-J NEW PSYCHOLOGY BY JOHN P. GORDY, PH.D., LL.D. HEAD OF THE PEDAGOGICAL DEPARTMENT OF THE OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY Copyright, 1898, by Hinds (y Noble HINDS & NOBLE, Publishers 4-5-13-14 COOPER INSTITUTE, NEW YORK CITY WE ARE ACTING As the Agents of numerous Educational Institutions, large and small, throughout the country,, for the purchase and forward- ing of all Text-books used therein. Our exceptional facilities enable us to attend to this line of business with the utmost promptness, and we save our customers the delay and uncertainty of correspondence and dealings with numerous publishers, express companies, etc. \Ve can present no better testimony as to the success of our efforts in this direc- tion, than the cordial approval of our old patrons, who are constantly sending us new customers. We have purchased the stock and good- will of the New York School Book Clearing House, which firm retires from business. HINDS & NOBLE, 4 Cooper Institute, - New York City. orei4tt (aiuuiaac A. C. A. LlNSENBARTH & Co. BOSTON, MASS., U.S.A. PREFACE. THAT the most effective teaching is impossible without an acquaintance with the elementary principles of Psy- chology, is no longer a debated question. Fortunately there are many who are "born teachers." Even they are more successful when to a " certain instinct for teaching " they have added a knowledge of Psychology. Still more helpful to a genuine success is a knowledge of the Mind to the plodding rank and file, that large body of earnest men and women teachers whose really splendid equipment for their profession is to be credited to unremitting hard work inspired by an honest ambition to win success, and a sturdy determination to avail themselves of every approved resource. This book has been written principally for the special benefit of that large number of progressive young teachers who have not enjoyed the benefits of a college education, but who nevertheless are striving without the aid of an instructor to make their work rational and therefore more efficient by basing it on a knowledge of the Mind. The division of the subject matter into " Lessons," while ad- mirably adapting the book to the special requirements of teachers' reading circles, was particularly intended by the author to supply the need of a practicable text-book for iii 2210827 IV PREFACE. classes in Psychology. Having embodied in these pages the experience of many years in teaching Psychology not only to teachers but also to pupils in the schools, the author believes that he has provided a c/assbook that the teacher may place with confidence in the hands of his pupils, and the superintendent or Normal School instructor in the hands of his training classes. It is hoped that the " (Juestions" following each Lesson will enhance its help- fulness both to the teacher and the student. The author ventures to hope that the emphasis laid upon the limitations of Physiological Psychology and upon education as a preparation for rational living ; above all, that his constant effort to keep the essential difficulties of the subject in such full view as to prevent the student from mistaking his easy mastery of this elementary book for a real mastery of the science of which the book treats are essential features which will be commended. The object of the author throughout has been to call the attention of his readers to important mental facts in such a way as to set them to observing their own minds and the minds of their pupils, in order to see for them- selves the usefulness of the facts and the experience so gained, their application to the daily work of teaching, and their inestimable value as an added factor toward success. Profoundly convinced as he is of the importance of a knowledge of Psychology to the teacher, he is quite as strongly convinced that the only really fruitful knowledge of Psychology which the teacher will ever gain, he will derive from a study of his own mind and the minds of the people with whom he comes in contact, and that books about Psychology are useful chiefly as they give sugges- tions in this direction. In other words, the aim of the PREFACE. V author has been to act the part of a guide in a strange city> to tell his readers where to look to find valuable truths. If he succeeds in stimulating them to become diligent students of their own minds and the minds of their pupils, he will be more than satisfied. The author wishes to make acknowledgment to his col- leagues, Dr. Bleile and Mr. Wissler, for suggestions relating to the chapters on Physiological Psychology. J. P. G. OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY, COLUMBUS, OHIO, Feb. 8, 1898. CONTENTS. LESSON I. PAGE THE BENEFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY TO THE TEACHER i LESSON II. THE BENEFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY TO THE TEACHER continued 8 LESSON III. BODY AND MIND . . . . . . . . .16 LESSON IV. THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM ..... 25 ' LESSON V. THE FUNCTIONS OF THE NERVOUS SYSTEM ... 41 LESSON VI. THE FUNCTIONS OF THE CEREBRUM 53 LESSON VII. WHAT is PSYCHOLOGY? 65 LESSON VIII. THE SUBJECT MATTER OF PSYCHOLOGY .... 72 vii v jji CONTENTS. LESSON IX. PAGE 77 THE METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY . LESSON X. N, , KSSARY TRUTHS AND NECESSARY BELIEFS ... 86 LESSON XI. 94 WHAT ARE WE CONSCIOUS OF? . LESSON XII. . 103 ATTENTION LESSON XIII. . no ATTENTION continued LESSON XIV. .. . 118 ATTENTION continued LESSON XV. ATTENTION continued ! 3 LESSON XVI. ATTENTION continued . . . H 2 LESSON XVII. KNOWING, FEELING, AND WILLING *5 2 LESSON XVIII. SENSATION 1 3 LESSON XIX. SKNSATION continued J 73 LESSON XX. THE LAW OF HABIT 183 CONTENTS. IX LESSON XXI. ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS 196 LESSON XXII. PERCEPTION 208 LESSON XXIII. PERCEPTION continued . . . . . . -215 LESSON XXIV. PERCEPTION AND EDUCATION 224 LESSON XXV. MEMORY 234 LESSON XXVI. THE CULTIVATION OF THE MEMORY 242 LESSON XXVII. IMAGINATION 255 LESSON XXVIII. IMAGINATION continued 263 LESSON XXIX. CONCEPTION 273 LESSON XXX. CONCEPTION continued 281 LESSON XXXI. CONCEPTION continued 288 LESSON XXXII. CONCEPTION continued 296 x CONTENTS. LESSON XXXIII. PAGB . 305 JUDGMENT LESSON XXXIV. JUDGMENT continued 3 12 LESSON XXXV. REASONING 32 LESSON XXXVI. KI.ASOMNG continued 3 2 9 LESSON XXXVII. REASONING continued 339 LESSON XXXVIII. APPERCEPTION . 346 LESSON XXXIX. APPERCEPTION continued 354 LESSON XL. NATURE OF DEVELOPMENT 364 LESSON XLI. THE END OK EDUCATION 373 LESSON XLII. THK STUDY OK INDIVIDUALS 384 Ai-rixnix A, B 394 INDEX 395 GORDY'S NEW PSYCHOLOGY. LESSON I. THE BENEFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY TO THE TEACHER. WE all believe that it is worth while to study a great many things of which we do not expect to make any practi- cal use. You believe, for example, that it is a good thing to study algebra and geometry, not because you think the knowledge of them is likely to be useful to you unless you should be called upon to teach them but because you think the study of them will develop your mind. Reasons for Studying Psychology. Probably that is one of the reasons why you wish to study Psychology. And it certainly is a good reason for studying it. Few subjects are better calculated to develop the power of thinking than Psychology. You know that the way to develop any power of the mind is to use it, and it is quite impossible to make any headway in studying Psychology without thinking. That is the reason why it is so hard, Develops Power of Thought. When any one makes an assertion about your mind and that is what human 2 BENEFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY. Psychology consists of, assertions about your mind and the minds of all human beings it is often, indeed generally, impossible to realize what it means without thinking. Thus, suppose I say that a mental fact is known directly to but one person, and that one the person experiencing it. In order to realize what that means, you have to look into your own mind for an example of a mental fact. You recall the oft-repeated assertion, no one knows what any one thinks but himself, and you realize that a thought is a mental fact known to but one person directly, and that one the person experiencing it. But in order to know what other facts are mental facts, you must think long and carefully, until you have made up your mind just what facts are known to but one person directly, and that one the person experiencing them. Even when you can understand an assertion that any one makes about your mind without looking into your own mind, it is generally necessary for you to do so before you can decide intelligently whether or not it is true. If any one says that you can not get the continuous attention of your pupils without asking questions, or without giving them some other motive for attending besides interest, that statement can be understood without special effort. But in order to determine whether or not it is true, you must look into your own wind. You must ask yourself whether any one can keep your attention for a half or three-quarters of an hour simply by being interesting. If you set about answering it in the right way, you will think until you recall some speaker who never asked you ques- tions, or did anything except try to interest you to keep your attention, but who was interesting ; then I am sure you will remember that when he was -speaking your mind PRACTICAL REASONS. 3 wandered much more than it would have done if you had known that, when he had finished, he would question you about what he was saying. You will remember that you often allowed your mind to dwell on interesting points that he raised, to the exclusion of what he said directly after. For these two reasons (i) because you can not under- stand most of the assertions in Psychology without think- ing ; and (2) because, even when you understand them, you can not tell without thinking whether or not they are true I know of no subject better calculated to make a pupil think, and therefore better fitted to develop the power of thinking, than Psychology. Practical Reasons. But apart from this, you wish to study Psychology for quite practical reasons. As a man who intends to be a surveyor studies trigonometry, not merely because it will develop his mind, but because of the use it will be to him, so you study Psychology because you think the knowledge of it will make you a better teacher. Nature of Teaching. How will it help you in this direction ? Before you can answer this question, you must answer another. What is teaching ? People used to intimate what they thought of this by saying that a teacher "keeps school." But "keeping school" is not teaching. Nor is it to teach to hear recitations. To teach is to deal with mind is to get it to DO something which it would not have done apart from the teacher, in order to get it to BECOME something which it would not have become apart from him. In order to do this intelligently, you plainly need to 4 BENEFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY. have as clear an idea as possible of what you wish your pupils to become. If your pupils were everything that you wish them to become, you would not undertake to teach them. What is it that you wish them to become ? In what respect do you wish them to change as the result of your teaching ? That question, the study of Psychology will help you to answer ; and the more you know about Psychology, the more clearly and fully and definitely you can answer it. Meaning of Development. Quite likely you think you can answer it now. You say you wish your pupils to have better developed minds at the end of each day than they had at the beginning. But better developed in what direction ? The North American Indians had remarkable powers of observation. They could track an enemy through a forest where you could see no trace of a human being. Will you be content to have your pupils acquire powers similar to those possessed by the North American Indians ? Is this what you wish them to become ? The Chinese have remarkable memories. Many educated Chinamen remember almost word for word the nine classics compiled and edited by Confucius. Do you want your pupils to have minds like the Chinese ? I do not, of course, mean to imply that you should not aim to cultivate the observing powers of your pupils as well as their memories. But the North American Indians developed their powers of observation at the expense of the higher powers of their minds, and the Chinese their mechanical memory in the same costly way. And yet the Chinese aim at development. It is evident, there- fore, that when one says that the object of education NECESSITY OF A DEFINITE AIM. 5 is development, he has not expressed a very definite idea. The question is, What kind of development? and that question Psychology will help us answer. Necessity of a Definite Aim. So you see that when you say you want to help your pupils develop their minds, you have by no means proved that you know precisely what, as an intelligent teacher, you ought to aim at. And unless we know what to aim at, we can not hope to have success. Do you think an architect could build a beauti- ful house if he began to build it and worked at it from day to day without having in his mind, so to speak, the house he was trying to build ? Well, if a carpenter must have a picture in his mind of the kind of house he wishes to build in order to build it, how can we hope to succeed in moulding and forming the minds of our pupils in an intelligent way, unless we have the clearest ideas of what we wish them to become ? Need of a Criterion of Knowledge. But at any rate, perhaps you think you are clear as to one thing in which you wish your pupils to change ; you wish them to become less ignorant you wish them to know more. But to know more of what ? We have not got. very far when we say that we wish to help our pupils to acquire knowledge, unless we have made up our minds as to what knowledge is worth acquiring. There is a good deal of history in the text-books which is not worth learning, and a good deal out of them which is in the highest degree important, and the same is true of the other subjects we teach. How are we to make up our minds what knowledge is worth acquir- ing ? The study of Psychology will help us do that. It 6 BENEFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY. will help us see the effect which the acquiring of this or that piece of knowledge will have on the mind, and in this way enable us to estimate its worth. Here again it is evident that it is quite impossible to succeed in teaching unless in some way we are able to decide intelligently what we ought to get our pupils to learn. Until we are able to decide that, we can, in the first place, aim only to get them to learn everything in the text-book. This is bad for two reasons : in the first place, text-books are sometimes written by men who know so little of the subject that they can not tell what is important and what is not important ; and in the second place, intel- ligent men put many things in text-books, not that students may learn them, but that they may be able to refer to them if they have occasion to use them. No one but a fool would commit to memory a railroad guide. And yet railroad guides are very useful; but when any one has occasion for them, he goes to them. He remembers what he finds there just as long as he wants it, and then does not trouble his head with it any longer. Now, intelligent men put many such facts in the books they write facts which they do not expect any one to learn, but to which they think persons may sometimes have occasion to refer. For these two reasons, it is very unfortunate for a teacher to have to rely entirely upon his text-books in deciding what to teach. The study of Psychology, then, will help us see what we ought to aim at. It will help us see the kind of develop- ment we ought to try to help them get, and the kind of knowledge we ought to try to impart. QUESTIONS. 7 QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1. What are the two reasons for studying Psychology? 2. How is any power of the mind developed? 3. What are the two reasons which make the study of Psychology so useful in developing the power to think? 4. What is teaching? 5. Give two illustrations to show that when you say you wish your pupils to have better developed minds, your statement lacks clearness. 6. Show that you can not succeed as a teacher unless you know what to aim at. 7. Show that when you say you wish to make your pupils less ignorant, your statement lacks clearness. 8. How will the study of Psychology help you in this direction? 9. Why should not a teacher limit himself to teaching what is in the text-books ? 10. What is the central thought which this lesson aims to bring out? SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1. Which do you regard as the more important service rendered by the study of Psychology to the teacher increasing his power to think, or expanding his knowledge of the conditions under which the mind acts ? 2. One writer speaks of a certain kind of memory as the "index" memory, and another of another kind as the " mechanical " memory. Can you get from this lesson any idea of what they are? 3. Do you believe that it is possible to train the powers of obser- vation in general, i.e., to train them in such a way that their pos- sessor will be a good observer of any kind of facts ? LESSON II. THK KKNKFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY TO THE TEACHER. (Continued.) Conditions of Success. To succeed well in any diffi- cult undertaking, three things are necessary: (i) one must see clearly the thing to be done ; (2) he must have a clear idea of the best means of doing it ; and (3) he must have a strong motive for doing it well. He in whom these conditions meet most perfectly who sees most clearly the thing to be done, who has the clearest percep- tion of the best means of doing it, who has the strongest motive for making strenuous efforts to do it is the per- son most likely to succeed in any difficult undertaking. The study of Psychology can not be urged on the ground that it is likely to do much toward making the u-acher interested in his work, and more willing, therefore, to work hard in order to do it well. It is not, indeed, without effect in this direction. The work of teachers who make no study of mind is likely to be mechanical, while the work of teachers who base their efforts on a knowledge of mind is rational. And mechanical work is uninteresting, unattractive fit only for machines. Any- thing, therefore, which tends to make a teacher's work rational certainly tends to make it interesting. This was what Fitch meant when he called teaching the noblest of arts and the sorriest of trades. Practiced mechanically, PSYCHOLOGY AND TEACHING. 9 it is indeed a trade, and a sorry one at that ; practiced rationally practiced by one who realizes that he is deal- ing with mind, and who uses this method or that, not because some one else has used it, but because his knowl- edge of mind leads him to believe that a given method is the best teaching is the noblest of arts. Psychology and Teaching. But while the study of Psychology is of some benefit to the teacher in that it tends to give him more interest in his work, I do not urge it on this ground. It is for the other two reasons, ( i ) be- cause of the clearness which it is fitted to give to the aim of the intelligent teacher, and (2) because of the light it throws on the best methods of realizing that aim, that I believe no teacher who is ambitious to succeed should neglect to study those phases of Psychology that bear on education. In the last lesson I tried to show what the study of Psychology can do for us in the first direction. I tried to show that when we are able to say that our aim is to bring about the development of our pupils, we have not got very far unless we have made up our minds as to the value, so to speak, of the various faculties of the mind that unless we know the worth of the observing powers, and of the various kinds of memory, imagination, and reasoning, we can not proceed intelligently in training them. In like manner, unless we have made up our minds as to " what knowledge is of most worth," I tried to show that it is of little use to be able to say that we wish to induce our pupils to acquire knowledge. I tried further to show that Psychology, by helping us discover the relation of the various powers of the mind to each other, will help us determine the kind of development we ought to aim at ; I0 BENEFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY. and also, that by helping us see the effect of the various kinds of knowledge upon the mind, it will help us decide "what knowledge is of most worth." But not only will the study of Psychology tend to give clearness and definiteness to our aim, it will tend quite as strongly to show what we must do to realize that aim. Methods Used in Dealing with Objects in the Mate- rial World. In dealing with mind we must use the same kinds of methods which we use when we deal with objects in the material world. What we accomplish in the mate- rial world we accomplish by putting objects where they will be subject to new influences, so that the forces of nature may do the work we wish to have done. Mortar in one place and bricks in another do nothing to make the walls of a house, but place the bricks on a strong founda- tion, and put the mortar between them, and you have a strong wall. All you have done, you will note, is to move the bricks and mortar so as to put them in new positions and make them subject to new influences, so that the forces of nature may do the desired work. Heat water to the boiling-point, and it will change into steam ; and if you leave it where it can escape, nothing will come of it. But move the water into a confined place, so that the steam can not escape, and then you can make it drive immense palaces across the sea, or pull huge trains across the continent. Every invention which has ever been made is simply a way of moving things into new positions where they are subject to new influences, so that the forces of nature may do the desired work. All the force that is employed in nature exists in nature. All that man accomplishes he accomplishes by making the forces of METHODS IN DEALING WITH THE MIND. I I nature worfc under different circumstances, and by turn- ing them into different channels from those in which they wotild have worked apart from him. It is by making nature our servant that we have made such wonderful progress in material civilization in the nineteenth century. How is it that we have been able to make nature work for us in such wonderful ways ? Simply by knowing the laws of nature. Knowing the laws of nature, we have been able, so to speak, to foresee what she would do under cer- tain circumstances, and the result is the steam-engine, the telegraph, the telephone, the phonograph, and all the other inventions which minister to our well-being. Methods to be Used in Dealing with the Mind. In dealing with mind we must work in the same way. As everything which happens in nature is due to the laws of nature, so everything which happens in mind is due to the laws of mind. As our power in nature depends upon the skill with which we get her to work for us, so our power in dealing with mind depends upon our ability to get it so to act that the results we desire will follow. As success in dealing with nature consists in supplying the conditions which make it possible for nature to do the desired work, so success in dealing with the mind consists in supplying the conditions which make it possible for the mind to do the work we want it to do. And as the better we know the laws of nature (in other words, the better we know the con- ditions under which nature will produce this or that result) the better we can supply those conditions ; so the better we know the laws of the mind (in other words, the better we know the conditions under which the mind will do this or that, the better we can supply these conditions. The 12 BENEFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY. aim of the teacher being a certain kind of development, and the communication of a certain kind of knowledge, evidently the more he knows of the conditions under which the mind develops, and the conditions under which it acquires knowledge, the better he can supply them. Difference in this Respect between Natural Agent and the Mind. " But is there no difference," you may ask, "between a natural agent and the human mind in this regard ? May we say of the human mind, as we may of a natural agent, that it will always do all the work it can under the given condition ? " There is an important difference, but it makes for rather than against the skillful teacher. A natural agent can not be flattered, bribed, or cajoled ; it takes no account of intentions or motives. In dealing with a natural agent, the one single, simple, all- determining question is, Are the conditions fulfilled ? If they are fulfilled, the effect will follow ; if they are not fulfilled, the effect will not follow. But the case is dif- ferent with the human mind. When we have put the mind under the right influences, it has a natural tendency to the kind of activity we wish to occasion ; but this ten- dency may be increased or diminished by purely personal relations. A teacher who adapts the subject of instruction to the mental condition of his pupil creates a tendency in the mind of his pupil to follow his instruction with interest. But if by impatience, ill-humor, or sarcastic remarks the teacher has excited the antagonism of the pupil, the pupil resists the tendency ; he is unwilling to do what he knows his teacher desires. If, on the other hand, the teacher by patience and industry and kindness has gained the regard of his pupil, the pupil exerts himself to attend to the sub- WHY PUPILS DO NOT LEARN. 