o 
 
 CO 
 
 o 
 
LIBRARY 
 
 OF THE 
 
 University of California. 
 
 Class 
 
THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
A0ENT8 IN AMERICA 
 
 THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 64 & 66 Fifth Avenub, New York 
 
THE 
 
 METAPHYSICS 
 OF NATURE 
 
 BY 
 
 CARVETH READ, M.A. 
 
 PROFESSOR OK PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AND LOGIC IN DNIVERSITY COLLEGE, LONDON 
 
 LONDON 
 
 ADAM AND CHARLES BLACK 
 
 1905 
 

CONTENTS 
 
 INTKODUCTION 
 
 Chapter I. — Belief and Knowledge 
 
 1. The Scope of Philosophy 
 
 2. Belief, Knowledge, and Science 
 
 3. Hume on Belief. 
 
 4. Society and Belief 
 
 5. Initial difficulty of Philosophy 
 
 6. Natural Doubt, Belief, and Reason 
 
 PAGE 
 
 3 
 
 6 
 
 8 
 
 12 
 
 13 
 
 15 
 
 Chapter II. — Reality and Truth 
 
 1. Reality Empirical, Physical, Transcendent, Subjective 
 
 2. The Truth of Perception 
 
 3. The Conceptual System and the Physical Method 
 
 4. The Truth of Subjective Reality 
 
 5. The Subjective Conceptual System 
 
 6. The Truth of the Conceptual System . 
 
 7. In Metaphysics, Percepts and Concepts imply Judgments 
 
 19 
 23 
 26 
 28 
 29 
 31 
 33 
 
 BOOK I.— CANONIC 
 
 Chapter III.— The Test of Truth: Historical 
 
 1. The Greeks 
 
 2. Descartes 
 
 3. Locke .... 
 
 4. Cudworth and Spinoza, Intuition 
 
 5. Leibniz .... 
 
 6. Kant .... 
 
 7. Mill .... 
 
 8. Spencer .... 
 
 39 
 43 
 46 
 48 
 51 
 54 
 56 
 59 
 
VI 
 
 THEf METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Chapter IV. — The Test of Truth : Analytic 
 
 SECT. PAGE 
 
 1. The value of (a) Sense -perception ; (b) of the distinction between 
 
 Formal and Material ; (c) of Universality ; (d) of Innateness ; (e) 
 
 of Clearness and Distinctness ; (/) of the Sufficient Reason . 64 
 
 2. Necessity and the Inconceivability of the Opposite . . .71 
 
 3. Necessity as determined by Defiuiteness of Conception and Relation . 73 
 
 4. Necessity and Consistency ...... 75 
 
 6. Though the characterisation of the Criterion be imperfect, it is not 
 
 useless ........ 78 
 
 Chapter V. — Scepticism 
 
 1. The Modality of Judgments : Pyrrhonism 
 
 2. Carneades and Probability 
 
 3. Hume ..... 
 
 4. Characteristics of his * Scepticism ' 
 6. Motives of his sceptical disguise 
 
 6. Pragmatism .... 
 
 80 
 83 
 86 
 88 
 91 
 93 
 
 Chapter VI. — The Eelativity of Knowledge 
 
 1. Modes of Relativity classified and illustrated . . . .97 
 
 2. Incidence of the sceptical criticism of Knowledge . . .102 
 
 3. The means of correcting Relativity are immanent in Sense-perception 105 
 
 4. The limited range of Sense-perception is no objection to its validity . 108 
 
 5. Difficulties arising from the abstract character of Science . . 110 
 
 6. — from its departmental character ..... 113 
 
 7. — and from the nature of Explanation .... 115 
 
 BOOK II.— COSMOLOGY 
 
 Chapter VII. — Substance in Experience 
 
 1. Analysis of Empirical Substance 
 
 2. Empirical Substance is prior to Self-consciousness 
 
 3. Substance and Quality .... 
 
 4. Primary and Secondary Qualities 
 
 5. How can the World be Known ? 
 
 6. ' Powers '..... 
 
 7. Permanence of Substance : Kant and Spencer upon the grounds of 
 
 this Belief ....... 
 
 121 
 125 
 126 
 128 
 130 
 136 
 
 137 
 
 Chapter VIII. — Ontology of the World 
 
 1. Origin of the problem : Democritus and Plato 
 
 2. Materialism ..... 
 
 3. Hypothetical Realism : Locke, Malebranche, Kant 
 
 4. Subjective Idealism : Berkeley 
 
 144 
 148 
 150 
 153 
 
CONTENTS 
 
 ▼u 
 
 6. Mill's Psychological Theory 
 
 6. Absoluto Idealism : Groen 
 
 7. Monism : Spinoza, Schopenhauer, Spencer 
 
 8. Conclusion .... 
 
 PAOE 
 
 156 
 160 
 165 
 170 
 
 Chapter IX. — Universal Forms of the Phenomenon 
 
 1. Time Space, Matter and Motion are co-implicated in the growth of 
 
 Perception ...... 
 
 2. Time is empirically real ..... 
 
 3. Space is empirically real ..... 
 
 4. Time, Space and Motion are conceived as infinitely divisible ; but 
 
 the divisibility of Matter is a jihysical j)roblem . 
 6. Motion and Time are conceived as of infinite duration 
 
 6. Whether Space and Matter are finite or infinite quantities is a 
 
 physical problem ...... 
 
 7. The interest of Reason in these questions 
 
 173 
 176 
 179 
 
 182 
 
 185 
 
 187 
 188 
 
 BOOK III.— PSYCHOLOGY 
 
 Chapter X. — The Subject in Experience 
 
 1. Souls .... 
 
 2. Consciousness in relation to Physics 
 
 3. Grades of Consciousness in Nature 
 
 4. Is the Subject Substance ? 
 
 5. Is Consciousness Energy ? 
 
 6. Consciousness is an activity of Transcendent Reality 
 
 7. Mind and Body .... 
 
 195 
 197 
 199 
 203 
 205 
 209 
 211 
 
 Chapter XL — The Ontology of the Subject 
 
 1. Plato and Aristotle on the Soul 
 
 2. Descartes and Materialism 
 
 3. Leibniz's Monads 
 
 8. A mind is the consLiousness of that transcendent Being whose pheno- 
 menon is the mind's body ...... 
 
 217 
 218 
 221 
 
 4. Berkeley's "thinking, active Principle" ; Hume's "bundle" ; Spinoza 223 
 
 5. Mill's " Permanent Something" .... 
 
 6. Kant on the Unity of Apperception and the Paralogisms ; Lotze 
 
 7. Green's "Self-distinguishing Agent" .... 
 
 227 
 230 
 235 
 
 240 
 
 Chapter XIL— Natural History of the Subject 
 
 1. Experience and Heredity 
 
 2. Primitive mental functions 
 
 3. Teleology of mental development 
 
 4. Development of the Individual 
 
 5. l)e servitule humana 
 
 6. Growth of Intelligence . 
 
 7. Reason .... 
 
 242 
 245 
 247 
 251 
 253 
 255 
 256 
 
VUl 
 
 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 BOOK IV.— THE CATEGORIES 
 
 SECT. 
 1. 
 
 2. 
 3. 
 4. 
 
 Chapter XIII — The Abstract Categories 
 Part I. — Of Ilelation in General 
 
 Relation is the ground of every Judgment 
 
 Is Relation conceivable ?..... 
 
 Is Relation objectively valid ? . 
 
 Relations are discriminated by Understanding in Empirical Realitj' 
 
 Simple Relations of Time and Quality .... 
 
 PAGE 
 
 263 
 264 
 269 
 270 
 273 
 
 Part II. — Qualitative Relations 
 
 6. Secondary Relations of Time and Quality 
 
 7. Change and Becoming ; Potential and Actual . 
 
 8. Possible and Impossible ; Contingent and Necessary . 
 
 9. Thing and Nothing ...... 
 
 10. Specimen and Species ; Event and Law ; Particular and Universal 
 
 11. Matter and Form ; Phenomenon and Substance 
 
 275 
 276 
 
 278 
 280 
 283 
 286 
 
 Part III. — Quantitative Relations 
 
 12. Scientific prerogative of Equality 
 
 13. Relations of Space and Time 
 
 14. Number 
 
 15. Indirect Measurement of Quantity 
 
 290 
 292 
 297 
 301 
 
 Chapter XIV. — The Physical Categories 
 
 9. 
 10. 
 
 Metaphysical treatment of Physics 
 Atoms and Ether 
 Rest, Change and Identity 
 Motion ..... 
 Force ..... 
 Inertia, Mass, Elasticity, Incompressibility 
 Actio in distans .... 
 Mechanics, Chemistry, Organisation 
 Causation as Conservation and Uniformity of Nature 
 Causal Instances. Causation is a Category of the physical or 
 tual System ...... 
 
 concep 
 
 307 
 308 
 309 
 312 
 315 
 317 
 318 
 320 
 323 
 
 326 
 
 Chapter XV. — Categories of Subjective Activity 
 
 1. Activity, Interaction, Parallelism 
 
 2. Will and Free Will 
 
 3. Final Causes 
 
 4. Human Ends or Ideals . 
 
 5. Man and Society 
 
 332 
 337 
 340 
 349 
 352 
 
INTBODUCTION 
 
CHAPTEK I 
 
 BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE 
 
 § 1. As to the nature aud scope of Philosophy, two opinions 
 are current. Some regard it as no more than the organisation 
 of the Sciences : that further content is unattainable has been 
 shown, they say, by experience of repeated failure and by 
 reflection upon the nature of the case. According to others, 
 there are prescientific beliefs that still have a necessary place 
 in human life ; and, even if no definite predications can be 
 made outside the circle of the sciences, still the grounds of 
 the sciences themselves must be examined, and their claims to 
 be a comprehensive and sufficient explanation of the course 
 of the world and of human experience must be vindicated. 
 These opposing doctrines may conveniently be called the 
 Positive and the Critical. To me it seems that, when reason- 
 ably stated, they are not opposed, but that both are necessary 
 and complementary one to another. 
 
 Positive Philosophy, the attempt to imite the Sciences in 
 one system, to expound their mutual relations and the 
 harmony of their laws, is such a manifest demand of reason, 
 that almost at the beginning of European speculation it was 
 felt by Plato {Rep. B. VII.) ; at the beginning of modern 
 thought, by Bacon ; since Comte the idea has become popular, 
 and the first problem of the Positive Philosophy, the Classifica- 
 tion of the Sciences, is now a common exercise. The great 
 body of the Positive Philosophy (not merely Comtian) is 
 constituted by those sciences which give an account of the 
 genesis and history of the world, — Astronomy, Geology, 
 
 3 
 
4 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 Biology, Psychology, Sociology : the Analytic Sciences, treating 
 of the modes of energy or activity which the genetic Sciences 
 imply, are, — Mechanics, Physics, Chemistry, Physiology, Eco- 
 nomics, etc. : the Formal Sciences, Logic and Mathematics, 
 investigate the conditions of proving the relations and laws of 
 phenomena in general, so far as proof is possible from accepted 
 premises. 
 
 Critical Philosophy, which takes its name from Kant, 
 and which I shall usually call Metaphysics, is the study of 
 the validity and adequacy of knowledge and belief. Positive 
 Philosophy, with its premises, is, therefore, part of the object 
 of Metaphysics ; but only a part : for Metaphysics has two 
 branches, the Metaphysics of Natm'e and Science, and the 
 Metaphysics of Ideals. The Ideals are expressed in Polity, 
 Eeligion, Art, and Virtue ; but these human Ideals and their 
 metaphysical significance are beyond the scope of this volume. 
 The Metaphysics of Nature, as Nature is presented to us in 
 science and experience, is my subject ; but since the regions of 
 science are certainly greater than I can explore, I shall deal 
 only with their most general principles, where they come 
 nearest to philosophical interest, are least technical, and have 
 now become an element of general culture ; and it is a rule 
 from which I never depart, not to attempt to solve a priori 
 any problem, that can only be effectually treated by inductive 
 methods. The criticism of knowledge and beliefs, then ; and, 
 of course, some extensions and interpretations of them, in order 
 to give roundness and coherence to the whole ; in fact, an 
 essay toward the Prima Fhilosophia. 
 
 He who makes the Sciences of Nature or Ideals of 
 Himianity the object of criticism, and investigates their 
 validity and value, is not therefore sceptical about them. In 
 some ages it is a fashionable distinction of the Minute 
 Philosopher to doubt of the Ideals ; at present, perhaps, to 
 doubt of the Sciences ; but it would be very insincere of me 
 to claim merit upon either score. It is, indeed, foolish not to 
 recognise that Natural Science, so recent a growth, must be 
 immature, or not to admit that much even of what is 
 considered to have been established may be infected with 
 
BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE 5 
 
 error. It is also obvious that popular morals are little better 
 than barbarous, and philosophic morals often narrow, timid 
 and compromising ; that jjopular religion is wavering, confused 
 and superstitious, and that philosophical religion usually con- 
 sists in offering one's personal persuasions as an apology for 
 catholic dogma. But these things cannot hide the equally 
 obvious truth that our daily life depends in every detail upon 
 science, and for its stability and amelioration upon morals and 
 religion. 
 
 There is indeed one conception characteristic of our age 
 and sprung from its profoundest reflections, whicli may yet 
 paralyse us with self-suspicion and fear. So long has been 
 the process of the world, so long the period of human existence, 
 60 recent is the growth of science and moral enlightenment ; 
 so long is to be the future of mankind, so vast perhaps the 
 expansion of civilisation and intelligence : what hope that we 
 can yet have achieved or perfected anything ? Must not all 
 our culture appear shallow and vain in the comprehension of 
 the world to come ? May not our own descendants be the 
 " superior beings " to " show a Newton as we show an ape " ? 
 But to let ourselves be inhibited by such forebodings is the 
 surest way to prevent their realisation. The city founded on 
 science which Plato and Bacon beheld in prophetic vision, can 
 only be built by the continuous labour of human generations ; 
 of which ours is one. As the past is not abolished but re- 
 embodied in ourselves, so shall it fare with us hereafter. 
 And indeed better : for we are hardly rid of the illusion of 
 astonishment or even laughter at the errors of ancient or even 
 recent predecessors ; but Time, with equal travail the mother 
 of truth and error, will at last give birth to comprehensive 
 criticism. 
 
 Still it is true and significant that philosophy, not yet 
 3000 years old, is a new thing in the world, and that 3000 
 years hence it will still be new: whether we consider the 
 immense period of preparation for thought duriug the growth 
 of organic consciousness ; or the immense prospective period 
 of reflection that remains, and will remain, for the human or 
 Buper-human mind. Modesty, therefore, becomes us well, but 
 
6 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 not despair. If many of our beliefs are erroneous ; if little 
 surprise is felt when what has passed for knowledge turns out 
 to involve some mistake or oversight ; if the sciences stand in 
 need of perpetual revision and readjustment ; yet comparison 
 and criticism, rejection and confirmation, analysis and integra- 
 tion go hopefully forward ; and in each age it is the part 
 of Metaphysics to carry out the process methodically with 
 reference to those doctrines and conceptions that at the time 
 are assumed to be fundamental. Scientific discoveries, social 
 changes and the indefinable growth of the public mind, have 
 again and again thrown the older criticisms and systematisa- 
 tions out of use, like last year's crab-shells. To readjust the 
 world's beliefs the philosopher was needed ; he was a social 
 organ for that purpose ; without him the public mind must 
 have remained either cramped or formless : and whatever 
 mental blemishes he may have had, such as fancifulness, 
 paralogy, megalomania, — all most incident to that sort of man, 
 who is as much an imagination as an understanding, he 
 brought the plasticity that is necessary to readjustment. And 
 the task which giants of old accomplished single-handed must 
 now be discharged by the regiment, each of us doing his 
 share. 
 
 § 2. As to the use of the terms Belief, Knowledge, Science, 
 not much refinement is required, and I mean to avoid needless 
 technicality. Every one thinks of science as the most definite, 
 systematic, and best -ascertained kind of knowledge. The 
 meaning of belief is less settled. It sometimes stands for the 
 region of opinion or doctrine about which we are not quite 
 confident ; so that we recognise degrees of belief, or of subjec- 
 tive assent ; whereas we should hesitate to say that we had 
 knowledge or science of anything concerning which we felt 
 doubtful, or saw any reasonable grounds for doubting. Some- 
 times, again, a fact or doctrine is called a belief when no 
 logical reason can be given for it, though it may be held with 
 the utmost force of conviction ; whereas knowledge and science 
 are supposed to be grounded upon evidence that can be 
 explicitly stated and methodically adduced. But then, since 
 the grounds of science are said to be axioms and facts of 
 
BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE 7 
 
 sense-perception, for neither of whicli logical reasons can be 
 given, the claim is laid that knowledge and science are them- 
 selves based upcm belief, and are therefore even less certain 
 than this from which they are derived. Or, again, if it be 
 said that sense-perceptions and the intuition of axioms are 
 direct cognitions, and that this is more akin to science than 
 to belief, as the terms are commonly used ; it may be replied 
 that, at any rate, the greater part of any man's science depends 
 upon memory, or upon the testimony of others, and that this 
 is certainly called belief. Besides, there is no impropriety in 
 saying that a man ' believes ' the fifth proposition of Euclid, 
 though he may just have demonstrated it ; and even the 
 wildest beliefs of savages are based upon some sort of evidence 
 and elaborated by some sort of reasoning. 
 
 For my part, I shall use Belief as the most comprehensive 
 term, including Knowledge, which again includes Science. For 
 although a science may have some appearance of being an 
 independent structure, it is better to regard it as an outgrowth 
 of beliefs, having the original nature in every part, without 
 which it would have no hold upon us or serious interest. 
 Belief is the subjective acceptance of Eeality : whatever we 
 believe in is regarded as real, or as grounded in, or correspond- 
 ing with, reality : and whatever we take to be real is thereby 
 an object of belief, and determines our conduct accordingly. 
 Our discussions will be concerned hereafter with the validity 
 of Belief, Knowledge, or Science ; that is, only so far as it is 
 regarded as implying Eeality. Metaphysics is not like formal 
 Logic, which may deal with ' X is Y,' no matter what X and Y 
 stand for ; and it cannot, like formal Logic, deal with judg- 
 ments or propositions without reference to the attitude or 
 process of believing or knowing them. To give a full account 
 of belief as merely subjective, and of all the processes of percep- 
 tion and inference, belongs, indeed, especially to Psychology, 
 and the most comprehensive account of belief is given by 
 James Sully in The Human Mind (chap, xii.) ; but Metaphysics, 
 as best it can, makes use of all the sciences. "We must there- 
 fore consider these things so far as they throw light upon 
 metaphysical inquiries : though our object is Belief for the 
 
8 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 sake of Reality, Reality cannot be isolated from the subjective 
 processes through which it arises for each of us and stands 
 there for us all. 
 
 § 3. Psychologists seem not to have been able to carry 
 their investigation of the nature of belief much beyond the 
 point that was reached by Hume {Treatise, P. II., Sects, v. to x.; 
 Inquiry, Sect, v., P. 2). They have drawn more attention to 
 the importance of our emotions and activities in establishing 
 belief, but he did not overlook these factors. Now Hume 
 found that belief differs from ' conception ' or ' fiction,' not in 
 its content, but only in the manner of conception, or (more 
 precisely) in a certain " feeling or sentiment " it has in the 
 mind : a feeling that cannot be defined any more than cold or 
 anger, that is, than any state of mind that Locke would have 
 called a " simple idea " ; because, of course, such states cannot 
 be analysed : they must be severally experienced. This result 
 gives him some embarrassment : " For my part I must own 
 that I find a considerable difficulty in the case ; and that even 
 when I think I understand the matter thoroughly, I am at a 
 loss for terms to express my meaning. . . . And this different 
 feeling I endeavour to explain by calling it a superior force, 
 or vivacity, or solidity, or firmness, or steadiness. . . . And in 
 Philosophy we can go no further than assert, that it is some- 
 thing felt by the mind, which distinguishes the ideas of the 
 judgment from the fictions of the imagination. It gives them 
 more force and influence ; it makes them appear of greater 
 importance, it fixes them in the mind ; and renders them the 
 governing principles of all our actions." 
 
 Hume's embarrassment has generally been shared by his 
 readers : partly, perhaps, because ' feeling ' is the name of so 
 many experiences that are fugitive and insignificant ; chiefly 
 because it is paradoxical to refer the Reality of the universe 
 ultimately to my feeling or sentiment. But the paradox 
 results from identifying the metaphysical with the psycho- 
 logical point of view, the position of self-consciousness, which 
 involves metaphysical ' solipsism.' The difficulty of accepting 
 Hume's doctrine disappears if Reality be based upon what we 
 (dl feel with such ' force,' ' firmness,' ' steadiness ' : for what 
 
BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE 9 
 
 more can we say ? Modern Scepticism has descended from 
 Descartes not because he insisted upon proving all things, 
 but because he found nothing to hold fast by except self- 
 consciousness ; for the Hegelian interpretation of this position, 
 as implying universality, was far from Descartes's mind. The 
 existence of other people than ourselves may indeed be sup- 
 ported by arguments ; we may say that (a) they are like 
 ourselves externally, therefore internally ; (b) they proceed 
 from similar generative causes, therefore are similar effects ; 
 (c) they answer when we consult them, and thus verify the 
 hypothesis of their being conscious. Thus a justification may 
 be obtained for recognising their assent or dissent ; but such 
 arguments cannot be said to carry conviction, since they add 
 nothing to the conviction we already have ; and to urge them 
 seems a disparagement of the instinctive belief that existed in 
 full force before they were thought of. 
 
 But whatever difficulty Hume may profess to find in the 
 conclusion that belief is a kind of feeling, he is, of course, 
 pleased with the literary effect of his paradox ; and he goes 
 on to inquire into the causes of belief. He observes first that 
 belief always attends the memory and the senses. This is 
 universally admitted ; Kant identifies Eeality with sensuous 
 data. Among the senses some are more convincing than 
 others ; the prerogative of sight is witnessed by the proverb, 
 " Seeing is believing," and the still greater efficacy of active 
 touch, by the test of St. Thomas. That is especially real 
 which we act upon and which limits our activity by acting 
 or reacting upon us. 
 
 But Hume's next remark takes us deeper ; an impression 
 of the senses communicates its vivacity and force to all ideas 
 related to it. Hence memory is distinguished from imagina- 
 tion by its greater vivacity and also by the fixity in the order 
 of its ideas, derived from the order of the original impressions. 
 Further, the vigour and vivacity of mental processes, and 
 therefore of belief, is favoured by attention, by the associative 
 principles of resemblance and contiguity, and, more especially, 
 by causation and by repetition or custom. Even an idea of 
 which we have forgotten the correspondent impression may 
 
10 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 itself become the ground of belief and inference ; because 
 whatever firmness or vivacity it has it must be able to bestow 
 on whatever is related to it. " Of these impressions or ideas 
 of the memory we form a kind of system, comprehending 
 whatever we remember to have been present, either to our 
 internal perception or senses ; and every particular of that 
 system, joined to the present impressions, we are pleased to 
 call a reality. But the mind stops not here. For finding 
 that with this system of perceptions, there is another connected 
 by custom, or if you will, by the relation of cause and effect, 
 it proceeds to the consideration of their ideas ; and as it feels 
 that it is in a manner necessarily determined to view these 
 particular ideas, and that the custom or relation, by which it 
 is determined, admits not of the least change, it forms them 
 into a new system, which it likewise dignifies with the title 
 of realities. The first of these systems is the object of the 
 memory and the senses, the second of the judgment. 'Tis 
 this latter principle which peoples the world, and brings us 
 acquainted with such existences as, by their removal in time 
 and place, lie beyond the reach of the senses and memory." 
 Hence, although the passions and the excitement of poetry 
 and oratory, by increasing the force and vivacity of ideas, 
 influence our beliefs, yet " by reflection and general rules, 
 the understanding corrects the appearances of the senses," and 
 determines the judgment, " even contrary to present observa- 
 tion and experience." 
 
 Thus in reviewing the causes of Belief, Hume, starting 
 from sensation as its origin, has effected a transition to science 
 as still more coercive. His explanation of this is that the 
 system of general rules rests upon customary experience, and 
 that the mass of this overcomes the strength of any particular 
 impression that seems to oppose it. He has not completely 
 guarded his position : a general rule cannot, of course, over- 
 come a single impression per se ; if I see ' red,' I see ' red ' : 
 but a rule may determine the significance of an impression ; 
 if I take it for blood, the rule may assure me it is claret, or 
 even that it has a subjective origin with no external corre- 
 spondence. One might also complain that only by a strained 
 
BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE 11 
 
 interpretation can our belief in systematic science be said to 
 be based upon the custom of experience : so much analysis 
 intervenes. Yet it is essentially true that, first, the reduction 
 of general laws under others still more general, and these 
 again under others, as in the systematisation of science, 
 confirms one by another through identification of the relations 
 involved, in a manner analogous to the confirmation by 
 repetition of particular passages of experience, such as the 
 striking of a flint and the outburst of fire ; for every physical 
 law, as a relation of cause and effect, is a repetition of every 
 other : and that, secondly, as a sensation or idea " transports 
 the mind to such ideas as are related to it," and " likewise 
 communicates to them a share of its force and vivacity," all 
 the elements of experience embodied in a general rule must 
 strengthen and enliven one another, and so must all the rules 
 related together in any system. It is easy, therefore, to 
 understand that in such a system the greatest intensity and 
 stability of belief is found ; especially in those who have not 
 merely learnt to rehearse its formulae but in whom it has been 
 renewed by experience and labour; for a hearsay system 
 depends upon who, or how many, are heard to say it, and may 
 not prevail over other prejudices. 
 
 Exception may be taken to another expression of Hume's : 
 he says that " we form " the system of memory, and that the 
 mind " forms " the system of understanding ; but this seems 
 to me true only in the sense that an acorn forms an oak. It 
 is manifest that the system of memory grows, and that in 
 most men a very small part of it is designedly formed ; and 
 the same is true of the system of understanding. Hume's 
 expression too strongly suggests an artificiality in our systems 
 of belief. On the other hand, he observes in the Inquiry that 
 beKef " depends not on the will, nor can be commanded at 
 pleasure " ; that is, belief depends not on an immediate act 
 of will. The Philosopher of " Common Sense " {Intellectual 
 Powers, vi. 4) agrees with him : " It is not in our power to 
 judge as we will. The judgment is carried along necessarily 
 by the evidence, real or seeming, which appears to us at 
 the time." Plainly, belief upon evidence, far from being 
 
12 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 volitional, is a kind of acquiescence. But here, again, some 
 qualification is needed ; for if, as Hume says, attention and 
 the passions help to determine belief, it follows that, without 
 design, the cumulative effect of volition may be very great ; 
 and, accordingly, it is a common remark that people believe as 
 they list ; and Pasteur had reason to say that " the greatest 
 disorder of the mind is to allow the will to direct belief." The 
 passions determine belief by communicating a " greater force, 
 vivacity, solidity," to ideas ; that the sthenic emotions have 
 such influence is easily understood ; but so have the asthenic, 
 by the infusion of fear which (as Mosso shows) is pathologic 
 and exerts a fascination — whence the power of superstitions. 
 And voluntary action itself strengthens belief without any 
 direct ' will to believe ' ; for having an end in view, and being 
 busy with means toward it, we are concerned with relations of 
 causation, which (as Hume might say) afford an easy transition 
 of thought ; and, moreover, the reaction of our efforts irradiates 
 from the kinaesthesis the whole region of correlated ideas. 
 
 § 4. There remains an important cause of Belief of which 
 Hume says remarkably little : the influence of social life in 
 the various forms of education, tradition, authority, common 
 sense, confirming alike our sciences and our superstitions. It 
 seems to have been characteristic of the Sophists to dwell upon 
 this topic, insisting that what was taken for truth or justice 
 existed only by institution or convention, not by nature ; 
 whereas Plato and his followers have maintained that in 
 nature or the reason of nature, the truth of everything is 
 grounded : Aristotle, for example, argues that both absolute 
 justice and slavery are by nature. For me this dispute turns 
 upon an exaggerated distinction between nature and society ; 
 since institutions and conventions are as natural as trees in 
 the forest ; where, also, poisonous weeds are found. But social 
 influence introduces new causes of belief; for Society has 
 interests besides those of which its members are aware ; and 
 from social relations grow many distinctively human senti- 
 ments, such as loyalty, honour, justice; since it is necessary 
 that men should co-operate : and these feelings determine our 
 way of thinking. The great organ of social influence is 
 
BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE 13 
 
 language, whose terms derive their meaning from experience ; 
 and propositions, bringing these terms together in thought, as 
 experience brings facts or events together, produce, where there 
 is no overwhelming conflict, some degree of belief. For what 
 else is the use of language ? But see the consequences. As 
 soon as we can talk, the right of private judgment is en- 
 croached upon by irresistible power, and every artifice is 
 adopted to bury the nascent understanding under a load of 
 prejudice. What might not happen could there ever be an 
 intellectus sibi permissusl Socrates, perhaps, by fighting his 
 way back, got nearest to it ; and no such force to make others 
 think has ever appeared in the world. But family, school, 
 church, and State instruct the boy and the man what to think 
 and what to do. Inheriting a nature fit for such a life, his 
 instincts of imitation, honour, sympathy, reverence, and the 
 rest, all co-operate in delivering him over to the great tutor 
 or arch-sophist (however you regard it), Society, till both in 
 thought and manners — 
 
 Custom lies upon him with a weight 
 Heavy as frost and deep almost as life. 
 
 The habit of believing assertions, become almost instinctive, 
 gives opportunity to liars and other imaginative persons. 
 Falsehood and romance, imperfectly differentiated, flourish 
 amongst children and savages ; and this is quite natural, for 
 deceit is common in organic Nature. Hence, if we may 
 assume (on the principle of natural selection) that in a 
 successful tribe or nation most of the prevalent beliefs are, or 
 have been, useful, still we cannot infer without special inquiry 
 that any particular belief is true. 
 
 § 5. Philosophy, then, coming late in human life, meets 
 at the outset with a great difficulty : how to begin the dis- 
 crimination of truth and error, what to accept, what to 
 reject ? Hume's remark about Eeligion at the beginning of his 
 Natural History is true of every belief : there are two questions 
 to be considered — " its foundation in reason," and " its origin 
 in human nature." The mass of beliefs, ingrained in child- 
 hood and youth, abides with us ; preceding the exercise, it is 
 
14 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 necessarily amongst the foundations of reason. Sometimes the 
 philosopher has affected to disregard this situation, to base all 
 his structure of thoughts or words upon one first principle, or 
 even to proceed without assuming anything at all. Whereas, 
 in fact, even the greatest philosophers rely on the history of 
 culture and the attainments of their own age, and in the 
 elaboration of their doctrines at last depart at but few points 
 from common sense ; are sometimes anxious to show that it is 
 the other philosophers who are at issue with " the plain man " ; 
 or if they venture to maintain here and there a monstrous 
 paradox or two, they compound for it, and excuse their treason 
 to King Mob, by deducing thence through unexpected links 
 of inference all the most popular conclusions. Who does not 
 see that the pretended conclusions are the real premises ? 
 The Sceptics abolish all knowledge, and then restore it under 
 the name of probability. On the other hand, though some- 
 thing must be assumed, we cannot begin by accepting the 
 whole accumulated traditions of our race. But, fortunately, 
 wherever Philosophy becomes possible distinctions have already 
 been recognised, by those who can be interested in Philosophy, 
 between various groups of beliefs as more or less trustworthy. 
 Not only belief but criticism is antecedent to Philosophy. 
 Why not take frank advantage of this, and assume provision- 
 ally all that is accepted by well-informed and sensible people ; 
 in fact, as much as a candid reader is likely to grant ? 
 
 Akin to the illusory purism of deductive method, evading 
 the traditionary foundations of knowledge, is the egotism of 
 some Philosophers as against their predecessors and rivals, their 
 claim to originality. Each man, indeed, feels bound to treat 
 all the problems that have formerly been dealt with, and he 
 recognises a closer relationship to some of the dead than to 
 others, and sometimes approves of an attitude of mind or even 
 adopts a formula ; but, on the whole, he undertakes to create 
 anew the intellectual world by the intervention of his own 
 word ; if others had the right point of view, they failed to see 
 the landscape in its true perspective ; if they had a glimpse of 
 a sound principle, they had no steady vision of it and could 
 nob draw the necessary inferences. As for those with whom 
 
BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE 15 
 
 the philosopher feels little sympathy but rather antipathy, his 
 criticisms of them are often so unintelligent that he may be 
 suspected of having taken little pains really to understand what 
 they were trying to say. In short, hitherto, by his account of 
 it, mankind had sat in the cave, gazing at shadows, and he first 
 had managed to turn round, to climb up to the sunlight, and 
 to behold the world of things in their truth and substance. 
 In consequence of such egomania, a philosopher's view, though 
 often ingenious or even sublime, is manifestly one-sided and 
 partial ; it is just his view ; we learn from his works only what 
 the infinite world seemed like as reflected in his little head. 
 
 Eclecticism, meanwhile, has been a term of reproach ; it 
 means the unreasoned adoption from others of incoherent 
 principles by mere subjective preference. And it must be 
 acknowledged that those who have been especially called 
 Eclectics have been second-rate thinkers ; a good deal of self- 
 confidence is natural to the great man. But the possibilities 
 of really independent performance are greatly exaggerated. The 
 limits of individuality are narrow ; no one man is equal to any 
 great task. In such a personal matter as epic and dramatic 
 poetry, the greatest geniuses never invent their own fables, but 
 are content to give a new form to that upon which the human 
 mind has long brooded. Similarly in science and mechanical 
 invention, each discoverer builds upon the labours of others. 
 And so, in fact, it must be in Philosophy ; the systems that 
 make such a figure in history age after age, are patchworks ; 
 the critical historian has no difficulty in tracing the materials 
 to former owners, and in many cases he might trace them to 
 folk-lore. Is it not better to acknowledge all this ; to recognise 
 that in experience, tradition, speculation, the foundations of 
 Philosophy have already been laid ; that other foundations can 
 no man lay ; that the work belongs to the ages, not merely to 
 us, and that as it was well begun long before we put hand to 
 it, so after we have done our best and gone away it must be 
 carried on by countless generations ? 
 
 § 6. The causes of Belief manifestly give rise to both truth 
 and error. In simple, barbarous tribes the discrepancies of 
 popular tenets are slightly felt. With the growth of experience 
 
16 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 and the keeping of records, with the change of social interests 
 and establishment of orderly and definite conditions of life, the 
 contradictions of fact with fancy and of fancies with one 
 another are gradually forced upon the attention of the more 
 reflective minds. Hence, as we said, before the rise of Philo- 
 sophy some beliefs have become less trusted than others. Belief 
 admits of all degrees of intensity, from the subjective feel- 
 ing of " necessity," through degrees of probability, to doubt 
 and suspension of judgment ; and, again, through degrees of 
 improbability, to disbelief. Subjective probability and improba- 
 bility differ from belief and disbelief, not merely in the intensity 
 of their feeling ; as states of mind they are more complex and 
 a later attainment ; and suspension of judgment is the most 
 complex and the latest attainment of all. Bain's ' primitive 
 credulity ' rules the savage life. Considerable growth in the 
 organisation of thought is requisite before those comparisons 
 are made by which it is explicitly recognised that one belief 
 excludes another ; which, therefore, must be rejected and 
 disbelieved ; and prior to such growth, beliefs persist in spite 
 of many and glaring contradictions of fact. A sense of 
 improbability depends upon a more refined appreciation of con- 
 flict amongst the causes of belief and therefore amongst ex- 
 pectations. Suspension of judgment implies that incompatible 
 beliefs are felt to be equally balanced in a mind susceptible to 
 their influence at the same time, that is, within the psycho- 
 logical present ; therefore, in a highly co-ordinated mind. For 
 an imperfectly co-ordinated mind, it is well known, may be 
 possessed at different times with incompatible beliefs, and never 
 compare them at one and the same time ; may be quite unaware 
 of their incompatibility, and perhaps incapable of comparing 
 them. We may all of us be more or less in this condition, and 
 the ideal Philosopher, entirely free from confusion and latent 
 self-contradiction, may not be born for some thousands of years 
 to come. 
 
 The causes of Belief are always, in the first place, regarded 
 as reasons for believing ; whatever, at any stage of culture, 
 determines the judgment, may be adduced as evidence. " I 
 was told so " ; " It is a story honourable to my tribe " ; "I 
 
BELIEF AND KNOWLEDGE 17 
 
 saw it in a dream " : in certain conditions of society these are 
 reasons. But when Hobbes observes, that the last of them is 
 equivalent to " I dreamt that I saw it," every one smiles, and 
 recognises that the value of evidence changes with the mind 
 of man, and that to assign the cause of one's own belief is not 
 to give a catholic reason for assenting to it. But what security 
 can our own age have, or any age, that its ' reasons ' will not 
 excite the smiles of posterity ? Will it not be always true 
 that, in giving reasons for a belief, mankind must point at last 
 to some of its causes ? Is it possible in the case of any belief, 
 to draw clearly Hume's distinction between " its foundation in 
 reason " and " its origin in human nature " ? 
 
 Argumentative discussions and scientific investigations 
 having drawn attention to the methods of arranging and 
 formulating evidence, or of reasoning, which are especially 
 embodied in Logic and Mathematics ; the effectiveness of this 
 organon within certain limits, and the exultation of command- 
 ing it, have led men to identify it with Eeason itself, and to 
 invest it with all the glory of the differentia of the paragon of 
 animals. It has been supposed to carry conviction by means 
 altogether different from those that excite vulgar credulity ; 
 and in comparison with it every other kind of evidence has 
 been disparaged, and experience itself regarded as irrational 
 and inconclusive. Inasmuch as these systems of reason, Logic 
 and Mathematics, must have some basis, this, we are told, is 
 intuitive reason, which gives the axioms or necessary grounds ; 
 so that the formal systems are reason throughout ; intuitive 
 and discursive reason are ground and superstructure. If any 
 account of intuitive reason be asked for, it is a priori, ' innate,' 
 ' heaven-implanted ' : all which phrases amount to a refusal 
 to give any explanation at all. And in this faith many a thin 
 enthusiast will still live and die. The theory of evolution, 
 however, to any one who accepts it, is, I suppose, incompatible 
 with any but an experiential origin of intuitions, as instinc- 
 tive modes of cognition developed in the human mind and 
 generalised by language. An intuitive axiom is a general 
 judgment concerning ultimate unconditional truth : its gener- 
 ality distinguishes it from a perception of fact, and its uncon- 
 
 2 
 
18 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 ditionality from discursive reason, which depends on premises. 
 It was in attempting, under some misapprehension of the facts, 
 to explain the intuition of causation that Hume attributed it 
 to "custom"; and for this he is always charged with scepticism 
 concerning reason ; whereas he was only giving the best 
 account he could of the growth of reason as to this concept : 
 " Custom " is intuitive reason in the making. Intuition, then, 
 is at once a resultant and an element of experience, and as 
 such it is a cause of belief. But, further, not only is the basis 
 of Logic and Mathematics to be derived from experience, but 
 unless their forms are filled with the content of experience, they 
 are absolutely useless not only in practice but in the discovery 
 of truth, and can never make us believe anything. All reason, 
 therefore, rests upon, and is merely a mode of formulating, 
 material that is not technically rational, namely, experience. 
 
 It must be acknowledged that such a way of considering 
 beliefs, as wholly determined by experience, suggests a 
 mechanical interpretation of thought, as if Truth were the 
 survival of a conflict in the mind, as the equilibration of any 
 system depends on the cancellation of disturbing forces. More- 
 over, so far as experiences can be expressed in propositions 
 they may be exhibited as reasons, but in extensive regions of 
 experience this may be impossible ; for much of our experience 
 is subconscious, and our subconscious life powerfully influences 
 judgment and belief, but cannot be read into the forms of 
 Logic. If then, in fact, such experience determines beliefs that 
 are inexpugnable and a necessary complement to those in which 
 formal reason plays its greatest part, our judgment seems to 
 be given over to a power beyond our control and beyond the 
 reach of analysis. 
 
 But the consideration of Belief in relation to reason and 
 experience, draws us from the subjective to the objective side 
 of knowledge. An attempt to discriminate the characters of 
 truth and error; to collect and examine the grounds upon 
 which philosophers have endeavoured to justify their convictions 
 or their scruples ; and to inquire whether, or how far. Belief 
 is, or may become, co-extensive with Reason, will occupy the 
 following pages. 
 
CHAPTER II 
 
 REALITY AND TRUTH 
 
 § 1. Opposite me, at a distance of about 500 yards, a hill 
 rises steeply to a height of about 1000 feet. At its foot lies 
 a narrow meadow surrounded by dark green woods of oak, 
 chestnut and fir. Above the wood runs a brighter border of 
 ferns, then heather, and at the top grey crags. In the blue 
 overarching sky a few white or grey clouds drift slowly along. 
 From the valley at the foot of the hill is heard the rushing of 
 a mountain stream, hidden by trees, and from this side of it a 
 meadow and lawn slope up to my window. Cattle browse 
 across the meadows ; swallows skim by in the air, and a light 
 wind rustles through the woodland. 
 
 This is Empirical Eeality, matter of fact, the scene of 
 the activity and interest of life, the beauty of the world, which 
 can never be " explained away," and for which no theory can 
 ever be substituted. Why not be content with this, instead 
 of making a theory about it ? 
 
 Still, this being a working hour, terms of the Schools 
 begin to jangle in my ears and gurgle in my throat. I 
 observe grimly that the scene before me is matter in space, 
 a continuum of points of resistance and intervals of free move- 
 ment ; that I am necessarily impressed with its permanence 
 as a whole, in spite of changes among its parts ; and with its 
 independence of myself, in the sense that others will see it 
 when I go away, and that if I come back next year it will 
 seem much the same. I see that all objects in the landscape 
 have characteristic properties ; that only oak, and fir, and 
 fern, and heath, and rock look just like that : that only 
 
 19 
 
20 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 swallows and one or two other birds with similar wings 
 have just that casting, sweeping flight ; that only mountain 
 streams make just that everlasting noise. And as to all this 
 no serious doubt is possible, and if any one suggests a doubt 
 there is no use in arguing about it. A belief so primitive as 
 generally to be inarticulate, no other can compare with it in 
 " force, solidity, firmness, or steadiness." 
 
 This Empirical Eeality is equivalent to human sense- 
 perception. It involves much more than sensation, more 
 than the sense -perception of an animal such as the cow 
 yonder; nay, to one man sense -perception has far more 
 significance than to another. As mind develops all its 
 functions develop, and sense - perception comes to include 
 more and more the elements which, considered abstractly, 
 are ascribed to thought. In fact no clear separation of 
 mental functions is possible, but only a distinction of view 
 for special purposes. Thought is immanent in perception 
 and perception is implied in all thought. We may say that 
 most characteristic of thought are the scientific processes of 
 classification and explanation ; and these are plainly involved 
 in the present perception : for I classify in saying that I see 
 oaks, chestnuts and fir trees ; and I explain in saying that 
 I hear the noise of a river that cannot be seen. 
 
 However, by thought these processes are carried much 
 further than by perception. Thought, dealing with concrete 
 things, has chiefly three investigations, what things are, how 
 they came to be so, and what they do ; or their nature, their 
 causes, and their effects. Not content with seeing that certain 
 trees are oak, chestnut and fir, according to popular recogni- 
 tion, we desire to know exactly the structure of each of them 
 and how they differ from one another. We find that the oak 
 and chestnut are much more alike than either of them is to 
 the fir. We also learn that these trees and all other plants 
 consist of cells, and that this is also true of cows and swallows 
 and all other animals ; that the cells again consist of chemical 
 molecules, and that this intimate structure is common to them 
 with the rocks at the top of the hill. This, then, it may be 
 said, is what things are. 
 
REALITY AND TRUTH 21 
 
 As to liow things came to be such as we now perceive 
 them, the conclusions are at present less definite; but a 
 botanist or zoologist would give some account, or suggestions 
 toward an account, of how oaks or cows arose ; and a 
 geologist would explain that the rocks at the top of the hill 
 (which I believe to be weathered slate) were long ago deposited 
 as fine mud at the bottom of the ocean ; then covered with 
 other deposits, and during disturbances of the earth's crust 
 subjected to enormous lateral pressure at a great depth and 
 probably at high temperature ; whence resulted their character- 
 istic cleavage and the tilting and fracture of their stratification. 
 Beyond the deposition of the mud lies a region of surmise 
 concerning still earlier rocks, and farther back still the 
 supposed cooling of the planet, after its origin in the con- 
 densation of a cloud of molecules. 
 
 What things do depends upon what they are. Now they 
 are regarded as special arrangements of molecules; so that 
 what they do depends upon the nature and grouping of these 
 molecules according as they constitute inorganic or organic 
 bodies, plants or animals, oaks or cows. Amongst their 
 activities, it is explained, are those that enable us to see 
 them, hear, smell, taste them, feel them to be warm or cold ; 
 for these elements of experience are scientifically regarded as 
 merely our sensations, not belonging to the Reality as such. 
 The oscillations of the molecules of a body, for example, 
 by setting in motion the ether, stimulate the nerves of our 
 eyes or skin, and thereby the sense of light or warmth arises. 
 Since, then, as every inquiry brings us to a world of molecules 
 and ether, and of their movements, it is very common to 
 speak of these as real in an eminent degree, to the disparage- 
 ment of the manifold of Empirical Reality, as if this were 
 comparatively unreal. An obvious impropriety: to avoid 
 which I shall call the world, as conceived by scientific thought. 
 Physical Reality. 
 
 Some metaphysicians reduce Reality to much narrower 
 bounds. They argue that the only absolute existence in 
 the world we perceive is a Substance or substratum, of which 
 Physical and Empirical Realities are merely the manifestation 
 
22 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 in our consciousness. The properties of the Physical World, 
 resistance, extension, and motion, they call primary qualities 
 of this substance ; and the further properties of the Empirical 
 World, colour, sound, etc., they call secondary qualities. There 
 are various ways of formulating this doctrine ; but they all 
 agree in degrading the world of perception and scientific 
 analysis to the position of a phenomenon, having only a 
 conditional reality and lying, in fact, as Plato says, some- 
 where between reality and nothingness. We may call the 
 substance which all appearances or phenomena are said to 
 depend on, or inhere in, but which is never directly known, 
 Transcendent Reality, or Being. 
 
 As to the nature of this substance, however, whilst the 
 commoner practice is (or has been) to call it Matter, others 
 maintain that it is essentially Thought. The activity of the 
 Divine Mind, they say, or the self-existent Ideas of things 
 (for here again there are various opinions) must be regarded 
 as the ultimate ground of phenomenal existence. And the 
 ultimate ground, thus conceived, it may be convenient to call 
 Noumenal Eeality. 
 
 Reality is, however, not exhausted by the object of percep- 
 tion and its supposed conditions. Looking out upon the 
 landscape, I am aware of my own delight and interest in it, an 
 expanding curiosity, activity, and exhilaration ; listening to the 
 rush of the river, I cannot help wishing that the trees on this 
 side of the valley were a little thinner, that I might also see 
 the shimmer of the waters ; if whilst watching the swallows it 
 occurs to me that they are catching many insects, there may 
 cross my mind some disturbing considerations of the raven of 
 nature, mitigated by further considerations of the annoyance 
 that would be caused by too many insects ; and so on. Now 
 these feelings, wishes, inferences also belong to Empirical 
 Reality ; it is the reality of what Locke calls * Reflection,' and 
 may be termed ' subjective ' to distinguish it from the objective 
 Reality of Perception. 
 
 There is nothing in the subjective region corresponding 
 with Physical Reality. Something approaching the character 
 of a primary quality of mind may be found in the nisus of 
 
EEALITY AND TRUTH 23 
 
 attention ; but this cannot be regarded both as a condition 
 of other modes of cousciousneHS and at the same time inde- 
 pendent of them, as molecules are in relation to visual and 
 auditory sensations. 
 
 A Transcendent Reality of Reflection is generally recognised 
 under the names of Mental Substance, Ego, Self or Spirit ; or, 
 considering it as informing and animating the body, and (by 
 most) as capable of subsisting independently, it is called the 
 Soul. Concerning the nature of this mental substance, how- 
 ever, and its relations to the thoughts and feelings which are 
 its properties, modes, or activities, there is, as in the corre- 
 sponding case of material substance, much difference of opinion ; 
 and, according to Materialism, the substance of mind is the 
 body. 
 
 Finally, the Self, or Soul, or particular human (or animal) 
 consciousness is sometimes treated as an emanation or process 
 or phase of the Universal or Divine Consciousness ; and, 
 according to this doctrine, the worlds of perception and reflection 
 have the same fundamental Noumenal Reality. 
 
 § 2. The notions of Reality and Truth are sometimes 
 identified, as when it is said that the truth of the world is 
 the Good : meaning that Good is the ultimate Reality. But 
 it seems better to say that Reality is that of which Truth is a 
 more or less adequate representation ; or that Truth is the 
 correspondence of cognition with Reality. It may be com- 
 plained that this is to give a secondary place and an inferior 
 dignity to truth ; and further that, thus understood, truth 
 cannot be ascribed at all to the Divine Consciousness, which 
 is Reality itself. Such difiiculties, arising from traditionary 
 associations of words, are amongst the reasons why Metaphysics 
 must be written. It seems to me that human consciousness 
 likewise is Reality itself. Whether the Universal Conscious- 
 ness can be called ' true,' matters little : I despair of doing 
 honour to the Absolute by any accumulation of predicates. But 
 if the word truth implies the possibility of error, it cannot be 
 an attribute of the Divine Mind ; and it seems an advantage 
 of the above definition that it regards truth as only appertain- 
 ing to particular consciousness, and restrains the vagaries of 
 
24 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 speculation by the consideration that what we seek is to 
 avd pdnTTivov a\rj6e<;. 
 
 Truth, then, must be considered under each of the 
 recognised modes of cognition and representation, Percept, 
 Image,. Concept, Judgment ; and in relation to the various 
 modes of conceiving Eeality. 
 
 The Percept, indeed, may seem identical with Empirical 
 Reality ; and so it may be as far as it goes ; but it is never 
 adequate, as we may see by looking closer at an oak tree, by 
 tearing off the bark, making sections of the wood, examining 
 it under a microscope. The percept, again, may contain 
 representations that accurate inspection will not verify ; that 
 is, it may be illusory. Besides, not every one looking at yonder 
 hill can discriminate all the shades of its manifold coloration ; 
 some are blind, or colour-blind in various degrees ; there are 
 limits of discrimination to the most delicate sense : nor, listen- 
 ing to the concert of nature, can every one hear the various 
 tones of stream, thrush, grasshopper ; nor when night falls, the 
 cry of bats in altissimo, the hooting of owls and still the 
 rushing of the stream ; some are deaf, some hear various noises 
 but no music. There are, therefore, three ways in which 
 perception may come short of the truth of Empirical Reality : 
 it may be abnormal, or illusory, or inadequate. 
 
 The content of any percept is direct Empirical Reality for 
 the perceiving Subject ; but so far as it does not agree with 
 the perception of other Subjects in the same circumstances, it 
 is abnormal or illusory. So far as merely inadequate, it is 
 symbolic or representative of a whole ; and it is true so far as 
 it signifies further possible percepts discoverable, immediately 
 or conceptually, by exploration. 
 
 Perception may be especially inadequate in respect of the 
 relations and reciprocal influence of things. Where a thing 
 is, seems to perception a needless question, but it is very 
 difficult to answer; how far things are distant from one 
 another may be perceived more or less accurately, but only 
 within narrow limits. That a certain tree flourishes in one 
 situation and not in another ; that one tree shadows barren 
 ground, whilst another allows the growth of grass or under- 
 
REALITY AND TRUTH 25 
 
 wood : so much we may, perhaps, be said to perceive, but not 
 the processes that have these results. We cannot perceive 
 how vegetable life depends upon soil and sunshine ; how 
 animal life depends upon vegetable, and vegetable upon 
 animal ; tlie processes and conditions of dependence are secret 
 and obscure. We perceive the voice of the river and the 
 light of the sun, but not the means by which they reach us. 
 Thus, when we try to trace the connections of things and 
 events, the inadequacy of direct perception drives us from 
 Empirical to Physical Reality. 
 
 Now the elements of Physical Reality, atoms and ether, 
 cannot be directly perceived at all, cannot be sensibly dis- 
 tinguished from space, being too refined to offer any sensible 
 resistance to our movements. Atoms massed together, indeed, 
 become directly perceptible by manipulation ; but this is a 
 very coarse means of perception, since millions of atoms may 
 be added to, or subtracted from, a given mass without our 
 being at all aware of it. The size and qualities of atoms, the 
 nature of the ether and the movements of these things are 
 altogether conceptual. Conceptual truth, which will presently 
 be considered, is entirely representative ; it is not only 
 symbolic of something else, but it is also no part of that which 
 it symbolises ; for the name or definition of oxygen is no part 
 of the gas, as the colour of a rose is part of its Empirical 
 Reality. 
 
 As to the truth of percepts in relation to Transcendent 
 Reality, Substance was supposed by Locke to resemble 
 Empirical Reality (ideas of sensation) in its primary qualities, 
 but no further. Spencer tries to show that, whilst there is 
 no direct resemblance, there must be a correspondence of 
 relations between the world as perceived and the Unknowable 
 Force ; others have even denied that a transcendent Substance 
 exists at all. Noumenal Reality presents similar difficulties : 
 Plato treats the truth of the phenomena (percepts) sometimes 
 as a participation in, sometimes as an imitation of. Ideas ; and 
 he shows that great perplexity arises in either course. In fact, 
 we are here confronted with a great traditionary question of 
 Metaphysics. (See Chapter VIIL) 
 
26 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 § 3. Less metaphysical interest attaches to the truth of 
 images : I mean the phantasms or traces that perceptions 
 leave in the mind and which fill our study of memory or 
 imagination. On the whole, it must be considered to follow 
 the truth of perception itself ; that is, images may be normal 
 or abnormal, or illusory, adequate or inadequate ; and, in the 
 latter case, either as to objects and events, or to their order 
 and relations. The older psychologists greatly exaggerated 
 the extent to which, in ordinary minds, images are copies of 
 their original percepts. A few people have very vivid and 
 complete mental pictures, most people much less perfect, some 
 hardly any that can be said to resemble objects or occurrences : 
 similarly with phantasms of hearing and of active touch ; 
 of other sense -perceptions still less. In general, as percep- 
 tion is inadequate, it is symbolic; and imagery is far more 
 so, as we see in the swift and synoptic career of memory; 
 but this is a matter of Psychology rather than of Meta- 
 physics. Mental imagery is a great source of illusions and 
 primitive superstitions ; but with the development of reason 
 imagery and the vague ideas it supports are superseded by 
 concepts, and become important chiefly as subsidiary to the 
 conceptual system. 
 
 If you mention an oak to any Englishman who has ever 
 lived in the country, it may call up some image of a tree grow- 
 ing in a wood or in a meadow ; it will at least suggest certain 
 characteristics of such a tree in verbal schemes if you ask him 
 to describe it ; as that it bears leaves of a certain shape and 
 colour, branches almost horizontal with sharp lateral twists, 
 has acorns for fruit, sometimes carries oak-apples, makes a 
 hard durable wood of a certain structure. This is his idea 
 of an oak. A botanist makes this idea more definite and 
 detailed, explains that oak-apples are not a natural product, 
 assigns a particular oak to its genus and species, showing how 
 it differs from other allied kinds. This is the concept of an 
 oak. The botanist may go on to explain how the oak grows, 
 feeding upon the soil and air ; how its leaves inhale carbon 
 dioxide and exhale oxygen, for the nature of which gases he 
 refers you to the chemist, and the chemist is ready with 
 
EEALITY AND TRUTH 27 
 
 definitions or concepts of them and their laws. Thus, again, 
 the conceptual system is created to make good the short- 
 comings of perception and imagination, Physical Reality to 
 complete Empirical Reality. The creation of this conceptual 
 system is carried out by a combination of observation, 
 hypothesis, deduction and induction, for which I refer to books 
 on Logic and Methodology. The physical method proceeds 
 from percepts to concepts concerning their nature and con- 
 nection, and comes back to percepts again : the return to 
 percepts being the verification of the conceptual construction. 
 At every stage the conceptual process must conform to the 
 analogy of perception, and is checked by perceptual conditions. 
 By conforming to the analogy of perception, I mean that the 
 things conceived must be endowed only with such qualities 
 and movements as bear some resemblance to the qualities 
 and movements of things perceived, though they may not 
 resemble the very percepts of which they are conceptions : 
 the vibrations of molecules are not like the perceived fact 
 of heat, but they are like vibrations that are things 
 perceived. That the process is checked by perceptual 
 conditions means that if (for example) it is conceived that 
 plants exhale oxygen, it must be shown to perception 
 that the gas exhaled has the properties and reactions of 
 oxygen ; and the properties of pure oxygen are inferred 
 from the reactions of a gas obtained under conditions 
 such as to satisfy our perception that nothing else can be 
 present. 
 
 It follows from this that the conceptual process, in spite 
 of its highly symbolic character, is an imaginable one, at least 
 to those whose imagination is tolerably powerful ; and this 
 has two consequences. First, imagination may prepare the 
 way for conceptual theory; since by its means even atoms 
 and ether may be seen, as by an indefinitely powerful magnify- 
 ing-glass. Secondly, the fact that the conceptual process can 
 be pictured, or intuitively represented, whether by visual or 
 tactile schemata, brings it into the same plane with the 
 perceptual process; so that Empirical and Physical Reality 
 form one continuum, and thereby that satisfaction is obtained 
 
28 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 for the sake of which the mind creates Physical Reality. 
 Without intuition, no understanding. 
 
 There remain, however, two discrepancies between these 
 modes of Reality. The first is that, whilst the Empirical is 
 mainly static, the Physical is a world of incessant movement. 
 The scene before me presents indeed some objects moving at 
 various rates — the dashing swallows, the rushing stream, the 
 browsing cattle ; but the meadows and mountains give an 
 irresistible impression of permanence, and even the sunshine 
 seems a steady illumination. The conceptions of Physical 
 Reality represent the whole as a scene of incessant change. 
 The motions of animals are attributed to molecular motions 
 going on inside them, most of which are active when the 
 animal lies at rest ; the hills are whirling with me through 
 space in a frantically complex figure, and all their rocks 
 vibrating with thermal and other latent forces : any apparent 
 rest is relative to my position or my perceptive powers. The 
 sunshine that gives such steady illumination dances past with 
 incredible activity, and its apparent steadiness is mere sensa- 
 tion. That introduces the second discrepancy : Physical and 
 Empirical Reality are only conceived as a continuum in respect 
 of the primary qualities of matter, as if these were not 
 sensation : the secondary qualities are regarded as connected 
 with the primary only in Empirical Reality. 
 
 § 4. So far we have only considered the Truth of objective 
 consciousness, but in the subjective region we may draw 
 parallel distinctions. Corresponding with the perception of 
 things, there is introspection of mental states and processes, 
 whether wholly subjective (like toothache), or (like yellow) 
 objective in their first significance but now considered merely 
 in themselves or in subjective relations. Introspection may 
 be abnormal or pathological in various ways ; but we are here 
 concerned with its adequacy or inadequacy, because this is 
 the condition of its truth in relation to subjective Reality. 
 
 The content of every introspection is, like the content of 
 every percept, symbolic and, in that sense, representative of a 
 whole comprising far more than the immediate and distinct 
 consciousness of it. Generally, closer attention to any psychic 
 
KEALITY AND TKUTH 29 
 
 content is enough to bring to light elements that at first were 
 undiscriminated. To realise this, any one who is not familiar 
 with such matters has only to read the description of Anger 
 or Fear in a psychological text-book ; though indeed novelists 
 and poets often say the same things in their own way. These 
 writers draw our attention to much that the distracted mind 
 neglects ; but there is a great deal in a fit of anger that will 
 never be set down in books. Perhaps the symbolic character 
 of consciousness may be most easily seen in this, that every 
 emotion develops through a series of stages, but we know 
 what is the matter with us as soon as one begins : the initial 
 stage is a sign of all that is to follow. 
 
 Direct analysis by mere attention shows us much, but 
 indirect analysis brings out much more, as every one must 
 have realised on first reading Berkeley's Th eory of Vision : the 
 first great triumph in Psychology of indirect analysis. This 
 proves to us that we must have certain sensations which it 
 costs some effort to become aware of. Clearly, therefore, 
 introspection, like perception, is inadequate and representative 
 or symbolic ; and it is true, as distinct from real, so far as it 
 signifies further possible content of introspection discoverable, 
 immediately or conceptually, by exploration. 
 
 § 5. Discoverable immediately or conceptually I say ; for 
 here too we may distinguish the Empirical Reality of intro- 
 spection from something analogous to Physical Eeality, namely, 
 a conceptual system designed to connect and complete the 
 inadequate and fragmentary contents of introspection. The 
 possibility of such a system has been indicated by such con- 
 ceptions as Leibniz's petites perceptions, Spencer's atomic 
 feelings, and Fechner's subliminal consciousness. All these 
 expressions point to depths of mental life that underlie, in 
 indefinite remoteness and obscurity, all that can be brought 
 within the region of self-consciousness : a mental life the laws 
 of whose growth must contain the explanation (if there be 
 any) of the work and play of our superficial thoughts and 
 feelings. Such hypotheses are often scouted by those who 
 think that physiological conditions give a sufficient explana- 
 tion of the mind, and by those who teach that the limits of 
 
30 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 introspection are the limits of analysis. But the former 
 group are palpably mistaken, and the latter soon surrender to 
 them. To take the final results of introspection as the limits 
 of psychological analysis is as unreasonable as to confine 
 Physics to the data of sense. Some would even make the 
 perception of space an ultimate datum, though space is the 
 subject of all Geometry, and has therefore an infinitely diversi- 
 fied content. But it seems to me that even the sensations of 
 blue or yellow, however apparently structureless, as they are 
 correlative with the functions of an ancient and complex organ, 
 must cany in their constitution the records of that organ's 
 growth. To fix upon any data as ultimate is to repeat the 
 error of those " limitary cherubs " who, in the name of innate 
 ideas or a priori forms, have affected to settle for us all the 
 questions of nature and genesis ; it is to infringe the interest 
 of Reason in everlasting labour. 
 
 This conceptual system of Psychology, as it bears many 
 analogies to Physical Reality, must be investigated by the 
 Physical Method, proceeding from introspective data, through 
 concepts, to introspective verification. But there are certain 
 differences between the subjective and objective conceptual 
 systems: (1) The subjective is not, like the objective system, 
 the scene of incessant motion ; for it is not in space, which is 
 a condition of motion : but it is the scene of incessant change 
 of quality, of intensity, and of feeling-tone. (2) The distinc- 
 tion of primary and secondary qualities has no place in 
 subjective Reality, nor in sensations considered as subjective 
 experience ; for the whole of consciousness is real in the same 
 sense and in the same degree. (3) Low-grade or sub-liminal 
 consciousness in the psychological conceptual system is more 
 difficult to imagine than the play of atoms and ether in 
 Chemistry and Physics ; for, by hypothesis, low-grade con- 
 sciousness cannot be imitated by our imagination, which is 
 always high-grade. One would like to be a dog, or a butterfly, 
 or a spinal ganglion for a time ; for the failure of imagination 
 to follow the lower life discourages the understanding and 
 makes it too readily acquiesce in merely physiological explana- 
 tions. An introspective magnifier would be useful ; but, if 
 
REALITY AND TRUTH 31 
 
 relatively as powerful as those used in Physiology, it would 
 still (like them in their own function) fall far short of 
 revealing the latens schematisinus and the latens processus 
 of sensation. Biological and physical analogies must help, 
 or some other way may yet be found. 
 
 § 6. As to the truth of concepts, it may be considered, 
 first, as a question of their consistency with one another ; but 
 this is sufficiently treated of in Formal Logic under the heads 
 of Division and the Predicables. Secondly, there is the 
 relation of concepts to Empirical Reality ; and this, again, is 
 treated of in Inductive Logic under the heads of Classification 
 and Nomenclature. But, thirdly, there is the relation of 
 concepts to Physical Reality ; and this at first may seem to 
 need no special discussion, for, it may be asked, what is 
 Physical Reality except concepts ? But it is much more ; for 
 the concept is a function of cognition, and beyond it lie the 
 things to be known by it. The concepts of Physical Reality 
 are symbolic of something ; and their truth consists in 
 signifying things and processes in such a way that inferences 
 drawn from them can be verified in Empirical Reality : where 
 waves from the depths of Nature come to the surface and 
 break in the light of day. We verify perceptually as far as 
 possible, but the weakness of our senses leaves a conceptual 
 region which is believed to correspond to something impercept- 
 ible ; just as perception itself does, except that perception is 
 identical with Reality in that character which is a sign of 
 the rest. That further region is conceived as if it might 
 be perceived ; and is, therefore, conceived on the analogy of 
 perception, so that it may also be imagined. For if the 
 conceptual system is reduced to merely arbitrary symbols, 
 such as mathematical equations, these may be verifiable and 
 very useful ; but to formulate is not to explain, for it does 
 not present to us the continuity of the World ; nor, therefore, 
 does it subserve that final use of science and philosophy, the 
 raising of Nature into Self-consciousness. 
 
 The difference between the question of the truth of 
 concepts in relation to Physical Reality on the one hand, and 
 on the other hand in relation to Transcendent Reality, is that 
 
32 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Transcendent Eeality is conceived of as having its being 
 otherwise than as possible perception. But if, by hypothesis, 
 it is imperceptible, how can it be conceivable ? Undoubtedly, 
 " Substance " and " Idea " present themselves to us as concepts ; 
 but can we assign them any distinct content or connotation 
 and any reference or denotation beyond themselves ? This, 
 like the corresponding question with regard to percepts, is a 
 traditionary problem of Metaphysics, and we must hereafter 
 try to solve it. Philosophers often assure us the solution is 
 unattainable, that the transcendent is unknowable ; but it 
 presently appears that this is only an exordium to stimulate 
 curiosity whilst they go on to tell us all about it. They seem 
 anxious to restrain the vagaries of other minds ; unbridled 
 speculation is such a waste of time, they say : like Locke, who 
 nevertheless cannot restrain his own speculations concerning 
 cherubim. But Locke, like Sir Thomas Browne, may have 
 seen reason " to fear the prophecy of Elias," and that the time 
 of this world was running to its dregs. We have better 
 hopes, or at least we have longer views. Why should the 
 human race, now assured of its youth, be in as great a hurry 
 as when anticipating its decrepitude ? Is it certain that 
 philosophers can waste their time ? Would they, if otherwise 
 employed, be very useful ? But meanwhile they do no harm : 
 a statesman usually does more mischief by a single Act of 
 Parliament than the whole line of philosophers have accom- 
 plished since Thales. 
 
 But we cannot hope to approach Transcendent Eeality 
 entirely by the Physical Method, proceeding from percepts 
 through analogous concepts to empirical verification. To 
 maintain that this is the only valid method for all investiga- 
 tions that deserve the name of science, no matter how largely 
 the conceptual element may predominate in them : this I 
 take to be the true position of Empirical Philosophy ; and the 
 Physical Method must be followed as far as it will lead us. 
 The opposite method is to begin with concepts, to endeavour 
 to establish their relations to one another, and to regard 
 the success of this procedure, that is, the systematisation of 
 concepts, as the sole requisite verification. Such a method 
 
REALITY AND TRUTH 33 
 
 needs no organon but Formal Logic. Plato's plan of Dialectic 
 makes the nearest approach to it, and Hegel has made the 
 most elaborate attempt to carry it out. We are often assured 
 that Hegel did not disregard the facts ; and that is true : to 
 disregard the facts is impossible, for without them there could 
 be no sense in concepts. But he had no clear view of the 
 place of facts in the method of investigation and proof, nor of 
 the uses of facts in relation to different orders of concepts. 
 Hence, so far as it is based upon facts, his Rationalism is only 
 an unintelligent Empiricism. We must begin with experience, 
 since otherwise there is no problem ; and return to experience, 
 since otherwise no solution is made good ; and proceed on the 
 analogy of experience, since otherwise there is a failure of 
 that continuity and resemblance in which explanation consists. 
 The use of quitting the cave is to find the essential nature 
 and connection of the shadows, and to return, and to interpret 
 them. But the chief concepts of the transcendent world, 
 " Substance " and " Idea," have not the definiteness of content 
 which the Physical Method presupposes. No inference has 
 ever been drawn from them that could be verified by particular 
 experience in perception or introspection. And the truth is, 
 I think, that they are not concepts of science or knowledge, 
 but of that background of Belief out of which knowledge has 
 been differentiated as science has been out of knowledge. If 
 such concepts are to be justified, it must be as appertaining to 
 the necessary background of our picture of the World ; and it 
 should appear possible by fair inferences (though imperfect 
 because unverifiable) — to trace in that obscurity a few faint 
 outlines of resemblance to things that stand in the foreground 
 and are more distinctly known. 
 
 § 7. Reflecting on the above discussion, we find that to 
 question the truth of perception or of conception implies 
 that they are modes of Judgment. To distinguish these three 
 processes may be necessary in Psychology or in Logic, but 
 metaphysically the third is involved in the two former. 
 Whether the phenomenon that suggests to me an oak or a 
 chestnut will prove on inspection to have the further properties 
 of such a tree ; whether yonder rock is slate or granite, yonder 
 
34 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 bird a swallow or a martin ; or whether any o'f them are even 
 solid bodies : these and innumerable other points in the region 
 of present perception may be doubtful ; and in deciding in 
 one way or another, I judge. Similarly with the concept : it 
 is not only that, as Hamilton observes, " every concept is a 
 fasciculus of judgments," implying as many judgments as it 
 comprises attributes and relations between the attributes ; so 
 that if the concept A has the attributes b, c, d, we may be 
 said to judge, logically, that b, c, d, coexist, and that each of 
 them determines A ; but, further, if the concept is used cogni- 
 tively, which is its only interest for Metaphysics, we judge 
 that b, c, d, belong to the reality that A represents, and 
 coinhere in that reality. Hence a doctrine of Categories or 
 highest Concepts is properly a doctrine of Judgments, and is 
 concerned with their truth or relation to reality. Kant shows 
 that it is the reference to objects that distinguishes the meta- 
 physical from the merely logical forms of the understanding. 
 The Truth of Judgments, then, is the ultimate question as to 
 truth of every kind. 
 
 A judgment comprises a sign and something signified : it 
 is a representation or symbolic consciousness of the relations 
 of connection or resemblance in which certain elements of 
 reality stand to one another. There is no impropriety in 
 saying that to judge is to conceive the relation of such or such 
 terms ; but it is always something more, namely, to believe in 
 that relation ; for in no other way can it constitute experience 
 or science. The elements related may belong to the same 
 order, Empirical, Physical, Transcendent ; or these orders may 
 be cross -related in a judgment: that oil of vitriol (for 
 instance) is H.,SO^, is an empirico-physical judgment. But 
 let us avoid as much as possible the humours of technicality. 
 Locke held that any body perceived resembled in its primary 
 qualities the corresponding unknown substance ; but he could 
 not have called this an empirico-transcendent judgment. 
 
 Metaphysics, however, does not inquire into the truth of 
 all possible judgments : it is enough to deal (1) with those for 
 which no forms of proof are given by Logic or Mathematics, 
 namely, judgments taken for granted by those Sciences them- 
 
REALITY AND TRUTH 36 
 
 selves ; (2) the first principles uf the Natural Sciences, so far 
 as they have been ascertained ; and (3) certain judgments that 
 have merely been preserved by i)hilosophic{d tradition ; for 
 this tradition must be continuous. Metaphysics, then, is the 
 criticism of those judgments, whether scientific or traditionary, 
 whicli cannot be proved from otlier judgments, and therefore, 
 strictly speaking, cannot be proved at all : judgments of which 
 no methodical proof is possible, because method supposes some 
 more general principle (which must be a judgment) on which 
 to proceed. Yet, without method, how can there even be 
 criticism ? It becomes necessary to try to advance " considera- 
 tions determining the mind " (in Mill's phrase), in order to 
 induce reasonable people to grant some principle upon which 
 a method may be founded. Hence the fundamental problem 
 of Philosophy is the possibility •)f a criterion or test of truth. 
 
BOOK I.-CANONIC 
 
CHAPTER III 
 
 THE TEST OF TRUTH. 1. HISTORICAL 
 
 § 1. Both in the preparatory and in the great age of Greek 
 Philosophy, Reason was confident in her own powers. Daring 
 and constructive thinkers seem to have been of Spinoza's mind 
 that the truth reveals both itself and error : sane sicut lux 
 seipsam et tenebras manifestat, sic Veritas norma sui, et falsi 
 est. Plato, indeed, mentions the principle of Contradiction 
 as a ground of discrimination {Rep. 436 b), and infallibility 
 (477 e) and distinctness (478 c) as characteristics of science 
 iu contrast with opinion ; but although these remarks remind 
 us of many anxious attempts in subsequent ages to define the 
 nature of truth, for Plato they are rather descriptive than 
 canonical, and show more security than caution. As in the 
 course of investigation difficulties accumulated, he acknow- 
 ledged that truth had not yet been attained, left the Good 
 undetermined, as to the origin and nature of the world was 
 content with probability ; Aristotle, too, whilst carefully 
 investigating the conditions of formal truth, or consistency, 
 admitted Chance amongst the principles of things, and irre- 
 ducible accidentia amongst the consequences. Yet they both 
 assumed that truth was attainable, and that when attained it 
 would manifest itself as a systematic explanation of a world 
 of Reason ; that such a world of Reason exists, and therefore 
 is by Reason knowable. It was only in the age of speculative 
 disappointment and of political and social depression that the 
 force of negative criticism drove men to seek a criterion or 
 test of truth : sedulous to lay sure foundations for the new 
 structure of practical life ; indisputable principles, if not of 
 
 39 
 
40 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 Nature, at least of human conduct. It was in behalf of 
 rational action that the Epicureans and Stoics tried to solve 
 the initial question of Philosophy. 
 
 There were, in fact, two questions: (1) What is Reality? 
 and (2) How do I know that my judgment corresponds with 
 Reality ? 
 
 According to Epicurus, a materialist of the School of 
 Democritus, the criterion of truth concerning Nature is sense- 
 perception, which must be distinct {ivapyi]';) and ultimate, i.e. 
 incapable of being shaken or confirmed by reasoning {a\oyo<i). 
 Touch is the most trustworthy of the senses, because it gives 
 direct knowledge of the properties of the only reality in the 
 world, atoms, when in sufficient mass to be perceptible. This 
 is a criterion of Empirical Reality rather than of Truth. 
 
 Opinion and belief Epicurus traced to the persistence of 
 perceptions in the mind, and therefore held that, to be trust- 
 worthy, they too must be distinct and verifiable by the senses ; 
 at least they must not be contradicted by the senses. Even 
 the atoms, since they are not severally perceptible, can only be 
 the object of belief, and they come under the rule that " con- 
 cerning things imperceptible it is necessary to draw inferences 
 from the phenomena." This is the way of analogy, and it 
 implies a belief in the uniformity of Nature. It also implies 
 that perception is our authority not only for particular sensa- 
 tions but also for their relations or synthesis ; and that the 
 synthesis of belief must also be derived from the perceived 
 connections of things. The only definite synthetic principle 
 discoverable in Epicureanism is the maxim that " nothing 
 arises from nothing or perishes into nothingness." And this 
 is now recognised as one of the constituents of the law of 
 Causation ; yet the way of analogy which governed the 
 conjectures of Epicurus seems to have been concerned (if we 
 may judge from the remains of Philodemus) not with causation, 
 but with the properties of kinds (cf. Diog. Laert. x. 20, and 
 Wallace's Epicureanism, c. x.). 
 
 Epicurus claimed the attainment of positive knowledge 
 only so far as it touched human interests. As to the region 
 of stars and meteors, he was content with any hypothesis that 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 41 
 
 was not contradicted by the senses ; since any possible ex- 
 planation of these things on physical analogies would dispense 
 with the intervention of the Gods : contemplative idlers in 
 intramundane gardens, for whose perfect leisure and repose he 
 was always chiefly anxious. 
 
 The Stoics, materialists of the School of Heraclitus, also 
 derived knowledge from sense-perception : the test of truth, 
 they said, is the irresistibility of conviction (KaraXT^-v/ri?) that 
 accompanies impressions. Hume's " superior force, vivacity, 
 and solidity " is not quite the same thing ; for KaTaXTjyjnf; was 
 due rather to the apprehension of the Subject than to the im- 
 pressions themselves. In fact, of course, both physical and 
 mental agencies are necessary. 
 
 Next to sensations, according to the Stoics, certain con- 
 ceptions are trustworthy, namely, those that are common to 
 all men (kocvoI evvoiai). But they must have been aware that 
 such percepts or concepts could test only the elements of truth ; 
 for they had learnt from Aristotle that truth, or knowledge, 
 requires a synthesis and can only belong to judgments ; and 
 nothing is more memorable of them than their sublime con- 
 ception of the order, law, and unity of the World. No doubt 
 they tried to arrive at such judgments and to correct and 
 justify them by the logical methods which they studied and 
 elaborated ; but no logic can give an original synthesis, and 
 their attempts to avoid this difficulty seem to have incited the 
 later Pyrrhonists to attack the doctrine of the syllogism and 
 all first principles on which syllogisms depend. 
 
 Cicero, though in speculative questions an Academic, 
 followed the Stoics in moral philosophy ; and one tendency 
 of their school attained in his writings to great distinctness of 
 expression : I mean the tendency, derived from the Cynics, to 
 lay stress upon what seemed to them " natural " or according 
 to Nature, as necessarily good and true. It was this that led 
 them to seek the basis of truth in perceptions and in common 
 conceptions formed by a natural process of growth (like Aris- 
 totle's (f)p6vT]ai<;), in spite of their addiction to the artificial 
 processes of Logic and repugnance to the sensuous relations of 
 human life. Cicero followed them in regarding perceptions as 
 
42 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 generally carrying conviction in spite of frequent deceit ; and 
 the KOivaX evvoiac (at least, of morals) appear in his writings as 
 the famous doctrine of innate ideas : sunt enim ingeniis nostris 
 semina innata virtutum {Tusc. iii. 1. 2). 
 
 "Whether indeed this notion, so contrary to the earlier 
 Stoic Psychology, was original with Cicero, cannot, I suppose, 
 be known. It may be traceable to the Platonic reminiscence, 
 which, Th. Whittaker tells us, in his Neo-Platonists (chap. v. § 1), 
 was transformed by Plotinus into a doctrine of innate ideas 
 potentially present. It also occurs in Epictetus, who asked, 
 according to Arrian (AmrptyS. ii. 11. 3), whether of good or 
 evil, of what we ought and ought not to do, there was ever 
 any one without an innate idea {€^<^vtov evvouav). This is 
 something more definite and universal than the hereditary 
 potentiality of virtue recognised by Plato and Aristotle. If the 
 seed of virtue were allowed to mature, Cicero thought. Nature 
 herself would lead us to a happy life. Moral ideas, common to 
 all men, are clearest in children and those who stand nearest 
 to the origins; being, in fact, the expression of that divine 
 Reason which is the life of Nature in the human mind : omnium 
 consensus naturae vox est (Tusc. i. 15. 35). It is vicious 
 customs and institutions that obscure the light of Nature. 
 
 If, however, we inquire strictly for the test of truth in 
 this theory, we can hardly find it in the innate ideas them- 
 selves, since some test is necessary to determine what they are : 
 such as their universal recognition, the canon of catholic truth, 
 quod semper, quod uhique, quod ah omnibus. The trace of this 
 argument is left upon Locke's polemic. 
 
 By whom self- evidence was first alleged as the test of 
 synthetic judgment, I cannot discover ; perhaps by the mathe- 
 maticians : for Plato {Bep. 510) says that the mathematicians 
 set forth their principles as self-evident and rejected all pro- 
 posals to prove them. It implies confidence not so much in 
 a system of reason as in specific intuitions. At any rate, 
 Galen {©epair. MeO. i. 4) speaks of two kinds of manifest truth 
 recognised by ancient philosophers : the one, perceptions of 
 particular sensation, the other, intellectual cognitions, indemon- 
 strable, but evident upon the first inspection. And of the 
 
THE TEST OF TEUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 43 
 
 latter he enumerates : things equal to the same thing are equal ; 
 if equals be added to or taken from equals, the sums or re- 
 mainders are equal ; nothing happens without a cause ; nothing 
 arises from nothing or corrupts into nothing ; and, finally, 
 the principle of Excluded Middle. 
 
 If, then, we sum up the criteria which commended them- 
 selves to Greek philosophers, of various ages and schools, we 
 may say that (1) the earlier inquirers trusted to a systematic 
 or (at least) a comprehensive explanation of the world as its 
 own justification ; that then (2) the principles of logical con- 
 sistency were worked out; that next, when partly by force of 
 this', Logic, partly from other causes, truth seemed ftirther off 
 than ever, (3) trust was put in sense-perceptions, either for 
 their clearness or their aggressiveness, as supplying the elements 
 of knowledge and the means of verifying concepts and judg- 
 ments ; that (4) self-evidence was regarded as a ground for 
 accepting axioms as well as percepts; that (5) naturalness, 
 original endowment, universal consent — they come to the same 
 thing — was more and more relied on by the Stoics ; and that 
 (6) on the whole, in spite of some inconsistencies, the uniformity 
 of Nature (always implied in the belief in a rational world) 
 became more and more explicit amongst both the Stoics and 
 the Epicureans. 
 
 With the revival of Philosophy (that is, of personal 
 unofficial speculation, the Philosophy of private judgment) the 
 search for the Criterion revived; for the Middle Age, like 
 that of the free Greek Cities, had its own confidence, though 
 not exactly of the same kind; and now again criticism, 
 accompanying vast social and political changes, had destroyed 
 that confidence. The Eenascence, like the later Greek 
 schools, professed (at least, in its most conspicuous leaders) to 
 seek knowledge for the sake of life, but with far wider interests 
 and better hope than the Stoics and Epicureans, and in fact 
 disinterestedly. 
 
 § 2. The influence of those schools upon the moderns is 
 very obvious. The moderns went back not to Plato and 
 Aristotle — the latter especially having been discredited by 
 new prejudices and unfashionable friends, — but to those who 
 
44 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 stood nearest themselves ; either (like Bruno and Cudworth) 
 to the Neo-Platonists, or to the Stoics and Epicureans. 
 Bacon may be said to have had Epicurean affinities ; but 
 it is not easy to state his criterion briefly and satisfactorily, 
 nor is it necessary to attempt it, since this is not an ex- 
 haustive history of the subject, but an inquiry as to the main 
 positions ; and the unquestionable characters of Bacon's method, 
 observation, comprehensive comparison, experiment, elimination, 
 will be met with elsewhere. 
 
 The doctrine of Descartes, according to its most conspicuous 
 and oft-repeated statement, is that those things are true which 
 we clearly and distinctly conceive {Discours, P. iv) ; that 
 is, a clear and distinct conception answers for the fact ; and 
 although the terms ' clear ' and ' distinct ' remind one of the 
 Epicurean ivdpjeta rather than of the Stoical KaTaX7)-y^i,'i, yet 
 his derivation of such conceptions (according to the more 
 prominent passages) not from perception but from the innate 
 capacity of the soul, sufficiently indicates the line of tradition ; 
 and, indeed, he calls them communes notiones, though in some 
 men they, are obscured by prejudice {Frincipia, i. § 50). 
 The truths which he thus adduced and relied upon were not 
 only abstract concepts, such as self-existence and perfection, 
 but also axioms : if equals be added to equals the wholes are 
 equal (Frincipia, i. § 13), and that 'nothing cannot be the 
 cause of anything' {Frincipia, i. § 75). 
 
