THE SCIENCE SERIES. 
 
 1. The Study of Man. By A. C. HADDON. 
 
 2. The Groundwork of Science. By ST. GEORGE 
 
 MIVART. 
 
 3. Rivers of North America. By ISRAEL C. RUS- 
 
 SELL. 
 
 G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS, NEW YORK & LONDON 
 
ZTbe Science Series 
 
 EDITED BY 
 
 professor 3. QbcTkecn Gattell, /TO.H., pb.H). 
 
 THE GROUNDWORK OF 
 SCIENCE 
 
THE GROUNDWORK 
 OF SCIENCE S2 
 
 A STUDY OF EPISTEMOLOGY 
 
 BY 
 
 ST. GEORGE MIVART 
 
 V 4 
 
 M.D., PH.D., F.R.S. 
 
 NEW YORK 
 
 G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS 
 
 LONDON 
 
 BLISS, SANDS, & CO. 
 1898 
 
COPYRIGHT, 1898 
 
 BY 
 G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS 
 
 ftnicfterbocfeer preas, Hew li;orb 
 
PREFACE 
 
 WE have again and again been impressed by the ready 
 disposition of men whose views and opinions are 
 most opposed, to agree in accepting as certain, things which 
 are by no means evident, and in adopting conclusions as 
 proved, which are by no means the only consequences that 
 follow from conceded premisses. Our great object, there- 
 fore, in this little volume, is to represent nothing as certain 
 which does not appear to us to be really evident, and yet 
 not to shrink from upholding as true whatever, in our judg- 
 ment, possesses the highest conceivable evidence. 
 
 It has been our constant care to be impartial and, above 
 all, to allow no consideration not purely scientific no an- 
 ticipations as to possible consequences to influence us in 
 the conclusions which our judgment has led us to form. 
 Our appeal throughout has been to the dry light of reason, 
 and to that alone. Not so to act; to allow any kind of 
 prejudice, any non-scientific consideration, to influence us 
 in such a task as an endeavour to investigate the ground- 
 work of science, would be both treason to science and a 
 betrayal of the cause of philosophy. 
 
 But it is possible that to some persons the title of this book 
 may prove a rock of offence, namely, persons disposed to 
 doubt whether its object can be by any possibility attain- 
 able. " Is there," they may ask, " anything which can 
 really merit the name of a ' groundwork of science ' ; and, 
 
iv PREFACE 
 
 should there be such a thing, can a knowledge of it be really 
 attainable by us ? " 
 
 To this question the answer appears to be that some 
 groundwork of science there must be. For no one can deny 
 that science exists, and this is obtrusively evident in our own 
 time, when we are witnessing the closing days of an age 
 which has been conspicuous beyond all others for scientific 
 progress. Now, any science which we may select for con- 
 sideration will be found to consist of some truths which are 
 the results of other truths antecedently ascertained, whether 
 the latter have served as incentives to more patient and 
 careful observations and experiments, or whether the ante- 
 cedent truths have served as premisses from which the newer 
 truths have been logically inferred. These primitive and 
 fundamental truths of the science selected, together with the 
 efforts made to ascertain and establish them, must be allowed 
 to form the groundwork of that particular science. And as 
 every science must possess such primitive and fundamental 
 truths, there must be a groundwork of science generally, 
 even if it consists only of a collection of all the fundamental 
 truths of all the several sciences. 
 
 But can there be one common groundwork for all the 
 sciences from logic to geology, however diverse may be their 
 several subject-matters ? It might be supposed that such 
 there cannot be, the sciences being so numerous and diverse. 
 Nevertheless, there is one point which is common to them 
 all. However numerous and diverse the sciences may be, 
 they all agree in having been developed by one kind of 
 energy, namely, that of the human mind. And, indeed, 
 after putting on one side all the differences which have 
 arisen from diversities of culture (qualitative and quanti- 
 tative), of energy, and of industry, there is a general and 
 fundamental unity in human capacity. The sciences there- 
 fore being many and diverse, while the nature of the energy 
 
PREFACE v 
 
 applied to their investigation is essentially one, it is evident 
 that the groundwork of science must be sought in the human 
 mind, and in the mind of each individual man who applies 
 himself to its study the study of Epistemology. 1 
 
 Now the mind of each one of us is, during our waking 
 hours, ceaselessly active, but active in very different ways. 
 We may be vaguely conscious of our existence while 
 listening to some sweet melody' which entrances us with its 
 charm. We may be enjoying the freshness of the air and 
 the augmenting brightness of the sun of a summer's day, 
 hardly aware of undefined thoughts passing through our 
 mind. We may be anxiously longing for the arrival of a 
 friend whom we impatiently expect, or dreading the delay 
 in his arrival as foreboding evil. We may be dwelling in 
 fancy over events of days gone by, or looking forward to the 
 future fruition of a hope long entertained. We may be 
 simultaneously applying our senses of sight and touch to as- 
 certain the shape and structure of some material object a 
 feather, a shell, or a work of art. We may be carrying out 
 a piece of deductive reasoning, or we may be reflecting upon 
 what we are about, and making sure we know, suspect, or 
 doubt what we are actually cognising, suspecting, or doubt- 
 ing. But if we happen to be engaged in the study and 
 pursuit of science, we must be aware of what we are doing, 
 and, at least occasionally, reflect upon our perceptions. 
 
 Therefore, once more, the groundwork of science must be 
 sought for in the human mind in our own mind when 
 cognising scientific truths; especially those deemed most 
 certain and far-reaching. And such truths cannot be truths 
 obtained by reasoning, and cannot depend for their certainty 
 on any experiments or observations alone. Such is mani- 
 festly the case, since whatever truth depends on reasoning 
 cannot be ultimate, but must be posterior to, and depend 
 
 /, understanding, and AoyoS, a discourse. 
 
vi PREFACE 
 
 upon, the principles, experiments, or observations which 
 show us that it is indeed true, and upon which its accept- 
 ance thus depends ; while the reflex certainty of observations 
 and experiments themselves also implies the recognition 
 of fundamental intellectual perceptions. Therefore, the 
 groundwork of science must be composed of facts and of 
 truths which carry with them their own evidence which 
 are self-evident together with our own mental activity in 
 reflecting upon and recognising such propositions as being 
 the self-evident truths they are. Amongst such truths (as 
 we shall hereafter see) must be that of our continued exist- 
 ence from day to day, and the certainty that we cannot at 
 the same time continue to exist and yet cease to be, with 
 others of similar nature. Such truths, it will be sought to 
 show, cannot be really doubted without mental paralysis 
 and self-stultification, for complete scepticism, as absolutely 
 and necessarily self-destructive, is impossible for us. This 
 assertion our readers are now asked to accept provisionally 
 for what it may be worth, as full treatment of this and 
 kindred subjects will find its place in the eighth chapter. 
 They cannot be fully treated earlier, because before begin- 
 ning to consider those fundamental questions, regarded as 
 most essential elements of the groundwork of science, the 
 way must be cleared for their due appreciation by a prelim- 
 inary consideration of the various intellectual structures (the 
 sciences) the foundations common to the whole of which 
 it is the purpose of this book to point out. 
 
 At the commencement, therefore, it appears incumbent 
 on us, after considering what science is and of what it must 
 consist, to call attention to certain elementary facts and dis- 
 tinctions without which it seems impossible to follow up any 
 intellectual inquiry: such facts, e. g., are (in our opinion) 
 the essential nature both of our ideas and the words we 
 make use of to express them. 
 
PREFA CE vii 
 
 Obviously, without an adequate acquaintance with the 
 nature of our ideas no one can hope to succeed in a task an 
 important part of which consists in the analysis of mental 
 conceptions. What factors, therefore, co-operate in their 
 elicitation, and the nature of such factors, the shares they 
 respectively take, and the rank of each in ideation, are 
 preliminary matters which must be noted at the very com- 
 mencement of this book. Similarly, no one can arrive at 
 even a provisional conclusion with respect to any merely 
 initial problem unless he can be satisfied that there is some 
 criterion of truth and that he can avail himself of it. To 
 these first steps towards an understanding of the ground- 
 work of science, the earlier portion of this book must, it 
 appears to us, be exclusively devoted. 
 
 But in order to explore the groundwork of all science, it 
 seems reasonable that the reader's attention should also be 
 called to the different kinds of systematic and organised in- 
 quiry the different sciences about which men's minds have 
 been hitherto occupied their number, nature, and the 
 various degrees of affinity and relationship existing between 
 them, etc. But before we can take another step forwards 
 we shall find our progress arrested by the idealists. It is 
 true that we hear it said that all the physical sciences can 
 be pursued and taught as well on the idealistic hypothesis, 
 as on that view concerning a real, external, independent 
 world existing on all sides, which is entertained by all men 
 who are not idealists. This we regard as true for one reason 
 only : the reason, namely, that nature is too strong for ideal- 
 ism, and that no man can be always a consistent idealist, 
 least of all students and adepts in physical science, who are 
 continually recognising in thought and speech, and are con- 
 stantly occupied about, certain bodies acting and interacting 
 upon other bodies, not only quite without regard to their 
 own perceptions (which need not be adverted to as being 
 
viii PREFACE 
 
 such), but with an implied perception of substantial exist- 
 ences, underlying and utterly different from any plexuses 
 of feelings. If we shall be compelled to admit that ideal- 
 ism is true, we shall have to admit also that the groundwork 
 of science is indeed mental, in a very different sense from 
 that in which we and most other men have taken it to be. 
 Moreover, for our own part, we should then feel that the 
 authority and certainty of other seemingly self-evident 
 truths were gravely compromised, especially if a truth ap- 
 parently so self-evident as the existence of our own body 
 (as we and most men understand that body to exist) were 
 but a delusion and self-deception of the mind. But al- 
 though, even then, the most fundamental truths of all 
 would still, for us, remain evident and unimpaired in their 
 certainty, it nevertheless appears to us to be incumbent on 
 anyone who desires to study Epistemology, to enter upon a 
 serious inquiry as to the truth of idealism. 
 
 An inquiry respecting a system which has been adopted, 
 and is maintained, by so many men of eminence, not only 
 in philosophy but in physical science also, can evidently be 
 no light task; yet it must be undertaken and idealism ac- 
 cepted or rejected before further progress is possible. If 
 such an inquiry were neglected the groundwork of science 
 would, we think, have to remain for the student a problem 
 unsolved and (till this has been finally decided one way or 
 the other) insoluble. 
 
 The inquirer, having become once convinced of the real 
 existence of an external independent world of " things in 
 themselves " should, we think, have his attention next 
 called to the modes and methods wherewith science deals 
 with the objects it investigates, in order to ascertain, as far 
 as he may, what assumptions and convictions are implied in, 
 and by, and are necessary for, all and any scientific research. 
 This appears to us a desirable, if not an absolutely neces- 
 
PREFA CE i x 
 
 sary, preliminary, because assumptions and convictions 
 which are indispensable for the carrying on of science must 
 be more or less closely connected with the groundwork 
 thereof. Such an introductory inquiry, however, should, 
 we think, be made only in order to ascertain what are the 
 necessary implications of science, the question as to the 
 objective truth of such necessary implications finding its 
 place (as before said) later on, namely, towards the climax 
 of our inquiry. These implications cannot but be very 
 nearly related to questions concerning our highest mental 
 faculties. Such must be the case, since science, in the 
 widest sense of that word (including even the science of 
 sciences, or metaphysics), requires for its satisfactory pro- 
 secution the employment of our very noblest powers, and it 
 is by them alone that we can hope to attain a knowledge of 
 the most supreme and ultimate truths which our intellectual 
 faculties have the power to apprehend. 
 
 On this account, before entering upon our final inquiry as 
 to what it is which constitutes the groundwork of science, 
 we must study the nature and power of what seem to be our 
 highest faculties; but this we cannot usefully proceed to 
 do till we have taken cognisance of our ordinary mental 
 powers, upon the pre-existence and exercise of which the 
 possibility of such higher faculties depends. But, again, it 
 is obvious that our ordinary mental powers, our emotions, 
 our feelings, and the actions which thence result, are abso- 
 lutely dependent on our bodily capacities, and our bodily 
 powers are not less entirely dependent upon our corporeal 
 structure. 
 
 Therefore, in order duly to comprehend our highest in- 
 tellectual faculties, we needs must begin with a consideration 
 of at least some points in the construction of the human 
 body especially that of such parts as minister to feeling in 
 general, and to our special senses, such as sight and hearing. 
 
X PREFACE 
 
 But to appreciate what the human body is, it is necessary, 
 since nothing can be understood by itself, to learn some- 
 thing also about other animals, so that we may know what 
 is the place occupied in nature by that living body of ours 
 which possesses powers and attributes so wonderful. But a 
 mere study of structure of anatomy can serve but to 
 supply us with a knowledge of the material elements indis- 
 pensable to human thought and feeling. We must also, 
 therefore, acquire some knowledge as to how the various 
 parts and organs of the body act during its life, and how 
 that life is maintained, how the body is formed and nour- 
 ished, and how, if need be, injuries that it may suffer are 
 repaired. The living energy of the body, apart from the 
 feelings and sentiments to which it may give rise, requires 
 to be understood in a certain degree before we advance to 
 the consideration of our feelings and sentiments themselves. 
 Such an elementary acquaintance with both anatomy and 
 physiology will serve to pave the way for our entrance upon 
 the first stage of our proper subject, namely, the study of 
 the human mind in its ultimate pursuit of science. In the 
 first stage of this psychological inquiry, it will be necessary 
 to consider what our own intellect tells us concerning the 
 various kinds and orders of psychical activity whereof our 
 total mental life is made up. It is evidently desirable to 
 ascertain what, if any, psychical activities besides sensation 
 are most closely connected therewith, what are most allied 
 in nature to our unconscious energies, and whether by the 
 aid of reflection, memory, and inference, we can detect the 
 existence of psychical states of which we were unconscious 
 when they were being actually carried on. Evidently, it will 
 also be desirable to ascertain, if possible, whether in the 
 absence of consciousness we possess any other central and 
 unifying psychical faculty, and, if so, what are its utmost 
 powers and capabilities. Very special attention also needs 
 
PREFACE 
 
 XI 
 
 to be given to the consideration of the phenomena of 
 instinct. 
 
 But as idealists appear to bar the way to what, for all but 
 themselves, can alone lead to a satisfactory Epistemology, so 
 a distinguished school of naturalists oppose an analogous, 
 though very different, obstacle to our even entertaining a 
 reasonable hope that we may be able to see and comprehend 
 what are and must be the foundations of science. 
 
 What confidence, it has been asked, can we place in the 
 declaration of an ape's mind ? Now we by no means admit 
 that were the human intellect and the highest powers of 
 brutes really of one kind (so that the essential rationality of 
 animals was simply restrained by circumstances from making 
 itself manifest), any valid ground for distrusting truths, 
 which to us are self-evident, would thence arise. On the 
 contrary, instead of giving us good reasons for such distrust, 
 it would but supply us with an amply sufficient motive for 
 an enormously increased regard for what we might certainly 
 then, with reason, call our " poor relations." What seems 
 to us to be clear and indisputably evident in and by itself, 
 and what reason demonstrates absolutely, can be none the 
 less true on account of its cause and origin, or the mode in 
 which it may have become manifest. It is plain that in our 
 own case the truths which are for us most certain must 
 have been gained through the evolution and development 
 s of psychical power latent in the mind of an unconscious in- 
 fant, which once showed no sign whatever of rationality. 
 Why then should we distrust the dictates of a mind evolved 
 from creatures which, though giving no evidence of actual 
 rationality, afford us far more signs of cognitive energy than 
 does the child for some time after its birth ? 
 
 Nevertheless, since there are so many persons who do feel 
 a sceptical distrust of their reason on account of the source 
 from whence they believe it to have had its origin, it will, 
 
xii PREFACE 
 
 we think, be most advisable to consider carefully the ques- 
 tion whether or not there seems to be a difference of kind 
 between the highest psychical energy found present in the 
 brute and the intellect of man. This is simply a question 
 of fact. 
 
 Now, since man certainly possesses, besides his intellect, 
 the sensitivity, faculty of sense-association, desires, emo- 
 tions, instincts, and powers of emotional manifestation with 
 which the higher animals are endowed, it will be incumbent 
 on us to ascertain whether man's lower mental faculties, with- 
 out the exercise of conscious intellect, will not suffice to ex- 
 plain all the various more or less intelligent actions which 
 mere animals display. Should such turn out to be the case, 
 and should both the positive and negative evidence concern- 
 ing rationality concur in affirming that there is no need to 
 attribute intellect to animals, then it must be admitted that 
 a difference of kind is thereby demonstrated to exist be- 
 tween them and ourselves. But there is one other question 
 which requires very special care in its examination. It is 
 plain that, as a rule, all men speak while animals are dumb. 
 A special consideration is therefore demanded for language. 
 If it should prove that we have two sets of faculties (higher 
 and lower), have we also two corresponding modes of ex- 
 pression ? It is plain that we and animals make signs. It 
 will be necessary, therefore, carefully to inquire and distin- 
 guish as to what a sign really is, and, if there are different 
 kinds of signs, what relation they bear to the intellect ? It 
 will be further most necessary to examine the relations which 
 exist between gestures and vocal expressions, and, above all, 
 the relations which both of these bear to thought and to the 
 faculty of forming and communicating abstract ideas, and 
 the perception of relations as such. But that we may not, 
 through neglect, underestimate the psychical powers of 
 animals, it will be well to pass in review some of the more 
 
PREFACE xiii 
 
 striking anecdotes of animal intelligence in both the lower 
 and higher classes of the animal kingdom. Remarkably 
 divergent forms of speech of both infants and savages would 
 likewise seem to require some notice, as also the question as 
 to the origin of speech. 
 
 If the result of this somewhat prolonged inquiry should be 
 a conviction that between the highest psychical powers of 
 men and animals there is a difference of kind a difference 
 absolute and not consisting of degrees of difference it 
 would then be a question whether such a breach of con- 
 tinuity, such a new departure, stands alone, or whether there 
 are others, analogous sudden interruptions, to be met with 
 in nature ? If we become convinced that it is an unques- 
 tionable fact that there are other breaches of continuity 
 such, for example, as between the inorganic and organic 
 worlds and between insentient and sentient organisms then 
 a priori probability will become thereby established in favour 
 of a breach of continuity between merely sentient animality 
 and the rational animality of man. 
 
 All these introductory inquiries (as to the conditions nec- 
 essary for the existence of science; as to idealism ; as to 
 what science implies ; as to both physical and psychical 
 antecedents of science; and as to the place in nature of the 
 human intellect) having been disposed of, we shall next have 
 to examine into our own highest intellectual powers. In 
 beginning that examination, existing circumstances, and 
 the prevalent prejudices of the day, compel us expressly 
 to consider the bearing upon our estimate as to the rank 
 and value of our own mental powers, of the widely ac- 
 cepted doctrine of " natural selection." If we come to 
 recognise that we are in the possession of self-evident 
 truths which could never have given their possessors an 
 improved chance of survival, then it is clear that our 
 apprehension of such truths could never have been gained 
 
xiv PREFA CE 
 
 by " natural selection," but must be altogether independ- 
 ent thereof. 
 
 But it is evidently necessary, in order to decide this ques- 
 tion, that we should be acquainted with those of our powers 
 which we might expect to be least dependent on " natural 
 selection," and for this it will be necessary to revert (once 
 more, and more fully) to the questions of certainty and of 
 what must be, if anything can be, its criterion. This, again, 
 will necessarily lead us to examine more carefully the pos- 
 sible self-evidence of propositions, the knowledge of our 
 own existence, and the trustworthiness of memory as vouch- 
 ing for such existence in the past. 
 
 Then, also, if we conclude jt to be true that we can know 
 objects of knowledge as they exist objectively (or in them- 
 selves) the problem of the special relation which must, in 
 that case, exist between " subject " and " object," will 
 have to be investigated. The decision of this question will 
 naturally lead us to a further investigation of first principles 
 underlying all our reasoning, what they are, and whether 
 we can attain to an evident and logical adjustment of truths. 
 Amongst the most important of such principles, and one 
 about which the most vigorous disputations have taken 
 place, is the principle of causation. The truth and validity 
 of this principle, if it can once be established, have evidently 
 most important consequences bearing upon the cause and 
 origin of our own intuitions, and upon the existence, quali- 
 ties, and powers of the entire cosmos. Here the theory of 
 " natural selection " again courts our notice ; and its 
 bearing on the living world will have to be considered in 
 the light derived from that far larger and more enduring 
 world, which is inorganic and lifeless. The question con- 
 cerning the significance of human faculty as a part of the 
 universe will come next, and bring to a conclusion all but 
 the main question to be dealt with. 
 
PREFACE XV 
 
 When, in our final chapter, we have to apply ourselves 
 directly to that main question, in the light derived from the 
 various preceding investigations, the groundwork of science 
 will, we are persuaded, be found to consist of three divisions : 
 the labourers who work, the tools they must employ, and 
 that which constitutes the field of their labour. Taking 
 the last first, it will, we think, appear that the matter of 
 science is partly physical and partly psychical. In relation 
 with the former, questions concerning the various physical 
 energies, matter, motion, space, and time must be noted, 
 and an inquiry made as to the value of a mechanical theory 
 of the universe, and the reasons why it is so commonly ac- 
 ceptable. Next must come some reference to the tools 
 which must be made use of, namely, those first principles 
 and universal, necessary, self-evident truths which lie, so 
 frequently unnoticed, within the human intellect, and which 
 are absolutely indispensable for valid reasoning. Finally, 
 the nature of the workers themselves must also be noticed, 
 as necessarily affecting the value of their work; and, last of 
 all, a few words must be devoted to the question whether 
 there is any, and, if any, what, foundation underlying the 
 whole groundwork of science, and giving support and 
 validity to that entire conception of the universe which an 
 impartial study of the phenomena it exhibits may have led 
 us to regard as alone consonant with the dictates of reason. 
 
 ST. G. M. 
 
CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 PREFACE .'''''... . . . iii 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 INTRODUCTORY 
 
 CHAPTER II 
 AN ENUMERATION OF THE SCIENCES 16 
 
 CHAPTER III 
 
 \ \ 
 
 THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 34 
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 89 
 
 CHAPTER V 
 THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE ...... 108 
 
 CHAPTER VI 
 THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE ..... 137 
 
 CHAPTER VII 
 
 LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE . 186 
 
xviii CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 CHAPTER VIII 
 INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE . . . . .215 
 
 CHAPTER IX 
 CAUSES 'OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 255 
 
 CHAPTER X 
 THE NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE .... 296 
 
THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
THE 
 GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 IN TROD UCTOR Y 
 
 THE century now so near its close has been distinguished 
 from all preceding centuries by the rapid, varied, and 
 continuous progress in science that it has witnessed. An 
 interest in, and a real love for, science have by degrees 
 ceased to be confined to a limited society of experts, and 
 have happily become diffused far and wide amongst all 
 classes of society. 
 
 The scientific spirit is, above all, an inquiring spirit. It 
 can never rest satisfied with what has become known, but 
 must ever press on in all directions into fields of truth yet 
 unexplored, and even seek to ascend into regions commonly 
 deemed inaccessible to human research. But the results of 
 these praiseworthy endeavours, however successful they may 
 be, cannot by themselves fully satisfy the scientific mind. 
 It is not only the phenomena surrounding us which demand 
 exploration. Reason cannot be satisfied until it has probed, 
 to the utmost of its power, the depths of science itself, and 
 either ascertained what is and must be its ultimate founda- 
 
2 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 tions, or assured itself that such fundamental knowledge is 
 beyond the scope and power of human endeavour. 
 
 It is not enough for the true man of science to be ac- 
 quainted with many sciences, and to reflect on the know- 
 ledge he so possesses. The rational mind sooner or later 
 seeks to know what is the basis of his own knowledge and 
 the ultimate groundwork of all science. It thus calls for a 
 science of science, and cannot rest satisfied without a pur- 
 suit of Epistemology, or the study of the grounds of all the 
 learning the mind of man can acquire. 
 
 It is an attempt to satisfy this rational desire to which the 
 present volume is devoted. Such an attempt appears to us 
 greatly needed at the present time when every branch of 
 science is rapidly becoming more and more subdivided. 
 For the fact of that very subdivision makes a comprehensive 
 contemplation of science and of nature, as one whole, both 
 more and more difficult, and also more and more requisite 
 for the satisfaction of the intellect. 
 
 Epistemology is a product of mental maturity, individual 
 and racial ; but, sooner or later, a demand for it is inevitable, 
 while the attainment of a satisfactory response to that de- 
 mand is not only a thing to be pursued for its own sake, but 
 will be found an aid to the study of every separate science 
 and an introduction to them all. This science of the 
 grounds and groundwork of science is one to the study of 
 which gifted minds are spontaneously impelled, as ordinary 
 minds are impelled to acquire at least the rudiments of 
 ordinary scientific truth. For all men (not congenitally de- 
 fective) are, in fact, forced by a natural and spontaneous 
 impulse to seek and to acquire some knowledge. To most, 
 knowledge is pleasurable, while many pursue it with passion, 
 and find in its possession a perennial source of happiness. 
 
 Amongst the latter are to be found men of the noblest 
 minds; for though right action, rather than right thinking, 
 
IN TR OD UC TOR Y 3 
 
 constitutes the highest human activity, yet the will cannot 
 act with good effect unless the intellect be first sufficiently 
 informed. 
 
 The earliest known ages of man's existence have afforded 
 us pictorial evidence of some endeavour after knowledge, 
 while the relics of Egypt, Babylon, and China speak plainly 
 of its deliberate and systematic pursuit. 
 
 But an ordered, systematic pursuit of knowledge is 
 " science " ; for " science " is but the careful and exact ap- 
 plication of ordinary reason and good sense to the examina- 
 tion of any object we seek, as best we may, to understand. 
 The endeavour thus to obtain the most complete knowledge 
 possible about any subject of investigation, whatever it may 
 be, constitutes the highest form of science, for it necessitates 
 the study of Epistemology. 
 
 When we first deliberately and reflectively survey the 
 world about us, we may well be appalled by the immense 
 variety of objects and activities which on every side seem to 
 solicit our attention. Striking differences, however, be- 
 tween many of these become at once obvious, and, little by 
 little, they are found to arrange themselves in groups ac- 
 cording to their apparent degrees of likeness and unlikeness. 
 Such groups roughly correspond with those various branches 
 of human inquiry which have grown into distinct yet con- 
 nected systems of ordered knowledge, familiarly known as 
 so many different sciences. Among them are the sciences 
 which deal with the celestial bodies ; with the earth, its 
 structure and formation; with the multitudinous tribes of 
 living creatures which people its surface, and with the 
 human race. 
 
 Ordered and systematic knowledge considers such subjects 
 from various points of view and along different lines of 
 thought. But two questions commonly suggest themselves 
 with respect to each new object or event which comes within 
 
4 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 the sphere of our experience. Having recognised its exist- 
 ence, or " that it is," the first of these questions asks, 
 "What is it ? "; the second makes the inquiry, " Why is 
 it ? " Whence does it arise ? How does it come to be ? 
 
 Demands which thus rise to the lips even of the child 
 must assuredly be included amongst the problems which 
 systematic knowledge investigates. They constitute indeed 
 the most searching inquiries which science can carry on with 
 respect to whatsoever objects may become the subject of its 
 labours. To classify each object or event with its congeners 
 is one great end of scientific inquiry, and such an end was 
 attained in each case when the fundamental similarity be- 
 came understood between the fall of any object to the earth's 
 surface and the moon's motions; between the electric spark 
 and the lightning's flash ; and between that hugest of the 
 ocean's inhabitants, the whale, and the little bat which flits 
 through the summer air at twilight. These may serve as 
 familiar examples of approximate answers to the question, 
 " What is it ? " The origin of the solar system, the ex- 
 planation of reflex and sensori-motor actions, 1 and the 
 genesis of new species of animals and plants, are instances 
 of most interesting scientific inquiries as to the " how " 
 and " why " of matters of scientific or of ordinary experi- 
 ence. 
 
 Knowledge is initiated in the individual by the actions of 
 surrounding objects upon his organs of sense, which objects 
 the child becomes gradually able to perceive more or less 
 distinctly. Self-knowledge is of later origin, and much ac- 
 quaintance with the external world is acquired before the 
 attention of anyone becomes directed to his own mental 
 processes and his internal experiences. 
 
 1 Movements which take place independent of the will on the occurrence of 
 some sensation, as the movements of swallowing take place when a morsel is 
 felt at the back part of the mouth. 
 
IN TR OD UC TOR Y 5 
 
 So it is with the lower races of mankind and the least 
 cultivated members of civilised communities. Physical 
 phenomena attract their attention almost exclusively, and 
 usually they attend but slightly, or hardly at all, to matters 
 psychical. All men also, however cultivated, are continually 
 impelled and compelled to notice what they regard as sur- 
 rounding objects, to the apprehension of which the mind 
 applies itself with extreme facility. But they are by no 
 means so often impelled to notice their own mental states. 
 
 Now, as we all know, " practice makes perfect," and new 
 or unfamiliar modes of activity are generally at first unwel- 
 come and performed with comparative difficulty. It is small 
 wonder, then, that to most men the study of their own 
 minds and mental processes is at first both repugnant and 
 difficult. 
 
 But a moment's reflection will suffice to make clear to the 
 reader that if he would become acquainted with the ground- 
 work of science, he must also carefully inform himself re- 
 specting the means and conditions indispensable for that 
 inquiry. No language can be fully understood without a 
 knowledge of its grammar, and no art can be successfully 
 pursued by anyone who is^ ignorant as to the nature and 
 use of the tools needed for its exercise. Obviously the 
 study of objects and actions around us, as they are com- 
 monly apprehended, and also as the results of the most care- 
 ful examination, lies at the base of every science, and is 
 therefore closely connected with the study of the ground- 
 work of science. But none of the objects of any science, 
 however simply physical, can be comprehended by us with- 
 out the employment of certain mental tools of different 
 kinds, which must be used in the right manner. No science 
 can be properly cultivated without a certain amount of hard 
 work, and in order to lay bare and see clearly the founda- 
 tions of all science, such work is especially needed. It is 
 
6 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 on this account we have chosen for our title The Ground- 
 work of Science, it being our desire to point out not only 
 what those foundations are, but also the tools to be used 
 and the kind of work requisite for their discovery and 
 correct apprehension. The study of psychical states being 
 thus indispensable, it is fortunate that the difficulty anyone 
 may find in turning the mind inwards upon itself can soon 
 be overcome ; for the faculties of introspection and retro- 
 spection, like our other faculties, can be strengthened by 
 exercise, and all that is ordinarily needed to perfect it is 
 patient perseverance. 
 
 Perceptions of external and internal facts are primary 
 elements of science. But neither physical facts alone, nor 
 mental facts alone, will suffice for even the commencement 
 of science. For that, conceptions, which are the result of 
 both, are needed. The facts our senses make known to us 
 are the existences and actions of what we regard as in- 
 dividual objects, while mental facts are individual states of 
 what is known as " the mind " : states in which we act or 
 are acted on. All that we thus know are real individual (or 
 concrete) existences and activities. But with such materials 
 only the intellect could do no work at all. Thoughts, of 
 which words are the external signs, relate not to what con- 
 cerns external or internal individual things, but each thought 
 relates to many things of the same kind, i. e., to " univers- 
 als." Almost always thoughts, and the words which ex- 
 press them, refer to and denote what is abstract instead of 
 concrete, and what is universal instead of individual. The 
 thought symbolised by the word " triangle " does not refer 
 to any individual, concrete triangle, nor even to a definite 
 kind of triangle (e.g., to an equilateral or non-equilateral 
 one), but refers to " triangle-in-general " to a triangle con- 
 sidered as abstract and universal, and to all triangles as 
 members of one class of figures. It is the same with every 
 
IN TROD UCTOR Y >j 
 
 noun-substantive which is not a proper name, with every 
 adjective, and with every verb. The words " apple," 
 " red," " fallen," are equally applicable to every kind of 
 apple, to whatever object is of a red tint, and to everything 
 which has fallen from a higher to a lower level. 
 
 It is impossible intelligently to utter the simplest sentence 
 no savage could even say "Spear broken!" without 
 making use of highly abstract ideas. Indeed, the highest 
 and most abstract of all ideas, that of " being " or " exist- 
 ence," is necessarily implied in every statement we make 
 and every question we ask. Again, no progress in science 
 is possible without apprehending degrees of likeness and 
 unlikeness, perceptions as to which constitute the basis of 
 all classification. But neither " likeness " nor " unlikeness " 
 can, of course, exist by itself in the concrete, and no single 
 object taken by itself can be either one or the other. But 
 as with likeness, so with every relation in which one object 
 or action can possibly stand to another object or action, we 
 can only apprehend it by means of an abstract idea, and as 
 all science consists of a study and comprehension of " re- 
 lations," so all science is essentially abstract, although 
 derived from, and accurately applicable to, real concrete 
 states of real concrete things. 
 
 " Thoughts " in one sense are concrete, individual mental 
 (or psychical) realities, as truly as a heap of stones are con- 
 crete physical realities. But the meaning of a thought and 
 its oral expression e. g. t " triangle " or " apple " is (as 
 just said) abstract. Nevertheless, it is not purely mental, 
 but refers to real things which constitute the " class " to 
 which the abstract term refers the class of triangles and the 
 class of apples each real concrete member of each such 
 class possessing the real concrete characters referred to by 
 the abstract term. Thus these " thoughts " so considered 
 are not simply mental any more than simply physical. 
 
8 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 They are ideas which have their roots in the real concrete 
 character of real concrete things. Therefore what we mainly 
 make use of are these activities of a mixed nature in essence 
 psychical and in reference, generally, physical. It is thus 
 we apprehend the relations between the various existences 
 known to us. And the work of science may be said to con- 
 sist (i) in the accurate classification of perceived objects, and 
 the relations which exist between them, both simultaneous 
 and successive which are often called " the co-existences 
 and sequences of phenomena" and (2) in estimating the 
 possibility, probability, necessity, or impossibility of their 
 recurrence. Thus are formulated what are commonly called 
 " laws of nature." Some of these so-called " laws" are 
 termed " empirical," because they merely express. co-exist- 
 ences and sequences which have been observed to exist as 
 facts, apart from any knowledge of the causes which produce 
 them. Necessary laws, on the other hand, are such as we 
 can perceive to be the inevitable result of known causes, or 
 such as possess other evidence of their universal truth. 
 Some scientific truths must be directly evident (in and 
 through perception) or science could make no beginning; 
 but we must also be able to attain to truths which are 
 indirectly evident (in and through reasoning or infer- 
 ence), otherwise we could make no progress, and so sci- 
 ence would remain a mere mass of empirically ascertained 
 data. 
 
 Now, amongst the laws of nature are the laws which, so 
 to speak, regulate the mode in which mental processes 
 should be carried on in order to secure valid and satisfactory 
 results and to avoid mistakes and fallacies in our judgments 
 and inferences. Therefore, since science depends, and must 
 depend, largely on reasoning, it imperatively requires not 
 only the greatest care with respect to the observation of 
 facts, but also the greatest care that, in our inferences, those 
 
INTRODUCTORY 9 
 
 laws of thought the violation of which induces error, should 
 in no case be disobeyed. 
 
 In every human perception, and therefore of course in 
 every perception wherewith science is concerned, there are 
 two constituents (i) the mental or " subjective" constit- 
 uent the psychical modification of the subject, /'. e., of 
 him who perceives and (2) the external or " objective " 
 constituent that (of whatever it may consist and whatever 
 be its cause) which is the object cognised or perceived in the 
 psychical act of cognition or perception on the part of the 
 subject. Again, in every act of intellectual cognition or 
 perception, there are also two elements (i) the sensational 
 and (2) the intellectual. 
 
 In the earliest stages of mental life, psychical action 
 though no doubt partly excited by internal feelings (that is, 
 by feelings due to physical changes in the internal bodily 
 organs) is mainly roused to activity, as before said, by the 
 action of external bodies upon the infant's organs of sense 
 and, through them, upon its central and supreme nervous 
 organ, its brain. Numerous feelings are thus aroused and 
 subsequently experienced again and again in various com- 
 binations of co-existence and sequence of feelings thus 
 excited by external objects. These experiences lay the 
 foundation for subsequent minute brain modifications, the 
 accompaniment of which are what we call " mental images," 
 " imaginations," or " phantasmata. " Such mental phe- 
 nomena are internal feelings, and resemble, more or less 
 closely, the feelings previously excited by external objects. 
 
 Without the aid of such mental images, or imaginations, 
 it is impossible for us to think at all, while it is impossible 
 for us to imagine aught save things which our senses have 
 previously experienced, either entire or in their constituent 
 parts. Our sense-impressions can, as it seems to us, alone 
 furnish a basis and support on which the intellect may build 
 
IO THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 and act, and it can build nothing except upon a foundation 
 of sense-impressions, nor can it take a step without the aid 
 of the imagination. Thus sensations and subsequent mental 
 images are both the necessary antecedents and also the in- 
 dispensable accompaniments of all our ideas, however ab- 
 stract or refined. 
 
 Nevertheless, it would (in our opinion) be the greatest 
 mistake possible to affirm that there is absolutely nothing in 
 the intellect save what previously existed in our sensations. 
 To say this would be to deny the essential distinctness which 
 exists between " ideas " and " feelings," whether the latter 
 are " sensations " or " mental images." As to the signifi- 
 cation of the word " idea," our definition would be " an 
 intellectual representation of an object either actually exist- 
 ing or merely possible." 
 
 One or two examples may suffice to show how, by the 
 help of sensations, and mental images, the mind rises to the 
 conceptions of ideas beyond the power of mere feeling. 
 Thus we often refer to some past " experience," and the 
 idea is a sufficiently familiar one, yet that idea cannot pos- 
 sibly be a faint reproduction of past feelings, for " experi- 
 ence " is an abstract term, and, therefore, denotes something 
 which never could have been felt at all. By receiving or 
 obtaining over and over again feelings of the same or of 
 different kinds, we may feel them more easily, more pleasur- 
 ably, or (as is too often the case) more painfully. But to 
 undergo such changes of feeling, and to obtain the idea 
 " experience," are two very different things. 
 
 Again, we can all form an idea of the action of our eyes 
 in seeing (our act of sight), yet that act of seeing was never 
 itself felt, nor can the idea be decomposed into mere feelings 
 it contains much more. We may have certain feelings in 
 our eyeballs while looking, but even if we could feel (which 
 we cannot) every minute action of every part of the eyes 
 
IN TR OD UC TOR Y \ \ 
 
 and of the brain's complex mechanism, such feelings would 
 be no " idea of the act of seeing." Among the constant 
 experiences of our daily life are our perceptions of different 
 shades of colour, and different feelings have accompanied 
 such perceptions. But of " colour" we have never once 
 had a feeling ; yet we have a clear idea of it and often speak 
 of it. 
 
 We have certainly another idea which was never felt, and 
 that is our idea of " nothing," or " nonentity." It is very 
 certain that past sensations can never account for thai con- 
 ception, which is nevertheless commonly enough employed. 
 How often do we not hear such expressions as " It is worth 
 nothing," or, " There is nothing in it " ? 
 
 That our powers of mental conception are not tied down 
 to experience is shown by the very fact that we can conceive 
 of its not being so tied down, and also that we conceive of 
 other senses besides those which we possess such, e. g., as 
 senses which might enable us to feel the chemical composi- 
 tion, or the magnetic currents and condition, of different 
 bodies. We can conceive of possible experiences which are 
 as remote from being actual as would be perceptions of 
 colour gained by most carefully listening with the ear, or 
 musical harmonies detected by specially contrived lenses 
 carefully fitted to our microscopes. 
 
 This essential distinction may be further shown by the 
 fact that one and the same intellectual conception can be 
 initiated and supported by a variety of very different sets of 
 feelings, while a single set of feelings may initiate and sup- 
 port a number of divergent intellectual conceptions. Thus 
 the one abstract idea, " motion," may be initiated or sup- 
 ported by our actual experience or mere imagination of (i) 
 the sight of something traversing our field of vision ; (2) a 
 feeling of something slipping through the hand ; (3) a sound 
 as of falling waters; (4) one like that accompanying the 
 
12 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 ascent of a rocket; (5) the sight of a bow and arrow, a 
 musket, or a pile of cannon-balls; (6) the name of a well- 
 known race-horse; (7) dance-music from a familiar ballet; 
 (8) the smell of a fox, and so on. 
 
 So also with a single set of feelings, such as those we 
 might experience after gazing upon a marble statue of 
 Shakespeare : its aspect, or even our mere recollection of it, 
 might give rise to and support a number of very diverse in- 
 tellectual conceptions. Thus it might lead us to conceive 
 of (i) the man Shakespeare who once lived; (2) the Eliza- 
 bethan age ; (3) the man's merit as a dramatist ; (4) of poetry 
 as an art ; (5) plays we have seen acted ; (6) theatrical mise 
 en scene ; (7) the name and merit of the statue's sculptor; 
 (8) the appearance of the marble ; (9) the mountains of Car- 
 rara; (10) the geographical age of the limestone; (ii)the 
 creatures which existed whilst it was being deposited; (12) 
 marble as a substance; (13) the particular piece making the 
 statue; (14) individuality; and lastly (15) the idea of being 
 or existence. 
 
 To state this distinction as shortly as possible, it may be 
 pointed out that our sensitive faculty is affected by sur- 
 rounding objects in various ways, but that it is the intellect 
 alone which can apprehend the relations in which they 
 stand to it and to each other, and that such relations do, in 
 fact, exist. But it is plain that to understand the relative 
 position of two objects, we must perceive both of them and 
 turn back the mind (reflect) from the last to the first per- 
 ceived. Without so doing, their spatial relations, their re- 
 lations as to position, could not possibly be apprehended. 
 
 Again, feelings (both sensations and imaginations) can 
 never reflect on feelings ; but thought can reflect on thought. 
 Feeling may be so intense as to annihilate itself and pro- 
 duce insensibility as light may dazzle and blind; but an 
 idea can never be too bright and clear, and no amount of 
 
IN TROD UCTOR Y 1 3 
 
 vividness on the part of the intellect can mar intellectual 
 perception. 
 
 The profound and essential distinction which exists be- 
 tween (i) an idea, or intellectual conception, and (2) a 
 feeling felt or imagined is particularly conspicuous with 
 respect to our idea of ' ' being " or ' ' existence. ' ' That idea 
 is so fundamental that it is simply applicable to everything, 
 while without it nothing can be apprehended. No group of 
 feelings could possibly give us a feeling of " being," because 
 there neither is nor can be one feeling common to all other 
 feelings, and yet a feeling of a distinguishable kind. Never- 
 theless, though we have no " feeling " of " being," the 
 idea of " being " lies at the root of all our conceptions, and 
 is present (though, of course, it is not reflected on) in the 
 mind of the young child who asks what that " thing " is. 
 It may be well further to contrast our " feelings " and our 
 " intellectual perceptions " from yet another point of view. 
 
 In the pursuit of every science we have to make use of 
 both, and the way we should regard them the relations in 
 which they stand to each other is supremely important for 
 those who would enter upon the science of the sciences 
 Epistemology. To determine what is most certain and most 
 fundamental, it is obvious that we need to see clearly what 
 is and must be the nature of our absolute and ultimate 
 criterion of truth in all cases. 
 
 There are some persons who would assign the dignity of 
 an ultimate test of reality and truth to our sensitive faculty. 
 But a little careful consideration will be enough to show the 
 investigator that it is the intellect alone which is, and must 
 be, supreme; and this not only in judging about recondite 
 problems, but even in deciding concerning things which 
 we see, hear, feel, etc., and concerning all concrete experi- 
 ences as they actually occur. Thus, even with those matters 
 which can be submitted to the test of sensation, the last 
 
14 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 word, in all cases of doubt, rests with the intellect and not 
 with the senses. It might seem that in making experiments 
 with different bodies (as in chemistry), when we directly ap- 
 peal to our senses for information, those senses must be our 
 ultimate criterion ; yet such is not the case. The enormous 
 value and indispensable nature of our sensations is obvious 
 and unquestionable. Observation and experiment are al- 
 ways, of course, to be made use of, when possible, for verify- 
 ing our inferences. Nevertheless, in the last resource, when 
 we have done experimenting, how do we know, with absolute 
 certainty, that we have obtained such results as we may have 
 obtained ? Manifestly by the intellect. How otherwise are 
 we to judge between what may seem to be the conflicting 
 indications of different sense-impressions ? Nothing could 
 .be more foolish than to undervalue the testimony of the 
 senses, which are both tests and causes of certainty. They 
 are not, however, the test of it. Certainty does not pertain 
 to sensation, but to thought alone. Self-conscious, reflect- 
 ive thought, then, is our ultimate and absolute criterion. It 
 is by thought only by the self-conscious intellect that we 
 know we have " feelings " at all. Without that we might 
 indeed feel, but we could not have complete certainty as to 
 our feeling and know assuredly that we possessed it. Our 
 ultimate court of appeal and supreme criterion is the intel- 
 lect and not sense, and our act of intellectual perception 
 which is thus ultimate, which both knows what it knows and 
 knows that it knows it, with absolute certainty, which is 
 above any possibility of proof and is self-evident in and to 
 itself, is called " intellectual intuition." 
 
 The matters thus put forward in a simple elementary way 
 in this introductory chapter will be treated of more fully 
 and scientifically when we begin to grapple with the most 
 fundamental questions concerning human knowledge. We 
 have here somewhat anticipated what we shall have to say 
 
IN TROD UCTOR Y \ 5 
 
 in our eighth chapter. We have, however, felt ourselves 
 forced so to do, as otherwise we could hardly make clear 
 matters we must deal with almost immediately. 
 
 Here, at the outset, we take for granted that a world of 
 material, independent objects, possessing various powers and 
 activities, exists about us ; also that we possess a material, 
 extended body, so organised as to produce in us feelings of 
 various kinds which are closely connected with our percep- 
 tions and our judgments. 
 
 Taking these data provisionally as unquestionable facts, 
 it may, we think, suffice to affirm and point out what will 
 be fully demonstrated later on, that, though in the invlsti- 
 gation of science we should make use of all our available 
 powers and faculties our powers of feeling, imagination, 
 sensuous perception, memory, and inference yet that our 
 intellect's declaration, as to what is here and now certainly 
 and self-evidently true, is our supreme guide, and the most 
 powerful and effective instrument for our use in every inquiry 
 we make. A provisional assent to this statement and a 
 temporary obedience to the law thus set forth, is all we wish 
 to ask of those who would follow us in our investigation 
 concerning the groundwork of science. 
 
CHAPTER II 
 
 AN ENUMERATION OF THE SCIENCES 
 
 A BRIEF enumeration of the principal sciences, the 
 ^ groundwork of which it is our business to inquire 
 into, may fitly, we think, precede the inquiry itself. 
 
 Various attempts have been made at a classification of the 
 sciences according to the subjects about which they are oc- 
 cupied; some sciences being set down as " abstract," others 
 as "abstract-concrete," and yet others as "concrete" 
 simply. 
 
 All such attempts we regard as futile. Every science is 
 a definitely organised system of recognised relations between 
 thoughts and objects, between thoughts and thoughts, and 
 between objects and objects; and no science can be learned 
 save by the aid of language, spoken, written, or both. But 
 all language is highly abstract ; nor can the most concrete 
 objects (e. g. y a tray of specimens of different minerals) be 
 apprehended and compared save by the aid of very abstract 
 ideas. 
 
 On the other hand, not the most abstract of all ideas, that 
 of " being," or " existence," can be made use of without 
 reference to some concrete reality to which that idea truly 
 applies. Even the most extreme of idealists, he who thinks 
 that the whole universe about him is but the creation of his 
 own mind, or he who deems it (his own being and thoughts 
 included) to be but passing phases of some other unknown 
 
 16 
 
AN ENUMERATION OF THE SCIENCES \J 
 
 mind each such idealist must regard that mind he so con- 
 ceives of as a concrete reality and the object of thought. 
 
 Everything which can be an object of study has multi- 
 tudinous relations, of most varied orders, to other objects 
 and to the mind which studies it. A sphere of crystal, as 
 being a single object, solid, transparent, spherical, of a 
 definite weight, of a certain chemical composition, of a cer- 
 tain temperature, capable of projection in various directions 
 and at definite velocities, as a manufactured object, made 
 in a certain locality, for a definite purpose, etc., etc., ob- 
 viously possesses numerous relations, and cannot be fully 
 understood save from many points of view and by the aid 
 of abstract ideas of very different orders. 
 
 How difficult, then, must be the task of classifying the 
 sciences according to the degrees of abstraction made use of 
 by them, seeing that every one of them is, in fact, highly 
 abstract. It is true that an effort might be made to classify 
 them on other lines, as, for example, from an historical 
 point of view. This, however, would obviously be most 
 unsatisfactory were we to try and arrange them in the order 
 wherein the objects they treat of become known in the 
 history of the individual mind ; and hardly less unsatisfactory 
 would be an endeavour to arrange according to the date of 
 their origin as sciences. Could astrology and alchemy be 
 deemed incipient stages of astronomy and chemistry ? The 
 mere fact that such a question can be asked is enough to 
 lead us to abandon the task of attempting an historical 
 classification. 
 
 For our part, we shall not try to construct any classifica- 
 tion of the sciences at all, but will content ourselves with 
 the humble task of their brief enumeration, endeavouring, 
 at the same time, to indicate some of their logical relations 
 one to another. 
 
 Indeed, reason, it seems, does not permit us to concede 
 
1 8 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 that any one science has an indefeasible claim to priority, 
 for conflicting, apparently equal, claims point in various 
 directions. 
 
 Our own body is the object we most intimately know, 
 and next might be ranked the objects most closely related 
 to us, and with which we are the most familiar. But such 
 things, taken together, do not constitute any distinct science. 
 
 There is, however, one property which belongs to them 
 and to everything else we can think of likewise to every 
 separate object, natural or artificial, to every motion or ap- 
 pearance, and even to every thought we can entertain about 
 any possible object. 
 
 To know anything whatever, is to know that it is distinct 
 from something else. Two marbles, alike in colour, size, 
 shape, and weight, are known with perfect certainty to be 
 distinct, though we may not, when apart, be able to tell one 
 from the other. We recognise them as two things of the 
 same kind, and together they form " a pair." If we have 
 elsewhere a group of three marbles exactly like the first two, 
 then these two groups differ in number. " Number " is a 
 property possessed by every object, motion, or appearance, 
 and even by every thought. 
 
 The one thing which alike pertains to everything we 
 know, terrestrial or celestial, material or mental, is " num- 
 ber. ' ' Probably it was this truth which underlay the system 
 of Pythagoras, who, more than two thousand four hundred 
 years ago, taught that " number " was the principle of all 
 things. 
 
 But the study of that which is thus common to every- 
 thing is the study of mathematics. Therefore mathematics, 
 as the science of number, would seem to have a reasonable 
 claim to be regarded as the most fundamental of all the 
 sciences, since it pertains to every other, and no other can 
 be pursued without it. 
 
AN ENUMERATION OF THE SCIENCES 19 
 
 Nevertheless, another science can advance a claim seem- 
 ingly as unanswerable in another respect as is the claim of 
 mathematics, as just stated. No science can claim to be 
 absolutely primary which has to depend on another science 
 for explanation and comprehension. Mathematics is a 
 science of " number"; but what is " number " ? More- 
 over, numbers are alike or not unlike, and a perception of 
 " likeness and unlikeness " was declared, in our introductory 
 chapter, to be at the base of all the sciences. What, then, 
 it must be further asked, is " likeness " ? May not the 
 science which can solve these riddles justly claim to under- 
 lie, and be prior to, the science of mathematics ? 
 
 The idea of "number" implies comparison, together 
 with a recognition that the things compared are similar, and 
 yet not identical. Things which are quite dissimilar such 
 as, e. ., "a violet blossom " and " a fall in consols " 
 cannot be said to be two, unless it be two expressions or two 
 thoughts in which respects they are alike. But the idea of 
 number, inasmuch as it recognises things as similar but not 
 identical, implies many things besides similarity and iden- 
 tity. In every perception of number there are, and must 
 be, latent the ideas of " existence," " distinction," " simil- 
 arity," " unity," and " truth," as a little reflection will 
 show. Thus, to say " there are two sheep," implies that 
 they are not merely imaginary, but that they actually exist ; 
 that they are not seen double by some optical delusion, but 
 are really distinct ; that they are certainly both sheep and 
 not one of them a goat i. e., that they are similar, and that 
 they have that unity of nature which we have just seen to 
 be necessary in order that they should be susceptible of 
 numeration, and finally the assertion implies that the 
 thought of the assertion corresponds with objective reality, 
 that is, it implies truth. 
 
 It may be replied that mathematics deals with abstractions 
 
20 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 and considers numerical relations of things apart from the 
 things themselves. The assertion is most true, but from 
 that very fact it must be applicable to all things and would 
 be mere nonsense apart from the implication that there 
 really are things, be it only thoughts, to which the idea of 
 number can be really and truly applicable. And if thoughts 
 are to be capable of enumeration they must have existence, 
 distinction, similarity, unity, and truth, just as a pair of 
 sheep (as above pointed out) must possess those attributes. 
 But this degree of similarity between things so essentially 
 dissimilar as ' ' thoughts ' ' and ' ' sheep, ' ' suggests the further 
 question, " What is likeness ? " 
 
 Now a moment's reflection must make it evident to any 
 thinker that not everything can be defined or explained. 
 If there were not some things capable of being understood 
 without definition and explanation, then nothing whatever 
 could ever be understood at all ; for in that case the pro- 
 cesses of definition and explanation would have to be car- 
 ried on forever. Now " likeness," like " number," can be 
 clearly seen to imply ideas of existence, distinction, unity, 
 and truth; but that, of course, is no explanation of it. It 
 is one of those primary, ultimate, fundamental ideas which 
 (like the idea of " existence " or " being ") is incapable of 
 definition or explanation just because it is so simple. For 
 to say that two things are " alike " when they are identical 
 in some respect, or respects, does not deserve to be called 
 an explanation. For to recognise that two objects are iden- 
 tical in certain respects we must be aware that their other 
 respects are alike in not being identical. Anyone who 
 thinks he cannot understand what he means when he says 
 two things are " alike," or when he declares, " there is a 
 4 likeness ' between them," may as well give up the attempt 
 to understand any branch of science and, a fortiori, its 
 groundwork. But the science of mathematics enables us to 
 
AN ENUMERATION OF THE SCIENCES 21 
 
 prove a vast quantity of truths which would be inaccessible 
 to the human mind without its aid. By its help truths, ap- 
 plicable to all existing things, can be deduced from other 
 truths by means of various processes of inference. But can 
 mathematics, which thus makes use of " proofs," dispense 
 with the aid of that science upon which it thus leans: which 
 tells us in what proof consists, and lays down the laws by 
 obedience to which alone valid inference can be carried on 
 and truth attained ? Now, such a science is logic. Surely, 
 then, logic may advance a strong claim to be the most 
 fundamental, and, therefore, to head our list of the sciences. 
 
 But to comprehend logic, speech is necessary, and though, 
 as we shall hereafter see, there are strong grounds for con- 
 cluding that speech was posterior to thought, nevertheless 
 here and now, the use of, and a considerable knowledge 
 about, speech is long anterior to our comprehension of, or 
 even to the very first application of our minds to, logic. 
 Therefore, the science which treats of human speech could 
 also advance a claim to priority. 
 
 But, as before said, logic is essentially the science of the 
 art of proof, and all proof must repose upon certain data. 
 Therefore, such data must, in the first place, be either per- 
 ceptions which we have concerning our own mental states 
 and operations, or perceptions concerning external things, 
 or conceptions of, and reflections about, one or the other, or 
 both of these. 
 
 But all these are forms of psychical activity, or are the 
 direct results of different forms of psychical activity. Now 
 these psychical activities must be anterior to any processes 
 of reasoning, and form the data whence all reasonings pro- 
 ceed. But the elucidation of these data is the business of 
 psychology. Surely, then, the science which deals with 
 the initiation and performance of psychical phenomena 
 (phenomena which constitute the data and basis of logic) 
 
22 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 may claim priority over, and to be more fundamental than, 
 logic itself. 
 
 But the science of reasoning cannot, for another reason, 
 validly lay claim to be primary and fundamental, since it 
 requires other data than those given it by psychology. 
 Now in order to prove anything by reasoning, we must show 
 that it necessarily follows, as a consequence, from other 
 truths, on the truth of which its own truth depends. Such 
 other truths must therefore be deemed more indispensable 
 than the thing they are called on to prove. Evidently we 
 cannot prove everything. However long may be our argu- 
 ments, we shall at last come to statements which must be 
 taken for granted as ultimate. One such statement is that 
 which affirms the validity of reasoning. If we had to prove 
 the validity of the reasoning process, then either we must 
 argue in a circle, or our process of proof must go on forever 
 without ever coming to a conclusion. In other words, there 
 could be no such thing as proof at all. There must, then, 
 if any human knowledge is trustworthy, be some truths 
 which require no proof, but are evident in and by them- 
 selves. Once more, then, that science, whatever it may be, 
 which thus deals with the basis of all reasoning, and there- 
 fore of all psychology, of all logic, and also of all mathe- 
 matics, would seem to have, if anything has, a valid claim 
 to be the most primary and fundamental of all sciences. 
 But the science which does this is metaphysics ! 
 
 Metaphysics, however, though it thus deals with what is 
 so primary and fundamental, is a science which has also to 
 do with the human mind, with our views concerning an ex- 
 ternal world, and with whatever constitutes the subject- 
 matter of every other science. For of what does the science 
 of metaphysics treat ? 
 
 In the first place, it may be said to be " the science of the 
 supersensuous considered objectively." 
 
AN ENUMERA TION OF THE SCIENCES 2$ 
 
 It is also divisible into two great sections; the first of 
 these (a) may be distinguished as " general," occupied as 
 it is about " being," its properties and categories about 
 " reality " in the sense we give to that term. For us 
 " reality " is composed of " whatever actually does or 
 possibly may exist"; while, similarly, " being " is that 
 which possesses either form of " reality." 
 
 " Reality " cannot be anything else but possible or actual, 
 for there evidently can be nothing intermediate between 
 the two. Abstract "being" cannot, of course, exist as 
 conceived by the mind ; but nevertheless it is not absolute 
 nothing (nihilum), because, though incapable of existence 
 in itself, the conception is nevertheless realised in things 
 which do 'exist, while pure nonentity (nihilum) is the abso- 
 lute negative, and cannot possibly exist in any mode. As 
 to what is " actual," that term needs, and can have, no 
 definition, since it'must be implied in every attempt to de- 
 fine it. 
 
 The second great conception (b) of metaphysics may be 
 called " special," since it concerns itself with definite in- 
 quiries about cosmology, the world as it appears to the 
 human intellect, the origin and nature of the latter, with 
 consequences which appear evidently to follow therefrom in 
 all directions. 
 
 It would, then, be manifestly absurd to place it first upon 
 our list. It should come; as its name implies, after the 
 study of all that concerns the external world, and the study 
 of man as a living and thinking organic being. But not 
 only must metaphysics, though the most abstract of sciences, 
 be denied the first place in our list ; something may even be 
 said for the sciences usually deemed the most concrete. In 
 fact, a knowledge of the physical precedes that of the 
 psychical (as was before asserted), and if concrete sciences 
 need, for their comprehension, abstract ideas, the most ab- 
 
24 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 stract sciences have need of the concrete. Thus psychology 
 cannot be fully investigated and understood without some 
 comprehension of our organic frame and its multitudinous 
 activities. But our body is the subject of anatomy (includ- 
 ing histology) and its activities, or physiology, while neither 
 human anatomy nor physiology can be adequately compre- 
 hended if dealt with alone. For such adequate compre- 
 hension the aid of comparative anatomy (or morphology) 
 and comparative physiology which contrast man's form and 
 functions with those of animals and plants are needed, and 
 these cannot be made use of without some acquaintance 
 with zoology and botany. But, again, the creatures about 
 which the last-named two sciences are concerned, must be 
 studied with respect to extinct as well as existing species 
 (palaeontology), and to know that requires a knowledge of 
 the world's past history (geology), and this cannot be fully 
 understood without regard to the earth as a member of the 
 solar system and of the sidereal universe, and so we are led 
 to astronomy. 
 
 We have hitherto passed over (simply because everything 
 cannot be mentioned at the same time) the study of me- 
 chanics and of the physical energies gravitation, heat, 
 light, sound, chemical change, electricity, and magnetism ; 
 but every one of these sciences is intimately connected with 
 what concerns the inorganic as well as the whole organic 
 world. Nor can that study which relates to the origin and 
 evolution of the world (the only theatre actually known to 
 us of all the sciences) be said to have no claim to be itself 
 primary and fundamental. But the whole universe has 
 been revealed to us by human study alone, and human ac- 
 tivity is the cause of the existence of all our sciences, on 
 which account anthropology, the science of man, must be 
 allowed in its turn some claim to be considered fundamental. 
 Now if a separate science (physiology) be devoted to the 
 
AN ENUMERATION OF THE SCIENCES 2$ 
 
 consideration of the activities of animals and plants, surely 
 the story of human actions has yet more claim on our care- 
 ful investigation, and the most important results of human 
 activity are recorded in history, which tells us of the first 
 beginnings and systematisation of mathematics, psychology, 
 and logic. And here must also follow on the study of 
 man's pursuit of his ideals of beauty, truth, and goodness 
 the history of art, of science, of philosophy, of ethics, and 
 of religion. All questions of religion, however, will be very 
 carefully excluded from the present work, all the arguments 
 in which claim to repose on and appeal to nothing but the 
 pure dry light of human reason. 
 
 But the fact that different religions have existed has been 
 too often made most painfully evident, and therefore the 
 recognition of the existence of religions and systems of 
 theology as facts, cannot possibly be excluded from the 
 sphere of the sciences any more than the external manifesta- 
 tions of the inner nature of each such system. Now theo- 
 logy professes to occupy itself with man's relations to a God 
 or to gods, and to other superhuman beings, if such there 
 are, and to his fellow-men, and so may be called (on the 
 assumption that the only really intelligent animals are men) 
 " the sociology of intelligences." But this form of sociol- 
 ogy demands the aid of philosophy, psychology, and history 
 and ethics. But ethics, like metaphysics, may be divided 
 into (a) general and (#) special. The former regards the 
 existence and first principles of ethical distinctions ; the 
 latter the special application of those principles to society, 
 the family, and the individual. 
 
 But for the due application of those principles to individ- 
 uals and groups of men we must call in physiology to our 
 aid, and therefore anatomy, while physiology brings with it 
 the study of the physical energies (statics, dynamics, thermo- 
 dynamics, chemistry, optics, acoustics, and the sciences of 
 
26 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 electricity and magnetism), which again necessitates recourse 
 to mathematics, and once more to logic and psychology. 
 
 In a word, all the sciences are connected by such a laby- 
 rinth of interrelations that the construction of a really satis- 
 factory classification of them appears to be an insuperable 
 task. Anyhow, it is a task beyond our powers. 
 
 But for our special purpose the explorations of the 
 foundations of science a systematic classification of 
 the sciences does not appear necessary. We will therefore 
 aim at nothing but to place before our readers a catalogue of 
 the sciences in what seems, to our judgment, a not incon- 
 venient order. It will also, we think, be well here to 
 assume the existence of real, external, independent bodies, 
 as they are commonly supposed to exist, reserving all 
 questions as to the truth of that supposition for our next 
 chapter. 
 
 Accepting, then, provisionally, the existence of a world 
 of real and independent external bodies, generally exhibit- 
 ing some definite shape and figure, with powers of intrinsic 
 motion, of motion due to external causes, and in all cases 
 capable of enumeration, we may thus set down the series. 
 
 On account of this last characteristic we will place first on 
 our list the science of Mathematics. This, as the reader of 
 course well knows, consists of Arithmetic, or the study of 
 definite quantities of things of whatever kind; of Algebra, 
 or the use of definite symbols to investigate undefined 
 quantities of undefined things; and of Geometry, which 
 studies the properties of figures, the direction of lines, and 
 the conditions of space in its three dimensions (length, 
 breadth, and thickness), including the properties of the 
 sphere, the cone, and the cylinder. Though geometry ap- 
 pears to have arisen through the desire to measure land 
 accurately (for which the properties of triangles and their 
 angles served, and still serve), Greek geometers occupied 
 
AN ENUMERA TION OF THE SCIENCES 2J 
 
 themselves, in a purely speculative manner, with the differ- 
 ent methods in which a circular cone may be cut. The 
 investigation of the various kinds of curves which may be 
 produced by cutting across it in different directions, gave 
 rise to the study we know as Conic Sections. 
 
 By various other processes the most varied properties of 
 objects have been investigated, including complex recipro- 
 cal relations of increase, decrease, and variation. When 
 two quantities vary they may do so equally or in different 
 proportions or ratios. The Differential calculus deals with 
 computations concerning the rates of change between quan- 
 tities. The Integral calculus passes from the relation be- 
 tween such rates back to the relations which exist between 
 the changing quantities themselves. 
 
 We may next pass to the science of Mechanics, with its 
 subdivisions, Statics, Dynamics, Hydrostatics, Hydrodynam- 
 ics, and Pneumatics. 
 
 ;< Mathematics " is, as we have seen, concerned with num- 
 ber, space, and direction; "' Mechanics" also with time, 
 motion, and force, and especially the action or effects of 
 gravity. Mechanics deals also not only with solids but 
 with fluids, whether liquids or aeriform (or gaseous) sub- 
 stances; and these whether apparently at rest or in a state 
 of motion. 
 
 Statics concerns itself with equilibrium, the composition 
 of forces, the lever, the balance, the incline'd plane, etc. 
 Dynamics considers motion, its velocity, duration, extension, 
 and direction (according to Newton's three laws), its quan- 
 tity, acceleration, and retardation, and the law of falling 
 bodies due to the action of centrifugal and centripetal forces. 
 
 In Mechanics it is assumed that solids consist of particles 
 cohering stably in some definite order, but liquids are sup- 
 posed to consist of particles which possess freedom of 
 motion in all directions, each particle pressing equally on 
 
28 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 all those which surround it and being equally pressed on by 
 them. 
 
 In Hydrostatics, therefore, pressure in all directions, and 
 not only the pressure of gravity, is considered, with the well- 
 known consequence that the surface of tranquil liquids is 
 horizontal, and water will always find its own level, and 
 those concerning the sinking and rising and other motions of 
 solid bodies in liquids. Hydrodynamics, or Hydraulics, deals 
 with the motions of liquids (waves, running water, etc., 
 etc.), which are so complex compared with those of solids, 
 and the various machines the utilities of which are due to 
 the laws of moving liquids water-rams, water-wheels, etc. 
 
 The science of aeriform fluids, i. e., Pneumatics, adopts 
 the hypothesis that such fluids are composed of particles 
 which repel each other, separating as far as they can but 
 pressing equally in all directions. Such fluids are, there- 
 fore, both extremely elastic and compressible, but, like 
 solids and liquids, they have their due weight, inertia, mo- 
 mentum, etc., and, like liquids, they have their waves of 
 motion. The weight of the atmosphere is also treated of 
 in its practical applications through the barometer, siphon, 
 pump, etc. 
 
 We may place next the sciences which treat of what are 
 called the physical energies of matter, both in their non- 
 manifest or potential condition (capable of doing work), and 
 in their active or kinetic state (actually doing work). The 
 first of these sciences is that which treats of Heat, its powers 
 of expanding bodies, its phenomena of conduction, convec- 
 tion, radiation, absorption, reflection, and refraction, and its 
 relations to other physical energies. The science of Light 
 deals in turn with its wonderful velocity of motion, in waves 
 of various lengths, its aberration, reflection, refraction, inter- 
 ference, polarisation, etc., with the laws of Optics, and such 
 practical results in the microscope, telescope, spectroscope. 
 
AN ENUMERA TION OF THE SCIENCES 2Q 
 
 and other instruments constructed in accordance with its 
 laws. 
 
 Acoustics is the science which concerns itself with sound, 
 its propagation, reflection, and diffusion through aerial waves 
 in all directions, with the laws of musical sounds or notes, 
 the nature of timbre, and various conditions presented by 
 different musical instruments. 
 
 The science of Electricity is one the amazing consequences 
 of which are familiar to everyone, so that we need but men- 
 tion its name together with that of Magnetism, so intimately 
 connected with it, and pass on to the science of Chemistry, 
 which has a distinct, though very indirect, connection with 
 the subject of this work. 
 
 All the sciences which treat of solids, fluids, and the 
 already mentioned physical energies, plainly exhibit what 
 are commonly termed the laws which govern nature, but 
 had better be called the definite tendencies which are innate 
 in the substances which compose the universe. Yet chem- 
 istry is, above all, distinguished by the clear and unanswer- 
 able manner in which it demonstrates that these tendencies 
 act in clearly defined directions, and build up by a selective 
 agency certain bodies and none others. Such is the case 
 whatever may be the reduction in number of what are at 
 present considered elementary substances, even if we should 
 ultimately become, convinced that the material world is 
 composed only of inconceivably numerous combinations of 
 particles of one elementary substance. Processes of analysis 
 and synthesis demonstrate the definite proportions in which 
 alone different (as yet seemingly distinct) substances can 
 unite and transform themselves into others not less well de- 
 fined ; while Crystallography reveals the extraordinarily 
 definite shapes into which alone definite substances can 
 crystallise, two such substances of different kinds and modes 
 of crystallisation sometimes growing so as to become in- 
 
30 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 extricably mixed, each of them preserving its own individu- 
 ality and growing according to its own laws. This science 
 is closely allied to, or rather a part of, Mineralogy, a know- 
 ledge of which leads to, and is a necessary part of, the study 
 of the crust of the earth and the strata which compose it, 
 which are dealt with by Geology ; while Meteorology concerns 
 itself with the movements which take place in the earth's 
 atmosphere, and all forms of storms, and the varying direc- 
 tions of currents, and all that concerns storms of all kinds. 
 But these, with the flow of rivers and the action of tides, 
 the descent and upheaval of parts of the earth's crust with 
 earthquakes and volcanoes, also come within the purview 
 of Geography and Geology^ which latter is again largely in- 
 debted to the science of organic remains (Paleontology) for 
 its knowledge of the relations of the superimposed layers of 
 rocks which clothe our globe externally, revealed, as they 
 often are, by the kinds of fossils they contain. 
 
 But the phenomena of tides, of dawn and sunset, of the 
 year's seasons, with their shortening and lengthening days, 
 and, above all, of eclipses, force us to pursue the science of 
 the earth's celestial sisters, Astronomy, which, in turn, has 
 a distinct bearing on the possibilities of that inexplicable 
 energy with which the sciences which remain to be enumer- 
 ated are concerned namely, life. 
 
