cell as much as equilibration between cell 
 and environment determines all that is characteristic of living 
 matter both in structure and in function. Equilibration between 
 
 1 Giddings, "The Laws of Evolution," Science, August 18, 1905.
 
 ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 141 
 
 the central nervous system and other organs and tissues creates 
 the characteristic controls of behavior. In the evolution of po- 
 litically organized nations extra and inter equilibrations take the 
 form of war and conquests, while intra equilibrations appear as 
 class struggles and revolutions. Governments and their functions 
 are products of equilibrations between a relatively small group of 
 alert and persistent men reacting to situations, and a relatively 
 large mass of men that are inert and ineffective. 
 
 Development of internal structures and controls in living bodies 
 produces numerous machines ; among which the articulated skele- 
 ton, the circulatory apparatus, and the central nervous system, are 
 outstanding examples that everybody in a measure understands. 
 Many of them, the organs of sense preeminently, are complicated 
 and delicate, but their performance is not often the precise one- 
 to-one correspondence that we look for in machines made by man. 
 The reason for deviation is highly significant. Organic machines 
 are automatically adaptable to changing conditions to a degree 
 that artificial machines do not attain. 
 
 The apparatus of heredity and of mutation is machine-like in 
 form but is ballistic in performance ; except in one particular, if 
 the non-inheritance of characters acquired after birth turns out 
 to be a one hundred per cent correlation. The Mendelian propor- 
 tions in which the traits of two ancestral lines are transmitted are 
 a high but not a perfect correlation. Mutation apparently is con- 
 tingent upon "cross overs" of chromosome halves, but these may 
 be brought about in more than one accidental way, as well as by 
 experimental predetermination. As a general proposition we can 
 say that heredity is a relatively strict determination and limitation 
 of biological possibility, while mutation is relatively indeterminate. 
 
 A similar general proposition holds true in the domain of be- 
 havioristic psychology. Behavior is a function of two variables, 
 namely, stimulation and the performance of a reaction apparatus. 
 Development of the reaction apparatus including internal controls, 
 limits and defines the possibilities of behavior. Stimulation is 
 indeterminate, and forever will be. 
 
 At this point it is interesting to inquire why mankind has always 
 more or less resented the proposition that life is mechanistic, and, 
 has clung to "free will" in the realm of conduct. The usual
 
 142 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 answer, that we like to believe that we are "spiritual" beings and 
 "responsible," is more orthodox than informing. If the evolu- 
 tionist biology is substantially trustworthy the true answer, it 
 would seem, must be that this prejudice is a by-product of the 
 adjustment of life to a world in which luck plays its part against 
 certainty ; in which correlation is not always one hundred per cent ; 
 in which the mechanistic is as often ballistic as machinistic. As- 
 suming that such adjustment has been under way from the be- 
 ginning, it is not surprising that man likes it. He may flatter 
 himself that he likes it because he experiences exaltation (not to 
 mention self-esteem) when he freely chooses the true and the 
 good, but, notoriously, he likes it no less well when he chooses 
 the false and the bad. 
 
 In a famous passage Mr. Huxley said : 
 
 "I protest that if some great power would agree to make me always 
 think what is true and do what is right, on condition of being turned 
 into a sort of clock and wound up every morning before I got out of 
 bed, I should instantly close with the offer. The only freedom I care 
 about is the freedom to do right; the freedom to do wrong I am ready 
 to part with on the cheapest terms to any one who will take it of me." * 
 
 Without abatement of respect for one of the clearest-headed 
 men that ever lived, I protest that Mr. Huxley did not think 
 what is true, in this instance. Man wants freedom both to do 
 right and to sin, to know and to guess wrong, as may happen, no 
 less than as he, in his self-determination may choose; and he 
 wants this large freedom (immeasurably wider than "moral" 
 freedom) because he is so made up and adapted that he craves, 
 with a modicum of certainty, a large measure of chance. He is 
 glad to know that summer will follow winter, an important matter 
 of course, but he is not less glad that when it does follow he again 
 will bet on the horse race, the stock market and the election. 
 Above all, he wants adventure, of thought, decision and experi- 
 ence. He swells with self-determination, relying on his own 
 apparatus of internal controls, but he could never again be happy 
 if he were deprived of his self-indetermination. He wants to 
 
 1 Essay On Descartes "Discourse Touching the ^ Method of Using One's 
 Reason Rightly and of Seeking Scientific Truth."
 
 ORDER AND POSSIBILITY 143 
 
 change his mind when he wants to, and to go back for his um- 
 brella. 
 
 Well, he always will. He lives in a world in which, for all we 
 know, reaction mechanisms may become machines as perfect as 
 Huxley's hypothetical clock, except that they will have to be 
 played on by stimuli instead of wound, and that the stimuli will 
 swirl forever in turbulences, and play pranks.
 
 CHAPTER VIII 
 
 A THEORY OF SOCIAL CAUSATION 
 
 USING the word "causation" in the stricter of the meanings 
 defended in Chapter VII, and assuming, in accordance with it, 
 that social causes are stimulations that call forth pluralistic reac- 
 tions of a particular kind or of various kinds, I shall attempt in 
 this chapter to examine the phenomena of social causation from 
 the standpoint of stimulation, and in Chapter IX to describe them 
 in terms of response. In the remaining chapters of this Part, I 
 shall look at stimulations and responses, actions and reactions, as 
 concretely inseparable in pluralistic behavior. 
 
 I have before me a pile of newspaper accounts of assemblings 
 of human beings, from small gatherings to great crowds. In one 
 hundred and thirty-one instances the occasions, circumstances, 
 situations or other stimulations which brought the participants 
 together have been stated by the reporters. These stimulations 
 are most various but fall into classification as follows: natural 
 resources of a geographical place or region, 4 ; drought, 2 ; storm, 
 i ; conflagration, 2 ; epidemic, i ; war, 8 ; insurrection, 10 ; minor 
 occurrences of human origin, 87; personal example, appeal, or 
 intimidation, 16. 
 
 Here, obviously, are two contrasted kinds of stimuli namely, 
 static situations consisting chiefly or perhaps wholly of regional 
 influences changing so slowly that change is negligible, and kinetic 
 situations consisting of regional changes disturbing to mankind, 
 and of other circumstantial influences. The circumstantial in- 
 fluences are divisible into a, those consisting of physical factors 
 only or chiefly (drought, storm, conflagration, epidemic), and b, 
 those consisting of human factors only or chiefly (war, insurrec- 
 tion, minor occurrences of human origin and personal example, 
 appeal and intimidation). 
 
 Also, obviously, the stimuli here classified are of two orders, 
 primary and secondary. The influences that consist wholly or 
 
 144
 
 MS 
 
 chiefly of human factors are products of past responses to ante- 
 cedent stimulations. The numerical preponderance of these cases 
 in our data indicates that a major part of all pluralistic behavior 
 is provoked by secondary stimuli, and this we know (by every day 
 observation) to be true. The very arrangements under which we 
 live, the groupings and the doings of our fellow men, their ideas 
 and purposes, their laws and institutions, are ever present, ever 
 potent causes of continuing collective action. But back of all 
 secondary stimuli, products of past social life, are primary or 
 original stimuli presented to every mind by the multiplicity and 
 presence of fellow beings, by the events and the order of nature, 
 and by the concrete objects of nature. These collectively are the 
 environment, human and physical, and the human is determined 
 by the physical. As physical environments differ in fundamental 
 character and in complexity, so differ the original stimuli to 
 which the minds of men respond in pluralistic behavior, including 
 collective action. 
 
 Accepting the .distinctions that have been drawn between static 
 and kinetic situations, and between primary and secondary stimuli 
 we apprehend the prime requirement laid upon social theory. A 
 scientific theory of social causation must first give full recogni- 
 tion and weight to the facts (i) that regional influences of the 
 static sort usually stimulate behavior (when they do stimulate it) 
 through a medium of circumstance rather than immediately, and 
 (2) that all stimuli of the primary order, including regional 
 changes, usually stimulate behavior (when they do stimulate it) 
 through a social medium created by antecedent stimulation. 
 Theory must then determine what are the possibilities and limits 
 of response to primary stimulation, and, thereby, determine the 
 possibilities and limits of secondary stimulation. 
 
 In trying to formulate (at least tentatively) a theory scientific 
 according to these specifications, we necessarily begin with an at- 
 tempt to discover what features of the physical habitat of a 
 human population are significant, and through what channels 
 or groupings of concrete fact they exert their controlling influence. 
 
 The earlier theories of the relation of environment to national 
 life and character placed emphasis upon the direct influence of 
 soil, climate and topography upon mental and institutional life.
 
 146 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 Montesquieu hardly got beyond this simple view of the prob- 
 lem. He attributes a relatively great boldness to the inhabitants 
 of cold climates, and to boldness he attributes frankness and a 
 lack of suspicion and cunning. To the enervating influence of 
 great heat, and the deliciousness of rest in a hot climate, he at- 
 tributes the belief of the Hindoo that "repose and non-existence 
 are the foundation of all things, and the end in which they termi- 
 nate." From these temperamental effects of climate Montesquieu 
 thought that he could derive systems of laws and institutions. His 
 observations, nevertheless, were keen and significant, and doubt- 
 less much important scientific work is yet to be done in following 
 out the suggestions in which the Esprit des Lois abounds. 
 
 Buckle, perceiving that the action of environment upon national 
 life is more complex than Montesquieu represented it, laid em- 
 phasis upon those influences of nature that develop on the one hand 
 the emotional, on the other hand the intellectual habit. Regions 
 in which nature is uncertain, violent and destructive, especially 
 where earthquakes, volcanic catastrophies and tempests abound, 
 inspire terror and superstition, and thereby unfit the mind for 
 scientific research and for the systematic conquest of the external 
 world. Regions that are tractable, having seldom more startling 
 occurrences than the regular succession of seasons and the rela- 
 tively mild storms of the temperate zones, awaken an intellectual 
 interest; and by suggesting a constant order in nature, they lead 
 the mind on to scientific comprehension. Buckle also made the 
 distinction between primary and secondary civilizations, and drew 
 attention to the exceeding importance of the relation existing be- 
 tween any secondary civilization and that environment which is 
 human and historical rather than physical. So, clearly enough, 
 although without psychological analysis, Buckle discriminates be- 
 tween static regional influences and kinetic or circumstantial in- 
 fluences, and between primary and secondary stimulations. 
 
 Herbert Spencer, in the first volume of his Principles of So- 
 ciology, comprehensively reviews the influence of climates and 
 topographies upon the emotional and the intellectual natures of 
 men, and he calls especial attention to the relation of the flora and 
 the fauna to the possibilities of social evolution. He lays chief 
 stress, however, upon the human environment, since it is in the
 
 A THEORY OF SOCIAL CAUSATION 14? 
 
 relation of a tribe or a nation to its stronger or weaker neighbors 
 that the causes determining its type of organization as military or 
 industrial, seem to him to be found. 
 
 In the writings of Ratzell and of Ellen Churchill Semple we 
 have expert studies extending and correcting our knowledge of 
 the influence of persisting geographical features including oceans 
 and seas, islands and continents, coastal plains, river basins and 
 mountain systems upon the distribution and the pursuits of 
 mankind. Ellsworth Huntington's studies of the profound and 
 varied effects of the major rhythms of heat and cold, rainfall and 
 dessication, upon the mutation, selective winnowing and migration 
 of the human species have laid foundations of scientific history. 
 
 In studies that have taken the form of an economic interpreta- 
 tion of history, it is an indirect rather than a direct action of the 
 environment that finds recognition. Situation and resources 
 mould the social organization ; first, by determining the character 
 of the predominant industries; and, secondly, by determining the 
 prevailing form of property, as real estate or free capital. 
 
 The theory that I submit here differs from all of these, but 
 more by addition or supplement than by disagreement. I suggest 
 that the really significant phenomenon is found in the relation of 
 the physical environment to the composition of its population. 
 My propositions are, first, that the character of the environment 
 determines the composition of a population as more or less 
 heterogeneous, more or less compound; and second, that the 
 composition of the population determines the character, the com- 
 plexity and the range, of its reactions to stimulation. 
 
 To develop these propositions, let us begin with a phenomenon 
 very simple, very obvious, yet very far-reaching in its conse- 
 quences. A physical environment has, or it has not, the power 
 to attract inhabitants to itself and to keep them. In America we 
 have witnessed the most remarkable example in human history of 
 this immediate relation of population to environment. By hun- 
 dreds of thousands men and women from the older lands have 
 been drawn here by the bounty of nature, underlying that varied 
 economic opportunity which this nation affords to its people. 
 Quite as striking as the mere numbers of immigrants to America, 
 however, is the varied composition of our foreign-born popula-
 
 148 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 tion. Every nationality is included. But the geographical dis- 
 tribution of the foreign born has brought about a marked differ- 
 ence of one region from another in degree of compositeness. The 
 North Atlantic division is heterogeneous in the extreme. The 
 North Central division is relatively homogeneous, and the white 
 population of the South Atlantic and South Central divisions is 
 highly homogeneous. 
 
 Environments are of two fundamental types in respect of their 
 power to maintain society ; those that are so poorly endowed with 
 resources that they can maintain and attract only relatively small 
 numbers of inhabitants, and those that, being richly endowed, 
 support large populations of the native born, and tend to draw a 
 large immigration from elsewhere. Each of these types of en- 
 vironment, in turn, presents two well-marked subdivisions: the 
 isolated, or difficult of access or of egress; and the accessible, a 
 land of ports and open ways, through which the currents of 
 population may easily flow. 
 
 The composition of the population can by no possibility be the 
 same in these four types of environment. That which is charac- 
 teristic of one is unattainable in another. 
 
 In the environment that is both poor and isolated, population is 
 not only sparse, but it is relatively simple and homogeneous in 
 composition. The struggle for existence is severe and the death 
 rate of infancy and of age is high. A relatively large proportion 
 of the living, therefore, is found in the middle age frequencies. 
 The sexes are approximately equal numerically, unless female 
 infanticide prevails. This population is maintained only by its 
 birth rate, and it increases only if its birth rate is in excess of its 
 death rate. It is a genetic aggregation, and is ethnically of one 
 kind. Extreme examples of this environment and of the structure 
 of its population are afforded by the coasts of Greenland, the 
 Aleutian Islands, the southern extremity of South America, and 
 the interior regions of Australia. 
 
 In the environment that is poor but accessible, or, what in this 
 instance is more to the point, admits of easy egress, the population 
 again is a genetic aggregation. The attractions and inducements 
 are not sufficient to bring immigration. But neither are they suffi- 
 cient in all cases to keep the men born within its borders, and,
 
 A THEORY OF SOCIAL CAUSATION 149 
 
 escape being relatively easy, many of the most energetic emigrate 
 to better lands, leaving not only unmarried women, but often also 
 young mothers and children, and old people of both sexes. Here, 
 in the concrete, the process of selection is seen going on through 
 reaction to stimulus. The resources of other environments in 
 some degree awaken the desire of all the inhabitants of the im- 
 poverished land, but only those that are relatively enterprising 
 and energetic are moved to better their condition. The result is a 
 gradual deterioration of the stock remaining in the land. It is 
 bred from the leavings that have been incapable of efficiently 
 responding to the stimulus of larger opportunities. The most 
 interesting modern examples of such environments are those ex- 
 tensive tracts of upland or hill country in the North Atlantic 
 states that once had prosperous farming populations, but-now are 
 inhabited only by unambitious families presenting the unmistak- 
 able marks of degeneration. 
 
 The third type of environment is that which is both rich in 
 resources and relatively isolated or inaccessible. Parts of 
 the Arabian peninsula, the Hawaiian Islands, the Samoan Islands, 
 and the islands of Tahiti, are good examples. So also are the 
 uplands of Mexico and Peru. Here again the population is a 
 great kinship, a genetic aggregation. It is relatively dense. The 
 birth rate is high, and every inequality of energy or ability counts 
 in the struggle for existence. The people alike respond to the 
 bounty of nature and develop those simple forms of economic 
 activity that often are sufficient to create a fair degree of pros- 
 perity. The isolation of such a population while it lasts deter- 
 mines the whole course of social evolution, but it is relative. 
 Sooner or later, or perhaps repeatedly at long intervals, it yields 
 to migration. An increasing pressure of the native born upon the 
 means of subsistence at length forces some of the more vigorous 
 elements to break through confining barriers, and as conquerors, 
 or otherwise, to seek distant homes ; or the natural resources and 
 the acquired prosperity enjoyed by the inhabitants become a 
 stimulus of sufficient power to tempt distant populations to in- 
 vade and exploit. 
 
 There remain environments of the fourth type, richly bountiful 
 in resources and so accessible that men may flock to them from all
 
 ISO STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 quarters of the world. Such are the great river valleys of the 
 Nile and the Euphrates, seats of the most ancient civilizations ; of 
 the Po, the Danube and the Rhine, highways of the nations from 
 an immemorial past ; of the Seine and the Thames ; and, in our 
 own land, the Mississippi basin. Such also are many favored 
 coasts, abounding in inlets and sheltering ports. In all such en- 
 vironments population must sooner or later be composite, nor- 
 mally so in age and sex, and variedly so in blood, and the more so 
 if their resources are not only abundant, but also varied. 
 
 The" composition, however, is determined in the long run by 
 two cooperating processes. Aboriginal populations are overrun 
 by invaders, who come not as individuals, but as organized bands, 
 or armies equipped for conquest. Populations that have attained 
 a measure of economic advancement are now and again overrun 
 by hosts of ruder people that have been dwelling in relatively 
 unkindly habitats. Further conquests also may follow, after 
 civilization has been attained by both the invaders and the in- 
 vaded, if the civilization of the invaders is still of the military 
 type. When, however, industrial civilizations of the modern type 
 have been reached, further migration is a movement of in- 
 dividuals. 
 
 It happens, therefore, that with few, if any, exceptions the popu- 
 lations of the most favored environments are both compound and 
 composite; compound as being made up of successive strata of 
 conquered and conquerors, and composite, as being made up of 
 immigrant individuals scattered among the native-born. In time 
 all of these elements are in some degree amalgamated. The 
 amalgamation of invaded and invaders, however, is determined 
 largely by the physical characteristics of the region itself. If 
 they are such as to tempt the invaders to scatter themselves 
 throughout the land as local overlords, while at the same time 
 maintaining a general distribution of the invaded or conquered, 
 the possibilities of amalgamation are far greater than when for 
 any reason either stratum is geographically concentrated. This 
 seems to have been the history of the thorough-going amalgama- 
 tion of Celtic and Teutonic elements in the midland and western 
 counties of England. 
 
 When an immigration of individuals begins to bring important
 
 A THEORY OF SOCIAL CAUSATION 151 
 
 additions to a compound population, the foreign-born element 
 itself may be more or less composite. And this circumstance 
 again is determined by the character of the physical environment. 
 If the natural resources, while great, are all of one kind, and 
 especially if they are predominantly agricultural, the inhabitants 
 are far more homogeneous than if the resources are in mineral 
 wealth, or, above all, if they are varied, including commercial and 
 manufacturing opportunities. Practically, however, an environ- 
 ment of homogeneous resources is usually but part of a larger 
 geographic unity that is occupied by one entire people, and that 
 in the aggregate includes resources of varied kinds. This in- 
 tegral geographic unity inevitably has a population that not only 
 is largely congregate, rather than genetic, in origin, but that also 
 is in a high degree composite. 
 
 All of these variegations of composition observable in human 
 populations are products of pluralistic reaction to stimulation. 
 How do they, in their turn, limit and determine the possibilities of 
 further reaction? 
 
 In the first place, they set the character of reaction as vigorous 
 and adaptive, or not. 
 
 The adolescent, and the mature who are yet in early middle 
 life, normally react quickly, and are capable of reacting strongly 
 and persistently; the old notoriously are not only slow but also 
 easily and frequently discouraged. The young respond to novelty 
 and delight in it : to the old, notoriously, it is one more weariness 
 to the flesh. Usually it is the new to which adaptation must be 
 made, and the population in which the young are relatively few 
 is therefore relatively non-adaptive. Because of these and other 
 influences, among which heredity is chief, regional populations are 
 unequally alert and unequally adaptive, and when emigrants from 
 them are merged in a heterogeneous population in process of ag- 
 gregation, the proportions in which they are combined determine 
 the quality of its reactions ; temporarily, as far as the effects of 
 age distribution go, permanently, as far as the influences of 
 heredity extend. 
 
 In the second place the ethnic composition of a population pre- 
 vents or it permits a relative complexity of total reaction.
 
 152 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 A population homogeneous in blood is made up of individuals 
 who, in a general way, have undergone similar experiences and 
 have survived the same selective winnowings. Their reaction 
 mechanisms are alike. This means, not only that they react in 
 like manner to a common situation, but also that their reactions 
 are not complicated by necessities of adjustment to the different 
 reactions of neighbors and competitors. The total reaction is 
 simple, while, by contrast, the total reaction of a population made 
 up of differing nationalities or races is inevitably complex. The 
 reaction of each ethnic element is affected by this more or less 
 dissimilar reaction of each other element, not necessarily through 
 media of example and imitation, which may or may not play a 
 part, but always by necessities of adjustment. American life 
 abounds in examples, one of which will suffice. Reaction to an 
 epidemic, by a local population made up preponderantly of the 
 native born of native parents, is simple and straightforward. It 
 does or it does not proclaim and observe scientific precautions, 
 according as it is or is not enlightened. The reaction of a neigh- 
 boring population, composed of native "old settlers," immigrant 
 English, immigrant Irish, and immigrant Slavs or Italians is 
 complex and devious, not merely because the reactions are differ- 
 ent, but because efforts are made to work out adjustments. 
 
 In the third place, the degree to which a population is com- 
 posite determines the range of its total reaction. 
 
 No individual can react to all stimuli; but to stimuli to which 
 one is unresponsive, another, different, individual may be sensi- 
 tive. In like manner, indeed by consequence, one homogeneous 
 group, or population, may be incapable of reaction to situations 
 that provoke other groups to immediate and prolonged effort, 
 although each of them has its own incapabilities. Combined in 
 a heterogeneous population these groups contribute their various 
 potentialities to a large total. The more there are of them, the 
 more composite the population is in which they are merged, the 
 wider is its range of possible reaction to stimulation. 
 
 Finally, in a homogeneous population a majority of all indi- 
 viduals may respond with like behavior in nearly every one of 
 the relatively few situations to which they can respond at all, and 
 the stimuli are not necessarily powerful. The component groups
 
 153 
 
 of a heterogeneous population can react with like behavior in 
 only a few of the many situations to which they can respond 
 variously and the stimulation must be strong. The kith and kin 
 of the New England town in which I was born fished alike, whit- 
 lied alike, chewed tobacco alike, pitched hay alike, talked politics 
 alike at the store, and sang psalm tunes alike at church. The 
 human millions, of all nations and races, that compose the stupen- 
 dous city in which I write now behave in every manner known 
 to man, and in the same manner only on election night or when 
 the prize fight is bulletined, or when the mercury goes above 90 
 degrees. 
 
 The consequences of these determinations of reaction by en- 
 vironment and circumstance and by the composition of the react- 
 ing population, must now be followed out.
 
 CHAPTER IX 
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 
 
 THE phrase is a figure of speech. If we must be literal there is 
 no "Mind of the Many." Literally there is no "group mind" or 
 "social mind." However, when Henry Osborn Taylor writes a 
 book on The Medi&val Mind no one is made to believe that a 
 period of time has a mind in the same sense in which Mr. Taylor 
 has a mind. The mediaeval mind was a prevailing attitude and 
 a customary performance of European minds a thousand years 
 ago. The mind of the many at any time or anywhere is a pre- 
 vailing attitude and usual performance of enough minds then and 
 there alive to be called "many." And inasmuch as performance 
 or functioning is correlated with the make up (with the composi- 
 tion and the constitution) of the thing that functions, it is ac- 
 curate to say that the mind of the many is a kind of minds, react- 
 ing at a given time to a common situation or circumstance, and 
 perhaps inter-acting one with another. 
 
 A situation or circumstance, as has more than once been re- 
 marked on foregoing pages, is a lot or combination of stimuli to 
 psychological goings on. Reacting to it are "irritable" organisms. 
 The word quoted is technical in physiology: "irritability" is a 
 quality of living matter. If only one organism reacts, I call the 
 phenomenon "singularistic." If two or more organisms react to 
 the same stimulation at approximately the same time, I call the 
 phenomenon "pluralistic." Leaving plant organisms out of con- 
 sideration (for our present purposes) the two major kinds of re- 
 acting organisms are animals and human beings. Within each 
 major kind are minor kinds (species or varieties) ; and within 
 each minor kind there are gradations : that is, the organisms are 
 more or less highly organized, their reactions are more or less 
 complex. 
 
 The higher animals and man exhibit also "sensitivity." 1 Man 
 
 1 "Irritability" and "sensitivity" are often used interchangeably in psy- 
 chology, but they should not be. 
 
 154
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 155 
 
 feels pain, and the higher animals appear to feel it. Man con- 
 sciously has sensations and memories, and the higher animals 
 seem to have them. Man consciously has ideas, and the higher 
 animals perhaps have a few simple ones. 
 
 All reactions of irritable matter to stimulation are physiological 
 behavior. All reactions of organisms as units (or individuals) 
 are psychological behavior. Sensitive (and conscious) organisms 
 may be described as mentalized organisms. For brevity we call 
 them minds. The behavior of reasoning minds we are in the habit 
 of calling conduct. 
 
 Every human being learns a good deal about himself as a mind 
 by consciously looking at and into his own mental processes, that 
 is to say, by introspection ; but he cannot by this method become 
 acquainted with the mind of his neighbor. All that we know 
 about the minds of fellowmen we learn from their conduct. 
 This is why there can be no other psychology of society than the 
 behavioristic. A subjective psychology of the individual is pos- 
 sible, but it is scientific and significant only as its facts are corre- 
 lated with behavior, both singularistic and pluralistic. This 
 means that we cannot explain society in terms of an individual- 
 istic psychology, but must, on the contrary, explain an individual- 
 ized mind (a person) as a product of society. 
 
 Viewed as reaction to stimulus all behavior, both animal and 
 human, unconscious and conscious, is mechanistic. Reflexes are 
 reactions of relatively simple nervous mechanisms. Instincts are 
 reaction tendencies, normally completed in reactions, of relatively 
 complex mechanisms. 1 Reflex and instinctive reactions are now 
 and then set going, however, by new stimuli (new to individual 
 experience) that have become associated with old ones ; they are 
 "reconditioned" ; 2 and reconditioning is the beginning of the 
 processes of learning. Reflexes and instincts are ready for 
 business at birth ; they are hereditary. Habits, on the contrary, 
 are sequences and other combinations of responses that have in 
 the first instance been learned by the fumbling called "trial and 
 
 1 Woodworth, Psychology, p. 109. 
 
 "I have used this word (Intellectual Consequences of the War, Trans- 
 actions of the Royal Canadian Institute, Vol. XII, Part I, May 1919, p. 
 108) and I use it here because, strictly speaking, the "conditioned reflex," 
 (Pawlow) is reconditioned, and reconditioning is continually happening 
 in all mental processes, including memory, imagination, and reflection.
 
 156 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 error." They can be taught to successive generations but are not 
 hereditary. Reasoning is a fumbling with ideas, an experimenting 
 in thought preliminary to experimenting in doing. It is an 
 enormous economizing of energy and averts countless disasters. 
 Rational conduct is the complex reaction of nerve and brain 
 mechanisms almost inconceivably complicated. 
 
 These elementary propositions are set down here only to sug- 
 gest the depth of the background from which the mind of the 
 many emerges. Consistently with them I shall assume that the 
 category, ''pluralistic behavior," is wider than the category, "the 
 mind of the many," and that the wider category includes the nar- 
 rower; and I shall use the word "mind" only in reference to 
 psychological goings on in which (at least occasionally) conscious- 
 ness is unmistakably manifested. 
 
 Antecedent, then, to the mind of the many are, first, that 
 pluralistic behavior of unicellular bodies which was first ade- 
 quately observed under experimental conditions and properly de- 
 scribed by Jennings, 1 and second, the gregariousness of the higher 
 animals, in which presumably the mind of the many has its be- 
 ginnings. 
 
 The behavior of the lowest organisms is subinstinctive : no 
 nervous mechanism is involved. Herd behavior is instinctive in 
 part; in part it is a phenomenon of habit. Here we encounter a 
 number of problems over which psychologists have fallen into 
 disagreement, and which are fundamental for social theory. 
 
 To say that herd behavior is instinctive is not equivalent to 
 saying that gregariousness is an instinct, and the second proposi- 
 tion does not follow from the first. If an instinct is the response 
 of a particular and definite nervous mechanism, as the seizing of 
 food is, as caterwauling is, as fighting is and as flight is, there is 
 no gregarious instinct. Yet it is equally certain that pursuit of 
 prey by a pack of wolves and a stampede of cattle are instinctive 
 behavior. 
 
 The bare factual truth so far seems to be that a great part of 
 gregariousness is nothing less and nothing more than pluralistic 
 instinctive reaction to common stimulation, and that no scientific 
 necessity drives us to assume a gregarious instinct distinct from 
 
 1 The Behavior of the Lower Organisms.
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 157 
 
 and cooperating with the primitive instincts of food seizure and 
 flight. 
 
 This is not the whole case, however. The individual members 
 of a herd keep together or frequently get together. Often they 
 show distress or terror if separated. And their cohesion is be- 
 havioristic: no material connective tissue holds them together. 
 
 Is such behavior an instinct ? By strict definition, no : there is 
 no gregarious instinct-mechanism. Is it instinctive? Perhaps, or 
 perhaps it is subinstinctive. Possibly it is a multitude of re- 
 sponses even simpler than instinctive ones. I am convinced that 
 it is. Like the behavior of the lower organisms it is essentially 
 (there are adventitious complications) nothing more than reac- 
 tion by the motor mechanisms of the body along lines of least re- 
 sistance. 
 
 Every animal on countless occasions reacts to self-stimulation. 
 He is excited by his own play, his own yelping, leaping and run- 
 ning. There is no conscious attempt to beat his own record, or 
 to maintain it, such as human beings make, but the circle of 
 stimulation and response is complete and closed within the in- 
 dividual organism, in the one case as in the other. 
 
 Herd-fellows are highly similar. They look alike, smell alike, 
 bleat, bark and bellow alike, and they otherwise behave alike. 
 Therefore, the stimulation that herd-fellow A gets from herd- 
 fellow B is extraordinarily like the stimulation that he gets from 
 himself. It is familiar not only in the sense that he is used to it, 
 but also in the deeper sense that it has been familiar from the 
 beginning. Therefore again, and further, it is not repellant; it 
 does not ordinarily cause recoil or set going the instinct of flight. 
 In contrast, stimulation from animals not of the herd, and from 
 the outer world in general, does alarm, as often as not. There is 
 then recoil, and the adventurer is thrown back upon his herd. 
 
 But if these facts (of pluralistic instinctive response to com- 
 mon stimulation, and reaction on lines of least resistance to inter- 
 stimulation) sufficiently explain gregariousness, why, one may 
 ask, are not all animals gregarious? The question is pertinent 
 (we do not want our proofs of a theory to prove too much) but 
 the answer to it is rather obvious. The food of herbivorous ani- 
 mals does not take fright and run away when scores of them at a
 
 158 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 time tramp and mill about "all over the place." The food of 
 carnivorous animals starts at a flicker, or the crack of a twig. 
 Dogs and wolves are able, nevertheless, to capture it because they 
 are swift of foot and can run incredible distances without exhaus- 
 tion. Dogs and wolves, therefore, can hunt in packs and they do, 
 but a considerable "drove" of tigers beating the jungle would 
 starve. Cubs of the stalking carnivora snuggle together in sleep 
 and play together when awake ; it is of necessity that they separate 
 when mature. The "herds" of lions now and then observed are 
 small. 
 
 That primitive man was a consorting beast a hunter in packs 
 is as nearly certain as any purely inferential fact can be. In 
 The Principles of Sociology published in 1896 I argued at 
 length that the human ancestor was not a solitary ape, but the 
 ape's gregarious relative. The relative was not swift like the dog, 
 but he had learned to use clubs and missiles, and with them to 
 attack game bigger and stronger than himself, but slow. If this 
 contention interested anybody very much I never heard of it, 
 but subsequently the idea occurred to others who thought it im- 
 portant. 1 
 
 Assuming that the human mind was developed in the hunting 
 pack of pre-savagery, but remembering that adaptations and ad- 
 justments are not hereditary, we may now observe the genesis 
 of the mind of the human many as it over and over occurs in 
 successive generations of men, and under most varied circum- 
 stances. 
 
 In one of the great halls of the Metropolitan Museum of Art 
 are grouped examples of the work of Rodin. Among them is 
 "The Hand of God." Before it the stream of visitors divides. 
 Many pass on, bestowing only a glance. Others stop, their at- 
 tention arrested. Of these, a number linger, fascinated. For a 
 time they are silent, they see only the hand. Then their glances 
 wander to one another. They quicken with sympathetic under- 
 standing. One speaks, and reserve breaks down. In a moment 
 all are talking. They know themselves to be, in appreciation of 
 this beautiful thing, of one kind. A psychological group has been 
 formed by pluralistic reaction to a common stimulation, by inter- 
 
 1 Compare Carveth Read, The Origins of Man and of his Superstitions.
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 159 
 
 stimulation and responses thereto, and by awareness of a kinship 
 of minds, manifested in similarity of behavior. 1 
 
 The psychological group arising in mere like-response, may 
 collectively begin to do something. The doing may be instinctive, 
 or it may be premeditated. A purpose to do may be talked over 
 and become concerted volition. Agreeing decision may become 
 concerted action ; which may be repeated, and become a f olkway. 2 
 
 In the codes of ancient law that have come down to us from 
 peoples emerging from a tribal into a civic life, there are pictures 
 of pluralistic response becoming concerted action that, by reason 
 of their relative simplicity, enable us to see what happens more dis- 
 tinctly than we do when we observe the complex institutional ac- 
 tivity of our own time. Of such pictures none more clearly re- 
 veals the psychology of it all than do the triads of Dyvnwr.l Moel- 
 mud, which are included in the Ancient Laws of Wales. The 
 various occasions that draw men together in mote, or meeting are 
 described. Here are examples: 
 
 5. There are three motes of mutual protection : an outpouring mote ; 
 mast gathering; and co-tillage. Herein the hand of everyone is required 
 to assist according to his ability. 
 
 6. There are three horn motes : the assembling of the country by elders 
 and chiefs of kindreds ; the horn of harvest ; and the horn of battle and 
 war, against the molestation of a border country and strangers. 
 
 14. There are three motes of consociation : a convention of a country 
 and elders, arranging the laws and judgments of a common country; 
 bards as teachers of sciences, where they assemble in session ; and the 
 congress of a kindred, at a meeting for worship on the principal high 
 festivals. 
 
 15. There are three motes of imminent attack: the inroad of a border 
 country enemy; the cry, or the horn, of murder and waylaying; and a 
 hamlet on fire : for assistance is required from everybody. 
 
 16. There are three horns of joint mote: the horn of harvest; the horn 
 of pleadings; and the horn of worship. 
 
 17. There are three motes of commotion: the horn of the country; 
 ships from a strange country effecting a landing; and the non-return of 
 the messenger of a country and elders from a foreign country. 
 
 a For this luminous example I am indebted to my friend and colleague, 
 Mr. Frank A. Ross. 
 
 'A f olkway of superior grade, however. Simpler folkways not involv- 
 ing concurring decision after premeditation are mere like ways of behav- 
 ing which have become customary.
 
 160 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 18. There are three motes of request: for tillage; festal games; and 
 burning of woods; for, upon a request, they are not to be impeded. 
 
 21. There are three motes of pursuit : after a wolf ; after thieves ; and 
 after a mad dog; and all who shall hear the cry are to assemble together. 
 
 22. There are three outpouring motes : the approach of strangers 
 without permission; the depredation of a border country; and a pack of 
 wolves. 
 
 26. There are three motes of banishment: for murder and waylaying; 
 treason against the state, or treachery to the country and kindred; and 
 irretrievable spoliation; for it is required of everybody, of every sex and 
 age within hearing of the horn, in the direction taken, to accompany 
 the progress of that exile; and keep up the barking of dogs, to the period 
 of putting to sea, and until the one banished shall have gone three score 
 hours out of sight. 
 
 Without attempting now a systematic or even a full description 
 of the mind of the many, I may hazard here a partially analytical 
 account of certain important details. 
 
 The irritability of all organisms from the lowest up to and 
 including man; the sensitivity of the higher animals (perhaps of 
 all animals) and of man; the power to experience conscious sensa- 
 tions which presumably exists in all creatures that have organs 
 of sense; the capacity for emotional feeling, the powers of con- 
 scious memory and of perception which men and the highest ani- 
 mals have; and the ability to reason which man enjoys these are 
 factors which, in combination constitute the natural ego : the 
 hereditary, or original, nature of man. 
 
 By reacting to hard knocks ; by fumbling and learning, by the 
 acquisition of habits, the natural ego becomes in his individual 
 lifetime and for its duration an adapted ego, better suited to his 
 environment than he was when he was born because after adapta- 
 tion he is in part a product of environment. 
 
 And this is but the beginning of reconditioning, of modification, 
 of remaking. Both biology and psychology have answered a 
 whimsical question propounded by Oliver Wendell Holmes : 
 
 "Should I be I, or should I be 
 One-tenth another and nine-tenths me?" 
 
 if my great-grandmother had married another suitor? Biologi- 
 cally it depends on who was which, or might have been which,
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 161 
 
 among my ancestral dominants and recessives. Psychologically, 
 as Ribot, James and Baldwin a good while ago demonstrated, 
 every human individual is largely a product of mental intercourse 
 with other living individuals, and of memories (more or less 
 reflected upon) of the deeds and the thoughts of the dead. The 
 process substantially, as I see it, is this : 
 
 If the adapted ego and an alter, who also is an adapted ego, or 
 if many individuals each of whom is an adapted ego, are so far 
 alike in their reactions to fundamental stimulations that they 
 dwell in proximity, or frequent the same places, they repeatedly 
 knock up against one another. They stimulate one another and 
 respond to one another. In human populations these processes 
 are unimaginably more complicated than they are in subhuman 
 herds. Interstimulation among men takes forms not onlj of acci- 
 dental suggestion and example, but also of consciously intended 
 suggestion and example; not only of unconsciously made and 
 unanalyzed impression, but also of premeditated appeal and in- 
 tended intimidation. Response takes forms of conscious imitation, 
 of dramatization, of conversation, of discussion and of concerted 
 action. Dramatization and conversation are particularly impor- 
 tant. In the presence of a fellow being a conscious individual does 
 not do things artlessly. 1 He enacts them. Conversation, which 
 too often we think of as something other than behavior, is be- 
 havior in fact. It is objective, and states of consciousness peculiar 
 to A or peculiar to B (which as feeling cannot be shared by ego 
 and alter) when talked about by A and B become objects of 
 thought to each, and can thenceforth be correlated by each with 
 observed behavior. It is doubtful whether in the whole range of 
 facts germane to both psychology and sociology there is any 
 other thing more significant than the conversationalizing of con- 
 sciousness. Through it and by means of it we develop our 
 "ejective" interpretations of one another, which, without con- 
 versation, could not get far, or be other than vague. 2 
 
 *He may unconsciously or self-consciously do them so artfully as to 
 seem to do them artlessly. 
 
 "The term "eject" was first used by William Kingdon Clifford in a 
 remarkable article, "On the Nature of Things in Themselves," which 
 appeared in Mind, in January, 1878. Clifford's own definition of the word 
 as there given was as follows : "When I come to the conclusion that you
 
 162 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 The play of minds upon one another is a give and take which 
 expands and enriches all : a "dialectic of personal growth," Mark 
 Baldwin called it. Also, little by little, stage by stage, and in the 
 long run it is an adjustment to one another made by mentalized 
 organisms reacting to common stimulations, having like wants, 
 and in like ways trying to satisfy them. Adjustment works out 
 as toleration, which, among herding animals, is little if anything 
 more than an equilibrium of fighting ability, but among men is 
 premeditated and consciously practiced. Also, among men, it 
 works out further in a formulation and observance of rights. 
 Through give and take with fellowmen and through adjustment 
 with them, the adapted ego becomes a complicit ego. 1 
 
 The account of the making of ego by alter which Baldwin gives 
 and from which I dissent, is both simpler than mine and different 
 from it. "The dialectic of personal growth," Baldwin says, may 
 be read thus : "My thought of self is in the main, as to its charac- 
 ter as a personal self, filled up with my thought of others, dis- 
 tributed variously as individuals; and my thought of others, as 
 persons, is mainly filled up with myself. In other words, but for 
 certain minor distinctions in the filling, and for certain compelling 
 distinctions between that which is immediate and that which is 
 objective, the ego and the alter are to our thought one and the 
 same thing." 
 