 What Descartes understood by ' clear ' and ' distinct ' is 
 explained in the Frincipia (i. § 45) : " Clear I call that which 
 to an attentive mind is present and open (aperta) ; distinct, 
 that which, besides being clear, is so separated and marked off 
 from everything else, as to contain in itself nothing but what 
 is clear." That, then, is a true conception which is clear in 
 its contents and distinct in all its relations. Descartes did 
 not see that such ideas imply an already completed system of 
 knowledge, and are to be hoped for not in the initiation but 
 in the consummation of Philosophy. Consider the concepts of 
 ' self ' or ' perfection ' in all their relations ! No wonder he 
 should complain that many people never all their lives perceive 
 anything in the way in which alone it can be truly judged of. 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 45 
 
 Conceptions, clear and distinct so far as they have been 
 investigated, must still serve the science of many a generation. 
 Perhaps, however, in spite of the frequency with which 
 the criterion of clearness and distinctness of conception is 
 insisted on by Descartes, and its prominence in the famous 
 fourth part of the Discours de la Methode, we ought to look for 
 his views of systematic proof in the sixth part of that essay, 
 where the use of experiments is explained. He there tells us 
 that his philosophy, assuming at first certain principles of 
 nature, dependent only on the creative activity of God, and 
 derived from " certain seeds of truth that exist by nature in 
 our souls," goes on to deduce from these the phenomena of 
 heaven and earth ; and that when, as sometimes happens, these 
 phenomena are such that they seem deducible in many 
 different ways, there is no other expedient but " to seek out 
 experiments of such a kind that their results will not be the 
 same if the explanation ought to be in one of those ways as 
 it would be if the explanation should be in another way." 
 That is to say, the test of truth is a crucial experiment 
 according to the Physical Method, except that the premises 
 are not inductions. The Uniformity of Nature which this 
 method presupposes is represented by the perfect and immut- 
 able natui-e of God ; but the experiment itself depends on 
 sense-perception. And, in fact, whether Descartes is rightly 
 to be considered as a Rationalist, relying upon pure thought 
 as opposed to sensation, is very questionable. For although 
 when speaking of ideas and principles he uses the verb 
 concevoir or concipere, he also uses percipere : in the Principia 
 having said (i. 30) that everything is true quatenus dare et 
 distincte percipitur, he adds (§ 32) sentire, imaginari, et pure 
 intelligere, sunt tantum diversi modi percipiendi. Hence it 
 appears that he did not place the test of truth in conception 
 in opposition to sense, but held that clear and distinct know- 
 ledge in whatever mode is its own assurance. But he is 
 anxious to dissociate himself from the Epicureans (with whom 
 there was some risk of confusing him) ; and, indeed, he 
 seems to limit clear sense-perception to the subject-matter of 
 Geometry as the sole invariable character of body {Principia, ii. 
 
46 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 § 11) ; although his speculations extended to many phenomena 
 which did not then, and do not even now, admit of reduction 
 to extension, figure, and motion. 
 
 § 3. Descartes was a born system-maker, to whom doubt 
 was an hypothesis and self-confidence an instinct ; his specu- 
 lative ambition was noble and boundless, though its expression 
 was restrained by prudence. But as every man is imperfect, 
 one must be set against another in the dialectic of History. 
 Speculative caution is also precious, if uninspiring. There 
 were more extravagant adventurers than Descartes : and Locke, 
 therefore, set himself " to prevail with the busy mind of man 
 to be more cautious in meddling with things exceeding its 
 comprehension " ; to find how far the understanding " has 
 faculties to attain certainty," and in what cases it can only 
 judge and guess {Essays of Human Understanding, i. chap. 1 , 
 § 4). He was a philosopher by occasion, not by profession ; 
 and it is absurd to criticise him with the same strictness as 
 the rest of them. Upon every subject he was content to say 
 the most sensible thing, and to refrain from any afl&rmation or 
 denial that seemed extravagant or paradoxical. 
 
 According to Locke, knowledge consists in ideas, derived 
 from sensation and reflection, and compared by the mind 
 receiving them. Truth belongs not to ideas as such, but to 
 propositions or judgments concerning their agreement or dis- 
 agreement. The excellence of an idea lies in its being clear, 
 distinct, and adequate ; the truth of our judgment concerning 
 it depends upon its agreement with its object (which it is a 
 sign of), namely, either an idea in another mind, or some real 
 existence {Essays, ii. 32, § 5). As to the latter case, sensations, 
 or " simple ideas, which the mind can by no means make to 
 itself, carry with them all the conformity which is intended, or 
 which our state requires ; for they represent to us things 
 under those appearances, which they are fitted to produce in 
 us " (iv. 4, § 4). But our ideas of sensation resemble the 
 things sensed only in the primary qualities of body ; and how 
 even this can be known he never explains ; ideas produced in 
 us by secondary qualities have no resemblance to them at all 
 (ii. 8, § 15). And ideas are never to be judged true of the 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 47 
 
 real essences of things, the constitution of their insensible parts 
 (Bacon's latens scheviatismus) ; becfiuse they are never adequate 
 to such a representation (ii. 32, § 24). Of such things in 
 nature as fall not within the reach of our senses we can only 
 judge by * analogy ' ; as, finding that friction produces heat, we 
 have reason to think that what we call heat and fire consists 
 in a violent agitation of the imperceptible minute parts of the 
 burning matter (iv. 16, § 12). Having no conception of 
 inductive method, it may, he says, be suspected " that natural 
 philosophy is not capable of being made a science " ; though 
 great probability is attained concerning objects, when the 
 general consent of mankind concurs with one's own constant 
 experience (iv. c. 16). So far as to material things. 
 
 Of our own existence we have ' intuitive knowledge ' by an 
 immediate comparison of ideas ; it is " an internal infallible 
 perception. In every act of sensation, reasoning, or thinking, 
 we are conscious to ourselves of our own being" (iv. c. 9). 
 This implies that our " being " is an idea immediately com- 
 pared with every sensation or thought. The existence of God 
 may be demonstrated from the knowledge of our own existence 
 and the maxim that " bare nothing cannot produce any real 
 being " : which also we know by intuitive certainty (iv. c. 10). 
 
 Further than this, truth is unattainable with regard to 
 particular existences ; but knowledge admits of further exten- 
 sion, for it includes all the agreements or disagreements of 
 our ideas amongst themselves, as expressed in any proposition 
 (iv. c. 6). General propositions concern not existence, but 
 only the relations of our abstract ideas. When the mind can 
 bring two ideas together to perceive by immediate comparison 
 their agreement or disagreement, this we may call intuitive 
 knowledge ; and this gives the greatest certainty. But if the 
 ideas to be compared cannot be brought together immediately, 
 the mind " is then fain, by the intervention of other ideas, to 
 discover the agreement or disagreement which it searches " ; 
 and this is reasoning or demonstration. Each step of such 
 reasoning must be intuitively certain (iv. c. 2). 
 
 Hence arise the Sciences ; of which Mathematics is a great 
 example ; whilst Physics and Moral Philosophy are very back- 
 
48 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 ward. And in Physics the reason of this is, that our ideas, 
 being inadequate to the real essence of things, au intuitive 
 comparison of them is ineffectual to discover the truth. For it 
 can assure us of nothing that passes without the mind. But 
 in Moral Philosophy our backwardness is due to indifference 
 and infirmity ; because the " desire of esteem, riches, or power, 
 makes men espouse the well-endowed opinions in fashion." 
 For in Morals, as in Mathematics, the ideas to be compared, 
 such as angle and circle, murder and government, are 
 constructed by the mind itself, so that the nominal and real 
 essences coincide. There is nothing, therefore, to prevent 
 Moral Philosophy from becoming as demonstrative as Geometry, 
 except the greater complexity of its ideas, and the impossibility 
 of representing them to sense-perception. Unfortunately, as 
 examples of axioms of demonstrative morals he offers only 
 identical propositions : " Where there is no property there is 
 no injustice," and " no government allows absolute liberty " 
 (iv. c. 3). 
 
 In short, Locke's demand for certainty seems to have been 
 solely determined, like that of the Stoics and Epicureans, by 
 practical needs. By sensation and the intuitive comparison 
 of ideas we have enough knowledge to guide us in "this 
 twilight state " : God has made the world habitable, though 
 by no means transparent. The most pious of philosophers, 
 Locke, never thinks of man except as God's feeble creature 
 and ceaseless care, ill-equipped for any knowledge that sub- 
 serves not convenience or virtue. How near this position is to 
 speculative Scepticism it hardly needed the light of Hume to 
 show us. 
 
 § 4. Contrast with it the primitive security of Reason in 
 herself as we find it expressed in Cudworth's Eternal and 
 ImmutaUe Morality : " Now all the knowledge and wisdom 
 that is in creatures whether angels or men, is nothing else 
 but a participation of that one eternal, immutable, and 
 increated wisdom of God " (i. 3). " The first intellect is 
 essentially and archetypally all rationes, and verities, and all 
 particular created intellects are but derivative participations 
 of it " (iv. 4). " But sense being but an idiopathy, we can- 
 
THE TEST or TRUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 49 
 
 not be absolutely certain by it that every other person or 
 animal has the same passion, or affection, or phantasm in it 
 from the same corporeal object that we ourselves have." 
 Hence, " the necessary truth of no geometrical theorem can 
 ever be examined, proved, or determined by sensible things 
 mechanically. And though the eternal, divine intellect be 
 the archetypal rule of truth, we cannot consult that neither 
 to see whether our conceptions be commensurate with it. I 
 answer, therefore, that the criterion of true knowledge is not to be 
 looked for anywhere abroad out of our own minds, neither in 
 the height above nor in the depth beneath, but only in our 
 knowledge and conceptions themselves. For the entity of all 
 theoretical truth is nothing else but clear intelligibility, and 
 whatever is clearly conceived is an entity and a truth ; but 
 that whatever is false, divine power itself cannot make it to 
 be clearly and distinctly understood." Hence it comes to pass 
 that "philosophers and divines have without scruple measured 
 the divine omnipotence itself, and the possibility of things, by 
 their own clear intellections concerning them" (v, 5). 
 
 This is the doctrine of intuitive knowledge. When 
 Descartes says that any universal truth or axiom is " innate," 
 he seems to me to claim merely that it is intuitive. Spinoza's 
 attitude, as we observed, shows just the same confidence : 
 " He that has a true idea knows that he has a true idea." 
 Such certainty may be attained either by deduction from 
 adequate ideas of the properties of things, or by intuition 
 {scientia intuitiva), as when 1 : 2 : : 3 : a; being given, every- 
 body sees that ic=6 {Ethica, ii. 40). By the latter 
 method, he says in the De Intellectus Emendatione, he has 
 not yet been able to know many things : and no wonder, for 
 by intuitive knowledge I understand him to mean direct 
 insight into what is usually discovered by deduction. But 
 in the examples given by Spinoza (much the same in both 
 works), namely, direct cognitions of the equality of simple 
 ratios, we have the same mental activity as in the intuitions 
 of Locke and the clear intellections of Cudworth. It is not 
 imagination, in any sense in which these three authors would 
 intentionally use the word ; nor is it " pure " understanding, in 
 
 4 
 
50 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 the sense of depending on definitions alone ; but a process in 
 which imagination and understanding are undifferentiated. 
 
 There is an instinctive disposition to know, as well as to 
 do : it operates with representative ideas ; and I take it to be 
 essentially a kinsesthetic imagination, working under a given 
 cognitive interest. The typical case is geometrical intuition. 
 It may, or may not, have pictorial or quasi-pictorial accom- 
 paniments, according to a man's cast of mind, Whewell says 
 intuition is " imaginary looking " {Hist, of Sc. Ideas, ii. 9, 
 § 5) ; and it would be an interesting inquiry, how far the 
 philosophers have left in their writings traces of their mental 
 habits, as visile, motile, etc., or only verbile, mistaking the 
 custom of language for insight ; and what are the correlated 
 doctrines. Plato and Bacon are plainly visiles ; but visual- 
 isation of the pictorial sort is, after all, never more than an 
 accompaniment or introduction to the kinsesthesis ; and whilst 
 in some men it persists, as a sort of generous excess or extra- 
 vagance of ideation, in others, for greater concentration, it is 
 omitted, like many other links, in the economic abbreviation 
 of organised processes. The depth of the differences between 
 visile, audile, motile, types, is easily exaggerated : motility 
 is fundamental in objective judgment. 
 
 But in such " imaginary looking," what is it that is seen ? 
 Cudworth and Spinoza are deplorably vague in their state- 
 ments. Locke in his fourth Book (chaps, i. ii. iii.) is much more 
 explicit, and indicates relations of likeness and difference, 
 equality and inequality, as the contents of intuition, in 
 contrast with relations of time and place, of which we can 
 very imperfectly discover uniformities, and only by experience. 
 It was probably from these passages that Hume derived his 
 doctrine ; and, I believe, he was the first to set the matter 
 in a clear light. In the Treatise he begins the first section of 
 Part III. by re-enumerating the " seven different kinds of 
 philosophical relation," and says : " These relations may be 
 divided into two classes ; into such as depend entirely upon 
 the ideas which we compare together, and such as may be 
 changed without any change in the ideas." Those that 
 depend " solely upon ideas can be the objects of knowledge 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— 1. HISTORICAL 51 
 
 and certainty," namely, resemblance, contrariety, degrees in 
 quality, and proportions in quantity or number. Of the 
 other three relations, situation in time and place, identity, 
 and causation, wc receive iuiormation I'roni experience and 
 not from abstract reasoning or reflection. Such remarks, 
 immediately following Hume's criticism of Mathematics and 
 introducing his criticism of Causation, constitute the central 
 turning-point of his work, and may be compared to the 
 metabasis of a tragedy. Intuition, demonstration, the self- 
 evident concatenation of reasoning are only possible in some 
 mode of resemblance. If the resemblances are merely of 
 qualitative terms, we are restricted to climbing up and down 
 in Porphyry's tree, proving that Bucephalus is an animal, 
 and that some animal is Bucephalus. Resemblance of 
 quantity opens the whole range of Mathematics. But of 
 coexistence, succession, identity, there is no intuition or 
 demonstration, but only inference from observation. 
 
 Still, even in the intuition of resemblance or equality, 
 the terms compared are grounded in experience. And so, 
 of course, are all differences, and amongst them quantitative 
 differences or ratios, which are the materials of an intui- 
 tion of equality, that is, proportion. Similarly, relations of 
 coexistence and succession, having been learnt by experience, 
 become the materials of intuitive comparison ; and it is by 
 this means that all the Laws of Nature (constant relations 
 of phenomena) are explained by discovering their resemblance 
 to one another. And as the ultimate form of all such 
 resemblance is causation, this (as Hume says) is the sole 
 foundation of our knowledge concerning either identity or 
 regularity of coexistence and succession amongst concrete 
 things. Compare the discussions of reasoning by intuitions 
 of conjunct and of disjunct relations in Spencer's Principles of 
 Psychology (Part VI. chaps, i.-viii.). He has not made it 
 clear enough that intuitions of disjunct relations involve a 
 comparison of the terms related ; has omitted, in fact, the 
 equivalent of the minor premise in a syllogism. This is true 
 of proportion as well as of syllogism. 
 
 § 5. Leibniz's views of the nature of truth are, historically, 
 
 I 
 
52 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 very important. In the first place, he divides propositions 
 into those of fact, those of reason, and those that are mixed, 
 that is, derived from premises of both the former kinds. 
 General propositions of Keason are necessary, and their 
 opposites are impossible ; those of Fact are obtained by 
 observation or induction, and are not necessary, because we 
 do not see their necessity. Mixed propositions follow as to 
 certitude their weaker premise, that is, the proposition of 
 fact upon which they depend (Nouv. Uss. iv. 11. 13; of. 
 Monaclologie, § 33). 
 
 The foundation of our certitude as to universal and eternal 
 truths is in the ideas themselves, and (like a pure and intel- 
 ligible idea, such as being or unity) does not depend upon 
 the senses {N. E. iv. 4. 2). The chief necessary truths are 
 the principle of Contradiction — that of two contradictory 
 propositions one is true and the other false, or that which 
 involves a contradiction is false ; and the principle de la 
 raison dUerminante (or suffisante) — that is, that nothing 
 happens without a cause, or at least a raison dUerminante, 
 to show a priori why it exists thus rather than otherwise. 
 To an omniscient Being there must be such reasons ; though 
 they may not be clearly known to us, or even, for the most 
 part, cannot be known to us at all {Tliiodicee, i. 44 ; 
 Monadologie, 31-32). In his Bemarques sur le livre de 
 M. King (§ 14) we read that one may say in some sort 
 that these two principles are implied in the definitions of 
 True and of False. Still, eternal truths are at bottom all con- 
 ditional, that is, they posit the existence of the subject : thus 
 ' Every figure that has three sides has three angles ' means, 
 ' Supposing a figure to have three sides, the same figure has 
 three angles' {K E. iv. 11. 11). 
 
 The first truths of fact, or a posteriori, are the immediate 
 perceptions of our own existence and of our thoughts {N. E. 
 iv. 9. 2). But of an universal truth we can never by 
 induction from any number of particular experiences prove the 
 universality, without a knowledge of its necessity by reason 
 {N. E. i. 1. 5). Nor is certainty of innate principles to be 
 based upon universal consent ; for all truths that are not 
 
THE TEST OF TKUTH.— I. IIISTOKICAL 53 
 
 primitive should be demonstrated (N. E. i. 1. 4). Of course 
 ' universal consent ' can only be known by induction. The 
 principle of sufficient reason is indeed applicable to truths of 
 fact, or contingent truths, though we can rarely trace it. 
 Every event depends upon conditions, and these upon others, 
 in a series leading back to God : a necessary substance out- 
 side of the series of contingencies, dans laquelle le lUiail des 
 changemens ne soit queminemment, but which is the last and 
 sufficient reason of them all. The foundation of all truths 
 is the supreme and universal spirit whose understanding is 
 la region des virites Sternelles ; and these contain the suliicient 
 reason and regulative principle of existences themselves and, 
 in a word, of the laws of the universe (iV. ^. iv. 11. 13; 
 Monadologie, §§ 36-38). This is inconsistent with the position 
 that eternal truths are conditional. 
 
 Most important in the history of Philosophy is Leibniz's 
 doctrine that an induction, never being complete, cannot give 
 us necessary truth. This had been an ancient sceptical topic, 
 but it now derived fresh significance from the progress of 
 physical science. Together with Hume's criticism of causation 
 it led Kant to write the Transcendental Analytic. The 
 doctrine is groundless if there is an uniformity of Nature, and 
 if our experience is a fair sample of Nature ; which there is 
 no reason to doubt : for the necessity of a law has no de- 
 pendence upon our seeing or feeling its necessity. Leibniz, 
 however, seems to have held that in our experience there 
 may not be any necessary order ; for although he tells us 
 {Discours de Mitaphysique, § 6) that there is an order in 
 everything that God does, yet his explanations show that to 
 us, in his opinion, this order may present the utmost irregu- 
 larity. Natural processes obey certain maximes subalternes ; 
 but Nature is only a coustume de Dieu (§ 7), which may be 
 altered whenever He sees reason. It is by Him, for Him. 
 
 This order, such as it is, can nevertheless be known 
 analytically from the complete concept of an individual sub- 
 stance : for such a concept is infinite, including all the deter- 
 minations of the substance, and therefore its whole history 
 and relations to everything else : so that every substance is a 
 
54 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 mirror of the world. God, then, having a concept of any sub- 
 stance or of the world, sees in it the ground and reason of all 
 truths ; and every such truth is an identical proposition (§ 8). 
 Hence the principle of sufficient reason is not really co-ordinate 
 with the principles of Formal Logic ; for the analysis of the 
 concept of the world in the mind of God requires only 
 Identity and Contradiction. 
 
 The analytic method of Formal Logic and Mathematics 
 became for Leibniz an Idol of the Den : it was to explain 
 everything ; but in a mind not wholly devoted to scientific 
 interests it provided excuses for obscurantism, and issued in 
 puerile inconsistences. 
 
 § 6. In the Transcendentale Logik {Einl. § 3) Kant says 
 that a criterion of material truth cannot possibly be found, 
 because such a criterion must hold good of all material 
 cognitions, whereas their truth depends upon their particular 
 contents, being in fact the Uehereinstimmung einer Erkenntniss 
 mit ilirem Gegenstande. But, as Henry Sidgwick observes in 
 Mind (No. 33 N.S.), this argument assumes "that true 
 cognitions as such cannot have any common characteristic 
 except that of agreeing with their objects ; but that is surely 
 to assume the very point in question." Accordingly, it is 
 easy to find in the Critiqite of Pure Reason an investigation 
 into the criterion of truth, and the above passage may be 
 considered as an oversight. 
 
 Kant followed Leibniz in holding that true or strict 
 universality cannot be known by experience. A necessary 
 and universal judgment must be known a "priori ; and such 
 judgments — necessary, universal, and synthetic — are found in 
 Mathematics, in all physical sciences, and are, indeed, implied 
 in the possibility of experience itself and its certainty accord- 
 ing to rules {K. d. r. V., Einl. ii.). 
 
 But the principle of Contradiction, so important to 
 Leibniz, he regarded as having only logical validity as the 
 criterion of all analytical cognition, and therefore altered its 
 form of statement. Instead of " It is impossible that anything 
 can at the same time be and not be," where the mention of 
 ' time ' is foreign to merely logical use, he wrote : " Nothing can 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 55 
 
 have a predicate that contradicts it " (its definition); for in the 
 usual statement incompatibility is alleged between two suppos- 
 able predicates of the same subject, both of which may be true 
 at different times ; not, as it should be, between the predicate 
 and the subject itself, which is always the same. Tlie point 
 is that a predicate whose truth depends upon time implies a 
 synthetic judgment, and the principle of Contradiction is to 
 be reserved exclusively for analytic judgments. But, thus 
 restricted, the principle applies only to a contradiction in 
 terms ; whereas synthetic propositions may be contradictory 
 without any reference to time. Must we then invent another 
 principle to demonstrate that one of them is false ? 
 
 For synthetic propositions (Kant goes on), in which the 
 predicate is something quite different from the subject, we re- 
 quire some other criterion than the principle of Contradiction. 
 The different elements of a judgment must be brought together 
 by the imagination into the unity of apperception ; and, 
 further, if the judgment is to have objective reality, it must 
 be related to some actual or possible object of experience, 
 without which it is a mere playing with representations 
 ( Vorstellungen). {Transcendentale Analytik, Buch II. 2nd 
 Hawpst. 1. 2.) 
 
 Toward the end of the same Book, under the Postulate des 
 empirischen Denkens, we find a fuller account of the criteria 
 of objective truth. That is possible, he says, which agrees 
 with the formal conditions of experience both as to intuition 
 and conception : that is to say, it must be capable of existing 
 in time and space and of being determined by the Categories. 
 But to be real (wirklich) it must also cohere with the 
 material conditions of experience ; perception, and therefore 
 sensation {Wahrnehmung niithin Empfindung), is requisite. 
 It is not, indeed, requisite that we should immediately per- 
 ceive the object itself, but we must perceive something 
 with whicli it is connected according to the analogies 
 of experience ; thus magnetic matter is not directly cog- 
 nisable, but only by seeing how a magnet attracts iron 
 filings ; though, if our senses were more acute, we should 
 perceive the magnetic matter itself. It is in this sense that 
 
56 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 we must understand the expression in the foregoing paragraph : 
 " related to some actual or possible object of experience." 
 Finally, that is necessary/ whose coherence with reality is 
 determined according to universal conditions of experience, 
 that is, as an effect of known causes. The category of necessity, 
 therefore, is only applicable to phenomena, not to substances, 
 which can never be regarded as empirical effects, or as 
 beginning or changing. 
 
 We may be surprised that in this passage, after speak- 
 ing of " the universal conditions of experience," Kant only 
 particularises causation. But, plainly, the general meaning 
 is that the criterion of synthetic truth is not some principle 
 that may, like the law of Contradiction, be directly applied 
 to any given analytic judgment merely on its own merits, but 
 demands that every judgment shall be in harmony with all 
 others in a phenomenal world, or experience, which constitutes 
 a possible representation in one unity of apperception. This, 
 however, is a characteristic common to all cognitions of 
 material truth, the very thing which in an earlier passage 
 Kant had declared to be impossible. It is the complex 
 content of Empirical and Physical Reality according to a 
 system of laws, for which, in any particular detail, no general 
 anticipatory principle can be laid down, except that it must 
 involve sensation. 
 
 § 7. The importance to Kant of the Category of Causation 
 as an universal condition of experience may be attributed to 
 the ever -increasing interest of the physical sciences. To 
 establish the possibility of such bodies of necessary truth 
 concerning phenomena, against Rationalism which disparaged 
 experience, and Scepticism which disparaged the necessity of 
 law, was one of the three leading purposes of the Critical 
 Philosophy. A very different procedure brings Mill to a 
 similar result in signalising Causation as the ultimate ground 
 of the sciences of Nature. He was in no way influenced by 
 Kant, whose writings were little studied in this country until 
 after Mill had completed the circle of his ideas ; and it must 
 always be regretted that he saw Kant only in the distorting 
 mirrors of Hamilton and Whewell. But having set himself 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 57 
 
 the task of explaining the methods of science, and of supple- 
 menting and perfecting the Aristotelian Logic by discovering 
 the ground of all generalisation, he was led to recognise the 
 law of causation as that which is implied in all the canons 
 of experimental proof. The want of any such governing 
 principle is the chief defect in Bacon's Orgauon : the defect 
 was made good by Hume, who showed that causation is the 
 ground of elimination : and by means of it Mill was able 
 to amend the Baconian method of observation, comparison, 
 elimination, verification ; to extend it by recognising the part 
 of Mathematics and deductive reasoning, and to draw the 
 outlines of the Logic of Induction in (I believe) their 
 permanent form. 
 
 Mill's writings present a fair summary of the results of the 
 Empirical Philosophy in the middle of the nineteenth century. 
 The Test of Truth is experience : in Psychology, introspection ; 
 in the sciences of the external world, the senses. But experience 
 needs interpretation ; it is subject to illusion ; for every state 
 of consciousness enters into associations with others, which 
 may obscure it or be confounded with it ; and all such 
 growths must be disentangled in order to discover the 
 immediately present idea or sensation. Observation always 
 consists partly of direct consciousness, partly of inference : 
 this cannot be avoided ; but good observation requires that we 
 should be aware of the distinction between the immediate and 
 the inferential factors, and verify the inferential {Logic, Book 
 IV. chap. i. ; Book V. chap. iv.). 
 
 But science consists not merely of observations, but of 
 Laws, and these are generalised after a comparison of observa- 
 tions : they state observed uniformities in the connections of 
 phenomena. In order to know and formulate such general 
 laws, we must have general or abstract ideas or conceptions ; 
 and these are arrived at by comparing individual things : a 
 comparison of white things forms the abstract idea ' white ' ; 
 of round things, the idea ' circular.' When such ideas have 
 been formed they become types with which to compare further 
 particular things (Book IV. chap. ii.). 
 
 To fix an idea it is generally connected with a word, / 
 
58 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 though other signs may serve as the point of attachment ; and 
 it is then possible to carry on a train of thought by means of 
 the signs without always referring to the ideas or the things 
 they represent {On Hamilton, chap, xvii.). 
 
 Laws, however, though expressed in the signs of concep- 
 tions, are not laws of ideas, but of the phenomena denoted. 
 The chief kinds of laws are (1) those of Mathematics and (2) 
 those of Causation. " The axioms of mathematics are experi- 
 mental truths ; generalisations from observation " ; e.g. that 
 two straight lines cannot enclose a space ; that 1 + 1 = 2; etc. 
 (Book II. chaps, v.-vi.). The Law of Causation is generalised 
 from a comparison of less extensive uniformities of succession ; 
 and these are found by observation of particular sequences of 
 events. There is no method of proving it, because there is 
 no more general principle; but it rests on uncontradicted 
 experience. Having assumed it, a ground is obtained for the 
 methodical proof of all other laws according to the Canons ; 
 and then every law so established confirms the major premise, 
 the law of causation. The method must not be regarded as 
 superseding experience or having any authority of its own : 
 causation, the method of induction, and all particular laws 
 have only one basis, experience itself (Book III. chap, xxi.). 
 
 The evidence, says Mill, may now be considered, for 
 practical purposes, complete ; but theoretically we must reflect 
 that Causation, being based on experience, cannot be assumed 
 to prevail far beyond the limits of experience : e.g. in remote 
 parts of the stellar universe (Book III. chap, xxi.) : and that 
 it involves no necessity (Book III. chap. ii.). We may under- 
 stand ' necessity ' to mean either : (1) a strong feeling of con- 
 nection, which may be due to associations by no means 
 corresponding with universal experience; or (2) necessary 
 dependence on certain premises. In the latter sense, laws 
 of Mathematics or Causation are necessarily true, if the 
 axioms are (Book II. chap, v.) ; they are hypothetically 
 necessary. 
 
 Finally, experience is confined to phenomena ; and there- 
 fore all axioms and conceptions, being derived from experience, 
 are concerned only with the order and relations of phenomena, 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 59 
 
 have uo hold upou " matter " or " mind " ^;er se. In fact, 
 these very notions are only constructions from experience. 
 
 § 8. In the latter part of the nineteenth century the 
 theory of evolution iu its application to mental life gave so 
 new a turn to certain doctrines of the Empirical Philosophy 
 and to the whole of Psychology, with which those doctrines 
 were intimately connected, that it might be expected to 
 throw some fresh light upon the old problem of the Criterion 
 of Truth. 
 
 Spencer discusses the test of truth in his Frinciples of 
 Psychology, Part VII., with special reference to the metaphysical 
 controversy between Idealists and Realists (cf. his essay on 
 the Test of Truth). This controversy, he says, persists because 
 the parties to it do not, or will not, agree upon a criterion, 
 yet " there must be somewhere, in some shape, some funda- 
 mental act of thought [some ultimate law of intelligence, 
 § 417] by which the validities of other acts of thought 
 are to be determined" (§ 416). In chap. xi. he states 
 this Universal Postulate : " The inconceivableness of its nega- 
 tion is that which shows a cognition to possess the highest 
 rank, is the criterion by which its unsurpassable validity is 
 known" (§426). 
 
 This principle must be clearly understood and carefully 
 applied. The inconceivable is not to be confounded with the 
 merely incredible. "An inconceivable proposition is one of 
 which the terms cannot by any effort be brought before con- 
 sciousness in that relation which the proposition asserts 
 betwen them " : " An unbelievable proposition is one which 
 admits of being framed in thought, but is so much at variance 
 with experience that its terms cannot be put in the alleged 
 relation without effort." It is unbelievable that a cannon 
 ball should be fired from England to America, but not 
 inconceivable : but it is inconceivable that one side of a 
 triangle should be equal to the sum of the other two, not 
 simply incredible (§ 427). 
 
 In applying the criterion we must consider the kind of 
 proposition to which it is applicable, and do our best to apply 
 it rigorously. The kind of proposition to be dealt with is not 
 
60 THE METAPHYSICS OE NATUEE 
 
 a complex one, of which the terms and their relations are 
 liable to be indefinitely conceived, but a simple one which is 
 "not further decomposable" (§ 428). "That there are anti- 
 podes," a proposition once inconceivable (as Mill urged), is too 
 complex to be tested in this way. Fairer examples are : 
 " whatever resists has extension," and the axioms of Mathe- 
 matics and Logic. Again, in the most sincere endeavour to 
 apply the criterion, we are liable to lapses of thought and 
 attention ; hence " that must be the most certain conclusion 
 which involves the postulate the fewest times " (chap. xii.). 
 
 This criterion is a higher warrant for a cognition than 
 any direct appeal to experiences, such as an empiricist might 
 make, because " it represents experiences almost infinitely 
 nimierous in comparison." Propositions of which the nega- 
 tions are inconceivable depend on nervous structures developed 
 through innumerable generations in correspondence with 
 external relations, and are fixed in proportion as the outer 
 relations are fixed. The inconceivableness of the negation 
 of an axiom results from the impossibility of inverting the 
 actions of the correlative nervous structures (§ 430). 
 
 Now it is not my object to discredit any useful criteria of 
 Truth ; I would gladly see them multiply ; but this is im- 
 possible as long as any of them claims to be exclusive. It is 
 therefore necessary to draw attention to an ambiguity in the 
 use of the term " inconceivable." Spencer has distinguished 
 it from incredible ; but there remains another cognate term, 
 " unimaginable," and this he seems to have overlooked. The 
 opposite of the judgment " whatever resists has extension " 
 seems to me unimaginable, but not inconceivable ; and its 
 unimaginability no doubt depends upon the fixed connection 
 of correlative nervous structures. But inconceivability re- 
 quires that the difficulty of conception should result from the 
 definitions or meanings of the terms; and I find nothing in 
 the meanings of ' resistance ' and ' extension ' to prevent these 
 terms being separated in thought. If their separation is to be 
 called inconceivable, it must be in a psychological, not in the 
 logical, sense. It is otherwise with such an axiom as " Things 
 equal to the same third are equal." In this case the cognition 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 61 
 
 is not indeed merely analytic, depending on the meanings of the 
 terms only ; but the synthesis involved is nevertheless guided 
 and determined by the meanings of ' equality ' and ' sameness ' : 
 the attempt to compare in thought the ' two things ' with the 
 ' third ' is governed by the caution that severally they are to 
 be really equal to it, and that it is to remain strictly the same 
 thing. Hence, however, the axiom is far from being a simple 
 proposition. 
 
 That this distinction between the unimaginable and the 
 inconceivable is not impertinent may perhaps appear, if we 
 inquire how they are severally affected by the alleged guarantee 
 of neuro-psychical evolution. Such a guarantee, by the way, 
 is not to be mistaken for a circuhis in demonstrando : this 
 seems to me a puerile objection. Spencer's design is, I take 
 it, not to give a reason for the criterion itself, but to show 
 how it has come to be the foundation of reasoning .- his 
 argument is explanatory, not demonstrative. If we are now 
 to determine the test of truth, it is reasonable to do so, in 
 view of all our present knowledge ; for it must agree with 
 all the structural lines of that knowledge ; and the reference 
 to organic evolution has especial weight on this ground, that 
 the test of truth, whatever it be, must be reconcilable with 
 the history of the human mind. On the other hand, this 
 very reference draws attention to the limitations attaching to 
 Spencer's criterion, namely, the experiential range of the 
 zoological individual, a range so narrow, indiscriminate, and 
 merely practical in all sub-human species, that it cannot be 
 supposed to include ' a fair sample of all Reality.' Is it not 
 more reasonable to suppose that such experience would give 
 rise to almost inexpugnable prejudices, such as the disbelief in 
 antipodes, than that it would prepare a criterion of universal 
 truth ? But whatever influence sub-human experience has 
 upon our minds, it must affect imaginations rather than con- 
 ceptions ; for imagination is an outgrowth of perception, and 
 is exercised by many animals; but conception, though some 
 rudiments of it may exist in some species, yet attains any 
 degree of development only in man. There must be a con- 
 siderable development of the signs of thought before thoughts 
 
G2 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 can be compared according to the meaning of their signs. 
 And if we consider the definiteness and the caution necessary 
 in conceptual thinking, and how much this depends upon 
 discipline (though some men have an apter disposition for it 
 than others), it seems that those who are judges of what is 
 inconceivable must be few, and to be selected rather for their 
 education than for their ancestry ; and not at all for their 
 remote ancestry ; which, beyond a few generations, is the same 
 for all mankind, and common to Socrates and Sambo. 
 
 Again, granting that the inconceivability of the negation 
 may have some value as a test of truth, still it seems to hold 
 a secondary place, whilst the direct intuition of relations is 
 the primary and essential ground of intellectual certitude. 
 As Spencer says, the axiom concerning equal magnitudes " was 
 held by the Greeks, no less than by ourselves, as a direct 
 verdict of consciousness from which there can be no appeal. 
 Each step in each demonstration of Euclid we accept, as they 
 accepted it, because we immediately see that the alleged rela- 
 tion is as alleged ; and that it is impossible to coticeive it 
 otherivise" (§ 428). But has not the last clause, which I have 
 italicised, somewhat the air of an afterthought ? Is it not 
 the immediate insight into the equality or inequality of the 
 relations compared that carries conviction to the reader of 
 Euclid ? They, I believe, are very few who at each step try 
 to think the opposite ; though to do so would certainly be a 
 harmless, and might even be a wise, precaution. 
 
 From this brief survey of the history of the Test of Truth 
 it appears that modern inquirers have, on the whole, confirmed 
 the conclusions of the Greeks : ( 1 ) the principles of logical 
 consistency have been recognised as necessary to systematic 
 thought; (2) sense-perception has been generally accepted as 
 the test of Empirical Eeality (though its merely phenomenal 
 character has been oftener insisted on), and the improved 
 analysis of Relations has shown that the connection of parti- 
 cular phenomena in time and space can only be known by 
 observation ; (3) the self-evidence of intuition has been ac- 
 knowledged by thinkers of schools the most opposed on other 
 grounds, and clearness and distinctness have been treated as 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— I. HISTORICAL 63 
 
 essential to all cognition ; (4) the value of general consent, 
 though not frequently appealed to and sometimes denied, 
 was defended by the Philosopher of Conmion Sense, and the 
 agreement of competent judges is generally effective, if not 
 conclusive ; (5) the Uniformity of Nature, as the necessary 
 correlate of consistent thought and a rational system of ex- 
 perience, and as implied in every inference and induction, has 
 been generally assumed, and often explicitly stated. It is at 
 this point that the moderns have made the greatest advance 
 upon ancient thought, by defining the principles of Continuity 
 and Conservation in all changes of the world, and by showing 
 their complication with the explanatory function of Under- 
 standing. Hume and Kant agreed in signalising Causation 
 as the essential judgment that gives coherence to the ever- 
 lasting movement of the world. This was probably suggested, 
 as it is continually illustrated, by the progress of the physical 
 sciences ; and it is this that gives us the surest grounds for 
 hope that in the course of ages a comprehensive and systematic 
 explanation of Nature may justify the confidence of Eeason 
 in herself. 
 
CHAPTER IV 
 
 THE TEST OF TRUTH. II. ANALYTIC 
 
 § 1. (a) That sense-perception is the criterion of Empirical 
 Reality must be assumed by every science or philosophy that 
 professes to be a study or explanation of experience. How- 
 ever remote the explanation of experience may be from its 
 immediacy, even if the explanation be sought in transcendent 
 Ideas, nothing can be done, there is no assignable problem, 
 unless the immediacy is accepted as matter-of-fact. After 
 Plato's dialectician had spent some time in that upper region 
 where things are to be seen in their absolute nature, his duty 
 was to return to the cave and instruct his former companions 
 concerning the shadows on the wall ; but his task would be 
 impossible unless these shadows had a definite character ; its 
 possibility would be strictly proportional to their definiteness, 
 and its value to their interest for human Life. 
 
 It must be further assumed that the contents of sense- 
 perception can be determined for a normal subject by eliminat- 
 ing personal errors, and that it is possible to discriminate 
 between what is directly observed and what is inferred, 
 represented, or signified. But how to ensure these conditions 
 is the problem of Methodology, not of Metaphysics. We can 
 see, however, that whether that which is inferred or signified 
 is really connected with that which is observed, can only be 
 known either by further direct observation or by hypothesis 
 and verification. Everything perceived — say a tree seen in 
 the meadow — is a visual picture, including or seeming to 
 include various qualities which, as they are only knowable 
 by other senses than the eye, cannot in fact be seen, but 
 
 64 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— II. ANALYTIC 65 
 
 are associated or integrated with the visual picture and sub- 
 represented in it; whetlier they are truly represented must be 
 discovered by exercising the other senses. 
 
 It must again be assumed, then, not only that a single 
 perception gives Empirical Keality, but also that the connection 
 of discriminated perceptions in one judgment gives Empirical 
 Reality. This is implied in verifying the represented contents 
 of a thing perceived ; and exactly the same assumption is 
 made in perceiving the whole context of things that constitutes 
 Nature or objective experience. The order of things in place 
 and time can only be known to the understanding by the 
 connection of discriminated perceptions in one judgment, and 
 of many such judgments in one comprehensive unity of 
 apperception ; but the source and the verification of such 
 judgments is the detail of sense-perception. 
 
 Reflective analysis of Empirical Reality has two con- 
 sequences. Eirst, the feeling of Reality seems to evaporate ; 
 immediate experience turns into a shadow - world ; and no 
 wonder, for the feeling of Reality depends not on discrimina- 
 tion and judgment, but upon the growth of perceptive powers 
 in organic consciousness. Empirical Reality is originally 
 constructed upon the animal plane of intelligence, and even 
 such confidence as deliberate judgment possesses is transmitted 
 to it from the perceptive system. Hence intuition is an 
 " imaginary looking." But, secondly, the reflective analysis 
 of immediate experience reveals its miscellaneous and frag- 
 mentary character. Although human perception is impossible 
 without classification, still the resemblances recognised in 
 perception by no means satisfy the himian understanding ; 
 and this gives rise to attempts at constructing conceptual 
 systems ; which, when constructed, are sometimes used to 
 disparage sense-perception as an illusion and deceit : data and 
 verification are supposed to be sublated by an hypothesis that 
 derives from them its whole vitality. 
 
 (b) One way of disparaging sense-perception by means of 
 concepts is to distinguish between formal and material truth, 
 and to assign certainty and necessity only to the formal. 
 But " formal truth " and " material truth " are both of them 
 
66 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 contradictiones in adjecto ; for the essence of truth is the 
 correspondence of form with matter, the verifiable agreement 
 of judgment with Reality. It is in this sense that truth is 
 the subject of Metaphysics. 
 
 In Logic, indeed, the distinction between form and matter 
 is all - important : for first, it determines the limits of that 
 Science ; which discusses the form of propositions or judg- 
 ments, that is, the relations of terms, and whatever is implied 
 therein, without regard to any special character of the terms ; 
 and secondly, it thereby makes conspicuous the inadequacy 
 of a merely logical treatment of any concrete matter of fact 
 apart from observation. The Logician says (or should be 
 understood to say), let us see what can be said about the 
 relations of things without considering the things themselves, 
 or about the form of knowledge apart from the things to be 
 known. This may lead to consistency, but not to truth. 
 
 But the problem of Metaphysics is altogether different 
 from this ; it is to survey knowledge in relation to existence ; 
 if possible, the whole of knowledge in relation to the whole of 
 existence ; and therefore cannot regard the forms of the world 
 apart from the world itself, unless they exist separately. Now 
 they are only regarded as existing separately according to a 
 certain possible doctrine ascribed to Plato. But that doctrine 
 turns the forms or Ideas into the essential Reality, with which 
 our knowledge can only be a correspondence. For Metaphysics 
 it is true that this Ideal Theory is but a duplication of Nature, 
 for the metaphysical problem remains the same. And so it 
 must if noumenal Reality be the presence of things to the 
 Divine mind, where they exist not merely formally but 
 eminently, not in bare relation but in greater fulness and 
 glory than for us. Reality in whatever mode is always the 
 object, and can never be the content, of Metaphysics ; nor can 
 any conceptual system concerning Reality convince the human 
 mind that is not verifiable by human organs, l)y the prying 
 eye and the searching finger. 
 
 Hence the vanity of any such scheme as Locke proposed 
 for a Moral Philosophy based upon ideas which we make for 
 ourselves, concerning property, justice, and other presumptive 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— II. ANALYTIC 67 
 
 contents of the original contract, not upon observation of the 
 Empirical Reality of Morals, that is, human life. It could 
 only be a place of verbal propositions where the law of Con- 
 tradiction was supreme. Whether that law has any appli- 
 cation to Reality will be considered in Chapter XIV.; but as a 
 test of formal or analytic " truth " (more properly consistency), 
 the place given it by Leibniz and Kant, it can have for Meta- 
 physics only a methodological interest in the elaboration of 
 concepts. 
 
 (c) The universality of a belief, in the sense that it has 
 been held by all mankind, was justly rejected by Leibniz as a 
 test of truth. If a Church takes the universal acceptance of a 
 doctrine by its adherents to be evidence of truth, it may mean 
 that the doctrine has been acknowledged by all Councils, and 
 that may be ascertainable. But the assent of all mankind can 
 only be discovered by exhaustive observation : as impossible in 
 the case of man as in any other kind of natural objects. 
 Attempts to carry out the investigation have led to much cross- 
 examining of timid troglodytes and sullen anthropophagi ; but 
 many a tribe near to the origins, a depository of primitive 
 wisdom, has departed beyond the reach of your questionnaire : 
 those precious witnesses, the Tasmanians, have just escaped, 
 and we shall never know whether ex nihilo nihil was a tenet 
 of theirs. For my part, I deny that, in a philosophical 
 question concerning men, the zoological definition of Man 
 affords a satisfactory means of determining the individuals 
 referred to. 
 
 It is true, of course, that the consent of others strongly 
 confirms our own belief; and the support of the expert, the 
 specialist, the initiated, the illuminated, and the inspired is 
 particularly comforting. Most people are incapable of believ- 
 ing except in a crowd, and those who can be happy alone upon 
 the bleak mountains of speculation are rare indeed. Still, even 
 if the universality of beliefs could be established, it would only 
 be conditional evidence of their objective truth. Granting 
 that such beliefs must rest upon a correlatively wide and 
 lasting experience, yet we have seen that the value of any 
 experience depends upon whether it gives a fair sample of 
 
68 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Nature ; if it does, the quantity of it is unimportant ; if it does 
 not, no amount of it is conclusive. Now many things that 
 are universal in the experience of men may, nevertheless, be 
 peculiar to human nature or to its circumstances on this earth, 
 and so give occasion to Idols of the Tribe. This is notorious. 
 Or, again, granting that universal beliefs must be useful, it 
 will remain to inquire how utility is to be estimated, and 
 whether we are prepared to maintain that it is never weU to 
 be deceived, and that the usefulness of a belief is a proof of its 
 objective truth. In short, the alleged universality of a belief, 
 far from proving its validity, makes it an interesting object of 
 history, analysis, and interpretation. 
 
 As for the doctrine of innate ideas or principles, which is 
 historically connected with that of notiones communes, it seems 
 not to have been urged by any one that innateness is an ulti- 
 mate criterion of truth, since reasons are given for believing 
 such or such ideas to be innate : as that they are common to 
 all men ; that they are clearest in children ; that they become 
 manifest (like gout) in the maturity of life ; that with furniture 
 so useful God must have endowed us ; that, like Descartes's 
 idea of perfection, they are too good for a poor man to have 
 invented ; or that we cannot imagine how else they came to 
 us, and that acceptance of traditionary phrases is more com- 
 fortable than suspension of judgment. 
 
 The Kantian modification of this doctrine, speaking of 
 a priori forms of intuition and understanding, instead of innate 
 ideas, explicitly infers the activity of such forms from the given 
 fact that there are true sciences of Mathematics and Physics. 
 But this separation of the form from the content of Science, 
 whilst it is admitted that neither of them can ever be separately 
 known, is the same idle whim as the belief in Laws of Nature 
 as having some sort of existence apart from the order of events. 
 The laws of Eeason are an abstraction and generalisation of 
 perceptions and reasonings. 
 
 The theory of mental evolution gives a new aspect to the 
 doctrine of innate principles ; but, instead of assigning them 
 any origin other than experience, it ascribes them to heredity 
 and selection; not suggesting that they are ultimate, but 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— II. ANALYTIC 69 
 
 assuming the uniformity of nature and an orderly world to 
 which they were our ancestral adaptations ; pointing as 
 emphatically to the limitations as to the antiquity of experi- 
 ence, and therefore as favourable to scepticism as to science. 
 Inherited dispositions to perceive or judge, though essential 
 to experience and influential in speculation, do not dispense 
 with analysis and verification, nor preclude the soothing 
 reflection that one hour in a physical laboratory is more 
 instructive than a thousand years of clambering in the 
 Congo forest. 
 
 (d) The clearness and distinctness of cognition, insisted on 
 under various conditions by Epicurus, Descartes, and Locke, 
 certainly increases with advancing knowledge ; and, no doubt, 
 it is one criterion of truth. Clearness and distinctness of 
 perception is instinctively held to be a test of Empirical 
 Reality ; and to increase the adequacy of perception we always 
 endeavour to make it more and more clear and distinct. 
 Conception, by its very nature, has these characteristics ; for 
 a concept is nothing but the complete determination of an 
 abstract or general idea by methodical analysis ; and, accord- 
 ingly, it is expressed by a definition. Similarly with the 
 more explicit acts of judgment concerning the relations of 
 percepts or concepts ; these, too, when they are really intel- 
 lectual acts and not merely associations of custom, asseveration, 
 or interest, are regarded as trustworthy in proportion as they 
 are clear and distinct. Convinced by a demonstration of 
 Euclid, a boy says that he clearly sees it ; and this is what 
 Locke and others mean by ' intuitive knowledge.' The intuition 
 of equality — the masterform of understanding — is the most 
 clear and distinct of all. 
 
 Still, whilst clearness and distinctness are characteristics 
 of truth, they do not seem to be peculiar to it ; and, if not, 
 they do not afford an adequate criterion : not, at least, if we 
 take the percepts or concepts so marked, in the limited sense 
 that would seem to have satisfied Epicurus and Descartes. 
 For an hallucination may be very clear and distinct. My 
 concept of a centaur is, I think, clear and distinct, and so is 
 the judgment that Hercules slew Nessus. My reason for not 
 
70 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 regarding such things as true is not their vagueness or 
 obscurity, but a want of evidence that they cohere with the 
 material conditions of experience, and assimilate with other 
 concepts and judgments that have such coherence. The 
 reports of ancient authorities concerning centaurs are deficient 
 in the guarantees of observation, and are in conflict with the 
 teachings of Comparative Anatomy, that is, with the analogy 
 of experience ; whilst they assimilate readily enough with 
 other incredible things, — for the great world of The Incredible 
 has its own laws and intuitions. 
 
 It may be objected that the concept of a centaur is not 
 really clear and distinct ; two chests, two stomachs with the 
 appurtenances (it may be said), how is this conceivable ? It 
 is conceivable in the limited sense which seems to have 
 sufficed when this criterion was relied upon. The real objec- 
 tion is, that such a conception is not what it ought to be, in 
 view of the animal system ; that no concept by itself can be 
 adequate, because nothing in Nature is isolated. The meaning 
 of a concept is always relative to other concepts in some 
 scientific scheme, according to the character of the relations 
 conceived. Hence the clearness and distinctness of a cogni- 
 tion fer se is not a sufficient criterion : its relations must be 
 considered and the analogy of experience consulted. 
 
 (e) To follow the analogy of experience, then, is certainly 
 another characteristic of Truth, as Epicurus saw, though 
 vaguely. It implies the uniformity of Nature and other 
 concepts which cannot now be discussed without anticipating 
 future chapters. If interpreted as including the ' ex nihilo 
 nihil,' it is an essential postulate of all reasoning and explana- 
 tion ; and hence some such meaning has generally been 
 regarded as the valuable element in Leibniz's principle of 
 Sufficient Eeason ; bvit whatever his meaning may have been, 
 he has, in the spirit of the pre-Kantian Metaphysics, purposely 
 expressed it in such a way as to carry the train or context of 
 conditions beyond the bounds of experience. The same 
 criterion is implied in tlie belief of Bacon and Descartes as 
 to the value of crucial instances ; for Logicians have shown 
 that crucial instances derive their probative force from the 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— II. ANALYTIC 71 
 
 law of Causation, which is the chief clue to the analogy of 
 experience. Accordingly, Kant says that that is necessary 
 whose coherence with reality is determined according to 
 universal conditions of experience, that is, as an effect of 
 known causes ; and Mill regards Causation as a principle fit 
 to be the test of all others concerning clianges in the 
 phenomenal world, though not as a necessary truth. 
 
 § 2. Whatever is true is necessary. Mill's detestation 
 of this word ' necessary ' probably arose from his observing 
 how readily men use it to consecrate their prejudices, as a 
 sort of taboo in defence of tradition, or as a brow -beating 
 term to intimidate opponents. It may seem to check inquiry 
 in all directions ; or, at any present stage of inquiry, to claim 
 too much for human certitude. Still, I suppose a principle 
 may be necessary " humanly speaking " ; and no doubt it is in 
 this sense that Spencer regards those simple propositions of 
 which the opposite is inconceivable as necessarily true. Now 
 I have already observed that inconceivability, as distinguished 
 from unimaginability, requires that the difficulty of concep- 
 tion should result from the definition or meaning of the 
 terms ; and those synthetic judgments are most clearly, dis- 
 tinctly, and confidently held that are guided and determined 
 by the definitions or meanings of the terms ; and in this it is 
 implied that the terms themselves are clearly and distinctly 
 conceived. 
 
 Such terms and such judgments belong to methodical 
 systems of knowledge, of which the whole structure has been 
 framed according to the analogies of experience. And those 
 systems of knowledge, both as wholes and in their parts, will 
 be most precisely conceivable (and their opposites most incon- 
 ceivable) whose terms and relations admit of the most clear, 
 distinct, and adequate definition. Such are Mathematics and 
 Physics, and therefore they were rightly selected by Kant as 
 the exemplars of necessary truth. In these sciences the 
 terms are precisely defined, and the relation of judgment, 
 Equality, is the most definite of all relations. Causation in 
 Physics is not merely a qualitative relation, but is treated 
 quantitatively as the redistribution of matter and energy ; so 
 
72 THE .METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 that the effect, so far as quantitative, being given in the cause 
 and the cause in the effect, the doctrine of Hume (adopted 
 inconsistently by Kant) that cause and effect are different 
 things, and that one cannot be anticipated from the other, 
 ceases in this quantitative aspect of them to be true ; in other 
 words, the conceivability of the causal relation is determined 
 by the definition of the terms. For the same reason its 
 negative is inconceivable, and the causal judgment becomes 
 necessary. 
 
 If it be said that, according to this doctrine, necessity 
 would seem to characterise any consistent body of judgments 
 concerning clear and definite terms and relations, though it had 
 no coherence with experience, I reply that necessity would 
 characterise the internal relations of such a system, which 
 would be a gigantic illustration of formal Logic ; but that the 
 construction of systems so extensive as the sciences, without 
 the data of experience, surpasses human ingenuity. At least, 
 no assurance that it can be done will content me unless 
 accompanied by a fair sample of its accomplishment. Schemes 
 that, like the Ptolemaic system, depart from the analogy of 
 experience, even though they start from experience, break 
 down ; so do those that, like Rational Ontology, vaguely apply 
 the analogies of experience to nothing that is verifiable. And, 
 finally, even if such a system had an internal, relative, or 
 hypothetical necessity, still, since (by hypothesis) it would not 
 also cohere with Empirical Reality, the necessity attaching to 
 it would not have that quality of belief which arises from 
 connection with experience and practice. 
 
 But if the precise conception of relations (that is, judgment) 
 and the inconceivability of the opposite, result from the 
 determination of judgment by the definitions of the terms 
 compared ; and if the terms thus defined are found in 
 methodical systems of knowledge constructed from the data, 
 and according to the analogy, of experience ; it follows that 
 conceivability and inconceivability as tests of necessary truth, 
 are only modes of appealing to the analogy of experience. And 
 this agrees with Spencer's view that they result from an 
 infinite inherited experience ; and with his position in First 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— II. ANALYTIC 73 
 
 Principles (§ 40), that " there is no mode of establishing the 
 validity of any belief except that of showing its entire 
 congruity with other beliefs." 
 
 Apparently, then, a comparison of the doctrines of all the 
 philosophers (not being sceptics) who have investigated the 
 criterion of Truth, shows that they agree in regarding it as — 
 clear and distinct conceptions and judgments cohering with 
 Eeality and harmonising amongst themselves according to the 
 analogy of experience. 
 
 § 3. To return to the nature of scientific necessity : it is 
 not, I take it, a quality of pure cognition (of course, there is 
 no such thing as pure cognition), but a mode of feeling that 
 accompanies clear intuitions, and is in some respects similar to 
 the feeling that accompanies other cognitions and beliefs of 
 very different kinds. When a " necessary belief " is in question, 
 it is not the fact of necessity but the feeling of it that has 
 to be explained ; knowledge of the fact, so far as attainable, 
 depends upon systematic verification, and upon the exemplary 
 character of our experience. For example, a man may feel 
 the necessary truth of Euclid's 47th Proposition, and he may 
 also feel that the omission of some ceremonial observance is 
 necessarily connected with retributory misfortune. But the 
 causes of the feeling in these two cases are very different ; and 
 the feeling, like every effect, differs according to the nature of 
 its causes. Every one may consult his own consciousness for 
 the difference between the necessity of demonstration and the 
 necessity of prejudice. The latter seems to be sufficiently 
 explained as a case of what Mill calls ' inseparable association.' 
 Suppose that a man has been told often, and in awful 
 circumstances, that omission will be punished ; that he has 
 conformed from childhood under fear of punishment, and has 
 known occurrences which he interpreted as verifications of the 
 fear (overlooking ' negative instances ') ; that the belief coheres 
 with the whole system of his religious life, and has the consent 
 of all his friends and neighbours ; so that it has become 
 impossible for him to think of breaking his custom without 
 having a terrifying premonition of supernatural vengeance. 
 No one will contend that a feeKng of necessity thus generated 
 
74 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 is any guarantee of a corresponding reality of connection 
 between the terms of the belief. 
 
 But our sense of the necessity of Euclid's 47th Proposition 
 has quite another origin. It depends upon the clear concaten- 
 ation of the argument, which the inward eye seems to follow 
 from premises to conclusion through the definite relations of 
 equality. The effect is similar to that of looking around the 
 room and seeing the position of the walls and furniture, 
 the cognition of which is necessary. To be sure, the inward 
 rarely has the distinctness and steadiness of the bodily eye ; 
 but in geometrical reasoning this defect is corrected by the 
 definitions, which call back and illumine the mind's eye when- 
 ever it wanders and grows dim ; and by resort to perception 
 or imagination in constructed figures, by which it is plain 
 that any appreciable departure from the hypothesis there (say, 
 an ill-drawn right angle) involves a corresponding incongruity 
 with the conclusion. 
 
 Hence it was that, so early in the history of philosophy, 
 the mere rudiments of Mathematics could suggest to Plato's 
 susceptibility the exalted conception of science as necessary 
 and universal truth ; and hence his anxiety in the BepuUic to 
 reduce science to its pure mathematical elements, treating of 
 Acoustics without sounds and Astronomy without stars ; the 
 sensuous element of knowledge being intractable by the same 
 methods. Plato's conception of science descended to Kant : 
 that science consists of synthetic propositions universal and 
 necessary, is one of the main foundations of the Critique of 
 Pure Reason (the other is, that perception is the test of 
 Reality) ; and the scope of science is still regarded by him as 
 limited to Mathematics and mathematical Physics. The 
 success of his speculations upon this basis was astonishing, 
 and remains instructive in spite of his archaic Psychology. 
 And the soundness of his foundations may be judged by the 
 comparative failure of his attempt to derive the theory of 
 conduct, in a similar way, from the concept of Duty as a 
 command of Reason requiring unconditional obedience ; for 
 conduct belongs to a region in which the appropriate concepts 
 and their relations are not yet sufficiently determinate for 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— II. ANALYTIC 75 
 
 necessary reasoning. The same characteristics of precision 
 and continuity that charmed Plato continue to captivate the 
 scientific mind : whence the unceasing effort to extend and 
 universalise the quantitative and mechanical way of conceiving 
 Nature ; and the tendency to regard the conceptual Physical 
 World as more necessarily true and more real than the fulness 
 of Empirical Eeality. 
 
 I do not contend that association has nothing to do with 
 the sense of scientific necessity. Whatever judgment is taken 
 up into a system of judgments already held with conviction, 
 will be suffused with the same feeling. And any method that 
 has been pursued with good results in one department of 
 research, will retain a certain prestige when carried into 
 another. Eeasonings about a fourth dimension of space may 
 acquire plausibility from this influence. Even when the 
 transference of method is superficially formal and quite 
 illusory, this effect of quasi - necessity may be produced, as 
 in Spinoza's Ethics : where the simulation of mathematical 
 method is entirely external ; since the judgments throughout 
 are as often concerned with co-existence and succession as 
 with quantity ; and the many excellent results obtained are 
 due not at all to the method but to native insight and induc- 
 tion. This fact is but slightly obscured by giving the name 
 of ' axiom ' or ' postulate ' to observations and inductions : as in 
 the remarkable passage between Propositions 13 and 14, in 
 Part II. 
 
 § 4. But besides the definiteness of conception and relation 
 that characterises the exact sciences, there is another condition 
 of the sense of necessary cognition which they share with 
 other departments of knowledge ; and that is the interest of 
 consistency. If we have the luck to form a true judgment 
 we adhere to it for our own sakes ; in intercourse with others 
 we are bound to use words in their accepted meanings and 
 relations ; and, indeed, such is the charm of consistency that 
 even if we fall into an error, there is a strong temptation to 
 make everything else square with it. Bain says : " It is a 
 fundamental requisite of reasoning, as well as of communica- 
 tion by speech, that what is affirmed in one form of words 
 
76 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 shall be affirmed in another." If we say ' matter is heavy/ 
 we must admit that it ' gravitates/ and so forth. " To these 
 self- consistent, though variously worded, affirmations is 
 applied the description Necessary Truth. A more exact de- 
 signation would be an equivalent, implicated, or self -consistent 
 assertion" {Logic, Introd. § 21). To this kind of necessary 
 truth belongs every verbal or analytic proposition, in which 
 the predicate is part of the definition of the subject, and of 
 which, as Kant says, the principle of Contradiction (in his 
 version of it) is the universal and sufficient regulative. The 
 doctrine of Conversion and Obversion in Logic is an out- 
 growth of this demand for consistency, and an attempt to 
 determine the formal conditions of it. 
 
 The logical doctrine of the Syllogism is also a scheme of 
 consistent statement, with one further condition, namely, that 
 its axiom be true ; and this, whether expressed as the Dictum 
 or Nota Notae, is an example of distinct precise judgment 
 guided and determined by definite concepts — ' middle term ' 
 or 'mark.' It is characteristic of the Syllogism that the 
 conclusion is true if the premises are ; and Mill, extending 
 this characteristic to the deductive sciences in general, says : 
 " When it is affirmed that the conclusions of geometry (for 
 example) are necessary truths, the necessity consists in reality 
 only in this, that they correctly follow from the suppositions 
 from which they are deduced" {Logic, ii. 5, § 1): that is, 
 from the axioms and from the hypothesis that things exist 
 corresponding to the definitions, line, circle, and so on (which 
 is not quite true). Thus, so far as Mill will recognise necessity 
 at all in our cognitions, he identifies it with consistency. Now 
 the ground of the consistency of judgment and of the necessity 
 of it is that consistency or uniformity of Nature which, found 
 in fragments or divined in Empirical Eeality, is carried out 
 into Physical Eeality and verified. 
 
 If, then, we suppose the whole of possible Knowledge and 
 Belief to have been organised into Sciences, and all sciences 
 to have attained the precision and coherence of Physics 
 (especially if they should have become branches of Physics), 
 this body of knowledge, starting from Empirical Eeality, 
 
THE TEST OF TKUTH.— IT. ANALYTIC 77 
 
 coherent and harmonious in all its judgments and verified in 
 Empirical Keality, would constitute Positive Philosophy and 
 would be felt to be necessary truth. It would be our nearest 
 approach to realising Leibniz's conception of the system of the 
 world as in the Divine Mind eternally extant. The derivative 
 laws of such a system would be necessary in the sense that 
 they could not be denied without denying the Axioms and 
 Causation. Nor could the Axioms and Causation be denied 
 without denying all their consequences : for although it is 
 generally good logic that the denial of an antecedent does not 
 sublate the consequent, yet in this case it does, because the 
 Axioms and Causation are the sole logical conditions of the 
 derivative laws, and indeed for human knowledge they have 
 no separate existence. The whole system would also have the 
 guarantee of Empirical Eeality, from which its concepts are 
 shaped and in analogy with which its judgments are determined; 
 so far at least as it succeeded in supplementing the inadequacy 
 of perceptions : but I cannot say that it would attain to equal 
 necessity. For, again, it is vain to apply the logical maxim 
 that the denial of the consequent sublates the antecedent, 
 since there is no hypothesis about Empirical Eeality : it 
 existed before any conceptual system, has survived the failure 
 of many, and may see the passing of many more. 
 
 How the precision and consistency of science, the great 
 system of definitions and equations, produce the sense of 
 necessity in a good mind, may be seen in the confessions of 
 the growth of conviction which Whewell somewhat naively 
 makes, and which are quoted against his own a prioi-i theory 
 of necessary truth by Mill (Logic, ii. 5, § 6): "Though the 
 discovery of the first law of motion was made, historically 
 speaking, by means of experiment, we have now attained a 
 point of view in which we see that it might have been 
 certainly known to be true independently of experience." And 
 again : " That they (the laws of chemical composition) could 
 never have been clearly understood, and therefore never firmly 
 established, without laborious and exact researches, is certain ; 
 but yet we may venture to say, that being once known, they 
 possess an evidence beyond that of mere experiment. For 
 
78 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 how, in fact, can we conceive combinations otherwise than as 
 definite in kind and quality ? " Thus, even beyond the sphere 
 of Physics, in Chemistry, where the processes cannot be 
 followed with the same intuitive precision, the influence of 
 systematic treatment, the analogy of the concepts of uniformity 
 and equality to those of the mathematical sciences and, 
 generally, what may be called the scientific way of thinking 
 (and not, I think, merely, as Mill says, habitual association), 
 produce the effect which (as above suggested) is to be expected, 
 in such circumstances. And I hope the view here set forth 
 of the nature of necessary intuition may reconcile the historical 
 schools of disputants represented by Whewell and Mill ; since 
 it shows that whilst sense-perception is the test of Eeality 
 and the starting-point of the conceptual process, it is only the 
 test of truth when working in alliance with the intuitive 
 imagination and the scientific understanding. 
 
 § 5. But it may naturally be objected that such a state 
 of scientific development as I have described is very far from 
 having been reached : the system of Positive Philosophy 
 contemplated is only an ideal. How then can it be used as 
 a criterion of truth ? Besides, if such a system were complete, 
 a criterion would no longer be needed. But although the 
 system does not yet exist, and if it did would be needless as 
 a criterion, the method and the character of the system are 
 sufficiently known to serve our purpose. It must start from, 
 and return to. Empirical Reality ; its judgments must consist 
 of definite concepts definitely related ; the things and processes 
 supposed to obtain beyond the region of sense-perception must 
 be intuited on the analogy of those within this region ; 
 judgments (or laws) concerning these things and processes 
 must harmonise with one another, and conspire to form one 
 system imder the presiding schemata of the axioms and 
 causation. Surely, these conditions admit of being applied to 
 any judgment, law, or hypothesis that is called in question, 
 due allowance being made for the different stages of progress 
 that have been reached in different departments of study. In 
 each study there is possible, at any given time, a certain degree 
 of definiteness of conception and intuition and a certain quality 
 
THE TEST OF TRUTH.— II. ANALYTIC 79 
 
 of systematic co-ordination ; and (as you may have heard) a 
 good mind with the appropriate culture knows what it is. 
 But in every study, in proportion as definiteness of conception, 
 rigour of verification, or systematic co-ordination is wanting, 
 in that proportion a good mind does not experience necessar}' 
 conviction. 
 
 Indeed, is not this the criterion actually employed at 
 present, so far as method is understood or instinctively 
 apprehended ? Suppose that a great outburst of scientific 
 genius should astonish the world ; that men should arise in 
 every department of inquiry with power to revolutionise it, 
 discovering more commanding generalisations than the Atomic 
 Theory, the Undulatory Theory, Gravitation, the Laws of 
 Motion, and more certain principles than the Axioms and 
 Causation : how could they make good their claims, except by 
 greater definiteness of conception, greater strictness of verifica- 
 tion, and more systematic co-ordination of results ? 
 
 It may be some confirmation of this view of the criterion 
 to observe that definiteness, verification, and co-ordination are 
 the differentia of Science and Philosophy in contrast with 
 popular Knowledge ; that each Science as it grows, strengthens 
 and comforts itself (as Bacon might say) by the increase of 
 these characters ; and that such progress is the instinct of the 
 scientific mind and the aim of every philosopher : except some 
 Sceptics. 
 
CHAPTER V 
 
 SCEPTICISM 
 
 § 1. The chief dissensions between schools of Philosophy seem 
 to begin with their sense of the modality of Knowledge — 
 whether apodeictic, or assertory, or problematic. There are 
 thinkers, such as Kant, who maintain that some cognitions, 
 mathematical, physical, moral, are necessary. Others, such as 
 Mill, regard our knowledge as at most assertory ; we may, 
 they say, hold with entire confidence an extensive array of 
 propositions as true, according to our powers of discovering 
 truth ; but to treat them as absolutely true of the Universe, 
 or as if the objective correspondence could not have been 
 otherwise, is to go beyond our warranty. But besides these 
 schools there are the Sceptics, the mildest of whom will not 
 admit that knowledge can be better than problematic. 
 
 It might seem, if we considered only this sense of the 
 modality of knowledge, that the problematic philosophers 
 must be more opposed to both the assertory and the apodeictic, 
 than these to one another. Yet I think it will be admitted 
 that, historically, the closest sympathy upon general grounds 
 has existed between the problematic and assertory schools ; 
 or, let us say, since it comes to much the same thing, between 
 the Sceptics and Empiricists. But this grouping cannot last 
 much longer ; for the difference between apodeictic and 
 assertory philosophers tends to disappear. I, at least, cannot 
 understand how any Empiricist can deny that whatever is 
 true is necessary, and that certain intuitions are both seen to 
 be true and felt to be necessary, — whatever the value of such 
 feeling. On the other hand, the claim to know by intuition 
 
 80 
 
SCErXICISM 81 
 
 the universal necessity in Nature of certain truths, is palpably 
 inconsistent on the part of Transcendentalists who accept the 
 argument of Leibniz ; for intuitions are only particular 
 experiments in knowledge, and therefore can never give 
 necessity to a general judgment. It is indeed a contradiction 
 in terms to claim for pure cognition a quality tliat is essentially 
 feeling. As for the tenet that mental conditions a priori are 
 implied in what we take to be universal and necessary 
 knowledge, it must be abandoned by any one who accepts (as 
 I do) the biological theory of the growth of the mind : and 
 the attempt to save it by limiting the conditions of cognition 
 a priori to the activity of the Subject is vain ; seeing that 
 the activity of the conscious organism is, of course, a doctrine 
 of the physiologists. Hence the spiritualistic interest of the 
 apodeictic character of knowledge is lost ; the issues involved 
 in it cannot be discussed merely on speculative grounds. 
 
 Should we then expect that the apodeictic and assertory 
 schools of philosophy will coalesce, recognising that all truth 
 is necessary, but that whether any general proposition is true, 
 depends upon whether human experience comprises a fair 
 sample of the Universe ; or is it more likely that many minds, 
 that in former times would have embraced the apodeictic view 
 of truth, will henceforth incline, at least in physical specula- 
 tions, to the problematic, and enforce the doctrine and discipline 
 of Scepticism ? As to this, one cannot read anything more 
 instructive than the candid chapter that brings to a close 
 Jevons's work on the Principles of Science. 
 
 It is remarkable that in spite of the conflict of dogmas in 
 Greece, Scepticism was, until the end of the fourth century, 
 only sporadic there. Speculative contradiction alone was not 
 enough to give it continuous vitality : it was social and 
 political decay, the loss of the City's sovranty and the citizen's 
 dignity, responsibility and incentive, that infected Philosophy 
 with the taint of vanity and failure, and gave occasion to the 
 parasitic sect that fed upon the corruption of systems. 
 
 Sceptics, however, may be divided into two groups: (1) 
 the Academics, who, like Carneades and Hume, admit that we 
 have at least probable knowledge, and for whom therefore 
 
 6 
 
82 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 the modality of truth is problematic ; and (2) the Pyrrhonists, 
 who dispute the possibility of any knowledge whatever, — 
 intellectual Nihilists, undertaking to show that any proposition 
 and its contradictory may be supported by evidence equally 
 strong, that is to say, equally weak ; for whom, therefore, 
 truth is not so much problematic as antilogistic. 
 
 To begin chronologically with the latter doctrine : the ten 
 Pyrrhonic tropes (supposed to have been listed by ^nesidemus) 
 are given in every history of Philosophy. On reviewing them, 
 it is easily seen that they are all reducible to two heads, the 
 relativity of perception and the inconsistency of opinions. 
 The doctrine of Eelativity, as affecting the modality of 
 knowledge, I purpose to examine in the next chapter. As to 
 the inconsistency of opinions, to make that the test of untruth 
 implies the admission that a test of truth is consistency, or 
 the systematic harmony of knowledge, if it be attainable. 
 The refutation of this sceptical animadversion, therefore, must 
 be left to posterity ; let them construct, if they can, the 
 Positive Philosophy. 
 
 I do not bring against the Sceptics the stale objection, 
 that the denial of all certainty involves the denial of their 
 own position, that if they cannot be sure of anything 
 they cannot be sure even of that ; for these men, being not 
 altogether dull, at least no duller than their critics, seem to 
 have anticipated this tolerably obvious reflection, and to 
 have explained that they only balanced one argument against 
 another, so that judgment remained in suspense between 
 them ; that they employed even the forms of deductive 
 reasoning as a concession to opponents who would argue in 
 that way ; in short, that they threw upon the rest of the 
 world the onus of proving something. 
 
 Much less do I regard the Sceptics as legitimate objects 
 of moral reprobation. Their characters range through all 
 gradations of frivolity and earnestness. A man may hold that 
 to believe anything is in bad taste, at least, for a cultivated 
 mind ; or that if anything can be proved, very inconvenient 
 tenets may get a foothold ; or that if nothing can be proved, 
 belief becomes a matter of choice, and then one's own 
 
SCEPTICISM 83 
 
 prejudices may get the most votes ; or that by recognising 
 any success in tlie attainment of truth, we limit the field 
 of research. In fact, Scepticism seems to be a necessary 
 apparition whenever, in the movement of social life, tradi- 
 tionary formulai become obsolescent, whilst the new-fangled 
 are still inadequate. If such be the actual state of affairs, 
 to comprehend and illustrate it, to express what many feel, to 
 define what many surmise, may be a useful social function ; 
 and the man who discharges that function effectually is, for 
 the most part, such a Euphues that to live the ordinary life 
 of honour and integrity comes easy to him without the sup- 
 port of priest or scholarch. Moreover, the sceptical and the 
 mystical evaluations of this world's good and evil lead to 
 much the same result ; so that the Ilissus may flow into the 
 Ganges. 
 
 It seems to be agreed that in the present age of the 
 world. Scepticism of some sort is a good thing ; that it is 
 a necessary condition of all prudent investigation ; that our 
 opponents have much too little of it in regard to their own 
 demonstrations ; that generally (as Mill urges) Truth lives 
 only whilst she is militant, so that even our own doctrines may 
 be the better for candid strictures. In the fulness of time it 
 may be possible to hold beliefs with intelligence as well as 
 conviction, though never called upon to defend them ; that is 
 to say, when man shall be a rational animal. That time is 
 not yet ; and meanwhile the reproach of ' scepticism ' is an 
 appeal to lewd fellows of tlie baser sort — 
 
 Almighty crowd ! thou pettiest all dispute ; 
 Power is thy eseence, wit thy attribute. 
 
 Hitherto, the crowd having been on the side of tradition, 
 scepticism has been a reproach to those who doubted of 
 tradition : ere long it may with equal vulgarity be cast at 
 those who doubt of science. 
 
 § 2. The scepticism of Carneades seems to have turned at 
 tirst upon his theory of knowledge : distinguishing between 
 the Subject of cognition, its representation of the object, and 
 the object itself, he argued that, granting the confidence of 
 
84 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 the Subject in its representation, it yet can know nothing of 
 the correspondence of that representation with the object, and 
 therefore can have no knowledge of the truth. It was very 
 natural for this difficulty to arise among the successors of 
 Plato. If dialectic failed to discover the Ideas, supposed to be 
 the only real objects of knowledge, mankind were imprisoned 
 in the region of the senses and therefore of mere opinion : the 
 senses were discredited by hypothesis, and Reason by defeat. 
 Ever since that time, upon this or on closely related grounds, 
 — in connection, that is, with the notion of Substance or of 
 the Thing -by -itself, — the same difficulty has embarrassed 
 Philosophy ; and hereafter we shall have to consider whether, 
 or under what conditions, it is insuperable. Meanwhile we 
 may note that, according to Carneades, the Subject may 
 entertain belief in its own representations, that is, in the 
 world of perception, or Empirical Eeality. 
 
 Another ground of his scepticism was, that no test of 
 truth can be satisfactory, because we may always ask why it 
 should be trusted. This is the alleged regressus ad infinitum 
 of all proofs, which is inevitably suggested by the syllogistic 
 method : granting that the premises prove the conclusion, 
 how are the premises proved ? Aristotle had foreseen this 
 question, and required that, for necessary reasoning, the middle 
 term should express the cause of the major. But his theory 
 of causes was one of the weakest points of his system ; and he 
 appears to have wavered as to the best way of determining 
 the cause, sometimes appealing to Induction, sometimes to a 
 faculty of Reason. The latter device was ill calculated to 
 check a determined Sceptic ; the arbitrariness of all prin- 
 ciples assumed upon that ground being urged again and again. 
 The former device was unsatisfactory because of Aristotle's 
 imperfect apprehension of what induction requires. Whatever 
 Carneades may have had to say upon induction, the objection 
 is attributed to Agrippa (a much later sceptic) that the major 
 premise of tlie syllogism must at last be proved by a complete 
 collection of all the instances, and that this must include 
 those which form the subject of the conclusion ; so that a 
 circulus in demonstrando inevitably results from the attempt 
 
SCEPTICISM 85 
 
 to base syllogism on induction. Mill's reply to this argument 
 has been given in Chapter III. § 7: belated nearly 2000 years. 
 
 Carneades' criticism, then, of any possible test of truth, 
 such as that of the Stoics or Epicureans, that seeks to set up 
 one principle as a test of all otliers, was at least very plausible. 
 Accordingly, in discussing the criterion in the last chapter, 
 I avoided the dogmatic position of resting upon one only 
 principle, and sought to combine the view of common sense, 
 the general agreement of philosophers and the method and 
 aim of the exact and progressive sciences ; and to this doctrine 
 I must claim the assent of Carneades himself, upon the strength 
 of his theory of Probability. 
 
 For we have seen that, whilst holding a knowledge of 
 objects to be impossible, he recognised that our representations 
 of them excite belief ; they may have verisimilitude, and such 
 cognition may be called probable. Of probability he distin- 
 guished three stages: (1) the lowest degree belongs to a 
 single, emphatic, persuasive cognition ; (2) our confidence 
 increases when, on comparing a probable cognition with others 
 that are concatenated with it, it remains undetachable or 
 uncontradicted; and (3) the highest degree of probability is 
 attained when all these cognitions are emphatic, consistent, 
 and methodically confirmed (Sextus Empiricus, Adv. Math. 
 vii. 166: quoted by Kitter and Preller). Plainly, €fi(f>a<rt<; 
 is the sceptical equivalent of KaTdXrjylrtq ; and the meaning 
 of concatenation and of methodical confirmation will vary with 
 the development of scientific culture. 
 
 Now to call such knowledge only probable implies that 
 some other knowledge of greater certainty is possible or con- 
 ceivable. If so, will not some one say what it is ? It is not 
 enough to offer a negative concept of some knowledge, defined 
 merely as without the imperfections of our own. One may 
 suppose a vision of all things at a glance, as I see the land- 
 scape yonder ; but this acknowledges that I do see the land- 
 scape : or a knowledge of all things such as we have of the 
 axiom of mediate equality ; but this grants the truth of the 
 axiom. If a knowledge be demanded that shall never be 
 liable to sucli change and supersession as have overtaken so 
 
86 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 many supposed sciences ; I say that Empirical Reality has 
 never been discredited, nor have the axioms, nor yet the 
 method of intuitive and harmonious construction and verifica- 
 tion. In short, our standard of certainty must lie within om* 
 knowledge ; and, therefore, there is nothing outside of our 
 knowledge wherewith to disparage the whole of it under the 
 name of probability. We have in the Platonism from which 
 Carneades glissaded one of the impossible ideals that have 
 done so much now to elevate and now to vex mankind. 
 
 Apparently the scepticism of the New Academy was 
 academic in the modern sense of the word, a refined amuse- 
 ment, which bore about the same relation to Philosophy as 
 Italian fencing does to the art of war. Still, in its own day, 
 it seems to me to have been superior, even as Philosophy, both 
 to the fanatical dogmatism of the Stoics and to the gaseous 
 hypotheses of the Epicureans ; and the accomplished and adroit 
 figure of Carneades warns one of the vanity of hoping to pose 
 and dumbfound him. I hear him say : ' Ich bin mir selbst auch 
 in der Holle noch gleich.' But, alas ! poor ghost, so may 
 many another say who yet is every day triumphantly refuted. 
 Striking tableaux in the underworld, when from time to time 
 a new colonist arrives, have been imagined. Let us figure to 
 ourselves Green descending (against his proper motion) with 
 the edition of Hume under his arm, and envisaging the author : 
 whom now I see approaching ; for his turn has come. 
 
 § 3. Yet, in fact, Hume's liability to be classed amongst 
 Sceptics is not so clear as common repute would lead us to 
 suppose. For, in the first place, he is in many directions 
 a constructive thinker. To Psychology, Ethics, Esthetics, 
 Inductive Logic, Economics, Politics, Philosophy of History 
 and Eeligion, his contributions are numerous and important. 
 It would be a useful and edifying task to collect and display 
 them, and thereby correct the injustice of histories of 
 Philosophy, which exhibit under his name nothing but bare 
 bones of the criticism of Cause and Substance. Few philo- 
 sophers, if any, have done more for the positive instruction, 
 as well as for the enlightenment, of the human mind. 
 
 Secondly, if we take the most deliberate statements of his 
 
SCEPTICISM 87 
 
 opinions, it will appear that as to the Natural Sciences he was 
 not sceptical at all. Thus in the Treatise (111. § 11) he 
 writes : " Those philosophers who have divided human reason 
 into Knowledge and ProhaUlity, and have defined the first to 
 be that evidence which arises from the com2mrison of ideas, 
 are obliged to comprehend all our arguments from causes or 
 effects under the general term of probability. But though 
 every one be free to use his terms in what sense lie pleases ; 
 and accordingly in the precedent part of this discourse, I have 
 followed this method of expression ; 'tis however certain that 
 in common discourse we readily affirm, that many arguments 
 from causation exceed probability, and may be received as a 
 superior kind of evidence . . . 'twould be more convenient 
 in order at once to preserve the common signification of words, 
 and mark the several degrees of evidence, to distinguish human 
 reason into three kinds, viz. : that from knoivledge, from proofs, 
 and from j^robabilities. By knowledge, I mean the assurance 
 arising from the comparison of ideas. By proofs, those argu- 
 ments which are derived from the relation of cause and effect, 
 and which are entirely free from doubt and uncertainty. By 
 probability, that evidence which is still attended with uncer- 
 tainty." According to this passage, then, laws of causation 
 are assertory ; and the same view is required by his doctrine 
 of Chance : " Though there be no such thing as chance in 
 the world ; our ignorance of the real cause of any event has 
 the same influence on the understanding etc." (Inquiry, § 6) ; 
 and by his notorious criticism of miracles in the Inquiry 
 (§ 10) : "A miracle is a violation of the laws of nature ; and 
 as a firm and unalterable experience has established these laws, 
 the proof against a miracle, from the very nature of the fact, 
 is as entire as any argument from experience can possibly be 
 imagined." As to knowledge " from the comparison of ideas," 
 it includes " Geometry, Algebra, and Arithmetic ; and in short 
 every affirmation which is either intuitively or demonstratively 
 certain " (Inquiry, § 4). Though, I believe, he nowhere says 
 it in so many words, his statements imply that he regarded 
 pure Mathematics as consisting of analytic propositions, and 
 necessarily true because capable of being tested by the 
 
88 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 principle of Contradiction. For thus he contrasts such know- 
 ledge with matter of fact, the contrary of which can never 
 imply a contradiction : " That the sun will not rise to-morrow 
 is no less intelligible a proposition, and implies no more con- 
 tradiction, than the afl&rmation that it will rise. We 
 should in vain, therefore, attempt to demonstrate its false- 
 hood. Were it demonstratively false, it would imply a con- 
 tradiction, and could never be distinctly conceived by the 
 mind." Hume's view of Mathematics is, of course, inad- 
 equate : but we are now only concerned to observe that, 
 although he treats the application of Geometry to matter of 
 fact as hampered by the impossibility of exact measurements, 
 yet he regards Pure Mathematics as necessary, laws of 
 Causation as assertory, and propositions of less certainty as 
 problematic. In what, then, does Hume's Scepticism consist ? 
 § 4. In the first place, Hume doubts, or rather denies, the 
 supremacy of Eeason: for (1) our reasonings are not based 
 upon Reason but upon Custom and sentiment and imagination. 
 Now it was recognised by Aristotle that reasonings cannot 
 always be derived from antecedent reasonings, but must have 
 their beginnings in something else. But since it seems de- 
 rogatory to Eeason that it should begin from anything called 
 by another name and, therefore, supposed to be of lower rank ; 
 philosophers distinguish between Intuitive Eeason that gives 
 principles, and Discursive Eeason that draws conclusions. Well, 
 in his theory of Causation, Hume for ' Intuitive Eeason ' sub- 
 stitutes ' Custom ' ; and this is the chief incitement to call 
 him a Sceptic. But (2) he tries to show (and with no little 
 glee) that reasoning everywhere needs the guidance of custom, 
 on peril of ranging through useless subtleties to fantastic and 
 incredible results. Such he thinks is the fate of the mathe- 
 matician, speculating about infinitesimals ; and of the meta- 
 physician, attributing reality to a world other than that world 
 of sense-perception which the ordinary man takes to be real. 
 (3) Every decision concerning the validity of reasoning rests 
 with sentiment. " All probably reasoning [which here includes 
 causation] is nothing but a species of sensation. 'Tis not 
 solely in poetry and music, we must follow our taste and 
 
SCEPTICISM 89 
 
 sentiment, but likewise in philosophy. When I am convinced 
 of any principle, 'tis only an idea which strikes more strongly 
 upon me. When I give the preference to one set of arguments 
 above another, I do nothing but decide from my feeling con- 
 cerning the superiority of their influence" {Treatise, III. § 8). 
 Must not this have been painful reading to any Clerk — 
 
 That unto logik hadde long i-go ? 
 