 Our reference to Palceontology has, indeed, already borne 
 some reference to that energy, since fossil remains are relics 
 of bodies which once had life. 
 
 The two great groups of living things, plants and animals, 
 were long supposed to be so widely separated that each was 
 treated of by a separate science only. Now, however, so 
 many deep resemblances are known to exist between them 
 that we have been forced to treat with them together as one 
 whole, in the science of living things, as Biology. Living 
 things being classed in the two great, so-called kingdoms of 
 
AN ENUMERA TION OF THE SCIENCES 3 1 
 
 plants and animals, it is accordingly, as everyone knows, 
 divided into the sciences of Botany and Zoology. But every 
 animal and plant has to be considered according to its form 
 and structure on the one hand, and according to the activi- 
 ties of all its component parts. Those activities are treated 
 of by Physiology. Structure may be considered in its larger 
 division as existing in one or many species (Anatomy), or in 
 its microscopic division the structure of the component 
 " tissues " of the organism (Histology]. The structure of the 
 various kinds may be studied in reference to many or all 
 others, simply as to matters of fact, or with the aim of dis- 
 covering general laws of structure (Morphology). Yet another 
 science investigates the modes in which each species and 
 group of animals or plants is developed from its germs (Em- 
 bryology, Development, and Ontogeny], and the mode in 
 which it may be conjectured to have been derived from an- 
 tecedent species (Phylogeny). But living creatures have to 
 be considered with respect to the relations they severally 
 bear to space (Biological Geography], as also to past time, 
 which brings us once more to palaeontology. 
 
 A special science, which has been termed Hexicology, 1 is, 
 moreover, devoted to a study of the relations which exist 
 between organisms and their environment as regards the 
 nature of the localities they frequent, the temperatures and 
 amounts of light which suit them, and their relations to 
 other organisms as enemies, rivals, or accidental and invol- 
 untary benefactors. 
 
 Finally, as resuming and uniting all the sciences which 
 deal with the various bodies which compose the universe, 
 comes the science of the material universe considered as one 
 whole namely, the science of Cosmology. 
 
 After these sciences, acquaintance with which is necessary 
 for a complete knowledge of man, may follow that science 
 
 1 &<3. Habit, state, or condition. 
 
32 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 which concerns him specially and directly namely, Anthro- 
 pology. This science studies the various physical conditions 
 needful for human existence, as the various subdivisions of 
 biology investigate the conditions necessary for the life of 
 other organisms also. Such are the studies of Human 
 Anatomy and of the lower activities, i. e., Human Physiology. 
 But since man has powers and characteristics which other 
 organisms do not possess, additional sciences are devoted to 
 the study of such additional facts. Thus Ethnology occupies 
 itself with the various races into which mankind is divided, 
 while Philology examines the languages they speak, and 
 History describes their successive appearances and disap- 
 pearances, their aggregations into tribes and nations, their 
 migrations, wars, and the series of events which have taken 
 place, their form of government, and the actions both of 
 their rulers and of the classes they ruled over. The study 
 of the various conditions which have been, or which now 
 exist, or which might be beneficial or hurtful to the race, is 
 known by the awkward term Sociology. The science of 
 Politics deals with the various kinds of civil aggregations in 
 which men do or may exist, with the probable or certain 
 benefits and defects of each. Man's conceptions of right 
 and wrong and the relations which thence arise between 
 each individual and other human beings standing to him in 
 a multitude of different relations, constitute the science of 
 Ethics, while ethical relations have been supposed to extend 
 to some various real or imagined superhuman intelligences, 
 so constituting Religion. 
 
 In connection with these latter sciences comes the study 
 of man's lower and higher mental powers, together with the 
 probably psychical powers of lower organisms, namely, the 
 study of Psychology, closely connected with which are Logic 
 and Philosophy or Metaphysics, about which enough has, we 
 venture to think, been already said in this chapter. 
 
AN ENUMERA TION OF THE SCIENCES 33 
 
 Finally, and last of all, comes the special subject of this 
 work, namely, the study of the ultimate grounds of all 
 knowledge and of all science of whatsoever kind the science 
 of Epistemology. 
 
CHAPTER III 
 
 THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 IN our enumeration of the principal sciences, as also 
 in our initial chapter, we have taken for granted that 
 the ordinary and spontaneous judgments of mankind as to 
 the external world are true and valid. But before proceed- 
 ing any further in our endeavour to apprehend the ground- 
 work of our science, we must carefully consider the question 
 as to its objects. We must endeavour to attain as true a 
 knowledge as possible concerning the nature of those things 
 which science occupies itself about. 
 
 The sciences of psychology and logic occupy themselves 
 with the human mind, its powers and processes, its mental 
 images, its feelings and emotions, its thoughts and infer- 
 ences. But mechanics, astronomy, geology, biology, etc., 
 are commonly thought to busy themselves about things 
 which, though we apprehend them by mental acts, truly 
 exist independent of the mind, and form parts of a really 
 existing external world. 
 
 Now, of course, we can know nothing which we do not in 
 some way perceive or indirectly gain information about by 
 eye or ear or some sense organ, and everything we appre- 
 hend we apprehend as in various ways related to other 
 things, as well as to our own mind. Every object, there- 
 fore, of which science can take cognisance, is only known to 
 us through a variety of mental states which we term feelings, 
 
 34 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 35 
 
 reminiscences, inferences, or apprehensions, and amongst 
 the latter are apprehensions of such object's relations: both 
 its relations to other things and its relations within its own 
 being its external and internal relations. Every object, 
 therefore, looked at as regards our apprehension of it i. e. , 
 merely subjectively may be said to consist of a plexus of 
 such mental states or " states of consciousness." 
 
 It is also true that not only can we know nothing about 
 any object except by means of some mental state of our own 
 being, but that were it possible to preserve such mental 
 states in their entirety while the object they referred to was 
 annihilated, our mind, and therefore our knowledge, might 
 remain unaffected thereby. It is notorious that under 
 abnormal conditions, things may seem to be perceived which 
 do not in fact exist, as also that there may be existences 
 which, to exceptional individuals, remain unperceived as 
 the odour of the rose to one congenitally devoid of all olfac- 
 tory power, its red hue to one who is colour-blind, and the 
 cry of the bat to very many persons. 
 
 May it not then be that no independent external world 
 really exists at all, and may not the " esse " of every seem- 
 ingly independent thing be " percipi" ? We know with 
 absolute certainty (with the certainty of reflex consciousness) 
 that we have ideas ; may they not be the only real exist- 
 ences ? 
 
 This, as the reader well knows, is Idealism. But idealism 
 has much to say for itself. 
 
 Such could not fail to be the case, seeing how many illus- 
 trious men of a very high order of intellect have professed 
 and do profess idealism, and it is far indeed from being 
 confined to pure metaphysicians. Many distinguished cul- 
 tivators and teachers of physical science declare themselves 
 to be idealists. 
 
 Its advocates ask : 
 
36 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 " What possible ground can anyone have for not being an 
 Idealist? If we examine any object, as for example an apple, 
 what are really its various qualities ? Are they not rather ours 
 than the apple's ? We think that we look at it, but all we see is 
 a definitely shaped patch of colour, and that is a sensation of 
 our own. We take it up and hold it to the nose, when we per- 
 ceive its apple-odour. But that is only another of our sensations. 
 We may grasp it, feel it, and squeeze it, and these acts will occa- 
 sion a number of other sensations through our skin, muscles, and 
 the nerves supplying both, and these sensations are merely our 
 own feelings once more, though we refer them to an imagined 
 object and say that it is rounded and rather hard. We may tap 
 it on a table or drop it on the ground, when we shall hear sounds ; 
 in other words, we shall experience sensations of another order. 
 Finally, we may bite it, and so have other experiences of resist- 
 ance overcome and a pleasant flavour ; but the taste is certainly 
 not in the apple, but in us. It is but one mental state the more. 
 Do what we may we cannot by examining any so-called material 
 object arrive at anything more than modifications of our own 
 mental states different feelings. Other feelings we have, in- 
 deed, of a less vivid kind. These, however, are nothing but 
 faint revivals of sensations previously experienced, or of feelings 
 of the modes in which such previously experienced feelings have 
 stood one to another. Such ' faint revivals ' and * faint feelings 
 of modes of sensation ' we call ' ideas.' These vivid and faint 
 feelings are the only things which can be perceived by us, and 
 the whole of our knowledge consists of nothing else. Therefore, 
 as far as we know, nothing exists or can exist except as some- 
 thing felt and perceived. We cannot even conceive anything 
 otherwise existing, and therefore the very essence of * existence ' 
 must consist in being perceived. Evidently an * idea ' or a * sen- 
 sation ' can be like nothing but an idea or a sensation. A colour, 
 taste, smell, or sound can be like nothing but a colour, taste, 
 smell, or sound. We can have no experience and no knowledge 
 of anything in any object, e.g., in an apple, which exists under- 
 neath (so to speak) its size, solidity, shape, colour, smell, and 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 37 
 
 taste, and which supports these qualities, but which itself can 
 never by any possibility be perceived. What Idealism denies, 
 therefore, is not the existence of that which we really perceive, 
 and which we habitually call ' external things.' It only denies 
 the existence of a something underlying what we call external 
 things, which * something ' is a mere phantom, a creation of the 
 fancy, and cannot be attained to by any of our senses, but is 
 equally out of the reach of them all. If ordinary people when 
 they speak of any object mean to refer to what they actually per- 
 ceive (and which we cannot any of us know otherwise than as a 
 mere plexus of our feelings), then they are Idealists all the time 
 without knowing it, as Idealism fully accepts and asserts the ex- 
 istence of such things so actually perceived. Idealism does not 
 contest the existence of any one thing which we can feel, per- 
 ceive, or even imagine of anything which we can apprehend 
 either by sensation or reflection. That things which we see with 
 our eyes and touch with our hands do really exist and are really 
 known to us, it does not in the least question. It only denies 
 that in these really known and existing things there is an under- 
 lying, unknowable and unimaginable * substance,' which in some 
 mysterious way supports the qualities which our senses perceive. 
 In denying the existence of this unknown and unknowable * sub- 
 stance,' it deprives men of nothing which they can even imagine, 
 and therefore of nothing they can really miss. If the word * sub- 
 stance ' be taken in the vulgar sense for a collection of all the 
 1 qualities ' quantity, shape, weight, colour, etc., etc., which 
 compose an object as we know it Idealism can never be accused 
 of taking it away, for, according to Idealism, it is that alone 
 which exists. But if 'substance ' be taken in a so-called 'philo- 
 sophic ' sense for something external to and independent of the 
 mind which supports all the ' qualities,' the existence of which 
 the mind recognises, then Idealism may be accused of taking it 
 away, if one may be said to take away a thing which never has 
 been or can be perceived to exist or be even imagined so to do. 
 Far from inculcating any disbelief in the senses or in what the 
 senses tell us, Idealism attaches the very highest value to the senses 
 
38 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 and to their teaching. It no more doubts the existence of 
 what is seen, heard, or felt, than it doubts the existence of the 
 mind which sees, hears, or feels. Nothing, therefore, can be 
 more absurd than the criticisms of those persons who say that 
 Idealists, to be consistent, ought to run up against lamp-posts, 
 fall into ditches, and commit other similar absurdities. Idealism 
 is not only a thoroughly logical' system, but also one quite in 
 harmony with every-day life, its perceptions and its duties. It is 
 obvious that we can never get outside ourselves, or feel the feel- 
 ings of anyone else. We can only know our own sensations and 
 ideas. The existence of these sensations and ideas is sufficient 
 to explain our whole experience, and we are not idly to suppose 
 that other things exist when such 'other things' are altogether 
 superfluous for explaining any of the phenomena we are or can 
 become acquainted with. As we cannot know anything beyond 
 our own ideas, why should we affirm that there is anything be- 
 yond them ? It is impossible for us to even imagine anything 
 existing unperceived. We cannot imagine matter existing in the 
 absence of mind, for in the very act of imagining it we are com- 
 pelled to imagine someone perceiving it. It is, of course, easy 
 enough to imagine trees in a park or books in a library, and no- 
 body by to perceive them. But so to do is only to form in the 
 mind certain ideas which we call books and trees, and at the 
 same time to omit to form the idea of anyone perceiving them. 
 But the person so imagining them must himself be thinking of 
 them all the time. To show, or even to know, that anything was 
 existing independently of the mind, it would be necessary to 
 perceive it while it remained unperceived, or to think of it while 
 at the same time it remained unthought of, which would 
 manifestly be an absurd contradiction and a downright impossi- 
 bility. Idealism, therefore, does not contradict the assertions of 
 common-sense, or cause any practical inconvenience to him who 
 maintains it, seeing that it only denies what is but a figment of 
 perverse Metaphysicians a groundless and utterly irrational be- 
 lief in a necessarily unknown and unimaginable entity, about 
 which no one of our senses can tell us anything whatever." 
 

 THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 39 
 
 Such is idealism as put forward and defended by its in- 
 genious and estimable author, Bishop Berkeley, whose piety 
 led him to explain our ideas and perceptions as the result of 
 the direct action of God upon our minds ; the whole visible, 
 audible, and tangible universe being the product of the 
 energy of the divine mind so acting upon us. 
 
 This explanation, could we accept it, would indeed en- 
 able us to know at once what is the groundwork of science. 
 But we by no means see how to reach our goal by so short 
 a journey. We need not even linger over this pious hy- 
 pothesis, since, so far as we know, no one now adheres to it. 
 
 Nor has idealism remained unmodified in other respects. 
 It began with the assertion that we can know nothing but 
 sensations and ideas the latter being generally interpreted 
 as plexuses of faintly revived sensations. Still it must al- 
 ways be manifest to anyone who would carefully examine 
 his own mental states, that his sensations were very rarely 
 noted or attended to as such, but that his mind was almost 
 always occupied, not about ' ' feelings, ' ' but about ' ' things. 
 Even Berkeley himself allowed that we might reasonably 
 speak of " things " and habitually employ our notions of 
 what we so spoke about as if they were what he said they 
 were not, namely, absolute external existences independent 
 of the mind. Things were for him, as they are for modern 
 idealists, stably associated groups of sensuous experiences, 
 and not by any means mere passing feelings of the moment. 
 Berkeley denied, and idealists deny, that we can have any 
 notion of an object save in terms of sense-perception, and 
 this is so far true that, as before pointed out, 1 we can have 
 no conception of anything, however abstract, save by the 
 said mental images or imaginations. 
 
 As our readers know, Berkeley's denial of the existence 
 of material substance was followed by Hume's denial of the 
 
 1 See ante, p. 9. 
 
4O THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 existence of any substance of mind, and his representation 
 of our own being as only made up of a succession of fleeting 
 feelings, their mode of succession being modified by custom. 
 According to Fichte, all that exists is the self, or subjective 
 Ego, the thoughts of which constitute the universe (the 
 system of Solipsism). According to others there is an ob- 
 jective Ego, of which our own existence is but a thought. 
 For modern transcendental idealists, a " thinking subject " 
 is the source of relations and of the world they constitute ; 
 for, as we before said, nothing exists unrelated. 
 
 It would be beside the purpose of this book to enter upon 
 a description of the different forms of idealism. What con- 
 cerns us is not their various affirmations, but the denial in 
 which they all agree the denial, namely, that we do, or 
 can, know and perceive an independent external world, con- 
 sisting of objects known to us as things in themselves, and 
 possessing a number of objective qualities which are revealed 
 to us through our subjective sensations.. 
 
 Many of our readers may think idealism so unreasonable 
 as to feel unwilling to pursue any further the question of its 
 truth or possible validity. If, however, they are really in- 
 terested in the inquiry to which this volume is devoted, they 
 can hardly rest satisfied without coming to some decision as 
 to whether the groundwork of science has to do with 
 14 thoughts " only, or whether it has necessarily also to do 
 with " things." 
 
 It is easy to laugh at idealism, but unless it contained 
 some important truth, it would never have spread as it has 
 done, and captivated so many men exceptionally gifted. 
 
 Its propagation, moreover, is a remarkable and interesting 
 example of the vitality and influence of the English mind. 
 For the whole of the philosophy of Germany and Holland, 
 from Spinoza to Hartmann, has been a result of the mental 
 seed first sown in men's minds by Berkeley, who explicitly 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 41 
 
 produced what was implicitly contained in Locke. When 
 we call to mind that Berkeley begot his parricidal child, 
 Hume; that Hume set going the partially antagonistic, yet 
 largely similar, system of Kant ; that Kant begot Fichte, 
 and Fichte produced Schelling and Hegel, and these again, 
 by a revulsion, Schopenhauer and Hartmann it seems im- 
 possible to deny that English thought, from Locke through 
 Berkeley, has been far more influential than aught else in 
 the domain of philosophy, save the Greek mind as manifested 
 in Aristotle. 
 
 It is easy also to be unjust to idealism in the following 
 way : Because idealists affirm that perceptions consist of 
 plexuses of feelings of various kinds actual feelings and 
 grouped images of past feelings it may be represented that 
 they (idealists) occupy themselves exclusively about their 
 own feelings, and thus treat as the objects of perception what 
 are merely the means of perception. But idealists no more 
 especially observe their own sensations and feelings than 
 other people do ; they are, like other people, occupied about 
 " things perceived." The difference is that we, and most 
 men, affirm that through our feelings the mind becomes 
 aware that material objects consist of extended corporeal 
 substance, though of that substance in itself we have no 
 direct knowledge, but only apprehend it through its object- 
 ive qualities, the existence of which is made known to us 
 through our sensations. 
 
 Idealists, on the other hand, deny the reality of this uncog- 
 nisable substance, and deny also that we can know it to be 
 really and objectively extended, existing apart from the mind, 
 and they further deny the reality of anything apart from 
 mind, usually seeming to mean a human mind, though many, 
 when pressed by argument, will postulate an objective non- 
 human mind and often a divine mind, as the necessary and 
 indispensable cause of the existence of anything whatever. 
 
42 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 Now, as before said, we have no intention of entering 
 upon any question touching religion in this work, but merely 
 of treating of such questions as seem to us necessary for any 
 investigation of Epistemology. 
 
 We have, therefore, no intention of denying that the ex- 
 istence of a divine mind is a necessary condition for the 
 existence of anything else, and we have just as little intention 
 of affirming it. But we are perfectly convinced that objects 
 and substances can, because they do, exist apart from our 
 own mind and apart from any mind we can have any direct 
 knowledge of, or even imagine, as existing. Certainly we 
 have no direct perception, no intuition, of the existence of 
 a God ; nor do we believe that such an intuition exists in 
 the minds of other men, while we (our individual selves) 
 have a direct perception, an intuition, of the existence of a 
 real, extended, external world existing independently of our 
 own mind and of any mind, as above stated. 
 
 Anyhow, we are convinced that the existence of a God 
 can only be known through a process of inference based 
 upon things and actions perceived ; and it appears to us a 
 very illogical proceeding to affirm that objects cannot be 
 perceived save as related to a certain entity, which entity 
 itself cannot possibly be known to us except by the help of 
 objects not perceived as being so related. 
 
 Nevertheless (as we think), idealism enshrines an import- 
 ant truth, namely, the truth that our apprehension of the 
 world about us is much less perfect and complete than is 
 often supposed. Our perceptive powers are inadequate to 
 supply us with a complete knowledge of nature, which, as it 
 appears to us, may be very different from what it might 
 appear to any intelligences higher than our own. 
 
 It is certain^-quite apart from any system of idealism 
 that the material bodies about us (assuming that there are 
 such bodies) must possess powers and qualities which our 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 43 
 
 present senses are entirely unable to detect. Had we (as be- 
 fore suggested) an organ of sense fitted to enable us to ap- 
 prehend " magnetism," as our eyes enable us to apprehend 
 " light," how modified might not the aspect of the world 
 become ! We rejoice in the beauty of wild flowers and the 
 gay plumage of biijds, some of which delight us with their 
 song; yet, though we are not idealists, we do not hesitate 
 to affirm that their colours and their notes are not by any 
 means just that which they seem to us to be. The most 
 startling and impressive lesson we have had in the present 
 century is that taught us by the Rontgen rays like light, 
 yet so different from it with such unexpected powers of 
 penetration that wood is to them, as it were, translucent, 
 as the iron rod of a lightning-conductor is for electricity a 
 tube down which it tumbles. 
 
 We may seem to have thus delivered ourselves up to the 
 idealists with our hands bound ; yet such is by no means the 
 case. We, however, most willingly acknowledge the merits 
 and the intellectual gifts of its supporters. But those sup- 
 porters are nevertheless relatively very few in number, in 
 spite of the great temptations and the two special attractions 
 which idealism holds out to inquirers about, and students 
 of, philosophy. 
 
 Its first attraction for them consists in the fact that the 
 system is exceedingly easy of comprehension. No difficult 
 and sustained acts of mental introspection are needed to 
 understand it. All that is required is to see clearly the dif- 
 ference between " things " and their " qualities," to recog- 
 nise that no " things " can become known to us except 
 through their " qualities," and to recollect that all the ex- 
 perience we have of these consists in our own sensations, 
 imaginations, and perceptions. 
 
 The second attraction which idealism presents is due to 
 the fact that it seems to carry the novice in philosophy into 
 
44 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 a region very much above that of ordinary men. For him 
 a wonderful change has taken place. What common persons 
 regard as the most stubborn and solid realities he is enabled 
 to transform into an airy pageant consisting of nothing more 
 substantial than a ceaseless series of feelings and ideas; yet 
 all the time his elevated position causes him no practical in- 
 convenience, because it is the boast of his philosophy that 
 it in no way contradicts the assertions of common-sense, but 
 only denies the existence of what no one ever did or ever 
 can perceive, namely, " material substance." 
 
 He may also assert though, as we shall shortly see, in 
 this he is mistaken that idealism is not out of harmony 
 with " science " any more than it is irreconcilable with 
 " common-sense " ; and he can certainly appeal (as before 
 said) to distinguished men of science who affirm that they 
 are idealists. 
 
 Some of our readers, influenced by such representations, 
 may be inclined to say to us: " Why, if these so-called 
 ' facts ' bodies and their activities can be conveniently 
 dealt with as so many ' bundles of feelings,' and if we may 
 speak of such ' bundles of stably associated feelings ' as 
 ' objects ' and ' things,' why should we not be content so to 
 call them ? Why should we not leave all disputes about the 
 truths of idealism on one side, concern ourselves only with 
 what both parties thus agree to term ' things ' and ' objects,' 
 and to treat them as if they were really independent entities 
 quite external to the mind ? " 
 
 Certainly we do not for one moment seek or wish to deny 
 that idealists may be very good scientific men, and do excel- 
 lent scientific work ; nor, for the purposes of physical science, 
 are the conceptions of such scientific idealists unserviceable 
 for the scientific ends to which they are directed, though (as 
 will be shortly urged) their scientific conceptions are not 
 really idealistic, but are like those of ordinary persons. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 45 
 
 Nevertheless, as we have before observed, for our present 
 purpose (namely, the exploration of the groundwork of 
 science) it is necessary to determine whether the foundation 
 of science is entirely mental or partly mental and partly 
 material ; and there is a yet graver consideration which for- 
 bids us to rest contented with a philosophical concordat, and 
 compels us to do our best to arrive at a satisfying solution as 
 to the system of idealism. 
 
 This yet graver consideration refers to the nature of our 
 intellectual faculties. No man can get behind human 
 reason, and no rational man will make any attempt so to 
 do. A belief in a real, external, and independent world of 
 things in themselves appears to most men to be an abso- 
 lutely certain and self-evident truth. But if idealism is true, 
 then " absolutely certain self-evidence " can be no sufficient 
 guarantee of the truth of that for which it vouches. We 
 should thus be reduced to a state of uncertainty and sceptic- 
 ism, casting a shade of doubt over every proposition what- 
 ever. But in such a state of mind it would indeed be a 
 hopeless task to seek to investigate the groundwork of 
 science. The question as to idealism must therefore be 
 examined to the extent of our ability as a necessary pre- 
 liminary for any possible satisfactory conclusion with respect 
 to Epistemology. 
 
 We have done our best to present the case of the idealists 
 fairly. What is now to be urged on the other side ? 
 
 In the first place, as we said before, most men are not 
 idealists. Indeed, the professed adherents of that system 
 constitute but a very small portion of the most educated 
 part of mankind. Secondly, even idealists themselves can- 
 not help entertaining and acting on the notions common to 
 other men. It is not merely that they make use of ordinary 
 phraseology about " perception " and " things perceived," 
 but they habitually as we shall shortly see give to the 
 
46 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 terms they use the ordinary signification, and reserve their 
 idealistic interpretation for the time they are occupied with 
 philosophising. The most distinguishing character of the 
 notion all men have of the reality of an extended, external, 
 independent world, is the absolute inevitableness of that 
 notion, which holds sway over idealists as well as others. 
 
 It has been said that the inevitable character of this notion 
 is due to " natural selection." Men who did not promptly 
 make their actions accord with it, would, it is urged, be very 
 quickly eliminated, and only those most ready to act as if 
 an independent external world existed would survive. Thus 
 it is that this notion has become ingrained in survivors. 
 
 But, as we shall see later on, 1 our firmest, clearest, most 
 certain and highest perceptions cannot have been due to 
 " natural selection." If, therefore, there is some efficient 
 cause which has, independently of such selection, produced 
 our highest and most certain perceptions, applicable to all 
 ages and every part of the universe, a fortiori it could have 
 also independently produced the very minor effect of en- 
 abling us to become aware of the present state of the world 
 about us. We shall here contend that such awareness is of 
 an intuitive character, and that we possess a direct intuition 
 of " the extended " i. e., of the various extended bodies 
 which make up the material world. Nevertheless, all intui- 
 tions do not stand on the same level, and, as we have just 
 implied, our intuition about " extension " does not stand 
 on the highest level but on one below that upon which 
 rest those ultimate first principles of knowledge with which 
 Epistemology directly deals, and which will be carefully con- 
 sidered in our last two chapters. Had it this highest degree 
 of certainty, it would be impossible for us even to entertain 
 about it that sort of fictitious doubt which idealists possess, 
 nor could any dispute take place as to whether the inevitable 
 
 1 Chapter ix. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 47 
 
 character of our notion about the external world is either an 
 inference or a delusion. 
 
 But before proceeding to argue in favour of the reality as 
 well as the inevitableness of our conviction as to an external 
 world, it may be well to state, as clearly as we can, what 
 that reality according to us is. It may be expressed as 
 follows : 
 
 " All the different bodies and substances of the universe 
 about us really exist independent of the mind, and with 
 equal reality, whether they be perceived or not. Through 
 our senses our intellect becomes directly aware of their 
 existence, as ' things of themselves,' and of some of their 
 objective qualities. Those qualities, however, are unlike 
 the sensations external bodies excite in us ; though our per- 
 ceptions, aroused by our sensations, do correspond to such 
 objective qualities. External material bodies exist inde- 
 pendently of us, and have a substantial reality in addition 
 to that of the qualities we perceive, and our perception of 
 them also does not in any way essentially alter them." 
 
 That this position is the true one is, we think, shown (i) 
 by the natural spontaneous judgment of mankind ; (2) by 
 the careful examination of the dicta of our own mind, and 
 (3) by what we learn through science. 
 
 The first of these three arguments meets with no con- 
 sideration on the part of idealists, on the ground that to the 
 multitude it has never been given to understand what ideal- 
 ism is. But in the eyes of persons who are not idealists 
 that argument may well, nevertheless, have some value, 
 since it is plain that the spontaneous judgment of mankind 
 accords with what even animals practically learn through 
 their senses. A wide river is an objective obstacle to the 
 progress of a man's dog, as well as to that of the dog's 
 owner; and a rotten fruit on the ground is plainly not only 
 an external reality to the human observer of it, but also to 
 
48 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 the various insects which gather on its surface. Certainly 
 those who hold that the inevitable nature of our sentiments 
 about a really independent external world has been produced 
 by the action of " natural selection," must allow the validity 
 of our impressions about it, since they suppose it was the 
 action of that very world which eliminated those persons 
 whose impressions did not correspond with sufficient ac- 
 curacy to fatal objective realities. 
 
 But, in the second place, let the inquirer firmly fix his 
 mental gaze upon his own personal experience, as, for ex- 
 ample, when playing a game of billiards. Is it possible for 
 him to believe, as he cannons and " goes in off the red," 
 that the balls he perceives are but groups of vivid and faint 
 feelings, and not real, extended, independently existing 
 bodies which really move, and, by striking, impel each other 
 in different directions as ordinary people think they do ? 
 Who that hears the pleasant voices of his children as they 
 are playing in the garden, or even when silence succeeds to 
 their audible merriment, can doubt their independent object- 
 ivity entirely apart from his own feelings ? Should shrill 
 cries break that silence, and the father, rushing out, find 
 that one of his children has met with a serious mischance, 
 not only his feelings and his actions, but his inmost thoughts, 
 however determined an idealist he may be, will be in full 
 accord with those of any other man similarly circumstanced. 
 We are persuaded the more the reader examines into the 
 dictates of his own mind during his actual experiences from 
 day to day, the more profoundly he will be impressed by a 
 conviction that real external bodies things in themselves 
 exist and act independently of his feelings, wishes, thoughts, 
 or perceptions, and that he has full and valid ground to be 
 absolutely certain about it. This will be brought home to 
 anyone with special vividness while undergoing a surgical 
 operation without the use of anaesthetics. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 49 
 
 But it is physical science which specially vouches for the 
 reality of an external independent world. 
 
 The advocates of idealism generally content themselves 
 with explaining, according to their system, some of our 
 simple perceptions an apple, a landscape, the furniture of 
 a room, trees in a park, books in a library, etc. Such things 
 may plausibly be represented as made up of bundles of 
 feelings, because bundles of feelings are the means by which 
 we perceive them, and because we have but to gaze on and 
 contemplate a quiet scene devoid of conspicuous interactions 
 between its parts. But what we learn through science is 
 something very different: it is a systematic investigation as 
 to what are the causes of different phenomena and their 
 various modes of action on one another. It has, therefore, 
 to do not only with our perceptions themselves, but also 
 with the causes of our perceptions. 
 
 Although, as before said, we do not question the eminence 
 or the services of men of science who are idealists, neverthe- 
 less we believe idealism to be fundamentally out of harmony 
 with physical science. We strongly suspect that the intel- 
 lectual nature of idealistic physicists is too much for them ; 
 and that, though they may be ever ready to represent the 
 objects of their study and experience as so many complex 
 groups of feelings, they really regard them (in common with 
 other people) as independent objects with special qualities 
 and powers. We think thus because, though (as we have 
 just observed) it is easy enough to translate mere objects 
 perceived into groups of feelings and relations between 
 them, it is much more difficult to investigate and describe 
 the reciprocal actions of objects (as, e. g., of the sun and 
 moon on the tidal wave) as only relations between ideas 
 and not as activities of external, absolutely independent ex- 
 tended things which really affect each other. 
 
 There can be no question about the fact that observations 
 
5<D THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 and experiments are accepted by scientific men as real 
 objective facts and occurrences, and the whole of physical 
 science, understood as men of science themselves understand 
 it, is based upon that way of regarding them. It would be 
 ridiculous to pretend that when astronomers, chemists, and 
 anatomists are tracing the motions of the heavenly bodies, 
 or analysing minerals, or ascertaining the course followed by 
 a nerve or an artery, they remain all the time convinced that 
 they are really investigating the relations borne by groups 
 of past and present feelings to other such groups, and 
 nothing more! 
 
 It is very certain that, but for their conviction they were 
 dealing with independent realities and discovering really ob- 
 jective truths, the physical sciences would never have at- 
 tained their present degree of development. If idealism 
 were true, then the advance of science must simply have 
 been due to a profound mistake, and, the mistake having 
 been once found out, can we believe that scientific advance 
 would continue, or could even maintain itself where it is ? 
 
 The attempt has been made more than once, and with 
 admirable perseverance, to describe truths of physical 
 science in terms of feeling and no more; and the attempt 
 has always ended (as it must always end) in complete failure. 
 
 A few concrete examples may bring home to the reader 
 the intenseness and inevitability with which the notion of 
 external things in themselves, really existing independently 
 of the mind, is forced home upon the intelligence of the 
 man of science by his own pursuits. 
 
 Leverrier, by studying the movements of the planet 
 Uranus, came to the conclusion that they were influenced 
 by some external body in such a way as to lead him to be- 
 lieve that Uranus was not, as up to that time supposed, the 
 planet of the solar system which was most distant from the 
 sun, but that there must be another revolving round that 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 51 
 
 luminary at a yet greater distance. After further study he 
 predicted the place in the heavens where that yet more dis- 
 tant orb would be found. The prediction was put to the 
 test, with the result that the planet now known as Neptune 
 was there found. In this instance science did not merely 
 predict that a new body (for idealism " a new group of feel- 
 ings ") would be found if looked for, but it affirmed " how " 
 and " why " it would be so found. It was a statement as 
 to causation. 
 
 Another memorable prediction, in another science, was 
 made by Cuvier. The fossil skeleton of a small beast having 
 been found in the quarries of Montmartre, the great French 
 naturalist, seeing a peculiar conformation in its jaw, foretold 
 that when the lower part of the trunk was laid bare, two 
 peculiar bones present in but few beasts would there be 
 found. Friends assembled to see the prediction verified, 
 and it was verified. 
 
 The late Sir Richard Owen ventured to affirm that a huge 
 extinct animal of South America (which had been furnished 
 with very powerful limbs and tail) had been in the habit of 
 obtaining its nourishment by uprooting trees and then feed- 
 ing on their leaves. It was objected to this hypothesis that 
 had animals of that kind really been in the habit of so pro- 
 curing their nourishment they would now and again have 
 had their heads broken by falling trees. Owen thereupon 
 re-examined the head of the beast which had been the sub- 
 ject of his investigations and conjectures, and found that its 
 head had been broken. But he also found that the skull of 
 the animal was so constructed as to enable it to. endure such 
 fracture with very little inconvenience. 
 
 How can these facts be adequately expressed in terms of 
 idealism ? Is it possible to regard the matters thus per- 
 ceived as but groups of feelings or ideas in any mind, 
 human or non-human ? If we do not recognise the relation 
 
52 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 of an actually " falling tree " as a cause of an independently 
 existing " fractured skull," the whole point and meaning of 
 the venerable naturalist's sagacious inference would be lost. 
 
 Similarly with respect to the planets Uranus and Nep- 
 tune. The philosophy of idealism puts before us nothing 
 but groups of feelings or ideas in the idealistic sense of 
 the word which co-exist and succeed arbitrarily without 
 any rational order or any evident reason why they should so 
 co-exist or succeed. The idealist cannot say why the group 
 of feelings he calls " the movements of Uranus " should be 
 related to another set of feelings, distinguished as " the in- 
 fluence of an external body," or why the feelings known as 
 " looking through a telescope " should be succeeded by 
 those called " seeing the planet Neptune." 
 
 And modern science teaches us not only that real, ex- 
 tended, material bodies interact upon each other apart from 
 anybody perceiving them, but also that they so interacted 
 for untold ages before any human mind existed. It tells us 
 that the world, at first devoid of life, became fitted for it, 
 and ultimately fit for mind. The view which science opens 
 to us concerning the fact may be briefly expressed thus: 
 After an unknown but vast period of time, what we regard 
 as the oldest rocks yet extant were deposited, and after 
 multitudes of lower forms of life had had their day and dis- 
 appeared, huge reptiles came upon the scene, swam in the 
 ocean, sported in lakes and rivers, browsed in ferny forests, 
 and flitted through the air, all to disappear before the white 
 chalk of our Downs was finally deposited. Then beasts and 
 birds, strangely unlike those which yet live, came into being 
 and passed away unseen by any human eye. Genus suc- 
 ceeded to genus and species to species. Gigantic long-armed 
 apes bounded through the forests of Southern France, and 
 many kinds of monkeys chattered in the woods of what is 
 now Greece. At last the human form walked for the first 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 53 
 
 time on the earth's surface, and then came races destined 
 to dwell for centuries in caves, rudely chipping flints for 
 weapons, but by degrees exhibiting signs of an innate love 
 for art. Race succeeded race, till at last came those whose 
 annals constitute the dawn of history and from whom we 
 proceed. Such is the teaching of science. Such is that 
 process of evolution in our world, which it declares to be 
 certain and indisputable. 
 
 But how is it possible to describe such relations and con- 
 ditions in the language of idealism ? 
 
 If idealism were true, evolution would indeed be nothing 
 but a dream, nor could any branch of physical science be 
 considered more substantial. 
 
 If nothing exists but feelings and " ideas," and some un- 
 perceived cause theistic, pantheistic, or atheistic which 
 produces them, then everything must depend upon the 
 action of that agent, and all secondary causes and interac- 
 tions, such as those by which one body is supposed to act 
 on another, can be nothing but deceitful illusory appear- 
 ances. 
 
 But since physical science largely consists in a search after 
 secondary causes and the laws of the interaction of bodies 
 one on another, a system which can have nothing to say to 
 either must be quite useless to such science. 
 
 It is indeed the fact that, while following their special 
 scientific pursuits, idealists must, temporarily, if tacitly, ab- 
 jure their idealism. As men of science it is impossible for 
 them to be idealists, and this some of them confess, candidly 
 avowing that it would be absurd to try to describe scientific 
 processes and state scientific conclusions in idealist phrase- 
 ology, while all that science needs is to describe co-existences 
 and successions of appearances and in no way to explain 
 them. But surely such avowals amount to nothing less than 
 a condemnation of the system which makes them necessary. 
 
54 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 Physical science requires us to admit the absolute reality 
 of extended bodies which can move or be moved, and which 
 have real objective relations of number and position and 
 really act and react on one another. Newton's discovery is 
 much more than a mere description of appearances, and of 
 the theory of evolution the same may certainly be affirmed. 
 Any system of philosophy, therefore, which denies the ob- 
 jective reality of primary qualities, cannot serve as a ground- 
 work of science. Either physical science has no foundation 
 at all or its groundwork is other than idealistic. 
 
 Now, according to received idealism the world is consti- 
 tuted by " relations," the source of which is a " mind " or 
 " thinking subject." 
 
 Certainly no object can exist without relations. These 
 are real objective relations of which the mind is not the 
 " source " but the " observer." The immense majority of 
 these objective relations exist in independent objectivity, 
 and would continue so to exist were every mind imaginable 
 by us annihilated. On the other hand, it is surely too 
 absurd to regard the world as made up of relations without 
 objects which are related. 
 
 The mind in perceiving these " objective relations " i. e., 
 the circumstances in which different things stand to each 
 other cannot, of course, do so without having correspond- 
 ing subjective mental perceptions, which may be termed 
 " subjective relations " since they make known to us the 
 corresponding "objective" ones. But the latter exist 
 quite independent of any imaginable mind. Our perceiving 
 or not perceiving them is a mere accident of such relations, 
 and in no way affects them save as regards their being or 
 not being perceived. 
 
 A simple illustration or two will, we think, make this 
 clear. Thus, e. g. , a definite relation exists between a piece 
 of rock and a volcano in eruption which ejected it, but this 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 55 
 
 relation is substantially similar between a rock and volcano 
 perceived and a rock and volcano of the Antarctic Continent 
 which never have been perceived, or between a rock and a 
 volcano on the averted surface of the moon, if such things 
 there exist. Multitudes of relations probably exist between 
 various heavenly bodies, which relations existed long before 
 the formation of our solar system. 
 
 But idealists may be asked the following question : If all 
 the truth concerning the universe consists not in the existence 
 of extended things, but in relations essentially " mental" 
 how comes it that the outcome has been the production of 
 what idealists must regard as a universal delusion ? For 
 the practically universal belief of mankind that external, in- 
 dependent, extended bodies really exist on all sides of us 
 must, in their eyes, be just such a delusion. A philosophy 
 with such a result hardly commends itself to the inquirer 
 after the ultimate tests and grounds of truth. 
 
 We therefore do not hesitate to affirm that the existence 
 of the " extended " that is, of real, independent, external, 
 and extended bodies is an intuition. It is a revelation 
 concerning the world about us directly apprehended by our 
 intellect through the medium of our sense-perceptions. It 
 is a fact certainly true, and shown so to be by its own evi- 
 dence. ' Why " extended things exist and " how " they 
 exist we know not, and may never be able to know ; but 
 that they do exist is a truth intuitively perceived, and this it 
 is which gives to our perception of the external world that 
 character of " inevitableness " which has been recognised as 
 pertaining to it. The possession of this direct intellectual 
 apprehension, together with the need for us of the due action 
 of our organs of sense to call it forth, well explains both 
 our power of directly perceiving what idealists are unable to 
 understand our perceiving, and also the obscurity and con- 
 fusion into which idealists themselves have fallen. 
 
56 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 It is no doubt a wonderful thing that such apparently im- 
 perfect means as our organs of sense and general bodily 
 organisation supply, should enable us to know so much 
 concerning the world about us the extension of bodies and 
 their relations as to size, shape, solidity, motion, and num- 
 ber, yet it is not more wonderful, essentially, than is the 
 rest of our knowledge and, in fact, the whole of our mental 
 powers. How we get any knowledge at all, how we see 
 objects, how we feel anything is most mysterious, and all 
 our knowledge, deeply considered, is very wonderful. On 
 the occurrence of certain changes in our bodies, induced by 
 surrounding agencies, we experience ' 4 sensations. ' ' Through 
 such sensations (actual and remembered) sense-perceptions 
 are aroused, and by the aid of mental abstraction ideas are 
 called forth, and we perceive what we know to be " external 
 objects." Through our own activities and by things done 
 to us we recognise our existence, our feelings, and our ac- 
 tions. Nothing can be more wonderful than our faculty of 
 memory, which gives us absolutely certain knowledge of a 
 continuously existing being our own self the continuous- 
 ness of which it is impossible for our senses to perceive, for 
 they can perceive nothing but what is present to them. 
 There is really no more difficulty in our perception of the 
 external world about us than in our experiencing a sensation 
 of azure or of sweetness. The fact is so, and we perceive it 
 to be so ; and the act by which we do this is no more really 
 marvellous in one case than in the other ; or rather every act 
 of knowledge is alike marvellous. We know things, and 
 we know that we know them. How we know them is a 
 mystery indeed, but one about which it is idle to speculate, 
 as it is absolutely insoluble. The oft-repeated question 
 " How is knowledge possible ? " is therefore one of the most 
 idle and futile questions which can be asked. 
 
 It is an absurd question, because it leads to a regressus ad 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 57 
 
 infinitum. To every possible reply to it, giving some ex- 
 planation of its possibility, it may be rejoined " but how is 
 our knowledge of that explanation possible ?" and so on 
 forever. We cannot (once more) get behind the intellect, 
 and therefore no ultimate explanation of our intellectual 
 power is possible. No intellectual perception can be more 
 than self-evidently true. We are compelled to trust our 
 intellect, as we are compelled to trust that we are not mad; 
 and that we are not altogether mad or deluded is shown us 
 by the fact of our seeing quite clearly that if we were de- 
 luded our judgments could not be trustworthy. 
 
 The mystery of knowledge runs parallel, as we have just 
 said, to the mystery of sensation. We feel things savoury 
 or odorous or brilliant or melodious, as the case may be; 
 and, with the aid of the scalpel and the microscope, we may 
 investigate the material conditions of such sensations. But 
 how such conditions can give rise to the feelings themselves 
 is a mystery which defies our utmost efforts to penetrate. 
 Yet, because we cannot discover this, we never doubt our 
 sensations or the fact that we feel them ; and we have as 
 little reason to doubt our intellectual intuitions or the facts 
 we know as made evident to our intellect through our 
 feelings. 
 
 By our recognition of this direct intellectual intuition of 
 the existence and, in part, the nature of things around 
 us, science and its progress can be both understood and ad- 
 vanced without the denial of one single fact for which ideal- 
 ism vouches. Its affirmations are justified while its negations 
 can by such recognition be shown to be unreasonable though 
 explicable, and almost necessary upon that conception of 
 the nature of ideas which idealism adopts, and the insecure 
 basis upon which it builds. 
 
 By its affirmations, our feelings are correctly described, 
 but its great fault is its non-appreciation of the profound 
 
58 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 difference which exists between them and our ideas, and its 
 consequent practical negation of the higher source of all our 
 knowledge. That the affirmations of idealism are justified 
 is unquestionable. Idealists rightly affirm that, as we have 
 before pointed out, 1 we can know nothing without the aid 
 of our sensations, that a plexus of our own feelings accom- 
 panies every one of our perceptions, and that not even our 
 most abstract ideas are destitute of such accompaniments. 
 In our first chapter we endeavoured at some length to make 
 clear the profound distinction which exists between " feel- 
 ings," however complexly associated together, and intel- 
 lectual conceptions, and a similar distinction exists between 
 (i) the associated plexuses of feelings, vivid and faint, which 
 constitute a "sense-perception" of an object an act 
 which cannot truly be called intellectual, but seems to be 
 merely a form of sensitivity and ( : 2) the non-sensuous 
 activity, which is an intellectual perception a an act of 
 " consciousness." 
 
 The latter is not the mere apprehension of an object as an 
 individual " thing," 3 but as a " thing of a certain kind," 
 and the recognition that it is such is the result of our power 
 of abstraction. Idealists are too apt to confound " sensuous 
 universals " with true ones. A sensuous universal is a mere 
 blurred or defective mental image of an object which has 
 been produced by the successive experience of a variety of 
 individual objects of the same kind. Thus the successive 
 sensuous impressions produced by a number of horses, 
 different in size, colour, and somewhat in shape, have, of 
 course, their effect upon the imagination, and reminiscences 
 of these concur with freshly received impressions to aid us in 
 eliciting the perception and idea of a horse by a direct intel- 
 lectual act. But that the intellectual perception and idea 
 of a " horse " is not a mere amalgam of modified imagina- 
 
 1 See ante, p. 9. 8 See ante, p. 9. 3 See ante, p. 6. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 59 
 
 tions, or a mere generalised mental image, is plain from the 
 fact that the imaginations which have helped to call it forth, 
 may persist in the mind side by side with it, which they 
 evidently could never do if the idea was made up of such 
 imaginations. 
 
 A true universal the intellectual conception supported 
 by the sensuous universal is a single idea called forth by 
 a natural activity of the mind, and is by no means a mere 
 collection or residuum of blurred sensuous impressions. Our 
 power of abstraction instantaneously analyses the thing 
 perceived into its ideal qualities, and also synthesises them 
 as belonging to a really existing concrete object. It appre- 
 hends both the object's concrete individuality (that it is 
 " this thing here ") and also the kind to which it pertains 
 (that it is a member of a group, which, as a group, exists 
 only in the mind). 
 
 How different is the intellectual apprehension from the 
 sensuous affection is clear from the fact that changes in 
 such sensuous affections may only render the intellectual 
 apprehension a more complete and perfect unity. Thus, if a 
 solid cube be suspended by a string and then turned round 
 before us, we can never see all its surfaces at once, and its 
 square faces, as we see them in perspective, do not look 
 square but lozenge-shaped. Nevertheless, these incomplete, 
 defective signs not only serve to give us an accurate per- 
 ception of the cube, but its revolution, though it changes 
 our sensuous impressions, only makes our intellectual con- 
 ception more complete and stable while the former changes, 
 the latter remains the same throughout. 
 
 Thus every material object whereof our senses can take 
 cognisance, has various qualities its size, shape, solidity, 
 colour, etc. and acts upon our senses accordingly. 
 
 Its qualities affect us in response to our activities of eye, 
 ear, hand, etc. Our two eyes form two slightly discordant 
 
60 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 images of it, and our hands and arms may give us numbers 
 of synchronous and successive feelings respecting it. Sim- 
 ultaneously with these sensuous impressions, we have a per- 
 ception of the object and its qualities. But that perception 
 is by no means correspondingly multiform. The per- 
 ception is one intellectual cognition resulting from a multi- 
 tude of sensations and reminiscences. Our attention may, 
 of course, be directed to any one of its qualities, but if so, 
 what we then directly perceive is no longer the thing itself 
 but the quality in question. 
 
 As it is with the revolving cube, so also changes produced 
 by our own movements may make our intellectual cognition 
 of what surrounds us more unchanging. When walking in 
 Notre Dame, as we progress, the pillars of the double row 
 of columns on either side of its nave successively change 
 their relative positions in our eyes. Yet they remain in 
 reality unchanging, and by the experiences thus received 
 we gain a clearer intellectual apprehension of their true 
 relative positions than we could do by remaining fixed to 
 one spot. 
 
 Some opponents affirm that what is really different be- 
 tween a mere sense-perception and an intellectual perception 
 of an object, is that to the latter a word is applied, and that 
 apart from this word there would be no difference. Such a 
 view is, of course, the teaching of the oft-refuted system 
 known as " Nominalism." 
 
 That the essence of intellectual perception and conception 
 does not lie in the word, is shown by the fact that the same 
 idea may be made known by different words, different modes 
 of speech, and even by gesture language. 1 But it is plain that 
 if the intellect had not universal ideas, then general terms, 
 such as ' ' dog, " " horse, ' ' etc. , would be meaningless. It may 
 also be asked how general terms ever came to be, if the mind 
 
 1 See below, Chapter vii. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 6 1 
 
 knew nothing but individual things ? Again, even nominal- 
 ists must profess to understand the meanings of certain 
 words; but since almost all words are universals, it is plain 
 that they could not understand them unless they really 
 possessed universal ideas. If we can perceive the general 
 nature of certain words, why not of other things also ? But 
 nominalists agree with idealists in one fundamental error. 
 They confuse the objects of cognition with the means of 
 cognition, not, as before said, because they pay any excep- 
 tional attention to their feelings, but because they regard 
 what are really, for both idealists and non-idealists, " ob- 
 jects perceived ' ' as being mere plexuses of feelings, plexuses, 
 therefore, of what are in truth but " means of perception." 
 Objects are known directly by means of our mental affec- 
 tions. It is true that modern idealists describe our experi- 
 ence as made up of " perceptions" ; but by" perceptions " 
 they mean congeries of vivid and faint feelings, and not that 
 direct intellectual cognition which exists over and above, 
 and in addition to, " feelings " of whatsoever kind they may 
 be. Thus our perception of material, external, independent 
 objects they declare to be not a direct intuition but an 
 inference. 
 
 The term " inference " means, as we all know, the percep- 
 tion by our mind of the fact that one truth is implicitly 
 contained in other truths antecedently known. Now it is 
 quite true that an inference, though if it exists it must be 
 conscious, may excite our attention but very slightly and be 
 rapidly forgotten. Can our perceptions of objects, then, 
 be due to such hasty, little adverted-to, and speedily forgot- 
 ten inferences ? Now inferences, even of that kind, can 
 be recognised by reflection to have occurred if they have 
 done so. Thus, if we have on a dark evening mistaken a 
 stranger for a friend, we can recognise afterwards the cir- 
 cumstances which occasioned our mistake, and made us 
 
62 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 hastily conclude from insufficient evidence that the fact was 
 otherwise than in truth it was. But it is impossible to 
 recognise the presence of any act of inference in our ordinary 
 perceptions of objects, however much we may look back and 
 analyse such perceptions. When, for example, after having 
 perceived an apple, we look back on our various sensations 
 thus derived, we do not find that they have constituted the 
 premises of any conclusion, but, on the contrary, we see 
 that they have directly revealed the apple they have made 
 it present to our intellect. It is thus with the immense 
 majority of our perceptions. Why, then, should we deem 
 them to be inferences, when they exhibit to us no signs of 
 having been produced by an inferential process ? Is it one 
 bit more wonderful or mysterious that we should perceive 
 "objects" than that we should perceive " inferences "? 
 An " inference " a perception that one thing must be true 
 because its truth is implicitly contained in other things is 
 surely a much more complex and involved mental process 
 than is the direct perception of an object. For this reason, 
 then, if for no other, we should not conclude that we have 
 made use of a process of " inference " when nothing in our 
 minds assures us that we have really done so. 
 
 What probably has caused some persons to mistake " per- 
 ception " for " inference " is the fact that every perception 
 is the result of a number of psychical processes sensations 
 and imaginations associated in complex groups and a variety 
 of unconscious ' affections also. This process of complex 
 sensuous association it is which seems to have been denoted 
 under the self-contradictory term, " unconscious inference." 
 
 Yet if our perceptions of objects were " inferences," then, 
 since no inference can exist without data, the data of such 
 perceptions must be the feelings which objects occasion in 
 us. But if that were the case, then such feelings must be 
 
 1 As to this, see below, Chapter vi. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 63 
 
 primarily observed, or else no consequence could be deduced 
 from them. In that case it would be quite true to charge 
 idealists with mistaking the means for the objects of percep- 
 tion, and in spite of all their denials, we should have to 
 affirm that they do direct their attention upon their sensa- 
 tions and feelings in an exceptional and most misleading 
 manner. 
 
 But that " perception " is not " inference " is very plainly 
 shown by the fact that we can and do obtain a reflective 
 assurance of the truth of our perceptions when we clearly 
 do not employ inference to obtain it. 
 
 No one can deny that there is a plain distinction between 
 " attention " and " inference," and we may gain an in- 
 creased certainty for our perceptions by acts of attention 
 alone. The reader will, we think, readily admit that he 
 sometimes perceives an object consciously, but without 
 paying particular attention to it; and that when his atten- 
 tion to it is by some circumstance aroused, he has then a 
 far clearer consciousness of it and of its nature than before. 
 He can, indeed, thus " make sure " by merely, as it were, 
 tightening his sensuous grasp of the object and carefully 
 focussing his sense-perceptions regarding it. 
 
 Thus perception is no process of inference from known 
 signs to a before unknown notion of an object, but is a spon- 
 taneous interpretation of signs (which themselves are by no 
 means expressly adverted to) by a natural power the mind 
 possesses, and which is rapidly perfected by exercise. By 
 it we gain an immediate assurance (and, by attention, can 
 gain an augmented assurance) that a perception is certain 
 and needs no proof. 
 
 But there remains one supremely important point to con- 
 sider. If our perceptions were " inferences," our intellect 
 would necessarily be thereby altogether stultified. For no 
 " inference " can be certain which does not repose on per- 
 
64 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 ceptions previously acquired and known to be true. If, 
 therefore, every perception .were an inference, we should get 
 a rcgressus ad infinitum, and be incapable of ever acquiring 
 a perception of any truth whatever. Anterior to all possible 
 truth, we must know truths which are not inferences, which 
 require no proofs but are evident in themselves. 
 
 The fact that we have a direct and immediate knowledge 
 of objects which are made present to the mind through our 
 sensations, is a fact fatal to idealism. It alike justifies the 
 spontaneous and reflective declarations of our own minds, 
 when once we have clearly understood the great difference 
 which exists between (i) intellectual conceptions and per- 
 ceptions, and (2) their merely sensuous accompaniments. 
 
 The conviction, then, that science is really concerned not 
 alone with thoughts but also with external, independent, 
 and extended realities, is so far justified. 
 
 It only now remains forus to consider the various objec- 
 tions which have been brought against the validity of this 
 conviction. 
 
 The stock objection is based on the supposed constant 
 and inevitable delusion we are led into by our sensations of 
 colour, sound, smell, and taste the secondary qualities of 
 bodies as contrasted with their primary qualities of exten- 
 sion, size, shape, number, motion, etc. It is then further 
 argued that if we are entirely deceived as regards the second- 
 ary qualities, the primary qualities can be in no better case, 
 each of them being, to our experience, but a plexus of our 
 own feelings, vivid and faint. 
 
 And we freely concede that in this idealists are so far right 
 that if we could not directly know things in themselves, but 
 only the impressions they make on us, then the said primary 
 qualities might be no more than combinations of certain of 
 those groups of muscular feelings and feelings of effort and 
 resistance which have been made use of by us in acquiring 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 65 
 
 such ideas. Nevertheless, there is a great difference in our 
 notions of these two sets (primary and secondary) of quali- 
 ties. For, in the first place, colours and sounds are each 
 perceived by one sense only ; but in examining the solidity, 
 extension, figure, number, and motion of any object we 
 perceive, we can bring various modes of feeling to confirm 
 the evidence of vision. We find also that doubt as to 
 primary qualities carries with it very different results from 
 a disbelief in the objective validity of our impressions as to 
 secondary ones. If we became convinced that nothing in 
 the remotest degree like the secondary qualities we know 
 of existed in the perceived objects themselves, the world 
 would lose very much of its charm for us. Flowers would 
 have lost their tints as well as their fragrance, and the 
 melpdy of birds, no less than their brilliance of plumage, 
 would have disappeared ; but otherwise things would remain 
 substantially as they were. But with the disappearance of 
 primary qualities the solid earth itself would vanish, and we 
 should even lose the companionship of that most faithful 
 ally our own body ! If we hold three marbles in our hand 
 and we are told they are not truly of the tint we suppose, or 
 that they really have an odour of garlic which escapes our 
 notice, we are not greatly disturbed thereby. If, however, 
 it were asserted to us that they were not three and not solid 
 objects at all, that we could not touch distinct parts of the 
 surface of any one of them, or that they were not spherical 
 in shape, or that when we dropped them from one hand to 
 the other there was no real motion in them apart from our 
 feelings of touch, effort, and movement, then, if we were 
 not idealists, we should consider the assertor, if serious, to 
 be irrational, or that he regarded our own rationality as 
 dubious. 
 
 The colour of any object, as we all know, is said to be 
 nothing but a result of the undulation of certain waves of 
 
66 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 light reflected from its surface to us, and we are asked how 
 there can possibly be any real resemblance between that 
 condition of any object, which causes it to reflect such 
 waves, and our sensations of colour ? How also, it is further 
 asked, can there be any possible likeness between the real 
 condition of a body thrown into rapid vibration and the 
 sounds those rapid vibrations occasion in us ? As well, they 
 exclaim, might a wound be like the knife which inflicted it 
 thus tacitly asserting the necessary adequacy of a cause 
 for its effect ! 
 
 Now, of course, as we have before said, no subjective feel- 
 ing can be like an objective quality belonging to an external 
 object. The simplest rustic, with his senses about him, 
 knows as much philosophy as that. But he also knows that 
 there are in external things real qualities which give rise to 
 the feelings he experiences. This can be easily ascertained 
 (as we have ascertained it) by questioning such rustics in 
 language they can understand. The conviction they really 
 entertain is the spontaneous and universal conviction of 
 mankind, from a Sussex cowherd to the greatest philosopher 
 of Greece ; and a spontaneous and universal human convic- 
 tion should be accepted and acquiesced in unless there are 
 valid reasons against our so doing. 
 
 We must here revert to a point before noticed. In our 
 perception of any object it is made present to our mind by 
 feelings to which we do not advert. Its presence is a pres- 
 ence in the mind's perception and not in the feelings (vivid 
 and faint) which accompany such perception. Moreover, 
 though " subjective feelings " cannot be like " objective 
 qualities" there may nevertheless be a true correspondence 
 between our subjective perception of an object and its object- 
 ive mode of existence. For, as we have before pointed out, 1 
 we can know things which never were and never could be 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 10, n. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 6/ 
 
 felt or imagined, and there is the greatest possible difference 
 between " feelings " and " ideas." 
 
 Now let the reader examine what his own mind tells him, 
 and we are confident he will see that in perceiving any 
 body to be one body, or to be solid or to be extended or to be 
 moving, he has, in each separate case, one single and simple 
 idea and not an amalgam of feelings of " touch," " press- 
 ure," " effort," and " sight," however indispensable such 
 feelings may have been in order to call forth perceptions and 
 ideas of unity, solidity, extension, and motion. 
 
 Moreover, the idea of extension may exist apart from 
 visual feelings, for the blind have it, and apart from tactual 
 feelings, for it is given by sight alone especially with the 
 twofold grasp of objects our two eyes simultaneously afford 
 us. That an idea can persist unchanged amidst changing 
 sensuous experiences and remain single though revealed to 
 us by sensuous experiences of many and such diverse kinds, 
 we have already seen. 1 That feelings of different kinds are 
 required to arouse our idea of extension, does not show that 
 the idea is a plexus of feelings any more than that " coal " 
 is " digging " because we may have to dig in order to obtain 
 it. The nature of an idea and the modes of its elicitation or 
 acquisition are two very different things. 
 
 Our idea of "force" again becomes known to us by 
 means of our sense of effort, of resistance, and of resistance 
 overcome, and such sensations form the occasion through 
 and by which our intellect comes to perceive that surround- 
 ing bodies have powers corresponding to our own. Some 
 persons pretend that we thus commit the absurd mistake of 
 attributing to inanimate bodies around us activities abso- 
 lutely like our own. But, in fact, we only attribute to such 
 bodies powers which have a certain analogy with our own. 
 If we try to pull a man up from the ground and fail because 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 59, 60. 
 
68 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 he is stronger than we are, and if we try to raise a piece of 
 rock and fail because it is too heavy, we can indeed perceive 
 a certain analogy between the effect on us of the man and 
 the rock, but the difference between the two cases is also 
 plainly evident to the intellect, however alike may be our 
 sensations in the two cases. Similarly with respect to 
 our ideas of " number," " extension, " etc. By means of 
 our sensations, and the relations between them, we arrive at 
 something fundamentally different from either namely, 
 an apprehension of external, objective conditions of real, in- 
 dependent bodies. But, as we have said before, these 
 conditions are utterly unlike the sensations and relations 
 between sensations which serve to make such objective 
 conditions known to us. In considering these things we 
 must never fail to recollect 1 that it is not " sense" but 
 " intellect," not our " feelings" but our " perceptions," 
 which are our ultimate criteria of certainty and truth. 
 
 And our intellect surely tells us that by means of our 
 sensations we attain to a certain degree of truth with respect 
 even to the secondary qualities of bodies, and certainly even 
 the common belief on the subject is nearer the truth than 
 its negation can be. 
 
 We are sometimes told that were there no eyes or ears 
 darkness and silence would be universal. Now our notion 
 of light is quite inadequate to make its essential nature 
 known to us as it might be known by some intelligence of a 
 higher order than our own. But, nevertheless, if light as 
 we know it, and sound as we know it, are imperfect cogni- 
 tions because thus subjective, the vepy same objection ap- 
 plies to our notions of " darkness " and " silence." They 
 are as much subjective as our sensations of colour or melody. 
 A world without eyes or ears would be neither light nor 
 dark, neither sonorous nor silent, but in a condition abso- 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 13, 14. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 69 
 
 lutely unimaginable by us. Yet that world would be far 
 more like the brilliant one we know than it would resemble 
 one plunged in darkness. For since we suppose the physi- 
 cal forces, sun, moon, and stars, meteors, volcanoes, and 
 phosphorescent organisms to exist in it as they do now, all 
 the objective conditions of light, save sense-organs, would, 
 by the hypothesis, be present, while the objective conditions 
 of what, to our senses, is darkness, would not be present. 
 Though all sensations of eye and ear would, of course, 
 vanish from such a world, yet the objective qualities those 
 sensations reveal to us would continue to exist. Other per- 
 sons, again, think that they get nearer to the absolute truth 
 of things by considering colours and sounds to be really 
 " modes of motion " different orders and different degrees 
 of " vibrations." But, as we have seen, the very same 
 cavils may be brought against the validity of our perceptions 
 of primary qualities as against our perceptions of secondary 
 ones. In that case " vibrations " would be nothing but as- 
 sociated, vivid and faint, muscular and tactual feelings, and 
 such must at least be as unlike the objective causes of light, 
 colour, and sound as are the conceptions of ordinary persons 
 with respect to the latter. 
 
 Bearing these facts in mind, let us once more consider 
 some objections made by idealists against those who believe 
 in an independent, external world of real, extended objects 
 possessing real, objective qualities. 
 
 The iridescent tints of minutely grooved surfaces do not 
 really deceive any more than the effects of coloured lights 
 or tinted glasses, or than distant mountains which look 
 purple make us suppose that they are actually purple when 
 seen close at hand. 
 
 The effects of bodily injuries are often cited as evidence 
 of the untrustworthiness of judgments our sensations induce. 
 Men who have had a leg amputated sometimes feel as if they 
 
7O THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 still had it, and also feel pains in their vanished toes. But 
 no one would surely be so foolish as to pretend that our 
 feelings, or even our perceptions, are independent of our 
 bodily organisation ; if, then, that organisation be impaired, 
 the action of our sensitive faculty would be likewise im- 
 paired, nor should we be surprised if our perceptions were 
 thereby also occasionally misled. If our normal organisa- 
 tion is so arranged as to guide us right, it should be small 
 wonder to us if it sometimes guided us wrongly when in an 
 abnormal condition! But, after all, even though a man 
 whose leg has been amputated may suffer with pains like 
 those he might feel if he still had his toes, that does not 
 lead him to believe that he has actually still got them ! 
 
 If objects may appear different in size and shape as we 
 change our place in respect to them, though they in truth 
 do not so change at all, not only are we not thereby deceived, 
 but, as we have seen, 1 our knowledge of their objective 
 qualities may be thereby perfected. A pea held between 
 our crossed first and middle fingers will not feel like one 
 pea, but like two peas. But there is no real deception in 
 this. No one would afBrm that the mere touch of a surface 
 can impart knowledge as to the bulk and solidity of the ob- 
 ject touched ; for this, we must also have some experience of 
 resistance. If, then, with the fore and middle fingers we 
 simultaneously touch two opposite surfaces and find we can- 
 not bring our fingers together, the feeling naturally arises 
 (from long experienced associations of sensations) that an 
 obstacle in the form of a solid body lies between them an 
 obstacle situated between the adjacent sides of those fingers. 
 But if we cross our fingers, then the pea touches those sides 
 of each finger which do not ordinarily touch the same thing, 
 but two different things, and this makes the single pea 
 naturally feel as if it were two peas. 
 
 1 See ante, p. 60. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 7 1 
 
 As everyone knows, various ingenious instruments have 
 been invented to produce optical delusions, but that in no 
 way makes the declaration of our perceptive faculty at all 
 less trustworthy. We are able, indeed, so to arrange things 
 as to invert or distort impressions ordinarily made; what 
 wonder, then, that our sense-perceptions sometimes be- 
 come inverted or distorted likewise ? But it is generally 
 the case that though our sense-perception is changed, 
 our intellectual perception remains perfect all the time, 
 and so enables us to be the better amused by the sense- 
 deception induced. 
 
 But, it may be urged, most people even now, and every- 
 one a few centuries ago, have been deceived by their senses 
 with respect to the motions of the sun and the earth, yet 
 the fact is, their senses did not deceive them. They only 
 drew too hasty an inference from what they saw, as a little 
 reflection will, we think, make obvious. Our sight gives us 
 no information at all with respect to motion, save indirectly, 
 /. e., as shown by changes of relative position between ob- 
 jects. Thus, when we are moving, we may, under some 
 circumstances, be quite unconscious of it, save for jolts, 
 jars, the feeling of meeting the air, and other incidents 
 which are no elements of motion, but merely its accidental 
 accompaniments. When travellers in a balloon ascend from 
 the earth, they are said to have no feeling whatever of their 
 movement, save by looking down on an apparently sinking 
 world beneath them. The feelings our senses give us, oc- 
 casion an intellectual apprehension of motion and of moving 
 things; but that apprehension, we can see by reflection, may 
 take place with or without inference. With regard to the 
 movement of the sun, there really is this relative change of 
 position a fact about which the senses give us accurate in- 
 formation. Our perception of this relative change of place 
 does certainly awaken in our intellect a perception of motion, 
 
72 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 but it does not, for it cannot, tell us where the motion is, 
 without processes of observation and inference. The sup- 
 posed perception of the sun's motion is an instance of an 
 inference, not noticed, perhaps, at the time, but clearly 
 recognisable by reflection. It is impossible for anyone to 
 really see the sun move. If we fix our eyes on it at sunset 
 we shall, indeed, from second to second, see that it has 
 more and more disappeared ; but we cannot see it move. 
 As to the movement of the sun, the mass of men never think 
 about its relation to that of the earth. The first observers 
 inferred that it moved, and that the earth stood still, and 
 their inference embedded in language, has so affected us, 
 that to this day everyone speaks of the " rising and set- 
 ting sun," even though he may know quite well that it 
 neither sets nor rises, but that the revolving earth gradu- 
 ally hides it from view and afterwards lets it be seen 
 once more. What men's senses ever did and do now 
 make known, are " changes of relative position between 
 the earth, on which the observer stands, and the sun," and 
 just such changes do really take place. Thus none of the 
 objections yet considered allow us to say that our senses 
 really deceive us. 
 
 And, indeed, with regard to the secondary qualities of 
 bodies, more might yet be urged in defence of the veracity 
 of our faculties respecting them than we have yet advanced. 
 No one has ever shown, or can, we believe, show, that it is 
 impossible for our intellect to obtain, through our sensations 
 of colour, sound, etc., the truest notions it is possible for 
 us to have concerning the objective qualities which give rise 
 to those sensations. The objective cause, whatever it may 
 be, must be admitted to be occult in each case, except as it 
 may be made more or less known to us by the sensations it 
 occasions. Granting, for argument's sake, the absolute 
 truth of the undulatory theory of light, the objective con- 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 73 
 
 dition of an object which causes it to select certain rays for 
 reflection must be admitted to be as yet quite occult. 
 Therefore, it cannot be denied that there may be such a 
 conformity between objective qualities and the effects they 
 produce on us, that those effects may be the best means 
 possible for giving us the best understanding we can attain 
 to of what those objective qualities really are. Though 
 those effects may be, and probably are, far from telling us 
 the whole truth, though the objective qualities that produce 
 them may be very differeit from such effects, and though 
 much ignorance about su';h objective qualities (the existence 
 of which we do know) m iy thus have to be added to our 
 ignorance about various other qualities which probably ex- 
 ist unknown to us nevertheless, our knowledge, however 
 fragmentary, is in part true, and, therefore, our faculties, 
 though inadequate to reveal to us much we might wish to 
 understand, are nevertheless not mendacious. But some 
 persons, strange to say, have affirmed that incomplete 
 knowledge is error ; and that what we know only in part, 
 we therefore know wrongly. 
 
 Yet such an affirmation is surely a most irrational one. 
 Is the statement, " The angles at the base of an isosceles 
 triangle are equal," false or erroneous, because it does not; 
 also express the facts which follow if its sides be produced ? 
 Is it false to say, "A gibbon has extremely long arms," be- 
 cause we do not also say, " No ape except a species of gib- 
 bon has a chin " ? 
 
 It is, of course, most true that no man can possess, with 
 respect to any object whatever, a knowledge of all its 
 relations (real and possible) with the rest of the universe. 
 But the impossibility of our being omniscient does not 
 prevent our having some knowledge which is perfectly 
 accurate, absolutely true, as far as it goes. Our know- 
 ledge, for example, of the numerical difference between 
 
74 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 two groups of marbles (one with three, the other with 
 five) is a perfectly true knowledge, and in no way tainted 
 with error. 
 