 To this I object first that it is inaccurate to say that "my thought 
 
 are conscious, and that there are objects in your consciousness similar 
 to those in mine, I am not inferring any actual or possible feelings of 
 my own, but your feelings, which are not, and cannot by any possibility 
 become, objects in my consciousness. . . . But the inferred existence of 
 your feelings, of objective groupings among them similar to those among 
 my feelings, and of a subjective order in many respects analogous to 
 my own, these inferred existences are in the very act of inference thrown 
 out of my consciousness, recognized as outside of it, as not being a part 
 of me. I propose, accordingly, to call these inferred existences ejects, 
 things thrown out of my consciousness, to distinguish them from objects, 
 things presented in my consciousness, phenomena." 
 
 1 1 am now closely following the argument of an article on "The 
 Psychology of Society," Science, January 6, 1899, in which I criticized 
 Baldwin's "Social and Ethical Interpretations," contending that he had 
 not made enough of that natural ego which is not a product of the 
 dialectic, that he had failed to perceive the dominating importance of 
 mental and moral relations with similars, and that in identifying the 
 "matter" or stuff of social organization with "all kinds of knowledges 
 and informations" (with "thoughts" in general) he was off the track 
 altogether.
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 163 
 
 of self is, in the main, filled up with my thought of others," even 
 if we admit "minor distinctions in the filling" and "certain com- 
 pelling distinctions between that which is immediate and that 
 which is objective." What are these compelling distinctions of 
 the immediate? Obviously, they are those presentations in con- 
 sciousness which arise from organic conditions rather than from 
 mental intercourse with others. Hunger is a state of conscious- 
 ness which can subvert the entire product of the "dialectic of 
 personal growth" ; and it will not do to ignore the fact that when 
 men who have been amended and amplified by that dialectic are 
 confronted by starvation, they are liable to have thoughts of self 
 which can hardly be construed as filled up mainly with thoughts 
 of others, unless we are prepared to accept a cannibal's definition 
 of "others." Therefore we must continue to think of the indi- 
 vidual as being essentially a natural ego, and at all times more 
 natural and adapted than complicit. 
 
 A further and more important objection that I make to Bald- 
 win's analysis is that the give and take in which the ego engages 
 is not carried on indiscriminately or to equal extent with any 
 alter. From the beginning of conscious life a tendency is mani- 
 fest to discriminate between one alter and another, and develop- 
 ment of the complicit ego is conditioned by a state of awareness 
 which may be described as a consciousness of similars or of kind. 
 The rise of this consciousness marks a distinct stage in the evolu- 
 tion of the mind of the many. Also it converts mere gregarious- 
 ness into society; and it transforms further the already twice 
 amended and doubly amplified natural ego. 
 
 The consciousness of kind, it is necessary to observe, is not an 
 undecomposable or ultimate mental state. Sensations are the 
 foundation of it. Ideas and emotions are mingled, perhaps 
 blended, in it. Long before any discriminations of kind have 
 become possible, a preparation for them and a tendency toward 
 them is made in conscious experience. Of the sensations which 
 first arise in consciousness, some are received from the bodily 
 organism which the self inhabits ; some are received from similar 
 bodily organisms, and some are received from wholly unlike 
 objects in the external world. Now we know that many sensations 
 received from self are so nearly like sensations received from like
 
 164 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 selves that, merely as sensations, they can be distinguished only 
 with difficulty. If, for example, I strike with my voice a certain 
 note of the musical scale, and another person a moment after 
 strikes the same note with his voice, my auditory sensations in the 
 two cases are nearly alike. If I cry out in pain, and then hear 
 another man like myself cry out in pain, my auditory sensations 
 are nearly alike; but if I hear a dog bark, the sensation is 
 different from that which I have received from my own voice. If 
 I walk with my friend down the street, and happen to notice the 
 motion of my feet as I take successive steps, and then to notice 
 the motion of my friend's feet, the visual sensations, in these two 
 cases, are closely alike ; but if I happen to notice the trotting of 
 a horse that is being driven by me, the visual sensation is dif- 
 ferent from that which I have received in observing my own steps. 
 If I stroke the back of my hand, and then stroke the back of 
 my friend's hand, I receive tactual sensations that are closely 
 alike ; but if I then stroke the fur of a cat or the mane of a horse, 
 or touch the paw of a cat or the hoof of a horse, I receive 
 sensations very different from those received from the back of 
 my hand. It therefore appears that before there is power to make 
 discriminations of any kind, even to think of differences of sen- 
 sation, sensations themselves fall into different groupings. At the 
 very beginning of conscious life, certain elements which are to 
 enter into a consciousness of kind begin to appear in experience. 
 They consist of like sensations received from self and from others 
 who resemble self. 
 
 On the basis of these experiences there are developed others 
 that call for investigation from the same point of view. When 
 suggestion begins to play an important part in mental life, are 
 suggestions from persons very unlike self equally efficacious with 
 suggestions from persons nearly like self? There is here a great 
 field for investigation. A thousand familiar observations strongly 
 indicate the superiority of suggestions that come from those whose 
 neural organization resembles that of the person affected. Why, 
 for example, does Maudsley venture to say, without offering the 
 slightest proof, that, while men are as liable as silly sheep to fall 
 into panic when they see panic among their fellows, they are not 
 similarly liable when they perceive panic among sheep? Obvi-
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 165 
 
 ously, because facts of this general character are so familiar that 
 no one would think of questioning them. Phenomena like these, 
 of course, have thefr origin in a like responsiveness of like or- 
 ganisms to the same stimulus. 
 
 When power to make intellectual discriminations is attained, a 
 perception of resemblances and differences begins to create ob- 
 jective science, to react upon pluralistic behavior, and to bias the 
 intercourse of individuals. Objects of the external world are 
 sorted and classified. "Men," "animals," and "plants," are early 
 categories. In the folk lore of many lands the making and filling 
 of them is the first brain work spoken of. "Whatsoever Adam 
 called every living creature, that was the name thereof. And 
 Adam gave names to all cattle, and to the fowl of the air, and to 
 every beast of the field." The first sortings are by obtruf ive fea- 
 tures of size, shape and color. Then actions arrest attention, and 
 men already sorted by size and color, 1 are sorted by speech and 
 behavior. Last of all they are classified with reference to feelings, 
 beliefs, tastes, sentiments, judgments and philosophies imputed to 
 them. In all this classifying every individual assigns himself (in 
 most instances with obvious satisfaction) to certain kinds, and, 
 thanking God that he is not as other men are, excluding himself 
 from their kinds. 
 
 These intellectual operations of discrimination and assignment 
 react upon the sensory sympathy (I have called it organic sym- 
 pathy) that has been described, and condition it by reflection. It 
 becomes the complex sympathy (partly feeling and partly idea) 
 that Adam Smith discoursed of in The Theory of Moral Senti- 
 ments. Even in the emotional madness of mob action the reac- 
 tion of the perception of kind may be seen. When, for example, 
 masses of men simultaneously respond to a party cry or symbol, 
 the action for the moment is merely a like responsiveness to the 
 same stimulus. An instant later, when each man perceives that, in 
 this respect, his fellow beings are resembling himself in feeling 
 and in action, his own emotion is enormously intensified. It is this 
 which gives to all symbols and shibboleths their tremendous practi- 
 cal importance. 
 
 1 Size and color are the peculiarities of white men first remarked upon 
 by brown men on first acquaintance.
 
 1 66 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 From the moment when the individual becomes intellectually 
 aware of his kind (or kinds) he begins to pick and choose his 
 familiars. He is acutely conscious of likes and dislikes, and de- 
 velops countless prejudices. On the whole he likes best those 
 fellowmen whose ways are his ways, whose foibles are his 
 foibles, whose vices are his vices, whose virtues are his virtues, 
 whose tastes are his tastes, and whose beliefs are his beliefs. His 
 consorting becomes a preferential association, and this is the be- 
 ginning of society in distinction from the herd. Ever since the 
 derivatives of sociiis appeared in speech they have carried the 
 denotation or the connotation, preferential association. Gregari- 
 ousness began when plural offspring kept together instead of 
 separating. Society began when the consciousness of kind first 
 manifested itself in preferential association. 
 
 In association and through its exigencies, the ego takes on the 
 subtleties, of feeling, attitude, and demeanor, that make him a 
 comrade. Already a complicit ego, made so by gregariousness, he 
 now becomes a socialized ego, made so by preferential association, 
 a product of the consciousness of kind. 
 
 There are two further stages in the development of the ego 
 which I shall only mention, without describing them or further 
 accounting for them, in this place. Society becomes organized. 
 Through its mores spontaneous society exerts a social pressure 
 upon its component human units. Through its governments and 
 laws organized society exerts a legal pressure. Reacting to these 
 pressures the individual becomes a societized, or, to use a less 
 accurate but more familiar word, a civilized ego. Organized 
 society ameliorates the struggle for existence, thereby making 
 possible a survival of human variates from type (if they are soci- 
 etized) that under harder conditions would perish. Varying from 
 type, the human units of organized society also differ from one 
 another. They are individual not only in the sense that each is 
 an ego but also in the sense that each is in a degree peculiar, 
 which is what we mean when we say that each has individuality. 
 So, as the final product of social evolution, we get human per- 
 sonality, concrete in an ego that has been adapted, made complicit, 
 socialized, civilized, and, in the end, individualised.
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 167 
 
 It should be clear by now why I cannot assent to the proposition 
 that the "material" of society is all kinds of thoughts and "knowl- 
 edges." The material of society is a plural number of concrete 
 human beings so constituted that they think alike on matters of 
 fundamental importance, behave alike in critical situations and, 
 intellectually knowing that they so do behave, consciously count 
 on one another to keep on so thinking and so behaving. Or, more 
 briefly put, the material of society is a plural number of like- 
 minded persons. 
 
 When, many years ago, I singled out like-mindedness as a 
 phenomenon of preeminent importance for the theory of human 
 society, I was careful to acknowledge my obligation for the idea to 
 a source very old and immensely respectable. 
 
 Paul the Apostle was not only one of the most gifted men of 
 any age, but also one of the most practical. He had been reared 
 in Jewish formalism and had witnessed the beginnings of Roman 
 imperialism before he participated in the organization of Chris- 
 tianity. Accepting the duties which circumstances and his own 
 nature placed upon him as an interpreter and missionary of the 
 new faith he gave heed to the social cohesion of its converts, and 
 perceived in what it must consist. All of the older religions 
 against which Christianity was to make headway had grown into 
 elaborate social systems, with their priesthoods, their carefully 
 graded ranks or classes of believers, their rituals and festivals, 
 and against these the disciples had protested. Knowing, there- 
 fore, that the social unity of Christian believers must be more 
 spiritual and spontaneously behavioristic than authoritative and 
 legal, Paul saw that it must be the unity of like-mindedness. 
 Therefore insistently in the Epistles he forces like-mindedness 
 upon the attention of his readers, and warns them to give heed 
 to it. "Be of the same mind one toward another," he says to the 
 Romans; and in the same Epistle he prays for them, that they 
 may be of the same mind; that with one accord and with one 
 mouth they may glorify their God. The Corinthians he beseeches 
 to "speak the same thing" ; to "have no divisions" among them ; 
 that they may be "perfected together in the same mind and in the 
 same judgment." And the Philippians he implores to "stand fast
 
 168 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 in one spirit, with one soul" ; to "be of the same mind, having the 
 same love, being of one accord." 
 
 That it was in truth Paul who first seized upon this social 
 phenomenon for practical purposes, we have proof. Only in two 
 places outside of his writings can any allusion to it be found in 
 either the Old or the New Testament. One is in the first epistle 
 of Peter, where the expression "finally, be ye all like-minded" is so 
 exactly the phraseology of Paul that we can hardly doubt that it 
 was borrowed from him. The other is in Revelation, where ten 
 kings are spoken of as having one mind. That the Apostle him- 
 self derived the suggestion from a Greek or a Roman source is 
 probable. Plato in the passage quoted in Chapter VI observes how 
 different is the behavior of "all kinds of people flowing together 
 to the same point" from that of a community homogeneous in 
 blood and speaking one language. Aristotle in the Ethics quotes 
 the saying that "birds of a feather flock together," and recalls a 
 contention of Empedocles that "like desires like." To Roman 
 lawyers the "meeting of minds" was an essential factor of a con- 
 tract. But, so far as we know, neither Greek nor Roman before 
 Paul insisted as he did that like-mindedness is the effective co- 
 hesion and unity of discrete individuals for practical ends. 
 
 If he and those who anticipated his thought were right in this, 
 we find in implications of their teaching a provisional definition of 
 society and of its "stuff." The like-mindedness that is essential is 
 known and understood for what it is by those who share it. They 
 foster it, knowing its value. Not only do A and B agree in their 
 thoughts, feelings, purposes ; but also both A and B are aware of 
 their agreement. Moreover, they perceive that agreement is pleas- 
 urable ; that the fruits of concord are peace ; that discord is not 
 happiness and is likely to end in disunion. They strive, as en- 
 joined, to be "perfected together in the same mind and in the 
 same judgment." Obviously, then, it appears, a society is any num- 
 ber of individuals in a general way like-minded, or like-minded 
 on a particular matter, who know and enjoy their like-mindedness, 
 and are therefore able to work together for common ends. 
 
 The inhabitants of villages, cities and nations are like-minded 
 in a general way, but usually tolerant of many differences that 
 are not divisive and favorably disposed to any that function in
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 169 
 
 occupational specialization, the so-called division of labor. The 
 members of artificial societies intentionally formed and main- 
 tained for particular purposes, the church for example, the politi- 
 cal party, the business corporation, the scientific association, or 
 the club, are like-minded in respect of the particular interests 
 which these societies conserve or foster, and usually they are 
 intolerant of attitudes inimical to the interests cherished. 
 
 Toleration of the modes and degrees of unlike-mindedness that 
 are as necessary for social variation as fundamental like-minded- 
 ness is for cohesion and for stability, is always "within limits" of 
 kind, degree and range. These do not necessarily, or perhaps 
 usually, coincide with limits of desirability, but what the latter 
 are has never been determined. Everybody except the fanatic 
 and the moron can see that only if new types of character, new 
 habits and ambitions, and new ways of thinking appear by muta- 
 tion or are brought in, can a community undergo appreciable 
 change for better or for worse; that only as individual men differ 
 from their fellows can the church or the party adapt itself to new 
 conditions; but beyond this all is guesswork, and experimental 
 policies are shaped by conflicts of group and class interest, as these 
 are played upon by winds of destiny. Scientific knowledge of this 
 matter is presumably attainable ; but at present we know only that 
 the balance of like-mindedness over unlike-mindedness must be 
 large for society to exist at all and that for orderly development a 
 continually appearing unlikeness of behavior, of expressed pur- 
 pose, feeling and thought, must be reconcilable with a great mass 
 of established agreement, and in fact, be harmonized with it, and 
 utilized. 
 
 By tolerated variegations of population and variations of be- 
 havior much social change is accomplished quietly and unob- 
 served. Slight differences of nationality are assimilated; minor 
 peculiarities of manner are imitated ; modifications of opinion are 
 effected ; until, in time, a really important metamorphosis of soci- 
 ety has taken place, and no one can tell exactly how. These from 
 the first are things "of course" or of habit more than of emotion 
 or of conviction, far more than of intellectual concern. They 
 enter into tradition, partaking of its color, and mellowing in its 
 atmosphere.
 
 1 70 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 But, now and then, masses of men become consciously dissatis- 
 fied with existing conditions, and by combined action, consciously 
 begun and intentionally kept up, bring about momentous changes 
 in a relatively brief while. Such are revolutionSj_and occasional 
 transformations inaugurated by governmental policy. Such, for 
 example, were the Puritan rebellion in England, the American 
 Revolution in 1776, the establishment of the French Republic, the 
 ratification of the Federal Constitution of the United States, the 
 abolition of negro slavery, and the communistic regime in Russia. 
 
 These comparatively swift overturns or metamorphoses are 
 brought about in two ways : an impulsive, unreasoning social ac- 
 tion, like that of the mob, is one ; deliberation and discussion are 
 the other. Of impulsive social action, sane men in their sane 
 moments have a well-grounded dread. Not all the cruelties that 
 have deliberately been inflicted by political tyrants and ecclesiasti- 
 cal councils can be compared with the horrors that have been 
 perpetrated by irresponsible masses of men who have broken 
 with tradition or ceased to reason about their social situation, and 
 have surrendered themselves to the frenzy of emotion. 
 
 Scientific analysis of the conditions and processes of mob 
 action can add nothing to the repugnance which calm-minded men 
 feel toward collective outbreaks of the brute nature that still sur- 
 vives in man. Nevertheless, inventory and description contribute 
 two elements of value to our knowledge of this subject. The first 
 is the record of history that transition from violent talk to violent 
 action is begun by irresponsible, quasi-criminal elements of the 
 population. Riots, insurrections, revolutions, rarely begin with 
 the striking of a well-directed blow by a disciplined force, under 
 the command of a far-seeing leader. They start with assaults, 
 thefts, and homicides, with volleys of stones, with random shoot- 
 ings and stabbings, with the looting of shops, and the lynching of 
 opponents. To mention but one among countless instances, the 
 Crusades, a true epidemic craze, did not begin with the setting 
 forth of armed expeditions under Godfrey of Bouillon, Hugh the 
 Great, Robert Curthose, Count Robert of Flanders, Prince Boeh- 
 mond of Tarentum, and Count Raymond of Toulouse, in the year 
 1097. They began with the three unorganized crusades of the 
 preceding year, under Walter the Penniless, whose twenty thou-
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 171 
 
 sand followers, described as the dregs of Christendom, filled Bul- 
 garia with robbery and murder, until they were themselves slaugh- 
 tered in the storming of Belgrade ; under Peter the Hermit, whose 
 rabble of forty thousand men, women, and children was hardly 
 better in character; and under the German priest, Gottschalk, 
 whose fifteen thousand followers from Strassburg, Worms, and 
 Mayence inaugurated their pilgrimage by massacring Jews in the 
 valley of the Rhine. Collective conduct of this kind, whether it 
 develops into revolutionary "terrors" to culminate in the devasta- 
 tion of an empire, or becomes a f olkway, like lynching in America, 
 admits of but one interpretation. It means that the unchaining 
 of the wild beast in man, which is often spoken of as a result of 
 mob action, is not its result at all, but its beginning; and that a 
 fearful responsibility rests upon those men and women who, while 
 believing in rational deliberation, and justly dreading epidemic 
 emotion, look tolerantly upon the initial stages of social excite- 
 ment, or carelessly permit themselves to contribute to it, in the 
 unwarranted belief that they can turn to and check it when it 
 begins to go too far. 
 
 The impossibility of checking, until it has run its course, any 
 mob action that has once gathered headway, has fully been estab- 
 lished as a demonstrated sociological principle; and this is the 
 second element which a scientific description of society adds to 
 our knowledge of the non-reasoning or impulsive modes of social 
 transformation. From the moment that habit and reason lose 
 control over masses of communicating men, they fall under the 
 power of example and suggestion; and emotional fury sweeps 
 through them with increasing volume and accelerating velocity, 
 as a conflagration sweeps through accumulations of combustible 
 material. Impulsive social action, in short, proceeds not slowly 
 through the mass, as water filters through sand, but with the ac- 
 celeration of a geometrical progression. This law is no more open 
 to doubt than is the law of gravitation, and no fact of social knowl- 
 edge is more sobering. The only way to prevent the devastating 
 consequences of epidemic madness is to multiply in the com- 
 munity the number of those men who habitually subordinate feel- 
 ing to morale or to reason, and who, therefore, cannot become a 
 part of the combustible material of the mob spirit.
 
 172 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 If these things are true, it is certain that as far as well-being 
 depends upon human intention and the putting forth of human 
 will to supplement the slow accumulation of minute changes that 
 are imperceptibly effected, we must look chiefly to the agency of 
 deliberation. What, then, are the conditions under which reason 
 functions in social affairs and establishes morale? What are the 
 conditions under which deliberated behavior is encouraged, and 
 the proportion of emotional, fanatical, hypnotizable, impulsive be- 
 havior is diminished? 
 
 These questions may best be answered by converting them into 
 a negative form. Under what conditions are irrationality, hyp- 
 notic susceptibility, willingness to follow without question or 
 resistance any suggested course of action, most likely to prevail? 
 Are we tolerant of influences or agencies, whose certain tendency 
 is to break down morale and give rein to impulse ? The answer is 
 disturbing but not disputable. For generations society has per- 
 mitted, not to say encouraged, in the name of religion, the practice 
 of arts that menace happiness and social order. A certain type of 
 the professional revivalist plays upon ignorance and upon fear. 
 A certain type of the revival meeting is, and always has been, .a 
 school of ill-considered action. Throughout history a kind of 
 revival in which reason is denounced, anathematized, and sub- 
 merged under billows of crazing emotion, has been a foster- 
 mother of the mob. 
 
 No sane person can witness the occurrences of a negro revival 
 in the South, or read of the similar occurrences that took place 
 during revival epidemics that swept westward from the Atlantic 
 seaboard in 1837 an d in 1857, or listen to the preaching of some 
 of the more popular of contemporary revivalists, without being 
 convinced of the truth of these propositions. The methods of the 
 professional revivalist are those of the professional hypnotizer, 
 even when they are more refined, and keep their machinery out of 
 sight. The professional revivalist tells his hearers that their 
 reason is the most deadly enemy of their souls ; that the deliberat- 
 ing, critical habit of mind endangers eternal salvation ; that safety 
 lies in acting immediately upon the impulse which he is striving 
 to awaken in their bosoms. Such a teacher, addressing an audi- 
 ence of thousands in New York City, repeated as a model for
 
 THE MIND OF THE MANY 173 
 
 universal imitation the prayer of a man who besought God to 
 crush his individual will, and make him a drift-log on the current 
 of divine purpose. Men and women who surrender themselves 
 to such teaching in the revival will not act coolly, reasonably, 
 and courageously in the affairs of secular life. Those who yield 
 to the impassioned appeal of the exhorter, will not be unmoved by 
 the harangue of the partisan orator, or resist the impulse to fellow 
 blindly the lead of the "boss" who, like his religious preceptor, 
 exacts unquestioning obedience. As long as the grosser forms of 
 revivalism are possible, the protection of society against epidemic 
 madness, and the overthrow of "bossism" of the brutal sort will be 
 impossible. It is unreasonable to believe that we can make men 
 irrational, impulsive, hypnotic creatures for the purposes of re- 
 ligion, and then find them cool-headed, critical, rational men for 
 the purposes of politics. 
 
 When reason controls the social situation, deliberation consists 
 largely in a review and criticism of social values ; one of the high- 
 est enterprises in which the rational intelligence can engage. 
 
 By the term "social value" I mean a regard or esteem for any 
 social habit, relation, or institution which makes men cherish and 
 defend it. In the long run, social values are measured, as eco- 
 nomic values are, by the sacrifices that men make for them. The 
 measure of the value that we attach to civil liberty is found in the 
 sacrifices that we make to maintain it. The measure of the value 
 that we attach to any ancient usage or institution which, in some 
 degree, obstructs the later developments of our social system is the 
 sacrifice of new possibilities that we submit to, rather than witness 
 the destruction of things that we long have admired or revered. 
 
 Social values, like economic values, are determined in part by 
 comparisons that theoretically should be extended throughout the 
 entire range of possible utilities and costs. It would be worth 
 while for the individual, if he were well enough informed and 
 sufficiently in control of his impulses and prejudices, to estimate 
 accurately every utility and every cost which enters into his cal- 
 culations. It would promote the general welfare if society could 
 estimate accurately the utility of every social institution, of every 
 cherished usage or custom, and, with equal accuracy, the sacri- 
 fices, not only of the time and money of individuals, but also of
 
 174 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 possible developments oh new lines of progress, which must be 
 made in order to maintain the old ; or, taking the other point of 
 view, if it could estimate accurately how much of the old must be 
 sacrificed to secure the new. Therefore, the rational process in 
 social development consists chiefly in that criticism of all our 
 social values which enables us wisely to choose among them. 
 
 Objects of social esteem are ends to be attained or they are 
 means to attainment. Here, again, we find analogy with economic 
 categories, since economic goods are either goods for final con- 
 sumption, or the means of production which we describe as capi- 
 tal. The ends that we strive to attain in society are not essentially 
 different from those that we strive to attain as individuals. The 
 objects of endeavor, whether of individuals or of communities, 
 are life, happiness, and the development of our rational personal- 
 ity. Society itself is a means. Philosophy cannot set aside or 
 improve upon the Platonic and Aristotelian dictum that the state 
 exists for the good life. Yet no truth is more frequently lost sight 
 of in personal conduct or in public policy. Nothing is so hard 
 for the partisan to see and admit as that his party is only an in- 
 strumentality, and that it cumbers the ground when it no longer 
 promotes the end for which it was instituted. Nothing is more 
 difficult for men and women in general than to see and admit 
 that customs, usages, institutions, parties, churches, creeds, have 
 no sacredness in themselves, and that there is no other warrant for 
 their existence than may be found in their power to contribute 
 to the safe and comfortable maintenance of human life, or to the 
 advance of the human mind in knowledge and command. 
 
 The conditions under which means in use are effectively com- 
 bined for the promotion of ends in view have been set forth in 
 part, and now must be considered further. Institutions have be- 
 come what they are through historical processes of evolution, and 
 cannot instantly be made over or re-correlated. Also, they are 
 related in definite ways to like-mindedness and to variability. 
 The criticism of social values must proceed in presupposition and 
 recognition of these conditions.
 
 CHAPTER X 
 
 THE GROUP-MAKING ROLE OF IDEAS AND BELIEFS 
 
 CONFLICTS and contradictions among ideas and beliefs are of 
 various degrees and of various modes besides that specific one 
 which we call logical incompatibility. A perception, for example, 
 may be pictorially inconsistent or tonically discordant with an- 
 other perception ; a mere faith unsupported by objective evidence 
 may be emotionally antagonistic to another mere faith, as truly as 
 a judgment may be logically irreconcilable with another judg- 
 ment. And this wide possibility of contradiction is particularly 
 to be recognized when the differing ideas or beliefs have arisen 
 not within the same individual mind, but in different minds, and 
 are therefore colored by personal or partisan interest, and warped 
 by idiosyncrasy of mental constitution. These intermental con- 
 flicts are more extensive and more varied than the logical duels 
 that are intramental; they are also less definite, less precise. In 
 reality they are culture conflicts, in which the opposing forces, so 
 far from being specific ideas only, or pristine beliefs only, are in 
 fact more or less bewildering complexes of ideas, beliefs, preju- 
 dices, sympathies, antipathies, and personal interests. 
 
 Any idea or group of ideas, any belief or group of beliefs, may 
 happen to be, or may become, a common interest, shared by a 
 small or a large number of like-minded or potentially like-minded 
 individuals. It may draw and hold them together in bonds of 
 acquaintance, of association, even of cooperation. So it may play 
 a group-making role. Contradictory ideas or beliefs, therefore, 
 may play a group-making role in a double sense. Each draws into 
 association the individual minds that entertain it or find it attrac- 
 tive. Each also repels those minds to whom it is repugnant, and 
 drives them toward the group which is being formed about the 
 contradictory idea or belief. Contradictions among ideas and 
 beliefs, then, it may be assumed, tend on the whole to sharpen the 
 lines of demarkation between group and group. 
 
 i75
 
 1 76 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 These assumptions are, I suppose, so fully justified by the 
 everyday observation of mankind, and so confirmed by history, 
 that it is unnecessary to discuss them, or in any way to dwell 
 upon them ; but it should be not unprofitable to inquire what kind 
 or type of groups, distinctive ideas and beliefs and the inevitable 
 contradictions among them are likely to create and to main- 
 tain within the progressive populations of the world, from this 
 time forth. 
 
 Somewhat more than three hundred years ago, Protestantism 
 and geographical discovery had combined to create conditions 
 extraordinarily favorable to the formation of groups or associa- 
 tions about various conflicting ideas and beliefs functioning as 
 nuclei; and for nearly three hundred years the world has been 
 observing a remarkable multiplication of culture groups of two 
 fundamentally different types. One type is a sect, or denomina- 
 tion, having no restricted local habitation, but winning adherents 
 here and there in various local communities, provinces, or nations, 
 and having, therefore, a membership either locally concentrated or 
 more or less widely dispersed ; either regularly or very irregularly 
 distributed. The culture group of the other type, or kind, is a 
 self-sufficing community. It may be a village, a colony, a state, 
 or a nation. Its membership is concentrated, its habitat is defined. 
 
 To a great extent, as everybody knows, American colonization 
 proceeded through the formation of religious communities. Such 
 were the Pilgrim and the Puritan commonwealths. Such were 
 the Quaker groups of Rhode Island and Pennsylvania. Such 
 were the localized societies of the Dunkards, the Moravians, and 
 the Mennonites. 
 
 As late as the middle of the nineteenth century, the American 
 people witnessed the birth and growth of one of the most remark- 
 able religious communities known in history. The Mormon com- 
 munity of Utah, which, originating in 1830 as a band of relatives 
 and acquaintances, clustered by an idea that quickly became a 
 dogma, had become in fifty years a commonwealth de facto, defy- 
 ing the authority de jure of the United States. 
 
 We are not likely, however, again to witness a phenomenon of 
 this kind in the civilized world. Recently we have seen the rise 
 and the astonishingly rapid spread of another American religion,
 
 GROUP-MAKING ROLE OF IDEAS AND BELIEFS 177 
 
 namely, the Christian Science faith. But it has created no com- 
 munity group. It has created only a dispersed sect. It is obvious 
 to any intelligent observer, however untrained in sociological dis- 
 crimination he may be, that the forces of Protestantism, still 
 dividing and differentiating as they are, no longer to any great 
 extent create new self-sufficing communities. They create only 
 associations of irregular geographical dispersion, of more or less 
 unstable or shifting membership. In a word, the conflicting-idea 
 forces, which in our colonial days tended to create community 
 groups as well as sects, tend now to create sectarian bodies only 
 mere denominational or partisan associations. 
 
 A similar contrast between an earlier and a later stage of cul- 
 ture group-making may be observed if we go back to centuries 
 long before the Protestant Reformation; there to survey a wider 
 field and a longer series of historical periods. 
 
 It is a commonplace of historical knowledge that in all of the 
 earliest civilizations there was an approximate identification of 
 religion with ethnic consciousness and of political consciousness 
 with both religious and race feeling. Each people had its own 
 tribal or national gods, who were inventoried as national assets, 
 at valuations quite as high as those attached to tribal or national 
 territory. 
 
 When, however, Roman imperial rule had been extended over 
 the civilized world, the culture conflicts that then arose expended 
 their group-creating force in bringing together like believers in 
 sectarian association. Christianity, appealing to all bloods, in a 
 measure to all economic classes, and spreading into all sections of 
 the eastern Mediterranean region, did not to any great extent 
 create communities. And what was true of Christianity was in 
 like manner true of the Mithras cult, widely diffused in the second 
 Christian century. Even Mohammedanism, a faith seemingly 
 well calculated to create autonomous states, in contact with a 
 world prepared by Roman organization could not completely 
 identify itself with definite political boundaries. 
 
 The proximate causes of these contrasts are not obscure. We 
 must suppose that a self-sufficing community might at one time 
 as well as at another be drawn together by formative beliefs. 
 But that it may take root somewhere and, by protecting itself
 
 178 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 against destructive external influences succeed for a relatively 
 long time in maintaining its integrity and its solidarity, it must 
 enjoy a relative isolation. In a literal sense it must be beyond 
 easy reach of those antagonistic forces which constitute for it the 
 outer world of unbelief and darkness. 
 
 Such isolation is easily and often possible, however, only in 
 the early stages of political integration. It is always difficult and 
 unusual in those advanced stages wherein nations are combined 
 in world-empires. It is becoming well-nigh impossible, now that 
 all the continents have been brought under the sovereignty of the 
 so-called civilized peoples, while these peoples themselves, freely 
 communicating and intermingling, maintain with one another that 
 understanding which constitutes them, in a certain broad sense 
 of the term, a world-society. 
 
 The proximate effects also of the contrast that has been sketched 
 are generally recognized. 
 
 As long as blood, sympathy, religious faith, and political con- 
 sciousness are approximately coterminous, the groups that they 
 form, whether local communities or nations, must necessarily be 
 rather sharply delimited. They must be characterized also by 
 internal solidarity. Their membership is stable, because, to break 
 the bond of blood is not only to make oneself an outcast^ but is 
 also to be unfaithful to the ancestral gods ; to change one's religion 
 is not only to be impious, but is also to commit treason; to ex- 
 patriate oneself is not only to commit treason, but is also to 
 blaspheme against high heaven. 
 
 But when associations of believers, or of persons holding in 
 common any philosophy or doctrine whatsoever, are no longer 
 self-sufficing communities, and when nations, composite in blood, 
 have become compound in structure, all social groups, clusters, 
 or organizations, not only the cultural ones drawn together by 
 formative ideas, but also the economic and the political ones, 
 become in some degree plastic. Their membership then becomes 
 to some extent shifting and renewable. Under these circum- 
 stances any given association of men, let it be a village, a religious 
 group, a trade-union, a corporation, or a political party, not only 
 takes into itself new members from time to time; it also permits 
 old members to depart. Men come and men go, yet the associa-
 
 GROUP-MAKING ROLE OF IDEAS AND BELIEFS 179 
 
 tion or the group itself persists. As group, or as organization, 
 it remains unimpaired. 
 
 The economic advantage secured by this plasticity and renew- 
 ableness is beyond calculation enormous. It permits and facili- 
 tates the drafting of men at any moment from points where they 
 are least needed, for concentration upon points where they are 
 needed most. The spiritual or idealistic advantage is not less 
 great. The concentration of attention and of enthusiasm upon 
 strategic points gives ever-increasing impetus to progressive 
 movements. 
 
 Let us turn now from these merely proximate causes and 
 effects of group formation, to take note of certain developmental 
 processes which lie further back in the evolutionary sequence, 
 and which also have significance for our inquiry, since, when we 
 understand them, they may aid us in our attempt to answer the 
 question, What kind of group-making is likely to be accomplished 
 by cultural conflicts from this time forth? 
 
 The most readily perceived, because the most pictorial, of the 
 conflicts arising between one belief and another are those that 
 are waged between beliefs that have been localized and then, 
 through geographical expansion, have come into competition 
 throughout wide frontier areas. Of all such conflicts, that upon 
 which the world has now fully entered between occidental and 
 oriental ideas is not merely the most extensive; it is also by far 
 the most interesting and picturesque. 
 
 Less picturesque, but often more dramatic, are the conflicts 
 that arise within each geographical region, within each nation, 
 between old beliefs and new the conflicts of sequent, in dis- 
 tinction from coexistent ideas; the conflicts in time, in distinc- 
 tion from the conflicts in space. A new knowledge is attained, 
 which compels us to question old dogmas. A new faith arises, 
 which would displace the ancient traditions. As the new waxes 
 strong in a region favorable to it, it begins there, within 
 local limits, to supersede the old. Only then, when the conflict 
 between the old as old, and the new as new, is practically over, 
 does the triumphant new begin to go forth spatially as a con- 
 quering influence from the home of its youth into regions out- 
 lying and remote.
 
 i8o STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 Whatever the form, however, that the culture conflict assumes, 
 whether serial and dramatic, or geographical and picturesque, 
 its antecedent psychological conditions are in certain great es- 
 sentials the same. Men array themselves in hostile camps on 
 questions of theory and belief, not merely because they are vari- 
 ously and conflictingly informed, but far more because they are 
 mentally unlike, their minds having been prepared by structural 
 differentiation to seize upon different views and to cherish op- 
 posing convictions. That is to say, some minds have become 
 rational, critical, plastic, open, outlooking, above all, intuitive of 
 objective facts and relations. Others, in their fundamental con- 
 stitution have remained dogmatic, intuitive only of personal atti- 
 tudes or of subjective moods, temperamentally conservative and 
 instinctive. Minds of the one kind welcome the new and wider 
 knowledge; they go forth to embrace it. Minds of the other 
 kind resist it. 
 
 In the segregation thus arising, there is usually discoverable a 
 tendency toward grouping by sex. 
 
 Whether the mental and moral traits of women are inherent 
 and therefore permanent, or whether they are but passing effects 
 of circumscribed experience, and therefore possibly destined to 
 be modified, is immaterial for my present purpose. It is not cer- 
 tain that either the biologist or the psychologist is prepared to 
 answer the question. It is certain that the sociologist is not. It 
 is enough for the analysis that I am making now if we can say 
 that, as a merely descriptive fact, women thus far in the history 
 of the race have generally been more instinctive, more intuitive 
 of subjective states, more emotional, more conservative than men; 
 and that men, more generally than women, have been intuitive of 
 objective relations, inclined therefore to break with instinct and 
 to rely on the later-developed reasoning processes of the brain, 
 and willing, consequently, to take chances, to experiment, and to 
 innovate. 
 
 If so much be granted, we may perhaps say that it is because 
 of these mental differences that in conflicts between new and old 
 ideas, between new knowledge and old traditions, it usually hap- 
 pens that a large majority of all women are found in the camp
 
 GROUP-MAKING ROLE OF IDEAS AND BELIEFS 181 
 
 of the old, and that the camp of the new is composed mainly of 
 men. 
 
 In the camp of the new, however, are always to be found 
 women of alert intelligence, who happen also to be tempera- 
 mentally radical ; women in whom the reasoning habit has asserted 
 sway over instinct, and in whom intuition has become the true 
 scientific power to discern objective relations. And in the camp 
 of the old, together with a majority of all women, are to be found 
 most of the men of conservative instinct, and most of those also 
 whose intuitive and reasoning powers are unequal to the effort of 
 thinking about the world or anything in it in terms of impersonal 
 causation. Associated with all of these elements, both male and 
 female, may usually be discovered, finally, a contingent of priestly 
 personalities ; not necessarily religious priests, but men who love 
 to assert spiritual dominion, to wield authority, to be reverenced 
 and obeyed, and who naturally look for a following among the 
 non-skeptical and easily impressed. 
 
 Such, very broadly and rudely sketched, is the psychological 
 background of culture conflict. It is, however, a background 
 only, a certain persistent grouping of forces and conditions ; it is 
 not the cause from which culture conflicts proceed. 
 
 Always one and the same throughout the ages, although in the 
 course of human history it has assumed endlessly varied outward 
 shapes, the cause of all conflict, cultural, economic, juristic, polit- 
 ical, has slowly fashioned also their psychological factors. From 
 the dawn of life until now the alternative has ever and again 
 confronted living things, to change their habits or die. By far 
 the greater part of them have prematurely died because they could 
 not change. Of the survivors, the greater part have lived on be- 
 cause they have changed unconsciously. To a very few, of the 
 human kind, it has been given to know before the event that 
 change must come. They have perceived in time the shifting of 
 external relations, and this perception has been the fearsome New 
 Idea that has set man at variance against his father and the 
 daughter against her mother, that has brought not peace on earth, 
 but the sword. 
 
 And from the beginning it has literally been true that a man's 
 foes have been they of his own household. Sheltered in some
 
 182 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 degree in the struggle for existence, women have rarely felt, as 
 men have felt, the first staggering shock of new conditions. They 
 have rarely been compelled to change their outlook and their way 
 of life as unexpectedly and decisively as men have had to change. 
 They have been able therefore to cling longer to the established 
 order, and to cherish for it a lingering sentiment, a deep affection 
 even, that vigorous men have not been able fully to share. 
 
 From the beginning, therefore, whenever the necessity for a 
 new adjustment of life to its conditions has arisen, a conflict 
 between old and new habits, between old and new convictions, 
 between old and new sentiments, has been precipitated, and it has 
 arrayed the rationalistic or kinetic minds, chiefly men, against the 
 instinctive or static minds, chiefly women. 
 
 Yet from the beginning another tendency also has been mani- 
 fest. The approximate identification of static interest with 
 woman and of innovating interest with man, never absolute, has 
 become more and more imperfect. 
 
 In the dim past of the primitive age, when each sex had its 
 own traditions and its own ritual, each was taboo to the other, 
 except as the taboo could be broken by ceremonial magic. 
 
 Yet that primitive cult of the feminine, it is necessary to 
 remember, always included men as well as women. Boys who 
 could not endure the formidable initiation ceremonies that would 
 admit them to the cult of the men, were consigned to the camp 
 of the women, perhaps for life; were often compelled to don 
 female costume and to remain with the women while their more 
 stalwart brothers went forth to the chase or to war. As time 
 went on, around this nucleus of women and effeminate men 
 gathered an ever-enlarging accretion of men somewhat less femi- 
 nine in mental constitution, although, on the whole, timid and 
 conservative, and therefore antagonistic to a broadly masculine 
 view of life. At length men of strong personality, dogmatic and 
 authoritative, including old and clever men no longer fit for war, 
 seeing their opportunity to establish dominion, threw in their 
 fortunes also with the backward-looking multitude. In the camp 
 thus constituted, there developed one general attitude toward life 
 and conduct, one general scheme of piety and morals. In the 
 boldly masculine camp there developed another. There, superla-
 
 GROUP-MAKING ROLE OF IDEAS AND BELIEFS 183 
 
 lively virile minds stood ready to dare new risks. Crudely and 
 awkwardly but fearlessly experimenting, they perfected new ad- 
 justments and took the first infinitely difficult steps of human 
 progress. 
 