13 ject. In this way it happens that personal qualities may atone, to some extent, for lack of skill on the part of the teacher. Do you ask if a corresponding increase in the teacher's knowledge of mind, and a corresponding increase in his skill in basing his work on that knowledge would enable him to work such miracles in the minds of his pupils as inventors have worked in nature through their knowledge of the laws of nature ? I can not, of course, answer such a question. No one can. But in the School of the Far-off Future' when no teacher will be allowed to enter a school-room who has not made a thorough study of educa- tional Psychology, and who has not proved to the entire satisfaction of competent judges his ability to apply what he has learned in that school there will be no dull, list- less, inattentive pupils. There will be no boys who leave school because they do not like it. There will be no pupils who hate books. Why Pupils do not Learn. As a child learns not only rapidly but with intense pleasure from the time of his birth to the time he starts to school simply because the activities in which he spontaneously engages are fitted to his state of development, so he will continue to learn rapidly and with intense pleasure after he starts to school if the work he is set to doing is adapted to his state of development. Answer of Comenius. Do you know who Comenius was ? It was he who said that if our pupils do not learn it is our fault. And he was undoubtedly right. If we supplied the proper conditions, our pupils would as certainly learn I4 BENEFITS OF PSYCHOLOGY. as a train will move when the engineer turns on the steam. Answer of Pestalozzi. Do you know who Pestalozzi was ? It was he who said that if pupils are inattentive the teacher should first look to himself for the reason. He also was undoubtedly right. As certainly as a blade of com will grow and mature if it is treated right if the proper conditions are supplied so certainly will our pupils attend, and think as the result of attending, and develop as the result of thinking, if we supply the proper conditions. Can Conditions of Learning Always be Supplied ? " If we supply the proper conditions." It is but truth to say that that sometimes is beyond our power under the circumstances in which we are obliged to work. Some pupils have so little capacity for a subject that to supply the proper conditions would require an amount of atten- tion which the teacher can not possibly give them. It is doubtful also if there are not cases in which there is so little capacity for a subject as to make it a waste of time for the pupil to attempt to study it. A case came under my own observation of a boy who would spend jive hoiirs on a spelling lesson, and still miss nine words out of ten. I am strongly inclined to the opinion that spelling was an accomplishment which he could not afford to acquire. (.SVr Appendix A.) QUESTIONS. 15 QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1 . What three things are essential to success in a difficult under- taking ? 2. What can the study of Psychology do to make a teacher inter- ested in his work ? 3. What did Fitch say about teaching, and what did he mean by it ? 4. How will the study of Psychology help a teacher to see at what he should aim ? 5. How do men accomplish anything in nature ? 6. Illustrate your statement. 7. Show that the same thing is true in our dealings with mind. 8. Do you believe that teachers could accomplish as wonderful results in dealing with the minds of their pupils as inventors have accomplished in dealing with nature, if they knew as much about mind ? 9. Why do so many pupils dislike the work of school ? 10. What did Comenius say is the reason our pupils do not learn? 11. Is there anything in our system of classification which increases the difficulty of adapting our work to individual pupils so as to make it pleasant to them ? 12. What can be done to obviate this ? SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1 . Who is Fitch ? 2. What book on education has he written ? 3. Who was Comenius ? When did he live ? 4. Who was Pestalozzi, and when was he born ? 5. What reform did he work in education ? LESSON III. BODY AND MIND. Connection between Body and Mind. We all know that there is an intimate connection between body and mind. We know that when our eyes are open we see, and when they are closed, we do not see ; that when our hands, or other parts of the body, are in contact with an object we have a sensation of touch, and when they are not, we do not. We know that when we deprive our bodies of proper nourishment, as in fasting, we have a headache, and the longer we fast, the more incapable we become of any kind of mental exertion. We know that any derange- ment of the bodily functions produces an immediate effect upon the mind. We know that tea and coffee stimulate, and that alcoholic liquors intoxicate. Many a student has brought upon himself a feeling of bodily exhaustion through purely mental labor ; or, by a long tramp or some other form of prolonged physical exertion, he has produced a feeling of mental exhaustion. In other words, prolonged mental labor not only fatigues the mind but the body; prolonged physical labor not only fatigues the body but the mind. Those are a few of the familiar facts which have made it impossible for any one to doubt that there is a very close relation between the body and the mind. 16 THE BRAIN AND THE MIND. I'J Opinion of the Greeks as to the Connection of the Brain and the Mind. But it is by no means so evident that the brain is the part of the body which is in some sort of direct relation with the mind, and that the rest of the body influences the mind only through its relation to the brain. We shall realize this if we remember that though the Greek physician, Alcmaeon regarded the brain as the common meeting-place of the senses, and this opinion was accepted by Plato, yet Aristotle, himself the son of a doctor, and one of the greatest of the Greek philosophers, rejected it. He said that the brain was a lump of cold substance, useful .as the source of the fluid which lubricates the eyes, but quite unfit to be the organ of mind. What is the evidence which has led physiologists to conclude that he was mistaken ? Effect on Consciousness of a Blow on the Head. It is a matter of direct experience that the connection between consciousness and the brain is closer than that between consciousness and any other part of the body. A blow on the head may deprive us of consciousness ; a blow on any other part of the body, as a rule, only inflicts pain. It is indeed true that a blow on the heart may cause uncon- sciousness. But that is because the blow may prevent the heart from sending to the brain its proper supply of blood. The Nerves Compared with Telegraph Wires. More- over, the pain that we feel from a blow on any other part of the body depends upon the brain. Cut the nerve that connects one of the fingers with the brain, and an injury inflicted upon it makes no impression on consciousness. jg BODY AND MIND. The relation between the body and the brain may be roughly compared to the relation between a telegraph wire and the receiving office. The telegraph wire is important because it is the medium through which the messages are transmitted to the receiving office. But it is the machinery at the receiving office which makes the receipt of messages possible. And precisely as no message can be received if the telegraph wire is cut or injured, so no effect is pro- duced upon the brain, and therefore none on conscious- ness, if the nerves connecting an injured part of the body with the brain are injured. There is a rough resemblance between the relation of consciousness to the brain, and that of the ringing of a bell to the striking of its sides by its clapper. Cause the bell by any means to swing to and fro so that the clapper strikes its sides, and you cause it to ring. Affect the brain in any way, either by a blow on the head, or by increasing or decreasing the quantity of blood that supplies it, or by changing its quality, and you affect consciousness. Pulling the bell-rope only causes the bell to ring because it causes the clapper to strike the sides of the bell. When we see how closely pain follows upon an injury inflicted on any part of the body, we might suppose that the bodily injury is the direct cause of the consciousness of pain. But when we remember that the bodily injury affects consciousness only as the effect of the injury is communicated to the brain, we see that it is the effect upon the brain that influences consciousness. The Supply of Blood to the Brain. This conclusion, which facts familiar to all of us render highly probable, may be regarded as demonstrated by the conclusions of MOSSO S TABLE. IQ science. While the weight of the entire brain is only about one forty-second of the weight of the body, it has been calculated that the supply of blood used by the brain is one eighth of that used by the whole body. How essen- tial this supply of blood is, becomes evident if it is in any way interfered with. Stop one of the great arteries lead- ing to the brain by compression in the neck or in any other way, and great disturbances in consciousness at once appear, even to the point of its entire cessation. One investigator, Dr. Lombard, found that the temperature of the head varies rapidly, though slightly, during waking hours. By careful measurements with delicate thermo- electric apparatus he found that " every cause that attracts the attention a noise, or the sight of some person or other object produces elevation of temperature. An elevation of temperature also occurs under the influence of an emotion, or during an interesting reading aloud." 1 Mosso's Table. If it were possible to doubt that this rise in temperature is due to an increase in the blood supplied to the brain, that possibility would seem to be removed by the experiments of an Italian investigator named Mosso. He devised a table so accurately balanced that a man might recline on it without disturbing its balance. He found that its balance was at once destroyed by any cause that quickened the activity of the subject's consciousness. A sudden noise, an interesting thought, anything that increased the activity of consciousness, would cause the head end of the table to sink down as quickly as if a weight had been placed upon it. 1 Quoted by Ladd, Physiological Psychology, p. 242. 2O BODY AND MIND. Localization of Cerebral Functions. All the argu- ments in support of what is called the localization of cerebral functions are so many arguments to show that the brain is the organ of the mind. These arguments we will con- sider in a later chapter. Suffice it here to say that it has been proved to the satisfaction of physiologists and psy- chologists, not only that the brain is the organ of mind, but that particular parts of the brain are connected in a pecu- liarly close and intimate way with certain mental activities. Evidently every argument in support of this conclusion is equally good to show that the brain is the organ of the mind. A large number of experiments made upon the lower animals prove the same fact. First one part and then another of the brain of various lower animals (frogs and pigeons, for example) has been removed for the purpose of ascertaining what part of the brain is connected with par- ticular classes of mental operations. And though the phenomena vary with the animal, and with the part of the brain removed, to say nothing of the skill of the operator, the facts taken together leave no doubt of the special con- nection between the brain and the mind. The American Crow-bar Case. For obvious reasons such experiments have not been performed upon the brains of men, but disease and accident have performed them for us. One of the most famous of these experiments is that which is now known as the American crow-bar case. While a young man named Gage was " tamping a blasting charge in a rock with a pointed iron bar, 3 feet 7 inches in length, i inches in diameter, and weighing 13*. Ibs., the charge suddenly exploded. The iron bar, propelled with its pointed end first, entered at the left angle of the AMERICAN CROW-BAR CASE. 21 patient's jaw, and passed clean through the top of his head, near the sagittal suture in the frontal region, and was picked up at some distance covered with blood and brains. The patient was for a moment stunned, but, within an hour after the accident, he was able to walk up a long flight of stairs and give the surgeon an intelligible account of the injury he had sustained. His life naturally was for a long time despaired of ; but he ultimately recovered, and lived twelve and a half years afterwards. . . . The whole track of the bar is included in that region of the brain which I have described as the praefrontal region. . . . Hear what Dr. Harlow (in a paper read in 1868 before the Massachusetts Medical Society) says as to his mental con- dition : ' His contractors, who regarded him as the most efficient and capable foreman in their employ previous to his injury, considered the change in his mind so marked that they could not give him his place again. The equi- librium or balance, so to speak, between his intellectual faculties and animal propensities seems to have been de- stroyed. He is fitful, irreverent, indulging at times in the grossest profanity (which was not previously his custom), manifesting but little deference to his fellows, impatient of restraint or advice when it conflicts with his desires, at times pertinaciously obstinate, yet capricious and vacillat- ing, devising many plans of future operation, which are no sooner arranged than they are abandoned in turn for others more feasible. A child in his intellectual capacity and manifestations, he has the animal passions of a strong man. Previously to his injury, though untrained in the schools, he possessed a well-balanced mind, and was looked upon by the people who knew him as a shrewd, smart business man, very energetic and persistent in executing all his 22 BODY AND MIND. plans of operation. In this regard, his mind was radically changed, so decidedly, that his friends and acquaintances said he was no longer Gage.' " Impairment of Memory Due to Injury of the Brain. - It is a matter of common knowledge that injuries to the brain often result in an impairment of memory. Forbes Winslow notes a remarkable case of a soldier upon whom the operation of trephining had been performed and who lost a portion of his brain. The result was that he forgot the numbers five and seven, and those only. After a time his memory of these numbers was restored. Numerous cases are on record of the impairment of memory in con- sequence of a violent blow on the head. Aphasia. Very significant as to the dependence of mind on brain are the phenomena designated by the general term aphasia. Dr. Bateman says the term is used "to designate that condition in which the intelligence is unaffected, or at all events but slightly impaired ; when thoughts are conceived by the patient but he can not express himself, either because he has lost the memory of words, or because he has lost the memory of the mechan- ical process necessary for the pronunciation of these words; or because the rupture of the means of communication between the gray matter of the brain and the organs, whose co-operation is necessary to produce speech, does not allow the will to act upon them in a normal manner as the ideas are formed, but the means of communication with the external world do not exist." 2 1 Quoted by Calderwood in The Relations of Mind and Brain, pp. 479- 481, from Terrier's Localization of Cerebral Disease. 3 Quoted by Calderwood, p. 388. MOTOR APHASIA. 23 Motor Aphasia. The foregoing definition, as we shall see in a later chapter, covers phenomena widely different from each other. A man who can understand what is said to him, but who can not talk, is said to suffer from motor aphasia. He knows what he wants to say, but he has lost control of the mechanism of speech. Sufferers from another kind of aphasia have perfect control of the mechan- ism of speech. They can talk, but they can not under stand what is said to them. They can hear, but they can not grasp the meaning of what is said to them. Now in cases of motor aphasia it has been proved that the cause of the difficulty is located in a definitely ascer- tained part of the brain. Says Professor James : "When- ever a patient dies in such a condition as this and an examination of his brain is permitted, it is found that the lowest frontal gyrus is the seat of injury." Correspondence between Size and Weight of Brain, and Intelligence. Still another class of facts may be pointed out as indicating the closeness of the relation between the mind and the brain. Comparative anatomy shows that there is a general, though indefinite, corre- spondence of the place of an animal in the scale of intel- ligence, to the size and weight of its brain compared with the bulk of its entire body. In other words, as a rule, the larger and heavier the brain of an animal in comparison with the weight of its entire body, the higher it is in the scale of intelligence. As Professor Ladd says, " The law itself is confessedly subject to remarkable and unexplained exceptions ; at best it only holds good in a general way. For example, the relative weight of the brain is not greatly different in the dolphin, in the baboon, and in 24 BODY AND MIND. man." Nevertheless, it may fairly be regarded as adding to the evidence which has convinced physiologists and psychologists that the brain is the organ of the mind. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1. Mention some of the facts that prove the dependence of the mind upon the body. 2. Show how essential to consciousness is a plentiful supply of blood to the brain. 3. What is meant by aphasia ? 4. State the details of the American crow-bar case. 5. What is the relation between the size and weight of the brain of an animal, and its position in the scale of intelligence ? SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1. What is meant by the localization of functions ? 2. Have any cases of impairment of memory from injury to the brain come under your observation ? LESSON IV. THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM. IN the preceding chapter we have considered the evi- dence which seems to prove that the brain is the organ of the mind. Let us in this chapter endeavor to get an idea of that wonderful mechanism of which the brain consti- tutes the most conspicuous part. Let us try to get an idea of the central nervous system. We learned in the last lesson that there is a direct con- nection between the outside of the body and the brain. If your hand comes in contact with a hot stove, you quickly become aware of it through sensations of touch and of pain. There is an equally direct connection between the brain and the muscles that move the hand. As soon as you become conscious of the sensation of pain you snatch your hand away. Nerves and Tendons. If you dissect the body of one of the higher animals, you will see some of the machinery by means of which such phenomena are brought about. You will see numerous white cords which look like tendons those dense white cords in which a muscle terminates, and which attach the muscles to the bones of the body. But that these white cords are not muscles, is shown by the fact that many of them are not connected with muscles 25 2 6 THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM. at all and those which are, usually enter the central part of the muscle, instead of being attached to its end as ten- dons usually are. These cords are nerves. If you follow them in one direction, they subdivide into smaller and smaller branches until they become too small to be seen without the aid of the microscope. If you fol- low them in the opposite direction, they become larger and larger through uniting with similar nerves until they enter a much larger mass, whose structure and appearance differ widely from that of the nerves which enter it. This mass is called a nerve centre. Nerve Fibres and Nerve Cells. Nerves are composed of one or more nervous elements called nerve fibres, bound together by connective tissue. The chief constituent of a nerve centre is nerve cells. Nerve fibres and nerve cells differ in density, shape and chemical composition. Fibrous nerve matter contains more water than cellular nerve mat- ter, and is therefore less dense than the latter. They differ in their shape. Fibres are long "thread-like connec- tions," while nerve cells have a great variety of forms. " Some are nearly round ; others ovoidal, caudate, stellate, or shaped like a flask or the blade of a paddle." Nerve fibres and nerve cells differ in size. Nerve fibres vary from about -j-g^ry to -^\^ of an inch in diameter, while nerve cells vary from about ?fa to -5^5 of an inch. It is supposed that there are not less than two and a half mil- lions of sensory nerve fibres alone, while man's entire central nervous system is reckoned to have about three thousand million nerve cells. Nerve fibres are never found apart from nerve cells. Indeed, recent investigation has shown that the fibre is an NERVE FIBRES AND NERVE CELLS. 