 The same example may serve to refute another and very 
 common objection to the veracity of our perceptions. Some 
 persons, while professing to know nothing but sensations 
 and sense-impresses, vivid and faint, yet believe as a sort 
 of faith in the existence of an independent material world, 
 quite unlike our perceptions, and yet the cause of them. 
 The men of this school do really believe in " independent 
 material objects " and " actual physical states," as realities 
 independent of their minds and of everyone else's. But, on 
 their system of knowledge, they can (since they say they 
 can know nothing but states of consciousness) only get this 
 belief of theirs by an act of blind and unreasoning credulity. 
 They also affirm our knowledge to be necessarily untrue, 
 because it corresponds neither with what is internal and 
 subjective, nor with what is external and objective. They 
 regard it as a sort of tertium quid which results from the 
 combined activity and interaction of both subject and ob- 
 ject, but resembling neither just as water resembles neither 
 the oxygen nor the hydrogen from the combination of both 
 .of which it results. But experience and reflection clearly 
 show us that our intelligence has the power of unconsciously 
 subtracting its own subjective element from the result. Let 
 us concede that every perception is produced by the com- 
 bination x-\-y ; x being the Ego, or self, and y the object. 
 Yet the mind has the power of supplying its own x, and 
 so we get x-\-y x, or y pure and simple. Unless such 
 were the case, how could we know the real numerical differ- 
 ence between three marbles and two marbles, between a 
 cube and a sphere ? Does any reasonable person doubt 
 that, in these matters at least, we attain to absolute object- 
 ive truth ? 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 75 
 
 It is clear that the mind can correct any such supposed 
 delusive tendency of its own, or the above facts could not 
 be known to us as perfectly certain and accurate objective 
 truths. Thus the mind unquestionably must possess the 
 power of transmitting to us a knowledge of at least some 
 facts and principles as they really and objectively exist. 
 Why should we distrust its other dictates ? Grounding all 
 our assertions on the positive declarations of our conscious- 
 ness, we can affirm that we really know (though more or less 
 imperfectly) things in themselves, and not a mere amalgam 
 made up of a mixture of the results of objective and subject- 
 ive influences results neither resembling ourselves nor the 
 world without us in any one respect. 
 
 As to the contention of idealists that the essence of all 
 existence " is " being perceived," we may freely allow 
 that nothing can exist in absolutely the same condition 
 when perceived as when unperceived, for in the former case 
 it is " a thing perceived," and in the latter case " a thing 
 unperceived," and " a thing unknown " cannot be identical 
 with " a thing known." But this contention is one which 
 is utterly trivial. Of course, things unknown cannot be 
 known while they exist as unknown objects, and of course, 
 again, a thing perceived by us does not exist in a state of 
 " being perceived by us " when we do not perceive it. But 
 our perceiving it or not perceiving it is (as we have more 
 than once urged) a mere accident of its existence, which ex- 
 istence continues on essentially the same, whether perceived 
 or not. Who has perceived the mountains on the other 
 side of the moon ; but are they the less real because no one 
 can perceive them ? Who perceived for untold ages the many 
 palaeozoic fossils which have been in modern times disen- 
 tombed ; but have they been less persistently existent on that 
 account ? Does want of being perceived impair the reality of 
 the thousands of fossils which as yet remain undiscovered ? 
 
76 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 Surely here, as in the former instances we noted, 1 physical 
 science is fatal to idealism. 
 
 Before finally concluding this chapter it may be well to 
 consider some special objections made by one of our most 
 esteemed idealists 2 against a non-idealistic conception of 
 the universe as being self-contradictory and replete with 
 illusion. 
 
 After the usual objections founded on the divergence be- 
 tween our sensations induced by the secondary qualities of 
 objects and the objective nature of the latter, he endeavours 
 to raise difficulties as to our perception of the extended on 
 the ground that the mode of inherence of its secondary 
 qualities and the relations holding between them 3 (" how 
 the qualities stand to the relations which have to hold be- 
 tween them "), are, on any non-idealistic system, inex- 
 plicable. 
 
 We have already protested 4 against the question, " How- 
 is knowledge possible ? " as a necessarily idle one. Our 
 knowledge of the " how anything is " must always repose 
 upon a previous knowledge of the fact " that it is." To 
 seek to know the " how " and " why " of every " that," is 
 to enter upon an inquiry which it is plain cannot possibly 
 have any end a necessary regressus ad infinitum. All men, 
 even idealists themselves, have, we are convinced, con- 
 sciously or unconsciously, an intuition of the extended. 
 Nevertheless, when affirming anything thus evidently true, 
 it is specially needful to guard against the appearance of de- 
 claring any other things to be evident which really are not 
 evident. Thus many persons assume that " the extended " 
 must possess secondary qualities, and, of course, our uniform 
 sensuous experience renders it impossible for us to imagine 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 51-53. 
 
 9 Dr. F. H. Bradley in his work entitled Appearance and Reality, 1893. 
 
 3 Ibid., pp. 14, 15. 4 See ante, p. 56. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 77 
 
 any extended object devoid of such qualities. Yet it really 
 is not evident that it must possess such qualities, though, 
 of course, its possession of them may in fact be necessary 
 for all that. 
 
 The " extended " must, of course, have some definite 
 quantity, but it is not evident that " corporeal substance " 
 must be extended, or, so to speak, be quantitatively ex- 
 tended in space. Let us suppose that the earth and the 
 moon were both simultaneously deprived of their extension 
 while remaining individually distinct, the one from the 
 other; they would, though not externally extended, have a 
 definite state of some kind, though we cannot imagine it 
 even so well as we can imagine what Newton said as to the 
 possibility of reducing the earth, without loss of substance, 
 to the size of one cubic inch. 
 
 Although merely speculative, it is well to recognise that 
 when Kant argued that the noumenon of substance did not 
 evidently demand the phenomena n of extension, he was not 
 unreasonable save in denying our intuition of extension as 
 a fact. We have no intuition of the essential nature of 
 material bodies of corporeal substance in itself such as 
 would warrant us in drawing the conclusion that it necessa- 
 rily postulates, short of annihilation, actual extension. But 
 in order to be able to affirm with certainty that the extended 
 the external world exists, it is by no means necessary to 
 know its intimate " nature," and the absolute exhaustive 
 truth about all or any of its qualities. " Qualities " and 
 " relations," as such, are, of course, mere abstractions, 
 though every one of them has a foundation in those real 
 things of which they are truly predicated. 
 
 The difficulties raised by Dr. Bradley are very largely 
 verbal ones, and result from the impossibility of our imagin- 
 ing what is beyond our sensuous experience, and from his 
 proneness to make use of exceedingly sensuous illustrations. 
 
78 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 Appearance, he tells us, 1 must belong and yet cannot be- 
 long, to the extended. 
 
 But it is not evident that something extended may not 
 exist in our vicinity which our sensitive faculties may be 
 unable to perceive, so that it cannot appear to them ; and it 
 is certain that multitudes of extended bodies exist in space 
 (so to speak) which never can appear to any human being. 
 So much for the first alternative. As to the second, " ap- 
 pearance " can and does belong to the extended, in so far 
 as it has objective qualities and powers which our faculties 
 are able to apprehend. The " appearance " is partly object- 
 ive and partly subjective, or rather it is in one sense the 
 former and in another sense the latter, just as we have seen 
 that colour and sound are both objective and subjective. 
 
 That the extended comes to us " only by relation to an 
 organ," and is " perceived through an affection of our body 
 and never without," is another objection. But why should 
 we not apprehend extension through our organs, and what 
 doubt does such a means of apprehending it cast on the 
 truth of our apprehension ? Why also should we doubt 
 the truth of the extension of our own body because we can 
 only perceive it by the action of one part of it upon another ? 
 
 Dr. Bradley says 8 : " That we have no miraculous intui- 
 tion of our own body as spatial reality is perfectly certain." 
 The word " miraculous " should not have been used by him 
 in this context, as it tends to excite an initial prejudice 
 against the view he opposes. Nobody pretends that we 
 have such an intuition, but that our possession of an evident 
 natural intuition is certain we do not hesitate to affirm. 
 Of course we cannot think till after we have begun to feel, 
 and our intuition of the body's extension is not gained with- 
 out experience and without multitudinous antecedent move- 
 ments between its various parts. But that intuition once 
 
 1 Bradley, loc. cit., p. 15. 2 Ibid,, p. 15. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 79 
 
 gained is not on that account a bit less clear and distinct at 
 a very early date. 
 
 There is no difficulty in the fact that nothing extended 
 can be perceived except in relation to thought which is 
 unextended. Who would expect that two extended but 
 thoughtless things could perceive each other ? What doubt 
 is cast upon our intellectual intuitions from the fact that 
 they cannot do so ? 
 
 That extended objects may be real in themselves, with 
 various relations to our percipience, is opposed by Dr. Brad- 
 ley on the ground that, " if a thing is known to have a 
 quality only under a certain condition, there is no process 
 of reasoning from this which will justify the conclusion that 
 the thing, if unconditioned, is still the same." 
 
 But here the use of the term " unconditioned " seems 
 quite unwarrantable. Because the conditions which accom- 
 pany perception may be absent, it by no means follows that 
 all conditions are absent. Indeed, it is clear and manifest 
 that no extended object can exist devoid of all relations to 
 the rest of the universe. The antithesis, therefore, is be- 
 tween the extended under " some " conditions, and the ex- 
 tended under " other " conditions, and, thus corrected, the 
 assertion is plainly erroneous. 
 
 We have only known the sun in so far as it is above the 
 horizon. But that does not prevent our being certain that 
 we could, were we supplied with certain helps, also see it 
 on the opposite side of the heavens. 
 
 That objection to the reality of qualities only known to 
 us through one sense one relation which is grounded on 
 the assertion that to affirm the reality of such qualities apart 
 from that relation is " more than unwarranted " is itself 
 " more than unwarranted." 
 
 For we always have more than one source of information 
 about the qualities of things. We have (i) our sensitive 
 
8O THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 faculty, which informs us of the subjective results of such 
 qualities, and we have (2) the intellect, which assures us that 
 our sensation has, under normal conditions, a real objective 
 cause. 
 
 That extension cannot be presented in thought, or thought 
 of except as possessing secondary qualities, we altogether 
 deny, though, as we have already affirmed, it cannot be im- 
 agined without them. 
 
 The former assertion is manifestly false. For though we 
 cannot think of our extended body except by the aid of 
 sensuous images, into which imaginations of secondary qual- 
 ities enter, nevertheless, thus aided, we can think of such 
 things as devoid of secondary qualities. If we could not do 
 so we should not be able even to discuss the question 
 whether the extended can or cannot exist without such 
 secondary qualities, nor could we have declared, as we have 
 done, that it is not evident to us either that they can or that 
 they cannot do so, and that an open mind is to be main- 
 tained there anent. 
 
 Dr. Bradley could not discuss the question either, unless 
 he had the " miraculous " faculty of writing about a ques- 
 tion concerning which he is utterly unable to think. 
 
 ' Extension," like quality (whether primary or second- 
 ary), is, of course, an abstraction, though with a very solid 
 foundation in extended things. 
 
 The reality of extension, once more, is for us a direct per- 
 ception. It is no inference, but an intellectual intuition 
 acquired through the ministry of sense. It is, of course, 
 most true that we can feel nothing of an object save the 
 subjective effects of its objective qualities: that in a lump 
 of sugar we have no sensitive perception of anything but its 
 whiteness, hardness, roughness, sweetness, etc., together 
 with its shape and its extension ; but we none the less know 
 that there is more. We have, as we before said, no intuition 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 8 1 
 
 of the corporeal substance in itself, but we have an evident 
 intuition of corporeal substance in conjunction with the 
 qualities our senses make known to us. This is the material 
 substance which Bishop Berkeley said he alone denied the 
 existence of, and the absence of which, he declared, would 
 be missed by none. But its absence would, indeed, be 
 missed by all ; for the plain man always thinks of a material 
 object as something real in itself over and above its qualities. 
 Such reality is apprehended by every healthy and normal 
 intellect. It is easy to laugh at Dr. Johnson's refutation 
 of idealism by kicking a stone. But that simple act was a 
 refutation of it, for it was an energetic manifestation of 
 Johnson's perception that he had an intuition of real, ex- 
 tended, independent objects. It was a mute expression of 
 a profound philosophic truth a truth which underlies all 
 physical science the truth, namely, that we have an intui- 
 tion of the extended. 
 
 After the most patient consideration it has been in our 
 power to bestow on Dr. Bradley's contention, we remain 
 convinced that he has succeeded neither in showing that 
 primary and secondary qualities stand on a similar footing 
 in the mind, nor that the latter are appearances only, and 
 are not known to us as revealing corresponding objective 
 realities. But if neither primary nor secondary qualities are 
 mere appearances, a fundamental mistake underlies his whole 
 contention, that the world as perceived and understood by 
 the mass of mankind is mere delusion. If, then, we are to 
 rise out of utter scepticism the irrational nature of which 
 will be later pointed out we are justified in shaking off the 
 prejudices of idealism. 
 
 These prejudices are ultimately due to a non-recognition 
 of the fundamental difference which exists between feelings 
 and ideas, between the impressions of our sensitive faculty 
 and the dictates of the pure intellect. They are therefore 
 
82 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 due to an utterly inadequate apprehension of the power and 
 dignity of human reason. 
 
 But if the system which underlies idealism were true, if 
 we had no means of perception save sensations and sense- 
 impresses (vivid and faint feelings), then we could have no 
 warrant for a belief in an external world, or for a conviction 
 that other minds existed in addition to our own. If we 
 could know nothing but complex associations of our own 
 feelings, what right could we possibly have to affirm that 
 anything else existed ? If we could in no way get beyond 
 our own being, the only absolute certainty for us must 
 be our own feelings, and so we become upholders of Solip- 
 sism. It would be all very well to talk of a divine mind which 
 produced those feelings in our mind; or of a material uni- 
 verse possessing many energies, whereof our own feeling was 
 one ; or of an impersonal absolute which became conscious 
 in our consciousness; or of a monistic universe, the absolute 
 unity of which has two sides one physical, the other 
 psychical like the one substance of Spinoza with its two 
 attributes, thought and extension. All these for the con- 
 sistent idealist would be so many pleasant or unpleasant 
 dreams, with no more body or coherence in any one of them 
 than in the mist of the morning. For 'such an idealist there 
 is but one firm reality his own sentient being, and of all 
 else he is evidently the creator (since everything he knows 
 is a plexus of feelings which his being has caused to exist), 
 though as to how he created the universe he need neither 
 know nor care to inquire. It is enough for him that he has, 
 in fact, produced it, and that its being depends absolutely 
 on his own. The divine mind, the material world, the ab- 
 solute, the uncogitable unity of the monists, and the sub- 
 stance of Spinoza, will by him be courteously bowed out or 
 unceremoniously kicked out, according to his idealistic 
 temperament, and he can logically remain, like the Indian 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 83 
 
 sage in peaceful contemplation of the plexus of feelings he 
 calls his own navel, as a symbol of that first cause and im- 
 manent upholder, from which all things have proceeded, 
 and in which all things have their only being. 
 
 This logical development of idealism finds small favour 
 with existing idealists. Solipsism is looked at askance with 
 evident dread by some, and vain attempts at its refutation 
 have been made by others. But it remains none the less 
 invincible on its rock of "nothing-known-but-feelings." It 
 was, as our readers know, first developed and upheld by 
 Fichte, though he ultimately abandoned it; and thus the 
 logical outcome of the system of idealism has been practi- 
 cally condemned by its own disciples. To the other ideal- 
 istic extreme, that by Hume, we will sacrifice no space, for, 
 in spite of its author's acuteness and great ability, it does 
 not really admit of logical statement, so utterly incoherent 
 is it, and so confident are we that its ingenious author had 
 no belief in it himself, but was laughing in his sleeve at his 
 inept admirers and disciples. 
 
 In opposition to the notion of solipsism that everything 
 we can perceive or imagine is but a mode of our own per- 
 sonality may be opposed the contradictory form of ideal- 
 ism, before referred to by us, 1 which would assert that our 
 personality is but a mode of the absolute or of some divine 
 existence. But, as Mr. Arthur Balfour has well remarked, 
 " the very notion of personality excludes the idea of any 
 one person being a ' mq^e ' of any other." 
 
 A system which would strongly, and with reason, deny 
 that it was idealist, may conveniently, with apologies to its 
 advocates, be here briefly referred to. 
 
 This at present popular system is Monism, which solves 
 the conflict between the advocates of mind and the advo- 
 cates of matter (as alone the source of all whereof we can 
 
 1 See ante, p. 40. 
 
84 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 have any knowledge) by denying them both and affirming 
 that nothing exists but a substance utterly unknowable save 
 as regards two of its aspects, one psychical, the other 
 material. According to it, thought is nervous tissue in mo- 
 tion just so far as nervous tissue in motion is thought, both 
 being eternally divergent and antithetical modes of a sub- 
 stance which is neither thought nor matter. 
 
 This system affords a seemingly easy way of explaining 
 the ever-recurring puzzle about " matter" and " mind." 
 How can mind (unextended and immaterial) ever possibly 
 act or be acted on by such a thing (extended and material) 
 as matter ? This question has tortured many choice minds 
 for more than two centuries, because men sought to obtain 
 an answer to it in impossible terms, namely, in terms of the 
 imagination. But it is utterly impossible for us to imagine 
 the action of mind on matter or of matter on mind, simply 
 because the mind never has been or can be a matter of 
 sensuous experience, and we can never imagine anything of 
 which we have not had such experience. 
 
 But our inability to imagine such action does not consti- 
 tute an argument of the slightest value against the reality 
 of such action (in ways which are beyond our power of im- 
 agination), if our intellect shows us good reason for thinking 
 that such action does, in fact, take place, and there is no 
 real evidence that such reciprocal action is impossible. 
 
 But because it is felt difficult to imagine the action of 
 mind on matter or of matter on mind, it is a curious method 
 of obtaining relief to assume the unique existence of some- 
 thing more unimaginable (because more unknowable) than 
 either, and take that as a satisfactory explanation ! 
 
 Matter we know and mind we know, but what is this x 
 underlying both, the only properties of which are the two 
 manifestations of existence (mental and physical) deemed 
 the very metaphysical antipodes of being ? 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 85 
 
 If it is difficult to understand matter and mind as recipro- 
 cally active, how can the emergence of entities so antitheti- 
 cal from one absolutely unique and common source be better 
 understood ? 
 
 We have an intuition of the extended the physical. Is 
 it possible that we should have a less perfect intuition of 
 our own consciousness ? Surely our reason tells us that we 
 know them both as evident existences and as existences pro- 
 foundly different. This is made manifest by the diversity 
 of their activities, and this diversity can be perceived in our 
 own intimate, unique, concrete being. 
 
 Suppose we are energetically opposing the entrance of 
 someone into the room we are in, by leaning the whole 
 weight of our body against the door of it. We have a dis- 
 tinct intuition both of our volitional effort and intention and 
 also of our body acting by its mere weight as a corpse or a 
 block of wood might do. 
 
 To disregard such positive intuition of two evident entities 
 thus different in action, in favour of an unthinkable entity, 
 with no apparent power of exercising activity in either mode, 
 is, in our humble judgment, little less than a deliberate 
 abandonment of philosophy gained by experience in favour 
 of a mere intellectually groundless fancy. 
 
 We hope that enough has here been said to justify the 
 dictates of the human intellect (as recognised by all but 
 idealists and monists) in its declaration that we have the 
 power of cognising an external, independent world of things 
 in themselves, real objects possessing real qualities, apart 
 from any perception of them by any imaginable mind. We 
 have maintained, and do maintain, that the existence of 
 such a world is (in our judgment) an absolutely certain and 
 self-evident fact, of which the intellect, through the ministra- 
 tion of the senses, acquires a direct intuition. Yet we will 
 proffer one more argument for the consideration of those 
 
86 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 who may still hesitate as to the final rejection of ideal- 
 ism. This argument springs from a recognition of the fact 
 that the contentions and objections put forward by idealists 
 remain as plausible as ever, even upon the hypothesis that 
 an external world exists. Let us assume, for argument's 
 sake, that a real, external, extended world of " things in 
 themselves " exists on all sides of us, we remaining the 
 beings we are. Could we possibly know of the existence of 
 such a world except by some influence it should exercise 
 upon our organs of sense ? Could we get at it in any way 
 except by means of our faculties conjoined with its influ- 
 ences ? It would, therefore, always be possible for men of 
 a certain turn of mind to declare they had no ground to ac- 
 cept the existence of anything save the " influences " and 
 the " faculties " themselves, and to deny the existence of 
 anything producing the former or anything possessing the 
 latter. Nay, let us suppose ourselves creatures possessing 
 a thousand different kinds of sense-organs, revealing to us a 
 mass of properties possessed by objects now quite unimagin- 
 able by us ; however great the number of orders of sensitivity 
 or of properties possessed by the external objects, the posi- 
 tion must ever remain the same. The external world could 
 never, under any circumstance, be known save through some 
 influence exercised by it on organs capable of in some way 
 responding thereto, and thus nothing could make evident an 
 external world (by our hypothesis supposed to exist inde- 
 pendently) to men bent upon regarding the mere means of 
 cognition as the object of cognition itself. 
 
 The systems which different idealists have put forward 
 are just those, and nothing more, which men, determined to 
 regard mere signs as everything, and utterly to disregard 
 their signification (a signification evident to the good sense of 
 all who are not blinded by an extraordinary intellectual per- 
 versity), are forced to construct. 
 
THE OBJECTS OF SCIENCE 8/ 
 
 To those who have so far followed us, then, it will be 
 clear that the objects of science are in part mental and in part 
 material. 
 
 Its objects are, in part, thoughts and all that concerns our 
 mental nature, but they also, in part, consist of material 
 things, possessing various powers 'and energies ; and all 
 these things (a knowledge of which the human mind can 
 attain to), as well as matters mental, are true and proper 
 objects of science. 
 
 But the human mind has never been satisfied with a mere 
 knowledge of facts. Having ascertained the fact that any 
 individual thing is (i. e., exists), its next questions are, what 
 is it and why is it ? What is its essential nature ? In what 
 relation does that nature stand to the natures of other exist- 
 ences ? What are we to think of the whole whereof it is a 
 part, that is, the universe ? What is the cause of the in- 
 dividual thing investigated ? Has it a purpose, or final 
 cause, as well as an efficient cause ? Finally, can anything, 
 and, if so, what, be said as to the nature and causation of 
 the universe itself ? 
 
 Beyond the knowledge we may be able to acquire about 
 our own minds, and beyond all we can ascertain about the 
 material universe, man has, by a natural, spontaneous im- 
 pulse, been ever driven to pass beyond all that is physical 
 and seek for metaphysical truth. Physics never have, and 
 probably never will content him. He will ever crave to add 
 thereto the science of metaphysics. That such a science 
 does or can exist many men devoted to this or that special 
 branch of physics energetically deny. 
 
 It is neither our business nor our purpose here to consider 
 whether this denial is, or is not, to be justified. All we 
 have to do is to recognise the fact that very many of the 
 highest minds the world has ever known have been devoted 
 to metaphysics, and also the further fact, that if such know- 
 
88 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 ledge can be acquired, since all knowledge is science of some 
 kind, such metaphysical science must be the highest of 
 sciences, and may be called the science of science. The 
 objects of science, then, described in the most general 
 terms, may be said to be threefold : mental, physical, and 
 metaphysical. 
 
CHAPTER IV 
 
 THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 
 
 THE objects about which science concerns itself are, as 
 we saw in the last chapter, threefold : they are, in the 
 first place, the material bodies, inanimate and animate, which 
 surround us, together with all those of their relations, quali- 
 ties, and energies, which our senses and our reason combine 
 to inform us about. In the second place, they are the 
 various mental facts and processes which are revealed to us 
 by consciousness and introspection. In the third place, 
 they are problems concerning the essences and causes of 
 whatever can be to us an object of knowledge, including the 
 universe itself, in all its parts and considered as one whole. 
 The method by which science proceeds with its investiga- 
 tions of the objects of its study is essentially the same in all 
 cases, though variously modified according to the kind of 
 matter about which it is for the time occupied. 
 
 But it is in no way the object of this work to describe 
 the special methods whereby the various sciences have been 
 brought to their present state of cultivation, nor the several 
 modes in which each of them is now being pursued. Our 
 only purpose is to point out, in the most general terms, 
 certain characteristics, certain necessary conditions, which 
 are common to the study of all, or of a great many of them. 
 
 Physical science the science occupied about the first of 
 the three categories of objects distinguished at the beginning 
 
 89 
 
90 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 of this chapter has been said to consist of careful meas- 
 urements ; and there is much truth in the saying, if a 
 sufficiently wide meaning be assigned to the term " measure- 
 ment." For science has to consider, as everyone knows, 
 not only spatial dimensions or the extent and directions in 
 which any body is extended, or, in popular phraseology, 
 " occupies space " but also differences of quality, differ- 
 ences of energy, and of qualities as well as quantities of 
 energy, and differences in respect to all those qualities 
 which the different senses we possess enable us, though in 
 radically diverse ways, to be subjectively affected by, and, 
 through the intervention of the intellect, to perceive the 
 objective existence of. 
 
 But for the apprehension of all these matters, measurement 
 is an indispensable and also an efficient aid. Thus, inquiries 
 as to matters seemingly so purely qualitative as different 
 degrees of warmth, are answered by thermometric measure- 
 ments ; differences of velocity are estimated by the aid of 
 the chronometer, and differences in the action of gravity, 
 under various conditions, by the measurement of weight. 
 Our own past history and the history of mankind are to be 
 understood only by measurements of time. Moreover, to 
 know anything, as we said before, 1 is to know that it is dis- 
 tinct from something else, which is to know numerical differ- 
 ence, which is again counting, and that, to a certain degree, 
 is measurement. 
 
 But, though the inquiries of physical science may be gen- 
 erally described as various kinds of measurements, such a 
 phrase is obviously inapplicable to the investigations of 
 mental science. It is true that our own existence does not 
 become known to us save through successive changes in 
 consciousness (successive " states of consciousness "), that 
 is, through " relations " which exist between them, and all 
 
 1 See ante, p. 18. 
 
THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 91 
 
 mental facts become known through relations in which they 
 stand to other such facts and to our consciousness. But 
 these are not, in any true sense, " measurements." On the 
 other hand, all the problems solved by careful measurements 
 in physical science are in every case ascertained and solved 
 by the attainment of a correct appreciation of relations 
 existing between different objects and activities. And, in- 
 deed, metaphysics may also be said to be occupied about 
 metaphysical relations. Thus all science is one vast process 
 of ascertaining, as correctly as possible, relations (e. g., co- 
 existence, succession, and causation) of very different orders 
 of things. 
 
 But owing to our organisation, every such inquiry must 
 be carried on, and every conclusion arrived at, through 
 either our sense-perceptions * or by the aid of sensuous im- 
 aginations, however supersensuous the essential nature of 
 the object of our inquiry may be. 
 
 The imaginations we make use of need not, of course, be 
 mental pictures of concrete, extended things ; they may be 
 the merest symbols, and such symbols are not only of the 
 greatest utility, but are absolutely necessary for the very 
 simplest kinds of science. 
 
 Spoken and written words are such audible and visible 
 symbols, and so are numerals and all algebraic signs. By 
 means of symbols we can work out the most complicated 
 results without any need of thinking, meanwhile, what it is 
 such symbols represent. But in the end, to arrive at any 
 practical or complete result, the symbols must be retrans- 
 lated into the things they symbolised, and thus the corre- 
 spondence of processes gone through (simple or complex) 
 may be tested by our direct or our indirect sense-perceptions. 
 Thus, in matters so elementary as the simple addition of 
 numerals, the result may be tested by taking parcels of 
 
 1 See ante, p. 9. 
 
Q2 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 things, e.g., marbles, each corresponding in number with 
 one of the (symbols) numbers to be added together, and, 
 having mixed the whole, then counting them, and so seeing 
 that the senses of sight and touch confirm the previous re- 
 sult of the addition of the numerical symbols. It is the 
 same as regards the process of subtraction ; its correspond- 
 ence with the real relations which exist between the sub- 
 stantial things may be similarly tested. 
 
 The symbolism of science may be very well exemplified by 
 the simplest facts of algebra, which, as our readers know, is 
 a branch of science replete with the most beautiful, complex, 
 ingenious, and far-reaching processes, whereby alone many 
 calculations are made possible, or the labours of investigation 
 lessened, while the results arrived at have complete accuracy. 
 This is the case even when we find need to employ symbols 
 which express not only unreal, but even impossible, quanti- 
 ties, by means of which we may arrive at otherwise unattain- 
 able truths concerning real or possible existences. Such is the 
 case, because they express abstract truths which have real 
 applications, or would have them could the impossible con- 
 ditions, sometimes supposed, really exist. Thus even the 
 absurd and impossible quantities expressed by the symbol 
 V x has its relations with reality. It is, of course, really 
 impossible in itself, since there is no quantity which, being 
 multiplied by itself, gives a negative product. Yet it has 
 its relation with reality, inasmuch as it can be used as if it 
 were a real quantity, and all the laws and relations relating 
 to real quantities can be applied to it. 
 
 The truths and processes of algebra may be tested by our 
 direct sense-experience (as may those of arithmetic) by 
 making use of definite numbers as representatives of alge- 
 braic symbols, and so translating algebra into arithmetic in 
 order to be practically tested. The truths of geometry may 
 be tested by being made evident to the eye and by reasoning. 
 
THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 93 
 
 Making free use of the indispensable aid of symbols, 
 science proceeds to investigate the objects of its study (i) 
 by observation, (2) by reasoning, (3) by putting forward 
 hypotheses, and (4) by testing the hypotheses put forward. 
 
 Scientific observation consists in carefully and attentively 
 bringing to bear the senses appropriate to each fact to be : 
 investigated, making use of all the artificial means and ap- 
 pliances available for the purpose, with a mind well informed 
 as to what has been done in the same field before, the in- 
 tellect being also aroused for the detection of likenesses 
 and differences between the objects or actions studied, 
 and other allied objects or actions, and in a state of expect- 
 ancy as to the possibilities or probabilities of results to be 
 anticipated. 
 
 Where it is possible, such observations have to be supple- 
 mented by others in which circumstances and conditions 
 have been specially arranged to facilitate discovery. In 
 other words, simple observations have to be supplemented 
 by experiments, and these must evidently be varied accord- 
 ing to the nature of the matter under investigation. 
 
 In many sciences it is evident that no true experiments 
 are possible, but only different degrees of ingenuity in de- 
 vising modes of accurate observation. Such must be, of 
 course, the case with the study of astronomy, history, palae- 
 ontology, etc. 
 
 Facts having been sufficiently ascertained, the truths so 
 elicited may be further developed by reasoning according to 
 the laws of logic. Thus it is we gain a distinct and certain 
 perception of truths which were before but imperfectly, 
 only implicitly, apprehended, through the deductive reason- 
 ing of the syllogism. By induction, as we all know, we can 
 form judgments more or less probable, and sometimes even 
 certain. Thus, for example, having examined many kinds 
 of pouched animals, and found that they all possess both a 
 
94 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 peculiar conformation of jaw and also marsupial bones, we 
 judge that if a new species be discovered with one of these 
 characters it will also possess the other. 
 
 Such a judgment can never be a certain, but only an em- 
 pirical, 1 judgment, and it is no wonder that exceptions to 
 the above-mentioned rule of co-existence have been found. 
 But certainty may be attained in some cases. Thus, by the 
 study of different kinds of rocks we easily perceive that they 
 have been deposited at different dates, and that the animals 
 which 'have left their remains fossilised within them were 
 inhabitants of the earth at different periods. 
 
 In endeavouring to reason out the cause (or causes) of any 
 event or fact, we seek it amongst the invariable antecedents 
 or concomitants of that event or fact by five different 
 methods. 
 
 There is first the " method of agreement," which endeav- 
 ours to discover whether, in many cases of the occurrence 
 of the fact we seek to explain, one circumstance is present 
 in every case, and is the only one so invariably present. 
 
 Secondly, there is the " method of difference," by which 
 the endeavour is made to find two instances alike in all their 
 circumstances save one, in addition to the difference that in 
 one instance the event, or fact, the cause of which is sought 
 is present, while in the other it is absent. When two such 
 instances are found, then the single circumstance found to 
 co-exist with the event or fact must at least be closely 
 related to its cause. 
 
 Thirdly, we have the " joint method of agreement and 
 difference," which may be thus stated: 
 
 If in two instances in which y occurs JIT is also present, while 
 two instances in which y does not occur, have nothing in 
 common save the absence of x, then x is the cause of y. 
 
 If we subtract from a given effect all that is due to cer- 
 
 1 See ante. p. 8. 
 
THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 95 
 
 tain causes, then the residue is the effect of the rest of the 
 causes. This is the fourth method " that of residues." 
 
 Fifthly, and lastly, if x and y increase, decrease, and vary 
 together, then one is the cause of the other or is closely 
 connected with such cause. This is called " the method of 
 concomitant variations." 
 
 Objection has been made to the validity of such reason- 
 ings on the ground that the universe is never the same in all 
 particulars save one, at any two successive instants, and 
 that two instances of any event or fact have never occurred 
 with only one circumstance in common. These theoretical 
 objections may also be urged not only against the above 
 " methods," but against all investigations by experiment 
 and observation. 
 
 The objection is no doubt formally correct. The celestial 
 bodies are never in the same position for two successive in- 
 stants, while, on the other hand, their existence persists 
 through whatever series of experiments we carry on. 
 
 In all cases also there are, and must be, both a multitude 
 of persistences and a multitude of changes, no one of which 
 we may ever become aware of. But although such theo- 
 retical inadequacies must be admitted to exist in every such 
 proof, they can in most cases be sufficiently well allowed for 
 to serve all practical purposes. 
 
 The existence of the Pleiades, or even of the mountains 
 in the moon, can be tranquilly ignored while we are trying 
 experiments with respect to the solidification of gases, nor 
 do the gavials of the Ganges interfere with careful investiga- 
 tions into the development of the amphioxus or the apteryx. 
 
 There is hardly need to remind any reader of this book 
 that the " method of agreement " is necessarily uncertain, 
 because one effect may have several causes ; but this defect 
 does not apply to " the joint method of agreement and 
 difference." 
 
96 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 The idea as to what may be the cause of any effect is gen- 
 erally suggested by analogy, or resemblance known, or sus- 
 pected, to exist between causes and effects thought to be 
 similar to the case investigated ; and, of course, a cause will, 
 as a rule, be the more easily discovered the greater the num- 
 ber of instances of the supposed effect we examine. 
 
 A suspected cause may be tested by allowing it to operate 
 in circumstances of less complication, to see whether the 
 effect will still be produced. This is, of course, one import- 
 ant instance of carrying on scientific experiments. The 
 process of seeking out analogies and resemblances wisely is 
 perhaps the special characteristic of a sagacious man of 
 science. The process of constructing carefully thought out 
 hypotheses, and then skilfully and accurately submitting 
 them to fitting tests for verification, is the method by which 
 the greatest scientific advances have been made during the 
 last three centuries ; although it must be admitted that much 
 time and effort have been wasted by the frequent emission 
 of careless and ill-considered speculations. 
 
 The foregoing observations with respect to the methods 
 of science may suffice, because our purpose in referring to, 
 and briefly noting them in the most general terms, has not 
 been for their own sake. We assume that most of our 
 readers already know as much as we could tell them with 
 respect to the methods of science generally, and the details 
 of such methods with respect to those sciences with which 
 they are best acquainted. 
 
 Our purpose in devoting this chapter to a general view of 
 the methods of science has had special reference as every 
 chapter in this book has special reference to the subject of 
 Epistemology. 
 
 Our main object is briefly to call attention to certain ideas, 
 perceptions, and convictions which are present, in at least a 
 latent condition, in every method whereby science is pursued 
 
THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 
 
 97 
 
 and advanced, and consciously or unconsciously in the minds 
 of those who pursue it. 
 
 The question concerning the intellectual justification of 
 these ideas, perceptions, and convictions will be entered 
 upon later. 
 
 Now, doubt and scepticism are not only legitimate but 
 necessary in science. They are safeguards against rash as- 
 sent to propositions inadequately proved. True as this 
 is as regards physical science, it is still more true with 
 regard to problems that are ultraphysical, in studying 
 which it is especially necessary to withhold assent from 
 what does not appear to be clearly and evidently true to 
 our own minds. 
 
 Yet it is possible, here as elsewhere, to go from one ex- 
 treme to another, and to become so possessed by a tendency 
 to doubt as to forget the existence and legitimacy of 
 certainty. 
 
 Nevertheless, we all of us possess absolute certainty con- 
 cerning many things, and this especially applies to those 
 men who cultivate science. We are all certain that science 
 has advanced, and that our physical knowledge is greater in 
 extent and better grounded than it was in the days of 
 Copernicus. Every man of science is also certain that some 
 progress is being made in that department to which he is 
 himself devoted, whatever that may be. But it is obvious 
 that such advance would be impossible if we could not, by 
 means of observations, experiments, and reasoning, become 
 so certain with respect to some facts as to be able to make 
 them the starting-points for fresh observations and inferences 
 as to other facts. 
 
 Thus for the astronomer, the earth's annual revolution 
 round the sun, its daily revolution round its own axis and 
 the coinciding of these two revolutions in the case of the 
 moon, are matters of absolute certainty. No geologist en- 
 
98 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 tertains the slightest doubt that the earth's crust is largely 
 composed of strata which have been in past ages deposited 
 from water. 
 
 No zoologist can doubt that the transitory stages which 
 most of the higher animals go through in passing from their 
 embryonic to their adult condition, bear a general resem- 
 blance to permanent adult conditions of other animals of 
 lower types of organisation. In science, as in matters of 
 every-day life, there are a multitude of facts as to which no 
 man in his senses can entertain any doubt. Though we are 
 for the most part content to act on reasonable probabilities, 
 yet certainty attends us at every turn. If we meet a friend 
 in the street going away from home, we know that we shall 
 not find him if we go straight to his house. If we find on 
 returning to our library that a window, which we had care- 
 fully closed before starting, is open, we are quite sure that 
 someone must have opened it. Such certainties about 
 ordinary and scientific matters are quite beyond the reach 
 of reasonable doubt, and it is very necessary, for our pur- 
 pose here, to recognise that such is the case. 
 
 The methods of science clearly imply a conviction on the 
 part of those who follow them that there really is such a 
 thing as legitimate certainty. 
 
 If such were not the case, there could be no true science 
 of any kind. Blind disbelief would be as fatal to science as 
 blind belief, and healthy and firm convictions must follow 
 the presence of sufficient evidence, otherwise the progress 
 of science would be fatally arrested. It is necessary, then, 
 distinctly to recognise that there is such a thing as legiti- 
 mate certainty, not to perceive the force of which is illegiti- 
 mate doubt. The first conviction, then, to which we desire 
 in this chapter to call attention as being implicit in all pur- 
 suit of science, is the conviction that there is such a thing 
 as certainty, and that there are at least some things which 
 
THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 99 
 
 we can ascertain to be certainly true. In a later chapter we 
 will consider the justification of this conviction, and the 
 other convictions implied in the pursuit of science. 
 
 But what does the assertion that anything can be " cer- 
 tainly trtie " imply ? 
 
 " Truth " has sometimes been said to be a mere subjective 
 feeling of the mind truth for each man being just that 
 which each man troweth and no more. But the objectivity 
 of truth is easily shown, since the sceptic who would deny 
 it, in denying it, refutes himself. For if the statement 
 " Truth is merely an individual feeling" were true, then 
 that very statement, as a fact, would itself be an objective 
 truth, and therefore, more than a mere individual feeling. 
 But, as John Stuart Mill long ago pointed out, the recogni- 
 tion of the truth of any judgment is not only an essential 
 part, but the essential part, of it as a judgment. Leave 
 that out, and it remains a mere play of thought in which no 
 judgment is passed. No follower of any branch of physical 
 science can doubt that truth is more than a mere quality of 
 a feeling, or that it has a real relation to things external to 
 his mind. Were not such the case, science, once more, 
 could make no progress. We do not base our scientific in- 
 ductions and deductions on what we regard as so many 
 individual feelings, but upon what we regard as facts real 
 relations between real events and things without a found- 
 ation in which our conclusions would be worthless. The 
 truth of physical science consists, and must consist, in the 
 agreement of " thought " with " things," of the world of 
 " perceptions, ideas, and inferences " with the world of 
 
 external existences." 
 
 In our last chapter we endeavoured to point out how im- 
 possible it is to express the facts, processes, and conclusions 
 of physical science in terms of idealism ; and we find that 
 the most devoted idealists who also follow some branch of 
 
100 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 physical science are absolutely forced by their science to use 
 language essentially inconsistent with their philosophy, of 
 which fact it would be as easy as it seems superfluous (and 
 perhaps invidious) to give instances. 
 
 But the fact that the pursuit of science cannot be carried 
 on without a real and true apprehension of things objective, 
 and that we possess a special faculty which certainly reveals 
 to us objective truths, are truths contained (however little 
 it may be noticed) in every observation or experiment we 
 may make, and in every conclusion we may draw. 
 
 That special faculty of ours, the wonderful office of which 
 it is to reveal to us objectivity with absolute certainty, is 
 our faculty of memory. 
 
 Now, as we hardly need say, everything which is objective 
 is external to the self to the self which is feeling or think- 
 ing. Thus all existences, even states of the " self " or the 
 " Ego," which are anterior to the time of any actual think- 
 ing are also objective: they are objects of thought. 
 
 It is memory which enables us to get, intellectually, out- 
 side our present selves and our present feelings, in a way 
 the truth of wriich no sane man can question. For memory 
 informs us with absolute certainty about some events of our 
 past lives. There is probably no one who reads these pages 
 who is not absolutely sure that he was doing some other 
 thing before he began to read them. 
 
 And since it is thus actually demonstrated to us through 
 our memory that we can know with absolute certainty things 
 which are objective as regards time, it is the less disputable 
 that our faculties have the power also to inform us as to 
 things which are external to us spatially objective and 
 that, as was contended in the last chapter, we have an in- 
 tuition of real external bodies : an external world as ordinar- 
 ily understood. The questions as to the validity and the 
 nature of memory will be subsequently considered. They 
 
THE ME THODS OF 'SCIENCE ' I O I 
 
 are only here referred to as auxiliary to our apprehension of 
 objectivity. 
 
 Thus the second conviction which we desire to point out 
 as existing, at least in a latent condition, in all physical 
 science, and therefore implied in all its methods, is the con- 
 viction that an independent, extended, external world really 
 exists, that there are truly objective existences, and that 
 truth is a relation of conformity between the dictates of the 
 mind and other really existing conditions and relations. 
 
 We have just referred to our faculty of memory, and that 
 same faculty is intimately connected with the third convic- 
 tion which must be latent in every pursuit of science. This 
 third conviction is the certainty we have of our own con- 
 tinued personal existence, and along with it the certainty 
 that we do, in fact, know our actions, sensations, reminis- 
 cences, emotions, perceptions, conceptions, and inferences. 
 
 How would it be possible for any scientific experiments to 
 be carried on if we could not be perfectly certain that it was 
 we ourselves who carried them on : that it was we who had 
 both arranged the test conditions and also noted the results ? 
 How, again, could we arrive at any conclusion if we had 
 any doubt about our really having felt, perceived, or reasoned 
 out the results we had felt, perceived, or reasoned out ? 
 
 Even mere scientific observation would be impossible if 
 we had any doubt that it was we ourselves one and the 
 same person who began the observation and carried it 
 through to its end. 
 
 To some of our readers these remarks and queries may 
 seem superfluous or even idle. Such, however, is by no 
 means the case, as the same readers will clearly see if they 
 will have patience to peruse this volume to its close. The 
 truths which to them may seem so obvious and undeniable 
 that their enumeration is unnecessary, are truths which have 
 been denied, and are denied by men of very considerable in- 
 
IO2 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 tellectual distinction. For our purpose, that is, to obtain a 
 correct view as to Epistemology, it is extremely necessary 
 to recognise the fact that we cannot follow science if we 
 either, really and truly, doubt the possibility of certainty, 
 or the actual certainty of a greater or less number of facts 
 and principles, the truth of which every science, whatever it 
 may be, necessarily implies. 
 
 Provisionally recognising, then, the fact of our continued 
 existence, as vouched for by memory (i. e., till in our eighth 
 chapter the question is more fully discussed), and recognis- 
 ing the fact of the existence of an external world, the com- 
 ponents of which stand in various active and causal relations 
 to each other and to us, we have next to consider a matter 
 hardly less momentous. This is the bearing of scientific 
 progress on the question of the validity of the process of in- 
 ference. The remark hardly need be made that no science 
 has been developed or could be made to progress without 
 it. A direct knowledge of events, facts, and their relations, 
 sufficiently complete to constitute any one of the sciences, 
 would be too vast in extent to be possible for the human 
 mind. 
 
 It is conceivable that other beings, endowed with much 
 greater and more far-reaching intellectual powers, might be 
 able to perceive, by direct intuition, all that we are able 
 laboriously to attain to by indirect processes of inference. 
 However that may be, ratiocination is necessary for us 
 (being no better endowed than we are), and every man of 
 science must admit that valid inference is not only a possi- 
 bility, but a fact. He must admit that inferences which are 
 perfectly valid and certain have been drawn ; since, other- 
 wise, there could be no science about the certainty of which 
 we could rest secure. He also knows (as we have already 
 seen) that there is such a thing as scientific certainty, and 
 that to some scientific propositions we can assent without 
 
THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 103 
 
 the least fear of error. But this implies that we may, and 
 that we must, place confidence in the principles of deduction 
 in that perception of the mind which we express by the 
 word " therefore." When we use that word we mean to 
 express by it that there is a truth, the certainty of which is 
 shown through the help of different facts or principles, which 
 themselves are antecedently known to be true. The valid- 
 ity of inference is, then, the fourth of those truths to which 
 we desire here to call attention as being convictions implied 
 in physical science and in all methods by which that science 
 is pursued. Of the process of inference itself, we shall have 
 more to say hereafter; all we desire here to insist upon is 
 that to deny its validity is absolutely to stultify the whole 
 of human science. 
 
 But though inferences are necessary for science, our read- 
 ers will not forget that (as we before pointed out) all reason- 
 ing reposes upon a knowledge of facts antecedently known 
 to be true. However long our processes of reasoning may 
 be they must stop somewhere. If we were bound to prove 
 everything, the process would never end, and in this way 
 again we should be reduced to a regressus ad infinitum, and 
 no single proposition could ever be proved. It is therefore 
 certain that if any inferences are true and valid they must 
 ultimately repose on facts directly known to us without 
 reasoning; and our fifth conviction, implicitly contained in 
 every method by which science is pursued, is, and must be, 
 the truth that there are some propositions which carry with 
 them their own evidence, which are evident in and by them- 
 selves. What is to be said in deprecation or defence of this 
 character of self-evident truthfulness thus attributed to some 
 propositions, we will see later on. What is here to be noted 
 is the fact that science can have neither justification, de- 
 velopment, nor even existence, unless it be conceded that 
 not only is the principle of inference valid, but also that 
 
104 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 underlying true and valid inferences, there are, and must be, 
 in the last resort, certain truths which are made known to 
 us by their own direct evidence, and need no process of 
 proof. 
 
 These are intuitive truths, directly apprehended by our 
 power of intellectual intuition. 1 And, indeed, it is perfectly 
 evident that the convictions at which men of science arrive 
 ,by means of their observations, experiments, and inferences, 
 are not blind convictions which they are compelled to arrive 
 at they know not how or why. They are eminently intelli- 
 gent convictions, attained by a conscious and intentional 
 pursuit of truth, and of which those who hold them can 
 give a good account, assigning valid reasons for the scientific 
 faith which is in them. 
 
 Amongst the facts and truths thus self-evident are certain 
 evident principles of reasoning. Physical science is em- 
 phatically experimental science. But every experiment 
 carefully performed implies a most important latent truth. 
 For when an experiment has shown us that anything is 
 certain, as, for example, that a newt's leg may grow again 
 after amputation, because one actually has so grown again, 
 we shall find that such certainty implies an a priori truth. 
 It implies that if the newt has come to have four legs once 
 more, it cannot at the very same time have only three legs. 
 This remark may seem almost absurdly trivial ; but it is im- 
 possible to make principles of this kind too clear too plainly 
 certain and inevitable and there is nothing so useful for 
 bringing home to the mind an important abstract truth as 
 the presentation of a plain and indisputable concrete example. 
 Anything we are certain about, because it has been proved 
 to us by experiment, is certain only if we know, and because 
 we know that a thing which has been actually proved can- 
 not at the same time remain unproven, and this depends 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 14, 47. 
 
THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 105 
 
 again on a still more fundamental truth which our reason 
 recognises the truth, namely, that "nothing can at the 
 same time both be and not be "the truth known as the 
 principle of contradiction, which we here bring forward as 
 the sixth conviction which must be tacitly, if not expressly, 
 recognised by everyone who cultivates science. It is, at 
 lea.3t, latent in every scientific method we employ. Whether 
 or not, in ultimate analysis, the validity of this principle can 
 be sustained, it is at least certain that it is constantly acted 
 on; and this not only in the pursuit of science, but in the 
 judgments and actions of every-day life. 
 
 A seventh conviction, which is latent and is acted upon 
 in all the methods of science, is that of the truth of such 
 axioms as " the whole is greater than its part," and that 
 " things which are equal to the same thing are equal to 
 each other." Merely noting this fact, which no one will 
 care to dispute, and reserving what more we may have to 
 say about it for a subsequent chapter, we will pass on to the 
 eighth conviction implied, and at least latent in the methods 
 of science, namely, the principle of causation. However 
 much the validity of this principle may be disputed by philo- 
 sophers and such disputes will be considered later it is 
 impossible to deny that it is practically acted upon by those 
 who prosecute any branch of physical science. It is indis- 
 putable that any sudden and unexpected change which may 
 be detected by any scientific observer, is at once put down 
 as due to some cause, while he will often do his utmost to 
 detect what that cause may be. That no change can take 
 place, that no new existence can arise, save as the result of 
 causation, is spontaneously acted on by every man of 
 science, and, indeed, by every man of ordinary intelligence, 
 as if it were the most certain and indisputable of axioms. 
 Closely connected with this principle is the ninth conviction, 
 namely, the conviction that the course of nature is uniform. 
 
106 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 The uniformity of nature is so evidently necessary an as- 
 sumption for all who would investigate nature's phenomena 
 and ascertain her laws, that the mere mention of the fact is 
 all that seems necessary at this stage of our progress. 
 
 Lastly, since we have seen that the methods of science 
 imply the conviction on our part that some truths are nec- 
 essary, and that they reveal to us objective necessities in 
 external nature, we must here set down the tenth and last 
 of those convictions to which we desire to call attention. 
 This is the conviction that there really is a condition ex- 
 pressed by the abstract term necessity, a term which would 
 be meaningless without the correlative condition and term 
 contingency. 
 
 Reserving, as before said, for a future occasion, an 
 examination into the validity of the fundamental assump- 
 tions which must be made by all who pursue physical 
 science, and which are latent in its every method, we may 
 briefly tabulate those assumptions as follows : 
 
 (1) It is possible to arrive at certain knowledge about 
 
 some things, and some absolute scientific certainty 
 has been actually attained. 
 
 (2) An external objective world exists and is truly appre- 
 
 hended by some of our intellectual acts, an abso- 
 lutely certain knowledge of objectivity being afforded 
 us through memory, which reveals to us real exist- 
 ences external to all our present experience. 
 
 (3) We can know not only our actions, sensations, im- 
 
 aginations, reminiscences, perceptions, conceptions, 
 and inferences, but also our own substantial and 
 continuous personal existence. 
 
 (4) We know that if certain premises be true, then what- 
 
 ever logically follows from them must be true like- 
 wise. 
 
THE METHODS OF SCIENCE 107 
 
 (5) Since we thus know certain truths indirectly by in- 
 
 ference, we must also know some things directly and 
 see that they are self-evident. 
 
 (6) Nothing can at the same time both be and not be. 
 
 (7) Some axioms are self-evident. 
 
 (8) Every change and every new existence must be due 
 
 to some cause. 
 
 (9) Nature is uniform. 
 
 (10) Some things are necessary and others are contingent. 
 
 The fact that the above ten propositions are true aud cer- 
 tain is then implied by the methods of science. 
 
 Unless we are convinced, and act on the conviction, that 
 the propositions thus implied are true, science is logically 
 impossible, and any scientific man who should deny any one 
 of them would either deceive himself or try to deceive other 
 people. Without their acceptance it is impossible to have 
 any consistent, harmonious, and stable system of ordered 
 knowledge any true science. More than that, if these 
 ten propositions were really doubted by anyone, he would 
 thereby necessarily fall into a state of mental paralysis 
 and intellectual inanition, in all that relates to scientific 
 knowledge. 
 
 Having thus recognised these important convictions, 
 which find a necessary place amongst the implications of 
 science, we may next proceed to consider what are the 
 physical and mental antecedents of all and every science. 
 
 A knowledge of such physiological and psychical facts 
 will serve as an introduction to the study of our highest in- 
 tellectual powers, the dicta of which can alone enable us to 
 judge whether we can attain to a knowledge of the ground- 
 work of science, and, if so, what that groundwork may, or 
 must, be. 
 
CHAPTER V 
 
 THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 WE have no experience of knowledge save as consisting 
 of mental states our own, and those which ob- 
 servation reveals to us as existing in other minds. We have 
 no experience of mental states save as immanent in a living 
 body our own, and those of other living beings. Without 
 mental states we cannot hope for knowledge, and without 
 organised knowledge there is no science. The groundwork 
 of science, as known to us by experience, may so far, there- 
 fore, be said to be twofold: (i) mental and (2) corporeal. 
 Granting, for argument's sake, the essential independence 
 of intellect from all that is material substance, nevertheless 
 we men, here and now, have no experience whatever of it 
 apart from matter, apart from living organised matter, 
 and apart from living matter with a special and definite form 
 of organisation. 
 
 If, then, it should be objected that the groundwork of 
 science is, and must be, purely intellectual, we can at 
 least reply that, so far as our actual experience goes, 
 material conditions a special kind of living organisa- 
 tion are at least a sine qua non for our apprehension of 
 such groundwork. 
 
 The groundwork of science must be closely related to the 
 nature of science itself. Now science, as we have seen, is 
 an organised result of knowledge; knowledge is dependent 
 
 108 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE IOQ 
 
 on, and called forth by feelings; and feelings area result of 
 a normal, vital condition of a physical organisation. To un- 
 derstand fully what is psychical, it is, therefore, generally 
 necessary to have a certain acquaintance with what is physi- 
 ological and physical. Moreover, as function depends on 
 structure, any sufficient comprehension of the vital activities 
 of our frame necessitates some previous acquaintance with 
 its physical organisation its anatomy. As we cannot vent- 
 ure to assume that the great majority erf our readers are 
 possessed of even a small amount of anatomical and physio- 
 logical knowledge, we feel it impossible to dispense with 
 some description of the physical antecedents of science 
 (readers, however, who do possess such knowledge, and an 
 elementary knowledge of zoology, had better pass over this 
 chapter unread), related as they necessarily are to the 
 groundwork of all science, which it is our ultimate object 
 to study and endeavour to comprehend. 
 
 Very little, however, need be said here, except with re- 
 spect to that substance and those organs of the body which 
 are the necessary means by which alone we are capable of 
 different special feelings and imaginations, or of any feelings 
 at all. 
 
 Feeling, knowledge, thought, everyone knows to be car- 
 ried on by us only in a living body, which ought to be in a 
 sufficiently healthy and normal state. Abnormal conditions 
 may be accompanied by an absence, or paralysis, of one or 
 more of our senses, or by various forms of mental aberration 
 down to complete idiocy. In order, therefore, to have a 
 satisfactory comprehension of our powers of thinking (one 
 indispensable preliminary for investigating the groundwork 
 of science), it is necessary to have some knowledge of those 
 vital functions which are necessary for the exercise of 
 thought ; and to understand them, as already intimated, we 
 require to know something of the order and condition of 
 
HO THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 that special mechanism the actions of which so nearly con- 
 cern us. 
 
 To appreciate correctly human thought, it is also necessary 
 to know something of the psychical powers of living creat- 
 ures which are not human. Some adequate notion as to 
 man's place in nature cannot be dispensed with by anyone 
 who would estimate at their just value the products of 
 human thought. We have already enumerated the sciences 
 which deal with living things, 1 and probably no one will dis- 
 pute the assertion that man, corporeally considered, is a 
 kind of animal, and that the sciences which relate to animals 
 generally relate, therefore, to him also. 
 
 The multitude of species which compose what is called 
 the " animal kingdom " is so vast that it would be impos- 
 sible to study them otherwise than by classifying them in a 
 number of more and more subordinate groups, each of which 
 is defined by an enumeration of certain structural characters 
 which the creatures included in such group possess in com- 
 mon. It is usual to divide the animal kingdom into two 
 great groups, the lower of which is made up by creatures 
 the whole body of each of which is composed of a single cell, 
 or, at most, a few cells only. Of these creatures, animal- 
 cules of various kinds, it is not necessary for our present 
 purpose to say more than a few words. One kind, the 
 Amceba, may here be mentioned, as it is so often referred 
 to as closely resembling certain particles (known as the 
 colourless corpuscles) in human blood. It is a microscopic 
 creature, consisting of a minute piece of " protoplasm," with 
 some internal modifications, which protrudes parts of its 
 body in the form of short, blunt projections, and feeds by 
 engulfing what it preys on into its body at various parts of 
 its surface. The bell-animalcule, or Vorticella, may also be 
 referred to for the following reason : its bell-shaped body 
 
 1 See Chapter ii., pp. 24, 32. 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE III 
 
 is connected with a fixed point of support by means of an 
 elongated stem, traversed by a special fibre. At the slight- 
 est shock this fibre contracts, and throwing the filament 
 into curves, draws the body of the creature near to the point 
 of attachment of the filament. 
 
 The second division of the animal kingdom consists of 
 creatures the body of each of which is formed by a multitude 
 of cells which are aggregated together into, or give rise to, 
 various kinds of distinct substances, termed " tissues " 
 such as bone, gristle, muscle, nerve, etc., etc. 
 
 The lowest of these many-celled animals are the sponges, 
 and the cells which compose their bodies are arranged in 
 two layers. 
 
 Next come the zoophytes, or plant-like animals (corals, 
 sea-anemones, jelly-fishes, etc.), to which succeed the star- 
 fishes, sea-urchins, and their allies. A multitude of creatures 
 compose at least two large groups of worms, of which the 
 leeches and earth-worms may serve as examples of the 
 higher kinds. We have then an enormous group, Arthro- 
 poda, which embraces all insects, hundred-legs, scorpions, 
 spiders, mites, crabs, lobsters, and shrimp-like creatures. 
 We have, again, a very much less extensive group of Mol- 
 lusca, which includes all snails, whelks, cuttle-fishes, oysters, 
 mussels, etc. Lastly we have the group of backboned 
 animals (fishes, reptiles, birds, and beasts), to which we 
 ourselves belong. Of beasts, or mammals, there are some 
 dozen different orders, such as opossums, whales, rats, and 
 squirrels, cattle, bats, beasts of prey, apes, etc. 
 
 The structure of man's body closely resembles that of 
 the higher apes, while ape and man agree to differ so much 
 from all other mammals that they may be said to stand, as 
 it were, on a zoological island by themselves. Thus man, 
 when only structurally considered, is a species of the order 
 of apes, though widely differing from most of them. 
 
112 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 Such being man's place in nature as regards the structure 
 of his body, it remains briefly to pass in review the main 
 facts of that body's organisation. 
 
 As everyone knows, the human frame is a very complex 
 structure : a mass of flesh (composed of a great number of 
 muscles of different sizes) embracing a skeleton and clothed 
 with skin the skeleton consisting of the skull, backbone, 
 ribs, and the bones of the two pairs of limbs. Within the 
 body are the heart, lungs, stomach, intestines, liver, kidneys, 
 etc. The skull and backbone together enclose a mass of 
 soft, white substance the brain and spinal marrow or spinal 
 cord. Delicate threads of similar substance (nerves) and 
 tubes of various sizes (vessels) traverse the body in all 
 directions. 
 
 Conditions essentially similar, but differing greatly in 
 various ways in different groups (thus, e. g., there may be 
 but two pairs of limbs or none), prevail in all beasts, birds, 
 and reptiles. 
 
 Organs nearly related to each other form what are termed 
 " systems " of organs. Thus the muscles, each of which is 
 made up of a mass of fibres, and are of different shapes and 
 sizes (muscles of the limbs, trunk, head, jaws, etc.), consti- 
 tute "the muscular system." Muscles are generally at- 
 tached by their opposite extremities to different bones. 
 Thus, again, the mouth, stomach, and alimentary canal, 
 with their appendages, form the " alimentary system " ; the 
 heart, with all the tubes (arteries, veins, etc.) connected 
 with it, composes the " circulating system " ; the windpipe 
 and lungs constitute the " respiratory system " ; the organs 
 concerned with reproduction are the " generative system " ; 
 and the brain, spinal cord, and all the nerves of the body 
 together make up the " nervous system." These groups 
 of organs are respectively named as above, because they 
 severally minister to vital actions termed " bodily motion," 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 113 
 
 " alimentation," " circulation," " respiration," " genera- 
 tion," and " sensation " (or " feeling "). 
 
 The functions of alimentation, circulation, respiration, and 
 generation also take place in plants, and are indispensable 
 for organic life. Thus they may be said to exist and prepare 
 the way for development of the higher animal functions of 
 locomotion and sensation. It is with the last-named func- 
 tion alone and the organs which serve it the nervous sys- 
 tem, including its annexed organs of special sense that we 
 have here to do. Nevertheless, it should be noted that in 
 order to act properly the organs of the nervous system re- 
 quire an adequate supply of blood from the circulating 
 system, which blood must be sufficiently refreshed through 
 the respiratory system and purified by organs of " secre- 
 tion," while it must also be adequately supplied with suffi- 
 cient and appropriate nutritious matter by the alimentary 
 system. Through an inadequate supply of blood, or 
 through blood insufficiently nourished, purified, or refreshed, 
 the actions of the nervous system become perverted or 
 paralysed till death ensues. 
 
 The entire nervous system is divisible into two main parts : 
 a central and a peripheral portion. The central part con- 
 sists of the brain and spinal cord, which are directly contin- 
 uous. Its peripheral part is made of all the nerves of the 
 body. The spinal cord (enclosed within the backbone) is 
 divisible into two lateral halves, and nerves, called spinal 
 nerves, are connected with it symmetrically in pairs (one 
 right and one left), one nerve to each of its lateral halves. 
 Each spinal nerve is connected with the spinal cord by two 
 roots, one anterior in position and the other posterior, and 
 each root is made up of a number of small bundles of nerve 
 fibres. The fibres connected with the hinder and the ante- 
 rior part of each lateral half of the spinal cord, are mixed 
 and run together into the nerves or rather compose them 
 
114 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 but those connected with its anterior half go especially to 
 the muscles, while those from its posterior half go especially 
 to the skin. 
 
 Within the spinal cord itself is a mass of longitudinal 
 nervous fibres and more or less spherical nervous " cells." 
 The fibres extend upwards and downwards, towards and 
 from the brain, and are closely connected with the spinal 
 nerves. 
 
 The brain (which is entirely enclosed within the skull, 
 and is composed of delicate nervous filaments and a multi- 
 tude of cells) is the expanded summit of the whole nervous 
 axis, and may be said to consist of three noticeable portions : 
 
 (1) The hindmost under part, or medulla, which may be de- 
 scribed as the expanded upper part of the spinal cord, so 
 becoming the posterior portion of the base of the brain. 
 
 (2) The cerebellum, a rounder, narrowly grooved prominence, 
 forming the posterior under portion of the brain. (3) The 
 third part, which is by far the largest, is formed in part by 
 the continuance forwards and the divergence of the nervous 
 axis, in part by connection with the cerebellum, and also by 
 a very large quantity of nervous tissue apparently independ- 
 ent of either. This whole mass, called the cerebrum, is 
 divided by a deep, median groove into two lateral halves 
 the cerebral hemispheres which form the whole of the upper 
 surface of the brain, and are marked all over by meandering 
 rounded prominences the convolutions of the brain. The 
 cerebral hemispheres are deemed to be main agents in oc- 
 casioning our sensations and imaginations, and it is very 
 noteworthy that as we have two eyes and two ears, so also 
 we have two distinct yet similar cerebral organs which are 
 of such importance. The greater number of the nerves 
 which proceed from the brain have their origin in the 
 medulla. This is notably the case with those which go to 
 the lungs, stomach, and heart. Perhaps the most import- 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 115 
 
 ant, for our purpose, of all the structures which make up 
 our bodily frame, are those organs by the aid of which, in 
 unison with the brain, we are enabled to have sensations of 
 different kinds. 
 
 The organ of sight consists essentially of an extremely 
 delicate membrane, the retina, wherein are a multitude of 
 minute bodies called rods and cones placed side by side, and 
 lining the rear of the eyeball. The retina is an expansion 
 of the optic nerve (or nerve of sight), through which it is 
 directly continuous with the substance of the brain itself. 
 
 The eyeball is bounded by a tough spherical case, and 
 contains within it three transparent media, of different dens- 
 ities, while it is itself transparent anteriorly. It also con- 
 tains a mechanism to facilitate vision at different distances, 
 and its transparent media produce a picture (though an in- 
 verted picture) of what is opposite the eye, on the posterior 
 part of the internal lining of the eyeball. 
 
 As each eye forms an image of what is opposite it, the 
 two pictures simultaneously formed in the two eyes slightly 
 differ from each other. They, of course, must do so, 
 since each looks out on the world from a different point 
 of view. 
 
 The essential organ of hearing in man (and also in back- 
 boned animals) consists of most delicate nervous fibres, 
 which are distributed over a small, complexly shaped mem- 
 branous bag containing fluid, and itself surrounded by 
 another fluid, which is enclosed in a cavity (corresponding in 
 shape to the bag it encloses) in the densest bone of the skull, 
 some distance within the opening on the surface of the side 
 of the head, surrounded by that conspicuous projection com- 
 monly spoken of as " the ear." The nerve of hearing passes 
 outwards from the brain, traverses a canal through the dense 
 bone just referred to, which canal gives it entrance into the 
 cavity wherein lies the membranous structure before men- 
 
Il6 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 tioned, and wherein the ultimate filaments of the auditory 
 nerve terminate. 
 
 The organ of smell is composed of minute terminal fila- 
 ments of very delicate nerves (olfactory nerves), which pro- 
 ceed downwards, from two special prolongations of the 
 brain, to the moist membrane which lines the uppermost 
 part of the cavity of the nostrils. 
 
 The organ of taste also consists of minute nervous fila- 
 ments, distributed in the tongue and the hinder portion of 
 the palate, which filaments are derived from two gustatory 
 nerves, by which the gustatory filaments are brought into 
 direct connection with the brain, as in the three sense 
 organs before noticed. 
 
 The organ of touch is very widely distributed, consisting 
 as it does of a multitude of nervous filaments that ramify 
 and end in the skin, which is, however, very differently sup- 
 plied by these nerves in different parts, some parts being 
 much more richly supplied than others. These fibres are 
 connected with some part of the nervous axis, either the 
 brain or the spinal cord. 
 
 Having gained an elementary acquaintance with the 
 structure of the human body, and of its component systems 
 of organs, we have next to consider what those organs and 
 systems of organs do, what are their functions, and espe- 
 cially those of the nervous system. 
 
 The functions of muscles everyone is in a general way ac- 
 quainted with, i. e., that their special activity is to produce 
 motion. To do this they contract, becoming shorter and 
 thicker, and thus bringing nearer together the two parts to 
 which the two ends of any muscle may be respectively 
 attached, and it is by these means that all movements of 
 the body are effected. Most muscular movements are vol- 
 untary, but others are independent of the will. Such is the 
 case with those of the heart and alimentary canal. Some, 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE \\J 
 
 like our respiratory movements, ordinarily take place inde- 
 pendently of our will, but can be performed voluntarily, and 
 can be voluntarily suspended. Soon, however, the power 
 of voluntarily restraining them ceases, and they take place 
 in spite of all our efforts to the contrary. Movements begun 
 with a voluntary effort may be subsequently carried on 
 automatically, as we see in setting out for a walk. Such 
 movements may be carried on much better automatically 
 than when attended to. Attention often positively impedes 
 the rapidity and accuracy of our movements, as is easily 
 seen if we begin to consider what our movements are as we 
 are running downstairs. 
 
 The agents which induce muscular contraction are termed 
 stimuli. Such are heat, cold, a puncture, a very acrid or 
 acid substance, electricity, and, normally, the influence of 
 the nerves supplied to muscles, and emotion and volition 
 each may be a stimulus. Stimuli physically equal have a 
 more powerful effect when acting on a muscle through a 
 nerve than when acting directly on the muscle itself. 
 
 We have seen that muscular movements may take place 
 in us without .any advertence thereto on our part, and, of 
 course, such actions are quite independent of our will. But 
 much more wonderful, when we come to think over it, is 
 the fact that muscular contractions will take place in appro- 
 priate groups, resulting in co-ordinated movements and 
 groups of groups of such movements, which not only we do 
 not will, but which we do not even know ! How wonderful, 
 when we carefully consider it, is the trivial act of a lad 
 throwing a stone at a mark! How complex must be the 
 co-ordinated movements between different parts of the 
 body in order to produce even such a result! The lad's 
 mind has little to do with it beyond the one impulse to hit 
 the mark. He knows nothing of anatomy, but simply sets 
 going the wonderful mechanism of his body, and this works 
 
Il8 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 out the desired effect for him, just as if it were an elaborate 
 machine. In the first place, the various movable parts of 
 his eyes must be so adjusted that he may see the mark dis- 
 tinctly. Then his body must be held in a proper position, 
 the stone be grasped with just the right amount of firmness 
 (that is, certain muscles must be contracted to the proper 
 amount), the arm must be thrown back to the due extent, 
 and its muscles contracted, in co-ordination with the move- 
 ments of the eyes, and with just that degree of vigour which, 
 as his fingers are relaxed, will carry the stone as he desires 
 it should go. Thus various complex groups of movements 
 may be synthesised without our will and without our know- 
 ledge so as to result in the production of one complex 
 action of the whole body. 
 
 Besides these conspicuous movements, a multitude of 
 minute ones are continually taking place in the living body 
 movements which we not only cannot feel but can in no 
 way perceive in ourselves. They can only be perceived in 
 animals by making use of various devices, including the use 
 of the microscope. 
 