 Can we wonder if he clung to j/oO? and ima-Ttj/xT} as better 
 words than ' custom ' and ' sentiment ' ? 
 
 In the second place, his observation that we never know 
 the soul per se but only its passing thoughts and feelings, 
 must seem sceptical to those who rely upon such dogmatism 
 as Berkeley's in proof of Spiritualism. It is, however, on the 
 contrary, one of Hume's positive results, and is now on all 
 hands accepted. 
 
 In the third place, of course, his attitude toward tradition 
 is really sceptical : various points of Theology are the subject 
 of frequent innuendo, and miracles and prophecy of direct 
 attack. He might have urged, however, that it is questionable 
 whether the term ' sceptic ' is more properly applicable to one 
 who believes in miracles and doubts of natural law, or to one 
 who believes in natural law and doubts of miracles. The really 
 clever thing is to believe both. 
 
 In the fourth place, a very easy - going and sceptical 
 temperament is suggested by his style ; which often leaves us 
 in doubt whether its failings are due to carelessness or design. 
 For instance, he says that " the ideas of the memory are much 
 more lively and strong that those of the imagination," and are 
 tied down to the order and form of the original impressions 
 (Treatise, 1. § 3). But this does not prevent him from say- 
 ing that " the memory, senses, and understanding are all of 
 them founded on imagination, or the vivacity of our ideas " 
 {Treatise, IV. § 7) ; or from attributing to the influence of 
 imagination that identity which the vulgar ascribe to objects 
 during the intervals of perception (IV. § 2). Such passages 
 illustrate the strain of meiosis, amounting to impropriety, that 
 runs through nearly all his phraseology in describing the 
 
90 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 operations of the understanding, and tends to sap our confi- 
 dence in them. Take another instance of this : his account of 
 the work of imagination as " a propension to unite these 
 broken appearances (perceptions) by the fiction of a continued 
 existence " (IV. § 2) ;^ and again, " the identity which we 
 ascribe to the mind of man is only a fictitious one and of a 
 like kind to that which we ascribe to vegetables and animal 
 bodies " (IV. § 6) : where by ' fiction ' and ' fictitious ' he 
 means constmcction and constructive. But whilst it is true that 
 every fiction is a construction, yet we do not call it a fiction 
 unless we also regard it as false ; and in neither case did Hume 
 so regard it ; so that his language is capricious and perverse. 
 But the worst case of all, because it affects the foundations of 
 his system, is the use of the term ' custom ' in order to explain 
 our belief in causation. For custom, in the usual sense, is 
 itself a result of causation, a highly complex result depending 
 on many causes, and therefore variable ; and yet he makes it, 
 by a violent extension of meaning, the ground of our belief in 
 causation, though he certainly regarded causation as invariable 
 and the basis of all synthetic reasoning. It is true that to 
 find a just word for what he had to express is difficult : 
 " association," " integration," " routine of experience," etc., are 
 each and all open to exception ; but surely Hume's ingenuity 
 and power of language might have led him to something better 
 than ' custom ' had he strongly desired it : ' organic growth,' 
 for example, would have agreed well with his comparison of 
 the mind's identity to that of an animal body. But literary 
 weakness, the love of effect, has been not unfairly attributed to 
 Hume. He was an artist, and wrote as much for the joy of 
 it as to convince his readers. To give a quasi-literary air to 
 a scientific treatise, and for the sake of an impracticable 
 purism, he risks obscurity rather than enlarge the philosophical 
 vocabulary, and in avoiding neology falls into solecism. 
 
 In the fifth place, and as another instance of his love of 
 effect, what he grants to natural belief he often takes away 
 again on second thoughts, and leaves it doubtful whether he 
 regards the first or second thoughts as the more, or the less, valid. 
 In the Treatise (IV. ^4:, Of the Modern Philosophy) he says that 
 
SCEPTICISM 91 
 
 " the fundamental principle of that philosophy is the opinion 
 concerning colours, sounds, tastes, smells, heat, and cold ; which 
 it asserts to be nothing but impressions in the mind derived 
 from impressions of external objects, and without any resem- 
 blance to the qualities of the objects. On examination I find 
 only one of the reasons commonly produced for this opinion 
 to be satisfactory, viz., that derived from the variations of these 
 impressions, even while the external object, to all appearance 
 {sic), continues the same." He then recites most of the ten 
 sceptical tropes mentioned above, and says that " the conclu- 
 sion drawn from them is as satisfactory as can possibly be 
 imagined," namely, that primary qualities, " extension and 
 solidity with their different mixtures and modifications, figure, 
 motion, gravity, and cohesion," are " the only real ones of 
 which we have any adequate notion." But presently he goes 
 on : "I believe many objections might be made to this system : 
 but at present I shall confine myself to one, which is in my 
 opinion very decisive. I assert that instead of explaining the 
 operations of external objects by its means, we vitterly annihilate 
 all those objects, and reduce ourselves to the opinions of the 
 most extravagant scepticism concerning them." On examining 
 motion, extension, and solidity, the only qualities left to the 
 world by the modern philosophy, he finds that they all depend 
 upon solidity which can only be known by " feeling " [touch] ; 
 but this does not resemble solidity ; nor can it, because it is a 
 simple impression, and solidity supposes the pressure of two 
 bodies. " Thus there is a direct and total opposition between 
 our reason and our senses ; or, more properly speaking, betwixt 
 those conclusions we form from cause and effect, and those 
 that persuade us of the continued and independent existence 
 of body." So, whilst pretending to repudiate scepticism, and 
 leading the reader to expect a refutation of it, he concludes 
 with an antilogy which is the essence of scepticism. Yet 
 plainly in this jeu d'espjit he has a serious purpose : to 
 illustrate the processes of the understanding, and to show that 
 the dogmatic Philosophy, fairly worked out, ended in scepticism 
 as " hideous " as his own. 
 
 § 5. What then is really Hume's position with regard to 
 
92 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 the modality of knowledge ? It seems to me to lie somewhere 
 between the problematic scepticism of Carneades and the 
 assertory empiricism of Mill, but decidedly nearer to Mill. 
 Scepticism was to some extent a disguise with Hume : in his 
 ethical speculations there is very little of it. In Metaphysics 
 he professes, or strongly suggests, adherence to the Academic 
 Philosophy; but his reasons for this seem to have been as 
 follows: (1) To indulge his literary humour. (2) To gratify 
 a genuine impartiality of mind. He saw real difficulties in 
 every theory of knowledge, and found suspense of judgment 
 not disagreeable : a state of mind how superior to the eager, 
 anxious bigotry of your forensic philosophaster. (3) He exposed 
 the conflicting results of ratiocination in order to prove his 
 main point, that the basis of knowledge is sensitive not cogni- 
 tive. " My reasons then for displaying so carefully the argu- 
 ments of that fantastic sect [the Pyrrhonists] is only to make 
 the reader sensible of the truth of my hypothesis, that all our 
 reasonings concerning causes and effects are derived from nothing 
 ha custom; and that belief is more properly an act of the 
 sensitive than of the cogitative part of our natures" (Treatise, 
 IV. § 1). (4) He desired to limit the field of human inquiry 
 " to such subjects as are best adapted to the narrow capacity 
 of human understanding" {Inquiry, § 1 2, Part III.) ; had in fact 
 the same object as Locke and Kant. With what mixed feelings 
 of glee and contempt does he now, among the shades, watch 
 the changing fortunes of his scepticism in recent literatui-e ; 
 whilst he glances over the books (if any have life enough to 
 double themselves in Hades !) of those who enjoy the twofold 
 pleasm-e of rating him as a sceptic and of using his arguments 
 to excuse their own credulity. 
 
 It is easy to show that Hume recognises the main outlines 
 of the criterion of truth set forth in our last chapter. (1) 
 Empirical Pieality is everywhere recognised by him as the 
 starting-point, and as the constant guide of all effective think- 
 ing ; it is the ground of that 'custom' of experience that 
 generates the causal judgment. (2) The principle of Contra- 
 diction is recognised in his theory of Mathematics. (3) The 
 method of discovery is to pass from " impressions " (elements of 
 
SCEPTICISM 93 
 
 Empirical Eeality) by " natural relations " to conclusions, under 
 the control of the canons of Induction given in the Treatise 
 (III. § 15). But I do not tind that he anywhere distinctly 
 signalises the method of hypothesis and veriiication, thougli 
 often employing it. (4) The verification implied in systematic 
 agreement is appealed to ; first, negatively, in the sceptical 
 procedure of opposing sense to reason, or one philosophy to 
 another, as a test of untruth ; and, secondly, by positively 
 claiming it as evidence on his own behalf : " "What principally 
 gives authority to this system is, beside the undoubted argu- 
 ments upon which each part is founded, the agreement of these 
 parts, and the necessity of one to explain another" {Treatise, 
 III. § 13). 
 
 As for the Pyrrhonists, Hume often repudiates their 
 doctrine upon characteristic grounds. Such people in fact 
 never existed : " whoever has taken the pains to refute the 
 cavils of this total scepticism has really disputed without an 
 antagonist" {Treatise, IV. § 1); "the great subverter of 
 Pyrrhonism, or the excessive principles of scepticism, is action, 
 and employment, and the occupations of common life " ; though 
 " it may flourish and triumph in the schools " {Inquiry, 
 §§ 12-13). 
 
 § 6. Thus Hume puts forward Pragmatism as the natural 
 remedy for Scepticism, and the opposition between the two is 
 usually regarded as thorough-going ; and such probably is the 
 view of William James {Psych, c. 28) and of F. C. S. Schiller 
 ("Axioms as Postulates," in Personal Idealism, ed, H. Sturt). 
 Yet, in a sense. Pragmatism is a kind of Scepticism, as any 
 doctrine must be that puts the conviction of Keason solely 
 upon any ground other than cognition, whether it be action 
 or feeling. But neither course involves Scepticism, unless 
 action or feeling be made the test of truth to the exclusion of 
 cognition : Hume, as we have seen, says that the preference of 
 one set of arguments over another is a matter of feeling ; but 
 he does not say that this feeling of preference is not determined 
 by the character of the arguments. 
 
 Psychologists have shown that every mental process 
 involves cognition, feeling, conation ; it may, therefore, be 
 
94 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 viewed in any of these ways. A theorem of Euclid, a game 
 of cricket, or a Turkish bath, is a complex of feeling, or cona- 
 tion, or cognition, as you may choose to consider it ; but, when 
 speaking generally (if we wish to avoid confusion), we must 
 treat the first as cognition, the second as conation, and the 
 third as feeling, according to the predominant interests of those 
 experiences ; or, when speaking precisely, we must show how 
 every strand of the triple process is present in varying degrees 
 in them all. Now, how is this applicable to the consciousness 
 of truth in general ? 
 
 Plainly, the consciousness of truth is primarily a matter of 
 cognition, intuition, or synthetic attention. But this is a kind 
 of conation ; and its success or failure is attended by feelings 
 of belief, hesitation, perplexity, disbelief. Still, the conation 
 is to know, and its success or failure is a knowing or not 
 knowing. Truth, therefore, is essentially cognitive; and its 
 primary tests are cognitive, namely, clearness and agreement ; 
 which, in fact, are nothing else than successful knowing. 
 
 Since all experience involves action and reaction, it is 
 possible to use ' activity ' as equivalent to experience ; but such 
 exclusive emphasis creates a misleading abstraction. How im- 
 portant action is in connection with truth may be seen in this 
 — that Empirical Keality is brought home to us in action, and 
 that (biologically considered) only workable beliefs can survive. 
 Such is Spencer's doctrine. But let us avoid expressions that 
 may seem to imply that the survival of a belief merely con- 
 nected with successful action, without clear and coherent cog- 
 nitions concerning it, is a guarantee of its truth ; for as a true 
 conclusion may be drawn from false premises, so the same act 
 (Trpay/jLo) may be done under very different and conflicting 
 beliefs. If action is to verify belief otherwise than in universal 
 experience, it cannot be by 2^ost hoc, propter hoc, but must be 
 subject to the same conditions as other experimental proofs : 
 we must show (1) that the action is reaUy due to the belief it 
 is alleged to prove, and not merely accompanied by it ; (2) 
 that no other belief coald have had equally successful results; 
 (3) that the belief agrees with all others that are held to be 
 true. All this involves comparison, perhaps much subtle in- 
 
SCEPTICISM 95 
 
 terpretation, processes of understanding : in short, we must be 
 enabled to see the connection. It cannot be right to adopt a 
 belief merely on the ground of its apparent success, without 
 taking any methodological precautions, and to urge it upon 
 others — that good may come of it. 
 
 It is also necessary to inquire what is meant by successful 
 action. How long a course of action is enough to establish 
 its success ? Witliin what limits are the consequences to be 
 considered ? To whom ? These questions are serious, and 
 difficult to answer. 
 
 Teleologiciilly, Pragmatism seems to imply the entire 
 relativity of knowledge to action ; that action is the end, 
 whilst intelligence exists merely for the sake of it, and has no 
 rights of its own in the world. But it is not plain that 
 organic activities, as such, are of any more worth than chemical 
 activities, or that the Universe might not have been content 
 to culminate in compounds with good long formulae, without 
 going on to develop highly conscious beings at such cost of 
 pain and havoc. Schopenhauer thought that consciousness 
 exists for the sake of organic life, but that this is part of the 
 blunder of things ; and that, accordingly, consciousness labours 
 in error and illusion, until that consummation of knowledge 
 which is the annihilation of Nature. But certainly much 
 knowledge has been attained for which we have no use present 
 or prospective, except the gratification of disinterested curiosity. 
 And why may not disinterested curiosity be the noblest of 
 desires, and the attainment of knowledge the only true success, 
 the self- consciousness of the World: and therefore, to its 
 humble organs the purest, the most enduring, the divinest 
 satisfaction, and the only one that is never poisoned by regret ? 
 
 As for the PyiThonists, they would never have submitted 
 to a pragmatic refutation. Hume has slipped : they did not 
 deny that the world is a practicable phenomenon, that the 
 street seems to be a place to walk in, and that bread seems to 
 appease hunger. The sect, however, has not revived in modern 
 times, and may require special circumstances in the state of 
 learning or of society to nourish its vitality. It is not that 
 its criticism of prevailing tenets was, as Hegel says, more 
 
96 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 profound or more thorough than modern scepticism: for all 
 its positions have been (as we shall see) reinforced by recent 
 reflection ; but it was eminently Greek. Two generations 
 earlier than Pyrrho, the Cynics and Cyrenaics had displayed 
 with like extravagance a practical scepticism, rejecting all pre- 
 cepts and institutions as he did all opinions. These schisms 
 sprang from the independence and self-sufficiency of the Greek 
 intellect; for which even the innumerable ties of City -life 
 were an inadequate restraint. They did not, indeed, illustrate 
 the boasted principle of Measure : but was the general praise 
 of that principle, affectionate or precautionary ? No matter. 
 If the men are extinct, their arguments survive them, and the 
 chief of their arguments were derived from the Relativity of 
 Knowledge. 
 
CHAPTER VI 
 
 THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 
 
 ^ 1. The phrase " relativity of Knowledge " is used to express 
 the central idea of a number of doctrines to the efifect that 
 oiu' cognition of objects is not direct, immediate, adequate, 
 intimate, like the consciousness we have of our present thoughts 
 and sensations, but is conditional (1) upon our place in the 
 Universe; or (2) upon the media that intervene (like air or 
 ether) between objects and our organs of sensation ; or (3) 
 upon the structure of our own bodies ; or even upon the struc- 
 ture of our own minds : as having either (4) an elaborate 
 formal apparatus a priori, such as Kant determined; or (5) 
 some ultimate character, however simple, and a natural history 
 — in both cases making it impossible that our perception or 
 representation of the world can be direct or unconditional. 
 A lover of technical terms might hereupon distinguish Cos- 
 mological. Physical, Biological, Metaphysical, and Psychological 
 Eelativity ; but for me it is enough if the reader sees what I 
 mean. Eelativity in any of these ways being admitted, it is 
 argued that there can be no knowledge worth the name, or that 
 at least our knowledge must be liable to great and numerous 
 errors and limitations. 
 
 Now there are here two positions: (1) that all cognition 
 is relative or conditional, and this is a proposition in Psycho- 
 logy supported by other natural sciences ; (2) that knowledge 
 is therefore partial or invalid, and this is a metaphysical pro- 
 position. We are directly concerned only with the latter ; but 
 as it may be expedient to indicate plainly the grounds of the 
 difficulty before attempting to overcome it, we shall begin with 
 
 7 
 
98 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 a little fuller, though still brief account of the ways in which 
 knowledge is said to be relative. In doing this nothing would 
 be gained by adhering to the Pyrrhouic tropes ; we shall, 
 therefore, set out more recent considerations that have absorbed 
 and superseded them. 
 
 If we suppose the Keality of Eealities to be a Substance 
 transcending all experience, the physical World of atoms and 
 ether in space may be regarded as the first stage of its pheno- 
 menality, having only the qualities of resistance and extension, 
 which are made known to a living organism by direct mechanical 
 pressure and by muscular reaction and movement. Empirical 
 Keality includes a secondary manifestation, in such qualities 
 as sound and light, depending upon the intervention, between 
 external things and the organism, of air and ether, the former 
 producing mechanical, the latter chemical effects upon the 
 corresponding sense-organs. Impressions of all kinds upon 
 the organs of sense require a nervous system in which fibres 
 conduct currents to certain central tracts (in the cortex), 
 where alone consciousness is believed to arise. Consciousness, 
 then, of what ? Of change in the brain, or sense-organ, or 
 physical World ? What possibility that it should resemble 
 transcendent Eeality ? It is entirely relative to physical and 
 psychophysical conditions. 
 
 It is also relative to merely psychical conditions, the first 
 of which, for all organic consciousness, is change. Any state of 
 consciousness which we know as B could never have been known 
 by itself, there must be a transition from A to B in order that 
 we may be aware of anything. It follows that a first state of 
 consciousness is inconceivable ; but allowing for the lapse of 
 inscrutable ages of growth, and assuming any starting-point, the 
 next state is known in relation to it. B, therefore, is known in 
 relation to A, and must be modified by this relation ; similarly 
 C in relation to B, or rather to B as modified by A. The series, 
 therefore, is A, B^, C^a, Dcba* ''^^^ ^o on to Z, that is to say, 
 to the present moment. Present consciousness is determined 
 by the history of consciousness ; and each individual, having 
 had a different personal history, must have a characteristic mode 
 of cognition, a ' personal equation,' in all his thinking and 
 
THE KELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 99 
 
 feeling. But the personal history of an individual is the least 
 important part of his liistory : he is a mode of his species, the 
 history of whose consciousness has again determined its forms : 
 and the species is a mode of animal life ; so that our present 
 cognitions are determined by the history of consciousness, 
 stretching back at least to the earliest organic beings. 
 
 This history of consciousness is another name for universal 
 experience, or intercourse witli Nature ; which is also the con- 
 dition of the development of organised bodies and of nervous 
 systems. As consciousness grows and develops there also 
 develop sense-organs, nervous connections, ganglionic centres, 
 and specialised tracts of the cortex which are the organs of 
 specific consciousness. The sense-organs are visible signs of 
 the limitations of knowledge : if in any species (or individual) 
 certain organs are wanting or feeble, wanting or feeble must be 
 the corresponding cognitions. 
 
 The history of the sense-organs confirms the dependence 
 of present cognition upon past experience. All sense-organs 
 appear to be modifications of the skin. Assuming a primitive 
 irritability of the skin with corresponding unspecialised sensa- 
 tion (unlike any sensation now recognisable, perhaps as much 
 like Taste as Touch) ; that it was stimulated by pressure and 
 by chemical disturbance, and that lines of transmission of these 
 influences severally to central cells, and of consequent reaction 
 and movements, were gradually established ; that the epiperi- 
 pheral pressure-nerves were again differentiated, in response to 
 mass-contact and air-waves, into those of Touch and Hearing ; 
 whilst other pressure nerves, having become entoperipheral, 
 began to serve as the organs of kinesthetic and visceral Sensa- 
 tions (though the latter, or some of them, may be chemically 
 stimulated) ; that the chemically excited nerves were differen- 
 tiated into those that are influenced by material particles or 
 effluvia in solution, giving rise to Taste and Smell, — and those 
 that are influenced by ethereal and molecular vibrations, giving 
 rise to sensations of Light and Heat ; and that many of these 
 underwent further and more refined specialisation : we have 
 here a process similar to the differentiation of species of 
 animals from a generalised type. Parallel with the differentia- 
 
100 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 tion of sense-organs goes the discrimination of sense-qualities. 
 Historically, then, every mode of sensation is relative to all the 
 others, or may be regarded as existing by contrast with them ; 
 since, tracing the various modes of sensation back to their 
 origin, all their differences merge and disappear in prmiitive 
 unspecialised sensation. 
 
 The assumed unity of the psychological with the biological 
 individual in existence and in development, leads to some 
 obvious reflections. It is held that no animal has faculties 
 incommensurate with its present or recent conditions of life : 
 since such endowments would imply a waste of organisation 
 and energy, which Natural Selection always tends to eliminate. 
 Applying this doctrine to the mental powers, it may appear 
 that cognition is relative to action, arises to enlighten action, 
 exists for its utility, and that there can be no kind of cogni- 
 tion that does not subserve life. I say no kind of cognition, 
 not that every specialisation of cognition, or every addition 
 to knowledge, must be directly ancillary to action ; so that if 
 some branches of Mathematics, or if astral Chemistry, cannot 
 be directly applied to useful purposes, this implies no conflict 
 with the biological law ; for such branches of science do not 
 differ in kind from terrestrial Chemistry and Algebra, which 
 are certainly useful. If, regarding science as existing to 
 realise the World's self-consciousness, we were to suggest that 
 all truths unutilisable by man subserve that purpose, it might 
 be retorted that we do not know what is useful to man ; 
 that the movement of civilisation makes ever increasing 
 demands upon the utmost refinements of speculation, and that 
 an extensive store of potential or unorganised cortex, upon 
 which original speculation depends, is the most general con- 
 dition of adaptabihty and is, therefore, of the utmost utility 
 to the human race or any branch of it. 
 
 Again, if there are in Nature any modes of energy such 
 that the expense of organising a special nervous correspondence 
 with them would not leave a balance of utiHty, so far no such 
 nervous correspondence can have arisen in animal life ; nor 
 if, once organised, it ceased to be economical, could it maintain 
 its activity in any order of animals; and this may explain 
 
THE EELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 101 
 
 why (for example) there is in man no specific electrical sense, 
 nor any sense (other tlian that of heat) correlated with the 
 ether-rays that spread beyond the chromatic series at either 
 end of the spectrum, whether such senses exist in other animals 
 or not. De Morgan humorously supposes it " very likely that 
 the universe may contain a few agencies — say half a million 
 — about which no man knows anything." Besides those 
 agencies which, like electricity, certainly affect the organism, 
 yet have set up no specific correspondence with it, there may 
 be others that for some reason cannot directly communicate 
 with us from matter in mass,' and are also unable to com- 
 municate with us indirectly (like luminous bodies) for want 
 of any appropriate medium of transmission. Modes of energy 
 may exist in Nature which, within the region of our ex- 
 perience, are as rare as certain elements are : with such 
 forces a nervous correspondence could hardly have been worth 
 establishing, and so far our direct experience cannot be a 
 complete sample of the universe. Moreover, the constitution 
 of every sense-organ sets limits to the intensity of the stimuli 
 that can be sensed ; there is a minimum stimulus below which 
 no sensation is excited, and a maximum above which there is 
 no increase of sensation intensity. Ziehen suggests that this 
 is due to Natural Selection ; for an unlimited increase of 
 sensation intensity would be too engrossing, and sensibility to 
 the innumerable minute stimuli always assailing us would be 
 too distracting. For similar reasons many modes of energy 
 may remain entirely unsensed. 
 
 After these far-reaching considerations it seems unim- 
 portant to mention that all sensations vary with the con- 
 stitutional state of the individual in health or disease, in 
 youth or age. See the chapter on The Relativity of Feelings 
 in Spencer's Psychology (Part II. chap. iii.). In the next chapter 
 on The Relativity of Relations, he gives reasons for believing 
 that the perception of space varies in different animals accord- 
 ing as they have, or want, eyes ; or have more or less perfect 
 eyes ; and according to the size of each species of animal and 
 its powers of locomotion ; and even in individuals of the same 
 species according to their size, giants or dwarfs, because stature 
 
102 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 is a standard of comparison. So with time, different species 
 have different standards of comparison, according to the 
 character of the subjective or objective sequences of event 
 that are open to their observation. Alike in time and space, 
 of equal magnitudes the more remote (other things equal) 
 seems the less. Times of monotonous waiting seem long, 
 because attention rests upon the time itself; times of bustle 
 and excitement seem short, because time is neglected in the 
 multiplicity of experience : but in retrospect the bustle seems 
 long, because there is much to remember ; the monotonous 
 waiting, short, because it has left the imagination a blank. 
 But more important than any of these is the simple relation 
 of Difference ; because, according to Spencer, it is from the 
 cancelling and compounding of this that all other relations 
 arise. " The relation of Difference, as present in consciousness, 
 is nothing more than a change in consciousness. How, then, 
 can it resemble, or be in any way akin to, its source beyond 
 consciousness ? Here are two colours which we call unlike. 
 As they exist objectively the two colours are quite independent, 
 there is nothing between them answering to the change that 
 results in us from contemplating first one and then the other. 
 Apart from our consciousness they are not linked as are the 
 two feelings they produce in us. Their relation as we think 
 it, being nothing else than a change of our state, cannot 
 possibly be parallel to anything between them, when they 
 have both remained unchanged" (§ 93). It is one of 
 ^nesidemus's objections to the principle of causation, that it 
 is a relative conception, exists therefore only in the mind, and 
 can have no external existence. In short, not only modes of 
 sensation, but the manner of their occurrence, their order and 
 grouping and the quasi -blank forms or schemata of their 
 occurrence, are determined by our own nature and by disposi- 
 tions inherited from an indefinitely remote ancestry, whereby 
 we conceive of things as like ourselves, not like the World. 
 
 § 2. Since, then, it is generally admitted that Truth is 
 relative in so many ways, both as to its matter and as to 
 its form, to the species, the individual and the present con- 
 ditions of each witness, we cannot wonder if many regard it 
 
THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 103 
 
 as unattainable, on the ground that we can never have any 
 confidence in the correspondence of our judgments with their 
 objects. To deal with this difJiculty is the chief task of 
 constructive Metaphysics ; it will meet us in one shape or 
 another throughout this book, and in the present chapter we 
 can only begin the undertaking. First of all, it is necessaiy 
 to be clear as to what the object is with which our judgment 
 is required to correspond. In the passages of Spencer's 
 Psychology above quoted from, he argues that our sensations 
 are "produced by objective agencies that are unknown and 
 unknowable," and that their relations cannot resemble, or be 
 in any way akin to, their " sources beyond consciousness." 
 And in Part VII. chap. xix. he explains, by his theory of 
 Transfigured Eealism, how a correspondence may be conceived 
 to exist between consciousness and transcendent Eeality, though 
 nothing of the nature of the correspondence or of the Eeality 
 itself can ever be known. 
 
 Now no one can mistake Spencer for a sceptic ; he bears 
 no resemblance to Carneades ; he certainly holds that truth 
 is attainable and partly published : yet the position that 
 human knowledge is at fault, because it does not and cannot 
 comprise the truth of transcendent Reality, is essentially 
 sceptical. The ancient Sceptics granted that we have per- 
 suasions concerning phenomena, probable knowledge ; but 
 taking advantage of the Dogmatist's belief in something 
 more real (to vTroKelfievov of the Stoics, or the imperceptible 
 atoms of the Epicureans), they urged that, except of that 
 Reality, no knowledge can properly be called truth. They 
 needed not to be so inconsistent as to believe in such Reality 
 (and here Spencer differs from them) ; it was enough for 
 their purpose to balance the inconsistent doctrines of their 
 opponents : urging, for example, that the Causation which 
 they recognised could not merely be a principle of phenomena, 
 but if real must be true of Reality, of things imperceptible. 
 That the belief in an unknowable ' substratum ' furnishes a 
 continual excuse for scepticism, is one reason for Berkeley's 
 attack upon the notion of Matter; and for Kant's Dialectic 
 of Pure Reason, which aims at the establishing of Physical 
 
104 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Science by excluding the transcendent Ideas from any consti- 
 tutive part in science or in causation ; and here, again, we 
 may see how little Hume was a Sceptic, inasmuch as he 
 first proved that causation is discoverable in phenomena 
 only. Therefore, Spencer, in spite of his own professions to 
 the contrary, must be understood throughout nearly all his 
 works, not as engaged in interpreting the unknowable by 
 the symbols of its transfiguration, but in endeavouring, more 
 successfully than most inquirers, to complement the inadequacy 
 and fragmentariness of Empirical Keality by constructing the 
 conceptual system of Physical Eeality. In this sense he has 
 discovered enough truths to make the reputation of a dozen 
 other men, truths which are not at all invalidated by most 
 of the tropes of Relativity. These tropes may afford good 
 grounds for disputing the pretensions of some philosophers 
 to a knowledge of transcendent Eeality ; but give little, if 
 any, excuse for denying the possibility of truth as the 
 correspondence of our judgments with the world of possible 
 experience. 
 
 For my own part, I am no enemy of the Ding an sich, 
 nor one to glory in its incognoscibility, and therefore I am 
 not pleased with the argument (noticed above) against the 
 possibility of our knowing anything but phenomena, namely, 
 that, granting the existence of transcendent Eeality, still the 
 indisputable facts of Physical and Biological Eelativity, the 
 interposition of media and nerve-fibres between the supposed 
 Eeality of things and our consciousness, must destroy any 
 possible agreement between the first and last terms of the 
 process. It may be said, for example, that the Eeality 
 represented by a resonant body cannot be like the vibration 
 of that body ; that this is not like the waves of air it sets 
 agoing ; that air-waves are not like a process in the aural 
 nerve ; nor is this like a sensation of sound : how then can 
 such a sensation resemble the Eeality at the other end of 
 this series ? But why not ? If A is unlike B, B unlike C, 
 C unlike D, why may not D be like A ? The conclusion of 
 the above argument may be true, but a worse argument I 
 never met with. It is needless to ask how we know what 
 
THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 105 
 
 an uir-wave or a nerve-current really is like : the genuine 
 ditliculty is that Likeness, a mode of consciousness, cannot be 
 predicated between consciousness and the real World-process, 
 because the World-process is assumed to be unconscious. But 
 what if this is an error, what if the World-process has its 
 own consciousness comparable with ours ? 
 
 § o. However this may be, turning to the relativity of 
 Empirical and I'hysical Truth, we must consider what extent 
 of comprehension and what degree of certitude is reasonably 
 to be expected : bearing in mind that the truth we have 
 here in view is merely the truth for man ; how short a time 
 he has given to methodical investigation ; that no one can 
 suppose a complete system, without error or hiatus, to be near 
 attainment, but that this is a task for the living and posterity, 
 of which posterity must bear the greater burden : so that 
 though many problems may be unsolved, the general method 
 hitherto pursued and the results attained may be justified, if 
 we are able to show that allied problems have been solved 
 and that the kinds of error we are subject to are corrigible. 
 
 Since the question is whether the relativity of knowledge, 
 as found in Empirical Eeality, is an objection to the validity 
 of science and an argument against the possibility of construct- 
 ing the system of experience, let us first recall the account of 
 Empirical Eeality given in Chap. II. § 1 : where we saw 
 that for man it includes a considerable conceptual element, 
 even for unsophisticated man inevitably, since without it the 
 life of an adult is impossible. Now the development of the 
 conceptual element of common experience is the means of 
 correcting errors that are due to relativity, by discovering the 
 cause and law of every error. 
 
 Some of the chief difficulties of Philosophy before the 
 recent growth of Psychology, arose from assuming a separation 
 between sense and understanding, the matter and form of 
 thought. A desire to refine human life has led to errors 
 of logic analogous to asceticism. The pride of reason, as of 
 sanctity, demands something to despise. To this mood it is 
 not repugnant that there should be in sense-experience a 
 remnant of inexplicable chaos ; and the supposed interests 
 
106 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 of supernaturalism fall in with the malice of the sceptic. 
 Availing themselves of the traditionary Animism, men have 
 assumed the separability of body and soul as a " colour " 
 easily acceptable, and have even represented the body as the 
 temporary prison of the soul, restraining its activities and 
 corrupting its powers in damp and darkness : so that to 
 escape from sense-perception is necessary to the native sovranty 
 of thought. But this is abdication, and leaves the senses 
 lawless. According to Plato in llie EepuUic, even the 
 very stars (though in The Timaeus he makes them gods) are 
 too coarse a kind of data to enter into a true Astronomy. 
 There is a vestigial Animism in Aristotle's doctrine of active 
 Eeason : which is no part of the soul as the form of the body, 
 but has a diviner source and destiny. The whole history of 
 innate ideas illustrates the same well meant error ; and so does 
 Kant's difficulty in applying the pure categories of Under- 
 standing to the manifold of sensation : it assumes that sensa- 
 tion itself is not in the realm of law. But the solution of all 
 such puzzles is, that in organised consciousness (which is 
 necessarily our point of view) these elements of experience, 
 sensation and understanding, the matter and form of thought, 
 never exist separately, and are only discriminated by a 
 " distinction of reason " : that is to say, as sensation and 
 understanding occur in very various proportions at different 
 stages of animal and human life, and at different levels of 
 each man's consciousness, they are certainly distinguislmble ; 
 and by carrying out the series of varying proportions symboli- 
 cally, we may suppose ourselves to conceive of " blind 
 sensation " at one end and " pure thought " at the other, 
 especially as we can phrase them. But " blind sensation " on 
 its ovjn level (not merely as subliminal to us) is a contradiction 
 in terms : and the highest thought, if genuine, is the most 
 sense-representative, as well ; as impure by its dependence on 
 some word or sign : which word or sign is both itself sensuous, 
 and derives its value, as representing that thought, from its 
 profound and intricate sensuosity, from roots wide-ramifying 
 in the detail of experience. 
 
 If, then, form or relation is immanent in the life of the 
 
THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 107 
 
 senses, the reality of perception is merely a subject of investiga- 
 tion. In human life the conceptual element even in Empirical 
 Reality is extensive ; the growth of knowledge during savage 
 and barbarous ages continually extends it, and embodies in 
 language the resulting classifications and judgments concerning 
 things and their active properties ; and, finally, in civilised 
 life the methodical pursuit of science gives it still greater 
 refinement and comprehension : and all this is nothing else 
 than the surmounting of those objections to the validity of 
 knowledge, which are drawn from the doctrine of relativity. 
 The relativity of knowledge, as an argument for the invalidity 
 of knowledge, is itself the result of an early stage of scientific 
 culture ; but its weight is diminished by every forward step 
 of scientific discovery ; and it is a reproach to understanding 
 only as long as it is not understood. 
 
 Some old fashioned difficulties are so easily overcome, that 
 it may seem needless to mention them. That a straight stick 
 looks bent when plunged in the water, is explained by the 
 laws of refraction. That the same object seems of different 
 magnitudes according to its distance from the spectator, is 
 explained by the laws of perspective. The error of judging an 
 object warm or cold according to the temperature of our hand 
 in touching it, is corrected by using a thermometer. If the 
 old and the young, the sick and the hale have different 
 sensations of weight in lifting the same mass, they come to 
 agreement by using a pair of scales. Conflicting subjective 
 estimates of time have an arbitrator in the clock and the 
 system of chronology. To suppose that any of these differences 
 of perception are in the nature of logical contradictories is 
 only possible to a man to whom, as to poor Hegel, the 
 principle of Contradiction is the insuperable j^ons assinorum. 
 They are merely incentives to the discovery of laws : which 
 would be impossible if they really were contradictory. 
 
 As to the doctrine that every sensation is so modified by 
 its context (B by A, C by B, etc.) that none can have a 
 character of its own, it has been badly overstated. Such 
 modification is greatest where it is most useful, as in the 
 comparison of temperatures. But with the progress of 
 
108 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 organisation, all the most delicately discriminated and objec- 
 tively significant sensations have attained a quasi-absolute 
 character. Natural Selection must insure this, since nothing 
 else would be compatible with their utility as signs, unless 
 we suppose that there are really no special stimuli. The 
 phenomena of complementary colours are not yet clearly 
 understood, but nobody despairs of them. In these and in all 
 similar cases we try to avoid the misleading influences of 
 relativity by finding objective standards and general laws ; that 
 is to say, by extending the conceptual system that is im- 
 manent in Empirical Reality. 
 
 § 4. The differentiation and fixation of sensations goes 
 along with the development of sense-organs ; and the existence 
 of apparently different sense-organs, or organs of special structure 
 (like insects' eyes), or at different stages of perfection, no doubt 
 implies corresponding differences of experience in zoological 
 species. Of course, if animals that possess the same senses as 
 ourselves, have the eye, the nostril, tactile organs, etc., developed 
 in much greater power and refinement than our own, still, in 
 most cases the use of instruments and apparatus gives to 
 civilised man an immeasurable superiority of apprehension. 
 But some animals are supposed to have organs of sensation 
 correlated with natural forces, with which we have no direct 
 correspondence : a specific electrical sense is conceivable. 
 Evidence has been found that ants and other insects are affected 
 by the ultra-violet rays, and that, therefore, if the sensation of 
 those rays is a colour different from all the others, all complex 
 light effects into which it enters must also be unknown to us. 
 Even if the octave of colour repeats itself, and ultra-violet is a 
 higher value of red, still all its particular and blended effects 
 must be unknown to us. Such reflections indicate the narrow 
 range of sense-perception in any species, but do not invalidate 
 its reports. Each sensation is what it is as sensation ; and 
 its truth as a sign depends not on its quality but on the 
 uniformity of its connections. 
 
 De Morgan's opinion concerning unknown forces, that there 
 may be 500,000 of them, has been quoted; and it is rash for 
 a mere spectator of the physical sciences to surmise that if 
 
I 
 
 THE EELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 109 
 
 there were 500 such forces as electricity, or 50, some evidence 
 of their activity would by this time have been detected. If 
 such forces exist, specific senses dealing with them may have 
 been developed in animals off our line of ancestry ; or even in 
 our own line, though long lost and superseded by others more 
 useful On the hypothesis that every faculty is relative to its 
 utility, it is intelligible that we should want those senses, if our 
 present organs are economically the most efficient for guidance 
 in life such as it has been. It is even possible that other 
 organs would now be more useful, but that organisation long 
 ago advanced too far to leave room for their initiation. 
 
 On the hypothesis that a purpose of Nature, in the develop- 
 ment of animal and rational life, is self-knowledge, this purpose 
 may seem to fail in man so far as he is a ' defective ' in the 
 powers of sense. But such a failure is very natural of Nature, 
 and many things suggest that man may not be amongst her 
 most successful variations. In Mars or some satellite of Sirius 
 all possible organs may exist, the speculations of Micromegas 
 may be far outdone ; and it may be enough if such mere 
 sensation-knowledge be attained somewhere. If animals on 
 this planet really have senses correlated with unknown forces, 
 the study of such species may enable us to learn something of 
 the nature and laws of those forces, and to establish an indirect 
 correspondence with them. Plainly, our knowledge of natural 
 forces does not depend upon a direct sensing of them : the X 
 rays and Electricity were not discovered in that way. What- 
 ever force leaves a trace in our experience, whether directly or 
 indirectly, may be pursued by the Physical Method. And as 
 the classification of chemical elements has indicated the 
 existence, and even some of the qualities, of elements not yet 
 discovered ; so possibly the study of known forces may reveal 
 a scheme within which every possible force must find a place. 
 In fact, the solar spectrum is part of such a scheme : a series, 
 the various sections of which are gradually filled, as phenomena 
 are discovered and interpreted with reference to them. But 
 granting that our ignorance of the extent of Nature's powers 
 may in some respects be incurable, still the question con- 
 cerning the truth of our knowledge bears with far heavier 
 
no THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 stress upon its validity, than upon its adequacy or compre- 
 hensiveness. 
 
 § 5. Many objections, then, to the possibility of science 
 which have been suggested by the character and conditions of 
 the human mind, the progress of science has set aside ; but 
 it has brought forward others more serious. Some of these 
 cling to the very methods of investigation ; which, because of 
 our mental limitations, are necessarily (a) abstract and (&) 
 departmental. The human mind is unequal to the copiousness 
 and complexity, as well as to the subtlety of Nature. Hence, 
 despairing to deal directly with the fulness of Empirical 
 Eeality, it expends its energies chiefly upon quantitative 
 problems ; and finding the total object far exceed the grasp of 
 one inquirer, resorts to the division of labour. 
 
 In pure science of quantity, the difficulties of actuality 
 are avoided by substituting a supposed absolute Space, Time 
 and Motion for the infinite variability of experience, neglect- 
 ing whatever cannot be exactly calculated. But to avoid an 
 enemy (it may be said), though justifiable strategy, is not to 
 defeat him, and this one is entrenched behind the constitution 
 of the World. For it has been discovered that all bodies in 
 the World, masses and molecules alike, are in perpetual 
 gyration and agitation, and in such reciprocal infiuence that 
 the motion of each, as to velocity and direction, is always 
 affected by the approach or recession of every other. It 
 follows that no fixed points are known by relation to which 
 direction in space can be determined; and that there is no 
 uniform motion, and therefore no ultimate measure of time, 
 so that the obtaining of exact quantitative data is even 
 theoretically impossible. See the masterly working out of 
 this subject in James Ward's Naturalism and Agnosticism 
 (Part I.). To me such reflections are not exhilarating. 
 Bain's remark, that " we may not see the world from a 
 commanding point of view," is just but not consolatory. 
 Though I began by declaring that the truth possible to man 
 is all we can hope for, yet when another enforces and illustrates 
 the same doctrine, it hurts : and this reminds me to apply 
 Spinoza's observation, that " we should attend to that which 
 
THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 111 
 
 is good in everything, in order that we may be actuated by 
 pleasurable feelings." It is more strengthening to reflect 
 that, although scientific method is new, and although we 
 inhabit a poor planet of a poor sun, perhaps in an obscure 
 corner of the galaxy, yet we have discovered concerning the 
 planet, solar system, and even the galaxy, a good deal about 
 which there is in fact no doubt, in spite of any theoretical 
 impossibility. The ground of this antilogy is, that the 
 theoretical impossibility can be explained in few words and 
 understood at a glance ; whereas the scientific demonstrations 
 (which it would be senseless to call ' practically ' true) depend 
 upon innumerable observations, calculations, corrections, ever 
 accumulating and mutually confirmatory, the effect of which 
 is indescribable. Hence the antiscientific argument has a 
 great rhetorical advantage over the defence ; although the 
 experience which the defence can never fairly represent in 
 words is entirely convincing, and although the attack depends 
 entirely upon the truth of that experience. 
 
 It is another characteristic abstraction of the physical 
 sciences to treat external Reality as constituted solely by the 
 Primary Qualities of matter (resistance and extension), and 
 to regard the Secondary (colour, sound, temperature, etc.) as 
 in themselves subjective reactions, though excited by the 
 Primary and objectified by association with them. The 
 reasons for this abstraction seem to be that, in the first place, 
 the Primary Qualities are the most strongly contrasted in 
 experience with those feelings that are most subjective — 
 pleasure, pain, and the ccenesthesis ; and that, secondly, they 
 are the most constant and unconditional in experience. For 
 both our own bodies and all the things around us present 
 them in all circumstances ; whilst many things have neither 
 sensible odour nor savour, may feel warm or cold according to 
 conditions, and are colom^less or coloured according to the 
 supply of light. Illusions are chiefly of seeing or hearing, 
 but to touch or grasp a thing is conviction. It next follows 
 from the constancy of the Primary Qualities, that they are 
 conceived to have the greatest coherence ; so that the breaks 
 that occur in our seeing or hearing of things (say, dui'ing the 
 
112 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 night) are supposed to be filled up by a " permanent possi- 
 bility " of touching them ; and even our own existence during 
 sleep is commonly so conceived, and all lacunae of conscious- 
 ness to be filled up with " cerebration." It is in their 
 Primary Qualities, again, that things are most precisely 
 measurable in dimension, weight, movement, and most 
 uniform in their variation, and for these reasons most 
 calculable. Hence in respect of the Primary Qualities the 
 processes of Nature can be imaginatively intuited (by the 
 hand, if not by the eye), when they cannot be actually 
 observed, as a continuous transition ; and this continuity of 
 process, measurable and calculable, is a ground of the peculiar 
 confidence felt in mathematical Physics. Finally, the supposed 
 reduction of all other qualities to the Primary, or at least to 
 a dependence on them, seems to gratify our instincts of 
 explanation and simplification. 
 
 It is easily intelligible, then, that the sciences should 
 regard the Primary Quahties as pre-eminently real, and should 
 carry on in terms of them the whole conceptual extension of 
 Empirical Eeahty. Yet it is, I suppose, generally admitted 
 that (as Hume showed) the Primary Qualities are, as truly as 
 the Secondary, grounded on sensations (namely the tactile and 
 kinsesthetic), and that therefore, reflecting on the conditions of 
 experience, they are (to use a Kantian expression) " transcen- 
 dentally subjective." It cannot be denied that the Second- 
 ary Qualities are an essential element of Empirical Eeality ; 
 indeed, by visual qualities we habitually think of all the rest. 
 If then things are hard, why should they not be coloured and 
 scented ? If pressure and movement correspond in any way 
 with transcendent Eeality, why may not colour and odour 
 correspond with it in some other way ? 
 
 The immediacy of Empirical Eeality makes it impossible 
 that the Secondary Qualities should be ' explained away ' and 
 denied any place in the world. It is probable that in primitive 
 organic consciousness the manifold of sensation is undeveloped ; 
 but somehow the progress of organic consciousness is certainly 
 toward fuller knowledge ; human and adult faculty is the 
 truest. The very relativity of the Secondary Qualities, de- 
 
THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 113 
 
 termined by the process of organic differentiation, may point 
 to some specific function of theirs in the representation of 
 transcendent Eeality. Natural Selection guarantees the growtli 
 of a more and more effective correspondence ; and we ought to 
 consider whether there are sufficient grounds for Huppo.sing 
 that this growth of practical efficiency by the differentiation 
 of sensation, is at the same time a growth of mental illusion. 
 May not the equivalent of all that we perceive, and far more, 
 exist in inorganic consciousness, I mean in the consciousness 
 of what we call inorganic Nature ? If such a view should, 
 on the whole, give the greatest coherence to our conception 
 of things, it would appear that the organisation of conscious- 
 ness is a gradual realisation of the truth of the World, not 
 merely as an atomic skeleton, but as the infinite glory that 
 we know and delight in. 
 
 § 6. By the division of scientific labour many departments 
 of study have been created, to each of which men devote their 
 whole lives. Passing over all sub-divisions of the sciences 
 and omitting the merely descriptive investigations, there 
 remain five great groups : Mathematics, Astronomy and 
 Physics, Chemistry, Biology, Psychology. Each of these 
 sciences has been explored with the greatest ardour ; and the 
 result is that, whatever the internal consistency of each, a 
 certain unconformability has appeared amongst them, making 
 it difficult to conceive of them as one system of Nature ; yet 
 human understanding requires that they shall be so conceived. 
 
 Besides the theoretical impossibility of applying pure 
 Mathematics to Astronomy and Physics, of passing from the 
 postulates of absolute Space, Time and Motion to the intricate 
 relativity of actual phenomena, there is the practical difficulty 
 of obtaining exact measurements of phenomena, seeing that 
 such measurements must depend at last upon an appeal to 
 sense-perception, and must be stated, after every precaution has 
 been taken, as lying within certain limits of error. Yet, with- 
 out exact measurements, how establish between the processes 
 of Nature those equations which constitute explanation ? The 
 reply to this is that the more nearly actual measurements 
 approach ideal exactness, the better is the verification of 
 
 8 
 
114 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 physical theories, and the systematic cohesion of laws : so 
 that a belief in the soundness of the methods employed, and 
 in the uniformity of processes explored, continually increases. 
 
 In passing from Physics to Chemistry a difficulty emerges 
 which is usually conceived of as if it were necessarily a 
 problem to reduce chemical action to mechanical principles ; 
 and, similarly, in passing from Chemistry to Biology, it is 
 often assumed that the phenomena of life in plants and ani- 
 mals must be reduced to chemistry and mechanics. To find 
 some definite resemblance between all three orders of phenomena, 
 the physical, chemical, and biological, is indeed, according to 
 our present conceptions of explanation, a regulative principle 
 of the philosophy of Nature ; but the end would seem to be 
 equally attained were it possible either to reduce any two of 
 these orders of phenomena to the third, or to find some further 
 ground upon which all three are explicable. The former of 
 these courses has not yet succeeded ; whilst the latter (I 
 believe) has never been attempted. 
 
 But the transition from Biology to Psychology brings to 
 light a far greater difiiculty of explanation, the greatest 
 problem known to speculation. For whilst Physics, Chemistry, 
 and Biology have at least this in common, that they all treat 
 of matter and motion, Psychology calls for a theory of the 
 manifold of sensation, pleasure and pain, passion and volition ; 
 and the Philosophy of Nature, as a whole, requires that these 
 phenomena shall be explained in harmony with the theories 
 of matter and motion, in fact that Matter and Consciousness 
 shall be reduced to the same concept. Now, subjectively, such 
 a reduction can be made ; for one's own organism and the 
 whole external world are manifestly a construction of sen- 
 sations and ideas in consciousness ; but, objectively, whoever 
 believes that there are other minds than his own must find it 
 impossible to suppose that matter stands for nothing but his 
 own construction ; and approaching the question as the 
 natural sciences do, it is plain that an organic consciousness 
 capable of constructing a World is a late and recent product in 
 the history of things. This opposition between the subjective 
 or analytic and the objective or historical views, has been 
 
THE KELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 115 
 
 forcibly presented by Shad worth Hodgson in liis Philosophy 
 of Rejlection. Various theories of intercausatiou, parallelism, 
 or other connection of Mind and Body will confront us in 
 future chapters. Here I shall merely, by way of anticipation, 
 state my own opinion : namely, that in our own consciousness 
 we have an immediate knowledge of ultimate Reality, and 
 that the remainder of Empirical Eeality, including our own 
 bodies and the external world, is a system of phenomena 
 constructed in consciousness and in some manner representing 
 the ultimate Eeality. That lieality is universally conscious, 
 but its whole being cannot be fully expressed by consciousness ; 
 so that as to the remainder of its being, it is transcendent, and 
 can only be miderstood, partly, from the laws of phenomena, 
 which represent it objectively, and partly, from the laws of 
 self-consciousness, which does not represent it and is not a 
 phenomenon but the Eeality itself subjectively conditioned. 
 What from these data can be inferred of transcendent Eeality 
 will hereinafter be considered : but it is not unknowable. 
 
 From what has been said it follows, that Matter and 
 Consciousness cannot be wholly reduced to one concept. In 
 Empirical Eeality indeed, they are merely contrasted areas of 
 consciousness itself — matter is in consciousness ; in Physical 
 Reality, matter is reduced to certain quantitative aspects of 
 objective consciousness ; but in ultimate Eeality, matter has 
 no place, being a phenomenon or representation of that Eeality 
 so far as Reality is not consciousness. It follows further that 
 the concept of ultimate Eeality is not simple but contains a 
 duality, namely. Consciousness and the Transcendent Being or 
 Idea that is conscious ; and that, therefore, the ambition of 
 Philosophy to attain to absolute simple Being, without differ- 
 ence or relation, is overstrained and illusory. 
 
 § 7. Explanation is shown by logicians to consist in the 
 discovery of Likeness between phenomena, or ideas, or their 
 relations. The nature of explanation, then, is the last strong- 
 hold of those who impeach human knowledge on the ground 
 of its relativity ; for there is no Likeness unqualified by 
 Difference. But this impeachment derives all its force from 
 the rashness of those who demand an absolute simplicity of 
 
116 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 conception. Apart from this infatuation, there is no reason 
 why the Relativity of Knowledge should be a bar to the con- 
 struction by the human mind of the scientific system of ex- 
 perience, or in other words, to the rise of the World to self- 
 consciousness. The love of simplicity is a treacherous in- 
 stinct ; the belief in simplicity promises a theory of the world 
 to dialectical ignorance if only enthusiastic or presumptuous 
 enough. 
 
 But, fortunately, in the foundations of the human mind 
 there is provision for our discovery of the fulness and variety 
 as well as of the unity of the world. For the occurrence of a 
 change or difference in some diffused, indefinite, potential 
 sensibility, is the nearest approach we can make to a conception 
 of the beginning of organic consciousness ; and a reversal of 
 this change or return to the antecedent condition, which thus 
 by contrast obtains a higher degree of actuality, may be con- 
 ceived as the experience from which a sense of likeness gradu- 
 ally emerges and grows into recognition. Eecognition (if I 
 may use the term in a generalised sense) is a condition of all 
 the organism's adaptive correspondence with Nature, from 
 reflex action to the highest scientific inference. It has been 
 shown experimentally that conscious recognition is intrinsically 
 pleasurable: and explanation is recognition amidst disguise. 
 As the surprise of a new explanation subsides, there ensues a 
 feeling of relief, familiarity, security. So strong is the pleasure 
 of recognition that a merely customary familiarity of experience, 
 or dogma, is often mistaken for understanding, and offers 
 resistance to any profounder analysis ; which, by requiring a 
 rearrangement of ideas and bringing to light unnoticed differ- 
 ences, gives at first a feeling of strangeness allied to fear. But 
 for this very reason the sense of difference, or discrimination, 
 is as important as the sense of likeness, or assimilation, to the 
 full explanation of the world. For men are too easily content 
 to find the unity of thought in superficial resemblances, or in 
 the use of some one word (such as the ' Absolute ') to bundle 
 up all differences. But the differences from which likeness 
 emerges cling to it at every level of mental growth, alike in 
 the detail of perception and in the widest reaches of specula- 
 
THE KELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE 117 
 
 tive thought. Discrimination saves us from swallowing stones 
 for bread, and destroys the authority of premature systems of 
 Philosophy. Bread, indeed, must be recognised, if starvation 
 is to be avoided ; and new systems of Philosophy must be 
 established upon deeper resemblances, if our spiritual instincts 
 are to be fulfilled. But a system that ends in unqualified sim- 
 plicity, as the ultimate character of Reality, can never, strictly 
 speaking, be conceived ; and, therefore, I accept the reproach of 
 not attempting to construct such a system. 
 
 The sceptical doubt must indeed remain, whether there be 
 in the empirical world, in Natura naturata, any such unity 
 as can satisfy the love of explanation in the human mind ; 
 and the only possible answer to this trope is the completion by 
 posterity of the system of Positive Philosophy. If there be, 
 in fact, no unity, discrimination will forbid the prolonged reign 
 of any system of error, until the habit of recognising the irre- 
 concilable differences of things shall give rise to resignation in 
 that last scene of the tragedy of Reason. 
 
 Bacon found a chief som'ce of the idols of the Den in the 
 tendency of one man to perceive the resemblances, and of another 
 to insist on the differences of phenomena ; and Kant saw in 
 these two kinds of men the constructive and critical thinkers. 
 As in our present imperfect development every quality carries 
 its defect, the assimilative mind is often too hasty in subsump- 
 tion, and even resentful of exception ; whilst the discriminative 
 seems almost to hate explanation and to exult in the dilapida- 
 tion of systems : for every animal uses its own weapons and 
 rejoices in its own strength. 
 
 From the intellectual cravings after assimilation and dis- 
 crimination spring our conceptions of the unity and unifor- 
 mity of Nature amidst all the variety of phenomena ; and those 
 more definite conceptions of the persistence of matter and 
 energy, or of the quantitative likeness or equality of the 
 contents of Nature, amidst all changes throughout all time ; 
 and all the sciences, and our whole endeavour after a system- 
 atic knowledge of the world. These, in fact, are those forms 
 of thought that necessarily govern our interpretation of things ; 
 not such products of psychic growth as Space and Causality, 
 
118 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 forms that have a natural history. Hence the Metaphysical 
 Eelativity of the Kantian system needs no examination. 
 
 But what shall we say to the limits of explanation pointed 
 out by Mill, namely, wherever in comparing phenomena we 
 can find no resemblance ? For the experimental psychologists 
 have shown that there are more than 40,000 different sensa- 
 tions known to the human mind alone, to say nothing of 
 other animals and the sons of Mars and of the Dog-star ; and 
 each distinguishable sensation must have its own law of gener- 
 ation. A solution of this difficulty may be attempted upon 
 the basis of Spencer's speculation, that all different sensations 
 are only different groupings of one original shock of change, 
 the atom of consciousness ; but this theory seems to be in- 
 applicable to those sensations whose stimuli are chemical 
 changes. Or, again, it may be said that the differences of our 
 present consciousness are deceptive, since our differentiated 
 sensations exhibit only a cross-section of consciousness develop- 
 ing in time, just as existing plants and animals exhibit 
 only a cross -section of all the great processions of life, that 
 are yet united by a common ancestry. For similarly all 
 consciousness, whatever contrasts it now comprises, is one 
 growth from age to age, by infinitesimal gradations self- 
 distinguishing. But, strictly speaking, this conception of con- 
 sciousness does not efface, but multiplies, the differences that 
 frustrate explanation. If, as many considerations indicate, the 
 differences that we perceive disguise innumerable imperceptible 
 shades that come infinitely near resemblances, on the other 
 hand, where our apperceptive consciousness finds miqualified 
 sameness, there may again lurk as many imperceptible differ- 
 ences. It follows that the explanation of the World is not to 
 be sought in the region of sensations or their proper laws, 
 which only express its inexhaustible fulness and variety, and 
 are common to us and the animals ; but in the region of con- 
 cepts, of laws of laws, and of the harmony of laws which lies 
 open to human understanding. 
 
BOOK II.-COSMOLOGY 
 
CHAPTER VII 
 
 SUBSTANCE IN EXPERIENCE 
 
 § 1. That the World should be a necessary existence, 
 whilst yet we continually wonder at it: these things, says 
 Schopenhauer, are contradictory. Not only do we continually 
 wonder at it, but some have brought themselves to believe 
 that it is but a dream. To one it is too monstrous, to another 
 too insignificant for reality. And with apparent sobriety 
 metaphysicians dispute, above all, whether the World is 
 Substance ; and, if so, in what sense. 
 
 Bodies moving in space or relatively at rest are often 
 called ' substance ' in an unsophisticated way of speaking ; in 
 Chemistry, too, one may speak of substances to be analysed, 
 or resulting from analysis : they may also be called ' matter.' 
 Substance and matter are regarded by Common Sense as 
 immediately given in Empirical Reality, for otherwise it 
 would not deserve to be called Reality. But most meta- 
 physicians, if the ghosts of the study haunt them in the 
 street, must fall in with the popular usage not without qualms 
 and reservations ; for they are accustomed to employ the 
 terms Substance and Matter for something extremely subtle 
 and obscure : something common to all concrete things without 
 being discoverable in any of them ; or something which makes 
 itself indirectly known through things without ever being an 
 object of experience ; or something that by natural illusion is 
 thought into things, though in fact there is nothing there. 
 These hypotheses will be reviewed in the next chapter : in this 
 one we are concerned witli the substance accepted by Common 
 Sense, empirical substance. 
 
 121 
 
122 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 Now it is generally admitted that by reflection an empirical 
 substance is resolvable into a group of qualities, founded 
 severally on sensations, cohering in one place, or all moving 
 together, and regarded as one perdurable whole. The meta- 
 physical aspect of qualities, as distinguished from qualities of 
 sense-perception, depends further upon a comparison of things 
 perceived and an abstraction of their resemblances ; and the 
 relative unreality of the quality is the contrast of it as thought 
 with the sensation-complex perceived. The coherence of the 
 qualities of any substance is not side by side, like the physical 
 cohesion of particles, but in interfusion, so that however small 
 a part of any homogeneous substance be taken (provided it is 
 still an object of actual, not merely conceptual, experience), it 
 exhibits all the qualities characteristic of the whole. The 
 foundation of the qualities in sensation, does not mean that 
 each quality is derived exclusively from one corresponding 
 kind of sensation, but that each of them may be derived from 
 sensation simple or complex. Even the colour of an object (say 
 gold) does not correspond to one pure sensation, but is a mixed 
 result of chromatic and achromatic vision, and, as an extent of 
 colour, involves movements of the eye ; and such a quality 
 as elasticity, though depending essentially on certain varying 
 degrees of muscular strain, may be habitually signified by the 
 image of something stretching or contracting and recovering 
 itself in a regular manner. 
 
 The realisation of this position, that a substance is a group 
 of qualities all of which are grounded in sensation, may be said 
 to be the first step in Metaphysics, and whoever takes it never 
 again looks reflectively upon the world with quite the same 
 eyes ; and yet it is a very simple step, and necessarily results 
 from the fact that in analysing an object, or empirical 
 substance, we are dealing with something that occurs in our 
 consciousness, and can never find in it anything that is not a 
 factor of our consciousness ; for even if we discover in it 
 qualities before unknown, these very discoveries appear in 
 consciousness. 
 
 But as to the nature of the qualities, not merely in their 
 subjective grounds, but in their present and universal objec- 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXrEEIENCE 123 
 
 tivity, and as to their relation to one another, to the substance 
 they constitute or " inhere in," and to the Subject or mind 
 that perceives them, there are many inventions. 
 
 According to Hume, the idea of a substance " is nothing but 
 a collection of simple ideas, that are united by the imagination, 
 and have a particular name assigned them " ; either referred 
 to an unknown something in which they are supposed to 
 inhere, or at least supposed to be inseparably connected by the 
 relations of contiguity and causation : the principle of union 
 being regarded as the chief part of the complex idea (Treatise, 
 Book I. Part II. § 6); and when such unity seems inadequate the 
 imagination is apt to feign something unknown and invisible, 
 which it supposes to continue the same amidst all variations, 
 a substance, or original and first matter (Treatise, Part IV. § 3). 
 To refer the connection of the simple ideas or qualities to the 
 " imasrination " without further ado, is characteristic of Hume, 
 and must proceed either from carelessness, or the love of 
 frightening his reader ; for in § 3 of Part I. he has told us that 
 imagination is not restrained to the same order and form with 
 the original impressions. Therefore, it cannot be the condition 
 of union amongst ideas that are "inseparably connected." 
 Similarly Kant, as if following Hume, after observing that the 
 elements of our representation of an object, or the synthesis of 
 objects which is Nature, must be first given serially in experi- 
 ence, makes it the function of imagination (Eirihildung) to 
 retrieve the past or lapsing members of the series and repre- 
 sent the whole simultaneously. But he explains that the 
 order of representations in the object cannot be capricious 
 or arbitrary, because they are necessarily connected in one 
 pure consciousness ; that is, in the Universal Understanding 
 in the World ; in subservience to whose Categories, again, 
 imagination analyses, classifies, and interprets individual ex- 
 perience according to rules, and thus (e.g.) subsumes an object 
 as Substance (K d. r. V., transscendentale Deduktiov). 
 
 Whether this is a just account of Kant's view his own 
 perplexity leaves me uncertain. But there is no doubt that 
 Hume and Kant agree verbally as to the importance of 
 the part played by imagination in constructing our idea of 
 
124 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Substance; and I think they are both right in what they 
 mean, though their language is crude. That the qualities of 
 what we now perceive as a concrete body were gradually 
 united or differentiated in experience is highly probable, and 
 that they now are in some way simultaneously presented is 
 certain ; and we must try to name the condition of this 
 process and result, and of course imagination is our name for 
 much later and more superficial mental activities. It is 
 plainly that function which more recent writers have called 
 ' retentiveness,' ' reinstatement,' ' integration.' We cannot ex- 
 pect to find ready-made any term to express such unique and 
 obscure conditions ; but perhaps it will be least misleading to 
 call it " growth." 
 
 The qualities which we regard as belonging to a substance 
 are sensations, or sensation-modes, that have been ' projected ' 
 and objectified, or differentiated in the course of organic history 
 from the subjective life of feeling, by their special alliances 
 with the sensations of movement and resistance. A point of 
 colour (e.g.) is found to coincide with a point of pressure and 
 resistance when, putting forth one's hand and touching an object, 
 the colour of the object has the same relative brightness and 
 distinctness as that of the hand, and a different relative bright- 
 ness from that of the hand when not put forth so far : it thus 
 comes to be regarded as at the end of such a possible movement 
 or distance in space. Similarly with resonance, odour, warmth ; 
 they are found to increase as we approach the place of a thing, 
 until their maximum intensity coincides with the solid core of 
 resistance in that place. An account of this process will be 
 found in books on Psychology : though some indeed dispute 
 it ; James (vol. ii. chap, xvii.) maintaining that sensations are 
 external in space as perceived ah initio. But certainly he cannot 
 directly know this, and it is inconsistent with his other state- 
 ments. Mill's view, that sensation is originally neither internal 
 nor external, seems to me the true one. But whilst in general 
 this hypothesis is (I believe) correct, the reading of a thousand 
 text-books will not enable us fully to realise it ; because the 
 process described is a growth, and involves the changes of 
 character that always occur in growth ; and because the essential 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXPEEIP:NCE 125 
 
 part of the process has not taken place within our own niemoi}-, 
 nor within our own life, nor even within the life of tlie human 
 race, but originates deep in the animal kingdom, how far back 
 we cannot say. 
 
 § 2. Now if any such hypothesis is true of the construction 
 of an object as Substance, it is true of that context or synthesis 
 of objects which is Nature on the perceptual plane. Nature 
 has been projected in organic history as an Object in contrast 
 with a Subject ; but for the human individual it is preformed, 
 or prepared for, in his inherited organisation ; for the organic 
 growth of perceptions in the mind corresponds with the growth 
 of the nervous system. It is true that in man the complete 
 formation of perception is delayed until some time after 
 birth ; he is born only half-baked. Hence our early post-natal 
 growth and development are indeed accompanied by some small 
 amount of ' experience ' (for perhaps a disciple of Locke is bound 
 to apply this term even to vague and confused sentience) ; but 
 such experience bears no proportion to the development that 
 takes place, and cannot be considered as " the cause " of it, or 
 as more than a condition whose value depends upon the activities 
 aroused in the central nervous regions by peripheral stimuli 
 and limb-movement : activities which promote the differentia- 
 tion of the brain and the co-ordination of its organs. We must 
 consider that in a few months before birth the whole history 
 of early animal life has been traversed ; that the power that 
 has brought this about cannot be supposed to cease at birth ; 
 that, accordingly, both before and after birth a man grows of 
 his own impulse, like everything else in organic natm-e ; and 
 that the proportional influence of experience, inappreciable at 
 first, grows greater and greater, in comparison with that of 
 inherent development, up to some variable date. 
 
 Perception and the nervous system grow together ; and 
 whilst the perceptive powers are being established, and long 
 afterwards, other more plastic powers of the mind appear, 
 corresponding with nervous growths of a less stable character. 
 Perhaps the necessity of completely interlacing the later powers 
 of the mind (dependent on experience) with the perceptual 
 system, is the chief reason why man is born with a perceptual 
 
126 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 system so incomplete. However this may be, it is the later 
 and more plastic powers of the mind that are properly called 
 ' imagination,' ' reflection,' ' understanding ' ; and nothing can 
 be more perverse than to explain the facts of perception by 
 referring them to imagination or understanding, it is the 
 anthropomorphic fallacy. The concept " Substance " is indeed 
 a function of understanding ; but what it stands for, the ex- 
 perience it subsumes, belongs to the perceptual plane and is 
 shared by men and animals. 
 
 The objects as perceived are stable ; and stable are the 
 cerebral organs and connections of the perceptive apparatus, 
 and therefore the correspondingly grouped sensations and 
 suggestions or subrepresentations which, being " projected," 
 constitute those objects. The objects and the brain are alike 
 empirical substances, regarded as existing and perduring, 
 whether we sleep or wake ; and if we believe in a trans- 
 cendent Substance, this must stand in the same relation to 
 objects and to the brain, and must be regarded as the ulti- 
 mate ground of the objective synthesis. 
 
 Because perception precedes the growth of reflection, the 
 Object precedes Self; and therefore by all animals as well as 
 by unsophisticated men, it is assumed to be an object for all, 
 the context of which, or Nature, is alike for all ; and therefore 
 Hegel is mistaken when he says that " all consciousness of 
 another object is also self-consciousness. The object is my 
 idea : I am aware of the object as mine ; and thus in it I am 
 aware of me" {Encycl. iii. § 424). Not more than one man 
 in a million can ever be got to say, in the moment of percep- 
 tion, " the object is my idea " ; and he mistakes reflection for 
 perception. For with perception goes the fact (it is more than 
 conviction) that the tree stands there for everybody, since it 
 belongs to the prepersonal life, and corresponds with stable 
 nervous growths ; whereas ' Self ' and * mine ' belong to reflec- 
 tion, and correspond with the less stable nervous growths 
 that are characteristic of human development. 
 
 § 3. If then, an empirical substance yields to analysis 
 nothing but a group of interfused qualities regarded as perdui'- 
 able in one place, how can we be justified in speaking of a 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXPERIENCE 127 
 
 " quality " at all, since this term is correlative with " substance " 
 which, apart from the qualities, is a mere space ? On the plane 
 of Empirical Reality there is not much difficulty about this. 
 Each quality, taken severally, is referred to the rest of the 
 group : the scheme of judgment — S is Q — predicates co-exist- 
 ence or coinherence. That because it is possible to refer any 
 one quality to the group, we may refer the whole list of 
 qualities to something that still remains, may illustrate the 
 common fallacy of " Division and Composition " : for certainly 
 we do not mean to refer them merely to the place in which 
 they are found to co-exist. It is true that one quality is more 
 important than all the rest, namely resistance ; for in any 
 circumstances wherever we find this, we say there is a Body ; 
 whilst any phenomenon in which this is wanting is declared an 
 illusion. Still resistance is itself a quality and not Substance ; 
 for we do not refer other qualities, such as size or colour, 
 merely to resistance. 
 
 Unity of place is, indeed, essential to the concept of Sub- 
 stance ; as we see in the axioms that " a body can occupy only 
 one place at the same time," and that " two bodies cannot 
 occupy the same place at the same time." These are statements 
 of universal experience in the jostling, collision, fracture and 
 recoil of things, and in the manage of our own bodies ; since 
 we can only occupy the place of anything by removing it, and 
 if it is too massive to be moved we cannot get there at all. 
 Yet the fact that most things can be moved and, indeed, that 
 all things do move, makes it impossible to identify substance 
 with place. Nor is it the abstract of places ; for each substance 
 is in a particular place ; and the common notions that qualities 
 " inhere " in substance, and that substance " supports " its 
 qualities, imply something more than place : it is hard to say 
 what — a " confused idea of something," as Locke expresses it. 
 
 Perhaps this " something " is to be found in a primitive 
 subjectivising of the object, the attributing to it of a sub- 
 consciousness of weight and other sensations, like that 
 consciousness of our own bodies that stands in the background 
 of all our thoughts. And such a belief may be justifiable ; 
 but as soon as this idea of an object's inwardness is made 
 
128 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 explicit, it loses the character of substance, and becomes an 
 attribute, even if we shrink from calling it a quality. It 
 cannot be regarded as ' supporting ' qualities, nor as that in 
 which they ' inhere.' Such expressions still seem a sort of 
 illusory verbiage. And, indeed, it is plain that nothing that 
 is represented in consciousness as belonging to a thing, can 
 be regarded as the substance of it : for, as Spinoza says, " an 
 attribute is that ivhich the intellect perceives concerning 
 substance, as constituting its essence." Cointerfusion of 
 qualities must always be, for reflection, the content of Empirical 
 Eeality : otherwise in this region substance is unknown to 
 analysis. 
 
 § 4. The Qualities of Substances are usually distinguished 
 as Primary and Secondary : those that are derived from 
 " muscle sensations " of resistance and movement — solidity, 
 size, weight and motion ; and those that are derived from 
 other senses — heat, colour, sonority, taste and smell. The 
 distinction seems to have originated with Democritus or 
 Leucippus in connection with the doctrine of atoms, and so 
 far prevails at the present day that the physical sciences 
 generally assume that the ' real ' world, the world of Conceptual 
 Eeality, has only the primary qualities, and that the secondary 
 depend upon the presence of a sensitive organism that, being 
 stimulated by contact with the primary world, reacts in these 
 astonishing ways. 
 
 The distinction thus drawn has both a practical and a 
 speculative interest. For the primary world is (1) the seat 
 of mechanical and chemical energy, which for our life's sake 
 it behoves us to respect at every hour and in every action ; 
 (2) it is perdurable and unconditional, the same by day and 
 night, whether we are present or absent (necessarily assumed 
 to be so) ; (3) it is objective, that about which we can all 
 agree, or come nearest to agreement ; (4) it is measurable in 
 three dimensions of space, in duration of existence or rate of 
 change, and in energy : for these reasons it is the object of 
 the conceptual system. But the secondary world is not 
 satisfactorily measurable in any way except by referring its 
 phenomena to primary standards. For even the discrimina- 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXPEKIENCE 129 
 
 tion of differences of quality is relative to the capacity of our 
 senses, which varies even in normal subjects ; and although 
 degrees of intensity are doubtless felt, it is only within narrow 
 limits, and how far they are from being measurable is shown 
 by the difticulty of interpreting the subjective side of Weber's 
 law, in deciding whether " least noticeable differences " are 
 equal or proportional, or what else. The secondary world, 
 again, is not perdurable but conditional, and goes and comes 
 accordingly ; it is not a unity or continuum, but consists of 
 distinct genera of sense-qualities, visual, auditory, etc., related 
 by their common dependence on the kineesthesis ; and its 
 chief interest lies not in itself (though it is coloured far 
 more constantly than the primary world by pleasure and pain), 
 but in being a system of signs, whose significance lies in that 
 outer region of possible utility and destruction. 
 
 Yet what a recondite, sophisticated, and difficult way of 
 thinking, is this ; and how many spectres it conjures up for 
 one that it lays, if it can be said to lay any at all. Is it 
 supposed to explain the meaning of Eeality, by contrasting 
 the primary world with one comparatively transient and 
 therefore um-eal ? But both are real, empirically considered ; 
 and both are unreal, if all external experience is considered as 
 merely phenomenal of something unknown. 
 
 Is it supposed that the distinction between the two 
 worlds enables us, through the conceptual system, to explain 
 the secondary by the primary, and thereby to reduce the 
 number of elementary problems of existence ? But every law 
 of connection between mechanical or chemical change in the 
 primary world and its corresponding sensation in the secondary, 
 is (as we have seen) an unique fact, distinct in some character 
 from every other ; and this is the opposite of explanation. 
 Secondary qualities cannot be deduced from the primary ; 
 they are connected with them by laws of experience, just as 
 the connection between cause and effect (qualitatively) is a 
 law of general experience. This does not impugn or render 
 doubtful the connection of qualities, for there is no better 
 assurance than constant experience ; which, as a condition of 
 consistency, is implied in all proof. But every law of the 
 
 9 
 
130 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 connection of qualities is an extension of knowledge ; and its 
 explanatory value consists (1) in the collection of many 
 experiences into the law itself, and (2) in ha\'ing the same 
 general character as other laws of such connection and not 
 conflicting with them. By " the same general character " 
 prevailing amongst laws of the connection of qualities, I 
 mean (for example) that differences of colour correspond 
 regularly to differences in the vibration rate of light-rays, 
 though we cannot see any resemblance between the two series 
 of differences ; and again, that all sensations are classifiable 
 with reference to chemical and mechanical stimuli ; and that 
 both kinds of stimuli operate upon nervous organs having 
 specific differences but the same general constitution : and in 
 all this there is no conflict. But this kind of explanation 
 does not (except in the summarising of laws) reduce the 
 number of the elementary problems of existence. And if we 
 turn to the purely subjective side of experience, and consider 
 that " mechanical and chemical stimuli," though referred to 
 the primary world, are nevertheless grounded in sensations, it 
 becomes impossible to think of explaining sensations by 
 stimuli. Here, indeed, the distinction between primary and 
 secondary qualities vanishes ; for it belongs to the conceptual 
 treatment of Nature as a perdurable thing. The muscle- 
 sensations upon which the primary qualities are grounded, 
 when considered merely as sensations, have no more claim 
 than colour or sound to be the seat of energy, or perdurable, 
 or unconditional, or objective, or directly measurable. 
 
 § 5. Does then the distinction between Primary and 
 Secondary Qualities throw any light upon the problem of 
 external cognition, by contrasting the primary world as some- 
 thing known, with the secondary as a means of knowing it ? 
 But if cognition implies that the thing known is something 
 distinct from the process or medium of knowing it, the primary 
 world is no such object of cognition ; for it is itself, by 
 analysis, a fact in consciousness. Or if cognition implies the 
 ancient doctrine that " like is known by like," we cannot be 
 helped toward the understanding of it by a distinction that 
 claims to be fundamental. 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXrERIENCE 131 
 
 This brings us to oue of the most harassing problems of 
 Philosophy, the cognition of the World ; for ever since 
 Democritus and Plato the cognition and the Being of the 
 "World Iiave been inseparable problems. 
 
 It is usually assumed by philosophers that the thing 
 known is other than the cognition of it, that the tree yonder 
 (to take Berkeley's example), whether seen or grasped, is not, 
 as a cognition or percept, identical with the ' real ' tree, the 
 Tree-by-itself ; and although this is not the view of cursory 
 irreflective Common Sense, yet to dispute it leads to obvious 
 difficulties. The tree or any other thing in Nature, is 
 certainly not merely identical with my cognition of it, or any 
 other man's ; since all normal men know it in much the same 
 way, and yet each of us with a certain difference ; and each of 
 us believes that it is perdurable and exists in some sense 
 though none of us be looking on. If there is nothing but the 
 cognition, there must be for each thing that we take to be 
 one, as many in fact as there are observers of it, as many 
 worlds as there are minds ; and each thing in each world 
 exists only as long as each mind perceives it. I really do not 
 think this nonsense can be directly refuted ; but fortunately 
 refutation is needless, as it obtains no public sympathy or 
 adhesion. 
 
 To avoid this unpopular conclusion it may be suggested 
 that when we identify the object with our cognition, we are 
 to mean — ' so far as it is cognised,' and that a distinction 
 may still be made between our knowledge of it and all there 
 is of it that remains to be explored. ' Our cognition,' it may 
 be said, ' does not indeed exhaust the object, for even about 
 things already well known we often learn more. The object 
 as distinguished from our cognition is the whole list of its 
 properties known and unknown.' But this way out of the 
 trap is immediately closed by two simple reflections : first, 
 what is the present condition of those properties of an object 
 that are not yet known ? — and, secondly, if all were known 
 would there not still be as many worlds as there are 
 Subjects ? For whatever further we may discover, thereupon 
 becomes a fact of consciousness ; so that the whole object 
 
132 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 may be regarded as exhausted by my cognition actual and 
 possible. 
 
 If, however, the thing known is something distinct from 
 our knowledge of it, how shall we set any limits to the 
 divergence ? Indeed, may not the thing and the knowledge of 
 it be so separate as to admit of no comparison ; since, as 
 Berkeley says, " how can an idea [percept] be like anything 
 that is not an idea ? " And in that case how can there be 
 said to be any knowledge ? 
 
 Next, let us suppose some one to take up the dogma that 
 ' like is known by like,' and to find some support for it in 
 modern monistic and animistic theories, such as occur in this 
 volume : he may observe that in the animal organism a body 
 and consciousness are, in some inexplicable way, always 
 associated, and he may ask : ' May not Nature at large be like 
 an organism in this, that consciousness in some form accom- 
 panies all things, or perhaps rather the energy of all things ? 
 — though this comes to much the same, since all things are 
 always energising. If so, may not our consciousness of objects 
 correspond with, and even resemble, the consciousness that is 
 in objects or that accompanies their movements ; so that our 
 consciousness is indirectly, but not the less definitely, con- 
 stantly and necessarily, a cognition of the things ? ' 
 
 It may be replied that such a suggestion is of no use to 
 Common Sense, because that authority holds that perception 
 is a knowledge of things themselves, not of how they feel. 
 But is this just ? Does not Common Sense hold that the 
 tiles of the house yonder are red whether seen or not ; and 
 what sense is there in saying that things are red when none 
 is looking, if they do not feel red ? How common the belief 
 is that secondary as well as primary qualities exist in the 
 object, every one knows. Plato in the BepuUic (507) says, as 
 a matter of course, that colour is in the object ; though later 
 in Thecctetus (153) and Timcev.s (67) he treats it as sensation 
 arising from collision between the activities of objects and 
 those of the eye. Th. Whittaker has pointed out to me that 
 in Plotinus' opinion qualities are not generated by the 
 collisions of bodies, but that colours, tastes, etc., whether 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXrERTENCE 133 
 
 aggregated in bodies and sensible, or dispersed and insensible, 
 are imperishable (En7i. iv. 4, 29). But how completely 
 moderns have rejected this belief may be seen in Mr. Spencer's 
 remark {Psych. § 318) that, strictly, the secondary qualities 
 are " not attributes of body at all," but are reactions upon 
 " certain forces which pervade the universe " ; they are a 
 " product of the subject, the object, and the environing 
 activities." 
 
 The difficulty of imagining that sensible qualities should 
 exist in bodies (as uninstructed Common Sense assumes) just as 
 they are known to us, must be acknowledged. It is not 
 logically impossible ; but it requires that our elaborate sense- 
 organs with their cerebral connections should have been so 
 adjusted during tlie evolution of the nervous system, that all 
 the changes and disturbances implied in the excitation of cog- 
 nition through various media with different modes of motion, 
 are corrected by them ; making our sensations not merely 
 correspond with, but resemble, the qualities of things as they 
 exist in the consciousness of Nature ; whereby Nature is truly 
 manifested to us, that is, known in phenomena. 
 