2/ outgrowth or prolongation of the cell. 1 A nerve cell with its prolongation into a nerve fibre constitutes the unit of the nervous system. The essential element of a nerve fibre is called its axis-cylinder. Near the ending of a nerve fibre it is the only constituent of the fibre that is FIG. i. Isolated body of a large cell from the ventral horn of the spinal cord. Human, X 2 diameters. A, fibre or fibrous element ; Z>, dendrons ; A 7 ", nucleus with enclosures ; P, pigment spot. (Modified from Donaldson.) left ; the other elements the transparent envelope, called the primitive sheath, and the fatty substance, called the medullary sheath, which the primitive sheath encloses and which usually encloses the axis-cylinder being wanting. 1 The term neuron is applied to the cell with all of its prolongations, of which the fibre is only one. The other prolongations of a cell are called dendrons. 28 THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM. Two Functions of the Nervous System. We may regard the nervous system as a mechanism having two great functions to perform : (i) reporting the condition of the outside world to the individual, and enabling him to control his actions accordingly ; and (2) binding the various parts of the body into an interdependent whole. The first function we are too familiar with to make extended illustration necessary. A person suffering from rheumatism, feeling a draught of cold air, gets up and FIG. 2. Longitudinal and transverse (A) sections of nerve fibres. The heavy border represents the medullary sheath, which becomes thicker in the larger fibres. Sciatic nerve. Human, X 4 diameters. (Donaldson.) closes the window. His nerves report the condition of the outside world ; his nerves set in motion the machinery the proper muscles by means of which he closes the window. The one action may be compared with the tele- phoning to the fire department of a city that a building in a certain part of it is on fire ; the other to the sending of engines to extinguish the fire. The same illustration may be used to illustrate the second function of the nervous system, the binding to- gether of the various parts of the body into one inter- FUNCTIONS OF FIBRES AND CELLS. 2Q dependent whole. When a draught of cold air strikes the body, apart from the voluntary motion which it may occa- sion, its effects may be felt throughout the entire body. The heart and lungs may modify their activity ; some of the involuntary muscles may contract ; and a shudder may run through the entire physical organism. 1 Martin well says that in common life "the very fre- quency of this uniting activity of the nervous system is such that we are apt to entirely overlook it. We do not wonder how the sight of pleasant food will make the mouth water and the hand reach out for it ; it seems, as we say, 'natural,' and to need no explanation. But the eye itself can excite no desire, cause the secretion of no saliva, and the movement of no limb. The whole complex result depends on the fact that the eye is united by the optic nerve with the brain, and that again by other nerves with saliva-forming cells, and with muscular fibres of the arm ; and through these a change excited by light falling into the eye is enabled to produce changes in far-removed organs, and excite desire, sensation, and movement." 2 Functions of Fibres and Cells. This general survey of the functions of the nervous system enables us to antici- pate in an indefinite way the work to be done by the two elements of the nervous system. The fibres, or nerves composed of fibres, will have as their function to transmit stimulations from the surface or outer part of the body to the nerve centres, and to transmit impulses from those centres to the muscles. The cells, or centres composed of cells, will have as their function to receive the stimula- 1 Cf. Ladd, Physiological Psychology, p. 19. 2 Martin's Physiology, p. 208. 30 THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM. tions transmitted by the nerves, and to send impulses along the nerves to the muscles. Afferent and Efferent Nerves. The nerves, accord- ingly, may be divided into two classes : the first class connect some sensitive structure as the skin, the retina, the nervous membrane of the stomach, at their peripheral termination, with the centre ; the second connect the cen- tre with the muscles to which they are attached at their peripheral termination. The first class are excited to activity by some structure at their peripheral termination, and transmit nervous action to the centre. They are, therefore, called afferent, in-carrying, or centripetal nerves. The second class are excited to activity by the nerve centres with which they are connected, and transmit nervous excitation to the mus- cles with which they are connected at their peripheral extremity. They are, therefore, called efferent, out-carry- ing, centrifugal, or motor nerves. The most important of the afferent nerves for Psychology are those which are called sensory nerves, because they connect the sense organs eyes, ears and so on with the nerve centres. The most important of the motor nerves for Psychology are those which connect the nerve centres with the "voluntary" muscles those of the hands, arms, legs, eyes, for example. Nature of the Sense Organs. The greater part of the sense organs consist largely of mechanical contriv- ances whose function is to modify the external stimulus, and convey the impulse imparted by it to the nerves of sense. NATURE OF THE SENSE ORGANS. 31 For example, the nose consists in large part of a mechanism for bringing the particles of odorous sub- stances in contact with that part of the mucous mem- brane of the nose in which the olfactory nerve terminates. In order that an object may be smelled, it is not enough that an odorous substance be held near the nose. A current of air containing particles of the odorous sub- stance must be drawn through the nose, and thus brought into contact with the terminal fibres of the olfactory nerve. In like manner the ear consists for the most part of a mechanism whose function is to modify the waves of sound, and transmit them so modified to the internal ear, in which the fibres of the auditory nerve terminate. When the vibrations of air reach the tympanum, they have too large an amplitude, and too little intensity, to occasion these vibrations in the elements of the internal ear, which are essential to the excitation of the auditory nerve. The tympanum modifies these vibrations so as to adapt them to the excitation of the terminal fibres of the auditory nerve, and at the same time transmits them to the internal ear. So likewise, the eye consists in part of an optical instru- ment, in part of a sensitive nervous membrane called the retina, on which the image resulting from the optical instrument is formed. The eye, as an optical instrument, transmits the stimulations received from light to the nervous elements in the retina in which the optic nerve terminates. The nerve centres with which Psychology is especially interested are those which are found in the encephalon, or contents of the skull, and the spinal cord. 32 THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM. Gray and White Matter. These centres consist of masses of gray and white matter. The white matter con- sists chiefly of nerve fibres; the gray matter, of nerve cells. These cells, as we have seen, have prolongations or out- growths called fibres, of which the axis-cylinder is the most essential element. After the axis-cylinder leaves the cell, it divides into two or more parts. Some of these parts enter the white mass, composed chiefly of nerve fibres, and become part of these fibres. Some pass through this white mass and unite with the parts into which the axis-cylinders, extending from other cells, are divided. Gray Matter of the Brain. The gray matter of the brain is not found in a single compact mass. The cere- brum, located in the upper and front part of the brain, has a covering of gray matter, "like a thin rind," called the cerebral cortex, from ^ to of an inch in thickness. Within the cerebrum, and separated from the gray matter of the cortex by a mass of white matter, are found the large ganglia masses of gray matter which are called the optic thalami. Behind these are the corpora quadri- gemina, and behind these, and forming a part of the out- side surface of the brain, is the cerebellum. These, with the gray masses of the spinal cord, and the medulla ob- longata, the body in which the spinal cord terminates, are the gray masses of the nervous system in which Psychology is especially interested. Spinal Cord. The spinal cord and the brain are con- There is no point where we can say that the one tops and the other begins. Physiologists have, however, greed to regard the cord as commencing opposite the SPINAL CORD. 33 outer margin of the foramen magnum of the occipital bone. Its average diameter is about | of an inch ; its length, 1 7 inches ; and its weight, I \ ounces. It is nearly divided into right and left halves by two fissures, one on the ventral, and the other directly opposite, FIG. 3. The spinal cord and nerve-roots. A, a small portion of the cord seen from the ventral side ; B, the same seen laterally ; C, a cross-section of the cord ; D, the two roots of a spinal nerve ; I, anterior (ventral) fissure ; 2, posterior (dorsal) fissure ; 3, surface groove along the line of attachment of the anterior nerve- roots ; 4, line of origin of the posterior roots ; 5, anterior root filaments of spinal nerve ; 6, posterior root filaments ; 6', ganglion of the posterior root ; 7, 7', the first two divisions of the nerve-trunk after the union of the two roots. (Martin.) on the dorsal side. If we examine a transverse section of the cord, we shall find that it is composed of white and gray matter, and that its white matter surrounds its gray matter, which is arranged "somewhat in the form of a capital H," the horizontal bar representing the gray matter which connects the gray matter in the right and 34 THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM. left halves of the cord, and the two vertical bars represent- ing the gray matter on the right and left of the fissure. The white matter consists of fibres, some traversing it in a horizontal and others in a vertical direction, and a connecting substance called neuroglia. The gray matter consists of ganglion cells and a homogeneous gray mass in FIG. 4. Diagram illustrating the general relationships of the parts of the brain. A, fore-brain ; f>, mid-brain; B, cerebellum ; C, pons Varolii ; D, medulla oblon- gata; B, C, and D together constitute the hind-brain. (Martin.) which a majority of recent observers find a net-work of fine axis-cylinders running in all directions. Thirty-one pairs of nerves enter the spinal cord. Each of these nerves, before entering the cord, divides into a dorsal and ventral part which are called respectively the posterior and the anterior roots of the nerve. The posterior root consists of afferent or sensory fibres, the anterior root of efferent or motor fibres. FOLDS OF THE CORTEX. 35 The brain is much larger than the spinal cord, and much more complex in its structure. The whole brain in the adult male weighs on the average about 50 ounces. Figure 4 illustrates in a general way the position of the various parts of the brain. The fore-brain weighs in man on the average about 44 ounces. It consists chiefly of the cerebrum, which is divided into two parts known as the cerebral hemispheres by a deep fissure which extends through its middle. Folds of the Cortex. The gray cortical rind which constitutes the surface of the cerebrum is folded upon itself many times as appears from Figure 5. These folds are called gyri or convolutions. Their effect is to greatly increase the surface of the brain. It is estimated that if the cortex of the brain of a person of average intelligence were unfolded it would be found to have an area of about four square feet. The folds of the human cortex are deeper and more numerous, as a rule, than those of the most intelligent animals, and in the brains of the most highly civilized nations than in those of savages. For reasons which will be stated in a later chapter, the cortex of the cerebrum is the part of the brain which is supposed to be connected in the closest and most intimate way with intelligence. It is, therefore, important for stu- dents of Psychology to pay special attention to it. If we examine the convolutions of different brains, we shall see that they vary greatly in their details, not only in different individuals, but even in the two hemispheres of the same brain. The convolutions have been divided into primary, secondary and tertiary classes according to the strength and clearness and positiveness with which they 36 THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM. are distinguishable. The primary convolutions have been compared to the large mountain ranges whose height and breadth and direction give to an extensive territory its characteristic features; the secondary convolutions to those subordinate ranges which owe their existence to valleys in the mountain range, running in the same direction ; the tertiary convolutions to the small spurs that extend into cu FIG. 5. The brain from the left side. Cb, the cerebral hemispheres forming the main bulk of the fore-brain ; Ci>/, the cerebellum ; Mo, the medulla oblongata ; P, the pons Varolii ; * the fissure of Sylvius. (Martin.) the valleys from the side of the ranges. The primary con- volutions are distributed in the brains of different individ- uals and in the two lobes of the same cerebrum with a good deal of regularity. With them, all regularity stops. The depressions between the convolutions are called sulci. Corresponding to primary, secondary and tertiary convo- lutions are, accordingly, primary, secondary and tertiary sulci. CORTEX A SYSTEM OF ORGANS. 37 Cortex a System of Organs. The cortex is a very complex organ perhaps we ought to say, system of organs. For it is made up of a vast multitude of nervous elements with immovable fibres connecting them with each other and with other parts of the nervous system. We shall the more clearly realize the reasons for regarding at least in a provisional way the cortex as a system of organs, if we bear in mind what these connecting fibres are. They may be divided into four classes. Sensory Fibres and the Cortex. The first class is composed of sensory fibres. They may be described in brief as the fibres which form the last connecting link between the surface of the body where the sensory impulse starts, and the centre. I say the last connecting link. For the nervous impulse "changes cars," so to speak, a number of times on its way from the surface of the body to the cortex. The first change is made when the sensory im- pulse reaches the cells in the posterior horns of the spinal cord. Sometimes as in the case of reflex action, here- after to be described the sensory impulse travels no farther. But generally it travels upward along fibres which run throughout the entire length of the spinal cord to the medulla oblongata, where these terminal fibres bend at right angles and pass into its gray matter. The sensory impulse is interrupted here "changes cars" but passes out of the medulla oblongata through a number of other gray masses, until it finally reaches the cortex. These fibres then, the fibres which form the last connecting link between the various parts of the surface and the centre, are the first of the four classes which terminate in the cortex. 5 THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM. Motor Fibres and the Cortex. -The second class of connecting fibres in the cortex are those that form the first connect- ing link between the cortex and the volun- tary muscles. These motor fibres, as we may term them, are the paths by which motor impulses travel from the cortex. The entire path from the cortex to the muscle has been divided into two parts the central motor path and the peripheral motor path. The cen- tral motor path in the case of the spinal motor nerve consists of (i) the fibres extend- ing from the cells in the cortex, and (2) the fibres extending up- wards from the motor cells of the anterior horns of the spinal cord. The peripheral motor path consists of the fibres connecting the muscle. The motor fibres FIG. 6. Schema showing the pathway of the sensory impulses. On the left side, S, S' t represent afferent spinal nerve fibres ; C, an afferent cranial nerve fibre. This fibre in each caso terminates near a central cell, the fibre of which crosses the middle line, and ends in the opposite hemisphere. (Modified from Donaldson.) same motor cell with the ASSOCIATION FIBRES. 39 of the cortex constitute the first part of the central motor path. Association Fibres. The third class of connecting fibres are called association fibres. They connect one part of the cortex with another. Says Edinger : " They extend everywhere from convolution to convolution, connecting parts which lie near each other as well as those which are widely separated." They are called association fibres because it is supposed to be by means of them that we are able to associate one experience with another. FIG. 7. Lateral view of a human hemisphere, showing the bundles of association fibres. (Starr.) A, A, between adjacent gyri ; , between frontal and occipital areas ; C, between frontal and temporal areas, cingulum ; Z?, between frontal and temporal areas, fasciculus uncinatus ; E, between occipital and temporal areas fasciculus longitudinalis inferior; C.N., caudate nucleus; O. T,, optic thalamus. (Donaldson.) Commissural Fibres. The fourth class of connecting fibres are those which connect identical parts of the two hemispheres of the cerebrum with each other. They are called commissural. 4O THE CENTRAL NERVOUS SYSTEM. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1 . What is the difference between nerve cells and nerve fibres ? 2. What is a neuron ? 3. What are the two functions of the nervous system ? 4. What are afferent nerves ? 5. Mention the parts of the brain in which Psychology is espe- cially interested. 6. Describe the four classes of fibres which connect one part of the cortex with another, and with the various parts of the body. LESSON V. THE FUNCTIONS OF THE NERVOUS SYSTEM. Functions of the Fibres. After this brief survey of the nervous system we are ready to consider its functions. It is evident that the office of the fibres is to conduct nervous excitations. When you snatch your hand away from a hot stove, the pain is not in the hand ; for, if the nerve which connects the hand with the spinal cord is divided, you will feel no pain. The brain has caused a change in the ends of the nerve that cerminate in the injured part, and this change has been transmitted along the nerve to the spinal cord. The same kind of evidence shows that the motor nerves running from the spinal cord to the muscles have the same office. For, if the nerves extending to the muscles of your arm be divided, you can not snatch your hand away when you feel the sensation of pain. You will be like an animal shot by an arrow which has been dipped in the poison called curari a poison which renders the motor nerves incapable of action, while it does not affect the sensory nerves. You will feel the pain, but will be unable to move your hand. Nature of a Nervous Impulse. As to the nature of the change which takes place during the passage of a nervous impulse, physiologists and psychologists are almost 42 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE NERVOUS SYSTEM. entirely ignorant. Says Professor Martin : " Since between sense organs and sensory centres, and these latter and the muscles, nervous impulses are the only means of communi- cation, it is through them that we arrive at our opinions concerning the external universe and through them that we are able to act upon it ; their ultimate nature is there- fore a matter of great interest, but one about which we unfortunately know very little." * Nerve centres also conduct nervous excitations, but this is not their most characteristic work. Perhaps the best way to realize what this is, is to contrast reflex with volun- tary actions, as many physiologists understand it. We all know what is meant by voluntary actions. They are actions which seem to be the result of our volitions. For certain conscious reasons, we will to act in a certain way, and the action follows. If, however, the act takes place as the result of the stimulation of an afferent nerve, without the intervention of consciousness, it is called reflex. Voluntary, Reflex and Semi-reflex Actions. Pro- fessor James gives a clear illustration of the difference between voluntary and reflex actions and a kind of action intermediate between the two. " If I hear the conductor calling 'All aboard !' as I enter the depot," he says, "my heart first stops, then palpitates, and my legs respond to the air waves falling upon my tympanum by quickening their movements. If I stumble as I run, the sensation of Hing provokes the movement of the hands towards the direction of the fall, the effect of which is to shield the body from too sudden a shock. If a cinder enter my eye, 1 Martin's Physiology, p. 203. MECHANICAL NATURE OF REFLEX ACTIONS. 