 We have mentioned the function of alimentation as that 
 of the system of organs termed alimentary organs which 
 receive and digest food. But though these organs do in 
 this way minister to that function, nutrition ultimately takes 
 place in parts altogether out of reach of all our powers of 
 observation, consisting as it does in the reception of new 
 elements into the very ultimate substance of the body the 
 change of the prepared residuum of the food we have eaten 
 into our own living flesh and blood, i. e. y assimilation. 
 That this does take place is absolutely certain, but how it 
 takes place is an entirely unsolved problem. Moreover, it 
 is to be noted that this function, so absolutely necessary for 
 life, takes place in the intimate substance of the body be- 
 yond the terminal filaments of the ramifying nerves. 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 119 
 
 We have spoken of " the circulation " as the function of 
 the organs which compose the " circulating system." But 
 over and above that great stream of life there is a minute 
 circulation which takes place within each smallest particle 
 of the body's substance (just as it takes place in unicellular 
 animals), for the sake of which multitudinous microscopic 
 streamlets the great sanguineous current may be said to 
 exist. 
 
 Respiration consists in the gaseous exchange to which our 
 breathing organs minister. But it is not in that conspicuous 
 respiratory process which is evident to our senses that the 
 process really consists. It is in the minute gaseous inter- 
 change which takes place in the ultimate and intimate com- 
 ponents of the body's substance. 
 
 Similarly, " secretion " is a process of formation, by 
 organs, from the blood of products which did not previously 
 exist as such within it. It is thus analogous to the power 
 by which the various tissues that compose the body are en- 
 abled to add to their own substance from the life-stream 
 which bathes them, though their substance does not exist as 
 such in that stream. Thus the process of assimilation in 
 which alimentation culminates is analogous to secretion. 
 
 Having thus, in the briefest manner, noticed the most 
 essential facts concerning various bodily functions, we may 
 next turn to our special subject in this chapter the func- 
 tions of the nervous system. In the first place, it is by the 
 agency of this system that all the other organic activities of 
 the human body are carried on. Without its aid all nutri- 
 tion, growth, circulation, respiration, and muscular motion 
 would not exist, just as its activity would be arrested were 
 it not nourished by a sufficient supply of duly constituted 
 blood. 
 
 But besides organic activities, this system also ministers 
 to, and is necessary for, sensation, and, therefore, for know- 
 
120 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 ledge, seeing, once more, that the latter is impossible for us 
 except as following upon sensation. The nervous system 
 is thus the special, the only, intermediary between our con- 
 sciousness and the external world, and the only bridge be- 
 tween the subjective and all that is objective besides itself. 
 It both receives the various effects to which the world about 
 us and our own body can give rise to within it, and which 
 result in sensations; and it also causes all the movements 
 which take place in response to stimuli. But it is necessary 
 to note that it not only acts as an intermediary between 
 each organ and its environment, through the sensations to 
 which it gives rise, but also that it so acts without the in- 
 tervention of sensations. When acted on by external influ- 
 ences it may, and constantly does, excite corresponding 
 activities in our body without giving rise to any feeling of 
 which we are conscious. The special consideration of 
 sensation itself, its various forms, and their other mental 
 accompaniments and effects, will be considered in our next 
 chapter on the psychical antecedents of science ; but sensa- 
 tion in its physiological aspect, in so far as it is related to 
 different portions and diverse conditions of parts of the 
 nervous system, concerns us here and now. 
 
 As everyone knows, different parts of the nervous system 
 have different functions, and the special functions of differ- 
 ent nerves are partly learned by the. study of their distribu- 
 tion, and partly by the simplest observations. Thus an 
 irritation of the nerve which goes to the eye (to the retina) 
 or to the internal ear, does not produce feeling in the ordinary 
 sense of that word, but only certain sensations of light or of 
 sound. The nerves which, as before said, are connected in 
 pairs with the spinal cord, minister either to sensation or to 
 motion, according to their distributions and connections. 
 
 If one of these nerves be divided, and the part cut off from 
 the spinal cord be irritated, then motion ceases in the 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 121 
 
 muscles to which such nerve is distributed, but no pain 
 accompanies such irritation. If the part which remains 
 attached to the spinal cord be irritated, then pain is caused 
 but not motion. If the so-called posterior root ' of a spinal 
 nerve alone be severed, the parts supplied with twigs from 
 such nerve only, lose their power of feeling, but their power 
 of motion remains. If the anterior root of such a nerve 
 alone be divided, then the parts supplied by such nerve are 
 paralysed as to motion, but, nevertheless, retain their sensi- 
 bility their power of feeling. If the spinal cord itself be 
 cut or broken through, it is impossible for a man thus injured 
 to feel any irritation which may be applied to those portions 
 of his body which are supplied with nerves which are con- 
 nected with any part of the spinal cord below the point of 
 injury. Neither can he move such parts by any act of his 
 will, try as he may. Nevertheless, movements of those very 
 parts may be produced by stimuli applied to them, of which 
 he remains entirely unconscious, or which, if by observation 
 he is aware that they are applied, he has none the less no 
 feeling whatever, nor can he possibly withdraw any such 
 part out of reach of the stimulus so being applied. A man 
 so injured, though he may have entirely lost the power of 
 feeling any pricks, cuts, or burns applied to such parts, will 
 none the less execute movements, often in an exaggerated 
 manner, in response to such stimuli, just as if he did feel 
 them. He will withdraw his foot if it be tickled just as if 
 he felt the tickling, which he is incapable of feeling. Such 
 unconscious movement in response to stimuli which are not 
 felt is called reflex action, for the following reason : under 
 ordinary circumstances stimulations of the surface of the 
 body convey an influence inwards which produces sensation, 
 and gives rise to an outwardly proceeding influence passing 
 to the muscles, and resulting in definite appropriate motions. 
 
 1 See ante, p. 113. 
 
122 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 The influence inwards appears to travel upwards through 
 the spinal cord to the brain, and so produces feeling, because 
 the brain is the main organ of sensation. The influence out- 
 wards appears to travel downwards from the brain, which is, 
 ordinarily, the main fundamental agent for producing mo- 
 tion, and onwards down the spinal cord, and thence to the 
 muscles, which thus move in response to a surface stimulus 
 which has been felt. But when the spinal cord has been 
 divided it becomes no longer possible for such influences to 
 ascend to the brain (and, therefore, there can be no feeling), 
 or to descend from the brain (and, therefore, there can 
 be no voluntary motion). But the unfelt influence travel- 
 ling inwards is supposed in that case, on reaching the 
 spinal cord, to be thence automatically reflected outwards. 
 That such is the case appears to be shown by the fact that 
 appropriate movements are made in response, but made 
 without the intervention of the will. Reflex action may 
 also take place when the body is quite uninjured, as during 
 sleep, under the influence of chloroform, etc. 
 
 But this kind of action is much more strikingly displayed 
 in some of the lower animals. A frog which has had its 
 head cut off will yet make with its hind legs appropriate 
 movements to remove any irritating object applied to the 
 hinder part of its body. If its skin be touched with some 
 caustic fluid, one leg will be brought forward so that the 
 foot may be applied to the irritated spot ; and if that leg be 
 held, then the other leg will be similarly moved forwards. 
 A more striking instance of the same power can be obtained 
 from the same kind of animal at the breeding season. The 
 male frog has the habit of tightly grasping the female, and 
 to enable him the more securely to maintain his hold, 
 a warty prominence becomes developed on the inner side of 
 each of his fore-feet. Now, if such a male frog be taken, 
 and not only decapitated, but the whole hinder part of the 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 123 
 
 body also removed, so that nothing remains but the 
 small portion of its trunk from which the two arms, with 
 their nerves, proceed, and if, under these circumstances, 
 the warty prominences be touched, the two arms will 
 then fly together as if they were moved by a spring, 
 and this remarkable and complex response to a stimulus 
 must take place altogether without the intervention of 
 sensation. 
 
 But in all these instances of reflex action, the stimulus 
 applied should be regarded as the occasion, not the cause, 
 of the movements in question. They must, it seems to us, 
 be due to powers and energies latent in the organism, which 
 powers the stimulus serves to make manifest. 
 
 Other actions may take place in us which resemble reflex 
 action in so far as they take place independently of the will, 
 and, indeed, in spite of all the voluntary efforts we can make, 
 while yet they differ from reflex action because they occur 
 as consequences of sensations distinctly felt. We have 
 already seen how impossible it is for us to impede our 
 respiratory actions after they have been suspended long 
 enough to give rise to peculiarly distressing feelings. 
 Similarly, if an object, not too large, be placed very far 
 back in the mouth, it must be swallowed, and we cannot 
 help it. But the presence of the object is all the time dis- 
 tinctly felt. Such actions are termed ' ' sensori-motor " 
 actions, to distinguish them from reflex ones in which 
 sensations do not intervene. 
 
 It cannot be doubted that different regions of the brain 
 are specially connected with our experience of different 
 sensations, imaginations, and sense-perceptions, and it is 
 also certain that different parts of it are organs for originat- 
 ing different motions and combinations of movements. But 
 though very much has been done towards determining these 
 connections, a vast deal more remains quite uncertain, and 
 
124 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 for our purpose here, such localisations are indifferent, and 
 it is enough to note the fact that there are various central 
 regions which are thus connected with feelings and move- 
 ments respectively. 
 
 What it is especially desirable that the reader should here 
 carefully note, is the fact that nervous activities which are 
 accompanied by definite corresponding feelings, shade off, 
 as it were, into activities which are but occasionally felt, 
 and into activities which are in no way felt, nor can by any 
 possibility be felt. 
 
 A delicate network of nerves is distributed to the heart, 
 arteries, intestines, liver, kidneys, etc., which network is 
 generally spoken of as the ' ' sympathetic system. ' ' Usually 
 the influences which these nerves exercise do not give rise 
 to sensations, but under some abnormal conditions of any 
 of these internal organs, such influences may be felt and be 
 accompanied by pain. 
 
 Another notable fact is that exposure to fresh conditions, 
 it may be the reception of injuries, may result in very re- 
 markable results, which cannot have been brought about 
 without the help of that great co-ordinating system of the 
 body the nervous system. The thickening of the skin of 
 the hand constantly employed in hard work, and that of the 
 muscles of the blacksmith's arm or the dancer's leg, are in- 
 stances in point ; but most striking of all are the processes 
 of repair which may take place after injury. Very complex 
 structures, appropriately formed and nicely adjusted for the 
 performance of complex functions, may be so developed. 
 Thus a new elbow-joint has been known to be produced 
 in a railway guard who was compelled to have his own 
 cut out as a consequence of an injury he had received. 
 The new joint served his purpose exceedingly well, he 
 having soon acquired the power of swinging himself by it 
 from one carriage to another, while a train was in motion, 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 12$ 
 
 as easily and securely by means of the newly formed parts 
 as he could do with his other, uninjured arm. 
 
 Processes of repair are far more conspicuous and remark- 
 able in certain lower animals than they are in man and the 
 creatures nearly allied to him. The tails of lizards, the legs 
 of newts, and even the eye, lower jaw, and the front part of 
 the head of similar animals can be reproduced after removal. 
 
 Processes of repair in ourselves take place in perfect un- 
 consciousness, and our will has no direct control over them ; 
 but they are directed to a useful end, and are carried on by 
 vital processes which are practically full of purpose though 
 their end is altogether unforeseen, because quite unknown 
 to the patient who benefits by them. 
 
 These facts as to unconscious but appropriately purposive 
 processes of repair naturally lead us to reflect on those 
 wonderfully appropriate, and seemingly purposive processes 
 and metamorphoses whereby the embryo is developed, and 
 the adult condition gradually attained. A description of 
 such processes does not come within the sphere of the 
 present work. Indeed, some of our readers may wonder 
 why we have already said so much respecting merely vital 
 processes which are not accompanied by sensation, and may, 
 therefore, well seem altogether foreign to questions of 
 thought, knowledge, science, and its groundwork. 
 
 Nevertheless, they have a distinct reference thereto, as 
 will almost immediately appear when we come to speak of 
 instinctive action. But before entering upon that function 
 a few words must be said concerning our faculty of acquiring 
 habits. 
 
 The power of forming habits has a certain analogy with 
 reflex action, since it is the result of a power which our 
 organism possesses to react, within limits, when it is acted 
 on. Let us consider what a habit is. A " habit " is not 
 formed by repeating an action a great number of times, 
 
126 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 though it may be much confirmed and strengthened thereby. 
 If an act performed only once had not in it some power of 
 generating a habit, then a thousand repetitions of that act 
 would not generate it. Habit is the determination in one 
 direction of a previously vague tendency to action. We 
 possess a natural inclination to activity. Action is not 
 only natural to us, it is a positive want. Our powers and 
 energies also tend to increase with exercise and action (up 
 to a certain limit), while they diminish and finally perish 
 through a too long repose. Thus a power of generating 
 " habit " lies hid in all, and in the very first of those actions 
 which facilitate and increase the general activity and power 
 of our body, and facilitate and increase the exercise of that 
 power in definite modes and directions. 
 
 This tendency to bodily and mental activity, which under- 
 lies our acquisition of " habits," is closely allied to that 
 special form of action which we have above spoken of as 
 " instinctive action." Instinct, as a feeling, will concern 
 us in the next chapter, but its physiological and physical 
 aspects must be noticed here. Instinctive movements differ 
 from reflex actions in that they are not merely responsive 
 to a stimulus felt, but respond to that stimulus in such a 
 manner as to serve a future unforeseen purpose. Such an 
 action is that of the infant, which, in response to the feeling 
 produced on its lips by contact with the breast, first sucks 
 the nipple and then swallows the thence extracted nutriment 
 with which its mouth becomes filled. It is an action neces- 
 sary for the nutrition of the infant, and one performed very 
 soon after birth, when there has been no lapse of time 
 wherein it could have learned to perform that action. It is 
 also an action which is definite and precise, and one per- 
 formed in a similar manner by all infants, though it is 
 effected by a very complex mechanism, and is performed at 
 once, prior to all experience. But not only sucking and 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 1 27 
 
 deglutition, but also the movements by which the products 
 of excretion are removed from within the body of the in- 
 fant, are, in our opinion, essentially instinctive. In later 
 life various other instinctive actions minister directly or in- 
 directly to reproduction. 
 
 It is an instinct which prompts the female child to seek 
 adornments for her little body, and to fondle a doll, and 
 even press it against her breast, whence, when fully de- 
 veloped, her future baby will draw its nourishment. Later 
 on, when the time for love and courtship has arrived, in- 
 stinct leads youths and maidens to seek each other's society, 
 and tends naturally to induce affectionate feelings and ul- 
 timately caresses, each of which acts as a further stimulus, 
 ultimately leading on towards actions indispensable to the 
 race. 
 
 But instinct, as it exists in man, is very feebly and ob- 
 scurely developed, compared with the manifestations of that 
 faculty which may be met with in various of the lower 
 animals, and especially amongst insects. Chickens will, 
 very soon after they are hatched, peck at small objects, 
 grains, and insects, and but little later will at once per- 
 form, when they come in contact with water, the move- 
 ments for making it flow over their backs and fall off. 1 
 
 Some birds will feign lameness, or some other injury, to 
 draw off attention from their eggs or young. Birds of the 
 first year, when the time of migration arrives, are often the 
 earliest to depart, and duly accomplish their journey, though 
 they can have no knowledge of the route they have to 
 pursue, or the region it is the object of their journey to 
 attain. 
 
 Snakes taken out of their mother's body just before their 
 natural birth will even then threaten to strike, and, if rattle- 
 
 1 For an admirable account of such phenomena, see Habit and Instinct, by 
 C. Lloyd Morgan, F.G.S. 
 
128 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 snakes, to rattle, or at least rapidly vibrate the end of the 
 tail. 
 
 Ichneumon flies will lay their eggs within the bodies of 
 caterpillars, that they may find abundant suitable food when 
 they are hatched, but we cannot believe that they foresee 
 the purpose and practical utility of their action. 
 
 A kind of wasp, called " sphex," provides for the nutri- 
 tion of her unhatched young in an analogous but yet more 
 remarkable manner. She will hunt about till she finds a suit- 
 able caterpillar, grasshopper, or spider, which she adroitly 
 stings on the spot which induces, or on the several spots 
 which induce, complete paralysis, so as to deprive it of all 
 power of motion, but not to kill it, as to kill it would defeat 
 her purpose. This done, she stores away the helpless victim 
 along with her eggs, in order that when her eggs are hatched 
 the grubs which issue from them may find living animal food 
 ready for them and in a suitable state of helplessness ; for 
 were they not in such a state, the grubs would be utterly 
 unable to catch, retain, and prey upon them. The species 
 of sphex which preys on the grasshopper first stings it and 
 then throws it on its back, so as to get at the delicate mem- 
 brane which unites the pieces of its hard armour at their 
 joints. This it bites through to reach a specially enlarged 
 portion of nervous tissue there concealed, by mutilating 
 which it attains its practical but surely unforeseen end. 
 
 But if the adult insect cannot reasonably be supposed to 
 understand the future conditions of its unborn young which 
 it will never see, still less can the poor grub be expected to 
 understand what will be the future conditions of its own life 
 when it is a grub no longer conditions so utterly different 
 from those of which it has had any experience. Yet many 
 species of caterpillar form cocoons in modes and places most 
 suitable for their protection and for their own easy emerg- 
 ence when they have changed into the adult form. The 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 129 
 
 caterpillars of a moth found in Africa will unite their efforts 
 to form a great, as it were, common cocoon, within which 
 external envelope each caterpillar makes its own special 
 cocoon, but which are so skilfully arranged as to leave pass- 
 ages between them to facilitate their departure when, as 
 moths, the time has come for them to fly away. 
 
 The caterpillar of the emperor moth is described as spin- 
 ning for itself a double cocoon, but leaving an opening 
 fortified with elastic bristles pointing outwards, and so 
 directed that while they readily yield to pressure from 
 within, they firmly resist pressure from without. Thus the 
 caterpillar is at the same time both protected from intrusion 
 from outside, and enabled easily to obtain its own exit when 
 fully developed. 
 
 As an example of the blindness which characterises these 
 instinctive actions, we may refer to a kind of wasp which 
 does not enclose living food with her eggs, but from time to 
 time feeds the grubs which thence emerge with fresh food, 
 visiting her nest for that purpose at suitable intervals, She 
 covers her nest so carefully with sand that it is completely 
 hidden, and this covering is replaced with equal care after 
 each of her visits. While it remains thus hidden she, it is 
 said, can always find it; but if an entrance is made ready 
 for her, this, instead of helping her to get to her young, 
 seems to puzzle her completely, and even to prevent her 
 from recognising her own offspring. 
 
 But, as everyone knows, moths and butterflies habitually 
 lay their eggs on the leaves of such plants as will form 
 suitable food for the grubs when hatched, although the 
 parents themselves neither feed on such leaves nor make any 
 other use of them than that of serving as a receptacle for 
 their eggs. It may be that the parents are insects which, 
 in the adult condition, do not feed at all, and it is incredible 
 that they foresee the use to their unhatched young of leaves 
 
I3O THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 useless to themselves, and the past utility of which to the 
 grubs they once were, they cannot be supposed to remember. 
 
 Still more incredible is it, however, that a grub should 
 foresee the shape of the body it is destined later to acquire, 
 especially when this shape is widely different in the two 
 sexes. Yet the grub of the female stag-beetle, when she 
 digs the hole wherein she will undergo her metamorphosis, 
 digs it no bigger than her own body ; whereas the grub of 
 the male stag-beetle makes a hole twice as large as his own 
 body, in order to leave room for the enormous jaws (the so- 
 called " horns ") which he will have to grow. 
 
 One more example of that function of the nervous system 
 which results in instinct must here suffice. 
 
 There is a kind of beetle, called " sitaris," which is para- 
 sitic on certain bees, while its relation to those insects is 
 very different during the very different stages of existence 
 which make up its life-history. 
 
 It is hatched from eggs which the mother sitaris lays in 
 passages in the bees' nest. Instead of being in the form 
 of a grub (as is the case with beetles generally), it comes 
 forth from the egg as an active, six-legged little insect with 
 eyes and two long " feelers," or antennae. In the spring, 
 as the male bees (drones) pass out for their nuptial flight 
 with the queen, the sitaris attaches itself to one of them, 
 and as soon as the opportunity offers, passes from it to the 
 body of the queen bee. When, afterwards, the queen bee 
 lays her egg in the hive, the sitaris springs upon it, and is 
 unsuspectingly enclosed in a cell with the honey destined to 
 nourish the bee-grub when the queen's egg is hatched. 
 Thus left alone with the egg, the sitaris devours it, and 
 then undergoes a transformation in the empty egg-shell. 
 Having been active in the earliest stage of its life it assumes 
 the helpless form of a fleshy grub, which floats on the honey 
 and gradually consumes it. Afterwards it transforms itself 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 131 
 
 once more, and regaining six legs, emerges as a peaceful 
 beetle, and so with its egg begins again the cycle of this 
 species' strange life-history. 
 
 All these various forms of instinctive action consist of move- 
 ments which take place in response to feelings which have 
 been given rise to, and which are often, in part, feelings of 
 antecedent actions, which are the earlier, or the earliest, 
 stages of the whole instinctive process. An interruption of 
 the normal course of procedure will sometimes greatly im- 
 pair or render impossible the completion of the entire action 
 as we saw in the case of the wasp, the carefully concealed 
 entrance to whose nest was laid bare. They thus have a cer- 
 tain analogy with sensori-motor action, 1 which only differs 
 from reflex action because of the intervention of sensation, 
 and so might be called a sensuous-reflex action of an organ, 
 or system of organs, which so react on felt stimuli. 
 
 But in both insentient and sensuous-reflex action there is 
 a spontaneous response to a stimulus, and a response which 
 is more or less appropriate at the time of its occurrence, 
 but which certainly has no reference to future events, which 
 are to occur long after every trace of the stimulus has 
 disappeared. 
 
 The very essence of instinct, however, is that it provides 
 for a more or less distant future, often, as in the case of 
 various instincts of insects hereinbefore noticed, for the 
 wants of a succeeding generation, which will never be known 
 to the creature that performs the instinctive actions without 
 which the new generation could never come into being. 
 Instinct is essentially telic (i. e., is directed to a definite 
 end), and refers to circumstances future and unforeseen at 
 the time the instinctive action takes place. Moreover, the 
 actions which are instinctive, are actions not of this or that 
 organ, but they are rather the reactions of the whole animal 
 
 1 See ante, p. 123. 
 
132 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 in response to its environment. But though we cannot ex- 
 plain " instinct " by reflex action, insentient or sensuous, 
 there is, as we have said, a certain analogy and, we may 
 add, an affinity between all three. Indeed, all animal life 
 is reflex in the widest sense of that term ; for all vital actions 
 result, and are a reaction, from stimuli (internal or external), 
 which are either felt or not felt. The effects of stimuli, 
 moreover, differ according to what it is they stimulate. The 
 ultimate particles of the innermost substance of man's body, 
 like the minute particles which form the whole body of 
 unicellular animals, react upon the stimulus of a certain de- 
 gree of heat, moisture, or chemical action. The different 
 
 tissues ' ' which compose the bodies of multicellular animals 
 and of our own body, react more or less differently under 
 similar circumstances, as the science of the physiology of 
 the tissues shows us. The different organs and systems of 
 organs all react according to the composition of each, and 
 the study of their reactions is physiology as ordinarily 
 understood. Similarly, the entire body of a living creature 
 reacts as one whole in response to influences brought to bear 
 upon it. This we see in the hibernation, or winter sleep, of 
 bats and hedgehogs ; in the effects of violent emotions of 
 fear and anger, and in the results of sexual and reproductive 
 influences upon the whole organism. The activities and 
 reactions of the whole body of an animal including the 
 process of its individual development form a separate de- 
 partment of the study of animal functions, and may be 
 called " the physiology of organisms considered each as an 
 entire whole." 
 
 Now it is a generally admitted principle in biology that 
 structure and function vary together, and the various actions 
 of the several organs of animals depend upon the properties 
 of the parts which act. So also the activities of each animal as 
 one whole, and the sum of the actions it habitually performs 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 133 
 
 its habits and instincts are closely related to its struc- 
 ture. They may thus be said to be sensuous reflex actions 
 not of. this or that organ, but of each animal as a whole, and 
 so instinct may be explained as a form of reflex action in 
 the highest and widest sense of that term. But it must not 
 be forgotten that the actions which instinct prompts are not 
 absolutely invariable. They are modifiable to a certain ex- 
 tent by circumstances, through such powers of perception as 
 different animals may possess. The absence of accustomed 
 objects and the presence of others in their place, may lead 
 birds in abnormal conditions to build their nests in un- 
 wonted ways. Similarly, many creatures may be led, by the 
 pressure of adverse circumstances, to seek their food in ways 
 different from those which beings of their species usually 
 employ. In this we seem to see the action of a cognitive 
 power of some sort co-operating with and modifying the 
 promptings of instinct. But however much it may now and 
 again be modified, it is clear (from the facts to be noted as 
 to human infancy, the earliest stages of existence in in- 
 dividual beasts and birds, and, above all, from the instinct- 
 ive activities of insects) that there are courses of continuous 
 action to which animals are prompted by an internal spon- 
 taneous impulse, which impulse is blind as to the beneficial 
 consequences of the actions it induces. 
 
 Instinct, then, would seem to be a special internal tend- 
 ency to perform blindly a series of definite and useful actions. 
 It cannot be insentient reflex action, neither can it be what we 
 have termed the sensuous reflex action of an organ or system 
 of organs. It must be more : it must be the sensuous reflex 
 action proper to an individual animal as one whole, or, as 
 we have before said, the highest and most complex kind 
 of all reflex action, " the reflex action of the individual." 
 
 The facts and considerations brought forward in the 
 present chapter, not only show us that various material 
 
134 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 conditions are conditions indispensable for science, because 
 they are conditions indispensable for sensation, but also 
 make it clear what admirable results may proceed from 
 causes seemingly most inadequate. 
 
 The different " tissues " of our body are so combined as 
 to form efficient " organs," different sets of which are com- 
 bined into systems the activities of the tissues, organs, and 
 systems harmoniously resulting in the performance of those 
 vital functions which characterise and compose the life- 
 history of each kind of animal. 
 
 The various vital functions of the body take place in the in- 
 timate recesses of our frame quite unperceived, and in a man- 
 ner in no way directly controllable, by us. Yet these func- 
 tions are so admirably interrelated that their common result, 
 under normal conditions, is continuous and prolonged life. 
 
 Similarly, the intimate processes of repair after injury can 
 neither be perceived nor directly controlled, though their 
 outcome is the practical fulfilment of an indisputably desir- 
 able end, and yet more is this evident as regards the pro- 
 cesses of embryonic development. In pure reflex action we 
 have a clear example of the close dependence of the actions, 
 and even the practically purposive actions, of animals, on 
 the structure a#id function of their nervous system ; while in 
 sensori-motor action, habit, instinct as fixed, and instinct 
 slightly modifiable by cognition, we meet with a gradual 
 transition from actions in which the will has no sway, and 
 which need not be even matters of cognition, to acts which 
 are results of a cognitive process, and are more or less vol- 
 untary in character. 
 
 Instinct is a result a practically purposive and highly in- 
 telligent result of an impulse which is blind and, so to 
 speak, mechanical. But we shall have, in the next chapter, 
 to revert to the question concerning the nature of instinct. 
 So we think no more need be said here upon that subject. 
 
THE PHYSICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 135 
 
 More remarkable still are the results produced by means 
 of those structures we term " organs of sense." Were we 
 pure intelligences devoid of bodies and ignorant of the char- 
 acteristic psychical endowments of animals, there is nothing 
 in an eye which could lead us to suppose that the inverted 
 picture thrown upon the backs of a pair of them could enable 
 their possessor to see real external objects, and to see them 
 upright and single, and not inverted and double, as they 
 are in each man's pair of eyes. Of course, the mere eyes 
 could not see apart from the brain or apart from the brain's 
 rich supply of duly conditioned blood, etc. Where sight 
 takes place, who knows ? The exact nature of the relation 
 of the brain and its parts to actual visual cognition, who can 
 tell ? Moreover, as we have seen, the brain is double as 
 well as the organ of sight. But the practical outcome of an 
 organisation so incomprehensible in its innermost nature is 
 none the less satisfactory. That the perception of the eyes 
 is valid, and the cognitions it affords are true, can be shown 
 by comparing small solid objects apprehended by our sight 
 with the same objects as known to us by the use of our 
 hands. Not that we have any ground for considering our 
 physical means of sight less perfect than any other possi- 
 ble physical means any organ which was not an eye for ob- 
 taining a visual knowledge of objectivity. No such means, 
 which we can in any way imagine, could appear better 
 adapted or less mysterious, because every psychical result 
 of physical antecedents is most absolutely mysterious. But 
 we can hence obtain at least one practical lesson the 
 lesson, namely, that because we do not know how our bodily 
 organisation enables us to obtain a real and true knowledge 
 of what is objective, we can be none the less sure that it 
 does enable us to obtain valid cognition of that kind, and 
 one about which we are certain. 
 
 Similarly, our two ears enable us to apprehend the exist- 
 
136 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 ence of single external bodies possessing energies which 
 translate themselves into sensations of sound, as we say, in 
 our ears, though, for all we can determine, " in our brain " 
 might be an expression more in accordance with reality. 
 For our purpose, however, such distinctions are of no ac- 
 count. What is of account what relates to considerations 
 which, later on, will concern us much is the undeniable 
 fact that true and valid cognition are produced by means 
 which, save for familiar experience, we should not, a priori, 
 regard as having any capacity, or being at all likely, to pro- 
 duce them. 
 
 It also concerns us to note that there is a gradual trans- 
 ition in each of us from vital processes performed altogether 
 beyond the terminations of the nerves, in the most intimate 
 parenchyma of the body, through unfelt nervous activities 
 and nervous activities only sometimes felt, on to acts which 
 are distinctly felt and voluntarily performed. Thus, in 
 addition to our known actions and those corporeal activi- 
 ties which are only occasionally felt, there is an energy 
 operating throughout the body by the intimate activities of 
 which its vitality is ultimately and mainly sustained, and 
 through which entirely unfelt responses are constantly made 
 to received impressions, which never can be perceived, and 
 ever remain beyond the domain of consciousness. 
 
 We have in this chapter been mainly occupied about ques- 
 tions of structure, together with the vital energies such 
 structures subserve. We have been compelled to treat 
 somewhat of feelings and cognitions, as forming part of the 
 energies resulting from such structures. But in the next 
 chapter the psychical energies of sensation, imagination, and 
 sense-cognition will be our principal object, though we shall 
 incidentally revert, now and again, to matters of structure 
 and organisation, as we have had here to take some notice, 
 by anticipation, of facts of feeling and cognition. 
 
CHAPTER VI 
 
 THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 THE time has now come to leave behind us, as far as may 
 be, questions of mere physics and physiology, and turn 
 our attention to what concerns the declarations of our own 
 consciousness with respect to our feelings and cognitions. 
 
 Our present task, then, is to begin that process of intro- 
 spection which, in the first chapter of this work, 1 we declared 
 to be indispensable, and though, at first, somewhat repug- 
 nant to beginners, yet soon made easy by a little patient 
 perseverance. 
 
 Psychical facts can of course be directly known to us only 
 through such introspection only through consciousness. 
 On this account consciousness itself must be somewhat 
 considered here, although, as one of our higher psychical 
 faculties, its special place is in our next chapter but one. 
 Consciousness is one of those things which can neither be 
 defined nor made known by description. Any being who 
 did not already possess it if we can conceive of a being 
 who could know other things but not himself could never 
 be made to comprehend it by any description or definition 
 whatever. Consciousness is, for each of us, both an ulti- 
 mate fact and an ultimate abstract truth. As an ultimate 
 fact, it is that actual concrete knowledge of ourselves in the 
 act of having some feeling or experience a knowledge, the 
 
 1 See ante, p. 5. 
 137 
 
138 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 absolute certainty of which is absolutely unquestionable. 
 It is a fact which, being ultimate, is necessarily not only 
 undefinable and indescribable, but also inexplicable. We 
 know, as a fact, that we are conscious, but how that fact 
 comes about we know no more than we know the " how " 
 of any other ultimate " that " e. g., " how " it is that 
 "extended" bodies are extended, or "how" it is that 
 " motion " is a possibility, or " how " it is we can have any 
 knowledge at all. 
 
 As an abstract truth, as a universal, 1 consciousness is the 
 ideal perception which the mind gains by abstraction from 
 its experience of concrete conscious states of its own being. 
 Such abstract consciousness, like all other abstractions, is, of 
 course, only an idea, and has no real existence except in that 
 actual living consciousness of an individual conscious being, 
 which is the foundation of the idea. 
 
 Consciousness constantly attends our normal waking life, 
 though, of course, it is but rarely that we are expressly con- 
 scious of our consciousness. We only become so by turning 
 back the mind and saying, " Now I know that I am con- 
 scious." That is reflex consciousness. But, like all our 
 other ordinary mental acts, it is accompanied by direct 
 consciousness. 
 
 Had we not true and valid knowledge in our direct 
 consciousness, without the need of turning back the mind 
 and reflecting thereon, we could never have any knowledge 
 at all ; for we should have to go through a regressus ad 
 infinitum to obtain it in other words, we never could 
 obtain it. 
 
 When we do turn back the mind and reflect on our ex- 
 perience, we become aware (with special attention to the 
 fact as a fact) expressly of what we may be doing, as when 
 we are playing golf, or engaged in any other amusement or 
 
 1 See ante, p. 6. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 139 
 
 occupation whatsoever. Thus, consciousness seems to be 
 normally, in its very essence, continuous, and, while exist- 
 ing at each instant, to be aware (directly or reflexly) of its 
 persistence of its continuity. We each of us know and are 
 conscious, not only that we are actually doing whatever we 
 may be about (as, for example, the reader while reading this 
 passage is aware that he is reading it), but also that before 
 we began to read it we were doing something else. But 
 what still remains to be said about consciousness we shall 
 reserve for a future chapter. Here it is only necessary to 
 recognise the facts: (i) that we know and are conscious of 
 our mental states, and (2) that when we are conscious that 
 we have a thought or feeling, it is absolutely certain 
 that we really have it ; (3) that in being thus conscious of our 
 present feeling, we both know it as a feeling, and therefore 
 something so far objective as it is an object of thought; 
 and (4) also that this feeling is something we are actually 
 feeling, and therefore so far subjective. In this act of per- 
 ception, then, subject and object appear to be identified ; 
 but this will be further considered later on. What, then, 
 does this absolutely trustworthy and infallible witness tell 
 us about our own psychical states ? Turning our mental 
 eye inwards, and considering our experiences by a process 
 of introspection, what does it tell us concerning the question 
 as to whether any mental states can exist, as it were, beside 
 consciousness states, the past existence of which, conscious- 
 ness can by some means become fully aware of as having 
 certainly existed ? 
 
 It is unquestionable that our consciousness can and does 
 inform us of the existence of very different kinds of psychi- 
 cal experience. Thus it tells us of our very distinct feelings 
 of colour, sound, smell, taste, and touch; or sometimes that 
 we have feelings of exerting force, or undergoing pressure; 
 also that we have feelings which are simultaneous and others 
 
I4O THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 which are successive, etc. Besides all these feelings and 
 others allied to them, our consciousness also tells us that we 
 have a multitude of cognitions of very different kinds, some 
 of which are direct perceptions of external objects, others of 
 the force of arguments, or of the evidence of axioms, or the 
 truth of intellectual principles. Now in our visual percep- 
 tion of the world about us, our consciousness informs us 
 that we perceive at any one time a certain small portion of 
 our field of vision with special distinctness, but that around 
 this portion, receding on all sides, are visual perceptions 
 which become more and more indistinct and, as it were, 
 " out of focus." Similarly, in our musical experience, we 
 hear with great distinctness a series of sounds as they suc- 
 ceed each other, as also that they gradually fade as they re- 
 cede from the present into the past ; while, if we are listening 
 to a more or less familiar melody, the notes which are about 
 to be heard become anticipated, so that past, present, and 
 future may be more or less truly present to the mind simul- 
 taneously. Similarly, once more, in all that we attend to, 
 there is always some part of what our mind is occupied 
 about which is apprehended with special distinctness, while 
 other matters more or less nearly related thereto are cognised 
 with various inferior degrees of clearness of perception. 
 
 Whatever might be the case in this respect with a creature 
 all intellect, and independent of material conditions, such, 
 it would seem, must be the case with beings like ourselves. 
 It must be so, because all our most abstract ideas require to 
 be attended and supported by mental images or phantas- 
 mata, which have been derived from the actual experiences 
 our senses have gained from material things. Since also 
 material things, and therefore our imaginations of them, 
 can only be attended to with the greatest keenness piece- 
 meal and in succession, it cannot be otherwise with the 
 intellectual considerations they minister to and support. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 141 
 
 The recognition of these facts naturally leads us to the 
 consideration of two other very important facts to which 
 our consciousness gives distinct testimony. These are^i) 
 that past experiences will often rise up in our minds, and (2) 
 that experiences yet to come may also be anticipated. We 
 have both powers of memory and of anticipation. Thus it 
 is we have a power of faintly reviving complex groups of 
 past sensations, and so forming mental images, or imagina- 
 tions, of persons we have known, scenes we have witnessed, 
 etc. ; and we have also the power not only of thus imagining 
 the past, but also what is, or may be, yet to come. We 
 thus also become fully aware that we can (as pointed out in 
 the first chapter) apprehend certain degrees of likeness and 
 of difference, and can cognise ' ' relations. ' ' l We can also be 
 only too sure we have sometimes feelings of pain as well as 
 of pleasure, which appear to us external in origin, as well 
 as internal pleasurable and painful feelings accompanied 
 with anticipations or recollections feelings which we dis- 
 tinguish as emotions and desires. Yet other mental states 
 are also clearly known to us which may, or may not, ac- 
 company the last-named feelings e. g., states which we 
 term " volitions." 
 
 Thus consciousness, in examining the mind which is con- 
 scious, perceives its perceptions, feelings, and activities with 
 differences of intensity and of other qualities. But con- 
 sciousness/ through memory, also shows us as will shortly 
 be pointed out that we have had experiences without 
 advertence and vague cognitions of presence, absence, and 
 relations of various kinds, to which consciousness at the 
 time did not attend, so that we were unconscious of parts 
 of our mental affections not that we were not conscious 
 when we were so affected, but that our attention was other- 
 wise occupied. It is, of course, impossible for us directly to 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 8 and 91. 
 
142 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 perceive these unconscious psychical processes, because 
 whatever we direct our mental gaze upon becomes thereby 
 in the very focus of consciousness. Nevertheless, by the 
 aid of memory and reasoning, we may plainly perceive that 
 we have passed through such unconscious psychical states. 
 
 It is very desirable that we should endeavour to recognise 
 and distinctly draw out, through the assurance of our con- 
 sciousness, that we must have had certain mental modifi- 
 cations which we did not advert to at the time when our 
 senses were being thus acted upon and were receiving such 
 impressions. 
 
 Before proceeding to do so, however, we desire to recall 
 to the reader's mind, yet once more, our representation ' of 
 the distinction which exists between feelings and ideas, as 
 also that ideas cannot exist for us, unless ministered to and, 
 as it were, supported by mental images, that is, by feelings 
 of the imagination. These two facts may help us to under- 
 stand how it is that, although we have no ground to regard 
 our mind as other than a perfect unity, it yet has two orders 
 of mental powers. There are two kinds of mental activity : 
 (i) those allied to the sensations which are the means of 
 perception, but which consciousness does not advert to when 
 it perceives an object; (2) those allied to the intellectual 
 perceptions to which such sensations and imaginations min- 
 ister. A great number of mental facts mental processes 
 may be grouped around each of these two kinds 'of mental 
 affection. Those which are allied to feelings and imagina- 
 tions constitute our lower mental faculties ; while those allied 
 to our intellectual perceptions are our higher ones. No one, 
 probably, will question that a process of conscious reasoning 
 and a perception of the truth of an axiom are higher mental 
 processes than mere feelings of colour, warmth, or sweetness. 
 
 This distinction between our higher and lower mental 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 10-13. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 143 
 
 powers, though it has been so long and so generally neglected, 
 we believe to be one of the most profound and important 
 truths in psychology, and one the recognition of which is 
 absolutely necessary for everyone who would attain to a 
 sound and reasonable philosophy. 
 
 But as we are intellectual and conscious beings, we should 
 expect that every lower mental process would, in us, be 
 more or less modified by our higher nature, through the 
 existence of which alone we can (through reflection) ever 
 become aware of the existence of any such lower mental 
 process. As to animals, we can have no psychical experi- 
 ence of any creature's mind but our own. Nevertheless, 
 observation, experiment, and inference, in combination, 
 may suffice to give us a trustworthy assurance that faculties 
 like our lower psychical powers exist in them, and that they 
 are, or are not, sufficient to account for all their actions, how- 
 ever rational such actions may, at first sight, appear to be. 
 
 As a familiar illustration of this distinction to which we re- 
 fer as existing in ourselves, may be mentioned a circumstance 
 which has, perhaps, happened to many of our readers as it 
 has repeatedly happened to ourselves. In walking along a 
 street with consciousness absorbed by some train of thought, 
 it may suddenly strike us. that we had passed a house over 
 the shop-window of which there was a remarkable, or a 
 familiar, name, and then, turning back, find that our sus- 
 picion was justified. We may thus see that we had ex- 
 perienced sensations, grouped together into a mental image, 
 but which, so far as we can perceive, never rose into con- 
 sciousness. Again, we may set out to visit a friend at a 
 residence well known to us, and our consciousness, absorbed 
 as in the former case, may not serve to make us recognise 
 the familiar spot we were seeking, and we may only be awak- 
 ened to the fact that we have passed it by, through a check 
 to our career given by some passing vehicle. But while we 
 
144 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 have thus been walking in reverie, our senses, though not 
 our intellect, have been awake to all the conditions which 
 were necessary to enable us to walk without accident through 
 peopled streets, with repeated steppings down and up kerb- 
 stones, and other similar movements. Each turning, each 
 crossing, may have been accurately effected, and though we 
 had no consciousness of the several objects which passed 
 before our eyes, yet we must have felt them and had an un- 
 conscious sensuous cognition of them, or they never could 
 have served to guide us safely along our path. 
 
 Once more, let us suppose the case of a young lady play- 
 ing with perfect facility on the piano a difficult but well- 
 practised piece of music. While she is playing it, she talks 
 to a gentleman she thinks likely to " propose " to her. 
 
 Her consciousness is absorbed in attending to his words, 
 his tone, and manner, with mental side-glances as to fortune, 
 temper, and other matters. Yet she need never stumble in 
 her performance, or fail in exactitude as to the force of 
 stroke or prolongation of pressure to be applied to the dif- 
 ferent keys ; indeed, were she to direct her attention thereto, 
 the perfection of her execution might be thereby impaired 
 just as (once more) running up and down stairs may be im- 
 peded by the express direction of attention to the movements 
 necessary to effect it. Most persons who can play melodies 
 on the ,piano " by heart," know how, when they fail in any 
 familiar passage, the worst thing they can do is to think 
 what the order of the forgotten series of notes should be, 
 and that their best course is to turn their mind away to 
 something else while they try to play it unconsciously and 
 automatically. In other words, the melody is recalled by 
 avoiding the use of the intellect and trusting to the sensuous 
 association which has been formed between successive notes, 
 and which has become, as it were, embodied in the nerves 
 and muscles of the pianist. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 145 
 
 And here it seems desirable to point out the differences 
 which exist between our higher and our lower mental facul- 
 ties as regards " memory." 
 
 Memory is sometimes said to be a faculty which revives 
 past feelings and ideas. But any number of feelings or ideas 
 which might be revived and so once more felt or thought, 
 would not constitute true memory unless they were recog- 
 nised as having existed before, and as relating to the past. 
 Nevertheless, reason shows us that our being must somehow 
 have powers through which past feelings and imaginations 
 can be retained and revived without their appearance in 
 consciousness. 
 
 Now two feelings, which have been experienced by us 
 successively or simultaneously, may be so closely associated 
 that on the recurrence of one, the other may recur also. It 
 is natural to us thus to associate feelings and imaginations 
 which have been frequently experienced together. Thus 
 groups, and groups of groups, of such mental states may 
 become associated and will recur as just stated, and this may 
 take place anterior to, or without any intellectual advertence 
 to the ideas such associated feelings may occasion and serve 
 to support. Thus the sound of a dinner-bell, or the sight 
 of an expanded umbrella, may instantly arouse in our minds 
 associated mental images of food or of rain. It is not only 
 that we know, by an intellectual cognition, that the bell is a 
 call to dinner, or that the umbrella has been opened on ac- 
 count of rain. These cognitions of the intellect we may, of 
 course, have, but the associated mental images may be called 
 up before them and persist, sometimes to our annoyance, 
 after them; the notes of a melody familiar in times long 
 past may arouse vivid mental images and keen emotions re- 
 lating to the days of our youth, and even a mere perfume 
 will sometimes have a similar effect. How true it is that 
 these lower mental states can exist apart from intellectual 
 
146 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 cognition is proved by the fact that even idiots may some- 
 times have their emotions similarly aroused. 
 
 Such revivals of past feelings, unrecognised as such, can- 
 not, as before said, be properly called memory, but, except 
 for not being recognised, they closely resemble it, and may 
 therefore be distinguished as examples of what may be 
 termed " sensuous memory," or the memory of the imagina- 
 tion. It is this lower power which lies at the base of our 
 true intellectual powers of memory and reminiscence, and it 
 is by its aid, as we believe, that we are able to carry on 
 during those unconscious states of reverie and " absent- 
 mindedness " the actions we have above noted. It is by 
 associated groups, and groups of groups, of feelings and 
 imaginations, that we are enabled so practically to cognise 
 objects in a merely sensuous way that such complex actions 
 can be performed without intellectual advertence. 
 
 In our next chapter we shall inquire whether animals, by 
 the use of faculties analogous to our lower mental powers 
 only, may not be enabled to do a variety of seemingly 
 rational actions without consciousness, and therefore without 
 knowing that they do them. We, being intellectual creat- 
 ures, cannot (as before observed) know that we have these 
 lower faculties save by the intervention of the higher save 
 by introspection, the interrogation of consciousness, and 
 a consciousness of at least much of our environment. But 
 we can, through observation and memory, be sure that we 
 must occasionally have cognised objects with merely sensu- 
 ous cognition and without consciousness. And since we can 
 always argue that what has actually happened must be at 
 least a possible thing, we may also be sure that merely 
 sensuous cognition is possible, since we must really have 
 had it. Without such cognitions the actions above noted 
 as taking place during reverie and absence of mind could 
 never be performed. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 147 
 
 And the facts we noted in our last chapter ought to make 
 the occurrence of such merely sensuous actions easy of com- 
 prehension, because they have much resemblance to those 
 acts of sensuous reflex action and those instinctive actions 
 which were therein described. 
 
 But since such complex instinctive actions, and actions 
 resulting from sensuous cognition, are the action of the body 
 as a whole, and as the sensations which give rise to such 
 sensuous cognitions are often feelings produced by very 
 different sense organs by sights and sounds, feelings of 
 touch, pressure, etc. they must clearly be referred to, and 
 receive responses from, some common sensorium. 
 
 Now in the cases referred to, consciousness is not called 
 into play, but is otherwise occupied, and in consequence we 
 require a term to denote such a faculty and sensorium in 
 ourselves and in animals, at least in such as all would agree 
 have not intellectual consciousness. It has then been sug- 
 gested to denote that lower psychical faculty, that meeting 
 together of sensuous impulses of the most diverse kinds, by 
 the term Consentience. 
 
 Sometimes, as both in reverie and a state of absorbed 
 attention to some object, our minds are in a condition in 
 which all the direct consciousness of our being seems to be 
 suspended, and we have but a vague feeling of our existence 
 a feeling resulting from the unobserved synthesis of all 
 the various sensations and impressions we may then be 
 subject to. Such a blending of feelings is a form of con- 
 sentience, and it is by this faculty that the unconscious 
 sleep-walker receives and accurately responds to the varied 
 impressions which surrounding objects make on his organs, 
 and by it also the idiot makes such responses, as he may be 
 able to make, to similar impressions. It is to consentience 
 again that the ability to perform many instinctive actions is 
 due. 
 
148 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 In many of our rational actions, which consciousness 
 knows and can analyse, we can by attention detect the 
 merely sensuous elements of our cognitions. These ele- 
 ments might be expected to be capable of producing in 
 lower natures in mere animals acts apparently intelligent, 
 but which are not really so. 
 
 Thus we may recognise the presence of feelings of self- 
 activity or passivity accompanying our perceptions of those 
 states. When we draw our hand over a foreign body or 
 grasp it, we may detect one such feeling underlying our 
 perceptions, and both at once, when rubbing the hands 
 together or when struggling against a violent wind. 
 
 Similarly, a variety of sensations, real and imagined, 
 underlie our perceptions of succession, extension, position, 
 shape, size, number, and motion, and can, with a little 
 care, be easily detected and discriminated. Thus as we feel 
 the series of sensations of contact when the links of a chain 
 are drawn across the hand, we have feelings corresponding 
 with succession and motion. When handling a solid cube 
 we have feelings related to extension, shape, size. Again, 
 in a multitude of actions for example, in climbing up a 
 bank we have feelings relating to " relative position," and 
 we may also acquire such by merely drawing our hand from 
 the ankle upwards to the thigh. Of course, we have no 
 feeling of succession itself or of the other abstract ideas 
 above mentioned, but we have feelings which specially cor- 
 respond with all of those ideas just referred to. Such 
 feelings as serve to guide the footsteps of the unconscious 
 sleep-walker, might well be sufficient to direct the move- 
 ments of any creatures which were richly endowed with 
 feeling, but denied the power of intellect. 
 
 Similarly, we have feelings closely connected with percep- 
 tions of agreement or disagreement, and others which ac- 
 company surprise or doubt. Let us suppose that we grasp 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 149 
 
 an artificial orange so made as not only to look, but also to 
 feel, like a real orange, and that we cut it, and to our surprise 
 find its interior to be very different from what we expected 
 it to be. Thereupon we have, of course, our intellectual 
 perception of the fact, but we also have a certain feeling of 
 " shock," which accompanies our surprise at making the 
 discovery. Similarly, if the nature of an object seems to 
 us doubtful, we have a feeling of " suspended action " ac- 
 companying our state of intellectual doubt. If the object 
 turns out to be what we supposed, as we discover it we have 
 a simultaneous feeling of " smooth and easy transition " 
 along with our perception that our anticipation has been 
 fulfilled. If it should turn out otherwise, then, as we per- 
 ceive the disagreement, we have a feeling somewhat like 
 that which we get from a suddenly arrested motion. 
 
 Thus by the occurrence of different sensations and differ- 
 ent combinations with imaginations by the association of 
 sensations, imaginations, feelings of pain or pleasure with 
 those of activity, passivity, succession, extension, figure, 
 magnitude, unity, multiplicity, motion, and rest we come 
 to have most varied complex groups of feelings correspond- 
 ing with states of the world about us and of ourselves. 
 These groups of groups of feelings underlie and accompany 
 our intellectual perceptions, on which account they may be 
 termed " sensuous-cognitions," or " sense-perceptions," 
 since they may produce practical results resembling those of 
 intellectual cognitions and perceptions in any creature 
 capable of feeling them, but devoid of consciousness. 
 
 If we reflect on these sensuous cognitions with the asso- 
 ciations which may be established between feelings, as evi- 
 denced by the effects of merely sensuous memory, we shall 
 see that merely sensuous mental states may bear a notable 
 resemblance, practically, to true inference. 
 
 When different groups of feelings have become intimately 
 
150 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 associated, then, on the occurrence of one group, an imagin- 
 ation of the other group will arise in the mind, and we 
 have an " expectant feeling " of their proximate actual re- 
 currence as we may have an expectant feeling of orange 
 pulp when cutting the artificial orange. 
 
 This expectant imagination of feelings yet to come, has a 
 decided analogy with reasoning and inference, although 
 quite distinct and unlike them essentially. Very noticeable 
 also is that feeling of wondering expectancy which will arise 
 when some strange sound is heard, or some startling move- 
 ment seen, followed by a feeling of complacency when an 
 innocent cause of either comes in view. 
 
 Such feelings are the sensuous accompaniments of an in- 
 tellectual search for a cause followed by its satisfactory 
 detection. 
 
 Strong feelings, and especially strong emotions, tend to 
 manifest themselves externally, not only without our know- 
 ledge and intention, but against our utmost efforts, when we 
 become conscious of such manifestations. Thus terror and 
 anger show themselves by external signs, which express 
 feelings, not ideas, and so may be said to constitute a " lan- 
 guage of emotion." 
 
 Such unintellectual language manifests itself, as we have 
 just said, " by external signs." This is quite true in one 
 sense, yet, without further explanation, the assertion may 
 be misleading, as the word " sign" is used in two very 
 different meanings. 
 
 A " sign," in the full sense of that term, is a token or de- 
 vice addressed to eye or ear, depicting by some external 
 manifestation an internal, abstract idea, and made use of 
 with the intention of conveying to another mind the idea or 
 ideas in the mind of the sign-maker. 
 
 Yet a sign may be truly such, though quite in another 
 way. Thus the external contortion of the features in terror, 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 151 
 
 or screams or verbal exclamations, are truly signs to onlook- 
 ers of the feeling of the terror-stricken person. But as the 
 latter has not contorted his features or uttered sounds with 
 the intention of making his terror known, it can be nothing 
 but an accidental sign. 
 
 Yet, again, a sign may be made with the object of attract- 
 ing attention so far as to gain sympathy or make known a 
 sympathy felt. Such signs may be an uplifting of the eyes 
 with the hands clasped, or a hand may be smilingly kissed, 
 or articulate words of tender endearment may be uttered, or 
 curses may be shouted with clenched fists, the words in 
 neither case having any further meaning than an indication 
 of the feelings contained. Such signs, of course, are not 
 those of the first category, but only emotional signs. 
 
 We have before noticed the remarkable way in which 
 movements may be spontaneously and unconsciously co- 
 ordinated. 1 Such movements are due to feelings which have 
 also unconsciously become associated. The actions per- 
 formed apart from intellectual advertence show the power 
 we have of co-ordinating sensations as, e. g., in playing 
 the piano " by heart." Then the motions of the hands 
 and fingers follow each other in orderly succession, which is 
 manifestly due to co-ordinated sensations of touch and hear- 
 ing felt touches of the keys, and heard sounds of the 
 strings. Let only one note have become dumb, or one of 
 the keys struck fail to rise, and the whole automatic action 
 may come to an end through a failure of co-ordination in 
 the associated sensations. 
 
 But our power of unconsciously synthesising our move- 
 ments into one complex general action as in the stone- 
 throwing before described 2 runs parallel with another 
 remarkable power we have of unconsciously synthesising 
 
 various pleasurable tendencies into one dominant impulse. 
 
 
 
 1 See ante, p. 117. * See ante, pp. 117, 118. 
 
152 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 This power is singularly analogous to, though toto ccelo dif- 
 ferent from, volition. That we have such a power is mani- 
 fest from the actions of persons when walking in their sleep, 
 or during a state of reverie, and also from the actions of 
 some idiots. Another sensuous power we possess, and 
 which we may term " sensuous attention," is one that 
 simulates the intellectual and voluntary act we know as 
 paying attention to, deliberately observing, anything. 
 
 Thus persons who walk in their sleep have been observed, 
 when missing some object from its wonted place, to begin 
 to look or feel for it. We may also observe in ourselves, 
 when startled by some new and disturbing object, how our 
 senses automatically direct themselves to it without waiting 
 for the bidding of our conscious will. 
 
 But the complex association and co-ordination of a group, 
 or groups, of feelings (sensations and mental images), with 
 resulting co-ordination of groups of movements, may have 
 a yet more remarkable result. They may result in the 
 spontaneous, unconscious, and automatic employment of 
 what are, practically, " means to an end," quite apart from 
 any intellectual recognition of either means or end as such. 
 This result is sometimes strikingly manifested by somnambul- 
 ists, Who have been known to perform very complicated ac- 
 tions. Under such circumstances, a drawer may be opened 
 or a door unlocked in an unconscious search to obtain some 
 object or reach some locality. Such actions are easily 
 explicable in the way above stated. For the consentience 
 of the sleep-walker is impressed by various groups of sensa- 
 tions, such as those produced by the walls and furniture of 
 the room the sleep-walker may be traversing on the way to 
 the desired locality, the door of which is locked. The feel- 
 ings thus excited arouse his imagination of the inside of the 
 place sought, this in turn excites the nervous channels 
 habitually stimulated in overcoming the intervening obstruc- 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 153 
 
 tion the hand automatically seeks the key; the feelings 
 produced by its touch stimulate the muscles of the arm ; 
 the key is turned, and the door opened. Very complex 
 movements are sometimes thus automatically performed in 
 order to complete a sensuous harmony which the imagina- 
 tion, through habit, has come to crave. It craves for fresh, 
 completing sensations, and is thus led to perform appro- 
 priate movements when certain initial sensations have 
 been afresh excited, after which the completing sensations 
 have (in past experience) habitually followed. This, then, 
 is the " practical imagination of means to effect a desired 
 end." 
 
 Such sensuous acts are what we should expect to find 
 amongst animals if they are, as they have generally been 
 supposed to be, creatures richly endowed with sensitive 
 faculties, though devoid of those which are intellectual. 
 
 But what judgment are we to form with respect to the 
 highest psychical faculties of animals ? That is the next 
 question to which we must now address ourselves. The ques- 
 tion, however, is not, of course, to be pursued for its own 
 sake in a work such as this, but for the sake of its indirect 
 bearing on Epistemology. 
 
 Many persons who have accepted the Darwinian hypo- 
 thesis as to evolution are inclined to distrust their own reason, 
 as being but the intelligence of a more highly developed 
 ape. If, therefore, the study of animal intelligence should 
 convince our readers that there is a difference of kind be- 
 tween the psychical nature of man and that of animals, such 
 reason for distrust must disappear. But, on the other hand, 
 should we become convinced that there is no difference of 
 kind, the distrust referred to need not thereby be strength- 
 ened. For animals would then be seen to be of a much higher 
 nature than has been usually supposed, since (as we shall 
 see) there can be no doubt as to our own rationality. If 
 
1 54 THE GRO UND WORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 animals are also rational, though but potentially so, we may 
 suppose that their environment and some incompleteness of 
 internal development has prevented them from hitherto 
 manifesting their latent rationality. It must have remained 
 hidden, as that of the human infant is concealed by the co- 
 existence of internal and external conditions, which make 
 its external manifestation impossible. There would, there- 
 fore, be no more reason to distrust the dictates of human 
 reason, because developed from that of an unconscious 
 animal, than because developed (as that of all men has been) 
 from that of an unconscious infant. 
 
 We can, therefore, address ourselves czquo animo to the 
 question of animal intelligence and study it with the most 
 complete impartiality, since the absolute value of the 
 dictates of our own intelligence cannot be affected thereby. 
 Nevertheless, the question is most interesting, as bearing 
 on the problem of nature's continuity, and as being one to 
 which many excellent persons have (we believe most mis- 
 takenly) attached an extreme importance. 
 
 In dealing with this matter, great confusion and numerous 
 mistakes have arisen from the fact that many persons will 
 attempt to understand and explain the psychical powers of 
 animals without having previously obtained a comprehen- 
 sion of their own. As Mr. C. Lloyd Morgan has amusingly 
 remarked, 1 " the psychologist is apt sometimes to smile 
 when, after the recital of some anecdote of animal intelli- 
 gence, the writer exclaims, ' If this is not reason, I do not 
 know what reason is.' As, however, in such cases, the 
 writer has himself suggested the alternative, there is perhaps 
 no discourtesy on the part of the psychologist in accepting 
 it." Indeed, men often interpret the actions of animals in 
 a way which they regard as being simple and natural. 
 
 1 In his excellent work entitled Introduction to Comparative Psychology, p. 
 261. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 155 
 
 " Simple and natural " such explanations would be if they 
 were applied to human beings, but exceedingly forced and 
 unnatural they may be when applied in estimating the acts 
 of creatures the natures of which are exceedingly different. 
 They are also apt to be caught ia a snare, which it is as 
 necessary as it is difficult to avoid. This is the necessity we 
 are all under of expressing ourselves in terms which have 
 been gained as the result of prolonged processes of abstrac- 
 tion, since, as we have before observed, 1 all our words are the 
 results of such processes. To make use of such symbols, 
 then, to denote psychical states which are not the result of 
 abstraction, is to run the greatest risk either of misrepre- 
 sentation or of being misapprehended. 
 
 Occam's celebrated saying, " Entia non sunt multiplicanda 
 prater necessitatem," applies to psychology as well as to 
 other sciences, and it forbids us to credit mere animals with 
 the higher human mental powers when their actions can be 
 quite well explained more simply by those lower psychical 
 activities which we have just passed in review as existing in 
 ourselves. The tales told by the owners of pet animals 
 are often absolutely untrustworthy, so strong is the ten- 
 dency they have unconsciously to exaggerate the perform- 
 ances of their favourites, and naively to interpret them in 
 terms of purely human psychology. 
 
 As to the highest psychical faculties of mere animals gen- 
 erally those which are not pets many persons credit them 
 with powers (i) of perceiving objects; (2) of perceiving rela- 
 tions between objects; (3) of perceiving their own existence 
 consciousness ; (4) of having ideas ; (5) of reasoning; (6) of 
 perceiving moral quality; (7) of expressing their ideas by 
 sounds, and (8) by gestures. 
 
 Since the question of animal rationality is for us a sub- 
 ordinate question, with only an indirect bearing on our main 
 
 1 See ante^ p. 7. 
 
THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 conclusions, we are compelled to consider the eight just 
 enumerated points but very briefly. 
 
 That animals in one sense perceive objects is, of course, 
 unquestionable. If they did not do so, coursing and hawk- 
 ing would be impossible. But what is the nature of such 
 perceptions ? We have already seen how, by turning the 
 mind backwards and considering our experience, we may 
 recognise that we have had perceptions of which we were 
 not conscious at the time we experienced them. Such per- 
 ceptions were sufficient to guide our movements, as they 
 serve to guide those of the unconscious sleep-walker in our 
 words, there was not consciousness, but only consentience. 
 Need we then credit animals with more than this ? Such 
 sense-perceptions of theirs may be much more keen and 
 more rapidly cognised than are our own. We ourselves do 
 not know of any animal actions which we think cannot be 
 explained by cognitions of this lower kind. It will be said, 
 however, for a cat to watch the movements of a mouse and 
 to catch it, needs not only that it should see the mouse, but 
 the objects around it, and the varying bearings of the run- 
 ning mouse thereto. This, of course, must be fully con- 
 ceded, yet such cognition is sufficiently accounted for by 
 that mere unintellectual, unconscious awareness which we 
 have termed 1 the "practical imagination of means to an 
 end." 
 
 Again, it may, perhaps, be objected that the cat not only 
 sees the mouse, but knows that it is a mouse and nothing 
 else. This also may be freely admitted in the sense of a 
 mere sensuous cognition or sense-perception. But there is 
 no need to credit the animal with even the direct perception 
 of the mouse, as the embodiment of a universal abstract 
 idea, such as is possessed by the lowest and most uncultured 
 human being who is sane. The cat need only have that 
 
 1 See ante, p. 153. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 synthesis of sensations and imaginations that kind of men- 
 tal image which we distinguish as a " sensuous universal." 
 
 If, then, we need not credit animals with the perception 
 of objects as we understand perception, can we credit them 
 with any perception of " relations " between objects ? The 
 answer to this question will make yet plainer what we mean 
 by a perception of objects themselves ; since, as we shall see 
 directly, such a perception of objects themselves implies a 
 perception of relations themselves. 
 
 To perceive anything with conscious perception, though 
 only that of direct consciousness, also implies a direct con- 
 sciousness of the main relations in which it stands to other 
 things, and which differentiate it from them. To perceive 
 anything with reflex consciousness, which affirms, " I do 
 know that thing to be what it is," implies and necessitates 
 a reflex consciousness also of those of its relations which en- 
 able us to be sure it is what it is. For without turning back 
 the mind to reconsider what it had previously done, we could 
 not recognise the relations as relations, and so obtain the 
 certainty we are thus enabled to reach. If we have occa- 
 sion to note only one relation as the relation of right and 
 left we must, to be conscious of it, turn our attention to 
 both these conditions successively, and then simultaneously 
 have regard to both terms, or we could not apprehend the 
 relation. 
 
 We think there is no need to credit animals with such 
 complex psychical acts in order to explain even their most 
 startling performances. It seems to us that their consen- 
 tience affords them practically sufficient sensuous percep- 
 tions of the relations in which objects and events stand to 
 each other, as well as of the objects themselves. 
 
 Similarly, it is plain that animals have a practical sense of 
 their existence, and run no risk of mistaking another creature 
 for themselves. But for such a sensitive synthesis there is 
 
158 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 no need of consciousness, as we know by purely human ex- 
 perience. All that is needed is consentience, and this no 
 one can doubt that they possess, and probably exert this 
 faculty with greater energy than we do, on account of the 
 absence in them of a truly intellectual, conscious self- 
 perception, such as that which enables us to perceive that 
 " I am I, and not another." 
 
 As to the possession by animals of " ideas," no one can 
 deny them such psychical activities as are often so termed 
 namely, the faint revival of complex groups of past sensa- 
 tions and imaginations previously experienced, and varied 
 associations of groups of groups of such psychical states. 
 But this is by no means what we understand by " ideas." 
 An " idea " is a " psychical " entity, which spontaneously 
 starts forth in our mind, upon the reception of certain 
 sensuous experiences (sensations and imaginations), like 
 Athene from the head of Zeus. Thus one of our earliest 
 ideas is also the most ultimate and most abstract, namely, 
 the idea of being. For the rest we must refer our readers 
 to what we have said about " ideas " in our first chapter. 1 
 But it has been very unreasonably contended, since animals 
 examine and reject some things for food and yet eat other 
 things with avidity, that they must have such universal 
 ideas as " good-for-eating " and " not-good-for-eating. " 
 Now, the inner nature and faculties of an organism can only 
 be judged of by the outcome of its powers, whatever these 
 may be. If animals really had ideas of the kind, and con- 
 sciously performed voluntary acts of examination in order 
 to see which of two general ideas might be applicable in any 
 given case, then they would, most surely, soon make us 
 very fully aware of it by other less equivocal manifestations 
 of their possession of intellectual faculties essentially like 
 our own. Interpretations such as the above might carry us 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 10-13. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 159 
 
 very far. We might say, for instance, that plants have 
 abstract ideas of " suitable-for-nutrition " and " not-suit- 
 able-for-nutrition," and of the still more abstract ideas, 
 " big-enough-to-be-worth-a-prolonged-effort," and " not- 
 big-enough-to-be-worth-a-prolonged-effort. " For Venus's 
 looking-glass (Dioncea) will snap together the blades of its 
 singular leaf to catch an insect, but will not do so to catch 
 a non-digestible object. More than this, if the blades of its 
 leaf have closed on an insect of very small size (not worth 
 catching) they will (it is said) unclose and let it go again; 
 while otherwise they will hold it till it is killed and digested. 
 
 Animals, even very lowly ones, possess multitudes of com- 
 plex associations of feelings and movements. What, then, 
 is more to be expected than that when an animal experiences 
 a group of new sensations from a novel object, it should 
 apply its senses and consentience to aid their reception and 
 instinctively make movements in response thereto ? Such 
 movements need be no sign of the existence of ideas when 
 other evidence clearly points to their non-existence. 
 
 Sensuous analogues of ideas, then, animals, of course, 
 possess, and the phenomena they present do not, we be- 
 lieve, demand the recognition in them of any higher powers 
 for their satisfactory explanation. 
 
 Similarly, the faculty of reason which we possess is, we 
 believe, quite distinct from any power possessed by mere 
 animals. There are, indeed, many actions on their part 
 which at first sight look like reason, but for which that lower 
 faculty of our own we have termed 1 " expectant imagina- 
 tion " amply accounts, so far as we can see. 
 
 In considering this question we should always take pains 
 to understand and correctly appreciate the distinction which 
 exists between true " inference," which is an essentially in- 
 tellectual apprehension of a truth as implicitly contained in 
 
 1 See ante, p. 150. 
 
l6o THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 other truths, and that mere sensuous reinstatement of past 
 impressions which may simulate it. The latter affection is 
 what we regard as the " sensuous " or " organic " inference 
 of animals. Let any group of sensations have become in- 
 timately associated with certain other sensations, then, as 
 before pointed out, upon the recurrence of that group, an 
 imagination of the sensations previously associated therewith 
 spontaneously arises in the mind, and we have, as before 
 said, an expectant feeling of their proximate actual recur- 
 rence as in the instance of a flash of lightning having come, 
 by association, to lead to an expectant feeling of thunder 
 to follow. 
 
 Thus mere " association " may give rise to " feelings of 
 expectation," which when satisfied may give rise to a feeling 
 of satisfaction or completion, and such may certainly exist 
 in animals as well as in ourselves without the presence of 
 any true reasoning faculty. 
 
 In Mr. C. Lloyd Morgan's work, 1 already referred to, 
 readers will find a very painstaking examination of the evi- 
 dence both for and against the rationality of animals. 
 
 Although his opinion favours the non-existence of a differ- 
 ence of kind between human and animal intelligence, he is, 
 nevertheless, of opinion that animals can neither perceive 
 relations nor reason, and that with the advent of the latter 
 power a breach of continuity and a fresh departure really 
 took place. The book also contains a careful criticism of a 
 variety of tales concerning animal intelligence. 
 
 He is also of opinion that animals are entirely devoid of 
 ethical perceptions; but other persons are not wanting who 
 do credit them with moral perception ! 
 
 That dogs will not only love their master but readily obey 
 his commands, and feel pain if they have yielded to a tempta- 
 tion to transgress them, may be very true. That dogs and 
 
 1 Introduction to Comparative Psychology. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE l6l 
 
 other animals may sometimes feel impelled to assist their 
 fellows in distress on witnessing their sufferings, we should 
 not care to dispute, and it is possible that to some migrating 
 bird, which has left its young behind, an imagination of its 
 deserted brood may arise and cause it a painful emotion. 
 But such feelings have really nothing to do with ethical 
 perception. " Conscience " is the exercise of judgment in 
 a particular direction. It is a particular kind of judgment 
 namely, a judgment about " right " and " wrong," and 
 nothing else. Acting rightly is often pleasurable, but it is 
 also not unfrequently very painful, for it may tell us we are 
 bound to give up something which is for us the very joy of 
 life, or to take upon us a task as irksome as it is dutiful. 
 