 To some minds, on the other hand, it may seem equally 
 incredible that the manifold glories of the world should exist 
 only for the higher animal life ; that there should be no 
 austere joy in deserts, no rapture in tropical wildernesses ; 
 that the music of winds and waters, and the colours of sky 
 and sea, should be deaf and blind. 
 
 Yet what has Common Sense to say, in the case of 
 temperature ? Objectively, it is a continuous scale of vibra- 
 tion rates ; but subjectively, intensity of heat or cold ; and 
 these are quite different sensations of special nerves. Every- 
 body instinctively believes that fire is itself hot, and snow 
 cold, not merely that they make us feel so. A defender of 
 the immediate truth of sense-preception might possibly replji 
 that our organism need not be supposed to respond to all the 
 feelings of Nature ; that our knowledge may be true, or supply 
 the grounds of truth, without being exhaustive ; that the 
 diffusion of the temperature sense, necessary to preservation, 
 is incompatible with such a differentiated organ as the eye for 
 
134 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 light ; but that, did such exist, we might perceive a heat- 
 spectrum, and with further organs another spectrum of the 
 ' chemical rays,' etc. ; that possibly these are repetitions in 
 lower and higher pitch of the light-spectrum ; and that, if so, 
 we know what they are, as we might fairly be said to know 
 the musical scale even if able to perceive only one octave. 
 
 It is not, however, common sense to regard heat and cold 
 as a sort of colours in lower octaves. Still, what refined 
 hypotheses concerning the correspondence of our sensations 
 with Nature may be within the power of an ingenious mind 
 to frame, it is not for me to say. I decline to assert that a 
 problem is insoluble merely because it baffles me ; and any 
 man may come to look very foolish who presumes to set a 
 limit to the speculations of posterity. Nor can I condemn such 
 speculations as a waste of time, as if there was not to be 
 plenty of time before the sun goes out. There is really no 
 hurry. Even if we fail to do some piece of work, or to 
 make some discovery ourselves, posterity may be trusted to 
 catch it up before the desolate end. Future generations may 
 have reason to thank those who left them something to do, 
 more than those who anticipated everything. How many 
 grateful monuments may hereafter commemorate the men who 
 did nothing and discovered nothing ! 
 
 That the thing known should be without any ground of 
 resemblance to the cognition of it, is a contradiction in terms. 
 In such a relation there is no knowledge. But the ground of 
 resemblance is not to be sought in feeling or sensation, though 
 in some cases (say mechanical exertion) a resemblance is more 
 imaginable than in the special sensations. It is rather in 
 certain ultimate relations that we must look for the agreement. 
 Things as phenomena and the brain as a phenomenon, are so 
 differently constituted that we cannot suppose their energising 
 to accompany similar consciousness ; for, as Spinoza says, * the 
 emotions of animals differ from those of man as their nature 
 differs from his' {Eth. iii. 57); and this principle extends to 
 the inorganic world. But consciousness is Reality, and there- 
 fore Time, being a form of consciousness, is a form of Reality. 
 Comparative consciousness, again, involves co-existence within 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXPERIENCE 135 
 
 tho spau of the empiricjil Now ; aiul therefore, although 
 we may not be able to show that all consciousness is com- 
 parative, still CO- existence is a possible form of Ideality; 
 and the co-existence of phenomena in Space suggests that 
 co-existence is a universal condition of things transcendent or 
 Being, that is, so far as Reality is not consciousness ; though, 
 since Space is a construction of organic consciousness, it may 
 not be justifiable to treat co-existence in Space as a condition 
 of things-by-themselves. And I may say here that I speak 
 of things transcendent as things-by-themselves, because 
 Reality so far as it is not consciousness cannot be an 
 immediate object of consciousness ; for then it would be a 
 phenomenon. Nevertheless, since all Reality is conscious, 
 things transcendent are not "by themselves" in the sense 
 of being without consciousness. 
 
 There are, then, fundamental relations in which the thing 
 known may agree with the cognition of it through phenomena : 
 we are not obliged to maintain that the thing known is 
 unknowable : and the meagre contents of knowledge here 
 indicated may be enriched by further reflection. But, now, 
 what are we to think of the vast extent and variety of oui- 
 knowledge of the World ? How does it stand to that faint 
 Thing transcendent which, as Plato says of the Good, can 
 hardly be discerned ? The contrast of riches and penury seems 
 to make the riches unreal and a kind of illusion. But this 
 feeling is itself an illusion arising from the demand, that that 
 which is not consciousness shall be an immediate content of 
 consciousness, or a phenomenon ; and from treating as empty 
 that which is necessarily hidden. For knowledge is a 
 consciousness, and, if there is anything other than consciousness, 
 the knowledge of it can only be a representation in conscious- 
 ness. Now the growth of such representation in life and 
 mind I take to be a function of the evolution of Nature ; and 
 it is a true knowledge of Nature because it is her Self- 
 knowledge. The universal consciousness grows into such 
 knowledge. That in the course of its development it is very 
 imperfect may be true ; but that its central character and 
 tendency should be deceptive, is a foolish anthropomorphic 
 
136 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 superstitution. On the whole, there is nobody to deceive. It 
 may have the defect of economy but not of ostentation. 
 
 § 6. Besides the Secondary Qualities of a Body, interpreted 
 as effects of certain energies of it upon a sensitive organism, 
 and hence called by Spencer " dynamic qualities," it has other 
 properties, by Locke called "powers" {Of the Understanding, 
 Book II. chap, xxi.), whereby it acts on other bodies, altering 
 their positions or their sensible qualities; and both the 
 energies known to us as the secondary qualities and those by 
 which it acts on other bodies, as well as their reactions and 
 sensible changes, are traced to the primary qualities or to modi- 
 fications of them. They are powers of attraction and pro- 
 pulsion, of absorbing, reflecting, or radiating light and heat, of 
 generating or conducting electricity, of synthesis, growth, and 
 reproduction ; all generally regarded as reducible to movements 
 or tendencies to move on the part of the atoms, molecules, cells, 
 or whatever units constitute a body. To investigate the laws 
 of all such energies belongs to the natural sciences. The 
 facts are sometimes sensibly manifest, sometimes are insensible ; 
 and in the latter case may sometimes be made sensible by 
 instruments or indirectly by indices, or may be given over to 
 conceptual analysis and description according to the analogy of 
 experience, — that is to hypothesis, which must be made definite 
 enough to be tested by sensible experience or observation. 
 The metaphysician notes that the scientific treatment of the 
 energies of bodies always regards them as objects of actual or 
 possible perception, or at least of intuition trained by percep- 
 tion, that is, as facts of objective consciousness. The latens 
 schematismus and the latens processus are not regarded as ap- 
 pertaining to things-by-themselves ; and all attempts to treat 
 them as ' occult qualities ' have been resultless. The ' positive ' 
 method prevails, and a metaphysician who proposed to adopt 
 any other would hardly be considered worth a shrug. 
 
 Yet 1 suppose it is generally felt that the positive method 
 is adhered to not as absolutely satisfying, but as the only 
 possible one to work with for definite results. If the World, 
 as it is known, is a construction and projection of the per- 
 ceptual apparatus of our consciousness, how can ' power,' ' force,' 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXPERIENCE 137 
 
 ' energy,' have any place in it ? In using such words we 
 certainly attribute to objects a feeling corresponding with our 
 own feelings of muscular exertion, which is in fact the ground 
 of all primary qualities; and yet we ctmnot attribute this 
 feeling to objects considered merely as our own perceptions ; 
 but can only mean that there goes along with the changes 
 (however inconceivable) of things-by-themselves, manifest as 
 movements and pressures of masses, a feeling of exertion in 
 some way analogous to our own feeling of exertion ; though 
 the power or force, whatever it may be, belongs not to the 
 thing's feeling but to the activity which that feeling accom- 
 panies. The greater diffusion of the feelings of temperature 
 and exertion, connected with nearly every part of our bodies, 
 not specially localised in organs like the retina, may make it 
 easier for us to suppose that they are shared by inorganic 
 Nature. From Nature comes all that we have, and we can 
 hardly help allowing her (though under protest) the most 
 vague and (during most of our life) the most submerged and 
 neglected sensations of all that she has endowed us with. 
 
 According to this hj^othesis. Laws of Nature, primarily 
 descriptive of phenomena, have, through the mediation of 
 phenomena, a correspondence with the powers and activities of 
 things-by-themselves, that constitute transcendent Eeality so 
 far as that Eeality is not itself consciousness. And we have 
 seen that the assumption of such a Reality is forced upon us 
 in many ways : by this instinctive belief in something not 
 oiurselves that consciously moves and strives ; by the fact that 
 the World, reflected on as a phenomenon, exists only in con- 
 sciousness, and as such is a distinct world for each of us, 
 whilst some common ground of all our experience is indis- 
 pensable ; by our need for some permanent condition of all 
 the things of which we have occasional glimpses, which were 
 already familiar to our life before subjective reflection began, 
 are figured to us by the history of the world as antecedent to 
 organic life, and in all our preparations for the future. 
 
 This ontological hypothesis has, I believe, the merit of not 
 making the slightest difference to any scientific proposition. 
 
 § 7. The fundamental physical quality of a body is 
 
138 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 inertia : any ostensive body that wants it is considered an 
 hallucination. It is sensibly known by the resistance things 
 offer to our movements or efforts to move, or (more abstractly) 
 by their resistance to acceleration. This is a measure of their 
 mass, and coincides with the measurement of mass by weight. 
 And it is in relation to mass that the physical principle is 
 generally understood which Kant gives as the First Analogy 
 of Experience : in all the changes of phenomena the substance 
 is permanent, and its quantity in Nature is neither increased 
 nor diminished. 
 
 The scientific evidence upon which the persistence of mass 
 rests is, first, the verifiability of mechanical calculations made 
 upon that assumption ; and secondly, the results of chemical 
 analysis and synthesis. And upon this basis the more positive 
 minds are sometimes content to rest the ancient principle 
 of the permanence of substance, or the persistence or conser- 
 vation of matter, as an universal truth or axiom. But recent 
 speculation as to the nature of atoms has tended to undermine 
 the position, by attempting to resolve atoms into some condi- 
 tion of the ether ; and plainly if atoms are in any way formed 
 out of ether, and by parity of reason may return into it, the 
 principle of persistence cannot be maintained with reference 
 to the number of atoms in the world ; nor could chemical or 
 mechanical investigations be appealed to as disproving the 
 increase or decrease of mass, since measurements are confessedly 
 imperfect, and addition or subtraction of atoms might take place 
 so slowly or in such remote parts of the universe as to escape 
 detection. 
 
 This is a physical question which physical inquiry must 
 determine by the appropriate methods ; but there is a manifest 
 speculative interest in the position that atoms and ether are not 
 everlastingly distinct modes of existence. How else can the 
 impulse to generalise to the utmost be satisfied ? And should 
 it be established, although the empirical evidence for the 
 persistence of matter may be impaired, the principle (we may 
 be sure) will not be abandoned : it will be extended from the 
 mass of the world, or the number of atoms, to the sum of atoms 
 and ether. 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXPERIENCE 139 
 
 Kant observes that, in all ages, not only the philosopher 
 bub even the popular understanding has assumed the per- 
 manence of a substratum amidst all changes of phenomena. 
 He does not mention the evidence he had for the popularity of 
 the belief, and probably many of us could tell amusing stories 
 of men who were far from believing it ; but it is remarkable 
 how easily the notion is grasped as soon as it is explained. 
 Primitive genesis-myths assume something original by which 
 the present world was begotten, hatched, or otherwise produced. 
 All the Ionic cosmologies based on the transmutability of the 
 elements, manifestly assume the permanence of the whole, and 
 even perhaps of a substratum (as Kant says) in the sense that 
 one of the elements — water, air, fire — is regarded as primordial 
 and essential, — a notion that grows especially clear in Anaxi- 
 mander's aireipov. Heracleitus gives the doctrine quantitative 
 expression : " This order, which is the same in all things, no 
 one of gods or men has made, but it was ever, is now, and 
 ever shall be an everlasting Fire, fixed measures of it kindling 
 and fixed measures of it going out" (Fr. 20, Burnet's trans- 
 lation). Still, as the exact measurement of ' Fire ' is not an 
 easy thing to conceive of, it is to the Atomists that we usually 
 trace the modern conception of the persistence of matter. 
 
 But, says Kant, no one has attempted to prove this pro- 
 position ; and, indeed, his own proof is such as might deter 
 others from attempting any. Time, according to him, is a 
 permanent form of intuition, but cannot be itself perceived. 
 Consequently in perceptions or phenomena there must be a 
 substratum representing time in general, so that every change 
 or co-existence can be perceived in the act of cognition by the 
 relation of phenomena to such substratum. This is Substance 
 {Analogien der Erfahrung — A). The derivation of the per- 
 manence of substance, then, depends on Kant's peculiar tenets : 
 first, that time is a priori whilst phenomena are empirical ; so 
 that their order can only be interpreted in relation to time : 
 secondly, that change can only be conceived in contrast with 
 something permanent. But it is better to regard the order 
 of phenomena and the cognition of time as emerging correl- 
 atively ; and our belief both in the infinity of time and in 
 
140 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 the everlastingness of the world, as arising from our inex- 
 perience of any limit, and from the difficulty of conceiving any 
 end, break, or loss, in the regress or progress of changes ; and 
 this belongs to Causation rather than to Substance so far as 
 these can be distinguished. And for the perception of change, 
 it is enough that phenomena themselves should change at 
 different rates, some being relatively permanent ; and such is 
 our experience. And hence time is not permanent, and 
 cannot be so conceived except by confounding it with the 
 spatial representation of a line ; which is merely a device for 
 calculation, for chronology, or for picturing memories in a vista, 
 because space is the more vivid and definite form of perception. 
 Hamilton identifies the permanence of Substance with the 
 principle of Causality, and goes on to deduce it from " the 
 imbecility of the human mind " which results in the law of 
 the Conditioned. Hence an increase or decrease in the totality 
 of existence cannot be " construed in thought" {Metaphysics, 
 38, 40). '\A1ien Spencer began to write on Metaphysics he 
 was a good deal influenced by Hamilton, and adapted a priori 
 arguments to his own theory of mental evolution. " Our 
 conception of Matter," he says {First Principiles, § 48), " reduced 
 to its simplest shape, is that of co-existent positions that offer 
 resistance, as contrasted with our conception of Space, in which 
 the co-existent positions offer no resistance." And the inde- 
 structibility of Matter is a datum of consciousness ; for 
 " conceive Space to be cleared of all bodies save one. Now 
 imagine the remaining one not to be removed from its place, 
 but to lapse into nothing whilst standing in that place. You 
 fail. The space which was solid you cannot conceive becoming 
 empty, save by transfer of that which made it solid." This 
 results from the nature of thought as consisting in the 
 establishment of relations ; there can be no relation nor thought 
 " when one of the related terms is absent from consciousness. 
 Hence it is impossible to think of something becoming nothing, 
 for the same reason that it is impossible to think of nothing 
 becoming something — the reason, namely, that nothing cannot 
 become an object of consciousness " (§ 53). Such necessities 
 of thought have been rendered organic by immense accumula- 
 
SUBSTANCE TN EXPERIENCE 141 
 
 tious of experieuces, received partly by the individual, but 
 mainly by all ancestral individuals whose nervous systems he 
 inherits (§ 54, note, referring to Fsych. §§ 426-433). 
 
 To these arguments it may be replied, (1) that when 
 challenged to imagine a body disappearing without being 
 removed, I do not fail. To imagine a disappearance is possible, 
 because it sometimes occurs in perception. To conceive it 
 with belief is, indeed, impossible, because it is in contradiction 
 with well-established concepts. But as Hamilton incon- 
 sistently says, " it is not competent to argue that what cannot 
 be comprehended as possible by us is impossible in reality " ; 
 and the validity of concepts depends partly upon the quantity 
 of experience they represent, partly upon the method of their 
 framing. (2) That the disappearance of a body is not in- 
 compatible with relational thought, since what remains is not 
 " nothing " but the space the body occupied, which is as 
 positive an object of experience as the body itself was. (3) 
 That the appeal to ancestral experience is inconsistent with 
 the demand to be judged by " disciplined thought " ; for this 
 has only been attainable during two or three generations ; and 
 two or three generations must be admitted to count for hardly 
 anything in comparison with our infinite lines of loose-thinking 
 ancestors. In fact, the inductive evidence indicated by Mr. 
 Spencer in § 5 2 (which might be indefinitely extended) is the 
 means of disciplining thought, rendering the belief definite and 
 the contrary truly inconceivable according to the analogy of 
 experience, though far from unimaginable. 
 
 Still, when the indestructibility of Matter is first proposed 
 to a boy, although the doctrine may be surprising, a little 
 explanation makes it readily conceivable and a thing to be 
 believed as a matter of course ; so that an hereditary predis- 
 position to understand and accept it may reasonably be assumed 
 to exist ; and such a predisposition needs to be accounted for. 
 
 The aspect of most things in Nature is relatively static 
 and permanent : the ground under our feet, the distant hills^ 
 forests and watercourses. When increase or diminution takes 
 place, some conditions are usually obvious, as that the swelling 
 of streams and growth of plants depend upon rain, that the 
 
142 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 growth of animals depends upon food. The chief contrary 
 experiences are evaporation and certain meteoric phenomena ; 
 but as soon as men lit fires it became possible to interpret 
 evaporation and the dispersal of clouds by analogy with smoke ; 
 lio-htning and shooting-stars were like the hurling of brands. 
 These dumb suggestions became more intelligible with the rise 
 of industries. In the shaping of arrow-heads or clubs, they 
 grew lighter ; but chips strewed the ground, and showed that 
 alteration of form was not a destruction of material. The 
 cares of a pastoral or agricultural life drew closer attention to 
 the conditions of growth and destruction. Building impressed 
 the belief that the construction of a new body needs the con- 
 sumption of materials. Building and the division of land 
 gave rise to the arts of measurement ; and commerce to definite 
 ideas of the measurement of all things. We may trace this 
 in another aphorism of Heracleitus closely connected with that 
 above quoted : " All things are exchanged for fire, and fire 
 for all things; as wares are exchanged for gold, and gold 
 for wares " : cf. Fr. 29, in which to exceed measure is regarded 
 as injustice. 
 
 Whilst, however, experience of Nature and of human 
 economy may explain the predisposition to understand the 
 permanence, transmutability, and measurability of things, yet 
 the permanence of Substance amidst all changes, considered 
 as a scientific postulate, depends upon something else and 
 still more primitive, namely, the growth of all relational 
 consciousness by discrimination and assimilation. To be dealt 
 with, all things must be discriminated; but they must be 
 assimilated to be understood. Hence it is an accepted doctrine 
 that the explanation of Nature consists in discovering the 
 resemblances of phenomena; and the most exact resemblance 
 is equality of magnitudes. It follows that Nature cannot be 
 intelligible unless amidst all changes exact equality is traceable 
 in the fundamental properties of matter or substance. The 
 conception, therefore, is employed in all investigation, and 
 methodical investigation defines and justifies the conception. 
 
 That the permanence of Substance must be an universal 
 truth because our understanding needs it and our narrow 
 
SUBSTANCE IN EXPERIENCE 143 
 
 experience does not contradict it, may seem too great a claim 
 to be made by creatures whoso sublimest discoveries have 
 taught them their physical insiguiticauce. liut as laws of 
 Nature are established in ever greater numbers and in ever 
 throwing harmony, and are confirmed by success in applying 
 them to the arts on which our life securely builds, belief in 
 the first postulate of concrete science will certainly increase 
 in strength ; unless there be reason to suspect that the portion 
 of the universe within the range of investigation is not a fair 
 sample of the whole. At any rate the belief rests not on 
 " the imbecility of the human mind," but springs from the 
 function that has created science and made possible the reign 
 of Man. 
 
CHAPTER VIII 
 
 ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 
 
 § 1. The belief in Substance is immanent in Empirical Reality 
 and the concept of it has a place in popular understanding. 
 But we have seen that reflective examination of the empirical 
 notion leads to an ontological hypothesis concerning trans- 
 cendent Substance, and we must review the various forms 
 which this hypothesis has taken ; forms which are nearly all 
 of them still living, not merely fossil; though it may often 
 seem to the student of Metaphysics as if, amidst familiar 
 species of the modern world, he was confronted in some dark 
 jungle with monsters of the Jurassic Age. 
 
 Bodies perceived in relative rest or motion, and popularly 
 taken to be substantial, differ in many ways, and differences of 
 cohesion and specific gravity are amongst the most obvious 
 and general. Hence, very early, earth, water, air, and fire 
 were discriminated as the four elements ; and the first impulse 
 of the philosophic instinct amongst the Greeks, when they 
 attempted to explain the nature of the World, was to adopt 
 this distinction of elements and try to find some common 
 ground to which all might be reducible. Some surmised 
 that one or another element was primordial, and that the rest 
 were modifications of it by condensation and rarefaction. 
 Anaximander suggested a boundless something that was not 
 any one of the elements, but an indefinite totality out of 
 which they all arose and into which they all relapsed. After 
 a time, the conception of atoms was reached : minute, invisible 
 bodies, infinite in number, of various but definite size, shape 
 and weight ; being themselves none of the four elements, 
 
 144 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 145 
 
 but in their ever-changing combinations giving birth to 
 the elements and to all particular things. Then with the 
 increasing tendency to abstraction came the notion of a certain 
 characterless condition of things, itself without form or quality 
 {vXrj, uTTOKetfiivov), which might be supposed to subsist in or 
 underlie whatever has form or manifestation. 
 
 Now although, before this last stage was arrived at, a 
 change had come in the positing of the problem, yet all these 
 doctrines might have been the direct result of what may be 
 called inductive reflection, a serious thinking about the facts 
 without methodical analysis or experiment. They represent 
 an enterprising but necessarily crude inquiry in Physics, 
 Chemistry, or " Natural Philosophy," and do not partake of 
 the characteristic difiiculties of the metaphysics of Substance. 
 These are due to that change in the positing of the philo- 
 sophical problem that followed the attempt to construct a Theory 
 of Knowledge. 
 
 In the Theory of Knowledge there are two capital investi- 
 gations — by no means separable but convenient to distinguish — 
 into (1) the possibility of Perception, and (2) the possibility 
 of Science. The first may be traced to Democritus (or 
 Leucippus), the second to Plato, and both issue in speculations 
 that render the notion of Substance ever more and more 
 obscure and mysterious. In offering some preliminary 
 remarks upon the positions of these philosophers, it will fall 
 in best with the plan of this chapter if we violate chronology 
 and begin with Plato. 
 
 Plato's inquiry into the possibility of Science starts from 
 the conception of Science itself as universal and necessary 
 Knowledge ; such, therefore, as cannot, he thought, be 
 obtained from Empirical Eeality, considered (according to 
 the insight of Heracleitus) as subject to perpetual change. 
 Another region of things must exist as the object of Science ; 
 a region of things changeless and eternal : Ideas visible to 
 the mind, not to the senses, which nevertheless are the true 
 natures and the causes of all objects of perception according 
 to their kinds. A knowledge of the Idea, because it is one, 
 must be universal ; and necessary, because it is unchangeable : 
 
 10 
 
146 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 and such knowledge is the only means of interpreting 
 Empirical Reality. These Ideas corresponded to the Defini- 
 tions sought by Socrates ; and in the earlier of Plato's dialogues 
 in which the theory occurs, they are a comprehensive collection, 
 natural and artificial, substantive and relational ; from which, 
 in his later reflections, what Mill terms ' Natural Kinds ' seem 
 to have emerged as the most important. Plato, however, 
 never succeeds in explaining the dialectic method by which 
 these Ideas are to be discovered, nor their relations to one 
 another, nor to the objects of perception and opinion ; and, in 
 fact, in the first part of the Farmenides, he is much more 
 successful in demonstrating the impossibility of his own theory 
 than he is in the Fhccdrus, Republic, or Phcedo, where he 
 endeavours to explain it. In his most ambitious constructions, 
 he has recourse to parables of a glorified Animism, the earliest 
 hypothesis of the human mind, upon which it always falls 
 back with relief when fatigued and perplexed by speculation. 
 So far as his positive conceptions are traceable he seems to 
 have held in the later phases of his philosophy, that the Ideas, 
 as objects and conditions of scientific thought and paradigms 
 of Nature, are themselves thoughts of the avro^Mov, itself the 
 supreme Idea {Tiin. 30, 31 and 52a); and this doctrine 
 was developed by the Neo-Platonists, and has been recast by 
 Hegel and his followers. The theory of Ideas was a state- 
 ment of what is demanded by a certain conception of Science ; 
 a conception overstrained and erroneous. Kant pursued the 
 same method, with results that are much more like Plato's 
 than a hurried reader is apt to perceive. But we cannot help 
 being astonished at the precocious audacity of Plato's philo- 
 sophical instinct in demanding universal and necessary 
 knowledge of the whole universe, when as yet no science 
 existed but a little elementary Arithmetic and Geometry. 
 From them the conception was derived ; and yet they were 
 regarded as an inferior kind of knowledge, compared with the 
 divine comprehension that would be attainable by a dialec- 
 tical intercourse with Ideas. 
 
 Elementary Mathematics also perhaps determined the 
 statical way in which the Ideas were generally taken, for 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WOKLD 147 
 
 numbers and figures were amongst the Ideas. It is true that, 
 in the Philehus and Sophistes, Plato came to describe the 
 Ideas (Cause or Being) as living, rational, and active ; but 
 these conceptions are obscure, and incoherent with the rest 
 of his doctrine. It is true, again, that he saw the need and 
 the possibility of Dynamics, a pure science of Motion (for so I 
 interpret his account of Astronomy in the Repuhlic, 529-30): 
 but he never followed this indication. Had he been able to 
 do so, he might have found that the true character of Ideas, 
 as interpreters of the world of birth and change, is to be 
 Universals (or Laws) of process : thereby avoiding the diffi- 
 culty of connecting unchangeable Ideas with the Heracleitan 
 flux of phenomena. 
 
 However, we are here chiefly concerned with the ontological 
 consequences of the Ideal Theory ; and we observe that it re- 
 gards the truth of Being (or Substance, ovcrLa) as (1), in a 
 vague sense, the cause of Empirical Reality; whilst (2) it is 
 divorced from that Reality, as having another nature. Such 
 is Aristotle's interpretation, the justice of which is much 
 disputed ; and a history of the theory must discuss this question 
 at length. But, again, om- concern is with the opinions of 
 philosophers, or with opinions ascribed to them, only so far as 
 they have had an important influence upon the course of 
 classical thought ; and it will hardly be denied that the 
 Platonic Ideas have, until recently, had most effect upon 
 speculation according to this way of understanding them — the 
 Scholastic universalia ante rem. 
 
 The hypothesis of Democritus concerning Atoms necessarily 
 demanded a theory of Perception. For the atoms themselves 
 were invisible and intangible and differed from one another 
 only in shape, size, weight (proportionate to size) and position. 
 Objects of perception are formed of tangible groups of atoms, 
 from which some atoms emanating affect the soul (itself consist- 
 ing of the finer sort of atoms) ; and thence arise sensible heat, 
 colour, sound, smell, taste, in short the secondary qualities ; 
 whereas in the atoms and groups of atoms only the primary 
 qualities are present. We perceive things, therefore, not as 
 they really are, except perhaps in a gross way by touch, but 
 
148 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 by a subjective representation which is entirely deceptive ; 
 though the real nature of things may be discovered by reason- 
 ing as distinct from sense-perception. 
 
 Now this fascinating paradox has haunted physical and 
 metaphysical inquiry ever since ; has been more prolific of 
 hypotheses than even the theory of Ideas ; has become so 
 familiar that many thinkers take it for granted, as an ultimate 
 fact, and as if the only business of speculation must be to 
 shape a theory agreeing with it. 
 
 We may distinguish four principal doctrines concerning 
 Substance which proceed from the Democritan theory of 
 Perception : Materialism, Hypothetical Eealism (as Hamilton 
 calls it), Subjective Idealism, and Nihilism. 
 
 § 2. Materialism holds that the world of Atoms with their 
 primary qualities and motions, is the only real world ; that it 
 would exist much as it is now, if the finer atoms in animal 
 bodies (nervous system) had no consciousness ; that all sub- 
 jective phenomena, including the secondary qualities of bodies, 
 are relative, transient and non-essential — in Hobbes' words, 
 " as striking the eye makes us fancy a light." 
 
 The radical error of Materialism is to assume that scientific 
 theories are ontological doctrines. Hence three fallacies : (1) to 
 regard that gTeat mass of experience which consists in the 
 secondary qualities of bodies as relatively unreal, though it 
 comprises most of the data upon which scientific analyses are 
 founded; (2) to disparage consciousness and thought, as a 
 function of the brain, or epiphenomenon, though it is the very 
 seat of science ; and (3) to treat the remainder of Empirical 
 Eeality, the primary qualities of the object, together with the 
 conceptual interpretation of it in terms of atoms and ether, 
 as having independent Eeality ; though it is manifestly un- 
 known except as object of a Subject, that is, as a phenomenon. 
 
 The plausibility of Materialism has been greatly extended 
 in modern times by the theory of gravitation, which has taken 
 the place of the Epicurean clinamen ; by proofs of the persist- 
 ence of matter and energy, giving definiteness to the ancient 
 ex nihilo nihil ; by the physiological researches that have 
 discovered the chemical character of many vital processes, and 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 149 
 
 have on the whole streugthened the hypothesis that the animal 
 body is an automaton independent of consciousness ; and by 
 the explanation that Natural Selection gives of the appearances 
 of design in Nature. 
 
 On the other hand, the ontological significance of these 
 discoveries has been unexpectedly weakened by the theory of 
 Natiu-al Selection. For it is a leading idea of that theory that 
 every property of organic life is acquired and developed for 
 its usefulness ; and this condition must apply to consciousness, 
 if consciousness is acquired ; since it not only accompanies 
 animal life (at least) but increases and develops step by step 
 with the progress of organisation. 
 
 Now, if consciousness, as such, is useful, it must be a 
 vehicle or mode of energy correlated with the physical forces, 
 and therefore a reality in the same sense as they are. But if 
 it is not useful, it must be necessary or essential ; that is to 
 say, it must be not an acquired attribute but inherent in Nature, 
 and must appear in its organic form when organised animals 
 appear, as a matter of course and because it cannot be other- 
 wise. Whether, then, consciousness is a mode of energy 
 correlated with the physical forces, and therefore capable of 
 intervening in animal activities, is an all-important question. 
 If it is not, and if all animal activities admit of a purely 
 physiological explanation, consciousness cannot be regarded as 
 an effect of organic matter and energy ; because all the efficacy 
 of physical energy (outward stimulus and inward potential) is 
 absorbed in physical activities and their consequences in the 
 environment. This is precisely why consciousness has been called 
 an epiphenomenon, because the physical, chemical, and bio- 
 logical laws that explain phenomena, have not the slightest 
 hold upon it. But to consciousness, as to anything else, the 
 principle ex nihilo nihil and the Law of Continuity apply. 
 Unless then, these principles be abandoned, consciousness must 
 be regarded as a continuum self-generated and self-perpetuative 
 from everlasting to everlasting. But if consciousness be a 
 mode of energy, though it must then be real in the same sense 
 as physical heat and light are, yet it is, like them, material, 
 and it is conditional in its manifestations ; and therefore 
 
150 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 conceivably its realisation may be interrupted ; it may be 
 for vast periods of time non-existent, if the conditions of its 
 manifestation nowhere exist. In short, to establish Materialism, 
 the one requisite is, to show that consciousness absorbs, trans- 
 mits, or propagates energy. 
 
 To me, certainly, it seems next to nonsense, or next after 
 nonsense, to speak of consciousness as possibly a mode of 
 physical energy ; and it is as useless to identify it with the 
 ether as with molecular nervous structures. How, in fact, 
 do such notions differ from those of Epicurus, who thought 
 the soul consisted of the finer sort of atoms ; or from those of 
 the Stoics, who said it was a kind of fire ? 
 
 § 3. Hypothetical Realism differs from Materialism (as I 
 understand it) chiefly in two ways: (1) the Materialist holds 
 that we perceive things as they really exist (at least in their 
 primary qualities), whereas the Hypothetical Eealist says that 
 even in the primary qualities we perceive only signs or re- 
 presentations of the true Reality. (2) The Materialist holds 
 that perception arises from the interaction of the inorganic 
 world and organic (animal) bodies, both being of the same 
 substance ; whereas the Hypothetical Realist regards perception 
 as due indeed to some stimulus from the material world, but 
 as essentially depending upon the reciprocal activity of a 
 Subject, soul or spirit, w^hose nature it is to perceive and know ; 
 and therefore he believes in two substances, a material and a 
 spiritual. 
 
 As to what is the object of perception, the thing 
 perceived. Hypothetical Realists are not agreed. Locke, e.g., 
 appears to have held that it was a tertium quid between mind 
 and matter ; for he speaks of abstract material substance as 
 something of which we have only a confused idea ; whilst 
 particular substances (or things) exist in such a way that their 
 primary qualities belong to them whether we perceive them 
 or not ; and of these particular things we obtain ideas by 
 sensation. He thus recognises four factors in perception, — 
 Material Substance, Things, Ideas, Spirits (FssaT/ concerning 
 Human Understanding, Book II. chap, xxiii.). 
 
 Malebranche, again, thought that the Cartesian distinction 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 151 
 
 between Mind and Matter (Thought and Extension) made 
 any intercourse between the two impossiVjle ; that the material 
 world, thougli it exists as created, is incapable of stimulating 
 a mind to perceive it ; but that what we perceive is the ideas 
 of the world in God, by means of sensations (joined to the 
 ideas) which He causes in us on the occasion of objects being 
 present {Recherche de la V., Bk. IIL Pt. II. ch. vi.). This is 
 what Malebranche calls " seeing all things in God " ; but he 
 should rather have said " understanding them there." For so 
 far as perception is sensible, it is not in God, but caused by 
 Him in us ; whereupon the idea, which we know in God, 
 interprets the thing to us according to its kind. 
 
 If the ideas in God are supposed to be distinct from our 
 own, they constitute a sort of tertium quid, in as much as 
 they are neither material things nor our ideas, though allied 
 to our ideas, as beings also of intelligible, though more perfect 
 nature. But perhaps Malebranche's view rather is, that the 
 ideas of things in God are also our own by a limited 
 participation — God being the place both of ideas and of 
 spirits — a mystical doctrine which he pretends not to explain : 
 neither do I. 
 
 To take another example : there can be no question that 
 in Kant's view the thing perceived is a modification of our 
 own minds, being constructed out of sensations by the 
 imagination according to the forms of intuition and 
 understanding. As for the sensations, they are due to the 
 stimulus of some apparently alien condition, the Ding an sich ; 
 which, however, it is suggested may have the same source as 
 Reason ; and so it must in order to satisfy Kant's ethics. 
 Now, although Substance, according to the system of the 
 K d. r. v., is a category applicable only to phenomena, yet in 
 the second edition, at least, the Ding an sich is either Substance 
 or nothing at all ; and Kant is very anxious that it shall not 
 be nothing at all. In fact it is much like Locke's abstract 
 Substance. 
 
 Every one knows how useless the notion of Substance is 
 to the Hypothetical Realists. Malebranche received it as a 
 burden laid upon him by the first chapter of Genesis : he had 
 
152 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 no use for it. In other systems, where Substance is a mere X 
 without assignable quality or character, it can resemble 
 nothing in experience, and therefore can explain nothing. 
 Perhaps, however, one character is always ascribed to Substance, 
 namely, perdurability ; and this is felt to be important, as 
 corresponding with the continuity of the empirical World in 
 past and future time, or during the sleep or absence of the 
 empirical Subject. Still, such perdurability is of little avail 
 unless some connection can be indicated between the supposed 
 substance and the qualities of actual bodies ; and all the 
 terms once in use for suggesting the relation proposed, such as 
 " support," " underlie," " inhere," " depend," are undisguisable 
 metaphors. In Mill's opinion the notion of substance is 
 partly due to our supposing that something must exist, 
 related to the primary qualities of bodies in a way analogous 
 to that in which the primary stand to the secondary. As the 
 secondary qualities stand to the primary so do the primary 
 to X — is a plausible adaptation of the " rule of three." But X 
 remains a blank qucesitum. The form of inference is unful- 
 filled ; for whilst the relation of secondary to primary 
 qualities can be determined as a matter of fact by induction, 
 to find the relation of the primary qualities to X we are left 
 groping about in the emptiness of pure reason. 
 
 In this situation it is natural to the natural man to try 
 to reduce Substance to Cause ; and formerly the attempt was 
 excusable, so easily current was the word Cause, and so desti- 
 tute of precise meaning. But the excuse no longer exists : 
 for — 
 
 (1) On any view of the grounds of the law of Causation, 
 whether Humean, Kantian, or evolutionary, Causation is a 
 category of experience, and to apply it to X is to make a 
 transcendent use of it. 
 
 (2) Causation is the explanation of events, and neither 
 substance nor quality is an event ; in other words, Causation 
 involves a series in time and the relation of Substance and 
 Attribute does not. 
 
 (3) Again, every Cause is absorbed in its Effect; but 
 Substance is not absorbed by its Attributes. 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 153 
 
 (4) The Cause is quantitatively equal to the Effect ; but 
 no quantitative relation between Substance and Attriljute is 
 intelligible. 
 
 (5) Causation implies the reciprocity of co-existing 
 empirical substances or agents, as localised groups of interfused 
 qualities : it cannot, therefore, explain the origin of such groups 
 of qualities, nor the reciprocity obtaining between them. 
 
 The inapplicability of Cause and Effect — a category of the 
 synthesis of phenomena — to the case of Eeality and Pheno- 
 menon was insisted on by Schopenhauer. 
 
 Still, the notion of perdurable transcendent Substance has 
 a function of its own in giving coherence to the system of 
 experience. As a refuge from Solipsism and Nihilism, it is 
 ancient, popular, and classical ; and the modern academic outcry 
 against the Ding an sich is hysterical. Taking consciousness 
 to be immediate Reality, does it express or comprise the whole 
 of Reality ? If not, the remainder of Reality is not in 
 consciousness but is manifested in consciousness by phenomena. 
 The relation of Substance and Attribute is the same as 
 Noumenon and Phenomenon, and accordingly Kant calls the 
 unconditioned world the cosmological Idea. But these 
 relations are incurably static and otiose ; and therefore it may 
 be better to name a new Category — Manifestation (" Objecti- 
 vation," Schopenhauer called it) — and to recognise fully its 
 one-sided character. It stands for a relation of which there 
 is only one term in experience : it is therefore an Imperfect 
 Category, not constitutive but only indicative or orectic ; for 
 the other term, lying beyond experience, is inapprehensible. 
 But I think it reasonable (as shown in Chap. VII. § 5) to 
 transfer to the transcendent term some of the forms of sub- 
 jective Reality, if not also those of phenomena in space. 
 
 Let us first see whether there is not some other way of 
 interpreting Substance which may make my hypothesis 
 superfluous. 
 
 § 4. Subjective Idealism — the doctrine that, since whatever 
 we directly know is reducible to ideas (percepts or images), the 
 world consists entirely of Spirits and their ideas — follows 
 very naturally upon the recognition of the otiose and 
 
154 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 ineffective character of X, the abstract Substance of Hypothetic 
 Eealism. Some critics suppose that Berkeley, the founder of 
 Subjective Idealism, derived the doctrine from Malebranche, his 
 senior contemporary, in whose theory Matter is most otiose 
 and superfluous. But it seems a juster view that Berkeley 
 proceeded from Locke, rejecting the " confused notion of Sub- 
 stance," which Locke had done much to discredit, and developing 
 an hypothesis of the world as perceived, according to his own 
 view of the impossibility of abstract ideas. 
 
 It is needless nowadays to explain that by ' ideas ' Berkeley, 
 following Locke, meant " whatever is the object of the mind," 
 and therefore sensations and perceptions (contrary to the use 
 of Malebranche) as well as images or representations of memory, 
 imagination, reason ; though the overlooking of his meaning, 
 carefully explained by Berkeley, and obvious to every one who 
 studies systems in their historical context, has misled innumer- 
 able critics, not only Dr. Johnson but even Kant. Natural 
 objects, such as cherry trees, are percepts (or ideas) ; they are 
 objects of a mind : a perceiving mind is essential to the 
 existence of things perceived ; whose esse is percipi ; and to 
 attempt to think of them as not perceived is to try to frame 
 an abstract idea : which is impossible. By means of images, 
 words, or signs, taken in a representative way, general thinking 
 is possible, but not abstract thinking, as Locke had supposed. 
 We can never separate in thought what may not possibly exist 
 separately : a percept cannot exist without a percipient, and 
 therefore cannot be thought to do so : it implies a contradiction. 
 We cannot consider objects of the mind as even resembling 
 things that are not objects of the mind : only an idea can be 
 like an idea: colour cannot be like something invisible. A 
 material substratum, without qualities and imperceivable, is the 
 most monstrous and contradictory abstraction of all. 
 
 But besides ideas there are spirits. A spirit is a perceiving 
 active being " entirely distinct from ideas." Ideas depend upon 
 a perceiving mind or spirit ; and as they only exist as per- 
 ceived, we know all that they contain ; and we do not perceive 
 in them any power. They are passive and inert, and therefore 
 we can have no idea of a spirit, but only a sort of notion got 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 155 
 
 by intuition, or reflection upon our own thinking and activity. 
 All power resides in spirits : " I have no notion of any action 
 distinct from volition," nor of volition except in a spirit {Hyl. 
 and Phil. iii.). 
 
 Ideas in the narrow sense, those of memory and imagina- 
 tion, are under my control ; but those of sensation, dis- 
 tinguished by greater vividness and by a certain unalterable 
 order, are not. These latter " have an existence exterior to my 
 mind, since I find them by experience to be independent of it." 
 They cannot be caused by the supposed ' Matter,' for that is 
 inert (such was the prevalent belief), and, moreover, has no 
 ideas to communicate. Yet they exist in the intervals when 
 I do not perceive them, preceded my birth and would survive 
 my annihilation. And all finite spirits are in the same case 
 in relation to such ideas. They must therefore be known to 
 an omnipresent eternal Mind. Such a mind cannot be known 
 to us by an inert idea, but only by a notion " obtained by 
 reflecting on my own soul, heightening its powers and removing 
 its imperfections." For God is of infinite power, creates and 
 upholds the world, and presents it to our perception. Not 
 that it is present to Him sensibly as it is to us ; but " there is 
 a twofold state of things, the one ectypal or natural, the other 
 archetypal and eternal The former was created in time" 
 [made perceivable to finite minds — angels] ; " the latter existed 
 from everlasting in the mind of God " {Hyl. and Phil. iii.). 
 
 It thus appears that Berkeley acknowledged the need of a 
 perdurable Substance corresponding with the continuity of 
 Physical Eeality, but found this in the Theological Idea and 
 could dispense with the cosmological. The hypothesis is com- 
 plicated by archetypal Ideas, merely taken for granted ; and by 
 the relation of these to the ectypal, which, whether by imitation 
 or participation, introduces all the controversy concerning the 
 universalia ante rem. I fear, too, he ought to have seen that 
 a mind without sensibility is an impossible abstract idea. 
 But were the divine ideas sensible and qualitatively the same_ 
 as ours, yet their existence would not help the problem of ex- 
 ternal perception ; for, as Mill says, the divine ideas are not 
 identical with those of a finite mind, and cannot constitute or 
 
156 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 sustain my world. And, finally, spirits are not only perceiving 
 but active ; they are agents : their whole being is not expressed 
 in perceiving or knowing ; for ideas cannot be like a power, 
 nor can a " notion " we have of it. A notion of our activity is 
 not itself that activity. The power of God is a separate thing 
 from the natural World in time and in consciousness. Con- 
 sciousness, then, is not power ; the consciousness of power is 
 not power ; there is something more than consciousness in 
 Berkeley's ultimate Being. 
 
 § 5. Nihilism is the doctrine that there is no Substance of 
 either matter or mind, that perceptions and ideas are the only 
 realities. To ascribe this position to Hume is an unwarrant- 
 able grafting of a dogma upon his scepticism. Some oriental 
 scholars tell us that Nihilism is to be found in the metaphysics 
 of Buddhism ; but Karma, the synthetic principle of the world, 
 according to that philosophy, a sort of mystical causation allied 
 to Nemesis, implies that in Keality there is something else 
 than consciousness. Again, Mill's Psychological Theory of an 
 External World, expounded in his Examination of Hamilton's 
 Philosophy (chap. xi. and Appendix to chap, xii.), has this in 
 common with Nihilism, that it attempts to restate the doctrine 
 of Subjective Idealism without Berkeley's theological hypothesis. 
 Mill undertakes to show that the belief in an external World 
 is not intuitive but acquired, if it be granted (1) that the 
 human mind is capable of expectation, and that the Laws of 
 Association describe the course of its ideas ; and (2) that in 
 Nature sensations occur in uniform orders simultaneous and 
 successive. The belief to he explained is, that things exist 
 when unperceived and unthought of, and even before being 
 known either by ourselves or others, and would exist if we were 
 all annihilated, and that there is something perdurable and 
 independent of us, which is moreover a sort of substratum and 
 cause of our sensations. 
 
 The first instructive experience is that when some sensa- 
 tions are actual others are possible, namely, those obtainable in 
 the next room and in all parts of the world ; and these are 
 generally far more important to me than my present actual 
 sensations. Then, every particular object presents the same 
 
ONTOLOGY OF TliP: WORLD 157 
 
 contrast : it is a group of sensations, sonic actual, otliers pos- 
 sible. If the sensation of colour is actual, resistance is possible ; 
 so that there arises the notion of a permanent background or 
 substratum to any actual experience. Call this group a thing, 
 instead of a group of sensations, and we easily imagine it is 
 something else than sensations. Again, sensations have laws 
 of recurrence ; but the most important of all laws. Causation, 
 prevails, chietly, amongst not the actual but the possible 
 sensations, effecting changes in them and consequently in our 
 actual sensations. If the changes occur in our absence we have 
 different sensations on returning, and we learn to expect such 
 changes according to laws. Distribution of things in place is less 
 regular than causation, but it is definite ; any absent thing or 
 group of sensations (say, a chair in the next room) can only be 
 realised by going through certain definite series of sensations. 
 Such law and order is independent of our will ; therefore the 
 possibilities of sensation are believed to be independent of us. 
 The possibilities and the order of them are the same for us and 
 for other minds ; therefore they are external to us. Finally, 
 the notion of Matter as something dilt'ering from and underlying 
 all series and groups of sensations, is generated by our conceiv- 
 ing, negatively, something which differs from all experience as 
 the elements of experience differ from one another, and which 
 stands in the background of all sensations as the possible 
 sensations underlie the actual. Thus we inevitably grow up 
 in the belief that there is something permanent, independent, 
 external, unlike all sense-experience and yet the ground and 
 cause of that experience and its laws. 
 
 Remembering the state of Psychology when Mill wrote, it 
 will be admitted that his theory was well-reasoned : some- 
 thing closely allied to it was accepted by Bain, Huxley and 
 others. Bain, indeed, in his Life of J. S. Mill (chap. iv. ; cf. 
 Senses arid Intellect, "Intellect," chap. i. § 38), says that more 
 stress should have been laid upon the sense of resistance 
 as fundamental in our objective consciousness, and upon the 
 fact of the object being common to others as proving its 
 independence of ourselves. He also explains the importance 
 of the definite changes which sensations of sight, hearing, etc., 
 
158 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 undergo according to our own movements : in strong contrast 
 with the relation between our movements and subjective 
 feeUngs. It should also, I think, be pointed out that the 
 connection between our own mind and one sensation-group 
 (our body), being transferred by analogy (whether justifiably 
 or not) to other sensation-groups, saves the notion of Matter, 
 as something differing from and underlying all groups 
 and series of sensations, from being entirely negative. Mill's 
 assumption that our most profound forms of cognition can be 
 explained by conscious experience, allowing nothing for organic 
 inheritance and growth, is merely a clue to the date of 
 his book. 
 
 But it will be observed that Mill's original purpose was 
 to give a merely psychological account of external perception 
 — an analysis of the behef in an external World, and of how 
 that belief is arrived at ; and had that been the whole result, 
 his doctrine could hardly have figured in our present ontological 
 investigation. He would have repudiated Ontology as a 
 delusive place of spectres ; but that many of his readers took 
 the " possibilities of sensation " in an ontological sense, is 
 plain from the criticisms they published ; and I think their 
 misapprehension modified Mill's own conception of his theory. 
 For in the Appendix to chap. xii. he writes, that almost 
 all philosophers are agreed " that Substance need only be 
 postulated as a support for phenomena, or as a bond of 
 connection to hold a group or series of otherwise unconnected 
 phenomena together : let us only then think away the support, 
 and suppose the phenomena to remain, and to be held 
 together in the same groups and series by some other agency, 
 or without any agency but an internal law, and every con- 
 sequence follows without Substance, for the sake of which 
 Substance was assumed." In this passage " some other agency " 
 might be the Divine Mind, as in Berkeley's theory ; " without 
 any agency but an internal law," suggests that ' law ' may be 
 an ontological agent, — but this is only a verbal slip. Mill 
 must be understood to say that a law of the order of experience, 
 or the uniformity of experience itself, is enough without any 
 ground beyond experience. 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 159 
 
 Distinctions that may appear pedantic are often indispens- 
 able. There are three ways of considering the external World : 
 (1) to give a psychological explanation of our belief in it: 
 Mill's original purpose, as to which we may say of liis work 
 — so far good. (2) To determine the methodological con- 
 ception of Nature ; that is, a conception adequate to the 
 demands of the Natural Sciences : for which Mill's suggestion 
 of ' groups and series of phenomena connected only by laws ' 
 may suffice ; it is equivalent to the region of Empirical and 
 Physical Reality. This is the supreme methodological postu- 
 late, and according to some philosophers the determination 
 of it is the limit of Metaphysics (see the discussions in 
 Karl Pearson's Grammar of Science). But (3) there remains 
 the ontological question, whether to complete the whole 
 circuit of our Knowledge and Belief anything must be 
 assumed besides the phenomena ? As to Mill's theory, what, 
 after all, are the " possibilities of sensation " ? How can 
 " phenomena " be supposed to remain in the absence of a 
 Subject ? 
 
 Two points seem to me of chief importance : (1) to account 
 for changes of phenomena that go on in the absence of any 
 known percipient — say the burning away of a fire whilst we 
 are out of the room. No doubt we think of this according 
 to the analogy of experience, as a series of perceptions which 
 we should have had if present. But, then, as we were not 
 present, there was for us no real possibility of sensation but 
 only one of the conditions — a condition of the Non-Esro. 
 What was it ? Clearly, there can be no " permanent possibility 
 of sensation " unless a Subject is permanently present : in his 
 absence, there can be merely some unknown condition of things, 
 such that the realisation of sensations is contingent only on 
 the Subject's return. The case of the World before the 
 genesis of animal life or sensitive beings, is in the same position. 
 We think of it as we should have perceived it had we been 
 present : but as we were not there, and yet must either hold 
 that there was something there, or else give up our belief in 
 the continuity of the World, we may if we like call that some- 
 thing ' a permanent condition not ourselves of tlie possibility 
 
160 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 of sensation/ but this seems only long-hand for Ding an sich, 
 or Being, or X. 
 
 Then (2) there is the fact that the external world is 
 believed to be common to oneself and others. Mill says in the 
 Appendix to chaps, xi. xii. : " On the same evidence on 
 which I recognise foreign threads of consciousness, I believe 
 that the Permanent Possibilities of sensation are common to 
 them and to me : but not the sensations." The Permanent 
 Possibilities then, are not themselves sensations ; they are not 
 themselves objects of cognition, but one side of the conditions 
 of cognition ; and, as such, in their one-sidedness, permanent 
 and apparently independent, but unknown. What is this but 
 Hypothetical Kealism ? 
 
 Thus even the working out of the Psychological Theory 
 seems to involve Ontology : and the interest of this for us is, 
 that we are inquiring whether any svich theory of Substance 
 is necessary to complete the system of Empirical Eeality. 
 Physical theories of Nature assume the presence of the Subject 
 as a latent term in all their propositions ; even atoms and 
 ether are conceived in analogy with objects perceived ; the 
 continuity of Nature in all directions is an unfailing 
 contingency of one phenomenon upon another. But if we 
 admit the possibility of any state of the World in which no 
 organic consciousness exists, there is no longer a possibility of 
 organised percepts. How then shall we conceive or express 
 that state of the World ? 
 
 § 6. This surd of analysis, then, this perdurable somewhat, 
 independent certainly of our private minds, can it be rationalised 
 by any of the doctrines that descend to us from Plato ? They 
 are chiefly three : ( 1 ) That Ideas are the sole Eeality of the 
 World, self-existent and the ground of all particular things ; 
 (2) that the Ideas are archetypes of all things, but exist in 
 the Divine Mind ; (3) that Ideas or Forms are the essence 
 of all things and immanent in them — universalia in re. 
 
 The third doctrine was never able to give any account of 
 the accidents or differences of things without referring to 
 Matter ; and, if interpreted according to modern Methodology, 
 in which ' Universal ' is equivalent to Definition or Law, it is 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WOELD 161 
 
 compatible with Materialism. The first doctrine is no longer 
 maintained ; the second, that the Ideas exist in a Divine 
 Mind, is a compromise with Theology. It gives by anthro- 
 pomorphic analogy a factitious unity to the Ideas, whereas 
 their unity must subsist in their relations ; but it rests the 
 World upon Reason, not Will, and makes (as Hooker says) 
 the Being of God a kind of law to His working. 
 
 Berkeley, in his earlier writings, made only a tentative 
 alliance with Hellenic thought ; but in Siris we find that its 
 influence has grown upon him ; so that by suggestion rather 
 than assertion he leads us to the nobler view of an Universal 
 Reason, and of our relation to it, citing the authority of Plato, 
 Aristotle, the Neo-Platonists, and others ; though not without 
 hints of their probable indebtedness to Moses. More explicitly 
 the doctrine is stated by Cudworth {Eternal and Im. Mor. 
 Book I. chap. iii. § 7), and it seems to be the sense of many 
 theologians who follow the Johannine Gospel. But it had 
 taken little hold of our Philosophy until the imposing vogue 
 of such theories in Germany gained the adhesion of certain 
 English thinkers, most notably Coleridge and Green. As it 
 cannot matter which exposition of this view we take, I shall 
 consider it chiefly as it appears in Green : he being the most 
 recent and the most explicit, and availing himself of modern 
 scientific doctrines in his exposition. 
 
 According to Green, Nature is a system of relations ; it 
 is [essentially knowledge : in the experience of each man the 
 manifold particulars presented to him are combined into one 
 orderly whole by the activity of his intelligence ; and if his 
 experience is imperfect and fragmentary, implying a greater 
 whole beyond it, that greater whole can only be conceived as 
 real and orderly and one, by means of a unifying principle 
 analogous to — say, rather, the original of — human thought : 
 namely, the Universal Reason {Prolegomena, Book I. chap. i.). 
 Such is the ground of the perdurability of things and of their 
 independence of the particular Subject, which are unexplained 
 by Mill and Berkeley ; for they make the mistake of beginning 
 with inert sensations or ideas that have no principle of unity. 
 Should Green be asked how sensation is to be explained if 
 
 11 
 
162 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 we begin with understanding, his reply is, that we have no 
 knowledge of sensation merely as such and unrelated, and that 
 what we regard as the sensation-element in perception is 
 found on examination to be determinable only in its relations 
 ad infinitum (cf. Hegel's Encyklopadie, § 20). Sensation is 
 an illusion of subjective consciousness. In the real world of 
 knowledge there is nothing that needs a Ding an sich to 
 account for it, or anything other than the spiritual principle in 
 Nature (§§ 42-51). 
 
 Now it is true, in my judgment, that wholly unrelated 
 sensation is unknown : from the fact that our consciousness is 
 relational it follows that if sensations are known it must be 
 in relations ; but it also follows that there must be terms for 
 relations to relate, and that at last these terms cannot 
 themselves be relations. Nature, as a system of relations that 
 at last relate nothing, is both a contradiction in thought and 
 a divorce of experience. Even Plotinus found a place for 
 Matter as to ea-j^aTov : no bad name for elementary sensation, 
 whatever that may be. 
 
 Instead of this abstract method of explaining away 
 sensation, an Hegelian may resort to confusion of metaphors. 
 In Hutchison Stirling's Secret of Hegel (Book I. chap, iii.) he 
 says that the thought which constitutes the world is not 
 " subjective thought ; it is objective thought ; it is thought 
 really out there, if you will, in that incrustation that is named 
 the world. It, this world and all outer objects, are but 
 sensuous congeries, sensuous incrustations of these thoughts. 
 Did a human subject not exist, it is conceivable that this 
 congeries and incrustation would still exist." But it matters 
 little, for " Thought is a system and this system is the 
 universe, and the element of sense, or what we conceive as 
 that element, is nothing as against this system, and can only 
 be named with propriety the Other." Sensuous incrustations 
 of thought, then, are independent of man (or of a sensuous 
 Subject), and for the Absolute they are the Other. It is 
 useless to ask, how can there be an Other for the Absolute, or 
 how the Absolute's own thoughts can incrust and congest 
 themselves into an Other ; for in this system the Absolute is 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 163 
 
 constructed to contain whatever it may be convenient to find 
 there. 
 
 It occurs to Green that the word " thought " is hardly 
 strong enough to characterise the unifying principle in 
 Nature; for of course our thoughts are transient and often 
 erroneous, and we correct tliem by Nature which is permanent 
 and unchangeable ; and he suggests that the true character of 
 thought is rather to be sought in the unity of its object, that 
 is, in Nature itself (§ 47). To understand Nature he has 
 referred us to our own thought ; and now for the truth of 
 thought he refers us to Nature. Pursuing the latter sugges- 
 tion, he goes on to argue that our thought is not a process in 
 time. But it would be an intricate task to pursue his 
 argument in detail ; so seeing that, in fact, thought does take 
 time, I shall be content to exhibit under three heads the 
 difficulties of understanding Nature or the Laws of Nature as 
 thought. 
 
 In the first place, it cannot be admitted that the system 
 of Nature is only to be understood as the content of an 
 Universal Unity of Apperception. The analogy of the human 
 mind gives no support to such a view ; every mind comprises 
 and depends upon an infinity of indiscernible elements that 
 never enter into the unity of apperception ; and, moreover, 
 every mind once contained a vast deal that, having passed 
 through that unity, has disappeared beyond its grasp. 
 Again, in human minds the unity of apperception does not 
 determine the laws of growth, but is itself a gradual outcome 
 of those laws : so that, by analogy, an Universal Unity of 
 Apperception would cast little or no light upon the reciprocity 
 and causation of things in the World, but must rather be 
 explained as a result of them — as, in fact, the brain of the 
 philosopher must be explained. Hence physical science 
 conceives the world as unified by Gravity, the Conservation of 
 Energy, etc. 
 
 In the second place, most laws of the perdurable and 
 independent contents of Nature, are not like laws of the 
 human mind. A fire which, during my absence, burns itself 
 out and falls to the bottom of the grate, follows chemical and 
 
164 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 mechanical laws ; whilst the laws of the mind are (or are 
 analogous to) those of organic life, or else peculiarly subjective. 
 
 In the third place, to speak of objective Thought as so 
 " incrusted and congested " as to become common to all per- 
 cipients, or in any way directly to manifest itself to all beholders, 
 is to overlook the essential subjectivity of thought in the usual 
 sense of the word. Thought may be objective in the sense that 
 all can agree to think it ; and in this sense every scientific law 
 is an objective thought. But in the sense of being an object 
 of perception to others, " objective thought " is a contradiction 
 in terms. Thought in the individual is only known to himself ; 
 and can only be expressed to others by grimace, gesticulation, 
 speech, or some other bodily activity. Hence, if in such a case 
 it is possible at all to pursue an analogy, we ought to infer that 
 the objective Thought of Universal Reason can only find public 
 expression (so to speak) through the activity of bodies ; and 
 this I take to be the Semitic or popular sense in which God is 
 said to reveal Himself in His creation. But if there is no 
 analogy with human thought, there is no meaning in the words. 
 
 I conclude, then, that to speak of Nature as itself the 
 Universal Reason or Thought, is an abuse of language (cf. 
 Hegel's Uncyklopddie, § 24) ; that the objectifying or hypos- 
 tatising of thought does not give us the differential characters 
 of inorganic Nature ; and that it does not explain the fact of 
 Empirical Reality, where thought and sensation meet in the 
 perceptions and experience of normal men. 
 
 There are three senses in which the World may by a figure 
 of speech be called rational: (1) in the Semitic or popular 
 sense, according to which it is believed to be a created material 
 thing, operating by laws imposed by God and, of course, by the 
 Reason of God, — it is a work of Reason. (2) By a sort of 
 metonymy, transferring to an object the name of an activity 
 concerned with it ; for as the interpretation of Nature is the 
 work of Reason, the interpretation itself, when discovered, may 
 be called rational. (3) Since every result of the interpretation, 
 displaying continuity and universality, is admitted to govern 
 every subsequent inquiry, the World, whose character is given 
 by that interpretation, comes more and more to be regarded as 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 165 
 
 the judge, or as the type and fulfilment of Reason herself. 
 But it may be a left-handed compliment to ascribe to the 
 World our own faculties ; and whether it is finally justifiable 
 to do so is a consideration beyond the Metaphysics of Nature. 
 
 § 7. It remains to consider certain systems of Monism, in 
 which Absolute Substance is conceived as neither Mind nor 
 Matter, but as a somewhat of which both these are manifesta- 
 tions. It will suffice to notice three : Spinoza's, Schopenhauer's 
 and Spencer's. 
 
 According to Spinoza, God is a Substance of infinite 
 attributes, of which two enter into human nature and are known 
 to us, namely, Thought and Extension. The attributes are 
 diversified into modes: every mode of thought corresponds 
 with a mode of extension, and all changes or processes of the 
 world run a parallel course in both modes : there is no causation 
 between the lines of change. God is both a thinking Thing 
 and an extended Thing; and the full knowledge of this in 
 all its relations and consequences is human perfection and 
 happiness. 
 
 Now, in so far as God exists in other attributes than 
 Thought and Extension, He is to us unknowable ; but must 
 be known to some mind ; for an attribute implies mind to 
 perceive it. Hence it may be said that since an attribute is 
 only a way of perceiving Substance, and since Substance is a 
 perceiving Thing, Spinoza's system works out into Absolute 
 Idealism. But certainly Spinoza did not intend this. That 
 there is something other than consciousness, is necessary to 
 his doctrine, that it is only as the human body is a mode of 
 extension that the human mind is able to perceive extended 
 things and to understand the order of Nature. That God can 
 only be known to mind is an identical proposition ; but it is 
 not merely as mind that He is known. 
 
 The existence of God appears in a system of rigidly 
 mechanical and mental determinations. Substance apart from 
 the attributes has no place in the course of the world, which 
 conforms to the requirements of a scientific Methodology. 
 The name of God in Spinoza's system is a kind of rhetoric, 
 softening the intellectuality of his philosophy, but never 
 
166 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 modifying its career ; and we see in his reception by mankind 
 that the rhetoric was effectual with himself rather than with 
 his readers. Not that he was insincere : the place of God in 
 his system was derived both from his racial traditions and 
 from his Cartesian culture : and if every one is to be called 
 insincere who clings to certain words that have little intel- 
 lectual significance for him, few of us can pass for honest. 
 But I hold that the general judgment of men in the seventeenth 
 and eighteenth centuries, that the author who often uses the 
 phrase ' God or Nature ' was a Naturalist rather than a Theo- 
 logian, is defensible. In his heart he was, as Coleridge said, a 
 " God-intoxicated man " ; but his system, apart from his own 
 feelings about it, — as a moment in the history of thought, — 
 cannot be called " Acosmism," as by Hegel, without confusion 
 of ideas. Hence, although the name of God gave him strength 
 to cast out many scholastic prejudices, it remained a name and 
 a feeling. 
 
 Schopenhauer's theory is that the Eeality of the World is 
 Will ; but this Will is originally blind : Ideas, consciousness, 
 understanding, phenomena in space, are all of them results of 
 its activity. The primordial exertion of the Will is as obscui^e 
 as the beginning of things in every system that from the One 
 pretends to derive the many. According to Schopenhauer's 
 verbal formula, the first objectifying of the Will takes place 
 in the species of things (Ideas) ; the second, in individuals in 
 Time and Space : all the forces of Nature and all the desires 
 of beasts and men are also modes of its manifestation. He 
 adopts Kant's position in the Transcendcntale Analytik that 
 Causality is a judgment applicable only to the synthesis of 
 phenomena, and therefore not to the objectifying of the Will 
 in phenomena. We find in our own being that Will is the 
 Eeality, our body its phenomenon ; and the same is true of the 
 whole World. 
 
 Now the Will is evil : its crime is to forsake its absolute 
 condition, sole and eternal, and to multiply itself in in- 
 dividuals ever striving and perishing. That this endeavour 
 is evil the universal pain of animal life declares : in which 
 life, through the advent of consciousness and perception, a 
 
ONTOLOGV OF THE WORLD 107 
 
 manifold existeuce first becomes recognisable in Time and 
 Space ; for these, as Kant showed, are forms of perception, 
 and are the principles of individuation. It follows that our 
 existence as individuals is illusory; in Eeality the one Will 
 lives in each and all. Intelligence increases with organisation 
 to meet the increasing complexity of life ; it culminates in 
 Man, or rather in men of genius ; and then the Will meets 
 with Nemesis ; for by art-intuition, by sympathy and, above 
 all, by philosophy the falsehood of individuality with all its 
 strife and pain is felt and seen and repudiated. 
 
 Schopenhauer, then, regards consciousness as a secondary 
 and ancillary thing in the World, brought forth for the 
 ser\ace of the individual life ; and he gives no intelligible 
 derivation of it. Bewustlosigkeit ist der urspriingliche imd 
 natlirliche Zustand aller Dinge. Most things remain in this 
 state : plants have at most a faint analogue of consciousness ; 
 the lowest animals merely a glimmering of it ( Welt als W. u. 
 v., Ergiinzungen, Book I. chap. xv.). Yet at the end of the 
 previous chapter he has specidated upon grades of subcon- 
 sciousness in man, and might have extended the conception 
 to inorganic Nature. I seem to remember that somewhere 
 he does so, but cannot recover the passage. The term ' Will ' 
 suggests consciousness ; but for Schopenhauer Will is the 
 genus of all forces, not (as often conceived) a species of force 
 {W. a. W. u. v., Book II. chap. xxii.). Will, as subjectively 
 experienced, is consciousness ; but consciousness is not force, 
 and can never be derived from force, nor traced to anything 
 that is not consciousness. It is of no avail, for instance, to 
 invent the name of ' metakinesis ' to bridge the gulf between 
 kinesis and consciousness. It is like Kant's attempt to bring 
 Understanding to Sense by means of Imagination ; or like the 
 series of emanations or generations by which Plotinus derives 
 Matter from the One. A middle term between concepts 
 cannot make them agree ; it can only exhibit their agreement ; 
 where no agreement exists no middle term can make it 
 conceivable. If we propose a middle term that does not 
 agree with either extreme, we then have not one inconceivable 
 but two inconceivables ; and to increase the number of 
 
168 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 inconceivables does not decrease their inconceivability. Hence, 
 if Schopenhauer's system is not sheer Dynamism, its Reality 
 is altogether distinct from Consciousness. 
 
 In Spencer's philosophy {Psychology, Part VII.) the 
 Absolute is described as something existing beyond conscious- 
 ness, and unknowable except as the Force implied in our 
 sense of resistance to muscular efforts, and as corresponding 
 in its relations, or rather in the variation of its relations, 
 with changes in the world of our consciousness. He calls 
 his ontological doctrine Transfigured Realism. The develop- 
 ment of our consciousness from a primitive sentiency in which 
 there is no distinction of Object and Subject, gradually gives 
 rise to that distinction and, at last, to a full recognition 
 within the world of consciousness of two contrasted orders of 
 phenomena which respectively are vivid and faint, original 
 and copy, etc., each order controlled by characteristic laws. 
 Thus what are usually called mind and matter are both of 
 them departments of consciousness, and take their rise, during 
 the development of organic life and mind, from something 
 which is neither one nor the other, but is co-manifested in 
 both. Belief in such an entity is necessarily generated by 
 experience, and is indispensable to an understanding of the 
 permanence and continuity of things. 
 
 There is some resemblance between this view and Spinoza's, 
 that God is unknowable to us in all but two of His attributes, 
 and in these two is simultaneously manifested ; but there are 
 these differences. According to Spinoza, the attribute of 
 Extension is only indirectly known to us through modes of 
 thought, that correspond to modifications of our extended 
 body as affected by other modes of extension. Extended 
 things in the rest of the world are not directly perceivable. 
 According to Spencer, however, the whole of the object- 
 world is directly given in experience, and is a division of 
 consciousness itself. For Spinoza, again, the attributes are 
 the Substance in its own knowledge ; whereas for Spencer 
 Object and Subject imply unassignable correspondences with 
 the Absolute. 
 
 Now, admiring as I do Spencer's account of the develop- 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 169 
 
 ment of the knowledge of Object and Subject so far as it is 
 psychological, I am unable to follow the ontological inferences. 
 His argument starts from what I have called Empirical 
 Eeality, in which (as he says) the opposition of Self and Not- 
 self is immediately given. Against Idealism he urges that 
 the conviction of Eealism concerning tlie reality of the Not- 
 self is («) prior to reflective Idealism ; (b) direct, and so 
 simple as to seem iindecomposable ; (c) vivid and distinct ; 
 (rf) implies the Universal Postulate (inconceivability of the 
 opposite) only once (chaps, vi. vii. viii. and xii.). But every 
 one of these arguments is more favourable to what he calls 
 ' Crude Realism ' (Empirical Eeality) as against Transfigured 
 Realism ; wliich is (a) later ; (b) indirect and far from simple ; 
 (c) exceedingly faint and indistinct ; (d) implies the Universal 
 Postulate a great many times : indeed we must presently 
 inquire whether it is conceivable at all. 
 
 Then, the psychological analysis of the conviction of 
 Eealism discloses at the basis of our objective consciousness, a 
 feeling of resistance to our efforts, and the representation of a 
 force in the Not-self opposed, but akin, to that w^hich we exert 
 (chap. xvii.). But, strictly, this analysis of the Object into 
 sensation is more favourable to Subjective Idealism than to 
 Realism of any kind ; and it is more favourable to Crude 
 than to Transfigured Realism, because to speak of the ob- 
 jective power as akin to our own is to diminish its unknow- 
 ability. To illustrate his theory of Transfigured Realism, 
 Spencer takes (chap, xix.) two symbolic cases : first, the per- 
 spective drawing of a tree-trunk, " in which along with extreme 
 unlikeness between the symbol and the actuality, there is an 
 exact though indirect correspondence between the varying 
 relations " among their component lines ; and, secondly, the 
 image of a cube projected on a cylinder, in which the corre- 
 spondences of lines and angles are even more complicated 
 but still absolutely definite. Here the perspective drawing 
 and the projected image of the cube stand severally for 
 perception ; the tree-trunk and the cube themselves, for objects 
 of perception ; and the comparison shows " how it becomes 
 possible that a plexus of objective phenomena [sic] may be so 
 
170 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 represented by the plexus of subjective effects produced, that 
 though the effects are totally unlike their causes, and though 
 the relations among the effects are totally unlike the relations 
 among their causes, and though the laws of variation in the 
 one set of relations differ entirely from those in the other : yet 
 the two may correspond in such a way, that each change 
 in the objective reality causes in the subjective state a 
 change exactly answering to it — so answering as to cause a 
 cognition of it." 
 
 "Well, merely protesting against the unknowable entities 
 being called ' phenomena,' and against the interpretation of 
 perception by the category of cause and effect, what I have 
 chiefly to draw attention to in this theory is, the conception 
 of a correspondence between perceptions and states of Being 
 beyond consciousness. Correspondence is a kind of likeness, 
 here conceived as a likeness of relations of relations of rela- 
 tions, etc. ; very remote and refined, but originating in, and (as 
 Spencer has shown us) depending on, the simplest perception 
 of likeness. A likeness, then, is asserted between our percep- 
 tions (ideas in Berkeley's sense) and things that are not and 
 cannot be perceptions, nor in any sense states of consciousness ; 
 and, therefore, we must ask Berkeley's question : " How can 
 an idea be like anything that is not an idea ? " 
 
 § 8. My own hypothesis concerning Keality bears a closer 
 resemblance to these monistic doctrines than to any others ; 
 and of late years such doctrines have multiplied — Fechner, 
 von Hartmann, Hiickel — and may now be said to predominate 
 in the speculative world. But no amount of authoritative 
 support will console me unless I can give some answer to 
 Berkeley's question : " How is it possible to predicate any- 
 thing of that which is other than consciousness?" 
 
 My first position is that consciousness is Eeality. But, 
 then, it is not the whole of Keality ; and we have seen that 
 no metaphysical system has been able to avoid the assuming, 
 or implying, of something else. 
 
 Secondly, consciousness is a factor of all Eeality ; because 
 it cannot be derived from anything else ; cannot be explained 
 by its utility ; and is manifested by all living organisms, 
 
ONTOLOGY OF THE WORLD 171 
 
 which participate in chemical and mechanical forces, and are 
 hypothetically resolvable, like everything else, into protyle. 
 
 Thirdly, an organism's consciousness is not on a level with 
 the organism itself; for the organism is a phenomenon in con- 
 sciousness ; but that in which phenomena exist is not a 
 phenomenon. No doubt in I'sychology, one may conveniently 
 speak of processes of consciousness as phenomena ; but meta- 
 physical reflection shows that such expressions are for con- 
 venience only. The true correlation of conscious processes is 
 not with the organism as phenomenon, but with the trans- 
 cendent Eeality whose phenomenon it is ; and similarly with 
 all lower grades of consciousness. This distinguishes my 
 hypothesis from Hylozoism. 
 
 The notion of a relation between consciousness and some- 
 thing beyond is necessarily an imperfect one ; for there can 
 be no second term for the relation to take hold of: the cate- 
 gory of Transcendence, like its correlative, Manifestation, is 
 one-sided, or merely indicative or orectic. Nevertheless, since 
 all metaphysical specidation points to transcendent Being, I 
 submit, fourthly, that we may give this vacuum some body, 
 or at least a skeleton, by transferring thither something from 
 its correlative consciousness : namely — 
 
 (1) Time or, at least, Succession; and (2) Change: for 
 these are the forms of all consciousness. 
 
 (3) Coexistence : for this is found even in subjective con- 
 sciousness, and is the most insistent of all relations amongst 
 material phenomena in space. But whether space-relations, 
 a construction of the activity of consciousness, are predicable 
 of the transcendent Reality, I cannot determine. 
 
 (4) Order, or uniformity, of change may be predicated of 
 the Transcendent upon both subjective and objective evidence ; 
 and perhaps something equivalent to that which we know in 
 phenomena as Causation (not between the Real and phenomena, 
 but in the changes of the Real) ; but this with less confidence, 
 because (as with space) the evidence is objective only. 
 
 That which is thus defined cannot be called " Subject," for 
 that term is applicable only to its conscious activity. Nor is 
 " Substance " a satisfactory name ; for it suggests that con- 
 
172 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 sciousness is an attribute and therefore a degree less real. 
 " Soul " has the merit of meaning a conscious thing having 
 also other characters ; at least, in popular belief, — the only 
 test of truth in such matters. Perhaps the most colourless 
 name for it is the Transcendent, or merely Being. 
 
 But I do not care what it is called. Let us quit this 
 Limbo where Anthelios seems to reign, making darkness visible, 
 and revisit the comfortable daylight, or (if you will) return to 
 the old familiar cave with its cheerful bonfire. 
 
CHAPTER IX 
 
 UNIVERSAL FOKMS OF THE PHENOMENON : TIME, SPACE, MATTER 
 
 AND MOTION 
 
 § 1. The Universal is the philosopher's quest, his quarry ; the 
 more abstract anything is the more it fascinates him, and the 
 more ardently he pursues it, like the Wild Huntsman, through 
 the watches of the night. Hence the lustre and music of the 
 World interest him less than Time, Space, Matter and Motion. 
 These things have provoked his eloquence for ages ; and the 
 Schools have established a tradition of investigating certain 
 problems concerning them that must never be interrupted. 
 The being of Time and Space especially, has engrossed the 
 imagination of philosophers and children : sages have toiled in 
 vain to comprehend it ; and youths have swooned, whilst the 
 first excursions of their wonder sounded that bottomless 
 abyss. 
 
 It was by a misleading abstraction that Kant signalised 
 Space and Time as pure forms of experience. For, first, they 
 are not merely forms, but are at the same time objects of 
 experience ; and, secondly, they are not pure, but have a sen- 
 sational ground. Moreover they are inseparable in objective 
 cognition from Matter and Motion. It is true that Time has 
 a greater generality than Space, Matter and Motion, since it 
 it is an universal form also of subjective Eeality ; but it is 
 not cognisable as such until Space, Matter and Motion have 
 been fully developed in consciousness. 
 
 The inseparability of these forms in experience appears 
 in the attempts of psychologists to analyse them severally ; 
 whereby it is shown that the sensations on which all these 
 
 173 
 
174 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 cognitions depend are those of movement and resistance, and 
 that the relations involved in their genesis are those of suc- 
 cession and co-existence. The relativity of these data may be 
 exhibited thus : — 
 
 w !25 Q ^ 
 
 E2. P <t g 
 
 Matter p • rf Space S' • g Time 
 
 Matter traversing Space in Time 
 
 >■ -> 
 
 Motion 
 
 The germinal experience is our own movement ; though it 
 cannot be known as such till all its latent contents have been 
 differentiated. 
 
 None of these cognitions can have grown up without the 
 others ; and although they are not equally prominent in all 
 objective cognition, and probably are very unequally devel- 
 oped in different species of animals and even vary amongst 
 men, yet to attend to, or treat of, any one of them apart from 
 the rest can never be a complete but only a quasi-abstraction. 
 
 I am assuming that the analysis of external perception 
 given by Bain, Spencer and most English psychologists, is 
 essentially sound ; though a good many psychologists, such 
 as Kiilpe, reject it as too speculative. For whilst I admit 
 that the effect of the argument, as urged by Spencer or Sully, 
 does not amount to conviction, yet reflection always increases 
 my sense of its probability ; and the failure of direct con- 
 viction seems to me sufficiently explained by the immeasur- 
 able antiquity of the organic preparation for these perceptions. 
 It is unreasonable to expect that the growth of countless ages 
 can be adequately unravelled and reconstituted in a few pages 
 of reasoning that are read in half an hour. 
 
 Now if it is true that the cognitions of Time, Space, 
 Matter and Motion all have their root in the same experiences, 
 namely, in the kinsesthesis, or sensations of muscular contrac- 
 tion resisted and unresisted (with the correlative relaxations), 
 and in the adjustment of limbs and eyes, and their sliding 
 
TIME, SPACE, MATTER AND MOTION 175 
 
 from one adjustment to another (with the accompanying tactile 
 and retinal sensibility) ; if this is true, the finished percepts, 
 or concepts, of Time, Space, Matter and Motion can never be 
 distinguished, compared and contrasted, without the danger 
 of isolating in words and half-thoughts the things that are 
 inseparable in Nature and experience. They are four factors 
 of th3 Siime experience ; discriminated factors of the same 
 empirical Eeality. Hence, moreover, such being the mutual 
 implication of Time, Space, Motion and Matter, any concepts 
 of them that are incompatible with this fact are bad concepts ; 
 or else any dialectic that seems to exhibit the concepts as 
 incompatible with the facts or with one another, is mere 
 eristic. It is indeed the natural sophistry of the analytic 
 understanding to assume that distinct concepts stand for 
 possibly separate existences ; to treat the results of analysis 
 as independent factors of creation. Then, what more reason- 
 able than to treat Time or Space, or both, as existing in their 
 own right, and to introduce Matter and Motion to them as if 
 from outside ? But any question as to their relations raised 
 in this way, must be stated in such a form as to pester the 
 answer. There is not the smallest reason to suppose that 
 any one of the four. Time, Space, Matter, Motion, ever existed 
 separately or was experienced separately, and it is a delusion 
 to suppose that any one of them can be separately explained. 
 
 Kant says that Time and Space cannot be represented as 
 non-existent, but can be represented as empty. The former 
 clause is, I think, true ; for though in some conditions even 
 human consciousness may be so narrow and dark that neither 
 Space nor even Time defines its content, this is not the 
 deliberate suppression of Space and Time that Kant declares 
 to be impossible. But as to our ability to represent Space and 
 Time as empty, he is mistaken ; for, even granting it possible 
 to exclude the representation of all other bodies or images 
 (which is not true), still our own body from which all Spaces 
 radiate, and our present consciousness from which Time flows, 
 are quite inexpugnable. 
 
 I have here used ' representation ' as equivalent to Kant's 
 Vorstellung ; but for the ensuing discussion we shall need 
 
176 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 terms to distinguish three modes or grades of cognition : 
 
 (1) Perception — particular, concrete cognition; organised in 
 experience and aroused by the stimulus of immediate sensation. 
 
 (2) Imagination, derived from perception and having its con- 
 crete character, and sharing many of its limitations, but not 
 dependent on present sensation, nor restricted to the scale of 
 perception, nor to the order of perception in experience. (3) 
 Conception, dependent on perceptions or imaginations for its 
 contents ; yet not upon any in particular, but on the comparison 
 and analysis of many, and therefore not concrete but abstract. 
 A concept may be sustained by an image taken in a repre- 
 sentative character, or by a word, or other symbol : the 
 representative character being preserved by definition. By 
 operating with symbols the power of conception extends far 
 beyond the limits of perception and imagination ; and therefore, 
 for the sake of sanity, it must proceed from perception, follow the 
 analogies of perception, and return to it for verification. We 
 have seen that perception is in general the ground of Empirical 
 Reality ; that conception is the means of completing and 
 explaining Empirical by Physical Reality ; that to be imagin- 
 able or intuitable in a representation is a condition imposed 
 on any concept in order that Empirical and Physical Reality 
 may form one continuum ; but that to be perceivable or 
 imperceivable, imaginable or unimaginable, conceivable or 
 inconceivable, is no proof of Reality or Unreality in any 
 particular case apart from systematic confirmation. 
 
 § 2. Time, Space, Matter and Motion are all empirically 
 real. Kant, however, when he says that Time and Space are 
 empirically real, is inconsistent ; for he also says that they 
 are pure (non-sensuous) intuitions, and that sensation is the 
 test of Reality. That pure forms may be empirically real, it 
 is not enough that they should be excited to activity by 
 sensation ; and in fact it is as inconceivable that pure forms 
 of intuition should be aroused by sensation, as that pure forms 
 of judgment should connect sensations : if knowledge is to be 
 one it must all grow together from one root. 
 
 The reality of Time is immediately known in the " psycho- 
 logical Now " : every experience has a certain duration, some 
 
TIME, SPACE, MATTEK AND MOTION 177 
 
 seconds ; but tlie ' how much ' i.s variable and cannot be 
 generally determined : every experience also involves a change 
 or changes ; and Duration and Change are the elements of 
 Time. No experience is simple ; it is a process whose phases 
 blend and overlap, and this is the condition of the inteirration 
 and comparison of experience. Human experience is at every 
 reach of it an immeasurably complex process ; the more you 
 investigate it, the more you discover ; for the brain acts as a 
 whole. If, neglecting this basis of fact, we treat Time con- 
 ceptually as a line divisible, the present moment becomes 
 infinitely small, is inappreciable in experience as duration or 
 change. The past has gone ; the future is not yet ; the present 
 is iucognisable : therefore the World is a nonentity. Such 
 puzzles distress the youth of speculation, and reward the 
 speculations of youth. But in the moment of true experience 
 the whole of reality is grounded : the past is recorded as Effect 
 and the future germinates in its Causes ; and, therefore, to a 
 sufficient intellect it carries the World siih sjjecie eternitatis. 
 
 The reality of Time is known in the Now ; but the com- 
 prehensive consciousness of Time is the vastest abstraction (if 
 justly called abstract) of the human mind. As the form and 
 enfoldment of all possible experience, it is another name for 
 the Universe in its everlasting movement. For as there is but 
 one Universe and one process. Time as a whole cannot be 
 considered apart from its actual contents. Hence the true 
 character of Time is disguised by the methodological device of 
 treating it as of one dimension, representable by a straight 
 line. This can only represent the lapse of Time by an image 
 of dui-ation (no matter what it is that endures). But Time 
 beyond the Now has no duration ; and even there it is 
 consciousness rather than Time that endures ; for it reposes 
 on the universal process. This process, again, is co-extensive 
 with moving bodies in Space of three dimensions. Time, 
 therefore, comprehends the height and the breadth and the 
 depth of the galaxy, and something more, the life and mind 
 of all that world. 
 
 It may also be a convenient fiction to treat Time as made 
 up of moments ; but in experience all moments are fused in 
 
 12 
 
178 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 the continuity of movement. Moments are occurrences in the 
 course of time and are marked upon a background of obscurer 
 changes. Nothing can be less like our consciousness of Time 
 than a series of moments. It is indeed probable that the accents 
 of attention (sensations of adjustment) help in defining for us 
 the process of Time by giving a subjective measure : the fixation 
 of attention takes about three-fourths of a second, and this is the 
 period of which our subjective estimate is most exact. But 
 the point of attention is neither the whole of consciousness nor 
 the sole determinant of its growth : it is a selection within 
 consciousness, and all that lies about or beyond to the most 
 obscure marginal sentience (and, no doubt, still farther) has its 
 influence and its registration. Hence Time, as the form and 
 content of all experience of movement and change, is the whole 
 mass of consciousness ; but since in the Now, or in any given 
 lapse of time, the contents of experience continually vary (for 
 even the accent of attention is of unequal intensity and is 
 sometimes suspended), a concept of Time has been developed 
 having no particular content, but as a " quasi-blank form " of 
 any possible content. And this, I suppose, is Kant's pure 
 form of intuition. 
 
 The perception of any particular time beyond the Now is 
 vague, because it is one-sided ; I mean that its sensation- 
 element lies in the Now from which we measure, whilst at the 
 other end of the period there is only a memory, expectation, or 
 representation. The perception of a space, or body in space 
 (which comes to the same thing), is supported by sensation in 
 the Self measured from, in the object of regard, and in others 
 on every side of the line of vision : it has, therefore, a high 
 sensation-vivacity. But the most distinct personal memory is 
 supported by sensation only in the present ; the fact 
 remembered has only an idea's vivacity, which faintly illumines 
 neighbouring objects, but leaves dark the intervening hours or 
 years. 
 
 The vagueness and subjectivity of times perceived or 
 remembered makes them hard to measure and arrange. So to 
 measure them we turn to things external and take the motion 
 of some body as a constant ; then construct a calendar and 
 
TIME, SPACE, MATTER AND MOTION 179 
 
 insert iu it our own history, and are apt to think we remember 
 the order of events when in fact we read them there. 
 Without a calendar, the best way of arranging our past life is 
 by reference to our movements and where we have lived, for 
 this is the best clue to causation. Altliough Time may be 
 primarily subjective, the human idea of it is developed by 
 means of objective experience and by need ; yet it now far 
 transcends any need we have for it. In animals who have little 
 need of memory and foresight, the development of the 
 perception of Time is backward in comparison with Space, 
 Matter and Motion. And this seems also to be true of 
 children ; still even in them the sense of Time is so far 
 developed before the rise of self-reflection, that it is known as 
 that in which we live and not as our invention. And though 
 less clear and distinct than Space, Time is more comprehensive ; 
 for Space is only the form of phenomena, but Time of all 
 consciousness ; and therefore it is more real than Space, 
 because consciousness is Reality. Nothing, therefore, is more 
 preposterous than the notion of a 7iunc stans : which, in fact, 
 is the mistaking of Space for Eternity. Such is the penalty of 
 manipulating concepts in contempt of experience. But the 
 comprehension of Time by man, transcending all utility, belongs 
 to the World's self-knowledge ; and, I suppose, the dimness of 
 our comprehension is the still unlifted veil of that knowledge. 
 § 3. The reality of Space in experience is given primarily 
 in sensations of movement, which in the development of 
 perception come to be signified to us by every touch, by 
 every limb-adjustment, by every eye-adjustment, and hence by 
 every coloured expanse ; nay, further, by every focussing of 
 the eyes upon a point that yields no retinal sensation, and by 
 every experience of not touching, for this (though less attended 
 to) is as real an experience as touching is. But it may be 
 said, if Space is real, what sort of reality is it ? It is not 
 Substance. No : but we must not assume that we have 
 already named every Category that is needed for thinking 
 Reality ; any more than that all the Categories we name have 
 a correspondence in Reality. Space is not Substance ; for 
 the fundamental attribute of empirical Substance is resistance, 
 
180 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 and this is the opposite of Space. And yet it has an attribute, 
 of which it may be said to be the subject ; for as the defining 
 attribute of Matter is resistance to movement, so that of 
 Space is non-resistance, known by freedom of movement ; and 
 this is quite as positive as impeded movement. I say non- 
 resistance is the attribute of Space, for it is not the same thing 
 as Space. Space is a construction, or rather a mental organic 
 growth, to which other experiences, tactile and visual, con- 
 tribute ; and the product is not the same as any of its elements 
 or even all of them together. It is something known on 
 occasion of them, most vividly by movement. 
 
 As this growth is complete before the rise of self-conscious- 
 ness, it is empirically objective, and, like Time and the material 
 World, something into which the self-conscious individual is 
 born. Hence the natural man laughs when he hears of 
 Kant's doctrine that Time and Space are (transcendentally) 
 subjective forms of intuition. But in my opinion Kant did 
 not really mean that they were forms of merely individual 
 intuition, but of the universal Knower in Nature ; though the 
 misunderstanding is Kant's own fault, not only by bad statement, 
 but by not clearly conceiving what he meant : influenced 
 perhaps by the Cartesian innate ideas. 
 
 It may be asked whether, then, Kant was wrong in arguing 
 that, since every sensation has degree, empty Space, a vacuum, 
 cannot be proved from experience {Anticipationen der Wahrneh' 
 mung) ; because the kinsesthesis has degree, and this is the 
 essential condition of the perception of Space. But we must 
 consider that empirical Space is not empty, but tilled with 
 ether (according to current hypothesis) ; which, however, offers 
 no sensible resistance. An ether-vacuum cannot be obtained ; 
 and if it could be we might discover that movement of a body 
 as a whole is impossible in such a vacuum, because any body 
 entering it would instantly turn into ether, and therefore, as 
 a body, could move no farther. The kinsesthesis or sense of 
 our own movement, therefore, is conditional upon Space not 
 being empty. I know not what a physicist would think of 
 this speculation. 
 
 There is no perception of pure Space, but only of spaces 
 
TIME, SPACE, MATTER AND MOTION 181 
 
 variously bounded by (or measured I'roni) bodies at diflerent 
 distances and directions in a variously -coloured patchwork, 
 or in an active-tactile exploration. The dill'erences of colours, 
 adjustments and movements being abstracted from our percep- 
 tions, there remains what is common to them, the concept of 
 pure Space, which Kant mistook for a pure intuition. Kant 
 was unfortunate in every way : first, in denying tlie conceptual 
 character of pure Space ; secondly, in supposing pure Space 
 to be the object of Geometry, which treats of determinations 
 of Space ; and thirdly, in supposing that Geometry treats of 
 intuitive Space, whereas in intuitive Space no determination 
 satisfies the conditions of pure Geometry. Clearly Geometry 
 in treating of points, lines, surfaces, etc., and their relations, 
 deals with abstractions from experience of the determinations 
 of Space, conceived as existing in a Space similarly abstracted 
 from experience. 
 
 Space as perceived has three dimensions, and is so conceived 
 by Euclid and his followers ; but that it may be conceived 
 as having four, or more, is a liberal paradox. Granting 
 Space in four dimensions to be conceivable (that is, definable), 
 whether it be real or not in any other sense Heaven knows : 
 we shall never know in this life ; because the matter in such 
 Space can never influence our experience. Just as surface is 
 not a physical but only a geometrical property of Matter in 
 three dimensions, and therefore our Matter can never disturb 
 the inhabitants of a superficies ; so three dimensions constitute 
 no physical property of Matter in four dimensions, and such 
 Matter can never intrude upon us ; because in our Space it 
 would be destroyed by its own definition, annihilated by its 
 own essence ! 
 
 Whether all Space is really curved, so that it is impossible 
 to draw a straight line in it, seems to be a physical question. 
 Does the assumption of curvature fiicilitate the solution of any 
 physical problem ? Does the assumption of straight lines ever 
 give rise to appreciable error within the limits of calculation 
 and of verifying by measurement ? We cannot determine 
 this by reference direct to Empirical Eeality ; for within such 
 limits the measurable segments of innumerable curves might 
 
182 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 not differ from straight lines. As to the further speculation 
 that Space may not only be essentially curved, but even change 
 its curvature with the process of Time, and that this may be 
 the truth of Motion ; abstractly considered, this is conceivable, 
 because Motion is a traversing of Space in Time, and it is a 
 mere translation of this to consider Space itself as changing in 
 Time. But tui'ning to the experience of many bodies traversing 
 adjacent spaces at different velocities, to conceive of this as a 
 wriggling of Space itself is painful to a sympathetic mind. 
 And, to avoid hypocrisy, I must confess that to me these 
 speculations have an air of belonging to the play rather than 
 to the work of Reason. Still, play may be serious enough, and 
 Nature shows that it is the best preparation for work, and this 
 is the best excuse for many shelves of Philosophy ; and, to be 
 sure, there is time enough to be all in earnest, and there is 
 posterity to fall back upon. 
 
 § 4. Time and Space then are real, and in Chap. VII. we 
 showed in what sense Matter is real in experience ; and since 
 Motion is nothing else than Matter traversing Space in Time, 
 this too is real. We next take up the problems of infinite 
 divisibility. 
 
 Our immediate perception of the Now, the Time-process, is, 
 of course, not infinitely divisible ; in other words, in the 
 psychological Now there is a minimum sensibile (for sound 
 _!._ sec.) ; so that if the Now lasts 6 seconds, it comprises 
 3000 minima. But conceptually Time is infinitely divisible; 
 because, taking any unit in experience, we may apply the 
 symbolic system of numeration and divide ad libitum, or 
 save ourselves this trouble by an algebraic sign. And the use 
 of this device as far as may ever be requisite is justified by 
 the appalling calculations of physical science concerning the 
 movements of atoms and ether. Moreover, since such move- 
 ments affect our organisms they must our minds, and we may 
 reasonably regard the minimum sensibile of the Now as having 
 been, in our own and ancestral experience, subliminally divided 
 according to the minutest differences of Nature : an infinite 
 division is not required. Whoever supposes that the mind 
 cannot be affected by less than the Empirical minimum 
 
TIME, SPACE, MATTEIt AND MOTION 183 
 
 sensihile, should consider the organ of Hearing, how it counts 
 and multiplies and does sums in proportion, as if it had an 
 over-mind of its own. But even tlie minutest sensible 
 ditt'erences are not to be treated as moments constituting 
 Time, for they are events in Time, and are fused together in 
 Time by the continuity of Motion and Experience. The dis- 
 continuity of Time is inconceivable, not beaiuse there must be 
 an interval of Time between any two moments, but because 
 each moment would then be an origination and cessation of 
 existence. There would be no Time and no Understandins:. 
 
 In perceptual Space there is a minimum sensihile (for 
 the retina "005 mm.). But conceptually, of course, any unit 
 measure of Space may be divided ad infinitum ; and the 
 smallest part, considered as Space, contains the conditions of 
 all Geometry. And, as in the case of Time, the use of this 
 device as far as requisite is justified by the calculations of 
 physical science ; and it is futher justified by the discovery 
 of space -relations which are incommensurable except by 
 reference to an infinitely small unit. Nor would it be 
 reasonable to regard the immediate perception of our minds 
 as a standard of Nature, seeing that all our perceptions are 
 immeasurably compounded in correspondence with our bodily 
 organisation. 
 
 Nor, of course, does Space consist of distinguishable 
 minima or points, whether in the visual expanse or in eye- 
 and-limb adjustments, for all such points are fused by the 
 continuity of movements. The discontinuity of Space is 
 inconceivable, not because there must be an interval of Space 
 between any two points, but because we should find an 
 immeasurable and impenetrable barrier between them. The 
 movements of primary importance in the cognition of Space 
 are, doubtless, those of our own (and ancestral) limbs ; which, 
 extended to all practicable distances and turned in all possible 
 directions, have carved out that geometrical character of Space 
 in which the human mind seems to be exploring its own 
 infinite resources. But in experience the exploration of Space 
 is relative to bodies that occupy and determine it : for it 
 happens through the movements of our own body or limbs. 
 
184 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 sometimes leading to contact with other bodies, sometimes 
 swinging free. 
 
 Space, therefore, is not known as relation without terms ; 
 for bodies in Space are terms in the experience of space- 
 relations ; and even when the arm swings free, the relation 
 perceived is not without its appropriate term, for there is 
 special sensation in the finger-tips when they do not, as truly 
 as when they do, touch a body. And further experience 
 shows that the tingling absence of contact is a sign of possible 
 further movement, which again must be imagined to end 
 either in contact or not. Similarly the focussing of the eyes 
 on an unoccupied point has its own sensitive registration. 
 But, again, since the same movements and adjustments have 
 under different conditions different results, it becomes possible 
 to conceive of Space apart from any particular perceptions, 
 and to study the relations of distance and direction from any 
 points assumed. For, by the way, distance and direction are 
 the fundamental relations of Space, or of points in Space ; 
 not relations in the abstract, of which to be sure there could 
 not be parts ; but distance and direction are defined by lines 
 and angles, and of these there may be parts. 
 
 Body is known as occupying Space by its offering resistance 
 to pushing and grasping. When a moving limb explores a 
 greater or less extension, and all the way its tactile organs 
 obtain continuous stimulation, a muscular contraction that 
 intensifies the tactile sensation at any point has a certain 
 quality of strain in contrast with the sliding ease of those 
 muscular contractions that lessen, or put an end to, the tactile 
 sensation. Body being extended, then, it is conceived to be, 
 like Space, infinitely divisible ; that is to say, geometrically 
 considered, it is infinitely divisible. But whether it is so in 
 fact, considered physically, is entirely a question for physical 
 science. It is in vain to say with Descartes, who identified 
 Body with Space, that whatever is extended must consist of 
 parts ; for whether every Body has physical parts is the very 
 question at issue. To say that whatever the force of its 
 coherence, a greater force is conceivable, which may, therefore, 
 break it up, is to commit two fallacies. For, first, to speak of 
 
TIME, SPACE, MATTER ANJ) MOTION 185 
 
 its coherence is to assume that it has parts that cohere, the 
 geometrical conception is slid into the physical question. 
 And, secondly, the assumption is made that if we can conceive 
 a force capable of breaking up a given whole, such a force in 
 fact exists ; and there can be no worse prejudice. There may, 
 therefore, be physical atoms : the existence or non-existence 
 of atoms is to be determined by scientific method in the con- 
 ceptual interpretation of experience. 
 
 Even if it should be shown that a chemical atom consists 
 of ether, it would not follow that it consists of parts, unless 
 it were shown that ether itself consists of parts ; and if this 
 should be shown, the question would return as to the ether- 
 atom (the physical as distinguished from the chemical), 
 whether that consists of parts. Similar reasoning holds good 
 of the electrons, of which chemical atoms are now supposed 
 to consist ; whether electrons be ultimate and indivisible, or, 
 again, condensed ether. That if the chemical atom consists 
 of ether or electrons, its distinctive character is conditional and 
 may be temporary, has hardly any metaphysical significance. 
 
 Since Motion is a traversing of Space in Time, it is 
 conceived to be infinitely divisible ; that is to say, there is 
 no limit to the smallness of the Space that may be considered 
 as traversed, nor to the smallness of the Time that elapses in 
 the traversing of a given Space. Such conceptions are easy 
 symbolical extensions of Empirical Reality, and are justified 
 by the verification of physical calculations. 
 
 § 5. It remains to consider whether Time, Space, Matter 
 and Motion are finite or infinite in duration or extent. This 
 question is often argued upon the ground of what we can 
 imagine or conceive. But imagination depends upon empirical 
 perception, and as the untutored mind often perceives Matter 
 or Motion originating or ceasing, there is no difficulty in 
 imagining it. Nor, it seems to me, is there any difficulty in 
 forming an isolated concept of the beginning or ending of 
 things. But how does all this affect the question of fact ? 
 When for empirical we substitute experimental perception, 
 the beginning and cessation of Matter and Motion is no longer 
 perceived, and to scientific investigators (I understand) it 
 
186 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 ceases to be imaginable ; and the conception of it is in con- 
 tradiction with the principles of scientific explanation. If 
 the principles of the persistence of Matter and Energy be 
 admitted, and extended throughout the stellar system, on the 
 ground that some at least of the chemical elements exist, and 
 the laws of mechanics and physics prevail, in remote stars ; 
 and if it be acknowledged that explanation consists in the 
 discovery of resemblance, especially in causes, and that equality 
 of ca,use and effect in all changes is the most complete explana- 
 tion ; it follows that the everlasting existence of the World 
 and its everlasting movement are necessary concepts. 
 
 It is merely the logical obverse of this doctrine that in 
 the phenomenal World a First Cause is inconceivable ; and that 
 any suspension or interruption of the order of equivalent 
 changes is inconceivable. It is true that, for the same reason, 
 the explanation of the present World can never be complete, 
 because the regress of causes can never be followed to infinity, 
 and no unconditional beginning can be found in the infinite 
 series. It is also true that within the period during which 
 the World is known to have existed the series of events is still 
 very imperfectly articulated in thought ; many things — of 
 which perhaps the origin of life is the most interesting — are 
 not understood. And some minds are so constituted that 
 whenever they are unable to explain an event by natural 
 antecedents, according to the usual principles of explanation, 
 they feel no difficulty in referring it to an extra-mundane 
 cause. Sometimes it is even said that science itself points 
 to such a cause ; but that is impossible. Whatever the 
 shortcomings of scientific inquirers, the ideal of science can 
 never require any explanation for anything, except equivalent 
 antecedent phenomena according to a law. Not appreciating 
 this limitation, those who appeal to extra-mundane causes do 
 not take enough pains to make clear the principles of their 
 reasoning. Unless they state in precise terms (1) the marks 
 by which we may know that an event not yet explained is 
 essentially insusceptible of scientific explanation, and (2) in 
 what sense any extra-mundane power can be a cause, or can 
 be the ground of explanation according to any analogy of 
 
TIME, SPACE, MATTER AND MOTION 187 
 
 experience, although their authority may weigh with those of 
 us who muft rely upon authority of some kind, they will 
 hardly convince the more rellective part of their fellow- 
 creatures. An exact treatise on the Logic of Extra-mundane 
 Inference and Explanation is still a desideratum. 
 
 If an infinite regress of the World's movements is required 
 by the principles of explanation, so of course is an infinite 
 Time. It happens that a finite Time cannot be imagined, 
 because it is never perceived : since in experience every 
 movement follows, and is followed by, others. But, on the 
 other hand, an infinite Time cannot be imagined : like 
 perception, imagination can only proceed to a given point and 
 beyond it. The imagination of Time is indefinite : to follow 
 the regress of movement to infinity requires an infinite Time 
 in which to accomplish it. But infinite Time may be 
 adequately conceived as exceeding any assignable limit. For 
 this is all that is required by the principle of explanation, that 
 to whatever point the history of the World may be traced 
 back, it remains to investigate the cause of the state of things 
 then existing. 
 
 § 6. In Space it is our constant experience that wherever 
 we go, there lies Space beyond us ; hence we cannot imagine 
 limits to Space. On the other hand, we cannot imagine it 
 infinite, for want of time to complete the exploration. Space 
 may be conceived as infinite or exceeding any assignable 
 limits, and Motion will then be conceived as having the same 
 range. And although it is often denied that Space can be 
 conceived as finite, I do not see any difficulty, if we do not 
 confound conception with imagination. The conception of a 
 limited Space implies a limited range of Motion. The concept 
 of infinite Space is not, like infinite Time, required by the 
 principle of explanation. 
 
 That Matter exists in Space is proved to us by oiur 
 grasping, circumambvdation and circumnavigation of things, 
 and by Astronomy. It follows that if Space is limited so is 
 Matter ; and if Matter is infinite in quantity. Space must be 
 infinite to contain it ; but if Space is infinite. Matter may still 
 be limited. The prevalence of a belief in the boundlessness of 
 
188 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 the material World (except amongst the Epicureaiis) seems to 
 be modern. But, recently, the evidence has l)ee^ interpreted 
 as indicating that Matter is a limited quantity, and attempts 
 have even been made to weigh the Universe. 
 
 Whether the World is finite or not has some metaphysical 
 interest. For supposing the atomic World to be finite and 
 the ether infinite, it must, according to the principle of the 
 degradation of Energy, run down in a finite time ; and 
 therefore, contrary to the principle of explanation, must have 
 had a beginning, in the sense that no known laws of 
 phenomena will explain how it began to work. But if the 
 ether is finite as well as the atomic World, there may be a 
 limit to the dissipation of Energy, and after that has been 
 reached the Universe may recover itself, and pulsate through 
 infinite series of evolutions and dissolutions. If the material 
 World is infinite, it can never run down. If Space is finite, 
 so is the ether ; but if Space is boundless, the ether may still 
 be a limited whole in the midst of it — unless subject to some 
 law of expansion and interminable diffusion which I have not 
 seen mentioned amongst its versatile properties. The whole 
 problem is essentially physical, and to attempt a metaphysical 
 solution of it a priori would, in my opinion, be ridiculous. 
 Still, it is a problem upon whose solution the principle of 
 explanation is staked, and Metaphysics is indirectly concerned 
 in it. Should the progress of physical inquiry make it appear 
 that Space is limited, it would at the same time accustom the 
 imagination to follow it ; for proceeding from experience, and 
 following the analogies of experience, the inquiry would itself 
 give experience of a limit without a beyond. 
 
 § 7. The nature of Time, Space, Matter and Motion, as at 
 present understood, presents no necessary limit to the elabora- 
 tion of Positive Philosophy. The foregoing discussions treat 
 of the problems which Kant, in his criticism of Rational 
 Cosmology, sets out in the form of Antinomies of Pure Reason. 
 Reason, he says, in endeavouring to explain the World, falls 
 into a dialectic within itself, because it assumes that the 
 conditioned phenomena of experience indicate an Unconditioned 
 Cause or ground; and its dialectic leads to contradictory 
 
TIME, SPACE, MATTER AND MOTION 189 
 
 conclusious because, as no such Unconditioned is given in 
 experience, but only as an Idea, there is no intuitive basis of 
 all the logoniacliy. 
 
 The Antinomies may be abbreviated thus : — 
 
 I. The World has a beginning 
 in Time and limits in Space. 
 
 II. Everything is either simple 
 or composed of simple parts. 
 
 III. Causality through freedom, 
 as well as by natural law, is 
 necessary to explain phenomena. 
 
 IV. A necessary Being exists as 
 part or cause of the World. 
 
 The World is infinite in Time 
 and Space. 
 
 There is not in the World any- 
 simple substance. 
 
 Everything happens according to 
 natural law. 
 
 There is no such necessary 
 Being. 
 
 Now, any one who reads through these propositions can see 
 that no Unconditioned Cause is assumed except by the first, third 
 and fourth theses, and that these three have the same meaning. 
 The antitheses are notliing but dogmatically expressed prin- 
 ciples of empirical Methodology ; namely, that no limit to 
 analysis is to be assumed, and that all investigation presup- 
 poses uniformity. Therefore, the whole imposing criticism 
 of Rational Cosmology — the origin of the problem, the strife 
 of Reason, the critical solution — is groundless. It is not 
 Philosophy but literary invention. De Quincey observes that 
 Kant's writings belong not to the literature of knowledge but 
 to the literature of power. Kant saw that " human reason is 
 naturally architectonic," and he essayed to gratify this instinct 
 by a prodigious exertion of constructive genius akin to the 
 faculty of Titanic artists. He explains nothing, but he is 
 deeply affecting. Both the architectonic instinct and the 
 impulse to gratify it, no doubt, prognosticate the future develop- 
 ment of knowledge. 
 
 Kant next discusses the interest of Reason in the 
 Antinomies : if we must take sides, which set of propositions 
 should we desire to see victorious ? First, there is a practical 
 interest in favour of the theses ; because, that the World has 
 a beginning and depends upon a necessary Being, and that the 
 
190 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 course of the World is determined not only by natural law 
 but also by free causality — these are the grounds of religion 
 and morals. Secondly, there is a certain speculative interest 
 on the side of the theses ; for if there was a beginning of the 
 World, and if every compound consists of simple parts, we 
 may hope to carry our investigation of Nature to an end and 
 complete our scientific system. And, thirdly, there is a 
 popular interest on the same side ; for the vulgar mind would 
 gladly see speculation finished and done with. Besides, in 
 the dogmatism of Reason (so Kant calls the theses) the vulgar 
 find themselves on a level with the learned ; have indeed this 
 advantage, that the philosopher feels some qualms, but the 
 vulgar none at all, in accepting the incomprehensible. Hence, 
 he says, the antitheses of Empiricism, demanding exact 
 thought and endless labour, will never prevail outside the 
 Schools or find favour with the crowd. For the speculative 
 interest of Empiricism lies in this very fact, that it knows no 
 limits to the exploration of Nature ; whose laws it may trace 
 with certainty, dealing with the facts themselves in perception, 
 or with conceptions that can be verified by distinct percepts. 
 Such an attitude of mind is incompatible with the expectation 
 of finding a beginning of the World or any breach in its order. 
 But, therefore, it is contrary to the practical interests of 
 morality and religion : " If there is no Urwesen distinct from 
 the World ; if the World is without a beginning and there- 
 fore without a Creator ; if the Will is not free and if the Soul 
 is, like Matter, divisible and perishable ; moral ideals and 
 principles lose all their validity, and fall along with the 
 transcendental Ideas which were their theoretical buttresses." 
 
 It is impossible to find in literature a more desperate 
 sentence than this, or a more false. It is false that morality 
 or religion depends upon the dogma of creation. It is false 
 that morality or religion depends upon the dogma that the 
 will is exempt from natural law. That there is any opposi- 
 tion between empirical science and morality is false. Happily 
 too : for is it not plain that science is what every one now 
 trusts, and believes in, more than in anything else ? And 
 what can be more pernicious to human life than to put 
 
TIME, SPACE, MATTER AND MOTION 191 
 
 morality in conflict with men's convictions ? Yet in sympathy 
 with Kant's most imluippy delusion, persistent attempts arc 
 made to di.sparage the sciences ; not merely by necessary criti- 
 cism, but in the spirit of scepticism for the sake of faith : a 
 fatal error! For faith is always born of faith, and scepticism 
 has no offspring but scepticism. 
 
BOOK III.-PSYCHOLOGY 
 
 13 
 

CHAPTER X 
 
 THE SUBJECT IN EXPERIENCE 
 
 § 1. Having arrived at the early maturity, or prematurity, of 
 Reason, Man finds himself amidst a world of which he is 
 indisputably the head. The earth is covered with his works, 
 his cities and possessions, his empires. That other things 
 about him are conscious and even intelligent, serves only to 
 emphasise his superiority. Glancing down over the ranks of 
 living things and seeking for the widest and most decisive 
 difference between himself and them, he defines himself the 
 " rational animal." Long ago he recognised the other animals 
 as his kindred ; then he doubted and even denied their claim 
 to relationship ; now he acknowledges it again, but is loath to 
 draw any inferences from it, except to excuse his own vices, or 
 to find fresh grounds for self-satisfaction. 
 
 But he has long been accustomed to believe in another sort 
 of kindred : even other men who have left their palpable bodies 
 and become impalpable and invisible, except sometimes at night 
 when the conditions are least favourable to distinct vision. 
 These others, the doubles, shades or ghosts of men, once had a 
 world of their own much like ours, and their life there was 
 something entirely natural and matter of course. As they had 
 not wholly lost their interest in our world, nor forgotten their 
 former affections, antipathies and fixed ideas, the neighbourhood 
 of their viewless world, which might at any moment invade 
 our own, became a disturbing but also a restraining power 
 over men's actions. As human society developed and division 
 of labour, rank and government were established, a parallel 
 development happened in the kingdom of the dead ; and in 
 
 1Q5 
 
196 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 the great religions those kingdoms attained a power and 
 exaltation far above all fleshly rule ; supernatural and divine, 
 overwhelming imagination with wonder and awe. 
 
 Man's relationship to this unseen world became an absorb- 
 ing interest ; and since rank was there distinguished by 
 intelligence as well as by power, the dignity of his rational 
 nature was enhanced ; whilst his animal nature was degraded, 
 until the body, as seat of the animal nature, became the prison 
 of the soul, or a wild beast, or a corrupting corpse to which the 
 soul was un wholesomely fettered. The reward of the religious 
 life was honour there and the expansion of reason ; of the 
 irreligious the reward was degradation to a brutal life and the 
 obscuring of reason, or else to a shameful life in the dungeons 
 of demoniacal wrath amongst the " dejected and downtrodden 
 vassals of perdition." As the unseen world was more lasting, 
 more powerful, more vital and comprehensive than this one, so 
 it was more real ; and therefore the shade or soul that should 
 dwell there was more real than the body. Hence when onto- 
 logical discussion arose it was easily decided that, since the 
 most real things are called substances, the soul must certainly 
 be a substance. 
 
 In modern cities men are safe, busy and prosaic. Gradually 
 there grow up systems of thought and habits of thinking that 
 readily assimilate positive interpretations and exclude the 
 mythological. The interference of things unseen is no longer 
 traceable ; and, unsupported by either experience or utility, 
 the too elaborate structures of celestial and diabolical tradition 
 disintegrate and fall by their own weight. At first slowly, 
 then rapidly, the ancient beliefs lose form and content : 
 their imaginations become unimaginable ; the supernatural, 
 unnatural ; the wonderful, merely perplexing. In the history 
 of Philosophy the change came late, but very suddenly. At 
 the end of the seventeenth and beginning of the eighteenth 
 centuries, Locke and Leibniz still speak of angels as familiarly 
 as we do of pterodactyls, and then they are no more heard of. 
 But man is still defined as a " rational animal," and the soul, 
 under the name of the conscious Subject, is still generally 
 assumed to be a substance. 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXPERIENCE 197 
 
 § 2. Approaching the study of life and mind from the 
 side of Physics, we find Consciousness, the essential character 
 of the Subject, a sort of mystery ; it is like nothing that has 
 hitherto been met with, and therefore wants the ground of 
 explanation. As Huxley says, the rise of consciousness after 
 the stimulation of a sensory nerve is as mysterious as the 
 appearance of the Djin when Aladdin rubbed his lamp. Not 
 only on the strictly mechanical, but on any physical theory — 
 even admitting mechanics, chemistry and vitality, to be ulti- 
 mate and irresolval)le processes — consciousness seems a useless 
 ' extra ' ; and a thinker may pose himself with doubts whether 
 he has any right to think before he has explained how thinking 
 is useful or possible. As Subject, he is told that he is an epi- 
 phenomenon, a secondary, accidental and rather inconvenient 
 result, a sort of by-blow or parergon of the play of molecules 
 constituting the real phenomenon, his body, especially his brain, 
 most particularly the grey matter of his cortex. To protest 
 that he is indeed there, places him in the ridiculous position 
 of poor Partridge after the Examiner had announced his 
 funeral. Nevertheless, since to trust the conceptual system of 
 Physics apart from Empirical Eeality, is to cut off the bough 
 on which you sit, it is necessary to return to the security of 
 primitive fact ; and there the Subject recovers his rights. 
 Whilst the reality of the Object is in my opinion not seriously 
 disputable, still, even if it is, at any rate the reality of the 
 Subject is not disputable at all : it is conceded even by 
 mechanical engineers. 
 
 Consciousness being real, why from the side of Physics 
 should it seem inexplicable ? Because it is not regarded as a 
 mode of energy in correlation with those modes that Physics 
 investigates ; and if this is true, a living body may be con- 
 ceived to go through all its changes and discharge all its 
 functions without the aid of consciousness. Consciousness, 
 therefore, appears as something detached, otiose, and useless. 
 As detached, it has no value in the equations of change 
 through which matter and energy pass in the evolution and 
 dissolution of animal bodies. To take account of it spoils the 
 equations ; for with life, or at some stage of life, consciousness 
 
198 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 is manifest, and yet there is no traceable antecedent ; so that 
 the principle of continuity, in the form ex nihilo nihil, seems 
 to be violated. Again, as useless, consciousness is equally 
 inexplicable by the biological theory of Natural Selection, 
 according to which every organ and function of an animal is, 
 or has been, useful to it (allowing for possible " correlated 
 growths "). Here also, then, no antecedent can be traced. 
 So it seems to follow either that consciousness is really a mode 
 of energy, or that the principle of Causation and Continuity 
 is not true. There are, however, three other suppositions : (1) 
 that consciousness is created when it first appears in animal 
 life; (2) that it is due to a soul which at some stage of 
 evolution is united with the animal body; (3) that conscious- 
 ness is universal in Nature, inorganic as well as organic, and 
 that its special manifestation in organic life is a correlated 
 growth of the organisation. 
 
 Of these suppositions (1) and (2) involve many considera- 
 tions that lie outside the scope of the present volume. Here, 
 however, we may say that the concept of absolute creation ex 
 nihilo can never be an explanation of anything, because it is 
 not like any known process ; so that if it should appear that 
 Religion requires such a concept, nevertheless, it cannot find 
 a place within any philosophical system. Some points 
 i/ connected with the notion of a soul — namely, substance and 
 
 personality — we shall presently discuss. Meanwhile it may 
 be observed that supposition (3), that consciousness is universal 
 in Nature, allows us to understand that all equations of 
 change in the redistributions of matter and transformations of 
 energy may be treated without error in terms of those things 
 that are measurable ; whilst at the same time the equations 
 are satisfied by corresponding values of consciousness on each 
 eide of them ; though these cannot be precisely measured and 
 are only known to us as accompanying certain changes in our 
 own organisms : and further to understand that, if in the 
 activities of our organisms consciousness cannot be shown to 
 be specially useful, that is (as we have said before) because it 
 is universally necessary. 
 
 It may be asked — Why universal in Nature ? Why not 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXPERIENCE 199 
 
 rather as accompanying the activities of those elements that 
 enter into organic life — H, O, C, N, S, P, etc. ? For by no 
 means all tlie elements are concerned : man is not in this 
 sense a microcosm. Phosphorus especially, it may be said, 
 has been thought the essential condition : but the evidence of 
 its special relation to consciousness has (I believe) been over- 
 stated. And as to H, O, C, N, it does not follow that, because 
 they have the character that best fits them for organisation 
 on this planet, they are therefore the sole conditions of con- 
 sciousness, or even of organisation. And if all elements have 
 a common ground (ether or protyle) it is more reasonable to 
 look to the activities of that as the concomitant of conscious- 
 ness than to any special groupings of it ; and if consciousness 
 exists there, it may be supposed to exist in the activities of 
 all the elements that have arisen from that common ground. 
 It would, however, be more correct to say that consciousness 
 accompanies the activities of that of which the elements, 
 ether, protyle, are phenomena ; for all phenomena have their 
 Eeality by existing in consciousness. 
 
 § 3. Now it is certain that consciousness exists in many 
 degrees of fidness and intensity, several of which are known 
 to us. First, there is discursive thought with the infinite 
 variety of ideal and emotional life which we consider to be 
 distinctively human : and this we may call self-consciousness 
 or apperception. Secondly, there is the narrower region of 
 perception, activity and feeling which we share with (at least) 
 the higher animals : it is a state of mind which incursions of 
 the higher powers perturb and hinder, the state in which a 
 man plays billiards or a dog noses about for rabbits. Both 
 these degrees of mental activity in their greatest efficiency are 
 characterised by the attitude of attention, in which conscious- 
 ness is focussed. But, thirdly, in contrast with such ' focal,' 
 there is ' marginal ' consciousness (to use Lloyd Morgan's 
 pregnant terms), the much greater volume of sensation and 
 feeling which is present in consciousness without being 
 attended to, sometimes seems struggling to attract attention 
 and sometimes succeeds, and is always ready to become more 
 lively and prominent whenever attention relaxes or wanders. 
 
200 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Then, fourthly, there is (as it seems to me) a far vaster region 
 which rarely comes into distinct consciousness at all — petites 
 perceptions — which may sometimes be discovered experiment- 
 ally or by trained introspection, is sometimes made known in 
 abnormal or diseased conditions, is sometimes only hypothetic- 
 ally discoverable (such as the elements of sensation integrated 
 or fused in the perception of space, in an emotion, in the 
 coenfiesthesis) : and this I propose to call sentience. 
 
 So far we have modes of consciousness and sub-conscious- 
 ness that are all in some sort known to us as entering into or 
 profoundly affecting our lives, and of which the more obscure 
 are believed to be shared in some degree by lowlier organised 
 animals even down to the simplest forms. I do not mean 
 that these grades of consciousness are mutually exclusive or 
 exactly defined. On the contrary, the higher grades depend 
 on the lower and consist chiefly in the co-ordination of them ; 
 and within each grade, again, finer distinctions might be 
 made. In sentience, especially, it is impossible to say 
 how many degrees there are of faintness and indistinctness. 
 Perhaps Binet, in his Psychology of Micro-Organisms, has 
 exaggerated the variety and definiteness of their consciousness ; 
 and similarly Wundt, when he says in his Outlines (§ 14) that 
 " the movements of the lowest animals are all evidently simple 
 volitional acts." Lloyd Morgan, in his Animal Behaviour, is 
 judiciously sceptical : whether a certain process in Paramecium 
 is accompanied by sentience, he says, we do not know. " That 
 it is controlled and guided by any consciousness in the cell 
 is most improbable" (p. 13). The "profiting by individual 
 experience is the criterion of the effective presence of conscious 
 guidance and control " (p. 31). But this means " the influence 
 of certain nerve-centres which have for their concomitant what 
 we have termed effective consciousness " (p. 51). So that in 
 no case is there a question of anything but concomitance of 
 consciousness : its degree varying with organisation. Whoever 
 grants consciousness to the new-hatched chick but denies it 
 to the new-laid egg, can only excuse his rejection of continuity 
 by some device for conjuring a ghost into the chicken. 
 
 But, again, the simplest forms of life are indistinguishably 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXPERIENCE 201 
 
 animal or vegetal; and if the least organised plant life is 
 indistinguishable from animal life that is admitted to be 
 conscious, it is arbitrary to deny consciousness of such plant 
 life ; and, if so, it is still more arbitrary to deny it of more 
 higlily organised plants. This may offer some excuse for those 
 poets who, like Shelley and Wordsworth, have believed in the 
 sentiency of tlowers and trees. But evidence of it, or at least 
 strongly suggestive matter, may be found in the phenomena 
 of irritability, contractility and purposive movement exhibited 
 by plants. These ideas have been entertained by many 
 botanists and biologists since Darwin published his investiga- 
 tions into plant-movement. Plants possess what may be most 
 naturally called sense-organs in relation to gravitation, contact, 
 light and perhaps other stimuli; these organs seem to have 
 developed like those of animals from the epithelium; and 
 their stimulation excites reflexes, which, according to Francis 
 Darwin {Nature, Nov. 1901), are of the same type as action 
 in animals by association, and therefore allied to habit and 
 memory. 
 
 Having got so far beyond the range of human sympathy 
 as the level of plant-life, the principle of Continuity carries us 
 further and points to some actuality even in inorganic Nature 
 corresponding with animal consciousness, however vague and 
 undifferentiated. Of course, we cannot imagine what it is 
 like. The feeling of movement, energy, striving, which we 
 commonly read into the operations of Nature, is with us 
 a specialised sensation having its own organs, peripheral, 
 afferent, central. There is a natural hesitation to ascribe 
 consciousness not only to things that have no nervous system 
 (for this is not traceable lower than the Medusse) but even to 
 those that have not the special form of matter from which 
 nerve-fibres and ganglia develop, such as we suppose to exist 
 in simple animals and plants. 
 
 But perhaps ere long it may be shown that the differences 
 between the organic and inorganic are much less than we are 
 now accustomed to assume. J. C. Bose, in his Response in the 
 Living and the Non-Living, after showing that under electrical 
 stimuli plants exhibit fatigue, etc., and are affected like animals 
 
202 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 by ansesthetics and poisons, goes on to prove the same pro- 
 perties of tin and platinum wire. These also become fatigued ; 
 there is a threshold of response ; subliminal stimuli become 
 effective by repetition ; response increases with the intensity of 
 stimulus up to a certain point at which another limit is 
 reached ; response is affected by temperature, and the median 
 range is most favourable to it ; some substances act as stimulants 
 upon tin and platinum, others like anaesthetics, others as 
 poisons (destroying all response) ; a small dose may increase 
 the response, and a large dose of the same agent abolish it. 
 The resemblance of these results to some of those obtained in 
 Physiological Psychology is obvious. 
 
 Inorganic matter is much simpler than organic, and so is 
 its molecular activity; the simpler an organism, the simpler 
 its consciousness; hence no doubt inorganic consciousness is 
 the simplest of all. If it be true that one organic cell may 
 comprise 300,000,000,000,000 atoms; and if it is difficult 
 to imagine what the consciousness of a cell can be like, compared 
 with our own ; the consciousness of an atom must seem to us to 
 be pretty near the vanishing point. But so is the magnitude 
 of physical atoms and of some ether waves at the vanishing 
 point. By the standard of customary ideas, all physical 
 speculations seem monstrous and maniacal. I make the very 
 reasonable request that the same possibility of infinite refine- 
 ment should be recognised in consciousness, as already has 
 been acknowledged in the case of " gross, dead, brute matter," 
 as it used to be called. Whoever refuses this, ought to say 
 whether he denies the principle of Continuity, or knows of some 
 magic by which a ghost is conjured into every organic cell. 
 
 It is true that the characteristic of our own consciousness 
 is relationality : petites perceptions are only knowable when 
 occasionally they come into relation v^ith the larger masses of 
 our experience, and the most convincing ground for believing 
 that our minds correspond with our nervous systems is the 
 manifest fitness of these systems for carrying out the relational 
 processes of our minds. But if from the analysis of our own 
 minds we infer that consciousness can only exist through the 
 continuous relation of its elements, it is impossible to explain 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXrERIENCE 203 
 
 the beginning of consciousness in organic life; or in any indi- 
 vidual, unless it be said that such consciousness is transmitted 
 by germs in virtue of their predisposition to develop a nervous 
 system ; or on awaking from sleep, except by maintaining that 
 we are apperceptive all night without being aware of it. But 
 how many people would rather maintain a contradiction than 
 follow an argument ! 
 
 If the ether be that from whose activities all things arise, 
 its psychoses have an inexpressible simplicity, purity and calm 
 — invidious to contemplate : having the best claims of any- 
 thing to the whole list of predicates that have always been 
 ascribed to the Absolute — one and the same, universal, un- 
 changing, self-active, everlasting and supra-substantial. We 
 cannot indeed, at the present stage of our argument, regard 
 this absolute consciousness as a Subject ; for subject implies 
 object, whilst consciousness (as such) does not. Consciousness 
 is not necessarily a knowledge of something else ; that contrast 
 arises with the increasing volume and differentiation of organic 
 minds ; though even we, in spite of our highly specialised 
 growth, sometimes pass through experiences during which the 
 distinction of subject and object is nearly, or entirely, lost. 
 But even the denial of subjectivity to the absolute conscious- 
 ness need not be resented ; it is a condition of limitation, 
 opposition and of all pain : and, therefore, it is no compliment 
 to the Universal Ether to insist upon calling it " Subject " after 
 the model of ourselves. 
 
 § 4. According to this hypothesis of the universality of 
 consciousness in Nature, it everywhere accompanies the move- 
 ments or activities of that which is manifested to sense-percep- 
 tion and which, conceptually, is figured to exist as atoms and 
 ether, but which itself is necessarily transcendent. On the 
 other hand, each human Subject at least is still regarded 
 as a Substance. Every one knows that Descartes defined 
 the Self to be a thinking Substance, and how many later 
 philosophers have discussed that position of his. I shall have 
 to return to it in the next chapter on the Ontology of the 
 Subject ; but here it is necessary to consider whether the 
 Subject is Substance, or how far it may be considered so, on 
 
204 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 empirical grounds, just as we have already done in the seventh 
 chapter concerning objects or bodies; and we may conveniently 
 begin with Locke's opinion. In his Essay of H. U. (Book II. 
 chap, xxiii.), having shown that we have no distinct idea of the 
 substance of bodies, but only a supposition of one knows not 
 what support of such qualities as are capable of producing 
 simple ideas in us — an obscure and relative idea, — he goes on 
 to maintain (§ 15) with much humour that, "by putting 
 together the ideas of thinking, perceiving, liberty and power of 
 moving themselves and other things, we have as clear a 
 perception and notion of immaterial substances, as we have of 
 material. For our idea of substance is equally obscure, or 
 none at all, in both." The primary ideas of body, he says, 
 are the cohesion of solid, and consequently separable, parts, 
 and a power of communicating motion by impulse ; figure is 
 only a consequence of finite extension : the ideas peculiar to 
 spirit are thinking and will, or a power of putting body into 
 motion by thought ; existence, duration, mobility are common 
 to both (§§ 17-18). "We have by daily experience clear 
 evidence of motion produced both by impulse and by thought. 
 . . . Pure spirit, God, is only active ; pure matter is only 
 passive ; those beings (such as men) that are both active and 
 passive, we may judge to partake of both " (§ 28). 
 
 Here then we may seem to be taking our stand upon 
 experience ; though in fact the ground is mined by scholastic 
 prejudices. Substances are known by their attributes ; that 
 could be assumed : matter especially might be taken for 
 granted. As to spirit, Locke knows there will be greater 
 difficulty in bringing home its substantiality to the ordinary 
 reader ; but, he urges, the argument is as good for this as for 
 that. Here too there are certain attributes or "peculiar ideas," 
 namely, thought and will, or the power of moving bodies by 
 thought : these attributes are distinct from those of matter, 
 and imply a distinct substance — so far as we can form any idea 
 of substance ; why is not the argument convincing ? Partly, 
 no doubt, because most men are so continuously engrossed in 
 manipulating material bodies and think so seldom of their own 
 minds, that they are not accustomed to apply to the latter any 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXPERIENCE 205 
 
 category : partly, by mere force of association between the word 
 substance and bodies. But even to the psychologist or meta- 
 physician retiection discovers many diflicul ties in maintaining the 
 substantiality of the Self. Subjective consciousness is so different 
 from the objective qualities of bodies, solidity, movement, etc., 
 that it does not directly suggest a substance in the same 
 sense as they do : it wants vividness, steadiness, independence, 
 permanence, continuity and measure in its changes. Its most 
 constant character, the nisus or kinujsthesis, had until recently 
 gone unnoticed or unnamed. Few philosophers have adopted 
 such a doctrine as Hamilton's of "unconscious mental modifica- 
 tions," according to which all past thoughts still exist in the 
 substance of the soul, as bodies are supposed to when out of 
 sight ; and no one, I believe, except Leibniz (of whom in 
 Chap. XL), has suggested that future thoughts already exist 
 like undiscovered bodies. But all this seems necessary in 
 order to put the substance of mind on the same footing as the 
 substance of matter. It is very natural to regard consciousness 
 as an activity of the organic body ; and in fact that is what 
 happens when consciousness is attributed to the soul or ghost; 
 for this is a shadow, double, or imitation of the body and is 
 intensely imagined as an objective thing. Being less palpable 
 and visible than the body, it is now conceived by meta- 
 physicians as of a wholly different nature. But, surely, con- 
 sciousness would never have been supposed to imply a distinct 
 substance from the body, had not the belief in ghosts arisen 
 from other causes, and been universally popular before the 
 beginning of philosophical reflection. Besides, if substance is 
 an obscure relative idea of I know not what even when referred 
 to bodies ; how much more obscure it becomes if we attempt 
 to refer it to bodies and also to such a different thing as 
 consciousness. 
 
 § 5. Whether Subject is Substance, then, must depend 
 upon that other attribute which Locke ascribes to it, the 
 power of moving bodies. But this attribute is common to 
 bodies and created spirits ; and if Locke regarded bodies as 
 having received their original impulse from God, he certainly 
 regarded all the powers of created spirits as derived from the 
 
2a6 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 same source ; and there is no difference between a body's 
 moving another by impulse, and a spirit doing the same by 
 thought, except that the latter process is more obscure because 
 we can trace no equivalence. If, then, the attribute of 
 motivity be the same in bodies and spirits, it points to the 
 same substance as common to both. However, in Locke's 
 view, God has endowed spirits with self-activity and has 
 denied this to matter; he held that spirits and bodies are 
 entirely different ; so, as it is of little use to argue with him 
 now, I will turn to more recent ways of thinking. 
 
 If thought itself moves bodies, it must be either as a 
 mode of energy correlated with others, or not. In the former 
 case it belongs to the system of material things, just as they 
 do. But as this may seem to imply a charge of " materialism " 
 against such a way of thinking, I beg leave to say that the 
 term " materialism " is here used descriptively, not contume- 
 liously. A system of Materialism is, in my esteem, as respect- 
 able as a system of Spiritualism, if it is as well reasoned ; and 
 if better reasoned, it is more respectable. Why not, seeing 
 that our knowledge of bodies shows them to be far more 
 wonderful than anything we have been told of spirits ? 
 
 But now in the alternative case, that thought moves bodies, 
 not as a mode of energy, but in some way peculiar to itself; 
 what shall we say of it ? I say that whatever is peculiar can 
 neither explain anything nor be explained, and has no place 
 in philosophy. 
 
 If indeed consciousness could be separated from organised 
 bodies and experimented with in isolation, empirical laws 
 might conceivably be discovered concerning its relation to 
 moving bodies ; but such laws would merely make a list by 
 themselves, not only irrelevant to, but in conflict with, the 
 laws of energy. 
 
 Let us then inquire what evidence there is that thought 
 moves bodies. It is now generally held that our consciousness 
 of activity, or sense of effort, is excited by muscular, tendinous, 
 articular stimuli in moving, straining, etc., just as colour or 
 sound is due to the stimulus of the optic or aural nerve ; that 
 is to say, it points to the influence of body on mind rather 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXPERIENCE 207 
 
 thuu of mind on body. Thus what was formerly the most 
 popular iU'gument in favour of the moving power of thought, 
 or will-force, has quite lost its significance. 
 
 Spencer, however, thinks that states of consciousness are 
 " factors " in our nervous and physical activities, and for this 
 opinion he gives three reasons: (1) the facts of habit "prove 
 that states of consciousness which were at first accompaniments 
 of sensory impressions and resulting motions, gradually cease 
 to be concomitants " ; they suggest that consciousness " exists 
 in any line of communication in course of establishment and 
 disappears when the communication becomes perfect." But I 
 do not see that this proves anything more than that distinct 
 consciousness accompanies the activities of the more plastic 
 and less organised matter of the cortex, and sinks to some 
 lower degree of consciousness or subconsciousness when organi- 
 sation has so far advanced that the current passes more rapidly 
 or by a shorter circuit. We must not exaggerate the uncon- 
 sciousness of habit : true habit, formed within the individual's 
 experience with little or no inherited predisposition, is not 
 only a conscious process, but is always liable to disturbances 
 and interruptions in which the fuller original consciousness 
 revives. Spencer's examples of reading and knitting fully 
 illustrate this. (2) "Sundry facts appear to imply that con- 
 sciousness is needful as an initiative in cases where there are 
 no external stimuli to set up the co-ordinated nervous changes : 
 the nervous structures, though capable of doing everything 
 required if set going, are not set going unless there arises an 
 idea. Now this implies that an idea, or co-ordinated set of 
 feelings, has the power of working changes in the nervous 
 centres and setting up motions : tlie state of consciousness is 
 a factor." But whilst it is true that in many cases the 
 nervous structures are not set going unless there arises an 
 idea ; can we suppose that the idea arises without any 
 corresponding nervous change ? There may be no external 
 stimuli, or none traceable ; but this does not exclude central 
 excitation. And although the antecedents, whether physical 
 or mental, are by no means always known, and accordingly 
 psychologists discuss "free" or "spontaneous" ideas; yet 
 
208 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 they do not suppose such ideas to be absolutely free or spon- 
 taneous ; but regard them as having, of course, some physio- 
 logical concomitant, and therefore propose hypotheses, such as 
 local congestion, or omitted links. (3) There are "passive 
 emotions," such as grief, which, though directly dependent on 
 nervous changes, do not initiate actions ; so that the feeling 
 seems to be produced by the molecular activity and to absorb 
 it, since otherwise it must have further effects {First Princ. 
 71 b). But surely there are other ways, besides external actions, 
 by which the molecular activity accompanying grief may be 
 relieved. The vaso-motor discharge gives a sufficient accoimt 
 of it, and, by affecting the blood-supply to the voluntary tracts, 
 partly (at least) explains the passivity which characterises this 
 emotion. 
 
 In § 71c, Spencer declares the relation of consciousness 
 to nervous action to be on any hypothesis inconceivable ; he 
 mentions particularly the supposition that " consciousness in- 
 heres in the all-pervading ether," which may be capable under 
 special conditions in certain parts of the nervous system, of 
 being affected by nervous changes so as to result in feeling, 
 and reciprocally of affecting the nervous changes. But then, 
 he says, " we must assume that the potentiality of feeling is 
 universal," though realised only in special conditions ; and 
 such an explanation is merely verbal, since we know not what 
 the ether is. How mind and matter affect one another is a 
 mystery, but not a profounder one " than the transformation 
 of the physical forces into one another. All ultimate problems 
 are insoluble." To these positions, however, it is again 
 impossible to assent. The transformation of physical forces is 
 not a mystery in the same sense as the relation of mind and 
 body is : for it has been experimentally ascertained in detail, 
 and generalised in such a way as to satisfy the requirements 
 of explanation. But consciousness, besides the not being 
 definitely measurable, and therefore not equatable with physical 
 forces, is further of such a different character from them that 
 an equation is inconceivable : and where the conditions of 
 scientific explanation are wanting there is some sense in pro- 
 claiming a mystery. That any physical force and consciousness 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXPERIENCE 200 
 
 are so different that an equation, or any exchange between 
 them, is inconceivable, is in my judgment intuitively plain or 
 self-evident ; but this argument can have no weight with those 
 who see otherwise. 
 
 § 6. The very suggestion that possibly the ether may be 
 that in which " consciousness inheres," shows that consciousness 
 cannot be put upon the same footing with physical forces ; 
 for no one, I presume, would speak of light as " inhering " in 
 the ether. Physical light is the ether itself in a certain state 
 of vibration, but consciousness is nothing like vibration. The 
 truth is that neither the ether, nor the cerebral cortex, nor 
 any other phenomenon, can be the seat, or basis, or vehicle 
 of consciousness, even because all phenomena exist in 
 consciousness and cannot be related to it as they are to one 
 another. For exactly the same reason consciousness is not a 
 substance or a force ; all empirical substances and forces are 
 phenomena. To a free consideration consciousness does not 
 even suggest any substance : the dogma of its substantiality is 
 a mixture of savage superstition and scholastic gibberish. As 
 for its alleged simplicity, nothing is more contrary to every 
 man's experience. Its boasted unity is a mystical derivative 
 from the Greek's amazement at Arithmetic : organic totality 
 is the character of an individual Subject. 
 
 It ought not to be surprising that consciousness, or any 
 Subject, should not need to be a substance, seeing that itself 
 is Reality : with phenomena it is otherwise, and therefore they 
 need to be referred to a substance. But how is this : was it 
 not agreed that the world of sense-perception, i.e. phenomena, 
 constituted Empirical Reality, the ground and beginning of all 
 inquiry and of all confidence ? That is a very natural question ; 
 and I reply, first, that Empirical Reality is a mode of conscious- 
 ness, and in that sense has the reality of consciousness ; 
 secondly, that Empirical Reality is, as to confidence, more real 
 than the Transcendent Being, which (in Chap. VIII.) seemed 
 to be required by reflection upon experience ; and thirdly, that 
 it is only with reference to Transcendent Being that Empirical 
 Reality has the character of a phenomenon. The phenomenon 
 is constructed by the Subject, but is not subjective : reflection 
 
 14 
 
210 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 finds a difficulty in this, and tries to overcome it by considering 
 the phenomenon as representing something not subjective, 
 from which relation it has its objective character. It is 
 another way of expressing this relation to speak of the 
 phenomenon as consisting of the attributes of a substance. 
 
 There is no contradiction between simple experience and 
 reflection. Happily, this is impossible ; because the un- 
 sophisticated man has not our concepts, and we have not his 
 simplicity. If we try to put ourselves in his place, and say 
 — Now that tree is indisputably real ; yet, on reflection, it is 
 a phenomenon — this can only seem a contradiction from not 
 reflecting enough. To suppose that to be " representative " is 
 to want reality, confuses the philosophic with the popular or 
 political uses of this word. More reasonably it might be 
 contended that since the phenomenon has the reality of 
 consciousness and is also representative of the Ding an sich, it 
 has the power of both, and hence is more real than either of 
 them ; as, in fact, to simple experience it is. Representative- 
 ness is merely a way of considering phenomena in relation to 
 a Being which is half thought by an indicative or orectic 
 category for the sake of filling up a sort of blind-spot in 
 experience. 
 
 But if the Subject is not substance how is it related to 
 Transcendent Being ? Is it a phenomenon or an attribute of 
 that mysterious thing ? It is not a phenomenon, because it is 
 a condition of all phenomena ; and it is quite useless to call 
 it an attribute. We have seen (Chap. VII.) that even in 
 experience the category of Substance and Attribute can have 
 significance given to it only if we treat a part of any group 
 of attributes as substance in relation to some other of the 
 group : we cannot, therefore, by this analogy, transfer it 
 beyond experience. Further, Substance and Attribute in- 
 evitably suggest " prior and posterior in Nature," " higher and 
 lower," degrees of dignity in the list of the ten Categories, the 
 metaphysician's table of precedence ; and it is intolerable that 
 Self-consciousness should be logically inferior to an hypothesis. 
 Besides, to quote again Spinoza's definition, an attribute is 
 that which the intellect regards as of the essence of substance ; 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXPERIENCE 211 
 
 jind this is tlie necessiiry and linal definition : for what else 
 can an attribute be ? But, then, strictly speaking, intellect 
 knows only its own contents, and therefore the essence of 
 substance is exhausted by modes of consciousness. To call 
 consciousness the attribute of Being, then, would lead to a 
 contradiction with the conclusion already drawn that conscious- 
 ness is not the whole of Being. Of course, no words can 
 meet this dithculty ; but, perhaps, to think of consciousness as 
 an activity of Transcendent Being may be least misleading ; 
 and for the particular Subject, if any one must have a ' Thing ' 
 that thinks, he may take that Being of which the body is 
 phenomenon, and may (if he likes) call it the Soul. It would 
 be convenient, and I might do so myself, but for the latent 
 rhetoric of technical terms, that often gains adhesion without 
 unanimity and assent without understanding. 
 
 § 7. I have been drawn by the trend of ideas into that 
 region beyond experience which belongs to our next chapter ; 
 but before closing this one there remains for discussion the 
 " relation of body and mind " as conceived by empirical 
 Physiology and Psychology. A belief in some connection of 
 body and mind is instinctive : Greek psychological speculation 
 is full of it; and with the development of modern Physiology 
 it has become increasingly definite. It is now almost 
 impossible to try to theorise about the mind without appealing 
 to what is supposed to be the bodily correspondence. It is 
 true that no physical theory can ever be an explanation of 
 mental activity; for the category of Causation fails us, and 
 even Eesemblance cannot be traced between mental and 
 physical processes but only between the relations of such 
 processes : I mean, there is no resemblance between the 
 excitement of the retina and a colour, nor yet between the 
 activity of the eye muscles and the kinaesthesis, but the retina 
 and the muscles co-operate, and so do colour and the 
 kinsesthesis, in the act of perception. Yet a physiological 
 theory of the processes corresponding with the mental life, 
 though so remotely explanatory, is strongly desired. 
 The reasons for desiring it, I take to be these : — 
 (1) Mental states cannot be developed by introspection, 
 
212 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 and traced in their connections and retraced, with enough 
 fulness, certainty and constancy to produce the conviction that 
 we are observing a thorough continuity of events according to 
 laws. I shall not sneer at the laws of association, which 
 in their day constituted the best Psychology extant ; but is 
 it not a great relief to have discovered " association-fibres " ? 
 Moreover, one's own consciousness is full of fag-ends. As 
 James Ward says, sensation cannot be explained by antecedent 
 psychoses : it is always beginning. It seems to me, further, 
 that most trains of thought never definitely end ; but 
 presently we find ourselves thinking of something else. The 
 fluctuation of attention is notorious : the occasion of it may be 
 external distraction as often as internal, or mere fatigue : but 
 what is the meaning of consciousness being fatigued ? 
 
 (2) Mental states give little opportunity for measurement : 
 except as to their time-relations, duration and interval, they 
 have no definite quantity. And in mental processes of any 
 complexity so much is subconscious that measurement is out 
 of the question. If, for example, we could measm-e the more 
 intense or conspicuous of our motives to any action, the 
 indefinite remainder would far outweigh them. This vagueness 
 and uncertainty of our subjectivity may be ascribed, partly, to 
 the withdrawal of attention from it by the predominant interest 
 of action in the external world : hitherto few people have seen 
 much use in introspection. Partly, it is due to the symbolic 
 character of apperception : this is necessary to the co-ordination 
 of consciousness, but it submerges all that which G-. F. Stout 
 calls the " meaning " of images and signs — incomparably the 
 greater portion of the consciousness involved ; so that more 
 and more of it lapses into subconsciousness. 
 
 (3) The first object of Psychology is to explain the nature 
 of the mind so far as it is common to us all : we therefore 
 turn to that upon which we can agree, physical fact. Each 
 man is a physical fact to all others : for you, your volition 
 precedes your action ; but for me, your action is a conversion 
 of potential. Introspective Psychology can never explain a 
 completed volition. In the region of physical fact we find 
 measurement, continuity, law : we find it as instructive con- 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXrERIENCE 213 
 
 cerniiig idiosyncrasies as concerning our common nature : we 
 learn from it facts most important to the mental life which 
 introspection could never have discovered ; for example, the 
 function of the semi -circular canals. 
 
 (4) Througli Physiology, Psychology is connected with 
 Biology, obtains the aid of biological retrospect, biological laws 
 and the comparative method. This alliance has been the re- 
 birth of the science. 
 
 (5) It is througli our physical nature that society exists, 
 since our bodies are the sole means of communication ; and 
 consequently on our despised bodies depend religion, art, polity 
 and morals : upon all which subjects Physiology and Biology 
 are very instructive. 
 
 In short, self-observation or introspection does not afford 
 sufficient grounds for the construction of mental science ; and 
 it seems to me that this belongs to the nature of the mind as 
 immediate Reality ; that which admits of prolonged and exact 
 study by experiment and demonstration is the phenomenon. 
 Hence the attraction of physiological method. Psychologists 
 who, being also physiologists, attempt to construct mental 
 science by introspection alone, cannot eliminate the influence 
 of their physiological knowledge. An investigation the most 
 comprehensive possible into the physiological phenomena 
 is necessary ; and along with it a generalisation of the 
 conditions, so far as ascertainable, of the rise, activity and 
 lapse of the correlative consciousness. In pursuing these 
 inquiries it is now usual to assume a " parallelism " between 
 physical and mental processes ; for criticisms of that doctrine 
 James Ward's Naturalism and Agnosticism (Part III.) may be 
 consulted. In my judgment, if the doctrine of parallelism is 
 understood metaphysically, it makes the mistake of treating 
 consciousness as a phenomenon on the same footing as nervous 
 changes. For scientific purposes, indeed, any hypothesis that 
 is helpful is justifiable ; and in psychological discussions, it 
 would be pedantic to object to the practice of describing 
 processes of consciousness as phenomena of mind. But the 
 border between Psychology and Metaphysics is not always easy 
 to determine. Of course, it is not expected that an exact 
 
214 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 purallel should be discoverable between nervous or cerebral 
 changes on the one hand, and on the other those degrees of 
 consciousness that are open to introspection : the sinking into 
 subconsciousness of innumerable processes is a condition of the 
 unembarrassed supremacy of apperception, whether in control- 
 ling conduct or enlarging knowledge. 
 
 We have inferred the universality of consciousness, and 
 free-living cells are generally held to be conscious ; so that as 
 the human body is an organisation of cells and atoms, it is 
 natural to regard the human mind as an organisation of 
 consciousness. This consideration may remind the reader of 
 certain doctrines of " mind-stuff" ; but those doctrines, though 
 well meant, have (such of them as I have seen) the same fault 
 as the popular doctrine of parallelism ; namely, that they put 
 phenomena and Reality upon the same footing. Still, if I am 
 asked how my hypothesis is to be defended against the 
 assaults of William James in chap. vi. of his Principles 
 of Psychology, I reply (1) that he takes for granted that 
 a combination of mental processes must be causative and 
 mechanical, and that I have shown these Categories to be 
 inapplicable; and (2) that his assertion that an unity cannot 
 be formed of atoms except as it affects something else, is merely 
 a denial in the case at issue that this unity is a consciousness. 
 It is true he hints here that there is much to be said for 
 regarding the soul as that which is conscious ; but as, in chap. 
 X., he very candidly explains that the conception of the soul 
 is in his opinion quite useless, and that the present section of 
 the stream of consciousness may be regarded as carrying the 
 whole of it— and that for itself, not for some one else — I do 
 not see how he differs from his opponents ; especially the 
 Associationists : whom he misunderstands. 
 
 But, again, if there is an organisation of consciousness 
 into a more comprehensive unity, it does not follow that the 
 elements were originally discrete. No cells, since the origin 
 of life, are discrete (at least in the same line of descent) ; 
 they are discrete in space, but continuous in time, which we 
 have shown to have the greater reality. As to the molecules 
 of which cells are composed, whether they are really discrete 
 
THE SUBJECT IN EXPERIENCE 215 
 
 or in some way continuous through the ether, we do not know. 
 So far, theu, as we may infer from these phenomena to the 
 conscious Eeality, we have no ground for denying that all 
 Consciousness may be one continuum, though under special 
 conditions it rises at many points into special fulness. 
 
 If the question be put — How the rise of special minds 
 is possible ? the reply must serve, that the corresponding 
 growth of the body offers the best analogy for interpreting 
 the growth of the mind. What is ultimate is unique : there 
 can be no true analogue to the development of mind; but 
 organisation is the nearest we have. Because organisms alone 
 of things have their single interests in the series of birth, 
 youth, maturity, decay and death, they alone have a continuous, 
 unified teleological consciousness, and probably they alone 
 know pleasure and pain. Organic life is a constant struggle, 
 or co-operation, of the organism with other things that are 
 contrasted with itself; and the increasing consciousness of this 
 is self-consciousness. To make an extraordinary wonder of 
 self-consciousness has no ground but the love of wonder. Self 
 is the continuity of the consciousness and interest of that of 
 which the body is the phenomenon. The more widely the 
 interests of the organism extend to events in space and time, 
 the more comprehensive consciousness becomes, and the higher 
 self- consciousness rises : yet Schopenhauer rightly held that 
 this progress tends to the obliteration of individuality, through 
 recognition of the unity of the World whose self-consciousness 
 the individual is: for as a whole it cannot be self-conscious 
 for want of contrast. 
 
 If it be urged that, nevertheless, consciousness seems to be 
 of no more use to the world than to a single animal, since all 
 physical changes might go on just as well without it, such a 
 speculation ranges beyond my power of flight. A world 
 without consciousness would be a very different world from 
 the present one ; and what might be possible in it, is not for 
 me to say. That an animal, considered from the outside, may 
 be construed to lead its life independently of consciousness, 
 and, therefore, seems to have no need of it ; whilst we, being 
 animals ourselves, have no doubt that, inside, it is somehow 
 
216 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 conscious according to its organisation : this is good ground 
 for inferring that consciousness is the inside of all Nature, 
 from which plants and animals and men arise. But when we 
 turn to Nature herself, to speculate as to what may be useful 
 to her is grotesque. Shall we hear it suggested that the 
 present world is conscious in virtue of Natural Selection, all 
 other unconscious worlds having been annihilated in an 
 antecosmic struggle for existence, and that thereby tlie utility 
 of consciousness is proved ? Use is for them that lack ; for 
 you and me because we are limited and poor : for us, who 
 want and desire, utility seems a great matter. But these 
 things have no place in the world of Nature, serene above 
 hope or fear, and tranquil in inexhaustible sufficiency. 
 
CHAPTER XI 
 
 THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 
 
 § 1. According to the earliest beliefs concerning ghosts, they 
 were a kind of bodies, though of a more subtle material than 
 ordinary bodies. This was also the view of the early Greek 
 philosophers, even of Anaxagoras, and of the Stoics and 
 Epicureans for centuries later. Nay, though such a notion 
 would now by most people be verbally disavowed, all popular 
 stories and all the practices of Sludge imply that it still 
 prevails. It is generally held by scholars that the clear 
 conception of immaterialism was first reached by Plato. In 
 various Dialogues he describes the soul as most real, living, 
 self-active, unitary, by nature divine, without beginning or 
 end. On the other hand, his separation of the soul's faculties 
 is not easily reconcilable with its alleged unity, and the 
 doctrines of metempsychosis, degradation and purification, of 
 animal souls and plant souls and specific souls (that is the 
 Ideas) are all derived from traditionary mythology ; and the 
 parables by which he tries to explain himself are so thick with 
 suggestions of material things, that if we discard the imagery 
 it is impossible to say what remains. Still it is undoubtedly 
 from Plato chiefly that all these predicates concerning the 
 Soul — unity, simplicity, substantiality, immortality — descended 
 to the Rational Psychology of the seventeenth and eighteenth 
 centuries that suffered so severely under the criticism of Kant. 
 According to Aristotle, soul is the form or entelechy of an 
 organic body : the nutritive soul of plants exists in subordina- 
 tion to the sensitive soul in animals, and both to the rational 
 soul in man. Memory and imagination belong to the sensitive 
 
 217 
 
218 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 soul and are shared with man by the higher animals ; and 
 even in man reason itself has two functions, a passive and an 
 active, and its passive fimction is dependent on the i^avrda- 
 jxara of memory and imagination, consisting in what may be 
 called picture-thinking, whilst the higher processes of abstrac- 
 tion and unification belong to active reason. The sensitive 
 soul is transmitted by generation, grows with the individual 
 and dies ; but active reason, though born with a man, is not 
 generated but comes from without, and at death remains akin, 
 and returns, to the Keason of all things, thought of thought — 
 equivalent to form of form, — or absolute abstraction of actual 
 Being. Hence in Aristotle's view the soul is immaterial in 
 the sense that form is distinguished from matter in his system. 
 The individual soul is neither simple nor immortal, and is 
 self-active only in the sense that every living thing is self- 
 moving : it implies the existence of a body (its matter) and 
 each soul implies a particular body whose form it is ; so that 
 metempsychosis is impossible. On the whole, Aristotle's 
 doctrine is much further removed than Plato's from the 
 ghost-theory and all popular notions ancient or modern. It 
 is the most attenuated version of Animism : Spinoza's stands 
 nearest to it, amongst philosophic doctrines. 
 
 Immaterialism in the modern sense is much more explicitly 
 stated by Plotinus, developing the teaching of Plato ; but for 
 details I shall be content to refer to T. Whittaker's Neo- 
 Platonists (chap. v. § 1, on the Psychology of Plotinus). It 
 is, of course, Christian Theology that has moulded the great 
 body of existing belief about the soul: at least verbally, and sub- 
 ject to the influence of local traditions and to the limitations 
 of the popular mind when trying to apprehend metaphysical 
 concepts. Its doctrine of the immateriality of the soul is 
 explicit, in spite of the theory of a celestial body and many 
 imaginative forms employed in exposition ; the effect of which 
 upon the unmetaphysical disciple is to beget in most cases a 
 very materialistic way of thinking. 
 
 § 2. In the modern schools of philosophy discussions of 
 the soul or ego date from the definitions of Descartes. Matter 
 he defined by the single attribute of Extension, and Mind by 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 219 
 
 the single attribute of Thought. Since thinking was the only 
 f^round for believin<r in his own existence, it followed that he 
 was " a certain thing or substance whose whoh^ nature consists 
 in thinking, and needs for its existence neither any place nor 
 any material thing or body " {De Methudo, iv.). From this 
 passage subsequent speculations concerning the Subject set out 
 in three directions. 
 
 First, a strong current has followed the course ostensively 
 taken by Descartes himself : the Ego is a thinking Substance. 
 Little, indeed, can be said for his own argument : however we 
 may justify the inference from thought to existence, the further 
 transition to Substance is not formally legitimate. It is so 
 bad that, considering it in connection with other remarkable 
 paralogisms in this part of his philosophy, as well as other 
 data, some critics have suspected his sincerity ; but this has 
 no bearing upon the issue. A bad argument is bad even in 
 the mouth of a martyr ; yet there may be a legitimate way of 
 reaching the same conclusion. So strong is the sense of the 
 reality of consciousness, and so persistent the influence of the 
 ghost -theory in determining the way in which its reality 
 shall be conceived, that in every age some of the greatest 
 philosophers have striven to establish, or re-establish, the 
 position that consciousness, thought, or the ego is a Substance 
 or (by a vain refinement) an Agent. If the position ever 
 seems to be captured, it soon seems to be retaken : as we may 
 see in the Continental series, Leibniz, Kant, Lotze ; or in the 
 English series, Berkeley, Hume, J. S. Mill. 
 
 Secondly, reconsidering Descartes' data, instead of defend- 
 ing his conclusion, the more scientific inquirer recognises the 
 Empirical Eeality of consciousness, but sees that, whilst the 
 mind or Self is an immediate fact, yet it is not immediately 
 given as Substance but only as Subject. As to this Subject 
 problems arise similar to those that concern the Object : only 
 fragmentary experience being directly attainable, to find the 
 conceptual system that completes it ; its reality being granted, 
 to determine its relation to other real things, and this both 
 as to existence and as to knowledge. According to the 
 temperament of the men who undertake such inquiries, they 
 
220 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 may lead to the Scepticism of Hume or the Criticism of 
 Kant. 
 
 Or thirdly, considering the ostentatious feebleness of 
 Descartes' argument for the substantiality of the Soul, and 
 finding his mechanical Natural Philosophy of the world and 
 of the animal body far more interesting and fruitful, other 
 thinkers have been content to regard consciousness as a 
 function of the body : I mean the Materialists. Eare in 
 philosophical schools, common in laboratories, they are oftener 
 feared than understood, and are liable to be condemned for 
 their doctrine's inferential consequences rather than for its 
 inconsequential inferences. 
 
 The error of Materialism concerning the Subject, lies in 
 regarding it as dependent on a thing given in experience or 
 in the conceptual extension of experience. It hypostatises 
 the phenomenon, assumes that Substance is presented by 
 Empirical Reality ; where, in fact, only the Object is pre- 
 sented, whilst the notion of Substance is immanent there and 
 must be elicited by reflection and criticism. Materialism, 
 then, treats the Subject as dependent on the Object and 
 inferior to it in persistence and reality : dependent, however, 
 on the organic form of the body, not on the particular mole- 
 cules organised, since their presence is long outlived by 
 memory and purpose ; so that the particular molecules that 
 come and go must be considered substitutable for one another 
 as to their psychic activities. The special seat of the Ego or 
 centre of psychic life, which Descartes placed in the pineal 
 gland, may now be sought by some speculative physiologists 
 in the frontal lobes, as the chief organ of attention, because 
 there the movements of the head and eyes are controlled ; by 
 some, again, more especially in the third left frontal con- 
 volution (in right-handed people — precision being desirable 
 in such a matter), because that is the organ of speech, 
 essential to the using of the pronouns of the first person ; by 
 others in the brain as a whole, because it acts as a whole, and 
 nothing less can explain those alterations of personality by 
 which the same body exhibits at different times distinct 
 egos, each complete in all its psychic functions. But, 
 
THE OXTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 221 
 
 interesting as such speculations are (and to me they are 
 deeply interesting), I am obliged to say as before, that the 
 body is a phenomenon to the Subject, and cannot be the 
 ground of its existence or activities. 
 
 § 3. It will be convenient to take the other hypotheses 
 concerning the Subject nearly in historical order, and to begin 
 with Leibniz's Monadology as, after Descartes, the most 
 original account of the Soul's substantiality. The Monad is 
 a simple substance having no extension, figure or divisibility. 
 Monads are the true atoms of Nature and, in a word, the 
 elements of things. Tliey are regarded as created by God 
 and dependent solely on His will ; but otherwise, in the 
 course of Nature, they are without beginning or end. Having 
 no internal structure of parts, no internal movement is 
 possible, nor any change due to external causes : they have 
 no windows. According to their internal qualities, which 
 consist in perceptions, each is different from every other ; for 
 these perceptions represent to each the relations of all other 
 Monads, and therefore must in each be different. Being 
 created, they are subject to change ; but since external 
 influence is impossible, there can only be a change of per- 
 ceptions caused by an internal principle of appetition. 
 Monads further differ in the distinctness of their perceptions ; 
 which in some are only petites or faint, as in ourselves whilst 
 asleep : but in others they rise to full consciousness or apper- 
 ception, as when we are awake ; and similarly with desires. 
 
 All changes of perception in a Monad follow upon appe- 
 tition or final causes ; but they also represent the changes 
 taking place in the relations of other Monads, as if these 
 were movements only to be explained by efficient causes ; and 
 the correspondence between a Monad's internal changes and 
 the changes in the relations of other Monads, is maintained 
 by the pre-established Harmony, 
 
 A body is an aggregate of Monads, but as an aggregate 
 of points cannot make a real body, its unity comes from our 
 perception ; it is un Stre de raison, ou plutot d' imagination, 
 un FhdnoriUne {Examen des Principes du E. P. Malehranche). 
 And so is its movement ; for space and time are not real 
 
222 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 things, but ideal. Space is the order of possible co-existences, 
 time of possihiliUs inconstantes, mais qui ont pourtant de la 
 connexion (JRdplique aux R6Jlexions de Bayle). They are 
 eternal truths holding alike of the possible and the existent 
 (that is, of positions whether occupied or not) {Nouveaux 
 Essais, ii. 14, § 26). 
 
 Such is the artificial Idealism of Leibniz, ingenious and 
 circumspect, adroitly adapted to contemporary prejudices, yet 
 suggesting important truths ; bizarre and in a manner revolt- 
 ing, yet easier to ridicule than refute. We may first observe 
 that a nominal Idealism was easy in that age when the word 
 ' idea ' was commonly used for every object of the mind : 
 danger lay in the temptation to transliterate material into 
 mental terminology, and so produce an Idealism nominal and 
 nothing more. Has not Leibniz fallen into this snare ? 
 Certainly, time, space and body are all ideal in the sense 
 that the given Real is an Object or Phenomenon ; but in this 
 sense ' ideal ' and ' real ' are not contrasted. 
 
 It is disappointing to find that the faint ' perceptions ' 
 which in each Monad, however fast asleep, represent the 
 relations of all others, or mirror the world as if it were a 
 scene of moving bodies, are merely substituted verbally for 
 mechanical forces, through which the rest of the world 
 is conceived to influence (or be mirrored in) each atom. 
 There is no design to alter the interpretation of Nature, but 
 only to provide an excuse for regarding it as an hallucination. 
 The plan is harmless, useless and negligible. The appetitions 
 that are the only means of changing a Monad's perceptions, 
 and are identified by Leibniz with Final Causes, become if 
 possible still more disappointing, when we consider that an 
 appetition cannot be a Final Cause unless it represents the 
 change about to happen ; that is, unless it is a perception (P) 
 anticipating a perception (Q) ; and, again, that P can only 
 have arisen from an earlier anticipation (0) ad infinitum. 
 By this device Final Causes depend on antecedents, and 
 do not differ from purely natural determination. In fact, 
 of course, this is always true : those who take the notion 
 of Final Causes from human action must suppose that it 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 223 
 
 is possible to lay u plan without character aud without 
 experience. 
 
 As in this system forces are called percej)tions without 
 prejudice to their objectivity ; and appetitions are called Final 
 Causes without ceasing to be Effects ; so time and space are 
 called ideal without any loss of reality. They are said to be 
 only the orders of things that do or may exist. But time at 
 any rate is an order of changes of perception in the Monad ; 
 and it is a real order, unless experience goes for nothing. It 
 would be vain to say that time is ideal because it is an order 
 of ideas ; for (1) an order of ideas is itself real; and (2) if 
 ideas are not real, Idealism is another name for Nihilism ; or, 
 contrast having been abolished, why not call it Materialism ? 
 Let us see. Space, being ideal in the same sense as time, is 
 in fact real. Therefore movements represented in space 
 are real ; and so are moving bodies. But real bodies can- 
 not consist of unextended parts : therefore the Monads are 
 physical Atoms. Observe, moreover, that time and space are 
 " eternal truths," whose seat is the Divine Mind and whose 
 apprehension is the highest reach of human reason ; yet they 
 are not anything real or absolute. This is flat contradiction 
 and the negation of Idealism. It sets God thinking to no 
 purpose. 
 
 Leibniz offers no proof of the substantiality of the Monad : 
 it is an hypothesis depending upon the adequacy of the 
 speculative superstructure as a working model of the World ; 
 and the superstructure turns out to be veibal and nugatory. 
 "VVe may be sure that in Philosophy ingenuity will never long 
 avail. The taint of it always warns us that the author is 
 inventing a scheme for himself, not discovering the plan of 
 Nature. And how shall he escape detection ? Even if a 
 pliant adaptation to prevailing prejudices should conciliate 
 contemporary criticism, it is impossible to square posterity. 
 Leibniz is a salient example of the men who are too clever 
 by half. 
 
 § 4. Berkeley's Idealism on its subjective side is less of a 
 departure from the natural way of thinking than the Monad- 
 ology. His discussion of the Self or Subject is brief and 
 
224 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 confident. It first occurs in the Princ. of H. K. (§§ 2 and 27). 
 
 The spirit, he argues, is not anything of which we have an 
 
 idea, since ideas are inert, whilst spirit is perceiving, active 
 
 substance. It is distinct from ideas, though, it must be owned, 
 
 we have some notion of it. — But can anything that is not an 
 
 idea be distinct from an idea ? — Again, in a passage of the 
 
 third Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous, inserted in 
 
 the third edition, Philonous having granted that he has 
 
 no idea like unto the nature of God, whilst yet he infers 
 
 His being and power, is asked by Hylas why similarly one 
 
 may not conceive the existence of Matter \_per se] without 
 
 having an idea of it ; and he replies that " all the notion 
 
 I have of God is obtained from reflecting on my own soul." 
 
 For ideas are altogether passive and inert, and therefore 
 
 can never represent active spirit. But I know that I am 
 
 a spirit or thinking substance, — an indivisible, unextended 
 
 thing which thinks, acts, and perceives — " immediately or 
 
 intuitively, though I do not perceive it as I perceive a 
 
 triangle, a colour or a sound." From this notion of self 
 
 we may by reflection know God, and from our dependency 
 
 infer His creative power. But the case is different with 
 
 material things, the notion of which is (1) inconsistent, and 
 
 (2) unsupported by any evidence. When Hylas suggests 
 
 that Philonous seems after all to be " only a system of fleeting 
 
 ideas," Philonous repeats that he is conscious of his own 
 
 being, as a thinking active principle, one and the same self, 
 
 perceiving colours and sounds, whereas they cannot perceive 
 
 one another. Rational beings have in the production of 
 
 motions only limited powers, though " sufficient to entitle them 
 
 to all the guilt of their actions." As to the existence of 
 
 extended things, houses and trees, in the unextended mind, 
 
 most mental operations (he says) are signified by words 
 
 borrowed from sensible things, and the meaning here really is 
 
 that the mind comprehends or perceives such things, as it is 
 
 affected by some active being distinct from itself. 
 
 But how vain was this attempt to evade the consequences 
 of Empirical Idealism is shown by Hume ; who accepts 
 Berkeley's criticism of material substance and his denial of 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 225 
 
 the activity or power of sensible things, greatly strengthening 
 hie reasonings, especially about causation ; but then goes on 
 to direct a similar criticism against the notions of mental 
 substance and mental activity. 
 
 Hume's polemic {Treatise, Part IV. § 5) is not in the first 
 place directed against Berkeley, but against Materialists and 
 Spiritualists alike ; against all the curious reasoners about 
 " material and immaterial substances, in which they suppose 
 our perceptions to inhere." Observing that the notion of 
 substance and inherence is unintelligible, he argues that in 
 ]>articular it is inconceivable that a thought or a passion can 
 be conjoined to anything divisible and extended ; it cannot be 
 to the right or left, inside or outside, imless at one point 
 wliich is indivisible ; and if it were coextensive with an 
 extended thing, we must suppose the possibility of a passion 
 being a yard long, a foot broad and an inch thick : but, again, 
 it is equally inconceivable that an extended perception, such 
 as a table, can incorporate with a simple and indivisible 
 Subject ; for this cannot lie to the right or left of that, nor be 
 entire in every part of it though itself unextended, without 
 leading to absurdities and justifying the supposed union of 
 our indivisible perceptions with an extended substance. 
 
 It is, I suppose, admitted that this argument of Hume's 
 disposes of the vague notion of inherence as explaining per- 
 ception : Berkeley had already repudiated it, and substituted 
 a spiritual power or activity sui generis. But Hume next 
 discusses the cause of our perceptions, and he argues that 
 whether or not they are caused by the motions of matter is 
 purely a question of experience and evidence ; since (as he 
 has shown) we are never sensible of any connection betwixt 
 causes and effects, and a priori anything may produce any- 
 thing. And it is in vain, he says, to appeal to the action or 
 power of ourselves or of the Deity, since it has already been 
 shown that " we have no idea of a being endowed with any 
 power, much less with infinite power." 
 
 Hume then (§ 6) makes a more direct attack on Berkeley : 
 he argues that we have no idea of Self in " its perfect identity 
 and simplicity," for if we had there must be in self-conscious- 
 
 16 
 
226 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 ness some impression " invariably the same through the whole 
 course of our lives," whereas " there is no impression constant 
 and invariable." We are always conscious in introspection 
 of " some particular perception or other." Setting aside some 
 metaphysicians, the rest of mankind are (each of them) nothing 
 but a " bundle or collection of particular perceptions which 
 succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity, and are in 
 a perpetual flux and movement." Whilst, then, the strict 
 conception of identity or sameness is of an object that remains 
 invariable and uninterrupted through a supposed variation of 
 time, the identity of a self or person is analogous to that we 
 attribute to a plant or an animal. In the successive exist- 
 ence of a mind or thinking person, the " fictitious " identity 
 we ascribe to it is due, first, to the resemblances amongst 
 successive states in which memory consists, and, secondly, to 
 causation which links together its different perceptions in a 
 system. The soul, therefore, may best be compared to a 
 " commonwealth in which the several members are united by 
 the reciprocal ties of government and subordination, and give 
 rise to other persons, who propagate the same republic in the 
 incessant changes of its parts." As to the soul's simplicity, 
 " an object, whose different coexistent parts are bound together 
 by a close relation, operates upon the imagination after much 
 the same manner as one perfectly simple and indivisible." We 
 therefore " feign a principle of union as the support of this 
 simplicity and the centre of all the different parts and qualities 
 of the object." 
 
 In spite of the instructiveness of this section, the use 
 of such expressions as " fictitious " for what is entirely natural, 
 " feign " for a process instinctive and undesigning, " bundle " 
 for what he acknowledges to have organic unity, and the 
 analogy of a commonwealth adopted in preference to the 
 closer organic structure of an animal — all suggest an endeavour 
 to minimise the integrity of personal life as against the over- 
 strained statements of Berkeley and the dogmatic philosophers. 
 Still, the essential conclusion, that the mind does not immedi- 
 ately know itself as a Substance, was supported by Kant, and 
 has never since been shaken. 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 227 
 
 Spinoza's philosophy bears a greater rosemblauce to Hume'« 
 than h;is generally been recognised. The scepticism of the 
 one and mysticism of the other are so opposed in tone as to 
 disguise the fact that both issue in u strict phenomenalism 
 according to laws of Nature. In their views of the Subject 
 this is very plain : for according to Spinoza the mind is the 
 idea of the body (Part II., 13); and as the body consists of 
 innumerable small parts of extension, so does the mind of 
 corresponding ideas (Part II., 1 5); and, finally, the union among 
 ideas of the mind corresponds with the organisation of the 
 body. For "in so far as a body is better fitted to do or 
 suffer many things, in that degree is its mind more fit to 
 perceive many things at the same time; and the more the 
 actions of a body depend solely on itself, and the less other 
 bodies concur with it in action, the more capable is its mind 
 of distinct understanding" (Part II., 13, Schol. ; cf. IV. 38), and 
 therefore of blessedness and self-control (Part V., 39). At least, 
 I do not see how we can translate a ' fitness to do or suffer 
 many things ' and ' depending in action upon itself,' except by 
 the word ' organisation.' 
 
 § 5. Mill, turning like Hume from the analysis of material 
 to that of mental Substance, inquires in his Examination of 
 Hamilton (chap, xii.) whether the conception of the mind as a 
 permanent existence is an original datum of consciousness. 
 He observes that " our notion of Mind, as well as of Matter, 
 is the notion of a permanent something, contrasted with the 
 perpetual flux of the sensations and other feelings or mental 
 states which we refer to it"; and that this permanence, 
 supposing that there were nothing else to be considered, 
 might (like Matter) be explained as "a Permanent Possi- 
 bility of states," sensations, etc. : in sleep, e.g., my capability 
 of feeling is not destroyed, but only conditionally suspended. 
 But there is something else to be considered, namely. Memory : 
 which has the peculiarity of involving " a belief in more than 
 its own present existence. A sensation involves only this : 
 but a remembrance of sensation involves the suggestion and 
 belief that a sensation of which it is a copy or representation 
 actually existed in the past " ; and not only that it existed 
 
228 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 but that I myself, and no other, formerly had the sensation 
 remembered. Thus I am not only a series of feelings or 
 possibility of them, but am aware of myself as such ; and it 
 is a paradox that a series of feelings should be " aware of 
 itself as a series." In the Appendix, Mill adds a good deal 
 to this. " The organic tie," he says, " which connects the 
 present consciousness with the past one of which it reminds 
 me, is as near as I think we can get to a positive conception 
 of Self." He will not decide whether " we are distinctly 
 conscious of it in the act of remembrance," or, " according to 
 the opinion of Kant, are not conscious of a Self at all but are 
 compelled to assume it as a necessary condition of memory." 
 But further, whilst the Mind is only known to itself pheno- 
 menally, as a series, " we are forced to apprehend every part 
 of the series as linked with the other parts by something in 
 common which is not the feelings themselves, any more than 
 the succession of the feelings is the feelings themselves ; and 
 as that which is the same in the first as in the second, in the 
 second as in the third, * * "^ must be the same in the first as 
 in the fiftieth, this common element is a permanent element." 
 We have here a significant transition of expression from 
 " the notion of a permanent something," which " we figure as 
 remaining the same while the particular feelings, through 
 which it reveals its existence, change" (p. 235, 3rd ed.) — 
 to a common and permanent element in the feelings, which 
 is not the feelings themselves (p. 257), nor any definite mode 
 of consciousness, but which belongs to experience and is not 
 merely the ' notion ' of something. Now there is a relatively 
 stable element in the flux of consciousness, namely, the 
 coenaisthesis or somatic feeling; it is not indeed permanent, 
 but may remain much the same for hours in the background oi 
 consciousness whilst the distinct foreground rapidly changes ; 
 and this, as Eibot says, is a decisive factor of the empirical per- 
 sonality; but Mill does not seem to have meant the coeniesthesis. 
 And he can hardly have meant that every mental state has 
 the character of memory ; for though the fact of memory (or 
 " retentiveness ") is involved in every state, that is a very 
 different thing from its having consciously the specific quality 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 229 
 
 of being remembered. Nor does he seem to have meant that 
 the judgment " I think " accompanies every act of consciousness. 
 
 Mill's notion of a permanent self in introspection, though 
 approacliing Berkeley's belief, falls far short of it in confidence 
 and definiteness. As to the Permanent Possibility of feeling 
 that is figured to remain during the lapse of consciousness in 
 sleep, since (in chap, xv.) he is inclined to admit Hamilton's 
 " unconscious modifications in the only sense in which I can 
 attach any very distinct meaning to them, namely, unconscious 
 modifications of the nerves " — why should not the nervous 
 system have served him equally well as the Permanent Possi- 
 bility of feeling, or indeed, of memory ? 
 
 Finally, as to the paradox of Memory, the difficulty of 
 conceiving a series of conscious states conscious of itself as 
 a series : if we really mean a series of " feelings," it is not 
 only paradoxical but impossible : for ' feeling ' is the lowest 
 term of consciousness and can never amount to memory. But 
 memory is not " peculiar in involving a belief in more than 
 its own present existence." Mill knew, and has explained, 
 that every cognition has this character, being significative or 
 representative — reason of the universal, even sense-perception 
 of some object ; and a series, or stream, or organic activity of 
 consciousness, conscious of its own former existence, is one in 
 which occur ideas having the significative character which we 
 call memory and believe to represent past reality. In this 
 there is no peculiar paradox. 
 
 It is impossible to appreciate the reality of consciousness 
 whilst treating its processes as phenomena. In Mill's Essay 
 on Theism (Part III.) he goes somewhat further : " Feeling and 
 thought are much more real than anything else, they are the 
 only things which we directly know to be real." And as to 
 the mind's substantiality, he says : " Substance is but a general 
 name for the perdurability of attributes : wherever there is 
 a series of thoughts connected together by memories, that 
 constitutes a thinking substance." But, surely, such a series 
 constitutes not a substance but a continuous activity. In 
 his work on Hamilton, he says that our notion of Mind is 
 " a permanent something, contrasted with the perpetual flux 
 
230 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 of mental states " ; which is not really perpetual because of 
 sleep. No one would call that a substance which, as Mill 
 supposed, might be suspended for several hours every day. 
 What has become of the " permanent possibility " ? In his 
 Theism, then. Mill has emphasised the reality of the Subject, 
 but he has committed an impropriety and a contradiction in 
 calling it a thinking substance. 
 
 § 6. Had Mill appreciated Kant's philosophy he could 
 hardly have written his chapters on the Self without some 
 discussion of the famous doctrines of the Unity of Appercep- 
 tion and the Paralogisms of piu-e Eeason, Without taking up 
 disproportionate space it is impossible here to examine all the 
 passages in which Kant labours to explain these matters ; but 
 I must attempt a summary of his teaching. 
 
 The unity of Apperception, that is, of explicit conscious- 
 ness, first becomes prominent in the Deduction of the Categories 
 (§ 16). "The / think" he says, "must be able to accompany 
 all my representations ; for else something would be represented 
 in me that could not at all be thought, which is as much as 
 to say the representation would either be impossible or for 
 me at least nothing at all," All the manifold of intuition, 
 therefore, is necessarily related to the I think in any Subject ; 
 and this is an act of spontaneity not of sense (which is only 
 receptive). It is called pure consciousness to distinguish it 
 from the empirical ; and original consciousness because it is 
 that self-consciousness which, inasmuch as it gives rise to the 
 representation / think accompanying all representations and 
 in all consciousness one and the same, cannot be derived from 
 anything further. It is also called the transcendental unity 
 of self-consciousness to indicate the possibility of cognition 
 a priori. It is the highest principle of all synthesis in both 
 intuition and understanding; the ground of the categories, of 
 the unity of objects, of the necessity and universality of 
 experience or Nature : at least it is so for the human mind, 
 though perhaps not for a mind whose representations should 
 merely as such be actual — an intuitive Understanding (§ 17). 
 Therefore, this objective unity of consciousness must be dis- 
 tinguished from the subjective unity of the internal sense. 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJPXT 231 
 
 which is empirical and contingent and varies in different men 
 (§ 18), and consists of phenomena in time, which are thought 
 under the categories (§ 24) ; that is, the unity of the empirical 
 Subject is that of a something thought as one ; but the pure 
 unity of consciousness is the condition of all thinking, by the 
 category of unity or any other. Herein I am conscious of 
 myself, not as I appear to myself, noch wie ich an mir selbst 
 bin, but only that I am : it is a thought not an intuition ; so 
 that the consciousness of self is far from being a knowledge of 
 self (§ 25). 
 
 Now, to overlook this fact was the error of Eational 
 Psychology (as in Descartes and Leibniz), which took the pure 
 consciousness / think for an object, and proceeded to prove 
 that it is (1) a Substance; (2) simple; (3) identical at all 
 times ; (4) in relation to possible objects in space, a soul. 
 The proofs err, first, by assuming that the Self which is always 
 a subject, never a predicate to thought, is therefore a Sub- 
 stance ! Secondly, by inferring that the Ego, which is of course 
 a single subject, is therefore a simple Substance. Similarly 
 with the third case, identity. Fourthly, I distinguish Self as 
 a thinking being from things in space ; but it does not follow 
 that the consciousness of myself is possible without things 
 outside of me through which representations are given to me, 
 or that I can exist merely as a thinking being, not as man. 
 Such are the Paralogisms. 
 
 Although I cannot regard as historically true Kant's 
 derivation of Eational Psychology from the mistake of treating 
 the / think as a given object, since Rational Psychology is 
 manifestly a scholastic recension of the ghost-theory ; still, 
 seeing the general truth of Kant's position that only the 
 phenomenon (in his sense) is given, and that Self at any rate 
 is posited as subject only, one cannot help wondering at Lotze's 
 attempt to establish the independence of the soul as a simple 
 substance merely on the evidence of the unity of Apperception. 
 He explains indeed {Metaphysics, § 243) that this is in 
 accordance with his own definition of a substance as " every- 
 thing which possesses the power of producing and experiencing 
 effects, in so far as it possesses the power " ; and presently he 
 
232 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 adds : " The fact of the unity of consciousness is eo ipso at once 
 the fact of the existence of a substance : we do not need by a 
 process of reasoning to conclude from the former to the latter 
 as the condition of its existence " (I quote the translation). 
 But this is hardly reconcilable with other passages. In § 241 
 he says : " Any comparison of two ideas, which ends by our 
 finding their contents like or unlike, presupposes the absolute 
 indivisible unity of that which compares them : it must be 
 one and the same thing which first forms the idea of a, then 
 that of h, and which at the same time is conscious of the 
 nature and extent of the difference between them." "What is 
 this but arguing (I will not call it reasoning) from the unity 
 of consciousness to a substance, a " thing " that " forms an 
 idea " ? It is the style of mythology. The unity of consciousness 
 can have a " power of producing and experiencing effects " only 
 if it is one of the phenomena related. But this it certainly is 
 not. Common modes of speech would excuse a man's writing 
 of the Soul as a Thing having a unity of consciousness in its 
 activities ; but there can be no excuse for describing the unity 
 itself as a thing producing and experiencing effects, which are 
 nothing but the consciousness of which it is the unity. Hence, 
 Lotze has in fact inferred Substance from Subject. But we 
 have seen that a relation between substance and phenomena 
 or between soul and activity (if it can be thought at all) 
 is not the relation between cause and effect : and still less 
 is this the relation between the unity of consciousness and 
 the phenomena of consciousness. The unity of consciousness 
 neither acts nor suffers. 
 
 As to Kant's doctrine of Apperception, it is only intelligible 
 in connection with the deepest thoughts of his philosophy, 
 which are left in a sort of secret script to be deciphered as 
 best we can. Every one knows how the Ding an sich plays 
 hide-and-seek with us throughout the K. d. r. V. ; but in the 
 ethical and religious writings it becomes as manifest as words 
 can make it. There we learn that the reality of our life and 
 fate is homo noumenon ; and we may easily suppose that there 
 is a multitude of noumena, one for each of us, besides those of 
 other rationals. But on reflection it must appear that this is 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 233 
 
 iuconceivable ; for noumena out of Time and Space cannot be 
 many ; there cannot be a numerical individuation, but at most 
 a ciualitative difference, and this only a moral one — holy and 
 uot-lioly. That individual men, not only in this life but ad 
 infinitum, are sensuously determinate is implied in the 
 argument for immortality : homo phenomenon does not become 
 a noumenon by death in this world, since it is the persistence 
 of sensuous opposition to Keason that guarantees his own per- 
 sistence. 
 
 The noumenon, then, is one with two aspects — the Absolute 
 Rejison, and homo noumenon who is fallen. The fall (we 
 learn in the Religion i. d. G. d. hi. Vernunft) is a mystery, its 
 origin unaccountable, and of course not to be thought of as 
 occurring in time; but, seeing that evil is due to the influence 
 of Sense upon Reason, we may suppose that homo noumenon 
 is nothing else than the aspect of Reason in a sensuous world 
 — whose self-diremption in Time and Space, or the ' taking 
 of flesh,' is, as such, a ' fall ' from Absolute Reason. Hence 
 we may understand the objectivity of Reason in experience 
 or Nature ; which in the K. d. r. V. is such a monstrous 
 doctrine, if we understand it as the constitution of Nature by 
 the individual human mind. The individual, as rational, 
 shares in the knowledge of Reason which is the law of Natiu-e, 
 but in his limitations only knows the outlines of the world- 
 scheme, and must find out the details as best he can. 
 
 Now, pure transcendental original Apperception is the 
 common consciousness of Nature, in which all objective 
 knowledge resides ; of which Time, Space and the Categories 
 are the most general functions, but every detail of fact and 
 relation is equally and as necessarily a function. Accordingly, 
 it is widely distinct from the mere subjective empirical unity 
 of Apperception. As the condition of the representation of 
 objects in Space, it is the condition of the existence of any 
 homo phenomenon ; and, through Time and the Categories, it 
 is the condition of the synthesis of his subjective experience 
 and of the thought of its unity, even to himself. But the 
 Categories are conditions of his thoughts as Laws of Nature ; 
 they are not his private organs of thinking ; he must be 
 
234 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 content to do his private thinking with the Schemata of 
 Imagination. Hence transcendental Apperception itself is One 
 in a qualified sense — not under the Category of Unity, not 
 numerically then ; and, therefore, if spoken of as Self-conscious- 
 ness, this is also in a qualified sense ; for ' self ' implies others 
 on the same footing, and what is above unity is above plurality, 
 and else it could not be pure. In short, we may best interpret 
 it as the Kantian Logos. 
 
 But as for the subjective unity of apperception, or 
 empirical self-consciousness, yours or mine, it is merely a 
 limited particular fact, and to make great ado about it is very 
 unphilosophical. For it is far from being the whole even of 
 oneself; since beyond it lies the vast region of sub-consciousness 
 (much more than ^^ of oneself), and the period of infancy, 
 and all the forgotten experience that once was conscious, and 
 a considerable part even of consciousness as it flies. Kant 
 fully recognises this in his Anthropologie (Book I. § 5); and 
 even Lotze says {Metaphysics, § 241) that he does not 
 " repeat the frequent but exaggerated assertion, that in every 
 single act of feeling or thinking there is an express conscious- 
 ness which regards the sensation or idea simply as a state 
 of self; on the contrary, every one is familiar with that 
 absorption in the content of a sensuous perception which often 
 makes us entirely forget our personality in view of it." This 
 is as true of attentive thought as of perception. Lotze adds : 
 " But then the very fact that we can become aware that this 
 was the case, presupposes that we can retrieve what we omitted 
 at first, viz., the recognition that the perception was in us, as 
 our state." How much can we retrieve ? Often next to 
 nothing of all that has passed. 
 
 I must not be supposed to contend that the above 
 interpretation of Kant is borne out by every passage in which 
 he treats of Apperception. Far from it: at the very outset 
 the proposition, " I think accompanies every act of conscious- 
 ness," suggests the individual unity, and is both false and 
 misleading. He did not from the first distinguish clearly in 
 his own mind the universal and individual unities ; else he 
 must have seen that the latter necessarily includes the sub- 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 235 
 
 jective unity of the internal sense. But, viewing his philosophy 
 as a whole, I have given the only sensible meaning of tranH- 
 cendentul Apperception ; for the notion that this am be a 
 function of the individual is so intolerably foolish that any 
 other is comparatively sane. 
 
 § 7. The esoteric Kantian doctrine of homo phenomenon, 
 then, is akin to the ancient theory of emanation in the 
 Vedanta and Neo-Platonism. Lotze expresses it (§ 246) : 
 " Nor again is it out of nothing that the soul is made or 
 created by the absolute; but, to satisfy the imagination, we may 
 say it is from itself, from its own real nature that the absolute 
 projects the soul, and so adds to its one activity, the course of 
 nature, that other which, in the ruling plan of the absolute, 
 is its natural completion." Even in the history of English 
 Philosophy similar doctrines have been held at various times by 
 Oudworth and others ; of whom the most recently interesting 
 is the late T. H. Green. Green says {Prolegomena, § 67) that 
 our consciousness " can only be explained by supposing that in 
 the growth of our experience, in the process of our learning to 
 know the world, an animal organism, which has its history in 
 time, gradually becomes the vehicle of an eternally complete 
 consciousness." 
 
 Apparently, the marks by which, according to Green, our 
 consciousness may be identified with the Divine are five: (1) 
 it is not itself in time, as may be proved by the very fact of 
 its perceiving events in time ; (2) in every act of consciousness 
 it distinguishes itself from the content of its activity ; (3) it 
 is a unifying principle to the contents of consciousness by 
 relating them together; (4) it is therefore an agent, and (5) 
 a free agent. 
 
 All these marks, except the fifth (for which see § 77), 
 are given in the following passage {Prolegomena, § 32): 
 "Thus in order that successive feelings may be related in 
 objects of experience, even objects related in the way of suc- 
 cession, there must be in consciousness an agent which 
 distinguishes itself from the feelings, uniting them in their 
 severalty, making them equally present in their succession." 
 Many similar passages might be quoted : this is the essence 
 
236 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 of Green's Metaphysics, and every position is gained by a 
 paralogism. 
 
 For (1) human consciousness is entirely determined in 
 time : not only are relations of succession cognised as such 
 and by an actual succession of their terms in thought, but 
 this is even true of relations of co-existence ; and if there is 
 any mysterious question here it is, not how succession can be 
 presented as such, but how co-existences can be recognised at 
 all. Green seems to have mistaken the " psychological now " 
 for the nunc stans. 
 
 (2) That in every act of consciousness the agent (soul or 
 ego) distinguishes itself from the content of its activity is 
 (a) untrue, because in fact self-consciousness does not accom- 
 pany every act of human consciousness, (h) There is probably 
 here a confusion between the total empirical content of the 
 ego at any time, which contrasts with any fresh feeling or 
 cognition (if distinct), and the abstract Subject, which (as 
 such) is never known at all. For (c) to suppose that the 
 abstract Subject can be distinguished from any particular 
 content, is to make it one term of a relation of difference, and 
 therefore an object needing another Subject for its presenta- 
 tion (Third Man). The same objection applies to the descrip- 
 tion of the Unity of Apperception as the " correlate of all 
 experience " ; for a ' correlate ' is a term related. 
 
 (3) Self-consciousness is not the unifying principle even 
 in knowledge ; for all knowledge begins with perception, and 
 the integration of psychic elements in perception which gives 
 it its significative character, is infinitely more ancient and 
 profound than any individual human consciousness. Hence 
 the unsatisfactory character of the psychological analysis of 
 perception : hence the fact that the unity of perception is 
 felt as depending on the object. At present the unity of 
 perception can best be understood as a growth. Similarly, 
 the integrations of instinct, habit, and even memory are 
 growths, as truly as the physical tissues are. Memories, 
 indeed, both in acquisition (as a rule) and in revival, are 
 clearer and more analysable than the more ancient functions 
 of the soul, but their connection or unity is not determined 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 237 
 
 by self-consciousness, but (rather) determines it. The inven- 
 tions and discoveries of imagination and discursive thought, 
 though they appear in consciousness, do not come by the 
 routes of consciousness : the lines that signal and summon 
 them run through the dark. What a shallow thing our 
 explicit consciousness is we have not yet enough considered. 
 
 (4) To assume that the unity of consciousness is the 
 activity of an agent, is precisely the paralogism of treating 
 the Subject as Substance. " What is the use (poor Kant 
 might ask) of writing, or refuting, or proving anything ^ — 
 
 Were it not better done as other use, 
 To sport with Amaryllis in the shade ? " 
 
 But (5) that human consciousness should be a free agent 
 is in conflict with the principles of Green's philosophy. 
 Having inferred from human consciousness a divine Conscious- 
 ness as sustaining the world, he finds that it must be timeless, 
 uniting all existence in eternal knowledge, and in this aspect 
 he calls it a " free cause." But he does not mean that it is a 
 cause in any ordinary sense of the word by which some 
 " separate particularity " is implied in cause and effect : for 
 " the agent [divine Consciousness] must act absolutely from 
 itself in the action through which that world is — not, as does 
 everything within the world, under determination by some- 
 thing else. The world has no character but that given it by 
 this action ; the agent no character but that which it gives 
 itself in this action" (§ 76). Now, how such a relation is 
 possible we are to understand by comparing our own activity 
 in knowledge ; which is " an action as absolutely from itself, 
 as little to be accounted for by the phenomena which through 
 it become an intelligent experience, or by anything alien to 
 itself, as is that which we have found to be implied in the 
 existence of the universal order " (§ 77). But this explanation 
 raises appalling difficulties. How is it possible that in know- 
 ing I should be a " free cause " of knowledge, seeing that the 
 object known is always a fact of the eternal Mind ? Whilst 
 awake I necessarily know something, and must know it as it 
 is. I cannot choose how I shall know a thing, and the thing 
 
238 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 takes no character from my knowledge of it, nor is my 
 character merely equivalent to my knowledge of the thing. 
 In knowledge, then, man is not a ' free cause,' and does not 
 help us to bring the divine Consciousness under that odd 
 category. In experience causa libera is without example or 
 analogy : it neither explains anything, nor can it be 
 explained. 
 
 It is especially odd that any one should apply the adjective 
 " free " to the Divine ' Agent ' as above described. According 
 to Leibniz, God was not free to choose any world but the best 
 possible (namely, this one) ; and Green cannot have meant 
 that the Divine Agent was free to cognise another world ; for 
 he explicitly asserts that " it has no character but that which 
 it gives itself in this action " (knowledge of the world). This 
 world therefore is not merely the best but the only possible 
 one. And the Divine Unity of Apperception, as Green con- 
 ceives it, cannot be an ' agent ' at all. For agency implies 
 activity, implies changes brought about; and this is impos- 
 sible in the world known to such a Being, a world without 
 beginning, or end, or process, or development, or decay. 
 
 Still, such a world, a nunc stans, being granted, it may 
 seem a fair inference that it can only be represented in Time 
 by an invariable order ; and this agrees with Green's remark 
 that "all results are necessary results" (§ 109). But then all 
 human knowledge and actions are necessary. 
 
 We may conclude that there is no way of comprehending 
 man as resembling the Divine Consciousness in being a free 
 agent, unifying the object of knowledge from which it dis- 
 tinguishes itself as a timeless principle ; and that therefore 
 Green was right in saying that " the indivisible reality of our 
 consciousness [at once divine and human] cannot be compre- 
 hended in a single conception. In seeking to understand its 
 reality we have to look at it from two different points of view ; 
 and the different conceptions that we form of it, as looked at 
 from these different points, do not admit of being united " 
 (§ 68). This seems quite just; but things that '^cannot be 
 united in a single concept " have no resemblance, and can never 
 help to explain one another. Such is the truth : and, having 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJP:CT 239 
 
 perceived it, is it uot ustouishiug that this most earnest, sincere 
 and benevolent man sliould try to make an impossible concep- 
 tion the basis of human maunei's and of family and social life { 
 Has the house of our life no foundation but tliis impalpable 
 sand ? 
 
 Unless a scheme of notions is in fact merely verbal, if it 
 cannot be clearly rendered in concatenated concepts, there is 
 no support for it but some sort of incoherent imagery. Theories 
 of emanation are not merely verbal, and they cannot be clearly 
 concatenated ; but such words as ' emanation,' ' the absolute 
 projects the soul,' etc., not only had orignally a physical mean- 
 ing (in which, as in so many mythologies, ' generation ' 
 predominated), but they still retain it ; and physical sugges- 
 tions, half suppressed by habits of technical thought, are still 
 that which gives them all the sense they have. In short, 
 Emanation is essentially a materialistic theory, in spite of 
 every effort to refine away its sensuous dross. If I am asked 
 whether the outological suggestions of this volume are purely 
 verbal, or clearly concatenated, or vaguely imagined ; my 
 answer is that, so far as conceptual, the imperfect character of 
 the concepts employed has been explicitly shown, and that 
 nothing will be built upon them without fair warning ; and 
 that, where these concepts fail, there is a dim impulse of 
 imagination to supplement the quasi-intelligible, which of course 
 likewise fails, and, as far as it goes, is materialistic. But here, 
 indeed. Materialism and Mysticism meet ; for Mysticism is 
 always an attempt to walk by imagination where perception 
 has left no vestiges. This cannot be helped in any Ontology. 
 The nature of human thought and language makes it impossible 
 — once we quit the ground of immediate consciousness, — to 
 imagine the non-material or to define it except by blank 
 negations of materiality. And the remedy for this defect of 
 thought is to find a way of looking at the "World so as to see 
 that ' Material-Spiritual ' is a crude, strained and indefensible 
 opposition. It is not a case in which any theory can be proved 
 by the physical method and incorporated with the sciences, 
 but one in which we have to consider, in view of the sciences 
 and the whole of experience, what scheme of notions will best 
 
240 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 serve us to fill up that background of experience which all 
 admit to be obscure. Such is the purpose of these specu- 
 lations. 
 
 § 8. We iiave seen, then, that the ego or consciousness is 
 not, and cannot be explained by, any Substance, material or 
 spiritual. Hume and Kant (in his speculative Philosophy) 
 recognise what are called the phenomena of the Soul ; and, if 
 interpreted dogmatically, they might be supposed to be 
 Nihilists, denying any Substance ; but if fairly treated as 
 sceptic and critic, they are Agnostics, demonstrating the grounds 
 of our ontological nescience. The sequel of Kant's Philosophy 
 shows that this Agnosticism was unsatisfactory to himself; 
 and it is so to me, as well as to many others who acknowledge 
 the force of the sceptical and critical arguments. Therefore, I 
 am recommending as the most coherent and natural way of 
 thinking, on the whole, this hypothesis that the World is 
 essentially a conscious thing ; that in consciousness we have 
 immediate knowledge of Keality, but not of the whole of Being ; 
 that the rest of Being is made known to us by phenomena ; 
 that it is everywhere conscious, but in various degrees, and 
 that the higher degrees are known to us by the phenomena of 
 organisation. In support of this view I argued in Chap. X. from 
 the phenomena, and it has been necessary to show why other 
 hypotheses are less satisfactory. It remains to consider, in 
 this chapter, how it compares with other hypotheses in the 
 account it gives of Perception and Volition. 
 
 Neither Materialism nor Spiritualism can give any account 
 of perception or volition. To Materialism all consciousness is 
 a miracle, and therefore so is perception : to Spiritualism no 
 perception is possible, because there is nothing to perceive. 
 Dualism, maintaining the reality both of a material and of a 
 spiritual Substance, has, from Descartes to Hamilton, tried in 
 vain to circumvent the truism that between Substances 
 divided by definition there is no community. Our own way 
 of representing these things, on the hypothesis that there is 
 an intimate parallelism between consciousness and the rest of 
 Being which is manifested in phenomena, such that conscious- 
 ness may be considered as an activity of Being, may be put 
 
THE ONTOLOGY OF THE SUBJECT 241 
 
 in this way : Sensation arises when a disturbance in the 
 transcendent Being of the brain is set up by changes in the 
 Being of other phenomena ; and perception is the integration 
 of sensations that takes place under certain conditions in 
 which one sensation becomes a sign of the others. An idea 
 consists of perceptions and their associations centrally excited ; 
 that is, accompanying disturbances propagated from other 
 parts of the Being of the brain. Volition, or the acting upon 
 the idea of an action, implies a specific disturbance in the 
 Being of the brain corresponding with the idea of the action, 
 and a propagation of this disturbance by the Being of nerves 
 and muscles into the outer world. 
 
 This story contains so many queer phrases that it asks 
 some courage to write it ; and, in fact, it would not have been 
 written if I had thought that it expressed merely notions of 
 my own. But, however crude the expression (and I have 
 deliberately refrained from refining it), I believe it is the 
 way in which many, perhaps most people now think, who 
 have given any attention to Psychology and also to the recent 
 progress of the physical and biological sciences. For they 
 hold (1) that consciousness has no mass or energy ; (2) that 
 it cannot be explained by any other mode of existence; (3) 
 that phenomena do manifest mass and energy ; and (4) that 
 phenomena (as such) are not the reality of Being. My 
 account of perception and volition follows from these four 
 propositions. 
 
 But how little I can venture to infer concerning Being 
 that is not Consciousness, has been shown in Chap. VIII. § 8 ; 
 namely, Succession, Change, Co-existence, Order. And amidst 
 the contempt into which Ontology has now fallen it is lonely, 
 wearisome and depressing to write about it. Once more let 
 us return to the common daylight, to the fresh green fields of 
 primitive credulity, to the great conjuring entertainment where 
 seeing is believing. 
 
 IS 
 
CHAPTER XII 
 
 NATURAL HISTORY OF THE SUBJECT 
 
 § 1. ' Phenomena of consciousness ' is a convenient phrase in 
 treating Psychology as a Natural Science, which is my purpose 
 in the present chapter : for we must trace in outline the 
 development of the rational life, without which there could be 
 no Metaphysics. ' Phenomena of consciousness ' is also a very 
 natural phrase, for it is only by late reflection, and not 
 without difficulty, that the conviction can be reached that in 
 fact consciousness is not a phenomenon, but the direct and sole 
 revelation of the ultimate Being of the universe. 
 
 Consciousness seems a fragmentary thing, not only by the 
 intermissions of sleep and other lapses, but because each man 
 has some first recollection, and it is always of something that 
 happened a very little while ago ; and a few relics of events 
 from then till now are all that he directly knows of conscious- 
 ness : like the bridge that Mirza saw stretching out across an 
 unfathomable sea, many of whose arches were broken, whilst 
 its further end was hidden in mist. We learn from others 
 that we lived before we can remember ; but they know us 
 only by our bodies, as we know them ; and it is only by 
 expression, gesture, behaviour that we can infer anything of 
 them or of the animals, upon which to poise still more 
 hazardous conjectures concerning the rest of Nature. By such 
 a dim and flickering lamp is the vast world warmed and 
 illumined. 
 
 We have, therefore, no choice but to recognise human 
 society and animal life and the sciences of these, as conditions 
 of psychological inquiry : not that the psychologist fails to 
 
 242 
 
NATUKAL IIISTOKY OF THK SUBJECT 243 
 
 make u full returu for what he takes, but that his f»\vn 
 experieuce is isolated, incoherent and meaningless apart from 
 the environing and antecedent activities of other men and 
 other animals. To understand the growth of any single 
 human mind, we must begin with the inherited organisation 
 and disposition to development presented by its body, and 
 with the social circumstances into which it is bom. And the 
 psychologist's first problem is to determine, if possible, how 
 much of a man's mental development is traceable to education 
 and experience, and how much to the intrinsic maturing of 
 the germ-plasm of his psycho-physical being. 
 
 This problem will not soon be solved ; but I shall not 
 disguise my own inclination to lay great stress upon the 
 organic development, which is a growth of the body as a sign 
 of the soul. Works of Psychology give elaborate accounts of 
 how we learn to perceive objects and to will movements. I 
 admire these writings, their penetrating insight and subtle 
 analysis, and eagerly acknowledge how much I owe them. 
 Yet they seem to me to describe what may be supposed to 
 have happened in the infancy of our minds rather than what 
 really happened. In my view we cannot properly be said to 
 learn any of those things. We come to perceive objects by 
 organic growth, before discriminating the sensations that 
 are the ground of the qualities that constitute objects ; and 
 by the same means we acquire many voluntary actions before 
 we are able to attend to motor ideas. Our interpretations are 
 apt to be as anthropomorphically misleading in studying the 
 mind of a child as in studying the minds of other animals. 
 To perceive an object, to perceive it at a distance and to 
 acquire control of the movements necessary to reach it, are all 
 involved in the generic development of the neuro-muscular 
 apparatus. Since that development is greatly furthered by a 
 child's activities, which imply a varied consciousness, we easily 
 regard such acquisitions as " outgrowths of the same experi- 
 ences," as they would be were a child's mind like our own ; 
 but this is impossible. When the time comes for learning by 
 experience, we already live in an orderly world, and are in 
 possession of the general scheme of our faculties. 
 
244 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Our early growth is accompanied and influenced by 
 experience, but is rapid out of all proportion to experience, and 
 may be attributed to that inherent activity by which every 
 seed develops according to its kind. Before birth far greater 
 progress is made than during the whole of an individual's 
 subsequent life ; and this self-development continues for many 
 years, is conspicuous again at puberty, and gradually slackens 
 and ceases at ages varying in different races and in different 
 men of the same race. Then come middle age and old age, 
 considered to be especially the time of experience ; but the 
 essential characters of these periods express, no less than those 
 of infancy, the individuality of each organism. Why do 
 children of the same family, families of the same folk, various 
 races of liomo sapiens, grow up even under similar conditions 
 with widely different abilities, aptitudes, characters ? The 
 whole range of capacity from idiocy to genius has little to do 
 with experience. 
 
 The period of infancy in man is much longer than in other 
 animals of equal bulk at maturity, and in some races of men, 
 and in some men of the same race, longer than in others. As 
 this is manifestly inconvenient, it may be asked why the 
 period of gestation should not have been lengthened instead. 
 Mechanical difficulties connected with the size of the head 
 at birth may be alleged ; but gestation is said to be already 
 three months longer with man than with the gorilla. 
 Longer gestation might have been inconvenient to savages 
 (our recent ancestors) still nomadic ; but it would have 
 been safer for the offspring. Long infancy is favourable 
 to the development of family life, and of active sympathy 
 and affection, which are advantageous to a co-operative 
 animal. All these are considerations ; yet I think some- 
 thing must still be allowed for the necessity of thoroughly 
 interfusing from the first the animal growths of perception 
 and instinct with the growths that are stimulated by free 
 activities in the beginning of experience, and with the 
 gradual differentiation of the great plastic reserve in the 
 cortex which corresponds with the specifically human 
 powers of imagination and reason ; though even these later 
 
NATUKAL IIISTOKY OF THE SU3UECT 245 
 
 growths are controlled iu their main features by inherited 
 predispositions to organisation. 
 
 The human child, according to Romanes, at about the 
 sixteenth month, reaches the gorilla's level of intelligence. 
 The poor gorilla ! Perhaps Romanes has a little antedated 
 the success of our rivalry ; for we know nothing about the 
 gorilla's intelligence under natural conditions. However, 
 thenceforward the proportion iu which human development 
 depends upon experience, as compared with the internal forces 
 of organisation, increases. But to maturity and even to the 
 close of life (as we see in the oncoming of insanity) it seems 
 that the general type of intellect and character, as distinguished 
 from the details of knowledge, accomplishment and behaviour, 
 is a realisation of hereditary conditions. 
 
 § 2. In the biological evolution of mind we first see the 
 relation of its cognitive and active qualities in the sequence of 
 stimulus and contraction ; when a nervous system begins to 
 appear this relation is concentrated in the reflex arc ; and when 
 the energy of reaction grows greater and greater in proportion 
 to the energy of a stimulus, a release of intra-organic potential 
 is implied to which the psychic parallel is feeling and emotion. 
 Mr. Spencer has admirably traced and illustrated the develop- 
 ment of the correspondence between the living mind and the 
 conditions of its existence ; he has shown how the corre- 
 spondence extends in space and time, and increases in 
 speciality, generality and complexity (Psychology, Part III.). 
 Tiiroughout, the character of the mental organism and all its 
 powers and activities are conditioned by Natural Selection ; 
 whereby it becomes, through obedience, the interpreter of the 
 law and reason of the world. 
 
 " The essential feature of living matter," says A. D. Waller, 
 " ia its instability." Every organic body is metabolic : it can 
 only maintain its existence if a moving equilibrium be 
 established between waste and repair, that is, as long as the 
 anabolic balances the catabolic process. Every change in it, 
 therefore, has a reference to some further change : tliis is its 
 teleological character ; and it is sanctioned by Natural Selection, 
 which favours those forms that live best, and best conduct the 
 
246 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 activities that preserve life. Self-preservation, said the Stoics, 
 is the first effort of Nature. It is only by internal forces that 
 inorganic compounds are preserved ; but self-preservation, by 
 the very process of change, is characteristic of the organic — by 
 " the adaptation of internal to external relations." Hence 
 everything, so far as it is conscious, always strives to live, to 
 obtain food, to find its mate, to escape enemies or defeat them. 
 
 All activity is destructive and must be repaired ; the 
 individual dies at last and must be replaced : hence the 
 appetites of hunger, thirst and sex. In the satisfaction of 
 these appetites lies the primary interest and attention of 
 animals : success is pleasure and " corroboration of vital 
 motion " ; failure is pain and enfeeblement. 
 
 In attention, all the organism is focussed, and all its powers 
 are brought to bear on whatever is interesting. This attitude 
 is certainly favoured by Natural Selection ; and the same may 
 be said for the primary functions of cognition, assimilation 
 and discrimination. Assimilation is, in the first place, the 
 ground of action ; because, a known situation having been 
 reinstated, an action formerly successful may be repeated, an 
 action formerly unsuccessful inhibited ; and the pleasure of 
 former success reinforces repetition, and the pain of former 
 failure inhibits it. By discrimination, assimilation is defined 
 and guarded. At their first appearance in micro-organisms 
 these functions have a quasi-chemical aspect ; there the living 
 thing blends with inorganic Nature ; whilst, in the progress of 
 animal and human life, we find them to have contained the 
 germs of reason and science. Since, when we know what a 
 thing is and where we are, we know also what to do, assimila- 
 tion is pleasurable ; and from this humble source is derived 
 the impassioned joy of explanation. 
 
 When images begin to enter into the mental life, the 
 difference between them and perceptions is a condition of 
 sanity, and to this difference is proportioned the energy of 
 their motor reactions. Images subserve foresight and adap- 
 tation to things remote ; and their guiding power depends 
 on the processes of Association ; which are determined by 
 Natural Selection. For association and suggestion according 
 
NATURAL HISTORY OF THE SUBJECT 247 
 
 to contiguity, correspond with the connections that muke one 
 thing a mark of another in time and place ; and the con- 
 tirraation of association by repetition ensures a tendency to 
 think of things in some proportion to the frequency of their 
 recurrence. True, these tendencies may be very misleading, 
 and must often be destructive ; but animal life is generally 
 confined to a narrow routine in which approximate adaptation 
 is enough for the species. Interest and attention confirm 
 associations, because, in the routine life, that is interesting 
 which is preservative. The unhappiness of human life is due to 
 the failure of routine, and the persistence of primitive interests 
 in conditions that require analytic reason and circumspect 
 control, whilst these powers are still undeveloped. 
 
 § 3. Whilst the adaptation of the organism to deal 
 directly with things remote in space has reached a high degree 
 of perfection in many animals, particularly in some birds of 
 prey, its aoaptation to deal with events remote in time is 
 characteristic of man. Teleology, as we have seen, is inherent 
 in all organic life, as a series or system of co-ordinated self- 
 and - species preservative changes : this begins with the 
 appetites ; is carried further by many instincts having a 
 remoter reference, in which there is a consciousness of the 
 action and a s-.rong feeling for it, but no distinct consciousness, 
 or even none at all, of the end : in human life it is increas- 
 ingly taken up into an explicit consciousness of ends and 
 means, though bhis process is far from complete ; I mean that 
 human nature is still largely instinctive and full of ideas and 
 impulses whose purpose it does not understand. 
 
 To deal successfully with events remote in time, there 
 must be a certain spontaneous orderliness of thought or 
 expectation, of which animals exhibit the beginnings ; but, 
 further, a power cf discovering the order of Nature, laws of the 
 relations of events, and of calculating their results with some 
 degree of precisioL or probability — in a word, reason. Of this 
 I shall speak presently ; but here I draw attention to a third 
 condition of the attainment of remote results, namely, the 
 growth of corresponding feelings. Plato had regarded certain 
 passions as the natural allies of reason, and even the later 
 
248 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 Stoics found a place in their death's-head dogma for rational 
 emotions. Aristotle saw that " thought moves nothing " ; 
 though his expressions are not always consistent with this 
 truth ; for he talks of desire being opposed to reason, instead 
 of to the desire to act reasonably. But Spinoza was the first 
 to see clearly that " a passion can only be controlled by 
 another and stronger passion," and that the orderliness of our 
 life requires the development of emotions fit for human nature ; 
 though the, influence of Aristotle led him to put a too exclu- 
 sive stress upon the philosophic nisus. We see, then, the 
 inadequacy of defining man merely as ' rational ' : since 
 reason must be unavailing without the growth of correspond- 
 ing feelings, these must equally be differentiae of human 
 nature. 
 
 Perhaps it is not quite true that thought, or its physical 
 process, moves nothing ; it has some energy, but not enough 
 to move twelve stone ; for that there must be a release of 
 potential, and therefore (where organisation is imperfect) a 
 wave of feeling. But purposive actions arise in special 
 situations, such as aggression and escape, and thence acquire a 
 speciality of feeling. I take it that every special emotion is 
 an integration of the algedonic experiences of actions of the 
 same kind as those that they now reinforce and sustain. 
 Under the influence of less specialised feeling, efforts to escape 
 or hide generated the emotion of fear ; habits of hoarding 
 were the precondition of prudence ; the practice of equal 
 sharing gave rise to the sense of justice ; aud the worship 
 preceded the love of God. 
 
 With the development of animal life adaptation to a 
 greater and greater variety of circumstances becomes necessary ; 
 in man most, and especially in civilised man. Every situation, 
 as determined by purposes and the relations of persons and 
 things, has its own feeling ; and therefore our feelings are 
 shaded and blended in endless variety, so ihat Malebranche 
 may have been justified in saying that perhaps no two men 
 ever felt the same passion. Still, certain situations frequently 
 recur which approximate to an average tfpe, and there are 
 emotions corresponding with such situations having a suf- 
 
NATUKAL HISTORY OF THE SUBJECT 249 
 
 ficiently specific character to be readily recognised, though 
 they cannot be precisely classified. 
 
 The emotions exist either to intensify expression, like Joy 
 and Grief, or to reinforce action. Tlie latter are either 
 Impulsive, like Fear, Anger, Affection, which are common to 
 the higher animals, — the interpretation of their apparent 
 manifestation in the lowest animals is conjectural, - — or 
 liegulative in many degrees of co-ordination : the inferior 
 degrees being shared by some animals, whilst the superior are 
 proper to man, or even to some civilised men. 
 
 The regulation of action implies inhibition ; and this may 
 be due to the asthenic influence of an emotion tinged with 
 fear, or dread, like Prudence ; or to the fact that if one action 
 is effectually reinforced all incompatible actions must be 
 suppressed, as Justice suppresses Arrogance. 
 
 The regulative feelings, like the impulsive, are at first 
 instinctive ; that is, they direct conduct to an end without a 
 distinct prevision of that end, and with most men such is 
 still their condition. Quasi-rational, they help to secure the 
 ends of reason during the immaturity of reason ; they are 
 provident without circumspection, and but for them, reason- 
 ing, even to the last, would be ineffectual. 
 
 Various emotions may be considered as specially subserv- 
 ing the interests of the Individual, the Family, the Tribe ; 
 but in a normal civilised man all emotions are socialised, or 
 modified in the interests of the tribe or society. 
 
 Some emotions are concrete, like Love. Others are 
 abstract, like Pride — the integration of all satisfactions in 
 success of whatever kind, but especially in competition ; or 
 like Fairness — the integration of all satisfactions in pro- 
 portionate dealing. The differential circumstances in either 
 case cancel, and the common body of feeling remains with a 
 corresponding reflex or expression, the stiffening of the spinal 
 column or the opening out of the hands. 
 
 The social emotions are (1) Ego-altruistic, representing 
 what we believe to be the feelings of others toward us, such 
 as Vanity, Shame, Honour ; or (2) Altruistic, sympathetic 
 affections toward others, such as Pity, Generosity, Benevolence 
 
250 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 (cf. Spencer's Psychology, Part VIII.) ; or (3) what I can only 
 call Panic emotions, meaning that they depend for their 
 development upon a sympathetic rajpport of the tribe, such as 
 Loyalty, Religion, Duty. If it be said that these last in their 
 highest form, so far from having a panic quality, brace the 
 solitary protestant and most shine against the face of tyranny 
 and clamour, we must remember that this happens in few 
 men, that it is not solitary where God is, and that every 
 mental structure in its highest organisation attains a relative 
 independence. 
 
 I need not show how all these feelings, though instinctive, 
 regulate and rationalise our life ; and this is not the place to 
 show how all emotions, whilst they remain instinctive, involve 
 more or less illusion, guiding the conduct of the individual to 
 ends of Nature other than those which he proposes to himself. 
 
 Play imitates all the actions of life and, therefore, all its 
 feelings. Hence every emotion is experienced in two ways : 
 first, in earnest as a motive or reinforcement, and then in 
 recreation. From the play -instinct the Fine Arts are an 
 outgrowth with a panic inspiration, especially in the rhythmic 
 Arts ; and under this influence the emotions suffer a further 
 transfiguration ; grief turns to pathos, terror to sublimity, 
 laughter to comedy. In this form their motive force is 
 nearly lost ; indeed, the possibility of its suspension is the 
 limit of Art : whence the rule not to intrude poetry into 
 oratory ; which urges to do something, except the encomiastic. 
 Still, indirectly, the Fine Arts are regulative, especially by 
 enhancing loyalty, religion and personal ideals. They unite 
 mankind ; sympathy reconciles us most in suffering, but Art 
 in rapture. 
 
 The effort to reason and to know, the more necessary as 
 the interests of life grow more enduring, has its own in- 
 stinctive passion — Curiosity. Plato and Aristotle traced the 
 beginning of Philosophy to Wonder ; but Wonder presides 
 chiefly over the mythopoeic stage of explanation : from which 
 indeed Plato half emerges, like 
 
 The tawny lion, pawing to get free 
 His hinder parts. 
 
NATURAL HISTORY OF THE SUBJECT 251 
 
 Wonder wants the permanence that is requisite to sustain 
 long and arduous research. Curiosity, derived from remote 
 animal progenitors, and at first directly subserving the simpler 
 needs of life, only finds its true field when the complexity of 
 human society demands the discovery of general truths 
 applicable to various circumstances, and at the same time 
 makes it possible to carry out the division of labour between 
 thought and action. To ensure the service of men at tasks 
 the least directly and plainly useful, like those of Art and 
 Science, Nature infuses master-passions into those whom she 
 calls ; who labour often unrewarded and careless of reward, 
 accounting themselves blest in their toil ; though to the 
 bystander they seem a sort of victims. Becoming aware of 
 this, they justify themselves by proving that science cheapens 
 bread, cotton and pig-iron ; but this is a concession to the 
 illusions of the world ; for amongst all the passions of man- 
 kind Philosophy alone is without illusion. Science truly is 
 a condition of civilisation ; but civilisation is for the sake of 
 Science. 
 
 § 4. Every man is born to develop a peculiar organic 
 structure of impulse and emotion, more of this and less of 
 that, through the whole range of feeKngs. Such a struc- 
 ture varies inexhaustibly from man to man, as faces and 
 finger-prints do, and constitutes his character (the dominant 
 tendencies of his reaction) ; so far as this can be distinguished, 
 on the one hand, from behaviour, which is determined partly 
 by experience ; and, on the other hand, from temperament, 
 which depends upon the ccensesthesis. 
 
 In intra -uterine consciousness, wherein the feeling of 
 nutrition and growth is contrasted with the sense of move- 
 ment and resistance — or ccensesthesis with kinsesthesis — 
 begins the differentiation of Subject and Object. 
 
 The kinaesthesis accompanies all the special sensations, 
 and becomes the connective tissue of the objective mind or 
 Nature. It is that which every other sensation signifies ; 
 and because of the weight and resistance of my body, always 
 pressing on the earth, the significance of perception is always 
 reinforced by present experience : that star, that cloud, that 
 
252 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 church is like this — this earth beneath my feet. My body 
 itself is such a thing ; such things favour or hurt the body 
 and affect the coenaesthesis. Hence the conviction of Physical 
 Reality, and the necessity of the conceptual system of the 
 physical sciences. 
 
 The coeuaesthesis is the original and the most permanent 
 factor of subjective consciousness, the background of all 
 changes of thought and feeling; so that some psychologists 
 regard it as the essence of the personal life. But to me it 
 seems rather to be the essence of subjectivity, and generic in 
 character ; too little individualised to constitute a person ; 
 who springs from it like a tree from the soil, or (say) like a 
 leaf from the tree. The utmost subjectivity brings us nearest 
 of all that we know to eternal and universal Being ; but a 
 man inhabits Time and Society. Expectation, memory, endur- 
 ing interests, concatenated endeavours, achievements and plans 
 mark out the cycle of his life, his individuality. 
 
 The living organism, moreover, cannot be understood 
 merely as the Subject ; it is the union of Subject and Object ; 
 for the kinaesthesis is as constant an experience as the 
 coensesthesis ; and hence spring our surmises concerning the 
 truth of the World. 
 
 But neither can man be understood merely as an individual, 
 for his interests are fused with other men's ; sympathy signifies, 
 as Schopenhauer shows, the kindred of mankind, and even of 
 organic nature ; and so do religious beliefs. Biological theory 
 explains this by the continuity of all life in Time, which (aa 
 we say) is more real than Space, the divider ; and doubtless 
 the coensesthesis is continuous, derived from germ to germ. 
 
 Hence a man's personality is inseparable from the family 
 and its possessions and traditions ; and hitherto it has been 
 inseparable from the Tribe or State. There, on the one hand, 
 grows up a consciousness of the relation of self to others, 
 according to rules implying responsibility and defining the 
 individual ; on the other hand, suggestion, imitation, education, 
 emulation and specialised industry and rank, modify hie 
 individuality, and disguise his character by codes of behaviour. 
 And further, since society is the greater part of every man's 
 
NATUKAL HISTORY OF THP: SUBJECT 253 
 
 environment, it operates selectively, eliminating those who 
 fail to ' behave,' and thus determining the possible types of 
 character itself. 
 
 Different social conditions, town or country ; different 
 constitutions, despotic or free, operate differently in the 
 selection of character ; and of all considerations bearing upon 
 the comparison of social or political affairs, this is the most 
 important to mankind. Mill thought that Democracy tended 
 to favour uniformity and mediocrity of character, because he 
 dreaded uniformity and mediocrity ; Plato thought that 
 Democracy produced the utmost variety and extravagance of 
 character, because he hated Democracy and variety ; and it is 
 certainly odd that the worse motive should have prompted 
 the better inference. 
 
 § 5. Nothing so clearly proves the secondary and dependent 
 character of the individual as a study of his appetites, desires, 
 emotions ; for they all refer to things or persons beyond him, 
 in relation to which he endeavours, so far as he is aware of 
 them, to adjust his actions, in order to save, or to better, him- 
 self, his family, his tribe. His actions depend upon what he 
 is aware of and what he is capable of desiring ; neither of 
 which can be arbitrarily altered. Nay, his desires further 
 determine what he shall be aware of ; confine his eyes within 
 the deep-trodden lane of customary life ; or if he ever looks over 
 the hedge, determine what shall interest him in the world 
 around, and therefore what he shall see there. Hence in the 
 quality and limits of our desires lies the true poverty of 
 human nature : it springs from a poor root. 
 
 A few generations ago we were little better than savages ; 
 a few generations farther back, and what then ? If the state 
 in which we live is civilisation, it has come too soon ; we have 
 not had time to prepare for it. The reign of man has been 
 established before he is fit to govern. Power has been acquired 
 over Nature ; but for most men there is no further use for 
 it than to provide a frivolous variety of satisfactions for the 
 same cravings of the same soul that 5000 years ago was 
 happier upon a kitchen-midden. 
 
 So unready are we that every country swarms with 
 
254 THE METAPHYSICS OE NATUKE 
 
 thieves, harlots, faith -healers, gamblers, idlers, miracle-mongers, 
 quacks, politicians, and all sorts of parasites and impostors. 
 And for the rest of men, or not much less than half, who can 
 give a sincere reason why they should live in such toil and 
 darkness ? For some indeed there is ease and comfort, — a 
 noble result of Nature's travailing and groaning ; for a few 
 there is even wealth and ostentation. There is social gaiety, 
 possible by the grace of oblivion. Philanthropy, more truly 
 honourable than hopeful, and Art and Science remain, 
 
 Nothing is more depressing than the poetry of magic and 
 devil-conjuring: there we see the hero armed with super- 
 natural power, and helpless because he remains himself. 
 Hence Shakespeare treats such power ironically : Prospero 
 makes an exalted marriage for his daughter, and recovers the 
 duchy which, when formerly possessed, was never valued. 
 Superstitious prejudice, exasperated by the Eenascence, produced 
 the legend of Faustus ; and Marlowe's genius cannot disguise 
 its fatuity. According to Goethe, Faust escapes the devil and 
 satisfies his own soul by reclaiming waste land and founding 
 an industrial colony. We find with some disappointment 
 that the devil cannot help us to anything that cannot be 
 done without him. The same thing happens when epic poets, 
 from Homer to Milton, treat of the gods. The gods, it 
 seems, have the same narrow interests as we have ; or, indeed, 
 narrower ; for to idealise is to impoverish. So there is no 
 escape from our lot ; even imagination is as helpless as the 
 devil. Popular pictures of Heaven would be extravagantly 
 comic, if one did not reflect how desirable must seem eternal 
 rest to the weary, clean linen to the dirty, and a decent 
 participation in glory to the down-trodden and despised. 
 
 I do not suggest that human nature is always the same ; 
 far from it : but progress is slow, the average man of a race 
 advances little in 3000 years; the head of the procession 
 drags after it an appalling tail, and sometimes there is 
 retrogression. There has been during the last 100 years. 
 For it is an obvious truth that whenever any species has 
 unusual facility in getting a living, it degenerates ; since many 
 poor specimens then survive who, imder normal difficulties, 
 
NATUKAL HISTOKY OF THE SUliJECT 255 
 
 must have perished. This is the condition under which the 
 population of North-west Europe and America, by the aid of 
 machinery and expanding industries, has so rapidly increased. 
 It cannot continue indefinitely, but will probably end in a 
 period of remorseless selection and misery. Modern industry 
 has done nothing for human happiness ; but it was necessary 
 to the inventing and perfecting of scientific apparatus. 
 
 § 6. As our character determines our actions so it deter- 
 mines our thoughts ; for thought is a kind of action. Char- 
 acter, that is, determines our thinking, so far as we are able to 
 think; but the ability to think depends upon the plan or 
 structure of that which thinks, or upon its original disposition 
 to produce such a plan. As we are now speaking of phenomena, 
 this means that the ability to think is objectively represented 
 by the plan and structure of the brain. I suppose that every 
 brain has a certain innate disposition, generic, specific, in- 
 dividual, to develop certain connections of its tracts or sub- 
 organs ; and, in the case of the higher animals and man, an 
 aptitude for falling from time to time into new combinations, 
 which constitute a further development of its structure (if 
 confirmed) and exhibit the same specific or individual traits. 
 Plasticity of structure corresponds with originality of thought. 
 
 At first, all cognition and thought merely subserves the 
 organism, as a lamp before the footsteps of desire. Then with 
 the adaptation of man and society to more and more remote 
 conditions, thought discovers the objects of our true desire ; 
 that which is good for us on the whole, co-ordinates best our 
 conduct, is consented to by the preponderant weight of our 
 character ; which implies the inhibition of " chance desires " 
 that tend to frustrate the attainment of that good. Mean- 
 while, in these labours thought becomes self-impassioned and 
 obtains strength to lead its own life ; and we learn that he who 
 would discover truth must have in view no interest but truth. 
 
 Adaptive intelligence begins not from reflex action, nor 
 from instinct, but from expectation, which is a simple out- 
 growth of perception : differing from it in this, that some 
 interesting factor of an experience-complex is deferred. Ex- 
 pectation is not a projection of conscious memory, but of 
 
256 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 experience ; for the predominant course of the stream of con- 
 sciousness is forward ; the primitive movement of attention is 
 watchfully forward ; at the lower levels of life no power is 
 possessed that is not useful, and memory (as distinct from re- 
 tentiveness) only becomes useful when there is sufficient 
 fulness and plasticity of mind to compare and discriminate, 
 and so to adapt conduct to new cases by the light of the old. 
 It may be, indeed, that primitive expectation is not even 
 illuminated by an idea of that which is expected ; for it seems 
 enough that there should be an attitude of preparation, and 
 a subactivity of certain nervous tracts facilitating the per- 
 ception of certain objects, and inhibiting all actions excited 
 by irrelevant objects. Certainly expectation is exhibited by 
 animals much lower in the scale of organisation than the 
 level at which evidence can be found of dreaming, hallucina- 
 tion, or home-sickness : the three criteria of the capacity for 
 free ideas according to Komanes, — the last of which is 
 questionable (^Mental Evolution in Animals, chap. x.). 
 
 From this lowly stage of adaptive intelligence, the rise of 
 memory and free generic ideas, or recepts, leads to " reasoning 
 from particulars to particulars " ; that is, to a judging of the 
 present in the light of parallel cases recalled. Not that such 
 reasoning supersedes the early expectant judgment ; for this 
 still serves us well, even after the last stage of reasoning has 
 become possible by means of principles, generalised or abstracted 
 from aggregates of remembered or recorded experience, and 
 methodically verified. 
 
 § 7. Generalisations concerning the relations of things 
 and events are possible only by means of language ; and, 
 therefore, if generalised thought is a human differentia, society, 
 in which alone the growth of language is possible, is older 
 than man. This truth, that man never by contract or other- 
 wise formed society, but that society is older than he, and 
 that from the first he has grown up and been moulded in all 
 his traits in relation to society, is of the utmost importance to 
 Moral Philosophy ; but what we are here concerned to note is 
 that the language that has developed in social life is the 
 necessary organ of Reason. 
 
 I 
 
NATURAL HISTORY OF THE SUBJECT 257 
 
 That we should reason chiefly by means of language seems 
 a superficial and probably deceptive arrangement, and in fact 
 so it is ; but the possibility and even necessity of it appears 
 when we consider that the advantage of economising time and 
 energy has imposed a symbolic character on all mental opera- 
 tions. The reasoning by means of signs is not an unintelli- 
 gible change in the process of mental growth ; we find the 
 same thing in perception, where (normally) visual sensations 
 are the signs of complex objects and motions ; and in memory 
 and imagination, not only as derived chiefly from vision in 
 most of us, but also by the use of fragments of images to 
 signify extensive tracts of potential representation, or of words 
 to supersede even the fragments of images. This is the 
 condition of that " quickness " commonly ascribed to thought ; 
 for if in such processes of representation we could not be 
 content without reviewing the whole phantasmagoria of our 
 associations, thought would by no means be quick. And the 
 same device facilitates volition : for the most part it is only in 
 acquiring control of an unused muscle, or of a new muscle- 
 grouping, that ideas of actions are explicit in consciousness ; 
 but otherwise they are taken for granted, — complicated with 
 the idea of the end to be attained, as the weight of an object 
 is complicated with its visual presentation, — whence the tran- 
 sition is easy to secondary automacy. 
 
 In all these cases the effectiveness of abbreviation depends 
 upon the strength of integration or association between the 
 signs and the facts signified. Without this condition, reason- 
 ing, whether with ourselves or with others, could not, as it 
 often does, take the form of a verbal continuum, comparable 
 with the visual continuum that, as we look round, presents to 
 us the realm of Nature. Accordingly, the fitness of language 
 to lead our thoughts is ensured by its three-fold roots in the 
 mind and a corresponding intricacy and pervadingness of asso- 
 ciation : namely, as received by the ear, as articulated, and as 
 seen by the eye — not only when written but in lip-movement 
 and in the accompanying gestures and expression. And being 
 in all these ways, but especially in articulation, an active experi- 
 ence, it is an apt organ of attention and of universal control. 
 
 17 
 
258 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Still, whilst language is an indispensable organ of human 
 reason, it implies the existence of a reason of which it is the 
 organ, that is, the organisation of the mind as a whole, which 
 has come into existence for the use and for the sake of 
 reasoning, because the world itself is orderly and predictable. 
 Spencer has given the most elaborate account of the growth of 
 this organisation : see his Principles of Psychology, especially 
 Part III., ou Mind as a Correspondence, and Part V., on the 
 Evolution of the Nervous System ; also Part II. chap, ii., on 
 the Composition of Mind, and Part VIII. chap, iii., on the 
 Development of Conceptions. The chief defects of his theory 
 are its extreme abstractness, as if the process of development 
 depended not at all upon the endeavour of the individual mind 
 to know ; and its giving no part to language itself in aiding 
 the evolution of Eeason. 
 
 The essential features of rational organisation are, on the 
 one hand, the perceiving, imagining, thinking as totalities 
 those things, events, ideas that have a physical or logical 
 cohesion ; and, on the other hand, the discriminating and 
 identifying as such the properties and relations of those 
 totalities. Both these processes, grouping and abstraction, 
 whatever crude beginnings of them may exist in the animal 
 world by the " logic of recepts," depend in the degree in which 
 they are performed by ourselves upon the words and construc- 
 tions of language. The groupings range from such simple 
 percepts as " stone " or " flying bird " to such complex ideas 
 as " History of Home," " Astronomy," " Self," " World " ; the 
 abstractions range from such recepts or generic impressions 
 as " sweet," or " edible " to such categories as " gravitation," 
 " number," " equality " ; and it cannot be supposed that the 
 later terms of these series could possibly be fixed and manipu- 
 lated without language. 
 
 In considering the rational organisation of experience by 
 grouping and abstraction, or synthesis and analysis, it is 
 usual to confine the term reasoning to the analytic process ; 
 but, in fact, the two processes are inseparable. High abstrac- 
 tions imply vast aggregates of experience to be compared, and 
 the aggregates themselves, though largely formed by associa- 
 
NATURAL HISTORY OF THE SUBJECT 259 
 
 tion, are extended by iuferences, and limited by discriminative 
 judgments. According to Wundt, to reason is to analyse a 
 total idea that has been formed by " apperceptive synthesis " 
 (selective attention) ; but this is too narrow a view. We do, 
 indeed, analyse an aggregate idea, as we do a percept. We 
 analyse (say) an orange, by attending to its visual properties, 
 prepared to grasp whatever other properties suggest themselves. 
 Similarly, we may attend to the sign of an aggregate idea 
 (usually a verbal sign), — say, Cartesianism, — and note the 
 contents that suggest themselves, — initial doubt, certitude of 
 self-consciousness, innate ideas, mutual exclusiveness of thought 
 and extension, etc. ; and further, the relations between those 
 ideas that constitute the total, and which, like the whole, are 
 known to us by their verbal signs. But the more original 
 functions of reasoning are the breaking up of aggregate ideas 
 erroneously formed, and the building up of others upon juster 
 conceptions of community ; for example, to judge that the 
 idea of Monarchy as including Constitutionalism and Autocracy 
 is superficial and misleading, and that the true connection of 
 Constitutional Monarchy is with Republics : or, again, the 
 identification of aggregates commonly assumed to be opposed ; 
 for example, to judge that human life, animal life, and plant 
 life agree in this, that Malthus' law of population is equally 
 true of them all. It could be shown, I think, that our 
 advances in reasoning, including the great scientific discoveries, 
 conform to these types. 
 
 When aggregates are named they are apt to acquire not 
 only unity but isolation ; more especially when their names 
 signify opposition, the aggregates they stand for have a mutual 
 repulsion. Words spread a sort of skin over their meanings : 
 such ideas as buying and selling, rational and brutal, mind 
 and matter, become so strongly delimited, that until the 
 barriers are broken through by some exceptional nisus of 
 thought, there is an end of understanding. 
 
 The faculty that carries forward this disruptive and 
 recombining process is the primitive function of discrimination 
 and assimilation, raised to various powers under the name 
 of abstract thought. William James happily describes the 
 
260 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 procedure as " dissociation by varying concomitants." I 
 believe the credit of first explaining the matter is due to 
 Hume in his Treatise, Book I. Part I. § 7, 0/^ Abstraction, 
 especially the last two paragraphs on the " distinction of 
 reason." When any quality or relation is repeated amidst 
 complex experiences that otherwise vary, it attains a quasi- 
 independence ; and the same is true when a quality varies 
 amidst complexes otherwise constant. In either case, attention 
 is attracted and assimiliation is accomplished; and thence- 
 forth the identification of the quality or relation is facilitated 
 should it occur in further experience. Its fixation is assured 
 by a name or proposition. 
 
 The primitive function of assimilation is therefore also 
 the ground of the explanation of Nature ; for this consists in 
 the progressive identification of the properties and relations 
 of things and events under all the disguises of variety, and 
 the co-ordination of them in a system of concepts and laws, 
 the most general or abstract of which are called Categories 
 and Axioms. 
 
 We have now considered self-conscious reason as arising 
 in individuals in the course of nature by natural laws. If 
 this is the explanation of the individual, it is also the 
 guarantee of the reality of the World. In no other way is 
 that explanation and guarantee possible ; no otherwise can 
 the knower be related to the known ; and only so far as 
 there is law can there be any system or any truth. The 
 development of reason carries with it the criteria of truth : it 
 becomes clear and definite, excludes contradiction, presupposes 
 uniformity, and tends to establish universal consent. 
 
 Whether, or in what sense, the World itself is to be 
 thought rational, we are not yet ready to discuss. To declare 
 that that which reason interprets must be rational, may be 
 rash and even impious. Discursive reason is tentative and 
 fallible ; in Nature there are no paralogisms nor " provisional 
 hypotheses." But if it be hazardous to speak of the World 
 as Universal Reason, at least we are sure that it is the 
 ground, the measure, the law, the judge, and in every way 
 the superior of human reason. 
 
BOOK IV.-THE CATEGORIES 
 

 I 
 
CHAPTER XIII 
 
 ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 
 
 I. Relation in General 
 
 § 1. In Formal Logic a Judgment is analysed into two 
 Terms (subject and predicate) and a Eelation between them 
 (marked by the copula) ; and it is usual to speak of subject 
 and predicate as concepts, but not to call the relation between 
 them a concept. Yet it expresses the same judgment to say 
 ' A is like B,' or ' A and B are alike ' ; ' A is the cause of B,' 
 or * A and B are cause and effect.' Thus the relation of the 
 terms is turned into a predicate, and so becomes manifestly a 
 concept. It is true, though not immediately relevant, that, 
 as Hamilton says, every concept, though in the place of the 
 subject or predicate term, itself involves relations, and is a 
 " fasciculus of Judgments." Now the Metaphysic of Logic is a 
 reflective evaluation of conceptual knowledge ; but of course it 
 examines not all concepts, — an infinite task, — but those that 
 are variously called the highest, or most abstract, or universal, 
 or fundamental ; and such are the concepts that are most 
 conspicuously relations because commonly in the place of the 
 copula in judgments : wherefore Kant called them " judging 
 concepts " ; and, following him, it has become fashionable to 
 call them Categories. 
 
 The recognition of Eelation as the nexus of all judgment 
 and knowledge is a late result of analysis ; it was, I believe, 
 original with Locke, and is one of his chief services to 
 Philosophy. Plato had reckoned some relations amongst the 
 Ideas which he regarded as constitutive conditions of experi- 
 
 263 
 
264 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 ence; Aristotle had given Kelation the fourth place in the 
 list of Categories. But the vague logical copula was for ages 
 allowed to disguise with superficial facility both the true 
 unity and the variety of thought ; so that, although Locke's 
 doctrine was illustrated and reinforced by Hume, Kant, misled 
 by his admiration of the Scholastic Logic, treated Relation as 
 only one genus of the Categories ; although Eelation is as 
 essential, if not as conspicuous in the Categories of Quality 
 and Quantity as in Substance and Attribute, Cause and 
 Effect. Moreover, whilst indicating a special connection 
 between the three categories of each genus, he declared them 
 to be all equally original and independent. Hegel, following 
 Fichte, added to the number of the Categories and pretended 
 to deduce them one from another in a series, beginning with 
 Being and ending with the Idea (or Thought of the Universe), 
 by a necessary process of dialectic. But no enterprise was 
 ever more irrational. The argument is sometimes fallacious, 
 depends often upon bare assertions and arbitrary definitions. 
 Relation first emerges under the rubric of Appearance, and is 
 naively investigated in special cases after having been assumed 
 again and again : being in fact the nerve of every dialectical 
 process, since this takes place (by the way) in the mind of 
 some thinker, not amongst Categories in vacuo. But recent 
 Psychology and Metaphysics agree in restoring Relation to 
 its true place as the essential character of apperceptive con- 
 sciousness, the universal of cognition and thought of thought. 
 
 § 2. The Categories, or most general forms in which 
 men judge, are, then, the object of our present inquiry ; and, 
 first. Relation itself, whether it is clear or (in other words) 
 possible ; and, if so, whether it is valid : for both points are 
 disputed. 
 
 In the Theory of Logic (chap, ii.) I observed that " A 
 relation cannot be defined, for we know of nothing more 
 elementary. The only way of bringing it to light is by 
 contrasting it with its co-ordinate abstraction, the term. 
 Every relation lies between, or connects, or ties two terms, 
 and no more. All terms are connected and tied by relations. 
 * * * The world consists of related terms or terminated 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 265 
 
 relations. This seems to be the eud of all analysis, whether 
 of the Object or Subject." In this somewhat figurative way 
 I sought to express the necessary form of all judgment ; and 
 I still hold that every sound Logic or Metaphysics of Logic 
 must make this its starting-point. Accordingly, it was a 
 great satisfaction to tind that in Appearance and Reality 
 (chap, iii.) F. H. Bradley takes a similar view of the indissoluble 
 co-implication of these elements of thought. He says in § 1 : 
 " Qualities are nothing without relations. * * * We have 
 seen that in fact the two are never found apart. We have 
 seen that the separation by abstraction is no proof of real 
 separateness. And now we have to urge, in short, that any 
 separateness implies separation, and so relation, and is there- 
 fore, when made absolute, a self-discrepancy." Nothing can 
 be truer or better stated ; nevertheless, he j&nds the conception 
 full of intricate puzzles. 
 
 In § 2 he writes : "We have found that qualities without 
 relation have no intelligible meaning. Unfortunately, taken 
 together with them they are equally unintelligible. They 
 cannot, in the first place, be wholly resolved into relations. 
 Hence the qualities must be, and must also be related. But 
 there is hence a diversity which falls inside each quality. It 
 has a double character, as both supporting and as being made 
 by the relation." To recognise these two aspects of the 
 quality is, of course, to relate them ; and then each aspect 
 may be treated in the same way ; and the process is endless. 
 
 But why should the process begin ? For a quality to 
 " be " and to " be related " are not two facts : to treat them 
 as different is a breach of the conditions already laid down, 
 that " qualities are nothing without relations." To treat the 
 being of a quality as distinct from its relatedness, is to make 
 abstract separateness absolute, and leads (as foretold) to self- 
 discrepancy. Whose fault is that ? 
 
 In § 3 we read : " We may briefly reach the same dilemma 
 from the side of relations. They are nothing intelligible 
 either with or without their qualities. In the first place, a 
 relation without terms seems mere verbiage, and terms appear, 
 therefore, to be something beyond their relation." A relation 
 
266 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 without terms is " a false abstraction, and a thing which 
 loudly contradicts itself." " But how the relation can stand 
 to the qualities is, on the other hand, unintelligible. If it is 
 nothing to the qualities, then they are not related to it at 
 all ; and, if so, as we saw, they have ceased to be qualities, 
 and their relation is a nonentity. But if it is something to 
 them, then clearly we now shall require a new connecting 
 relation. For the relation hardly can be the mere adjective 
 of one or both of its terms ; or at least as such it seems 
 indefensible. And, being something itself, if it does not 
 itself bear a relation to the terms, in what intelligible way 
 will it succeed in being anything to them ? " This process 
 also is endless. 
 
 The dilemma assumes that a relation must be either 
 " nothing " or " something " to the qualities ; and then comes 
 proof that it can be neither : therefore, the notion is unin- 
 telligible. But the whole process depends upon our forgetting 
 the original position that terms and relations imply one 
 another. When it is said, " If it [the relation] is nothing 
 [or something] to the qualities," are we to understand by 
 " it " the relation considered in abstraction from the qualities, 
 or the relation in actuality along with the qualities ? 
 
 In the latter sense (the only legitimate one) the supposition 
 is — 'if the relation of qualities is to be nothing to the qualities 
 as related, they are not related at all ; if something, we requu'e 
 a new connecting relation.' But these horns are only made of 
 paper : for the relation of qualities and the qualities as related 
 are the same thing ; so that the supposition of one being 
 nothing to the other, or of tlieir needing fiurther relation, is 
 merely supererogatory. 
 
 If, on the other hand, we are to understand by " it " the 
 relation considered in abstraction from the qualities, this is 
 precisely what has been condemned (quite justly) as a " false 
 abstraction." Yet now it is described as being " something 
 itself," and " bearing a relation to the terms," apart from 
 which, we have just been told, it cannot be conceived at all. 
 The fact is that the author, after having declared terms and 
 relations, taken severally, to be false abstractions, is still a 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 267 
 
 victim of the natural illusiou that separate words imply 
 separate things, and that therefore terms and relations must 
 be such things. His whole argument is a misapplication of 
 the ' Third Man ' : which always consists in showing that a 
 certain position involves the " finding new relations without 
 end." But the position against which this objection is valid 
 is always a denial in some form that ' relation of terms ' is 
 ultimate : such a position as Plato's Idea, or Green's Self- 
 consciousness, or Spencer's Absolute. The ' Third Man ' shows 
 that relation of terms is ultimate ; and the third chapter of 
 Appearance and Eeality shows the same thing: but this is a 
 very different matter from the showing that 'relation of terms' 
 is unintelligible, which was the point to be proved. 
 
 Some light may be thrown upon this matter if, instead of 
 illustrating related terms by A-B, we take a particular case, 
 such as greenness and transparency , terms related as coinhering 
 in emerald. Suppose it to be said that we may take either 
 term and compare it with the relation, say, greenness with 
 coinherence ; and that as the relation of difference then 
 emerges, we may again take this and compare it with either 
 term ; and so on. But there are some oversights in this 
 dialectic. For, first, in comparing coinherence with greenness 
 we are not comparing a relation with a term ; coinherence has 
 become a term in the act of comparison. To overlook this is 
 to assume that relations are self-existent things or species ; 
 whereas they are functions of thought, so that a relation of 
 terms in one process may be the term of a relation in another. 
 But, secondly, the relation of difference emerging from the 
 above comparison, is not a new fact ; for it was involved in 
 the original thought of greenness as a quality related to 
 another by coinherence. This rests upon the classification of 
 the elements of thought according to their functions into 
 terms and relations ; and this is justifiable because " separation 
 by abstraction is no proof of real separateness." 
 
 The abstract consideration of terms and relations is only 
 possible by means of language. We have here the extreme 
 case of the ' distinction of reason.' Starting from the position 
 that Relation of Terms is ultimate for thought, there is no 
 
268 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 difficulty in seeing how either terms or relations may acquire 
 a quasi-independence. We need only reflect that, though 
 there are no terms unrelated, yet each term may stand in 
 many different relations to other terms. Hence it is inde- 
 pendent of any particular relation or relationship ; and this is 
 the nearest we can get to its heing as distinct from its heing 
 related. Similarly, any general relation is independent of any 
 particular terms. As red is unlike yellow and also unlike 
 green, and yellow is unlike green and also unlike blue ; and 
 as the tone C is unlike D, and D unlike E, and so on through 
 all orders of phenomena; it becomes possible, by means of words, 
 to think of Unlikeness apart from any given contrast, although 
 without supposing some terms the word is meaningless, or (as 
 F. H. Bradley admirably expresses it) it is a " false abstraction." 
 
 He says, " The conclusion to which I am brought is that 
 a relational way of thought — any one that moves by the 
 machinery of terms and relations — must give appearance and 
 not truth." And with this position, if it means that relational 
 thought can yield only relative not absolute truth, I have no 
 quarrel ; for it is a familiar doctrine of the good old-fashioned 
 Empirical Philosophy. And I agree heartily when he adds : 
 " Our intellect " (that is, the Absolutist's intellect) " has been 
 condemned to confusion and bankruptcy " ; for, in fact, it 
 never yet honoured a single draught. 
 
 The Absolute, I believe, is a whole without internal 
 contradiction ; and knowledge of the Universe as a whole will 
 not be obtained in this or the next generation, even if thought 
 do not involve an infinite regress. Whether our knowledge 
 involves an internal contradiction, is indeed a serious question ; 
 but an infinite regress is not an internal contradiction. And, 
 odd as it may seem, relation is the one thing that c^u never 
 be self-contradictory ; for the Principle of Contradiction runs : 
 It is impossible for anything to be and not be in the same 
 relation. The principle, therefore, applies to terms as related, 
 and assumes the validity of relation ; and this is the same 
 thing as to say, what is obvious and trite, that the validity of 
 relation cannot be denied, except by a judgment that takes it 
 for granted. 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 269 
 
 § 3. If the concept of Relation is clear and valid in the 
 sense of being free from internal contradiction, it still remains 
 to inquire into its objective validity : do the relations 
 established in apperception correspond with Reality ? We 
 saw in Chap. VI. (§1) that Spencer disputes this. In the 
 passage there quoted he says, that our sense of the diflierence 
 of two colours corresponds with notliing in the outward fact ; 
 for it is merely a change of our consciousness, whilst the 
 colours remain unchanged. From the context, however, it 
 appears that by " two colours " Spencer means two " objective 
 agencies unknown and unknowable " (Frinc. of Psych. § 93). 
 
 It is of no use to ask how any one can know that unknow- 
 able agencies are two, are mutually independent and are 
 unchanged. It is a desperate question. But confining 
 ourselves to a consideration of the correspondence between 
 Judgment and Empirical Reality, I venture to say that, when 
 two colours — say red and blue — side by side are seen by us 
 to be different, to find whether or not there is any conscious- 
 ness of them and of their difference other than that of organic 
 Subjects, is a problem, if not a very prosperous one, and not 
 an occasion for dogma. 
 
 Further, to speak of the relation of such colours, " as we 
 think it, being nothing else than a change of our state," is to 
 give a very inadequate account of the matter. Such may 
 have been the germ of relational cognition in primitive 
 organic consciousness, but for us at present the consciousness 
 of red and blue is an essential part of the consciousness of their 
 difference. Sense-qualities, from the multiplicity of their 
 relations in an experience coinciding with the differentiation 
 of the organism, have become independent of any particular 
 relations. They cannot be resolved into relations ; the older 
 doctrine of Psychological Relativity, according to which even 
 every sensation varied with its context, was much overstated : 
 it confused the sensation with the relations in which it is 
 known. But the progress of organic consciousness is toward 
 fuller and more definite knowledge : manifestly, red and blue 
 and the other sense-qualities exist in Empirical Reality, and 
 our perception of their differences is based upon that fact. In 
 
270 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 other words, things are objectively different, whether there is 
 an objective non-organic consciousness of their difference, or 
 whether non-organic consciousness is non-relative. 
 