 So, while priests and women created backward-looking religion 
 and a punctilious morality of personal behavior, men of the daring 
 mood prophet and discoverer, warrior and reformer created a 
 forward-looking faith and fashioned the plastic secular structure 
 of economic, juristic, and political relations. 
 
 From the moment that these differentiations are established, one 
 new adjustment of human life to its changing conditions follows 
 swift upon another. Culture succeeds culture. That which in 
 its day and generation is practical and profane is transmuted into 
 the sacred and ceremonial. That which today is faith, front-fac- 
 ing and alive, tomorrow will have become reminiscent religion, 
 the sentimental worship of dead ideas, a thing of gentle memories 
 and regrets. 
 
 For long ages, each new faith as it arises, each new economic 
 and juristic order, is locally circumscribed. It cannot pass beyond 
 the bounds of a rigid political organization, and these are identi- 
 fied with the blood of tribe or nation. 
 
 But, little by little, political integration is achieved, and as age 
 after age goes by, each new culture finds a wider area open to it 
 for possible extension. At the same time each is more and more 
 restricted as a community- forming activity, because political 
 integration makes isolation difficult. Thenceforward, each cul- 
 ture beats upon every other, each mingles with every other, until 
 at length each blends with all. 
 
 The significance of this evolutionary process for our immediate 
 question I conceive to be somewhat as follows : 
 
 We are practically at the end of the community-forming stage 
 in culture conflict. Every vigorous group of ideas or beliefs in 
 the world will henceforth have unhindered way to propagate itself 
 geographically, to form vast associations of adherents. 
 
 The groups so formed will be indefinite. In the main they 
 will be plastic. In the main their membership will be mobile and 
 shifting. 
 
 That mobility is on all accounts to be desired. But while its
 
 1 84 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 gradual increase is on the whole inevitable, it will, nevertheless, in 
 some measure be restricted, and certain tendencies will be mani- 
 fest toward the formation of relatively definite groups of rela- 
 tively stable membership. The cause of these tendencies will be 
 the effort which each of these contending forces will make to 
 control and to use the police power of the state. 
 
 The police power has always a strictly regional or territorial 
 application. A municipal ordinance is valid for that local area 
 the population of which is incorporated as borough or city. The 
 statute of the commonwealth applies throughout the territory of 
 that state, but not elsewhere. The laws and administrative orders 
 of a national government have force within its territorial bound- 
 aries, but not beyond. 
 
 It follows that to the extent to which the use of the police power 
 for the achieving of any particular purpose is effective the popu- 
 lation to which it is applied becomes a selected group. Opponents 
 and misdemeanants are eliminated, or forced into conformity. 
 It is, therefore, theoretically possible for idea-forces, including 
 religious faiths and moral creeds, still to create community, as 
 well as sectarian, groupings. How far it is practically possible is 
 perhaps well enough illustrated by prohibition legislation in its 
 various forms. 
 
 If now we wish to judge what use is likely thus to be made of 
 the police power in culture conflict, we must call to mind the 
 character of the chief groups of conflicting ideas at present ar- 
 rayed against each other, and, as far as can be foreseen, likely to 
 maintain their antagonism into an indefinitely distant future. 
 
 The chief culture conflict today is the world-wide struggle 
 between scientific secularism on the one hand, and, on the other 
 hand, the various cults of supernaturalism, obscurantism, and 
 dogmatism. On the side of the cults are the forces of sentiment 
 and inertia. On the side of scientific secularism are arrayed the 
 forces of practical interest. Science makes its way with the mul- 
 titude, not because the multitude is capable of understanding it, 
 or even of greatly caring about it, but chiefly because the multi- 
 tude sees that science does things. It safeguards the crops. It 
 prevents or controls epidemics. It cuts down freight rates, and it 
 transmits thought through pathless wastes of firmament and sea.
 
 GROUP-MAKING ROLE OF IDEAS AND BELIEFS 185 
 
 Now it is a peculiarity of scientific secularism or profane 
 practicality, if we prefer so to describe it that, with all its power 
 and prestige, it has not been disposed thus far to employ the police 
 power to any considerable extent in furtherance of propagandism 
 or any sort of social group-making. It has used it chiefly for 
 general utilitarian ends as, for example, to enforce sanitation, 
 or to prevent destructive forms of exploitation, like child labor. 
 It has been distinctly opposed to any use of the police power to 
 compel assent to a belief, to enforce a creed, or to establish any 
 code of purely personal morals. 
 
 On the other hand, dogmatic supernaturalism has never cared 
 greatly about utilitarian interests, since these are of the earth, 
 and materialistic. But since the dawn of history dogmatic super- 
 naturalism has unhesitatingly made use of the police power, when- 
 ever it has been in a position to do so, to compel assent to articles 
 of faith, to enforce rules of purely personal conduct, and to 
 establish ceremonial forms. 
 
 Therefore it is probable that to the extent that scientific secular- 
 ism commands the situation, cultural association will be free. 1 
 To the extent that dogmatic supernaturalism, obscurantism, 
 mysticism, are in any region dominant, we may expect them to 
 use the police power to create group solidarity. 
 
 Much will depend, accordingly, upon the mental composition of 
 the various regional populations. By this I mean that much will 
 depend upon the predominance, in any given region, of one or 
 another mental type. The inductive, critical, intellectual mind, 
 intuitive of objective relations, turns naturally to scientific secu- 
 larism. The mystical, emotional, subjectively intuitive, instinctive 
 mind as naturally, indeed inevitably, embraces some highly re- 
 spectable dogmatism with an impressive pedigree, or rushes upon 
 a new-fangled miracleism. 
 
 It is to be regretted that we seem to have no quite appropriate 
 descriptive name for these two types of mind. In the writings of 
 European sociologists they are commonly designated as masculine 
 and feminine, and the social dominance of one type or the other 
 
 1 This I still believe to be true, notwithstanding all that has happened 
 since 1914.
 
 i86 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 is called masculinism or feminism. This usage is sometimes car- 
 ried to the point of labeling entire nations by sex-connoting terms. 
 Germany, for example, was by Bismarck called a masculine na- 
 tion, and Russia a feminine nation. 
 
 If the analysis of the two mental camps, radical and conserva- 
 tive, which I have presented in the foregoing pages, is substantially 
 accurate, these sex-connecting tags are somewhat inappropriate 
 and misleading. If we adopted them for scientific purposes, we 
 should be compelled to say that the prophet, whether man or 
 woman, is mentally masculine, and that the priest, whether woman 
 or man, is mentally feminine. This might not mystify because, 
 as a mere satirical conceit, the discrimination has long been fa- 
 miliar. But what would be said if we should apply this nomen- 
 clature to the business population of the United States? We 
 should then be compelled to class as masculine the business minds 
 of an engineering type minds that weigh, measure, calculate, and 
 plan, and to class as feminine all business minds that are incapable 
 of grasping the conception of impersonal causation. This would 
 be to say that American business men in general are woman-like, 
 since they are unable as yet to find any better explanation of com- 
 mercial crisis or industrial depression than the truly feminine 
 hypothesis that the administration is to blame for it. 
 
 But while we cannot describe intellectualism as masculine, .or 
 instinctive dogmatism as merely feminine, we cannot, I think, 
 afford to overlook the influence of so-called feminism when 
 we try to predict which of the conflicting culture forces will prob- 
 ably be ascendant in civilized life in the near future. 
 
 As we see it today, feminism is difficult to analyze. Doubtless 
 we may discover in it an effort by intellectual women to awaken 
 large numbers of their sex to the rational life, to wean them 
 from instinct, and to make their outlook increasingly objective. 
 It appears, however, that in certain respects the woman's move- 
 ment is so conducted as to defeat this commendable end. 
 
 When, for instance, women make up their minds to see things 
 "from the man's point of view," how shall they go about it? 
 
 As far as the somewhat skeptical observer, like myself, can 
 judge, they imagine that they are getting the masculine view 
 when they draw men into the circle of their own projects and
 
 GROUP-MAKING ROLE OF IDEAS AND BELIEFS 187 
 
 enterprises, planned, organized, and conducted by themselves. I 
 may be quite wrong in my interpretation of the facts, and I hold 
 my opinion subject to revision, but at present I am sure that by 
 this process of influencing and converting men, women get nothing 
 whatever but an intensification of feminism. They get "the point 
 of view" not of masculine men, but of two somewhat nondescript 
 varieties; namely, first, those gentlemen who in their schoolboy 
 days preferred daisies and buttercups to snowballs and "double 
 rippers," and second, those authoritative persons who are but too 
 glad to seize upon the opportunity thus afforded them to become 
 the confessors and demigods of a worshipful sex. Such always 
 are the men who lend themselves to those moral crusades which 
 proceed on the assumption that there is only a quantitative dif- 
 ference between virtue of private vintage and the virtue that is 
 squeezed and barreled at the public winepress. 
 
 To this particular skeptic now speaking, it appears that the 
 person who at the present moment is commonly styled "the new 
 woman" is of all women in civilized lands the most thoroughly 
 primitive. So far from seeing life from the man's point of view, 
 she has taken herself back to that most ancient camp of her sex 
 from whose sacred ground all strictly non-feminine men were 
 looked upon as scandalous and taboo. 
 
 On the other hand, it does not seem to this skeptic that woman 
 necessarily gets the man's point of view by following "the good 
 old way, the simple plan" of giving herself to him in the holy 
 bonds of matrimony and bearing numerous sons to distribute his 
 property. 
 
 In reality, her getting the man's point of view, if that is what 
 she wants and is bound to have, depends altogether upon the kind 
 of men, including father and brothers, husbands, sons, and ac- 
 quaintances that she happens to consort with. If she is thrown 
 with anabolic gentlemen only, she can never arrive at the mascu- 
 line outlook. If her associations are with masculine men she will 
 enjoy that outlook, if she is capable of seeing it. 
 
 Probably nothing can with so much certainty be counted on to 
 bring women into contact with men of essentially masculine type 
 as an intellectual education and the cultivation of intellectual 
 interests in intellectual association and comradeship with men.
 
 1 88 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 But this in my judgment is not to be achieved by the ordinary 
 processes of college training only. Intellectual principles must 
 be applied to life, and women must be associated with men in 
 making the application. Of the many spheres of activity in 
 which this may be done, the economic, the scientific, the literary, 
 and the artistic are not to be despised. Yet, after all, the great 
 realm in which intellectual principles can be and should be applied 
 to life is the realm of politics, and possibly women in general will 
 not see life quite as men see it until they fully participate in the 
 obligations as in the privileges of the masculine Brotherhood of 
 Machiavelli. 
 
 If such, however, is the truth, argument appears to end in 
 dilemma, as indeed, most arguments on practical questions do. 
 For it is not probable that if all women were at once to take part 
 in political life, the forces of true radicalism, of scientific secular- 
 ism, could make headway, or even hold their ground. What then 
 would become "of the man's point of view"? The dogmatic pro- 
 gram of using the police power of legislatures and the courts 
 to compel uniformity of moral profession and pretense would 
 in all likelihood be used to the uttermost. 1 We should have retro- 
 gression from free and plastic association toward local or com- 
 munity grouping on grounds not perhaps of belief, as in bygone 
 days, but at least of "good morals." 
 
 Happily, no such calamity need be apprehended. Great num- 
 bers of women are yet too wedded to tradition to become at once 
 politically active. Those that accept political obligations will in a 
 measure be transformed and broadened by them before the multi- 
 tude of their sisters follows their example. Therefore, with some 
 confidence we may still hold to the main conclusion that this 
 survey of forces and tendencies of culture conflict has suggested. 
 Political integration will not cease. Scientific secularism, not only 
 through its appeal to the intelligence of modern man, but also 
 through its sheer practical utility, will assuredly hold the ground 
 it has taken and make further gains. Whatever its momentary 
 victories, the old, in the long run, cannot overthrow the new, 
 because Its own inertia incapacitates it for continuous aggressive 
 action. Therefore we may reasonably expect that the world of 
 * It is, in 1922.
 
 GROUP-MAKING ROLE OF IDEAS AND BELIEFS 189 
 
 social relations will continue from this time on to become less and 
 less a congeries of static, solidaristic groups, and more and more a 
 bewildering complex of free associations, through which the ener- 
 gies of mankind, responsibly economized, will freely create the 
 things of human good.
 
 CHAPTER XI 
 
 FOLKWAYS AND STATEWAYS 
 
 IDEAS, including group-making ideas, and policies, including 
 policies of control, are carried out, or "realized," in collective 
 action through two contrasting procedures, each of which uses 
 characteristic means. One of them is without authority to com- 
 mand, although it now and then does command, and it is not 
 governmental in form or power; the other commands, and it 
 uses all arms of the political state to compel. 
 
 The value of non-governmental mechanisms and methods was 
 emphasized in radical political theory and insisted on in radical 
 practical politics long before their true nature was understood; 
 long, indeed, before their history, variety and actual performance 
 were known. Men temperamentally rebellious against authority 
 and intellectually convinced that the government which governs 
 least is best, looked to voluntary cooperation to initiate and carry 
 on most of the enterprises of civilization. In particular, they 
 objected to governmental meddling in business, they resented gov- 
 ernmental dictation of private conduct, and they distrusted 
 governmental activity in education. The classical formulations 
 of this creed are Mill's Liberty and Spencer's Social Statics. 
 
 If one were looking for an example of how not to think about 
 human behavior one could hardly hope to stumble upon anything 
 better for the purpose than a political platform constructed out 
 of laissez faire economics and utilitarian ethics. As an appeal to 
 reason it gets the assent of not a few vigorous intellects, but the 
 masses of mankind are not made up of vigorous intellects, and 
 political parties have never been able to do a large scale business 
 on appeals to reason. The Liberal party of Great Britain has 
 been Benthamite and the Democratic party in the United States 
 has been Jeffersonian on occasions, but theoretical consistency has 
 not often strengthened them with electorates. 
 
 190
 
 FOLKWAYS AND STATEWAYS 191 
 
 The practical politician has always known what the psychologist 
 and the sociologist have been slow to learn, that "muddling 
 through," as the Englishman (not without a touch of pride per- 
 haps) is wont to describe the collective behavior of Britons, is a 
 general practice. It has been the method of the human race 
 throughout history. Even the Frenchman, with all his love of 
 logic, has been experimental in the main. He has arrived at an 
 approximately stable republicanism after trial of most of the pos- 
 sibilities of aristocracy and royal despotism, of revolution and 
 communism, of dictatorship and militaristic imperialism. 
 
 This does not mean that voluntaristic cooperation has played a 
 smaller part than government in human affairs. It has played 
 an immensely larger part, but it has been a thing hit upon at ran- 
 dom, an accumulation of accidental combinations of efforts, a 
 slowly developed usage, and not in any considerable measure 
 a reasoned contrivance. 
 
 Among the earliest scholarly studies of the history and preva- 
 lence of usage were Henry Sumner Maine's writings on custom. 
 The first scientific account of its origin was Walter Bagehot's 
 Physics and Politics. In that little book, one of the most 
 valuable contributions to sociology ever made, the true character 
 of custom is clearly exhibited, and its functioning in the collective 
 struggle for existence is accurately described. In one particular, 
 however, it leaves a wrong impression, as Maine's studies also 
 did, namely that custom, the substance of early society, is super- 
 seded in later society by deliberation. This impression is con- 
 veyed also in a degree by Spencer's Ceremonial Institutions. 
 How far from the whole truth it is we were made aware when 
 William Graham Sumner published Folkways. In this further 
 unique contribution to our knowledge of society, indispensably 
 supplementing Bagehot, we learn how large and pervading is the 
 part played in our most complex modern civilizations by modes 
 of voluntaristic cooperation that began nobody knows when or 
 how, that in most instances have been modified only with incred- 
 ible slowness throughout the generations, and that are resistant 
 now, as always hitherto, to rationalization. 
 
 The serious student of these matters must know his Bagehot 
 and Spencer and Sumner at first hand. Not otherwise can he
 
 IQ2 
 
 attain appreciation and understanding of the infinite variety and 
 complexity, the quality and the social functioning of the folk- 
 ways and the mores : of all that we have called ceremony, usage 
 and custom, manners and morals. I shall make no attempt, there- 
 fore, to summarize the matter here. Assuming on the part of my 
 readers a sufficient acquaintance with it, I call attention to some 
 of the more important particulars in which folkways differ from 
 stateways (the governmental ways of states) and stateways from 
 folkways, and to the ways (a highly important specialization of 
 ways), in which these fundamental modes of human behavior 
 react upon one another, setting bounds to the scope and the 
 performance of each. 
 
 It is to be understood that while all prevailing modes of volun- 
 tary cooperation are folkways, not all folkways are modes of co- 
 operation. Anything that everybody does is a folkway, and so is 
 anything that most or even many persons do in any region for two, 
 or three, or many generations. 
 
 When in 1888 I went to Bryn Mawr to live I found myself 
 curiously interested one morning in "the green bag." On a train 
 going into Philadelphia every commuting attorney and counselor- 
 at-law was carrying one. . In the Housatonic and Connecticut 
 River valleys, where I had spent my childhood and earlier bread- 
 winning years, I had never seen one, although I happened to know 
 something about the history of the thing and the legal connotations 
 of its name. Such localization of a folkway is one of the more 
 obvious marks of its true character as a spontaneous or uncon- 
 trivecl product of the adaptations and adjustments of men to 
 environment and circumstance . It is itself highly adaptive. It 
 can extend widely by imitation, or so identify itself with the 
 region in which it arose or to which it was transplanted that it 
 remains unknown elsewhere. In contrast to this fundamental 
 characteristic of folkways, stateways extend themselves aggres- 
 sively. The state itself is an inclusive organization which pro- 
 claims authority over all individuals residing within defined geo- 
 graphical bounds, admitting them into its citizenship or govern- 
 ing them as aliens.
 
 FOLKWAYS AND STATEWAYS 193 
 
 Because the folkway is adaptive it is variable, and folkways, 
 therefore, become various, not only because new ways from time 
 to time arise out of new circumstances and demands, but also 
 through differentiation. One has only to call to mind the fluctua- 
 tions of fashion, the changing forms of address and ceremony, the 
 rise and fall of recreations, the fleeting fads in games and sports, 
 to realize the enormous flexibility of folkways. Stateways tend 
 toward uniformity. Governments attempt to standardize not only 
 rights at law but also legal procedure, administrative rules, and 
 the conduct of citizens. Legislators are intolerant of exceptions, 
 bureaucrats abominate them, and courts, while finding precedents 
 for them when moral justice or the rule of reason requires, do 
 not otherwise make them. Trial by jury, however, which medi- 
 ates between folkways and stateways, is a venerable if not always 
 a venerated defense against the governmentalists, who would dic- 
 tate and ration our food and drink, write our medical prescrip- 
 tions, cut our clothes, tell us what we may read and look at, and 
 send us to bed at curfew. 
 
 Stateways are instituted by command, backed up by physical 
 force. They are formal, as machine-like as they can be made, 
 and relentless. Folkways exert pressure which may be resist- 
 less, but it is indefinable, elastic and automatically variable. 
 
 At a seashore club of the quiet sort I remarked to a lady whose 
 associations were with college folk and writers, that habitues 
 there, most of them apparently intelligent, did not desecrate the 
 place with intellectual conversation. "No," she replied with 
 admonitory severity, "it isn't done." There you have the true 
 folkway pressure, or control. The thing is done or it isn't, and 
 you know (or you learn) which. 
 
 Means or devices are used, to be sure, but they are countless 
 and protean. They range from silent approval or disapproval to 
 taboo, from snubbing to bullying. In a majority of instances the 
 lighter means suffice, but occasionally, in times of stress, especially 
 in days of war or of industrial clash, more vigorous measures are 
 resorted to. These include "drives," the boycott and slacking, the 
 strike, property-destroying sabotage and violence, and, in last 
 resort, the use of physical force in direct action. When this
 
 194 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 happens the folkway is verging on revolution, which, in fact, is 
 contemplated. The folkway then has become an incipient state- 
 way. 
 
 In these latest named phenomena we come to the reactions of 
 folkways and stateways upon each other. 
 
 Antecedent to revolution, and usually by warning preventive of 
 it, are folkways of disregard and disobedience of law and of open 
 opposition to government. These lower the state's coercive 
 efficiency, and admonish it to reconsider its possibly unjust or 
 inexpedient command, or its ruthless or arbitrary policy. 
 
 The assumption of pre-sociological political science that 
 sovereignty is a power to compel obedience was never quite true 
 and probably it never will be. 1 The dean of one of our most 
 reputable law schools said to me, "You couldn't find a citizen of 
 this or of any other American commonwealth who is not a law- 
 breaker." Whether or not he was right in his belief, it is true that 
 no law ever enacted has been obeyed by all individuals in any 
 group or class of citizens, however respectable. It is also true 
 that a large proportion of all legislative enactments sooner or later 
 fall into the "dead letter" category. Furthermore, drastic laws 
 are openly contemned by great numbers of otherwise reputable 
 citizens. Laws prescribing Sunday observance, laws like the 
 Dred Scott decision maintaining slavery, laws forbidding discrim- 
 ination on account of color, and laws prohibiting alcoholic drinks, 
 are notorious American examples. 
 
 The dictum attributed to General Grant, often quoted and 
 widely accepted, that the way to get ruTof a bad law is to enforce 
 it, may be good logic but it is not historical fact. Laws are re- 
 pealed only when law breakers, and voters who would be law 
 breakers if conscience or good sense would permit them to be, are 
 numerous enough and courageous enough to upset legislative 
 majorities. Often a highly provocative law cannot be repealed by 
 this procedure because the necessary courage is lacking. Out- 
 spoken advocates of repeal are set upon as irreligious or immoral, 
 as apologists for vice and crime, or as anarchists who want to 
 destroy property and upset the social order. Such penalizing, 
 
 1 See Giddings, The Responsible State.
 
 FOLKWAYS AND STATEWAYS 195 
 
 which is meant to frighten off support by the timid, and usually 
 does, is itself a folkway. It is powerless, however, against the 
 folkways of clandestine disobedience, and when these flourish, 
 disobedience presently ceases to be clandestine. Nothing further 
 happens then, perhaps for generations, unless new attempts to 
 enforce create enough irritation to provoke organized defiance, as 
 happened in the case of slavery. In either case the objectionable 
 law, whether quietly nullified or noisily defied is not done away 
 with by due process of stateways, until these have been changed or 
 mitigated by folkway pressure. 
 
 In all these instances, however, the folkways are attacked by the 
 state, which may or may not prevail. If it does not prevail, it 
 nevertheless impedes and limits folkway achievement. In partic- 
 ular it forbids and undertakes to repress the use in folkway action 
 of physical force, which the state asserts its authority to monopo- 
 lize. 
 
 These, then, are the normal reactions of folkways and stateways 
 upon each other: folkways of disobedience nullify laws, and now 
 and then defy the stateways; the state paralyzes disobedience 
 when it can ; and at any cost it makes vigorous effort to repress 
 folkway violence. 
 
 Normally these contrary forces arrive at equilibrium. Ways 
 of adjustment develop, and in these society attains a compromise 
 of liberty with security. Out of trial and error a tradition of 
 general consent grows up that the state shall use physical force 
 to repel invasion, to put down rebellion, to repress organized vio- 
 lence and mob action, and to penalize crime. No equally general 
 consent is ever reached to the use of for^e by the state to repress 
 vice and to correct negligence. This province remains fighting 
 ground where folkways and stateways contend. We are not with- 
 out indications, however, of possible truce. When vice or negli- 
 gence threatens social existence because folkways have failed to 
 repress, or to meet urgent needs, action by the state is usually 
 assented to ; but when folkways are presumably adequate to the 
 occasion, objection to state interference and resentment against it, 
 extend and deepen- The possibilities of truce are measured, how- 
 ever, by the intelligence and the education of the population. To 
 see when folkways spontaneous, elastic, and adaptable are
 
 196 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 adequate to correct and superior to improve, and, conversely, to 
 see when state interference is indubitably called for, is not given 
 to ignorance or to stupidity. 
 
 The interactions of folkways and stateways are further ex- 
 hibited in the next two following chapters.
 
 CHAPTER XII 
 
 SOCIAL SELF-CONTROL 
 
 AT a meeting of the inhabitants of Dorchester, Massachusetts, 
 on October 28, 1634, it was "agreed that whosoever is chosen into 
 any office for the good of the plantation, he shall abide by it or 
 submit to a fine as the company shall think meet to impose." 
 Less than a week later, on November 3, it was "ordered that no 
 man within the plantation shall sell his house or lott to any man 
 without the plantation whom they shall dislike of." 1 
 
 In voting these measures the people of Dorchester only made 
 definite and explicit a general policy adopted by all the early 
 New England towns, and for a long time adhered to. No one was 
 a franchise-exercising member of a town until he was formally 
 admitted as a freeman, and at the outset church membership was 
 a condition. 
 
 Historically interesting because of the conditions which it was 
 intended to meet and because of the specific tests that were applied 
 in carrying it out, this policy was not new or exceptional as a phe- 
 nomenon of community action. Since human beings began to 
 dwell together in groups and to work together in bands or com- 
 panies, the groups and the bands have exercised supervision over 
 their membership and over the conduct of their members. On a 
 larger scale than elsewhere, or before in history, the United States, 
 through its immigration and naturalization laws, exercises super- 
 vision over the membership of a national community; and our 
 local state and federal laws probably comprise the largest body 
 of rules of conduct ever enacted by a politically organized popula- 
 tion for the regulation of individual life. 
 
 It is not for the purpose of recalling a chapter of American 
 history, however interesting it may be in itself, that these facts 
 are here set down. They are given because they happen to exhibit 
 
 1 Fourth Report of the Record Commissioners of Boston (1880), docu- 
 ment 9, pp. 7, 8. 
 
 197
 
 ig8 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 clearly a social phenomenon that too often has been overlooked 
 or forgotten in the construction of social science, but which may 
 prove to be the point of departure for important discriminations. 
 The minutes cited from the Dorchester record quite plainly 
 show that the inhabitants of that town were looking after the 
 make-up of their community and the conduct of its members for 
 at least two distinct purposes. The resolution that a man chosen 
 to office must undertake its duties or pay a penalty shows that 
 the Dorchester folk assumed that they were collectively doing 
 something, not idly enjoying the pleasure of neighborly association 
 while pursuing merely individual ends. Translated into the com- 
 pact language of these latter days, the resolution tells us that the 
 townsmen of Dorchester understood that they were attempting 
 "team work," and that every man in the enterprise must accept 
 that particular part of the task which "the team" assigned to him. 
 The second resolution manifests an alert consciousness of the 
 importance of group cohesion, a thing even more essential than 
 individual efficiency as a factor in common enterprise. The mem- 
 bers of the community must be agreeable one to another. The 
 man "disliked of" should be kept out. 
 
 Let us apply a bit of analysis to these elementary facts. The 
 common activity of a community of the simpler sort a neighbor- 
 hood group of farmer folk, for example may be extremely slight. 
 Its team work may for a long time be potential only, a mere readi- 
 ness to undertake the common defence, if necessary, or to co- 
 operate in some emergency, as of flood or fire. In a large and 
 complex community the team work is actual, often energetic, 
 carefully organized and extremely varied. It provides for the 
 common safety. It engages in the production of wealth. It 
 establishes and maintains those rules of the game which collec- 
 tively are called law, and it carries on government to ascertain 
 and to apply the common will. 
 
 But whether actual and organized or only potential and un- 
 formed, the collective activity of any group of human units 
 obviously presents to scientific view two unmistakably different 
 aspects. A community collectively does things for itself that is, 
 for its members and it collectively does things to or upon itself,
 
 SOCIAL SELF-CONTROL 199 
 
 scrutinizing and determining its membership, scrutinizing and 
 censoring conduct. It does things collectively for itself, because 
 experience has shown that many things can be accomplished by 
 collective action or team work that cannot be accomplished ade- 
 quately or at all by individual effort. It does things to itself, 
 because experience has shown that not every aggregate of indi- 
 viduals can carry on team work effectively or even live together 
 amicably. 
 
 This differentiation of social function into collective action 
 for and collective action upon society would seem to be funda- 
 mental. If it is, we apparently have here the point of departure 
 for a working distinction between certain special social sciences 
 and a more general science of society. It is clear, for example, 
 that the economist, in studying the social production and distribu- 
 tion of wealth, is primarily investigating the action of the com- 
 munity in doing an important work for its productive units. He 
 concerns himself only incidentally with the reactions of economic 
 activity upon the social composition and structure. In like man- 
 ner the jurist, in studying the nature and the evolution of legal 
 relations and activities, and the student of political science, in 
 examining the nature and the evolution of government, are pri- 
 marily looking at social functioning as it bears directly upon the 
 well-being of component elements of society, although incidentally 
 or secondarily they may be interested in consequent modifications 
 of the integral social order. On the other hand, a student who 
 has followed the genesis of the community itself and has observed 
 that sooner or later it becomes aware of itself as a community 
 and begins consciously to react upon itself, may then direct his 
 further inquiries upon the nature, scope and consequences of the 
 reaction. If he does this, he is engaged upon investigations which, 
 in recent years, have been grouped under the name of general 
 sociology. 
 
 In offering this distinction between general sociology and the 
 special social sciences, I suppose that I am not making an essen- 
 tially new generalization; certainly I am not doing violence to 
 usage. For the distinction itself, I think, has unconsciously 
 grown up in usage, and I am here merely recognizing it, pointing 
 out the two distinct aspects of social functioning upon which it
 
 200 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 rests and putting it in explicit terms for more convenient appli- 
 cation. 
 
 Assuming, then, that general sociology, whatever else it may 
 comprise, is particularly concerned with the phenomenon of social 
 self-control, 1 including under this term the social determination 
 of the composition of the community, the control of conduct, the 
 promotion of efficiency, the shaping of social organization and 
 the determination of general policies, we may further look at the 
 whole subject in certain other lights, hoping so to get a more 
 rounded notion of what social self-control is, how it arises, what it 
 does and by what methods it may be subjected to effective scien- 
 tific study. 
 
 All nations compel their subjects to live under restraints and to 
 perform prescribed acts. As far as their observed conduct goes, 
 subjects must be loyal, whether or not they are patriotic at heart. 
 In a lesser degree the modern nations constrain their subjects in- 
 accordance with some prevailing idea of the common good. A 
 protective tariff, for example, does not altogether prevent, but 
 it restricts, the purchase of desired commodities produced abroad. 
 
 Within the broad limits fixed by national policy, states and 
 municipalities regulate the individual lives of their citizens in 
 endless detail. From birth to death the pressure of organized 
 society is hourly felt by its conscious units. Parental authority 
 is restrained wifhin bounds which the state prescribes. At the 
 command of the state the child is taught and drilled. Growing 
 to manhood, he orders his walk and conversation as the state in- 
 structs, or he languishes in jail. 
 
 If the citizen, thus reared and moulded by an external power 
 manifesting itself through government and law, happens to be a 
 religious as well as a political animal, he finds himself subjected 
 to further rules and orders. The church to which he belongs 
 exacts an obedience sanctioned by penalties which may be as 
 fearsome to his mind as are the fines and imprisonments im- 
 
 *In employing this term I am not trying to improve upon the phrase 
 made familiar through Professor Ross's admirable book on Social 
 Control but am only examining some aspects of social control more 
 particularly.
 
 SOCIAL SELF-CONTROL 201 
 
 posed by a secular power. If he earns his bread in the sweat of 
 his brow, he discovers that he is only partly free to work as 
 he pleases, or when or as long as he pleases, or to make such 
 contracts as his own best judgment approves. The "walking 
 delegate" finds him out and instructs him in the ethics of industrial 
 solidarity. If in idleness he consumes the substance that other 
 men have provided and, in the quiet of his club, seeks refuge from 
 the over-regulated life of a Philistine world, even there he encoun- 
 ters the rules committee taking cognizance of his language and 
 his drinks, and standing ready to exclude him if he oversteps the 
 line of that conduct which is reputable among gentlemen. 
 
 In barbarian and in savage communities the collective regula- 
 tion of life is not less but greater than it is in the civilized state. 
 The bounds that may not be overstepped are narrow and dread. 
 Immemorial custom is inflexible, and half of all the possible joys 
 of existence are forbidden and taboo. 
 
 Even in animal bands and herds, individual behavior is con- 
 strained. Inadequate or obnoxious members of the company are 
 abandoned, expelled or killed by their fellows. We do not presume 
 that in animal groups there is any cooperative understanding in 
 these matters. We cannot suppose that there is. But through 
 like response to the same stimulus or to similar stimuli, through 
 suggestion and impression, a real although non-reasoned coopera- 
 tion is effected. While, therefore, we may not say that animal 
 society abides by rules, we observe that it lives by habits from 
 which a member departs only at the risk of life. 
 
 There would be no excuse for bringing forward observations 
 so commonplace as these if the general truth which they thrust 
 upon us had not been very nearly left out of consideration in 
 our attempts to establish the broad conceptions of a science of 
 society. Whatever else society is, it is a group of units and 
 relations which collectively acts under self-direction. It not only 
 manifests a continuing process, as brain and nervous system 
 manifest the processes of mind, as organic matter manifests the 
 processes of life, but also, like living matter and like mind, it con- 
 trols its own processes. Society constrains. Unconsciously at 
 first, but consciously in its later and higher development, it brings
 
 202 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 pressure to bear upon its component units. It incites and re- 
 strains them. It trains and moulds them. It conforms them to 
 a norm or type and sets limits to their variation from it. 
 
 Here, then, we have a generalization of significance. Society 
 4s a type or norm or mode, which in a measure controls the varia- 
 tions from itself. 
 
 In thus functioning, society, by trial and error and by rational 
 effort, carries further and brings to greater precision that process 
 which in its unconscious mode we call natural selection. In the 
 organic struggle for existence those individuals and those groups 
 survive which are adapted to the conditions under which they 
 dwell. This is only another way of saying that organisms which 
 in some fortunate way combine certain structures, qualities and 
 traits, and which, therefore, conform closely to a type that hap- 
 pens to be suited to a given place, can live there ; while individuals 
 or groups that vary too widely from this type sooner or later fail 
 there to perpetuate their race. Or, to put it in yet another way, 
 in every inhabitable region there is an environmental constraint, 
 compelling conformity of organic structure and of life to certain 
 adapted or adaptable types, from which variation is possible only 
 within somewhat definite limits. 
 
 It is because of this conformity to type that society arises. 
 Typical units or individuals of a given species or variety are alike 
 as far as they are typical. Animate individuals that closely re- 
 semble one another respond in like ways to the same given stim- 
 ulus or to similar stimuli. So organized and responding, they 
 want the same things and by similar behavior try to obtain them. 
 If the supply is inadequate for all and some part of it can be 
 obtained by individual effort, like acts develop into competition. 
 If the supply is adequate for all but cannot easily be obtained by 
 individual effort, the like efforts of many individuals directed 
 toward the same end develop, unconsciously and accidentally at 
 first, but afterwards, in mankind, rationally, into cooperation. In 
 either case, those adaptations which the animate organism, in 
 common with all others, makes directly to its environment in gen- 
 eral, are supplemented by a set of highly complicated adjustments 
 made to the similar adaptations of other units like itself.
 
 SOCIAL SELF-CONTROL 203 
 
 These adjustments of animate individuals to the like adapt- 
 ations of other individuals of their own kind are the bases of 
 social relations. Repeated and developed into habits, they create 
 and establish those relationships which we call social organization. 
 
 The similarity which is antecedent to all these adjustments and 
 relations becomes to some extent an object of consciousness in all 
 associating creatures of the higher varieties. Appearing first as 
 sympathy, it develops into a perception of likeness and at length, 
 in mankind, into a more or less rationalized understanding of re- 
 semblances and differences, of agreements and dissensions. Step 
 by step with this evolution of a consciousness of kind, the impor- 
 tance of "kind" itself is apprehended. Fundamental identities or 
 similarities of nature and purpose, of instinct and habit, of mental 
 and moral qualities, of capacities and abilities, are recognized as 
 factors in the struggle for existence. To the extent that safety 
 and prosperity depend upon group cohesion and cooperation, they 
 are seen to depend upon such conformity to type as may suffice to 
 insure the cohesion and to fulfil the cooperation. 
 
 Conforming to the requirement of group life which itself is a 
 product of the struggle for existence animals instinctively and 
 by habit, human beings instinctively, by habit, and rationally, 
 manifest a dominant antipathy to those variations from type 
 which attract attention. There are striking exceptions to this rule, 
 as there are to nearly all rules of behavior by organic units. But 
 the rule is beyond question. From the insects to the highest mam- 
 mals, individuals deformed or queer are commonly objects of 
 attack and may be put to death by their fellows. Death or aban- 
 donment usually overtakes the conspicuous variates among sav- 
 ages and barbarians, while in civilized communities they are ob- 
 jects of suspicion and avoidance, or of guardianship or restraint, 
 according to the state of enlightenment and the degree of humane 
 feeling. 
 
 How far individual conduct in swarms of insects and in bands 
 of gregarious animals is forced into conformity to type by an 
 instinctive adjustment, distinct from a circumstantial constraint, 
 it is not possible on the basis of present knowledge to say. That 
 the uniformity of human conduct in savage and barbarian 
 communities is immediately a product of social constraint largely
 
 204 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 spontaneous, imitative and unconscious, but also partly conscious 
 and deliberate and only remotely and indirectly a product of 
 environmental or circumstantial constraint, is a fact too familiar 
 to call for demonstration. By the conscious cooperation of elders 
 in directing the rearing of children by young parents, by organ- 
 ized initiation ceremonies, by clan and tribal councils, each new 
 generation is remorselessly trained in those beliefs, habits and 
 loyalties which the group regards as vital to its existence. Care- 
 fully analyzed, the entire mass of inculcations and restrictions 
 whereby individual behavior is controlled in uncivilized society 
 may be seen to be a means of enforcing conformity to type, of 
 recognizing and maintaining a "kind," for the ulterior purpose of 
 ensuring group cohesion and cooperative efficiency. 
 
 The restraints, the inculcations, the obedience-compelling de- 
 vices of civilized society are so varied and so interlaced that they 
 easily mislead, and it is only after long and comprehensive study 
 of them that one begins to grasp their nature and function. 
 Stripped of all adventitious features, they one and all are means to 
 the same general end which is served by social constraint in bar- 
 barian and in savage communities. They determine, limit and 
 control variation from type, now extending its range, now nar- 
 rowing it and compelling a closer conformity. 
 
 A word must here be added regarding the consequences of 
 social control. Society constrains. What are the effects of con- 
 straint ? 
 
 The proximate results are new or wider uniformities of be- 
 havior and ultimately of character. Life is made so difficult for 
 the variates that stray too far from type that they go down in the 
 struggle. Society, in a word, create? artificial conditions of exist- 
 ence which affect selection, as natural conditions do, by determin- 
 ing a selective death-rate. When, for example, a Christian civili- 
 zation compels a savage population to wear clothes, it kills off 
 those individuals whose viscera cannot adapt themselves to the 
 unaccustomed burden. When society increases its educational 
 pressure, it eliminates some who cannot endure further nerve 
 strain or whose reproductive powers fail under the increased re- 
 quirement of individuation. Social constraint, then, creates arti-
 
 SOCIAL SELF-CONTROL 205 
 
 ficial conditions, which act selectively upon the associated units. 
 From a human point of view, such selective action may be good 
 or evil. It may tend to produce and to perpetuate a stock of 
 which intelligent minds think well, or one of which they think ill. 
 From the point of view of the evolutionary process, the selected 
 and surviving stock may be one which perpetuates its line with 
 diminishing or with increasing cost to the individual. Assuming 
 that race perpetuation with diminishing cost to the individual, or 
 with actual increase of individual opportunity and happiness, is 
 worth while and is, substantially, the thing which mankind calls 
 progress, we may say that social constraint makes for progress or 
 against it. 
 
