THE CHOWKHAMBA SANSKRIT STUDIES Vol. XVI THE SIX SYSTEMS OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY PROF. MAX MULLER LIBRARY I UNIVERSITY OF I C . THE iCHOWKHAMBA SANSKRIT STUDIES L Vol. XVI THE SIX SYSTEMS OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY BY THE RIGHT HON. PROFESSOR MAX MULLER, K. M. THE CHOWKHAMBA SANSKRIT SERIES OFFICE Post Box 8, Rs. 15-00 Varanasi-1 ( India ) PRINTED BY THE VIDYA VILAS PRESS VARANASI-l ( India ) PUBLISHER'S NOTE ? t During the last one year we have reprinted several important out-of-print works, all of which have been greatly welcomed by scholars and students of Indian thought. Thus encouraged we are now bringing out the present work which has been written by the most illustrious of the Orientalists from the West, Prof. Max Muller. The work deals with the Six Systems of Indian Philo- sophy, about the greatness of which Prof. Max Muller him- self observes : "It was only in a country like India, with all its physical advantages and dis-advantages, that such a rich development of philosophical thought as we can watch in the six systems of philosophy, could have taken place. With this high degree of admiration Prof. Max Muller has tried in the present work to publish the results of his own studies in Indian Philosophy, not so much lo restate the mere tenets of each systems, so deliberately and so clearly put forward by the reputed authors of the principal philo- sophies of India, as to give a more comprehensive account of the philosophical activity of our country from the earliest times, and to show how intimately not only our religion, but our philosophy also was connected with our National character. We hope that our present effort would also be welcomed by the Scholars and students alike. THE SIX SYSTEMS OF INDIAN PHILOSOPHY BY THE RIGHT HON. PROFESSOR MAX MULLER, K.M, LATE FOREIGN MEMBER OF THE FRENCH INSTITUTE NEW IMPRESSION LONGMANS, GREEN AND CO. 39 PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON FOURTH AVENUE & 30TH STREET, NEW YORK BOMBAY, CALCUTTA, AND MADRAS 1919 PREFACE It is not without serious misgivings that I venture at this late hour of life to place before my fellow-workers and all who are interested in the growth of philosophical thought throughout the world some of the notes on the Six Systems of Indian Philosophy which have accumulated in my note-books for many years. It was as early as 1852 that I published my first contributions to the study of Indian philosophy in the Zeitschrift der Deutschen Mor- genlandischen Gesellschaft. My other occupations, however, and, more particularly, my preparations for a complete edition of the Rig-Veda, and its voluminous commentary, did not allow me at that time to continue these contri- butions, though my interest in Indian philosophy, as a most important part of the literature of India and of Universal Philosophy, has always remained the same. This interest was kindled afresh when I had to finish for the Sacred Books of the East (vols, I and XV) my translation of the Upanishads, the remote sources of Indian philosophy, and especially of the Vedanta-philosophy, a system in which human speculation seems to me to have reached its very acme. Some of the other systems of Indian philosophy also have from time to time roused the curiosity of scholars and philosophers in Europe and America, and in India itself a revival of philosophic and theosophic studies, though not always well directed, has taken place, which, if it leads to a more active co-operation between European and Indian thinkers, may be productive in the future of most im- portant results. Under these circumstances a general desire has arisen, and has repeatedly been expressed, for vi PREFACE the publication of a more general and comprehensive account of the six systems in which the philosophical thought of india has found its full realisation. More recently the excellent publications of Professors Deussen and Garbe in Germany, and of Dr. G, Thibaut in India, have given a new impulse to these important studies, important not only in the eyes of Sanskrit scholars by pro- fession, but of all who wish to become acquainted with all the solutions which the most highly gifted races of mankind have proposed for the eternal riddles of the world. These studies, to quote the words of a high authority, have indeed ceased to be the hobby of a few individuals, and have become a subject of interest to the whole nation. 1 Professor Deussen's work on the Vedanta- philosophy (1883) and his translation of the Vedanta-Sutras (1 887), JProfessor Garbe's translation of the Sawkhya-Sutras (1889) followed by his work on the Samkhya-philosophy (1894), and, last not least, Dr. G. Thibaut's careful and most useful translation of the Vedanta - Sutras in vols. XXXIV and XXXVIII of the Sacred Books of the East (1890 and 1896), mark a new era in the study of the two most important philosophical systems of ancient India, and have deservedly placed the names of their authors in the front rank of Sanskrit scholars in Europe. My object in publishing the results of my own studies in Indian philosophy was not so much to restate the mere tenets of each system, so deliberately and so clearly put forward by the reputed authors of the principal philosophies of India, as to give a more comprehensive account of the philosophical activity of the Indian nation from the earliest 1 Words of the Viceroy of India, see Times, Nov. 8, 1898. PREFACE vii times, and to show how intimately not only their religion, but their philosophy also, was connected with the national character of the inhabitants of India, a point of view which has of late been so ably maintained by Professor Knight of St. Andrews University, 1 It was only in a country like India, with all its physical advantages and disadvantages, that such a rich develop- ment of philosophical thought as we can watch in the six systems of philosophy, could have taken place. In ancient India there could hardly have been a very severe struggle for life. The necessaries of life were abundantly provided by nature, and people with few tastes could live there like the birds in a forest, and soar like birds towards the fresh air of heaven and the 'eternal sources of light and truth. What was there to do for those who, in order to escape from the heat of the tropical sun, had taken their abode in the shade of groves or in the caves of mountainous valleys, except to meditate on the world in which they found themselves placed, they did not know how or why ? There was hardly any political life in ancient India, such as we know it from the Vedas, and in consequence neither political strife nor municipal ambition. Neither art nor science existed as yet, to call forth the energies of this highly gifted race. While we, overwhelmed with news- papers, with parliamentary reports, -with daily discoveries and discussions, with new novels and time-killing social functions, have hardly any leisure left to dwell on meta- physical and religious problems, these problems formed almost the only subject on which the old inhabitants of India could spend their intellectual energies. Life in a 1 See 'Mind/ vol. v. no. 17. viii PREFACE forest was no impossibility in the warm climate of India, and in the absence of the most ordinary means of com- munication, what was there to do for the members of the small settlements dotted over the country, but to give expression to that wonder at the world which is the beginning of all philosophy ? Literary ambition could hardly exist during a period when even the art of writing was not yet known, and when there was no literature except what could be spread and handed down by memory, developed to an extraordinary and almost incredible extent under a carefully elaborated discipline. But at a time when people could not yet think of public applause or private gain, they thought all the more of truth ; and hence the perfectly independent and honest character of most of their philosophy. It has long been my wish to bring the results of this national Indian philosophy nearer to us, and, if possible, to rouse our sympathies for their honest efforts to throw some rays of light on the dark problems of existence, whether of the objective world at large, or of the subjective spirits, whose knowledge of the world constitutes, after all, the only proof of the existence of an objective world. The mere tenets of each of the six systems of Indian philosophy are by this time well known, or easily accessible, more accessible, I should say, than even those of the leading philosophers of Greece or of modern Europe. Everyone of the opinions at which the originators of the six principal schools of Indian philosophy arrived, has been handed down to us in the form of short aphorisms or Sutras, so as to leave but little room for uncertainty as to the exact position which each of these philosophers occupied on the great PREFACE ix battlefield of thought. We know what an enormous amount of labour had to be spent and is still being spent in order to ascertain the exact views of Plato and Aristotle, nay, even of Kant and Hegel, on some of the most important questions of their systems of philosophy. There are even living philosophers whose words often leave us in doubt as to what they mean, whether they are materialists or idealists, monists or dualists, theists or atheists. Hindu philosophers seldom leave us in doubt on such important points, and they certainly never shrink from the conse- quences of their theories. They never equivocate or try to hide their opinions where they are likely to be unpopular. Kapila, for instance, the author or hero eponymus of the Sawkhya-philosophy, confesses openly that his system is atheistic, an-isvara, without an active Lord or God, but in spite of that, his system was treated as legitimate by his contemporaries, because it was reasoned out consistently, and admitted, nay, required some transcendent and invisible power, the so-called Purushas. Without them there would be no evolution of Praknti, original matter, no objective world, nor any reality in the lookers-on themselves, the Purushas or spirits. Mere names have acquired with us such a power that the authors of systems in which there is clearly no room for an active God, nevertheless shrink from calling themselves atheists, nay, try even by any means to foist an active God into their philosophies, in order to escape the damaging charge of atheism. This leads to philosophical ambiguity, if not dishonesty, and has often delayed the recognition of a Godhead, free from at the trammels of human activity and personality, but yet endowed with wisdom, power, and will. From a philo- x PREFACE sophical point of view, no theory of evolution, whether ancient or modern (in Sanskrit Pariwama), can provide any room for a creator or governor of the world, and hence the Sawkhya-philosophy declares itself fearlessly as an-i5vara, Lord-less, leaving it to another philosophy, the Yoga, to find in the old Samkhya system some place for an isvara or a personal God. What is most curious is that a philo- sopher, such as Sawkara, the most decided monist, and the upholder of Brahman, as a neuter, as the cause of all things, is reported to have been a worshipper of idols and to have seen in them, despite of all their hideousness, symbols of the Deity, useful, as he thought, for the ignorant, even though they have no eyes as yet to see what is hidden behind the idols, and what was the true meaning of them. What I admire in Indian philosophers is that they never try to deceive us as to their principles and the consequences of their theories. If they are idealists, even to the verge of nihilism, they say so, and if they hold that the objective world requires a real, though not necessarily a visible or tangible substratum, they are never afraid to speak out. They are bona fide idealists or materialists, monists or dualists, theists or atheists, because their reverence for truth is stronger than their reverence for anything else. The Vedantist, for instance, is a fearless idealist, and, as a monist, denies the reality of anything but the One Brah- man, the Universal Spirit, which is to account for the whole of the phenomenal world. The followers of the Sawkhya, on the contrary, though likewise idealists and believers in an unseen Purusha (subject), and an unseen Prakr/ti (objective substance), leave us in no doubt that they are and mean to be atheists, so far as the existence PREFACE xi of an active God, a maker and ruler of the world, is con- cerned. They do not allow themselves to be driven one inch beyond their self-chosen position. They first examine the instruments of knowledge which man possesses. These are sensuous perception, inference, and verbal authority, and as none of these can supply us with the knowledge of a Supreme Being, as a personal creator and ruler of the world, Kapila never refers to Him in his Sutras. As a careful reasoner, however, he does not go so far as to say that he can prove the non-existence of such a Being, but he is satisfied with stating, like Kant, that he cannot establish His existence by the ordinary channels of evidential knowledge. In neither of these statements can I discover, as others have done, any trace of intellectual cowardice, but simply a desire to abide within the strict limits of knowledge, such as is granted to human beings. He does not argue against the possibility even of the gods of the vulgar, such as Siva, Vishnu, and all the rest, he simply treats them as Ganyesvaras or Karyesvaras, produced and temporal gods ( Sutras III, 57, comm. ), and he does not allow, even to the Supreme Isvar, the Lord, the creator and ruler of the world, as postulated by other systems of philosophy or religion, more then a phenomenal existence, though we should always remember that with him there is nothing phenomenal, nothing confined in space and time, that does not in the end rest on something real and eternal. We must distinguish however. Kapila, though he boldly confessed himself an atheist, was by no means a nihilist or Nastika. He recognised in every man a soul which he called Purusha, literally man, or spirit, or subject, because xii PREFACE without such a power, without such endless Purushas, he held that Prakn'ti, or primordial matter with its infinite potentialities, would for ever have remained dead, motion- less, and thoughtless. Only through the presence of this Purusha and through his temporary interest in Praknti could her movements, her evolution, her changes and variety be accounted for, just as the movements of iron have to be accounted for by the presence of a magnet. All this movement, however, is temporary only, and the highest object of Kapila's philosophy is to make Purusha turn his eyes away from Prakrfti, so as to stop her acting and to regain for himself his oneness, his aloneness, his indepen- dence, and his perfect bliss. Whatever we may think of such views of the world as are put forward by the Samkhya, the Vedanta, and other systems of Indian philosophy, there is one thing which we cannot help admiring, and that is the straightforwardness and perfect freedom with which they are elaborated. How- ever imperfect the style in which their theories have been clothed may appear from a literary point of view, it seems to me the very perfection for the treatment of philosophy. It never leaves us in any doubt as to the exact opinions held by each philosopher. We may miss the development and the dialectic eloquence with which Plato and Hegel propound their thoughts, but we can always appreciate the perfect freedom, freshness, and downrightness with which each searcher after truth follows his track without ever looking right or left. It is in the nature of philosophy that every philosopher must be a heretic, in the etymological sense of the word, PREFACE xiii that is, a free chooser, even if, like the Vadantists, he, for some reason or other, bows before his self-chosen Veda as the seat of a revealed authority. It has sometimes been said that Hindu philosophy asserts but does not prove, that it is positive throughout, but not argumentative. This may be true to a certain extent and particularly with regard to the Vedanta-philosophy, but we must remember that almost the first question which every one of the Hindu systems of philosophy tries to settle is, How do we know ? In thus giving the Noetics the first place, the thinkers of the East seem to me again superior to most of the philosophers of the West. Generally speaking, they admitted three legitimate channels by which know- ledge can reach us, perception, inference, and authority, but authority freely chosen or freely rejected. In some systems that authority is revelation, Sruti, Sabda, or the Veda, in others it is the word of any recognised authority Apta-vafcana. Thus it happens that the Samkhya philoso- phers, who profess themselves entirely dependent on reason- ing (Manana), may nevertheless accept some of the utterances of the Veda as they would accept the opinions of eminent men or Sishfas, though always with the proviso that even the Veda could never make a false opinion true. The same relative authority is granted to Smnti or tradition, but there with the proviso that it must not be in contradiction with Sruti or revelation. Such an examination of the authorities of human know- ledge (Pramanas) ought, of course, to form the introduction to every , system of philosophy, and to have clearly seen this is, as it seems to me, a very high distinction of Indian philosophy. How much useless controversy would have xiv PREFACE been avoided, particularly among Jewish, Mohammedan, and Christian philosophers, if a proper place had been assigned in limine to the question of what constitutes our legitimate or our only possible channels of knowledge, whether perception, inference, revelation, or anything else / Supported by these inquiries into the evidences of truth, Hindu philosophers have built up their various systems of philosophy, or their various conceptions of the world, telling us clearly what they take for granted, and then advancing step by step from the foundations to the highest pinnacles of their systems. The Vadantist, after giving us his reasons why revelation or the Veda stands higher with him than sensuous perception and inference, at least for the discovery of the highest truth (Paramartha). actually puts Sruti in the place of sensuous perception, and allows to perception and inference no more than an authority restricted to the phenomenal (Vyavaharika) world. The conception of the world as deduced from the Veda, and chiefly from the Upanishads, is indeed astounding. It could hardly have been arrived at by a sudden intuition or inspiration, but presupposes a long preparation of metaphysical thought, undisturbed by any foreign influences.' All that exists is taken as One, because if the existence of anything besides the absolute One or the Supreme Being were admitted, whatever the Second by the side of the One might be, it would constitute a limit to what was postulated as limitless, and would have made the concept of the One self-contra- dictory. But then came the question for Indian phiosophers to solve, how it was possible, if there was but the One, that there should be multiplicity in the world, and that there should be constant change in our experience. They knew that the one absolute and undetermined essence, what they PREFACE xv called Brahman, could have received no impulse to change, either from itself, for it was perfect, nor from others, for it was Second-less. Then what is the philospher to say to this manifold and ever-changing world ? There is one thing only that he can say, namely, that it is not and cannot be real, but must be accepted as the result of nescience or Avidya, not only of individual ignorance, but of ignorance as inseparable from human nature. That ignorance, though unreal in the highest sense, exists, but it can be destroyed by Vidya, knowledge, i. e. the knowledge conveyed by the Vedanta, and as nothing that can at any time be annihilated has a right to be considered as real, it follows that this cosmic ignorance also must be looked upon as not real, but tem- porary only. It cannot be said to exist, nor can it be said not to exist, just, as our own ordinary ignorance, though we suffer from it for a time, can never claim absolute reality and perpetuity. It is impossible to define Avidya, as little as it is possible to define Brahman, with this difference, however, that the former can be annihilated, the latter never. The phenomenal world which, according to the Vadanta, is called forth, like the mirage in a desert, has its reality in Brahman alone. Only it must be remembered that what we perceive can never be the absolute Brahman, but a perverted picture only, just as the moon which we see manifold and tremulous in its ever changing reflections on the waving surface of the ocean, is not the real moon, though deriving its phenomenal character from the real moon which remains unaffected in its unapproachable re- moteness. Whatever we may think of such a view of the cosmos, a cosmos which, it should be remembered, includes ourselves quite as much as what we call the objective xvi PREFACE world, it is clear that our name of nihilism would be by no means applicable to it. The One Real Being is there, the Brahman, only it is not visible, nor perceptible in its true character by any of the senses ; but without it, nothing that exists in our knowledge could exist, neither our Self nor what in our knowledge is not our Self. This is one view of the world, the Vedanta view; another is that of the Sawkhya, which looks upon our perceptions as perceptions of a substantial something, of Praknti, the potentiality of all things, and treats the individual per- ceiver as eternally individual, admitting nothing besides these two powers, which by their union or identification cause what we call, the world, and by their discrimination or separation produce final bliss or absoluteness. These two, with some other less important views of the world, as put forward by the other systems of Indian philosophy, constitute the real object of what was originally meant by philosophy, that is an explanation of the world. This determining idea has secured even to the guesses of Thales and Heraclitus their permanent place among the historical representatives of the development of philosophical thought by the side of Plato and Aristotle, of Des Cartes and Spinoza. It is in that Walhalla of real philosophers that I claim a place of honour for the representatives of the Vedanta and Samkhya. Of course, it is possible so to define the meaning of philosophy as to exclude men such as even Plato and Spinoza altogether, and to include on the contrary every botanist, entomologist, or bacteriologist. The name itself is of no consequence, but its definition is. And if hitherto no one would have called himself a philoso- PREFACE xvii pher who had not read and studied the works of Plato and Aristotle, of Des Cartes and Spinoza, of Locke, Hume, and Kant in the original. I hope that the time will come when no one will claim that name who is not acquainted at least with the two prominent systems of ancient Indian philo- sophy, the Vedanta and the Samkhya. A President, how- ever powerful, does not call himself His Majesty, why should an observer, a collector and analyser, however full of information, claim the name of philosopher ? As a rule, I believe that no one knows so well the defects of his book as the author himself, and I can truly say in my own case that few people can be so conscious of the defects of this History of Indian Philosophy as I myself. It cannot be called a history, because the chronological framework is, as yet, almost entirely -absent. It professes to be no more than a description of some of the salient points of each of the six recognised systems of Indian philosophy. It does not claim to be complete ; on the contrary, if I can claim any thanks, it is for having en- deavoured to omit whatever seemed to me less important and not calculated to appeal to European sympathies. If we want our friends to love our friends, we do not give a full account of every one of their good qualities, but we dwell on one or two of the strong points of their character. This is what I have tried to do for my old friends, Badara- yana, -Kapila, and all the rest. Even thus it could not well be avoided that in giving an account of each of the six systems, there should be much repetition, for they all share so much in common, with but slight modifications, and the longer I have studied the various systems, the more have I become impressed with the truth of the view taken 2S. xviii PR-EFACiE by Vign&na-Bhikshu and others that there is behind the variety of the six systems a common fund of what may be called national or popular philosophy, a large Manasa lake of philosophical thought and language, far away in the distant North, and in the distant Past, from which each thinker was allowed to draw for his own purposes. Thus, while I should not be surprised, if Sanskrit scholars were to blame me for having left out too much, students of philosophy may think that there is really too much of the same subject, discussed again and again in the six different schools. I have done my best, little as it may be, and my best reward will be if a new interest shall spring up for a long neglected mine of philosophical thought, and if my own book were soon to be superseded by a more complete and more comprehensive examination of Indian philosophy. A friend of mine, a native of India, whom 1 consulted about the various degrees of popularity enjoyed at the present day by different systems of philosophy in his. own country, informs me that the only system that can now be said to be living in India is the Vadanta with its branches, the Advaitis, the Madhvas, the Ramanugas, and the Valla- bhas. The Vedanta, being mixed with religion, he writes, has become a living faith, and numerous Pandits can be found to-day in all these sects who have learnt at least the principal works by heart and can expound them, such as the Upanishads, the Brahma-Sutras, the -great Commen- taries of the Akaryas and the Bhagavad-gita. , Some of the less important treatises also are studied, such as the Pawka- dasi and Yoga-Vasishf/za. The Purva-Mimawsa is still studied in Southern India, but not much in other parts, although expensive sacrifices are occasionally performed. The Agnishfoma was performed last year at Benares. PREFACE xix Of the other systems, the Nyaya only finds devotees, especially in Bengal, but the works studied are generally the later controversial treatises, not the earlier ones. The Vaiseshika is neglected and so is the Yoga, except in its purely practical and most degenerate form. It is feared, however, that even this small remnant of philosophical learning will vanish in one or two generations, as the youths of the present day, even if belonging to orthodox Brahmanic families, do not take to these studies, as there is no encouragement. But though we may regret that the ancient method of philosophical study is dying out in India, we should welcome all the more a new class of native students who, after studying the history of European philosophy, have devoted themselves to the honorable task of making their own national philosophy better known to the world at large. I hope that my book may prove useful to them by showing them in what direction they may best assist us in our attempts to secure a place to thinkers such as Kapila and Badarayana by the side of the leading philosophers of Greece, Rome, Germany, France, Italy, arid England. In some cases the enthusiasm of native students may seem to have carried them too far, and a mixing up of philosophical with religious and theosophic propaganda, inevitable as it is said to be in India, is always dangerous. But such journals as the Pandit, the Brahmavadin, the Light of Truth, and lately the Journal -of the Buddhist Text Society, have been doing most valuable service. What we want are texts and translations, and any information that can throw light on the chronology of Indian philosophy. Nor should their labour be restricted to Sanskrit texts. In the xx PREFACE South of India there exists a philosophical literature which, though it may show clear traces of Sanskrit influence, con- tains also original indigenous elements of great beauty and of great importance for historical ^purposes. Unfortunately few scholars only have taken up, as yet, the study of the Dravidian languages and literature, but young students who complain that there is nothing left to do in Sanskrit literature, would, I believe, find their labours amply re- warded in that field. How much may be done in another direction by students of Tibetan literature in furthering a study of Indian philosophy has lately been proved by the publications of Sarat Chandra Das, C.I.E., and Satis Chandra Acharya Vidyabhushana, M.A., and their friends. In conclusion I have to thank Mr. A. E. Gough, the translator of the Vaiseshika-Sutras, and the author of the 'Philosophy of the Upanishads,' for his extreme kindness in reading a revise of my proof-sheets. A man of seventy- six has neither the eyes nor the Memory which he had at twenty-six, and he may be allowed to appeal to younger men for such help as he himself in his younger days has often and glady lent to his Gurus and fellow-labourers. Oxford, May 1, 1899. F. M. M. PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION Though I am aware that the Six Systems of Indian Philosophy, the last large work written by my husband, and published only two months before the beginning of his fatal illness, shows spme signs of weariness, and that the materials are perhaps less clearly gathered up and set before the reader than in his other works, I have had so many letters from friends in India as well as in England, expressing a desire for a second and cheaper edition, that I could not hesitate to comply with Messrs. Longmans' wish to add the 'Six Systems' to the Collected Works. A friend on whose judgement I have complete reliance writes : 'There is nothing like it in English for compre- hensiveness of view, and it will long remain the most valuable introduction to the study of Indian philosophy in our language. It is an astonishing book for one who had passed threescore years and ten.' GEORGINA MAX MULLER. August, 1903. CONTENTS INTRODUCTORY CHAPTER PAGE Philosophy and Philosophers . . . . . . 1 Srutam and Smrztam ....* Upanishad-period, from about 700 B.C . . . 4 Period antecedent to the Upanishads . . . . . 5 Intellectual Life in ancient India ..... 7 Kshatriyas and Brahmans ....... 8 The Evidence of the Upanishads, Ganaka, Agatasatru . . 11 Agatasatru . . . . . . . . .13 Buddhist Period. . . . . . . . .14 Prasenagit and Bimbisara . . . . . . .16 Brahma-gala-sutta . . . . . . .16 Mahabharata . . . . . . . . . 21 Buddha . . . . . . . . . 23 Greek Accounts. * . , . . . .26 Buddhist Pilgrims, Hiouen-thsang . . . . . .27 King Harsha . . . . . . . . 30 CHAPTER II. THE VEDAS The Vedas 30 The Philosophical Basis of the Vedic Gods . . . .35 Three Classes of Vedic Gods .37 Other Classifications of Gods . . . . . .38 The Visve or All-gods. . . . . . . .39 Tendencies towards Unity among the Gods .... 40 Henotheism ......... 40 Monotheism and Monism . . . . . . .41 CONTENTS xxiii / PAGE Pragapati ....... , 42 Visvakarman . . . . . .43 Tvashfn . . 43 Search for a Supreme Deity. .45 Hymn to the Unknown God. . . . .46 Brahman, Atman, Tad Ekam . . . 4 ^ Nasadiya Hymn ,... 49 Brahman, its various Meanings . . . . .52 Bn'h and Brahman, Word 55 East and West 58 Mind and Speech . . . . . . .67 Atman '. . . . . . . .70 Pragapati, Brahman, Atman. . . . .72 CHAPTER III THE SYSTEMS OF PHILOSOPHY. Growth of Phi losophical^Ideas . . . 74 Prasthana Bheda . . . . . . . .75 Literary References in the Upanishads , . . 84 The Six Systems of Philosophy . . . . ... 85 Bnhaspati Sutras . . . . . .... 86 Books of Reference . 87 Dates of the -Philosophical Sutras . . . . . . 88 Samkhya-Sutras ........ 90 Vedanta-Sutras ......... 90 Mnemonic Literature. . . . . . . .92 The Bnhaspati-Philosophy . . . . . . . 94 Common Philosophical Ideas . . * . . .104 1. Metempsychosis Samsara ... , . . 104 2. Immortality 'of the Soul. . ..... . . 105 3. Pessimism . . . . . ... . 106 xxiv CONTENTS PAGE 4. Kafman ' . . . . . . . .109 5. Infallibility of the Veda. . . . . . .111 6. Three Gurcas . . . . . . . .111 CHAPTER IV VEDANTA OR UTTARA-MIMAMSA Vedanta or tlttara-Mimawsa . . . . . .113 Badarayana . . . . . . * .116 Fundamental Doctrines of the Vedanta . . . . .121 Translation of the Upanishads . . . \ . 1 3 7 Character- of the Upanishads . . . . . .139 Vedanta-Sutras . . . . . . . . . 140 Appeals to the-Veda . .... . .143 Praraanas. . . . . . . . . 143 Pramanas according to the Samkhya . . . . .144 Pratyaksha , . . . . . . . .144 Anumana . . . . . . * . * 145 Sabda * 145 Authority of the ^Vedas . . , . . 149 The Meaning of Veda. . . . . .149 Work-part and Knowledge-part of the Veda . . . .151 Vidya and Avidya . . . > . . . . .152 Subject and Object 152 The Phenomenal Reality of the World ..... 154 Creation or Causation. . . . . ....155 Cause and Effect. ..... . . . 156 Dreaming and Waking . . . . , . .160 The Higher and the Lower Knowledge . . . . .164 Is Virtue Essential to Moksha ? . . . . . . 166 The two Brahmans ... . . . . . .168 Philospphy and Religion . ..... . , . .171 CONTENTS xxv PAGE Karrnaft . ' . . . .171 Brahman is Everything < . . . . . 172 The Sthula-and Sukshma-sarira? . . . k . ,173 The Four States . . . . . . . .174 Eschatology ........ . . . .175 Freedom in this Life . . ( . . . .180 Different Ways of Studying Philosophy ; . . . .182 Ramanuga ... . . . . . .185 Metaphors 4 . . . . . % , , .195 CHAPTER V, PURVA-MlMAMSA Purva-AlimaHisa . . . . . . t , 197 Contents of the Purva-Mimamsa . . . . t ,. .200 Pramanas of Caimini . . . ... .202 Sutra-style . 203 Has the Veda a Superhuman Origin ? . . . . .206 Supposed Atheism of Purva-Mimamsa . . . . . . 210 Is the Purva-Mimawsa a system of Philosophy ? . . .213 f CHAPTER VI. SAMKHYA-PHILOSOPHY. Samkhya-Philosophy ,215 Later Vedanta mixed with SaTTzkhya . . . . .215 Relative Age of Philosophies and Sutras. . . /' . 219 Age of the KapUa-Sutras . , . . . 220 Samkhya-karikas . . . .... . .222 Date of Gaurfapada . . . .... . .223 Tattva-samasa , ..-..- .224 Anteriority of Vedanta or Samkhya . - . . . t 229 CONTENTS PAGE Atheism ancf Orthodoxy . . . . .. . . * , 231 Authority of the Veda .232 Sawkhya hostile to Priesthood . . . . .233 Parallel development of Philosophical Systems. , . . .235 Buddhism subsequent to Upanishads . . * .236 Lalita-vistara . . . . ... . 237 Ajvaghosha's Buddha-Aarita . . . .237 Buddhist Suttas . ... . . 238 A^valayana's Grihya-Sutras .... . * 239 Did Buddha borrow from Kapila ? . . ,240 j (J A I Bana s Harshafcarita . .' . The Tattva-samasa . . . . . .242 List of Twenty-five Tattvas . . . . . .244 The Avyakta 245 Buddhi . . . .246 Ahamkara . . . ' . 249 Five Tanmatras . . . . . . 250 Sixteen Vikaras . . . . . .251 Five Buddhindriyas . . . . . - - .251 Five Karmendriyas . . . . . . .252 Manas 252 Five Mahabhutas . . . . . . 252 Purusha . . . . . ... ..253 Is Purusha an Agent ?..... 255 Three Gunas , . . . 255 Is Purusha one or many ? . . . . . . 256 Vedanta Sayings . . , . . . ,256 Early Relation between Vedanta and Samkhya * . .258 Traiguflya . . . , . . .262 Sanara and PratisanA;ara ...... * 264 CONTENTS xxvii PAGE Adhyatma, Adhibhuta, Adhidaivata . . . . . 264 Abhibuddhis (5) . . . r . '. '. . .265 Karmayonis (5) . . ~ . . ' . ' . ' * i 266 Vayus (5) '., ', ; . '. -. . . . 267' Karmatmans (5) . . . '. . . . 267 Avidya, Nescience (5) . . .. . . . 268 Asakti, Weakness (28) . . . . * . 26a Atush^i'and Tusha . ... . . . . 269- Asiddhis and Siddhis. 269- Tushm and Siddhis . . 270 Mulikarthas 270 Shashti-tant ra . . . . . . . . .271 Anugraha-sarga. . . . . .271 Bhuta-sarga . . . . . k . . .272 Bandha, Bondage . . . . . . 4 272 Dakshina-bondage, Gifts to Priests. . . . . .272 Moksha . . . . . . . . . 27& Pramar?as . . , . . . . . .273 Du/zkha . . . . . . . . . . 274 The true Meaning of the Sawkhya . . . . . .275- Nature of Pain . . '. . ' t . . .276 Vedanta and Samkhya . . . . . .27^- Vedanta, Avidya, and Aviveka . . . . . .280 Samkhya, Aviveka .... 281 Atman and Purusha ..... 285- Origin of Avidya .... 289 The Sastra ..... 289^ Development of Prakriti, Cosmic . ... 290 Retrospect ... 290 Is Samkhya Idealism ? . . . , ^ .293 Purusha and Prakriti . 295 xxviii CONTENTS PAGE 296 State of'Purusha, when Free . 297 Meaning of ram PurUsha 298 Prakriti an Automaton ? 299 Prakrui's Unselfishness . . Gross and Subtle Body . . 30 302 The Atheism of Kapila . . . 304 Immorality of the Samkhya . 305 Samkhya Parables ..' CHAPTER VII. YOGA-PHILOSOPHY en? Yoga and Samkhya . . . a r\ O Meanings of the word Yoga. . O/-VQ Yoga, not Union, but Disunion . YogaasViveka . . . . .310 Patangali, Vyasa ' ..313 3 14 Second Century B. C. . 315 Chronology of Thought . . , 917 The Yoga-Philosophy- Misconception of the Objects of Yoga . . . .31 Devotion to Ijvara, Misconceptions . . * .319 What is Lyvra ? .321 Kapi la's Real Arguments . . . .327 The Theory of Karman 33 The four Books of Yoga-Sutras . . . . ... 334 True Object of Yoga . . . . . . .335 Xitta . . . . . . . .336 Functions of the Mind . . . . .337 Exercises. . . .338 CONTENTS xxix PAGE Dispassion, Vairagya . ..... . 333. Meditation With or Without an Object . . . . .341 Ijvara once more . . . . . . . 343 Other Means of obtaining Samadhi . , . . 344 Samadhi Apragnata . . . ... . .347 Kaivalya, Freedom . . . . . .347 Yogangas, Helps to Yoga . . . ... .348 Vibhutis, Powers ........ 349 Samyama and Siddhis . . . . . . .350 Miracles .... . * . . . . 352 True Yoga . . ...... . 355 The Three Gunas . ...'... 357 Sawskaras and Vasanas . . . . . . . 357 Kaivalya .3^9 Is Yoga Nihilism ? . . . . . . . 359 CHAPTER VIIL NYAYA AND VAISESHIKA Relation between Nyaya and Vaueshika . . . .362 Dignaga . . . . . . . 364 Bibliography *. . J . ... . . , 368 Nyaya-Philosophy . . . . . . . 369 Summum Bonum . . . . . . . 370 Means of Salvation . . . . . [ . 373 The Sixteen Topics or Padarthas . . . . . .374 Means of Knowledge . . . . . ,374 Objects of Knowledge ...... 375 Padartha, Object . . . . . t t .376 Six Padarlhas of Vaijeshika . . . , * ' . 376 Madhava's Account of Nyaya . 4 . . . t .377 xxx CONTENTS PAGE I. Pramana . . * * * ' 3 ^ 8 Perception or Pratyaksha . . . .379 Inference or Anumana . . . * .379 Comparison or Upamana . . . . . .382 Word or Sabda 382 II. Prameya . . ... . ' . . .382 III. Sawwaya ' . . .385 IV. Prayogana. V. Drtshmnta. VI. SMdhanta . . .385 VII. The Avayavas, or Members of a Syllogism . . . 385 Indian and Greek Logic ....... 386 VIII. Tarka . . .... . . .388 IX. Nirnaya .388 X-XVI. Vada, Galpa, Vitanda, Hetvabhasa, Gati, 'Khala, Nigra- hasthana . . . 389 Judgments on Indian Logic . . . . . .390 The Later Books of the Nyaya . . . . .391 Pratyaksha, Perception . . . . . . .392 Time Present, fPast, Future . . . . . .393 Upamana, Comparison . . . . . . .394 5"abda, the Word ... . . . . . 394 The Eight Pramanas . , .... . .395 Thoughts on Language * .... . .397 Spho/a . . . . . . . . i 402 W r ords express the Summun Genus . . . . .405 Words expressive of Genera or Individuals ? . . . . 406 All Words mean TO o ^ . . . . , . 406 Vedanta on Spho/a . . . . . .410 Yoga and Sawkhya on Spho.'a .... . . .412 Nyaya on Spho/a . ... . . . .413 Vaueshika on Sphote . . . . . . . .414 Prame^as, Objects pf Kno.w ledge . . . ..415 CONTENTS xxxi PAGE Indriyas, Senses .... ... 415 ,9arira, Body ...... 416 Manas, Mind . . . * .416 Atman - 419 Memory . . . . .419 Knowledge not Eternal . . . . . . .421 More Prameyas. . . . . . . . .421 Life after Death 422 Existence of Deity . . . . . . 422 Cause and Effect 423 Phala, Rewards 425 Emancipation ......... 425 Knowledge of Ideas, not of things . . . . . .426 Syllogism . .427 Pramanas in different Philosophical Schools . . . .428 Anumana for Others . . . . . . . .431 CHAPTER IX VALS-ESHIKA PHILOSOPHY Date of Sutras . . . . . . . . . 433 Dates from Tibetan Sources. . . . . . 439 Karcada .......... 449 Substances ....... 441 Qualities ...... 44! Actions ....... 442 Cause ...... 443 Qualities Examined . . . . . . .443 Time 444 S P ace 444 Manas ... 445 Anus or Atoms .... . 445 xxxii CONTENTS PAGE . 447 Samanya. Vuesha . . ......... 447 . 447 Samavaya .... Abhava . . ..'--. The Six Systems . . 461 INDEX . . ... . . - . INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. INTRODUCTORY CHAPTER. Philosophy and Philosophers. WHILE in most countries a history of philosophy is inseparable from a history of philosophers, in India we have indeed ample materials for watching the origin and growth of philosophical ideas, but hardly any for studying the lives or characters of those who founded or supported the philosophical systems of that country. Their work has remained and continues to live to the present day, but of the philosophers themselves hardly anything remains to us beyond their names. Not even their dates can be ascertained with any amount of certainty. In Greece, from the earliest times, the simplest views of the world and of the destinies of man, nay even popular sayings, maxims of morality and worldly wisdom, and wise saws of every kind, even though they contained nothing very original or personal, were generally quoted as the utter- ances of certain persons or at least ascribed to certain names, such as the Seven Sages, so as to have something like a historical background. We have some idea of who Thales was. and who was Plato, where and when they lived, and what they did ; but of Kapila, the supposed founder of the Smkhya philosophy, of Patafyali, the founder of the Yoga, of Gotama and Ka^ada, of Badara- yana and (raimini, we know next to nothing, and what we know hardly ever rests on contemporary and trust- worthy evidence. Whether any of these Indian philosophers lived at the same time and in the same place, whether they were friends or enemies, whether some were the pupils and 2 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. others the teachers, all this is unknown to us, nor do I see any chance of our ever knowing more about them than we do at present. We read that Thales warned King Croesus, we are told that Empedocles finished liis days by throwing himself into the flames of Aetna, we know that Socrates drank poison, arid that Anaxagoras was the friend of Pericles, but there is nothing to connect the names of the ancient Indian philosophers with any historical events, with any political characters,, or with dates before the time of Buddha. It is quite true that every literary composition, whether in prose or in poetry, presupposes an individual author, that no poem makes itself, and no philosophical syatem is elaborated by the people at large. But on the other hand, no poet makes himself, no philosopher owes everything to himself. He grows from a soil that is ready made for him, and he breathes an intellectual atmosphere which is not of his own making. The Hindus seem to have felt this indebtedness of the individuals to those before and around them far more strongly than the Greeks, who, if they cannot find a human author, have recourse even to mythological and divine personages in order to have a pedestal, a name, and an authority for every great thought and every great invention of antiquity. The Hindus are satisfied with giving us the thoughts, and leave us to find out their antecedents as best we can. /Sxntam and Smritasn. The Hindus have divided the whole of their ancient literature into two parts, which really mean two periods, jSrutam, what was heard, and was not the work of men or any personal being, human or divine, and Smritam, what was remembered, and has always been treated as the work of an individual, whether man or god. $rutam or Sruti came afterwards to mean what has been revealed, exactly as we understand that word, while Smritam or Smriti comprised all that was recognised as possessing human authority only, so that if there ever was a conflict between the two, Smriti or tradition might at once be overruled by what was called $ruti or revelation. #RITTAM AND SM/KTAM. 3 It is curious, however, to observe how the revealed literature, of the Hindus, such as the hymns of the Rig-veda, have in later times been ascribed to certain families, nay even to individual poets, though many of the names of these poets are clearly fictitious. Nor are even these fictitious poets supposed to have created or composed their poems, but only to have seen them as they were revealed to them by a higher power, commonly called Brahman, or the Word, What we call philosophy in its eystematie form, is, from an Indian point of view, not revealed, /Srutam, but belongs to Smriti or tradition. We possess it in carefully composed and systematically elaborated manuals, in short aphorisms or Sutras or in metrical Karikas, ascribed to authors of whom we hardly know anything, a-nd followed by large commentaries or independent treatises which are supposed to contain the outcome of a continuous tradition going back, to very ancient times, to the Sutra, nay even to the Br&hmawa period, though in their present form they are confessedly the work .of medieval or modern writers. In the Sutras each system of philosophy is complete, and elaborated in its minutest details. There is no topic within the sphere of philosophy which does not find a clear or straightforward treatment in these short Sutras. The Sfttra style, imperfect as it is from a literary point of view, would be invaluable to us in other systems of philosophy, such as Hegel's or PJato's. We should always know where we are, and we should never hear of a philosopher who declared on his deathbed that no one had understood him, nor of antago- nistic schools, diverging from and appealing to the same teacher. One thing must be quite clear to every attentive reader of these Sfttras, namely, that they represent the last result of a long continued study of philosophy, carried on for centuries in the forests and hermitages of India. The ideas which are shared by all the systems of Indian philo- sophy, the large number of technical terms possessed by them in common or peculiar to each system, can leave no doubt on this subject. Nor can we doubt that for a long time the philosophical thoughts of India were embodied in wha-t I call a Mnemonic Literature. Writing for literary B c 4 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. purposes was unknown in India before the rise of Buddhism, and even at the Buddhist Councils when their Sacred Canon, the Tripitfaka, was settled, we hear nothing as yet of paper, ink, and reeds, but only of oral and even musical repetition. The very name of a Council was Samgiti or Mahasamgiti, i.e. singing together, and the different parts of the Canon were not consigned to writing, but rehearsed by certain individuals. Whenever there arose a dispute as to the true, teaching of Buddha, it was not settled by an appeal to any MS., but an invitation was addressed to a member of the Samgha who knew the text by heart. It is actually mentioned that the Southern Canon was not reduced to writing till the first century B. c., under King Va^agamani, about 80 B.C. Nothing can be more explicit than the statement in the chronicles of Ceylon on that point : ' Before this time the wise monks had handed down the texts of the Tipiaka orally ; and also the Atf^akatha (commentary). At this time the monks, perceiving the decay of beings (not MSS.), assembled, and in order that the Law might endure for a long time, they caused it to be written down in books/ Such a state of things is difficult for us to imagine, still if we wish to form a true idea of the intellectual state of India in pre- Buddhistic times, we must accustom ourselves to the idea that all that could be called literature then was mnemonic only, carefully guarded by a peculiar and very strict educational discipline, but of course exposed to all the inevitable chances of oral tradition. That Mnemonic Period existed for philosophy as well as for everything else, and if we have to begin our study of Indian philosophy with the Stitras, these Sutras themselves must be considered as the last outcome of a long continued philosophical activity carried on by memory only. JDTpanishad-period, from about 700 B.C. But while the Sutras give us abstracts of the variouc systems of philosophy, ready made, there must have been, nay there was, one period, previous to the Stitras, during which we can watch something like growth, like life and strife, in Indian philosophy, and that is the last stage , UPANI SHAD-PEEIOD. 5 of the Vedic period, as represented to us in the Upanishads. For gaining an insight into the early growth of Indian philosophic thought, this period is in fact the most valu- able; though of systematised philosophy, in our sense of the word, it contains, as yet, little or nothing. As we can feel that there is electricity in the air, and that there will be a storm, we feel, on reading the Upanishads, that there is philosophy in the Indian mind, and that there will be thunder and lightning to follow soon. Nay, I should even go a step further. In order to be able to account for what seem to us more sparks of thought, mere guesses at truth, we are driven to admit a long familiarity with philosophic problems before the time that gave birth to the Upanishads which we possess. Period antecedent to the Upanishads. The Upanishads contain too many technical terms, such as Brahman, Atman, Dharma, Yrata, Yoga, Mimawsa, and many more, to allow us to suppose that they were the products of one day or of one generation. Even if the later systems of philosophy did not so often appeal them- selves to the Upanishads as their authorities, we could easily see for ourselves that, though flowing in very different directions, like the Ganges and the Indus, these systems of philosophy can all be traced back to the same distant heights from which they took their rise. And as India was fertilised, not only by the Ganges and Indus, but by ever so many rivers and rivulets, all pointing to the Snowy Mountains in the North, we can see the Indian mind also being nourished through ever so many channels, all starting from a vast accumulation of religious and philosophic thought of which we seem to see the last remnants only in our Upanishads, while the original springs are lost to us for ever. If some of the seeds and germs of philosophy could be discovered, as has been hastily thought, among the savage tribes of to-day, nothing would be' more welcome to the historian of philosophy,' but until these tribes have been classified according to language, we must leave these 6 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. dangerous enterprises to others. For the present w# must be satisfied with the germs of thought such as we find them in the Upanishads, and in the archives of language which reach back far beyond the Upanishads and even beyond the folklore of Khonds, Bhils, and Koles. It is true that during that distant period which we eun watch in the Upanishads, philosophy was not yet separated from religion ; but the earliest religion, at least among the speakers of Aryan languages, serins always to have been not only the first religion, but the first philosophy also, of the races that had taken possession of India, as well as of the best soil of Asia and Europe. If it is ihe object of philosophy to discover the causes of things, 'rerwn co- gnoscere eausas, what was the creation of the earliest mytho- logical gods but an attempt to explain the causes of light, of fire, of dawn, of day and night, of rain and thunder, by postulating agents for every one of them, and calling them Dyaus or Agni, light or fire, Ushas, dawn, the Asvins, day and night, Indra, the sky-god, a,nd calling all of them Devas, the Bright, or dii, the gods ? Here are the first feeders of the idea of the Godhead, whatever tributaries it may have received afterwards. Of course, that distant period to which we have to assign this earliest growth of language, thought, religion, law, morals, and philosophy, has left us no literary monuments. Here and there we can discover faint traces in language, indicating the foot- prints left by the strides of former giants. But in India, where we have so little to guide us in our historical re- searches, it is of great importance to remember that there was such a distant period of nascent thought ; and that, if at a later time we meet with the same ideas and words turning up in different systems, whether of religion or philosophy, we should be careful not to conclude at once that they must have been borrowed by one system from the other, forgetting that there was an ancient reservoir of thought from which all could have drawn and drank. Considering how small our historical information is as to the intellectual and social life of India at different times of its history, it is essential that we should carefully gather whatever there is, before we attempt to study Indian INTELLECTUAL LIFE IN ANCIENi INDIA. 7 philosophy in its differentiated and systematised system^. Mueh^of our information may represent a chaos only, but we want such a chaos in order to understand the kosmos that followed. Intellectual Life in ancient India. In certain chapters of the BrahmaTias and in the Upani- shads we see a picture of the social and intellectual life of India at that early time, which seems fully to justify the saying th<< b India has "always been a nation of philo- sophers. The picture which these sacred books give us of the seething thoughts of that country may at first sight seeni fanciful and almost incredible ; but because the men of ancient India, as they are there represented to us, if by tradition only, are different from Greeks and Romans and from ourselves, it does not follow that we have not before us a faithful account of what really existed at one time in the land of the Five or Seven Bivere. Why should these accounts have been invented, unless they contained a certain verisimilitude in the eyes of the people? It is quite clear that they were not composed, as some people seem to imagine, in order to impose after two thousands of years on us, the scholars of Europe, or on anybody else. The idea that the ancient nations of the world wished to impose on us, that they wished to appear more ancient than they were, more heroic, more marvellous, more en T lightened, is an absurd fancy. They did not even think of us, and had no word as yet for posterity. Such thoughts belong to much later times, and even then we woudei rather how a local, not to say, provincial poet like Horack should have thought so much of ages to come. We must not allow such ideas of f raud and forgery to spoil our 'fyitik and our interest in ancient history. The ancients thought much more of themselves than of the nations of the distant future. If, however, what the ancients tell us about their own times, or about the past which could never have extended very far back, seems incredible to us, we should, always try first of all to understand it as possible, before we reject it as impossible and as an intentional fraud. That in very early times kings and nobles and 8 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. sages in India should have been absorbed in philosophical questions seems no doubt strange to us, because the energies of the people of Europe, as far back as we know anything about them, have always been divided between practical and intellectual pursuits, the former, in ancient times, con- siderably preponderating over the latter. But why should not a different kind of life have been possible in a country which, without much effort on the part of its cultivators, yielded in abundance all that was necessary for the support of life, which was protected oii three sides by the silver- streaks of the* ocean, and on the fourth by almost impassable mountain barriers, a country whicli for thousands of years was free from war except the war of extermination directed against barbarous tribes, the so-called sons of the soil? After all, to thoughtful people, finding themselves placed on this planet, they did not know how or why, it was not so very far-fetched a problem, particularly while there was as yet no struggle for life, to ask who they were, whence they came, and what they were intended' for here on earth. Thus we read at the beginning of the /SVetasvatara-upani- sliad : ' Whence are we born '? Whereby do we live, and whither do we go? O ye who know Brahman, (tell us) at whose command we abide here, whether in pain or in pleasure 1 Should time or nature, or necessity, or chance, or the elements be considered as the cause, or He who is called Purusha, the man, that is, the Supreme Spirit l '? ' Xshntriyas and Brahmans. It might be thought that all this was due to the elevating influence of an intellectual aristocracy, such as we find from very early times to the present day in India, the Brahmans. But this is by no means the case. The so- called Kshatriyas or military nobility take nearly as active a part in the intellectual life of the country as the Brahmans themselves. The fact is that we have to deal in the earlier period of ancient India with two rather than with four castes and their numerous subdivisions. This term ca&tt has proved most mischievous and mis- 1 Sec also Anugita, chap. XX ; S. B. E., Vlil, p. 311. KSHATRIYAS AND BRAHMANS. 9 leading, and the less we avail ourselves of it the better we shall be able to understand the true state of society in the ancient times of India. Caste is, of course, a Portu- guese word, and was applied from about the middle of the sixteenth century by rough Portuguese sailors to certain divisions of Indian society which had struck their fancy. It had before been used in the sense of breed or stock, originally in the sense of a pure or unmixed breed. In 1613 Purchas speaks of the thirty and odd several castes of the Banians (Va.?vi#). To ask what caste means in India would be like asking what caste means in England, or what fetish (feitico) means in Portugal. What we really want to know is what was implied by such Indian words as Varna (colour), (Jati (kith), to say nothing of Sapi?wZ- atva or Samanodakatva, Kula (family), Gotra (race), Pra- vara (lineage) ; otherwise we shall have once more the same confusion about the social organisation of ancient India as about African fetishism or North American totemism! Each foreign word should always be kept to its own native meaning, or, if generalised for scientific purposes, it should be most carefully defined afresh. Otherwise every social distinction will be called caste, eveiy stick a totem, every idol a fetish. We have in India the Aryan settlers on one side, and the native inhabitants on the other. The former are named Aryas or Aryas, that is, cultivators of the soil which they had conquered ; the latter, if submissive to their conquerors, are the jS'udras 1 or Dasas, slaves, while the races of indi- genous origin who remained hostile to the end, were classed as altogether outside the pale of political society. The Aryas in India were naturally differentiated like other people into an intellectual or priestly aristocracy, the Brahmans, and a fighting or ruling aristocracy, the Ksha- triyas, while the great bulk remained simply Vis or Vaisyas, that is, householders and cultivators of the soil, and after- wards merchants and mechanics also. To the very last 1 Thus we read as early as the Mnhabharata 'The three qualities abide in the three castes thus : darkness in the S'udni, passion in the Kshatriya, and the highest, goodness, in the Brahinafta.' (Aiiugita, S. B. E., VIII, P- 329-) IO INDIAN PHILOSOPHY the three great divisions, Brahmans, Kshatriyas^ and Vaisyas, shared certain privileges and duties in common. Originally they were all of them called twice-born, and not only allowed, but obliged to be educated in Vedic knowledge and to pass through the three or four Asramas or stages of life. Thus we read in the Mahabharata : ' The order of Vanaprasthas, of sages who dwell in forests and live on fruits, roots, and air is prescribed for the three twice-born (classes) ; the order of householders is prescribed for all.' (Anugita, S. B. E. ; VIII, p. 310.; While the divi^ sion into Aryas and Dasas was due to descent, that into Brahmans, Kshatriyas, and Vaisyas seems originally to have been due to occupation only, though it may soon have acquired an hereditary character. The Brahmans had to look after the welfare of souls? the Kshatriyas after the welfare of the body politic, and the Vaisyas represented originally the undifferentiated mass of the people, engaged in the ordinary occupations of an incipient civilisation. The later subdivision of Indian society, as described by Manu, and as preserved under different forms to the present day, does not concern us for our present purpose. The lessons which the names of Varna (colour) and (Jati (genus) teach us had long been forgotten even in Manu's time, and are buried at present under a heavy heap of rubbish. Still even that rubbish heap deserves to be sifted, as I believe it is now being sifted by scholars like Mr. Risley and others. In ancient times neither Kshatriyas nor Vai&yas were excluded from taking part in those religious and philo- sophical struggles, which seem to have occupied India far more than wars of defence or conquest. Nay women also claimed a right to be heard in their philosophical assem- blies. The Kshatriyas never surrendered their right to take part in the discussions of the great problems of life and death, and they occasionally asserted it with great force and dignity. Besides, the strong reaction against priestly supremacy came at lafct from them, for we must 'not iorgot that Buddha also was a Kshatriya, a prince of Kapilavastu, and that his chief opposition, from a social and political point of view, was against the privileges of KING KANAKA. IX leaching and sacrificing, claimed by the Brahmans as their exclusive property and against the infallible and divine character ascribed by them to their Vedas. Che Evidence of the Upaaishads, (raxtaka, If we look back once more to the intellectual life of India in the ancient Vedic times, or at least in the times represented to us in the Upanishads, we read there of an ancient King Garaka, whose fame at the time when the Upauishads were composed had^ already spread far and wide (Kaush. Up. IV, i ; Brih. Ar. Up. II, i, i). He was a king of the Videhas, his capital was Mithila, and his daughter, Sita, is represented to us in later times as the famous wife of Rama (Rarnapurvatap. Up.). But in the Upanishads he is represented, not as a successful genera. I or conqueror, not so much as a brave knight, victorious in chivalrous tournaments. We read of him as taking part in metaphysical discussions, as presiding over philo- sophical councils, as bestowing his patronage on the most eminent sages of his kingdom, as the friend of Ya(//?avalkya, one of the most famous philosophical teachers of the Upaninhad period. When performing 1 a great sacrifice, this king sets apart a day for a B rah mod yam, a dispu- tation in which philosophers, such as Ya<7//avalkya, Asvala, Artabhaga, and even women, such as Gargi, the daughter of Va&aknu (Brih. Ar. Up. Ill, i, 5), take an active part. To the victor in these disputations the king promised a reward of a thousand cows with ten pa das of gold fixed to, their horns. As Yagr/?avalkya claimed these cows on account of his superior knowledge, the other Brahmans present propounded a number of questions which he was expected to answer in order to prove his superiority. And BO he does. The first question is how a man who offers a sacrifice can be freed thereby from the fetters of death. Then follow questions such as, While death swallows the whole world, who is the deity that shall swallow death? What becomes of the vital spirits when a man dies ? What is it that does not forsake man in the hour of death? * Kaushitaki Up. IV, i. ; B/rh. Ar. Up. Ill, i. 12 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. What becomes of man after his speech at death has entered the fire, his breath the wind, his eye the sun, his A mind the moon, his ear space, his body the earth, his Atman the ether, the hairs of his body the herbs, the hair of his head the trees, his blood and seed the \vaters ? Whither did the descendants of King Parikshit go? What* is the soul? What contains the worlds? Who rules everything and yet is different from everything? Far be it from me to say that these and other questions were answered by Ya#r7avalkya in a manner x that would seem satisfactory to ourselves. What is important to us is that such ques- tions should have been asked at all, that they should have formed the staple of public discussion at that early time, a time previous to the establishment qf Buddha's religion in India, in the fifth century B.C.. and that his answers should have satisfied his contemporaries. 7'iere is no other country in the world where in such ancient times such disputations would have been thought of, unless it were in Egypt. Neither Menelaos nor Priam would have pre- sided over them, neither Achilles nor Ulysses would have shone in them. That these disputations took place in public and in the presence of the king we have no reason to doubt. Besides, there is one passage (Brih. Ar. Up. Ill, 2, 13) where we are A told expressly that th$ two disputants, Yarpavalkya arid Artabhaga, retired into a private place in order to come to an understanding about one question which, as they thought, did not admit of being discussed in public. Do we know of any other country where at that early time such religious congresses would have been thought of, and royal rewards bestowed on those who were victorious in these philosophical tournaments ? One of the sayings of 6?anaka has remained famous in Indian literature for ever, and deserves to remain so. Whe-n his capital, Mithila, was destroyed by a conflagration, he turned round and said, ' While Mithila is burning,jaothing that is mine is burnt.' Very curious is another feature, that, namely, in these public assemblies not only was a royal reward bestowed on the victor but the vanquished was sometimes threatened AtfATASATRTT. 13 with losing his head 1 . Nor was this a threat only, but it actually happened, we are told, in the case of >Sakalya (B^h. Ar. Up. Ill, 9, 26). Must we withhold our belief from such statements, because we have learnt to doubt the burnt hand of Mucius Scaevola and the suicide of Lucretia? I believe not, for the cases are not quite parallel. Besides these public disputations, we also read of private conferences in which Ya///7avalkya enlightens his royal patron (?anaka, and after receiving every kind of present from him is told at last that the king gives him the whole of his kingdom, nay surrenders himself to him as his slave. We may call all this exaggerated, but we have no right to call it mere invention, for such stories would hardly have been invented, if they had sounded as incredible in India itself as they sound to us. (Br?'h. IV, 4, 23.) It is true we meet in the Upanishads with philosophical dialogues between gods and men also, such as Kaush. Up. Ill, i, between Indra and Pratardana, between Sanatku- mara, the typical warrior deity, and Narada, the repre- sentative of the Br&hmans, between Pragapati, Indra, and Virofcana, between Yama, the god of death, and Naiiketas. But though these are naturally mere inventions, such as we find everywhere in ancient times, it does not follow that the great gatherings of Indian sages presided over by their kings should be equally imaginary. Even imagina- tion requires a certain foundation in fact. We have a record of another disputation between a King A^atasatru and the Brahman Balaki, and here again it is the king who has to teach the Brahman, not vice versa. A<7&tasatru was king of Kasi (Benares), and must have been later than (?anaka, as he appeals to his fame as widely established. When he has convinced Balaki of the insuffi- 1 I translate vi pat by l to fall off,' not by < to burst,* and the causative by * to maJte fall off,' i. e. to cut off. Would not ' to bucst ' have been vipaf? 8 Kaushitaki Up. IV, a ; Erik. ir. Up. II, i. 14 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. ciency of the information which this learned Br&hman had volunteered to impart to him, the proud Braliman actually declares himself the pupil of the king *. I do not mean, however, to deny that originally the rela- tion between the kings and the sages of ancient India was that which we see represented, for instance, in the case of King ffanasruti and the Brahman Raikva, who contemptu- ously rejects all offers of friendship from the king, till at last the king, "has fco offer him not only gold and laud (the Raikvapama villages in the country of the Mah&vrshas) but his own daughter, in order to secure his amity and hifl instruction. But though this may have been the original relation between Brahmans and Kshatriyas, and remained so to the time represented by M'anu's Law-book, the warrior class had evidently from a very early time produced a number of independent thinkers who were able to grapple with and to hold their own against the priests, nay, who were superior to them particularly in one subject, as we are told, namely, in their knowledge of the A turns, the Self, In the Maitrayana-upanishad we read of King Brih- adratha who gives up his kingdom, retires into the forest, and is instructed by the sage S&kayanya, whose name may contain the first allusion to $akas and their descendants in India. Such a royal pupil would naturally in the course of his studies become a sage and teacher himself. Again, in the Kh&nd. Up, V, 1 1 we see a number of eminent Brahmans approaching King Asvapati Kaikeya, and making themselves his pupils. The question which they discuss is, What is our Self and what is Brahman (V, ii, i) ? and this question the king was supposed t j be able to answer better than any of the Brahmans. Buddhist Period. When we leave the period represented by the Upani- shads, and turn our eyes to tha/fc which follows and which is marked by the rise and growth of Buddhism, we find no 1 See also the dialogue between Sanatkumara and Narada (JEMnd. Up. VII, a, i). BUDDHIST PERIOD. 15 very sudden change in the intellectual life of the country, as represented to us In the Sacred writings of the Buddhists. Though there is every reason to suppose that their sacred code, the original text of the Tripifaka, belongs to the third century B.C., and was settled and recited, though not written down, during the reign of Asoka, we know at all events that it was reduced to writing in the first century before our era, and we may therefore safely accept its descriptions as giving us a true picture of what took, place in India while Buddhism was slowly but surely supplanting the religion of the Veda, even in its latest offshoots, the Upani- shads. It seems to me a fact of the highest importance that *he Buddhists at the time when their Suttas were composed, were acquainted with the Upanishads and the Sutras, at all events with the very peculiar names of these literary compositions. We must not, however, suppose that as soon as Buddhism arose Vedism disappeared from the soil of India, India is a large country, and Vedism may have continued to flourish in the West while Buddhism was gaining its wonderful triumphs in the East and the South. We have no reason to doubt that some of the later Upanishads were composed long after King Asoka had extended his patronage to the Buddhist fraternity. Nay, if we consider that Buddha died about 477 B.C., we # are probably not far wrong if we look upon the doctrines to which he gave form and life, as represented originally by one of the many schools of thought which were springing up in India during the period of the Upanishads, and which became later on the feeders of what are called in India th,e six great systems of philosophy. Buddha, however, if we may retain that name for the, young prince of Kapilavastu, who actually gave up his palace and made himself a beggar, was not satisfied with teaching a philosophy, his ambition was to found a new society. His object was to induce people to withdraw from the world and to live a life of abstinence and meditation in hermitages or monasteries. The description of the daily life of these Buddhist monks, and even of the Buddhist laity, including kings and nobles, may seem to us at first sight as incredible as what we saw before in the Upanishads. 1 6 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Prosenagit and Bimbisara. We read in the Tripitfaka, the sacred code of the Buddhists, of King Prasenagit, of Kosala, drawing near to Buddha and sitting down respectfully at one side before venturing to ask him a question (Samyutta Nikaya III, I, 4). We read likewise of King Bimbisara, of Magadha,. showing the same respect and veneration to this poor monk before asking him any questions or making any suggestions to him. Bante or -Lord is the title by which the paramount sovereigns of India address these mendicants, the followers of Buddha. Brahma-^ala- su t ta . If we want to get an idea of the immense wealth and variety of philosophic thought by which Buddha found himself surrounded on every side, we cannot do better than consult one of the many Suttas or sermons, supposed to have been preached by Buddha himself, and now forming part of the Buddhist canon, such as, for instance, the Brahma-<7ala-sutta *. We are too apt to imagine that both the believers in the Veda and the followers of Buddha formed compact bodies, each being held together by generally recognised articles of faith. But this can hardly have been so, as we read in the Brahma-#ala-sutta that even among the disciples who followed Buddha, some, such as Brahmadatta, spoke in support of Buddha, in support of his doctrines and his disciples, while others, such as Suppiya, spoke openly against all the three. Though there was a clear line of demarcation between Brahmans and Samanas or Buddhists, as far as their daily life and outward ceremonial were concerned, the two are constantly addressed together by Buddha, particularly when philosophical questions are discussed. BrahmaTia is often used by him as a mere expression of high social rank, and he who is most eminent in knowledge and virtue is even by Buddha himself called 1 We possess now an excellent translation of this Sutta by Rhys Davids. The earlier translations by Gogerly, by Grimblot (Sept Suttas Palis, 1876), were very creditable for the time when they were made, but have now been superseded. B-RAH? * A-0ALA-SUTTA. I J 1 a true BrahmaTia.' Brahman with us is often used in two senses which should be kept distinct, meaning, either a member of the first caste, or one belonging to the three castes of the twice-born Aryas, who are under the spiritual sway of the Brahmans. We must try to get rid of the idea that Brahmans and Buddhists were always at daggers drawn, and divided the whole of India between themselves. Their relation was not originally very different from that between different ystems of philosophy, such as the Vedanta and Samkhya, which, though they differed, were but seldom inflamed against each other by religious hatred. In the Brahma- (/ala-sutta, i.e. the net of Brahma, in which all philosophical theories are supposed to have been caught like so many fishes, we can discover the faint traces of some of the schools of philosophy which we shall have to examine hereafter. Buddha mentions no less than sixty- two of them, with many subdivisions, and claims to be acquainted with every one of them, though standing him- self above them all. There are some Samanas and Br&hmans, we are told 1 , who are eternalists, and who proclaim that both the soul and the world are eternal 2 . They profess to^be able to remember an endless succession of former births, including their names, their lineage, and their former dwelling-places. The soul, they declare, is eternal, and the world, giving birth to nothing new, is steadfast as a mountain peak. Living creatures transmigrate, but they are for ever and ever. There are some Samanas and Brahmans who are eternal- ists with regard to some things, but not with regard to others. They hold that the soul and the world are partly eternal, and partly not. According to them this world- system will pass away, and there will then be beings reborn in the World of Light (Abhassara), made of mind only, feeding on joy, ' radiating light, traversing the air and continuing in glory for a long time. Here follows a most 1 Brahma-r/ala-siitta, translated by Rhys Davids, p. 8 This would be like the Sasvata-vada. 2 C l8 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, peculiar account of how people began to believe in one personal Supreme Being, or in the ordinary God. When the world-system began to re-evolve, tiiere appeared (they say) the palace of Brahm&, but it was empty, Then a certain being fell from the World of Light and came to life in the palace of Brahma. After remaining there in perfect joy for a long period, he became dissatisfied and longed for other beings. And just then other beings fell from the World of 'Light, in all respects like him. But he who had come first b^gan to think that he was Brahm& the Supreme, the Euler, the Lord of all, the Maker and Creator, the Ancient of days, the Father of all. that are and are to be. The other beings he looked upon as created by himself, because as soon as he had wished for them, they had come. Nay, these beings themselves also thought that he must be the Supreme Brahma, because he was there first and they came after him, and it was thought that this Brahma must be eternal and remain for ever, while those who came after him were impermanent, mutable, and limited in duration of life. This Brahma reminds one of the tsvara of the Samkhya and other philosophies, which as Brahm&, masc., must be distinguished from Brahma, neuter. Then we are told that there are some gods who spend their lives in sexual pleasures and then fall from their divine state, while others who abstain from such indulgences remain stead- fast, immutable, and eternal. Again, that there are certain gods so full of envy that their bodies become feeble and their mind imbecile. These fall from their divine state, while others who are free from such failings remain stead- fast, immutable, and eternal. Lastly, some Samana^ and Brahmans are led to the conclusion that eye, ear, nose, tqngtie, and body form an impermanent Self, while heart or mind or consciousness form a permanent Self, and therefore will remain for ever steadfast, immutable, and eternal. Next follows another class of speculators who are called Antanantikas, and who set forth the infinity and finiteness of the world. They maintain either that the world is finite or that it is infinite, or that it is infinite in height and BRAHMA-tfALA-SUTTA. 1 9 depth but finite in lateral extension, or lastly, that it is neither finite nor infinite. The next description of the various theories held by either Samanas or Brahmaiias seems to refer to what is known as the Syadvada, the theory that everything may be or may not be. Those who hold to this are called wriggling eels. They will not admit any difference be- tween good and bad, and they will not commit themselves to saying that there is another world or that there is not, that there is chance in the world or that there is not, that anything has a result or reward or that it has not, that man continues after death or that he does not. It \7ould seein. according to some of the Suttas, that Buddha himself was often disinclined to commit himself on some of the great questions of philosophy and religion. He was often in fact an agnostic on points which he con- sidered beyond the grasp of the human mind, and Maha- vira, the founder of Grainism, took the same view, often taking refuge in Agnosticism or the A t qwanavada l . Next, there are Samanas and Brahmans who hold that everything, the soul and the world, are accidental and without a cause, because the}^ can remember that formerly they were not and now they are, or because they prove by means of logic that the soul and the whole world arose without a cause. Furthermore, there are Sarnanas and Brahmans who hold and defend the doctrine of a conscious existence after death, but they differ on several points regarding this conscious existence. Some maintain that the conscious soul after death has form, others that it has no form, others again that it has and has not, and others that it neither has nor has not' form. Some say it is finite, others that it is infinite, that it is both and that it is neither. Some say that it has one mode of consciousness, others that it has various modes of consciousness, others that it has limited, others that it has unlimited consciousness. Lastly, it is held that the soul after death is happy, is miserable, is both or is neither. 1 M. M., Natural Religion, p. 105, c a 20 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. There are, however, others who say that the soul after death is unconscious, and while in that state has either form, or no form, has and has not, or neither has nor has not form ; that it is finite, infinite, both or neither. Again, there are some Samanas and Brahmans who teach the entire annihilation of all living beings. Their argu- ments are various, and have in their general outlines been traced back to some of the teachers of Buddha, such as Alara Kalama, Uddalaka and others J . They uphold the doctrine of happiness in this life, and maintain that com- plete salvation is possible here on earth. Thus when the soul is in perfect enjoyment of the five pleasures of the senses, ~they call that the highest Nirvana. Against this view, however, it is said that sensuous delights are tran- sitory and always involve pain, and that therefore the highest Nirvana consists in putting away all sensuous delights and entering into the first GMna,' i. e. Dhyana, that is, a state of joy born of seclusion and followed by reflection and meditation. Against this view, again, it is asserted that such happiness involves reasoning, and is therefore gross, while the highest Nirvana can only arise when all reasoning has been' conquered and the soul has entered the second (Mana, a state of joy, born of serenity without reasoning, a state of elevation arid internal calm. But even this does not satisfy the true Buddhist, because any sense of joy must be gross, and true Nirvana can only consist in total absence of all longing after joy and thus entering into the third CrMna, serene and thoughtful. Lastly, even this is outbidden. The very dwelling of the mind on care and joy is declared to be gross, and the final Nirvana is said to be reached in the fourth C?Mna only, a state of self-possession and complete equanimity. This abstract may give an idea of the variety of philo- sophical opinions which were held in India at or even before the time of Buddha. The Brahma-^ala-sutta professes that all speculations about the past and the future aro included in this Sutta of the net of Brahma. By division and sub- division there are said to be sixty-two theories, arranged 1 Rhys Davids, 1 c., p. 48. MAHABH ARATA. 2 1 into two classes so far as they are concerned either with the past or with the future of the soul ; the soul, as it seems, being always taken for granted. The extraordinary part is that in the end all these theories, though well known by Buddha, are condemned by him as arising from the deceptive perceptions of the senses, which produce desire, attachment, and th6refore, reproduction, existence, birth, disease, death, sorrow, weep- ing, pain, grief, and misery, while Buddha alone is able to cut off the root of all error and all misery, and to impart the truth that leads to true Nirvana. It does not seem, indeed, as if the philosophical teaching of Buddha himself was so very different at first from that of other schools which had flourished before and' during his lifetime in India ; nay, we can often perceive clear traces of a distant relationship between Buddhism and the six orthodox systems of philosophy. Like streams, all springing from the same summit, they run on irrigating the same expanse of country without proving in the least that one channel of thought was derived from another, as has been so often supposed in the case particularly of Buddhism in its relation to the Samkhya philosophy, as known to* us from the Karikas and Sutras. Though the Brahma-grala-sutta does not enter into full details, which may be gathered from other Suttas, it shows at all events how large a number of philosophical schools was in existence then, and how they differed from each other on some very essential points. Mah&bh&rata. If now we compare one of the numerous passages in, the Mahabharata, containing descriptions of the philosophical sects then flourishing in India, we shall be struck by the great, almost verbal, similarity between their statements and those which we have just read in the Buddhist Brahma-gala-sutta. Thus we read in the Anugita, chap. XXIV : ' We observe th& various forms of piety to be as it were contradictory. Some say piety remains after the body is destroyed ; -some say that it is not so. Some say everything is doubtful ; and others that there is no doubt. 22 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Some say the permanent principle is impermanent and others, too, that it exists, and others that it exists and does not exist. Some say it is of one form or twofold, and others that it is mixed. Some Brhma%as, too, who know Brahman and perceive the truth, believe that it is one ; others that it is distinct ; and others again that it is manifold. Some say both time and space exist, and others that it is not so. Some have matted hair and skins ; and some are clean-shaven and without any covering/ This last can only refer to the followers of Buddha, what ever the ds^te of our Mahabharata may be. * Some people are for bathing ; some for the omission of bathing. Some are for taking food; others are intent on fasting. .Some people extol actions, and others tranquillity. Some extol final emancipation and various kinds of enjoyments ; some wish for riches, and others for indigence/ The commentator NilakantfAa refers all these remarks to certain sects known to us from other sources. ' Some hold/ he says, ' that the Self exists after the body is lost ; others, that is, the Lokayatas or Jf&rvakas, hold 'the con- trary. Everything is doubtful, is the view of the Satya- vadins (Sy&dvadins ?) ; nothing is doubtful, that of the Tairthikas, the great teachers. Everything is impermanent, thus say the Tarkikas ; it is permanent, say the Mimamsa- kas; nothing exists, say the $unyavadins ; something exists, but only momentarily, say the Saugatas or Buddhists. Knowledge is one, but the ego and non-ego are two dif- ferent principles, thus say the YogaHras ; they are mixed, say the Uduiomas ; they are one, such is the view of the worshippers of the Brahman as possessed of qualities ; they are. distinct, say other Mimamsakas, who hold that special acts are the cause (of everything) ; manifdkl they are, say the atom is ts ; time and space they are, say the astrologers. Those who say that it is not so, that is to say, that what we see has no real existence at all, are the ancient philosophers ; omission to bathe l is the rule of the NaishtfAika Brahrna- /dirms ; bathing that of the householders/ 1 Does not this refer to' the solemn bathing which is the first step towards the stage of a Grihastha or independent householder? BUDDHA. 23 Thus both rom Buddhistic and Brahmanic sources we learn the same fact the existence of a large number of re- ligious and philosophical sects in the ancient days of India. Buddha. Out of the midst of this whirlpool of philosophical opinions there rises the form of Buddha, calling for a hearing, at first, not as the herald of any brand new philo- sophy, which he lias to teach, but rather as preaching a new gospel to the poor. I cannot help thinking that it was Buddha's marked personality, far more than his doctrine, that gave him the great influence on his con- temporaries and on so many generations after his death. Whether he existed or not. such as he -is described to us in the Suttas, there must have been some one, not a mere name, but a real power in the history of India, a man who made a new epoch in the growth of Indian philosophy, and still more of Indian religion and ethics. His teaching must have acted like a weir across a swollen river. And no wonder, if we consider that Buddha was a prince or nobleman who gave up whatever there was of outward splendour pertaining to his rank. He need not have been a powerful prince, as some have imagined, but he belonged to the royal dass, and it does not appear that he and his house had any suzerain over them. Like several of the philosophers in the Upanishads, he was a Kshatriya, and the very fact of his making himself a popular teacher and religious reformer attracted attention as a social anomaly in the eyes of the people. We see in fact that one of the principal accusations brought against him, at a later time, was that he had arrogated to himself the privilege of being a teacher, a privilege that had always been recognised as belonging to those only who were Brahmans by birth. And as these Brahinans had always been not only the teachers of the people, but likewise the counsellors of princes, we find Buddha also not only patronised, but consulted by the kings of his own time. Curiously enough one of these kings has the name of A^atatatru, a name well known to us from the 24 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Upanishads. He, the son of Vaidehi, a Videha princess, sends two of his ministers, who were Brahmans by birth, to Buddha in order to consult him on what he ought to do. It has been supposed by some scholars that this is the same Ac/atasatru, king of Kaa (or Benares), who, as we saw in the Upanishads, silenced the Brahman Balaki (Kaush. Up. IV, 2, i). But, according to others, Ao me necessary as a preliminary to a study of Indian philosophy as being throughout the work of the people rather than that of a few gifted individuals. As far back as we can trace the history of thought in India, from the time of King Harsha and the Buddhist pilgrims back to the descriptions found in the Mahabharata, the testimonies of the Greek invaders, the minute accounts of the Buddhists in their Tripi^aka, and in the end the Upanishads them- selves, and the hymns of the Veda, weare met everywhere by the same picture, a society in which spiritual interests predominate and throw all material interests into the shade, a world of thinkers, a nation of philosophers, CHAPTER IL The Vedas. IP after these preliminary remarks we look for the real beginnings of philosophy on the soil of India, we shall find them in a stratum where philosophy is hardly differentiated as yet from religion, and long before the fatal divorce between religion and philosophy had been finally accom- plished, that is in the Vedas, There .have been curious misunderstandings about this newly-discovered relic of ancient literature, if literature it may be called, having nothing whatever to do in its origin with any litera scnpia. No one has ever doubted that in the Veda we have the earliest monument of Aryan language and thought, and, in a certain sense, of Aryan literature which, in an almost miraculous way. has been preserved to us, during the long night of centuries, chiefly by means of oral tradition. But seeing that the Veda was certainly more ancient than anything we possess of Aryan literature elsewhere, people jumped at the con- clusion that it. would bring us near tp the very beginning of all things, and that we should find in the hymns of the Rig-veda the c very songs of the morning stars and the shouts of the sons of God.' When these expectations were disappointed, many of these ancient hymns* turning out tp be very simple, nay sometimes very commonplace, and with little of positive beauty, or novel truth, a reaction set in, as it always does after an excessive enthusiasm. The Vedic hymns were looked on askance, and it was even hinted tha* they might be but forgeries of those very suspicious individuals, the Brahmans or Pandits of India. In the end, however, the historical school has prevailed, and the historian now sees that in the Vedas we have to deal, not with what European philosophers thought 3 D 34 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. ought to have been, but with what is and has be^n ; not with what is beautiful, but with what is true and his- torically real. If the Vedic hymns are simple, natural, and often commonplace, they teach us that very useful lesson that the earliest religious aspirations of the Aryan conquerors of India were simple and natural, and often, from our point of view, very commonplace. This too is a lesson worth learning. Whatever the Yedas may be called, they are to us unique and^ priceless guides in opening before our eyes tombs of thought richer in relics than the royal tomos of Egypt, and more ancient and primitive in thought than the oldest hymns of Babylonian or Accadian poets. If we grant that they belonged to the second millennium before our era, we are probably on safe ground, though we should not forget that this is a con- structive date only, and that such a date does not become positive by mere repetition. It may be very brave to postu- late 2000 B.C. or even 500.0 B.C. as a minimum date for the Vedic hymns, but what is gained by such bravery? Such assertions are safe so far as they cannot be refuted, but neither can they be proved, considering that we have no contemporaneous dates to attach them to. And when I say that the Vedic hymns are more ancient and primitive than the oldest Babylonian and Accadian hymns, all that I mean and could mean is that they contain fewer traces of an advanced civilisation than the hymns deciphered from cuneiform tablets, in. which we find mention of such things as temples in stone and idols of gold, of altars, sceptres and crowns, cities and libraries, and public squares. There are thoughts in those ancient Mesopotamian hymns which would have staggered the poets of the Veda, such as their chief god being called the king of blessedness, the light of mankind, &c. We should look in vain in the Veda for such advanced ideas as * the holy writing of the mouth of the deep/ ' the god of the pure incantation/ ' thy will is made known in heaven and the angels bow their faces/ ' I fill my hand with a mountain of diamonds, of turquoises and of crystal/ ' thou art as strong bronze/ ' of bronze and lead thou art the mingler/ or ' the wide heaven is the habitation of thy liver/ All this may be very old as far PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF VEDIC GODS. 35 as the progression of the equinoxes is concerned, but mthe progress of human thought these ideas mark a point, not yet reached by the poets of the Veda. In that sense, whatever their age, these Babylonian hymns are more modern in thought than the very latest hymns of the Rig-veda, though I confess that it is that very fact, the advanced civilisation at that early time which they reflect, that makes the Babylonian hymns so interesting in the eyes of the historian. I do not speak here of philosophical ideas, for we have learnt by this time that they are of no age and of any age. Whatever may be the date of the Vedic hymns, whether 1500 or 15000 B.C., they have their own unique place and stand by themselves in the literature of the world. They tell us something of the early growth of the human mind of which we find no trace anywhere else. Whatever aesthetic judgements may be pronounced on them, and there is certainly little of poetical beauty in them, in the eyes of the historian and the psychologist they will always retain their peculiar, value, far superior to the oldest chronicles, far superior to the most ancient inscrip- tions, for every verse, nay every word in them, is an authentic document in the history of the greatest empire, the empire of the human mind, as established in India in the second millennium B.C. The Philosophical Basis of the Vedic Gods. Let us begin with the simplest beginnings. What can be simpler than the simple conviction that the regularly recurring events of nature require certain agents? Animated by this conviction the Vedic poets spoke not only of rain (Indu), but of a rainer (Indra), not only of fire and light as a fact, but of a lighter and burner, an agent of fire and light, a Dyaus (Zetk) and an Agni (ignis). It seemed impossible to them that sun and moon should rise every day, should grow strong and weak again every month or every year, unless there was an agent behind who controlled them. We may smile at such thoughts, but they were natural thoughts, nor would it be easy even now to prove a negative to this view of the world. One 36 , INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. of these agents they called Savitar (*ue'r??/o, or foVos), the enlivener, as distinguished yet inseparable from Surya, the heavenly, the sun, Greek Helios. Soma, from the same root Su, was likewise at first what enlivens, i.e. the rain, then the moon which was supposed to send dew and rain, and lastly the enlivening draught, used for sacrificial purposes and prepared from a plant called Soma or the enlivener, a plant known to Brahmans and Zoroastrians before the separation of the two. Tn this way both the religion and the mythology of the Vedic sages have a philo- sophical basis, and deserve our attention, if we wish to understand the beginnings not only of Indian mythology and religion, but of Indian philosophy also. ' No, one,' as Deussen truly says, ' can or should in future talk about these things who does not know the Kig-vedaV The process on which originally all gods depended for their very existence, the personification of, or the activity attri- buted to the great natural phenomena, while more or less obscured in all other religions, takes place in the Rig-veda as it were in the full light of day. The gods of the Vedic, and indirectly of all the Aryan people, were the agents postulated behind the great phenomena of nature. This was the beginning of philosophy, the first application of the law of causality, and in it we have to recognise the only true solution of Indo-European mythology, and likewise of Aryan philosophy. Whatever may have existed before these gods, we can only guess at, we cannot watch it with our own eyes, while the creation of Dyaus, light and sky, of Prithivi, earth, of Varuna, dark sky, of Agni, fire, and other such Vedic deities, requires neither hypothesis nor induction. There was the sky, Dyaus, apparently active, hence there must be an agent called Dyaus. To say that this Aryan Theogony was preceded by a period of fetishism or totemism, is simply gratuitous. At all events, it need not be refuted before it has been proved. Possibly the naming of the sky as an agent and as a masculine noun came first, that of the mere objective sky, as a feminine, second. 1 Deussen, Allgemeine Geschichte der Philosophie, p. 83. THREE CLASSES OF VEDIC GODS. 37 Three Classes of Vedic Gods. We know now by what very simple process the Vedic Aryas satisfied their earliest craving for causes, how they created their gods, and divided the whole drama of nature into three acts and the actors into three classes, those of the sky, those of mid-air, and those of the earth. To the first belong Dyaus, the agent of the sky ; Mitra, the agent of the bright sky and day; Varuna, the agent of the dark sky and evening; Surya, the agent of the sun; Savit?'i, the agent of the enlivening or morning sun ; Asvinaii, the twin agents of morning and evening ; Ushas, the maiden of the daWri. To mid-air belong Indra, the agent of the atmosphere in its change between light and darkness, the giver of rain ; the Marutas, the agents of the storm-clouds; Vayu and Vata, the agents of the air ; Pan/anya, the agent of the rain- cloud ; Rudra, the agent of storm and lightning) and several others connected with meteoric phenomena. To the earth belong Prithivi herself, the earth as active ; Agni, the agent of fire ; Saras vati and other rivers ; some- times the Dawn also, as rising from the earth as well as from the sky. These gods were the first philosophy, the first attempt at explaining the wonders of nature. It is curious to observe the absence of anything like star- wor- ship in India among the Aryan nations in general. A few of the stars only, such as were connected with human affairs, determining certain seasons, and marking the time of rain (Hyades), the return of calmer weather (Pleiades), or the time for mowing (Kr^ttikas), were noticed and named, but they never rose to the rank of the high gods. They were less interesting to the dwellers in India, because they did not exercise the. same influence on their daily life as they do in Europe. There was of course no settled system in this pantheon, the same phenomena being often represented by different agents, and different phenomena by the same agents. The gods, however, had evidently been known before they were distributed into three classes, as gods of the sky, of the earth, and of the clouds t . 1 M. M., Contributions to the Science of Mythology, p. 475. 38 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Other Classifications of Cfods. If we call this creation and likewise classification of the Devas or gods, the first philosophy of the human race, we can clearly see that it was not artificial or the work of one individual only, but was suggested by nature herself. Earth, air, and sky, or again, morning, noon, and night, spring, summer, and winter, are triads clearly visible in nature, and therefore, under different names and forms, mirrored in ancient mythology in every part of the world. These triads are very different from the later number assigned to the gods. Though the Devas are known in the Rig-veda and the A vesta as thirty- three, I doubt whether there is any physical necessity for this number *. It seems rather due to a taste very common among uncivilised tribes of playing with numbers and multiplying them to any extent 2 . We see the difficulty experienced by the Brahmans themselves when they had to fill the number of thirty-three and give their names. Sometimes they are called three times eleven; but when we ask who these three times eleven are, we find no real tradition, but only more or less systematising theories. We are told that they were the gods in the sky, on earth, and in the clouds (1, 139, 1 1), or again that they were Vasus, Rudras, Adityas, Visve Devas, and Maruts 3 , but the number of each of these classes of gods seems to have been originally seven rather than eleven. Even this number of seven is taken by some scholars in the general sense of many, like devanam bhftyish^AaA ; but it is at all events recognised in the Rig-veda VIII, a#, 5, though possibly in a late verse. What we look for in- vain in the Veda are the names of seven Maruts or seven Rudras. We can perhaps make out seven Vasus, if, as we are told,, they are meant for Agni, the Adityas, the Marutas, Indra, Ushas, the Asvins and Rudra. The seven Adityas, too, may. possibly be counted as Varuwa, Mitra, Aryaman, Bh t aga, Daksha. Am^a, and Tvashtri, but all this is very uncertain. We see in fact the three times eleven replaced by the eight Vasus, -the eleven 1 Satap. Br. XII, 6, i, p. 205. 8 Contributions, p. 475. 1 Ved&nta- Sutras I, 3, 28 ; and Rig- Veda X, 125, i. THE VISVE OR ALL-GODS. 39 Marut? and the. twelve Adityas, to which two other gods are added as leaders, to bring their number up to the required thirty-three. In still later times the number of the Adityas, having been taken for the solar light in each successive month, was raised to twelve. I look upon all these attempts at a classification of the Vedic gods as due once more to the working of a philosophical or systematismg spirit. It is not so much the exact number or names of these gods, as the fact that attempts had been made at so early a time to comprehend certain gods under the same name, that interests the philosophical observer. The Visve or All-gods. The first step in this direction seems to be represented by the Visve or the Visve Devas. Visva is different from Sarva, all. It means the .gods together, Gesammtgotter (curicti), not simply all the gods (omnes). Sometimes, there- fore, the two words can be used together, as Taitt. Br. Ill, i, i, Vfsv& bhuvanani sarva, 'all beings together/ The Maruts are called Visve MarutaA, in the sense of all the Maruts together. These Visve, though they belong to the class-gods (Ga?ias), are different from other class-gods inas- much as their number is hardly fixed. It would be endless to give the names 'of all the gods who are praised in the hymns addressed to the Visve Devas. Indra often stands at their head (Indraryyesh^a/*), but there is hardly one of the Vedic gods who does not at times appear as one of them. What is really important in these Visve is that they repre- sent the first attempt at comprehending the various gods as forming a class, so that even the other classes (Ga?ias), such as Adityas, Vasus, or Rudras may be comprehended under the wider concept of Visve. It is all the more curious that this important class, important not only for mytho- logical but for philosophical and religious purposes also, should have attracted so little attention hitherto. They are passed over, as a class, even in that rich treasure-house of Vedic Mythology, the fifth volume of Muir's Original Sanskrit Texts, but they ought not to be ignored by those who are interested in the progress of the ancient rnytho- 4O INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. logical religions from given multiplicity to postulated unity, as an essential character of the godhead. Tendencies towards Unity among- the Ctodg. But while this conception of Visve Devas marks the first important approach from the many incoherent gods scattered through nature to a gradually more and more monotheistic phase of thought in the Veda, other move- ments also tended in the same direction. Several gods, owing to their position in nature, were seen to perform the same acts, and hence a poet might well take upon\ himself to say that Agni not only acted with Indra or Savitri, but that in certain of his duties Agni was Indra and was SavitH. Hence arose a number of dual gods, such as Indra- Agni, Mitra-Varuwau, Agni-Shomau. also the two Asvins. On other occasions three gods were praised as working together, such as Aryaman, Mitra and Varuna, or Agni, Soma and Gandharva, while from another point of view, Vishnu with his three strides represented originally the same heavenly being, as rising in the morning, culminating at noon, and setting in the evening. Another god or god- dess, Aditi, was identified with the sky and the air, was called mother, father, and son, was called all the gods and the five races of men, was called the past and the future. Professor Weber has strangely misunderstood me if he imagines that I designated this phase of religious thought as Henotheism. Benotheism. To identify Indra, Agni, and Varuna is one thing, it is syncretism ; to address either Indra or Agni or Varuria, as for the time being the only god in existence with an entire forgetf ulness of all other gods, is quite another ; and it was this phase, so fully developed in the hymns of the Veda, which I wished to mark definitely by a name of its own, calling it Henotheism l . 1 This phase of religious thought has been well described in the same fifth volume of Muir's Original Sanskrit Texts, p. 354 ; see also Deussen, Geachichte and, after a time, they declared that there was behind all the gods that one (Tad Ekam) of which the gods were but various names. Rv. I, 164, 46. EkaFi sat viprSA bahudha vadanti, Agnim, Yatnam, Matarisv&nam ahuft. The bages call that One in many ways, they call .it Agni, Yama, Matarisvan. Rv. X^ 129, a. Axiit avatam svadhaya tat ekam, tasmai ha anyat na paraA kim fcana asa. That One breathed breathlessly by itself, other than it there nothing since has been. The former thought led by itself to a 'monotheistic reli- gion, the latter t as .we shall see t to a monistic philosophy. In trying to trace the onward movement of religious and philosophical thought in the Veda, we should recognize once for all the great difficulties with which we have to contend. Speaking as yet of the hymns only, we have in the Kig-veda a collection of 1,017 hymns, each on an average containing about ten verses. But this collection was made at different times and in different places, syste- matically in some respects, but in others, more or less at random. We have no right to suppose that we have even a hundredth part of the religious and popular poetry that existed during the Vedic age. We must therefore carefully guard against such conclusions as that, because we possess in our Rig-veda-samhita but one -hymn addressed to a cer- tain deity, therefore that god was considered as less impor- tant or was less widely worshipped than other gods. This has been a very common mistake, and I confess that there is some excuse for it, just as there was for looking upon Homer as the sole representative of the whole epic poetry of Greece, and upon his mythology as the mythology of the whole of Greece. But we must never forget that the 42 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Rig-veda is but a fragment, and represents the whole of Vedic mythology and religion even lees than Homer repre- sents the whole of Greek mythology and religion. It is wonderful enough that such a collection should have escaped destruction or forgetful ness, when we keep in mind that the ancient literature of India was purely mnemonic, writing being perfectly unknown, but the art of mnemonics being studied all the more as a discipline essential to intel- lectual life. What has come down to us of Vedic hymns, by an almost incredible, yet well attested process, is to us a fragment only, and we must be on our guard not to go beyond the limits assigned to us by the facts of the case. Nor can the hymns which have come down to vs have been composed by one man or by members of one family or one community only ; they reach us in the form of ten collections (Mandalas) composed, we are told, by different men, and very likely at different periods. Though there is great similarity, nay even monotony running through them, there are differences also that cannot fail to strike the attentive reader. In all such matters, however, we must be careful not to go beyond the evidence before us, and abstain as much as possible from attempting to syste- matise and. generalise what comes to us in an unsystematised, nay often chaotic form. Pro// A,pati. Distinguishing therefore, as much as possible, between what has been called tentative monotheism, which is reli- gion, and tentative monism, which is philosophy, we can aiscover traces of the former in the famous hymn X, 121, which, years ago, I called the hymn to the Unknown God. Here the poet asks in every verse to whom, to what Deva, he should offer his sacrifice, and says towards the end whether it should be, ydh devdshu dhi devaA dkaL asit, * he who alone was goc} above gods/ Many of the ordinary gods are constantly represented as supreme, with an entire torgetfninees that one only can be so; but this is very different from the distinct demand here made by the poet for a god that should be abovy all other gods. It is much niore like the Semitic demand for a god above all gods VISVAKARMAN. TVASHT7?/. 43 (Exod, xviii. n), or for a father of gods and men, as in Greece (irar^p avbpvv re Oe&v re). Aristotle already re- marked that, as men have one king, they imagined that the gods also must be governed by one king 1 . I believe, however, that the ground for this lies deeper, and that the idea of oneness is really involved in the idea of God as a supreme and unlimited being. But Aristotle might no doubt have strengthened his argument by .appealing to India where ever sg many clans and tribes had each their own king, whether Ragrah or Maharajah, and where it might seem natural to imagine a number of supreme gods, each with their own limited supremacy. Still all this would have satisfied the monistic craving for a time only. Here too, in the demand for and in the supply of a supreme deity, we can watch a slow and natural progress. At first, for instance, when (Rv. VIII, 89) Indra was to be praised for his marvellous deeds, it was he who had made the sun to shine. He was called $atakratu, the all-powerful and all-wise, or Abhibhu, the conqueror. At the end the poet sums up by saying : Visva-karma vLsva-devaA maMn asi, * thou art the maker of all things, thou art the great Visvadeva (all-god)/ The last word is difficult to translate, but its real purport becomes clear, if we remember what we saw before with reference to the origin of the Visve Devas. Visvafcarman. In such adjectives as $atakratu, and still .more in Visva- karman, the maker of all things, we see the clear germs that were to grow into the one supreme deity. As soon as Visvakarman was used as a substantive, the Brahmans had what they wanted, they had their All-maker, their god above all gods, the god whose friendship the other gods were eager to secure (VIII, 89, 3). Tvasfe/H. The maker or creator of all things is the nearest approach to the onjB and only god of later times. It should not be forgotten, however, that, there was already another maker. 1 Arist. Politics, i, a, 7 ; Muir, 0. S. T., V, p. 5. 44 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. called TvashJ ri, i. e. T&TOH-', only that he did not rise to the position of a real creator of all things. He seems to have been too old, too mythological a character for philosophical purposes. He remained the workman, the Hephaestos, of the Vedic gods, well known as the father of SaraTiyu and Visvarftpa. He had all the requisites for becoming a supreme deity, in fact, he is so here and there, as when he is addressed as having formed heaven and earth (X, no, 9), nay, as having begotten everything (visvam bhuvanam (jac/ana). He is in fact all that a Creator can be required to be, being supposed to have created even some of the gods, such as Agni, Indra, and Brahman aspati (Rv. X, 2, 7 ; II, 23, 17). If Agni himself is called Tvashtfri (Rv. II, 1,5), this is merely in consequence of that syncretism which identified Agni with ever so many gods, but more par- ticularly with Tvashtfri, the shaper of all things. When Tvashfrri is called Savitri, this does rfot necessarily imply his identity with the god Savitri, but the word should in that case be taken as a predicate, meaning the en- livener, just as in other places he is praised as the nouri^her or preserver of all creatures, as the sun (Rv. Ill, 55, 19). One of the causes why he did not, like Pragrapati or Visva- karman, become a supreme god and creator was his having belonged to a more ancient pre- Vedic stratum of gods. This might also account for Indra's hostility to TvashZri, considering that he (Indra), as a new god, had himself supplanted the older gods, such as Dyaus.. We must be prepared for many such possibilities, though I give them here as guesses only. It is possible also that the name of Asura, given to Tvashtfri and to his son Visvarupa, points in the same direction, and that we should take it, not in the sense of an evil spirit, but in the sense of an ancient daimon in which it is applied in other hymns to Varu'wa, and other ancient Devas. Tvashr is best known as the father of Saranyft and the grandfather therefore of the Asvins (day and night), but it is a mistake to suppose that as father of Yama and Yami he was ever conceived as the progenitor of the whole human race. Those who so con- fidently identify Yama and Yaml with Adam and Eve seem to have entirely forgotten that Yama never had any SEARCH FOE A SUPREME DL1TY. 45 children of Yaini. In his mythological character, Tvashtri is sometimes identical with Dyaus (Zeus) *, but he never becomes, as has sometimes been supposed, a purely abstract deity ; and in this we see the real difference between Tvashtfri and Visvakarman. Visvakarman, originally a mere pre- dicate, has no antecedents, no parents, and no offspring, like Tvashtfri (Rv. X, 81, 4). The work of Visvakarman is described in the following words, which have a slight mythological colouring : ' What was the stand, the support, what and how was it, from whence the all-seeing Visva- karman produced by his might the earth and stretched out the sky ? The only god who on every side has eyes, mouths, arms and feet, blows (forges) with his two arms and with wings, while producing heaven and earth 2 / How vague and uncertain the personal character of Vis- vakarman was in Vedic times, we can see from the fact that the Taittiriya Brahmawa ascribes the very acts here ascribed to Visvakarman to Brahman 3 . At a later time, Visvakarman, the All-maker, became with the Buddhists, as Visvakamma, a merely subordinate spirit, who is sent to act as hairdresser to Buddha* The gods also have their fates ! Search for a Supreme Deity. The same human yearning for one supreme deity which led the Vedic priests to address their hymns to the Visve Devas or to Visvakarman as the maker of all things, induced them likewise to give a more personal character to Pra^apati. This name, meaning lord- of creatures, is used in the Rig-veda as a predicate of several gods, such as Soma, Savitrt, and others. His later origin has been in- ferred from the fact that his name occurs but three times in the Rig-veda 4 . These arithmetical statistics should, however, be used with great caution. First of all my index 1 Contributions, II, p. 560. a This blving has reference to the forge on which the smith does his work. Wings wfere used instead of bellows, and we must take care not to ascribe angels* wings to Tvashfri Or to any god of Vedic times, unless he is conceived as a bird, and not as a man. 8 Taitt. Br. II, 8, 9, 6 ; Muir, O. S. T., V, p. 355. Muir, O.S.T., V, p, 390. 46 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. verborum is by no means infallible, and secondly pur.Sam- hita of the Rig-vcda is but a segment, probably a very small segment, of the mass of religious poetry that once existed. In the case of Pra^apati I had left out in rny Index one passage, X, 1-21, 10, and though, for very good reasons, I considered and still consider this verse as a later addition, this was probably no excuse for omitting it, like all that is omitted in the Pada-text of the Rig-veda. The whole hymn must have been, as I thought, the expression of a yearning after one supreme deity, who had made heaven and earth, the sea and all : that in them is. But many scholars take it as intended from the very first verse for the individualised god, Pra^apati. I doubt this still, and I give therefore the translation of the hymn as I gave it in 1860, in my 'History of Ancient Sanskrit Literature' (p. 568)- It has been translated many times since, but it will be seen that I have had but little to alter. Hymn to the Unknown God. 1. In the beginning there arose the germ of golden light, Hiranya- garbha; he was the one born lord of all that is. He stablished the earth and this sky Who is the god to whom we should offer our sacrifice? 2. He who gives life, he who gives strength : whose command all the bright gods revere ; whose shadow is immortality and mortality (gods and men) Who is the god to whom we should offer our sacrifice ? 3. He who through his power became the sole king of this breathing and slumbering world he who governs all, man and beasW-Who is the god to whom we should offer our sacrifice ? 4. He through whose greatness these snowy mountains are, and the gf-a, they say, with the Rasa, the distant river, he whose two arms these regions are Who is the god to whom we should offer our sacrifice ? 5. He through whom the sky is strong, and the earth firm, he through whom the heaven was established, nay the highest heaven, he who mea- sured the light in the air Who is the god to whom We should offer our sacrifice? 6. He to whom heaven and earth (or, the two armies) standing firm by his help, look up, trembling in their minds, he over whom the rising sun shines forth Who is the god to whom we should offer our sacrifice ? 7. When the great waters went everywhere, holding the germ and generating fire, thence he arose who is the sole life of the bright gods Who is the god to whom we should offer our sacrifice ? 8. He who by his might looked even over the waters, which gave strength and produced the sacrifice, he who alone is god above all gods Who is the god to whom we should offer our sacrifice ? 9. May he not destroy i\s, he, the creator of the earth, or he, the righteous, who created the heaven, he who also created the bright and mighty waters Who is the god to whom we should offer our sacrifice ? HYMN TO TEE UNKNOWN GOD. 47 Then follows the verse which I treated as a later addition, because it seemed to me that, if Pra(/apatrhad been known by the poet as the god who did all this, he would not have asked, at the end of every verse, who the god was to whom sacrifice should be offered. However, poets have their own ways. But- the strongest argument against the final verse, which my critics have evidently overlooked, is the fact that this verse has not been divided by the Padakara. I still hold, therefore, that it was a later addition, that it is lame and weak, and spoils the character of the hymn. It runs as follows : 10. 'O Pra Darkness there was, in the beginning all this was a sea without light ; the germ that lay covered by the husk, that One was born by the power of heat (Tapas). 4. Love overcame it in the beginning, which was the seed springing from mind; poets having search d in their heart found by wisdom the bond of what is in what is not. 5. Their ray which was stretched across, was it below or was it above? There were seed-bearers, there were powers, self-power -below, and will above. 6. Who then knows, who has declared it hew, from whence was born this creation ? The gods came later than this creation, who then knows whence it arose? 7. He from whom this creation arose, whether he made it or did not make it, the Highest Seer in the highest heaven, he forsooth knows ; or does even he not know ? There are several passages in this hymn which, in spite of much labour spent on them by eminent scholars, remain as obscure now as they were to me in 1859. The poet himself is evidently not quite clear in his own mind, and he is constantly oscillating between a personal and imper- sonal or rather superpersonal cause from whence the uni- E 50 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. verse emanated. But the step from a sexual to a sexless d, from a mythological TiyxSro? to a metaphysical TT/XOTW, evidently been made at that early time, and with it the decisive step from mythology to philosophy had been taken. It is strange to meet with this bold guess in a collection of hymns the greater part of which consists of what must seem to us childish petitions addressed to the numerous Devas or gods of nature. Even the question whibh in Europe was asked at a much later date, where the Creator could have found a TTOV orS for creating the world out of matter or out of nothing, had evidently passed through the minds of the Vedic seers when they asked, Rv. X, 81, 2 and 4: 'What was the stand, what was the support, what and how was it, from whence the all- seeing Visvakarman produced by his might the earth and stretched out the sky?' These startling outbursts of philosophic thought seem indeed to require the admission of a long continued effort of meditation and speculation before .so complete a rupture with the old conception of physical gods* could have .become possible. We must not, however, measure every nation with the same measure. It is not necessary that the historical progress of thought, whether religiouB or philosophical, should have been exactly the same in every country, nor must we forget that there always have been privileged individuals whose mind was untrammelled by the thoughts of the great mass of the people, and who saw and proclaimed, as if inspired by a power not themselves, truths far beyond- the reach of their fellow men. It must have required considerable bold- ness, when surrounded by millions who never got tired of celebrating the mighty deeds achieved by such Devas as Agni, Indra, Soma, Savitri, or VaruTia, to declare that these gods were nothing but names of a higher power which was at first without any name at all, called simply Tad Ekam, that One, and afterwards addressed by such dark names as Brahman and Atman. The poets who utter these higher truths seem fully conscious of their own weakness in grasping them. Thus, in I, 167, 5 and 6, thQ poet says : 1 As a fool, ignorant in my own mind. I ask for the hidden places of the NASADIYA BYMN. 5 1 gods ; the sages, in order to weave, stretched the seven strings over the newborn calf 1 .' ' Not having discovered I ask the sages who may have Discovered, not knowing, in order to know : he who supported the six skies in the form of the unborn was he perchance that One ? * And .again in ver. 4 of the same hymn : 'Who has seen the firstborn, when he who had no bones (no form) bears him that has bones (form) ? Where is the breath of the earth, the blood, the self? Who went to one who knows, to ask this ?' In all this it is quite clear that the poets themselves who proclaimed the great truth of the One, as the sub- stance of all the gods, did not claim any inspiration ab extra, but strove to rise by their own exertions out of the clouds of their foolishness towards the perception of a higher truth. The wise, as they said, had perceived in their heart what was the bond between what is and what is not, between the visible and the invisible, between the phenomenal and the real, and hence also between the indi- vidual gods worshipped by the multitude, and that One Being which was free from the character of a mere Deva, entirely free from mythology, from parentage and sex, and, if endowed with personality at all, then so far only as personality was necessary for will. This was very different from the vulgar personality ascribed by the Greeks to their Zeus or Aphrodite, nay even by many Jews and Christians to their Jehovah or God. All this represented an enormous .progress, and it is certainly difficult to imagine how it could have been achieved at that early period and, as it were, in the midst of prayers and sacrifices addressed to a crowd of such decidedly personal and mythological Devas as Indr& and Agni and all the rest. Still it was achieved; and whatever is the age when the collection of our Rig-veda-samluta was finished, it was before that age that the conviction had been formed that there is but One, One Being, neither male nor female, a Being raised high above all the con- ditions and limitations of personality and of human nature, 1 This calf seems meant for the year, and in the seven strings we might see a distant recollection of a year of seven seasons; see Galen, v. 347. Pragapati is often identified with the year. E 2 52 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. and nevertheless the Being that was really mean!, by all such names as Indra, Agni, Mataris^an, nay even by the name of Pra^apati, lord of creatures. In fact the Vedic poets had arrived at a conception of the Godhead which was reached once more by some of the Christian philo- sophers of Alexandria, but which even at present is beyond the reach of many who call themselves Christians. Before that highest point of religious speculation was reached, or, it may be, even at the same time, for chronology is very difficult to apply to the spontaneous intuitions of philosophical truths, many efforts had been made A in the same direction. Such names as Brahman and Atman, which afterwards became so important as the t f vo main supports of Vedanta-philosophy, or Purusha, the name of the transcendent soul as used in the Samkhya system, do not spring into life without a long previous incubation. Brahman, its various If then we find Brahman used as another name of whaf before was called Tad Ekam, That One, if later on we meet with such questions as ' Was Brahman the first cause ? Whence are we born ? By what do we live? Whither are we hastening? By whom constrained do we obtain our lot in life whether of happiness or of misery, O ye knowers of Brahman? Is time, is the nature of things, is necessity, is accident, are the elements, or is Purusha to be considered the source ? ' We naturally ask, first of all, whence came these names ? What did Brdhrnan mean so as to become fit to signify Ttf JzTecs ov't It is curious to observe how lightly chis question has been answered 1 . Br&hman, it was said by >r. Haug, means prayer, and was derived from the root Barh or Brih. to swell or to grow, so that originally it would have meant what swells or grows. He then assigned to Br&hrnan the more abstract meaning of growth and welfare, and what causes growth and welfare, namely sacred songs. Lastly, he assigned to Br&hman the meaning 1 M. M., Theosopliy, p. 240. BRAHMAN, ITS VARIOUS MEANINGS. 53 of force as manifested in mature, and that of universal force as the Supreme Peing. I confess I can see no con- tinuity in this string o thought. Other scholars, however, have mostly repeated the same view. Dr. Muir starts from Brahman in the sense of prayei', while with the ordinary change of accent Brahman means he who prays. Here the first question seems to be how Brahman could have corne to mean prayer. Prof. Roth maintained that Brahman expressed the force of will directed to the gods ; and he gave as the first meaning of Brahman, 'Die cds Drang und F Lille des Gemuths au/tretende ^tmd den G otter n zustrebende Andacht,' words difficult to render into intelligible English. The second meaning, according to him, is a sacred or magic formula ; then sacred and divine words, opposed to ordinary language ; sacred wisdom, holy life; lastly, the absolute or impersonal god. These are mighty strides of thought, but how are they to be derived one from the other'? Prof. Deusseri (p. TO) sees in Brahman 'prayer/ the lifting up of the will above one's own individuality of which we become conscious in religious meditation. I must confess that here too there seem to be several missing links in the chain of meanings. Though the idea of prayer as swelling or exalted thought may be true with us, there is little, if any, trace of such thoughts in the Veda. Most of the prayers there are very matter-of-fact petitions, and all that has been said of the swelling of the heart, the elevation of the mind, the fervid impulse of the will, as expressed by the word Brahman, soems to me decidedly modern, and without any analogies in the Veda itself. When it is said that the hymns make the gods grow (Vr*dh), this is little more than what we mean by saying that they magnify the gods (Deussen, 1. c., p. 245). Even it: a more profound intention were supposed to be necessary for the word Brahman in the sense of prayer, there would be nothing to prevent its having originally grown out of Brahman in the sense of word. Of course we cannot expect perfect certainty in a matter like this, when we are trying to discover the ahnost imperceptible transitions by which a root which expresses the idea of growing forth 54 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. (Vriddhau), growing strong, bursting forth, increasing, came to supply a name for prayer as well as for deity. This evolution of thought must have taken place long before the Vedic period, long before the Aryan Separation, long before the final constitution of the Aryan language of India. We can but guess therefore, and we should never forget this in trying to interpret the faint traces which the earliest steps of the human mind have left on the half-petrified sands of our language. That Brahman means prayer is certain, and that the root Brih meant to grow, ^0 break forth, is equally certain, and admitted by 1 all. What is uncertain are the intermediate links connecting the two. I suppose, and I can say no more, that Vrih or Brih, which I take to be a parallel form of VrMh, to grow, meant to grow, to come forth, to spread. Hence Brihat means simply great (like great from growing), broad, strong, BarhishtfAa, strongest. We should note, however, though we cannot attribute much importance to the fact, that Brirahati and Brimhayati also were quoted by Indian grammarians in the sense of speaking and shining. Here we can see that speaking could originally have had the meaning of uttering, and that ' word ' has been conceived as that which breaks forth, or is uttered, an utterance (Aus- druck), as we say. The next step to consider is the name Bfihaspati. We must start from the fact that Brihaspati is synonymous with Va/cas-pati, lord of speech. Unless Brih had once meant speech, it would have been impossible to form such a name as T3rhas-pati, as little as Brahman as-pati could have been possible without Br&hman \ From this point once gained I make the next step and suppose that Br&h-man was formed to express what was uttered, what broke forth, or shone forth, that is, the word or speech. If we have arrived at this, we can easily under- stand how the general concept of word was specialised in the sense both of sacred utterance or formula and of prayer; without any idea of swelling meditation or lifting up of 1 See A'Mnd. Up. I, a, n, vag ghi brt'bati, tasyu csha patiA , and VII, ti f 2, yo va/cam brahma *ity upa*ate. Ofc Briii. I, 3, 20. AND BRAHMAN, WORD. 55 hearts, so alien to Vedic poets, such as they are known to us. But if I am right in seeing in Brahman the original meaning of what breaks forth, of a force that manifests itself in audible speech, it will become easy to understand how Brahman couid also, from the very beginning though in a different direction, have been used as a riame of that universal force which manifests itself in the creation of a visible universe. We need not suppose that it had to ascend a scale first from holy word, holy wisdom to the source of that wisdom, the absolute god. Brtli and Brahman, Word. We may suppose therefore I say no more that Brah- man meant force or even germ, so far as it bursts forth, whether in speech or in nature *. But now comes a much more perplexing question. It can hardly be doubted that Vrih or Brih is a parallel form of Vridh ; and it is a well- known fact that both the Latin verbum and the German Wort can be regularly derived from the same root, cor- responding to a possible Sanskrit Vr/h-a or Vr?'dh-a. In that case Brahman also may be taken as a direct derivation in the sense of the uttered word, and brahman as the speaker, the utterer. So far we are still on safe ground, and in the present state of our knowledge I should not venture to go much beyond. But Colebrooke and other Vedic scholars have often pointed out the fact that in the Veda already we find a goddess Va&, speech, which we met in Va/cas-pati and Srfhas-pitr*, the lord of speech. This Va/c, as Colebrooke pointed out as early as 1805, was 'the active power of Brahma, proceeding from him 3 / After reading Colebrooke's remarks on it, few Sanskrit scholars could help being reminded of. the Logos or the Word that was in the beginning, that was with God, and by whom all things were made. The important question, however, 1 Divyud&'-a Datta quotes a passage from the Yognvasisht&a : l Brahma- vrfwhaiva hi j/agiigr, 99 ; provided that Visakha can refer to K&ina shoot- ing his arrows ? EAST AND WEST. 6 1 It cannot be doubted that the art of coining money was introduced into India by the Greeks, and it the images of Indian gods and even of Baddha on ancient coins, may be supposed to have favoured idolatry in India, that too may be admitted. Indian gods, however, were anthropomorphic, had legs and arms, heads, noses and eyes, as early as the Veda, and the absence of workable stone in many parts of India would naturally have been unfavourable to a develop- ment of sculptured idols. The Hindus had a god of love in the Veda, but he was very different from the Kama, imaged on more modern coins as an archer sitting on the back of a parrot. We are now in possession of specimens of much earlier Greek workmanship in India, than this Kama on the back of a parrot, nor is there any reason to doubt that the idea of temples or monasteries or monuments, built and carved in stone, carne from Greece, while some of the Indian archi- tecture, even when in stone, shows as clear surviving traces of a native wood-architecture as, for instance, the Lycian tombs. The later influence which Christianity is supposed to have exercised in originating or in powerfully influencing the sectarian worship of Krtshfta does riot concern us here, for, if it should be admitted at all, it would have to be referred to a much later period than that which gave rise to the six systems of philosophy. Ever since the beginning of Sanskrit studies, nay even before, these startling simi- larities between Krislma and Christos have been pointed out again and again. But iteration yields no strength to argument, and we are as far as ever from being able to point to any historical channel through which the legends of Christ or Krishna could have travelled. No one can deny the similarities, such as they are, but no one, I believe, can account for them. Some of those who have been most anxious to gather coincidences between the Bhagavad-gita and the New Testament, have been rightly warned by native scholars themselves, that they sliould learn to trans- late both Sanskrit and Greek before they venture to com- pare. It should riot be forgotten that as the'Bhagavad-gita bears the title of Upanishad, it may belong to the end of 62 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. the Upanishad-period, and may, as the late Professor Telang maintained, be older even than the New Testament. If Damascius tells us that there were Brahmans living at Alexandria *, we must riot forget that this refers to the end of the fifth century A.D., and does not help us much even as indicating the way by which the idea of the Creative Word could have reached Clement of Alexandria or Origen. That Clement of Alexandria knew the name of Butta is well known, he even knew that he had been taken for a god. Nor should it be forgotten, that Pantaenus who, according to Eusebius, had preached the Gospel in India, was one of the teachers of Clement. But all this is far from proving that Clement or Origen was able to study the Vedanta-Sfttras or the Buddhist Abhidharmas, or that their opinions were influenced by a few Indian travellers staying at Alexandria who cared for none of these things. Some of the coincidences between Buddhism and Christi- anity are certainly startling, particularly by their number, but in several cases they exist on the surface only and are not calculated to carry conviction on one side or the other. I have treated of them on several occasions, for .the last time in my paper on c Coincidences/ but the same coinci- dences, which have been proved to be anything but real coincidences, are repeated again and again. The story cf Buddha sitting under an Indian fig-tree (ficus rdigiosa) has nothing whatever in common with Nathaniel sitting under a Palestinian fig-tree, and the parable *of the Prodigal Son in the Buddhist scriptures is surely very different in spirit from that in the New Testament. There remain quite sufficient similarities to startle and perplex us, without our dragging in what has no power of proving anything. No critical historian would listen for one moment to such arguments as have been used to establish a real exchange of thought between India and Europe in ancient' times. On this point we owe a great deal to students of ethnology, who have pointed out coincidences quite as startling be- tween the religious and philosophical folklore of uncivi- lised and civilised races, without venturing to suggest any See Goblet d'Alviella, 1. c., p. 167. EAST AND WEST. 63 borrowing or any historical community of origin. The iTinvat 1 bridge, for instance, which seems so peculiar to the Persians, had its antecedents as far back as the Veda, and is matched by a similar bridge among the North American Indians 2 . I say, a similar bridge, for it differs also, as I pointed out, very characteristically from the Persian bridge. Again, it is -well known that the creation of the world by the Word has been discovered among so low a race as the Klainaths 3 , but no one has ventured to say that the two accounts had a common origin or were borrowed one from the other. This should serve as a use- ful warning to those who are so fond of suggesting channels through which Indian thought might have influenced Palestine or Greece, and vice versa. No doubt, such channels were there ; neither mountains nor seas would have formed impassable barriers. Besides, Buddhism, as early as the third century B.C., was certainly a missionary religion quite as much as Christianity was at a later time. Alexandria was known by name, as Alasando, to the author of the Mahava?nsa 4 . On the other hand, the name of King Gondaphoros, who is mentioned in the legend of St. Thomas' travels to India, has been authenticated on Indo-Parthian coins as Gondio- phares, likewise the name of his nephew Abdayases, and po&sibly, according to M. S. L^vi, that of Vasu Deva as Misdeos. All this is true, and shows that the way between Alexandria and Benares was wide open in the first century A.D. Nor should* it have been forgotten that in the Dialogues between Milinda and Nagasena we have a well- authenticated case of a Greek king (Menandros), and of a Buddhist philosopher, discussing together some of the highest problems of philosophy and religion. All this is true, and yet we are as far as ever from having discovered a Greek or Indian go-between in flagrante delicto. We have before us ever so many possibilities, nay even proba- bilities, but we could not expect any bond fide historian to accept any one of them as a proof of a real influence 1 Contributions to the Science of Mythology. 2 Theosophy, p. 168. 3 Theosophy, p. 383. * Le Comte d'Alviella, 1. c., p. 177. 64 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY having been exercised by Greece on India or by India on Greece, at a time when Greek philosophy and religion might still have been amenable to Eastern guides, or Indian schools of thought might have gratefully received fresh impulses from the West. Though the literature of India has no trustworthy chronology, still, unless the whole structure of the literary development of India is once more to be revolutionised, we can hardly imagine that the occurrence of such names as Bodcla and Zarades (Zoroaster) among the followers of Mani, or that of Terebinthos the pupil of Scythiaiios 1 , the very founder of the Maniehaean sect in Babylon, would hqlp us to discover the secret springs of the wisdom of Kapila or Buddha $akya Muni. They may point out whence these heresiarchs derived their wisdom, but they leave the question which concerns us here totally untouched. Gorres, in spite of all his mysticism, was right w^hen he looked for a similarity in technical terms in order to establish an Indian influence on Greek or a Greek influence on Indian philosophy.- His principle was right, though he applied it wrongly. It is the same as in Comparative Mythology. There may be ever so many similarities between two mythologies, such as changes of men and women into animals or plants, worship of trees and ancestors, belief in spirits and visions in sleep or dreams, but one such equation as Dyaus = Zeus, is more convincing than all of them taken together. If people ask why, they might as well ask why the discovery of one coin with the name of Augustus on it is a more convincing proof of Roman influence in India than the discovery of ever so many pieces of uncoined gold. To return to the origin of the word Brahman. Tempting 2 1 It has been suggested that Soytliianos may have been an adaptation of Sakya tbe Scythian, a name of Buddha, and Terebinthos mny contain traces of Them (elder). All this is possible, but no more. 2 There is a curious passage in Bhartr/hari's Brahiiuikimd which seems to identify Speech and Brahman. Sec Sarvadursaria-sangraha, Bibl. Ind , p. 140: Anadinidhanam brahma sahdntaltvam yad ukshnram, Vivartate*rthabhavena prakriyA f/ngato yntha. EAST AND WEST. 65 as the distant relationship between Brdhman and Brh, in the sense of speech, with verbwm and Word may be, we could not admit it without admitting at the same time a community of thought; and of deep philosophical thought, at a period previous to the Aryan Separation ; and we certainly have no evidence sufficiently strong to support so bold a hypothesis. What we may carry away from a consideration of the facts hitherto examined is that in India itself Brahman, as a name of the TTP&TGV K.IVOVV, need not have passed through a stage when Brahman meant prayer only, and that Br&hman, prayer, could not have assumed the meaning of the object of prayers, that is, the Universal Spirit, who never required any prayers at all. In order to show what direction the thoughts connected with Va& took in the Veda, I shall first of all subjoin here a few passages from the hymns, the Bnihma?ias and Upanishads : V&&, speech, speaking in her own name, is introduced in hymn X, 125, also in Atharva-veda IV, 30, as saying: ' i. I wander with the Vasus and the Rudras, I wander with the Adityas and the Visve Devas, I support Mitra and Varuwa both, I support Agni and the two Asvins ; 2. I support the swelling (?) Soma, I support Tvasbtfr^ and Pftshan and Bhaga. I bestow wealth on the zealous offerer, on the sacrilicer who presses Soma. 3. I am the queen, the gatherer of riches, the knowing, first of those who merit worship ; the gods have thus established me in many places, staying with many, entering into many. 4. By me it is that he who sees, he who breathes, he 'who hears what is spoken, eats food; without knowing it, they rest on me* Hear, one and all ! I tell thee what I believe. (?) Brahman without beginning or end, which is the eternal essence of speech, Is changed into the form of things, like the evolution of the world. Equally strong is the statement of Madhava himself, Spho&khyo nirava- yavo nityafc sabdo brahmaiveti, 'The eternal word which is called S photo and does not consist of parts, is indeed Brahman.' 5 V 66 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. 5. I, even I myself, say this, what is good for gods, and also for men; whomsoever I love, him I make formidable, him I make a Brahman, him a Rishi, him a sage. 6. I bend the bow for Rudra (the storm-god) that his arrow may strike the hater of Brahman ; I make war for the people, I have entered both heaven and earth. 7. I bring forth the (my?) father (Dyaus) on the summit of this world, my origin is in the waters, in the sea ; from thence I spread over all beings, and touch yonder heaven with my height. 8. I indeed spread forth like the wind, to lay hold on all things, beyond the sky, beyond the earth; such have I become through my greatness/ I ask, is there any trace in these utterances of the thoughts that led in the end to the conception of the Greek Logos? There is another hymn (X, 71) which is very obscure and has for the first time been rendered more intelligible by Professor Deussen (A. G. P., p. 148), where we meet with some important remarks showing that language formed an object of thought even at that early tinie. But here also there is nothing, as yet, approaching to the conception of the Word as a creative power. We meet' with such observations as that words were made in the beginning in order to reveal what before had been hidden.' This is, no doubt, an important thought, showing that those who uttered it had not yet ceased, like our- selves, to wonder at the existence of such a thing as l&nguage. The struggle for life that is going on among words is alluded to by saying that the wise made speech by mind (Manas), silting as by a sieve the coarsely ground flour. The power of speech is greatly extolled, and elo-' quence is celebrated as a precious gift. All men shout when the eloquent man appears, holding the assembly subdued or spellbound by his words (Sabh&saha), nay he is supposed to remove all sin and to procure sustenance for his friends. The knowledge of all things or, as Deussen says, the knowledge of the origin of things, is taught by the Br&hman. We meet with passages of a very similar character, in MIND AND SPEECH. 67 various parts of the BrahmaTias. One of the most startling is found in a verse inserted in the Purusha-hymn, as given in the Taittiriya-aranyaka (III, 12, 17), ' I know that great sun-coloured Purusha, when on the verge of ,darkness, he, the wise, rests, addressing them, after having thought all forms, and having made their names/ Here we have only to translate forms by t6r?, and names by \6yoi, and we shall not be very far from the world of thought in which Plato and Aristotle 1 moved. But although we can discover in this hymn an apprecia- tion of the mysterious nature of speech, we look in vain for the clear and definite idea that language and thought are one, which can be so clearly read in the Greek word Logos, both word and thought, nor do we find more than plight anticipations of the Neo-platonist dogma that the creation of the universe was in reality an utterance of the hidden thoughts and words of the Deity. Mind and Speech. The following passages will give some idea of what was thought in India about mind and language and their mutual relation. They may be vague and mystical, but they show at all events that a good deal of thought must have been expended by the early thinkers of India on this problem, the nature of speech and the relation between speech and thought. $atap. Brahinana VI, i, i : ' Prar/apati, after having created the Veda (Brahman, neut.), created the waters out of Va/c (speech), for Va/c was his. That was created (sent forth). He then entered the waters with Brahman, i. e. the threefold Veda, and there arose from the water an egg which he touched and commanded to multiply. Then from' the egg there arose first Brahman, neut., that is, the three- fold Veda.' Paw/cavimsa Brahmana XX, 14, 2 : ' Pras 6V, rd Trpwrou KWOVV, though, even of those terms, as we shall see, not one corresponds fully and exactly to the character of Brdhman as developed in the history of the Indian mind. The next word we have to examine is Atman. It is next in importance to Brahman only, and the two together may be called the two pillars on which rests nearly the whole of the edifice of Indian philosophy, more particularly of the Vedanta and Samkhya systems. 1 Taitt. Br. II, 7, 17, i. ATMAN. 71 As early as the time of the Apastamba-Sutras, that is, at the end of the Vedic period, we read, I, 8, 23, i : * The BrahmaTia who is wise and recognises all things to be in the Atman, who does not become bewildered when pondering (on it), and who recognises the Atman in every (created) thing, he shines indeed in heaven . . .' And in the same Sutras, I, 8, 23, 2, we find a definition of Brahman, as the cause of the world, which presupposes, as clearly as possible, the prevalence of Vedantic ideas l at the time of the author of this Sutra : c He who is intelligence itself and subtler than the thread of the lotus-fibre, He who pervades the universe and who, unchangeable and larger than the earth, contains this universe; He who is different from the knowledge of this world which is obtained by the senses and is identical with its objects, possesses the highest (form of absolute knowledge). From him who divides himself, spring all (objective) bodies. He is the primary cause, eternal and unchangeable.' The etymology of Atman is again extremely obscure, probably because it belongs to a pre-Sanskritie, though Aryan stratum of Indian speech. However, there can be little doubt that in the Veda Atman, in several places, still means breath, as in Rv. X, 16, 3, suryam Jfc&kshuA ga/cMatu, va'tam atma, words addressed ^ to a dead person, ' May the eye go to the sun, the breath (Atma) to the wind/ It then came to mean vital breath, life, and, like the spirit or breath, was frequently used in the sense of vrhat *we call soul. In some passages it is difficult to say whether we should translate it by life or by spirit. From soul there is but a small step to Self, and that step is often gram- matical rather than real. If -in the Atharva-veda IX, 5, 30 we read : Atnictnain pitarain putram pautram pitamaham, (ray am #amtrim mataiam ye priyas tan upa hvaye, we have to translate in English, ' Myself, father, son, grand- 1 Yoga and Mimarnsti also are mentioned by name in the Apastamba- Sntras, but not yet as definite systems of philosophy. Cf. I, 8, 23, 5; _ II, 4. 8, 13. 72 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. son, grandfather, wife, mother, whoever are dear, I call upon them/ But Self may here be translated by soul or person also, just as we may say, * My soul doth magnify the Lord/ instead of ' I magnify the Lord/ Again we read, Rv. IX, 113, i, balam ddhanaA atmni, 'putting strength into oneself/ In the end Atman became the regular pronoun self. I need not go through all the evidence which may be seen in any Sanskrit dictionary 1 , but we have still to see at what stage in its development Atman became the definite name of the soul or Self within. This transition of meaning in Atman offers a curious parallel to that of As, in Asu and Asti, which we examined before. There are passages such as Rv. I, 164, 4, bhflmyaA isu& asrik &tma kva svit, * Where was the breath, the blood, the spirit of the world?* Here Atma may be rendered by spirit or life. But in other passages Atman signifies simply the inmost nature of anything, and more par- ticularly of man, so that in the end it means much the same as what medieval philosophers would have called the quiddity, or Indian philosophers the Idanta of things. Thus we read at first &tinanam atman& pa.sya, ' see thy Self by thy Self ; ' atmaiva hy &trnana/i sakshi, * Self is the witness of Self/ In this sense Atman is afterwards used as the name of the highest person, the soul of the world (Paramatnian), and we read ($atap. Br. XIV, 5, 5, 15): sa va ayam atma sarvesham^ bh&tanam adliipatiA, sarve- sham bhfttanam ra#a, ' That Atman is the sovereign of all beings, he is the king of all beings/ Pra^&pati, Brahman, Atman. We have thus seen three words growing up in the hymns and Brahmanas of the Veda, Prac/apati, Brahman, and Atman, each of which by itself represents in mice a whole philosophy or a view of the world. In Pra#apati we have the admission of a personal and supreme being, a god above all gods, a creator and ruler of the world. He created the primeval waters and rose from them as Hirawyagarbha, 1 See Anthropological Religion, pp. 200 seq. ; Theosophy, pp. 247 seq., or more recently, Deussen's Geschichte der Philosophic, pp. 324 seq. PRACZAPATI, BRAHMAN, ATM AN. 73 in order to send forth, to animate, and to rule all things. Whether this Pra#apati was himself the material cause of the world may seem doubtful. Many times it is said that he was everything and that he desired to become many, and thus created the world, in which case matter also would have come out of him. In other places, how- ever, the primeval waters seem to have been admitted as existing by themselves and apart from Prac/apati (Rv. X, 121, 7). We also read that in the beginning there was water over which Pra t gapati breathed as wind and produced the earth, or that the waters themselves produced a golden egg from whence arose Pragfapati, the creator of gods and men. There occur even in the Brahma^as allusions to the legend well known from the Puramis, that a boar brought forth (Udbabarha or Udvavarha from Vrih) the earth, or that a tortoise supported it 1 . A belief in that Pra^apati, as a personal god, was the beginning of monotheistic religion in India, while the recognition of Brahman and Atman, as one, constituted the foundation of all the monistic philosophy of that country. 1 M. M., India, pp. 134, 287. CHAPTER III. THE SYSTEMS OP PHILOSOPHY. Growth of Philosophical Ideas. WE have thus learnt the important lesson that all these ideas, metaphysical, cosmological, and otherwise, burst forth in India in great profusion and confusion, and without any preconceived system. We must not suppose that these ideas follow each other in chronological succession. Here once more the Neben- einander gives us the true key, much more than the Nacheinander. We must remember that this earliest philo- sophy existed for a long time without being fixed by writing, that there was neither control, authority, nor public opinion to protect it. Every Asrama or settlement was a world by itself, even the -simplest means of com- munication, such as high-roads or rivers, being often want- ing. The wonder is that, in spite of all this, we should find so much unity ii\ the numerous guesses at truth pre- served to us among these Vedic ruins. This was due, we are told, to the Parampara, i. e. to those who handed down the tradition and at last collected whatever could be saved of it. It would be a mistake to imagine that there was a continuous development in the various meanings assumed by or assigned to such pregnant terms as Prapapati, Brahman, or even Atman. It is much more in accordance with what we learn from the Brfthmanos and Upanisbads of the intellectual life of India, to admit an infinite number of intellectual centres of thought, scattered all over the country, in which either the one or the other view found influential advocates. We should then understand better PRASTHANA BHBDA. 75 how Brahman, while meaning what bursts or drives forth, came to signify speech and A prayer, as well as creative power and creator, and why Atman meant not only breath, but life, spirit, soul, essence, or what I have ventured to render by the Self, das Sdbst^ of all things. But if in the period of the Brahnianas and Upanishads we have to find our way through religious and philo- sophical thoughts, as through clusters of thickly tangled creepers, the outlook becomes brighter as soon as we approach the next period, which is characterised by per- sistent attempts at clear and systematic thought. We must not imagine that even then we can always discover in the various systems of philosophy a regular historical growth. The Sutras or aphorisms which we possess of the six systems of philosophy, each distinct from the other, cannot possibly claim to represent the very first attempts at a systematic treatment ; they are rather the last summing up of what had been growing up during many generations of isolated thinkers, Prasth&na Bheda. What the Brahmans themselves thought of their philo- sophical literature we may learn even from such modern treatises as the Prasthana-bheda, from which I gave some extracts by way of introduction to some papers of mine on one of the systems of Indian philosophy, published as long ago as 1852 in the Journal of the German Oriental Society. It is but fair to state that the credit of having discovered that tract of Madhusiidana Sarasvati, and perceived its importance, belonged really to Colebrooke. I myself came to be acquainted with it through my old friend, Dr. Trithen, who had prepared a critical edition of it, but was prevented by illness and death from publishing it. It was published in the meantime by Professor Weber in his Indische Studien, j 849, and I think it may be useful to give once more some extracts from it l . 1 A new translation of the Prasthaua-bheda lias been published by Prof. Deussen as an Introduction to his Allgemeine Geschichte der Philosophic, vol. i, p. 44, 1894. 76 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. ' Nyaya 1 / he writes, * is logic 2 , as promulgated by Gotarna 3 in five Adhyayas (lessons). Its object is knowledge of the nature of the sixteen Padarthas by means of name, defini- tion, and examination/ These Padarthas are the important or essential topics of the Nyaya philosophy; but it has proved very misleading to see Padartha here translated by categories. No one could understand why such things as doubt, example, wrangling, &c., could possibly be called categories or praed,icahilia, and it is no wonder that Bitter and others should have spoken of the Nyaya with open contempt, as they have done, if such things were repre- sented to them as the categories of Indian logic. ' There is also the Vaiseshika philosophy in ten lessons, promulgated by Kanda. Its object is- to establish by their similarities and dissimilarities 4 the six Badarthas, viz. : 1. Dravya, substance. 2. Guna, quality. 3. Karman, activity. 4. Samanya, what is general and found in more than one object. The highest Samanya is Satta or being. 5. Visesha, the differentia or what is special, residing in eternal atoms, &c. 6. Samavaya, inseparable inherence, as between cause and effect, parts and the whole, c. To which may be added 7. Abh/iva, negation. This philosophy also is called Nyaya/ The,se Padarthas of the Vaiseshikas, at least 1-5, may indeed be called categories, for they represent what can be 1 Nyaya is derived from ni 'into,' and i Ho go.' The fourth member of a 'syllogism is called Upanaya, * leading towards* or * induction.' Balla'Atynu translates Nyaya by pftioSos. a Anvikshiki as an old name of philosophy, more particularly of logic, OCCUYS also in Gautama's Dharrnasastra II, 3. It is used sometimes as synonymous with Mimuwsa, and is more comprehensive than logic. 3 As the MSS. vary between Gotuma and Gautama, I have kept the former for the Nyayfi, 'philosopher,' the latter for Buddha. * Barthelemy St. Hilaire, in his work on Indian Logic, p. 356, remarks, 'Kais le philosophe Vai.seshika n'a point cherche* a distinguer lea categories entre elles, en <5riumernnt leurs propriltes, com me Ta fait le S*;agirite. II n'a point montre*, eomme Aristote, leurs rapports et leurs differences.' But this is exactly what he has done, cf. Sutras I, 8 seq. PRASTHANA BEEDA. 77 Eredicated, in general, of the objects of our experience, or, :om an Indian point of view, what is predicated by, or what is the highest sense (Artha) of words (Pada). Thus it has come to pass that Padartba, literally the meaning of a word, was used in Sanskrit in the sense of things in genera], or objects. It is rightly translated by category when applied to the five Pad&rthas of Kaw&da, but such a translation, doubtful even in the case of the sixth or seventh Padartha of the Vaiseshikas, would of course be quite misleading when applied to the Padarthas of Gotama. The real categories would, in Ootama's system, find their pjace mostly under Prameya, meaning not so much what has to be proved or established, as what forms the object of our knowledge. Madhusftdana continues : * The Mimamsa also is twofold, viz. the Karma-Mimamsa (work-philosophy) and the S&ri- raka-Mim&msd, (philosophy of the embodied spirit). The Karma-Mimamssl has been brought out by the venerable Craimini in twelve chapters/ The objects of these twelve chapters are then indicated very shortly, and so as to be hardly intelligible without a reference to the original Sutras. Dharma, the object of this philosophy, is explained as consisting of acts of duty, chiefly sacrificial. The second, third, and fourth chapters treat l of the differences and varieties of Dharma, its parts (or appendent members, contrasted with the main act), and the principal purpose of each sacrificial performance. The fifth chapter tries to settle the order of all sacrificial per- formances, and the sixth the qualifications of its performers. The subject of indirect precepts is opened in the seventh chapter and carried on more fully in the eighth. Inferrible changes, adapting to any variation or copy of certain sacrincial acts what was designed for the types or models of them, are discussed in the ninth, and bars or exceptions in the tenth. Concurrent efficacy is considered in the eleventh chapter, and co-ordinate effect in the twelfth ; that is, the co-operation of several acts for a single result is the 1 I give this more intelligible description from Colebrooke, Miscellaneous Essays, vol. i, p. 330 seq. 78 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. subject of the one, and the incidental effect of an act, of which the chief purpose is different,, is discussed in the other l . 'There is also the Sa?rikarshafta-k&?MZa, consisting of four chapters, composed by Gaimini, and this,, which is known by the name of Devata-k&ncfai,, belongs to the Karma-Mimawsa, because it teaches the act called Upasanli, or worship. * Next follows the $&riraka-M}ma/wsa, consisting of four chapters. Its A object is to make clear the oneness of Brahman and Atman (Self), and to exhibit the rules, which teach the investigation (of it) by means of Vedic study, &c/ It is in fact much more what we call a system of philosophy than the Purva-Mim&msa, and it is quoted by different names, such as Uttara-Mim&ms&, Brahma-Mimams&, Ve- d&nta, &c. 2 * In the first lecture is shown the agreement with which all Vedanta passages refer, directly or indirectly, to the inward, undivided, second-less Brahman. In the first section are considered Vedic passages which have clear indications of Brahman ; in the second, passages which have obscure indications of Brahman, and refer to Brahman so far as he is an object of worship; in the third, passages which have obscure indications of Brahman, and mostly refer to Brahman, so far as he or it is an object of knowledge. Thus the consideration of the Vedanta texts has been finished, and in the fourth section such words as Avyakta, A.g&, &c., are considered, of which it can be doubtful whether they may not refer to ideas, adapted and formu- lated by the Samkhya philosophers, such as Pradhana, Prakriti, which is generally, though quite wrongly, trans- lated by nature, as independent of Brahman or Purusha. ' The convergence of all Ved&nta texts on the second-less Brahman having thus been established, Vyasa or Badara- yawa, fearing an opposition by means of arguments such as 1 Professor Deussen has given a somewhat different version of these titles. He gives, for instance, as the subject of the fifth chapter the successive order of recitation, as enjoined by Srtiti, but to judge from Mim. Sutras V, i, i, the right meaning seems to be the * settling of the order of performance, according to Sruti, subject-matter, recitation, &c." a Read Adya for Akhya in the Frasthana bheda. PRASTHANA BHEDA. 79 have been produced by acknowledged Smritis and various other systems, undertakes their refutation, and tries to establish the incontrovertible validity of his own argu- ments in the second lecture. Here, in the first section, the objections to the convergence of the Vedanta passages on Brahman, as stated by the Smritis of the Samkhya-yoga, the K?iadas, and by the arguments employed by the Samkhyas, are disposed of. In the second section is shown the f aultiness of the views of the followers of the S&mkhya, because every examination should consist of two parts, the establishment of our own doctrine and the refutation of the doctrine of our opponents. In the third section the contradictions between the passages of the Veda, referring to the creation of the elements and other subjects, are removed in the first part, and in the second those referring to individual souls. In the fourth section are considered all apparent contradictions between Vedic passages referring to the senses and their objects. f ln the third chapter follows the examination of the means (of salvation). Here in the first section, while con- sidering the going to and returning from another world (transmigration), dispassionateness has to be examined. In the second section, the meaning of the word Thou is made clear, and afterwards the meaning of the word That. In the third section there is a collection of words, if not purely tautological, all referring to the unqualified Brahman, as recorded in different akhas or branches of the Veda ; and at the same time the question is discussed whether certain attributes recorded by other jS&kh&s in teaching a qualified or unqualified Brahman, may be taken together or not. In the fourth section the means of obtaining a knowledge of the unqualified Brahman, both the external, such as sacrifices and observing the four stations in life, and the internal, such as quietness, control, and meditation, are investigated. * In the fourth chapter follows an inquiry into the special rewards or fruits of a knowledge of the qualified and un- qualified Brahman. In the first section is described salva- tion of a man even in this life, when free from the influence of good or bad acts, after he has realised the unqualified Brahman by means of repeated study of the Veda, &c. In 8O INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. the second section the mode of departure of a dying man is considered. In the third, the further (northern) road of a man who died with a full knowledge of the unqualified Brahman is explained. In the fourth section the obtain- ment of disembodied aloneness by a man who knows the unqualified Brahman is first described, and afterwards the abode in the world of Brahman, promised to all who know the qualified (or lower) Brahman. ' This, the Vedanta, is indeed the principal of all doctrines, any other doctrine is but a complement of it, and therefore it alone is to be reverenced by all who wish for liberation, and this according to the interpretation of the venerable $amkara this is the secret ! ' Here we see clearly that Madhusudana considered the Vedanta-philosophy as interpreted by $amkara, if not as the only true one, still as the best of all philosophies. He made an important distinction also between the four, the Nyaya, Vaiseshika, P&rva, and Uttara-MimamsS, on one side, and the remaining two, the Samkhya and Yoga- philosophies on the other. It is curious indeed that this distinction has been hitherto so little remarked. According to Madhusftdana, the philosophies of Gotama and Ka?iada are treated simply as Srnritis or Dharmasastras, like the Laws of Manu, nay like the Mahabharata l of Vyasa, and the RamayaTia of Valmiki. Of course these systems of philosophy cannot be called SmHti in the ordinary sense of Dharmas&stra ; but, as they are Snm'ti or tradition, and not $ruti or revelation, they may be said to teach Dharma, if not in legal, at least in the moral sense of that word. Anyhow it is clear that S&mkhya and Yoga were looked upon as belonging to a class different from that to which the two Mimamsas, nay even Nyaya and Vaiseshika, and the other recognised branches of knowledge belonged, which together are* represented as the eighteen branches of the Trayi (the Veda). Though it may be difficult to understand the exact reason of this distinction, the distinction itself should not be passed over. 'The Samkhya/ Madhusfldana continues, 'was brought 1 See Dnhlinann, Das Mahabhftrata als Epos und Rechtsbuch, 1896. PRASTHANA BHEDA. . 8 1 out by the venerable Kapila in six Adhyayas. In the first Adhy&ys the objects for discussion are considered ; in the second the effects or products of Pradliana, or original matter; in the third aloofness from sensuous objects; in the fourth stories about dispassionate persons, such as Pingala (IV, n), the fletcher (IV, 18), &c.; in the fifth there is refutation of opposite opinions; in the sixth a resume of the whole. The chief object of the Samkhya- philosophy is to teach the difference between Prakriti and the Purushas. 'Then follows the Yoga-philosophy as taught by the venerable Pata/?<7ali, consisting of four parts. Here in the first part meditation, which stops the activity and distrac- tion of the mind, and, as a means towards it, repeated practice and dispassionateness, are discussed ; in the second the eight accessories which serve to produce deep medita- tion even in one whose thoughts are distracted, such as (II, 29) restraint, observances, posture, regulation of breath, devotion, contemplation, and meditation ; in the- third, the supernatural powers; in the fourth aloneness. The chief object of this philosophy is to achieve concentration by means of stopping all wandering thoughts/ After this follows a short account of the Pasupata and Patt/caratra-systems, and then a recapitulation which is of interest. Here Madhusftdana says, ' that after the various systems have been explained, it should be clear that there are after all but three roads. i. The Arambha-vada,the theory of atomic agglomeration. * a. The Parirmma-vada, the theory of evolution. 3. The Vivarta-vada, the theory of illusion. The first theory holds that the four kinds of atoms (ATIU), those of earth, water, fire, and air, by becoming successively double atoms, &c., begin the world which culminates in the egg of Brahman. This first theory, that of the Tarkikas (Nyaya and Vaiseshika) and the Mimamsakas, teaches that an effect which was not (the world), is produced through the activity of causes which are. The second theory, that of the Samkhyas, Yoga-pa ta/7#a- las, and Pasupatas, says that Pradhana alone, sometimes 6 G 82 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. called Prak?'iti or original matter, composed, as it is, of the Gu?*as of Sattva (good), Ra#as (moderate), and Tamas (bad), is evolved through the stages of Mahat (per- ceiving) and Ahamkara (subjectivity) ink) the shape of the (subjective and objective) world. From this point of view the effected world existed before as real, though in a subtile (invisible) form, and was. rendered manifest through the activity of a cause. ^Ihe third theory, that of the Brahmavadins (Vedanta), says that the^ self-luminous and perfectly blissful Brahman which has no second, appears by mistake, through its own power of Maya, as the world, while the Vaislmavas (Ramanugra, &c.) hold that the world is an actual and true evolution of Brahman. But in reality all the Munis who have put forward these theories agree in wishing to prove the existence of the one Supreme Lord without a second, ending in the theory of illusion (Vivarta). These Munis cannot be in error, con- sidering that they are omniscient; and these different views have only been propounded by them, in order to keep off all nihilistic theories, and because they were afraid that human beings, with their inclinations towards the objects of the world, could not be expe'cted at once to know the true goal of man. But all comes right when we understand that men, from not understanding their true object, imagined that these Munis would have propounded what is contrary to the Veda, and thus, accepting their opinions, have become followers of various paths/ Much of what has here been translated from Madhu- sftdana's Prasthana-bheda, though it gives, a general survey, is obscure, but will become more intelligible hereafter when we come to examine each of the six philosophies by itself ; nor is it at all certain that his view of the development of Indian philosophy is historically tenable. But it shows at all events a certain freedom of thought, which we see now and then in other writers also, such as Vi<7/7ana-bhikshu, who are bent on showing that there is behind the diversity of Vedanta, Sa/mkhya, and Nyaya one and the same truth, though differently expressed; that philosophies, in fact, may be many, but truth is one. PRASTHANA BHEDA. 83 But however we may admire this insight on the part of Madhusudana and others, it is our duty, as historians of philosophy, to study the different paths by which different philosophers, whether by the light of revelation or by thaty of their own unfettered reason, have striven to discover the trr.th. It is the very multiplicity and variety of these paths that form the chief interest of the history of philo- sophy, and the fact that to the present day these six different systems of philosophy have held their own in the midst of a great multitude of philosophic theories, pro- pounded by the thinkers of India, shows that we must first of all try to appreciate their characteristic peculiarities, before attempting with Madhusudana to eliminate their distinctive features. These philosophers are 1. Badarayana, called also Vyasa Dvaipayana orKrislma Dvaipayana, the reputed author of the Brahma-Sutras, called also Uttara-Mimamsa-Sutras, or V/asa-Sutras. 2. (jaimini, the author of the PCirva-Mim&msa-Sutras. 3. Kapila, the author of the Samkhya-Sutras. 4. Pata/7(T/ali, also called $esha or PhaTiin, the autlior of the Yoga-Sutras. 5. Kanada, also called Kanabhu#, Karcabhakshaka, or Ult A ika, the author of the Vaiseshika-Sutras. 6. Gotama, also called Akshapada, the author of the Nyaya-Sutras. It is easy to see that the philosophers to whom our Sutras are ascribed, cannot be considered as the first originators of Indian philosophy. These Sutras often refer to other philosophers, who therefore must have existed before the time when the Sfttras received their final form. Nor could the fact that c ome of the Sutras quote and refute the opinions of other Sfttras, be accounted for without admitting a growing up of different philo- sophical schools side by side during a period which pre- ceded their last arrangement. Unfortunately such refer ences hardly ever give us the title of a book, or its author, still less the ipsissima verba. When they refer to such topics as Purusha and Prakriti we know that they refer to the S&mkhya, if they speak of A?ius or atoms, we know a 2 84 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. that their remarks are pointed at the Vaiseshikas. But it by no means follows that they refer to the Samkhya or Vaiseshika-Sfttras exactly as we now possess them. Some of these, as has been proved, are so modern that they could not possibly be quoted by ancient philosophers. Our S&mkhya-Sfttras, for instance, have been proved by Dr. F. Hall to be not earlier than about 1380 A. D., and they may be even later. Startling as this discovery was, there is certainly nothing to be said against the arguments of Dr. Hall or against those by which Professor Garbe l has supported Dr. Hall's discovery. In this case, therefore, these Sutras should be looked upon as a mere rifaccimento, to take, the place of earlier S&tras, which as early as the sixth cent. A.D. had probably been already superseded by the popular S&mkhya-k&rik&s and then forgotten. This late date of our Samkhya-Sutras may seem incredible, but though I still hold that the Sutra-style arose in a period when writing for literary purposes was still in its tentative stage, we know that even in our time there are learned Pandits who find no difficulty in imitating this ancient Sutra-style. The Sutra-period, reaching down as far as Asoka's reign in the third century, and his Council in 243 B.C., .claims not only the famous Sutras of P&Tiini, but has also been fixed upon as the period of the greatest philosophical activity in India, an activity called forth, it would seem, by the strong commotion roused by the rise of the Buddhist school of philosophy, and afterwards of religion. Literary References in the Upanlshads. It is of considerable importance to remember that of the technical names of the six systems of philosophy, two only occur in the classical Upanishads, namely Samkhya and Yoga or S&wkhya-yoga. Vedanta does not occur, except in the $vet&8vatara, MumZaka and some of the later Upanishads 2 . Mima;m8& occurs in the general sense of investigation, Nyaya 1 Garbe, Die Sawkhya-Philosophie, p. 71. 8 A curious distinction is made in a commentary on the Gautama- Sutras XIX, 12, where it is said that ' those parts of the Aranyakas which ar* not Upanishads are called Vedantas.' THE SIX SYSTEMS OP PHILOSOPHY. 85 and Vaiseshika are altogether absent, nor do we meet with such words as Hetuvidya, or Anvikshiki, nor with the names of the reputed founders of the six systems, except those of the two Mimamsas, Badaraya?ia and ffaimini. The names of Pata/tyali, or Ka^ada, are absent altogether, while the names of Kapila and Gotarna, when they occur, refer, it would seem, to quite different personalities, The Six Systems of Philosophy. No one can suppose that those whose names are men- tioned as the authors of these six philosophical systems, were more than the final editors or redactors of the Sutras as we now possess them. If the third century B.C. should seem too late a date for the introduction of writing for literary purposes in India, we should remember that even inscriptions have not yet been found more ancient than those of Asoka, and there is a wide difference between inscriptions and literary compositions. The Southern Buddhists do not claim to have reduced their Sacred Canon to writing before the first century B.C., though it is well known that they kept up close relations with their Northern co-religionists who were acquainted with writ- ing 1 . During all that time, therefore, between 477 and 77 B.C., ever so many theories of the world, partaking of a Vedanta, Sa??ikhya or Yoga, nay even of a Buddhist character, could have sprung A up and have been reduced to a mnemonic form in various Asramas. We need not wonder that much of that literature, considering that it could be mnemonic only, should have been irretrievably lost, and we must take care also not to look upon what has been left to us in the old Darcanas, as representing the whole outcome of the philosophical activity of the whole of India through so many generations. All we can say is that philosophy began to ferment in India during the period filled by Branmittas and Upanishads, nay even in some of the Vedic hymns, that the existence of Upanishads, though not necessarily our own, is recognised in the Bud- dhist Canon, and lastly that the name of Suttas, as a 1 The snered Bo-tree in. the city of Anuradhapura in Ceylon was grown, we are told, from a branch of the tree at Buddha Gaya. 86 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. component part of the Buddhist Canon, must be later than that of the earliest Brahmanic Sutras, because in the mean- time the ' meaning of the word had been changed from short mnemonic sentences to fully developed discourses. Possibly Sutra was originally meant for the text to be elucidated in a sermon, so that the long Buddhistic sermons came to be called Suttas in consequence. Brihaspati-S&tras. That some of the earlier philosophical Sutras were lost, is shown in* the case of the Brihaspati-Sutras. These are said to have contained the doctrines of the out and out materialists, or sensualists, the Laukayatikas or 7farvakas, who deny the existence of everything beyond what is given by the senses. They are referred to by Bhaskara- Hrya at Brahma-Sutras III, 3, 53 *, and as he gives an extract, it is likely that they still existed in his time, though no MS. of them has been found as yet in India. The same applies to such Sutras as the Vaikhanasa-Sutras, possibly intended for the Yanaprasthas, and the Bhikshu- Sutras-, quoted by PaTiini, IV, 3, no, and intended, it would seem, for Brahmanic, and not yet for Buddhistic mendicants. It is a sad truth which we have to learn more and more, that of the old pre-Buddhistic literature we have but scanty fragments, and that even these may be, in some cases, mere reproductions of lost originals, as in the case of the Samkhya- Sutras. We know now that such Sutras could have been produced at any time, and we should not forget that even at present, in the general decay of Sanskrit scholarship, India still possesses scholars who can imitate K&lidasa, to say nothing of such poems as the Mahabharata and Ramayana, and so successfully that few scholars could tell the difference. It is not long ago that I received a Sanskrit treatise written in Sutras with a com- mentary, the work of a living scholar in India, which might have deceived many a European scholar of Sanskrit 1 Colebrooke^ Misc. Essays*, I, 429. 3 They were identified by T&r&n&tha Tarkav&tospati with the Vedanta- Sutras ; see Siddhanta KaumudS, vol. i, p. 593. BOOKS OF REFERENCE. 87 literature \ If that is possible now, if, as in the case ot the Kapila-Sutras, it was possible in the fourteenth cen- tury, why should not the same have taken place during the period of the Renaissance in India, nay even "at an earlier time ? At all events, though grateful for what has been preserved, and preserved in what may seem to us an almost miraculous manner, we should not imagine that we possess all, or that we possess what we possess in its original form. Books of Reference. I shall mention here some of the most important works only, from which students of philosophy, particularly those ignorant of Sanskrit, may gain by themselves a knowledge of the six recognised systems of Indian Philosophy. The titles of the more important of the original Sanskrit texts may be found in Colebrooke's Miscellaneous Essays, vol. ii, p. 239 seq., and in the Catalogues, published since his time, of the various collections of Sanskrit MSS. in Europe and India. - For the Vedanta-philosophy of Badaraya^a the most useful book is Thibaut.'s English translation of the text of the Sutras and $arakara's commentary in the S. B. E., vols. xxxiv and xxxviii. Of books written in German, Deussen's translation of the same work, 1887, preceded as it was by his 'System des Vedanta/ 1883, can be thoroughly recommended. Of the Samkhya-system we have the Sutras translated by Ballantyne in 1882-1885, the Aphorisms of the Samkhya Philosophy of Kapila, with illustrative extracts from the Commentaries, 1852, 1865, 1885. In German we have the Samkhya-Prava&ana-Bhashya, Vi7ana-bhikshu's Commentar zu den Samkhya-Sutras, ubersstzt von R. Garbe, 1889. Also Aniruddha's Com- mentary and the original parts of Vedantin Mahadeva's commentary on the S&wkhya-Sutras, by Richard Garbe, J 892. 1 It is called KatantraArfcfcandaftprakriya by JTandrakanta Tarkalankara, 1896, and gives additional Sutras to the Katantra on Vedic Grammar. He makes no secret that Sutraw vnttis A-obhayam api mayaiva vyara# ' the Sutra and the commentary, both were composed by me.' 88- INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Der Mondschein der Samkhya Wahrheit, Va/raspatimi^ra's Samkhya- tattva-kauinudi, iibersetzt von R. Garbe, 1892, is also a very useful work. The S&mkhya Karika by f swarakrishna, translated from the Sanscrit by H. T. Colebrooke, also the Bhashya or com- mentary by Gaurapada; translated and illustrated by an original comment by H. H. Wilson, Oxford, 1837, may still be consulted with advantage. Other useful works are : John Davies, Hindu Philosophy. The Sankhya Karika of IswarakVishna, London, 1881. Die Samkhya-Philosophie, nach den Quellen, von R. Garbe, 1894. Of the Purva-Mimamsa or simply Mtmamsa, which deals chiefly with the nature and authority of the Veda with special reference to sacrificial and other duties, we have the Sfttras with /Sabarasvamin's commentary published in the original; but there is as yet no book in English in which that system may be studied, except Professor Thi- baut's translation of Laugakshi Bhaskara's Arthasamgraha, a short abstract of that philosophy, published in the Benares Sanskrit Series, No. 4. The Vaiseshika system of philosophy may be studied in an English translation of its S&tras by A. E. Gough, Benares, 1873 ; also in a German translation by Roer, Zeitschriffc der Deutschen Morgenlandischen Gesellschaft, vols. 21 and 22, and in some articles of mine in the same Journal of the German Oriental Society, 1849. The Nyaya-Sfttras of Gotama have been translated, with the exception of the last book, by Ballantyne, Allahabad, 1850-57. The Yoga-Sfttras are accessible in an English translation by Rajendralala Mitra, in the Bibiiotheca Indica, Nos. 462, 478, 482, 491, and 492. Dates of the Philosophical Sfctras. If we consider the state of philosophical thought in India such as it is represented to us in the Brahmawas and Upanishads, and afterwards in the canonical books of the Buddhists, we cannot wonder that all attempts at fixing DATES OP THE PHILOSOPHICAL SttTEAS. 89 the dates of the six recognised systems of philosophy, nay even their mutual relationship, should hitherto have failed. It is true that Buddhism and ffainism were likewise but two philosophical systems out of many, and that it has been possible to fix" their dates. But if in their case we know something about their dates and their historical development, this is chiefly due to the social and political importance which they acquired during the fifth, the fourth, and the third centuries B. o., and not simply to their philosophical tenets. We know also that there were many teachers, contemporaries of Buddha, but they have left no traces in the literary history of India. Nor should we forget that, though the date of the Buddhist Canon may be fixed, the date of many of the texts which we now possess and accept as canonical is by no means beyond the reach of doubt. In the Buddhist annals themselves other teachers such as (?tfatiputra, the Nirgrantha, the founder of Gainism, Pftrana Kasyapa, Kakuda KMyayana, A#ita Kesakambali, Sam^aya Vaira^i-putra. Gosali-putra, the Maskarin, are mentioned by the side of Gautama, the prince of the clan of the S&kyas. One of these only became known in his- tory, (?/?atiputra, the Nirgrantha or gymnosophist, because the society founded by him, like the brotherhood founded by Buddha, developed into a powerful sect, the Gain as. Another, Gosali with the bamboo stick, originally an Agi- vaka, then a follower of Mahavira, became likewise the founder of a sect of his own, which, however, has now disappeared 1 . Cr/iatiputra or Nataputta was actually the senior of Buddha. Though it seems likely that the founders of the six systems of philosophy, though not the authors of the Sfttras which we possess, belonged to the same period of philosophical and religious fermentation which gave rise to the first spreading of Buddha's doctrines in India, it is by no means clear that any of these systems, in their literary form, are presupposed by Buddhism. This is owing to the vagueness of the quotations which are hardly ever given 1 Kern, Buddhismus, I, p. 182. 90 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. verbatim. In India, during the mnemonic period of litera- ture, the contents of a book may have become considerably modified, while the title remained the same. Even at a much later time, when we see Bhartrihari (died 650 A.D.) referring to the Mimamsaka, Samkhya, and Vaiseshika Darsanas, we have no right to* conclude that he knew these Darsanas exactly as we know them, though he may well have known these philosophies after they had assumed their systematic form. Again, when he quotes Naiyayikas, it by no means follows that he knew our Gotama-Sfttras, nor have we any right to say that our Gotama-Sutras existed in his time. It is possible, it is probable, but it is not certain. We must therefore be very careful not to rely too much on quotations from, or rather allusions to, other systems of philosophy. The S&mkhya-Stitras, as we possess them, arc very chary of references. They clearly refer to Vaiieshika and Nyaya, when they examine the six categories of the former (V, 85) and the sixteen Padarthas of the latter (V, 86). Whenever they refer to the Anus or atoms, we know that they have the Vaiseshika-philosophy in their minds; and once the Vaiseshikas are actually mentioned by name (I, 35). Sruti, which the Samkhyas were supposed to disregard, is very frequently appealed to/Smrtti once (V, 123), and Vama- deva, whose name occurs in both $ruti and Smriti, is mentioned as one who had obtained spiritual freedom. But of A individual philosophers we meet only with Sanan- dana AMrya (VI, 69^ and Patffoudkha (V, 32; VI, 68), while the teachers, the A&aryas, when mentioned in general, are explained as comprehending Eapila himself, as well as others. Ved&nta-Sfttras. The Vedanta-Sutras contain more frequent references, but they too do not help us much for chronological purposes. Badarayana refers more or less clearly to the Buddhists, the (?airia,s, Pasupatas, and Pa//Jtaratras, all of whom he is endeavouring to refute. He never refers, however, to any VEDANTA-SUTRAS. 9 1 literary work, and even when he refers to other philo- sophical systems, he seems to avoid almost intentionally the recognised names of their authors, nay even their tech- nical terms. Still it is clear that the systems of the Purva- Mimamsa, the Yoga, Samkhya, and Vai-seshika were in his mind when he composed his Sutras, and among Mimamsic authorities he refers by name to Gaimini, Badari, Audulomi, A&marathya, Kasakritsna, Karsh^a^ini, and Atreya, nay to a BadarayaTia also. We cannot be far wrong therefore if we assign the gradual formation of the six systems of philosophy to the period from Buddha (fifth century) to Asoka (third century), though we have to admit, particu- larly in the cases of Vedanta, S&mkhya, and Yoga a long previous development reaching back through Upanishads and BrahmaTias to the very hymns of the Big-veda. It is equally difficult to fix the relative position l of the great systems of philosophy, because, as I explained before, they quote each other mutually. With regard to the rela- tion of Buddhism to the six orthodox systems it seems to* me that all we can honestly say is that schools of philosophy handing down doctrines very similar to those of our six classical or orthodox systems, are presupposed by the Buddhist Suttas. But this is very different from the opinion held by certain scholars that Buddha or his disciples actually borrowed from our Sfttras. We know nothing of Smkhya-literature before the Samkhya-karikas, which belong to the sixth century after Christ. Even if we admit that the Tattva-samasa was an earlier work, how could We, without parallel dates, prove any actual borrow- ing on the part of Buddha or his disciples at that early time? In the Upanishads and BrahmaTias, though there is a common note running through them all, there is as yet great latitude and want of system, and a variety of opi- nions supported by different teachers and different schools. Even in the hymns we meet with great independence and individuality of thought, which occasional!^ seems to amount to downright scepticism and atheism. 1 Bhandarkar, Samkhya Philosophy (1871), p. 3. 92 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. We must keep all this in mind if we wish to gain a correct idea of the historical origin and growth of what we are accustomed to call the six philosophical systems of India. We have seen already that philosophical discussions were not confined to the Brahmans, but that the Kshatriyas also took a very active and prominent part in the elabora- tion of such fundamental^ philosophical concepts as that of Atman or Self. It is out of this floating mass of philosophical and religious opinion, which was common property in India, that the regular systems slowly emerged. Though we do not know in what form this took place, it is quite clear that what we now possess of philosophical manuals, in the form of Sfttras, could not have been -written down during the time when writing for any practical purposes except inscriptions on monuments and coins was still unknown in India, or at all events had not yet been employed for literary purposes, so far as we know. Mnemonic Literature. It has now been generally admitted, I believe, that whenever writing has once become popular, it is next to impossible that there should be no allusion to it in the poetical or prose compositions of the people. Even as late as the time of $amkara, the written letters are still called unreal (Anrita) in comparison with the audible sounds, as classified in the Pratisakhyas, which are represented by them (Ved. Sutras II, i, 14, p. 451). There is no allusion to writing in the hymns, the Brahman as and Upanishads ; very few, if any, in the Sfitras. The historical value of these allusions to writing which occur in the literature of the Buddhists depends, of course, on the date which we can assign, not to the original authors, but to the writers of our texts. We must never forget that there was in India during many centuries a purely mnemonic literature, which continued down to the Siitra-period, and which was handed down from generation to generation according to a system which is fully described in the Pratisakhyas. What would have been the use of that elaborate system, if there had been manuscripts in existence at the same time ? MNEMONIC LITERATURE. 93 When that mnemonic literature, that Smriti, came for the first time to be reduced to writing, this probably took place in something like the form of Sutras. The very helplessness of the Sutra-style would thus become intel- ligible. Letters at that time were as yet monumental only, for in India also monumental writing is anterior to literary writing, and to the adoption of a cursive alphabet. Writing material was scarce in India, and the number of those who could read must have been very small. At the same time there existed the old mnemonic literature, invested with a. kind of sacred character, part and parcel of the ancient system of education, which had so far answered all purposes and was not easy to supplant. Much of that mnemonic literature has naturally been lost, unless it was reduced to writing at the proper time. Often the name may have survived, while tne body of a work was entirely changed. Hence when we see the Samkhya mentioned by name in the Buddhist texts, such as the Visuddhi-m$gga (chap. XVII), it is impossible to tell whether even at that time there existed a work on the Sarakhya-philosophy in the form of Sutras. It is clear at all events that it could not have been our Samkhya-Sutras, nor even the Samkhya-karikas which seem to have super- seded the ancient Sutras early in the sixth century, while our present Sfttras date from the fourteenth. It might be possible, if not to prove, at all events to render probable the position assigned here to Buddha's teaching as subsequent to the early growth of philosophical ideas in their systematic and more or less technical form, by a reference to the name assigned to his mother, whether it was her real name or a name assigned to her by tradi- tion. She was called Maya or Mayadevi. Considering that in Buddha's eyes the world was Maya or illusion, it seems more likely that the name was given to his mother by early tradition, and that it was given not without a purpose. And if so this could only have been after the name of Avidya (nescience) in the Vednta, and of Prakriti in the Samkhya-philosophy had been replaced by the tech- nical term of Maya. It is well known that, in the old classical Upanishads, the name of Maya never occurs ; and 94 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. it is equally significant that it does occur in the later and more or less apocryphal Upanishads. In the $vetasvatara, for instance, I, 10, we read, Mayam tu Prakritim vidyat, ' Let him know that Prakriti is Maya or Maya Prakriti/ This refers, it would seem, to the Samkhya system in which Prakriti acts the part of J'JA.ya and fascinates the Purusha, till he turns away from her and she ceases to exist, at all events as far as he is concerned. But whether in Samkhya .or Vedanta, M&ya .in its technical meaning belongs certainly to a secondary period, and it might there- fore be argued that Maya, as the name of Buddha's mother, is not likely to have found a place in the Buddhistic legend during the early period of Indian philosophy, as repre- sented in the early Upanishads, and even in the SMras o these two prominent schools. There was, no doubt, a certain amount of philosophical mnemonic composition after the period represented by the old Upanishads, and before the systematic arrangement of the philosophical Sutras, but whatever may have existed in it, is for ever lost to us. We can see this clearly in the case of" the Brihaspati-philosophy. The Bn'liaspati-Fhilosophy. Brihaspati is no doubt a very perplexing character. His name is given as that of the author of two Vedic hymns, X, 7i, A X, 72, a distinction being made between a Brihas- pati Angirasa and a Brihaspati Laukya (Lauk&yatika ?). His name is well known also as one of the Vedic deities. In Rv. VIII, 96, 15, we read that Indra, with Brihaspati as his ally, overcame the godless people (adevi/i, vis&h). He is afterwards quoted as the author of a law-book, decidedly modern, which we still possess. Brihaspati is besides the name of the planet Jupiter, and of the preceptor or Purohita of the gods, so that Brihaspati-purohita has become a recog- nised name of Indra, as having Brihaspati for his Burohita or chief priest and helper. It seems strange, therefore, that the same name, that of the preceptor of the gods, should have been chosen as the name of the representative of the most unorthodox, atheistical, and sensualistic system of philosophy in India. We may possibly account for this THE B/?/HASPATI-PHILOSOPin 95 by referring to the Brahmar however, to a scholion of Bhuaskara on the Brahma-Sfltras, he seems to have known, even at that late time, some Sutras ascribed to Brihaspati 1 , in which the doctrines of the J&Tarvakas, i. e, unbelievers, were contained. But although such Sfttras may have existed, we have no means of fixing their date as either anterior or posterior to the other philosophic Sfttras. Panini knew of Sfttras which are lost to us, and some of them may be safely referred to the time of Buddha. He also in quoting Bhikshu-Sfttras and Natfa-Sutras, mentions (IV, 3, no) the author of the former as P&ra^arya, of the latter as illin. As P&ra- saryc. is a name of Vy&sa, the son of ParlUara, it has been supposed that Panini meant by Bhikshu-Sfttras, the. Brahma-Sfttras 2 , sometimes ascribed to Vyasa, which we still possess. That would fix their date about the fifth century B.C., and has been readily accepted therefore by all who wish to claim the greatest possible antiquity for the philosophical literature of India. But Parasarya would hardly have been chosen as the titular name of Vyasa ; and though we should not hesitate to assign to the doc- trines of the Vedanta a place in the fifth century B.C., nay even earlier, we cannot on such slender authority do the same for the Sutras themselves. When we meet elsewhere with the heterodox doctrines of Brihaspati, they are expressed in verse, as if taken from a Karika rather than from Sfttras. They possess a peculiar _ interest to us, because they would show us that India, which is generally considered as the home of all that is most spiritual and idealistic, was by no means devoid of sensur l ; stic philosophers. But thouglTit is difficult to say how old such theories may have been in India it is certain that, as soon as we get any coherent treatises on philosophy, sensuajfetic opinions crop up among them. Of course the doctrines of Buddha would be called sceptical and atheistic by the Brahmans, and .ffarvaka as 1 Colebrooke, II, 429. a See before, p. 86, 7 H 98 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. well as Nastika are names freely applied to the Buddhists. But the doctrines of Brihaspati, as far as We know them, go far beyond Buddhism, and .nay be said to be hostile to all religious feelings, while Buddha's teaching was both religious and philosophical, though the lines that separate philosophy and religion in India are very faint. There are some tenets of the followers of Brihaspati which seem to indicate the existence of other schools of philosophy, by their side. The Barhaspatyas speak as if being inter pares, they differ from others as others differed from them, Traces of an opposition against the religion of the Vedas (Kautsa) appear in the hymns, the Brahman as, and the Sutras, and .to ignore them would give us an entirely false idea of the religious and philosophical battles and battle-fields of ancient India. As viewed from a Brahmanic point of view, and we have no other, the opposition represented by Brihaspati and others may seein insignificant, but the very name given to these heretics would seem to imply that their doctrines had met with a world-wide acceptance (Lokayatikas). Another name, that of Nastika, is given to them as saying No to every- thing except the evidence of the senses, particularly to the evidence of the Vedas, which, yunonsly enough, was called by the Vedantists Pratyaksha, that is, self-evident, like sense-perception. These Nastikas, a name not applicable to mere dissenters, but to out and out nihilists only, ai.*e interesting to us from a historical point of view, because in arguing against other philosophies, they prove, ipso facto, the e'xistence of ortho- dox philosophical systems before their time. The recog- nised schools of Indian philosophy could tolerate much; they were tolerant, as we shall see, even towards a qualified atheism, like that of the Sarakhya. But they had nothing but hatred and contempt for the Nastikas, and it is for that very reason, and on account of the strong feelings of aversion which they excited, that it seemed to me right that their philosophy should not be entirely passed 'Vet by the side of the six Vedic or orthodox systems. Madhava, in his Sarvadarsana-samgraha or the Epitome of all philosophical systems, begins with an account of the THE B#/HASPATI-PHILOSOPHY. 99 Nastika or jKarvaka system. He looks npon it as the lowest of all, hut nevertheless, as not to be ignored in a catalogue .of the philosophical forces of India. /&rvka (not Jfarvaka) is given as the name of a B&kshasa, and he is treated as a historical individual to whom Brihas- pati or Va/caspati delivered his doctrines. The name of ATarv&ka is clearly connected with that of K lirva, and this is given as a synonym of Buddha by B&las&strin in the Preface to his edition of the K&ak& (p. a). He is repre- sented as a teacher of the Lokayata or world- wide system, if that is the meaning originally intended by that word. A short account of this system is given in the Prabodha- fcandrodaya 27, 18, in the following words: 'The Lokayata system in which the senses alone form an authority, in which the elements are earth, water, fire, and wind (not Akasa or ether), in which wealth and enjoyment form the ideals of man, in which the elements think, the other world is denied, and death is the end of all things/ This name Lokayata occurs already in Pa/raini's GaTia TJkthMi. It should be noted however, that Hema/candra distinguishes between Barhaspatya or Nastika, and If&rvaka or Lokfe- yatika, though he does not tell us which he considers the exact points on which th$ two are supposed to have differed. The Buddhists use Lok&yata for philosophy in general. The statement that the Lokayatas admitted but one Pram&na, i. e. authority of knowledge, namely sensuous perception, shows clearly that there must have been other philosophical systems already in existence. We shall see that the Vaiseshika acknowledged two, perception (Prat- yaksha) and inference (Arminana); the S&nikhya three, adding trustworthy affirmation (Aptavakya); the Nyaya four, adding comparison lUpamana) ; the two Mim&wsils six, adding presumption (Arthapatti) and privation (AbhU- va). Of these and others we shall have to speak here- after. Even what seems to us so natural an idea as that of the four or five elements, required some time to develop, as we see in the history of the Greek arotxcta, and yet such an idea was evidently quite familiar to the jfif&rvakas. While other systems admitted five, i.e. earth, water, fire, air, and ether, they admitted four only, excluding ether, H 2 1OO . INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, probably because it was invisible. In the Upanishads we see traces of an even earlier triad of elements. All this shows the philosophical activity of the Hindus from the earnest times, and exhibits to us the K &rv&kas as denying ratlier what had been more or less settled before their time, than as adding any new ideas of their own. So it is again with regard to the soul. Not only philo- sophrs, but every Arya in India had a word for soul, and never doubted that there was something in man different from the visible body. The If&rv&kas only denied this. They held that what was called soul was not a thing by itself, but was simply the body over again. They held that itr was the body that felt, that saw and heard, that remembered and thought, though they saw it every day rotting away and decomposing, as if it never had been. By such opinions they naturally came in conflict with religion even more than with philosophy. We do not know how they accounted for the evolution of consciousness and in- tellect out of mere flesh, except that they took refuge with a simile, appealing to the intoxicating power that can be developed by mixing certain ingredients, which by them- selves are not intoxicating, as an analogy to the production of soul from body. Thus we read : ' There are four elements, earth, water, fire, and air, And from these four elements alone is intelligence pro- duced Just like the intoxicating power from Ki^wa, &c., mixed together ; Since in " I am fat," " I am lean," these attributes abide in the same subject, And since fatness, &c., resides only in the body, it alone is the soul and no other, And such ^phrases as " my body " are only significant metaphorically/ In this way the soul seems to have been to them the body qualified by the attribute of intelligence, and therefore supposed to perish with the body. Holding this opinion, it is no wonder that they should have considered the highest end of man to consist in sensual enjoyment, and that they THE Btf/HASPATI-PflILOSOMU r . IO I should have accepted pain simply as an inevitable con- comitant of pleasure. A verse is quoted : ' The pleasure which arises to men from contact with sensible objects, Is to be relinquished as accompanied by pain such is the warning of fools ; The berries of paddy, rich with the finest white grains, What man, seeking his true interest, would fling them away, because covered with husks and dust x ? ' From all this we see that, though fundamental philo- sophical principles are involved, the chief character of the Jf&rv&ka system was practical, rather *than metaphysical, teaching utilitarianism and crude hedonism in the most outspoken way. It is a pity that all authoritative books of these materialistic philosophers should be lost, as they would probably have allowed us a deeper insight into the early history of Indian philosophy than the ready-made manuals of the six Darsanas on which we have chiefly to rely. The following verses preserved by M&dhava in his Epitome- are nearly all we possess of the teaching of Brihaspati and his followers: ' Fire is hot, water cold, and the air feels cool ; By whom was this variety made? (we do not know), therefore it must have come from their own nature (Svabh&va).' Brihaspati himself is held responsible for the following invective: 'There is no paradise, no deliverance, and certainly no Self in another world, Nor are the acts of the Asramas (stations in life) or the castes, productive of rewards. The Agnihotra, the three Vedas, the three staves (carried by ascetics) and smearing oneself with ashes, They are the mode of life made by their creator a for those who are devoid of sense and manliness. 1 See for these verses Cowell and Gough's translation of the Sarvadawana- sa.ngraha, p. 4. * Dhatri, creator, can here be ujed ironically only, instead of Svabhava, or nature. IO2 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. If a victim slain at the GyotisWoma will go to heaven, Why is not his own father killed there by the sacrificer ? If the raddha-offering gives pleasure to beings that are dead, Then to give a viaticum to people who travel here on earth, would be useless. If those who are in heaven derive pleasure from offer- ings, Then why not give food here to people while they are standing on the roof ? As long .as he lives let a man live happily ; after borrow- ing money, let him drink Ghee, How can there be a return of the body after it has once been reduced to ashes ? If he who has left the body goes to another world, Why does he not come back again perturbed by love of his relations ? Therefore funeral ceremonies for the dead were ordered by the Brahmans. As a means of livelihood, nothing else is known any- where. The three makers of the Vedas were buffoons, knaves, and demons. The speech of the Pandits is (unintelligible), like (?ar- phari Turphari. The obscene act there (at the horse sacrifice) to be per- formed by the queen has been Proclaimed by knaves, and likewise other things to be taken in hand. The eating of flesh was likewise ordered by demons.' This is certainly very strong language, as strong as any that has ever been used by ancient or modern materialists. It is well that we should know how old and how widely spread chis materialism was, for without it we should hardly understand the efforts that were made on the other side to counteract it by establishing the true sources or measures of knowledge, the Prama/nas, and other funda- mental truths whicli were considered essential both for religion and for philosophy. The idea of orthodoxy, how- ever, is very different in India from what it has been I THE Bfl/HASPATI-PHILO&OPH*. IO3 ^Isewhere. We shall find philosophers in India who deny the existence of a personal god or f svara, and who, never- theless, were tolerated as orthodox as long as they recog- nised the authority of the Veda, and tried to bring their doctrines into harmony with Vedic texts. It is this denial of the authority of the Veda which, in the eyes of the Brahmans, stamped Buddha at once as a heretic, and drove him to found a new religion or brotherhood, while those, who followed the Sarakhya, and who on many important points did not differ much from him, remained secure within the pale of orthodoxy. Some of the charges brought by the Barhaspatyas against the Brahmans who followed the Veda are the same which the followers of Buddha brought against them. Considering therefore, t ; hat on the vital question of the authority of the Veda the Samkhya agrees, however inconsistently, with orthodox Brahmanism and differs from the Buddhists, it would be far easier to prove that Buddha derived his ideas from Brihaspati than from Kapila, the reputed founder of the Samkhya. If we are right in the description we have given of the. unrestrained and abundant growth of philo- sophical ideas in ancient India, the idea of borrowing, so natural to us, seems altogether out of place in India. A wild mass of guesses at truth was floating in the air, and there was no controlling authority whatever, not even, as far as we know, any binding public opinion to produce anything like order in it". Hence we have as little right to maintain that Buddha borrowed from Kapila as that Kapila borrowed from Buddha. No one would say that the Hindus borrowed the idea of building ships from the Fhenieians, or that of building Stupas from the Egyptians. In India we move in a world different from that which we are accustomed to in Greece, Rome, or Modern Europe, and we need not rush at once to the conclusion that, because similar opinions prevail in Buddhism and in the Samkhya- philosophy of Kapila, therefore the former must have bor- rowed from the latter, or, as some hold, the latter from the former. Though we can well imagine what the spirit of the philosophy of the ancient Indian heretics, wliether they 104 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. are called JSTarvakas or Barhaspatyas, may have been, we know, unfortunately, much less of their doctrines than of any other school of philosophy. They are to us no more than names, such as the names of Y&gravalkya, Raikva, or any other ancient leaders of Indian thought mentioned in the Upanishads, and credited there with certain utterances. We know a few of the conclusions at which they arrived, but of the processes by which they arrived at them we know next to nothing. What we may learn from these utterances is that a large mass of philosophical thought must have existed in. India long before there was any attempt at dividing it into six well-defined channels of systematic philosophy, or reducing it to writing. Even when the names of certain individuals, such as Craimini, Kapila, and others, are given us as the authors of certain systems of philosophy, we must not imagine that they were the original creators of a philosophy in the sense in which Plato and Aristotle seem to have been so. Common Philosophical Idea*. It cannot be urged too strongly that there existed in India a large common fund of philosophical thought which, like language , belonged to no one in particular, but was like the air breathed by every living and thinking man. Thus only can it be explained that we find a number of ideas in all, or nearly all, the systems of Indian philosophy which all philosophers seem to take simply for granted, and which belong to no one school in particular. 1 . Metempsychosis Sams&ra. The best known of these ideas, which belong to India rather than to any individual philosopher, is that which is known under the name of Metempsychosis. This is a Greek word, like Metensomatosis, but without any literary authority in Greek. It corresponds in meaning to the Sanscrit Sams&ra, and is rendered in German by Seelemvanderung. To a Hindu the idea that the souls of men migrated after death into new bodies of living beings, of animals, nay, even of plants, is so self-evident that IMMOKTALITV OF THE SOUL IO5 it was hardly ever questioned. We never meet with any attempt at proving or disproving it among the prominent writers of ancient or modern times. As early as the period of the Upanishads we hear of human souls being reborn both in animal and in vegetable bodies. In Greece the same opinion was held by Empedocles; but whether he borrowed this idea from the Egyptians, as is commonly supposed to have been the case, or whether Pythagoras and his teacher Pherecydes learnt it in India, is a question still hotly discussed. To me it seems that such a theory was so natural that it might perfectly well have arisen independently among different races. Among the Aryan races, Italian, Celtic, and Scythic or Hyper- borean tribes are mentioned as having entertained a faith in Metempsychosis, nay, traces of it have lately been dis- covered even among the uncivilised inhabitants of America, Africa, and Eastern Asia. And why not ? In India certainly it developed spontaneously ; and if this was so in India, why not in other countries, particularly among races belonging to the same linguistic stock? It should be remembered, however, that some systems, particularly the Sarakhya- phiiosophy, do not admit what we commonly understand by Seelemvanderung. If we translate the Samkhya Purusha by Soul instead of Self, it is not the Punish a that migrates, but the S&kshma-tarira, the subtile body. The Self remains always intact, a mere looker on, and its highest purpose is this recognition that it is above and apart from anything that has sprung from Prakr/ti or nature. 8. Immortality Of the Soul. The idea of the immortality of the soul also should be included in what was the common property of all Indian philosophers. This idea was so completely taken for granted that we look in vain for any elaborate arguments in support of it. Mortality with the Hindus is so entirely restricted to the body which decays and decomposes before our very eyes, that such an expression as Atrnano mrita- tvam, immortality of the Self , sounds almost tautological in Sanskrit. No doubt, the followers of Brihaspati would 7O6 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. deny a future life, but all the other schools rather fear than doubt a future life, a long-continued metempsychosis ; and as to a final annihilation of the true Self, that would sound to Indian ears as a contradiction in itself. There are scholars so surprised at this unwavering belief in a future and an eternal life among the people of India, that they have actually tried to trace it back to a belief sup- posed to be universal among savages who thought that man left a ghost behind who might assume the body of an animal or even the shape of a tree. This is a mere fancy, and though it cannot of course be disproved, it does not thereby acquire any right to oui? consideration. Besides, why should the Aryas have had to learn lessons from savages, as they at one time were no doubt savages them- selves, and need not have forgotten the so-called wisdom of savages as little as the $udras themselves from whom they are supposed to have learnt it? . . 3. Pessimism. All Indian philosophers have been charged with pes- simism, and in some cases such a charge may seem well founded, but not in all. People who derived tfyeir name for good from a word which originally meant nothing but being or real, Sat, are not likely to have lopked upon what is as what ought not to be. Indian philpsophers are by no means dwelling for ever on the miseries of life. They are not always whining and protesting that life is not worth living. That is not their pessimism. They simply state that they received the first impulse to philosophical reflection from the fact that there is suffering in the world. They evidently thought that in a perfect world suffering had no place, that it is something anomalous, something that ougnt at all events to be accounted for, And, if possible, overcome. Pain, certainly, seems to be an imperfection, and, as such, may well have caused the question why it existed, and how it could be annihilated. But this is not the disposition which we are accustomed to call pessimism. Indian philosophy contains no outcry against divine injus- tice, and 'in no way encourages suicidal expedients. They would, in fact, be of no avail, because, according to Indian PESSIMISM. 107 views, the same troubles and the same problems would have to be faced again and again in another life. Con- sidering that the aim of all Indian philosophy was the removal 01 suffering, which was caused by nescience, and the attainment of the highest happiness, which was pro- duced by knowledge, we should have more right to call it eudsemonistic than pessimistic. It is interesting, however, to observe the unanimity with which the principal systems of philosophy in India, nay some of their religious systems also, start from the conviq- tion ' that the world is full of suffering, and that this suffering should be accounted for and removed. This seems to have been one of the principal impulses, if n'ot the principal impulse to philosophical thought in India. If we begin with traimini, we cannot expect much real philosophy from his Purva-Mimamsa, which is chiefly con- cerned with ceremonial questions, such as sacrifices, &c. But though these sacrifices are represented as being the means of a certain kind of beatitude, and so far as serving to diminish or extinguish the ordinary afflictions of men, they were never supposed to secure the highest .beatitude for which all the other philosophers were striving. The Uttara-Mimamsa and all the other philosophies take much higher ground. BadarayaTia teaches that the cause of all evil is Avidya or nescience, and that it is the object of his philosophy to remove that nescience by moans of science ( Vidya), and thus to bring about that true knowledge of Brahman, which is also the highest bliss (Taitt. Up. II, i). The*Samkhya-philosophy, at least such as we know it from the Karikas and the Sutras, not however the Tattva- samasa, begins at once with the recognition of the existence of the three kinds of suffering, and proclaims as its highest object the complete cessation of all pain ; while the Yoga philosophers, after pointing out the way to meditative absorption (Samadhi), declare that this is the best means of escaping from all earthly troubles (II, 2), and, in the end, of reaching Kaivalya or perfect freedom. The Vaiseshika promises to its followers knowledge of truth, and through it final cessation of all pain ; and even Gotama's philosophy of logic holds out in its first Sutra complete blessedness IO8 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. (Apavarga) as its highest reward, which is obtained by the complete destruction of all pain by means of logic. That Buddha's religion had the same origin, a clear perception of human suffering and its causes, and had the same object, the annihilation of DuAkha or suffering (Nirvana), is too well known to require further elucidation, but it should be remembered that other systems also have one and the same name for the state to which they aspire, whether Nirvana or Du/tkhanta, i. e. end of Du&kha, pain. If therefore all Indian philosophy professes its ability to remove pain, it can hardly be called pessimistic in the ordinary sense of the word. Even physical pain, though it cannot be removed from the body, ceases to affect the soul, as soon as the Self has fully -realised its aloofness from the body, while all mental pain, being traced back to our worldly attachments, would vanish by freeing our- selves from the desires which cause these attachments. The cause of all suffering having been discovered in our- selves, in our works and thoughts, whether in this or in a previous existence, all clamour against divine injustice is silenced at once. We are what we have made ourselves, we suffer what, we have done, we reap what we have sown, and it is the sowing of good seed, though without any hope of a rich harvest, that is represented as the chief purpose of a philosopher's life on earth. Besides this conviction that all suffering can be removed by an insight into its nature and origin, there are some other ideas which must be traced back to that rich treasury of thought which was open to every thinking man in India. These common ideas assumed, no doubt, different guises in different systems, but this ought not to deceive us, and a little reflection allows us to perceive their common source. Thus, when the cause of suffering is inquired for, they all have but one answer to give, though under different' names. The Vedanta gives Avidya, nescience, the Smkhya, Avi- veka, non-discrimination, the Nyaya, Hithy%7ina, false knowledge, and these various aberrations from knowledge are generally represented as Bandha or bondage, to be broken again by means of that true knowledge which is supplied by the various systems of philosophy. 109 4. Xarman. The next idea that seems ingrained in the Indian mind, and therefore finds expression in all the- systems of philo- sophy, is a belief in Karman deed, that is, the continuous working of every thought, word, and deed through all ages. * All works, good or bad, all must bear and do bear fruit/ is a sentiment never doubted by any Hindvi, whether to-day or thousands of years ago l . And the same eternity which is claimed for works and their results is claimed for the soul also, only with this difference, that while works will cease to work when real freedom has been obtained, the soul itself continues after the obtainment of freedom or final beatitude. The idea of the soul ever coming to an end is so strange to the Indian mind that there seemed to be no necessity for anything like proofs of immortality, so common in European philo- sophy. Knowing what is meant by ' to be/ the idea that 'to be' could ever become 'not to be' seems to have been impossible to the mind of the Hindus. If by 'to be' is meant Samsara or the world, however long it may last, then Hindu philosophers would never look upon it as real. It never was, it never is, and never will be. Length of time, however enormous, is nothing in the eyes of Hindu philosophers. To reckon a thousand years as one day would not satisfy them. They represent length of ^ime by much bolder similes, such as when a man once in every thousand years passes his silken kerchief over the chain of the Hima- layan mountains. By the time he has completely wiped them out by this process the world or Samsara may indeed come to an end, but even then eternity and reality lie far beyond. In order to get an easier hold of this eternity, the very popular idea of Pralayas, i. e. destructions or absorptions of the whole world, has been invented. Accord- ing to the Ved&nta there occurs at the end of each Kalpa a Fralaya or dissolution of the universe, and Brahman is then reduced to its causal condition (K&ran&vastha), con- taining both soul and matter in an Avyakta (undeveloped) 1 Cf. The Mysteries of Karma, revealed by a Brahmin Yogee, Allaha- bad, 1898. 110 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. state *. At the end of this Pralaya, however, Brahman creates or lets out of himself a new world, matter becomes gross and visible once more, and souls become active and re-embodied, though with a higher enlightenment (Vik&sa), and all this according to their previous merits and demerits. Brahman has then cissumed its new Karyavastha or effec- tive state which lasts for another Ealpa. But all this refers to the world of change and unreality only. It is the world of Karman, the temporary produce of Nescience, of Avidya, or Maya, it is not yet real reality. In the Samkhya- philosophy these Pralayas take place whenever the three Qunas of Prakriti recover their equipoise 2 , while creation results from the upsetting of the equipoise between them. What is truly eternal, is not affected by the cosmic illusion, or at least is so for a time only, and may recover at any moment its self-knowledge, that is, its self-being, and its freedom from all conditions and fetters. According to the Vaiseshikas Ihis process of creation and dissolution depends on the atoms. If they are sepa- rated, there ensues dissolution (Pralaya), if motion springs up in them and they are united, there follows what we call creation. The idea of the reabsorption of the world at the end of a Kalpa (aeon) and its emergence again in the next Kalpa, does not occur as yet in the old Upanishads, nay even the name of Sawsara is absent from them ; and Professor Garbe is inclined therefore to claim the idea of Pralaya as more recent, as peculiar to the S&mkhya-philosophy, and as adopted from it by the other systems 3 . It may be so, but in the Bhagavad-gita IX, 7, the idea of Pralayas, absorptions, and of Kalpas or ages, of their end and their beginning (Kalpakshaye arid Kalp&dau), are already quite familiar to the poets. The exact nature of the Pralayas differs so much, according to different poets and philo- sophers, that it is far more likely that they may all have borrowed it from a common source, that is, from the popular belief of those among whom they were brought up and from whom they learnt their language and with it 1 Thibaut, V. S. I, p. xxviii. * S&mkhya-Stitras VI, 43. * Sawkhya-Philosophie, p. 221 TETRBE GUtfAS. . Ill the materials of their thoughts, than that they should each have invented the same theory under slightly varying aspects. 5. Infallibility of tile Veda. One more common element presupposed by Indian philo- sophy might be pointed out in the recognition of the supreme authority and the revealed character ascribed to the Veda. This, in ancient times, is certainly a startling idea, familiar as it may sound to us at present. The Samkhya-philosophy is supposed to have been originally without a belief in the revealed character of the Vedas, but it certainly speaks of Sruti (Sfttras I, 5). As long as we know the Samkhya, it recognises the authority of the Veda, calling it /S y abda, and appeals to ifc even in matters of minor importance. It is important to observe that the distinction between $ruti and SmHti, revelation and tradition, so well known in the later phases of philosophy, is not to be found as yet in the old Upanishads. 6. Three Chinas. The theory of the three Giirias also, which has been claimed as originally peculiar to the Samkhya-philosophy, seems in its unscientific form to have been quite familiar to most Hindu philosophers. The impulse to everything in nature, the cause of all life and variety, is ascribed to the three GuTias. Guna means quality, but we are warned expressly not to take it, when it occurs in philosophy, in the ordinary sense of quality, but rather as something substantial by itself, so that the Gu9?as become in fact the component constituents of nature. In the most general sense they represent no more, than thesis, antithesis, and something between the two, such as cold, warm, and neither cold nor warm; good, bad, and neither good nor bad; bright, dark, and neither bright nor dark ; and so on through every part of physical and moral nature. Tension between these qualities produces activity and struggle: equilibrium leads to temporary or final rest. This mutual tension is sometimes represented as Vishamatvam, uneven- ness, caused by a preponderance of one of the three, as we 112 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. read, for instance, in the Maitr&yaTia Upanishad V, a : ' This world was in the beginning Tamas (darkness) indeed. That Tamas stood in the Highest. Moved by the Highest, it became uneven. In that form it was Ragras (obscurity). That Ragras, when moved, became uneven, and this is the form of Sattva (goodness). That Sattva, when moved, ran forth as essence (Rasa)/ Here we have clearly the recog- nised names of the three Gutias, but the Maitrayana Upani- shad shows several S&wkhya influences, and it might therefore be Jargued that it does not count for much, in order to establish the general acceptance of the theory of the GuTias, not for more, at all events, than the later Upani- ahads or the Bhagavad-git&, in which the three Gurais are fully recognised. CHAPTER IV. Ved&nta or Trttara-MiuiA?ns. IF now we pass on to a consideration of the six orthodox systems of philosophy, and begin with* the Vedanta, we have to take as our chief guides the Sutras of Badarayajia, and the commentary of amkara. We know little of Badarayawa, the reputed author of the SMras. Of course when we possess commentaries on any Sutras, we know that the Sutras must have existed before their commen- taries, that the Sutras of Badareayana were older therefore than Samkara, their commentator. In India he has been identified with Vyasa, the collector of the M^h&bh&rata, but without sufficient evidence, nor should we gain much by that identification, as Vyasa of the Mahabh&rata also is hardly more than a name to -us.' Thi.$- Vy|sa is said by $amkara, III, 3, 32, to have lived at the end of the Dvapara and the beginning of the Kali age, and to have had intercourse with the gods, 1. c., I, 3, 33, But though he- calls him the author of the Mahabharata, 1. c., II, 3, 47, $amkara, in the whole of his commentary on the Ved&nta- Sutras, never mentions that the Vyasa of the epic was the author of the book on which he is commenting, though he i nentions Badarayarta as such. This convinced Windisch- inann that Samkara himself did not consider these two Vyasas as one and the same person, and this judgment ought not to have been lightly disturbed. It was excus- able in Ctflebrooke, but not after what had been said by Windischmann, particularly when no new argument could be produced. All we can say is that, whatever the date of the Bhagavad-gitft is, and it is a part of the Mah&bharata, the age of the Vedanta-Sfttras .and of Bddardyana must have been earlier. We may also say that B&dar&yawa himself never refers to any work which could be assigned with any amount of I 114 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. certainty to any time after our era. Even when Badara- ya-na quotes the Smriti, it does not follow that $amkara is always right when suggesting passages from the Mahabha- rata (Bhagavad-gita), or irom Manu, for it is not too much to say that similar passages may have occurred in other and more ancient Smriti works also. Badafaya-na is cer- tainly most provoking in never quoting his authorities by name. If we could follow $amkara, Badaraya?ia would have referred in his Sutras to Bauddhas, (ramas, Pasupatas and Paw fearatras, to Yogins, Vaiseshikas, though not to Naiyayikas, to Sarakhyas, and to the doctrines of (?aimini 3 . By the name of Sniti BadarayaTia; according to $amkara, meant the following TJpanishads, Brihad-&ra?iyaka, Kh&n- dogya, Kanaka, Kaushitaki, Aitareya, Taittiriya, Mundaka, Prasna, $veta8vatara, and (?abala. This must suffice to indicate the intellectual sphere in which 'BadarayaTia moved, or was supposed to have moved, and so far may be said to determine his chronological posi- tion as far anterior to that of another Vyasa, who was the father of $uka, the teacher of Gauc?apada, the teacher of Govinda, the teacher of $amkara y and who, if >$amkara belonged to the eighth century, might have lived in about the sixth century or our era 2 . The literary works to which jSamkara refers in his com- menta,ry are, according to Deusscn (System, p. 34), among the Samhitas, that of the Rig-veda, of the Va^asaneyins. MaitrayaTtiy'as and Taittiriyas, and Ka&ag (nothing from the Sama and Atharva-samhitas) ; among the Brahiria??,as, the Aitareya, Arsheya, Shacvimsa, Datapaths, Taittiriya, Tar?^ya, AL Aandogya ; among the AraTiyakas, Aitareya and Taittirfya; and among the Upanishads, Aitareya Bnhad-araTiyaka, Isa, Katta, Kaushitaki-brahma-na, Kena, K Aandogya, Maitrayaniya, Mut?xiaka., Prasna, $vetasvatara, Taittiriya. These are sometimes called the old or classical Upanishads, as being quoted by $a?>ikara, though Paimgi, Agnirahasya, Narayaniya and" (Jabala may have to be 1 Deusscn, System dss Vod&nta, p. 24. 2 Another stemma of Vyasa, given by native writers, is Naraynwa, Vasiah^a (Padmnbhava), tfakti, PiinX?ara, Vy\a, Suka, Gaudapada, HastAmalaka (Sishya), Troika, VArttikakftra, &c VEDANTA OR UTTARA-MIMA3fS. 115 added. As belonging to Snmti /Samkara quotes MaM- bhsirata (Bhagavad-ftM), RamayaTia, M^rkarTdeya-pur^oia, Manu, Y&ska, Pa/mm, ParibhasMs, S&wkhya-k&rik, and he refers to S&rakhya-Siltras (though it is important to observe that he gives no ipsissima verba from our S&mkhya- Sfttras), to Yoga-Sfttras, Nyaya-Sfttras, Vaiseshika-Sfttras, and to Mim&ms-Sfttras. When he alludes to Sugata or Buddha he refers once to a passage which has been traced in the Abhidharma-Kos&a-vy&khylL He also knew the Bh&gavatas and the Svapnadhy&yavids. Though the name of Ved&nta does not occur in the old Upanishads, we can hardly doubt that it was the Ved&ntic thoughts, contained in the Upanishads, which gave the first impulse to more systematic philosophical speculations in India. Several scholars have tried to prove that S&mkhya ideas prevailed in India at an earlier time than the Ve- dantie ideas. But though there certainly are germs of Samkhya theories in the Upanishads, they are but few and far between, while the strictly Ved&ntic concepts meet us at every step in the hymns, the Brahma^as, the AraTi- yakas and in the SMras. Vedanta is clearly the native philosophy of India. It is true that this philosophy is not yet treated systematically in the Upanishads, but neither is the S&mkhya. To us who care only for the growth of philosophical thought on the ancient soil of India, Ved&nta is clearly the first growth ; and the question whether Kapila lived before Badarayana, or whether the systematic treatment of the S&mkhya took place before that of the Vedanta, can hardly arise. , I only wonder that tho?^ who maintain the priority of the S&mkhya, have not appealed to the Lalita-vistara, twelfth chapter, where, among the subjects known to Buddha, are mentioned not only Nirgha^fa, /Pandas, Ya<7/7akalpa, ffyotisha, but likewise S&mkhya, Y^ga, Vaise- shika Vesika ( Vaidy aka?), Arthavidy, Barhaspatya, As/carya, Asura, Mrigapakshiruta, and Hetuvidy t a (Nyayal There are several names which are difficult to identify, out there can be no doubt that the five philosophical systems here mentioned were intended for Smkhya, Yoga, Vaiseshika, Ny&y&, and B&rhaspatya. The two Mim&Tnsas are absent, I 2 Jl6 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. but their absence does not prove that they did not exist, but only that they were considered too orthodox to f orm a proper subject of study for Buddha This shows the real character of the antagonism between Buddhism and Brah- manism, now so often denied or minimised 1 , and is con- firmed by similar references, as when Hema/candra in his Abhidhana mentions indeed such names as Arhatas or Gainas, Saugatas or Buddhists, Naiyayikas, Yoga, Sam- khya or Kapila, Vaiseshika, Barhaspatya or Nastika, .K"arvaka or Lokayatika, but carefully omits the two really dangerous systems, the Mimamsa of Badarayana and that of Gaimini. It should also be remembered that considerable doubt has recently been" thrown on the age of the Chinese translation of the Lalita-vistara, which seemed to enable us to assign the original to a date at all events anterior to-7o A.D. The case is not quite clear yet, but we must learn to be more cautious with Chinese dates. It has been the custom to give the name of Vedanta- philosophy to the Uttara-Mimawsa of BadarayaTia, nor is there any reason why that name should not be retained. If Vedanta is used as synonymous with Upanishad, the Uttara-Mimamsa is certainly the Vedanta-philosophy, or a systematic treatment of the philosophical teaching of the Upanishads. It is true, no doubt, that VasishAa as well as Gautama distinguishes between Upanishads and Ve- dantas (XXII, 9), and the commentator to Gautama XIX, 7 states distinctly that those parts only of the AraTiyakas which are not Upanishads are to be called Vedantas. But there is no real harm in the received name, and we see that the followers of the Vedanta were often called Aupanishadas. Badarayana. As to BadarayaTia, the reputed author of the Vedanta- Sfttras, we had to confess before that we know nothing about him. He is to us a name and an intellectual power, but nothing else. We know the date of his great commen- tator, $arakara, in the eighth century A.D., and we know 1 See Brahmav&din, Fob., 1898, p. 454. BADAKAYA^A. 117 that another commentator, Bodhayana, was even earlier. We also know that Bodhay ana's commentary was followed by Ramanu(/a. It is quite possible that Bodhayana, like Ramanm/a, represented a more ancient and more faithful interpretation of Badaraya?ia's Sutras, and that $amkara's philosophy in its unflinching monism, is his own rather than Badarayana's. But no MS. of Bodhayana has yet been discovered. A still more ancient commentator, Upavarsha by name, is mentioned, and $amkara (III, 3, ,53) calls him Bhagavad or Saint. But it must remain doubtful again whether he can be identified with the Upavarsha, who, according to the Katha-sarit-sagara, was the teacher of Pa/iini. It must not be forgotten that, according to Indian tra- dition, Badarayana, as the author of the Vedanta-Sutras, is called Vyasa or Vedavyasa, Dvaipayana or Krishna, Dvai- payana. Here we are once more in a labyrinth from which it is difficult to find an exit. Vyasa or Krishna Dvaipa- yana is the name given to the author of the Mahabharata, and no two styles can well be more different than that of the Vyasa of the Mahabharata and that of Vyasa, the supposed author of the so-called Vyasa-Sutras. I think we should remember that Vyasa, as a noun, meant no more than compilation or arrangement, as opposed to Samasa, conciseness or abbreviation ; so that the same story might be recited Samasena, in an abbreviated, and Vyasena in a complete form. We should remember next that Vyasa is called Parasarya, the son of Parasara and Satyavati (truthful), and that Pa/mm mentions one P&rasarya as the author of the Bhikshu- Sutras, while Va/caspati Misra declares that the Bhikshu- Sfttras are the same as the Vedanta-Sutras, and that the followers of Par&sarya were in consequence called Parasarins. (Pa?i. IV, 3, no.) This, if we could rely 011 it, would prove the existence of our Sutras before the time of P.avmni, or in the fifth cen- tury B.G This would be a most important gain for the chronology of Indian philosophy. But if, as we are told, Vyasa collected (Vivy t asa) not only the Vedas, the Maha- bMrata, the Puranas, but also the Vyasa-Sfttras, nay even Il8 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. a prose commentary on Pata/7(/ali's Yoga- Sutras, we can hardly doubt that the work ascribed to him must be taken as the work of several people or of a literary period rather than of one man. I formerly thought that Vyasa might have represented the period in which the first attempts were made to reduce the ancient mnemonic literature of India to writing, but there is nothing in tradition to sup- port such a view, unless we thought that Vyasa had some connexion with Nyasa (writing). Indian tradition places the great Vyasa between the third and fourth ages of the present world, whatever that may mean, if translated into our modern chronological language. If Vya-sa had really anything to do with our Vedanta-Sutras, it would hardly have been more than that he arranged or edited them. His name does not occur in the Sutras themselves, while that of Badarayaiia does, and likewise that of Badari, a name mentioned by Gaimini also in his Purva-Mimamsa 1 . In the Bhagavad-gita, which might well be placed as con- temporary with the Vedanta-Sutras, or somewhat later, Vyasa is mentioned as one of the Devarshis with Asita and Devala (X, 13), and he is called the greatest of Rishis (X, 37). But all becomes confusion again, if we remember that tradition makes Vyasa the author of the Mahabharata, and therefore of the Bhagavad-git& itself, which is even called an Upanishad. The only passage which seems to me to settle the rela- tive age of the Vedanta-Sutras and the Bhagavad-gita is in XIII, 3 2 , ' Hear and learn from me the Supreme Soul (KshetraSvetaketii abstained from food for fifteen days. Then he came to his father and said : ' What shall I say ? ' The father said : ' Repeat the Rik y Ya^us, and S&man verses/ He replied : ' They do not occur to me, Sir/ 3. The father said to him: 'As of a great lighted fire one coal only of the size of a firefly may be left, which would not burn much more than this (i.e. very little), thus, my dear son, one part only of the sixteen parts (of you) is left, and therefore with that one part you do not remember the Vedas. Go and eat ! 4. 'Then wilt thou understand me/ Then tfvetaketu ate, and afterwards approached his father. And whatever his father asked him, he knew it all by heart. Then his father said to him : 5. 'As of a great lighted fire one coal of the size of FUKDAMENTAL DOCTRINES OF THE VTOANTA. 127 a firefly, if left, may be made to blaze up again by putting grass upon it, and will thus burn more than this, 6. * Thus, my dear son, there was one part of the sixteen parts left to you, and that, lighted up with food, burnt up, and by it you remember now the Vedas/ After that, he understood what his father, meant when he said : ' Mind, my son, comes from food, breath from water, speech from lire/ He understood what he said 5 yea, he under- stood ite NINTH KEA#DA. T. 'As the bees, my son, make honey by collecting the juices of distant trees, and reduce the juice into one form, 2. ' And as these juices have no discrimination, so that they might say, J am the juice of this tree or that, in the same manner, my son, all these creatures, when they have become merged in the True (either in deep sleep or in death), know not that they are merged in the True. 3. ' Whatever these creatures are here, whether a lion, or a wolf, or a boar, or a worm, or a midge, or a gnat, or a musquito, that they become again and again. 4. ' Now that which is that subtile essence, in it all that exists has its Self. It is the Truel It is the Self, and thou, O Svetaketu, art it/ ' Please, Sir, inform me still more,' said the son. * Be it so, my child/ the father replied. TENTH KHAJVDA. 1. 'These rivers, my son, run, the eastern (like the Ganga) toward the east, the western (like the Sindhu) toward the west. They go from sea to sea (i. e. the clouds lift up the water from the sea to the sky, and send it back as rain to the sea). They become indeed sea. And as those rivers, when they are in the sea, do not know, I arn this or that 'river, 2. 'In the same manner, my son, all these creatures, when they have come back from the True, know not that they have come back from the True. Whatever these crea- 128 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, tures are here, whether a lion, or a wolf, or a boar, or a worm, or a midge, or a gnat, or a musquito, that they become again and again. 3. ' That which is that subtile essence, in it all that exists has its Self. It is the True. It is the Self, and thou, O Svetaketu, art it.' ' Please, Sir, inform me still more/ said the son. * Be it so, my child/ the father replied. ELEVENTH KHAJVDA. 1. ' If one were to strike at the root of this large tree here, it would bleed, but it would live. If he were to strike at its stem, it would bleed, but it would live. If he were to strike at its top, it would bleed, but it would live. Per- vaded by the living Self that tree stands firm, drinking in its nourishment and rejoicing ; 2. ' But if the life (the living Self) leaves one of its branches, that branch withers; if it leaves a second, that branch withers ; if it leaves a third, that branch withers. If it leaves the whole tree, the whole tree withers. In exactly the same manner, my son, know this.' Thus he spoke : 3. 'This (body) indeed withers and dies 'when the living (Self) has left it ; the living (Self) dies not. 4 That which is that subtile essence, in it all that exists has its Self. It is the True. It is the Self, and thou, tfvetaketu, art it.' ' Please, Sir, inform me still more/ said the son. c Be it so, my child/ the father replied. TWELFTH KHAIVDA. i. 'Fetch me from thence a fruit of the Nyagrodha tree/ ' Here is one, Sir/ ' Break it/ ' It is broken, Sir/ ' What do you see there ? ' ' These seeds, almost infinitesimal/ IQNDAMENTAL DOCTRINES OF THE V-2DANTA. 129 * Break one of them.' 1 It is broken, Sir/ ' What do you see there?' ' Not anything, Sir/ 2. The father said : ' My son, that subtile essence which you do not perceive there, of that very essence this great Nyagrodha tree exists. 3. ' Believe it, my son. That which is the subtile essence, in it all that exists has its Self. It is the True. It is the Self, and thou, O vetaketu, art it/ ' Please, Sir, inform me still more/ said the-son, ' Be it so, my child/ the father replied. THIRTEENTH KHA^DA. 1. ' Place this salt in water, and then wait on me in the morning/ The son did as he was commanded. The father said to him ; * Bring me the salt, which you placed in the water last night/ The son, having looked for it, found it not, for, of course, it was melted. 2. The father said: 'Taste it from the surface of the water. How is it ? ' The son replied : ' It is salt/ ' Taste it from the middle. How is it ? ' . The son replied : ' It is salt/ ' Taste it from the bottom. How is it ? ' The son replied : ' It is salt/ The father said : ' Throw it away and then wait on me/ He did so ; but the salt continued to exist. Then the father said : ' Here a^o, in this body, indeed, you do not perceive the True (Sat), my son; but there indeed it is. 3. ' That which is the subtile essence, in it all that exists has its Self. It is the True. It is the Self, and thou, O tfvetaketu, art it/ ' Please, Sir, inform me still more/ said the son. ' Be it so, my child/ the father replied. : 9 K 130 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. FOURTEENTH KIUJTOA. 1. ' As one might lead a person with his eyes covered away from the Gandharas, and leave him then in a place where there are no human beings; and as that person would turn towards the east, or the north, or the west, and shout, " I have been brought here with my eyes covered, I have been left here with my eyes covered," 2. c And as thereupon some one might loose his bandage and say to him, " Go in that direction, it is the Gandharas, go in that direction ; " and as thereupon, having been in- formed and being able to judge for himself, he would by asking his way from village to village arrive at last at the Gandharas, in exactly the same manner does a man, who meets with a teacher to inform him, learn that there is delay so long only as " I am not delivered (from this body) ; and then I shall be perfect/' 3. * That which is the subtile essence in it all that exists has its Self. It is the True. It is the Self, and thou, O A^vetaketu, art it/ ' Please, Sir, inform me still more/ said the son, ' Be it so, my cliild/ the father replied. FIFTEENTH KHAATDA. 1. 'If a man is ill, his relatives assemble round him and ask : " Dost thou know me ? Dost thou know me ? " Then, as long as his speech is not merged in his mind, his mind in breath, breath in heat (fire), heat in the Highest Being (Devata), he knows them. 2. ' But when his speech is merged in his mind, his mind in breath, breath in heat (fire), heat in the Highest Being, then he knows them not. ' That which is the subtile essence, in it all that exists has its Self. It is the True. It is the Self, and thou, O $vetaketu, art it/ ' Please, Sir, inform me still more/ said the son. ' Be it so, my child/ the father replied. The next extract is from the KatfAa Upanishad of the F TNDAMJBNTAL DOCTRINES OF THE YZDANTA. Ya#ur-veda, and has by many scholars been classed as of later date. FIRST VALL!. i. Va^asravasa, desirous (of heavenly rewards), surren- dered (at a sacrifice) all that he possessed. He had a son of the name of Na&iketas. 4. He (knowing that his father had promised to give up at a sacrifice all that he possessed, and therefore his son also) said to his father : ' Dear father, to whom wilt thou give me ? ' He said it a second and a third time. Then the father replied (angrily) : ' I shall give thee unto Death/ (The father, having once said so, though iu haste, had to be true to his word and to sacrifice his son.) 5. The son said : ' I go as the first, at the head of many (who have still to die) ; I go in the midst of many (who are now dying). What will be the work of Yama (the ruler of the departed) which to-day he has to do unto me ? 6. * Look back how it was with those who came before, look forward how it will be with those who come here- after, A mortal ripens like corn, like corn he springs up again/ (NaMketas then enters into the abode of Yama Vaivas- vata, and there is no one to receive him. Thereupon one of the attendants of Yama is supposed to say :) 7. < Fire enters into the houses, when a Brahmawa enters as*a guest. That fire is quenched by this peace-offering; bring, water, O Vaivasvata ! 8. 'A Brahmaria that dwells in the house of a foolish man without receiving food to eat, destroys his hopes and expectations, his possessions, his righteousness, his sacred and his good deeds, and all his sons and cattle/ (Yama, returning to his house after an absence of three nights, during which time Na&iketas had received no hos- pitality from him, says :) 9. ' O BrahmaTia, as thou, a venerable guest, hast dwelt in my house three nights without eating, therefore choose now three boons. Hail to thee ! and welfare to me i ' K 2 132 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. 10. Na/dketas said : ' Death, as the first of tlie three boons I choose that Gautama, my father, be pacified, kind, and free from anger towards me ; and that he may know me and greet me, when I shall have been dismissed by thee/ 11. Yama said: 'With my leave, Audd&laki Armu, thy father, will know thee, and be again towards thee as he was before. He shall sleep peacefully through the night, and free from anger, after having seen thee freed from the jaws of death/ 12. Na/dketas said: 'In the heaven- world there is no fear ; thou art not there, O Death; and no one is afraid on account of old age. Leaving behind both hunger and thirst, and out of the reach of sorrow, all rejoice in the world of heaven/ 13. ' Thou knowest, O Death, the fire-sacrifice which leads us to heaven ; tell it to me, for I am full of faith. Those who live in the heaven-world reach immortality, this I ask as my second boon/ 14. Yama said: 'I will tell it thee, learn it from me, and when thou understandest that fire-sacrifice which leads to heaven, know, O Naiiketas, that it is the attain- ment of the eternal worlds, and their firm support, hidden in darkness/ 15. Yama then told him that fire-sacrifice, in the begin- ning of the worlds, and whafT bricks* are required for the altar, and how many, and how they are to be placed. And Na/dketas repeated all as it had been told to him. Then Mrityu, being pleased with him, said again : 19. 'This, O Nafciketas, is thy fire which leads to heaven, and which thou hast chosen as thy second boon. That fire all men will proclaim as thine. Choose now, O Na&iketas, thy third boon/ ' 20. NaAdketas said: 'JThere is that doubt, when a man is dead, some saying, he is; others, he is not. This I should like to know, taught by thee ; this is the third of my boons/ 2,1. Death said: 'On this point even the gods have been in doubt formerly; it is not easy to understand. That subject is subtle. Choose another boon, O Na&iketas, do not press me, and let me off that boon/ FUNDAMENTAL DOCTRINES OF THE VEDANTA 133 22. Na/dketas said : ' On this point even the gods have been in doubt indeed, and thou, Death, hast declared it to be not easy to understand, and another teacher like thee is not to be found : surely no other boon is like unto this/ 23. Death said : c Choose sons and grandsons who shall live a hundred years, herds of cattle, elephants, gold, and horses. Choose the wide abode of the earth, and live thyself as many harvests as thou desirest.' 24. ' If thou canst think of any boon equal to that, choose wealth, and long life. Be (king), Na&iketas, on the wide earth. I make thee the enjoy er of all desires/ 25. 'Whatever desires are difficult to attain among mortals, ask for them according to thy wish; these fair maidens with their chariots and musical instruments, such are indeed not to be obtained by men, be waited on by them whom I give to thee, but do not ask me about dying/ 26. Na&iketas said : ' Thoughts of to-morrow, O Death, wear out the present vigour of all the senses of man. Even the whole of life is short. Keep thou thy horses, keep dance and song for thyself/ 27. 'No man can be made happy through wealth. Shall we have wealth, when we see thee ? Let us live, as long as thou rulest? Only that boon (which I have chosen) is to be chosen by me/ 28. ' What mortal, slowly decaying here below, and knowing, after having approached them, the freedom from decay enjoyed by the immortals, would delight in a long life, after he has pondered on the pleasures which arise from beauty and love ? ' 29. ' No, that on which there is this doubt, O Death, tell us what there is in that great. Hereafter. Na&iketas does not choose another boon but that which enters into what is hidden/ SECOND VALL! j. Death said: 'The good is one thing, the pleasant another ; these two, having different objects, chain a man. 134 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, It is well with him who clings to the good ; he who chooses the pleasant, misses his end/ 3. ' The good and the pleasant approach man : the wise goes round about them and distinguishes them. Yea, the wise prefers the good to the pleasant, but the fool chooses the pleasant through greed and avarice/ 3. 'Thou,0 Na&iketas, after pondering all pleasures that are or seem delightful, hast dismissed them all. Thou hast not gone into the road that leadeth to wealth, in which many men perish/ 4. ' Wide apart and leading to different points are these two, ignorance, and what is known as wisdom. I believe NaAdketas to be one who desires knowledge, for even many pleasures did not tear thee away/ 5. 'Fools dwelling in darkness, wise in their 'own con- ceit, and puffed up with vain knowledge, go round and round, staggering to and fro, like blind men led by the blind/ 6. * The Hereafter never rises before the eyes of the care- less child, deluded by the delusion of wealth. " This is the world," he thinks, " there is no other ; " thus he falls again and again under iny sway/ 7. * He (the Self) of whom many are not even able to hear, whom many, even when they hear of him, do not comprehend ; wonderful is a man, when found, who is able to teach this (the Self) ; wonderful is he who comprehends this, when taught by an able teacher/ 9. 'That doctrine is not to be obtained by argument, but when it is declared by another, then, O dearest, it is easy to understand. Thou hast obtained it now ; thou art truly a man of true resolve. May we have always an inquirer like thee!' 10. Na&iketas said : 'I know that what is called treasure is transient, for the eternal is not obtained by things which are not eternal. Hence the Na/ciketa fire-sacrifice has been laid by me first; then, by means of transient things, I have obtained what is not transient (the teaching of Yama)/ 11. Yaina said: 'Though thou hadst seen the fulfilment of all desires, the foundation of the world, the endless FUNDAMENTAL DOCTRINES OP THE YEDANTA 135 rewards of good deeds, the shore where there is no fear, that which is magnified by praise, the wide abode, the rest, yet being wise thou hast with firm resolve dismissed it all/ 1 2. ' The wise who, by means of meditation on his Self, recognises the Ancient, who is difficult to be seen, who has entered into darkness, who is hidden in the cave, who dwells in the abyss, as God, he indeed leaves joy and sorrow far behind/ 13. * A mortal who has heard this and embraced it, who has removed from it all qualities, and has thus reached that subtle Being, rejoices, because he has obtained what is a cause for rejoicing. The house (of Brahman) is open, I believe, O Na&iketas/ 1 8. ' The knowing Self is not born, it dies not ; it sprang from nothing, nothing sprang from it. The Ancient is unborn, eternal, everlasting; he is not killed, though the body is killed/ 19. 'If the killer thinks that he kills, if the killed thinks that he is killed, they do not understand ; for this one does not kill, nor is that one killed/ 2,0. ( The Self, smaller than small, greater than great, is hidden in the heart of the creature. A man who is free from desires and free from grief, sees the majesty of the Self by the grace of the Creator (or through the serenity of the elements)/ 31. * Though sitting still, he walks far; though lying down, he goes everywhere. Who, save myself, is able to know that God, who rejoices and rejoices noil ' 22. ' The wise who knows the Self as bodiless within the bodies, as unchanging among changing things, as great and omnipresent, he never grieves/ 23. 'That Self cannot be gained by the Veda, nor by understanding, nor by much learning. He whom the Self chooses, by him the Self can be gained. The Self chooses him (his body) as his own/ 24. ' But he who has not first turned away from his wickedness, who is not tranquil, and subdued, or whose mind is not at rest, he can never obtain the Self (even) by knowledge/ INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. THIRD VALL! 1. 'There are the two, drinking their reward in the world of their own works, entered into the cave (of the heart), dwelling on the highest summit (the ether in the heart). Those who know Brahman call them shade and light; likewise, those householders who perform the TriTi^iketa sacrifice.' 2. * May we be able to master that Na&iketa rite which is a bridge for sacrificers ; which is the highest, imperish- able Brahman for those who wish to cross over to the fearless shore/ 3. ' Know the Self to be sitting in the chariot, the body to be the chariot, the intellect (buddhi) the charioteer, and the inind the reins/ 4. 'The senses they call the horses, the objects of the senses their roads. When he (the Highest Self) is in union with the body, the senses, and the mind, then wise people call him the Enjoy er/ 5. ' He who has no understanding and whose mind (the reins) is never firmly held, his senses (horses) are unman- ageable, like vicious horses of a charioteer/ 6. ' But he who has understanding and whose mind is always firmly held, his senses are under control, like good horses of a charioteer/ 7. ' He who has no understanding, who is unmindful and always impure, never reaches that place, but enters into the round of births/ 8. * But he who has understanding, who is mindful and always pure, reaches indeed that place, from whence he is not born again/ 9. 'But he who has understanding for his charioteer, and who holds the reins of the mind, he reaches the end of his journey, and that is the highest place (step) of Vishnu/ 10. ' Beyond the senses there are the objects, beyond the objects there is the mind, beyond the mind there is the intellect, the Great Self is beyond the intellect/ ii.' Beyond the Great there is the Undeveloped, beyond the Undeveloped there is the Person '(Purusha). Beyond TRANSLATION OF THE UPANISHAOS. 137 the Person there is nothing this is the goal, the furthest road/ 12. 'ifhat Self is hidden in all beings and does not shine forth, but it is seen by subtle seers through their sharp and subtle intellect/ 13. 'A wise man should keep down speech and mind ; he should keep them within the Self which is knowledge; he should keep knowledge within the Self which is the Great ; and he should keep that (the Great) within the Self which is the Quiet/ 14. 'Rise, awake! having obtained your boons, under- stand them ! The sharp edge of a razor is difficult to pass over ; difficult is the path (to the Self) ; the wise tell it/ 15. ' He who hS perceived that which is without sound, without touch, without form, without decay, without taste, eternal, without smell, without beginning, without end, beyond the Great, and unchangeable, is freed from the jaws of death/ Translation of the Upaniahads. May I be allowed to say here a few words with regard to my translation. Those who know my translation of the Upanishads, published in 1879 and 18(84, will easily see that I have altered it in several places. But I do not wish it to be understood that I consider my translation even now as quite free from doubt. Our best scholars know how far we are still from a perfect understanding of the Upanishads. When therefore, in 1879, I undertook a translation of all the more important Upanishads, all I could hope for was to give a better translation than what we had before. Though I was well aware of the difficulties of such an undertaking, I knew that I could count on the same in- dulgence which is always granted to a first attempt at translating, nay, often, as in our case, at guessing and deciphering an ancient text. Nor have I been at all con- vinced that I was wrong in following a text, such as it is presupposed by the commentaries of $a??ikara, instead of introducing conjectural emendations ; however obvious they seem to be. Scholars should learn that the more obvious their emendations are, the more difficult it becomes to 138 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, account for the introduction of such palpable corruptions into an ancient text, such as it was at the time of &amkara, My determination also, whenever it was impossible to dis- cover a satisfactory meaning, to be satisfied with /Samkara's interpretations, who after all lived a thousand years ago, may be criticised, and I never represented it as more than a pis aller. Besides that, all the translators of the S. B. E. had to make a sacrifice in giving what they could give at the time, without waiting for the ninth year. Though I have hardly ever referred to the mistakes made by earlier translators of the Upanishads, but have simply corrected them, anybody who will take the trouble to compare them with my own will find a good harvest of them, as those who come after me will no doubt glean many a stray ear even in a field which so many mowers have mowed. But the work of the children who glean some ears is very different from that of the mower who has to mow a whole field alone. Such a work as Colonel Jacob's Concordance of the Principal Upanishads and the Bhagavad-gita, pub- lished in 1891, has placed at the disposal of all Vedantic students what may almost be called a mowing machine in place of a sickle; and the careful and brilliant translation of the Sixty Upanishads published by Professor Deussen, in 1897, shows what an immense jadvance has been made with its help. I have adopted many emendations, in the extracts given above, from Professor Deussen's work, and when my translations differ from his, all I can say is that I always differ most reluctantly from one who has devoted so many years to Vedantic studies, and whose mind is so thoroughly imbued with Vedantic ideas. If we could always know at what time each Upanishad was finally settled and reduced to writing, whether before or after the time when the Vediinta and Stt9?ikhya-philosophy assumed each its own independent and systematic form, our task would be much lightened. Whenever we come across such words as Atrnan and Brahman we suspect Vedantic in- fluences, whereas Purusha and Prakriti at once remind us of Samkhya doctrines. But Atman is by no means un- known to early S&mkhya philosophers, nor is Purusha entirely outside the Vedantic horizon. To say, therefore. CHARACTER OF THE UPANISHAL3. 1.39 that Purusha must always be taken in the technical Samkhya sense, and Atman in that of the Vedanta, is going too far, at least at present. We go still further out of our depth if we maintain, with regard to the KaAa Upanishad, for instance, that there was a time when it consisted of one chapter and three Vallis only. It may have been so, and who shall prove that it was not so ? But on the other hand, what do we know of the compilers of the Upanishads to enable us to speak so positively on such a subject? Everybody can see that there was a divi- sion at III, 13, or 1 6, or 17. The technical repetition of certain words in IV, 17 might indicate that the Upanishad originally ended there, and that V, 18 is later. Anybody can see also that the second Adhyaya differs in spirit from the first. The name of Na/dketas, for instance, is never mentioned in the second chapter, except in the last and probably spurious or additional verse, and then it appears as N&fciketa, as derived from NaHketa, not from the old form Na/ciketas. We may easily discover a different spirit in the third, as compared with the first and second Valli. In fact, there is still plenty of work left for those who come after us, for with all that has been achieved we are on the threshold only of a truly historical study of Indian philosophy and literature. Here, also, we are still like children playing on the sea-shore and finding now and then a pebble or a shell, whilst the great ocean of that ancient literature lies before us undiscovered and unex- plored. Character of the Upanishads. Such utterances as I have here quoted from the Upani- shads will hardly seem worthy of the name of philosophy. It would have been almost impossible to describe them so as to give a clear idea of what the Upanishads really are. With us philosophy always means something systematic, while what we find here are philosophic rhapsodies rather than consecutive treatises. But that is the very reason why the Upanishads are so interesting to the historical student. Nowhere, except in India, can we watch that period of chaotic thought, half poetical, half religious, 140 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. which preceded, in India at least, the age of philosophy, properly so called. Possibly, if we knew more of the utter- ances of such men as Heraclitus or Epimenides in Greece, they might show some likeness to the outpourings of the authors of the Upanishads. What is quite clear, however, is that the systematic philosophy of India would be per- fectly unintelligible without the previous chapter of the Upanishads. And however unsystematic these relics of the childhood of philosophy may seem, there is really more system in them than appears at first sight. They contain a number even of technical terms which show that the Upanishads did not spring up in one day, and that there must have been a good deal of philosophical controversy during the age that is recorded to us in the Upanishads. If /Svetaketu is represented as attending the schools of famous teachers till he is twenty-four years of age, and is then only learning from his father the highest wisdom, we see that that highest wisdom had already been fully elabo- rated in the formula of ' Tat tvam asi,' ' Thou art that/ that is, thou, man, art not different from that divine nature which pervades the whole world, as salt pervades the sea. You cannot see it, you cannot handle it, but you can taste it and know that, though invisible, it is there. That divine essence, that which is alone true and real in this unreal or pheno- menal world, is present likewise, though invisible, as the germ of life in the smallest seed, and without it there would be no seed, no fruit, no tree, as without God there would be no world. That this ancient wisdom should be so often mixed up with what seems to us childish and absurd, is as true as it is difficult to explain, but we must remember that a long continued oral tradition must naturally leave 'a wide door open to additions of every kind. Whatever we may think of these Upanishads, it cannot be doubted that they represent the soil which contained the seeds of philosophy which sprang up and had their full growth in the great systems of philosophy of a later age. Ved&nta-Sfltras. If now we turn to these, and first of all, to the philosophy VEDANTA-SUTRAS 141 elaborated by BadarayaTia, we find no longer rhapsodies, but a carefully reasoned system, contained in 555 short para- graphs, the so-called Ved&nta-Sutras. We read there in the first Sutra and as a kind of title, ' Now then a desire to know Brahman/ or as Deussen translates 6?i/7/Sabda, sound, or Brahman or Va/c or *Brih = word, was eternal, absolute, self-luminous, self-evident, in fact all that the Veda is said WOltK-PART AND KNOWLEDGE-PART OP THF- VEDA. to be. Two such words as Brahman and Atman would by themselves convey that eternal truth for which the Vedanta- philosophy is fighting, and in support of which there is bufc.. one appeal, not to sensuous experience nor to inference, but to the Word itself, i.e. to Brahman, or the Veda. I know full well how entirely hypothetical, if not mystical, this may sound to many Sanskrit scholars, but I could not entirely suppress these thoughts, as they seem to me the only way in which we can free our Vedanta philosophers from the charge of childishness, for imagining that they could establish the highest truths which are within the reach of the human mind, on such authorities as the hymns, the Brahma^as and even some of the Upanishads, &s we possess them now. Returning to the Vedanca, however, such as we know it from the Sutras, we must be satisfied with the expressea view of Badaraya?ia that the evidence for what the Yed&ntd teaches is neither perception nor inference, but the Word (/Sabda) alone, such as we find it in our manuscripts, or rather in the oral tradition of the Veda. Work-part and Knowledge-part of the Veda. Of course a distinction has to be made, and has been made by Badaraya?ta between the Knowledge-part, the G^ana-k&ftcZa, chiefly the Upanishads, and the Karma- karcda, the Work-part, the hymns and Brahma /ms. Both are called Veda or $ruti, revelation, and yet the work-part does not exist for the true philosopher, except in order to be discarded as soon as he has understood the knowledge- part. $arakara is bold enough to declare that the whole Veda is useless to a man who has obtained knowledge, or Mukti, or freedom. * Not all the Vedas together/ he says, ' are more useful to one who has obtained true knowledge than is a small tank of water in a country flooded with water/ A man who has neglected the Vedas and disre- garded thu rules of the four Asramas, in fact, a man who has lost caste, may still be allowed to study the Vedanta as the fountain of all true knowledge, and thus become liberated (III, 4, 36). The hymns and Brahrruuias refer in fact to the 'phenomenal world, they presuppose the exist- 152 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. ence of a manifold creation, of an enjoyer of what is to be enjoyed, of good works and their fruit. But all this, as we shall see, is not real, but phenomenal; it belongs to the realm of Avidya, Nescience, and vanishes as soon as true wisdom or Vidya has been obtained. It is to be observed in the world, such as it is, as a lower stage, but as essential in leading on to a higher stage. Vidyfl, and Avi&ya. If then the highest truth contained in the Veda is the Tat Tvam,Asi, that is, Thou, the Givatman, art it (the Parawatman or Brahman), and if, as we are told, there is but one Brahman and nothing beside it, the Vedanta philo- sopher is at once met by the question, How then are we to account for the manifold Thou's, the many individuals; and the immense variety of the objective world? If the Veda is true, our view of the world cannot be true at the same time. It can therefore be due only to what is called Avidya, Nescience, and it is the very object of the Vedanta- philosophy to expel and annihilate this Avidya, and replace it by Vidya. Subject and Object. This Avidyft is the next point that has to be discussed. $amkara, in the introduction to his commentary, has some important remarks on it 1 . ' As it is well known,' he says, * that object and subject, which fall under the concepts of We and You (or as we should say, of the Ego arid Non- Ego), are in their very essence opposed -to each other, like darkness and light, and that the one can never therefore take the place of the other, it follows further that their attributes also can never be interchanged.' This means that object and subject mutually exclude each other, so that what is conceived as object can never in the same act of thought be conceived as subject, and vice versa. We can, for instance, never say or think : We are you, or You are we, nor ought we ever to substitute subjective for objective qualities. ' Therefore/ he continues, * we may conclude that to transfer what is objective, that is what is perceived 1 Three Lectures on the Vod&nta, p. 62. SUBJECT AND OBJECT. 153 as You or Non-ego with its qualities, to what is subjective, that is what perceives as We, the Ego, which consists of thought, or vice versa to transfer what is subjective to what is objective, must be altogether wrong.' A subject can never be anything but a subject, the object always remains the object. * Nevertheless/ he adds, < it is a habit in human nature (a necessity of thought, as* we might call it), to say, combining what is true and what is false, " I afh this/ 3 " this is mine, &c. This is a habit, caused by a false apprehension^ of subject and predicate, and by not distin- guishing one from the other, but transferring the essence and the qualities of the one upon the other/ It is clear that $amkara here uses subject and object net only in their simple logical sense, but that by subject he means what is real and true, in fact the Self, while object means with him what is unreal and phenomenal, such as the body with its organs, and the whole visible world. In * I am/ tiie verb has a totally different character from what it has in ' thou art * .or * he is.' Such statements therefore as 4 1 am strong/ or ' I am blind/ arise from a false appre- hension which, though it is inseparable from human thought, such as it is, has slowly to be overcome and at last to be destroyed by the Vedanta-phiiosophy. This distinction between subject and object in the sense of what is real and what is phenomenal is very important, and stamps the whole of the Vedanta-philosophy with its own peculiar character. It follows in fact from this fundamental distinction that we should never predicate what is phenomenal or objective of what is real and subjective, or what is real and subjec- tive of what is phenomenal and objective; and it is in causing tliis mistake that the chief power of Avidya or Nescience consists. I should even go so far as to say that this warning might be taken to heart by our own philo- sophers also, for many of our own fallacies arise from the same Avidya, and are due in the end to the attribution of phenomenal and objective qualities to the subjective reali- ties which we should recognise in the Divine only, and as underlying the Human Self and the phenomenal world. It must not be supposed, however, that the Avidya or 154 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Nescience which makes the world what we make it and take it to be, is simply our own individual ignorance, our being unacquainted with the truths of the Vedanta. It should rather be looked upon as inborn in human nature, or, from an Indian point of view, as the result of accumu- lated thoughts and deeds before the mountains were brought forth. It has. truly been called a general cosmical Nes- cience, inevitable for a time, as darkness is with light. So far as in true reality we are Brahman, our Nescience might indeed be called the Nescience of Brahman, if for a time only; and if we remember that it can be annihilated, we can understand why it was said to be nought, for, according to a general principle of the Vedanta, nothing that is real' can ever be annihilated, so that nothing that is liable to annihilation has a right to be called real. The Phenomenal Reality of the World. But it is very curious to find that though $arakara looks upon the whole objective world as the result of Nescience, he nevertheless allows it to be real for all practical purposes (Vyavaharartham). Thus we read (II, i, 14), * The entire complex of phenomenal existence is considered as true so long as the Knowledge of Brahman and the Self of all has not arisen, just as the phantoms of a drearn are considered to be true until the sleeper wakes. . . .' Hence, as long as true knowledge does not present itself, there is no reason why the ordinary course of secular and religious activity should not go on undisttirbed, and more particularly, why all the commands of the Veda, even of the work-part, should not be obeyed. . But apart from this concession, the fundamental doctrine of $amkara remains always the same. There is Brahman and nothing else ; and to this Brahman as the subject, nothing must be ascribed that is peculiar to the individual living soul (I, 3, 19). The individual, soul is, no. doubt, Brahman, for the simple reason that there is nothing but Brahman, but Brahman is riot the individual soul, which in its present state is personal, that is conditioned, and pheno- menal. All we may predicate of that Highest Brahman is CREATION OB CAUSATION. 155 that it is one, never changing, never in contact with any- thing, devoid of all form, eternally pure, intelligent and free. To ascribe anything phenomenal to that Brahman or Atman would be the same error as to ascribe blue colour to the colourless ether of the sky. Creation or Causation. If with these ideas, taken as granted, we approach the problem of what we call the creation or the making of the world, it is clear that creation in our sense -cannot exist for the Vedantist. As long as creation is conceived as a making or fashioning of matter, it does not exist for Badarayarta; only so far as it is a calling forth out of nothing does it approach the ideas of the Vedantist. Crea- tion with Badaraya?ia would be nothing but the result of Nescience, and yet Brahman is again .and again repre- sented as the cause of the world, and not only as the efficient, but as the material cause as well, so far as such foreign terms can be applied to the reasoning of the Ve- danta. Here lies our great difficulty in rendering Hindu- philosophy intelligible. The terms used by them seem to be the same as those which we use ourselves, and yet they are not. It is easy to say that Kararia is cause and Karya effect, that the created world is the effect, and that Brah- man is the cause. But the Vedahtists have elaborated their own theory of cause and effect. According to them cause and effect are really the same thing looked at from two points of view, and the effect is always supposed to be latent in the cause. Hence, if Brahman is everything, and nothing exists besides Brahman, the substance of the world can be nothing, but Brahman. Divyadasa, a living Vedantist, seems therefore to draw a quite legitimate in- ference when he says 1 that the universe with all its sins and miseries must have existed latent in Brahman, just as steam existed latent in water before it was heated, though it does not become evident as vapour till tire is brought near to water. 1 Lectures on the Vedanta, p. 24. 156 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Cause aad Effect. This question of cause and effect and their mutual rela- tion has occupied most of the philosophical systems of India; and when we remember what different views of cause and effect have beun held by some of the most eminent philosophers of Europe, it is not surprising that the Hindus also should have arrived at very different results. The Vedantists stand up for Karya-kara?iabheda, the non-difference or substantial identity of cause and effect, and the Samkhya philosophers agree with them up to a certain point. In the Vedanta, .11, I, 14, we read in so many words, Tadananyatvam, that is, ' they, cause and effect, are not other, are not different from each other/ On this, as a general principle, ress their dogma of the substantial identity of Brahman and the phenomenal world, Nor does $amkara support this principle by passages from the Veda only, but he appeals likewise to observation. Thus he continues, II, i, 15, 'Only when a cause exists is an effect observed to exist, not when it does riot exist. The non-difference of the two (cause and effect) is perceived, for instance, in an aggregate of threads, when we do not perceive the thing which we call cloth in addition to the threads, but merely threads running lengthways, and cross- ways. In the threads again we perceive finer threads, and in these again still finer threads, and so on. On this ground we conclude that the very finest parts which we can per- ceive are ultimately identical with, their causes, viz. red, white, and black, these again with air, the air with ether, and, at last, the ether with Brahman which is without a second and the ultimate cause of the whole world. Or again, when we look at a tree and ask what it is, when we see through its leaves and fruits, its bark and wood, and ask again what it is, the answer comes that it would be nothing if it were not Brahman, that it lives through Brah- man, that it exists through Brahman, that it would not be at all but for Brahman. This is the real Pantheism of the Vedanta : and strange as it may sound to us, it would not be difficult to match it whether from our own philosophers or our poets. Even so recent a poet as Tennyson is reported CAUSE AND EFFECT. 157 to have said, ' Perhaps this earth and all that is in it storms, mountains, cataracts, the sun and the skies, are the Almighty: in fact, such is our petty nature, we cannot see Him, but we see His shadow, as it were, a distorted shadow/ Is not this pure Vedanta? only that the Ve- daritists hold that a cause, by its very nature, can never become the object of perception, while what Tennyson calls the distorted shadow would come very near to the Avidya of iSawkara. The Veda has declared * that what is posterior in time, Le. the effect, has its being, previous to its actual beginning, in the nature of the cause/ And $arakara adds that, even, in cases where the continued existence of the cause (in the effect) is not perceived, as, for instance, in the case of seeds of the fig-tree from which spring sprouts and new trees, the term birth, as applied to the sprout, means only that the causal substance, viz. the seed, becomes visible by becoming a sprout through the continued accre- tion of similar particles, while the term death means no more than that through the secession of these particles, the cause passes again beyond the sphere of visibility. This problem of cause and effect in connection with the problem of Brahman and the world was no doubt beset with difficulties in the eyes of the Vedantists. If they turned to the Veda, particularly to the Upanishads, there were ever so many passages declaring that Brahman is one and unchangeable, while in other passages the same Brah- man is called the Creator, and from him, and not, as the Samkhyas hold, from a second non-intelligent power, called Prakriti, the creation, sttstentation, and reabsorption of the world are said to proceed. If it be asked how two such opinions can be reconciled, 6'a.mkara answers : ' Belonging to the Self, as it were, of the omniscient Lord, there are names and forms (Namarupa)/ These correspond very closely to the Logoi of Greek philosophy, except that, instead of being the ideas of a Divine Mind, they are the figments of Nescience, not to be defined as either real (Brahman), or as different from it. They are the germs of the entire expanse of the phenomenal world, that is, of whatinSruti and Snm'ti is called illusion (Maya), power (&akti), or nature (Prakriti). Different, however, from all 158 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. this is the Omniscient Lord, and in support of this a number of Vedic passages may be quoted, such as 'He who is called Ether is the revealer of all forms and names ; that wherein these forms and names are contained, that is Brahman' (J^M-nd. Up. VIII, 14, i); Let me evolve names and forms ' (JfAand. Up. VI, 3, 2) ; ' He, the wise one, having defined all forms and having made their names, sits speak- ing/ i.e. creating (Taitt. Ar. Ill, 12, 7); 'He who makes the one seed manifold ' (/Svet. Up. VI, 12). The Lord as creator, as Lord or tsvara, depends upon the limiting conditions of the Upadhis of name and form, and these, even in the Lord, are represented as products of Nescience, not like the Logoi, creations of a Divine Wisdom. The true Self, according to the Vedanta, is all the time free from all conditions, free from names and forms, and for the truly informed enlightened man the whole phenomenal world is really non-existent. To steer between all these rocks is no easy matter. Brahman, though called the material cause (Upadana) of the world, is himself immaterial, nay the world, of wnich he is the cause, is considered as unreal /while at the same time cause and effect are held to be identical in substance. While the Vedantist is threatened by all these breakers, the Samkhya philosopher is far less imperilled. He starts with a Prakriti, a power different from Brahman, gener- ally, though very imperfectly, translated by Nature, as the material cause of the world. Prakriti exists, as far as man is concerned, only so far as it is taken notice of by man (Purusha) ; and he, the Purusha, on taking notice, may therefore be called the efficient cause of the world, Prakriti itself being its material cause. Otherwise Kapila takes much the same view of the relation between cause and effect as the Vedantist. The Karya-karanabheda, the identity "of cause and effect, is valid as much for S&rakhya as for Vedanta. According to both, no real effect would be possible without the continuance of its cause. Though different in appearance or phenomenally, both are the same substantially. An effect is not something newly produced or created, it is a new manifestation only, the cause being never destroyed, but rendered invisible only. This is so CAUSE AND EFFECT. 159 characteristic a dogma of the Samkhya that this philo- sophy is often spoken of as the Sat-karyavada, the doctrine that every effect pre-exists, and is the effect of something real, while the Asat-karyavada is peculiar to Nyaya and Vaiseshika, and strongly supported by the Buddhists. Whether this doctrine of the identity of cause and effect was first proclaimed by Kapila or by BadarayaTia, it is almost impossible to settle. Professor Garbe \ who claims it for Kapila, may be right in supposing that it would be a more natural theorem for a follower of the Samkhya than of the Vedanta, but this could never be used as an argument that the Samkhya-philosophy is older in its entirety than the Ved&nta. $amkara himself certainly gives us the im- pression that with him the recognition of the identity of cause and effect came first, and afterwards its religious application, the identity of Brahman and the world. For he says (II, i, 20), ' Thus the non-difference of the effect from the cause is to be conceived. And therefore, as the whole world is an effect of Brahman, and non-different from it, the promise is fulfilled.' It is curious that Kapila seems, almost in so many words, to guard against what is known to us as Hume's view of causality. For in Stitra I, 4, i, he says, If it were only priority, there would be no law or hold (Niyama) between cause and effect. 1 The Sat-karyavada, which might be compared with Herbart's ftelbsterhaltung des Realen, is often illustrated by the very popular simile of the rope which is mistaken for a snake, but which, even in its mistaken character, has the very real effect of frightening those who step on it. There is more in this often-quoted simile than at first sight appears. It is meant to show that as the rope is to the snake, so Brahman is to the world. There is no idea of claiming for the rope a real change into a snake, and in the same way no real change can be claimed for Brahman, when perceived as the world. Brahman presents itself as the world, and apart from Brahman the world would be simply nothing. If, therefore, Brahman is called the material cause of the world, this is not meant in the 1 Samkhya- Philosophic, p. 232. 160 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. sense in which the clay is the material cause of a jar. Even the apparent and illusory existence of a material world requires a real substratum, which is Brahman, just as the appearance of the snake in the simile requires the real substratum of a rope. If we once see this clearly, we shall also see that Nescience may quite as well be called . the material cause of the world as Brahman, the fact being that, strictly speaking, there is with the Vedantists no matter at all; in our sense of the word. Breaming and Waking 1 , There is, however, in the Vedanta, as well as in many other systems of philosophy, a certain ambiguity as to what is meant by material and real. One would have thought that philosophers, who look upon everything as the result of Avidya or Nescience, would have denied all reality in the highest sense to everything except Brah- man. And so in a certain sense they do. But besides the concession to which we alluded before, that for practical purposes (Vyavaharartham) things may be treated as real, whatever we may think of them in our heart of hearts, a concession, by-the-by, which even Berkeley and Kant would readily have allowed, there is another important argument, It is clearly directed against Buddhist philo- sophers who, carrying tile Vedanta principle to its extreme consequences, held that everything is empty and unreal, and that all we have and know are our perceptions only. This is called the Sftnyavada (doctrine of emptiness or vanity) or Vidyamatra (knowledge only). Although some Vedantists have been credited with holding the same opinion, and have actually been called Cryptobuddhists in consequence, Samkara himself argues most strongly against this extreme idealism. He not only allows the reality of the objective world for practical purposes (Vya- vaharartham), but he enters on a full argument against the nihilism of the Buddhists. These maintain that per- ception in dreams is oi* the same kind as all other perception, and that the admission of the existence of external things is therefore unnecessary. No, says jS'amkara, there is a difference between perceiving viands and perceiving the DREAMING AND WAKING. , l6l satisfaction arising from eating them. He holds, therefore, that in perceiving anything we not only perceive our per- ceptions, but perceive something not ourselves, and not our perceptions. He also points out that there is this difference between dreaming and waking, that dreams on awaking are found to be unreal. Dreams at night are contradicted by full daylight, but. perceptions in full day- light are not contradicted by dreams. When the Btiddhist replies that, in spite of that, we never can be said to per- ceive anything but perceptions, the Tedantist answers that, though we perceive perceptions only, these perceptions are always perceived as perceptions of something. And if the Buddhists answer that these perceptions are illusive only, that they are perceptions o things as if they were without us, the Vedantist asks What is meant by that ' without us/ to which all things perceived by us are referred ? If our perceptions conform to anything without us, the existence of such perceived objects is ipso facto admitted. No one would say that perception and what is perceived are iden- tical ; they stand to each other in the relation of instrument and effect, just as when we speak of an impression, we admit something that impresses as well as something that is impressed. This must suffice to show what the Vedantists thought of the difference between the real and the phenomenal, and what was the meaning they attached to Avidy& by which not only the individual Egos, but the whole phenomenal World exists or seems to exist.. Creation is not real in the highest sense in which Brahman is real, but it is real in so far as it is phenomenal, for nothing can be phenomenal except as the phenomenon of something that is real. No wonder that, with all these ambiguities about .the pheno- menally real and the, really real, different schools even in India should have differed in their views about Avidygi, and that European scholars also should have failed to form a clear idea of that creative Nescience of which we can neither say that it is or that it is not. Avidya, like all other words, has had a history. In the Upanishads it is often used in the simple sense of ignorance, and opposed to Vidy&, knowledge. Both are in that sense simply sub- 11 M 1 62 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. jective. Thijs we read, jKMnd. Up. I, i, 10 : * Both perform the sacrificial act, he who knows and he who does not know. But there is a difference between Vidya (know- ledge) and Avidya (nescience). For what is performed with Vidya, with faith, and with the Upanishad, that is more efficacious/ Or again, Brih. Ar. Up. IV, 3, 20 : ' If he feels in a dream as if he were murdered, then, in his ignorance, he takes that to be real whatever he fears, when awake/ Here we see that it is ignorance alone which imparts a false character of reality to the visions of a dream. In the same Upanishad, IV, 4, 3, a man, when dying, is said to shake off his body and his Avidya. We are right therefore, I believe, if historically we trace the concept of Avidya back to the subjective ignorance of the individual, just as we saw that the higher concept of the Self, though in the end identical with Brahman, arose from that of the indi- vidual personal Self , when as yet not free from the limits of the Ego. In some of the later Upanishads this Nesci- ence or Ignorance assumes a more independent character and even a new name, viz. M&ya. It. is then no longer the Nescience of the individual, but the result of that universal Nescience, which is the cause of what we should call the phenomenal world. Thus we read in the /Svet. Up. IV, 10 : ' Know Prakriti (nature) as Maya (magic), and the great Lord as the May in, (magician)/ Though this is not pure Vedanta, it shows us, at all events, the way by which the ignorance of the individual became the cause of what we call objective reality, and led, at the same time, to the admission of an, active and creative Lord, the personal Brahma or Isvara ; how Avidya in fact became a /Sakti or potentia, somehow or other related to Brahman itself. But before there arises this M&ya of objective nature, belonging as it were to Brahman himself, there was the Maya of the internal or subjective world. THis was originally the only Maya, and, deceived by that Maya or Avidya, the Atman, or pure Self, was covered up (Upahita) or blinded, or conditioned by the so-called Upadhis, the conditions or impositions, if we may say so, in both senses. There is here again a certain ambiguity, the UpMhis being caused by primeval Avidya, and, from another point of DREAMING AND WAKING. 163 view, Avidya\ being caused in the individual soul (Giv&b- man) by the UpMhis. These Upadhis are : 1. The Mukhyapr&raa, the vital spirit; (unconscious) ; 2. the Manas, the central organ of perception, ready to receive what is conveyed to it by the separate senses, and to react on them by will ; Manas being that which, as we say, perceives, feels, thinks and wills ; 3. the Indriyas, the five senses, both afferent and efferent. The five afferent (Upalabdhi) senses are the senses of hearing, touch, sight, taste, scent. The five efferent or acting senses (Adhyavasaya l ) are the senses of speaking, grasping, going, evp"uat:*ng and generating ; 4. the material organic body. To these is sometimes added 5. The objective environment, or the objects or meanings of the senses (Artha). All these are not the Atman, and it is only through Avidy& that the Atman has become identified with them. That there is in man something that can be called Atman or Self requires no proof, but if a proof were wanted it would be found in the fact that no one can say, 'I am not* (I being the disguised Atman), for he who would say so, would himself be not, or would not be. The question then is, What is really I or what is there real behind the 1 1 It cannot be the body as influenced by our objective environ- irient, for that body is perishable ; it cannot be the Indriyas or the Manas "or the MukhyaprS/tta, for all these have a beginning, a growth, and therefore an end. All these, called the Upadhis, conditions, are to be treated as Not- self ; and if it be asked why they should ever have been treated as Self, the only possible answer is that it was through Nescience or Avidy&, but through a Nescience that is not only casual or individual, but universal. What in our common language we call the Ego or Ahamkra is but a product of the Manas and quite as unsubstantial in reality as the Manas itself, the senses and the whole body. We can understand how this startling idealism or 1 Adhyavasftyo buddhifc, S&wkhya-Sfttras II, 13. M 2 1 64 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. monism for it is not nihilism, though our philosophy has no better name for it led to two distinct, yet closely united view? if the world. Ail that we should call phenomenal, comprehending the phenomena of our inward as well as of our outward experience, was unreal ; but, as the pheno- menal was considered impossible without the noumenal, that is, without the real Brahman, it was in that sense real also, that is, it exists, and can only exist, with Brahman behind it. And this led to the admission by the strict Advaitists or Monists of two kinds of knowledge, well -known' under the names of Apara, the lower, and Jrar&, the higher knowledge. Th Higher and th X-ower Knowledge. The higher knowledge consists in A the distinction and thereby the freedom of the Self (Atman) from all its Upadhis, and this not for this life only, but for all eter- nity. This is the true Moksha or freedom which implies knowledge of the identity of the Atman with Brahman, and deliverance from birth and rebirth in the constant evolution (Sams&ra) of the world. The lower knowledge is likewise founded on the Veda, but chiefly on its work- portion (Karmakanda), and teaches, not how Brahman is to be known, but how it or he is to be worshipped in its or his phenomenal state, that is, as a personal Lord and Crea- tor, or even under the name of any individual deity. This worship (Up&san&) being enjoined in many parts of the Veda, 'is recognised as obligatory on all who have not yet reached the highest knowledge. These are even allowed the comfort that, in worshipping a personal god, they are really worshipping Brahman, the true Godhead, though in its phenomenal aspect only, and they are promised, as a reward of their worship, happiness on earth and in heaven, nay by way of preparation, a slow advance (Kra- mamukti) towards complete Moksha or freedom. In this sense it has been truly said that $arakara did not attack or destroy idolatry, though with him it was always symbolism rather than idolatry. On this point which has given rise to much controversy among the Hindus them- THE HIGHEH AND THE LOWEE KNOWLEDGE. 165 selves, some appealing to $amkara's contempt of all ritual* ism and Karman, others to his defence of a worship of the popular gods, I may quote the words of a living Ved&ntist. Divyadas Datta, in his Lectttre on Vedantism, p. 1 2. ' It is certain/ he says, ' that $amkara was opposed to the abuse of ritualism, and though he did not cut off all con- nection with idolatry, he tried to introduce the right spirit of idolatry. Idolatry in the sense of religious symbolism and I believe the most orthodox Hindus would take no other view cannot be open to objection. Symbolism there must be, whether in words or things. Verbal symbols appeal to the ear, and the symbols of things to the eye, and that is all the difference between them. Verbal symbolism is language. Who 'would object to the use of language in religion ? But if the one is allowed, why shouid not also the other? To my mind, idolatry, apart from its attendant corruptions, is a religious algebra. And if verbal symbols, without the spirit or in a corrupted spirit, are not objec- tionable, [but are they not ?] so, and to the same extent, formal symbols, or stocks and stones also are unobjection- able. At one stage of its growth, idolatry is a necessity of our nature. The tender seed of a religious spirit requires to be carefully preserved in a soft coating of -symbols, till it has acquired the strength to resist the nipping frost of worldliness and scepticism. . . . When the religious spirit is mature, symbols are either given up, or suffered to remain from their harmlessness. . . . . Samkara did bow to idols, sometimes as symbols of the great Infinite, sometimes as symbols of lower orders of beings in whom he believed. . . . These lower orders of divine beings, Brahma, Vishnu, Indra, Yama, &c., in whom he believfed, are phenomenal, $nd subject to creation and dissolution as much as ourselves/ &amkara himself expresses this opinion very clearly when (I, 3, 38) he says: 'The gods (or deities) must be* admitted to be corporeal, and though by their divine powers they can, at one and the same time, partake of oblations offered at numerous sacrifices, they are still, like ourselves, subject to birth and death/ If a?nkara did riot dbim full freedom or Moksha for himself, he did so, as he says, for the sake of others. * If 1 66 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. I/ he says, 'had not walked Without remission in the path of works, others would not have followed my steps, O Lord ! ' Is Virtue Essential to Moksha ? Another question which has been hotly contested both in India and in Europe is whether Moksha can be the result of knowledge only, or whether it requires a fulfilment of moral duties also *. Though, as far as I understand $ara- kara, knowledge alone can in the end lead to Moksha, virtue is certainly presupposed. It is the same question which meets us with regard to the Buddhist Nirvana. This also was in the beginning the result and the reward of moral virtue, of the restraint of passions and of perfect tranquillity of soul, such as we find it described, for instance, in the Dhammapada ; but it soon assumed a different char- acter, as representing freedom from all bondage and illusion, amounting to a denial of all reality in the objec- tive, and likewise in the subjective world. There are a few traces left in the Upanishads, showing that virtue was-con- sidered an essential preliminary of Moksha. In the KatKa, TJpanishad II, i, which is generally quoted for that purpose, we read: 'The good is one thing, the pleasant another; these two having different objects chain a man. It is well with him, if he clings to the good ; but he who chooses the pleasant, misses his end. The good and the pleasant approach a man ; the wise goes round about them and dis- tinguishes them. Yea, the wise prefers the good to the pleasant, but the fool chooses thp pleasant through greed and avarice/ But even in this passage we are not told that virtue or self-denial by itself could secure Moksha or perfect freedom ; nay, if we only read a few lines further, we see : ' Wide apart and leading to different points are those two, ignorance ( Avidya) and what is known as wisdom (Vidya).' And Na/dketas is praised because he desires knowledge, and is not tempted away from it by pleasure. Still less convincing are passages taken from the Bhagavad- gita, a work which was meant to present different views See Mokaha or the Vedantic Release, by Divyadas Datta, Journal of the R. A. S., vol. xx, part 4. IS VIRTUE ESSENTIAL TO MQKSFA? 167 of Moksha. All of them, no doubt, though they do not explicitly say so, presuppose high morality on the part of the candidate, so that Arguna is made to say for himself : (Janami dharmam, na &a me prav?^tti&, (?anamy adharmam, -na Aa me mvriitih, which has been somewhat freely translated : ' For what I would that I do not, Lut what I hate that do I.' That later treatises, such as the Pa/?&adast, should lay great stress on the religious and moral side of Moksha is tyuite compatible with what has been maintained before, that Moksha cannot be achieved by sacrifices or by moral conduct, but in the end by knowledge only. Hence a prayer such as, ' May such unchanging love as foolish people feel for earthly pleasures never cease in my heart when I call upon Thee ! ' may well be uttered by worshippers of Brahma or Isvara, but not by the true Mumukshu, \v ho is yearning for Brah- man and true Moksha. Even the prayer from the Brihad-araTiyaka (I, 3, 28) * Lead me from the unreal to the real ! Lead me from darkness to light ! Lead me from death to immortality ! ' refers to the lower knowledge only, and has for its reward another world, that is, the heaven world, which will also pass away. It would not be difficult, no doubt, to produce passages which declare that a sinful man cannot obtain Mqksha, but that is very different from saying that Moksha can be obtained by mere abstaining from sin. Good works, even merely ceremonial works, if performed from pure motives and without any hope of rewards, form an excellent prepa- ration for reaching that highest knowledge which it is the final aim of the Vedanta to impart. And thus we read : ' Brahmarcas seek to know Him by the study of the Veda, by sacrifices, by charitable gifts' (Brih. Up. IV, 4, 22). But when the knowledge of the highest Brahman has once been reached or is within reach, all works, whether good or bad, fall away. ' The fetter of the heart is broken, 1 68 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, all doubts are solved, extinguished are all his works, when He has been beheld who is both high and low' (MuraZ. Up. II, *, 8). Hence, to imagine that true Moksha can be obtained by moral conduct alone is a mistake, while there are passages in the Upanishads to show that some Vedantists taught that a man who had reached Brahman and the highest knowledge, was even in this life above the distinction of good and evil, that is, could do nothing that he considered good and nothing that he considered evil. Dangerous as this principle seems to be, that whosoever knows Brahman cannot sin/ it is hardly more dangerous, if properly under- stood, than the saying of St. John (Ep. I, v. 68), that who- soever is born of God, sinneth not. The Two Brahmans. It sometimes seems as if $amkara and Badarayawa had actually admitted not only two kinds of knowledge, but two Brahmans also, Sagunarn and NirguTiam, with or without qualities, but this would again apply to a state of Nescience or Avidya only; and it is in this sense alone that Brahman also may be said to be affected by Avidya, nay to be produced by Avidya, not by the Avidya of single individuals, but by an Avidya inherent in sentient nature. The true Brahman, however, remains always Nirgunam or unqualified, whatever we may think about him ; arid as, with regard to Brahman, to be conceived and to be is the same thing, so likewise, so far as we are concerned, Brahman is conceived by us and becomes to us qualified, active, crea- tive and personal through the deception of the same uni- versal and inevitable Avidya. In the same way the creation of the world and of man is not the work of Brahman, but the result of Avidya and of man while under her sway. This ambiguity runs through the whole of the Vedanta, at least according to the interpretation of /Samkara. It will be seen how small a step it was from this view to another which looked upon Brahman itself as affected by Avidya, nay which changed this Avidya into a >S'akti or potent ia of Brahman, thus lowering him, not raising THE TWO BRAHMANS. 169 him, to the character of an active creator. In full reality Brahman is as little affected by qualities as our true Self is by Upadhis (conditions), but the same Nescience which clouds us for a time, clouds ipso facto Brahman also, Atman (Crivatman) and Brahman being substantially A one. If the qualified Brahman makes us, we, the qualified Atman, make Brahman, as our maker. Only we must never forget that all this is illusion, so that in truth we can predicate nothing of Brahman but Na, na, i. e. No, no ; he is not this, he is not that. He is, that is all we can say* and is more than everything else. In that sense Brahman may be called both Sat and A sat, being and not being, being in the highest sense, not being, as different from all that the world calfe being or true. If in the later Upanishads Brahman is called Safc-Add-ananda, ' being, perceiving, and blessed/ then these three predicates are in reality but one, for *he or it could not be without perceiving itself (esse est percipere), and he or it could not per'ceive himself or itself except as inde- pendent, perfect, unaffected and untrammelled by anything else ( Advitiya). Having no qualities, this highest Brahman cannot of course be known by predicates. It is subjective, and not liable to any objective attributes. If it knows, it can only know itself, like the sun that is not lighted, but lights itself. Our knowledge of Brahman also can only be consciousness of Brahman as our own subjective Atman or Self. It seems only a concession to the prejudices, or let us say, the convictions of the people of India, that an ecstatic per- ception of Brahman was allowed as now and then possible in a state of trance, such as the Yogins practised in ancient, and even in modern times, though, strictly speaking, this perception also could only be a perception of the Atman as identical with Brahman. The fatal mistake which in- terpreters of the Vedanta-philosophy both in India and Europe have made is to represent this absorption or re- covery (Samnullianaii), accomplishment) as an approach of the individual soul towards God. There can be no such approach where there is identity, there can only be recovery or restitution, a return, a becoming of the soul of what it always has been, a revival of its true nature. 170 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Even Yoga, as we shall see, did not mean technically union, nor Yogin a man united with God, but Yoga is effort, towards Nirodha or suppression of Kiita, (the activity of thought) (see Yoga-Sutras I, 2). We shall thus understand the distinction which the Ve- dantists and other Indian philosophers also make between the Brahman, TO OVTMS ov, and the Brahman as Isvara, the personal God, worshipped under different names, as creator, preserver, and dissolver of the universe. This Isvara exists, just as everything else exists, as phenomenally only, not as absolutely real. Most important acts are ascribed to him, and whatever he may appear to be, he is always Brahman,, When personified by the power of Avidya or Nescience, he rules the world, though it is a phenomenal world, and determines, though he does not cause, rewards and punish- ments. These are produced directly by the acts themselves. But it is He through whose grace deeds are followed by rewards, and man at last obtains true knowledge and Mukti, though this Mukti involves by necessity the w disap- pearance of Isvara as a merely phenomenal god. It must be clear to any one who has once mastered the framework of the true Vedaiita-philosophy, as I have here tried to explain it, that there is really but little room in it for psychology or kosmology, nay even for ethics. The soul and the world both belong to the realm of things which are not real, and have little if anything to do with the true Vedanta in its highest and truest form. This consists in the complete surrender of all we are and know. It rests chiefly on the tremendous synthesis of subject and object, the identification of cause and effect, of the I and the It. This constitutes the unique character of the Vedanta, unique as compared with every other philosophy of the world which has not been influenced by it, directly or in- directly. If we have once grasped that synthesis, we know the Vedanta. All its other teaching flows naturally from this one fundamental doctrine ; and though its carefully thought out and worked out details are full of interest, they contain no thoughts, so entirely new at the time when they were uttered, as this identity of subject and object, or this complete absorption of the object by this subject. PHILOSOPHY AND BELIGION, KAR.^AN. Philosophy and Religion. It is interesting to see how this very bold philosophy of- the Vedanta was always not only tolerated, but encouraged and patronised by religion and by its recognised repre- sentatives. Nor did the Vedanta as a philosophy interfere with popular religion; on the contrary, it accepted all that is taught about the gods in the hymns and in the BrahmaTi-as, and recommended a number of sacrificial and ceremonial acts as resting on the authority of these hymns and Brahmartas. They were even considered as a neces- sary preliminary to higher knowledge. The creation of the world, though not the making of it, was accepted as an emanation from Brahman, to be followed in great periods by a taking back of it into Brahman. The individual souls also were supposed, at the end of each Kalpa, to Be .drawn back into Brahman, but, unless entirely liberated, to break forth again and again at the beginning of every new Kalpa. The individual souls, so far as they can claim any reality, date, we are told, from all eternity, and not from the day of their birth on earth. They are clothed in their Upadhis (conditions) according to the merit or demerit which they have acquired by their former, though long-forgotten, acts. Here we perceive the principal moral element in the ancient Vedanta, so far as it is meant for practical life, and this doctrine of Karman or deed, to which we alluded before, has remained to the present day, and has leavened the whole of India, whether it was under the sway of Brahmans or of Buddhists. The whole world, such as it is, is the result of acts ; the character and fate of each man are the result of his acts in this or in a former life, possibly also of the acts of others. This is with them the solution of what we venture to call the injustice of God. It is their Theodicee. A man who suffers and suffers, as we say, unjustly, seems to them but paying off a debt or laying up capital for another life. A man who enjoys health and wealth is made to feel that he is spending more than he has earned, and that he has therefore to make up his debt 172 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. by new efforts. It cannot be by a Divine caprice that one man is born deaf or dumb or blind, another strong and healthy. It can be the result of former acts only, whether, in this life, the doer of them is aware of them or not. It is not even necessarily a punishment, it may be a reward in disguise. It might seem sometimes as if Avidya too, which is answerable for the whole of this phenomenal world, had to be taken as the result of acts far back before the beginning of all things. But this is never clearly stated. On the contrary, this primeval Avidy is left unexplained, it is not to be accounted for, as little as Brahman can be accounted for. Like Brahman it has to be accepted as existent ; but it differs from Brahman in so far as it can be destroyed by Vidygt, which is the eternal life-spring of Brahman. The merit which can be acquired by man even in this state of Avidya is such that he may rise even to the status of a god, though for a time only, for at the end of a Kalpa even gods like Indra and the rest have to begin their career afresh. In fact it might be said with some truth that Avidy is the cause of everything, except of Brahman ; but that the cause of that primeval Avidya is beyond our powers of conception. Brahman is Everything 1 . These powers of conception are real indeed for all practical purposes, but in the highest sense they top are phenomenal only. They too are but Namarftpa, name and form; and the reality that lies behind them, the Atman that receives thorn, is Brahman and nothing else. This might become clearer if we took Brahman for the Kantian Ding an sick, remembering only that, according, to the Kantian philosophy, the Kupa, the forms of intuition and the categories of thought, though subjective, are accepted as true, while the Vedanta treats them also as the result of Nescience, though true for all practical purposes in this phenomenal life. In this sense the Vedanta is more scep- tical or critical than even Kant's critical philosophy, though the two agree with each other again when we remember that Kant also denies the validity of these forms of per- ception and thought when applied to transcendent subjects. THE STHULA- AND SUKSHMA-SARTBA. 173 According to Kant it is man who creates the world, as far as its form (Namarftpa) is concerned; according to the Vedanta this kind of creation is due to Avidya. And strange as it may sound to apply that name of Avidya to Kant's intuitions of sense and his categories of the under- standing, there is a common element in them, though hidden under different names. It would be natural to suppose that this Atman within had been taken as a part of Brahman, or as a modification of Brahman: but no. According to &amkara the world is, as I tried to show 1 on a former occasion, the whole of Brahman in all its integrity, and not a part only ; only, owing to Avidya, wrongly conceived arid individualised. Here we have in fact the Holenmerian theory of Plotinus and of Dr. Henry More, anticipated in India. If the Atman within seems limited like the Brahman when seen in the objective world, this is once more due to Avidya. Brahman ought to be omni- present, omniscient, and omnipotent ; though we know but too well that in ourselves it is very far from all this. The Sthflla- and StLkshma-x&rira, These are the conditions or Upadhis which consist of Manas, mind, Indriyas, senses, Pranas, vital spirits, and the Sarira, body, as determined by the outward world. This Vedantie arrangement of our organic structure and our mental organisation is curious, but it seems to have been more or less the common property of all Indian philoso- phers, and supplied by the common language of the people. What is peculiar in it is the admission of a central organ, receiving and arranging what has been conveyed to it by the separate organs of sensQ. We have no word corre- sponding to it, though with proper limitations we may continue to translate it by mens or mind. It woi^ld repre- sent perception as uniting and arranging the great mass of sensations, but it includes besides Upalabdhi, perception, Adhyavasaya, determination also, so far as it depends on a previous interaction of percepts. Heuce a man is said to see by the mind (Manas, vovs), but he may also be said 1 Theosophy, p. 280. I 74 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. to decide and act by the mind (Manas). All this may seem very crude, leaving particularly the question of the change of mere sensations into percepts (Vorstdlungen), a subject so carefully elaborated by modern philosophers, and of per- cepts into concepts, unapproached and unexplained. Here the philosophy of Herbart would supply what is wanted. He too, being opposed to the admission of various mental faculties, is satisfied with one, the Manas, and tries to explain all psychical phenomena whatever as the result of the action and interaction of elementary Vorstellungen (ideas or presentations). By the side of the vital spirit, the Mukhya Pr&na, we find a fivefold division into Prana, Upana, Vyana, Samana, and Udana, meaning originally forth-, off-, through-, with-, and out-breathing, but afterwards defined differently and without much reference to any physiological data. This also is a doctrine common to most systems of Indian philo- sophy, though it is difficult to see by what physiological observations it could have been suggested. What is more interesting is the distinction between the Sthftla- and Sftkshma-sarira, the coarse and the fine body, the former the visible outward body; the latter invisible and consisting of Mukhya Pra?ia, vital spirit, Manas, mind, and Indriyas, organs of sense. This body is supposed to remain after death, while the outer body is dissolved into its material elements. The thin or subtle body, though transparent or invisible, is nevertheless accepted as mate- rial; and it is this Sukshma-sarfra which is supposed to migrate after death from world to world, but, for the most part, in an unconscious state. It is not like a human body with arms and legs. The Four States. Here again we come across an original idea of Indian philosophy, the doctrine of the four states, the state of being awake, the state of dreaming, the state of deep and dreamless sleep, to which is added A as the fourth, the state of death. In the first state the Atman is supposed to be Krceiving and acting by means of the Manas and the driyas. In the second the Indriyas cease to act, but ESOHATOLOGY. 175 the Manas remains active, and the Atman, joined to the Manas, moves through the veins of the body and sees dreams made out of the remnants of former impressions (Vasan&s). The third state arises from a complete separa- tion of Atman from Manas and Indriyas. While these are absorbed in the vital spirit, which remains in full activity, the Atman in the heart is supposed to have for a time become one with Brahman, but to return unchanged at the time A of awakening. In the fourth or disembodied state the Atman with the Sftkshma-sarira is supposed to escape from the heart through a vein in the head or through the hundred veins of the body, and then to take, according to merit and knowledge, different paths into the next life. Escbatology. Such fancies seem strange in systems of philosophy like the Ved&nta ; and, with the full recognition of the limits of human knowledge, we can hardly understand how Vedaritists accepted this account of the Sftkshma-sarira, the circumstances attending the departure of the soul, in fact, a complete Eschatology, simply on the authority of the Veda. It is taken over from the Upanishads, and that may be the : excuse for it. Vedantists had once for all bound themselves to accept the Upanishads as revealed truth, and the usual result followed. But we should see clearly that, while much may be taken over from the Veda as due to Avidya, we are here really moving in an Avidya within that Avidya. For practical purposes Avidya may often be called common sense, under its well-understood limitations, or the wisdom of the world. But these dreams about the details of a future life are a mere phantasmagoria. They cannot even be treated as Naisargrka, or inevitable. They are simply Mithyag/lana, fanciful or false knowledge, if not that which is commonly illustrated by the son of a barren woman that is, a self -contradictory statement that kind at least which is unsupported by any evidence, such as the horn of a hare. This is really a weakness that runs through the whole of the Vedanta, and cannot be helped. After the supreme and superhuman authority of the Word or of the Veda had once been recognised, a great 176 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. portion of the sacred traditions of the Vedic age, incor- porated as they are in the hymns, the BrahmaTias, and the Upanishads, had to be accepted with the rest, though ac- cepted as part of the Apara Yidya, the lower knowledge only. All the sacrificial rules, nay the very conception of a sacrifice, had no place in the Para Vidya, or the highest knowledge, because they involved, an actor and an enjoy er of the fruits of such acts, and the truly enlightened man cannot be either an actor or an enjoyer 1 . However, as a preparation, as a means of subduing the passions and purifying the mind by drawing it away from the low and vulgar interests of life, all such commandments, together with the promises of rewards vouchsafed to them, might perhaps have been tolerated. But when we come to a full description of the stations on the road by which the subtle body is supposed to travel from the veins of this body to the very steps of the golden throne of the Lower Brahman, we wonder at the long suffering of the true philosopher who has learnt that the true and highest knowledge of the Vedanta removes in the twinkling of an eye (ApatataA) the veil that in this life seems to separate Atman from Brah- man. As these eschatological dreams have been included in the Vedanta system, they had to be mentioned here, though they are better studied in the pages of the Upani- shads. We are told there that, in the case of persons who have fulfilled their religious or sacrificial duties and have lived a good life, but have not yet reached the highest know- ledge, the subtle body in which the Atman is clothed migrates, carried along by the Udana through the Mftr- dhanya N&di, the capital vein, following either the path of the fathers (Pitriy&na) or the path of the gods (Devayana). The former is meant for good people, the latter for those who are good and have already reached the lower, if not the highest knowledge. The former leads on to smoke, night, the waning moon, the waning year, the world of the fathers, the ether, and lastly the moon. In the moon the departed souls remain for a time enjoying the rewards of * See Sarnkara's Introduction to the Aitareya Upanishad. ESCHATOLOGY. 177 their good deeds, in company with the Pitn's, and then descend again, supported by the remnant of unrewarded merit due to their good works, to the ether, wind, smoke, cloud, rain, and plants. From the plants springs seed which, when matured in the womb, begins a new life on earth in such a station as the rest of his former deeds (Anusaya), Anlage, may warrant. As this is, as far as I know, the earliest allusion to metempsychosis or fteelen- wanderung, it may be of interest to see in what sense /Samkara in his commentary on Sutra III, I, 22 took it 1 : 'It has been explained/ he says, 'that the souls of those who perform sacrifices, &c., after having reached the moon, dwell there as long as their works last, and then redescend with a remainder of their good works. We now have to inquire into the mode of that descent. On this point the Veda makes the following statement: "They return again the way they came to the ether, from the ether to the air (wind). Then the sacrificer having become air becomes smoke, having become smoke he becomes mist, having become mist he becomes a cloud, having become a cloud he falls down as rain." Here a doubt arises whether the descending souls pass over into a statQ of identity (Sabhavyam) with ether, &e., or into a state of similarity (Samyam) only. The Purvapakshin (opponent) maintains that the state is one of identity, because this is directly stated by the text. Otherwise there would take place what is called indication only (Laksha?i&, i.e. secondary application . of a word), and whenever the doubt lies be- tween a directly expressed and a merely indicated meaning, the former is to be preferred. Thus the following words also, " Having become air ha becomes smoke," &c., are ap- propriate only if the soul be understood to identify itself with them. Hence it follows that the souls (of the de- parted) become really identical with ether. To this we ($arakara) reply that they only pass into a state of simi- larity to ether, &c. When the body, consisting of water which the soul had assumed in the sphere of the moon for 1 S.B.E., vol. xxxvii, Thibaut's translation. 12 N- i;8 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. the purpose of enjoyment, dissolves at the time when that enjoyment comes to an end, then it becomes subtle like ether, passes thereupon into the power of the air, and then gets mixed with smoke, &c. This is the meaning of the clauses, " They return as they came to the ether, from the ether to the air," &c. How is this known to be the mean- ing ? Because thus only is it possible. For it is not pos- sible that one thing should become another in the literal sense of the word. If, moreover, the souls became identified wl'li ether, they could no longer descend through the air. And as connection with the ether is, on account of its all- pervadingness, eternal, no other connection (of the souls) with if can here be meant, but their entering into a state of similarity to it. In cases where it is impossible to accept the literal meaning of the text, it is quite proper to assume the meaning which is merely indicated. For these reasons the souls' becoming ether, &c., has to be taken in the secon- dary sense of their passing into a state of similarity to ether, and so on/ We see from this that $awkara believed in a similarity only, an outward and temporary similarity between the departed (in its Sftkshma-sartra) and the ether, air, mist, cloud, and rain; and it is important to observe how, in doing so, he violently twisted the natural meaning of S&bhavya, the word used in the Sfttras, rather than alter- ing a word of the Sfttra, and replacing S&bhavyam by S&myam. A similar difficulty arises again when it has to be deter- mined whether the departed, in his further descent, actually becomes a plant, such as rice, corn, sesamum, beans, &c., or becomes merely connected with them. Samkara decides strongly in favour of the latter view, though here again the actual words of the S6tra have certainly to be twisted by him ; nay, though Samkara himself has to admit that other people may really, on account of their bad deeds, sink so low as to become plants. He only denies this with re- ference to the departed who, on account of their pious works, have already reached the moon, and are after that redescending upon earth. Lastly, if it is said that the plant, when eaten, becomes ESCHATOLOGY. 179 a piogenitor, this also, according to tfamkara, can only mean that it is joined with a progenitor. For the pro- genitor must exist long before he eats the rice or the beans, and is able to beget a child. Anyhow, the child when begotten is the soul that had ascended to and descended from the moon, and is born again according to his former works. I must confess that, though the Ved&ntists may be bound by /Samkara's interpretation, it seems to me as if the author of the Sfttras himself had taken a different view, and had looked throughout on ether, air, mist, cloud, rain, plants as the habitat, though the temporary habitat only, or the de- parted in their subtle body \ Little is said in the Upanishads of those who, owing to their evil deeds, do not even rise to the moon and descend again. But Badar&yaTia tries to make it clear that the Upanishads know of a third class of beings (III, I, 12) who reap the fruits of their evil actions in Samyamana (abode of Yama) and then ascend to earth again. Theirs is the third place alluded to in the Kh&nd. Upanishad V, 10, 8. But while evil doers are thus punished in different hells, as mentioned in the Puranas, and while pious people are fully rewarded in the moon and then return again to the earth, those who have been pious and have also reached at least the lower knowledge of Brahman follow a different road. After leaving the body, they enter the flame, the day, the waxing moon, the waxing year (northern preces- sion), the year, the world of the Devas, the world of V&yu, air, the sun, the moon, and then lightning ; but -all these, we are told, are not abodes for the soul, but guides only who, when the departed has reached the lightning, hand him over to a person who is said to be not-a-man. This person conducts him to the world of Varuna, then to that of Indra, and lastly to that of Pra(/apati or the qualified Brahma. Here the souls are supposed to remain till they realise true knowledge or the Samyagdarsana, which does not mean universal, but thorough and complete knowledge, 1 See Vishwu Dh. S. XLIII, 45. N 2 ISO INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. that knowledge which, if obtained on earth, at once frees a man from all illusion. Finally the souls, when fully re- leased, share in all the powers of Brahrnan except those of creating and ruling the universe. They are not supposed ev.er to return to the world of Samsara (IV, 4, 17). All this is hardly to be called philosophy, neither do the different descriptions of the road on which the souls of the pious are supposed to wander towards Brahrn&, and' which naturally vary according to different schools, help us much towards a real insight into the Vedanta. But it would have been unfair to leave out what, 'though childish, is a charac- teristic-feature of the Vednta-phtlosophy, and must be judged- from a purely historical point of view. Freedom in, this Life. What is of importance to remember in these ancient fancies is that the enlightened man may become free or obtain Mukti even in this life (Givanmukti 1 ). This is indeed the real object of the Vedknta-philosophy, to A over- come all Nescience, to become once more what the Atman always has been, namely Brahman, and then to wait till death removes the last Up&dhis or fetters, which, though they fetter the mind no longer, remain like Jbroken chains hanging heavy on the mortal body. The Atman, having recovered its Brahmahood, is even in this life so free from " the body that it feels no longer any pain, and cannot do anything, whether good or bad This has been always laid hold of as the most dangerous doctrine of Vedantism, and no doubt it may be both misunderstood and misapplied. But in the beginning it meant no more than that the Atman, which is above the distinctions of subject and object, of past and present, of cause .and effect, is also by necessity above the distinction of good and evil. This never was intended as freedom in the sense of licence, but as freedom that can neither lapse into sinful acts nor claim any merit for good acts, being at rest and blessed in itself and in Brahman. It is hardly necessary to say or to prove that the Vedanta- philosophy, even in its popular form, holds out no en- 1 Vodanta-Sfctras III, 3, 28, FEE JB DOM IN THIS LIFE. l8l couragement to vic$. Far from it. No one can even approach it who hastoot previously passed through a course 01 discipline, whether as a student (Brahrna&arin) or as a householder (GrihastKa). In order to make this quite clear, it may be useful to add a few verses from one of the many popular works intended to teach Vedanta to the masses. It is Called the Mohamudgara, the Hammer of Folly, and is ascribed to /Samkara. Though not strictly philosophical, it may serve at least to show tjie state of mind in which the true Ved&ntist is meant tov maintain himself. It was carefully edited with Bengali, Hindi and English translations by Durga Das Ray, and published at Darjeeling in 1888. ' Fool ! give up thy thirst for wealth, banish all desires from thy heart. Let thy mind be satisfied with what is gained by thy Karman. Who is thy wife and who is thy son? Curious are the ways of this world " Who art thou ? Whence didst thou come ? Ponder on this, O Brother." Do not be proud of wealth, of friends, or youth. Time takes all away in a moment. Leaving all this which is full of illusion, leave quickly and enter into the place of Brahman. Life is tremulous like a water-drop on a lotus-leaf. The company of the good, though for a moment only, is the only boat for crossing this ocean of the world As is birth so is death, and so is th^ dwelling in the mother's womb. Thus is manifest the misery of the world. How can there be satisfaction here for thee, O Man ! Day and night, morning and evening, winter and spring come and go. Time is playing, life is waning yet the breath of hope never ceases. The bpdy is wrinkled, the hair grey, the mouth has become toothless, the stick in the hand shakes, yet man leaves not the anchor of hope. To live under a tree of the house of the gods, to sleep on the earth, to put on a goat-skin, to abandon all worldly enjoyment ; when does such surrender not make happy ? Do not trouble abgut enemy, friend, son, or relation, whether for war or peace. Preserve equanimity always, if 1 82 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. you desire soon to reach the place of Vishnu (Vishnu- pada). The eight great mountains, the seven oceans, Brahma, Indra, the Sun and the Rudras, thou, I and the whole world are nothing ; why then is there any sorrow ? In thee, in me, and in others there dwells Vishnu alone, it is useless to be angry with me and impatient. See every self in Self, and give up all thought of difference. The child is given to play, the youth delights in a beauti- ful damsel, an old man is absorbed in cares no one clings to the Highest Brahman. Consider wealth as useless, there is truly no particle of happiness in it. " The rich are afraid even of their son, this is the rule established everywhere. So long as a man can earn money, his family is kind to him. But when his body becomes infirm through old age, no man in the house asks after him. Having given up lust, anger, avarice, and distraction, meditate on thyself, who thou art. Fools without a know- ledge oiHSelf are hidden in hell and boiled. In these sixteen verses the whole teaching of the disciples has been told. Those in whom this does not produce under- standing, who can do more for them ? ' Different Ways of Studying 1 Philosophy. This may not be exactly moral teaching as we under- stand it. But there are two ways of studying philosophy. We may study it in a critical or in a historical spirit. The critic would no doubt fasten at once on the superses- sion of morality in the Vedanta as an unpardonable flaw. One of the corner-stones, without which the grandest pyramid of thought must necessarily collapse, would seem to be missing in it. The historian on "the other hand will be satisfied with simply measuring the pyramid or trying to scale it step by step, as far as his thoughts will carry him. He would thus understand the labour it has required in building up, and possibly discover some counteracting forces that rendjer the absence even of a corner-stone in- telligible, pardonable, and free from danger. It is surely astounding that such a system as the Vedanta should have DIFFERENT WAYS OF STUDYING PHILOSOPHY. 183 been slowly elaborated by the indefatigable and intrepid thinkers of India thousands of years ago, a system that even now makes us feel giddy, as in mounting the last steps of the swaying spire of an ancient Gothic cathedral. None of our philosophers, not excepting Heraclitus, Plato, Kant, or Hegel, has ventured to erect such a spire, never frightened by storms or lightnings. Stone follows on stone in regular succession after once the first step has been made, after once it has been clearly seen that in the beginning there can have been but One, as there will be but One in the end, whether we call it Atman or Brahman. We may prefer to look upon the expansion of the world in names and forms as the work of Sophia or as the realised Logos, but we cannot but admire the boldness with which the Hindu metaphysician, impressed with the miseries and evanescence of this world, could bring himself to declare even the Logos to be but the result of Avidya or Nescience, so that in the destruction of that Avidya could be recog- nised the highest object, and the summum bonum (Puru- shartha) of man. We need not praise or try to imitate a Colosseum, but if we have any heart for the builders of former days we cannot help feeling that it was a colossal and stupendous effort. And this is the feeling which I cannot resist in examining the ancient Vedanta. Other philosophers have denied the reality of the world as per- ceived by us, but no one has ventured to deny at the same time the reality of what we call the -Ego, the senses and the mind, and their inherent forms. And yet after Jif ting the Self above body and soul, after^ uniting heaven and earth, God and man, Brahman and Atman, these 'Vedanta philosophers have destroyed nothing in the life of the. phenomenal beings who have to act and to fulfil their duties in this phenomenal world. On the contrary, they have shown that there can be nothing phenomenal without something that is real, and thai? goodness and virtue, faith and works, are necessary .as a preparation, nay as a sine qud non. for the attainment of that highest knowledge which brings the soul bstck to its source and to its home, and restores it to its true nature, to its true Selfhood in Brahman. 184 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. And let us think how keenly and deeply Indian thinkers must have felt the eternal riddles of this world before they could propose so desperate a solution as that of the Vedanta; how desperate they must have thought the malady of mankind to be, before they could think of so radical a cure. A student of the history of philosophy must brace himself to follow those whom he wants to reach and to understand. He has to climb like a mountaineer, undismayed by avalanches and precipices. He must be able to breathe in the thinnest air, never discouraged even if snow and ice bar his access to the highest point ever reached by the boldest explorers. Even if ne has sometimes to descend again, disappointed, he has at all events strengthened his lungs and his muscles for further work. He has done his athletic exercise, and he has seen views such a& n.r x 3 never seen in the valleys below. I am myself not a mountaineer, nor am I altogether a Ved&ntist ; but if I can admire the bold climbers scaling Mount Gaurf-Samkar, I can also admire the bold thinkers toiling up to heights of the Vedanta where they seem lost to us in clouds and sky. Do we imagine that these ascents were undertaken from mere recklessness, from mere love of danger? It ig easy for u6 to call those ancient explorers reckless adventurers, or dispose of them with the help of other names, such as mystic or pantheist, often but half understood by those who employ them. The Vedantists have often been called Atheists, but as the gods which they denied were only Devas, or what we call false gods, they might thus far have been forgiven. They have been called Pantheists, though their theos, or their theoi, were not the P&n, but the P&n was their theos. They have been called Nihilists, but they themselves have drawn a sharp line between the upholders of the $ftnya-v&da *, the emptiness- doctrine, and their own teaching, which, on the contrary, insists throughout on the reality that underlies all phe- nomenal things,, namely Brahman, and inculcates the duties which even thin world of seeming imposes on all who are not yet in possession of the highest truth. That this 1 An important distinction between Buddhists and Vedantists is that the former hold the world to have arisen from what is not, the latter from what is, the Sat or Brahman. BAMANU0A. 185 phenomenal ivorld has no exclusive right to the name of real is surely implied by its very name. Besides, whatever perishes can never have been real. If heaven and earth shall pass away ; if we see our body, our senses, and all that has been built up on them, decaying and perishing every day before our very eyes ; if the very Ego, the Aham, is dissolved into the elements from. which it sprang, why should not the Vedantist also have held to his belief that Brahman alone is really, real, and everything else a dream ; and that even the Nama-rupas, the words and things, will vanish with each Kalpa ? To sum up, the Vedanta teaches that in the highest sense Creation is but Self-forgetfulness, and Eternal L^fe remembrance or Self-consciousness. And while to us such high abstractions may seem useless for the many, it is all the more surprising that, with the Hindus, the fundamental ideas of the Vedanta have pervaded the whole of their literature, have leaventid the whole of their language, and form to the present day the common property of the people at large. No doubt these ideas assume in the streets a different garment from what they wear among the learned in the Asramas or the forests of the country. Nay even among the learned few stand up for the complete Advaita or Monism as represented by $arakara. . The danger with $amkara's Vedantism was that what to him was sim ply phenomenal, should be taken for purely fictitious. There is, however, as great a difference between the two as there is between Avidya and Mithyagwana. Maya 1 is the cause of a phenomenal, not of a fictitious, world : and if amkara adopts the Vivarta (turning away) instead of the Pari/iama (evolution) doctrine, there is always something on which the Vivarta or illusion is at work, and which cannot be deprived of its reality. R&m&niv/a. There are schools of Vedantists who try to explain the Sutras of Badarayarca in a far more human spirit. The best known is the school of Ramanu^a, who lived in the 1 In the only passage where the Sfttras speak of Maya (III, a, 3), it need not meato more than a dream. 1 86 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. twelfth century A.D. l If we place $amkara's literary activity about the eighth century -, the claim of priority and of prior authority would belong to $amkara. But we must never forget that in India more than anywhere else, philosophy was not the property of individuals, but that, as in the period of the Upanishads, so in later times also, everybody was free to contribute his share. As we find a number of teachers mentioned in the Upanishads, and as they give us long lists of names, pupil succeeding teacher through more than fifty spiritual generations, the com- mentators also quote ever so many authorities in support of the views which they either accept or reject. Hence we cannot accept /Samkara as the only infallible interpreter of the Vedanta-Sutras, but have to recognise in his commen- tary one only of the many traditional interpretations of the Sutras which prevailed at different times in different parts of India, and in different schools. A most important passage in this respect is that in which $arakara has to copfess that others (apare tu vadinaA) differ from him, and some, as he adds, even of our own (asmadiyas 7ca Kefcit) 3 . This allows us a fresh insight into the philosophical life of India which is worth a great deal, particularly a&j the difference of opinion refers to a fundamental doctrine, namely the absolute identity of the individual soul with Brahman. $amkara, as we saw, was uncompromising on that point. With him and, as he thinks, with Badarayawa also, no reality is allowed to the soul (Atman) as an indi- vidual (Criva), or to the world as presented to and by the senses. With him the soul's reality is Brahman, and Brahman is one only. But others, he adds, allow reality to the individual souls also. Now this is the very -opinion on which another philosopher, Ramanugra, has based his own interpretation of Badaray ana's Sutras, and has founded a large and influential sect. But it does not follow that this, whether heretical or orthodox opinion, was really first propounded by Ramanut/a, for Ramanu?asa, * Now therefore the desire of knowing Brahman/ (7aimini, apparently in imitation of it, begins with Athato Dharmogrit/iz&sa, * Now therefore the desire of knowing Dharma or duty/ The two words 'Now therefore' offer as usual a large scope to a number of interpreters, but they mean no more in the end than that now, after the Veda has been read, and because it has been read, there arises a desire for knowing the full meaning of either Dharma, duty, or of Brahman, the Absolute ; the former treated in the Uttara-, the latter in the Pfrrva-Mimamsa. In fact, whatever native commentators may say to the contrary, this first Sutra is not much more than a title, as if we were to say, Now begins the philosophy of duty, or the philosophy of (raimini. Dharma, here translated by duty, refers to acts of pre- scriptive observance, chiefly sacrifices. It is said to be a neuter, if used in the latter sense, a very natural distinc- tion, though there is little evidence to that effect in the Sfttras or in the literature known to us. 2OO INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. This Dharma or duty is enjoined in the Brahman as, and these together with the Mantras are held to constitute the whole of the Veda, so that whatever is not Mantra is Brahma?m, whatever is not BrahmaTia is Mantra. The Brahmawas are said to consist of Vidhis, injunctions, and Arthavadas, glosses. The injunctions are meant* either to make us do a thing that had not been done before, or to make us know a thing that had not been known before 1 . Subsequently the Vidhis 2 are divided into Utpatti-vidhis, original or general injunctions, such as Agnihotram #uhoti, he performs the Agnihotra, and Viniyoga-vidhi, showing the manner in which a sacrifice is to be performed. The latter comprises injunctions as to the details, such as Dadhna guhoti, he performs the sacrifice with sour milk, &c. Then follow the Prayoga-vidhis which settle the exact order of sacrificial performances, and there is lastly a class of injunctions which determine who is fit to perform a sacrificial act. They are called Adhikara-vidhis. The hymns or formulas which are to be used at a sacrifice, though they are held to possess also a transcendental or mysterious effect, the Apurva, are conceived by (7aimini as mainly intended to remind the sacrificer of the gods who are to receive his sacrificial gifts. He likewise lays stress on what he calls Namadheya or the technical name of each sacrifice, such as Agnihotra, Darsapftrnamasa, Udbhid, &c. These names are found in the Brahmawas, and they are considered important, as no doubt they are, in defining the nature of a sacrifice. The Nishedhas or prohibitions require no explanation. They simply state what ought not to be done at a sacrifice. Lastly, the Arthavadas are passages in the Brahmawas which explain certain things ; they vary in character, being either glosses, comments, or explanatory statements. Contents of the P&rva-Mim&ms&. Perhaps I cannot do better than give the principal con- tents of (jaimini's Sutras, as detailed by Madhava in his 1 Rigvedabhashya, vol. i, p. 5. 2 Thibaut, Arthasamgraha, p. viii. CONTENTS OF THE JPUllVA-MIMAiSA. 2OI Nyaya-mala-vistara l . The Mimamsa consists of twelve books. In the first book is discussed the authoritative- ness of those collections of words which are severally meant by the terms injunction (Vidhi), explanatory passage (Arthavada), hymn (Mantra), tradition (Srmiti), and name (Namadheya). In the second we find certain subsidiary discussions, as e. g. on Apurva, relative to the difference of various rites, refutation of erroneously alleged proofs, and difference of performance, as in obligatory and voluntary offerings. In the third are considered revelation (Sruti), * sign ' or sense of a passage (Linga), ' context ' (Vakya), &c., and their respective weight, when in apparent opposition to one another; then the ceremonies called Pratipathi-Kar- mam, things mentioned by the way, Anarabhyadhita, things accessory to several main objects, as Praya^as, &c., and the duties of the sacrificer. In the fourth the chief subject is the influence of the principal and subordinate rites on other rites, the fruit produced by the Guhu when made of the Butea frondosa, &c., and the dice-playing, &c., which forms part of the Ra^asuya-sacrifice. In the fifth the subjects are the relative order of different passages of the Sruti, &c., the order of different parts of a sacrifice, as the seventeeq animals at the Va#apeya, the multiplication and rion-multi- plication of rites, and the respective force of the words of the Sruti, the order of mention, &c., as determining the order of performance. In the sixth we read of the persons qualified to offer sacrifices, their obligations, the substitutes for prescribed maiemls, supplies for lost or injured offer- ings, expiatory rites, the Sattra-offeririgs, things proper to be given, and the different sacrificial fines. In the seventh is treated the mode of transference of the ceremonies of one sacrifice to another by direct * command in the Vaidic text, others as inferred by 'name' or 'sign/ In the eighth, transference by virtue of the clearly expressed or obscurely expressed ' sign ' or by the predominant ' sign/ and cases also where no transference takes place. In A the ninth, the discussion begins with the adaptation (Uha) of hymns, 1 See Cowell and Gough in then* translation of the Sarvadarsana- samgraha, p. 178. 2O2 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. when quoted in a new connection, the adaptation of Samans and Mantras, and collateral questions connected therewith, In the tenth the occasions are discussed where the non- performance of the primary rite involves the * preclusion * and non-performance of the dependent rites, and occasions when rites are precluded, because other rites produce their special results, also Graha-offerings, certain Samans, and various other things, as well as different kinds of negation. In the eleventh we find the incidental mention and subse- quently the fuller discussion of Tantra. where several acts are combined into one, and Avapa, or the performing an act more than once. In the twelfth there is the discussion on Prasanga,- when the rite is performed with one chief purpose, but with an incidental further reference, on Tantra, cumulation of concurrent rites (Sarnu&Maya), and option. It is easy to see from this table of contents that neither Plato nor Kant would have felt much the wiser for them. But we must take philosophies as they are given us ; arid we should spoil the picture of the philosophical life of India, if we left out of consideration their speculations about sacrifice as contained in the Purva-Mimamsa. There are passages, however, which appeal to philosophers, such as, for instance, the chapter on the Pramanas or the authori- tative sources of knowledge, on the relation between word and thought, and similar subjects. It is true that most of these questions are treated in the other philosophies also, but they have a peculiar interest as treated by the ritualistic Piirva-Mimamsa. Pramanas of t?aimini. Thus if we turn our attention first to the Pramanas, the measures of knowledge, or the authorities to which we can appeal as the legitimate means of knowledge, as explained by the Ptirva-Mimamsa, we saw before that the VedanSsts did not pay much attention to them,, though they were acquainted with the three fundamental Praiuawas sense- perception, inference, and revelation. The Purva-Mirnamsa, on the contrary, devoted considerable attention to this subject, and admitted five, (i) Sense-perception, Pratyaksha, SUTRA- STYLE. 203 when the organs are actually in contiguity with an object ; (2) Inference (Anumana), i. e. the apprehension of an unseen member of a known association (Vyapti) by the perception of another seen member ; (3) Comparison (Upamana), know- ledge arising from resemblance; (4) Presumption (Artha- patti), such knowledge as can be derived of a thing not itself perceived, but implied by another ; (5) $abda, verbal information derived from authoritative sources. One sect of Mimamsakas, those who follow KumarilaBhafta, admitted besides, (6) Abhava, not-being, which seems but a subdivision of inference, as if we infer dry ness of the soil from the not- being or absence of clouds and rain. All these sources of information are carefully examined, but it is curious that Mimamsakas should admit this large array of sources of valid cognition, considering that for their own purposes, for establishing the nature of Dharma or duty, they practically admit but one, namely scripture or $abda. Duty, they hold, cannot rest on human authority, because the 'ought* which underlies all duty, can only be supplied by an authority that is more than human or more than fallible, and such an authority is nowhere to be found except in the Veda. This leaves, of course, the task of proving the superhuman origin of the Veda on the shoulders of (?aimini; and we shall see hereafter how he performs it. Before, however, we enter on a consideration of any of the problems treated in the Purva-Mimamsa, a few remarks have to be made on a peculiarity in the structure of the Sutras. In order to discuss a subject fully, and to arrive in the end at a definite opinion, the authors of the Sutras are encouraged to begin with stating first every possible objection that can reasonably be urged against what is their own opinion. As long as the objections are not perfectly absurd, they have a right to be stated, and this is called the Purvapaksha, the first part. Then follow answers to all these objections, and this is called the Uttarapaksha, the latter part ; and then only are we led on to the final conclusion, the Siddhanta. This system is exhaustive and 204 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. has many advantages, but it has also the disadvantage, as far as the reader is concerned, that, without a commentary, he often feels doubtful where the cons end and the pros begin. The commentators themselves differ sometimes on that point. Sometimes again, instead of three, a case or Adhikaraw-a is stated in five members, namely : i. The subject to* be explained (Vishaya). 3. The doubt (Samsaya). 3. The first side or prima facie view (Purvapaksha). 4. The demonstrated conclusion (Siddhanta) ; and 5. The connection (Samgati). This is illustrated in the commentary on the first and second SMras of the Mima/msa \ which declares that a desire to know duty is to be entertained, and then defines duty (Charm a) as that which is to be recognised by an insti- gatory passage, that is by a passage from the Veda. Here the question to be discussed (Vishaya) is, whether the study of Duty in Craimini's Mimamsa is really necessary to be undertaken. The Purvapaksha says of course, No, for when it is said that the Veda should be learnt (Vedo *dhyetavya&), that clearly means either that it should be understood, like any other book which we read, or that it should be learnt by heart without any attempt, as yet, on the part of the pupil to understand it, simply as a work good in itself, which has its reward in heaven. This is a very common view among the ancient Brahmans ; for, as they had no written books, they had a very perfect system for imprinting texts on the memory of young persons, by making them learn every day a certain number of verses or lines by heart, without any attempt, at first, of making them understand what they learnt; and afterwards only supplying the key to the meaning. This acquisition of the mere sound of the Veda was considered highly meritorious ; nay, some held that the Veda was more effieac'ous, if not understood than if understood. This was in fact their printing or rather their writing, and without it their mnemonic literature would have been simply impossible. 1 Sarvadarsana-samgraha, p. iaa ; translation by Cowell and Gough, p. 1 80 ; Siddhanta Dipika, 1898, p. 194. SUTRA-STYLE. 205 As we warn our compositors against trying to understand what they are printing, Indian pupils were cautioned against the same danger ; and they succeeded in learning the longest texts by heart, without even attempting at first to fathom their meaning. To us sucl\ a system seems almost in- credible, but no other system was possible in ancient times, and there is no excuse for being incredulous, for it may still be witnessed in India to the present day. Only after the text had thus been imprinted on the memory, there came the necessity of interpretation or understanding. And here the more enlightened of the Indian theologians argue that the Vedic command ' Vedo dhyetavyaA,' ' the yeda is to be gone over, that is, is to be' acquired, to be learnt by heart/ implies that it is also to be understood, and that this intelligible purpose is prefer- able to the purely mechanical one, though miraculous rewards may be held out for that. But if so, it is asked, what can be the use of the Mlm8tws&? The pupil learns the Veda by heart, and learns to understand it in the house of his teacher. After that -he bathes, marries and sets up his own house, so that it is argued there would actually be no time for any inter- vening study of the Mimamsa. Therefore the imaginary opponent, the Purvapakshin, objects that the study of the Mim&msa is not necessary at all, considering that it rests on no definite sacred command. But here the Siddh&ntin steps forward and says that the Smr?^ti passage enjoining a pupil's bathing (graduating) on returning to his house is net violated by an intervening study of the Mimamsa, because it is not said that, after having finished his apprenticeship, he should immediately bathe ; and because, though his learning of the text of the Veda is useful in every respect, a more minute study of the sacrificial pre- cepts of the Veda, such as is given in the Mimamsa, cannot be considered superfluous, as a means towards the highest object of the study of the Veda, viz. the proper performance of its commands. These considerations in support of the Siddhanta or final conclusion would probably fall under the name of Samgati, connection, though I must confess that its meaning is not 2O6 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. quite clear to me. There are besides several points in the course of this discussion, such as, for instance, the so-called four Kriyaphalas, on which more information is much to be desired. Has the Veda a Superhuman Origin? This discussion leads on to another and more important one, whether the Veda has supreme authority, whether it is the work of man, or of some inspired person, or whether it is what we should call revealed. If it were the work of a person, then, like any other work, it could not establish a duty, nor could it promise any rewards as a motive for the performance of any duty; least of all, a reward in heaven, such as the Veda promises again and again to those who perform Vedic sacrifices. It follows therefore either that the Veda has no binding authority at all, or that it cannot be the work of a personal or human author. This is a dilemma arising from convictions firmly planted in the minds of the ancient theologians of India, and it is interest- ing to see how they try to escape from all the difficulties arising out of their postulate that the Veda must be the work of a superhuman or divine author. The subject is interesting even though the arguments may not be con- vincing to us. It is clear that even to start such a claim for any book as being revealed requires a considerable advance in religious and philosophical thought, and I doubt whether such a problem could have arisen in the ancient literature of any country besides India. The Jews, no doubt, had their sacred books, but these books, though sacred, were not represented as having been the work of Jehovah. They were acknowledged to have been com- posed, if not written down, by historical persons, even if, as in the case of Moses, they actually related the death of their reputed author. The Mimamsa philosopher would probably have argued that as no writer could relate his own death, therefore Deuteronomy must be considered the work of a superhuman writer ; and some of our modern theologians have not been very far from taking the same view. To the Brahmans, any part of the Veda, even if it bore a human or historical name, was superhuman, eternal HAS THE VEDA A SUPERHUMAN ORIGIN? and infallible, much as the Gospels are in the eyes of certain Christian theologians, even though they maintain at the same time that they are historical documents written down by illiterate people, or by apostles such as St. Mark or St. John. Let us see therefore how the Mimamsa deals with this problem of the Apaurusheyatva, i.e. the non- human origin of the Vedas. Inspiration in the ordinary sense of the word would not have satisfied these Indian orthodox philosophers, for, as they truly remark, this would not exclude the possibility of error, because, however true the message might be, when given, the human recipient would always be a possible source of error, as being liable to misapprehend and misinterpret such a message. Even the senses, as they point out, can deceive us, so that we mistake mother-of-pearl for silver ; how much more easily then may we misapprehend the meaning of revealed words ! However, the first thing is to see how the Brahmans, and particularly the Mimamsakas, tried to maintain a super- human authorship in favour of the Veda. I quote from Madhava's introduction to his commentary on the Rig-veda 1 . He is a great authority in matters connected with the Pftrva-Mimamsa, having written the Nyaya-mal&-vistara, a very comprehensive treatise on the subject. In his introduction he establishes first the authority of the Mantras and of the Brahmawas, both Yidhis (rules) and Arthavadas (glosses), by showing that they were per- fectly intelligible, which had been denied. He then pro- ceeds to establish the Apaurusheyatva, the non-human authorship of the Veda, in accordance, as he says, with (?aimini's Sfttras. * Some people/ he says, and he means of course the Pftrva- pakshins, the recognised objectors, ' uphold approximation towards the Vedas/ that is to say, they hold that as the Raghuvamsa of KalidAsa and other poems are recent, so also are the Vedas. The Vedas, they continue", are not without a beginning or eternal, and hence we find men quoted in them as the authors of the Vedas. As in the J See my Second Edition, vol. i, p. 10. 208 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. case of Vyasa's Mahabharata and Valmiki's Ram&yawa, Vyasa, Valmiki, &c., are known to be their human authors, thus in the case of the KltfAaka, Kauthuma, Taittiriya, and other sections of the Veda, KaAa, &c., are given us as the names of the authors of these brandies of the Veda ; and hence it follows that the Vedas were the works of human authors. And if it were suggested that such names as Katta, &c., were meant for men who did no more than hand down the oral tradition, like teachers, the Purvapakshin is ready with a new objection, namely, that the Vedas must be of human origin, because we see in the Vedas themselves the mention of temporal matters. Thus we read of a Babara PravahaTii, of a Kusuruvinda Auddalaki, &t. The Vedas, therefore, could not have existed in times anterior to these persons mentioned in them, and hence cannot be prehistoric, pre-temporal, or eternal. It is seen from this that what is claimed for the Veda is not only revelation, communicated to historical persons, but existence from all eternity, and before the beginning of all time. We can understand there- fore why in the next Sutra, which is the Siddhanta or final conclusion, Gaimini should appeal to a former Sutra in which he established that even the relation of words to their meanings is eternal. This subject had been discussed before, in answer to the inevitable Objector-general, the Purvapakshin, who had maintained that the relation between words and their meanings was conventional (foWi), estab- lished by men, and therefore liable to error quite as much as the evidence of our senses. For as we may mistake mother-of-pearl for silver, we may surely mistake the meaningLof words, and hence the meaning of words of the Veda also. Craimini, therefore, in this place, wishes us first of all to keep in mind that the words of the Vedas them- selves are superhuman or supernatural, nay, that sound itself is eternal ; and thus fortified lie next proceeds to answer the objections derived from such names as Kanaka, or Babara PrivahaTM. This is done by showing that K&thn, did not compose, but only handed down a certain portion of the Veda, and that Babara PravAhani wa& meant, not as the name of a man, but as a name of the wind, Babara HAS THE VEDA A SUPERHUMAN OBtGIN ? imitating the sound, and Pravahana meaning 'carrying along/ as it were pro-vehens. Then follows a new objection taken from the fact that impossible or even absurd things occur in the Veda; for instance, we read that trees or serpents performed a sacri- fice, or that an old ox sang foolish 3 songs fit for the Madras. Hence it is argued once more that the Veda must have been made by human beings. But the orthodox traimini answers, No ; for if it had been made by man, there could be no injunction for the performance of sacrifices like the (?yotishoma, as a means of attaining Svarga or paradise, because no man could possibly know either the means, or their effect ; and yet there is this injunction in the case of the Cryotishfoma, and other sacrifices are not different from it. Such injunctions as ' Let a man who desires paradise, sacrifice with the (?yotishtoma ' are not like a speech of a madman; on the contrary, they are most rational in pointing out the object (paradise), in suggesting the me"ans (Soma, &c.), and in mentioning all the necessary subsidiary acts (Dikshaniya, &c.). We see, therefore, that the com- mands of the Veda are not unintelligible or absurd. And if we meet with such passages as that the trees and serpents' performed certain sacrifices, we must recognise in them Arthavadas or glosses, conveying in our case indirect laucfo- tions of certain sacrifices, as if to say, * if even trees an4 serpents perform them, how much more should intelligent beings do the same ! ' ^ As, therefore, no flaws that might arise from human workmanship can be detected in the Veda, (?aimini concludes triumphantly that its superhuman origin and its authority cannot be doubted. This must suffice to give a general idea of the character of the Pftrva-Mim&wsa. We may wonder why it should ever have been raised to the rank of a philosophical system by the side of the Uttara-Mimamsa or the Vedanta, but it is its method rather than the matter to which it is applied, that seems to have invested it with a certain importance. This Mim&msa method of discussing questions has been 1 On Mftdraka, see Muir, Sansk. Texts, IT, p. 482. 14 P 2IO INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. adopted in other branches of learning also, for instance, by the highest legal authorities in trying to settle contested questions of law. We meet with it in other systems of philosophy also as the recognised method of discussing various opinions before arriving at a final conclusion. Thre are some curious subjects discussed by (?aimim, such as what authority can be claimed for tradition, as different from revelation, how far the recognised customs of certain countries should be followed or rejected, what words are to be considered as correct or incorrect. ; or again, how a good or bad act, after it has been performed, can, in spite of the lapse of time, produce good or bad results for the performer. All this is certainly of interest to the student of Indian literature, but hardly to the student of philosophy, as such. Supposed Atheism of I One more point seems to require our attention, namely. the charge of atheism that has been brought against Craiiinni's Mimamsa. This sounds a very strange charge after what we have seen of the character of this philosophy, of its regard for the Veda, and the defence of its revealed character, nay, its insistence on the conscientious observance of all ceremonial injunctions. Still, it has been broitght both in ancient and in modern times. So early a philo- sopher as Kumarila Bhafta tells us that the Mima/msl had been treated in the world as a Lokayata l , i\ e. an atheistic system, but that he was anxious to re-establish it as orthodox. Professor Banerjea 2 tells us that Prabhakara also, the other commentator of the MimawsA, had openly treated this system as atheistic, and we shall meet with H passage from the Padrna-Pura-rJa supporting the same view. However, there seems to be a misunderstanding here. Atheistic has always meant a great many things, so much so that even the most pantheistic system that could be imagined, the Vedanta, has, like that of Spinoza, 1 Lok&ynta is explained by Childor*, P.V., as controversy on fabulous or alimird points, l\it in the Ambn////a-Sutta. I, 3, it is mentioned as forming }>url of the studicfl proper for :i Brahman. * MUJI, n r, 95. SUPPOSED ATHEISM OF P$RVA-MlMiU/SA. 21 I been accused of atheism. The reason is this. The author of the Vedfinta-Sfttras, Badarayayia. after having established the omnipresence of Brahman (III, 2, 36-37) by quoting a number of passages from the Veda, such as ' Brahman is all this' (Mum/. Up. II, 2, n), 'the Self is all this' (JSfMnd. Up. VII, 25, 2), proceeds to show (III, 2, 38) that the re- wards also of all works proceed directly or indirectly from Brahman. There were, however, two opinions on this point, one, that the works themselves produce their fruit without any divine interference, and in cases where the fruit does not appear at once, that there is a supersensuous principle, called Ap&rva, which is the direct result of a deed, and produces fruit at a later time; the other, that all actions are directly or indirectly requited by the Lord. The latter opinion, which is adopted by Baaaraya??a, is supported by a quotation from Brih. Up. IV, 4, 24, ' This is indeed the great, unborn Self, the giver of food, the giver of wealth/ (raimini, however, as we are informed by Badarayaim in the next Sutra, accepted the former opinion. The command that 'he who IB desirous of the heavenly world should sacrifice,' implies, as he holds, a reward of the sacrificer by moans of the sacrifice itself, and not by any other agent. But how a sacrifice, when it had been performed and was ended, could produce any reward, is difficult to understand. In order to explain this, (raimini assumes that there was a result, viz. an invisible something/ a kind of after-state of a deed or an invisible antecedent, state of the result, something Apurva or miraculous, which represented the reward inherent in good works. And ho adds, that if we supposed that the Lord, himself cancel rewards and punishments for the acts of men, we should often have to accuse him of cruelty and partiality; and that it is better therefore to allow that all works, good or bad, produce their own results, or, in other words, that for the moral government of the world no Lord is wanted. Here, then, we see the real state of the case as between (raimini and BAdarayatia. ffaimini would not make the Lord responsible for the injustice that seems to prevail in the world, and hence reduced everything to rause and effect, and saw in the inequalities of the world the natural v 2 212 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. result of the continued action of good or evil acts. This surely was not atheism, rather was it an attempt to clear the Lord from those charges of cruelty or undue partiality which have so often been brought against him. It was but another attempt at justifying the wisdom of God, an ancient Theodice'e, that, whatever we may think of it, certainly did not deserve the name of atheism. Badarayam, however, thought otherwise, and quoting himself, he says, c Badaraya?ia thinks the Lord to be the cause of the fruits of action/ and lie adds that he is even the cause of these actions themselves, as we may learn from a well-known Vedic passage (Kaush. Up. Ill, 8) : ' He makes whomsoever he wishes to lead up from these worlds, do good deeds; and makes him whom he wishes to lead down from these worlds, do bad deeds/ Atheism is a charge very freely brought against those who deny certain characteristics predicated of the Deity, but do not mean thereby to deny His existence. If the Mimamsakas were called atheists, it meant no more than that they tried to justify the ways of God in thir own way. But, once having been called atheists, they were accused of eve*r so many things. In a passage quoted by Professor Banerjea from a modern work, the Vidvan- modatarangi??,i, we read: 'They say ther^e is no God, or maker of the world ; nor has the world any sustainer or destroyer; for every man obtains a recompense in con- formity with his own works. Neither is there any maker of the Veda, for its words are eternal, and their arrange- ment is eternal. Its authoritativeness is self -demonstrated, for since it has been established from all eternity how can it be dependent) upon anything but itself ?' This shows how the Mimamsakas have been misunderstood by the Vedantists, and how much $amkara is at cross-purposes with ffaimini. What has happened in this case in India is what always happens when people resort to names of abuse rather than to an exchange of ideas. Surely a Deity, though He does not cause us to act/ and does not Himself reward or punish us, is not -thereby a non-existent Deity. Modern Vedantists also are so enamoured of\ their own conception of Deity, that is, of Brahinan or Atman, that IS THE PURVA-M1MAJ/SA A SYSTEM 0* PHILgSOPIJY \ 213 they do not hesitate, like Vivekananda, for instance, in his recent address 011 Practical Vedanta, 1896, to charge those who differ from himself with atheism. * He is the atheist/ he writes, ' who does not believe in himself. Not believing in the glory of your own soul is what the Vedanta calls atheism/ Is the Pfcrva-Mimamsa a system of Philosophy? Let me say once more that, in allowing a place to the Purva-Mimamsa among the six systems of Indian Philo- sophy, 1 was chiefly influenced by the fact that from an Indian point of view it always held such a place, and that by omitting it a gap would have been left in the general outline of the philosophic thought of India. Some native philosophers go so far as not only to call both systems, that of Craiinini and Badaraya7ia, by the same name of Miinamsa, but to look upon them as forming one whole. They actually take the words in the first Sutra of the Vedanta-philosophy, 'Now then a desire to know Brahman/ as pointing back to Craimini's Sutras and as thereby im- plying that the Purva-Mimamsa should be studied first, and should be followed by a study of the Uttara-Mimamsa afterwards. Besides, the. authors of the other five systems frequently refer to Graimini as an independent thinker, and though his treatment of the sacrificial system of the Veda would hardly seem to us to deserve the name of a system of philosophy, "he has nevertheless touched on many a problem which falls clearly within frhat sphere of thought. Our idea of a system of philosophy is different from the Indian conception of a Dar^ana. In its original meaning philosophy, as a love of wisdom, comes nearest to the Sanskrit (?ic//7asa, a desire to know, if not a desire to be wise. If we take philosophy in the sense of an examination of our means of knowledge (Epistemology), or with Kant as an inquiry into the limits of human knowledge, there would be nothing corresponding to it in India. Even the Vedanta, so far as it is based, not on independent reasoning, but on the authority .of the >S Y ruti, would lose with us its claim to the title of 'philosophy. But we have only to waive the claim of infallibility put forward by Badaraya/w* 214 INDIAN rillLOBOPHY. in favour 01 the utterances of the sages of the Upanishads, and treat them as simple human witnesses to the truth, and we should then find in the systematic arrangement of these utterances by Badaraya/ia, a real philosophy, a com- plete view of the Kosmos in which we live, like those that have been put forward by the great thinkers of the philo- sophical countries of the world, Greece, Italy, Germany, France, and England. CHAPTER VI HAVING explored two of the recognised systems of Indian philosophy, so far as it seemed necessary to a general survey of the work done by the ancient thinkers of India, we must now return and enter once more into the densely outaugled and almost impervious growth of thought from which aii the high roads leading towards real and definite systems of philosophy have emerged, brandling oft in different directions. One of these and, as it seems to me, by j'a-r the most important for the whole intellectual development of India, the Vedanta, has been mapped out by us at least in its broad outlines. It seemed to me undesirable to enter here on an examina- tion of what has been called the later Vedtmta which can bo studied in such works as the Pau&ada&i or the Vedanta - Sara, and in many popular treatises both in prose and in verse. &ater Yed&nta mixed with S&wfcfcye,, It would be unfair and unhistorical, however, to look upon this later development of the Vedanta as aiinply a deterioration of 1 the old philosophy. Though it 'is cer- tainly rather confused, if compared with the system as laid down in the old Vedanta-Sutras, it represents to us what in the course of time became of the Vedanta, when taught and discussed in the dijierent schools of philosophy in medieval and modern India. What strikes us most in it is the mixture of Vedaata ideas with ideas borrowed chiefly, a.s it would vse^m, from Sfu/tkhya, but also from Yoga, and Nyaya sources. 15ut here again it is difficult to decide whether such ideas were actually borrowed from these systems in their finished state, or whether they were originally common property which in later times only had restricted to one or the other of the six systems of 2l6 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. philosophy. In the Pa 7/cadasi, for instance, we meet with the idea of Prakriti, nature, which we are accustomed to consider as the peculiar property of the Samkhya-system. This Prakriti is said there to be the reflection, or, as we should say, the shadow of Brahman, and to be possessed of the three Gu?ias or elements of goodness, passion, and darkness, or, as they are sometimes explained, of good, indifferent, and bad. This theory of the three Gunas, how- ever, is altogether absent from the original Vedanta ; t at least, it is not to be met with in the purely Vedantic Upanishadfc, occurring for the first time in the $vetasvatara Upanishad. Again in the later Vedanta works Avidya and Maya are used synonymously, or, if distinguished from one another, they are supposed to arise respectively from the more or less pure character of their substance 1 . The omniscient, but personal Isvara is there explained as a reflection of Maya, but as having subdued her, while the individual soul, Pr%/7a or (?iva, is represented as having been subdued by Avidya, and to be multiform, owing to the variety of Avidya. The individual soul, being endowed with a causal or subtle body, believes that body to be its own, and hence error and suffering in all their variety. As to the development of the world, we are toM that it was by the command of tsvara that Prak?^ti, when dominated by darkness, produced the elements of ether, air, fire, water and earth, all meant to be enjoyed, that is, to be experienced by the individual souls. In all this we c<;n hardly be mistakeh if we recognise the influence of S&mkhya ideas, obscuring and vitiating the monism of the Vedanta, pure and simple. In that philosophy there is no room for a Second, or for a Prakriti, nor for the three Gurtas, nor for anything real by the side of Brahumn. Hrw that influence wa exercised we cannot discover, and it is possible that in ujicient times already there existed this iuiluenee of one philosophical system upon the other, for we set; ev^n in some of the Upaniehads a certain 1 I translate Suttva hero by substnce>f** the context hardly allows that wo should take it for the Guna of goodness LATER VEDANTA MIXED WITH SAlfXHYA. 21 7 mixture of what we should afterwards have to call the distinctive teaching* of Vedanta, Samkhya, or Yoga- philo- sophy. We must remember that in India the idea of private property in any philosophic truth did hardly exist. The individual, as we saw before, was of little consequence, and could never exercise the same influence which such thinkers as Socrates or Plato exercised in Greece. If the descriptions of Indian life emanating from the Indians themselves, and from other nations they came in contact with, whether Greek conquerors or Chinese pilgrims, can be trusted, we may well understand that truth, or what was taken to be truth, was treated not as private, but as common property. It' there was an exchange of ideas among the Indian seekers after truth, it was far more in the nature of co-operation towards a common end, than in the assertion of any claims of originality or priority by individual teachers. That one man should write and publish his philosophical views in a book, and that another should read and criticise that book or carry on the work where 1 it had been left, was never thought of in India in ancient times. If A. referred to B. often, as they say, from mere civility, Pujartham, B. would refer to A., but no one would ever say, as so often happens with us, that he had anticipated the discovery of another, or that some one else had stolen his ideas. Truth was not an article that, accord- ing to Hindu ideas, could ever be stolen. All that could happen and did happen was that certain opinions which had been discussed, sifted, and generally received in one Asrama, hermitage, Arama, garden, or Parishad, religious settlement, would in time be collected by its members and reduced to a more or less systematic form. What that form was in early times we may see from the Brahrnafias, and more particularly from the Upanishuds, i.e. Seances, gatherings of pupils round their teachers, or later on from the Sutras. It cannot be doubted that these Sutras pre- suppose, by their systematic form, a long continued in- tellectual labour; nay it seems to me difficult to account for their peculiar literary form except on the ground that they were meant to be learnt by heart and to be accom- panied from the very beginning by 9 running commentary. 2l8 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. without which they would have been perfectly unintel- ligible. I suggested once before that this very peculiar style of the Sutras would receive the best historical expla- nation, if it could be proved that they represent the tirst attempts at writing for literary purposes in India. What- ever the exact date may be of the introduction of a &inis- trorsum and dextroraum alphabet for epigraphie purposes in India (and in .spite of all efforts not a single inscription has as yet been discovered that can be referred with cer- tainty to the period before Asoka, third century B.C.), every classical scholar knows that there always is a long interval between an epigraphic and a literary employment of the alphabet. People forget that a period marked by 'written literary compositions requires a public, and a large public, which is able to read, for where there is no demand there is no supply. IS 1 or must we forget that the old .system of a mnemonic literature, the Paramparii, was invested with a. kind of sacred character, and would not have been easily surrendered. The old mnemonic system was upheld by a strict discipline which formed the principal part of the established system of education in India, as has been fully described in the PrMieakhyas. They explain to us by what process, whatever existed at thai time of literature, cliieiiy sacred, was firmly imprinted on the mewicry of the young. These young pupils were in fact the books, the scribes were the Gurus, the tablet Was the brain* We can hardly imagine such a state of literature, and the transition from it to a written literature must have marked a new start in the intellectual life of the people at large, or at least of the educated classes. Anybody who has come in contact with the Pandits of India has been able to observe the wonderful feats that can be achieved by that mnemonic discipline even at present, though it is dying out before our wyptf al the approach of printed books, nay of printed editions of their own sacred texts. I need hardly say that even if Biihler's idea of the introduction of a Semitic alphabet into India by neans of commercial travellers about 800 or 1000 B.C. wore more than a hypothesis, it would not prove the existence of a written literature at that time. The adaptation of a Semitic alphabet to the RELATIVE AGE OF PHILOSOPHIES AND SUTliAS. 2 19 phonetic system as elaborated in the Prati*akhyas may date from the third, possibly from the fourth century u.c., but the use of that alphabet for inscriptions begins in the middle of the third century only; and though we cannot deny the possibility of its having been ustd for literary purposes at the same time, such possibilities would form very dangerous landmarks in the chronology of Indian literature. But whatever the origin of the peculiar Sutra-literature may have been and I give my hypothesis as a hypothesis only all scholars will probably agree that these Sutras could not be the work oi : one individual philosopher, but that we have in them the last outcome of previous centuries of thought, and the final result of the labours of numerous thinkers whose name** are forgotten and will never be, recovered. Relative Age of Philosophies and If we keep this in mind, we shall ECO that the question whetlier any of the texts of the six philosophies which we now possess should be considered as older than any other, is really a question impossible to answer. The tests for settling the relative ages of literary works, applicable to European literature, are not applicable to Indian literature. Thus, if one Greek author quotes another, we feel justified in taking the one who is quoted as the predecessor or contemporary of the one who quoees. But because (rainuni quotes BMarayana and Btularayawa traimini, and because their systems show an acquaintance with the other five systems of philosophy, we have no right to arrange them in chronological succession. Karmda, who is acquainted with Kapihi, is clearly criticised by Kapila, at least in our Kupi la-Sutras. Kapiki, to whom the Sitmkhya-Sutras are ascribed, actaally adopts one of Badavay aria's Sutras, IV, s, i, and inserts it tut Idem verb is in his own work, IV, 3. He does the same for the Yoga- Sutras I, 5 and II, 46, which occur in II, 33, III, 34, and VI, 24 in the Samkhya-Sutrus which wo possess, . Kanada was clearly acquainted with Goiama, while Gotama attacks in turn certain doctrines of KapJ;= : Badar&yami. It 22O INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. has been supposed, because Pata7 t gali ignores all other systems, that therefore he was anterior to all of them l . But all such conclusions, which would be perfectly legiti- mate in Greek and Latin literature, have no weight what- ever in the literary history of India, because during its mnemonic period anything could be added and anything left out, before each system reached the form in which we possess it. Age of Kapila- Sutras. The Sutras of Kapila, which have come down to us, are so little the work of the founder of that system, that it would be far safer to treat them as the last arrangement of doctrines accumulated in one philosophical school during centuries of Parampara or tradition. It is easy to see that the, Yoga-philosophy presupposes a Samkhya-philosophy, but while Pata;7vatara Up. VI, 13 and in several of the minor Upanidiads. It should be observed that Vedanta also occurs for the first time in the Maine SVet&tfVatara VI, 22, and afterwards in the smaller Upanishads. All such indications may become valuable hereafter for chronological purposes. In the 1 Rajondralal Mitra, I.e., p. xviii. AGE OF KAPILA-SUTRAS. 221 Bhagavad-gita II, 39 we meet with the Samkhya as the name of a system of philosophy and likewise as a name of its adherents, V, 5. As to our Samkhya-Sutras their antiquity was first shaken by Dr. FitzEdward Hall. Va/caspati Misra, the author of the Samkhya-tattva-Kaumudi, who, according to Professor Garbe, can be safely referred to about 1 150 A. D., quotes not a single Sutra from our Samkhya-Sutras, but appeals to older authorities only, such as Pa>~fca.sikha, Var- shaganya, and the Rar/avartika. Even Madhava about 13^0 A.D., who evidently knew the Sutras of the other systems, never quotes from our Samkhya-Sutras ; and why not, if they had been in existence in his time ? But we must not go too far. It by no means follows that every one of the Sutras which we possess in the body of the Samkhya-Sutras, and the composition of which is assigned by Balasastrin to so late a period as the sixteenth century, is of that modern date. He declares that they were all composed by the well-known Vigwana-Bhikshu who, a*s was then the fashion, wrote also a commentary on them. It is quite possible that our Sa?/ikhya-Sutras may only be what we should call the latest recension of the old Sutras. We know that in India the oral tradition of certain texts, as, for instance, the Sfttras of Pa/mni, was interrupted for a time and then restored again, whether from scattered MSS., or from the recollection of less forget- ful or forgotten individuals. If that was the case, as we know, with so voluminous a work as the MahabMshya; why should not certain portions of the Samkhya-Sutras have been preserved here and there, and have been added to or remodelled from time to time, till they me"et us at last in their final form, at so late a date as the fourteenth or even the sixteenth century ? It was no doubt a great shock to those who stood up for the great antiquity of Indian philosophy, to have to confess that a work for which a most remote date had always been claimed, may not be older than the time of Des Cartes, at least in that final literary form in which it has reached us. But if we con- sider the circumstances of the case, it is more than possible that our Sfttras of the Samkhya-philosophy contain some 222 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. of the most ancient as well as the most modern Sfttras, the utterances of Kapila, Asuri, Pav/raakha and Varslia- gawya, as well as those of Isvara-Krishna and even of Vio, Siimkhya uinl Yoga, p. 7. 3 SH' Mayor's Chinese Reader's Manual, which gives the ex.ict dates. DATS OF GATLDAPADA, 223 But though we are thus enabled to assign the Samkhya- karika to the sixth century A.D., it by no means follows that this work itself did not exist before that time. Na- tive tradition, we are told, assigns his work to the first century B.C. Pate of But even here new difficulties arise with regard to the age of GawZapada, the author of the commentary on the Karikas. This commentary also, so we were informed by Beal, had been translated into Chinese before 582 A. D. ; but how is that possible without upsetting the little we know of GaucZapada's date, tfamkara is represented as the pupil of Govihda who was the pupil of Gaurfapada. But jS'awkara's literary career began, as is generally supposed, about 788 A.B. How then could he have been the literary grandson of Ganrfapada, and son or pupil of Goviuda ? As Mr. Beal could no longer be consulted I asked one of my Chinese pupils, .the late Mr. Kasa- wara,*to translate portions of the Chinese commentary for me ; but the specimens he sent me did not suffice to settle the question whether it was really a translation of Gaurfa- pada's commentary. It is but right to state here that Telang in the Indian Antiquary, XIII, 95, places Sawkara much earlier, in 590 A.D., and that Fleet, in the Indian Antiquary, Jan., .1887, assigns 630 to 65.5 as the latest date to King Yrishadeva of Nepal who is said to have received Samkara at his court, and actually to have given the name of $a?;ikaradeva to his son in honour of the philosopher. In order to escape from ail these uncertainties I wrote once more to Japan to another pupil of mine, Dr. Takakusu, and he, after carefully collating the Chinese translation with the Sanskrit commentary of Gaurfapada, informed me that the Chinese translation of the commentary was not, and could not in any sense be called, a translation of Gaua'apada's com- mentary. So much trouble may be caused by one unguarded expression I Anyhow this difficulty is now removed, and /Samkara's date need not be disturbed. The author of the Kfcrikas informs us at the end of his work that this philo- sophy, proclaimed by the greatest sage, i. e. Kapila, had 224 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. been communicated by him to Asuri, by Asuri to Paw&a- sikha, and, as the Tattva-samasa adds, from Pa/7&asikha to Pata/?any Sanskrit scholar deny that the Sutras of BadarayaTia are older than the Samkhya-Sutra^s, as we now possess the two. But for all that, Greek, as a language, cannot be a day older than Latin. Both branched off, slowly it may be and almost imperceptibly at firso, from the time when the Aryan separation took place. In their embryonic form they both go back to some indefinite date, far beyond the limits of any chronology. In India we may learn how, like language, religion, and rnytliOAOgy, philosophy also formed at first a kind of common property. We meet with philosophical ideas of a Vedantic character, though as yet in a very undecided form, as far back as the hymns of the Kig-veda ; ihey meet us again in the Brahmawas and in some of the Upanishads, while the Samkhya ideas stand out less prominently, owing, it would seem, to the ascendency gained at that early period already by the Vedanta. Instead of supposing, however, that passages in support of Samkhya ideas occurring in certain of the older Upanishads were foisted in at a later time, it seems far more probable to me that they were survivals of an earlier period of as yet undifferentiated philosophical thought. 236 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Buddhism subsequent to Upanishads. What remains of the chronological framework of Indian philosophy is in the end not much more than that both Vedanta and Samkhya ideas existed before the rise of historical Buddhism. The very name of Upanishad, for instance, as so peculiar that its occurrence in ancient Bud- dhist texts proves once for all the existence of some of these works before the rise of Buddhism. The recognition of mendicant friars also, as a social insti- tution, seems to me simply taken over from the Brahmans. The very name of Bhikkhu, applied to the members of the Buddhist fraternity, comes from the same source. It is true, no doubt, that the name of Bhikshu does not occur in the classical Upanishads, but the right of begging, whether in the first or the third of the Asramas (Brahmafcarin or Vanaprastha), is fully recognised, only that the third and fourth Asramas are not so clearly distinguished in early times as they are in Manu and afterwards. In the Kaush. Up. II, 2 we read of a man who has begged through a vil- lage and got nothing (Bhikshitva) ; in the Kh&ud. tip. IV, 3, 5, a Brahmafcarin is mentioned who has begged. The technical term for this begging is Bhiksh&fcarya in the Brih. Ar. Up. Ill (V), 5, i, and exactly the same compound, BhikkhaMrya, occurs in the Dhammapada 392 ; BhaiksM- Mrya occurs also in the MuTidaka I, z, u, so that the fact that the substantive Bhikshu does not occur in the classical Upanishads can hardly be used as an argument to prove that the status of the mendicant friar was not known before the spreading of Buddhism. It is true that in its social meaning Asrama, the name of the three or four stages, does not occur in the classical Upanishads ; but, as we find Asramin in the Maitray. Up. IV, 3, we can hardly doubt that the. three or four stages (Brahma&ari, Gaha^Ao, Vana- "p&tflio, Bhikkhu) were known before the rise of Buddhism, and taken over by the Buddhists from the Vedic Brahmans. Socially, the only Asramas that remained among the Bud- dhists were two, that of the Gn'hins and that of the Bhikkhus. That many of the technical terms of the Buddhists (Uposhadha, &c.) could have come from the same source ASVAGHOSHAS BUDDHA-A'AEITA. 237 only, has long been known, so much so that it has been rightly said, Without Br&hmanism no Buddhism. The institution of the Vasso *, for instance, the retreat during the rainy season, is clearly taken over from the Varshas, the rainy season, as kept by the Br&hmans, and so is the quinquennial celebration of the Pa/J/cavarsha-pari- shad, and many other customs adopted by the Buddhists. Lalita-vlstara. I have explained before why at present I attribute less importance than I did formerly to the occurrence of a number of titles, including S&mkhya, Yoga, Vaiseshika, and possibly Nyaya, in the Lalita-vistara. If the date assigned by Stanislas Julien and others to certain Chinese translations of this work could be re-established, the passage so often quoted from the twelfth chapter would be of con- siderable value to us in forming an idea of Indian literature as it existed at the time when the Lalita-vistara was orig- inally composed. We find here the names not only of the Vedic glossary (NighaTitfu ?) the Nigamas (part of Nirukta), Puratias, Itihasas, Vedas, grammar, Nirukta, /SiksM, jfiTAan- das, ritual (Kalpa), astronomy (6?yotisha), but, what would be most important for us, the names of three systems of philosophy also, Samkhya, Yoga, and Vaiseshika, while Hetuvidyzt can hardly be meant for anything but; Ny&ya. But until the dates of the various Chinese translations of the Life of Buddha have been re-examined, we must abstain from using them for assigning any dates to their Sanskrit originals. Asvag hosha' a Buddha-arita. We may perhaps place more reliance on Asvaghosha's Buddha-fcarita, which, with gre&t probability, has been ascribed to the first century A. D. He mentions Vyasa, the son of Sarasvati, as the compiler of the Veda, though not of the Vedanta^Sfttras ; he knows Valmiki, the author of the Ram&yaTia, Atreya as a teacher of medicine, and Ganaka, the well-known king, as a teacher of Yoga. By far the most important passage in it for our present purpose is the conversation between Arada and the future Buddha, here 1 S.B.E., vol. viii, p. 213. 338 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. already called Bodhisattva in the twelfth book. This Arada'is clearly a teacher of Samkhya-philosophy, it may be of Samkhya in an earlier state ; and, though the name of Samkhya does not occur, the name of' .Kapila does (XII, 31), and even a disciple of his is mentioned. Here then we have in a poem, ascribed to the first century A. D., a clear reference to that philosophical system whiah is known to us under the name of S&mkhya, and we have actually the name of Kapila, the reputed author of that system.- The name of Kapila- vastu l also occurs, as the birthplace of Buddha and as the dwelling of the famous sage Kapila. No reference to the Vedaiita has been met with in Asva- ghosha's Buddha-Aiarita, though the substitution of the Vedantic name of Brahman for the S&mkhya name of Purusha deserves attention. Buddhist Suttas. If we consult the Buddhist Suttas, which, whatever the date of their original composition rnay have been, were at all events reduced to writing in the first century B.C., and may be safely used therefore as historical evidence for that time, we find there also views ascribed to the Brahmans of Buddha's time which clearly breathe the spirit of the Samkhya-philosophy. But it would be very unsafe to say more, and to maintain that such passages prove in any way the existence of fully developed systems of philosophy, or of anything very different from what we find already in certain Upanishads. All we* can say is that there are a number of terms in the Suttas which are the very terms used in the Vedanta, S&mkhya and Yoga-philosophies, such as Atman, /S&svata, Nitya (? Anitya), Akshobhya, Brahman, t^vara, Dhanna, PariTtftma, and many more ; but, so far as I know, there is not one of which we could say that it could have been taken from the Sutras only, and from nowhere else. We should remember that in the Buddhist Canon we find constant mention of Titthiyas or Tirthakas and their here- 1 I write V&stu, because that alone means dwelling-place, while Vastu moans thing. Vastu became Vatthu in Pali, and was then probably retranslated into Sanskrit as Vastu. AVALAYANA S G/?/HYA-SUTKAS. 239 il systems of philosophy. Six contemporaries of Buddha mentioned, one of them, NigaTitAo Nataputta, being the tical are well-known founder of (rainism, Parana Kassapa, Makkhali, Agita, Pakudha and Sar7^aya l . Nor are the names of the reputed authors of the six systems of Brahmanic-philosophy absent from the Tripifaka. But we hear nothing of any literary compositions ascribed to Badarayana, Craimini, Kapila, Pata/?#ali, Gotama or Ka^ada. Some of these names occur in the Buddhist Sanskrit texts also, such as the Lankavatara where the names of KaTiada, Kapila, Akshapada, Brihaspati are met with, but again not a single specimen or extract from their compositions. Asvalayana's Grthya-Sfttras. Another help for determining the existence of ancient Sutras and Bhashyas may be found in the Grihya-Sutras of Asvalayana and $amkhayana, works belonging to the age of Vedic literature, though it may be to the very end of what I call the Sutra-period. Here, as I pointed out in 1859 in my History of Ancient Sanskrit Literature, we find not only the Rig-veda with all its subdivisions, but such names as Sumantu, (raimini, Vaisampayana, Paila, Sutras, Bhashyas, Bharata 2 , Mahabharata, teachers of the law, (rananti, Bahavi, Gargya, Gautama, A^akalya, Babhravya, MartcZavya, MaraZiikeya, Gargi Vafcaknavi, Vadava Prati- theyi, Sulabha Maitreyi, Kahola Kaushitaka, Mahakaushi- taka, Paimgya, Mahapaimgya, Suy&gns, >Samkhayana, Aitareya, Mahaitareya, the Sakala (text), the Bashkala (text), Su^atavaktra, Audavahi, Mahaudavahi, Sau(/ami, 6'aunaka, Asvalayana. The /Samkhayana Grihya-Sutras IV, 10, give the same list, though leaving out a few names and adding others. The most valuable part in both sets of Grihya-Sutras is their testifying at that early and probably pre-Buddhistic time, not only to the existence of Sutras, but of Bhashyas or commentaries also, without which, as I said before, neither the philosophical, nor the 1 SamatfHa-Phala-Sutta 3. 2 How careful we must be, we may learn from the fact that instead of Bharata and Mahabharata, other MSS. read Bharatadharma/caryas ; while in the Samkhayana Gnhya-Sutras IV, 10, 4, Bharata, MahAbharata and Dharmafcaryas are loft out altogether. 240 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. grammatical, nor any other Sfttras would ever have been intelligible, or even possible. Did Buddha borrow from Kapila? I may seem very sceptical in all this, but I cannot even now bring myself to believe that the author of Buddhism' borrowed from the Samkhya or any other definite system of philosophy, as known to us in its final Sutra form, in the sense which we ourselves assign to borrowing. Buddha, it seems to mfe, had as much right to many of the so-called Sa7ftkhya or Vedanta ideas as Kapila or anybody else. Who would say, for instance, that his belief in Samsara or migration of souls was borrowed from Badaraya??a or Kapila ? It belonged to everybody in lrd ja as much as a belief in Karman or the continuous working of deeds. In the great dearth of historical dates it may no doubt be excusable, if we lay hold of anything to save us from drowning while exploring the chronology of Indian litera- ture. Our difficulties are very great, for even When the names of the principal systems of philosophy and the names of their reputed authors are mentioned, how do we know that they refer to anything written that we possess ? Unless we meet with verbatim quotations, we can never know whether a certain book of a certain author is in- tended, or simply the general Parampara, that is, the tradi- tion, as handed down in various Asramas, two things Which should be carefully distinguished. It is strange to see how often our hopes have been roused and disappointed. We were told that in Professor Hardy's most valuable edition l of the Anguttara a number of philosophical sects, were mentioned which existed at the time of Buddha's appearance, such as (i) Agrlvakas, (2) NigaTitf/tas, (3) Mundasavakas, (4) 6?ailakas, (5) Paribba- gfakas, (6) MagaraKkas, (7) Teda?ic?ikas, (8) Aviruddhakas, (9) Gotamakas, and (10) Devadhammikas. But not one of these names helps us to a real chronological date. Agivakas and NigaTi^Aas are the names of ffaina ascetics, the latter belonging to the Digambara sects, which could hardly have been established long before Buddha's appearance, while 1 The Pali Text Society, vol. iii, p. 276. BANAS HAUSHAATAKITA. 241 MuTicJaaavakas, i.e. pupils of the shaveling, the Buddha, and Gotamakas would seem to be schools which owed their existence to Buddha himself. The other names ascetics, Paribb%aKas, religious mendicants, i.e, Samnyasins carrying the three staves, would be appli- cable both to Brahmanic and Buddhist sects. Magamftkas. if meant for Magadhikas, people of Hagadha, would be Buddhists again. Aviruddhakas, a name not clear to me, may have been intended for ascetics no longer impeded by any desires, while Devadbamrnikas are clearly worshippers of the ancient national Devas, and therefore Br&hinanic, and possibly Vedic. We get no historical dates from the names of any of these schools, if schools they were. All tj^ey teach is that at tLe time Brahmanic and Buddhist sects were existing side by side in large numbers, but by no means, as is commonly supposed, in constant conflict with each other l . * Of the six recognised systems of philo- sophy, of their eponymous heroes or their written works, we do not hear a single word. Bana's Harshaarlta. Not even in later works, which have been referred to the sixth, seventh, and eighth centuries A.D., do we meet with actual quotations from our S&tras of the six Dar*anas. Bana, in his Life of King Harsha, knows indeed of Aupam- shadas, Kapilas, K&nadas; and if the Kapilas are the followers of the Sa/mkhya, Kanadas the followers of the V^aiseshika school, the Aupanishadas can hardly be meant for anybody but the Vedimtins. Varaha-Mihira also, in the sixth century A.D.. mentions Kapila and Kanabhufl (Vaiseshika), but even this does not help us to the dates of any Sfttras composed by them. The Chinese translator of the K&rikas, likewise in the sixth century, informs us that these Karikas contain the words of Kapi)a or of Pa/7fcasikha, the pupil of Asuri, who was the pupil of Kapila. We are told even tha,t there were originally 60,000 Gathas, and all that lavara- Krishna did 1 Cf. Rhys Davids, J. R A. S., J.m., 1898, p. 197. 16 * INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. was to select seventy of them for his seventy or seventy- two KPirikas. That Madhava (7350 A.D.), while mentioning the Sutras of the other systems, should not have mentioned those of the Samkhya, is no doubt, as I pointed out before, a strong argument in support of their non-existence in his time. But it is no proof, as little as we may conclude from the fact that Eiouen-thsang translated the Vaiseshika-nik&ya- dasapadartha-sastra by (r/tanafcmdra, and riot the Vaise- shika-Sutras by Ka^ada, that therefore these Sutras did not exist in his time. We cannot be too careful in such matters, for the unreserved acceptance of a purely conjectural date is very apt to interfere with the discovery of a real date. Hiouen-thsang likewise mentions a number of Nyaya works, but not Gotama's Nyaya-Sfttras, Does that prove that Gctt&ma's Sutras were unknown in the seventh century ? It< ..may or may not. Pie relates that Guwamati defeated a famous Samkhya philosopher of the name of Madhava, but again lie tells us 110 more. His own special study, as is well known, was the Yoga-philosophy. And here again, though h& speaks of a number of Yoga works, he says not a word of the most important of them all, the Siltras of Pata%ali l . Yet I doubt whether we may conclude from this that these Sutras did not exist at his time. The If then I venture to call the Tattva-samasa the oldest record that has reached us of the Samkhya-philosophy, and if I prefer to follow them in the account I give of that philosophy, I am quite aware that many scholars will object, and will prefer the description of the Samkhya as given in the KarJkas and in the Sutras. Both of them, particularly the Karikas, give us certainly better arranged accounts of that philosophy, as may be seen in the excellent editions and translations which we owe to Professor Garbe, and 1 may now odd to Satish Chandra Banerji, 1898. If, as J believe, the Tattva-samasa-Sutras are older than our Sti9/?anasantati, continuity of thought, Smriti, memory, and Dhi, meditation. It is quite clear that in all these explanations Buddhi is taken as intellect, and as personal intellect, and that the idea of a cosmic stage of intellectuality has been entirely forgotten. Thus only can we account for the statement that this Buddhi, if dominated by Sattva (Gu^a of purity), is said to assume the form (Rupa) of virtue, knowledge, dispassionateness, arid superhuman powers, while, if domi- nated by Tamas (Guna of darkness), it takes the four opposite forms of vice, &c. How could this be possible beforfe the distinction between subject and object has been realised by Ahamkara, and before Buddhi has assumed 1 These Alsvarytvs are believed in by Symkhya and Yoga, and are acquired by Yogins by moans of long and painful practices. a This also seems out of place here, unless the Sawkhyas give their own meaning both to Brahman and Brahma. In later times Buddhi, taken collectively, becomes the Upadhi or mental limitation of Brahma or Hiranyagarbha. AHAJfKARA, 249 the character of sense-perception (Buddhindriyani) ? We have, in fact, to read the Samkhya-philosophy in two texts, one, as- it were, in the old uncial writing that shows forth here and there, giving the cosmic process, the other in the minuscule letters of a much later age, interpreted in a psychological or epistemological sense. Ahamkara. 3. Now, he asks, What is called Ahamkara? And he answers, ' It is Abhimana, assumption or misconception, and this consists in the belief that I am in the sound, i. e. I hear, I feel, I see, I taste, and I smell, I am lord and rich, I am Lsvara, I enjoy, I am devoted to virtue, by me a man was slain, I shall be slain by powerful enemies, &c.' $amkara in his commentary on the Vedanta-Sfttras gives, though from a different point of view, some more instances, as when a man, because his wife and children are unhappy, imagines that he is unhappy, or that he is stout, thin, or fair, that he stands, walks, or jumps, that he is dumb, impotent, deaf, blind, that he has desires, doubts, or fears, whereas all these things do not pertain to him at all, but to Prakriti only. ' Synonyms of Ahamk&ra, or rather modifications of it, arer Vaikarika, modifying, Tairyasa, luminous, Bhtitadi, the first of elements, Sanumana, dependent on inference, Niranumana, not dependent on inference/ Here we must distinguish again between Ahamkara, as a cosmic power, and Ahamkara as a condition presupposed in any mental act of an individual thinker. Ahamkara was so familiar in the sense of Egoism that, like Buddhi, it was taken in its ordinary rather than in its technical Samkhya sense. I quite admit that this is a somewhat bold proceeding, but how to get without it at a proper understanding of the ancient Samkhya, the rival of the Vedanta, I cannot see. We must remember that Ahamkara, whatever it may mean in later times, is in the Samkhya something developed out of primordial matter, after that matter has passed through Buddhi. Buddhi cannot really act without a distinction of the universe into subject and object, without the introduction of the Ego or I, which 25 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. again is impossible without a Non-Ego, or something objective. After that only do we watch the development of what is objective in general into what is objectively this or that (the Tanmatras). But while the creation of what is subjective and objective is the only possible meaning of the cosmic Ahamkara, its psychological interpretation is far more easy. Thus we are told that there are three or four modifications of the Ahamkara, (i) the Vaikarika, dominated by the Sattva-gu^a, helps to do good works; (2) the Taigrasa, dominated by the Ra^asgiwa, helps to do evil works ; (3) the Bhutadi, dominated by the Tamas-givna, helps to do hidden works ; (4) the Sanumana Ahamkara Is responsible for unintentional good; (5) the Niranumana, for unintentional evil works. This (^vision, though rather confused, shows at all events that the Ahamkara is here treated as simply a moral agent, dominated by the Gwias, but no longer as a cosmic potentia. These five modes of Ahamkara are spoken of as Karma tma-ns also, i.e.* the very essence of our acts, while in another place the Tattva- samasa itself explains that Ahamkara should be taen as an act of Buddhi directed towards the perception of the nature of what is Self (subjective) or Not-Self (objective). Though Ahamkara means only the production of Ego, yet the production of Ego involves that of the Non-Ego, and thus divides the whole world into what is subjective and objective. Five Tanm&tras. 4-8. If it is asked, What are the five Tanmatras (sub- stances)'? he answers, The five substances or essences as emanating from Aha?7*,k&ra, the essence of s- >und, contact, colour, savour, and odour. The essences of sound are perceived in sounds only. Differences of sound, such as acute, grave, circumflexed, and the notes of the gamut, such as Shacfy/a, C, .Rishabha, D, Gandhara, E, Madhyama, F, Paft&ama, G, Dhaivata, A, Nishada, B, are perceived ; but there is no difference in the essence of sound. The essences of touch are perceived in touch only. Dif- ferences of touch, such as soft, hard, rough, slippery, cold, FIVE BUDDHINDRIYAS. 2$ I and hot, are perceived, but there is no difference in the essence- of touch. The essences of colour are perceived in colour only. Differences of colour, such as white, red, black, green, yel- low, purple, are perceived, but there is no difference in the essence of colour. The essences of savour are perceived in savour only. Differences of savour, such as pungent, bitter, astringentj corrosive, sweet, acid, salt, are perceived, but there is no difference in the essence of savour. The essences of odour are perceived in odour only. Differences of odour, such as sweet and offensive, are per- ceived, but there is no difference in the essence of odour. Thus have the essences been indicated ; and their syn- onyms, though sometimes very inaccurate ones, are said to be : Ayisesha, not differentiated, and therefore not percep- tible, Mahabhutas ('?), the great elements ; Prakritis, natures, Abhogya, not to be experienced, A??/u, atomic, Asanta, not- pleasurable, Aghora, not-terrible, Amiictea, not-stupid ; the last three being regations of the qualities of the Maha- bhutas, according to the three Gunas preponderating in each. And if it is asked why these eight Prakritis only, from A vyakta to the Tanniatras, are called Prakritis, the answer ib because they alone Prakurvanti, they alone bring forth, or evolve. Sixteen VikAras. II. If it be asked ' Which are the sixteen Vikaras or evolutions ? ' the answer is, ' the eleven sense organs (in- cluding Manas), &nd the five elements.' BuAdfc&ndriyas. 9-13. ' Now the organs are set forth; the ear, the skin, the eyes, the tongue, and the nose, constitute the five Buddhindriyab, or perceptive organs. The ear perceives as its object sound, the skin touch, the eye colour, the tongue savour, the nose odour/ Being produced from the Tanmatras, the senses, as per- ceiving, are represented as being of the same nature as the objects perceived, a view of considerable antiquity. 252 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Five Karmendriyas, 14-18. 'The five Karmendriyas or organs of action, voice, hands, feet, the organ of excretion, and the organ of generation, perform each its own work. The voice utters words, the hands work, the feet perform movement, the organ of excretion evacuation, the organ of generation pleasure/ Manas. 19. 'Manas, mind, both perceptive and active, performs its acts of doubting and ascertaining/ Central organ of the senses or KOLVOV alcrBriTijpLo^ might be the nearest approach to the meaning of Manas ; but mind may do, if we only remember its Samkhya definition, as perceptive, like the other organs, and at tho same time active like the Karmendriyas. ' Thus have the eleven organs been explained. Their synonyms are Karawa, instruments, Vaikarika, 'changing, Niyata, special, Padani, appliances 1 , Avadhritani, kept under (?), Anu, atomic, Aksha 2 , organ/ Five Mafcabhutaa, 20-24. 'The Mahabhutas, or gross elements, are earth, water, light, air, and ether/ Here the earth, we are told, helps the other four, by being their support. Water helps the other four by moist- ening. Light helps the other four by ripening. Air helps the other four by drying. Ether helps the other four by giving space. * Earth is possessed of five qualities, sound, touch, colour, savour, and odour. Water is possessed of four qualities, sound, touch, colour, and savour. Light is possessed of three qualities, sound, touch, and colour. Air is possessed of two qualities, sound and touch. Ether has one quality, sound. Thus are the five Mahabhutas explained. Their synonyms . are : Bhfttas, elements, A Bhuta-viseslias ; special elements, Vikaras, modifications, Akritfc, species, Tanu, skin (or body ?), Vigraha, shapes, /S'arita, pleasurable, 1 Garbe Sawkhya- Philosophic, p. 257. 3 Or Akshara, imperishable ? PUBUSHA. 253 Ghora, fearful, MM&a, stupid. Thus have the sixteen Vikaras been described/ Purasha. III. 25. Now it is asked, 'What is the Purusha?' and the answer is, * Purusha is without beginning, it is subtle, omnipresent, perceptive, without qualities, eternal, seer, experiencer, not an agent, knower of objects, spotless, not producing. Why is it called Purusha ? Because of its being old (Puranat), because it rests in the body (Puri sayate), and because it serves as Purohita (Director)/ These are, of course, fanciful etymologies; and we can hardly doubt that we have, in the name of Purusha, a recol- lection of the Vedic Purusha, one of the many names of the supreme deity, by the side of Visvakarman, Hirariyagarbha, Prair/apati, &c. Like Brahman when conceived as Atman, Purusha also was probably used both for the divine and for the human side of the same power. It is the multi- plicity only of the Purusha which is peculiar to the Sam- khya-philosophy. 1 And why is the Purusha without beginning 1 ? Because there is no beginning, no middle, and no end of it/ This is not a very satisfactory answer, but it is probably meant for no more than that we never perceive a beginning, middle, or end of it. Why is it subtle ? Because it is without parts and supersensuous. Why omnipresent ? Be- cause, like the sky, it reaches everything, and its extent is endless. Why perceptive ? Because it perceives (that is, for a time) pleasure, pain, and trouble. Why without qualities ? Because the qualities of good, indifferent, and bad are not found in it. Why eternal ? Because it wrs not made, and cannot be made. Why seer ? Because perceives the modifications of Prakriti. Why enjoy er ? Because being perceptive it perceives (for awhile) pleasure and pain. Why not an agent ? Because it is indifferent and without the qualities (Gmias). W T hy tho Knower of body or of objects ? Because it knows the qualities of objective bodies. Why spotless ? Because neither good nor evil acts belong to the Purusha. Why riot producing ? Be- cause it has no seed, that is, it can produce no-thing. Thus has the Purusha of .the Samkhya been described 254 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. The synonyms of Purusha are, Atman, Self, Puman, male, Puragu?ia#antugiva/i, a male living creature, Kshetra#wa, knower of objects or of the body, Nara, man, Kavi, poet, Brahman, Akshara, indestructible, Prawa, spirit, YaAka/t *, anybody, Sat, He. Thus h#ve the twenty-five substances been described, viz. the eight Prakritis, the sixteen Vikaras, and the Purusha. He who knows these twenty-five substances, whatever stage of life he may be in, and whether he wear matted hair, a topknot, or be shaven, he is liberated, there is no doubt. This verse is often quoted by Samkhya philo- sophers. Here, it seems, the first part of the Tattva-samasa is ended, containing a list of the twenty-five Tattvas, in the three divisions of Prakritis, Vikaras, and Purusha. Purusha (subject). I. Prakrit! (object). Avyakta (chaos). a. Mahat or Buddhi (light and intelligence as Samaahfi, not yet | individualised). 3. Ahawkara (subjectivation). 5 Tanmatras (Sattvika) 10 Indriyas, organs (Ragasa) + i Manas (mind) (subtle elements). (5 Buddhindriyas, 5 Karmendriyas, and Manas). Tanmatras. Buddhindriyas. Karmendriyas. 1. Sound, 5abda. I. Srotra, hearing i. Speaking in tongue in ear. 2. Touch, Sparra. 2. Tvafc, touch in 2. Grasping in hands. skin. 3. Colour, Kupa. 3. ATakshus, seeing 3. Moving in fest in eye. t 4. Savour, Rasa. 4. Cihva, tasting 4. Evacuating in Payu. in tongue. 5. Odour, Gandha. 5. Ghrana, smell- 5. Generating in Upastha. ing m nose. 5 Mahabhutas (Tamasa). 1. Aku-sa, ether (*abda). 2. VAyu, air (sabda *- sparsa). 3. Tejyas, fire (sabda + spai-sa + rftpa), 4. Ay>, water (sabda + sparsa + riipa f rasa), 5. J-Vtthivi, earth (sabda + sparsa + rupu. -r rasa -h gandha). 1 As ya/i, the relative pronoun could hardly be used as a name, I supposed it might bo meant fcr th indefinite pronoun ya/ikaA, but this is doubtful. THREE GUJVAS. 2.55 Is Pumaha an Agent? Now follow a number of special questions, which seemed to require fuller treatment. The first is, Is the Purusha an agent, or is he not ? If Purusha were an agent, he would do good actions only, and there would not be the three different kinds of action. The three kinds of action are (i) Good conduct, called virtue (Dharma), which consists in kindness, control and restraint (of the organs), freedom from hatred, reflection, displaying of supernatural powers. (a) But passion, anger, greed, fault-finding, violence, discontent, rudeness, shown by change of countenance, these are called indifferent conduct. (3) Madness^ intoxication, lassitude, nihilism, devotion to women, drowsiness, sloth, worthlessneL-s, impurity, these are called bad conduct. We see here once more that the three Gmias must have had originally a much wider meaning than is here described. They are here taken as purely moral qualities, whereas originally they must have had a much larger cosmic sense. They we not qualities or mere attributes at all ; they are on the contrary ingredients of Prakr/ti in its differentia- tion of good, indifferent, bad ; bright, dim and dark ; light, mobile, heavy. We see here the same narrowing of cos- rnical ideas which we had to point out before in the case of Buddhi and Ahamkara, and which, it seeing to me, would render the original conception of the Samknya-philosophy quite unmeaning. We must never forget that, even when the Samkhya speaks of moral qualities, these qualities belong to nature as seen by the Furusha, never to Purusha apart from Prakrtti. Three G>*u;as. Whenever this triad is perceived in the world it is clear that agency belongs to the GuTias, and it follows that Purusha is not the agent. Deceived by passion and darkness, and taking o wrong view of these Gutias which belong to Prakr^ti, not to himself, a fool imagine? that he himself is the agent, jbhough in reality he is unable by himself to bend even a straw. Nay. he becomes an agent, as it were, foolish and intoxicated by 256 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. vain imagination and saying, 'All this was made by me and belongs to me/ And then it is said (in the Bhagavad-gita III, 27) : * Acts are effected by the qualities (Gmtas) of Prakriti in every way, but the Self ( Atman), deluded by the conceit of the I (Ahamkara), imagines that the I is the agent/ Ibid. XIII, 31 : ' This imperishable supreme Self, from being without- beginning and devoid of qualities, neither acts nor suffers, even while staying in the body/ And XIII, 29 : ' He sees (aright) who looks upon actions as in all re- spects performed by Prakriti alone, and upon the Self as never an agent/ Zs Pnmsha one or many? Now comes the important question, Is that Purusha one or many ? The answer to this question divides the Sara- khya from the Vedanta-philosophy. The Samkhya answer is that the Purusha is clearly many, because of the variety in the acts of pleasure, pain, trouble, confusion and purify- ing (of race), health, A birth and death : also on account of the stages in life (Asrama) and the difference of caste ( Var,ui). If there were but one Purusha, as the Vedantins hold, then if one were happy, all would be happy ; if* one Wi^re unhappy, all would be unhappy, and so on in the case of people affected by trouble, confusion of race, purity of race, health, birth and death., Hence there is not one Purusha, but many, on account of the manifoldness >r ti- eated by form, birth, abode, fortune, society or loneliness. Thus Kapjfci, Awiia, Pa/f&asi'kha and Pata/77/cara dissolution or re-involution. * Evolution is as follows : From the Avyakta (undeveloped Prakriti) before explained, when superintended by the high and omnipresent Purusha (Spirit), Buddhi (intellect) arises, and this of eight kinds. From this Buddhi, the substance of intellect, arises Ahamkara (conceit of I, or subjectivity). Ahamkara is of three kinds, Vaikarika, modified, that is, modified of Sattva 1 ; Taigrasa, luihinous, as under the influence of Ra#as pro- ducing the Buddhindriyas ; and Bhutadi (first of elements). From the modified or Vaikarika Ahamkara, which under the influence of Tarn as produces the gross material elements, spring the gods and the senses ; from the first of elements. Bhutadi, the Tanmatras (essences) ; from the luminous, Taiiqrasa, both. From the Tanm&tras, essences, are produced the material elements. This is the development or Sahara. Pratisa.i^&ara or dissolution is as follows: The material elements are dissolved into the essences, Tanrnatras, the essences and senses into Ahamkara, Ahamkara into Buddhi (intellect), Buddhi into Avyakta (the undeveloped), all being different forms of Prakriti. The Undeveloped is nowhere dissolved, because it was never evolved out of anything. Know both Prakriti and Purusha as having no beginning. Thus has dissolution been explained. Adfcitolmta, and AdMdaivata. VII-IX. Now it is asked. What is meant by Adhyatma (subjective), AdhiBhuto (objective), and Adhidaivata (per- taining to deity)? To this it is answered, Intellect is subjective, what is to be perceived is objective, Brahma is deity. Ahamkara is subjective, what* is to be received and perceived by it is objective, Rudra is the deity. Marias, mind, is subjective, what is to be conceived is objective, A'andra, moon, is the deity . A The ear is subjective, what is to be hoard is objective, Akasa, ether, is the deity. The skin is subjective, what is to be touched is objective, Vayu, 1 Garbe, Sawkhya-Philosopliie, p. 236, ABHIBUDDHIS. 265 wind, is the deit. The eye is subjective, what is to be seen is objective, Aditya, the sun, is the deity. The tongue is subjective, what is to be tasted is objective, Varuna l is the deity. The nose is subjective, what is to be smelled is objective, Earth is the deity. The voice is subjective, what is to be uttered is objective, Agni, fire, is the deity. The two hands are subjective, what is to be grasped is objective, Indra is the deity. The feet are subjective, what has to be gone over is objective, Vishnu is the deity. The organ of excretion is subjective, what is to be excreted is objective, Mitra is the deity. The organ of generation is subjective, what is to be enjoyed is objective, Pravcrty, though there is hardly a more convenient term to render it by. In the Samkhya-philosophy Prakriti is a postulated something that exists, and that produces everything without being itself produced. When it is called Avyakta, that means that it is, at first, chaotic, undeveloped, and invisible. Development of Prakrtti, Cosmic. In place of this one Prakriti we often read of eight Prakritis, those beginning with Buddhi or the Mahat being distinguished as produced as well as producing, while the first, the Avyakta, is producing only, but not produced. This need not mean more than that ~the seven modifications (Vikaras) and/orms of Prakriti are all effects, and serve again as causes, while the Avyakta itself, the undeveloped Prakriti, has no antecedent cause, but serves as cause only for all the other forms of Prakriti. Retrospect. After going through the long list of topics wliich form the elements of the Samkhya-philosophy, it may be well to try to give a more general view of Kapila's system. 1 For the actual succession in the evolution of Ahnwkara from the Mahat, and of the Mahat from Praknti, &c., the .Sastra alone, we are told, can be our authority, and not inference, because inference can only l*arn. See also Garbe, S&mkhya- Philosophic, p. 26. X 2 308 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. ing to $awkara) is mentioned already in the -KMndogya Upanishad (III, u ; VIII, 15). It is much the same with the other philosophies, and w$ are left in doubt a? to whether the three couples, Samkhya and Yoga, Nyaya and Vaiseshika, nay even Pftrva- and Uttara-Mima?nsa, were amalgamations of systems which had originally an independent existence, or whether they were differentiations of former systems. Samkhya and Yoga might easily have formed one comprehensive system, because their divergence with regard to the existence of an Isvara, or Lord, was not so essential a point to them as it seems to us. Those who wanted an Isvara might have him as a first and super- eminent Purusha ; while those who had gone beyond this want, need not have quarrelled with those who still felt it. The Nyaya and Vaiseshika show clear traces of a common origin ; while the two Miinamsas, which in character are more remote from one another than the other systems, seem to sanction, by their names at least, the suspicion of their former unity. But the deplorable scarcity of any historical documents does not enable us to go beyond mere conjectures ; and though the names of Kapila, Vyasa, and Gotama may seenr to have an older air than those of Pata>7<7ali, Craimini, and Kanada, \ve must not in such matters allow ourselves to be guided by mere impressions. The often-cited passage from the Vedanta- Siitras II, i, 3, Etena Yoga/* pratyuktafc, 'By this the Yoga is refuted/ proves of coiirse no more than the existence of a Yoo-a-philosophy at the time of BadarayaTia ; it cannot be used to prove the existence of the Yoga-Sfttras, such as we pusses them, as previous to the composition of the Vedanta- Sutras. SAtfaninffs of the word Toga. In the Bhagavad-gita Yoga is defined as S'amatva, equa- bility (II, 48 v . It has been repeated again and again that Yoga, I: win Yu#, to join, meant 'originally joining the deity, or union with it. Even native authors occasionally tavour that view. A moment's consideration, however, would have shown that such an idea could never have entered the mind of a Sarokhya, for the simple reason that there was YOGA, NOT UNION, BUT DISUNION, 309 nothing for him that he could have wished to join. Even the Vedantist does not really join Brahman, though this is j, very common misconception; nay, a movement of the soul towards Brahman is distinctly guarded against as impossible. The soul is always Brahman, even though it does not know it, and it only requires the removal of ignorance for the soul to recover its Brahmahood, or to* become what it always has been. Yu<7, from meaning to join, came, by means of a very old metaphor, to mean to join oneself to something, to harness oneself for some work. Thus Yu# assumed the sense of preparing for hard work, whether preparing others or getting ready oneself. 1 And as people with us use the expression to go into harness, i.e. to prepare for work, or to buckle-to, jL e. to get ready for hard work, Yugr, particularly in the Atrnanepada, came to mean to exert oneself. Possibly the German Angespannt and Anspannung may have been suggested by the same metaphor, though the usual explanation is that it was suggested by a metaphor taken from the stretching of the bow. In Sanskrit ^this Yu# is often used with such words as Manas, jfiTittam, Atman, &c., in the sense of concentrating or exerting one's mind ; and it is in this sense only that our word Yoga could have sprung from it, meaning, a*? the Yoga-Sutras tell us at the very beginning, I, 2, the effort of restraining the activities or distractions of our thoughts (Jfitta-v?*itti-nirodha), or the effort of concentrating our thoughts on a definite object. Yoga, not Union, but Disunion. A false interpretation of the term Yoga as union has led to a total misrepresentation of Pata?anayoga) ; by ascetic exercises delivering the Self from the fetters of the body arid the bodily senses, (by Kar ; mayoga) adds Pata/?7anayoga of Kapila. On the contrary, he presup- poses it; he only adds, as a useful support, a number of exercises, bodily as well as mental, by which the senses should be kept in subjection so as not to interfere again with the concentration of all thoughts on the Self or the Purusha 1 . In that sense he tells us in the second Sutra that Yoga is the effort of restraining the activity or distractions of our thoughts. Before we begin to scoff at the Yoga and its minute treatment of postures, breathings, arid other means of mental concentration, we ought first of all to try to understand their original intention. Everything can become absurd by exaggeration, and this has been, no doubt, the case with the self-imposed discipline and tortures of the Yogins. But originally their object seems to have been no other than to counteract the distractions of the senses. We all consider the closing of the eyelids and the stopping of the ^ears against disturbing noises useful for serious meditation. This was the simple beginning of Yoga, and in that sense it was meant to be a useful addition to the Samkhya, because even a convinced Samkhya philosopher who had obtained 6V7anayoga or knowledge-yoga would inevitably suffer from the disturbances caused by external circumstances and the continual inroads of the outer world upon him, i.e. upon his Manas, unless strengthened to resist by Karmayoga or work -yoga the ever present enemy of his peace of mind. More minute directions as to how this desired concentration and abstraction could be achieved and maintained, might at first have been quite harmless, 1 I prefer, even in the Snmkhya-philosophy, to render Purusha by Self rather than by man, because in English r nan cannot be used in the sense of simply subject or* soul. Besidkes, Atwan, Self, is often used by Palawan" himself for Purusha, cf. Yoga-Sutras III, ai ; II, 41. 312 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, but if carried too. far they would inevitably produce those torturing exercises which seemed to Buddha, as they do to most people, so utterly foolish and useless. But if we our* selves must admit that our senses and all that they imply are real obstacles to quiet meditation, the attempts to reduce these sensuous affections to some kind of quietude or equa- bility (Samatva) need not surprise us, nor need we be altogether incredulous as to the marvellous results obtained by means of ascetic exercises by Yogins in India, as little as we should treat the visions of St. Francis or St. Teresa as downright impositions. The real relation of the soul to the body and of the senses to the soul is still as great a mystery to us as it was to the ancient Yogins of India, and their experiences, if only honestly related, deserve certainly the same careful attention as the stigmata of Roman Catholic saints. They may be or they may not be true, but there is no reason why they should be treated as a priori untrue. From this point of view it seems to me that the Yoga-philosophy deserves some attention on the part of philosophers, more particularly of the physical school 6f psychologists, and I did not feel justified there- fore in passing over this system altogether, though it may be quite true that, after we have once understood the position of the Samkhya-philosophy towards the great problem of the world, we shall not glean many new meta- physical or psychological ideas from a study of the Yoga. We must never forget that, although our Samkhya-Sfttras are very modern, the Samkhya as such, is not, and is always presupposed >by the Yoga. It has its roots in a soil carefully prepared by centuries of philosophical cultivation, and has but little in common with the orgiastic ecstasies which we see among savage tribes of the present day. The Hindus also, before they became civilised and philosophers, may or may not have passed through such a phase. But how little of true similarity there really exists between the Yoga and Tapas of the Hindus, and the sweating processes of the American Indians in their steam-booths, may easily be seen from the excellent Reports of the Bureau of Eth- nology, by J. W. Powell, 1892-3, p. 1 17 seq.; p. 823 seq., to mention no other .and more painful reports. PATA^C?ALI, VYASA. 313 Before we enter upon an examination of the peculiar teaching of the Yoga-philosophy, a few words with refer- ence to the sources on which we have to depend for our information may be useful. Pata%ali, Vyasa. The Stitras of the Yoga-philosophy are ascribed to Pata/7- grali, who is also called Phanin or &esha, th /Hi vine serpent. He may have been the author or the representative of the Yoga-philosophy without being necessarily the author of the Sfrtras. His date is of course uncertain, though some scholars have, with great assurance, assigned him to thjs second century B. c. It may be so, but we should say no more. Even the commonly received identification of the philosopher Pataw^ali with Pata/7(/ali, the grammarian and author of the Mahabhashya, should be treated as yet as a hypothesis only. We know too little about the history of Sanskrit proper names to be able to say whether the same Jiame implies the same person. That is not the case in any other country, and can hardly be true in India considering how freely the names of the gods or of great Rishis were taken, and are still taken, as proper names. It has actually been asserted that Vyasa, the author of a late commentary on Pata%ali's Yoga-Sfttras, is the same person as Vysa, the collector of the Vedas, the reputed author of the Mah&bharata and of the Vedanta-Sfttras. But there are ever so many Vyasas living even now, and no solid argument could possibly be derived from the mere recurrence of such a name. There are works ascribed to Hirawyagarbha, Harihara, Vishnu, &c.; then why not to Pata/7(/ali ? It is of course as impossible to prove that Pataw- amkara would appear on earth to uproot all heresies, if they had lived before the great heresy of Buddha. Pata/7r/ali is said to have been a portion of Sankarshawa or Ananta, the hooded serpent esha, encir- cling the world, and it may be for the same reason 'that he is sometimes called PhaTiin (Pha?*ibhartri). This is the kind of useless information which tradition gives us. 1 Yoga Aphorisms, p. Ixvi. CHRONOLOGY OF THOUGHT. 315 Chronology of Thought. In India we must learn to be satisfied with the little we know, not of the chronology of years, but of the chronology of thought; and taking the Yoga, in its systematic form, i.e. in the Pata^ali-Sutras, as post-Buddhistic, we can best understand the prominence which it gives both to th exercises which are to help toward overcoming the dis- tracting influences of the outer world, and to the arguments in support of the existence of an Isvara or Divine Lord. This marked opposition became intelligible and necessary as directed against Kapila as well as against Buddha ; and in reading the Yoga-Sutras it is often difficult to tf&y whether the author had his eye on the one or the other. If we took away these two characteristic features of the Yoga, the wish to establish the existence of an Isvara against all coiners, and to teach the means of restraining the affections and passions of the soul, as a preparation for true 'knowledge, such as taught by the Sa?nkhya-philosophy, littl'3 'Would seem to remain that is peculiar to Patafigrali. But though the Sutras are post-Buddhistic, there can be no doubt that not only the general outlines of the Samkhya, but likewise all that belongs to the Karmayoga or work- yoga was "known before the rise of Buddhism. Thus, if we turn to the Mahabharata, we find that the twenty-four principia, with Purusha as the twenty-fifth, are often mentioned, though arranged and described in different ways. Then we read again (Anugita XXV) : ' That which sageis by their understanding meditate upon, which is void of smell, of taste, of colour, touch or sound, that is called Pradlhana (Prakriti). That Pradhaiia is unperceived; a development of this unperceived power is the Mahat ; and a development of the Pradhana (when it has) become Mahat, is Ahawkara (egoism). From Ahamkara is pro- duced the development, namely, the great elements, and from the elements respectively, the objects of sense are staked to be a development/ As to the Yoga-practices or tortures we know that, after practising the most severe Tapas for a time, Buddha himself declared against it, and rather moderated than INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. encouraged the extravagant exercises of Brahmanic as- cetics. His own experience at the beginning of his career had convinced him of their uselessriess, nay, of their danger. But a moderately ascetic life, a kind of via media, remained throughout the ideal of Buddhism, and we can well understand that the Brahmans, in trying to hold their own against the Buddhists, should have tried ta place before the people an even more perfect system of asceticism. And, lest it should be supposed that the Sa?nkhya-philosophy, which was considered as orthodox or Vedic, had given its sanction to Buddha's denial of an Atman and Brahman, which was far more serious than the denial of an Isvara, Lord, it would have seemed all the more necessary to protest decidedly .against such denial, and thus to satisfy the ingrained theistic tendencies of the people at large, by showing that the Samkhya, by admitting Purusha, admitted a belief in something tran- scendent, and did by no means, according to Pata/J#ali at least, condemn a belief even in an Isvara, or Lord. In that sense it might truly be said that the Yog*a- philosophy would have been timely and opportune, if it came more boldly forward, after the rise of Buddhism, not so much as a new system of thought, but as a re- invigorated and determined assertion of ancient S&mkhya doctrines, which for a time had beei), thrown Into the shade by the Buddhist apostasy. Iry this way it Would become intelligible that Buddhism, though sprung from a soil saturated with S&mkhya ideas, should have been anterior to that new and systematic development of Sarakhya-philosophy, which we know in the Sfttras of Kapila or in the itarikas or even in the Tattva-sarnLsa ; that in fact, in its elements, the Sa?nkhya should be as decidedly pre-Buddhistic as in its final systematic foirm it was post-Buddhistic. That the existence side by side of two such systems as thoso of Kapila and Buddha, tihe one d'eemed orthodox, the other unorthodox, gave matter for reflection to the people in India we see best by a well-known verse which I quoted many years ago in my History of Ancient Sanskrit Literature (p. 102): 'If Bu.ddha knew the law and Kapila not, what is truth? THE YOGA-PHILOSOPHY. 317 If both were omniscient, how could there be difference of opinion between the two ? ' The Yoga-Philosophy. The Yoga-Siitras, or the Yoganusasaria *, called also by the same name which was giv^n to the Sa/mkhya-SiHras, viz. Sa/mkhya-prava/cana, both being considered as ex- positions of the old Samkhya, may have been contained originally in some such text-book as the Tattva-samasa. The Sutras were published and translated by Ballantyne, 1853, a translation continued by Govindadeva-.sastrin in the Pandit, vol. Ill, Nos. 28-68. A more useful edition, but not always quite correct translation, was given by Rajendralal Mitra in the Bibliotheca Indiea. 1883, 'Yoga Aphorisms of Pata;7(/ali, with the commentary of Bho^a R%a.' Vi<7/?ana-Bhikshu. whose commentary on Kapila's Samkhya- Sutras was mentioned before 2 , and who is chiefly 1 It is not much of an argument, but it may deserve to be mentioned, that th* title given by Pata%ali to the Yoga-Sutras, Atha Yoganusasanam, 'Now begins tbe teaching of the Yoga/ and not Atha Yogat/igwasa, reminds us of the title which the grammarian Pta%ali gives to his Mahabhashya, Atha Sabdanusasanam, *Now begins the teaching of Words or of tho Word.' This title does not belong to Panini's Sutras, but to the Maha- bhashya; and it is curious that such a compound as Sabdanusasariam would really oft'end against one of Panini's rules (II, 2, 14). According to Panini there ought to be no such compound, and though he does not give us the reason why he objects to this and other such-iike compounds, we can easily see that Sanskrit did not sanction compounds which might be ambiguous, considering that Word-teaching might be taken in the sense of teaching coming from words as well as teaching having words for its object. It is true that this apparent irregularity might be removed by a reference to another rule of Piwini (II, 3, 66), yet it is curious that the same, if only apparent, irregularity should occur both in the Mahabhashya and in the Yoga-Sutras, both being ascribed to Pata?1grali. a Other works ascribed to the same author are : The Brahma-mimawsa-bhashya, called Vigrnananm'ta. The Sawkhya-karika-bhashya, ascribed to him, but really composed by Gandapada (see Ganganatha, p. 2). The Yoga-varttika. The Isvara-gita-bhashya, from the Kurrna -purawa. The Prasnopanishad-aloka. An explanation of Prasastnpada's commentary on the Vaisoshika- Sutras, called Vaiseshika-varttika. There are printed editions of the Sawkhya-prava&ana-bhashya, the Yoga-varttika, and the Samkhya-sara. 31 8 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. known by his Yoga-v&rttika, is the author also of the ,Yoga-stra-samgraha, an abstract of the Yoga, which has been edited and translated by Ganganatha Jha, Bombay 1894, and may be consulted with advantage by students of philosophy. Colebrooke's essay on the Yoga, like all his essays, is still most useful and trustworthy ; and there are in German the excellent papers on the Sa?nkhya and Yoga by Professor Garbe in Buhler's Grundriss. Garbe speaks well of a dissertation by P. Markus, Die Yoga- philosophic nach dem Rajamdrtanda dargesteilt, which, however,, I have not been able to obtain. Misconception of the Objects of Yoga. It was almost impossible that the Yoga-philosophy, as represented by European scholars, should not have suffered from its close association with the Samkhya, properly so called. All its metaphysical antecedents were there. Yoga is indeed, as the Brahmans say, Samkhya, only modified, particularly in one point, namely, in its attempt to develop and systematise an ascetic discipline by which concentration of thought could be attained, and by admitting devotion to the Lord God as part of that discipline. Whether this was done, as is generally supposed, from mere theological diplomacy is a question we should find difficult tor answer, considering how little we know of the personal character of Patawgali or of the circumstances under which he elaborated his theistic Samkhya-philosophy. There is an entire absence o^ animosity on his part, such as our own philosophers would certainly have displayed in accusing another philosopher of atheism and in trying to amend his system in a theistic direction. No doubt there must always have been a majority in favour of a theistic philosophy of the universe as against an atheistic, but whether Patatf^ali may be fairly accused of having yielded to the brutal force of numbers, and curried favour with the many against the few is quite another question. It is certainly extraordinary to see the perfect calmness with which, with very few exceptions, Kapila's atheism is dis- cussed, and how little there is of the ad populum advocacy DEVOTION TO ISVARA, MISCONCEPTIONS. 319 in support of a belief in God and a personal God. Nor does Kapila, like other atheistic philosophers, display any animosity against the Divine idea and its defenders. He criticises indeed the usual arguments by which theists make and unmake their God, if they represent Him as the creator and ruler of the world, and charge him at the same time with cruelty, by making him responsible for the origin of evil also. But all this is done by Kapila in a calm and what one might almost call a businesslike manner ; and in answering Kapila's arguments, Pata^ali also preserves the same Samatva or even temper. He imputes no motives to his antagonist, nor does ho anywhere defend himself against any possible suspicion that in showing the neces- sity of a personal God, an Lsvara, he was defending the interests of the Brahman priesthood. After all, t&vara was not even a popular name for God, or the name of any special god, though it occurs as a name of Rudra, and in later times was applied even to such gods as Vislmu and $iva, after they had been divested of much of their old mythological trappings. Devotion to isvara, Misconceptions. In this respect also we have something to learn from Hindu philosophers. Considering the importance of the subject, it is useful to see how little heat was expended on it either by Kapila or by Pata/tyali. If we remember how the two philosophies were in popular parlance distinguished from each other as Samkhya with and Sa?7ikhya without a Lord, we should have expected to see this question treated in the most prominent place. Instead of which we find Pata;?$ali, at the end of the? first chapter, after having described the different practices by which a man may hope to become free from all worldly fetters, mentioning simply as one of many expedients, I, 23, * Devotion to the Lord/ or, as it is generally translated, ' devotion to God/ Devotion or Pranidhana (lit. placing oneself forward and into) is explained by Bhot/a as one of the forms of resignation, as worship of Him, and as the surrender of all one's actions to Him,, If a man, without wishing for any rewards con- 32O INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. sisting in worldly enjoyments, makes over all his cares to tsvara as the highest guide, that, we are told, is Pranidhana. Pata/7r/ali then goes on, c As it has been said that SamadhL or complete absorption can be obtained through devotion to the Lord, the next that has to be explained in order, is the nature of that Lord, the proof, the majesty, the name of Him, the order of His worship, and the fruit thereof/ In I, 24 Pata/7qali goes on to say : ' Isvara, the Lord, is a Purusha (Self) that has never been touched by sufferings, actions, rewards, or consequent dispositions/ The commen- tary adds : * Sufferings are such as Nescience, Avidya, &c. ; actions are either enjoined, forbidden, or mixed ; rewards are the ripened fruits of actions manifested in birth (genus, caste) and life, while dispositions (Asaya, Arilage) are so- called because they lie in the soil of the mind till the fruit has ripened, they are instincts (Sa??>skara) or impressions (Vasana). If the Lord is called a Purusha, that means that He is different from all other Purushas (Selves), and if Hi* is called Lord, that means that He is able by His work alone to liberate the whole world. Such power is due to the constant prevalence of goodness (a Gu?m) in Him, who has no beginning, and this prevalence of goodness arises from His eminent knowledge. But the two, knowledge and power, are not dependent on each other, for they are eternally abiding in the very substance of tsvafa. His very relation to that goodness is without beginning, be- cause the union of Prakriti and Purusha, that is, the creation would, from a Yoga point of view, have been impossible without the will of such an Lsvara. While the ATitta or mind in ordinary Purushas or Selves undergoes, while in the body, modifications tending towards happiness, unhappiness, and delusion, and, if remaining without blemish, good, and full of virtue, becomes conscious of the incidence of the pictures mirrored on the mind, it is not so with Isvara. His highest modification is of goodness alone, and he remains steadfast in enjoyment through eternal union with it. Therefore he alone is Isvara, eminent above all other Purushas. Again, even for one who has gained freedom, a return of sufferings, &c., is possible, and has to be guarded against by such means WHAT IS ISVARA? 321 as are inculcated in the Yoga ; but he, the tsvara, as he is always .such as he is, is not like a man who has gained freedom, but he is by nature free. Nor should one say that there may be many such Isvaras. Though there be equality of Purushas, qud Purushas, yet as their aims are different, such a view would be impossible. And though there be a possibility of more or less, yet the most eminent would always be the Isvara or the Lord, he alone having reached the final goal of lordship/ The Pataw#ala-bhashya dwells very strongly on this difference between the liberated soul and the Lord ; for 'the liberated or isolated souls/ it says, 'attain their isolation by rending asunder the three bonds, whereas in regard to Isvara there never was and never can be such bondage. The emancipated implies bondage, but this can never be predicated of the Lord/ We need not point out here the weak points of this argument, and the purely relative character of the great- ness and separateness claimed for th Isvara, as compared with other Purushas, but it may be well to try to compare our own ideas of God, when put into clear and simple language, with the ideas here propounded. Pata/?#ali seems to me to come very near to the Homoiousia of man with God, though he does jnot go quite as far as the Ve- d&ntin who claims for the Atmari perfect Homoousia with Brahman. Eis Isvara may be primus inter pares, but as one of the Purushas, he is but one among his peers/ He j is a little more than a god, but he is certainly not what we i itfean by God. What is As Kapila had declared that the existence of such a being as tsvara did not admit of proof, Pata%ali proceeds in the . next Sutra to offer what he calls his proofs, by saying : , ' In Him the seed of the omniscient (or omniscience) attains infinity/ It would be difficult to discover in this anything like a proof or a tenable appeal to any Pram&Tia, without the help of the commentary. But Bho#a explains that what is meant here is that there are different degrees of all excellences, such as omniscience, greatness, smallness, y. 322 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. and other Aisvaryas, and that therefore there mi^st be for all of them a point beyond which it is impossible to go. This Niratiseya point, this non plus ultra of excellency i what is claimed for Isvara or the Lord. Though this could hardly be considered as a convincing argument of the existence of a Being endowed with all such transcendent excellences as are here postulated, it shows at all events an honest intention on the part- of Pata/Tgali. Pata%ali's argument reminds us to a certain extent of the theistic argument of Cleanthes and Boethius. What he means is that where there is a great and greater, there must also be a greatest, and this is Lsvara, and that where there is good and better, there must be best. Nor does he flinch in trying to answer the questions which follow. The question is supposed to have been asked, how this Isvara, without any inducement, could have caused that union and separation of himself and Prakr/ti which, as we saw, is only another name for creation. The answer is that the inducement was his love of beings, arising from his mercifulness, his determination being to save all living beings at the time of the Kalpapralayas and Mahapralayas, the great destructions and reconstructions of the world. This, of course, would not have been admitted by Kapila. Next Pata#7 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. ' Live in the world but be not of it, is the precept taught by our old Kishis, and it is the only means of liberating yourself from the world/ ' The body is perishable and transitory, white the Self is imperishable and everlasting ; it is connected with the body only by the link of Karman ; it should riot be subservient to it/ ' * If, through sheer negligence, you do nothing good for your fellow creatures, you will be your own enemy, and become a victim to the miseries of this world/ * Better to do less good, with purity of heart, than to do more with jealousy, pride, malice, or fraud. Little, but good and loving work, is always valuable, like a pure gem, the essence of a drag, or pithy advice/ 'If you are unable to subject yourself physically to penances, to undergo austerities, and engage in deep con- templation, the proper course to liberate your soul from the hard fetters of Karman would be to keep the passions of your heart under control, to check your desires, to carry out your secular affairs with calmness, to devote yourself to the worship of God, and to realise in yourself the " Permanent Truth," bearing in mind the transitory nature of the universe/ ' To control your mind, speech, and body, does not mean to be thoughtless, silent or inactive, like beasts or trees ; but, instead of thinking what is evil, speaking untruth, and doing harm to others, mind, speech, and body should be applied to good thoughts, good words, and good deeds/ iMspassionateness, as here taught for practical purposes chiefly, reaches its highest point in the eyes of the Yoga- philosopher, when a man, after he has attained to the knowledge of Purusha, has freed himself entirely from all desire for the three Gunas (or their products). This is at least what Pata/? IV, 12) when he discovers here something like the theory of ideas or logoi in the mind of Pataw^ali, and holds that the three ways or Adhvans in which objects present themselves to the mind, or affect the mind, as past, present and future, correspond to the admission of universalia ante rem, the ideas or types, the universalia in re, the essence, and the universalia post rem, the concepts in our minds. I confess I hardly understand his meaning. It should never be for- gotten tnat the mind is taken by Pata/?#ali as by itself unconscious (not as Svabhasa, self-illuminated, IV, 18) and as becoming conscious and intelligent for a time only by the union between it and the Purusha, who is pure intelligence. The Manas only receives the consciousness of perception which comes in reality from the Purusha, so that here we 1 This kind of memory comes very near to what we call instinct, propensity, or untaught ability. IS TOGA NIHILISM? 359 should have the etymological, though somewhat fancifill, definition of consciousness (con-scientia) as well as of the Sanskrit Sara- vid, i.e. knowing along with the mind, i.e. apprehending the impressions of the mind (Svabuddhi- Sa?nvedanam). But though .Kitta is the work of the Manas, not directly of the Buddhi, this ^fitta, when seen by the seer (Purusha) on one side and tinged with what is seen on the other, may be spoken of as the thought of the Purusha, though it is so by a temporary misconception only. This JTitta again is coloured by many former im- pressions (Vasana). It may be called the highest form of Prakriti, and as such it serves no purpose of its own, but works really for another, the Purusha, whom it binds and fascinates for a *time with the sole purpose, we are told, of bringing him back to a final recognition of his true Self (IV, 24). Kaivalya, If that is once achieved, the Purusha knows that he hims3lf is not experiencer, neither knower nor actor ; and the Manas or active mind, when beginning to feel the approach of Kaivalya, turns more and more inward and away from the world, so as not to interfere with the obtainment of the highest bliss of the Purusha. Yet there is always danger of a relapse in unguarded moments or in the intervals of meditation. Old impressions may reassert themselves, and the mind may lose its steadiness, unless the old Yoga-remedies are used again and again to remove all impediments. Then at last, perfect discrimination is re- warded by what is called by a strange term, Dharmamegha, the cloud of virtue, knowledge and virtue being inseparable like cause and effect. All works and all sufferings have now ceased, even what is to be known becomes smaller and smaller, the very Grnias, i. e. Prakriti, having done their work, cease troubling^ Purusha becomes himself, is in- dependent, undisturbed f ree, and blessed. Is Yogra Nihilism? This is the end of the Yoga-philosophy, and no wonder that it should have been mistaken for complete nihilism by 360 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Cousin and others. But first of all, the play of Prakriti,- though it has ceased for our Purusha, who has gained true knowledge, is supposed to be going on for ever for the benefit of other innumerable Purushas ; and as long as ? there are any spectators, the spectacle of Prakrit! will never cease. Secondly, the Purusha, though freed from iUusion, is -not thereby annihilated. He is himself, apart from nature, and it is possible, though it is not distinctly ' stated, that the Purusha in his aloneness may continue his life, like the Givanmukta of the Vedanta, maintaining his freedom among a crowd of slaves, without any fear or hope of another Jife, unchanged himself in this ever-changing Samsara. However, we need not attempt to supply what Pataw^ali himself has passed over in silence. The final goal whether of the Yoga, or of the Sa/mkhya, nay even of the Vedanta and of Buddhism, always defies description. Nirvana in its highest sense is a name and a thought, but nothing can be predicated of it. It is ' what no eye has seen and what has not entered into the mind of man/ We know that it is ; but no one can say what it is, and !>hose who attempt to do so are apt to reduce it to a mere phantasmagoria or to a nothing. Though I hope that the foregoing sketch may give a correct idea of the general tendency of the Yoga- philosophy, I know but too well that there are several points which require further elucidation, and on which even native expositors hold different opinions. What we must guard against in all these studies is rejecting as absurd whatever we cannot understand at once, or what to us seems fanciful or irrational. . I know from iny own experience how often what seemed to me for a long time unmeaning, nay absurd^ Disclosed after a time a far deeper meaning than I should .ever have expected. The great multitude of technical tertaas, though it may be bewildering to us, could not be entirely suppressed, because it helps to show through how long and continuous a development these Indian systems of thought must have passed, before any attempt was made, as it was by Pataw- >rdT .aeeaimaiq Relation between Ny&ya and MbL^. iQ ^I^urnbj^ -jjjgi;-. [j&JT p| noidomdaib WHILE in the systems hitherto examined, ^ pfq^Acularlyrfaj the Ved^nta, Samkhya, and Yoga, there runa a strong i religious and even poetical vein, ye now ; corhe )bo two systems, Nyaya and Vaiseshika, which ar^ vey dry and unimaginative, and much more like what we mean by scholastic systems of philosophy, businesslike expositions of what can be known, either of the world which surrounds us or of the world within, that is, of our faculties or powers of perceiving, conceiving, or reasoning on one side, $rid the objects which they present to us, on the other. It should be remembered that, like the Samkhya and Yoga, and to a certain extent like the Pflrva and Uttara- Mim&rasa, the Ny&ya and Vaiseshika also have by the Hindus themselves been treated as forming but one disci- pline. We possess indeed a separate body of Ny&ya-Sfttras and another of Vaiseshika-Sfttras, and these with their reputed auth6rs, Gotania and KaTiada, have long been accepted as the original sources whence these two streams of toe ancient philosophy of India proceeded. But we know now that the literary style which sprang up naturally in what I called the Sfttra-period, th3 period to which the first attempts at a written, in place of a purely mnemonic, literature may have to be ascribed, was by no means restricted to that ancient period, but continued to be so well imitated in later times that we find it used with great success not only in the S&mkhya-Sfttras, which are later than M&dhava (1350 A.D.), but in more modern compositions also. It shoula always be borne in mind that the Sfttras ascribed to Gotama and KaTi&da presuppose a long previous EELATTQN BETWEEN NYAYA AND VALSESHIKA. 363 development of philosophical thought, and instead of regarding the' two as two independent streams, it seems far more likely that there existed at first an as yet un- differentiated body of half philosophical half popular thought^ bearing on things that can be known, the Padar- thas, i.e. omne scibile, and on the means of acquiring such knowledge, from which at a later time, according to the preponderance of either the one or the other subject, the two systems of Yaiseshika and Nyaya branched off. These two systems shared of course many things in common, and hence we can well understand that at. a later time they should have been drawn together again and treated as one, as we see in /Sivaditya's Saptapadarthi (about 1400 A.D.), in the Bhasha-Pari&Meda, with its commentary the Muktavali, in the Tarkasamgraha, the Tarkakauinudi, the Tarkamrita, &c. For practical purposes it is certainly preferable that we should follow their example and thus avoid the necessity of discussing the same subjects twice over. There may have been an old Tarka, very like our Tarkasamgraha, the one before the bifurcation of the old system of Anvikshiki, the other after the confluence of the two. But these are as yet conjectures only, and may have to remain mere con- jectures always, so that, in the present state of our know- ledge, and depending, as we have to do, chiefly on the existing Sutras as the authorities recognised in India itself, we must not attempt a historical treatment, but treat each system by itself in spite of unavoidable repetitions. A very zealous native scholar, Mahadeo Rajaram Bodas, in the Introduction to his edition of the Tarkasamgraha, has indeed promised to give us some kind of history of the Ny&ya-philosophy in India. But unfortunately that period in the historical development of the Nyaya which is of greatest interest to ourselves, namely that which preceded the composition of the Ny&ya-Sutras, had by him also to be left a blank, for the simple reason that nothing is known of Ny&ya before Gotamit. The i later periods, however, have been extremely well treated by Mr. feodas, and I may refer my readers to him for the best information' on the subject. Mr. Bodas places ths Sfttras of Qofcama and Ka?iada in the fifth or fourth cent. B. c. ; and he expresses 364 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. a belief that the Vaiseshika, nay even the Samkhya, as systems of thought, were anterior to Buddha, without how- ever adducing any new or certain proofs. MgaAg*. Dates are the weak points in the literary history of India, and, in the present state of our studies, any date, however late, should be welcome. In former years to assign the Kapila-Sutras to the fourteenth or even fifteenth century A.D., would have seemed downright heresy. Was not K&lidsa himself assigned to a period long before the beginning of our era? It seems now generally accepted that Kalidasa really belonged to the sixth century A.D., and this date of Kalidasa may help us to a date for the Sfttras of Gotama, valuable to us, though it may be despised by those who imagine that the value of Sanskrit literature depends chiefly on its supposed remote antiquity. I have pointed out 1 that, according to native interpreters, Kalidasa alluded to the logician Dignaga in a verse of 'his Megha- duta 2 . We may suppose therefore that Dignaga was considered a contemporary of Kalidasa. Now Dign&ga is said by Va&aspati Misra, in his Nyaya- v&rttika-tatparya- tfika, to have interpreted the Nyaya aphorisms of Gotarna in a heterodox or Buddhist sense, while Uddyotakara wrote his commentary to refute his interpretation and to restore that of Pakshilasvamin. If Va/caspati Misra is right, we should be allowed to place Dignaga in the sixth century, and assign the same or rather an earlier date to the Sutras of Gotama, as explained by him and other Nyaya philo- sophers. So late a date may not seem to be worth much, still I think it is worth having. Several other dates may be fixed by means of that of Dignaga as I tried to show in the passage quoted above (India, pp. 307 seq.). A more comprehensive study of Buddhist literature may possibly shed some more light on the chronology of the later literature of the Brahmans, if I am right in supposing that in the beginning the followers of Buddha broke by no 1 India, p. 307. 2 See also Prof. Satis Chandra Vidyablbrushana in Journal of Buddhist Text Society, IV, parts iii, and iv, p. 16. 365 means so entirely, as has generally been supposed, with the literary traditions of the Brahmans. It is quite intelligible ^rhy among the various systems of Hindu philosophy the Buddhists should have paid little attention to the two Mimamsas, concerned as they both were with the Veda, an authority which the Buddhists had rejected. But there was no reason why the Buddhists should forswear the study of either the Nyaya or Vaiseshika systems, or even the Samkhya system, though making their reserves on certain points, such as the existence of an Isvara, which was admitted by the Nyayas, but % denied by Buddha. We know that at the court of Harsha, Brahmans, Bauddhas, and Crainas were equally welcome (India, pp. 307 seq.). We know from Chinese travellers such as Hiouen-thsang that Vasubandha, for instance, before he became a Buddhist, had read with his master, Vinayabhadra or Samghabhadra l , not only the books of the eighteen schools which were Buddhist, but also the six Tirthya philosophies, clearly meant for the six Brahmanic systems of philosophy. This Vasubandha, as a very old. man, was actually the teacher of Hiouen-thsang, who travelled in India from 629 to 648 A.D. Therefore in Vasubandha's time all the six systems of Indian philosophy must have been in existence, in the form of Sutras or Karikas. For we possess, in one case at least, a commentary by Pakshila-svamin or Vatsya- yana on the Nyaya-SMras, the same as those which we possess, and we know that the same Sutras were explained afterwards by Dignaga, the Buddhist. This Buddhist commentary was attacked by Uddyotakara, a Brahman, of the sixth century, while in the beginning of the seventh century Dharmakirtti, a Buddhist, is said to have defended Dignaga 2 and to have criticised Uddyotakara's Nyaya- varttika. In the ninth century Dharmottara, a Buddhist, defended Dharmakirtti's and indirectly Dignaga's inter- pretation of the Nyaya-Sfttras, and it was not till the tenth 1 See also Journal of Buddhist Text Society, 1896, p. 16. 2 Though none of Dignaga's writings have as yet been discovered, Sri Sarat Chandra states that there is in the library of the Grand Lama a Tibetan translation of his Nyaya-samu&fcaya (Journal of Buddhist Text Society, part iii, 1896, p. 17). 366 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. century that Va/i'aspati Misra finally re-established the Br&hmanie view of the Nyaya in his Nyaya- varttika- tatparya-ilka. This would coincide with *the period of the Brahmanfe reaction and the general collapse of Bud- dhism in India, and thus place before us an intelligible progress in the study of the .Nyaya both by Brahmans and Buddhists from the sixth to the tenth century, while the revival of the Nyaya dates from Gamgesa Upadhyaya who lived in the fourteenth century at Mithila. Thanks to the labours of Sarat Chandra Das and Satis Chandra YidyabhftshaTia, we have lately gained access to some of the Sfttras of the Buddhist schools of philosophy, which are full of interest. Of the four great schools of the Buddhists, the Madhyamika, YogaMra, Sautrantika, and Vaibhashika, the first or Madhyamika now lies before us in the Madhyamika Vritti by jfiTandra-Kirtti, and there is every hope that other philosophical treatises also, for instance, the Nyaya-samu&/caya, may be made 4ccessible to us by the labours of these indefatigable scholars. The S&tras or rather K&rikas of the Madhyamika .school must, of course, be distinguished from the system of thought which they are meant to explain. The characteristic feature of that system is the $unya-vada, or nihilism, pure and simple. As such it is referred to and refuted in Gotama's Nyaya- Sutras IV, 37 to 40, in Kapila ; s Samkhya-Sutras I, 43, 44, in Badarayawa's Vedanta-Sutras II, % 28, where $amkara distinctly refers the doctrine- that We know no objects, but only our perceptions of them, tc> Sugata or Buddha. The author or the Pa/z&adasi quotes tli& Madhya- mikas by name as the teachers of universal nihilism (Sarvam . If Nagargruna was really ttye author of the Madhyamika- Sfttras, as we now possess tbfem, they would carry us backi to about the first century A.!\, and we should have in his' Karikas, as explained by -STandra-KiVtti, the oldest docu- ment of systematic philosophy in India, which will require very careful examination. Though it is different, no doubt, from all the six systems, it nevertheless shares in common with them many of the ideas and even technical terms. If it teaches the $flnyatva or emptiness of t^he world, this after DIGNAGA. 30JIH1 367 all is not very different from the Vedantic Avidya, and the Samkhya Aviveka, andl if n it teaches the Pratityatva of everything, that need be no more than the dependence of everything 'to something else 1 . The ! divine or supernatural. We meet with the five perceptions of colour, taste, smell, touch, and sound, and five causes, light, water, earth, air, and ether, sw4 the well-known idea that Manas, mind, to the Buddhists is that>t6 thrill neither the objects of sense nor the sensations ^iD&to an -^iderlying substance or reality. " W%^OWe ft ;i gi*eat debt of gratitude to both Sarat Chandra Das and /Sri Satis Chandra Vidy&bhushami for their labours in Tib^fc, ^tnd we look forward to many valuable contribu- tions from their pen/ more particularly for retranslations from Tibetan. Whether Buddhist philosophy shares more in common with the Sirakhya than with the Ny ay a and Vaiseshika seems to me as doubtful as ever. The fundamental position of the Samkhya, as Satkaryavada, is the very opposite of the Buddhist view of the world. -rhiB ai d -bio. R.r 1 PratTtya in Pratitya-samutpada and similar words may best be rendered by depea4nt or conditioned. A son, for instance, is a son, Pitaram Pratitya, dependent on a father, and a father is impossible without assort*. I$,!the sama way everything is dependent on . : w ni a>! 368 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Bibliography. It was in 1852 that I published my first contributions to a study of Indian philosophy in the Zeitschrift der Deut- schen Morgenld^dischen Gesellschaft. These papers did not extend, however, beyond the Vaiseshika and Nyaya-philo- sophy as treated in the Tarkasamgraha, and more urgent occupations connected with the edition of the Rig-veda prevented me ; at the time from finishing what I had pre- pared for publication on the other systems of Indian philosophy. Though, of course, much new and important material has come to light in the meantime, particularly through the publications of the Vaiseshika-Sutras in the Sibliotheca Indica, through the complete translation of them' by A. E. Gough, 1873, an( ^ through the comprehen- sive researches of European scholars, such as Professoirs Deussen and Garbe, I found that there was not much to alter in my old account of Gotama's and Kawada's philosophies, as given in the German Oriental Journal, and in my paper on Indian Logic contributed to the late Archbishop Thom- son's Laws of Thought. Indian philosophy has this great advantage that each tenet is laid down in, the Sutras with the utmost precision, so that there can be little doubt as to what KaTiada or Gotama thought about the nature of the soul, the reality of human knowledge, the relation between cause and effect, the meaning of creation, and the relation between God or the Supreme Being and man. Thus it may be understood why even papers published so long ago as 1824, such as J. Colebrooke's papers on the Nyaya and Vaiseshika and the other systems of Indian philosophy, may still be recommended to all who want trustworthy information on Indian philosophy. These essays have sometimes been called antiquated, but there is a great difference between what is old and what is anti- quated. The difficulty in giving an account of these systems for the benefit of European readers consists far more in deciding what may be safely omitted, so as to bring out the salient points of each system, than in re- capitulating all their tenets. Books in which the Nyaya and Vaiseshika-systems may NYAYA-PHILOSOPHY. 369 be studied by those who are unacquainted with Sanskrit are, besides the papers of Colebrooke : Ballantyne, The Aphorisms of the Ny&ya-Philosophy by Gautama. Sanskrit and English, Allahabad, 1 850. (Gau~ tarna is the same as Gotama, only that by a tacit agreement Gotama has generally been used as the name of the philo- sopher, Gautama as that of Buddha, both belonging, it would seem, to the family of the Gautamas or Gotamas, the MSS. varying with regard to the vowel.) A.. E. Gough, The Vaiseshika Aphorisms of Kauada, translated, Benares, 1873. Manilal Nabubhai Dvivedi, The Tarka-Kaumudt, being an introduction to fch* principles of the Vaiseshika and Nyaya-philosophies by Laugaksbi Bh&skara, Bombay, 1886. This is the same author to whom we owe a valuable edition of the Yogas*ara-sa / mgraha. Windisch, Uber das Nyaya-bhashya, Leipzig, s. a. Kesava $astri, The Nyaya-darsana with the commentary of Vatsyayana, in the Pundit, 1877, pp. 60, 109, 311, 363 (incomplete) ; see also Bibliothtca Indica. Mahadeo Rajaram Bodas, The Tarkasamgraha of Annam- bha^a, with the author's Dipika and Govardhana's Nyaya- bodbini, ^prepared by the late Rao Bahadur Yasavanta Vasadeo Athalya, and published with critical and explana- tory notes, Bombay, 1897. This book reached me after these chapters on the Nyaya and Vaiseshika were written, but not too late to enable me to profit by several of his explanations and criticisms, before they were printed. Though Nyya has always been translated by logic, we must not imagine that the Nyaya-Sutras are anything like our treatises on formal logic. There is, no doubt, a greater amount of space allowed to logical questions in these than in any of the other systems of Indian philosophy , but originally the name of Nyaya would have been quite as applicable to the Piirva-Miraamsa, which is actually called Nyaya in such works, for instance, as Sayana's Nyaya- maia-vistara, published by Goldst ticker, Nor is logic the sole or chief end of Gotama's philosophy. Its chief 24 Bb 370 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. end, like thai of the other Darsanas, is salvation, the summum bonum which is promised to all. This summum bonum is called by Gotama NiAsreyasa, literally that which has nothing better, the non plus ultra of blessedness. This blessedness, acco^-ding to the ancient commentator. Vatsy&- yana, is described as consisting in renunciation with regard tp all the pleasures of this life, and in the non-acceptance of, or indifference to any rewards in the life to come ; as being in fact what Brahman is, without fear, without desire, without decay, and without death. Even this Brahmahood must not be an object of desire, for such desire would at once produce a kind of bondage, and prevent that perfect freedom from all fear or hope, which is to follow by itself, but should never be yearned for. This perfect state of freedom, or resignation, can, according to Gotama, be realised in one way only, namely, by know- ledge, and in this case, by a knowledge of the sixteen great topics of the Nyaya-philosophy Summum Bonum. In this respect all the six systems of philosophy are alike, they always promise to their followers or their believers the attainment of the highest bliss that can be obtained by man. The approaches leading to that bliss vary, and the character also of the promised bliss is not always the same ; yet in each of the six systems philosophy is recommended r^ot, as with us, for the sake of knowledge, but for the highest purpose that man can strive after in this life, that is, his own salvation. We saw that the Vedanta recognised true salvation or Moksha in the knowledge of Brahman, which knowledge is tantamount to identity with Brahman. This Brahman or God is, as the Upariishads already declare, invisible, and far beyond the reach of the ordinary faculties of our mind. But he can be learnt from revelation as contained in the Veda, and as $vetaketu was taught ' Tat tvam asi,' ' Thou art it, 1 every Vedantist is to learn in the end the same lesson, and to realise his identity with Brahman, as the fulfilment of all desires, and the surcease of all suffering (DuAkhanta). SUMMUM BONUM. 371 The end of all suffering is likewise the- object of the Samkhya-philosophy, though it is to be reached by a dif- ferent road. Kapila, being a dualist, admits an objective substratum by the side of a subjective spirit or rather spirits, and he sees the cause of all suffering in the spirits' identifying themselves with what is purely objective or material. He therefore recognises the tnie means of destroying all bondage and regaining perfect freedom of the spirit in our distinguishing clearly between spirit and matter, between subject and object, between Purusha and Prakriti. Kaivalya, or aloneness, is the right name for that highest state of bliss which is promised to us by the Samkhya-philosophy. The Yoga-philosophy holds much the same view of the soul recovering its freedom, .but it insists strongly on certain spiritual exercises by which the soul may best obtain and maintain peace and quietness, and thus free itself effectually from the illusions and sufferings of life. It also lays great stress on devotion to a Spirit, supreme among all the other spirits, whose very existence, according to Kapila, cannot be established by any of the recognised means of real knowledge, the Pramawas. Of the two Mlmawsas we have seen already that the Brahma-Mtma/msa or the Vedanta recognises salvation as due to knowledge of the Brahman, which knowledge pro- duces at once the recognition of oneself as in reality Brah- man (Brahmavid Brahma eva bhavati, 'He who knows Brahman is Brahman indeed'). It is curious to observe tliat, while the Samkhya insists on a distinction between Purushas, the subjects, and Prakriti, all that is objective, as the only means of final beatitude, the Vedanta on the contrary postulates the surrendering of all distinction be- tween the Self and the world, and between the Self and Brahman as the right means of Moksha. The roads are different, but the point reached at last is much tjhe same. The other Mimamsa, that of Craimini, diverges widely from that of Badarayawa. It lays its chief stress on works (Karman) and their right performance, and holds that salvation may be obtained through the performance of B b 2 372 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. such works, if only they are performed without any deuire of rewards, whether on earth or in heaven. Lastly, the Nyaya and Yaiseshika systems, though they also aim at salvation, are satisfied with pointing out the means of it as consisting in correct knowledge:, such as can only be obtained from a clear apprehension of the sixteen topics treated by Gotama, or the six or seven categories put forward by Ka/n&da. These two philosophies, agreeing as they do among themselves, seem to me to differ very characteristically from all the others in so far as thev admit of nothing invisible or transcendent (Avyakta), whether corresponding to Brahman or to Prakriti. They are satisfied with teaching that the soul is different from the body, and they think that, if this belief in the body as our own is once surrendered, our sufferings, which always reach us through the body, will cease by them- selves. But while we can understand that each of the six systems of Indian philosophy may succeed in removing pain, it is very difficult to see in what that actual nappi- ness was supposed to consist which remained after that removal. The Vedarita speaks of Ananda, or bliss, that resides in the highest Brahman ; but the happiness to be enjoyed by the souls near the throne of Brahman, and in a' kind of paradise, is not considered as final, but is assigned to a lower class only. That paradise has no attraction, and would give no real satisfaction to those who have reached the knowledge of the Highest Brahman. Their blissful knowledge is described as oneness with Braliman, but no details are added. The bliss held out by the Samkhyas also is very vague and indefinite. It can arise only from the Purusha himself, if left entirely to himself, far from all the illusions and disturbances arising from objective nature, or the works of Prakriti. Lastly, the Apavarga (bliss) of the Ny&ya and Vaise- shika systems seems entirely negative, and produced simply by the removal of false knowledge. Even the different names given to the supreme bliss promised by each system of philosophy tell us very little. Mukti and Moksha mean MEANS OP SALVATION. 373 deliverance, Kaivalya, isolation or detachment, Nitareyasa, non plus ultra, Amrita, immortality, Apavarga, delivery. Nor does the well-known Buddhist term Nirvana help us much. We know indeed from PaTiini (VIII, 3, 50) that the word was pre-Buddhistic and existed in his time. He tells us that, if used in the sense of ' blown out/ the right form would be Nirvata/^, such as Nirvato vataA, ' the wind has ceased to blow/ but Nirva/fto *gr"dk, 'the fire is gone out/ We cannot prove, however, that NirvaTia was used as the technical term for the summum bonum in PaTiini's time, and it does not seem to occur in the classical Upani- shads. Its occurring as the title of one of the modern [Jpanishads makes it all the more likely that it was borrowed there from Buddhistic sources. There is one passage only, in the shorter text of the Maitreya * Upani- shad where Nirvar^am anusasanam occurs, possibly meant for Nirvananusasanam, the teaching of NirvaTia. What should be clearly understood is that in the early Buddhistic writings also, Nirvana does not yet mean a complete blow- ing oat of the individual soul, but rather the blowing out and subsiding of all human passions and the peace and quietness which result from it. The meaning of complete annihilation was a later and purely philosophical meaning attached to Nirvana, and no one certainly could form an idea of what that NirvaTia was meant to be in the Buddhist Nihilistic or $ftnyata-philosophy, I doubt even whether the Upanishads could have given us a description of what they conceived their highest Mukti or perfect freedom to be. In fact they confess themselves (Taitt. Up. II, 4, i) that ' all speech turns away from the bliss of Brahman, unable to reach it V an( i when language fails, thought is not likely to fare better. Means of Salvation. Turning now to the means by which the Nyaya-philo- sophy undertakes to secure the attainment of the summum 1 Sacred Books* of the East, XV, p. 61. 2 See a very learned article on Nirvana by Professor Satis Chandra Vidyabhushana in the Journal of the Buddhist Text Society, VI, part i, p. 33. 374 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. bonum or Apavarga, we find them enumerated in the following list : The Sixteen Topics or Padarthas. (j) Prama/n/a, raeans of knowledge; (2) Prameya, objects of knowledge ; (3) Samsaya, doubt ; (4) Prayo#ana, pur- pose ; (5). Dr/shianta, instance ; (6) SiddMnta, established truth; (7) Avayava, premisses; (8) Tarka, reasoning; (9) Nirnaya, conclusion ; ( 10) Vada, argumentation ; (i i) Galpa, sophistry; (12) VitaraZa, wrangling, cavilling; (13) Hetva- bhasa, fallacies; (14) IfAala, quibbles; (15) (?ati, false analogies; (16) Nigrahasthana, unfitness for arguing. This may seem a very strange list of the topics to be treated by any philosophy, particularly by one that claims . the title of Nyaya or logic. It is clear that in reality the chapters on Pramawa or means of knowledge, and Prameya. objects of knowledge, comprehend the whole of philosophy. Means of Knowledge. The four PramaTias, according to Gotama, are Pratyaksha, sensuous perception, Anumaiia, inference, Upamana, com- parison, and $abda, word. Perception 1 comes first, because inference can only begin to do its work after perception has prepared the way, and has supplied the material to which inference can be applied. Comparison is no more than a subordinate kind of inference, while the /Sabda or the word, particularly that of the Veda, depends again, as we should say, on a previous inference by which the authority of the word, more particularly the revealed word, has first been established. Imperfect as this analysis of our instruments of knowledge may seem, it seems to me highly Creditable to Indian philosophers that they should have understood the necessity of such an analysis on the very threshold of any system of philosophy. How^many misunderstandings might have been avoided if all philosophers had recognised the necessity of such a# introductory chapter. If we must depend for all our know- ledge, first on our senses, then on our combinatory and reasoning faculties, the question whether revelation falls OBJECTS OF KNOWLEDGE. 375 under the one or the other, or whether it can claim an* independent authority, can far more easily be settled than if such questions are not asked in limine, but turn up casually whenever transcendental problems come to be treated. Objects of Knowledge. The objects of knowledge, as given by the Nyaya, com- prehend omne scibile, such as body, soul, organs of sense, qualities, cognition, mind, will, fault, death, enjoyment, pain, and final freedom. These objects are afterwards discussed singly, but have of course little to do with logic. Doubt and purpose mark the first steps towards philosophical dis- cussion, instances and established ' truths s apply materials, while premisses and reasoning lead on to the conclusion which disputants wish to reach. From Nos. 10 to 16, we have rules for dialectic rather than for logic. We are taught how to meet the artifices of our antagonists in a long argu- mentation, how to avoid or to resist sophistry, wrangling, fallacies, quibbles, false analogies, and downright mis- statements, in fact, how to defend^ truth against unfair antagonists. If from our point-ef^yiew we deny the name of logic to such problems, we should be perfectly justified, though a glance at the history of Greek philosophy would show us that, before logic became an independent branch of philosophy it was likewise mixed up with dialectic and with questions of some more special interest, the treatment of w r hich led gradually to the elaboration of general rules of thought, applicable to all reasoning, whatever its subject may be. It is quite clear that these sixteen topics should on no account be rendered, as they mostly have been, by the six- teen categories. Categories are the praedicabilia, or whatever can be predicated, and however much the mean- ing of this term may have been varied by European philo- sophers, it could never have been so far extended as to include wrangling, fallacies, quibbles and all the rest. We shall see that the six 'or seven Padarthas o the Vaise- shikas correspond far more nearly to the categories of the 376 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Aristotelian and afterwards of European philosophy in general PadArth*. Object. Nothing shows so well the philosophical character of the Sanskrit language as this very word Padartha, which has been translated by category. It means in ordinary Sanskrit simply a thing, but literally it meant Irtha, the meaning, the object, Pada, of a word. What we should call objects of thought, they called far more truly objects of words, thus showing that from the earliest times they understood that no thought was possible except in a word, and that the objects of our knowledge became possible only after they had been named. Their language passed through an opposite process to that of Latin. Latin called every kind of knowledge or all known things gnomina, from g)nosco, to know ; but after a time, and after the initial g had been dropped, as we drop it involuntarily in gnat, their gnomiifia became nomina, and were then sup- posed to be something different from the old and forgotten gnomina ; they became nomina, i. e. mere names. Six Fadfcrthas of Vaiieshika. According to the Vaiseshikas, we have six Padarthas, i. e. six general meanings, categories or predicates, to which all words i.e. all things can be referred. All known things must be either substances (9), qualities (24), or motions, the last meaning, however, more than mere local move- ment, so as to correvspond in fact to our activity or even to our becoming (Werden). Knowledge (Buddhi) is here treated as one of the qualities of the soul, which itself is one of the substances, so that many things which with us belong to psychology and logic, are treated by the v^aise- shikas under this head. The next two, the general and the particular, com- prehend what is shared in common by many objects, and what is peculiar to one, and thus distinguishes it from all others. Samavaya or intimate connection is a very useful name for a, connection between things which cannot exist one MADHAVA'S ACCOUNT OF NYAYA. 377 without the other, such as cause and effect, parts and the whole, and the like. It comes very near to the Avina- bhava, i.e. the Not- without-being, and should be carefully distinguished from mere conjunction or succession. The seventh category, Abhava, or negation, was added, it would seem, at a later time, and can be applied to previous, to present or to subsequent non-existence, or even to absolute Abhava. Hadhava's Account of Nyaya. In order to see what, in the eyes of native scholars, the Nyaya-philosophy was meant to achieve, it may be useful to look at an account of it given by the great Madhava- fcarya in his Sarvadarsana-samgraha, the compendium of all the systems of philosophy. * The Nyaya-sastra/ he says, 'consists of five books, and each book contains two daily portions or Ahnikas. In the first Ahnika of the first book the venerable Gotama discusses the definitions of nine subjects, beginning with "proof" (PramaTia), and in the second those of the remaining seven, beginning with dis- cussion (Vada). In the first daily portion of the second book he examines doubt (8), discusses the four kinds of proof, and refutes all objections that could be made against' their being considered as instruments of right knowledge ; and in the second he shows that " presumption " and other PramaTias are really included in the four kinds of " proof " already given. In the first daily portion of the third book he examines the soul, the body, the senses, and their objects ; in the second, " understanding " (Buddhi) and mind (Manas). In the first daily portion of the fourth book he examines activity (Pravr^tti), faults (Dosha), transmigra- tion (Pretyabhava), fruit or reward (Phala), pain (DuAkha), and final liberation (Apavarga) ; in the second he investi- gates the truth as to the causes of the " faults," and also the subject of "wholes" and "parts." In the first daily portion of the fifth book he discusses the various kinds of futility (frati), and in the second the various kinds of objectionable proceedings (Nigrahasthana) ' After having held out in the first Sfttra the promise of eternal salvation to all who studv his philosophy properly, INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Gotama proceeds at once to a description of the steps by which the promised NiAsreyasa, or highest happiness, is to be attained, namely by the successive annihilation of false knowledge, of faults, of activity, and, in consequence, of birth and suffering. When the last or suffering has been annihilated there follows ipso facto freedom, or blessedness (Apavarga), literally abstersion or purification. This pro- cess reminds us strongly of some of the links in the Pai/c&a Samuppada of the Buddhists. This is generally translated by Chain of Causation, and was meant to sum up the causes of existence or of misery, the twelve Nidanas. It really means origin resting on something else. The first step is Avidya or that cosmic Nescience which was so fully elabo- rated in the Vedanta-philosophy. According to the Bud- dhists there follow on Avidy& the Samkharas 1 , all the varieties 'of existence; on these Vigrvv ana, sensation ; on this Namanlpa, names and 'forms; on these the Shad&yatana, the six organs of perception. Then follow in succession Sparsa, contact, Vedan&, sensation, Trislma, desire, Upa- dana, attachment, Bhava, state of existence, Cr&ti, birth, (raramaraTia, decay and death, $oka, sorrow, Parideva, lamentation, DuAkha, suffering, Daurmanasya, grief, and Upaysisa, despair 2 . This chain of successive states proclaimed by Buddha has formed the subject of ever so many commentaries, none of which seems quite satisfactory. The chain of Gotaina is shorter than that of Gautama, but the general likeness can hardly be mistaken. Who was the earlier of the two, Gotama or Gautama, is still a contested question, but what- ever the age of our Sutras (the sixteen topics) may be, a Nyaya-philosophy existed clearly before the rise of Bud- dhism. Z. Praxnana. Gotama proceeds next to examine each of the sixteen topics. The first topic or Padartha is Pramarta, which is said to consist of four kinds, all being means or measures of know- 1 Cf. Garbe, SAwkhya-Philosophie, p. 269 seq. 2 Cf. Childers, s.v. INlnlRBNCE OR ANUMANA. 379 ledge. They are in the Ny&ya as in the Vaiseshika, (i) Pratyaksha, sense-perception ; (2) Anumana, inference ; (3) Upamana, comparison ; and (4) Sabda, word. Perception or Pratyaksha. 1. Perception (Pratyaksha) is explained as knowledge produced by actual contact between an organ of sense and its corresponding object, this object being supposed to be real. How a mere passive impression, supposing the con- tiguity of the organs of sense with outward objects had once been established, can be changed into a sensation or into a presentation (Vorstellung), or what used to be called a material idea, is a question not even asked by Gotama. Inference or Anumana. 2. Inference (Anumana), preceded by perception, is described as of three kinds, Purvavat, proceeding from what was before, i.e. account for the process by which we take a part for the whole. No one, for instance, has ever seen more than one side of the moon, yet taking it as a whole, and as a globe, we postulate and are convinced that there is another side also. The illustration given by Gotama to show that a tree is a whole, namely, because when we shake one branch of it, the whole tree trembles, may seem childish to us, but it is exactly in these simple and so-called childish thoughts that the true interest of ancient philo- sophy seerns to me to consist. Time Present, Fast, Future. The next problem that occupies Gotama is that of time of present, past, and future. The objector, and in this case, it seems, a very real objector, for it is the opinion of the Buddhists, denies that there is such a thing as present 394 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, time, because the moment we see a fruit falling from a tree, we see only that it has fallen or that it has still to fall, but never that it is falling. Here the answer is that past and future themselves would be impossible, if the present did not exist, and on the objector's admitting such a possibility. Gotama remarks that in that case perception and all that springs from it would be altogether impossible, because it can only depend on what is present. Upamana, Comparison Passing over what is said in this piace about the validity of inference, because we shall have to return to it hereafter, we find Gotama bent on establishing by the side of it, by the side of Anumana, his next instrument of knowledge, namely Upamana, analogy or comparison. And here Gotama seems in conflict with KaTiada who, as we shall see, declines to accept Upamana, comparison, as one of the independent authoritative evidences, or, at all events, as essentially different from Anumana, inference. We might feel tempted to conclude from this that Gotama must have been laier in time than Kaw/ada. But first of all, Kanada's name is not mentioned here nor that of his system, Vaiseshika; and secondly, we know that this question of the Prama/nas had been discussed again and again in every school of Indian philosophy, so that a mere reference to the subject cannot be used as determining the seniority either of the opponent or of the defender. All we can say is that, whenever we see Upamana appealed to as a means of valid knowledge, we know that we have to deal with followers of the Nyaya school ; but the Vaiseshika, though denying it an inde- pendent place among the Pram&?ms, would by no means reject it, if presented as a kind of Anumana. abda, the Word. We now come to the various kinds of verbal testimony. Testimony is said to be conveyed by words, and by a sen- tence, consisting of many words, conveying the meaning of each word in its relation to the other words. Though the meaning of words is admitted to be conventional, yet opinions differ because some consider such conventions to THE EIGHT PRAMA.YAS. 395 be eternal or divine, while others take them to be non- eternal or human. The chief authority for determining the meaning of a word is admitted to be the usage of trustworthy persons, but it is argued that as the highest authority is Brahman or God, and as the Veda is the word of Brahman, it follows that every word of the Veda possesses the highest authority. This, however, as we know, does not satisfy the Mimamsakas, who assign eternity to the /Sabda itself, the word or the sound of a word. In the examination of the validity of $abda or word, we find again the same question started as before, whether it deserves a place by itself, or whether it should not rather be treated as a kind of inference. Then, after Gotama has shown the difference between I know ' and * I infer, 5 between acceptance of the word of an authority (Apto- padesa) and reliance on an inference, he enters on new problems such as the association of sense with sound, a question which is intimately connected with the question of what authority is due to the Veda as the Word par excellt/nce. Here we meet with a number of arguments in defence of the supreme authority of the Veda with which we are familiar from the Purva-Mimamsa, but which again, though clearly referring to it is added, be classed either under Word, like written letters, or under Anumana. The Prama^as seem to have formed a subject of prominent interest to the Nyaya philosophers ; in modern times they have absorbed the whole of Nyaya. We are told that Nagareing evanescent as soon as they have been pronounced, ;ve are asked to admit a Sphotfa, and to accept the first etters, as revealing the invisible Sphotfa, whereas the following letters serve only to make that Sphotfa more and more manifest and explicit. Words express the Summum Genus. After having thus in his own way established the theory of a Sphoia for every word, our philosophical grammarian lakes another step, trying to prove that the meaning of all words is ultimately that summum genus (Satta), namely >ure existence, the characteristic of which is consciousness )f the supreme reality. And lest it should be thought ihat in that case all words would mean one and the same ihing, namely Brahman or being, it is remarked that in one sense this is really so ; but that, as a crystal is coloured by its surroundings, Brahman, when connected with different things and severally identified with each, stands after- wards for different species, such as cow, horse, &c., these 3eing first of all ' existence ' (Satta) or the highest genus, as found in individuals, and then only what they are in ihis phenomenal world. In support of this another passage of BhartoiharFs is quoted : .' Existence being divided, a$ :ound in cows, &c,, is called this or that species by means of its connection with different objects, and on it all words depend. This they call the meaning of the stem, and the meaning of the root. This is existence, this is the great Aim an (or Brahman), expressed by affixes such as Tva, Tal, &c., which form abstract nouns, such as Ga-tva, cow-hood, &c. For existence, as the summum genus , is found in all things, in cows, horses, &c., and therefore all words, expres- sive of definite meanings, rest ultimately on the swrn/rriwn genus, existence, differentiated by various thoughts or words, such as cows, horses, &c., in which it resides. If the stem- word, the. Pratipadika, expresses existence, the root ex- presses Bhava, a state, or, as others say, Kriya, action/ . This will remind us of^many of the speculations of Greek as well as medieval logicians ; and tt is Exactly what my 406 -INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. late friend Noire tried to establish, that all words originally expressed action, to which I added the amendment that they expressed either an action or a status. If this true kernel of every word is Jby Hindu philosophers called the Great Atman (Mahan Atma). and Satta, the summum genus, we must remember that, according to the Vedanta, Brahman is the true substance of everything. This is stated again by Bhartrihari : ' The true reality is known under its illusory forms, by words under untrue disguises; the true reality is named (for a time), like the house of Devadatta, so called for a' vanishing reason (that is, only so long as Devadatta is the possessor of the house) ; but by the word house, pure househood l only is expressed/ Words expressive of Genera or Individuals V But while the meaning of all words is -thus admitted to be Brahman, we meet with two schools, the one of Vagrapyayana, maintaining that our ordinary words mean a genus, the other, of Vyadi, who holds that they mear: indi- vidual things. PaTiini holds both views as true in grammar, for in one place, I, 2, 58, he shows that * a Brahman 5 may mean many Brahmans,. as when we say, that a Brahman is to be honoured ; in another, I, 2, 64, he states that the plural Riimas means always Rama, Rama and Ramd, i.e, so many single Ramas. All Words mean rr> &\ The idea that all words in the end mean Brahman, the one Supreme Being, was necessitated by the very character of ijhe Vedanta-philosophy, which admits of "no duality except as the result of nescience. Hence it is said : The Supreme Being is the thing denoted by all words, arid it is identical with the word; but the relation of the two, while they are ultimately identical, varies as it does in the case of the, two Atmans, the Paramatman and the (?ivatman, the highest or universal, and the living or individual soul, the difference between the two being due to Avidya or i 1 Read Grihatvam instead of Gnhitam ? ALL WOliDS MEAN TO ov. i 407 temporary nescience. As early as the M&itraya?ia Upa- nishad we meet with verses to the same effect, and of an earlier date than itself, such as (VI, 32), ' Two Branmans have to he meditated on, the Word and the Non-word, and by the Word alone is the Non-word revealed/ In this way the grammatical philosophers endeavoured to prove that grammar or exposition of words, as it was called by Fata;? grail ($abd&nusasaiia), is, like every other system of philosophy, 'the means of final beatitude, the door of emancipation, the medicine of the diseases of language, the purifier of all sciences, the science of sciences ; it is the first rung on the ladder that leads up to final bliss, and the straight royal road among all the roads that lead to emancipation/ This may be accepted as representing the views, if not of Pa/mni himself, at least of his followers ; and I must say that if his explanation of a word as a number of letters ending in a suffix had been accepted, there would have been no necessity for the admission of a Sphoa. It was evidently not seen by the inventors of this Sphotfa that letters have no independent existence at all, and can be considered only as the result of a scientific analysis, and that words existed long before even the idea of letters had been formed. Letters, by themselves, have no raison d'etre. Sphota is in fact the word before it had been analysed into letters, the-- breaking forth of a whole and undivided utterance, such as Go, 'cow/ conveying a mean- ing which does not depend on any single letter nor on any combination of them. Though from our point of view the idea of such a Sphotfa may -seem unnecessary, we cannot help admiring the ingenuity of the ancient philosophers of India in inventing such a term, and in seeing difficulties which never attracted the attention of European philo- sophers. For it is perfectly true that the letters, ^is such, have no reality and no power, and that every word is something different from its letters, something undivided and indivisible. In such a word as V&&, Vox, we have not a combination of three letters, v, a, k, which would be nothing, but we have an indivisible explosion, expressive of its meaning in its undivided form only, and this maybe 4.68 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. raised to the s'atus of a word by means of a grammatical suffix which, as we should say, makes an organised whole of it. All this is true and recognised now by all students of the Science of Language, though never even suspected by the philosophers of other countries. Still more important is the idea that all words originally meant Brahman or TO 6v, and receive their special meaning from their relation to the genera or logoi in the mind of Brahman, as creative types. Words are not names of in- dividuals, but always of classes or genera, and as genera they are eternal. These logoi existed before the creation of the worlfl, nay, rendered that creation possible. This is the much-despised Neo-platonic philosophy, the basis of the Christian theory of creation ; and that we should find it so fully elaborated in the ancient world of India is surely a surprise, and, I should add, a welcome surprise. And can we suppose that ideas which, in Greece, required so many evolutions of thought till they reached the point which they reached in Alexandria, and afterwards in Palestine, should have sprung up in India suddenly or, as it were, casually? Do we not rather see clearly here also how long and how continuous a development of thought must have taken place south of the Himalayas before such fruits could have ripened ? Would any Greek scholar dare to say that all this was borrowed from Greece ? Would any Sanskrit scholar be so intrepid as to hint that the Greeks might possibly have learnt their Logos from the Vedic Va/c ? Even if we do not accept the last results of this Indian line of thought, which ended w\ere Greek philosophy ended, and where Christian philosophy began, nay even if we should put aside as unintelligible the beginning words of the fourth Gospel, * In the beginning was the Word/ we can at least admire the struggle which led up to this view of the world, and tried to establish the truth that there is a Logos, thought, that there is Rhyme and Reason in the world, and that the whole universe is full of Brahman, the Eternal and the Divine, not visible to the human eye, though visible to the human mind. That mind, according to Indian philosophy, has its true being in the Divine Mind, in which it lives and moves, in which alone it has its ALL WORDS MEAN TO 6V 409 true Self or Atman, which Atman is Brahman. To have mounted to such heights, even if we have to descend again frightened and giddy, must have strengthened the muscles of human reason, and will remain in our memory as a sight never to be forgotten, even in the lower spheres in which we have to move in our daily life and amidst our daily duties. Speaking for myself, I am bound to say that I have felt an acquaintance with the general spirit of Indian philosophy as a blessing from my very youth, being strengthened by it against all the antinomies of being and thinking, and nerved in all the encounters with the scep- ticism and materialism of our own ephemeral philosophy. It is easy, no doubt, to discover blemishes in the form and style of Indian philosophy, I mean chiefly the Vedanta' and to cite expressions which at first sight seem absurd. But there are such blemishes and such absurdities in all philosophies, even in the most modern. Many people have smiled at the Platonic ideas, at the atoms of Democritus, or at the location of the soul in the pineal gland or in certain parts of the brain ; yet all this belongs to the history of philosophy, and had its right place in it at the right time. What the historian of philosophy has to do is first of all to try to understand the thoughts of great philosophers, then to winnow what is permanent from what is temporary, and to discover, if possible, the vein of gold that runs through the quartz, to keep the gold, and to sweep away the rubbish. Why not do the same for Indian philosophy ? Why not try to bring it near to us, however far removed from it we may seem at first sight. In all other countries philosophy has railed at religion and religion has railed at philosophy. In India alone the two have always worked together harmoniously, religion deriving its freedom from philosophy, philosophy gaining its spirituality from re- ligion. Is not that something to make us think, and to remind us of the often-repeated words of Terence, Humani nihtt a me alienum puto ? A rich kernel is often covered by a rough skin, and true wisdom may be hiding where we least expect it, 4IO INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. Ved&nta on Sphofa. We have now to see what the other systems of philo- sophy have to say on this subject, for it is quite clear that the idea of a Sphoa, though known to them, was not ac- cepted by all. oflCmkara, as representing the Vedanta-philo- sophy, is entirely opposed to the admission of a Sphoa. He fully admits that earth and all the rest were created according to the words earth, &c., which were present to the mind of the Creator, but he asks, how were these words present ? Beginning as usual with the Purvapakshin l or opponent, he produces as arguments in favour of the admis- sion of a Sphotfa, that the letters cannot convey the meaning, because as soon as they are pronounced they perish, because they differ according to the pronunciation of each speaker, because they possess neither singly nor collectively any significative power, because not even the last letter with the impression left by the preceding letter in our memory, would convey to us the sense of a word. Hence something different from the letters must be admitted, the Sphoa, the outburst of the whole word, presenting itself all at once as the object of our mental act of apprehension. That Sphoa is what is eternal, different therefore from perishable and changeable letters, and it is that Sphoa from which what- ever is denoted by it was produced in creation, an$ which _in conversation conveys to others what is in our own rpind, but always clothed in sound. $amkara himself, however, considers such an admission of a Sphotfa entirely unnecessary, and, in order to prove this, he goes back and calls to his aid an old Vedantist, Upavarsha, whom he refers to elsewhere also (III, 3, 53) 2 . This Upavarsha argues that the letters by themselves con- stitute the word, because though they perish as fast as they are pronounced, they are always recognised again as the same letters, not only as belonging to the same class, but 1 Ved. Sutras i, 3, 28. This is one of the cases where the Piirvapaksha, the opponent's view, has boon mistaken for Samkara's own final opinion, or for the Siddhanta. 8 Here Samkara charges oauarasvamin, the famous commentator on the Purva-Mimaw&a, I, I T 5, with having borrowed an argument from Badarayana. VEDANTA ON SPHO^A. 411 as actually the same. Thus when the word cow is pro- nounced twice, we do not think that two words have been pronounced, but that the same word has been pronounced twice. And though two individuals may, no doubt, pro- nounce the same word differently, such differences are due to the organs of pronunciation, and not to the intrinsic nature of the letters. He holds that the apprehension of difference depends on external factors, but that their recog- nition is due only to the intrinsic nature of the letters. The sound which enters the ear (Dhvani) may be different, strong or weak, high or low, but the letters through all this are recognised as the same. And if it be said that the letters of a word, being several, cannot form the object of one mental act, this is not so, because the ideas which we have of a row, or a wood, or an army, show that things which comprise several unities can become objects of one and the same act of cognition. And if it be asked why groups of letters such as Pika and Kapi should convey different meanings, viz. cuckoo and ape, we have only to look at a number of ants, which as long as they move one after another in a certain order, convey the idea of a row, but cease to do so if they are scattered about at random, Without adducing further arguments, /Samkara in the end maintains that the admission of a Sphoa is unneces- sary, and that it is simpler to accept the letters of a word as having entered into a permanent connection with a de- finite sense, and as always presenting themselves in a definite order to our understanding, which, after apprehending the several letters, finally comprehends the entire aggregate as conveying a definite sense. We never perceive a Sphotfa, he argues, and if the letters are supposed to manifest the Sphoa, the Sphofo in turn would have to manifest the sense. It would even be preferable to admit that letters form a genus, and as such are eternal, but in either case we should gain nothing by the Sphoa that we could not have without it, by the admission of eternal words from which all non-eternal things, such as gods, cows, and horses, originated. Hence we see that, though the theory of the Sphotfa is rejected by the Vedanta, the eternal character of the words is strenuously retained, being considered essential, 412 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. as it would seem, in order to maintain the identity of Brahman and the Word, and the creation of the world by Brahman in accordance with the eternal words. Yoga and Sflwwkhya on 8phoa. The Yoga-philosophy accepted the theory of the Sphoa, nay it has been supposed to have first originated it J , for, according to the commentary, it was against the Yoga philosophers, rather than against the Mim&msa, that Kapila's objections concerning the SphoZa were directed. What Kapila says about Sphoa i&of much the same char- acter as what he had said about Isvara, the Lord, namely that its existence cannot be proved, not that it does not exist. If Sphotfa, he says, is meant for the group of letters forming a .word, then why not be satisfied with this, and simply speak of a word (Pada), as manifesting its sense ? Why invent something which has never been perceived, and which exists as little apart from the letters as a forest exists apart from the trees, what is in fact entirely gratuitous (V,57). Nor are the letters, from Kapila's point of view, eternal (V, 58), because, as Badaraya^a also remarked, we can wit- ness their production ; and our being able to recognise them as the same, proves no more than their belonging to one and the same genus, but not their being eternal. It is curious to* observe the elaborateness with which what seems to us a purely grammatical question is dis- cussed in the various schools of Indian philosophy. The Sphotfa, however, is to Indian thinkers not merely a gram- matical problem ; it is distantly connected with the question of the eternity of the Veda. This eternity is denied by Kapila (Samkhya V, 46) because the Vedas speak of them- selves as having been produced in such passages as : ' He became heated, and from him, thus heated, the three Vedas were produced.' Eternity of the Veda can therefore, ac- cording to Kapila, mean no more than an unbeginning and unbroken continuity, so that even at the beginning of a new creation the order of words in the Veda remains the same as before. But if, as Nyaya and Vaiseshika maintain, this 1 Garbe. S&wkhya-Philosophie, p. 1 1 1 u. NYYA ON SPHO^A. 413 Veda was the work of a personal being, such as Isvara, this is declared impossible by Kapila, because, as he holds, such an Isvara has never been proved to exist. For he holds that the Lord or Isvara could only have been either a liberated or an unliberated Purusha. Now a liberated Purusha, such as Vishwa for instance, could not have composed this enor- mous Veda, because he is free from all desires, nor could an active, non-liberated Purusha have been the author, because he would not have possessed the omniscience required for such a work. But we must not conclude that, because we know of no possible personal author, therefore the Veda is eternal, in the same way as germs and sprouts. What is called the work of a personal being always presupposes a corporeal person, and it presupposes a will. We should not call the mere breathing of a person in sleep, a personal work. But the Vedas, as we read, rise spontaneously like an exhalation from the Highest Being, not by any effort of will, but by some miraculous virtue. It must not be supposed that the words of the Veda are manifested, like the notes of birds, without any purpose or meaning. No, they are the means of right knowledge, and their innate power is proved by the wonderful effects which are produced, for instance, by medical formulas taken from the Ayur-veda. This is the same argument which .was used in the Nyaya-Sutras II, 68, as a tangible and irrefutable proof of the efficiency of the Vedas. Here all would depend on the experimental proof 3 and this the Hindus, ancient or modern, would find it diffi- cult to supply ; but if tiie Hindus were satisfied, we have no reason to find fault. Hyfcya on Sphofe. If now we turn to the Nyaya-philosophy we find that Gotarna also denies the eternity of sound, because, it is argued, we can see that it has a beginning or cause, because it is an object of sense-perception, and because it is known to be factitious. Besides, if sound were eternal, we should be able to perceive it always, even before it is uttered, there being no known barrier between the ether and our ear (II, 3, 86). This ethereal substratum of sound is, no doubt, 414 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. intangible (II, 3, 104), but it is nevertheless a something perceptible by one of our senses, that of hearing, and hence it must be non-eternal. The true eternity of the Vedas consists, according to Gotama, in the unbroken continuity of their tradition, study, and employment, both in the Man- vantaras and Yugas which are past and those that are still to come, whilst their authority depends on the authority of the most competent persons. This is the same with secular words \ This; last admission would of course be strongly resisted and resented by Vedanta philosophers, but it shows at all events the freedom with which all Indian philo- sophers were allowed to handle the ancient Sacred Books of the country. on Splio/a. The Vaiseshikas lastly dp not differ much from the Naiyayikas as to whether the Veda is eternal or not, is authoritative or not, but they follow their own way of reasoning. The very last Sutra of the Vaiseshika-Sastra, X, z, 9, says: *It A has been declared that authoritativeness belongs to the Amnaya (Veda) because it is uttered by Him ' ; and this declaration is i ? ound likewise in the third Sfttra of the first book to which the final Sutra refers. But though this Sfttra is given -twice, there attaches some uncertainty to its meaning, because, as pointed out by the native commentators, the. words ' because uttered by Him/ may also be translated by /because it declares it/ i.e. 'be- cause it teaches duty (Dharma).' But in either case there are objections, the same as those with which we are familiar from the Purvapaksha in the Vedanta and Mmiiimsaka- Sfttras, such as self-contradictoririess, tautology, and the rest discovered by some critics in the text of the Vedas. Thereupon the eternal character, too, of the Veda is called in question, and whoever its author may have been, whether human or divine, it is doubted whether he can justly claim any authority. In answer to this sweeping condemnation the Vaiseshika points out VI, i, J, ' that at all events there is in the Veda na's Commentary . 115. INDRIYAS, SENSES. 415 a construction of sentences consequent upon intelligence/ or as we should say, the Veda must at least be admitted to be the work of a rational author, and not of an author of limited intelligence, because no merely rational author could propound such a rule as * He who desires paradise, should sacrifice/ Such matters could not be known in their causes and effects to men of limited knowledge like our- selves. Whatever we may think of this -argument, it shoves at all events the state of mind of the earliest defenders of revelation. They argued that, because the author must at least be admitted to 'have been a rational being, he could not possibly have declared things that are beyond the knowledge of ordinary rational beings, such as the rewards of sacrifices in another world, and other matters beyond the ken of experience. The Vaiseshikas admitted a persona] author of the Veda, an tsvara, but this by no means in- volved the eternity of the Veda. With the Vaiseshikcis, also, the eternity of the Veda meant no more than its uninterrupted tradition (Sarnpradaya), but some further supports to its authority were found in the fact that. besides being the work of a rational being, in this case of fsvara, the Lord, it had been accepted as the highest authority by a long line of the great or greatest men who themselves might safely be regarded, if not as infallible, at least a&, trust worthy and authoritative. Prameyas, Objects of Hiaowlectg-e. If now, after an examination of the various opinions entertained by the Nyaya and other Hindu philosophers of the significative power of words, we return to the SMras of Gotama, we find that, in his third book, he is chiefly concerned with the Prameyas. that is, the objects of know- ledge, as established by the Prarna/nas ; and the first ques- tion that meets us is whether the senses or Indriyas, the instruments of objective knowledge, should be treated as different from the Atman, the Self, or not. Indriyas, Gotama holds that they are different from the Atman ; and in order to prove this, he argues, that if each sense 41 6 INIJIAN PHILOSOPHY. could perceive by itself, each sense would perceive its own object only, the ear sound, the eye colour, the skin warmth, &c.; and that therefore what perceives all these impres- sions together, at the same time and in the same object, must^be something different from the several senses, namely the Atman, or, according to other systems, the Manas or mind. arlra, Body. Next follows the question whether the body is the same as the Atman, a question which would never occur to a Vedantist. But Gotama asks it and solves it in his own way. It cannot be, he says, because, when the body has once been destroyed by being burnt, the consequences of good and evil deeds would cease to pursue the Self through an endless series of births and rebirths. A number of similar objections and answers follow, all showing how much this question had occupied the thoughts of the Nyaya philosophers. Some of them suggest difficul- ties which betray a very low state of philosophical reason- ing, while other difficulties are such that even in our own time they have not ceased to perplex minute philosophers. We meet with the question why, with the dual organ of vision, there is no duality of perception ; why, if memory is supposed to be a quality or mode of the Self, mere remembrance of an acid substance can ma>ke our mouth water. After these questions have been, if not solved, at least carefully considered, Gotama goes on to show that if the body be not Atman, neither can Manas, mind, be con- ceived as the Atman. Manas, Mind. The Self is the kriower, while the mind or Manas is only the instrument (Karar^a) of knowledge by which attention is fixed on one thing at a time. The Self is eternal, not of this life only, without beginning and therefore without end. And here a curious argument is brought in, different from the usual Indian arguments in support of our previous existence, to show that our Self does not begin with our birth on earth, because, as lie says, the smile of a new-born child can only arise from memory of a previous experience. MANAS, MIND. 417 . White our modern psycho-physiologists vouia probably see in the smiles or the cries of a new-born child a reflex action of the muscles, our Indian objector declares that such movements are to be considered as no more than the open- ing and closing of a lotus-flower. And when this view has been silenced by the remark that a child does not consist of the five elements only, is not in fact, as we should say a mere vegetable, a new argument of the same character ie adduced, namely the child's readiness to suck, which can only be accounted for, they say, by the child having, in a former life, acquired a desire for milk. When this again has been rejected as no arguments because we see that iron also moves towards a magnet, Gotarna answers once more that a child cannot be treated like a piece of iron. And when, as a last resource, desire in general, as manifested by a child, is appealed to as showing a child's previous existence, and when this also has once more been answered by the remark that a child, like every other substance, must be possessed of qualities, Gotama finally dismisses all these objectors by maintaining that desires are not simply qualities, but can arise from experience and previous impressions (Sa7>ikalpa) only. The consideration of the body and of the substances of which it consists, whether of earth only, or of three elements, earth, water and fire, or of four, earth, water, fire and air, or of five, because it displays 'the qualities of the five, is naturally of small interest in our time. The i final solution only deserves our attention, in so far as it clearly shows that the Nyaya also recognised in some cases the authority of the Veda as supreme, by stating that the body is made of earth, and why? '/Srutipr&rn&^yat,' ' because scripture says so/ What follows, the discussion of sight or of the visual ray proceeding from the eye, and the question whether we possess one general sense only, or many, may contain curious suggestions for the psycho-physiologist ; but there is little of what we mean by really philosophic matter in ii. The qualities assigned to the objects of perception are not very different from what they are supposed to be in the other systems of philosophy, and they may be passed 27 41 8 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. by here ail the more because they will have to be 1 con- sidered more fully when we come to examine the Vaiseshika system. More interesting is the discussion which occupies the rest of the third book. It is chiefly concerned with the nature of Self (Atman), the mind (Manas), the difference between the two, and their relation to knowledge. Here we should remember that, according to I, 15, Buddhi (understanding), Upalabdhi (apprehension), and (?/1&na (knowledge) are used synonymously. Though there are many manifestations of Manas,, such as memory, inference, verbal testimony, doubt, imagination, dreaming, cognition, guessing, feeling of] pleasure, desire, and all the rest, yet its distinguishing feature, we are told, is what we should call attention, or as Gotama explains it (I, 16), * the preventing of knowledge arising altogether.' This is declared to be due to attention, and in many cases this would be the best rendering of Manas. Manas is therefore often called the doorkeeper, preventing sensations from rushing in promiscuously and all at once. If therefore we translate Manas by mind, we must always remember its technical meaning in Indian philosophy, and its being originally different from Buddhi, understanding, which might often be rendered by light or the internal light that changes dark and dull impressions into clear and bright sensations, perceptions, and knowledge in general, or by understanding, at least so far as it enables us to transform and understand the dull impressions of the ' senses. The difference between the philosophical nomenclatures in English and Sanskrit for the Manas and its various, functions is so great that a translation is almost impossible, and I am by no means satisfied with my own. It should also be remembered that the same Sanskrit term has often: very different meanings in different systems of philosophy. The Buddhi of the Ny&ya philosophers, for instance, is totally different from the Buddhi of the Sarakhyas. Their Buddhi is eternal, while the Buddhi of Gotama is distinctly declared to be non-eternal. The Buddhi of the Samkhya is a cosmic principle independent of the Self, and meant to j account for the existence of the light of reason in the whole ! MEMORY, 419 universe; while in the Nyaya-philosophy it signifies the subjective activity of thought in the acquisition of know- ledge, or in the lighting up and appropriating of the inert impressions received by the senses. This knowledge can come to an end and vanish by f orgetfulness, while an eternal essence, like the Buddhi of the Samkhyas, though it may be ignored, can never be destroyed. Atman. In answering the question, What is knowledge, Gotama declares in this place quite clearly that real knowledge belongs to the Atman only, the Self or the soul. It cannot belong to the senses and their objects (Indriyartha), because knowledge abides even when the senses and what they perceive have been suppressed. Nor does knowledge belong to the Manas, which is but the instrument of know- ledge, but it arises from the conjunction of Atman (Self) with Manas (attention), and on the other side of Manas with Indriyas (senses). Manas is the instrument, and the wielder of that instrument, like the wielder of an axe, must be some one different from it ; this, according to the Ny&ya, can only be the Self who in the end knows, who remembers, who feels pain and pleasure, who desires and acts. Memory. Memory, Smriti, has not received from Indian philo- sophers the attention which it deserves. If it is treated as a means of knowledge, it falls under Anubhava, which is either immediate or mediate, and then called Smriti. Every Anubhava is supposed to leave an impression or modifica- tion of the mind, which is capable of being revived. There is another manifestation of memory in the act of remember- ing or recognising, as when on seeing a man we say, This is he, or This is Devadatta. Here we have Anubhava, know- ledge of this, joined with something else, namely he or Devadatta, a revived Samskara, impression, or Sm?vti. The subject of memory is more fully treated in III, 113, and the various associations which awaken memory are enumerated as follows : 420 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. 1. Attention to an object perceived ; 2. Connection, as when the word Pram&Tia, p/oof, recalls ^rameya, what has to be proved ; 3. Repetition, as when crie has learned a number of thing? together, one calls up the other ; 4. A sign, as when a thing recalls its sine qua non ; ,5. A mark, as when a standard reminds one of its bearer; 6. Likeneas, as when one body recalls a similar bocly , 7. Possession, as when a property reminds us of its owner : 8. Belonging:, as when royal attendants remind us of the king; 9. Relation, as when a disciple reminds us of the teacher, or kine of a bull ; 10. Succession, as when the pounding 01 rice reminds one of sprinkling ; j i. Absence, as of a wife ; 12. Fellow- workers, as when one disciple reminds us of the co-disciples ; 13. Opposition, as when the ichneumon recalls the snake ; 14. Pre-eminence, as when investiture with the sacred string recalls the principal agent, the Guru or teacher ; 15. Receiving, as when a gift reminds one of the giver; 16. Covering, as when a sword reminds one of the sheath ; 1 7. Pleasure and pain, eacK of which recalls the occasioner of it; 1 8. Desire and aversion, reminding us of their causes ; 19. Fear, reminding us of what is feared, such as death; 20. Want, which makes us think of those who can supply our wants ; 21. Motion, as when a shaking branch reminds us of the wind; 22. Affection, reminding us of a son, &c. ; 23. Merit and Demerit, which make us reflect on joys and sorrows of a former life. Such lists are very characteristic of Hindu philosophy, and they show at the same time that it is a mistake to MORE PRAMEYAS. 421 ascribe them exclusively to the Samk&ya-philosophy. Though they do not add much to our knowledge of the fundamental tenets of 'Indian philosophy, they show once more how much thought had been spent in the elaboration of mere details ; and this, as we are tolfl in this case by the commentator himself, chiefly in order to stir up the thoughts of the learners, /Sishyavyutpadanaya, to indepen- dent activity. Knowledge not Sternal. The important point, however, which Gotama wishes to establish is this, that knowledge, though belonging to the eternal Self, is not in itself eternal, but vanishes like any other act. He also guards against the supposition that as we seem to take in more than one sensation at the same time, as in eating a cake full of different kinds of sweets, we ought to admit more than one Manas ; and he explains that this simultaneousness of perception is apparent only, just as the fiery circle is when we whirl a firebrand with grea f . rapidity, or as we imagine that a number of palm- leaves are pierced by a pin at one blow, and not in succession, one after the other. Lastly, he states that the Manas is Anu, infinitely small, or, as we should say, an atom. More Prameyas. While the third book 'was occupied with the first six of the Prameyas, or objects to be known and proved, including the whole apparatus of knowledge, such as Atman, Self or soul, Indriyas, senses, Manas, mind, central sensorium, Buddhi, understanding, and $arira, body, and therefore gave rise to some important questions not only of meta- )hysics, but of psychology also, the fourth book which is levoted to the remaining six Prameyas, such as (7) Pra- vritti (activity), (8) Dosha (faults), (9) Pretyabhava (trans- Inrigration), (10) Phala (rewards), (n) DuAkha (pain), and J(i2) Apavarga (final beatitude), is naturally of a more .(practical character, and less attractive to the student of ithe problems of being and thinking. Some questions, how- jever, are treated in it* which cannot well be passed over, if 422 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. we wish to give a full insight into the whole character, and the practical bearing of the Nyaya-philosophy. Though this philosophy is supposed to represent Indian logic only, we have already seen enough of it to know that it included almost every question within the sphere of philosophy and religion, and that its chief object was the same as that of all the other systems of Indian philosophy, namely salvation. Life after Death. One of the seven interesting subjects treated here is Pretyabhava, literally existence after having departed this life, and this is proved in a very short way. As the Self has been proved to be eternal, Gotama says (IV, 10) it follows that it will exist after what is called death. Some of the objections made to this tenet are easily disposed of, but nothing is said to establish what is meant by trans- migration, that is being born again in another world as either a human or as some other animal being, or even as a plant. Existence of Deity. Another important subject, if it is not passed over alto- gether, is treated by Gotama, as it was by Kapila, inci- dentally only, I mean the existence of a Deity. It comes in when a problem of the Buddhists is under discussion . namely, whether the world came out of nothing, and whether the manifestation of anything presupposes the destruction of its cause. This is illustrated by the f act- that the seed has to perish before the flower can appear. But Gotama strongly denies this, and reminds the opponent that if the seed were really destroyed by being pounded or burnt, the flower would never appear. Nor could it be said that the flower, if it had not existed previously, destroyed the seed, while, if it had, it would have owed its existence to the simple destruction of the seed. Therefore, he continues, as nothing can be produced from nothing, nor from an annihilated something, like a seed, the world also cannot have sprung from nothingness, but requires the admission of an Lsvara, the Lord, as its real cause. And CAUSE AND EFFECT. 423 this admission of an tsvara, even though in the capacity of a governor rather than of a maker of the world, is con- firmed by what was evidently considered by Gotama as a firmly established truth, namely, that every act of man invariably produces its result, though not by itself, but under the superintendence of some one, that is, of Isvara. We then meet with a new argument, different from that of the Mim&'msakas, namely that, if work done continued to work- entirely by itself, the fact that some good or evil deeds of men do not seem to receive their reward would remain unaccounted for. This is certainly a curious way of proving tl 3 existence of God by the very argument which has generally been employed by those who want to orove His non-existence. Gotarna's real ^object, however, is to refute the Buddhist theory of vacuity (/Sftnya), or of Nothing being the cause of the world, and afterwards to disprove the idea that effects can ever be fortuitous. And as Gotama differs from Gautama in denying the origin of the world out of nothing, he also differs from the Samkhya philosophers, who hold that all things, as developed out of Prakriti, are real only so long as they are noticed by the Purusha. He holds, on the contrary, that some things are real and eternal, but others are not, because we actually see both their production and their destruction. If we were to doubt this, we should doubt what has been settled by the authority of all men, and there would be an end of all truth and untruth. This 1 is a novel kind of argument for an Indian philosopher to use, and shows that with all the boldness of their speculations they were not so entirely different from ourselves, and not entirely indifferent to the Securu8 judicat or bis terrarum. Cause and Effect. If, however, we call the Nyaya-philosophy theistic, we should always remember that such terms as theistic and atheistic are hardly applicable to Indian philosophy in the sense in which they are used by Christian theologians. With us atheistic implies the denial of a supreme and 1 SHrvalfukikapram&tva. 424 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, absolute Being , but we saw that even the so-called atneism of the Samkhya-philosophy does not amount to that. It is simply the denial of an tsvara, as an active and persopal creator and ruler of the world. And even such a personal God is not altogether denied by the Samkhyas ; they only deny that He can be proved to exist by human arguments, and it* He exists as such, tht>y hold that in the eyes of philosophers He would be but a phenomenal manifestation of the Godhead, liable to change, liable even to temporary disappearance at the end of each aeon, and to reappearance at the beginning of a new aeon. It is this kind of a divine being, a personal Isvara or Lord, that is taken for granted by the Nyaya philosophers, and, it may be added at once, by the Vaise- shika philosophers also ] . In the Tarka-Samgraha, for instance, it is distinctly stated that l the Atman or Self is twofold, the (rivatman (personal Self), and the Paramatman (the Highest Self)/ It must not be supposed, however, that Isvara, the omni- scient Lord, is Patamatman, which is one only, while the Crivatman is separate for each individual body, all-per- vading and eternal. Though Paramatman is Isvara, Isvara is not Paramatman, but a phenomenal manifestation of Paramatman only. The argument which we met with before is fully stated in Catania's Sutras, IV, 19-21. The actions of men, it is said, do not always produce an effect, Good actions do not always produce good results, nor bad action ,s bad results, as they ought, if every act continued to act (Karman). Hence there must be another power that modifies the continuous acting of acts, and that can be Isvara only. It is not denied thereby that human actions are required, and that no effects would take place without the working of human agents, only they are not the sole cause of what happens, but we require another power, an Isvara, to account for what would otherwise be irrational results of human actions. Baliantyne, Christianity contrasted with Hindu Philosophy, p. 12 : Muir, O. S. T., vol. iii, p. 133. EMANCIPATION. 425 Fhala, Stewards. We now come to the tenth of the Prameyas, Phala ; and here the same subject is treated once more, though from a different point of view. It is asked, how are effects, rewards or punishments, possible in another life ? As both good and evil works are done in this life, the cause, namely these works, would have ceased to exist long before their fruit Is to be gathered. This objection is met by an illus- tration taken from a tree which bears fruit long after it has ceased to be watered. The objector is not, however, satisfied with this, but, on the contrary, takes a bolder step, and denies that any effect either is or is not, at the same time. Gotama is not to be frightened by this apparently Buddhistic argument, but appeals again to what we should call the common-sense view of the matter, namely, that we actually see production and destruction before our very eyes. We can see every day that a cloth, before it has been woven, does not exist, for no weaver would say that the threads are the cloth, or the cloth the threads. And if it should be argued that the 'fruit pro- duced by a tree is different from the fruit of our acts, because there is no receptacle (Asraya) or, as we should say, no subject, this is met by the declaration that, in the case of good or bad acts, there is a permanent receptacle, namely the Self, which alone is capable of perceiving pain or joy in this or in any other state of existence. Emancipation After examining the meaning of pain, and expressing his conviction that everything, even pleasure, is full of pain, Gotarna ab last approaches the last subject, emancipation (Apavarga). He begins as usual with objections, such as that it is impossible in this life to pay all our moral debts, that certain sacrificial duties are enjoined as incumbent on us to the end of our lives, and that if it is said that a man is freed from these by old age, this does not imply that, even when he is no longer able to perform his daily duties, he should not perform certain duties, if in thought only. If, therefore, good works continue, there will be rewards 426 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. for them, in fact there will be paradise, though even this would really have to be looked upon as an obstacle to real emancipation. Nothing remains but a complete extinction of all desires, and this can be effected by knowledge of the truth only. Therefore knowledge of 'the truth or removal of all false notions, is the beginning and end of all philo- sophy, and of the Nyaya-philosophy in particular. The first step towards this is the cessation of Aha,mkara, here used in the sense of personal feelings, such as desire for a beautiful and aversion to a deformed object. Desire therefore has to be eradicated and aversion also ; but before he explains how this desire, w r hich arises from false appre- hension (Mithyagwaiia) can be eradicated, Gotama is carried back once more to a subject which had been discussed before, namely whether the objects of desire exist as wholes or as parts. And this leads him on to what is the distin- guishing doctrine both of the Nyaya and of the Vaiseshika- philosophies, namely the admission of Anus or atoms. If wholes are constantly divided and subdivided, we should in the end be landed in nihilism, but this is not to be. There cannot be annihilation because the A-nus or the smallest parts are realities (IV, 8-82), and, according to their very nature, cannot be further reduced or compressed out of being. Against this view of the existence of what we should call atoms, the usual arguments are then adduced, namely that ether (or space) is everywhere, and therefore in an atom also, and if an atom has figure or a without and a within, it is of necessity divisible. In reply, ether is said to be intangible, neither resistant nor obstructing, that is, neither occupying space against others, nor preventing others from occupying space ; and in the end an appeal is made to a recognised maxim of Hindu philosophy, that there must never be a regressio in infinity m,) as there would be in attempting to divide an atom. Knowledge of Ideas, not of Things. And now the opponent, again, it would seem, a E'iddhist, makes a still bolder sweep by denying the existence of any external things. All we have is knowledge, he says, not things; nothing different from our knowledge, or inde- SYLLOGISM. 427 pendent of our knowledge, can exist for us. Gotama objects to this (Vidyamatra) doctrine, first of all because, if it were impossible to prove the existence of any external things, it would be equally impossible to prove their non- existence. And if an appeal were made to dreams, or visions produced by a mirage, or by jugglery, it should be remembered that dreams also, like remembrances, presup- pose previous perception of things ; and that even in mis- taking we mistake something, so that false knowledge can always be removed by true knowledge. After granting that, one more question arises, how that true knowledge, if once gained, is to be preserved, because we saw that knowledge is not eternal, but vanishes. And here the Nyaya suddenly calls the Yoga to its aid, and teaches that Samadhi or intense meditation will prove a safe preserva- tive of knowledge, in spite of all disturbances from without, while the Nyaya-philosophy retains its own peculiar use- fulness as' employed in the defence of truth against all comers, in which case even such arts as wrangling and cavilling may prove of service. This may seem a very humble view to take with regard to a system of philosophy which at the very outset promised to its students final beatitude as the highest reward. But considering the activity of philosophical speculation, of which- we have had so many indications in the ancient as well asjn the modern history of India, we can well under- stand that philosophers, skilled in all the arts and artifices of reasoning, would secure for their system that high posi- tion which the Nyaya certainly held and still holds 1 among the recognised systems of orthodox philosophy. It would be useless to go once more over the topics from ?ati, futility, No. XIV, to No, XVI, Nigrahasthana, objectionable proceedings, which are fully treated in the fifth book. Syllogism. There is one subject, however, which requires some more special consideration, namely the Syllogism, or the Five Members, treated as VII. This has always excited the 1 Cowell, Report on the Toles 01 ^ uddea, 1867. 428 TtfDIAN PHILOSOPHY. special interest of European logicians on account of certain startling similarities which no doubt exist between it and the syllogism of Aristotle and the schoolman. But from a Hindu point of view this syllogism or even logic in general is by no means the chief object of the Nyaya- philosophy, nor is it its exclusive property. It has been tully discussed in the Vedanta and S&mkhya systems, and on<& more in the Vaiseshika ; but as it forms the pride of the Nyya, it will find its most appropriate place here l . As we saw colour mentioned as the distinguishing quality of light, we found knowledge put forward as the char- acteristic feature of Self. The Nyaya looks upon know- ledge as inseparably connected with the Self, though in the larger sense of being the cause of every conception that has found expression in language. Knowledge, according to the Nyaya, is either perception or remembrance. Percep- tion again is twofold, right or wrong. Right perception represents a thing such as it is, silver as silver. This is called truth, Prama. Wrong perception represents a thing as it is not, mother-of-pearl as silver. This right perception, according to the Nyaya-philosophy is, as we saw, of four kinds, sensuous, inferential, com- parative, and authoritative, and is produced by perception, by inference, by comparison, and by revealed authority. Here we are brought back to the Pramanas again which were discussed in the beginning, but among which one, Anumana or inference, receives here a more special treat- ment. We are thus obliged, in following the Sdtras, to go over some of the ground again. Different systems of philosophy differed, as we saw, in the number of Pram&ftas which they admit, according to what each considers the only trustworthy channels of knowledge. Pram&nas in different Philosophical Schools. One, Perception : .ATarv&kas. Two, Perception and inference: Vaiseshikas arid Buddhists. 1 See M. M., Appendix to Archbishop Thomson's Laws of Thought j also Die Theorie df-s indischeu Rationaliaten von den Erkenninissmitteln, von R. Gar be, 1888. PRAMAJ^AS IN DIFFERENT PHILOSOPHICAL SCHOOLS. 429 Three, Perception, inference, and word (revelation) Four, Perception, inference, revelation, and comparison Naiy&yikas. Five, Perception, inference, revelation, comparison, and presumption : Prabh&kara (a Mim&rasaka) Six, Perception, inference, revelation, comparison, pre- sumption, and not-being : MimUmsakas. Otners admit also Aitihya, tradition, Sambhava, equiva- lence, Keshth, gesture. After sensuous knowledge, which take? cognisance of substances, qualities, and actions, has been examined, the question arises, how can we know things which are not brought to us by the senses? How do we know, for instance, that there is fire which we cannot see in a moun- tain, or that a mountain is a volcano, when all that we do see is merely that the mountain smokes? We should remember that there were three kinds of Anum&na (Ny&ya- S&tras II, 37) called Pftrvavat, having the sign before, or as the ' cause, $eshavat, having the sign after or as the effect, and Srn&nyatodrisha, seen together. In the first cla-ss the sign of past rain was the swelling of rivers ; in the second the sign of coming rain was the ants carrying off their eggs ; in the third the sign of the motion of the sun was its being seen in different places. Knowledge of things unseen, acquired in these three ways, is called in- ferential knowledge (Anum&na), and in order to arrive at it, we are told that we must be in possession of what is called a Vy&pti. This, as we saw, was the most important word in an Indian syllogism. Literally it means pervasion. Vypta meanp pervaded ; Vy&pya, what must be pervaded ; Vy&paka, wjb^t pervades. This expression, to pervade, is used by logicians in the sense of invariable, inseparable or universal concomitance. Thus sea-water is always per- vaded by saltness, it is inseparable from it, and in this aense Vy&pya, what is to be pervaded, came to be used for whatJ we should call the middle term in a syllogism. Vy&pti, or invariable Concomitance, may sometimes be taken as a general rule, or even as a general law, in some cases it is simply the sine qud non. It is such a Vy&pti, 430 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. for instance, that smoke is pervaded by 01 invariably con- nected with fire, or, as the Hindus say, that smokiness is pervaded by fieriness, not, however, fieriness by smokiness. We arrive by induction at the Vyapti that wherever there is smoke, there is lire, but not that wherever there is fire, there is smoke. The latter Vy&pti in order to be true would require a condition or Upadhi, viz. that the firewood should be moist. If we once are in possession of a true Vy&pti as smokiness being pervaded by fieriness, we only require what is called groping or consideration (Paramarsa) in order to make the smoke, which we see rising from the mountain, a Paksha or member of our Vyapti, such as 'wherever there is smoke, there is fire.' The conclusion then follows that this mountain which shows smoke, must have fire. All this may sound very clumsy to European logicians, but it would have been easy enough to translate it into our own more technical language. We might easily clothe KaTiada in a Grecian garb and make him look almost" like Aristotle. Instead of saying that inferential knowledge arises from discovering in an object something which is always pervaded by something else, and that the pervading predicate is predicable of all things of which the pervaded predicate is, we might have said that our knowledge that b is P arises from discovering that S is M, and M iS P, or with Aristotle, 6 (rv\\oyi rptra) bctKwa-iv. What KaTiada call& one member of the pervasion, Paksha, e.g. the smoking mountain, might have been trans- lated by subject or terminus minor] what pervades, Vyapaka or Sadhya, e. g. fieriness, by predicate or terminus major; and what is to be pervaded, Vyapy a, i.e. smokiness, by terminus medius. But what should we have gained by this ? AH that is peculiar to Indian logic would have evaporated, and the remainder might have been taken for a clumsy imitation of Aristotle. Multa fiunt eadem, sed aliter, and it is this very thing, this aliter, that constitutes the principal charm of a comparative study of philosophy. Even such terms as syllogism or conclusion are incon- venient here, because they have with us an historical Colouring and may throw a false light on the subject. The ANUMANA FOR OTHERS. 43! Sanskrit Anumara is not exactly the Greek but it means measuring something by means of something else. This is done by what we may call syllogism, but what the Hindus describe as Paramarsa or groping or trying to find in an object something which can be measured by something else or what can become the member of a pervasion. This corresponds in fact to the looking for a terminus medius. In Kapila's system (1, 61) the principal object -of inference is said to be transcendent truth that is, truth which transcends the horizon of our senses. Things which cannot be seen with our eyes, are known by in- ference, as fire is, when what is seen is smoke only. Gotama therefore defines the result of inference (I, 101) as knowledge of the connected, that is, as arising from the perception of a connection or a law. But, again, the rela- tion of what pervades and what is pervaded is very different from what we should call the relative extension of two concepts. This will become more evident as we proceed. For the present we must remember that in the case before us the act of proving by means of Anurnana consists in our knowing that there is in the mountain something always pervaded by, or inseparable from something else, in our case, smoke always pervaded by fire, and that therefore the mountain, if it smokes, has fire. By this process we arrive at Anumiti, the result of Anumana, or inferential knowledge, that the mountain is a volcano. So much for the inference for ourselves. Next follows the inference for others. Annm&na for Others. What follows is taken from Annambha^a's Compendium. 'The act of concluding/ he says, 'is twofold, it being intended either for one's own benefit or for the benefit of others. The former is the means of arriving at knowledge for oneself, and the process is this. By repeated observa- tion, as in the case of kitchen hearths and the like, we are reminded of a rule (Vypti), such as that wherever we have seen smoke, we have seen fire. We now approach a mountain and wonder whether there may or may not be fire in it. We see the smoke, we remember the rule, and 432 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY, immediately perceive that the mountain itself is fierv This is the process when we reason for ourselves. But if we have to convince somebody else of whrt we, by inference, know to be true, the case is different We then start with the assertion, The mountain is fiery, We are asked, Why? and we answer, Because it smokes. We then give our reason, or the major premiss, that all that smokes is fiery, as you may see, for instance, on a kitchen hearth and the like. Now you perceive that the mountain does smoke, and hence you will admit that I was right when I said that the mountain is fiery. This is called the fivermembered form of exposition, and the five members are severally called *, (i) Assertion (Prati#/?H), the mountain has fire; (Q.) Reason (Hetu 2 ), because it has smoke , (3) Instance (Ud&harana or Nidarsana), look at the kitchen hearth, and remember the Vy&pti between smoke and fire ; (4) Application (Upanaya), and the mountain has smoke ; (5) Conclusion (Nigamana), therefore it has fire V In both cases the process of inference is the same, but the second is supposed to be more rhetorical, more per- suasive, and therefore more useful in controversy. What is called by Annambhafta the conclusion for oneself, corresponds totidem verbis to the first form of Aristotle's syllogism: All that smokes is fiery, The mountain smokes; Therefore the mountain is fiery. We must not forget, however, that whatever there is of formal Logic in these short extracts, has but one object with Gotama, that of describing knowledge as one of the qualities of the Self, and as this knowledge is not confined to sensuous perceptions, Gotama feit it incumbent on him to explain the nature and prove the legitimacy of the in- ferential kind of knowledge also It is not so much logic 1 ny&ya-Sutras I, 39. 8 Synonyms of Hetu are Apade** T.iwisa. Framana, and Karana. Vai*eshika-Sutras IX, a, 4. 3 The Vaiseshika terms are (i) Pratigrfta, (a) Apadea, (3) Nidarsana, (4) Anusawdhana, (5) Pratyamnaya. ANUMiNA FOR OTHERS. 433 as ii is noetic that interested KaTiada. He was clearly aware of the inseparability of inductive and deductive reasoning The formal logician, from the time of Aris- totle to our own, takes a purely technical interest in the machinery of the human mind, he collects, he arranges and analyses the functions of our reasoning faculties, as they fall under his observation. But the question which occupies Gotama is, How it is that we know any thing which we do not, nay which we cannot perceive by our senses, in fact, how we can justify inferential knowledge. From this point of view we can easily see that neither in- duction nor deduction, if taken by itself, would be sufficient for him. Deductive reasoning may in itself be most useful for forming Vyaptis, it may give a variety of different aspects to our knowledge, but it can never add to it. And if on one side Gotama cannot use deduction, because it teaches nothing new, he cannot on the other rely entirely on induction, because it cannot teach anything ceitain or unconditional. The only object of all knowledge, according to Gotama, is absolute truth or Prama. He knew as well as Aristotle that 7rayo>y?/ in order to prove the oXcos must be 6ta -navTav, and that this is impossible. Knowledge gained by epagogic reasoning is, strictly speaking, always tnl TO TTO'AV, and not what Gotama would call Prama. The conclusion, f. i., at which Aristotle arrives by way of induction, that animals with little bile are long-lived, might be called a Vyapti. He arrives at it by sa"ying that man, horse, and mule (C) are long-lived (A) ; man, horse, and mule (C) have little bile (B); therefore all animals with little bile are long-lived. Gotama does not differ much from this, but he would 3xpress himself in a different way. He would say, wher- ever we see the attribute of little oile, we also see the attribute of long life, s for instance in men, horses, mules, &c. But there he would not stop. He would value this Vyapti merely as a means of establishing a new rule ; he would use it as a means of deduction and say, ' Now we know that the elephant has little bile, therefore we know also that he is long-lived/ Or to use another instance, where Aristotle -says that all men are mortal. Kanada 28 * f 434 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. would say that humanity is pervaded by mortality, or that we have never seen humanity without mortality; and where Aristotle concludes that kings are mortal because they belong to the class of men, Gotama, if he argued for himself only, and not for others, would say that kinghood is pervaded by manhood and manhood by mortality, and therefore kings are mortal. I*' would be easy to bring objections against this kind of reasoning, and we shall see that Indian philosophers them-' selves have not been slow in bringing them forward, and likewise in answering them. One thing can be said in favour of the Indian method. If we go on accumulating instances to form an induction, if, as in the afore-men- tioned case, we add horses, mules, men, and the like, we approximate no doubt more and more to a general rule, but we never eliminate all real, much less all possible, exceptions. The Hindu, on the contrary, by saying, ' Wherever we have seen the attribute of little bile, we have observed long life/ or better still, ' We have never observed long life without the attribute of little bile/ and by then giving a number of mere instances, and these by w&y of illustration only, excludes the reality, though not the pos- sibility, of exceptions. He states, as a fact, that wherever the one has been, the other has been seen likewise, and thus throws the onus proba/ndi as to any case to the con- trary upon the other side. The Hindu knows the nature of induction quite well enough to say in the very words of European philosophers, that because in ninety-nine cases a Vystpti 1 or rule has happened to be true, it does not follow that it will be so in the hundredth case. If it can be proved, however, that there never has been an instance where smoke was seen without fire,' .the mutual inherence and inseparable connection of smoke and fire is more firmly established than it would be by any r umber of accumulated actual instances where the two have been seen together. The conditions (Upadhis) under which it is allowable to form a Vy&pti, that is to say, to form a universal rule, have greatly occupied the thoughts of Hindu philosophers. 1 'SatasaA sahaftaritayor api vyabhi&aropalabdheA.' Anumaiiiakhanda of Tattvafrint&mani/ ANUMANA FOB. OTHERS. 435 Volumes after volumes have Deen written on the subject, and though they may not throw any new light on the origin of universals, they furnish at all events a curious parallel to the endeavours of European philosophers in defence both of inductive and deductive thinking. It seems hardly time as yet to begin to criticise the in- ductive and the deductive methods as elaborated by Hindu philosophers. We must first know them more fully. Such objections as have hitherto been started were certainly not unknown to Gotarna and Kanada themselves. In accord- ance with their system of Purvapaksha and Uttarapaksha, every conceivable objection was started by them and care- fully analysed and answered. Thus it has been pointed out by European philosophers that the proposition that wherever there is smoke there is fire, would really lose its universal character 1 by the introduction of the instance, ' as on the kitchen hearth/ But the Hindu logicians also were perfectly aware of the fact that this instance is not essential to a syllogism. They look upon the instance simply as a helpful reminder for controversial purposes, as an illustration to assist the memory, not as an essential part of the process of the proof itself. It is meant to remind us that we must look out for a Vyapti between the .smoke which we see, and the fire which is implied, but not seen. It is therefore in rhetorical syllogisms or syllogisms for others only that the instance has its proper place. In Sfttra I, 35 Gotama says, * The third member or example is c some familiar case of the fact which, through its having a character which is invariably attended by that which is to be established, establishes (in conjunction with the reason) the existence of that character which is to be established/ It is Indian rhetoric therefore far more than Indian logic that is responsible for the introduction of this third member which Contains the objectionable instance; and rhetoric, though it is not logic, yet, as Whately says, is an offshoot of logic. 1 Ritter, History of Philosophy, IV, p. 365,, says that ' two members of Kanada's -argument are evidently superfluous, while, by the intro- duction of an example in the third, the universality of the conclusion is vitiated.' 436 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. The fact is that Gotama cares far more or the formation of a Vy&pti, pervasion, than for the manner in which it may serve hereafter as the basis of a syllogism, which must depend on the character of the . Vy&pti. A Vy&pti was considered as threefold in the school of Gotama, as Anvaya- vyatireki, Kevalanvayi, and Kevala-vyatireki. The first, the Anvaya-vyatireki, present and absent, is illustrated by such a case as, Where there is smoke, there is fire, and where firo is not, smoke is not. The second, or Ke\-al&n- vayi, i.e. present only, is illustrated by such a case as, Whatever is cognisable is nameable, where it is impossible to bring forward anything that is not cognisable. The third case, or Kevala-vyatireki, is illustrated by a case such as, Earth is different from the other elements, because it is odorous. Here we could not go on and say, all that is different from the other elements has odour, because the only case in point (Ud&haraTia) would again be earth. But we have to say, what is not different from the other elements is not odorous, as water (by itself). But this earth is not so, is not inodorous, and therefore it is not not-different from the other elements, but different from them, q.e.d. . Much attention has also been paid by Hindu philoso- phers to the working o the Upadhis or conditions assigned to a Vy&pti. Thus in the ordinary Vyapti that there is smoke in a mountain, because there is fire, the presence of wet fuel was an Upadhi, or indispensable condition. This Up&dhi pervades what is to be established (S&dhya-vy&- paka), in this case, fire, but it does not pervade what establishes (SMhana-vyapaka), i.e. smoke, because fire is not pervaded by or invariably accompanied by wet fuel, as, for instance, in the case of a red-hot iron ball, where we have really fire without smoke. Hence it would not follow by necessity that there is fire uecause there is smoke, or that there is no fire because there is no smoke. How far the Indian mind may go in these minutiae of reasoning may be seen from the following instance given by Dr. Bal- lantyne in his Lectures on the Nyaya-philosophy, founded chiefly on the Tarkasamgraha, p. 59 : * To be the constant accompanier of what is to be esta- ANUMANA FOE OTHERS. 437 Wished (Sdhya-vyapakatva) consists in the not being the counter-ertity (Apratiyogitva) of any absolute non-exist- ence (Atyantabh&va) having the same subject of inhesion (SamanadhikaraTia) as that which is to be established. To be not the constant accompanier of the argument (S&dhanvy&pakatva) consists in the being the counter- entity (Pratiyogitva) of some absolute non-existence r not impossibly] resident in that which possesses [the character tendered as an] argument.' The credit of this translation belongs not to me, but to the late Dr. Ballantyne, who was assisted in unravelling these cobwebs of Nyltya logic by the Ny&ya-Pandits of the Sanskrit College at Benares. Such native aid would seem to be almost indispensable for such an achievement. \ CHAPTER IX. VAISESHIKA PHILOSOPHY. Date of Sfrtras. IT is fortunate that with regard to the Vaiseshika philosophy, or rather with regard to the Vaiseshika-Sutras, we are able to fix a date below which their composition cannot be placed. In the year 1885 Professor Leumann, well known by his valuable researches in Gaina literature, published an article, * The old reports on the schisms of the Gainas,' in the Indische Studien, XVII, pp. 91-135. Among the various heresies there mentioned, the sixth, we are told, p. 12J, was founded by the author of the Vaisesiya- sutta of the Chaulu race, and hence called Chauluga *. If there could be any doubt that this is meant for the Vaise- shika-Sutras it would at once be dispersed by the 144 so-called points of that system, as mentioned by the author, Ginabhadra. Ginabhadra's date is fixed by Professor Leu- inann in the eighth century A.D., and is certainly not later. This, it is true, is 110 great antiquity, still, if we consider the age of our Samkhya-Sutras, referred now to the thirteenth century A.D., even such a date, if only certain, would be worth having. But we can make another step backward. Haribhadra, originally a Brahman, but con- verted to Gainism, has left us a work called the ShacZdar- sanasarnuM'uya-sutrani, which conta : ns a short abstract of the six Darsanas in which the Vai&eshika-darsana is de- scribed as the sixth, and in that description likewise we meet with the most important technical terms of the VaiSushika. This short but important text was published in the iirst volume of the Giornale della Societd Asiatica * Could this be meant for Auluka ? DATES FROM TIBETAN SOURCES. 439 Italiana* 1887, and Sanskrit scholarship is greatly indebted to Professor C. Puini for this and other valuable contribu- tions of his to Craina literature. The author, Haribhadra, died in 10.55 ^ ^ ne Vlra-era, i.e. 585 Samvat, that is 528 A.D. This would give us an attestation for the Vaise- shika-Sutras as early as that of the Samkhya-karikas, if not earlier, and it is curious to observe that in Hari- bhadra's time the number six of the Darsanas was already firmly established. For, after describing the (i) Bauddha, (3) Naiyayika, (3) Samkhya, (4) (?aina, (5) Vaiseshika,' and (6) (?aiminiya systems, he remarks, that if some consider the Vaiseshika not altogether different from the Nyaya, there would be only five orthodox systems (Astika), but that in that case the number six could be completed by the Lokayita (sic) system which he proceeds to describe, but which, of course, is not an Astika, but a most decided Nastika system of philosophy. It is curious to observe that here again the Vedanta-philosophy, and the Yoga also, are passed over in silence by the (?ainas, though, for reasons explained before, we have no right to conclude from this that these .systems had at that time not yet been reduced to a systematic form like the other four Darsarias. What we learn from this passage is that early in the sixth cen^ tury A.D. the Nyya, Smkhya, Vaiseshika, and Purva- Mim&y7is& systems of philosophy formed the subject of scientific study among the (?ainas, and we may hope that a further search for S'aina MSS. may bring us some new discoveries, and some further light on the chronological development of philosophical studies in India. Dates from Tibetan Sources. Whenever we shall know more of the sources from which Tibetan writers derived their information about Indian literary matters, more light may possibly come from thence on the dates of the Indian philosophical systems of thought also. It is true that the introduction of Buddhism into Tibet dates from the eighth century only, but the trans- lators of Sanskrit originals, such as $anti Rakshita, Padma Sambhava, Dharmakirti, Dipamkara $ri<7//ana and others, may have been in possession of much earlier information. 440 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. In an account ' of King Kanishka (85106 A.D.) and his Great Council under Vasumitra and Purnaka, we read that there was at that time in Kashmir a Buddhist of the name of Sutra who maintained a large Buddhist congregation headed by a sage Dharmarakshita, and he is said to have belonged to the Vaiseshika school 2 . This would prove the existence of the Vaiseshika philosophy in the first century A.D., a date so welcome that we must not allow ourselves to accept it till we know what authority there was for the Tibetan writers to adopt it. It is taken from Sumpahi Choijung, and the same authority states that after the death of Kanishka, a rich householder of the nainu of Jati who lived at Asvaparanta in the north, invited Vasunetra, a monk of the Vaiseshika school, from Maru in the west, "and another, Gosha Samgha from Bactria, and supported the native clergy, consisting of three hundred thousand monks, for a period of ten years. Xanada. Although Nyaya and Vaiseshika have been often treated as sister philosophies, we must, after having examined Gotama's philosophy, give, for the sake of completeness, at least a general outline of Ka^ada's system also. It does not contain much that is peculiar to it, and seems to pre- suppose much that we found already in the other systems. Even the theory of Anus or atoms, generally cited as its peculiar character, was evidently known to the Nyaya, though it is more fully developed by the Vaiseshikas. It begins with the usual promise of teaching something from which springs elevation or the summum bonum, and that something Kart&da calls Dharma or merit. From a par- ticular kind of merit springs, according to Kanada, true knowledge of certain Padarthas, or categories, and from this oncfe more the summum bonum. These categories, of which we spoke before as part of the Nyaya-philosophy, embrace the whole realm of knowledge, and are: (i) sub-, stance, Dravya; (2) quality, Gmia; (3) action, Karman; (4) genus or community, Samanya, or what constitutes 1 Journal of Buddhist Text Society, voL I, p. i seq. 1 Ibid., vol. I. part 3, p. 19. QUALITIES. 441 a genus ; (5) species or particularity, Visesua, or what con- stitutes an individual ; (6) inhesion or inseparability, Sama- vaya ; (7) according to some, privation or negation, Abhava. These are to be considered by means of their mutual similarities and dissimilarities, that is, by showing how they differ and how far they agree. Here we have, indeed, what comes much nearer to Aristotle's categories than Gotama's Padarthas. These categories or predicaments were believed to contain an enumeration of 11 things capable of being named, i. e. of being known. If the number of Aristotle's categories was controverted, no wonder that those of KaTiada should have met with the same fate. It has always been a moot point whether Abhava, non- existence, deserves a place among them, while some philo- sophers were anxious to add two more, namely, akti, potentia, and Sad-mya, similitude. Snbvtanoev. I. The substances, according A to the Vaiseshikas, are: (i) earth, PHthivi; (2) water, ApaA; (3) light, Terras ; (4) air, Vayu ; (5) ether, Akasa ; (6) time, Kala ; (7) space, Dis ; (8) self, Atman ; (9) mind, Manas. These substances cannot exist without qualities, as little as qualities can exist with- out substances. The four at the head of the list are either eternal or non-eternal, and exist either in the form of atoms (Amis) or as material bodies. The non-eternal sub- stances again exist as either inorganic, organic, or as organs of sense. The impulse given to the atoms comes from God, and in that restricted sense A the Vaiseshika has to be accepted as theiatic. God is Atman in its highest form. In its lower form it is the individual soul. The former is one, and one only, the latter are innumerable. Qualities. II. The principal qualities of these substances are: (i) colour Rupa, in earth, water, and light; (2) taste, Rasa, in earth and water ; (3) smell, Gandha, in earth ; (4) touch, Sparsa, in earth, water, light, and air ; (5) number, Sam- khya, by which we perceive one or many; (6) extension or quantity, Parim&wa; (7) individuality or severalty, 44 2 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. P?^thaktva ; (b) ' conjunction, Samyoga , (9) disjunction, Viyoga ; (10) priority, Earatva ; (i i) 1 posteriority ,Aparatva ; (12) thought, Buddhi ; (13-14) pleasure and pain, Sukha du&kha; (15-16) desire and aversion, IMAa-dveshau ; (i?) 1 will, effort, Prayatna. Actions. III. The principal actions affecting the substances are: (i) throwing upwards, UtkshepaTia; (2) throwing do,wn- . wards, Avakshepawa (or Apa); (3) contracting, Aku/S&ana; (4) expanding, Utsarawa (or Pras-); (5) going, Gainana. These actions or movements are sometimes identified with or traced back to the Samskaras, a word difficult to translate, and which has been rendered by dispositions and instincts, as applied to either animate or inanimate bodies. These Saraskaras 3 have an important position both in the Samkhya- and in the Bauddha-philosophies. In the Tarkadipika Samskara is rendered even by Crati (p AlOepi b y aiOcpa blov] arap irvpl irvp diSrjAor. But though we may discover the same thought in the philosophies of Kaw&da and Empedocles, the form which it takes in Tmlia is characteristically different from its Greek form. Ether is always eternal and infinite. The sense of hear- ing is the ethereal organ : nay, it is supposed by some that ether is actually contained in the ear. As to atoms, they are supposed to form first an aggregate of two, then an aggregate of three double atoms, then of SAMAVAYA. 447 four triple atoms, and so on. While single jitoms are inde- structible, composite atoms are by their very nature liable to decomposition, and, in that sense, to destruction. An atom, by itself invisible, is compared- to the sixth part of a mote in a sunbeam. S&m&nya. IV. As to Samanya, community, or, as we should say, genus, the fourth of Kanada's categories, it is supposed to be eternal, and a property common to several, and abiding in substance, in quality, and in action. It is distinguished by degrees, as fiigh and low ; the highest Sm&nya, or, as we should say, the highest genus (Crati) is Satta,- mere being, afterwards differentiated by Upadhis, or limitations, and developed into ever so many subordinate species. The Buddhist .philosophers naturally deny the existence of such a category, and maintain that all OUT experience has to do with single objects only. V. These single objects are what KaTi&da comprehends under his fifth category of Visesha, or that whiclr consti- tutes the individuality or separateness of any object. This also is supposed to abide in eternal substances, so that it seems to have been conceived not as a mere abstraction, but as something real, that was there and could be dis- covered by means of analysis or abstraction. Saxnavaya. VI. The last category, with which we have met several times before, is one peculiar to Indian philosophy. Sarna- vaya is translated by inhesion or inseparability. With Ka7i4da also it is different from mere connection, Samyoga, such *,s obtains between horse and rider, or between milk and water mixed together. There is Samavaya between threads and cloth, between father and son, between two halves a.nd a whole, between cause and effect, between sub- stances and qualities, the two being interdependent and therefore inseparable. Though this relationship is known in non-Indian philo- sophies, it has not received a name of its own, though 448 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. . such a term iright have proved very useful in several controversies. The relation between thought and word, for instance, is not Samyoga, but Samav&y, insepar- ableness. Abi&va. VII. In addition to these" six categories, some logicians required a negative category also, that of Abhava or absence. And this also they divided into different kinds, into (i) Prgabh&va, former not-being, applying ID the cloth before It was woven; (2) Dhvamsa, subsequent non- being, as when a jar, being smashed, exists no longer as ajar; and (3) Atyant&bMva, absolute not-being, an impos- sibility, such as the son of a barren woman ; (4) Anyonya- bh&va, reciprocal negation, or mutual difference, such as we see in the case of water and ice. It may seem as if the Vaiseshika was rather a disjointed and imperfect system. And to a certain extent it is so. Though it presupposes a knowledge of the Nyaya-system, it frequently goes over the same ground as the Ny&ya, though it does not quote verbatim from it. We should hardly Imagine that the Vaiseshika-Sfttras would argue against Upamana, or comparison, as a separate Pram&?ia, in addition to Pratyaksha (sense) and Anum&na (inference), unless in some other school it had been treated as an inde- pendent means of knowledge ; and this school wag, as we saw, the Nyaya, which is so far shown to be anterior to the Vaiseshika-philosophy. Kan&da denies by no means that comparison is a channel through which knowledge may reach us, he only holds that it is not an independent channel, but must be taken as a subdivision of another and larger channel, viz. Anum&na or inference. He probably held the same opinion about Sabda, whether we take it in the sense of the Veda or of an utterance of a recognised authority, because the recognition of such an authority always implies, as he rightly holds, a previous inference to support it. He differs in this respect from the ATarvaka secularist, who denies the authority of the Veda outright, while Ka?ida appeals to it in several places. A similar case meets us in Gotaina's Nyaya-Sfttras (1, 16). Here, apparently without any definite reason. Gotama tells THE SIX SYSTEMS. 449 us iii a separate aphorism that Buddhl (understanding), Upalabdhi (apprehension), and (?/?ana (knowing) are not different in meaning. Why should he say so, unless he had wanted to enter his protest against 6me one else who had taught that they meant different things ? Now this some one else could only have been Kapila, who holds, as we saw, that Buddhi is a development of Prakriti or unintel- ligent natiire, and that conscious apprehension (Sam vid) originates with the Purusha only. But here again, though Gotama seems to have had the tenets of the S&mkhya- school in his eye, we have no right on this ground to say that our Sarakhya-Sftoras existed before the Nyya-Sutras were composed. All we are justified in saying is that, like all the other systems of Indian philosophy, these two also emerged from a common stratum in which such opinions occupied the minds of various thinkers long before the final outcome settled down, and was labelled by such names as Sslmkhya, or Nyaya, Kapila, or Gotama, and long, of course, before the Samkhya-Sutras, which we now possess, were constructed. Tfce Six Systems. It must have been observed how these six, or, if we include the B&rhaspatya, these seven systems of philosophy, though they differ from each other and criticise each other, share nevertheless so many things in common that we can only understand them as products of one and the same soil, though cultivated by different hands. They all promise to teach the nature of the soul, and its relation to the God- head or to a Supreme Being. They all undertake to supply the means of knowing the nature of that Supreme Being, and through that knowledge to pave the way to supreme happiness. They all share the conviction that there is suffering in the world ,vhich is something irregular, has no right to exist, and should therefore be removed. Though there is a strong religious vein running through the six so-called orthodox systems, they belong to a phase of thought in which not only has the belief in the many Vedic gods long been superse3ed by a belief in a Supreme Deity, such as Pragdpati, but this phase also has been left behind 29 Qs 45O INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. to make room or* a faith in a Supreme Power, or ir the Godhead which has no name but Brahman or Sat, * I arn what I am/ The Hindus themselves make indeed a dis- tinction between the six orthodox systems. They have no word for orthodox ; nay, we saw that some of these systems, though atneistic, were nevertheless treated as per- missible doctrines, because they acknowledged the authority of che Veda. Orthodox might therefore bfc replaced by Vedic ; and if atheism seems to us incompatible with Vedism or Vedic orthodoxy, we must remember that athe- ism with Indian philosophers means something very dif- ferent from 4 what it means with us. It means a denial of an active, busy, personal S'ruti Vif/wana-Bhikshu, a philosopher of considerable grasp, while fully recognising the difference between the six systems of philosophy, tried to discover a common truth behind them all, and to point out how they can be studied together, or rather in succession, and how all of them are meant to lead honest students into the way of truth. THE SIX SYSTEMS. 451 In his Preface to the Samkhya-Sutras, so well edited and translated by Professor Garbe, Vigrwana-Bhikshu says : " If we read in the BrihadaraTiyaka Upanishad II, 4, 5, and IV, 5, 6, that the Self must be seen, must be heard, must be pondered and meditated on, hearing and the rest are evidently pointed out as means of a direct vision of the Self, by which the highest object of man can be realised. If it is asked how these three things can be achieved, SmHti or tradition answers : ' It must be heard from the words of the Veda, it must be pondered on with proper arguments, and, after that, it must be meditated on con- tinuously. These are the means of the vision of the Self/ ' Meditated on/ that is, by means proposed in Yoga- philosophy. Three things are known from passages of the Veda, (i) the highest object of man, (acknowledge essential for its attainment, (3) the nature of the Atman or Self which forms the object of such knowledge. And it was the pur- pose of the Exalted, as manifested in the form of Kapila, to teach, in his six-chaptered manual on Viveka or distinc- tion between Purusha and Prakriti, all the arguments which are supported by $ruti. If then it should be objected that we have already a logical treatment of these subjects in the Nyaya and Vaiseshika systems, rendering the Samkhya superfluous, and that it is hardly possible that both the Samkhya as well as the Nyaya and Vaiseshika could be means of right knowledge, considering that each represents the Self in a different form, the Nyaya and Vaiseshika as with qualities, the Samkhya as without, thus clearly contradicting each other, we answer No, by no means! Neither is the Sam- khya rendered superfluous by the Nyaya and Vaicseshika, nor do they contradict each other. They differ from each other so far only as Nyaya and Vaiseshika treat of the objects of empirical knowledge, but the Samkhya of the highest truth. The Nyaya and Vaiseshika, as they follow the common-sense view that it is the Self that feels joy and pain, aim at no more t han at the first steps in know- ledge, namely at the recognition of the Atman as different from the body, because it is impossible to enter per saltum into the most abstruse wisdom. The knowledge of those C a- 2 452 INDIAN PHILOSOPHY. preliminary schools which is attained by oimply removing the idea that the Self is the body is no more than an empirical comprehension -of facts, in the same manner as by a removal of the misapprehension in taking a man at a distance for a post, there follows the apprehension that he has hands, feet, &c., that is, a knowledge of the truth, yet. purely empirical. If therefore we read .the following verse from the Bhagavad-gita III, 29 : 'Those who are deceived by the constituent GuTias of Prakriti, cling to the workings of the Gu?ias (Sattva, Ra 23. Aghora, not terrible, 35: Agrita Kesakambali, teaeher men- A tioned in Buddhist annals, 89. Agivaka, Gosali originally an, 89. Agrivakos. 240. Agfianavada, Agnosticism, 19. Agni as Indra and Savitri, 40. Ahamkara, subjectivation, 249, 250, 283. Ahawktlra, a cosmic power, a&. modifications of the, 250. mental act, 250. of three kinds, 264. the cause of creation, 283. personal feelings, 426. Aisvaryas, or superhuman powers, 226. Aitihya, tradition, 395, 429. Akasa, fifth element, vehicle of sound, 383, 386, 400, 443. Akhyayikas, or stories, 225, 243. absent in the Tattva-samasa and the Karikas, 243. reappear in the Samkhya-Sutras, 243- Afcit, matter, 187. Akn'tis, species, 252, 398. Aksha, organ, 252. Akshapada and Kanada, 454. Alara Kahuna, 20. Alberuni, 222. Alexander and Indian philosophy, 386. Alexandria, known as Alasando, saec. Ill, 63. Brahmans did not borrow ideas from, 150. did Brahmans come to ? 399. Logos-idea, no antecedents of it in Greek philosophy, 56. Alimga, i. e. Prakn'ti, 341 n. American Indians, their sweating processes, 312. Amu^a, not stupid,, 251. Ananda, or bliss in the highest Brahman, 372. Anarabhyadhita. 201. AnathapincZika, 25. Aniruddha, 188. Ann'ta, unreal written letters, 92, Antanantikas, 18. Anugraha-sarga, 271, 462 INDEX. Anumftna, or infer, nca, 145, 274, 374, 379, 448. applied by Badarayana to Smriti, tradition, 147. fpr others, 431. Anus, or atoms, 426, 440, 445, 446. Anusaya, Anlage, 177. Anusravika, revealed, 338. Anuttamambhasika, 269. Anva % ya-vyatireki, 436. A nvikshikl, old name of philosophy, 76 n. 1 bifurcation of the old system of, 363. Anyatva, 271. Apara, lower knowledge, 164. Apara-vairagya, lower impassive- ness, 452. Apaumsheyatva, non-human origin of the Vedas, 207. Apavarga, or final beatitude, 373, 378, 385, 421, 424- bliss of the Nyaya, 372. Apotheosis, 279. Application, Upanaya, 432. Apramoda, 269. Aprainodamaiia, 269. Apramudita, 269. Aprasuta, not produced, 245. Apratiyogitva, 437. Apia, not to be translated by aptus, 146. ~ explanation of, 274. Aptava/cana, the true word, 232, 382. Apta-va/rana, 274. Aptopadesa = Aptavafcana, 145, 395. Apurva-principle, 211. miraculous, 211. Arada, teacher of Samkhya-philo- ^ sophy, 238. Arambha vada, theory of atomic agglomeration, 81. Aranyakas, distinction of parts of, into Upanishads and Vedantas, 84 n. Arasya, 269. Arksih. the, 119. Artabhuga, 12. Arthu, objects of the senses, 163. Arthapatti, assumption, 395. Arthuvadas, glosses, 209. Asakti, weakness, 269. Asanta, not-pleasurable, 351. Asat-karyavada, peculiar to Nyaya and Vaiseshika, 159. Asatpramuditam, 269. Asaya, Anlage, 320. Asiddhis and Siddhis, 269. Asmarathya, referred to by Bada- rdy ana, 91. Asmita, different from Ahamkara, 343 n. Asoka, King, 263 B. c., 26. Asrama, not found in the classical A Upanishads, 236. Asramas of the Buddhists, only two, Grihins and Bhikkhus, A 2 3<5. Asramas, stations in life, 101. Asramin in the Mai tray. Up., 236. Assertion, Prati^mt, 432. Astitva, yeality, 271. AsumariA-ika, 269. Asunetra, 269. Asupara, 269. Asura, name given to Tvash/n*, and to his son Visvarupa, 44. Asuri, 295. Asutara, 269. Asvaghosha's Buddha-fcarita, first cent. A. D., 237. Asvala, n. Asvalayana Grzhya-Sutras, 239. Asvapati Kaikeya, 14. Atara, 269. Ataratara, 269. Atheism of Purva-Mimamsa, the supposed, 210. of Kapihi, 302. attributed to the Vaiseshika and Nyaya and Purva-Mimamsa, 327- Ativahika-sarira formed of eighteen elements, 301. Atma-anatma-viveka, 285. Atmadarsanayogyata, fitness for beholtling the Self, 357. Atman, taught by Kshatriyas, 14. importance of the word, 70. etymology of, 71. = breath in Veda, the Mfe, soul, 7 1 - the name of the highest person, 72. and Purusha. 277, 285. INDEX. 463 Atman, not cognitive, 330. Atom, invisible, si.vth part of a mote, 447. Atoms, Greek origin of theory of, 446. Atreya, referred to by Badarayarja, 91. Atushii and Tushd, 269. Atyantabhava, 437. Audulomi, referred to by Badara- yana, 91. Avapr, 202. Avayavas, or Premisses, i. e. the members of a syllogism, 382, 385. Avidya, history of, 161. changed to a Sakti or potentia of Brahman, 168. not to be accounted for, 172. applied to Kant's intuitions of sense and his categories, 173. and Mithyagruana, 185. N. science, 268, 284, 285, 378, 386. an actual power, Sakti, 280. origin of, 289. Avif a, not having a seed, 342. Avinabhava, Not -without -being, 377- Aviruddhakos, 240. Avisesha, subtle elements, 341 n. Aviveka, 285, 367. Avividi^ha, carelessness, 266. Avrishii, 269. Avyakta, 188, 246, 341 n., 372. producing, Prasuta, 245. doubtful meaning of, 78. chaos, 245. Awake, state of being, 174. Ayur-veda, 413. BABARA PRAVAHAM, signi- ficative name, 208. Babylonian hymns, more modern in thought than tho r 3 of Rig- veda, 34. Badarayarca, author of one of the Mimamsas, 85, 116, 120, 371. quotes Gaimini, 91, 198. identified with Vyasa, 113. Badari, referred to by Badarayana, 91. Bahutva, 27*1. Bana know.* Kfcpilas, Kanadas, 241. Bana's HarshaArarita, 600 A. D.,. 241. Bandha, bondage, 272. Bandhas, or bindings, 349. Bante, Buddhist title, 16. Barhaspatyam, studied by Buddha, 97- Bathing, ^graduating) the pupil, 205. Berkeley, 194. Bhadrasana, 349. Bhagavatas, follower of Krishna, 31- Bhartnhari, date of death, 650 A. D., 9<>> 339- refers to the Darsanas, 90. Bhafta, 404. Bhava, the real world, the causey of Samadhi, 343. Bhikkhu, name of, 236. Bhiksha&arya, or begging, 236. and BhaikshaMrya, 236. Bhikshu-Sutras, loss of, referred to by Bhaskara&arya, 86. Parasarya, the author, 97, 117. same as Vedanta-Sutras, 117. Bhikshus, mendicants, 24, 31. Bhur, 150. Bhuta-sarga, 272. Bhutadi, 249, 250. Bhutatman, elementary Atman, 261. Bimbisara, 16, 27. Boar legend that it brought forth the earth, allusions in Brah- rnanas, 73. Bod da, name found among followers of Marii, 64. Boddo (on coins), name of Buddha. 27. Bodhayana, 117, 230. Body, a subtle and a gross, 300. &arira, 416. is it the same at Atman, 416. Brahma, creator, 18. called Vasudeva, 188. Brahmadatta, 16. Brahma-(/ala-sutta, 16, 17, ai. Brahman, various meanings of, 52. identified with speech, 65. is the sun, 142. is Manas, 142. 464 INDEX. Brahman is food, 14", is Vi^nana, 142. as the Word, the first creation of divine thought, 145, 149, 150, 397- or VsJc or Bn'h, eternal, 150. is everything, 172. as the Kantian Ding an sich, 172. is the world, 280. may become to us Brahma-, 281. of the Vedanta, 285. is Anirva&aniya, un definable, 288. Brahmana, a social title, 17, Brahmanas consist of Vidhis, in- junctions and Arthavadas, glosses, 200. Brahmans, two, Saguna and Nir- guna, 1 68. Bn'h, parallel form of Vn'dh, 54. to grow, c. p. Latin verbum and German wort, 55. speech, 397. Brihaspati, synonymous with Va- A-aspati, lord of speech, 54, 99, 397- Sutras, lost, 86. philosophy, the, 94. Laukya, 94. Angirasa, 94. Budh, means to awake, 283. Buddha, a Kshatriya, 10. guru, identified with Pythagoras, 60. works studied by, 96. did not borrow from Kapila, 103. subjects known to, 115. borrowed from Kapila no evi- dence that, or vice versa, 297. later than the classical Upani- shads, 314. declared against Yoga tortures, 315- Buddha-frarita, the, 237. Buddha's mother, name of, 93. denial of an Atman or Brahman, 316. Buddhi v intellect, 246, 376, 383. or Mahat, in a cosmic sense, 246. the lighting up of Prakn'ti, 282. of the Nyaya different from that of the Samkhyas, 418. 'Buddhindriyas, five, 25 r. Buddhism, sul sequent to Upam- shads, 236. in Tibet, eighth century A. D., 439- Buddhist-Suttas, reduced to writing in the first century B.C., 238. Buddhists support Asat-karyavada, 159. derive the real from the unreal, 303. paid little attention to th> two Mimawsas, 365. deny present time, 393. Butta (first Greek mention of Buduha by Clement of Alexan- dria), 27 CALF, the new-born year, 51 n. Case, five members of a (Adhi- karana), 204. Caste, Portug. casto, 9. Castes, origin of, in India, 9, 10, Categories of the Nyaya, 440. Causal state of Brahman, 188. Causation, chain of, 378. Cause and effect, Vedkntist theory of, 155- with them are the same thing, seen from different points, 155. Causes, are intimate, non-intimate, and instrumental, 443 Chronology of thought, 120. Cleanthes and Boethius, 322. Clement of Alexandria, 27. knows name of Butta, 27, 62. Coining money, 61. Colebrooke on the Gunas, 262. Comparison, Upamana, 382. Conclusion, Nigamana, 432. Conditions, Upadhis, of forming a Vyapti, or universal rule, 434- Con-scien^ia, Sam-vid, 359. Consideration, Paramarsa, 430. Creation, or causation, 155. the result of Nescience, 154. proceeds from Brahman, 155, 157. caused by Maya or Avidya, 192. Cripple who could not walk, and cripple who could not see, 302. INDEX. 465 PAitSHA, force, one meaning of Brahman, 70. Dakshina-ba idha, bondage, 234. gifts to priests, 272. Damascius says Brahmaiis lived at Alexandria saec. V, 62. Dandasana, 349. Darsanns, or systems, the six all orthodox, 288, 439. Death, state of, 174. Deity, existence of a, 422. Deussen, Professor, theory of evo- lution of Word and Brahman, 70. Deva, supreme, never assented by Kapila, 302. Devadhammikas, 240. worshippers of the Devas, 241. Devas, thirty-three in number, ac- cording to Rig- veda and Avesta, difficulty of filling up this number, 38. Devayana, path of the gods, 176. Devotion to the Lord, one of many expedients, 319. Dhanna, duty, 199, 440. Dharmakirfcti, seventh century, 364, 439- Dharmamegha, cloud of virtue, 357- Dharmarakshita, a sage, 439. Dharmottara, ninth century, de- fended Dharmakirtti, 365. Dhatri, maker, name given to the one god, 47. Dhishana (Bn'haspati), 457. Dhriti, energy, 266. Dhyanas (GMna), four, 20. Dignaga, the logician, 364. Dignaga' s writings lost, 365 n. Nyaya-sainu/c/eaya, a Tibetan translation of, 365 n. ^-ipamkara Srigwana, 439. Distinction of good and eyil, 180. Divakara, a sage, 600 A. D., 30. Divine thinker, every word au act of a, 150. Divyadasa Datta, living Vedantist, 155, 105- Dosha, faults, 421. Dreaming, state of, 174. Drishfam. what is seen, 274. , example, 385. Drumstick and Irum together cbn- vey, even to the deaf, the idea of sound, 380. Dual gfids, two or three gods work- ing together, tendency towards unity among the gods, 40. Duftkha, puin, 274, 367, 421. Du&khanta, or Nirvana, 108, 370. EFFECT, an, only a new manifesta- tion, dogma characteristic of the Samkhya, 158. Ekagrata, concentration, 357. Emancipation, Apavarga, 425. Eschatology, 175. Esse is percipi or pertipere, 291. Eternal punishment, 276. Evolution, Pariwama, 280. of works, the independent. 331. Exercises, Abhyasa, 338. Exposition, five-mem bered form of, 432. FABLES in the Sutras, 305. Fa-hian visits India, 399-414 A. D., 27. Fancy chiefly due to words, 337. Fetishism or Totemism, did they precede the Aryan theogony? 36. Fifth element, called aKa.r-ov6fjux.rovj 386. First and last inference, Vita, or straightforward, 382. Fivefold division of tho vital spirit, 174. Four or five elements, the, 99. states, the, 174. Pramanas, according to Gotama, 374- Freedom from passions, Vairagya, 338. or beatitude depends on philo- sophy, 391. Frog- wife, the, 316. &AIMINI, author of one of the Miniawsiis, 85. 371. referred to by Badaraya?ia, 91, 198. his work atheistic, 457, and Vyasa, 454. Sutras, contents of, soo. 466 INDEX. Gaina literature, 4^8, 439. Gainas, in white robes, 31. (?alpa, sophistical wrangling, 389. Gamgesa Upadhyaya, fourteenth century, 366. Ganaka, king of Mithila, the Vide- ha, 11-13, a ? Ganganatha Jha, of Bombay, 318. Gargi Vafc&knavi, n. tfati, kith and caste, 9. birth or genus, a transitio in cUterum (jenus, 389. futility, 389. Gatilakas, 241, Gaudapada, date of, 223, Gauri-Sawkar, Mount, 184. Ghora, fearful, 253. Ginabhadra, eighth century, 438. Glvanxnukti, 180, 360. Gflanayoga, 311, 347. Gfiatiputra, teacher mentioned in Buddhist annals, the Nirgran- tha, founder of Gainism, 89. Gnomina, nomina, 376. God in the beginning created namos and forms of things, 398. Gods of the Vedic people, the agents postulated behind the great phenomena of nature, 36. Gondaphoros, king, authenticated as Gondophares, 63. G&rres on Sk. terms retained by the Greeks, 386. Gosha-Samgha, from Bactria, 440. Gosaliputra, teacher mentioned in Buddhist Annals, 89. Gotama and Kanada, philosophies of, 80. Gotamakas, 240. Greek accounts of India, 26, 386. Gunas, constituents of nature, lii. the three, in, 216, 255, 256, 262, 263, 357. as Dravyuni, matter, 263. equilibrium of the three, 263. of Prakrit i, 341 n. not qualities, but substantial, 357- Gyotishtoma sacrifice, 209. HAMMER OF FOLLY, Mohamud- gara, 181 Haribhadra, his uAr/caya-sutfam, 438. died, 528 A. D., 439. Harihara, 256, 313. Harsha, King, 600 A. D., 27. history of, by Ban*, 30. court of, 365. Ha&a, or Kriya-yoga, 344, 345. Head, forfeited ip disputations, 13. Heart, seat of consciousness, 356. Hegel's thesis, antithesis, and syn- thesis, 263. Henotheism = phase in which God is addressed as if the only god in existence, with forgetfulness of all others, 40. Herbart's Selbsfa-hattung des Realm, 159- philosophy, 174. Hetvabhasas, specious arguments, four kinds, 389. Hiouen-thsang, Buddhist pilgrim, visits India, 629-645 A. D,, 27. did not translate the Vaiseshika- Sutras by Kanada, 242. Hiranyagarbha, 256, 313. Holenmerian theory of Plotinus and Henry More, 173. Homoiousia, 321. Human souls reborn in animal and vegetable bodies (in Upani- shads), 105. Hume's view of causality, 159. Hyades, stars marking time of rain, 37. Hylobioi, forest-dwellers, 27. Hymn to the Unknown God, 46. Hymns, adaptations of, 201. Hypnotic states, how produced, 365, Hypnotism, 349. ICHNEUMON AND SNAKE, 380. Idealism, is Samkhya? 293. Identity, Sabhavyam, 177. Idolatry, a necessity of our nature 165. Ignorance, or Mithyagfftana, 391, Immortality of the soul, 105. India, a nation of philosophers, 7. early philosophers in, 8. Indian coinage, 60. leaven in our thoughts, 194, 385. philosophy, books on, 368, 369, INDEX. 467 Indian logic, 390. Individual soul is Brahman, not vice twsfl, 154. Xndra, the rainer, 35. Indriyagraya, subjugation of senses, 357- Indriyas, five senses, 163, 415. sense, 173. Indu, the rain, 55. Inference, Anum&na, 379. thrse kinds of, 379, 382, Smfiti, 397. Instance, Udaharana, 432. Inward-turned thought, Pratyak- fcetana, 323. tsvara exists phenomenally only, 170. the Lord, 188. Krishna, 224. or personal Lord, denial of, not in the original Samkhya, 230. abc T e all Purushas, 320. -T- a Punish a, 320. one of many souls, 325, 344. perception of the, 327, 328. a maker, a Sat-kara, 328. tsvaras, not many, 321. JATI, of Asvaparanta, 440. KAIVALYA, aloneness, 345, 356, 359, 3?c, 373- Kaivalva-pada, 334. means isolation qf the soul, 334. Kaivalya/347, 359. Kaiyafa, 404. jfifakrapravartana, the turning of the wheel, 24. Kakuda Katyayana, teacher men- tioned in Buddhist annals, 89. Kalanos (Kalyana) gymnosophist, 386. Kalidasa, alludes to the logician Dignaga, 364. Kanada, 362, 372, 440. /vandrakanta Tarkulunkara, author of Sanskrit treatise, 87 n. Kanishka, King, 85-106 A. .. 440. his Great Council, under Vasumitra and Purnakaj 440. an-ti, not a good Chinese scholar, 222. Kapila and Pataffcali, 307. and Buddha, existence side by siharma, 455. Monotheism, Monism, tendencies working together produce idea of supreme personality, 41. Morality depends on prescriptive sacra or on Samaya, 390. More, Henry, Holenmerian theory of, 173. MudT&a, stupid, 353. Mudras, 349. Mukhya-Prana, 163, 174. vital spirit, as first Upadhi, 163. the vital spirit, 301. Mulikarthas, 270. Munrfasavakas, 240. Murdhanya Nfidi, capital vein, 176. NACHEIlN ANDER AND NEBEN- EINANDER, 235. Nagargruna, author of the Madhya- mika-.Sutras, 366, 396. first century A. D., 366. NaishMika, 22. Naiyayika derives what is not yet from what is, 303. Naiyay.kas believe in God as a Creator, 31. hold the Veda to be non-eternal, 332. Namadha, name-giver, name given to the one God, 47. Nainadheya, technical name of each sacrifice, 200. Namarupa, 157. correspond to the Greek Logoi, 157. Narayana is Brahman, 142. Nasadiya hymn, 49. Nastika, heretics, 98, 279, or .ZCarvaka system, 99. Nate-Sutras, Silalin author of, 97! Nebeneinander, truerJjey to growth of philosophical ideas than the Nacheinander, 74. Nescience, cosmical, 154. Newton's system, and Darwin's theory of evolution, 326. Niebuhr's derivation of Indian philosophy from Greece, 387. Nigantaas, 240, 241. Nigrahasthana, unfitness for dis- cussion, 389. Niranumana, 249, 350, 268. Niratisaya, ncn plus idtra, 322. Niratman (selbqflos), 262. Nirnaya, ascertainment, 388. Nirodha, restraint, 336. Nirvana, 296, 360, 373. also Nirvataft, 373. not a technical term in Panini's time, 373. the blowing out of passions, 373. or Dufckhanta, 108. Nirvikalpa, one kind of Pratyaksha, 144. Nirvitarka, 346. Northern Kurus, 374. Notion, Anubhava, 383. Nyasa, writing (Vyasa?), 118. Nyaya-Sutras, 83. not found in Upanishads, 84. modern, confined to Pramana, 39i- later books of the, 391. Nyayii-mala-vistarn , 20 1 . INDEX. Nyaya and Vni*eiiiika represent Self endowed with qualities. 288. a first step towards truth, 388, 308. systems, 331, 362, 373. relation between, 362. books on, 369. Nyaya -philosophy, history of, 363, cS 9 . also applicable to the Purva- Mimawta, 369. studied first century A. D., 396 n. Nyaya on Sphofei, 413. # recognised the Veda, 417. calls Yoga to its aid, 427. OM, 322. contraction of Avam, 323. Organic body, the, 163. PAD.X.NI, appliances. 252. Padartha, not categories, 76, 375. the meaning of the word, 376. Pad&rthas of Kanada, the five, 77- (omne scfbile), 363. Padma-Purawa, 456. Padma Sarabhava, 439. Padmasana. 348. Pain, nature of, 376. meaning of, 297. Paksha, or memixv of a Vyapti, 43o. or terminus minor, 430. Pakshilasvamin, 365. Palm-leaves pierced, 421. Pan-- ni, lost Sutras known to, 97. Panini's principle as to letters forming a word, 404. Paftftadasi, 215. author of the, quotes the Madh- yamikas, 366. Panfraratra, account of system in Prasthana Bheda, 81. PaJMpratras, 31. PajWcasikha, philosopher referred to in-Sawkhya-Sutras, 90, 295. Pantaenus in India, one of the teachers of Clement, 62. fara, higher knowledge. 164. Parables, Buddhist love of teaching by, 306. Parft gati, the highest poal,.2 4 . Parama-tavara, highest Lord, 334. Pai*amartha, a law t jacher, A. i>. 557"589, 234. Paramarthika, real, 367. Paramatman is Isvara, but tsvara is not Paramatman 5 434. Parampara, tradition, as handed down orally, 04. mnemonic literature, ai8. of the Brahmaus, 306. Parasara, 455. Parasarya (Vyasa), author of Bhik- shu-Sutras, 97, 117. Parava^a, controversies, 325. Paravairagya, higher impassive- ness, 452. Paribhagrakas, 241. Parikshit, old King, is. Pariwama, evolution, 185, 280. Parinama-vada, theory of evolution, 81. Parivragraka, or Bhikshu, 24. an itinerant friar, a* (mendicants), 31. Pasupata, account of system in Prasthana Bheda, 81. Patoliputra, Buddhist Council at, 276 B.C., 25. Pata%ali, author of Yoga-Sutras, and Patangrali, author of the Mahabhashya, 118. the grammarian, age of, w ii9. by no means settled; 119. second century B.C.. 220. the philosopher may be the same as the grammarian, 313. called Phanin, or Sesha, 313. date" of, only constructive, 314. called a portion of Sankarshana or Ananta, 314, his theistic Sawkhya-philosophy, 318. Patikka Samuppada, 378. Perception, Pratyaksha, 379. contact of sense with its object, 393. contact of thp senses and mind, 39 2 - contact of mind and the Self, 392, Sruti, 397. Perceptions, always perceived as perceptions of something, 161. INDEX. 47' Peoftfmasm 106. Phala, rewards, 421, 495. Phanibhartn, 314. Phanin, name for Pataflgali, 313, Phenomenal and fictitious, differ- ence between, 185. Philosophical ideas, common, 104. systems, parallel development the time of Buddha, 240. Philosophies and Sutraa, relative age of, 219. Philosophy, different ways of study- ing, 182. Pin run through sheets of a MS. seems simultaneous, but is successive, 393. Pitriyana, path of the fathers, 176. Pleiades, the return of calmer weather, 37. Plotiius, Holenmerian theory of, 173- Postures, Yogarigas, 347. and tortures, 355. Prabhakara, commentator on the Mimamsa, 210. a Mimamsaka, 499. Practical life (Vyavahara), 294. purposes (Vyavaharartham), 160. Pradhana, Praknti, 269, 315, 341 n. Pradynmna, 188. Pragrapati, supreme god, 42* attains more personal char- acter, 45. called Visva, &c. , 260. tradition from, 307 . Prav(Tis, 290. Praksa, or light, 291. firs'- wakened to life by disturb- ance of its three constituents, 291. In all her disguises, Purusha and the dancer, 295. Prakn'ti-purusha-viveka, 285. Prakntilaya, 248. absorbed in Prakrtti, 343, 343. Prakn'tis, eight, 290. Prakriti's unselfishness, 299. Pralaya, the idea of, recent, no. Pralayas, absorptions of the whole world, 109. Pramana, only one admitted by the Lokayatas, 99. instrument of measuring, 143. Pramana, 374, 378. Pramana-samufc&aya, the Tibetan version, 396. Pramanas, 143. three essential, 144. the three go back to one, 145- authoritative sources of know- ledge. 202. of (ruimini, 202. three, 273, 274. eight, 395. in different Philosophical Schools, 428. Prameya, 374, : 375> 382. Prameyas, objects of knowledge, 392, 415, 421. Pra?ia breath, 47. Pranas, vital spirits, 173. Pranava, 322. the inner guide, 335. Prawayamas, 344, 347. Prasenagrit, 27. Prasthana-bheda, treatise on philo- sophical literature, 75. Pratipathi-karmam, 201. Pratisakhyas, 218. Pratisan/rara is dissolution, 264. Pratitya, dependent or conditioned, 367 n. Pratityatva, 367^ Pratiyogitva, 437. Pratyfihara, complete abstraction, 349- 472 INDEX. Pratyaksha, sense perception, 144, 73, 374- two kinds of, 144. perception and Anumara, in- ference, ignored by Badara- yana, 146. applied by Badarayana to Sruti (revelation), 147. perception, 379, 392. Pravn'tti, activity, 421. Prayoga-vidhis, 200. Prayograna, purpose, 385. Presumption (Arthapatti), 203. Pretyabhava, transmigration, 384, 421, 422. Primeval waters, existing apart from Pragrapati, 72. Punarukti, useless repetition, 226. Purana Kasyapa, teacher men- tioned in Buddhist annals, 89. Puratana, 307. Purchas, 1613, mentions castes of Banians, 9. Purusha = man, name given to the one god, 47. (soul) does not migrate, but the Sukshma-sarira, subtle body, 105. Purusha, 253, 277. name of supreme deity, 253, 34i. one or many ? 256. never the material cause of the universe, 286. state of, when free, 296. rendered by Self, not by man, 3" n. the 25th Tattva, 342. Purushas of the Sawkhya, many, 285, 371. Purushottama, 329. Purva, the prius, 381.' Purva/caryas, 330. Purva-Mimamsa, the first step, 141. 196, 200, 202, 213. and Uttara-Mimamsa, 213. charged with atheism, 321. Purvapaksha, 204, 435. Purvavat preceded by a prius, 379. Pythagoras, identified with Bud- dha-guru, 60. claimed a subtle covering for the soul, 300. QUALITIES, Guna, 441 Quality, intang ble in sound, 401 RA0AGJRIHA, Buddhist Council at, 477 B. c., 25. Ragra-yoga, true Yoga, 345. Raghuvawsa of Kalidasa, 207. Rahu, head of, 337. Raikva and Ganasruti, 14. Rajendralal Mitra, 324, 325, 341, 358. Ramanugra, lived twelfth century A. D., 185. his view of universe, 280. Ramanugra's system called Visishfa- Advaita, 187. Real and the phenomenal, differ- ence between the, 161. Reason, Hetu, 432. Receptacle, Asraya, or subject, 425. Religion and philosophy have worked together harmoniously in India alone, 409. Religious persecution, Buddhists and Brahman*, 29. Religious and Popular Poetry of Vcdic Age, not one hundredth part of it remains, 41. Remembering is not wiping out, 338. Remembrance, Smarawa, 383. can make our mouths water, 416. Jftddhis, or Aisvaryas, 350. Rig-veda, a fragment only, does not represent whole of Vedic my- thology and religion, 42. Jtttambhara, truth-bearing, 346. Ritter, his contempt of the Nyaya, 76, 390. Root, the, expresses Bhava, a state, or Kriya, action, 405. SABDA, the word, 274, 394, 399, 404, 448. or wora, a Pramawa, 145, 374, 382. iSabdanusasanam, 31 7 n. Sabhapati Svamy^, 352, 353. Sacrifice was Karman, woMc, 198. Sadhana-pada, 334. Sadness cleaves to all finite life, 297. Saiva and Pasupata systems, 457. INDEX. 473 Sakalya, -3. /Sakayanya, a Saka, 14. Sa/c-fcid-aiinnda, being, perceiving, blessed, Brahman called, 169. Sakshatkara, or manifestation, 142. Sakti, power, 157, 44*- Samadhi, obstacles to, 323. meditation or absorption. 334, 34i, 35o. - or Samapatti, 346. ' Samadhi, Apragrnata, 347, 427. Samanya. genus, 441, 447. Samanyato Drtshia, constantly seen together, 380. SainasM, 282. Samavaya, intimate connection, 37^ 447- Sambhava, probability, 395. equivalence, 429. Sawgati, connection, 204, 205. Saw0aya-Vaira#i-putra, teacher mentioned in Buddhist annals, 89. Sawgiti, a council (symphony), 4. Samkara, literary works referred to by, 114. his contempt of ritualism, 165, lived eighth century A. i>., 186. and. B4manu 155. Thlodicle, the Hindu, 171. an ancient, 212. Third place, the, 179. Third Valli of K&th& Upanishad, 136. Three couples of philosophical sys- tems, 308. Time, 444. present, past, future, 393. Titthiyas, or Tirthakas, 239. Traigunya, 262. Tranquillity (tfanti), 296. Triad, Dharma, Art ha and Kama, 60. of elements, 100. TripUaka, date of, 15. Trithen, Dr., andPrasthana Bheda, 75- Truth better than sacrifice, 361. Prama, 428. Tryanuka, three double atoms, 446. Tushtis and Siddhis, 270, 270 n. Tvashfn, the maker, not real crea- tor, of a) 1 things, 43, 44. 476 INDEX. Two Brahmans, tbo word and the non-word, 407. UDDALAKA, 20. Uddyotakara, not Udyotakara, 364, 365. Udulomas, 22. Universalia in re&us, 398. Upada, a, material cause, 158. Upadhi, condition, 430. Upadhis, liirltirig conditions of name and form, 158. five, 163. conditions, impositions, 163. or conditions, 173. conditions, 380, 436. Upalabdhi, perception, 173, 418. Upamana, comparison, 374, 394, 448. belongs to the Nyaya school, 394. Upanayana, 141. Upanishad-period, 700 B. c., 4. Upanishads, known to Buddhists, 24. existence of, recognised in Bud- dhist Canon, 85. translation of, published 1879, 1884, 137. character of the, 139. contain the seeds of later philo- sophy, 140. and Vedanta, something between the, 143. Upasakas, laymen, 25. Upavarsha, teacher of Panini, 117. the Vedantist, 410. Upayas, means of attaining Sama- dhi, 344. Uposhadha, 236. Utpatti-vidhis,original injunctions, 200. Uttarapaksha, 203, 435. VADA, 389. Vagapyayana, words, mean a genus, ' 406. Vaikarik*, 250, 252, 267. Vaikhanasa-Sutras, Joss of; referred to by Bhaskara/carya, 86. Vairagya-sataka of Gainafcarya, 339. Vaisali,Buddhist council at, 377 B.C. , Vaiseshika, word not f-mnl in Upanishads, 35. on Spho/a, 414. philosophy, 438. Vaiseshikas, followers of Kanada, 3i- creation and dissolution accord- ing to, no. Vaishnavas (Ramamgra), theory of, contrasted with that of Brah- mavadins, 82. Vafc, direction taken in Veda by thoughts connected with speech, 65. Vafcaspaf ' -Misra, on Buddhi, 247. tenth century, 366. Valkala, dress of bark, 27. Vanaprasthas, 10, 27, 86. Vanigr = Banian, 9. Varaha-Mihira mentionsKapila and Kanabhugr, 241. Varna, colour and caste, 9. Vasamas, impressions, 175, 320, 358. Vasso, from Varshas, 237. Vasubandha, knew the six Tirthya philosophies, 363. Vasunetra of the Vaiseshika school, 440, Vasus, seven, can be distinguished, 38. Vattagamani, 80 B. c., Tripi&ka written, 4. Vayus, winds, 267. Veda, infallibility of the, in. authority of, 149, 232. meaning of, 149. acquisition of the mere sound, meritorious, 204. superhuman origin of the, 206. authority assigned by Kapila to the, 232. cannot prove the existence of a Supreme Being, 332. the word of Brahman, 395. Vedadhyayana, learning the Veda by heart, 141. Vedanta, word does not occur in old Upanisl; .ds, 84. or Uttara-Mimamsa, 113. the first growth of philosophical thought, 115. followers of the, called Aupani- shadas, 116. INDEX. 477 Vedanta fundamental doctrines of the, 121. resume of the, 122. philosophies, two, 192. monism of, 216. . first occurs in the Svetasvatara, 220. and Samkhya, early relation be- tween, 258. Avidya, Aviveka, 280. the, monistic, 281. on Sphote, 410. Vedanta-Sara, 215. Vedanta- Sutras and Bfidarayana, earlier than the Bhag~vad-gita, 113- and Bhagavad-gita, relative age of, 118. methodical, 141. Vedantins, followers of Upanishads, 31- Ved ntist, a, does not really join Brahman, 309. Vedantists derive the unreal from the real, 303. Vedas, authority of the, 149. sound of, eternal, 208. words of the, supernatural, 208. Vedic gods, three classes (i) of the sky ; (2) of the mid-air ; (3) of the earth, 37. Vedic hymns, date for, 2000 B.C. or 5000 B.C., little gained by this, 34 Vedic VlUfc, a feminine, 56. coincidence with Sophia of O.T., 57- VedosdhyetavyaA, 205. Verbal symbols, 165. Vibhuti-pada, 334. Vibhutis, powers, 349. Videhas, bodyless, 342, 343. Vidhatri, arranger, name given to the one god, 47. Vidvan-moda-tararigim, 212. Vidyamatra, knowledge only, 160. doctrine, 427. Vigrflana Bhikshu, 285, 288, 451. supposed to have composed the Sutras, 221. Vikaras, sixteen, 253, 283. Vikasa, r higher enlightenment, no, Viniyoga-vidni, 200. Virasana, 349. Virtue, a preliminary of Moksha, 166. Viruddha, arguments proving the reverse, 389. Visakha- found on earliest Mauryan coin, 60. Visesha, gross elements, 341 n., 447. Vishamatvam, unevenness, m. Vishaya, 204. Vishnu, 313. disguised as Buddha, 457. Vishwi-Purana, 456. Visishte-Advaita, Ramanugra's sys- tem, 187. Visva, or Vaisvanara, 260. Visvakamma, later development of Visvakarman, 45. Visvakarman, described, vague and uncertain character, 45. maker of all things, adjective showing germs that were to grow into supreme deity, used as substantive, 43. Visve, or All-gods, represent first attempt at comprehending the various gods as forming a class, 39- Vitanda, cavilling, 389. Vivarta, turning away, 185. Vivarta-vada, theory of illusion, 81. Vivas vat, 307. Vivekananda, 213. Vividisha, desire of knowledge, 266. Viyoga or Viveka, 310. Vriha or Vn'dh-a, possibly Sanskrit words, 55. Vnshadeva received Sawkara ? 223. king of Nepal, A. D. 630, 223. Vyadi, words mean individual things, 406. Vyakta, 188. Vyapaka, fire, 145. what pervades, 429. or Sfidhya, terminus major, 430. Vyapta, pervaded, 429. Vyapti, universal rule, pervasion, 429, 434- a, may be true in ninety-nine oa8es,yet not in the hundredth, 434- INDEX. vyapti, threefold, 436. Vyapya, what must be pervaded, 429. terminus medius, 430. Vyasa, identified with Badarayana, "3- lived at the end of the Bvapara age, 113. neyer named by Samkara as the autfior of the Sutras, 112. the father of Suka, 114. called Parasarya, 117. and Harihara, 256. commentary on Yoga-Sutras, 313. Vyashtf, 283. Vyavaharartham, practical pur- poses, 1 60. Vyavaharika, phenomenal, 367. WEBER, A., Professor, 56, 307 n. Whole, is there a ? 393. Women, present at philosophical discussions, 10. Wood-architecture, previous to stonework, 61. Word, the, as a creative power, 66. or Sabda, 382, 399. Words, meaning of, conventional i 394- express the summum genus, 405. not names of individuals, but of classes, 408. World, phenomenal reality of the, 154- created by the Word, 397. Worlds, the, created from the Word, 150- Worship (UpasaniO, 164. Writing, allusions to, 92. Writing, when first attempt sd, in India, 218. Written letters called Unreal, 92. YlfftfAVALKYA, xx, la, 340. and kanaka, 13. Ya&kafc, anybody, 254, 254 n. Yama and Yami, usually identified with Adam and Eve, children of Tvashfri, but childless them- selves, 44. Yoga, quoted in Upanishads, 5, 84. and Samkhya, the true philoso- phies, 80. not ration, 170. in the Taittiriya and Katoa Upanishads, 220. and Samkhya, 307. meanings of the word, 308. is Samatva, equability, 308. not union, but disunion, 30^. means really Viyoga, 310. steadying of the mind, 336. as a Taraka, or ferry across the world, 356. is it Nihilism ? 359. and Samkhya on Sphote, 412. Yoga-Sutras, 334. Yogafcaras, 22, 366. Yogangas, helps to Yoga, 347, 348. eight accessories of Yoga, 350. Yoganusasanam, 317 n. Yoga-sara-sawgraha, abstract of the Yoga, 318. Yogins in Mai tray. Up. VI, 220. perceptions of the, 327. nine classes of, 343. ZARADES (Zoroaster), name found among followers of Mani, 64. THE END,