 It is plain that we may feel pleasure in doing things which 
 are wrong, for certainly otherwise they would never be done. 
 On the other hand, there may be much painful regret on ac- 
 count of quite innocent actions, such as some trifling breach 
 of etiquette. Keen remorse also may be felt on account of 
 having neglected some excellent opportunity of pushing our 
 fortune, or even of committing some very pleasurable but 
 very immoral action. 
 
 The late Mr. Darwin, who may be regarded as the leading 
 exponent of the view which would regard morality as essen- 
 tially similar in men and animals, said that " conscience " 
 was " that feeling of regretful dissatisfaction which is in- 
 duced in a man who looks back and judges a past action with 
 disapproval." Now " conscience " certainly " looks back 
 and judges," but not every act of that kind which is accom- 
 panied by " regretful dissatisfaction " is a moral judgment. 
 
 A French writer has said that no regret is so keen as the 
 regret which may accompany the recollection of the non- 
 commission of pleasant sins which might have been enjoyed. 
 
 Such judgments, however much remorse may accompany 
 them, can hardly be called " moral." 
 
1 62 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 The profound distinction which exists between the idea 
 " goodness " and every other idea, will be made plain by a 
 consideration of the reasons which may be urged in favour 
 of the performance of any plain duty. 
 
 Every step we take to explain why any duty should be 
 performed, must consist of some still more simple assertion 
 of the same kind, till we come to an assertion about duty 
 the truth of which is admitted to be self-evident. 
 
 Now all our certain knowledge must be either evident in 
 itself or must depend upon some other knowledge which is 
 evident in itself. As we have before remarked, we cannot 
 go on arguing forever, and every proof must stop some- 
 where namely, when we reach what is evident of itself, and 
 therefore needs no proof. 
 
 If, then, we want to urge some statement about any par- 
 ticular action being " right " or " wrong," if that statement 
 be not admitted to be evidently true, we can only prove it 
 to be so by means of some more general and elementary 
 statement of the same nature. Therefore the judgments 
 which lie at the root of any system of thought about ethics 
 (about right and wrong) must themselves be ethical. 
 
 This profound truth shows us that it is absolutely impos- 
 sible that the power of ethical judgment could ever have 
 been gained through the experience of mere feelings of liking 
 or disliking, pleasure or pain, sympathy or aversion, good- 
 will or hostility of other beings. 
 
 It is a distinct kind of intellectual perception, and, there- 
 fore, if animals are in the least moral, they must possess the 
 power of intellectual perception, and also be able to form 
 and comprehend highly abstract truths. For the purpose 
 of this work, as before said, it does not matter in the least 
 whether a snail or a starfish has or has not this intellectual 
 faculty. We confess, however, that we have been .quite 
 unable to obtain evidence satisfactory to us that any mere 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 163 
 
 animals are endowed with intellect, though we are quite 
 ready to consider any better evidence which may be forth- 
 coming. But if we have been mistaken, and if our ethical 
 judgments have been mere congeries of animal feelings, and 
 ultimately of physical impulses, which impulses and feelings 
 have lost their way and come to mistake themselves for 
 something else, then doubts might well arise as to the other 
 declarations of our intellect, falsus in uno, falsus in omnibus, 
 and it would be difficult for us thus to arrive at a satisfac- 
 tory Epistemology. 
 
 On this account we deem it well to make a few more 
 remarks upon the essential distinction of the ethical idea, a 
 recognition of the validity of that perception being for our 
 purposes of such extreme importance. 
 
 In the first place, the assertion is sometimes made that 
 ethic is but coincidence with " social approbation." But 
 no stream can possibly rise higher than its source. " Social 
 approbation," then, could never have produced the concep- 
 tion of " right and wrong " ; for how could a mere habit of 
 obeying society have ever led a moral hero to denounce that 
 habit and defy society ? 
 
 It has, again, been often affirmed that there is no real 
 distinction between " virtue " and " pleasure." Instead of 
 there being any absolute distinction between them it is said 
 that " good actions " are merely actions pleasurable or use- 
 ful to the individual who performs them, or are advan- 
 tageous to his fellow-men. They say, also, that it is the 
 pleasurable or useful results which cause actions to be good 
 actions, not the intentions with which the doer may perform 
 them. 
 
 It is true we say " That is a ' good ' knife " because it 
 cuts well, and any weapon or any other useful article is said to 
 be a "good " one if it well serves the purpose it was intended 
 to serve. But a very little consideration will show that such 
 
164 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 a use of the word does not bring home to us the fundamen- 
 tal meaning of the term. For " conformity to an end " will 
 not make an action good unless the end aimed at is itself 
 good and agreeable to duty unless by conforming to it we 
 " follow the right order." If a young person, carefully in- 
 structed by a thief, conforms to the end aimed at so com- 
 pletely as to pick pockets with extraordinary deftness, such 
 " conformity " will not make his action a " good " one. 
 
 But if the end aimed at is really a good end, and one which 
 is for us a " duty," if we ask, " Why should we do our 
 duty ? Why should we follow the right order ? " the only 
 possible final answer is, " It is right so to do." 
 
 If it be urged in opposition that " we should follow the 
 right order because it is our true interest to do so," he who 
 so urges must either mean " we should always follow our 
 own interest," which is abandoning the rule of " right and 
 wrong" altogether, or he must mean " we should follow 
 our interest, not because it is our interest, but because it is 
 right " a proposition which, however mistaken it may be 
 in fact, yet is one which, in its mistaken way, affirms the 
 very principle, the rule of " right and wrong," which it was 
 designed to oppose. 
 
 But persons who say that the morality of any action de- 
 pends on its results can always be refuted simply by examin- 
 ing into the assertions about duty which they themselves 
 make. Thus that eminent utilitarian philosopher, the late 
 John Stuart Mill, declared that he would rather go to hell 
 than consent to call " good " a God who should violate the 
 laws of the highest human morality, and in so saying he, 
 of course, implied that other men ought to do the same. 
 
 The sentiment was a very admirable one, yet singularly 
 inconsistent in the mouth of a utilitarian. For on the one 
 hand, as a utilitarian, he taught that men in all cases should 
 seek the greatest happiness for all, while on the other he 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 165 
 
 declared, in the case supposed, that in so pursuing happi- 
 ness they should all voluntarily plunge into the greatest 
 possible misery. 
 
 But without having recourse to any such extreme supposi- 
 tion, the simplest facts suffice to show that it is not the conse- 
 quences of an act but the intention wherewith it is performed 
 which makes the action " good " or " bad." 
 
 Let us suppose that two men have each a sick wife, and 
 that the doctor has left with each man two bottles : one a 
 valuable internal remedy, the other a poisonous lotion. One 
 of these men, who is devoted to his wife, gives her by pure 
 mistake the lotion to drink, and kills her. The other man 
 desires to poison his wife, but, by also making a mistake as 
 to the bottles, gives her unintentionally the right medicine 
 and cures her. Can there be any doubt as to who is the 
 truly guilty man ? Who would venture to assert that the 
 act of the second man was really a " good " action because, 
 in spite of his evil intention, it had a good result ? 
 
 Again, it was said that the highest virtue is to do good 
 without thinking about it. Yet it cannot be the mere ab- 
 sence of thought which makes a spontaneously performed 
 useful action specially meritorious ; otherwise we should 
 attain the climax of virtue by performing beneficial actions 
 unconsciously, in a state of somnambulism. 
 
 The truly admirable nature of good actions done spon- 
 taneously and without reflection, lies in their being the 
 result of previously acquired good habits and of a fixed, 
 undeviating direction of the will towards what is right. But 
 this does not make such acts blind actions, and deprive the 
 doer of all power of knowing what he is about. A man 
 cannot act from a sense of justice without knowing justice 
 from injustice, and to approve habitually of kind and good 
 acts he must know what " goodness" is. 
 
 But another objection against the existence of any abso- 
 
1 66 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 lute distinction between " right " and " wrong " is some- 
 times drawn from the fact that different nations (and the 
 same nation at different times) take different views as to the 
 " goodness " of some particular kind of action. But this 
 argument is quite valueless. It would be absurd, indeed, 
 to suppose that all men were somehow furnished with a 
 whole code of laws directing what is to be done and what 
 abstained from in all cases. What we affirm is, that all 
 men (idiots apart) can perceive that there is such a thing as 
 " right " and " wrong." Men are not necessarily devoid 
 of morality because they draw their lines and rules in differ- 
 ent places, and actions revolting to us, such as the killing of 
 parents, may seem good to those who- kill, if they act in 
 obedience to the wishes of their parents, and to procure for 
 them, as they suppose, a happy immortality. 
 
 For the existence of moral perception it is by no means 
 necessary that men should always agree about the application 
 of ethical principles; what they agree about, though they 
 need not cognise it by a reflex act, is that some actions are 
 wrong and deserve punishment. The merest savage knows 
 that an ungrateful and treacherous injury inflicted on him- 
 self is an act of that kind. Australian savages appear to 
 have very clear and precise ethical notions about punish- 
 ments which they have themselves merited, and will hold 
 out a limb to be speared when they have done an act which 
 merits that chastisement. 
 
 Though tribes may differ as to what is right and just, 
 men have never thought an action to be right because it 
 was unjust, or because it was ungrateful, or another act to 
 be wrong because it was just or kind. 
 
 So essential is the distinction between the " good " and 
 the " useful," that not only does the idea of " benefit " 
 not enter into the idea of " duty," but the very fact of an 
 action not being beneficial may make it praiseworthy. Its 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 167 
 
 merit may be increased by any self-denial which attends on 
 its performance, and also decreased by gain. 
 
 To nurse carefully and tenderly is " good," but our ap- 
 preciation of its merit is diminished if we know that the 
 patient's death has brought his nurse a rich and hoped-for 
 legacy. A woman may have an immoral connection with 
 another's husband, but if we find that instead of any gain 
 thereby accruing, she has sacrificed herself for him, our 
 censure may be thereby mitigated, since it shows she " has 
 loved much." 
 
 In the material gain or loss which may attend our acts it 
 is not that the absence of the former, or of pleasure, bene- 
 fits our neighbour more ; it is that any diminution of pleasure 
 which circumstances may occasion (irrespective of any ad- 
 vantage thereby occasioned to our neighbour) in itself 
 heightens the value of an action. But evidently that can 
 never be the substance of duty which makes any act more 
 dutiful by its absence! 
 
 The conception of duty is the conception of something 
 supreme and absolute, apart from all question of pleasures 
 and pains, rewards and punishments, and also of utility. 
 As Cicero said, it is "Quod tale est ut detracta omni utilitate 
 sive aliis prcemiis fructibusque per se ipsumpossitjure laudari. " 
 
 Some of our readers may, perhaps, fancy that we have 
 devoted too much space to this question of ethics. But 
 without a full explanation of a matter so often misunder- 
 stood and misrepresented, the problem concerning the 
 morality of brutes could not be demonstrated with sufficient 
 clearness. There is, however, another reason why we have 
 thought it well to dwell at some length upon this question. 
 We have done so in anticipation of what we shall have to 
 say in our eighth chapter concerning our highest faculties, 
 and we consider that it has a bearing on Epistemology, 
 which cannot reasonably be ignored. 
 
1 68 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 We will now return to the question of the psychical 
 powers of brutes, and notice some anecdotes and examples 
 of their asserted intellectuality. 
 
 In considering the value of the reports made about the in- 
 telligence of this or that animal, 1 we ought carefully to bear 
 in mind two facts. If the creatures about which the asser- 
 tions are made are creatures low in the scale of animal life, 
 we should recollect the extraordinary development of in- 
 stinct amongst the class of insects. If the creatures referred 
 to are animals of a superior kind, then we should compare 
 their actions with those lower faculties which we possess, 
 and which, as we have seen, 8 enable us to do so many things 
 in a merely automatic manner. We should recollect how 
 we every now and then have experienced a feeling of malaise, 
 we did not know on what account, till we have found it 
 suddenly relieved by finding something which was pre- 
 viously missing, though we were not conscious of missing it 
 till the shock we experienced on our having automatically 
 found it has called our attention to the matter. We our- 
 selves have frequently experienced this when one of the 
 various objects we habitually carry in our pockets has been 
 unconsciously transferred from one to another. We can, 
 as everyone knows, do many things automatically and with- 
 out consciousness which we often perform with full con- 
 sciousness. This fact makes it probable that similar actions 
 may take place in animals, and another fact is also very 
 significant : this is the notorious circumstance that persons 
 deprived of one of their senses often have their remaining 
 senses made more acute. It is also commonly affirmed that 
 some savages, who have very little intellectual power, have 
 much keener powers of seeing, hearing, and, perhaps, even 
 
 1 No one has better or more thoroughly advocated the rationality of animals 
 than the late Mr. Romanes. See his book entitled Mental Evolution in Man. 
 9 See ante, pp. 143-156. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 169 
 
 of smelling, than we have. How much keener still may not 
 be the sensitive powers of creatures whose whole being is 
 entirely given up to sensitivity, without its being interfered 
 with by any true intellectual activity ! It should surely 
 cause us little wonder if we find them doing many things 
 which we ourselves could not do in similar circumstances. 
 That an elephant should blow through its trunk on the 
 ground beyond some object it sought to obtain, and thus to 
 drive it back ; that a bear should paw the water in order to 
 bring a floating piece of bread within reach, or that dogs, 
 accustomed to rivers or the seashore, should automatically 
 allow for the action of currents with which they were prac- 
 tically familiar, need occasion no surprise to anyone. Such 
 actions are just the ones we might confidently anticipate 
 should take place under the given circumstances. 
 
 The late Mr. Darwin related the circumstance that a dog 
 of his, on hearing the words " Hi ! hi ! where is it ? " rushed 
 about, looking in all directions and even up into trees; and 
 he considered that these actions clearly showed that the dog 
 entertained " a general idea that some animal was to be 
 discovered and hunted." Now, of course, such sounds 
 uttered in an eager voice excited the dog's emotions and 
 awoke in its consentience reminiscences of before-experi- 
 enced groups of smells, sounds, colours, and motions and 
 relations of various kinds, between them previously con- 
 nected with pleasurable activities and feelings of cravings 
 satisfied, etc., etc. But such groups of feelings, vivid and 
 faint, are, as we have seen before, something very different 
 from " a general idea." 
 
 Wolves have both a fear of man and a suspicious feeling 
 with respect to traps and snares, on which account they 
 have been credited with possessing an " abstract idea of 
 danger." But the lower human unconscious activities we 
 have passed in review are amply sufficient to account for 
 
1 70 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 such phenomena, especially as the smell of man may often 
 lead a wolf not to touch a bait which a man has set for him. 
 In order correctly to appreciate the limits of the emotional 
 language of animals, we must understand how much they 
 can do by mere consentience, and that actions on their part, 
 at which most ignorant wonder is often expressed, do not 
 imply either self-consciousness or the possession of any ab- 
 stract ideas. All the actions of the most intelligent animal 
 can, we think, be fully understood as results of powers 
 similar to our own lower faculties described in the last 
 chapter. For such actions on the part of animals, it is 
 necessary, indeed, that they should sensibly cognise things, 
 but not that they should perceive them intellectually ; that 
 they should feel themselves as existing, but not recognise 
 their own existence ; that they should feel relations between 
 objects, but not perceive them as relations ; that they should 
 remember, but not seek to recollect, or know that what 
 actually recurs to memory really relates to a past recognised 
 as such; that they should feel and express emotions, but 
 not know they possess them ; that they should seek what 
 pleases them, but not aim at pleasure knowingly, or know 
 that the pleasure they feel is pleasurable. By the exercise 
 of such merely sensitive faculties, brutes can pursue an es- 
 caping prey, jump up banks or rocks, climb to attain what 
 is otherwise out of reach, raise up a dam, as does the beaver, 
 or make use of a stone to crack a hard nut, as does the 
 American sapajou ape. Actions such as these are performed 
 to complete a harmony which the imagination craves, owing 
 to associations previously effected between groups of feel- 
 ings and emotions, and groups of groups of such. A cat 
 does not need to entertain any intellectual knowledge or 
 belief that the sound of clattering plates means possible 
 food, to attain which it must make certain movements. 
 Quite independently of such belief, and by virtue of mere 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 17 1 
 
 sensuous association, the sound of the plates alone is enough 
 to give rise to such movements on the part of the cat as 
 have previously become associated with pleasant sensations 
 of taste. Let certain sensations, emotions, and movements 
 become associated, and then the former need not be noted ; 
 they only need to exist for the association formed to produce 
 its effects. When the circumstances of any case differ from 
 those of some previous experiences, but imperfectly resemble 
 those of many past experiences, parts of these, and conse- 
 quent actions, are irregularly suggested by the laws of re- 
 semblance, until such action is hit on which relieves pain or 
 gives pleasure. For instance, let a dog be lost by its master 
 in a field in which it has never been before. The presence 
 of a group of feelings which we know to indicate its master 
 is associated with pleasure, while the absence of those feel- 
 ings gives pain. By past experience an association has been 
 formed between this feeling of pain and such movements 
 of the head as tend to recover some part of that group, its 
 recovery being again associated with movements which, de 
 facto, diminish the distance between the dog and its master. 
 The dog, therefore, pricks up its ears, raises its head, and 
 looks round. Its master is nowhere to be seen ; but at the 
 corner of the field there is visible a gate at the end of a lane, 
 which resembles a lane in which he has walked. An image 
 of that other lane and of its master walking there presents 
 itself to the imagination of the dog; it runs to the present 
 lane, but on getting into it he is not there. From the lane, 
 however, the dog can see a tree on the other side of which 
 he was accustomed to rest ; the same process is repeated, 
 but he is not found. Of course, throughout, the dog has 
 everywhere exercised its sense of smell but in vain. At 
 last it goes home. By the action of such feelings, imagi- 
 nations, and associations, which we know, by what takes 
 place in ourselves, do really exist and act as causes by 
 
172 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 these, all the apparently intelligent actions of animals can, 
 in our opinion, be explained without the need of calling in 
 the help of true intellect, the existence of which in them is 
 inconsistent with the phenomena they, as a whole, exhibit, 
 and which, did it exist, would most certainly make itself 
 very plainly manifest to us in many and often in very 
 unpleasant ways. 
 
 A stag which " doubles " on its own footsteps, when 
 hunted or before retiring to rest, has been credited, in the 
 former case, with seeking to confuse its trail against real 
 dogs, and in the latter case against imaginary hounds which 
 may possibly be on the scent. But there is not the slightest 
 need of such intellectual conceptions on the part of the stag 
 to account for such actions, which are clearly instinctive, like 
 the actions of the dog, which instinctively turns round and 
 round on a drawing-room hearth-rug before lying down, just 
 as if it were in its ancestral home in the greenwood where 
 herbs needed pressing down and treading round to make a 
 comfortable bed. . 
 
 Mr. Romanes cites ' an amusing tale from a Miss Bram- 
 ston about a certain archiepiscopal collie dog which had ac- 
 quired a habit of hunting imaginary pigs every evening 
 directly after family prayers. The fact is put forward as an 
 important instance of something beyond mere animal capac- 
 ity as commonly understood ; but, in truth, the fact is so 
 easily explicable by a mere association of sensations, that it 
 may well be cited as a type for other instances more or less 
 similar but not so easily explicable. It appears the animal 
 had formerly been accustomed to be sent to chase real pigs 
 out of a field, and so the sound of the word " pigs " and 
 the pleasurable action of running about after them had 
 become associated in the dog's imagination. It had been 
 the custom for Miss Branston to open the door for the collie 
 
 1 Op. ctf., p. 56. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 1/3 
 
 after dinner in the evening and say " Pigs! " when it very 
 naturally ran out and ran about according to its previously ac- 
 quired habit. Soon this exercise became in its turn a matter 
 of habit, and the phenomena attending the termination of 
 dinner, or, later, of family prayers, very naturally gave rise 
 in the collie to an expectant feeling (such as may arise with- 
 out consciousness in ourselves *) of the door being opened 
 for the accustomed pleasurable excitement. If the door 
 was not opened, the habit being now well established, the 
 expectant feeling, growing more and more vivid with delay, 
 could hardly fail to elicit barks, tail-waggings, and move- 
 ments towards the exceptionally unopened door, and the 
 accumulating excitement might very well lead it at last to 
 run out and bark without waiting for the utterance of the 
 word " pigs " ; nor is it in the least surprising to learn that 
 the phenomena attending family prayers at Miss Bramston's 
 house should arouse in the dog the same kind of expectant 
 feelings and the therewith associated actions, which had be- 
 come so engrained during its residence at the archbishop's. 
 We ought, perhaps, also to notice the oft-told tale about 
 crows which have been thought able to count. It appears 
 that somewhere beneath the nests shot at was a watch- 
 house, and by its aid the wary crow was, only after several 
 vain attempts, finally deceived. When about to shoot the 
 nests, in order to deceive the suspicious bird, the plan was 
 hit upon of sending two men to the watch, one of whom 
 passed on while the other remained. This stratagem was 
 without effect. The next day three went, but the bird 
 merely looked on while only two returned, and it was found 
 necessary to send five or six men to the watch-house before 
 her senses were sufficiently confused. But there was surely 
 nothing very wonderful in the fact that a crow, seeing a man 
 go beneath her nest with a gun, should keep clear till she 
 
 1 See ante, p. 150. 
 
1/4 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 saw him go away, even if he had hidden himself for a time. 
 What marvel was it, then, that the bird's sense-perception 
 felt a difference between the visual picture presented by a 
 group of three men and another presented by only two ? 
 The wonder rather is that the crow should not have been 
 more discriminative. 
 
 But obtuseness to numerical differences on the part of 
 highly organised animals, such as dogs and cats, seems to 
 us very wonderful, indeed absolutely to negative their 
 possession of any sensitive faculty which might run parallel 
 with our idea of number. Such is the case, since both 
 bitches and she-cats do not seem to miss a single pup or 
 kitten which may be taken away from the others in her litter 
 when they have not actually witnessed the act of its being 
 taken away. 
 
 But the fact which has been most relied on as a proof that 
 a mere animal can understand what " number " is, was the 
 fact that a chimpanzee known as Sally, and which lived a 
 long time at the Zoological Gardens, was in the habit of 
 picking up the exact number of straws she was told to pick 
 up by her keeper. She would pick up separately from the 
 ground, place in her mouth, and then present to him in one 
 bunch, two, three, four, five, and, we believe, ultimately, 
 ten straws, as she was told. She had distinctly associated 
 the several sounds of these numbers with corresponding 
 groups of picked-up straws. The ape would also, on com- 
 mand, pass a straw through a large or a small hole in the 
 fastening of its cage, or through a particular interspace of 
 its wire-netting. It would also put objects into its keeper's 
 pocket, play various odd tricks with boy visitors, howl 
 horribly when told to sing, and hold on its head pieces of 
 apple, remaining perfectly quiescent till some particular 
 word was said. This last trick, however, is one of the com- 
 monest performed by pet dogs, and the putting of objects 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 175 
 
 into the keeper's pocket was nothing remarkable. The 
 passing of a straw through a special aperture on command 
 would have been more so but for the fact that the basis of 
 the whole superstructure of such tricks was laid by the 
 animal itself having spontaneously taken to the trick of pick- 
 ing up a straw and passing it through a small hole near the 
 keyhole of the door of the cage possibly as a result of 
 having seen a key put in and out of the keyhole. Having 
 thus itself acquired a habit of picking up straws and passing 
 them through a hole, there could be little difficulty in get- 
 ting it to pass the straw through other holes, and not much 
 in getting it to pick up more straws than one. That it 
 should have associated certain motions with the sound of 
 certain words is no more than dogs, pigs, and various other 
 animals lower in the scale will accomplish. 
 
 There remains, then, as the single distinguishing peculiar- 
 ity of this case, the association in the ape's imagination and 
 consentience of the words one, two, three, four, five, or ten, 
 with the picking up, holding, and handing over a corre- 
 sponding number of straws. This fact of association is, so 
 far as we know, exceptional, and it is, therefore, very in- 
 teresting. But it does not prove that the animal has any 
 idea of these numbers not of course as numbers but as so 
 many separate things. 
 
 The idea of number implies comparison with a simultane- 
 ous recognition of both distinctness and similarity ; although, 
 of course, it is not necessary that the fact of our having such 
 apprehensions should be adverted to. No two things could 
 be known to be two without an apprehension that while they 
 are numerically distinct they can in some way be thought 
 of as belonging to one class of objects. We could not 
 reasonably say that four tons of coal and four o'clock are 
 " eight," or that Hamlet's idea of a future life and the At- 
 lantic cable are " two," unless we mean to speak of them as 
 
176 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 two of our thoughts; in which case they would be two 
 species of the genus " our ideas." 
 
 Sally was but one of many animals that had come to as- 
 sociate very complex bodily movements with articulate 
 sounds. The marvel of the matter is, in fact, due to a trick 
 our own imagination plays us. The keeper's words of com- 
 mand expressed and implied the highly abstract idea of 
 number, and as that idea and our sensuous impression of 
 such utterances have become closely connected, so we are 
 apt to picture to ourselves a like connection as existing in 
 the cognitive faculty of the ape. But its presence there is 
 by no means necessary to explain the action, while if such 
 a highly abstract idea was present there, the animal would 
 not allow us long to remain doubtful about such a fact. 
 
 We well recollect having specially questioned Sally's 
 keeper as to whether she ever pointed to any object or 
 made use of any gesture with the evident purpose of calling 
 attention to some fact or passing occurrence. 
 
 Although he was well disposed to extol the powers of his 
 charge so far as truth would permit, he distinctly assured us 
 that she did not do so. If anyone came in with a gun Sally 
 would show extreme terror, but she never pointed to it, or 
 by gesture called the keeper's attention to the dreaded ob- 
 ject. We were unable to see or hear anything which rend- 
 ered it possible to attribute to this very interesting animal a 
 psychical nature of a higher kind than that possessed by other 
 beasts. It appeared to us to have the same kind of powers 
 they possessed, though possibly somewhat higher in degree. 
 But this, surely, is just what we might have anticipated. 
 
 We may sum up the conclusions at which we have arrived 
 as follows : The minds of animals are analogous to ours, but 
 the analogy is expressed, as it were, on a lower plane. They 
 are astonished, but do not know it ; things recur to them 
 through their memory, but they know not that they have 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 1 77 
 
 recurred or that they remember. They recognise objects, 
 both natural and artificial, but they have no idea of them as 
 being either. A dog may fear another dog which is stronger 
 and fiercer, but it will have no idea of courage or fierceness. 
 Even insects will distinguish between differently coloured 
 objects the white from the blue, the red from the yellow 
 but no animal knows whiteness or blueness, and still less has 
 it any notion of " colour." Thus, the so-called " intelli- 
 gence, understanding, and knowledge " of animals are not 
 really true intelligence, understanding, and knowledge. 
 They are the sensuous groundwork of such intellectual 
 faculties. Since, also, they have no abstract ideas, they 
 cannot think " I." Yet, as we have said, though they have 
 not consciousness, they possess consentience, for we cannot 
 doubt that in them, as in us, sensitive influences of different 
 kinds are received into one common sensorium. A tiger 
 not only hears the plaintive cries of its victim, but at the 
 same time can see and feel its writhing limbs, and taste and 
 smell its blood. Such sensations also, no doubt, call up 
 within it more or less distinct reminiscences of similar feel- 
 ings previously experienced, and give rise to vivid emotions 
 and to appropriate actions. 
 
 But the irrationality of animals is shown by what, if they 
 were rational, would have to be called their exceeding 
 stupidity. Acts which would be reckoned as signs of ex- 
 treme obtuseness in us are common enough amongst animals 
 usually reckoned as the most intelligent. The fidelity of 
 dogs is proverbial, but in a sudden scuffle it is by no means 
 an unprecedented thing for a dog to fly at its own master. 
 
 Dogs have seen fuel put upon fires again and again, yet 
 what dog ever puts on any itself to maintain the heat it so 
 much enjoys ? Apes have been said sometimes to warm 
 themselves at deserted fires, yet no one asserts that they 
 have replenished them. It is quite wonderful they do not, 
 
THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 for such an act seems to come well within the scope of mere 
 sensuous faculties. Some readers may have had a pet cat 
 which has now and again got a piece of bone fixed between 
 its back teeth. The useless motions the animal, when so 
 circumstanced, will make with its paw are sufficiently irra- 
 tional; but although the accident may have occurred to it 
 several times, it will act in the same way again and again, 
 and will sometimes stupidly struggle against its master while 
 he removes the object which distresses it, and, as soon as it 
 is removed, the animal will go off licking its jaws without a 
 sign of gratitude for the relief afforded. 
 
 Swallows will continue to build on a house which they can 
 see is being pulled down, and flies will deposit their eggs on 
 a carrion plant instead of on real carrion. Even an elephant, 
 an animal often thought so extremely wise, has been known 
 to be so extremely stupid as to pull off the end of its trunk 
 (which had got caught in a cord) instead of calling for help 
 and waiting till its keeper came. 
 
 But in truth animals merit no such reproach, for, of 
 course, they cannot make use of faculties they do not 
 possess, while they make, as a rule, an admirable and ex- 
 cellent use of those non-intellectual faculties wherewith they 
 are actually endowed. 
 
 We venture to think that the facts and anecdotes we have 
 here considered are sufficient for our purpose; but certain 
 alleged cases of sign-making on the part of animals will be 
 noticed in our next chapter on science and language. 
 
 In the preceding chapter we cited various instances of the 
 high degree to which the faculty known as " instinct " may 
 be developed as so many physical facts. In the present 
 chapter we propose to deal with instinct as a feeling, and 
 consider the question as to what may be its true nature. 
 We have seen ' that it exists unmistakably in man, though 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 126, 127. 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 it is but very poorly developed in him compared with what 
 we find existing in many of the lower animals, notably 
 insects. 1 
 
 Of course we are unconscious of the performance of our 
 own instinctive actions, and the essence of instinct is that its 
 acts should be performed blindly. But by observation, re- 
 flection, and reasoning, we can be very sure that we have 
 performed that we must have performed certain instinct- 
 ive actions in early life. What ground, then, can there be 
 to suppose that such instinctive actions of animals as we 
 have hereinbefore described, are accompanied by anything 
 more than feelings such as unconsciously exist in the human 
 infant ? 
 
 Montaigne sought to explain instinct by intelligence, but 
 it is surely obvious that the acts of chicks newly hatched, 
 or of young snakes, who from their mother's womb have 
 been untimely ripped, cannot be due to intelligent purpose. 
 It is impossible to suppose that any form of knowledge 
 guides the actions of the emperor moth, the excavations of 
 the grub of the stag-beetle in proportion to its jaws which 
 are yet to be, or the actions of the beetle sitaris. Intelli- 
 gence, therefore, is a quite unsatisfactory explanation of the 
 nature of the instinctive faculty. Not less unreasonable is 
 Condillac's hypothesis that instinct is the result of the ex- 
 perience of the individual animal which exhibits it. It is 
 manifest that experience could never lead a creature to per- 
 form acts with reference to conditions quite different from 
 all those it has ever had any experience of. Yet such are 
 the acts of the insects before described, and the human in- 
 fant is certainly not less destitute of experience. 
 
 Another explanation was offered by Lamarck, who de- 
 clared instinct to be " habit which has become hereditary." 
 Of course, this implies, as all Lamarckism necessarily im- 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 128-130. 
 
180 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 plies, that acquired habits may become hereditary; but 
 granted, for argument's sake, that such is the case, there 
 remains a radical difference between instinct and habit. 
 " Habit " enables an agent to repeat with facility and pre- 
 cision an act which has been done before; but " instinct " 
 determines with precision the first performance of the act. 
 
 It is impossible to believe that any of the progenitors of 
 an infant acquired a habit of sucking, or that the insects 
 before referred to acquired a habit of performing their 
 purposive actions unless they were compelled by their 
 organisation so to do, in which case they would already 
 be instinctive. 
 
 But an attempt has also been made to explain instinctive 
 action as " lapsed intelligence " as consisting of acts which 
 were once performed with deliberate purpose, but which 
 are now carried on without advertence by unconscious auto- 
 matism. According to this view, instinctive actions would be 
 comparable with such actions as playing, without attention, 
 airs to learn to play which laborious, conscious atten- 
 tion was originally required. But here the same objections 
 apply as can be urged against Montaigne's hypothesis. It 
 may well be asked, could an adult female insect be supposed 
 to foresee the future needs of her first progeny, often so 
 totally different from her own wants ; or recollect her past 
 experiences as a chrysalis and as a grub, from the moment 
 she first quitted the egg ? Not less absurd would it be to 
 suppose that the grub of a male stag-beetle ever deliberately 
 reasoned out the need of making his chrysalis bed twice his 
 own size, on account of the jaws he is destined to grow, but 
 which he not only has not, but has never seen in adult in- 
 dividuals of his own species! 
 
 Lastly, the late Mr. Darwin has tried to explain instinct 
 as being partly due to intelligent, purposive action which 
 has become inherited, partly to the occurrence of accidental 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE l8l 
 
 variations of activity, which have been preserved by " na- 
 tural selection." 
 
 As to the former part of the explanation, the objections 
 we have already made to an intelligent origin of instinct 
 may, we think, suffice. Moreover, this explanation assumes 
 the truth of the proposition that acquired characters may be 
 inherited. As to the other part of the explanation, let us 
 look at one or two noteworthy instincts, and see if it is 
 credible that they should be due to accidental, haphazard 
 changes in habits already acquired. 
 
 Can we conceive that the duck which feigns an injured 
 wing that she may entice a dog away from her young brood, 
 can ever have come to do so by pure accident any more 
 than by deliberate intention ? Again, there is the case of 
 the wasp sphex, which stings spiders, caterpillars, and grass- 
 hoppers in the spots where their nervous ganglia respectively 
 lie, and so paralyses them. According to the doctrine of 
 " natural selection," either an ancestral wasp must have ac- 
 cidentally stung them each in the right place, and so the 
 sphex of to-day is the naturally selected descendant of a 
 line of ancestors which inherited this lucky, accidental 
 tendency to sting different insects differently, but always in 
 the right spots; or else the young of the ancestral sphex 
 originally fed on dead food, but the offspring of some indi- 
 viduals which happened to sting their prey so as to paralyse 
 but not kill them, were better nourished, and thus the habit 
 grew. 
 
 Finally, there is the curious instinct by which an animal, 
 when an enemy approaches, lies quite quiescent and appar- 
 ently helpless an action often spoken of as " shamming 
 death." The term is unfortunate, because the disposition 
 of the limbs adopted by insects which thus act is not the 
 same as that which their limbs assume when such insects are 
 really dead ; while some species are, when thus acting, less 
 
1 82 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 quiescent than others. The remarkable circumstance, how- 
 ever, is not that a helpless insect should assume a ppsture 
 approximating to that of its own dead, but that such a 
 creature, instead of trying to escape, should adopt a mode 
 of procedure utterly hopeless, unless the enemy's attention 
 be thereby effectually eluded. It is impossible that this in- 
 stinct could have been gained by minute steps, for if the 
 quiescence, whether absolutely complete or not, were not 
 sufficient at once to make the creature elude observation, its 
 destruction would be only the more fully insured by such 
 ineffectual quiescence. 
 
 We have hitherto spoken only of instinct as existing in 
 animals, and in certain human actions necessary for merely 
 organic life ; but there are a variety of human activities of a 
 much higher kind to which the term instinctive can hardly, 
 it would seem, be positively denied. Such a special higher 
 instinct is that which impels man to the external manifesta- 
 tion by voice or gesture of the mental abstractions which 
 his intellect spontaneously forms, but which does not exist 
 (as we shall see) in animals. The very first beginnings of 
 literature, art, science, and politics may also be considered 
 as activities to which men have been first urged by an im- 
 pulse analogous to instinct impulses which, on the whole 
 and broadly considered, have augmented the well-being and 
 happiness of mankind. 
 
 But " natural selection " is as impotent to explain man's 
 lowest psychical powers as is " lapsed intelligence." Can 
 it be for a moment seriously maintained that such infantine 
 actions as sucking, deglutition, defecation, or the actions 
 of adolescence tending towards reproduction, ever arose 
 through the accidental conservation of haphazard variations 
 of habit in remote ancestors ? If not, then it is impossible 
 to account for such actions without the recognition of in- 
 stinct as a distinct faculty, so comparable with reflex action 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 183 
 
 that it may be called, as we termed it in the last chapter, a 
 reflex 'action of the individual as a whole. At the very bot- 
 tom of the scale of animal life we find it present. Animals 
 utterly devoid of a nervous system, and consisting of little 
 more than minute particles of living jelly, will build up for 
 themselves an external armour symmetrical in form and 
 most artificial in construction. 
 
 " From the very same sandy bottom one series [of such minute 
 creatures] picks up the coarser quartz grains, cements them 
 together with phosphate of iron secreted from its own substance, 
 and thus constructs a flask-shaped test, having a short neck and 
 a single large orifice. Another picks up the finest grains and puts 
 them together with the same cement into perfectly spherical tests 
 of the most extraordinary finish, perforated with numerous small 
 pores at regular intervals. Another selects the minutest sand- 
 grains and the terminal portions of sponge spicules, and works 
 these up together, apparently with no cement at all, into perfect 
 spheres, each having a single fissured orifice." (Carpenter's 
 Mental Physiology ', p. 41.) 
 
 However far, then, we may put back the beginnings of 
 instinct, the question as to its origin ever returns, and in- 
 deed with increased importunity. How did the first sentient 
 creatures come to take and swallow their food ? How did 
 they first come to fecundate their ova or suitably to deposit 
 them ? How did they first effect such movements as might 
 be necessary for their respiratory processes ? Wherever 
 such phenomena first manifested themselves in sentient 
 organisms, we seem compelled therein to recognise the 
 manifest presence of instinct which may be called the 
 faculty provided by nature for bridging over the interval 
 which exists between the purely vegetative functions (nutri- 
 tion and reproduction) and the complex activities of sentient, 
 animal life. It is one of the most noteworthy of psychical 
 
1 84 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 powers, and its distinct and full recognition in all its bear- 
 ings will (as we shall see later on) be found to have an im- 
 portant bearing on problems of Epistemology. 
 
 The psychical antecedents of science, which we have 
 passed in review in the present chapter, consist of a number 
 of intellectual perceptions of facts and of relations between 
 facts, which enable us to understand the existence and 
 nature of psychical activities which do not rise into con- 
 sciousness. We have also been forced somewhat to antici- 
 pate matters and notice some of our higher psychical acts, 
 such as ethical conceptions, inferences, and reminiscences, 
 of which we are directly conscious, and which can only be 
 scrutinised by reflection with the aid of intellectual memory. 
 We have also (as before said) noted, as occurring in our- 
 selves, various acts of mere sense-perception, sensuous ideas 
 or imaginations, complexly associated with sensation and 
 sensuous memory, which may give occasion to sensuous in- 
 ference, with feelings of pleasure and pain, and also uncon- 
 scious co-ordinations of movements and feelings due to a 
 power of consentience our lower psychical powers. On 
 turning our attention to the world of mere animal life, we 
 saw reason to believe that the external manifestations made 
 by animals are susceptible of explanation by faculties re- 
 sembling our lower mental powers, without calling into play 
 the action of intellect and consciousness. 
 
 If we are correct in our estimate, then it must be admitted 
 that there is a distinction of kind between man and animals. 
 
 But we believe the question can only be decided by a 
 careful consideration of the true value and significance of 
 that obvious distinction between the lower creatures and 
 ourselves which is expressed by the proposition, " Men 
 speak, but animals are dumb." Have or have not mere 
 animals the power of expressing mental conceptions by 
 sounds or gestures ? 
 
THE PSYCHICAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 185 
 
 This, which we regard as the crucial question of a distinc- 
 tion of kind between man and animals, demands separate 
 and somewhat lengthy consideration, and to it the next 
 chapter will be devoted. 
 
CHAPTER VII 
 
 LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 
 
 IT has been already pointed out in the first chapter of this 
 book 1 that the simplest sentence cannot be rationally 
 uttered without giving expression (for the most part quite 
 unconsciously) to highly abstract ideas. In the last chapter 2 
 we also noted that there are at least three distinct categories 
 of " signs " the merely accidental, the emotional, and true 
 signs formally intended to serve as such, as also that all of 
 such signs may be either vocal or consist of some bodily 
 movements or gestures. 
 
 Signs which are merely accidental or emotional have now, 
 for our present purpose, to be carefully distinguished from 
 signs made with a rational purpose, and, therefore, neces- 
 sarily embodying abstract ideas. These merely accidental 
 and emotional signs gestures and cries often produce 
 sympathetic effects on those that see or hear them, who 
 may be thereby excited to make similar gestures and cries, 
 all expressive of excited feelings, on which account such 
 signs may be said to constitute a language of emotion. 
 
 These unintellectual manifestations may be divided into 
 three kinds or forms of emotional language. 
 
 They may consist of (i) inarticulate sounds only; such as 
 shouts and cries of pain or joy or surprise ; chuckles of satis- 
 faction or contempt ; murmurs of affection, as of a mother 
 to her infant, etc. ; (2) articulate sounds, wherein the 
 
 1 See ante, p. 7. 2 See ante, pp. 150-151. 
 
 186 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE l8/ 
 
 syllables have no rational meaning. Amongst such must 
 be included phrases sometimes repeated by idiots, or the 
 verbal exclamations made without real meaning by rational 
 persons during strong excitement as an Italian may ex- 
 claim per Dio Bacco ! or any Englishman may invoke damage 
 to his own eyes and limbs or those of his neighbours ; and 
 (3) gestures, which do not express or answer to rational con- 
 ceptions, but are merely manifestations of feeling, as, e. g., 
 jumping, dancing about, throwing up the arms, tossing the 
 hands, waving a hat, etc., etc. 
 
 Very different from all these is the spoken language, com- 
 posed of articulate sounds, as used in ordinary vocal inter- 
 course. In order to see this distinction clearly, it may be 
 well to analyse a very simple sentence, such, e. g., as " That 
 horse is running away." 
 
 The word " that," as thus used, has no signification in 
 and by itself, none without reference to the term " horse," 
 which it qualifies, dividing and separating off the particular 
 horse referred to from all others, and so limiting and deter- 
 mining the application of the universal abstract term ' ' horse' ' 
 to a single concrete example, for the word " that " conveys 
 the idea of an absolutely individual unity a unity which 
 cannot be present anywhere else except in the one concrete 
 entity referred to by it. 
 
 The word " horse," on the other hand, is a conventional 
 spoken, or written, sign of the idea " horse," and is a uni- 
 versal l abstract term, applicable, over and above the par- 
 ticular horse which is running away, to every other actual or 
 possible animal of the kind thus denominated. It denotes 
 no single subsisting thing, but a " kind " or whole class of 
 things a unity which can be present in many concrete in- 
 dividuals many horses besides the particular one referred 
 to in the sentence. 
 
 1 See ante, p. 6. 
 
1 88 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 The word " is " denotes the most wonderful, important, 
 and most abstract of all ideas the idea of " existence " or 
 " being." It is an idea which we must have in order to 
 perform any intellectual act. It is an idea which, though 
 not itself at first adverted to, makes all other ideas intelligible 
 to us, as light, though itself unseen, renders everything else 
 visible to us. But we shall return to the question of the 
 significance of the word " is," and, later on, justify fully 
 what is here said. 
 
 The term " running away " is one which denotes another 
 abstract idea namely, an abstract " quality " or " state " 
 of some object. The idea is one evidently applicable to 
 many things, such as all mice, dogs, lizards to anything, 
 in fact, which can " run away." Yet the idea itself "is one 
 single idea. 
 
 What is true of the simple sentence thus analysed is true 
 of all sentences. Thus the truth is plain of what we before 
 said about a savage, for all human language except the 
 emotional signs before distinguished necessarily implies 
 and gives expression to a number of abstract ideas. There- 
 fore, wherever language exists there the power of abstraction 
 must exist also. Therefore, again, thought is essentially 
 anterior to speech, and the latter is its consequence. It 
 may exist where the faculty of speech is wanting, and may 
 be expressed by gestures, which are also often made use of 
 by those who can speak, to convey a knowledge of their 
 thoughts and meaning to others. Similarly, inarticulate 
 sounds may also be made use of for the last-mentioned 
 purpose. 
 
 In addition, then, to the three forms of merely emotional 
 language before enumerated, there are three forms of intel- 
 lectual language, as follows : 
 
 (i) Sounds which are rational but not articulate, such as 
 the inarticulate ejaculations by which we sometimes express 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 189 
 
 assent to, or dissent from, given propositions. Such in- 
 articulate sounds are intellectual, because they depend on 
 the propositions referred to having been understood, and 
 are used to show that such is the case and what is the nature 
 of the judgment which may have been formed about them. 
 
 (2) Sounds which are both rational and articulate, such as 
 are used in conversation, and which constitute speech or 
 vocal language proper. 
 
 (3) Gestures which give external expression to internal 
 rational conceptions, and therefore are " external," though 
 not ' ' oral, ' ' manifestations of abstract thought. One special 
 manual expression of such abstract thought is writing or 
 the making of any pictorial signs. 
 
 Thus the essence of language as ordinarily understood 
 language used for the communication of ideas is an intel- 
 lectual activity. This is necessarily mental, and the root of 
 speech is therefore the " mental word," or verbum mentale. 
 The natural result or consequence of this is the external 
 expression, or speech the " spoken word," or verbum oris. 
 This is the normal consequence, but it can be replaced by 
 gesture or bodily expression to verbum corporis sed non oris. 
 
 It is evident that a man may be dumb and yet possess the 
 mental word, though he is accidentally hindered from giving 
 it expression by the spoken word ; but he can still do so by 
 gestures or writing the verbum corporis as long as he is 
 not paralysed. Should he become so, he would be deprived 
 of all means of external expression, while he might, never- 
 theless, still be in possession of the verbum mentale. 
 
 Now we believe that all the external signs of which mere 
 animals are capable are explicable as forms of the lower of 
 the two categories of human language the language of 
 emotion. We are also convinced that many forms of ex- 
 ternal expression, of which human beings incapable of 
 speech are reduced to make use, are fully and truly as in- 
 
190 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 tellectual as is the articulate language ordinarily used and 
 intended to convey ideas. To this question of the distinc- 
 tion between emotional and intellectual language, then, we 
 will now directly address ourselves. 
 
 It has been contended by some persons that there is no 
 essential difference between the language of men and that 
 of animals, and this contention has been based on two asser- 
 tions: (i) that verbal expressions in us precede correspond- 
 ing conscious mental conceptions, and (2) that brutes by 
 sounds and gestures can express ideas and so actually con- 
 vey a knowledge of the facts to which their ideas relate. 
 
 -No one has advocated these views more zealously than 
 the late Professor Romanes, 1 who, as an exceptionally can- 
 did and careful writer, may well serve as the best type of 
 the school to which he belonged. 
 
 He brings forward many instances which he considers 
 justify his opinion. Thus he tells us of a wasp, which, on 
 finding a store of honey, returned to the nest, and in a short 
 time brought off a hundred other wasps. But surely there 
 is no need to suppose that here any intellectual communi- 
 cation had been made, but merely an instinctive com- 
 munication inducing an instinctive response. Unfortunately, 
 superior as Mr. Romanes was to most of the advocates of 
 animal rationality, some of the tales he allows himself to 
 quote plainly show how saturated with prejudice their nar- 
 rators must have been. Thus, respecting some South 
 American ants, Mr. Belt is quoted as saying: " I noticed a 
 sort of assembly of about a dozen individuals that appeared 
 to be in consultation. Suddenly one ant left the conclave, 
 and ran with great speed up the perpendicular face of the 
 cutting without stopping." Shortly " information was 
 communicated to the ants below, and a dense column rushed 
 up in search of prey." 
 
 1 In his book, entitled Mental Evolution in Man, before referred to. 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE IQI 
 
 We have quoted this passage as a typical example of 
 increasing unconscious exaggeration. A dozen ants in 
 proximity are first called " a sort of assembly." Now any 
 creatures which happen to come together in close proximity 
 may, in a certain vague sense, be said to assemble ; but the 
 word " assembly " implies more than that. This implica- 
 tion is further intensified by the declaration that the ants 
 " appeared to be in consultation," though no fact in addi- 
 tion to physical proximity is given as justifying such a 
 purely fanciful interpretation. Finally, the implication is 
 driven home by calling these physically approximated ants 
 " a conclave." If those who narrate things of this kind 
 would content themselves with accurately describing the 
 facts they witness, the gain would be great indeed. 
 
 Such an account has been given l by one careful observer, 
 Mr. G. Larden. He tells us of a small South American 
 species of ant which makes a large nest underground with a 
 network of paths converging to the nest. 
 
 " These paths," he says, " are of all lengths, from ten yards up 
 to one hundred yards. As a general rule, one may say that 
 streams of ants, carrying leaves, buds, flowers, seeds, and other 
 valuable odds and ends, are always moving towards the nest, while 
 empty-mouthed ants are meeting and passing them on their out- 
 ward journey to the foraging grounds." 
 
 He then tried the experiment of turning some of these laden 
 home-going carriers round, when they had nearly reached 
 home. 
 
 " The general conclusion I came to," he continues, " was that 
 these ants did not then understand in what direction the nest lay, 
 nor did they (as far as I could see) draw any conclusions from the 
 fact that they now met the stream of carriers with which they had 
 
 1 In Nature for May 29, 1890, p. 115. 
 
IQ2 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 previously been travelling. Thus, one ant carrying a (relatively) 
 huge burden I reversed in direction when already near the nest. 
 I then followed it for about eight yards (or about twenty minutes 
 of time as far as I can say) in its mistaken reversed course away 
 from the nest. Though it met and collided with quantities of 
 burdened ants, and was passed in the same direction as its own 
 by unburdened ants only, it did not seem to take the hint. Its 
 final return home was the result of accident, as far as I could tell 
 it having got up the right way round after a severe fall. . . . 
 I dug a hole in one of the paths on several occasions. The hole 
 was small, and it was easy, though not so convenient, to go round 
 by the side over the very short grass. Nevertheless, it required 
 the falling of very many ants into the hole, and the leaving of 
 quite a pile of leaves there, before the stream learned to pass 
 about one inch to one or the other side, and so to avoid the pit- 
 fall. Some ants even turned back ; and I left them carrying 
 their burdens back to the foraging grounds again." 
 
 This statement quite accords with some observations we 
 have ourselves made. 
 
 As to higher animals and the asserted use by them of 
 gesture language, Mr. Romanes cites l a case recorded by 
 James Forbes, F.R.S., of a male monkey, which was said 
 to have begged back the body of a female which had just 
 been shot: " The animal came to the door of the tent, and, 
 finding threats of no avail, began a lamentable moaning, 
 and by the most expressive gestures seemed to beg for the 
 dead body. It was given to him ; he took it sorrowfully in 
 his arms and bore it away to his expecting companions." 
 One would like to know what the gestures were. Nothing 
 less than the actions essentially like those used in our ballets 
 would justify their being called " most expressive." 
 
 A Captain Johnson is also cited as having seen a monkey 
 which he had wounded run down a tree towards him. He 
 
 1 Op. cit., p. 100. 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE IQ3 
 
 then " stopped suddenly, and coolly put his paw to the part 
 wounded covered with blood, and held it out for me to see." 
 Finally, Sir William Hoste is referred to as having re- 
 corded that 
 
 " one of his officers coming home after a long day's shooting, saw 
 a female monkey running along the rocks with her young one in 
 her arms. He immediately fired and the animal fell. On his 
 coming up she grasped her little one close to her breast, and with 
 her other hand pointed to the wound which the ball had made, 
 and which had entered above her breast. Dipping her finger in 
 the blood and holding it up, she seemed to reproach him with 
 having been the cause of her pain, and also that of the young 
 one, to which she frequently pointed." 
 
 Now, that these narratives repose on a basis of truth is 
 not to be doubted, neither is the perfect good faith of the 
 narrators to be suspected. That the mother ape hugged 
 her young one, that the wounded animals made gestures 
 due to anger, pain, terror, or distress, is not to be ques- 
 tioned. But it is only too evident that the kind-hearted 
 sportsmen read, in such movements, motives and meanings 
 due to their own fertile imaginations. Such mistaken in- 
 ferences are not to be wondered at on the part of military 
 men, who may well have been unskilled in scientific observa- 
 tion, and little read in either psychology or philosophy. 
 
 But a very curious tale is told by Mr. Romanes himself 
 with respect to an American monkey of his, which had 
 found out the way to unscrew the handle of that object 
 which is often so much too easily unscrewed, namely, a 
 hearth-brush. He delighted in screwing it on and off, and 
 soon began to unscrew all the unscrewable articles so as to 
 become a nuisance to the household. This showed that 
 the monkey, we are told, 1 had " discovered the mechanical 
 
 1 Op. tit., p. 61. 
 13 
 
IQ4 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 principle of the screw " an " intelligent recognition of a 
 principle discovered by the most unwearying perseverance 
 in the way of experiment "(!). But to do what this 
 monkey did, needed as little the " intelligent recognition of 
 a principle " as any white mouse needed such knowledge to 
 learn to make rotating objects go round, or as a canary, 
 which had learnt to pull up a small vessel of water suspended 
 by a thread, need apprehend " principles" of mechanics 
 and hydrostatics. We are also informed that the monkey, 
 " however often he was disappointed at the beginning [of 
 the screwing process], never was induced to try turning the 
 handle the other way; he always screwed from right to 
 left." This would seem to show (on Mr. Romanes's method 
 of interpretation) that the monkey had much greater intel- 
 ligence than is possessed by many human beings, who often 
 do try screwing the wrong way when their efforts to screw 
 the right way have not succeeded. 
 
 But it is yet further asserted that the animal, having dis- 
 covered this " mechanical principle, proceeded forthwith to 
 generalise " concerning the objects thus mischievously un- 
 screwed, screwed, and unscrewed again. We are gravely 
 assured, as to the separated parts, that the monkey " was 
 by no means careful always to replace them ' ' as if it was 
 ever careful so to do, and as if those which were replaced, 
 were replaced by a sort of quasi-ethical deliberate intention. 
 
 With respect to apes, we have always to be on our guard 
 against the deceptive effects of their tricks and ways, due to 
 the close resemblance which exists between their bodily 
 frame and our own. On this account, if two actions essen- 
 tially similar are done, one by a pig and the other by an ape, 
 the latter would necessarily appear in our eyes to be far 
 more of a " human " action. 
 
 This may, in fact, account for the curious overestimate 
 above cited of the action of the American monkey so fond 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE IQ5 
 
 of screws. But other instances are given still more open to 
 criticism. 
 
 The climax of absurdity, however, is attained in an anec- 
 dote of a talking bird, 1 which our esteem and regard for the 
 late Professor Romanes do not allow us here to more than 
 refer to. 
 
 The vast difference between the emotional gesture- 
 language of animals and the intellectual gestures of men is 
 apparent, while those of infants show that mental concep- 
 tions may precede verbal expressions. Colonel Mallery * 
 has remarked that 
 
 " the wishes and emotions of very young children are conveyed 
 in a small number of sounds, but in a great variety of gestures 
 and facial expressions. A child's gestures are intelligent long in 
 advance of speech, although very early and persistent attempts 
 are made to give it instruction in the latter, but none in the 
 former, from the time when it begins risu cognoscere matrem. It 
 learns .words only as they are taught, and learns them through 
 the medium of signs which are not expressly taught. Long 
 after familiarity with speech, it consults the gestures and facial 
 expressions of its parents and nurses, as if seeking thus to trans- 
 late and explain words. . . . The insane understand and 
 obey gestures when they have no knowledge whatever of words. 
 . . . Sufferers from aphasia continue to use appropriate gest- 
 ures." 
 
 The same authority also tells us that Indians from the 
 West, who have been brought into the Eastern States, 
 
 " have often succeeded in holding intercourse, by means of their 
 invention and application of principles in what may be called the 
 voiceless mother utterance, with white deaf-mutes, who surely 
 
 1 See op, cit., p. 190. 
 
 2 In his memoir on " Sign -language among the North American Indians," 
 First A nnual Report of the Bureau of Ethnology. Washington , 1 88 1 . 
 
196 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 have no semiotic code more nearly connected with that attributed 
 to the Indians than is derived from their common humanity. 
 They showed the greatest pleasure in meeting deaf-mutes, pre- 
 cisely as travellers in a foreign country are rejoiced to meet 
 persons speaking their language." 
 
 Mr. Romanes himself has given 1 a very interesting ac- 
 count of a conversation held between two Indians of differ- 
 ent races, and carried on exclusively by gestures, beginning 
 as follows : 
 
 4 Which of the north-eastern tribes is yours ? " 
 
 " Mountain river men." 
 
 '* How many days from mountain river ? " 
 
 " Moon new and full three times," etc. 
 
 A deaf-mute from Washington is said 3 to have related to 
 some Indians, that 
 
 " when he was a boy he went to a melon field, tapped several 
 melons, finding them to be green or unripe ; finally reaching a 
 good one, he took a knife, cut a slice and ate it. A man made 
 his appearance on horseback, entered the path on foot, found the 
 cut melon, and, detecting the thief, threw the melon towards him, 
 hitting him in the back, whereupon he ran away crying. The 
 man mounted, and rode off in the opposite direction." 
 
 Another story of the kind, also told in gesture-language 
 only, was much appreciated by the Indians, and completely 
 understood. 
 
 A truly wonderful amount of abstract thought was thus 
 expressed and apprehended by means of gesture only. And 
 there is no evidence that speech generated or facilitated 
 gesture, but rather the contrary, while it is very evident 
 amongst many peoples notably in the more southern part 
 of Europe how very much gesture aids and enforces the 
 
 1 Op. '/., p. 108. 2 Ibid., p. 112. 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE IQ/ 
 
 meaning of speech. No doubt speech has greatly, must 
 have greatly, aided the elaboration of ideas, and so enriched 
 the mental pabulum for gesture-language ; but it can have 
 had no tendency to develop gesture-language itself, but 
 rather the contrary, speech being so rapid and serviceable an 
 agent compared with gesture only. 
 
 Deaf-mutes possessing an extraordinary manual dexterity 
 in signifying their ideas, could never have inherited it from 
 speaking ancestors, while they may well be supposed to have 
 inherited the structure common to those ancestors as the 
 physical means of speech. The nervous conditions relating 
 to abundant gesticulation, on the other hand, must have 
 been going through a process of atrophy for ages during all 
 the many generations of these loquacious ancestors of such 
 deaf-mutes. The latter also seem to have a special construc- 
 tion of their own in their gesture sentences a mode of con- 
 struction which could never have been inherited from their 
 speaking forefathers. 
 
 This special and peculiar construction is stated ' by Mr. 
 Romanes to be uniform in different countries. The deaf- 
 mutes " do not say ' black horse,' but ' horse black ' ; not 
 ' bring a black hat/ but ' hat black bring'; not ' I am 
 hungry, give me bread,' but ' hungry me, bread give.' ' 
 But such modes of construction answer every practical pur- 
 pose, and are as distinctly intellectual as any others. 
 
 The innate intellectuality of, and voluntary purposive 
 expression of ideas by, gesture is made specially clear in 
 the following statement, 2 which also shows how the deaf and 
 dumb express first that idea which they are most anxious to 
 impress on those they address : 
 
 " If a boy had struck another boy, and the injured party came 
 to tell us, if he was desirous to acquaint us with the idea that a 
 
 1 Op. at., p. 114. * Ibid., p. 115. 
 
198 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 particular boy did it, he would point to the boy first. But if he 
 was anxious to draw attention to his own suffering rather than to 
 the person by whom it was caused, he would point to himself and 
 make the act of striking, and then point to the boy." 
 
 The celebrated Abbe" Sicard asked a deaf and dumb pupil, 
 " Who made God ? " The answer he received is very re- 
 markable from the highly abstract conception which it 
 showed was present in the pupil's mind. His answer was, 
 44 God made nothing," meaning thereby that nothing what- 
 ever made God i. e., that God was not made by anything, 
 but was self-subsisting. 
 
 The deaf and dumb express a conjunctive sentence by an 
 alternate contrast. Thus the sentence " I must love and 
 honour my teacher " would be expressed thus, " Teacher I 
 beat, deceive, scold, no! I love, honour, yes!" This is 
 logical enough in spite of being a roundabout mode of 
 expression. 
 
 Colonel Mallery's evidence is invaluable. His account 
 of such an enunciation of the parable of the prodigal son by 
 signs is an example of an extremely elaborated instance of 
 the use of gesture-language. It is as follows : 
 
 " Once man one, sons two. Son younger say, Father property 
 your divide : part my me give. Father so. Son each, part his 
 give. Days few after, son younger money all take, country far 
 go, money spend, wine drink, food nice eat. Money by-and-bye 
 gone all. Country everywhere food little. Son hungry very. 
 Go seek man any, me hire. Gentleman meet. Gentleman son 
 send field swine feed. Son swine husks eat, see self husks eat 
 want cannot husks him give nobody. Son thinks, say, father 
 my, servants many, bread enough, part give away can I none 
 starve, die. I decide : Father I go to, say I had, God disobey, 
 you disobey name my hereafter son no I unworthy. But 
 father servants call, command robe best bring, son put on, ring 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 199 
 
 finger put on, shoes feet put on, calf fat bring, kill. We all eat, 
 merry, why ? Son this formerly dead, now alive : formerly lost, 
 now found : rejoice." 
 
 Even that most abstract of all ideas, the idea of " being " 
 or " existence," can be expressed by deaf-mutes. Colonel 
 Mallery tells us that the sign they use to express this is 
 stretching the arms and hands forward, and then adding the 
 sign of affirmation." 
 
 The idea of " equality " they can also signify by extend- 
 ing the index fingers side by side asL when repeating the 
 expression in the Lord's Prayer, " As in heaven." We 
 see, then, how intellectual conceptions may be expressed, 
 and distinct statements as to fact made the copula remain- 
 ing latent and implicit by this wonderful language of 
 gesture. By its means the most lofty abstractions can be 
 both mentally entertained and externally expressed. Church 
 services for deaf congregations are carried out by gesture 
 only. 
 
 That born mutes, without any teaching, do sometimes 
 make vocal sounds more or less articulate is an unquestioned 
 fact, and though we will not assert, we certainly suspect, 
 the existence in man of an instinctive tendency to produce 
 such sounds and to signify meaning by gesture. When 
 once anyone has a meaning to convey, he must, if he can 
 succeed in conveying it, convey it by some visible, audible, 
 or tactile sign. The employment of any one means must 
 be due to an internal impulse. How else could the language 
 of gesture have arisen ? 
 
 Therefore, if there ever was such a thing as a human com- 
 munity entirely dumb, a natural and instinctive language of 
 gesture would, we are persuaded, be evolved by it. We are 
 thus persuaded, not only on a priori grounds, but also from 
 the evidence afforded by such extraordinary examples of de- 
 
200 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 fective existence as that of Laura Bridgman and the still 
 more striking case of Martha Obrecht. The former is a 
 well-known case of a girl who was blind as well as deaf, 
 and had become so afflicted when too young to have retained 
 any recollection of seeing or hearing. Yet she learned to 
 apprehend abstract relations and qualities, and to read and 
 write. 
 
 Martha Obrecht * was deaf, dumb, and blind, and was 
 confided to the care of the nuns at a convent at Larnay 
 (Poictiers) when eight yeafs old. Then, by intelligent and 
 patient instruction, she was enabled gradually to acquire 
 the power of apprehending and expressing intellectual con- 
 ceptions, and highly abstract and lofty ideas, with distinct 
 and clear moral and religious notions. She was also taught 
 not only to read but to write perfectly well. 
 
 When first received she was a living, almost inert, mass, 
 with no means of communicating with her fellow-creatures, 
 though she emitted cries and made certain movements in 
 response to impressions she received. The first thing was 
 to give her some means of communication, and this was 
 done by making her touch different objects, and then touch- 
 ing her in different ways appropriate to each object, so that 
 each mode of touching became a sign to her of that object. 
 Thus, when a piece of bread was given her, she was made, 
 as it were, to cut her left hand with her right. Very soon 
 when hungry she began to make that sign herself. When 
 she did anything wrong she was slightly pushed away, and 
 thus she soon learnt to push away from her things she did 
 not like ; and so little by little from one point to another her 
 intellectual development was slowly completed. 
 
 It may be, as it has been, objected to these facts, that they 
 show no more than the influence on an infant of a long line 
 
 1 See Apologie Scientijique, by Canon F. Duilhe de Saint-Projet, pp. 374-387. 
 Toulouse, 1885. 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 2OI 
 
 of ancestors all capable of speech. But, as we before re- 
 marked, there could have been no inherited nervous structure 
 and conditions specially related to gesture-language. Yet 
 it was exclusively by gesture-language that the latent intel- 
 ligence of Martha Obrecht was developed. 
 
 Thus thought is evidently the cause, and not the effect, 
 of language. 
 
 We have said that the idea of " being " or " existence " 
 can be expressed by gesture, and also that the copula is 
 habitually implied and latent in gesture-language. But its 
 existence is, of course, no less effectively real because it is 
 thus latent. In every gesture statement, as in every orally 
 expressed proposition, the predication of existence is most 
 important. Its importance has been disputed on the ground 
 that " merely to say a thing is, is to form the most barren 
 (least significant) judgment about it." Now, of course, it 
 is manifest that so to affirm is to give the minimum of in- 
 formation about any object; but though it tells us little as 
 regards extent of information, it yet tells us a truth of the 
 most profound and intensely important kind. The reader 
 will readily appreciate how much more important to him is 
 his " existence " than a variety of other properties with 
 which he would be much less unwilling to part. 
 
 Having, we trust, to our reader's satisfaction, shown the 
 essential rationality which may be possessed by deaf-mutes, 
 we will next point out what we regard as the essential, 
 though latent, intellectuality of infants. We contend that 
 evidence shows intellect to be potentially present, i. e. y that 
 the normal conditions being supplied, it will infallibly come 
 to show itself as actually present. On the other hand, no 
 evidence plainly indicates that it is potentially present in 
 brutes, and that changes of mere environment can make it 
 actual. We are, as we said before, perfectly willing to 
 recognise the intellectuality of animals as soon as we can 
 
202 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 obtain any evidence thereof. All evidence we have been 
 able to obtain, however, points, we think, the other way. 
 
 But Professor Romanes seemed extraordinarily blind to 
 the intellectuality of even his own children. Thus we read 1 
 that a daughter of his, aged rather more than eighteen 
 months, called first her brother, and then other children, 
 " ilda," and then whenever she came upon a representation 
 of a sheep with lambs, she would point to the sheep and 
 say mama ha, white of the lambs she would say ilda ba. 
 Nevertheless, he affirms that in her case formal predication 
 had not begun. On the other hand, we regard these utter- 
 ances of the child as distinctly intelligent predications. 
 
 Similarly, he denies that a child two years old, who says 
 dit ki (sister is crying) makes an intellectual assertion. But 
 in saying those two words the child really enunciates a true 
 judgment composed of two concepts and an implied copula. 
 If such were not the case, if the child did not consciously 
 perceive both his sister and her crying condition, the state- 
 ment would be mere meaningless babble. But, of course, 
 the child does not advert to such psychical facts and recog- 
 nise what it says with reflex consciousness. Such a mental 
 act is but rarely performed even by an adult. 
 
 But much simpler, merely monosyllabic, utterances may 
 be true implicit judgments. Thus when a child on seeing 
 a dog looks up at her nurse and, pointing, says " bow- 
 wow," or taking food exclaims " ot " (hot), or letting fall a 
 toy says " dow " (down), it may thereby express what is 
 truly a judgment in each case. For in what respect does 
 the utterance of the monosyllable " ot " differ from " dit 
 ki " ? It merely differs in the emission of two sounds in- 
 stead of one. " Ot " really means as much as do the two 
 sounds " dit ki " namely, that the child's food is hot. In 
 one case the meaning of a sentence is conveyed by two 
 1 Op, dt., p. 218. 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 203 
 
 i 
 
 articulate sounds, and in the other by the utterance of a 
 monosyllable. The latter mode is in no way inferior except 
 that it seems incapable of being adapted to express the com- 
 plex ideas of later life. But very frequently the monosyl- 
 labic mode is made use of by adults and fully understood. 
 Suppose some men are watching, at a distance, certain birds 
 indistinctly seen, and that they are trying to make out what 
 they really are. When one man, having made sure, cries 
 out "Grouse ! " it is as true and clear an expression of a judg- 
 ment as would be the four words, " Those birds are grouse." 
 If it were only possible to follow out that mode without the 
 danger of confusion, then the use of monosyllables to express 
 whole sentences, instead of being inferior, would be the very 
 highest ideal of language. This reflection brings us natur- 
 ally to the consideration of different forms of language and 
 its possible origin. But there is one form of language which 
 exists, abundantly in low as well as in higher races of man- 
 kind, and that is metaphorical language. But what is 
 metaphor, and what sort of being must that have been 
 which first employed it ? 
 
 Had not the intellect the power of apprehending, through 
 the senses, and expressing, by bodily signs, what is beyond 
 the reach of mere sense-perception, metaphor would not and 
 could not exist. Neither could it exist if thought was the 
 mere outcome of language, and followed it, instead of the 
 opposite. It is precisely because speech is too narrow for 
 thought, and because words are too few adequately to make 
 known the ideas of the mind, that metaphor exists. It is 
 interesting also to note that figurative, metaphorical lan- 
 guage is natural, and especially abundant amongst various 
 savage and semi-savage tribes. Few things would be more 
 unwise than to take the plainest and most material mean- 
 ings of primitive words as being necessarily their only 
 meanings. Figure or metaphor has been occasioned by 
 
2O4 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 poverty and sterility of visible and audible signs, but their 
 cause is the wealth and fruitfulness of thought. Probably 
 many primitive terms had double meanings from the first. 
 
 As Carlyle has said, " An unmetaphorical style you shall 
 seek in vain, for is not ypur very attention a stretching to ? " 
 The sensuous element in language is but a necessary conse- 
 quence of our animal nature, and the necessity of phantas- 
 mata of the imagination as supports to (as before said) even 
 our most abstract thoughts. It does not follow from this 
 that thought once was mere sensation, but, on the contrary, 
 it manifests the wonderful spontaneity of the human intel- 
 lect, whence, by the help of the " beggarly elements " sup- 
 plied by the senses, the loftiest concepts spontaneously 
 spring forth like Athene, armed with the sharp spear of 
 intellectual perception, and swathed in the ample mantle 
 of signs, woven of the warp of matter and the woof of 
 thought. 
 
 It is just this power of metaphor-making which most 
 plainly displays to us the intellect in its creative energy, 
 giving rise to new external expressions for freshly arising 
 internal perceptions. This power belongs to man alone, and 
 no one even pretends that any brute can evolve a metaphor. 
 