 The validity of Relations, as corresponding with facts of 
 Empirical Reality, is confirmed by tracing the correspondence 
 back into the Conceptual System, That the grounds of our 
 relative judgments are facts and not merely cognitions, is 
 implied in all scientific inquiries, and confirmed by every 
 verification of any hypothesis or calculation according to the 
 Physical Method. That the Demiurgus, as Plato puts it, 
 mingled the Same and the Other with the essence of the 
 World, is not a mere hypostatisation of intelligence or of the 
 principles of explanation ; it is the condition of intelligence 
 and of the World's Self-knowledge. 
 
 § 4. Terms that may be related are all things whatsoever : 
 bodies and their qualities, sensations and all subjective modes, 
 positions in time and space and all relations themselves. 
 Relations related have, of course, their own terms, express or 
 implied, which may be other relations with further terms. 
 It is not to be understood that all pairs of terms may be 
 related in all ways : a body cannot be definitely like a pleasure ; 
 a position in time cannot be sequent to a position in space : 
 but any terms that are not related in other ways are still 
 different in a common consciousness : and this common ground 
 of all comparison in consciousness is signified by the differ- 
 entiation of all sense-organs from a common origin in the cells 
 of the epithelium, and by the co-ordination of all organs of the 
 cortex. 
 
 Hume was unfortunate in describing Difference as " rather 
 a negation of relation than anything real and positive " ; 
 for certainly it is as real and positive as Likeness ; and, 
 although less fruitful in positive results, it is, as Henry Sidg- 
 wick shows {Philosophy , its Scope and Belations, Lect. I. § 3), 
 equally important to Philosophy. Spencer's view that Dif- 
 ference is primordial in consciousness, and that Likeness is at 
 first of a comparatively negative character, as the cancella- 
 tion of a Difference {Psychology, Part VI. chap, xxiv.), is in- 
 teresting ; but Metaphysics is chiefly concerned with mature 
 
ABSTKACT CATEGOEIES 271 
 
 and explicit judgmeuts in apperceptive consciousness. There 
 Likeness and Diflerence are upon the same footing : both clear, 
 each having its distinctive feeling, neither resolvable into the 
 mere absence of the otlier. 
 
 Apperceptive consciousness and tlie analysis of judgment 
 and reality into terms and relations seems to be possible only 
 by means of some sort of language or appropriate signs. It 
 is indeed an important truth that relationality is implicit in 
 perception and in all modes of organic consciousness ; but it is 
 questionable whether the highest sub-human mammalia are 
 capable of explicitly recognising it; picture -thinking (or 
 'reception') seems to limit their powers (see Lloyd Morgan's 
 Comparative Psychology, chap. xiv.). Even in the simpler 
 forms of language the apparatus of comparative thought is 
 extremely imperfect, and is eked out by gesticulation ; and the 
 growth of language is marked by nothing more emphatically 
 than by increasing power of expressing relation : whether by 
 more precisely determining the relative places of words, by 
 inflections, by specialised words (prepositions, conjunctions, 
 etc.), or by the differentiation of names for relations themselves 
 (equality, coexistence, etc.), a process continually carried further 
 in scientific terminology. 
 
 As for the names of relations, they are derived from con- 
 crete terms and point to perceptual comparison as the original 
 ground of thought. Likeness is from A.S. lie, the body ; alike 
 (A.S. ordic) indicates agreement tested by superposition. So, 
 ' it likes me ' means, it suits or fits me. Equal is ' as one ' ; 
 same, similar, resembling, simultaneous, all primarily meant 
 ' together,' hence matched ; whilst different meant ' put 
 asunder.' Comparison, in short, as the word itself suggests, 
 begins with an actual distribution or arrangement of objects ; 
 and, as we now see in a Museum, this is still necessary to exact 
 knowledge. Yet, contrary to every one's experience, it has been 
 supposed that relational words subserve the expression of pure 
 thought: so that bad Metaphysics, rather than Mythology, 
 deserves to be called a " disease of language." 
 
 The fiict is that the Categories take their rise in human 
 perception, — which is not a separate thing from human 
 
272 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 understanding, and therefore may itself be classificatory and 
 apperceptive, — in the direct attentive consciousness (at once 
 analytic and synthetic) of Empirical Reality. This is the 
 strength of Kant's position, that the Categories constitute 
 Nature, for there they must be sought and justified. But 
 Kant treats them as primarily forms of pure understanding ; 
 and so can never bring them home to the experience of the 
 individual, except by the vicarious Imagination. 
 
 To attempt to systematise the Categories by abstract 
 reason has the worst character of Scholasticism. It assumes 
 the possibility of a purely deductive method, but there is no 
 such thing as abstract deduction ; every logical process arises 
 out of unfathomable depths of experience. In this sense 
 Empiricism is re-established. The term ' Empiricism,' indeed, 
 is now sometimes used as if it stood for a doctrine of the 
 complete passivity of the Subject in experience. But this 
 makes it meaningless ; for such was not the position of Locke 
 or Mill, and cannot be the position of any physiologist. If 
 ' Empiricism ' is thus employed by those who are essentially 
 Empiricists but wish to avoid classification, I sympathise 
 with any one who dislikes being labelled. The name of a 
 School is usually a nickname for each of its members. But 
 I do not sympathise with the avoidance of a nickname by 
 any one who does not repudiate it also for his allies. Let 
 every man take what name he pleases without prejudice to 
 others ; or let him, if he likes, like a savage, conceal his true 
 name to avoid cursing and incantation. 
 
 To look for the Categories in Empirical Reality saves us 
 from the absurdity of presuming that the system of them 
 (that is, of the World) already exists finished and round for 
 human reason. We must often ask not merely how the 
 Categories are thought but how they ought to be ; since 
 many scientific controversies are concerned with definitions — 
 as of ' force,' 'cause,' 'species,' — and such controversies can never 
 be ended except in full view of the perceptual World ; which 
 to explain is the test of the conceptual system. 
 
 The appeal to experience also saves us from the whim of 
 attempting a linear deduction or any formal scheme of the 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 273 
 
 Categories. Not only in psychological history but also iu 
 logical dependence, the Categories branch out in all directions, 
 like a family tree, from common roots. No doubt it would 
 be a relief to arrange them in a square, like the elements ; or 
 iu a circle, like the serpent, tail in mouth. Dichotomy seems 
 to save tlie labour of learning anything ; triads lend a colour 
 of romance to pure reason. But the expectation of greater 
 symmetry than exists in Nature, is justly classed by Bacon 
 amongst the Idols of the Tribe. 
 
 § 5. If the category of Relation is clear, it cannot be by 
 force of definition ; for, of course, the ultimate form of all 
 cognition cannot be itself defined. And the same is true of 
 Likeness and Difference, and even of their specific modes in 
 simple judgments of Time, Quality and Quantity. They are 
 abstract intuitions, analytic growths (according to the universal 
 process of abstraction) from the experience in which they are 
 implicit, and where they are now perceived by their own 
 assimilative power. 
 
 According to speculative Psychology, the beginning of 
 organic consciousness is a change of consciousness ; and this 
 implies (a) a Succession of states, which in the course of 
 mental development becomes known as a Difference and 
 Succession in Time ; and (b) a difference of states, which 
 becomes known as a Difference of Quality or of Quantity. 
 In adult consciousness every experience either involves a 
 change, and therefore Succession and Difference ; or, if 
 Difference be instantaneously apprehended, it is by an organ 
 which has been developed and trained to interpret simultaneous 
 experience as equivalent to that which originally could only 
 be learnt in succession. And differences are still most clearly 
 apprehended when experienced in immediate succession. In 
 such experience therefore, whether the Difference or the 
 Succession is attended to, depends upon the direction of our 
 interest. Whether the difference is of Quality or Quantity, 
 is an ultimate contrast of experience : Quality has not here 
 the sense of ' reference to a Substance,' but is a certain aspect 
 of terms that may vary in certain ways, in contrast with 
 another aspect of these terms (or others) that vary in the 
 
 18 
 
274 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 characteristic way of Quantity, that is, more or less. There 
 is no defining power in these sentences : all the expressions 
 imply one another. 
 
 Relations of Time are : — 
 
 (1) Succession, or Difference of Time. 
 
 (2) Contiguity, or immediate Succession. 
 
 (3) Interval, where succession is not immediate and we 
 
 are interested in the terminal changes. 
 
 (4) Duration, where we are interested in the experience 
 
 that fills the interval. 
 
 (5) Simultaneity, or Likeness in Time ; a relation applic- 
 
 able only to events, not implying place or more 
 than instantaneous duration, 
 
 (6) Co-existence, or Likeness in Time, predicated of bodies, 
 
 qualities, or positions in space, and compatible 
 with unequal duration of the terms. 
 
 (7) Coinhereuce, a relation especially of the qualities of 
 
 a body, generally implying coexistence, but not 
 necessarily. 
 Relations of Quality are indicated by several names whose 
 precise reference has never been determined. Even Likeness 
 is ambiguous ; but I cannot enter here upon a long psycho- 
 logical discussion. Whoever would examine the matter should 
 turn to E. B. Titchener's Instructor's Manual of Ex'p. Psych. 
 § 14, and the references there given. 
 
 (1) Likeness and Difference are the most general ex- 
 
 pressions of qualitative comparison. 
 
 (2) Sameness is the relation of terms that in respect 
 
 of Quality are indistinguishable ; whether (a) the 
 successive moments of a continuous simple experience 
 (a red light), or (h) experiences separate in time 
 or place (two red lights) ; or (c) groups of the 
 same qualities related in the same ways. ' Identity ' 
 is sometimes used in all these senses, but should 
 (I think) be reserved for the persistence of concrete 
 things. 
 
 (3) Similarity is compatible with some Difference, and 
 
 seems to imply a less Difference than some other. 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 275 
 
 If any Quality is perceived to undergo a slow 
 change, it presents at tirst a slight Difference, 
 but still a Similarity, until at last a state is 
 reached which presents a decided Difference, We 
 have no appropriate names for the distinguishable 
 places in such a series ; it presents degrees of 
 Similarity and DifiFerence until we reach a 
 
 (4) Contrast, or a striking Difference upon a common 
 
 ground of Similarity. 
 
 (5) Resemblance seems to mean a relation of concrete 
 
 things, the same or similar in some qualities, 
 
 differing in others, when our interest in the Likeness 
 
 preponderates. 
 
 If this seems to be the road to pedantry, I shall probably 
 
 atone for venturing upon it by not observing such distinctions 
 
 myself ; but fallacies arise from neglecting them ; thought 
 
 cannot be clear if language is indiscriminate. 
 
 Quality of sensation (say, heat) remaining the same, its 
 Quantity may change, grow more or less intensive or extensive : 
 this is Degree or Amount. Quantity of sensation remaining 
 equal, its Quality may change (say, from blue to green). As 
 to Time : Simultaneity, Interval, Duration, and Coexistent 
 Positions in Space imply also relations of Quantity, that is. 
 Equality, or More and Less. 
 
 The qualitative Likeness of Relations is called Analogy. 
 
 II. Qualitative Relations 
 
 § 6. The Categories take their rise in human perception, from 
 which they are partially released by language. In the ex- 
 perience of Reality things and their qualities coexist, or succeed 
 one another and change, and are of this or that kind ; that is 
 to say, are alike or unlike {a) in Time, (&) in Quality. Hence 
 follow two series of Concepts that have an astonishing pro- 
 minence in the history of Philosophy. From the unanalysed 
 experience of relative permanence and change issues the 
 series : — 
 
276 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Changeable Unchangeable 
 
 Becoming Enduring 
 
 Potential Actual 
 
 Possible Impossible 
 
 Contingent Necessary 
 
 From the experience that things are of various kinds, and 
 kinds of kinds, in Nature issues the series : — 
 
 Thing Nothing 
 
 Specimen Species — Genus 
 
 Event Law 
 
 Particular Universal 
 
 Matter Form 
 
 Phenomenon Substance 
 
 Having thus arranged such words, simple inspection may 
 convince us, that to treat them as of independent import is a 
 delusion. We must briefly review them. 
 
 § 7. As for Change, it has always been regarded as the 
 enemy of knowledge and felicity. But so common a concept 
 lies open to misconstruction from its indiscriminate usage. 
 That something changes, and that there is a change in some- 
 thing, may easily be taken as equivalent expressions ; but 
 they are very different. That there is a change in something 
 frequently implies that the ' something' still retains on the 
 whole its identity : that something changes implies no such 
 thing, but rather denies it. Hence ' that something changes * 
 is the more appropriate expression for describing the experience 
 {Kara irdOos:) in which one quality disappears and is succeeded 
 by another : whilst 'that there is a change in something* 
 rather suggests a process in some concrete whole, one or more 
 of whose qualities may change although, in some relevant 
 way, it may still bear the same name ; like Timon, who is 
 still the son of Echecratides though he was happy once and 
 now is grey. Neither of these meanings is self-contradictory. 
 
 However abstract the concept of Change, it is steeped in 
 sentiment. If to any one who should complain that all things 
 change, I were to reply, ' And a good job, too ! ' — he would 
 count me a ruftian. Yet what is it that is good enough to 
 last for ever ? Perhaps if Space is limited, the Infinite can 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 277 
 
 only be expressed in Time. But in unhappy ages men see 
 their native country decadent, as happened to Plato. The 
 decline of our own powers begins at last for all of us, and in 
 our memories pleasurable images fill most of the old rooms. 
 Then there is the pernicious and fatal desire of rest and ease. 
 Again, there is bereavement ; there are premonitions of death ; 
 there are affections, and labours unfulfilled, and the instinct to 
 persist in being, and egotism resenting to make room for 
 others. Few are content with the permanence of the Universe, 
 and understanding, and acquiescence, and the intellectual love 
 of God. 
 
 Indeed, does not Change frustrate understanding along 
 with our other hopes ? It has been thought so ; and the 
 Unchangeable has been proclaimed the only true object of 
 knowledge and the Reality of things — the Idea, the nunc 
 stans : whilst the apparent succession of events has been said 
 to warrant only opinion and even to be an illusion of our 
 perceptive constitution, or the parallax of our own inconstancy. 
 The Reality some one has compared to a row of pillars, which 
 seem to us to move because we are condemned to be always 
 passing by them. This hypothesis will presently recur ; but 
 if it were true, the progress of investigation ought to have led 
 to a static instead of a more and more dynamic view of 
 Nature, by which we seek in laws of change the explanation 
 of what seems even the least changeable. And it has already 
 been shown that Transcendent Reality is in Time, and that 
 nothing else can be conceived to be manifested in Empirical 
 Reality. Even the creation and sustentation of the world by 
 divine Power must be considered as an activity implying 
 change ; and one may learn from the theology of Cudworth 
 that it is not in this attribute that the Divine Being is 
 unchangeable, but in Thought. Now Thought unchangeable 
 may be manifest in unchangeable Laws ; for it is not the 
 object but the form of knowledge that is unchangeable suh 
 specie eternitatis ; it matters not whether in the thought of 
 God or man. 
 
 Becoming is a less abstract concept than Change, for it 
 more strongly implies termini a quo and ad quern, with the 
 
278 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 suggestion that such termini are at least relatively enduring ; 
 although the Enduring can only be relative, since change is, 
 in truth, all prevailing amongst the modes of Existence, and 
 all beginnings and endings are selections of interest and 
 distinctions of thought. At this height of abstraction birth 
 and death are the same thing. 
 
 As the object of knowledge is changeable, but the form of 
 knowledge is unchangeable ; so Becoming is a character of 
 experience and Keality, not of laws or concepts themselves. 
 If we add to or substract from a concept it does not become 
 another ; we merely make a fresh one, the old remaining. 
 Each concept is an identity ; and this is the logical meaning 
 of the Principle of Identity. Still a concept, though un- 
 changeable, cannot be called enduring ; for Time is irrelevant : 
 it is therefore eternal. 
 
 When we consider any process of Becoming, C to D, C is 
 called the Potentiality of D, and D the Actuality of : not 
 that either has a greater reality than the other ; for all 
 things that exist are actual ; and C is admitted to be the 
 Actuality of a foregoing B, and so on. The distinction, 
 therefore is essentially relative ; and the relativity is imperfect. 
 Not to abuse it, we must observe that B (say the seed of a 
 tree, or a cloud about to fall in rain) is not by itself the 
 Potentiality of C, but only under favourable conditions. 
 
 The truth is that the interest has gone out of these old 
 Categories of Heracleitus and Aristotle : they are vague 
 anticipations of Causation and of the processes known to 
 natural science. Motion, conversion of energy, chemistry, 
 organic metabolism ; it is these things that give definite 
 meaning to Change, Becoming, Potential and Actual ; and for 
 a logician to discuss under vague and antiquated terms the 
 truth of Nature in general, without knowing anything in 
 particular, is too comic an enterprise to be carried on much 
 longer. 
 
 § 8. Much the same may be said of the Possible and 
 Impossible, Contingent and Necessary. In fact logicians have 
 given up the attempt to treat by their own old methods the 
 Modality of Judgments, and have substituted outlines of the 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 279 
 
 Theory of Probabilities. Logically, Possible is anything that 
 18 conceivable, and any combination of attributes is conceiv- 
 able tliat is not self-contrudictory. But this only means 
 that it is possible to think of it, not that any corresponding 
 individual is possible in reality or even in imagination. Each 
 attribute of a concept is derived from perception, and there- 
 fore must comply with the forms of perceptual consciousness, 
 that is, it must be capable of entering into relations of Like- 
 ness, Difference, Succession and Coexistence with the rest of 
 experience ; but it does not follow that the combination of 
 attributes in a concept occurs or can occur in Nature : for 
 example, centaur, ghost, planetary influence, phlogiston. Every 
 new concept or hypothesis is a regrouping of elements of 
 knowledge that have severally a perceptual ground : its truth 
 depends upon whether the concept corresponds as a whole 
 with real, if hitherto unrecognised, groupings in Empirical 
 Reality. 
 
 Referred to Empirical Reality, the Possible is that which 
 agrees with the laws of Nature, and of which the causes and 
 conditions exist or are to exist ; but, in this sense, whatever 
 is possible is also Necessary. 
 
 The Impossible is, logically, the self-contradictory; and 
 this is the meaning of the Principle of Contradiction : physic- 
 ally, it is whatever does not agree with the laws of Nature, or 
 of which the causes and conditions have no existence. 
 Obviously, the Impossible-to-be is the same as the Necessary- 
 not-to-be. 
 
 Except in the formal interpretation of Conditional Propo- 
 sitions, Contingency has no specially logical significance. 
 Physically considered, whatever is possible but not yet extant, 
 is contingent upon the occurrence of its causes. But unless 
 its causes exist at some time it cannot be contingent ; whilst 
 whenever they do exist it is necessary. The character of 
 Necessity has been discussed in Chap. IV. § 4. 
 
 Thus the Categories of Possibility, Impossibility, Con- 
 tingency, Necessity, have only subjective value : things seem 
 Possible or Contingent when we do not know enough about 
 them to see that they are Impossible or Necessary. And, 
 
280 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 further, the Changeable, the Becoming, the Potential and 
 the Actual, are all Necessary as to their existence, and 
 as to the time, place and manner of existence they are 
 Unchangeable. 
 
 From this position, the notion of a nunc stans looks not 
 unattractive, for the concrete system of the World in which 
 every part is necessary becomes here more prominent than the 
 abstract Time in which everything is contingent. We must 
 remember that Time is the form of Consciousness, and that 
 Consciousness is the only known Reality. Still, objective 
 existence is not merely present existence, the tense of 
 predication : to forget this makes people afraid to die ; afraid, 
 that is, of losing hold of the pyschological Now. But, as 
 Spinoza says, there is necessarily in God an idea of each 
 human body under the form of Eternity. Whatever belongs 
 to past or future has existence or Reality, neither more nor 
 less than the present. None but the most immediate Solipsist 
 can dispute this. Whoever admits that there is any present 
 existence beyond perception, must on the same grounds admit 
 that past and future exist or are real, namely, by universal 
 integration and continuity. 
 
 § 9. The usefulness of the word Thing depends upon its 
 vagueness : to define would only spoil it. Still, we may say 
 that the notion of a Thing implies that it can be recognised, 
 and that it is somehow different from all others. Any given 
 Thing is said to exist, and the predication of this fact is called 
 an Existential Proposition or Judgment, as if it involved 
 nothing further. But everything exists in some determinate 
 part of Space and Time, which is conditioned by, and exclusive 
 of, every other part. 
 
 On the removal of any given Thing something else holds 
 its place : this experience is the ground of the Principle of 
 Excluded Middle. We cannot say in general what that 
 something will be ; but there is no such experience as 
 nonentity, the common uncritical acceptation of ' Nothing ' : 
 it is a self-contradictory concept, a supposititious offspring of 
 the negative particle. Tliere is always something or other 
 (fir) 6v = erepov). This reflection, far from being frivolous, is 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 281 
 
 80 important that it accompanies every exact investigation. 
 When in the ordinary careless life one says ' on opening the 
 cupboard there was nothing tliere ' (that is, nothing of the kind 
 required), such an expression represents a double experience : 
 (1) in the absence of the thing required, something else is 
 peitjeived — this is a Difference ; (2) there is a failure of expected 
 Likeness : the seeker had a mental phantasm of the thing 
 wanted (or, at least, a symbol of it and a preparedness to 
 recognise it), and the perceptual satisfaction of this expectation 
 is denied him. The latter experience, as the more interesting, 
 absorbs the whole attention, and is generalised in the term 
 Nothing, or non-satisfaction of any expectation whatever ; but 
 of expectations based upon definite experience there is no such 
 universal failure. 
 
 Tlie philosophers have taken up the problem of Nothing, 
 and it suits some of them perfectly ; but the best essay upon 
 it is Henry Fielding's. Kant distinguishes four kinds of 
 Nothing, according to Quantity, Quality, Relation and Modality 
 {K. d. r. V. — end of Transcendental Analytic) : 
 
 (1) There may be a conception of an object that cannot be 
 found in experience, such as noumena, or a supposed new 
 force in Nature. 
 
 But here we have a confusion of ideas, for though the 
 conception of nouraena, as such, involves no contradiction, the 
 conception of them as given in experience does : in experience, 
 therefore, they are logically impossible, and not on the same 
 foot as a supposed new force that involves no contradiction, 
 although it may be physically impossible. Such a supposed 
 but indiscoverable force is a case of disappointed expectation, 
 and one always finds something else. 
 
 (2) The conception of the absence of an object, such as 
 cold, or shadow. 
 
 But these examples are definite experiences, by no means 
 Nothing ; and, apart from examples, the conception of an 
 object that is absent is a disappointed expectation. 
 
 (3) The form of intuition without content — pure space, or 
 pure time. 
 
 But there are no such forms of intuition apart from 
 
282 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 experience. The perception of space or time involves a 
 kiniesthesis, and so does the representation of them. 
 
 (4) The object of a self-contradictory concept, such as a 
 figure bounded by two straight lines. 
 
 But the " object of a self-contradictory concept " is itself a 
 self-contradictory concept : where there is self-contradiction no 
 concept has been formed : and self-contradiction can only be 
 called Nothing in so far as the frustrated endeavour to frame 
 a concept resembles disappointed expectation in seeking an 
 object. 
 
 There are not, then, four Nothings, but one Nothing ; and 
 that is generalised from one side only of our experience of the 
 absence of things expected, namely, from the merely subjective 
 side, to the neglect of the objective and real side of that 
 experience, that something else is there. Hence the meta- 
 physical conception of Nothing is the Indefinite Other. Now 
 the Indefinite Other is always matter of experience, but the 
 noumenon never is : therefore, the noumenon is not the 
 Indefinite Other ; that is, transcendent Eeality, or Being, is 
 not Nothing. If the noumenon has often disappointed the 
 expectations of those who sought it, that was because they had 
 not noticed that whatever is discoverable must be within 
 consciousness, whilst the transcendent Real always lies beyond. 
 Their expectation of finding such Reality was not based upon 
 any foregoing experience of it ; for, on the other hand, it is 
 never Something. In short, we cannot do better than agree 
 with the Bhagavad-gita, that Brahm is neither Sat nor Asat. 
 
 All concrete things compared together have resistance 
 and extension in common. Add Space, and compare, and 
 only the common attribute of extension remains. Add plea- 
 sure, or relations of Succession, and again compare, and there 
 is no common quality or connotation, no one distinguishable 
 mode of consciousness left, but only comparison itself ; that 
 is, relation of Difference. On account of the supposed empti- 
 ness of the abstract of All Things, it has been identified 
 with the uncritical Nothing, or Nonentity, but, in fact it is 
 Consciousness itself or absolute Reality. And it is not the 
 Indefinite Other, but the discrimination of Otherness. Dividing 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 283 
 
 All Things, the Summmn Genus, by dichotomy, with auy 
 assignable fundamentum, we have Something or Other. 
 Nothing, therefore, is not on a foot with the Sumvium Genus, 
 but is a counter-class, infinite term, or remainder, relative to 
 a given Species, or Something. 
 
 It may be said, If Nothing is the Other, how can it be 
 true that ' Nothing can come of Nothing ' ? For does not each 
 thing come of another ? I suppose, in the ancient maxim, 
 the Nothing that is for ever barren, means Nonentity, a mere 
 grammatical negation. But it is still true if we understand 
 Nothing as the Indefinite Other, for no one thing has an 
 indefinite antecedent. The material World does not arise from 
 the Other in objective existence, namely, Space. Objective 
 Existence, the Phenomenon, does not spring from the Other 
 in experience, namely, the subjective processes now contrasted 
 with it ; and to experience as a whole there is no Other in 
 experience. Concerning Nothing, then, and its true inwardness, 
 may so much suffice. 
 
 § 10. That Things are alike in some ways and unlike in 
 others is the fact of Species in Nature, and the likeness and 
 unlikeness of Species is the fact of Genera ; that is to say. 
 Species have no other existence in Nature than in the resem- 
 blances of Things. A Thing, considered as exhibiting the 
 qualities of any specific resemblance, is called a Specimen, A 
 statement of the specific resemblance is a Definition of the 
 Name of any Species or of its connotation, and therefore a 
 Limitation of its denotation, that is, of the things that can be 
 considered Specimens. The thought of a Species, usually by 
 its name and, more precisely, according to the Definition, is a 
 Concept. 
 
 The Concept of a Species being unchangeable, it may seem 
 a matter of course that it should be perdurably represented 
 by specimens in Nature. A brief experience seems to confirm 
 this assumption, and then there may easily arise the notion 
 of Classificatory Sciences in which all things are to be arranged 
 according to Genera and Species. Ancient Idealism, too, was 
 beset by the prejudice that since the Concept or Science is 
 unchangeable, it must have, either in or above Nature, an 
 
284 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 unchangeable object. More comprehensive experience shows, 
 however, that not only everything but every kind of thing 
 has a determinate existence in time : and that, therefore, any 
 given Species may cease to be represented by specimens in 
 that present time during which men can think and have 
 concepts. A Species, then, does not exist perdurably, and yet 
 it has a permanent existence within certain limits of time, 
 and this is the grain of truth to be found in the older doctrines. 
 
 But if a Species comes at a certain time into existence, 
 and again comes to an end, to sum up its characteristics in a 
 Definition is not an adequate Science of it ; we must also 
 know the conditions of its coming to birth and death, and 
 therefore of its having such and such characteristics. Hence 
 a scientific classification is only a preparation for Science. 
 
 The words genera and species are apt to suggest plants 
 and animals, but we are here dealing with merely logical 
 categories. Whenever anything is definable by its likeness to 
 other things, there is a species. The coming or going of any 
 such thing, or any modification of it, is an Event, and the 
 statement of the conditions under which it comes or goes is a 
 Law. As a specimen is to a Definition, so is an event to a 
 Law, and Laws have no other existence in Nature than in the 
 resemblances of events. Hence, again, though a Law, as 
 conceived, is unchangeable or eternal, yet it may be represented 
 by events in Nature only during some definite period of time. 
 Therefore, Definitions and Laws do not determine the 
 existence of anything, but only describe it : inasmuch as they 
 remain in thought unchanged, whether any facts agreeing with 
 them exist or not in present time. 
 
 As there are species and genera and still wider classes, 
 according to the more or less resemblance of specimens, so 
 Laws are of less or greater generality according to the greater 
 or less resemblance of events. The greater the generality, 
 the longer the period of time during which a Kind or Law is 
 realised in Nature. The more complex Kinds have the less 
 duration. Not only animals and plants, but all inorganic 
 integrations, even the chemical atoms, may be supposed to 
 have a beginning and a dissolution. The ancient belief in a 
 
ABSTKACT CATEGORIES 285 
 
 Great Year of the World, during which all things and all 
 kinds of things, even the gods or (in modern prose) the Laws 
 of Nature, are born and reabsorbed, has been renewed by the 
 doctrine of Evolution. All things rush down into the maw 
 of Siva ; that is to say, they are resolved into Protyle. And 
 if the existence and character of all bodies is conditional and 
 transitory, so is the realisation of all Laws that are dependent 
 upon the collocations presented by such bodies. 
 
 It is, therefore, rash to draw up a list of Categories of 
 Absolute Eeason as necessarily determining the nature of 
 the Universe. There may be some temptation to put down 
 
 (1) the conditions of Knowledge, Likeness, and Difference; 
 
 (2) the relations of Time, Space, and Number, which are 
 independent of any particular concrete existence ; (3) Protyle 
 and the Laws of whatever dynamic conditions prevail in 
 Protyle. These last Categories have not yet been definitely 
 embodied in our new mythology, though the process may have 
 been begun by our Hesiod, Ernst Haeckel, in his Riddle of the 
 Universe (cf. chaps, xii.-xiii.). If there should not be sufficient 
 ff rounds for an inductive treatment of such things, the pos- 
 sibility would remain not only that the scheme of the World 
 is never repeated, but even that such Laws as those of gravita- 
 tion or of constant proportions are only realised in the present 
 Great Year. 
 
 Generalising the correlatives. Specimen and Species, Event 
 and Law, we find the contrast of Particular and Universal. 
 A particular Thing or Event is this or that, exists here and 
 now, or there and then : determinate time and place are its 
 indicative characters. It is further constituted by qualities 
 and relations to everything else, and these qualities and 
 relations, so far as they are the ground of resemblances, 
 are Universals. Such even is its time, for at the same time 
 there are many things in different places, and such also is its 
 place, for in the same place there are many things at different 
 times; it is only by time and place together that a Particular 
 is determined, since this character is different for each. But 
 this character colours all its other qualities and relations, 
 making them all grounds of difference as well as of resemblance : 
 
286 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 for example, the whiteness of two shillings may be the same, 
 but is not identical. We cannot conceive how it should be 
 so, but we perceive it plainly enough : it belongs to the 
 Empirical Reality of things. 
 
 Since the qualities and relations of every Particular are 
 infinite, it cannot be logically defined; since its localisation 
 is relative to points of measurement, which again are relative 
 to others ad infinitum (such is our present knowledge or 
 ignorance) it cannot be mathematically defined ; and since 
 every quality and relation of it carries a difference as well as 
 a resemblance, it cannot be fully understood according to laws. 
 Hence there can be no science of Particulars as such, but only 
 so far as their essence can be expressed by the universality 
 of their qualities and relations ; for differences apart from 
 resemblances do not constitute knowledge nor Nature. 
 
 Such reflections have sometimes led metaphysicians to 
 disparage the Particular as unreal, because it has not the 
 character of an Universal, which is definite and unchangeable: 
 forgetting that neither has the Universal the characters of 
 the Particular, which is original, infinite and inexpugnable. 
 Other metaphysicians, remembering these things, are for 
 disparaging Universals as mere abstractions ; forgetting that 
 human perception involves Universals, and that every valid 
 Universal is an apprehension of experience. Every abstract 
 principle is as truly a statement of matter-of-fact as the most 
 detailed description of a battle or a beetle. Perhaps an 
 education chiefly literary lays a man open to opposite errors: 
 familiarity with abstractions may lead one to exaggerate their 
 independent value; want of familiarity with the exact pro- 
 cesses by which abstractions are elicited from experience may 
 lead one, in a different mood, to treat them as empty formulae, 
 that possibly, or even probably, are at war with the facts. 
 
 § 11. Any Particular may be considered {a) as of such a 
 Kind, by a selection of certain resemblances which it bears to 
 certain others ; or (2) so far as it resembles things of many 
 or all Kinds. In the former case, the Kind to which it is 
 assigned is called its Form ; in the latter case, that by which 
 it belongs to no one class rather than to another, is called its 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 287 
 
 Matter. Taking Form and Matter as correlatives, what is 
 Matter in relation to one thing (pig-iron to knife-blades) may- 
 be Form in relation to another (pig-iron to iron), as in the 
 logical subalternation of genus and species. Taking Matter 
 as opposed to Form and an utter privation of every character, 
 we have the Indeterminate. Taking the doctrine of Form 
 and Matter in connection with some vague notion of the 
 development of Nature, we may identify the Indeterminate 
 with Protyle, out of which all Forms ultimately emerge ; but 
 in the more definite modern hypothesis of development Protyle 
 is not exactly the Indeterminate, however hard to determine. 
 
 Every Form is an universal, and Matter is also an 
 universal, whether something less determinate in relation to a 
 given Form, or in relation to all Forms quite indeterminate. 
 Matter is regarded as distributed in space, as divisible and 
 as " informed " in multitudinous ways to constitute Particulars. 
 But the Indeterminate cannot be distributed, nor divided, nor 
 informed, and no combination of universals. Form and Matter, 
 can produce a Particular ; for, as we have seen, the Particular 
 cannot be generated by conception, it belongs to Empirical 
 Reality and can only be perceived. Form and Matter are 
 ways of considering Particulars, they are abstractions not 
 elements. 
 
 Materialism considers the Forms of Nature as chanfrino' 
 the Matter as persistent, because Materialism, like Empiricism, 
 starts from perception, in which alone the change of Forms is 
 manifest. It resorts to the notion of Matter as the common 
 ground of Forms, but goes astray from the path of experience 
 by forgetting that Matter is not something independent of 
 perception. Matter, in fact, is a methodological Category : it 
 is for the physical sciences to decide how it may best be 
 defined, as a means of understanding phenomena. 
 
 Idealism considers the Forms as eternal, and Matter as 
 something relatively unreal, incessantly changing as it passes 
 through the Forms ; because Idealism starts from thought 
 and the forms of thought are universal and unchanging. But 
 since Forms are manifestly transient in experience, they have 
 to be regarded as, in their true nature, transcendent Realities ; 
 
288 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 either per se, which is Absolute Idealism (Plato in the 
 BepuUic) ; or in the Divine Mind, which is transcendent 
 Subjective Idealism (Cudworth). But neither of these doctrines 
 casts the faintest light upon the problems of human knowledge 
 and empirical existence. For, however such Ideas exist, we 
 cannot directly know them, having no power of transcendent 
 intuition but only powers of analysis and induction, according 
 to the measure of our feeble race. If they stood before us we 
 could only know them by comparison; in our tables of instances 
 they must be entered with the rest ; for the weakness of 
 knowledge, whatever it is, lies in us not in the facts : and, 
 therefore, an Idea of truth unrealised would still appear to 
 mock us. And as to Existence, Ideas cannot be the causes of 
 phenomena, because they lie out of the order of causation, and 
 their unchangeableness is repugnant to causation. Even the 
 creative activity assumed by transcendent Subjectivism, belongs 
 not to the Ideas but to the divine Power ; and if we carry 
 the category of causation into the noumenal world even the 
 divine Will becomes subject to it. Of course. Ideas of Laws 
 have no more energy than Ideas of Species. And they can 
 no more be the essence than the causes of phenomena, for how 
 can the essence of things exist in separation from them ? Or 
 if the doctrine be adopted that Forms are not transcendent (a 
 mere reduplication of existence) but immanent in phenomena, 
 each universal identical in all its manifestations, there is the 
 difficulty that in different times and places there cannot exist 
 an Universal numerically one, but only the same according to 
 the definition such as analysis may give ; and to dispute this 
 is to deny the reality of Time and Space, and then the Forms 
 become again transcendent. But we have seen that experience 
 is real. Finally, since Forms cannot explain the failures and 
 shortcomings of Nature, or the accidents of things, these are 
 attributed either to Matter, and then that shapeless shadow is 
 endowed with quality and energy ; or else to Necessity or to 
 Ahriman, and this leads to Fatalism, Manicheism, and Devil- 
 worship. 
 
 Nevertheless, one Idea is indispensable to speculative 
 philosophy, namely, transcendent Substance or Being. And it 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIt^J 289 
 
 hfis, I am sorry to say, all the characteristics of a genuine 
 Idea : we cannot adequately know it, it is never found in 
 experience, and is of no definite use in explaining either 
 knowledge or existence ; neither practical life nor special 
 science feels the need of it. Even in the philosopher's vision 
 it is a blind spot only discovered when he searches for it, yet 
 it is irresistibly suggested by all lines of metaphysical 
 reflection. 
 
 Most of these objections to Idealism were urged by Plato 
 himself in the Parmenidcs, at the height of his impassioned 
 curiosity, before relapsing into his later dogmatism. But how 
 is it possible to wish him to have abandoned it, or to have 
 thouglit otherwise than he did, if we have any sense of 
 sublimity in the retrospect of Philosophy, or of necessity in 
 the development of thought ? His conception of Reality as 
 static could only be overcome by calling in a personal agency. 
 The nature of concepts and his admiration for Arithmetic and 
 Greometry were opposed to any coherent theory of change ; for 
 Number and Space seem the most everlasting of all things 
 conceivable, and may well be undisturbed by the systole and 
 diastole of the Great Year. Aristotle's notions of the process 
 of phenomena were embarrassed by his doctrine of Causes. 
 The Stoics and Epicureans had better views of Causation, and 
 some specialists, like Hipparchus and Archimedes, made 
 memorable investigations ; but the vitality of classic civilisa- 
 tion declined before inductive method became fruitful. The 
 modern sciences resumed the conceptions of the Stoics and 
 Epicureans with two great advantages : improved powers of 
 mathematical analysis, and greater energy of the inductive 
 disposition. The activity of this disposition in antiquity 
 unfortunately coincided with the decline of Greek national 
 life, in modern times most fortunately with the early maturing 
 of the European nations ; for there is a sympathy between the 
 achievements of men, and their enterprises wax and wane 
 together. 
 
 Every Particular Thing is a Phenomenon and, as such, by 
 correlativity implies Substance. Consciousness is also usually 
 held to need a Substance ; but if, as we say, consciousness is 
 
 19 
 
290 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 immediate Reality, to consider it as dependent on Substance 
 is contradictory. Substance, then, is an objective category 
 correlative with Phenomenon. But we have seen that, on 
 analysing the Phenomenon, nothing can be tbmid but a group 
 of qualities, themselves phenomena, cohering in one place, per- 
 durable and moving as a totality. In view of this fact there 
 are three ways of treating the category of Substance: (1) to 
 reject it as illusory. But whoever does this should be careful 
 how he speaks of phenomena, for his words may seem coherent 
 by force of the implied concept of Substance, although his 
 repudiation of that concept has rendered his argument logically 
 empty. (2) To recognise Substance as a transcendent category, 
 inadequate, one-sided and orectic, signifying or indicating that 
 Reality which is not immediately expressed in consciousness, 
 but mediately by phenomena. In this use the term Substance 
 might well, perhaps, be replaced by Being. (3) To regard 
 Substance as a category necessary to the understanding of 
 phenomena, whether it be (as Kant says) a priori, or the result 
 of reflection upon experience, but merely methodological. It 
 is then hardly distinguishable from Matter ; it is the formal 
 way of considering Matter, and its precise definition must be 
 left to the physical sciences ; though we may be confident that 
 the Primary Qualities will be the core of the definition, 
 because these constitute the measurable aspect of Nature and 
 the ground of the conceptual system. 
 
 III. Quantitative Relations 
 
 § 12. As to Relations of Quantity, or Ratios, exact like- 
 ness is Equality ; difference is Greater or Less, according to 
 the order of terms in the act of comparison. A ratio of ratios 
 is called Proportion. Inasmuch as, in certain cases, exact like- 
 ness of Quantity is unattainable, things may be called equal 
 when there is less tlian any assignable difference between 
 them, or when one may be substituted for the other without 
 affecting the result. 
 
 The judgment of Equality has, for scientific purposes, the 
 following advantages : ( 1 ) It is more definite than qualitative 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGOPJES 291 
 
 Likeness, because of the two-fold contrariety — neither Greater 
 nor I^ss ; whereas Likeness of quality has only the contra- 
 dictory, Unlikeness. To give " neither Greater nor Less " as 
 a definition of Equality would be, in strict logic, a tautology 
 of relative terms : but though this is formally true, it is not 
 true for intuition, which is kept straight (as it were) by warn- 
 ings on either hand. Hence Likeness admits of degrees, but 
 Equality does not. Simultaneity, it is true, has also the double 
 contrariety of Before and After ; but whenever there is a 
 question not merely of instantaneous judgment but of 
 methodical determination, Simultaneity must be deduced from 
 measurements. The clear appreciation of Before, Simultaneous, 
 After, introduces the conception of a Series or order in Time, 
 the positions in which are relative to a given point from which 
 they are measured, and from which their distances are Less, 
 Equal or Greater. Finally, the judgments Greater or Less 
 when made definite (how much) require a common measure 
 and, therefore, judgments of Equality. 
 
 (2) The relation of Equality is simply convertible without 
 change of expression or risk of error : if A = B, B = A. This 
 is also true of Likeness : if A is like B, B is like A, But with 
 ' A > B .*. B < A,' the expression changes; and with *A is 
 simultaneous with B, therefore B is simultaneous with A,' 
 tliough the expression is the same, there is risk of error unless 
 we know that both events are either instantaneous or altogether 
 isochronous ; and this requires another judgment of Equality. 
 
 (3) The Relation of Equality may be repeated in judgment 
 any number of times without loss or change of significance. 
 Hence it is the chief means of mediate comparison, and gives 
 such immense range to the Mathematics. Qualitative Likeness, 
 being vaguer and admitting degrees, cannot be so transferred 
 without loss of confidence. 
 
 (4) The Relation of Equality admits of the most precise 
 application to things and events by the arts of measurement : 
 whereby the use of Mathematics in the Physical Sciences 
 becomes possible. 
 
 For these reasons, and because (as we have seen) Likeness 
 is the ground of Explanation, Equality, as the most exact 
 
292 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 Likeness, is the supreme category of Understanding. There- 
 fore, we seek to reduce Causation to equations, and to find the 
 explanation of Nature in those Primary Qualities that are 
 measurable and to which Causation is referred. 
 
 In subjective experience the modes of Quantity are Degree, 
 Duration and Amount (volume or extensity). But in the same 
 objective circumstances different Subjects appreciate differently 
 these modes of experience ; and there is no direct means of 
 comparing their judgments ; nor even those of the same Sub- 
 ject at different times with any certainty or exactness. We 
 therefore agree to recognise some grounds of comparison as if 
 they were the same for all Subjects, and for each Subject at 
 all times ; and we naturally adopt as such grounds the forms 
 of experience whose development precedes the consciousness of 
 subjectivity, namely, the space -relations of bodies and the 
 movements of bodies in space. Although the agreement of 
 subjective estimates with objective measures is relative and 
 approximate in each case, yet the accumulation of experience 
 in which differences are neutralised, has produced the disposi- 
 tion to accept such physical standards as thermometers and 
 balances. For example, that weights are equal when, being 
 equidistant from a common fulcrum, they hang evenly, is a 
 theorem accepted by every one as soon as proposed, because our 
 own bodies, being approximately symmetrical, are pairs of scales. 
 Standards and apparatus having been fixed upon and elaborated, 
 we are able to follow and estimate the forces of Nature far 
 beyond the lower and higher limits at which they can excite 
 recognisable sensations or sensation -differences in ourselves ; 
 and our instinctive confidence in such methods is confirmed 
 by the agreement of the results of calculation and verification. 
 
 § 13. Space -relations between bodies are Distances and 
 Directions measured by Lines and Angles. Lines and Angles 
 are given in perception ; but not mathematical lines, nor 
 therefore true angles formed by the meeting of lines that do 
 not coincide. Sigwart, indeed, says that the straight line is 
 the line of sight in depth, the line in which we originally 
 projected objects from ourselves {Logic, § 67). But even in 
 Berkeley's time it was admitted that the line of sight iu 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 1293 
 
 depth, being end-wise to the eye, cannot be seen at all ; and, 
 if it were seen, it need not be straight, since that depends 
 upon the medium. Or if the true line of sight is not 
 exactly end -wise to the eye, because it starts from between 
 the eyes, no other line is more diificult to see than this one. 
 As for the original projection of objects, it happened a long 
 time ago, some millions of years before the birth of Man ; 
 which I can hardly remember. An adequate experiential basis 
 of abstract science is, however, found in the lines approximately 
 straight that are seen in other directions by retinal sensation 
 interpreted by movement. Whether space-relations can be 
 known by retinal stimulus alone is disputed ; but, surely, no 
 peripherally initiated sensation without muscular reaction exists; 
 and if it did exist, it would be isolated and could give no aid 
 to judgment. The movements of the eye and hand yield a 
 perception of straightness ; and of the whole body, not in the 
 line of sight, but in the line from our feet to an object. It 
 is not ease of movement or economy of effort that determines 
 the matter ; for, from the structure of our organs, many motions 
 in a curve cost least effort : it is the importance of straight move- 
 ments to the activities of life, as in chasing and striking, that has 
 produced an instinctive judgment of straightness, and a quick 
 sense of all deviations from apparent straightness, as in dodging 
 round a tree. And, surely, it is far from true that, in Nature, 
 lines straight enough to give rise to a generic idea of straight- 
 ness, are rare. Innumerable pines and palms present them, 
 every stalk of grass or bamboo from knot to knot, the sea and 
 sky-line ; and the edges of split rock must have been familiar 
 to the troglodyte. Moreover, ages ago men learned to make 
 things straight — spears and arrows — of necessity, because they 
 fly best. 
 
 Approximately straight lines being perceived, the forma- 
 tion of the concept by abstraction is simple : to doubt this is 
 greatly to imderrate the power of abstraction. Similarly, 
 curves and angles are known by the sweep of the arm and by 
 pointing here and there ; besides what may be witnessed in 
 the flight of birds and missiles, in the stoop of trees, the set 
 of boughs to their trunk, of leaves to their stalk. The right 
 
294 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 angle is that at which most trees, and men themselves, stand 
 to the ground : it has the emphasis of equilibrium. It may- 
 be suspected that points were originally fangs and thorns. 
 Generic ideas of all these things were formed by unsophisticated 
 man, and named, and used in dealing with his world. To 
 Science remained the exact definition of the concepts ; the 
 discovery of methods for measuring angles by the division of 
 the circle, and for determining position by relation to points 
 assumed ; and processes of ratiocination by which properties 
 of figures not directly apprehensible are disclosed and 
 demonstrated. 
 
 Kant's error has already been referred to (Chap. IX. § 3), 
 namely, that Geometry is a science of the immediate intuition 
 of Space ; which leads him to contend that Space is pure form 
 of perception and not a concept. Space is certainly a percept, 
 but we never perceive pure space : our perception of space is 
 full of details, which differ from moment to moment ; so that 
 for us, intent upon what is essential, the differences cancelling, 
 a concept also forms itself; and without this there could be 
 no science. Geometry was at first a collection of devices for 
 measuring bodies and the relations between bodies ; but in 
 acquiring its scientific character it began to deal not with 
 particular space-relations but with the concepts of them. 
 Now such concepts are eternal and unchangeable, and therefore 
 all that is demonstrated concerning them is universal and 
 necessary. Geometry, then, is Abstract Science in the sense 
 that it is abstracted from the facts ; and, therefore, it is true 
 of the facts and verifiable, so far as percepts approximate to 
 their concepts. 
 
 Abstract Geometry, as the truth of experience, presupposes 
 the Uniformity of Space : its concepts, abstracted from a 
 narrow and coarse perceptual knowledge of the World, are 
 assumed to hold good of the remotest regions and of the most 
 minute and obscure recesses : their verifiability, then, can 
 hardly ever be placed beyond cavil ; though the incessant 
 accumulation of wide and complex deductions, involving 
 geometrical principles, gradually overcomes the doubts of all, 
 except a few ingenious and suspicious minds. On the one 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 295 
 
 hand, it may be said that Geometry is to be trusted as the 
 truth of experience, unless facts are found in contradiction 
 with it : meaning by facts such experiences as are accepted 
 by trained investigators, not silly ghost -stories such as, in 
 the modern recrudescence of superstition, we sometimes hear 
 alleged as only explicable on the hypothesis of a " fourth 
 dimension." At present no irreconcilable facts are known. 
 But, on the other hand, it may be urged that Geometry can 
 never be regarded as true and adequate as long as any region 
 of Empirical Reality remains unexplored ; and, remembering 
 that Space is a phenomenon constructed in experience, this 
 distrust of our conceptual Space must mean, that there may 
 be some conditions of Being of which Space is the phenomenon, 
 which are not represented in our perceptual construction, but 
 might in certain regions or conditions disturb our experience. 
 The Uniformity of Space implies that a straight line does not 
 alter its length or lose its straightness, to whatever part of 
 the universe it may be transferred ; that, supposing it 
 presented in some physically unchangeable body, it could be 
 used as a measure of all spaces. If any one disputes this, 
 there is no reply. Sigwart says he cannot conceive that, if 
 objects shrank when moved, we should not discover it by our 
 memory-images (upon which he thinks comparison depends) ; 
 that is, it is more conceivable that bodies in common Space 
 should change in magnitude than that the shallow traces of 
 our personal experience should vary ! He does not seem to be 
 jesting ; but this sort of argument comes of yielding to the 
 prevalent whim that any bare suggestion of nonsense imposes 
 an obligation to refute it. 
 
 The simplest perception of Time comprises a Duration in 
 which Future, Present and Past are all present : although this 
 seems a paradox, because we are in the habit of substituting 
 the conceptual instantaneous Present for our present experience. 
 The contents of such experience incessantly change ; and, 
 abstracting from the variable contents, we conceive of a 
 Duration that may be represented by a straight line ; though 
 nothing can be less like a line than our actual experience of 
 Time. Then, to this line all the determinations of one 
 
2 96 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 dimension of Space become applicable. Any point within it 
 being taken, the opposite directions from this point repre- 
 sent Future and Past, which may be measured by any unit ; 
 and then durations may be compared. Equidistant events in 
 the same direction are conceived as simultaneous ; if not 
 equidistant, the interval of their succession may be computed, 
 and so on. 
 
 To these abstractions, there correspond in experience the 
 perception and imagination of an indefinite duration of the 
 World-process, with its past, present and future diversified, 
 though uninterrupted, by countless events of all degrees of 
 interest, and more exactly marked by rhythms subjective and 
 objective. These rhythms are periodic movements, which may 
 be traced or conjectured throughout Nature, from vast revolu- 
 tions of remote celestial bodies to the undulations of ether 
 that are conceived as necessary to explain our perceptions of 
 the physical forces. From amongst such rhythms one must 
 be selected as the standard of duration ; whether the rotation 
 or the revolution of the Earth be taken, or some physical 
 standard from the region of molecular or etherial vibrations 
 shall be deemed more constant. The verification of the 
 standard (that is, the determining of its constancy) depends on 
 a comparison of observations or experiments with computations. 
 Observation and experiment involve reliance on subjective 
 testimony, and, as this is variable, problems arise in the 
 elimination of error. The best method for the elimination of 
 error is that which gives the most consistent results ; that is 
 to say, we refer again to objective measurements, and regard 
 the greatest agreement amongst these as the test of our 
 standard of Time, when freed as much as possible from the 
 influence of subjective rhythms and the idiosyncracies of self- 
 consciousness. We take for granted an uniformity of the 
 objective world into which we were born and which had laid 
 down the conditions of our conscious lives before we were 
 conscious of ourselves. So from the first it cannot be sup- 
 posed that the adoption of a standard (say, the day or 
 month) was made upon a subjective estimate of Time elapsing, 
 — a series of ideas, equal sums of which the standard was felt 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 297 
 
 to comprise and, therefore, to measure : it must have been 
 instinctive. 
 
 Time, then, is measured by the Motion of a Body, that is 
 assumed and computed to occupy a constant duration in tra- 
 versing a certain Space ; and some unit of Time being taken, 
 whether the standard or some multiple or division of it, all 
 other Motions are measurable by that imit. Thus velocity is 
 determined by the Space traversed in an unit of Time. 
 Berkeley tried to prove the impossibility of framing an abstract 
 idea of Motion without a moving Body ; and using ' idea,' as 
 he did, to mean ' image,' it is impossible ; for no such thing 
 can be perceived, nor therefore imagined. But there is no 
 difficulty in conceiving it ; for abstracting from all differences 
 (qualitative and quantitative) of moving bodies, there remains 
 a point moving in a line. And this concept is convenient in 
 computing the motions of masses by their centres of gravity, 
 and of atoms : being nearer to a representation of the truth of 
 atoms than any concrete image can be. 
 
 § 14. Measurement of Continuous Quantities, such as 
 Space, Time, Motion, supposes the recognition of a Unit, and 
 of laws of the addition, subtraction, etc., of units ; that is, of 
 Number. But it cannot be imagined that the laws of Number 
 were originally discovered by the analysis of Continuous 
 Quantity. Pure intuition comprises no data for any sort of 
 science, and Time and Space, being continuous even in percep- 
 tion, though diversified in their contents, and being purified in 
 conception from all diversity, do not, as such modes of 
 Quantity, offer the data for perceiving Plurality and learning 
 to count it. And in fact the history of this great acquisition 
 of culture is pretty well known. The Plurality of mere diversity 
 is given in every act of perception. The Indefinite Plurality of 
 things of a kind is also given, and is recognisable by the 
 higher animals. Deer in a herd, eggs in the nest, children in 
 the family, warriors in the tribe, articles of barter, are felt as 
 ' more or less ' before they are known as ' so many ' ; and to 
 analyse the Plurality of things of a kind is the problem of 
 learning that art of counting of which all arithmetical pro- 
 cesses are only abbreviations. The instinctive solution of the 
 
298 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 problem seems to have consisted in the taking of one standard 
 group, the best known, — that is, the fingers of the hand, each 
 of which generally has its distinctive name, and then comparing 
 all other groups of things with this standard as a common 
 measure of plurality. To compare five warriors, with the 
 thumb, forefinger, middle finger, stiff finger, and little finger 
 is the primitive equation. If there are more to be reckoned, 
 the other hand, or even the toes may be appealed to. This 
 detailed comparison unit by unit is often used in primitive 
 barter (say, one stick of tobacco for one glass bead); the 
 children and even the adults of modern Europe may still be 
 seen counting on their fingers ; and our semi-civilised world 
 has settled down by force of habit to the decimal system in 
 spite of its imperfections. 
 
 Still, comparison in detail with a standard group is not 
 true counting ; it is only a perceptual equation. True counting 
 requires : (a) abstraction, from all the differences of individuals, 
 except their distinctness as objects in a series ; (6) the recog- 
 nition that all arrangements of the series are indifferent ; (c) 
 the consequent freeing of the names of numbers from all con- 
 nection with particular objects or arrangements. Numbers 
 can then be analysed and defined and their relations compared 
 as abstract science ; and they can be applied conventionally or 
 arbitrarily to any objects, groups of objects or ideas, qualities 
 or relations, or to hypothetical divisions of continuous 
 quantities — Space, Time, Motion; always subject to the 
 condition that the predications made or conclusions drawn in 
 terms of number do not assert or imply anything as to the 
 qualitative character of the things counted, nor anything as to 
 their quantitative character except the numerical. Whether 
 the things counted are qualitatively alike, or whether the 
 continuous quantity has been evenly divided (say, into inches), 
 is a distinct consideration : the likeness or equality of things 
 counted implies not merely a numerical unit but a Unit- 
 measure. 
 
 In counting we attend to the things counted ; and the 
 abstract character of Numbers has led to the hypothesis that it 
 is the common facts of all counting — acts of Attention — that 
 
ABSTRACT CATE(a)IUES 299 
 
 are the basis of Number. But to attend to acts of Attention 
 is the most difficult exercise of introspection, and nobody 
 dreamt of it when Arithmetic was formulated. 
 
 Nevertheless, in counting it is always assumed that the 
 things counted belong to some group, or come under some 
 general denomination or siip-positio, though they may differ 
 widely in both (juality and quantity : a traveller may count 
 the ' items ' of his luggage, or the contents of any parcel ; a 
 farmer may count a flock of sheep, or the number of pounds 
 that one sheep weighs ; a chemist may count the elements, or 
 the qualities it is convenient to recognise in defining a given 
 element. Thus the suj)positio may be indicated by the nature 
 of the case, or by general convention, or may be quite arbitrary. 
 However determined, the swppositio is a Totality or Whole, of 
 which the items counted are numerical parts ; and any Total 
 may be treated as a Unit under a less comprehensive sup- 
 yositio. Thus all the things we usually deal with as concrete 
 units are chemical and physical Totals. 
 
 Nothing can be more obvious than these considerations, 
 yet on the neglect of them depend most of the puerile fancies 
 that have been entertained concerning the One and the Many : 
 fancies excusable enough in the beginnings of speculation, but 
 which we see persisting age after age in the writings of men 
 who invoke the name of Plato, 
 
 And wonder with a foolish face of praise. 
 
 That there should be one Idea or concept and many particulars, 
 is due to this, that when a man counts ideas he does not 
 count particulars, and that when he counts particulars he does 
 not count ideas : the suppositio is different. We might as 
 well express amazement that one strap should bind up many 
 sticks. That particulars should agree in some qualities 
 (determining the concept) and differ in others (locality, for 
 example), has nothing to do with Arithmetic, but is a physical 
 result: conditions of production being more or less similar, 
 so are the products ; but as the conditions are not exactly the 
 same, neither are the products. 
 
 That one Substance should have many Qualities can raise 
 
300 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 no surprise in any one who considers, that empirical Sub- 
 stances are metaphysical totalities and are counted under a 
 different suppositio from their qualities, which are metaphysical 
 parts. As for Substance transcendent, my advice is — not to 
 try to apply the ready reckoner in that region ; but, at least, 
 there is no contradiction in Spinoza's conception of one 
 Substance with infinite Attributes. We must, however, 
 distinguish this arithmetical consideration from the pseudo- 
 physical question how the One, if a prius, can become a 
 Many. This involves one of two fallacies : (1) either the 
 notion of Becoming or Generation, thus used for procession 
 from the Absolute, is a mere ghost of physical causation, 
 meaningless and inapprehensible — a " transcendent use of the 
 category "; or (2) it is assumed that the One must be simple, 
 confounding the suppositio ; for the One may be a meta- 
 physical totality of Attributes, or a physical totality of (say) 
 Atoms, or a numerical totality of anything. Unity has 
 nothing to do with simplicity ; the unity of Apperception, 
 for example, is in the highest degree complex. But, again, 
 the procession of the Many from the One, or self-diremption 
 of the Absolute, cannot be shown to be logically necessary on 
 the ground that One implies Many as correlative ; for the 
 One, as Idea, is not correlative with the Many as Phenomena. 
 And hence too, the vulgar objection to the doctrine of the 
 Trinity, that there cannot be One Substance and three Persons, 
 is absurd and laughable. Not that I can approve of the 
 pseudo-Athanasius's use of the number "three"; it is a 
 transcendent application of Arithmetic. 
 
 But this reminds us that the word ' One ' is often used 
 negatively, or mystically ; for when we say that God is One, 
 we are not about to count gods ; we merely repudiate Poly- 
 theism. The One of Plotinus was not a digit. Where there 
 can be no second, ' One,' numerically used, is a meaningless 
 predicate. That the Universe is one, is tautology ; that the 
 Absolute is one, is verbiage. But should we call them ' One,' 
 it would not follow that God, or tlie Universe, or the Absolute 
 is simple ; and they are very rash who maintain that whatever 
 consists of parts must perish : a shallow, empirical prejudice ! 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 301 
 
 Oiir own investigations indicate that, beginning with the 
 actual World in Self-consciousness, this implies Universal 
 Consciousness and Being ; but whether these shall be reckoned 
 One, or Two, or Three or Four, let them decide who think 
 more highly of Arithmetic than I do. 
 
 § 15. Tiie indirect measurement of Quantity (as Comte 
 defined the Mathematics) depends upon the Axioms of Mediate 
 Relation, which are reducible to two: (1) magnitudes equal 
 to the same third are equal ; and (2) if equal magnitudes be 
 added to equals, the sums are equal. Equality implies that 
 the magnitudes compared shall be of the same order (Degree, 
 or Duration, or Extension), since else they cannot be compared. 
 
 There is a resemblance between the mathematical Axioms 
 and the Dictum de omni et nullo, but much disparity in the 
 fruitfulness of these forms. For if logical comparison deals 
 with Classes, these are definitely related only within the 
 rings of Porphyry's tree, and elsewhere overlap one another 
 with endless irregularity ; and if with Causes, indefinitely 
 conceived as subject to plurality or vicariousness, no causal 
 series can be formally reversed. But in Porphyry's tree, 
 though we ascend it securely enough, the progress is always 
 brief, and we cannot descend again except by limitation at 
 every stage ; and as soon as we leave its shelter and attempt 
 to explore the neighbouring wood, on the strength of the like- 
 ness of Class A to B, B to C, C to D, from A to D becomes a 
 perilous leap, because the likeness may differ in each relation. 
 Or, again, if in general A is a cause of B, B of C, C of D, it 
 cannot be inferred that in any particular case D is the effect 
 of A, because at each step backwards there may have been 
 other causes. On the other hand, comparisons of Equality 
 admit of endless concatenation, reversal and substitution. 
 Hence the advantage of treating causal series as presenting 
 equations in the transformation of matter and energy. 
 
 The power of the Equation sometimes tempts meta- 
 physicians to imagine that they are wielding it when, in fact, 
 they have no more than the relation of Genus and Species at 
 command. Thus Schopenhauer establishes to his own satis- 
 faction the following series : The Will to live is an effort at 
 
302 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 individualisation ; individuality is limitation ; limitation is 
 exclusion ; exclusion is opposition ; opposition is strife ; strife 
 is pain ; pain is evil, therefore the Will to live is (morally) 
 evil. But only some opposition is strife, some strife pain, 
 some pain (moral) evil ; and even earlier in the series, though 
 limitation, exclusion, opposition may be abstractly correlative, 
 moral associations creep subtly in. Similarly deceptive series 
 are not uncommon in dialectic. Whilst ostensibly employing 
 abstract comparison, the meaning of terms is at every step 
 enriched, and it is not acknowledged, as it should be, that the 
 source of enrichment is experiential. No richer category was 
 ever derived from a poorer one: experience is the common 
 ground of them all. 
 
 In perception an equation may be determined more 
 exactly than any other comparison ; but as direct comparison 
 is limited by our powers of perception, so is the direct veri- 
 fication of the Axioms. The Axioms are, in the first place, 
 instinctive judgments, assumed and acted upon by men long 
 before they are formulated : not only in man but throughout 
 the animal kingdom, each creature's body is necessarily a 
 measure to it of all other things. That the comparisons of 
 active experience should be exact is not essential to the 
 practical use of the Axioms. It is enough that the nearer 
 other things are to being equal in length to a foot or a cubit, 
 the more nearly they are equal to one another : the short- 
 comings cancel, and the universal instinctive assumption 
 emerges. That if A is greater than B, and B than C, much 
 more is A greater than C, is a still commoner experience, but 
 less interesting, as its generalisation is now less fruitful. It 
 is necessary, however, to the further formation of progressive 
 quantitative series; and, therefore, cannot be derived from 
 such series. 
 
 When under definite ideas of method the Axioms are 
 formulated, the relation of Equality is conceptualised, and it is 
 thereby required that every comparison shall be not merely 
 in perception but unconditionally exact ; and in this sense 
 the Axioms can never be directly verified. But their truth is 
 known not merely by intuition but by the consensus of all 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGOKIES 303 
 
 deductions from them, and they are applicable to particular 
 experience in proportion as the relations determined in ex- 
 perience approximate to conceptual equality. 
 
 Quantitative reasoning then consists in the mediate com- 
 parison of Times, Spaces, Motions, Series, Groups, as conceived 
 and defined. When such quantities are measured in terms 
 of some unit they are expressed by Numbers. Number is 
 usually opposed, as discrete — to Time, Space and Motion, as 
 continuous. But how Number itself should be discrete I 
 cannot understand ; the predicate is only applicable to things 
 counted. In counting items in a group (say, sheep in a flock) 
 the things numbered are discrete ; in counting inches in a 
 rule, the things numbered are only discriminated. So far 
 from being opposed to a continuum. Number is essential to 
 the conception of it. A continuum is conceived as that which 
 can never be exhausted by division ; but this implies the con- 
 ception of a division infinitely continuable. That in fact the 
 process stops, has nothing to do with the conception of it. 
 Wherever it stops the result will be expressed by a finite 
 number ; but to say that if one divides for ever, an infinite 
 number will never be reached, is a rather bad bull. 
 
 The definitions of numbers are obtained by addition of units 
 up to 10 (that is, by counting), then by adding 10 to 10 or 
 part of 10 ; and arithmetical processes consist in establishing 
 equations between different ways of constituting a Number 
 according to the Definitions. The analytic process founded 
 upon the definitions has sometimes been mistaken, as 
 (apparently) by Hume (who may have followed Leibniz, 
 Monadologie, §§ 33-35), for the whole method of Mathematics ; 
 and, if there were nothing more, these sciences would consist 
 wholly of verbal or identical propositions. But, as Kant saw, 
 there is a synthesis, though he was not happy in the examples 
 he gave of it. In fact there are two synthetic processes in 
 Arithmetic: (1) the counting, upon which definitions of the 
 numbers are based; and (2) the intuition of Axioms that 
 justify the concatenation of equations. Similarly, geometrical 
 reasoning consists in establishing equations between difiierent 
 ways of constituting the same facts of distance and direction, 
 
304 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 according to the Definitions and in reliance on the Axioms. 
 As for the geometrical figure, given or constructed in percep- 
 tion or imagination, it is necessary to the analysis and helps 
 to confirm our sense of the conclusion ; but the demonstra- 
 tion is conceptual and, therefore, universal and necessary. 
 Algebraic reasoning carries out the comparison of quantities by 
 substituting symbols for the quantities themselves or their 
 relations ; and abbreviates the process of ratiocination by sub- 
 stituting signs of operations to be performed for the detailed 
 performance of them. 
 
 Negative quantities, expressed by the minus sign, may be 
 interpreted in the same way as Logical Negation. We saw in 
 § 9 that Nothing always means some Other ; and so does 
 negative quantity in Mathematics ; but whilst in Logic the 
 Other is quite indefinite, here it is always the Other of a given 
 quantity. Thus in measuring distance (say, a mile) we start 
 from some point in some one direction ; and the negative of 
 this, or minus quantity, is an equal distance measured from the 
 same point in the opposite direction. Similarly with degrees : 
 representing them upon a scale, any point in the scale may be 
 taken at convenience as zero ; and all degrees above it being 
 called positive, all below it are negative ; and if y stand for 
 any positive degree, the corresponding negative is — y. Zero, 
 of course, is not nothing, but a certain point in a scale. 
 Absolute zero of temperature is another state of matter than 
 that in which the molecular motion of physical temperature 
 exists. 
 
 It is a standing paradox that in manipulating algebraic 
 symbols, the multiplication of minus quantities into one 
 another should give a positive result : minus a multiplied by 
 minus 6 is db. But the apparent difficulty depends upon our 
 regarding the two minus expressions as independent of one 
 another : in fact, they are like clauses in a sentence, one of 
 which qualifies the other. That a degrees below zero taken 
 negatively (the reverse of below) h times, should be ab above 
 zero, is a truth corresponding with Obversion in Logic and 
 with the rules of English Grammar. 
 
 As for " irrational expressions " such as fj — a, they are 
 
ABSTRACT CATEGORIES 306 
 
 methodological devices whose justification is far from being 
 agreed upon amongst experts ; so that it is useless for a 
 layman to discuss them. Taken as they occur in a process of 
 calculation, they seem to me to stand for operations to be per- 
 formed subject to the context. Puzzles arise from assuming 
 that every expression must be good in any context ; but mathe- 
 matical symbols depend for their meaning upon what is being 
 reasoned about. De Morgan's explanation of ^ — 1 {Elements of 
 Trigonometry , chap, iv.) is the most intelligible I have ever 
 seen. 
 
 There is more promise of metaphysical interest in in- 
 commensurable quantities, but no fulfilment. According to 
 Sigwart, incommensurable magnitudes in space are " the most 
 striking proof against all empirical theories of Space ; no actual 
 measurement could convince us that it is impossible to express 
 the side of a square and its diagonal by numbers of the same 
 unit" (§ 67). I am not aware, however, that any empirical 
 theory of Space requires actual measurements. It would be 
 more plausible to urge that no rational theory of Space is 
 compatible with the discovery of incommensurables. It is a 
 discovery of fact made by discursive reasoning ; but Reason 
 is formed and guided by experience. The empirical growth 
 of Space-perception dates from the antiquity of organic life ; 
 but to urge that incommensurables are therefore due to the 
 imperfect manifestation of Being in the Phenomenon, would 
 need an extraordinary power of keeping one's countenance. 
 
 The approximate solution of such problems depends upon 
 the conception of infinitesimal quantities and a Limit. If any 
 factor of conceptual Reality cannot be exactly measured so as 
 to compare it with another, some third factor may be found 
 which can be so measured, and which differs from the first by 
 a very small quantity ; and we may suppose this difference to 
 be indefinitely reduced, until the third factor may be sub- 
 stituted for the first without assignable error. This is the 
 familiar conceptual process of fixing upon that which is common 
 to things and neglecting their differences. The difference 
 between a straight line of less than any assignable length and 
 its arc, whether in length or direction, is negligible, and a 
 
 20 
 
306 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 Limit is that stage of an operation at which differences become 
 negligible. Berkeley might have overcome his antipathy to 
 fluxions by carrying out the doctrine ofTJie Principles of Human 
 Knowledge, that general reasoning depends upon the use of 
 ideas, words, or other signs, in their representative character, 
 and he would then have avoided the irony of irony misplaced. 
 It may be doubted whether he fully grasped the significance 
 of his own reasoning in the Principles ; for in the Analyst his 
 argument turns entirely upon the confusing of conception with 
 imagination. On the ground of experience, comparison and 
 abstraction, a suflQcient account may be given of the Abstract 
 Categories ; and on no other hypothesis is it intelligible that 
 their application should be fruitful in the Physical Sciences. 
 
CHAPTER XIV 
 
 THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 
 
 § 1. Physics, in the widest and most natural sense of the 
 term, includes the whole theory of concrete existence, usually 
 distributed under the head of Mechanics, Physics (in the 
 narrower sense). Chemistry and Biology. The metaphysical 
 treatment of this universal science of Nature differs in many 
 ways from that of the special sciences. It deals only with 
 the most general notions of the subject. It may regard certain 
 concepts as still worthy of commemoration, though the special 
 sciences have discredited them. It endeavours to construe in 
 each case the whole fact of experience; whereas the special 
 sciences, limited by methodological considerations, may neglect 
 or even disparage whatever aspects of the fact cannot be 
 quantitatively valued and prepared for mathematical com- 
 putation ; and these aspects include the subjective character of 
 every fact. The metaphysician (in his proper function) seeks 
 in the special sciences their objective construction of Concepts 
 and Laws ; or, if the construction is still incomplete, he must 
 wait until it is completed : for this construction is concerned 
 with what is not ourselves ; it is essentially an inductive and 
 tentative process, and to attempt it by any other method is a 
 self-stultification. Still, whilst it is true on the whole that 
 Science, by the very fact of its progress, is its own criticism, 
 the metaphysician or any other bystander may require that 
 concepts and laws used in the interpretation of Nature shall 
 conform to the principles of explanation and consistency ; for 
 even the most exact knowledge ought to be intelligible : and 
 he must consider whether concepts are possible, or have veri- 
 
 307 
 
308 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 similitude in view of their history and alliances. If such 
 matters are neglected, there seems to be a justification of the 
 opinion that the sciences do not seek truth but are content 
 with " working hypothesis " ; an opinion which (I believe) 
 every sincere investigator repudiates. 
 
 § 2. That the progress of Science is its own criticism was 
 never better illustrated than it is at the present hour, when so 
 many beliefs are being modified or abandoned. The bystander 
 knows not where to find footing for the soles of unblest feet. 
 A short time ago he might have taken it as agreed upon that 
 the factors of concrete existence were Ether and Atoms. Now 
 the Atoms, on the one hand, are supposed to be ' knots,' ' kinks,' 
 or vortices in the Ether, produced by some process of ' pyknosis ' ; 
 the Ether, on the other hand, is said to be conceived too 
 inconsistently to explain anything, and it is even hinted that 
 by the new conceptions of Atoms the Ether may become 
 superfluous. 
 
 The theory of the atomic structure of bodies seems to 
 have been based upon their sensible comminutability. Kocks, 
 rubble, sand, powder : the series suggests an indefinite divisi- 
 bility, only checked by the reflection that division can never 
 be destruction, and that the smallest parts must have some 
 extension and mass to account for such properties in the 
 whole. Hence the antiquity of the doctrine introduced into 
 Philosophy by Democritus. And the most recent speculations 
 on the decomposition of chemical atoms into electrons, 
 similarly appeal to the experience that under certain con- 
 ditions pieces can be broken off from atoms, and that some of 
 the heaviest atoms, if not all, break down, or radiate, by their 
 own instability. Ether, according to Aristotle, was the matter 
 of the celestial regions, having the properties of permanence 
 and circular motion, in contrast with the elements of terrestrial 
 things that are perishable and move in straight lines. Never- 
 theless the notion was taken by him from folk-lore, in which 
 the ether, or upper air, was figured as something more refined 
 than that which we breathe. When the ether was adopted 
 into modern Physics it was endowed from time to time with 
 such properties as it seemed to require, as a vehicle for modes 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 309 
 
 of energy, and as a medium correcting the discontinuity of 
 the atomic structure of things. These notions, then, of Atoms 
 and Ether are entirely empirical : they do not involve the 
 deepest principle of the understanding. The Atomic Theory 
 appeals to familiar analogies in the formation of bodies, from 
 an animal organism to Silurian rocks ; whereas the continuity 
 of the Ether is without any physical analogy in familiar 
 experience. But even the Atomic Theory is on a different 
 footing from the doctrines of Conservation and of Continuity 
 in Time. Conservation and Continuity in Time cannot be 
 disputed without abandoning all possibility of explanation ; 
 but the notions of Atoms and Ether may be modified at 
 discretion, until by a series of trials the scientific mind shall 
 have reached at last the most comprehensive analysis of con- 
 crete existence. 
 
 § 3. In empirical Eeality all things in Time and Space 
 move and change, and sometimes seem to come to rest and 
 to remain unchanged. Movement, Change, Rest are plainly 
 given to our cursory perception : do they retain their reality 
 when we attempt a systematic interpretation of experience ? 
 
 Rest, although even Spinoza writes (perhaps unguardedly, 
 Eth. ii. 13) as if it were a phenomenon co-ordinate with 
 Motion, quickly disappears in the light of investigation. 
 Whilst a body may often be said to rest in relation to certain 
 other objects, it is easily shown that every body must be in 
 incessant movement both as a whole and (if composite) in the 
 configuration of its parts : the direction, velocity and com- 
 plexity of its movements baffling imagination. 
 
 Change was said by Aristotle to comprise (1) the origina- 
 tion and destruction of particular things, (2) growth and 
 decrease, (3) alteration of quality, (4) locomotion ; and he 
 showed that the last is a condition of all the others, but 
 maintained that it does not wholly account for alteration of 
 quality. The fact is that origination and destruction, growth 
 and decrease of particular things, are processes common to 
 empirical and conceptual Reality ; and in the latter region, 
 in which things exist only in their primary qualities, motion 
 is the ground of all changes : but alteration of quality in 
 
310 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 empirical Eeality includes those changes of secondary qualities 
 that depend on subjective reaction of the special senses ; and 
 this cannot be explained by motion, being the subjective 
 Eeality of that of which motion is itself the phenomenon and, 
 therefore, an ultimate experience. Qualitative Change is more 
 real than Motion, as Time is more leal than Space. 
 
 Kant said that the consciousness of Change requires the 
 contrast of something permanent in consciousness : but it is 
 enough that something more enduring be there. The 
 existential correlative of Kant's argument is that Change 
 implies some identical thing that changes ; and this seems to 
 involve a contradiction, for Identity and Change are incom- 
 patible predicates ; but the knot is at once loosened by 
 observing that Identity is predicated of different things in 
 different senses. If in space there be any simple and ultimate 
 phenomenon, its Identity excludes every sort of Change 
 except locomotion, which is not incompatible with Identity ; 
 and, strictly speaking, nothing else can be called self-identical. 
 In all generated things Identity is regarded as compatible 
 with some amount of Change, because there are limits to the 
 appreciation of Change, and in many classes of things con- 
 tinuous Identity implies a series of changes. A State or a 
 living Body is called the same, though undergoing such 
 metamorphoses as overtake a caterpillar or a constitution ; 
 without which the existence of the thing is not fulfilled 
 according to its nature. 
 
 Hume observed that Identity depends upon Causation 
 {Treatise, Book I. Part III. § 2), and this is true of all things 
 changeable, as we may see in several ways. Popularly, a 
 thing is no longer called the same so far as its effects become 
 different : a darned stocking may be the same in the economy 
 of ownership, but not in the market. Again, as to the re- 
 cognition of Identity : whereas Plurality depends upon the 
 determination of particular Things in time and place ; so 
 that different Things may at different times be in the same 
 place, and the same Tiling may at different times be in 
 different places, but not in different places at the same time ; 
 it follows that to trace the Identity of anything, we must 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 311 
 
 know what causes are capable of moving it and of substituting 
 something else that is perceptually indistinguishable from it. 
 Hence we may observe that, since Identity depends uy)on 
 Causation, Causation cannot be explained by Identity : Causal 
 Instances (even were they qualitatively and quantitatively 
 the same) are numerically different. And since Thinghood 
 involves Identity, we see that Causation, the latest concept 
 to be clarified, is necessary to the understanding of Thinghood ; 
 which, seeming primitive and simple, is in some ways arbitrary 
 and ambiguous and illusory. 
 
 But to see this still more clearly, let us consider that, as 
 Locke says, Identity implies that a Thing has only one 
 beginning (Assays of H. U. ii. 27, ^ 1); and this is obviously 
 true of all generated Totalities. Now its beginning is a 
 change or process of Causation, and its whole existence depends 
 upon the equilibrium thence resulting. That this equilibrium 
 should in certain cases be relatively permanent, because in 
 fact forces capable of overthrowing it are rare or no longer 
 active, may be admitted possible ; and in that case, in the 
 absence of adequate causes, there will be a relatively persistent 
 Identity. Nevertheless, so far as it is true that whatever 
 begins perishes, every such thing is a temporary result of 
 processes of change ; and, even granting that anything that 
 begins can be permanent, yet all its qualities are traceable to 
 the persistence of internal strains and movements implied in 
 its constitution ; nor can it be doubted that these are modified 
 by changes in its external relations. Amongst sensible 
 phenomena, then, an unchangeable thing has no existence ; 
 and, therefore, the question, ' how a Thing can change,' is 
 misleading. A Thing is a process of change ; even its tem- 
 porary persistence is due to the uniformity of changes, that 
 is, to Causation — master-concept of the concrete world. And, 
 therefore, the law of Contradiction, that A is not not-A, must, 
 in its physical application, be understood of processes : there 
 cannot be two moving bodies in the same relations of place 
 and time. 
 
 The concepts of Change and Identity, then, are not 
 impossible or contradictory, although they must be cautiously 
 
312 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 used in the interpretation of immediate experience. The 
 possibility of forming the concept of Identity depends, first, 
 upon the phenomena of relative Eest and relative persistence 
 of Quality ; secondly, upon the unchangeable nature of concepts 
 themselves. But whether Unchangeableness is a predicate 
 necessary to the ultimate interpretation of experience, remains 
 a question for physical science : is it necessary in any way, 
 qualitative or quantitative (other than Conservation), to the 
 formation of an universal Science of Nature ? If so, it is in 
 that relation verifiable ; and, because it is verifiable, its use is 
 truly immanent and not transcendent ; it applies to phenomena 
 and not directly to Being. 
 
 § 4. Heracleitus' profound intuition of the universality 
 of Change in the sensible world is still a paradox, but less 
 alarming perhaps to the public than Zeno's arguments against 
 the conceivability of Motion. The public approves of Diogenes' 
 answer, which was — to walk away : though it has been urged 
 that this was a most disgraceful blunder, since the arguments 
 were directed not against the fact but the concept of Motion. 
 According to J. Burnet, however {Early Greek Fhilosophy, chap, 
 viii.), Zeno's attack was made not so much upon the general con- 
 cept of Motion as upon the Pythagorean doctrine of Space. 
 The Pythagoreans seem to have held that Space is made up of 
 points ; and, if so, they must have admitted that any given 
 Space, being infinitely divisible, contains an infinite number 
 of points. It follows in four ways, according to Zeno, that 
 Motion is impossible. For, first, no such Space can be 
 traversed in a finite time. This, however, could present no 
 difficulty to the Pythagoreans unless they denied that Time, 
 likewise, is infinitely divisible. Now Zeno's third argument 
 was that a flying arrow is really always at rest, since at each 
 moment of time it is at some particular point of space. 
 Burnet approves of Aristotle's observation that this " depends 
 upon the assumption that Time is made up of ' Nows,' that is, 
 of indivisible instants " ; adding that " this, no doubt, was the 
 Pythagorean view." So that if the Pythagoreans were really 
 so simple as to assert infinite divisibility of Space, and deny 
 it of Time, they cut themselves off from what might seem an 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 313 
 
 easy answer to the first argument. Apart from this blunder 
 attributed to the Pythagoreans, it may be supposed that Zeno's 
 argument starts from the assumption that Motion in an 
 infinitesimal moment is not Motion but Rest ; that is to say, 
 that it merely begs the question. In any case, it is im- 
 possible to conceive of Motion unless Space and Time are 
 conceived as continua ; and that they are continua is the 
 ground of Aristotle's solution of these puzzles. Motion is a 
 traversing of Space in Time ; it cannot be completely analysed 
 into Space and Time ; something further — an ultimate ex- 
 perience — is of the essence of it : and this is some excuse for 
 Diogenes' retort. The right reply to the doctrine that Space 
 is made up of points, is that ' divisible ' and ' discrete ' are 
 very diSerent notions ; if Space, Time and Motion were not 
 divisible they could not be measurable : but if Space consisted 
 of discrete points, the impossibility of Motion would follow 
 from this, that between any two points there is no room to 
 move. 
 
 The Eleatic's fourth argument was, that if two bodies 
 move with equal velocity past one another in opposite 
 directions, they will do it in half the time that either of them 
 takes in passing a fixed body — that is, each of them has in the 
 same time different velocities. Grote thought this observation 
 designed to show that velocity is not absolute but relative ; 
 and, in that case, it is a sound argument. However, Burnet 
 approves of an explanation offered by Tannery : that it " was 
 directed against a possible answer to the preceding one, 
 namely, that in each indivisible instant the arrow is passing 
 from one point to the next. If so, answered Zeno, motion 
 must always have an equal velocity, for all instants, being 
 infinitely small, are equal." But that all infinitely small 
 instants are equal, is not necessarily true ; and if it were, to 
 assume that all motions in equal instants must traverse equal 
 spaces, is flatly to beg the question whether different velocities 
 are possible. It is just because velocities do in fact differ, 
 however small the time supposed, that it is necessary to fix 
 upon some actual motion of a body (say, a revolution of the 
 Earth) as a standard of comparison. 
 
314 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 But it is the second sophism (in the usual enumeration) 
 that has excited most amazement and scalp -scratching — the 
 famous race between Achilles and the tortoise. Should the 
 hero give the reptile a start, he can never overtake it : for 
 (granting, for argument's sake, that they can move at all) by 
 the time Achilles reaches the tortoise's starting-point, it will 
 have got beyond it a certain distance ; whilst Achilles is 
 covering that space, the tortoise will have moved on again : 
 and so forth ad infinitum. This description of the event, how- 
 ever, takes no account of the diminishing times of the several 
 distances. For suppose that, as Grote puts it in his Plato 
 (chap, ii.), whilst Achilles advances 100 yards (say in one 
 minute) the tortoise advances 1 yards ; then whilst Achilles 
 covers these 1 yards (in x^th of a minute) the tortoise covers 
 1 yard more, and Achilles walking that yard (in x^tj*^ °^ ^ 
 minute) is still xV^^ ^^ ^ yard behind the tortoise. Therefore 
 Achilles will never overtake the tortoise in the times supposed, 
 as I have supplied them (or t-f- j-\j^-f xo(y, etc.). But this 
 implies that the race is not to last very long ; for if it only 
 lasts one and one-fifth minute, Achilles will be nearly 9 yards 
 ahead (cf. Mill, On Hamilton, chap. xxiv.). So much in dis- 
 charge of the duty, imposed upon every writer on Metaphysics, 
 to offer some reflections upon the father of Dialectic : it was 
 not left to him to make men puzzle-headed ; but he first had 
 a happy knack of displaying our natural endowment. Motion 
 is so far from being inconceivable that only by a conceptual 
 treatment can we get any clear view of it. It cannot be 
 necessary here to show that all motions are relative both 
 in direction and velocity ; nor to answer the question how 
 Motion can originate from Eest or subside into Eest, seeing 
 that there is no such thing as Eest. 
 
 Motion, then, being an universal condition of all bodies, 
 there can be no cause of it in general, but only of its changes 
 or transformations, that is, of Acceleration or Eetardation, or 
 of Direction, or in the form of Energy. The specific forms of 
 Energy and their characters are a modern discovery, owing 
 little to early philosophers, and still less to primitive folk-lore : 
 for from these sources came the notions of Animism, occult 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 316 
 
 principles, fluids, which were rather a hindrance than an aid 
 to positive investigation ; except that the subjective notion 
 of Force, vaguely generalising all manifestations of energy, 
 mechanic<il, chemical, organic, gave a certain unity to the 
 object of investigation. But as to the phenomena of Accelera- 
 tion and Deflection, these are instinctively mastered by most 
 of the higher animals, conspicuously by birds, necessarily by 
 all men in the hunting stage of culture, most perfectly by the 
 champion of the billiard- table. In this sense, all who study 
 science begin with an organic knowledge of the laws of 
 Motion. 
 
 The conditions of the movements we are continually 
 witnessing are, for the most part, extremely complex ; and a 
 theory of Motion requires an analysis of these conditions into 
 their elements. In the experimental sciences attempts are 
 made to isolate the causes of movements ; but as experiments 
 are always imperfect, they serve chiefly to verify the theories 
 of Statics and Dynamics, which proceed from abstractions. 
 Newton's Laws of Motion, for example, are plainly abstracted 
 from experience by neglecting the differences of experience and 
 following amidst all perplexities the common fact. This pro- 
 cess is aided by the scene the heavens present of motions under 
 comparatively simple conditions. In experience every move- 
 ment is reinforced, opposed, or deflected, and therefore alters its 
 velocity or direction ; ' below the Moon ' the molar motion of 
 particular bodies is always at last frittered away until they 
 come to relative rest ; and even in the heavens the direction 
 and velocity of all bodies change according to the position of 
 other bodies : but, omitting all the conditions of change, infinite 
 and infinitely differing, there remains movement itself, un- 
 conditional, uniform and everlasting. Such is Newton's first 
 Law : the second and third declare the conservation of Motion 
 (or Force) amidst all interactions ; that is, Continuity and 
 Equality, the principles of the Understanding. 
 
 § 5. Motion implies some Matter that moves, a tangible 
 mass, or molecule, or the ether. Our own movements 
 are accompanied by ' sensations of effort,' which usually are 
 more intense the more rapid our movement. Sensations of 
 
316 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 the same class are felt in dragging a load or in trying to stop 
 or deflect another moving body : hence we form a notion of 
 Force as the cause of movement or of the checking of move- 
 ment. In interpreting the movements of Nature, man, before 
 the rise of discrimination and reflection, reads this experience 
 into other bodies ; not only into other men and animals, but 
 into swaying trees, rushing rivers, falling rocks : it is one of 
 the roots of Animism. And although this interpretation 
 would be defended by very few men in cold blood, it still 
 haunts our imaginations, and makes it easy to speak of 
 motion as due to Force. According to the doctrines of this 
 book, such an instinctive view of Nature is not false, but only 
 crude. It is, nevertheless, misleading ; for, using different 
 words, men regard them as standing for different things, and 
 speak of Force as impressed upon Matter and of causes as forces. 
 Force, however, can nowhere be found, nor imagined, nor even 
 conceived as a phenomenon, apart from Matter; there is no 
 way of measuring or conceiving it as a fact of the objective 
 world, except through the very movements it is supposed to 
 cause. 
 
 ' Force ' does not explain " the particular go " of anything. 
 Effort, being subjective, cannot be directly compared, it cannot 
 be a standard or a unit of measurement : in producing the 
 same effect (movement or resistance) it varies in different men 
 according to their strength, and in the same man according to 
 his age, health, etc. So far from giving a measure of Motion 
 it is supposed to be measured by Motion, according to the 
 doctrine that " causes are measured by their effects " : a doctrine 
 only applicable to " occult " causes ; since in true causation 
 amongst phenomena both cause and effect can be measured 
 and equated. 
 
 Hence arises a tendency to disparage the notion of Force, 
 and even to discard it altogether, because it is useless in 
 Mathematics. But, after all, to act upon this principle would 
 sadly impoverish the world. The facts of experience, even 
 though subjective, cannot be abolished for the convenience of 
 Methodology. Mach, in his Science of Mechanics, writes thus : 
 " Force is any circumstance of which the consequence is motion. 
 
THE THYSICAL CATEGORIES 317 
 
 ... In the motions which we ourselves determine, as well as 
 in those to which we are forced by external circumstances, 
 we are always sensible of a pressure. Thence arises our habit 
 of representing all circumstances determinative of motion as 
 something akin to volitional acts — as pressures. The attempts 
 we make to set aside this conception as subjective, animistic 
 and unscientific fail invariably. It cannot profit us, surely, to do 
 violence to our own natural-born thoughts and to doom our- 
 selves in that regard to voluntary mental penury " (chap. i. 
 § 5). In strict science, on the other hand, " force is not a some- 
 thing that lies latent in the natural processes, but a measurable 
 actual circumstance of motion, the product of the mass into 
 the acceleration " (chap. ii. § 8). That is, if used in science 
 at all, so the notion must be understood. 
 
 § 6. The Matter that moves or seems to rest is known 
 to us by various properties — Inertia, Mass, Space-occupancy 
 (volume with some limit to compressibility), Elasticity, etc. 
 — all of which are derived from the experience of Eesistance 
 to our efforts, which presents the world of Not-self in the 
 most irreducible and uncompromising form. Inertia is usually 
 said to be the property that all bodies have of remaining at 
 rest unless some cause sets them in motion, or of persisting in 
 rectilinear motion at constant velocity unless some cause im- 
 pedes or accelerates or deflects them. But since Rest is an 
 illusion, to " set in motion " is always to alter a body's 
 direction or velocity. The notion of Rest has led to the 
 coupling of ' inert ' with ' dead ' : so that ' inert, dead Matter ' 
 is familiar rhetoric. Mass is the same property as Inertia 
 conceived in a more definite way. The Mass of any body is 
 measured by the effect produced by it upon any other body 
 that alters its velocity or direction. The attempt has been 
 made to define it by the number of atoms contained in a 
 body ; if all atoms are alike inert, and gravitate equally, and 
 are all of the same size, the greater the number of them in 
 any aggregate the greater the mass ; and the greater the 
 number of them in a given volume the greater the density. 
 This doctrine is specious because it brings several concepts — 
 Mass, Weight, Density, Atom — into a simple relationship. 
 
318 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 But the atoms here assumed are not the ordinary chemical 
 atoms, which differ in size and weight : they are not any 
 known atoms, but merely units of Mass, obtained by hypo- 
 thetically dividing that which their multiplication is to explain. 
 It is, therefore, no true explanation, though it may prove to 
 have been an anticipation of the truth if the chemical elements 
 should be resolvable into homogeneous particles of Protyle. 
 Meanwhile we may be content with Mach's definition : " All 
 those bodies are bodies of equal mass, which, acting on each 
 other, produce in each other equal and opposite accelerations " 
 {pp. cit. chap. ii. § 5). 
 
 The doctrine that sensible bodies are aggregates of atoms 
 at short distances apart, has also been thought necessary to 
 the explanation of Elasticity : when an elastic body is com- 
 pressed and re-expands, it is easy to suppose that the inter- 
 spaces of its structure decrease and recover, but not that the 
 atoms themselves change their shape or volume ; for they 
 have no parts capable of changing their relative positions. 
 But although an ultimate physical Atom has (by definition) 
 no pliysical parts, yet if it has any volume there must be 
 geometrical parts : and that these are incapable of altering their 
 relative positions, of being compressed and re-expanding, seems 
 to be an assumption of that which should be left to inductive 
 investigation. That there is, in any case, some limit to com- 
 pressibility is asserted by the axiom, that ' two bodies cannot 
 occupy the same place at the same time ' ; and this is supported 
 (1) by experiments upon bodies under pressure at the lowest 
 temperatures, and (2) by the principle of Understanding, 
 equivalence or conservation. Otherwise, under sufficient pres- 
 sure. Matter ceases to differ from Space ; which is absurd, for 
 if it be the same as Space, how can it offer auy resistance at 
 aU? 
 
 § 7. The tendency of bodies to move or to maintain an 
 equilibrium is imagined as impact, attraction or repulsion, by 
 analogy with our own experience of striking, pulling or pushing. 
 That bodies gravitating pull one another is easily believed, 
 because, when we lift weights, they seem to pull us ; that a 
 magnet pulls another magnetic pole with one pole and pushes 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGOEIES 319 
 
 it away with the other may (with strong magnets) be sensibly 
 felt, if we hold eitlier magnet in our hand. If we consider 
 the commotion of molecules in a gas, it may be supposed that, 
 could we tie one of them by a fine thread, and were our 
 muscle-sense sufliciently discriminative, it would bo possible 
 to feel it twitching and rushing hither and thither like a 
 trout in a pool. In a luminous body the agitated molecules 
 may be thought of as pushing the adjacent ether and throwing 
 it into waves. Yet, on reflection, the analogies with our own 
 exertions in striking, pushing or pulling, fail in all those cases 
 in which one body influences another at a distance, without 
 apparent contact. Hence the possibility of actio in distans, or 
 rather the conceivability of it, is often denied, on the ground 
 that there is no sensible experience on which to base such a 
 concept ; the exertion of force without contact is supposed to 
 be too unfamiliar to the imagination. Lange assumes that 
 action at a distance is less picturable than impulse {Hist, of 
 Materialism, iii. 3). Gravitation being the most conspicuous 
 case of what looks like action at a distance, many attempts 
 have been made to explain it by molecular or etherial pres- 
 sure : hitherto (I believe) without much result. 
 
 I cannot see that action at a distance is less picturable 
 than impulse ; and the alleged difficulty of conceiving it is 
 obscure to me. That the concept exists in fact is shown by 
 this, that the law of gravitation assumes it : for that reason, 
 indeed, Newton did not regard it as a final explanation. 
 But the concept is also supported by sensible experience, and 
 is, therefore, imaginable : when we lift a weight, it is true 
 that we are in contact with it, but the weight is not apparently 
 in contact with the ground. In falling or jumping we have 
 the experience of being pulled to the ground without being 
 pushed or grasped ; and even of reciprocally pulling the ground 
 to us, though this side of the fact is submerged by the relative 
 smallness of our own mass. It may be said that when we 
 jump from a height, there is no muscular effort needed to get 
 to the ground ; and that is true, but a pure mechanist will 
 hardly urge it ; for it implies that ' force ' is to be interpreted 
 not by acceleration but by sensation. It may also be said 
 
320 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 that by Inertia a body is incapable of moving itself; and 
 this may be true of any body in isolation, but all movements 
 of actual bodies take place in relation to one another. Nothing 
 in the concept of Inertia requires that the reciprocal action of 
 bodies shall always be by contact, never by remote determin- 
 ation. And I agree with those who think that the maxim 
 that " a body only acts where it is," has been greatly over- 
 valued : in discussing action at a distance, it is a petitio 
 principii. It would be quite as reasonable to say that a body 
 is where it acts, that its existence is not necessarily limited 
 by its tangible superficies. 
 
 Perhaps to speak of bodies ' acting ' needs caution : the 
 methodological problem is to generalise the conditions of 
 Motion ; if a relation of remote bodies be sufficient, let it be 
 admitted ; if pressure be the only cause, let it be shown. 
 The alternative to absolute Mechanics is to accept the 
 contrast of Actual and Potential Energy, Energy of Motion 
 and Energy of Collocation. This contrast seems necessary in 
 other cases than gravitation ; and there is perhaps a certain 
 fanaticism in insisting upon a single ground of physical 
 changes. Simplification may be illusory : duality, contrast, 
 opposition, may be universal in Nature ; just as discrimination 
 is as fundamental as assimilation in the Understanding. 
 Hence there might be an error of the same kind in arguing 
 that all physical changes are actions at a distance ; that, for 
 example, chemical combination happens between molecules at 
 a distance, however small. If all matter is discrete (a sceptic 
 might say), certainly our bodies are, as an X-ray photograph 
 will show ; and therefore our own pulls and pushes imply 
 only a relative contiguity of parts. It may be doubted 
 whether immediate impact or contact is ever possible. To 
 reply that in none of these cases is there action at a distance, 
 because everywhere the Ether intervenes, is vain without 
 some definite account of how the Ether is helpful. Such an 
 explanation must be given in each case, and the explanations 
 must agree together : otherwise (the sceptic might conclude) 
 the Ether is no better than Mumbo Jumbo. 
 
 § 8. The phenomena of chemical Affinity must needs set 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 321 
 
 the poets agog : to whoHO warm iniagiuutious the distracted 
 elements seem to rush iuto each otliei's arms. Cooler heads, 
 looking througli microscopes, and seeing things happen 
 amongst the simpler forma of life in which bisexual generation 
 prevails, have supposed that sexual attraction even in higher 
 grades of organisation may be, in subconscious regions, nothing 
 else than the impulse of the spermatozoid seeking the ovule 
 — actio in distans notwithstanding — and, further, that this 
 impulse may be of a chemiail nature. Here are two ways 
 of identifying chemistry with holy matrimony : in their 
 aesthetic tone how different ! But according to the doctrine of 
 Chap. X. § 3, the various degrees of consciousness in the world 
 have their transcendent Being manifested by corresponding 
 degrees in the evolution and organisation of matter ; they 
 are all of them real, and none of them is to be confounded 
 with another. 
 
 Chemistry is more selective than gravitation, and in 
 this approaches life; and reviewing the series — Mechanics, 
 Chemistry, Organisation — the philosophic investigator is dis- 
 satisfied as long as they appear to be three separate and 
 irreducible manifestations of energy. All known bodies display 
 inertia and gravitation unconditionally. The constituents of 
 all bodies are capable of chemical activity, but its operation is 
 conditional on temperature, relative position, heterogeneous 
 structure and other circumstances. Life is shown only by 
 comparatively small portions of the material world; its 
 activities are the most special and complexly conditional of 
 all. Hence, the first impulse of generalisation is to attempt 
 the reduction of the forces of chemistry and life to those of 
 mechanics ; and a " mechanical theory of the world " has been 
 regarded as possible or even as a regulative aim of natural 
 science. The mechanical theory excites in some men an aversion 
 which is perhaps due to the illusion, that deduction effaces the 
 differential features of that which is deduced; although it 
 might have been supposed that this prejudice could only be 
 fostered by exclusively mechanical studies. But the suggestion 
 to explain the known activities of body by deriving from one 
 grade of them the remainder of the scale, may be misleading : 
 
 21 
 
322 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 another course may be necessary, though it seems more obscure, 
 namely, to explain all the known laws of material activity by 
 discovering still more general laws of protyle from which 
 the known laws may be derived. Gravitation, Chemistry, 
 Vitality may be differentiated derivatives of those laws of 
 protyle. At least such an explanation would agree with the 
 general character of evolution, as not a linear procession of 
 forms, but a differentiation of them from some type which is 
 for the most part no longer directly known. 
 
 The proposal to reverse the mechanical theory, to explain 
 all nature by the type of living activities, overlooks the 
 conditions of explanation in the region of phenomena, namely, 
 the discovery of resemblance. Living bodies gravitate, and 
 consist of chemically definite elements ; they are full of 
 machines and chemical experiments ; and so far they may be 
 explained by Mechanics and Chemistry ; for the fact that in 
 living bodies mechanical and chemical properties subserve 
 organic ends, has nothing to do with such explanations. But 
 the characteristic marks of the living body — cell-structure 
 with the functions of assimilation, adaptation, reproduction 
 (implying heredity) — are nowhere found in the inorganic world, 
 and throw no light upon its processes. It is not in the region 
 of phenomena, but in the region of Being that life, as the 
 vehicle of consciousness and self-consciousness, illumines the 
 abyss : not, it is true, by scientific explanation but by 
 metaphysical suggestion, indicating the unity of all phenomena 
 as co-manifestations of that which is known to us in thought 
 and feeling. 
 
 Organisation implies a totality generated under certain 
 special conditions, increasing by growth and differentiating its 
 structure, in such a way that its parts depend each upon all 
 and all upon each, and that all parts tend to preserve the 
 totality for some normal period which is closed by dissolution. 
 The notions of generation, growth, development, dissolution, 
 belong to Biology ; they are also of great interest in Politics 
 and Morals, and some of their metaphysical significance has 
 already been indicated. But the chief metaphysical interest 
 of organisation lies in that co-operation of parts to a common 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 328 
 
 result which we instinctively interpret as Means and End. 
 This is a subjective Category and belongs to the next chapter. 
 § 9. The sum of the movements and changes of bodies 
 makes up the course of Causation in the World. The category 
 of Causiition comprehends the conservation of matter and 
 energy, and the truth that in similar conditions of change 
 there are similar redistributions of matter and transformations 
 of energy (cf. Spencer, First Principles, §§ 63-65): Con- 
 tinuity and Equality in the contents of existence and Uni- 
 formity in its changes. 
 
 We have seen in Chap. VII. § 7, how ancient is the belief 
 in the persistence of Matter: announced by the Ionian 
 Cosmologists ; traceable in barbaric cosmogonies and mytho- 
 logies, however extravagant and incoherent ; forced upon 
 primitive man by the experience that things which come into 
 existence are modified from others, particularly in generation, 
 growth, corruption, and above all in the works of men's 
 hands. Direct experience, however partial and immethodical, 
 whilst begetting a general expectation of constancy and 
 routine, and a disposition to accept precise views when 
 demonstrated, yet fails to give a prevailing and definite belief 
 in the Uniformity of Nature. This may be seen both in the 
 popiilar mind in our own day, in spite of the increasing 
 exactness of modern industry and commerce (though I believe 
 this is a more effectual schooling in causation than is generally 
 known), and also in the history of Philosophy. For we find 
 that even Aristotle recognises as determining conditions of 
 events not only Divine Reason and Necessity but also Spon- 
 taneity and Chance. In this he seems inferior to Plato, who 
 ascribes the World's formation to the Divine and rational 
 Good, and even its deterioration to a certain Necessity in 
 things. But we may trace Aristotle's apparent backsliding to 
 his closer attention to human affairs and all kinds of matter 
 of fact, and to his love of truth, which compelled him to 
 recognise much that he could not explain ; for what are 
 Accident, Spontaneity, Chance, but the acknowledgment of 
 this ? We are apt to overrate Aristotle's love of system, and 
 to underrate his loyalty to fact such as he found it. The 
 
324 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 Stoics aud Epicureans had simpler and juster conceptions of 
 causation, though far less care for accurate inquiry ; still the 
 Epicureans retained the notion of Chance at the basis of their 
 system. The Stoics, although by thrusting upon Divine 
 Reason the function of Providence they used the notion of 
 Final Causes in a weak and tinkering fashion as subserving 
 particular utility, yet in their stricter Logic they resolved it 
 into antecedent plan and result (Zeller's Stoics, chap, vi. B 
 2) ; and by the conception of Divine Reason as the active 
 force in Nature they got rid of Chance ; for whoever in earnest 
 makes Reason king necessarily expels Spontaneity, Accident, 
 Chance and every other sort of rebel from the realm. But 
 how little right had they to this exalted conception, if the 
 right to a conception depends upon one's power of verifying 
 it ! We must recognise the part played in the progress of 
 thought by unjustifiable deduction. The Stoics' Law was 
 merely deduced from the idea of active Reason : and to them 
 it was less philosophy than fanaticism. In fanaticism Aristotle 
 was deplorably wanting : therefore he could not assert the 
 creative power of Reason, nor deny the automatism of 
 phenomena, and therefore the better man had the worse 
 doctrine. 
 
 I do not know how far to attribute to the growth and 
 establishment of the belief in Reason (that is, God), as the 
 creat6r and sustainer of the world, the fact that in modern 
 Philosophy a belief in Chance hardly appears, except in 
 imperfect notions concerning the freedom of the human will. 
 But in the special sciences the discovery of Laws and the 
 discrediting of Chance and Spontaneity has been the work of 
 a small class of minds, in whom the tracing of Continuity, 
 Equality, Uniformity, is a constructive instinct. They or 
 their ancestors have somehow profited more than the rest of 
 us by common experience, and the result is this genius. That 
 the laws of Mechanics, for instance, are based upon instincts 
 that spring from the self-analysing process of experience itself 
 in a growing mind, has been shown by many writers, and by 
 Mach with especial force, from his intimacy with the history 
 of the subject and from his own lucidity of introspection. 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 325 
 
 If the conservation of energy is less traceable in popular 
 thought than the persistence of matter, we may perhaps 
 account for this by the doctrine of Animism ; which, by 
 supplying an internal source for the movement of everything, 
 distracted attention from its transfer from one thing to 
 another. Internal sources of movement in fact there are, 
 that is, stores of potential ; and this may account for the 
 infrequent statements even in the history of Philosophy of 
 general principles concerning Motion, and also for the assumed 
 reality of Rest. I know of no earlier statement of anything 
 like the Conservation of Energy than that of Epicurus in his 
 Epistle to Herodotus (preserved by Diogenes Laertius), namely, 
 that the atoms are constantly in motion, and that from the 
 non-resistance of the vacuum their velocity is always the same. 
 Descartes says it seems clear to him that God in the beginning 
 created matter together with motion and rest, and maintains 
 them in the same quantity {Principia, ii. 36). Yet Kant 
 finds no principle of Motion amongst the Analogies of 
 Experience. Within certain limits the conservation of Energy 
 was expressed by mechanicians and astronomers, as in Newton's 
 Laws of IMotion ; but its detailed investigation in the theories 
 of Heat, Electricity and other modes, and its universal state- 
 ment, remained for the nineteenth century. 
 
 The conservation of Matter and Energy is usually regarded 
 as confirmed and even established by the results of Mechanics, 
 Physics and Chemistry; though it is admitted that neither 
 the mass nor the energy of the atomic world alone need be 
 constant, because of its relation to Ether or Protyle (supposing 
 this to be in no sense atomic), and that, on account of the 
 degradation of energy, we cannot be confident that the world's 
 capacity for work is conserved. We have already seen that 
 the equality of contents in all the transformations of Nature 
 is a necessary condition of Understanding ; but that 
 objectively, as a Law of Nature, it is a postulate that can 
 only be verified conditionally within a limited experience, and 
 can never be submitted to exhaustive proof. Of our limited 
 experience it may be unreasonable to assert either that it is, 
 or that it is not, a fair sample of the Universe. Still, con- 
 
326 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 servation is true as far as our knowledge reaches; we are 
 aware of no exception, and no alternative is offered in the 
 shape of any definite physical doctrine. Whoever doubts the 
 universality of conservation would do well, if he entertains 
 any Philosophy of Nature, to offer some alternative hypothesis 
 clearly formulated, in order that we may see what it is like. 
 To disclaim a Philosophy of Nature as too ambitious an 
 enterprise, is to relinquish the problem of Understanding, 
 not only as to the whole world but as to any fact or process 
 that occurs in it : for the understanding of any part implies 
 some view of the whole. At present, all definite explanations 
 of phenomena are afl&liated to the principle of Conservation. 
 And whoever shall construct a system of Nature, as compre- 
 hensive and consistent as the existing sciences, upon some 
 other principle, will do more to quell the arrogance of text- 
 books than all the Sceptics that ever lived. 
 
 In modern Methodology a place is found for ' Chance,' 
 but the analysis of it presupposes Causation. Contingency 
 is recognisable as dependence on a cause of whose occurrence 
 in any given case we are uncertain. Necessity, on the other 
 hand, a refuge to Plato and Aristotle, is a term malodorous 
 to some moderns who accept the Uniformity of Nature. No 
 doubt it may be misused to identify moral obligation with the 
 actual order of the world, or to raise personal prejudices to 
 the rank of universal laws : it lends itself to rhetoric ; and, 
 in fact, by association with Fate and Predestination, it has 
 acquired a mythological tinge. Moreover, there is not yet 
 sufficient ground for asserting the necessity of natural law. 
 I say this because, speculatively, it seems just ; though for 
 myself I cannot feel it. Still, the invariability of law is 
 necessary to reasoning, to generalisation and inference, and 
 from Reason nothing could proceed but Law ; so that I 
 bear with those who, knowing no higher praise, give the 
 name of Reason to Law itself; for it is the ideal of reason, 
 universal and unerring, and to human reason the way, the 
 guide and the goal. 
 
 § 10. Narrowing our view from the Uniformity of Nature 
 as a whole to the particular events selected and defined for 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 327 
 
 observation and experiment, us Causes related to Eirects, we 
 meet with many ditliculties in the isohition, measurement and 
 comparison of phenomena, concerning which the works on 
 Logic and Method must be consulted. The existence of the 
 World in its everlasting movement and change, is conceived 
 of as a process in Time, continuous, invariable in its laws, 
 unconditional (since there is nothing outside it) and always 
 equal to itself; and an ideal Causal Instance, or particular 
 relation of events to be investigated, may be conceived to 
 elapse as an independent system, and to have the same char- 
 acters as the World-process. That no such Instance is obtainable 
 in a test-tube, your sceptic never wearies of rejoicing. It is 
 true, of course, that no Causal Instance is ever unconditional, 
 and that (strictly) none can ever be repeated ; and it is 
 inferred that generalisation must always be fallacious. 
 Similarly, to the moral maxim ' that what is right for one is 
 right for all in the same circumstances ' ("their actions having 
 the same consequences), it may be objected that the circum- 
 stances of two men are never the same. The solution of these 
 puzzles is, that observation or experiment is not the whole 
 process of investigation ; that what we seek is the law of each 
 tendency, and the resultant of the tendencies combined in any 
 event ; and these are found by reasoning on the empirical 
 data. That the conceptions of tendency and resultant are 
 clearer in Mechanics than in more concrete sciences, is one 
 reason why mechanical explanations are preferred. 
 
 The complexity of the Category of Cause and Effect has 
 hindered its elaboration in the human mind ; it is the latest 
 of the master-categories to have become definite, and yet it 
 may not be finished ; but many have worked by it with clear 
 intelligence who could not enounce it in terms. Since move- 
 ment with consciousness precedes the consciousness of move- 
 ment reflected in apperception, there is an ancestral or 
 congenital basis of this Category as a disposition to perceive ; 
 may we not say that it is the core of the disposition to ex- 
 pectant attention ? Again, since sensible Causes are moving 
 bodies and collocations of bodies, a familiarity with certain 
 regular series of events is acquired during the growth of the 
 
328 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 individual's perception of an external World ; and even a 
 practical command of such series, as we see in children and 
 even low-type animals, before the rise of self-consciousness ; 
 and this is the ground of the Category's objectivity. 
 
 In the human race, the understanding of Causation was 
 very early confused by the doctrines of Animism and 
 Sympathetic Magic. The development of imagination in 
 primitive man had certain disastrous consequences, moral and 
 speculative. It encroached upon the objectivity of Nature, 
 and often left its victim less intelHgent than an unembarrassed 
 ape. The mind seems to have grown faster than it developed, 
 and so was given over to picture-thinking without the power 
 of analysis and abstraction. In a rich but unco-ordinated cortex 
 excitement is localised, and therefore intense and uninhibited, 
 and issues in violence and absurdity. Whenever total ideas 
 are relatively isolated and, therefore, uncriticised, they are apt 
 to be reified and to compete with perception ; and whatever 
 objects enter into them are believed to be physically connected. 
 Hence clothes, weapons, locks of hair, whatever belongs to a 
 man, especially his name ; and, again, effigies, mimicry, descrip- 
 tions, whatever resembles him, is believed to be a part of him 
 in such a way that whatever good or evil happens to them, or 
 is invoked by means of them, falls upon him. This is not 
 merely association of ideas, but is supported by a theory of 
 some continuity of existence between such things, along which 
 influences travel as by media, such as the air blowing or breathed, 
 or shafts of light and shadow. The idea of sympathetic Magic 
 is thus a confused matrix in which all sorts of relations. 
 Likeness, Coexistence, Succession, are huddled together as 
 equally connections of Causation, and from which the true 
 relation must be gradually eliminated. 
 
 In the course of dissociation, relations of Succession 
 as characteristic of Causation became predominant. On the 
 whole, this had happened amongst the Greeks ; as we may see 
 in Plato's satirical description of the men in the cave, who sat 
 watching the shadows and trying to remember which were 
 accustomed to go before and after, and to guess which would 
 come next : an odd anticipation of Hume ! But meanwhile 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATECxORIES 329 
 
 the type of humuu agency, uud the belief in Animism, had 
 filled the world with purposes, established the doctrine of Final 
 Causes, and prechuled the distinguishing between conscious 
 activity and physical ciiusation. And the successiveness of 
 Causation was not so definitely conceived as to prevent its 
 being confused with the relation of Substance and Attribute ; 
 as appears from the causal conception of Ideas by Plato and of 
 Forms by Aristotle, and even by Bacon. For I take it that 
 Bacon's Form is the latens scheviatisvius which determines the 
 attributes ; so that, when altered by a latens processus, other 
 attributes appear. Moreover, the notion of Substance as a certain 
 undiscoverable inwardness of things had become allied with 
 the doctrines of sympathetic Magic to form the theory of 
 Occult Powers. According to this doctrine, we must apply the 
 term cause " to a certain conception, force, abstracted from all 
 special events and considered as a quality or property by which 
 one body affects the motion of another. And in like manner 
 in other cases, Ciiuse is conceived as some abstract quality, 
 power or efficacy by which change is produced." 
 
 Hume's great service to the metaphysics of Causation was 
 to supersede occult causes by the notion of a sequence of 
 phenomena. His definition of Cause is clumsily expressed, 
 but amounts to this, that the cause of a phenomenon is its 
 constant antecedent. Occult causes were not conceived as 
 transcendent ; and the doctrine of this book that there are 
 changes in transcendent Eeality or Being, of which the course 
 of phenomena is a manifestation, is not a doctrine of occult 
 causes : I have shown in Chap. VIII. that Manifestation is a 
 distinct Category, one-sided and merely orectic. The phrase 
 " immanent Causation " involves a confusion of ideas. Occidt 
 causes were regarded as entering into the tissue of natural 
 processes, but as essentially unsearchable; and, under the name 
 of powers or virtues, were the discouragement of induction, 
 the refuge of ignorance, and a fastness of Scepticism. That 
 causation is concerned with things unseen and, therefore, gives 
 no explanation of phenomena, was one of the tropes of 
 j^^nesidemus. 
 
 It is a serious fault of Hume's definition of Cause that he 
 
330 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 calls it an " object precedent " instead of an event. Another 
 fault was pointed out by Mill, namely, the being content with 
 the constancy of the antecedent, without requiring the absence 
 of other conditions ; but Hume's second definition of Cause — 
 " where, if the first object had not been, the second never had 
 existed," — may imply its uuconditionality. Mill, at any rate, 
 insisted on the uuconditionality of Causation ; although it is 
 true that to discover the antecedent that is all, and no more 
 than all, that is necessary to the occurrence of a given effect, 
 is impracticable in a particular investigation. The conditions 
 constituting a Cause are relations of Space and Time, and 
 Agents. Agents are material things, popularly regarded as 
 exerting force, and contrasted with "patients," but of which 
 all that we can say is, that without their presence in such kind 
 and quantity, and the movement of some of them relatively to 
 the rest, the effect we have in view does not happen. Their 
 agency (if the term be allowable) depends upon their Reciprocity 
 or relations to one another in space, that is, upon distances and 
 directions of movement. But as it also depends upon their 
 velocity, and as all movement implies time, time is also a 
 condition. It is true that if we conceive the reduction of 
 causation to its simplest type, it is an immediate sequence, or 
 the time of its happening is infinitesimal : because (1) motion 
 is continuous, and (2) any interval admits other agencies and 
 destroys the unconditionality of the process. But observable 
 processes take an appreciable time ; and causal instances may 
 be selected occupying a less or greater time according to the 
 character of the inquiry : the causes of double refraction and 
 of coral-reefs are contrasted cases. Still, the simplest type of 
 causation is also the ideal of knowledge concerning it, and is 
 pursued by tracing in the unwieldy instances (say) of Geology 
 an indefinite multitude of chemical and physical instances. 
 
 With Mill causation remained a qualitative conception, 
 although the ancient doctrine of the persistence of matter and 
 the maxim causa aequat effectum strongly drew attention to its 
 quantitative aspect. Until the conservation of energy was 
 discovered the quantitative content of the notion could not be 
 definitely formulated ; yet J. R. Mayer, one of the discoverers 
 
THE PHYSICAL CATEGORIES 331 
 
 of that principle, begins his first essay by deducing it from 
 the maxim of equality in causation {Forces of Inorganic Nature). 
 Bain then, in his Inductive Logic, identified Conservation with 
 Causation, and used it in deducing the canons of experiment. 
 The principles of Conservation increase the definiteness of 
 Uncontlitionality as a mark of Causation. For when is a 
 cause unconditionally adequate to an effect ? Wlien the two 
 are equal : for if the effect is the greater, the whole cause 
 cannot have been discovered ; and if the cause is the greater, 
 some portion of the effect must still be unexplored. This brings 
 us back to the principle of explanation. 
 
 Nevertheless, the interpretation of Causation as merely a 
 redistribution of Matter and Energy withdraws it from the 
 foreground of Empirical Eeality into the conceptual world of 
 the physical sciences. Causation becomes an exclusively 
 physical Category. At the same time some excuse is made 
 tor the old doctrine of occult causes : which now appears as 
 one of those shadows of approaching truths that so often fall 
 across the path of Philosophy, and now lead, and now mislead, 
 the wayfaring man. 
 
CHAPTER XV 
 
 CATEGORIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 
 
 § 1. Causation is an exclusively Physical Category, but 
 its common use gives it a much wider scope. Sensations are 
 said to be caused by stimuli ; and many have held (on various 
 grounds) the position of Schopenhauer, that volition is an 
 immediate consciousness of causation ; that, therefore. Will is 
 indicated as the essence of the World, and that all the forces 
 of Nature are manifestations of Will. But whilst it is true 
 that our experience of voluntary action has had great influence 
 in moulding the concept of physical causation, since the actions 
 and reactions of phenomena have been interpreted in analogy 
 with our own experience in moving or being moved, in striking 
 or resisting ; still it appeared in Chap. X. that consciousness 
 is neither substance nor energy and, therefore, cannot be a 
 cause ; and this was confirmed in Chap. XI. by a review of the 
 history of doctrines concerning the Soul. At the risk of some 
 repetition I must offer further reflections upon the relation of 
 mind and body ; but the pith of it all is, that organised bodies 
 and all things in Nature are phenomena, whilst consciousness 
 is not a phenomenon but immediate Reality. The phenomenon 
 is empirically real, and even immediately real, considered as a 
 construction in consciousness itself; but standing, as it seems 
 to, in opposition to the Subject, it is not Being, but only 
 represents it. The phenomenon, however, is not a construction 
 in Self-consciousness, for it exists before that arises (whence its 
 opposition to the Subject) ; but in the generic growth of 
 consciousness the phenomenon is differentiated as the symbol 
 of Being, and defined by Inertia, Motion and other attributes, 
 
 332 
 
CATEGORIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 333 
 
 as if these were ultimate facts of experieuce ; whereas Volition 
 is a development of consciousness in its subjective Reality, 
 having no Inertia, Mass, Motion, Solidity, Elasticity, Attraction, 
 Repulsion, nor any single physical quality. 
 
 For all subjective changes the term Activity seems to me 
 the most suitable that can be found. In subjective changes 
 there are many degrees of Activity, and at the top of the 
 scale lie the intense experiences of volition : or near the top, 
 for there is a vision and a felicity of achievement beyond 
 endeavour. 
 
 If the term Activity be adopted as the Category of 
 subjective change and (more particularly) of purposeful change, 
 in speaking technically we ought to restrict it to that sense. It 
 is quite useless to set it up as a higher concept, inclusive of 
 Causation : that is, to substitute one obfuscation for another. 
 The present use of Causation for both subjective and objective 
 processes (as by Wundt), and also for the supposed " inter- 
 action " of Object and Subject, is extremely confusing ; and to 
 use Activity in the same way would be no gain at all. But 
 ' subjective Activity ' and ' objective Causation ' are an intelli- 
 gible contrast. For the " interaction " of the heterogeneous 
 some expression should be found as colourless as possible : 
 ' parallelism ' is in vogue, but is too diagrammatic ; for 
 psychological purposes, ' correlation ' is enough and is, therefore, 
 to be preferred. 
 
 To use any one expression for these three facts, sub- 
 jective Activity, objective Causation, and the Correlation 
 of body and mind, is to disguise the profound differences 
 that ought to be recognised between consciousness and 
 energy, reality and phenomenon. Energy and consciousness 
 cannot be assimilated without either depriving energy of mass 
 and movement, or bestowing these properties on consciousness ; 
 materialising consciousness, or dematerialising energy. Body 
 and mind cannot be considered as interactive, or even parallel, 
 without placing them on the same level, either as both 
 substances or both phenomena, Descartes conceived them as 
 both substances, but in such a way that interaction was 
 impossible without the assistance of God ; still the co-ordination 
 
334 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 of them upon the same plane of existence facilitated the 
 notion of their mutual influence, whether direct or indirect. 
 As a matter of fact, however, body and mind are in no sense 
 two substances, and are so far from being on the same level 
 that the notion of interaction between them is the greatest 
 absurdity that speculation has adopted from popular delusions. 
 The body is an empirical substance, and the mind is not : the 
 mind is a process of ultimate Reality, and the body is not ; 
 for empirical substance is itself a phenomenon. Now a pheno- 
 menon cannot influence that upon which it depends ; it cannot 
 influence the transcendent Substance or Being on which it 
 depends for existence, nor yet the Subject on which it depends 
 for representation. It cannot, therefore, be the stimulus of 
 sensation ; for sensations are what the phenomenon is, or 
 (rather) sensations are the elements out of which it is con- 
 structed. And again, Being cannot influence the phenomenon 
 as knowledge ; nor can the Subject influence it as existence, 
 or in the modes of its existence. Volition, therefore, cannot 
 be the cause of movement; it is the consciousness of some- 
 thing that happens in Being and becomes manifest in the 
 phenomenon, but it does not determine the happening. 
 
 Absolute unconditional Eeality is conscious Being : in 
 experience it is individuated as a World of bodies presented 
 to conscious Subjects ; and amongst these bodies are the 
 organisms that are the phenomena of Being so far as it is 
 conscious in each Subject. Every change or movement in the 
 "World of things makes manifest a change in Being ; it is not 
 caused by, but is the phenomenon of, that change. Those 
 changes of subjective consciousness which we call sensations 
 imply changes in Being so far as it is manifest in other bodies, 
 transmitted to Being so far as it is manifest in that body in 
 whose consciousness the sensations occur. And those changes 
 of consciousness which we call volitions imply changes in 
 Being so far as it is manifest in the organism of the Subject 
 that wills, transmitted to Being so far as it is manifest in 
 some other body or bodies and in their movements. 
 
 If this painful account of what seems so familiar and easy, 
 until you try to understand it, has any truth or likeness to 
 
CATEGORIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY^ 835 
 
 the truth, it follows that the doctrine of the parallelism of 
 bodily and mental changes, invented to circumvent the 
 Cartesian impasse, errs in the opposite way. For whilst 
 Descartes took body and mind to be two substances, this 
 hypothesis treats both of them as phenomena. According to 
 Spinoza, ideas and bodies are modes of the attributes of 
 thought and extension. Tliere is no interaction between ideas 
 and bodies ; each idea is to be explained by antecedents in 
 its own kind, and so is each body ; but the two series of 
 modes always correspond, because they are eftects of the same 
 Substance ; and they are so entirely upon the same level that 
 Substance or God, so manifested, may be called " a thinking 
 thing," and "uu extended thing" {Ethica, ii. 1, 2). But when 
 we remember that Spinoza defines an attribute as " that 
 which intelligence knows of Substance as constituting its 
 essence " (Book I. Def. 4), it seems clear that intelligence cannot 
 know anything as an ultimate character of existence except 
 consciousness. It is, therefore, justifiable to say that Substance, 
 or God, or Being, is a thinking thing, but not that it is an 
 extended thing. It has been shown that extension and body 
 are phenomena constructed in the generic consciousness to re- 
 present the transcendent Being ; and we cannot help inferring 
 that relations corresponding with the coexistence and order of 
 phenomena in space appertain also to Being, especially as they 
 are found in Self-consciousness ; but extension is a character of 
 the phenomenon alone. Mind and body, therefore, are not 
 upon the same footing, and metaphysically the doctrine of 
 parallelism is untrue. 
 
 Upon the ground of Hume's phenomenalism (by the way) 
 an attempt may be made to resuscitate the popular delusion 
 that a volition moves the body, or that a stimulus causes a 
 sensation. For causation, according to Hume, is an invariable 
 succession of phenomena ; why then may not bodily and 
 mental phenomena, if uniformly thus related, be reciprocally 
 cause and effect ? But this comes of overlooking the uncon- 
 ditional! ty of a cause. Suppose that a certain stimulus 
 is always followed by a certain sensation: this is not the 
 whole effect. Suppose that a certain action always follows a 
 
336 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 certain motive : this is not the whole cause. Without 
 molecular disturbance in the cortex, a motive would not issue 
 in actions, nor a stimulus arouse a sensation. 
 
 But although processes of consciousness are not phenomena, 
 it is convenient to treat them as such for the purposes of 
 Psychology, working as a natural science ; and in determining 
 the physiological conditions of sensation and volition the 
 hypothesis of parallelism or correlation is indispensable. Not 
 that a complete parallelism between mental and organic 
 changes is open to observation or to simple inference ; for only 
 the higher grades of consciousness are observable ; and if these 
 are correlated with the cortex, there remain profound regions 
 of subconsciousness to be otherwise assigned. Wundt, indeed, 
 holds that " there are two concepts that result from the 
 psychical combinations, which, together with their affective 
 elements, lie entirely outside the sphere of experience to which 
 the principle of parallelism applies. These are the concepts 
 of vahoe and end " {Outlines, § 22). But since the words 
 value, end, better, worse, with their associates, whether spoken, 
 heard or thought, are admitted to have parallel physical 
 processes, if there are no physical processes parallel with their 
 meanings, the course of physical causation must be interrupted 
 whenever they are intelligently acted upon ; for it is their 
 meanings that determine volition. Such a thrusting of 
 mysticism into a natural science is most mischievous. It stirs 
 up a cynical opposition, and sets men upon calling the mind 
 an " epiphenomenon," perhaps the most foolish phrase that ever 
 was coined ; and it may arouse the unjust suspicion that 
 Psychology is not written disinterestedly, but modified to 
 conciliate the supposed trend of contemporary Schwarmerei. 
 There is a better way of thinking nobly of the soul. Still, the 
 study of Physiology and Psychology should never blind us to 
 the truth that consciousness is not really an activity of the 
 body, but of transcendent Being so far as the body expresses 
 it. The transcendent nature of that activity I do not pretend 
 to explain, or understand, or name : parallelism, correlation, 
 unity, are alike unavailing in a region where none of our terms 
 can be just. 
 
CATEGOIUES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 337 
 
 § 2. Volition, then, as a conscious process, is an activity 
 of Being, not dependent on phenomena, nor (strictly speaking; 
 upon natural laws ; and such is Kant's doctrine of Freedom. 
 But this immanency (if I may so express it) of volitional 
 activity, this non-dependence upon phenomena or upon laws 
 of Nature, does not imply spontaneity, contingency, irregularity, 
 or any deviation of character from the uniformity of Nature. 
 For volition and the laws of phenomena are manifestations of 
 the same Being, the former immediate, the latter conditional ; 
 the laws of Nature bear witness to the order of thp transcendent 
 World, its universality of character in all its activities ; and 
 we judge accordingly of volition. We judge this the more 
 necessarily, because the body of a voluntary Subject is a 
 natural body, and its movements, which express volition, are 
 according to law in the natural context. For it is thus that 
 the activities of the Keal manifest themselves ; and though it 
 is only subjectively that they are immediately known, yet it is 
 only objectively, or in the course of Nature, that they can be 
 clearly understood as actions or events in a context of causes 
 and consequences, springing from and reacting on the agent as 
 a phenomenon in relation with the rest of phenomena : since 
 the region of motives is obscure and profoundly subconscious. 
 This doctrine of volition, therefore, differs entirely from 
 Kant's. He treats Freedom as Causation, thus making 
 (contrary to his own principles) a transcendent application of 
 that category : but here causation is confined to the region that 
 can be studied scientifically ; and no advantage is sought from 
 the use of such a term in recommending the metaphysical 
 hypothesis of Being. Kant regards all particular states of 
 mind as phenomena, and thereby is left with no clue whatever 
 to the character and activities of the intelligible World ; and, 
 accordingly, he falls into mysticism : but it has been shown 
 above, that subjective processes are immediate Eeality, so that 
 we have immediate knowledge of it. Kant, finally, treats all 
 that he calls phenomena as having a sensuous character, not 
 merely distinguishable from, but opposed to. Reason ; he uses 
 the laws of Nature as merely a type of what Morality ought 
 to be, flatly and fanatically denying that Morality can itself 
 
 22 
 
338 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 be natural : but we know that there is no opposition between 
 sensation and Eeason, and that Morality, as the growing 
 custom and conception of human life and the necessary con- 
 dition of its welfare, is truly natural ; so that nothing more 
 insane or pernicious can be conceived than to set Morality in 
 opposition to Nature. 
 
 But, be the source of volition what it may, if it belongs to 
 an invariable order, and if actions occur according to natural 
 laws, must not a belief in this oppress the sense of personal 
 Freedom ? Laws state the necessity or invariableuess of the 
 actions of agents and of the resultants of the co-operation of 
 agents ; the future of the World at any moment depends upon 
 the combination of existing agents, and of these agents each 
 man is one. His actions follow upon his character by neces- 
 sity ; for his character is expressed by his body ; but because 
 he acts according to his character he feels himself free. The 
 necessity of his action in this sense, far from weighing upon 
 him, is precisely what makes the action his own. It is true 
 that if the course of the World were known to be predetermined 
 by Fate, or Providence, he would feel oppressed and helpless. 
 Or if it were merely known to him as a process independent of 
 himself, he might despair ; and sometimes, say in a shipwreck, 
 when the predominance of the Not-self, though not absolute, is 
 overwhelming, this really happens. But such happenings are 
 rare : usually the course of the World, so far as it directly con- 
 cerns a man, cannot be known apart from his own actions ; 
 because, in fact, he is one of the agents that determine that 
 course, having the greater influence the more he exerts himself, 
 the more a force, the more a man he is. 
 
 But, it may be said, our characters being what they are, 
 we are not really free any more than other things in the world ; 
 for everything acts according to its nature. Certainly, no 
 more than other things ; for everthing is free, and, doubtless, 
 so far as conscious, feels free and rejoices in its power. Does 
 not a tiger feel free, slaying a deer ; or a blackbird, chaunting 
 to the dawn ? The feeling of coercion only arises when our 
 purposes are thwarted, never when they are fulfilled. The 
 notion that matter acts under constraint, that the Earth (e.g.) 
 
CATEGORIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 330 
 
 is constrained in her orbit by the Sun, is animistic. Where 
 there is no purpose there is no compulsion. The agents in 
 any material system co-operate, and in the resultant every one 
 of them tells with its full weight (cf. Sliadworth Hodgson's 
 Metaphysic of Experience, iii. 6, § 5). That we have these 
 feelings of freedom and constraint more clearly than other 
 things, is due to our more explicit consciousness of all that 
 happens, to our self-consciousness and purposefulness. To say 
 that our characters at any moment are what they are, is to 
 revive Zeno's sophism of the arrow ; for it is characteristic of 
 the development of organisation to produce forms more and 
 more modifiable by experience ; so that it is nearer truth to 
 say, that a man's character at any moment is changing as it is 
 changing, and that he can never twice be the same. Character 
 is not a fixed but a growing thing, and (as Mill said) our 
 desires to alter it (if we have any) are important conditions 
 (say, rather, symptoms) of its growth and transformation. 
 And even though a man's desires are the symptoms of his 
 character, and though he may feel no strong desire for good, 
 this ought not to discourage him ; for he never knows the 
 depths and resources of his own soul. 
 
 It is indeed most unreasonable to suppose that there are 
 no limits to the development of a man's character ; for it 
 must depend partly upon the circumstances that call upon him 
 to act, and finally upon the scope of his original congenital 
 endowments. But for a man of understanding to desire an 
 imconditional life is impossible. What, however, the con- 
 ditions are, circumstantial or congenital, that limit his 
 development, is always far from being fully known, and, 
 therefore, the knowledge of it cannot be oppressive. In short, 
 whether as to character or outward conduct we are, as Aristotle 
 said, at least avvairtot, joint-causes, of our own actions ; and 
 moralists seem justifiable in their tenet that we have more 
 power over our characters than over circumstances. 
 
 It may, perhaps, be further objected that our characters 
 belong to consciousness, and therefore cannot be causes of 
 physical events or have any power over the course of Nature. 
 But to this my reply may easily be anticipated : character in 
 
340 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 consciousness is our immediate knowledge of that Eeality 
 which is also manifested in our bodies. A man's body 
 expresses his character as much as his mind, and even more- 
 than his apperception ; for it is the phenomenon of his whole 
 Being, including that which is only subconscious but which 
 influences the apperceptive mind in innumerable ways, though 
 rarely or never rising into apperception. Hence by his body 
 a man is a cause in Nature to the full extent of his Eeality, 
 and accomplishes there what he wills ; sometimes less, some- 
 times more, than he had thought possible. 
 
 § 3. Volition, as a function of apperceptive consciousness, 
 not mere instinctive or even ideo-motor action, implies pur- 
 poses more or less remote, upon the prosecution or hindrance 
 of which depend the feelings of freedom or restraint, success or 
 failure, as they are characteristic of human life. 
 
 A purpose realised in action is a Final Cause ; and this 
 concept has been transferred to the operations of Nature, and 
 plays a somewhat spectral part in Metaphysics. Aristotle 
 uses TO ov eveKa in connection with human affairs, such as 
 house-building, in the sense of purpose ; but in the theory of 
 Nature as equivalent to to etSo?, the form or specific character 
 which everything, aspiring toward God, strives to realise in 
 itself according to its kind. 
 
 A Final Cause, as that which is the end of any human 
 action, may be analysed, as by the Stoics, into (1) a repre- 
 sentation of the end desired, which is an antecedent determin- 
 ing the action ; (2) the effect of the action when it has been 
 successful, and we say, ' This was what I aimed at.' Now 
 in this process we have two steps of cause and effect : A, the 
 representation (or its neural correlate), causing B, the action, 
 which causes C, the result. Nothing liere distinguishes final 
 from antecedent Causation ; unless it be supposed that by 
 a vis afronte A, the representation, is caused by C, the result. 
 Such a notion sometimes haunts the dialectical mind ; but of 
 course A, the representation, is derived from former experiences, 
 or reports, of things resembling it. That it was not caused 
 by the future event C, appears whenever the action B is 
 unsuccessful ; for then A may be notliing like C, although our 
 
CATEGOEIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 341 
 
 uusuccessful actions are as purposeful as our successful ones. 
 In fact, meiins and ends differ from causes and effects not as 
 processes or events but merely in this, that ends imply desire, 
 and means a choice on the part of the desiring Subject ; an 
 End is an event desired, and regarded as a possible effect of 
 certain causes, which are in the power of an agent, and are 
 therefore adopted as Means. Transferring these conceptions to 
 the region of Nature, and assuming the welfare of Man to be 
 the most desiraltle of all things, we may try to explain all the 
 fiu-uiture of the world as means of promoting that end ; in 
 which vein the ingenuity of the Stoics and others is known to 
 have laboured; though Montaigne would have pointed out 
 that a cat understands the world quite differently. 
 
 The Aristotelian doctrine of Nature is less encumbered 
 with difficulties of detail, and is more genial in its recognition 
 that everything exists by its own right ; but it lies open to 
 this general objection, that there is no way of showing that 
 the specific Form that seems to be realised in anything needs 
 any other explanation than as the effect of physical antecedents. 
 To say that anything sub-human strives to be what it becomes, 
 is only to say that from time to time it becomes what it 
 is. If we admit f^iilures in realising a type, it is easier to 
 reconcile our imaginations to them as due to the variable 
 concurrence of physical agents, than by attributing them to 
 the impotence of Nature. Moreover, to ascribe to Nature (or 
 to Being manifested in her) such a consciousness as the terms 
 ' aspiration,' ' endeavour,' ' purpose,' ' end,' imply, is only possible 
 if you recognise a dualism in the World, such as Matter and 
 Form, and along with it, upon one side, an inherent inferiority 
 and imperfection. Want, insufficiency, inferiority, something 
 unattained, can never characterise the Universe, if you say 
 with Spinoza {Ethics, ii. Def. 6), per realitatem et perfectionem 
 idem intelligo. 
 
 Kant, in the Critique of Pure Reason, requires all phenomena 
 in Nature to be explained by causation ; since Nature is so 
 constituted by pure Understanding. But in the Critique of 
 Judgment it appears that organic life cannot in fact be under- 
 stood in this way by the human mind ; so that an Antinomy 
 
342 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUKE 
 
 is established by confronting the Thesis of pure Understanding 
 with the Antithesis : " the production of some material things 
 cannot be explained by merely mechanical laws." And the 
 solution of the Antinomy is that, whilst the Category of 
 Causality requires a mechanical explanation of Nature, it does 
 not exclude every other kind of Causality ; there remains the 
 possibility that, in the unknown inwardness of Nature, mechani- 
 cal and final Causation are united as one principle in the same 
 things (§ 70). Hence we are to pursue the mechanical explana- 
 tion as far as we can ; and for inorganic Nature it suffices. 
 Even in organic forms much may be so explained, but never 
 the specific fact of a natural End. For that we must find 
 another principle ; as the universal laws of Nature are 
 determined by the Understanding, so particular laws of 
 empirical fact, that cannot be subsumed by the universal laws, 
 must also be explained as if an Understanding (not our own) 
 had presented them to us (§ 4), Organisms display such an 
 intrinsic adaptation of parts to one another and to the whole, 
 whole and parts being reciprocally end and means, that, with our 
 limited powers of reasoning, they are only to be explained by 
 Final Causes, as the work of a purposeful, intelligent First Cause 
 of the World (§ 71). In Kant's system, then, Causation and 
 Teleology are not upon the same footing as principles of explana- 
 tion ; for Causation is a category of the Universal Understand- 
 ing, not subjective, but constitutive of Nature; whereas Teleology 
 is a subjective principle, derived from reflection upon certain 
 groups of phenomena which we are unable to explain otherwise. 
 Indeed, he himself concludes that, whilst the notion of Final 
 Causes is indispensable to us men, and an useful clue to the 
 study of Nature, seeing that phenomena are given to us in 
 a fragmentary and accidental way, and have to be subsumed 
 under universals by discursive reasoning ; still by a higher 
 Understanding, an intellectus archetypus, free from such limita- 
 tions and intuitive. Nature throughout might be compre- 
 hended under one principle, and teleological explanation, with 
 which even we men are not long content, might be needless 
 (§ 77). Now such an intellectus archetypus, I should say, 
 is implied in Kant's doctrine of the Categories of pure Under- 
 
CATEGORIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 343 
 
 standing as constitutive of Nature. His own dissatisfaction 
 with anything else than mechanical explanation was proved 
 hy his theory of the Heavens. And why else does he assume 
 that the intuitive Understanding will comprehend Nature 
 under Causation, rather than under Teleology ? 
 
 Kant thought it absurd even to hope that a Newton should 
 ever arise to explain organic life by physical causes ; but 
 Darwin has done much to explain the appearances of design 
 in plants and animals without resorting to Final Causes. The 
 theory of Natural Selection assumes that organisms vary in 
 every species ; that those unsuited to the conditions of life are 
 destroyed ; whilst those best suited survive, and transmit their 
 constitution to descendants, so that from generation to 
 generation there is an improvement in adaptation to the 
 conditions of life. But as the theory thus stated gives no 
 account of the origin either of the conditions that determine 
 the form of species, or of the variations which the conditions 
 select, it may be urged that at both these points there is room 
 for the intervention of design. Herder (in his Ideen z. Phil. 
 d. Geschichte d. Menschheit) suggested that the Earth had been 
 prepared as the scene of human life. In a popular book on 
 Astronomy, I have seen it taught that the remoter planets are 
 supplied with many moons because they receive so little light 
 from the sun. But with or without satellites, Saturnians, 
 being what the prepared circumstances determined, would 
 think it all for the best, and prefer a dim light, as more 
 favourable to love and meditation. For every living thing 
 necessarily approves of the conditions in which it flourishes ; 
 and, exerting the reflective understanding, naturally regards 
 them as providential. However, we can give some account of 
 our Earth to the close of the Tertiary Period without appealing 
 to Final Causes. 
 
 As for the direction of variations, so many germs perish 
 for one that survives, so many rapacious and treacherous types 
 prevail, that to us men (as Kant might say) the process seems 
 wasteful and merciless. To the charge of wastefulness it may 
 be replied, indeed, that to the Universe economy can be no 
 concern ; Kronos engulfs his children, and yet nihil in nihilum 
 
344 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 revertit. And if it be urged that even in the conservation of 
 matter, there is a degradation of energy, rejoinder may be 
 made that, if the Universe be finite, the power of work may 
 under certain conditions be restored ; whilst, if the Universe 
 be infinite, its powers must be inexhaustible. The last point, 
 however, cannot be pressed in the defence of Final Causes, if 
 Final Causes imply a system of the World ; for an ' infinite 
 system ' is a contradiction in terms. Moreover, the riches of 
 the World cannot really be any ground of justification against 
 the charge of wastefulness in the method of Natural Selection ; 
 the gravamen of which lies here, that such a wasteful process 
 is an unintelligent one. It is as if the potter should make 
 pots by the gross, and appoint 90 per cent to destruction. If 
 any plan be hidden in such work, how can it help the intelli- 
 gence of us men ? 
 
 The merciless character of organic evolution appears to us, 
 first, in reckless propagation, and the consequent destruction. 
 Every species is as prolific as it can be compatibly with the 
 development of its individuals ; and the deaths that ensue from 
 inanition, disease and violence, present a stupefying scene. 
 The best one can say for it is that, as life rises in the organic 
 scale, the death-rate declines. Yet even man still suffers 
 outrageously by violence, disease, inanition : the notion that 
 " Malthus's Law " no longer holds of civilised man is a 
 foolish delusion. But more sinister than the direct destruction 
 of life is the spectacle of innumerable species profiting by a life, 
 parasitic or predatory, at the expense of others. The parasites 
 refute the vulgar prejudice that evolution is, by the measure 
 of man, progressive ; adaptation is indifferent to better or 
 worse, except as to each species, that its offspring shall sur- 
 vive though by atrophy and degradation. The predatory 
 species flourish as if in derision of moral maxims : we see 
 that, though human morality is natm'al to man, it is far from 
 expressing the whole of Nature. Animals, at first indistin- 
 guishable from vegetables, devour them and enjoy a far richer 
 life. Animals that eat other animals are nearly always 
 superior not only in strength and grace and agility but in 
 intelligence. There are exceptions to this rule ; some snakes 
 
CATEGORIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 345 
 
 eat monkeys (thanking rrovidence), and the elephant is 
 content with foliage ; Uut compare cats and wolves with the 
 ungulates that make a first concoction of herbs for their sake. 
 It is true that our monkey kin are chiefly frugivorous; but 
 this leads to the worst case of all ; for it may be plausibly 
 argued that man was first differentiated by becoming definitely 
 carnivorous, a sociable hunter, as it were a wolf-ape. Hence 
 the advantage of longer legs, the use of weapons, the upright 
 gait and defter hands to use and make weapons, more strategic 
 brains, tribal organisation ; and hence liberation from the 
 tropical forest and citizenship of the world. The greater 
 part of his subsequent history is equally unedifying : having 
 made the world his prey, he says that God made the world to 
 that end ; and those who have preyed upon their fellows, and 
 enslaved them, and flourished upon it, have declared that to 
 have been the intention of Nature. Whose are the kingdoms 
 of this world ? Slowly, through humiliation and martyrdom, a 
 better life has emerged. 
 
 It would be excusable if, like Kant, one were not very 
 anxious to carry out the explanation of such a world by Final 
 Causes : it seems to labour under a curse and sigh for atone- 
 ment. But the hope persists that the sinister indications of 
 Nature may be evaded, and to that end such considerations as 
 follow are laid before us. In various forms, by Plato, Leibniz, 
 Mill, it is suggested that the evil aspect of Nature should be 
 explained by a certain limitation of power on the part of the 
 Artificer in relation to certain necessary conditions of existence ; 
 and this suggestion might be acceptable if the evil were always 
 a sort of weakness, failure and incapacity ; it may excuse the 
 parasites, if we forget their victims. But how can the limita- 
 tion of power account for the shark, the tiger, and Jenghis 
 Khan ; or for the display of ingenuity and technique being as 
 great in the cobra's fang as in the cow's udder ? It is sometimes 
 said, again, that we do not, indeed, understand the whole 
 purpose of Nature, but that we cannot reasonably expect it ; 
 or even (at hazard) that the Universe may not recognise our 
 code of morals. But such arguments will never do : the 
 doctrine of Final Causes is an attempt to explain Nature by 
 
346 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 what is most familiar in ourselves ; and it is a strange 
 inversion to defend the doctrine on the ground that it passes 
 all understanding. 
 
 The course of our discussion tends, in my judgment, to 
 impair one's confidence in the reality of Design in Nature, and 
 even in the desirability of tracing it there ; but by no means 
 excludes its possibility ; and to show its possibility seems (I 
 fear) to some friends of Final Causes all that is required of 
 them. But that is a great mistake ; if no more can be done, 
 the belief must grow every day more attenuated and ghostly. 
 If Teleology is still to command adherents there must be 
 built up a definite system of the Design in Nature, comparable 
 in extent, detail and coherence with the system of physical 
 Causation that daily gains in power and prestige ; and the 
 explanation by Final Causes must have the continuity of 
 thought, the conceivableness, if possible the imaginableness, of 
 scientific explanation. For example, if it is suggested that the 
 conditions of any species' life may have been prepared, or that 
 useful variations may have been predetermined, was the work 
 done by physical antecedents or by miraculous intervention ? 
 One's choice between these alternative methods should be 
 plainly stated ; and whichever of them be adopted, the " partic- 
 ular go of it " should be made quite clear. For my part, I 
 decide in favour of physical antecedents, and regard Kant's 
 suggestion that in the inwardness of Nature physical and final 
 Causation may be the same principle, as the only possible 
 way of reconciliation. 
 
 In a Divine Consciousness, to which all existence is equally 
 present, there can be no causation physical or final, no process, 
 no distinction of End and Means, since whatever is possible is 
 eternally known there and realised. Yet it is from the con- 
 ception of such a state of Being, which no power of speculation 
 has ever been able to connect with the temporal world of birth 
 and decay, that the notion of a vis afronte seems to have been 
 derived, a turning back of the effect upon its cause, and a 
 determination of Means by Ends ; for it has been supposed 
 that whatever End may be represented, it already exists in the 
 eternal world and energises there ; but as it exists as much as, 
 
CATEGORIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 347 
 
 and no more than, the Means, its efficacy is unintelligible. 
 The difficulties which such a conception imposes upon the 
 problems of Evil and Freedom are sufficiently well known ; 
 and so is the difficulty of understanding how the very notion 
 of an End as something desired, or represented as a better, can 
 be reconciled with it. 
 
 According to the views taken in this volume. Eternity is 
 not a State of Being, but Law ; and Eeality is essentially a 
 process in time, as witnessed by the nature of consciousness ; 
 and there is no incongruity in regarding such a process as 
 expressed amongst phenomena in space by Causation. But 
 Means and End, as distinguished from Cause and Effect, are 
 irreconcilable with the conceptions of transcendent Being that 
 have been established by the great Religions, excluding 
 from that region of thought such differences of value as are 
 implied in Means and End. It is true that in its popular- 
 isation Religion is never consistent ; on the other hand, 
 consistency leads to such obscurity of thought (be it even by 
 excess of light), that all meaning seems to disappear : and 
 between vacuity and contradiction the choice is hard. Spinoza's 
 identifying of existence with perfection is a stroke of rhetoric : 
 to complain of a man for indulging his turn for style once in 
 a hundred pages would be too exacting; but 'perfection' is a 
 term of praise ; and praise or blame of the Universe is equally 
 impertinent. And the same may be said of any estimate 
 we may form of a Divine Purpose from phenomena that 
 interest us. 
 
 Besides, every use of teleological categories depends upon 
 a partial abstraction ; for the means to any end are only known 
 to us by experience, and we can hardly suppose that the 
 Universe learns in that way ; that through a series of Great 
 Years it serves an apprenticeship, and, correcting the blundera 
 of its immaturity, staggers forward to some remote accomplish- 
 ment. If such an hypothesis threw some light upon what we 
 may think the failures of our present World, it would also 
 prevent our inferring anything as to the true purpose of it 
 all. These suggestions are only fit to be put into the mouth 
 of one's opponent in a Dialogue. 
 
348 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 A system of Teleology, iu which ends determined means, 
 and these other means, and so forth, would have the same 
 character of uniformity, us a physical system in which causes 
 determined effects and these in turn became causes : the alphabet 
 is the same whether we read it from Z to A or from A to Z : 
 Spinoza's determinism and Calvin's predeterminism alike 
 exclude every sort of accident, caprice and spontaneous 
 deviation or intervention. Apparently, therefore, we may 
 interpret the course of the World in either way. What hinders 
 us in doing so is, that physical causes are in any case 
 intelligible ; but final causes are not, unless they present some 
 analogy to human purposes. Now, in Nature many things 
 have no human purpose ; many others suggest purposes quite 
 inhuman ; hence we hesitate about the remainder. 
 
 Again, an end, in the full sense, is contradictory of an 
 infinite process ; but so it is in human life, where every end or 
 effect is only a transition to new means, or causes ; and death, 
 the terminus, is not regarded as the purpose of our existence. 
 Thus, even in an infinite process, the End of Being might be 
 manifested through the World, as known or divined by us, in 
 certain culminating epochs in the history of things ; and so 
 we might read the course of Nature, if it were possible to 
 accommodate our reason, or our feelings, to such a conception of 
 Being that the contemplation of an End could be ascribed to 
 it. Then the spectacle of evolution would suggest that the 
 end of existence is the development of consciousness : first 
 the life of feeling and sense, that grows into all the riches 
 of subjective emotion and objective quality and form ; then 
 the life of self-consciousness, culminating in science and philo- 
 sophy, the self-knowledge of the World. 
 
 Frankly, I wish it were possible to prove or make credible 
 the teleology of Nature, because we might then follow Aristotle 
 in identifying the End of Nature with the End of Humanity ; 
 but I cannot help feeling that the weight of argument is 
 against the doctrine of Final Causation. Like transcendent 
 Being, it remains a merely indicative, orectic Category. The 
 adaptation of organisms is a fact ; and so far as we can follow 
 the history of the World from age to age, its gradual rise to 
 
CATEGOIUES OF SURIECTIVE ACTIVITY 349 
 
 self-consciousness is a fact ; but the teleological interpretation 
 of all this baflles our understanding. We see the usual 
 conflict between recent conceptions of Causation and the ancient 
 Animism, with the usual result. Because our forefathers stood 
 nearer to the gods than we do, they had greater confidence in 
 interpreting their purposes. 
 
 § 4. Man, at any rate, is subject to want and desire, and 
 lives by the representation and partial realisation of ends ; and, 
 however it may be with the Universe, for the philosopher, its 
 ' secretary,' life is chiefly an effort after the fulness of under- 
 standing, as Ai-istotle declared, Spinoza assenting. To discover 
 the end or chief Good of human life is the central problem of 
 Ethics. It cannot, therefore, be a vain inquiry whether there 
 are ends in Nature, and whether they are to be realised 
 especially in Man ; for, if there be, to discover them must 
 necessarily be to discover his end also. As the power of 
 external causes is, as Spinoza says, greater than that of Man, 
 the pursuit of ends that Nature does not sanction must lead 
 to disaster : for every nation this is an instant truth. It is 
 clear that pleasure is not the end, but a means of guidance ; 
 nor riches, but a means of leisure ; nor virtue, but a means 
 of co-ordination and an incentive of enterprise. May we not 
 say the same of knowledge, and, like Bacon, view it as a means 
 to the reign of Man ? That cognition, as well as pleasure and 
 virtue, is a guide to action, cannot be denied ; and the 
 structure of the nervous system, in which every stimulus has 
 its reaction, strongly points to the intermediate place of 
 knowledge in the process of life. But it has already been 
 shown that the end of Nature, or of human life, cannot be a 
 terminus, but only a transition. Therefore, it does not follow 
 that action, because it is a result of cognition, is also its end 
 or Good ; and it seems impossible it should be so, seeing that 
 action is a fact of the body or phenomenon, whereas knowledge 
 belongs to Eeality. Our knowledge far exceeds our power of 
 utilising it ; and the proportion of theoretical to applied science 
 is not likely to decrease in the future; because the synthesis of 
 principles necessary to the employment of knowledge is far 
 more difficult than the analysis of events that leads to new 
 
350 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 discoveries. That many who engage earnestly in investigation 
 look for their reward to the utility of their results, — by 
 no means to themselves, perhaps, yet to mankind, — is compat- 
 ible enough with the supremacy of speculation, if we consider 
 how common illusion is in the desires and efforts of men, and 
 how widely the result often differs from the intention. Thus 
 the love of fame and of riches provides leadership and capital, 
 not merely personal but social goods ; and the desire of a 
 scientific investigator to be useful may have other consequences 
 than the cheapening of cotton-yarn and pig-iron. Besides, the 
 use of applied science is always to increase the efficiency of 
 labour ; and what is the use of that, unless it be to shorten 
 the hours of labour, and to give the workmen more leisure for 
 culture and reflection ? 
 
 But if self-knowledge be the end of Nature, or mental culture 
 the chief Good of every normal man, these ends are plainly 
 not so predominant as to exclude all others. To philosophise 
 is not every man's ruling passion. The attempt to set up 
 the same ideal for all men is one of the greatest errors of 
 philosophy. Social life is not to be understood except as 
 constituted by various species of men, — not merely ethnological 
 but moral species. The differentiation of the human stock 
 into such species is due (apart from ethnological causes) in a 
 superficial way to the division of labour, but more profoundly 
 to congenital differences of capacity and disposition. This was 
 recognised by Plato and Aristotle, but obscured by Stoicism 
 and other forces ; so that it may now seem pagan and invidious, 
 whereas it is merely humanity and common sense. The dif- 
 ferent species of men have different systems of desire and 
 activity ; and the lonum consummatum is the harmonious ful- 
 filment of all our ends. 
 
 To impose one ideal upon all men is an intolerable torture, 
 that never has been, and ought not to be, submitted to. 
 The notion that such a thing is possible seems due chiefly to 
 a confusion of Virtue with Innocence. There is a certain list 
 of abstinences, such as we are familiar with in the Decalogue, 
 to which every one is necessarily subject, because their neglect 
 is manifestly injurious to others, and, therefore, tends to the 
 
CATEGORIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 351 
 
 dissolutiou of Society. The observance of these abstinences 
 is Innocence. Because no more can be enforced by positive 
 law or opinion ; because so much, though attained by few, is 
 abstractly possible to all, and because false notions of equality 
 require that here, at least, the dififerences of men shall be 
 obliterated, this negative standard is exalted into an universal 
 Ideal. Then, because even this standard is beyond the 
 attainment of most people, whilst the social grounds of it are 
 also misunderstood, morbid men turn to asceticism ; because 
 it is easily imitated in behaviour, cunning men turn to 
 hypocrisy ; because it is mistaken for the limit of human 
 excellence, the compatibility of great virtue with imperfect 
 observance is often denied. 
 
 But the belief in one universal Ideal has another root in 
 the truth that the chief Good, Philosophy or Culture, may be 
 participated in some degree by all ; or, rather, that no society 
 is other than barbarous in which any normal man is precluded 
 from participation. Philosophy or Culture (as I say, to avoid 
 a limitation of the notion to merely technical discipline) is, in 
 the first place, the greatest Good in itself; in the second 
 place, it is the object of a strong and tutelary passion (by 
 Spinoza too much weighted), though in most men ill-nourished ; 
 but, in the third place, it enlightens and guides the other 
 passions, which, for good or evil, are the forces of life. With- 
 out such enlightenment even the noblest passions, such as 
 patriotism and justice, although they contain in themselves a 
 sort of instinctive rationality and guidance, may yet issue in 
 actions the most injurious and unjust. 
 
 Still, under oppressive industrialism and our present 
 division of labour, little culture is possible for the majority 
 even of civilised men ; and we present, in fact, so many types 
 of character and ability, that to preach the chief Good as the 
 universal Ideal would be a preaching to the winds. This 
 variety of types is well adapted to the division of labour ; and 
 the greatest happiness of each man (so far as it depends on 
 circumstances) is to obtain employment according to his own 
 nature. Then activity in his vocation (as it may then be 
 truly called) becomes the first trait of his ideal ; caring for 
 
352 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATUEE 
 
 honour more than for wealth, and more for achievement than 
 for honour ; to which must be added public spirit in relation 
 to the reforms that may ameliorate and civilise our life, 
 and affability in domestic and friendly intercourse, where the 
 instinctive rationality of the passions is most naturally 
 fostered. 
 
 It is possible that the future amelioration of human life, 
 of which the last generation was more confident than we are, 
 may at last establish an universal Ideal ; and, if so, a little 
 reflection will show any one that it can be no other than 
 Culture. But hitherto even individuals, who have formed 
 ideals and lived near them, have been very scarce ; and a 
 subjective ideal, constructed for oneself, is likely to be partial 
 and misleading, since it is only in long years of experience 
 that we can learn what manner of men we are. Probably the 
 safest course for nearly every one is (as Plato tells us) to rely 
 chiefly upon activity in one's own vocation. A truly rational 
 life, in which all actions were co-ordinated to one end, would 
 be for most of us worse than prison or a strait-waistcoat. 
 Our lives are like Nature, in which a purpose seems sometimes 
 clear, and many mechanical adaptations are traceable ; whilst 
 for many other things no reason can be given and none is asked. 
 
 § 5. Science, Philosophy, Culture depend upon social life ; 
 for Society is the co-operation of minds manifest in bodies 
 wliereby they have power over Nature ; and this power is 
 necessary to free us from primary wants, to give leisure for 
 reflection, and to provide the means of investigation. In 
 society men appear as co-operative, yet in mutual opposition, 
 and order appears as an equilibrium of conflicting forces. 
 Hence the individual may suppose that his own realisation 
 in happiness, or virtue, or knowledge, is the end, at least for 
 him. But this delusion is dissipated by clearer insight. For 
 tlie subordination of the individual and the unity of the World 
 are indicated not only by industrial and social division of 
 functions, by the absolute dependence of every man upon his 
 fellow, and by sympathy and imitation ; but still more by the 
 biological evidence, that each of us is to organic Nature only 
 as a bud upon an ever-living tree. For in time all life is 
 
CATEGORIES OF SUBJECTIVE ACTIVITY 353 
 
 continuous, aud this is the form of Reality ; whereas the 
 separation aud opposition of men is a phenomenon of bodies 
 in space. It is true that social life provides the conditions of 
 greater individual development ; only in society is it possible 
 to secure method, and continuity in labour, and some approach 
 to the rationalising of one's own life under one end, and there- 
 fore integrity of character and systematisation of thought. 
 And how otherwise than through individuals can speculation 
 flourish ? But social services are reciprocal and interdependent ; 
 the development of character embraces public interests, and the 
 expansion of speculative thought has that universal significance 
 which I have indicated. 
 
 The growth of societies, the taming of mankind, the over- 
 coming of tribal isolation, the establishment of industry, — a 
 long and miserable story, is now being deciphered. The 
 primitive customary life of wandering tribes was gradually 
 superseded by the organisation of governments, which obtained 
 a formal unity for the people, partly by fear, partly by utility, 
 partly by loyalty ; largely by imaginative fictions (not unin- 
 formed with truth), such as the embodiment of the people in 
 the king, and (more powerful) his affiliation to the gods. 
 Polity could never have succeeded without Religion and the 
 immortal gods, who united generation to generation, who pro- 
 tected the laws even against kings, whose legends served for 
 history and philosophy, whose kinship drew mankind from 
 their brutal neighbours, who knew what was done in secret 
 and read the heart. In no other way could Morality have 
 been distinguished from Observance than by conscience of that 
 which the gods and no others knew. Thus the current of life 
 was traced to that secret fountain which is the witness of the 
 reality of Nature and of Man. 
 
 We must not forget or disguise the hideousness of most of 
 this story : worse, had it not been transfigured by poetry and 
 song and the plastic Arts, that have helped to humanise the 
 gods and to deify mankind. But greater has been the power, 
 indefinable and indescribable, of social and moral development, 
 that has slowly moralised government aud religion and liberated 
 private life. Though industry and the growth of reflection 
 
 28 
 
354 THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURE 
 
 have served us well, there is more in human history than our 
 own efforts and designs. Pestilence and famine have not been 
 useless allies ; and who shall say whether we owe more to 
 institutions, or to the destruction of those nations whose 
 institutions were or became perverse ? For in government 
 and religion there is a natural tendency to parasitism ; in 
 their growth they often strangle the people they had formerly 
 sustained. Only those constitutions can be always good that 
 train the individual to live by the law and inspiration of his 
 own heart. The essential changes in our life are the gradual 
 realisation in politics and religion of freedom to act and think ; 
 the growth of moral courage, and of the co-operative spirit 
 that makes authority needless ; and the increase of that 
 scientific enlightenment which, by giving control of physical 
 forces, makes possible the diffusion of leisure and culture, and 
 even if these be rejected by us, unworthy and bent upon 
 getting anything rather than understanding, still has its own 
 value and its own career, self-determined, disinterested, and 
 inevitable. 
 
 THE END 
 
 Pfinteii by R. Si R. Clark, Limited, Edinburgh. 
 
Demy 8vo. Cloth. Price Vs. 6d. net. 
 
 THE 
 
 GEAMMAK OF SCIENCE 
 
 BY 
 
 KAKL PEARSON, M.A., LL.B., F.E.S. 
 
 PROFESSOR OF APPLIED MATHEMATICS AND MECHANICS 
 DNIVER8ITT COLLEGE, LONDON 
 
 SECOND EDITION, REVISED AND ENLARGED, 
 WITH 33 FIGURES IN THE TEXT 
 
 SCOPE OF THE BOOK 
 
 This work attempts to give a philosophical basis to the fundamental principles 
 of modem science. It assumes no special mathematical or biological training on 
 the part of the reader, but endeavours to lay before the man with average 
 education an intelligible account of what science professes to achieve and of what 
 it does not. The fii-st four chapters define the material and lay down the 
 principles of all scientific reasoning ; they explain the scope, methods, and hopes 
 of science and its relation to our theory of life. The following four chapters 
 discuss the axioms and piinciples of physical science, and endeavour to give _a 
 rational view of mechanism which is not open to the criticisms raised against it 
 by Balfour, Ward, and other recent metaphysical wi'iters. The next three 
 chapters deal with the science of organic forms, discussing the principal factors 
 of evolution and endeavouring to give them exact quantitative definition. The 
 two chapters on evolution place before the reader the present position of the 
 Danvinian theory, at the same time indicating the futility of recent reactionary 
 attacks. The final chapter deals with the classification of the sciences, and 
 gives a bird's-eye view of the fields wherein the specialist alone can work. 
 
 SOME PRESS OPINIONS 
 
 " It would be impossible within the limits of a notice like the present to do justice 
 to the lucidity of Prof. Pearson's explanations, tlie ingenuity of his mathematical 
 devices, and the care with which he has avoided possible sources of error in his 
 calculations. " — Nature. 
 
 " Not the least interesting part of this powerful book is the discussion of the effect 
 on the mind of a true scientific education, which enables a man or woman to form 
 judgments freed from individual bias. . . . We recommend all readers, and especially 
 scientists, metaphysicians, theologians, and last, but not least, the ^vriters of scientific 
 tert-books, to read and digest this well-written, clearly reasoned description of what 
 science and scientific method is." — Pall Mall Gazette. 
 
 " It is still a grammar in that it deals with the foundations of science ; but a far 
 more ambitious title might have been given to so comprehensive a work." — Bookman. 
 
 ADAM AND CHARLES BLACK, SOHO SQUARE, LONDON, W. 
 
Demy 8vo. Cloth. 448 pp. Price 7s. 6d. net. 
 
 THE 
 
 ETHIC OF FEEETHOUGHT 
 
 AND 
 
 OTHER ADDRESSES AND ESSAYS 
 
 BY 
 
 KAEL PEARSON, M.A., LL.B., F.E.S. 
 
 FORMERLY FELLOW OF KING'S COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE ; PROFESSOR OF APPLIED 
 MATHEMATICS AND MECHANICS, UNIVERSITY COLLEGE, LONDON 
 
 SECOND EDITION {REVISED) 
 
 The aim of the book is to contrast the emotional and rationalistic treatments 
 of philosophical and social problems ; to show how the enthusiasm of the study 
 is a real factor of human development, and how the slow and gradual educa- 
 tional work of the thinker is after all more permanent than the emotional 
 influence of the market-place. The author would allow no social or religious 
 problem to lie outside the legitimate field of discussion, but he believes that any 
 profitable answer can only be found in a rational treatment of history — that all 
 great social changes can only be advantageous if based on a slow educational 
 reform of current ideas. 
 
 SOME PRESS OPINIONS 
 
 " The same clear mind that Mr. Pearson devotes to the stellar system he brings to 
 bear on the social phenomena of modern life. This is where lies the most valuable 
 portion of his work. He approaches all subjects of a social nature with absolute 
 fearlessness, and yet with consummate tact. He declines to allow that any social 
 or religious problem lies outside the legitimate field of discussion, and the problems 
 that he handles are among the most vital for the well-being and sanity of the race." — 
 Pall Mall Gazette. 
 
 " It is an able volume, to be studied by all who would know the modern apologetics 
 of freethought." — The Academy. 
 
 ADAM AND CHARLES BLACK, SOHO SQUARE, LONDON, W. 
 
THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE 
 STAMPED BELOW 
 
 AN INITIAL PINE OP 25 CENTS 
 
 WILL BE ASSESSED FOR FAILnot -r 
 THIS BOOK ON THE nAXnTI^. ^ ^° RCTURN 
 
 WILL INCREASE I" .^^^°"^- "^^E PENALTY 
 DAY AND TO sloo o''^'"'"^ °'' ^"^ "^O^RTH 
 OVERDUE * °° °'' ■'"^ SEVENTH DAY 
 
 Ill^Ji 
 
 NOV 2 81< 
 
 i 1' 
 
 •D L 
 
 ''"'■^' Ijii 
 
 JiL^l^ie Ki PM 
 
s^' .