 Summarizing the foregoing observations, we note that the un- 
 conscious evolutionary process in nature creates types. Because 
 they conform more or less closely to type, animate organisms 
 of the same variety or kind want the same things and in like 
 ways try to obtain them. The various primary adaptations to 
 environment, therefore, are inevitably supplemented by adjust- 
 ments made by each individual to the similar adaptations of 
 fellow-individuals. Group relations in which both competitive 
 and cooperative activities are carried on unconsciously and only 
 accidentally at first, but presently, in the human species, deliber- 
 ately therefore necessarily appear. Society comes into exist- 
 ence. The conscious units of human society become increasingly 
 aware of differences and resemblances among themselves. They 
 apprehend the extent of their conformity to type or kind. The 
 belief arises among them that in most instances marked departure 
 from type is dangerous to the safety of the group or is a limitation 
 of cooperative efficiency. Conformity to type is regarded as con- 
 tributing both to the safety and to the efficiency of the group. 
 Out of this notion grow conscious efforts to increase conformity, 
 to scrutinize the "kinds" and to limit the range of variation. A 
 social constraint is consciously evolved which exerts its pressure 
 upon all component units of the group. Like environmental con- 
 straints, social constraint affects selection. In the long run it 
 makes itself felt in the selective death-rate. The kind or type that 
 survives under social pressure is believed by the conscious units
 
 206 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 of society to be relatively efficient in the struggle for existence. 
 It is supposed also to be relatively individualized. A group or 
 community in which increasing individuation is secured without 
 imperiling race maintenance thinks of itself as progressive. 
 
 The means of constraint that society uses, as we learn early in 
 life by individual experience, are rewards and punishments. By 
 praise and blame, by avoidance and rebuke, by indulgence and 
 license, by penance and fine, by suspension and expulsion, by cor- 
 poral punishment and maiming, by imprisonment and execution, 
 men are forced to desist, to obey, to help ; their conduct is edu- 
 cated into habits ; their efforts are stimulated or goaded to accept- 
 able degrees of intensity and persistence; their characters are 
 moulded to approved types. 
 
 For all these processes of constraint and regulation in their 
 entirety, society has its own descriptive names. Collectively they 
 constitute the thing familiarly known as discipline, and their 
 objective product, conformity of behavior, is morale. 
 
 Upon the creation and perfecting of discipline, and upon 
 the standardizing of behavior and the selection of character by 
 means of discipline, society has directed conscious efforts from 
 the beginning. At first blunderingly, afterwards more or less 
 skillfully, it has discovered, applied and tested disciplinary 
 measures. The larger number and the best of them have been 
 folkways. Stateways have been cruder, often cruel and often 
 disastrous, but sometimes necessary and effective. But whether 
 folkways or stateways the particular methods constituting disci- 
 pline have been employed in the conviction that much conformity 
 to kind or type or standard is essential to security and to co- 
 operative efficiency. The object in view from the first has been 
 to diminish the failures and to multiply the successes of associat- 
 ing human beings, in the struggle for existence. 
 
 If then we say in the language of every-day life, that society is 
 an organization for the promotion of well-being and efficiency by 
 means of standardization and discipline, we say the same thing as 
 when in evolutionist terms we said that society is a type, control- 
 ling variation from itself for its own survival and further evolu- 
 tion. Discipline, from the evolutionist point of view, is a distinct
 
 SOCIAL SELF-CONTROL 207 
 
 phenomenon, differing in kind, rather than in mere degree, from 
 all others. Motion, the activity of all matter, inorganic or or- 
 ganic; metabolism, the activity of organic matter; response to 
 stimulus, the activity of animate organic matter; discipline, the 
 activity of type-conforming conscious groups this is the series 
 of natural phenomena. Physics and chemistry, biology, psychol- 
 ogy and anthropology, sociology these are the corresponding 
 sciences. 
 
 Material for the descriptive and historical study of the evolu- 
 tion of discipline and of the relations of discipline to efficiency, 
 to individuation and to survival, is abundant, but as a phenomenon 
 of control, by a type, of variation from itself, it calls for quantita- 
 tive study by the statistical method, since type as it appears among 
 natural objects, including forms of plant and animal life, as it 
 appears in mental processes and in conduct, and as it appears in 
 the groupings and the collective activities of individuals socially 
 organized, can always be expressed in the statistical terms of 
 "frequency" and "mode." In other words, a type or norm can be 
 resolved into numerical elements. 
 
 The question may naturally and properly be raised, however, 
 whether numerical measures of social constraint would afford us 
 any knowledge that we could not more directly obtain by other 
 methods of inquiry. The corresponding question was raised 
 when statistical methods were introduced in biology and in psy- 
 chology. We may confidently anticipate that the conclusive 
 answer which trial and demonstration have afforded in those sci- 
 ences will be reached and accepted in sociology also. 
 
 A simple illustration may help to make the point clear. The 
 temperature of the human body in health fluctuates within narrow 
 limits about the normal of 98.5 Fahrenheit. Under the physio- 
 logical disturbance of disease or of shock, the range of variation 
 is greatly widened, and every one acquainted with modern medical 
 practice, in hospitals and elsewhere, knows how closely the tem- 
 perature curve is watched by nurses and physicians. In most 
 cases the fact of illness or of shock is known independently of 
 any scrutiny of the chart. But there are instances, sometimes 
 critical ones, in which the temperature fluctuation affords the first
 
 warning ; and in all cases it affords the warning that possesses the 
 qualities of exactness and degree, and upon precisely these quali- 
 ties the issues of life and death may turn. In other cases the 
 condition of the system is made known by a blood test that is 
 statistical in form, consisting in a count of corpuscles exhibiting 
 certain characteristics; in yet others by records of heart action 
 and of arterial resistance. 
 
 It is reasonable to suppose that the social constraint which in 
 any given community bears upon individuals and upon component 
 or constituent groups is, under ordinary conditions, of a degree 
 and an extent that may properly be described as normal, and 
 that any considerable fluctuation from normal, could we measure 
 it, would immediately make known to us the action of disturbing 
 forces. The value of such knowledge can hardly be overesti- 
 mated. The question, how much restraint, how much liberty, 
 how much conformity to type, how much variation from it, are 
 conducive to the general welfare, is the supremely important 
 question in all issues of public policy. The right answer to it 
 turns upon the determination of a previous question, namely, what 
 is normal social constraint in a given community, at a given 
 stage of its evolution, and what at a given moment is the actual 
 range of fluctuation? 
 
 To obtain, then, determinations of normal social constraint for 
 modern communities, including municipalities, commonwealths 
 and nations, and to perfect the methods of measuring fluctuations 
 must, I think, be regarded as an important object of sociological 
 effort in the immediate future. That the effort will be successful 
 is, I am convinced, a fairly safe prediction.
 
 CHAPTER XIII 
 
 SOCIAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 1 
 
 IT is an interesting circumstance that the makers of social 
 theory in all generations have aimed to be true counselors in the 
 sense contemplated by Demosthenes, who said that to censure "is 
 easy, and in the power of every man," but that the true counselor 
 "should point out conduct which the present exigence demands." 
 Like other men, they have reacted to the greater exigencies of 
 their day. With fellow citizens they have played their part in the 
 collective struggle for existence and advantage. By one sort of 
 thinking or another, their theories have been derived, at least 
 in part, from observations or reflections upon large issues of 
 public policy, and upon public policy they have left an impression 
 by no means insignificant. 
 
 If their counsel has been not always wise, not always salutary, 
 imperfect knowledge, more than any defect of patriotism, has 
 been at fault. Until social theory became sociology, it was highly 
 a priori and speculative. A conclusion much desired for fortify- 
 ing a policy predetermined, more often than not, was the actual 
 base of intellectual operations. Knowing what he ought to prove 
 for the glory and safety of the state, the pragmatic political philos- 
 opher discovered adequate premises for it as unerringly as any 
 soothsayer to Cyrus or Alexander found the right flock of birds 
 to deliver a prognosis of promise for expeditions then afoot. 
 
 It would be rash to assume that speculative methods have faded 
 with the nobler intellects that used them "into the infinite azure of 
 
 1 This chapter was written in 1910 and read as the president's address 
 at the annual meeting of the American Sociological Society at St. Louis 
 in December of that year. It was printed in the Proceedings of the 
 Society in 1911. Except for one transposition of sentences for form's 
 sake, the elision of a few redundant words, and the omission of nine 
 lines of reference to peace propaganda from Fox and Penn to Carnegie, 
 it is here reprinted without change. I take a frankly egotistical satisfac- 
 tion in having said these things before 1914 instead of after 1920. 
 
 209
 
 210 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 the past." In an age which is witnessing, in supposedly educated 
 circles, a revival of every cult of magic and demonism known 
 among men from Gadara to Salem, we cannot feel sure that any 
 absurdity or obsession may not again mask under the austere 
 name of "science." But for the time being, social theory of the 
 speculative sort is discredited. The name "sociology" was in- 
 vented and is used to lay stress upon inductive method. To find 
 the facts first, to sort and array them with discrimination, to 
 observe differences, resemblances, and dimensions closely, to gen- 
 eralize with caution, and only then to ask what suggestions, if any, 
 the approximations to truth so obtained offer us for guidance in 
 private and in public conduct, is the only reputable procedure 
 among students of social, as of physical, phenomena. 
 
 Of the founders of sociology it may be said that in a pre- 
 eminent degree their interest in practical affairs was deep and 
 continuous and directed upon the weightier matters of the law. 
 The "mint, anise, and cummin" of administrative reform they 
 did not despise, but, one and all, they entertained the high am- 
 bition to mould public policy. Comte wrote The Positive Philos- 
 ophy in part that he might fashion The Positive Polity. Spencer 
 never lost sight of his initial purpose to formulate the principles 
 of justice. Walter Bagehot, in whatever by-way of science or 
 criticism he wandered, did not forget that his self-appointed task 
 was to increase and heighten in the public life of his age that "ani- 
 mated moderation" which he held to be the unique excellence of 
 English character. 
 
 We cannot doubt that these men, like their forerunners, were 
 tempted to lay philosophical foundations in the old manner, for 
 preconceived political systems. That they never dallied with the 
 temptation need not be claimed. But to whatever extent they 
 yielded to it, they impaired the value of their total achievement. 
 Their fame rests upon so much of their accumulation and classifi- 
 cation of facts as was unprejudiced and so much of their general- 
 ization as was inductive in quality. If any one of the three did 
 not fully realize that his contribution to thought would be so 
 measured, he at least did not fail to shape his intellectual life by 
 scientific standards. In mature years each one frankly revised the 
 dogmatic political creed of his youth by the objective light of
 
 211 
 
 abundant knowledge. Comte began as the fervid disciple of the 
 social revolutionist Saint Simon. He became the prophet of a 
 progress as smoothly projected as a parabolic curve. Spencer's 
 hatred of aggression proclaimed in Letters on the Proper Sphere 
 of Government was formulated in his earliest book in the language 
 of finality. But, mellowed by his historical study of social evolu- 
 tion, the author of Social Statics arrived at an understanding of 
 the part that war has played in political integration, and a per- 
 ception that equal liberty cannot be established among men while 
 militarism survives. Bagehot, described by the friend of his 
 college days as an intellectually arrogant and supercilious youth, 
 became the scientific man of the world, the adviser of ministers 
 of state and the one psychologist who has succeeded in explain- 
 ing the mind of the average Englishman to the average English 
 mind. 
 
 To recall these origins of inductive social theory is to realize 
 that the work remembered was not only ground-clearing and 
 ground-breaking; it was also superlatively constructive. 
 
 Comte not only insisted that completeness of description is a 
 requisite of method, he also, making contribution, demonstrated 
 the successive mutations of the human mind. Going forth from 
 the barbaric feast of credulity, to be "long fed on boundless hope" 
 of metaphysic, the race of man must, in the end, content itself 
 with the "simpler fare" of verifiable knowledge. In that day 
 reason may qualify the passions which dogma has denounced and 
 damned, but never yet repressed. 
 
 Spencer's sociological theories were formulated as a part of 
 his evolutionist conception of the world. That conception has 
 become an integral part of the mental equipment of every edu- 
 cated man. Those writers who would convince us that Spencer is 
 forgotten are of all philosophers most miserable. They must 
 either avoid the post-Spencerian problems or think about them in 
 terms of Spencerian ideas. 
 
 As Comte taught students of social science to expend their 
 energies within confines of the knowable; as Spencer compelled 
 them to see every process as evolution or dissolution ; so Bagehot, 
 examining more closely than any predecessor had done the 
 strictly social phenomenon of a collective struggle for existence,
 
 212 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 demonstrated that fundamentally sociological explanation is 
 psychological interpretation. Bagehot, rather than Tarde, was 
 the true founder of the so-called psychological school. Physics 
 and Politics is one of those excessively rare books that the critic 
 who has a sense of moral responsibility may daringly call original. 
 As sociology, the chapters on the "Preliminary Age" and "Nation 
 Making" forestall Les Lois de limitation. As psychology, the 
 chapter on "The Uses of Conflict" more than foreshadows some 
 of the generalizations that we associate with the name of William 
 James. And he would be a remarkable writer indeed who, desir- 
 ing to set forth the social interplay of instinct, habit, and reason, 
 could put it all so luminously as Bagehot has put it in the chapter 
 on "Government by Discussion." 
 
 It is a fair presumption that work of such enduring influence 
 upon theory has not yet spent its practical power in suggestion. 
 It is reasonable to think that, were we now to re-examine it, we 
 might find it still an unexhausted fund of wisdom, as of correlated 
 knowledge. It may afford us guidance today, not less than it 
 did yesterday, for a rational criticism of public policy. To that 
 possibility, it may be well to give attention. 
 
 The problems of public policy do not become simpler with 
 advancing civilization. To speak for the moment of our own 
 nation, the questions that vex us are of bewildering variety and 
 complexity: questions of territorial expansion and of rule over 
 alien peoples; questions arising out of race conflict within our 
 older continental domain; questions of the restriction of immi- 
 gration, of the centralization or the distribution of administrative 
 authority, of the concentration or the diffusion of economic power. 
 Well may the skeptic ask if any science of human relations, how- 
 ever wide its generalizations, can offer even presumptive answers 
 to questions so far-reaching and so diverse. Yet every citizen, 
 whether he be instructed or ignorant, is expected to help answer 
 them. 
 
 Before we admit that the objection is fatal, let us remember 
 that an overshadowing question has still to be named, and that 
 when one question overshadows all others the relative values of 
 the others are determined. That question .is the world-old
 
 SOCIAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 213 
 
 query older than science, older than any record of history the 
 question, "Is it War or Peace?" 
 
 After ten thousand years of so-called progress, is reason still 
 so ineffective against instinct that only minor issues can be re- 
 moved from fields of battle to arenas of intellectual conflict? 
 Must sovereignty the ultimate social control forever prove and 
 declare itself in government by slaughter, or may international 
 relations also be brought under government by discussion? By 
 this "previous question" of world-politics every question of do- 
 mestic politics is qualified. With war a possibility, the restriction 
 of immigration is one problem ; with war made impossible it would 
 become an entirely different problem. A further democratizing 
 of the social order, which might be safe if world-peace were 
 assured, may be fraught with peril if the greater nations are 
 again to challenge one another's right to live. 
 
 These considerations might be dismissed as academic if it were 
 certain that war will indefinitely continue, or certain that it will 
 not. Happily we do not know that it will. Unhappily we do not 
 know that it will not. There are sincere and able men who doubt 
 if the cessation of war should be desired. They exalt its disci- 
 plinary value, believing that the world yet needs a measure of 
 sacrifice, of daring, of endurance and of superiority to material- 
 istic aims which only war can give. A larger number of men, 
 also sincere and able, reject every defense of war as invalid, but 
 are incredulous when ways and means of disarmament are pro- 
 posed. 
 
 It is upon these two interpellations, namely, the desirability of 
 world-peace and its possibility, that the verdict of sociology may 
 rightly be demanded and should carry weight. And as a sort of 
 preliminary report, the conclusions of Spencer and of Bagehot 
 assuredly deserve a profoundly respectful consideration. 
 
 As all students of Spencer know, his most important socio- 
 logical generalizations pertain to the characteristic differences 
 between what he calls the militant and the industrial types of 
 society. His theory of social causation is stated mainly in terms 
 of war-habit and peace-habit. And, like Mr. Carnegie, who was 
 his loyal friend, Mr. Spencer looked upon war as the most mon-
 
 2 14 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 strous of social ills, as the most formidable obstacle to the com- 
 plete evolution of man. Mr. Bagehot, on his part, believed that 
 in government by discussion we have an agency attained through 
 immeasurable effort and suffering for the inhibition of hasty 
 action, for the subordination of brutal passion to a reasonable 
 expediency, for the final settlement of disputes by reason instead 
 of by force. Surely, then, we should ask these scouts of inductive 
 social science whether in their opinion the cessation of war at 
 the present stage of social evolution is a thing to be desired, and, 
 if it is, by what policies the consummation may be attained. 
 
 Sentiment, doubtless, and the abhorrence of suffering move 
 most of those who are participating in peace efforts now. Mr. 
 Spencer shared these feelings, but he did not rest his case against 
 militarism upon sentiment alone. His faith was in the im- 
 provability of man, the final and superlative product of cosmic 
 evolution. He saw that improvement involves adaptation to con- 
 ditions on which life depends, and ever nicer adjustments of 
 differing interests. He believed that improvement consists in an 
 expanding sympathy of man for man, a continuing differentiation 
 of powers, a better and always better coordination of life-activi- 
 ties and therewith an ever-deepening joy of living. It has pro- 
 ceeded through a social process. In this process war has played 
 a great and recurring part. In breaking down the barriers that 
 separated primitive men, in bringing savage camps together into 
 tribes, in hammering tribes together into nations, war was inevi- 
 table and it was useful. Nevertheless, war achieves results 
 through frightful cost and waste. It is incompatible with those 
 more delicate processes of evolution which we associate, or should 
 associate, with high civilization. This is a point of such funda- 
 mental importance, and the Spencerian demonstration of it is so 
 complete and so irrefutable, that we may well linger for a mo- 
 ment to note wherein the demonstration consists. 
 
 Evolution is simple or compound. 
 
 Simple evolution is swift, direct and business-like. It occurs 
 whenever a group of units of any kind, from white-hot iron to 
 the professors of a faculty, discharge energy promptly and with- 
 out indirection. Let the heated iron be cooled with least possible 
 waste of time and in the most economical way. The molecules
 
 SOCIAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 215 
 
 will draw together. Integration, the initial process in evolution, 
 will quickly be completed. There will be no secondary, no inci- 
 dental changes. Close crystallization will uniformly characterize 
 the mass. There will be no differentiation. The product will be 
 a bar of iron contracted, instead of expanded ; nothing more. Let 
 professors attend strictly to the business of teaching, withholding 
 no energy that can freely be discharged upon the environing 
 student mind. Let there be no day-dreaming and no sauntering, 
 no dallying with research by the way, nor idle discussion of the 
 cosmic, or the social, order. As before, there will be integration. 
 The units of the mass will get together. There will be no disturb- 
 ing differences of opinion, no disquieting differentiations of apti- 
 tude or ability. The product will be a coherent, standardized, 
 teaching force, dependable to turn out standardized 'Masters of 
 Arts and intellectually pasteurized Doctors of Philosophy, at a 
 minimum unit cost. 
 
 Compound evolution is slow, tortuous, uncertain, halting, and 
 unbusiness-like to the last degree. Energy, instead of discharg- 
 ing itself in a straightforward way, goes maundering about in 
 crooked currents and incalculable eddies. Some Quixotic mind 
 imagines that it would be interesting to trifle with the cooling bar 
 of iron. He interferes with the simplicity of its habits, with the 
 honest promptitude of its crystallization, exposing it to charcoal 
 fumes, hammering it on an anvil, thrusting it now and again into 
 boiling oil, reheating it in his forge and hammering it some more. 
 Very slowly its molecules draw together. They arrange them- 
 selves in strange, fibrous shapes, no two alike. Infinitely minute 
 changes work their way upon and through that iron bar. It 
 integrates, but it also differentiates. It becomes tense, pliant, 
 elastic, vibrant. It sings, when you strike it, with a clear full 
 note, and the Quixotic workman, touching it lightly with one last 
 tap of his hammer, no longer calls it a bar of iron ; it has become 
 a Damascus blade. Quixotic faculties there have been, teaching 
 effectively but not too much ; not incoherent and not anarchistic, 
 though united by little else than a common interest in intellectual 
 pursuits and a kindly thoughtfulness of man for man. Their 
 energy has freely been given to their chief task, instruction; but 
 some of it, unguarded, has escaped into by-ways of science or
 
 216 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 creative thought. Exposed to the play of many forces, not always 
 equal or alike, members of such faculties have become different 
 from one another. They have become individuals, each with his 
 own view of life and its problems, each with his own distinctive 
 work and record of achievement. Some of them have become 
 absent-minded and detached, some absorbed in researches which 
 neither colleague nor intrusive tourist could fully comprehend. 
 This compound evolution of the loosely integrated faculty has, 
 therefore, been scandalously irregular, and costly withal. It has 
 made the business man thank God that he, at least, is not as these 
 professors are. And yet, because of it, and by means of it, and 
 chiefly through its very irregularity and freedom, have those dis- 
 coveries been made which have multiplied the business man's 
 thousands and millions into billions of ingots of good red gold. 
 Through and by means of it students have been tempered and 
 tested as well as taught, and sent forth into life to be leaders of 
 men. Above all, this idling compound evolution, seemingly so 
 loose and irresponsible, has sustained the pristine faith of man, 
 which happily shall live when every other faith is dead, the faith, 
 to wit, that the world is still "full of a number of things." 
 
 All this is but a way of saying that growth, and the art which 
 simulates growth, are not manufacture. Nature knows nothing 
 of standardization. Within some given range of variation she 
 creates types, that is to say, resemblances, but no two individuals 
 are precisely alike. But growth, with its possibilities of correlated 
 difference, of diversity in unity, requires freedom and takes time. 
 It can be hastened, but only with some sacrifice of results. Some 
 strength of fiber, some delicacy of adaptation, is missed. Has- 
 tened evolution is crude evolution. Massiveness of parts and 
 brutality of power may be attained, but not completeness of life. 
 
 Now of all ways of hastening social evolution, war is the most 
 obvious, the most effective, the most absolutely business-like. A 
 well-organized and well-drilled army is the best example of 
 standardization that we know. Conquest and a rigorous military 
 rule over conquered foes are the quickest way to integrate and 
 standardize vast populations. The product is a militaristic em- 
 pire. It is massive and imposing. It brings together the ma- 
 terials from which civilization may be evolved, but it is not itself
 
 SOCIAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 217 
 
 an example of compound evolution. The notion that war can 
 perfect the internal adaptations of national life, the finer adjust- 
 ments of sectional, racial, or class interests, has no historical 
 justification. Two concrete illustrations will suffice. 
 
 Writing of Bismarck's inflexible purpose to consolidate the 
 German empire, Emile Ollivier, minister to Napoleon III, says: 
 
 The cause of the Franco-German conflict was one of those artificial 
 fatalities born of false conceptions and the unwholesome ambitions of 
 statesmen, which time might wear out, transform, and often extinguish. 
 . . . But there existed a man to whom it imported much that this factitious 
 fatality should subsist, and should finally burst forth into war. It was 
 this puissant genius, unwilling to leave to time the glory of accomplishing 
 the task of unification, the triumph of which would have been inevitable, 
 who wished to make short work of evolution and impose upon the present 
 what the future would have freely established, and to keep for himself 
 the glory that his successors might have shared. 1 
 
 And M. Ollivier might have added that the ceaseless activities 
 of a generation of statesmen and writers had not sufficed to com- 
 plete in the hearts of the German people that unification by divine 
 right which was outwardly and politically established by Bis- 
 marck's crass attempt to hasten social evolution. 2 
 
 Can it be said that the attempts of our southern brethren to 
 solve by war, or of the federal government to solve by the essen- 
 tially militaristic policies of reconstruction, the terrible problem 
 of race interests were more successful? Can any sane man ex- 
 pect that the problem will ever be solved in any other way than 
 through the infinitely slow process of a social evolution so com- 
 plex as to baffle analysis ? 
 
 This, then, is the evolutionist's case against war. It can hasten 
 social integration, but in the measure that it succeeds, it prevents 
 or postpones those finer and endlessly varied adaptations which 
 require freedom and time, and upon which completeness of life 
 depends. War has rudely assembled the factors of civilization, 
 but the possible recurrence of war menaces civilization from this 
 time forth. 
 
 Can war then be outlawed and generally prevented? These 
 
 1 Philosophic d'une Guerre, pp. 342, 343. 
 
 1 Nor did the war of 1914 complete it, as swift-following revolution 
 proved.
 
 218 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 terms are used advisedly, because no wrong has ever been com- 
 pletely abolished by penalizing it, or by adopting resolutions to 
 discountenance it. We do not, however, on that account think it 
 useless to penalize or to resolve. 
 
 I suppose that there is substantial agreement among economists 
 and historians that the prevailing causes of war have been hunger 
 and greed. Primitive men, made desperate by impending famine, 
 have pushed into productive regions already occupied, there to 
 contend for a share of nature's bounty. Modern men do as savage 
 and barbarian did, but in ways so devious that the actual process 
 is rarely seen or understood. Whole peoples or nations no longer 
 move en masse, but, like the ancient Aryans at springtime, of 
 whom Festus, describing the ver sacrum, tells us, they mitigate the 
 bitter economic struggle by sending forth their youth and maid- 
 ens into distant parts. Nations that live, grow. They must work 
 more intensely, keying up the strings of life to higher pitch, or 
 they must expand. Either way, the struggle for existence within 
 nations becomes a struggle for advantage among nations. Emi- 
 grants from one may not be welcomed as immigrants by another. 
 Colonization is an intrusion of the strong upon the weak. An 
 acceleration of domestic industry is correlated with an expansion 
 of foreign trade. With colonies and profit by trade, greed enters, 
 adding its insatiable demands to those of primal human need. 
 
 These conditions create tension and provoke contention. They 
 do not, however, inevitably produce war. The sociologist may 
 go far with economist and historian in recognizing economic 
 causes in history, but he may not lose sight of other factors, 
 which it is peculiarly the province of his own science to analyze 
 and appraise. 
 
 These factors are psychological, and without their cooperation 
 war does not begin. The passions of men must be consolidated. 
 Consuming hatred or fierce exaltation must merge individual 
 wills in the collective fury of the psychologic crowd. Even then 
 war does not follow if the fury merely bursts. An explosion may 
 make hell writ small, and war is hell writ large, but there resem- 
 blance ends. An explosion in the open does no work, and war is 
 systematic work. To make war, the public fury must so far be 
 controlled that it can discharge itself only through the mechanism
 
 SOCIAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 219 
 
 of a military organization, in a series of regulated explosions, 
 directed upon a definite object, until its infernal task is done. 
 
 Failure to remember this incontrovertible fact has had unfor- 
 tunate consequences for historical theory and for political ethics. 
 How does the control of public wrath arise? In what does it 
 consist? Through what agents or agencies does it direct this 
 fearful power, dissipating it in peace, or aggregating it for war? 
 
 Answers to these questions I find in Bagehot's chapters on 
 "Nation Making," and it is at variance with those notions of the 
 insignificance of great men in history which, for twenty years or 
 more, have reigned unchallenged in the domain of historical 
 criticism. 
 
 A nation is more than a population. Millions of individuals, 
 differing one from another, compose it; yet, although not stand- 
 ardized, they are alike. In ways not easy to describe, Englishmen 
 are Englishmen and Frenchmen are Frenchmen. Their resem- 
 blances are not merely physical. Englishmen are blue-eyed and 
 dark-eyed, florid and brunette. Nor are they merely racial. The 
 Frenchman may be Picard or Gascon, Breton or Provengal. The 
 similarities that we note lie within a well-defined range of mental 
 facts. They are not phenomena of instinct, nor yet of reason. 
 If men were creatures of instinct only, that is, if all their activities 
 were narrowly determined by heredity and began at birth, there 
 would be no distinctions of nationality. Or, if we never saw 
 Englishmen or Frenchmen, nor heard them talk, and if we knew 
 them only by scientific writings, we could not easily tell them 
 apart. The resemblances that constitute national type or national 
 character are tricks of expression, ways of doing things, prefer- 
 ences and antipathies, criteria of taste, views of life and conduct. 
 They were not imparted at birth ; they have all been learned. 
 They cannot be discarded at will ; they are things of habit. 
 
 Now habits are acquired, we say, by doing things or thinking 
 things many times over. That is true, but it is not all. Most of 
 the repetitions that make up habit are imitations ; they are copies 
 of models or examples. Many of our elemental and most useful 
 habits are imitations of parents ; but plainly, if we imitated parents 
 only, there would be no national traits, and, in the strict sense of 
 the word, no nations. There would be only some millions of
 
 220 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 families, each abiding by its own mental and moral law. National 
 habits, and therefore national traits and character, are copies of 
 those relatively conspicuous models that are widely imitated, 
 irrespective of kinship; imitated locally at first, perhaps, but at 
 length throughout a population. 
 
 If so much be granted, a further and significant truth is granted 
 by implication. Conspicuous or dynamic men, who become models 
 to thousands or millions of their fellows, are true social causes, 
 and centers of social control. As they think, the multitude thinks ; 
 as they do, the multitude does, and for the most part uncon- 
 sciously, every man believing that he thinks or acts spontaneously, 
 and because it is his nature to think or to act so, and not otherwise. 
 
 Is not the conclusion obvious? Men in positions of authority, 
 whether, as they believe, by divine right, or, as others think, by 
 human choice, are necessarily conspicuous. Often they are men 
 of power, and whether they would have it so or not, their decisions 
 become to some extent the popular decision, and their voice be- 
 comes in part the people's voice. Without dictation or argument, 
 and solely because their choice is spontaneously copied and their 
 course of action is uncritically followed by multitudes that swear 
 the choice was theirs, these men control, and controlling, direct, 
 the public complaisance and the public wrath. In the final throw- 
 ing of the dice of fate, they are causes of peace and war. 
 
 From this sober conclusion of inductive science I see no escape. 
 That it is in harmony with an unsophisticated moral prejudice is 
 not, I wish to believe, a reason for distrusting it. The conscience 
 of civilized mankind has never yet admitted that deliberately de- 
 clared war has been irresponsibly begun. Rather has it held, that 
 great men in all ages, as moulders of opinion and ministers of 
 state, have been moral agents, rightly to be branded with infamy 
 when, for their own aggrandizement or glory, they have drawn 
 the sword. 
 
 One rule of policy then, it would seem, may fairly be derived 
 from sociological theory for the discouragement of war. It is 
 right and expedient to teach that exceptional men, and especially 
 all emperors and presidents and ministers of state, are not puppets 
 of the Zeitgeist, but, in a scientific sense of the word, are true
 
 SOCIAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 221 
 
 social causes, and, as such, are morally responsible for the main- 
 tenance of peace. 
 
 Beyond policies to restrain the makers of war, are there policies 
 which might render the making of war more difficult? 
 
 The conditions preventive or inhibitive of war have been three, 
 namely : isolation, the inclusion of minor states within confedera- 
 tions or imperial systems, and the so-called balance of power. 
 
 In the past mere inaccessibility of territory has assured the 
 relatively peaceful development of many peoples, among whom 
 some have made priceless contributions to civilization. There 
 are no inaccessible nations now. Political integration has con- 
 tinually widened the areas within which domestic peace prevails, 
 and the work is so far done that no important lands or peoples 
 remain to be appropriated. Further integration will be redistribu- 
 tive only. There remains the balance of power, as the one im- 
 portant objective condition upon which the maintenance of peace 
 will largely depend. 
 
 I am using the term in a general or descriptive, not a technical 
 or diplomatic, sense. I mean by it political forces in approximate 
 equilibrium throughout the world. In this sense the balance of 
 power is a sociological phenomenon of peculiar interest, for two 
 reasons. 
 
 First, it is interesting because of its nature or composition. 
 It is a distribution of forces roughly in accordance with what the 
 mathematician calls "chance occurrence." If as many as a thou- 
 sand shots are fired at a target, those that miss the bull's-eye are 
 distributed about it with curious regularity. Of those that miss 
 it by three inches, about as many will hit above as below, about as 
 many to the left as to the right. Of those that miss it by six 
 inches, about as many will hit right as left, about as many below 
 as above. In like manner a balance of power is a symmetrical 
 distribution of forces about a central point. An international 
 balance of power exists when, with reference to any interest or 
 question upon which states may differ, as many strong powers 
 range themselves on one side as on the other, and the weak ones 
 are symmetrically distributed with reference to the strong ones. 
 
 Does this bit of exposition seem too elementary or too academic 
 to bring into a discussion of world-peace ? Let me then ask if a
 
 222 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 corollary from the principle stated may be taken for granted? 
 The probability of a symmetrical distribution of shots or of forces 
 about a central point increases with their number. Fifty shots 
 about a bull's-eye would not be so regularly distributed as a thou- 
 sand. A million shots would make a nearly circular pattern. If, 
 then, an International Court of Arbitral Justice should be estab- 
 lished at The Hague, or elsewhere, would the chances that the 
 political forces represented there would remain in approximate 
 balance be increased, if, meanwhile, a number of the now inde- 
 pendent small states of Europe and the East should be absorbed 
 in one or more of the great imperial systems ? Or need we fear 
 that the chances of equilibrium would be diminished if one or 
 two of the more heterogeneous imperial systems should some day 
 be resolved into independent states, each relatively homogeneous 
 and individual? 
 
 The balance of power is of interest, secondly, because it is 
 correlated with government by discussion. Bagehot's chapter on 
 this subject deals chiefly with the nature of such government 
 and its consequences. Like compound evolution, government 
 by discussion is a slow, irregular, and unbusiness-like procedure : 
 and therein lies its value. It inhibits ill-considered action. It 
 gives passion time to cool, it makes for moderation and for 
 poise. Bagehot does, however, ask how government by discus- 
 sion arises. His answer is, on the whole, the least satisfactory 
 part of his book, but it is essentially correct. Government by 
 discussion arose, he says, in those nations that had a polity, that 
 is to say, a constitution. Greeks and Germans had what Aris- 
 totle calls the mixed government. King, aristocracy, and free- 
 men participated in it. Here, then, were distinct political forces 
 in balance, and because they were in balance they had to talk 
 before they could act. 
 
 Our modern account of reason and its relations to instinct 
 enables us to generalize Mr. Bagehot's guess and to verify it. 
 Government by discussion depends upon a balance of power and 
 necessarily proceeds from it. It is a social expansion of the 
 reasoning processes of the individual mind. 
 
 Reasoning begins when instinct fails or is inhibited. As long 
 as we can confidently act, we do not argue, but when we face
 
 SOCIAL THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 223 
 
 conditions abounding in uncertainty or when we are confronted 
 by alternative possibilities, we first hesitate, then feel our way, 
 then guess, and at length venture to reason. Reasoning, ac- 
 cordingly, is that action of the mind to which we resort when 
 the possibilities before us and about us are distributed substan- 
 tially according to the law of chance occurrence, or, as the mathe- 
 matician would say, in accordance with "the normal curve" of 
 random frequency. The moment the curve is obviously skewed, 
 we decide. If it is obviously skewed from the beginning, by bias, 
 or interest, by prejudice, authority, or coercion, our reasoning 
 is futile or imperfect. So, in the state, if any interest or coalition 
 of interests is dominant and can act promptly, it rules by ab- 
 solutist methods. Whether it is benevolent or cruel, it wastes 
 neither time nor resources upon government by discussion. But 
 if interests are innumerable, and so distributed as to offset 
 one another, and if no great bias or overweighting anywhere ap- 
 pears, government by discussion inevitably arises. The interests 
 can get together only if they talk. So, too, in international rela- 
 tions. If in coming years these shall be adjusted by reason instead 
 of by force, by arbitration instead of by war, it will be because 
 a true balance of power has been attained. If any one power or 
 coalition of powers shall be able to dictate, it will also rule. 
 By what policies can an equilibrium of international power 
 be established? I shall name only those that the foregoing con- 
 siderations suggest, and not attempt to describe or to analyze 
 them. They must of course be policies that will tend both to 
 differentiate interests and to disintegrate coalitions of power 
 that create an overwhelming preponderance of strength. The 
 great superiorities that now preclude effective government by 
 discussion throughout the world are, (i) technical proficiency 
 based on scientific knowledge, and (2) concentrated economic 
 power. If we sincerely wish for peace, we must be willing to 
 see a vast equalizing of industrial efficiency between the East 
 and the West. We must also welcome every change that tends 
 to bring about a fairer apportionment of natural resources among 
 nations and within them, and a more equal distribution of wealth. 
 If these conditions can be met, there may one day be a Parlia- 
 ment of Man.
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 
 
 THEOPHRASTUS SUCH was of the opinion that one teaches "a 
 blinding superstition" who teaches "that a theory of human well- 
 being can be constructed in disregard of the influences that have 
 made us human." Being of one mind with George Eliot's modern 
 ancient on this point, I have considered at length in these chap- 
 ters, the influences that have made us human. Incidentally, I have 
 been at pains to make clear what it is to be made human, discrim- 
 inating between heredity and heritage, and explaining how, when 
 mutation and selection have brought forth the reflective (or 
 reasoning) intelligence, experience instructs and disciplines it, and 
 equips it with culture. In particular, I have tried to prove that 
 to be made human is to be "individualized" until, attaining "per- 
 sonality," we become persons. Now I wish, and think it de- 
 sirable, to examine more closely certain conditions, named in 
 Chapter VII, which "practical" experimenters in social control 
 and in public policy ("uplifters" and professional reformers 
 above all) often neglect and sometimes openly contemn. 
 
 Of course the subject is not new. No humanistic problem is. 
 That is why I introduced it with my quotation from the modern 
 ancient. If inductive science has new truth to contribute to the 
 inherited stock of humanist wisdom, it is because we are in a posi- 
 tion to study more minutely than was possible in earlier days, the 
 forces and conditions that have made and formed us. We shall find 
 them to be not altogether different in kind from those that were 
 recognized by Plato, Aristotle, and Zeno. In fact, the Greek con- 
 ceptions were truer than some later ones. Most of the social 
 theories that have been constructed since the Protestant Ref- 
 ormation have dealt directly with the individual, and have at- 
 tempted to work from the individual to society. In this they have 
 been not altogether wrong. Centuries of suppression of in- 
 dividuality by Church and State had obscured one-half of po- 
 
 224
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 225 
 
 litical truth. Men needed to be reminded that the individual, 
 when he has come into existence, has a value in and for himself, 
 and must be counted as a force reacting on society. But as far 
 as theories have assumed the individual as an independent start- 
 ing-point of social and moral phenomena, they have been untrue. 
 
 The Greeks never failed to see that rational living is a product 
 of social conditions. To the Greek, says Butcher, " 'The man 
 versus the state' was a phrase unknown; the man was complete 
 in the state; apart from it he was not only incomplete, he had 
 no rational existence. Only through the social organism could 
 each part, by adaptation to the others, develop its inherent pow- 
 ers." 1 Nevertheless, this doctrine of the creation of man by 
 society was by no means completely thought out in the minds of 
 the writers who first formulated it, and those who last concerned 
 themselves about it left much to be added by the students of a later 
 time. Aristotle's comparative study of one hundred and fifty- 
 eight different communities, which enabled him first among 
 scientific investigators to show in detail how and why the good 
 life can have existence only in the organized state, was a theo- 
 retical no less than a practical advance beyond the speculative 
 insight of Plato. So, our modern study of social progress is 
 an advance, both theoretical and practical, beyond the work of 
 Plato and Aristotle, and beyond the philosophy of man as it 
 stood when post-Kantian idealism had achieved its task of re- 
 viving Hellenic moods of thought. 
 
 This assertion perhaps demands a word of explanation. They 
 misapprehend the work of science who think of it as incompatible 
 with philosophy, and suppose that one must choose between 
 them. It may be that inductive science can discover few great 
 truths of which at least glimmerings were not seen in Greece. 
 The doctrine of evolution is in that sense not new. But 
 the mission of science is a patient conversion of insight into 
 sight; of dialectic into knowledge. Our advantage is not in a 
 conviction more sure than Aristotle held, that he who can live 
 without society must be either a beast or a god ; it is in a minute 
 and relatively precise knowledge of those slow but certain proc- 
 esses of biological and social change by which the transformation 
 
 *Some Aspects of the Greek Genius, p. 51.
 
 226 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 of brutality into humanity is effected. And we cannot afford to 
 despise this better knowledge, as but a tedious elaboration of 
 ideas long since familiar and accepted. It is itself a new factor in 
 the social process. In the game of chess with the unseen an- 
 tagonist of Mr. Huxley's picture, it enables man to play with 
 the cool and calculating joy of one who knows the meaning and 
 the end of every move; knows, too, that on the other side the 
 play, though real and relentless, is fair. 
 
 Therefore, chief among the relations of cause and effect in 
 the process that has made us human, is one that brings together, 
 in a complete truth, the partial explanations that we owe to 
 Athens, with other explanations, no less partial, that have been 
 worked out in our own day. Mutations creative of intelligence 
 and character on the one hand, natural selection and social pres- 
 sure on the other, these influences together have created 
 human faculty. There came a time in the struggle for existence, 
 as Wallace and Darwin both saw, when mental resource counted 
 for more than physical strength. Anthropoid apes and simian 
 men, we have reason to suppose, found safety and advantage in 
 the pack that used wits. The intelligence that association from 
 the first selected and disciplined has never ceased to depend 
 on association for perpetuation. Deprived of comradeship by 
 circumstance or law, men go back to the brutality from which 
 they came. Wilfully rejecting companionship, they learn, with 
 Manfred, that man is not yet qualified to act the part of God : 
 
 . . . "There is an order 
 Of mortals on the earth, who do become 
 Old in their youth, and die ere middle age, 
 Without the violence of warlike death." 
 