 It is ethical propositions especially which demonstrate to 
 us that a higher meaning must be latent in terms which to 
 some persons seem merely sensuous. For everyone must 
 admit either (i) that he does not really know what an ethical 
 proposition means, that he does not know the difference be- 
 tween right and wrong, or (2) that he recognises it as a dis- 
 tinction toto ccelo divergent from every other, and one which, 
 as before pointed out, 1 could have had none but an ethical 
 origin, and therefore could never have been evolved from 
 the sensuous life and perceptions of mere animals. 
 
 As folly or prejudice makes tales of animal intelligence so 
 
 1 See ante, p. 166. 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 2O$ 
 
 often quite untrustworthy, so also the statements as to the 
 mental defects of savages are hardly less so. Love of the 
 marvellous, credulity, exaggeration, and, above all, hasty 
 and inconclusive inferences, abound in both. Mr. Tylor, 
 who has devoted his life to the study of such things, has 
 again and again protested to this effect. 
 
 It has, for example, been objected against the intellectual 
 ability of the Society Islanders that they have separate 
 words for " dog's tail," " bird's tail," " sheep's tail," etc., 
 but no word for tail itself i. e., tail in general. But, really, 
 the experience of the use of that word by ourselves leads us 
 to consider the condition of these Islanders in this respect to 
 be no great misfortune. We have our word " tail " tail 
 in general and it is constantly made use of in a way which 
 is hopelessly misleading. To use the same term, as we do, 
 for what we call the " tails " of a peacock, a monkey, and 
 a lobster is, so far, to be in a worse plight than that asserted 
 of the Society Islander. 
 
 Much has been said about some savages being unable to 
 say " I." Thus Professor Sayce tells us that a Malay who 
 would mean " I " says ulun that is, " a man " in Lampong 
 and also that at least one other race expresses the idea " a 
 man in a similar manner. 
 
 But that is of not the slightest consequence as regards the 
 intellectuality of the speaker. Asa child will say " Charley 
 don't like it," meaning I do not like it," so if an adult 
 Englishman were to speak of himself as " this one here," 
 pointing to his breast, his meaning would be as clear as if 
 he articulated the sound " I." 
 
 It has been supposed that the Grebo two sounds " ni ne," 
 which may mean "I do it " or " you do not," according to 
 the context and gestures of the speaker, may be taken as 
 evidence of conscious speaking in the making. Yet we have 
 in our own language equivalent instances of the explication 
 
206 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 of sound by context or gesture. Thus the expression " my 
 work " may be shown to signify either " I do it " or " you 
 do not." A man may say " my work," pointing to the 
 product with a look showing lively satisfaction at being able 
 to boast himself as the performer of so remarkable a feat ; 
 or he may say " my work " while pointing to his own body, 
 with a look of indignation at the idea of anyone else pretend- 
 ing to have done it. 
 
 A few further examples of what have been deemed forms 
 of predication so low as to border on mere sensuous and 
 animal language, must here suffice. 
 
 We have been told by Mr. Romanes ' that if a Dyak 
 wants to say " Thy father is, or looks, old," he has, for want 
 of words, to put together such expressions as " father of 
 thee," " age of him." Also he says that if such a man 
 wants to say of another " He is wearing a white jacket," the 
 form of the statement would be "he with white with 
 jacket," or more tersely, " he jackety whitey." But this 
 does not in the least tell against the presence of distinct in- 
 tellectual meaning in the utterance of such phrases. They 
 may strike the imagination of some persons so as to call up 
 a smile, but in sober truth, as regards meaning (which is the 
 only important thing), the expression, " he jackety whitey," 
 is essentially as good as the expression, " The external upper 
 garment of that man is of the colour of the driven snow." 
 
 If in Fiji the response " I will " is expressed by the form 
 " will of me," that surely is sufficient. It would be easy 
 enough to parallel such rendering by means of examples 
 from English slang. 
 
 No doubt the parts of speech of English grammarians 
 may be, in their external form, inapplicable to the Polynes- 
 ian languages. But the fact, however interesting, has no 
 significance as regards the essentially abstract nature of the 
 1 Op. fit., p. 317. 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 2O/ 
 
 ideas conveyed. Our expression, " I will eat rice," may 
 require to be rendered, " The eating of me the rice; my 
 eating will be of the rice." But such expressions are quite 
 reasonable and logical. 
 
 If it can be pointed out of any object that it is here, or 
 there, or thus, or sitting, or standing, or waiting, there can 
 be no doubt whatever of the implication that it is that it 
 exists even though no special articular sound may be de- 
 voted to the explicit assertion that such is the case. And 
 how great is the significance of that small word " is " ! If 
 a brute could think " is," brute and man would indeed be 
 brothers. ' Is," as the copula of a judgment, implies the 
 mental separation and recombination of two terms that only 
 exist united in nature, and can therefore never have im- 
 pressed our sensitive faculty except as one thing. ;< Is," 
 again, considered as a substantive verb, as in the example, 
 ' This man is," contains in itself the application of the 
 copula of judgment to the most elementary of all abstrac- 
 tions " thing " or " something." Yet if a being has the 
 power of thinking " thing" or " something," it has the 
 power of transcending space and time by dividing or decom- 
 posing the phenomenally one ideally separating the in- 
 dividuality, or haecceity, of an object or idea from its 
 existence. This is an act done with reflex consciousness by 
 philosophers, but entirely without advertence by the im- 
 mense majority of mankind. Here is the point where 
 
 instinct " is entirely left behind and where reason has 
 begun. 
 
 We have now examined and reviewed the several asserted 
 cases here considered as giving the best clue to the real 
 nature of animal language. If we are right in deeming that 
 no evidence has been brought forward to show that brutes 
 can evolve and entertain abstract ideas, it is plain they can- 
 not possess intellectual language, since the presence of such 
 
2O8 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 mental abstraction is a sine qua non for its existence. No 
 doubt the songs and calls of birds have, in a sense, meanings 
 which are practically understood by their fellows. Some 
 dogs will make certain facts, e. g., the presence of a rat or a 
 thief, known to their masters, and may also indicate which 
 of the two it is by the kind of sound they make. Pointers 
 and setters, by their movements and the postures they 
 assume, will make known other facts, while parrots and 
 jackdaws can be taught to articulate whole sentences. All 
 this is very true, but it is nothing to the purpose, because it 
 does not surpass that lower emotional language which we 
 also possess. We have, we hope, sufficiently shown how 
 truly intellectual may be the language of gesture which 
 mutes can use. Could animals do likewise, could any of 
 them by gestures make us understand what the language of 
 pantomime used in certain ballets can very plainly signify, 
 there would be no need for them to utter sounds such 
 movements alone would be amply sufficient to demonstrate 
 to us their rationality. And they have ample bodily powers 
 so to do, especially the apes, which are so like us in struct- 
 ure. Their senses, also, are quite keen enough to give them 
 ideas about the things they sensuously perceive, were they 
 not destitute of some higher faculty such as enables us to 
 form intellectual conceptions. On the other hand, they 
 might do much more by sound and gesture than they do, 
 and yet neither possess nor express such conceptions. It is 
 quite conceivable that a parrot might learn to utter certain 
 words which, by teaching, he has come to associate with 
 something pleasant to follow, just as a dog who " begs " 
 has associated that felt gesture with the imagination of bis- 
 cuit which he has habitually received after begging. But 
 such actions and imaginations do not tend even to bridge 
 over the chasm which exists between intellectual speech and 
 the language of emotion. 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 2Og 
 
 Similarly, dogs or pigs, trained to select from a number 
 of cards with letters on them, those bearing the letters 
 CAKE, are animals very curiously and ingeniously trained ; 
 but their actions prove nothing more than that there has 
 been established in their imagination sensuous associations 
 similar to those which have been formed in the psychical 
 nature of any dog that " begs." 
 
 It now only remains to consider what may be said with 
 respect to the origin of human speech. In the absence of 
 all direct evidence only more or less plausible hypotheses 
 are possible. One thing, however, we regard as quite cer- 
 tain, and that is that thought, the verbum mentale, was 
 anterior to the verbum oris. The phenomena presented by 
 deaf-mutes are sufficient to show that abstract ideas can 
 exist without spoken words, and that oral terms are the con- 
 sequence of thought ordinary experience suffices to prove. 
 When, in the cultivation of any new science or art, newly 
 observed facts or newly devised processes give rise to new 
 conceptions, new terms are invented to give expression to 
 such conceptions. Thus new words arise as a consequent, 
 and not as an antecedent, of such intellectual action. New 
 terms are always fitted to fresh ideas, and not fresh ideas to 
 new terms. Whoever attentively follows the mental de- 
 velopment of a child, will see that in it also, notions are 
 formed spontaneously, and often give rise to new words of 
 the child's own coining. 
 
 The antecedence of thought is also shown by the wonder- 
 ful rapidity far exceeding the rapidity of speech with 
 which the mind may detect a fallacy in an argument. And 
 such detection is always due to some reason our mind per- 
 ceives to be fatal, it may be, to a long chain of reasoning. 
 A mere cry or gesture of negation may be the sign of intel- 
 lectual perceptions which would require more than one 
 sentence to express fully, but which are perceived too rapidly 
 
210 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 for even the mental repetition of the words of such sentences. 
 We have seen how deaf-mutes may spontaneously evolve 
 a gesture-language, through which they can convey ideas to 
 one another. Dr. W. W. Ireland has recorded 1 the case of 
 a boy who could not speak ordinary words, and yet had in- 
 vented a few of his own, to which he attached fixed mean- 
 ings. Thus he said ' ' weep-oo ' ' for night or black ; ' ' burly ' ' 
 for wood or for a carpenter; " tatteras " for soldiers, and so 
 on. An analogous case has come within our own experience, 
 and Dr. Bastian has described another, 2 which seems to show 
 that the faculty of rational speech is so potentially present 
 in us that it sometimes manifests itself spontaneously and 
 very unexpectedly. It appears that in 1877 he was con- 
 sulted concerning the health of a boy of twelve, occasionally 
 subject to fits. When five years old he had not spoken, but 
 before another year had passed, on the occasion of an acci- 
 dent happening to one of his favourite toys, he suddenly ex- 
 claimed, " What a pity! " which were his very first words. 
 He was then silent for a fortnight, but thereafter became 
 very talkative. A medical friend of ours was much alarmed 
 about his son (now an eminent medical man himself), be- 
 cause he was long unable to speak, though he showed 
 clearly by an elaborate language of gesture that he had 
 very distinct intellectual conceptions which, after a time, 
 he began to express vocally. The cases of Laura Bridgman 
 and Martha Obrecht have been already described. 3 
 
 Speech has, in many cases, been shown to be reducible to 
 a certain number of probably primitive terms called ' ' roots, ' ' 
 and a large number of these denote some kind of action or 
 movement. On this account the suggestion has been made 
 
 1 Idiocy and Imbecility, p. 276. Churchill, 1877. 
 
 2 The Brain as an Organ of Mind, p. 606. Kegan Paul, Trench and Co. 
 1880. 
 
 8 See ante, p. 200. 
 

 LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 211 
 
 that speech arose through a custom which grew up of emit- 
 ting peculiar sounds when performing certain actions, as 
 seamen and others often utter sounds in common when 
 working together. 
 
 But it is conceded by all that speech could not have'arisen 
 except by the utterance of sounds, the meaning of which 
 was understood both by those who uttered them and those 
 who heard them. Speech requires an apprehending intelli- 
 gence on the part of the hearer as well as on the part of the 
 speaker if it is to be more than a monologue. Without the 
 attainment of this mutual comprehension spoken language 
 could never have arisen. It is true, of course, that one man 
 performing some act in the presence of others would know 
 what he was about while the onlookers would know it also, 
 and thus a sound repeated by him while so acting might 
 generate a term to denote such action, which term would be 
 understood by him and by those who saw and heard him. 
 But for this it must have been necessary to have the mental 
 conception of what was being done, that is, an abstract idea. 
 If the man acting and the onlookers only uttered the sound 
 accidentally, without will and intention, and then repeated 
 it automatically, and not as a sign deliberately meant, such 
 sounds (articulate or not) could be no form of speech. It 
 is evident none of them could understand or apply it except 
 by first acquiring the idea or conception itself. Therefore 
 the doctrine, " Speech begot reason," cannot be maintained, 
 for speech cannot exist without the existence with it of that 
 intellectual activity of which it is the external expression. 
 As well might the concavities of a curved line be supposed 
 to exist without f its convexities, as the spoken word be sup- 
 posed to have arisen prior to the idea which it represents. 
 Experience shows us, as we have already observed, that it is 
 new thoughts which generate new words, and not the re- 
 verse. As the deaf-mutes teach us, rational conceptions 
 
212 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 can exist without words. The intellect is the common 
 root from which both thought and language (whether of 
 word or gesture) spring. 
 
 This radical distinction between sounds denoting abstract 
 ideas and sounds which are but the expression of emotional 
 feeling is the distinction between the language (whether of 
 speech or gesture) of men on the one hand and of animals 
 on the other. That we cannot imagine how so fundamental 
 a distinction arose should be no bar to our recognising its 
 existence as a fact. This break, or new departure, in the 
 order of nature is by no means an isolated one. There is an 
 absolute break between the living world and the world de- 
 void of life ; and though it is true that at some period life 
 for the first time appeared upon the surface of this planet, 
 whenever it did so appear, there must have been a breach 
 of continuity and a new departure, which is no whit less cer- 
 tain because we cannot imagine how it took place. We are 
 convinced there was another breach of continuity and a 
 fresh new departure when the first organisms appeared which 
 were capable of sensation. 
 
 That all the higher animals " feel " will not be disputed. 
 They give abundant evidence of sensitivity, and they 
 possess the special living substance nervous tissue which 
 we know is the organ of sensation in ourselves. But the 
 world of plants affords us no such evidence. The move- 
 ments of the leaves of some as notably of the sensitive 
 plant and of Venus's fly-trap might be thought so to do, 
 but they are explicable without sensitivity. That the 
 vegetable world is devoid of sensation is what should be ex- 
 pected, since plants are devoid of all trace of a nervous 
 system ; and it is a universally admitted biological law that 
 structure and function vary together. If, then, there are 
 any organisms whatever which do not feel, while certain 
 other organisms do feel, then (as a gate must be shut or not 
 
LANGUAGE AND SCIENCE 21$ 
 
 shut) there is and must be a break and distinction between 
 the one and the other. 
 
 But it may be objected : " The transition is so gradual, it 
 is impossible to draw a hard and fast line between sentient 
 and insentient organisms." Even if this assertion be true, 
 such an objection would be of no avail, because an appar- 
 ently continuous and uninterrupted course of action is often 
 not really such, but only seems to be so on account of our 
 organisation our very limited power of vision. 
 
 Let us suppose an action to take place at precisely such a 
 rate as to permit of our seeing its steps separated from each 
 other by just appreciable intervals; then we have but to 
 suppose the period needed for our nervous activity to be 
 slightly increased, and it would necessarily follow we could 
 no longer perceive the intervals, and the supposed action 
 would seem to be continuous. Next let us suppose that an 
 action, which is really interrupted, takes place so quickly 
 that we cannot perceive the intervals ; we have but to im- 
 agine our nervous activity accelerated to a sufficient degree 
 and the intervals would be plainly perceptible to us. 
 
 Absolute interruptions and new departures take place 
 every day in nature. Such, for example, take place at 
 every junction of the ultimate sexual elements in impregna- 
 tion and in the final separation of the embryo from the 
 parent at birth. 
 
 Because we cannot imagine the origin of an intellectual 
 nature or any other origin, no argument thence arises 
 against such breaches of continuity such new departures. 
 We cannot imagine them, simply because we cannot see, 
 feel, or in any way sensuously cognise them. We cannot 
 perceive them, as we cannot perceive the ultimate constitu- 
 tion of matter, because we have not been provided with the 
 organs necessary to minister to such perception. As Pro- 
 fessor Miers once remarked to us, we cannot perceive them 
 
214 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 any more than we can distinguish colours by listening, how- 
 ever attentively, with our ears. 
 
 But however impotent may be our imagination, our reason 
 assures us that wherever a distinction of kind exists, there 
 must also be a breach of continuity, and a new departure. 
 For a " nature " or a " kind of existence " does not admit 
 of augmentation or diminution of " greater " or " less " 
 it simply " is " or " is not," and there is no possibility of 
 any intermediate condition. 
 
 Seeing, then, that there is now existing an absolute differ- 
 ence between the non-living and the living, and between 
 non-sentient organisms and those endowed with sensitivity, 
 we may, on grounds of analogy, deem it antecedently prob- 
 able (what a study of the question seems to us to make 
 almost certain) that there is also a breach of continuity and 
 a new departure in passing from merely sentient creatures 
 to beings endowed with reason. 
 
 The distinction which exists between that lower form of 
 language, of which mere animals are capable, and by which 
 they express their feelings and emotions, and that external 
 manifestation (by words or gestures) of abstract ideas of 
 which man alone is capable, constitutes the strongest possible 
 argument for the existence of a difference of kind between 
 human reason and the cognitive faculties of brutes. A 
 recognition of the existence of this distinction of kind, then, 
 removes every cause for doubt and wonder that the intellect 
 of man should be capable of apprehending absolute truths 
 to which all the other inhabitants of this planet are blind, 
 and should dispose us to accept with readiness and without 
 distrust whatever our highest faculties declare to us to be 
 absolutely and necessarily true. 
 
CHAPTER VIII 
 
 INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 WE have now passed through our preliminary inquiries 
 respecting the objects, methods, and antecedents of 
 science. We have recognised that there is a real, external 
 world, the conditions, laws, and relations of which it is the 
 business of science to investigate, as it is also its business to 
 take note of the existence, laws, and relations of the investi- 
 gating human mind. We have seen what are the main 
 physical and psychical conditions necessary for the very 
 being of human knowledge, and what are those fundamental 
 psychical activities of which we must make use for even its 
 most trifling increase. 
 
 In our last two chapters we carefully distinguished be- 
 tween our lower and our higher mental powers, and it now 
 becomes our business to direct our whole attention to the 
 latter, as they are the only tools of which we can make use 
 in exploring the foundations of science and seeking to ob- 
 tain a satisfactory Epistemology. 
 
 But before we can advance one step further in our inquiry, 
 we must make sure that the ground beneath our feet is 
 perfectly solid and secure, so that there shall be no danger 
 of our falling into an abyss of intellectual nihilism, or a 
 quagmire of doubt and uncertainty. 
 
 We long ago ' remarked that we are all certain about 
 
 1 See ante, p. 97. 
 215 
 
2l6 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 many things, and that certainty is necessary for any real 
 scientific progress ; and later on l we noted, in an introduct- 
 ory manner, the absolute certainty which attends our reflex 
 consciousness. These remarks were necessary preliminaries 
 to some subsequent considerations which we then brought 
 forward. Now, however, the time has come for us to study 
 the question of certainty deliberately and as fully as we are 
 able, and to call the reader's attention to those considera- 
 tions which earlier (when speaking of reflex consciousness) 
 we said we would reserve for a future chapter. 
 
 In the first place, it is evident that we must be certain of 
 something, and that, do what we may, we cannot get rid of 
 our certainty. For if anyone were to affirm he was certain 
 of nothing, and that to no proposition could he give an 
 unhesitating and fully confident assent, he would thereby 
 contradict himself, for he would at the same time be affirm- 
 ing the certainty of his own disbelief in and denial of 
 certainty. 
 
 To avoid this charge of self-contradiction, he might, per- 
 haps, go on to say: " Oh! I do not affirm that there is no 
 certainty ; I am far from denying that there may be such a 
 thing; all I affirm is that I doubt everything, even whether 
 I have any conviction about certainty one way or the other. " 
 But by so objecting he does not cease to affirm certainty : 
 all the difference is that his certainty takes a different form 
 from that before attributed to him. Instead of asserting 
 the certainty of his denial of certainty, he would thereby 
 be affirming the certainty that his mind was in a state of 
 doubt. But that is a matter about which anyone may be as 
 certain as of any other fact of belief or conviction. 
 
 Concerning the present mental state in which anyone 
 knows himself to be whether it be a state of doubt or be- 
 lief, or a state of having a sensation of blue or of a sour 
 
 1 P. 138. 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 21 / 
 
 taste he has the most absolute certainty possible ; for it is 
 a fact concerning which Omnipotence itself is powerless to 
 deceive him. It may be, indeed, that his sensation of blue 
 is a merely subjective one, and the sourness he tastes may 
 be occasioned not by what he puts in his mouth, but by 
 some abnormal condition of his gustatory nerves or of his 
 brain. That, however, does not make it in the least the 
 less certain that he has the sensation he feels. The reality 
 of the fact of the feeling is in no way lessened by whatever 
 may have been the cause producing it. Similarly, he may 
 believe what is the merest delusion, e. g., that his legs are 
 made of glass, or may doubt what is most evident to his 
 senses, as that there is light when the sun is shining at 
 noonday. But none the less, his belief is his belief while 
 he has it, and so is his doubt, his doubt. Both are, and 
 can only be, to him just what they are while he is ex- 
 periencing them. As to this, he has the most absolute 
 certainty conceivable, that is, the certainty of both his direct 
 and his reflex consciousness. He can with full conscious- 
 ness direct his attention on his own mental state and say : 
 ;< I certainly have such a belief, or such a doubt." As to 
 this, if he thinks about it, no man can really doubt. But a 
 man, nevertheless, may not think of it, and not having real- 
 ised that he has a subjective, absolute certainty which no- 
 thing can even weaken, he may yet fall into an unreasonable 
 doubt as to his own mental faculties. Being fully aware 
 that he has in his life made many mistakes, and that most 
 men also frequently make them, it is conceivable he might 
 say to himself, " As my faculties have deceived me in 
 something, may they not deceive me in everything ? What 
 guarantee have I that they are not always fallacious ? I 
 cannot get outside myself and compare my convictions with 
 external realities ; therefore I have no satisfactory evidence 
 of their truth, and so I really know nothing, and am intel- 
 
2l8 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 lectually, as it were, entirely at sea, drifting I know not 
 where or how. The idea that I can be really certain about 
 anything is for me an absurdity. What can I ascertain 
 about the cause and origin of the faculties I possess ? For 
 all I can tell, I may be the sport of a demon who amuses 
 himself with deceiving me in all things! " 
 
 But to such a man we would say, Why do you feel this 
 distrust of your faculties ? It is evident that your want of 
 certainty about them can only be due to your certainty 
 about something else. 
 
 You are convinced that you cannot surely arrive at truth 
 because your faculties may be deceptive ; but on what is this 
 conviction of yours founded ? Why cannot you trust them 
 all the same ? It is, and must be, owing to your perception 
 that no one can arrive at conclusions which are themselves 
 certain by means of premisses which are false, or even uncer- 
 tain. Now, in this perception of yours you are evidently 
 quite right, but please observe that you cannot have the 
 conviction you say you have about it except by trusting 
 your faculties after all. Therefore, if you are convinced, as 
 you say you are, about this impossibility of attaining con- 
 clusions which are certain from false or uncertain premisses, 
 you must be convinced that your faculties are not always 
 fallacious, and you must also perceive that your imaginary 
 demon cannot deceive you in everything. 
 
 Therefore, doubt as we may, certainty is the inalienable 
 possession of even the most absolute sceptic, who, when he 
 says he is certain of nothing even of his own scepticism 
 simply contradicts himself, and says what is mere nonsense. 
 
 At the outset of this our most important inquiry, namely, 
 the study of our highest faculties, it is necessary for the 
 reader thus to see clearly that certainty exists, and that he 
 not only can but must possess it about some things, or else 
 pay the penalty of drifting into imbecility and mental im- 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 2I 9 
 
 potence. He would, indeed, be compelled to affirm the 
 certainty of uncertainty, and so to contradict himself, and 
 to deny the truth of the system he at the same time up- 
 holds. Such a position is so unspeakably foolish a one, 
 that it cannot be understood and seriously maintained by 
 any sane mind. 
 
 From this fact it is well to note that an important con- 
 sequence follows: no proposition, no argument, and no sys- 
 tem of thought, which logically and necessarily results in 
 such absolute scepticism, can be valid ; and every system, 
 argument, and proposition which carries with it such con- 
 sequences, can thus be shown to be false by a process of 
 reductio ad absurdum. 
 
 Unquestionably, then, certainty exists; but the recogni- 
 tion of this truth constitutes but a very small step on the 
 road to an inquiry as to what propositions are most true, 
 and on what evidence do they depend ? 
 
 Now, our imaginary sceptic was shown to have based his 
 scepticism on the following process of reasoning on the 
 syllogism : 
 
 All conclusions resulting from 
 uncertain or false premisses 
 But the declarations of my 
 mental faculties 
 
 are untrustworthy. 
 
 . are conclusions resulting 
 from uncertain or false 
 premisses. 
 Therefore, the declarations of 
 
 my mental faculties . are untrustworthy. 
 He, therefore, must have been under the persuasion that 
 reasoning is the test of truth, and there are not a few persons 
 who are similarly minded and think that, in order to be ab- 
 solutely certain about anything, it must be capable of proof, 
 as also that to accept as true anything which is incapable of 
 proof, is to accept a conviction blindly. 
 
22O THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 Of course it is common enough and reasonable enough to 
 ask for proof to be given with respect to any new or extra- 
 ordinary statement, and it is most reasonable not to assent 
 to any proposition which does not possess sufficient evidence. 
 
 It is also true that the greater part of our knowledge is 
 gained by us indirectly, by inference or testimony of some 
 kind. And thus it has come about that many persons (as 
 before said) have acquired, half-unconsciously, a persuasion 
 that to believe anything which cannot be proved is an act 
 of irrational credulity, and thus a tendency has arisen to 
 distrust any assertion for which no proof is offered. 
 
 But, as we before pointed out, 1 however long our pro- 
 cesses of proof may be, they must stop somewhere. We 
 cannot go on reasoning forever if anything is ever to be 
 proved. Therefore, every valid process of reasoning must 
 ultimately depend upon propositions which need no proof, 
 and are undemonstrable not " undemonstrable " because, 
 like matters which have been taken on trust, we can obtain 
 no evidence for them, but because they are so luminously 
 self-evident that they admit of no demonstration, nothing 
 else being so clearly and necessarily true as they are. We * 
 have, indeed, just said that it is most reasonable to demand 
 sufficient evidence for any proposition to which our assent is 
 demanded. But that evidence need not be external evi- 
 dence, and the evidence of those ultimate propositions which 
 need no proof is, and must be, internal evidence. They 
 carry with them their own evidence, and so are evident in 
 and by themselves. 
 
 Thus the reasoning of our supposed sceptic his syllogism 
 reposes on premisses which are accepted by him as true 
 the major very reasonably, though the minor, most mis- 
 takenly. 
 
 Either, therefore, we have no certainty as to anything a 
 
 1 See ante, p. 103. 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 221 
 
 position we have seen to be absurd and untenable or the 
 propositions upon which our certainty ultimately reposes 
 are such as are self-evident and need no proof. If, also, it 
 is reasonable to accept as true, statements which are shown 
 to be so by reasoning, it must be still more reasonable to ac- 
 cept propositions which are shown to be true in and by 
 themselves : which are evident to our intellect as necessarily 
 true, as is the statement that we have a feeling which at the 
 time we know by our consciousness we actually possess. 
 
 If any reader still has some feeling of dissatisfaction or 
 discomfort about the self-evidence of ultimate truths, we 
 would ask him to reconsider the reasoning of our supposed 
 absolute sceptic. We represented him as objecting that he 
 could obtain no external evidence as to the correspondence 
 of his internal convictions with external realities. 
 
 Let us then suppose that he could, by some unimaginable 
 miracle, get outside his present mental state and view his 
 convictions and the objects they were related to, from out- 
 side, so that he could compare them one with the other, and 
 obtain a higher kind of conviction in a secondary mental 
 state as to their correspondence. But how could he thereby 
 gain any better assurance as to the objective correspondence 
 of the convictions of his subjective secondary mental state 
 with respect to the objective realities of the comparisons he 
 had originally made ? For this he would need to go outside 
 himself again, and then again and yet again forever, with- 
 out ever attaining to any better grounded conviction than 
 the one wherewith he originally set forth. Sooner or later 
 he must accept self-evidence as sufficient (as we before 
 provisionally pointed out), 1 or he must fall into absolute 
 scepticism, which is a form of idiocy. What other or better 
 criterion, or ground of belief, could any ultimate truth pos- 
 sibly have ? Any criterion of an ultimate proposition must 
 
 1 See ante, p. 57. 
 
222 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 be contained either in that proposition itself, and so make 
 it luminously self-evident, or else in something external to 
 it. Now any external criterion, however complete and 
 perfect it may be, could only be appreciated by us through 
 our perception of it and our judgment about it. If a pro- 
 position suddenly appeared written upon a cloud, or on the 
 face of the full-moon, we could not on that account accept 
 it as certainly true till we had examined the evidences which 
 circumstances could possibly afford us. Our first impres- 
 sion, of course, would be that we were the victims of a 
 hallucination, and next, the question of the possibility and 
 probability of common hallucinations would have to be 
 taken into consideration. But, finally, and at last, if we 
 did accept the proposition as true, it would only be because 
 we perceived that our ultimate judgments about it were 
 self-evidently so. If the proposition so written were, " Two 
 added to two make five," we should not believe it to be 
 true any the more for its inexplicable appearance. By no 
 external criterion, then, neither by the absurd one just im- 
 agined, nor by any other, could we be furnished with better 
 evidence than we already possess. We could but have self- 
 evidence, after all, as our ultimate criterion. It will be 
 clearly seen, on reflection, that nothing external no com- 
 mon consent of mankind, common-sense, or any amount of 
 human testimony could ever take the place of an ultimate 
 criterion of knowledge, since some judgment of our own 
 mind must always decide for us with respect to the existence 
 and the value of such criteria. Self-evidence, then, is the 
 necessary and only criterion of truth. The principle of evi- 
 dence is one which is really ultimate, and must be accepted 
 under pain either of futile reasoning, or of complete intellect- 
 ual paralysis. It is, of course, necessarily incapable of demon- 
 stration or any kind of proof, since it depends on nothing 
 else. We all of us assume it as a criterion unconsciously, 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 22$ 
 
 and it is confidently acted on by everyone who reasons. 
 But when we ponder over the matter, we see that what we 
 have thus done spontaneously, through the natural activity 
 of our intellect, has been done most reasonably. Did we 
 not adopt it, we should not only be utterly unable to think 
 logically, but should be plunged into the most utter and 
 most absurd mental disorganisation. 
 
 On the other hand, by recognising that criterion for what 
 it must be, and is, we gain a secure foundation for our 
 knowledge, and are enabled to make progress in science. 
 Our mental condition is, by such recognition, transformed 
 from a hopeless chaos into an orderly cosmos. 
 
 It has now, we trust, been made sufficiently clear to the 
 attentive reader (what has been incidentally put forward in 
 earlier chapters) that his own mind that the mind of each 
 one of us already possesses absolute certainty about some 
 things, and that his intellect declares that things which are 
 clearly seen to be evident in and by themselves possess the 
 greatest certainty which it is possible for the human mind 
 to attain to, and that such certainty is abundant. 
 
 If one is so unfortunate as not to be able to see this 
 clearly, and not to be able to have a firm conviction that 
 there is such a thing as certainty, as also that many things 
 are actually and in fact certain, then he had better close 
 this volume and abstain from opening any other work on 
 science, contenting himself with simple matters, the toils 
 and pleasures of every-day life, without a thought beyond. 
 
 Having satisfied ourselves once for all that certainty 
 exists, and that the criterion of certainty is evidence, 
 whereof intrinsic self-evidence is the highest kind, our next 
 step should be an endeavour to ascertain what things are 
 most evident what things are supremely certain. 
 
 In our third chapter we contended that we have an intui- 
 tion of an external, independent world of extended things. 
 
224 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 This is equivalent to the affirmation that extended things 
 are self-evident, and that we do actually affirm them so to 
 be. Nevertheless, as we have before pointed out, 1 the self- 
 evidence and certainty of the existence of such an external 
 world do not attain to the very highest degree of certainty 
 and evidence. They have not this pre-eminence, because 
 we have to obtain their certainty through the ministry of 
 the senses, by the aid of which, together with reflection, we 
 recognise the action of external bodies upon us, and the 
 sensations they excite within us, through which (without 
 our at first attending to and recognising our sensations) such 
 bodies are made present to our minds so that we perceive 
 them. The fact that we gain this perception by so com- 
 plex a process (though, through it, we cognise objects 
 directly and not reflexly, or by inference), 2 makes us able 
 to entertain a sort of fictitious doubt about the nature of 
 our perceptions of external things, but for which all idealism 
 would be absolutely impossible. We may (because many 
 persons do) believe that our inevitable perception of the 
 world about us is either an inference or a delusion, even to 
 the extent of regarding ourselves as the one only cause of 
 everything we perceive that is to say, we may accept 
 solipsism. As our own body is, for our mind, one portion, 
 though a very peculiar portion, of the external world, 
 doubts which may be entertained about that world must 
 apply also to it. Moreover, what we perceive with the 
 greatest certainty about the external world is just that which 
 our senses do not and cannot show us. That secondary 
 qualities should be, objectively, very different from what we 
 subjectively feel them to be we can easily admit ; but that, 
 underlying them, there should .not be an unperceived and 
 imperceptible substance in each body, constituting it essen- 
 tially a " thing in itself," belies that intuition of extension 
 
 1 See ante, p. 46. 2 See ante, p. 62. 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 22$ 
 
 by which we know bodies to be the self-evident entities they 
 are, and thus and therefore it is that idealism is in conflict 
 with sound sense. 
 
 So with respect to the existence of our own bodies : the 
 supreme certainty we have about it is not merely what is 
 present in the feeling of the moment, but the cognition we 
 have of it is gained (as we shall shortly see) through our 
 faculty of memory together with the exercise of reflection. 
 
 Thus all that is most evidently and supremely certain for 
 us is not, as so commonly supposed, anything we experience 
 in sensation, nor anything we cognise in examining or ex- 
 perimenting with material things, but, on the contrary, 
 exclusively that which is immaterial, abstract, and mental. 
 
 The truth of whatever is true, and the evidence of what- 
 ever is evident, can be most perfectly known to us only by 
 thought and not sensation. Not observation, not experi- 
 ment, not sensitivity, but thought and thought only (as we 
 pointed out earlier), 1 is and must be our supreme, ultimate, 
 and absolute criterion. Our last appeal in all cases is and 
 must ever be to a perception an intuition of the intellect. 
 
 Nevertheless, a mental world of abstract intuitions and 
 nothing else could never supply us with a knowledge of 
 science, still less with a perception of the groundwork of 
 all science. Abstract intuitions furnish us with fundamental 
 principles, which are not only priceless in themselves, but 
 are also indispensable elements in all reasoning. But be- 
 sides such processes of reasoning and such fundamental 
 principles, science requires a knowledge of absolute facts. 
 Without such facts all our reasonings must remain, as it 
 were, in the air, and could never descend to earth and be- 
 come of practical utility to us. There are, therefore, three 
 categories of truths, the perception of all of which is indis- 
 pensably necessary for science. These are : (i) certain general 
 
 1 See ante, p. 14. 
 
 15 
 
226 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 principles ; (2) certain particular facts ; and (3) certain pro- 
 cesses of reasoning. 
 
 Without a knowledge of certain general principles we 
 could not argue; without a knowledge of certain facts all 
 our reasoning would merely concern abstract ideas ; and 
 without a reference to concrete reality, and without some 
 criterion of valid reasoning, we could never arrive at any 
 conclusion or discover and explicitly recognise implicit 
 truths, no inferences could be deduced, and no advance in 
 science could be consequently attained. 
 
 We will select from the category of particular facts one 
 which may serve as a solid foundation and starting-point 
 towards a pursuit of our object. 
 
 Let us suppose that certain definite observations and ex- 
 periments have been carried on such, e. g., as those which 
 were performed by the late M. Pasteur with a view to the 
 treatment of rabies. Now there is one supremely important 
 truth which is implied in our certainty as to the result of 
 any such experiment, whatever that result may be. Unless 
 we can be sure that it was we who both began the experi- 
 ment and also witnessed its conclusion that there had been 
 no change in our personality while experimenting such 
 conclusion could not be confidently relied on by us, as we 
 have before pointed out. 1 The most fundamental of all 
 facts for our purpose is the fact of our continous personal 
 existence. 
 
 Now, of course, no one is so mad as to deny that he 
 knows his existence at the moment he thinks about it. We 
 have already noticed the absolute certainty we have about 
 any feeling while we feel it; and as nothing can feel which 
 does not exist, the certainty about the existence of a feel- 
 ing makes no less certain the existence of him who feels it. 
 It is not this momentary knowledge of self-existence what 
 1 See ante, p. 101. 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 22/ 
 
 is known as the "empirical Ego "which is here in ques- 
 tion, but the existence of our being continuously, from hour 
 to hour, from day to day, from year to year, and from child- 
 hood till the present time. 
 
 Such a " continuous self," it has been again and again 
 affirmed by followers of Hume, cannot be known (i) with 
 supreme certainty, such as attends our certainty about our 
 possession of any present feeling we may have ; and (2) that 
 it cannot be certainly known because it cannot be known 
 absolutely and by itself, but always as some modification or 
 present state of consciousness. 
 
 But, in the first place, though we may be perfectly certain 
 about our possessing any present feeling, that certainty is 
 not in the feeling but in the conscious thought which recog- 
 nises the existence of the feeling. Secondly, not only is it 
 untrue that we cannot have supreme certainty about our 
 continuous existence, but the supremacy and certainty we 
 have of that is actually higher in degree than is our certainty 
 about our possessing any present state of feeling. 
 
 What we are conscious of when not directing our own 
 mind backwards upon its own experiences is a direct con- 
 sciousness of whatever we may be about what we may be 
 doing or feeling and whatever may be done to us what 
 we are doing or suffering. The focus of our consciousness 
 (the apex of the conscious wave) is not directed either upon 
 our own existence from moment to moment, or upon the 
 particular feeling or state of consciousness which we may 
 then have. We can, however, at almost any moment direct 
 it backwards and reflect upon either of these, and so attain 
 supreme certainty either about our continuous existence 
 from moment to moment, or upon the feeling or state of 
 consciousness then present with us. 
 
 Let the reader test this assertion by his own experience. 
 As, for example, let him examine what his mind is oc- 
 
228 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 cupied about while sitting and attentively reading these 
 pages. 
 
 He will find his mind is not occupied about the feelings 
 occasioned by his sitting in the chair which supports him, 
 or the book he holds in his hand, any more than it is oc- 
 cupied about his own continuous existence, but about the 
 contents of this book. Yet he can at will make himself 
 explicitly aware of either his feelings or his perception of 
 his own self-existence. After thus turning his mind back 
 upon itself he will then be able to say, either " I have the 
 feelings which attend holding and reading a book on the 
 Groundwork of Science," or he may say to himself, " It is 
 I who have these feelings." But, as before said, this is not 
 a natural, primary act, but an act of reflection that is, a 
 secondary act. No one, when he begins to think, adverts 
 either to his " present feelings " or to his " continuous per- 
 sonal existence." No one begins by perceiving his act of 
 perception a bit more than he begins by expressly adverting 
 to the fact that it is he himself who perceives it. 
 
 Only by reflecting on the direct spontaneous perception 
 of the mind is it that we can explicitly see (by such a second- 
 ary act) that our perceptions and feelings are perceptions 
 and feelings, or that it is truly we who perceive and feel. 
 When a man playing cricket is having his innings, he has all 
 the " perceptions " and " states of consciousness " which 
 attend the assumption of the fit postures for the reception 
 and striking of the ball, and for gaining such runs as his ad- 
 dress may make possible. He knows very well all the time 
 what he is about during his play. But he never directs his 
 mind upon " his states of consciousness," or " the persist- 
 ence of his being." What he directly regards is what he is 
 doing and what is being done to him the defence of his 
 wicket from the attack of the bowler. If he were to divert 
 his attention therefrom to either his own " perceptions " or 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 229 
 
 his " persistent existence," the result would certainly not 
 contribute to the success of the eleven whereof he was a 
 member. 
 
 But we said that when men do so reflect, the certainty 
 thus gained of a persistent existence is even higher in degree 
 than that of any present feeling, perception, or state of con- 
 sciousness. And in fact, it is the " self " which is the more 
 prominently given. For the " feeling " or " perception " 
 is perceived as our present " feeling " or " perception," and 
 cannot be cognised altogether apart from the " self." But 
 our " self-existence " can be cognised without our advert- 
 ence to any feeling which may accompany such cognition or 
 to any " perception " as such. 
 
 In all our ordinary perceptions, wherein there is but a 
 " direct " and no " reflex " cognition of either " self " as 
 " existing " or of our " perception " as being such, it is the 
 self again which is, as it were, nearer the surface of the 
 mind. For we are sure, at least in our own case, that a 
 more laborious mental act is needed to bring explicitly be- 
 fore the mind the " feelings " implicitly contained in any 
 perception, than to bring explicitly before the mind the 
 self-existence implicitly contained in any such perception, 
 as also that the existence of the self, as self, is more readily 
 recognised than the existence of a perception as a percep- 
 tion. 
 
 Men repeatedly and very quickly advert to the fact that 
 actions or sufferings are their own. They are generally 
 prompt to claim any merit there may be in the former, or 
 to cry out against the unmerited character of the latter. 
 They do not, however, by any means so repeatedly and 
 quickly advert to the fact that the feelings and perceptions 
 they experience are " existing feelings and perceptions." 
 
 We think, therefore, it is impossible to deny that to 
 assert we can know our " states of consciousness" more 
 
230 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 certainly, and directly than we can know the " continuously 
 existing self " which has them, is a most profound and 
 fundamental mistake. 
 
 We are at this moment writing : we feel the pen and the 
 motions of our hand and arm, and recognise that we have 
 such sensations, and that we perceive hand and arm, pen, 
 ink, and paper. But ordinarily, when writing, we no more 
 advert to such " perceptions " than we advert to our " per- 
 ceptions " when running up or down stairs. It is plain that 
 we do not so advert; for as surely as our attention is so 
 directed, our movements in writing become hampered in 
 the one case, and a stumble on the staircase ' is very likely to 
 occur in the second. Much less inconvenience ensues from 
 turning the mind inwards (while writing or running up or 
 down stairs), and recognising our existence, than from ad- 
 verting to our bodily movements while thus occupied. 
 Thus here, again, we may recognise the fact that of the two 
 certainties, the certainty of our own existence from moment 
 to moment is more easily attained than the certainty as to 
 what is the nature of the various feelings and perceptions 
 which may accompany the actions above referred to, or any 
 others. 
 
 But, as we have noted, it has been objected against the 
 possibility of our self-knowledge that we can never know 
 ourselves absolutely and unmodified, but only in some state 
 or under some relation. Now it is very true that we have 
 no intuition of our own psychical being in its essence, and 
 apart from any of its activities, passivities, and relations. 
 But then the same thing can be, and must be, said of every- 
 thing else we perceive. In fact, nothing we can in any way 
 perceive exists apart from everything else, or " absolutely " 
 as it is (in our opinion) very unreasonably termed. 
 
 Everything which exists, exists always in some state or 
 
 1 See ante, p. 117. 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 23! 
 
 condition, and stands in some definite relation to other 
 things. Small wonder, then, if we do not know things in a 
 way in which they never do and probably never can exist. 
 We can know nothing by itself, for the very good reason 
 that nothing exists " by itself." It is quite true that we 
 have never known our own existing being except in some 
 state ; but then we have never known anything else except 
 in the same manner. jOur knowledge of ourselves is, in this 
 respect, like our knowledge of anyone else. Many persons 
 knew, as we did, the late Professor Huxley, but no one ever 
 knew, or could possibly imagine, him except in some state 
 either standing or not standing, speaking or silent, etc. 
 But that did not in the least prevent them from knowing 
 him well, and the fact of his continuous existence for a 
 greater or less number of years. 
 
 To many of our readers this exposition of the certainty 
 we have concerning our own continuous existence may seem 
 superfluous. But just as we have been convinced that it 
 was necessary to make as evident as it was in our power 
 to do, the truth that certainty exists and what is its crite- 
 rion, so we are convinced it is necessary to do our best to 
 show that the first and most fundamental of all facts is the 
 fact of our continuous being. If doubts as to either of 
 these truths cannot be entirely expelled from the mind of 
 any inquirer, that mind must remain subject to a sort of in- 
 tellectual falling-sickness, rendering all steady progress in 
 what concerns science really hopeless, and a pursuit of 
 Epistemology utterly futile. The fact of self-existence 
 from day to day is the most fundamental and important 
 of all facts about which our minds can give us any informa- 
 tion not on its own account so much as on account of the 
 consequences which follow its distinct recognition, as we 
 shall clearly see when we come to speak of memory. 
 
 But before leaving this subject, we must notice one further 
 
232 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 objection against the possibility of our knowledge of our 
 own continuous and substantial being. 
 
 It has been said that the self of each instant, the self the 
 existence of which no one denies (the " empirical Ego "), 
 must, if we know our continuous substantial existence, be 
 identical with an underlying principle of unity, continuous 
 and enduring (the " pure Ego "). This, we are told, is im- 
 possible, because the Ego of each -instant is the feeling 
 " subject," while the underlying principle is an existence 
 is a thing thought about, and is an "object " of cognition. 
 But the " subjective " and " objective " are necessarily anti- 
 thetical, and therefore the " pure " and " empirical " Egos 
 must be separated from each other by the unfathomable 
 chasm which divides " subject " from " object." 
 
 Yet, as we have seen, the " pure Ego " can be perceived 
 in conjunction with its states, modifications, and relations, 
 and recognised as being the " Ego " which also recognises 
 that identity. 
 
 The fact is that our own being our Ego differs from 
 everything else whatever in that it can be, and is, both 
 " subject " and " object." It is, as we before noted, 1 in a 
 sense subject and object identified ; though more cognised as 
 especially the one or especially the other, according to the 
 direction taken by the mind at one or another moment. 
 
 We have but to turn our minds carefully inwards and ad- 
 vert to what our consciousness tells us in order to be able 
 clearly to see that the fact of our own substantial existence 
 is a truth which carries with it its own evidence, and is 
 absolutely certain in and by itself. 
 
 We say, "what consciousness tells us," but by that we do 
 not mean consciousness only of the present but also our 
 consciousness as to some of the past. For it is not a 
 momentary existence, but a substantial and continuous 
 
 1 See ante, p. 139. 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 233 
 
 existence, the certainty of which we have been affirming is 
 both so fundamental and supreme. 
 
 Our knowledge of our continuous existence carries with it 
 the conviction of the validity of o\ir faculty of memory. 1 It 
 is, of course, obvious that by asserting the validity of this 
 faculty we do not and cannot mean that our memory is 
 always to be trusted. For everyone knows, and generally 
 regrets, that there are things he is certain he once knew but 
 which he can no longer recollect. As age advances, the 
 recollection of the facts of the recent past becomes gradually 
 less, and there are many instances of exceptionally defective 
 memory, sometimes of a whole subject-matter, sometimes 
 of particular parts thereof. But all these exceptional phe- 
 nomena do not affect the assertion of the general trustwor- 
 thiness of memory the assertion that what most people 
 remember clearly and distinctly, and which they are certain 
 really was as they remember it, did in fact occur as they 
 remember it. Putting aside exceptional persons, in patho- 
 logical conditions, it is certain that everyone can recollect a 
 portion of his past experience either what has just occurred 
 or what happened at a somewhat earlier, or very much 
 earlier, date. 
 
 It is also obvious that the trustworthiness of memory is 
 implied in our knowledge of our own existence, since we 
 could never know either what our most recently experienced 
 feelings or our direct perceptions of the empirical Ego have 
 been save by the aid of memory. Therefore the certainty 
 we have as to the one or the other of these carries with it a 
 certainty that our memory can inform us truly as to the 
 past. 
 
 As we have before pointed out, in order that memory 
 should exist, it is necessary that whatever is remembered 
 should be recognised by him who remembers it as having 
 
 1 See ante, p. 100. 
 
234 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 occurred before, and without such recognition no recurrence 
 of a bygone mental image, however many times it should 
 occur, would be an act of memory. 
 
 But there are two forms of real memory. All our readers, 
 we are quite sure, have now and again tried to recall some- 
 thing they know they before knew and ought to recollect. 
 As memory is not truly a voluntary act, they can only turn 
 their minds in this or that direction, which they think may 
 possibly or probably lead them to it, till at last they have 
 thus succeeded, and have before their minds once more 
 the thought they wanted to regain. Such a mode of re- 
 appearance, due to a more or less prolonged effort of the 
 imagination directed in different directions by the will, is 
 distinguishable as recollection. 
 
 But very often an image of the past suddenly appears 
 in consciousness unsought unbidden and, it may be, its 
 reappearance is far from a welcome one. Such a spontane- 
 ous resurrection of past thoughts and images is distinguish- 
 able as reminiscence. 
 
 It is " recollection," the presence of which is implied in 
 our reflex knowledge of our own existence, because for that 
 we voluntarily turn the mind backwards on itself. We have 
 spoken of our knowledge of our existence " from moment 
 to moment," because we are not sure that it is possible ever 
 to know the present moment by a reflex act. It is true that 
 it is possible to look at a coloured object and say, " Now I 
 see red." In our own case, it seems to us that we can thus 
 be reflexly conscious of the present moment. Nevertheless, 
 we cannot be sure that in this we do not deceive ourselves. 
 For since we are a unity made up of material existence, 
 thought, and feeling; since the mind -cannot act in any way 
 without some concurrent action of the nervous system ; and 
 since no nervous action can take place without requiring a 
 certain time for its performance, it appears to us that the 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 reflex act which recognises " I am I," or " My feeling is 
 now being felt," must be one that occupies a portion of 
 time, however minute, and that therefore the existence, or 
 act, thus reflexly cognised, must be an existence or act of 
 the moment past. That our faculties, with our bodily 
 organisation, may fail to seize on this minute and moment- 
 ary state of succession, is no more wonderful than that an 
 iron bar, red-hot at one end, should, when very rapidly 
 twirled, give our eyes the impression of a circle of light. 
 
 But, however this matter may be, though mistakes of 
 various kinds are possible, we are none the less all of us cer- 
 tain as to some past events in our lives. It may be an event 
 of childhood ; it may be one when leaving school ; it may 
 be our marriage ; or it may be the last thing that those who 
 are now reading this did before they began to read it. As 
 to some portions of the past, memory gives us as much cer- 
 tainty as we can have with respect to some portions of the 
 present if we can have reflex knowledge of anything abso- 
 lutely present. 
 
 If we could not trust our faculty of memory, not only 
 would all history be impossible, but we could never order 
 our future conduct according to the lessons our experiences 
 of life ought, and are supposed, to give us. 
 
 But the veracity of the faculty of memory can never be 
 proved, and is, manifestly, a self-evident truth carrying with 
 it its own certainty. There can be no possible proof of it, 
 because we cannot argue at all unless we already trust it. 
 How could we ever reach the conclusion of a syllogism if we 
 could not trust our memory as to what the assertions of the 
 major and minor premisses were ? 
 
 Yet, marvellous to relate, an eminent physicist once de- 
 clared that we may trust our memory because we learn its 
 trustworthiness by experience ! Surely never was fallacy 
 more glaring! How could we ever gain experience at all 
 
236 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 unless we trusted our memory in gaining it ? What the 
 physicist said, in effect, amounted to this: " You may trust 
 your present memory because experience has confirmed it, 
 while you can only know that it has confirmed it by trusting 
 your present memory! " 
 
 But memory, as will be quickly pointed out, performs a 
 yet more wonderful office than any we have yet described. 
 
 In the beginning of this work ' we pointed out the great 
 distinction which exists between the " objective " and the 
 " subjective." 
 
 Every " feeling," " thought," " desire," " volition," or 
 other " state of consciousness " present to the mind of 
 whoever is the subject of it, is spoken of as being " subjec- 
 tive." It is a thing which pertains to the subject to the 
 mind which feels or thinks. The whole of such experiences, 
 taken together, constitute the subjective world, or the sphere 
 of subjectivity. 
 
 On the contrary, everything whatever which exists exter- 
 nally to our present consciousness or feelings is spoken of as 
 being " objective"; and all that is thus external to the 
 mind constitutes the objective world, and is the region of 
 objectivity. It is the world of real objects the world which 
 occasions thought or feeling as opposed to the subjective 
 modifications so occasioned. 
 
 Everything which is subjective pertains to the self or 
 Ego during the time in which that "self" is feeling or 
 thinking. 
 
 Everything which is objective is external to the self which 
 is feeling or thinking, so that all states, even of the " self " 
 or " Ego," which are anterior to the time when that self or 
 Ego feels, are also objective objects of thought, indeed, 
 but not the thought or feeling of the thinking subject not 
 subjective. 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 8, 9. 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 All thoughts and feelings are " objects " and objective 
 while they are being thought of or reflected upon, while the 
 acts of " thinking about " them or " reflecting on " them 
 are subjective. 
 
 It is generally recognised that there is no greater antithesis 
 than that which exists between the subject which thinks 
 and everything which may or can be an object of thought. 
 It is the great distinction between the " self " and the " not- 
 self." Every modern philosopher, beginning with Des- 
 cartes, has sought in vain to discover a bridge capable of 
 spanning that abyss. To avoid the difficulty the material- 
 ists have simply ignored the need of a bridge, and pretended 
 they were already on the other side, having effected the 
 transit by an act of blind credulity ; while the idealists, like 
 the philosophers of Laputa, have tried by elaborate calcula- 
 tions and manipulations of mere feelings to bring the other 
 side over to themselves. 
 
 Yet all the time nature has provided us with the simplest 
 and most practically useful of bridges in the mere existence 
 of that conscious memory which is involved in our perception 
 of our own substantial being. 
 
 That is the " yet more wonderful office" performed by 
 memory to which we recently made reference. It is the 
 bridge implanted in our own being between object and sub- 
 ject. It is memory which enables us to get intellectually 
 outside our present selves and our present feelings and sen- 
 sations, in a way no sane man can question. 
 
 For memory, inasmuch as it reveals to us part of our own 
 past, reveals to us what is " objective," and so actually in- 
 troduces us into the realm of objectivity, shows us more or 
 less of objective truth, and carries us (as we have before said) 
 into a real world beyond the range of our present feelings, 
 our sensations and sense-impresses. 
 
 The power which memory possesses of thus lifting us, as it 
 
238 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 were, out of our present selves and showing us facts which 
 otherwise we could never know, is certainly a most wonder- 
 ful power; and, if we only have certainty as to one of our 
 past experiences, even if that took place but a few hours 
 ago, one such certainty would alone be sufficient to prove 
 indisputably that we can and do, through the faculty of 
 memory, learn real objective truth and can be certain about 
 much more than mere " impressions " and " sense-im- 
 presses," more than "appearances " and "present feelings," 
 more than mere "phenomena" namely, about objective 
 reality. 
 
 Thus the fact that we can know with certainty our sub- 
 stantial, continued existence, and facts anterior to our 
 present feelings, is a truth fruitful indeed with far-reaching 
 consequences. 
 
 We have said that in the recognition, by a reflex act, of 
 our continued being, subject and object were, " in a sense," 
 identified. 
 
 We used the expression " in a sense " for a very definite 
 and important reason, for though in that recognition subject 
 and object are to a certain extent conjoined and so " identi- 
 fied," yet what memory vouches for remains truly " object- 
 ive "; our past states and experiences are distinct objects 
 of cognition. Nevertheless, the consciousness which recog- 
 nises them and affirms, through them, our own identity (all 
 through the changes and experiences we have undergone), 
 is no less completely and truly " subjective" -it is the 
 conscious act of the subject which cognises and witnesses its 
 own being and past experience. 
 
 Therefore, in this act, subject and object, in one sense, 
 keep the distinctness of their two natures, while, in another 
 sense, they become identified in a single act of reflex con- 
 scious cognition. 
 
 In this circumstance we have indeed a vast and profound 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 239 
 
 distinction between human nature and anything of which 
 the psychical being of mere animals has as yet, to our 
 knowledge, shown itself capable. No one pretends that 
 brutes possess this marvellous intuition, while it is and must 
 be present, however unrecognised, in any savage who has 
 but one recollection of anything he has done or has had 
 done to him. 
 
 It is thus alone that we can unite the past with the 
 present and say" I am." These two 'words have an im- 
 mense significance for anyone who will carefully ponder over 
 them. They signify that he who utters them intelligently 
 recognises certain past acts as his own acts, and that a con- 
 tinuous unity (himself) has persisted, essentially the same, 
 for a longer or shorter time and has had more or less varied 
 experiences. He who utters them also thereby indicates 
 that he has the power of knowing at least one objective 
 existence which his senses cannot perceive. 
 
 Such must be the case, because our senses can only feel 
 what is present to them ; they can never feel the past. The 
 very fact of our feeling anything shows, with certainty, that 
 something is actually present which occasions that feeling. 
 But it is clear to everyone that his intellect can, by the help 
 of memory, know with certainty something which is far from 
 being present here and now, namely, some event of his past 
 life. Similarly, he is thus able to perceive his own continu- 
 ous existence, which is most certainly a thing which cannot 
 be felt. Our body can, of course, be felt as often as we like, 
 in several ways at the same time, and as long as we choose 
 to feel it. Nevertheless, each time we feel it we can but 
 experience the present feeling, and without memory and 
 without reflex acts of the intellect, we cannot know that our 
 own body has, and has had, a continuous enduring exist- 
 ence. It can never be felt as" enduring," although by the 
 aid of repeated sensations it can be intellectually perceived to 
 
240 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 be enduring. But the intellect, aided by memory, can 
 know very well, by itself and directly, that it has an endur- 
 ing permanence, and that the thought of the day before 
 yesterday was its own thought. It can know this with a 
 degree of certainty which it is impossible to attain to as 
 regards any other fact. To doubt the continuous existence 
 of our body from day to day would be absurd indeed, 
 and a sure sign of lunacy; but to doubt the continuous 
 existence of the intellect, while illuminated by a clear 
 memory as to some of its past acts, known with certainty 
 to have been performed, would be infinitely still more 
 absurd. 
 
 This power of memory, however, is so wonderful, and the 
 consequences which follow the recognition of the work it 
 does are so profound, that it is in no way surprising its 
 value should have been underestimated. Yet, as we have 
 seen, its validity cannot be impugned without intellectual 
 suicide and falling into a fatuous system of universal scepti- 
 cism. The self-evident truth that our faculty of memory 
 is valid is one, the acceptance of which is absolutely neces- 
 sary for the pursuit of any inquiry, and for the full recogni- 
 tion of what is for us the most certain of all facts, namely, 
 the fact of our own existence. 
 
 We have now seen (i) that certainty does exist that 
 there is such a thing as certainty (2) that our own existence 
 is a most certain fact, and (3) is vouched for by our self- 
 evidently valid faculty of memory. 
 
 But facts alone, however certain and well-remembered, 
 cannot constitute science without the aid of some abstract 
 fundamental principles. We require a knowledge of some 
 principles which are self-evidently true ever and always. 
 Otherwise we could never arrive at certain truths with 
 respect to any matter of investigation or study. These 
 principles, also, must not merely be laws and conditions of 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 241 
 
 our own mind, but must be true of all objects open to our 
 ken. They must be true objectively as well as subjectively, 
 and must be laws of " things " no less than laws of 
 " thought." They must be seen to be necessarily true 
 everywhere and everywhen, quite independently of any or 
 of every mind. If such be the case, the same laws must 
 apply to the most common circumstances of every-day life 
 as well as to the highest matters of philosophy. They 
 must also be no mere blind mental processes, the result of 
 any faculty such as instinct, or be due to any kind of non- 
 rational impulse. Their influence must be seen in daily life, 
 in actions resulting from definite and certain intellectual 
 first principles and necessary and evident truths, to which 
 the competent philosopher can always trace them. This 
 does not mean they are evident as such principles and truths 
 to the mind of every man who uses them, but that their 
 truth is completely evident without reflection. In vain will 
 the village grocer try to persuade the farmer's wife that if 
 from sixteen ounces of tea two ounces be removed, the rest 
 is none the less equal to a pound. She will be quite sure 
 such is not the case, though she may be quite guiltless of 
 the knowledge of a single axiom. Similarly, if a labourer 
 has given the whole of his week's wages to his wife, he will 
 be quite sure no part of them is still in his pocket, though 
 he never heard a word about any first principles. The intel- 
 lectual light of such first principles illuminates the intellect 
 of every sane man, be he civilised or savage. Not, most 
 certainly, that savages and ignorant men can know such 
 principles as abstract truths. But those principles, none the 
 less, reveal themselves to the mind in the concrete facts of 
 every-day life as practical motives for judging and acting. 
 It is true we cannot explain how these truths became thus 
 practically apprehended in the objects and actions of our 
 constant experience, but we are and must be ignorant of 
 
 16 
 
242 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 14 how " anything, which is for us ultimate, is, whatever it 
 may be. The " that " must ever be final. The " how " 
 can never be so, for the answer to every " how " must be 
 a " that." 
 
 The first and most important of these principles is the 
 perception of the reality of existence that what we per- 
 ceive to exist evidently does in truth so exist. This is often 
 expressed by the formula, " A is A," a formula which to 
 some persons appears utterly trivial, but which, neverthe- 
 less, lies at the basis of all our knowledge, and is a funda- 
 mental certainty without which no science could even begin 
 to be. 
 
 Another principle is that known as " the excluded 
 middle," which affirms that any given thing must either be 
 or not be, closely allied with which is that great regulative 
 principle to which we have already adverted, 1 and which is 
 called "the principle of contradiction'' the principle, 
 namely, that nothing can, at one and the same time, both 
 be and not be. 
 
 Now it has been strangely objected against this law of the 
 universe, that it is but a law of grammar, or, at most, of 
 logic. It has been said * to be but " a verbal convention," 
 not possessing " objective validity." 
 
 But the objector might be (as, in fact, he was) asked 
 " whether, if he had lost an eye, he would still remain, after 
 that loss, in the same condition as he was in before ? " 
 
 If anyone does not see the objective impossibility of such 
 a thing in all places and at all times /'. e., if he does not 
 apprehend the application of the law of contradiction then 
 he either does not understand the question, or his mental 
 condition is pathological. 
 
 Men may pretend to doubt such principles, their own 
 
 1 See ante, p. 105. 
 
 * See Nature for Dec. 20, 1891, and Feb. u, 1892. 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 243 
 
 existence, or the objectivity of mathematical truths. But 
 their practice demonstrates their unfailing confidence in 
 them on each occasion as it arises as when cheated by 
 false accounts, personally injured, or busied with some 
 serious investigation. That nothing can simultaneously be 
 existent and non-existent does not at all depend on the 
 words employed to denote that truth, but is "a law of 
 things." It would not lose its validity and objective truth, 
 not only if there were no such things as " words " at all, 
 but it would not lose them if the whole human race came to 
 an end. The necessity and universality of this principle is 
 easily recognised. Thus if we think of what the condition 
 of things must have been a long while ago in the days of 
 Julius Caesar, or when palaeolithic implements were first 
 fashioned we shall see that the law of contradiction is as 
 sure and certain with respect to the past as it is with the 
 present. We do not " think," we actually " know " with 
 absolute certainty that had Julius Caesar been drowned off 
 the coast of Britain he could not also have been assassinated 
 in the Roman Senate House, as also that at the time when 
 some early palaeolithic man was in the act of fashioning a 
 flint implement, he had not then both his hands empty. 
 The same certainty exists as to the most distant regions. 
 We are quite sure that the moon's surface cannot be both 
 mountainous and also absolutely smooth, and that the spec- 
 trum of a fixed star which shows certain definite lines, can- 
 not at the same time be devoid of them. Such assertions 
 might well seem too superfluous and trivial did not men 
 who have written letters to the journal named Nature, make 
 it only too evident that they are sorely needed. 
 
 This first principle, this law, then, is one of those which 
 are at once both absolute and universally necessary, while 
 they are incapable of proof and carry with them their own 
 evidence. 
 
244 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 But it is possible that one or two of our readers may be 
 startled at those words which we have more than once used, 
 namely, " absolutely necessary " and " universal." They 
 may feel some vague doubt as to how this matter may be in 
 the Dog-star now, or how it may have been long ages before 
 our nebula was churned into worlds supposing the solar 
 system did so arise. We may be asked: " How is it pos- 
 sible for creatures such as men are, mere insects of a day, 
 inhabiting a floating atom in an obscure corner of the uni- 
 verse, to know that anything is, and must be, absolutely 
 true for all regions of space and the most distant abysses of 
 time ? " 
 
 Yet, in fact, we know much more even than this. How- 
 ever poor, feeble, and incomplete intellectually human 
 nature may be, it is nevertheless endowed with power to 
 see necessary limits to the action even of Omnipotence itself. 
 
 Let us suppose that our planet might have been the abode 
 of vegetable life only; its hills and dales and plains abound- 
 ing in forests in which the voice of no songster could be 
 heard or even the hum of insect life. Let us also suppose 
 that the world might have been devoid of dry land and 
 covered everywhere by an ocean, in the waters of which 
 animal life existed exclusively and abounded. However 
 possible we may suppose each of these conditions to have 
 been, it is manifest that no power, however omnipotent we 
 may believe it to be, could ever have made both of these 
 possible states of our globe simultaneously actual. Such 
 considerations as these may help to give confidence to any 
 of our readers who, from want of thought, may have been 
 disposed to doubt their powers of perception as to necessary 
 truths and truths of a lower order. It is necessary, indeed, 
 to be careful not to declare anything to be certain till it has 
 been seen to be clearly and indubitably true ; but it is no 
 less necessary that we should not shrink from declaring that 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 24$ 
 
 to be true, the certainty of which is evident to our minds, 
 however wonderful it is, and however inexplicable may be 
 the fact of our knowledge of it. We are able to explain 
 how it is we know many things, but how we know primary 
 and fundamental truths which are self-evident and neces- 
 sarily incapable of proof must ever remain for us entirely 
 inexplicable. Were they explicable they could not be 
 ultimate. 
 
 The feeling of distrust which some persons experience 
 when they are told they can know with absolute certainty 
 certain truths to be both universal and necessary, seems to 
 be due to a habit of mind which has been brought about by 
 an unconsciously formed association between ideas. Things 
 which are very remote in space or which happened ages ago 
 are generally known to us as results of elaborate mental 
 processes, and some uncertainty about them is by no means 
 uncommon. On the other hand, we often feel very con- 
 fident about matters the circumstances and conditions of 
 which are within easy reach of our powers of observation. 
 Thus we have come to associate a feeling of uncertainty 
 with respect to statements concerning things which are 
 very remote in either time or space. It is not, then, sur- 
 prising that a feeling of vague distrust should arise when 
 beginners in philosophy hear it affirmed that the law of 
 contradiction applies equally to whatever concerns the 
 Dog-star and our portion of the universe, myriads of ages 
 before the solar system had its first origin. 
 
 It is, as we have before said, very wonderful that we 
 should have this knowledge of necessary truths, but, as 
 before 1 pointed out, it is most wonderful that we should 
 know anything. 
 
 Yet if we deny or doubt " the law of contradiction " we 
 fall, as before said, into the most unutterable absurdity 
 
 1 See ante, p. 56. 
 
246 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 that of absolute scepticism, which shows, by a reductio ad 
 absurdum, that our denial, or doubt, was itself absurd, and 
 that we must admit that law's universal validity. 
 
 But, once more, it is no mere law of our own minds, no 
 affair of mere logic, since, if we are to accept as absolutely 
 true what our reason declares to be self-evident, it is a law 
 which applies to all things from physical phenomena to 
 mental states. Such we have seen to be the case with re- 
 spect to the various instances we have put forward as 
 examples. When we say that the number of balls in a 
 bag cannot at the same time be both " odd " and " even," 
 we are certain that this is not a truth due to our organ- 
 isation, but to the real necessary objective conditions of 
 existence of the balls themselves. Our reason declares 
 that the law of contradiction is no " form of thought " im- 
 posed on our intellect, but is a certain and inevitable law of 
 objective existence independent of our intellect. 
 
 To doubt this would be to destroy all certainty, since it is 
 a fundamental truth on which all reasoning depends. 
 
 If we could not be sure that the fact that " all men are 
 mortal " did not necessarily imply that none could live 
 forever, we could never infer the mortality of anyone as 
 a consequence of his humanity. Thus for anyone to 
 attempt such a task as that of "proving" the law of 
 contradiction would be, in the highest degree, absurd, 
 since he would be compelled already to assume its cer- 
 tainty at the very outset of his demonstration at the 
 very first assertion he made. 
 
 Our perception, therefore, of the necessary validity of the 
 law of contradiction, teaches us both an absolute verity with 
 respect to objective existences with respect to the matter 
 of all science as well as the existence of our own mental 
 perception thereof. 
 
 Another principle of universal application and self-evident 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 
 
 validity is the well-known axiom : " Things which are equal 
 to the same thing are equal to each other." 
 
 As with the law of contradiction, so with this axiom it 
 is practically known and constantly acted on in every-day 
 life without advertence to its axiomatic character, and even 
 without any knowledge of it as a recognised truth at all. 
 The familiar application of a yard measure to different ob- 
 jects is an amply sufficient demonstration that such is the 
 case. But the principle applies not only to the equality of 
 material things but to every kind of equality equality 
 of motion, illumination, and feeling and it is evidently a 
 principle of objective validity, and is a law of things no less 
 than of thought. 
 
 This axiom about equality, though it can be illustrated 
 by any number of instances, can never be proved by reason- 
 ing. It is a self-evident truth which reposes on its own evi- 
 dence as do the other axioms of mathematics. The same 
 may be said of the fundamental laws of mathematics and 
 geometry. 
 
 Yet a very curious argument against the objective validity 
 of our perceptions in such matters has been put forward by 
 persons no less distinguished than the late Professors Clif- 
 ford and Helmholtz. Their object in advancing it was to 
 show by an example how truths which appear necessary to 
 us are not objectively necessary. But the result of their 
 efforts was the direct contrary of what they intended. 
 Their intention evidently was to support the proposition, 
 " We can know no truths to be absolutely necessary," but 
 the result was to show that even according to them some 
 truths are (and were, even in their own eyes) absolutely ne- 
 cessary. The necessary truths they proposed to controvert 
 were : (i) " A straight line is the shortest one which can be 
 drawn between two points," and (2) " Two straight lines 
 cannot enclose a space." 
 
248 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 To prove their contention they imagined the existence of 
 curious living creatures possessed of length and breadth but 
 devoid of thickness, living on a sphere with the surface of 
 which their bodies coincided. They were supposed to have 
 experience of length and breadth in curves, but none of 
 height or depth, or of any straight lines. To such creatures, 
 it was said, our geometrical truths would not appear to be 
 " truths " at all. A straight line for them would not be the 
 shortest line between two points, while two parallel lines 
 prolonged would enclose a space. 
 