43 its lids close forcibly, and a copious flow of tears tends to wash it out." 1 In this illustration we have examples of three different kinds of action. The quickening of the pace in con- sequence of the conductor's " All aboard ! " is an example of voluntary action. It is an action following upon a dis- tinct volition, or at least upon a definite state of conscious- ness. With the closure of the eye, on the other hand, and the flow of tears, consciousness had nothing to do. The nervous impulse caused by the cinder passed along an afferent nerve leading from the eye to a certain nerve centre, and that centre imparted an impulse to an efferent nerve connected with the muscles whose contraction results in the closure of the eye, and the result was the closure of the eye without the intervention of consciousness. Such actions are called reflex. The movement of the hands illustrates what is some- times called semi-reflex actions, and sometimes acquired reflexes. The last term is the better because it marks the two essential facts in the case: (i) The action so characterized is now performed without the intervention of consciousness. In that respect it is like reflex actions, so called. (2) Such actions were not originally so performed. They are therefore said to be acquired reflexes. Mechanical Nature of Reflex Actions. That the actions described as reflex are mechanical, there can be no manner of doubt. Certain afferent and efferent nerves, with the nerve centres of which they are outgrowths or prolongations, with the muscles with which the efferent nerves are connected, are the mechanical contrivances for 1 James's Psychology, p. 12. 44 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE NERVOUS SYSTEM. the performance of certain particular kinds of actions Any correct definition you may make of a machine will apply equally well to the mechanism concerned in reflex action. Pull the trigger of a gun and it fires ; put a cinder in the eye and it closes. Strike a certain key of a piano and it produces a certain note. Stroke the flanks of a brainless frog and it croaks. I will not stop here to enlarge upon the fact that a large number of actions originally voluntary become acquired reflexes which is only a way of saying that certain nerve centres can be educated to perform, without the aid of consciousness, actions of which they were quite incapable in the beginning. What I wish to emphasize is the fact that many eminent physiologists and not a few psycholo- gists believe that there is no real difference between reflex actions and voluntary actions, except in the degree of com- plexity of the mechanism by means of which they are brought about. The Automatic Theory. Says the physiologist Foster: " The real difference between an automatic (reflex) action and a voluntary act is that the chain of physiological events between the act and its physiological cause is in the one case short and simple, in the other long and com- plex." In other words according to this doctrine as a segment of the spinal cord, with its afferent and effer- ent nerves, may be regarded as a comparatively simple machine, the cerebrum, with the nerves and the nerve centres connected with it, is likewise a machine, only very much more complex and intricate in its structure. As you can not help closing your eye when a cinder gets into it, your spinal cord being what it is, so you can not help read- THE AUTOMATIC THEORY. 45 ing this chapter, providing you are reading it, your cere- brum being what it is. As consciousness certainly has nothing to do with reflex actions so the doctrine asserts it has nothing to do with so-called voluntary actions. If you could find a machine whose actions made no noise, it would illustrate the reflex machinery of our bodies in that such a machine acts without consciousness. The ordinary, more or less noisy machinery with which we are acquainted illustrates the nervous mechanism by which so-called vol- untary actions are performed. For, as the noise of the machine contributes nothing whatever to what the machine does, as it is the inert effect of its activity, so (accord- ing to the doctrine) consciousness our feelings, hopes, fears, volitions has nothing whatever to do with our actions. We get up, eat, walk, write, read, study, go on journeys, adapt a long series of actions to what seems an intelligent purpose, not because we are intelligent, con- scious beings, but because our bodies are supplied with a wonderful piece of mechanism the cerebrum. Some crude diagrams may help to make the matter clear. Diagram i illustrates the mechanism of reflex action. The line AB represents the afferent nerve along which a nerv- ous impulse travels to the nerve centre BC, and CD the efferent nerve along which the nervous impulse is deflected by the nerve centre. This illustrates in a rough way the 46 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE NERVOUS SYSTEM. mechanism of reflex action. A nervous impulse starts at one point A and is propagated to a nerve centre, where it is deflected and propagated in the opposite direction by a nerve centre. The action from start to finish is purely material. Consciousness has no more to do with it than it has with the falling of a house which is blown down by a tornado. Diagram 2 illustrates the mechanism of so-called volun- tary action according to the doctrine. The line AB represents the path of a nervous impulse to a nerve centre as before. But instead of deflecting the nervous impulse in the opposite direction along the efferent nerve CD, the nerve centre transmits the impulse along the nerve BF to the cortex the cortical cells deflect it in the opposite direction and propagate it along the nerve GC. Although consciousness accompanies such actions, it has nothing to do with causing them according to the theory. A mate- rial change at A was the occasion of the nervous impulse, itself only a material change, which travels to B ; a mate- rial change at B was the occasion of a nervous impulse material change which travels to the cells of the cortex ; a material change in the cells of the cortex caused the nervous impulse material change along the nerves GC and CD. From start to finish the action is material, and material only. And although at a certain point in the path consciousness appears, this consciousness has no more to do with the action that follows than the whiz of a moving wheel has with its motion. Objections to the Theory. I have not explained this theory for the purpose of criticising it. A theory that flies so rudely in the face of common sense does not need FUNCTION OF THE NERVE CENTRES. 47 criticism in the case of the great majority of students. Most of us, I am confident, will feel sure that it is rather the result of the limitations in the knowledge of the spe- cialists who hold it than the proved outcome of incontest- able reasoning. Most of us will feel that these specialists have their faces toward their laboratories, and their backs toward life, with its almost infinite wealth of intricate and complex adaptations of means to ends. If we could forget these adaptations, these manifestations of intelligence in ourselves and others which meet us on every hand, it would doubtless be easy to accept a theory which reduces the actions which our bodies perform to one ultimate type, a theory which banishes consciousness from the scene of causality as an unwelcome intruder and disturber of that perfect unity, the realization of which is the ideal of the scientific mind. But with a vivid appreciation of these manifestations of intelligence we shall not be disturbed by the speculations of these theorists, and the less so in view of the fact that some of the most eminent psychologists in the world among them Professors Wundt, James and Ladd in full view of all the evidence that seems to sup- port the theory, have rejected it. Function of the Nerve Centres. I have called atten- tion to the theory because it seems to me to put in a clear light what is admitted by all parties to be the function of the nervous centres what we shall call the co-ordination of nervous impulse, in such a way as to cause the outgoing impulses to produce an apparently purposive result. To exhibit the evidence in detail for this conclusion in such a book as this is impossible, but it may be said that the whole difference between the psychologists like Professors 48 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE NERVOUS SYSTEM. James, Wundt and Ladd, who reject the theory I have described called the automaton theory and those who hold it, is as to the extent to which this work of co-ordina- tion is performed by the nerve centres without the aid of consciousness. The former admit that some of the centres of the nervous system perform this work of co-ordination without the aid of consciousness; they also admit that where consciousness intervenes, these nerve centres are the mechanism it employs. The automatists, on the other hand, maintain that this work of co-ordination is in all cases the unassisted work of the nerve centres. Mechanism Required in Reflex Actions. The mech- anism required in reflex actions is clear, from what has been said of them. It consists (i) of a sensitive surface exterior or interior, (2) an afferent nerve, (3) a cell or nerve centre connecting the afferent nerve with the sensi- tive surface (4) of an efferent nerve connecting the nerve centre with (5) a muscle or muscles. 1 The afferent impulse starts in (i), passes along (2), reaches (3), is there changed into an efferent impulse, which passes along (4), finally reaches (5), where it causes a contraction of a muscle or muscles. The essence of reflex action, then, consists in the change by means of the protoplasm of a nerve cell of an afferent into an efferent impulse. 2 Efferent Impulses. An efferent impulse is not simply a deflection of an afferent impulse. A crumb of bread in 1 For the sake of simplicity, I omit from consideration those reflex actions in which the efferent nerve is not connected with muscles. 8 Foster's Physiology, p. 129. AUTOMATIC ACTIONS. 49 contact with the glottis may occasion a violent fit of cough- ing in which not only all the respiratory muscles, but nearly all the muscles of the body, are brought into action. The efferent impulse which stimulated the muscles whose contraction resulted in coughing is not in such a case a mere deflection of the afferent impulse. The afferent impulse was slight and feeble ; the efferent impulse was extensive and powerful, and was communicated to a large number of nerves. Evidently, the number and character of efferent impulses in any given case depend primarily not on the afferent impulse, but on the changes which take place in the nerve centres. Automatic Actions. In addition to the functions of the nerve centres in reflex action, acquired reflexes and voluntary actions, some of them have functions which seem to be sharply contrasted with these. These are the auto- matic centres, " which are centres not directly excited by nerve fibres conveying impulses to them, but in other ways." For example, the movements in breathing do not depend upon consciousness. In that respect they are con- tracted with voluntary actions. But the nerve centres that propagate the nervous excitation to the muscles con- cerned in breathing are not themselves excited to activity by efferent fibres leading to them. They are stimulated directly by the blood that flows through them. Actions so resulting are, in this respect, contrasted with reflex actions. We have then four classes of actions: (i) automatic actions in which the nerve centres concerned are not stimulated by afferent fibres ; (2) reflex actions in which the centres are stimulated by afferent fibres, and to which 50 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE NERVOUS SYSTEM. they respond with machine-like directness and regularity ; (3) acquired reflexes in which the centres are also stim- ulated by afferent fibres, and in which they now respond with machine-like directness and regularity, but in which they did not have that power to begin with; (4) voluntary actions whose differentiating characteristic is that the centres concerned in their production seem to depend on the will. Centres of Automatic Action. The medulla oblongata contains numerous centres of automatic action, among them the movements employed in breathing. If the brain is removed above the medulla, the breathing movements are hardly disturbed at all. But if the medulla is removed or injured, all breathing stops, even though the injury be confined entirely to the medulla, the muscles and nerves concerned in breathing being entirely uninjured. The Cerebellum. The cerebellum is the organ for many acquired reflexes. We all know how easy it is to walk, and at the same time concentrate our entire atten- tion on a conversation. All that it seems necessary for the mind or consciousness to have to do with it is to set the machine well going, so to speak, when some part of the nervous mechanism relieves consciousness of all further work in the matter. We have forgotten how we learned to walk, but we all remember how necessary it was to give our entire attention to our movements when we were learn- ing to skate or ride a bicycle. But the experienced skater or cyclist can skate or ride with as little attention to what he is doing as we are obliged to give to walking. The difference between a man who can skate and one SUMMARY OF CONCLUSION. 51 who can not is that the one can and the other can not control his muscles in such a way as to produce the desired result. And the difference between the man who can only skate by giving his entire attention to it, and the one who can skate and think about something else, is that in the one case the mandate to the necessary muscles pro- ceeds from the cerebrum, the centre directly connected with consciousness ; in the other, from a centre not directly connected with consciousness. In other words, in the case of the person learning to skate, walk, ride a wheel, play on a musical instrument, the nervous impulse to the proper muscles proceeds directly from the cortex of the cerebrum. In the case of a person who has learned to walk, or the skillful skater or wheelman, all that the cortex of the cerebrum seems to do is to initiate the action, when the supervision and further direction of it is carried on by a lower centre. That centre seems to be the cere- bellum. The reason for this conclusion may be summarized as follows : When the cerebellum is injured, the most marked result seems to be a loss of the power to perform the acquired reflexes used in locomotion. Summary of Conclusion. We may then sum up the results of this chapter as follows : The functions of the nervous system may be broadly divided into two classes those of the fibres or nerves, and those of the cells or centres. The office of the fibres is to conduct excitations to and from the centres. The centres are concerned in four kinds of actions : automatic, reflex, acquired reflexes, and voluntary. The medulla oblongata is one of the cen- tres from which automatic actions proceed. The spinal cord is pre-eminently a centre of reflex actions. It is also 52 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE NERVOUS SYSTEM. a centre of many acquired reflexes. The cerebellum is the centre for the acquired reflexes used in locomotion. We will consider the functions of the cerebrum in the next lesson. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1. What is the function of nerve fibres? 2. What is the nature of the change which takes place during the passage of a nervous impulse ? 3. What is the difference between reflex, semi-reflex, automatic, and voluntary actions ? 4. Explain the automaton theory. 5. What is the mechanism required in reflex actions ? SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1. Do you believe in the automaton theory? 2. Physiologists are much more inclined to accept the theory than psychologists ; what do you suppose is the reason for it ? 3. How do you account for the purposive character of reflex actions ? LESSON VI. THE FUNCTIONS OF THE CEREBRUM. Cerebrum and Intelligence. That the cerebrum is more closely related to intelligence than any other part of the nervous system, is proved by the same evidence that goes to show that the brain is the organ of the mind. Re-read the lesson on that subject and you will have before you the evidence that has convinced physiologists and psychologists that the cerebrum is in a special sense the organ of the mind. The blow on the head that deprives one of consciousness is a blow that affects the cerebrum. The nervous connection that must be main- tained in order that pain may be felt, is the connection between the injured part and the cerebrum. The injuries to the brain that result in the impairment of memory or aphasia are injuries of the cerebrum. Cortex and Intelligence. But the cerebrum is a large organ. Is there any evidence to show that any par- ticular part or parts of it sustain this especially intimate relation to intelligence ? There is nearly a consensus of opinion among physiologists and psychologists to the effect that there is such a part, and that is the thin rind of gray matter called the cortex. The evidence for this opinion may be stated under two 53 54 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE CEREBRUM. heads: (i) The higher an animal stands in the scale of intelligence, the deeper and more numerous, as a rule, are the folds or convolutions of the cortex. Remembering that these folds increase the surface of the cortex, we may say that, as a rule, the higher an animal stands in the scale of intelligence, the greater the extent of the surface of its cortex in proportion to its size. There are, indeed, a few exceptions to the rule. A few animals, not high in the scale of intelligence, have deeper and more extended folds than other animals standing above them in that scale. (2) The cerebral functions, so far as they have been located, have been located in the cortex. All the evidence, therefore, for the localization of those functions points to the same conclusion. What, then, is the nature of that evidence ? Meaning of " Localization of Functions." Before attempting to answer this question, let us try to get a clear idea of what is meant by "localization of mental func- tions." The question which the theory undertakes to answer may be stated as follows : Have different parts of the cerebrum the same work to do in relation to our men- tal life ? Do they sustain the same relation to the life of sensation, memory, and voluntary motion ? Those who say that they have, deny, and those who say that they have not, affirm, the localization of the cerebral functions. Presumptions in Favor of it. The most general knowledge of the nervous system would lead. one to expect some localization of the functions of the cerebrum. We have seen that there are sensory nerves and motor nerves nerves that minister to sensation and nerves that min- THE DOCTRINE COMPARATIVELY NEW. 55 ister to motion. A further study of the nerves shows us that this division of labor is carried much farther. Some of the efferent nerves are motor and some are not ; some of the motor nerves are voluntary and some involuntary. Moreover, each motor nerve is connected with some par- ticular muscle, not with the muscles in general. And precisely as the motor nerves are each of them connected at their peripheral terminations with certain particular muscles, so they have their origin in different parts of the brain. It is difficult to believe that the nervous impulse that travels along them to the muscles does not have its origin in some definite cell or group of cells. In like man- ner the sensory nerves that connect the surface of the body with the cortex must connect that surface with a definite part of the cortex, provided they go to the cortex at all. The nerves that proceed from the end of my little finger and connect it with the cortex must terminate in some definite place ; they cannot terminate in the brain in general. The presumption, thus created, that different parts of the cerebrum will be found to have different offices to per- form in relation to our mental life, is strengthened by a consideration of the nerve centres. The gray matter of the spinal cord is a. succession of centres for the perform- ance of different reflex actions ; the medulla oblongata is a group of centres for various automatic actions, each hav- ing its own definite place. Whether, then, we consider nerve fibres or the lower centres, a strong presumption in favor of the localization of cerebral functions is created. The Doctrine Comparatively New. Nevertheless, the doctrine as a scientific theory is only a little more 56 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE CEREBRUM. than a quarter of a century old. The most eminent authorities in physiology half a century ago decided em- phatically against it. One of them declared that he had experimented upon the cortex of different animals, dogs, rabbits, and kids, " had irritated it mechanically, cauterized it with potash, nitric acid, etc., and had passed galvanic currents through it, in different directions, without obtain- ing any signs whatever of muscular contractions." ] The same year another eminent physiologist summed up the results of numerous experiments with the declara- tion that the various parts of the cerebrum have no special function, but that the lobes of the cerebrum perform their functions with their whole mass. In 1870 Fritsch and Hitzig began the investigations, which, with those of many other workers in the same field, have caused the opinion of those physiologists to be over- thrown. It has been perfectly established that certain parts of the cerebrum, at least, have certain specific func- tions in our mental life. In stating the evidence for this conclusion no descrip- tion will be attempted of the particular parts of the cortex which have been proved to be connected with particular mental activities. Knowledge of this sort can be best imparted by diagrams, and upon these I shall rely for making clear the areas of the cortex concerned in particu- lar mental activities so far as they are known. The localizations most clearly established are the motor areas, those areas from which the nervous impulse starts which results in the contraction of the voluntary muscles. The evidence which proves that there are such areas is of various kinds. 1 Ladd's Physiological Psychology, p. 253. EFFECTS OF STIMULATION. 57 Effects of Stimulation. (i) It has been proved that the stimulation of a definite part of the cortex of dogs, monkeys and other animals produces definite movements, sometimes in the face, sometimes in the hind-legs, some- times in the fore-legs, sometimes in the tail, according to the part stimulated. A savage, upon accidentally strik- ing a key of a piano, might suppose that there was no real connection between his action and the sound that followed it, that the one followed the other by accident. But if he struck the same key again and again, and if he extended his experiments to the other keys of the piano, he could hardly fail to believe that there was a causal connection between each particular key and the sound that followed it. In like manner, when we learn that the stimulation of a particular part of the cortex, both by electricity and mechanically, is invariably followed by a particular move- ment; when we learn that this movement does not follow if this connection between the part of the cortex stim- ulated and the nerve centres at the base of the brain has been cut off, it is impossible not to believe that that part of the cortex is the place from which the motor nerves that lead to the muscles concerned in the movement take their origin. Effects of Removal of Parts of the Brain of Animals. (2) While stimulating definite areas of the cortex occa- sions a definite movement of a definite part of the body, it has been proved that a removal of the cortical area which has been shown by stimulation to be connected with a definite movement, deprives the animal of the power to perform that movement. 58 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE CEREBRUM.' Difficulties. It must indeed be admitted that these experiments do not permit such definite, clear-cut con- clusions as those arising from the experiments described in the preceding paragraph. For it has been proved that the loss of the power to perform definite movements which results from a removal of a particular part of the cortex is not permanent. Says Professor James : " Even when the entire motor zone of a dog is removed, there is no perma- nent paralysis of any sort." Explanation of these Difficulties. The explanation of these facts is too intricate and involved to be under- taken in such a book as this. I will only say that the generally accepted explanation is that other centres some- how learn to do the work usually performed by the cen- tres which have been destroyed. If we bear in mind that every cortical centre may be regarded from one point of view as the place where incoming currents, along afferent fibres, become outgoing currents along efferent fibres, and if we remember that innumerable fibres connect every cortical centre with every other, we shall perhaps be able to form some idea of how this is possible. As a train, by the destruction of the city of Chicago with all its tracks and depots, although prevented from going from New York to Denver by its customary route, would neverthe- less eventually reach its destination by another route, so nerve currents, at first prevented from reaching their des- tination particular muscles by the destruction of the depots nerve centres on their customary route, might eventually reach this destination over new routes or new paths. But whatever may be the explanation of the fact that MEN SUFFERING FROM BRAIN DISEASE. 59 animals whose motor areas have been removed somehow learn to perform the movements which they were unable to perform, the fact can not overthrow the conclusion that definite parts of the cortex are the centres particularly concerned in definite movements. Observations of Men Suffering from Local Brain Dis- ease. Observations of men suffering from local brain disease have helped to put this conclusion beyond the reach of doubt. These observations have made it possible to map out with a great deal of definiteness the areas of the brain concerned with particular movements. Not only have the centres for the legs and face been mapped out, but within the areas of these centres smaller ones have been mapped out, areas which are concerned with definite movements of the parts of the body concerned. Thus, the areas concerned with the motion of the eyelids, with the muscles of the angle of the mouth, all have their definite positions in the area for the face. " So definite," says Professor Martin, " are the positions of these areas that in cases of localized paralysis, diagnosed as due to lesions of the cerebral cortex, surgeons now have no hesitation in opening the skull in order if possible to remove the cause of trouble, as a small tumor : they know precisely in what spot they will find it." 1 Said Dr. W. W. Keen : " When I say that the existence of a tumor about the size of the end of the forefinger can be diagnosticated, and before touching the head it should be said (and I was present when the statement was made) that it was a small tumor, that it did not lie on the surface of the brain but a little underneath it, and that it lay 1 Martin's Physiology, p. 624. 60 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE CEREBRUM. partly under the centre for the face and partly under that for the arm in the left side of the brain, and that the man was operated on and the tumor was found exactly where it was believed to be, with perfect recovery of the patient, it is something which ten years ago would have been declared the art of a magician rather than the cold preci- sion of science." Evidence such as this may be regarded as conclusive, however difficult we may find it to explain to ourselves all the related facts. Aphasia. Observations of persons suffering from aphasia confirm this same conclusion. As mentioned in a preceding lesson, in every case in which a post-mortem examination of the brain of a person suffering from motor aphasia has been permitted, an injury has been found in a certain definite part of the brain. ' The curious facts in connection with aphasia, for example, that a person has control of his voice but can not talk, or that he can write intelligently but can not talk, or that he can write but can not say what he wishes to say, or that he can write but can not read what he has written, are easily explained by the theory of localization of cerebral functions. If we suppose the cortical centre for the control of the voice and for talking are different, it is easy to see that the injury of the one is not necessarily the injury of the other, and that, therefore, there is no necessary connection between the loss of the power to talk and the ability to control the voice. In like manner it is easy to see that the centre for writing may not be impaired, even if the association fibres that connect the writing centre with the cells concerned in the production of certain ideas are injured. Also, a person whose centre for talking is injured HERING ON FUNCTIONS OF THE CEREBRUM. 6 1 will be unable to talk, but that will not prevent him from being able to write, if the writing centre is unimpaired. Nor will the fact that a person can write enable him to read what he has written if the association fibres connect- ing the centres concerned in seeing with the centres cor- responding to the idea of^what is read are injured. Bering on the Functions of the Cerebrum. Professor E. Hering states his conclusions as to the functions of the cerebrum in the following language : " The different parts of the hemispheres are like a great tool-box with a count- less variety of tools. Each single element of the cerebrum is a particular tool. Consciousness may be likened to an artisan whose tools gradually become so numerous, so varied and so specialized that he has for every minutest detail of his work a tool which is especially adapted to perform just this precise kind of work very easily and accurately. If he loses one of his tools he still possesses a thousand other tools to do the same work, though under disadvantages both with reference to adaptability and the time involved. Should he happen to lose the use of these thousand also, he might retain hundreds with which to do the work still, but under greatly increased difficulty. He must needs have lost a very large number of his tools if certain actions become absolutely impossible." Problem of Physiological Psychology. The assertion that each single element of the cerebrum is a particular tool specially adapted to perform a certain work in con- sciousness goes a long way beyond the evidence. The sensations of sight, sound, smell, touch and taste have *been localized with varying degrees of probability. But 62 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE CEREBRUM. if the famous postulate of Meynert becomes satisfactorily proved, as seems possible, the most distinctive features of the consciousness of human beings will remain unex- plained. Professor James states that postulate in the following language : " The highest centres contain nothing but arrangements for representing impressions and move- ments, and other arrangements for coupling the activity of these arrangements together." Suppose this proved. Suppose we knew the cortical centre for each sensation and each movement, and each idea of a sensation and each idea of a movement ; suppose also we knew the association fibres by means of which one sensation (cor- tical centre) is connected with another sensation (cortical centre), shall we have then an explanation of all the tools which consciousness uses ? We shall, provided the entire mental life consists of sensations and ideas, and associa- tions of sensations and ideas. But if this is not all of the mental life, if it leaves out of account the distinctive feature of mental life, the consciojisness of relations, as I maintain that it does, then thinking (which consists in the consciousness of relations] is a part of the mental life which in the nature of the case can not be explained by the cerebrum. Upon this conception of the matter, the work possible to Physiological Psychology will have been done when Meynert' s postulate shall have been satisfac- torily proved in all its details. But consciousness, as the relating activity of the mind, as binding sensations into a whole of consciously related parts (concepts), and concepts into a whole of consciously related parts (judgments), and judgments into a whole of consciously related parts (acts of reasoning), all these distinctive and unique features of the human mind must seek their explanation in a' PROBLEM OF PHYSIOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. 63 Ro 11 r Pa Fr FIG. 8. Diagram of outer surface of left cerebral hemisphere to illustrate the localization of functions. The motor area is shaded in vertical and transverse lines : Sy, fissure of Sylvius ; an, angular gyrus or convolution ; Ro, fissure of Rolando ; Fr, frontal lobe ; Pa, parietal lobe ; Te, temporal lobe. Only a very- few of the more important fissures are indicated. Compare with Fig. 9. (Martin.) FIG. 9. Diagram of inner surface of left cerebral hemisphere to illustrate cerebral localization. Sy, fissure of Sylvius ; Ro, fissure of Rolando ; Fr, frontal lobe ; Of, occipital lobe ; Te, temporal lobe Cc, corpus callosum ; ///, third ventricle. Compare with Fig. 8. (Martin.) 64 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE CEREBRUM. department of thought to which Physiological Psychology is an entire stranger. The figures on page 63 will show what is known of the parts of the cortex in which the various mental activities have so far been localized. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1. Show that the cerebrum is more closely related to intelligence than any other part of the brain. 2. Show that the cortex is more closely related to intelligence than any other part of the cerebrum. 3. What is meant by the "localization of cerebral functions"? 4. State the evidence for it 5. What is Meynert's postulate ? 6. What would follow if it were proved ? SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1. What is meant by the "relating activity of the mind"? 2. Why can not Physiological Psychology explain it ? LESSON VII. WHAT IS PSYCHOLOGY ? What is Psychology ? The answer usually given is that Psychology is the science of the mind or soul. But what is the soul ? People who have not thought carefully about it would probably say that, whatever it is, it cer- tainly is not the mind. Animals, they would say, plainly have minds, but no one believes that they have souls. Do Animals Have Souls ? It may serve to give clear- ness to our ideas to consider the question whether or not animals have souls. Without doubt, in the confused sense in which the word is used in popular language, the true answer is that they have. If you suppose that animals have no souls, let me ask you if you have one. You will undoubtedly say that you have. Suppose I ask you whether you are always dreaming when you are asleep. You will probably answer that you are not. And when you say that you are not dreaming, what do you mean ? " I mean," I imagine you saying, " that there are no thoughts or feelings in my mind." " And when there are no thoughts and feelings in your mind, does your soul continue to exist ? " " I do not understand you." " You say that you do not think you are always dream- 6S 66 WHAT IS PSYCHOLOGY? ing when you are asleep ; and when you say that you are not dreaming, you say that you mean that you have no thoughts or feelings in your mind. So far as thoughts and feelings go, I understand you to say that you are exactly like a dead man. A dead man has no thoughts and feelings, neither have you when you are not dreaming. Now, when you have no thoughts and feelings in your mind, does your soul continue to exist ? " "I certainly believe it does, as I have no reason to believe that it ceases to exist when I fall asleep and begins to exist as soon as I awake, as must be the case if it ceases to exist when I have no thoughts and feelings." "Then you do not mean by soul the thoughts and feel- ings of which you are conscious, or a part of those thoughts and feelings ? " " Again I do not understand you." " You say that your soul does not cease to exist when you have no thoughts or feelings ; now, if it does not, your soul can not be your thoughts and feelings, can it ? " " Why not ? " " Because if it were, when you have no thoughts and feelings, you would have no soul, would you ? " " I see that I would not." "And it can not be a part of your thoughts and feel- ings?" ' No, for if it were an/part of them when I had none of any kind, I would have no soul." "You mean by soul, then, not thoughts and feelings, but the thing that has thoughts and feelings ? " " Again I am obliged to say that I do not understand you." "A German professor is said to have begun a first THE SOUL ONE OF THREE THINGS. 67 lesson on Psychology in this way : ' Students, think about the wall.' After a moment's pause : ' Now think about the thing that thinks about the wall. The thing that thinks about the wall is what is to be the subject of your study.' That is what you mean by soul, is it not the thing which thinks and feels, the thing which has thoughts and feelings ? " "It is." " And what do you mean by mind ? " " I mean that which thinks and feels, or that which has thoughts and feelings." " But things which are identical with the same thing are identical with each other, are they not ? " " They are." " And if the soul is that which thinks and feels, and the mind is that which thinks and feels, they must be the same, must they not ? " " I see that they must." "If then you say that dogs, for instance, have minds, can you refuse to admit that they have souls ? " " I am obliged to confess that I can not." The Soul One of Three Things. In this imaginary dialogue you may say that in the nature of the case I can prove what I wish to prove, since I can put any words in your mouth I please. But if you will carefully consider it, you will see that you are obliged to say that the soul is one of three things : It is either all of our thoughts and feelings, or a part of them, or the thing which has thoughts and feelings the thing which thinks and feels and wills. If you say that the soul is all or a part of our thoughts and feelings mental facts, in a word then, instead of 68 WHAT IS PSYCHOLOGY? saying that Psychology is the science of the soul, it would be much plainer to say that Psychology is the science of mental facts. But if you say that the soul is that which thinks and feels and wills, then, as we have seen, there is no difference between soul and mind, and we are left with the definition, Psychology is the science of the mind. Meaning of Mind. But what do you mean by mind ? What we have seen in the case of the soul that it con- sists of thoughts, feelings, and acts of the will, or that which thinks, feels, and wills is plainly true of the mind also. It must either be that which thinks, feels, and wills, or it must be the thoughts, feelings, and acts of will of which we are conscious mental facts, in one word. But what do we know about that which thinks, feels, and wills, and what can we find out about it ? Where is it ? You will probably say, in the brain. But if you are speaking literally, if you say that it is in the brain, as a pencil is in the pocket, then you must mean that it takes up room, that it occupies space, and that would make it very much like a material thing. In truth, the more carefully you consider it, the more plainly you will see what thinking men have known for a long time that we do not know and can not learn anything about the thing which thinks and feels and wills. It is beyond the range of human knowledge. The books which define Psychology as the science of mind have not a word to say about that which thinks ana feels and wills. They are entirely taken up with these thoughts and feelings and acts of the will mental facts, in a word trying to tell us what they are, and to arrange them in classes, and tell us the circum- stances or conditions under which they exist. DEFINITION OF MENTAL FACTS. 69 It seems to me, therefore, that it would be better to define Psychology as the science of the experiences, phe- nomena, or facts of the mind, soul, or self of mental facts, in a word. Definition of Mental Facts. But what is a mental fact ? Let us say, to start with, that it is a fact known directly to but one person, and that the person experi- encing it. If you are standing on the street with a half dozen friends, you can all see the houses, and men and women and horses. You can all hear the tramping of feet and the clatter of the vehicles that pass along the street. These facts are open to the observation of all of you alike. But there is a class of facts known directly to but one of you ^what you think and feel and will, you know, and no one else does ; what A thinks and feels and wills, he knows, and no one else does. These thoughts and feelings and volitions are experiences, phenomena, or facts of the mind, soul, or self mental facts, in a word facts known to but one person directly, and that the person experiencing them. Unconscious Mental Facts. But I believe there are mental facts not known to any one. If you are intent upon a book, the clock may strike and you may not hear it at the time, and a minute after you may be entirely sure that you heard the clock strike a minute before, although you did not know at the time that you heard it. The true explanation of facts like these seems to be that the clock produced a sensation which you would have known was a sensation of sound if you had attended to it at the time the clock struck, and in the sense of having received a yO WHAT IS PSYCHOLOGY ? sensation because of the clock, you heard it. But you did not know that you heard it until the minute after. Now, what must we call this sensation ? Plainly a mental fact, although there was a time when it was not known by any one. Still, however, it is marked off quite sharply from all other facts physical facts we may call them, which may be known with equal directness by any number of people by the circumstance that, although not known, it is knowable by but one person, and that the person experiencing it. We may then define a mental fact as a fact known or knowable to but one person directly, and that the person experiencing it, and Psychology as the science of mental facts, or the science of the facts of mind. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1. How is the question, "What is Psychology, " usually answered? 2. Would you say that dogs have souls T 3. How would you defend your answer? 4. What is the objection to defining Psychology as the science of the mind or soul ? 5. How would you define Psychology? 6. What is a mental fact? 7. What is a physical fact ? 8. Into what two classes would you put mental facts ? 9. Can you have mental facts without knowing that you have them? 10. Give examples. SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1. Do animals reason ? 2. Are you ever in a state of dreamless sleep ? 3. What is the difference between matter as a substance, and matter as a group of phenomena ? QUESTIONS. 71 4. What do we know of matter as a substance of the experi- ences, phenomena, or facts of the mind, soul, or self ? 5. Why is it that it so often happens that you can not tell your motives for what you do ? 6. In what sense is it true that the soul is in the brain ? LESSON VIII. THE SUBJECT MATTER OF PSYCHOLOGY. IN the last lesson I tried to point out the subject of which Psychology treats. I objected to the usual defini- tion, " Psychology is the science of the mind or soul," not because it is incorrect, but because I do not believe it gives young students definite ideas. I want you to get at the outset the clearest possible notion of the subject you are to study. I want you to realize that the facts of which you are directly conscious, the facts known directly to you only that these and similar facts form the subject of which Psychology treats. Physical and Mental Facts. We may, perhaps, put the subject matter of Psychology in a clearer light by contrasting mental facts with physical facts. A physical fact, as we know, is one open to the observation of all men. Trees, houses, flowers, fences the whole of external nature, in a word are physical facts, since all of us can observe them with equal directness. But what shall we say of the brain, or any of the internal organs of one's body ? Are they mental facts ? They are, provided they are known to but one person directly, and that the person experiencing them. But careful reflection will con- vince you that no one has any direct knowledge of his body. 72 DIRECT KNOWLEDGE OF OUR BODIES. 73 Have we Direct Knowledge of our Bodies? That we have such an organ as the heart, for example, was established by a process of reasoning. If we had known it directly, it is hard to see why the world was obliged to wait for Harvey to demonstrate the circulation of the blood why it was not from the beginning a matter of direct knowledge. Strange as it may seem at first thought, it is pretty nearly absolutely certain that we have no direct knowledge of our own bodies. We learn of the existence of our own bodies as we do of the rest of the external world, by a process of reasoning. Descartes long ago said that if we could move the sun or moon by an effort of will, as we can our hands and feet, we should regard them as a part of our own bodies. The sole difference, so far as Psychology is concerned, between any external object, as a tree, and our bodies, is (i) that the former does not move in obedience to our wills, and (2) that it is not a source of sensations as our bodies are. I put my hand on a hot stove, and I have a feeling of pain. I put a stick in the same position, and I have no such sensation. How a Child Distinguishes his Body from the Rest of the External World. Any one who has ever watched a very young child will be quite sure that he has not dis- criminated his body from the rest of the external world. He first confuses his body with the rest of the external world. Little by little he comes to learn that a little piece of this external world sustains a very peculiar relation to him that it obeys his will, moves when he wishes it to move, stops when he wishes it to stop, and that it is the direct occasion of pleasure and pain as nothing else is. These two facts, then, and these two facts alone, distin- 74 THE SUBJECT MATTER OK PSYCHOLOGY. guish our bodies from the rest of the external world, so far as Psychology is concerned, and give us our peculiar interest in them. While this course of reasoning makes it clear that the internal organs of the body are not mental facts, another course will make it equally clear that they are physical facts. Is a pencil in a drawer a physical fact ? No one can see it. No, you say, but every one can see it if it is taken out of the drawer. Precisely. We need, then, to think of a physical fact as one open to the observation of all men, certain conditions being complied with. Bearing this in mind, we see that the various internal organs of the body are physical facts, because when the body is dis- sected they are open to the observation of all men, pre- cisely as is a tree or flower. Nature of the Mental Facts of which we are Conscious. Hoping, then, that the difference between mental and physical facts is so clear that there will be no danger of confusing them, permit me to call your attention a little more closely to the mental facts which we are to study, in order that we may avoid a mistake into which many people fall the mistake of supposing that any of the mental facts of which we are conscious are simple. You remember our definition of Psychology the science of the facts, phenomena, or experiences, which, when we are conscious of them, we are conscious of as experiences of the mind, soul, or self. The point I wish to emphasize is that we are never conscious of any experience, separated or detached from the mind. As you read this, you are, perhaps, conscious of attending. Look into your own mind and see what it is you are conscious of ; it is of OF UNCONSCIOUS MENTAL FACTS. 75 yourself attending, is it not ? not of an abstract act of attention. So, also, when you perceive or remember or imagine or reason, what you are conscious of is not an abstract act of perception or memory or imagination or reasoning, but yourself perceiving, yourself remembering, yourself imagining, yourself reasoning. This, of course, is only another way of saying that you yotirself enter as a constituent into every mental fact of which you are con- scious. In other words, in being conscious of mental facts, we are conscious of ourselves. Many writers appear to think that a mental fact of which we are conscious exists independently of the mind and separate from it, as a tree or a stone seems to do. But a careful looking into your own mind will convince you that they are mistaken ; it will convince you that when you are conscious of a mental fact you are really conscious of yourself in a certain act or state, of yourself having a certain experience. As you never know the act or state or experience apart from your- self, so you never know yourself apart from the act or state or experience. Hume said that when he looked into his own mind he always found thoughts and feelings and acts of the will, but he never found anything else he never found any self. Certainly not in the sense in which he was speaking. He was looking for a self apart from, and independent of, the various thoughts, feelings, and acts of the will of which he was conscious, and no such self is to be found. The self of consciousness, I repeat, exists not apart from, but as an element of, the various experi- ences of which we are conscious. s Of Unconscious Mental Facts. You will be careful to note that the mental facts into which the mind enters 76 THE SUBJECT MATTER OF PSYCHOLOGY. as a constituent are those of which we are conscious. I have already tried to show that mental facts exist in the lives of each of us of which we are not conscious ; mental facts of the existence of which we never know save by a process of reasoning. Of such mental facts the mind is not an element, and that is precisely why we are not con- scious of them. The mind is conscious, or has direct knowledge, of only its own acts or states or modifications or experiences. A mental fact which is not an act or state or modification of the mind, the mind can learn the existence of only by a process of reasoning. And now I hope the scope of our definition of Psychology is entirely clear. Psychology is the science of those facts, phenomena, or experiences which, when we are conscious of them, we are conscious of as experiences of the mind, soul, or self. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1. What is the usual definition of Psychology, and what is the objection to it ? 2. Is the brain a mental fact ? Why not? 3. How do we come to distinguish our bodies from the rest of the external world ? 4. What is the difference between a mental fact of which we are conscious and one of which we are not conscious ? 5. Why is it that we are not conscious of some mental facts ? 6. State and explain the definition of Psychology. SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1. When was Harvey born, and what did he do ? 2. Descartes is called the father of modern philosophy; what does that mean ? When was he born ? 3. Hume is called a philosophical skeptic; what is a philosophical skeptic ? LESSON IX. THE METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. Kinds of Mental Facts in which Psychology is Inter- ested. " But in what kind of mental facts," perhaps you ask, " is Psychology interested ? I had the toothache yesterday ; that, if I understand you, was a mental fact ; but Psychology has no interest in such facts, has it ? " No and yes. That you, John Smith, had the toothache is a matter of indifference to Psychology. Psychology has no more interest in that fact than the science of Botany has in the fact that you have a bed of geraniums. Like all sciences, its aim is general knowledge ; and that you, John Smith, had the toothache is not general knowledge it is knowledge of an individual. But when you had the tooth- ache, you found it difficult to study, did you not ? You can doubtless recall many similar cases in your experience cases in which severe pain interfered with that concen- tration of mind which we call study. And keen delight is just as unfavorable to study. You received a letter some time ago that made you very happy, so happy that you could not concentrate your mind on your work for an hour ; and you find that the experience of other people is like yours in this regard. So, although Psychology cares nothing about your toothache, there is something 77 78 THE METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. in the experience that it does care about. So far as your experience illustrates what is true of all minds under similar circumstances, so far it is a matter of interest to Psychology. Laws of Mind. Or I might say that what Psychology especially seeks to ascertain is laws of mind, or of mental facts. A law of mental facts is a general truth about mental facts something which will be true, not only in all your experience, but in the experience of every one under similar circumstances. We have just been consider- ing an example of a law of mental facts that intense feeling, whether of pleasure or pain, can not exist along with concentration of mind on another subject. That is a law of mental facts, because it is true of the experiences of all men without exception. Since one of the conditions of concentration of thought one of the things which makes it possible is the absence of intense feeling, concentra- tion of thought, on a subject foreign to the feeling, never can co-exist with intense feeling. That is a perfectly general proposition, and, as such, illustrates a law of the mind. Evidently, then, to ascertain laws of the mind, you must not only study the facts of your own experience, but those of other people. If you confine yourself to your own experience, you can not be sure that your knowledge is general ; you are liable to confuse a personal peculiarity with a principle of human nature. Imagine Andrew Jack- son endeavoring to get a knowledge of human nature by studying himself alone. If he had taken himself as a type of men in general, he would have had very erroneous ideas of human nature. INTROSPECTIVE METHOD. 79 Introspective Method. But can you study the minds of other people in the same way that you can your own ? Try it. You often wish to know whether your pupils are attending to you, or whether they understand you. Can you find out, in the same way, that you know whether or not you are attending ? Plainly not. You know that you are attending simply by looking into your own mind, and you can not look into the mind of any one else. The word which means looking into is "introspection"; and the adjective " introspective " seems, therefore, to describe best the way or mode or method in which you study your own mind. But you can not learn anything about the minds of other people in that way. When you study other people, you notice their looks and actions. Many teachers think they can tell whether their pupils are attending to them without asking questions. They look or act as though they were attending, and so the teachers who believe this con- clude they are. Conclude, I say. Note the word. It denotes a process of reasoning. And when we study the minds of others, we have to do it by processes of reason- ing by acts of inference. Inferential Method. You do not even know that there is any one in the world besides yourself except by a process of reasoning. When you say you see a man, the truth is that you have sensations of color, and from this fact infer the presence of a human being like yourself. When you see this human being laugh, you infer that he is amused, just as you are conscious of being amused when you laugh. All that you learn of any human being you learn by reasoning by inference. As, then, we call the method of studying our own minds the introspective 80 THE METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. since we study them by looking directly within so we may call the method of studying the minds of others the inferential, since we do it by processes of inference. The Inferential Method and the Study of History. Whatever you learn about the minds of others whether you learn it from what you see them do, or what you read about them you learn by means of the inferential method. When you learn how Washington exposed him- self when Braddock's army was routed, and at the battle of Princeton, you infer that he was brave, precisely as you would have done if you had seen him. Since all the facts of human history relate to the actions of men, they are materials which the inferential method uses to increase our knowledge of human nature. When we learn, for example, that the ancient Greeks left their weak children exposed, in order that they might die, the inferential method enables us to see that Greek fathers and mothers did not love their children as fathers and mothers love their children now, and that they probably loved their country more, since a weak child was considered of no worth because it gave no promise of being able to be of service to the State. When we know that Aristotle said that all that was necessary to reform or relax the manners of a people was to add one string to the lyre or take one from it, the same method enables us to see that the Greeks had a susceptibility to music of which we can scarcely have any idea to-day. When we know that " those doughty old mediaeval knights despised the petty clerk's trick of writing, because, compared to a life of toilsome and heroic action, it seemed to them slavish and unmanly," we know that they looked upon a very different world from ours INFERENTIAL METHOD AND MIND STUDY. 8 1 a world of different aims and ideals ; that the knowledge we prize so highly, and toil so painfully to gain, was a thing of no value in their eyes. The inferential method even uses the relics of the prehistoric ages to add to our knowl- edge of men. It takes the rough tools of the cave-dwellers and forces from them a little knowledge of the strange men who used them. Inferential Method and the Study of our own Minds. I have said that the introspective method is the method we use in studying our own mental facts. That needs qualification. It is possible for us to study our own minds by means of the inferential method. People often forget their motives for their actions. They say : " I do not know how I came to do that." In such cases they can learn their motives only by means of the inferential method, precisely as though they were other people whose actions they were considering, and which they were trying to account for. It is doubtless true, as we shall see in a later chapter, that in many cases there is no reason in the sense of conscious motive. Some idea suggested the action, and the action was straightway performed in the entire absence of anything that can be called reasoning. Further, the introspective method can only give us individual facts. As the bodily eye only sees isolated objects, and can not connect them by laws, so the eye of the mind only sees isolated mental facts, and can not connect them together by laws. In other words, we observe facts not laws. Laws are the result of inference never of direct obser- vation. The introspective and inferential methods, then the two methods of studying mind evidently sustain a close ,82 THE METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. relation to each other. You can, indeed, use the intro- spective method without the inferential, in the mere collec- tion of facts; but you can not use the inferential at all without the introspective. When you infer that people have such and such mental facts under such and such cir- cumstances, it is because you know by introspection that you have the same mental facts under the same circum- stances. The laughter and tears of others would have no meaning to you if you had never known amusement or sorrow. Difficulties of the Inferential Method. Each of these methods has its peculiar difficulties. The results reached by means of the inferential method are always more or less uncertain. If you have ever made a thorough study of the history of any great man, you have doubtless had an excellent illustration of this. While different his- torians generally agree substantially as to the actions of men, they differ very widely in their interpretations of those actions. Federalist historians, and those who sym- pathize with them, usually regard Jefferson, for example, as a demagogue, while Democratic historians regard him as an exalted and devoted patriot. The reason of course is that, using the inferential method, the one explained his actions by one set of mental facts, the other by another. Illustration. A passage in John Fiske's The Begin- nings of New England gives such an excellent illustration of the inferential method and its difficulties that it deserves to be quoted at length : " It is difficult for the civilized man and the savage to understand each other. As a rule, the one does not know DIFFICULTIES OF INTROSPECTIVE METHOD. 83 what the other is thinking about." And then, speaking of Eliot, and what the Indians thought about him, the author goes on : " His design in founding his villages of Christian Indians was in the highest degree benevolent and noble, but the heathen Indians could hardly be expected to see anything in it but a cunning scheme for destroying them. Eliot's converts were for the most part from the Massa- chusetts tribe, the smallest and weakest of all. The Plymouth converts came chiefly from the tribe next in weakness the Pokanokets, or Wampanoags. The more powerful tribes Narragansetts, Nipmucks, and Mohegans furnished very few converts. When they saw the white intruders gathering members of the weakest tribes into villages of English type, and teaching them strange gods while clothing them in strange garments, they probably supposed that the pale-faces were simply adopting these Indians into their white tribe as a means of increasing their military strength. At any rate, such a proceeding would be perfectly intelligible to the savage mind, whereas the nature of Eliot's design lay quite beyond its ken. As the Indians recovered from their supernatural dread of the English, and began to regard them as using human means to accomplish their ends, they must, of course, interpret their conduct in such light as savage experience could afford. It is one of the commonest things in the world for a savage tribe to absorb weak neighbors by adoption, and thus increase its force preparatory to a deadly assault upon other neighbors." Difficulties of the Introspective Method. The great difficulty with the introspective method is that a mental fact vanishes as soon as you begin to examine it introspec- 84 THE METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. lively. The feeling of amusement, of course, is a mental fact. The next time you are amused, suppose you try to analyze the feeling. Some psychologists say that it con- sists in part of a feeling of superiority. If you make a study of your experience to see whether they are right, your feeling of amusement will disappear. Or suppose you try to ascertain what sort of a mental fact pity is. \Yhen you find yourself pitying some one, if you examine your experience to see what pity is, the feeling will vanish. If the nature of flowers were such that they disappeared the moment one began to observe them closely, the study of Botany would exactly illustrate the difficulty of studying the mind by means of the introspective method. And as, in such a case, the botanist would have to content himself with observing his facts in the dim light of memory, so also must the psychologist. As his facts disappear the moment he begins to examine them, his only resource is to appeal to the memory his introspection becomes retrospection. Study of Children. Of course the minds that are of the most importance for you as teachers to study are the minds of children, and it is evident that you must study them by means of the inferential method. If you would get that knowledge of them that will enable you to teach them well, you must note their likes and dislikes, their amusements, their games, the books they read, the mis- takes they make everything, in short, that may throw light on their minds. Do not rely on any knowledge of the mind you can get from this or any book. A good book on Psychology is like a guide in a strange city useful chiefly in telling you where to look. But, as a guide QUESTIONS. 85 is of no service to a man who refuses to use his eyes, so a writer on Psychology can be of little use to his readers unless they constantly test his statements by their own experiences and by the study of the minds of those around them. 1 QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1 . What kind of mental facts constitutes the science of Psychology ? Illustrate. 2. What is a law of mental facts ? Illustrate. 3. State and explain and illustrate the two ways of studying mental facts. 4. Illustrate how the inferential method uses historical facts to enlarge our knowledge of mind. 5. How can you study your own mind by means of the inferential method ? 6. Point out the relations that exist between the two methods. 7. State and illustrate the difficulties of the two methods. SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1. Are there any mental facts which do not form part of the science of Psychology ? 2. Do you know any facts which indicate that there is a difference in the keenness of internal perception in different people ? 3. If you were a Turk or a Chinaman,^and knew nothing of any other people, how would it influence your notion of human nature? 4. Is pity a state of pleasure ? 5. How does the quotation from Fiske illustrate the difficulties of the inferential method ? 1 For a brief explanation of some varieties of the inferential method, see Appendix B. LESSON X. NECESSARY TRUTHS AND NECESSARY BELIEFS. WE would all agree that Geometry does right to state its axioms at the beginning. All its demonstrations depend upon 'them, and therefore it is proper that they should receive our attention at the outset. What we can Learn by Means of the Introspective Method. For similar reasons it is important for us to ascertain as clearly as possible what we can learn by means of the introspective method. Since the introspec- tive and the inferential methods are the only methods of studying mental facts, and since the inferential is based on the introspective, what we learn by means of the intro- spective method lies at the foundation of our knowledge of mind. If you were building a house, you would be especially careful about the foundation. You would want it all strong and well made, but you would take particular pains to see that there was no flaw in the foundation. No matter how strong and fine and beautiful the rest of the house might be, you would feel that if the foundation was weak the whole thing might come tumbling down about you any day. So it behooves us to look carefully to the foundation of our knowledge of mind, and therefore to ascertain precisely what kind of knowledge we have of the 86 INTROSPECTIVE METHOD. 87 facts known to us through introspection, and what we can learn by means of it. But the knowledge gained by introspection so closely resembles another kind of knowledge that the two are liable to be confused, unless at the outset the latter is clearly explained. To this end permit me, in imagination, to talk with you about some familiar matters. " Have you ever seen a stick with but one end, or a white crow ? " " No," you answer. " Do you think it possible that you ever will ? " " Possible to see a white crow ? Certainly there is no impossibility in that. I know no reason why a bird might not exist like the crow in every respect except the color of its feathers. But a stick with one end ? That is not merely an impossibility ; it is an absurdity. You can not even assert its existence." " Pardon me, but I think you are mistaken. ' This stick has but one end.' Have I not asserted its existence ? " " Apparently, but not really. You have indeed strung a lot of words together in the form of a sentence a sen- tence to which I have no objection on the score of gram- mar. But there is one fatal objection to it : it does not mean anything." " Does not mean anything ? I do not understand you." " Your statement does not express any action of the mind. All sentences that mean anything are expressions of thought. But when you say, ' This stick has but one end,' you have simply used your organs of speech ; you have not thought anything. I might teach a parrot to say, ' Kant's arguments in defense of the antinomies of human reason have never been refuted.' But what would those 88 NECESSARY TRUTHS AND BELIEFS. words mean in the mouth of a parrot ? Nothing, and that is all you mean when you assert the existence of a one- ended stick." "Possibly I am stupid, but I really do not see why." For this very simple reason : The word ' stick ' means a thing that has two ends. When, therefore, you say, ' This stick has but one end,' it is equivalent to saying, 'This two-ended thing has but one end ; this thing, which has two ends, has but one end.' Now it is easy enough to say that, but impossible to think it, is it not ? " " I see that it is. A thing can not have two ends and but one end at the same time ; it can not both be and not be." Necessary Truths. This is an example of what meta- physicians call necessary truths 1 "a truth or law the opposite of which is inconceivable, contradictory, nonsensi- cal, impossible." 3 A little reflection will enable us to think of many others. Two straight lines can not inclose a space ; two -j- three = five ; these are examples of neces- sary truths because the opposite of each of them is incon- ceivable, contradictory, nonsensical, impossible. If two straight lines could inclose a space, they could be straight and crooked at the same time ; if two -\- three could be more or less than five, it could be itself and not itself at the same time, which is absurd, contradictory, impossible. To determine whether a proposition expresses a neces- sary truth or not, we must see if we can put any meaning into the proposition which contradicts it. But in apply- ing the test we must be on our guard against confusing 1 These are sometimes called intuitions. a Terrier's Institutes of Metaphysics, p. 20. NECESSARY BELIEFS. 89 putting a meaning into the subject and predicate ting a meaning into the proposition. " This square is round." Here both subject and predicate bring up familiar ideas. But a moment's reflection enables us to see that the intelligibleness of the subject and predicate is a very different thing from the intelligibleness of the proposition. For if the square is round, it is itself and not itself at the same time, which is unthinkable and impossible. Necessary Beliefs. Let us now turn our attention to a class of propositions that, at first sight, look very much like necessary truths, but which, nevertheless, are funda- mentally different. You go to your room on a cold winter morning and begin to build a fire. " Why do you build a fire?" I ask. "Because it is cold." " What makes you think that a fire will make it warmer ? " " Because it did so yesterday, and the day before, and the day before that because it always has done so in the past." "But what has the past to do with the present and the future ? How do you know that things will behave in the future as they have done in the past?" I can not answer the question ; I do not believe any one can. The past, as Bain says, is separated from the future by a chasm which no resources of logic will ever enable us to bridge. 1 1 " The most authentic recollection gives only what has been, some- thing that has ceased and can concern us no longer. A far more perilous leap remains, the leap to the future. All our interest is concentrated on what is yet to be ; the present and the past are of value only as a clue to the events that are to come. " The postulate that we are in quest of must carry us across the gulf, from the experienced known, either present or remembered, to the unex- perienced and unknown must perform the leap of real inference. ' Water has quenched our thirst in the past ; by what assumption do we affirm 90 NECESSARY TRUTHS AND BELIEFS. But while we "can give no reason or evidence" that "what has been will be," that things will behave in the future as they have done in the past under precisely simi- lar circumstances, the peculiar fact is that we do not want any. When we know that a thing has happened in the past, we are entirely sure that it will, under similar cir- cumstances, in the future so sure that we can not help believing it even if we would. Necessity of Necessary Truths and Necessary Beliefs. This is one of the reasons why we may properly call such beliefs necessary the fact that we can not rid our- selves of them. But while they share this characteristic of inevitableness or necessity with necessary truths, the necessity in the two cases is of a very different character. The necessity of necessary truths is a necessity of seeing; the necessity of necessary beliefs is a necessity of believ- ing. We know with absolute certainty that two straight lines can not inclose a space ; we believe with irresistible strength of conviction that what has been will be, under similar circumstances not that it must be. We can not even think of two straight lines inclosing a space ; we can very easily think of this orderly universe becoming a chaos in which there would be an utter absence of law and order, in which combustion would be followed by heat one day, cold another, and so on. The necessity, then, of necessary beliefs is a necessity of belief, not of knowledge. We do that the same will happen in the future ? ' Experience does not teach us this ; experience is only what has actually been ; and after ever so many repetitions of a thing there still remains the peril of venturing upon the untrodden land of future possibility. What has been will be,' justifies the inference that water will assuage thirst in after-times. We can give no reason or evidence for this uniformity." Bain's Logic, p. 671. NECESSITY OF TRUTHS AND BELIEFS. Ql not know, strictly speaking, that the thing we believe so firmly is true, but we believe it with irresistible strength of conviction, notwithstanding. Some of our necessary beliefs for instance, the one we have been considering have another kind of necessity. If we did not assume that the past would enable us to judge of the future, all rational action would be impossible. Take that belief from the minds of men, and their rational activities would cease as suddenly as though they had been transformed into stone. I eat when I am hungry, drink when I am thirsty, rest when I am tired do every- thing which I do under the influence of that belief so far as my actions have any rational basis. The farmer sows, the mechanic builds, the lawyer prepares his brief, the doctor writes his prescription, because each thinks that a knowledge of the past enables him to anticipate the future more or less accurately. The principle, then, that what has been will be, is necessary not only in the sense that we can not get rid of it, but also in the sense that we must believe it in order to live in the world. If a being were born in the world destitute of the tendency or predisposition to accept the past as in some sense a type of the future, he would necessarily perish. Of necessary beliefs of this class it is absurd to raise the question as to their truth. Though we are not pre- vented from questioning them by the very nature of our minds as in the case of necessary truths still, if we must accept them in order to act and live, the possibility of questioning them will remain a bare possibility. But if we have beliefs that are necessary in the sense that we can not get rid of them, but not in the sense that 92 NECESSARY TRUTHS AND BELIEFS. we must accept them because of their practical importance, it is evident that the question as to their truth is altogether in order. A dozen different branches of science physics, chemistry, physiology, astronomy, etc., as well as Psychol- ogy have shown us very clearly that many of the things which seem to be true and which continue to seem to be after we know they are not are false. The sun still seems to rise and set, although we know it does not. To call a halt to investigation, therefore, on the threshold of necessary beliefs of this character would amount to an attempt to protect Error against the assaults of Truth. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1. What is the relation between the introspective and inferential methods ? 2. Why is it important for us to learn what we are conscious of ? 3. State the difference between a necessary truth and a necessary belief. 4. Can you doubt a necessary belief ? 5. What are the two classes of necessary beliefs ? 6. Can you question the truth of a necessary belief ? 7. What is the difference in meaning between questions four and six? , SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1. Make as complete a list as you can of what you regard as necessary truths. 2. What do you suppose the phrase, entertain the idea," orig- inally meant? 3- You believe many things because, as you say, you remember them. Are the assertions of memory examples of necessary truths, or necessary beliefs, or neither ? 4- What does Bain mean by the "leap of real inference "? QUESTIONS. 93 5. Mention some other necessary beliefs besides the one spoken of in the lesson. 6. Mention some that are necessary in the sense that we can not help believing them, but not necessary in the sense that the nature of the world compels us to assume them. 7. Mention some things that seem to us to be true, although science has shown that they are not. 8. What is meant by the " uniformity of nature " ? LESSON XI. WHAT ARE WE CONSCIOUS OF ? THE object of the last lesson was to make clear the distinction between necessary truths and necessary beliefs. I tried to show that there are truths that the mind must see when it clearly grasps the subject and predicate of the proposition that expresses them. But the mind by no means inevitably sees all the necessary truths it is capable of seeing, because there are subjects and predicates that are beyond its grasp at certain stages of its development, and others that it might grasp, but which, as a matter of fact, it has not grasped. " Seven plus five makes twelve " is a necessary truth. But the child does not see it, because he can not grasp seven and five. A necessary truth, then, is not a truth that the mind must see, but. one which, when seen, is seen to be necessary. Necessary beliefs resemble necessary truths in that we are not only willing, but, in a measure, forced to believe them, in the absence of reason and evidence. Indeed, we are certain both of necessary truths and necessary beliefs ; but our certainty differs widely in the two cases. In the one, it is a certainty of knowledge ; in the other, of belief. Moreover, the necessity of necessary beliefs, unlike that of necessary truths, is not in all cases absolutely unyield- ing in its nature. When we look through an opera-glass 94 NATURE OF NECESSARY TRUTHS. 95 we can not help seeming to see the object much nearer than it really is. Such irresistible "seemings" we call beliefs until, we learn that they are false, but no longer. This is one of a multitude of instances in which what seems to be true is directly opposed to what we know to be true. It would appear, therefore, only a matter of com- mon prudence to accept as true only those necessary beliefs which we can not get along without. Reasons for Studying the Nature of Necessary Truths. Necessary truths, necessary beliefs, and what we are conscious of, then, constitute the foundation of everything we know and believe, not only about mind, but about the world in general. Now that we know what necessary truths and necessary beliefs are, it will be com- paratively easy for us to determine the kind of knowledge that consciousness is, and the kinds of facts of which we are conscious. If we had attempted to learn what con- sciousness is before making a study of necessary truths, there would have been great danger of our confusing the knowledge of the facts that we are conscious of, with the knowledge of necessary truths. Nature of Conscious Knowledge. Let us first try to ascertain what that kind of knowledge is that we call con- scious knowledge. For to ask what kind of facts we are conscious of is to ask what we know in precisely the same way, with the same kind and degree of certainty, that we do the facts which every one admits we are conscious of. Every one admits that we are conscious of the mental facts we know by introspection. Evidently, in order to learn whether we are conscious of anything else, we need 96 WHAT ARE WE CONSCIOUS OF? to learn whether we know anything else in the same way, and with the same kind and degree of certainty ; we need to learn whether our knowledge of any other facts has the same characteristics as our knowledge of mental facts. When Columbus first came to this country, if he had been told that certain animals that he saw were buffaloes, he would have had to learn their characteristics in order to be able to recognize buffaloes when he saw them again. Knowing their characteristics, he would have been able to recognize a buffalo as easily as a horse or dog. In like manner, since we are conscious of those facts which we have agreed to call mental facts, we have to learn the characteristics of our knowledge of mental facts, in order to learn whether we are conscious of anything else. For if our knowledge of anything else has the same character- istics as our conscious knowledge, it also must be conscious knowledge. What, then, are the characteristics of the kind of knowledge that every one admits to be conscious knowledge ? Have you ever been in pain ? Suppose that, while you were writhing in agony, some one had asked you if you were sure you had any pain. How do you think you would have answered the question if, indeed, you had possessed the patience to answer it at all ? You would have said, I think, that your certainty was so great that it could be no greater. Put so much water into a glass, and not another drop, not an atom more can you make it hold. So, you would have said, certainty beyond or greater than yours it was impossible for any conscious being to have. " But may you not be deceived may not your pain be a mere illusion, like the experiences of your dreams ? " your questioner might have asked. Deceived as to being in DIFFERENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. 97 pain, when I am literally writhing in agony ? No ! I know it so absolutely that I know that I can not be mistaken. There is much that I believe that I realize I may be mis- taken in. But this is certainty certainty that admits of no doubt- certainty that makes doubt an absurdity and an impossibility." Conscious knowledge, then, is abso- lutely certain knowledge knowledge so certain as to make doubt an absurdity and an impossibility. Difference between Knowledge of Necessary Truths and Conscious Knowledge. But this, we have seen, is exactly what the knowledge of necessary truths is. We know that two straight lines can not inclose a space so certainly as to make doubt an absurdity and an impos- sibility. Is there no difference between the knowledge of necessary truths and conscious knowledge ? If we compare the attitude of our minds towards a necessary truth with its attitude towards a mental fact, I think we shall see a difference. Two straight lines can not inclose a space. Where ? In England, on the sun, wherever straight lines are, we know that they can not inclose a space. Our knowledge is not of an individual fact, with which the mind seems face to face, but of an entire class of facts, wherever they may exist. But our knowledge of a pain, for example, although it is like our knowledge of a necessary truth in the kind and degree of certainty that it gives us, differs from it in being knowledge of an individual fact with which the mind seems face to face of which the mind seems directly aware. Conscious knowledge, then, is absolutely certain knowl- edge of individual facts of which the mind seems directly aware. Instead, then, of asking whether there are any 98 WHAT ARE WE CONSCIOUS OF ? facts except mental facts that we are conscious of, we can put the question in this form : Are there any facts except mental facts with which the mind seems face to face, and which we know with such absolute certainty as to make doubt an absurdity and an impossibility ? Are you Conscious of the Stars? Perhaps, some evening shortly after reading this lesson, you will take a walk. As you glance at the stars shining so brightly above you, you think of the subject of the lesson, and ask yourself if you really are conscious of them. Do you, as you see those little twinkling points of light in the heavens above you, know that they exist, so certainly, so absolutely, as to make doubt an impossibility ? The fixed stars, as we know, are almost inconceivably far away. They are so far away that astronomers never think of stating their distance in miles. Instead of telling us their distance in miles, they tell us how long it takes light to travel from them to us. Now, light travels about 180,000 miles in a second, and the nearest of the fixed stars is so far away that it takes light three years to come from it to us. Suppose, then, that the nearest fixed star had been destroyed two years and a half ago. Would you see it to-night ? Certainly, just as you see any other star ; for the light that strikes your eyes as you look at it left it two years and a half ago six months before it was destroyed. And for the same reason you would see it to-morrow night, and the next, and so on for six months. Night after night for six months you would see the star shining above you, although it did not exist at all. When, then, I ask if you know that the stars exist as you look at them, evidently the most you can say is that they do, THE OBJECTS ABOUT YOU. 99 unless they have been destroyed since the light left them by which you now see them. But if that is your answer, you can not say that you know that they exist so absolutely as to make doubt an impossibility, for you do not know that they have not been destroyed since the light left them which enables you to see them. Therefore you are not conscious of them. Are you Conscious of the Objects about you ? " But at any rate," perhaps you will say, " I am conscious of the objects about me. I take a walk, and I see the beautiful bouquets of autumn adorning the hill-sides. I see the fields stretching out before me, and here and there a farmer busy at work. As I mark how the leaves of the hedge were nipped by last night's frost, a rabbit suddenly leaps from under my feet, and I wish for my gun as he fairly flies away from me. Surely," you will say, "you will admit that I am conscious of these things." Are you ? Put the question to yourself. Ask yourself if you know that these things exist so absohitely that doubt is an impossibility. Do you like hunting ? If so, I am sure you have dreamed of standing behind a trusty pointer, gun in hand, ready to take the first quail that made its appearance above the weeds. And while you are in the midst of your excitement you awake perhaps to find that you have neither dog nor gun to find that you have been hunting only in a dream. " What of it ? " you ask. This : A certainty quite as great as indeed indistinguishable from your waking certainties proved untrustworthy ; may not your waking certainties be unreliable ? You will not, of course, imagine that I doubt that I see and hear the various things which I seem to see and hear, or that I0 WHAT ARE WE CONSCIOUS OF? I am trying to make you doubt them. I am simply trying to show that you do not know them with the same absolute certainty that you do the mental facts of your experience, and that, therefore, you are not conscious of them. Strongest Argument that we are not Conscious of External Objects. But these arguments, conclusive as they seem to me, are not the considerations which are entitled to most weight. Simply by looking into my own mind, I know that I do not know the existence of the objects about me with the same kind and degree of cer- tainty that I do the mental facts I am conscious of, and therefore I know that I am not conscious of them. Look carefully into your experience, and you will see that the only facts which you know with absolute certainty are the facts of your own mental life. You will need no arguments to prove that you can not have absolute knowl- edge of any other individual facts you will see that you do not so clearly as to make argument superfluous. But if you do not, permit me to ask you to hold your judgment in suspense until you have had more experience in the study of mental facts. You would take the opinion of a sailor as to the character of a distant object at sea in preference to your own, simply because of his more ex- tended experience. Inasmuch as trained psychologists, almost without exception, contend that we are not con- scious of the objects about us, I ask you to hold your judg- ment in suspense until you have studied the subject long enough to give you a right to an opinion. Not Conscious of our own Bodies. It seems to me equally clear that we are not conscious of our own bodies. QUESTIONS. IOI A man with an amputated limb often feels pain in the amputated member, exactly as he does in any other part of the body. But he can not be conscious of the ampu- tated limb. You admit that. You admit that a man can not be conscious of a leg that has been buried for months. Well, if he seems to be conscious of the amputated mem- ber and is not, he has no reason to believe that he is con- scious of a member that is not amputated because he seems to be. I think we may conclude, therefore, that we know no other individual facts with the same kind and degree of certainty that we do the facts of which we are conscious ; and that, therefore, we are conscious of nothing else. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1. What is the foundation of all we know and believe? 2. What is the difference between our knowledge of a necessary truth and our knowledge of a mental fact ? 3. Are you conscious of the stars ? Of the objects about you ? Of your own body ? 4. Give your reasons for your answers. 5. If you believe that you are not conscious of anything except mental facts, state what you regard as the strongest reason for your opinion. SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1 . Give examples of necessary truths that are beyond the grasp of a savage. 2. How do you account for the effect of looking at an object through an opera-glass ? 3. What is the difference between real pain and imaginary pain ? IO2 WHAT ARE WE CONSCIOUS OF? 4. " In this wonder-world a dream is Our whole life and all its changes, All we seem to be and do Is a dream and fancy too. Briefly, on this earthen ball Dreaming that we're living all." What part of these assertions do you know to be false ? 5. How do you account for the fact that a man often feels pain in an amputated limb ? LESSON XII. ATTENTION. Sensation and Attention. We have seen that conscious knowledge is that knowledge which we have of those men- tal facts which we know directly. We have learned also that there are mental facts of which we are not conscious. You remember the example a student intent upon a book and not hearing the clock strike till a moment after. What is the explanation of such facts ? The attention of the student was so fixed upon this book his entire con- sciousness was so concentrated upon it that there was no consciousness left for the sensation. Thus the sensations of which vve are conscious depend tipon attention. In his Mental Physiology, Carpenter gives some remarkable examples of this. For instance : " Before the introduction of chloroform, patients sometimes went through severe operations without giving any sign of pain, and afterwards declared that they felt none : having concentrated their thoughts, by a powerful effort of abstraction, on some subject which held them engaged throughout." "The writer has frequently begun a lecture, whilst suffering neuralgic pain so severe as to make him apprehend that he would find it impossible to proceed ; yet no sooner has he, by a determined effort, fairly launched himself into the stream of thought than he has found himself continu- 103 IO4 ATTENTION. ously borne along without the least distraction until the end has come, and the attention has been released ; when the pain has recurred with a force that has overmastered all resistance, making him wonder how he could have ever ceased to feel it." A similar experience in the case of Sir Walter Scott is thus recorded by his biographer : " John Ballantyne (whom Scott, while suffering under a prolonged and painful illness, employed as his amanuensis) told me that, though Scott often turned himself on his pillow with a groan of torment, he usually continued the sentence in the same breath. But when dialogue of peculiar animation was in progress, spirit seemed to triumph altogether over matter he arose from his couch, and walked up and down the room, raising and lowering his voice, and, as it were, acting the parts. It was in this fashion that Scott produced the far greater portion of the Bride of Lammer- inoor, the whole of the Legend of Montr ose, and almost the whole of Ivan hoc." Perception and Attention. What we perceive depends upon attention. Let a botanist and a geologist take the same walk and the botanist will see the flowers, and the geologist the rocks, because each sees what he attends to. The next time you take a walk go along the most familiar road in your neighborhood, and see if you can not discover something new to you some tree or shed that has been there all the time. I have often had that expe- rience. The reason is that these unperceived objects were not attended to. Memory and Attention. What we remember depends upon what we attend to. Have you ever thought of it ? RECOLLECTION AND ATTENTION. 1 05 Most of our past lives is a perfect Sahara of forgetfulness blank, bleak, barren swallowed up in oblivion. But here and there gleam little green spots of memory, little oases in the midst of the mighty desert of the past. How is this? The things which we remember are the things which we attend to. Talk to an old man about his past life, and you will find that the events of the last year he but dimly remembers ; but when he speaks of his boy- hood, the incidents of the time crowd themselves upon him as though they had happened but yesterday. In that far-off happy time, when his heart was light and his mind was free from care, the most trivial events received a degree of attention sufficient to stamp them on his memory forever. Recollection and Attention. What we recollect depends upon what we attend to. (Recollecting is remem- bering by an effort of will. All recollecting is remember- ing, but all remembering is not recollecting. Recollecting is a kind of remembering.) What do you do when you try to recall the name of a friend which has slipped your memory for the moment ? You think of attend to the thought of how he looks, of his dress, of some peculiarity in his manner, of the first letter of his name, of some place where you saw him, of something connected with him until, by and by, his name flashes into your mind. All you did, you notice, was to attend to certain thoughts in your mind. Reasoning and Attention. What conclusions you reach depends upon what you attend to. To Newton, sitting in his garden, the fall of an apple suggested the I0 6 ATTENTION. law of gravitation. Why ? Because he fixed his attention upon the resemblance between the fall of the apple from the tree and the revolution of the moon around the earth. The chief difference between the man of great reasoning powers and the ordinary man is that the former notices remote resemblances resemblances that escape the atten- tion of the latter. Feeling and Attention. What we feel depends upon attention. The same author already quoted from (Car- penter) gives some remarkable illustrations of this : The celebrated German mathematician, Gauss, while engaged in one of his most profound investigations, was interrupted by a servant, who told him that his wife (to whom he was known to be deeply attached, and who was suffering from a severe illness) was worse. " He seemed to hear what was said, but either he did not comprehend it or imme- diately forgot it, and went on with his work. After some little time, the servant came again to say that his mistress was much worse, and to beg that he would come to her at once ; to which he replied : ' I will come presently.' Again he relapsed into his previous train of thought, entirely for- getting the intention he had expressed, most probably without having distinctly realized to himself the import either of the communication or of his answer to it. For not long afterwards when the servant came again and assured him that his mistress was dying, and that if he did not come immediately he would probably not find her alive, he lifted up his head and calmly replied : ' Tell her to wait until I come ' - - a message he had doubtless often before sent when pressed by his wife's request for his presence while he was similarly engaged." VOLITION AND ATTENTION. 107 Volition and Attention. What we will likewise de- pends upon attention. Suppose a boy has a lesson to get, and another boy invites him to go fishing. Will he go or will he stay and get his lesson ? That depends on what he attends to. If he allows his mind to dwell on the fun he will have, if he does not permit himself to think of the consequences of neglecting his work, he will go. But if he keeps his mind firmly fixed on the consequences ; if he vividly realizes the displeasure of his parents, the disappro- bation of his teacher, the probability of losing his place in his class, he will stay. Importance of the Part Played by Attention in our Mental Life. This brief survey will enable us to form some idea of the importance of the part which attention plays in our mental life. I think you see that the chief difference between the educated and the uneducated man is the greater capacity of the former for close, continuous, concentrated attention. Some writers indeed have gone so far as to say that genius depends entirely on the power to concentrate the attention. Newton thought that the sole difference between himself and ordinary men consisted in his greater power of attention. This, I think, is an exaggeration. But however this may be, I think that the importance of training the attention can scarcely be over- estimated. Training of Attention. How can we train the atten- tion of our pupils ? Precisely as we cultivate any other power of their minds by getting them to attend. Our pupils learn to observe by observing, and to think by thinking, and to attend by attending. We never make IO8 ATTENTION. the mistake of assuming that our pupils have a high degree of reasoning power when they first go to school, that they are capable of solving difficult problems in arithmetic, or understanding abstract statements in gram- mar ; and it is just as absurd for us to suppose that they are capable of continuous attention, and yet we are prone to do that. "Because people are attentive when strong interest is roused" says Edward Thring "there is a common idea that attention is natural, and inattention a culpable fault. But the boy's mind is much like a frolicking puppy, always in motion, restless, but never in the same position two minutes together, when really awake. Naturally his body partakes of this unsettled character. Attention is a lesson to be learned, and quite as much a matter of training as any other lesson. A teacher will be saved much useless friction if he acknowledges this fact, and instead of expecting attention which he will not get, starts at once with the intention of teaching it." How can he teach it ? That question is of the utmost impor- tance for us to be able to answer. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT. 1. Show (a) that the sensations of which we are conscious depend upon attention ; (b) that what we perceive depends upon attention ; (c) that what we remember depends upon attention ; (cf) that what we recollect depends upon attention ; (e) that what we believe de- pends upon attention ; (/) that what we feel depends upon attention ; (g) that what we will depends upon attention. 2. Illustrate your answers from your own experience. 3. Illustrate the difference between remembering and recollecting. 4. How is the power of attention to be acquired ? QUESTIONS. IO9 SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1. "The botanist sees much in a plant; the horse-dealer in a horse ; the musician hears much in a piece of orchestral music, of whose presence in the sense-perception the layman has no idea. From the same story each hearer interprets something different; out of the same laws each party interprets its right; the same turn of battle is proclaimed by both armies as a victory ; out of the same book of nature the different readers, men and people, have gathered the most diverse things." (Volkmann.) How would you explain these facts ? 2. Account for the truth embodied in the proverb, "There are none so blind as those that won't see." 3. Account for the use of mind in the following sentence : " I can't put my mind on anything to-day." LESSON XIII. ATTENTION. (Continued.] IN the last lesson I tried to make it clear that our entire mental life is controlled by attention, in order that we may realize that the beginning of teaching is getting the atten- tion of our pupils, and that the end of education is the developing of powers of attention, and directing those powers into right channels. An inattentive mind is an absent mind ; and, as Thring remarks, a teacher " might as well stand up and solemnly set about giving a lesson to the clothes of the class, whilst the owners were playing cricket, as to the so-called class " if they were inattentive. Moreover, as the character of the mind depends upon the things it attends to and the manner in which it attends to them, evidently the object of education is to develop the power of attending to the right things in the right way. Definition of Attention. But what is attention ? When you are reading an interesting book, you are scarcely conscious, if at all, of the sensations of pressure produced by your chair ; carriages and wagons are clattering along the street, but you do not note them ; various objects are directly before you, but you do not see them. Indeed, you are but dimly conscious of the sensations produced by the very type of the book you are reading. But the thoughts no TWO KINDS OF ATTENTION. I I I called to your mind by your book stand out clearly and conspicuously in your consciousness every feature, as it were, sharply denned. The act of the mind by which certain facts in our experience are thus emphasized and made prominent is called attention. Attention, then, may be defined as that act of the mind by which we bring into clear consciousness any subject or object before the mind. When you say to your pupils, " Give me your attention," you mean that you want them to stop thinking of the game they played at recess, of the book they read last night, of everything except what you are saying. 1 Two Kinds of Attention. Making another study of our experience, we find that there are two kinds of atten- tion. You are reading a difficult and not very interesting book, when some one in the next room begins to sing your favorite song. You do your best to keep your attention on your book, but your mind wanders to the song in spite of you. Or you go to a lecture just after reading a letter that contained some very good news. You try to listen to the lecture, but the thought of the letter persists in drag- ging your mind away. In both these cases you are con- 1 " Clear consciousness may be thought as the circle of those concepts " experiences "upon which attention rests. Experience shows us that this circle, like the pupil of the eye, can be extended or contracted within certain rather wide limits. The greatest narrowing occurs when we con- centrate our attention upon a single object as, for example, when we become absorbed in thought, or narrowly observe an outward phenom- enon ; the greatest extension takes place when we widen the bounds of the narrow consciousness to its greatest extent, in which case there would be really no concentration of mind and no attention. It is apparent that the width of the circle is indirectly proportioned to the clearness of its single points i.e., that our attention is so much the less intensive the more extensive it is." Lindner's Psychology, p. 13. 112 ATTENTION. scious of two very different kinds of attention attention depending upon the will, or voluntary attention, and atten- tion independent of the will, or non-voluntary attention. We can see the difference between them more clearly, perhaps, if we bear in mind that, in the case of non-volun- tary attention, there is but one thing that influences the mind the thing attended to ; while in voluntary attention there are two the thing attended to and some reason or motive for attending to it. When you listen to a song simply because you like it, you attend involuntarily ; when you keep your mind fixed upon a book by an effort of will, you attend voluntarily. In the first case, there are but two things concerned your mind and the song ; in the second, there are three your mind and the book, and some reason or motive for attending to it. In the first case, you attend because of the attraction which the song has for your mind directly; in the second, you attend not because of any attraction which the book has for your mind, but because of its relation to something else that attracts you directly, as the desire to improve. Non-volun- tary attention, then, is that attention which results from the influence exerted upon the mind by the thing attended to, in and of itself; voluntary attention is that which results from the influence exerted upon the mind, not by the thing attended to, but by the knowledge of its relation to something else that attracts the mind in and of itself. Conditions of Voluntary Attention. It is evident that voluntary attention is impossible without some variety of experience and some mental development. To attend voluntarily, we must perceive relations ; and to perceive relations, the mind must have had experience, and must CHILDREN AND VOLUNTARY ATTENTION. 113 be developed enough to interpret that experience. A bath may, almost from the beginning, give a child pleasant sensations. But his mind must be developed enough to perceive the relations between the preparations for his bath and the bath before the sight of the former can give him pleasure. Moreover, it is evident that the child must not only have had experience of relations in order to regard one thing as the sign of another ; he must have not only some development of intellect to be able to connect things together, but also .some development of his capacity for feeling, in order to be able to form ideas of things desir- able in themselves. When the child is able to form the idea of a thing desirable in itself, and to see the connec- tion between such a thing and something undesirable, the latter begins to be interesting because of its relation to the former the conditions of voluntary attention exist. Very Young Children Incapable of Voluntary Atten- tion. This analysis of the circumstances under which voluntary attention is possible prepares us to anticipate what observation confirms that very young children are incapable of voluntary attention. Indeed, it seems prob- able that in the first days of a child's life there is no atten- tion of any kind. Mental Life of Very Young Children. The mental life of a new-born child seems to consist of a mass of con- fused sensations, none of them coming into clear and dis- tinct consciousness, because none of them are attended to. But the quality of some of its sensations, their character as pleasant or painful, causes the sensations that possess it to be emphasized in the child's experience. Bain well says 114 ATTENTION. that "enjoyment, immediate and incessant, is a primary vocation of the infant mind." Two Causes of Non-voluntary Attention. " In the presence of the more enjoyable, the less enjoyable is dis- regarded." "Attention lasts so long as enjoyment lasts, and no longer." 1 So far as a child is under the influence of pleasure alone, these statements are true without quali- fication. But pain has fully as strong a hold on attention as pleasure. Moreover, as the same author remarks, " In- tensity of sensation, whether pleasant or not, is a power." A bright light, a loud noise, "take the attention by storm." But in considering the effect of intensity of sensations upon attention, we must bear in mind that the greater their relative intensity the greater, in other words, the contrast between the sensation and the other experiences of the child the stronger will be its influence in attract- ing his attention. A remark made in an ordinary tone, for example, when it breaks in upon absolute stillness, will attract attention more strongly than one made in a very loud tone in the midst of noise and confusion. Under the influence of these two causes the quality of sensations or their character as pleasurable or painful and their intensity, absolute and relative, the child's power of attention develops with wonderful rapidity. As long as he is capable only of non-voluntary attention, he is at the mercy of his impressions. As the course of a stream depends upon the slope of the ground, so the direc- tion of his attention depends upon the attractiveness of his sensations. 1 Bain's Education as a Science, p. 179. POWER OF VOLUNTARY ATTENTION. 115 How the Power of Voluntary Attention is Developed. But the exercise of non-voluntary attention develops the power to attend voluntarily. Every exercise of non-volun- tary attention makes that kind of attention easier. Sensa- tions less and less intense sensations whose pleasurable or painful character is less and less pronounced have power to attract it, in accordance with the universal law of the mind that exercise develops power. While the child's power of non-voluntary attention is in this way increasing, his growing experience is leading him to form ideas of things he desires, and to perceive the relation between the things that give him pleasure and the means of gratifying his desires. When this relation is clearly perceived, all the conditions of voluntary attention exist. Probably the first exercise of distinctively voluntary attention usually occurs when the child is from three to six months old. Experiment upon a Child. Professor Preyer reports an instructive experiment made by Professor Lindner upon his little daughter, twenty-six weeks old, which experiment proves conclusively that the child was exercising voluntary attention : "While the child, at this age, was taking milk as she lay in the cradle, the bottle took such a slant that she could not get anything to suck. She now tried to direct the bottle with her feet, and finally raised it by means of them so dex- terously that she could drink conveniently. This action was manifestly no imitation ; it can not have depended upon a mere accident ; for when, at the next feeding, the bottle is purposely so placed that the child can not get anything without the help of hands or feet, the same performance Il6 ATTENTION. takes place as before. Then, on the following day, when the child drinks in the same way, I prevent her from doing so by removing her feet from the bottle, but she at once makes use of them again as regulators for the flow of the milk, as dexterously and surely as if the feet were made on purpose for such use. If it follows from this that the child acts with deliberation long before it uses language in the proper sense, it also appears how imperfect and crude the delibera- tion is, for my child drank her milk in this awkward fashion for three whole months, until she at last made the discovery one day that, after all, the hands are much better adapted to service of this sort. I had given strict orders to those about her to let her make this advance of herself." What the Experiment Proves. We must not forget to note that the conditions of voluntary attention were completely fulfilled in this case, and that it was only through this that the child's action was possible. If the child had not known by experience the relation between certain movements and the effects of those movements, she would not have been able to attend to those move- ments in themselves uninteresting in order to get hold of her bottle. And if her experience had not enabled her to form an idea of her bottle as a thing that gave her pleasure, it would not have been possible for her to fix her attention upon certain movements as a means of experi- encing that pleasure. QUESTIONS ON THE TEXT, t so important for you to know th 2. Illustrate and define the two kinds of attention. I. Why is it so important for you to know the conditions of attention ? QUESTIONS. 117 3. State and illustrate the conditions of voluntary attention. 4. Show that these conditions can not be fulfilled in the case of a very young child. 5. Describe as clearly as you can the consciousness of a new- born child. 6. What are the two causes of non-voluntary attention in a child's experience ? 7. Show how the conditions of voluntary attention are gradually developed. 8. Analyze the voluntary attention exercised by Prof. Lindner's child for the purpose of showing that the conditions of voluntary attention were fulfilled. SUGGESTIVE QUESTIONS. 1 . Account for the miser's love of money. 2. Account for the knowledge of Prof. Lindner's child. 3. Make a study of any children you know of from two or three months to six or seven years of age in order to ascertain (i) the kind of objects that attract their non-voluntary attention ; and (2) the lines of interests that control their voluntary attention after they are capable of exercising it. 4. President G. Stanley Hall says: "It is a striking fact that nearly every great teacher in the history of education who has spoken words that have been heeded has lived for years in the closest personal relations to children, and has had the sympathy and tact that gropes out, if it can not see clearly, the laws of juvenile development and lines of childish interests." (a) Who are some of the great teachers of whom he speaks? (b~) In what way do you think their personal relations to children were helpful to them ? (<:) Do you know any important educational questions that can be best solved by a careful and systematic study of children ? (r~-23Z O-i^o-.- s I> -sc3e *TfcK* ICmfce Dedaajac-.ca f r C^il-j- it=i Tfawt JCnote Rea.Cagx f-r r-z^ii Da^.ocarT * " t7n. Tnffiiab. Fir." Dxaooarr ' M'I ' ii i j * ** r^Bih. TaiJiifc Cn i \ Fkliu j ifc F i . Dicaamafj .............. x^a Hinds It 5o&e*s Xr Teacaoieit Lexxco. , T*J JJOU ip - - " -r OUT: ri n't'i Ti iki i riiMMi "ifc i f fTin irli IT 1 n rt