 Therefore it has been the humans best equipped with social 
 habit and its products that have won and maintained supremacy 
 in the contention with physical nature and living enemies. So- 
 ciety is a means to a definite end, namely, the survival and 
 improvement of men through a continuing selection of intelligence 
 and sympathy. There can be no sociology worthy of the name 
 which is not essentially an elaboration of this central principle. The 
 notion that society is an end in itself is an unthinkable proposition. 
 At the same time, the intelligence and the fraternity that asso-
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 227 
 
 ciation selects react in their turn on society, making it better 
 as a working organization, and as a medium of individual life. 
 So the interpretation of man as "human," and the interpreta- 
 tion of society as an ever-changing plexus of relationships, must 
 proceed together. 
 
 It is not enough, however, to know with the philosophers of 
 Greece that without society and social duty there can be no true 
 individual life. They well understood the problems of social 
 order and the nature of personal worthiness. They knew that 
 excellence is a fact of organization : Plato's demonstration that 
 justice in the state and goodness in the individual life are neither 
 more nor less than the correlated play of mutually dependent 
 and mutually limiting activities, in proportions harmonious with 
 one another, and in subordination to the unity of the whole, has 
 not been surpassed, in ethical analysis. They were familiar, too, 
 with a thousand aspects of social and of individual change. But 
 they did not combine these elements into a synthetic conception. 
 They were unable to unite the static with the kinetic factors of 
 their problem, and so to arrive at the peculiarly modern notion 
 of a moving equilibrium. Therefore they failed to achieve an 
 entirely true and sufficient philosophy of either man or the state. 
 For life is not the whirl of a constant number of jugglers' plates, 
 balanced on the sword-points of the players : it is a whirl in 
 which new plates and new motions appear at every instant, com- 
 pelling delicate readjustments throughout the system, and yet 
 without seriously disturbing the approximately perfect balance 
 of the whole. The large and difficult conception, then, to which 
 we must attain is that of a world, in which there can be no true 
 humanistic phenomena except through a process, at once pro- 
 gressive and orderly, of mutual modifications and adaptations of 
 man and society by each other, in which each acquires, stage by 
 stage, a more delicate complexity of organization. Of the many 
 implications of this conception we shall now examine some of 
 the more important. 
 
 In philosophy of every school the term personality stands for 
 the highest product of evolution. True personality is a unified, 
 self-conscious mental life, harmonious within itself, capable of ex-
 
 228 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 pansion, and sympathetic with surrounding life because real- 
 izing and comprehending in itself the possibilities of life. It is 
 the type at once of the concrete and the universal. One who 
 understands this will not make the mistake of believing, on the 
 one hand, that utility is the fundamental word of ethics, or, on 
 the other hand, that ethics can be complete without including 
 utilitarianism. The fundamental words in ethics (there are two 
 of them) are integrity (unity, wholeness) and spontaneity. There 
 can be no utility apart from a consciousness capable of wants and 
 satisfactions, and apart from unity and aliveness there can 
 be no such consciousness. Therefore if integrity and alive- 
 ness come into direct conflict with utility it is utility that must 
 for the moment give way. Nevertheless, because there can be 
 no continuing life without reactions of utility, ethics must 
 expand into utilitarianism, and must work out the laws of a 
 cumulative happiness which is the reward and the confirmation 
 of well-doing. 
 
 If now we put this conception of personality side by side 
 with our view of intelligence as selected and disciplined under 
 social conditions, is it not evident that personality in this sense 
 comes into being only in the relatively advanced society, which 
 has passed beyond the limitations of tribal existence, and even 
 of a narrow nationalism, into a sympathetic relation to mankind 
 in all its varied phases of development? If so, it is a prod- 
 uct of progressive as distinguished from both stationary and 
 anarchistic, or disintegrating, society, and the theory of per- 
 sonality can be worked out only in terms of a theory of social 
 evolution. 
 
 In detail this means that a society in which the highest type 
 of mind can appear is one that has had, first, such a vigorous 
 ethnic or national existence, and second, such varied contact 
 with surrounding peoples, that it has become plastic without 
 losing its distinctive character. In the nomenclature of evo- 
 lution, it has acquired internal mobility without losing cohesion. 
 By mutation a variable but not unstable physical nature has 
 been produced. By numberless comparisons of one mode of 
 civilization with another, a mental temper at once critical and 
 catholic has been created. Prosperity and an increasing popula-
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 229 
 
 tion have brought the young and enterprising to the front in the 
 conduct of affairs. Selection has weeded out those who could 
 neither learn nor forget. Force and authority in the social organ- 
 ization have so far given way to spontaneous initiative that the 
 individual can find scope for the development of his latent pow- 
 ers, but not so far as to permit disintegration. Contact and 
 mental intercourse being the conditions of progress, its phases 
 are an increase of material well-being, an inclusive sympathy, 
 a catholic rationality, and a flexible social constitution, adapting 
 itself readily to changing conditions, yet of enduring strength. 
 And since the conservation of energy is a fact of social as of 
 physical phenomena, the cause of progress, beneath all conditions 
 and phases, is a conversion of lower that is, more simple, imper- 
 fectly organized modes of energy into higher. Economic ac- 
 tivities transform the energies of physical nature into social en- 
 ergies, of which there is no other source, since artistic, religious, 
 educational, and political activities are but a further transforma- 
 tion of the results of economic effort. In the medium of all these 
 activities is moulded their final product, the human person, who 
 could come into being in no other way and under no other circum- 
 stances. 
 
 Such are a few of the sociological facts that underlie human- 
 istic problems. It is interesting to reflect that in a vague way the 
 big truth which they contain, that without social progress there 
 can be no development of man has always been present in popular 
 consciousness. The experiences of individual life, of course, 
 afford a basis for it, since the years from childhood to maturity 
 are normally a period of increasing personal power, in which 
 every ambitious man believes that he was born to accomplish 
 a desirable transformation of the community. But social ex- 
 periences in the mass have built the superstructure. Faith in 
 ongoing and in a better state of things has been an element in 
 every religious belief. 
 
 What has been the genesis of the conviction? Everywhere 
 social advance has been brought about through successive waves 
 of conquest. Naturally enough, in the minds of the conquerors 
 the good or the right order has been identified with the new 
 order of things which they have undertaken to establish. The
 
 23 o STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 evil order has been the old way of life that was followed by the 
 subjugated enemies who are now reduced to serfdom. Good 
 spirits are those who favor the plans of the enterprising and 
 successful, in whose control are the shaping of public policy and 
 the dictation of orthodox belief. It is true that orthodoxy is 
 no sooner born than it turns conservative and seeks to main- 
 tain itself against further change. But the effort is vain. An- 
 other conquest, or a new generation, brings forward new men 
 and new issues, and a new orthodoxy always stands ready to 
 crowd the old to the wall. The conquered and oppressed also, 
 on their part, have a doctrine of progress. It is belief in a 
 future in which justice shall be done; when they shall be de- 
 livered from their captivity and in their turn put their enemies 
 under foot. In time a closer intercourse and a finer feeling soften 
 and blend these conflicting faiths into a belief in the ultimate 
 happiness and perfection of all classes. 
 
 Crude and even visionary as it may be, perennial faith in 
 progress is humanistic motive power. Science must rectify it 
 at a thousand points, but the first word of a scientific humanism 
 must be an unequivocal declaration that such faith in se is the be- 
 ginning of achievement. The first law of life is a law of motion. 
 In society, as on the street, the preliminary duty is to "move on." 
 The nation that has no further reconstructions to effect, no new 
 ideals to realize in practice, has completed its work and will 
 disappear before the warfare or the migrations of more earnest 
 men. But the moving on must be developmental ; mere change 
 is not evolution, but confusion ; and the nature and limitations of 
 an evolutionary process, imperfectly recognized as yet in scientific 
 discussion, are practically unknown to popular thought. It is 
 here, then, that the rectifying work of science must begin. 
 
 Human society is not a something-for-nothing endowment 
 order. The vision of a completed society, lacking neither material 
 comfort nor any excellence, in which foolishness, want, and suf- 
 fering could linger only as dim memories of an imperfect past, has 
 had a strangely persistent fascination for speculative minds in 
 every age. Common sense has never accepted the dream for 
 reality; for common sense is a skeptic from the beginning. 
 Philosophy has doubted if evil be not inherent in the nature of
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 231 
 
 the world, and therefore ineradicable. But doubt and skep- 
 ticism have fallen short of reasoned demonstration from experi- 
 ence that the vision is inherently absurd. Yet the elements of 
 demonstration are simple enough. The available energy of so- 
 ciety at any given moment is limited in amount. The total can 
 be increased only by parting with some, in the thought and labor 
 by which larger stores of physical energy, contained in the natural 
 resources of the environment, are set free and converted to human 
 use. All progress, therefore, is conditioned by cost, and if the law 
 of conservation holds good in these matters, as we have assumed 
 that it does, the cost will increase with the progress; not, how- 
 ever, necessarily in the same ratio as the gain, since riper knowl- 
 edge should enable us to get more from physical nature with 
 a given expenditure of human effort. In this simple form the 
 limitations of progress present an economic problem, and need 
 not detain us at the present time. However, inasmuch as society 
 is organic and behavioristic the cost of progress takes on com- 
 plications, out of which grow practical problems that are both 
 grave and difficult. As appeared in the illustration of the moving 
 equilibrium, society, as an aggregate that is simultaneously los- 
 ing and absorbing motion, experiences an incessant rearrange- 
 ment of its parts. This means two very important things: 
 First, there can be no social gain that does not entail some- 
 where, on the whole community or on a class, the break-up of 
 long-established relations, interests, and occupations, and the neces- 
 sity of a more or less difficult readjustment. Second, the in- 
 crease of social activity, which is the only phase of progress 
 that most people ever see at all, may so exceed the rate of con- 
 structive readjustment that the end is disorganization and ruin. 
 For the further examination of these propositions let us 
 translate them from physical terms into the language of feel- 
 ing. The destruction of familiar relations and the necessity of 
 establishing new ones are known immediately in consciousness 
 in terms of hardship or suffering; and disorganization of social 
 or individual life involves the pain of retrogression. The limita- 
 tions of progress, then, are these r First, there can be no social 
 progress, and therefore no development of personality, except 
 at the price of an absolute, but not necessarily a relative, in-
 
 232 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 crease of suffering. Second, if the increase of social activity, 
 which is one phase of progress, becomes disproportionate to the 
 constructive reorganization of social relationships, which is the 
 complementary phase, the increase of suffering will become degen- 
 eration. 
 
 These limitations are not a cheering aspect of progress, but their 
 reality is established in historical and in statistical fact, and they 
 sharply define our obligations. The first of these sobering propo- 
 sitions has to be made a shade darker still. The suffering that 
 progress costs is borne for the most part vicariously. The classes 
 that are displaced, whose interests and occupations are broken up 
 by the relentless course of change, are not the ones who secure 
 the joys of richer and ampler life. That which enormously 
 benefits mankind is too often the irretrievable ruin of the few. 
 For illustration, one need not be confined to the familiar facts of 
 the wasting of barbarian peoples before the advance of civiliza- 
 tion, or the sacrifice of life in national self-defence. The history 
 of industrial advance affords examples quite as striking, and more 
 significant, since they show that after society has settled down to 
 the quiet occupations of peace the fundamental conditions of its 
 development remain unchanged. In reviewing them the sociolo- 
 gist expects to find that the minority which suffers the pains of 
 progress is composed mainly of the most unprogressive elements 
 of the population, and he is not disappointed. But he finds evi- 
 dences also that to some extent the sufferers are recruited by 
 victims of pure misfortune, whose undoing has been caused 
 neither by their nature nor by their conduct. 
 
 When in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries the growth 
 of towns, money payments, and the commutation of week work 
 loosened the bonds of custom and law that had held the serf to the 
 manor, the entire commonwealth of England experienced an eco- 
 nomic prosperity never before known. Population and wealth 
 increased, and the free tenants, as a class, rose steadily in social 
 position. They could cultivate more or less land, or engage in 
 trade and obtain municipal charters. But the economic equality 
 of an earlier day had disappeared. The growth of population 
 brought men into the world for whom there were places enough, 
 and more than enough, but not places already allotted to them in
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 233 
 
 the social order. They were places that had to be discovered by 
 intelligence and enterprise, qualities that are not possessed by all 
 men equally. The full virgate of land was no longer secured by 
 customary law to each family. Since the energetic and strong 
 could control more, the easy-going and weak had to get on with 
 less. In the towns the far-seeing and forehanded quickly monop- 
 olized trade and the more profitable crafts. And so, while this 
 comparative freedom of enterprise stimulated activity in a hun- 
 dred ways that made England as a nation richer and stronger, it 
 destroyed the old economic footing of the less competent members 
 of society, and left them to struggle on, thenceforth, as a wage- 
 earning class. 
 
 Two hundred years later, in the sixteenth century, society was 
 again transformed by the results of geographical discovery. Free 
 capital and foreign commerce quickened industry and thought into 
 intense and brilliant life. "It was indeed a stirring time," writes 
 Hyndman, obliged to admit that this period, which he calls the 
 iron age of the peasantry and wage classes, was, nevertheless, one 
 of progress in other respects. "A new world was being discov- 
 ered in art and in science in Europe as well as in actual existence 
 on the other side of the Atlantic. . . . Never before had so great 
 an impulse been given to human enterprise and human imagina- 
 tion." 1 But the splendor had its price, which socialists like Hynd- 
 man have superficially described and but imperfectly understood. 
 
 Political integration had been going on. The struggle of con- 
 tending factions had been costly, and the reestablished national 
 life, with its manifold activities, was more costly. Barons dis- 
 charged the bands of retainers that were no longer needed in civil 
 strife. To better their fortunes the great lords enclosed common 
 lands that had been used freely by the yeomanry, and began evict- 
 ing tenants to convert agricultural lands into the sheep pastures 
 that required little labor and returned a quick money income from 
 sales of wool in Flanders. The misery of the people so displaced 
 and forced into wage labor or vagabondage cannot be attributed 
 to any actual lack of land or of industrial opportunity. There 
 remained land enough and to spare, notwithstanding enclosures 
 and evictions, if it had been well used ; while the development of 
 
 1 Historical Basis of Socialism in England, p. 23.
 
 234 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 manufactures and commerce had only begun. If they had pos- 
 sessed the knowledge and the will to cultivate arable land more 
 intensively, they could not have been driven from the soil ; if there 
 had been a free mobility of labor, they could have found employ- 
 ment quickly in the best instead of tardily in the worst markets, 
 as too often happened; if the organizing ability of employers 
 had been greater, the best markets would more quickly have found 
 them. But the value of land had become too great for their 
 wasteful methods; they had to change or go. That knowledge 
 might increase, that freedom to come and go might be established, 
 that the organization of enterprise might be perfected it was nec- 
 essary that these economic and social changes which accomplished 
 so much ruin should occur. Consequently, if the world was to 
 become a larger and a better place for the alert, on-moving many, 
 the sacrifice of the sluggish had to be. 
 
 The industrial revolution at the close of the eighteenth century 
 again occasioned displacements of labor that bore more distinctly 
 the character of misfortune to those who were injured by them. 
 No degree of skill, enterprise, or assiduity could have enabled the 
 handicraftsmen to hold their own in competition with power- 
 machinery and the steam-engine. They could do nothing but 
 leave their shops to wind and weather, and begin life over, on 
 new terms, in factory towns. How many thousands of them 
 never fully reestablished themselves, how many succumbed to 
 illness or even to actual starvation before economic reorganiza- 
 tion was completed, the reports of parliamentary inquiries bear 
 witness. Yet an unprecedented increase of population was proof 
 that, on the whole, the masses of the people had never been so 
 prosperous. Before 1751 the largest decennial increase had been 
 three per cent. ; before 1781 it did not exceed six per cent. Then, 
 all at once, it rose, decade by decade, to nine, eleven, fourteen, and 
 finally, between 1811 and 1821, to eighteen per cent. In our own 
 time the displacement of manual labor by machinery continues, and 
 possibly less than in any previous period is the suffering visited 
 on the least valuable portion of the population, since not infre- 
 quently it is men of a higher standard of life who are forced 
 out by the competition of a lower type. Nevertheless, so large
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 235 
 
 has been the net gain from improved methods of production that 
 the consequences of displacement are less serious than they were 
 a century ago. The chance of finding reemployment quickly is, 
 for competent men, greater than in former times, and the period 
 of search is made endurable by accumulated savings and varied 
 forms of aid. All in all, industrial history discloses a progressive 
 diminution of the proportion of inevitable suffering mixed with 
 the gains of progress; but the absolute increase remains. The 
 personnel of the displaced class changes more rapidly than in 
 earlier times, but the class, as a class, is renewed. As a class, it 
 cannot disappear as long as progress continues. 
 
 Such, in its simplest statement, is the law of the cost of 
 progress. "He that increaseth knowledge increaseth sorrow." 
 Whatever augments well-being destroys some livelihood. As 
 an abstract proposition, no well-informed student of social 
 phenomena would call this truth in question. But, unfortu- 
 nately, the law-makers, the social reformers, and the moralists 
 have not bound it upon their fingers nor written it upon the 
 tables of their hearts. They legislate, reform, and advise, for- 
 getful that their wisest endeavors can be at the best only "some- 
 thing between a hindrance and a help"; and the world goes on, 
 therefore, not only deceiving itself with dreams, but wasting its 
 resources on impossible undertakings. 
 
 For this principle is one that would make the instant quietus 
 of many vain questionings if it were an ever-present element in 
 our thinking. The poor have always been with us. 'Must they 
 be with us always? Or may we hope that economic prosperity 
 and social justice will one day mete out comfort, if not abundance, 
 to all? 
 
 Not unless we can attain "finality in a world of change." Not 
 unless there is a definite limit to the humanistic progress of the 
 race; for the conditions that would eliminate poverty from the 
 earth would terminate the life that is more than meat, in society 
 first, and afterwards in individuals. Unless all men could be 
 made equally prudent, equally judicious, neither an increase of 
 wealth nor changes in its distribution could prevent the occasional 
 sweeping away of possessions by the social rearrangements that
 
 236 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 progress demands. The relative dimensions of poverty will con- 
 tract and its misery will be alleviated, but there is no reason to 
 believe that it will ever wholly disappear. 
 
 Will multitudes of human beings remain always in practical 
 subjection to individual or corporate masters? Can we not abol- 
 ish economic slavery as we have abolished legal bondage? 
 Aristotle's argument that slavery inheres in civilization has 
 shocked the sensitive and amused the shallow, while both have 
 quoted it to show what foolishness a philosopher can teach. But 
 to the wise it will ever remain a profound though mournful truth. 
 Essential slavery has aptly been described as the estate of a man 
 who "can't get any freedom." We have changed the legal con- 
 ditions under which millions of men and women perform ill- 
 requited tasks of daily toil. To some extent we have diminished 
 the total magnitude of their misery, if not in every individual case 
 its extreme intensity. But we have not enabled them to get actual 
 freedom. We have made it unlawful to buy and sell their per- 
 sons. The master can no longer obtain control of the laborer's 
 time and strength, and therefore of his freedom, from any legal 
 principal but the laborer himself. The laborer cannot sell his own 
 freedom in perpetuity. But he can sell any portion of it, or all of 
 it subdivided into portions, for a limited period of time, or for 
 his whole life subdivided into periods. Practically, therefore, any 
 man or woman may sell his or her entire freedom for life, and 
 practically thousands of both men and women are compelled by 
 hunger to make the sale on terms that are personally degrading. 
 Yet that interpretation of this melancholy fact which attributes it 
 to the wickedness and greed of a capital-owning class is a tissue 
 of economic and sociological fallacies. Another interpretation, 
 which explains it as unavoidable misfortune, becomes a perversion 
 of history when, in the desire to prove that the world has grown 
 better, it assumes that ancient legal slavery was a consciously- 
 devised oppression. Neither oppression nor greed has been at 
 any time the first cause of legal bondage or of economic depend- 
 ence. Both are secondary causes, induced by experiences with a 
 slavery already existent. 
 
 Modern civilization does not require, it does not even need, 
 the drudgery of needle-women or the crushing toil of men in a
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 237 
 
 score of life-destroying occupations. If these wretched beings 
 should drop out of existence and no others stood ready to fill 
 their places, the economic activities of the world would not greatly 
 suffer. A thousand devices latent in inventive brains would 
 quickly make good any momentary loss. The true view of the 
 facts is that these people continue to exist after the kinds of work 
 that they know how to perform have ceased to be of any consid- 
 erable value to society. Society continues to employ them for a 
 remuneration not exceeding the cost of getting the work done in 
 some other and perhaps better way. This economic law has been 
 too much neglected in scientific discussion. It should be repeated 
 and illustrated at every opportunity. Incessantly we are told that 
 unskilled labor creates the wealth of the world. It would be 
 nearer the truth to say that large classes of unskilled labor do not 
 create their own subsistence. The laborers that have no adaptive- 
 ness, that bring no new ideas to their work, that have no suspicion 
 of the next best thing to turn to in an emergency, might better be 
 identified with the dependent classes than with the wealth- 
 creators. 
 
 The same economic law offers the true interpretation of ancient 
 slavery. In strictness civilization did not rest on slavery. It 
 was not in any true sense maintained by slavery. The conditions 
 that created the civilization created economic dependence, and 
 they are working in the same way, with similar results, now. 
 Ancient civilization accepted the dependence and utilized it in the 
 crude form of slavery. Modern civilization accepts and utilizes 
 it in the slightly more refined form of the wage system. 
 
 Certain great social tasks of creative organization have always 
 confronted our race. The enforced effort to achieve them has 
 been history's great competitive examination. The slaves and 
 serfs have been those who have failed. The first great necessity 
 was social unity, the power to act together in a disciplined 
 way, and the first slaves were those who could not create a 
 sufficiently coherent social organization to sustain a growing civil- 
 ization. They had to make way before others who were equal to 
 that achievement, and they became slaves not solely nor chiefly 
 because of a conqueror's tyranny, but primarily because slavery 
 or serfdom was practically the only economic disposition that
 
 238 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 could be made of them. Now that social unity has been in good 
 measure established, and the world has entered on yet larger un- 
 dertakings, the condition of freedom is the ability to devise new 
 things, to create new opportunities, to make not only two blades 
 of grass grow where one grew before, but to make a hundred 
 kinds of grass grow where before grew none at all. Accordingly, 
 the practically unfree task-workers of this time are those who, 
 unaided, can accomplish none of these new things. They are 
 those who might do well in old familiar ways, but who have noth- 
 ing to turn to when their ways cease to be of value to the world. 
 To live they must force depreciated services upon society on any 
 terms that society can continue to allow. They are unfree task- 
 workers not because society chooses to oppress them, but because 
 society has not yet devised or stumbled upon any other dispo- 
 sition to make of them. Civilization, therefore, is not cruel. 
 Rather it is supporting and trying to utilize the wrecks and fail~ 
 ures of its own imperfect past. 
 
 But it may be said: All these negative conclusions are based 
 on the assumption that the regime of individualism is to con- 
 tinue. Might not redemption from poverty and dependence be 
 possible under the reign of a beneficent socialism ? 
 
 Two systems of socialism have been proposed, if we classify 
 them according to plans of organization, and two if we classify 
 with reference to a proposed division of wealth. According to 
 one plan industrial administration would be centralized ; accord- 
 ing to the other it would be decentralized. Either of these 
 systems might be communistic, incomes being made equal through- 
 out society, or either might be non-communistic, the services of 
 different men being valued unequally. 
 
 Decentralized socialism would merely substitute competing com- 
 munities for competing private organizations. It would follow 
 that some communities would prosper more than others, and that 
 some, therefore, would presently come under subjection to the 
 others. A centralized socialism would probably attempt to estab- 
 lish a rigid and final system of occupations, in the hope of pre- 
 venting industrial derangements. If successful, the attempt 
 would make an end of progress. If no such attempt were made, 
 men would be thrown, as now, from time to time, out of that ideal
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 239 
 
 arrangement in which each did the work to which he was best 
 adapted, and therefore, if rewarded in proportion to their services, 
 the unfortunates would receive, as now, only the pittance that 
 would no more than support life. The one difference would be 
 that society in its corporate capacity would assume the responsi- 
 bility of finding new work for them ; but, rewarding them accord- 
 ing to performance only, it would practically have them in sub- 
 jection. They would only have exchanged masters, and slavery 
 to individuals for slavery to society. 
 
 If, vainly hoping to escape from this dilemma, society should 
 not only assume the responsibility of finding new opportunities 
 for the displaced, but should undertake to compensate them for 
 the buffetings and losses that they had suffered by reason of indus- 
 trial changes, and regardless of their resulting worth to the com- 
 monwealth, it would transform the character of its socialism. 
 Rewarding no longer according to service, the socialism would 
 become communism. Men of unequal power to work and to use, 
 of widely varying capacities to enjoy, would share alike the com- 
 mon product of their labor. Only one result could follow. Men 
 of animal natures, having as large incomes as men of a higher 
 development, would spend a disproportionate share of it on the 
 grosser sorts of gratification. Materialism of life, with its debase- 
 ment, would be the unprofitable substitute for economic hardship. 
 Income cannot be greatly disproportionate to the social value of 
 work, talents, culture, and virtues, without degrading the man. 
 If it be said that many men whose whole social value is of the 
 slightest do have, in fact, fabulous incomes, which socialism would 
 diminish, the reply is that there are not, accurately speaking, many 
 such men, and that there would be no apparent advantage in sub- 
 stituting a systematic breeding of dull sensualists for the sporadic 
 genesis of more brilliant 'debauchees. 
 
 Shall we then conclude that an unrestrained individualism, 
 working out social changes that seem advantageous to their pro- 
 moters, can achieve limitless progress, and that only harm could 
 come from any checking of the rate or intensity of its activity? 
 Shall we assume that the inevitable costs of progress in economic 
 loss and human suffering must be uncomplainingly borne by those 
 on whom they fall, because all private reforms are Utopian, and
 
 240 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 all public regulation of industry or assumption of its losses in 
 accordance with any form of socialism or communism would 
 be worse than folly? Must we acknowledge that society has no 
 responsibility for the consequences of the processes and changes 
 by which its own well-being is maintained? Shall we give our- 
 selves over to the belief that laissez faire is the last word of social 
 science and the first law of ethics? 
 
 Nothing in the conditions of progress set forth in the foregoing 
 study hints at other than negative answers to these questions. 
 On the contrary, if the law of evolution exemplified in human 
 society has rightly been understood, we are prepared to find cer- 
 tain real limitations of the number and extent of the social, polit- 
 ical, or industrial metamorphoses which, within a given period, can 
 combine in genuine progress. We may expect to discover a grow- 
 ing necessity for integral social action. We may expect to hear 
 the conscience of trie race declaring that society is responsible 
 for the costs of its existence. 
 
 In dynamic phenomena of every kind results are a function, as 
 the mathematicians express it, of time. With a given amount of 
 energy we can go in an hour or a day a given distance. Pro- 
 long the time, and we can increase the distance. In the incon- 
 ceivably complicated dynamic phenomena of life, growth, organ- 
 ization, development, are functions of time. If we force the rate 
 of transformation, we prevent the establishment of relations of 
 integration, differentiation, or segregation, necessary to complete 
 organization. And if organization is incomplete there is a limit 
 to the life-possibilities of the organism. It can perform less and 
 enjoy less while it lives, and its dissolution will begin earlier. 
 Society on a great scale, as the individual life on a smaller scale, 
 exemplifies these laws. If social evolution is to continue, and 
 the life of man is to become larger, and. richer with increasing 
 happiness, social organization in the future will be not simpler 
 than it is now, but more complex. In its larger being, individual- 
 ism, socialism, and communism may not be the mutually exclu- 
 sive things that they now seem to be. There may be not a nar- 
 rower but a wider field for individual effort, not less but more 
 personal liberty. At the same time, more enterprises may be 
 brought under public control, and more of the good things of life
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 241 
 
 may be distributed, like the sunshine and the air, in free and 
 equal portions. The displaced men and women may be more 
 quickly reestablished than now, their services be made of greatef 
 value, and society may assume a larger portion of the burden 
 of their misfortunes. All these possibilities are implications of 
 the second of the limitations of progress to which attention has 
 been called, namely, that if the increase of social activity be- 
 comes disproportionate to the constructive reorganization of social 
 relationships, the increase of suffering will become degeneration. 
 A few of the facts in evidence may be noted. 
 
 Dazzled by the results of material progress already achieved, 
 men throw themselves into the enterprises of modern life with 
 the zest of an ambition that knows no bounds. The rate of in- 
 dustrial, professional, political, and intellectual activity becomes 
 proportionate to the swiftness of electricity and steam. The 
 struggle for success causes demographic changes which pro- 
 foundly modify the social conditions of existence. 
 
 One of these is a phenomenal increase of population following 
 upon an enormous production of wealth. We have already seen 
 how improved industrial conditions in England, in the first part 
 of this century, were followed by an unprecedented increase of 
 population. The expansion of the population of the United States 
 from 3,929,214 in 1790 to 62,622,250 in 1890, while the popula- 
 tion of Europe, in spite of enormous emigration, rapidly multi- 
 plied, was a phenomenon that Longstaff accurately described as 
 unique in history. 1 
 
 A second change is a rapid concentration of increasing popula- 
 tion in large cities, where the great prizes of worldly success are 
 striven for and won. More than one-half of the population of the 
 United States is now urban. Humanity is flowing into cities 
 faster than the reorganization of the manifold phases of town life, 
 including municipal government, is achieved. There is a contin- 
 uing drain upon the vitality of the country to meet the destruction 
 of vitality in the towns, which makes the depopulation of rural 
 sections a grave matter for the future of civilization. "By a curious 
 perversion," says Longstaff, "the advantage of towns is said to 
 be 'life.' There is in truth more life in a given space, more high 
 
 1 Studies in Statistics, pp. 54-55.
 
 242 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 pressure, more rush ; but it is the rush of a clock running down." * 
 A displacement, in many industries, of men of a relatively high 
 standard of life by cheaper men of a lower standard, more rapidly 
 than the better men can find places in industries requiring rela- 
 tively intelligent labor, is a third demographic consequence of 
 intense activity. The normal displacement, as has been shown, is 
 of the dull, mechanical, non-adaptable man by a more versatile 
 competitor. But industries are not all of the same character. 
 Some are more progressive in their methods than others because 
 they contribute to the satisfaction of growing wants, which cre- 
 ate a varying demand, while others minister to wants that are 
 relatively stationary. In some industries, therefore, the high- 
 priced man is the cheap man ; in others the low-priced man is the 
 cheaper man. Economists who have contended that high wages 
 mean a low cost of labor, and those who have affirmed the con- 
 trary, are alike half right and half wrong. They have been ob- 
 serving different classes of industries. Under a uniform, self- 
 regulating circulation of labor, the versatile man, of the high 
 standard of life, would displace the cheaper man in one class of 
 industries, and the duller, cheaper man would displace higher- 
 priced labor in the other class. Under normal progress the major 
 displacement would be of inferior by superior men. But unless 
 economic evolution, creating new wants and varying demands, and 
 reorganizing industry to supply them, is going on more rapidly 
 than the growth of social unrest, or of those political policies that 
 so often force hordes of destitute people into migrations that 
 have no definite destination, there may be a cruel and ruinous 
 substitution of the lower for the higher grade of workman, pre- 
 maturely and far beyond normal limits. 
 
 Under these circumstances the struggle for success piles up in 
 the community much wreckage of degeneration. Every statisti- 
 cian has been struck with the seemingly anomalous fact that 
 suicide, insanity, crime, vagabondage, increase with wealth, edu- 
 cation, and refinement ; that, as Morselli says, 2 they are phenomena 
 of civilization. But the fact is not altogether anomalous after 
 all. These things are a part of the cost of progress, forms that 
 
 1 Longstaff, Ibid., p. 35. 
 'Suicide, p. 16.
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 243 
 
 the cost of progress takes when the rate of social activity exceeds 
 the rate of constructive reorganization. Quicken the pace of a 
 moving army, and the number of the unfortunates who will fall 
 exhausted by the way will be increased disproportionately. Besides 
 quickening the pace let discipline lapse and organization break 
 up, and the number of stragglers will be more than doubled. In- 
 crease the strain of any kind of competitive work and derange the 
 conditions under which it is done, and the percentage of failures 
 will rise. 
 
 Practical solution of the problems of responsibility and policy 
 that are presented by the conditions and tendencies which we have 
 looked at depends on a difficult combination of two very difficult 
 things. The first is to convince one set of men and women that 
 society ought to assume the costs of its progress, and, as far as 
 possible, take openly the responsibility for replacing the displaced. 
 This is the element of truth in socialism. We have made progress 
 in this direction. Practicality and theoretically society admitted 
 the obligation when, in the reigns of the Tudors, it began to 
 supplement private and ecclesiastical charity by systems of public 
 relief. In a hundred forms of legislation and administration, in 
 public education, in the multiplication of asylums and hospitals, 
 in a thousand modes of private beneficence, the duty is being more 
 adequately discharged by each later generation. But we are yet 
 far from comprehending its full extent. We realize but faintly 
 how far the incompetent and impoverished have been made so 
 by social movements that have cut them off from possibility of 
 personal improvement. A second difficulty is to convince another 
 set of men and women of the fallacy of a cardinal socialistic no- 
 tion, namely, that industrial derangements can be prevented in 
 a progressive world ; to convince them, therefore, that at all times 
 a portion of mankind must be relatively useless to the community, 
 and, for that reason, relatively poor ; and that their greatest pos- 
 sible utilization and compensation depend on their being held for 
 the while in practical subjection to other individuals or to the 
 commonwealth. 
 
 Sooner or later there will have to be a courageous facing of the 
 fact that one portion of every community is inherently progressive, 
 resourceful, creative, capable of self-mastery and self-direction,
 
 244 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 while another portion, capable of none of these things, can be 
 made useful, comfortable, and essentially free, only by being 
 brought under bondage to society and kept under mastership and 
 discipline until, if ever, they acquire power to help and govern 
 themselves. If one should say that we all believe this doctrine, 
 that it is in no sense new, the necessary reply would be that we 
 nevertheless habitually disregard it in every matter save the jurid- 
 ical distinction between the law-abiding and the criminal. We 
 accept laissez faire as the expedient rule for all men and all indus- 
 tries alike, or we denounce it as bad for all alike. We advocate 
 socialistic methods for the entire field of industry, or we pro- 
 nounce them impracticable for any part of it. We denounce 
 compulsory education for any class in the community, or we insist 
 on forcing it on all classes. In all which sayings and doings we 
 confound unlike things, and show ourselves irrational in the last 
 degree. 
 
 What, then, in concrete detail, are some of the obligations 
 placed upon individuals and upon society by the conditions of 
 social progress? 
 
 The law that progressive, self-governing members of society 
 should lay on themselves includes at least three groups of duties. 
 First, they should resist, personally and in their influence, the 
 tendency to subordinate higher considerations to that mere quick- 
 ening of competitive activity which goes beyond its normal func- 
 tion of means to end, to become an irrational, unjustifiable end in 
 itself. Especially in the education of ambitious children should 
 competition be tempered. Second, they should resort more freely, 
 as fortunately they are beginning to do, to country life, and 
 especially should they study and experiment with the ways and 
 means of revitalizing it. Third, they should cultivate that true 
 individuality in the consumption of wealth, which is not only a 
 mark of genuine manliness or womanliness, but which acts on 
 economic demand in ways that give a competitive advantage to 
 the industrial qualities of men whose standard of life is high. 
 
 The duties that society should discharge in its relation to the 
 general conditions of progressive activity, and to its members 
 who are undeveloped or degenerate, fall also into three groups. 
 First, society should assume the regulation of international migra-
 
 THE COSTS OF PROGRESS 245 
 
 tion. Each nation should bear the burden of pauperism, ig- 
 norance, and degeneracy caused by its own progress or wrong- 
 doing. Society should also assume the regulation, by industrial 
 and labor legislation, of industries in which free competition dis- 
 places the better man by the inferior. Perhaps in time some 
 of these industries could advantageously come directly under pub- 
 lic management, as socialism proposes. Second, society should 
 act on the fact that a proportion of its population must be always 
 practically unfree, by extending compulsory education to the chil- 
 dren of parents who are unable or unwilling to provide in their 
 own way a training that the commonwealth can approve. This 
 education should be as well adapted as knowledge, money, and 
 sincerity of purpose can make it, to the work of fitting the children 
 of the poor for life in a changing world. Third, society should 
 enslave, not figuratively, but literally, all men and women who 
 voluntarily betake themselves to a life of vagabondage. 
 
 These are the obligations of individuals and of the state that 
 seem to be disclosed by a study of social progress. But we must 
 not forget that the same conditions impose a negative duty also, 
 an obligation of restraint. For all reform, all philanthropic work, 
 is itself a phase of social progress, and, like all others, has a cost 
 in effort and suffering. Therefore, if philanthropic reform is 
 hurried, or pursued by too radical methods, it may convert the 
 absolute increase of evil, which progress costs, into a relative 
 increase, and so wholly defeat itself. Lombroso and Laschi once 
 contended that political crime (the crime, that is, of those who 
 unsuccessfully resist governmental authority) consists essentially 
 in an attempt to accomplish in crude and violent ways desirable 
 changes or reforms for which society is not yet ready. 1 Devotion 
 to the cause of progress these authors proposed to call by the name 
 "philoneism" ; the dread of change by the name "misoneism." 
 Society is, on the whole, misoneistic ; and we can mend its ways 
 but slowly. 
 
 For, whatever happens, we must keep in touch with our fellow- 
 men. It was Marcus Aurelius, one of the most modern-minded 
 men of the first great western civilization, who said : 
 
 "The intelligence of the universe is social. Accordingly it has 
 
 1 Le Crime politique et les Revolutions.
 
 246 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 made the inferior things for the sake of the superior, and it has 
 fitted the superior to one another. Thou seest how it has sub- 
 ordinated, coordinated, and assigned to everything its proper 
 portion, and has brought together into concord with one another 
 the things which are the best." * 
 
 That was nearly two thousand years ago. The aspect of the 
 world has changed, but the essential nature and the fundamental 
 structure of human society have not. 
 
 l Marci Antonini Imperatoris De Rebus Suis. V, xxx.
 
 PART III 
 SYNTHETIC
 
 CHAPTER XV 
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 
 
 I. THE DYNAMICS OF PLURALISTIC STRUGGLE 
 i. LIFE AS PLURALISTIC 
 
 OUTSIDE my window seven belligerent sparrows make a 
 machine-gun din as they fight over a crust bequeathed to them 
 by an unscientific philanthropist. While I watch them, a motor- 
 cycle policeman charging into the street arrests a speeding auto- 
 mobile flying blue flags and laden with violets and girls. In two 
 minutes the boy "bunch" of the block has assembled to learn 
 whether the car will be permitted to go on to New Haven, in 
 time for "the game." 
 
 Of occurrences fundamentally like these life largely consists. 
 Living bodies "carry on" to sustain and to perpetuate themselves. 
 On occasion they fight. Their activity is more, however, than a 
 struggle for bare existence. It is an endeavor to enlarge life and 
 to enrich it. Conscious life is a struggle for satisfactions, includ- 
 ing individuation, and for achievement. 
 
 Perpetuating itself, life multiplies itself, and the multiplication 
 of individual lives complicates and intensifies the struggle for 
 existence. The casualties are countless. The organisms that 
 are most "fit," in the sense of being best adapted to their circum- 
 stances and best equipped to meet crises, survive. There is a 
 natural selection. 
 
 The activity of a living body is reaction to stimulus, and 
 reaction is behavior. 
 
 All reaction is a physiological behavior, and many reactions of 
 tracts and organs are physiological only ; but whatever the entire 
 organism does as a unit is also behavior in a psychological mean- 
 ing of the word. 
 
 249
 
 2 so STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 The behavior of plants and of the lowlier animals is uncon- 
 scious, or perhaps infinitesimally conscious : it is subinstinctive. 
 Such, for example, is the turning of the leaves of heliotropic 
 plants to the sunlight. Truly instinctive behavior begins with 
 organisms that have acquired an automatically reacting nervous 
 mechanism. It is accompanied by awareness, including sensa- 
 tions, with which, in the vertebrates (the higher ones, at least) 
 are associated also emotions, simple ideas, and memories. 
 These higher animals behave instinctively, and also by habit: in 
 the individual span of life between birth and death they learn 
 much by haphazard trial and elimination. The behavior of man- 
 kind is instinctive, habitistic, and rational. Self-consciousness 
 has appeared, speech has been acquired, and hit-or-miss trial has 
 been overlaid and brought under control by experimentation in 
 thought, which ranges from guessing to systematic induction. 
 Ideas, accordingly, have been correlated and coordinated. 
 
 The sum of behavior is the total struggle for existence and 
 achievement. By far the greater part of it consists of effort to 
 meet instant needs. A lesser but large part consists of efforts 
 to obtain desired but not imperative satisfactions. The remainder 
 is a free expenditure "for the fun of it," not at the moment pro- 
 ductive, but tending always to become experiment, including ex- 
 ploration of the environment ; and experiment leads to discovery, 
 without which there could be no achievement. 
 
 In a world of limited inhabitable area the multiplication of 
 individuals (whether cells or organisms), living by trial and error 
 and tending to explore their environment, causes contacts and 
 creates groupings of living units. 
 
 The earliest and simplest groupings are an incident of birth. 
 
 Usually an organism in its lifetime reproduces itself more than 
 once. Until they scatter, plural offspring are in form a group. 
 They share good and bad fortune. 
 
 The cells that compose and constitute a plant or an animal are 
 united in the intimacies of structure and process. Their collective 
 life is physiological. Usually they cannot break away from the 
 organic whole, or live apart from it. 
 
 The coelenterate polyps that secrete coral are attached directly,
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 251 
 
 or through branches, to a parent stem. They cannot get asunder, 
 but one of them torn away by violence could be the parent of a 
 new zoophyte. They do not constitute an organism. Their col- 
 lective life is conjunctive only. 
 
 The bees of a swarm, the beasts of a herd, the beavers of a 
 dam, the men of a community, move about in individual detach- 
 ment. Any one of them could live a hermit life for a while ; but 
 usually individuals of a kind act with reference to one another 
 and keep near one another. 
 
 Keeping near one another, notwithstanding physical detach- 
 ment, is behavior, and the collective life of physically detached 
 individuals is behavioristic only. 
 
 Accordingly, the multiplication of lives not only intensifies the 
 struggle of each individual for existence and complicates its con- 
 ditions; it also in certain instances creates for all or nearly all 
 individuals of the kind a physically collective life, and in other 
 instances it complicates and organizes behavior and creates for all 
 or nearly all individuals of the kind a behavioristically collective 
 life. 
 
 The behavior that constitutes the collective life of swarm, herd, 
 pack, or community is pluralistic. Any one or any combination 
 of behavior-inciting stimuli may on occasion be reacted to by more 
 than one individual ; as the bread crust is by the seven sparrows, 
 and as the "cop" and the car are by the gangster boys of the 
 block. 
 
 The reactions of the individuals of a plurel to a stimulation 
 common to them all in the sense that it reaches all may be similar 
 or they may be dissimilar. To the same stimulus or to like stimuli 
 like organisms normally react in like manner, as crows in the corn- 
 field take wing at a gunshot and boys in the street run after the 
 fire engine. 
 
 Alike or unlike, pluralistic reactions may be simultaneous or 
 they may "string out" from prompt to dilatory. They may be 
 substantially equal in strength, or unequal. They may be equally, 
 or unequally persistent. 
 
 Like acts by detached individuals may be competitive, or they 
 may fall into combinations, as when animals in a pack follow the
 
 252 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 same quarry or beat off a common enemy. When it is often 
 enough repeated, combined action becomes habitual group action. 
 
 Whether they are dissimilar or similar, rivalistic or combined, 
 simultaneous or not, equal or unequal, pluralistic reactions to a 
 common stimulation make a strictly individualistic struggle for 
 existence impossible. Above all is this true of the human struggle 
 for achievement. It is a pluralistic struggle. 
 
 Pluralistic behavior, in distinction from individual behavior, 
 has its own conditions, forms, and laws. 
 
 In early youth I often drove cattle on the highway, and I 
 learned that the secret of keeping them moving in good form lay 
 in the "crack" of the stimulus that I relied on. In later youth, 
 conducting and teaching a rural school, I learned that there also 
 one secret of orderly cooperation lay in the cogency of the stim- 
 ulation applied. Whether physical, utilitarian, or moral, it must 
 be adequate. From these experiences, however, I learned also 
 another thing not less interesting. It was that the part played by 
 resemblances (or differences) among nervous systems is always 
 significant and may be determinative. Two or three unruly steers 
 in a herd could tax the powers of any driver. Two or three con- 
 ceited morons in a school could tax the ingenuity and the patience 
 of any teacher. 
 
 These instances are not oddities ; they are representative rela- 
 tions. Always the character of pluralistic reactions (as similar or 
 dissimilar, simultaneous or not, equal or unequal) is determined 
 by two variables, namely, (i) the strength of the stimulation, 
 and (2) the similarity (or the dissimilarity) of the reacting mech- 
 anisms. 
 
 Pluralistic behavior is the subject-matter of the psychology of 
 society, otherwise called sociology, a science statistical in method, 
 which attempts, first, to factorize pluralistic behavior, and sec- 
 ond, to explain its genesis, integration, differentiation, and func- 
 tioning by accounting for them in terms of the variables (i) 
 stimulation, and (2) the resemblance (more or less) to one 
 another of reacting mechanisms. 1 
 
 J The psychology of society and social psychology are different things, 
 as I pointed out in the article on "The Psychology of Society," in Science, 
 January 6, 1899. One is identical with sociology, the other is not-
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 253 
 
 2. REGIONAL INFLUENCE 
 
 Stimuli are infinitely various. In character they range from 
 compulsions, impulsions, and constraints to inducements and 
 allurements. 
 
 Among stimuli that all living bodies react to are phenomena of 
 the surface of the earth, including its life-sustaining resources, 
 and of the atmosphere, including variations of temperature and 
 of precipitation. All these are unevenly distributed. Geography 
 is a variegated thing. There are regions that forbid, repel, starve, 
 and kill, and there are regions that nourish and attract. There- 
 fore, the teeming life of the earth is apportioned and segregated, 
 here in energetic aggregations, there in sporadic, ineffective exam- 
 ples according to the regional dispersion of environmental bounty 
 and exaction, incitement, and constraint. 
 
 The distribution of inhabitable areas on the earth's surface is 
 neither haphazard nor uniform. It is a grouping by coastal 
 plains, river basins, and mountain systems, or in relation to them. 
 The river deltas and the tide-water lowlands are relatively acces- 
 sible. The bottom lands and lower levels of the watershed are 
 abundantly productive of primary means of subsistence, the re- 
 moter plains and plateaus less so. Least bountiful in primary 
 food products, least accessible, and, in general, least inhabitable 
 are the high altitudes, in particular the continental divides, where 
 river systems take their rise. 
 
 For brief periods of time the physical environment is normally 
 static approximately but if its permutations throughout long 
 periods are observed, it is seen to be highly kinetic. It "breaks 
 out" in volcanic disturbances and in earthquakes. Variations of 
 climate from cold to hot, from wet to dry, range from enormous 
 revolutions consequent upon subsidences and elevations of the 
 earth's crust, or upon the advance or retreat of the polar ice cap, 
 down to minor fluctuations that are measured by familiar peri- 
 odicities of maximum and minimum rainfall. 
 
 The relative advantageousness of physical environments for 
 sustaining, energizing, and stimulating pluralistic life is a factor 
 of all social phenomena. It determines the density and the com- 
 position of every population. It provokes and limits collective 
 effort. It fixes the possibilities of organization and of collective
 
 254 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 effectiveness. Directly, and indirectly through collective effort 
 and effectiveness, it makes and limits the possibilities of well-being 
 and of individuation. 
 
 3. CIRCUMSTANTIAL PRESSURE 
 
 If the foregoing propositions are undeniable, the physiographic 
 or "environmental" theory of history is true, as far as it goes. It 
 is an inadequate and unsatisfactory philosophy, however, because 
 it fails to perceive and to explain the media through which a 
 physical environment acts upon conduct. We are creatures of 
 circumstance. 
 
 For among the stimuli that incite and sustain behavior are vari- 
 ous annoyances, hardships, dangers, and adversities that bear 
 so heavily upon individuals living in isolation or unaided by 
 neighboring fellow-beings that they constrain great numbers of 
 animals of various species and great numbers of men to live in 
 aggregations ; and constrain great numbers of group-dwelling men 
 to overlook many of their differences, to minimize many of their 
 antagonisms, and to combine their efforts. These constraining 
 circumstances may be conceived as constituting a circumstantial 
 pressure upon living beings. 
 
 In its totality circumstantial pressure, like chance (as the 
 mathematicians define chance), comprises innumerable small 
 causes. Rain drives beasts and human beings into momentary 
 assemblages. So does the glare of noonday sunlight. When 
 winds are cold some creatures hogs, notoriously, and sheep 
 huddle together for warmth. Drought, drying many springs and 
 streams commonly resorted to, and compelling assemblage at 
 those that remain, is often a pressure of extreme intensity. 
 Darkness with its fearsome uncertainties occasions recurrent con- 
 sorting of individuals (animal or human)- that feel sure of one 
 another. These pressures are not in themselves causes of co- 
 operation, whereas accidents and attacks upon persons and posses- 
 sions commonly are. 
 
 The curve, however, of circumstantial pressure is not a normal 
 frequency distribution. It is skewed by relatively large causes of 
 various magnitudes. Of these the most general, perhaps, is a 
 diminishing return to effort in the struggle for existence. Dimin-
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 255 
 
 ishing return in the economist's meaning of the phrase is a special 
 case. Economic adversity or threat is another. An important 
 instance is an extensive dessication, like that which periodically 
 recurs in Western Asia. 1 Little if any less general and more 
 unremittent is the pressure exerted by the hardships and dangers 
 of isolation. Continuous but highly variable is the pressure of 
 foreign economic competition, the reaction to which is protective 
 tariff legislation. Intermittent but most tremendous of circum- 
 stantial pressures, and in its consequences the most far-reaching, 
 is war, and war is a product of countless factors of more than one 
 category, as the failure of all attempts to account for the European 
 war of 1914 by any one cause, for example, economic interest, 
 has abundantly made clear. 
 
 The hardships and dangers of isolation are measured by urbani- 
 zation, namely, the percentage of the population of a given area 
 that dwells in towns and cities of a designated number, or more, 
 inhabitants. Urbanization is the best basic measure of circum- 
 stantial pressure. The chiefly important phenomena of society 
 are more highly correlated with it than with mere density of pop- 
 ulation. Supplementary measures are fluctuations of prices, 2 the 
 foreign exchanges, and the statistics of war. 
 
 4. DEMOTIC FACTORS OF LIKE-MINDEDNESS 
 
 Regional and urban aggregations of human beings increase in 
 two ways: (i) by births in excess of deaths; (2) by immigration 
 in excess of emigration. A population growing chiefly by births 
 in excess of deaths is predominantly a genetic aggregation. A 
 population growing chiefly by immigration in excess of emigra- 
 tion is predominantly a congregation. A normal population is 
 both a genetic aggregation and a congregation. 
 
 Normally, a population is composite. It is composed of the 
 young, the middle-aged, and the old ; of males and females ; of 
 the native- and the foreign-born. It may comprise more than one 
 color-race, and the foreign-born usually comprise more than one 
 ethnic stock and more than one nationality. 
 
 1 Ellsworth Huntington, The Pulse of Asia. 
 
 2 The newspapers reported in 1919 that the Sultan and pashas of Turkey 
 had cut down their harems to one wife each, because of the high cost 
 of living!
 
 256 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 Normally, as time goes on, there is intermarriage among 
 nationalities of the same color-race, with resulting amalgamation. 
 There is a tendency toward ethnic homogeneity within the limits 
 of the numerically dominant color-race. 
 
 As reacting mechanisms, the nervous systems of individuals of 
 the same color-race are in general more nearly alike than are the 
 nervous systems of individuals of different color-races ; and within 
 the limits of the same color-race the nervous systems of individ- 
 uals of the same ethnic stock (for example, the Germanic) 
 are in general more nearly alike than are the nervous systems of 
 individuals of different ethnic stocks (for example, the Germanic 
 and the Celtic) . The proof is, that it takes a stronger stimulation 
 to obtain like reactions from individuals of different color-races or 
 of different ethnic stocks of the same color-race than it does to 
 obtain like reactions from individuals of the same stock or race. 
 Try the experiment and repeat it until you are satisfied. 
 
 The young, however, react, in most cases, more readily to 
 novel stimulation than the old do. An amazing example (as most 
 observers regard it) is the world-wide interest of youth in revolu- 
 tionary radicalism. The phenomenon is not new, however. It 
 has been witnessed in every century. A significant and important 
 consequence of it is that it is easier to obtain like reactions from 
 the young of intermingled stocks or races than from the old. 
 Revolutionary radicalism and internationalism go together. 
 
 The sum of like reactions, instinctive, habitistic, and rational, 
 is like-mindedness. 
 
 The measure of basic like-mindedness is an index number, 
 obtained by decreasing the weight of successive increments that 
 diminish the homogeneity of their sum ; for example : white, 
 native-born of native parents ; plus white, of parents foreign-born, 
 divided by two; plus white, foreign-born, divided by four; plus 
 all colored, divided by eight. 
 
 The chiefly important phenomena of society for example, per 
 capita taxation, per capita expenditure for schools, and a habitual 
 exercise of the political franchise are not highly correlated posi- 
 tively or negatively with basic like-mindedness. The meaning of 
 this extremely significant statistical fact is that alert and progres- 
 sive social life is associated not with strict and exclusive similarity,
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 257 
 
 or with extreme dissimilarity, but with that intermediate degree 
 of mental and moral homogeneity which is an adequate meeting of 
 minds for practical purposes and yet is tolerant of individual 
 difference and dissent. 
 
 The best measure of radical like-mindedness is the percentage 
 number of individuals of the numerically dominant color-race 
 whose ages fall between the limits twenty and thirty-nine years. 
 The best measure of conservative like-mindedness is the percent- 
 age number of individuals native-born of native parents whose 
 ages fall in the class forty years and above. The radically like- 
 minded are normally more numerous than the conservatively 
 like-minded because they are indifferent (as the conservatives 
 are not) to the distinction "native-born," or, going a step farther, 
 "native-born of native parents." War tends to consolidate rad- 
 icals with conservatives and to merge these measures. 
 
 When the stimuli to which living bodies react have become a 
 circumstantial pressure, and the resemblances of reacting mechan- 
 isms have become like-mindedness, every social phenomenon 
 thenceforth and every social situation is a function of two vari- 
 ables, namely, (i) circumstantial pressure, and (2) like-minded- 
 ness, each of which varies under the influence of the other, under 
 influences that affect them differently, and under influences that 
 affect them similarly. 
 
 II. THE REACTIONS OF ASSEMBLED LIFE 
 5. COMPLEX PLURALISTIC RESPONSE 
 
 Simple pluralistic behavior is complicated and developed by 
 interstimulation and response. Each individual of a group or 
 assemblage is a complex of stimuli to his fellows, and each re- 
 sponds to fellow-stimulation. 
 
 The interstimulation of similar organisms differs from stimula- 
 tion otherwise arising. It has a distinct character. Normally it 
 is not repellent. It does not cause shrinking, recoil, or retreat. 
 The reactions also of resembling individuals to one another are 
 significantly different from the reactions of non-resembling indi- 
 viduals to one another. 
 
 Organisms of like kind stimulate each other non-repellently
 
 258 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 not only because, first, they are similar complexes of stimuli, and 
 because, secondly, they are similar complexes of reaction, but also, 
 thirdly (and this is important), because the behavior of one organ- 
 ism a which functions as stimulation to another organism of like 
 kind d (for example, the caw of a crow, the yelp of a dog, or the 
 whinny of a horse) normally calls forth from that other a among 
 various reactions a behavior (there is an answering caw, or yelp, 
 or whinny) that is so like the initial behavior of a that it might 
 have arisen in a by self -imitation. Such interstimulation cannot 
 be repellent in a high degree, although in a degree it may be antag- 
 onistic. Two dogs may bristle and fight on first acquaintance, 
 but they do not hasten to part company, as the horse shies from 
 the rattlesnake or from the bumblebee. The fight ends in tolera- 
 tion or in the submission of one dog to the other. 
 
 Reactions of either similar or dissimilar individuals to one 
 another may be unconscious or may be conscious. Unconscious 
 pluralistic reactions of similars to one another are factors of vari- 
 ous herd instincts and of numerous herd habits, all of which 
 combine in gregariousness. 
 
 The synthesis turns upon and proceeds from the distinctive 
 peculiarities of stimulation of kind by kind and of reaction of 
 kind to kind, above set forth. The movements of organisms, like 
 the motions of inorganic bodies, follow lines of relatively low 
 resistance. Repellent stimulation and recoiling reaction open 
 lines of relatively high resistance. Non-repellent stimulation and 
 forthgoing action open lines of relatively low resistance. Also 
 reactions to stimuli that resemble self-stimuli are relatively facile. 
 These reactions include automatic imitations innumerable. On 
 mechanistic principles, therefore, a reacting locomotor organism 
 tends to go toward or to go with objects (including other loco- 
 motor organisms) from which non-repellent or otherwise non- 
 resistent stimulation proceeds. 
 
 In distinctive stimulations of kind by kind, then, and in char- 
 acteristically facile reactions to kind we discover relatively simple 
 mechanistic factors of innate gregariousness or "herd instinct," 
 the chief manifestations of which are a matter-of-course tolera- 
 tion of one another by individual units of a kin group, an auto- 
 matic tendency to go with kind or at least to avoid separation
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 259 
 
 from kind, an automatic imitation of kind, and an unhesitating 
 reaction to herd stimulation. 
 
 This account of gregariousness is opposed to a commonly 
 accepted one which makes characteristic reaction to kind a mani- 
 festation of an unexplained herd instinct, so putting cause and 
 effect the other way around. 1 
 
 In the processes of interstimulation and its reactions pluralistic 
 behavior is dramatized. Action which, in the first instance, is 
 performed without reference to possible reaction by fellow -beings, 
 but which in fact is followed by fellow-reaction, is likely in subse- 
 quent performance to be affected thereby. In the presence of 
 fellow-beings action becomes acting, and thenceforward things 
 are not merely done, they are enacted. 
 
 Under common danger, and often under common opportunity, 
 similarities of behavior more or less dramatized develop into 
 spontaneous collective action. The individuals participating in it 
 may not be, or they may be, aware that they are combining their 
 efforts ; and they may not be, or they may be, aware that by com- 
 bination they are producing results; but whether conscious or 
 unconscious, cooperation commonly produces results advanta- 
 geous to the individuals participating in it. 
 
 The probability of collective action increases with circumstantial 
 pressure. 
 
 6. THE CONSCIOUSNESS OF KIND 
 
 In mankind interstimulation and its reactions have developed 
 into communication by means of vocal signs. Everything is 
 talked about. Pluralistic behavior having been dramatized is now 
 also conversationalised. 
 
 Not only outward behavior and material things are talked 
 about. "Ideas" and "feelings" as "states of consciousness" also 
 are talked about. Thenceforth a conversationalised consciousness 
 and its states may legitimately be included in a study of be- 
 havior, viewed as an objective phenomenon. 
 
 Stimulation and reaction are accompanied by sensation. Dif- 
 ferences and similarities among stimuli, differences and similarities 
 among reactions, are "felt" in consciousness, and presently are 
 
 1 See William McDougall, Social Psychology, ch. xii, and W. Trotter, 
 Instincts of the Herd in Peace and War, pp. 1-23.
 
 260 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 perceived. Differences and similarities among objects, among 
 the activities of things, and among behavioristic acts are felt and 
 perceived. Differences of individuals one from another and sim- 
 ilarities of individuals one to another also are felt and perceived. 
 The idea of "kind" arises. Individuals become aware of them- 
 selves as a "kind," and as being of one, or of more than one 
 "kind." This consciousness in human individuals of their differ- 
 ences one from another, of their similarities one to another, and 
 of their "kind" is the "consciousness of kind." More precisely, 
 the consciousness of kind is awareness of a concrete case or pos- 
 sibility of like-mindedness, and of such physical traits as are 
 commonly associated with it. 
 
 The consciousness of kind allays fear and engenders comrade- 
 ship. It converts instinctive consorting into a consciously dis- 
 criminative association. Without it there is no society; there is 
 only gregariousness. Of the instinctive herd it may be said as 
 Rousseau said of the state created by force, "C'est une agregation, 
 s'il vous plait, mais c'est non pas une association." The mem- 
 bers of a society are aware of themselves as preferentially asso- 
 ciating similars. For example, if they are Presbyterians, Repub- 
 licans, and Americans, they consciously prefer to associate in 
 religious communion with Presbyterians like-minded with them- 
 selves rather than with Methodists or with Episcopalians; to 
 associate in politics with Republicans like-minded with themselves 
 rather than with Democrats ; and to associate in nationality with 
 Americans like-minded with themselves rather than with the 
 people of any European land. The consciousness of kind is be- 
 coming not less but more potent in large affairs. Perhaps the 
 greatest manifestation of it ever seen is the nation-wide demand 
 in the United States at present for the Americanization of alien 
 residents. They must be made like-minded with Americans. 
 
 Odd as it may seem to the uninitiated, the statistical study of 
 the consciousness of kind to the extent of obtaining excellent 
 measurements of it, on either a small or a large scale, is not diffi- 
 cult. The data are frequency-distributions of preferences. The 
 curves which these approximately fit are in form like the familiar 
 curves of utility, demand, and price.
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 261 
 
 7. CONCERTED VOLITION 
 
 In the course of pluralistic behavior above the instinctive level 
 conscious agreements arise. Propositions are put forth and are 
 "talked over." There begins to be "a meeting of minds." Col- 
 lective choices or decisions are made. There is a concert of wills, 
 a concerted volition. 
 
 Like the volition of an individual, concerted volition is of 
 various degrees of completeness. There may be only an incipient 
 impulse, that dies out before behavior is visibly affected and that 
 is known in consciousness only as an unexpressed choice or per- 
 haps only as a wish. Or there may be a consciously apprehended 
 decision, which is expressed in words or in gestures or through 
 other media. As the vote of a committee or of an assembly or, 
 on a larger scale, as a political election, concerted decision ex- 
 pressed in words is an important behavior. Finally, concerted 
 will may be expressed in collective action, brief or persisting. 
 
 In a normal population there are individuals of every grade of 
 mentality, and more individuals of each intermediate grade than 
 of the lowest or of the highest. Inasmuch, however, as all highly 
 reflective individuals are also dogmatic, sympathetic, and instinc- 
 tive, and all dogmatic individuals are also emotional and instinc- 
 tive, and all emotional individuals are also instinctive, there are 
 always in a normal aggregation more individuals that are alike 
 in motor reactions and in appetites than are alike in sympathies, 
 more who are alike in sympathies than are alike in beliefs, and 
 more who are alike in beliefs than are alike in critical intelligence. 
 
 From these facts a law of concerted volition follows, namely: 
 
 In a normal population the percentage number of individuals 
 participating in a collective decision diminishes as the intellectual 
 quality of the decision rises. 1 
 
 This law does not mean that "the intellectuals" and the 
 "masses" cannot get together. They can and do concur for prac- 
 tical purposes, but only as one element yields to the other. The 
 masses may "believe" that it is expedient to follow a lead that they 
 do not understand but do trust ; or the intellectuals may compro- 
 
 1 In New York City the East Side vote on constitutional amendments 
 is light. The heavy vote is in the election districts of Greenwich Village, 
 Morningside Heights, and Washington Heights.
 
 262 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 mise with a crowd that stubbornly holds an antagonistic belief. 
 Conviction of the expediency of yielding, trusting, or compro- 
 mising strengthens and extends as circumstantial pressure 
 increases. 
 
 Circumstantial pressure determines the amount of concerted 
 volition in an aggregation in any respect heterogeneous. In a 
 homogeneous group, a majority of all individuals may alike react 
 to varied stimuli, and the stimuli are not necessarily powerful. In 
 the heterogeneous group a majority of all individuals can react in 
 identical or resembling ways to but few stimuli, and these must be 
 powerful ; but the more powerful they are, the larger will be the 
 absolute and the percentage number of individuals in like manner 
 reacting to them. This law holds good of conscious decisions as 
 of instinctive acts. 
 
 If one hundred or more persons vote "yes" or "no" on each of 
 twenty-five or more propositions, and the number of "yes" votes 
 for two propositions, for three, for four, for five, and so on, is 
 plotted, the resulting frequency-distribution is a skew, whether 
 the voting group is homogeneous or heterogeneous. In many ex- 
 periments I have not obtained a "normal" (or "chance") distri- 
 bution. Into the "infinite number of small causes" operative in 
 politics and in legislation a few big influences intrude; which 
 means that great interests always can be and always are manipu- 
 lated by the purposive will of man. The proposition means, 
 further, that for great historical calamities, like wars, a few 
 individuals are morally responsible. Statisticial sociology affords 
 no basis for historical fatalism. 
 
 Concerted volition working itself out in combined action is 
 a conscious and reasoned cooperation, a pluralistic behavior in 
 which like activities or complementary activities are correlated 
 and directed upon a useful achievement through conscious plan- 
 ning. 
 
 8. SOCIETY 
 
 The commingling and the pluralistic activities of individuals 
 who are conscious of themselves and of their behavior, and whose 
 consciousness is conversationalized, is association. 
 
 The consciousness of kind, becoming sensitive especially to
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 263 
 
 resemblances and differences that please or displease, converts 
 association into society, in the elementary sense of the word. 
 The associating unit -becomes the socius, loving and seeking ac- 
 quaintance, forming friendships and alliances with other socii like 
 himself, imitating them and setting examples for them, teaching 
 them and learning from them, and engaging with them in many 
 forms of common activity. Every human being is at once an 
 animal, a conscious individual mind, and a socius. 
 
 Association takes on the quality and the color of the prevailing 
 like-mindedness, which may be ideo-instinctive only, and charged 
 with suggestibility; or sympathetic, explosive with contagious 
 emotion and undisciplined imagination; or dogmatic, compact of 
 uncritically accepted beliefs; or reflective, wherein belief is dis- 
 placed by knowledge and by judgments based on evidence. The 
 concerted behavior of associates, therefore, may be a turbulent 
 "direct action" or an orderly procedure. 
 
 Reacting to circumstantial pressure, association generates a 
 social pressure, which increases with the multiplication of like 
 responses to common stimulations, as the pressure of a gas in- 
 creases with the number and the velocity of its molecules. 
 
 Reacting in its turn upon the pluralistic behaviors that have 
 created it, social pressure assembles and combines them in new 
 products, through which it distributes itself. The reacting indi- 
 viduals it constrains to type conformity. 
 
 Subjected to social pressure, pluralistic behavior of any kind 
 may become habitual. It may be imitated by one group from 
 another. It may be learned by one generation from another. 
 The accompanying ideas, histories, explanations, and instructions 
 are transmitted from group to group, and from one to another 
 generation in "talk." They become folklore. To the countless 
 cooperations and other pluralistic behaviors that "everybody" 
 participates in and that continue through generations, Sumner 
 gave the appropriate name "folkways," which immediately found 
 place in sociology and soon became a folk noun. 
 
 Folklore and folkways are comprehensive. There is no phase 
 of the struggle for existence that they do not enter into and more 
 or less affect. 
 
 In its original mode social pressure is not consciously willed.
 
 264 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 It is not planned or intended. It is only an inevitably arising 
 product (or by-product) of pluralistic behavior. 
 
 But having, as a force devoid of intent, created folkways, 
 social pressure, elemental yet, converts folkways into mores and 
 themistes, which in turn distribute and apply social pressure and 
 through these reactions develop it into an intended, planned, and 
 consciously concerted pressure. 
 
 Mores are folkways that have been selectively affected by emo- 
 tion, belief, reflection, and conscious inculcation, and that to 
 some extent are socially enforced. Like primary folkways the 
 mores, chiefly by penalties of disapprobation and neglect, bear on 
 individuals as such and primarily with reference to their own well- 
 being ; but also they are thought of and are made to serve as media 
 of social pressure affecting fellow-beings. The sanctions that 
 enforce them are informal, but may include the use of force in 
 private vengeance. 
 
 Themistes are important mores, of religion, for example, and 
 above all, of justice. They are mores of concerted volition and 
 apply social pressure through boycotting, outlawry, and other 
 social dooms, including death. 1 
 
 In mores and themistes under the reactions of the social pres- 
 sure which they themselves gather and distribute, pluralistic 
 behavior is traditionalized. 
 
 Folkways of every kind, including mores and themistes, are the 
 most stable syntheses of pluralistic behavior ; yet they are not un- 
 changing. Under new and widening experience they suffer 
 attrition and are modified. 2 Instincts, and with them emotion, 
 
 1 See Jane Ellen Harrison, Themis. 
 
 3 Numerous ballotings on hypothetical candidates for admission to social 
 organizations have been taken at my request in colleges, merchants' asso- 
 ciations, and labor organizations. The grounds of exclusion are offenses 
 against morals and manners and certain personal matters. They are 
 named in a list of twenty-seven items made in advance and submitted 
 to the voters. The method of proceeding has been carefully explained 
 and controlled. More than 50 per cent of the voters blackball for noto- 
 rious cruelty, dishonesty, frequent drunkenness, gambling, sexual immo- 
 rality, and personal uncleanliness of body and dress. Less than 50 per 
 cent of the voters blackball for habitual borrowing of money from 
 acquaintances, ungrammatical speech, atheism, inability to write a cor- 
 rectly worded letter, questionable political affiliations, and shabby dress. 
 Notorious cruelty is the vice most objected to by both men and women. 
 Dishonesty ranks second in offensiveness to men and sixth to women.
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 265 
 
 and imagination, which largely fills the vast realm between in- 
 stinct and reason, are reconditioned. The word means simply 
 that reflexes and higher processes subjected to new experiences 
 are in a degree or entirely detached from old stimuli and associated 
 with new ones. 1 
 
 From time to time also traditions are invaded and habits are 
 broken down by crisis. Pluralistic behavior then is scrutinized, 
 criticized, estimated, discussed. It is rationally deliberated. 
 
 Viewed broadly as reaction instead of strictly as reflection, 
 deliberation arises in the individual mind as a conflict of reactions 
 to stimulation. On the larger scale of social phenomena delibera- 
 tion arises when there are conflicting group or class reactions to 
 a common stimulation. 
 
 Therefore the probability of deliberation in a social population 
 increases with the multiplication of groups that react differently 
 to a common stimulation and with the approximation of the dif- 
 fering groups to numerical equality. 
 
 The members of a group in which pluralistic behavior is both 
 traditionalized and deliberated talk much about the group as a 
 group, and of their membership relation to it. They converse 
 about their common lot of danger or opportunity. They profess 
 to think about common interests, to care for group performance 
 and achievement, and to be sensitive to group prestige. 
 
 There is, accordingly, a complex of pluralistic behavior facts 
 which includes common situation and common stimulation, 
 similarity of reaction, a consciousness of kind, cooperation, tra- 
 dition, discussion, a proclaimed concern for the group, and sensi- 
 tiveness to its prestige. This complex is the social solidarity. 
 
 Otherwise named, the social solidarity is the social mind. This 
 name does not denote any other consciousness than that of indi- 
 
 Frequent drunkenness ranks second in offensiveness to women and thir- 
 teenth to men. More men than women object to personal uncleanliness 
 of body and dress. 
 
 1 A piece of meat in a dog's mouth causes a flow of saliva. A Russian 
 psychologist, Pawlow, tried the experiment of tinkling a bell when the 
 dog was fed. In course of time the tinkling of the bell without the 
 presence of the meat called forth the reflex and produced the salivation 
 (Robert Sessions Woodworth, Dynamic Psychology, p. 82). Hundreds 
 of similar experiments suggested by Pawlow's have demonstrated that 
 simple reflexes and elementary instincts can be reconditioned, practically 
 at will. This possibility is the basis of our power to learn.
 
 266 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 vidual minds ; it does denote a consciousness of individual minds 
 similarly reacting, and reacting in reference to and upon one 
 another. The social mind is the phenomenon of individual minds 
 in communication with one another, acting upon one another, and 
 acting concurrently. The self-consciousness of a class or of a 
 group is the consciousness of each individual that there is a group, 
 that he is a member of the group, and that the other members of 
 the group are feeling toward it as he feels, and thinking of it as he 
 thinks. 
 
 The decision of the social mind is social purpose. The momen- 
 tum of the social solidarity is a consciously controlled social 
 pressure of almost irresistible power. It may constrain pluralistic 
 behavior and curtail individual liberty to any degree. The indi- 
 vidual himself it both constrains and disciplines. It makes the 
 many individuals upon whom it bears increasingly alike in nurture 
 and in habits. It produces conformity to a type. 
 
 The degree or intensity of social constraint, however, is not 
 determined by reasoned choice. It is governed by circumstantial 
 pressure, to which it is elastic. When we entered into the 
 European war many timid souls feared that we should lose our 
 liberties. They believed that we should become militaristic and 
 Prussianized. They were right in part but largely they were 
 wrong. The war restricted liberty, as the Civil War did. Peace 
 removes restraints as it did after 1865. And war is not the only 
 circumstantial pressure that limits liberty. Herbert Spencer was 
 right in his insistence upon the constraining effect of war, but he 
 did not adequately measure the importance of other circumstances 
 that also curtail freedom. To mention one of recent occurrence, 
 when infantile paralysis became epidemic in 1916, hundreds of 
 American towns and cities established local quarantines. Guards 
 stationed on highways stopped and searched automobiles, and 
 suspicious parties were turned back. Furthermore, the social 
 pressure through which circumstantial pressure constrains is not 
 only political and legal and brought to bear by government; it 
 appears and develops also as a spontaneous pluralistic action, un- 
 organized at first but tending to become organized. For example, 
 the modes that it has assumed in money-raising drives are numer- 
 ous and many of them are highly coercive.
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 267 
 
 Society not only constrains its members, but also by disciplining 
 them and forcing them to conform to type it selects, conserving 
 some and rejecting others. 
 
 Biology unaided by sociology cannot show where, when, or how 
 the "better" may be the "fit" that survive. Darwin saw the prob- 
 lem and its solution, but he did not work it out. 1 
 
 Society favors individual units that have team-work value and 
 directs its adverse pressures upon units that obstruct or imperil 
 the collective struggle. 
 
 Tolerance, sympathy, and intelligence have team-work value in 
 a preeminent degree and, therefore, survival value in a preeminent 
 degree, in society. 
 
 Society, therefore, converts the "survival of the fit" into the 
 survival of the "better," if by the "fit" we mean individuals who 
 by organization and instinct are adapted to a situation as nature 
 has made it, and by "better" we mean individuals who by feeling 
 and intelligence are adapted to a situation modified and being 
 modified by combined effort guided by reflection. 
 
 How much the social community may achieve, transforming the 
 "fit" into the "better" and, in its pursuit of happiness, obtaining 
 substantial results, is a problem in the utilization of energy. 
 
 The strength, or potential energy, of a group is the product of 
 the number of individuals composing it, by various weighting 
 coefficients, among which are vigor, intelligence, and knowledge. 
 
 The working efficiency of a group of given strength is a func- 
 tion of certain arrangements which may have had an accidental 
 origin, which in part are products of a merely random experi- 
 mentation, but which in a large and always increasing measure 
 are brought about intentionally by superior individuals. 
 
 These arrangements are the social organization. 
 
 III. THE ORGANIZATION OF COLLECTIVE INTERESTS 2 
 9. PROTOCRACY 
 
 Not all individuals react to a given stimulation with equal 
 promptness, or completeness, or persistence. Therefore in every 
 
 1 The Descent of Man, chs. iii, iv, v. 
 
 2 Gustav Ratzenhofer and Albion W. Small, who has interpreted him 
 to the English-speaking public, have most fully discussed the general 
 aspects of "interests."
 
 268 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 situation there are individuals that react more effectively than 
 others do. They reinforce the original stimulation and play a 
 major part in interstimulation. They initiate and take respon- 
 sibility. They lead : they conduct experiments in a more or less 
 systematic fashion. 
 
 Those individuals that react most effectively command the 
 situation and create new situations to which other individuals must 
 adjust themselves. Few or many, the alert and effective are a 
 protocracy: a dominating plurel from which ruling classes are 
 derived. Protocracy is always with us. We let George do it, 
 and George to a greater or less extent "does" us. 
 
 Where two or three in quick or daring reaction are gathered 
 together to "start something" a dance or a revolution, or any- 
 thing between there is protocracy, and it gathers power if the 
 enterprise succeeds; for then protocracy recognizes or ignores, 
 gives out invitations or denies them, opens or bars opportunity, 
 protects or attacks, rewards or punishes, and so surrounds itself 
 with beneficiaries and retainers through which it works its will. 
 
 Protocracy may owe authority and power to the majority 
 that it dominates, but it has obtained them and it holds them 
 by psychological ascendancy. 1 The majority may withdraw au- 
 thority and power from a protocracy that it has trusted, but only 
 if another and rival protocracy arises and becomes ascendant. 
 
 Domination may amount to rule or it may not get beyond 
 leadership and direction. 
 
 Rule may be imposed and maintained by force, or by inspiring 
 fear, or through purchase, bribery, or bestowal of favors. The 
 protocracy has advanced knowledge of opportunities, and is in a 
 position to dispense offices and perquisites. If it does not actually 
 rule, it dominates by winning the uncoerced and unbought ap- 
 proval of the mass, often through a manifestation of ability, 
 integrity, or beneficent purpose. The methods of minority domi- 
 nation are commonly found in combination, but the proportions 
 are variable. 
 
 The concentration of controlling power in society is a function 
 (in the mathematician's sense of the word) of the behavioristic 
 
 'We owe to Edward Alsworth Ross the significant technical connota- 
 tions of this word in sociology.
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 269 
 
 solidarity. The more homogeneous the behavior and the greater 
 the like-mindedness, the broader is the basis of protocratic domi- 
 nation and the less autocratic is its authority. 
 
 The degree of domination and the extent and the rigor of con- 
 trol are functions of circumstantial pressure. 
 
 10. THE ORGANIZATION OF RELATIONS 
 
 The more or less definite arrangements of position and of 
 activity into which individuals fall in the collective struggle for 
 existence are shaped at first by a hit-or-miss trial of possibilities 
 that amounts to little more than a haphazard "fitting in." In 
 the long run they are shaped by a thought-out trial and correction 
 proposed and systematized by protocratic minorities. Ultimately, 
 after much experimenting and with frequent reconsideration, they 
 are approved by the social mind expressing its will through major- 
 ities. So arising and established, arrangements of individual 
 position and of individual activity are a mechanism through which 
 social reactions work aggressively, defensively, productively, and 
 with controlling incidence. 
 
 Described concretely, the social mechanism is a social com- 
 position, a product of integration; and a social constitution, a 
 product of differentiation. 
 
 The smallest and simplest arrangement of individuals by posi- 
 tion is the "bunch." It may be a genetic product, its units having 
 been born into proximity, or it may be a casual assemblage. A 
 relatively large bunch or a cluster of bunches, especially if identi- 
 fied with a place or region, is a group. 
 
 The smallest and simplest arrangement by activity of individuals 
 that go or work or play together is the "gang." It is a product of 
 like reaction by nervous mechanisms that are alike in a specific (or 
 differential) way. They have the same specific aptitude or 
 interest. 
 
 They are a "gang," however, only if, reacting to a common 
 stimulation or necessity, they "carry on" together. 
 
 Whether assembled or scattered, going in gangs or not, indi- 
 viduals of like aptitude and interest and therefore functioning in 
 like fashion are a class. As an observed fact, a class is usually 
 made up of both gangs and isolated individuals.
 
 270 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 In the creation of bunch or gang, of group or class, alert leader- 
 ship plays an essential part. In every group and in every class 
 there is a dominating protocracy. 
 
 By combination and recombination groups become the social 
 composition. 
 
 Sex mating and the birth of children create families. Numer- 
 ous families hold or drift together in residential relations ; others 
 drift apart. Those that hold together compose the horde (of 
 savage men) or the village (of civilized men). Hordes combine 
 in tribes, and tribes in tribal federations : the ethnic series. Vil- 
 lages grow into towns, and towns into cities. Towns or cities 
 compose provinces, departments, or commonwealths, and com- 
 monwealths hold together in federal nations : the demotic series. 
 
 Ethnic societies are genetic aggregations. Either a sacred 
 power or "mana" manifest in totem and regarded in taboo or a 
 real or a fictitious blood kinship is their chief social bond. They 
 are otherwise known as tribal societies and they include all com- 
 munities of uncivilized races which maintain a tribal organization. 
 They are of two general types, namely, the matronymic, or matri- 
 linear, in which names and relationships are traced in the mother- 
 line, and the patronymic, or patrilinear, in which names and 
 relationships are traced in the father-line. Demotic societies, 
 otherwise known as civil societies, are products in some degree of 
 genetic aggregation, but they are largely congregate associations. 
 They are groups of individuals that are bound together by habitual 
 intercourse, mutual interests, and cooperation. They emphasize 
 their mental and moral resemblance and give little heed to origins 
 or to genetic relationships. 
 
 The evolution of the social composition has been a double 
 process. As small groups have combined into larger ones, they 
 also have subdivided into smaller ones. The unit of composition 
 has become both smaller and more definite. 
 
 When small hordes combined to form tribes, they commonly 
 at the same time subdivided into polyandrian families. When 
 tribes, in their turn, banded together in confederations, the poly- 
 andrian household underwent changes which converted it into the 
 patriarchal kindred or compound family. Later on, when federa- 
 tions of tribes became the political state, the compound family
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 271 
 
 broke up into single families, each consisting of father and mother 
 and their immediate children, but no longer including, as in the 
 patriarchal kindred, married children and grandchildren. Each 
 family remained, however, an industrial unit, parents and children 
 earning livelihood together, and each in a large proportion of 
 states remained legally indissoluble. 
 
 Now, when political nations are combining into world-empires, 
 the single family, like its predecessors, has ceased to be an 
 industrial unit, and has nearly everywhere become legally dis- 
 soluble. More and more it depends for its integrity on unforced 
 personal choice. Human society is becoming humanity, and its 
 unit is no longer the legally indissoluble family but is the freely 
 choosing individual. 
 
 At every step in this long developmental process, three things 
 have happened. The dominant social group has entered as a com- 
 ponent into a larger social grouping. The smallest social group 
 has subdivided, thereby establishing a new social unit. The inter- 
 mediate social groups, losing their identity, have tended to atrophy 
 and in many instances have disappeared. 
 
 At every step in the evolution protocratic example or proposal 
 has incited or restrained and protocratic intelligence has directed. 
 
 Gangs and classes by multiplication and increasing interde- 
 pendence following upon increasing specialization become the 
 social constitution, a scheme of working or otherwise functioning 
 arrangements which makes a cross-classification with the resi- 
 dential arrangements of the social composition. Familiar exam- 
 ples of working arrangements become too dignified to be called 
 "gangs," except for purposes of scientific analysis (although that 
 is what in strict scientific analysis they are) and making number- 
 less cross-classifications with residential groupings are, business 
 partnerships and corporations, political parties, churches, philan- 
 thropic societies, schools, universities, and scientific associations, 
 social clubs, and societies for recreation and pleasure. 
 
 Each of these associations is obliged to exchange services or 
 products with others. It could not otherwise exist. The function- 
 ing of all of them in their several ways is the social (including the 
 economic) division of labor. Interdependence increases with 
 every new specialization in skill and in occupation. Because of
 
 272 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 their interdependence they are accurately described as constituent 
 societies. 
 
 Inasmuch as the constituent society has a defined object in 
 view it is purposive in character. Its members are supposed to be 
 aware of its object and to put forth effort for its attainment. 
 
 Purposive grouping, therefore, may be described as functional 
 association, and the mutual aid of purposive associations is not 
 limited to a mere increase of mass and power, as is the mutual aid 
 of component society. It is effected also through an advantageous 
 division of labor. 
 
 Psychologically the social constitution is an almost precise 
 opposite of the social composition. Component societies require 
 mental and moral like-mindedness, but within the limits of a 
 common morality there may be no insistence upon any one point 
 of similarity as long as the aggregate of resemblances remains 
 large and varied. Subject to these conditions, the differences 
 among the members of a component society may be of any imagi- 
 nable kind. The social constitution, on the contrary, is an alli- 
 ance, within each simple association, of individuals who in respect 
 of the purpose of the association must be mentally and morally 
 alike, but who in all other respects may be unlike ; supplemented, 
 in the relations of associations to one another and to integral 
 society, by toleration and by correlation of the unlike. 
 
 As the social constitution develops, the membership of con- 
 stituent societies falls into hierarchical arrangements, thereby 
 creating new complexities. Priests, bishops, archbishops, and 
 cardinals in the church ; teachers, principals, and superintendents 
 in the schools, are examples. In more technical words, through- 
 out the social constitution there may be observed superordination 
 (superiority of rank), coordination (equality of rank), and 
 subordination (inferiority of rank). The one word "coordina- 
 tion" is commonly used to designate the phenomena of subordina- 
 tion, coordination and superordination, in their totality. 
 
 Correlations and coordinations are products of relations of 
 units to one another and of modes of activity that are unchanging, 
 or nearly so. They are static phenomena of structure. But the 
 activities of social as of plant or animal units are not without
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 273 
 
 exception or always unchanging. There are adjustments and 
 adaptations in crises as well as in tranquil circumstances. 
 
 Activities of adaptation and of adjustment involve points of 
 contact (the neurons ramifying in a bit of muscle are a good 
 example) and actual contact. They involve lines of communica- 
 tion and arteries of transmission, and actual communications and 
 transmissions. They involve central or focal points of accumula- 
 tion and distribution, and actual centralizings and decentralizings, 
 storings, and distributions of materials and energies. 
 
 Corresponding to the morphological aspect of arrangements is 
 the functional aspect. Through accumulation and distribution, 
 through correlation and coordination, activities go on in an or- 
 derly and measured way. Even the increase and the decrease 
 of intensity, the enlargement or the diminution of volume, the 
 swifter or the slower rate, are facts of order and measure ; they 
 are facts of control. 
 
 When spontaneously formed relations and thought-out arrange- 
 ments devised by protocracy have become so well established that 
 they challenge the attention of all members of the community, 
 they become subjects of common discussion and of general ap- 
 proval or disapproval. Subjected then to analysis and criticism, 
 and finally by concurrent opinion pronounced good, evil, or doubt- 
 ful, they are thenceforth tolerated and their development is en- 
 couraged, or they are discouraged or even stamped out by a 
 concerted action more general than that which created them. 
 
 Described abstractly, therefore, the social mechanism is a 
 correlation and a coordination of socially reacting units. 
 
 Both as correlation and as coordination the social composition 
 and the social constitution develop with increasing necessity for 
 collective action. Under this necessity organization becomes more 
 extended and more hierarchical. 
 
 Yet mere intensity of the struggle for existence does not develop 
 complexity of organization as long as the struggle can be carried 
 on by individual effort or by small independent groups. Perhaps 
 nowhere in the world is the life of a population subsisting by agri- 
 culture harder than in China, yet the agricultural population there 
 is relatively unorganized. By individual effort, unremitting and
 
 274 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 intense, the individual applying himself to labor on the land has 
 been able to wrest from it a meager living. 
 
 Any social group, component or constituent, may be a privileged 
 and closed group, or a selectively open group, or an indiscrimi- 
 nately open group. 
 
 Eligibility to membership in a privileged and closed group is 
 governed by consideration of source. Descent from members of 
 the group in a former generation is one of the oldest and best- 
 known requirements. Membership in an antecedent group or 
 category may be the requirement: an example from modern 
 industry is the closed-shop requirement of membership in an 
 orthodox labor union. 
 
 Eligibility to membership in the selectively open group is 
 determined by the functioning value of members individually for 
 the functioning of the group collectively. 
 
 In the indiscriminately open group there are no eligibility tests. 
 
 Increasing circumstantial pressure substitutes closed or select- 
 ive groups for indiscriminately open groups ; a phenomenon which 
 always appears during war, in periods of religious enthusiasm, 
 and in times of industrial strife. 
 
 The social organization may become flexible while developing 
 strength and stability. When circumstantial pressure is not more 
 intense than it is in modern times in days of peace, the individual 
 can go freely from occupation to occupation. He can dissolve a 
 partnership and enter into another. He can be a director in one 
 and another corporation this year and in entirely different ones 
 next year. He can move freely from township to township, from 
 city to city, and from state to state. He can leave his church or 
 his political party at will. 
 
 Yet the social constitution does not suffer. The organization 
 that loses certain individuals from its membership gains others in 
 their place. Like organs of the living body, each is composed of 
 changing units, yet each maintains its integrity as a whole and per- 
 forms its function without interruption. 
 
 From this plasticity and mobility two great advantages arise. 
 Sooner or later individuals find the place where their maximum 
 efficiency as contributors to the social well-being is realized. And 
 at all times an increase of working force can be secured at any
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 275 
 
 point in the social system where the demand is exceptionally great, 
 by withdrawing units from points where the demand is for the 
 time being relatively small. 
 
 ii. THE ORGANIZATION OF ACTION 
 
 Woodworth's clarifying generalization that all the phenomena 
 of the individual mind may be assigned to one or the other of the 
 two categories, "mechanisms" and "drives," 1 is applicable also in 
 the psychology of society. The organization of social relations is 
 a mechanism, as has been shown. The organization of action is 
 a correlation and coordination of drives, and the product is a 
 procedure. Collective struggle tends to become an orderly pro- 
 cedure. 
 
 Wherever behavioristic groups are found, collective struggles 
 are seen to fall into one or the other of two series of drives. There 
 are conflicts of group with group, inter-group conflicts ; and within 
 each group there are conflicts of faction with faction, intra-group 
 conflicts. 
 
 Both component and composite groups hordes, tribes, towns, 
 and nations contend with one another for possession and control 
 of advantageous regions. From the moment that increasing popu- 
 lations begin to press upon food-producing resources, there is a 
 struggle for dominion and subsistence. Hungry populations 
 throw -off colonies, which go forth as invaders, to conquer ; the 
 invaded populations resist. 
 
 The major conflicts of inter-group struggle are foreign wars, 
 and these extend and consolidate the social composition. Success- 
 ful invaders, having conquered, annex lands and populations. 
 Threatened communities, especially if of one blood and speech, 
 combine by federation. 
 
 In peace and in war, gangs, including protocracies, contend 
 with one another for ascendancy and revenue. Under circum- 
 stantial pressure gangs of like kind and like function tend to con- 
 solidate, and thereby to become a class. In the struggle with 
 powers of earth and sky for safety and food, religious secret soci- 
 eties become a priesthood. In war, fraternities of braves become 
 an army and a military class. 
 
 1 Dynamic Psychology.
 
 276 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 With the rise of these two classes a succession of class struggles 
 begins. The shallowness of the Marxian philosophy of history is 
 in nothing more concretely shown that in its naive assumption of 
 the class struggle, as if the clash between capitalist and proletarian 
 were a phenomenon unique. The first class conflict is between 
 army and priesthood, and the army wins. In exchange for relig- 
 ious sanction military adventurers then 'let in" the priesthood and 
 create, by the combination, a landlord class to exploit free tenants 
 and serfs. Free tenants (some of them) become a merchant class, 
 and the next class struggle is between it and the landlords. The 
 merchants win, and in exchange for social recognition "let in" the 
 landlords. This new consolidation creates the capitalist class, to 
 make profits by organizing and employing the labor of emanci- 
 pated serfs. 
 
 The major intra-group conflicts, accordingly, are revolutions. 
 
 Conflicts among groups, including national groups, and con- 
 flicts between classes are the major phenomena of history. 
 
 In the drives of war and revolution protocratic rule broadens 
 into sovereignty: "the dominant human power, individual or 
 pluralistic, in a politically organized and politically independent 
 population." 1 Sovereignty is never under any circumstances the 
 absolute power to compel obedience babbled of in political meta- 
 physics. It is finite and conditioned. It is not even an indivisible 
 unit of power ; it is a composition of forces. The forces are vari- 
 able and their composition is variable. 
 
 A group in which protocratic rule has become sovereignty, and 
 which is independent to the extent that it is not subject .to the 
 sovereignty of any other group, is a state. Outside of the meta- 
 physical mind the state is never an abstraction. It is a politically 
 organized population, and altogether concrete. 
 
 Conflict between or among petty sovereignties creates the local 
 state ; conflict between or among local states creates the regional 
 state ; conflict between or among regional states creates the nation ; 
 conflict between or among nations creates the empire. 
 
 The local state is supreme until the regional state supersedes it. 
 The regional state is supreme until the nation supersedes it. The 
 nation is supreme until the empire supersedes it. 
 
 1 Giddings, The Responsible State, p. 50.
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 277 
 
 Individuals are not absolved from responsibility to the small 
 component groups to which they have belonged when they become 
 responsible also to large groups of which they are made members 
 through social integration; but responsibility to a large group 
 which, as a mutual benefit association, is relatively effective and 
 important, tends to override responsibility to its component lesser 
 groups and to constituent societies. 
 
 Nevertheless, individuals do not in a majority of instances give 
 highest allegiance to the largest organization that they might help 
 to form, and which may be thought of as in the making. There is, 
 therefore, a major number of instances of highest allegiance to the 
 largest existing aggregate. At the present time the largest existing 
 aggregates are nations, and more individuals give highest allegi- 
 ance to the nation than give it to the commonwealth, the province, 
 the city, the village, or the family, or to any hereditary caste or 
 rank, or to any social class, or than are yet prepared to give it to a 
 league of nations. 
 
 Sovereignty may be concentrated in an individual, a monarch, 
 or a dictator, or in a lesser degree concentrated in a class or in an 
 amorphous mass or majority, or it may be diffused throughout a 
 democracy. The degree of concentration is a function of the 
 social like-mindedness, more or less, and of the circumstantial 
 pressure. 
 
 The supreme will of a state (in whatever mode of sovereignty 
 manifested) expresses itself and achieves its end in various ways, 
 but chiefly through government, which may be defined as the 
 requisition, direction, and organization of obedience. It is the 
 most important and, all in all, most systematically ordered 
 procedure known to society. 
 
 The sovereign may govern directly or may delegate the function 
 of governing to authorized ministers or agents. Direct govern- 
 ment by the sovereign is necessarily an absolute rule. Indirect or 
 delegated government may be an absolute or a limited rule. Limi- 
 tations, however carefully embodied in written constitutions, are 
 actually observed only in those states whose populations are so 
 far like-minded that even their governmental activities are in 
 reality more like forms of spontaneous cooperation than like an 
 overruling direction. The real limitations are certain well-stabi-
 
 278 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 lized popular habits. Minorities bow to the will of a majority, 
 but in the understanding and on condition that they have liberty 
 by speech, publication, meeting, and all other peaceful and reason- 
 able ways of campaigning to increase their numbers and, if pos- 
 sible, become majorities. 
 
 The range and severity of government are determined by cir- 
 cumstantial pressure. 
 
 Sovereign power may act fitfully, unexpectedly, or at random; 
 or it may act methodically, after a declaration of purpose and 
 adhering to promulgated rules. Sovereign purpose formulated, 
 promulgated, and enforced is law, and governmental action within 
 the bounds of law is "due process of law." 
 
 Law is a form and a content. A large part of the content of 
 law is a body of rights. In large measure the basic substance of 
 legal (or positive ) rights is drawn from the "natural rights" of the 
 mores. 1 
 
 A further content of law is a more or less consistent and organ- 
 ized group of policies, becoming, as time goes on, a series of poli- 
 cies intended to assure and to further collective achievement. 
 
 First in time and in importance are policies of growth and 
 expansion, and of safeguarding against enemy attack or other 
 immediate calamity. When formulated and put into execution by 
 an absolute monarch bent upon perpetuating and extending the 
 rule of a dynasty or by an adventurer-despot or despotic group, 
 these policies become militarism, a rationalistic and quite cold- 
 blooded attempt to organize collective power for aggressive action 
 and to apply aggressive action relentlessly to the task of subjuga- 
 tion. Republics have to wage wars, but no republic, so called 
 or described by any one using words responsibly, has ever been 
 militaristic. 
 
 Mankind has not been able to enjoy peace by wishing it, ap- 
 proving it, or even by willing it or planning it. 
 
 The rise and the decline of militarism conform to the laws of 
 increasing and of diminishing return. For a time it may bring 
 in more than it costs; but a point is reached beyond whic'i the 
 costs increase faster than the returns. In the rivalry of nations 
 for territory, the lands available for annexation by any one of 
 
 1 See Giddings, ibid., ch. iii.
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 279 
 
 them become fewer in number and more difficult to obtain. The 
 frontier is extended, and its defense becomes more difficult and 
 more costly. The maintenance of armies of increasing size entails 
 a relative diminution of the industrial population available to sup- 
 port them. Nations vie with one another in perfecting the en- 
 ginery of war, and the cost of all military operations is thereby 
 increased. 1 
 
 Observe, however, that this argument applies only to militarism, 
 a rationalistic phenomenon. It does not hold true without quali- 
 fication of war merely as war. As individuals fight in sheer rage, 
 or in scorn of one another, or in resent of insult, so nations also 
 fight in fear and in hatred, in insolent contempt of one another, 
 and in vindication of their honor. Utilitarian considerations do 
 not apply to these tempests of wrath. 
 
 Successful war prepares the way for exploitation and stimulates 
 it. The annexation of territory, the creation of colonies, and the 
 establishment of dependencies bring lands and peoples hitherto 
 foreign into direct relations with the conquering nation. Exclusive 
 or preferential trade relations are established. Conquered people 
 may be enslaved, or compelled to toil as serfs, or as a nominally 
 free labor force be kept under strict subjection by economic or 
 other means. 
 
 Like militarism, exploitation is governed by the laws of increas- 
 ing and diminishing return. A point is found beyond which 
 slavery or any mode of enforced labor becomes unprofitable in 
 competition with free labor, and beyond which exclusiveness and 
 privilege in commercial relations provoke an increasingly costly 
 antagonism. Moreover, exploitive industry and commerce tend 
 to exhaust natural resources, and they are consistent with rela- 
 tively crude economic methods only. 
 
 In the most advanced modern civilization there is a partial 
 superseding of policies, both of subjugation and of exploitation, by 
 policies of assistance. Strong peoples extend educational advan- 
 tages, relief of acute distress, and to some extent economic oppor- 
 tunity to backward races and to dependent peoples. Great Britain 
 has performed this task and rendered this service on a vast scale 
 
 1 Compare William Graham Sumner, War and Other Essays and Earth 
 Plunger and Other Essays.
 
 280 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 and with a patience, common sense, and success that the world, 
 now envious, will one day recognize. America has fed a starving 
 Europe, and cared for her sick and injured, and helped to restore 
 her devastated areas. 
 
 Miscellaneous in character and of slow growth are policies of 
 conservation, development, and efficiency to prevent future want 
 or failure. Among these, policies of conservation of material 
 resources and of accumulation of material goods are fundamental. 
 They appear in a small way at the dawn of civilization in conser- 
 vation of water supply, in drainage and irrigation, but they de- 
 velop slowly and it is only in great modern nations and empires 
 that they are systematically organized. Yet more slowly grow 
 policies of conservation and efficiency of human resources and for 
 the prosperity of the population. These comprise policies of 
 sanitation, of education, and of economy, including (a) policies 
 primarily for property-owning classes, (&) policies primarily for 
 service-rendering classes, (c) policies primarily for the poor, the 
 unsuccessful, the relatively weak, and the unfortunate. 
 
 The execution of these policies may be undertaken by govern- 
 ment or committed to - private agencies subject to conditions and 
 limitations fixed by law. 
 
 It comes to pass, therefore, that governments and private 
 organizations in a measure duplicate each other's functions. The 
 actual distribution of functions between public and private agen- 
 cies is a varying one. It changes with changing circumstances, 
 that is to say, with the degree of like-mindedness and with circum- 
 stantial pressure. 
 
 Not only security and resources but also the composition of the 
 community, the equalities of its individual units, and their relations 
 to one another, to the several minor groups to which they belong, 
 and to the integral society, are factors of effectiveness. To con- 
 trol these and to improve them, policies of selection, of unification 
 and standardization, of liberty, and of equality are devised and 
 tried. 
 
 Policies of unification and standardization include attempts to 
 standardize and unify language, religion, behavior, opinion, com- 
 munication, education, business, law, politics. They aim to per- 
 fect the behavioristic solidarity of the group. Assimilation is
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 281 
 
 watched with concern. Laws are enacted or edicts are promul- 
 gated to hasten on the change. One language must be spoken 
 throughout the community. One religious faith must be embraced 
 by all. One consistent economic policy must be followed. One 
 standard of conduct and of legality must be established for all 
 citizens. Within the voluntary organization, a religious denomi- 
 nation, for example, or a trade union or a political party, an at- 
 tempt is made to persuade or to compel all members to believe the 
 same thing and to conduct themselves in like manner. A creed, 
 a body of rules, or a platform is imposed. An orthodoxy or regu- 
 larity is insisted upon as a primary obligation. 
 
 The extent to which these policies are pushed is determined by 
 circumstantial pressure. 
 
 Policies of liberty are reactions against the restraints, amount- 
 ing often to intolerable coercion, of excessive unification. They 
 aim at a toleration of variety, of individual initiative, of freedom 
 of thought, speech, and conduct. They take legal form in bills of 
 rights and constitutional guaranties of liberty. 
 
 Policies of equality are reactions against the abuse of liberty 
 by men and parties that take advantage of their freedom to curtail 
 the opportunities of their fellows and to exploit them. They aim 
 to establish an equality of liberty and, as far as possible, of oppor- 
 tunity. They include the establishment of political equality 
 through universal suffrage, equal standing before the law, the 
 abolition of state-created privileges in the realm of economic 
 interests, equality of educational opportunity, and measures for 
 the protection of the weak, particularly women and children, in 
 the economic struggle. 
 
 Not only do policies of security, conservation, selection, and 
 standardization start reactions toward liberty, and policies of 
 liberty provoke reactions toward equality; but also the process 
 reverses: experiments in equality provoke reactions toward lib- 
 erty, and experiments in liberty provoke reactions toward unifica- 
 tion and selection. 
 
 The static state of perfect adjustment and consequent equi- 
 librium is unattainable because of an inherent contradiction be- 
 tween personal or subjective equality and objective or social 
 equality. The conditions that tend to create subjective inequality
 
 282 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 tend to establish objective equality, and, conversely, the creation 
 of objective equality tends to increase subjective inequality. 
 Therefore social evolution, like organic evolution, creates increas- 
 ing inequality of personality. At the same time, however, it 
 creates increasingly large classes of individuals that as persons are 
 substantially equal within the same class. 
 
 "Social justice," as the term is popularly understood, comprises 
 an equalization of both rights and opportunities. Justice in a 
 larger sense of the word comprises all adjustments of social fac- 
 tors: individuals' interests, relations and actions to one another 
 and to the social whole. It includes, as those who have defined it 
 in the main agree, the definition and enforcement of rights, the 
 redress of injuries, the maintenance of sanctions, the equalization 
 of rights and opportunities, the adjustment of rewards to per- 
 formances; but it includes also much more and the "more" is 
 immeasurably delicate and difficult. It consists in unceasing read- 
 justment. 
 
 Readjustment is made necessary by ceaseless changings of cir- 
 cumstance and by continuing change in demotic composition and 
 in pluralistic behavior. The social population fluctuates about a 
 kind or type. Behavior fluctuates about a mode or norm. The 
 range of variation at one time is narrow; at another time it is 
 wide. 
 
 Policies of selection, unification, and equilibration recognize 
 and sanction modalities. Policies of liberty recognize and sanc- 
 tion variation. Readjustments change the range of permissible 
 variation. 
 
 Therefore justice in its highest and most delicate development 
 is a ceaselessly changing adjustment of equalities and modalities 
 to immunities and liberties, and of immunities and liberties to 
 modalities and equalities. 
 
 No arrangement of finite affairs is finally and forever just. 
 
 Through its policies and its readjustments of policy organized 
 society in a measure controls variation about its own modes. It 
 exercises self-control.
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 283 
 
 12. ORGANIZED SOCIETY 
 
 The reaction of social organization upon the interplay of like- 
 and unlike-mindedness and upon the consciousness of kind re- 
 shapes the social mind, as Cooley * has contended. 
 
 The process is experimental, and highly concrete. Unorganized 
 pluralistic reactions are simple and direct in form. Human energy 
 explodes in trial and error. But turmoil and riot, like the hit-or- 
 miss assaults of an untrained fighter, are wasteful expenditures. 
 If, however, the flow of energy keeps up, it finds points of low 
 resistance and begins to follow channels that branch and cross. 
 Social organization, like the individual nervous system, correlates 
 and coordinates these branchings and crossings, and more and 
 more diverts energy into them. Thereby it transforms much 
 direct and simple action into indirect and complex action. 
 
 The transformation normally goes so far that direct pluralistic 
 action becomes subordinate to indirect action, as instinct in the 
 individual mind normally becomes subordinate to reason. General 
 strikes and revolutionary violence give way to constructive policies 
 and to due process of law. Direct action is primitive, and un- 
 subordinated direct action is uncivilized. 
 
 Yet this evolution can begin and continue only if there is direct 
 action (crude pluralistic reaction to stimulus) to transform; and 
 only if the inequalities and diversities of reaction that are neces- 
 sary for differentiation, and so for any organization whatsoever, 
 are normally subject to a dominating like-mindedness in matters 
 of major importance. This proposition is perhaps less obtrusively 
 true of the economic division of labor that Adam Smith ex- 
 pounded than it is of the "division of social labor" that Durk- 
 heim 2 expounded ; but it is demonstrably true of both. 
 
 Adam Smith apparently never saw the true relation of The 
 Wealth of Nations to The Theory of Moral Sentiments, although 
 he was looking directly at it all his days. When in The Wealth of 
 Nations he had demonstrated that an increase of wealth is made 
 possible by division of labor, that the division of labor is limited 
 by the extent of the market, and that extent of the market is 
 extent of demand, he did not then by resolving extended demand 
 
 1 Charles Horton Cooley, Social Organisation. 
 'Emile Durkheim, De la Division du Travail social.
 
 284 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 into pluralistic demand discover its identity with like-mindedness, 
 of which, without so naming it, he had discoursed in The Theory 
 of Moral Sentiments. Therefore he did not appreciate, he prob- 
 ably did not quite see, the broad social fact that the differentiation 
 of productive effort is limited by the extent of like-mindedness in 
 respect of consumption. 
 
 As for the larger division of social labor, a population that is 
 not prevailingly like-minded is collectively ineffective (and usually 
 chaotic) or it is ruled and organized by the strong arm. Only like- 
 minded communities are capable of democratic self-government, 
 and only the like-mindedness that is enlightened and deliberative 
 can create and maintain a liberal democracy. Proof is superabun- 
 dant. Mexico is the great modern example. Without a meeting 
 of minds on large and fundamental issues Mexico submitted to 
 order and made material progress under the despotism of Diaz, 
 only to fall into a chaos of conspiracies when despotic rule ended. 
 
 As a mechanism organized society is good or bad. A good 
 machine is coherent and elastic to pressure. An organic machine 
 namely, a plant, an animal, or a man is also adaptable to crisis 
 or change. Man has succeeded in making machines adaptable in 
 a small way; the clock with a pendulum, the turbine and the 
 steam engine equipped with automatic cut-off to control the feed 
 of water or of steam, are familiar examples ; but he has not yet 
 made a machine comparable in adaptability to a living organism 
 or to a society. Adaptability turns upon the variability of units ; 
 cohesion upon the typicalness, uniformity, or standardization of 
 units. Anarchism, or lawless individualism, is excessive variabil- 
 ity and non-cohesion. Socialism is excessive standardization and 
 deficient adaptability. Individualism is theoretically a working 
 combination of enough like-mindedness for collective effectiveness* 
 with enough unlike-mindedness for organization and progress. 
 Theoretically, therefore, individualism at its best is the best social 
 system because, more adequately than any other, it combines 
 cohesion, elasticity, and variability ; but individualism at its worst 
 may be as bad as anarchism which is anti-social. Socialism is a 
 revolt against anti-social individualism. Socialistic policies may 
 be expedient as restraints of anti-social conduct and to supplement
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 285 
 
 private cooperation ; but on the whole and in the long run they are 
 justified only to the extent that they develop a social individualism. 
 
 IV. THE ACHIEVEMENTS OF ORGANIZED ENDEAVOR 
 13. AMELIORATION 
 
 The immediate business of organized endeavor is to mitigate 
 the struggle for existence in a large way and effectively and to 
 make life worth while. Its ulterior business and supreme function 
 are to develop human personality. 
 
 Organized endeavor mitigates the struggle for existence by 
 accumulating knowledge, amassing capital, and conducting gov- 
 ernment. By means of these activities and achievements life is 
 made relatively secure, comfortable, and satisfying. 
 
 The accumulation of knowledge has been the work of unnum- 
 bered generations tirelessly groping and exploring through ages 
 measured presumably by millions rather than by thousands of 
 years, as the world once thought. No argument is necessary to 
 prove that without society and organized endeavor the achieve- 
 ment of knowledge would have been impossible. Folkways, folk- 
 lore, and tradition have been necessary. Education has been 
 necessary. Organized investigation, writing, printing, libraries, 
 and laboratories have been necessary. 
 
 Without society the capital acquired by man could not have 
 exceeded the bees' store of honey, the beavers' dam, the apes' club, 
 the savages' chipped flint. There could have been no agriculture, 
 no domesticated animals, no exchangeable goods, and no money. 
 Without organized endeavor there could have been no mechan- 
 isms, no boats, no roads, no mines, no mills, no banks. 
 
 Without multiple and differentiated societies and organized 
 endeavor on a big scale there could have been no governments; 
 for among them all there is not one that is not a product of foreign 
 wars. and domestic revolutions. 
 
 Knowledge, capital, and government are necessary for security 
 against armed enemies, against tempest and flood and fire, against 
 pestilence, against famine and pitiless cold. They are necessary 
 to establish equity by balancing equality against liberty. They are
 
 286 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 necessary to expand and to clarify thought and to diminish fear. 1 
 Organized endeavor has achieved these things ; it has progres- 
 sively ameliorated the human lot. 
 
 14. MUTATION AND VARIATION 
 
 Variant organisms are relatively unstable: they are relatively 
 frail, and they perish more easily than do their kindred competi- 
 tors that more closely conform to type. All depends, therefore, on 
 the severity of the struggle. Whatever mitigates the struggle 
 multiplies the survival chances of variants that may develop a high 
 degree of individuality. It is because the social organization of 
 endeavor has ameliorated the life of man that the human race is 
 above all other species variable and adaptable ; capable of extraor- 
 dinary differentiation of aptitude and able to meet crises with 
 amazing skill. This is not the result of any physical transmission 
 of acquired traits. It is, as far as we can see, altogether a conse- 
 quence of the social mitigation of natural selection. Protected and 
 sustained by society, frail and unstable individuals, cranks and 
 oddities, crooks and martyrs, idiots and geniuses, who would 
 miserably perish in a "state of nature," survive and pass on their 
 qualities in Mendelian distributions. The problem of disposing 
 of the crooks and the idiots, or of enduring them, is the price we 
 have to pay for the geniuses and their contributions to our joy. 
 
 The study of human variation in its sociological aspect is a 
 statistical investigation. 
 
 There is a range of structural and physiological adequacy be- 
 tween extremes of defect or deformity and of completeness or 
 balance. Vitality as measured by energy, health, fecundity, and 
 longevity ranges from relatively low to relatively high extremes. 
 Mentality ranges from idiocy to genius, and character from de- 
 pravity to magnanimity. 
 
 Hardship and a standardizing social pressure, elastic to an 
 increasing circumstantial pressure, shorten all these ranges. Ame- 
 lioration and increasing freedom (intellectual, moral, and politi- 
 cal) lengthen them. 
 
 Organized endeavor can always shorten these ranges, and the 
 
 1 Lester Frank Ward's Dynamic Sociology remains the most compre- 
 hensive study of this field.
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 287 
 
 temptation to do so is great because stupidity and wickedness 
 annoy us and often anger us, an easy thing to do, while the value 
 of genius we can neither see nor weigh unless we can think (not 
 everybody can) and will take the trouble to think (most of us 
 won't) . Probably in no other enterprise has human wisdom made 
 so sorry an exhibition of itself as in its attempts to standardize 
 thought and morals. 
 
 15. SOCIALIZATION 
 
 Remembering that with conscious intent and by unconsciously 
 exerted pressure society eliminates much human material that 
 proves to be unfit for social life, we clarify the idea of socializa- 
 tion : a phenomenon of discipline and education, brought to bear 
 upon the socially possible. Socialization is the opposite of muta- 
 tion and supplementary variation. It is an aggregate of acquisi- 
 tions, in distinction from native traits. It cannot be transmitted 
 through heredity, but by teaching it can be handed on with com- 
 pounding interest from generation to generation. 
 
 The socialized members of organized society "play the game" ; 
 the non-socialized survivors from savagery and interlopers from 
 barbarism do not. The socialized are tolerant and regardful of 
 the rights (natural and legal) of their fellowmen; they are by 
 habit helpful; they value and observe manners; and they can 
 cooperate. 
 
 The zero point of socialization is criminality, that degree of 
 departure from prevailing and approved behavior which the com- 
 munity by process of law and with relative severity punishes. 
 
 If the range of socialization from zero up be divided into four 
 parts or grade quarters, we get the following distribution of habits 
 and persons: 
 
 In the lowest grade quarter are the predatory, aggressors upon 
 person and property, law-breakers. 
 
 In the second grade quarter (counting from the lowest up) are 
 the intentionally or willingly dependent, wholly or in part; the 
 self-seeking, intent on getting more than they give; the incon- 
 siderate and irresponsible. 
 
 In the third grade quarter are the dependable, the helpful, the 
 considerate, and the responsible, who are also type-conforming, 
 conventional, uninventive, and non-innovating.
 
 288 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 In the fourth and highest quarter are the dependable and the 
 helpful who are mindful of the value of social usage but are also 
 independent in thought, courageous, willing to experiment, but 
 cautiously, and with full responsibility for results. 
 
 This distribution into quarters is artificial, but it makes obser- 
 vation and recording possible. With competent assistance I have 
 obtained observations of 1,888 individuals comprised in 428 
 families and all personally known by the observers. The distri- 
 bution by socialization is : 
 
 Grade Quarter Number of Individuals 
 
 I 52 
 
 II 317 
 
 III 1044 
 
 IV 475 
 
 16. INDIVIDUATION 
 
 Original nature (inherited traits, variations) and acquired 
 nature (habits, socialization) are mingled, perhaps blended, in 
 individuation. 
 
 Individuation begins in the chromatin and proceeds through 
 Mendelian combinations of units. Probably no individual is an 
 exact duplicate of another, and inasmuch as the life-circumstances 
 of each living body are different in a great or a small degree from 
 those of every other body, life would soon cease if there were no 
 organic variability. And inasmuch as the life-circumstances of 
 each individual are in a degree peculiar (in other words, the 
 stimuli that play upon each individual are in a degree peculiar), 
 the behavior of each individual is differential. Among these 
 stimuli in the experience of the human race are social influences 
 and among the reactions are socialization. So by instinct in like 
 measure with lower animals and by habit in amazing measure 
 surpassing the experience of any other species, mankind is in- 
 dividuated. 
 
 The range of individuation is upward from a zero point at 
 instinct little above the animal level. Dividing it into grade 
 quarters we get the following distribution of original and acquired 
 traits, and of persons :
 
 PLURALISTIC BEHAVIOR 289 
 
 In the lowest quarter : instincts strong and not much controlled ; 
 sympathy deficient or narrow in range; cruel (when cruelty is 
 manifested) in an unfeeling and brutal rather than in a deliberate 
 and ingenious way ; tastes low and crude ; ideas elementary, primi- 
 tive, and limited in number and in range. 
 
 In the second quarter (counting from the lowest up) : motor 
 impulses variable in strength; instincts infused with abundant 
 emotion, variable from grave to gay ; sympathy quick but super- 
 ficial and unstable ; imaginative but without sufficient intellectual 
 power to be creative in literature or in art beyond the simpler 
 products; without strong convictions or a controlling sense of 
 responsibility; ideas relatively abundant and varied but only 
 loosely organized. 
 
 In the third quarter : motor impulses of any degree of strength 
 from weak to violent ; instincts and passions strong, but controlled 
 by convictions ; emotion strong, blended with beliefs, and partisan ; 
 convictions tenacious, and a dominant factor in mental processes 
 'and in behavior; may be ruthless and cruel under influence of 
 fanaticism; intolerant of doubt, impatient of hesitation, scornful 
 of weakness. 
 
 In the fourth and highest quarter: motor impulses, instincts, 
 and passions of any degree from weak to very strong ; emotions 
 abundant and varied, may or may not be well controlled; beliefs 
 subject to review and modification; ideas abundant and organized ; 
 open-minded, of investigating turn, insistent upon .evidence; 
 judicially critical rather than fault-finding or denunciatory; may 
 make discoveries ; may be inventive or creative. 
 
 With assistance I have obtained observations of 1,536 indi- 
 viduals comprised in 294 families and personally known by the 
 observers. The distribution by individuation is : * 
 
 Grade Quarter Number of Individuals 
 
 I 82 
 
 II 334 
 
 III 763 
 
 IV 357 
 
 *Cf. Giddings, "A Provisional Distribution of the Population of the 
 United States into Psychological Classes," The Psychological Review, Vol. 
 VIII, No. 4, July, 1901.
 
 2QO STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 In the degree that a human being is individuated he has per- 
 sonality, he is a person. 
 
 A person is unique but also social. In a million ways like other 
 persons, he is in many ways unlike any other that lives or that 
 ever has lived. Conforming to type in much, he also significantly 
 varies from type, and variability within race limits there must be, 
 if personality is to develop. Furthermore, the variant must sur- 
 vive and hand on his race. In this necessity lie all the possibilities 
 of achievement and of tragedy.
 
 CHAPTER XVI 
 
 FURTHER INQUIRIES OF SOCIOLOGY 
 
 IN the same large sense in which economics is the science of the 
 production and distribution of wealth, for man, sociology is the 
 science of the production and distribution of adequacy, of man 
 and in man. Economics tells us Bow, as far as it is possible, we 
 can get the things that we desire to have; sociology tells us how, 
 as far as it is possible, we can become what we desire to be. It 
 tells us by what gropings and fumblings, through what relations 
 with one another, and through what experiments in mutual aid 
 mankind has acquired power to survive under varied and changing 
 conditions, power to achieve, and capacity for happiness. Ade- 
 quacy comprises endurance, health, reproductive vigor, intelli- 
 gence, self control, ability to make adjustments with others and to 
 get on helpfully with others in cooperation. Society produces 
 these factors of adequacy in the same sense in which the breeder 
 produces desired qualities in animals, namely, by selecting them 
 and providing the conditions under which they can survive. The 
 practical manifestations of adequacy are: individual initiative, 
 individual responsibility, and an individual participation that is 
 efficient and helpful in collective endeavor. 
 
 It will not surprise my co-workers in sociology that I as an 
 individual so conceive of our science, because in all my writings 
 for twenty-five years I have insisted, perhaps tiresomely, that 
 society is comprehensible only if we know what it does, and that 
 what it does is to convert a biologicaf survival of the fit for the 
 jungle into a historical survival of the better for human purposes. 
 In other words, as I argued in The Principles of Sociology and 
 have since maintained, the function of society is to develop and to 
 safeguard the higher types of human personality. 
 
 If I can be said to have a system of sociology it is briefly this : 
 
 I. A situation or stimulus is reacted to by more than one indi- 
 
 291
 
 292 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 vidual ; there is pluralistic as well as singularistic behavior. Plu- 
 ralistic behavior develops into rivalries, competitions, and con- 
 flicts, and also, into agreements, contracts, and collective enter- 
 prises. Therefore social phenomena are products of two varia- 
 bles, namely, situation (in the psychologist's definition of the 
 word) and pluralistic behavior. 
 
 2. When the individuals who participate in pluralistic behavior 
 have become differentiated into behavioristic kinds or types, a con- 
 sciousness of kind, liking or disliking, approving or disapproving 
 one kind after another, converts gregariousness into a consciously 
 discriminative association, herd habit into society ; and society, by 
 a social pressure which sometimes is conscious but more often, 
 perhaps, is unconscious, makes life relatively hard for kinds of 
 character and conduct that are disapproved. 
 
 3. Society organizes itself for collective endeavor and achieve- 
 ment, if fundamental similarities of behavior and an awareness of 
 them are extensive enough to maintain social cohesion, while dif- 
 ferences of behavior and awareness of them in matters of detail 
 are sufficient to create a division of labor. 
 
 4. In the long run organized society by its approvals and dis- 
 approvals, its pressures and achievements, selects and perpetuates 
 the types of mind and character that are relatively intelligent, 
 tolerant, and helpful, that exhibit initiative, that bear their share 
 of responsibility and that effectively play their part in collective 
 enterprise. It selects and perpetuates the adequate. 
 
 This, I think, is an intelligible and rather straightforward way 
 of explaining society. But society is the most intricate tangle of 
 happenings and relationships that the scientific mind can investi- 
 gate. It can be approached in many ways. It has been described 
 in many formulas, not obviously identical. It is, therefore, quite 
 in order to ask whether the definition of sociology that I have 
 submitted is anything more than a personal reaction. Can it be 
 found elsewhere ? Are other definitions substantially identical, or 
 at least consistent, with it? 
 
 I am glad to answer this question, or, rather, to bring forward 
 an answer that other men have made. It is interesting and inspir- 
 ing. Without explicitly telling us so the founders of sociology 
 have, in fact, it would seem, without exception conceived of the
 
 FURTHER INQUIRIES OF SOCIOLOGY 293 
 
 science of society as a systematic study of the increase and dis- 
 tribution of human adequacy to exist and achieve. 
 
 How otherwise can we interpret Comte's major contention that 
 social dynamics is an account of the advance, or progress, that 
 mankind has made from theological through metaphysical to posi- 
 tive thinking, and that positive thinking has put him in command 
 of his destiny? How otherwise can we interpret Spencer's in- 
 sistence that mankind has begun to go right after having tried all 
 the possible ways of going wrong, chief of which has been mili- 
 tarism, which has selected authority-revering types of character; 
 and that only under a voluntaristic, cooperative industrialism, 
 which selects peace-loving and self-reliant natures, can our race 
 become humane ; inasmuch as, until then, we shall not be able to 
 educe golden conduct from leaden human natures. Certainly no 
 other interpretation can be put upon Lester F. Ward's Dynamic 
 Sociology as it is expounded in the volumes bearing that title and 
 in later writings. Its thesis is that society not only grows but also 
 is made, consciously and for a purpose. It is a product of telic 
 effort. And to what end is it made ? What is the purpose ? I do 
 not know that Ward anywhere uses the word, but he unmistak- 
 ably identifies and describes the thing ; society is made to the end 
 that it may produce human adequacy, and, above all, increase the 
 ratio of adequate individuals to the inadequate. Therefore, he 
 contends, it is the supreme duty of society to disseminate existing 
 knowledge and to educate everybody. Finally (and I say finally 
 because I limit my survey to four writers, one French, one Eng- 
 lish, and two American who are no longer living), no other in- 
 terpretation can be put upon the teaching of William Graham 
 Sumner whom, now that he is gone, we are beginning to recognize 
 as perhaps the most consistently sociological if not the greatest of 
 sociologists. In folkways Sumner finds the most characteristic of 
 social reactions and products. They are the primary mechanism 
 of pluralistic control and adjustment. The state is a secondary 
 and far more artificial mechanism. The folkways mediate be- 
 tween individual impulse and the conditions to which life must 
 adapt itself. They discipline the individual and hold him to his 
 obligations. He in turn reacts upon them by innovating experi- 
 ment and occasional rebellion. Products of trial and error, by trial
 
 294 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 and error they are changed. In such ceaseless conflict between 
 individual impulse and pluralistic habit individual adequacy dis- 
 covers itself and is discovered. It is tried and tempered. The 
 unsuccessful innovator is eliminated. His idea may have been 
 true and valuable but "untimely born" or ineffectively presented. 
 The successful innovator survives, and with him adequacy. 
 
 If, looking further, we could compare all known systems of 
 sociology, we should discover, I am confident, that their funda- 
 mental agreement lies precisely in this matter, namely, that, like 
 their ancient prototypes The Republic of Plato and The Politics of 
 Aristotle, they view society as functioning to produce human 
 adequacy. Their disagreements arise out of their differing as- 
 sumptions as to means or method. Systems that have taken for 
 granted a Lamarkian biology have laid emphasis on environment 
 and education. Systems that have anticipated or accepted a later 
 biology (built upon facts of mutation and predictable heredity) 
 lay emphasis on a social selection that is continuous with natural 
 selection and supplementary to it. At the present moment sociol- 
 ogy like psychology is quietly abandoning errors that it took over 
 from a biology now discredited. We are beginning to discriminate 
 between heredity, a physiological transmission of traits to off- 
 spring, and heritage, a sum total of knowledge, pattern, technique, 
 and property handed on by teaching and surrender, and we shall 
 cease to confuse habits, which each generation must acquire, with 
 original or instinctive nature which is the equipment that we are 
 born with. Having made these corrections, in our thinking we 
 shall probably stop kicking against the pricks, forget that we once 
 believed in the inheritance of acquired traits, and no longer feel 
 obliged to deny that character and intelligence are facts of original 
 nature, while behavior and knowledge are facts of habit. Charac- 
 ter cannot fundamentally be made over after birth any more than 
 bodily constitution can be, but behavior, including moral conduct, 
 can be improved until old age just as health can be. Intelligence 
 regarded as mental power cannot be increased after birth, but its 
 functioning can be speeded up and knowledge can be increased 
 indefinitely. 
 
 These elementary teachings of the new biology to which sociol- 
 ogy will have to adapt itself, if it has not already done so, throw a
 
 FURTHER INQUIRIES OF SOCIOLOGY 295 
 
 clear light upon adequacy. Plainly we now see, adequacy is partly 
 a fact of original nature or equipment ; that is to say, it is partly 
 a fact of ability; but also, it is partly a fact of acquisition or 
 habit ; that is to say, it is partly a fact of morale. 
 
 In so factorizing adequacy we have, I now suggest, the starting- 
 point from which certain further inquiries in sociology apparently 
 should and probably will proceed. They will explore possibility, 
 asking how and how far civilized communities now existing can 
 discover, select and develop adequacy in human beings ; as group 
 dwellers to participate in the opportunities, obligations and enter- 
 prises of society, and as individuals to profit by them. In my own 
 mind these further inquiries take form and arrangement somewhat 
 like this : 
 
 1. What regional and circumstantial influences antecedent to 
 society select, as elements of a local or a regional population, 
 individuals and stocks (i) superior in point of ability, (2) medi- 
 ocre, (3) inferior. 
 
 2. What circumstances and pluralistic reactions (including dis- 
 ciplines and selections, an inclusion which is to be understood 
 wherever the word "reactions" appears in these paragraphs) 
 develop (i) preference, (2) aptitude for (a) rural life, (b) vil- 
 lage or small town life, (c) the intense life of congested urban 
 areas ? 
 
 3. What circumstances and reactions (i) prevent or hinder 
 the amalgamation of differing stocks in a local or a regional popu- 
 lation, (2) facilitate indiscriminate amalgamation, (3) facilitate 
 a selective amalgamation? 
 
 4. What circumstances and reactions develop (i) preference, 
 (2) aptitude for (a) rivalistic and competitive behavior, (b) co- 
 operative behavior ? 
 
 5. What circumstances and reactions, when inequalities of 
 promptness, persistence and effectiveness are increasing, develop 
 admiration for intellect and strengthen a disposition to trust in- 
 tellectual ability? 
 
 6. What circumstances and reactions increase sensitiveness to 
 interstimulation, and develop orderliness (of sequence, correla- 
 tion, and coordination) of response to it? 
 
 7. What circumstances and reactions increase sensitiveness to
 
 296 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 behavioristic differences and resemblances among individuals, 
 among groups, among stocks, and so develop the consciousness of 
 kind? 
 
 8. What circumstances and reactions inhibit the inferior modes 
 of concerted volition, restraining a disposition to rely on coercive 
 direct action taking form, for example, in the boycott and the 
 strike, in slacking, in property-destroying sabotage, in bullying 
 or intimidation, or in physical violence, for attaining desired ends ? 
 What circumstances and reactions develop deliberative like-mind- 
 edness ? 
 
 9. What circumstances and reactions strengthen a disposition 
 to rely on religion, education, folkways and mores more than on 
 law and government to improve human behavior ? 
 
 10. What circumstances and reactions strengthen a disposition 
 to standardize behavior and to require conformity to standards 
 and types? Conversely, what circumstances and reactions 
 strengthen a love of liberty and a disposition to extend it ? 
 
 11. What circumstances and reactions strengthen minority rule 
 ( i ) established and maintained by the use of force, or by inspir- 
 ing fear, or through protection, purchase, bribery, or bestowal of 
 favors; (2) established and maintained by winning and holding- 
 the uncoerced and unbought approval of the majority through 
 proof of ability, character and beneficent purpose? 
 
 12. What circumstances and reactions develop a predilection 
 for (i) strictly monogamic relations of the sexes; (2) relations 
 usually monogamic but with toleration or approval of (a) excep- 
 tions, (b) divorce; (3) relations of any individually preferred 
 degree of simplicity, complexity, or variety, and of duration de- 
 termined by private agreement; (4) large families, unlimited by 
 birth control; (5) families large or small or unions childless, as 
 determined by birth control ; (6) families (or children reared by 
 other than parental care) that are products of eugenic experimen- 
 tation ? 
 
 13. What circumstances and reactions develop a stronger at- 
 tachment and loyalty to a local or a minor regional group (hamlet, 
 village, small town, large town, or city, or province) than to a 
 major regional group (nation or empire) ? Conversely, what 
 circumstances and reactions develop a stronger attachment and
 
 FURTHER INQUIRIES OF SOCIOLOGY 297 
 
 loyalty to a major regional group than to any minor regional or 
 local group? 
 
 14. What circumstances and reactions develop stronger attach- 
 ments and loyalties to the town, the nation, or the empire than 
 to occupational and class organizations? Conversely, what cir- 
 cumstances and reactions develop stronger attachments and loy- 
 alties to occupational and class organizations than to the empire, 
 the nation or the town ? 
 
 15. What circumstances and reactions develop a predilection 
 for authoritative types of organization? Conversely what cir- 
 cumstances and reactions develop a predilection for free types of 
 organization ? 
 
 16. What circumstances and reactions develop a predilection 
 for (i) closed organization, from which non-privileged individ- 
 uals (e. g. persons not of a designated lineage, or birthplace, or 
 not of a stipulated fortune) are excluded; (2) indiscriminately 
 open organization (e. g. "the open shop") ; (3) selectively closed 
 or open organization (e. g. the church in which assent to a creed 
 is demanded, the closed shop, the trade union) ? 
 
 17. What circumstances and reactions develop a predilection 
 for militarism? Conversely, what circumstances and reactions 
 strengthen antagonism to militarism? 
 
 18. What circumstances and reactions develop a predilection 
 for communism? Conversely, what circumstances and reactions 
 develop a predilection for individualism ? 
 
 19. What circumstances and reactions develop a predilection 
 for (i) democratic society, (2) the democratic state? 
 
 20. What circumstances and reactions strengthen a predilection 
 to conserve resources and to accumulate surplus? Conversely, 
 what circumstances and reactions strengthen a predilection to 
 squander and waste ? 
 
 21. What circumstances and reactions (i) increase (a) non- 
 hereditary variability, (b) hereditary variability; (2) diminish 
 (a) non-hereditary variability, (b) hereditary variability? 
 
 22. What circumstances and reactions by discipline improve 
 the morale of an increasing proportion of the population? 
 
 23. What circumstances and reactions impair morale, and if 
 persistent destroy it?
 
 298 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY 
 
 24. What circumstances and reactions acting selectively in- 
 crease (i) the absolute number, (2) the relative number, (3) both 
 the absolute and the relative number of able men and women in 
 the community, a standard of ability being taken, and the limits 
 of the community being defined? 
 
 25. What circumstances and reactions ( I ) both increase ability 
 and improve morale, (2) both diminish ability and impair morale? 
 
 26. Are the reactions of ability upon, pluralistic behavior (a) 
 more profound, (b) more dependable and enduring, than the 
 reactions of morale? 
 
 27. What are the reactions upon pluralistic behavior of im- 
 proved morale when there is no increase of ability? 
 
 28. What are the reactions upon pluralistic behavior of more 
 ability, when morale is not improved ? 
 
 29. How does the relative numerical increase of adequate men 
 and women react upon the drives, the mechanisms, and the 
 achievements of collective endeavor? 
 
 30. What measures of the phenomena that have been designated 
 in these paragraphs can be found or devised ? 
 
 If the limits of this book permitted I should be glad to present 
 these inquiries more concretely. I must be content to indicate 
 the concrete aspect of two of them. 
 
 Number twenty-six is the question that everybody asked when 
 the European war began in 1914. The civilized world was stunned. 
 It had believed that science, communication, commerce, acquaint- 
 ance, humane feeling, and reasonableness had made a general war 
 impossible. Therefore "when the thing that couldn't" had occurred 
 we asked whether civilization was more than a veneer of habit 
 laid upon a character of savagery. Is it more? Has it ever been 
 more than a morale which at any moment might break down? 
 Has it ever selected or does it now select for survival trust- 
 worthy characters and the far-seeing intelligences that can be re- 
 lied on to weather political storms of envy and hate ? This ques- 
 tion has not been answered. Should we not try to find the answer ? 
 
 Number twenty-nine is the question that the world at present is 
 asking about Russia. Since prehistoric times the inadequate have 
 said "Let George do it, we should worry," and George, accepting
 
 FURTHER INQUIRIES OF SOCIOLOGY 299 
 
 the commission, has made himself a boss, a capitalist, a ruler, and 
 exploiter. Now, the inadequate, having learned how by sabotage 
 and violence to bully, are saying: "Make George do it. Make 
 those who have been adequate enough to acquire wealth divide 
 with us who have not been. Make the expert take orders from 
 us the non-expert." Dictation by the incompetent is no more 
 democracy, however, than monarchy is, and it tends to work out 
 as despotism. Society is democratic only when men, saying 
 neither "Let George do it," nor "Make George do it," say, rather, 
 "We will do it," and proceed to make good. But this saying and 
 this doing presuppose a diffusion or distribution of adequacy. 
 How extensive must the distribution be ? To what extent do the 
 intellectually inferior spontaneously trust and follow, to what 
 extent do they obstinately distrust, the intellectually superior? 
 Can we alter the ratio, or might one as well attempt by taking 
 thought to add a cubit to his stature? These questions have not 
 been answered. Should we not try to find the answers? 
 
 These inquiries sharpen the distinction between sociology and 
 economics, with which we set forth. Studies of actual or possible 
 betterment of the conditions under which and by which people 
 live are economic investigations in substance, if not in form. 
 Studies of actual or possible improvement of the people themselves 
 are sociological investigations. It would conduce to efficient co- 
 operation between economists and sociologists, if this discrimina- 
 tion were made in teaching and in the organization of university 
 departments. Studies of housing, cost of living, family budgets, 
 wages, hours and conditions of labor, insurance, and pensions can 
 be well taught only by economists. Studies of folkways, social 
 pressure by taboo and bullying, social selection, organization, and 
 morale can best be taught by sociologists. The sociologist should 
 know his economics well enough to avoid making a fool of him- 
 self when he talks about economic problems. A more technical 
 knowledge of the subject he does not need unless, besides being a 
 sociologist he is also professionally an economist. As a sociologist 
 he must be technically trained and proficient in the behavioristic 
 psychology and in statistics ; and he must keep in touch with the 
 workers in eugenics, who inquire how the human race can be im-
 
 300 STUDIES IN THE THEORY OF HUMAN SOCIETY, 
 
 proved in heredity, and with the workers in religion, in ethics, and 
 in education, who are the technicians of morale. 
 
 How shall the further inquiries of sociology be made? What 
 method or methods can be used and relied on ? 
 
 The method must be inductive and there is only one inductive 
 method that sociology can use. It consists of three steps. First, 
 accurate first-hand observations must be made in great number 
 and carefully checked up. The second-hand observation of the 
 interviewer has been overworked; it can yield us nothing but a 
 journalistic sociology. Second, observations must painstakingly 
 be recorded and intelligently classified. Third, the data so ob- 
 tained and prepared must be subjected to statistical analysis for 
 the purpose of discovering ratios, modalities, coefficients of varia- 
 tion, and correlations. 
 
 What facts shall be observed? Not static conditions only or 
 chiefly. The survey has its place and its value, but it can never 
 give us the laws of social change. To discover these we must 
 observe and analyze social experiments. Social evolution has pro- 
 ceeded by trial and error. Mankind has made more experiments 
 on and in society than on or in any other medium. They have 
 been imperfect, errant, often erratic, and there is not much ground 
 for hope that in the future they will become scientifically more 
 satisfactory, because the sociologist cannot, like the physicist or 
 the biologist, isolate one factor of a situation after another either 
 by changing it while all other factors are kept unchanged, or by 
 keeping it unchanged while all other factors are changed. Dis- 
 couraged by this difficulty Mill in his Logic mistakenly tells us 
 that the social sciences cannot successfully employ induction to 
 any great extent, and must rely on the deductive reasoning used 
 by the classical political economy. Mill apparently knew nothing 
 of statistical theory or practice. Happily it is often possible 
 statistically to isolate a factor and measure its value even when, 
 from a laboratory viewpoint experimentation has been inconclu- 
 sive. Scientifically imperfect social experimentation is going on 
 at present throughout the world. It is the duty of the sociologist 
 to observe and analyze it.
 
 INDEX
 
 INDEX 
 
 Achaeans, of Homer, a Danubean 
 stock, 73. 
 
 Adams, Brooks, interpretation of 
 history by, 67. 
 
 Adams, Henry and Brooks, brothers, 
 their theories of history, 66. 
 
 Adequacy, selection and develop- 
 ment of, the function of society, 
 291 seq. 
 
 Alpine race, 73. 
 
 Althusius, Johannes, on sovereignty, 
 106. 
 
 Amelioration, 285 seq. 
 
 Aquitani, of Caesar's Gaul, a Medi- 
 terranean stock, 73. 
 
 Aristocracy, definition of, 87. 
 
 Aristotle, on early institutions, 87 ; 
 his theory of society, 102, 103 ; on 
 likemindedness, 168; as scientific 
 investigator, 225; on slavery, 236; 
 on adequacy, 294. 
 
 Augustine, Saint, social philosophy 
 of, 104. 
 
 Aurelius, Marcus (Aurelius) Anto- 
 ninus, quoted, 245, 246. 
 
 Baarda, M. J., van, cited, 48. 
 
 Bagehot, Walter, on problems of so- 
 cial causation, 5 seq. ; on most ter- 
 rible of tyrannies, 6, 18; on pre- 
 liminary age, 27 ; on custom, 191 ; 
 on public polity, 210; methods and 
 achievements of, 211, 212; on war, 
 213, 214, 219; on government by 
 discussion, 222. 
 
 Balance of power, 221, 222. 
 
 Baldwin, Mark, on concept of self, 
 161, 162, 163. 
 
 Baltic race, 73. 
 
 Behavior, subinstinctive, 156, 250; 
 herd, 156, 158; instinctive, 156, 157, 
 250; pluralistic, 145, 152 seq., 251 
 seq., 292, 298. 
 
 Belgae, of Caesar's Gaul, a Danu- 
 bean stock, 73. 
 
 Benini, Rodolfo, on statistical meas- 
 
 ure of consciousness of kind, 120, 
 121. 
 
 Bodin, Jean, on sovereignty, 106. 
 
 Boehmond, of Tarentum, Crusader, 
 170. 
 
 Bradford, William, belief of in di- 
 vine providence in New England 
 history, 52. 
 
 Breasted, James Henry, quoted, 72. 
 
 Brehm, Alfred Edmund, contribu- 
 tion of to study of instinct, 39. 
 
 Brunetiere, Ferdinand, on failure of 
 science, no. 
 
 Brythonic Celts, a Danubean stock, 
 73- 
 
 Buckle, Henry Thomas, interpreta- 
 tion of history by, 67, 112; on re- 
 gional influences, 146. 
 
 Budge, Ernest Alfred, on "Constitu- 
 tion of Athens" as work of Aris- 
 totle, 87. 
 
 "Bunch," as simplest of social 
 groups, 269. 
 
 Butcher, S. H., on Greek concept of 
 the individual, 225. 
 
 Caesar, Julius, his discrimination of 
 races, 73; his studies in ethnic 
 character, 104. 
 
 Carnegie, Andrew, his interest in 
 peace, 213. 
 
 Cause and causation, 130, 131. 
 
 Celts, of Caesar's Gaul, an Alpine 
 stock, 73. 
 
 Chance, its significance, 141-143. 
 
 Cicero, on laws, 104; his definition 
 of a people, 123. 
 
 Circumstantial pressure, 254-256. 
 
 Clark, John Bates, on utility and 
 value, 33. ^ 
 
 Class, scientific definition of, 131. 
 
 Clifford, William Kingdon, his con- 
 ception and definition of term 
 "eject", 161, 162. 
 
 Clinias, the Cretan, his questionings 
 as to source of laws, 94. 
 
 Collective life, modes of, 84-87. 
 
 303
 
 304 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Composition, social, 269. 
 
 Comte, Auguste, his interpretation 
 of history, 66, 67; "la sociologie", 
 no, in; his hierarchy of the sci- 
 ences, 134; on public polity, 210, 
 21 1 ; on human progress, 293. 
 
 Concerted volition, 261, 262, 296. 
 
 Condorcet, Jean Antoine, on nature 
 of man, 112. 
 
 Congregation, 255. 
 
 Consciousness, of kind, 17, 61, 62, 
 163, 164-169, 203, 205, 260, 262, 265, 
 283, 292, 296; conversationalized, 
 161, 259; social, 62, 283. 
 
 Constitution, social, 269. 
 
 Constraint, social, 203 seq. 
 
 Consumption, standardization of, 61. 
 
 Conversationalized consciousness, 
 161, 259. 
 
 Cooley, Charles Horton, on social 
 consciousness, 62, 283. 
 
 Cooper, James Fenimore, cited, 50. 
 
 Correlation, definition of, 132, 133. 
 
 Coordination, definition of, 272. 
 
 Cournot, Augustine, on utility and 
 value, 33. 
 
 Crusades, psychological character of, 
 170, 171. 
 
 Culture, as an economy, 21 seq. ; 
 conflicts of, 175 seq. 
 
 Curthose, Robert, Crusader, 170. 
 
 Curve, of error, 109; normal, 223. 
 
 Danubean race, 73. 
 
 Dante, his vindication of the rational 
 claim of the secular empire, 105; 
 on imitation, 115, 116. 
 
 Darwin, Charles, Darwinism and 
 social philosophy, 3 seq. ; on strug- 
 gle for existence, 13, 14; utility, 
 33; organic economy, 37; collec- 
 tive action, 39; mental resource, 
 226 ; better and fit, 267. 
 
 Degradation, of energy, 136 seq. 
 
 Democracy, definition of, 88. 
 
 Demosthenes, quoted, 209. 
 
 Demotic factors of likemindedness, 
 255 seq. 
 
 Determinism and free will, 141-143. 
 
 De Vries, Hugo, on mutations and 
 fluctuations, 7. 
 
 Discipline, as product of social self- 
 control, 206, 207. 
 
 Dramatization, in pluralistic behav- 
 ior, 161, 259. 
 
 Durkheim, Emile, on relation of 
 consciousness of kind to social or- 
 ganization, 62; his social theory, 
 
 115; on division of social labor, 
 283. 
 
 Economy, consumption and produc- 
 tion, 27-32; concepts of, 34, 35; 
 four stages of, 23, 24, 30, 36 seq. ; 
 organic, 36-38, 53, 54; instinctive, 
 38-40, 53, 54; apprehensive and 
 ceremonial, 36, 42-54; luck, 42-46; 
 magic, 46-50, 53, 54; sacrificial, 51- 
 54 ; ascertaining, 36, 54 seq. ; busi- 
 ness, 36, 54, 55; slave, 55; trade, 
 55; capitalistic, 55. 
 
 Ego, Baldwin's concept of, 162, 163 ; 
 socialized, 166. 
 
 Eliot, George, quoted, 224. 
 
 Empedocles on likemindedness, 168. 
 
 Environment, physical, effect on hu- 
 man behavior of, 145-150; and nat- 
 ural selection, 202; physical, as a 
 stimulus, 253. 
 
 Epicurus, his theory of society, 107. 
 
 Equilibration of energy, 137 seq. 
 
 Evolution, Spencerian account of, 3, 
 113; social, Bagehot's account of, 
 6; social, Kidd's account of, 9, 10; 
 mechanistic, 139, 140. 
 
 Fact, scientific definition of, 131. 
 
 Feminism, 186 seq. 
 
 Festus, quoted, 218. 
 
 Fiske, John, on sociality, 8, 9; on 
 prolongation of infancy, 8, 9. 
 
 Folkways, 18, 159, 191 seq., 206, 263, 
 264, 285, 293, 296. 
 
 Fourier, Jean Baptiste, on popula- 
 tion of Paris, 108. 
 
 Fowler, W. Warde, on magic econ- 
 omy, 49, 51. 
 
 Frazer, J. G., on magic, 46, 48. 
 
 Free will, and determinism, 141-143. 
 
 Frequency, statistical, 207. 
 
 "Gang", simplest arrangement of in- 
 dividuals that go, work or play to- 
 gether, 269. 
 
 Galton, Francis, on natural inher- 
 itance, 12; on sources of Greek 
 genius, 76. 
 
 Genetic aggregation, 255, 270. 
 
 Germans, of Caesar's Gual, a Baltic 
 stock, 73. 
 
 Gillen, F. J., on magic, 46, 48. 
 
 Godfrey of Bouillon, Crusader, 170. 
 
 Goidelic Celts, an Alpine stock, 73. 
 
 Good life, Plato's concept of, 102. 
 
 Gottschalk, the priest, unorganized 
 crusade of, 171.
 
 INDEX 
 
 305 
 
 Government by discussion, 222, 223. 
 Grant, U. S., on how to abolish a 
 
 bad law, 194. 
 Graunt, John, on statistics of mor^ 
 
 tality, 108. 
 "Great man", in relation to public 
 
 policy and social order, 105. 
 Gregariousness, S, 156-158, 163, 166, 
 
 258-260, 292. 
 Grinnell, G. B., cited, 48. 
 Gubernatis, Angelo de, on magic, 49. 
 
 Habits, of the herd, 157, 158, 201, 
 251, 252, 254, 259. 
 
 Halley, Edmund, on birth and death 
 rates, 108. 
 
 Happiness, Herbert Spencer on, in. 
 
 Harrison, Jane Ellen, cited, 264. 
 
 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, his 
 philosophy of history, 66. 
 
 Hellenes, a Danubean stock, 73. 
 
 Herd, behavior of, 8, 156-158, 163; 
 vs. society, 166; cooperation in 
 the, 201 ; pluralistic reactions in 
 the, 258; instinct of, 259; habits 
 of the, 157, 158, 201, 251, 252, 254, 
 
 259- 
 
 Hesiod, on luck economy, 44, 45. 
 History, interpretations of, 66, 67, 89 
 
 seq. 
 Hobbes, Thomas, on sovereignty, 
 
 106. 
 Holmes, Oliver Wendell, quoted, 
 
 1 60. 
 
 Hugh the Great, Crusader, 170. 
 Huntington, Ellsworth, on influence 
 
 of environment on behavior of 
 
 man, 67, 80, 147, 255. 
 Huxley, Thomas Henry, on moral 
 
 freedom, 142, 143, 226. 
 Hyndman, Henry Mayers, quoted, 
 
 233- 
 
 Imitation, 116. 
 
 Individual, as creator of society, 104, 
 107 ; as product of society, 102-104, 
 107. 
 
 Indiyiduation, 288, 289. 
 
 Instincts, in gregariousness, 156-158, 
 258, 260. 
 
 Interstimulation, 257-259, 295. 
 
 Irritability, as quality of living mat- 
 ter, 154, 160. 
 
 "It", as mana, 46. 
 
 James, William, contrary impulses, 
 42, 212; psychological constitution 
 of the individual, 161. 
 
 Jennings, H. S., behavior of lower 
 
 organisms, 156. 
 Jevons, W. Stanley, his theory of 
 
 consumption, 28; on utility, 33, 34; 
 
 on causation, 131. 
 Johnson, Edward, belief of in divine 
 
 providence in New England his- 
 tory, 52. 
 Justice, Plato's conception of, 102, 
 
 in; Spencer's conception of, in; 
 
 as adjustment and readjustment, 
 
 282. 
 
 Kakistocracy, definition of, 88. 
 
 Kepler, Johann, on planetary orbits, 
 131. 
 
 Kidd, Benjamin, on social evolution, 
 9, 10, n. 
 
 Kingsley, Mary H., on magic in 
 West Africa, 46. 
 
 Kinship, matrilinear and matrojiy- 
 mic, 85-87, 270; patrilinear and 
 patronymic, 85-87, 270. 
 
 Kirchhoff, Gustav Robert, his defini- 
 tion of mechanics, 127, 128. 
 
 Kropotkin, Prince Peter Aleksee- 
 vich, on mutual aid among ani- 
 mals, 7, 8, 39. 
 
 Lamarck, Jean Baptiste, on adapta- 
 tion, 112, 113. 
 
 Laplace, Pierre Simon, on quanti- 
 tative method in sociological re- 
 search, 1 08, no. 
 
 Laschi, R., on political crime, 245. 
 
 Leaders, as causes of war, 220, 
 221. 
 
 Likemindedness, 167, 168, 256, 257, 
 260, 263, 280, 283, 284, 296. 
 
 Lloyd, John Uri, on changing luck, 
 49- 
 
 Locke, John, on sovereignty, 107. 
 
 Lombroso, Cesare, on political 
 crime, 245. 
 
 Longstaff, G. B., quoted, 241, 242. 
 
 Lowie, Robert, on primitive society, 
 85, 86. 
 
 Luck, belief in as factor in primi- 
 tive economy, 42-46. 
 
 McDougall, William, on gregarious- 
 ness, 259. 
 
 Mach, Ernst, on nature of science, 
 127 seq. 
 
 Machiavelli, Nicolo, on leadership, 
 105, 106, 115. 
 
 MacMillan, George Blundell, on 
 structure of the atom, 89.
 
 306 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Magic, in early economy, 29, 46-54; 
 Frazer on, 46, 55, 182. 
 
 Maine, Henry Sumner, on early in- 
 stitutions, 86; on custom, 191. 
 
 Mallock, William Hurrell, on strug- 
 gle for domination, n, 12. 
 
 Malthus, Thomas Robert, death 
 rates, theory of population, 3, 7. 
 
 Mana, 22, 46, 47, 85, 270. 
 
 Mannhardt, W., on ceremonial 
 magic, 48. 
 
 Marshall, Alfred, his theory of con- 
 sumption, 28. 
 
 Marshall, Henry Rutgers, on hesita- 
 tion in reasoning, 42. 
 
 Marx, Karl, his theory of history, 
 66, 67, 83. 
 
 Masculinism, 186. 
 
 Mather, Cotton, belief of in divine 
 providence in New England his- 
 tory, 52. 
 
 Mather, Increase, belief of in divine 
 providence in New England his- 
 tory, 52. 
 
 Matrilinear and matronymic descent 
 and kinship, 85, 86, 87, 270. 
 
 Maudsley, Henry, cited, 164. 
 
 Mayo-Smith, Richmond, on statis- 
 tical methods, 120. 
 
 Mediterranean race, 73. 
 
 Megillus of Lacedaemon, his ques- 
 tionings as to source of law, 94. 
 
 Mendel, Johann Gregor, on law of 
 heredity, 7. 
 
 Menger, Carl, on utility and value, 33. 
 
 Mentalized organism, 155. 
 
 Militarism, as stage in social evolu- 
 tion, 114. 
 
 Mill, John Stuart, concept of causa- 
 tion, 131; on laissez-faire, 190; on 
 use of deductive method in social 
 sciences, 300. 
 
 Mind, of the many, 154 seq. ; medi- 
 aeval, 154; as activity of men- 
 talized organisms, 155, 162; social, 
 265, 266, 283. 
 
 Misoneism, 245. 
 
 Mobmindedness, 170, 171. 
 
 Mode, statistical, 202, 207, 282. 
 
 Moelmud, Dyvnwal, quoted, 159. 
 
 Montesquieu, Charles de Secondat, 
 his^theory of history, 67; his use 
 of inductive method, 107, 108; on 
 the nature of man, 112; on the 
 effects of climate, 146. 
 
 Morale, as product of social self- 
 control, and of other factors, 206, 
 295, 297, 298. 
 
 Mores, 18, 31, 192, 264, 278, 296 
 Morselli, Henry, on suicide as a phe- 
 nomenon of civilization, 242 
 
 Natural selection, as factor in hu- 
 man progress, 4, 5; vs. progress, 
 9, 10; in society, 202 
 
 Nature, scientific interpretation of, 
 62, 63 ; state of, 106, 107 ; original, 
 112; second, 112; human, improv- 
 ability of, 112 
 
 Newton, Isaac, on law of gravita- 
 tion, no 
 
 Norm, 202, 282 
 
 Ollivier, Emile, quoted, 217 
 
 Orenda, 46. 
 
 Ovid, on magic, 48, 49. 
 
 Panic, likemindedness as factor of, 
 164, 165. 
 
 Patrilinear and patronymic descent 
 and kinship, 85-87, 270. 
 
 Patten, Simon N., on consumption 
 economy, 27, 28. 
 
 Paul, the Apostle, on likeminded- 
 ness, 167, 168. 
 
 Pawlow, Ivan Petrovitch, on condi- 
 tioned reflex, 155, 265. 
 
 Payne, Edward John, on evolution 
 of language, 53. 
 
 Pearson, Karl, progress by selection 
 and inheritance, 12 ; on social the- 
 ory, 107; on science, 130. 
 
 Peter, the Apostle, on likeminded- 
 ness, 168. 
 
 Peter, the Hermit, his Crusade, 171. 
 
 Petroff, I., cited, 47. 
 
 Philoneism, 245. 
 
 Picts, a Danubean stock, 73. 
 
 Plato, his interpretation of history, 
 66, 67; theory of laws, 95, 96; 
 theory of society, 102, 103, in; 
 on likemindedness, 168; on specu- 
 lative method, 225 ; on individual 
 and the state, 227; on adequacy, 
 294. 
 
 Platonism, its view of the nature of 
 man, 112. 
 
 Pluralistic behavior, 144, 152 seq., 
 250 seq., 292, 298. 
 
 Plurel, 92, 251, 268. 
 
 Plutocracy, definition of, 88. 
 
 Political force, 105. 
 
 Post-Darwinism, its influence on so- 
 cial theory, 7. 
 
 Power, contagious, as mana, 46, 47.
 
 INDEX 
 
 307 
 
 Preferential association, as begin- 
 ning of society, 166. 
 
 Pressure, social, 121, 200 seq., 263 
 seq. ; circumstantial, 254-256, 263. 
 
 Probability curve, 109, no. 
 
 Progress, 119. 
 
 Prolongation, of infancy, John 
 Fiske's theory of, 8. 
 
 Protocracy, 267, 268, 270, 273, 375, 
 276. 
 
 Quetelet, Lambert Adolphe Jacques, 
 on statistical methods, 108, 109. 
 
 Races, European, 73, 91. 
 
 Ratzell, Friedrich, on effects of geo- 
 graphical features on m'an, 147. 
 
 Ratzenhofer, Gustav, on "interests", 
 267. 
 
 Raymond, of Toulouse, Crusader, 
 170. 
 
 Read, Carveth, his theory of hu- 
 man origins, 158. 
 
 Reason and reasoning, nature and 
 processes of, 47, 50, 53, 54, 55, 154- 
 156. 
 
 Reconditioned reflex, 155. 
 
 Religion, elemental, original fac- 
 tors of, 9, 10, ii. 
 
 Ribot, Theodule Armand, on psy- 
 chological constitution of the in- 
 dividual, 161. 
 
 Robert of Flanders, Crusader, 170. 
 
 Ross, Edward Alsworth, on social 
 control, 200; on psychological as- 
 cendancy, 268. 
 
 Ross, Frank A., example of psycho- 
 logical group cited from, 159. 
 
 Rousseau, Jean Jacques, on the so- 
 cial contract, 260. 
 
 Russell, Bertrand, on perceptions 
 and conceptions, 130. 
 
 Saint Simon, Claude Henri, social 
 revolutionist, his influence on 
 Comte, 211. 
 
 Schaffle, Albert Eberhard Friedrich, 
 his theory of society, 115. 
 
 Seebohm, Frederick, on inequalities 
 in early society, 87. 
 
 Seebohm, Hugh, on Greek tribal 
 society, 87. 
 
 Semple, Ellen Churchill, on influ- 
 ence of environment on behavior 
 of man, 67, 147. 
 
 Seneca, on Roman civilization, 57. 
 
 Sensitivity, discriminated from irri- 
 tability, 154, 155, 160. 
 
 Sewall, Samuel, belief of in divine 
 providence in New England his- 
 tory, 52. 
 
 Skeat, W. W., on magic in Malay 
 Peninsula, 46, 48. 
 
 Small, Albion W., on "interests", 
 267. 
 
 Smith, Adam, on division of labor, 
 62, 283, 284. 
 
 Smith, Robertson, on primitive 
 leadership, 86. 
 
 Social composition, 269. 
 
 Social consciousness, 62, 283. 
 
 Social constitution, 269. 
 
 Social constraint, 203 seq. 
 
 Social evolution, 6, 9, 10. 
 
 Social pressure, 121, 200 seq., 263 
 seq. 
 
 Social solidarity, 265, 266. 
 
 Sociality, John Fiske's discrimina- 
 tion of, 8. 
 
 Socialization, 287, 288. 
 
 Society, Bagehot's theory of, 6; Sen- 
 eca on Roman, 57 ; types of, 85- 
 88 ; Aristotle's theory of, 102, 103 ; 
 Plato's theory of, 102, 103, in; 
 Epicurus's theory of, 107 ; Schaf- 
 fle's theory of, 115; function of, 
 in, 112, 291, 292; Spencer's the- 
 ory of, 113,115,121; as preferen- 
 tial association, 166; material of, 
 167, 168; changes in, 169-171; as 
 constraining force, 201-208; as 
 means to end, 226, 227 ; and the 
 individual, 224-229; progress of, 
 230 seq. ; duties of, 244, 245 ; con- 
 sciousness of kind as factor in, 
 263; as selective force, 267. 
 
 Solidarity, group and collective con- 
 flict, Bagehot's theory of, 5, 6 j in 
 the gregarious group, 8; in Amer- 
 ica, 60, 61 ; from like response, 
 116; creation of by police power, 
 185 ; industrial, 201 ; social, 265, 
 266; behavioristic, 268, 269, 280. 
 
 Sovereignty, conceptions of, 106, 
 107, 194, 276, 277, 278. 
 
 Spencer, Baldwin, on magic in Cen- 
 tral Australia, 46, 48. 
 
 Spencer, Herbert, on evolution, 3-5 ; 
 his interpretation of history, 67; 
 on function of society, in, 112; 
 on social theory, 113-115, 121; on 
 mechanistic evolution, 139, 140; 
 environment, 146, 147; laissez- 
 faire, 190; folkways, 191; public 
 polity, 210, 211 ; war, 213 seq., 266; 
 human progress, 293.
 
 308 
 
 INDEX 
 
 State, of nature, 106, 107; definition 
 of, 276; vs. folkways, 293. 
 
 State ways, 192 seq., 206. 
 
 Stoicism, its view of the nature of 
 man, 112. 
 
 Subordination, 272. 
 
 Sumner, William Graham, on folk- 
 ways, 18, 191, 263, 293; on war, 
 279. 
 
 Superordination, 272. 
 
 Sutherland, Alexander, on origin 
 and growth of moral instinctj 9. 
 
 Taboo, 22, 23, 28, 182, 270. 
 
 Tacitus, descriptive studies of ethnic 
 character, 20, 104. 
 
 Tarde, Gabriel, on imitation, 6, 116, 
 212. 
 
 Taylor, Henry Osborn, on the medi- 
 aeval mind, 154. 
 
 Themistes, 264. 
 
 Thorndike, Edward L., on original 
 nature, 112. 
 
 Totemism, 22, 85. 
 
 Trial and error, 155, 156, 293, 204. 
 
 Trotter, W., on instincts of the herd, 
 259- 
 
 Turbulence, its relation to evolu- 
 tion, to free will, 143. 
 
 Type, society as a, 202, 206, 208, 
 282. 
 
 Utility, Wallace's conception of, 33, 
 34; Jevons's conception of, 33, 34. 
 
 Van Hook, La Rue, on Athenian 
 
 democracy, 76. 
 Virtue, as mana, 46, 85. 
 
 Wakunda, 46. 
 
 Wallace, Alfred Russel, on prin- 
 ciple of utility, 33, 34, 39; on men- 
 tal resource, 226. 
 
 Walras, Leon, on utility and value, 
 
 33- 
 
 Walter the Penniless, his Crusade, 
 170. 
 
 War, as integrating force, 213-217; 
 causes of, 218-221. 
 
 Ward, Lester Frank, on education 
 and knowledge as means to social 
 amelioration, 286, 293. 
 
 Weismann, Auguste, on continuity 
 of germ plasm, 7, 112. 
 
 Wells, H. G., his Outline of His- 
 tory, 93. 
 
 Wieser, Friedrich von, on utility and 
 value, 33. 
 
 Woodworth, Robert Sessions, on in- 
 stinct, 155 ; on drive and mechan- 
 ism, 275. 
 
 Zeno, his social theory, 103.
 
 University of California 
 
 SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 
 
 305 De Neve Drive - Parking Lot 17 Box 951388 
 
 LOS ANGELES, CALIFORNIA 90095-1388 
 
 Return this material to the library from which it was borrowed.
 
 JjgffiSffi Iff GOWL UBRABV FAO, 
 
 A 7)nn Q '''
 
 University of 
 
 Southern Fi 
 
 Librarv P