:i!;i);i!;i!r>T!i 

 
 EX LliM 
 
 I 
 
 CH/VRLES— ^ 
 MALMERI* 
 MAR5M 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA 
 AT LOS ANGELES
 
 THE FUNDAMENTALS 
 OF DEBATE 
 
 BY 
 
 HARRY FRANKLIN COVINGTON 
 
 PROFESSOR OF ENGLISH IN PRINCETON UNIVERSITY 
 
 CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS 
 
 NEW YORK CHICAGO BOSTON
 
 COPYSIGHT, 1918, BY 
 
 CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS 
 
 « . ■• •« ' •
 
 CD 
 
 cr 
 
 c- 
 
 CD 
 
 3 
 
 -9 
 i 
 
 > 
 
 /I 
 
 1 
 6 
 
 
 .< 
 
 TO 
 
 THE MANY EMINENT GRADUATES 
 
 OF 
 
 THE CLIOSOPHIC AND AMERICAN WHIG SOCIETIES 
 
 OF PRINCETON UNIVERSITY 
 
 -T
 
 PREFACE 
 
 As a teacher of argument and debate for more than 
 a generation, I have long been convinced that these 
 subjects are not so much an applied logic as an applied 
 psychologic; that, indeed, there are other powers of 
 the mind than the purely logical which are fundamental, 
 and that the principles governing them are capable of 
 a more thoroughly scientific exposition than has ap- 
 peared in our manuals. I have thus endeavored to write 
 a modern text-book on debating, grounded on psychology 
 as well as on logic, and to set forth principles and methods 
 tested by actual experience. 
 
 I have presented the material which I believe to be 
 necessary to a full understanding of argument and de- 
 bate in two parts, Logical Organization and The Pres- 
 entation. In considering Logical Organization, I have 
 retained the conventional view-point, dealing with Briefs 
 and Brief-making, Argument, and Evidence, and have 
 endeavored to weld them into a whole. Highly valuable 
 to the student as the conventional stress upon the pure 
 logic of the subject is, it has been found by the writer 
 to be utterly inadequate even when followed later by 
 a treatment of Persuasion. 
 
 The unique feature of the present text lies in the fact 
 that it recognizes more fully than has hitherto been the 
 case in text-books on argument the function of imag- 
 ination in reasoning; that the unconscious association
 
 VI PREFACE 
 
 of images in the mind leads to new ideas and progress, 
 and that, in presenting our ideas after they have been 
 logically organized, they must be imaged suggestively on 
 the minds of the audience. Part II, therefore, explains 
 the elemental nature of Imagination, and treats the 
 subject of what is usually called the Presentation as 
 Imaginative Suggestion. Whenever this view-point 
 and conception have been presented in the classroom, 
 they have aroused interest by supplementing the formal- 
 ism of the older treatises and by opening new avenues 
 of thought and suggesting original ways of approach. 
 For, after all, the debater and student of Enghsh com- 
 position m general should be free to act on his own 
 initiative, to express his own individuality. 
 
 All students in this field will gladly acknowledge their 
 indebtedness to the pioneer work of Professor George 
 P. Baker, of Harvard, author of *'The Principles of Ar- 
 gumentation" (1895), and also to Professor Walter 
 Dill Scott, author of "The Psychology of PubHc Speak- 
 ing" (1910). 
 
 I wish to express my especial obligation to Professor 
 Howard C. Warren, of Princeton University, for his 
 helpful criticism of the psychological foundations. To 
 Doctor Theodore W. Hunt, for many years head of the 
 EngUsh Department, now Professor Emeritus, I wish 
 also to express my appreciation for his interest and en- 
 couragement. 
 
 Princeton University, June, 19 18.
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 Chapter I. Introductory i 
 
 The Fundamentals of Debate — Logic — Evidence — Rhetoric 
 — Oratory — Psychology — Constructive Thinking — Minds, Is- 
 sues, and Audiences: Two Types — Persuasion — The Debater 
 Himself — Plan of the Book. 
 
 PART I. LOGICAL ORGANIZATION 
 Chapter II. Briefs and Brief-Making 15 
 
 Need of a Plan — The Brief Defined — The Making of a Brief 
 — ^The Process — Analysis — Classification — Arrangement — The 
 Result — Unity — Logical Sequence— Proportion — Process and 
 Result — Unity — Climax — Two Laws of Structure — Rules for 
 Brief-Making — The Three Main Parts of a Brief — Specimen 
 Brief. 
 
 Chapter III. Argument 39 
 
 The View-Point — Name — Effectiveness — Unity of Classifica- 
 tion. 
 
 Classes of Argument — I. Association, Argument from Sign — 
 Sign Argument Expounded — Force — Observation and Infer- 
 ence — Common Sources of Error. 
 
 II. Argument from Example — A. Resemblance (i) By Gen- 
 eralization — Illustrations in Law and in Parliamentary De- 
 bates—Further Analysis of the Process — Definition of Rel- 
 evancy and Rules — The Fallacy, Begging the Question — 
 Answering a Causal Example by Alleging a Different 
 Cause — (2) By Analogy — Definitions — Uses — Illustrations. 
 
 B. Contrast — A Principle of Association — Uses in Debating — 
 
 vii
 
 viii CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 Uses in Refutation — Types of Argument by Contrast — (i) Re- 
 ductio ad absurdum — Definition and Illustrations — Manner of 
 Treatment — How Answered — Its Special Value — (2) The 
 Dilemma — Definition and Illustrations — Two Kinds — Its Use — 
 How Answered — (3) The Method of the Residue — Definition 
 and Illustrations. 
 
 Chapter IV. Argument (continued) 87 
 
 III. Argument from Causal Relation — Definition — Rule of 
 Adequacy, Involving Parallelism or Difference, Other Com- 
 peting or Co-operating Causes, Law of Progress — Illustra- 
 tions — Causal Argument, and the Other Sources of Reasoning — 
 Differences of View-Point. 
 
 IV. Inductive and Deductive Arguments — Induction — ^The 
 Inevitable Assumption — The Inductive Formula — Induction, 
 the Scientific Method of Investigation — Kinds of Induction. 
 
 Deduction, a Ready Mode of Reasoning — Deduction Sup- 
 plemented by Induction — Deduction, a Method of Criticism — 
 The Syllogism — The Enthymeme — The Chain of Reasoning — 
 Two Classes of Fallacies — A Common Ground in Argument. 
 
 Refutation — Character — Preparation — An Important Limi- 
 tation — Selection — Fimdamental Criticism — Two General 
 Methods of Refutation: Overthrowing the Supporting Argu- 
 ment and Proving the Contradictory. 
 
 Chapter V. Evidence 112 
 
 The Proof — Meaning of Term — The Need of Evi- 
 dence — The Need of Assumptions — Classes of Evidence — 
 Direct and Circumstantial — Jiuy Verdicts upon Circumstan- 
 tial Evidence — Personal, Real, and Documentary Evidence — 
 The Law of Evidence — Examining Testimony — Consistency — 
 the One Great Test — (i) Internal — (2) External, General, or 
 Particular. 
 
 The Use of Evidence Outside the Courts — The Debater's 
 Chief Source of Evidence, Authority — Two Classes of Au- 
 thority — Examining Evidence from Authority — Rules for the 
 Interpretation of Documents — Suggestions for Reporting Evi- 
 dence — The Reasonableness of an Opinion — ^The Danger of 
 Partial Quotation — The Card System.
 
 CONTENTS ix 
 
 PART II. THE PRESENTATION 
 
 PAGE 
 
 Chapter VI. Imagination in Argument .... 150 
 
 The Need of Imagination in Argument — The Logical 
 and the Psychological — Images Are a Psychological Infer- 
 ence — Mental Processes — The Creative Imagination — The 
 Poverty of Mere Facts — The Vision of New Ideas — Anticipa- 
 tion Images — Perceptual Aspect of Imagery — Imaging a Con- 
 cept — Imaging (i) an Analogy; (2) a Cause; (3) a Conclusion; 
 (4) Affection and Desire; (5) in a Team Debate; (6) in General — 
 The Advantage of the Conceptual View-Point to the Debater — 
 Types of Imagery — Memory Images — Imagination Images of 
 the Past, the Present, and the Future — Summary. 
 
 Chapter VII. Suggestion in Argument i88 
 
 Laws of Suggestion and Their Use in Debating — Avoiding 
 and Removing Inhibitions — Hurtful Admissions as Inhibi- 
 tions — Immediate Removal of Inhibitions Introduced by an 
 Opponent — Logical Fallacies as Inhibitions — Removing an 
 Inhibiting Wish by the Image ad Absurd um — Conclusions. 
 
 Instruments of Suggestion — Gesture Images as Instnmients 
 of Suggestion — Word Images as Instruments of Suggestion — 
 Variability of Meanings, Due to the Speaker, Vocal Shadings — 
 Due to the Listener, The Mental Level, The Psychological 
 Moment — Imagery an Imperfect Means, 
 
 Chapter VIII. Instruments of Suggestion ... 212 
 
 Tonal Imagery — Illustrative Imagery — Avoiding Personal- 
 ities — Subjective Images — Personal Adjectives — All the Parts 
 of Speech — The Phrase — Sentence Forms — Climax — Repe- 
 tition — Variety — Paraleipsis — Confidence — Interestedness — 
 Avoiding Common Defects in Delivery — The Decision. 
 
 APPENDICES 
 Appendix A 
 
 Specimen Briefs — ^The First Ji:inius Letter — In Defense of 
 Damay. 
 
 247
 
 X CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 Appendix B 255 
 
 Questions and Exercises : In General — On Specific Speeches — 
 In Association-Reactions. 
 
 Appendix C 261 
 
 The Special Study of Imagery — Varied Imagery Appeals — 
 Auditory Imagery and the Disagreeable — Mixed Imagery 
 T3T)es. 
 
 Appendix D 269 
 
 The Imagery of Argument and of Poetry. 
 
 Appendix E 272 
 
 Addresses : Premier Lloyd George's "Peace Founded on the 
 Rock of Vindicated Justice" and President Wilson's "Force to 
 the Utmost." 
 
 Appendix F 283 
 
 Bibliography. 
 
 Appendix G 284 
 
 Resolutions for Debate. 
 
 Index 287
 
 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE
 
 THE 
 FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 INTRODUCTORY 
 
 The Fundamentals of Debate 
 
 On turning to the dictionary you will find that the 
 word "debate" formerly meant "strife, contention." 
 For example, Robert of Gloucester says in the thirteenth 
 century — "in the days of Trinity next ensuing was a 
 great debate and in that murder there were slain four- 
 score." Sir Walter Scott uses the term as applied to 
 physical contest: 
 
 "But question fierce and proud reply 
 Gave signal soon of dire debate." 
 
 The term is apphed usually to intellectual disputes; 
 its field is not actually but figuratively a battle-ground. 
 Its province is coextensive with the whole domain of 
 thought. Wherever there are propositions in dispute, 
 ideas attacked and defended, there is debate. In law 
 before the court, in theology before the synod, in politics 
 on the stump or in Congress — indeed, in almost all scien- 
 tific, philosophic, or popular speeches and writings. Its 
 instruments are not swords, shields, or arrows but argu- 
 ments. The arms of the contest are intellectual ones, 
 
 1
 
 2 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 the contest one of reasons. According to the present 
 use of the word, if A by chance meets B and makes an 
 assertion which is denied by B, whereupon A offers 
 reasons for his belief which are met by contrary reasons 
 from B, there is debate. "A thesis is set down; you 
 attack, I defend it; you insist, I reply; you deny, I prove; 
 you distinguish, I destroy your distinctions; my replies 
 balance or overturn your objections — such is debate." 
 You assert your intention of pursuing a certain line 
 of action, I reason with you to do the opposite — such 
 is debate. 
 
 Debating is not confined to formal tribunals. The 
 college student arguing upon the prospects of a base- 
 ball championship is as much a debater as the disputant 
 in an intercollegiate contest. An amusing controversy 
 showing the origin and conduct of a not uncommon 
 type of debate may be found in Scott's "Antiquary" 
 relating to the racial connection of the ancient Picts. 
 Were they Teutons or Celts? Here we have assertion 
 and denial, citation of authorities, pro and con, with 
 distinctions, until as too often happens, the disputants 
 lose their tempers, and Sir Arthur flounces out of the 
 parlor in high dudgeon — 
 
 "... Why, man, there was once a people called the 
 Piks " 
 
 "More properly Picis," interrupted the Baronet. 
 
 "I say the Pikar, Pihar, Piochlar, Piaghter, or Peughtar," 
 vociferated Oldbuck; "they spoke a Gothic dialect " 
 
 "Genuine Celtic," again asseverated the knight. 
 
 "Gothic! Gothic! I'll go to death upon it!" counter-as- 
 severated the squire. 
 
 "Why, gentlemen," said Lovel, "I conceive that is a dis- 
 pute which may be easily settled by philologists, if there are 
 any remains of the language."
 
 INTRODUCTORY 3 
 
 "There is but one word," said the Baronet, "but, in spite 
 of Mr. Oldbuck's pertinacity, it is decisive of the question." 
 
 "Yes, in my favor," said Oldbuck; "Mr. Lovel, you shall 
 be judge — I have the learned Pinkerton on my side." 
 
 "I, on mine, the indefatigable and erudite Chalmers. . . ." 
 
 "Tnily, gentlemen," said Lovel, "before you muster your 
 forces and overwhelm me with authorities, I should like to know 
 the word in dispute." 
 
 "Benval," said both disputants at once. 
 
 "Which signifies caput valli," said Sir Arthur. 
 
 "The head of the wall," echoed Oldbuck. 
 
 There was a deep pause. "It is rather a narrow foundation 
 to build a hypothesis upon," observed the arbiter. 
 
 "Not a whit, not a whit," said Oldbuck; "men fight best 
 in a narrow ring — an inch is as good as a mile for a home-thrust." 
 
 "It is decidedly Celtic," said the Baronet; "every hill in 
 the Highlands begins with Ben." 
 
 "But what say you to Val, Sir Arthur; is it not decidedly 
 the Saxon wall ? " 
 
 "It is the Roman vallum," said Sir Arthur; "the Picts bor- 
 rowed that part of the word." 
 
 "No such thing; if they borrowed anything, it must have 
 been your Ben, which they might have from the neighboring 
 Britons of Strath Cluyd. . . ." 
 
 Debating generally originates from conflicting opin- 
 ions. *'You say we are sectional!" exclaimed Lincoln 
 in his Cooper Institute address. "We deny it. That 
 makes an issue; and the burden of proof is upon you." 
 The common mode of procedure, in starting an action 
 at law, is for the plaintiff to file a paper which is fol- 
 lowed by another paper from the defendant which is 
 called an answer; at length, argmnent ensues, if not 
 upon the general issue, upon special issues arising dur- 
 ing the course of the trial, which are successively 
 weighed, till the final issue emerges and is weighed and 
 the case solved.
 
 4 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 In formal debating contests, the questions discussed 
 do not arise from conflicting opinions actually existing 
 among the debaters themselves ; the questions are chosen 
 by joint agreement, or by one party to the discussion, 
 and presented to the other for the choice of sides. The 
 two sides are called, respectively, the affirmative and the 
 negative, the former being that side which maintains 
 the proposition (which may be negatively stated) and 
 the latter the side which denies the proposition. The 
 proposition is usually stated affirm'atively. 
 
 Argument is the process of resolving differences of 
 opinion by assertion and denial, followed by proof and 
 counter-proof with distinctions. If the opponent is 
 pjresent and is heard, we call the argument a debate 
 (debatere — to beat off). By it we aim to influence the 
 opinions, beliefs, or actions of others. It thus presup- 
 poses the possibility at least of an opposing view, a dif- 
 ference of opinion. It presupposes also a knowledge of 
 facts, an ability to correlate them, as well as the power 
 to present them effectively. Viewed as an art, then, 
 argument may be regarded as applying (i) the rules 
 of evidence such as maintain in our courts of law, (2) 
 the rules of reasoning such as exist in common sense 
 or have been developed in text-books on logic, and (3) 
 the principles of literary art and oratory or public speak- 
 ing, at the basis of which we now know (4) must rest 
 a sound psychology. This forms a large and varied 
 background, from which the debater and the writer 
 on debating must draw his material if he is to grasp 
 his subject fully or treat it as a whole. 
 
 Y^j j ^ a.t are. \he. farts? What happened ? What wa s 
 done? These are the first questions which the lawyer 
 asks of his client. They are equally important for the
 
 INTRODUCTORY 5 
 
 student of debate. The debater should be first of all 
 the painstaking investigator. Even if the reasoning 
 is valid, conclusions based on unsupported assertions 
 may be entirely unwarranted. You say that we should 
 grant the^ Philippine Islands complete independence 
 within five years because they have shown themselves 
 to be capable of self-government. But have they? What 
 is the evidence in the case ? On whose authority does 
 it rest? Is he qu alified to speak as an authority? If 
 SO, are his statements prooable on their face, uncon- 
 tradicted by others who have an equal right to be heard 
 — and so on ? 
 ^ The legal rules of evidence are an important guide 
 I in any procedure in debating where the attempt is to 
 resolve such issues of fact; for they have grown up 
 through years of custom and practice, and though some- 
 times deeply embedded in legal subject-matter, have as a 
 rule come to be recognized as a safe and just mode of 
 procedure in general. The debater should know, for 
 instance, such things as the difference between testi- 
 mony and authority, hearsay and first-hand testimony, 
 primary and secondary evidence, and the important 
 rules governing the production of testimony in courts 
 of law. The law of evidence, according to Stephen, is 
 that part of procedure which with a view to ascertain- 
 ing the individual rights and liabilities in particular 
 cases decides : (i) What facts m ?^y nnH rnay nnf he 
 proved . (2) W hat sort of evid ence must be given of a 
 fact whic h rnay be proved, and (3) by whom and Tn 
 what manner th^evidence must be~produceidby which 
 any f act is to be proyed,^ 
 The facts being estabhshed as true, what do such 
 ' James F. Stephen, "A Digest of the Law of Evidence," p. 6.
 
 6 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 facts Jm^ort with refe rence to the substantial things in 
 
 doub t? To exactly wha t are they relevaiit?- _ .W-ha.t is 
 
 the nature o7lhisre][£vancy^:::caiisaLiDr_e^^ Ar- 
 
 gmnenfativeskill and the ability to think readily on one's 
 feet should be based on an ability to reason soundly. 
 The deb ater must know the natuy e of the relg,tions^ exist- 
 i ng between propositions, the groun d^ of warrant for 
 their assertion in an argume nt. Apprehension, judg- 
 'ment, and reasoning, according to Jevons,^ form the chief 
 parts of logical doctrine. Certainly, a debater must 
 be able to perceive the truth, be wise and discriminat- 
 ing in his judgments, scrupulous and sensible in his in- 
 ferences. Now, the proposition is the formal unit of 
 argument, whether employed as a premise or a con- 
 clusion. It is regarded in logic as divisible into two 
 parts called terms, and the process of formulating a 
 proposition is the process of expressing some judgment 
 between these terms. Grammatically, a proposition 
 consists of a subject and a predicate, while mathemat- 
 ically it may be defined as an equation between two 
 tenns. Of course, the discovery, analysis, and ar- 
 rangement of the material so as to appeal to the 
 understanding involve, first and foremost, reasoning 
 processes. The main and subordinate argument, heads 
 and subheads, in the outUne of a case are step-by-step 
 processes — Hnks in a chain of reasoning; and in fine, 
 as a perfect brief shows, a debate is an organic, logical 
 structure. 
 
 Since logic treats of the laws of reasoning, the rational 
 groundwork of the art of debate may be found in sys- 
 tematic shape in the science of logic. Its study there- 
 fore, if properly conducted, should mean for the de- 
 ^W. Stanley Jevons, "Elementary Lessons on Logic," p. ii.
 
 INTRODUCTORY 7 
 
 bater not only stability of foundation but a real gain 
 in argumentative skill. Speaking of Junius, Professor 
 Goodrich says: "His mind, in early life, had clearly 
 been subjected to the severest logical training, Corn^ 
 position, with him, was the creation of _ aL,^ ltem of 
 thought, in which everything is made subordinate to_ 
 a just order and sequence ot idea s. One thought grows 
 o'ut ot another in regular succession. His reasonings 
 often take the form of a syllogism, though usually with 
 the omission of one of the terms; and we never find 
 him betrayed into that careless diffusion of style so 
 common with those who are ignorant of the principles 
 of logic. In this respect, the writing of Junius will am'ply 
 repay the closest study and analysis. Let the young 
 orator enter completely into the scope and design of 
 the author. Let him watch the undercurrent of his 
 thoughts and feelings. Let him observe how perfectly 
 everything coincides to produce the desired impression 
 —the statement of principles and the reference to facts, 
 the shading of thought and the colorings of imagery. 
 Let him take one of the more striking passages and re- 
 mark the dexterous preparation by which each of its 
 several parts is so shaped that the leading thoughts 
 come forward to the best advantage — clear in all their 
 relations, standing boldly out, unencumbered by secon- 
 dary ideas, and thus fitted to strike the mind with full 
 and undivided force. Such a study of Junius will pre- 
 pare the young reader to enter into the logic of thought. 
 It will lead to the formation of a severe intellectual 
 taste, which is the best guard against the dangers of 
 hasty composition, and the still greater dangers of ex- 
 temporaneous speaking. Such speaking cannot be dis- 
 pensed with. On the contrary, it is becoming more
 
 8 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 and more essential to the success of public men in every 
 part of public life." ^ 
 
 Debating means also the expression of ideas in speech 
 or writing, and so must be classified as a species both 
 of oratory and of literary composition. It is well for 
 the college debater if he seeks to acquire the technic 
 both of the finished speaker and of the literary artist. 
 The distinguishing characteristics of debating as a type 
 of expression seem to lie in its argumentative and in 
 its dialogue character. Debating, however, is not only 
 an expression of ideas, but a presentation of them to 
 others; it is not only an appeal from reason to reason, 
 but from one state of consciousness to another state 
 of consciousness. The facts being known and their 
 relations, the question arises: "How shall I present 
 them? " The answer is that we may view logical reason- 
 ing and judgments as concepts, and image them sug- 
 gestively within the experience of the persons addressed. 
 Suggestion is the broadest term used for the process 
 of conveying our ideas to others. Since objects and 
 things, to which ideas refer, cannot always be present 
 to the senses, we are in the habit of recalling them to 
 consciousness by suggesting an image of our idea with 
 its understood meanings and with its natural associa- 
 tions. Imagination or the image-making process is 
 therefore a process of reducing general or abstract ideas 
 to sense-perception. It has a basis in feeling as well 
 as in memory, and furnishes the true method of gain- 
 ing interest and attention, as well as of producing con- 
 viction and beHef. Anterior to the associ ation _of ideas, 
 be it remembered," is the association of images, with 
 — cliildi eii, a-hd wilh a r tistg: 
 
 iC. A. Goodrich, "British Eloquence," p. 153.
 
 INTRODUCTORY 9 
 
 Psychologically, therefore, debating is the art of the 
 associative and suggestive or inhibiting imagination. 
 The successful arguer"will seek to remove all inhibitions', 
 of whatever sort, which tend to interfere with the ac- 
 ceptance by another, at their proper weight and value, 
 of the facts and logic of his case. He will also on his 
 own part seek to interpose objections which tend to 
 inhibit the case presented by his opponent. Psychology, 
 the ultimate basis of argument, is the science of mental 
 phenomena. 
 
 The media or symbols of imagery are words (written 
 or spoken) and gesture (including facial expression). 
 Their suggestions are carried by the physical vibrations 
 of light and sound. y 
 
 <^The same principle — adaptation — which causes the / 
 ^^;__Jeye to close when blinded by light, which makes one v 
 man succeed and another fail in the race of life, defines I 
 the good debater as the man who does the right thing V 
 at the right time — and in the right way. Arguments \ 
 are not absolute, but relative in character. ^^^ 
 
 Constructive Thinking. — Logical rigor is essential for 
 the foundation and structure of an argument, but it 
 should not be so stressed in the teaching of debating 
 as to interfere with the use and free play of the imagina- 
 tive powers nor with their growth and development. 
 
 Creative ability is more or less present in all men. 
 Fairy-tales and child myths find their counterpart among 
 older people in the projection of business enterprises 
 and idealistic plans in every sphere. Assuredly, the 
 man who debates needs to develop his analytical and 
 discriminating powers, but he will need more. I have 
 before me a report of a committee on prison reform 
 containing very detailed statements numbered from
 
 10 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 one to twelve, and giving conclusions and recommen- 
 dations as to facts and conditions. The preliminary 
 data based on a personal inspection of the prisons was 
 of course necessary to the making of sound recommen- 
 dations, but the recommendations which were made pre- 
 sented a new view of prison reform and in fact a new 
 prison. Thus, the data drawn from observation and ex- 
 perience were combined with new ideas in the minds of the 
 reform committee. Moreover, in presenting their report 
 to the assembly, they will defend their findings of things 
 as they unfortunately are in connection with their recom- 
 mendation as to what they would have them to be. Is 
 it not clear from this illustration that any theory of 
 argumentation which makes it one only of logical analy- 
 sis and logical classification is partial and inadequate? 
 Argument depends not only on past experience but 
 on past experience plus creative thinking applied to 
 the work at hand. Any other theory forced upon the 
 undeveloped student tends to dull and deaden his imag- 
 inative powers at the very time they are longing for 
 expression. The bird that does not learn to sing when 
 it is young rarely learns at all. Argument should be 
 taught as both analytic and synthetic, destructive and 
 constructive, and with a full appreciation of its psy- 
 chological and its logical basis. 
 
 Minds, Issues, and Audiences: Two Tjrpes. — There 
 are indeed two types of minds: the one conservative 
 and retrospective, the other progressive and prospec- 
 tive. The first type is guided by authority, habit, and 
 imitation, the second by the constructive and destruc- 
 tive tendencies in the changing world about us. The 
 one obeys fixed immutable, absolute, and dogmatic 
 principles or laws; the other, knowing that conditions
 
 INTRODUCTORY 11 
 
 are never identical except in purely scientific experi- 
 ments, recognizes first of all the facts perceived and or- 
 ganizes them at once into a clear conception or judg- 
 ment. It is naturally this second type— and it contains 
 geniuses and leaders of thought and action — which 
 sees the necessity and value of the argument from sign. 
 For they see in it as nearly as can be had an approxima- 
 tion to the reasoning which they constantly employ 
 and recognize as their own. 
 
 Just as there are two types of mind, there are two 
 types of opinion over which differences may arise, and 
 hence, two types of issues: issues of stability and issues 
 of change. To the first class belong the issues adjudicated 
 in law-courts, to the second the resolutions and bills 
 adopted by parhamentary assembfies. The issues in 
 academic debates are the issues of parliamentary bodies 
 — issues of change. And since the democracies of the 
 world are almost equally divided into great liberal 
 and conservative parties, the sharpest division which 
 we may make of audiences is also twofold : J'hose who 
 lo ok back before g oing forward, and those who go for- 
 ward withoutlooB ng back." ~~ " ' 
 
 Persuasion. — Persuasion may be defined as an ap- 
 peal for decision through logic and the emotional re- 
 actions to imagery. Psychologically, a speaker is related 
 to his hearers as stimulus to reaction; logically, as cause 
 to effect. The suggested images of objects which exist 
 in the external world may be necessary to enable others 
 to accept our ideas. Such images, moreover, may awaken 
 in others pleasurable or unpleasurable feelings with re- 
 gard to these ideas. Experience shows that in debating 
 it is almost impossible at times to avoid either an ex- 
 pression of our own feelings or an appeal of some sort
 
 12 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 to the feelings of others. The affirmative side, for in- 
 stance, will make use of the emotions of approbation; 
 the negative, those of disapprobation. A speaker ap- 
 peals to the emotions legitimately, when he does so to 
 overcome prejudice, to prevent fatigue, or otherwise 
 to facilitate thinking. Such appeals are at times not 
 only so instinctive as to be inevitable, but are essential 
 to the end in view — decision. They may create sym- 
 pathy or antagonism, suspense or surprise, desire, mo- 
 tive, or sheer determination of the will, but they should 
 always leave reason enthroned and be supported by 
 justice and right. 
 
 The Debater Himself. — As to the debater himself, 
 he should be a man of individuality, should possess con- 
 structive as well as analytical powers and, without run- 
 ning into the fallacies of the persuasive orator, should 
 always be able to give a personal touch which adds so 
 much to human interest. 
 
 No mere formal study of the elements of debate will 
 make a debater. No body of knowledge, no rules of 
 thinking, no principles of expression or suggestion can 
 take the place of the indefinable power of the speaker 
 himself. There is in every great orator, every great 
 debater, an individuality, a creative impulse which 
 masters formal rules so thoroughly that the mechanical 
 process — the technic — is lost in the earnest expression of 
 ideas and behefs. Facts, principles, illustrations, phrases, 
 rhythm, even processes of thought are all transmuted 
 by the alchemical power of the great artist, who knows, 
 who thinks, who feels, who images not after a pattern. 
 He combines what he gets from without with that which 
 comes from within and in so doing transforms and turns 
 into gold — true to reaHty, true to himself. Originality
 
 INTRODUCTORY 13 
 
 or genius is fed by innumerable sources, most of which 
 are too delicate, too subtle, too varied to be easily recog- 
 nized, even by the man himself, at the time. In addition 
 to formal rules, therefore, it is beheved that the growth 
 of such a power is to be encouraged in other ways, such 
 as by (i) familiarity and association, with the speeches 
 and writings of the great debaters and a careful study 
 and analysis of their productions, and (2) by frequent 
 practice in impromptu pubUc speaking and debate — 
 done under such circumstances and on such occasions 
 as will arouse and command the highest psychological 
 interest. 
 
 Plan of the Book 
 
 In one of his greatest speeches, Lincoln once said 
 with rare simpUcity and common sense: "If we could 
 first know where we are and whither we are tending, 
 we could better judge what to do and how to do it." 
 The larger divisions of the subject as treated in this 
 book are: (i) logical organization; and (2) presenta- 
 tion. 
 
 Under the term logical organization, we will con- 
 sider first, briefs and brief-making, or the analysis and 
 synthesis of a particular proof in a special skeletonized 
 form with its special features; second, arguments, or 
 the important types of associative processes which form 
 the basis of logical inference and which have been desig- 
 nated with special names as arguments; third, evidence, 
 or facts and opinions derived from others, as used in 
 debating in comparison and contrast with the prescribed 
 or customary use of evidence in courts of law. 
 
 We shall then perhaps be ready to consider the final 
 topic of presenting our ideas in an argument before an
 
 14 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 audience, or the subject of presentation. This will be 
 shown to involve imaginative suggestion, including, as 
 always, the need of adaptation to ends and circum- 
 stances. It involves further the viewing of our judg- 
 ments and reasons as concepts, for the purpose of bringing 
 them within local experience for recognition, compar- 
 ison, and decision. The presentation is treated in 
 chapters on imagination in argument, suggestion in ar- 
 gument, and the instruments of suggestion.
 
 PART I 
 LOGICAL ORGANIZATION 
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 
 
 Need of a Plan. — In our moments of appreciation 
 of any work of art, it is perhaps natural for us to think 
 of it more for itself than as the product of a mind that 
 had carefully planned and a hand that had skilfully 
 executed. And yet we know that every worthy artistic 
 product means skill both in designing and in execution. 
 In these respects, the art of composition closely resembles 
 the art of architecture. Just as the architect makes 
 his drawings and specifications in advance of the con- 
 struction of a building, so too the writer of any sub- 
 stantial work must give careful thought to the way his 
 material is to be put together, what purpose it is to 
 serve, and what impression it is to make when finished. 
 The plan of an argumentative composition when care- 
 fully worked out and with appropriate details is called 
 a brief; but a brief must follow certain elementary rules 
 of construction. It does not consist merely of a few 
 "speaking notes," but should be so full in material and 
 so exact in statement and in suggestion of method as 
 to be intelligible and convincing to another. 
 
 15
 
 IG THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 The Brief Defined. — The brief of an argument is 
 the record of the analysis, classification, and arrange- 
 ment of everything of importance which is necessary 
 to the explanation of the issues and to the process of 
 proof. It should disclose the material to be employed 
 as evidence; it should indicate in the clearest fashion 
 the method of the process; and it should be in the form 
 of a series of propositions put together according to 
 some plan and arranged in such a sequence as to pro- 
 duce a single and cumulative effect. It is analogous to 
 the plans and specifications of the architect. 
 
 The Making of a Brief. — The elements of a good brief 
 are a valuable subject-matter, a logical method, and an 
 artistic form. Of these the first two are controlhng; 
 for aside from mere details of exterior adornment, the 
 form of a brief is determined largely by its material 
 and its structure. Here, again, the brief resembles a 
 work of architecture; for the form of a building depends 
 of course upon the material of which it is built and its 
 mode of design and construction. Compare, for instance, 
 the workman's "tool shanty" with the massive stone 
 structure standing beside it. The material which is 
 organized into a brief should be drawn not merely from 
 a fund of general knowledge, but should be acquired 
 by diligent reading and study. There is a value or force 
 of argument in the subject-matter quite apart from 
 the way such matter is put together. It was said of 
 Burke, that one could hardly stop with him during a 
 thunder-shower under an awning without being im- 
 pressed with the idea that he was the most learned man 
 in England. The brief -maker should endeavor to know 
 everything of value pertaining to his subject; he should 
 be saturated with his material.
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 17 
 
 I. The Process 
 
 The chief steps in the process of brief-making are: 
 (i) Analysis, constructive and destructive; (2) Clas- 
 sification; (3) Arrangement. 
 
 I. Analysis. — The first step in brief-making is analy- 
 sis, by which is meant the separation of everything per- 
 taining to the subject into its component parts and 
 isolating them for the purpose of studying (i) their 
 truth and (2) their relations. 
 
 The unit of the brief is the proposition. It is not 
 meant by this that a proposition is indivisible, for it 
 can be separated into its terms; but rather that it is 
 the necessary unit of any formal course of reasoning, as 
 a premise or a conclusion. We cannot argue, for in- 
 stance, from or to the single idea or term, war, but we 
 may, however, argue from the proposition that war is 
 an evil to the conclusion that, let us say, war should be 
 abolished. 
 
 The first consideration then in the making of a brief 
 on any subject is: 
 
 A complete analysis of the subject itself, involving: 
 
 A. An analysis of all the propositions necessary to sustain 
 
 the side of the case which the brief-maker is attempting 
 to establish. 
 
 B. A complete analysis of all the propositions which an op- 
 
 ponent is obliged to establish in order to sustain his 
 side of the case. 
 
 Just as it is necessary, in order to understand the com- 
 plete workings of any mechanism, to take apart and 
 examine its parts separately, so it is necessary to any
 
 18 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 general mental conception of a subject to separate this 
 conception into all the various steps of reasoning by 
 which such mental conception is reached as a conclu- 
 sion. 
 
 If you are obliged to establish either the affirmative 
 or negative of any proposition, this analysis is neces- 
 sary, in order that you may, first, ascertain the strength 
 or weakness of the various propositions necessary in 
 order to establish the conclusion which you are bound 
 to prove; and second, see the proper relation which each 
 proposition bears to the conclusion that you are bound 
 to sustain and thus be in a position, when you reach 
 the constructive part of the argument, to arrange the 
 same in such relation with ease. 
 
 After you have thoroughly tested by analysis the 
 strength of your own case, the same analytical test should 
 be applied to your opponent's case, for the same reasons 
 and this additional one: it is only by analysis that any 
 latent defect in an opponent's structure can be deter- 
 mined; and such analysis, before proceeding with the 
 brief, will make the brief-maker's work in this regard 
 simply a matter of establishing the authority or evidence 
 which proves the inherent defect, or in the event that 
 such inherent defect is a non sequitur, or is otherwise 
 illogically supported, then the brief-maker's construc- 
 tive work will be merely a matter of exposing the fal- 
 lacy discovered. 
 
 After this introductory work, the brief-maker is pre- 
 pared to construct his brief, and his work is usually 
 constructive or destructive. 
 
 2. Classification. — A second consideration in the 
 making of a brief is classification, involving: (i) The 
 classification of the propositions to be presented in sus-
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 19 
 
 taining the side of the case which the brief-maker is 
 attempting to estabhsh; (2) the classification of the 
 propositions which an opponent is obhged to establish 
 in order to sustain his side of the case. 
 
 Instead of writing down a short Ust of unassorted 
 reasons or ill-digested bits of evidence, the brief-maker 
 should attempt to synthetize his material, to reduce it 
 to principles, to classify it; and so put it into the form 
 of a few main headings or points, easy to understand 
 and to remember, and which will give a view of his case 
 as a whole. These main divisions, of course, must be 
 so chosen that when properly supported they will form 
 a proof of the case. 
 
 If an opponent's case is to be understood and an- 
 swered most eft'ectively it is equally necessary that the 
 propositions essential to an opponents case should be 
 made clear and simple through this same process of 
 classification. 
 
 After the main headings are formed, the brief should 
 be filled in; that is, the other propositions studied as 
 supporting reasons, should be put in a logical sequence, 
 classified, when possible, and inserted in the brief in 
 their proper places and series as subheadings. 
 
 ILLUSTRATION A 
 
 BODY OF PROOF 
 
 The removal of troops is necessary, because: 
 
 I. It will show the willingness of the English to treat 
 
 amicably. 
 II. The resistance of the Americans was necessary. 
 III. The means of enforcing the measures of Parliament 
 have failed.
 
 20 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 IV. If Parliament tries by the aid of the army to enforce 
 its measures the result will be bad. 
 
 V. The statement that "the union in America cannot last" 
 is untrue. 
 
 VI. The statement that the Americans should be punished 
 for illegal violence is untrue. 
 
 VII. This removal of the troops must precede any other step. 
 
 VIII. The views of Congress are moderate and reasonable. 
 
 IX. It is an old maxim that the first concession comes most 
 freely from the superior. 
 
 X. While every policy urges withdrawal of the troops every 
 danger warns the English from keeping to the old 
 course. 
 
 In this illustration, it is apparent (i) that the points 
 are too numerous. The mind cannot readily carry 
 as many as ten reasons for accepting a conclusion. 
 This is so, even where the sequences are obvious. But 
 here, again (2), the sequences are not obvious. The 
 mind is carried forward by uneven steps, with a result- 
 ing jolt to the attention. For instance, while the first 
 reason offered to prove the need of removing the troops 
 asserts clearly that "it will show the willingness of the 
 English to treat amicably," the second asserting that 
 "the resistance of the Americans was necessary" does 
 not seem to come naturally after the first, and does not 
 appear to be a reason at all for the necessity of remov- 
 ing the troops. To put it in another way, the two 
 propositions do not belong in the same logical series. 
 Any plan which is to form the synthesis of the materials 
 into a logical proof must not be a mere enumeration 
 or catalogue of points. The main points must be stated 
 in an easy sequence, and so classified as to be few in 
 number and easily comprehended.
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 21 
 
 ILLUSTRATION B 
 
 BODY OF PROOF 
 
 The measure proposing the immediate withdrawal of troops 
 should be adopted, for: 
 
 I. Measures preparatory to peace and prosperity should be 
 
 adopted. 
 II. This measure is preparatory to peace and prosperity, for: 
 
 A. This measure will be conciliatory, for: 
 
 I. It will show our willingness to treat amicably. 
 
 B. Only conciliatory measures are preparatory to peace 
 
 and prosperity, for: 
 
 1. All other plans will fail, for: 
 
 a. Force is unwise.. 
 
 b. Inaction will avail nothing. 
 
 c. Coercion is unwarranted. 
 
 2. The remaining plan, conciliation, will succeed if we 
 
 withdraw the troops as a first step. 
 
 From illustration B it is apparent that classification 
 involves two steps — co-ordination and subordination. 
 For instance, since the main points of a brief are in a 
 logical sequence, they should appear in the brief as co- 
 ordinate. Then, for the next, or lower, order each main 
 proposition should be supported by a minor proposition 
 or sequence of propositions immediately subordinate 
 to it. If there is a series of such minor propositions 
 immediately subordinate to a main proposition, all such 
 propositions should be co-ordinated in the brief. They 
 must be classified as subordinate to the main proposi- 
 tion immediately above it and placed in sequence. This 
 double process of co-ordination and subordination is 
 continued in the other orders until the proof is com- 
 plete. In this view, a brief is a regular series of parallel
 
 22 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 and descending propositions by which the mind may, 
 by natural and even stages, reach the main conclu- 
 sion. 
 
 Illustration B is, of course, not an illustration of a 
 complete proof of the case, but rather of a mode of clas- 
 sification through co-ordination and subordination. It 
 will be noted, too, that the method of classification here 
 employed for the headings I, II, and A and B consists 
 (i) in laying down a general principle; (2) in making 
 a particular statement which is included within the 
 general principle. 
 
 There are various ways of classifying. The experi- 
 enced debater is quick to perceive that his arguments, 
 however diversified or compHcated they may seem, 
 are reducible to a few simple headings or categories, 
 which may be stated in the form of a proposition. Some 
 of the simple and most common methods may be in- 
 dicated: 
 
 The plan proposed should be adopted, because: 
 
 1. It is necessary. 
 
 2. It is desirable. 
 
 1. It is sound in theory. 
 
 2. It will work well in practice. 
 
 1. It is sanctioned by authority. 
 
 2. It is sanctioned by reason. 
 
 It is demanded for (i) political reasons. 
 
 (2) social reasons. 
 
 (3) economic reasons. 
 
 Its effect will be good upon (i) the state. 
 
 (2) the nation.
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 23 
 
 1. There is need of a remedy for existing evils. 
 
 2. The plan proposed will remedy existing evils. 
 
 3. The plan proposed will remedy existing evils better than 
 
 any other plan. 
 
 Such illustrations may be extended almost indefinitely. 
 Those given are merely suggestive. 
 
 3. Arrangement. — A third consideration in the making 
 of a brief is an arrangement for climax. 
 
 The grouping of the main divisions of a proof should 
 be made not only in accord with some central idea, but 
 these divisions should be arranged in such an order that 
 there vdll be a growth of thought, an onward movement. 
 
 The most common or t3^pical arrangement is that 
 in which the main parts rise or grow successively in 
 importance or force. There are variations from the 
 type; but in all cases a composition should gain an 
 increasing hold on the attention and interest of the 
 audience. Indeed, there must be in the mind of the 
 brief-maker, from the beginning and throughout, some 
 general plan or mode of procedure so conceived and 
 developed as to secure for the composition as a whole 
 the highest cumulative effectiveness. Likewise it is 
 desirable that whenever possible the subheadings should, 
 also, be arranged in the order of climcix. 
 
 We cannot reason without either progress or unity. 
 We get nowhere, for instance, by repeating the sentence: 
 "All men are mortal." If, however, after declaring 
 that all men are mortal, we add simply that Mr. Jones 
 is a man, we have taken a step forward which allows us 
 to conclude that, therefore, Mr. Jones is mortal. We 
 have done this, moreover, through the central or unify- 
 ing idea that Mr. Jones is a man, that is, belongs to the 
 class, man, known to be mortal. Further, where there
 
 24 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 is a series of such arguments, and — as is usually the 
 case — an option as to the order of arrangement, the 
 brief-maker will invariably choose the order of climax 
 as sanctioned by experience and by common sense. Take, 
 for example, the First Letter in which Junius attacked 
 the King and his ministry. When he was attempting 
 to prove that "the true cause of our misfortunes lies 
 in the distribution of the departments of state," there 
 was no inevitable order, from a logical standpoint, in 
 which all the heads of the departments must be taken 
 up. Junius chose an order of climax. He began with 
 the Duke of Grafton, first lord of the treasury, and Lord 
 North, chancellor of the exchequer; then he took up, 
 in turn, Hillsborough of the foreign department, Wey- 
 mouth of the home department, Granby of the army, 
 Hawke of the navy, and finally the powerful and able 
 Lord Mansfield, head of the department of justice. 
 
 Without interfering with the logic of the case, the 
 use of climax is grounded in sound principles of psy- 
 chology which lie at the basis of art. Practically, this 
 means that a climactic order is calculated to reach after 
 the waning attention and interest of the reader or hearer 
 at the time when he is becoming inattentive or disin- 
 terested, through fatigue. 
 
 II. The Result 
 
 The marks of a good brief, and therefore the ends 
 to be striven for by the brief-maker, are: (i) Unity, 
 (2) Logical sequence, (3) Proportion. 
 
 These principles are not only logical but aesthetic 
 in their nature. They underlie, slightly modified (unity, 
 continuity, proportion), the technic of such arts, for 
 example, as architecture, sculpture, and painting. In
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 25 
 
 the text-books on English composition they are gen- 
 erally treated as the most important principles which 
 can be laid down for writing "whole compositions," 
 not only because they are regarded as essential marks 
 of a good structure, but because when properly applied, 
 they afford a certain literary delight. Thus, a finished 
 argmnentative composition, whose chief aim is con- 
 viction, may through skill in design and workmanship 
 appeal also to the aesthetic sense. 
 
 1 . Unity. — The first principle determining the form of 
 the brief is unity. One dominant idea or related group 
 of ideas will guide, direct, and centralize the attention 
 of the mind and hold the interest. Such a structure 
 strikes the mind with single, undivided, force. Every 
 part adds to and helps to complete the whole. In his 
 own mind the brief-maker has taken the machine apart 
 by the analytical process which he has practised before 
 starting work. By the machine I mean the material 
 to be employed in the proof. This material has been 
 not only separated into propositions but in some way 
 grouped or classified. Now all these parts must be 
 properly united; nothing must be left out. And when 
 the structure is complete, it stands out as one complete 
 whole, each integer present in the unit. 
 
 2. Logical Sequence. — The second principle deter- 
 mining the form of the brief is logical sequence. Often 
 there are various ways in which the machine may be 
 constructed so that it will work; hence, the best ar- 
 rangement of the parts must be found. The value of 
 a logical arrangement is that it is a step-by-step process 
 in which each rung of the ladder appears in its proper 
 place, making it possible for a reader to climb regularly 
 and methodically to the top— the conclusion. This
 
 26 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 logical sequence tends to make for clearness; it also 
 makes the conclusion and the processes more easily 
 retained in the memory. But particularly for the reader 
 of a brief, it obviates the necessity of retracing one's 
 steps and reading over again, several pages back, propo- 
 sitions which, if they had been placed in their proper 
 order, would have been easily understood and retained. 
 
 3. Proportion. — The third principle governing form 
 is proportion. This principle requires that space in 
 the brief shall be allotted according to the needs of the 
 proof. It necessitates cutting out and filling in; and 
 requires careful attention and good judgment. 
 
 The object of a brief is to convince, and conviction 
 is attained by a step-by-step process from one proposi- 
 tion to another. Now some of these steps require con- 
 siderable support by the brief-maker before he can make 
 it seem to another safe to stand upon them. Others 
 require very Httle support for that purpose, and still 
 others are axiomatic and require none. 
 
 A brief which does not give to each step its proper 
 amount of support and no more, is necessarily out of 
 proportion. Too much elucidation and proof of simple 
 propositions is apt to tire the reader who has to climb 
 the ladder, and might result, and often does in court 
 cases, in a refusal to take the other steps and a return to 
 the ground. 
 
 Too little elucidation leaves too much to the reason- 
 ing process of the reader; and in case his mental equip- 
 ment or general knowledge is inadequate, he may re- 
 gard his footing as unsafe, and refuse to proceed further. 
 
 What has been said in regard to the steps necessary 
 to reach any conclusion is equally true when there are
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 27 
 
 several points to be established, when there are several 
 ladders to climb. Frequently there are one or more 
 ladders which it is much more important that the reader 
 should cUmb than all the others which have been offered 
 to him. A brief which gives more space and time to 
 the unimportant than to these one or two important 
 ladders is of course out of proportion. The most im- 
 portant propositions are apt to be those supported by 
 argimients of greatest difficulty or complexity, of greatest 
 force, or of greatest cogency. 
 
 In conclusion, it may be said that while much de- 
 pends upon analysis, classification, arrangement, unity, 
 sequence, and proportion, the fact must never be lost 
 sight of that no finished brief-maker will stop there. 
 The finesse of the art, of which all these things are the 
 soKd structure, is in making the brief so thoroughly 
 readable, so happy in its selection of words and phrases, 
 so clear in its expression, that it is a pleasure to read it, 
 that it entertains while it elucidates, that it dehghts 
 while it convinces, for the human element in all readers 
 is such that intellectual delight will make the road to 
 comaction much easier. A brief will be much more 
 thoroughly read if it dehghts and entertains while it 
 elucidates and convinces. 
 
 III. Process and Result 
 
 Unity. — The most important principle of structure 
 is unity. This is true both from the standpoint of the 
 process and the result. With a single exception, all 
 the ideas hitherto mentioned as involved in brief-making 
 (analysis, classification, logical sequence, and propor-
 
 28 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 tion) are contributory to unity and the means of ob- 
 taining it. If, then, we inquire how unity is to be ob- 
 tained, the answer is: 
 
 1. By the separating and combining process of analy- 
 sis and classification, so that the various logical sequences, 
 horizontal and perpendicular, lead the mind inevitably 
 to one thing — the conclusion — no logical breaks, no 
 disproportion; and 
 
 2. By an expression in language which adequately 
 records the above unified mental conceptions. In ar- 
 gument or debate unity of thought fails without unity 
 of expression. 
 
 a. It is perhaps a truism to say that all such con- 
 ceptions should be expressed with clearness and pre- 
 cision. It is not, however, a truism but a truth to say 
 that the brief-maker may use such apt and striking 
 forms of expressions that they will easily arrest the at- 
 tention and stick in the memory. Indeed a sharp, terse, 
 and sometimes an antithetical statement will often so 
 arrest the attention that it will remain in the mem- 
 ory long after the body of the proof has been for- 
 gotten. 
 
 h. But these conceptions must be expressed in lan- 
 guage which will not only reveal themselves but which 
 \^dll also disclose their relations to other propositions; 
 for, in a brief no proposition stands alone, each is re- 
 lated to another and to the whole. And always to show 
 the relationships involved requires good workmanship. 
 Indeed, where a number of conceptions are to be stated 
 as in a brief, and stated of course successively, he is 
 really an artist in language who can relate them all so 
 aptly and in such a manner as to impress the reader 
 with an idea of the whole. ''Clear thinking," valuable
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 29 
 
 as it is, does not necessarily mean clear writing; for, good 
 writing requires the work both of a good architect and 
 a good carpenter. 
 
 There are a few formal rules of rhetoric, which are 
 supposed to afford some help in giving expression to 
 conceptions, which in the mind are properly classified, 
 and stand in their proper sequence. They are: 
 
 (i) Parallel structure, or phrasing every one of a 
 series of conceptions in any sequence in a similar form 
 of language; (2) emphasizing the relation between 
 propositions by hack references, involving repetitions of 
 phrases or ideas, the use of this, that, these, those, the 
 former, the latter, such a, etc., (3) and joining proposi- 
 tions by the use of conjunctions — because, for, since, 
 but, moreover, and beside, etc. 
 
 For an apphcation of these rules the student is re- 
 ferred to the specimen brief on the First Junius Letter 
 and the other briefs in this volume. He may, however, 
 for himself apply them by taking, let us say, the six 
 capital causes for the colonists' love of Hberty in Burke's 
 speech on conciliation, formulating the six causes enu- 
 merated, in carefully phrased propositions. 
 
 The following extract from Matthew Arnold's essay 
 on "The Function of Criticism at the Present Time" 
 will illustrate a dexterous use of these devices. A httle 
 study of the italicized words will show by what means 
 the main proposition is here made to appear so closely 
 related both to its supporting propositions in this para- 
 graph and to the main proposition of the essay. 
 
 It is of Ihe last importance that English criticism should 
 clearly discern what rule for its course, in order to avail itself 
 of the field now opening to it, and to produce fruit for the future, 
 it ought to take. The rule may be summed up in one word —
 
 30 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 disinterestedness, (i) And how is criticism to show disinterested- 
 ness ? By keeping aloof from what is called " the practical view" 
 of things; by resolutely following the law of its own nature, 
 which is to be a free play of the mind on all subjects which it 
 touches. By steadily refusing to lend itself to any of those 
 ulterior, political, practical considerations about ideas, which 
 plenty of people will be sure to attach to them, which perhaps 
 ought often to be attached to them, which in this country at 
 any rate are certain to be attached to them quite sufficiently, 
 but which criticism has really nothing to do with. Its business 
 is, as I have said, simply to know the best that is known and thought 
 in the world, and by in its turn making this known, to create 
 a current of true and fresh ideas. Its business is to do this with 
 inflexible honesty, with due ability; but its business is to do 
 no more, and to leave alone all questions of practical consequences 
 and applications, questions which will never fail to have due 
 prominence given to them. Else criticism, besides being really 
 false to its own nature, merely continues in the old rut which 
 it has hitherto followed in this country, and will certainly miss 
 the chance now given to it. (2) For what is at present the bane 
 of criticism in this country? It is that practical considerations 
 cling to it and stifle it. It subserves interests not its own. Our 
 organs of criticism are organs of men and parties having prac- 
 tical ends to serve, and with them those practical ends are the 
 first thing and the play of mind the second; so much play of 
 mind as is compatible with the prosecution of those practical 
 ends is all that is wanted. An organ like the Revue des Deux 
 Mondes, having for its main function to understand and utter 
 the best that is known and thought in the world, existing, it may 
 be said, as just an organ, for a. free play of the mind, we have not. 
 But we have the Edinburgh Review, existing as an organ of the 
 old Whigs. . . . No other criticism will ever attain any real 
 authority or make any real way toward its end — the creating a 
 current of true and fresh ideas. 
 
 Climax. — It has been said that all the ideas previously 
 mentioned as involved in brief-making (analysis, clas- 
 sification, logical sequence, and proportion), with a soli- 
 tary exception, contribute to unity and are the means
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 31 
 
 of obtaining it. This exception is arrangement in the 
 order of climax. 
 
 The term climax means either one of two things: 
 (i) A mode of arrangement in which the parts grow or 
 rise successively in importance or force, or (2) the final 
 or last part of such an arrangement. It is either a ladder 
 in which the rungs are strengthened as we ascend, or 
 the top rung of such a ladder. 
 
 In making a brief, it is frequently not the sole de- 
 sideratum that the propositions should be arranged in 
 a logical sequence. There may be several modes of 
 arrangement all of which are strictly logical, so that 
 the brief-maker may have offered to him a choice of 
 arrangements. He will then doubtless select the ar- 
 rangement which he believes will be most effective. 
 
 Climax seems to be a perfectly natural process. Even 
 in driving a nail, the last stroke is often the hardest. 
 And as an informal discussion proceeds, it is apt to grow 
 in warmth. Climax is an attempt either to overcome 
 any possible lack of interest or fatigue as a discourse 
 proceeds, or to make the final impression the strongest. 
 Climax is generally recognized and employed in fiction, 
 in the drama, and in the sonnet as well as in public 
 speaking and debate. 
 
 Two Laws of Structure. — If unity consists in direct- 
 ing all parts naturally toward one thing — the conclu- 
 sion — climax is a progressive unity. It looks not only 
 toward a single but a cumulative effect. The process 
 presupposes unity, presupposes progress. Indeed, Cole- 
 ridge long ago expressed clearly the principles under- 
 lying the expression of thought in composition, when 
 he said that the essential marks of method are "unity 
 with a progression," Thus, it would appear that the
 
 32 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 fundamental Laws of Siruclure are two: Unity and 
 Climax. 
 
 IV. Rules for Brief-Making 
 
 The Three Main Parts of a Brief. — The propositions 
 of a brief fall into three separate divisions; first, those 
 which explain the issue; second, those which present 
 evidence in proof of the issue; and third, those which 
 sum up. The first set of propositions would constitute 
 an Introduction, the second set a Body of Proof, and 
 the third a Conclusion. These, then, make three main 
 parts for a brief. 
 
 I. The Introduction. — The process employed in the 
 introduction is entirely different from that used in the 
 body of proof. The one is exposition; the other is argu- 
 ment. Its function is to explain whatever is necessary 
 to an understanding of the issues. It must contain no 
 matter of a disputable character. Given a question 
 (carefully formulated), the problem is to lead the mind 
 by natural sequence, through steps carefully marked, 
 to a full understanding of the specific point or points 
 in dispute. The great aim should be impartiality of 
 attitude, clearness of expression, and orderliness of struc- 
 ture. 
 
 In the academic debates upon questions of public 
 policy, the steps usually employed may be briefly in- 
 dicated. First, the situation, including the origin of 
 the question, is explained. Second, since any ambiguity 
 in, or ignorance of, the exact meaning of an essential 
 term may result in confusion, the next step is to define 
 or expound all such terms. And third, since the dis- 
 cussion of apparently related and of admitted proposi- 
 tions would obscure the issue, it is necessary to eliminate
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 33 
 
 them. And finally, as a consequence of these three 
 steps, the specific issue, or issues, may be stated in exact 
 form. The introduction, then, consists of: 
 
 I. The situation, involving the origin of the question, 
 
 II. Definition of words, or exposition of phrases, contained 
 in the statement of the question or to be employed in 
 the discussion. 
 
 III. The elimination. 
 
 A. Of admitted propositions. 
 
 B. Of extraneous propositions. 
 
 IV. The formal statement of the specific issue, or issues. 
 
 II. TIic Body or Brief Proper. — The function of the 
 body of a brief is to set forth formally for the inspec- 
 tion of another all the means and processes employed 
 as the proof or compelling reason for accepting the main 
 conclusion. It consists of the propositions to be proved 
 and the subject-matter of their proof, each proposition 
 stated in the form of reasons, and all the propositions 
 so carefully correlated as readily to disclose the nature, 
 relevancy, and force of each part of the proof, and the 
 proof as a whole. 
 
 Rule I. The headings should be in the form of a 
 declarative statement or proposition; not mere topics. 
 
 Rule II. The headings should read as reasons; the 
 correct order being first, proposition; then, proof, and 
 the correct connectives being because, for, since, etc. 
 
 Rule III. The headings should be carefully cor- 
 related and marked in order by appropriate symbols: 
 I, II, III, etc.; A, B, C, etc.; i, 2, 3, etc.; a, h, c, etc.; 
 
 (i), (2), (3), etc. 
 Rule IV. The main headings should be statements,
 
 34 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 carefully phrased to include the proof to follow; and 
 they should be few in number. 
 
 Rule V. Each main heading should be elaborated 
 or developed by subordinate headings until its truth 
 is made apparent. 
 
 Rule VI. Refutation, if used at length, should be 
 indicated by marking the proposition to which it ap- 
 plies with the word "Refutation," or it may appear 
 in the brief in its proper place stated as the negative 
 of the proposition to be refuted. 
 
 III. The Conclusion. — The function of the conclu- 
 sion is to sum up. It consists usually of a restatement 
 of the propositions used as main headings in the body 
 of the proof. 
 
 It is sometimes possible, however, to vary the re- 
 capitulation from such an obvious process. As, for 
 example, by drawing some inference from the main 
 headings in combination; making some effective ap- 
 plication of them; comparing them for the purpose of 
 emphasizing one in particular as most important, or 
 decisive in turning the scale; or illustrating them in 
 relation to some underlying principle or course of reason- 
 ing. However varied the method, the purpose of the 
 conclusion is always that of a summary. 
 
 SPECIMEN BRIEF 
 
 ON THE REMOVAL OF TROOPS^ 
 
 Introduction 
 I. The Ministry have at length after long delay condescended 
 
 to submit to this House news from America. 
 II. The present alarming state of America is due to the mis- 
 advice of the Ministry, for 
 A. It is based on misrepresentation. 
 
 1 Drawn from Lord Chatham's address delivered in the House of 
 Lords, January 20, 1775.
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 35 
 
 III. To rescue my unhappy country and his Majesty from 
 the misadvice of his ministers I submit to him through 
 this House "An address to his Majesty for the imme- 
 diate removal of the troops from Boston." 
 
 IV. The crisis is so pressing and urgent as to admit of no de- 
 lay. 
 
 V. My contention is not for indulgence but justice, for 
 
 A. I admit that obedience is properly due from America — 
 
 an obedience limited, however, to our laws of trade 
 and navigation, but 
 
 B. 1 contend that the property of the Americans must 
 
 remain sacred — that is, taxable by their own consent 
 given in their provincial assemblies. 
 
 VI. The specific issue is the restoration of peace and pros- 
 
 perity by the adoption of this measure proposing the 
 immediate withdrawal of troops from Boston. 
 
 Argument 
 
 The measure proposing the immediate withdrawal of the 
 troops from Boston should be adopted, because 
 
 I. Just measures preparatory to peace and prosperity should 
 
 be adopted. 
 II. This just measure is preparatory to peace and prosperity, 
 for 
 
 A. This measure, if adopted, will be conciliatory, for 
 
 I. It will show our willingness to treat amicably and 
 equitably. 
 
 B. Conciliatory measures are preparatory to peace and 
 
 prosperity, for 
 
 1. It is necessary to show our willingness to treat 
 
 amicably and equitably, for 
 a. Your own declarations and doctrines have made 
 American resistance necessary and will in fu- 
 ture be as ineflfective. 
 
 2. All other plans will fail, for 
 a. Force is unwise, for 
 
 (i). The army is held in contempt, and 
 (2). General Gage must not act. 
 
 (o). The first drop of blood means civil war.
 
 36 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 (3). If reconciliation is attempted, it must be done im- 
 mediately. 
 (4). If Parliament tries to enforce its measures by means 
 of the army, the results will be bad, for 
 (a). If they were victorious, it would be over an 
 
 embittered people, but 
 (b). The troops are not strong enough to resist the 
 people, because of 
 Their numbers, their unity and courage, and 
 their descent from people who left their na- 
 tive land to escape tyranny. 
 (5). It must fail, for it is an unjust persecution. 
 b. Inaction on the part of England will avail us nothing, 
 for 
 (i). The assertion that the union in America cannot 
 last is false, for 
 (a). The evidence of the so-called "commercial 
 
 bodies" is unreliable, for 
 (b). They are not representative, and 
 (c). They are paid agents of the government. 
 (2). Even the evidence of the real commercial class 
 would be untrustworthy, for 
 (a). The farming class represents the real strength 
 
 of the country, and 
 (b). The American farmers are united for liberty, 
 for 
 The testimony of Dr. Franklin upholds it. 
 C. Coercion is unwarranted, for 
 
 (i). Even if illegal violences have been committed in 
 America, a policy of coercion should not be fol- 
 lowed, for 
 (o). An opportunity for reconciliation should not be 
 
 missed. 
 (b). A whole people should not be punished for the 
 
 faults of a few. 
 (c). Such severity will arouse the unappeasable 
 
 wrath of all the Colonies. 
 (d). Even if the army is victorious, it cannot control 
 \ the great tracts of conquered country.
 
 BRIEFS AND BRIEF-MAKING 37 
 
 (e). Resistance to such measures ought to have 
 been foreseen. 
 It is the animating principle of all men of Eng- 
 lish stock to resist taxation without the con- 
 sent of the taxed. 
 (/), This resistance will become too strong to be 
 overcome, for 
 The English Whigs will aid them, since the 
 spirit that moves the Americans has always 
 belonged to them. 
 The Irish will aid them, for they have always 
 maintained the ideas the Americans support. 
 (g). England has a right only to regulate the com- 
 merce and navigation of the Americans, for 
 Their property is private, individual, and ab- 
 solute. 
 (h). The means to oppose this united body is weak, for 
 A few regiments in America and 18,000 men 
 at home must oppose 3,000,000 Americans, 
 millions of Englishmen, and all the Irish, and 
 The tricks of the Ministry against it must fail. 
 The remaining plan, conciliation, will succeed if we 
 withdraw the troops from Boston as a first step, for 
 
 a. It is the main cause of the fear and the resentment 
 
 of the Americans, for 
 (i). While the troops remain, resentment will re- 
 main. 
 
 b. Even if the Colonies should concede, her conces- 
 
 sions would be suspicious and unsecure, for 
 (i). They would be the dictates of fear and ex- 
 tortions of force. 
 
 c. Servitude cannot be imposed upon such men as 
 
 compose the American Congress at Philadel- 
 phia, for 
 (i). They have shown solidity of reasoning, force 
 of sagacity, and wisdom of conclusion, un- 
 der such a complication of diflicult circum- 
 stances. 
 
 1"h^
 
 38 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 d. Concession should come from England first, for 
 (i). Concession from a superior power reconciles 
 the feelings of men and establishes confi- 
 dence in it. 
 
 Conclusion 
 
 I. Every motive, therefore, of justice and of policy, of dignity 
 and of prudence, urges the removal of the troops from 
 Boston, the repeal of the acts of ParUament, and a demon- 
 stration of amicable dispositions toward the Colonies. 
 
 A. Disturbances in America may mean foreign war, for 
 
 I. France and Spain are watching for an advantageous 
 chance to interfere. 
 
 B. And it also may mean domestic trouble, for 
 
 1. The king will aUenate the afifections of his subjects 
 
 and will lose his power. 
 
 2. The nation will be utterly undone.
 
 CHAPTER III 
 ARGUMENT 
 
 The View-Point. — Argument, it has been said, is a proc- 
 ess of resohdng differences of opinion by means of as- 
 sertion and denial, followed by proof and counter-proof 
 or distinctions. In one aspect, this process consists sim- 
 ply in suggesting to another the relations which exist be- 
 tween two or more ideas or judgments so as to enable 
 him to form a correct opinion concerning some partic- 
 ular matter of uncertainty or disagreement. 
 
 On the basis of the kind of relations thus employed, 
 argum-cnts may be divided into four classes, as follows: 
 
 1. Arguments involving the relation of simple as- 
 sociation. 
 
 2. Arguments involving the relation of resemblance 
 or contrast. 
 
 3. Arguments involving the relation of cause and 
 effect, antecedent and consequent, or motive and deed. 
 
 4. Arguments involving the relation of particular 
 and general. 
 
 Though arguments are thus easily classified into four 
 definite groups, it is not to be supposed that these groups 
 are commonly exclusive. For all arguments, in their 
 final analysis and when carried to completion, will in- 
 volve an inference from the complex relations of asso- 
 ciation, resemblance or contrast, particular and gen- 
 eral, and cause and effect. 
 
 For example, if we should conclude, because of the 
 
 39
 
 40 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 issuance of smoke from a chimney, that there was a 
 fire below, we should find on analysis that our reasoning, 
 when fully developed, might easily involve these four- 
 fold relations: 
 
 1. Smoke means fire — (association). 
 
 2. In other cases where I have found smoke I have found 
 
 fire — (resemblance) . 
 
 3. Smoke is an effect produced only by fire — (cause and ef- 
 
 fect). 
 
 4. Where there is smoke there is fire — (particular and gen- 
 
 eral). 
 
 The conclusion that there is fire, here drawn from 
 the presence of smoke, involves fundamentally an in- 
 ference grounded in all four of the relations mentioned. 
 Similarly, an argument based first on the resemblance 
 between two parallel cases may be shown to involve 
 the relation of particular and general, and also of cause 
 and effect. Moreover, all inductive reasoning (that is, 
 from particular to general) involves finally a search 
 for a cause. 
 
 While it is ideally true that every argument may in- 
 volve all these relations, it does not follow that every 
 argument must always set them forth. In practice, 
 arguments may not be developed sufficiently to suggest 
 all the relations involved, for two reasons: 
 
 1. Because it is sometimes impossible from a sheer 
 inadequacy of knowledge. 
 
 2. Because it is not necessary or desirable for the 
 accompHshment of the object in view. 
 
 The reasoner or investigator will sometimes associate 
 things together— the causes of which and the principles 
 underlying which he does not know— and still feel justi-
 
 ARGUMENT 41 
 
 fied in drawing conclusions from the slight relationship 
 he does recognize. Otherwise he could not go forward, 
 and tlie problem would be at a standstill. As instinct 
 or feeling precedes positive proof, so a very slight reason 
 may point the way to truth and behef. This is so not 
 merely in ordinary affairs, but even in science, as, for 
 instance, in the following conclusion in the field of 
 zoolog>' : 
 
 The presence of occipital condyles is uniformly associated 
 with the presence of mammal and of warm red blood, and this 
 general fact is treated as a quasi-induction. Hence when the 
 remains of a new animal are discovered, exhibiting such con- 
 dyles, the zoologist infers, by deduction, that the animal be- 
 longed to the class mammalia. 
 
 Moreover, it is not usually necessary or desirable to 
 develop an argument any further than is needed to 
 secure its acceptance and belief. To set forth, in every 
 argument employed, the several kinds of relationships 
 involved, would certainly mean an elucidation of the 
 obvious, an attempted proof of much that is admitted, 
 w^ould be a waste of time. A mere suggestion of a re- 
 lation easily recognized is frequently sufficient, as for 
 instance, that the leaden clouds indicate rain or snow, 
 that the thick ice means cold weather, that the rain- 
 bow denotes the end of the storm. Conclusions are 
 constantly accepted without opposition with no develop- 
 ment of the reasoning on which they are grounded. 
 
 Of course, we reason habitually, in the ordinary af- 
 fairs of fife from premises to conclusions, without any 
 conscious appreciation of the nature of the relation in- 
 volved. Thus, in shooting at a target in a lake, we might 
 infer that the target was struck because it sank, with-
 
 42 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 out troubling ourselves to consider that we were reason- 
 ing from an effect to its cause; we might buy a horse 
 without consciously realizing that we were applying 
 our ideas of a good horse, such ideas being derived from 
 past experience; we might attribute a painting to a 
 certain artist almost intuitively without thinking of 
 the painting like it we had seen by the same artist; or 
 startled by a sudden noise we might conclude that a 
 gun had been fired, obHvious of the idea of association 
 in the process employed. 
 
 But the debater and student of argument must be 
 able to analyze and test the nature of the relations in- 
 volved, must become conscious of the processes em- 
 ployed in argument, whether such processes are ex- 
 pressed or implied. 
 
 The name ordinarily given to any argument is usually 
 derived from the kind of relation first recognized be- 
 tween the phenomenon, circumstance, or principle first 
 observed and the conclusion drawn. If the relation is 
 that of simple association, it may be called argument 
 from sign; if that of resemblance, argument from ex- 
 ample or analogy; if that of particular to general, in- 
 duction, and if general to particular, deduction; if cause 
 to effect or eft'ect to cause, causal relation. 
 
 The effectiveness of any argument will depend upon 
 the recognition and acceptance, by another, of the truth 
 of the relations between the conceptions or judgments 
 presented. On this basis of effectiveness or force, ar- 
 guments may be further classified as (i) probable or 
 moral, and (2) certain or demonstrative. 
 
 Unity of Classification. — Arguments have been clas- 
 sified in rhetoric, as antecedent probability, sign, and 
 example; sjid m logic, 2iS induction ond deduction. The
 
 ARGUMENT 43 
 
 following treatment of the classes of argument removes 
 these distinctions and brings all classes of argument 
 under a single principle of unity. 
 
 Classes of Argument 
 /. Association — Argument from Sign 
 
 If the relation from which the conclusion is drawn 
 is regarded as one of simple association, the argument 
 may be called argument from sign. 
 
 Reasoning from sign is the simplest and earliest mani- 
 festation of mental activity. It appears not only in 
 children, but in the childhood of the race. 
 
 Motion signs — nods, becks, gestures— and auditory 
 signs — calls, whistles, etc. — are given a definite meaning 
 almost instinctively, a meaning whose certainty is 
 strengthened by experience. Even animals manifest 
 the ability to act upon sign suggestions or reasoning. 
 Olfactory unages acting on the brain of the dog through 
 many generations have developed a remarkable facility 
 in the use of signs conveyed through this sense. An 
 excellent example of animal intelligence is provided in 
 the case of Clever Hans, the trained horse which so 
 long deceived psychologists : This horse had been trained 
 by the owner to "count and calculate so it could retain 
 in mind, and when questioned indicate its own age, the 
 age of its master, and many other numbers. The ex- 
 planation of the horse's apparent mental feats, which 
 a few years ago created considerable psychologic in- 
 terest in Berlin, is due to the psychologist Stumpf and 
 his pupil Pfungst. Both these gentlemen showed that 
 Clever Hans, whenever making a calculation, kept close 
 watch pn the expressional movements of the interrogator,
 
 44 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 especially toward the end. If, for instance, the horse 
 were asked to give the product of five times seven, it 
 scraped a hoof on the ground repeatedly until a sHght 
 movement of the head or even a minimal twist of the 
 eye gave the animal the signal to cease pawing. As 
 soon as the horse's eyes were covered with bhnders, or 
 it was prevented in some other way from watching the 
 questioner, its remarkable mathematical ability was 
 absent. Moreover, the expressional movements of Von 
 Osten Sacken or of any other examiner were not pre- 
 meditated or intentional, as tricks designed to deceive 
 the public, but they occurred entirely involuntarily 
 when the animal reached the figure which represented 
 the answer to the question."^ 
 
 All human communication by means of language 
 involves sign reasoning. 
 
 Words . . . have no character in themselves. They are 
 merely conventional signs, and consequently they can be good 
 or bad, dignified or vulgar, only in accordance with the ideas 
 they conventionally denote or suggest in the mind of the speaker 
 and his hearers. Yet under this head of suggestions comes in 
 an important consideration, which accounts for a great deal 
 that would otherwise be inexplicable. Most words from their 
 use acquire general connotations or associations, which almost 
 seem to give them a character of their own. 
 
 Thus the word fist means simply "the hand with the fingers 
 doubled up against the palm." In the idiomatic comparison 
 "as big as your fist," it is purely descriptive, and has no partic- 
 ular character, good or bad. The use of the fist in fighting, how- 
 ever, has given a peculiar connotation to the term. We may 
 say, "He hit his opponent with his clinched fist," for here again 
 fist is purely descriptive, and occurs in an appropriate environ- 
 ment. Similarly, we may say, "The boy cried dismally, wiping 
 his eyes with his dingy fist," for here there is a certain grotesque- 
 
 ' " Suggestion and Psychotherapy," by George W. Jacoby.
 
 ARGUMENT 45 
 
 ness in the scene which justifies the use of undignified language. 
 But we can no longer say, as was formerly possible, "The lady 
 held a lily in her dehcate fist." In other words, the associations 
 of fist are either pugnacious, vulgar, or jocose. 
 
 These suggestive associations are partly general and partly 
 individual. If certain phrases are habitually associated in our 
 minds with low or disagreeable persons or things, they will in- 
 evitably be relegated to the category of unseemly terms, and, 
 on the other hand, phrases that are associated with dignified 
 and reputable persons or circumstances, will acquire a kind of 
 respectabihty independent of the e.xact meaning which they 
 convey. 
 
 The associations in question may be purely personal. Every- 
 body remembers certain words which he dislikes intensely, though 
 they are in common use, convey no bad or disagreeable meaning, 
 and are quite euphonious. We may even remember our reason 
 for such dislikes. Perhaps the word is associated with an un- 
 pleasant experience; more likely, however, our antipathy is 
 due to its habitual use by some one we do not fancy. Or we 
 may have been bored by hearing the word overused, so that 
 every new repetition gives us a feeling of satiety. 
 
 It is largely these indefinite connotations of words that make 
 it so difiicult to speak a foreign tongue. We may be well trained 
 in grammar and command a large vocabulary, and yet use words 
 which, though they express our meaning accurately enough, 
 suggest ridiculous or inopportune associations to a native. 
 "Baboo Enghsh" is proverbial. The awkward and equivocal 
 remarks into which one frequently blunders in speaking one's 
 own language, "the things one would rather have left unsaid," 
 depend on a momentary forgetfulness of some more or less ob- 
 scure connotation which the words that we are using may 
 bear.^ 
 
 Sign Argument Expounded. — Sign argument has 
 been regarded as confined to reasoning "from an effect 
 to a condition" of that effect, as, e. g., ice is a sign of 
 
 ' "Words and Their Ways in English Speech," by James B. Greenough 
 and George Lyman Kittredge.
 
 46 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 cold weather. It has also been regarded as having its 
 basis in a partial resemblance; that is, in a resemblance 
 in one respect to something in past experience. But 
 since the whole process of thinking is inherently a process 
 of association, the term argument from sign is com- 
 monly used to denote reasoning based on any principle 
 of association. It is immaterial whether the process 
 is from fact to principle or from principle to fact; from 
 one case to another case like it; from effect to condition, 
 from effect to cause, from one effect to another effect 
 of the same cause; or even from cause to effect. One 
 thing is connected with another; where one is the other 
 is. Such are arguments from sign. As we analyze and 
 develop them, however, we are apt to call them by the 
 name of the specific relation employed. Thus an ar- 
 gument based on indications that a thing happened or 
 was so elsewhere or in other cases may later be called 
 example, and one based on indications showing why 
 it may be expected to happen or is likely to be true may 
 later be recognized as antecedent probability and so 
 called. 
 
 After all, the name is less important than that we 
 should use the processes correctly, and that we should 
 recognize the fact that the full course of the processes 
 of sign will show that a proposition is true because (i) 
 of signs bearing upon it directly; because (2) of signs 
 showing its truth in other cases, and because (3) of signs 
 telKng why it is likely to be true. 
 
 For example, there are indications that the public 
 ownership and operation of telegraph-lines will result 
 in lower rates. As shown by testimonies in the man- 
 agement of the telegraph system; by testimonies illus- 
 trating lower rates in publicly owned lighting plants
 
 ARGUMENT 47 
 
 as compared with those privately owned; and by state- 
 ments tending to show that the absence of the need for 
 profit is likely to produce lower rates. Of course, there 
 may be signs in the form of testimonies pointing to the 
 reverse conclusion, testimonies showing, for instance, 
 that the telegraph management is efficient; that in 
 publicly owned railroads the rates have not been lowered; 
 and that the loss of initiative and energy in pubhcly 
 owned works may explain the reason why lower rates 
 will not follow. There are usually signs on both sides. 
 
 The force of sign arguments will vary from sHght 
 probability to a definiteness amounting to certainty. 
 
 Frequently the mere suggestions of an easily recog- 
 nized association may secure its acceptance and belief, 
 as, e. g., a flag at half-mast means the death of a prom- 
 inent person; the ringing of the college bell at a certain 
 hour is a call to chapel; geese flying southward in the 
 autmnn is an indication of cold weather; and so on. 
 There is a distinct force as an impression in the sugges- 
 tions of an accmnulated number of instances pointing 
 in a certain direction. This is greatest when there is 
 a uniform experience behind it or when the spirit or 
 emotional tone of the argument accords with the feel- 
 ing of the audience. "Trifles light as air are to the 
 jealous confirmation strong as proofs of Holy Writ." 
 
 Carefully stated probable conclusions based on a 
 series of signs are made by scientists and scholars in 
 every field of investigation or research. Internal docu- 
 mentary evidence is usually regarded as suppl>dng in- 
 ferences from sign. While such inferences do not often 
 clearly establish a cause, the resemblances noted may 
 warrant a conclusion of value. For example, it is only 
 in this way that we can assign probable dates to some
 
 48 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 of Shakespeare's plays. After noting, at length, points 
 of resemblance in the Old English story Beowulf and 
 in the Grettis Saga, Stopford A. Brooke states his con- 
 clusion as follows: 
 
 The parallel is very close, and three suggestions may be made 
 concerning it. Either the Beowulf Saga was known over Sweden 
 and Norway, and its lays came from Norway or the Western 
 Isles to Iceland with the first settlers; or some of the roving 
 Icelanders had heard of the tale in England, and brought it 
 back to Iceland in a broken fashion; or there was a tale older 
 than Beowulf itself — a combination of a nature-myth and a 
 folk-tale — which was common property of the Northmen, and 
 out of which the Grendel story in Beowulf, and the Glam and 
 Troll story both grew independently of each other.^ 
 
 While it is true that the greater the number of signs 
 noted, the greater the force, complete identity is rarely 
 possible. Indeed few arguments from sign are con- 
 clusive, unless they estabhsh a cause — as, e. g., smoke is 
 a sign of fire; where there is a chick, there has been 
 an egg. Junius argues in his first Letter that the char- 
 acter of the government is a sign of the deplorable state 
 of the people, because only such depravity and inef- 
 ficiency could have produced it. Illustrations may be 
 found, in abundance, in the courts in connection with 
 circumstantial evidence; as, e. g., signs showing the mo- 
 tive for an act — as those pointing to revenge, or hatred, 
 in the case of an act of violence charged, or of hungei 
 in a charge of theft. 
 
 Theoretically, the force of the argument from sign 
 will increase as the number of resemblances noted tend 
 to establish identity with a known circumstance or 
 fact; tend to estabhsh a principle known or easily 
 
 »"Hist. of Early Eng. Lit.," p. 92.
 
 ARGUMENT 49 
 
 recognized as true; and tend to establish a relation 
 which is causal in character. 
 
 Observation and Inference. — Reasoning from sign is 
 the basis of solution of the many complex problems set 
 up in the detective story, originated by Edgar Allan 
 Poe. Before facts can be interpreted and combined so 
 as to establish or overthrow an hypothesis, they must 
 of course be observed. In making an analysis of the 
 mental processes employed in playing successfully a 
 game of whist, Poe dwells upon the importance of ob- 
 servation, as follows: ^ 
 
 But it is in matters beyond the limits of mere rule that the 
 skill of the analyst is evinced. He makes, in silence, a host of 
 observations and inferences. So, perhaps, do his companions; 
 and the difference in the extent of the information obtained 
 lies, not so much in the validity of the inference, as in the quality 
 of the observation. The necessary knowledge is that of what 
 to observe. Our player confines himself not at all; nor, be- 
 cause the game is the object, does he reject deductions from 
 things external to the game. He examines the countenance 
 of his partner, comparing it carefully with that of each of his 
 opponents. He considers the mode of assorting the cards in 
 each hand; often counting trump by trump, and honor by honor, 
 through the glances bestowed by their holders upon each. He 
 notes every variation of face as the play progresses, gathering 
 a fund of thought from the differences in the expression of cer- 
 tainty, of surprise, of triumph, or chagrin. From the manner 
 of gathering up a trick he judges whether the person taking it 
 can make another in the suit. He recognizes what is played 
 through feint, by the air with which it is thrown upon the table. 
 A casual or inadvertent word; the accidental dropping or turn- 
 ing of a card, with the accompanying anxiety or carelessness 
 in regard to its concealment; the counting of the tricks, with 
 the order of their arrangement; embarrassment, hesitation, 
 eagerness, or trepidation — all afford, to his apparently intuitive 
 
 • "The Murders in the Rue Morgue," E. A. Poe.
 
 50 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 perception, indications of the true state of affairs. The first 
 two or three rounds having been played, he is in full pos- 
 session of the contents of each hand, and thenceforward puts 
 down his cards with as absolute a precision of purpose as if 
 the rest of the party had turned outward the faces of their 
 own. 
 
 Common Sources of Error in inferences from sign are 
 the ignoring of contrary signs, misinterpreting facts, 
 combining them improperly, and overdrawing the con- 
 clusion, that is, stating it without sufficient qualifica- 
 tion. Especially, a shght indication must not be used 
 as a sufficient cause. It is true, c. g., that clouds are a 
 sign of rain, but we are hardly warranted in asserting 
 that it will rain to-day merely because the sky is over- 
 cast. 
 
 II. Argument from Example 
 
 If the relation from which the conclusion is drawn 
 is regarded as one of resemblance, or its opposite con- 
 trast, the argument may be called argument from ex- 
 ample. 
 
 A. RESEMBLANCE 
 
 There are two classes of resemblance: (i) By general- 
 ization and (2) by analogy. 
 
 I. Example by Generalization. — Any of the facts of 
 observation and experience may be used as examples. 
 There are examples of war and peace, of heroism and 
 cowardice, of the blessings and sorrows of preparedness 
 as well as of pacificism. From the success or failure of 
 woman suffrage in Colorado we may argue to the wis- 
 dom or folly of adopting it in New Jersey; from a 
 government ownership and operation of the mails, we
 
 ARGUMENT 51 
 
 may argue to a government ownership and operation 
 of the telephone, or municipal ownership and operation 
 of car- lines; from the budget system of Parliament to 
 the budget system of Congress or the State Legislatures. 
 Its field is practically unlimited. "I have but one 
 lamp," says Patrick Henry, "by which my feet are 
 guided, and that is the lamp of experience." Again, 
 "History," says Dionysius, "is philosophy teaching by 
 example." 
 
 It is essentially, however, an argument from resem- 
 blance. It proceeds from case to case, from likeness to 
 likeness. What is true in one place under one set of 
 circumstances and conditions is equally true in another 
 place under similar circumstances and conditions; things 
 happening in a certain way at one time under one set 
 of circumstances and conditions will happen again in 
 a similar way at another time under parallel circum- 
 stances and conditions; whatever is alike in essential 
 parts is alike in whole. It cannot be confused with 
 sign, which is an argument of unanalyzed or unspecified 
 association; or with antecedent probability or causal 
 argument which tells why a thing is or must be so. Ex- 
 ample proves that it is so, or did happen. 
 
 The fact is so, and these people of the Southern Colonies are 
 much more strongly attached to liberty than those to the North- 
 ward. Such were all the ancient commonwealths; such were 
 our fathers — ancestors; such in our days were the Poles; and 
 such will be all masters of slaves who are not slaves themselves. 
 — Burke, "Conciliation." 
 
 Burke reinforces this argument from example, by an 
 argument from causal relation, when he adds: "In 
 such a people the haughtiness of domination com-
 
 52 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 bines with the spirit of freedom, fortifies it, and renders 
 it invincible " 
 
 Cavour whose monument is united Italy; Bismarck who has 
 raised the German Empire from a name to a fact; Gladstone to- 
 day the incarnate heart and conscience of England — they are the 
 perpetual refutation of the sneer that high education weakens 
 men for practical aEsLiTs.— Curtis, " The PubHc Duty of Educated 
 Men." 
 
 The argument from example always involves a prin- 
 ciple, stated or implied, a principle of classification or of 
 causation, a principle supported by authority or re- 
 garded as true. In the preceding illustration, Cavour in 
 Italy, Bismarck in Germany, Gladstone in England- 
 all come within the class of educated men who are prac- 
 tical and unvisionary. In the quotation from Burke, 
 a causal principle was stated at the end. In neither, 
 however, was there authoritative support of the prin- 
 ciple involved. 
 
 In law, it is often argued that the case at bar is suf- 
 ficiently like a case previously decided to bring it under 
 some well-estabKshed principle. In the famous Dart- 
 mouth College Case, Justice Story endeavored to show 
 that a charter is like a grant, through the definition of 
 a contract. The Federal Constitution denies to the 
 States the right to pass any law impairing the obliga- 
 tions of contract. Moreover, in Fletcher vs. Peck, it 
 was decided that a grant of land, from the State of 
 Georgia to a citizen, was a contract between two par- 
 ties. In order then to decide the question — is this 
 charter a contract? — it becomes important to prove 
 that the charter was like the grant of land in respect 
 to those essential things which made it a contract.
 
 ARGUMENT 53 
 
 Many questions naturally arise in such a comparison, 
 some important and some unimportant. For instance, 
 both are sealed instruments; the charter was from the 
 State to a corporation, while the grant was from a State 
 to a citizen; both involved mutual promises, and so on. 
 The resemblances, however, outweighed the differences 
 in all essential points affecting a contract, and the court 
 decreed that the Dartmouth College charter, being es- 
 sentially . like a land grant, was therefore a contract, 
 and so could not be impaired by the State. The gen- 
 eral principles so applied in the arguments of a case 
 at law are derived from the Federal Constitution, 
 statutes, decisions of courts, legal text-books, etc. 
 
 Thus the process of example may be little more than 
 a matter of estabhshing the correctness or relevancy of 
 a definition. The lawyer, for instance, seeks first to find 
 a principle covering the case under investigation; then 
 to interpret it according to the previous decisions of a 
 court; and finally to apply the definition so determined 
 to the case at bar. Another notable instance of an 
 argument of this sort is that made by Lord Erskine 
 in defense of Lord George Gordon when he was tried 
 for high treason; a speech worthy of analysis and careful 
 study for logical method, use of authority, and presen- 
 tation. 
 
 "What is law?" asks the student. "It is a rule of 
 action," says Blackstone. Practically, however, it is 
 an interminable definition. 
 
 The authority of precedents is perhaps more em- 
 phasized in law then elsewhere, for it must be re- 
 membered that precedents must sometimes be followed 
 by a court when its own view is to the contrary. And 
 yet the antecedent idea that the end of a State is jus-
 
 54 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 tice, is always more or less involved in the interpreta- 
 tion and application of our laws, and sometimes a view 
 is even taken of the probable consequences of a partic- 
 ular interpretation or application. It happens fre- 
 quently that, where two opposed arguments are struc- 
 turally correct and equally supported by authorities, 
 one will prevail over the other because it is supported 
 by a sound public policy. 
 
 In the debates in Parliament on the taxation of Amer- 
 ica, there was much citation of examples affecting the 
 question of representation — Lord Camden, Lord 
 Chatham, and Burke believed in a real representation 
 (such as is at present in vogue in the United States), 
 while Lord Mansfield held to the theory of a virtual 
 representation. We will see more in the latter view if 
 we recall that to-day parhamentary representatives 
 often do not reside in the district which elects them. 
 They represent the nation. 
 
 Lord Camden, speaking in the House of Lords in 
 1766, said: "My lords, I challenge any one to point out 
 the time when any tax was laid upon any person by 
 Parliament, that person being unrepresented in Par- 
 liament." He considered the cases of Chester, the clergy, 
 Wales, and Ireland; and averred that "from the whole 
 of our history from the earliest period, you will find 
 that taxation and representation were united." The 
 principle underlying his contention he derives from 
 John Locke, "The supreme power cannot take from any 
 man any part of his property without his own consent," 
 and B II, pp. 136-139, particularly 140, drawn from 
 the heart of our constitution, which he thoroughly un- 
 derstood, and will last as long as that shall last — Par- 
 liamentary Debates and Proceedings, vol. IV, p. 366. 
 
 Lord Mansfield answered "the noble Lord (Cam-
 
 ARGUMENT 55 
 
 den), particularly upon the cases he has quoted." With 
 respect to the marches of Wales, he admits that they 
 enjoyed the privilege of taxing themselves for a brief 
 time, "during the Hfe of Edward I till the Prince of Wales 
 became King," but says that they were then annexed 
 to tlie crown and became subject to taxes, like the rest 
 of the dominions, until Henry VIII. The latter issued 
 writs for it to return two members of Parliament, and 
 issued a writ also to Calais to send one Burgess. Be- 
 sides, one of the counties palatine (Durham) was taxed 
 fifty years before he sent members to Parliament, while 
 the clergy were, at no time, unrepresented in Parliament. 
 
 All parallels drawn from the colonies of antiquity 
 to the present case are then excluded as irrelevant and 
 immaterial. The Tyrians in Africa and the Greeks in 
 Asia, for instance, were totally different from ours. No 
 nation before ourselves had any regular system of colo- 
 nization except the Romans, whose system was a mili- 
 tary one. Expounding next the theory and history 
 of the British colonial system, he argues that if there 
 was no express law, usage alone would be sufficient, 
 and concluded by drawing the distinction between vir- 
 tual and real representation — the true source of differ- 
 ence — asserting that the colonies are as much repre- 
 sented in Parliament as are the greatest part of the 
 people of England. 
 
 Burke, speaking in 1774, argued from example to 
 show that "rebellion and loss to yourselves" would 
 surely follow the narrow pohcy of the crown, as they 
 had done in the case of Wales and of Lancaster. 
 
 You tried in Wales to raise a revenue which the people thought 
 excessive and unjust: the attempt ended in oppression, resis- 
 tance, rebellion, and loss to yourselves. You tried in the duchy 
 of Lancaster to raise a revenue which the people believed un-
 
 56 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 just: this effort ended in oppression, rebellion, vexation, and 
 loss to yourselves. You are now trj^ing to raise in America, a 
 revenue which the colonists disapprove. What must be the 
 result? — American Taxatiojt. 
 
 Thus, Lord Camden argued from the principle that 
 taxation and representation had always been united, 
 and quoted from John Locke to prove that a person 
 could not be deprived of his property without his con- 
 sent. The argument in the Dartmouth College case 
 rested on the principle that no State had the right to 
 deny or impair the obUgation of a contract, as affirmed 
 in the Federal Constitution. Here cases were examined 
 for the purpose of establishing sufficient resemblances 
 to the case in question to bring the latter under a prin- 
 ciple established by authority. 
 
 Lord Mansfield based his argument on the principle 
 of virtual rather than real representation as the his- 
 toric British pohcy — a principle grounded in tradition 
 and reason. Burke, in the last quoted passage on the 
 British attitude toward America, reasoned (as he did 
 later in his speech on conciliation) from the idea that 
 any colonial policy will fail which the people believe 
 to be unjust; or, in other words, that the feeling of in- 
 justice or oppression resulting from a policy will tend 
 to produce its failure. The process here too is one of 
 classification (for he brings America into the category 
 of colonies which have suffered through British policy) ; 
 but it is more. The resemblances are of things viewed 
 as results; results imply causes or antecedents; and 
 the antecedent here is British colonial policy acting as 
 an agency or law sufficient to produce the phenomenon 
 of rebellion, a principle of causation. 
 
 Unless the principle is easily accepted behind the argu-
 
 ARGUMENT 57 
 
 ment from example, there must be some warranting 
 process such as an authority or a cause. If, however, 
 an issue should arise as to the validity of any particular 
 causal principle asserted, so that we are obliged to con- 
 sider causal relationships instead of resemblances in 
 results, the argument becomes causal relation. But 
 even the use of authority, it should be remembered, 
 involves the idea that like follows like, like causes must 
 produce like results. 
 
 Further Analysis of the Process. — Any argument from 
 example will be vaHd, if the resemblances between the 
 case or cases cited and the case in question are sufficient 
 to bring them, in essential particulars, within the scope 
 of a recognized principle or law. This presupposes, 
 however, that the facts and circumstances relating to 
 the cases are truly and fully stated, and that other things 
 have not been overlooked. It will be clearly invahd, 
 for instance, if other cases are found which establish 
 another principle stronger and equally well recognized. 
 
 The following table or rules will show the process 
 as a whole, including its more important steps: 
 
 1 . Find the principle covering the cases cited and the 
 case in question. 
 
 2. Are the facts and circumstances concerning these 
 cases fully stated, and true as alleged? 
 
 3. Are they relevant and material to the principle 
 under which they are now included? 
 
 a. What of the number and points of resemblance? 
 h. What of the number and points of difference? 
 
 4. Are there contrary cases which weaken or invali- 
 date the conclusion? 
 
 5. If the contrary cases tend to establish a new and 
 different principle, what is the value, comparatively,
 
 58 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 of these two principles with respect to such things as 
 authoritative support, general acceptance, causal rela- 
 tion, or sound public policy? 
 
 A complete analysis of the process of example as an 
 argument may involve, therefore, the consideration 
 of such things as a general principle, truth and com- 
 pleteness of circumstantial details, relevancy, and ma- 
 teriality of cases cited both as to the case in question 
 and to a principle affirmed, contrary cases with their 
 circumstantial detail, and finally the comparative value 
 of opposed principles. 
 
 Next in importance to establishing the principle or 
 ground of reasoning is the rule of relevancy. 
 
 Definition of Relevancy and Rules. — Any case may be 
 said to be relevant to a case under inquiry if it re- 
 sembles the latter in such a way as to permit its use as 
 a premise in drawing a conclusion about a doubtful or 
 unknown X. 
 
 The logical form of the process of reasoning from 
 example may be stated thus: 
 
 Whatever is like B with respect to M is like it with 
 respect to X; ^ is like B with respect to M\ therefore 
 A is like B with respect to X. Here A represents a 
 cited case, B a case in question, and M is a known char- 
 acteristic of both A and B; while X is the uncertain 
 or disputed point about A. Concretely, this may be 
 expressed as follows: Whatever British policy is like 
 the pohcy toward Wales in that it is felt to be unjust 
 is like it in being followed by rebelHon and loss. The 
 British policy toward America is like that toward Wales 
 in that it is felt to be unjust. Therefore, the British 
 policy toward America will be like it in bringing rebel- 
 lion and loss.
 
 ARGUMENT 59 
 
 The major premise of this syllogism — "Whatever is 
 like B with respect to M (or M, N, etc.) is like it with 
 respect to X" — is sometimes called the basis of com- 
 parison. 
 
 The process in arguing thus from example may be 
 regarded as jointly inductive and deductive: in the 
 sense that we first find cases covering the case under 
 inquiry, including of course the doubtful point X, in 
 order to establish a general principle; and that we then 
 apply this general principle to the present case, and 
 conclude that X should be accordingly. 
 
 Where conditions are undeniably similar, and the 
 point to be proved is carefully stated so that the 
 parallelism cannot be pushed too far, a single example 
 may sometimes be convincing. Thus President Hibben 
 — when arguing that the United States Government 
 should prepare against war rather than for war, and 
 could do so without becoming militaristic — cited the 
 example of the invisible army of Switzerland: 
 
 This is not an impracticable theory, incapable of being realized 
 in the actual experience of a nation. Switzerland proves the 
 possibility of a nation in arms challenging the world as the de- 
 fenders of peace. 
 
 It happened that I crossed the western frontier of Switzer- 
 land on the first day of August, 19 14, and was compelled to 
 travel toward the eastern frontier in the Engadine Valley during 
 the time of mobilization of the troops. The invisible army of 
 Switzerland came into being within forty-eight hours. On the 
 first day of August there was no evidence of any military or- 
 ganization in the country; then within four days, between 
 400,000 and 500,000 troops were on the borders; guides from 
 the mountains, men from the shops and stores and fields, from 
 all the industrial pursuits of the country, and they remain there 
 to this day, defending their land from the incursions of any 
 foreign foe. There is no country in Europe that gives as little
 
 60 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 impression of military display as Switzerland, and no country 
 better prepared to defend its borders against the devastation 
 and disaster of war. 
 
 For our own country it is possible for us to follow a similar 
 policy. We too can have within our midst if we choose an in- 
 visible army, men having some training in military affairs and 
 yet not withdrawn from their daily activities and pursuits. In 
 this way our military strength may be conserved at a minimum 
 expense and minimum industrial disturbance. If we are con- 
 fident, and I think justly so, that in the event of war the young 
 men of our country would be ready and eager to volunteer their 
 services, why should we not issue a call to volunteer for the 
 military training-camps which the government has already 
 instituted with such marked success? Every thoughtful person 
 is naturally opposed to military ostentation and display and 
 the whole spirit of insolent militarism. That which is essen- 
 tially the American way of doing things is to have our military 
 strength in potential form rather than actually existent in a 
 large standing army. 
 
 The important rules of relevancy when using the argu- 
 ment from example may now be summed up thus: 
 
 1. Find the doubtful X in the present case or situation. In 
 
 the preceding illustration the doubtful X was the pos- 
 sibility of a nation being prepared against war without 
 militarism. 
 
 2. Find a case essentially similar (which contains the doubt- 
 
 ful X) after comparing resemblances and differences with 
 all attendant conditions. Such was the selection of the 
 example of Switzerland. 
 
 3. Make its relevancy apparent. On the first day of August 
 
 there was no evidence of a military organization in 
 Switzerland; but within four days about four hundred 
 thousand troops were on the borders, assembled from 
 the activities of peace, to defend their lands. No coun- 
 try in Europe makes so little display as Switzerland, 
 Iione is better prepared for defense. Then follows the
 
 ARGUMENT 61 
 
 comparison. We too can have an invisible army. Our 
 young men are eager to volunteer for military training- 
 camps; it is essentially the American way, and so on. 
 
 Indeed, the perpetual and insistent problem of all 
 argument is what is to be proved — what proves it — 
 and how to make the proof manifest. 
 
 4. Estabhsh the fundamental basis of the argument either 
 by reason or by authority. The training-camps already 
 existing in the United States, for instance, make pos- 
 sible, through natural growth, the development of an 
 invisible army. 
 
 If illustration of authoritative support be needed fur- 
 ther, let us take it from Lord Erskine. He is defining 
 the law of treason as it applies to the circumstances of 
 the Gordon case, and has just examined the case of Dem- 
 aree for essential resemblances to the case at bar. He 
 remarks that all men "agree that it is the intention of 
 assembling" the mob which forms the guilt of treason, 
 and adds, "I will give you the words of high authority, 
 the learned Foster" . . . who says, in a similar case: 
 "The true criterion seems to be quo animo did the par- 
 ties assemble ? With what intention did they meet ? " ^ 
 
 Argimients from example often need thus to be sup- 
 ported by further arguments. We may accumulate 
 resemblances, select the most striking, or summon our 
 greatest rhetorical skill; and yet not escape the in- 
 evitable why or suppress the feeling that authoritative 
 support should have been given. Even when this is 
 done, and when the resemblances are great in number 
 and striking, it should always be remembered that the 
 argument from example can never reach absolute cer- 
 tainty. Practically no two things are exactly ahke, 
 and the conditions under which they exist or operate
 
 62 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 are never exactly the same. It can, at best, only estab- 
 lish a very high degree of probability. 
 
 The Fallacy, Begging the Question. — A cited case will 
 not be relevant to a case under inquiry, unless it con- 
 tains the doubtful X. It will not be relevant unless 
 the resemblances noted are in essential, rather than 
 accidental or superficial, respects. We cannot know 
 that the resemblances are essential unless we compare 
 the cases not only theoretically, but in the full and exact 
 setting in which they actually existed, or with all the 
 attendant circumstances or conditions under which 
 they actually took place. It will be plainly irrelevant, 
 if the differences are found to be sufficient to overcome 
 the resemblances. 
 
 If in an argument we assume resemblances or ignore 
 differences, we assume the very basis of comparison, 
 the very premise needed to be proved, and so beg the 
 question. Indeed, arguments from example are com- 
 monly ineffective and regarded as irrelevant, simply 
 because the basis of comparison is not indicated by 
 pointing out and making clear the exact points or re- 
 semblance. Observe how carefully Shylock, when at- 
 tempting to show that he was entitled to human treat- 
 ment, indicated in detail his resemblance to a human 
 being and a Christian: 
 
 Hath not a Jew eyes? hath not a Jew hands, organs, dimen- 
 sions, senses, affections, passions? fed with the same food, hurt 
 with the same weapons, subject to the same diseases, healed 
 by the same means, warmed and cooled by the same winter and 
 summer, as a Christian is? If you prick us, do we not bleed? 
 If you tickle us, do we not laugh ? If you poison us, do we not 
 die? and if you wrong us, shall we not revenge? If we are like 
 jn the rest, we will resemble you in that.
 
 ARGUMENT 63 
 
 You are doubtless familiar with the ancient fable 
 relating to the donkeys. One donkey, carrying on its 
 back a bag of salt, plunged into a stream, with the re- 
 sult that the salt melted, and he disported himself with 
 glee on the opposite meadow. The other donkey which 
 was laden with sponges instantly followed the example 
 of the salt-burdened leader, and, leaping into the stream, 
 almost came to grief.^ 
 
 Indeed, the most common form of fallacy in arguing 
 from example arises from assuming a resemblance be- 
 tween cases and ignoring the differences in attendant 
 circumstances and conditions. Let us examine an il- 
 lustration or two of a causal example, involving the 
 prediction that what happened from a certain cause 
 in another place will inevitably happen in the same 
 way from the same cause here. 
 
 Ringwalt in "Briefs on Public Questions" frequently 
 uses the argument from example as one of the main 
 divisions of a brief. These briefs, it should be said, are 
 meant to be suggestive; and a good deal is purposely 
 omitted for the student to supply. In one of them the 
 doubtful X is the question whether or not ownership 
 of the railways by the United States Government should 
 be adopted, and the example of other nations is made 
 the closing argument, thus: 
 
 V. The experience of foreign nations is favorable to govern- 
 ment ownership and operation. A. The experience of Prussia 
 is favorable, i. In Prussia a large annual surplus has been 
 earned. 2. Uniform, stable, and lower rates have been secured. 
 3. Facilities and accommodations have been improved. 4. 
 Natural resources have been developed and the commercial 
 
 » "The Fables of La Fontaine." Trans, by Robt. Thomson, bk. II, 
 Fable 10.
 
 64 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 prosperity of the nation enhanced. B. The experience of Bel- 
 gium is favorable, i. A profit has been earned. 2. The total 
 of ton mileage has increased. 3. Improvements have been in- 
 troduced. 4. Rates have been lowered. 5. Accidents are fewer. 
 C. The experience of Australia and New Zealand is favorable. 
 I. Great social advantages have been secured, x. The better 
 distribution of labor, y. An increase in suburban dweUing. 
 z. Increased educational advantages. 2. Agricultural interests 
 have been fostered. D. The experience of other nations is 
 favorable, i. That of Austria-Hungary. 2. Of Switzerland. 3. 
 Of France. 
 
 This argument is not shown to be relevant to X ; 
 but to government ow^nership in general. If it is meant 
 to imply that, because government ownership has been 
 successful in certain respects in other countries, it will 
 be so in these same respects in this country, the con- 
 clusion does not follow. By ignoring the conditions 
 under which the railroads are owned in the countries 
 mentioned, as well as conditions in the United States, 
 the argument assumes so much that there is no valid 
 basis of comparison. In fine, the conclusion is too broad 
 and the premises are not proved. 
 
 We have seen that a case cited should have not only 
 a bearing on the general subject, but a relevancy to 
 the doubtful X in the case in controversy. Very rarely 
 do the many cases thought to be pertinent to a sub- 
 ject turn out on examination to resemble one another 
 completely. Indeed, so frequently and in so many ways 
 do differences appear, that the successful use of example 
 as an argument requires exhaustive study: involving 
 the exercise of memory to carry in mind all the circum- 
 stantial details; a power of discrimination and analysis 
 to discard the irrelevant, seize upon the vital points, 
 and determine the relationships of the cases to one an-
 
 ARGUMENT 65 
 
 other and to the various principles, as well as the ability 
 to grasp firmly the soundest principle involved and hold 
 it distinct, so that in the most intricate circumstances 
 its relation to the doubtful X will be clear and luminous. 
 Answering a Causal Example by Alleging a Different 
 Cause. — An argimient from example may be refuted 
 (i) by proving that the facts are not true as alleged, 
 or (2) by admitting or assuming the alleged facts to 
 be true and then proving that conditions are not parallel, 
 and that hence there is no valid basis of comparison. 
 The latter refutation will be even stronger if the alleged 
 results can be ascribed to another and different cause. 
 Thus, General Hugh L. Scott refutes the argument that 
 the cost of the United States army is too high as com- 
 pared with the cost of the German army. He shows 
 that there is no valid basis of comparison, and then 
 attributes the relatively higher cost of our miUtary estab- 
 Hshment to the voluntary as opposed to the compul- 
 sory principle: 
 
 From time to time statements have appeared in current pub- 
 lications showing the large appropriation necessary for the sup- 
 port of the military establishment of the United States and the 
 relatively small cost of the German army. By dividing each of 
 these amounts by the total strength of each military establish- 
 ment an effort is made to compare the high cost of one of our 
 soldiers with the cost of a German soldier, which is very much 
 lower than ours. No intelligent comparison can be made be- 
 tween the cost of the German and American military estab- 
 lishments without having first a clear understanding of the dif- 
 ferences in the military system of these two countries. 
 
 The German pays his military obligations to the state in 
 personal service, while we go into the labor markets, where we 
 are forced to compete with other employers of labor in order 
 to secure our soldiers. In addition, there is a small class of volun- 
 teers in the German army who, in exchange for certain privileges
 
 66 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 as to service, maintain themselves and supply their own uni- 
 forms and equipment. Again, the normal wages of our labor 
 markets, where we obtain our recruits, are much higher than in 
 Germany. The comparative cost of these two soldiers in dollars 
 and cents, therefore, means little except to emphasize the cost 
 of maintaining a military establishment on the voluntary prin- 
 ciple. If we wish, then, to compare the cost of our army with 
 the cost of those of other nations, we must limit our comparison 
 to those nations which employ the same general system as our- 
 selves. We will find that only one other nation in the world 
 does so — Great Britain. 
 
 • 
 
 2. Example by Analogy. — Analogy is another term 
 used to describe arguments from resemblance. Here 
 the objects compared are regarded as v^ddely different 
 and lying in totally different fields; and though the 
 implication of a common cause is present, the specific 
 cause is more remote and vague; so that the probability 
 established is regarded as less strong than if the cases 
 compared vi^ere known to be in the same class. Hence, 
 analogy has sometimes been defined as "a resemblance 
 of ratios" or a "resemblance of relations rather than of 
 objects" or a "parity of reasoning." It is of much value 
 to the scientist in offering hints or ideas for experiment 
 and investigation. There is, for instance, a relation 
 between the falUng of an apple to the ground and the 
 motion of the heavenly bodies; the lifting of the Hd of 
 a teakettle, through the idea of the expansion of steam, 
 and the piston in a locomotive; the structure of the 
 human ear and the receiver of a telephone. 
 
 Analogy is also used by the great orators, and often 
 with telhng effect. When so used as an argument the 
 resemblances should be essentially alike in all partic- 
 ulars which affect the proposition and they should be 
 true as stated. Besides, the proposition should, if im-
 
 ARGUMENT 67 
 
 portant enough, be supported by further evidence. 
 Analogy offers only parallel or collateral evidence. It 
 has place also in the clarifjdng processes of exposition; 
 is the essence of much of the description and narration 
 used as argumentative adjuncts, and is of great value 
 wherever the purpose is to engage attention, enhst in- 
 terest, appeal to desire, or to "suggest" to the imagina- 
 tion, as well as to prove. Lincoln's analogies are widely 
 known: 
 
 Gentlemen, I want you to suppose a case for a moment. Sup- 
 pose that all the property you were worth was in gold, and you 
 had put it in the hands of Blondin, the famous rope-walker, to 
 carry across the Niagara Falls on a tight rope. Would you 
 shake the rope while he was passing over it, or keep shouting to 
 him: "Blondin, stoop a little morel Go a little faster"? No, 
 I am sure you would not. You would hold your breath as well 
 as your tongue, and keep your hands off until he was safely 
 over. Now the government is in the same situation. It is carry- 
 ing an immense weight across a stormy ocean. Untold treasures 
 are in its hands. It is doing the best it can. Don't badger it I 
 Just keep still and it will get you safely over. 
 
 The use of the several arguments previously men- 
 tioned as well as a clear mode of procedure may be 
 illustrated from the following quotation from Whately 
 on mdirect description. He begins by telling what his 
 thesis is like, and then states it; after which he tells 
 why a description using carefully selected details will 
 produce a more striking impression than one based on 
 a catalogue method, and then cites two examples to 
 prove that this is so: 
 
 It is observed by opticians and astronomers that a side view 
 of a faint star, or, especially, of a comet, presents it in much 
 greater brilliancy than a direct view. To see a comet in its full
 
 68 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 splendor, you should look not straight at it, but at some star 
 a little beside it. Something analogous to this often takes place 
 in mental perceptions. It will often, therefore, have a better 
 effect to describe obliquely, if I may so speak, by introducing 
 circumstances connected with the main object or event, and 
 affected by it, but not absolutely forming a part of it. And 
 circumstances of this kind may not infrequently be so selected 
 as to produce a more striking impression of anything that is in 
 itself great and remarkable than could be produced by a minute 
 and direct description, because in this way the general and col- 
 lective result of a whole, and the effects produced by it on other 
 objects, may be vividly impressed on the hearer's mind, the 
 circumstantial detaU of collateral matters not drawing off the 
 mind from the contemplation of the principle matter as one 
 and complete. Thus, the woman's application to the King of 
 Samaria, to compel her neighbor to fulfil the agreement of shar- 
 ing with her the infant's flesh, gives a more frightful impression 
 of the horrors of the famine than any more direct description 
 could have done, since it presents to us the picture of that hard- 
 ening of the heart to every kind of horror, and that destruc- 
 tion of the ordinary state of human sentiment which is the re- 
 sult of long-continued and extreme misery. Nor could any 
 detail of the particular vexations to be suffered by the exiled 
 Jews for their disobedience convey so lively an idea of them as 
 that description of their result contained in the denunciation of 
 Moses: "In the evening thou shalt say. Would God it were 
 morning ! and in the morning thou shalt say. Would God it were 
 evening!" — Whaiely, "Elements of Rhetoric," p. 125. 
 
 Knowledge grows slowly by ever-widening generaliza- 
 tions. What in one age may seem to be a weak analogy 
 may later become an example of a truth. All men may 
 reason to-day, for instance, from the analogy of biolog- 
 ical growth in certain particulars in all living things 
 and their products, but once we find warrant for a be- 
 lief in some such generalization as that asserted by 
 Herbert Spencer as law, we would not hesitate to cite 
 as examples what hitherto we had regarded as analogies.
 
 ARGUMENT 69 
 
 WTioever, indeed, could accept the following should 
 find small difficulty in so doing: j 
 
 Now, we propose in the first place to show that this law of 
 organic progress is the law of all progress. Whether it be in 
 the development of the earth, in the development of life upon 
 its surface, in the development of society, of government, of 
 manufactures, of commerce, of language, Uterature, science, art, 
 this same evolution of the simple into the complex, through 
 successive differentiations, holds throughout. From the earliest 
 traceable cosmical changes down to the latest results of civiliza- 
 tion we shall find that the transformation of the homogeneous 
 into the heterogeneous is that in which progress essentially 
 consists. 
 
 B. CONTRAST 
 
 A Principle of Association. — Conventional treatises 
 on argumentation make insufficient mention of the ar- 
 gument from contrast. Aristotle included contrast as 
 well as resemblance among the fundamental categories 
 of association. Moreover, simple association-tests show 
 that there are certain t>pes of words which suggest 
 their opposites, as, e. g., head — foot; right — left or wrong, 
 etc. While there is a tendency among modern psy- 
 chologists to regard contrast as a secondary principle 
 rather than a primary, they are continually recognizing 
 a variation of method among individuals and a char- 
 acteristic individual method of reasoning. Indeed, 
 just as there are types of orators and debaters whose 
 method seems to be governed largely by the principles 
 of resemblance, as, for instance, Burke, so there are 
 others equally eminent — notably Lincoln — in whom the 
 principle of contrast seems also to be particularly strong. 
 
 Uses in Debating. — The method of contrast is per- 
 haps more essential in debating than in any other form
 
 70 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 of speech, for the debater must continually keep his 
 case before an audience in opposition to that of his op- 
 ponent. He does this in his definition of the main issues, 
 in the development of his argument, and in his recapit- 
 ulation. Refutation, too, may be not only a matter of 
 drawing distinctions in a counter-proof but of contrast- 
 ing premise with premise, proof with proof, conclusion 
 with conclusion; and so, in ordering his materials, when 
 the debater wishes to grapple with his opponent closely 
 and impress his audience strongly, he brings strength 
 into sharp contrast with weakness, or assumption and 
 assertion into bold opposition to his own evidence, 
 with their inevitable conclusions to his own advan- 
 tage. 
 
 In the remarks of Lincoln on the Dred Scott Decision^ 
 delivered June 26, 1857, observe how naturally and ef- 
 fectively Lincoln contrasted (i) the dissenting opinions 
 of Judge Curtis with the opinions of Justice Taney, 
 (2) the pubhc estimate of the black men in the days of 
 the Revolution with that at the present time, and (3) 
 Judge Douglas's action "three and a half years ago" 
 in forcing the Nebraska bill upon the country with its 
 consequences "now." We have here a contrast in au- 
 thoritative opinion, a contrast in time, and a contrast 
 involving the additional relation of antecedent to con- 
 sequent. 
 
 Uses in Refutation: Types of Argument by Con- 
 trast. — There are three special types of the argument 
 by contrast in which Lincoln, the great American de- 
 bater, was especially proficient, i. e., reducHo ad ahsur- 
 dum, the dilemma, and the method of the residue. They 
 are so effective in debating and so common in practice 
 » "Little Masterpieces," " Lincoln," by Bliss Perry, p. 13.
 
 ARGUMENT 71 
 
 that we wall consider them with some detail and with 
 a variety of illustration, 
 
 I. Reductio ad Absurdum. — In redudio ad absurdtim, 
 the debater contrasts the conclusion reached by his op- 
 ponent with an utterly ridiculous conclusion derived 
 from the citation of other cases involving the same 
 process of reasoning. 
 
 Any argument that can be reduced to an absurdity 
 is said to "prove too much"; for instance, the argu- 
 ment that "the Uquor traffic is Hable to abuse and there- 
 fore should be abolished" proves too much. Its 
 absurdity will appear if one should answer: "Rehgion 
 and learning also are Hable to abuse; therefore, they 
 should be abolished." The impHed premise in the argu- 
 ment is "whatever is Hable to abuse should be aboHshed." 
 The reductio ad absurdum connects this implied premise 
 not only with the expressed premise "the Hquor traffic 
 is Hable to abuse," thereby showing that the argument 
 leads correctly to the conclusion drawn, but also con- 
 trasts it with another premise, namely, "ReHgion and 
 learning are Hable to abuse," showing that the argu- 
 ment here leads to the absurd conclusion, "ReHgion and 
 learning should be abolished." 
 
 Every argument which proves too much does not 
 require a reductio ad absurdum to overthrow it. Webster 
 meets the objection that bank credit may be abused, thus : 
 
 I am well aware that bank credit may be abused. I know 
 that bank paper may become excessive; that depreciation will 
 then follow; and that the evils, the losses, and the frauds con- 
 sequent on a disordered currency fall on the rich and the poor 
 together, but with especial weight of ruin on the poor. I know 
 that the system of bank credit must always rest on a specie 
 basis, and that it constantly needs to be strictly guarded and
 
 72 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 properly restrained; and it may be so guarded and restrained. 
 We need not give up the good which belongs to it through fear 
 of the evil which may follow from its abuse. We have a power 
 to take security against these evils. It is our business as states- 
 men to adopt that security; it is our business not to prostrate 
 or attempt to prostrate the system, but to use those means of 
 precaution, restraint, and correction which experience has sanc- 
 tioned, and which are ready at our hands. 
 
 Macaulay detects in an argument of Mr. Gladstone 
 an instance of proving too much and exposes its premises, 
 indicating at the same time the unscientific mode of 
 deriving them: 
 
 He (Mr. Gladstone) lays down broad general doctrines about 
 power, when the only power of which he is thinking is the power 
 of governments — about conjoint action, when the only con- 
 joint action of which he is thinking is the conjoint action of 
 citizens in a state. He first resolves on his conclusion. He then 
 makes a major of most comprehensive dimensions; and having 
 satisfied himself that it contains his conclusion, never troubles 
 himself about what else it may contain. And as soon as we ex- 
 amine it, we find that it contains an infinite number of con- 
 clusions, every one of which is a monstrous absurdity.^ 
 
 In redudio ad dbsurdum, speaking exactly, the in- 
 correct premises and conclusion are not pointed out; 
 but the argument is assumed to be sound and contrasted 
 with other cases which prove it unsound. 
 
 The debater must not expect always to find actually 
 expressed the argument proving too much; it is fre- 
 quently derived by implication either from an opponent's 
 argumentation or from the usual or possible logic of 
 his side. In any event he seeks to fasten upon his op- 
 ponent a behef in its soundness. 
 
 In his Liverpool address Beecher charged upon a 
 ^Macaulay's Essay on "Gladstone on Church and State."
 
 ARGUMENT 73 
 
 hostile audience a belief in an argument which proved 
 too much and revealed its absurdity. He had Just been 
 interrupted and considerable tact was required in re- 
 suming. He caught the ear of the audience at once, 
 however, by attributing to them a very natural sym- 
 pathy for "the weaker party," and then altering his 
 position slightly and without stating the proposition 
 he intended to discuss, he applied the reductio ad ah- 
 surdum to the proposition that " the minority is always 
 right." 
 
 But I know that you say you cannot help sympathizing with 
 a gallant people. (" Hear, hear ! ") They are the weaker people, 
 the minority; and you cannot help going with the minority who 
 are struggUng for their rights against the majority. Nothing 
 could be more generous, when a weak party stands for its own 
 legitimate rights against imperious pride and power than to 
 sympathize with the weak. But whoever sympathized with 
 a weak thief because three constables had got hold of him? 
 (" Hear, hear ! ") And yet the one thief in the policemen's hands 
 is the weaker party. I suppose you would sympathize with him. 
 ("Hear, hear!" Laughter and applause.) Why, when that in- 
 famous King of Naples — Bomba — was driven into Gaeta by 
 Garibaldi with his immortal band of patriots, and Cavour sent 
 against him the army of northern Italy, who was the weaker 
 party then? The tyrant and his minions; and the majority was 
 the noble Italian patriots struggling for liberty. I never heard 
 that Old England sent deputations to King Bomba, and yet his 
 troops resisted bravely there. (Laughter and interruption.) To- 
 day the majority of the people of Rome is with Italy. Nothing 
 but French bayonets keeps her from going back to the kingdom 
 of Italy, to which she belongs. Do you sympathize with the 
 minority in Rome or the majority in Italy? (A voice: "With 
 Italy."). 
 
 The manner of treatment may be either direct or 
 indirect. The debater, that is, may proceed frankly,
 
 74 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 seriously, to show by a wider application that the argu- 
 ment is unsound; or he may pretend to agree with his 
 opponent, admit the soundness of his argument and 
 defend the truth of its absurdest conclusions — the op- 
 posite of what he really believes. Whately in "His- 
 toric Doubts" employs, in an ironical manner, Hume's 
 arguments against Christianity to prove the non-exist- 
 ence of Napoleon. Burke in "Vindication of Natural 
 Society" applies ironically BoHngbroke's arguments 
 against reUgious institutions to civil society. Swift's 
 "Modest Proposal" defends the cooking and eating of 
 the children as the proper mode of relief from famine 
 in Ireland. 
 
 A good instance of the direct way of treatment occurs 
 in a letter written to Junius by Sir William Draper. 
 Now, Junius had not only ridiculed the King in his first 
 letter to the printer of the Public Advertiser but had 
 handled unsparingly the Ministry. Sir WilHam then 
 came forward over his own signature to remove the 
 suspicions cast upon his friend the Marquis of Granby 
 as commander of the army. Draper was a man of 
 scholarly attainments, but alas! he was open-hearted 
 and highly sensitive to ironical criticism, the chief weapon 
 of his powerful antagonist. Junius accepted the chal- 
 lenge and instantly put the indiscreet Draper upon the 
 defensive. The latter managed to clear himself from 
 the charges affecting his personal honesty and with- 
 drew from the unequal contest. In the quotation given 
 below, referring to the Manila ransom, Draper showed 
 that if silence meant guilt, then Junius had convicted 
 himself of several charges. 
 
 Spain having taken sides with France during the 
 French and Indian War, an English expedition appeared
 
 ARGUMENT 75 
 
 (September 25, 1752) off Manila, capital of Luzon, an 
 island of the Philippine group, and at length carried the 
 place by assault (October 6). The victors accepted 
 "bills on ISIadrid for a million sterhng in lieu of pil- 
 lage," and departed; but Madrid repudiated the treaty. 
 Colonel Draper, who with Admiral Cornish commanded 
 the expedition, urged the government to insist upon pay- 
 ment of the ransom, but dropped the matter, as he tells 
 us, on grounds of "national convenience." Junius in- 
 sinuated that Draper's silence had been bought by sub- 
 sequent mihtary honors from the English Government, 
 and that he had sold out his companions who would 
 have shared in the prize. The charge must have ap- 
 pealed to a very strong popular sentiment, for, as Lecky 
 says, " the tame acquiescence of the government in the 
 Spanish refusal bitterly offended the national pride." 
 
 To support your story you have recourse to the following ir- 
 resistible argument: "You sold the companions of your vic- 
 tory, because when the i6th Regiment was given to you, you 
 were silent. The conclusion is inevitable." I believe that such 
 deep and acute reasoning could only come from such an extraor- 
 dinary writer as Junius. But, unfortunately for you, the prem- 
 ises as well as the conclusion are absolutely false. If your 
 puerile and tinsel logic could carry the least weight or conviction 
 with it, how must you stand affected by the inevitable conclu- 
 sion, as you are pleased to term it? According to Junius, silence 
 is guilt. In many of the public papers you have been called, 
 in the most direct and offensive terms, a liar and a coward. 
 When did you reply to these foul accusations? You have been 
 quite silent, quite chop-fallen; therefore, because you were 
 silent, the nation has a right to pronounce you to be both a liar 
 and a coward, from your own argument. 
 
 In his reply to Draper's argument, Junius neither 
 mentioned nor supported the general proposition that
 
 76 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 silence was guilt. He did not, however, refuse all con- 
 test; but, noticing the new and personal application, 
 was at great pains to explain why his name must be 
 withheld. It can pass unobserved largely from his use 
 of interrogatories and insinuations that in modifying 
 he has denied his original and sweeping contention. 
 His answer was as follows: 
 
 Your remarks upon a signature adopted merely for distinc- 
 tion are unworthy of notice; but when you tell me I have sub- 
 mitted to be called a liar and a coward, I must ask you, in my 
 turn, whether you seriously think it any way incumbent on me 
 to take notice of the silly invectives of every simpleton who 
 writes in a newspaper; and what opinion you would have con- 
 ceived of my discretion if I had suffered myself to be the dupe 
 of so shallow an artifice ? As to me it is by no means necessary 
 that I should be exposed to the resentment of the worst and most 
 powerful men in this country, though I may be indifferent about 
 yours. You assure me that my logic is puerile and tinsel; that 
 it carries not the least weight or conviction; that my premises 
 are false and my conclusions absurd. If this be a just descrip- 
 tion of me, how is it possible for such a writer to disturb your 
 peace of mind or to injure a character so well established as 
 yours? Take care, Sir William, how you indulge this unruly 
 temper, lest the world should suspect that conscience has some 
 show in your resentments. You have more to fear from the 
 treachery of your own passions than from my malevolence. 
 
 How Answered. — Reductio ad absurdum is effective 
 not only because it leaves an opponent's proposition 
 unproved, but because it reveals his unsound logic and 
 shakes confidence in his rehabiHty as a debater. In 
 answering; the chief aim of a debater may be to show 
 that he has not proved too much, that his position is 
 within reason. If he has been misrepresented, an em- 
 phatic denial that he believes the discredited ideas.
 
 ARGUMENT 77 
 
 accompanied by a statement of his true position, may 
 be all that is necessary. But generally it is well to show- 
 something more than the reasonableness of your posi- 
 tion. Possibly his argument was not germane to the 
 point at issue. An answer somewhat more effective 
 is the tu quoque or countercharge. For instance, if, upon 
 a question involving an amendment to an existing law, 
 it is held upon one side that the objections consider 
 only the abuses under the law, it can be held upon the 
 other that the enemies of amendment are merely oppos- 
 ing innovation. Circumstances may make it possible to 
 answer reductio ad ahsurdum by any of the chief modes 
 of attack suggested. Examine, in illustration, the fol- 
 lowing inquiries of Beecher's argument from the point 
 of view of his audience: 
 
 Suppose that a hstener in the audience refused to 
 believe that the "Minority is not always right." In 
 answering would it be effective to attempt to prove 
 the contradictory ? In tliis case, the reasoner would seek 
 to establish a proposition whose falsity seems obvious. 
 
 Refusing thus to believe that "the minority is not 
 always right," could the objector employ in his discus- 
 sion the method of the residue? Beecher's well-chosen 
 examples were most probably admitted and, therefore, 
 could not be eliminated. 
 
 Would it be effective to answer: "I grant your 
 premises and conclusion but remark in your reasoning 
 the fallacy ignoratio elenchi. I grant that the majority 
 is sometimes right and is sometimes wrong; that the 
 minority when right should receive support not because 
 it is the weaker party but because it is right, and be- 
 lieve that sympathy may go where it likes — usually to 
 the weaker party; still I fmd your argument irrelevant,
 
 78 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 for it ignores what, in my mind, is the real issue, 
 namely — Is the South in the right or in the wrong?" 
 Again, would it be effective to return upon Beecher's 
 general position, charging him with an equally false as- 
 sumption in the implied belief that "the majority is al- 
 ways right" ? In the event of a riot in a lunatic asylum, 
 for instance, would he always sympathize with the in- 
 mates or the superintendent? The inmates, it will be 
 noticed, are in the majority. 
 
 From its general nature, it is clear that reductio ad 
 ahsurdum is of special value in opening an attack. It 
 is used to introduce in a general way an answer to a 
 particular issue. In debate, therefore, it has proper 
 place in the first part of the first speeches in rebuttal. 
 When here employed it can overthrow an opponent's 
 entire case; more probably, however, it will remove 
 prejudice, enlist attention, and put an opponent upon 
 the defensive at the outset. If a speaker has reason 
 to believe that prejudice exists against his side, he may 
 employ the method in his first speech. An afiirmative 
 speaker, advocating a reform or amendment, sometimes 
 will begin by applying the argument to the conservative 
 temper; or recommending to a body of patriotic Amer- 
 icans the adoption of a European scheme of govern- 
 ment, before attempting proof, will reduce to an 
 absurdity the assumption that "whatever is American 
 is right." A debater objecting to a proposition on the 
 ground that it is an "innovation" employs a "question- 
 begging term" which can be effectively exposed by this 
 method. Henry Grattan, speaking upon the "Tithes," 
 answers this objection as follows: 
 
 Yes; but will you innovate? Admit this argument and we 
 sit here to consecrate abuses. The statutes of mortmain were
 
 ARGUMENT 79 
 
 innovations; for what is the Protestant religion but the inter- 
 position of Parliament, rescuing Christianity from abuses in- 
 troduced by its own priesthood? 
 
 Institutions, divine or human, corrupt by their nature or by 
 ours; the best human institution — the British Constitution — 
 did so corrupt, that at different periods it was anarchy, oligarchy, 
 despotism, and was restored by Parliament. 
 
 The only divine institution we know of — the Christian relig- 
 ion — did so corrupt as to have become an abomination, and was 
 rescued by act of Parliament. 
 
 Life, like establishments, declines; disease is the lot of nature; 
 we oppose its progress by strong remedies; we drink a fresh 
 life at some medical fountain, or we find a specific in some salu- 
 brious herb; will ^ou call these restorations innovation on the 
 physical economy ? Why, then, in the political economy, those 
 statutes which purge the public weal and from time to time guard 
 the infirm animal, man, against the evils to which civil society 
 is exposed — the encroachment of the priest and the politician? 
 
 It is then on a false surmise of our nature, this objection; 
 we live by a succession of amendments; such is the history of 
 man; such, above all, is the history of religion, where amend- 
 ment was even opposed; and those cant expressions, the sup- 
 porting church and state, were ever advanced to continue the 
 abuse of both. 
 
 2. The Dilemma. — We may also contrast two ideas 
 in the form of a dilemma, so as to put an opponent at 
 a disadvantage or render his position, or case, untenable. 
 Here the contrasted idea must be contradictory, and 
 each side of the contradiction — or, as we frequently 
 say, each "horn of the dilemma"— must have the power 
 to "gore" or injure. In his Cooper Institute Address, 
 Lincoln said: 
 
 You charge that we stir up insurrections among your slaves. 
 We deny it, and what is your proof? Harpers Ferry! John 
 Brown! John Brown was no Republican; and you have failed 
 to implicate a single Republican in his Harpers Ferry enterprise.
 
 80 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 If any member of our party is guilty in that matter, you know 
 it, or you do not know it. If you do know it, you are inexcusable 
 for not designating the man and proving the fact. If you do 
 not know it, you are inexcusable for asserting it, and especially 
 for persisting in the assertion after you have tried and failed to 
 make the proof. You need not be told that persisting in a charge 
 which one does not know to be true is simply malicious slander. 
 
 Two Kinds. — More closely, the dilemma is (i) simple 
 or (2) complex according as there are one or two sup- 
 positions. If it should be asserted that the United States 
 should declare war, a person, believing in the inadequacy 
 of the present navy, might answer: "If we declare war, 
 we must be able to defend our coasts and to attack the 
 enemy; either we cannot defend our coasts or we cannot 
 attack the enemy; therefore, we must not declare war." 
 The simple dilemma may be formally expressed as fol- 
 lows: If A is B, C is D, and E is F; either C is not 
 D or E is not F; therefore, A is not B. Imagine a 
 character, declared by his eulogist to be wise and then 
 good; imagine also that he is beheved by a critic to be 
 an irreverent person. The critic may resolve the argu- 
 ment into a contradiction, showing that he cannot be 
 both wise and good, e. g., "If he were wise, he would 
 not be irreverent in jest, and if he were good, he would 
 not be irreverent in earnest; but either he is irreverent 
 in jest or in earnest; therefore, either he is not wise 
 or not good." Again, Calhoun argued that the doctrine 
 of Nullification was a constitutional right, that it was 
 possible for a State to live within the Union and without 
 it at one and the same time; Webster, however, claimed 
 that the doctrine was rebellious. The doctrine may be 
 assailed thus: "If a State is without the Union, Nul- 
 lification is impossible, and if within, it is rebellious;
 
 ARGUMENT 81 
 
 but either a State is without the Union or within it; 
 therefore, either Nullification is impossible or rebel- 
 lious." The complex dilemma may be formally expressed 
 as foUows: If A is B, C is D; and if X is Y, E is F; 
 but either C is not D or E is not F; therefore, either A 
 is not B or X is not Y. 
 
 The simple dilemma has merely shown that an op- 
 ponent's assertion is false. The assertion being proved 
 false, it will follow that the argument of which it is a 
 premise must fall. The complex dilenmia ended with 
 stating that either of two assertions is false; that the 
 argument fails will follow from the fact that both as- 
 sertions are needed as premises to support it. 
 
 Ii^s Use. — It is clear from its twofold division that a 
 dilemma can attack either one or two assertions in an 
 argumentation. In case two assertions are attacked, 
 they may be found either in a single argument or in two 
 distinct arguments. The critic will sometimes discover 
 a contradiction in an opponent's proof of a single main 
 proposition and expose it by a complex dilemma; or 
 examining and criticising the proof of one main proposi- 
 tion and then of another, he will note some point of 
 contradiction contained in the proof of the two proposi- 
 tions and state it in dilemmatic form. But whether the 
 dilemma be simple or complex, or whether it be derived 
 from one or from two arguments, it should always be 
 remembered that unless the critic has grasped his op- 
 ponent's argumentation as a whole, has found his funda- 
 mental premises, his attack can hardly be fundamental 
 or essential. 
 
 How Answered.— In answering a dilemma you may 
 show that the contradiction is more apparent than real 
 — that there is a middle ground; or that one side is not
 
 82 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 sound; or admitting that the dilemma will hold true, 
 that it is irrelevant to the main argmnent. In any event, 
 your object is to show that your argument is not "in 
 dilemma." What I have said here of the destructive 
 dilemma applies, equally, to a constructive dilemma. 
 That is, for instance, if your opponent gives you a choice 
 between two alleged contradictions for the purpose of 
 eliminating one of your arguments (after which he in- 
 tends to disprove tlie remaining one), you may in answer- 
 ing, treat it likewise, by any of the ways mentioned. 
 
 Lincoln was particularly clever in charging his op- 
 ponent with putting him in a false dilemma and then 
 of showing that there was a middle ground. This is 
 what he did in the following: 
 
 He finds the Republicans insisting that the Declaration of 
 Independence includes all men, black as well as white, and forth- 
 •with he boldly denies that it includes negroes at all, and pro- 
 ceeds to argue gravely that all who contend it does, do so only 
 because they want to vote, and eat, and sleep, and marry with 
 negroes. He will have it that they cannot be consistent else. 
 Now I protest against the counterfeit logic which concludes that, 
 because I do not want a black woman for a slave I must neces- 
 sarily want her for a wife. I need not have her for either. I 
 can just leave her alone. 
 
 3. The Method of the Residue. — The method of the 
 residue may be regarded as a method of contrast, for 
 it is essentially a process of exclusion. Specifically, 
 the reasoner states a nimiber of cases; then eliminates 
 all the cases but one; and concludes, therefore, that 
 the residuary case is presumably true — e. g., it is not 
 this, it is not that, therefore it must be the other. If 
 a murder has been assigned to deliberate purpose, pas- 
 sion, or insanity, and the theories of passion and of de-
 
 ARGUMENT 83 
 
 liberate purpose have been respectively exploded, the 
 theory of insanity may be presumed to be true. Several 
 hypotheses are set up to account for a thing. Usually, 
 the affinnative will advance one hypothesis; the nega- 
 tive another or others. The affirmative then will en- 
 deavor to support his hypothesis against its rivals. He 
 must overthrow them. Enumerating all the hypotheses 
 advanced, excluding the opposing ones on specified 
 grounds, he infers that the remaining hypothesis, which 
 is, of course, his own, is presumably the true one. 
 
 It should be noted that only in case all possible hy- 
 potheses have been considered and the grounds of elim- 
 ination have been sufficient can the speaker go further 
 and conclude that his hypothesis is undeniably true; 
 but these suppositions do not often exist in fact. The 
 force of the method is destructive, but, as such, it is 
 simple and convincing. The debater will therefore 
 generally follow up his advantage by supporting his 
 theory by other and more positive proof. 
 
 The Hon. Member for Taunton insisted that there ought 
 to be "some understanding." Now, it was a mighty easy thing 
 to assert that there ought to be some understanding; but gen- 
 tlemen, however decided in their opinion, ought to come forward 
 and say what that understanding ought to be. There were 
 only three courses which the government of this country had 
 to pursue. It might decline all interference in the matter and 
 leave the planters, the negroes, and the Anti-Slavery Society 
 to fight the battle out amongst themselves. Would a resolution 
 like that be acceptable to the Hon. Member for Taunton? Was 
 the government not only to decline all interference, but to set 
 their faces, in toto, against alteration and improvement and to 
 abstain from proposing or recommending anything? Would 
 the Hon. gentleman approve of such a course? Why, probably 
 not; because the Hon. gentleman admitted that much altera- 
 tion and much gradual improvement of the condition of the
 
 84 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 slaves were desirable. The only question then was, how could 
 that amelioration be effected? But there was a third course 
 which the government might pursue upon the present question. 
 It might resolve to legislate altogether for the colonies — to take 
 the measures necessarily into their own hands; making no dis- 
 tinction between these colonies which had legislatures of their 
 own and those which were immediately under the control of 
 this country. Would that course be acceptable to the Hon. 
 Member for Taunton? Why, again, probably not; for a por- 
 tion of his speech had been occupied in showing the folly of such 
 a line of conduct. 
 
 The only remaining course, then, was that precise course which 
 government had pursued, and which the Hon. Member for Taun- 
 ton had taken much pains and time to show was the very wisest 
 that could possibly have been pursued. In those colonies as 
 to which the crown had a distinct right of legislation, govern- 
 ment had resolved to commence an example, which it was hoped 
 would soon be followed by those who had a right to legislate 
 for themselves. — {Peel, Sir Robert.) 
 
 Or look at it as a class question. What is it that is interested 
 in the maintenance of these laws? It cannot be the farmer, be- 
 cause the rent screw is turned upon him for every extra shilling a 
 quarter he makes on his corn. It cannot be the laboring classes, 
 for look at the wages of eight a week for a family of seven or 
 eight persons. It cannot be the commercial class, for the present 
 system keeps them out of a foreign as weU as a home market. 
 It cannot be the literary class, for who would care to provide 
 food for the mind when the food for the body is so heavily taxed ? 
 Then in fact it cannot be any class but that very small one 
 composed of some 10,000 or 20,000 (not more) of nominal owners 
 of the soil. — {Fox, W. J.) 
 
 In Plato's Republic, Socrates answered the erroneous 
 definitions which were held of justice, and suggested 
 that justice would best be seen in a perfect state. He 
 therefore traced the rise of a state; after which he 
 ascribed the four virtues, wisdom, courage, temperance, 
 and justice, to a state that is perfectly good. The first
 
 ARGUMENT 85 
 
 three ascertained the nature of the fourth, or justice 
 will be knowTi by the method of residues, "for it is plain 
 that it could only be the remainder," and when justice 
 is discovered in a perfect state, it may be recognized, 
 by analogy, in the individual man. Accordingly, the 
 ideal state is constructed. The following, from an analy- 
 sis^ of the Republic, will illustrate his emplo^Tiient of 
 the method of residues: 
 
 And now having traced the rise of a state from first to last, 
 Socrates returns to the question: Wliat is justice? And in what 
 part of the state are we to look for it? 
 
 The state, if it has been rightly organized, must be perfectly- 
 good, it must be wise, brave, temperate, and just. Hence, re- 
 garding the virtue of the state as a given quantity, made up of 
 wisdom, courage, temperance, and justice, if we can find three of 
 these, we shall by that very process have discovered the nature 
 of the fourth. 
 
 The wisdom of the state obviously resides in the small class 
 of guardians or magistrates. The courage of the state, as ob- 
 viously, resides in the auxiliaries, and consists essentially in ever 
 maintaining a right estimate of what is, or is not, really formi- 
 dable. 
 
 The essence of temperance is restraint. The essence of politi- 
 cal temperance lies in recognizing the right of the governing body 
 to the allegiance and obedience of the governed. It does not 
 reside in one particular class, like wisdom and courage, but is 
 diffused throughout the entire state in the form of a common 
 consent, or harmony, upon this subject. Thus we have found 
 the three: where, then, is the fourth? 
 
 After eUminating wisdom, courage, and temperance, there 
 still remains a something which enables the other three to take 
 root in the state, and preserves them intact therein. This some- 
 thing must, therefore, be justice. It may be defined as that 
 which teaches ever>'body to attend to his own business without 
 meddling in that of other people — which fuses together the three 
 
 * "The Republic of Plato." Davies and Vuughan.
 
 86 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 classes in the state and keeps each in its proper place. Con- 
 versely, the essence of political injustice lies in a meddling, rest- 
 less spirit pervading the three classes, and leading each to med- 
 dle with the offices, tools, and duties of the other two.
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 
 ARGUMENT 
 
 (continued) 
 
 ///. Argument from Causal Relation 
 
 If the source from which the conclusion is drawn is 
 regarded as having its basis in the relation which cause 
 bears to effect, antecedent to consequent or motive to 
 deed, the argument may be called argument from causal 
 relation. 
 
 We have learned from experience that "nothing 
 happens," but that all that exists is really the result 
 of some great antecedent principle or causal law. So, 
 in the field of science, we are constantly seeking to in- 
 terpret physical or biological phenomena through the 
 discovery of some general principle or law governing 
 the universe which we may apply in argument as a 
 causal reason or explanation of a particular phenomenon 
 or fact. Likewise, in the field of human conduct gen- 
 erally, we are prone to regard men as responsible agents 
 whose actions are guided by will, motive, desire, inten- 
 tion, modified of course by such attending circumstances 
 as heredity and environment. 
 
 Fundamentally, all reasoning assumes as its basis 
 the law of causation which affirms that every cause is 
 invariably followed by an effect and every effect is in- 
 variably preceded by a cause. The beUef in this law 
 is too generally recognized to need elaboration here, 
 
 87
 
 88 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 but the practical difficulties of appl3ang it to a concrete 
 case are so great as to be worthy of specific mention. 
 Obviously, causal reasoning may proceed from effect 
 to cause, from cause to effect, or from effect to effect. 
 
 The Rule of Adequacy. — The cause assigned must 
 be adequate to produce the known effect. 
 
 In discussing public questions as in government, 
 politics, economics, etc., when we assign a cause for a 
 known effect, we must take into account: 
 
 1. The parallelism or difference in conditions in past experi- 
 
 ence under which the assigned cause is said to operate. 
 It is here that reasoning from resemblance and differ- 
 ence or contrast performs its essential function in causal 
 reasoning. 
 
 2. The possibility of the existence of other causes operating 
 
 in conjunction wdth or in opposition to the assigned 
 cause in a cited case or in general, and also in the case 
 in question. Hunger, for instance, may in certain cir- 
 cumstances prompt to theft; but fear of detection may 
 prevent the act. 
 
 3. We must always allow for the evolution, change, and growth 
 
 of society as tending to modify, by progressive experi- 
 ences, the safe generalizations, abstractions, or opinions 
 of a former time. 
 
 That is to say, the adequacy of any cause assigned 
 for a known effect may depend on whether or not the 
 conditions we have in mind are really parallel, on the 
 absence of other co-operating or competing causes, and 
 on the law of progress. This same rule of adequacy is 
 equally true in using the reverse process, namely, that 
 of predicting the effects which will probably follow from 
 a known fact or principle asserted as a cause. 
 
 When we state some principle or fact and argue as 
 to the consequence or results which are likely to flow 
 from it, in general or in a particular case, we are arguing
 
 ARGUMENT 89 
 
 from cause to effect. In debating, the advantages of 
 adopting or rejecting a proposed plan, with its complex 
 of benefits and ev'ils, is a causal process of this kind. So 
 Washington argued against foreign alliances because 
 they would lead to international conflict, and Webster 
 opposed the South CaroUna Doctrine because it would 
 result in Civil War. As a rule, we first either affirm 
 or seek to establish some principle to guide our judg- 
 ment in the case in question, and then show also the 
 consequences which will result from its acceptance in 
 the present matter. The perorations of oratory are 
 replete with prophecies setting forth the effects result- 
 ing from the adoption of policies or courses of action, 
 with the added devices of imagery, important in em- 
 phasis and persuasion. 
 
 Further, we may argue directly from effect to effect. 
 If, for example, the process is from one effect to another 
 effect of the same probable cause, the argument may 
 be regarded simply as another name for argument from 
 sign. In the illustration, *'the clouds indicate rain," 
 it is hardly reasonable to regard the clouds as a cause 
 of rain, but rather to think of both clouds and rain as 
 effects of some such cause — as the weather bureau might 
 say — as "changes in the barometric pressure." If, 
 however, the process is from one effect to an allied effect 
 of a parallel cause, the argument may be simply re- 
 garded as argument from analogy. 
 
 Illustration of Causal Reasoning. — In seeking an an- 
 swer to the question "what is a nationaHty?" Theodore 
 Ruyssen,^ after examining six possible causes of nation- 
 ality, namely, the country, common interests, race, 
 language, rehgion, and spiritual unity, reaches the con- 
 ' American Associaiion for International Conciliation, No. 112.
 
 90 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 elusion that "the ideal nation appears to us as the close 
 synthesis of the social soul or collective will, with a sys- 
 tem of political institutions." To make clear further 
 the minute care needed in assigning causes for complex 
 facts or circumstances in human affairs, and also to 
 point out the difficulties of causal arguments, the follow- 
 ing points in Ruyssen's analysis should be of interest: 
 I. The interaction of cause and effect. 
 
 Does it not seem, after all, that the "natural boundary" 
 theorists by an unconscious sophism mistake for a cause what 
 is but an effect? In interpreting experience we naturally tend 
 to explain what is changeable by what is immutable, what is 
 variable by essential and permanent characteristics. Nothing 
 is more misleading than to account for the life of a people by 
 the form of their country in our atlases of historical geography. 
 The natural features of the great historic countries, Spain, Great 
 Britain, France, are so familiar to us, they have so completely 
 become for us the image of these nations, that there would seem 
 to be a necessary connection between their topography and 
 their history, and surely no one would deny that there is much 
 truth in this view. But it should be remembered that the geog- 
 raphy of a nation is itself the product of its history; we need 
 only look at an historical atlas to be assured of this. France 
 has not always reached to the Alps and the Pyrenees, and her 
 northeastern frontier has been subject to constant alteration. 
 Of what existing boundary may we say that it is fixed by the 
 nature of things ? If any country might be thought predestined 
 "by nature" to attain national unity, it is certainly Italy, iso- 
 lated from other nations by the sea and by the highest moun- 
 tains in Europe. Nevertheless, she remained for centuries after 
 the fall of the Roman Empire but a "geographical expression," 
 and even to-day she must fight hard to conquer the frontiers 
 which nature seemed to have assigned to her. Doubtless, it is 
 true enough that in one sense the country makes the people, 
 modifies their character and imposes on them certain habits; 
 but, on the other hand, we may also say that the people fashion 
 their country by their dreams and aspirations.
 
 ARGUMENT 91 
 
 2. Partial and temporary causes. 
 
 How explain by motives of self-interest the Polish insurrec- 
 tion of 1863, a movement of chivalrous folly condemned from 
 the outset to a cruel defeat? In short, common interests may 
 unite for a time even hostile forces, just as they may bring into 
 opposition persons or groups otherwise sympathetic. But the 
 national bond is of a different sort than a convenient com- 
 promise; a nation is not a syndicate of desires. 
 
 3. Multiplicity of causes. 
 
 The most important part of Renan's analysis, in my opinion, 
 is his masterly criticism of the theories which would determine 
 nationality by race. The progress of ethnography and of an- 
 thropology in the last thirty years has not in the least weak- 
 ened Renan's position. Can any one use the term race in its 
 strictest sense as implying a number of individuals of the same 
 species linked together by a common ancestry? It is obvious 
 that to do so we should have to seek out the very origins of the 
 human race which are lost in the uncertain distances of prehis- 
 toric times; rather a question of metaphysics than of physiology 
 or of human geography. We believe no longer in the mythical 
 division of the human family among the sons of Noah, and yet 
 we do not know whether the forest of humanity has sprung 
 from a single root or from a number of diverse stocks. An- 
 thropology knows no instance of a pure race, nor a single ex- 
 ample of any race unable to blend itself with another. We may, 
 it is true, by comparing certain outstanding human character- 
 istics, such as stature, facial angle, cephalic index, and so forth, 
 determine the predominance of certain types in a given region 
 and explain the variations from this by migrations or by the re- 
 surgence of very ancient homogeneous races; but, apart from 
 the fact that no one knows whether these races are themselves 
 pure or composite, the indications of anthropology are confirmed 
 neither by linguistics nor history. Nowhere can the geograph- 
 ical distribution of languages be traced back to the division 
 of populations into tall, blond dolichocephalic and dark, short 
 brachycephalic types.
 
 92 THE FUNDAMENT.\LS OF DEBATE 
 
 4. Relative value of causes. 
 
 But we readily perceive that in a race so considered, the factor 
 which is considered of first importance, physiological inheritance, 
 plays an uncertain but always secondary part, and that the truly 
 determining factors are climate, costume, or habits of life. It will 
 be found, for example, that peoples undoubtedly akin may be- 
 come decidedly different from each other — as with the Alsatians 
 and the Badenese — whereas populations that grow by immigra- 
 tion soon impose upon the newcomers a new type; for instance, 
 the Yankee type which asserts itself in so curious a fashion 
 after two or three generations among immigrants of every de- 
 scent who have come to the United States, Anglo-Saxons, Ger- 
 mans, Jews, Italians, and all others. From this it follows that 
 race, wherever it constitutes an effective social reality, is fully as 
 much a product of as a factor in the national life. A nation is 
 not determined by its heredity; it is a living organism which 
 is both adapted to its environment and adapts that to itself. Or 
 better said — ^for this mutual adaptation might be a wholly ma- 
 terial process — a nation bears the imprint of its spiritual vitality 
 on its brow and in its sinews. It may degenerate from alcohol, 
 debauchery, overstrain, or dehberate surrender; or it may en- 
 hance, rebuild, and beautify its life by good hygiene, athletics, 
 schooling, military training, games, the arts, and the intensive 
 development of spiritual life. 
 
 In a word, nationalities are populations that aspire to become 
 nations. Like nations they are complex collectivities, drawing 
 their sentiment of unity from a great number of sources, among 
 which the moral factors, traditions, religion, and a common 
 speech are the most essential. But in order to become nations 
 in the full sense of the term they must gain that political in- 
 dependence through which means alone a complete social life 
 can manifest itself. 
 
 Causal Argument, and the Other Sources of Reason- 
 ing. — Moreover, the reader will notice in these quota- 
 tions that, while the inquiry is obviously the solution 
 of a causal problem, there is used much concrete ma- 
 terial, involving the principle of resemblance and dif-
 
 ARGUMENT 93 
 
 ference as well as much generalization in order to make 
 the argument clear and intelligible. 
 
 It has been said that all arguments in their final analy- 
 sis, and when carried to completion, may be shown to 
 involve an inference from a complex of four relations. 
 The illustration previously used may be stated for causal 
 argimient thus: This smoke is the result of lire, for smoke 
 usually means fire. In other cases when I have seen 
 smoke I have found fire, or where there is smoke there 
 is (or has been) fire. 
 
 Differences of View-Point. — The points of view of 
 men differ so widely, as, for instance, between scientist 
 and business man, lawyer and doctor, professor and 
 student, that we often despair of agreeing with others 
 on a single cause for a known effect. On tliis account, 
 no doubt, we sometimes use exposition to show how a 
 proposed plan will work, and also persuasion to create 
 a wish or desire for its adoption. An attractive liow 
 is more effective than a disputed why. 
 
 Much of our causal reasoning, indeed, is merely ex- 
 planatory and not fundamental, which suggests the 
 uncertainty of all human reasoning about nature, life, 
 and conduct. 
 
 IV. Inductive and Deductive Arguments 
 
 If the source from which the conclusion is drawn is 
 regarded as having its basis in the relation which a par- 
 ticular bears to a general or a general to a particular, 
 the argument may be called inductive or deductive. 
 
 If the reasoning moves from a general to a particular, 
 from a more to a less general, the process is deductive. 
 Hence, when we say all sailors are swimmers — Jones 
 is a sailor; therefore, Jones is a swimmer — ^we reason
 
 94 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 deductively. If, on the other hand, the reasoning moves 
 from a particular to a general, from a less to a more 
 general, the process is inductive. Hence, when we say 
 that because John who is a sailor is a swimmer, and 
 because William who is a sailor is a swimmer, etc. — there- 
 fore, all sailors are swimmers — we reason inductively. 
 This classification, of course, is quite independent of the 
 source of the reasoning employed as involving the prin- 
 ciple of simple association, of resemblance, or of cause 
 to effect. Any such relations may exist either in deduc- 
 tion or in induction. 
 
 Whatever may be the sources of our particulars, facts, 
 or instances, whether they come from our own experi- 
 ence and observation, or are made known to us by read- 
 ing, or by the testimony of witnesses given in person; we 
 may draw inferences from them, as to facts not yet 
 known or as to general trutlis to which the particulars 
 are related. If, when travelling through the West, we 
 should happen to observe that the faces of all the In- 
 dians we have seen were invariably of a reddish color, 
 we should perhaps feel justified in concluding, therefore, 
 that the faces of all Indians are invariably of this color. 
 The reasoning is inductive, for it proceeds obviously 
 from the hue of a number of Indians separately observed 
 to a general conclusion about all Indians. Or, if upon 
 reading the lives of several Presidents of the United 
 States, for instance, of Washington, Jefferson, and Lin- 
 cohi, we should be impressed by their ability and char- 
 acter, and should conclude consequently that "all Presi- 
 dents of the United States are men of abihty and 
 character," the reasoning would be inductive. We 
 should draw a general conclusion about all Presidents 
 from what we had read about several,
 
 ARGUMENT 95 
 
 The Inevitable Assumption. — The great value of in- 
 ductive reasoning appears to be in those cases where 
 it is impossible to examine all the particulars or facts. 
 It is reasoning from the known to the unknown. Be- 
 cause the Indians whom we have observed are red, 
 we infer that all persons called Indians possess a like 
 appearance; because several Presidents whose lives 
 we have read appear to us as men of abihty and 
 character, we infer that all men belonging to the class, 
 Presidents, possess similar characteristics. But the ques- 
 tion arises, How can we say anything accurately about 
 "all Indians" or "all Presidents," since we have only 
 seen a few Indians and have read the Hves of but three 
 Presidents? The answer is that the argiunent from in- 
 duction is based upon the law of uniformity. In other 
 words, there Ues at the bottom of all inductive reason- 
 ing this unexpressed assumption: that what is true of 
 several particulars making 'up a general is true of the 
 general, "what is true of several members of a class is 
 true of the class as a whole." 
 
 The Inductive Formula. — If we attempt to put in- 
 ductive reasoning into a formula, it is clear that what 
 has been called the law of uniformity must appear as 
 a premise, for it has been shown to be necessary to the 
 inductive conclusion. The fomiula may be stated thus: 
 
 I. Assumption. What is true of several members of a class 
 
 is true of the class as a whole. 
 II, Facts. 
 
 a. President Washington was a man of character and 
 
 ability. 
 
 b. President Jefferson was ditto. 
 
 c. President Lincoln was ditto. 
 
 Ill, Therefore, all Presidents of the United States have been 
 men of character and ability.
 
 96 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 The previous illustrations are simple illustrations of 
 the loose inductions which we ordinarily make in daily 
 affairs. 
 
 Induction, the Scientific Method of Investiga- 
 tion. — Induction should proceed by hypothesis and 
 verification. The scientist who reasons pre-eminently 
 by induction is patient in his investigations and cautious 
 in drawing his conclusions. Starting with a few facts, 
 he will make some inference provisionally and assert 
 it as an hypothesis. This is hardly more than a con- 
 jecture made for the purposes of the investigation, and 
 to be modified or even abandoned as the subsequent 
 discovery of facts may seem to require. That hypothesis 
 which will explain all the facts in the best possible way 
 is the one finally to be accepted and affirmed as true. 
 
 Kinds of Induction. — Induction is of two kinds, im- 
 perfect or perfect. Imperfect induction is induction 
 based on the above assumption. It is of three kinds 
 according as it is regarded as involving the other sources 
 or bases of reasoning, e. g., in the first place there is the 
 causal or scientific method, in which the generalization 
 resulting is a cause — e. g., the law of gravitation. 
 Second, there is the method of resemblance, in which 
 the generalization is a conclusion drawn from other 
 cases similar in character; e. g., arsenic will prove fatal 
 because of cited cases in which death resulted. Third, 
 the method of association in which the generalization 
 is the result of .previous associations in experience, e. g., 
 clouds are a sign of rain. Here again we may see how 
 the name we affix to any argument will depend on the 
 point of view. Perfect induction does not involve an 
 assumption. It is sunply a method of enumeration, e. g., 
 there are fifteen persons in this room.
 
 ARGUMENT 97 
 
 Deduction, a Ready Mode of Reasoning. — Deduction 
 is a thoroughly simple, natural process. In ordinary- 
 affairs we constantly employ general ideas to aid us in 
 reaching a conclusion concerning a particular instance. 
 On seeing clouds I infer that it is likely to rain to- 
 morrow, because clouds are usually followed by rain. 
 Having to reach a railroad-station a mile off, I allow 
 myself fifteen minutes, because I have found out from 
 experience that I can walk a mile comfortably in that 
 time. I attend the Princeton- Yale football game, feel- 
 ing sure that it will be worth seeing, because all these 
 contests in the past have been worth seeing, and so on. 
 The process is, in each of these illustrations, deductive — 
 from the general to the particular. I have merely ap- 
 plied what I already know from past general experi- 
 ence to aid me in drawing conclusions in the several 
 special instances. I have done this, too, without specially 
 investigating the truth of the general ideas employed. 
 Hence, it may appear that deduction is a ready method 
 of reasoning and proof involving the use of generaliza- 
 tions already known or ascertained. 
 
 Deduction, Supplemented by Induction. — The generali- 
 zations employed by deduction usually have their source 
 in past experience. If we examine the general proposi- 
 tions used in the preceding illustrations, we find that 
 they rest upon previous inductions. It is from the ob- 
 servation of a number of separate instances that I have 
 been able to say that clouds usually mean rain; it is 
 from the recollection of the several Princeton- Yale games 
 that I have witnessed that I have confidently asserted 
 that all Prince ton- Yale games are worth seeing; and it 
 is because I have walked a mile comfortably in fifteen 
 minutes on this and that occasion that I feel justified
 
 98 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 in assuming in general that I can walk that distance 
 comfortably in that time. "Deduction," says President 
 Hibben, "that reaches other than purely abstract and 
 formal conclusions must rest upon induction for the 
 material to form its premises." Thus, while deduction 
 is a ready mode of reasoning, and may be sufficient for 
 one's purposes, we may have need to use induction in 
 order to make the conclusion more certain by establish- 
 ing the generalization on which the deduction is based. 
 
 The student should beware of the use of hastily as- 
 sumed generalizations in reasoning. "The boasted 
 Athenians," said Doctor Johnson, "were barbarians. 
 The mass of every people must be barbarous, where 
 there is no printing." Macaulay shows that this rea- 
 soning was based on a generalization which was both 
 incorrectly derived and false. 
 
 Deduction, a Method of Criticism. — We have been 
 thinking of deduction constructively, as a mode of 
 reasoning or proof; but it may be equally important 
 for us to be able to criticise scientifically the accuracy 
 of a reasoning process. We are sometimes less con- 
 cerned about the truth of the propositions used in reason- 
 ing than about the consistency of the reasoning itself. 
 In such cases, we can test the process in question by 
 throwing it into the form of a syllogism. 
 
 The syllogism is a group of three propositions; namely, 
 the conclusion or proposition to be proved and two 
 other propositions from which the conclusion is drawn. 
 If now we say "the man is intelligent," "an intelligent 
 person is rare," we can conclude therefore that "the 
 man is a rare person." The reasoning is in accord with 
 the known principle that things which are equal to the 
 same things are equal to each other. This group is called 
 a syllogism. But we cannot draw a conclusion from
 
 ARGUMENT 99 
 
 any two propositions; they must have one term in 
 common, as, for instance, "intelligent." There are three 
 terms in a syllogism, the first and second propositions 
 having one term alike and each a particular term, which 
 reappear in the conclusion. Not only must there be 
 a conmion term in the first two propositions but in one 
 of them this term must be, as it is called, distributed. 
 A universal proposition distributes its subject, that is, 
 makes it include all members of its class taken sepa- 
 rately, while a particular proposition does not. If we 
 say "John is intelligent," "William is intelHgent," we 
 have a common term, but since it is not distributed we 
 cannot draw a new conclusion. In the correct syllogism, 
 however, the common or middle term, as it is usually 
 called, was distributed in the proposition "an intel- 
 Hgent person is rare," for an assertion was made of all 
 intelhgent persons. The first two propositions in a 
 syllogism are called premises; the premise which con- 
 tains the middle term and the predicate of the conclu- 
 sion is called the major premise, that which contains 
 the middle term and the subject of the conclusion is 
 called the minor premise. 
 
 This is but one form of syllogism into which our 
 reasoning can be thrown. Altogether there are twenty- 
 four varieties of valid syllogisms, the variations depend- 
 ing on the position of the middle term and on the 
 quantity and quality of the first two propositions. The 
 quantity of a proposition refers to its universal or par- 
 ticular character, the quality to its affirmative or nega- 
 tive. 
 
 The Enthymeme. — In debating, the syllogism does 
 not appear in its complete form but with one of its 
 premises suppressed. Such instances of the incomplete 
 formula are known as enthymemes. The syllogism just
 
 100 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 mentioned may be stated as an enthymeme thus: the 
 man is a rare person because he is intelligent. Or dis- 
 carding the major premise we may say: the man is a 
 rare person because an intelhgent person is rare. If 
 we argue in the former way we assume, as admitted, that 
 **an intelligent person is rare"; if in the latter, that 
 "he is intelligent." We may see again the need of three 
 propositions in any reasoning that is logically complete. 
 We may also see that, for ordinary purposes, the use 
 of two propositions may be sufficient. An enthymeme, 
 however, can be tested by referring it to a syllogism. 
 
 The Chain of Reasoning. — When we reason so that 
 the conclusion of one argument is made the premise 
 of the second argument and so on to a final conclusion, 
 we employ a chain of reasoning. A single argument 
 may indeed be sufficient to estabhsh the conclusion de- 
 sired, but in case a premise of the argument employed 
 is questioned it may be necessary to formulate another 
 argument in which the disputed premise is made the 
 conclusion. Epictetus remarked that when ''death 
 may appear to be an evil, have ready the thought that 
 it is right to avoid evils and that death is unavoidable." 
 What he said was in effect this: (i) Nothing that it is 
 right to avoid is unavoidable; it is right to avoid all 
 evils; therefore, no evils are unavoidable. (2) No evils 
 are unavoidable; death is unavoidable; therefore, death 
 is no evil. The reasoning is here thrown into two syl- 
 logisms, the major premise of the first being supplied. 
 We may put this chain of reasoning into a series of en- 
 thymemes as follows: 
 
 Death is not an evil, because 
 A. All evils are avoidable, for 
 
 I. All that it is right to avoid is avoidable.
 
 ARGUMENT 101 
 
 The reasoning here is perfectly clear, both the suppressed 
 minor premise of A, that "death is unavoidable," and 
 the suppressed minor premise of ^ i, that "it is right 
 to avoid all evils," being taken for granted. 
 
 Two Classes of Fallacies. — Fallacies, or errors in 
 reasoning, have been divided into two classes, formal 
 and material, according as they occur in the form of 
 the reasoning or in the subject-matter. We may men- 
 tion several cases of formal fallacies: (i) Equivocation, 
 or the use of a word in more than one sense, e. g., Eng- 
 land has a responsible cabinet system. Her ministers 
 are responsible, trustworthy men. (2) Amphibology, 
 or ambiguous grammatical structure. This fallacy 
 frequently arises from undue ellipsis or from an improper 
 arrangement in a sentence — e. g., "the duke yet lives 
 that Henry shall depose," "and all the air a solemn 
 stillness holds," Daudet is nearer Trollope than Dickens. 
 (3) Composition, which affirms something of a class 
 separately in the major premise and collectively in the 
 minor, e. g., three and two are two numbers; five is 
 two and three; therefore, five is two numbers. (4) Divi- 
 sion, which afiirms something of a class collectively in 
 the major premise and separately in the minor, e. g., 
 all the angles of a triangle (taken together) are equal 
 to two right angles; these are angles of a triangle 
 (separately); therefore, these angles are equal to two 
 right angles. (5) Accent, or a grammatical structure 
 in which the ambiguity arises from a misplaced accent, 
 e. g., " thou shalt not bear false witness against thy neigh- 
 bor," as signifying that we can bear false witness against 
 others. 
 
 Several cases of material fallacies may be mentioned, 
 (i) Pelitii Principii, begging the question, which con-
 
 102 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 sists in its simplest form of attempting to prove a propo- 
 sition by itself, e. g., opium produces sleep, because it 
 is soporific. Broadly, it is the fallacy of assuming with- 
 out proof. (2) Ignoralio Elenchi, irrelevant conclusion, 
 e. g., arguing that the sexes are mentally equal while 
 pretending to argue that the suffrage should be given 
 to women. (3) Non Sequitur, or false consequent, e. g., 
 the ground is wet; therefore, it has rained. (4) Non 
 causa pro causa, or the false cause, e. g., one of a party 
 of thirteen who sat at a table died within a year; there- 
 fore, the unlucky number at the table was the cause 
 of his death. (5) Plurium Interrogationum, or many 
 questions. "Have you left off your bad habits?" This 
 question cannot be answered categorically without an 
 injurious admission. The remedy is to separate it thus: 
 Have you bad habits? If so, have you left them off? 
 
 A Common Ground in Argument. — Valuable as is 
 the preceding classification of arguments for an under- 
 standing of the nature and scope of the argumentative 
 processes, it should always be remembered that the end 
 of argument is agreement. Logically, unless there is 
 agreement in the premises, there can be no agreement 
 in the conclusion. There must be some common ground, 
 some basis of agreement in the premises and reasoning. 
 
 The practical debater simply applies portions of his 
 own experiences, with insight and tact, to the needs 
 of a particular situation. But the getting of another 
 to recognize one's point of view sufficiently to make him 
 change his mind is a very difficult matter. It will 
 usually demand the ability "to see others as they see 
 themselves," and will require considerable insight, a 
 process of interpretation which is both perceptual and 
 associative in character.
 
 ARGUMENT 103 
 
 In general, an effective argument is an argument 
 well imaged; as, for example, one whose major premise, 
 minor premise, and conclusion are so vividly presented 
 that the conclusion is instinctively visualized as a real- 
 ity by the mind to which it is addressed. But in imaging 
 ideas, we shall have need to consider not only our own 
 views but to find the ideas and beliefs in the mind and 
 experience of our hearers with which we may connect the 
 views urged by us. We can take care, for instance, that 
 the opinion or action urged is in accord with some class 
 conception or "principle of action which is sl fixed and 
 stable part" of the ego of the persons we seek to con- 
 vince, 
 
 "It may be said in general," says James, "that a 
 great part of every deliberation consists in the turning 
 over of all the possible modes of conceiving of the doing 
 or not doing of the act in point. The moment we hit 
 upon a conception which lets us apply some principle 
 of action which is a fixed and stable part of our ego, our 
 state of doubt is at an end. Persons of authority, who 
 have to make many decisions in a day, carry with them 
 a set of heads of classification, each bearing its voli- 
 tional consequence, and under these they seek as far 
 as possible to arrange each new emergency as it occurs. 
 It is where the species is without precedent, to which 
 consequently no cut-and-dried maxim will apply, that 
 we feel at a loss, and are distressed at tlie indeterminate- 
 ness of our task. As soon, however, as we see our way 
 to a familiar classification, we are at ease again. In 
 action as in reasoning, then, the great thing is the quest 
 of the right conception." ^ 
 
 There may also be a common ground of feeling as well 
 
 * "Briefer Course," 430.
 
 104 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 as of reasoning. But even when it is necessary to arouse 
 attention and interest in order to overcome prejudice 
 or belief, to enlist sympathy, or to stiffen the will before 
 we can get our views accepted by another, the image- 
 making process may be said to be the handmaiden of 
 that type of the associative process which we called 
 the logical. We shall see this more fully later on. 
 
 V. The Refutation 
 
 It is not to be supposed that the rebuttal is very dif- 
 ferent in character from the first speech. In the open- 
 ing address, for example, a debater will avoid fallacy 
 and assertion, things which he may hope to detect in 
 the argument of his opponent. There is no class of ar- 
 guments peculiar to refutation which may not be em- 
 ployed directly. The same power of analysis, knowledge 
 of evidence, skill in the construction of a logical frame- 
 work, tact in persuasion are to be employed in both 
 speeches. It is to be remembered, too, that the general 
 aim of debate is to compel assent or to induce action. 
 
 As distinguished from the first speech, the rebuttal 
 deals with objections. Its specific aim, therefore, is to 
 answer objections advanced in opposition, and to offer 
 objections to opposed arguments. Arguments which 
 are in form constructive belong to the first speech; 
 those in form destructive to the rebuttal. But this 
 rule is not invariable, for it is frequently wise to antic- 
 ipate objections, and answer them in the first speech. 
 This is done upon two grounds: either to remove prej- 
 udice or to weaken the force of the objections. Even 
 in rebuttal if an opponent's objections are weak, very 
 little time should be consumed in answering them. They 
 may, indeed, be ignored; in which case the debater will
 
 ARGUMENT 105 
 
 employ his time in presenting new arguments, in en- 
 forcing an argument already advanced, in recapitula- 
 tion, or in an appeal to the audience. It is important 
 to note that a great amount of attention devoted to 
 objections will give the impression of a lack of confidence 
 on the part of the speaker in his own constructive argu- 
 ments. 
 
 Preparation for the rebuttal must include a thorough 
 and minute study of the opposite side. Several sug- 
 gestions may be made. In the first place, the debater 
 should be so thoroughly acquainted with the arguments 
 usually employed in support of the opposite side and 
 the usual form of stating them, that he cannot be taken 
 by surprise. Again, he should be equally well acquainted 
 with the arguments usually advanced to refute the op- 
 posite arguments, including their usual form of state- 
 ment, so that he will know exactly with the least hesi- 
 tation how each argument may be answered. But a 
 study of only the usual arguments will be inadequate 
 if an opponent is specially skilled, and impossible if 
 the question is under discussion for the first time. At 
 all events, the successful debater will hardly be content 
 to quit work when he has guarded his defenses and di- 
 rected his attacks in only the conventional ways; to 
 many a man real work is just begun. He will institute 
 new inquiries, make new researches, glean new facts 
 from distant quarters, give old ones new applications, 
 find new theories, unexpected devices; in a word, he 
 will seek to discover by painstaking efi"ort the strongest 
 possible objections and the strongest possible ways of 
 overturning them. 
 
 An important limitation is imposed upon the discus- 
 sion by the presentation of the arguments upon the op-
 
 106 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 posite side. The affirmative's rebuttal is conditioned 
 by the negative's answer or opening speech, the nega- 
 tive's rebuttal by the affirmative's opening speech. The 
 practical rule is this: limit discussion to arguments 
 actually presented by your opponent. Your opposi- 
 tion is no longer general and undefined, it is not now 
 merely supposed or anticipated, but specific, real, and 
 present. Do not, for example, state that "my opponent 
 will say such and such a thing," but answer arguments 
 actually made. Do not set things up for the sake of 
 destro^-ing them, fight windmills, or deal with possible 
 arguments not actually employed. Your attack should 
 be directed against your opponent's case as made up 
 by him and with the evidence which he adduced to sup- 
 port it. 
 
 Selection. — It is sometimes difficult to consent to 
 throw away unnecessary ideas. But, unfortunately, 
 the things which come into the mind on first hearing 
 an argument are not always the most important. Your 
 objection being a weak one, it might be omitted alto- 
 gether, and a little coolness and deliberation might cause 
 you to canvass the subject more thoroughly and reveal 
 to you a stronger answer. Or perhaps the argument 
 should be ignored. Equally important with a knowl- 
 edge of the way each argument should be answered is 
 the exercise of judgment and tact in the selection of 
 the argument to be attacked. Not every main argu- 
 ment of your opponent is to be answered, for there are 
 usually strong arguments upon both sides. "There are 
 objections," says Doctor Johnson, "against a plenum 
 and objections against a vacuum; but one of them must 
 be true." To attempt, however, to answer an argu- 
 ment most probably true, will not only fail, but, in ad-
 
 ARGUMENT 107 
 
 dition, serve to emphasize the weakness of your own 
 argument. If, therefore, you believe an argument to 
 be valid, do not attempt to refute it. If it should seem 
 necessary to notice it, you can employ what may be 
 called a method of depreciatory contrast. You can do 
 this, for instance, by saying: "Even supposing such or 
 such a proposition of my opponent to be true, it is of 
 much less significance, of much inferior moment, than 
 such or such a proposition of my own." Or, again, with- 
 out denying the proposition, perhaps you can attack its 
 proof. In doing this, you will keep clearly in view the 
 distinction that the question is not whether the hearers 
 believe the proposition true, but whether its truth is 
 conclusively proved. 
 
 A debater can attack all the main propositions set 
 up by his opponent; he can attack only one main proposi- 
 tion, admitting or ignoring the others; or he can admit 
 or ignore them all, attacking only the general conclusion. 
 It is here to be said that the argmnents employed most 
 frequently in debate are not demonstrative but only 
 probable in their force; and, consequently, that the 
 debater's aim is to show that the preponderance of prob- 
 ability rests upon his side. If, then, this preponderance 
 can be shown as to the general conclusion, it is not ma- 
 terial that some objections are passed by. 
 
 What objections are to be selected for attack? What 
 ignored? What admitted? These questions, in prac- 
 tice, are not easy of solution. The decisions should be 
 made with deliberation after accurately weighing in 
 balance each argument against its corresponding ob- 
 jection. The strongest arguments which can be most 
 successfully rebutted should be made in every case in 
 the contest the objects of attack.
 
 108 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 Fundamental Criticism. — Where shall the argument 
 be attacked? Manifestly, at essential or fundamental 
 points. But these points should be vital. A spear thrust 
 through the cuirass or gorget is more formidable than 
 one through the joints of the greaves. Find the vital, 
 vulnerable points in your opponent's main argument. 
 Deal with the argumentation as a whole, and not only 
 in its minor divisions. Construct for yourself, if pos- 
 sible, the main syllogism of your opponent's argumen- 
 tation and notice minor syllogisms only when your criti- 
 cism of them can be shown to affect the main syllogism. 
 Now, the syllogism of an argument ought to be such 
 that its premises can either be granted or proved to be 
 true; and its reasoning ought to be conclusive. If, 
 however, the reasoning is inconclusive or either premise 
 is false absolutely or most probably, the fact should 
 be made evident. 
 
 Burke's argument that "taxation without represen- 
 tation is unjust" can be reduced to the following syl- 
 logism: taxation without an equivalent is unjust; the 
 taxation of the American colonies is without an equiv- 
 alent; therefore, the taxation of the American colonies 
 is unjust. In examining this syllogism two things will 
 appear: First, that the reasoning is conclusive; second, 
 that the major premise can perhaps be admitted to be 
 true, because taxation is of the nature of a contract. 
 It will be discerned, however, that the minor premise 
 demands proof, which, indeed, Burke did not ignore. 
 But if it should be expedient to attack this argu- 
 ment, the issue would be raised upon the truth of the 
 minor premise. Such criticism would be relevant and 
 fundamental, its success or effectiveness depending, of 
 course, upon the relative force of the arguments pro
 
 ARGUMENT 109 
 
 and con. A fundamental criticism directed against 
 slight misstatements, discrepancies, or minor and iso- 
 lated points will be, of necessity, weak and superficial. 
 
 Two General Methods of Refutation. — The suscepti- 
 bility of any proposition to attack is due either to the 
 existence of an error in the argument or to the existence 
 of other facts not taken into consideration. Sometimes 
 a part of the facts is suppressed. This is what happened 
 in the memorable trial of Bardell against Pickwick. 
 In our amusement here at the incident of the finding 
 of Mrs. Bardell in the arms of the defendant, who was 
 soothing and caressing her, we almost overlook, with 
 Sergeant Buzfuz, the fact that Mrs. Bardell was ill and 
 had just fainted away. Indeed, it is not surprising 
 that the verdict went to the plaintiff. Now what hap- 
 pened here intentionally can occur accidentally from 
 an ignorance of a part of the facts. There are in general 
 but two ways of refuting a proposition: overthrowing 
 its supporting argument and proving the contradictory. 
 They are not mutually exclusive, for a speaker can em- 
 ploy both methods in attacking one proposition. The 
 opposed structure is destroyed first, and the new one 
 is erected upon its ruins. You can find a good instance 
 in Burke's speech on American taxation. He stated 
 that there are two modes of discussing the subject, one 
 narrow and simple, another broad and historic. He 
 answered the arguments offered in the restrictive mode, 
 and then expounded the comprehensive view which he 
 thought was the proper one. 
 
 In overthrowing an argument already advanced in 
 support of a proposition, the reasoner may point out 
 errors in the syllogistic process. Is there an error in dis- 
 tribution of terms? Arc there two negative premises
 
 110 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 or two particular premises or some formal defect in 
 structure? If so, the argument will fall. Again, are 
 both premises true? In case one is doubtful, is it sup- 
 ported by evidence? Is the evidence offered relevant, 
 material, and competent? Failing here, it can be con- 
 cluded that the proof is inadequate and the premise 
 presumably false; for a proof which does not succeed, 
 raises, indeed, a strong presumption against the proposi- 
 tion it seeks to defend. In refuting a proposition by 
 overthrowing the argument it is generally advisable 
 to show not only where the faulty process Hes, but, in 
 addition, exactly how it can be supposed to have 
 arisen. 
 
 Suppose the point at issue — to illustrate the second 
 method — is supported by a syllogism which is logically 
 sound, and the premises of which seem true; still it 
 may happen that an opponent can find sufficient evi- 
 dence to prove a proposition which will contradict the 
 one attacked. While the method in such a procedure 
 is constructive in that it proves a new proposition, it is 
 destructive in that the proposition proved is incom- 
 patible with that of the opposite side. The proof of 
 an ahbi, for instance, by a man charged with murder 
 upon circumstantial evidence is just as complete a refu- 
 tation as if the evidence were shown to be "irrelevant, 
 immaterial, and incompetent." Perhaps, usually, it 
 will appear that where this method is employed the 
 opponent's argument is not strong in probative force. 
 The chief value of the method lies in the fact that it is 
 practicable when no other form of proof can be procured. 
 Not only, however, may the proposition in issue be re- 
 futed by direct opposed argument, but also the premises 
 (of which the proposition in issue is the conclusion).
 
 ARGUMENT HI 
 
 Special types of argument, useful in refutation — 
 redudio ad ahsurdum, the dilemma, and the method of 
 the residue — have been considered under the argument 
 from example.
 
 CHAPTER V 
 EVIDENCE 
 
 The Proof. — The word proof, according to Best, 
 "seems properly to mean anything which serves either 
 immediately or mediately to convince the mind of the 
 truth or falsehood of a fact or proposition." 
 
 Evidence and argument are parts of proof. Any 
 fact from which another fact or proposition can be 
 inferred may be called evidence, may prove the mat- 
 ter in question. Any operation of reasoning, by which 
 we proceed from one fact to another fact, or from 
 a number of facts to a generalization, or by syllo- 
 gism through two assumptions to a conclusion may be 
 called an argument, may tend to prove the matter in 
 question. The lawyer, for example, customarily ac- 
 quaints the court both with the evidence and the logical 
 processes by which he would estabhsh or disestablish 
 the matter in issue. On an issue of fact his brief con- 
 tains generally not only a statement of the facts but 
 also an argument based upon them. The sum total 
 thus presented is called by the lawyer the proof of his 
 case. It may appear also that evidence and argument 
 are not only parts of proof but the chief means or in- 
 struments employed in making proof. 
 
 The difference between evidence and argument, easy 
 enough to recognize in practice, is a little more difficult 
 to express accurately in words. Argument is a form 
 of expression of the processes of the mind in arriving 
 
 112
 
 EVIDENCE 113 
 
 at a conclusion from a given premise or datum; while 
 evidence, though it often does furnish or provide this 
 premise or datum, is always outside these mental proc- 
 esses. 
 
 Meaning of Term. — Primarily, the word evidence 
 signifies the state of being "evident, plain, apparent, 
 or notorious," but it also has a causative force as that 
 which renders evident, makes proof. In general, any 
 matter of fact or principle offered to prove a doubtful 
 matter is evidence as to that matter. 
 
 The word is in law used in a restricted sense. "Evi- 
 dence means," says Stephen, "(i) statements made by 
 mtnesses in court under a legal sanction in relation to 
 matters of fact under inquiry; (2) documents produced 
 for the inspection of the court or judge"; these two 
 forms of evidence being called, respectively, oral and 
 documentary. Evidence, says Greenleaf, is "that which 
 is legally submitted to a competent tribunal as a means 
 of ascertaining the truth of any alleged matter of fact 
 under inquiry; means of making proof; the latter, strictly 
 speaking, not being S3aionymous with evidence, but 
 ratJier the effect of it." According to Best, it is "that 
 which generates proof. ... It is any matter of fact, 
 the effect, tendency, or design of which is to produce in 
 the mind a persuasion affirmative or disaffirmative of 
 the existence of some other matter of fact." We shall 
 note that the phrase "matter of fact," which appears 
 in each of these definitions, serves to exclude the use 
 of evidence in connection with a matter of law. A prec- 
 edent cited to establish a legal principle is not, in the 
 legal sense, evidence. It is called an authority. 
 
 The Need of Evidence. — We must, of course, reason 
 in making proof and reason soundly; this is not the
 
 114 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 full requirement. Now, in formal logic, it is not re- 
 garded as necessary that the premises of an argument 
 should be true. They are simply taken for granted. 
 The syllogism denoted thus: All B is C, All A is B, 
 All A is C, may be expanded so as to read: Assuming 
 that All B is C, and assuming that All A is B, it will 
 follow that All A is C. We can entertain, that is to say, 
 the question of the correctness of an argument quite 
 apart from the matter of the truth of its premises. The 
 assumptions made will enable us to see more clearly 
 exactly how we can arrive at a conclusion. We make 
 such assumptions in debating, as we say "for the sake of 
 the argument," when, for instance, we wish to expose 
 a fallacy in our opponent's reasoning. 
 
 But in constructing a proof, it is just as important 
 that the premises or steps of an argument should possess 
 truth or reahty as that the relation between the premises 
 should warrant the conclusion. The legal rule is that 
 nothing, material to the issue, shall be taken for granted 
 and that whoever asserts must prove. Every one who 
 has had any experience in debating, most Ukely has 
 witnessed the wreck that comes of an argument com- 
 posed of statements which are false or unsupported — 
 it amounts to the same thing. Very probably the an- 
 tagonist upset the conclusion in a sentence by merely 
 denying the unwarranted premise. His denial being 
 as good as the original assertion, the reasoning founded 
 on the latter simply went for nothing. Recently, in 
 an intercollegiate debate it was argued that if the speaker 
 of the House of Representatives were deprived of cer- 
 tain specified powers which were said to facilitate legis- 
 lation, the United States would be rid of the evils of 
 overlegislation. The argument was refuted by a denial
 
 EVIDENCE ^ 115 
 
 that the United States are suffering from overlegisla- 
 tion, the evil being arbitrarily assumed and not proved. 
 Or, again, quite probably we have seen an adversary 
 actually prove that the very opposite of a statement, 
 employed in an argument, was the real truth of the 
 matter. Fully armed with the facts, he constructed his 
 counter-proof. Then, the premise in question being 
 false, it was argued that the conclusion was false also, 
 and the whole argument fell with a crash. An argument 
 raised on such premises is a house built upon the sand. 
 
 The debater must be ever mindful of the danger of 
 sheer assertion. The result has no value as e\'idence, 
 no place in any scheme which aims at conviction. For 
 observe that, when free rein is given to the practice, 
 it is not possible to draw any conclusion about the truth 
 of the points in dispute. The whole contest is reduced 
 to a question of logic, and — what is worse — of bad logic 
 usually. For the speaker's effort to defend some rash 
 statement, not infrequently in the heat of controversy, 
 gives rise to personalities and the various kinds of sophis- 
 try — offenses against taste as well as judgment. And 
 so the trouble deepens. 
 
 The habit of assertion, like all bad habits, is not 
 acquired with difficulty; sometunes it comes from care- 
 lessness or laziness, sometunes from prejudice. There- 
 fore we may insist that the debater should make a thor- 
 ough investigation of his case, distinguishing the true 
 from the false, and assessing ideas at proper values. 
 He should not only know what the real facts are, what 
 their proper weight and force are, but for every 
 doubtful declaration be prepared to produce his au- 
 thority, his examples, his statistics, that is, his evidence. 
 In making his investigations, moreover, he should main-
 
 116 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 tain as far as possible an impartial attitude so as not 
 to prejudge his conclusions. Doctor Johnson's failure 
 as a literary critic has been ascribed by Macaulay to 
 prejudice. "The judgments which Johnson passed on 
 books," he says, ''were in his own time regarded with 
 superstitious veneration; and in our time are generally 
 treated with indiscriminate contempt. They are the 
 judgments of a strong but enslaved understanding. 
 The mind of the critic was hedged round by an unin- 
 terrupted fence of prejudices and superstitions. Within 
 his narrow limits he displayed an activity which ought 
 to have enabled hnn to clear the barrier that confined 
 him. How it chanced that a man who reasoned on his 
 premises so ably should assume his premises so foolishly, 
 is one of the greatest mysteries of human nature. The 
 same inconsistency may be observed in the schoolmen 
 of the Middle Ages. Those writers show so much acute- 
 ness and force of mind in arguing on their wretched 
 data, that a modern reader is perpetually at a loss to 
 comprehend how such minds came by such data. Not 
 a flaw in the superstructure of the theory which they 
 are rearing escapes their vigilance. Yet they are blind 
 to the obvious unsoundness of the foundation. It is 
 the same with some eminent lawyers." 
 
 The Need of Assumptions. — We have been speaking 
 of assumptions as if they were altogether unwarrantable, 
 as if assertions must always be supported by evidence. 
 We were dealing, however, only with that class of evi- 
 dence which is derived from experience. You must 
 know that experience supplies to us not only most of 
 the questions of pubHc debate but most of the data 
 upon which we rear our arguments. It is the events 
 which go on about us, that we can see with our eyes
 
 EVIDENCE 117 
 
 and touch vnth our hands — the knowledge of the senses 
 — from which in practice our reasoning perhaps most 
 often starts. But there is another way of discovering 
 truth and hence of deriving our premises. We know 
 some things with certitude without the presence of 
 external evidence. Such knowledge as we get through 
 our intuitions we do not have to prove. They carry 
 their proofs in themselves. We know directly, for in- 
 stance, such things as that we exist, that a straight 
 line is the shortest distance between two points, or that 
 a lie is morally bad. 
 
 Argument is hardly possible without assumptions, 
 for our intuitions offer a basis of proof that is more 
 ultimate than experience. Let us take a single instance 
 in illustration of this. A man is accused of murder. 
 Trustworthy ■v\atnesses testify to his presence in some 
 other place when the deed occurred, and he is therefore 
 discharged. Now it is quite true that the testimony 
 was sufficient to establish the fact of the alibi; but the 
 aHbi warranted the acquittal because we know intui- 
 tively that a person cannot be in two places at one and 
 the same time. This assumption is necessarily involved 
 in the argument. 
 
 Such assumptions may be expressed or merely im- 
 plied. The beginning of the Declaration of Independence 
 was supposed, at the time, to proclaim self-evident 
 truths concerning natural equality. There is, indeed, 
 an advantage in setting out from an a priori truth, for 
 it affords at once a common ground, a common point 
 of sight, for the contrast of truth and error add an il- 
 lumination of differences. In the great orations, you 
 can find illustrations that assume such premises as a 
 universal love of liberty, desire for happiness, and so
 
 118 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 on. Burke called himself a "philosopher in action," 
 meaning the emphasis to fall upon the final word. But 
 his well-known dislike for abstract principles in polit- 
 ical debates did not prevent his use of religious and 
 moral sentiments when enforcing a maxim of civil pru- 
 dence. 
 
 Classes of Evidence 
 
 Direct and Circumstantial. — According as a fact of- 
 fered to produce an immediate or an ultimate conviction 
 concerning the point at issue, the evidence is said to 
 be direct or circumstantial. 
 
 The statement of a policeman that he saw the ac- 
 cused do the shooting charged, the revolver taken from 
 him immediately after the shooting, and the written 
 confession made by him later in his cell is, in each in- 
 stance, direct evidence connecting the accused with 
 the commission of the deed. In the suit of Shylock vs. 
 Antonio ("The Merchant of Venice"), the plain tifi, 
 by the terms of a contract, claims a forfeiture from the 
 defendant for non-payment of a loan. The bond on 
 which Shylock's argument is based is direct evidence. 
 The document, it will be remembered, becomes a 
 boomerang, and makes the coveted forfeiture altogether 
 undesirable to Shylock. Portia, in interpreting the 
 contract, says: 
 
 "This bond doth give thee here no jot of blood; 
 The words expressly are a pound of flesh: 
 Take thou thy bond, take thou thy pound of flesh; 
 But in the cutting if thou dost shed 
 One drop of Christian blood thy bonds and goods 
 Are, by the laws of Venice, confiscate 
 Unto the state of Venice."
 
 EVIDENCE 119 
 
 On the other hand, when the fact is such that another 
 fact is to be inferred from it before a conviction can re- 
 sult, the evidence is circumstantial. If the policeman, 
 in the instance previously cited, had said that he saw 
 the accused in the neighborhood immediately after the 
 shooting and had arrested him merely as a suspicious 
 character, or if the revolver, instead of being taken 
 from the hands of the accused, had been found in the 
 street near by, we could hardly grant that the ac- 
 cused did the shooting without inferring in the first 
 case, for instance, that he was present at the time and 
 place of the occurrence, and in the second, that the 
 revolver was in his possession when the shooting took 
 place. It is expected, in circumstantial evidence, that 
 the court or the jury will go through a process of reason- 
 ing and make inferences from the fact offered to some 
 other fact in dispute. The character Eugene Aram 
 (" Eugene Aram," by Bulwer) sought to free himself from 
 the charge of murder, by arguing in his own defense 
 that his past general good conduct was inconsistent with 
 the commission of the crime of which he was accused. 
 
 "My lord, the tenor of my life contradicts this in- 
 dictment. Who can look back over what is known of 
 my former years and charge me with one vice — one 
 offense? No! I concerted not schemes of fraud — pro- 
 jected no violence — injured no man's property or per- 
 son. My days were honestly laborious — my nights in- 
 tensely studious. This egotism is not presumptuous — 
 is not unreasonable. What man, after a temperate 
 use of life, a series of thinking and acting regularly, 
 without one single deviation from a sober and even tenor 
 of conduct, ever plunged into the depth of crime pre- 
 cipitately and at once? Mankind are not instantaneously
 
 120 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 corrupted. Villainy is always progressive. We decline 
 from right — not suddenly, but step by step." 
 
 Direct and circumstantial evidence may be conclu- 
 sive or presumptive in force; yet, theoretically, the 
 latter is the inferior mode of proof. This may have 
 been supposed from the statement that in the one a 
 conviction follows immediately, and in the other ulti- 
 mately. Since the facts offered as circumstantial evi- 
 dence are more remote from the issue, it is clear that 
 a given portion of circumstantial evidence will have 
 less weight than an equal portion of evidence that is 
 direct. Circumstantial evidence may be regarded simply 
 as a substitute for direct, to be employed to prove what 
 otherwise it might not be possible to prove. Its force 
 will depend on the "number, weight, independence, 
 and consistency" of the various links making up the 
 chain. 
 
 Jury Verdicts Upon Circumstantial Evidence. — There 
 are instances where after a conviction on circumstan- 
 tial evidence the prisoner has confessed his guilt. A 
 good example is the case of Courvoiser, the valet and 
 murderer of Lord Wm. Russell in 1840. Here there 
 was no direct testimony whatever to connect the ac- 
 cused with the crime, and there were circumstances 
 designed by the accused to suggest that it was the work 
 of burglars. It was proved, however, that the accused 
 had an opportunity of committing the crime, that some 
 of the abstracted property had been concealed in his 
 pantry, and that he personally had disposed of other 
 portions of it. The evidence, besides, excluded the 
 reasonable beHef that any other than the prisoner was 
 guilty, and upon these grounds he was convicted and 
 afterward confessed.
 
 EVIDENCE 121 
 
 On the other hand, there have been cases, exceed- 
 ingly rare, in which a miscarriage of justice and the con- 
 viction of the innocent instead of the guilty have re- 
 sulted from a reliance of the jury upon circumstantial 
 evidence. The most remarkable of these that have oc- 
 curred arose out of a burglar}'- committed at the rectory 
 of Edlingham in 1879. Two burglars, one of whom shot 
 at the rector, were seen on the night by the rector and 
 another person. Two men were arrested and tried for 
 the crime at Northumberton Assizes in 1879. Neither 
 the rector nor the other person who had seen the burglars 
 was able to identify the prisoners, and the defense was 
 that the case for the prosecution was entirely one of 
 mistaken identity. But a chisel found in the room where 
 the crime was committed was traced to the possession 
 of the prisoners; a piece of newspaper picked up in the 
 same room was found to correspond with a piece in the 
 coat of one of the prisoners, and footmarks found near 
 the scene of the crime corresponded with those of the 
 prisoners. 
 
 The jury, on this evidence, found them guilty, and 
 they were sentenced to penal servitude for life. They 
 served in the convict settlement at Portsmouth for nine 
 years, when, in 1888, the true burglars, two men other 
 than those that had been convicted, confessed to the 
 crime. Inquiries were made by the authorities, with the 
 result that the men who had been convicted on the 
 evidence of the chisel, the newspaper, and the footmarks 
 were set at liberty. 
 
 Personal, Real, and Documentary. — There are three 
 sources of evidence: persons, things, and documents. 
 On this basis. Best has classified legal evidence as per- 
 sonal, real, and documentary. In judicial matters the
 
 122 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 most useful division of evidence is undoubtedly that 
 into direct and circumstantial; but an examination 
 of the second classification may serve to clear up some 
 doubtful matters. 
 
 The evidence of witnesses — persons who inform the 
 tribunal respecting facts — is (i) personal evidence. Such 
 evidence in general must concern matters of knowledge 
 rather than opinion or hearsay. Expert witnesses, how- 
 ever, are allowed to give their opinions upon facts of 
 which they have no personal knowledge. They are 
 persons specially skilled in the matters upon which 
 they testify. 
 
 It is extremely difficult for the ordinary witness to 
 separate opinion from knowledge. He is, indeed, a very 
 good witness who when testifying as to what he saw 
 or heard is able to eliminate his personal views and in- 
 ferences. There are tests for the credibility of the ordi- 
 nary witness, such as his veracity, interest, physical 
 soundness, and so on, but nowadays the average person 
 is deemed competent to give testimony in the courts. 
 
 It should not be overlooked that the degree of skill, 
 reputation, or experience possessed by expert witnesses 
 is a matter of considerable importance; for where ex- 
 pert witnesses are employed by both sides, they, as a 
 matter of course, give conflicting testimony, in which 
 case their "expertness" may be called in question. 
 
 Expert testimony of an interesting scientific char- 
 acter was brought out in the trial of the person accused 
 of poisoning by arsenic a certain Mary Stannard. Now, 
 the accused admitted having bought an ounce of arsenic 
 from a drug-store on the day the girl died, but stated 
 he had deposited it in his barn, where it could be found 
 intact. The State claimed that this arsenic was pur-
 
 EVIDENCE 123 
 
 chased and placed In the barn subsequent to the arrest, 
 and hence could not have been that bought of the drug- 
 gist by the accused on the day of the girl's death. 
 Professor Edward S. Dana, of Yale University, was 
 called in as expert witness for the State. He procured 
 a sample of arsenic from the druggist's jar^ and also a 
 sample of that found in the barn, and endeavored to 
 determine whether or not they could have come from the 
 same source. By means of a microscope he noticed (i) 
 certain differences in the constituent parts of the two 
 samples, e. g., in the size and lustre of crystals, lumps, 
 dust, etc. He then examined ninety- two samples of 
 arsenic representing a number of different sources and 
 found (2) that all samples from the same source showed 
 uniformity in composition. Hence he inferred that (3) 
 the drug-store and barn samples could not have come 
 from the same source, and hence that the barn sample 
 could not have been taken from the druggist's jar. 
 
 From this illustration it is clear that expert testi- 
 mony is quite different from the testimony of the ordi- 
 nary witness. If it had happened that some one had 
 actually witnessed the purchase of the barn arsenic at 
 another place, this person might have testified as an 
 ordinary witness to such a fact. In the case in question, 
 however, Professor Dana merely expressed an opinion 
 to the effect that the barn sample could not have been 
 taken from the druggist's jar. This opinion was a con- 
 clusion drawn by an expert after a careful investigation 
 of facts. To observe and explain these facts, moreover, 
 required skill of a very special character. 
 
 The term (2) real evidence explains itself (from res, 
 a thing). This division of evidence into personal and 
 » "Commercial Arsenic," Edward S, Dana,
 
 124 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 real, it may be observed, is analogous to the usual legal 
 classification of property (personal and real). Real 
 evidence means "all evidence of which any object be- 
 longing to the class of things is the source; persons also 
 being included in respect of such properties as belong 
 to them in common with things." 
 
 The use of things in effecting proof is of so common 
 an occurrence as to make illustration almost superfluous. 
 The signals of the weather bureau may be mentioned 
 as indicating usually the kind of weather predicted for 
 the day following, or the sight of flags at half-mast the 
 death of a prominent person. Moreover, it is the basis 
 of business transactions, where inspection precedes 
 the purchase of goods, the goods being real evidence 
 as to their character and worth. We may refer, also, 
 to the daggers in "Macbeth," the rent in Csesar's cloak 
 in "Julius Caesar," the handkerchief in "Othello," 
 and, indeed, if you like, the thumb-prints in "Pudd'n- 
 head Wilson." In Caine's "Shadow of a Crime," when 
 the arm of the witness Lawson was examined in court 
 and disclosed "three clear marks of an iron-brand," 
 the marks were real evidence showing that he had been 
 branded. 
 
 In criminal practice, real evidence has usually only 
 a probable or presumptive force, and appears in con- 
 nection with circumstantial evidence. The weapon 
 with which an alleged murder was committed; in a 
 case of robbery, the marks of a key with which the robber 
 struck the prosecution witness, corresponding to the 
 key found in the robber's possession; a part of a knife- 
 blade left sticking in the window-frame through which 
 a burglar had entered, corresponding to the remnant 
 found in the burglar's pocket, are instances of circum-
 
 EVIDENCE 125 
 
 stantial real evidence. In such cases the force of the 
 evidence will depend very largely on the speaker's in- 
 sight and powers of interpretation. It should be said, 
 however, that, in criminal cases of this sort, the lawyer 
 frequently employs the services of a detective, whose 
 special duty is to give assistance in the discovery and 
 explanation of details. 
 
 In connection with the legal rule that only ''the best 
 evidence of which the case in its nature is susceptible " 
 is to be admitted into a court of law, (3) documentary 
 evidence has been divided into primary and secondary. 
 Any document may be said to be "primary evidence of 
 its own contents," while "the term secondary e\'idence 
 is used to designate any derivative proof of them, such 
 as memorials, copies, abstracts, recollections of persons 
 who have read them, etc." In general, secondary evi- 
 dence is not receivable in a court of law until it is shown 
 to be the best evidence that can be procured under the 
 circumstances. Since the debater usually procures his 
 evidence from a written or documentary source, he will 
 find it worth while to remember both the legal rule about 
 the best evidence and the legal distinction between 
 primary and secondary evidence. But this is hardly 
 as important for the debater as for the lawyer; for 
 the secondary e\ddence of the former, it is not in- 
 frequently sufficient. But he wdll sometimes find it 
 of advantage to be able to criticise an opponent for 
 faiHng to refer to original evidence which it were reason- 
 ably expected he would cite. Such criticism will be 
 especially effective if he is able to compare "the sub- 
 stitutionary evidence" employed by his opponent with 
 the more original evidence, and to disclose some error 
 in the former. At all events, the careful investigator
 
 126 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 should be ever ready to go behind derivative evidence 
 and study the source or sources from which it was de- 
 rived. 
 
 The Law of Evidence. — What is known in the legal 
 text-books as the law of evidence, consists of a body 
 of rules more or less arbitrary, but as binding on courts, 
 juries, and witnesses as the rest of the common and stat- 
 ute law of the land. These rules are under the control of 
 the legislature except in cases of conflict with constitu- 
 tional law. They prescribe such things as, that after 
 a seven years' absence without having been heard from 
 a man shall be presumed to be dead; that interest may 
 render a witness incompetent; certain fixed periods of 
 time when a debt is presumed to have been paid or satis- 
 faction to have been received. A great many of these 
 rules arei so special, and embedded in the subject-matter 
 of the law, that they are of little service outside of the 
 courts or in connection with issues not of a legal char- 
 acter. 
 
 The rules which prevail as to the production of evi- 
 dence in the courts have been reduced to the following 
 points: 
 
 1. Certain matters may be judicially taken notice of with- 
 
 out proof; e. g., facts of general knowledge. 
 
 2. Evidence must correspond with the allegations in the 
 
 pleadings and be confined to the point at issue. 
 
 3. Only the substance of the issue need be proved; that 
 
 is, minor and unimportant issues need not be established 
 as stated; e. g., the time or place when an event oc- 
 curred. 
 
 4. The burden of proof is with him who holds the affirma- 
 
 tive; e. g., he who makes an allegation which is dis- 
 puted so as to be at issue must establish it by evi- 
 dence.
 
 EVIDENCE 127 
 
 $. The best evidence must be produced of which the nature 
 of the case admits; e. g., if primary evidence is acces- 
 sible, it must be produced. 
 
 6. Hearsay evidence is in general inadmissible. 
 
 7. Testimony should, in general, concern matters of knowl- 
 
 edge as distinguished from opinion. Exception is made 
 in the case of an expert or one skilled in a particular 
 trade, art, or profession; e. g., superintendent of an in- 
 sane asylum as to matters connected with the subject 
 of insanity. 
 
 8. Certain evidence otherwise admissible is excluded on 
 
 grounds of public policy; e. g., confidential communica- 
 tions between lawyer and client. 
 
 9. In certain cases, principally by statute law, written evi- 
 
 dence must be resorted to rather than oral. 
 10. Oral contemporaneous evidence is not admissible to vary 
 or contradict the terms of a written contract. 
 
 In a trial with or without a jury, it rests with the 
 judge to determine whether the evidence is admissible 
 under these rules. 
 
 Examining Testimony 
 
 Consistency — the One Great Test of Evidence. — 
 
 The one great test of evidence is its consistency, ex- 
 ternal and internal. The facts presented should not 
 be self-contradictory. They should, moreover, be con- 
 sistent with the general knowledge we possess, derived 
 from our intuitions and experience. They should be 
 consistent also with the particular information derived 
 from other testimonies and circumstances in the case. 
 
 I, Internal Consistency. — Is the testimony consistent 
 internally — that is, is it consistent within itself? Are 
 all the statements made by the witness reconcilable 
 with one another? By means of cross-examination if 
 the witness is present, or by close analysis of his testi-
 
 128 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 mony if written, errors may be detected as follows: 
 (i) Incidental or undesigned testimony which a witness 
 gives without reaHzing its value in the case; (2) hostile 
 testimony or the frank admission of some fact opposed 
 to the witness's position, and (3) negative testimony or 
 "the failure of a witness to mention a fact so striking 
 that he must have noticed it, had it occurred," ^ or a 
 failure to remember such fact. The latter is sometimes 
 called testimony from silence. 
 
 Illustrations of this can be found in Erskine's speech 
 in behalf of Hardy; for example, his remarks on the 
 testimony of Lynam. 
 
 2, External Consistency. — Is the testimony consistent 
 with our (i) general knowledge, derived from our intui- 
 tions and experience? Does it seem probable when com- 
 pared with what we already know about such things? 
 Statements which partake of the marvellous or are in- 
 compatible with ordinary experience are received with 
 suspicion. Robert Burton in his "Anatomy of Melan- 
 choly" says: "The air is not so full of flies in summer 
 as it is at all times of invisible devils; this Paracelsus 
 stiffly affirms." If we should regard this as testimony 
 offered in good faith, we should reject it on account of 
 its external inconsistency. 
 
 This principle is so well recognized in all rules of 
 jurisprudence that all courts of law and equity are said 
 to "take judicial notice" of certain facts the existence 
 or truth of which is so well-known and established as 
 to be considered facts of general and every-day knowl- 
 edge. For example, "matters which must have hap- 
 pened according to the ordinary course of nature," as 
 the time of sunrise or sunset on a certain day and the 
 * "Practical Rhetoric," Genung.
 
 EVIDENCE 129 
 
 succession of the seasons. Or again, "matters of such 
 general and public notoriety that every one may fairly 
 be presumed to be acquainted with them," as the ordi- 
 nary duration of human Hfe, the usual length of time 
 for a voyage across the Atlantic, the usual time to run 
 trains between large cities/ etc. 
 
 And (2) is the testimony in question consistent with 
 our particular information, derived from other testi- 
 monies and circumstances in the case? So far as our 
 investigation has gone, Richard Roe — to be concrete — 
 has testified, let us say, in language which is straight- 
 forward and uncontradictory, and his testimony seems 
 probable on the face of it. But suppose there is an- 
 other witness, John Doe, to the same circumstances. 
 The testimony of these witnesses, then, will have to 
 be compared. If we should find that their testimony 
 is in substantial accord, our belief in the facts alleged 
 by Roe would be strengthened. And it would doubtless 
 be strengthened still more if it is apparent that there 
 had been no collusion between the witnesses. Hence, 
 when there is more than one witness and their testi- 
 mony is substantially the same, the force of the proof 
 will depend not only on consistency (internal consistency, 
 general external consistency, and the interconsistency 
 of the several testimonies), but also in the number of 
 testimonies and their independence. This mode of proof 
 is sometimes called corroborative testimony. 
 
 If, on the other hand, we should find that Doe's testi- 
 mony contradicted that given by Roe, we should in all 
 probability look for other circumstances in the case, 
 such as the characters of the two witnesses and the 
 conditions under which the testimonies were given. If 
 ' Stephen's "Digest of the Law of Evidence."
 
 130 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 it is established that Doe was prejudiced or incompetent 
 through intellectual, physical, or moral reasons, or that 
 his testimony is given under compulsion, we should feel 
 justified in rejecting his testimony. If the opposite 
 is shown of Roe, our belief in his testimony would be 
 still further strengthened. 
 
 When a mass of conflicting testimony is presented, 
 in determining the correct value to be given to any par- 
 ticular source of evidence, all these tests as to truth 
 and probabihty are necessary. The same may be said 
 of course in regard to the final conclusion to be arrived 
 at after considering all the testimony and attributing 
 to each its proper force and weight. 
 
 This classification, it should be remembered, is only 
 a test for arri\dng at the truth or probability of testi- 
 mony. Before, however, a conclusion can be arrived 
 at, the weight and force of the testimony presented 
 must be determined. Any attempt to classify the force 
 of testimony and the conclusion to be drawn therefrom 
 must necessarily fall short of absolute completeness. The 
 conclusion arrived at from conflicting testimony depends 
 so much on that illusive factor which, for lack of a better 
 name, we call "the personal equation," that it is im- 
 possible to lay down any general rule as to the probable 
 force and weight of evidence; for it can readily be con- 
 ceived that certain facts and circumstances may be 
 considered of great importance by some persons exercis- 
 ing judicial functions, which by others acting in the 
 same capacity would be regarded as of little weight 
 and consequence. This field is as varied as the minds 
 and temperaments of men. 
 
 Use of Evidence Outside the Courts. — From what 
 has been said, it appears that the law of evidence deals
 
 EVIDENCE 131 
 
 with rules governing the production of testimony in 
 courts. These rules have been established for the sake 
 of "faciHty in disposing of complicated questions or 
 on grounds of public pohcy." In non- judicial tribunals, 
 however, there are, strictly speaking, no rules governing 
 the admissibility of evidence. The judges or audience 
 have no actual power to exclude or admit evidence, but 
 must base their decision on the evidence produced, which 
 may fall within the legal rules or without them. The 
 speakers must decide for themselves what facts should 
 be proved and what sort of evidence should be employed. 
 The rules wliich apply in a debating contest are the 
 unformulated rules of universal evidence, the employ- 
 ment of which in particular cases rests in the judgment 
 of the debaters themselves. 
 
 In regard to the sort of evidence employable in non- 
 judicial tribunals, three important exceptions to the 
 legal rules should be noted: (i) Immaterial collateral 
 evidence; (2) hearsay or second-hand evidence; (3) 
 opinions not emanating from experts. The ordinary 
 debater employs such evidence, however, not upon the 
 ground that it is strong but merely that it may be taken 
 for what it is worth. Such evidence is rarely conclusive; 
 indeed, the presumption which it establishes is usually 
 very slight. 
 
 In manner of proof, many differences between the 
 legal and ordinary procedure appear. The most striking 
 of these, perhaps, arises in connection with witnesses. 
 Witnesses may be compelled by law to attend court 
 and give their testimonies in person. In other tribunals 
 (where such practice would be inconvenient and in- 
 capable of enforcement, as before deliberative bodies 
 generally), the speaker usually presents the evidence.
 
 132 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 It is, perhaps, much as if the lawyer should declare the 
 facts to the jury without the previous appearance of 
 witnesses. In this view, therefore, the debater can be 
 regarded as his own witness giving hearsay or second- 
 hand testimony — reported evidence. 
 
 The Debater's Chief Source of Evidence — Author- 
 ity. — What is usually known as the argument from au- 
 thority is "based upon the statements of others con- 
 cerning matters of opinion which they have reached 
 by rational processes and is to be distinguished from 
 testimony which consists of the statements of others 
 concerning matters of fact." This distinction between 
 authority and testimony does not hold literally or with 
 any degree of exactness for arguments in non-judicial 
 tribunals. The debater derives not only opinions but 
 facts from authorities. He can, of course, derive the 
 latter from the testimony of witnesses, but he is much 
 more likely to obtain it from scientific treatises or other 
 works of an authoritative character. The debater uses 
 the term authority to apply both to the author and the 
 work itself. 
 
 Two Classes of Authority. — Authorities may be of 
 two kinds: (i) That based on our confidence in the 
 knowledge of the authority quoted, and (2) that based 
 on our confidence in his judgment. 
 
 (i) Any declaration as to facts derived from books 
 or documents may, if disputed, need verification by com- 
 paring it with more original sources. Such comparison 
 may be made either with original written evidence or 
 with original testimonies given when the deed, event, 
 or course of action took place. If unnecessary issues 
 of this sort are to be avoided, the source quoted in the 
 first place should be trustworthy. The question is
 
 EVIDENCE 133 
 
 whether or not the State of Wisconsin has a referendum 
 in the particular case of banks. Now if the debater 
 should come across the following in Bryce's "American 
 Commonwealth" (Vol. I, p. 452) — "Wisconsin refers 
 it to the voters to decide whether or no banks shall be 
 chartered" — he would probably consider the question 
 settled. He would hardly seek for original written evi- 
 dence — the original draft of Section 5, Art. XI, Consti- 
 tution of 1843 — 01" ^or the testimonies of those legis- 
 lators who had the matter under consideration. He is 
 content to decide the point affirmatively upon the au- 
 thority of one whose knowledge in such matters can 
 be trusted. Thus we assert that Wordsworth was born 
 in 1770, on the authority of Knight's "Life of Words- 
 worth"; that Burke died in 1797, on the authority of 
 Morley's "Edmund Burke"; that Washington crossed 
 the Delaware, on the authority of Bancroft's "History 
 of the United States"; or that the British were at one 
 time in possession of Havana, on the authority of John- 
 son 's "Universal Cyclopedia." These works are au- 
 thorities in the special matters upon which they are 
 quoted; and while our acceptance of their statements 
 need not go so far as to imply confidence in the reason- 
 ing or judgment of their authors, it would necessarily 
 express confidence in their knowledge of those particular 
 matters upon which they were cited. 
 
 (2) Authority, which has weight because of our con- 
 fidence in the judgment of the person quoted, concerns 
 matters of opinion — conclusions from facts, generaliza- 
 tions, truths. The issue of a debate is a poUcy of ex- 
 pansion versus a policy of isolation for the United States. 
 Washington's celebrated warning in the Farewell Ad- 
 dress and parts of Monroe's famous message to Con-
 
 134 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 gress in 182 1 are quoted; such extracts would concern 
 ''matters of opinion" which Washington and Monroe 
 respectively had reached by rational processes. The 
 argument from authority is highly valuable in ascer- 
 taining the causes of known effects. For example, is 
 it advisable to amend our lawr of immigration? Now 
 it is admitted by the parties to the dispute that there 
 has been recently an increase of immigration from 
 southern Europe and a decrease from northern. Is this 
 admitted change due to our immigration laws or to other 
 causes? Obviously, the debater on either side would find 
 it to his advantage if he could support his position by 
 the opinion of experts on immigration. 
 
 The general of an army, it may be supposed, would 
 be more of an authority on the management of a cam- 
 paign than a private in his service. A newspaper ad- 
 vertisement containing letters from unknown persons 
 as to the merits of a cure for Uver trouble would have 
 little weight against the opinion of a good physician. 
 But an authority in one department may not be an au- 
 thority in another. The President of the United States 
 would be competent to speak on most questions of state- 
 craft but not necessarily in regard to theatrical matters 
 as would Henry Irving. Even in such allied depart- 
 ments as chemistry and medicine an eminent chemist 
 might not be an authority on medical practice. Nor 
 could an ocuhst necessarily speak authoritatively upon 
 the throat. 
 
 Moreover, when the opinion cited is that of a specialist 
 in the department within which the subject Hes, it is 
 important to know his standing and reputation. In 
 economic matters would you follow Henry George or 
 John Stuart Mill? In art would you prefer Ruskin to
 
 EVIDENCE 135 
 
 Philip Gilbert Hamerton? In natural history would you 
 follow Pliny or Mandeville rather than Darwin or Hux- 
 ley? There are degrees of standing among specialists. 
 
 Examining Evidence from Authority 
 
 It has been previously shown that the debater's 
 statements which come from others are taken, as a rule, 
 not from the testimony of eye-witnesses but from the 
 testimony of authorities. The classification of tests to 
 be applied in examining evidence from authority is, in 
 general, the same as in examining ordinary testimony. 
 The one great test of evidence is consistency: (i) Is the 
 evidence cited consistent internally? That is to say, 
 are there incidental, undesigned admissions — are there 
 frank admissions, open concessions — and are there miss- 
 ing statements of fact so striking as to throw doubt 
 upon those made? (2) Is the evidence cited consistent 
 externally with our general knowledge derived through 
 our intuitions and experience? Extraordinary state- 
 ments, even if they emanate from an authority, may be 
 examined by this test. And (3) Is the evidence con- 
 sistent externally with our particular information ob- 
 tainable from other authorities and circumstances in 
 the case? When a number of authorities agree in stating 
 substantially the same fact or opinion, we have what 
 is called corroborative testimony from authority. It 
 is important, moreover, that such statements should 
 possess independence; in the case of facts, that they 
 should not have come originally from the same source; 
 in the case of opinions, that they should have been sepa- 
 rately determined. Here, as in ordinary testimony, 
 number and independence may have to be considered 
 before a final conclusion can be arrived at.
 
 136 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 If, however, there are several authorities and their 
 testimonies disagree, we should look for other circum- 
 stances in the case which would throw hght on the com- 
 petence of the authorities. If the statements under 
 examination can be considered as concerning a matter 
 of knowledge (as, for example, the exact time of the de- 
 livery of Webster's speech in reply to Hayne), a de- 
 cision may be possible after a determination of the stand- 
 ing of the authorities in question — their scholarship, 
 methods of investigation, and opportunities for research. 
 If, on the other hand, the statements undergoing ex- 
 amination concern a matter of opinion (as, for example, 
 Webster's usual habits of preparation for a speech), 
 it is necessary to determine not only the knowledge of 
 the several authorities, but also their relative compe- 
 tence to draw conclusions from circumstances ascer- 
 tained. Are the authorities cited competent through 
 intellectual power, training, and experience to ascertain 
 circumstances correctly and to have trustworthy opinions 
 upon them? And are they unprejudiced by personal or 
 professional bias? 
 
 A comparison of the several testimonies and a de- 
 termination of the relative competence of the authori- 
 ties, if their statements were made from personal ob- 
 servation, may be sufficient to warrant a final decision, 
 after applying the other tests of consistency, number, 
 and independence. And, indeed, in case the conflicting 
 statements are of a secondary character, a decision 
 may be reached which is practically sulSicient. But 
 the scientific or scholarly investigator will look at once 
 at the sources of the authorities, the primary evidence 
 (if such be available) upon which the statements were 
 based. For example, Marsh in his "Webster and His
 
 EVIDENCE 137 
 
 Contemporaries" assumes that Webster's great speech 
 was deUvered on a single day, Tuesday, January the 
 twenty-sixth, eighteen hundred and thirty; while Everett 
 in his "Life" tells us that its deUvery occupied parts of 
 two days; namely, the twenty-sixth and twenty-seventh. 
 The relative competency of these conflicting authori- 
 ties, if determined, would not settle the matter abso- 
 lutely. At all events, the historical investigator would 
 seek at once for such evidence as Gales [and Sea ton's 
 "Reports" or Benton's "Debates of Congress." Such 
 an investigation, if made, will verify Everett's state- 
 ment. In examining primary evidence the following 
 questions are of great importance: (i) Is the document 
 authenticated? And (2) Was it made by a person ful- 
 filling the requirements of an expert? The Gales and 
 Seaton "Reports," just mentioned, fulfil these tests; 
 so, for example, does Thucydides' "History of the Pelo- 
 ponnesian War." The story of William Tell's marks- 
 manship, on the other hand, rests upon a documentary 
 basis which cannot be authenticated. It is, of course, 
 neither a contradictory nor an impossible story, but is 
 externally inconsistent with certain particular facts 
 established in regard to it. Substantially the same story 
 is related of other heroes; for example, Toko and Egill, 
 in manuscripts equally trustworthy.^ The second-hand 
 testimony of an authority need not, it may be supposed, 
 depend upon documents. It may indeed sometimes 
 depend upon more remote testimonies given when the 
 deed, event, or course of action took place. When such 
 occurs, the test previously given for examining testi- 
 mony may need to be appHed. But, as a matter of 
 fact, it should not be too strongly emphasized that 
 'Vide Paul's "Grundriss der germanischen Philologie," II, 62.
 
 138 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 documents form the almost exclusive IdesIs of historic 
 proofs. 
 
 The historian works with documents. Documents are the 
 traces which have been left by the thoughts and actions of men 
 of former times. Of these thoughts and actions, however, very- 
 few leave any visible traces, and these traces, when there are 
 any, are seldom durable; an accident is enough to efface them. 
 Now every thought and every action that has left no visible 
 traces, or none but what have since disappeared, is lost for his- 
 tory; is as though it had never been. For want of documents 
 the history of immense periods in the past of humanity is destined 
 to remain forever unknown. For there is no substitute for docu- 
 ments; no documents, no history.^ 
 
 In a word, in determining the particular external 
 consistency of testimony from authority, the other cir- 
 cimistances to be considered may concern two things: 
 the competency of an authority and the original source. 
 And in determining the weight of any particular testi- 
 mony and circumstance, all the tests as to truth and 
 probability are necessary. This is equally true of the 
 final conclusion arrived at after comparing all the testi- 
 monies and circumstances in the case, and attributing 
 to each portion of evidence its proper force and weight. 
 What has been said, moreover, of the personal equation 
 as rendering impossible a complete general classification 
 of the force of ordinary testimony is true of every species 
 of evidence. 
 
 The following classification of authorities, together 
 with the questions which may be asked in examining a 
 particular class of authority, should be useful. 
 
 I. Authoritative statements of a secondary character based 
 on documents. 
 
 ^"Introduction to the Study of History"; Langlois and Seignobos.
 
 EVIDENCE 139 
 
 A. Competency. 
 
 1. In a matter of knowledge: Is the authority com- 
 
 petent through general ability, training, and ex- 
 perience to ascertain circumstances and facts 
 correctly ? 
 In a matter oi judgment : Is he competent through 
 general ability, training, and experience to ascer- 
 tain circumstances and facts correctly, and to 
 base trustworthy opinions upon them? 
 
 2. Is he unprejudiced? 
 
 B. Primary source. 
 
 1. Is the document authenticated? 
 
 2. Was it made by a person competent to know and 
 
 to judge? Was he unprejudiced ? 
 II. Authoritative statements of a second-hand character 
 based on ordinary testimony, 
 
 A. Competency. 
 
 (Same as the preceding.) 
 
 B. Source, 
 
 Do the testimonies fulfil the tests given for ordinary 
 testimony ? 
 
 III. A document — primary evidence. 
 
 1. Is the document authenticated? 
 
 2. Was it made by a person competent to know and 
 
 to judge ? Was he unprejudiced ? 
 
 IV. A person — authoritative statements based on personal ob- 
 
 servation. (Expert testimony.) 
 In a matter of knowledge and judgment; is he competent? 
 (Same test of competency as in I., A.) 
 
 Of these classes, I and II are the most usual sources 
 of evidence employed in debating; III and IV are the 
 best evidence theoretically considered; but, as has been 
 shown, I and II may under certain circumstances be as 
 good as III, may be sufficient for practical purposes. 
 
 Rules for the Interpretation of Documents. — i. The 
 presumption is always in favor of the plain, obvious 
 meaning of the language.
 
 140 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 2. In all cases of uncertainty and ambiguity, that 
 interpretation should be adopted which other circum- 
 stances indicate as the intention of those who had the 
 authority to fix the phraseology. 
 
 3. A document is its own best interpreter. Its ob- 
 scure passages are to be constructed in harmony with 
 those whose meaning is plain. 
 
 i 4. The design the author had in view will aid in de- 
 termining what his intention was in using his words. 
 
 5. The spirit and temper of the author must be con- 
 sidered. 
 
 6. The daily language of an author must be under- 
 stood to understand his writings. 
 
 7. Documents are to be interpreted in harmony with 
 the surroundings of their authors.^ 
 
 Suggestions for Reporting Evidence. — The debater 
 knows that his opponent or the judges will generally 
 be aware of the truth concerning important matters 
 and discover inaccuracies. Hence, fear of detection by 
 the judges and exposure by an opponent with the con- 
 sequent damage to the speaker's reputation and his 
 side are most important checks upon error. The chief 
 check, of course, is the debater's own responsibility as 
 respects the truth. 
 
 If he is to get the most out of his evidence, he must 
 possess such an intimate acquaintance with it and the 
 source from which it comes that he can during a contest 
 recall his knowledge at a moment's notice. Now an 
 opponent may question either the accuracy of a state- 
 ment, the source from which it was taken, or the au- 
 thoritative character of that source. Hence, in prepar- 
 ing for a contest, the debater should remember exactly 
 
 ^ Hay's "Every-Day Reasoning," pp. 155 et seq.
 
 EVIDENCE 141 
 
 what his authority said and where it was said, and why 
 it or he may be considered as an authority. He should 
 be prepared (i) to quote verbatim, (2) to cite the au- 
 thority quoted, and (3) to describe its or his character. 
 (i) Verbatim Quotation. — In reporting the words of 
 others for the purpose of e^ddence, the debater should 
 always quote substantially or word for word. This 
 means practically that he should always take pains to 
 understand and to repeat exactly what was said. It 
 is not to be supposed that a speaker would intentionally 
 misquote, but, through carelessness in the examination 
 of the authority or an unrestrained partiaUty for his 
 own side, misrepresentation may be the result. Hence 
 the value of verbatim over substantial quotation. Burke, 
 laborious in everything, was exceedingly particular, per- 
 haps tediously so, in the matter of quotation whether 
 for ornament or evidence. The great orators and states- 
 men through this practice have usually developed won- 
 derful memories. Such was Webster's habit in this 
 respect that it has been said of him: "Anything once 
 well taken into his mind was never afterward absolutely 
 forgotten." William Pinkney's memory was "a bed 
 of steel." And what a triumph did the latter 's memory 
 score for him in the supreme court! On one occasion 
 Pinkney happened to remark that he beheved such an 
 author gave such an opinion, quoting it substantially; 
 whereupon the counsel on the other side interrupted 
 him with a flat denial. "Pinkney turned toward him 
 with the greatest apparent fury. 'Hand me the book,' 
 said he. 'Never in my not short juridical life have I 
 attempted to mislead the court, and certainly I would 
 not attempt it with a court of such wisdom and lore 
 as this; if I did, I should be sure of being exposed, and
 
 142 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 I hope I think too much of my reputation for such an 
 artifice.' Then again turning to the startled adversary, 
 'Pass me the book,' he exclaimed, 'and now before I 
 open it, I shall tell your honor the page, and the part 
 of the page where this authority is stated, and let me 
 begin by repeating it to your honors.' He then opened 
 the book and pointed to the very page he had indicated 
 and the authority was found to correspond word for word 
 with what he had stated." 
 
 (2) Citation of Authority. — Of course the debater 
 must be prepared to cite authorities upon disputed 
 points. He may be called upon in actual debate, it 
 should be remembered, to do so at any time and at a 
 moment's notice. He may, like Pinkney, moreover, 
 have to do it with considerable warmth and minuteness. 
 Hence, in preparing his case, for every quoted statement 
 he should always make a point of remembering not only 
 what was said, but the work and the place in the work 
 from which the statement was taken. The experienced 
 debater knows that facts which seem incontrovertible 
 when he is making up his case will in some way during 
 an argument occasionally become an issue. In connec- 
 tion with apparently indisputable facts, Burke frequent- 
 ly referred in his speech upon Conciliation to the jour- 
 nals of the House, giving volume, month, and year. A 
 constant reference to authority, it should be said, has 
 a good effect upon the judges, by increasing their con- 
 fidence in the speaker. 
 
 (3) Description of the Authority. — When Burke was 
 discussing the commerce with America, in his speech 
 on Concihation, he stood with two accounts in his hand: 
 one, a comparative statement of the export trade of 
 England to its colonies as it stood in the year 1704 and
 
 EVIDENCE 143 
 
 as it stood in the year 1772; the other, a statement of 
 the export trade of this country to its colonies alone, 
 as it stood in 1772, compared with the whole trade of 
 England to all parts of the world (the colonies excluded) 
 in the year 1704. He then adds: "They are from good 
 vouchers; the latter period from the accounts on your 
 table, the earher from an original manuscript of Dave- 
 nant, who first estabhshed the inspector-general 's office, 
 which has been ever since his time so abundant a source 
 of parliamentary information." 
 
 The Reasonableness of an Opinion. — It is not to be 
 overlooked that in matters of opinion the force or weight 
 of a cited authority rests primarily on the reasonableness 
 or convincingness of an opinion, and only secondarily on 
 the general character or reputation of the one who ex- 
 pressed it. The debater should be especially cautioned 
 against quoting a man loosely as an authority on his 
 side of a question without stating the authority 's expressed 
 reasons for the position ascribed to him. The following 
 (from the "Principles of Rhetoric," by A. S. Hill, p. 13) 
 will serve to illustrate the correct use of another's 
 opinion: 
 
 The real question is, Are the United States — so far as language 
 is concerned — still provinces of England, or do they constitute 
 a nation? 
 
 The true doctrine appears to be that expressed by the late 
 Edward A. Freeman, whose opinion on this point is valuable 
 because he was an Englishman of Englishmen. After discuss- 
 ing several cases in which usage differs in the two countries, 
 Mr. Freeman goes on to say: "One way is for the most part 
 as good as the other; let each side of the ocean stick to its own 
 way, if only to keep up those little picturesque differences which 
 are really a gain when the substance is essentially the same. 
 This same line of thought might be carried out in a crowd of
 
 144 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 phrases, old and new, in which British and American usage 
 differs, but in which neither usage can be said to be in itself 
 better or worse than the other. Each usage is the better in 
 the land in which it has grown up of itself. A good British writer 
 and a good American writer will write in the same language 
 and the same dialect; but it is well that each should keep to 
 those little peculiarities of established and reasonable local usage 
 which will show on which side of the ocean he writes." * 
 
 But to say that the force of argument from author- 
 ity rests prunarily on the reasonableness or convincing- 
 ness of an opinion, and secondarily on the character or 
 reputation of the authority quoted, is not to state all 
 of the truth. An ipse dixit, for instance, will sometimes 
 be conclusive through its appeal to authority qua au- 
 thority, to habit, or to imitation. 
 
 The Danger of Partial Quotation. — In reporting evi- 
 dence, the debater should be especially warned against 
 the danger of partial quotation. It usually happens, 
 for instance, that an authority may be loosely "quoted 
 on both sides," as it is called. This is particularly true 
 of pubHc questions which are new, but there is no excuse 
 whatever for the deliberate attempt sometimes made 
 by debating teams to "steal" an opponent's author- 
 ities for one's own side. Thus, it is both improper and 
 hazardous for a debater to use what is really a quahfying 
 remark or a remark made in some special or minor part 
 of the discussion as if it really represented the author- 
 ity's true position. Pubhc men have sometunes been 
 flagrantly misrepresented in this way; and the honest 
 debater must be ever on his guard against such trickery 
 or carelessness, and be prepared to supply when neces- 
 sary the full and complete statements of the authority 
 
 1 Longman'' s Magazine, November, 1882, p. 90.
 
 EVIDENCE 145 
 
 in question and to supply them so effectively as to secure 
 his opponent's downfall. Whether the cause of the 
 misrepresentation be studied or accidental, certainly a 
 debater in his preparation should be so thorough and 
 exact that his own authorities caimot be improperly 
 appropriated by an opponent without his being able to 
 expose by specific citation the misrepresentation. 
 
 The Card System. — The importance of system in 
 note- taking when gathering e\adence for a debate can 
 hardly be overestimated. In the thorough preparation 
 demanded in our intercollegiate debates, hundreds of 
 volumes, magazines, or periodicals must frequently be 
 examined, sifted, and classified. With such a mass of 
 material, debaters have, almost without exception, 
 found it necessary to adopt the use of small cards which 
 can be easily sorted and shifted from hand to hand. 
 The notes on them usually show the subject, the state- 
 ment of fact or opinion, name of authority, and ref- 
 erence, thus: 
 
 Subject 
 
 Statement Authority Reference
 
 146 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 Exercises 
 
 The subject of brief-making, accompanied by a study 
 of evidence and of argument and the dehvery of at 
 least one oration, may well occupy the first term in a 
 course in debating. It should include the drawing of 
 three or four briefs of arguments, found in a book of 
 specimens, so as to develop in the student the habit of 
 accurate and thorough thinking, that is, through co- 
 ordination and subordination. The following ques- 
 tions on argumentative theory may be suggestive. 
 
 1. Distinguish between the following: argument, 
 evidence, proof; assumption, presumption; persuasion, 
 conviction. 
 
 2. What are the two important laws of structure? 
 Give the main syllogism of any two of the specimens 
 studied and show how they conform to these laws. 
 
 3. Define the several classes of evidence. Mention 
 the chief tests used in the examination of ordinary testi- 
 mony. 
 
 4. What important differences can you point out in 
 the employment of evidence in a court of law and be- 
 fore deliberative bodies? 
 
 5. Give the rules for the interpretation of documents. 
 
 6. Define argument, and (a) show how all arguments 
 in their final analysis and when carried to completion 
 will involve an inference from the complex relations of 
 association, resemblance or contrast, particular and 
 general, and cause and effect. 
 
 7. What, in your opinion, is the relative importance 
 of observation and inference in reasoning about ordinary 
 affairs? {b) Show that sign argument may vary in force 
 from slight probability to certainty. Illustrate.
 
 EVIDENCE 147 
 
 8. When may a cited case be said to be relevant to 
 a matter under inquiry? Illustrate, (c) Mention the 
 most common fallacies in the use of argument from 
 example. Illustrate. 
 
 9. Indicate the important steps which may be em- 
 ployed in the process of arguing from example. 
 
 10. Show the use of the redudio ad ahsurdum, made 
 by Mansfield in the "Evans Case," by Macaulay on 
 "Copyright," or by Beecher when speaking at Liver- 
 pool. Give an effective way of answering the reductio 
 ad ahsurdum cited. 
 
 11. From the specimens studied, give an illustration 
 of the development by the speaker of a common gromid 
 as a basis for argument to people hostile in their mental 
 attitude. 
 
 12. Describe, as far as possible, the method you would 
 naturally follow in getting a person to change his mind. 
 
 After brief-drawing and argumentative theory have 
 been sufficiently stressed, there should be pro\aded ample 
 opportunity for practice in actual debates, in which the 
 student is permitted to draw his own material from 
 varied sources. This practice accompanied by a study 
 of presentation may well occupy the second term of a 
 college year. 
 
 The questions may be posted at the beginning of 
 the term and debaters assigned to them from week to 
 week; a reading-room set apart in the university library, 
 and the reference librarian requested to place every 
 Monday on the shelves all material necessary for an 
 intelhgent investigation and discussion of the question 
 under debate for that week. In this Hbrary room the 
 debaters may be given an hour for preliminary con- 
 ference in groups with the instructor in charge. The
 
 148 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 material is then carefully examined, and the case for 
 the affirmative and negative analyzed and distributed 
 among the speakers, each speaker being given a central 
 idea, fundamental to the case, and told to image it ef- 
 fectively on the minds of his audience. There should 
 be no requirement of a formal brief from the speakers 
 in this debate, but rather a dependence placed on previous 
 systematic training in brief-drawing. Every encourage- 
 ment should be given for original and individual think- 
 ing. 
 
 Obviously, good debating means the ability to think 
 on one's feet and to talk quietly to an audience, an- 
 ticipating objections and answering them, conciliating 
 rather than antagonizing, in order to secure approval. 
 The debater must speak extemporaneously in rebuttal; 
 he should also be required to do so in his first speech. 
 For this purpose, special supplementary exercises in 
 extempore speaking are sometimes found advantageous. 
 In a literary society or a class of a dozen men, a list 
 of topics on current events may be gathered from the 
 head-lines of the morning paper, or from a weekly or a 
 monthly magazine, and numbered in order. At the 
 meeting, the presiding officer may call upon a member 
 to speak, whereupon the clerk announces the topic after 
 the speaker has taken the floor. The clerk, of course, 
 announces each topic, in the order in which it appears 
 on the list. By organizing the class into a congress or 
 other deHberative body for the discussion of resolutions, 
 familiarity may also be had with the rules of parlia- 
 mentary law. Always following a debate, a vote should 
 be taken first on the merits of the debate, and then the 
 resolution should be thrown open for general discussion, 
 and finally voted up or down. All members of the class
 
 EVIDENCE 149 
 
 other than the assigned debaters, usually six, are re- 
 quired to hand in a brief on the question to be debated. 
 This adds interest to the general discussion on the merits 
 of the question. 
 
 This actual practice in speaking should, of course, be 
 accompanied by a study in presentation, stress being 
 laid on the imagination and also on suggestion, volun- 
 tary and involuntary, conscious and subconscious, as 
 being essential and logical elements in the development 
 of the process of effective thinking. In other words, 
 the aim is to develop, first, logical accuracy and sound 
 thinking, and afterward the other qualities, imaginative, 
 rhetorical, and practical, and always in connection with 
 a valuable subject-matter. Debate lends itself peculiarly 
 to educational purposes because it demands of a man 
 that in self-defense he think soundly and effectively 
 under fire.
 
 PART II 
 THE PRESENTATION 
 
 CHAPTER VI 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 
 
 Whether the means or aims are those of description, 
 narration, exposition, or argument, the chief problem 
 in conveying our ideas to others is one of imaginative 
 suggestion. 
 
 Suggestion is the broadest term used to describe the 
 act of influencing others, whether spontaneous or de- 
 liberate, by word or by gesture. Any act mental or 
 physical used to awaken or to direct in others mental or 
 physical activity is suggestion. This implies, of course, 
 that thinking always involves molecular or physical 
 changes. 
 
 Imagery, too, has a pecuUar power as an agent of 
 suggestion upon the attention, interest, sympathy, and 
 thinking of an audience, over its mental activity, its 
 processes, conclusions, and actions. 
 
 I. Need of Imagination in Argument 
 
 Great progress has been made in the development 
 of public speaking in the last few years. A more pleasing 
 and more durable edifice is being artistically built on 
 the old logical, rhetorical, and elocutionary foundations, 
 in accordance with newly recognized vital principles; 
 
 150
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 151 
 
 and we are, I think, coming to see more clearly both 
 the need of developing the imagination of the speaker 
 and the way to do it. There arise before us new vistas 
 in investigation, knowledge, and methods. Important 
 explorations have already been made, and good ore is 
 being found and reduced to practical use. There is, 
 first of all, need of a new emphasis in the training of 
 the imagination of the student of argument and debate. 
 Since all language is, of course, only suggestive, and 
 since argument at best is unaginatively suggestive (since 
 it is impossible to argue without assumption) , one cannot 
 but feel the danger, to certain types of students, which 
 would result from too formal processes of reasoning. 
 For instance, the model of a brief-form made by older 
 men may be held up by us before younger minds for 
 emphasis of the rational basis of conviction, to give an 
 idea of the need of firmness of structure, to illustrate 
 the logical characteristics of unity and sequence; but 
 shears and measuring- tape are needed in fitting the suit 
 of the older son to his next younger brother. Indeed, 
 the theory of argumentation, as laid down in some of 
 our text-books, is at times unsuited to college classes, in 
 which the students are unacquainted with inductive 
 processes, unused to making careful generalizations and 
 comparisons, and have had no earher courses, for ex- 
 ample, in logic or philosophy, or no large background of 
 knowledge upon which to draw. And does not the sepa- 
 rate treatment of "persuasion" smack of the ancient 
 teaching that the mind is a series of water-tight com- 
 partments? At all events, such compendiums of "prin- 
 ciples" or "elements" are of value only in the hands 
 of an experienced instructor, who, in using them, takes 
 account of the fact that they are not adapted to persons
 
 152 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 of all ages, nor indeed to all types of mind. Charles 
 Lamb remarked of Scotsmen that he had been trying 
 all his life to like them, but had given it up in despair. 
 
 Principles, methods, and forms should be taught only 
 in so far as they are readily assimilable by the student, 
 and are used with freedom and enthusiasm in parallel 
 original work in writing and speaking. The university 
 witj Nicholas Udall, of Eton, wrote a play, modelled 
 after Plautus, called " Ralph Royster Doyster," the first 
 EngUsh comedy. Two younger gentlemen of the Inner 
 Temple, Norton and Sackville, presented before Queen 
 Elizabeth a play called "Gorboduc," patterned after 
 Seneca, and now venerated as the first English tragedy. 
 But, valuable as this classic influence was, no one would 
 think of sa5ang that without the addition of the more 
 original imaginative or romantic elements we could ever 
 have had a consummate expression of life in Elizabethan 
 drama, such as was reached in Shakespeare's plays. It 
 is a long time now since Professor Baker of Harvard 
 separated argumentation from the older rhetorics and 
 performed a great service by giving it distinct and sepa- 
 rate prominence as a form of composition. The older 
 rhetorics, from which it was taken, have long since passed 
 away, chiefly because they did not allow for individuality 
 in men. Argumentative formalism has survived the 
 longest, partly because the theory is the hardest to per- 
 fect, and partly because of the desire to recognize the 
 supremacy of reason in influencing afifairs in the world. 
 
 We should welcome to-day the serious efforts being 
 made by what may be called the new psychological 
 school of expression. It not only opens a stimulating 
 field of thought and investigation, but bids fair to suc- 
 ceed where the older methods failed, namely, in allow-
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 153 
 
 ing for individual growth and development. I believe, 
 in particular, in the opportunity which this line of 
 thought offers to the student of argument; for, while 
 it recognizes reason as a stabilizing force, it teaches 
 clearly that man is not to be reached by it alone, and 
 that in applying the laws of reasoning for the purpose 
 of influencing the thoughts of others, there are deeper 
 considerations to be taken account of. Not that we 
 have not heretofore paid some heed to association and 
 inhibition, nor recognized the importance in expression 
 of attention, imagination, memory, and feeling; but 
 never before have we reahzed so fully the value of the 
 psychological elements and at the same time possessed 
 sufficient and accurate data for their effective exploita- 
 tion. Or, again, recognizing the constant diversification 
 of the attention of indi\'iduals in modern Hfe, and the 
 ease with which our consciousness may be flooded with 
 feelings on matters of principle or of interest or of no 
 consequence at all — with or against our wills — or re- 
 calling the different memory associations of different 
 men, we perceive at once how valuable to the trained 
 student of argument or debate is that illmiiinating emi- 
 nence of \'iew-point which enables him to see his field 
 anew in the clear air of imaginative suggestion. We 
 should never forget, too, that the iinagination is the 
 vanguard, the pioneer of all progress in the world, of 
 which reason is only the explanation. It has, I think, 
 been sufiiciently shown heretofore that reason does not 
 exist apart from, and cannot proceed independently of, 
 the imagination; and perhaps I may add that there is 
 an abstract as well as a concrete imagery. Mathematics, 
 for instance, is as much imaginative as it is intellectual. 
 It is a distinct gain for the thinking and for the power
 
 154 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 of expression of the student of argument when he learns, 
 for instance, to image a concept in its relations; that is, 
 with its implications, whether the purpose be coldly to 
 explain or warmly to impress. Certainly he must learn 
 to see the content in the form and the form in the 
 content, the part in the whole and the whole in the part, 
 the means in the end and the end in the means, the prin- 
 ciple in the fact and the fact in the principle, cause in 
 effect and effect in cause, similitude in example-, and 
 the reverse. Imagination, indeed, is a Kght shining from 
 afar which beckons us on; reason is the road built by 
 an engineer to enable us safely to reach it. It is subject 
 to error, of course, may prove an ignis fatuus; but so, 
 too, may the intellect. And, finally, inasmuch as lan- 
 guage is a chief medium of expression employed in argu- 
 ment, the words which are used as symbols must be 
 symbohc of something, must be suggestive of meaning 
 to the persons addressed. The teacher of argument 
 should thus be, not a mere mental undertaker, but an 
 inspiration to original creative thinking and revealing*. 
 This is the high meaning of the word "educo." 
 
 From what has been said, it is apparent that the 
 debater may examine with profit the psychological point 
 of view from which an argument may be regarded, and 
 the processes through which the imagination functions 
 in a well-presented argument, as well as the various 
 imagery types. 
 
 II. Psychological View-Point and Processes 
 
 The Logical and the Psychological. — Perhaps we may 
 see even more clearly the dift'erence between the logical 
 and the psychological view-points from which an argu- 
 ment may be regarded if we examine such a passage
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 155 
 
 as the foIlo^^-ing from Hall Caine commenting on Presi- 
 dent Wilson's "Peace Without Victory" address to 
 the United States Senate: 
 
 President Wilson probably knows by this time that the first 
 expression of French and British opinion on his speech to the 
 Senate has been that of scarcely disguised disdain. 
 
 He has no reason to be seriously troubled on that account. 
 So bold a challenge could hardly have failed of any other imme- 
 diate effect. From the days of Joseph downward ridicule has 
 been the first heritage of all exalted dreamers. 
 
 The dreamer is the marked victim of what is called the prac- 
 tical mind. The loftier the theme and the more idealistic the 
 form the easier the play of satire. The world has never thought 
 it a proof of genius, even in the works of men of genius, to 
 make sport of the Angel Gabriel or of yet the Blessed Trinity; 
 on the contrary, it has often found proof of sublimity in the 
 ideas that have excited derision. It was the exaltation as well 
 as the excess of Euripides which created Aristophanes. Warmth 
 and glow of mind and heart are a natural challenge to icy na- 
 tures. When red-hot iron is plunged into freezing water it al- 
 ways goes off with a hiss. Let President Wilson take heart 
 from the first reception of his remarkable speech. — {N. Y. Times, 
 January 24, 1917.) 
 
 Logically, the writer shows why the President "should 
 take heart from the first reception of his remarkable 
 speech." He argues that from the days of Joseph down- 
 ward, ridicule has been the first heritage of all exalted 
 dreamers, for, indeed, the dreamer is the marked victim 
 of the practical mind. He applies the reductio ad ah- 
 surdum to the case of the Angel Gabriel and of that of 
 the Blessed Trinity, and then cites directly the fact 
 that Aristophanes is due to the exaltation of Euripides. 
 He has made his point by examples or, if you like, in- 
 ductively, by bringing instances under a class, and he
 
 156 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 has made it causally, by showing that an exaltation of 
 mind creates exalted results. 
 
 Psychologically, however, the passage may be re- 
 garded as imaging the concept of the world's view of 
 the "exalted dreamer" by bringing forward a few 
 chosen portraits from the gallery of memory. True, 
 there is here no fulness of descriptive detail, no richness 
 of epithet, but in the act of associating a league of peace 
 with the Angel Gabriel and the Blessed Trinity, the 
 writer has fixed the attention startlingly on the exalta- 
 tion of dreaming and set the mind to thinking on the 
 inconsistency and the limitations of that t3^e of mind 
 which scoffs at a world league of peace. The other 
 memory picture, that of Euripides and Aristophanes, is 
 not so rich in ideal association, but it fixes attention on 
 a more definite and a nearer conclusion, namely, that 
 an exaltation of mind may produce fortunate results. 
 In the concluding sentences we will notice, too, the vivid- 
 ness and force due to the perceptual and emotional ap- 
 peals- in such phrases or words as "warmth and glow," 
 "icy nature," "red-hot iron," "plunged," "freezing 
 water," "goes off," "a hiss." 
 
 An argument viewed as a logical process has been 
 said to be one of sign, example, or analogy, causation, 
 and classification. As a psychological process, it is a 
 concept imaged on the attention with its proper im- 
 pHcations and in its readily recognized relations. The 
 logical relations thus employed in the imagery of argu- 
 ment, therefore, may be causal; general or abstract as 
 well as particular or concrete; exemplative or analogical; 
 and, indeed, sometimes so simple or minute as to be un- 
 analyzed, or so complex or elusive as to be almost un- 
 jinalyzable. Broadly speaking, the myriads of minute
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 157 
 
 elements which go to make up the background of an 
 argument and give it its general tone or character, and 
 which are before the mind of the creative artist but an 
 instant in the act of writing or speaking, are mere ac- 
 companiments or associations and may be regarded as 
 reasonings from sign. They emphasize to us the im- 
 portance of little things, and contribute immeasurably 
 to the argument by imparting to it a sense of complete- 
 ness, richness, and reality. 
 
 Images Are a Psychological Inference. — We may use 
 the temi psychological inference to apply to any in- 
 ference which depends for its cognizance upon other 
 states of consciousness than the logical reason. Thus 
 an imaged statement offered as a reason supphes a ground 
 of psychological inference, for it makes the idea per- 
 ceptual. So Lincoln argues against slavery that it 
 "closed the door of hope." It may also appeal to 
 memory and feehng. So President Wilson speaking for 
 preparedness, emphasizing the spiritual over the com- 
 mercial, said: "We do not hang a yardstick over the 
 mantelpiece, but we do hang a musket, for somehow it 
 is associated with the lad's sacrifice and has come to 
 be revered in the family." When the debater offers a 
 reason for a proposition phrased in vivid imagery, it is 
 usually a conclusion which he has previously reached 
 by careful methods of investigation and by sound logical 
 processes. 
 
 We are morally justified in the use of psychological 
 inference for such ideas as we may regard as having 
 been previously proved or which are profoundly believed 
 to be true and valuable. We rightly condemn the 
 demagogue for his insincerity, but for any sound be- 
 lief sincerely held, we may unhesitatingly and will al-
 
 158 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 most instinctively seek support by appealing to per- 
 ception, feeling, and memory to assist the thinking. 
 
 Psychological inference is really the process of making 
 a logical inference psychological. If logical inference 
 be regarded as necessarily involving the class idea, psy- 
 chological inference is an intuitive perception. It differs 
 from logical inference in the fact that, at the time and 
 so far as we are then conscious, the process is immediate 
 rather than mediate. The syllogism is a mediate infer- 
 ence; that is, from one proposition to another by means 
 of a third. The immediate process, on the other hand, 
 takes the character of a mental flash. Effective argument, 
 indeed, may be described as a mental process of which 
 imagination is the major premise, perception the minor 
 premise, and common sense the ground of inference. 
 By common sense is meant the perception of nature as 
 it is, by a person of well-balanced mind. 
 
 Mental Processes. — The debater will perhaps under- 
 stand better the nature of some of the processes which 
 he employs if we note a few simple distinctions made 
 by psychologists in elementary terms: First, the psy- 
 chologist distinguishes between the reproductive and 
 the productive imagination. The reproductive imag- 
 ination is really memory, for it actually repeats what 
 was formerly in consciousness; while the productive 
 imagination contains images "not before in our minds 
 in their present order and form." This makes possible 
 the artistic character of literary composition. The 
 imagination of poets, novelists, and orators is productive, 
 or, as the artists call it, creative. 
 
 Second, the psychologist distinguishes between an 
 image and an idea. " So far," says Angell, " as we have 
 in mind the sensuous content of a thought, as, for ex-
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 159 
 
 ample, its \asual or auditory character, we use the term 
 image. So far as we wish to emphasize in addition to 
 or in distinction from this fact of sensuous constitution 
 the purport, significance, or meaning of an image, we 
 use the term idea. Images merely represent on the 
 cognitive side the more substantive moments in the 
 onward outflow of consciousness." So Jaques images 
 his idea of Hfe in — "All the world's a stage." 
 
 A third distinction of the psychologist is that made 
 between an image and a perception; the latter being 
 the "consciousness of a particular material thing pres- 
 ent to sense," while an image is the consciousness of a 
 thing not present to sense. We perceive a star or a flower 
 which is actually before the eye: it rises before the con- 
 sciousness later as an image. The poet perceives a sun- 
 rise, but, being a creative artist, he images it thus: 
 
 "Night's candles are burnt out, and jocund day 
 Stands tiptoe on the misty mountain- tops." 
 
 Obviously, imagery is both conceptual and perceptual. 
 Either characteristic may be exaggerated and abused 
 by an orator or debater. If it is too ideational, the 
 audience will miss the meaning; if too sensory, it will 
 possess no meaning. 
 
 The Creative Imagination. — Ruskin makes the art 
 process in general depend on the eye, the head, and the 
 hand, which Bliss Perry renders for poetry into vision, 
 transforming imagination, and expression. The imagery 
 of our best prose, too, is the result of real vision and crea- 
 tive power in the image-making process. Vision, that 
 is, perception, whether conducted by external observa- 
 tion and selection, or by introspection, suppHes material
 
 IGO THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 from an individual's own experiences, which the asso- 
 ciative processes of his mind transmute, through imagery 
 and suggestion, into forms of memorable beauty. 
 
 Illustration. — Professor Goodrich cites the following 
 as "one of the finest amplifications in English oratory, 
 justified by the importance of the subject which it em- 
 braces and admirably suited to produce the designed 
 impression." The central idea was probably suggested 
 by a remark of Burke, whose writings Mr. Erskine in- 
 cessantly studied: "It is the nature of all greatness not 
 to be exact." Defending Stockdale from the charge 
 of hbel, and seeing the evils of a too great restriction 
 on the press, Erskine said: 
 
 From minds thus subdued by the terrors of punishment there 
 could issue no works of genius to expand the empire of human 
 reason. ... It is the nature of everything that is great and 
 useful, both in the animate and inanimate world, to be wild 
 and irregular, and we must be contented to take them with the 
 alloys which belong to them, or live without them. Genius 
 breaks from the fetters of criticism, but its wanderings are sanc- 
 tioned by its majesty and wisdom when it advances in its path; 
 subject it to the critic and you turn it into dulness. . . . Tem- 
 pests occasionally shake our dwellings and dissipate our com- 
 merce, but they scourge before them the lazy elements, which 
 without them would stagnate into pestilence. In Hke manner, 
 liberty herself, the last and best gift of God to his creatures, must 
 be taken just as she is; you might pare her down to bashful 
 regularity and shape her into a perfect model of severe scrupulous 
 law, but she would then be liberty no longer; you must be con- 
 tent to die under the lash of this inexorable justice which you 
 have exchanged for the honor of freedom. 
 
 The Poverty of Mere Facts. — "It would not be a bad 
 conjecture but an obvious truism," says WilHam Haz- 
 litt, "to say that all the great changes which have been
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 161 
 
 brought about in the moral world, either for the better 
 or the worse, have been introduced not by the bare state- 
 ment of facts which are themselves already known and 
 which must always operate nearly in the same manner, 
 but by the development of certain opinions and abstract 
 principles of reasoning on life and manners, on the origin 
 of society and man's nature in general, which being 
 obscure and uncertain, vary from time to time and pro- 
 duce correspondent changes in the hmnan mind. They 
 are the wholesome dew and rain, or the mildew and 
 pestilence that silently destroy. To this principle of 
 generalization all religious creeds, the institutions of 
 wise lawgivers, and the systems of philosophy owe their 
 influence." 
 
 There are moments in the great debates when the 
 orator feels impelled to go beyond the precise mechanics 
 of logic and express the instincts of the race, or of in- 
 dividuals, which will hght the fires of understanding 
 and kindle the common enthusiasm and beliefs of hu- 
 manity. Reduction of reasoning to mere genus and 
 species by palpable facts is utterly fruitless without a 
 manifestation of the insight of the soul into the wider 
 spaces of the imagination which point, as unerringly 
 as the needle of the compass, because guided by the 
 subconscious, the involuntary — by instinct, if you like- 
 by whatever goes to make up truth and behef. The 
 mere logician would depreciate all this with the phrase, 
 "Mere imagery," but we must speak with intuition as 
 well as with precision. 
 
 The Vision of New Ideas. — Perhaps one may indicate 
 briefly how in general new ideas come into the mind. 
 The law of association has been defined as the tendency 
 of ideas which have been in the mind together to come
 
 162 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 up together, but we have seen that the imagination is 
 more than memory associations; we have the sugges- 
 tions of new images. The imagination is continually- 
 offering to consciousness the sensations, experiences, 
 and reactions from new stimuli, or from old stimuU in 
 new circumstances. From the slightest subconscious 
 hint, the mind may perceive an image which will incline 
 it in a new direction, and which if followed intently and 
 with determination, may result in discovery, uivention, 
 and progress. All such experiences have been called by 
 psychologists anticipation images. 
 
 Anticipation Images. — Thus, while it is of course true 
 that images bring back past memory associations, it is 
 equally true that presentations are constantly arising 
 in consciousness as images, which find their way event- 
 ually into new combinations of value and interest. Crea- 
 tive art also is the result of the suggestion of new images. 
 New images depend on the laws of suggestion. 
 
 The mind is constantly obliged to sail uncharted seas 
 for an unknown, imagined port. The western voyages 
 of Columbus, the Cabots, and Verrazzano, or the search 
 for an earthly paradise which occupied the thoughts 
 of the Middle Ages, are paralleled daily in the h3^oth- 
 esis of the scientific investigator, the plans for new 
 enterprises in business, and the ambitions, aims, hopes, 
 and expectations of the average man in the smallest 
 affairs of life. Rely upon past experience we must, in 
 testing and perfecting all new ideas; otherwise, we shall 
 go astray and be lost in the quagmires of fancy and false- 
 hood. Columbus, for instance, when saiUng for the 
 western world used the sailing ships of his day and all 
 the knowledge of navigation with which astrology and 
 superstition could provide him. But he had a vision,
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 163 
 
 a purpose, a hope, which enabled him from Genoa to 
 see "land"; a land, moreover, which he was determined 
 to see, and which he so ardently desired to see that he 
 was willing to bear any burden of sacrifice that would 
 enable him to experience the joy of accomplishing it. 
 Perhaps, indeed, the original suggestion to make the 
 voyage came to liim from Marco Polo. The world is 
 full of such adventurous spirits in every field, to whom 
 the vision of a new idea is more real than the known and 
 familiar objects of perception. 
 
 The debater, too, intently pursues his vision (be it the 
 reform of prisons or the success of our army) until he 
 moulds the fleeting suggestions which come before his 
 mind into the single image of a well-defined, construc- 
 tive plan. He pursues his vision further, and employs 
 the imagery of words to express this plan so suggestively 
 to others that tliey will perceive it, believe in it, and 
 perhaps be willing to act upon it. 
 
 Perceptual Aspect of Imagery. — The perceptual aspect 
 of imagery may always be pointed out with profit to 
 that type of mind which is accustomed to generaliza- 
 tions and to abstractions, as, for example, to students 
 of mathematics and philosophy. Moreover, an appre- 
 ciation of this fundamental basis of imagery often needs 
 to be awakened anew in debaters who have worked as- 
 siduously on the logic and fonn of a brief or have spent 
 much time in the Hbrary. A boat in the trough of the 
 sea may not observe the stars. Effectiveness in speak- 
 ing usually means the bringing of our ideas within the 
 listener's experience or life. I shall now show that an 
 important part of this imaging process involves psy- 
 chologically, the reduction of our ideas to sense-percep- 
 tion.
 
 164 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 We recognize the value of the concrete or the partic- 
 ular in driving home an argument, but we do not under- 
 stand fully the nature of the process. We do not suf- 
 ficiently realize, for instance, that the function of the 
 concrete or particular in driving home an argument is 
 to bring it before the senses of the hstener, and that it 
 is this sensory appeal of imagery which gives it its clear- 
 ness and force. 
 
 Language itself is of course primarily a perception; 
 auditory when it greets the ear as sounds, visual when 
 it strikes the eye as sights, as, for example, on the printed 
 page. But words may produce other sensations than 
 the purely auditory or the purely visual, for we may 
 speak or write of a Jwt day, a fragrant rose, a luscious 
 apple, and so on. Thus words or phrases ma}^ suggest 
 the sensations of past tactile, olfactory, gustatory, or 
 other experiences. The Hterary artist, in his endeavor 
 to create in another a consciousness of things not ac- 
 tually present to sense, recognizes this and makes in- 
 directly a varied sensory appeal. 
 
 No image, however, should be expected to bring to 
 mind the same perception in all individuals, but the 
 perceptual character of hnagery may be illustrated a 
 little further, at least suggestively. Portia's appeal in 
 behalf of Bassanio begins: "The quality of mercy is 
 not strained." Take the word "quality"; a word in 
 my mind opposed to quantity, which I know about 
 concretely either by observation or by the feeling of 
 touch, as when I speak of the quality of a piece of cloth. 
 The image "quality of mercy" may therefore be re- 
 garded by some, as visual and tactile. "Is not strained" 
 suggests remotely the absence of muscular energy. Its 
 falling "like the gentle rain from heaven" brings a pic-
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 165 
 
 ture to my eyes of things in motion but falling silently. 
 The second line is therefore to me visual and auditory 
 in its suggestions. "It is twice blessed" brings before 
 me the picture of a minister or bishop holding out his 
 hands in benediction. "It blesses him that gives and 
 him that takes" fills in the picture by adding the two 
 objects of tlie benediction. " 'Tis mightiest in the 
 mighty. It becomes the throned monarch better than 
 his crown," suggests the prerogative of the King in exer- 
 cising the pardoning power as prominently illustrated 
 later by King James's pardon of Sir Francis Bacon. You 
 probably did not recall the particular material things 
 which this imagery suggested to me, you may even have 
 assigned some of the images to different senses; but you 
 will admit the suggestiveness of the imagery, and the 
 vividness, and force, of its varied sense-appeal. 
 
 Or turn to another well-known illustration and ex- 
 amine its sense-suggestions, "Well, honor is the sub- 
 ject of my story" — an indirect suggestion to give ear 
 to the tale. "I was born free as Caesar. We both have 
 fed as well," brings a picture to the eye with a distinct 
 gustatory imphcation. "For once upon a raw and gusty 
 day" instances the comparison concretely; but notice 
 that the adjectives "raw and gusty," used to describe 
 the day, contain in the first case, a tactile suggestion 
 and in the second case, auditory and visual suggestions, 
 and perhaps even muscular force. " Caesar cried, 'Barest 
 thou, Cassius, now leap in with me?'" — obviously audi- 
 tory and visual. In such wise does Shakespeare com- 
 monly express his thoughts with concrete details and 
 image them with a varied and indirect suggestiveness 
 of sensory appeal. 
 
 Obviously, imagery rests on a past sense-perception.
 
 166 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 and its power is conditioned by its ability to recall to 
 the eye or ear the sensations experienced when past 
 particular, material things were in some order or form 
 previously before the senses. Indeed, an artistic image 
 produces the illusion of a real perception, and the artist 
 in his enthusiasm may actually so regard it. Henry 
 Ward Beecher, for instance, once spoke of a diamond 
 sceptre, and, on being reminded later that no diamond 
 had been found as large as a sceptre, replied: *'I saw it." 
 
 Imaging a Concept. — We have said that since objects 
 and things to which ideas refer cannot always be pres- 
 ent to the senses, we are in the habit of callmg them to 
 consciousness by suggesting the image of our ideas with 
 its natural associations. The image-making process is 
 therefore a process of reducing abstract or general ideas 
 to sense-perception. It has a basis in feeling as well as 
 in memory and furnishes the true method of gaining 
 interest and attention as well as of producing convic- 
 tion and belief. 
 
 General or abstract ideas make little impression on the 
 average mind accustomed to think in particulars and 
 by means of comparisons. All such ideas need to be 
 brought within the listener's experience and imaged con- 
 cretely. The more conceptual an audience is, the more 
 abstract or general may be the presentation, but even 
 with educated audiences we gain in interest by the spe- 
 cific, concrete, detailed, illustrative methods of imagery. 
 
 The debater must learn, if he does not know it al- 
 ready, that he will be dry and uninteresting if he re- 
 stricts himself when speaking to processes which are 
 as purely formal as those of his brief. He must know, 
 for instance, that he may quite properly make use of 
 exposition, narration, or description when appealing to
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 167 
 
 grounds of belief or to motives of action. He should 
 recall Lincoln's story-telling habit, his graphic descrip- 
 tive powers, and his lucid expositions. How ineffective, 
 indeed, would Lincoln have been in his debates with 
 Douglas had he presented his arguments in an unimag- 
 inative or purely logical way! Webster was called the 
 Great Expounder, it being said of him that his very 
 exposition was argument. Nothing is more erroneous 
 than the idea that an argument must always be in an 
 argumentative form. Even a talk may be adorned with 
 a moral. Woodrow Wilson, for instance, uses an apt 
 anecdote in a dignified Phi Beta Kappa address. Ob- 
 serve also the suggestive power of Colonel Roosevelt's 
 analogy of "The Man with a Muckrake." The argu- 
 mentative process should be obvious, but not tiresomely 
 obtrusive. 
 
 We may regard any proposition (process or conclu- 
 sion) as a concept for the purposes of imagery. We 
 may also regard "affection and desire" as a concept 
 and image that. Let us, then, illustrate the imaging 
 (i) of an analogy, (2) of a cause, (3) of a conclusion, 
 and (4) of affection and desire; (5) in a team debate 
 and (6) in general. 
 
 I. Imaging an Analogy. — The trained mind of Alex- 
 ander Hamilton, arguing on the adoption of the federal 
 constitution at the New York convention of 1788, per- 
 ceived a likeness in the strong attachment of the in- 
 dividual for the State to certain social and physical facts 
 which he imaged thus: 
 
 There are certain social principles from which we may draw 
 the most solid conclusions with respect to the conduct of in- 
 dividuals and of communities. We love our families more than 
 our neighbors; we love our neighbors more than our country-
 
 168 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 men in general. The human affections like the solar heat lose 
 their intensity as they depart from the centre and become languid 
 in proportion to the expansion of the circle on which they act. 
 On these principles, the attachment of the individual will be 
 first and forever secured by the State governments; they will 
 be a mutual protection and support. 
 
 2. Imaging a Cause. — The process of imaging the 
 relation of cause and effect or of motive to deed may 
 be illustrated by Hugo's description of the circumstances 
 of poverty and struggle which made Jean Valjean steal 
 the loaf of bread. The argument is, that a hungry man 
 will steal; that Jean Valjean was hungry; therefore he 
 burglarized the baker's shop. 
 
 Toward the middle of the night, Jean Valjean awoke. He 
 belonged to a poor peasant family of La Brie. ... At night he 
 came home tired, and ate his soup without saying a word. His 
 sister, Mother Jeanne, while he was eating, often took out of 
 his porringer the best part of his meal, the piece of meat, the 
 slice of bacon, or the heart of the cabbage to give to one of her 
 children; he, still eating, bent over the table with his head al- 
 most in the soup, and his long hair falling around his porringer 
 and hiding his eyes, pretended not to see it, and let her do as 
 she pleased. . . . One Sunday evening, Maubert Isabeau, the 
 baker in the church square at FaveroUes, was just going to bed 
 when he heard a violent blow dealt the wired and glazed front 
 of his shop. He arrived in time to see an arm passed through 
 a hole made by a fist through the wires and window-pane; the 
 arm seized a loaf and carried it off. Isabeau ran out hastily; 
 the thief ran away at his hardest, but the baker caught him 
 up and stopped him. The thief had thrown away the loaf, but 
 his arm was still bleeding; it was Jean Valjean. . . . Jean 
 Valjean was sentenced to five years at the galleys. 
 
 In the following, the writer is endeavoring to image 
 the evil efects of cigarette smoking in connection with 
 its cause:
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT IGO 
 
 Have you ever seen a white, puny, stunted youngster, whose 
 anaemic face has aroused the question why? Nicotine is like 
 an evil, yellow god, which eats into the system, destroying the 
 sensitive nerve-cells and life-giving vitality. Its use is prev- 
 alent in the form of cigarettes. Here to the terrible danger of the 
 poisonous nicotine is added the poison carbon monoxide which 
 arises from the incomplete combustion of the cigarette-paper. 
 This poison is taken into the system by the very effective process 
 of osmosis. Now to answer the question why? Before the 
 deUcate age of twenty-one is reached, the life-giving white blood- 
 corpuscles are not fully developed, and when the strong nicotine- 
 laden smoke is inhaled, the growth of the white blood-corpuscles 
 (which are essential to good health) is stunted, and as a result 
 we see the white, puny, ansmic faces (resembling prison-walls) 
 of those most unfortunate and foolish youths who have started 
 the vitality-sapping use of tobacco before physical full develop- 
 ment has taken place. Thus, does the all-powerful, grasping 
 nicotine sap the weak vitaHty of our whelp. — {Student's Com- 
 position.) 
 
 3. Imaging a Conclusion. — Burke's imagery of his ad- 
 miration of the American character, as shown by the 
 growth of the whaling industries of New England, is 
 expressed in sublime eloquence: 
 
 As to the wealth which the colonies have drawn from the sea by 
 their fisheries, you had aU that matter fully opened at your bar. 
 You surely thought those acquisitions of value, for they seemed 
 even to excite your envy, and yet, the spirit by which that en- 
 terprising employment has been exercised, ought rather, in my 
 opinion, to have raised your esteem and admiration. And pray, 
 sir, what in the world is equal to it? Pass by the other parts, 
 and look at the manner in which the people of New England 
 have of late carried on the whale fishery. Whilst we follow them 
 among the tumbling mountains of ice, and behold them pene- 
 trating into the deepest frozen recesses of Hudson's Bay and 
 Davis's Straits, whilst we are looking for them beneath the arctic 
 circle, we hear that they have pierced into the opposite region 
 of polar cold, that they are at the antipodes, and engaged under
 
 170 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 the frozen serpent of the south. Falkland Island, which seemed 
 too remote and romantic an object for the grasp of national 
 ambition, is but a stage and resting-place in the progress of 
 their victorious industry. Nor is the equinoctial heat more 
 discouraging to them than the accumulated winter of both 
 the poles. We know that whilst some of them draw the line, 
 and strike the harpoon on the coast of Africa, others run the 
 longitude, and pursue their gigantic game along the coast of 
 Brazil. No sea but what is vexed by their fisheries. No cUmate 
 that is not witness to their toils. Neither the perseverance of 
 Holland, nor the activity of France, nor the dexterous and firm 
 sagacity of English enterprise, ever carried this most perilous 
 mode of hardy industry to the extent to which it has been pushed 
 by this recent people; a people who are still, as it were, but in 
 the gristle, and not yet hardened into the bone, of manhood. 
 When I contemplate these things; when I know that the colonies 
 in general owe little or nothing to any care of ours, and that 
 they are not squeezed into this happy form by the constraints 
 of watchful and suspicious government, but that, through a 
 wise and salutary neglect, a generous nature has been suffered 
 to take her own way to perfection; when I reflect upon these 
 effects, when I see how profitable they have been to us, I feel 
 all the pride of power sink, and all presumption in the wisdom 
 of human contrivances melt, and die away within me. My 
 rigor relents. I pardon something to the spirit of liberty. 
 
 Mr. Charles Kendall Adams points out that this pas- 
 sage is based on substantial facts. "Massachusetts had 
 183 vessels carrying 13,820 tons in the North, and 120 
 vessels carrying 14,025 tons in the South. It was in 
 1775, the very year of Burke's speech, that English ships 
 were first fitted out to follow the Americans into the 
 fisheries of the South Seas." 
 
 Thus, our best arguments are usually illuminated 
 judgments tempered with feeling. In debating, we 
 frequently illustrate this process in our first speeches, 
 leaving it to the rebuttal speeches to supply, when nee-
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 171 
 
 essary, the statistical facts previously gathered during 
 our investigations and tested in practice debates. For 
 example, in a debate on preparedness according to the 
 Swiss plan subsequently mentioned, the size of the army 
 of 11,000,000 men and the small cost of such an army 
 were imaged at length in the first speeches. These con- 
 cepts, however, were conclusions which had been pre- 
 viously derived from painstaking investigations. Their 
 further justification, if necessary, was left to the work 
 of rebuttal. Debaters should learn that audiences, 
 though they expect accuracy, do not take kindly to 
 dull statistics or needless facts. All imaged concepts 
 which are conclusions from previous investigations must 
 of course be logical reasons for believing in the main 
 proposition. 
 
 A timely illustration may be found in a passage from 
 Fisher Ames, setting forth in sympathetic language the 
 sanctity of treaties: 
 
 What is patriotism? Is it a narrow affection for the spot 
 where a man was born? Are the very clods where we tread 
 entitled to this ardent preference because they are greener? 
 No, sir, this is not the character of the virtue, and it soars higher 
 for its object. It is an extended self-love, mingling with all the 
 enjoyments of life, and twisting itself with the minutest filaments 
 of the heart. It is thus we obey the laws of society, because 
 they are the laws of virtue. In their authority we see, not the 
 array of force and terror, but the venerable image of our coun- 
 try's honor. Every good citizen makes that honor his own, and 
 cherishes it not only as precious, but as sacred. He is willing 
 to risk his life in its defense, and is conscious that he gains pro- 
 tection while he gives it. For, what rights of a citizen will be 
 deemed inviolable when a state renounces the principles that 
 constitute their security? Or if his Hfe should not be invaded, 
 what would its enjoyments be in a country odious in the eyes of 
 strangers and dishonored in his own? Could he look with affec-
 
 172 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 tion and veneration to such a country as his parent ? The sense 
 of having one would die within him; he would blush for his 
 patriotism, if he retained any, and justly, for it would be a vice. 
 He would be a banished man in his native land. I see no ex- 
 ception to the respect that is paid among nations to the law of 
 good faith. If there are cases in this enlightened period when 
 it is violated, there are none when it is decried. It is the phi- 
 losophy of politics, the religion of governments. It is observed 
 by barbarians — a whiff of tobacco smoke, or a string of beads, 
 gives not merely binding force but sanctity to treaties. Even 
 in Algiers, a truce may be bought for money, but when ratified, 
 even Algiers is too wise, or too just, to disown and annul its 
 obligation. Thus we see, neither the ignorance of savages, nor 
 the principles of an association for piracy and rapine, permit a 
 nation to despise its engagements. If, sir, there could be a resur- 
 rection from the foot of the gallows, if the victims of justice 
 could live again, collect together and form a society, they would, 
 however loath, soon find themselves obliged to make justice, 
 that justice under which they fell, the fundamental law of their 
 state. They would perceive, it was their interest to make others 
 respect, and they would therefore soon pay some respect them- 
 selves, to the obligations of good faith. 
 
 4. Imaging Affection and Desire. — Just as concepts 
 may be regarded as generalized percepts, so the emo- 
 tions may be regarded as generalized feelings or sen- 
 sations. There are, of course, intuitive ideas such as 
 religious feelings, but all concepts, whether emotional 
 or intellectual and in whatever way derived, may be 
 suggestively imaged. Concepts such as joy, sorrow, 
 hope, mercy, love, have so decided an emotional con- 
 notation that they are commonly regarded as emotional 
 concepts, but even they may be imaged intellectually. 
 
 Everything of importance in experience, over which 
 men differ and about which they argue, has a basis in 
 human feelings and human wants. It is almost impos- 
 sible to eliminate our feelings and wishes when arguing
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 173 
 
 on matters of conduct or policy. For example, Webster's 
 argument for the Union was not only a constitutional 
 justification of his position, but an appeal to the grow- 
 ing desire of the people to become a nation. LikcAvise, 
 in the debate on S%\'iss preparedness for America alluded 
 to above, both sides admitted and made incidental 
 appeal to the feeling for an adequate defense of America. 
 Too often, however, we image our likes and dislikes in 
 a self-deceived rationalism. We are so constituted that 
 it often seems that all that is needed to secure support 
 for a proposition is a reasoned groundwork for a de- 
 sired action. A mere bauble dangled before the eyes 
 of a child will prompt the desire to reach for it. What 
 we feel an impulse to do, we are apt to feel is justified 
 in reason; what we like, we are apt to approve; what 
 we dislike, to disapprove. And so an argument is pre- 
 sented for approval and disapproval. At all events, 
 the coincidence of reason and desire may be needed to 
 secure a fully satisfied judgment and a confident ac- 
 tion. Argument may exist without desire, it cannot 
 exist without reason. Argument is primarily intellec- 
 tual in aim and method. 
 
 Daniel Webster's address to the supreme court of 
 Massachusetts in 1817, in defense of the Kennistons, is 
 noted for its simplicity and vital directness of style. 
 The following extract contains only a few words of 
 slight emotional suggestion: 
 
 From the time of the robbery to the arrest, five or six weeks, 
 the defendants were engaged in their usual occupations. They 
 are not found to have passed a dollar of money to anybody. 
 They continued their ordinary habits of labor. No man saw 
 money about them, nor any circumstance that might lead to a 
 suspicion that they had money. Nothing occurred tending in
 
 174 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 any degree to excite suspicion against them. When arrested, and 
 when all this array of evidence was brought against them, and 
 when they could hope in nothing but their innocence, immunity 
 was offered them again if they would confess. They were 
 pressed, and urged, and allured, by every motive which could 
 be set before them, to acknowledge their participation in the 
 offense, and to bring out their accompUces. They steadily pro- 
 tested that they could confess nothing because they knew noth- 
 ing. In defiance of all the discoveries made in their house, they 
 have trusted to their innocence. On that, and on the candor 
 and discernment of an enlightened jury, they still rely. 
 
 It is in the perorations of arguments or debates, how- 
 ever, that we usually find emotional concepts imaged 
 with undisguised directness for the purpose of awakening 
 feeling and securing action— e. g., the desire for hap- 
 piness, the wish to avoid unhappiness, the hope of suc- 
 cess, the dread of failure, or the binding obUgations of 
 duty — all, of course, as appHcable to the thesis attacked 
 or defended. An illustration from a modem jury ad- 
 dress may perhaps be taken as typical. After analyzing 
 the evidence and recapitulating with great clearness, 
 Mr. Henry L. CHnton concluded thus: 
 
 Gentlemen, I have now discharged my duty— my duty to 
 my cHent, my duty to you, my duty to my own conscience. The 
 responsibility of this case is with you. Do your duty. There 
 is no enjoyment so great, no consolation so sweet, as the con- 
 sciousness of duty performed. With entire confidence I commit 
 my client to your hands. Though you obey the stern behests 
 of duty and acquit him promptly, you cannot undo the injury 
 done him through the instrumentality of that wife whose vows 
 at the holy altar to love and honor him he fondly believed would 
 guide her, as he determined that his vows should guide him, 
 until death. Hereafter, though he may live a Hfe of spotless 
 purity, though he may practise every virtue known to man, 
 though in aU the relations of life he be without fault, or the
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 175 
 
 semblance of fault — in a word, though his whole future life be 
 the incarnation of every excellence, of even absolute moral per- 
 fection, yet hereafter his enemies will be too ready to proclaim 
 that his wife charged him with this crime, and that he was tried 
 upon the charge. And, gentlemen, let it be added that a jury 
 of twelve upright, intelligent, conscientious citizens of West- 
 chester County, mindful of their oaths to render a true verdict 
 according to the evidence, pronounced him "Not Guilty!" 
 
 5. Imaging in a Team Debate. — In the training of a 
 debating team, the case may be first separated into 
 several main ideas. And then after the facts are all 
 gathered and the arguments formulated, the real prob- 
 lem of presentation is— how to image most effectively 
 these main ideas or concepts, with essential matters of 
 proof, on the minds of the audience. With an exact 
 knowledge of the facts and of the work to be done by 
 each debater, the latter must now bridge the chasm be- 
 tween subjective library work and adjusted objective 
 presentation. He must, with all the power that imagi- 
 nation can siunmon, conceive his audience and apply his 
 technic. 
 
 If he is to present his arguments with success, he must 
 take special pains to image effectively his fundamental 
 concepts or reasons. Moreover, all imagery of such 
 fundamental concepts must be accurate and interesting. 
 They will be accurate if they are consistent with the 
 things to which they refer in nature, history, conduct, 
 or affairs, and are also consistent with one another. The 
 student who has carefully put his arguments into the 
 form of a brief, it is beUeved, will usually speak with 
 accuracy. His reasons are likely to be interesting if 
 they are really suggestive to his Usteners. 
 
 In a debate on the adoption of the Swiss military
 
 176 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 system of compulsory service for the United States, 
 the negative, speaking at Princeton, imaged the absence 
 of any necessity for it thus : 
 
 Consider the position of Switzerland, one of the smallest of 
 sovereign states, with an area of about fifteen thousand square 
 miles — just twice the size of this State of New Jersey — with a 
 population less than that of our single city of New York. Switzer- 
 land's largest city is but half again the size of our neighboring 
 metropolis of Trenton. She is, moreover, surrounded by four 
 warlike and powerful neighbors, France, Germany, Austria, 
 and Italy, with a combined war strength of over eighteen million. 
 We are a powerful state with thirty times the population of 
 Switzerland. Instead of being surrounded by dangerous rivals, 
 we are supreme upon two continents. It is absurd to suppose 
 that a people so blessed by fortune in strength and location 
 should be forced to make sacrifices in proportion to those neces- 
 sary in a tiny state whose situation is as unfavorable as ours is 
 favorable. 
 
 The size of the vast army was imaged thus: 
 
 Under the Swiss system about eleven million would be trained 
 and liable to service. But the numbers are the astonishing 
 thing — eleven million trained men in the United States. Do 
 you fully grasp the enormity of these figures ? Can you conjure 
 up even in the wildest flight of your imagination a situation in 
 which we would need such a force? Do we contemplate con- 
 quering the world? A force this size would be larger than the 
 combined total trained strength of both Germany and Russia 
 at the outbreak of the present war. New York State alone would 
 have a force more than two-thirds the size of the war strength 
 of Japan. Illinois, eight hundred miles from any coast, would 
 have a force of seven hundred thousand trained men. 
 
 The affirmative endeavored to offset this by imaging 
 the magnitude of our ideals and of our country thus: 
 
 We are the greatest democracy in the world. Our miUtary 
 system must therefore be democratic in every sense of the word. 
 It must recognize the fundamental duty of every citizen of a 
 democracy to defend his nation. We are proud of the fact that
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 177 
 
 our system provides a large reserve force. We are proud be- 
 cause we are proud of the magnitude of our country, of her enor- 
 mous wealth and resources. It is idle to speak of our national 
 defense in terms of thousands when we have three millions of 
 square miles of area, one hundred millions of population, and 
 two hundred billions of resources. Cahfornia is three times as 
 large as England; all Germany could be put in Wyoming and 
 Colorado. We have ten thousand miles of boundary, vulnerable 
 at almost every point. Does the negative hope to protect such 
 a country with a few hundred thousand men? 
 
 Modern wars are fought in terms of millions, and nations 
 employ not only one army but several armies; we must face 
 these conditions. How does the negative expect to defend both 
 Boston and San Francisco against invading armies? And yet 
 it is quite possible that both shores will be attacked by a power- 
 ful alliance. How would they protect both the Canadian and 
 the Mexican borders, or either alone, with a few hundred thou- 
 sand soldiers? Your army must be either concentrated or scat- 
 tered; if concentrated, what enemy would be so foolish as to 
 attack at the point of concentration? If scattered, what sort 
 of resistance force could it give at the point of attack? We 
 must face the issue squarely; half-way measures will not do. 
 Modern wars are fought on a large scale; our protection must 
 also be on a large scale. Such protection will be much more 
 than preparedness for war: it will be the best possible prepara- 
 tion for peace. 
 
 Verily, in debate, there may be a battle of imagery 
 as well as of arguments. Moreover, the affirmative used 
 the preceding as a prelude to showing that the cost of 
 such an army of 11,000,000 men would not be excessive, 
 but would be an insurance premium of less than one- 
 tenth of one per cent on our two hundred billion of re- 
 sources. (Analogy.) 
 
 For vividness and directness, note further the imagery 
 of the following shorter passages: 
 
 You ask what we would think of a fire-engine which reached 
 a fire six months after the fire had started. That is not the ques-
 
 178 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 tion. I ask what you would think of a fire department which 
 pumped water on a fire two years after the fire was out. 
 
 In fact, with conditions in the two countries so diametrically 
 reversed, we might just as well advocate the American plan 
 for the Swiss navy as the Swiss plan for the American army. 
 
 The average American does not consider digging a trench 
 under a blazing hot sun a recreation or a pleasure. 
 
 A sudden blow at this vital and exposed organ (New York) 
 might well prove fatal. 
 
 The European nations will not come forth bled white. 
 
 No eagle scream of patriotism. 
 
 Would you have American patriotism carry the millstone of 
 compulsory service about its neck? 
 
 In debating, an aphorism, epigram, paradox, meta- 
 phor — especially any vivid image of likeness or unlike- 
 ness — will often make extended proof unnecessary. It 
 may not only arrest the attention and quicken the in- 
 terest, but may awaken old and familiar associations, 
 give the mind the challenge of a new idea, flood the 
 consciousness with feelings, or decide the will. Mere 
 phrases are potent psychological instruments used by 
 a debater to make clear and obvious the perception of 
 a truth so that it can be easily understood, identified, 
 accepted, by a hearer and carried in memory. 
 
 6. Imaging in General. — Accuracy and interest are, 
 perhaps, the chief characteristics of effective imagery. 
 Interest is the cause of attention. Given an idea, there 
 is no better way of arousing interest in it than by use 
 of vital illustrations, no better practice for the student 
 than that of searching for illustrative material which 
 will start the Hstener's mind to tliinking in connection 
 with the idea advanced. 
 
 The moving scene which Lincoln draws of the grow- 
 ing "bondage of the negro" suggests to the mind a situa-
 
 lAI AGINATION IN ARGUMENT 179 
 
 tion which no constitutional argument could ever con- 
 fute: 
 
 43- 
 
 Mammon is after him, ambition follows, philosophy follows, 
 and the theology of the day is fast joining the cry. They have 
 him in his prison-house; they have searched his person, and 
 left no prying instrument with him. One after another they 
 have closed the heavy iron doors upon him; and now they have 
 him, as it were, bolted in with a lock of a hundred keys, which 
 can never be unlocked without the concurrence of every key — 
 the keys in the hands of a hundred different men and they 
 scattered to a hundred different and distant places; and they 
 stand musing as to what invention, in all the dominions of mind 
 and matter, can be produced to make the impossibility of his 
 escape more complete than it is. 
 
 A narrative example of the power of imagery through 
 suggestion is that of the Master, in Saint Matthew: 
 
 Therefore, whosoever heareth these sayings of mine and doeth 
 them, I will liken him unto a wise man, which built his house 
 upon a rock; and the rain descended and the floods came and 
 the winds blew and beat upon that house, and it fell not; for 
 it was founded upon a rock. 
 
 And every one that heareth these sayings of mine, and doeth 
 them not, shall be likened unto a foolish man which built his 
 house upon the sand; and the rain descended and the floods 
 came, and the winds blew and beat upon that house, and it fell; 
 and great was the fall of it. 
 
 The images here are made more vivid through the 
 use of contrast and skilful repetition. The assumed 
 resemblances and contrast, too, are easily recognized 
 and accepted. Their real force, of course, is due to the 
 great Authority who uttered them. 
 
 "Suppose, sir," says Burke, "that the angel of this auspicious 
 youth (Lord Bathurst) . . . had appeared to him in vision, . . .
 
 180 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 and should tell him: 'Young man, there is America which at this 
 day serves for little more than to amuse you with stories of savage 
 men and uncouth manners; yet shall, before you taste of death, 
 show itself equal to the whole of that commerce which now at- 
 tracts the envy of the world. Whatever England has been grow- 
 ing to ... in a series of 1700 years, you shall see as much added 
 to her in the course of a single life ! ' Fortunate man, he has lived 
 to see it." 
 
 This supposed case has no argumentative value. The 
 older rhetoricians would have called it vision, a figure 
 of emphasis. The final statement that he had "lived 
 to see it" brings it back to reality. Burke, you re- 
 member, had already cited comparative tables showing 
 the export trade of England and of her colonies in 1704 
 and in 1772. 
 
 Individual or concrete instances are often used to 
 make plain a general statement, and have a special in- 
 terest when they lie within the listener's experience: 
 
 Political economy consists simply in the production, preserva- 
 tion, and distribution, at fittest time and place, of useful, 
 pleasurable things. The farmer who cuts his hay at the right 
 time; the shipwright who drives his bolts well home in sound 
 wood; the builder who lays good bricks in well-tempered mortar; 
 the housewife who takes care of the furniture in her parlor, and 
 guards against all waste in her kitchen; and the singer who 
 rightly disciplines and never overstrains her voice are all polit- 
 ical economists in the true and final sense; adding continually 
 to the riches and well-being of the nation to which they be- 
 long. — {Ruskin.) 
 
 Finally, observe the effect of the linguistic strokes 
 of Senator Thurston in his speech preceding our war 
 with Spain. He introduces the theme — "God's force" — 
 by a sorites or chain of reasoning in the first three sen-
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 181 
 
 tences. Then notice how he gains something more than 
 unity and clearness by repeating "force" as the subject 
 of each clause in the second paragraph. And note par- 
 ticularly, how from this subject numerous and varied 
 illustrations radiate. No fatigue or loss of attention, 
 but kaleidoscopic change of thought and a gradual in- 
 crease of interest. When, at the end, the music and 
 drum-beat stop, we are left with the sensation audibly 
 evoked, that God is marching on: 
 
 Intervention means force. Force means war. War means 
 blood. But it will be God's force. When has a battle for hu- 
 manity and liberty ever been won except by force? What bar- 
 ricade of wrong, injustice, and oppression has ever been carried 
 except by force? 
 
 Force compelled the signature of unwilling royalty to the 
 great Magna Charta; force put life into the Declaration of In- 
 dependence, and made effective the Emancipation Proclama- 
 tion; force beat with naked hands upon the iron gateway of 
 the Bastille and made reprisal in one awful hour for centuries 
 of kingly crime; force waved the flag of revolution over Bunker 
 Hill and marked the snows of Valley Forge with blood-stained 
 feet; force held the broken line at Shiloh, climbed the flame- 
 swept hill at Chattanooga, and stormed the clouds on Lookout 
 Heights; force marched with Sherman to the sea, rode with 
 Sheridan in the valley of Shenandoah, and gave Grant victory 
 at Appomattox; force saved the Union, kept the stars in the 
 flag, made "niggers" men. The time for God's force has come 
 again. Let the impassioned lips of American patriots once more 
 take up the song: 
 
 "In the beauty of the lilies Christ was born across the sea, 
 With a glory in His bosom that transfigures you and me; 
 As he died to make men holy, let us die to make men free, 
 For God is marching on." 
 
 Logic makes clear only to him who is interested and 
 will follow. The trouble with logic is its monotone,
 
 182 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 which, if long continued, produces fatigue. We need 
 variety to rest and stimulate the attention. 
 
 Concrete suggestions, such as the imagery of speech 
 figures, parables, fables, allusive stories or anecdotes 
 used to point a moral — analogies, drawn from history, 
 literature, science, art, religion, or from every-day Hfe — 
 may be used to enrich and fertilize barren places, to 
 illuminate dull themes, or when occasion arises to raise 
 the winds like Prosper©, and if need be to cause the 
 waters to subside as they did at the Red Sea. An en- 
 cyclopaedic knowledge without the power of association, 
 without the impelling desire to bring facts together and 
 weave them into new creations for the purpose of in- 
 fluencing thought and action, is a pump that holds water 
 but does not give it out, a fourteen-inch-gun that will 
 not go off, a football or debating team, an army, that 
 goes down to defeat when it might have the power to 
 triumph. 
 
 The Advantage of the Conceptual View-Point to 
 the Debater. — The debater may regard any process or 
 proposition as a concept for the purpose of imagery, 
 and may exhibit all the arts of rhetoric when attempting 
 to suggest the image of a concept to the minds of his 
 audience. 
 
 After a thorough work in briefing, which involves a 
 careful analysis, discrimination, classification, and ar- 
 rangement of his material, the debater will often find 
 it of advantage to sum up the main proposition of his 
 speech in a single abstract word or phrase significant 
 of meaning to himself. In a team debate, the case as 
 a whole may be summed up in several such words, as, 
 e. g., democracy, security, permanency; causes, examples, 
 consequences, etc. These concepts, of course, must
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 183 
 
 contain the fundamental reasons for the proposition to 
 be proved, and the imaging of them must be the imaging 
 of fundamental reasons. 
 
 This broad conceptual view-point, moreover, should 
 give the debater the free hand needed for a suggestive, 
 imaginative, handling of his material. Confident in 
 the logical structure of his argument, and of his knowl- 
 edge of facts and material, he is less constrained in the 
 use of his own processes. He can also make his processes 
 and conclusions more perceptual to others. He can, for 
 instance, adjust his imagery to his audience, and to re- 
 sponses received while speaking, and can continue in 
 his imaginative suggestions until the responses noticed 
 indicate that his idea is understood and accepted. In 
 a word, the adoption of the conceptual view-point by 
 the logically trained student means freedom in the imag- 
 ing process and in adaptation; and this means effec- 
 tiveness. For the debater is thus enabled to give to 
 his logical formulas detailed or expansive content, as 
 occasion may require, to express his own individuality, 
 to introduce a sincere, natural, personal touch, and to 
 instil into his remarks atmosphere and reality. Facts 
 and logic are made to appeal to human interest in ex- 
 perience and consciousness. 
 
 III. Types of Imagery 
 
 We are familiar with the fact that there is a classifica- 
 tion of imagery made on the basis of the senses employed 
 (see Perceptual Aspect of Imagery, this chapter). The 
 types of imagery so based are considered further in 
 Appendix B. 
 
 In conclusion, we should note that there is also a divi- 
 sion of imagery based on past, present, and future.
 
 184 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 Moreover, images of the past are of two kinds : memory 
 images and imagination images. Memory images call 
 to mind specific, actual experiences in the life of an au- 
 dience. All other images are products of the creative 
 imagination and are called imagination images of the 
 past, present, or future. A twenty-six-year-old general, 
 speaking in Italy, used Memory Images and Images of 
 the Future as a means of inspiring confidence, courage, 
 and hope in his men in the following proclamation: 
 
 Soldiers, you have, in fifteen days, gained six victories, taken 
 twenty-one stands of colors, fifty pieces of cannon, several forti- 
 fied places, made fifteen hundred prisoners, and killed or wounded 
 over ten thousand men. You are the equals of the conquerors 
 of Holland and of the Rhine. Destitute of everything, you have 
 supplied yourselves with everything. You have won battles 
 without cannon, crossed rivers without bridges, made forced 
 marches without shoes, bivouacked without spirituous hquor 
 and often without bread. The repubhcan phalanxes, the sol- 
 diers of liberty, were alone capable of enduring what you 
 have suffered. Thanks to you, soldiers ! Your country has a 
 right to expect of you great things. You have still battles to 
 fight, cities to take, rivers to pass. Is there one amongst you 
 whose courage flags? One, who would prefer returning to the 
 sterile summits of the Apennines and the Alps, to undergo pa- 
 tiently the insults of that slavish soldiery? No, there is not 
 one such among the victors of Montenotte, of Millesimo, of 
 Diego and of Mondovi ! Friends, I promise you that glorious 
 conquest: but be the liberators of peoples, be not their scourges. ^ 
 
 Not always, of course, are the emotions and will so 
 dominant as here with Napoleon. Indeed, a sweet 
 reasonableness and a quiet library calm are better 
 adapted to the average occasion and the mood of the 
 
 ^ " The Orators of France," by Timon, translated by J. T. Headley, 
 p. 80.
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 185 
 
 average person. It is a better way to sell bonds or in- 
 surance, or to adjust the price when buying a house and 
 lot. 
 
 Or, we may refer in illustration to the twenty-third 
 Psalm. The effect of this beautiful lyric is a feeling of 
 sympathy with David's confidence: 
 
 1. As he recalls the contentment of green pastures (imagina- 
 
 tion image of the past). 
 
 2. As he suggests the spiritual comfort which he experiences, 
 
 with God actually present by his side. "For Thou art 
 with me" (immediate image), and 
 
 3. As he exclaims in Faith and Hope, "I will dwell in the 
 
 house of the Lord forever" (imagination image of the 
 future). 
 
 The ability to suggest to the consciousness of an au- 
 dience scenes, events, and happenings of the past, or to 
 prophesy the future consequences of a proposed plan, 
 policy, or course of action is constantly demanded of 
 the debater. In the reply to Ha3aie, Webster's eulqgy 
 of his own State is an imagination image of the past, 
 while his description of the consequences of disunion 
 is an imagination image of the future. Indeed, whether 
 the image used is an image of past or future, of imagina- 
 tion or of memory, the debater must manifest his logical, 
 psychological, and artistic skill. He is more likely per- 
 haps to "ride the winged horse" when imaging the 
 future, as, for example, when he is describing in his per- 
 oration the consequences of the organization of a society 
 of nations to enforce peace after the war. 
 
 Since the word "present" may mean an hour, a day, 
 a year, a decade, or a century, the length of time sug- 
 gested by an image of the present will vary with cir-
 
 186 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 cmTistances. Images of the present refer to happenings 
 in the more or less remote present as distinguished from 
 past or future. 
 
 In the most limited sense, however, the present exists 
 only as a nexus between past and future. We no sooner 
 utter the word "now" than it is gone. The present 
 in which we live is ever moving; what is thought to be 
 with us is with us only in a world of motion. There is 
 only a theoretical present, consisting of the moment of 
 time in which we are thinking; and there is always, of 
 course, the possibility of shutting out both the past and 
 the future for an absorbing contemplation of that which 
 is immediately before us in time and space. We may, 
 therefore, in a sense regard all effective images as present 
 images; so that the function both of images of the past 
 and of the future is simply to bring to the focus of im- 
 mediate attention the other experiences of other times. 
 Moreover, the creative imagination through the infinite 
 suggestions and implications of imagery simply brings, 
 with a conscious or subconscious logic, other experiences 
 to bear on a matter at hand. 
 
 Summary. — The present chapter calls attention, first, 
 to the need of the imagination in argument. This is 
 believed to be necessary, on account of the dangers aris- 
 ing from an overemphasis of the logical, and is believed 
 to be desirable because of the opportunity for origmal- 
 ity afforded, and the resulting higher degree of excel- 
 lence attainable, through the use of the imaginative 
 powers. It sets forth, second, the character and function 
 of the imaging process in argument; distmguishing be- 
 tween the logical and psychological view-points from 
 which an argument may be regarded; and explaining 
 the processes other than the logical which are employed.
 
 IMAGINATION IN ARGUMENT 187 
 
 It appears that in presenting an argument a debater 
 may exercise his creative imagination, and may use 
 the skill of the real hterary artist, if he wdsely allows 
 himself a greater freedom in his mental point of view- 
 when speaking or writing. Imagery is also shown to 
 have both a perceptual and a conceptual aspect, and 
 the problem of communicating our ideas to others in 
 order to image them on their consciousness is declared 
 to be a process of reducing concepts to sense-percep- 
 tion. Assuming, then, that argument is the perceptuali- 
 zation of a concept, the process of imaging a concept is 
 illustrated variously and at length, logically and broadly, 
 and applied to debating and general use. Third, the 
 last topic, types of imagery, suggests the wide scope 
 of the imaging power through its ability to bring to 
 immediate perception images of the past, present, and 
 future.
 
 CHAPTER VII 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 
 
 We have defined the presentation as a problem in im- 
 aginative suggestion, and have examined the imagina- 
 tion from the standpoint of the speaker. We are now 
 to examine the subject of suggestion (which is the other 
 side of imagery) as the process and means of communi- 
 cating our ideas to others. This carries us into the dif- 
 ficult territory of the hearer, for suggestion is to be 
 defined in terms of response, effect, or reaction. 
 
 Argument, it may be said, is an appeal, through the 
 imagery of words and gestures, for immediate and strong 
 response; and makes use either of the concealed, indirect 
 methods of persuasion, or the open and consciously log- 
 ical method of conviction. Our immediate purpose is to 
 assist the debater to an understanding of the mental op- 
 erations by which the decisions in argument are consci- 
 ously or subconsciously reached. The present discus- 
 sion, therefore, is restricted to two topics: (i) The laws 
 of mental suggestion and their use in debating, and (2) 
 the instruments of suggestion as applied to the delivery 
 and rhetoric of argument. Gestures, voice, and manner 
 are images of ideas used to convey meaning to others 
 and are, therefore, instruments of suggestion. Words, 
 sentences, paragraphs, whole compositions are also 
 images of ideas used to convey meaning, and likewise 
 must be regarded as instruments of suggestion. 
 
 188
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 189 
 
 I. Laws of Suggestion and Their Use in Debating 
 
 The Laws of Mental Suggestion proclaim the dynamic 
 power of the image to produce response. They assert 
 the tendency of the mind to act in line with a suggested 
 idea unless interfered with by a contrary or inhibiting 
 idea. They have been summed up in two definite state- 
 ments, as laws, thus: 
 
 1. Every idea of an action (or function) will result in that 
 action unless hindered by a competing idea or physical impedi- 
 ment. 
 
 2. Every idea that is suggested to the mind is held as truth 
 unless inhibited by some contradictory idea. 
 
 The value of these laws for the speaker depends chiefly 
 on '' limiting the consciousness of the minds of the hearers 
 to the idea suggested, and the avoidance of the ideas 
 in their minds which invaHdate or hinder the idea sug- 
 gested." 1 
 
 Let us, in explanation, start with the simple fact that 
 when a speaker images an idea so that it can be visuaHzed 
 by another, the suggested image awakens in the hearer 
 a mental activity in a particular direction (i) of think- 
 ing, e. g., What? Hark! If— but; and (2) also in a 
 particular direction of acting, e. g., "Do you see that 
 sign? " prompting one to turn his head in the direction 
 of a spot indicated. 
 
 The second law is recognized in the popular idea of 
 "beheving what we are told," and of "accepting as true 
 what we see in print." 
 
 On the other hand, when a hearer does not follow 
 out a suggested idea either in his thinking or his acting 
 1 "Psychology of Public Speaking," W. D. Scott, p. 156.
 
 190 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 or does not believe something that he is told or sees in 
 print, it is because of obstacles rising in that mind in 
 the shape of inhibitions to compete with or interfere 
 with the carrying out of the process. 
 
 In general, it is apparent that any vivid image of an 
 idea or action tends to produce a quick and strong re- 
 sponse in others. The clever advertiser endeavors to 
 make his suggestions compelling, thus: 
 
 1. Go to the Big Store. 
 
 2. Visit the store you have always visited. 
 
 3. Everybody goes to the Big Store. 
 
 4. Bargains at the Big Store. 
 
 5. The Patriotic Store. 
 
 If you will examine these statements a Uttle closely, 
 you will notice that there is an attempt to make the 
 mind go forward in thinking about the store, through the 
 responses given to a command, and through appeals to 
 habit, imitation, opportunity of advantage, and finally, 
 I may say, to ideahsm. There was also an expectation 
 on the part of the advertiser, that the idea so vividly 
 fixed in the thinking, will be accepted as truth by the 
 reader, and that we may become sufficiently interested 
 in what the store may hold out for us to inchne us to 
 find out more about it. Vividness, frequency, and 
 recency are psychological principles, of which those 
 who are most successful make constant use. 
 
 It will be noticed, however, that the first statement, 
 " Go to the Big Store," is not so much the imaging of 
 an idea which can be regarded as a reason, as the imag- 
 ing of a command to action. All the other sentences 
 contain a vivid imagery of reasons. The orator, like 
 the advertiser, may appeal openly for action, but the
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 191 
 
 debater cannot do so unless his appeal for action is well 
 grounded in an imaging of reasons. 
 
 The debater's problem, indeed, is more difficult than 
 either that of the orator or the advertiser. For he no 
 sooner suggests his own case than an opponent seeks 
 to inhibit it and to suggest another of his own. In the 
 privacy of his study, he may have placed his argument 
 in a secure, logical form by which he hopes to start and 
 give direction to the thinking — 
 
 Proposition because 
 
 A since 
 
 I for 
 
 a 
 
 But practically and in action, he finds that his sug- 
 gested ideas are in constant conflict with others. They 
 may come, indeed, not only from his visible opponent 
 but also from his audience to block, retard, or change 
 the direction of his ideas, as well as to faciUtate them. 
 Such inhibitions and suggestions may spring from the 
 ill-defined regions of the subconscious, as well as from 
 the better known or conscious experiences. Let us illus- 
 trate. 
 
 In an expressed argument, the debater at the out- 
 set suggests the proper mental attitude of his audience 
 toward the proposition as he sees it by such phrases as 
 "I propose to show," *'I commend," "I approve," which 
 inclines the minds of his hearers in the desired direc- 
 tion. Then an opponent takes the floor and inhibits 
 the thinking and leads it in another direction with "I 
 object," "I oppose," "I hesitate," ''I fear." And then, 
 one speaker will tell us, for example, that the United 
 States should not enter a league to enforce peace after
 
 192 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 the war by a reminder of Washington's warning against 
 foreign alliances. This is primarily an appeal to au- 
 thority, but there may be in it also a hidden appeal, 
 for Washington is an authority whom we habitually 
 accept and whom we like to imitate. An opposing 
 speaker then reminds us that "President Wilson and 
 former Presidents Taf t and Roosevelt are all in favor of 
 our joining such a league." We have now raised a doubt 
 as to the wisdom of Washington's advice, and intro- 
 duced into the mind a new notion involving conflicting 
 authority and incidentally, and, perhaps, subconsciously, 
 appeals to habit and imitation. And so the problem 
 deepens and continues. Indeed, whether we are de- 
 bating with ourselves or with others, or merely listening 
 to a debate, the mind is continually facilitating and 
 retarding our initial suggestions by other suggestions 
 or inhibitions of its own, so that there may be a con- 
 stant vacillation between a feeling of certainty and 
 doubt until a decision is definitely reached. 
 
 This, then, is the nature of the process and the ma- 
 terial on which the debater must impress his views; 
 active, living minds, with varying antecedent experi- 
 ences, and differing present capacities, operations, atti- 
 tudes, and views. He naturally strives to win the good- 
 will, sympathy, and confidence of his hearers in order 
 to get their co-operation; he also strives to find a 
 common ground, in thought as well as in feeling — real, 
 vital grounds of belief. But he may fail, unless he is 
 able, through insight and imaginative power, to get 
 within the inner circle of the consciousness of his hearers, 
 in order to interest them and to set them to thinking, 
 so that their minds will naturally and of themselves go 
 forward in the proper direction.
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 193 
 
 The debater's primary responses are in interest and 
 in belief. Indeed, the first law of mental suggestion, 
 given above, as applied to debating, seems to assert 
 the need of interest; and the second law, the need of 
 proof, if the suggested idea is to be held in the mind as 
 a truth more than temporarily, and not brushed aside 
 by an immediate denial or contradiction. 
 
 1. Interest is a prerequisite of all successful speaking 
 or writing. The factors of interestingness have been 
 variously described, and are said to include such things 
 as the vital, the unusual, the uncertain, the sunilar, 
 the antagonistic, and the animate.^ 
 
 In general, anything which will attract the listener's 
 mind and incHne it to think for itself about the reasons 
 given, is of value in securing and holding interest when 
 presenting an argument. The responsive is the interest- 
 ing. 
 
 2. The nature of proof has been considered under 
 logical organization. It was shown that an effective 
 argument should be imaged within an accepted class 
 concept of a hearer, so as to bring it within his experi- 
 ence. Professor Phillips points out the great value of 
 the principle of reference to experience, — 
 
 because it enables the speaker to attain his purpose along the 
 right psychological line — that of allowing the listener to use 
 his own powers. The use of this principle gives the Hstener 
 or reader the pleasant feeling that he is not driven or cajoled, 
 but that he sees, feels, accepts, or does the thing desired of his 
 own free will and through his own processes. To illustrate: 
 When my friend entered his home the sky was cloudless. An 
 hour later I come in and say there will be a storm. He contra- 
 dicts me. I then tell him that heavy black clouds are rolling 
 
 1 "Effective Speaking," Phillips, A.B., p. 6^.
 
 194 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 up from the west, that flashes of lightning can be seen and that 
 the wind is increasing. He now agrees with me. What did I 
 do? I gave him three facts that were Uke his own experience 
 in respect to the conditions generally preceding a storm. He 
 came to his own conclusion by means of my reference to his 
 experience. I simply called up part of his stock of knowledge 
 applicable to the case, he did the rest. I recalled to his conscious- 
 ness some of his subconscious knowledge. I held up to him 
 the mirror of his own experience, and he himself came to the 
 conclusion. 
 
 He notes further, that, when the end is belief, as in 
 argument, it is very important to show that the mat- 
 ter in question is like something we already believe. 
 "BeHef, then, demands references to experience that 
 show the thing for which acceptance is sought, is like 
 something already accepted as truth — reahty. And 
 the most powerful reference will be that accepted ac- 
 tuality wliich most resembles the thing to be believed." 
 Not only likeness, however, but all the principles of 
 association, likeness and unlikeness, cause and effect, 
 or the inclusion of the thing offered within a more gen- 
 eral principle or class concept already known or ac- 
 cepted. For there is great variation among men in their 
 modes of associating ideas. As Doctor McCosh has 
 noted: "One mind ever tends to repetition, another 
 rather to correlation. One man delights in poetical 
 images, another in scientific classes of causes. One in- 
 tellect is inclined to observe resemblances, another ex- 
 ceptions and differences." We must, however, make our 
 suggestions along the proper psychological lines — em- 
 ploying so far as we can the processes, facts, and man- 
 ner that a hearer would most likely be able to follow. 
 
 Avoiding and Removing Inhibitions. — A few specific, 
 practical suggestions may be given, namely: (i) That
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 195 
 
 a speaker should not inhibit his own case by hurtful 
 admissions; (2) that in an actual debate the inliibitions 
 introduced by an opponent should be removed at the 
 earliest opportunity; (3) that logical fallacies may act 
 as inhibitions, and (4) that an inhibiting wish, always 
 difficult to handle, may sometimes be removed by the 
 image ad ahsurdum. 
 
 1. Hurtful Admissions as Inhibitions. — In the nature 
 of things, the debater cannot keep inhibiting ideas from 
 entering the mind of his audience, for assertion is met 
 by denial, proof by counter-proof or distinctions. 
 
 He must, in the first place, avoid introducing inhibit- 
 ing ideas himself into his own argument. Indeed, if 
 they are unconsciously permitted to enter, they may be 
 regarded as hurtful admissions and made the basis of 
 attack as in the following: 
 
 GERMAN DECEPTIVE EXPERIENCES 
 
 The phrase is from the Berlin Kreuz-Zeitung. It was report- 
 ing the chancellor's belief that the submarine campaign would 
 end the war quickly, and said: "We must hasten. Five or six 
 months will suffice." But then it added, perhaps with more 
 significance than it was aware of: "God grant that we do not 
 renew with our submarines our deceptive experiences with Zep- 
 pelins." 
 
 2. Immediate Removal of Inhibitions Introduced by an 
 Opponent. — The debater should also, in the second place, 
 remove inhibiting ideas which have been introduced 
 by an opponent the instant he has the opportunity. When 
 Patrick Henry made his famous remark, "Caesar had 
 his Brutus, Charles the First his Cromwell, and George 
 the Third — " he was interrupted, it will be remembered, 
 by cries of "Treason"; but equal to the occasion he
 
 196 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 defiantly answered: "If that be treason make the most 
 of it." Though the inhibited idea was permitted to 
 enter, it was quickly expelled. An objection raised by 
 an opponent is, of course, an inhibiting idea and will 
 hinder the acceptance of new arguments in the mind of 
 a hearer until that objection is removed. 
 
 In a team debate, the first speaker in the negative 
 should at the outset remove the interfering ideas ad- 
 vanced by the first afiirmative, and then also introduce 
 inhibiting ideas on his own part concerning the affirma- 
 tive case presented. All speakers other than the one 
 assigned to speak first on the affirmative side, who begin 
 immediately with their constructive speeches, by pay- 
 ing no heed to what has been previously said, fail to 
 remove an inhibition, and so lose the attention of the 
 audience. Even if a speaker cannot answer or does 
 not care to answer an objection fully at the moment, 
 he should at least parry or notice in some way an im- 
 portant objection before presenting an entirely new or 
 different argument. Once a university debater, fear- 
 ing surprise and wishing to gain time, wrote down a 
 sentence to be used at the opening of any speech: 
 "Against the argument which you have just heard, we 
 
 of the side throw the whole force of our position." 
 
 Speakers in debating cannot be "ships that pass in the 
 night." The side that does not speak to an opponent 
 or that continually ignores evidence presented, deserves 
 to lose. Its members may be orators, they are not de- 
 baters or practical psychologists. The enthusiasm or 
 joy of an audience, frequently manifested during the 
 rebuttal speeches, is largely due to the clear perception 
 of the alternate processes of suggestion and inhibition in 
 rapid succession. The intruder evicted returns again
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 197 
 
 and again for admission. Ejected by one door he ap- 
 pears at another, or at a window. Lucky for hini if he 
 remains on the inside when the last bell rings! 
 
 A volume might be written in illustration of the func- 
 tion of suggestion and inhibition in the handling of an 
 opponent and of an audience in varjdng moods and 
 circumstances. Sometimes, even logic and truth are 
 factors of inhibition, for there are none so deaf as those 
 who will not hear; and, of course, a luckless glance, 
 gesture, or allusion may raise a whirlwind which a mere 
 nothing will cause to subside. 
 
 The debater plays upon the emotions less than the 
 orator, but he touches an emotional chord, as through 
 the turn of a phrase or a flash of wit, more often per- 
 haps than he is aware. Complex though laughter is, 
 it is at least a means of preventing fatigue and relieving 
 tension. Laughter Uberates the energies, sets the soul 
 free, and refreshes it. Irony, sarcasm, and invective 
 assist reasoning by turning the emotions against an- 
 other, while mere amusement or entertainment, which 
 causes a spontaneous expression of the emotion jo}'' in 
 smiles and laughter, inchnes one to follow the sugges- 
 tions of a speaker through the sheer pleasure of Hsten- 
 ing. 
 
 3. Logical Fallacies as Inhibitions. — The discovery of 
 a logical fallacy in an argument may act as an inhibition. 
 It is easy to show, for instance, that in case the imagina- 
 tive processes are dominant in the mind of the speaker 
 and the logical in the mind of the hearer, the acceptance 
 of imaginative data is inliibited through the discovery of 
 an improper or inadequate logical organization of the 
 thought. Consider, for instance, (i) an accidental 
 association of images such as occurs in figures of
 
 198 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 speech. In the following, Bryan's association is purely 
 fatuous: 
 
 Mr. McKinley was the most popular man among the Repub- 
 licans, and three months ago everybody in the Republican 
 party prophesied his election. How is it to-day? Why, the 
 man who was once pleased to think that he once looked like 
 Napoleon — that man shudders to-day when he remembers that 
 he was nominated upon the anniversary of the Battle of Water- 
 loo. Not only that, but as he listens he can hear with ever- 
 increasing distinctness the sound of the waves as they beat upon 
 the lonely shores of Saint Helena. 
 
 The orator here simply used a metaphor to image a 
 conclusion which he had reached on other grounds. But 
 as we read it to-day apart from the context, its power 
 of appeal is lost through the absence of logical connec- 
 tion. There is no inherent or necessary relation shown 
 between McKinley and Napoleon in the matter referred 
 to. Or notice again (2) how an emphasis of the con- 
 crete without orientation may interfere with the in- 
 tended effect of an imaginative appeal. The question 
 involved the merits of the Canadian plan of a manda- 
 tory investigation of labor difficulties before strikes or 
 lockouts could take place. A negative team had planned 
 a campaign of opposition through an elaboration of 
 the specific instances in which the plan had failed. In- 
 stances were cited again and again with full detail, in 
 which strikes actually occurred during the period of 
 investigation, and the audience was duly impressed 
 with the futility of the plan. When, however, the au- 
 dience discovered the small proportion of failures to 
 successes, the greater number of instances in which 
 there had been no strikes during the period of investi- 
 gation, and the gradually diminishing number of strikes
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 199 
 
 in the past few years, all the intended effect of the ac- 
 cumulated images, with their display of detailed knowl- 
 edge and indirect appeal to the emotions, failed at once, 
 for they were logically inhibited. In this way, too, a 
 pubHc executive who is the recipient of propagandist 
 literature, all emanating from one source, sometimes 
 gets an erroneous unpression of political opinion. As 
 a logical fallacy, the instances are not topical and taken 
 at random, or one is led to mistake a part for the 
 whole. 
 
 4. Removing an Inhibiting Wish by the Image ad 
 Absurdunx. — '*How shall I get rid of the inhibiting wish 
 in the mind of the audience?" is often the most trouble- 
 some problem in debating. "I have a good case, but 
 there is an undercurrent of feehng against it which I 
 fear it will be impossible to overcome." Reahzation of 
 the problem, however, is the first step toward its solu- 
 tion. When Edmund Burke talked with the wind, he 
 was hailed as the greatest orator of his time; when he 
 spoke against it, he became the dinner-bell of Parlia- 
 ment. There are tunes in the experience of every orator 
 and debater when the wind is dead ahead. Argument 
 avails nothing, for the audience can hardly be induced 
 to follow, much less to heed; it is mastered by its own 
 desires and purposes now in conflict with that of tlie 
 speaker. Diversion of attention, by holding up for ap- 
 peal a new object of desire, has failed as utterly as argu- 
 ment. The favorite recourse of most debaters in such 
 an emergency is to image the opposed feeUng with new 
 concrete examples which will bring the audience to 
 laughter and ridicule of itself. Beecher often used this 
 device (reduciio ad absurdum), as at Liverpool, when 
 he accused his audience of sympathizing with the South,
 
 200 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 because they were in the minority, and reminded them 
 that they should also sympathize with a thief in the 
 hands of three constables. It was a favorite method of 
 Lincoln's when he felt compelled to grapple closely with 
 his opponent. 
 
 But you will not abide the election of a Republican Presi- 
 dent! In that supposed event you say you will destroy the 
 Union! And then you say the crime of having destroyed it 
 will be upon us ! That is cruel ! A highwayman holds a pistol 
 to my ear and mutters through his teeth: "Stand and deliver, 
 or I shall kill you, and then you will be a murderer," 
 
 You will find in debating that your opponent is not 
 averse to letting out all his sail when going with the 
 wind. You should, therefore, take time to discover 
 this probable source of appeal and to find out if pos- 
 sible the most effective way of removing it. It is for- 
 tunate if, Uke Lincohi, you can dispose of it quickly and 
 decisively by an analogy of the meteoric sort. In a 
 debate on ship subsidies, the negative had made a strong 
 case against it on economic, political, and moral grounds, 
 but felt that the afiirmative had gained much influence 
 through a covert appeal to the desire for a larger mer- 
 chant marine. The situation was serious, but how was 
 it to be met? In this case the last speaker, in summing 
 up, broke the spell thus: "We sympathize with the af- 
 firmative in their desire for a larger merchant marine. 
 We feel much pleasure in seeing the American flag flying 
 from the stem of vessels when we are in foreign ports," 
 and then leaning forward gravely, "but, ladies and 
 gentlemen, let me warn you lest your pockets should 
 be picked while the band is playing the 'Star Spangled 
 Banner,' "
 
 SUGGESTIOiV IN ARGUMENT 201 
 
 Conclusions. — A debate may be defined as a psy- 
 chological process of admitting ideas properly associated 
 to secure interest and belief and of avoiding and exclud- 
 ing all ideas of whatever character or description which 
 tend to interfere with this purpose. 
 
 Whoever, when speaking, can prevent serious inhibi- 
 tions from arising in the minds of his hearers, and can 
 also secure quick and strong responses for the funda- 
 mental reasons which he suggests, possesses the quali- 
 fications of an effective debater. •) 
 
 The word inhibition is a valuable addition to the de- 
 bater's vocabulary. Anything which stands in the way 
 of or prevents the acceptance of an idea by another, 
 may be called an inhibition. There are inhibitions of 
 fact and of logic; of style, sentence, or word; of manner, 
 voice, and gesture. Whatever, indeed, may be sup- 
 posed to be offensive or disagreeable to others, which 
 may be avoided — in taste, sentiment, feeling, perceiv- 
 ing, thinking, or believing — may act as inhibitions, may 
 prevent the acceptance of our ideas. The debater must, 
 therefore, possess and manifest, in no small degree, a 
 power of consideration for others, a delicacy of feeling, 
 a courtesy, a spirit of consideration, fair play, tact — 
 in a word, the characteristics of the educated gentle- 
 man. 
 
 II. Instruments of Suggestion 
 
 In the process of influencing by suggestion, the de- 
 bater uses the two instruments of ordinary intercourse: 
 gesture images and word images. He usually visualizes 
 his ideas and touches them with feelings, at the same 
 time co-ordinating the muscular or motor functions 
 with the mental and emotional. Body and mind act
 
 202 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 together. "Don't" is a word of prohibition, to which 
 an even clearer and stronger meaning is attached if 
 its utterance is accompanied by a frown or backward 
 wave of the hand. Indeed, the mind, as we have seen, 
 tends to act in Kne with a transmitted suggestion, so 
 that he who argues must continually take heed of the 
 psychology of the one with whom he argues, and of those 
 who listen. No expression can be effective unless it is 
 impressive; and all reactions between giving and re- 
 ceiving minds — the minds of speaker and hearer, or 
 writer and reader — which look toward agreement or 
 difference, are produced through mental suggestion. 
 The suggestions of argument call for an immediate and 
 direct response. As to the long-mooted question — 
 ''how far an actor must feel his part" — modern psy- 
 chology tends toward a belief in the existence of an ac- 
 tual feehng on the part of the actor. There are words 
 like bubble, for instance, which we can hardly think of 
 without a shght feeling in the lips or a muscular impulse 
 to pronounce the word. Speech, indeed, is an ex-pres- 
 sion, a pressing out. 
 
 All gestures and words used must be images of mean- 
 ing in order to become effective instruments of sugges- 
 tion. Indeed, if they are so chosen or so placed as to 
 add nothing in cloarness, force, or ease to the presenta- 
 tion, they may easily inhibit meaning and prevent the 
 acceptance of our ideas. Word unages, moreover, are 
 not only suggestive of meaning but of old associations. • 
 
 Gesture Images as Instruments of Suggestion. — His- 
 torically, it is deemed hkely that gestures preceded 
 speech, and that the labials m and p were the first spoken 
 utterances. This at least is a fair inference from the 
 analogy of child development. All movements of the
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 203 
 
 human body — face, head, trunk, and linibs — have an 
 image value in suggesting our ideas to others. For ex- 
 ample, the image of the clinched fist suggests determina- 
 tion; the finger gesture, the idea of close or logical dis- 
 tinctions; the open palm, the approval of ideas, and 
 the inverted palm, tlieir rejection or disapproval. A 
 movement of the arms toward the speaker calls atten- 
 tion to himself; outwardly, or away from the speaker, 
 it attracts notice to others or to objects in nature. Such 
 movements, hke the images of words, may be personal or 
 impersonal, but again, as with words, the person speak- 
 ing before an audience is a person feeling and wilHng 
 through physical or motor power as well as one think- 
 ing and conveying ideas. Certainly all such physical 
 movements are suggestive of ideas. Gestures appear to 
 be less arbitrary and more based on reason than the 
 meaning assigned to many words, but there is also a 
 recognized conventional use of gesture, as shown in 
 formal treatises. 
 
 Professor Houghton, in an excellent work on dehvery, 
 uses the term "action" as the foundation of all bodily 
 expression and defines it as a muscular response to men- 
 tal or emotional stiinuh. He says: 
 
 The student of psychology is familiar with the influence of 
 the mind over the body, with the marked effect that each mental 
 or emotional stimulus has upon the muscular organisms. The 
 inexperienced speaker is often astonished at the unexpected 
 exhilaration that he feels as he faces an audience. He finds 
 that the mind is singularly alert and acts much more freely than 
 he had expected; that the blood flows faster; that he has a sense 
 of unusual physical vigor; and that there is an insistent call 
 from the brain for muscular response to the lively activities of 
 the mind. This is the true foundation for all bodily expression. 
 Any voluntary action that is not a direct response to such
 
 204 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 prompting is necessarily false and purely mechanical. To be 
 sure, there is a great deal of action that is not the result of volun- 
 tary prompting. Various emotions such as timidity, fear, im- 
 patience, or anger express themselves through the muscles in- 
 voluntarily in a way no less mistakable to an audience than 
 voluntary action. But, whether voluntary or involuntary, the 
 fundamental cause is the same — the telegraphic message sent 
 out to the muscles from the brain. The entire problem of plat- 
 form deportment, therefore, resolves itself into two fundamental 
 considerations: 
 
 I. Is the bodily action of the speaker the result of mental 
 or emotional stimuli? 
 
 II. Does the bodily action resulting from these stimuli look 
 well and contribute to the general efiectiveness of the speech ? ^ 
 
 It is here implied, of course, that the kind, degree, 
 and quality of the reactions vi^hich are awakened in 
 others are dependent upon the kind, degree, and quality 
 of the stiinuH employed by a speaker. 
 
 Word Images as Instruments of Suggestion. — As it 
 is natural to suppose that gesture preceded speech, it 
 is also likely that speech came before writing; but why, 
 in the beginning, a chair was called a chair rather than a 
 table, we do not know. All speech utterances, of course, 
 have a physiological basis, and speech organs and de- 
 velopment must have been greatly influenced by such 
 elementary muscular actions as eating, swallowing, and 
 ejecting. 
 
 Verbal nouns seem to have been assigned to things 
 at first more or less arbitrarily, until certain names be- 
 came associated with certain meanings. These names 
 with their meanings, through constant changes and 
 variations, have gradually obtained a customary, con- 
 
 i"The Elements of Public Speaking," Harry Garfield Houghton, 
 p. s8.
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 205 
 
 ventional, and established use. Indeed, words are so 
 largely records of past experiences that for scientific 
 purposes the great German scholar Ebbinghaus^ has 
 invented a series of nonsense-words in an effort to get 
 rid of the uncertain and variable elements of memory. 
 The arbitrar}^ character of many conventional names 
 which have become attached to things, and so have 
 acquired definite associations almost startles us when 
 we read, for instance, sentences like the following: 
 
 "The ghost is willing, but the meat is weak." 
 " As harmless as pigeons and as wise as stiakcs." 
 
 It is the function of linguistics and of lexicography 
 to record the correct and established uses of words. The 
 best key to the meaning of words is in a study of lan- 
 guages, classic and foreign. Doctor Austin Phelps thus 
 emphasizes the importance of a patient groping after 
 the right word: 
 
 "Do we not," he asks, "often fret for the right word, which 
 is just outside the closed door of memory? We know that there 
 is such a word; we know that it is precisely the word we want; 
 no other can fill its place; we saw it mentally a short half-hour 
 ago; but we beat the air for it now. The power we crave is 
 the power to store words within reach, and hold them in mental 
 reserve till they are wanted, and then restore them by the mental 
 vibration of a thought. Nothing can give it to us but study and 
 use of the language in long-continued and critical practice." Again 
 he says: "By such studies, when combined with scholarly use 
 of language of a laborious profession, a man masters words singly, 
 words in combinations, words in varieties of sense, words in 
 figurative uses, and those forms of expression which always lie 
 latent in original uses of one's mother tongue." * 
 
 ' "Memory," by Hermann Ebbinghaus, translated by Henry A. Ruger. 
 2 "The Making of an Oration/' C. M. Brink, p. 109. (McCiurg.)
 
 206 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 There are few neutral words in our language, that is, 
 words without the experiences of past associations. In- 
 deed, neutrality in words is almost as rare as neutrahty 
 in patriotism. Professor L. W. Smith gives the usual 
 division of words into impersonal words and personal 
 words, and shows that the words which give a writing 
 its literary character are personal. Impersonal words 
 are used for clarity, simphcity, and precision; but per- 
 sonal words are used for strength (orientation, energy, 
 dignity, weight) , for emphasis, and for beauty (harmony, 
 euphony, speech figures). He continues: 
 
 We should always strive to write cleariy, and we should also 
 strive to write as simply as is consistent with writing concisely. 
 If a subject is difficult, it may not be possible to deal with it 
 in a simple manner and yet achieve accuracy. In the degree 
 in which the subject and our interest in it permit, however, we 
 should be clear, simple, and precise in everything we write. Evi- 
 dently, then, the qualities that make a writing personal, that 
 give it literary character, are additions to the simple qualities 
 when purpose does not go beyond that of establishing under- 
 standing of the author's meaning.^ 
 
 Likewise, in the speech of the normal man, personal 
 words are as natural as the light in the eye, the smile 
 on his countenance, or his gesture of hand or body. 
 
 Words are as temperamental as the individuals who 
 employ them. They may be regarded, theoretically, 
 as counters in a process of intellectual exchange; but 
 practically, such symbols of thought usually manifest 
 personahty and feeling, and appeal to old experiences. 
 Even general or abstract words, such as faith, power, 
 duty, enemy, soldier, have emotional associations, as 
 
 i"The Mechanism of English Speech," Lewis Worthington Smith, 
 p. 12. (Oxford.)
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 207 
 
 well as simple or concrete words, like father, mother, or 
 home. Indeed, impersonal terms hardly exist outside 
 the sciences; and in public speaking, they do so only 
 in those occasional instances where clearness only is 
 needed, as in addresses before purely technical bodies. 
 There is no feeling, for instance, in the abstract state- 
 ment that the sum of the angles of a triangle is equal 
 to two right angles. On the other hand, take such a 
 random Hst of words as the following: 
 
 Tartar, Hun, Vallombrosa, Mesopotamia, Tophet, Paradise, 
 Eden; copperhead, jingo, protectionism, pension, free trade, 
 civil service, IMonroe Doctrine; rose, alcohol, cabbage, turkey, 
 tobacco, apple, roast pig; reeking, rollicking, working, playing, 
 hunting, fishing, crying; eat, swim, dive, run, blow, rest, sleep. 
 
 Such words produce overtones of suggestion which 
 cause emotional judgments, and the bare mention of 
 their names may awaken in others in varying degrees 
 the experiences of earlier associations. Thus, literature, 
 art, business, and all forms of public speech are largely, 
 though often unconsciously, dependent for effectiveness 
 on the hidden emotional associations wliich lurk in our 
 common speech. 
 
 Variability of Meanings. — The ever-changing char- 
 acter of the meanings of words is sometimes due to the 
 speaker himself, and sometimes to the listener. 
 
 I. Due to the speaker. 
 
 Vocal Shadings. — Obviously, a different color of mean- 
 ing may be imparted to words through the manner of 
 their utterance. You have probably heard an Irish- 
 man say, "Good morning," in such a manner as to re- 
 member it all day. You have also no doubt occasionally 
 heard a speaker who, through egotism or vanity, through
 
 208 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 ignorance or spurious art, has displeased or disgusted 
 you. I shall do no more here than to mention the great 
 possibilities for shading in the use of that marvellous 
 musical instrument — the voice — and the equally marvel- 
 lous capacity of the brain to analyze and interpret au- 
 ditory impressions. 
 
 Negatively, the most common faults in speech utter- 
 ance which may inhibit meaning are, perhaps, poor 
 articulation and enunciation, throaty constringency, 
 nasaUty, and monotony of tone. The most pleasing 
 voice, therefore, and the voice most likely to convey 
 the intended meaning, possesses freedom, flexibility, and 
 variety; and in quality is pure, clear, round, fairly mu- 
 sical and fairly deep and rich. 
 
 II. Due to the listener. 
 
 a. The mental level. 
 
 h. The psychological moment. 
 
 There is also a variation of meaning due to the lis- 
 tener. Since word meanings are so dependent upon 
 experience, it remains to be pointed out how word mean- 
 ings will vary on this account with different listeners. 
 Meanings are not constant either among individuals at 
 the same time or among the same individuals at dif- 
 ferent times. Thus, there is the law of the mental level 
 as applied to words. Illustrations : The Indo-European 
 family of languages includes eight branches, as follows: 
 The Aryan, the Armenian, the Hellenic, the Albanian, 
 the Italic, the Celtic, the Balto-Slavic, the Teutonic.^ 
 A mention of these names opens trains of associations 
 to the linguistic scholar which floods them with signif- 
 icance; while to the uninformed reader they are as de- 
 
 1 "The History of the English Language," 0. F. Emerson. (Macmil- 
 lan.)
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 209 
 
 void of meaning as if they were written in Choctaw. 
 Again, this may be illustrated by the use of learned or 
 technical terms. In speaking of the vagueness and un- 
 intelligibiUty of some German writers, Boris Sidis ridi- 
 cules Hegelian philosophical speculation by quoting 
 from Hegel's chapter on perception: 
 
 " The this is thus given as not this, or as sublimated, and there- 
 with not nothing, but a definite nothing, or a nothing having a 
 content, namely the //i/5." The italics are Hegel's. The sense 
 is chiefly in the suggestive power of the itaHcs. Such meta- 
 physical speculations are recommended by some Hegelians as 
 the profoundest wisdom of idealistic philosophy. One is re- 
 minded of the semi-Platonic, semi-Hegelian definition of love: 
 " Love is the ideality of the relativity of reality of an infinitesimal 
 part of the infinite totality of the Absolute Being." * 
 
 Another important consideration is the verbal law 
 of the psychological moment, for words, hke fashions in 
 dress, have their seasons. I feel sure that ice and coal 
 bear a different significance in summer than in winter. 
 Football terms, which are readily bandied about in the 
 autumn, become almost obsolete during the athletic 
 periods of baseball, rowing, and tennis. There are, in- 
 deed, words of the hour, which for some special reason 
 are suddenly lifted bodily out of the dictionary and 
 translated as if by magic into meanings of transcendent 
 power. In this class was the word peace, when Presi- 
 dent Wilson, in February, 191 7, proposed to all the Eu- 
 ropean belligerents the formation of a league to enforce 
 peace after the war. By April, however, of the same 
 year, it was war, which had become capitalized in the 
 pubUc mind, and peace was being written with a small 
 letter. I doubt if the word coincidence was ever more 
 
 ' "The Psychology of Laughter," Boris Sidis, p. 22. (.'\pplcton.)
 
 210 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 fraught with meaning than on July 4, 1824. On this 
 day, which was the semicentennial anniversary of the 
 Declaration of Independence, Jefferson and Adams both 
 passed away. The name of the hero of the hour is usually 
 expected to elicit a demonstration. 
 
 Thus, the meaning values of images suggested will 
 vary with speakers, and will vary with the experience 
 of listeners; which, in turn, vary from time to time, as 
 does the bullion which goes to make up the silver dollar. 
 Moreover, the shadings and adjustments given to ges- 
 ture images and to word images demand for their effec- 
 tiveness the consideration of such factors as the mental 
 receptivity of the particular Hstener and the inevitable 
 emotion-bearing element hidden in words of the partic- 
 ular moment. Some plants grow only in certain soils, 
 while some blossom best in particular seasons of the 
 year. 
 
 Imagery an Imperfect Means.— The best we can ever 
 do with such an imperfect means as word imagery is 
 to arrive at approximate truth. Moreover, in our theory 
 of reasoning, it seems we must strike an average between 
 the logic of categories and pure empiricism. We must 
 admit the inherent capacity of the mind to reason, but 
 then we must admit, also, the necessity of explaining 
 this process by an objective reference. Even Aristotle's 
 association laws are merely an explanation of the sort 
 of "hunt" he would go on in order to call to mind some- 
 thing which he had forgotten. He asks what is its like, 
 what is its contrary, or what it was next to in space or 
 time. 
 
 Fundamentally, we start with an idea, we give it an 
 objective reference or test; but the words used to image 
 the idea will remain an indefinite variable, ever open
 
 SUGGESTION IN ARGUMENT 211 
 
 to error and correction. Fortunately, in argument it is 
 sufficient if we employ sincerely such means as we are 
 provided with, and so are enabled to resolve differences 
 of opinion by overcoming probable error or by estab- 
 lishing probable truth. The end of education indeed 
 is not only to know the truth, but to make it known. 
 Learning is not a light hidden under a bushel, but a 
 torch to be held aloft. These limitations of imagery, 
 moreover, hold to a certain extent for the finding and 
 statement of knowledge, as well as for its dissemination. 
 Two further remarks may be made. First, that it is 
 precisely this plasticity of imagery which gives to the 
 speaker or writer his opportunity for freedom and in- 
 di\'iduality, and enables us to dignify his best products 
 by the name of art in the higher sense at once difficult 
 and interesting to create. Second, that the attainment 
 of success in debating demands sterHng honesty and 
 sincerity — in a word, character.
 
 CHAPTER VIII 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 
 
 The debater should acquire a discriminating use of 
 words. He needs not only accurate or precise words 
 but suggestive words, words rich in associations, emo- 
 tion-arousing words, and, of course, a copious vocabulary. 
 For this purpose, he may pursue any Hne of reading or 
 study which will lead him to consider for himself such 
 things as the connotations of words, the synonyms and 
 antonyms of words used by great writers and speakers, 
 and the history and etymology of words. He should 
 know the primal or root meanings of words, and be able 
 to compare them with their customary meanings, so 
 as to keep as close as possible to these primal or root 
 meanings. In accomplishing this, Latin of course is the 
 great hnguistic study, but translating from the Greek 
 and modern languages is of great assistance. Indirectly, 
 good reading and the study of languages; directly, a 
 study of the dictionary; books of synonyms are espe- 
 cially commended. 
 
 Verbal meanings and tonal meanings, which are de- 
 rived from antecedent experiences, will generally do 
 more in getting attention, and in impressing others with 
 the interesting and solid character of one's ideas, than 
 verbal commonplaces which are only precise. A man's 
 speech, however, is the mirror of himself. Indeed, it is 
 
 212
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 213 
 
 so largely a product of his education, environment, and 
 natural ability, so individual and personal, that any 
 advice given must recognize as fundamental the in- 
 alienable right of an individual to choose his words as 
 he chooses his friends. 
 
 Let us, then, return to the elementary notion of re- 
 garding words as images of ideas, not only that we may 
 present them effectively, but in order to keep our vo- 
 cabulary from ' becoming impoverished. The business 
 man who writes, "Yours of even date received. In 
 reply, I would state , . . Yours very truly," is likely 
 always to be a man of limited vocabulary. The words 
 of a speaker, however, are not mere automata, but vital 
 energies of human thought and life, possessing an in- 
 finite variety of meanings in their nuances of etymo- 
 logical significance, customary or special usages, and 
 practical applications. The speaker must know his 
 words as the engineer the strength of his materials and 
 the stability of his structures; he must also know them 
 as the harpist knows his strings and the painter his colors. 
 He is both scientist and artist. Words, in fine, are the 
 most important elements in the instrumentation of 
 ideas by civilized man. Word imagery, tonal and illus- 
 trative, always essential to effective presentation, is 
 equally important to personal growth in the use of these 
 instruments, in imparting, in receiving, and in inter- 
 preting the meanings intended to be transmitted. They 
 express the finesse as well as the soHdity of thinking. 
 
 I. Tonal Imagery. — This term is used (in contra- 
 distinction to illustrative imagery, or imagery of the 
 content) to describe all those subconscious influences 
 upon the thinking which are due to sounds, and includes 
 onomatopoeia and rhythm. Their primary function is
 
 214 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 aesthetic or emotional, so that they are more important 
 to music, the dance, poetry, and certain forms of oratory, 
 than to argumentative discourse. 
 
 Onomatopoeia is only an auxiliary of argument. A 
 word or phrase used to illustrate the content of an idea 
 is more striking if the vowel or consonant combinations 
 which go to make it up imitate or tonally suggest the 
 object or action referred to. It intensifies an auditory 
 suggestion. Ordinarily, moreover, we prefer euphonious 
 to cacophonous words. Ex-President Roosevelt's mes- 
 sage in the spring of 191 7 was summed up in the strik- 
 ing phrase: "Arm and Farm." 
 
 Rhythm is the recurrence of accented and unaccented, 
 of emphasized and unemphasized, words or syllables. 
 In poetry, there is a definite unit of measure called a 
 foot, but the rhythm of prose possesses much greater 
 freedom, and is more noticeable in spoken than in written 
 forms. , 
 
 Prose passages which are most regularly rhythmical 
 are usually those which are most emotional; e. g., Dick- 
 ens's description of the death of Paul Dombey. In his 
 classical collection, "British Eloquence," Professor Good- 
 rich twice makes note of the rhythmus: once in the 
 speech by Plenry Grattan on "Irish Rights," and again 
 in Lord Erskine's "Defence of Stockdale." The former 
 is slow and dignified, while the latter possesses a more 
 rapid, iambic movement: 
 
 (i) "Hereafter, when these things shall be history, your age 
 of thraldom, your sudden resurrection, commercial redress, and 
 miraculous armament, shall the historian stop at liberty, and 
 observe that here the principal men among us were found want- 
 ing, were awed by a weak ministry, bribed by an empty treasury; 
 and when liberty was within their grasp, and her temple opened
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 215 
 
 its folding doors, fell down and were prostituted at the thresh- 
 old?" 
 
 "I might, as a constituent, come to your bar and demand my 
 liberty. I do call upon you by the laws of the land, and their 
 violation; by the instructions of eighteen counties; by the arms, 
 inspiration, and providence of the present moment — tell us 
 the rule by which we shall go; assert the law of Ireland; declare 
 the liberty of the land ! I will not be answered by a public lie, 
 in the shape of an amendment; nor, speaking for the subjects' 
 freedom, am I to hear of faction. I wish for nothing but to 
 breathe in this our island, in common with my fellow subjects, 
 the air of liberty. I have no ambition, unless it be to break your 
 chain and contemplate your glory. I never will be satisfied so 
 long as the meanest cottager in Ireland has a link of the British 
 chain clanking to his rags. He may be naked, he shall not be 
 in irons. And I do see the time at hand; the spirit is gone forth; 
 the Declaration of Right is planted, and though great men should 
 fall off, yet the cause shall live; and though he who utters this 
 should die, yet the immortal fire shall outlast the humble organ 
 who conveys it, and the breath of liberty, like the word of the 
 holy man, will not die with the prophet, but survive him." 
 
 (2) ''Gentlemen, I think I can observe that you are touched 
 with this way of considering the subject, and I can account for it. 
 I have not been considering it through the cold medium of books, 
 but have been speaking of man and his nature, and of human 
 dominion, from what I have seen of them myself among reluc- 
 tant nations submitting to our authority. I know what they 
 feel, and how such feelings can alone be repressed. I have heard 
 them in my youth from a naked savage, in the indignant char- 
 acter of a prince surrounded by his subjects, addressing the 
 governor of a British colony, holding a bundle of sticks in his 
 hand, as the notes of his unlettered eloquence. 'Who is it,' 
 said the jealous ruler over the desert, encroached upon by the 
 restless foot of English adventure, 'who is it that causes this 
 river to rise in the high mountains, and to empty itself into the 
 ocean ? Who is it that causes to blow the loud winds of winter, 
 and that calms them again in summer? Who is it that rears
 
 216 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 up the shade of those lofty forests, and blasts them with the 
 quick hghtning at his pleasure? The same Being who gave 
 to you a country on the other side of the waters, and gave ours 
 to us; and by this title we will defend it,' said the warrior, throw- 
 ing down his tomahawk upon the ground, and raising the war- 
 sound of his nation. These are the feelings of subjugated man 
 all round the globe; and depend upon it, nothing but fear will 
 control where it is vain to look for affection." 
 
 It has recently been asserted, that while rhythm is 
 primarily aesthetic in aim and function, secondarily it 
 "assists the thinking." This is true only if the emphasis 
 in speaking is properly made dependent on the sense 
 of the passage, on the thought groups rather than on 
 sound groups. 
 
 In keeping time with rhythm our muscles contract with the 
 accented and relax with the unaccented part of the foot or line. 
 This contraction of the muscles is an influence beneficial in pro- 
 ducing a rise of the attention. Our attention is best employed 
 when periods of activity are followed by periods of rest.^ 
 
 Similarly, while writing in another connection, an- 
 other psychologist refers to "expectancy" as resulting 
 from our "flow" of speech: 
 
 The articulate voice per se seems, then, to have a function of 
 pointing, i. e., of leaving us expectant and ready, even when 
 there is no content pointed to. Every one has the experience 
 of listening to others conversing in an unknown tongue (Chinese 
 laundrymen, for instance), where there is not the remotest con- 
 ception of the subject in hand, yet a feeling of significance ac- 
 companies the flow of uncomprehended talk. Those who do not 
 understand French or Italian well enough to follow the connec- 
 tion in a play, will leave the theatre with the impression of hav- 
 ing understood every word said. In these cases the expectancy, 
 
 ' " Psychology of Public Speaking," W. D. Scott, loi.
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 217 
 
 the pointing consciousness has been there, the feeling of other- 
 ness or of significance, although there was no subsequent content 
 to fill it up.^ 
 
 When the emphasis is placed on sound groups rather 
 than on thought groups, the effect is likely to lull rather 
 than to arouse. 
 
 2. Illustrative imagery or imagery of the content may 
 be classified as objective or subjective, according as it 
 omits or expresses the emotions of the speaker, i 
 
 Classical illustrations of the impersonal objective image 
 which are formed by analogy are Gibbon's description 
 of Byzantium in the form of an unequal triangle ("De- 
 cHne and Fall of the Roman Empire, XVII"), Victor 
 Hugo's battle-field of Waterloo presented in the form of 
 the letter A ("Les Miserables"), and Stevenson's like- 
 ness of the Bay of Monterey to a bent fishing-hook 
 (''Across the Plains"). 
 
 Every pubhc speaker soon learns the value of a 
 mental sketch-map as an aid to the understanding of 
 an audience. Webster presents a vivid picture of the 
 opening situation in the Hayne-Webster debate by re- 
 ferring to the fact that when the mariner, after being 
 tossed at sea for many days, attains a glance of the sun, 
 he immediately takes his latitude, and learns his true 
 position. So Webster argues that before we float farther 
 on the waves of this debate we should ascertain where 
 we now are, and concludes by calling for a reading of 
 the resolution before the Senate. In debating, the func- 
 tion of an image is just as properly to convey informa- 
 tion which implies a conclusion as it is to secure atten- 
 
 * The Psychological Review, Monograph Supplement No. 30, by Eleanor 
 H. Rowland, p. 7.
 
 218 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 tion and interest through an emotional reaction. Unless 
 reliance is placed upon reason, in controversial matters 
 the process, indeed, becomes one of persuasion, and is 
 not argument at all. The debater, therefore, should 
 acquire skill in the use of the objective image. He may- 
 use this skill in the introduction, where impartiality is 
 requisite without implying a conclusion, as in imaging 
 the terms of the proposition under discussion, or in ex- 
 cluding irrelevant matter, or in explaining by analogy 
 what the issue is like. Moreover, during the debate, 
 whenever the reasoning is to be set forth impressively, 
 such objective images have place. But there is also 
 an effective expository type of argument, where con- 
 clusions are not formally drawn but implied through the 
 association of ideas well imaged. Thus, signs and ex- 
 amples have force and convey meaning in the presenta- 
 tion of those ideas which we know rest ultimately upon 
 unstated but remotely suggested inductions or causal re- 
 lationships. That which we perceive, we know; seeing 
 is believing. Such images used with argumentative 
 effect express the relation of simple association and 
 resemblance, and imply those of particular with general 
 or of antecedent with consequent. 
 
 Avoiding Personalities. — Argument, moreover, pre- 
 supposes sufificient emotional color to enable a listener 
 to reach a sound judgment. The tendency, however, 
 to personalities which lower the intellectual tone of an 
 argument is always to be avoided. If, at length, per- 
 sonal charges are found to be necessary, they should, 
 of course, be made as free from feeling as possible and 
 always with a full consideration of an opponent's point 
 of view. In the passage beginning "Matches and Over- 
 matches," Webster met the personal taunts of Hayne
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 219 
 
 with a reserve of feeling, a dignity, and exaggerated 
 courtesy which intensified the power of his sarcasm. 
 In the heat of debate, even Lincoln, who was calmness 
 itself in his second inaugural, sometimes went too far 
 in his earlier days, as in his personal attacks on Presi- 
 dent Polk. Certainly his Framed Timber Analogy in 
 the House-Divided- Against-Itself speech possesses more 
 argumentative merit than such a passage as the fol- 
 lowing : 
 
 But if he cannot or will not do this — if on any pretense or 
 no pretense he shall refuse or omit it — then I shall be fully con- 
 vinced of what I more than suspect already — that he is deeply 
 conscious of being in the wrong; that he feels the blood of this 
 war, like the blood of Abel, is crying to Heaven against him; 
 that originally having some strong motive — what, I will not 
 stop now to give my opinion concerning — to involve the two 
 countries in a war, and trusting to escape scrutiny by fixing 
 the public gaze upon the exceeding brightness of military glory- 
 that attractive rainbow that rises in showers of blood — that 
 serpent's eye that charms to destroy — he plunged into it, and 
 has swept on and on till, disappointed in his calculation of the 
 ease with which Mexico might be subdued, he now finds himself 
 he knows not where. How like the half-insane mumbling of a 
 fever dream is the whole war part of his late message ! 
 
 Something, however, may perhaps be here pardoned 
 to the temper of the times. 
 
 Subjective images are the commonest type, even in 
 debating. They tend to awaken in the hearer personal 
 feelings, either favorable or unfavorable. Feeling begets 
 feeling. It is very difficult to describe a thing, let us 
 say, as beautiful or as just, without manifesting quite 
 unconsciously some pleasure concerning it, or as ugly 
 or unjust, without evincing some feeling of dislike, aver- 
 sion, or even contempt. With some persons a beautiful
 
 220 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 view is always a "charming" one, and a thing ugly in 
 appearance may quickly become hideous and hateful. 
 Thus, there is value in learning, through a study of 
 synonyms, the temperaments of words. 
 
 In the following, the italicized words give it an emo- 
 tional quality: 
 
 We can organize an army on either the plan submitted by 
 the majority of the Committee on Military Affairs or that of 
 the minority. Both provide conscription, but that of the ma- 
 jority makes the stronger appeal to me. It does not insult the 
 young men of the country by assuming that they will not do 
 as the young men of England did, come voluntarily to their 
 country's assistance. My contention is that the drastic method, 
 the odious conscription plan, should not be resorted to until 
 a chance has been given for getting men into the army on a basis 
 that is generally regarded as honorable. Even advocates of the 
 conscription system say that it is inadvisable to have volun- 
 teers and conscripts in the same army, because the former are 
 thought to have a more honorable status. I fancy this must 
 be true, for certainly they will be the men of spirit, who do not 
 require compulsion to bring them to the defense of their coun- 
 try. 
 
 In a recent debate on the compulsory investigation 
 of labor troubles before strikes and lockouts should take 
 place, an affirmative speaker imaged his main conten- 
 tion vividly as follows: "The economic forces of our 
 country may be Hkened unto a sword, one edge of which 
 is capital, the other labor. Periodically, the pubUc 
 is asked to take hold of this sword, with the result 
 that it gashes its hand. We of the affirmative have 
 provided a hilt for that sword. The hilt is ready — 
 compulsory investigation. Will you reach for it and 
 grasp it?" 
 
 As emotions have been classified broadly into ap-
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 221 
 
 proving and disapproving, so subjective images may be 
 classified as appro\ang and disapproving images. So we 
 have the imagery of the eulogy and that of the phiUppic. 
 It should be remembered, however, that we will some- 
 times seek approval for a cause, object, or person, by 
 awakening a dislike or disapproval of the opposite. Some 
 political campaigns seem to be conducted on this prin- 
 ciple. Ob\4ously, the suggestions offered on the affirma- 
 tive and negative sides in a debate need not always 
 be, for the affirmative one of approval, or for the nega- 
 tive one of disapproval. Neither side need confine it- 
 self to one set of emotions or harp too continually on 
 one string. The affirmative, for instance, will image 
 e\^s in an existing system to be remedied, or will sug- 
 gest objections to the negative case; while the negative 
 side may seek not merely to estabHsh a negation but 
 to secure approval for a substitute plan. 
 
 Personal Adjectives. — The excessive use of personal 
 adjectives is especially to be avoided in argument, for, 
 of all the parts of speech, adjectives seem most commonly 
 to possess "an affective coloring." No words expressive 
 of feehng are really justified in argument unless that 
 feeling is also justified by evidence and reasordng. The 
 word odious, for instance, in the phrase "the odious 
 plan" above, really begs the question at issue. The 
 characterization of an argument by an adjective of feel- 
 ing (after the argument has been clearly established) 
 is another matter, provided it expresses the reaction 
 also clearly experienced by others. 
 
 In studying synonyms, therefore, to enrich one's vo- 
 cabulary, attention should always be paid to this dis- 
 tinction between subjective and objective adjectives. 
 A synonym, it may be said, is not a word whose mean-
 
 222 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 ing is identical with that of another, but similar. It 
 possesses a family rather than an individual likeness, 
 the points of difference at the moment being regarded 
 as unimportant. 
 
 Many speakers have their characteristic adjectives. 
 Referring to Rufus Choate's use of adjectives, it was 
 once said that he "drove a coach and six," each new 
 adjective applied adding something new to the picture, 
 giving it an increased vividness and the hearer a new 
 delight. On the other hand, William Pinkney, for many 
 years his rival for legal supremacy during the adjudica- 
 tion of marine cases arising out of the War of 1812, was 
 at times as sparse in adjectival imagery as Choate was 
 copious. 
 
 The student might profitably read some argument 
 and make a report of it on the following plan: First, 
 write down in one column a list of the adjectives used. 
 Second, record in another column, opposite each word, 
 a list of its synonyms. Then he should consider the 
 relative appropriateness of the several words to the 
 context, and also their intellectual or emotional quality. 
 Similar investigations may be made as to the other parts 
 of speech, particularly concrete nouns, verbs, and ad- 
 verbs. 
 
 All the parts of speech, it would seem, may be con- 
 sidered as imagery, expressing a state of mind having 
 an objective reference. We should cultivate the habit 
 of imaging nouns as concrete objects, and verbs as ac- 
 tions. Adjectives and verbs are imaged as modifiers, 
 respectively, of things and actions; the preposition 
 with suggests the accompaniment of things; over and 
 under the position of things; the conjunction and the 
 connection^ and or the alternative of things, etc.
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 223 
 
 The very experience of a concrete noun involves associated 
 images. It is the part of speech devoted to that unusual habit 
 of mental imagery, especially visual. As soon as we ignore our 
 images, or for some reason have but few, our vocabulary is im- 
 poverished of concrete nouns. 
 
 Observe the concrete nouns and adjectives by which 
 the chief justice proves to Falstaff that he is an old 
 man: 
 
 Do you set down your name in the scroll of youth, that are 
 written down old with all the characters of age? Have you 
 not a moist eye ? a dry hand ? a yellow cheek ? a white beard ? 
 a decreasing leg? an increasing belly? is not your voice broken? 
 your wind short? your chin double? your wit simple? and 
 every part about you blasted with antiquity? and will you yet 
 call yourself young? Fie, fie, fie, Sir John! 
 
 The motor response to verbs, especially in the im- 
 perative form, is too well recognized to be dwelt upon. 
 Doubtless it is often because of this that, when we wish 
 to avoid bluntness of speech invoking action, we give 
 the verb adverbial or other modifiers. 
 
 The Apostle Paul's remarks to the Corinthians, upon 
 the abstract virtue charity or love, illustrates concrete 
 suggestion through verbs: 
 
 Charity suffereth long and is kind; charity envieth not; 
 charity vaunteth not itself, is not puffed up, doth not behave 
 itself unseemly, seeketh not her own, is not easily provoked, 
 thinketh no evil; rejoiceth not in iniquity but rejoiceth in the 
 truth; beareth all things, believeth all things, hopeth all things, 
 endureth all things. 
 
 The verbs of the man of science grow in significance 
 when they are imaged concretely: 
 
 From the time that the first suggestion to introduce physical 
 science into ordinary education was timidly whispered, until
 
 224 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 now, the advocates of scientific education have met with opposi- 
 tion of two kinds. On the one hand, they have been pooh-poohed 
 by the men of business who pride themselves in being the represen- 
 tatives of practicality; while, on the other hand, they have been 
 excoynmunicated by the classical scholars, in their capacity of 
 Levites in charge of the ark of culture and monopolists of liberal 
 education. — {Thomas H. Huxley.) 
 
 But most of all, perhaps, the debater should pay at- 
 tention to his use of adjectives, for they express the 
 mental attitude and the emotion of the speaker. 
 Characterization, hovi^ever, is not argument, though 
 often an important aid to it. Excessive characteriza- 
 tion is quickly detected, and defeats its own ends. 
 
 Adjectives seem to be more intimate, more personal words 
 than any yet given. . . . We find that the adjective function 
 in general is that of expressing the intimate effect of stimuli 
 on organism and at the same time of pointing to an object as 
 possessing these qualities, and it is more likely than the other 
 parts of speech to have an affective coloring.^ 
 
 The following passage from Sidney Smith may illus- 
 trate imaginative suggestion in general, marked by a 
 pecuhar richness of diction: 
 
 Take some quiet, sober moment of life, and add together 
 the two ideas of pride and man; behold him, a creature of a 
 sphere high, stalking through infinite space in all the grandeur 
 of littleness. Perched on a speck of the universe, every wind 
 of heaven strikes into his blood the coldness of death; his soul 
 floats from his body like melody from the string; day and night, 
 as dust on the wheel, he is rolled along the heavens, through a 
 labyrinth of worlds, and all the creations of God are flaming 
 above and beneath. 
 
 ^ Thz Psychological Review, Monograph Supplements, No. 30, by 
 Eleanor H. Rowland, pp. 19, 23.
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 225 
 
 It has been well said that " there are three great words 
 in expression — imagination, sympathy, and suggestion." 
 To the Hterary artist, the greatest of these is imagi- 
 nation, for the imagination is the mental source of 
 suggestion. It suggests feehng, it suggests thought. 
 Through its dynamic power it awakens the mental ac- 
 tivity of others, which under guidance and control seems 
 of itself to reach the anticipated goal — whether that 
 goal be the perception of a truth or the performance of 
 an action desired. Thus the verbal image is the natural 
 agency of the mind in conveying its ideas. Nothing is 
 simpler, except gesture and facial expression. 
 
 "The eye it cannot choose but see, 
 We cannot bid the ear be still, 
 Our bodies feel where'er they be 
 Against or with our will." 
 
 The Phrase.^Fortunate, indeed, is the debater who 
 is able to image such concepts as necessity, advantage, 
 and danger, when they are fundamental to his case, 
 in interest-arousing, memorable phrases. Failing in 
 tliis, like most pohtical orators, he lays stress on the 
 power of the quoted phrase or epigram which appeals 
 to a cherished attitude or a familiar ideal. Indeed, even 
 the main issues of a debate have sometimes been so 
 stated as almost to beg the main question at issue. This 
 happened quite unconsciously, for example, when a 
 negative team, opposing the participation by the United 
 States in a league of peace to be formed after the war, 
 defined the issue as freedom and independence of action 
 versus a formal alHance. All such phrases appeal to 
 emotional judgments.
 
 226 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 The power of the phrase has been emphasized by 
 Emerson in his "Essay on Eloquence" as follows: 
 
 The orator must be, to a certain extent, a poet. Condense 
 some daily experience into a glowing symbol, and an audience 
 is electrified. ... It is a wonderful aid to memory, which carries 
 away the image, and never loses it. A popular assembly, Hke 
 the House of Commons, or the French Chamber, or the Amer- 
 ican Congress, is commanded by these two powers — first by a 
 fact, then by skill of statement. Put the argument into a con- 
 crete shape, into an image — some hard phrase, round and sohd 
 as a ball, which they can see and handle and carry home with 
 them — and the cause is half won. 
 
 An effective artistic image must appeal as an actuality 
 or truth and give the impression of spontaneity, ob- 
 taining its effects instantly or not at all. It is simple, 
 not stilted or overwrought, is drawn with a free but 
 sure hand. It has the force of an intuitive perception 
 whose implications and suggestions are so obvious and 
 compelling as to be inescapable. It is a psychological 
 bow-shot at the bull's-eye. 
 
 Great truths which have influenced the policies of 
 this nation have, on great occasions, been imaged vividly 
 as a mental flash. Washington fixed the foreign policy 
 of the United States for over a hundred years in his 
 Second Inaugural through his use of the term "En- 
 tangling AUiances." Lincoln defined the issues which 
 saved the Union through his application to slavery of 
 the Biblical quotation that a "house divided against 
 itself cannot stand." And more recently, President 
 Wilson justified America's entrance into the great Eu- 
 ropean War by a phrase whose truth was instantly per- 
 ceived, recognized, and accepted, namely, that we must 
 "make the world safe for democracy." Throughout
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 227 
 
 the century, indeed, slogans of parties in succeeding 
 campaigns have figured prominently in their triumphs 
 or defeats. The mottoes of our States, and in ancient 
 times those on the coats of arms of families, served as 
 the rallying cries for loyalty, devotion, and sacrifice. 
 
 Sentence Forms. — In making argument effective, 
 there is much to enhghten us in the psychology of 
 grammar and rhetoric. Chief, among the sentence forms 
 used to awaken and intensify interest, is the interroga- 
 tory. 
 
 (i) Our best oratory fairly bristles with the rhetorical 
 question: "Is hfe so dear or peace so sweet as to be pur- 
 chased at the price of chains and slavery? Forbid it, 
 Almighty God !" Such a direct appeal has an advantage 
 over the declarative form, in that it starts the mind of 
 the listener to thinking and, even though the question 
 suggests the answer, seems to permit it to reach its con- 
 clusion by its own processes. Interest is secured by 
 setting the listener's mind to work under the speaker's 
 control. In the debate on the Swiss military plan, notice 
 further how the negative massed a series of interroga- 
 tories in a summary, to implant the doubt that the af- 
 firmative had proved their case: 
 
 You have heard the whole case of the aflarmative. Have they 
 shown what tremendous change has come about in our condi- 
 tion that we are forced to forsake sober thought and turn to so 
 radical a proposal? Have they shown why, when we consider 
 the problem of defense, we are to find its solution in a slavish 
 imitation of a system used and developed by a little landlocked 
 European state the size of Massachusetts? Have you heard any 
 reason why we are to lay such tremendous emphasis upon that 
 branch of our defense which is secondary in character, namely, 
 our land forces? Have they justified by necessity their proposal 
 to compel every normal American to let his time be confiscated
 
 228 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 by the state for this type of defense? Have they shown how it 
 is economical to train eleven million men? Have they proved 
 why we must expose ourselves to the dangerous national psy- 
 chology which universal military training develops? Have they 
 proved that under the system they propose we will at least have 
 adequate, real defense? Will their plan, whatever its faults 
 and exaggerations in principle and application, stand the acid 
 test of war, and guarantee us at least safety against a possible 
 foe? The answer, ladies and gentlemen, is emphatically "No." 
 
 Notice, too, the compelling force of the skilfully 
 phrased questions in this British "War Poster," almost 
 brutal in their directness: 
 
 FOUR QUESTIONS TO MEN WHO HAVE NOT ENLISTED 
 
 1. If you are physically fit and between 19 and 38 years of 
 age, are you really satisfied with what you are doing to-day? 
 
 2. Do you feel happy as you walk along the streets and see 
 other men wearing the King's uniform? 
 
 3. What wiU you say in years to come when people ask you: 
 "Where did you serve in the great war?" 
 
 4. What would you answer when your children grow up and 
 say: "Father, why weren't you a soldier too?" 
 
 ENLIST TO-DAY 
 
 The interrogatory may suggest the answer yes as 
 well as no, and interest the mind in the most difficult 
 and important phases of any subject. It is intended 
 to bring a strong reaction. 
 
 (2) When the experienced lawyer says to the court, 
 "Turn to folio 304 and you will find," so and so, he hopes 
 to prompt the court to obey his suggestion and examine 
 the evidence. Likewise, the seasoned debater knows 
 that when he tells his audience to follow him figuratively 
 to a certain quarter of the globe, it will usually be in-
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 229 
 
 clined at least to the mental act. The imperative form, 
 however, is often varied with the more courteous or 
 concessive "If you will turn, if you will follow me, you 
 will find," etc. 
 
 (3) It must not be supposed from tliis, however, that 
 the h}'pothetical sentence form always or even usually 
 implies courtesy or agreement. Indeed, the over-argu- 
 mentative "If, therefore," style often awakens opposi- 
 tion and combativeness, for it may unply quite unin- 
 tentionally some distrust in the Kstener and actually 
 raise the doubt which it would down. In speaking to 
 an audience which is antagonistic, as, for example, to a 
 body of h}^henated Americans on "Foreign-Born Amer- 
 icans Real Americans," you might imply distrust by 
 saying: "If you beheve in the greatness of our mission, 
 then you must accept our problems as your problems 
 and identify our life with your own." The danger of 
 disapproval would at least be lessened by saying more 
 diplomatically: "Since you believe in the greatness of 
 our mission, then you will accept our problems as your 
 problems and identify our Hfe with your own." 
 
 Climax. — The most vivid imagery in an argument is 
 often used for the purpose of obtaining a strong final 
 impression, which is likely to be the most lasting. After 
 clarif}ing the processes in a discriminatory way, an 
 idea is sometimes effectively driven home by an analogy 
 or a metaphor, thus: 
 
 The hand of Heaven appears to have led us on to be, perhaps, 
 humble instruments and means in the great Providential dis- 
 pensation which is completing. We have fled from the political 
 Sodom; let us not look back, lest we perish and become a monu- 
 ment of infamy and derision to the world ! For can we ever 
 expect more unanimity and a better preparation for defense;
 
 230 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 more infatuation of counsel among our enemies, and more valor 
 and zeal among ourselves ? The same force and resistance which 
 are sufficient to procure us our liberties, will secure us a glorious 
 independence, and support us in the dignity of free, imperial 
 states. We cannot suppose that our opposition has made a 
 corrupt and dissipated nation more friendly to America, or 
 created in them a greater respect for the rights of mankind. 
 We can, therefore, expect a restoration and establishment of our 
 privileges, and a compensation for the injuries we have received, 
 from their want of power, from their fears, and not from their 
 virtues. The unanimity and valor which will effect an honorable 
 peace can render a future contest for our liberties unnecessary. 
 He who has strength to chain down the wolf is a madman if he lets 
 him loose without draiving his teeth and paring his nails. — {Samuel 
 Adams.) 
 
 Repetition. — Words, phrases, and sentences gain 
 peculiar povi^er through repetition, so that what at first 
 we know not and care not for, will in time, through the 
 sheer persistency with which it is forced on our atten- 
 tion, come to be accepted and embraced. Thus, articles 
 of trade are successfully exploited by advertising, and 
 pohtical slogans and epigrams casually mentioned at 
 first, come gradually to be accepted and extended be- 
 3^ond the occasion of their first utterance. Not only 
 that, but recurrent sounds and forms, as in the litany 
 or in many devices of poetry such as the refrain of the 
 old ballads, or in Burke's "I impeach him," in his prose- 
 cution of Warren Hastings, have a pecuhar effect of 
 monotony which fascinates the Hstener into quiescence. 
 In his Reply to Hayne, too, Webster uses the phrase, 
 "I understand him to say," with a slightly ironical effect 
 of disapproval. 
 
 No element of debating is more important than the 
 keeping of the main ideas— arguments and facts — before 
 the mind of the audience. Repetition of subject, repe-
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 231 
 
 tition of phrases, suggesting the main reasons! Indeed, 
 debates have been won without much debating abihty 
 except such as is shown in a frequent restatement of 
 the proposition supported by three main reasons as 
 the unified scheme of proof. We may even forget the 
 absence of further or supporting arguments in the con- 
 secutive din of the "three reasons." They alone, so 
 melodiously phrased, so rhythmically uttered, so con- 
 fidently proclaimed, will remain in our ears. This, of 
 course, is more likely to happen if the question is such 
 that neither side can prove anything about it with cer- 
 tainty. And in all debates on matters of pubhc poHcy, 
 it must be remembered that we can never establish any- 
 thing more than a preponderance of probability. If, 
 however, in debating, the intellectual is to predominate, 
 it is far better that the main ideas should be emphasized 
 through a development of consecutive proofs than that 
 the emotions should be besieged by a quasi-poetic re- 
 petend. The debater must always recognize that reasons 
 qua reasons are more important than language. This 
 understood, skilful repetition is an important and proper 
 instrument of effectiveness; for frequency of occurrence 
 acquaints the audience clearly and fully with what is 
 of most importance. Such acquaintance is a condition 
 precedent to the acceptance of a case. 
 
 Variety. — Ideas arranged in good sequence may be- 
 come tiresome, even if clearly imaged. Nothing is so 
 fatal to interest and attention as monotony — monot- 
 ony of subject, monotony of incident, monotony of 
 style, monotony of dehvery. Vivid imagery gives rest 
 from the monotone of logical sequence and suggests, 
 through the laws of association, obvious detours into 
 bypaths of memory or feeling. Whether its purpose,
 
 232 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 however, is to adorn, or simply to inform and make clear, 
 the use of imagery must take into account this funda- 
 mental fact of the psychology of the human mind, that 
 the holding of attention and interest demands variety, 
 t Monotony is desirable for its impressiveness, but when 
 we wish to avoid the fatigue it produces, we image our 
 ideas in various ways. Indeed, repetition of phrase 
 in general is more suitable to poetry than to prose, (i) 
 There is, for example, an advantage in the parallel struc- 
 ture of sentences expressing an idea from the same view- 
 point and relating to the same subject, as in the preceding 
 paraleipsis of Lord Erskine. There is here no monotony, 
 no exact repetition, only a suggestion of similarity: "It 
 is not my purpose — I will not follow the example — 
 I will not call your attention — ." The classical illustra- 
 tion of such a parallelism perfectly clear and effectively 
 varied is Burke's six capital causes why the Americans 
 love liberty. For the varied literary expression of the 
 main propositions of a brief, the debater will derive much 
 profit from a study of this and similar masterpieces. 
 (2) But even where there is exact repetition, the words 
 may be differently spoken. Both manner and mood 
 will vary meaning. Mark Antony, for example, fre- 
 quently repeats the suggestion that Brutus is an honor- 
 able man in exactly the same words, but we know that 
 he must have gradually altered his manner and voice, 
 to be able to express finally the irony of his true mean- 
 ing. Humor pleases us, as a relaxation from a serious 
 strain. Thus, Falstaff is depicted in sharp contrast to 
 the other main characters of Henry the Fourth. When 
 he propounds to himself his catechism on honor, he fLxes 
 his attention on the theme and repeats the word honor 
 often, but he holds our interest and attention by his
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 233 
 
 surprises and quick turns. We even find real amuse- 
 ment in a droll cynicism with which we do not wholly 
 agree: 
 
 Prince. Why, thou owest God a death. 
 
 Falstaf. 'T\s not due yet; I would be loath to pay him be- 
 fore his day. What need I be so forward with him that calls 
 not on me? Well, 'tis no matter; honor pricks me on. Yea, but 
 how if honor prick me off when I come on? how then? Can 
 honor set to a leg? no; or an arm? no; or take away the grief 
 of a wound? no. Honor hath no skill in surgery, then? no. 
 What is honor? a word. What is that word honor? air. A 
 trim reckoning! Who hath it? he that died o' Wednesday. 
 Doth he feel it? no. Doth he hear it? no. 'Tis insensible, 
 then? yes, to the dead. But will it not live with the living? 
 no. Whyr detraction will not suffer it. Therefore I'll none 
 of it. Honor is a mere scutcheon; and so ends my catechism. 
 
 Proceeding further with an analysis of the sources 
 of variety, we find (3) that we may hold or intensify 
 interest and tend to reach a maximum of effectiveness 
 by diversifying methods, proofs, and illustrations. Hav- 
 ing shown from signs that a fact is true, we may give 
 examples showing that it has often been true before, or 
 state reasons why it must now in the nature of the case 
 be true. Having shown one effect of a cause, we will 
 specify additional effects; having supported an asser- 
 tion by the opinion of one authority, we will add others 
 with their varying opinions. Now we may appeal to 
 habit, to imitation, to desire, to idealism; now draw 
 illustrations from one field and now from another more 
 or less remote. Now we are slow and minute in style 
 or manner, now fast and sweeping as the need may be, 
 for the eye may move as easily from crag to crag as from 
 petal to petal. We usually like the speaker who holds 
 his subject so firmly that he can, if need be, treat it
 
 234 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 lightly, illustrating and proving, smiling and disapprov- 
 ing; simply letting the mind of the audience play natu- 
 rally about the subject, sharply focussing the attention 
 only on what is really important. When the attention 
 is so strained as to be unpleasant, a varied appeal tends 
 to bring rest and delight. 
 
 (4) Finally, a variation in the sources of sensory ap- 
 peal may give increased power of effect. Speech is in 
 its nature primarily auditory. Though the mental and 
 emotional associations which it awakens are suggested 
 to the ear, it converts to its use the other sources of 
 sensory appeal. When it does not, its monotony may 
 be due to a narrow range of suggestion. Certainly, the 
 speaker is a word-painter, picturing objects to the sight 
 by the use of sahent characteristics and indicative words. 
 But this is by no means all. He should on occasion in- 
 tensify and diversify his appeals by the use of imagery 
 which enUsts the other senses. How instinctively, for 
 instance, that master of expression and human nature, 
 Shakespeare, varied his appeals in this way: 
 
 "Why, man, he doth bestride the narrow worid 
 Like a Colossus; . . . 
 
 Brutus and Cczsar : what should be in that Casar? 
 Why should that name be sounded more than yours? 
 Write them together, yours is as fair a name; 
 Sound them, it doth become the mouth as well; 
 Weigh them, it is as heavy; conjure with them, 
 Bmtiis will start a spirit as soon as Ccesar. 
 Now, in the names of all the gods at once, 
 Upon what meat doth this our Caesar feed, 
 That he is grown so great?" 
 
 The whole complex origin of our ideas of the outside 
 world may be reflected in the purely audible.
 
 INSTRUIMENTS OF SUGGESTION 235 
 
 Let us contrast speech briefly with a visual art. The 
 moving scenes of the vitascope produce an illusion of 
 reahty and vividly portray action to the eye. Yet in 
 a motion-picture of a great drama such as "Hamlet," 
 how much we miss the power of the human voice, espe- 
 cially if we have heard the play rendered by a noted 
 actor ! The auditory art of speech does well in suggest- 
 ing to the mind both action and visual objects. In fact, 
 it has been found that the great orators use visual imagery 
 more than all the other forms combined. 
 
 A public speaker may possibly become popular chiefly 
 because of his pictorial power, as well as for his rhythmic 
 and sonorous effects, his Hterary style, his argumen- 
 tative skill, or his extensive knowledge, y£t such popular- 
 ity has been known to fade away as quickly as it came, 
 because of a violation of the essential principle of change 
 which underlies all sustained human interest. Just as 
 statistics may be overdone, so may word-paintin,g; in 
 the end, variety itself may become monotonous. In- 
 deed, there is a valid basis for the psychological prin- 
 ciple of variety as well as for the psychological prin- 
 ciple of monotony. Its effective use marks the climax 
 of art. 
 
 Paraleipsis. — It is singular that the figure paraleipsis, 
 or omission, so highly prized by the ancient orators, 
 and so common in the public speeches of to-day, should 
 have failed to receive a notice from modern text-writers. 
 The student is doubtless familiar with the aXka ravra 
 irapaXei^oi of Demosthenes (but these things I pass 
 by), the prceteritio of Cicero, and the colloquial "not to 
 mention" of modern speech. By paraleipsis, a speaker, 
 while bringing ideas forward for the purpose of exclud- 
 ing them, fixes the attention on the apparently excluded
 
 236 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 ideas in such a skilful way as to secure their full force 
 and effect. Though negative in form, it is positive in 
 meaning; it has the force of paradox, and aptness of 
 irony. 
 
 So Webster says: "I will not accuse the honorable 
 member of violating civilized war; I will not say that 
 he poisoned his arrows. But whether his shafts were 
 or were not dipped in that which should have caused 
 rankling — there was not quite strength enough in the 
 bow to bring them to their mark." This figure is quite 
 frequently employed in the address to the jury, as, for 
 example, in Lord Erskine's defense of Gordon as follows : 
 
 It is not my purpose to recall to your minds the fatal effects 
 which bigotry has, in former days, produced in this island. 
 I will not follow the example the crown has set me, by 
 making an attack upon your passions, on subjects foreign 
 to the object before you. I will not call your attention from 
 those flames, kindled by a villainous banditti (which they have 
 thought fit, in defiance of evidence, to introduce), by bringing 
 before your eyes the more cruel flames, in which the bodies of 
 our expiring, meek, patient Christian fathers were, little more 
 than a century ago, consuming in Smithfield. I will not call 
 up from the graves of martyrs all the precious holy blood that 
 has been spilled in this land, to save its established government 
 and its reformed religion from the secret villainy and the open 
 force of Papists. The cause does not stand in need even of such 
 honest arts; and I feel my heart too big voluntarily to recite 
 such scenes, when I reflect that some of my own, and my best 
 and dearest progenitors, from whom I glory to be descended, 
 ended their innocent lives in prisons and in exile, only because 
 they were Protestants. 
 
 We may suggest our ideas through concrete illus- 
 trations and analogy, we may state them in highly sug- 
 gestive rhetorical forms, but most important of all is
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 237 
 
 what we image — what we put into our imagery! Webster 
 used paraleipsis in the eulogy of his State beginning, "I 
 shall enter upon no encomium of Massachusetts," but 
 the real power of the passage lay in its content, with 
 its skilful allusion to that wliich existing easily in memory 
 would quickly touch the feelings and sentiment. With 
 what strong sense-appeal does Shakespeare image his 
 reflections on the possibilities of a Hfe beyond, in the 
 following: 
 
 "Ay, but to die and go we know not where; 
 To lie in cold obstruction and to rot; 
 This sensible, warm motion to become 
 A kneaded clod; and the delighted spirit 
 To bathe in fiery floods, or to reside 
 In thrilling region of thick-ribbed ice; 
 To be imprison 'd in the viewless winds, 
 And blown with restless violence round about 
 The pendent world; or to be worse than worst 
 Of those that lawless and incertain thought 
 Imagine howUng; 'Tis too horrible." 
 
 If any one should miss the lofty idealization in such 
 passages or think that imagery is merely a use of fine 
 words, let him first read Dorothy Wordsworth's rambles 
 about Grasmere and then her brother William's "I wan- 
 dered lonely as a cloud." 
 
 Confidence. — If a debater betrays doubt or uncer- 
 tainty with reference to himself or to his case, or if he 
 exhibits suspicion or distrust toward his audience, his 
 state of mind may quite unconsciously react on his au- 
 dience with disastrous results. Indeed, no principle of 
 effectiveness needs to be more generally recognized 
 than that confidence begets confidence. Mr. Roosevelt 
 is noted as a campaign speaker for the vehemence and
 
 238 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 force of his utterances. Speaking in Chicago in 191 6 
 on National Duty and International Ideals, he said: 
 
 Every nation in the world now realizes our weakness, and 
 no nation in the world believes in either our disinterestedness or 
 our manliness. The effort to placate outside nations by being 
 neutral between right and wrong, and to gain good-will along 
 professional pacifist lines by remaining helpless for self-defense, 
 has resulted, after two fatuous years, in so shaping affairs that 
 the nations either already feel, or are rapidly growing to feel, 
 for us not only dislike but contempt. 
 
 On the other hand, Benjamin Franklin learned hu- 
 mility from a Quaker friend, and preached the doctrine 
 of qualified assertion thus: 
 
 I made it a rule to forbear all direct contradiction to the senti- 
 ments of others, and all positive assertion of my own. I even 
 forbid myself, agreeably to the old laws of our Junto, the use 
 of every word or expression in the language that imported a 
 fix'd opinion, such as certainly, undoubtedly, etc., and I adopted, 
 instead of them, / conceive, I apprehend, or / imagine a thing to 
 be so or so; or it so appears to me at present. When another 
 asserted something that I thought an error, I deny'd myself 
 the pleasure of contradicting him abruptly, and of showing im- 
 mediately some absurdity in his proposition; and in answering 
 I began by observing that in certain cases or circumstances his 
 opinion would be right, but in the present case there appeared 
 or seem'd to me some difference, etc. I soon found the advan- 
 tage of this change in my manner; the conversations I engag'd 
 in went on more pleasantly. The modest way in which I pro- 
 pos'd my opinions procur'd them a readier reception and less 
 contradiction; I had less mortification when I was found to 
 be in the wrong, and I more easily prevail'd with others to give 
 up their mistakes and join with me when I happened to be in 
 the right. 
 
 Much, of course, depends, as Webster says, on the 
 man, the subject, and the occasion. Temperaments
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 239 
 
 differ. The orator, like the artist, may at times need 
 to draw with broad strokes particularly in summaries, 
 and at other times with a more delicate shading. Some- 
 times, too, the larger the audience the more positive 
 and unqualified the assertion required. But whenever 
 a debater gives rein to strong assertion, he should do 
 so only from a profound sincerity of belief and a full 
 knowledge of his subject based on investigation. Other- 
 wise, his abihties may be put to a severe test, when called 
 upon to defend himself by evidence and proof. 
 
 Indeed, the value of mutual confidence for practical 
 results and the idea that we beget confidence in others 
 by possessing it and exhibiting it in ourselves, is so un- 
 doubtedly true, that strong assertions which are utterly 
 false sometimes receive wide credence on this account. 
 Witness the personal rumors and stories which circulate 
 during hotly contested poHtical campaigns. 
 
 Interestedness.^ — The speaker cannot speak well un- 
 less he has the ear of his audience, nor will an audience 
 listen long to a speaker who does not possess an interest 
 in what he has to say. Any indifference in manner of 
 speaking, or in treatment of subject shown in inept 
 words or in poorly formed sentences, or in the use of 
 commonplace ideas, tends to produce inattention and 
 hstlessness. What you give, that shall you receive. The 
 speaker's concentration of attention on his subject and 
 manifestation of interest in it may be made as contagious 
 as confidence. Such a manifestation of attention will 
 naturally suggest to the audience the attitude of lis- 
 tening. It will thus give a chance to the magnetic power 
 of the speaker's personahty to assert itself, which alone 
 may fix the gaze and compel interest, and so make pos- 
 sible the necessary reaction of the audience from the
 
 240 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 stimuli employed. At all events, it is by getting the 
 attention of an audience, and, if need be, of holding it 
 on the important ideas, persistently and consistently, 
 that the speaker is able to communicate his ideas simply 
 and with force. 
 
 Thus, after a debater has completely saturated him- 
 self with his material, and ordered it for the end in view, 
 his presentation, as good or bad, will naturally depend 
 on the effect which it produces on the audience. Or per- 
 haps I should say on the unity or totality of its effects. 
 He will be able to follow the scheme of his brief more 
 effectively if he holds it in his mind neither too firmly 
 nor too loosely and can regard it readily either as a whole 
 or in its parts. Practically, a centraHty of topic is needed 
 for a suggestive development adapted to the occasion, 
 of each phase of the larger theme. He should, for ex- 
 ample, be able to say, "I propose to speak of the dan- 
 gerous consequences of the proposed measures. At the 
 outset I would picture the magnitude of the scheme," 
 and so on. Great pains should be taken with junctures 
 and transitions, or attention and interest will break down. 
 However the latter may have been originally secured, 
 they can hardly be maintained without rhetorical clear- 
 ness and logical relevancy. Words colored with mean- 
 ing, and collocated into sentences full of association or 
 paragraphs of emotional elation, are but the romance of 
 speech, of which logic and evidence are the stern reali- 
 ties. Indeed, a brilHancy of retort in debating, even if 
 provocative of applause, is not hkely to survive a mis- 
 representation of facts, whether accidental or intentional. 
 
 Avoiding Common Defects in Delivery. — The dangers 
 in manner to be guarded against in debate, says Pro- 
 fessor Winter, "are wearying monotony, overhammer-
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 241 
 
 ing — too frequent, too hard, too unifonii an emphasis — 
 too much or too continued heat, too much speed, espe- 
 cially in speaking against time, a loss of poise in the 
 bearing, halting, or jumbling in speech, nervous tension 
 in action, an overcontentious or bumptious spirit." ^ 
 To the same effect is the following criticism: 
 
 We have inherited wrong ideas about argumentative delivery. 
 
 Ninety per cent of college debaters seem to have not the 
 slightest knowledge of effective presentation. Their speaking 
 is so "preponderantly boisterous and conclusive, so disfigured 
 by volcanic fervor, for which the matter ejected affords no 
 adequate excuse," that our sensibilities are paralyzed and ren- 
 dered incapable of absorbing the evidence they produce. 
 
 I inveigh against the prevalent style of debate for several 
 reasons. First, average debating is not good public speaking. 
 Most modem authorities will accept as the definition of public 
 speaking, "enlarged and dignified conversation." The virtues 
 of good address are clearness, directness, and force. But what 
 coach can have these principles in mind and allow his team to 
 pound furiously for thirty minutes without pause or variety? 
 Confused thinking only can result. How many debaters can 
 look calmly at their audience and say implicitly: "I am talking 
 to you and you and you. I want this idea to get under your 
 skin"? No! There is a torrent of speech accompanied by vio- 
 lent shakings of the head, a flood of facts and quotations, a 
 fifteen-minute speech in ten, and a "Thank you." Now the 
 first end of aU speech is to make itself clear. Lincoln accused 
 Douglas of being like a cuttlefish, a fish that throws out a dark 
 substance into the water to hide its exact position. Again, he 
 said Judge Douglas reminded him of the little Frenchman he 
 knew in the northwest whose legs were so short that when he 
 walked through the snow the seat of his trousers rubbed out his 
 footprints. These analogies characterize the average coUege 
 debater. His speeches also lack force. Things are great or small 
 only by comparison. Ideas are made important by contrast. 
 The speech that strikes a constant key, that plunges along in 
 
 1 "Public Speaking," Irving L. Winter, p. 47.
 
 242 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 the same channel, orotund and extreme, lacks the first degree 
 of force. Yes, average debating is not good public speaking. 
 There is nothing of the human quality, no conversational style, 
 no sincere personality. Should we not pay more attention to 
 debate delivery ? 
 
 Secondly, to allow this style of speaking is to lose the ideal 
 of training a student to think on his feet. To roll forth auto- 
 matically a mass of highly concentrated data, to grind along mo- 
 notonously for ten minutes like a hand-organ, to recite parrot 
 fashion, as most debaters do, is not thinking on one's feet. The 
 chief concern of our profession — physical and psychical correla- 
 tion — is totally obscured. 
 
 Last of all, we must face the evident lack of public interest 
 in debating and overcome it. I again blame poor delivery. An 
 instructor, asked recently to judge some class try-outs, said: 
 "Yes, but I hate debates, they are bores." He served, and for 
 two hours bravely endured the agony of senseless jargon that 
 rattled upon us mercilessly as hailstones. I sympathized with 
 him. Each of the twenty speakers except one labored under 
 the delusion that because this was a debate try-out he must rant 
 and yell and glare; that a high, sustained key and lightning 
 rapidity was a proof of excellent skill and training. Shades of 
 Caesar! If they could learn to talk, just talk. 
 
 I plead, therefore, for more common sense in debate delivery, 
 more of the "just human" quality, more of conversational style. 
 I know that we are more intense and excited in a conversation 
 over Roosevelt than over Longfellow, that barber-shop con- 
 versation contains more dynamite than after-dinner talk — in 
 short, that genuine argument is the expression of deep feehng 
 and strong conviction, but let us practise more moderacy.^ 
 
 The most suggestive delivery is usually to be found 
 in the man who (i) has reduced his case to the simplest 
 terms, and (2) whose habit has been to speak extem- 
 poraneously rather than to deKver memorized orations. 
 If, for instance, his own case and that of liis opponent 
 
 ' Quarterly Journal of Speech Education, IV, 3; article by C. F. Linds- 
 ley.
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 243 
 
 have been placed in the form of a syllogism, and he is 
 properly trained in the value of the concentrated form 
 of attack, his dehvery is not so Hkely to be objection- 
 able. The fewer the points the better. In both the 
 first speech and in the rebuttal the audience will be 
 more responsive if the propositions examined are hmited 
 in number. Of course, they must be fundamental and 
 well imaged. No scattered fire or mere sharpshooting! 
 In rebuttal, indeed, it is sometimes possible to limit 
 an attack to a single point. The first speaker makes 
 an objection which is followed up by the second speaker 
 and then by the third, or, to make a football allusion, 
 the first speaker starts "an opening" which the others 
 enlarge until it "looks as big as a house." Thus, in 
 opposing the formation of a league to enforce peace, 
 I heard a negative team win a decision by a continuous 
 bombarcbnent of the contradiction contained in the 
 phrase "enforce peace," and on another occasion, by 
 an equally effective artillery-fire against "formal al- 
 hances." 
 
 If the debater has also been in the habit of speaking 
 extemporaneously he will not be likely to yell, and rave, 
 and fan the air. The training of a debater should in- 
 clude (besides an immersion in the subject-matter of 
 his debate, and the logical organization of his case) 
 such practice in speaking as will require him to think 
 clearly and express his ideas effectively on his feet. Given 
 a concept containing his fundamental reason, he should 
 be told simply to image that on the mind of the audience. 
 He will learn the value of natural, personal, and direct 
 speech. He will learn to hold his subject in mind, but 
 to look his audience in the eye, and to speak in a tone 
 which means something. He will perceive and feel the
 
 244 THE FUNDAMENTALS OF DEBATE 
 
 responses which come from meeting eye with eye, and 
 from a really communicative tone. For, speaking is but 
 a dialogue with an audience, whose responses, though 
 silent and often subconscious, are instructive guides 
 to the speaker. The extempore speaker, indeed, simply 
 converses with his audience on his topic, until he feels 
 sure that they have caught his meaning, and then, and 
 not until then, passes on to something else. We image 
 our ideas, according to Professor Winans, by centering 
 the attention of the audience upon it. It is here in 
 delivery that the "image theory" of argument as pre- 
 sented in this text meets the "attention theory" of Pro- 
 fessor Winans.^ Each supplements the other. 
 
 The Decision. — The decision of a board of judges re- 
 cords an opinion in favor of the affirmative or negative 
 sides. The judges express an opinion as to which of the 
 two sides has succeeded in satisfying certain reasonable 
 expectations or standards. These include such ideas as 
 that the debaters must be interesting, awaken sym- 
 pathy, clarify the issues, illustrate view-points common 
 to the speaker and audience, as well as be informing 
 and show an extensive knowledge of the subject-matter. 
 They must, of course, exhibit the powers of reasoning — 
 analysis and discrimination, synthesis and abstraction. 
 They must image effectively all fundamental reasons 
 so tliat they will be vividly perceived and readily be- 
 lieved, and bring to their support, whenever necessary, 
 reHable authority. They must exhibit proper platform 
 manners and form, good literary finish and style, and 
 always be quick, ready, and skilful to down an opponent 
 in triumph, with fact, authority, reason, phrase, or flash 
 of the eye. At length they must sum up, analyzing the 
 
 ^ "Public Speaking," J. A. Winans.
 
 INSTRUMENTS OF SUGGESTION 245 
 
 opponent's failure, touching on the weak spots and 
 setting forth defects, in vivid contrast with the articu- 
 lated proofs of their own side. These are some of the 
 reasonable expectations, based on customary instruc- 
 tions to judges. 
 
 No exact valuation, so far as I know, has ever been 
 fixed to the elements of good debating. Indeed, it seems 
 doubtful if any can ever be made. The elements are 
 too numerous and too uncertain in quantity, quality, 
 and relation to make it practicable. As with the painter, 
 one false detail, for instance in color, may change the 
 accent of the entire picture. Facts and logic, however, 
 should take precedence over style and delivery. 
 
 The decision should always be a measurement of 
 the relative debating skill shown by the two contesting 
 teams. Since the essence of the art of debating consists 
 in assertion and denial, proof and counter-proof with 
 distinctions, it must follow that memorized speeches 
 may defeat the purpose of debate and are, therefore, 
 a proper object of penalty. 
 
 Finally, we would note that all the elements of the 
 problem of decision in debating are variables; and that 
 the problem itself, abstractly considered, is indetermi- 
 nate; except, perhaps, that we may say that a decision 
 records a victory in a contest of supporting suggestions 
 and attacking inhibitions — arising from facts, logic, style, 
 and delivery — and modified further, quite subconsciously 
 and unintentionally, by suggestions and inhibitions, aris- 
 ing in the minds of those exercising the judicial func- 
 tion. A decision is a sincere personal opinion on the 
 ''fnerits of the debate.^'
 
 APPENDICES 
 
 APPENDIX A 
 
 Specimen Briefs 
 
 THE FIRST JUNIUS LETTER 
 
 This letter has been chosen to illustrate brief-making be- 
 cause it is believed to be one of the most remarkable bits of ar- 
 gumentative composition in our language. The argument is 
 particularly remarkable in that, while it succeeds in arousing 
 the feelings, it adheres closely to strictly logical processes, in- 
 geniously conceived and dexterously expressed. It is to be re- 
 gretted that such a brilhant argument is sometimes marred 
 by a disregard of the facts, as occurs, for instance, conspicuously 
 in the vicious attack upon the character of Justice Mansfield. 
 
 It may be explained that the first two paragraphs of this 
 letter contain the introduction, the third being transitional. 
 The fourth paragraph presents the main proposition to be proved 
 and the main syllogism. The main proposition is supported 
 further by the proposition advanced in the fifth paragraph, to 
 the proof of which the rest of the letter, excepting the last two 
 paragraphs, is devoted. These two paragraphs sum up and 
 enforce the conclusion. 
 
 A few points of divergence in the following brief from the 
 method and form of the letter may be mentioned: 
 
 The brief follows the usual sequence, first proposition, then 
 proof, regardless of the order in the letter. For example, the 
 conclusion of the main argument is presented after the premises 
 in the last sentence of the fourth paragraph; while in the brief 
 it is, of course, stated first as the proposition to be proved, and 
 is followed by the reasons marked A and B. 
 
 247
 
 248 APPENDIX 
 
 But Junius himself sometimes follows the order (i) proposi- 
 tion, (2) proof. For instance, the paragraphs containing the 
 attack upon Mansfield are so compact and coherent, that it has 
 been possible to insert in the brief the sentences of the letter with- 
 out change of order or language. Here, therefore, the brief- 
 maker has added only a classification of the proposition (as co- 
 ordinate or subordinate). 
 
 Again in the letter, a conclusion is sometimes not formally- 
 stated but only implied from a chain of reasoning; in the brief, 
 such an implied conclusion is formally expressed. Thus, the 
 proposition at the head of the introduction does not appear in 
 the letter, except as an insinuation from the four propositions of 
 the first paragraph. 
 
 Finally, in all cases in the letter, where the opposite is said 
 from what is meant, as in the criticism of Weymouth, the brief- 
 maker has discarded the irony and used the direct form of state- 
 ment. 
 
 The following brief is offered for use and criticism in study- 
 ing the principles of brief-making: analysis, classification, ar- 
 rangement, unity, logical sequence, and proportion. 
 
 BRIEF I 
 
 Introduction 
 The abuse of our loyalty naturally fills us with resentment, be- 
 cause — 
 
 [Note — This proposition is the conclusion of a syllogism, with reason- 
 ing supporting each premise.] 
 
 Argument 
 Our present ruinous condition is due to government, because 
 I. The condition of the people in a state is due to government, 
 II. Our people at present are in a ruinous condition, for 
 
 A. Perhaps there never was such an instance of a change as that 
 
 brought about by the misconduct of the present ministry. 
 
 B. After a rapid succession of changes, we are reduced to that con- 
 
 dition which hardly any change can mend, for 
 I. The King's folly and depravity are likely to have produced 
 
 it. 
 8. The true cause of our misfortunes lies in the distribution of 
 
 the departments of state, for
 
 APPENDIX 249 
 
 a. The treasury has been intrusted to the Duke of Grafton, 
 
 who is incompetent. 
 
 b. Lord North, as chancellor of the exchequer, is without 
 
 ability. 
 [Note — Similarly in this series are to be placed the attacks on c. Hills- 
 borough; d. Weymouth; e. Granby; /. Hawke; g. Mansfield.] 
 
 Conclusion 
 
 The nation is in a deplorable condition, brought about by govern- 
 ment by men without wisdom and capacity. 
 
 [First draft, drawn from the First Letter of Junius, to be studied and 
 expanded. Note carefully, in the letter, the assumption of premises not 
 stated, and the insinualion of conclusions not drawn.] 
 
 Brief I Expanded 
 
 Introduction 
 The abuse of our loyalty naturally fills us with resentment, for 
 
 A . In our own case, there has been an abuse of loyalty, for 
 
 I. A free people obey the laws, because 
 
 I. They enacted them — and 
 II. This obedience is cheerful and almost unlimited. 
 
 III. Such obedience to the guardian of the laws leads to a strong 
 
 affection for his person. 
 
 IV. This affection has often been excessive among Englishmen 
 
 who are peculiarly liable to a strong affection for his per- 
 son. 
 
 B. (All) abuses of loyalty naturally fill us with resentment. 
 
 Body 
 
 Our present ruinous condition is due to government, because 
 
 A. The condition of the people in a state is due to government, 
 
 I. From a prosperous condition of the people we argue that their 
 
 government is good, and 
 II. From a ruinous condition of the people that their government 
 is bad, for 
 I. Such a ruinous condition does not depend originally on the 
 patient multitude, for 
 a. Their indignation and excesses are effects of ill usage by 
 government rather than causes of a ruinous condition. 
 
 B. Our people at present are in a ruinous condition. 
 
 I. "Perhaps there never was an instance of a change in the cir- 
 cumstances and temper of a whole nation so sudden and
 
 250 APPENDIX 
 
 extraordinary as that which the misconduct of ministers has 
 within these very few years produced in Great Britain." 
 I. "When our gracious sovereign ascended the throne we were 
 a flourishing and contented people." 
 n. After a rapid succession of changes we are reduced to that con- 
 dition which hardly any change can mend, for 
 I. The King's folly and depravity must have produced it. 
 a. His plan has failed to produce salutary effects, is unwise, 
 and bad in design, for 
 (i) It involved the idea of uniting all parties, of trying 
 all characters, and distributing the offices of state 
 by rotation. 
 (2) It showed a capricious partiality to new faces, a nat- 
 ural turn for low intrigue and the treacherous amuse- 
 ment of double and triple negotiations. 
 
 C. The true cause of our misfortunes lies in the distribution of the de- 
 partments of state. 
 
 I. The treasury has been committed to the Duke of Grafton, 
 
 who is utterly incompetent, because 
 {A) He is already ruined by play. 
 (5) He became minister by accident, and is an apostate 
 
 by design. 
 (C) He has shown no business ability, unless a wayward in- 
 consistency be a mark of genius, for 
 I. His view of finance is to distribute, not save, the public 
 money, and 
 iP) A reliance by him on Lord North, chancellor of the ex- 
 chequer, would not deter him from being as thought- 
 less and extravagant as he pleases. 
 
 II. Lord North as chancellor of the exchequer is without ability, 
 
 for 
 {A) The absence of any proof of his talents cannot mean that 
 
 he has voluntarily concealed them. 
 (5) There is such an absence of proof, for 
 
 1. Since he has been in office, no plan has been formed 
 
 for the relief of the public credit. 
 
 2. He should think seriously of his plan to increase the 
 
 public debt, for 
 
 a. The people will not bear, after a six years' peace, 
 
 to see new millions borrowed without a diminu- 
 tion of debt or interest. 
 
 b. The attempt might arouse them beyond the sacri- 
 fice of a minister.
 
 APPENDIX 251 
 
 3. Moreover, the people expect that the debt upon the 
 
 civil list will not be paid without a strict inquiry, 
 for 
 a. A lotterj'' may be justifiable for war, but not for 
 the prince's expenses. 
 
 4. The mismanagement of the King's affairs in the House 
 
 of Commons would not be more disgraced. 
 a. (Examples.) 
 
 5. Before he became chancellor he was not derided by 
 
 his enemies or pitied by his friends. 
 m. At a most critical season, Hillsborough is made secretary to 
 govern America, and he is without capacity, for 
 (A) The season was most critical when he was made secre- 
 tary. 
 I. A series of inconsistent measures had divided the 
 colonies, for 
 a. This division resulted from the spirit and argu- 
 ment given the colonies by Lord Chatham's and 
 Lord Camden's opposition to Mr. Grenville's 
 policies. 
 {B) He is without capacity or superior knowledge, for 
 I. His despatches and measures determine this, for 
 
 a. His despatches are bad, 
 
 b. His measures are failures, for 
 
 (i) The people have been driven into excesses 
 little short of rebellion, for 
 (a) Petitions have been hindered from reaching 
 
 the throne, and 
 {b) An "arbitrary condition" had been im- 
 posed upon the General Court of Mas- 
 sachusetts which, even if it had considered 
 the temper of the people, would have 
 availed nothing. 
 (2) While at peace, our military may support him, 
 but if it be withdrawn his dismissal would 
 not console us, outraged and abused. J 
 IV. Weymouth is made secretary for the Southern Department, 
 for which he was wholly unqualified. 
 (A) Drawing lots would be a prudent and reasonable mode 
 of appointment compared to a late disposition of the 
 secretary's oiBce, for 
 I. Lord Rochford was qualified for the Southern De- 
 partment, Lord Weymouth for neither the Southern 
 nor Home Department; yet, by caprice Rochford
 
 252 APPENDIX 
 
 was appointed to the Home Department, and Wey- 
 mouth to the Southern. 
 (B) Weymouth is wholly unqualified for the Southern De- 
 partment, for 
 I. In his first employment as secretary of the Home De- 
 partment, by urging the magistrates to use the 
 military if certain disturbances in the streets should 
 continue, he acted with deliberation in carrying out 
 a headlong passion. 
 V. The Marquis of Granby as commander-in-chief is incom- 
 petent, for 
 (A) The fashion of complimenting the commander-in-chief 
 for his bravery and generosity is unwarranted, for 
 
 1. His bravery is marred by a total absence of feeling 
 
 and reflection. 
 
 2. His generosity is lacking in disinterestedness, inde- 
 
 pendence, or firmness in providing lucrative employ- 
 ments or in granting commissions in the army. 
 VI. Sir Edward Hawke as secretary of the navy is inefficient and 
 
 should be retired. 
 VII. Mansfield as chief justice is pernicious to the whole country, 
 for 
 {A) His administration has not been pure and impartial, for 
 
 1. The pure and impartial administration of justice is, 
 
 perhaps, the firmest bond to secure a cheerful sub- 
 mission of the people, and to engage their affections 
 to government. 
 
 2. It is not sufficient that questions of private right or 
 
 wrong are justly decided, nor that judges are su- 
 perior to the vileness of pecuniary corruption. 
 a. Jeffries himself, when the court had no interest, 
 was an upright judge. 
 
 3. A court of justice may be subject to another sort of 
 
 bias, more important and pernicious, as it reaches 
 beyond the interest of individuals, and affects the 
 whole community. 
 a. A judge under the influence of government may be 
 honest enough in the decision of private causes, 
 yet a traitor to the public, 
 (i) When a victim is marked out by the ministry, 
 this judge will offer himself to perform the 
 sacrifice. 
 (2) He will not scruple to prostitute his dignity 
 and betray the sanctity of his office when-
 
 APPENDIX 253 
 
 ever an arbitrary point is to be carried for 
 government or the resentment of a court to 
 be gratified. 
 (B) These principles and proceedings, odious and contemp- 
 tible as they are, in effect are no less injudicious. 
 
 1. A wise and generous people are roused by every ap- 
 
 pearance of oppressive, unconstitutional measures, 
 whether those measures are supported openly by 
 the power of government or masked under the forms 
 of a court of justice. 
 
 2. Prudence and self-preservation will oblige the most 
 
 moderate dispositions to make common cause, even 
 with a man whose conduct they censure, if they see 
 him persecuted in a way which the real spirit of the 
 laws will not justify. 
 
 3. The facts on which these remarks are founded are 
 
 too notorious to require an application. 
 
 Co7iclusion 
 I. The nation is in a deplorable condition. 
 
 II. It is governed by councils from which a reasonable man can ex- 
 pect no relief but death. 
 III. The true cause of our deplorable condition is due to government 
 by men without wisdom or integrity. 
 
 BRIEF II 
 IN DEFENSE OF DARNAY' 
 
 Introduction 
 
 I. The arrest of Darnay arose from the fact that for several years he 
 
 had been travelling between France and England. 
 II. He was tried for treason, it being declared that on these trips 
 he had borne information to the French concerning the English 
 forces in America. 
 III. The accused admitted that he had been a frequent traveller across 
 the Channel, but was unwilling to explain the trips further than 
 that they were of a private nature and involved the interests of 
 others. 
 
 IV. Whether the facts charged, if proved, legally constituted treason 
 
 was not in issue. 
 
 V. The accused, however, denied that he was guilty of treason, and 
 
 * Prepared from material in Dickens's "A Tale of Two Cities."
 
 254 APPENDIX 
 
 argued that the evidence was insuflBcient to establish the facts 
 charged. 
 
 Body 
 
 Darnay was not guilty, because 
 A. The testimony which, if true, might be damaging was false, since 
 I. John Barsad's testimony was false, for 
 
 a. In the cross-examination, he was shown to be untruthful 
 
 and altogether bad, for 
 
 1. He probably hed about his owning "property," for 
 
 (i) He would not specify the property which he swore 
 
 he owned. 
 (2) He too willingly adopted the suggestion that he had 
 
 acquired it by inheritance. 
 
 2. He admitted that he had been in a "debtor's prison," 
 
 after denying that he had been in "prison." 
 
 3. He said that his profession was simply "gentleman." 
 
 4. He admitted that he had "received a kick at the top of 
 
 a staircase and fell down of his own accord," after deny- 
 ing that he had been "kicked down-stairs." 
 
 5. He admitted that he had lived somewhat by play and 
 
 sought to extol it. 
 
 6. He admitted that he owed the accused money, but denied 
 
 that he was actuated by any other motive in this case 
 than "sheer patriotism." 
 II. Roger Cly's testimony was false, for 
 
 o. There was the greatest probability that Barsad and Cly 
 were in league and hired spies, for 
 
 1. They were both bad characters, since 
 
 (i) Cly had probably committed a theft, for 
 
 (a) He admitted having been maligned about steal- 
 ing a plated mustard-pot. 
 (&) He admitted having examined Darnay 's pockets. 
 
 2. They had known each other for "seven or eight years." 
 
 3. Their testimony was similar in respect to the motives 
 
 assigned. 
 
 b. His testimony was made worthless by the resemblance of the 
 
 accused to Carton. 
 B. The testimony which was true was not damaging, since 
 
 I. It was indefinite and could support the statement that Darnay 
 was travelling on private business, since 
 a. Lorry's testimony was chiefly as to the prisoner's travelling, 
 and the existence of a conversation between Darnay and 
 Lucy Manette.
 
 APPENDIX 255 
 
 b. Lucy Manette's testimony about this conversation revealed 
 
 nothing damaging, for 
 
 1. His remark that England's treatment of America was un- 
 
 just was unimportant, for 
 (i) It was but a casual remark. 
 
 (2) It was unlikely that a traitor should express his sym- 
 pathies openly and to a stranger. 
 
 2. His remark about George III was a "monstrous joke." 
 
 c. Doctor Manette's testimony was of no value, for 
 I. He remembered nothing. 
 
 d. The testimony of the "garrison and dockyard" witness proved 
 
 nothing against the accused, since 
 I . He failed to identify the accused as the man in the coffee- 
 house, for 
 (i) He coxild easily have mistaken Darnay for Carton. 
 
 Conclusion 
 The testimony of Barsad and of Cly was false, and Darnay was the 
 victim of a plot. The testimony of the reputable characters corroborated 
 Damay's explanation that he was travelling on private business. More- 
 over, the trustworthy witnesses showed sympathy for the accused and a 
 belief in his innocence. The evidence has, therefore, been insuflScient to 
 prove that Darnay conveyed the alleged information to the French, 
 and thus to establish the charge of treason. 
 
 APPENDIX B 
 
 Questions and Exercises 
 
 I. In General 
 
 1. Explain the importance of imaginative suggestion in pre- 
 senting an argument to an audience. 
 
 2. Distinguish between the following terms: the productive 
 and reproductive imagination, an image and an idea, an image 
 and a perception. 
 
 3. Write briefly a paragraph using other than visual imagery. 
 
 4. Illustrate the principle of description that the character- 
 istics of an object which will most readily suggest the image of 
 that object is the one most readily recalled by the particular 
 audience.
 
 256 APPENDIX 
 
 5. Select a story or anecdote from your reading, and rewrite 
 it so as to recall a person or situation, and also establish a point, 
 
 6. What are the tests of an effective image? 
 
 7. Write a brief address illustrating the perceptual and con- 
 ceptual aspects of imagery on the following plan: Image some 
 historic scene; draw inferences or lessons from it respecting 
 human life or conduct; and image these conceptions within 
 modern experience and also within the experience of the chosen 
 audience, e. g., Psalm 121. 
 
 8. Write a few paragraphs on "divided forces," illustrating 
 the principles of unity and variety. 
 
 9. Compare the imagery of a eulogy and a philippic with re- 
 spect to the appeal to the approving or the disapproving emo- 
 tions. 
 
 10. Recalling a team-debate which you have recently heard, 
 (a) suggest how the issue might have been more effectively pre- 
 sented by the use of an analogy, (b) state the main concepts of 
 each of the three speeches, and consider how each might have 
 been more effectively imaged, and (c) show how imaginative 
 suggestion might have been used in some respect so as to heighten 
 the final impression. 
 
 II. On Specific Speeches 
 
 James Otis on "Writs of Assistance." — What are the four 
 reasons which Otis states in order, against general writs? Does 
 the effectiveness of the speech really depend on these logical 
 reasons, or on the process of imaging the idea of the "tyranny 
 of the writs " on the mind of his hearers ? What types of imagery 
 does he use other than auditory? What adjectives does the 
 speaker use which possess an emotional coloring? What asso- 
 ciation-reaction do you get personally from the phrase "A 
 man's house is his castle"? How does the introduction to the 
 speech predispose one to a feehng of opposition to the writs? 
 Is the speech as a whole marked by sound thinking, by thor- 
 ough thinking, and by effective presentation? 
 
 Patrick Henry in the Virginia Convention, March 28, 1776. — 
 Make a brief of the argument proving the necessity of fighting. 
 Viewing the central idea of the speech as the "vanity of hope," 
 how does he image it on the mind of his hearers? How does he 
 in opening, inhibit the suggestions of the speaker who has pre-
 
 APPENDIX 257 
 
 ceded him, so as to make the audience susceptible to his own 
 suggestions, and to be able to state clearly the issue before the 
 country? How much of the effect of the speech is due to his 
 suggesting to his hearers specific past events or acts easily re- 
 called? How much to his constructive imagination? Point 
 out instances of Biblical allusions; of tonal imagery (euphonious 
 or cacophonous); also of illustrative imagery, and classify the 
 latter as visual, auditory, kinaisthetic, etc. What effect does 
 his use of the interrogative form of sentence produce upon at- 
 tention and interest? What use does he make of repetition and 
 of positive assertion? Is the style too rhymical? Does the 
 speech as a whole give a sufficient reason which may be recalled 
 and stated for the action it would incite? 
 
 Samuel Adams on American Independence in Philadelphia, 
 August I, 1776. — In predisposing his hearers to his point of 
 view, what common ground in thought and feeling does Samuel 
 Adams seek to establish in the introduction to his speech ? Does 
 he image this idea logically as well as emotionally? In the body 
 of the speech does he really deliberate on the matters he dis- 
 cusses, or seek simply to incite to action? By what means does 
 he inhibit the effect of the talk of "our obligations to Great 
 Britain"? In answering this first objection are his arguments 
 both sound and effective? By what illustration or analogy, 
 appealing to common experience, does he finally show that "the 
 protection we received" does not annul our rights as men? Why 
 does he so often use the rhetorical question in opening a line 
 of thought and positive assertion in concluding it? Why does 
 he seek to image the idea of the justice of independence before 
 imaging its expediency? In opposing "the doctrine of depen- 
 dence on Great Britain," point out his use of images of the pres- 
 ent and of the past as a preliminary to the suggested image of 
 the future (anticipation images). Logically, may not the under- 
 lying reasoning here be called, a priori, causal, or antecedent 
 probability? Does the argument gain in force by associating 
 it with the idea of a providential dispensation? What value 
 do you give to the kinaesthetic (muscular) image of "chaining 
 down the wolf without drawing his claws and paring his nails"? 
 Note the force of the contrasted anticipation images, the one 
 based on independence, the other on "an accommodation" which 
 would mean "the ruin of the country." In appeaUng thus both
 
 258 APPENDIX 
 
 to the approving and to the disapproving emotions, was the 
 speaker probably correct in assuming that men are influenced 
 by their fears as well as their hopes? Was the pathetic over- 
 done for those stirring times? Does he effectively turn the ob- 
 jections based on "dissensions in our popular system " by saying 
 pithily: "Suffer yourselves to be chained down by your enemies 
 that you may not be able to fight your friends" ? Regarding the 
 speech as a whole, can you truthfully characterize the argument 
 as sound (being mostly causative or exemplative) and also effec- 
 tively imaged, in that it is imaged within the general and in- 
 dividual experience of the delegates and audience of the Phila- 
 delphia State-house in the summer of 1776? 
 
 III. In Association-Reactions 
 
 I. Experiments in association-reactions are of value in study- 
 ing the nature of the processes of association. 
 
 In a small group of students inclined to co-operate, such a 
 list of words as the foUowing^ may be used: 
 
 I. table; 2. dark; 3. music; 4. sickness; 5. man; 6. deep; 7. soft; 
 8. eating; 9. mountain; 10. house; 11. black; 12. mutton; 13. comfort; 
 14. hand; 15. short; 16. fruit; 17. butterfly; 18. smooth; 19. command; 
 20. chair; 21. sweet; 22. whistle; 23. woman; 24. cold; 25. slow; 26. 
 wish; 27. river; 28. white; 29. beautiful; 30. window; 31. rough; 32. 
 citizen; s^. foot; 34. spider; 35. needle; 36. red; 37. sleep; 38. anger; 
 39. carpet; 40. girl; 41. high; 42. working; 43. sour; 44. earth; 45. 
 trouble; 46. soldier; 47. cabbage; 48. hard; 49. eagle; 50. stomach. 
 
 The simplest method consists in asking the student to an- 
 swer as quickly as possible the first word which comes to mind, 
 on hearing the stimulus-word read. Then, before proceeding, 
 the instructor may ask the group such questions as the follow- 
 ing: (i) Was the reaction a percept or a concept? (2) If the 
 former, was it a new or old image? (3) Name the principle of 
 association expressing the relation of the reaction-word to the 
 stimulus-word. 
 
 II. The experiment is also of interest if applied to sentences. 
 
 ' This list of fifty is part of a list of words used in the Kent and Rosanoff 
 tests, a full report of which may be found in the American Journal of In- 
 sanity, vol. LXVII, Nos. I and 2 — 1910.
 
 APPENDIX 259 
 
 Ask the student to hand in a list of aphorisms, epigrams, para- 
 doxes, or other striking phrases. As before, the instructor may 
 read the sentence, and ask the student to state as quickly as 
 possible the first thing which comes to mind. The answer may 
 be analyzed as before: 
 
 Illustration: Stimulus: "A rolling stone gathers no moss." 
 Reaction: i. A tramp. 2. Aimlessness. 
 The first answer was obviously a perception, the second 
 (in which more time was used) a conception. 
 Illustration: Stimulus: "Slavery closes the door of hope." 
 
 Reaction: Dante, "AU hope abandon, etc.," plainly a 
 memory image. 
 Illustration: Stimulus: "Distance lends enchantment to the view." 
 Reaction: i. The future. 2. A girl. The former is, of 
 course, conceptual, the latter perceptual, the associa- 
 tion in the second case being that of specific and gen- 
 eral, etc. 
 
 III. In trying these experiments with a group, it is interest- 
 ing to note how the reactions differ among individuals, and also 
 change with a change of mood; e. g., Stimulus: "Vanity of 
 vanities, all is vanity." Reaction: i. A pretty girl. 2. Eccle- 
 siastes. The instructor should, therefore, in analyzing the gen- 
 eral results of his experiments call attention to the different 
 type of answers given when his subjects were in a lighter mood 
 from those made in a serious frame of mind. It thus affords 
 an excellent opportunity to show how the emotions of a hearer 
 influence his reaction. 
 
 IV. Indeed, a preliminary study of audiences may be made 
 by examining the reactions had from a single sentence stimulus. 
 For example, we may classify the stimulus-sentence as the dif- 
 ficult or the easy; the abstract or the concrete; the novel, the 
 familiar, or the stale; or we may consider the association 
 awakened as stimulated by curiosity, surprise, antagonism, 
 suspense, motive, sympathy, etc., and also the influence on in- 
 terest, attention, and conviction. 
 
 V. For a study of the nature and force of imagery, (i) write 
 a statement in plain language in the form of a reason for be- 
 lieving a proposition, and (2) express this reason in figurative 
 language. Discuss each paper (or speech) fully in conference.
 
 260 APPENDIX 
 
 VI. For the stimulation of interest in the development of 
 a vocabulary, the following is suggested as a word-recognition 
 test. This list is from the "Stamford Revision of the Binet- 
 Simon Tests," by Professor L. M. Terman, published by Hough- 
 ton Miffin Company: 
 
 I. orange; 2. bonfire; 3. roar; 4. gown; 5. tap; 6. scorch; 7. puddle; 
 8. envelope; 9. straw; 10. rule; 11. haste; 12. afloat; 13. eyelash; 
 14. copper; 15. health; 16. curse; 17. guitar; 18. mellow; 19. pork; 
 20. impolite; 21. plumbing; 22. outward; 23. lecture; 24. dungeon; 
 25. southern; 26. noticeable; 27. muzzle; 28. quake; 29. civil; 30. 
 treasury; 31. reception; 32. ramble; s^. skiU; 34. misuse; 35. insure; 
 36. stave; 37. regard; 38. nerve; 39. crunch; 40. juggler; 41. majesty; 
 42. brimette; 43. snip; 44. apish; 45. sportive; 46. hysterics; 47. Mars; 
 48. repose; 49. shrewd; 50. forfeit; 51. peculiarity; 52. coinage; 53. 
 mosaic; 54. bewail; 55. disproportionate; 56. dilapidated; 57. charter; 
 58. conscientious; 59. avarice; 60. artless; 61. priceless; 62. swaddle; 
 63. tolerate; 64. gelatinous; 6.5. depredation; 65. promontory; 67. frus- 
 trate; 68. milksop; 69. philanthropy; 70. irony; 71. lotus; 72. drabble; 
 73. harpy; 74. embody; 75. infuse; 76. flaunt; 77. declivity; 78. fen; 
 79. ochre; 80. exaltation; 81. incrustation; 82. laity; 83. selectman; 
 84. sapient; 85. retroactive; 86. achromatic; 87. ambergris; 88. casuis- 
 try; 89. paleology; 90. perfunctory; 91. precipitancy; 92. theosophy; 
 93. piscatorial; 94. sudorific; 95. parterre; 96. homunculus; 97. cameo; 
 98. shagreen; 99. limpet; 100. complot. 
 
 In order to get the entire vocabulary by this test we should 
 multiply the number of correct definitions by 180. The Binet 
 tests are found to be "extremely useful in determining the mental 
 age of backward children." For vocabulary-building among 
 college students the following method is suggested. Ask the 
 student to write down the figures i to 100 in order on a sheet 
 of paper on different lines. Then the instructor may call out 
 the words in order, with its number, requiring the student (who 
 is put on his honor) to write yes or no after each number, in- 
 dicating whether or not he knows the word sufficiently to use 
 it. This test may be varied with different groups by reqiuring 
 the student to write a sentence using each of the words. 
 
 Whitney says that "the vocabulary of a rich and long culti- 
 vated language like the English may be roughly estimated at 
 joOjOoo words, but 30,000 is a very large estimate for the nurn-
 
 APPENDIX 261 
 
 ber ever used in writing or speaking by a well-educated man; 
 3,000 to 5,000, it has been carefully estimated, cover the ordinary 
 needs of a cultivated intercourse." ^ 
 
 It appears that the above vocabulary test is based on an as- 
 sumed maximum of 18,000 words for an educated person. The 
 fifteen or sixteen thousand words (derived from experiments 
 with this list on Princeton juniors and seniors) would indicate 
 a much higher average for the vocabulary of the educated, than 
 Whitney's figures suggest, were we not to make the distinction 
 that the proposed experiment is not a word-use test but a word- 
 recognition test. 
 
 It may be recalled that there is a speaking vocabulary and 
 a writing vocabulary, and that the latter is by far the larger. 
 The visual symbols of speech are greater in number for the 
 average person than the auditory; for most persons are visiles 
 rather than audiles. But even for a writing vocabulary, we 
 cannot determine by such a test as the preceding with any ac- 
 curacy the words which one would naturally use in writing; 
 for, in recording any such test, there is some suggestion that 
 the words hsted at least may be used, and some inclination 
 awakened in the subject to make the effort. The above experi- 
 ment is then offered as a word-recognition test to stimulate 
 vocabulary-building, on which we may estimate (i) the com- 
 parative vocabulary size of the different men in a group, and 
 (2) the percentage of 18,000 words recognized by each person. 
 
 APPENDIX C 
 
 The SPECLA.L Study of Imagery 
 
 I. Varied Imagery Appeals. — Since the public speaker and 
 debater must prefer the concrete to the abstract, the definite 
 to the indefinite, the specific to the general, in presenting his 
 ideas to others for decision and approval, it may well be a part 
 of the work of the advanced student to investigate the various 
 classes of imagery (visual, auditory, tactile, kinjesthetic, etc.) 
 with a view to determining the peculiar force of the several kinds 
 
 ' "Life and Growth of Language," by W. D. Whitney, p. 25.
 
 262 APPENDIX 
 
 of imagery. By such investigations and by frequent practice 
 in writing themes illustrating the several classes of imagery, 
 the student will learn both to extend his range and to diversify 
 his means of suggestion. He should endeavor not only to visual- 
 ize but also to auralize, to kincBSthetize, to tactualize, to olfactorize, 
 and to gustatorize. In such ways will he learn to make the in- 
 visible visible, the inaudible audible, and to explore the mys- 
 tery of the subconscious, so as to return to the threshold of con- 
 sciousness with its treasures. 
 
 II. Atiditory Imagery and the Disagreeable. — Adverting now to a 
 particular phase of imaginative suggestion, I shall refer to auditorj' 
 imagery in its peculiar connection with the impleasurable emotions. 
 I had asked a group of students to write a theme, using auditory imagery 
 to the exclusion, if possible, of all other forms of imagery. The results 
 were surprising, in that all the auditory images which they used dealt 
 with the disagreeable. We at once recalled other instances in point, 
 such as Patrick Henry's allusion to clanking chains on the plains of Bos- 
 ton, and John Randolph's reference to the ringing of the fire-bell as an 
 alarm associated with negro uprisings, when it occvirred to us that, if 
 there was any vital connection between the emotions arising from the 
 sense of danger and their auditory expression, it should appear in the 
 stories of that master of mystery, Edgar Allan Poe. Turning then to 
 his Tales of Horror and Death, Vol. VI (Funk and Wagnalls edition), we 
 read on the first page: 
 
 "The sentence — the dread sentence of death — was the last of distinct 
 accentuation which reached my ears. After that, the sound of the in- 
 quisitorial voices seemed merged in one dreamy, indeterminate hum. 
 It conveyed to my soul the idea of revolution — perhaps in its association 
 in fancy with the burr of a mill-wheel." And again, "I saw them writhe 
 with a deadly locution. I saw them fashion the syllables of my name; 
 and I shuddered because no sound succeeded." We were reading from 
 "The Pit and the Pendulum," and were thus quickly rewarded. A little 
 further on, we found the climax of a paragraph of fear (describing the 
 sweep of the pendulum, razor-like, and heavy, and rapidly descencUng) 
 expressed in the following sentence: "It was appended to a weighty 
 rod of brass, and the whole hissed as it swung thro' the air." The tale 
 ends thus: "There was a discordant hum of human voices ! There was 
 a loud blast as of many tnimpets ! There was a harsh grating as of a 
 thousand thunders! The fiery walls rushed back! ..." 
 
 Running through the thirteen tales contained in this volume and 
 glancing at the last paragraph or two, we found that the climax in each 
 tale contained auditory imagery. We hear the "long, wild, and con-
 
 APPENDIX 263 
 
 tinuous shriek of agony" of the subterranean night in "The Premature 
 Burial," the "low laugh" and the "sad voice" and the "jingling of the 
 bells" in the catacombs in "The Cask of Amontillado"; the loud din of 
 " voices " in " The Tell-Tale Heart," including " the beating of his hideous 
 heart"; the "reverberation" of blows, and "screams" and "howls," 
 in "The Black Cat," which in "The Fall of the House of Usher" become 
 a "fierce breath of the whirlwind" and "tumultuous shouting sounds." 
 It was pleasing to pass then from the "shriek" and the "rattling sounds" 
 of "Berenice" to the quieter ending of "Eleanora." "And once — but 
 once again in the silence of the night — there came thro' mj' lattice the 
 soft sighs which had forsaken me; and they modelled themselves into a 
 familiar and sweet voice saying: 'Sleep in peace, for the spirit of Love 
 reignethandruleth.' " "Ligeia" and"MoreIla" are no exceptions to the 
 climactic use of auditory expressions in the field of the horrible. The last 
 tale in the volume, "Shadow — A Parable," concludes as follows: "And 
 then did we. the seven, start from our scats in horror and stand trembling 
 and shuddering and aghast, for the tones in the voice of the shadow 
 were not the tones of any one being, but of a multitude of beings, and 
 var>'ing in their cadences from syllable to syllable, fell duskly upon our 
 ears in the well-remembered and familiar accents of many thousand 
 departed friends." 
 
 Poe's tales, though making constant use of other imagery, thus con- 
 firm the value of auditory imagery for the expression of the emotions 
 of fear and horror, and show its peculiar fitness to express great heights 
 and depths of feeling. I find that Professor Scott has observed that 
 "presentations which awaken auditory images are more productive of 
 terror than those which awaken images of sight." Orators, novelists, 
 and poets in general use visual imagery more than auditor}'. In this 
 connection it is interesting to note that such a poet as Browning 
 in "Childe Roland" uses an auditory climax in a poem which elsewhere 
 is almost completely visual. Indeed, we are justified, I think, in speak- 
 ing of the peculiar power of auditory imagery to express the climax of 
 fear and terror. 
 
 The question at once arises as to why this should be the case. The 
 first explanation which occurred to me was suggested by Poe also. On 
 one occasion when the menacing danger, in "The Pit and the Pendulum," 
 became too great, the prisoner closed his eyes, and on another he averted 
 his head. It may well be that we have very little stored-up visual imagery 
 of the disagreeable, because of our desire to avoid it and our ability to 
 shut out the sight of it. We instinctively close our eyes to the disagree- 
 able, but we cannot close our ears ! In the second place, a large part of 
 our time is spent in darkness, when the eye cannot see impending danger, 
 and the ear must be relied on to give the warning. For such physical 
 reasons it would seem that man may have developed, through the ages,
 
 264 APPENDIX 
 
 his peculiar auditory sensitiveness to danger, with its accompanying 
 emotional apparatus. So the imagination of the artist would naturally 
 describe by auditory suggestion scenes too horrible to be optically ob- 
 served.^ 
 
 Images of fear and horror may, of course, be other than audi- 
 tory. For example: 
 
 "I have almost forgot the taste of fears 
 The time has been my senses would have cooled to hear a night- 
 shriek!" 
 
 There are doubtless persons who viill think of the phrase "to 
 taste of fear" as unreal, just as there are persons who see a literal 
 inaccuracy in Hamlet's taking up arms against a sea of trouble — 
 a phrase, however, accurately marking the perturbation of his 
 mental state when contemplating suicide. During the strong 
 excitation of fear, indeed, all the senses will of course be affected, 
 and the writer is unwilling to admit the unreality of a gustatory 
 reaction from a disagreeble stimulus. How the mouth of a child 
 expands, for instance, when fed with sugar, and draws up when 
 it is given medicine ! Again, does Shakespeare use this gusta- 
 tory image: 
 
 " Cowards die many times before their death, 
 The valiant never taste of death but once." 
 
 A close study, either of Shakespeare's great tragedies or of 
 Poe's tales of horror, will show innumerable ways in which the 
 effect of fear on the human frame may be imaged. The mouth 
 may be parched and dry, the throat choked, the cheeks blanched, 
 the eyes start, the hair stand up, the voice speechless, the muscles 
 powerless to move; and as the blood rushes with increasing 
 force through the veins, the only conscious thing to engage us 
 may be the sound of the beating of our own heart. 
 
 III. Auditory Imagery and the Agreeable. — Likewise, audi- 
 tory imagery appeahng to the pleasurable emotions is quite 
 common: 
 
 * The Qitarterly Journal of Piiblic Speaking, II, 2, 181, by H. F. Coving- 
 ton.
 
 APPENDIX 265 
 
 "Let music swell the breeze, 
 And ring from all the trees, 
 
 Sweet freedom's song 1 
 Let mortal tongues awake, 
 Let all that breathe partake. 
 Let rocks their silence break, — 
 The sound prolong." 
 
 — America. 
 
 In the description of the dawn in Milton's "L'AUegro," we 
 hear the "lark" startling the dull night, the "cock" with his 
 lively din, and the "ploughman" whistling o'er the furrowed 
 land. As an illustration in prose, the last sentence of Lincoln's 
 First Inaugural contains auditory imagery: 
 
 The mystic chords of memory, stretching from every battle-field and 
 patriot-grave to every living heart and hearthstone all over this broad 
 land, will yet swell the chorus of the Union when again touched, as 
 surely they will be, by the better angels of our nature. 
 
 Here, such phrases as "the mystic chords of memory," "the 
 chorus of the Union," etc., as well as the rhythmic beat of the 
 line, produce a decidedly agreeable effect on the emotions. Tonal 
 imagery has a less important place in prose than in poetry, 
 and in argument than in some other prose forms, but even in 
 argument it may play an important part. The word "muck," 
 for instance, in the phrase "man with a muck-rake," expresses 
 a disapproved idea in a word tonally unpleasant; so, too, "in- 
 nocuous desuetude" and "profiteering." On the other hand, 
 "selective draft" is a happy substitute for the rather harsh term 
 "conscription." 
 
 It is a constant source of surprise to find how little auditory 
 illustrative imagery is used even in spoken discourse. This 
 may be due in part to the fact that the rhythm of speech makes 
 it appeal to the ear. At all events, we should encourage a variety 
 of appeal through diversified forms. 
 
 IV. Mixed Imagery Types. — Scientific investigations of an 
 important character have already been made of mental imagery. 
 The results tend to show marked differences in the kind of 
 imagery used by different persons, and by the same persons 
 under changed conditions. A report of the psychological experi-
 
 266 APPENDIX 
 
 ments conducted by Doctor Fernald, in which eleven trained 
 students of imagery were the subjects, should be of interest. 
 In general: 
 
 The individual differences in imagery are too complex to be stated 
 adequately in terms of difference in "type" unless this type is carefully 
 explained for each individual case. An adequate statement of an in- 
 dividual's imagery type would involve an account of the kinds of imagery 
 used in various representative situations, with an estimate of their 
 relative importance and a discussion of the characteristics of such imagery 
 under the varying conditions.^ 
 
 The investigator, however, was able to divide her eleven sub- 
 jects into two groups: 
 
 (i) The more versatile, who seem to use visual-auditory and vocal- 
 motor forms with perfect ease, changing from one to another with change 
 in the material, or using all forms in handling one kind of material. 
 
 (2) The other group consists of those subjects who have certain 
 specially favored kinds of imagery which they use with considerable 
 constancy in the various tests, and who practically omit, as far as actual 
 use is concerned, certain other forms.^ 
 
 Visual imagery, as might be supposed, was found to be most 
 extensively and consistently used, with auditory imagery rank- 
 ing next in order. 
 
 In the first place, one positive result, which is of considerable im- 
 portance for our general diagnosis, is the discovery that none of our 
 subjects report an absolute lack of msual Illustrative imagery. More- 
 over, all but three report at least occasional instances of auditory, and 
 these three express themselves not as absolutely certain of its absence, 
 but rather as exceedingly dubious of its presence.- 
 
 Again: 
 
 Investigation shows a decided preponderance of visual imagery over 
 the auditory for the majority of subjects. In no case did the auditory 
 images surpass the visual in amount.- 
 
 1 "Mental Imagery," by Mabel Ruth Fernald. The Psychological 
 Monographs, vol. XIV, No. 58, p. 130. 
 '^ Ibid., pp. 131-132.
 
 APPENDIX 267 
 
 Moreover: 
 
 Again and again where auditory imager>' is suggested, only the visual 
 image of the sounding object appears. In certain cases the significance 
 of a phrase is even changed to favor the visual rather than the auditory. 
 Thus, both G. and T. report, independently of one another, that the 
 "low-crying birds" of passage were thought of as "low-flying birds" 
 with appropriate visual imagery. G. also transformed the "drowsy 
 tinklings" of No. 20 into twinklings of star lights. 
 
 In general, then, we may say, for the majority of our subjects, that, 
 under the conditions of reading and listening, a greater susceptibility 
 is shown to the suggestion of accompanying visual imagery than to that 
 of accompanjnng sounds. We cannot state with certainty the explana- 
 tion of this, but in all probability several causes conspire together to 
 produce the effect. It may be true, as Segal, Meumann, and others have 
 said, that visual is the prevailing form of concrete imagery throughout 
 the thinking of the majority of persons, because visual objects have 
 a much greater practical significance for most of us than do sounds. It 
 may also be due to the fact that, while we constantly experience visual 
 objects which give no sound, we seldom experience sounds without some 
 sounding object which can be or has been seen. In the reading process, 
 the fact that most of our subjects have a running accompaniment of 
 auditory-vocal-motor verbal imagery may help to account for the de- 
 ficiency in auditory concrete imagery, since one of these may inhibit 
 the other. Another consideration seems pertinent, that sounds may 
 get a fairly adequate representation through changes in the inflection 
 in reading and through the onomatopoetic effect of many of the words — 
 a representation which the visual entirely lacks.^ 
 
 Other Jorvis of imagery, as revealed in the above investigation, 
 are commented upon specifically, as follows: 
 
 With regard to the other forms of possible imagery the best we can 
 do is to note their presence or absence in the few cases of more or less 
 vivid description. Cold, for example, is introduced in a very striking 
 way in No. 7, yet only one subject reported any Icmperalurc imagery, 
 though some observed organic reactions (shivering, etc.), or visual rep- 
 resentation of its effects. Cold is also an element of the situation in 
 No. 24, in connection with the wet, and in No. 28, in the reference to 
 the wind, yet we find it mentioned by only one subject in the former 
 case and then as questioned, and in the latter case only three report it. 
 Warmth is mentioned in several passages but appears most vividly in 
 
 ' Ibid., pp. 41-44.
 
 268 APPENDIX 
 
 No. 24, where it appears twice — in the reference to the heat of the night 
 and in the account of the touch of the warm animal — yet none of the 
 subjects report it for the first case and only four for the latter. For 
 contact, No. 24 again gives us the best instance. Here there are two 
 very striking references — the touching of the animal and the feeling of 
 the tongue on the palm. Most of the subjects get at least one of these, 
 and all commented on the cleverness of the description. Olfactory 
 material is fairly well suggested in at least four selections, yet there is 
 noticeably little imagery aroused. With kincesthetic and organic material 
 we have the same sort of problem that we had with the vocal-motor, 
 that of distinguishing between imagery and actual reinstatement of 
 sensations. Again, aside from the certainty that in many cases it is 
 the latter, we have had to leave the problem unsolved. ^ 
 
 Two of the passages used in Doctor Fernald's tests are given 
 below — (7) and (24). The first may illustrate the little-used 
 imagery of cold, and the second of warmth, as well as many other 
 kinds of imagery. 
 
 (7) "St. Agnes' Eve — ah, bitter chill it was! 
 The owl, for all his feathers, was a-cold; 
 The hare limp'd trembling through the frozen grass, 
 And silent was the flock in woolly fold; 
 Numb were the Beadsman's fingers while he told 
 His rosary, and while his frosted breath. 
 Like pious incense from a censer old, 
 Seem'd taking flight for heaven without a death. 
 Past the sweet Virgin's picture, while his prayer he saith.'' 
 —Keats: " St. Agnes' Eve," ist stanza.^ 
 
 (24) An oppressive slumber hung about the forest branches. In 
 the dells and on the heights was the same dead heat. Here where the 
 brook tinkled it was no cool-hpped sound, but metallic, and without 
 the spirit of water. . . . The breathless silence was significant, yet 
 the moon shone in a broad blue heaven. Tongue out of mouth trotted 
 the httle dog after him; couched panting when he stopped an instant; 
 rose weariedly when he started afresh. Now and then a large white 
 night-moth flitted through the dusk of the forest. ... All at once the 
 thunder spoke. . . . Then there were pauses, and the lightning seemed 
 as the eye of heaven, and the thunder as the tongue of heaven, each 
 alternately addressing him; filling him with awful rapture. . . . Lower 
 down the lightened abysses of air rolled the wrathful crash; then white 
 
 J Ihid., pp. 41-44. ' Ihid., Appendix.
 
 APPENDIX 2G9 
 
 thrusts of light were darted from the sky, and great curving ferns, seen 
 steadfast in pallor a second, were supernaturally agitated and vanished. 
 Then a shrill song roused in the leaves and herbage. Prolonged and 
 louder it sounded, as deeper and heavier the deluge pressed. A mighty 
 force of water satisfied thp desire of the earth. Even in this, drenched 
 as he was by the first oatpouring, Richard had a savage pleasure. 
 Keeping in motion, he was scarcely conscious of the wet, and the grate- 
 ful breath of the weeds was refreshing. Suddenly he stopped short, lift- 
 ing a curious nostril. He fancied he smelt meadow-sweet. . . . He was 
 sure he smelt it fresh in dews. . . . After two or three steps he 
 stooped and stretched out his hand to feel for the flower, having, he 
 knew not why, a strong wish to verify its growth there. Groping 
 about, his hand encountered something warm that started at his touch, 
 and he, with the instinct we have, seized it, and lifted it to look at it. 
 The creature was very small, evidently quite young. Richard's eyes, 
 now accustomed to the darkness, were able to discern it for what it was, 
 a tiny leveret. ... He put the httle thing on one hand in his breast, 
 and stepped out rapidly as before. 
 
 The rain was now steady: from every tree a fountain poured. So 
 cool and easy had his mind become that he was speculating on what 
 kind of shelter the birds could find, and how the butterflies and moths 
 saved their colored wings from washing. . . . He was next musing on 
 a strange sensation he experienced. It ran up one arm with an inde- 
 scribable thrill, but communicated nothing to his heart. It was purely 
 physical, ceased for a time and recommenced, till he had it all through 
 his blood, wonderfully thrilling. He grew aware that the little thing 
 he carried in his breast was licking his hand there. The small rough 
 tongue going over and over the palm of his hand produced the strange 
 sensation he felt. — {Meredith: "Richard Feverel," chap. XLII.)i 
 
 APPENDIX D 
 
 The Imagery oe Argument and of Poetry 
 
 By contrasting the sermons of Jonathan Edwards relating 
 to hell with the treatment by Dante of the same theme in the 
 "Inferno," Doctor DeWitt makes clear the purely incidental 
 function of imagery in argument and its prime function in 
 poetry. He cites in illustration the passage when Dante was sail- 
 ing through the Lake of Mud in the Fifth Circle of Hell. The 
 
 ' Ibid., Appendix.
 
 270 APPENDIX 
 
 latter, it will be recalled, made reply to Philippe Argenti: "Mas- 
 ter, I should like to see him ducked in this broth before we de- 
 part from the lake." 
 
 There is nothing in Edwards which, so far as I can judge, equals this 
 in its horrid imagery and suggestion. And yet men enjoy Dante and 
 the "Inferno." They do not "execrate" him for a "monster," as Doctor 
 Allen says they do Edwards. And in his great essay on Dante, Mr. 
 James Russell Lowell makes this very scene the text of an eloquent lauda- 
 tion of Dante's moral quality, in which he says of him: "He believed 
 in the righteous use of anger, and that baseness was its legitimate quarry." 
 Why is it that the attitude of the general public, thus represented by 
 Mr. Lowell, toward the hell of Dante is so different from the attitude 
 of the same public toward the hell of Edwards? I think we shall find 
 an answer to this question in what I may call Edwards's spiritual realism. 
 Of course, Dante is a realist also. How often this quality of his poem 
 has been pointed out to us ! But Dante's is the realism of the artist, 
 the poet who appeals to our imagination. Our imagination being grati- 
 fied, we enjoy the picture and even the sensations of horror which the 
 picture starts. Of all this there is nothing in Edwards. There is no 
 picture at all. There is scarcely a symbol. Here and there there is an 
 illustration. But the illustrations of Edwards are never employed to 
 make his subject vivid to the imagination. They are intended simply 
 to explicate it to the understanding. The free, responsible, guilty, and 
 immortal spirit is immediately addressed; and the purely spiritual ele- 
 ments of the hell of the wicked, separated from all else, are made to ap- 
 pear in their terrible nakedness before the reason and the conscience. 
 The reason and the conscience respond. We are angry because startled 
 out of our security. And we call him cruel, because of the conviction 
 forced on us that we are in the presence of a terrible, even if mysterious, 
 spiritual reality. Edwards always spoke, not to the imagination, but 
 to the responsible spirit. Men realized when he addressed them that 
 because they are sinners their moral constitution judicially inflicts upon 
 their personality remorse; and that remorse is an absolute, immitigable 
 and purely spiritual pain, independent of the conditions of time and 
 space and, therefore, eternal.' 
 
 Imagery is merely an instrument used in communicating our 
 ideas to others. The chief function of Dante's imagery was to 
 make vivid; that of Edwards generally to explicate. The latter, 
 moreover, appealed to the reason, the understanding, and the 
 
 » " Jonathan Edwards, a Study," by John DeWitt,
 
 APPENDIX 271 
 
 responsible will. This, indeed, is "the serious business" of argu- 
 ment, as expounded by the philosopher Kant: 
 
 The arts of speech are rhetoric and poetry. Rhetoric is the art of 
 carrying on a serious business of the understanding as if it were a free 
 play of the imagination; poetr>' the art of conducting a free play of the 
 imagination as if it were a serious business of the understanding. 
 
 The orator then promises a serious business, and in order to entertain 
 his audience conducts it as if it were a mere play with ideas. The poet 
 merely promises an entertaining play with ideas, and yet it has the same 
 effect upon the understanding as if he had only intended to carry on 
 its business.' 
 
 The same authority recognizes the impressiveness of per- 
 suasion, but condemns its use before judgments are formed: 
 
 Rhetoric, in so far as this means the art of persuasion, i. e., of deceiv- 
 ing by a beautiful show (ars oratoria), and not a mere elegance of speech 
 (eloquence and style), is a dialectic, which borrows from poetry only so 
 much as is needful to win minds to the side of the orator before they 
 have formed a judgment and to deprive them of their freedom; it cannot, 
 therefore, be recommended either for the law-courts or the pulpit.* 
 
 The legitimate use of persuasion has been previously dis- 
 cussed; rhetoric is not deceptive and need not, of course, be 
 employed to "win minds to the side of the orator before they 
 have formed a judgment." Verily, truth and justice may as 
 well surrender in despair, if, for instance, we deprive the speaker 
 of the right to induce in the hearer a willingness to listen in- 
 cluding an interest in doing so, or the right to implant a wish 
 to know what is true and just. 
 
 Indeed, though Kant always fears and often assumes the 
 abuse of persuasion, he recognizes its use as legitimate and proper 
 when employed "in a lively sympathy with what is truly good ": 
 
 The man who, along with a clear insight into things, has in his power 
 a wealth of pure speech, and who with a fruitful imagination capable 
 of presenting his ideas unites a lively sympathy with what is truly good, 
 is the vir bonus dicendi perilits, the orator without art but of great im- 
 pressiveness, as Cicero has it; though he may not always remain true 
 to this ideal.' 
 
 ' "Kant's Kritik of Judgment," translated by J. H. Bernard, p. 207.
 
 272 APPENDIX 
 
 Further, we may agree with Kant in his appreciation and 
 glorification of poetry, without accepting his impUcations as 
 necessary, in so far as they involve the honesty of the orator. 
 Oratory is no more illusory or deceptive than poetry. It is dif- 
 ficult to conceive, for instance, how the penumbrations of con- 
 notative words are more Hable to mislead in prose than in the 
 rhythmic beats of verse. Certainly, we may properly image a 
 concept in prose; soundly as respects the truth, honestly as 
 respects the individual who utters it, and effectively as respects 
 the hearer, if driven home with all the sensible and supersen- 
 sible instruments of utterance which God has given us to make 
 the truth prevail ! At all events, in debating, the preHminary 
 analysis and investigation of all the material relating to a sub- 
 ject and the opportunity for the immediate detection and ex- 
 posure of error by means of the rebuttals are sufficient preven- 
 tives of misrepresentation. The debater who is careless or dis- 
 honest carries within him the seeds of his own destruction. 
 
 APPENDIX E 
 
 Addresses 
 I 
 
 "PEACE FOUNDED ON THE ROCK OF VINDICATED 
 
 JUSTICE "1 
 
 Lloyd George's Guildhall Address 
 
 My Lord Mayor, my Lords, Ladies, and Gentlemen: The 
 chancellor of the exchequer [Bonar Law] in his extremely lucid 
 and impressive speech has placed before you the business side 
 of this proposal, and I think you will agree with me, after hear- 
 ing his explanation of his scheme, that he has offered for sub- 
 scription a loan which possesses all the essential ingredients of 
 an attractive investment. They are the most generous terms 
 
 1 This address, which was delivered at the Guildhall London, January 
 II, 1917, appealed primarily for subscriptions to the new war loan, but 
 also touched largely upon questions in the peace discussions.
 
 APPENDIX 273 
 
 that the government can offer without injury to the taxpayer. 
 I agree that the chancellor was right in offering such liberal 
 terms because it is important that we should secure a big loan 
 now, not merely in order to enable us to finance the war effec- 
 tively, but as a demonstration of the continued resolve of this 
 country to prosecute the war; and it is upon that aspect of the 
 question that I should like to say a few words. 
 
 The German Kaiser a few days ago sent a message to his 
 people that the Allies had rejected his peace offers. He did so 
 in order to drug those whom he could no longer dragoon. Where 
 are those offers? We have asked for them; we have never seen 
 them. We were not offered terms; we were offered a trap baited 
 with fair words. They tempted us once, but the lion has his eyes 
 open. We have rejected no terms that we have ever seen. Of 
 course, it would suit them to have peace at the present moment 
 on their terms. We all want peace; but when we get it it must 
 be a real peace. 
 
 The allied powers separately and in council together have 
 come to the same conclusion. Knowing well what war means, 
 knowing especially what this war means in suffering, in burdens, 
 in horrors, they have still decided that even war is better than 
 peace at the Prussian price of domination over Europe. We 
 made it clear in our reply to Germany; we made it still clearer 
 in our reply to the United States. 
 
 Before we attempt to rebuild the Temple of Peace we must 
 see now that the foundations are solid. They were built before 
 upon the shifting sands of Prussian faith; henceforth, when 
 the time for rebuilding comes, it must be on the rock of vin- 
 dicated justice. 
 
 I have just returned from a council of war of the four great 
 allied countries upon whose shoulders most of this terrible war 
 falls. I cannot give you its conclusions; they might be informa- 
 tion to the enemy. There were no delusions as to the magni- 
 tude of our task; neither were there any doubts about the re- 
 sults. 
 
 I think I can say what was the feeling of every man there. 
 It was one of the most businesslike conferences I ever attended. 
 We faced the whole situation, probed it thoroughly, and looked 
 its difiQculties in the face, and made arrangements to deal with 
 them. We separated feeling more confident than ever. All
 
 274 APPENDIX 
 
 felt that if victory were difficult, defeat was impossible. There 
 was no flinching, no wavering, no faint-heartedness, no infirmity 
 of purpose. 
 
 There was a grim resolution at all costs that we must achieve 
 the high aim with which we accepted the challenge of the Prus- 
 sian military caste and rid Europe and the world forever of her 
 menace. No country could have refused the challenge without 
 the loss of honor. None could have rejected it without impair- 
 ing national security. No one would have failed to take it up 
 without forfeiting something which is of greater value to every 
 free and self-respecting people than life itself. Those nations 
 did not enter into the war lightly. They did not embark upon 
 this enterprise without knowing what it really meant. They 
 were not enticed by the prospects of immediate victory. 
 
 Take this country. The millions of our men who enlisted in 
 the army enlisted after the German victories of August, 1914, 
 when they knew the accumulated and concentrated power of 
 the German military machine. That was when they placed 
 their lives at the disposal of their country. What about the 
 other lands? They knew what they were encountering; that 
 they were fighting an organization which had been perfected 
 for generations by the best brains of Prussia — perfected with 
 one purpose, the subjugation of Europe. 
 
 Why did they do it? I passed through hundreds of miles 
 of the beautiful land of France and of Italy, and as I did so I 
 asked myself this question: Why did the peasants leave by 
 myriads these sunny vineyards and corn-fields in France ? Why 
 did they quit these enchanting valleys, with their comfort, their 
 security, their charm, in order to face the grim and wild horrors 
 of the battle-field? They did it for one purpose, and one pur- 
 pose only. They were not driven to the slaughter by Kings. 
 These are great democratic countries. No government would 
 have lasted twenty-four hours that had forced them into an 
 abhorrent war against their own free will. They embarked 
 upon it because they knew the fundamental issue had been raised 
 which no country could shirk without imperilling all that has 
 been won in the centuries of the past and all that remains to 
 be won in the ages of the future. 
 
 That is why, as the war proceeds and the German purpose 
 becomes more manifest, the conviction is becoming deeper in
 
 APPENDIX 275 
 
 the minds of those people that they must work their way through 
 to victory in order to save Europe from an unspeakable 
 despotism. That was the spirit that animated the allied con- 
 ference in Europe last week. 
 
 But I tell you one thing that struck me, and strikes me more 
 and more each time I attend these conferences and visit the 
 Continent: the increasing extent to which the allied peoples 
 are looking to Great Britain. They are trusting her rugged 
 strength and great resources more and more. She is to them 
 like a great tower in the deep. She is becoming more and more 
 the hope of the oppressed and despair of the oppressor; and I 
 feel more and more confident that we shall not fail the people 
 who put their trust in us. 
 
 But when that arrogant Prussian caste flung the signature 
 of Britain in the treaty in the waste-paper basket as if it were 
 of no account, they knew not the pride of the land they were 
 treating with such insolent disdain. They know it now. Our 
 soldiers and our sailors have taught them to respect it. You 
 had an eloquent account from my colleague, the chancellor of 
 the exchequer, of the achievements of our soldiers; our sailors 
 are gallantly defending the honor of the country on the high 
 seas. They have strangled the enemy's commerce; they will 
 continue to do so in spite of all the piratical devices of the foe. 
 
 In 1914 and 191 5, for two years, a small, ill-equipped army 
 held up the veterans of Prussia, with the best equipment in 
 Europe; in 1916 hurling them back and delivering a blow from 
 which they are reeling. In 1917 the armies of Britain will be 
 more formidable than ever in training, in efficiency, in equip- 
 ment; and you may depend upon it, if you give them the neces- 
 sary support, they will cleave a road to victory through the 
 dangers and perils of the next few months. 
 
 But we must support them; they are worth it. Have you 
 ever talked to a soldier who has come back from the front? 
 There is not one of them who will not tell you how he is 
 encouraged and sustained by hearing the roar of the guns be- 
 hind him. 
 
 I will tell you what I want to do. I want to see checks hur- 
 tling through the air, fired from the city of London; fired from 
 every city, town, and village and hamlet throughout the land; 
 fired straight into the intrenchraents of the enemy.
 
 276 APPENDIX 
 
 Every well-directed check, well loaded, properly primed, is 
 a more formidable weapon of destruction than a twelve-inch 
 shell. It clears a path to the barbed-wire entanglements for 
 our gallant fellows to march through. A big loan helps you, 
 insures victory; a big loan will help shorten the war; it will 
 help save lives; it will help save the British Empire; it will 
 help save Europe; it will help save civilization. 
 
 That is why we want the country to rise to this occasion and 
 show that the old spirit of Britain, represented by those great 
 men [pointing to the monuments in the hall] you have here, is 
 still alive, alert, and as potent as ever. 
 
 I want to appeal to the men at home — yes, and to the women. 
 I want to appeal to both; they have done their part nobly in 
 this war. A man who has been a munitions minister for twelve 
 months must feel a debt of gratitude to the women for what 
 they have done. They have helped to win the war, and with- 
 out them we could not have done it; but I want to make special 
 appeal, or rather to enforce the special appeal of the chancellor 
 of the exchequer. 
 
 Let no money be squandered in luxury and indulgence which 
 can be put into the fight and which counts — every penny of 
 it; every ounce has counted in this struggle. Do not waste it, 
 do not throw it away; put it there to help the valor of our brave 
 young boys. Back them up ! Let every one contribute to as- 
 sist them, with greater pride in it than in costly garments. It 
 will become them; they will feel prouder of it to-day, and their 
 pride will increase in the years to come, when the best garment 
 they have got will have rotted, when the glisten and glitter of 
 it will improve with the years. They can put it on in old age 
 and say, "This is something I contributed in the great war," 
 and they will be proud of it. 
 
 Men and women of England, Scotland, Wales, and Ireland! 
 The first charge upon all your surplus money, over your needs 
 for yourselves and your children, should be to help those gallant 
 young men who tendered their lives to the cause of humanity. 
 The more we get the surer the victory; the more we get the 
 shorter the war; the more we get the less it will cost in treasure, 
 and the greatest treasure of all is brave blood. The more we 
 give the more you will be enriched by your contribution, by 
 your sacrifices of extravagance.
 
 APPENDIX 277 
 
 I want to bring this home to every man and woman. This 
 extravagance during the war has cost blood — valiant blood, 
 the blood of heroes. It will be worth millions to save one of 
 them — the big loan will save myriads of them. Help them not 
 merely to win; help them to come home, to shout for the vic- 
 tory which they have won. 
 
 It means better equipment for our troops, it means better 
 equipment for the Allies as well; and this I say for the fiftieth, 
 if not the hundredth, time: this is a war of equipment. That is 
 why we are appealing for your assistance. Most of us could 
 not do more, but what we can do it is our duty, it is our pride, 
 to do. 
 
 I said it was a war of equipment. Why are the Germans 
 pressing back our gallant Allies in Rumania? It is not that 
 they are better fighters; they certainly are not. The Rumanian 
 peasant has proved himself to be one of the doughtiest fighters 
 in the field when he has the chance — he never had much — and 
 as for the Russian, the way in which, with bared breast, he has 
 fought for two years and a half, with inferior guns, insufiicient 
 rifles, inadequate supplies of ammunition, is one of the tales 
 of heroism of the world. 
 
 Let us help to equip them, and there will be another story 
 to tell soon; but it is for us to do so, and that is why I am glad 
 to follow the chancellor of the exchequer in the appeal he has 
 made to the patriotism of our race — but with true Scottish in- 
 stinct he put the appeal to prudence first. He had a good founda- 
 tion for patriotism, and reserved that for his peroration. I am 
 going to reverse the order, belonging to a less canny race. I 
 want to say it is a good investment, after all; the old country 
 is the best investment in the world. It was a sound concern 
 before the war; it will be sounder and safer than ever after the 
 war, and especially safer. 
 
 I do not know the nation that will care to touch it after this 
 war. They had forgotten what we were like in those days, and 
 it will take them a long time to forget these. It will be a safer 
 investment than ever, and a sounder one. 
 
 Have you been watching what is going on? Before the war 
 we had a good many shortcomings in our business, our com- 
 merce, our industry. The war is settling them all right in the 
 most marvellous way. You ask a great business man like my
 
 278 APPENDIX 
 
 friend, Lord Pirrie, what is going on in those great factories 
 throughout Great Britain and Ireland. Old machinery is 
 scrapped; the newest, the best, and the latest is set up; slip- 
 shod and wasteful methods are scrapped, and hampering cus- 
 toms discontinued. Millions are brought into the labor-market 
 to help to produce who were before purely consumers. 
 
 I do not know what the national debt will be at the end of 
 this war, but I will make a prediction: whatever it is, what is 
 added in real assets to the real riches of the nation will be in- 
 finitely greater than any debt we ever acquire. The resources 
 of the nation in every direction have been developed and di- 
 rected; the nation itself disciplined, braced up, quickened, has 
 become a more alert people. We have thrown off the useless 
 tissues; we are a nation that has been taking exercise. We 
 are a different people. 
 
 I will tell you another thing: the Prussian menace was a run- 
 ning mortgage which detracted from the value of our national 
 security. Nobody knew what it meant. We know too well 
 now. You could not tell whether it meant millions or hundreds 
 of millions or thousands of millions, or how many of them. You 
 could not tell that it would not mean ruin. 
 
 That mortgage will be cleared off forever — better security 
 on a better foundation, safer security, and at a better rate of 
 interest. The world will then be able, when this war is over, 
 to attend to its business in peace. There will be no war or rumors 
 of war to disturb and to distract. We can build up, we can re- 
 construct, we can till, we can cultivate and enrich, and the burden 
 and terror and waste of war will have gone. 
 
 The peace and security for peace will be that the nations will 
 band themselves together to punish the first peacebreaker who 
 comes out. 
 
 As to the armies of Europe, every weapon will be a sword 
 of justice in the government of men; every arm will be a con- 
 stabulary of peace. There were men who had hoped to see this 
 achieved in the way of peace. We were disappointed. It was 
 ordained that you should not reach that golden era except along 
 the path which was paved with gold — yea, and cemented with 
 valiant blood. There are millions who have given of the latter 
 who are ready — nay, millions more ready, myriads more ready 
 — for the sacrifice, if the country needs it.
 
 APPENDIX 279 
 
 It is for us to contribute the former. Let no man, no woman, 
 in this crisis of the nation's fate, through indolence, greed, 
 avarice, or selfishness, fail. If they are doing their part, then, 
 when the time comes for the triumphal march through the dark- 
 ness and terror of the night into the bright dawn of the morn- 
 ing of the new age, they will each feel that they have done their 
 share. 
 
 n 
 
 "FORCE TO THE UTMOST"* 
 
 President WUson's Speech 
 
 Fellow Citizens: This is the anniversary of our acceptance 
 of Germany's challenge to fight for our right to live and be free, 
 and for the sacred rights of freemen everywhere. The nation 
 is awake. There is no need to call to it. We know what the 
 war must cost, our utmost sacrifice, the lives of our fittest men, 
 and, if need be, all that we possess. 
 
 The loan we are met to discuss is one of the least parts of what 
 we are called upon to give and to do, though in itself imperative. 
 The people of the whole country are alive to the necessity of 
 it, and are ready to lend to the utmost, even where it in- 
 volves a sharp skimping and daily sacrifice to lend out of meagre 
 earnings. They will look with reprobation and contempt upon 
 those who can and will not, upon those who demand a higher 
 rate of interest, upon those who think of it as a mere commercial 
 transaction. I have not come, therefore, to urge the loan. I 
 have come only to give you, if I can, a more vivid conception 
 of what it is for. 
 
 The reasons for this great war, the reason why it had to come, 
 the need to fight it through, and the issues that hang upon its 
 outcome, are more clearly disclosed now than ever before. It 
 is easy to see just what this particular loan means, because the 
 cause we are fighting for stands more sharply revealed than at 
 
 ' This address was delivered in the sth Regiment Armory, Balti- 
 more, April 6, 191 8, at the opening of the Third Liberty Loan Cam- 
 paign.
 
 280 APPENDIX 
 
 any previous crisis of the momentous struggle. The man who 
 knows least can now see plainly how the cause of justice stands, 
 and what is the imperishable thing he is asked to invest in. Men 
 in America may be more sure than they ever were before that 
 the cause is their own, and that, if it should be lost, their own 
 great nation's place and mission in the world would be lost wit'h 
 it. 
 
 I call you to witness, my fellow countrymen, that at no stage 
 of this terrible business have I judged the purposes of Germany 
 intemperately. I should be ashamed in the presence of affairs 
 so grave, so fraught with the destinies of mankind throughout 
 all the world, to speak with truculence, to use the weak language 
 of hatred or vindictive purpose. We must judge as we would 
 be judged. I have sought to learn the objects Germany has in 
 this war from the mouths of her own spokesmen, and to deal 
 as frankly with them as I wished them to deal with me. I have 
 laid bare our own ideals, our own purposes, without reserve 
 or doubtful phrase, and have asked them to say as plainly what 
 it is that they seek. 
 
 We have ourselves proposed no injustice, no aggression. We 
 are ready, whenever the final reckoning is made, to be just to 
 the German people, deal fairly with the German power, as with 
 all others. There can be no difference between peoples in the 
 final judgment, if it is indeed to be a righteous judgment. To 
 propose anything but justice, even-handed and dispassionate 
 justice, to Germany at any time, whatever the outcome of the 
 war, would be to renounce and dishonor our own cause, for we 
 ask nothing that we are not willing to accord. 
 
 It has been with this thought that I have sought to learn 
 from those who spoke for Germany whether it was justice or 
 dominion and the execution of their own will upon the other 
 nations of the world that the German leaders were seeking. They 
 have answered — answered in unmistakable terms. They have 
 avowed that it was not justice, but dominion and the unhin- 
 dered execution of their own will. The avowal has not come 
 from Germany's statesmen. It has come from her military 
 leaders, who are her real rulers. Her statesmen have said that 
 they wished peace, and were ready to discuss its terms when- 
 ever their opponents were willing to sit down at the conference 
 table with them. Her present chancellor has said — in indefinite
 
 APPENDIX 281 
 
 and uncertain terms, indeed, and in phrases that often seem 
 to deny their own meaning, but with as much plainness as he 
 thought prudent — that he believed that peace should be based 
 upon the principles which we had declared would be our own 
 in the final settlement. 
 
 At Brest-Litovsk her civilian delegates spoke in similar terms; 
 professed their desire to conclude a fair peace and accord to 
 the peoples with whose fortunes they were dealing the right to 
 choose their own allegiances. But action accompanied and 
 followed the profession. Their military masters, the men who 
 act for Germany and exhibit her purpose in execution, pro- 
 claimed a very difTerent conclusion. We cannot mistake what 
 they have done — in Russia, in Finland, in the Ukraine, in Ru- 
 mania. The real test of their justice and fair play has come. 
 From this we may judge the rest. 
 
 They are enjoying in Russia a cheap triumph in which no 
 brave or gallant nation can long take pride. A great people, 
 helpless by their own act, lies for the time at their mercy. Their 
 fair professions are forgotten. They nowhere set up justice, 
 but everywhere impose their power and exploit everything for 
 their own use and aggrandizement, and the peoples of conquered 
 provinces are invited to be free under their dominion ! 
 
 Are we not justified in believing that they would do the same 
 things at their western front if they were not there face to face 
 with armies whom even their countless divisions cannot over- 
 come? If, when they have felt their check to be final, they 
 should propose favorable and equitable terms with regard to 
 Belgium and France and Italy, could they blame us if we con- 
 cluded that they did so only to assure themselves of a free hand 
 in Russia and the East? 
 
 Their purpose is, undoubtedly, to make all the Slavic peoples, 
 all the free and ambitious nations of the Baltic Peninsula, all 
 the lands that Turkey has dominated and misruled, subject to 
 their will and ambition, and build upon that dominion an empire 
 of force upon which they fancy that they can then erect an em- 
 pire of gain and commercial supremacy — an empire as hostile 
 to the Americas as to the Europe which it will overawe — an 
 empire which will ultimately master Persia, India, and the 
 peoples of the Far East. 
 
 In such a programme our ideals, the ideals of justice and hu-
 
 282 APPENDIX 
 
 manity and liberty, the principle of the free self-determination 
 of nations, upon which all the modern world insists, can play 
 no part. They are rejected for the ideals of power, for the prin- 
 ciple that the strong must rule the weak, that trade must follow 
 the flag, whether those to whom it is taken welcome it or not, 
 that the peoples of the world are to be made subject to the 
 patronage and overlordship of those who have the power to 
 enforce it. 
 
 That programme once carried out, America and all who care 
 or dare to stand with her must arm and prepare themselves to 
 contest the mastery of the world — a mastery in which the rights 
 of common men, the rights of women and of all who are weak, 
 must for the time being be trodden under foot and disregarded 
 and the old, age-long struggle for freedom and right begin again 
 at its beginning. Everything that America has lived for and 
 loved and grown great to vindicate and bring to a glorious real- 
 ization will have fallen in utter ruin and the gates of mercy once 
 more pitilessly shut upon mankind ! 
 
 The thing is preposterous and impossible; and yet is not that 
 what the whole course and action of the German armies has 
 meant wherever they have moved ? I do not wish, even in this 
 moment of utter disillusionment, to judge harshly or unright- 
 eously. I judge only what the German arms have accomplished 
 with unpitying thoroughness throughout every fair region they 
 have touched. 
 
 What, then, are we to do? For myself, I am ready, ready 
 still, ready even now, to discuss a fair and just and honest peace 
 at any time that it is sincerely purposed — a peace in which the 
 strong and the weak shall fare alike. But the answer, when 
 I proposed such a peace, came from the German commanders 
 in Russia and I cannot mistake the meaning of the answer. 
 
 I accept the challenge. I know that you accept it. All the 
 world shall know that you accept it. It shall appear in the utter 
 sacrifice and self -forget fulness with which we shall give all that 
 we love and all that we have to redeem the world and make it 
 fit for freemen like ourselves to live in. This now is the mean- 
 ing of all that we do. Let everything that we say, my fellow 
 countrymen, everything that we henceforth plan and accom- 
 plish, ring true to this response till the majesty and might of 
 our concerted power shall fill the thought and utterly defeat
 
 APPENDIX 283 
 
 the force of those who flout and misprize what we honor and 
 hold dear. 
 
 Germany has once more said that force, and force alone, shall 
 decide whether justice and peace shall reign in the affairs of 
 men, whether right as America conceives it or dominion as she 
 conceives it shall determine the destinies of mankind. There 
 is, therefore, but one response possible from us: force, force 
 to the utmost, force without stint or limit, the righteous and 
 triumphant force which shall make right the law of the world 
 and cast every selfish dominion down in the dust. 
 
 APPENDIX F 
 
 Bibliography 
 
 The following list of books, including manuals, books of 
 specimens, and works referring to special phases of the sub- 
 ject, may be found useful: 
 
 Adam, G. Mercer, "Speeches of Abraham Lincoln." 
 Adams, C. K., and Alden, John, "British Eloquence." 
 Alden, Raymond M., "The Art of Debate." 
 Askew, John Bertram, "Pros and Cons." 
 Bacon, Corinne, "Debaters' Handbook Series." 
 Baker, George P., "Specimens of Argumentation." 
 Baker, G. P., and Huntington, H. B., "The Principles of Argu- 
 mentation." 
 Bradley, Cornelius P., "Orations and Arguments." 
 Brookings, W. D., and Ringwalt, R. C, "Briefs for Debate." 
 Buck, Gertrude, "Argumentative Writing." 
 Curry, C. C, "Imagination and Dramatic Instinct." 
 Denny, Duncan, and McKenny, "Argumentation and De- 
 bate." 
 Foster, William T., "Argumentation and Debate." 
 George, A. J., "Select Speeches of Daniel Webster." 
 Harper, George McLean, "President Wilson's Addresses.' 
 Hibbefi, John Grier, "Logic— Deductive and Inductive." 
 Holyoake, George J., "Public Speaking and Debate." 
 
 )>
 
 284 APPENDIX 
 
 Houghton, Harry Garfield, "The Elements of Public Speak- 
 
 ing." 
 
 Johnston, Alexander, "American Orations." 
 Ketcham, Victor A., "The Theory and Practice of Argumenta- 
 tion and Debate." 
 Kleiser, Grenville, "How to Argue and Win." 
 Lee, Guy Carleton, "Principles of Public Speaking." 
 MacEwan, Elias J., "Essentials of Argumentation." 
 Maxcy, CarroU L., "The Brief." 
 Miller, Irving Elgor, "The Psychology of Thinking." 
 Nichols, Egbert Ray, "Intercollegiate Debates," vols. I- VII. 
 O'Neill, Laycock, and Scales, "Argumentation and Debate." 
 Perry, Bliss, "Lincoln," "Webster," in "Little Masterpieces." 
 Phillips, Arthur Edward, "Effective Speaking." 
 Ringwalt, Ralph Curtis, "Briefs on Public Questions." 
 Robinson, Frederick B., "Effective Public Speaking." 
 Scott, Walter Dill, "The Psychology of Pubhc Speaking," "In- 
 fluencing Men in Business." 
 Shurter, Edward Du Bois, "How to Debate." (igi?-) 
 Stephen, Sir James Fitzjames, "Digest of the Law of Evidence." 
 Stone, A. P., and Garrison, S. L., "Essentials of Argument." 
 Thomas, Ralph W., "A Manual of Debate." 
 Titchener, Edward B., "A Text-book of Psychology." 
 Wigmore, John Henry, "Principles of Judicial Proof." 
 Winans, James Albert, "Public Speaking." 
 Winter, Irving Lester, "Public Speaking and Practice." 
 
 APPENDIX G 
 
 Resolutions for Debate 
 
 Resolved: 
 
 That after the present war the United States should take 
 steps to secure the adoption of the programme of the League 
 to Enforce Peace. 
 
 That the federal government should adopt a permanent 
 policy of price control. 
 
 That a war tax of twenty per cent should be levied on all in- 
 comes over two thousand dollars.
 
 APPENDIX 285 
 
 That after the war an international police force should be 
 created to preserve peace. 
 
 That the successful prosecution of the war requires that all 
 citizens of Germany, Austria, Bulgaria, and Turkey now re- 
 siding in the United States be interned until peace is declared. 
 
 That the war-time scope of federal regulation should, in prin- 
 ciple, be continued in times of peace. 
 
 That the administration be granted absolute censorship of 
 the press in time of war. 
 
 That Congress should enact legislation providing for the com- 
 pulsory arbitration of interstate public utility disputes as a 
 permanent policy. 
 
 That the federal government should require compulsory ar- 
 bitration (with power to enforce decision) of disputes between 
 organized labor and interstate public service corporations, con- 
 stitutionality granted. 
 
 That the States should adopt the cabinet-parliamentary form 
 of government. 
 
 That the government, in financing the war for the future, 
 should obtain a larger percentage of its funds from taxes than 
 from bonds. 
 
 That the Japanese should be admitted to the United States 
 and to citizenship therein on the same basis as foreigners of 
 other nations. 
 
 That the federal courts should be deprived of the power to 
 declare acts of Congress unconstitutional. 
 
 That conscription of labor should be adopted by the govern- 
 ment.
 
 INDEX 
 
 Accent, fallacy, loi. 
 
 Adams, C. K., 170. 
 
 Adams, John, 210. 
 
 Adams, Samuel, 230, App. B. 
 
 Adaptation, the principle, g. 
 
 Adjectives, personal, 221. 
 
 Advertising, suggestion in, igo. 
 
 Ames, Fisher, 171. 
 
 Amphibology, loi. 
 
 Anecdote, the, 167. 
 
 Antecedent probability, 42. 
 
 Anticipation images, 162. 
 
 Argument — definition, 4, sq; classes 
 of, 3g; incomplete, 40; relations 
 in, not always known, 41; names 
 applied, 42. 
 
 Aristophanes, 155. 
 
 Arnold, Matthew, ag. 
 
 Assertion, 115. 
 
 Association-reactions, App. B. 
 
 Attention theory, the, 244. 
 
 Auditory images, 163, App. B. 
 
 Authority, 132, 135. 
 
 Bacon, Sir Francis, 165. 
 
 Bank referendum, 133. 
 
 Bardell vs. Pickwick, log. 
 
 Beecher, Henry Ward, 72, 77, 166, 
 igg. 
 
 Benton's "Debates of Congress," 137. 
 
 Best, W. M., 113, 121. 
 
 Blackstone, Sir William, 53. 
 
 Brief, the, defined, 16; analysis, 
 classification, and arrangement, 
 17-23; unity, logical sequence, and 
 proportion, 25-26; language in a, 
 28; parallel structure in a, 2g; two 
 laws of structure, 31; rules for a, 
 32; three parts of a, 32; specimen 
 briefs, 34, App. A. 
 
 Briefs, specimen. Lord Chatham on 
 the removal of troops, 34; first 
 Junius letter, App. A; in defense 
 of Darnay, App. A. 
 
 Brink, C. M., 205. 
 
 Brooke, Stopford A., 48. 
 
 Browning, Robert, App. B, 
 
 Bryan, \Vm. J., ig8. 
 
 Burden of proof, 3, 126. 
 
 Burke, Edmund, learning, 16; "Con- 
 ciliation," 2g, 142, 180, 232; theory 
 of representation, 54; resemblance, 
 6g; vindication of natural society, 
 74; taxation, 108; citation of 
 authority, 142; imagery, i6g; 
 Warren Hastings, 230. 
 
 Cabots, the, 162. 
 
 Caine, Hall, 155. 
 
 Calhoun, John C, 80. 
 
 Camden, Lord, 54. 
 
 Causal relation, argument from, 87; 
 rule of adequacy, 88; interaction of 
 cause and effect, go; partial and 
 temporary causes, gi; multiplicity 
 of causes, gi; relative value of 
 causes, g2 ; causal and other sources 
 of reasoning, g2; differences of 
 view-point, g3. 
 
 Chatham, Lord, 34, 54. 
 
 Choate, Rufus, 222. 
 
 Cicero, 235. 
 
 Circumstantial evidence, 118. 
 
 Classics, the, 212. 
 
 Climax, 24, 30, 22g. 
 
 Clinton, H. L., 174. 
 
 Coleridge, Samuel Taylor, 31. 
 
 Columbus, 162. 
 
 Common ground, in argument, 102. 
 
 Composition, fallacy, loi; a basis of 
 debate, 8. 
 
 Concept, 8, 14, 166, 182. 
 
 Conceptual view-point, the advantage 
 of the, to the debater, 182. 
 
 Confidence, 237. 
 
 Consciousness, appeal to, ig2. 
 
 Consistency, 127. 
 
 Constructive thinking, g. 
 
 Contrast, a principle of association in 
 argument from example, by re- 
 ductio ad absurdum. the dilemma, 
 and the method of the residue, Og. 
 
 Creative imagination, the, isg. 
 
 Curtis, George W., 52. 
 
 287
 
 288 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Dana, Edward S., 123. 
 
 Dante, App. D. 
 
 Darnay, in defense of, App. B. 
 
 Dartmouth College case, 52. 
 
 Darwin, Charles, 135. 
 
 Debate, meaning of term, i, 4, 201; 
 universality of, i; informal and 
 formal, 2; how it originates, 3, 4; 
 varied background, 4; a presenta- 
 tion of ideas, 8. 
 
 Debater himself, the, 12. 
 
 Decision, the, 244. 
 
 Deduction, 97; supplemented by in- 
 duction, 97; a method of criticism, 
 g8; the syllogism, 98; the enthy- 
 meme, 99; the chain of reasoning, 
 100. 
 
 Delivery, common defects in, 240. 
 
 Demosthenes, 235. 
 
 DeWitt, John, App. D. 
 
 Dickens, Charles, 109, 214, App. B. 
 
 Dilemma, the, 79; two kinds, 80; its 
 use, 81; how answered, 81. 
 
 Dionysius, 51. 
 
 Direct evidence, 118. 
 
 Division, fallacy, loi. 
 
 Documents, their interpretation, 139. 
 
 Draper, Sir William, 74. 
 
 Ehbinghaus, Hermann, 205. 
 
 Emerson, O. F., 208. 
 
 Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 226. 
 
 Emotions, the, 11, 197, 221. 
 
 Epictetus, 100. 
 
 Equivocation, fallacy, loi. 
 
 Erskine, Lord, 53, 61, 128, 160, 214, 
 236. 
 
 "Eugene Aram," 119. 
 
 Euripides, 155. 
 
 Everett, Edward, 137. 
 
 Evidence, a basis of debate, 4; mean- 
 ing of term, 113; need of, 113; need 
 of assumptions, 116; classes of, 
 118; jury verdicts upon circum- 
 stantial, 120; personal, real, and 
 documentary, 121; the law of, 126; 
 examining testimony, 127; use of 
 evidence outside the courts, 130; 
 debaters' chief source of, 132; 
 authority, two classes of, 132; ex- 
 amining evidence from authority, 
 135; suggestions for reporting evi- 
 dence, 140; the reasonableness of an 
 opmion, 143; the danger of partial 
 quotation, 144; the card system, 
 I4S- 
 
 Example, argument from, based on 
 resemblance, 50; by generalization, 
 50; by analogy, 66; based on con- 
 trast, 69; always involves a prin- 
 ciple, 52; table showing steps in the 
 process, 57; definition, and rules of 
 relevancy, 58; need of support by 
 other arguments, 61; fallacy, beg- 
 ging the question, 62; answering a 
 causal argument by alleging a dif- 
 ferent cause, 6s; special types of 
 example used in refutation, 69. 
 
 Fallacies, two classes of, loi. 
 Femald, M. R., App. B. 
 Fletcher vs. Peck, 52. 
 Fox, W. J., 84. 
 Franklin, Benjamin, 238. 
 Freeman, E. A., 143. 
 Frequency, 190. 
 
 Gales and Seaton's Reports, 137. 
 George, Lloyd, address, "Peace 
 
 Founded on the Rock of Justice," 
 
 App. E. 
 Gesture images, 202. 
 Gibbon, Edward, 217. 
 Goodrich, Charles A., 7. 160. 2i4- 
 Grattan, Henry, 78, 214. 
 Greenleaf, Simon, 113. * 
 
 Greenough, James B., 45. 
 Gustatory images, 163. 
 
 Hamerton, P. G., i3S- 
 
 Hamilton, Alexander, 167. 
 
 Hans, Clever, 43. 
 
 Hazlitt, William, 160. 
 
 Henry, Patrick, 51. i9S. 227, App. B. 
 
 Hibben, President John G., 59. 98. 
 
 Hill, A. S., 143- 
 
 Houghton, H. G., 204. 
 
 Hugo, Victor, 168, 217. 
 
 Huxley, T. H., 13S. 224. 
 
 Idea, an, 158. 
 
 Ignoratio elenchi, 102. 
 
 Image ad absurdum, the, igo- 
 
 Imagery, an imperfect means, 210. 
 
 Imagery, illustrative, 217. 
 
 Imagery of argument and poetry, 
 App. D. 
 
 Imagery, the special study of; varied 
 appeals; auditory, and the dis- 
 agreeable; auditory and the agree- 
 able; mixed types; other forms of, 
 App. C.
 
 INDEX 
 
 289 
 
 Imagery, tonal, 213. 
 
 Images, types of, 163, 183, 213, App. B. 
 
 Imagination, 8, 150; need of, 150; 
 psychological view-point and proc- 
 esses, 154; images, a psychological 
 inference, 157; mental processes, 
 158; the creative imagination, 159; 
 the poverty of mere facts, 160; 
 the vision of new ideas, 161; an- 
 ticipation images, 162; perceptual 
 aspect of imagery, 163; imaging a 
 concept, 166; an analogy, 167; 
 a cause, 16S; a conclusion, i6g; 
 affection and desire, 172; in a team 
 debate, 175; in general, 178; the 
 advantage of the conceptual view- 
 point to the debater, 182; types of 
 imagep', 183. 
 
 Imperative, the, 228. 
 
 Imperfect induction, g6. 
 
 Independence of the Philippine 
 Islands, 4. 
 
 Inductive argument, 93; the inevita- 
 ble assumption, 95; the formula, 
 95; induction, the scientific method 
 of investigation, 96; kinds of in- 
 duction, 96. 
 
 Inhibitions, 9, 189; hurtful admis- 
 sions, 19s; immediate removal of, 
 195; logical fallacies as, 197; 
 removing an inhibiting wish, 199; 
 the inhibiting function in debating, 
 201. 
 
 Instruments of suggestion, 188, 201, 
 212. 
 
 Interest and belief, as ends in debate, 
 
 193- 
 Interestedness, 239. 
 Interrogatory, the, 227. 
 Invective, 197. 
 Irony, 74, i97- 
 Irving, Henry, 134. 
 Issue, 3; types of issues, 11. 
 
 Jacoby, Dr. George W., 44. 
 James, William, 103. 
 Jefferson, Thomas, 210. 
 Jevons, W. Stanley, 6. 
 Johnson, Dr. Samuel, 98, 106. 
 Junius, 6, 24, 29, 48, 76, App. A. 
 
 Kant, Immanuel, App. D. 
 Keats, John, App. C. 
 Kinaesthetic images, App. B. 
 Kittredge, George L., 45- 
 Knowledge, matters of, 122. 
 
 La Fontaine, the Fables of, 63. 
 
 Lamb, Charles, 152. 
 
 Laughter, 197. 
 
 Law of evidence, the, 126. 
 
 Law of the mental level, 208. 
 
 Laws of structure, 31. 
 
 Lincoln, Abraham, Cooper Institute, 
 
 3; analogies, 67; contrast, 69, 70; 
 
 Dred Scott, 70; dilemma, 79, 82; 
 
 imagery, 157, 167; ad absurdum, 
 
 200; personalities, 219; the phrase, 
 
 226. 
 Lindsley, C. F., 242. 
 Locke, John, 54. 
 Logic, a basis of debate, 6. 
 Logical organization, 13. 
 
 • 
 
 Macaulay, T. B., 72, 98, n6. 
 
 Major premise, 99. 
 
 Mandeville, Sir John, 135. 
 
 Mansfield, Lord, 54. 
 
 McCosh, James, 194. 
 
 Media or symbols, the, 9. 
 
 Memory, 8, 28, 141, 158, 166, 178, 184. 
 
 Mental level, the, 208. 
 
 Meredith, George, App. C. 
 
 Method of the residue, the, 82-86. 
 
 Milton, John, App. C. 
 
 Minor premise, 99. 
 
 Monroe, James, 133. 
 
 Napoleon, 184. 
 Non causa pro causa, 102. 
 Non sequitur, 18, 102. 
 Norton and Sackville, 152. 
 Nullification, 80. 
 
 Olfactory images, 164, App. B. 
 Onomatopoeia, 213. 
 Opinion, matters of, 112; reasonable- 
 ness of an, 143. 
 Oratory, a basis of debate, 8. 
 Otis, James, App. B. 
 
 Paraleipsis, 235. 
 
 Peace, a league to enforce, 191. 
 
 Peel, Sir Robert, 84. 
 
 Perceptual aspect of imagery, 163. 
 
 Perfect induction, 96. 
 
 Peroration, the, 174- 
 
 Perry, Bliss, 159. 
 
 Personalities, 115, 218. 
 
 Persuasion, 11, 188, App. D, 271. 
 
 Peliiio principii, loi. 
 
 Phillips, A. B., 193. 
 
 Phrase, the, 325.
 
 290 
 
 INDEX 
 
 "Pickwick Papers," 109. 
 Pinkney, William, 141, 222. 
 Plan, need of a, 15. 
 Plato, the Republic of, 85. 
 Pliny, 135. 
 
 Plurium inlerrogationum, 102. 
 Poe, E. A., 49, App. B. 
 Polo, Marco, 163. 
 Praleritio, 235. 
 Presentation, the, 13, 150. 
 Primary evidence, 125. 
 Prison reform, report on, 9. 
 Proof, the, 112. 
 Proposition, a, 6. 
 Psychological inference, 157. 
 Psychological moment, the, 208. 
 Psychology, a basis of debate, 9. 
 
 Quarterly Journal of Public Speaking, 
 
 App. B. 
 Quarterly Journal of Speech Education, 
 
 242. 
 Questions or exercises, 146, App. B. 
 Quotation, danger of partial, 144. 
 
 Randolph, John, App. B. 
 
 Recency, 190. 
 
 Reductio ad absurdum, 69; illustra- 
 tions, 69; manner of treatment, 73; 
 how answered, 76. 
 
 Reference to experience, 183. 
 
 Refutation, the, 104; preparation, 
 105; selection, 106; fundamental 
 criticism, 108; two general methods 
 of, 109; special types of, 11 1; 
 avoiding and removing inhibitions 
 in, 194. 
 
 Repetition, 230. 
 
 Reproductive imagination, the, 158. 
 
 Resemblance, a principle of associa- 
 tion in argument from example 
 by generalization and by analogy, 
 50. 
 
 Response, 188, 202, App. B. 
 
 Rhythm, 214. 
 
 Ringwalt, R. C, 63. 
 
 Robert of Gloucester, i. 
 
 Roosevelt, Theodore, 167, 192, 214, 
 
 237- 
 Rowland, E. H., 217. 
 Ruskin, John, 159, 180. 
 Russell, Lord William, 120. 
 Ruyssen, Theodore, 89. 
 
 Sacken, von Osten, 44. 
 Saint Matthew, 179. 
 
 Saint Paul, 223. 
 
 Scott, General Hugh L., 65 
 
 Scott, Sir Walter, 1,2. 
 
 Scott, Walter Dill, 189, 216. 
 
 Secondary evidence, 125. 
 
 Sentence forms, 227. 
 
 Shakespeare, 0th., 47, 124; M. of V., 
 118, 164; Macb., 124, App. C; Jul. 
 Cass., 124, 165, 232, 234, App. C; 
 Rom. and Jul, 159; Temp., 182; 
 Hen. IV, 223, 232; Ham., 235, 
 App. C; Meas. for Meas., 237. 
 
 Ship subsidies, 200. 
 
 Sidis, Boris, 209. 
 
 Sign, argument from, defined, 43; 
 early form of mental activity, 43; 
 words as signs, 44; various defini- 
 tions, 45 ; force, 47; scientific use 
 of, 47; observation and inference, 
 49; common sources of error, 50; 
 sign reasoning in constructive 
 thinking, 9; signs as the back- 
 ground of an argument, 157. 
 
 Sincerity, 211, 239. 
 
 Smith, L. W., 206. 
 
 Smith, Sidney, 224. 
 
 Spencer, Herbert, 68. 
 
 Stephen, James F., 5, 113, 129. 
 
 Stevenson, R. L., 217. 
 
 Story, Justice Joseph, 52. 
 
 Subconscious, the, 188, App. C. 
 
 Suggestion in argument, 8, 188; laws 
 of, and their use in debating, 189; 
 instruments of suggestion, 201 ; ges- 
 ture images as instruments of, 202; 
 word images, 204; variability of 
 meanings, 207; imagery an imper- 
 fect means, 210. 
 
 Summary, the, 34, 230. 
 
 Swift, J., 74- 
 
 Swiss military system, 175. 
 
 Switzerland, the military organization 
 
 of, 59- 
 Syllogism, the, gS. 
 
 Tactual or tactile images, 163, App. 
 B. 
 
 Taft, William H., 192. 
 
 Telegraph-lines, government owner- 
 ship of, 46. 
 
 Tell, WilUam, 137. 
 
 Terman, L. M., App. B. 
 
 Testimony, 127. 
 
 Thucydides, 137, 
 
 Thurston, Senator, 180. 
 
 Transition, the, 240.
 
 INDEX 
 
 291 
 
 Types, of audiences, ii; of issues, ii; 
 of mind, lo. 
 
 Udall, Nicholas, 152. 
 
 Variety, 231. 
 
 Verrazzano, 162. 
 
 Visual images, 163, App. B. 
 
 Vividness, 190. 
 
 Vocabulary development, 204, 212, 
 
 App. B. 
 Vocal shadings, 207. 
 
 Washington, George, 133, 226. 
 
 Webster, Daniel, bank credit, 71 
 on South CaroUna doctrine, 89 
 reply to Hayne, 136; memory, 141 
 the great expounder, 167; eulogy of 
 his State, 185; mental sketch-map, 
 217; personalities, 21 8; irony, 230; 
 
 paraleipsis, 236; sentiment and 
 memory, 237. 
 
 Whately, Archbishop, by, 74. 
 
 Whitney, W. D., App. B. 
 
 Wilson, President Woodrow, imagery, 
 157; the apt story, 167; for a 
 league to enforce peace, 192, 209; 
 an immortal phrase, 226; his 
 Baltimore address, "Force to the 
 Utmost," App. E. 
 
 Winans, James A., 244. 
 
 Winter, Irving L., 241. 
 
 Wish, 199. 
 
 Wit, 197. 
 
 Word images, 204. 
 
 Word-recognition test, App. B. 
 
 Words, connotation of, 44; as instru- 
 ments of suggestion, 201, 204, 212. 
 
 Wordsworth, Dorothy, 237. 
 
 Wordsworth, Wilham, 225.
 
 University of California 
 
 SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 
 
 305 De Neve Drive - Parking Lot 17 • Box 951388 
 
 LOS ANGELES, CALIFORNIA 90095-1388 
 
 Return this material to the library from which it was borrowed. 
 
 VmVERL 
 
 .^I^JC 
 
 ORNIA 
 
 
 LOS ANGSLES 
 LIBRARY
 
 UC SOUTHERN RFGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 
 
 i!P II jll 111 11:11 i| |l I 11 ill IN II ,1 tl 
 III II III lil lllliil II ill III III II 
 
 AA 000 409 622 8
 
 ^Uil| 
 
 Uni 
 
 ; ^UfMlfJlOT^I