 But beings so extraordinarily defective might well be sup- 
 posed incapable of perceiving geometrical truths evident 
 enough to others less imperfect such as ourselves. Never- 
 theless, if they could at all conceive of the things we denote 
 by the terms " straight lines " and " parallel lines," then- 
 there is nothing to show that they could not also perceive 
 those same necessary truths concerning them which are 
 evident to us. 
 
 It is strange that the very men who brought forward this 
 fanciful objection actually showed, by the way they made 
 it, that they themselves perceive the necessary truths of 
 those very geometrical relations the necessity for which they 
 verbally denied. For how, otherwise, could they affirm 
 what would or would not be the necessary results attending 
 such imaginary conditions ? How could they confidently 
 declare what perceptions such conditions would certainly 
 produce, unless they were themselves convinced of the 
 validity of the laws regulating the experiences of such 
 beings ? Anyone who should affirm (as they did) that they 
 can perceive what would necessarily be the truth with re- 
 gard to the perceptions of such beings, would thereby im- 
 plicitly assert the existence of some necessary truths, or else 
 their own argument itself must fail as utterly futile. 
 
 There is one more general principle which, for the end we 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 249 
 
 have in view, we must endeavour to depict as fully as we 
 can, namely, the principle of causation. It is, however, so 
 important in our eyes that we will reserve its treatment for 
 the following chapter, and terminate the present one by pre- 
 senting to our readers the remarks we have yet to make 
 with respect to the process of reasoning. 
 
 The process of deduction, its validity, and the force of the 
 word " therefore," have been already referred to in our 
 fourth chapter, 1 but here they must be considered more 
 fully. 
 
 Of the many truths to a perception of which the human 
 mind has attained, a large proportion have been reached by 
 reasoning, and the reasoning process is, as we all know, one 
 so important even to the progress of science, that any at- 
 tempt to dispense with its use would be an endeavour fit 
 only for a lunatic. For an exploration of the groundwork 
 of science, a clear perception of the validity of the process 
 of reasoning is an indispensable antecedent. Of course, it 
 is in the first place necessary that all reasoning should be 
 strictly logical. Logic has two ends in view : one is to teach 
 us how to avoid certain errors, the commission of which 
 would vitiate all our reasoning; the other is the manifesta- 
 tion of truths which are involved in, and depend upon, the 
 recognition of other antecedent truths, from the truth of 
 which they necessarily follow as consequences. It is with 
 the latter end of logic we are here concerned, and we have 
 to make manifest the fact that the conclusion of any prop- 
 erly constructed syllogism, the premisses of which are true, 
 is a proposition which, as a consequence, is necessarily and 
 self-evidently true. 
 
 If it is really a fact that all female whales have mammary 
 glands, or organs for suckling their young, then if a particu- 
 lar animal just caught turns out to be a female whale, we 
 
 1 See ante, p. 103. 
 
250 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 may, in that case, most confidently expect to find it pro- 
 vided with such organs. 
 
 But many objections have been made to such syllogistic 
 reasoning on the ground that the conclusion is already con- 
 tained in the premisses. If " all men are mortal," such 
 objectors say, then those who know that, know that any 
 special man, such as Socrates, is mortal also, and, therefore, 
 the assertion that he is mortal can be nothing more than a 
 repetition of part of the major premiss. Here then, they 
 say, we have no true " inference " at all, but merely a re- 
 statement. We do not " conclude " that Socrates is mor- 
 tal, but only say over again, with the use of his name, what 
 was said before without the use of his name. 
 
 Now, of course, the mortality of Socrates, and the mam- 
 mary glands of the freshly caught female whale, were im- 
 plicitly included in what was previously known about " all 
 men " and " all female whales." Unless they were thus 
 " implicit," they could never be seen to follow as explicit 
 consequences in the conclusions of the respective syllogisms. 
 But the syllogism really does afford fresh knowledge to the 
 mind, and often very important knowledge, by making 
 truths explicit and manifest, so that they can be most clearly 
 recognised, which before were merely implicit, and so were 
 not necessarily obvious. 
 
 There is, indeed, a very great difference between implicit 
 and explicit knowledge. To cause a knowledge which we 
 only possess " implicitly " to become " explicitly " present 
 to our minds, may often be, in effect, to give us fresh 
 knowledge altogether practically to give us a knowledge 
 of something whereof we had before no available or conscious 
 knowledge at all. 
 
 Let us suppose that a youth has learned by heart the 
 characters which respectively distinguish the four classes of 
 backboned animals beasts, birds, reptiles, and fishes but 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 2$l 
 
 that he has seen and knows very little about specimens of 
 different kinds. It would be by no means wonderful if such 
 a youth should consider a porpoise to be a kind of fish. 
 But his teacher might remind hirn that all creatures possess- 
 ing certain characters of brain and heart were beasts. He 
 might thus come to see that the porpoise, which he took to 
 be a fish, must, since it has those characters, really be a 
 beast. 
 
 Referring again to the character of this class of beasts, he 
 might further exclaim, " This fish-like thing, when alive, 
 must, as being really a beast, have had warm blood." His 
 conclusion would have been a perfectly correct one, and in 
 this way his inferences would really have supplied him with 
 knowledge which he certainly did not possess before. 
 
 So great, indeed, is the difference between explicit and 
 implicit knowledge, that the latter may not deserve to be 
 called " knowledge " at all. Probably there is no opponent 
 or derider of the syllogism who will venture to affirm that a 
 student who has learned, and recollects, the axioms and 
 definitions of Euclid, can, by that fact alone, have obtained 
 such a real knowledge of all the geometrical truths the work 
 contains, that he will fully understand all its propositions 
 and theorems without having to study them. Yet all the 
 propositions, etc., of Euclid are implicitly contained in the 
 definitions and axioms. Nevertheless, in spite of that, 
 the student will have to study much and go through many 
 processes of inference, by which he may be enabled to 
 recognise these implicit truths explicitly, before he can truly 
 be said to have any real knowledge of them. 
 
 Of course, in the very rare instances in which the major 
 premiss expresses a truth which has been arrived at by an 
 examination of every instance referred to in it a " com- 
 plete induction " there is nothing implicit. 
 
 Thus, if we knew with absolute certainty that every man, 
 
252 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 woman, and child in some Indian village was a leper, then 
 to say that a man came from that village would be equi- 
 valent to saying explicitly that he was a leper. In such a 
 case there would be no evolution of implicit into explicit 
 truth there would be no process of inference, and the word 
 44 therefore " would, if used, be quite out of place. 
 
 Such cases are, however, most rare. No one can pretend 
 to know by a complete induction that all the radii of a circle 
 are equal. It is absolutely impossible to examine all exist- 
 ing circles; besides, the assertion that all the radii of a circle 
 are equal applies not only to all existing, but also to all 
 possible, circles. 
 
 Similarly, if we are shown a triangular figure and are 
 asked, "Are its angles equal to two right angles ? " we may 
 not be able at once to answer the question by directly in- 
 specting the figure. If, however, we already know that 
 the angles of every triangle are together equal to two right 
 angles, then we should be able at once to infer the truth, 
 and to say that in so far as the figure approximated to an 
 ideally perfect triangle, would its three angles approximate 
 to two absolutely perfect right angles. We should arrive at 
 this truth mediately, and reach the conclusion by the com- 
 bined help of a major and minor premiss. 
 
 A very great part of the knowledge we acquire through- 
 out our whole lives is acquired, in this indirect way, by the 
 help of that mental process which is expressed by the word 
 " therefore." 
 
 But we have no special reason to be proud of that word, 
 since it implies that we are compelled to get at truth by a 
 very roundabout process. Were our intellect of a much 
 higher order, 1 it is conceivable that we might be able to 
 see equally well, and at one and the same time, all those 
 truths which a proposition may contain implicitly as well as 
 
 1 See ante, p. 102. 
 
INTELLECTUAL ANTECEDENTS OF SCIENCE 253 
 
 explicitly. In that case, of course, we should be saved the 
 trouble of any process of inference. The truths we now 
 have to gather indirectly, would then be directly evidentjo 
 us, just as our own actual mental activity is evident to us. 
 Only having, however, the imperfect nature we possess, we 
 must .be content with the more laborious, though practically 
 sufficient, process of inference or ratiocination. We must 
 be content to gain actual knowledge from implicit truth by 
 placing propositions side by side, and so evolving explicit 
 truth as a consequence of that process properly performed. 
 
 Reasoning, then, is an indirect process of attaining truths, 
 and one which, when properly carried out, is necessarily and 
 self-evidently true. It is not, however, the highest kind of 
 act our intellect is capable of. Its highest possible act is 
 the direct apprehension, or intellectual intuition, of a uni- 
 versal and necessary truth or of a concrete fact as absolutely 
 certain and self-evident. 
 
 Just, however, as certainty, self-perception, the principle 
 of contradiction, and axiomatic truths, may be perceived 
 directly with reflex advertence to each, so also correct 
 reasoning can be carried on, and the force of the term 
 " therefore " (as the expression of a truth which is a con- 
 sequent from truths antecedently known) appreciated, with- 
 out any reflex consciousness of ratiocination as a process, 
 and a process performed by us. 
 
 It is, of all things, important to note and keep in mind 
 the truth, that " thought " as we know and experience it, 
 is our only means of arriving at knowledge, and gives the 
 highest certainty thereto. It is evidently necessary to state 
 this very distinctly, since there are men who profess to be 
 philosophers and yet ignore or deny this truth. To sup- 
 pose that by any kind of reasoning we can come to under- 
 stand what we can never think, may seem an utterly 
 incredible folly ; yet at a meeting of a metaphysical society 
 
254 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 in London, a speaker, a few years ago, expressly declared 
 " thought " to be a misleading term, the use of which 
 should be avoided. 
 
 " Thoughts " may be, and should be, carefully examined 
 and criticised ; but however much we may do so, and what- 
 ever the results we may arrive at, such results can, mani- 
 festly, only be reached by thoughts and must be expressed 
 by the aid of our thoughts. 
 
 We are far indeed from denying that unconscious activities 
 of various orders take place in our being; yet, whatever in- 
 fluence such activities may have, they cannot affect our 
 judgments save by and in thoughts. Even if a man should 
 become convinced that his thoughts were worthless tools, 
 he could only arrive at that conclusion by making use of the 
 very tools he declared to be worthless. What, then, ought 
 his conclusion to be worth even in his own eyes ? 
 
 We can never justify reason, because we must employ 
 reason in criticising and seeking to justify it, and so work in 
 a circle. Not to trust our reason before we have justified 
 it, is to be, as Hegel said, like the prudent GxoTtaGTiHoz 
 who would not enter the water till he had first learned to 
 swim. 
 
 It is simply impossible by reason to get behind conscious 
 thought, and our thoughts are, and must be, our only means 
 of investigating problems however fundamental. 
 
 Yet some persons appear to believe that our convictions 
 even as to self-evident truths may be invalidated on ac- 
 count of the causes which have, or may have, been at work 
 in eliciting them. This question forces us to consider the 
 principle of causation, its nature and effects, in this relation 
 amongst others. To that consideration, then, the next 
 chapter will be devoted. 
 
CHAPTER IX 
 CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 
 
 IN the introductory chapter to the present work we ob- 
 served how constant was the desire of ordinary men to 
 know the " how " and " why " of things to know the 
 causes and circumstances of events. To know this is, as 
 before said, above all, the aim and object of science, and to 
 the successful man of science the old adage eminently ap- 
 plies: " Felix qui potuit rerum cognoscere causas." But not 
 only the devotee of science, but every man on every day of 
 his life, experiences what he regards as the effects of causes, 
 and deems that he produces effects himself. Whatever 
 may have brought it about, it is plain that notions of causes 
 as really acting, and of effects which are produced by them, 
 have somehow become embedded in the mind of man and 
 are ready to start up and manifest themselves at any mo- 
 ment. Indeed, so strong is the notion of the necessity of 
 causation, to account for all we see about us, often felt to be, 
 that it has given rise to the assertion, so often made, that 
 " everything must have a cause." 
 
 Yet such a dictum is quite untenable, and would lead us 
 to a regressus ad infinitum, since, should our reasonings and 
 our intuitions convince us there must be a first cause, we 
 should have then to postulate another cause for that first 
 cause's existence, and so on without end. 
 
 But if we examine our own minds as to the nature of our 
 
 255 
 
256 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 conception of cause, and especially what seems to call it 
 forth, we shall find that it stands in close relation to our 
 perception and idea of " change." 
 
 When some change occurs, or when anything strikes us 
 as being a new thing, we spontaneously look out to see 
 what has brought it about what is its cause. And very 
 often our investigation is quite satisfactorily repaid. We 
 find what the cause was, and that we can by experiment 
 again produce the effect whenever we will. 
 
 Think over the matter as we may, when we perceive a 
 change, or that a new existence has come into being, we 
 are at once certain that some cause must have produced it. 
 If we have gone out of doors, leaving our library window 
 open, and on our return find it shut, we are at once abso- 
 lutely certain that some person or thing must have shut it. 
 If an infant begins to cry violently without any external 
 cause, we are sure that it has experienced some painful 
 feeling, produced through some internal modification. If 
 we find in a bird-cage which has long been shut up and 
 tenantless, a living thrush, the notes of which have attracted 
 our attention, we are at once as certain as it is possible to 
 be that, if it did not find its way in itself, someone must 
 have placed there this, for us, new existence. 
 
 This mental conviction of ours is no negative one, such, 
 e. g., as that " we cannot conceive such changes or new 
 existences without a cause," but that we positively do see 
 " that every change or new existence is, and must be, due to 
 some cause. ' ' 
 
 This proposition, indeed, expresses an intellectual intui- 
 tion which is for us a necessary and universal truth, and one 
 self-evident. As such, of course, it is quite incapable of 
 proof ; but a little pondering over it will, we think, make its 
 self-evidence quite clear, and show that it is no blind habit 
 of mind " due to custom," as Hume said (as if the origin 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 
 
 of any idea could be explained by such a notion !), but is one 
 seen to be necessarily true. 
 
 Thus, in the first place, a new thing could never have 
 caused itself, because it could never have acted before it 
 came into existence. It must, therefore, have been brought 
 into being by something else. 
 
 Secondly, every change in anything which already exists 
 is, in fact, a new mode of being; and therefore equally de- 
 mands a cause for its existence. It must, then, be due 
 either to something distinct from it, or to some antecedent 
 mode of being of that which now exists in its new mode. 
 
 Thus, when we awake from sleep, our awakening must be 
 due either to something external which has awakened us, or 
 to some change which has taken place in our own organism. 
 In the latter case, that change or new mode in our being, 
 which we call " wakening from sleep," had for its cause an 
 antecedent state of our body increased vigour of the cir- 
 culation or what-not. 
 
 Moreover, all the various objects we see or feel must, each 
 of them, we know, be a result of the action of some cause or 
 causes external to it. This is, of course, most manifestly evi- 
 dent with respect to every artistic product, and everything 
 which has been made by man. But a little reflection will 
 show that the same is the case with all the products of nat- 
 ure. No stone we tread upon, no patch of sand or mud, can 
 have come to be what it is, save by the action of antecedent 
 causes. The shape of every mountain is, at least, largely 
 due to the action of water, and so on. And this law of 
 causation applies to the most minute and simplest, as well 
 as to the largest and most complex, of bodies. Even pieces 
 of matter, which, so far as we yet know, consist of but one 
 chemical element such as a fragment of gold or carbon 
 owe the shape, place, and the relations in which we find 
 them, to conditioning causes. And carbon in its brilliant 
 
258 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 condition as a diamond (a state we term crystalline) is 
 equally an effect of causes ; and, as yet, all the causes which 
 have produced all the diverse and most definite forms of 
 crystallisation, which are characteristic of different minerals, 
 are for us mysterious. 
 
 Any and every such object demands a cause for its actually 
 being in the place it is, at the time it is there, for its size, 
 its shape, etc., and for all its relations to surrounding things, 
 as well as for any special qualities of its own internal con- 
 ditions. These special conditions would demand a cause, 
 even if such a body existed alone and by itself in an other- 
 wise empty universe if we may permit ourselves to frame 
 for a moment so absurd an hypothesis. 
 
 Therefore, everything which can be seen not to contain a 
 sufficient cause for its own existence within itself, must be 
 due to some cause or causes external to it. Nothing which 
 is composite, capable of division, or which gives evidence of 
 having had a beginning, can be so seen to contain within 
 itself a sufficient cause for its being. 
 
 Moreover, this perception of the necessity of causation is 
 not, as before said, the mere result of a mental impotence of 
 the imagination it is not a negative inability to imagine a 
 complex thing uncaused but a positive and active power 
 of perception. Let the reader first consider his own idea of 
 a stone of some definite shape and size, made of two or 
 more mineral substances. Then let him ask himself whether 
 he does not actively and positively see that its shape and 
 composition must positively be due to influences of different 
 kinds, or whether he finds himself merely passive and un- 
 able to help himself to an actively intelligent conviction on 
 the subject. 
 
 The idea of a " cause " is closely connected with the con- 
 ception of " power " or " force " ideas gained through our 
 own personal experience. When we make strenuous efforts, 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 259 
 
 or are overborne by the active energy of somebody or some- 
 thing else, we have this experience. We know, also, our 
 own power to think and act, and the influence exercised by 
 our own will. But there is another yet more noteworthy 
 instance of the exercise of power which may come within 
 our experience. When under strong temptation to indulge 
 in some very keen and entrancing pleasure, we can easily 
 perceive, if we will, the strong hold the desire for self- 
 indulgence has over us and its power and force in attracting 
 our will in one direction. Similarly, when the thought of 
 most repulsive consequences which will probably, or cer- 
 tainly, follow such indulgence occurs to us, we may feel the 
 power exercised by that thought in repelling us from it and 
 in some contrary direction. 
 
 The idea of " power " or " force " is a primary ultimate 
 idea which cannot be resolved into other more fundamental 
 or elementary conceptions. If the reader doubts this, we 
 would recommend him to try so to resolve it himself. 
 
 But the reality of our conception of cause of our percep- 
 tion of the universal and necessary truth of the law of causa- 
 tion has been denied on the following grounds. It is 
 objected that though we have, of course, seen one condition, 
 relation, or event follow another condition, relation, or event, 
 we have never once perceived any inflow or passage of in- 
 fluence from one thing to another; and yet the law of causa- 
 tion implies the existence of such a thing. We have never, 
 it is further stated, really seen or felt any " causation," but 
 only sequences of one kind or another. Therefore, it is con- 
 cluded, there is probably nothing but sequence, and our 
 idea of the passage of influence in causation is a mere mis- 
 take, derived from foolishly transferring in imagination to 
 external things that " feeling of effort " which we experience 
 in our actions, such mistake being then perpetuated by 
 custom. 
 
260 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 This objection is very easily answered. It is, of course, 
 quite true that we never see the act of physical causation 
 over and above the things which act and react, because it is 
 invisible as well as intangible. But though our senses can- 
 not perceive it, our intellect can and does. When we knock 
 a nail into a board with a hammer, it is simply nonsense to 
 tell us that because we can only perceive the nail, the board, 
 and the hammer, we cannot know that we exert a force 
 which makes the nail go in. 
 
 But there is one instance in which a man can be aware, 
 through his actual feelings, not only of an antecedent and 
 consequent, and the relation of causality between them, 
 but also the very bond or nexus between them may be not 
 only distinctly perceived by our intellect, but its inflow actu- 
 ally felt. This is whenever a man is in doubt about what 
 course to pursue owing to his being drawn in different direc- 
 tions by different motives. Then the inflow and force of 
 the conflicting motives acting upon his own mind can be 
 distinctly perceived by him. This instance is substantially 
 the same as that we before adduced with respect to our per- 
 ception of the emission of " force." We can all also 
 perceive force when anything resists our will. Thus, let us 
 suppose that the stem of a small tree has been partly sawn 
 through, and that we then try whether we can pull it down. 
 If the coherence of the part not sawn through is still very 
 great, we may have to exert all our force to overcome it. 
 When at last we have succeeded, and are exhausted with 
 our efforts, we may feel very vividly that anyone who denied 
 we had caused the tree to come down must be as great a 
 lunatic as anyone who denied the real objective existence of 
 the tree itself. 
 
 But it may be said (we know it may, because such follies 
 have actually been printed) that, though we may be con- 
 scious of our own force, we err if we assert efficient causation 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 26 1 
 
 in any other instance. In fact, Mr. Herbert Spencer has 
 said that by such an assertion we make the great mistake of 
 attributing to inanimate things feelings like those we ex- 
 perience in making such physical efforts. Surely greater 
 nonsense has rarely been written. Let us suppose the 
 partly-sawn-through tree to be not even touched by us, but 
 that a gale has sprung up which, after having swayed it to 
 and fro, breaks it off, and prostrates it, just as we have sup- 
 posed it prostrated by human efforts. Are we not then to 
 say that the wind has exerted as much force as was ours ? 
 Can we not say this confidently, without being such idiots 
 as to attribute " feelings " to the wind ? 
 
 Truly, then, we have in our observations and experiments 
 with external things, as well as in the consciousness of our 
 own efforts and the action of motives on our minds, actual 
 experience of causation, while, as we have seen, . a very 
 moderate study of the matter suffices to show us that the 
 law of causation is a necessary and universal truth which 
 carries with it its own evidence. 
 
 A clear perception of the law of causation gives efficient 
 support to a great principle, without which all science 
 would be absolutely impossible. This is the law of the 
 Uniformity of Nature* It is true that the ordinary ex- 
 perience of mankind makes men perfectly contented that 
 things will take their normal course, e. g., that the sun will 
 daily rise and set, and that any tool dropped from the 
 hand will at once fall towards the ground unless otherwise 
 upheld. In circumstances which seem to recur under, so 
 far as we can see, the same conditions as those wherein 
 they occurred before, we naturally expect the same results 
 to ensue as we before met with ; and such expectations 
 are fulfilled. 
 
 Nevertheless, mere common sense and human testi- 
 
 1 See ante, p. 106. 
 
262 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 mony cannot suffice, any more than the experience of any 
 individual can suffice, to show that the uniformity of nature 
 is, and must always be, positively certain and absolute. 
 Our mere observation of natural laws can never suffice to 
 enable us to affirm that never and nowhere is there a law- 
 less condition of things, or that such a lawless condition 
 may not one day come within our own sphere of experience 
 utter irregularity of co-existences and sequences. But here 
 that necessary and self-evident principle, the law of causa- 
 tion, comes in, and supplies us with the basis for science 
 which is so imperatively required. For, since there can be 
 no change without a cause, it follows there can be no differ- 
 ence between the results of two perfectly similar sets of 
 antecedent conditions, and that the more completely two 
 sets of conditions are alike, the more completely similar will 
 be the results produced by them. 
 
 Thus the uniformity of nature is a necessary result of the 
 law of causation, which necessary and self-evident truth 
 gives the efficient and necessary support to that expectation 
 which good sense and human testimony combine to produce 
 in us. 
 
 But there must also be a certain proportion between any 
 physical or mental cause and its effects; and our reason 
 assures us that we can to a considerable extent judge as to 
 causes by the effects they have produced. We can often 
 form a rational judgment as to the adequacy of some cause 
 to produce a given effect. No child with a toy hammer 
 could level the Great Pyramid of Egypt, and no ignorant 
 peasant could translate and adequately comment upon 
 Plato's Symposium. No creature devoid of intellect could 
 ever perform a truly virtuous action, for it could have no 
 perception about ethical relations. That a cause must 
 be adequate in order that a given effect may be produced, 
 is an absolute, universal, and necessary truth, no less than 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 263 
 
 is the law of causation itself, as is commonly if tacitly 
 assumed. 1 
 
 But, as we before observed, an objection is often raised to 
 this assertion on the ground that there is no resemblance 
 between the steel blade of a dagger and the wound it can in- 
 flict or between a red-hot coal and the burn it may occasion. 
 How, we are asked, could we know, a priori, the " ade- 
 quacy " of cither to produce the " injuries " they respect- 
 ively cause ? 
 
 But, in the first place, there is a certain resemblance 
 between the width of the cut and that of the dagger's 
 blade, and between the size of the coal and the extent of 
 the burnt surface. In addition to that, it is plain, after a 
 moment's thought, that the "adequacy" of the cause to pro- 
 duce the effect is neither in the steel nor in the coal, but in 
 these as affecting a sensitive organism which they may in- 
 jure. The organism and the agents are together adequate 
 to produce the effects cited, and that adequacy is evident 
 to our reason, and sufficient. 
 
 But the one appeal of physical science is to "experience" 
 to observation and experiment, and the verification of 
 hypotheses thereby. And what does experience teach us ? 
 In many instances, of course, our ignorance of the intimate 
 nature of, or the powers and properties of, bodies, makes us 
 quite unable to anticipate, a priori, what effects may be pro- 
 duced ; these we can only learn by experience. But in 
 multitudes of every-day observations, the inadequacy of 
 some things to produce certain effects (as with the 
 child's hammer and the pyramid) is manifest, as is the 
 impotence of an ignorant man to teach Greek, or of an 
 impecunious one to lend a sum of money; so that ex- 
 perience fully bears out the ancient dictum: " Nemo dat 
 quod non habet. ' ' 
 
 1 See ante, p. 66. 
 
264 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 We have now passed in review in the preceding and 
 present chapters the questions as to : (i) the existence of 
 certainty, and that what is, exists; (2) what must be our 
 ultimate criterion ; (3) our perception of our own substantial 
 existence ; (4) the validity of our faculty of memory ; (5) the 
 principle of contradiction ; (6) mathematical axioms; (7) the 
 validity of the reasoning process ; and (8) the law of causa- 
 tion. We hope the views here advocated concerning these 
 questions may have commended themselves to the judgment 
 of our readers. If so, we have already succeeded in the 
 greater part of our task. For there can be no question that 
 if the fundamental principles we have put forward are neces- 
 sary and universal truths, which carry with them their own 
 evidence and constitute the ultimate criteria of human 
 knowledge, they must also constitute a large part of the 
 groundwork of all science. 
 
 These truths we can recognise for what they are, namely, 
 absolutely certain and self-evident facts and principles. But 
 however evident they may be, it is no less evident that we 
 did not always recognise them. Not only in our infancy, 
 but during childhood and early youth we were either alto- 
 gether ignorant of them or, at any rate, did not take them 
 for what we now see them to be. 
 
 How, then, did we come to obtain a knowledge of them, 
 and is it possible that the mode in which we acquired 
 them, whatever it may have been, can give us reasonable 
 cause to mistrust them, or be half-hearted, as it were, in our 
 recognition of them as absolutely true facts and principles ? 
 Can we gain any light as to what may have been the causes 
 of our certitude, and have such causes any real bearing on 
 that certitude's validity ? 
 
 We have already disposed of that most unreasonable of 
 all suppositions, namely, the supposition that what we have 
 represented as first principles can possibly be based on 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 26$ 
 
 reasoning. We have seen ' that such a system results in a 
 regressus ad infinitum, and would necessarily emasculate 
 reasoning by depriving it of its indispensable premisses. 
 But some persons would represent our deepest convictions 
 as nothing but the result of habit and associations of images 
 and ideas, which have become so inveterate that it is quite 
 impossible for us now to detach ourselves from them. 
 
 This conception we have, it is hoped, incidentally shown 
 to be quite insufficient. For how, in the first place, could 
 habit give rise to ethical perceptions in beings who were 
 entirely devoid of them ? How could habit formed amongst 
 the experiences of life have enabled us to perceive that true 
 and absolutely certain conclusions could never be obtained 
 through premisses which were false or uncertain ? a It is 
 quite true, of course, that reason is developed and main- 
 tained by complex associations of sensations, images, and 
 ideas, as it is, in another way, maintained by the food we 
 eat and the air we breathe. But none of these things, in 
 whatever combinations, could give rise to intellectual intui- 
 tions in creatures devoid of intellect. 
 
 Other persons, again, who vehemently repudiate the last- 
 noticed hypothesis, would have us regard as supremely cer- 
 tain, the truths which are at first recognized by the dawning 
 intelligence of the child. Only such ideas do they consider 
 to be what they call ' ' a genuine testimony of consciousness. 
 But why should truths recognised by a dawning human in- 
 telligence be worth more than those recognised by a man's 
 intelligence at its full noontide ? It is against all our ex- 
 perience to assert that the ideas of young children are more 
 true and profound than those of full-grown and well- 
 educated men. This theory would be utterly absurd but 
 for a conception latent in it and unexpressed, which we 
 think must be its real, though unavowed, foundation. It is 
 
 1 See ante, p. 103. 2 See ante, p. 218. 
 
266 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 the notion that the infant mind bears, as it were, the fresh 
 impress of a Divine Creator, on which account its dicta 
 should be more regarded than persuasions of later days, 
 when that mind has become subjected to the corruptions 
 and delusions prevalent in the world. This fancy, it seems 
 to us, must also be the ground upon which other men have 
 declared that what we should most trust, and may entirely 
 trust, are ideas which are a priori^ and have never been 
 gained by experience. For why otherwise could anyone 
 think we should attach less importance and validity to im- 
 pressions and conclusions which have been gained by the 
 most patient and painstaking efforts, when large stores of 
 knowledge have been acquired in many different ways, than 
 to others (did any really exist), for the possession of which 
 antecedent experiences were in no way necessary ? 
 
 Obviously, the only ground upon which the latter could 
 make any special claim on our acceptance would be that 
 they had been implanted in human nature by " an All-wise 
 Creator. ' ' 
 
 Yet it is no less obvious that such a conviction could 
 never serve as a basis for our knowledge, because it would 
 first be requisite to prove that " an All-wise Creator " exists. 
 
 That His existence is not known by any intuition is mani- 
 fest from the fact that so many books have been written to 
 prove that existence, as well as from the circumstance that 
 so many persons doubt or positively disbelieve it. 
 
 But to prove any such theistic doctrine it is manifestly 
 necessary antecedently to possess a sufficient knowledge 
 of truths apt to serve as premisses for so important a 
 conclusion. 
 
 Now there is one assertion as to the cause of our convic- 
 tions especially about our confidence in the real existence 
 of the external world and the inevitableness of that confid- 
 ence which deserves special notice, not so much on its 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 267 
 
 own account as because it harmonises with a fashion of the 
 day. A strong tendency exists to try to account for ev- 
 erything by the action of " natural selection," and that 
 cause has been specially invoked to account for the inevit- 
 able character of our convictions about the reality of the 
 external world. 
 
 It is indeed a persuasion of many men of science that all 
 the characteristics, all the sense-organs, and all the intel- 
 ligence which any animal possesses, are and must have been 
 due to " natural selection," that is, to the preservation in 
 the struggle for life of the creatures possessing such sense- 
 organs and intelligence. Why then, it is asked, may not 
 human reason be in the same case ? Why may it not be 
 the mere result of a fortunate psychical variation which has 
 enabled the primitive brutal man to destroy and feed on the 
 brutal animal a trifle more easily than before ? Is it possible 
 for us to trust and confide in a faculty which has been at- 
 tained slowly through the persistent endeavours of our semi- 
 simian forefathers to feed and breed? A faculty so developed 
 may be admirable as a weapon, but what guarantee have we 
 to regard it as suited for very different purposes, namely, to 
 reveal to us the true nature of the world in which we find 
 ourselves, and to show us what it is reasonable for us to do 
 in other directions ? 
 
 This objection we have long before referred to, 1 stating 
 that it would be more fully considered later on. For such 
 fuller consideration the time has now come. 
 
 But we may here remind our readers of what we before 
 pointed out. 2 If our conviction about the existence of an 
 external world had been produced by " natural selection," 
 that would constitute a triumphant argument against ideal- 
 ism. "For, unless an independent, extended, and external 
 world really existed, no sentient organisms would be de- 
 
 1 See chapter Hi., p. 46. 8 See ante, p. 47. 
 
268 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 stroyed by contravening the laws and conditions thereof. 
 If it had acted so efficiently, it must have been a reality. 
 But, though there has been, and still is, a great deal of 
 talking and writing about " natural selection," it is sur- 
 prising how many persons talk and write about it without 
 knowing what it really is. It may be useful, therefore, to 
 say here a few words upon the subject, so that our readers 
 may run less risk of being misled and wasting their time 
 over questions which are in no way to the purpose. 
 
 In the first place, we must remember what the action of 
 " natural selection " is, what it can do, and what it is im- 
 possible that it should ever effect. 
 
 " Natural selection," as everyone knows, was put forward 
 by the late Mr. Charles Darwin to account for the origin of 
 new kinds (new species) of animals and plants. Considering 
 that no two individuals of either kingdom are absolutely 
 alike, and that every species tends to increase rapidly, it is 
 evident that any variation (whether structural or functional) 
 which should arise, of a seriously detrimental character, 
 would render almost inevitable the destruction of the in- 
 dividual possessing it. 
 
 It is no less evident that any animal or plant which should 
 come to possess a new character exceptionally favourable, 
 would have a better chance of survival amidst the various 
 adverse influences which threaten the lives of all animals 
 and plants. 
 
 Thus individuals which survive by escaping the elimina- 
 tion which awaits others, are said to be naturally " selected. " 
 It is not, however, any active " selection " which takes 
 place ; it is merely an escape from destruction through the 
 possession of some favourable characteristic. 
 
 ' Natural selection," therefore, is in reality a term de- 
 noting all the destructive powers of nature taken together 
 and considered as an active unity. 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 269 
 
 Whether or not this is a sufficient account of the origin 
 of species is a question upon which we cannot enter at any 
 length here, and it is the less necessary to do so as we 
 have elsewhere explained our views and the arguments 
 which, in our opinion, support them. 
 
 It is, of course, obvious that the origin of a new species 
 must be due to the development of new positive characters 
 which distinguish it from other species; the action of nature 
 can be but that of a pruning-knife applied to the sprouting 
 tree of organic life. 
 
 This, of course, 'Darwin well knew, and he never for a 
 moment pretended (as some of his opponents have very un- 
 justly and foolishly represented that he did pretend) that 
 " natural selection " could account for, or produce, the 
 variations upon the occurrence of which the origin of every 
 new species must absolutely depend. 
 
 But Mr. Darwin was most exceptionally fortunate in the 
 character of his hypothesis, for it was of such a nature as to 
 be almost incapable of disproof. Having taken up the 
 position that every characteristic of a species exists through 
 its utility to that species, and that it may be assumed to 
 have so originated unless proof to the contrary can be given, 
 his opponent was thereby reduced to sore straits indeed, and 
 it would be similar even if we knew, from some infallible 
 source, that the hypothesis was a false one. 
 
 For its opponent would have to show that minute, hap- 
 hazard variations in all directions in all the organs of every 
 species, were impossible or did not take place; he would 
 also have to show that there were structures or functions 
 possessed by some species which were not only of no use 
 to it now, but could never have been of any use to any of 
 its ancestors at any period of the world's history, or, under 
 any possible conditions, of any use to even any hypo- 
 thetical ancestor which an advocate of " natural selection " 
 
2/O THE -GROUND WORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 can suggest may have existed under conditions widely 
 divergent from those which form the present environment 
 of the species in question. A disciple of Mr. Darwin can 
 also always say: " It is very true that this or that charac- 
 ter could not have been produced by ' natural selection ' 
 directly, but it may have been produced by it indirectly, 
 for you cannot deny that it may have been an accompani- 
 ment of some other character which was useful." Thus 
 such a disciple may claim a victory on the mere ground of 
 his being able to imagine some possible cause for the past 
 or present existence of which he is unable to bring forward 
 a shadow of proof. 
 
 The Darwinian is free to invoke climatic changes, geo- 
 graphical modifications, and the presence or the absence 
 of rivals or of enemies at his will and discretion. Easy, in- 
 deed, is it for such an one, with some flexibility of imagina- 
 tion, to construct suggestions of utility when provided with 
 such an unlimited field of free speculation. Let an animal 
 be black, and reasons can be very readily found to show that 
 blackness may have saved it from destruction. Let it be 
 shown to be white, and another set of reasons are easily im- 
 agined to show that the snowier its tints, the more assured 
 are its chances of survival. Thus, upon a rabbit's white tail 
 being adduced as a character dangerously conspicuous, it 
 has been replied, " Oh, but it serves as a signal in danger 
 to guide the young on their way to the burrow! " 
 
 Perhaps the most notable character of the Darwinian 
 theory is the extraordinary easiness of its advocacy and 
 difficulty of its refutation, quite apart from any question of 
 its truth. The chances of its author in such a game of 
 biological speculation can only be expressed by the well- 
 known vulgarism, " Heads I win, tails you lose." 
 
 Nevertheless, there are characters which as it has always 
 seemed and still seems to us defy explanation even amidst 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 2? I 
 
 such extraordinary facilities. Some such could easily be 
 now brought forward, but it would be out of place to adduce 
 them here, as, though " natural selection" has some in- 
 direct bearing on Epistemology, the question as to the origin 
 of animals and plants has none save in one respect only. 
 
 The tendency of Darwinism has plainly and manifestly 
 been to propagate a conviction that the origin of species 
 has been due -to what we must call chance that is, not to 
 any rational cause. The essence of the hypothesis is the 
 origin of species by the fortuitous action of the destructive 
 forces of nature on individuals which differ by innate, in- 
 definite, haphazard variations in all directions. Purposeless 
 energy is conceived as the cause of the variations, and the 
 selection of certain kinds is also conceived of as due to the 
 chance action of physical forces and of other organisms. 
 By this expression we mean, of course, that the cause of 
 variation is thus deemed to be not only unknown, but to 
 be due to no definite law which is the outcome of any kind 
 or sort of intelligent energy. By this system, then, un- 
 reason may be regarded as practically lord of the universe, 
 and the source of all the beauties and harmonies which exist 
 in organic nature. 
 
 The above philosophical conception, which underlies the 
 Darwinian theory, has a very distinct though indirect bear- 
 ing on Epistemology, as we shall see later on. 
 
 We must now return to the consideration of the asserted 
 genesis by " natural selection " of the inevitable character 
 of our perceptions of an external, extended world. The 
 main answer to this objection is the answer which we shall 
 shortly give to all the theories concerning the origin of 
 human knowledge. It consists in pointing out that what is 
 supremely important is not the origin of knowledge but the 
 grounds of knowledge the reasons why it should and must 
 be confided in and trusted. It is strange that 'so many 
 
2/2 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 persons should be blind to this fact, which, in our eyes, is 
 so obvious a truth. 
 
 But, putting aside for the present this reply, let us 
 consider whether we possess any knowledge which could 
 not have been due to the action of " natural selection " 
 upon minute variations in the clearness and extent of our 
 perceptions. 
 
 Now, as we have more than once before pointed out, our 
 intuition of the extended is not the most absolutely certain 
 of our intuitions or one of the highest rank, and it certainly 
 is not our only intuition. 
 
 If it did stand alone, if that were our only intuition, then 
 there might be some plausibility in attributing its origin to 
 such a cause. But we possess other intuitions which 
 " natural selection " could never have developed. If, 
 therefore, we are forced to assign the existence and develop- 
 ment of those other intuitions to some cause quite different 
 from " natural selection," then the cause which developed 
 them may obviously also have developed our invincible con- 
 viction that an external, independent universe of extended 
 objects (things in themselves) exists. 
 
 Now amongst the intuitions possessed by us for which 
 " natural selection " cannot account, are those gained by 
 our reflex consciousness respecting the necessary truth of 
 first principles, such as that of the principle of contradiction, 
 the force of the word " therefore," the certainty that for 
 every new existence there must be a cause, etc. 
 
 But more striking still, in this relation, are our certainties 
 about purely hypothetical verities, e. g., " If premisses are 
 false or uncertain no certain conclusion can be derived 
 therefrom " ; " If an engine can travel only thirty miles an 
 hour, it could never traverse one hundred miles in an hour 
 and a half " ; " If A, having been entrusted with money to 
 pay a debt of B, should spend it in gratifying some desire 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 2/3 
 
 of his own, he would commit an unjust act," etc. (< Natural 
 selection " has efficiency to compel action in harmony with 
 the requirements of physical conditions, but none to teach 
 us speculative, and especially hypothetical, propositions. 
 
 If, then, there is some efficient cause which can, inde- 
 pendently of " natural selection," produce these intuitive 
 results, a fortiori it could produce the indefinitely minor 
 effect, namely, " sense-perception," the apprehension of 
 spatial relations, and a conviction that the objects we 
 see and feel really exist independently of any imaginable 
 feelings. 
 
 We have said above that had we no other intuition save 
 that of things extended, that intuition might plausibly be 
 attributed to the action of " natural selection." But it 
 certainly would be only a plausible attribution, and not a 
 truly reasonable one. For, as we have seen, " natural 
 selection" can give rise to nothing; all it can do is to 
 favour the existence and development of that which has 
 already risen. 
 
 But between a mere sense-perception such as we suppose 
 animals to possess exclusively, and an intellectual intuition, 
 there is a profound difference of kind, and such a difference 
 can never arise by spontaneous development. For the 
 origin of a new kind of perception a new power and faculty 
 some adequate cause must intervene, as we have lately 
 urged when considering the law of causation. 1 
 
 Between a power which can reflect upon its experiences 
 and recognise relations as relations, gifted with self-con- 
 sciousness and the power of ratiocination, and another 
 power which possesses none of these things, it would surely 
 be difficult to exagerate the difference. 
 
 And yet this difference is by no means all the divergence 
 which exists between the mind of man and the highest 
 
 1 See ante, p. 256. 
 18 
 
274 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 psychical power commonly attributed exclusively to animals. 
 There is, further, the power of apprehending a distinction 
 between right and wrong, and conceiving of moral respon- 
 sibility, and also the power of forming abstract ideas and 
 apprehending absolute, necessary, and universal truths as 
 such. Surely the difference between a nature possessing 
 all these powers and one which has them not, must, indeed, 
 be a difference of kind. 
 
 The difference of kind which we have before l represented 
 as existing (and which we consider does exist) between man 
 and mere animals, must, we hope, be now evident to the 
 reader's mind. 
 
 Nevertheless, as we declared when directly considering 
 the psychical powers of brutes, we have no desire to dog- 
 matise with respect to this matter. That there is, and must 
 be, a very real and great difference of kind between a 
 nature essentially, though latently, intellectual, and possess- 
 ing a capacity for the apprehension of these highest truths, 
 and a merely sensitive power, is, for us, unquestionable. 
 But whether that higher psychical nature exists latent and 
 incapable of manifestation in animals, as it does in the human 
 infant, is a question not absolutely evident, though, as we 
 believe, the amount of evidence which does exist tells 
 strongly against the view that animals have a nature which 
 is in its essence potentially rational. 
 
 Yet there is no absolute impossibility that they may, and, 
 if they do, then variations in the amount and kinds of its 
 incipient and ultimate manifestations might have been de- 
 veloped by " natural selection." But to this question we 
 shall return in our next and final chapter, when we consider 
 possibilities as to the nature of the cosmos. Were human 
 intelligence really evolved from a hidden intelligence in 
 animals, that fact would in no way invalidate or weaken the 
 
 1 See ante, p. 214. 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 275 
 
 difference between a higher nature, such as man's, and a 
 much lower one, such as that commonly attributed to 
 animals. Its only effect would be, as before said, to raise 
 mere animal life in our esteem, and in no way to depress or 
 diminish our respect for our own mental powers. It would 
 be a process of psychical " levelling up." 
 
 It is the opposite process, that of ' ' levelling down, ' ' which 
 is so profoundly unreasonable, and which we shall almost 
 immediately 1 proceed to consider. 
 
 Thus one and the same answer can be given to all the dif- 
 ferent representations which have been made concerning the 
 value to be attributed to human perceptions and the de- 
 velopment of intelligence from the germ, as to which differ- 
 ent persons have advanced special claims for exceptional 
 security of one and another mode, as lately stated. All 
 such inquiries are interesting and valuable for some purposes 
 (such as the study of the human mind), but they are all 
 utterly beside the question which supremely concerns us. 
 
 We have seen * that the ultimate ground of certainty, 
 whatever proposition we may be considering, is, and must 
 be, its own intrinsic self-evidence its manifest certainty in 
 and by itself. 
 
 All inquiries into the origin and causes of our convictions 
 whether they are gained by experience, or innate, or 
 dawning in the mind of the infant, or only acquired at men- 
 tal maturity, or brought forth from intelligence latent at 
 birth, or brought forth by " natural selection " from in- 
 telligence truly latent in our animal ancestors are futile for 
 Epistemology. 
 
 That a fruit we at the same time see, feel, smell, and taste 
 exists ; that it cannot, at the same time, have a seed within 
 it and be seedless ; that we are the same person we were be- 
 fore we saw this fruit ; that if we give half of it away, what 
 
 1 See infra, p. 277. 8 See ante, pp. 221-222. 
 
276 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 of it remains to us will be thereby diminished ; that if all 
 peaches are juicy, and we know a peach has been given to 
 a child, we may be sure it has been given something juicy; 
 that if a fruit was in a cupboard, but is now there no longer, 
 its absence is to be attributed to some cause, and that a 
 really ungrateful action must be bad are plain truths, no 
 whit less certain whatever may have been the mode in which 
 we have come to know them. In other words, the certainty 
 of our knowledge of the objective reality of bodies, and of 
 the objective validity of the first principles of human intel- 
 ligence, is in no way affected by the nature of the agency, 
 or the modes of action, which have furnished us with the 
 certainty we possess. That is of the highest possible kind, 
 so that no one can even conceive of any mode by which 
 greater certainty could be given to us than is given to us by 
 self-evidence. It matters not to us what was the intellectual 
 condition of our immediate or our remote ancestors, nor 
 what was our state in infancy, nor how it was we acquired 
 the intellectual intuitions we have. Their validity is not 
 affected thereby, for their self-evidence to us, hie et nunc, is 
 clear and luminous. Of nothing else have we, or can we 
 have, such complete and absolute certainty. 
 
 So far, then, the suggestion of the development the im- 
 proving and perfecting of intellect through the action of 
 " natural selection " upon creatures already latently intel- 
 ligent, and varying in their approximations towards its 
 incipient manifestations, is one which has no bearing upon 
 Epistemology, and may therefore be put aside by us, as 
 nothing but a waste of time could ensue from its further 
 study. 
 
 Very different, however, are the consequences which 
 ensue from that approximation between the highest psychi- 
 cal powers of men and brutes, which we have spoken of ! as 
 
 1 See ante, p. 275. 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 277 
 
 a " levelling down/' and from the philosophical system 
 which underlies ' the system put forth by Mr. Darwin, and 
 that which Mr. Herbert Spencer has recently brought to 
 its termination. The consequences which thence ensue do 
 indeed bear upon the science of Epistemology, and, indeed, 
 not only upon the groundwork of science, but upon every 
 separate science, and therefore, necessarily, on the basis of 
 them all. They are thus fatal because they spring from, 
 and can only exist with, a complete want of apprehension 
 of what the human intellect is and what are its powers. 
 
 In the first place, we now desire to call attention to the 
 law and principle which Mr. Spencer has enunciated as 
 specially his own, and as one extending from the founda- 
 tion of his whole philosophical construction to its highest 
 pinnacle. 
 
 This great law and principle propounded by him his 
 version of the process of evolution is the assertion that all 
 things in nature are proceeding "from an indefinite, incoher- 
 ent homogeneity to a definite, coherent heterogeneity. ' ' 
 
 It will be well for all readers who may be inclined to defer 
 to and reverence Mr. Herbert Spencer's doctrines, to ponder 
 a little over this, his first principle, which he long ago chose 
 as a starting-point, and which his very latest writings pro- 
 fess to enforce and illustrate. 
 
 The process and procession of evolutionary changes are 
 thus declared by him to start from what is homogeneous, 
 incoherent, and indefinite ! Could any procession be more 
 unfortunate as to its starting-point, any process more neces- 
 sarily impotent, any philosophical structure more baseless ? 
 
 Hegel has received far more than his share of ridicule for 
 saying that " being and not-being are identical." But 
 Hegel was dealing with abstract ideas, regarded in a certain 
 way, while Mr. Spencer is busy about concrete things. As 
 
 1 P. 271. 
 
278 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 to them he, in effect, makes an assertion which is utterly 
 self-contradictory. The starting-point of his procession lies 
 nowhere, the fulcrum for his process is nonentity, and the 
 foundation of his system is an absolute vacuum. 
 
 For, according to him, everything depends for its origin 
 on the " indefinite," and, most unfortunately for Mr. 
 Spencer, the " indefinite " is just what does not, never did, 
 and never can exist. 
 
 It is absolutely impossible for any concrete entity to be 
 " indefinite." Whatever is, is necessarily a thing of some 
 kind or another. It must have certain qualities and charac- 
 ters, be they what they may. Let us conceive of the most 
 attenuated and amorphous nebula we can ; it must yet be 
 quite definite. It must have some composition, some char- 
 acters of cohesion and possible resistance, some limits as to 
 size, and some shape, change as it may from instant to in- 
 stant. In reality it is as definite a thing as a plum-pudding, 
 and it is nothing but a trick of the imagination which may 
 make it seem not to be so. Less easily perceived by our 
 sense-organs, and therefore less easy to imagine and less 
 easy to describe, it certainly is. But less " definite " it no 
 less certainly is not. 
 
 Here then, at the very base, or the very starting-point, of 
 Mr. Spencer's whole philosophy, lies an absurdity so pro- 
 found as necessarily to destroy the philosophical value of 
 the entire system based upon it. And his system agrees 
 with that " levelling-down " method of treating human in- 
 telligence which now demands our attention. We need, 
 however, occupy but little space here or little of our reader's 
 attention, if he is already convinced that self-evidence, as 
 recognised by the intellect, is the supreme and ultimate 
 criterion of the truth of those propositions which lie at the 
 base of all our " ordered knowledge " i. e., of all science. 
 
 The process of " levelling down " seeks to explain our 
 
CA USES OF SCIENTIFIC KNO WLEDGE 2?$ 
 
 highest faculties by our lowest, and to make not intellect 
 but sense the criterion of our judgments. After what we 
 have before pointed out, we think it needless further to 
 criticise that fundamental error which forms a main part of 
 the system of philosophy which underlies the system known 
 as Darwinism. Its result, for those who are so unfortunate 
 as not to have forced their way through it, is to hide from 
 their intellectual eyesight the objective truth of these prin- 
 ciples which are logically necessary for all science, 1 and 
 which if not (as they should be) expressly accepted, must at 
 least be unconsciously assumed when pursuing science. 
 
 The ultimate result of that system is necessarily self- 
 destructive, ending (when consistently carried out to its 
 consequences) in a scepticism which amounts to intellectual 
 paralysis. 
 
 The system to which we here specially refer is that which 
 affirms the essential relativity of knowledge. 
 
 Now that all human knowledge is relative is, in one sense, 
 of course, a most obvious truth. Our knowledge plainly 
 depends upon and is relative to our powers of discernment 
 and reasoning our senses and our intellect. Had we more 
 senses we should doubtless know many things which we now 
 cannot even conceive of because the imaginations necessary 
 for such conceptions are lacking. Had we deeper powers 
 of intuition and a greater capacity for ratiocination our 
 knowledge would be indefinitely increased thereby. In 
 such senses as these our knowledge is truly relative. But 
 though we can thus know only in part, we -can know many 
 truths with absolute certainty and complete adequacy, and 
 we can and do see the self-evident certainty and complete- 
 ness of such knowledge. 
 
 Even Omniscience could not know with an essentially 
 greater certainty than we do the fact of our own existence, 
 
 1 See ante, chapter iv. 
 
280 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 the fact that one moon, and not two, circles round our planet, 
 the truth of the principles of contradiction and causality, 
 etc. About such knowledge there can be no uncertainty on 
 the ground of its relativity or on any other ground. It is 
 absolute knowledge. But this is what the upholders of 
 the doctrine of its relativity deny. They deny that, being 
 relative, it can ever at the same time be absolutely and per- 
 fectly true. 
 
 This system became, a short time ago, widely popular, 
 and its doctrines may be conveniently summed up as 
 follows : 
 
 (1) All our knowledge is merely relative. 
 
 (2) We can know nothing but phenomena. 
 
 (3) We cannot be supremely certain as to our substantial 
 existence. 
 
 (4) We cannot emerge from subjectivity and attain any 
 knowledge of objective truths. 
 
 The second, third, and fourth of these doctrines we have 
 already, we hope, sufficiently passed in review. As to the 
 mere assertion of relativity as implying untruth or untrust- 
 worthiness, a very brief consideration will, we think, suffice. 
 
 Every system of knowledge must start with the assump- 
 tion, implied or expressed, that something is true and can 
 be certainly known so to be. Therefore, those who uphold 
 the doctrine of the relativity of knowledge must evidently 
 hold, since they honestly teach it, that their doctrine of the 
 relativity of knowledge is true and can be known with 
 certainty to be true. 
 
 Yet if we cannot know that any of our internal convictions 
 correspond with objective reality, if nothing we can assert 
 can be and be known by us to be absolutely true and cer- 
 tain, then this character must also appertain to the doctrine 
 of the " relativity of knowledge." Either, then, this system 
 of philosophy is merely uncertain, and cannot be known to 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 28 1 
 
 be true, or else it is absolutely true and can be known so to 
 be. 
 
 But it must be merely uncertain, and possibly untrue, if 
 everything which any human being can ever know is such. 
 Its value then can be only " relative," cannot be known to 
 correspond with external reality, and cannot, therefore, be 
 declared to be true. Now anybody who asserts that he can 
 know it to be true, thereby asserts that it is false to say 
 that all our knowledge is relative and cannot be known to 
 be true. But in that case some of our knowledge must be 
 absolute. Therefore, he who asserts that all our knowledge 
 is necessarily relative and uncertain, affirms at the same 
 time that some of it is necessarily absolute and certain, and 
 thus plainly and explicitly contradicts himself. With a 
 perception of which fact the reader need not, we think, 
 trouble himself any further concerning the doctrine of the 
 necessary relativity of knowledge. 
 
 But is the special Darwinian view, which regards the 
 forms of the organic world as being the result of minute in- 
 definite variations acted on by the chance conflict of for- 
 tuitous influences of all kinds, one which really harmonises 
 with the teaching of nature ? 
 
 The universe open to our ken gives us no positive evidence 
 of life elsewhere than in our planet. No doubt, analogy 
 suggests that many other worlds are inhabited, and for our 
 own part we cannot doubt that such must be the case. 
 Still, from what astronomers teach us, it would seem that 
 great spaces in the heavens are destitute of animal or vege- 
 table life, and that the worlds which are destitute of it pro- 
 bably predominate in number. Even in our solar system 
 the majority of its planets seem unfitted to be the abode 
 of living creatures. 
 
 When, from considerations of extent as regards space, we 
 turn to consider duration and ponder over the past history 
 
282 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 of our own globe, it seems difficult to think that the vast 
 series of succeeding ages which have seen so many races of 
 living beings successively arise and perish, were not preceded 
 by even a vaster series during which the earth revolved a 
 mere mass of inorganic matter. 
 
 And even in our own day such inorganic matter forms an 
 enormously preponderating part of its total composition. 
 How small a film upon its surface would be formed were 
 the whole mass of creatures now living spread over it. 
 
 Surely, then, when we begin to consider the universe 
 known to us, as its laws, as one whole, it becomes clear that 
 the vastly preponderating inorganic part of it is what we 
 should take as our norm, or standard of comparison, when 
 endeavouring to understand, as far as we may, the nature 
 of its constitution and laws. It is to the inorganic world 
 we must address ourselves if we would attain to the most 
 comprehensive view possible for us, of the order and method 
 which dominates and pervades nature. Such is especially 
 the case since, however we may be impressed by the pro- 
 bability that life such as exists in this world exists also in 
 others, we cannot actually know that such is the case. But 
 we do actually know, by the aid of spectrum analysis, that 
 the laws, properties, and species of inorganic substances, 
 such as those of our own earth, do extend into the remotest 
 regions of the cosmos which our telescopes enable us to 
 explore. 
 
 What, then, is the order of nature revealed to us by the 
 inorganic world? 
 
 Throughout that world and amongst the multitude of 
 mineral, and especially of crystalline, species which compose 
 it, most definite and ceaseless order reigns. 
 
 Each species has its own absolute internal constitution 
 and laws by which it continues to be, from age to age, just 
 what it is and no other, whether or not such stable sub- 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 283 
 
 stances originally arose from diverse combinations of one 
 primitive matter. 
 
 And the changes which take place in that inorganic world 
 are all most definite and ruled by rigid laws. All the 
 various chemical combinations which can and do take place 
 are definite combinations. And only certain such combina- 
 tions are possible. Mix substances, compound or element- 
 ary, as we may, we can only induce certain syntheses 
 resulting in new substances, and by no means a fresh sub- 
 stance for every possible blend. 
 
 These various syntheses, moreover, can only take place 
 under certain definite conditions, and most frequently the 
 states and properties of the separate substances, the syn- 
 thesis of which produces a new one, by no means give a 
 clue to the states and properties possessed by such new sub- 
 stance. Of this fact, the simplest and most familiar of all 
 chemical syntheses the synthesis of oxygen and hydrogen 
 in the production of water affords an instance as striking 
 as it is familiar. Between the physical condition of the 
 substances before synthesis and that of the new substance 
 after synthesis, there is a manifest breach of continuity. 
 Somehow or other we meet here, as in the instances pre- 
 viously given, 1 with a " new departure." Surely we could 
 hardly have more plain and unmistakable evidence of per- 
 manent law and order than that with which the inorganic 
 world supplies us. 
 
 But law and order are not the only characteristics of 
 the cosmos thus made evident : symmetry and beauty are 
 not less conspicuous. In crystals, as they form from so- 
 lution, the most definite, and often the most charmingly 
 symmetrical, forms are produced. Nor are the junctions of 
 crystals with crystals in compound aggregations less orderly 
 and beautiful, as we see in the fern-like growths upon our 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 213-214. 
 
284 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 window-panes during frost, and in the marvellous symmetry 
 of snowflakes. 
 
 What, again, is more wonderful than the beauty of mar- 
 ble and serpentine, of malachite and lapis lazuli, of the sap- 
 phire, the emerald, and the opal, and the other gems of dif- 
 ferent hues as well as the silky, fibrous textures and flakes 
 as of pearl which the mineral world has produced ? The 
 lovely and varied tints of humming-birds, of butterflies, and 
 of some Coleoptera are thus rivalled, while neither beauty 
 of tint nor matchless symmetry of form can, even in them, 
 have been the product of that process suggested by Mr. 
 Darwin as auxiliary to " natural selection," namely, 
 " sexual selection." ' 
 
 Yet all these species have their special properties and 
 active powers their definite physiology as have, pre- 
 eminently, all crystalline substances their complete and 
 specific anatomy. 
 
 Passing now from the consideration of the inorganic world 
 
 1 According to that notion, all the special characteristics of the male sex in 
 each species all that seems to us beautiful, bizarre, or revolting (strength and 
 nimbleness apart) have been evolved by means of the constantly recurring ex- 
 ercise of choice by the female amongst contending suitors. We thus find it as 
 impossible as ever to believe that the brilliant tints displayed by certain apes 
 were thus produced, when we recall to mind what are the psychical natures of 
 the females, and the physical force of their would-be spouses. 
 
 The tastes of female animals also must not only have been strangely diverse 
 but wonderfully persistent. One of the oddest notions thus promulgated was 
 the assignment to such feminine influence of the gradual denuding of men's backs 
 of the hairy coat with which they were supposed to be at first copiously clothed. 
 It is evident that the primitive ladies of the Kalmuck and Persian nationalities 
 differed widely in their sentiments as regards the beard ; but, nevertheless (if 
 the theory is true), the females of every tribe and nation of mankind in spite 
 of the frequent mutations of fashion must have unanimously and persistently 
 agreed in abhorring hirsute shoulders, and this though the females amongst 
 their immediate pithecoid, supposed ancestors entertained a directly opposite 
 sentiment. We refer our readers, as to sexual selection, to a work on Animal 
 Colouration, by Mr. Frank E. Bedhard, F.R.S. London, 1892. 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 285 
 
 to that of the world of life, and granting the truth of the 
 hypothesis of evolution, it seems to us clear that we ought 
 to start on our inquiry imbued with the lesson impressed on 
 us by the characteristics of the practically infinite and eternal 
 laws of the inorganic universe, which lies apart from the 
 brief and passing episode of existence endowed with life. 
 
 The anticipations of the kind with which we shall thus set 
 out on our exploration will by no means be disappointed 
 when we come to consider the beautiful sculpturing of 
 the hard parts of many very lowly organisms, such as 
 Diatoms, and the complex symmetry displayed by Fora- 
 minifera, and, above all, by the siliceous skeletons of num- 
 erous Radiolarians. How remarkable is the sculpture on 
 certain pollen grains, on many an egg-shell, as also the 
 patterns on various shells, and on multitudes of feathers and 
 of flowers. As little is it conceivable that they should have 
 been brought about by " natural selection," as that it 
 should have caused the pearly lining of shells or their sub- 
 superficial beauty, or that of gems and other minerals buried 
 for ages in the bowels of the earth. 
 
 One of the most obvious characters presented by the bodies 
 of animals, including our own, is that each has a right and left 
 side, and that these two sides, and their parts, correspond as 
 our right hand proverbially resembles our left one. When 
 deeply considered, this fact is by itself sufficient to prove 
 that the body of an animal has its own innate laws, which 
 regulate its development ; for this kind of correspondence 
 technically called " bilateral symmetry " shows itself not 
 only in these familiar conditions, but in the effects of disease 
 and in very peculiar structures found in some exceptional 
 species of animals. Indeed, on the hypothesis that a blood- 
 relationship of descent binds together different kinds of 
 animals, nature actually forces upon us the perception that 
 new and more intensely marked forms of bilateral symmetry 
 
286 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 have arisen in a space of time which, geologically considered, 
 must be called brief. Thus, naturalists now are generally 
 agreed that birds have descended from reptiles; but the 
 very diversity of the bilateral symmetry which exists be- 
 tween the two wings of birds on the one part, and between 
 their two legs on the other part, is far more striking than 
 any which is found in their hypothetical progenitors. 
 
 Another form of bodily symmetry in animals is known as 
 " serial symmetry." Such symmetry is most plainly seen 
 and obvious in the successively similar segments and pairs 
 of limbs in the centipede and its allies; but it is also to be 
 traced in the bony structure of the human chest, with its 
 successive ribs, in the series of bones (called vertebrae) which 
 compose our spinal column or backbone, and in the resem- 
 blances which can be traced between the arm and the leg and 
 between the hand and the foot. 
 
 A vast number of instances of variations which have ap- 
 peared suddenly have recently been brought forward in a 
 very interesting and important work. 1 It has been sought 
 to lessen the value of these instances on the ground that the 
 great majority of them may be called " monstrosities." 
 But this effort shows much shallowness of mind on the part 
 of those who made it. For what, after all, is the real nature 
 of these variations ? However they may merit to be called 
 
 monstrosities," as structures out of harmony with the 
 whole whereof they form a part, they are, almost all of 
 them, orderly and perfect in themselves. They eloquently 
 proclaim that organic nature is not a passive mass of matter, 
 devoid of innate laws of self-regulation, but that every frag- 
 ment of it, even each of its very aberrations, is replete with 
 order of its own kind and in its due degree. 
 
 It is impossible to have somewhat widely studied the 
 
 1 Materials for the Study of Variation, by William Bateson, M.A. Lon- 
 don, 1892. 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 287 
 
 science of zoology or that of botany without being impressed 
 with the plain fact that considerable or small gaps between 
 the various kinds of living creatures are manifest on all sides. 
 The existing creation is plainly discontinuous, not only in 
 the inorganic world, but also in that which is organic, how- 
 ever much its gaps may be filled up by the discovery of the 
 remains of organisms which exist no longer. 
 
 That they could ever be entirely filled up had we full 
 cognisance of every form of life which has passed away, can- 
 not certainly be affirmed with reasonable confidence when 
 we reflect on the great facts of discontinuity to which we 
 before called attention. 1 
 
 There is, in the first place, the chasm which exists between 
 everything which lives and all that is devoid of life. Grant- 
 ing that the universe may have had such a constitution that, 
 upon the occurrence of certain conditions, life (which pre- 
 viously existed in potentia] should suddenly manifest itself, 
 such a possible process of evolution does not make it less 
 the fact that for all our experience no life arises save from 
 what already lives, and could never come to be save through 
 some adequate cause. 
 
 Secondly, there is the chasm between everything which 
 feels and all that is devoid of sensation. Everyone must 
 admit that this chasm exists everyone, that is, who is not 
 prepared to affirm that the pen he writes with and the ink 
 he uses are not both sentient existences. 
 
 For ourselves, we are profoundly convinced that we cause 
 no pang when we pluck an apple from a tree, and that we 
 may send grain to the mill with a perfectly good conscience. 
 
 But if the living world enables us to understand these two 
 great instances of discontinuity, that world, when we include 
 men within it, makes us aware of a chasm much greater 
 still : we mean the chasm which yawns between every being 
 
 1 See ante, p. 213. 
 
288 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 capable of self-consciousness and a recognition that some 
 things are true and some actions laudable, and all that is 
 devoid of self-conscious life. 
 
 The laws which we have seen to be impressed, not only 
 upon mineral species, but also upon structure as known to 
 us in plants and animals, though they cannot be said to 
 coincide with the dictates of human reason, yet proclaim 
 order as innate in the world so far as it is known to us; and 
 law and order are certainly akin to intelligence taken in the 
 broadest significance we can assign to it. 
 
 We have briefly considered certain facts concerning the 
 inorganic and organic worlds, but to form any satisfactory 
 conception of either, it is necessary to take into our con- 
 sideration, as best we may, the entire cosmos as one whole. 
 
 Preceding considerations must, we think, make it plain to 
 every thoughtful mind possessing a somewhat wide grasp of 
 science, that the universe does not consist of an unordered 
 flux of amorphous matter. 
 
 So much is evident, a posteriori. Experience and science 
 show that something analogous to reason, as we know it, 
 pervades the great whole, the existence of which is revealed 
 to us by the synthesis of our mental powers. 
 
 Can we gain any further light as to this matter by a priori 
 reasoning ? 
 
 We saw in our last chapter that the law of causation is a 
 primary, universal, and self-evident objective truth, which 
 declares that there must be a cause for every change which 
 takes place, for every new existence which comes into being 
 (an extreme form of "change"), for the special concrete 
 conditions of whatever exists, and for the very existence of 
 anything which has not within itself a sufficient reason for 
 its being. We also saw J that science is continually occupied 
 with investigations concerning causes. 
 
 1 See ante, p. 255. 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 289 
 
 But the world is in a condition of incessant change, and 
 new existences are constantly arising within it. The entire 
 universe known to us is also incessantly changing, and new 
 conditions are incessantly arising, for the planetary and 
 sidereal bodies are never for two instants in the same relat- 
 ive positions, and, apparently, their relative position of any 
 one moment never recurs, but is ceaselessly replaced by 
 another altogether novel. 
 
 That each and every one of these changes, new collo- 
 cations, and new existences must have had its causes 
 its group of causes cannot be denied; and more and 
 more of these are every day being discovered by men of 
 science. 
 
 But putting aside now all questions as to the causes of 
 existences and changes considered individually or in groups, 
 how about the universe considered as one great, unimagin- 
 ably complex whole ? In the first place, does reason abso- 
 lutely show that it must have had a beginning ? That our 
 own world, her sister planets, and our whole solar system 
 must have had a beginning can hardly be questioned ; but 
 it does not seem necessarily thence to follow that the same 
 must be said of the whole cosmos. It certainly is not evi- 
 dent to us that the cosmos, considered as one vast unity, 
 must have had a beginning, or need ever come to an end. 
 For all we see, the universe may constitute a true system of 
 perpetual motion in one of two ways. It may be conceived 
 of (i) as eternally passing, as one whole, from a state of 
 nebula to that of suns, with their attendant planets, their 
 satellites, etc., and thence backwards to a state of nebula 
 once more, and so alternating in one unending rhythm, un- 
 ceasingly pulsating to and from a nebular condition, for 
 ever and ever ; or (2) as undergoing such changes partially, 
 at one time here, at another time there, such a change eter- 
 nally creeping, as it were, over the face of the cosmos, so 
 
THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 that each part in turn, but never the whole simultaneously, 
 may undergo such a transformation. 
 
 Such conditions, for anything that reason can affirm with 
 certainty, might be eternal as the result of an eternal arrange- 
 ment or collocation of causal agencies and conditions. 
 
 As we before pointed out, 1 our reason by no means affirms 
 that everything must have a cause, but only changes, new 
 existences, and existences which do not contain within 
 themselves any sufficient reasons for their being. 
 
 Now if the universe ever had a beginning, it must evi- 
 dently have had a cause. If it never had a beginning, it 
 must as a whole have eternally been what we now see it to 
 be, substantially, whatever the succession of changes in its 
 various parts. It could never have had the form of one 
 universally diffused and everywhere similar substance, unless 
 it had been acted on from without by something external to 
 itself. The attribute of instability applied to the conception 
 of a homogeneous universe could not, as has been most ab- 
 surdly supposed, account for the development of the uni- 
 verse from a primitively simple condition. The term 
 " instability " is a mere abstract term denoting the quality, 
 as such, of what is unstable. But whatever is unstable is 
 not thereby endowed with any active power; it is merely 
 easily upset and disturbed by anything external to it. Any- 
 thing quite homogeneous might be unstable to the most 
 extreme degree possible, and yet remain absolutely un- 
 changed forever if nothing external ever came to act upon 
 it. It must be an action from without, since in a universe 
 absolutely homogeneous no possible change could ever take 
 place from within. For whatever is thus homogeneous must 
 be everywhere identical in the mode of its being and activ- 
 ity, and therefore could never change of itself unless it were 
 pervaded by some existence really distinct from it, change 
 
 1 See ante, p. 255. 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 2gi 
 
 produced by which, though materially an action from within, 
 would be essentially an action from without namely, the 
 action of something distinct from and external to it in 
 nature and being. 
 
 One most important consequence follows from the fact 
 that the universe is necessarily one. Since the universe em- 
 braces all that we know now or can conceive of as hereafter 
 to be discovered, it is all-embracing. Were it not this, it 
 could not be the universe. 
 
 Now, since the universe is thus one, it could never it- 
 self have been evolved by any process of " natural selec- 
 tion." An eternal universe could never have been naturally 
 selected that is, have proved itself, through competition, 
 to have been a universe able to survive others, since it 
 never could have had any competitor. Therefore, if the 
 universe is eternal, it must have existed from all eternity 
 in the multiform complexity in which we know it now to 
 be. 
 
 On this account, reason postulates a cause for the universe, 
 considered as one whole, even though it were eternal. A 
 cause is required to account for the special orderly condi- 
 tions, and the definite actions of the multitudes of secondary 
 causes it contains, the specific laws of the bodies and sub- 
 stances which enter into its composition, and the peculiar 
 collocations of the substances, causes, and conditions which 
 pervade it. For the material universe cannot be shown to 
 contain within itself any sufficient cause for its existence 
 for its existence as it exists and in no other mode. An eter- 
 nal complex mixture of different substances, with very 
 different powers, all harmoniously co-ordinated, and which 
 were never otherwise than harmoniously co-ordinated, could 
 not evidently contain within itself the sufficient cause for its 
 own existence ; and the greater the number of the natural 
 laws which physical science reveals to us, thus acting in har- 
 
THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 mony, so much the more does reason make evident to us 
 the necessity for one great integrating and pervading cause 
 sustaining that harmony unchanged. Such a cause is neces- 
 sary for the existence of the universe at all, and however 
 far back the duration of such a universe be supposed to ex- 
 tend, even to eternity, so far back must the duration of its 
 cause evidently extend. 
 
 The existence and operation of that cause can be no 
 more dispensed with at one epoch than at another, and so 
 backwards for an eternity of duration. Hence, an ever- 
 present, constantly causing, and everywhere active and 
 sustaining principle must endure and energise now, as in the 
 past, and forever onwards for a future eternity, should the 
 universe persist eternally under the same laws. 
 
 As to that cause we can, in some respects, judge of its 
 nature from its effects, since a cause must, as we have seen, 1 
 always be at least adequate to produce the effects it causes. 
 As we said before, ' ' Nemo dat quod non habet, ' ' and what 
 experience and reason combined assure us is true with every 
 portion of the universe open to our examination, reason de- 
 clares to us no less necessary when applied to the universe 
 considered as one whole. 
 
 What, then, do our powers of sense-perception, observation, 
 experimentation, reasoning, and intuition, combine to assure 
 us respecting the nature of the causal principle underlying 
 and pervading the entire cosmos? No student of science 
 can dispute that our faculties combine to bear witness to the 
 universal prevalence throughout it of an unceasing uniform- 
 ity and a definite order. We know it to be not a chaos but 
 a cosmos, possessing such a uniformity, with respect to all 
 the different successions and co-existences within it, as to 
 be not inaptly termed a universe governed by natural laws 
 that expression serving conveniently to summarise all the 
 
 1 See ante, p. 262. 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 293 
 
 various uniformities of orderly successions and co-existences 
 which have been observed within it. 
 
 Though the order which we thus see pervade the organic 
 and inorganic worlds alike, does not clearly proclaim the 
 existence throughout the irrational universe of an intelligence 
 in a certain extent analogous to the reason of man, there is, 
 nevertheless, an unmistakable congruity between order and 
 intelligence, such that it becomes impossible to regard any- 
 thing non-intelligent as the dominating causal principle. 
 Not only would it be a verbal contradiction, but it would 
 contradict the evidence which science affords us on every 
 side, to proclaim " unreason " as pervading the orderly uni- 
 verse, which is made known to us by physics and biology, 
 quite apart from any consideration of man and of his works. 
 But when we add the consideration of human faculty to the 
 other powers and existences we know the cosmos to possess, 
 it must assume an altogether different character in our eyes. 
 So considered, its causal principle must be indeed a rational 
 principle, since it has been adequate to be the cause of the 
 reason and intellect of man. 
 
 Human beings, whatever the feebleness, follies, and de- 
 
 [ : fects of multitudes of them, are, nevertheless, endowed with 
 
 the wonderful power of knowing their own existence, of re- 
 flecting on it and on the universe which is their abode, and 
 of recognising abysses of space and time far exceeding the 
 
 \ utmost possible powers of their imagination. Man can 
 
 apprehend existence and non-existence, necessity, impossi- 
 bility, and contingency, and, most wonderful of all, he can 
 perceive truth as such, the existence and bearings of object- 
 ive relations and verities, which are absolute and necessary, 
 recognising them, meantime, for what they truly are. 
 
 The adequate cause and principle of a nature thus endowed 
 must possess powers indefinitely exceeding that human 
 reason which it has called into being. It must be intelli- 
 
294 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 gent, not only beyond all our possible powers of imagina- 
 tion, but beyond all human conception. For the special 
 character of those primary and fundamental principles of 
 our intelligence which we have passed in review, is that they 
 need no proof, being self-evident in and by themselves, 
 while they constitute the indispensable foundation of all 
 proof whatever it may be. Such primary principles may be 
 said to be rays of light which radiate into our intellect from 
 a source which is entirely hidden from our direct mental 
 gaze, and only to be imperfectly apprehended through 
 meditation, reflection, and inference. Truth being the cor- 
 respondence of thought with things, what must be that 
 hidden cause in a correspondence with which the truth of 
 all our highest, ultimate, and most certain intellectual prin- 
 ciples consists ? 
 
 After pondering over the fact that the cause of the uni- 
 verse is the cause of all truth and of all the knowledge to 
 which it is possible for us to attain, it seems impossible to 
 regard it as other than an eternal and ever-present reason 
 latent in all the phenomena of which we can take cognisance. 
 If, then, we turn back our mental gaze over the devious 
 path we have traversed, and survey it in the light thus 
 gained, an important consequence appears necessarily to 
 follow. 
 
 We have considered, in successive chapters, a variety of 
 intervals, breaches of continuity, and fresh departures which 
 have now and again occurred in nature. We have taken note 
 of the gap between the non-living and the living, the insen- 
 tient and the sentient, the irrational and the rational. But 
 these breaches of continuity present a difficulty and seem 
 repugnant to the mind of the modern student of nature. It 
 needs the distinct recognition of a profound and pervading 
 reason, as underlying and governing nature, satisfactorily to 
 do away with such difficulty and repugnance, and to enable 
 
CAUSES OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE 2$$ 
 
 us to apprehend how such difficulty and repugnance may be 
 merely due to the impotence of our imagination to picture 
 to itself how such new departures could ever have taken 
 place. We must frankly concede the utter impossibility of 
 any imagination thereof, while at the same time recognising 
 once more the important truth that our inability to imagine 
 anything is no necessary bar to our conception of it or to 
 our perception that what is unimaginable is none the less 
 necessarily true and certain. 
 
 Other marvels which have similarly tried our imaginative 
 powers have been the varied instincts wherewith so many 
 animals are endowed, and the first occurrence of the exter- 
 nal expression of abstract ideas by human gestures and vocal 
 utterances. But a cause replete with intelligence as well as 
 power, may serve perfectly well to assure us that however 
 little we can picture such energies to our mental vision, the 
 determination of blind psychical energies and of spontaneous 
 intelligent efforts, resulting in the external manifestation 
 of new-born ideas (language), forms part, and a rational 
 part, of that wonderful complexity of activities of the most 
 diverse natures and degrees, which together compose the 
 wondrous cosmos, the gradual and patient comprehension 
 and explanation (so far as possible) of which it is the task of 
 science to pursue. It is its most noble task gradually, and 
 step by step, to make more and more plainly manifest to 
 the reason of man that intelligence (not only unimaginable 
 but inconceivable) which seems latent in the cosmos, and 
 to reveal itself diversely in the manifold aspects of the uni- 
 verse of which it is, in our eyes, the evident and ultimate 
 cause. 
 
CHAPTER X 
 
 THE NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF 
 SCIENCE 
 
 THE various preliminary inquiries and considerations, 
 which it has appeared to us necessary to make or en- 
 tertain before addressing ourselves to the main question, 
 having been now disposed of, we will endeavour to draw out 
 what appears to us to be the answer to that main question 
 the question, namely, What is the groundwork of science ? 
 
 As we said in the beginning of this book, we selected for 
 our title the phrase " groundwork of science " because its 
 object was to examine the essential nature of the efforts 
 of scientific workers, of the tools they have to use, as well 
 as of that which constitutes their field of labour. 
 
 The question, then, as to what is the nature of the 
 groundwork of science resolves itself into the three sub- 
 ordinate questions : 
 
 (1) What is the nature of that field wherein scientific 
 labourers have to work : what is the matter of science ? 
 
 (2) What are the tools which it is absolutely necessary for 
 such workers to make use of in their labour ? 
 
 (3) What must be the nature and qualifications of the 
 workers themselves in order that they may be able to obtain 
 good results from their labour ? 
 
 Assuming the validity of our contention that we possess 
 an intuition of the extended, we have seen that the matter 
 
 296 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 297 
 
 of science consists of two divisions: (a) a division made 
 up of what is physical and material, and (b) a division 
 made up of what is mental and ideal. 
 
 The first division includes all extended bodies and their 
 energies ; for no concrete existence can possibly be merely 
 passive, but must actively respond to stimuli (as iron to the 
 blacksmith's hammer) according to definite internal laws, 
 by which powers and activities it is we recognise the nature 
 of each such concrete existence. 
 
 Some readers may object to our subdivision of the matter 
 of science on the ground that we have assigned no place to 
 entities of such supreme importance as the various physical 
 energies. 
 
 We have not, however, really omitted them, for we in- 
 clude them amongst the active powers of material bodies. 
 We have no experience of any physical energy save in con- 
 nection with some extended substance from which it is 
 sometimes said to emanate, and thence to be transmitted to 
 others. But the terms energy, force, light, heat, sound, 
 etc., are but so many abstract terms. We have no evidence 
 that they can really denote " substances," but only certain 
 real actions of real bodies considered in the abstract. Thus 
 light and heat are commonly thought of as set going on 
 their radiant but very unequal course by the fires of the sun 
 (as one source), and thence transmitted by the universally 
 disposed ether to the surrounding bodies of the solar system 
 beyond. Similarly, the vibratory agitation of some sensu- 
 ous body sets going corresponding vibrations in the air, 
 which may ultimately cause similar agitations within the 
 ears of men and animals, so giving rise ultimately to what 
 we know as " sounds." 
 
 This way of speaking of the transmission of energies has 
 not unnaturally arisen from the discovery of what was 
 originally termed " the correlation of the physical forces," 
 
298 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 in other words, the discovery of the quantitative equivalence 
 which exists between the different kinds of actions which 
 different bodies exhibit, as, e. g., between heat, light, 
 chemical action, motion, etc. 
 
 But though it is convenient to express such definitely cor- 
 relative actions of different kinds in terms of persistent 
 " energy," and of different kinds of persistent energy, yet 
 all the physical phenomena capable of expression in such 
 terms may also be described in terms denoting the existence 
 of real bodies exercising real activities in different modes. 
 The conception of the same, or of different bodies being 
 successively affected, and acting successively in different 
 manners, with a quantitative equivalence between the modes 
 of their affection and activity, seems a sufficient conception 
 to apply to the mechanism and action of a moving body 
 (e. g., a locomotive engine) and one as consonant with the 
 facts as is the conception of a force which is transformed 
 from heat into motion. On the other hand, to speak of 
 energy persisting and being transformed, favours the con- 
 ception of energy as some objectively existing substance, 
 which really passes out of one body and into another, and 
 has a positively enduring, though protean, existence. 
 
 It is often said that bodies may by impact communicate 
 motion, as when one suspended ball, falling against a row 
 of others (suspended so as to be all on the same level), 
 ceases itself to move, while another, the terminal one of the 
 series, begins to be in motion. We have here, however, no 
 real evidence of any " communication " or " transference " 
 of " motion," but only of successive and correlative motions. 
 The above-noted frequent mode of expression shows the 
 existence of a tendency to regard the abstract quality 
 " motion " as a substantial entity, actually passing from 
 one body and into another. 
 
 Thus it has sometimes been said that a coal-bed contains 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 299 
 
 the heat and light of the sun of bygone ages shut up, like 
 enchanted knights, within it, and set free again when that 
 coal comes to be burned. But, in fact, it contains nothing 
 of the kind, but is itself in a state resulting from bygone 
 solar energy, and will under certain circumstances become 
 active in ways similar to the activities of the sun which 
 produced those results in it. 
 
 But the usual mode of scientific expression relating to 
 these various activities of real bodies, as well as the popular 
 way of speaking of light, heat, etc., are, no doubt, con- 
 venient ; and there can be no objection to their use provided 
 only it be fjorne in mind that we have no evidence of 
 these energies being themselves substances, instead of only 
 peculiar modes of diverse action in substances which really 
 exist. It is certainly different real things which are now 
 and again hot, luminous, sonorous, or moving from place 
 to place. 
 
 Such movements are perhaps the commonest of all our 
 experiences, and moving things are constantly said (as we 
 have just remarked) to move from place to place with 
 greater or less rapidity in a longer or shorter space of time. 
 
 It seems to us needful, then, to make a few remarks upon 
 those three universally existing and continually employed 
 conceptions motion, space, and time. 
 
 As to motion, our conception of that idea and our intel- 
 lectual recognition of the motion of moving bodies are both 
 called forth by our sensuous perception of the latter, and 
 mental images of moving objects also sustain that conception 
 after they have been so elicited ; just as our idea of exten- 
 sion is elicited and sustained by parallel sensuous perceptions 
 and imaginations. But when once thus called forth, our 
 idea " motion is a single and primary idea, and cannot be 
 resolved into more fundamental conceptions. 
 
 Now there are no facts of experience which have been, 
 
30O THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 and are more frequent with all of us than movements, 
 especially relative changes of place of solid bodies. 
 
 We have that experience in every movement of our own 
 frame, either in its change of place as a whole, or in the 
 movements of its various parts. Every breeze which sways 
 the smallest branches of a tree, or but makes its leaves to 
 vibrate, reveals it to us. Every cloud we see blown across 
 the sky and every dust-eddy gives us that experience. By 
 movements, the dawning human intellect is first aroused to 
 activity as the infant notices the movements and gestures 
 of those around it, and the movements it can itself impart 
 to objects it begins to grasp or kick against. * In boyhood 
 the throwing of stones or balls, the movements of marbles, 
 the spinning of tops, and all games up to football and 
 cricket, continually reinforce the experiences gained at the 
 dawn of mental life. 
 
 Indeed, the motion of solid bodies is the most primitive, 
 most constant, and most universal of all our experiences. 
 Thus the abstract idea " motion " comes most readily be- 
 fore the mind, and at first it seems that nothing can be 
 easier than to understand the movements of bodies, and 
 what is meant by the term denoting that idea. And for 
 most purposes of science an apprehension of that ordinary 
 meaning is aimply sufficient ; but here, including as we do, 
 and must do, in our purview the science of sciences, we 
 think it incumbent on us to endeavour to draw out more 
 carefully the significance of the idea with which we are now 
 concerned. 
 
 When we proceed to study our conception of motion, 
 various difficulties and problems present themselves for solu- 
 tion. Obviously, any given object, e. g. , a feather blown 
 by the wind, must be one and the same thing when so pro- 
 pelled as when resting on the ground. Nevertheless, it is 
 no less obviously in a different state when in motion from 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 301 
 
 that in which it is when at rest. What, then, do we really 
 mean by its " motion " ? As we have said, that term is 
 abstract, and therefore what it denotes cannot really exist 
 in the concrete; yet there must be some concrete reality 
 which is the foundation of that abstraction. 
 
 Now in all our experience, whatever has moved has 
 always moved away from the vicinity of something and in 
 the direction of something else. This uniform experience 
 must of course prevent us from being able to imagine motion 
 taking place in any other mode. But can we conceive 
 of its taking place otherwise ? To us it seems perfectly clear 
 that motion must be, not only in some definite direction 
 at each instant, but also from one entity and towards 
 another. 
 
 Some of my readers may think that, were all objects save 
 one annihilated, one might nevertheless traverse space. 
 Now if space were a real, permanent existence, then any 
 object moving through it would of course proceed from the 
 vicinity of one part of it to the vicinity of another portion 
 of space ; but if, as we believe to be the case, there is no 
 such thing as " space " at all, then evidently no object could 
 traverse it, for no object could traverse that which has no 
 existence. 
 
 But if space does not exist, it is evident that the universe, 
 considered as one whole, must be absolutely incapable of 
 motion, save internally. Such is the case, since the uni- 
 verse must contain everything, or it would not be the 
 universe; and therefore there can be nothing for it to 
 approach or recede from. 
 
 Thus motion is, or includes, a relation of one body to 
 another or to other bodies. But can this be all ? Can 
 there be nothing more objective in motion ? 
 
 We have seen the wide-spread tendency which exists to 
 speak of the physical energies as if they were material sub- 
 
3O2 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 stances. Is this the result of a pure delusion, or can there 
 be a true and valid objective foundation for it ? 
 
 Evidently motion, heat, light, etc., cannot be so many 
 material substances co-existing beside, or within, any 
 moving, hot, or luminous body. The days of " phlogiston " 
 are at an end. But is it possible that they may each sever- 
 ally be a manifestation of some immaterial constituent of 
 bodies ? 
 
 Every material body known to us we know through some 
 power or quality which we perceive it to possess, whereby 
 we also distinguish it from other bodies. But the active 
 powers which thus pervade material bodies are no more 
 themselves material than are motion, light, and heat. 
 
 But what is matter ? It is an entity perceived intellectu- 
 ally by the aid of our sensitivity, and constituting those 
 substantial objects of which our senses take cognisance. 
 Through our sense-perceptions the intellect acquires an in- 
 tuition, not only of extended bodies, but also of matter, as, 
 at least in part, composing them. Yet though matter is 
 thus constantly and familiarly known as existing in bodies, 
 pure and simple, " matter " itself remains unknown, and 
 has never been revealed to any man, and shows no signs of 
 existing in rerum naturd. 
 
 What we always perceive is matter of one or another 
 definite kind. It is always a " sort of matter," and never 
 simply" matter," which we come to know. Matter seems 
 never to exist unmodified, though it abounds in unimagin- 
 able transformations of material substances of all kinds. 
 
 Thus every material body or substance known to us seems 
 to consist of something corresponding with our idea of mat- 
 ter, and something immaterial some energy existing with 
 the matter whereby that body or substance comes to possess 
 and exercise those active powers which make it known to us 
 as being whatever kind of body or substance it may happen 
 
NA TURE OF THE GRO UND WORK OF SCIENCE 303 
 
 to be that immaterial constituent being the active and 
 dominant principle. But we do not by any means intend 
 to assert that this view is an absolutely certain and evident 
 one. We nevertheless regard it as highly probable, and we 
 think it not unlikely that this may be the truth which the 
 system of Monism shadows forth, as it seems to us, imper- 
 fectly and irrationally. 
 
 We have spoken of any motion of the universe in its en- 
 tirety as being an impossibility. Some of our readers may 
 exclaim, " This is, indeed, impossible, because the universe 
 is, and must be, infinite." But this is an utter mistake, 
 and one due to that inveterate slavery of the reason to the 
 imagination under which so many persons even some men 
 of science seem content to remain. 
 
 We have never seen anything with nothing beyond it, and 
 therefore, try as we may, we can never imagine a final limit 
 outside which nothing is or can be. We cannot imagine a 
 boundary line over which no arm could be thrust, and be- 
 yond which no glance even could ever be cast. Such being 
 the case, it is, and must be, an utterly futile attempt to im- 
 agine the universe as terminated, and without any possibil- 
 ity of existence beyond it. But our impotence to imagine 
 the universe as finite is no reason whatever for thinking that 
 finite it cannot be. 
 
 Passing now from the consideration of the extent of the 
 universe, it seems needful to say a few words with respect 
 to prevalent conceptions respecting its composition, what 
 may be the ultimate nature of all the various activities it 
 manifests, and whether they can be resolved into one funda- 
 mental activity. 
 
 Nothing is more marked, or more remarkable, than the 
 tendency of many scientific men to try to describe all 
 other phenomena in terms of motion, and especially by the 
 motion of minute moving particles. This may be in terms 
 
304 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 of such moving particles, " molecular motion," or a" dance 
 of atoms," of a differently complex pattern in each case, 1 
 or it may be in terms of brain waves or thrills traversing 
 the nerves, in the case of feelings or of thoughts. A me- 
 chanical explanation of all nature is an avowed ideal with 
 many men, and is felt as a comfort by very many more. 
 So wide-spread a tendency must be due to no less wide- 
 spread a cause, and it is a fact that men do feel a certain 
 satisfaction and mental rest in such an interpretation of 
 phenomena of all orders, from physical energies to feelings 
 and thoughts. What, then, may be the reason for this 
 
 1 A striking example of this tendency has been shown by Professor Haeckel, 
 who ventures to describe atoms as if he had actually seen and handled them. 
 He tells us that (in his Monism, pp. 26 and 32 of the English Translation, 
 Adam and Charles Black, 1894) : " To these original or mass atoms the ulti- 
 mate discrete particles of inert ' ponderable ' matter we can with more or less 
 probability ascribe a number of eternal and inalienable fundamental attributes ; 
 they are probably everywhere in space of like magnitude and constitution. Al- 
 though possessing a very definite finite magnitude, they are, by virtue of their 
 very nature, indivisible. Their shape we may take to be spherical ; they are 
 inert (in the physical sense), unchangeable, inelastic, and impenetrable by the 
 ether. Apart from the attribute of inertia, the most important characteristic of 
 these ultimate atoms is their chemical affinity their tendency to apply them- 
 selves to one another and combine in small groups in an orderly fashion. These 
 fixed groups ... of primitive atoms are the atoms of the elements the 
 well-known ' indivisible' atoms of chemistry, the qualitative, and, so far as our 
 present empirical knowledge goes, unchangeable distinctions of our chemical 
 elements are therefore solely conditioned by the varying number and disposition 
 of the similar primitive atoms of which they are composed." As to the most 
 remote past, he speaks of "An unbroken series of natural events following an 
 orderly course of evolution according to fixed laws . . . from a primeval 
 chaos to the present ' order of the cosmos.' At the outset, there is nothing in 
 infinite space but mobile elastic ether and innumerable similar separate particles, 
 the primitive atoms, scattered throughout it in the form of dust ; perhaps these 
 are themselves originally ' points of condensation' of the vibrating ' substance,' 
 the remainder of which constitute the ether. The atoms of our elements arise 
 from the grouping together in definite numbers of the primitive atoms or atoms 
 of mass." 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 305 
 
 feeling of satisfaction in the explanation of matters the most 
 diverse by a conception of solid bodies in motion? 
 
 As we have pointed out in preceding chapters, we can 
 imagine nothing except what our senses have previously 
 experienced either as a whole or in its constituent parts. 
 This close connection between experience and imagination 
 has for its consequence the following law of association : 
 
 Facts of experience are reproduced in our imagination 
 with the greater ease and readiness the more frequently or 
 continuously they have been experienced by us. 
 
 But we have just seen l how movements of solid bodies 
 constitute the most constant and universal of all our experi- 
 ences. What wonder, then, that a sense of ease and pleasur- 
 able relief should be felt whenever difficult and puzzling 
 phenomena of any kind can be presented to the intellect in 
 terms and by the aid of mental images of moving solid 
 bodies. 
 
 It should also be recollected that few things are more 
 familiar to us than the experience that objects of consider- 
 able size can mostly be broken, cut, or crushed by us into 
 smaller portions, and these again similarly further sub- 
 divided. It is a most common experience also to see sub- 
 stances crushed into very small particles (sand, dust, or what 
 not) particles so small that we are unable to subdivide them 
 any further. Hence a vague feeling can be produced of a 
 distinctness in nature between large bodies that we can sub- 
 divide and possessing obvious qualities, and minute particles 
 which we cannot so act upon, and of which we can detect 
 hardly any qualities particles only just within the range of 
 our vision. In this way an imagination easily and spontane- 
 ously arises of large bodies being made up of minute solid 
 particles incapable of smaller subdivision which, by their 
 union and coherence, compose such bodies. 
 
 1 See ante, p. 300. 
 
306 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 Through a combination of these multitudinous and con- 
 tinual experiences, the tendency has arisen (probably ages 
 before Democritus), still exists, and will, most likely, ever 
 exist, to try to represent all the phenomena of the world 
 by mental images of particles in motion, and by dances of 
 atoms. 
 
 We do not, of course, for one moment, mean to underrate 
 the enormous value and practical utility of working hypo- 
 theses such as the " atomic theory, " the " undulatory theory 
 of light," of vibrating ethereal vortex rings, etc., etc. Our 
 only intention is to point out that such theories are to be 
 recognised for what they really are, and not regarded, as is 
 too frequently the case, as absolute truths, really evident, 
 explaining satisfactorily the phenomena of nature, and con- 
 stituting an important part of the real matter of science, and 
 as truths which have been shown to be finally and absolutely 
 evident. The futility of such explanations may easily be 
 seen by thinking of such ultimate atoms as magnified to 
 inches in diameter. Then all the difficulties which we can 
 feel as to the ultimate composition of larger bodies, will be 
 found to be no less existent as regards the molecules and 
 atoms themselves. 
 
 Leaving now the subject of motion, and proceeding to 
 consider the truth as to space and time, we again meet with 
 the deluding consequences of uniform sensuous experience 
 upon the imagination. 
 
 Now (as we said when speaking of the supposed -necessary 
 infinity of the universe), no man, anywhere or anywhen, has 
 ever met with an object which has not got some other object 
 beyond it. No man, also, has ever found anything to hap- 
 pen without finding that something else happened after it. 
 It results from this constant and invariable experience that 
 it is utterly impossible for us to imagine anything to exist 
 without something beyond it, or to imagine anything to 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 307 
 
 happen without something, sooner or later, happening after 
 it. 
 
 Thus it is that men who have not emancipated themselves 
 from the chains of their sense-perceptions, declare, as we 
 above observed, that " space " is, and must be, " infinite." 
 Mistaking the impotence of their imagination for a percep- 
 tion of objective reality, they affirm the real, and even in- 
 finite, existence of what has no real being at all, and is 
 nothing in reality beyond a creation of the mind. 
 
 Space is but an abstraction from abstractions a doubly 
 abstract idea. There is, of course, no such thing even as 
 " extension " as such. That is but an abstract idea gained 
 from a perception of that property which every extended 
 thing possesses, and which real objective property is the 
 foundation in the thing itself of the abstract idea exten- 
 sion. Similarly, " space is an abstract idea drawn from 
 the different extensions of all the extended things we know, 
 from inter-sidereal ether to the densest mass of metal. It 
 is, as we said, a doubly abstract idea, and is abstracted 
 from, and denotes the extension of, all extended things 
 taken together, and united in one highly abstract idea. 
 
 ' Time " is, similarly, but another highly abstract idea 
 gained from things which succeed each other, and which 
 are said to follow each other " in succession." But, of 
 course, there is and can be no such thing as " succession " 
 by itself. Succession is but a term expressing our idea of a 
 real condition possessed by each thing which happens after 
 another which occurred before, and which condition is the 
 foundation in the thing itself of that abstract idea. Simi- 
 larly, " time " is a doubly abstract idea, since it is drawn 
 from the different successions of all the succeeding things 
 we know. It denotes the succession of all succeeding things 
 taken together and united in one highly abstract idea. 
 
 Of course, for ordinary scientific work, the common con- 
 
308 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 ceptions as to space and time, as well as motion, molar 
 and molecular, ethereal undulations, etc., serve every need- 
 ful purpose, and are most valuable, just as the commonly 
 used physical hypotheses as to atoms, molecules, etc., serve, 
 as before said, very important ends, and have greatly aided, 
 as they no doubt will continue to be of great service 
 to, scientific progress. But as with respect to these hypo- 
 theses, so also with respect to space and time, it seems to 
 us we cannot be dispensed, in a work such as the present 
 one, from an attempt to analyse those common motions as 
 fully as it is within our power to do. 
 
 The physical division of the matter of science may, then, 
 be described as follows : 
 
 It consists of real, substantial things in themselves, with 
 all their qualities, powers, and energies, inorganic and or- 
 ganic, vegetable, animal, including rational animals (men) 
 as well as the merely sentient portion of animal life. 
 Amongst and between different portions of this physical 
 division of the matter of science, we have recognised various 
 branches of continuity various new departures. Our con- 
 fidence in the accuracy of our judgment as to these new de- 
 partures and their rationality, as well as their possibility in 
 the material universe, are guaranteed and rendered as far as 
 possible intelligible to us by our recognition that the uni- 
 verse is pervaded, as it seems to have been and to be caused, 
 by something which our intellect reveals to us as having 
 necessarily some analogy with our own reason and intelli- 
 gence, however inconceivably greater it may be. 
 
 The second division of the matter of science consists of 
 everything psychical, from the faintest and most obscure 
 feelings, which any animated being can experience, to the 
 most abstract ideas that the human mind can possibly form. 
 These feelings and ideas are not regarded, in the work of 
 science, mainly as abstractions, but rather as concrete reali- 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 309 
 
 ties feeljngs as being, or having been, actually felt, and 
 ideas as being, or having been, actually thought. 
 
 The matter of science must consist of these two divisions, 
 which to speak most briefly are composed of things and 
 thoughts. 
 
 For all idealists must regard, and do regard, the groups of 
 psychical modifications, which for them make up the exter- 
 nal world, as distinguishable from that reflex self-conscious- 
 ness which reflects upon its own mental experiences, and 
 apprehends knowledge and truth as knowledge and truth. 
 It is unquestionable, therefore, that things and thoughts 
 constitute, and must constitute, the matter of human science 
 in its widest acceptation of that term. 
 
 Such, then, being the field of labour wherein all pursuers of 
 science have to work, what are the tools which are absolutely 
 necessary for them that they may accomplish their task ? 
 
 Now, obviously, the simplest and earliest used of these 
 tools are our various organs of sense, by the use of which 
 alone we can attain to sense-perceptions, which together 
 form the indispensable starting-point of all our knowledge, 
 and which supply us with materials necessary for the exer- 
 cise of the imagination, without the presence of which all 
 intellectual activity is impossible. 
 
 To these, of course, must be added all those common 
 those normal intellectual powers, the due exercise of which 
 constitutes a man a person of ordinary sound judgment and 
 good sense. 
 
 Amongst and bound up with these intellectual faculties r 
 however, are certain fundamental principles which constitute 
 our intellectual tools par excellence, and which here need 
 distinct recognition. We have seen in our fourth chapter 
 (" The Methpds of Science ") how utterly impossible it is 
 not only to cultivate science, but even to make one valid 
 observation, or usefully to carry on the simplest experiment, 
 
310 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 without the tacit assumption of certain fundamental princi- 
 ples as convictions implicitly accepted. Such convictions 
 were : the existence of certainty ' ; the existence of an exter- 
 nal world a ; our continuous substantial existence 3 ; the valid- 
 ity of the process of inference 4 ; the self-evidence of some 
 truths 6 ; the principle of contradiction 6 ; the evidence of 
 axioms 7 ; the principle of causation 8 ; the uniformity of 
 nature"; and the existence of necessity and contingency. 10 
 After what has been said in Chapter VIII. about these first 
 principles of .knowledge of which our highest mental powers 
 take cognisance, we think that we need not occupy much 
 more space concerning them here, but only give once more 
 a brief summary thereof. 
 
 The fundamental truths, the intellectual perceptions and 
 convictions which must be employed for the cultivation of 
 science may, then, be thus summarised : 
 
 (1) The first intellectual tool which must be employed is 
 the principle which affirms that certain things can be per- 
 ceived with certainty and are evident. 
 
 (2) The second principle is that nothing can both exist 
 and not exist at the same time, and this principle serves to 
 test the solidity of the work which the first tool enables the 
 scientific labourer to perform. 
 
 (3) Thirdly comes the perception and conviction (for 
 which the second principle vouches) that there are truths 
 which are true, not only here and now, but which must be 
 true ever and always, and that such truths are not merely 
 laws or conditions of our own mind, but are true objectively, 
 being applicable to and valid for all " things in themselves " 
 apart from the existence of any imaginable mind. 
 
 1 See ante, p. 98. 6 See ante, p. 103. 9 See ante, p. 106. 
 
 8 See ante, p. 101. See ante, p. 105. 10 See ante, p. 106. 
 
 3 See ante, p. 101. 7 See ante, p. 105. 
 
 4 See ante, p. 102. 8 See ante, p. 105. 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 311 
 
 (4) Thus it is clear that there are objective relations, cor- 
 responding with subjective ones. 
 
 (5) The perception and conviction that not only our 
 actions, sensations, imaginations, reminiscences, emotions, 
 perceptions, and conceptions, are known to us, but also our 
 own substantial and continuous personal existence. 
 
 (6) The perception and conviction that we have the faculty 
 of knowing not only present external existences but what is 
 external to our present experience, memory showing us such 
 experience and enabling us to recognise it as such, so that 
 in each of us subject and object become identified. 
 
 (7) We must also make use of the principle which upholds 
 and supports the process of inference or reasoning, namely, 
 the perception that if certain premisses be true, then what- 
 ever logically follows from them must be true likewise. 
 
 (8) Finally, there is the principle of causation, which 
 assures us that every new existence, state, or condition, and 
 every existence which does not contain the principle of its 
 being within itself, demands a cause for its existence. 
 
 It is these fundamental truths which constitute the intel- 
 lectual instruments, by the use of which all science that now 
 exists has been elaborated, and which must be employed to 
 develop whatever scientific truths shall hereafter come to 
 be ascertained or established. 
 
 The self-evident, fundamental, and ultimate truths which 
 guarantee and support all our knowledge, are not ideas 
 which are innate, but the faculty of apprehending them is 
 innate. They are ideas which our reason has the power of 
 extracting and of perceiving the self-evidence of, just as the 
 faculties of a mere animal enable it to become aware of suit- 
 able food through its organs of sense when it meets with 
 such, as the roots of a plant enable it to absorb water by 
 growing towards damp earth in its vicinity, and as the 
 nature of a crystal enables it to refract doubly when the re- 
 
312 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 quisite means (certain rays of light) are brought to bear upon 
 it in a suitable manner. 
 
 All the phenomena of nature are alike wonderful, and 
 amongst its wonders is to be ranged our faculty of evolving, 
 by abstraction, perceptions of objective, necessary, and 
 self-evident truths as objective, necessary, and self-evident, 
 when the requisite means (careful attention, i. e., certain 
 beams of intellectual light) are brought to bear upon it. 
 
 As to the eight perceptions and convictions above enumer- 
 ated, unless we really know and trust them, science is logic- 
 ally impossible. Without them (as we have seen in Chapter 
 IV.) it is impossible to have a complete, harmonious, and 
 stable system of knowledge. If these truths were denied, 
 or even really doubted, by anyone, he would necessarily be 
 reduced to a state of mental paralysis and intellectual inani- 
 tion. His intellect, deprived of their aid, would, indeed, 
 not only be paralysed so that it could no further advance, 
 but it would be entirely disintegrated like a world in which 
 the force of gravity had been suddenly annihilated. But 
 because we must (to be rational) recognise the self-evidence 
 and absolute certainty of the fundamental principles of all 
 human knowledge, we must always be extremely careful to 
 be guilty of no exaggeration as to the amount of that know- 
 ledge, but to keep an open mind as to possibilities concern- 
 ing which we have no evidence. However improbable any 
 such possibilities may be, we must be scrupulous in not 
 representing any improbability, however great it may be, as 
 an impossibility. 
 
 Thus as to the structure, composition, or nature of the 
 universe, very divergent conditions are by no means evi- 
 dently impossible. It is, of course, evident that there is an 
 intelligent energy in the universe, because we are conscious 
 of what exists in ourselves our own self-conscious intelli- 
 gence. But it is not impossible (though so improbable that 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 313 
 
 the mere possibility seems hardly worth mentioning) that be- 
 sides intelligent energy, there may be nothing but one 
 essential kind of matter with intrinsic motion, animals 
 having merely the appearance of being sensitive organisms, 
 while in truth literally nothing more than mere machines. 
 The possibility of this cannot be denied for two reasons: 
 
 (1) We can only know our own sensations and emotions 
 through the intellect, so that we cannot be absolutely sure 
 that our higher estimate of animals (as being really sensitive 
 organisms) may not be due to the fact that we know them 
 only intellectually, and so may unconsciously transfigure 
 them. 
 
 (2) We cannot know with certainty what the emotions 
 and sensations of animals really are. They are probably 
 like what our sensations and emotions might be apart from 
 the intellect. But it can never be absolutely evident to us 
 that they are so, or what they are in themselves, or even 
 what our own sensations and emotions may be, apart from 
 our intellect, though, as we have endeavoured to show, 1 
 our intellect enables us to obtain a high degree of probabil- 
 ity in the matter. 
 
 Secondly, it is not evident that the universe may not con- 
 sist of one kind of matter (the parent of all the combinations 
 we know), and one physical energy (the root of the physical 
 energies of our experience), together with an intelligent 
 energy. 
 
 Thirdly, it may consist of one matter and several or many 
 energies, essentially distinct from all eternity, together with 
 intelligent energy. 
 
 Fourthly, it is not evident that it may not be composed 
 of several, or many, essentially distinct matters (true ele- 
 ments) with a physical energy essentially one, together with 
 intelligent energy. 
 
 1 See ante, p. 214. 
 
314 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 Fifthly, it may consist of several or a multitude of distinct 
 elements, together with several or a multitude of essentially 
 distinct energies, and also intelligent energy. 
 
 But it cannot consist of only one kind of energy, even if 
 that energy were mind, because we have an intuition of 
 something extended, and of three dimensions upon which 
 intuition all mathematics repose. 
 
 As to the intelligent energy of the universe, apart from 
 that of its absolute cause, it is conceivable there may be 
 none but what is human; but it is also conceivable that 
 there may be several kinds, or an unimaginable multitude 
 of kinds of intellectual energy, all essentially different from 
 that of man. 
 
 But what, in our opinion, is evidently impossible is the 
 evolution of intellect from mere physical force, above all, 
 the origin therefrom of our ethical intuitions and our con- 
 victions as to necessities and possibilities. 
 
 But for the two reasons given above it cannot be declared 
 absolutely impossible, improbable as it seems to us to be, 
 that life and mere sensitivity should have been evolved 
 from some energy underlying what we know as the physical 
 forces. 
 
 Nor, as we before pointed out, 1 is it impossible that the 
 human intellect may have been evolved from the psychical 
 power of animals if their psychical powers be essentially and 
 potentially intelligent. It is possible that intelligent energy 
 may be latent in animals and only able actually to manifest 
 itself in a manner far below its intrinsic power, and, on ac- 
 count of all the conditions present to it, which render it 
 unable to emerge in thought, into which it would emerge if 
 a suitable environment were provided. But, certainly, ani- 
 mals, so far as we have been able to obtain evidence, show 
 no signs of possessing such a latent intellectuality, while 
 
 1 See ante, p. 154. 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 315 
 
 they often show what, did they possess it, would be a per- 
 fectly amazing degree of stupidity. 
 
 In pursuing our quest of the groundwork of science, if 
 anything is certain/ it is that the portion of truth which we 
 are able to attain to in our investigations of the cosmos is 
 but an unimaginably small portion of the whole. 
 
 There are two facts which the man of science ought to 
 have frequently and clearly before his mind. The first is 
 the practical infinitude of knowledge, as yet unattained by 
 him, and, probably, beyond all human ken. The second 
 fact, and one no less important, is the absolute certainty of 
 that small portion of knowledge which his intellect is able 
 to attain to and recognise as being self-evident, and evi- 
 dently of universal and necessary validity. Because the 
 matter for exploration is indefinitely vast and but partially 
 attainable, we have no reason to distrust our knowledge of 
 what we do perceive to be certain, or to undervalue the 
 means at our disposal for obtaining such scientific knowledge 
 and certainty. The means here referred to consist of first 
 principles which have in these pages been drawn out and 
 enumerated- the tools of which the labourers in the field 
 of science are compelled to make use, and which they should 
 rejoice exceedingly in the possession of. It now only 
 remains to notice some facts and make a few remarks con- 
 cerning the nature of the scientific labourers themselves. 
 
 Uneducated men are often confident of their knowledge 
 in proportion to their ignorance, while the modesty of the 
 cultured is generally not less noteworthy. But whatever 
 diffidence ordinary persons may feel with respect to de- 
 ficiencies in their own knowledge of unfamiliar facts, or of 
 matters of science, they are generally confident enough that 
 they have a sufficient acquaintance with their own nature 
 and those mental faculties which common sense assures 
 them they daily exercise. They may, indeed, be aware 
 
316 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 that it is possible for interest to induce some of their neigh- 
 bours not only to say, but even to think, that " there is 
 nothing like leather, " and they may recognise the fact that 
 an habitual employment of the mind and energies in one 
 special pursuit can prevent men from being able readily to 
 apply themselves to another of a very different kind. Never- 
 theless, as a rule, they have no proximately correct appre- 
 ciation either of the wonderfully lofty nature of their mental 
 powers or of the warping and narrowing effect of prejudice 
 in hampering their exercise. As the late Cardinal Newman 
 truly observed many years ago : 
 
 " Any one study, of whatever kind, exclusively pursued, dead- 
 ens in the mind the interest, nay the perception, of any others. 
 Thus Cicero says that Plato and Demosthenes, Aristotle and 
 Isocrates might have respectively excelled in each other's prov- 
 ince, but that each was absorbed in his own. Specimens of this 
 peculiarity occur every day. You can hardly persuade some 
 men to talk about anything but their own pursuit ; they refer 
 the whole world to their own centre, and measure all matters by 
 their own rule, like the fisherman in the drama, whose eulogy on 
 his deceased lord was, that ' he was so fond of fish/ " 
 
 This tendency to mental one-sidedness, arising from the 
 almost exclusive study of one side of nature, has', as ex- 
 perience convinces us, made not a few able men, exclusively 
 devoted to the study of one or more physical sciences, less 
 able, than would have been the case had their culture been 
 wider, to appreciate and assign full weight to the facts of 
 mental and, above all, of metaphysical science. The one 
 great requisite for the study and correct estimate of the 
 nature of things external to ourselves, is true and accurate 
 knowledge of our own. It is necessary for us to recognise 
 that we are not only conscious but conscious of our con- 
 sciousness; that we not only can make use of and be guided 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 317 
 
 by inference, but that we are capable of analysing the pro- 
 cess of inference, and that we can not only act well or ill, 
 but can recognise an ethical ideal. We require to recognise 
 distinctly what our intellect can and does do, in order that 
 we may assign his due part in the groundwork of science to 
 the worker himself. 
 
 Now, reflex self-consciousness shows us that the " self " 
 exists continuously, and is conscious of successive objects 
 and events, and can and does recognise them as forming 
 part of a series which it transcends, but which it can con- 
 template as a whole or in parts and in different orders, ac- 
 cording as may be desired. This power or principle it also 
 knows with perfect certainty can not only know itself, but 
 is also aware of the kinds and directions of its activities, and 
 can regard them as a whole, or in groups, or singly. It can, 
 it well knows, perceive its own states, both passive and 
 active, and also external objects and events, and can com- 
 pare the relations between them, returning upon itself at 
 will along different lines of thought, and also setting forth 
 in various directions at will. Such a power, aware of all 
 these things and present to them all, must itself be our 
 very ideal of unity, and stand in the greatest possible con- 
 trast to the material world it is able directly and immediately 
 to apprehend and make present to it. Yet, since each man 
 who reflects can know that it is he who not only thinks but 
 also feels, he must recognise his living body and his think- 
 ing principle as constituting, to his experience, one unity. 
 He perceives himself as knowing and recognising the exter- 
 nal world as independent of and yet known to him. He 
 thus knows that in his consciousness the external and the 
 internal meet and blend, and that in himself subject and 
 object are, as before said, identified. This is a supreme 
 truth of science, and no certainty we can attain to about 
 any other object is, or can be, so certain as is this truth. 
 
318 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 Thus we come to know how it is, and how alone it is, 
 possible for the scientific worker ably and with good effect 
 to wield the wonderful intellectual tools he is supplied with 
 for labouring in that field which constitutes the matter of 
 science. 
 
 The labourer thus being replete with conscious reason and 
 labouring with tools which, the more skilfully he uses them, 
 afford him ever better grounds for confiding in his reason, 
 which he also recognises as the basis of all his conclusions 
 and convictions, can it likewise be said that reason is latent 
 and implied also in the very matter of science ? 
 
 If the reader will recall to mind and weigh with care the 
 facts and considerations which have been again and again 
 brought forward in this book, he will, we venture to think, 
 be convinced that there is much to be said in support of 
 such a latent intelligence. 
 
 Let him recollect the phenomena of crystallisation and 
 how a crystal's broken angle can be and will be, the needful 
 conditions being supplied, accurately replaced. Let him 
 remember how different chemical substances possess their 
 own special and in different mineral species very different 
 innate laws, and also the inherent tendencies of chemical 
 substances to combine in definite proportions. Let him 
 note well the marvellous processes of individual development 
 from the earliest condition of the germ upwards, and also 
 consider how during the whole life of each it bears a relation 
 both to the past and the future, as does the chrysalis both 
 to the larval and the imago state of its existence. 
 
 Moreover, if the repair of a crystal is wonderful, how 
 much more so those which take place in animal and even in 
 human ' life. How wonderful is the transition a from vital 
 activities which are utterly unconscious to actions which 
 are present to consentience and ultimately can be recognised 
 
 1 See ante, pp. 124, 125. * See ante, p. 136. 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 319 
 
 by reflex consciousness. Yet, perhaps, above all other 
 wonders is the wonder of instinct, the significance of which 
 Schelling so truly appreciated. 
 
 There is, indeed, a latent logic in the actions of the beast 
 which hunts its prey; in the nesting bird; the bee, the ant, 
 the climbing plant with its marvellous tendrils and even 
 in the mathematical regularities of crystallisation ! But such 
 logic is not the logic of the crystal, nor of the plant, nor of 
 the bird, nor of the beast. It is, in a sense, truly in them, 
 but it is no less certainly not of them, nor is it merely even 
 of ourselves. Mankind did not always inhabit this planet, 
 and when the first animals possessed of self-consciousness 
 and rationality first appeared here, they were not and could 
 not have been the causes of their own advent, but, as new 
 existences, must have been effects of a greater cause. 
 
 He who with an unprejudiced mind ponders over the 
 phenomena which the universe lays open to his gaze can 
 hardly, we think, fail to discover immanent therein an 
 activity the results of which harmonise with man's reason: 
 an activity which is orderly and disaccords with blind 
 chance, or " a fortuitous concourse of atoms," but which, 
 nevertheless, is not an intelligent activity such as is our 
 own, but one which acts in modes which are different from 
 those we should adopt in order to attain similar ends. It is 
 sometimes objected against reason as latent in nature, that 
 we see in all directions so much waste, and that of so great 
 a multitude of organic germs, very few attain maturity. 
 But this objection is indeed an anthropomorphic one, and 
 would imply that the cause of all things is a contriving 
 human mind ! But the non-human rationality of which 
 nature affords so many hints and glimpses as everywhere 
 pervading it, is a universal cause and reason, and, if we may 
 speak of " purpose " in this connection, its purpose is ful- 
 filled by every event, and thus no waste is possible. Every 
 
320 THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE 
 
 seemingly " wasted " germ fulfils other purposes of nature, 
 as the spores of our ancient coal-fields now help the man of 
 science to cross oceans in quest of fresh material for study. 
 
 But though the reason which pervades nature is not that 
 of a human intellect, yet the fact that it has a certain, how- 
 ever remote, analogy therewith is shown us by our own 
 minds. For to it, as a cause, we must ascribe our power of 
 knowing first principles and ethical laws ' and of recognising 
 fundamental truths as being what they are. To it must be 
 due that marvellous light shed upon our intelligence which 
 enables us to know that such truths are absolute, universal, 
 and necessary, objectively as well as subjectively. 
 
 Thus our answer to the question, " What is the ground- 
 work of science ? " may be thus expressed: It is the work 
 of self-conscious, material organisms, making use of the 
 marvellous intellectual first principles which they possess in 
 exploring all the physical and psychical phenomena of the 
 universe, which sense, intuition, and ratiocination can any- 
 how reveal to them as real existences whether actual or only 
 possible. Such being the groundwork of science, what may, 
 nay, what must, be said to be its foundation what the 
 support and guarantee alike of the workers, the principles, 
 and the objects of science ? 
 
 It appears to us impossible rationally to deny that such a 
 foundation can only be sought in that reason which evidently, 
 to us, pervades the universe, and is that by which our intel- 
 lect has been both produced and illumined. 
 
 We must admit that the principle of causation and the 
 uniformity of nature are truths which our minds apprehend 
 from sources which are mainly not sensuous but intellectual. 
 These principles, when we apply them to the world of ex- 
 perience, reveal an orderly universe. By them we are 
 forced to read an order and a reason into the profoundest 
 
 1 See ante, p. 170. 
 
NATURE OF THE GROUNDWORK OF SCIENCE $21 
 
 depths of the essence and being of the universe, nor can we 
 forget that in those depths there must repose the ultimate 
 cause of all that we recognise as beautiful and good, as well 
 as true. 
 
 In concluding, we feel bound to confess that the more we 
 study nature the more profoundly convinced do we become 
 that the action of an all-pervading but unimaginable in- 
 telligence alone affords us any satisfactory conception of the 
 universe, as a whole, or of any single portion of the cosmos 
 which may be selected for exclusive study. 
 
 Unless we are profoundly mistaken, it is only through the 
 conception of such an energy, as an active causative principle, 
 underlying and pervading the material cosmos, together with 
 the recognition of the dignity of human reason, empowered 
 as it is to perceive self-evident, universal, and objective 
 truths, that we can understand the groundwork of science 
 and attain to a final and satisfactory Epistemology. 
 
INDEX 
 
 Absolute existence, 230 
 Abstract ideas, 7 
 
 Absurdity of Herbert Spencer's start- 
 ing point, 278 
 
 of scepticism, 219 
 Act of sight, 10 
 
 All knowledge wonderful, 56, 245 
 Analogy of human and divine reason, 
 
 320 
 
 Analysis of a sentence, 187 
 Anatomy, 24 
 Animal intelligence, 156-161 
 
 kingdom, no 
 
 stupidity, 168 
 Animals, groups of, in 
 Animals' latent logic, 319 
 
 Animals possibly latently intellectual, 
 
 154 
 
 Anthropology, 32 
 
 Ants, 190 
 
 Appearance and reality, 75 
 
 Application of ethics may vary, 166 
 
 Arguments as to external world, 47-53 
 
 Associated feelings, 145 
 
 feelings cause uncertainty, 245 
 Astronomy, 24 
 
 Atomic theory, 306 
 
 Atoms, 304 
 
 Attention impairs automatic action, 
 
 144 
 
 Attractions of idealism, 43 
 Automatic actions, 143, 151 
 Axiom of equality, 247 
 Axioms, 105 
 
 Balfour, Mr. Arthur, 83 
 
 Being, 23 
 
 Belt, Mr., and ants, 190 
 
 Berkeley, 39 
 
 Bifold unity of man, 317 
 
 Bilateral symmetry, 285 
 
 Blind disbelief fatal, 98 
 
 Bodies consist of matter and energy, 
 
 302 
 
 Bodily injuries, effects of, 70 
 Botany, 24 
 
 Bradley, Dr. F. H., 76-78, 80 
 Breaches of continuity, 214 
 
 of continuity in the cosmos, 294 
 Bridge between subject and object, 
 
 237 
 
 Carpenter and instinct, 183 
 
 Causal principle of universe rational, 
 
 293 
 Causation, 256 
 
 and uniformity of nature, 262 
 
 and the universe, 289 
 
 may be felt, 260 
 
 principle of, 105 
 
 Cause, a, demanded for new or de- 
 pendent being, 256, 258 
 
 and force, 258 
 
 of universe judged by its effects, 
 
 292 
 
 Causes of scientific knowledge, 255 
 Certainties, 240-254 
 Certainty, grounded in self-evidence, 
 
 57, 221 
 
 of existing feelings, 217 
 
 of our existence, 101 
 
 of some knowledge, 315 
 Chasms in nature, 287 
 Chimpanzee named Sally, 174 
 Cicero and ethic, 167 
 Classification of sciences, 16, 17 
 
 323 
 
324 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Clifford, Professor, 247 
 Cognition, direct and reflex, 229 
 
 its elements, 9 
 Colour, idea of, n, 65 
 Condillac and instinct, 179 
 Confidence in reason warranted, 318 
 Consentience, 147 ' 
 Conscience, 163 
 Consciousness, 137, 227 
 
 its trustworthiness, 218 
 
 of self, 317 
 
 Corporeal substance and extension, 
 
 77, 78 
 
 Cosmology, 23 
 Cosmos has latent intelligence, 294, 
 
 295 
 
 pervaded by intelligence, 321 
 Counting crow, 173 
 Credulity of sensists, 74 
 
 Criterion of truth, the ultimate, 13, 
 
 14, 221-223, 22 5 
 Crystals, 282, 318 
 Cuvier, 51 
 
 Darwin and instinct, 180 
 Deaf-mutes, 196-200 
 Definiteness of all that exists, 278 
 Delusion as to motion, 306 
 Delusions, tactual and optical, 70 
 Democritus, 306 
 
 Dependent being needs a cause, 258 
 Difference between ideas and feelings, 
 
 II, 12 
 
 Dionaea and intelligence, 159 
 Direct and reflex cognition, 229 
 Direct consciousness, 138 
 Distinction of kind, 213 
 
 Effects of bodily injuries, 69 
 Ego, empirical, 232 
 
 pure, 232 
 Elements of cognition, 9 
 Emotional language, 170 
 
 signs, 1 50 
 Emperor moth, 129 
 
 Empirical laws and judgments, 8, 94 
 Energy, 298 
 
 Enumeration of the sciences, 16 
 Epistemology, 2 
 
 and levelling down, 276 
 
 derivation, v 
 
 Error and incomplete knowledge, 73 
 Esse and per dpi, 35, 74 
 
 Eternal causal principle, 29! 
 
 Ethic and results, 163, 164 
 
 Ethics, 25, 32 
 
 Ethnology, 32 
 
 Everything which exists is definite, 
 
 278 
 
 Excluded middle, 242 
 Existence implies state of existence, 
 
 231 
 Extension, idea of, 67 
 
 our intuition of, 46 
 External world, its nature, 46 
 
 self-evidence of, 46, 224 
 
 Faculties, not ideas, innate, 311 
 Fallacy as to memory, 235 
 
 of Clifford and Helmholtz, 247 
 Feeling and reflection, 12 
 Feelings, associations of, 145 
 
 present ones, certain, 217 
 
 underlying perceptions, 147-150 
 Fichte, 40, 41,^3 
 
 Field of scientific labour, 309 
 
 First principles not gained through 
 
 natural selection, 272 
 Forbes, Mr., 192 
 Force and cause, 258 
 
 idea of, 67 
 
 or power and primary idea, 259 
 Forms of thought, 246 
 
 Fortunate character of Darwin's con- 
 ception, 269 
 
 Functions of man's body, 116-127 
 Fundamental assumptions of science, 
 106 
 
 Geology, 24 
 
 Gesture language, 195-202 
 Goodness, and distinct idea, 162, 166 
 Groundwork of science : its nature, 
 296 
 
 ultimate, of science, 321 
 
 Habit, 125 
 
 Haeckel, Professor, 304 
 Hartmann, 41 
 Hegel, 41 
 
 and the swimmer, 254 
 Helmholtz, 247 
 Hexicology, 31 
 
 Higher and lower mental powers 142 
 
 History, 32 
 
 Hoste, Sir William, 193 
 
INDEX 
 
 325 
 
 How is knowledge possible? 57, 76 
 
 was knowledge obtained ? 264 
 Human and cosmic reason analogous, 
 
 320 
 Hume, 41, 83 
 
 and causation, 256 
 
 followers of, 227 
 Hypothetical truths notknown through 
 
 natural selection, 272 
 
 I am, significance of, 239 
 Idea of cause, 258 
 of colour, II, 65 
 
 of extension, 67 
 : of force, 67 
 
 of nonentity, II 
 
 of power or force, 259 
 Idealism, 35-39, 41-43 
 
 its attractions, 43 
 Ideas, abstract, 7 
 
 and feelings, differences between, 
 
 ii, 12, 65, 80 
 " Ideas" of animals, 158 
 Implicit truth made explicit by infer- 
 ence, 250 
 
 Impressions and sense impresses, 238 
 Incomplete knowledge not error, 73 
 Indefinite, the, an improbable source 
 
 of things, 277 
 Inference and perception, 62, 63 
 
 makes implicit truth explicit, 250 
 Infinitude of knowledge, 315 
 Initiation of knowledge, 4 
 Inorganic world and innate law, 281- 
 
 285 _ 
 Instinct, in animals, 127-131, 179-184 
 
 in man, 126 
 
 its essence, 131, 133 
 
 reflex action of a whole organism, 
 
 182 
 Intellect possibly latent in animals, 
 
 154 
 Intellectual antecedents of science, 
 
 . 2I ?. 
 
 intuition, 14, 104 
 
 language, 187 
 
 Intelligence latent in the cosmos, 295 
 
 pervades cosmos, 321 
 Intention at the basis of ethics, 165 
 Intuition, 14, 104 
 
 of extension, 46 
 Ireland, Dr. W., 2IO 
 Iridescence, 69 
 
 Is, significance of the word, 207 
 
 Johnson, Captain, 192 
 
 Johnson, Dr., 81 
 
 John Stuart Mill and ethic, 164 
 
 and truth, 99 
 
 Joint method of agreement and differ- 
 ence, 94, 96 
 
 Kalmuck and Persian ladies, 284 
 Kant, 41 
 
 Kind, distinctions of , 214 
 Knowledge, all wonderful, 56, 245 
 
 how obtained, 264 
 
 its certainty, 315 
 
 its initiation, 4 
 
 not due to association, 265 
 
 not due to natural selection, 267 
 
 not due to revelation, 266 
 
 not innate, 265 
 
 of our feelings reflex, 228-230 
 
 practically infinite, 315 
 
 Lamarck and instinct, 179 
 Language, intellectual, 187 
 
 and science, 186 
 
 of savages, 205, 206 
 
 unintellectual, 186 
 Lapsed intelligence, 180 
 Larden, Mr., and ants, 191 
 Latent ideas, etc., 97 
 
 logic in animals, 319 
 Laura Bridgman, 200 
 Legitimacy of certainty, 97 
 Levelling down and epistemology, 277 
 Leverrier, 50 
 
 Literature, politics, and instinct, 182 
 
 Lloyd Morgan, 154, 160 
 
 Locke, 41 
 
 Logic, 21, 32 
 
 Lord's Prayer in gesture, 199 
 
 Mallery, Colonel, 195, 199 
 Man's body, functions of, 116-127 
 
 body, structure of, 1 11-116 
 
 duplex unity, 317 
 
 zoological position, in 
 Martha Obrecht, 200 
 Material and repair, 134 
 Mathematics, 18, 20, 26 
 Matter, 302 
 
 of science, 308 
 
 Means and objects of perception, 41 , 61 
 
326 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Memory, 100, 145 
 
 its validity, 233 
 
 reveals the objective, 237 
 Mental onesidedness, 316 
 
 powers, the orders of, 142 
 Metaphor, 203, 204 
 Metaphysics, 22, 23, 32, 87 
 Method of agreement, 94, 96 
 
 of concomitant variations, 95 
 
 of difference, 94 
 
 of residues, 95 
 Methods of science, 89 
 Mind can know truths, 75 
 Molecular motion, 304 
 Monism, 83 
 
 the truths latent in it, 303 
 Monkeys, 192-194 
 Monosyllabic utterances, 202 
 Montaigne and instinct, 179 
 
 More than phenomena knowable, 238 
 Most certain truths of science, 317 
 Motion, 298-300 
 
 a constant experience, 305 
 
 perception of, 71 
 
 Natural selection almost incapable of 
 disproof, 269 
 
 selection and evolution of intellect, 
 
 274 
 
 selection and instinct, 182 
 
 selection and realism, 46 
 
 selection and the universe, 29 r 
 
 selection could never have shown 
 
 us hypothetical truths, 272 
 
 selection did not reveal necessary 
 
 truths, 272 
 Nature of the external world, 47, 55 
 
 of the groundwork of science, 296 
 Nature's ultimate teaching, 319 
 Neptune, 51, 52 
 
 New existence demands a cause, 256 
 
 Newman, Cardinal, 316 
 
 Nihilum, 23 
 
 Not everything must have a cause, 255 
 
 Nothing, idea of, n 
 
 No waste in nature, 319 
 
 Number, j8, 19, 175 
 
 Objections against realism, 63 
 Objective and subjective worlds, 236 
 
 relations, 54 
 
 truths perceived, 246 
 
 Objects and means of perception, 41, 
 
 61 
 
 of science, 34 
 Omniscience and human knowledge, 
 
 279 
 
 Ontogeny, 31 
 Organic inference, 160 
 Origin from the indefinite absurd, 277 
 Owen, Sir Richard, 51 
 
 Pasteur, M. 226 
 
 Perceptions, 3, 41, 63 
 
 Perception of existence, 242 
 
 Phantasmata, 9 
 
 Phylogeny, 31 
 
 Physical antecedents of science, 108 
 
 sciences, 24-32 
 Physiology, 24, 25 
 Pigs and prayers, 172 
 Plants do not feel, 287 
 Politics, 32 
 
 Possibilities as to the nature of the 
 
 universe, 312-314 
 Possible latency of intellect in animals, 
 
 154, 274, 314 
 
 Present feelings certain, 217 
 Primary and secondary qualities, 64, 
 
 69, 72 
 Principle of causation, 105 
 
 of contradiction, 105, 242, 243 
 
 of the universe, 291, 292 
 Process of reasoning, 102, 252, 253 
 Processes of repair, 125 
 Prodigal son in gesture, 198 
 
 Proof impossible for ultimate certain- 
 ties, 221 
 Psychical antecedents of science, 137 
 
 powers of animals, 155-160 
 Psychology, 22, 24, 32 
 
 Qualities, of material objects, 59 
 
 primary and secondary, 64, 69, 72 
 
 Realism, objections against, 63 
 Reality, possible and actual, 23 
 Reasoning must end somewhere, 103, 
 220 
 
 not a very high faculty, 102, 252 
 Reason not invalidated by its possible 
 
 origin, 153 
 
 to be confided in, 318 
 Recollection and reminiscence, 234 
 
INDEX 
 
 327 
 
 Reflection, 227, 228 
 
 and feeling, 12 
 Reflex action, 121 
 
 consciousness, 138 
 Relations, 91, 141 
 
 apprehended, 12 
 
 objective ones, 54 
 Relativity of knowledge, 279, 280 
 Religion, 32 
 
 Religions, 25 
 
 Reminiscence and recollection, 234 
 
 Remorse, 161 
 
 Results, no ethical test, 163 
 
 Reverie, 146 
 
 Revolving cube, 59 
 
 Romanes, 168, 172, 190, 192-194, 196, 
 
 197, 202, 206 
 Rontgen rays, 43 
 
 Root of thought and language, 211 
 Roots of language, 210 
 
 Sally the Chimpanzee, 174 
 Savages' language, 205, 206 
 Sayce, Professor, .205 
 Schelling, 41 
 
 and instinct, 319 
 Scepticism, absurdity of, 219 
 Science and language, 186 
 
 has advanced, 97 
 
 intellectual antecedents of, 215 
 
 is measurement, 90 
 
 its objects, 34 
 
 its physical antecedents, 108 
 
 its ultimate groundwork, 321 
 
 methods of, 89 
 
 physical antecedents of, 137 
 
 what it is ? 3 
 Sciences, enumeration of, 16 
 Science's most certain truth, 317 
 Sciences, physical, 24-32 
 Scientific knowledge, causes of, 255 
 
 observation, 93 
 Self-evidence, 103, 104 
 
 ground of certainty, 56, 221 
 
 of external world, 46, 224 
 Self-existence known, 317 
 Sensitivity and organic world, 212 
 Sensori-motor action, 123, 131 
 Sense perceptions of animals, 155 
 Sensuous universals, 58 
 Sentence, analysis of one, 187 
 Serial symmetry, 286 
 Shamming death, 181 
 
 Sign, what it is, 150 
 
 Significance of " I am," 239 
 
 Sitaris beetle, 130 
 
 Sleep-walking, 152 
 
 Social approbation and ethics, 163 
 
 Sociology of intelligences, 25 
 
 Solipsism, 40, 82, 83 
 
 Sounds, rational and articulate, 189 
 
 , rational but not articulate, 188 
 Source of primary principles of intel- 
 ligence, 293 
 
 Space, 307 
 Speech, 189, 211 
 
 and reason, 211 
 
 Spencer, Mr. Herbert, and causation, 
 
 261 
 
 Spencer's great law, 277 
 Sphex wasp, 128 
 Spinoza, 40 
 Stimuli, 117 
 
 Structure of man's body, 112 
 Stupidity of animals, 169, 174, 177 
 Subject and object, 236 
 
 and object identified, 232, 238 
 Symbols, 91-93 
 
 Symmetry, bilateral and serial, 285 
 
 That follows how, 242 
 
 "That," "what," and "why," 4, 76, 
 
 87 
 
 Theology, 25 
 
 Therefore, its meaning, 252 
 Thing in itself, 224 
 Thought curiously undervalued, 253 
 
 our only means of certainty, 253 
 Thoughts, 7 
 
 Three categories of indispensable 
 
 truths, 225 
 Time, 307 
 
 Tools of science, 309-311 
 Transition from unconsciousness to 
 
 conscious activities, 318 
 
 from unconsciousness to voluntary 
 
 actions, 136 
 
 Transitions and time, 213 
 Trustworthiness of consciousness, 218 
 
 of memory, 233 
 Truth and the world, 101 
 
 can be known, 74 
 
 what it is, 99 
 
 Truths, indispensable, three categories 
 
 of, 225 
 Two forms of memory, 234 
 
328 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Two orders of mental powers, 142 
 Tylor, Mr., 205 
 
 Ultimate certainties need no proof, 221 
 
 criterion of truth, 14, 221-223, 225 
 
 criterion of truths, 13, 14 
 
 groundwork of science, 321 
 
 teaching of nature, 319 
 Uniformity of nature, 261 
 Unimaginable not impossible, 84 
 Unintellectual language, 186 
 Unity of man's nature, bifold, 317 
 Universals, 6, 58, 61 
 
 Universe and causation, 290 
 
 as a whole, 289 
 
 Universe, is it infinite ? 303 
 
 not due to natural selection, 291 
 
 - the possibilities as to its nature, 
 
 312-314 
 
 Unreason not cause of universe, 293 
 Uranus, 50, 52 
 
 Validity of inference, 102 
 
 of memory, 233 
 
 Verbum, mentale, oris, corporis, 189, 
 
 209 
 
 Vibrations, 69 
 Vocal language proper, 189 
 
 Waste in nature non-existent, 319 
 
The Science Series 
 
 Edited by Professor J. McKEEN CATTELL, Columbia Uni- 
 versity, with the cooperation of FRANK EVERS BEDDARD, 
 F.R.S., in Great Britain. 
 
 Each volume of the series will treat some department of 
 science with reference to the most recent advances, and will 
 be contributed by an author of acknowledged authority. 
 Every 'effort will be made to maintain the standard set by the 
 first volumes, until the series shall represent the more im- 
 portant aspects of contemporary science. The advance of 
 science has been so rapid, and its place in modem life has 
 become so dominant, that it is needful to revise continually 
 the statement of its results, and to put these in a form that is 
 intelligible and attractive. The man of science can himself 
 be a specialist in one department only, yet it is necessary for 
 him to keep abreast of scientific progress in many directions. 
 The results of modern science are of use in nearly every pro- 
 fession and calling, and are an essential part of modern 
 education and culture. A series of scientific books, such as 
 has been planned, should be assured of a wide circulation, 
 and should contribute greatly to the advance and diffusion of 
 scientific knowledge. 
 
 The volumes will be in octavo form, and will be fully illus- 
 trated in so far as the subject-matter calls for illustrations. 
 
 G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS, NEW YORK & LONDON 
 
THE SCIENCE SERIES. 
 
 (Volumes ready, in press, and in preparation.) 
 
 The Study of Man. By Professor A. C. HADDON, Royal College of 
 
 Science, Dublin. 
 
 The Groundwork of Science. By ST. GEORGE MIVART, F.R.S. 
 Rivers of North America. By ISRAEL C. RUSSELL, LL.D., Professor of 
 
 Geology in the University of Michigan. 
 The Stars. By Professor SIMON NEWCOMB, U.S.N., Nautical Almanac 
 
 Office, and Johns Hopkins University. 
 
 Meteors and Comets. By Professor C. A. YOUNG, Princeton University. 
 The Measurement of the Earth. By Professor T. C. MENDENHALL, 
 
 Worcester Polytechnic Institute, formerly Superintendent of the U. S. 
 
 Coast and Geodetic Survey. 
 Earth Sculpture. By Professor JAMES GEIKIE, F.R.S., University of 
 
 Edinburgh. 
 
 Volcanoes. By T. G. BONNE Y, F.R.S., University College, London. 
 Earthquakes. By Major C. E. BUTTON, U.S.A. 
 Physiography; The Forms of the Land. By Professor W. M. DAVIS, 
 
 Harvard University. .; 
 
 The History of Science. By C. S. PEIRCE. 
 General Ethnography. By Professor DANIEL G. BRINTON, University 
 
 of Pennsylvania. 
 Recent Theories of Evolution. By J. MARK BALDWIN, Princeton 
 
 University. 
 
 Whales. By F. E. BEDDARD, F.R.S. , Zoological Society, London. 
 The Reproduction of Living Beings. By Professor MARCUS HARTOG, 
 
 Queen's College, Cork. 
 
 Man and the Higher Apes. By Dr. A. KEITH, F.R.C.S. 
 Heredity. By J. ARTHUR THOMPSON, School of Medicine, Edinburgh. 
 Life Areas of North America : A Study in the Distribution of 
 
 Animals and Plants. By Dr. C. HART MERRIAM, Chief of the Bio- 
 logical Survey, U. S. Department of Agriculture. 
 Age, Growth, Sex, and Death. By Professor CHARLES S. MINOT, 
 
 Harvard Medical School. 
 Bacteria. Dr. J. H. GLADSTONE. 
 History of Botany. Professor A. H. GREEN. 
 Planetary Motion. G. W. HILL. 
 Infection and Immunity. GEO. M. STERNBERG, Surgeon-General U.S.A. 
 
 G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS, NEW YORK & LONDON 
 

 THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE 
 STAMPED BELOW 
 
 AN INITIAL FINE OF 25 CENTS 
 
 WILL BE ASSESSED FOR FAILURE TO RETURN 
 THIS BOOK ON THE DATE DUE. THE PENALTY 
 WILL INCREASE TO SO CENTS ON THE FOURTH 
 DAY AND TO $1.OO ON THE SEVENTH DAY 
 OVERDUE. 
 
 MAR 26 1939 
 
 
 LD21-5m-l,'39 (7053s7) 
 
YC 22509 
 
 327133 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY