Digitized by the Internet Archive 
 in 2007 with funding from . 
 IVIicrosoft Corporation 
 
 http://www.archive.org/details/earlygreekphilosOOburnrich 
 
EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
5 
 
 AGENTS 
 
 America . The Macmillan Company 
 
 64 & 66 Fifth Avenue, New York 
 
 Australasia The Oxford University Press 
 
 205 Flinders Lane, Melbourne 
 
 Canada . . The Macmillan Company of Canada, Ltd. 
 
 St. Martin's House, 70 Bond Street, Toronto 
 
 India . . . Macmillan & Company, Ltd. 
 
 Macmillan Building, Bombay 
 
 309 Bow Bazaar Street, Calcutta 
 
i 
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 PAGES 
 
 Introduction ........ 1-30 
 
 t 
 
 |MOTE ON THE SOURCES 31-38 
 
 I CHAPTER I 
 
 The Milesian School 39-79 ^ 
 
 jl CHAPTER n 
 
 I Science and Religion 80-129 
 
 CHAPTER HI 
 Herakleitos of Ephesos* 130-168 ^ 
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 Parmenides of Elea 169-196 ^ 
 
 CHAPTER V 
 
 Empedokles of Akragas 197-250 ^ 
 
 CHAPTER VI 
 Anaxagoras of Klazomenai . . . . . 251-275 V 
 
 CHAPTER VII 
 
 The Pythagoreans 276-309 
 
 vii 
 
viii EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 CHAPTER VIII 
 
 PAGES 
 
 v/ The Younger Eleatics 310-329 
 
 CHAPTER IX 
 ^ Leukippos of Miletos 330-34^ 
 
 CHAPTER X 
 
 Eclecticism and Reaction 350-361 
 
 1 
 
 APPENDIX 363-364 
 
 INDEX 365-375 
 
ABBREVIATIONS 
 
 Arch. Archiv fur Geschichte det Philosothie. Berlin, 1888- 
 
 1920. 
 
 Be ARE. Greek Theories of Elementary Cognition^ by John I. 
 
 Beare. Oxford, 1906. 
 
 DiELS Dox. Doxographi graeci. Hermannus Diels. Berlin, 1879. 
 
 DiELS Vors. Die Fragntente der Vorsokratiker, von Hermann Diels, 
 Dritte Auflage. Berlin, 1912. 
 
 GOMPERZ. Greek Thinkers^ by Theodor Gomperz, Authorised 
 (English) Edition, vol. i. London, 1901. 
 
 Jacoby. Apollodors Chronik, von Felix Jacoby {Philol. Unters. 
 
 Heft xvi.). Berlin, 1902. 
 
 R. P. Historia Philosophiae Graecae, H. Ritter et L. Preller. 
 
 Editio octava, quam curavit Eduardus Wellmann. 
 Gotha, 1898. 
 
 Zeller. Die Philosophie der Griechen^ dargestellt von Dr. Eduard 
 
 Zeller. Erster Theil, Fiinfte Auflage. Leipzig, 1892. 
 

 ri 
 
EARLY G^EK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 INTRODUCTION 
 
 I. It was not till the traditional view of the world and the The cos- 
 customary rules of life had broken down, that the Greeks ^°i^a^cter 
 ""' began to feel the needs which philosophies of nature and q^.^^'^ 
 of conduct seek to satisfy. Nor were those needs felt ptuo- 
 all at once. The ancestral maxims of conduct were not 
 seriously questioned till the old view of nature had passed 
 away ; and, for this reason, the earHest philosophers busied 
 themselves mainly with speculations about the world 
 around them. In due season. Logic was called into being 
 to meet a fresh want. The pursuit of cosmological inquiry 
 had brought to Hght a wide divergence between science and 
 common sense, which was itself a problem that demanded 
 solution, and moreover constrained philosophers to study 
 the means of defending their paradoxes against the pre- 
 judices of the unscientific. Later still, the prevaiUng 
 interest in logical matters raised the question of the origin 
 and vahdity of knowledge ; while, about the same time, 
 the break-down of traditional moraUty gave rise to Ethics. 
 The period which precedes the rise of Logic and Ethics has 
 thus a distinctive character of its own, and may fitly be 
 treated apart .^ 
 
 ^ It will be observed that Demokritos falls outside the period thus 
 defined. The common practice of treating this younger contemporary of 
 Sokrates along with the " Pre-Socratics " obscures the historical develop- 
 ment altogether. Demokritos comes after Protagoras, and he has to face 
 the problems of knowledge and conduct far more seriously than his pre- 
 decessors had done (see Brochard, " Protagoras et Democrite," Arch. ii. 
 p. 368). 
 
2 ^^^.^ EARLY. GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The IL J^ .Hi\js,t,. .however; \be remembered that the world 
 
 vtewoP^ was aheady Very'' old ^'\\^eri science and philosophy began, 
 the world. In particular, the Aegean Sea had been the seat of a high 
 civiUsation from the NeoUthic age onwards, a civiUsation 
 as ancient as that of Egypt or of Babylon, and superior to 
 either in most things that matter. It is becoming clearer 
 every day that the Greek civilisation of later days was 
 mainly the revival and continuation of this, though it no 
 doubt received certain new and important elements from 
 the less civiUsed northern peoples who for a time arrested 
 its development. The original Mediterranean population 
 must have far outnumbered the intruders, and must have 
 assimilated and absorbed them in a few generations, except 
 in a state like Sparta, which dehberately set itself to resist 
 the process. At any rate, it is to th^ older race we owe 
 Greek Art and Greek Science. ^ \lVis a remarkable fact 
 
 1 See Sir Arthur Evans, " The Minoan and Mycenean Element in 
 Hellenic Life " (J.H.S. xxxii. 277 sqq.), where it is contended (p. 278) 
 that " The people whom we discern in the new dawn are not the pale- 
 skinned northerners — the ' yellow-haired Achaeans ' and the rest — but 
 essentially the dark-haired, brown -complexioned race ... of whom we 
 find the earlier portraiture in the Minoan and Mycenean wall-paintings." 
 But, if the Greeks of historical times were the same people as the 
 *' Minoans," why should Sir Arthur Evans hesitate to call the " Minoans " 
 Greeks ? The Achaians and Dorians have no special claim to the name ; 
 ; for the Graes of Boiotia, who brought it to Cumae, were of the older race. 
 I can attach no intelligible meaning either to the term " pre-Hellenic." 
 If it means that the Aegean race was there before the somewhat un- 
 important Achaian tribe which accidentally gave its name later to the 
 whole nation, that is true, but irrelevant. If, on the other hand, it implies 
 that there was a real change in the population of the Aegean at any time 
 since the end of the Neolithic age, that is untrue, as Sir Arthur Evans 
 himself maintains. If it means (as it probably does) that the Greek 
 language was introduced into the Aegean by the northerners, there is no 
 evidence of that, and it is contrary to analogy. The Greek language, 
 as we know it, is in its vocabulary a mixed speech, like our own, but its 
 essential structure is far liker that of the Indo-Iranian languages than that 
 /. of any northern branch of Indo-European speech. For instance, the 
 
 ' ' augment is common and peculiar to Sanskrit, Old Persian, and Greek. 
 
 The Greek language cannot have differed very much from the Persian 
 in the second millennium b.c. The popular distinction between centum 
 ^ and satem languages is wholly misleading and based on a secondary 
 ^y'"'"^^ phenomenon, as is shown by the fact that the Romance languages have 
 become satem languages in historical times. It would be more to the 
 point to note that Greek, like Old Indian and Old Persian, represents the 
 
 .dll 
 
INTRODUCTION 3 
 
 that every one of the men whose work we are about to 
 study was an Ionian, except Empedokles of Akragas, and, 
 this exception is perhaps more apparent than real. Akragas 
 was founded from the Rhodian colony of Gela, its olKL(TTrj%. 
 was himself a Rhodian, and Rhodes, thougH otticially 
 Dorian, had been a centre of the early Aegean civilisation. 
 We may fairly assume that the emigrants belonged mainly 
 to the older population rather than to the new Dorian 
 aristocracy. Pythagoras founded his society in the Achaian 
 city of Kroton, but he himself was an Ionian from 
 Samos. 
 
 This being so, we must be prepared to find that the 
 Greeks of historical times who first tried to understand the 
 world were not at all in the position of men setting out on 
 a hitherto untrodden path. The remains of Aegean art 
 prove that there must have been a tolerably consistent 
 view of the world in existence already, though we cannot 
 hope to recover it in detail till the records are deciphered. 
 I^The ceremony represented on the sarcophagus of Hagia 
 7 Triada implies some quite definite view as to the state of 
 iHhe dead, and we may be sure that the Aegean people were 
 as capable of developing theological speculation as were 
 the Egyptians and Babylonians. We shall expect to find 
 traces of this in later days, and it may be said at once that 
 things Hke the fragments of Pherekydes of Syros are in- 
 expHcable except as survivals of some such speculation. 
 There is no ground for supposing that this was borrowed 
 from Egypt, though no doubt these early civiUsations all 
 influenced one another. The Egyptians may have borrowed 
 from Crete as readily as the Cretans from Egypt, and there 
 was a seed of Ufe in the sea civiUsation which was somehow 
 lacking in that of the great rivers. 
 
 On the other hand, it is clear that the northern invaders 
 must have assisted the free development of the Greek 
 
 sonant n in the word for "hundred" {eKaT6v=satam, satem) by a, and to 
 classify it with them as a satem language on that ground. 
 
4 • EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 genius by breaking up the powerful monarchies of earlier 
 days and, above all, by checking the growth of a super- 
 stition Uke that which ultimately stifled Egypt and Babylon. 
 That there was once a real danger of this is suggested by 
 certain features in the Aegean remains. On the other hand, 
 the worship of Apollo seems to have been brought from 
 the North by the Achaians,^ and indeed what has been called 
 the Olympian reUgion was, so far as we can see, derived 
 mainly from that source. Still, the artistic form it assumed 
 bears the stamp of the Mediterranean peoples, and it was 
 chiefly in that form it appealed to them. It could not 
 become oppressive to them as the old Aegean rehgion 
 might very possibly have done. It was probably due to 
 the Achaians that the Greeks never had a priestly class, 
 and that may well have had something to do with the rise 
 of free science among them. 
 
 HI. We see the working of these influences clearly in 
 Homer. Though he doubtless belonged to the older race 
 himself and used its language, ^ it is for the courts of Achaian 
 princes he sings, and the gods and heroes he celebrates are 
 mostly Achaian. 3 That is why we find so few traces of the 
 traditional view of the world in the epic. The gods have 
 become frankly human, and everything primitive is kept 
 out of sight. There are, of course, vestiges of the early 
 
 ^ See Farnell, CuUs of the Greek States, vol. iv. pp. 98 sqq. 
 
 ^ This is surely a simpler hypothesis than that of Sir Arthur Evans, 
 who postulates (loc. cit. p. 288) " an earlier Minoan epic taken over into 
 Greek." The epic dialect has most points of contact with Arcadian 
 and Cypriote, and it is wholly improbable that the Arcadians came 
 from the North. There are sufficient parallels for the prowess of the 
 conqueror being celebrated by a bard of the conquered race (Ridgeway, 
 Early Age of Greece, vol. i. p. 664). Does this explain the name "0/j.r]pos, 
 " hostage " ? 
 
 3 Professor Ridgeway {Early Age of Greece, i. p. 674) points out that the 
 specifically Achaian names, such as Achilles, Odysseus, Aiakos, Aias, Laertes 
 and Peleus, cannot be explained from the Greek language, while the 
 names of the older race, such as Herakles, Erichthonios, Erysichthon, etc., 
 can. No doubt Agamemnon and Menelaos have Greek names, but that 
 is because Atreus owed his kingship to the marriage of Pelops with a 
 princess of the older race. It is an instance of the process of assimilation 
 which was going on everywhere. 
 
INTRODUCTION 5 ^ 
 
 beliefs and practices, but they are exceptional.^ It has i 
 
 often been noted that Homer never speaks of the primitive ] 
 
 custom of purification for homicide. The dead heroes are ^ 1 
 
 '/burned, not buried, as the kings of the older race were. \ 
 
 I Ghosts play hardly any part. In the Iliad we have, to be \ 
 
 i|sure, the ghost of Patroklos, in close connexion with the j 
 
 'solitary instance of human sacrifice in Homer. There is I 
 
 Jalso the Nekyia in the Eleventh Book of the Odyssey.^ ; 
 
 ISuch things, however, are rare, and we may fairly infer that, ; 
 
 at least in a certain society, that of the Achaian princes for i 
 
 whom Homer sang, the traditional view of the world was ; 
 
 already discredited at a comparatively early date,^ though j 
 
 it naturally emerges here and there. \ 
 IV. When we come to Hesiod, we seem to be in another 2. Hesiod. - 
 
 world. We hear stories of the gods which are not only \ 
 
 irrational but repulsive, and these are told quite seriously. : 
 Hesiod makes the Muses say : " We know how to tell many 
 false things that are Uke the truth ; but we know too, when 
 we will, to utter what is true." * This means that he was 
 
 conscious of the difference between the Homeric spirit and j 
 
 his own. The old light-heartedness isgone, and it is \ 
 
 important to tell the truth about tEe^ds.^ Hesiod knows, ] 
 
 too, that he belongs to a later and a sadder time than 1 
 
 Homer. In describing the Ages of the World, he inserts a \ 
 
 fifth age between those of Bronze and Iron. That is the ^ 
 Age of the Heroes, the age Homer sang of. It was better 
 
 than the Bronze Age which came before it, and far better ; 
 
 than that which followed it, the Age of Iron, in which Hesiod j 
 
 * There are traces of cosmogonical ideas in the Ai6s airdTtj (II. xiv.). 1 
 
 2 Od. xi. has been referred to a late date because it is supposed to i 
 contain Orphic ideas. In the light of our present knowledge, such a ! 
 hypothesis is quite unnecessary. The ideas in question are primitive, i 
 and were probably generally accepted in the Aegean. Orphicism was i 
 essentially a revival of primitive beliefs. 
 
 3 On all this, see especially Rohde, Psyche^, i. pp. 37 sqq. (=Ps.^ I 
 T?P-3i sqq.). ; 
 
 * Hes. Theog. 27 (the words are borrowed from Od. xix. 203). The !■< 
 Muses are the same as those who inspired Homer, which means that Hesiod 1 
 wrote in hexameters and used the Epic dialect. X 
 
 i 
 
6 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 lives. ^ He also feels that he is singing for another class. 
 It is to shepherds and husbandmen of the older race he 
 addresses himself, and the Achaian princes for whom Home: 
 sang have become remote persons who give " crooke 
 dooms.'* The romance and splendour of the Achaia 
 Middle Ages meant nothing to the common people. The' 
 primitive view of the world had never really died out among; 
 them ; so it was natural for their first spokesman to assume ' 
 it in his poems. That is why we find in Hesiod these olc 
 savage tales, which Homer disdained. 
 
 Yet it would be wrong to see in the Theogony a mere' 
 \ revival of the old superstition. Hesiod could not help being 
 affected by the new spirit, and he became a pioneer in spite}, 
 of himself. The rudiments of what grew into Ionic science 
 and histor v are to be found in his poems, and he really did 
 more than any one to hasten that decay of the old ideas 
 which he was seeking to arrest.. The Theogony is an attempt 
 to reduce all the stories about the gods into a single system* 
 and system is fatal to so wayward a thing as mythology. 
 Moreover, though the spirit in which Hesiod treats his theme 
 is that of the older race, the gods of whom he sings are for 
 the most part those of the Achaians. This introduces an 
 element of contradiction into the system from first to last- 
 Herodotos tells us that it was Homer and Hesiod who made 
 a theogony for the Hellenes, who gave the gods their names, 
 and distributed among them their ofiices and arts,^ and it 
 is perfectly true. The Olympian pantheon took the place 
 of the older gods in men's minds, and this was quite as 
 much the doing of Hesiod as of Homer. The ordinary man 
 would hardly recognise his gods in the humanised figures, 
 detached from all local associations, which poetry had 
 substituted for the older objects of worship. Such gods 
 were incapable of satisfying the needs of the people, and 
 
 1 There is great historical insight here. It was Hesiod, not our 
 i modern historians, who first pointed out that the " Greek Middle Ages " 
 / were a break in the normal development. 
 / 2 Herod, ii. 53. 
 
gony. 
 
 INTRODUCTION 7 
 
 that is the secret of the rehgious revival we shall have to 
 consider later. 
 
 K V. Nor is it only in this way that Hesiod shows himself Cosmo- 
 ^ child of his time. His Theogony is at the same time a 
 tosmogony, though it would seem that here he was following 
 the older tradition rather than working out a thought of his 
 own. At any rate, he only mentions the two great cosmo- 
 gonical figures, Chaos and Eros, and does not really bring 
 them into connexion with his system. They seem to belong, 
 in fact, to an older stratum of speculation. The conception 
 of Chaos represents a distinct effort to picture the beginning 
 of things. It is not a formless mixture, but rather, as its 
 etymology indicates, the yawning gulf or gap where nothing 
 is as yet.^ We may be sure that this is not primitive. 
 Primitive man does not feel called on to form an idea of 
 the very beginning of all things ; he takes for granted that 
 there was something to begin with. The other figure, that 
 of Eros, was doubtless intended to explain the impulse to 
 production which gave rise to the whole process. These are 
 clearly speculative ideas, but in Hesiod they are blurred and 
 confused. 
 
 We have records of great activity in the production of 
 cosmogonies during the whole of the sixth century B.C., 
 and we know something of the systems of Epimenides, 
 jPhergli^ides^l^d Akousilaos. If there were speculations ol 
 this kind eveno^^e" Hesiod, we need have no hesitation 
 in beheving that the earHest Orphic cosmogony goes back 
 to that century too.^ The feature common to all these 
 systems is the attempt to get behind the Gap, and to put 
 Kronos or Zeus in the first place. That is what Aristotle 
 has in view when he distinguishes the " theologians " from 
 
 ^ The word x«ios certainly means the " gape " or " yawn," the x^<^f^ 
 ireXdbpLov of the Rhapsodic Theogony (fr. 52). Grimm compared it with 
 the Scandinavian Ginnunga-Gap. 
 
 2 For the remains of Pherekydes, see Diels, Vorsokratiker, 71 b, and 
 the interesting account in Gomperz, Greek Thinkers, vol. i. pp. 85 sqq. 
 
 3 This was the view of Lobeck with regard to the so-called " Rhapsodic 
 Theogony " described by Damaskios. 
 
EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 those who were half theologians and half philosophers, and 
 
 who put what was best in the beginning.^ It is obvious, 
 
 owever, that this process is the very reverse of scientific, 
 
 and might be carried on indefinitely ; so we have nothing 
 
 to do with the cosmogonists in our present inquiry, except 
 
 so far as they can be shown to have influenced the course of 
 
 more sober investigations. 
 
 General VI. The louiaus, as we can see from their literature, 
 
 rstks^of^^' ^^^^ deeply impressed by the transitoriness of things.* 
 
 Greek cos-. There is, in fact, a fundamental pessimism in their outlook 
 
 mology. 
 
 on Hfe, such as is natural to an over-civilised age with 
 no very definite religious convictions. We find Mimnermos 
 of Kolophon preoccupied with the sadness of the owning 
 of old age, while at a later date the lament of Simonides, 
 
 .that the generations of men fall like the leaves of the forest, 
 touches a chord that Homer had already struck. ^ Now 
 this sentiment always finds its best illustrations in the 
 changes of the seasons, and the cycle of growth and decay 
 is a far more striking phenomenon in Aegean lands than in* 
 the North, and takes still more clearly the form of a war' 
 of opposites, hot and cold, wet and dry. It is, accordingly, 
 from that point of view the early cosmologists regard the 
 world. The opposition of day and night, summer and 
 
 ./winter, with their suggestive parallelism in sleep and 
 waking, birth and death, are the outstanding features of 
 the world as they saw it.^ 
 
 The changes of the seasons are plainly brought about: 
 by the encroachments of one pair of opposites, the cold and 
 the wet, on the other pair, the hot and the dry, which in 
 
 1 Arist. Met. N, 4. 1091 b 8. 
 
 2 See Butcher, " The Melancholy of the Greeks/' in Some Aspects of 
 the Greek Genius, pp. 130 sqq. 
 
 3 This is well brought out by Prof. J. L. Myres in a paper entitled 
 " The Background of Greek Science " (University of Chicago Chronicle, 
 vol. xvi. No. 4). There is no need to derive the doctrine of the " opposites " 
 from a " reUgious representation " as Mr. Cornford does in the first chapter 
 of From Religion to Philosophy. In Greece these force themselves upon 
 our attention quite apart from anything of the sort. Of course they are 
 also important in agrarian magic for practical reasons. 
 
 I 
 
INTRODUCTION 9 
 
 their turn encroach on the other pair. This process was 
 naturally described in terms borrowed from human society ; 
 for in early days the regularity and constancy of human 
 life was far more clearly reaHsed than the uniformity of 
 nature. Man lived in a charmed circle of social law and 
 custom, but the world around him at first seemed lawless. 
 That is why the encroachment of one opposite on another 
 was spoken of as injustice {aSLKLo} and the due observ- 
 ance of a balance between them as justice (BUtj). The 
 later word Koo-fMo^ is based on this notion too. It meant 
 originally the discipline of an army, and next the ordered 
 constitution of a state. 
 
 That, however, was not enough. The earhest cosmo- 
 logists could find no satisfaction in the view of the world - 
 as a perpetual contest between opposites. They felt that 
 these must somehow have a common ground, from which 
 they had issued and to which they must return once more. 
 They were in search of something more primary than the 
 opposites, something which persisted through all change^:.^ 
 and ceased to exist in one form only to reappear in another. ' 
 That this was really the spirit in which they entered on their 
 quest is shown by the fact that they spoke of this something ' 
 as " ageless '* and " deathless." ^ If, as is sometimes held, 
 their real interest had been in the process of growth and 
 becoming, they would hardly have applied epithets so 
 charged with poetical emotion and association to what is 
 alone permanent in a world of change and decay. That 
 is the true meaning of Ionian " Monism." ^ 
 
 ♦^ Ar. Phys. T, 4. 203 b 14 addvarov yap Kal dvuikedpov (sc. t6 &Trei.pov), ws 
 <f>tl<Ti.v 'Ava^ifiafSpos Kal ol TrXeicrToi tuv <pva-L6\6yu}v, Hipp, Ref. i. 6, I (p^aiv 
 Tiva ToO direipov . . . rathrju S' diSiov elvai Kal dyqpw. The epithets come from 
 the Epic, where dddvaTos Kal dy-fiptas is a standing phrase to mark the 
 difference between gods and men, 
 
 2 As it has been suggested that the Monism ascribed by later writers 
 to the early cosmologists is only based on Aristotle's distinction between 
 those who postulated one dpxv s-^d those who postulated more than one 
 {Phys. A, 2. 184 b 15 sqq.), and -is not therefore strictly historical, it will 
 be well to quote a pre-Aristotehan testimony for it. In the Hippokratean 
 Uepl (pijatoi dvOpwirov (Littre, vi. 32) we read 0a(rf re yap iv tl elvai 6Ti'JaTi, 
 
10 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 4>{,<Tii. vn. Now, Ionian science was introduced into Athens 
 
 by Anaxagoras about the time Euripides was born, and 
 there are sufficient traces of its influence on him.^ It is, 
 therefore, significant that, in a fragment which portrays 
 the blessedness of a hfe devoted to scientific research 
 (lo-Topia),^ he uses the very epithets " ageless and deathless " 
 which Anaximander had applied to the one primary sub- 
 stance, and that he associates them with the term <f)vo-i,<;. 
 The passage is so important for our present purpose that 
 I quote it in full : 
 
 oA/3tOS OCTTtS T^S ICTTOpiaS 
 
 €ar\€. ixdOr)(riv, fii^Te ttoAitwv 
 €7rt 7rr]fiocrvva<s firjT els dStKOVs 
 rrpa^eis opjxiov, 
 
 dX)C dOavoLTOv KaOopdv ^vcrews 
 Koa-piov dyyjpo), rts re (rvvearriq 
 
 KoX OTTY) Koi OTTCDS* 
 
 TOIS TOLOvrOfS OvSeTTOT alcT^piiiV 
 
 epyctiv fxeXeTrjfxa it poa-t^ei.^ 
 
 \ 
 
 This fragment is clear evidence that, in the fifth century B.C., 
 the name ^vai^ was given to the e verlasting som ething of 
 which the world was made. That is quite in accordance 
 with the history of the word, so far as we can make it out. 
 Its original meaning appears to be the " stuff " of which 
 
 Kal rovT elvai t6 iu Kal rb irav, Kara 5k to. 6v6fj.aTa ovk 6/xoXoyeovai ' X^^ei 5' aiiTuu 
 6 fih Tis <t>6.aK03v aipa eluai tovto rb iy Kal rb Trap, 6 8k ttO/?, 6 dk f/5a)/), 6 5^ yrjv, Kal 
 iiri\4yei ^Kacrros t^ eojvrov Xdycf) fiapr^^pid re Kal re/c/xij/aia, & ye iariv oi54v. 
 
 1 See below, § 123. 
 
 ^ Cf. Plato, Phaedo, 96 a 7 rairrj^ ttjs crocpias ^v drj KaXovcri irepl 0iJ(rcwj 
 laroplav. This is the oldest and most trustworthy statement as to the 
 name originally given to science. I lay no stress on the fact that the 
 books of the early cosmologists are generally quoted under the title Uepl 
 (puaeoos, as such titles are probably of later date. 
 
 3 Eur. fr. inc. 910. The word k6<t/jlos here means, of course, " order- 
 ing," " arrangement," and dyripw is genitive. The object of research is 
 firstly what is " the ordering of immortal ageless (pvais," and secondly, how 
 it arose. Anaxagoras, who introduced Ionian science to Athens, had 
 belonged to the school of Anaximenes (§ 122). We know from Aristotle 
 {loc. cit. p. 9 n. i) that not only Anaximander, but most of the (pvaio\6yoi, 
 applied epithets like this to the Boundless. 
 
INTRODUCTION ii 
 
 anything is made, a meaning which easily passes into that 
 of its " make-up," its general character or constitution. 
 Those early cosmologists who were seeking for an " undying 
 and ageless " something, would naturally express the idea 
 by sa5dng there was " one (pvat^ " ^ of all things. When 
 that was given up, under the influence of Eleatic criticism, 
 the old word was still used. Empedokles held there were 
 four such primitive stuffs, each with a (pvcrt^ of its own, 
 while the Atomists beUeved in an infinite number, to which 
 they also appHed the term.^ / 
 
 The term ap'^rj, which is often used in our authorities, is 
 in this sense ^ purely Aristotelian. It is very natural that 
 it should have been adopted by Theophrastos and later 
 writers ; for they all start from the well-known passage 
 of the Physics in which Aristotle classifies his predecessors 
 according as they postulated one or more apyai!^ But Plato 
 never uses the term in this connexion, and it does not occur 
 once in the genuine fragments of the early philosophers, 
 which would be very strange on the assumption that they 
 employed it. 
 
 Now, if this is so, we can understand at once why the 
 lonians called science Ilept (^uo-6a)9jaT2^2i2?.----We shall see 
 
 1 Arist. Phys. A, 6. 189 b 2 ol fiLav rtva <f>vaiv elvai X^yovres rd irdv, oloy 
 v8o)p 1} irvp ij t6 fiera^ij to&twv, B, I. 193 a 21 ol fi^u irvp, ol dk yfjv, ol 5' aipa 
 (paalv, ol 8^ vSwp, ol 8' ^utaTodruv (Parmenides), ol 8^ TrcLvra raOra (Empedokles) 
 TTjv (pvaiv chat ttjv twu 6vto}v. 
 
 2 For the history of the term 0i;<rts, see Appendix I. 
 
 3 Professor W. A. Heidel has shown that the cosmologists might have 
 used apxn in a sense different from Aristotle's, that, namely, of " source," 
 " store," or " collective mass," from which particular things are derived 
 {Class. Phil. vii. pp. 217 sqq.). I should be quite wilUng to accept this 
 account of the matter if I could find any evidence that they used the 
 term at all. It is only in the case of Anaximander that there is even a 
 semblance of such evidence, and I believe that to be illusory (p. 54, «. 2). 
 Moreover, Diels has shown that the first book of Theophrastos's great 
 work dealt with the apx-q ^'^ ^^^ Aristotelian sense, and it is very unlikely 
 that the word should have been used in one sense of Anaximander and 
 in another of the rest. 
 
 * Phys. A, 2. 184 b 15 sqq. It is of great importance to remember 
 that Theophrastos and his followers simply adopted the classification of 
 this chapter, which has no claim to be regarded as historical. 
 
12 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 that the growing thought which may be traced through the 
 successive representatives of any school is always that 
 
 . which concerns the primary substance/ whereas the astro- 
 nomical and other theories are, in the main, peculiar to the 
 individual thinkers. The chief interest of all is the quest 
 
 i for what is abiding in the flux of things.^ 
 
 "^ Vni. According to Aristotle and his followers, the early 
 cosmologists beUeved also in an " eternal motion ** (aLBLo<; 
 Kiv7]ai<;), but that is probably their own way of putting the 
 thing. It is not at all likely that the lonians said anything 
 about the eternity of motion in their writings. In early 
 times, it is not movement but rest that has to be accounted 
 for, and it is unUkely that the origin of motion was discussed 
 till its possibiHty had been denied. As we shall see, that 
 was done by Parmenides ; and accordingly his successors, 
 accepting the fact of motion, were bound to show how it 
 originated. I understand Aristotle's statement, then, as 
 meaning no more than that the early thinkers did not feel 
 
 •the need of assigning an origin for motion. The eternity of 
 motion is an inference, which is substantially correct, but 
 is misleading in so far as it suggests deliberate rejection of 
 a doctrine not yet formulated.^ 
 
 1 I am conscious of the unsatisfactory character of the phrase 
 " primary substance " {irpCJTov vwoKelfiepov), but it is hard to find a better. 
 The German Urstojf is less misleading in its associations, but the English 
 " stuff " is not very satisfactory. 
 
 2 The view of O. Gilbert {Die meteorologischen Theorien des griechischen 
 Altertums, Leipzig, 1907) that the early cosmologists started from the 
 traditional and popular theory of " the four elements " derives all its 
 plausibihty from the ambiguity of the term " element." If we only mean 
 the great aggregates of Fire, Air, Water and Earth, there is no doubt 
 that these were distinguished from an early date. But that is not what 
 is meant by an " element " {aroix^lov) in cosmology, where it is always an 
 irreducible something with a (piatt of its own. The remarkable thing 
 really is that the early cosmologists went behind the theory of " elements " 
 in the popular sense, and it was only the accident that Empedokles, the 
 first to maintain a plurality of elements, selected the four that have 
 become traditional that has led to the loose use of the word " element " 
 for the great aggregates referred to. 
 
 3 This way of thinking is often called Hylozoism, but that is still more 
 misleading. No doubt the early cosmologists said things about the 
 world and the primary substance ,which, from our point of view, imply 
 
INTRODUCTION 13 
 
 A more important question is the nature of this motion. 
 It is clear that it must have existed before the beginning 
 of the world, since it is what brought the world into being. 
 It cannot, therefore, be identified with the diurnal revolu- 
 tion of the heavens, as it has been by many writers, or 
 with any other purely mundane motion.^ The Pythagorean 
 doctrine, as expounded in Plato's Timaeus,^ is that the 
 original motion was irregular and disorderly, and we shall 
 see reason for beheving that the Atomists ascribed a motion 
 of that kind to the atoms. It is safer, then, not to attribute 
 any regular or well-defined motion to the primary substance 
 of the early cosmologists at this stage. ^ 
 
 IX. In all this, there is no trace of theological speculation. The 
 We have seen that there had been a complete break with cha'rl^ter 
 the early Aegean religion, and that the Olympian poly- of. Ionian 
 
 SC 16I1C6 • 
 
 theism never had a firm hold on the Ionian mind. It is 
 therefore quite wrong to look for the origins of Ionian_. 
 science in mythological ideas of any kind. No doubt there 
 were many vestiges of the older beliefs and. practices in 
 
 that they are alive ; but that is a very different thing from ascribing 
 a " plastic power " to " matter." The concept of " matter " did not 
 yet exist, and the underlying assumption is simply that everything, 
 life included, can be explained mechanically, as we say, that is, by 
 body in motion. Even that is not stated explicitly, but taken for 
 granted. 
 
 1 It was Aristotle who first took the fateful step of identifying the 
 " eternal motion " with the diurnal revolution of the heavens. 
 
 2 Plato, Tim. 30 a. 
 
 3 As I understand him. Prof. W. A. Heidel regards the " eternal 
 motion " as a rotary or vortex motion {8lv7]), on the ground that it is 
 hazardous to assume that an early thinker, such as Anaximenes, " dis- 
 tinguished between the primordial motion of the infinite Air and the 
 original motion in the cosmos " (see his article, " The dipr) in Anaximenes 
 and Anaximander," Classical Philology, i. p. 279). It seems to me, on 
 the other hand, that any one who held the world had come into being 
 must have made such a distinction, especially if he also held the doctrine 
 of innumerable worlds. As will be seen later, I adopt Prof. Heidel's 
 view that the " original motion of the cosmos " was a rotary one in the 
 earhest cosmological systems, but it was certainly not " eternal," and I 
 do not think we can infer anything from it as to the pre-mundane motion, 
 except that it must have been of such a nature that it could give rise to 
 the Slyrj. 
 
14 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 those parts of Greece which had not come under the rule 
 of the Northerners, and we shall see presently how they 
 reasserted themselves in the Orphic and other mysteries, 
 but the case of Ionia was different. It was only after the 
 coming of the Achaians that the Greeks were able to estabhsh 
 their settlements on the coast of Asia Minor, which had 
 been closed to them by the Hittites,^^ and there was no 
 traditional background there at all. In the islands of the 
 Aegean it was otherwise, but Ionia proper was a country 
 j without a past. That explains the secular character of the 
 earliest Ionian philosophy. 
 
 We must not be misled by the use of the word ^eo9.in 
 the remains that have come down to us. It is quite true 
 that the lonians appHed it to the " primary substance " 
 and to the world or worlds, but that means no more and no 
 less than the use of the divine epithets " ageless " and 
 " deathless " to which we have referred already. In its 
 religious sense the word " god " always means first and 
 .foremost an object of worship, but already in Homer that 
 has ceased to be its only signification. Hesiod's Theogony 
 is the best evidence of the change. . It is clear that many 
 of the gods mentioned there were never worshipped by 
 any one, and some of them are mere personifications of 
 natural phenomena, or even of human passions. ^ This 
 non-rehgious use of the word " god " is characteristic of 
 the whole period we are deaUng with, and it is of the first 
 importance to reahse it. No one who does so will fall into 
 the error of deriving science from mythology.^ 
 
 We see this, above all, from the fact that, while primitivj 
 
 1 See Hogarth, Ionia and the East, pp. 68 sqq. 
 
 2 No one worshipped Okeanos and Tethys, or even Ouranos, and si 
 less can Phobos and Deimos be regarded as gods in the reUgious sense. 
 
 3 This is, I venture to think, the fundamental error of Mr. Cornford's 
 interesting book. From Religion to Philosophy (19 12). He fails to reaUse 
 how completely the old " collective representations " had lost their hold 
 in Ionia. We shall see that his method is more appHcable when he comes 
 to deal with the western regions, but even there he does not recogi 
 sufficiently the contrast between Ionian science and the old tradition. 
 
INTRODUCTION 15 
 
 religion regards the heavenly bodies and the heavens 
 themselves as divine, and therefore •of a wholly different ' 
 nature from anything on this earth, the lonians from the 
 very first set their faces against any such distinction, though 
 it must have been perfectly familiar to them from popular 
 beliefs. Aristotle revived the distinction at a later date, 
 but Greek science began by rejecting it.^ 
 
 X. We have also to face the question of the nature and Alleged 
 extent of the influence exercised by what we call Eastern orTgin of 
 wisdom on the Greek mind. It is a common idea even p^^1°" 
 
 sopny. 
 
 now that the Greeks in some way derived their philosophy 
 from Egypt and Babylon, and we must therefore try to 
 understand as clearly as possible what such a statement 
 really means. To begin with, we must observe that the 
 question wears a very different aspect now that we know 
 the great antiquity of the Aegean civilisation. Much that 
 has been regarded as Oriental may just as well be native. 
 As for later influences, we must insist that no writer of the 
 period during which Greek philosophy flourished knows 
 anything of its having come from the East. Herodotos 
 would not have omitted to say so, had he heard of it ; for it 
 would have confirmed his own beUef in the Egyptian origin 
 of Greek rehgion and civilisation. 2 Plato, who had a great 
 respect for the Egyptians on other grounds, classes them as 
 a business-like rather than a philosophical people.^ Aristotle 
 speaks only of the origin of mathematics in Egypt* (a point 
 
 1 The importance of this point can hardly be exaggerated. See 
 Prof. A. E. Taylor, Aristotle, p. 58. 
 
 2 All he can say is that the worship of Dionysos and the doctrine of 
 transmigration came from Egypt (ii. 49, 123). We shall see that both these 
 statements are incorrect, and in any case they do not imply anything 
 directly as to philosophy. 
 
 3 In Rep, 435 e, after saying that t6 dv/ioeid^s is characteristic of the 
 Thracians and Scythians, and t6 (piKofiad^s of the Hellenes, he refers us to 
 Phoenicia and Egypt for to tpCKoxp'ntJ-a.TQv. In the Laws he says (747 b 6) 
 that arithmetical studies are valuable only if we remove all dveXevdepla 
 and (piXoxpvi^o^Tia from the souls of the learners. Otherwise, we produce 
 iravovpyia instead of aocpia, as we can see that the Phoenicians, the Egyptians, 
 and many other peoples do. 
 
 * Arist. Met. A, i. 981 b 23. 
 
i 
 
 ( 
 
 i6 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 to which we shall return), though, if he had known of an 
 Egyptian philosophy,- it would have suited his argument 
 better to mention that. It is not till later, when Egyptian 
 priests and Alexandrian Jews began to vie with one another 
 in discovering the source? of Greek philosophy in their 
 own past, that we have definite statements to the effect 
 that it came from Phoenicia or Egypt. But the so-called 
 Egyptian philosophy was only arrived at by a process of 
 turning primitive myths into allegories. ' We are still able 
 to judge Philo's Old Testament interpretation for ourselves, 
 
 (and we may be sure that the Egyptian allegorists were even 
 more arbitrary ; for they had far less promising material 
 to work on. The myth of Isis and Osiris, for instance, is first 
 interpreted according to the ideas of later Greek philosophy, 
 and /hen declared to be the source of that philosophy. 
 V,/1rhis method of interpretation culminated with the 
 Neopythagorean Noumenios, from whom it passed to the 
 ^^^jQiristian Apologists. It is Noumenios who asks, " What is 
 /plato but Moses speaking Attic ? " ^ Clement and Eusebios 
 ' give the remark a still wider appHcation.^ At the Renais- 
 sance, this farrago was revived along with everything else, 
 and certain ideas derived from the Praeparatio Evangelica 
 continued for long to colour accepted views. ^ Cudworth 
 speaks of the ancient " Moschical or Mosaical philosophy '* 
 taught by Thales and Pythagoras.* It is important to 
 realise the true origin of this prejudice against the originahty 
 of the Greeks. It does not come from modern researches 
 
 1 Noumenios, fr. 13 (R. P. 624), Tf ydp iari UXdrup ij Mcovarjs arriKL^wv ; 
 
 2 Clement {Strom, i. p. 8, 5, Stahlin) calls Plato 6 i^ 'EjBpaicov <pL\6(ro<pos. 
 
 3 Exaggerated notions of Oriental wisdom were popularised by the 
 Encyclopedie, which accounts for their diffusion and persistence. Bailly 
 (Lettres sur I'origine des sciences) assumed that the Orientals had received 
 fragments of highly advanced science from a people which had disappeared, 
 but which he identified with the inhabitants of Plato's Atlantis ! 
 
 * We learn from Strabo (xvi. p. 757) that it was Poseidonios who 
 introduced Mochos of Sidon into the history of philosophy. He attributes 
 the atomic theory to him. His identification with Moses, however, is a 
 later tour de force due to Philon of Byblos, who published a translation 
 of an ancient Phoenician history by Sanchuniathon, which was used by 
 Porphyry and afterwards by Eusebios. , 
 
INTRODUCTION 17 
 
 into the beliefs of ancient peoples ; for these have disclosed 
 nothing in the way of evidence for a Phoenician or Eg5^tian 
 philosophy. It is a mere residuum of the Alexandrian 
 passion for allegory. 
 
 Of course no one nowadays would rest the case for 
 the Oriental origin of Greek philosophy on the evidence 
 0/ Clement or Eusebios ; the favourite argument in recent 
 times has been the analogy of the arts. We are seeing more 
 land more, it is said, that the Greeks derived their art from 
 the East ; and it is urged that the same will in all proba- 
 bihty prove true of their philosophy. That is a specious 
 argument, but not at all conclusive. It ignores the difference 
 in the way these things are transmitted from people to 
 people. Material civiHsation and the arts may pass easily 
 from one people to another, though they have not a common 
 language, but philosophy can only be expressed in abstract 
 language, and can only be transmitted by educated men, 
 "whether by means of books or oral teaching. Now we 
 know of no Greek, in the times we are dealing with, who 
 could read an Egyptian book or even listen to the discourse '"'' 
 of an Egyptian priest, and we never hear till a late date of 
 Oriental teachers who wrote or spoke in Greek. The Greek 
 traveller in Egypt would no doubt pick up a few words of 
 Egyptian, and it is taken for granted that the priests could 
 make themselves understood by the Greeks.^ But they 
 must have made use of interpreters, and it is impossible to 
 conceive of philosophical ideas being communicated through 
 an uneducated dragoman. ^ 
 
 But really it is not worth while to ask whether the 
 communication of philosophical ideas was possible or not, 
 till some evidence has been produced that any of these 
 
 1 Herod, ii. 143 (where they boast to Hekataios of their superior 
 antiquity) ; Plato, Tim. 22 b 3 (where they do the same to Solon). 
 
 2 Gomperz's " native bride," who discusses the wisdom of her people 
 with her Greek lord {Greek Thinkers, vol. i. p. 95). <ioes not convince me 
 either. She would probably teach her maids the rites of strange goddesses ; 
 but she would not be hkely to talk theology with her husband, and still 
 less philosophy or science. 
 
 2 
 
i8 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 peoples had a philosophy to communicate. No such 
 evidence has yet been discovered, and, so far as we know, 
 the Indians were the only ancient people besides the Greeks 
 who ever had anything that deserves the name. No one 
 now will suggest that Greek philosophy came from India, 
 and indeed everything points to the conclusion that Indian 
 philosophy arose under Greek influence. The chronology 
 of Sanskrit hterature is an extremely difficult subject ; but, 
 so far as we can see, the great Indian systems are later in 
 date than the Greek philosophies they most nearly resemble. 
 /Of course the mysticism of the Upanishads and of Buddhism 
 / was of native growth ; but, though these influenced philo- 
 V sophy in the strict sense profoundly, they were related to 
 it only as Hesiod and the Orphics were related to Greek 
 scientific thought. 
 Egyptian XL It would, howcver, be another thing to say that 
 
 matics. Greek philosophy originated quite independently of Oriental 
 influences. The Greeks themselves believed their mathe- 
 matical science to be of Egyptian origin, and they must 
 have known something of Babylonian astronomy. It 
 cannot be an accident that philosophy originated just at 
 the time when communication with these two countries 
 was easiest, and that the very man who was said to have 
 introduced geometry froni^ Egypt is also regarded as the first 
 philosopher. It thus~becbrneslinportant for us to discover 
 what Egyptian mathematics meant. We shall see that, 
 even here, the Greeks were really original. 
 
 The Rhind papyrus in the British Museum ^ gives us a 
 glimpse of arithmetic and geometry as they were understood 
 on the banks of the Nile. It is the work of one Aahmes, 
 
 1 I am indebted for most of the information which follows to Cantor's 
 Vorlesungen iiber Geschichte der Mathematik, vol. i. pp. 46-63. See also 
 Gow's Short History of Greek Mathematics, §§ 73-80 ; and Milhaud, La 
 Science grecque, pp. 91 sqq. The discussion in the last-named work is 
 of special value because it is based on M. Rodet's paper in the Bulletin 
 de la SociHe Mathematique, vol. vi., which in some important respects 
 supplements the interpretation of Eisenlohr, on which the earlier accounts 
 depend. 
 
INTRODUCTION 
 
 19 
 
 and contains rules for calculations both of an arithmetical 
 and a geometrical character. The arithmetical problems 
 mostly concern measures of corn and fruit, and deal parti- 
 cularly with such questions as the division of a number of 
 measures among a given number of persons, the number of 
 loaves or jars of beer that certain measures will yield, and 
 the wages due to the workmen for a certain piece of work. 
 It corresponds exactly, in fact, to the description of Egyptian 
 arithmetic Plato gives us in the Laws, where he tells us that 
 children learnt along with their letters to solve problems in 
 the distribution of apples and wreaths to greater or smaller 
 numbers of people, the pairing of boxers and wrestlers, and 
 so forth. ^ This is clearly the origin of the art which the 
 Greeks called X oY^g-T^/cy/ and they probably borrowed that' 
 from Egypt, where it was highly developed ; but there is 
 no trace of what the Greeks called dpLdfirjrtKTj, the scientific 
 study of numbers. 
 
 The geometry of the Rhind papyrus is of a similar 
 character, and Herodotos, who tells us that Egyptian 
 geometry arose fronPthe necessity of measuring the land 
 afresh after^iheJmmdatiefit&r'is clearly far nearer the mark 
 than Aristotle, who says it grew out of the leisure enjoyed 
 by the priestly caste. ^ The rules given for calculating areas 
 are only exact when these are rectangular. As fields are 
 usually more or less rectangular, this would be sufficient for 
 practical purposes. It is even assumed that a right-angled 
 triangle can be equilateral. The rule for finding what is 
 called the seqt of a pyramid is, however, on a rather higher 
 level, as we should expect. It comes to this. Given the 
 " length across the sole of the foot," that is, the diagonal 
 of the base, and that of the piremus or " ridge," to find a 
 number which represents the ratio between them. This is 
 
 1 Plato, Laws, 81954 fx-fiXojv t4 tlvuv diavofxal Kal aT€<f>dpuv TXeioaiv dfia 
 Kal iXdrrocrtv apixoTT6vTwv dpidfiQp tCjv avrdv, koX itvktCov Kal iraKaKjTQiv iipeSpelai 
 re Kal avWrj^ecoi iv fjApei Kal i<pe^ris Kal cos 7re0i5/ca(n yiyveadai. Kal 8r] Kal 
 iraLi^ovres, (pidXas d/xa xP^<^ou Kal x<^^i(o^ f<*^ dpy^pov Kal TOLoiriav rcvQy dXXwv 
 Kepavvivre^, ol bk Kal 6\as ttws 8ia8L86vT€S. 
 
 2 Herod, ii. 109 ; Arist. Met. A, i. 981 b 23. 
 
 X 
 
20 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 done by dividing half the diagonal of the base by the 
 " ridge/' and it is obvious that such a method might quite 
 well be discovered empirically. It seems an anachronism 
 to speak of elementary trigonometry in connexion with 
 a rule Hke this, and there is nothing to suggest that the 
 Egyptians went any further.^ That the Greeks learnt as 
 much from them is highly probable, though we shall see 
 also that, from the very first, they generahsed it so as to 
 make it of use in measuring the distances of inaccessible 
 objects, such as ships at sea. It was probably this generali- 
 sation that suggested the idea of a science of geometry, 
 which was really the creation of the Pythagoreans, and we 
 can see how far the Greeks soon surpassed their teachers 
 from a remark attributed to Demokritos. It runs (fr. 299) : 
 " I have listened to many learned men, but no one has yet 
 surpassed me in the construction of figures out of Hues 
 accompanied by demonstration, not even the Egyptian arpe- 
 donapts, as they call them." ^ Now the word apTreSovdTrrrjf; 
 is not Egyptian but Greek. It means " cord-fastener," ^ 
 and it is a striking coincidence that the oldest Indian 
 geometrical treatise is called the ^ulvasutras or " rules of 
 the cord." These things point to the use of the triangle 
 of which the sides are as 3, 4, 5, and which has always a 
 right angle. We know that this was used from an early 
 date among the Chinese and the Hindus, who doubtless got 
 it from Babylon, and we shall see that Thales probably 
 learnt the use of it in Egypt.* There is no reason for 
 
 ^ For a fuller account of this method see Gow, Short History of Greek 
 Mathematics, pp. 127 sqq. ; and Milhaud, Science grecque, p. 99. 
 
 2 R. P. 188. It should be stated that Diels now considers this frag- 
 ment spurious {Vors.^ ii. p. 124). He regards it, in fact, as from an 
 Alexandrian forgery intended to show the derivative character of Greek 
 science, while insisting on its superiority. However that may be, the 
 word dpiredovdiTTai is no doubt a real one, and the inference drawn from 
 it in the text is justified. 
 
 * The real meaning of dpireSovdTrTTjs was first pointed out by Cantor. 
 The gardener laying out a flower-bed is the true modern representative of 
 the " arpedonapts." 
 
 * See Milhaud, Science grecque, p. 103. 
 
INTRODUCTION 21 
 
 supposing that any of these peoples had troubled themselves 
 to give a theoretical demonstration of its properties, though 
 Demokritos would certainly have been able to do so. As 
 we shall see, however, there is no real evidence that Thales 
 had any mathematical knowledge which went beyond the 
 Rhind papyrus, and we must conclude that mathematics 
 in the strict sense arose in Greece after his time. It is 
 significant in this connexion that all mathematical terms 
 are purely Greek in their origin.^ 
 
 XII. The other source from which the lonians were Baby- 
 supposed to have derived their science is Babylonian astro- 
 astronomy. It is certain, of course, that the Babylonians '^^'^^'• 
 had observed the heavens from an early date. They had 
 planned out the fixed stars, and especially those of the 
 zodiac, in constellations. ^ That is useful for purposes of 
 observational astronomy, but in itself it belongs rather to 
 mythology or folklore. They had distinguished and named 
 the planets and noted their apparent motions. They were 
 well aware of their stations and retrograde movements, i 
 and they were famiUar with the solstices and equinoxes. / 
 
 1 Cf. e.g. kvkXos, Kij\iv8pos. Very often these terms are derived from 
 the names of tools, e.g. yptb/xuv, which is the carpenter's square, and rofxe^s, 
 " sector," which is a cobbler's knife. The word irvpafiis is sometimes 
 supposed to be an exception and has been derived from the term piremus 
 used in the Rhind papyrus, which, however, does not mean " pyramid " 
 (p. 19) ; but it too is Greek. Uupafxb (or wvpa/xovs) means a " wheat- 
 cake," and is formed from irvpoL on the analogy of a-rja-a/xis (or a-rjaa/xoOs). 
 The Greeks had a tendency to give jocular names to things Egyptian. I 
 Cf. KpoKdSeiXos, o^eXla-Kos, (Trpovdds, KarapaKTrj^ (lit. "sluice"). We seem to 
 hear an echo of the slang of the mercenaries who cut their names on the 
 colossus at Abu-Simbel. 
 
 2 That is not quite the same thing as dividing the zodiac into twelve 
 signs of 30° each. There is no evidence of this before the sixth century 
 B.C. It is also to be noted that, while a certain number of names for 
 constellations appear to have reached the Greeks from Babylon, most of 
 them are derived from Greek mythology, and from its oldest stratum, 
 which became localised in Crete, Arkadia, and Boiotia. That points to 
 the conclusion that the constellations were already named in " Minoan " 
 times. The disproportionate space occupied by Andromeda and her 
 relatives points to the time when Crete and PhiHstia were in close contact. 
 There is a clue here which has been obscured by the theory of " astral 
 mythology." 
 
22 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 They had also noted the occurrence of eclipses with a view 
 to predicting their return for purposes of divination. But 
 we must not exaggerate the antiquity or accuracy of these 
 observations. It was long before the Babylonians had a 
 satisfactory calendar, and they kept the year right only by 
 intercalating a thirteenth month when it seemed desirable. 
 That made a trustworthy chronology impossible, and 
 
 V therefore there were not and could not be any data avail- 
 able for astronomical purposes before the so-called era of 
 
 \Nabonassar (747 B.C.). The oldest astronomical document 
 of ~a really scientific character which had come to Hght up 
 to 1907 is dated 523 B.C., in the reign of Kambyses, when 
 Pythagoras had already founded his school at Kroton. 
 Moreover, the golden age of Babylonian observational 
 astronomy is now assigned to the period after Alexander the 
 Great, when Babylon was a Hellenistic city. Even then, 
 though great accuracy of observation was attained, and 
 data were accumulated which were of service to the Alexan- 
 drian astronomers, there is no evidence that Babylonian 
 astronomy had passed beyond the empirical stage.^ 
 
 We shall see that Thales probably knew the cycle by 
 means of which the Babylonians tried to predict ecUpses 
 (§ 3) ; but it would be a mistake to suppose that the pioneers 
 of Greek science had any detailed knowledge of Babylonian 
 
 * All this has been placed beyond doubt by the researches of Father 
 Kugler {Siernkunde und Sterndienst in Babel, 1907), There is a most in- 
 teresting account and discussion of his results by Schiaparelli in Scientia, 
 vol. iii. pp. 213 sqq., and vol. iv. pp. 24 sqq., the last work of the great 
 astronomer. These discussions were not available when I published my 
 second edition, and I made some quite unnecessary concessions as to 
 Babylonian astronomy there. In particular, I was led by some remarks 
 of Ginzel {Klio, i. p. 205) to admit that the Babylonians might have 
 observed the precession of the equinoxes, but this is practically impossible 
 in the light of our present knowledge. There is a good note on the 
 subject in Schiaparelli 's second article [Scientia, iv. p. 34). The chief 
 reason why the Babylonians could have no records of astronomical records 
 from an early date is that they had no method of keeping the lunar and 
 the solar year together, nor was there any control such as is furnished by 
 the Egyptian Sothis period. Neither the o/craerT/pts or the eweaKaLdeKaTrjpi^ 
 was known to them till the close of the sixth century b.c. They are 
 purely Greek inventions. 
 
INTRODUCTION 23 
 
 observations. The Babylonian names of the planets do 
 not occur earUer than the writings of Plato's old age.^ We 
 shall find, indeed, that the earliest cosmologists paid no ; 
 attention to the planets, and it is hard to say what they 
 thought about the fixed stars. That, in itself, shows that 
 they started for themselves, and were quite independent • 
 of Babylonian observations, and the recorded observations 
 were only made fully available in Alexandrian times. ^ But, 
 even if the lonians had known them, their originaUty would 
 . remain. The Babylonians recorded celestial phenomena 
 KioT astrological purposes, not from any scientific interest. 
 There is no evidence that they attempted to account for 
 what they saw in any but the crudest way. The Greeks, 
 on the other hand, made at least three discoveries of capital / 
 importance in the course of two or three generations. In 
 the first place, they discovered, that the earth is a sphere 
 and does not rest on anything.^ In the second place, they 
 discovered the true theory of lunar and solar ecUpses ; 
 and, in close connexion with that, they came to see, in 
 the third place, that the earth is not the centre of our \ 
 system, but revolves round the centre Hke the planets.,^ 
 Not much later, certain Greeks took, at least tentatively, 
 the final step of identifying the centre round which the 
 earth and planets revolve with the sun. These dis- 
 coveries will be discussed in their proper place ; they are 
 only mentioned here to show the gulf between Greek 
 astronomy and everything that had preceded it. On the 
 
 1 In classical Greek literature, no planets but "Eo-Trepos and 'Eoxr^Apos are 
 mentioned by name at all. Parmenides (or Pythagoras) first identified ^ 
 these as a single planet (§ 94). Mercury appears for the first time by 
 name in Tim. 38 e, and the other divine names are given in Epin. 987 b sq., 
 where they are said to be " Syrian." The Greek names ^aipuy, ^a^dwv, 
 Uvpoeis, ^u}a-(p6pos, I:,tI\^u}u, are no doubt older, though they do not happen 
 to occur earlier. 
 
 2 The earhest reference to them is in Plato's Epinomis, 987 a. They 
 are also referred to by Aristotle, De caelo, B, 12. 292 a 8. 
 
 3 The view of Berger [Erdkunde, pp. 171 sqq.) that the sphericity of the 
 earth was known in Egypt and Babylon is flatly contradicted by all the 
 evidence known to me. 
 
24 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 other hand, the Greeks rejected astrology, and it was not till 
 the third century B.C. that it was introduced among them.^ 
 We may sum up all this by saying that the Greeks did 
 not borrow either their philosophy or their science from the 
 East. They did, however, get from Egypt certain rules 
 of mensuration which, when generalised, gave birth to geo- 
 metry ; while from Babylon they learnt that the phenomena 
 of the heavens recur in cycles. This piece of knowledge 
 doubtless had a great deal to do with the rise of science ; 
 for to the Greek it suggested further questions such as 
 no Babylonian ever dreamt of.^ 
 The XI n. It is necessary to insist on the scientific character 
 
 character of the phUoSOphx^ W^^^^ SCen 
 
 LJw^ that the Eastern peoples were considerably richer than the 
 
 Greek COS- Qrccks in armrrm]afprl i^rU thoUgh these factS had UOt 
 mology. -~--.:-*'v».>,.w,..,.v, ,..vjfc,..«<p;srr7Ti77r^ y,.«^,v . .. ^>.j, ..■,.. .^.„ 
 
 been observed for any scientific purpose, and never suggested 
 a revision of the primitive view of the world. The Greeks, 
 however, saw in theni someCMrig tfia!' bMlc!^ turned to 
 account, and they were never as a people slow to act on 
 the maxim, Chacun prend son hien partout ou il le trouve. I 
 The visit of Solon to Croesus which Herodotos describes, 
 however unhistonc^^^^ be, gives us a good idea of tins J 
 
 ^ The earliest reference to astrology among the Greeks appears to be 
 Plato, Tim. 40 c 9 (of conjunctions, oppositions, occultations, etc.), 
 (f)6^ovs Kai arjfieia tG)v ixera ravra yevri<To^ivu:v roh ov dvva/x^uoLS Xoyi^eadai 
 Tri/MTTovaiv. That is quite general, but Theophrastos was more definite. 
 Cf. the commentary of Proclus on the passage : dav/xaa-noTdTriv elvai (prja-iv iv 
 TOLS KUT avrbv xP^f'OLS ttjv tQv XaXSaiuv dewplav rd re dXXa irpoKeyovcav Kal roi>s 
 /Stoi's €Kd<TT(ov /cat Toi)s davdrovs Kal ov rd KOLvd fibvov. The Stoics, and especially 
 Poseidonios, were responsible for the introduction of astrology into Greece, 
 and it has recently been shown that the fully developed system known 
 in later days was based on the Stoic doctrine of elfiapjuivri. See the verj 
 important article by Boll in Neue Jahrb. xxi. (1908), p. 108. 
 
 2 The Platonic account of this matter is to be found in the Epinomisi 
 986 e 9 sqq., and is summed \fjp by the words Xd/Sw/iey 8k ws drnrep fti 
 "EWrjves ^ap^dpcov irapaXd^ucn, KdWiou tovto ei's tAos direpyd^ovrai (987 d 9) 
 The point is well put by Theon (Adrastos), Exp. p; 177, 20 Hiller, whc 
 speaks of the Chaldaeans and Egyptians as Avev <pv(noKoyia$ dreXe^s troio^fieva 
 rcLs fxedodovs, diov dfia Kal (pvcriKCis irepl toIjtup eincKoiTetv ' birep ol vapd rot 
 "EXXrjaiv daTpoXoyifi(ravT€S eireipQvTO Troietv, rds irapd rovnav Xa^dvres dpxds Kal rwi 
 <f)aLvo/j,hiav TTjprja-ets. This gives the view taken at Alexandria, where th| 
 facts were accurately known. 
 
 I 
 
INTRODUCTION 25 
 
 spirit. Croesus tells Solon that he has heard much of " his 
 wisdom and his wanderings," and how, from love of know- 
 ledge {(fnXocrocpecov) , he has travelled over much land for 
 the purpose of seeing what was to be se^n {Oecopiri^ eXveKev), 
 The words Oeaypiij, <f>LXo(To<^i7] , and l<TToplrj are, in fact, the 
 catchwords of the time, though they had, no doubt, a 
 somewhat differ.ent meaning from that they were afterwards 
 made to bear at Athens.^ The idea that underHes them all 
 may, perhaps, be rendered in EngHsh by the wor4 Curiosity ; 
 and it was just this great gift of curiosity, and the desire to f 
 see all the wonderful things — pyramids, inundations, and I 
 so forth — that were to be seen, which enabled the lonians 
 to pick up and turn to their own use such scraps of know-/ 
 ledge as they could come by among the barbarians. No 
 sooner did an Ionian philosopher learn half-a-dozen geo- 
 metrical propositions, and hear that the phenomena of the 
 heavens recur in cycles, than he set to work to look for 
 law everywhere in nature, and, with an audacity almost 
 
 We may smile at the medley of childish fancy and 
 scientific insight which these efforts display, and. sometimes 
 w|i*feel disposed to sympathise with the sages of the day 
 who warned their more daring contemporaries " to think 
 the thoughts befitting man's estate " (avOpcoinva (j^povelv). 
 But we shall do well to remember that even now it is just 
 such hg.rdy anticipations of experience that make scientific * 
 progress possible, and that nearly every one of these early ^ 
 inquirers made some permanent addition to positive know- 
 ledge, besides opening up new views of the world in every 
 direction. 
 
 There is no justification either for the idea that Greek 
 science was bjiilt up by more or less lucky guesswork, \ 
 instead of by observation and experiment. The nature \ 
 
 1 still, the word Oeiopia never lost its early associations, and the Greeks 
 alway^ felt that the dewpriTiKdi ^lot i meant literally " the life of the 
 spectator." ' Its special use and the ^ whole theory of the " three lives " 
 seem to be Pythagorean. (See § 45.) 
 
 t 
 
26 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 of^our tradition, which mostly consists of Placita — that is, 
 ot.Vi{b^l.3Y^ c,^lLl!uXg§Jil,ts 
 
 impression. We are seldom told why any early philosopher 
 
 held the views he did, and_j:Ji9,,,.appej.ranpe^q^^^ 
 
 of **jop inions " suggests dogmatism. There are, however, 
 
 certain exce*ptioffi''t'o''fe'^enTra!' character of the tradition ; 
 
 and we may reasonably suppose that, if the later Greeks 
 
 had been interested in the matter, there would have been 
 
 many more. We shall see that Anaximander made some 
 
 rgtnarkable^discoveries in marine biology, which the re- 
 
 /feearch^'on^e^mn^^^^ (§ 22), 
 
 / and even XenQDhanes supported one of his theories by 
 
 i referring to the fossils and petrifactions of such widely 
 
 . separated places as MalSrKro"^'ana'§yftgi!f^1^ This 
 
 is enough to show that the theory, so commonly Tield by 
 
 the earlier philosophers, that the earth had been originally 
 
 in a moist state, was not purely mythological in origin, but 
 
 based on biological and palaeontological observations^^. It 
 
 would surely be absurd to imagine that the men who could 
 
 make these observations had not the curiosity or the ability 
 
 ^ . io make many others of which the memory is lost.'V Indeed, 
 
 ; .the idea that th^ observers is ludicrously 
 
 i sciij£^^|^;^}iicjti bears witness to trained habits of observa- 
 
 ^'tion, while the Hippokrategin corpus contains models of 
 
 I scientific observation at its bestT* 'We know, then, that the 
 
 j Greeks could observe well, and we know that they were 
 
 curious about the world. Is it conceivable that they did not 
 
 use their powers of observation to gratify that curiosity ? 
 
 It is true that they had not our instruments of precision ; 
 
 but a great deal can be discovered by the help of very simple 
 
 apparatus. It is not to be supposed that Anaximander 
 
 erected his gnomon merely that the Spartans might know 
 
 the seasons.^ 
 
 ^ As we saw, the word yudjfxuiv properly me9,ns a carpenter's square 
 (p. 21, n. i), and we learn from Proclus {in End. I. p. 283, 7) that Oinopides 
 of Chios used it in the sense of a perpendicular {KaSeTo^). The instrument 
 
INTRODUCTION 27 
 
 Nor is it true that the Greeks made no use of experiment/^ 
 The rise of the experimental method dates from the time 1 
 when the medical schools began to influence the develop- \ 
 ment of philosophy, and accordingly we find that the first 
 recorded experiment of a modern type is that of Empedokles 
 ^i\h.thit»hki^y([^^^ ^^ have his own account of this (fr. ibo), 
 and we can see how it brought him to the verge of anticipating 
 Harvey and TorricelU. It is inconceivable that an inquisitive 
 people should have applied the experimental method in a 
 single case without extending it to other problems. 
 
 Of course the great difficulty for us is the geocentric • 
 hypothesis from which science inevitably started, though 
 only to outgrow it in a surprisingly short time. So long as 
 the earth is supposed to be in the centre of the world, 
 meteorology, in the later sense of the word, is necessarily 
 identified with astronomy. It is difficult for us to feel ^t 
 home in this point of view, and indeed we have no suitable 
 word to express what the Greeks at first called an ovpavo^. 
 It will be convenient to use the term " world " for it ; but 
 then we must remember that it does not refer solely, or 
 even chiefly, to the earth, though it includes that along 
 with the heavenly bodies. 
 
 The science of the sixth century was mainly concerned, 
 therefore, with those parts of the world that are " aloft **_# 
 (ra jjLeriaypa), and these include such things as clouds, rain- 
 bows, and lightning, as well as the heavenly bodies.^^ That 
 is how the latter came sometimes to be explained^^f^gnited 
 
 so called was simply an upright erected on a flat surface, and its chief 
 use was to indicate the solstices and the equinoxes by means of its shadow. 
 It was not a sundial ; for it afforded no means of dividing the day into 
 equal hours, though the time of day would be approximately inferred 
 from the length of the shadow cast by it. For the geometrical use of 
 the term, see below, p. 103, «. i. 
 
 ^ The restricted sense of /xereajpoKoyia only arose when Aristotle intro- 
 duced for the first time the fateful distinction between the ovpav6s and 
 the " sublunary " region, to which it was now confined. In so far as 
 they make no such distinction, the early cosmologists were more scientific 
 than Aristotle. Their views admitted of correction and development ; 
 Aristotle's theory arrested the growth of science. 
 
28 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 clouds, an idea which seems astonishing to us.^ But even 
 that is bgy.g^^Jtjia|>^.j^;Miiegar4v4he sun, moon, and stars as 
 having a different nature from the earth, ahd*%c1ence* in- 
 evitably and rightly began with the most obvious hypothesis, 
 and it was only the thorough working out of this that could 
 show its inadequacy. It is just because the Greeks were 
 
 /the first people to take the geocentric hypothesis seriously 
 
 I that they were able to go beyond it. Of course the pioneers 
 
 of Greek thought had no clear idea of the nature of scientific 
 
 .hypothesis, and supposed themselves to be deahng with 
 ultimate reaUty, but a sure instinct guided them to the right 
 method, and we can see how it was the effort to " save _ 
 appearances " ^ that really operated from the first. It is 
 to those men we owe the conception of an exact science which 
 
 .^should ultimately take in the whole world as its object. 
 
 They fancied they could work out this science at once. We 
 
 sometimes make the same mistake nowadays, and forget 
 
 fthat all scientific progress consists in the advance from a 
 
 ^ 1 less to a more adequate hypothesis. The Greeks were the 
 
 first to follow this method, and that is their title to be 
 
 Lxegarded as the originators of science. 
 
 / XIV. Theophrastps^,the,first writer to treat the history 
 
 bi Greek philosophy in a systematLc wav^^ reprg^Sfewecrthe 
 
 •early cosmologists as standing to one another m the relation 
 
 lof master and schpla^and a Jmembej;§^of regular societiegu,^ 
 This has been regarded as an anachronism, and some have 
 even denied the existence of " schools " of philosophy 
 altogether. But the statements of Theophrastos on such a 
 subject are not to be lightly set aside. As this point is of 
 
 1 It is well, however, to remember that Galileo himself regarded comets • 
 as meteorological pheaomena. 
 
 2 This phrase originated in the school of Plato. The method o£i 
 research in use there was for the leader to " propound " {TrpoTeiveivA 
 TTpoBdWead.^.it as a " problem " (ir^SB^^imeX. to find the simplest' ^"BypU- j 
 thes'is**' (TLvojyJnroTedtvTuv) on whicnit is possible to account for and doj 
 justice to anthe o^if^Pt^ facts i^^^l^^^gjA^^^^^"-) • ^^- Milton, Paradise\ 
 Lost, viii. 8i, " how build, unbuild7con^^7'g'*pPtf^ve appearances." 
 
 3 See Note^^on Sources, § 7. 
 
INTRODUCTION 29 
 
 great importance, it will be necessary to elucidate it before 
 we^enter on our story. 
 
 C"*^'"^ In almost every department of life, the corporation at 
 first is everything and the individual nothing. The peoples 
 of the East hardly got beyond this stage ; their science, 
 sucS^s^fnsTlfs'an^^^u^^^l!^^^^ property of a caste 
 
 or guild, and we still see clearly in some cases that it was 
 once the same among the Greeks. % Medicine, for instance, 
 
 / W^s^s^th^^p^^^^ 
 
 distinguished ,tJie,^G^^e^^^^ - 
 
 \ earty'Sate these crafts came^under, ^e,,inflvien^^ 
 V^'StS^fiffing'^inffvi&ais, who gave them a fresH direction and 
 \^ new impulse. But this does not destroy the corporate 
 character of the craft ; it rather intensifies it. The guild 
 becomes what we call a " school,'* and the discipl^^^Jsss^^v^^ - ^ 
 the place of., the c^pprentiQe.. ^Tnat is a vital change. A 
 close gmld with none but olficial heads is essentially conser- 
 vative, while a band of disciples attached to a master they 
 revere is the greatest progressive force the world know^ 
 
 It is certain that the later Athenian schools were legally 
 recognised corporations,|the^^9^^^^^ 
 
 maintained its existence as such for somefc nine hundred 
 ^jg^rs,|and the only question we have to deciSe*ts^w^tfief 
 this was an innovation made in the fourth century B.C., or 
 rather the continuance of .an old tradition. Now we have 
 the authority of Plato for speaking of the chief early systems 
 as handed down in schools. He makes Sokrates speak of 
 " the men of Ephesos," the Herakleiteans, as forming a 
 strong body in his own day,^ and the stranger of the Sophist 
 and the Statesman speaks of his school as sl^U in existence at 
 Elea.2 We also hear of I* Anaxagoreans/f.^ and no one, of 
 
 ^ Theaet. 179 e 4, aurots . . . rots xepl tt)v "E^cctoi'. The humorous 
 denial that the Herakleiteans had any disciples (180 b 8, Iloiots fiadrrrais, 
 u)' 8aifM6vL€ ;) implies that this was the normal and recognised relation. 
 
 2 Soph. 242 d 4, t6 . . . Tap ijfjuy 'EXearLKby idvos. Cf. ib. 216 a 3, 
 eraipov 5e tQv dfKpl Ilapfi€vi8r}v Kal Z-qvojva [iralpojp] (where iraipoip is probably- 
 interpolated, but gives the right sense) ; 217 a i, oZ irepl t6v CKeT rdiroy. 
 
 ' Crat. 409 b 6, etirep aX-ndrj ol 'Ava^aySpeioL X^yovaiv. Cf. also the Ai<rcroi 
 
30 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 bourse, can doubt that the [Pythagoreans wem a society. 
 /In fact, there is hardly any school but that of Miletos for 
 
 / which we have not external evidence of the strongest kind ; 
 
 / and even as regards it, we have the significant fact that 
 Theophrastos speaks of philosophers of a later date as 
 having been " associates of the philosophy of Anaximenes." ^ 
 We shall see too in the first chapter that the internal evidence 
 in favour of the existence of a Milesian school is very strong 
 indeed. It is from this point of view, then, that we shall 
 now proceed to consider the nlen who created Greek science. 
 
 \6yoi (Diels, Vors.^ ii. p'.' 343) ri 5^ 'Ava^aySpeioi Kal Ilvdaydpeioi Tjev 
 independent of Plato. 
 1 Cf. Ghap. VI. § 122. 
 
 This is 
 
 t 
 
NOTE ON THE SOURCES 
 ^.—PHILOSOPHERS 
 
 I. It is not very often that Plato allows himself to dwell on piato. 
 the history of philosophy as it was before the rise of ethical 
 and epistemological inquiry ; but when he does, he is always 
 illuminating. His artistic gift and his power of entering 
 into the thoughts of other men enabled him to describe the 
 views of early philosophers in a sympathetic manner, and 
 he never, except in a playful and ironical way, sought to read 
 unthought-of meanings into the words of his predecessors. 
 He has, in fact, a historical sense, which was a rare thing in 
 antiquity. 
 
 The passage of the Phaedo (96 a sqq.) where he describes 
 the state of scientific opinion at Athens in the middle of the 
 fifth century is invaluable for our purposes. 
 
 2. As a rule, Aristotle's statements about early philoso- Aristotle. 
 phers are far less historical than Plato's. He nearly always 
 discusses the facts from the point of view of his own system, 
 and that system, resting as it does on the deification of the 
 apparent diurnal revolution of the heavens, made it very 
 hard for him to appreciate more scientific views. He is 
 convinced that his own philosophy accompUshes what all 
 previous philosophers had aimed at, and their systems are 
 ♦therefore regarded as " Usping " attempts to formulate it 
 (Met. A, 10, 993 a 15). It is also to be noted that Aristotle 
 regards some systems in a much more sympathetic way 
 than others. He is distinctly unfair to the Eleatics, for 
 
 31 
 
32 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 instance, and in general, wherever mathematical considera- 
 tions come into play, he is an untrustworthy guide. 
 
 It is often forgotten that Aristotle derived much of his 
 information from Plato, and we must specially observe that 
 he more than once takes Plato's humorous remarks too 
 hterally. 
 
 stoics. 3. The Stoics, and especially Chrysippos, paid great 
 
 attention to early philosophy, but their way of regarding it 
 was simply an exaggeration of Aristotle's. They did not 
 content themselves with criticising their predecessors from 
 their own point of view ; they seem really to have believed 
 that the early poets and thinkers taught doctrines hardly 
 distinguishable from their own. The word awocKecovv, which 
 Cicero renders by accommodare, was used by Philodemos 
 to denote this method of interpretation,^ which has had 
 serious results upon our tradition, especially in the case of 
 Herakleitos. 
 
 Skeptics. 4. The same remarks apply mutatis mutandis to the 
 
 Skeptics. The interest of such a writer as Sextus Empiricus 
 in early philosophy is mainly to exhibit its contradictions. 
 But what he tells us is often of value ; for he frequently 
 quotes early views as to knowledge and sensation in support 
 of his thesis. 
 
 Neo- 5. Under this head we have chiefly to consider the 
 
 piatomsts. commentators on Aristotle in so far as they are independent 
 of the Theophrastean tradition. Their chief characteristic 
 is what Simplicius calls evyvcofioa-vvrj , that is, a Uberal spirit 
 of interpretation, which makes all early philosophers agree 
 with one another in upholding the doctrine of a Sensible 
 and an Intelligible World. It is, however, to SimpUcius 
 
 ^ Cf. Cic. De nat. ti. i. 15, 41 : " Et haec quidem (Chrysippus) in primqB 
 libro de natura deorum, in secundo autem vult Orphei, Musaei, Hesiodi 
 Homerique fabellas accommodare ad ea quae ipse primo libro de deis 
 immortalibus dixerat, ut etiam veterrimi poetae, qui haec ne suspicati 
 quidem sunt, Stoici fuisse videantur." Cf. Philod. De piet. jr. c. 13, iv Zh 
 Tip bevT^pip rd re els 'Op(p4a Kal Movaalov dvacpepS/Jieva /cat to. irap 'Oix-qpip koI 
 'H<ri65y Kal 'EvpirLdj] /cai Troiijrats dWois, ws /cai KXedvdTji, wcipdraL avvoiKeiovjf rais 
 56|ais avTuv. 
 
 i 
 
NOTE ON THE SOURCES 33 
 
 more than any one else that we owe the preservation of the 
 fragments. He had, of course, the library of the Academy 
 at his disposal, at any rate up to a.d. 529. 
 
 B.— DOXOGRAPHERS 
 
 6. The Doxographi Graeci of Professor Hermann Diels The do^po- 
 (1879) threw an entirely new Ught upon the filiation of the GrLci. 
 later sources ; and we can only estimate justly the value 
 
 of statements derived from these if we bear constantly in 
 mind the results of his investigation. Here it will only be 
 possible to give an outline which may help the reader to 
 find his way in the Doxographi Graeci itself. 
 
 7. By the term doxographers we understand all those The 
 writers who relate the opinions of the Greek philosophers, ofmo*-^^ 
 and who derive their material, directly or indirectly, from the P^^^tos. 
 great work of Theophrastos, '^vacKcbv Bo^mv ct}' (Diog. v. 46). 
 
 Of this work, one considerable chapter, that entitled Uepl 
 aladrjaecov, has been preserved (Dox. pp. 499-527). And 
 Usener, following Brandis, further showed that there were 
 important fragments of it contained in the commentary 
 of Simplicius (sixth cent, a.d.) on the First Book of 
 Aristotle's ^vo-ikt) aKpoaau^ (Usener, Analecta Theophrastea, 
 pp. 25 sqq.). These extracts SimpHcius seems to have 
 borrowed in turn from Alexander of Aphrodisias (c. a.d. 200) ; 
 cf. Dox. p. 112 sqq. We thus possess a very considerable 
 portion of the First Book, which dealt with the ap'^^ai, as 
 well as practically the whole of the last Book. 
 
 From these remains it clearly appears that the method 
 of Theophrastos was to discuss in separate books the leading 
 topics which had engaged the attention of philosophers 
 from Thales to Plato. The chronological order was not 
 observed ; the philosophers were grouped according to the 
 affinity of their doctrine, the differences between those who 
 appeared to agree most closely being carefully noted. The 
 First Book, however, was in some degree exceptional ; for 
 
 3 
 
34 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 in it the order was that of the successive schools, and short 
 historical and chronological notices were inserted. 
 Doxo- 8. A work of this kind was, of course, a godsend to the 
 
 graphers. epitomators and compilers of handbooks, who flourished 
 more and more as the Greek genius declined. These either 
 followed Theophrastos in arranging the subject-matter 
 under heads, or else they broke up his work, and rearranged 
 his statements under the names of the various philosophers 
 to whom they applied. This latter class form_ the jiatural 
 transition between the doxographers proper and the bio- 
 graphers, so I have ventured to distinguish them by the 
 name of biographical doxographers. 
 
 I. Doxographers Proper 
 
 The 9. These are now mainly represented by two works, viz. 
 
 ^^"^* the Placita Philosophorum, included among the writings 
 
 stobaios. ascribed to Plutarch, and the Eclogae Physicae of John 
 Stobaios (c. a.d. 470). The latter originally formed one 
 work with the Florilegium of the same author, and includes 
 a transcript of some epitome substantially identical with the 
 pseudo-Plutarchean Placita. It is, however, demonstrable 
 that neither the Placita nor the doxography of the Eclogae 
 is the original of the other. The latter is usually the fuller 
 of the two, and yet the former must be earher ; for it was 
 used by Athenagoras for his defence of the Christians in 
 A.D. 177 (Dox. p. 4). It was also the source of the notices in 
 Eusebios and Cyril, and of the History of Philosophy ascribed 
 to Galen. From these writers many important corrections 
 of the text have been derived (Dox. pp. 5 sqq.). 
 
 Another writer who made use of the Placita is Achilles 
 (not Achilles Tatius). For his ElaaycoyT] to the Phaenomena 
 of Aratos see Maass, Commentariorum in Aratum reliquiae, 
 pp. 25-75. His date is uncertain, but probably he belongs 
 to the third century a.d. (Dox. p. 18). 
 
 Actios. 10. What, then, was the common source of the Placita 
 
NOTE ON THE SOURCES 35 
 
 and the Eclogue ? Diels has shown that Theodoret [c. 
 A.D. 445) had access to it ; for in some cases he gives a fuller 
 form of statements made in these two works. Not only 
 so, but he also names that source ; for he refers us [Gr. aff. 
 cur. iv. 31) to 'Aertov rr^v irepl dpea/covTcov (TVvajQyyrjv. Diels 
 has accordingly printed the Placita in parallel columns with 
 the relevant parts of the Eclogae, under the title of Aetii 
 Placita. The quotations from " Plutarch " by later writers, 
 and the extracts of Theodoret from Actios, are also given 
 at the foot of each page. 
 
 11. Diels has shown further, however, that Actios did The 
 
 Vetusta 
 
 not draw directly from Theophrastos, but from an inter- piadta. 
 mediate epitome which he calls the Vetusta Placita, traces 
 of which may be found in Cicero (infra, § 12), and in 
 Censorinus (De die natali), who follows Varro. The Vetusta 
 Placita were composed in the school of Poseidonios, and 
 Diels now calls them the Poseidonian 'ApiaKovra [tJher das 
 phys. System des Straton, p. 2). There are also traces of 
 them in the " Homeric AUegorists." 
 
 It is quite possible, by discounting the somewhat unin- 
 telligent additions which Actios made from Epicurean and 
 other sources, to form a pretty accurate table of the contents 
 of the Vetusta Placita [Box. pp. 181 sqq.), and this gives us 
 a fair idea of the arrangement of the original work by 
 Theophrastos. 
 
 12. So far as what he tells us of the earhest Greek Cicero, 
 philosophy goes, Cicero must be classed with the doxo- 
 graphers, and not with the philosophers ; for he gives us 
 nothing but extracts at second or third hand from the work 
 
 of Theophrastos. Two passages in his writings fall to be 
 considered under this head, namely, " LucuUus " (Acad, ii.), 
 118, and De natura deorum, i. 25-41. 
 
 (a) Doxography of the " LucuUus." — This contains a 
 meagre and inaccurately-rendered summary of the various 
 opinions held by philosophers with regard to the apxv (Dox. 
 pp. 119 sqq,), and would be quite useless if it did not in one 
 
36 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 case enable us to verify the exact words of Theophrastos 
 (Chap. I. p. 50, n. 4). The doxography has come through 
 the hands of Kleitomachos, who succeeded Karneades in 
 the headship of the Academy (129 B.C.). 
 
 (6) Doxography of the " De natura deorum." — A fresh 
 hght was thrown upon this important passage by the dis- 
 covery at Herculaneum of a roll containing fragments of an 
 Epicurean treatise, so like it as to be at once regarded as its 
 original. This treatise was at first ascribed to Phaidros, 
 on the ground of the reference in Epp. ad Att. xiii. 39. 2 ; 
 but the real title, ^Cko^fxov irepl evcrelBeia^, was afterwards 
 restored [Dox. p. 530). Diels, however, has shown [Dox. 
 pp. 122 sqq.) that there is much to be said for the view that 
 Cicero did not copy Philodemos, but that both drew from a 
 common source (no doubt Phaidros, liepl Oecov) which itself 
 went back to a Stoic epitome of Theophrastos. The passage 
 of Cicero and the relevant fragments of Philodemos are 
 edited in parallel columns by Diels (Dox. pp. 531 sqq.). 
 
 II. Biographical Doxographers 
 
 Hippoiytos. 13. Of the " biographical doxographies," the most 
 important is Book I. of the Refutation of all Heresies by 
 Hippoiytos. This had long been known as the Philosophou- 
 mena of Origen ; but the discovery of the remaining books, 
 which were first pubUshed at Oxford in 1854, showed finally 
 that it could not belong to him. It is drawn mainly from 
 some good epitome of Theophrastos, in which the matter 
 was already rearranged under the names of the various 
 philosophers. We must note, however, that the sections 
 deahng with Thales, Pythagoras, Herakleitos, and Empe- 
 dokles come from an inferior source, some merely bio- 
 graphical compendium full of apocryphal anecdotes and 
 doubtful statements. 
 The 14. The fragments of the pseudo-Plutarchean Stromateis, 
 
 stromatets. ^^^^^^ ^y E^sebios in his Praeparatio Ev angelica, come from 
 
 M 
 
NOTE ON THE SOURCES 37 
 
 a source similar to that of the best portions of the Philo- 
 sophoumena. So far as we can judge, they differ chiefly in 
 ({wo points> In the first place, they are mostly taken from 
 the earliest sections of the work, and therefore most of them 
 deal with the primary substance, the heavenly bodies and 
 the earth. In the second place, the language is a much less 
 faithful transcript of the original. 
 
 15. The scrap-book which goes by the name of Diogenes "Diogenes 
 Laertios, or Laertios Diogenes (cf. Usener, Epicurea, pp. i 
 sqq.), contains large fragments of two distinct doxographies. 
 One is of the merely biographical, anecdotic, and apophtheg- 
 matic kind used by Hippolytos in his first four chapters ; 
 the other is of a better class, more Hke the source of Hippo- 
 lytos' remaining chapters. An attempt is made to disguise 
 this " contamination " by referring to the first doxography 
 as a " summary " {Ke^a\aLa)hr)^) account, while the second is 
 called " particular " (eVl fiepov^). 
 
 16. Short doxographical summaries are to be found in Patristic 
 Eusebios (P. E. x., xiv., xv.), Theodoret (Gr, aff. cur. ii. 9-11), ^^phies. 
 Irenaeus (C. haer. ii. 14), Arnobius (Adv. nat. ii. 9), Augustine 
 
 {Civ. Dei, viii. 2). These depend mainly upon the writers of 
 ** Successions," whom we shall have to consider in the next 
 section. 
 
 C— BIOGRAPHERS 
 
 17. The first to write a work entitled Successions of the succes- 
 Philosophers was Sotion (Diog. ii. 12 ; R. P. 4 a), about ^^°''''- 
 200 B.C. The arrangement of his work is explained in 
 Dox. p. 147. It was epitomised by Herakleides Lembos. 
 Other writers of AcaSoxau were Antisthenes, Sosikrates, and 
 Alexander. All these compositions were accompanied by a 
 very meagre doxography, and made interesting by the 
 addition of unauthentic apophthegms and apocryphal 
 anecdotes. 
 
 18. The peripatetic Hermippos of Smyrna, known as Her- 
 KaXKLfidxeio^; (c 200 B.C.), wrote several biographical works °"pp*^^- 
 
38 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 which are frequently quoted. The biographical details are 
 very untrustworthy ; but sometimes bibliographical infor- 
 mation is added, which doubtless rests upon the Il/i/a/ce? of 
 Kallimachos. 
 
 Satyros. 19. Another peripatetic, Satyros, the pupil of Aristarchos, 
 
 wrote {c. 160 B.C.) Lives of Famous Men. The same remarks 
 apply to him as to Hermippos. His work was epitomised 
 by Herakleides Lembos. 
 
 "Diogenes 20. The work which goes by the name of Laertios 
 Diogenes is, in its biographical parts, a mere patchwork of 
 all earlier learning. It has not been digested or composed 
 by any single mind at all, but is little more than a collection 
 of extracts made at haphazard. But, of course, it contains 
 . much that is of the greatest value. 
 
 Z).— CHRONOLOGISTS 
 
 Eratos- 21. The founder of ancient chronology was Eratosthenes 
 
 anT^^ of Kyrene (275-194 B.C.) ; but his work was soon supplanted 
 doros°" ^y ^^^ metrical version of Apollodoros (c. 140 B.C.), from 
 which most of our information as to the dates of early 
 philosophers is derived. See Diels' paper on the XpoviKci of 
 Apollodoros in Rhein. Mus. xxxi. ; and Jacoby, Apollodors 
 Chronik (1902). 
 
 The method adopted is as follows : — If the date of some 
 striking event in a philosopher's life is known, that is taken 
 as his floruit [olkixt)), and he is assumed to have been forty 
 years old at tjjat date. In default of this, some historical 
 era is taken as the floruit. Of these the chief are the eclipse 
 of Thales 586/5 B.C., the taking of Sardeis in 546/5 B.C., the 
 accession of Polykrates in 532/1 B.C., and the foundation of 
 Thourioi in 444/3 B.C. It is usual to attach far too much 
 weight to these combinations, and we can often show that 
 Apollodoros is wrong from our other evidence. His dates 
 can only be accepted as a makeshift, when nothing better 
 is available. 
 
 d 
 
CHAPTER I 
 
 THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 
 
 I. It was at Miletqs^tli^t the earliest school of scientific MUetos 
 cosmology had its home, and it is not, perhaps, without 
 significance that Miletos is iust the place where the con- 
 
 ^ . lesiana.. 
 
 once with the Lydians, whose rulers were bent on extending 
 
 their, dominion to the coast ; but, towards the end of the 
 
 seventh century B.c^.^.the tyrant Thrasyboulos succeeded 
 
 *^^1[naEng terms with King Alyat&^anS^^^lSiance was 
 
 concluded which secured Miletos against molestation for 
 the future. Even half a century later^\yhen , Cipe^j^ 
 
 ^£?.^SHi&i.i.^.^.Si ^^^^^^3^^^^^^^^^P^^^^ made war upon and 
 conquereoEphesos, Miletos was able to maintain the old 
 treaty-relation, and never, strictly speaking, became subject 
 . to the Lydians at all. The ^ l^ ^ j j ^iiaj^ 
 
 N?,SS;ife-^'»^^-^**^ What 
 
 wVs called at a later date Hellenismu .§gems to have been 
 
 traditional in the dynasty of tfe Mermnadai. and Herodotos 
 
 says that all the " sophists " of the time nocked to the court 
 
 of Sardeis.2 The tradition which represents Croesus as 
 
 I v^ 1 Se# Introd. § II. Ephoros said that Old Miletos was colonised from 
 
 I l^ilatps In Crete at an eSiS1S^''9ate than the fortification of the new city 
 
 ty Nel'eus (Strabo, xiv. p. 634), and recent excavation has shown that 
 
 the Aegean civilisation passed here by gradual transition into the early 
 
 Ionic. I The dwellings of the old lonians stand on and among, the debris, 
 
 ^''W*fil6"'*TVI;ycenean " periodi |There is no " gepmg|^j^J!J^te^^ '- 
 
 "i^*^- 
 
 ^•i: 
 
 ^^ilefod. 
 
 :nean " periodi iThere is no " geomgtxur^.lJ!J.nterlude. > 
 
 Mermnades (Paris, 1893). 
 
 39 
 
40 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the *' patron *' of Greek wisdom was fully developed in the 
 I fifth centurj^; and, however unhistorical its details may 
 ^erit**MS¥^clearly have some foundation in fact. Particu- 
 larly noteworthy is " the common tale among the Greeks/* 
 that Thales accompanied Croesus on, his luckless campaign 
 against Pteri|^p.^apparently m the capacity of miutary 
 engineei^^^Herodotos disbelieves the story that h^'Wr^fted 
 
 the course of the Halys, but only because he knew there 
 were bridges there already. It is clear that the lonians 
 were erreat engineers, and that they were employed as such 
 by the eastern kings. ^ 
 
 |It should be added that the., ^Lydian alhance would 
 facifffate iiuef?8SSe'witli^^ and Egypt. Lydia was 
 
 an advanced post of Babyloman 'trnture, and Croesus 
 was on friendly terms with the kings of Egypt and 
 Babylon. ,^^^|i9^9|,,,£|-^^.^^ HeUenic^sym- 
 
 P^.^!^5^^#^-^^?'^^^vnd the Milesians possessed j^/temple 
 of their own at Naukratis,««^ ..««M«««**a^^'A=^'^^ ' 
 
 I. Thales 
 
 Origin. 2. The foundci of the Milesian school, and therefore the 
 
 mn^^^ first man of science, was Tliales ; ^ but all we can really 
 
 DC said to know of him comes from Herodotos, and the Tale 
 
 1 Herod, i. 75. It is important for a right estimate of Ionian science 
 to remember the high development of engineering in these days, Man- 
 drokles of Samos built the bridge over the Bosporos for King Dareios 
 (Herod, iv. 88), and Harpalos of Tenedos bridged the Hellespont for 
 Xerxes when the Egyptians and Phoenicians had failed in the attempt 
 (Diels, Ahh. der Berl. Akad., 1904, p. 8). The tunnel through the hill 
 above Samos described by Herodotos (iii. 60) has been discovered by 
 German excavators. It is about a kilometre long, but the levels are 
 almost accurate. On the whole subject see Diels, " Wissenschaft unc 
 Technik bei den Hellenen " {Neue Jahrb. xxxiii. pp. 3, 4). Here, as ii 
 other things, the lonians carried on " Minoan " traditions. 
 
 2 Simplicius quotes Theophrastos as saying that Thales had raan^ 
 predecessors {Dox. p. 475, 11). This need not trouble us ; for the scholias 
 on ApoUonios Rhodios (ii. 1248) tells us that he made Prometheus tl 
 first philosopher, which is merely an application of Peripatetic literalisi 
 to a phrase of Plato's {Phileb. 16 c 6). Cf. Note on Sources, § 2. 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 41 
 
 of the Seven Wise Men was already in existence when he 
 wrote. He says that Thales was of Phoenician, descmjl^y. 
 a statement which other writers explained by saying he 
 belonged to a noble house descended from Kadmos axidr^^iat 
 Agenor.-^ Herodotos probably mentions the supposed 
 ofesceniof Thales simply because he was beheved to have 
 introduced certain improvements in navigation from 
 Phoenicia. 2 At any rate, his father's name, Examyes, leriofe 
 no si^^onr to the view that he was a Semite. Tt is Karia^^ 
 and the Karians had been almost completely assimilated 
 by the lonians. On the monuments we find Greek 
 and Karian names alternating in the same famihes, while 
 the name Thales is otherwise known as Cretan. There 
 IS therefore no reason to doubt that Thales was of pure 
 Milesian descent, though he probably had Karian blood in 
 his veins. 3 
 
 3. The most remarkable statement Herodotos makes The 
 about Thales is that he foretold the ecHpse oTS^^smTwhich fo^So^d 
 put an end to the war between the Lydians and the Medes.^ by Thaies. 
 Now, he was quite ignorant of the caus^-^f echpses. Anaxi- 
 mander and his successors certainly were so,^ and it is 
 incredible that the explanation should have been given 
 and forgotten so soon. Even supposing Thales had known 
 the cause of echpses, such scraps of elementary geometry 
 
 1 Herod, i. 170 (R. P. 9 d) ; Diog. i. 22 (R. P. 9). This is no doubt 
 connected with the fact mentioned by Herodotos (i. 146) that there were 
 Kadmeians from Boiotia among the original Ionian colonists. Cf. also 
 Strabo, xiv. pp. 633, 636 ; Pausan. vii. 2, 7. These, however, were not 
 Semites. 
 
 2 Diog. i. 23, KaXXi/xaxos 5' avrbv olSev evperriv rrjs dpKTOV rrji fxiKpds Xiyup iP 
 rots 'Idfi^ois ourws — 
 
 Kai T7]s a/Jid^rjs iXiyero arad/j.-riaaa'dac 
 Tovs dareplaKovs, 77 irXiovcn ^olpikcs. 
 
 ' See Diels, " Thales ein Semite ? " {Arch. ii. 165 sqq.), and Immisch, 
 " Zu Thales Abkunft " {ib. p. 515). The name Examyes occurs also in 
 Kolophon (Hermesianax, Leontion, fr. 2, 38 Bgk.), and may be compared 
 with other Karian names such as Cheramyes and Panamyes. 
 
 * Herod, i. 74. 
 
 5 For the theories held by Anaximander and Herakleitos, see infra, 
 §§ 19. 71. 
 
LJ 
 
 (: 
 
 42 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 as he picked up in Egypt would never have enabled him to 
 calculate one. Yet the evidence for the prediction is too 
 strong to be rejected off-hand. The testimony of Herodotos 
 is said to have been confirmed by Xenophan es^ and 
 according to Theophrastos Xenophanes' was'^aoiscipie of 
 ^g^mand^ In any case, he*^Mtt^P*hl*% known scores 
 of people who were able to remember what happened. 
 The prediction of the eclipse is therefore better attested 
 than any other fact about Thales whatsoever. 
 
 Now it is possible to predict echpses of the moon 
 approximately without knowing their true cause, and there 
 is no doubt that the Babylonians actually did so. It is 
 generally stated, furth^^ffiaftHeylMlM^^^^P^ cycle 
 of 223 lunar months, Ivithin which eclipses of the sun and 
 moon recurred at equal mtervals of time.^f This, however, 
 would not have enabled them to predict echpses of the sun 
 ^^^ &&^^^%^J^%P^ ^^^ earth's surface ; for these pheno- 
 mena are not visible at all places where the sun is above the 
 horizon at the time. We do not occupy a position at the 
 centre of the earth, and the geocentric parallax has to be 
 taken into account. It would only, therefore, be possible 
 to tell by means of the cycle that an ecUpse of the sun 
 would be visible somewhere, and that it might be worth 
 while to look out for it, though an observer at a given place 
 
 ^ Diog. i. 23, 5o/cet 5^ Kara rivas irpCoTos daTpoXoyrjaat Kal ijXtaKas e/cXe/^ets 
 Kal TpoTTCLs Trpoenreiv, ibs (pyjcnv 'Etiibriixos iv rrj irepl rOiv dcTpoXoyovfMivojv laTopig., 
 6dev adrbv Kal fi!,€uo(f>(iv7]s Kal 'HpoSoros davfid^ei. The statement that Thales 
 " predicted " solstices as well as eclipses is not so absurd as has been 
 thought. Eudemos may very well have meant that he fixed the dates of 
 ,the solstices and equinoxes more accurately than had been done before. 
 That he would do by observing the length of the shadow cast by an 
 upright {yvibij.(x}p), and we shall see (p. 47) that popular tradition ascribed 
 observations of the kind to him. This interpretation is favoured by 
 another remark of Eudemos, preserved by Derky Hides (ap. Theon. p. 198, 
 17 Hiller), that Thales discovered ttjp /card rds Tpoirds avrov (roO^Xioi') wepioSov, 
 ws ovK ta-r] del av/m^aiuei. In other words, he discovered the inequality of the 
 four seasons which is due to the solar anomaly. 
 
 , 2 It is wrong to call this the Saros with Souidas ; for sar on the 
 monuments always means 602=3600, the number of the Great Year. 
 The period of 223 lunations is, of course, that of the retrograde movement 
 of the nodes. 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 43 
 
 might be disappointed five times out of six. Now, if we 
 may judge from reports by Chaldaean astronomers which 
 have been preserved, this was iust the position of the 
 
 I Babylonians in thet(SSKtn|century b.g. They watched for 
 echpses at the proper dates ; and, if they did not occur, 
 they announced the fact as a good omen.^ To explain 
 what we are told about Thales no more is required. He 
 said there would be an echpse by a certain date ; and 
 luckily it was visible in Asia Minor, and on a striking 
 
 V)ccasion.l 
 
 ''****^**¥fi^ prediction of the echpse does not, then, throw Date of 
 ' any light on the scientific attainments of Thales ; but, if 
 we can fix its date, it will give us an indication of the time 
 at which he lived. Astronomers have calculated that 
 there was an echpse of the sun, probably visible in Asia 
 Minor, on May 28 (O.S.), 585 B.C., while Pliny gives the date 
 of the eSB^o?afgmTl^S!g?m\)l. XLYlll.^^^S^^^^j^^^,.^^^^^^^^^^^^^ 
 This does not exactly tally ; for May 585 belongs to the 
 year 586/5 B.C. It ia^^near enough, however, to justify us in 
 
 ^ See George Smith, Assyrian Discoveries (1875), p. 409. The inscrip- 
 tion which follows was found at Kouyunjik : — 
 " To the king my lord, thy servant Abil-Istar. 
 
 " Concerning the echpse of the moon of, which the king my lord sent 
 to me ; in the cities of Akkad, Borsippa, arid Nipur, observations they 
 made, and then in the city of Akkad, we saw part. . . . The observation 
 was made, and the eclipse took place. 
 
 " And when for the eclipse of the sun we made an observation, the 
 observation was made and it did not take place. That which I saw with 
 my eyes to the king my lord I send." See further R. C. Thomson, Reports 
 of the Magicians and Astrologers of Nineveh and Babylon {1900), 
 
 2 Cf. Schiaparelli, " I primordi dell' Astronomia presso i Babilonesi " 
 {Scieniia, 1908, p. 247). His conclusion is that "the law which regulates 
 the circumstances of the visibihty of solar eclipses is too complex to be 
 discovered by simple observation," and that the Babylonians were not 
 in a position to formulate it. " Such a triumph was reserved to the 
 geometrical genius of the Greeks." 
 
 3 Pliny, N.H. ii. 53, It should be noted that this date is inconsistent 
 with the chronology of Herodotos, but that is vitiated by the assumptioi^ 
 that the fall of the Median kingdom synchronised with the accession of 
 Cyrus to the throne of Persia, If we make the necessary correction, 
 Cyaxares was still reigning in 585 B.C. 
 
44 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 identifying the eclipse as that of Thales,^ and this is 
 confirmed by Apollodoros, who fixed his floruit in the same 
 year. 2 The further statement in Diogenes that, according 
 to Demetrios Phalereus,ij,-Thales ' received the name of 
 
 wisT^'^'irtfie^^M^W^ Athens,|eally refers 
 
 to the Tale of theSev^ Wise Men, as is JSo^^ Dy the words 
 which follow, and is doubtless based on the story of the 
 Delphic tripod ; for the archonship of Damasias is the era 
 of the restoration of thelPythian Gam^^^ 
 
 5. The introduction oFEgyptian geometry into Hellas 
 is ascribed to Thales,* and it is probable that he did visit 
 Egypt i for he had a theory of the inundations of the Nile^L 
 Herodotos ^ gives three explanations of the fact that this 
 alone of all riverl^ rises ig^umm^ falls in winterAbut, 
 
 as his custom is, he does not name tS^S^'^^ESSfs. The 
 first, hAvever, which attributes the rise of the Nile to the 
 EtesianWinds, is ascribed to Thales in the Placita,^ and by 
 
 * The words of Herodotos (i. 74), oSpop irpod^fievos iviavrbv tovtov ev t(^ 
 drj Kal iyhero, mean at first sight that he only said the ecHpse would 
 occur before the end of a certain year, but Diels suggests {Neue Jahrb. 
 xxxiii, p. 2) that ivtavrSs has here its original sense of " summer solstice " 
 (cf. Brugmann, Idg. Forsch. xv. p. 87). In that case Thales would have 
 fixed the date within a month. He may have observed the eclipse of 
 May 18, 603 B.C. in Egypt, and predicted another in eighteen years and 
 some days, not later than the solstice. 
 
 2 For Apollodoros, see Note on Sources, § 21. The dates in our text 
 of Diogenes (i. 37 ; R. P. 8) cannot be reconciled with one another. That 
 given for the death of Thales is probably right ; for it is the year before 
 the fall of Sardeis in 546/5 B.C., which is one of the regular eras of Apollo- 
 doros. It no doubt seemed natural to make Thales die the year before 
 the " ruin of Ionia " which he foresaw. Seventy-eight years before this 
 brings us to 624/3 B.C. for the birth of Thales, and this gives us 585/4 
 B.C. for his fortieth year. That is Pliny's date for the eclipse, and Pliny's 
 dates come from Apollodoros through Nepos. 
 
 3 Diog. i. 22 (R. P. 9), especially the words Kad' 8v kuI ol eTrra ao<pol^ 
 iKK7]d7]<rap. The story of the tripod was told in many versions (cf. Diog.) 
 i. 28-33 ' Vors. i. p. 2, 26 sqq.). It clearly belongs to the Delphian Tale] 
 of the Seven Wise Men, which is already alluded to by Plato {Prot. 
 343 a, b). Now Demetrios.^ 0f'''M%leron dated this in the archonship ofj 
 Damasias at ^ '''"'"'gi?.^ ij;5^ij, ,T^'%^ ^.nd the Marmor Parium dates thel 
 restoration of th^yw''v''aT€^aviTr)s^t Delphoi in the same year, and alsr 
 identifies it with thaTorTJ^I'^as (cf. Jacoby, p. 170, n. 12). 
 
 * Proclus, in Eucl. /. p. 65, Friedlein (from Eudemos). 
 
 5 Herod, ii. 20. « Aet. iv. i. i {Dox. p. 384). 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 45 
 
 many later writers. Now, this comes from a treatise on 
 the Rise of the Nile attributed to Aristotle and known to 
 the Greek commentators, but extant only in a Latin epitome 
 of the thirteenth century.^ In this the first of the theories 
 mentioned bv Herodotos is ascribed to Thales, the second 
 to Euthymenes of Massaha, and the thiroto Anaxagora§^^^ 
 V7f;^lm*m^omfS^'^oeveT wrote the booSf fSlhese ' 
 names ? We think naturally of Hekataios ; and this 
 conjecture is strengthened when wennd that Hekataios 
 mentioned Euthymenes. ^ We may conclude that Thales 
 really was in'"*Egypt ; and, perhaps, that Hekataios, in 
 describing the Nile, took account, as was natural, of his 
 fellow-citizen's views. 
 
 6. As to the nature and extent of the mathematical Thaies 
 knowledge brought back by Thales from Egypt, it must be geometry. 
 pointed out that most writers have seriously misunderstood 
 the character of the tradition.^ In his commentary on the..... 
 First Book of Euchd, Proclus enumeratgL„dn the authority 
 ofmidemos, certam propositions which he says were known 
 
 to T£ales,^%ne of which is that two triangles are ec ^ 
 
 when they have one side and the two adjacent angles equaL, .,. 
 '-'^'^^''^-^'--^--^^--i^^^^ otherwise he could not have 
 
 measured the distances of ships at sea in the way he was 
 said to have done.^ Here we see how all these statements 
 arose. Certain feats in the way of measurement were 
 traditionally ascribed to Thales, and Eudemos assumed] 
 that he must have known all the propositions these impl^ 
 
 1 Dox. pp. 226-229. The Latin epitome will be found in Rose's edition 
 of the Aristotelian fragments. 
 
 2 Hekataios, fr. 278 {F.H.G. i. p. 19). 
 ' See Cantor, Vorlesungen uber Geschichte der Mathematik, vol. i. pp. 
 
 12 sqq. ; Allman, " Greek Geometry from Thales to Euclid " {Hermathena, 
 iii. pp. 164-174). 
 
 * Proclus, in Eucl. pp. 65, 7 ; 157, 10 ; 250, 20 ; 299, i ; 352, 14 
 (Friedlein). Eudemos wrote the first histories of astronomy and mathe- 
 matics, just as Theophrastos wrote the first history of philosophy. 
 
 ^ Proclus, p. 352, 14, ^Odrjfios 8^ iv rats yeuifxerpiKals laropiais ds QaXrju tovto 
 dvdyet, t6 dedip-qtia {Eucl. i. 26)' tt)v yap rdv iv daXdrrTj ttXoluji' diroaTaaLv 5C o5 
 rpoirov (paffiv avrbv deiKuOvai Toimp Trpocrxpw^^-^ <pT}(nv dvayKaiou. 
 
46 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 But this is quite illusory. Both the measurement of the 
 distance of ships at sea, and that of the height of t he nvra- 
 mids, which is also ascribed ,tp,. him/ are easy applkations 
 orire'Vule giWn|bx^^^^^ 
 
 the tradition really points to is that Thales applied this 
 
 empirical rule to practical problems which the Egyptians 
 
 ^ad never faced, and thM' He was'tKus* the originator of 
 
 General methods. jThat is a sufficient title to fame. 
 
 Thales 7. Thalcs appears once more in Herodotos some time 
 
 politician, before the fall of [the Lydian monarchy. | He is said to have 
 
 . , urged the Ionian u^rf^tefo unite in a federal state with its 
 
 [capital at Teos.¥ We shall have occasion to notice more 
 
 ^ than once that the early si:hools of philosophy by no m e gj )^, 
 
 |held aloof fprQpolit^ifg.^|. and there are many things, for 
 
 instance the part played b\f Hekataios in the Ionian revolt 
 
 which suggest that the scientific men of Miletostook up a 
 
 very decided position in the stirring times that followed the 
 
 J' death of Thales. It is this political action which has gained 
 
 the founder of the Milesian school his undisputed place 
 
 among the Seven Wise Men ; and it is owing to his inclusion 
 
 among those worthies that the numerous anecdotes told 
 
 of him in later days attached themselves to his name.* 
 
 Uncertain g. $0 far as we know, Thales wrote nothing, tnd no 
 
 character |^j,.^^j. taffier'^^an^^^g^tc^tie'r^i^no^ j^ a 
 
 '"^^'^°^- ^^i^Mific^J^a^a ^SS^^mr^ he 
 
 1 The oldest version of this story is gifen in Diog. i. 27, 6 5^ ' lepwi'w/Aos 
 KoX iKfi€Tp7]a-ai (prjatv avrbu rds irvpafjiidas, iK tt]S (tklols TrapaTrfpTjaai'Ta ore 7]fjui/ 
 Iffoixe-y^drjs iariv. Gf. Pliny, H. Nat. xxxvi, 82, mensuram aUitudinis earum 
 deprehendere invenit Thales Milesius umbram metiendo qua hora par esse 
 corpori solet. (Hiero|nym(^S^<3.f ^,^li^94^,S was rnnfemporRrj wifh^^j^^.rnnc! ^ 
 This need imply no more than the reflexion 'that me shadow's of all objects 
 will be equal to the objects at the same hour. Plutarch [Conv. sept. sap. 
 147 a) gives a more elaborate method, Ty]v ^aKTrjplav <TT7]aas iirl T(f Trepan ttjs 
 aKias i]v ij irvpafxls iiroiei, yevofiivuiv rfj iira(py ttjs clktTvos dvoiv rpLydovuv, ideL^as 8v 
 ij cTKict irpbs TTjv (xklolv \6yov elx^, ttjv irvpa/Jiida irpbs tt]u ^aKT-qplav ^xona-av. 
 
 2 See Gow, Short History of Greek Mathematics, § 84. 
 ,^ 3 Herod, i. 170 (R. P. 9 d). 
 
 /^ 4 The story of Thales falling into a well (Plato, Theaet. 174 a) is nothing 
 but a fable teaching the uselessness of aocpia ; the anecdote about the 
 "corner" in oil (Ar. Pol. A, 11. 1259 a 6) is intended to inculcate the 
 opposite lesson* 
 
 i 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 47 
 
 N4ǤiSi2lY ^^ engineer^ and ai\Jny,entor.j/ It is obvious, 
 however, tnat' tHe requirements of Milesian enterprise and 
 commerce would necessarily turn his attention to problems 
 which we should call astronomical. He was said, we saw, 
 to have introduced the practice of steering a ship's course 
 by Ursajmngr | ^ and there is a remarKaDTe persistence m 
 the tradition that he tried to do something for the calendar, 
 though the details are not sufficiently well atteste3To"'ffiy 
 a place here.^ No doubt he constructed a lirapaTriiryaaXlike 
 those of much later date which have been discovered at 
 Miletos.* The irapdirrjyfjba was the oldest form of almanac, 
 and gave, for a series of years, the equinoxes anffsoEtices, 
 the phases of the moon, the heliacal risings and settings of 
 certain stars, and also weather predictions.! Even Aristotle ' 
 does not pretend to know how Thales arrivefi at the views he 
 ascribes to him or by what arguments they wera supported. 
 I 'this very reserve, however, makes it hard to doubt that 
 
 f he was correctly informed with regard ^"' t]]i4,|fii4)iMBni*wiii**i^'i" " fc' 
 
 about them he mentions, so we may venture on a conjec- 
 tural restoration of his cosmology. This, of course, must 
 be taken for just what it is worth. 
 
 9. The statements ofj^jistQtJp.,may be reduced to three : The cos- 
 (i^^ Jhe earth floats1)n We'water.^ °^°^°^ °^ 
 
 l^^mm^ 
 
 Thales. 
 
 ^ Cf. Aristophanes, Clouds i8o (after a burlesque description of how 
 Sokrates provided himself with a cloak) tL 5i]t Ueipov rbv QaXiju eavfid^o/j-ep ; 
 Birds 1009 (of Meton's town-planning, HvdpuTros Qa\7js). Plato's way of 
 speaking is remarkable. Cf. Rep. 600 a dW ola drj els tcl ^pya co^ov dvdpbs 
 TToWal iirivoiai Kal evfj-rixafoi et's r^xvas ij rivas &Was Trpd^eis \4yovTaiy &<xirep aS 
 GdXew re iripL tov MiXtjaiov Kal ' Avaxdpaios tov 'Zk^Oov. 
 
 2 See p. 41, n. 2. 
 
 ' If he tried to introduce the year of 360 days and the month of 
 30 days, he may have learnt that in Egypt. 
 
 * For the Milesian TrapainfjyiuiaTa see Rehm, Berl. Sitzungsber., 1893, 
 p. loi sqq., 752 sqq. 
 
 6 Ar. Met. A, 3. 983 b 21 (R. P. 10) ; De caelo, B, 13. 294 a 28 
 (R. P. II). 
 
 6 Met. A, 3. 983 b 21 (R. P. 10). We must translate dpxv here by 
 " material cause," for ttjs Toia^Ttis dpxvs (b 19) means rijs iv ijXrjs etdeL dpxv^ 
 (b 7). The word, then, is used here in a strictly Aristotelian sense. Cf. 
 Introd. p. II, «. 3. 
 
EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 11 things are full of gods. The magnet is alive ; 
 
 The Irsl of tirae sMl-TOfitr mii'g^ in 
 
 the Hght of the second, which is expressed in Aristotelian 
 terminology, but would undoubtedly mean that Thales 
 had said water was the stuff of which all other things were 
 transient forms. We have seen that this was the great 
 question of the day. 
 Water. ^0- Aristotlc and Theophrastos| followed by SimgUckj^ 
 
 ^d the doxographers,i5Suggest several explanations of this 
 doctrine. Aristotle gives them as conjectures ; it is only 
 later writers that repeat them as if they were quite certain.^ 
 The most probable view seems to be that Aristotle ascribed 
 to Thales the arguments used at a later date by Hipppn of 
 Sambs^ in support of a similar thesis.^ That would account 
 for' iheir physiological character. The rise of sci ent.i£ c 
 medicine had made biological arguments popular in the 
 'fifth ''ceiiluryt butT in the d^ys of Thales, tHe "prevailing 
 interest was not physiological, but meteorological, and it is 
 from this point of view we must try^TOf^tiffSefstand the 
 theory. 
 
 Now it is not hard to see how meteorological considera- 
 
 1 Arist. De an. A, 5. 411 a 7 (R. P. 13) ; ib. 2. 405 a 19 (R. P. 13 a). 
 Diog. i. 24 (R. P. ib.) adds amber. 
 
 a Met. A, 3. 983 b 22 ; Aet. i. 3, i ; Simpl. Pkys. p. 36, 10 (R. P. 10, 
 12, 12 a). The last of Aristotle's explanations, that Thales was influenced 
 by cosmogonical theories about Okeanos and Tethys, has strangely been 
 supposed to be more historical than the rest, whereas it is merely a fancy 
 of Plato's taken literally, Plato says {Theaet. 180 d 2 ; Crat. 402 b 4) 
 that Herakleitos and his predecessors (ot p^ovres) derived their philosophy 
 from Homer (11. xiv. 201), and even earlier sources (Orph. frag. 2, Diels, 
 Vors. 66 B 2). In quoting this suggestion, Aristotle refers it to " some " 
 — a word which often means Plato — and he calls the originators of the 
 theory -n-aiinraXaiovs, as Plato had done {Met. A, 3. 983 b 28 ; cf. Theaet. 
 181 b 3). This is how Aristotle gets history out of Plato. See Note on 
 Sources, § 2. 
 
 3 Compare Arist. De an. A, 2. 405 b 2 (R. P. 220) with the passages 
 referred to in the last note. We now know that, though Aristotle declines 
 to consider Hippon as a philosopher {Met. A, 3. 984 a 3 ; R. P. 219 a), 
 he was discussed in the Peripatetic history of medicine known as Menon's 
 latrika. See § 185. 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 49 
 
 tions may have led Thales to adopt the view he did. Of all„^, 
 
 sh|^R;^.vv. It is famihar to us in a soUd, a liquid, and a 
 vaporous form, and so Thales may well have thought he 
 saw the world-process from water and back to water again 
 eoine on before his eyes. The phenomenon of evaporation 
 naturally suggests that the fire of the heavenly bodies is 
 k^t^tifr b^rtM itiotStm lAiey draw fern the ^^ Even at 
 the present day people speak of " the sun drawing water.** 
 Water comes down again in rain; and lastty,''sd' tlie" early 
 cosmologists thought, it turns to earth. This may have 
 seemed natural enough to men familiar with the river of 
 Egypt which had formed the Delta, and the torrents of 
 
 ■ At 
 
 tfef?^{raS7the(Gulfof'Latmospr^^^^ 
 to stand, is filled up. Lastly, ^they thought, earth turns 
 once more to water — an idea derived from the observation 
 of dew, night-mists, and subterranean springs. ]| For these 
 last were not in early times supposed to have anything to 
 do -with the rain. The ** waters under the earth " were 
 regarded as an independent source of moisture. ^^*"**^ 
 
 II. The third of the statements mentioned above is Theology, 
 supposed by Aristotle to imply that Thales believed in a 
 " soul of the worldJnvthough he is careful f 6 lA'afktMs^^^^^ 
 no more tnah an inference. ^ The doctrine of the world-soul 
 is then attributed quite positively to Thales by A ctios, v^ho 
 gives it in the Stoic phraseology which he found in his 
 immediate source, and identifies the world-intellect with 
 God.^ Cicero found a similar statement in'^tKe'TEpiciifean 
 manual which he followed, but he goes a step further. 
 Ehminating the Stoic pantheism, he turns the world- 
 intellect into a Platonic demiourgos, and says that Thales 
 
 1 The view here taken most resembles that of the " Homeric allegorist " 
 Herakleitos (R. P. 12 a). That, however, is also a conjecture, probably 
 of Stoic, as the others are of Peripatetic, origin. 
 
 * Arist. De an. A, 5. 411 a 7 (R. P. 13). 
 
 » Aet. i. 7, ii=Stob. i. 56 (R. P. 14). On the sources here referred 
 to, see Note on Sources, §§ 11, 12. 
 
 4 
 
50 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 I held there was a.^ivip^m^d, which formed, all thine-s out 
 mys[00^: All this is denved from Aristotle's cautious state- 
 
 ^ -"ment, and can have no greater authority than its source. 
 We need not enter, then, on the old controversy whether 
 Thales was an atheist or not. If we may judge from his 
 successors, he may very possibly have called water a "_god '' ; 
 but that would not imply any definite rehgtgttS '!yt di l!!f f! ^ - - 
 
 Nor must we make too much of the sa3dng that " all 
 things are full of gods.'^'| It is not safe to regard an apo- 
 phthegm as evidence, a'iid the chances are that it belongs to 
 Thales as one of the Seven Wise Men, rather than as founder 
 of the Milesian school. Further, such sayings are, as a rule, 
 anonymous to begin with, and are attributed now to one 
 sage and now to another.^ pn the other hand, it is probable 
 that Thales did say the magneV'^id^ffimrlfaff '^^J'' That 
 is no apophthegm, but more on the level of the statement 
 that the earth floats on the water. It is just the sort of 
 
 i thing we should expect Hekataios to record about Thales. I 
 It would be wrong, however, to draw any inference fromTt 
 as to his view of the world ; for to say the magnet and amber * 
 are aHve is to imply, if anything, that other things are not. / 
 
 / 
 
 II. Anaximander 
 
 Life. tz. Anaximander, son^of Praxiades^jA^as also a citizen 
 
 of Mnetos, and Theophrastos described him as an ** asso- 
 ciate of Thales.^ We have seen how that expression is to 
 be understood (§ XIV.). 
 
 1 Cicero, De nat. d. i. 25 (R. P. 13 b). On Cicero's soijrce, see Dox. 
 pp. 125, 128. The Herculanean papyrus of Philodemos is defective at 
 this point, but it is not likely that he anticipated Cicero's mistake. 
 
 2 See Introd. § IX. 
 
 3 Plato refers to the saying iravra wXripTj deCjv in Laws, 899 b 9 (R. P. 
 14 b), without mentioning Thales. That ascribed to. Herakleitos in the 
 De part. an. A, 5. 645 a 7 seems to be a mere variation on it. In any 
 case it means only that nothing is more divine than anything else. 
 
 * R. P. 15 d. That the words ttoXLttjs Kal eratpos, given by Simplicius, 
 De caelo, p. 615, 13, are from Theophrastos is shown by the agreement 
 of Cic. Acad. ii. 118, popularis et sodalis. The two passages represent 
 independent branches of the tradition. See Note on Sources, §§ 7, 12. 
 
. MILESIAN SCHOOL 51 
 
 tt.a^jr^f!^'^ 
 
 According to Apollodor^§,j^naximander was sixty-four 
 years old in 01. LVftl. 2 (547/6 b.c.| ; and this is confirmed 
 by Higgol^tcis^who says'W^^l^^ofn in 01. XLII. 3 (6io/§^,^^.^ 
 B.C.), and by Pliny, who assigns his great discovery '^tne 
 oWiouit^ of ^^^q^iii^^^^p^ 01. LVIII.^ We seem to have 
 something more here than a combination of the ordinary 
 type ; for, according to all the rules, Anaximander should 
 have "flourished" in 565 B.C., half-way between Thales,^ 
 and Anaximenes, and this would make him sixty, not sixty- 
 four, in 546. Now ApoUodoros appears to have said that 
 he had met with the work of Anaximander ; and the only 
 reason he can have had for mentioning this must be that 
 he found in it some indication which enabled him to fix 
 its date. Now 547/6 ^. just the year before the fall of 
 ^ardds^and we may perhaps conjecture that Anaximander 
 mentioned what his age had been at the time of that 
 event. I We know from Xenophanes that the question, 
 ^owold.were you when the Mede appear|d ? " was con- 
 sidered an interesting one in those days-.^H^At all events, 
 Anaximander was apparently a generation youjig^ji^-thaiii 
 Thales . ^ ^ 
 
 jp^^tical inventions. Some writers credited him with that of 
 
 %f.i^mBy^'^^^'''^'^ ^^^^^y ^^ correct. Herodg|p^«^.. . 
 us this instrument came from ,Bab^lQIi«^and Thales must 
 have usea it to determine the^i solstices and equinoxes.* \ 
 
 ^AgaLXimander was also the first to construct a m^ and^ 
 Eratosthenes said this was the map elabor^1T1!^Hekataios.\ 
 No doubt it was intended to be of service to Mil^'M^Mter- 
 prise in the Black Sea.| Anaximander himself conducted 
 
 1 Diog. ii. 2 (R. P. i5)4/f*ipp. Rej. i. 6 {Box. p. 560); Plin. N.H. ii. 31. 
 
 * Xenophanes, fr. 22 (= fr. 17 Karsten; R. P. 95 a). 
 
 » The statement that he " died soon after " (Diog. ii. 2 ; R. P. 15) 
 seems to mean that ApoUodoros made him die in the year of Sardeis 
 (546/5), one of his regular epochs. 
 
 * For the gnomon, see Introd. p. 26, n. i ; and cf. Diog. ii. i (R. P. 
 15) ; Herod, ii. 109 (R. P. 15 a). PUny, on the other hand, ascribes the 
 invention of the gnomon to Anaximenes {N.H. ii. 187). 
 
52 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Theo- 
 phrastos 
 on Anaxi- 
 mander's 
 theory of 
 the 
 
 primary 
 substance. 
 
 a colony to Apollonia,^ and his fellow-citizens erected a 
 statue to him.'^'^*-*'***-*^^'"" ' 
 
 13. Near]^.«.-aH'^^<w©^riq3l)QW of Anaximander's system is 
 intfee'iast^^l'^gjrt froni '1ffiet5^ 
 knew his book.^ He seems once' at tesf' to have quoted 
 Anaximander's own words, and he criticised his style. 
 Here are the remains of what he said of him in the First 
 Book: 
 
 Anaximander of Miletos, son of Praxiades, a fellow-citizen 
 and associate of Thales,* said that the material cause and first 
 element of things was the Infinite^Jje being the first to introduce 
 Jthis j^jpe. of the material ca!!§^' He says it is neither water nor 
 any other of the so-called ^ elements, but a substance difjerent 
 Hrom thera^wl^ch^is^n^jj^^ which^tse^afftfie neavens and 
 
 Sif '#8rfis within'them.— ^/i^/s^ Op. fr. 2 (Dox. |). 476 ; R. P. 16). 
 
 He says that this is 'V^eternal and ageless^ 'J and that it " en- 
 compasses all the ^oMs^^^ P. 17 a). ""^ 
 f An3nLnTo*'tft^tf om which things take their rise they pass 
 away once more,!" as is meet ; for they make reparation and 
 satisfaction to qse another for their injustice according to the 
 ordering of time," as he says ^ in these somewhat poetical terms. 
 —Phys. Op. fr. 2 (R. P. 16). 
 
 And besides this, there was an eternal motion, in which 
 was brought about the origin of the worlds. — Hipp. Ref. i. 6 
 (R. P. 17 a). 
 
 i\ 
 
 1 Aelian, V.H. iii. 17. Presumably Apollonia on the Pontes is meant 
 
 The lower part of a contemporary statue has been discovered at 
 
 iletos (Wiegand, Milet, ii. 88), with the inscription ANJAHlMANAPO. 
 
 It was not, we may be sure, for his theories of the Boundless that 
 
 Anaximander received this honour ; he was a statesman and an inventor 
 
 like Thales and Hekataios. 
 
 3 In this and other cases, where the words of the original have been 
 preserved by Simplicius, I have given them alone. On the various writers 
 quoted, see Note on Sources, §§ 9 sqq. 
 
 ^ Simplicius says " successor and disciple " (5td5oxos koI fxadrfr-qs) in his 
 Commentary on the Physics ; but see above, p. 50, n. 4. 
 
 5 For the expression to. Kokov/xeva aroLx^la, see Diels, Elementum, 
 p. 25. n. 4. 
 
 6 Diels ( Vors. 2, 9) begins the actual quotation with the words ^^ dv U 
 r} yive<n$ . . . The Greek practice of blending quotations with the text 
 tells against this.. Further, it is safer not to ascribe the terms yiveat^ and 
 <f)dopa. in their technical Platonic sense to Anaximander, and it is not 
 likely that Anaximander said anything about to. 6vTa. 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 53 
 
 I He did not ascribe the origin of things to any alteration in 
 matter, but said that the oppositions in the substratum, which 
 ^3iS a boundless body, were separated out. — Simpl. Phys. 
 |. 150, 20 (R. P. 18). 
 
 i4.^A naximander t aught, then, that there was an etoiialA The 
 indestructible something out of which e very th i n g^rll^S^| subSce 
 
 ajiymto^ which' ever ytliing returns 1 a boundless stock fromQ^°^°^® 
 which the waste of existence is^xontinually made goodj/'eiem^s. 
 That is only the natural dey^logrnent of the tnought we 
 
 have ascribed to Thal^§^.and there can be no doubt that 
 Anaximander at least formulated it distinctly. Indeed, we 
 can still follow to some extent the reasoning which led him 
 to do so. Thales had regarded water as the most likely 
 thing to be that of which all others are forms ; Anaximander 
 appears to have asked how the primary substance could be 
 one of these particular things. His argument seems to be 
 preserved by Aristoiy^^;.5y]5Q has the following passage in his 
 discussion of the Infinite I 
 
 Further, there cannot be a single, simple body which is 
 
 infinite, either, as some hold, one distinct from the elements, 
 
 which they then derive from it, or without this quaUfication. For 
 
 there are some who make this (i.e. a body distinct from the 
 
 elements)fthe infinite, and not^air , or water, in order that the 
 
 I other things may not be destroyed by their infinity. 'They 'are 
 
 'l^r^^ and fire 
 
 hot — and therefore, if any one of them were infinite, the rest would 
 
 {have ceased to he hy this time. Accordingly they say that what is 
 
 ^infinite is something other than the elements, and from it the 
 
 Wments arise. — Arist. Phys. F, 5. 204 b 22 (R. P. 16 b). 
 
 It is clear that A.naximandeMs herc contracted ...witll, 
 Thales and with Anaximenes. Nor is there any reason to 
 doubt that the account given of nis reasoning is substantially 
 correct, though the form is Aristotle's own, and in particular 
 the "elements" are an anachronism.! Anaximander started, f 
 '--tt-'WQul4^eem,-.f rem .4ke 'stiffs between the opposites which} 
 
 1 See p. 12, n. 2. 
 
54 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 go to make up the world ; the warm was opposed to the 
 cold, the dry to the wet. These were at war, and any 
 predominance, of , one over thT^gf wag^^F^^^ ^ 
 for which they must mai:'e*^re^arati6h to t^e anotl!'i!""S.T L'lie 
 appointed time.^ If Thales had been right in saying that 
 water was the fundamental reality, it would not be easy to 
 see how anything else could ever have existed. One side of 
 the opposition, the cold and moist, would have had its way 
 I unchecked, ^aad the warm and~4ry would have been driven 
 f from the^ld long-ago. fWe must, then, have something 
 ''''fibtH*®ei^r.c«a^..e4vAe«'>^r^ opposites, something more 
 ^mitive, out of which they arise, and into \^it*lf*fK?y'o'nce 
 more pass' away.| Thaf Xnaxifn^fiO^f^SlSled this something 
 by the name of 6v(tc^ is the natural interpretation of what 
 Theophrastos says ; the current statement that the term 
 ap'x^v was introduced by him appears to be due to a mis- 
 understanding. ^ We have seen that, when Aristotle used 
 
 1 The important word dXXTjXois is in all the MSS. of Simplicius, though 
 omitted in the Aldine. This omission made the sentence appear to mean 
 that the existence of individual things {6vTa) was somehow a wrong 
 (dSifc/a) for which they must be punished. With dXXTjXois restored, this 
 fanciful interpretation disappears. It is to one another that whatever the 
 subject of the verb may be make reparation and give satisfaction, and 
 therefore the injustice must be a wrong which they commit against one 
 another. Now, as SLkti is regularly used of the observance of an equal 
 balajiLtJ^wfeetween tW5*!3ppi3Sites hot and cold, dry and wet, the d^^^.here 
 referred to must be the undue encroachment of one opposite on another, 
 such as we see, for example, in the alternation of day and nigTit/winter 
 and summer, which have to be made good by an equal encroachment of 
 the other. I stated this view in my first edition (1892), pp. 60-62, and 
 am glad to find it confirmed by Professor Heidel {Class. Phil, vii., 1912, 
 
 P- 233 5^.)- 
 
 * The words of Theophrastos, as given by Simplicius {Phys. p. 24, 15 : 
 R. P. 16), are dpxw t^ k'^i- croixe'cov etprjKe tQv 6vtwv r6 B-ireipov, irpuros tovto 
 Towofia Ko/jLiaas rrjs dpxvs, the natural meaning of which is " he being the 
 first to introduce this name {to direipov) of the material cause." Hippo- 
 lytos, however, says {Ref. i. 6, 2) irpQiros Toxjvoixa KaXeaas ttjs dpxvs, and this 
 has led most writers to take the words in the sense^fBSf^^]SL§ximander intro- 
 l>i»'§^'S4-'^,'0^.^,,'iP^ Hippolytos, however, is not an independent authority 
 (see Note on Sources, § 13), and the only question is what Theophrastos 
 wrote. Now Simplicius quotes Theophrastos from Alexander, who used 
 the original, while Hippolytos represents a much more indirect tradition. 
 Obviously, /^gA^o-os^ ,,,is a corruption of the characteristically Peripatetic 
 KOfxicq,s^ and the omission of Todro is much more likely than its inter- 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 55 
 
 the term in discussing Thales, he meant what is called the 
 " material cause," ^ and it is hard to believe that it means 
 anything else here. 
 
 15. It was natural for Aristotle to regard this theory Aristotle's 
 as an anticipation or pres#itiment of his own doctrine of of the 
 ^**indeterminate matter/ #^ and that he should sometimes *^^o^y- / 
 ^^?«^^f^^^^^k^*^>m^ in terms of the later 
 
 theory of " elements."/ He knew that the Bounj^l^ap^ was 
 a body,^ though in his/ own system there was no room for 
 anything: corporeal prior to the elementsj so he had to 
 Speak of it as a boimdless body " alongside of " or " distinct 
 from " the elements (^^a^a^Tjf,^.o^^ So far as I know 
 
 no one has doubted that, when he uses this phrase, he is 
 referring to Anaximander. 
 
 In a number of other places Aristotle speaks of some one 
 who held the primary substance to be something *' inter- 
 mediate between /j'^tjj^je elements or between two of them.* 
 
 polation by Alexander or Simplicius. But, if tovto is genuine, the 6vona 
 referred to must be rb Etreipov, and this interpretation is confirmed by 
 Simpl. De caelo 615, 15, direipov 5k TrpQros viridero. In another place (p. 150, 
 23) Simplicius says -jrpQTos aiirbs dpxw dvo/xdaas rb v-rroKelfievov, which must 
 mean, as the context shows, " being the first to name the substratum 
 of the opposites as the material cause," which is another point altogether. 
 Theophrastos is always interested in noting who it was that " first " 
 introduced a concept, and both direLpou and viroKel/xevov were important 
 enough to be noted. Of course he does not mean that Anaximander used 
 the word vTroKeLixevov. He only infers that he had the idea from the doctrine 
 that the opposites which are " in " the Aireipov are " separated out." 
 Lastly, the whole book from which these extracts were taken was Uepl tCjv 
 dpx^v, and the thing to note was who first applied various predicates to 
 the dpxn or dpxaL 
 
 ^ See p. 47 n. 6 and Introd. p. 11 «. 3. 
 
 2 Arist. Met. A, 2. 1069 b 18 (R. P. 16 c). 
 
 3 This is taken for granted in Phys. r, 4. 203 a 16 ; 204 b 22 (R. P. 
 16 b), and stated in r, 8. 208 a 8 {R. P. 16 a). Cf. Simpl. Phys. p. 150, 
 20 (R. P. 18). 
 
 * Aristotle speaks four times of something intermediate between Fire 
 and Air {Gen. Corr. B, i. 328 b 35 ; ib. 5, 332 a 21 ; Phys. A, 4. 187 a 14 ; 
 Met. A, 7. 988 a 30). In five places we have something intermediate"^ 
 between Water and Air (Met. A, 7. 988 a 13 ; Gen. Corr. B, 5. 332 a 21 ; 
 Phys. r, 4. 203 a i8 ; ib. 5. 205 a 27 ; De caelo, T, 5. 303 b 12). Once 
 (Phys. A, 6. 189 b i) we hear of something between Water and Fire. This 
 variation shows at once that he is not speaking historically. If any one 
 
 / 
 
( 
 
 56 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Nearly all the Greek commentators referred this to Anaxi- 
 mander also, but most modern writers refuse to follow them. 
 It is, no doubt, easy to show that Anaximander himself 
 cannot have said anything of the sort, but that is no real 
 objection. Aristotle puts things in his own way regardless 
 of historical considerations, and it is difficult to see that it is_ 
 more of an anachronism to call the Boundless " intermedSate 
 Eelween tKe^eiements """"flian to say that it is^**'15iftinet 
 fi^rft^"1ii:^''^^gSiBnt^.'' Indeed, if once we introduce the 
 elements at all, the former description is the more adequate 
 of the two. At any rate, if we refuse to understand these 
 passages as referring to Anaximander, we shall have to say 
 that Aristotle paid a great deal of attention to some one 
 whose very name has been lost, and who not only agreed 
 with some of Anaximander's views, but also used some of 
 his most characteristic expressions.^ We may add that in 
 one or two places Aristotle certainly seems to identify the 
 " intermediate " with the something " distinct from " the 
 elements. 2 
 
 There is even one passage in which he speaks of Anaxi- 
 mander's Boundless as a " mixture," though his words may 
 perhaps admit of another interpretation.^ But this is '^of 
 no consequence for our interpretation of Anaximander. 
 It is certain that he cannot have said anything about 
 elements, which no one thought of before Empeuokles, 
 
 ever held the doctrine of rh fxera^ij, he must have known which " ele- 
 ments " he meant. »»«•«#=»'• 
 
 ^ Arist. De caelo, V, 5. 303 b 12, vbaros fih XeirTitrepov, aipo$ 5^ irvKybrepov, 
 6 irepL^x^'-^ (pacrl irdpras roi)s oi/pavods Aireipov 6v. 
 
 2 Cf. Phys. r, 5. 204 b 22 (R. P. 16 b), where Zeller rightly refers rb 
 trapdi. TO, (xroLxeta to Anaximander. Now, at the end (205 a 25) the whole 
 passage is summarised thus : Kal dtb. tovt oiidsls to iv kol direipov irvp iirolirjaev 
 ov5k yrjv TU)v (pvcioXdyoiv, dXX' •^ vdtop 7) d^pa ij to fjAaov avrCiv. In Cren. Cory. 
 B, I. 328 b 35 we have first tl jxeTa^i/ to6tuv cCoixd re bv Kal x'^/5to'7'6v, and a 
 little further on (329 a 9) /xiav vXrjv irapd to. elprj/uLiva. In B, 5. 332 a 20 we 
 have ou ixrqv ov5' &X\o tL ye irapd TavTa, olov jxiaov rt d^pos Kal vdaTOS r} depos Kal 
 irvp6s. 
 
 3 Met. A, 2. 1069 b 18 (R. P. 16 c). Zeller (p. 205, n. 1) assumes an 
 " easy zeugma." 
 
 •I 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 57 
 
 and no one could think of before Parmenides. 1 The question 
 has only been mentioned because it has ^vgsmse to a lengthy 
 controversy, and because it throws light on the historical 
 value of Aristotle's statements. From the point of view 
 of his own system, these may be justified ; but we shall 
 have to remember in other cases that, when he seems to 
 attribute an idea to some earher thinker, we are not bound 
 to take what he says in an historical sense. ^ 
 
 i6. Anaximander's reason for conceiving the primarytxhe 
 substance as boundless was, no doubt, as indicated byigy^jg^^Jj^g 
 Aristotle, " that becoming might not fail." ^ It is not clear, |s infinite. 
 however, t^^Tl^rwoix^^^Sf^^^^S^n^Th^ the doxo- 1- 
 graphers speak as if they were. It is enough for us that 
 
 iTheophrastos, who had seen his book, attributed the thought 
 to him. JAnd certainly his view of the world would bring 
 
 f home to him the need of a boundless stock of matter. The 
 " opposites " are, we have seen, at war with one another, 
 and their strife is marked by " unjust " encroachments on 
 
 "either side. The warm commits " injustice " in summer, 
 
 * For the literature of this controversy, see R. P. 15. Professor 
 Heidel has shown in his " Quahtative Change in Pre-Socratic Philosophy " 
 {Arch. xix. p. 333) that Aristotle misunderstood the Milesians because he 
 could only think of their doctrine in terms of his own theory of dXXoiwtns. 
 That is quite true, but it is equally true that they had no definite theory 
 of their own with regard to the transformations of substance. The 
 theory of an original " mixture " is quite as unhistorical as that of aWoiwcns. 
 Qualities were not yet distinguished from "things," and Thales doubtless 
 said that water turned into vapour or ice without dreaming of any 
 further questions. They all believed that in the long run there was only 
 one " thing," and at last they came to the conclusion that all apparent 
 differences were due to rarefaction and condensation. Theophrastos 
 (ap. Simpl, Phys. 150, 22) says ivovaas yap ras ivavTibras iv t(? viroKeLix^vt^ 
 . . . iKKpiveadai. I do not believe these words are even a paraphrase of 
 anything Anaximander said. They are merely an attempt to " accommo- 
 date " his views to Peripatetic ideas, and ivo6(yas is as unhistorical as 
 the VTTOKelfxevov. 
 
 2 Phys. V, 8. 208 a 8 (R. P. 16 a). Cf. Aet. i. 3, 3 (R. P. 16 a). The 
 same argument is given in Phys. V, 4. 203 b 18, a passage where Anaxi- 
 mander has just been named, ry ourws div fioi^ov fir] viroXelireiv yiveaip Kal 
 (pdopdv, €1 dweipop elt] SOev d0atpeirat rb yLyvofievov. I cannot, however, 
 believe that the arguments at the beginning of this chapter (203 b 7 ; 
 R. P.. 17) are Anaximander's, They bear the stamp of the Eleatic dialectic, 
 and are, in fact, those of Melissos.'^ *-'''*-''s->'»^*.^i.v»*j!Vi««^*««jftiiv«jfc'^^ 
 
58 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the cold in winter, and this would lead in the long run to 
 the destruction of everything but the Boundless itself, if 
 there were not an inexhaustible supply ol^^'iFTrom which 
 opposites might continually be separated out afresh. We 
 must picture, then, an endless mass, which is not any one of 
 the opposites we know, stretching out without Hmit on every 
 side of the world we live in.^ This mass is a body, out of 
 which our world once emerged, and into which it will one 
 day^.be absorbed again. 
 
 ' '; 17. We are told that Anaximander believed there were 
 " innumerable worlds in the Boundless," ^ and we have to 
 ecide between the interpretation that, though all the 
 orlds are perishable, there are an unhmited number of 
 hem in existence at the same time, and Zeller's view that 
 ^a new world never comes into existence till the old 
 ^one has passed away, so that there is never more than 
 §one world at a time. As this point is of fundamental 
 4' importance, it will be necessary to examine the evidence 
 ■ carefully. 
 
 In the first place, the doxographical tradition proves 
 that Theophrastos^ discussed the views of all the early 
 philosopBSs as to whether there was one world or an 
 infinite number, and there can be no doubt that, when he 
 ascribed " innumerable worlds " to the Atomists^e meant 
 coexistent and not successge_pj^|^|^,. Now, une nad 
 cM-^^eaT'^fWe^M^^^ifferent views 'under one head, he would 
 
 1 I have assumed that the word &Treipov means spatially infinite, not 
 qualitatively indeterminate, as maintained by Teichmiiller and Tannery. 
 The decisive reasons for holding that the sense of the word is ' boundless 
 in extent " are as follows : (i) Theophrastos said the primary substance 
 of Anaximander was direipov and contained all the worlds, and the word 
 wepiex^iv everywhere means " to encompass," not, as has been suggested, 
 " to contain potentially." (2) Aristotle says {Phys. V, 4. 203 b 23) 5td 
 yap TO iv TTJ voTjaei fxr] vnoXeiireiv ,/caJ 6 dpid/ibs 5ok€i diretpos ehaL /cat to. /xadrj/xariK^ 
 /xey^Orj Kai ra ?|w rod ovpavov ' atreipov 8' 6vtos tov ^^cj, Kal cQjfxa 6.irei.pov elvat. 5ok€i 
 K-al K6(TfxoL. The mention of <xCo/xa shows that this does not refer to the 
 Atomists. (3) Anaximander's theory of the dweipov was adopted by 
 Anaximenes, and he identified it with Air, which is not quahtatively 
 indeterminate. 
 
 2 Cf. [Plut.] Strom, fr. 2 (R. P. 21 b). 
 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 59 
 
 have been careful to point out in what respect they differed, 
 and there is no trace of any such distinction. On the 
 contrary, Anaximander, Anaximenes, Archelaos, Xeno- 
 )hanes, Dioe^enes, Leukippos, Deniokritos7"aM Epicurus aire 
 ^^ mentioned together as holding the doctrine oiJ^J^^^ 
 lumerable worlds " on every side of this one/ and the only 
 listmction is^^lJhat, while Epicurus made the distances 
 between these worlds unequal, Anaximander said aU the 
 ^orlds were equidistant. ^ Zeller rejected this evidence ^ 
 dpi the ground that we can have no confidence in a writer 
 who attributes " innumerable worlds " to Anaximenes, 
 Archelaos, and Xenophanes. With regard to the first two, 
 I hope to show that the statement is correct, and that it is 
 at least intelligible in the case of the last.* In any case, the 
 passage comes from Actios,^ and there is no reason for 
 doubting that it is derived from Theophrastos, though the 
 name of Epicurus has been added later. This is confirmed 
 by what Simplicius says : 
 
 Those who assumed innumerable worlds, e.g. Anaximander, 
 .eukippos, Demokritos, and, at a later date, Epicurus, held that 
 |they came into being and passed away ad infinitum, some always 
 tpming into being and others passing away.^ 
 
 It is practically certain that this too comes from Theo- 
 phrastos through Alexander. 
 
 ^ Aet. ii. I, 3 {Dox. p. 327). Zeller seems to be wrong in understanding 
 Kara iraaav irepLaywy-qv here of revolution. It must mean " in every 
 direction we turn," as is shown by the alternative phrase Kara irdaai' 
 TrepiaTaa-iv. The six irepiaTdaeL^ are Trp^crw, ott^cto;, Aucj, koltw, Se^cd, dpia-repd 
 (Nicom. Introd. p. 85, 11, Hoche). 
 
 ' Aet. ii. I, 8 [Dox. p. 329), tu)v direlpovs dirocfyquajxhujv roiis Koajiovs 
 'Apa^ifiavSpos to Ictov avroi/i dir^X'^'-^ dWrjXuv, 'EiriKovpos dviaop elvat. t6 fxera^u 
 rdv Kbaixwv 5tdcrT?7/xa. 
 
 3 He supposed it to be only that of Stobaios. The filiation of the 
 sources had not been traced when he wrote. 
 
 * For Anaximenes see § 30 ; Xenophanes, § 59 ; Archelaos, § 192. 
 
 5 This is proved by the fact that the list of names is given also by 
 Theodoret. See Note on Sources, § 10. 
 
 « Simpl. Phys. p. 11 21, 5 (R. P. 21 b). Cf. Simpl. De caelo, p. 202, 14, 
 ol 5e Kol ry irXrjdet. aTrelpovs KocTfiovs, ws ' Aua^ifji.av5pos . . . direipou t(^ fieyidei. ttjv 
 dpyjr]v di/xevos dirdpovs i^ avrov TifijirX-qdei K6<T/xovs^iroi,eTp 8oK€i. 
 
6o / EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 We come next to a very important statement which 
 Cicero has copied from Philodemos, the author of the 
 Epicurean treatise on ReHgion found at Herculaneum, or 
 perhaps from the immediate source of that work. " Anaxi- 
 mander's opinion was," he makes Velleius say, " that there 
 were gods )^p came into being, rising and passing away 
 anSng* intervals, and that these were the innumerable 
 worlds '* ; ^. .and this must clearly be taken along with the 
 ^^i^Miii of Actios that, according to Anaximande r^^ the 
 " innumerable heavens " were gods.^ Now it is much 
 more natural to understand tne*****iong intervals " as 
 
 that is right, we have a perfect agreement among our 
 authorities. 
 
 It may be added that it is very unnatural to understand 
 the statement that the Boundless " encompasses all the 
 worlds " of worlds succeeding one another in time ; for on 
 :his view there is at a given time only one world to " en- 
 compass." ,? Moreover, the argument mentioned by Aristotle 
 that, if what is outside the heavens is infinite, body must 
 be infinite, and there must be innumerable worlds, can only 
 be understood in one sense, and is certainly intended to 
 represent the reasoning of the Milesians ; for they were 
 the only cosmologists who held there was a boundless 
 body outside the heavens.* Lastly, we happen to know 
 that Petro i^v'One of the earhest Pytbagoreaiis^ *held 
 there were iust one hundred and eimh^ ^Siree worlds 
 
 1 Cicero, De nat. d. i. 25 (R. P. 21). 
 
 2 Aet. i. 7, 12 (R. P. 21 a). The reading of Stob., d-rrdpovs ovpavo^s, 
 is guaranteed by the direlpovs Koa/j-ovs of Cyril, and the direipovs vovs 
 {i.e. ovyovs) of the pseudo-Galen. See Dox. p. 11. 
 
 3 It is natural to suppose that Cicero found diacrTri/xacriv in his Epicurean 
 source, and that is a technical term for the intermundia. 
 
 * Arist. Phys. T, 4. 203 b 25, dwelpov 5' 6Vros rod ?^w (sc. rod ovpavov), 
 Kal (rdfia. direipov elvai doKcT Kal K6<xfioc (sc. direLpoL). The next words — ri ydp 
 fidXXov Tov Kepov ivravda i) ivravda ; — show that this refers to the Atomists 
 as well ; but the direipov a-Q^a will not apply to them. The meaning is 
 that both those who made the Boundless a body and those who made 
 it a Kevov held the doctrine of dveLpoi Kbaixoi in the same sense. 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 6i 
 
 arranged in a triangle,^ ^which shows at least that the 
 doctrine of a ptMLE^'y*of worlds was much older than the 
 Atomists. 
 
 i8. The doxographers say it was the *' eternal motion " "Eternal 
 that brought into being " all the heavens and all the worlds ^Vthe 
 within them.*' We have seen (§ VIII.) that this is probably ^^'"'• 
 only the Aristotelian way of putting the thing, and that we 
 must not identify the primordial motion of the Boundless 
 with, any purely mundane movement such as the diurnal 
 revolution. That would be quite inconsistent, moreover, 
 with the doctrine of innumerable worlds, each of which has, 
 presumably, its own centre and its own diurnal revolution. 
 As to the true nature of this motion, we have no definite 
 statement, but the term " separating off *' (diroKpia-is:) rather 
 suggests some process of shaking and sifting as in a riddle 
 or sieve. That is given in Plato's Timaeus as the Pytha- 
 gorean doctrine, 2 and the Pythagoreans followed Snaxi- 
 mander pretty closely in their cosmology' t^-'*3?)?'^^^ 
 school' of 'A'bdeVa', las ^m (§ 179), attributed a 
 
 motion of the same kind to their atoms, and they too were 
 mainly dependent on the Milesians for the details of their 
 system. This, however, must remain a conjecture in the 
 absence of express testimony. 
 
 When, however, we come to the motion of the world 
 once it has been " separated off," we are on safer groun( 
 It i^ certain that one of the chief features of early cosmology 
 is the part played in it by the analogy of an eddy in water 
 or in wind, a (Sti^^ (or ^Ivo^),^ and there seems to be little 
 
 ^ See below, § 53. Cf. Diels, Elementum, pp. 63 sqq. 
 
 2 Plato, Tim. 52 e. There the elemental figures (which have taken 
 the place of the " opposites ") " being thus stirred (by the irregular 
 motion of the ndrivT]), are carried in different directions and separated, 
 just as by sieves and instruments for winnowing corn the grain is shaken 
 and sifted ; and the dense and heavy parts go one way, while the rare 
 and light are carried to a different place and settle there." 
 
 3 Aristophanes, referring to the Ionian cosmology, says {Clouds, 828) 
 A2pos j8acriXei;et t6v At' e^'eXnXaKw^-. awWeb is nearer the truth than the 
 modern theory of its religious origin. 
 
62 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 h^oubt that we are entitled to regard this as the doctrine 
 S.Qf ^ Anaxiniander and ^, Am It would arise very 
 
 naturally in the minds of thinkers who started with water 
 as the primary substance and ended with " air," and it 
 would account admirably for the position of earth and water 
 in the centre and fire at the circumference, with " air " 
 between them. Heavy things tend to the centre of a vortex 
 and Ught things are forced out to the periphery. It is to be 
 observed that there is no question of a sphere in revolution 
 at this date ; what we have to picture is rotary motion in a 
 plane or planes more or less incHned to the earth's surface. ^ 
 It is in favour of the conjecture given above as to the nature 
 of the primordial motion that it provides a satisfactory 
 dynamical explanation of the formation of the Blvt), and 
 we shall find once more (§ i8o) that the Atomists held 
 precisely this view of its origin. 
 Origin / iQ- The doxographers also give us some indications 
 of the if ^Yie process by which the different parts of the world 
 
 heavenly ¥ 
 
 bodies. ^rose from the Boundless. The following statement comes 
 ultimately from Theophrastos : 
 
 He says that something capable of begetting hot and cold 
 out of the eternal was separated off at the origin of this world. 
 From this arose a sphere of flame which fitted close round the 
 air surrounding the earth as the bark round a tree. When this 
 had been torn off and shut up in certain rings, the sun, 
 
 1 I gratefully accept the view propounded by Prof. W. A. Heidel 
 (" The dlvr) in Anaximenes and Anaximander," Class. Phil. i. 279), so 
 far as the cosmical motion goes, though I cannot identify that with the 
 " eternal motion." I had already done what I could to show that the 
 " spheres " of Eudoxos and Aristotle must not be imported into Pytha- 
 goreanism, and it strengthens the position considerably if we ascribe a 
 rotary motion in a plane to Anaximander's world. 
 
 2 This is the plain meaning of Aet. ii. 2, 4, ol 5^ rpoxoO 51kt)u trepL- 
 diveiadai rbv Kda/xou, which is referred to Anaximander by Diels {Dox. 
 p. 46). Zeller's objections to the ascription of thte divT] to Anaximander 
 are mainly based on an inadmissible rendering of the word rpoiral 
 (p. 63 n. 2). Of course, the rotations are not all in the same plane; 
 the ecUptic, for instance, is incHned to the equator, and the Milky Way 
 to both. 
 
 i 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 63 
 
 moon and stars came into existence. — Ps.-Plut. Strom, fr. 2 
 (R. P. i9).i 
 
 We see from this that, when a portion of the Boundless 
 was separated off from the rest to form a world, it first 
 differentiated itself into the two opposites, hot and cold.^ 
 The hot appears as flame surrounding thecoIH'f 'mVcbld," a^^ 
 earth with air surrounding it. We are not told here how the 
 cold was differentiated into earth, water and air, but there 
 is a passage in Aristotle's Meteorology which throws some 
 light on the question. After discussing the views of the 
 " theologians " regarding the sea, he says : 
 
 But those who are wiser in the wisdom of men give an origin 
 
 for, |h^%;fi^. At first, they say, all the terrestrial region was' 
 
 ^ moist ; and, as it was dried up by the sun, the portion of it that 
 
 evaporated produced the winds and the turnings back of the 
 
 sun and moon,^ while the portion left behind was the seav So 
 
 , L^ 
 
 1 This passage has been discussed by Heidel {Proceedings of the A merican 
 Academy, xlviii. 686). I agree that ctTro rod aireipov must be supplied with 
 diroKpcdijvai, and I formerly thought that ck toO aldiov might be equivalent 
 to that, and might have been displaced if the order of words was 
 too harsh. ,1 cannot believe that it means " from eternity," as Heidel 
 thinks. On the other hand, he is clearly right in his interpretation of 
 ir€pi(f>vT]vai and diroppayelarjs. He also points out correctly that " the 
 sphere of flame " is an inaccuracy. The comparison to the bark of a tree 
 distinctly suggests something annular. 
 
 -* Zeller (p. 223, n. 5) asks what can be meant by rpoiral rrjs a-eXrjvrjs, 
 but his difficulty is an imaginary one. The moon has certainly a move- 
 ment in decUnation and therefore rpoirai. In other words, the moon does 
 not always rise at the same point of the horizon any more than the sun. 
 This is admitted by Sir T. L. Heath {Aristarchus, p. 33, «. 3), though he 
 has unfortunately followed Zeller in supposing that Tpowai here means 
 " revolutions." This seems to me impossible ; for rpeweadai. means " to 
 turn back " or " to turn aside," never " to turn round," which is arpi^eadai. 
 It is conceivable, indeed, that rpoTal ijeXioLo in Od. xv. 404 means the place 
 where the sun sets and turns back from west to east, though it is not 
 very likely, as Hesiod already uses rpoirai rieXioLo of the winter and summer 
 solstices {O.D. 479, 564, 663). Zeller's statement (repeated by Heath) 
 that Aristotle speaks of Tpowai of the fixed stars in De caelo, B, 14. 296 b 4, 
 is erroneous. What Aristotle does say is that, if the earth is in motion, 
 there ought to be TrdpoSot (movements in latitude) and rpoirai of the fixed 
 stars, which there are not. The passage is correctly rendered by Sir T. L. 
 Heath himself in a subsequent chapter (p. 241). For the other passages 
 referred to, see p. 64, n. i, and p. 76, n. 3. 
 
i 
 
 64 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 'they think the sea is becoming smaller by being dried up, and 
 that at last it will all be dry. — Meteor, B, i. 353 b 5. 
 
 And the same absurdity arises for those who say the earth 
 too was at first moist, and that, when the region of the world 
 about the earth was heated by the sun, air was produced and the 
 whole heavens were increased, and that it (the air) produced 
 winds and caused its (the sun's) turnings back.^ — Ih. 2. 355 a 21 
 (R. P. 20 a). 
 
 In his commentary on the passage, Alexander says 
 this was the view of Anaximander and Diogenes7"and cites 
 Theophrastos as his aufli6nty'for*tiie'«tatertl^t^ This is 
 confirmed by Anaximander's theory of the sea as given by 
 the doxographers (§ 20). |We conclude, then, that after the 
 first separation of the hot and the cold by the hivrj, the heat 
 SftKe 'li^e liJrriSa^^l^^ of the 
 
 world into air or vapour — it is all one at this date — and that 
 the expansion of this mist broke up the flame itself into 
 rings. We shall come back to these rings presently, but we 
 must look first at what we are told of the earth. 
 Earth / 20. The Origin of earth and sea from the moist, cold 
 
 and sea. / " , • 1 
 
 matter which was " separated off " m the beginning is thus 
 described : 
 
 The sea is what is left of the original moisture.^^The fire has 
 dried up most of it and turned the rest salt by scorching it. — 
 Aet. iii. 16, i (R. P. 20 a). 
 
 /^^ He says that the earth is cyUndrical in form, and that its depth 
 ^ as a third part of its breadth.— Ps.-Plut. Strom, fr. 2 (R. P. ih.). 
 
 The earth swings free, held in its place by nothing. It stays 
 where it is because of its equal distance from ^verjihmg. Its 
 
 1 From the whole context it is plain that ras rpowas avrov means 
 rhs Tov i]\iov rpoirds, and not rds tov ovpavov, as Zeller and Heath say. 
 The " air " in this passage answers to " the portion that evaporated " 
 {to diaT/xlaav) in that previously quoted, and toCtov must therefore refer 
 to it. Cf. the paraphrase of Alexander (p. 67, 3 from Theophrastos, 
 Dox. p. 494), t6 flip Ti T^s vypoTTjros virb tov i]\Lov e^aTfil^eadai, Kal yiveadai, 
 irvevfiaTo. re i^ avTov Kal Tpoiras rjkiov re koL a-eXrjprjs (see last note). In this 
 chapter of the Meteorology, Aristctle is discussing the doctrine that the 
 sun is " fed " by moisture and the relation of that doctrine to its 
 Tpowai at the solstices, and we must interpret accordingly. 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 65 
 
 shape is hollow and round, and like a stone piUar./ We are on 
 one of the surfaces, and the other is on the opposite side.^ — Hipp. 
 Ref. i. 6 (R. P. 20). 
 
 Adopting for a moment the popular theory of "elements/* 
 we see that Anaximander put fire on one side as the hot and 
 dry, and all the rest on the other as the cold, which is also 
 moist. This may explain how Aristotle came to sp<^J)^.„g|fr^ 
 the Boundless as intermediate between fire and wate^ And 
 we have seen also that the moist element was partly turned 
 into " air " or vapour by the fire, which explains how 
 Aristotle could say the Boundless was something between 
 fire and air, or between air and water. ^ ^r»> -> 
 
 The moist, cold interior of the world is not, in fact, 
 water. It is always called " the moist " or " the moist 
 state." That is because it has to be still further differ- 
 entiated under the influence of heat into earth, water, and 
 vapour. The gradual drying up of the water by the fire is a 
 good example of what Anaximander meant by ** injustice." 
 f Thales had said that the earth floated on the water, 
 /but Anaximander reahsed that it was freely suspended in 
 If space (fjL6Tecopo(;) and did not require any support. Aristotle 
 "has preserved the argument he used. The earth is equally 
 distant from the circumference of the vortex in every 
 direction, and there is no reason for it to move up or down 
 
 1 The MSS. of Hippolytos have vypbv trrpoyy^Xop, and so has Cedrenus, 
 a writer of the eleventh century who made extracts from him. Roeper 
 read yvpov [<TTpoyyv\ov], supposing the second word to be a gloss on the 
 first. Diels (Dox. p. 218) holds that the first applies to the surface of the 
 earth ; while the second refers to its circuit. Professor A. E. Taylor has 
 pointed out to me, however, the great improbability of the view that 
 yvpov means convex. The lonians down to Archelaos (§ 192) and Demo- 
 kritos (Aet. iii. 10, 5, KoiXriv rep /M^acf) regularly regarded the surface of 
 the earth as concave, and yvp6s can just as well mean that. The next 
 words are also of doubtful meaning. The MSS. of Hippolytos have x^<»'t 
 Xidcp, while Actios (iii. 10, 2) has Xidtp k'lovl. Diels doubtfully conjectures 
 \id(^ kIopl, which he suggests might represent an original Xidirj kIovi 
 {Dox. p. 219). In any case the pillar seems genuine, and the general 
 sense is guaranteed by the Plutarchean Stromateis {loc, cit.), vTrapxcv . . . 
 Ttj? jxev (Txrif^oLTi rrju yijv Kv\Lv5poei.5rj. 
 
 ' See above, p. 55, n. 4. 
 
 5 
 
66 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 or sideways.^ The doctrine of innumerable worlds was 
 inconsistent with the existence of an absolute up and down 
 in the universe, so the argument is quite sound. The central 
 position of the earth is due to the Blvt) ; for the greater 
 masses tend to the centre of an eddy.^ There is good 
 evidence that Anaximander made the earth share in the 
 <7 rotary movement.^ It is not, however, a sphere, so we 
 must not speak of an axial revolution. The shape given 
 to the earth by Anaximander is easily explained if we 
 adopt the view that the world is a system of rotating 
 rings. It is just a sohd ring in the middle of the 
 vortex. 
 
 21. We have seen that the flame which had been forced 
 to the circumference of the vortex was broken up into rings 
 by the pressure of expanding vapour produced by its own 
 heat. I give the statements of Hippolytos and Actios as to 
 the formation of the heavenly bodies from these rings. 
 
 the fire of the world, and surrounded by air. And there are 
 breathing-holes, certain pipe-like passages, at which the heavenly 
 bodies show themselves. That is why, when the breathing-holes 
 are stopped, eclipses take place. And the moon appears now to 
 wax and now to wane because of the stopping and opening of 
 
 1 Arist. De cash, B, 13. 295 b 10 elal di rives ot 5ia rV bixoibT-qra <paaiv 
 avTTjv {t7]V yrjv) fiiveiv, wcnrep tCjv dpxaicov 'Ava^lfiavdpos' fiaWov fxev yap oidh 
 8.v(i3 t) Kdroj t) els to. irXdyia (pepeadai it poa-riKeiv t6 iirl rod fj^aov idpvfxevov Kal ofioius 
 TTpbs TO. ^axo-To- ^x^v- One point of the blvrf is no more " down " than 
 another. Apparently, the Pythagoreans adopted this reasoning ; for 
 Plato makes Sokrates in the Phaedo say (108 e) laoppowov yap irpdyixa o/xolov 
 TLvbs ev fi^acp redev ovx ?^ei fidWov ov5^ ^ttov ov5afi6ae KKidijvaL. From this it 
 appears that ofioLOTrjs means something like " indifference." There is 
 nothing to differentiate one radius of a circle from another. 
 
 2 Arist. De caelo, B, 13. 295 a 9 (17 7^) (xvvrjXeev eirl to jxeaov (f>epofxivr] diii 
 T^u dLvrjaiV TatJTTjv yap tt]v ahlav irdures Xiyovaiv iK tQp iu tols vypoLS Koi irepl 
 Tov d4pa (TVjx^aLvbvTiav ' ev toijtols ydp del (piperai rd jmel^u Kal rd ^apirepa irpos t3| 
 fiiaov TTJs divTjs. 5l6 drj Kal ttju yrjv irdvTes 6(rot rbv ovpavbv yevvCJciP iirl rb fiiaolk 
 (TweXdetv (paaLv. 
 
 ' This was expressly stated by Eudemos {ap. Theon. Smyrn. p. igSl 
 18), 'Apa^ifxavdpos d^ oti iarlv ij yrj fieriiopos Kal KiPeLTai Trepl rb ^x^aovi 
 Anaxagoras held the same view (§ 133). 
 
 I 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 67 
 
 the passages. The wheel of the sun is 27 times the size oir>^J^ 7' 
 (the earth, while that of) the moon is 18 times as large.| ^The 
 sun is the highest of all, and lowest are the wheels of the ^ars. 
 —Hipp. Ref. i. 6 (R. P. 20). 
 
 The heavenly bodies were hoop-like compressions of air, full 
 of fire, breathing out flames at a certain point through orifices. — 
 Aet. ii. 13, 7 (R. P. 19 a). 
 
 The sun was a wheel 28 times the size of the earth, like a 
 chariot - wheel with the felloe hollow, full of fire, showing 
 the fire at a certain point through an orifice, as through the nozzle 
 of a pair of bellows. — Aet. ii. 20, i (R. P. 19 a). 
 
 The sun was equal to the earth, but the wheel from which 
 it breathes out and by which it is carried round was 27 
 times the size of the earth. — Aet. ii. 21, i. 
 
 The sun was eclipsed when the orifice of the fire's breathing- 
 hole was stopped. — Aet. ii. 24, 2. 
 
 The moon was a wheel 19 times the size of the earth, 
 like a chariot-wheel with its felloe hollow and full of fire like that 
 of the sun, lying oblique also like it, with one breathing-hole like 
 the nozzle of a pair of bellows. [It is eclipsed because of the 
 turnings of the wheel.] ^ — Aet. ii. 25, i. 
 
 The moon was eclipsed when the orifice of the wheel was 
 stopped. — Aet. ii. 29, i. 
 
 (Thunder and lightning, etc.) were all caused by the blast 
 of the wind. When it is shut up in a thick cloud and bursts 
 forth with violence, then the tearing of the cloud makes the 
 noise, and the rift gives the appearance of a flash in contrast with 
 the blackness of the cloud. — Aet. iii. 3, i. 
 
 Wind was a current of air (i.e. vapour), which arose when its 
 finest and moist est particles were stirred or melted by the 
 sun. — Aet. iii. 7, i. 
 
 ^ I assume with Diels {Dox. p. 560) that something has fallen out of 
 the text, but I have made the moon's circle 18 and not 19 times as large, 
 as agreeing better with the other figure, 27. See p. 68, n. 1. 
 
 ^ There is clearly some confusion here, as Anaximander's real account 
 of lunar eclipses is given in the next extract. There is also some doubt 
 about the reading. Both Plutarch and Eusebios {P.E. xv. 26, i) have 
 iiriaTpocpas, SO the Tpoirds of Stob. may be neglected, especially as the 
 codex Sambuci had arpocpas. It looks as if this were a stray reference to 
 the theory of Herakleitos that eclipses were due to a arpoipri or iTn(XTpo(f>ri of 
 the (r/cd077 (§71). In any case, the passage cannot be relied on in sup- 
 port of the meaning given to Tpoirai by Zeller and Heath (p. 63, n. 2). 
 
68 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 There is a curious variation in the figures given for the 
 size of the wheels of the heavenly bodies, and it seems most 
 likely that 
 
 refer to their 
 
 that ttie wheels of the " stars " were nine times the size of 
 the earth ; for the numbers ,2^8, 27 play a considerable 
 part in primitive co^sjHiQgftjsies^^ We '&d not see the wheels 
 of fire as complete circles ; for the vapour or mist which 
 formed them encloses the fire, and forms an outer ring except 
 at one point of their circumference, through which the fire 
 escapes, and that is the heavenly body we actually see.^ 
 It is possible that the theory of " wheels " was suggested 
 by the Milky Way. If we ask how it is that the wheels 
 of air can make the fire invisible to us without becoming 
 visible themselves, the answer is that such is the property 
 of what the Greeks at this date called " air/' For instance, 
 when a Homeric hero is made invisible by being clothed in 
 ^v;.v " air," we can see right through both the " air *' and the 
 { *hero.^ It should be added that lightning is explained in 
 eft the same way as the heavenly bodies. It, too, was 
 fire breaking through condensed air, in this case storm- 
 clouds. It seems probable that this was really the origin 
 of the theory, and that Anaximander explained the heavenly 
 bodies on the analogy of lightning, not vice versa. It must 
 be remembered that meteorology and astronomy were 
 still undifferentiated,* and that the theory of " wheels " 
 
 ^ See Tannery, Science helUne, p. 91 ; Diels, " Ueber Anaximanders 
 Kosmos " {Arch. x. pp. 231 sqq.). 
 
 * The true meaning of this doctrine was first explained by Diels {Dox. 
 pp. 25 sqq.). The flames issue per magni circum spiracula mundi, as 
 Lucretius has it (vi. 493). The wpTja-TTjpos aiXos, to which these are com- 
 pared, is simply the mouthpiece of the smith's bellows, a sense the word 
 TrprjcTTrip has in ApoUonios of Rhodes (iv. 776), and has nothing to do with 
 the meteorological phenomenon of the same name (see Chap; III. § 71), 
 except that the Greek sailors very likely named the fiery waterspout 
 after the familiar instrument. It is not necessary now to discuss the 
 earlier interpretations of the phrase. 
 
 3 This is not so strange a view as might appear. An island or a rock 
 in the ofl&ng may disappear completely when shrouded in mist (di^p), and 
 we seem to see the sky beyond it. * See above, p. 27. 
 
 
THE MILESIAN SbHOOL 69 
 
 or rings is a natural inference from the idea of the 
 vortex. 
 
 So far we seem to be justified, by the authority of Theo- 
 phrastos, in going; and, if that is so, certain further inferences 
 seem to be inevitable. In the first place, Anaximander 
 had shaken himself free of the old idea that the heavens 
 are a solid vault^., f There is nothing to prevent us from 
 seeing right out into the Boundless, and it is hard to think 
 that Anaximander did not beheve he did. The traditiai;^,, 
 cosmos has ^^nkyIjJa£^.,to a much grancto. scheme, that of 
 innumerable vortices in a boundless ^p^^^J^hich is neither 
 water nor air. In that case, it is difficult to resist the belief 
 that what we call the fixed stars were identified with the 
 " innumerable worlds " which were also " gods." It would 
 follow that the diurnal revolution is only apparent ; for 
 the stars are at unequal distances from us, and can have no 
 rotation in common. It must, then, be due to the rotation 
 of the cylindrical earth in twenty-four hours. We have 
 seen that the earth certainly shared in the rotation of 
 the BlvT}^ That gets rid of one difficulty, the wheel of 
 the *^ slars," which is between the earth and the moon ; 
 for the fixed stars could not be explained by a " wheel '* at 
 all ; a sphere would be required. What, then, are the 
 " stars " which are accounted for by this inner wheel ? I 
 venture to suggest that they are the morning ami the 
 evening stars, which, we have seen (p. 23, n. i), were 
 not recognised yet as a single luminary. In other 
 words, I believe that Anaximander regarded the , fixed 
 stars as stationary, each rotating in its own vortex.^y-^No 
 doubt this involves us in a difficulty regardi»g''*tne rota- 
 tion of the sun and the moon. It follows from the nature 
 of the vortex that they must rotate in the same direction 
 as the earth, and, on the assumption just made, that must 
 be from west to east, and it must be a slower rotation 
 than that of the earth, which is inconsistent with the fact 
 that the circumference of a vortex rotates more rapidly 
 
70 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 than the centre. That, however, is a difficulty which all 
 the Ionian cosmologists down to Demokritos had to face. 
 Holding, as they did, that the whole rotation was in the 
 same diTection,^^^,ihe^'^^t^ri^'''^m "=we- call the 
 
 ""greatest velocities were the leasj J'' The moon, for instance, 
 did not rotate so rapidly as the sun, since the sun more nearly 
 keeps up with the fixed stars. ^ That Anaximander failed 
 to observe this difficulty is not surprising, if we remember 
 that he was the first to attack the problem. Tit is not 
 immediately obvious that the centre of the ySrt'S'x must 
 have a slower niotion than the circumference, j This serves 
 to explain the origin of the theory that the heavenly bodies 
 have a rotation of their own in the opposite direction to 
 the diurnal revolution which we shall see reason for 
 attributing to Pythagoras (§ 54). 
 ^^j^wM**-^' 22. We have, in any case, seen enough to show us that 
 the speculations of Anaximander .^Q^j^fe. tb^^w^si^-mj^e of 
 
 ^3^.v>^.^tfg;S,^ly jlari^^^ charactej^ We.j?p^Oi^,,Uft55U.to the 
 crowning. ,aii3^d® ^i^f^JJC S iheory -ol thB ' ari^ qf Hving 
 creatures. The Theophrastean accoi^it ol^hi^.te^^ 
 well preserved by the doxographers : 
 
 y'^^'^lliving creatures ai»se from the moist' element as it was 
 / evaporated by the sun.J Man was like another animal, namely, 
 Va fish, in the beginning. — Hipp. Ref. i. 6 (R. P. 22 a). 
 
 The first animals were produced in the moisture, each 
 enclosed in a prickly bark. As they advanced in age, they came 
 out upon the drier part. When the bark broke off,^ they survived 
 for a short time.^ — Aet. v. 19, 4 (R. P. 22). 
 
 Further, he says that originally man was born from animals 
 of another species. His reason is that while other animals 
 
 ^ Lucretius, v. 619 sqq. 
 
 2 This is to be understood in the light of what we are told about yaXeoi 
 below. Cf. Arist. Hist. An. Z, 10. 565 a 25, rots /xey oZv ffKvXlois, oOs KoXovffl 
 TLves ve^pias yaXeovs, orap irepippay^ koL iKir^arj rb tarpaKov, flvovTat oi veorrol. 
 
 3 The true reading is ^tt' dXiyov xp^^o^ ixera^wvaL, the omission of 
 Xpovov by Diels in Vors.^ and Vors.^ being apparently a slip. In the 
 Index to Dox., Diels s.v. /xera^Lovv says " mutare vitam [cf. /ieraStaiTai/]," 
 and I followed him in my first edition. Heidel well compares Archelaos, 
 ap. Hipp. Ref. i. 9, 5 (of the first animals) 9jv 5e oXtyoxp^via. 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 71 
 
 quickly find food by themselves, man alone requires a lengthy 
 period of suckling. Hence, had he been originally as" he is npW^"'*^, 
 he would never have survived. — Ps.-Plut. Strom, fr. 2 (R. P. iBTf."*' 
 y He declares that at first human beings arose in the inside of 
 / fishes, and after having been reared like sharks,^ and become 
 ^capable of protecting themselves, they were finally cast ashore 
 and took to land. — Plut. Symp. Quaest. 730 f (R. P. ih). 
 
 / The importance of these statements has sometimes 
 Dfeen overrated and still more often underestimated. 
 Anaximander has. been called a precursor of Darwin by 
 some, while others hav^^^te^ed the whole thing as a mytho- 
 logical survival. It is therefore important to notice that 
 this is one of the rare cases where we have not merely a 
 placitum, but an indication of the observations on which it 
 was base A It is clear from tEE"tliat AnaximanaerlEiad" an 
 -id^^'oi what is meant by adaptation to ^^331 WQiUuent and 
 survival of the fittest , %nd tEat he saw _th£_highpr marhmals 
 could not retJfesent the o riginal t ype of animal. For this 
 he looked to the sea, and he naturally fixed upon those 
 fishes which present the closest analogy to the mammq}i(i,^i:.: 
 The statements of Aristotle about the galeus levis were 
 shown by Johannes Miiller to be more accurate than those 
 of later naturalists, and we now see that these observations 
 were already made by Anaximander. The way in which the ^ . 
 shark nourishes its young furnished him with the very thing 
 he required to explain the survival of the earliest animals. ^ 
 
 ^ Reading Cjairep ol yaXeoi for Cbairep ol TaXaLoi with Doehner, who 
 compares Plut. De soil. anim. 982 a, where the (pCKbaropyov of the shark is 
 described. 
 
 2 On Aristotle and the galeus levis, see Johannes Miiller, " Ueber den 
 glatten Hai des Aristoteles " {K. Preuss. Akad., 1842), to which my 
 attention was directed by my colleague, Professor D'Arcy Thompson. The 
 precise point of the words rpecpofxcpoi Sjo-irep ol yaXeoL appears from Arist, 
 Hist. An. Z, 10. 565 b I, ot 5^ Ka\ovp.€voi. \etoL rdv yaXewv tcl p.kv i^a taxovai 
 fiera^ii tCjv varepuiv ofMoius rois aKvXLoLS, irepLdTavTa ok ravra ets cKar^pav Tr,v biKpbav 
 TTis vcTT^pas KarajSalvei, Kal to. ^ipa yiveraL tov ofKpaXov ^x^^t^'- '"'P^^ '''V ^crrepq,, Cbare 
 avaXLaKOfieuwv tCjv i^dv ofxoiojs boKelv ^x^"' "^^ efi^pvov tois TeTpdvocnu. It IS not 
 necessary to suppose that Anaximander referred to the further phenomenon 
 " described by Aristotle, who more than once says that all the 7aXeot except 
 the dKav6Las " send out their young and take them back again " {e^a<pLdai 
 
72 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 HI. Anaximenes 
 
 Life. 23. Anaximenes of Miletos, son of Eurystjatos, was, 
 
 according to Theophrastos, an ** .assaciate ""of Anaximander.^ 
 Apollodoros said, it appears, that he "'36iifisTie3"'''"alDout 
 the time of the fall of Sardeis (546/5 B.C.), and died in 
 01. LXIII. (528/525' B.c.).2 In other words, he was born 
 when Thales^'iioTirished," and "flourished" when Thales 
 died, and this means that Apollodoros had no definite 
 information about his date. ^'He perhaps made him die in 
 
 \ "\ the sixty-third Olympiad because tjiat gives just three 
 generations for the Milesian school.^ |j We cannot therefore 
 say anything positive as to his datd, except that he must 
 have been younger than Anaximander. "I 
 
 s book. 24. Anaximenes wrote a book which survived until the 
 
 age of literary criticism ;^ for we are told that he used a 
 
 . simple^ j.H(i. iiiapr«t€«tiou's ftmioj.^,.. very diffejzqjgijt;^^ we J3ciay 
 
 ; suppose,, from, the. poetical ..prose of Anaxipa^dei:^,?,,,! The 
 
 , speculations of Anaximander were distinguished for their 
 
 f hardihood a^d breast Ji./-' those of Anaximenes are marked 
 
 by 'the opposite quality. He appears to have thought 
 
 out his system carefully, but he rejects the more audacious 
 
 theories of his predecessor. The result is that, while his 
 
 view of the world is less like the truth than Anaximander's, 
 
 Kal dexovrai els eavTods roi/s vcottovs, ib. 565 b 23), for which compare also 
 Ael. i. 17 ; Plut. De amore prolis 494 c ; De soil. anim. 982 a. The 
 placenta and umbilical cord described by Johannes Miiller will account 
 sufficiently for all he says. 
 
 1 Theophr. Phys. Op. fr. 2 (R. P. 26). 
 
 2 This follows from a comparison of Diog. ii. 3 with Hipp. Ref. i. 7 
 (R. P. 23) and Souidas (s.v.). In Hippolytos we must, however, read 
 Tpirou for irpuiTov with Diels. The suggestion in R. P. 23 e that Apollodoros 
 mentioned the Olympiad without giving the number of the year is in- 
 adequate ; for Apollodoros did not reckon by Olympiads, but Athenian 
 archons. 
 
 3 Jacoby (p. 194) brings the date into connexion with the floruit 
 Pythagoras, which seems to me less probable. 
 
 4 Diog. ii. 3 (R. P. 23). 
 
 5 Cf. the statement of Theophrastos above, § 13. 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 73 
 
 « 
 it is perhaps more fruitful in ideas that were destined to 
 
 hold their ground. 
 
 25. Anaximenes is one of the philosophers on whomjheory. 
 
 Theophrastos_^ja^^ote a special monograph ; ^ and this gives primary 
 
 ,11s an" additional guarantee for the trustworthiness of the ^^^^.^^°^®* 
 
 i tradition. The following ^ are the passages which contain 
 
 I the fullest account of the central feature of his system : 
 
 "'kj^' Anaximenes of Miletos, son of Eurystratos, who had been an 
 ■'associate of Anaximander, said, Uke hiip.,. that the underlying 
 
 :substance was one aM i.nfrmte.'./He did not, However, say it 
 
 was indet^rpiiiiai^eriike Anaximander, but determinate ; for he 
 '•^ said it wa^^^^J-Phys. Op. fr. 2 (R. P. 26). 
 
 From itT'Ke said, the things that are, and have been, and shall 
 
 be, the gods an4 things divine,^ took their ris^ while other things 
 
 come from its offspring.— Hipp. Ref.i.y{R. P. 28). 
 
 " Just as," he said, " our soul, being air, holds us together, 
 
 so do breath and air encompass the whole world." — Aet. i. 3, 4 
 
 And the form of the air is as follows. Where it is most.eve»j •'«'^'^.^;|^'** ^ \ 
 it is invisible to our sie^ht^; but cold and heat, moisture and /If ^ 
 motion, make it visible. J It is always in mojti(5in;,v4pr, if it were 
 not, it would not change ^o "much as it does.-J-Hipp. Ref. i. 7 
 (R. P. 28). 
 
 /""" It differs in different substances in virtue of its rarefaction 
 (and condensation. — Phys. Op. fr. 2 (R. P. 26). 
 
 When it is dilated so as to be rarer, it becomes fire ; while 'i 
 winds, on the other hand, are condensed Air. Cloud is formed l 
 from Air by felting ; ^ and this, still furth*er 'Condensed, becomes '^ 
 water. \ Water, condensed still more, turns to earth ; and when 
 condensed as much as it can be, to stones. — Hipp,,.R^. i. 7 
 (R. P. 28). ,.,.,.....-..-^^--- ' ' 
 
 2:6rvAt first, this looks like a falling off from the more^Rarefac- 
 reiined doctrine of Anaximander to a cruder view\ but this ^i^-^j'^^^l' 
 is not really the case. On the contrary, the introauction oli^^- 
 rarefaction and condensation into the theory is a notable 
 
 ^ On these monographs, see Dox. p. 103. 
 
 2 See the conspectus of extracts from Theophrastos given in Dox. p. 135. 
 ^ " Felting " [iriXTjaL^) is the regular term for this process with all the 
 early cosmologistsTiySmVhom Plato has taken it (Tim. 58 b 4 ; 76 c 3). 
 
74 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 advance.^ In fact, it makes the Milesian cosmology con- 
 
 ,.' iistent for the first time/ since a theory which explains 
 
 :' /everything as a form of a'Singk.5JljOtista»6^ts'~"CteaFly.,bound 
 
 ,' 4. to regard all differences as guantitative.^^^he only way to 
 
 '];. sa ve the uni ty ol the_priinary siiBstance is to say theiLall 
 
 ,,>*'^ J' di versities are due to the presence of more or less of it in 
 
 / j5 ! ^T^en^space. !|^nd when once this step has been taken, 
 
 I I I It is no longer necessary to make the primary substance 
 
 I .| I Something " distinct from the elements," to use Aristotle's 
 
 I ;' / inaccurate but convenient phrase ; it may just as well be 
 
 t bne^glthem. 
 Air. y' 27. The air Anaximenes speaks of includes a good deal 
 / that we should not call by the name. In its normal con- 
 dition, when most evenly distributed, it is invisible, and it 
 then corresponds to our ** air " ; it is the breath we inhale 
 and the wind that blows. That is why he called it irvevfia^ 
 On the other hand, the old idea that mist or vapour is 
 I condensed air, is still accepted without question. It was 
 f^Empedokles,|we shall see, \yho first discovered that what 
 we "call' air was a distinct corporeaf stflManceV ^nd not 
 identical either with vapour or with empty space. / In the 
 earher cosmologists " air " is alwa5^s a form of vapour, and 
 even darkness is a form of " air.' j It wa^^Emp^^^okleswho 
 cleared up, this point too by showing that darkness is a 
 shadow. 2 I 
 
 1 Simplicius, Phys. p. 149, 32 (R. P. 26 b), says that Theophrastos 
 spoke of rarefaction and condensation in the case of Anaximenes alone. 
 It should be noted, however, that Aristotle, Phys. A, 4. 187 a 12, seems 
 imply that Anaximander too had spoken of rarefaction and condenss 
 tion, especially if 6 eVn irvpbs fikv irvKvbTepov d^pos 8k XeirTOTepov is referred 
 him. On the other hand, at 20, ol 8' 4k rod evbs ivovaas ras epavrtoTrjTd 
 iKKpiveadai, ibairep 'Ava^i/xapSpos (f)rjat seems to be opposed to a 12, oi fxkv kt^ 
 As I have indicated already, it looks as if we were dealing here wit 
 Aristotle's own inferences and interpretations, which are far from clej 
 They are outweighed by the definite statement quoted by SimpUcius froi 
 Theophrastos, though Simplicius himself adds 8ri\op 8k tbs /cai ol &\\ol t^ 
 fmpoTTiTL Kal TTVKPOTTjTi ixP'^^To. That, howcvcr, is only his own inference^ 
 from Aristotle's somewhat confused statement. 
 
 2 For the meaning of d??p in Homer, cf, e.g. Od. viii. i, 7j4pi Kai p( 
 K€Ka\vfji,fA4pai ; and for its survival in Ionic prose, Hippokrates, 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 75 
 
 It was natural for Anaximenes to fix upon " air " as the 
 primary substance ; for, in the system of Anaximander, it 
 f occupied an intermediate place between the two fun'Sa- * 
 
 mental opposites, the ring of flame and the cold, moist J\qO^^^ 
 mass within it. .(§ 19). We know from Plutarch that he - ^j t^^^"'^ 
 fancie3 air became warmer when rarefied, and colder when 
 condensed, '{jOf this he satisfied himself by a curious -- 
 experimental proof. When we breathe with our mouthsTT"*/ ■ 
 open, the air is warm ; when our lips are closed, it is cold.V^?*^: 
 
 28. This argument brings us to an important point m The world 
 the theory, which is attested by the single fragment that ^£^.^*^^^* 
 has come down to us.^ " Just as our soul, being air, holds 
 us together, so do breath and air encompass the whole\^ 
 The primary substance bears the same relation 
 
 to the hfe of the world as to that of man. \ Now this was the 
 Pythagorean viaw >^ and it is al^o ah early instance of 
 the argument from the microcosm to the macrocosm, and 
 SO marks the beginning of an interest in physiological 
 matters. 
 
 29. We turn now to the doxographical tradition con- The parts 
 cerning the formation of the world and its parts : world. 
 
 He says that, as the air was felted, the earth first came into 
 being. It is very broad and is accordingly supported by tbe^,..,. 
 air.— Ps.-Plut. StronLlr.'s (R. P. 25). 
 
 In the same way the sun and the moon and the other heavenly 
 bodies, which are of ^ fiery nature, are supported by the air 
 
 d^ptav, vSdroov, Tbiriav, 15, ai^p re ■7roXi>s /car^xei tt]v x^PV^ *^^^ '^^'^ vSariov. 
 Plato is still conscious of the old meaning ; for he makes Timaios say 
 d^pos {y^vTf) rb fikv evayia-raTov iwiKk-qv aldT]p KaXoOfxevos, 6 5k doXepdoraros 
 ofiixXrj Kal <tk6tos {Tim. 58 d). For the identification of 0,17^ with darkness, 
 of. Plut. De prim. frig. 948 e, 6tl 5' aTjp to Trpwrws aKOTeivbv ianu ovde 
 Toits iroi7}Tct,s XiXrjdev • dlpa ydp rb cTKbros KoXovaiu. My view has been 
 criticised by Tannery, " Une nouvelle hypothese sur Anaximandre " 
 (Arch. viii. pp. 443 sqq.), and I have slightly altered my expression of it 
 to meet these criticisms. The point is of fundamental importance for 
 the interpretation of Pythagoreanism. 
 
 ^ Plut. De prim. frig. 947 f (R. P. 27), where we are told that he used 
 the term rb xo-^o.pov for the rarefied air. 
 
 2 Aet. i. 3, 4 (R. P. 24). 3 See Chap. II. § 53. 
 
76 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 {.^because of their breadtfc^ The heavenly bodies were produced 
 
 from tifieeaftli 15^1^^^ rising from it.) When this is rarefied, 
 
 fire comes into being, and the stars are'^tomposed of the fire thus 
 
 raised aloft. There were also bodies of earthy su|Dstance in the 
 
 region of the stars, revolving along with them| f And he says 
 
 that the heavenly bodies do not move under the earth, as others 
 
 suppose, but round it, as a cap turns round our head.t f The sun 
 
 is hidden from sight, not because it goes under the earth, but 
 
 because it is concealed by the higher parts of the earth, and 
 
 k because its distance from us becomes greater|\ The,,„»fe«FS give 
 
 || no heat because of the greatness of their distance.^Hipp. Ref. i. 
 
 i 7, 4-6 (R. P. 28). -■''^>s...J 
 
 /'*' Winds are produced when air is condensed and rushes along 
 
 ( under propulsion ; but when it is concentrated and thickened 
 
 I still more, clouds are generated ; and, lastly, it turns to water. ^ 
 "'v— Hipp. Ref. i. 7, 7 {Dox. p. 561). ^.^^,^^^<^-^^^^^'^^'^—-- 
 
 The stars [are fixed like nails in the crystalline vault of the 
 heavens, but some say they] are fiery leaves, like paintings.^ — 
 Aet. ii. 14, 3 {Dox. p. 344). 
 
 They do not go under the earth, but turn round it. — lb. 16, 6 
 
 (Dox. p. 34S). n:— . .,., 
 
 \ The sun is fiery .--^/&. 20, 2 [Dox. p. 348). 
 
 It-isbrbad Uke a leaf. 4-/6. 22, i {Dox. p. 352). 
 
 The heavenly bodies turn back in their courses ^ owing to the 
 resistance of compressed air. — lb. 23, i {Dox. p. 352). 
 
 The moon is of fire^.,^/6. 25, 2 {Dox. p. 356). 
 
 Anaximenes explaine4... lightning like Anaximander, adding 
 las' an illustration what happens in the case of the sea, which 
 flashes when divided by the oars. — lb. iii. 3, 2 {Dox. p. 368). 
 
 Hail is produced when water freezes in falling ; snow, when 
 tjbere is some air imprisoned in the water. — Aet. iii. 4, i {Dox. 
 
 A 370). 
 
 f^ Jhe rainbow is produced when the beams of the sun fall on 
 thick condensed aiiJ Hence the anterior part of it seems rafi, 
 being burnt by the sun's rays, while the other part is dark, 
 
 ^ The text is very corrupt here. I retain eKireirvKvufi^os, because|\ve 
 are told above that winds are condensed air. 
 
 ^ See below, p. 77, n. 4. 
 
 3 This can only refer to the Tpowai of the sun, though it is loosely 
 stated of rd aarpa generally. It occurs in the chapter Ilepl rpoiruv r,\lovj 
 and we cannot interpret it as if it were a detached statement. 
 
 i 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 77 
 
 'owing to the predominance of moisture. And he says that a 
 
 rainbow is produced at night by the moon, but not often, because 
 
 there is not constantly a full moon, and because the moon's light 
 
 is weaker than that of the sun. — Schol. Arat} (Dox. p. 231). 
 
 The earth was like a table in shape. — Aet. iii. 10, 3 (Dox. 
 
 p. 377)- 
 
 The cause of earthquakes was the dryness and moisture of \ 
 
 the earth, occasioned by droughts and heavy rains respectively, j 
 
 —lb. 15, 3 (Dox. p. 379). ■ 
 
 We have seen that Anaximenes was justified in going 
 back to Thales in regard to the nature of primary substance ; 
 but the effect upon the details of his cosmology was unfor- 
 tunate. / The earth is once more imagined as a table-like 
 disc fioatm'g on tlie air. ) The sun, moon, and stars are also 
 fiery discs which float 'on the air " Hke leaves *' ; an idea 
 naturally suggested by the " eddy*' (8ivv)/ It follows that 
 the heavenly bodies cannot go under the earth at night, as 
 U.naximander must have held, but only round it laterally 
 life a' cap" or a millstone.^ This view is also mentioned in 
 Aristotle's Meteorology y^ where the elevation of the northern 
 parts of the earth, which makes it possible for the heavenly 
 bodies to be hidden from sight, is referred to. This is only 
 meant to explain why the stars outside the Arctic circle 
 appear to rise and set, and the explanation is fairly adequate 
 if we remember that the world is regarded as rotating in a 
 plane. It is quite inconsistent with the theory of a celestial 
 sphere.* 
 
 1 The source of this is Poseidonios, who used Theophrastos. Dox. 
 p. 231. 
 
 2 Theodoret (iv. i6) speaks of those who believe in a revolution like that 
 of a miUstone, as contrasted with one like that of a wheel. Diels (Dox. 
 p. 46) refers these similes to Anaximenes and Anaximander respectively. 
 They come, of course, from Actios (Note on Sources, § lo), though they 
 are given neither by Stobaios nor in the Placita. 
 
 * B. I. 354 a 28 (R. P. 28 c). 
 
 * For this reason, I now reject the statement of Actios, ii. 14, 3 (p. 76), 
 ' Xvaiiifxhr^s -ffkiav 5iK-qv KaTaireir-qyivai t<^ KpvaraWoeidel. That there is some 
 confusion of names here is strongly suggested by the words which 
 immediately follow, ivLOi 8k Tr^raXa ehai irvpiva ibairep to. ^a>7/)a077/xaTa, 
 which is surely the genuine doctrine of Anaximenes. I understand 
 
 \ 
 
78 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 / 
 
 Innumelp 
 
 Influence 
 of Anaxi- 
 menes. 
 
 ^- v., ^^^ earthy bodies, which circulate among the planets, 
 are doubtless intended to account for eclipses and the phases 
 of the moon.^ 
 
 30. As might be expected, there is much the same 
 difficulty about the ** innumerable worlds " ascribed to 
 Anaximenes as there is about those of Anaximander. The 
 evidence, however, is far less satisfactory, l Cicero says 
 that Anaximenes regarded air as a god, and adds that 
 it came into being. ^ That cannot be right. Air, as the 
 primary substance, is certainly eternal, and it is quite hkely 
 that Anaximenes called it " divine," as Anaximander did 
 the Boundless ; but it is certain that he also spoke of gods 
 who came into being and passed awayr' These arose, he 
 said, from the air. This is expressly stated by Hippotytos,^ 
 and also by St. Augustine.* These gods are probably to 
 be explained like Anaximander's. Simplicius, indeed, takes 
 another view ; but he may have been misled by a Stoic 
 authority.^ 
 
 31. It is not easy for us to reaUse that, in the eyes of his 
 contemporaries, and for long after, Anaximenes was a much 
 more important figure than Anaximander.! And yet the 
 fact is certain. We shall see that Pythagoras, though he 
 followed Anaximander in his account of the heavenly bodies,) 
 
 ^ojypaip-fifxaTa of the constellations (cf. Plato, Tim. 55 c). To regard the stars 
 as fixed to a crystalline sphere is quite inconsistent with the far better 
 attested doctrine that they do not go under the earth. 
 
 1 See Tannery, Science hellene, p. 153. For the precisely similar bodies 
 assumed by Anaxagoras, see below. Chap. VI. § 135. See further Chap. 
 VII. § 151. 
 
 2 Cic. De nat. d.i. 26 (R. P. 28 b). 
 
 3 Hipp. Ref. i. 7, i (R. P. 28). 
 
 * Aug. De civ. D. viii. 2 : " Anaximenes omnes rerum causas infinite 
 aeri dedit : nee deos negavit aut tacuit ; non tamen ab ipsis aerem factum, 
 sed ipsos ex aere ortos credidit " (R. P. 28 b). 
 
 6 Simpl. Phys. p. 1121, 12 (R. P. 28 a). The passage from the Placita 
 is of higher authority than this from Simplicius. It is only to Anaximenes, 
 Herakleitos, and Diogenes that successive worlds are ascribed even here. 
 For the Stoic view of Herakleitos, see Chap. III. § 78 ; and for Diogenes, 
 Chap. X. § 188. That Simplicius is following a Stoic authority is suggested 
 by the words kolI varepov ol dirb r^y Sroas. 
 
THE MILESIAN SCHOOL 
 
 79 
 
 was far more indebted to Anaximenes for his general theory 
 of the world (§ 53). We shall see further that when, at a 
 later date, science revivCT'lSft'Ce inorie" in Ionia, it was " thev 
 philosophy of Anaximenes " to which it attached^,, itself >4 
 (§ 122). Anaxagoras adopted many of his most character- 
 istic views 1(5'T35), and so did the Atomists.^ Diogenes of 
 Apollonia went back to the central doctrine of Anaximenes, 
 and made Air the primary substance, though he also tried 
 to combine it with the theories of Anaxagoras (§ 188). We 
 shall come to all this later ; but it seemed desirable to point 
 out at once that Anaximenes marks the culminating point 
 of the line of thought which started with Thales, and to 
 show how the_.';,^hiJospp]^yjDf Anaxime« nieari 
 
 the Milesian doctrine as a whole. \ This it can only have 
 done because it was really the Work of a school, of which 
 Anaximenes was the last distinguished representative, and 
 because his contribution to it was one that completed the 
 system he had inherited from his predecessors. That the 
 theory of rarefaction and condensation was really such a 
 completion of the Milesian system, we have seen^(l 26), and 
 it need only be added that a clear realisation of this fact will 
 be the best clue at once to the understanding of the Milesian 
 cosmology itself and to that of the systems which followed 
 it. In the main, it is from Anaximenes they all start. 
 
 »iH>vf««--'^»>ifgf < 
 
 ^ In particular, both Leukippos and Demokritos adhered to his theory 
 of a flat earth. Cf. Aet. iii. 10, 3-5 {Uepl cxvI^tos yijs), ' kva^Lfiivq^ rpaire- 
 ^0€i8rj {ttjv yijv). Aei^/ftTTTTOs TVfjLTrapoeidrj. Arj/j^KpiTOi SiaKoeiSij /xh t($ TrXdret, 
 kolXtju d^ tQi /x^(r(f}. And yet the spherical form of the earth was already a 
 commonplace in circles affected by Pythagoreanism. 
 
CHAPTER II 
 
 SCIENCE AND RELIGION 
 
 Ionia an/ 32. The Spirit of the lonians in Asia was, as we have 
 the werft. gggjj^ thoroughly secular J and, so far as we can judge, the 
 Milesians wholly ignored traditional behefs.f Their use of 
 the term " god " for the primary substance aijd,jyh.e inliumer- 
 ableworids had no religious significance.^ It was different 
 m-4h;eu|AegeaLnL M the home of the 
 
 lonians iong"l)ef6re '^the AnatoUan coasts were open to 
 colonisation, and where there were many memories of a 
 remote past. These seem to have centred round the 
 Isanctuary of Delos,|and the fragments(of Pherekyd^, who 
 iBelonge3"'to the neighbouring island /of' Syros^fead like 
 belated utterances of an earUer a^e^J. ^c) SouSt'^it was also 
 different in the Chalkidian and Ionian colonies of the West, 
 which were founded at a time when Hesiod and his followers 
 sti^l held unchallenged authority. 
 
 ^.Now .PxtU^9^^^-^^^i?^^^^P^^^ ^^^ most striking 
 figures of the generation that saw tne Greek cities in Asia 
 become subject to PersiaJ^wei;§^both Ipni^^ but both spent 
 rthe greater part of their lives in the West. There it was no 
 longer possible to ignore rehgion, especially when reinforced 
 by the revival that now swept over the Greek world. 
 Henceforth the leaders of enUghtenment must either seek 
 to reform and deepen traditional religion, Hke Pytha^Qras, 
 or oppose it openly, Hke Xenophanes. { 
 
 1 See p. 14. /' ^ See p. 3. 
 
 80 
 
 I 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION Si 
 
 33 The revival was not, however, a mere recrudescence The 
 of the old Aegean religion, but was profoundly influenced rrn^m. 
 by the diffusion of certain ideas originating in what was then ' '" 
 the far North. The temple legend of Delos is certainly 
 ancient, and it connects the worship of Apollo witji..,l;he 
 HyperboreajC^S5viKho were thought of as living on ttie banfe... . 
 oTlfKe Danube.^; The "holy things wrapped in straw,"- 
 which were p'kssed on from people to people till they reached 
 Delos by way of the head of th4^ Adriatic, Dodona^ and the 
 \Malian Gulf; ^ bear witness to a rearcb'Mieifo'n' between the 
 DanuBiah and Aegean civilisations at an early date, and it 
 is natural to associate this with the coming of the Achaians. 
 The stories of t Abaris the HyperbQreai^ .'^= and Aristeas of 
 Prokonnes9§,i,i>€long to the same religious movement and 
 prove that it was based on a view of the soul which was 
 new, so far as we can see, in the Aegean. , Now the connexion 
 of Pythagoras with Delos is well attested, and it is certain 
 that he founded his society in cities which gloried in the 
 Achaian name. If the Delian religion was rean;y^,Achd 
 we have a clue to certain things in the life of Pythagoras 
 which are otherwise puzzUng. We shall come back to these 
 later.5 
 
 34. It was not, ho.wever, in its Dehan form that the orphicism. 
 northern rehgion had most influence. ^ Thr^jgf/it had 
 attached itself to the wild worship of Dionysos, and was 
 associated with the name of Orpheus. In this religion the 
 new beliefs were mainly based on the phenomenon of 
 "ecstasy" (|«:o-Taor(j§^_ " stepping out"). It was supposed 
 that it was only when " out of the body " that the soul 
 revealed its true nature. It was not merely a feeble double I 
 of the self, as in Homer, but a fallen god, which might be/ 
 
 ^ Pindar, 01. iii. 14-16. 
 
 2 Herod, iv. 33. Cf. Farnell, Cults of the Greek States, iv. pp. 99 sqq. 
 
 ' . Herod, iv. 36. 
 
 * Ibid. iv. 13-15. 
 
 5 I have discussed the origin of the Pythagorist religion in the Ency- 
 clopaedia of Religion and Ethics {s.v. Pythagoras) rather more fully than 
 would be appropriate here. 
 
 6 
 
,z EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 restored to its high estate by a system of " purifications " 
 (/ca^a^^ot)^^nd sacraments (opq^faj. ,. In this form, the new 
 religion made an immediate appeal to all sorts and condi- 
 tions of men who could not find satisfaction in the worship 
 ^oi the secularised anthropomorphic gods of the poets and 
 t^ state reUgions. 
 
 The Orphic religion had two features which were new 
 
 \ in Greece. \ It looked to a written revelation as the source 
 
 of religious authority, and its adherents were organised in 
 
 communities, based, not on any real or supposed tie of 
 
 blood, but on voluntary adhesion and initi^tj^^^w -Most of 
 
 the Orphic hterature that has come down to us is of late 
 
 date and uncertain origin, but the thin gold , plates, with 
 
 Orphic verses inscribed on them, discovered at Thoi^ioi 
 
 \^and Petelia;take us back to a time when Orphicism was still 
 
 a living creed. ^ From them we learn that it had some 
 
 striking resemblances to the beliefs prevalent in India 
 
 about the same time, though it is really impossible to 
 
 assume any Indian influence in Greece at this date.^ In 
 
 I any case, the main purpose of the Orphic observances and 
 
 ^ rites was to release the soul from the " wheel of birth," that 
 
 Iis, from reincarnation in animal or vegetable forms. The 
 soul so released became once more a god and enjoyed 
 '*^iB¥€rlasting bliss, 
 phiio- 35. The chief reason for taking account of the Orphic 
 
 Tway of communities here is that their organisation seems to have 
 
 life. 
 
 ^ For these gold plates, see the Appendix to Miss Harrison's Prolego- 
 mena to the Study of Greek Religion, where the texts are discussed and 
 translated by Professor Gilbert Murray. 
 
 2 The earliest attested case of a Greek coming under Indian influence 
 is that of Pyrrho of Elis (see my article " Scepticism " in the Ency- 
 clopaedia of Religion and Ethics). I venture to suggest that the religious 
 ideas referred to may have reached India from the same northern source 
 as they reached Greece, a source which we may vaguely call "Scythian." 
 If, as Caesar tells us {B.G. vi. 14, 5), the Gallic Druids taught the doctrine 
 of transmigration, this suggestion is strongly confirmed. The theories of 
 L. von Schroeder {Pythagoras und die Inder, 1884) are based on a mis- 
 taken view of Pythagoreanism, and appear also to involve chronological 
 impossibilities. See A. Berriedale Keith, " Pythagoras and the Doctrine 
 of Transmigration " {Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society, 1909, pp. 569 sqq,). 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 83 
 
 suggested the idea that philosophy is a}5pye,,a4Lv^,-'i^ . 
 
 hfe." In Ionia, as we have seenV^tX^j^oc^/a nieant some- , 
 thing hke '* curiosity,'* and from that use of it the common 
 Athenian sense of " culture," as we find it in Isokrates, 
 seems to have been derived. On the other hand, wherever 
 we can trace the influence of Pythagoras, the word has a 
 far deeper meaning. Philosophy is itself a " purification " 
 and a way of escape from the " wheel." That j,^.^tfeevidaa..... 
 so nobly expressed in the Phaedo, which is manifestly S 
 inspired by Pythagorean doctrine^J This way of regarding 
 philosophy is henceforth characteristic of the best Greek 
 thought. I Aristotle is as much influenced by it as any one, 
 as we ma^ see from the Tenth Book of the Ethics, and as we 
 should see still more clearly if we possessed hisIl^a^f^ew^iK^H'''' 
 in its entirety. 2 There was a danger that this attitude 
 should degenerate into mere quietism and " otherworldli- 
 ness," a danger Plato saw and sought to avert. It was he 
 TIiaF Insisted on philosophers taking their turn to descend 
 once more into the Cave to help their former fellow- 
 prisoners. ^ If the other view ultimately prevailed, that 
 was hardly the fault of the philosophers. 
 
 /^36. Science, then, became a reUgion, and to that extent Relation 
 jti is true that philosophy was influenced by religion. It andVhiio" 
 Vdtild be wrong, however, to suppose that even now philo- ^^P^y- 
 sophy took over any particular doctrines from religion. 
 The rehgious revival implied, we have seen, a new view 
 of the soul, and we might expect to find that it profoundly 
 influenced the teaching of philosophers on that subject. 
 The remarkable thing is that this did not happen. Even 
 the Pythagoreans and Empedokles, who took part in the 
 
 1 The Phaedo is dedicated, as it were, to the Pythagorean community 
 at Phleious. Plato speaks in Rep. x. 600 b of Pythagoras as the originator 
 of a private 656s tls ^lov. Cf. the arpa-jros of Phaed. 66 b. 
 
 2 For the UpoTpeTrrcKos, see Bywater in /. Phil. ii. p. 35. It was the 
 original of Cicero's Hortensius, which had such an effect on Augustine. 
 
 3 Plato, Rep. 520 c i, KaralSareov odv iv fj.4pei. The Allegory of the 
 Cave seems clearly to be of Orphic origin (Stewart, Myths of Plato, p. 252, 
 n. 2). 
 
84 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 religious movement themselves, held views about the soul 
 which flatly contradicted the beliefs impHed in their religious 
 practices.^V There is no room for an immortal soul in any 
 philosophy of this period, as we shall see^ Sokrates was the 
 irst philosopher to assert the doctrine on rational grounds,^ 
 md it is significant that Plato represents him as only half 
 ierious in appealing to the Orphics for confirmation of his 
 diwn teaching.^ 
 
 The reason is that ancient religion was not a body of 
 doctrine. Nothing was required but that the ritual should 
 be performed correctly and in a proper frame of mind ; the 
 worshipper was free to give any explanation of it he pleased. 
 It might be as exalted as that of Pindar and Sophokles or 
 as debased as that of the itinerant mystery-mongers described 
 in Plato's Republic. " The initiated," said Aristotle, " are 
 not supposed to learn anything, but to be affected in a certain 
 way and put into a certain frame of mind." * That is why 
 the religious revival could inspire philosophy with a new 
 spirit, but could not at first graft new doctrines on it. 
 
 I. Pythagoras of Samos 
 
 37. It is not easy to give any account of Pythagoras 
 that can claim to be regarded as historical. ^ The earliest 
 reference to him, indeed, is practically a "contemporary one. 
 Some verses are quoted from Xenophanes, in which we are 
 told that Pythagoras once heard a dog howling and appealed 
 to its master not to beat it, as he recognised the voice of a 
 departed friend.4 From this we know that he taught the 
 
 1 For Empedokles, see § 117 ; for the Pythagoreans, see § 149. 
 
 2 I have discussed this point fully in " The Socratic Doctrine of the 
 Soul " {Proceedings of the British Academy, 1915-16, p. 235). 
 
 * Plato, Phaed. 69 c 3, Kal KivdweOovcri Kal oi ras reXerdj ij/iiv oProt 
 K9LTa(TT-f}<TavT€$ ov (paOXoL Tives etvai, dXXd r^J 6vti iraXai alvlrreadaL kt\. The 
 irony of this and similar passages should be unmistakable. 
 
 * Arist. fr. 45 (1483 a 19), tovs reXov/xiuovs ov fiadeiv tl deiv, dXXd iradeTv 
 /cat diaTedrjpau 
 
 5 Xenophanes, fr. 7. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 85 
 
 doctrine of transmigration .^ Herakleitos, in the next 
 gmefatfon;^speal£s"^of h^ having carried scientific:, Jnvesti- 
 gation (fo-TopLT)) further than any one, though h^ made use 
 of it for purposes of imposture.^ Later, though still within 
 the century, Herodotos ^ speaks of him as " not the weakest, 
 scientific man (arocj^io-rri^;) among the Hellenesy' and he says 
 he had been told by the Greeks of the Hellespont that the 
 legendary Scythian SalmQ^^is had been a slave of Pythagoras 
 at Samos. He does not believe that ; for he knew Salmoxis 
 Hved many years before Pythagoras. The story, however, 
 is evidence that Pythagoras was well known in the fifth 
 century, both as a scientific man and as a preacher of 
 immortality. That takes us some way. 
 
 Plato was^'deeply interested in P;^thagor^9J|^i^n|^.,^]b^^^^ 
 is curiously reseTveS lBoS""l*ythagbras,| He only mentions 
 him once by name in all his writings; and all we are told then 
 is that he won the affections of his followers in an unusual 
 degree [hLa(^ep6vT(o^ r^^airrjOrj) by teaching them a ** way 
 of fife," which was still called Pythagorean.^ Even the 
 Pythagoreans are only once mentioned by name, in the 
 passage where Sokrates is made to say that they regard 
 music and astronomy as sister sciences.* On the other 
 hand, Plato tells us a good deal about men whom we know 
 from other sources to have been Pythagoreans, but he 
 avoids the name. For all he says, we should only have been 
 able to guess that EchekraX^,,|Lnd Philolaos belonged to 
 the school. Usually "Pythagorean views" aife given anony- 
 mously, as those of " ingenious persons " {/co/jLyjroL Tive<;) or 
 the like, and we are not even told expressly that Timaios the 
 Lokrian, into whose mouth Plato has placed an unmistak- 
 ^isfy 'Pythagorean cosmology, belonged to the society. We 
 are left to infer it from the fact that he comes from Italy. 
 Aristotle imitates his master's reserve in this matter. The 
 
 1 Herakleitos, fr. 17. For the meaning given to KaKOTexvirj, see note 
 in loc. 
 
 2 Herod, iv. 95. 
 
 3 Plato, Rep. X. 600 b. * Ibid. vii. 530 d. 
 
86 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 name of Pythagoras occurs only twice in the genuine works 
 that have come down to us. In one place we are told 
 that ^Alkmaion was a young man in the old age of Pytha- 
 goras/ ana tHe'^bther is a quotation from AJIgd^ja3aft4o the 
 effect that " the men of Italy honoured Pythagoras." ^ 
 Aristotle is not so shy of the word " Pythagorean " as 
 Plato, but he uses it in a curious way. He says such things 
 as " the men of Italy who are called Pythagoreans," ^ and 
 he usually refers to particular doctrines as those of " some 
 of the Pythagoreans." It looks as if there was some doubt 
 in the fourth century as to who the genuine Pythagoreans 
 were. We shall see why as we go on. 
 
 Aristotle also wrote a special treatise on the Pythagoreans 
 which has not come down to us, but from which quotations 
 are found in later writers. These are of great value, as 
 they have to do with the religious side of Pythagoreanism. 
 
 The only other ancient authorities on Pythagoras were 
 Aristoxenos oi,Tara%-Dikaiarchos of Messene, and Timaios 
 of Taliromenion, who all had special opportunities of 
 knowing something about him. The account of the Pytha- 
 gorean Order in the Life of Pythagoras by lamblichos is 
 based mainly on Timaios,^ who was no doubt an uncritical 
 historian, but who had access to information about Italy 
 and Sicily which makes his testimony very valuable when 
 it can be recovered. Aristoxenos had been personally 
 acquainted with the last generation of the Pythagorean 
 society at Phleious/ It is evident, however, that he wished 
 to represent Pytliagoras simply as a man of science, and 
 was anxious to refute the idea that he was a religious teacher. 
 In the same way, Dikaiarchos tried to make out that 
 Pythagoras was simply a statesman and reformer.^ 
 
 1 Arist. Met. A, 5. 986 a 29. 2 Arist. Rhet. B, 23. 1398 b 14. 
 
 3 Cf. e.g. Met. A, 5. 985 b 23 ; De caelo, B, 13. 293 a 20. 
 
 * See Rostagni, " Pitagora e i Pitagorici in Timeo " {Atti della R. 
 Academia delle Scienze di Torino, vol. 49 (1913-14), pp. 373 sqq. 
 
 6 See E. Rohde's papers, " Die Quellen des lamblichos in seiner Bio- 
 graphie des Pythagoras," in Rh. Mus. xxvi. and xxvii. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 87 
 
 When we come to the Lives of Pythagoras, by Porphyry, 
 lambHchos, and Diogenes Laertios/ we find ourselves once 
 more in the region of the miraculous. They are based on 
 authorities of a very suspicious character, ^ and the result 
 is a mass of incredible fiction. It would be quite wrong, 
 however, to ignore the miraculous elements in the legend of 
 Pythagoras ; for some of the most striking miracles are 
 quoted from Aristotle's work on the Pythagoreans ^ and 
 from the Tripod of Andron of Ephesos,* both of which 
 belong to the fourth century B.C., and cannot have been 
 influenced by Neopythagorean fancies. The fact is that 
 the oldest and the latest accounts agree in representing 
 Pythagoras as a wonder-worker ; but, for some reason, an 
 attempt was made in the fourth century to save his memory 
 from that imputation. This helps to account for the 
 cautious references of Plato and Aristotle, but its full 
 significance will only appear later. 
 
 38. We may be said to know for certain t^Q^, JJ^j^thagoras Life of 
 passed his early manhood at Samos, and was the son of gjras! 
 Mnesarchos ; ^ andTi'e ^"ffounsKed,** we are told, in the reign 
 
 "^•^ Porphyry's Life of Pythagoras is the only considerable extract from 
 his History of Philosophy that has survived. The Life by lamblichos has 
 been edited by Nauck (1884). 
 
 2 lamblichos made a compilation from the arithmetician Nikomachos 
 of Gerasa and the romance of Apollonios of Tyana. Porphyry used 
 Nikomachos and Antonius Diogenes, who wrote a work called Marvels 
 from beyond Thule, which is parodied in Lucian's Vera Historia. 
 
 3 It is Aristotle who told how Pythagoras killed a deadly snake by 
 biting it, how he was seen at Kroton and Metapontion at the same time, 
 how he exhibited his golden thigh at Olympia, and how he was addressed 
 by a voice from heaven when crossing the river Kasas. It was also 
 Aristotle who preserved the valuable piece of information that the Kro- 
 toniates identified Pythagoras with Apollo Hyperboreios, and that the 
 Pythagoreans had a division of the XoyiKou ^<$ov into rb fih . . . 6e6s, to di 
 dudpojiros, TO 5e oToi^ 1X1/^076^0$. For these and other statements of the 
 same kind, see Diels, Vors. 4, 7. It looks as if Aristotle took special 
 pains to emphasise this aspect of Pythagoras out of opposition to the 
 later Pythagoreans who tried to ignore it. 
 
 * Andron wrote a work on the Seven Wise Men, and the title refers 
 to the well-known story (p. 44, n. 3). 
 
 6 Cf. Herod, iv. 95, and Herakleitos, fr. 17 (R. P. 31 a). Timaios, 
 however, gave his father's name as Demaratos. Herodotos represents 
 him as Hving at Samos. Aristoxenos said his family came from one of 
 
\ 
 
 88 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 pi Polykrates J532 b.c.).^ This date cannot be far wrong ; 
 orTSS^aHTeifos already speaks of him in the past tense. ^ 
 
 The extensive travels attributed to Pythagoras by late 
 writers are, of course, apocryphal. Even the statement 
 that he visited Egypt, though far from improbable if we 
 consider the > close relations between Polykrates of Samos 
 ^d Am^^5j§^j:ests on no sufficient authority.^ Herodotos, 
 it is true, observes that the Egyptians agreed in certain 
 practices with the rules called Orphic and Bacchic, which 
 are really Egyptian, and with the Pythagoreans ; * but this 
 does not imply that the Pythagoreans derived these directly 
 from Egypt. He says also that the beUef in transmigration 
 came from Egypt, though certain Greeks, both at an earlier 
 and a later date, had passed it off as their own. He refuses, 
 however, to give their names, so he can hardly be referring 
 to Pythagoras.^ Nor does it matter ; for the Egyptians 
 
 the islands which the Athenians occupied after expeUing the Tyrrhenians 
 (Diog. viii. i). This suggests Lemnos or Imbros, from which the Tyr- 
 rhenian " Pelasgians " were expelled by Miltiades (Herod, vi. 140). That 
 explains the story that he was an Etrurian or a Tyrian. Other accounts 
 bring him into connexion with Phleious, but that may be a pious in- 
 vention of the society which flourished there at the beginning of the 
 fourth century B.C. Pausanias (ii. 13, i) gives it as a Phleiasian tradition 
 that Hippasos, the great-grandfather of Pythagoras, had emigrated from 
 Phleious to Samos. 
 
 1 Eratosthenes wrongly identified Pythagoras with the Olympic victor 
 of 01. XLVIII. I (588/7 B.C.), but Apollodoros gave his floruit as 532/1, 
 the era of Polykrates. He doubtless based this on the statement of 
 Aristoxenos quoted by Porphyry {V. Pyth. 9), that Pythagoras left Samos 
 from dislike to the tyranny of Polykrates (R. P. 53 a). 
 
 2 Herakl. fr. 16, 17 (R. P. 31, 31 a). 
 
 3 It occurs first in the Bousiris of Isokrates, § 28 (R. P. 52), 
 
 4 Herod, ii. 81 (R. P. 52 a). The comma at AlyvirTioLai is clearly right. 
 Herodotos believed that the cult of Dionysos was introduced by Melampous 
 (ii. 49), and he means that the Orphics got these practices from the wor- 
 shippers of Bakchos, while the Pythagoreans got them from the Orphics. 
 
 5 Herod, ii. 123 (R. P. ib.). The words " whose names I know, but 
 do not write " cannot refer to Pythagoras ; for it is only of contemporaries 
 Herodotos speaks in this way (cf. i. 51, iv. 48). Stein's suggestion that 
 he meant Empedokles seems convincing. Herodotos must have met him 
 at Thourioi. If Herodotos had ever heard of Pythagoras visiting Egypt, 
 he would surely have said so in one or other of these passages. There 
 was no occasion for reserve, as Pythagoras must have died before Herodotos 
 was born. 
 
 i 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGIC^T 89 
 
 '? / 
 
 didjaot^believe in transmigration at^a^U'^nd Herodotos was 
 
 deceived by'ffiFpries1Ps7)?tRe*'^r^ of the monuments. 
 
 Aristoxenos said that Pythagoras left Samos in order to ,,, 
 escape from the tyranny of PolykratggJ:^ It was at Kroton, 
 a city which had long been in friendly relations with Samos 
 and was famed for its athletes and its doctors,^ that he 
 founded his society. Timaios appears to have said that he 
 came to Italy in 529 B.C. and remained at Kroton for twenty 
 years. He died at Metapontion, whither he had retired when 
 the Krotoniates rose in revolt against his authority.^ 
 
 39. The Pythagorean Order was simply, in its origin, The Order. 
 a religious fr^i^t^tTi!? yjr and not, as has been maintained, a 
 poBticaT "league .* Nor had it anything whatever to do 
 with the " Dorian aristocratic ideal." Pythagoras was an 
 Ionian, and the Order was originally confined to Achaian 
 states.^ Moreover the " Dorian aristocratic ideal " is a 
 
 1 Porph. V. Pyth. g (R. P. 53 a). 
 
 2 From what Herodotos tells us of Demokedes (iii. 131) we may infer * 
 that the medical school of Kroton was founded before the time of i 
 Pythagoras. The series of Olympian victories won by Krotoniates in the w 
 sixth century B.C. is remarkable. jrf**''**'**^ 
 
 3 For a full discussion of the chronological problem, see Rostagni, 
 op. cit. pp. 376 sqq. It seems clear that Timaios made the rising of 
 Kylon take place just after the destruction of Sybaris (510 B.C.), with 
 which he connected it. The statement that Pythagoras then retired to 
 Metapontion is confirmed by Cicero, who speaks {De fin. v. 4) of the 
 honours still paid to his memory in that city (R. P. 57 c). Aristoxenos 
 (ap. Iambi. V. Pyth. 249) referred to the same thing (R. P. 57 c). Cf. 
 also Andron, fr. 6 {F.H.G. ii. 347). 
 
 * Plato, Rep. X. 600 a 9, clearly imphes that Pythagoras held no public 
 ofi&ce. The view that the Pythagorean sect was a political league, main- 
 tained in modern times by Krische [De societatis a Pythagora conditae scopo 
 politico, 1830), goes back, as Rohde has shown {loc. cit.), to Dikaiarchos, 
 the champion of the " Practical Life," just as the view that it was 
 primarily a scientific society goes back to the mathematician and musician 
 Aristoxenos. 
 
 s The idea that the Pythagoreans represented the " Dorian ideal " dies 
 very hard. In his Kulturhistorische Beitrdge (Heft i. p. 59), Max C. P. 
 Schmidt imagines that later writers call the founder of the sect Pythagoras 
 instead of Pythagores, as he is called by Herakleitos and Demokritos, 
 because he had become " a Dorian of the Dorians." The fact is simply 
 that IIi'^a76pas is the Attic form of Hvdaybp-ris, and is no more " Doric " 
 than 'kva^aybpa^. Even in the reign of Trajan, the Samians still knew that 
 'n.vea.ybpi)^ was the correct speUing. Cf . the title vignette in Diels, Vors. 
 
90 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Downfall 
 of the 
 Order. 
 
 fiction based on the Sokratic idealisation of Sparta and 
 Crete. Corinth, Argos, and Syracuse are quite forgotten. 
 Nor is there any evidence that the Pythagoreans favoured 
 the aristocratic party. ^ The main purpose of the Order was 
 / the cultivation of holiness. In this respect it resembled 
 an Orphic society, though Apolla,^^d not Dionysos^ 
 the chief Pythagorean god. '^TTnat is doubtlessmieto the 
 connexion of Pythagoras 'with Delos, and explains why the 
 Krotoniates identified him with Apollo Hj^jjerboreios.^ 
 
 40. For a time the new Order succeeded in securing 
 supreme power in the Achaian cities, but reaction soon came. 
 Our accounts of these events are much confused by failure 
 to distinguish between the revolt of Kylon in the lifetime 
 of Pythagoras himself, and the later risings which led to the 
 expulsion of the Pythagoreans from Italy. It is only if we 
 keep these apart that we begin to see our way. Timaios 
 appears to have connected the rising of Kylon closely with 
 
 ^ The only statement which might suggest that Pythagoras took the 
 aristocratic side is the remark in Diogenes (viii. 3) (bare ax^dby ehai 
 dpLCTTOKpariav ttjv iroXirelau. That may come from Timaios, but (as the 
 adverb crx^SSv shows) it is not to be taken Hterally. The Pythagorean 
 rule was no doubt an dpLaTOKparia in the sense given to the word by 
 Sokrates in Plato's Republic, but it was not based either on birth or on 
 wealth, so that it was not an aristocracy in the common Greek sense of 
 the word, and still less an oligarchy. It was more like the " Rule of the 
 Saints." Kylon, the chief opponent of the Pythagoreans, is described by 
 Aristoxenos (Iambi. V. Pyth. 248) as -yhei koL do^y kuI irXovrcp irpoiTevoiv 
 rCov 'KoKirOiv. Taras, later the chief seat of the Pythagoreans, was a 
 democracy. (Cf. Strabo, vi. p. 280, iax^a-av 8^ ttotc ol Tapavrivoi Kad' virep- 
 ^oXtju TToKiTevdfievoL drjfioKparLKCos . . . dired^^avro 5^ Kal ttjv TLvdaydpeLov 
 (f)i\o(TO(f)lav ktK.) The truth is that, at this time, the new religion 
 appealed to the people rather than the aristocracies, which were apt to 
 be " free-thinking." Xenophanes, not Pythagoras, is their man. 
 
 2 We have the authority of Aristotle, fr. 186. 15 10 b 20, for this 
 identification. The names of Abaris and Aristeas stand for a mystical 
 movement parallel to the Orphic, but based on the worship of Apollo. 
 The later tradition makes them predecessors of Pythagoras ; and that 
 this has some historical basis appears from Herod, iv. 13 sqq., and above 
 all from the statement that Aristeas had a statue at Metapontion, where 
 Pythagoras died. The connexion of Pythagoras with Salmoxis belongs 
 to the same order of ideas. As the legend of the Hyperboreans is DeHan, 
 we see that the religion taught by Pythagoras was genuinely Ionian in 
 its origin, and had nothing to do with Dionysos. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 91 
 
 the events which led to the destruction of Sybaris (510 B.C.). 
 We gather that in some way Pythagoras had shown sympathy 
 with the Sybarites, and had urged the people of Kroton 
 to receive certain refugees who had been expelled by the 
 tyrant Telys. There is no ground for the assertion that 
 he sympathised with these refugees because they were 
 " aristocrats " ; they were victims of a tyrant and supphants, 
 and it is not hard to understand that the Ionian Pytha- 
 goras should have felt a certain kindness for the men of the 
 great but unfortunate Ionian city. Kylon, who is expressly 
 stated by Aristoxenos to have been one of the first men 
 of Kroton in wealth and birth/ was able to bring about 
 the retirement of Pythagoras to Metapontion, another 
 Achaian city, and it was there that he passed his remaining 
 years. 
 
 Disturbances still went on, however, at Kroton after the 
 departure of Pythagoras for Metapontion and after his 
 death. At last, we are told, the Kyloneans set fire to the 
 house of the athlete Milo, where the Pythagoreans were 
 assembled. Of those in the house only two, who were 
 3^oung and strong, Archippos and Lysis, escaped. Archippos 
 retired to Taras, a democratic Dorian state ; Lysis, first 
 \to Achaia and afterwards to Thebes, where he was later 
 fti«,,teacher of Epameinondas.^ It is impossible to date 
 these events "accurately, but the mention' of Lysis proves 
 that they were spread over more than one generation. The 
 coup d'Etat of Kroton can hardly have occurred before 
 450 B.C., if the teacher of Epameinondas escaped from it, 
 nor can it have been much later or we should have heard 
 of it in connexion with the foundation of Thourioi in 
 444 B.C. In a valuable passage, doubtless derived from 
 Timaios, Polybios tells us of the burning of the Pythagorean 
 
 ^ See p. 90, n. I. I do not know why modern historians call him a 
 democratic leader. 
 
 2 Rohde, Rhein. Mus. xxxvi. p. 565, n. i. The later accounts telescope 
 these events into a single catastrophe. Some have it that Pythagoras 
 himself was burned to death in the house of Milo. 
 
Want of 
 
 92 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 I k 
 
 " lodges " ((rvv6Bpia)un all the Achaian cities, and the way in 
 
 \Al^h^ TO^igpg^a*^'^^^ that this went on for a consider- 
 
 able time, till at last peace and order were restored by the 
 Achaians of Peloponnesos.^ We shall see that at a later 
 date some of the Pythagoreans were able to return to Italy, 
 and once more acquired great influence there. 
 * 41. Of the opinions of Pythagoras we know even less 
 evidence fthan of his Hfc. Plato and Aristotle clearly knew nothing 
 teaching )^^^ Certain of ethical or physical doctrines going back to 
 °or^r^^'l^^^ founder himself.^ Aristoxenos gave a string of moral 
 I precepts.^ Dikaiarchos said hardly anything of what 
 I Pythagoras taught his disciples was known except the doc- 
 I trine of transmigration, the periodic cycle, and the kinship 
 I of all living creatures.* Pythagoras apparently preferred 
 ^ oral instruction to the dissemination of his opinions by 
 writing, and it was not till Alexandrian times that any one 
 ventured to forge books in his name. The writings ascribed 
 to the first Pythagoreans were also forgeries of the same 
 period.^ The early history of Pj^hagoreanism is, therefore, 
 wholly conjectural ; but we may still make an attempt to 
 understand, in a very general way, what the position of 
 Pythagoras in the history of Greek thought must have been. 
 
 ^ Polyb. ii. 39, Aca0' oOs yap Kaipoiis iv rots Karb. t^v 'IraXiav rdiroit /card 
 TT]v fi€ydL\7]v''E\\d5a t6t€ irpoaayopevofihriv iviirp-qcav to. avvidpia rdv Jlvdayopeiuv, 
 fjL€Ta ravTa yivoixevov KivrjfjLaros oXoo-x^povs -rrepl tcls TroXiTeLas (owep eUds, m Av 
 Twv irpujTOiv dvdpQy i^ eKaaTTji TroXews oijT(t} irapaXoyoiS diacpdapePTUiv) (xvvi^rj 
 ras Kar iKeivovs roiis rdirovs 'EXXtjvikcls irdXcLS dvairX-qadrjvaL (pSvov Kai (XTaaews 
 /cat iraPTodaTT^s rapaxTJi. if oh xatpots, dirb tCov irXdffTiov jxepQiv ttj^ 'EXXdSos 
 irpecr^evbvTuv itrl rds diaXvaeis, 'Amatols Kal ry roOrioy wlaTet (tvv€XPV(^o.vto 
 Tpbs Tr)v tQv irapbvTiav KaKwv i^aywyqy. 
 
 2 When discussing the Pythagorean system, Aristotle always refers it 
 to " the Pythagoreans," not to Pythagoras himself. He is quite clear 
 that what he knew as the Pythagorean system belonged in the main to 
 the days of Empedokles, Anaxagoras, and Leukippos ; for, after mention- 
 ing these, he goes on to describe the Pythagoreans as " contemporary 
 with and earlier than them " {iv 8^ tovtols Kai irpb tovtwv, Met. A, 5. 
 985 b 23). 
 
 3 The fragments of the HvdayopiKai axocpdcreis of Aristoxenos are given 
 by Diels, Vors. 45 d. 
 
 4 Porphyry, V. Pyth. 19 (R. P. 55). 
 
 6 See Diels, Dox. p. 150, and " Ein gefalschtes Pythagorasbucl 
 {Arch. iii. pp. 451 sqq.) ; Bernays, Die heraklitischen Brief e, n. i. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 93 
 
 42. In the first place, as we have seen/ he taught the Trans- 
 doctrine^'rraft^^^ 
 
 ex^^s^ea as' a developnii^ of the primitive behef in the 
 kinship of men and beasts, a view which Dikaiarchos said 
 Pythagoras held. Further, this beUef is commonly associ- 
 ated with a system of taboos on certain kinds of food, and 
 the Pythagorean rule is best known for its prescription of 
 similar forms of abstinence. It seems bertain that Pytha- 
 goras brought this with him from Ionia. / Timaios told how 
 at Delos he refused to sacrifice on any "^ut the oldest altar, 
 that of Apollo the Father, where only bloodless sacrifices 
 were allowed.^ 
 
 43. It has indeed been doubted whether we can accept Abstinence, 
 what we are told by such late writers as Porphyry on the 
 subject of Pythagorean abstinence. Aristoxenos undoubt- 
 edly said Pythagoras did not abstain from animal flesh in 
 general, but only from that of the ploughing ox and the 
 
 ram.* He also said that Pythagoras preferred beans to 
 every other vegetable, as being the most laxative, and 
 that he was partial to sucking-pigs and tender kids.^ The 
 palpable exaggeration of these statements shows, however, 
 that he is endeavouring to combat a behef which existed in 
 
 1 See above, p. 84. 
 
 2 The proper Greek for this is iraXiyyepeala, and the inaccurate term 
 fieTeixxpitxitXTL^ only occurs in late writers. Some of the Neoplatonists and 
 Christian apologists say fieTeva(afj.a.TU}ai.%, which is accurate but cumbrous. 
 Cf. Olympiodoros in Phaed. p. 54, 25 (Norvin), ttjj/ fi€Te/j.\l/uxoj<yi.f, iJToi ttjv 
 lxeTev(7(aiM6LT(i}(rLV, 5i6ti ov iroWaX \pvxoX ^v o-Qfia eiSoiroiovaiv, iirel aOrr] fMerefi- 
 yp{>X(^<Ti.^ ^v, dXXct fiia ^vxv Sid(f)opa awfiara fi€Tafnri(rx^Tai. See Rohde, 
 Psyche, p. 428, n. 2. 
 
 ^ See Diog. viii. 13. 
 
 * Aristoxenos ap. Diog. viii. 20, wdyra fikv ra &\\a <Tvyx(^peTv avrhv 
 iadUiu ^/xxj/vxo; fibvov 5' dir^x^^^'^'- /3o^s dpoTijpos Kal KpioO. 
 
 6 Aristoxenos ap. Gell. iv. 11, 5, Uvdaydpas 5^ tQiv oairpLwv fidXKrra rhv 
 Kvafiop edoKifiaaev ' \eiavTiK6v re yap eXvai Kal diax'^P'rjTLKbv ' 5ib Kal 
 fidXiara k^xpvtoh aiiTi^ ', ib. 6, " porculis quoque minuscuUs et haedis tene- 
 rioribus victitasse, idem Aristoxenus refert." It is just possible that 
 Aristoxenos may be right about the taboo on beans. We know that it 
 was Orphic, and it may have been transferred to the Pythagoreans by 
 mistake. That, however, would not affect the general conclusion that at 
 least some Pythagoreans practised abstinence from various kinds of 
 animal food, which is all that is required. 
 
94 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 his own day, so we can show, out of his own mouth, that 
 the tradition which made the Pythagoreans abstain from 
 animal flesh and beans goes back to a time long before the 
 Neopythagoreans. The explanation is that Aristoxenos 
 had been the friend of the last of the Pythagoreans ; and, 
 in their time, the strict observance had been relaxed, except 
 by some zealots whom the heads of the Society refused to 
 acknowledge.^ The " Pythagorists " who clung to the old 
 practices were now regarded as heretics, and it was said 
 that the Akousmatics, as they were" called, were really 
 followers of Hippasos, who had been excommunicated for 
 reveahng secret doctrines. The genuine followers of 
 Pythagoras were the Mathematicians. ^ The satire of the 
 poets of the Middle Comedy proves, however, that, even 
 though the friends of Aristoxenos did not practise abstinence, 
 there were. plenty of people in the fourth century, calHng 
 themselves followers of Pythagoras, who did.^ We know 
 also from Isokrates that they still observed the rule of 
 
 ^ Yet even Aristoxenos recorded that, when Pherekydes died, he was 
 buried by Pythagoras at Delos (Diog. i. ii8). It was, perhaps, too 
 notorious to be denied, 
 
 2 Hippasos of Kroton or Metapontion (in the catalogue of lamblichos 
 he is a Sybarite) is, we shall see, the regular scapegoat of the Pythagoreans, 
 lamblichos, who here follows Nikomachos, says {V. Pyth. 8i ; R. P. 56) 
 that the /j.adijfiaTLKoi were admitted to be Pythagoreans by the d/couc/za- 
 TiKoi, but did not recognise them in return. We are told (Diog. viii. 7) 
 that the fivariKos X670S ascribed to Pythagoras was really by Hippasos, 
 who wrote it iwl dia^oXy Uvdayopov, i.e. to throw discredit on him by 
 representing him as a purely religious teacher. The term UveayopKrHjs 
 seems to have been used specially of the Akousmatics, while the 
 scientific Pythagoreans were called HvdaybpeLoi in the same way as the 
 followers of other schools were called ' kva^aybpeioi, 'HpaKXeLreioi, and the 
 Uke. 
 
 3 For the fragments, see Diels, Vors. 45 e. The most striking are 
 Antiphanes, fr. 135, Kock, ioairep Uvdayopi^oiv eadUi \ ^ix\pvxov oidep ; Alexis, 
 fr. 220, ot 'n.vdayopLi;'ovTes yap, ws aKouo/xev, \ out 6\pov iadlovaLv oijr' &XK' ov8^ 
 iv \ l/x\pvxov ; fr. 196 (from the Hvdayopi^^ova-a), 17 5' eaTiaais tVxdSes Kal 
 aT€fi(pv\a 1 /cat rvpos iarai ' ravra yap dveiv vofios \ roh UvdayopeioLS ; Aristophon, 
 fr. 9 (from the l\vdayopi<JTr]s) , irpbs rdv deCov oiojxeOa toi)s TrdXai irore, \ Toiis 
 UvdayopLCTTas yevo/x^fovs turois pvirdv \ eKOvras ij (popelv rpi^uvas Tjdius; Mnesi- 
 machos, fr. I, ws nvOayopLari dvo/xep ry Ao^iq, \ ^fj-xpvxov ovdev eadiovres 
 iravTekCj^. See also Theokritos xiv. 5, tolovto^ Kal irpav tis d<piK€To Ilvdayo- 
 piKTas, I u}xpi>s KawTTodriTos ' 'Adrjyaios 5' icpar' fjfiev. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 95 
 
 silence.^ History has not been kind to the Akousmatics, 
 but they never wholly died out. The names of Diodoros 
 of Aspendos and Nigidius Figulus help .^ to bridge the gulf 
 between them and Apollonios of Jf^^^swasbiX: 
 
 We have seen that Pythagoras taught the kinship of 
 beasts and men, and we infer that his rule of abstinence 
 from flesh was based, not on humanitarian or ascetic grounds, 
 but on taboo J? This is strikingly confirmed by a statement 
 in Porphyr5^'s Defence of Abstinence, to the effect that, 
 though the Pythagoreans did as a rule abstain from flesh, 
 they nevertheless ate it when they sacrificed to the gods.^ 
 Now, among primitive peoples, we often find that the sacred 
 animal is slain and eaten on certain solemn occasions, 
 though in ordinary circumstances this would be the greatest 
 of all impieties. Here, again, we have a primitive behef ; 
 and we need not attach any weight to the denials of 
 Aristoxenos.^ 
 
 44. We shall now know what to think of the Pythagorean ^,*owswa/a. 
 rules and precepts that have come down to us. These are 
 
 1 Bousiris, § 28, ^n yap Kal pvv roOs TrpoaTroiov/xivovs iKeiuov fiadrjras 
 elvaL fxaWov aiyQvras davjxd^ovcnv fj toOs iirl ry X^7eiJ' fxeyi<TTr}v 56^av ^xoyras. 
 The Pythagorean silence was called ix^fivdia or ix^ppr^ixoavv-q, both 
 of which seem to be good Ionic words. It is probable that the 
 silence was disciplinary rather than a means of keeping the doctrine 
 secret. 
 
 2 See Bernays, Theophrastos' Schrift iiber Frommigkeit. Porphyry's 
 tract, Tlepl airoxn^ eixxpyx^^v, is addressed to Castricius Firmus, who had 
 fallen away from the strict vegetarianism of the Pythagoreans. The 
 passage referred to is De abst. p. 58, 25 Nauck, iaropouat 8i rives Kal 
 avTovs aimadaL tCov ijx^pvx'Jiv rods Jlvdayopeiovs, ore ddoiev deois. This does not 
 come, like most of Porphyry's tract, from Theophrastos, but it is in all 
 probability from Herakleides of Pontos. See Bernays, op. cit. p. 11. 
 Cf. also Plutarch, Q. conv. 729 c (ot JlvdayopLKol) iyeiovro twp lepodiruv 
 airap^dixevoi rots deocs. 
 
 3 Porphyry {V. Pyth. c 15) has preserved a tradition to the effect that 
 Pythagoras recommended a flesh diet for athletes (Milo ?). This story 
 must have originated at the same time as those related by Aristoxenos, 
 and in a similar way. In fact, Bernays has shown that it comes from 
 Herakleides of Pontos {Theophr. Schr. n. 8). lamblichos {V. Pyih. 5. 25) 
 and others (Diog. viii. 13, 47) got out of this by supposing it referred to 
 a gymnast of the same name. We see here how the Neoplatonists en- 
 deavoured to go back to the original form of the Pythagorean legend, and 
 to explain away the fourth-century reconstruction. 
 
 ■lftW)««l'itVi.? 
 
96 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 of two kinds, and have different sources. Some of them, 
 derived from Affstoxeiiqs, and for the most part preserved 
 by lambhchos, are mere precepts of morahty. They do 
 not pretend to go back to Pythagoras himself ; they are 
 only the sayings which the last generation of " Mathe- 
 maticians " heard from their predecessors. ^ The second 
 class is of a different nature, and consists of rules called 
 ^^^A^pusmatai which points to their being the property of the 
 sect which had faithfully preserved the old customs. Later 
 writers interpret them as " symbols " of moral truth ; but it 
 does not require a practised eye to see that they are genuine 
 taboos. I give a few examples to show what the Pytha- 
 gorean rule was really like. 
 
 1. To abstain from beans. 
 
 2. Not to pick up what has fallen. 
 
 3. Not to touch a white cock. 
 
 4. Not to break bread. 
 
 5. Not to step over a crossbar. 
 
 6. Not to stir the fire with iron. 
 
 7. Not to eat from a whole loaf. 
 
 8. Not to pluck a garland. 
 
 9. Not to sit on a quart measure. 
 
 10. Not to eat the heart. 
 
 11. Not to walk on highways. 
 
 12. Not to let swallows share one's roof. 
 
 13. When the pot is taken off the fire, not to leave the mark 
 
 of it in the ashes, but to stir them together. 
 
 14. Do not look in a mirror beside a light. 
 
 15. When you rise from the bedclothes, roll them together 
 
 and smooth out the impress of the body. 
 
 It would be easy to multiply proofs of the close con- 
 nexion between Pythagoreanism and primitive modes of 
 thought, but what has been said is sufficient for our 
 purpose. 
 
 ^ For the HvdayopLKal dTro<pd(r€Ls of Aristoxenos, see Diels, Vors. 
 2 There is a collection of 'AKova-/.!.ara kuI av/ji.j3o\a in Diels, Vors. 
 
 ^ 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 97 
 
 45. Now, were this all, we should be tempted to delete Pytha- 
 the name of Pythagoras from the history of philosophy, ^^0? ^ 
 and relegate him to the class of " medicine-men " i^^TS^)-"^^^^^^' 
 along with Epimenides and Onomakritos. That, however, 
 would be quite wrong. The Pythagorean Society became 
 the chief scientific school of Greece, and it is certain that 
 Pythagorean science goes back to the early years of the 
 fifth century, and therefore to the founder. Herakleitos, 
 who is not partial to him, says that Pythagoras had 
 pursued scientific investigation further than other men.^ 
 Herodotos called Pythagoras "by no means the weakest 
 sophist of the Hellenes," a title which at this date does not 
 imply the sHghtest disparagement, but does imply scientific 
 studies. 2 Aristotle said that Pythagoras at first busied 
 himself with mathematics and numbers, though he adds 
 that later he did not renounce the miracle-mongering of 
 Pherekydes.^ Can we trace any connexion between these 
 two sides of his activity ? 
 
 We have seen that the aim of the Orphic and other 
 Orgia was to obtain release from the " wheel of birth " 
 by means of " purifications " of a primitive type. The 
 new thing in the society founded by Pythagoras seems 
 to have been that, while it admitted all these old prac- 
 tices, it at the same time suggested a deeper idea of what 
 " purification " really is. Aristoxenos said that the Pytha-i 
 goreans employed music to purge the soul as thew 
 used medicine to purge the body.* Such methods op 
 purifying the soul were famiUar in the Orgia of the Kory- 
 
 1 Herakl. fr. 17 (R. P. 31 a). The word iaroplr) is in itself quite general. 
 What it chiefly means here we see from a valuable notice preserved by 
 lamblichos, V. Pyth. 89, iKaXeiro 5^ i] yeufxeTpia irpos UvOaydpov Icropia. 
 
 2 Herod, iv. 95. 
 
 ' Arist. Uepi tCov Uvdayopeiuv, fr. 186, 1 510 a 39, livdaySpas Mvrjadpxov 
 vlb^ rb ixev irpwrov dieiroveLTO irepl rot. fjiadrmara Kal roi/s dpidfiovs, varepov di 
 irore Kal ttjs ^epeKvSov reparoxoitas oiiK dv^aTr]. 
 
 ^ See Cramer, An. Par. i. 172, 6tl ol UvOayopiKoi, (bs ?07? ' ApiarS^euos, 
 Kaddpaei ixpCUvro tov fjih adifiaTOS did tijs laTpiKTJs, ttjs S^ ^vxv^ SiA t^s 
 /ioi;(riK^s. 
 
 7 
 
98 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 f bantes/ and will serve to explain the Pythagorean interest 
 in*''ffi:rmonics. But there is more than this. If we can 
 trust Herakleides, it was Pythagoras who first distinguished 
 the " three Hves," the Theq|;^ti«'/^the Pmcti^^^^nd the 
 Apolaustic, which Aristotle made use of in the Ethics, The 
 doctrine is" to this effect. We are strangers in this world, 
 and the body is the tomb of the soul, and yet we must not 
 seek to escape by self-murder ; for we are the chattels of 
 God who is- our herdsman, and without his command we 
 have no right to make our escape. ^ In this life there are 
 three kinds of men, just as there are three sorts of people 
 who come to the Olympic Games. The lowest class is made 
 up of those who come to buy and selL and next above them 
 are those who come to com^^I^^est of all, however, are 
 those who come to look o!r^g^g^4*^ The greatest purifica- 
 tion of all is, therefore, science, and it is the man who 
 devotes himself to that, the true philosopher, who has most 
 effectually released himself from the '' wheel of birth." It 
 would be rash to say that Pythagoras expressed himself 
 exactly in this manner ; but all these ideas are genuinely 
 Pythagorean, and it is only in some such way that we can 
 bridge the gulf which separates Pythagoras the man of 
 science from Pythagoras the reUgious teacher. ^ It is easy 
 to understand that most of his followers would rest content 
 with the humbler kinds of purification, and this will account 
 for the sect of the Akousmatics. A few would rise to the 
 higher doctrine, and we have now to ask how much of the 
 
 1 These are mentioned in Plato, Laws, 790 d, a passage which is the 
 origin of Aristotle's doctrine of Kddapais. For a full account see Rohde, 
 Psyche, ii. 48, n. i. 
 
 2 Plato gives this as the Pythagorean view in Phaed. 62 b. The 
 passage distinctly implies that it was not merely the theory of Philolaos, 
 but something older. 
 
 3 See Doring in Arch. v. pp. 505 sqq. There seems to be a reference 
 to the theory of the "three lives" in Herakleitos, fr. iii. It was 
 apparently taught in the Pythagorean Society of Phleious ; for Herakleides 
 made Pythagoras expound it in a conversation with the tyrant of Phleious 
 (Cic. Tusc. V. 3 ; Diog. pr. 12, viii. 8), and Plato makes Sokrates argue 
 from it in the Phaedo (see my note on 68 c 2). 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 
 
 99 
 
 later Pythagorean science may be ascribed to Pythagoras 
 himself. 
 v-^,46. In his treatise on Arithmetic, Aristoxenos said that Arithmetic. 
 Pythagoras was the first to carry that study beyond the 
 needs of commerced and his statement is confirmed by 
 everySKng'^we^^Eerwise know. By the end of the fifth 
 century B.C. we find that there is a widespread interest in 
 such subjects and that these are studied for their own sake. 
 Now this new interest cannot have been wholly the work 
 of a school ; it must have originated with some great man, 
 and there is no one but Pythagoras to whom we can refer it. 
 As, however, he wrote nothing, we have no sure means of 
 distinguishing his own teaching from that of his followers 
 in the next generation or two. All we can safely say is 
 that, the more primitive any Pythagorean doctrine appears, 
 the more hkely it is to be that of Pythagoras himself, and 
 all the more so if it can be shown to have points of con- 
 tact with views which we know to have been held in his 
 own time or shortly before it. In particular, when we find 
 the later Pythagoreans teaching things that were already 
 something of an anachronism in their own day, we may be 
 pretty sure we are deaUng with survivals which only the 
 authority of the master's name could have preserved. 
 Some of these must be mentioned at once, though the 
 developed system belongs to a later part of our story. It 
 is only by separating its earliest form from its later that 
 the place of Pythagoreanism in Greek thought can be 
 made clear, though we must remember that no one can 
 now pretend to draw the line*between its successive stages 
 with any certainty. 
 
 47. One of the most remarkable statements we have*^fe©^>, 
 about Pythagoreanism is what we are told of Eurytos on ^***^ 
 the unimpeachable authority of Archytas. Eurytos,, was 
 
 1 Stob. i. p. 20, I, iK tCjv ' Apta-To^^pov irepl dpiOfnjTtKrjs, Ttjj' 5^ irepl toijs 
 dpidfJLOvi Trpay/j-aTeiap fidXtcxTa irdvTiav TifirjaaL doKei Uvdaydpas /cat wpoayayeij/ 
 eirl rb irpbadev dirayayiav dirh t^s tCjv e/j-iropcov x/oe/as. 
 
100 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the disciple of . I^]3Lik)l€^o^;"''«bnd Aristoxenos mentioned him 
 along with Philolaos as having taught the last of the Pytha- 
 goreans, the men with whom he himself was acquainted. 
 He therefore belongs to the beginning of the fourth century 
 B.C., by which time the Pythagorean system was fully 
 developed, and he was no eccentric enthusiast, but one of 
 the foremost men in the school.^ We are told of him, then, 
 that he used to give the number of alV sorts of things, such 
 as horses and men, and that he demonstrated these by 
 arranging pebbles in a certain way. Moreover, Aristotle 
 compares his procedure to that of those who bring numbers 
 into figures {a-x^rj/jLaTo) like the triangle and the square.^ 
 
 Now these statements, and especially the remark of 
 Aristotle last quoted, seem to imply the existence at this 
 date, and earher, of a numerical symboHsm quite distinct 
 from the alphabetical notation on the one hand and from 
 the EucUdean representation of numbers by lines on the 
 other. The former was inconvenient for arithmetical 
 purposes, because the zero was not yet invented.^ The 
 representation of numbers by Unes was adopted to avoid 
 
 ^ Apart from the story in lamblichos {V. Pyth. 148) that Eurytos 
 heard the voice of Philolaos from the grave after he had been many years 
 dead, it is to be noticed that he is mentioned after him in the statement 
 of Aristoxenos referred to (Diog. viii. 46 ; R. P. 62). 
 
 * Arist. Met. N, 5. 1092 b 8 (R. P. 76 a). Aristotle does not quote 
 the authority of Archytas here, but the source of his statement is made 
 quite clear by Theophr. Met. p. vi. a 19 (Usener), tovto yap (sc. rb fii] 
 jx^xP'- '"Of TrpoeXddyra iraieadai) reK^ov Kol (ppovovpro^, Sirep 'Apx^Tas ttot' icjyrj 
 TTOietp EiipvTou diaridiura rivas \pifj(povs ' X^yeiv yap cos ode fiev dvdpdiirov 6 
 dpLOfids, Sde 5^ tirirov, 6de 8' &X\ov TLvbs rvyxdvec. 
 
 3 The notation used in Greek arithmetical treatises must have origin- 
 ated at a date and in a region where the Van and the Koppa were still 
 recognised as letters of the alphabet and retained their original position 
 in it. That points to a Dorian state (Taras or Syracuse ?), and to a date 
 not later than the early fourth century B.C. The so-called Arabic figures 
 are usually credited to the Indians, but M. Carra de Vaux has shown 
 {Scientia, xxi. pp. 273 sqq.) that this idea (which only makes its appearance 
 in the tenth century a.d.) is due to a confusion between the Arabic hindi, 
 " Indian," and hindasi, " arithmetical." He comes to the conclusion that 
 the " Arabic " numerals were invented by the Neopythagoreans, and 
 brought by the Neoplatonists to Persia, whence they reached the Indians 
 and later the Arabs. The zero, on which the value of the whole system 
 depends, appears to be the initial letter of oidiv. 
 
 dl 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGI^^N /. : loi 
 
 the difficulties raised by the discovBrvqf ipj^tion^lqu^j^tj:ties, 
 and is of much later date. It seems" rather 'thkt liiimbers 
 were originally represented by dots arranged in S5niimetrical 
 and easily recognised patterns, of which the marking of 
 dice or dominoes gives us the best idea. And these markings 
 are, in fact, the best proof that this is a genuinely primitive 
 method of indicating numbers ; for they are of unknown 
 antiquity, and go back to the time when men could only 
 count by arranging numbers in such patterns, each of which 
 became, as it were, a fresh unit. 
 
 It is, therefore, significant that we do not find any clue 
 to what Aristotle meant by " those who bring numbers into 
 figures like the triangle and the square " till we come to 
 certain late writers who called themselves Pythagoreans, 
 and revived the study of arithmetic as a science independent 
 of geometry. These men not only abandoned the hnear 
 symboUsm of Euclid, but also regarded the alphabetical 
 notation, which they did use, as inadequate to represent 
 the true nature of number. Nikomachos of Gerasa says 
 expressly that the letters used to represent numbers are 
 purely conventional.^ The natural thing would be to 
 represent linear or prime numbers by a row of units, poly- 
 gonal numbers by units arranged so as to mark out the 
 various plane figures, and solid numbers by units disposed 
 in pyramids and so forth. ^ We therefore find figures like 
 this: 
 
 
 
 a 
 
 
 a a 
 
 a 
 
 a 
 
 a a 
 
 
 aaa 
 
 
 
 
 
 a a 
 
 
 a a 
 
 a 
 
 a a 
 
 a a 
 
 
 aaa 
 
 
 
 
 
 a a 
 
 
 a a 
 
 a 
 
 1 Nikomachos of Gerasa, Inirod. Arithm. p. 83, 12, Hoche, Upbrepov S^ 
 iiriyvwaT^ov 6tl ^Kaarov ypd/xij,a (^ arjfxeiov/neda^ aptdixov, olov rb i, (^ t6 8iKa, t6 
 K, (^ rd etKoai, t6 w, ip rb. 6KraK6<na, vdfKp Kal avv6rj/j,aTt dvOpitiirivq}, dXX* 0^ 
 (t>v(r€L aT]fiavTLK6v ian rod dpLd/xov kt\. Cf. also Iambi, in Nicom. p. 56, 27, 
 Pistelli, iffriov yap wj rb irakaibv (ftvaiKibrepov ol irpoadev iarffiaivovTo rds rod 
 dpidfiov irocr6T7)Tas, dXX' ovx ioairep oi vvv avfi^oXiKuis. 
 
 2 For the prime or rectilinear numbers, cf. Iambi, in Nicom. p. 26, 25, 
 Pistelli, TTpQiTos ixkv odv Kal davvderos dpidfids iari irepKrabs 8s virb ^iMvtjs 
 fMOPadoi irXripovvTOii fierpelrai, ovk^tl bk Kal vir dXkov TLvbs fxipov$, Kal iirl filay 
 
102 : .. Ex\RLy. GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 No\7 it^oaght^to^be obvious that this is no innovation. Of 
 course t^he^eiiiplaynient of^ the letter alpha to represent the 
 units is derived from the conventional notation ; but other- 
 wise we are clearly in presence of something which belongs 
 to the very earhest stage of the science. We also gather 
 that the dots were supposed to represent pebbles {\fr7j(j)ot) , 
 and this throws light on early methods of what we still call 
 calculation. 
 Triangular, 48. That Aristotlc rcfcrs to this seems clear, and is 
 ISd^biong confirmed by the tradition that the great revelation made 
 numbers. \yy Pythagoras to mankind was precisely a figure of this 
 kind, the 'J^ta^tys, by which the Pythagoreans used to 
 swear, 1 and we ha*^ the authority of Speusippos for holding 
 that the whole theory >vas Pythagorean. ^ In later days 
 there were many kinds of tetraktys,^ but the original one, 
 that by which the Pythagoreans swore, was the " tetraktys 
 of the dekad." It was a figure like this : 
 
 • • • 
 
 • • • • 
 
 and represented the number ten as the triangle of four. 
 
 5^ didaraatu Trpo^rjaeTai 6 toloutos, 8ia touto d^ airhv Kal evdvjxerpLKbv rives 
 KoXovcn, Qvfiapidas d^ Kal evdvypafiixLKbv drXarT/s yap iv tt} eKdiffei ecf) ^v 
 fibvov dua-Tdfievos. It is generally recognised now that Thymaridas was 
 an early Pythagorean (Tannery, Mem. scient. vol. i. n, 9 ; G. Loria, 
 Scienze esatte, p. 807) ; and, if that is so, we have a complete proof 
 that this theory goes back to the early days of the school. For the 
 triangular, oblong, and square numbers, etc., see Theon of Smyrna, pp. 
 27-37, Hiller, and Nicom. loc. cit. 
 
 * Cf. the formula Ov fxd rbv afxer^pa yeveq, TrapaSbvra rerpaKTiJU, 
 which is all the more likely to be old that it is put into the mouth of 
 Pythagoras by the forger of the Xpvaa itrri, thus making him swear by 
 himself ! See Diels, Arch. iii. p. 457. 
 
 2 Speusippos wrote a work on the Pythagorean numbers, based chiefly 
 on Philolaos, and a considerable fragment of it is preserved in the 
 Theologumena Arithmetica. It will be found in Diels, Vorsokratiker, 32 A 13, 
 and is discussed by Tannery, Science hellene, pp. 374 sqq, 
 
 3 See Theon, Expositio, pp. 93 sqq.^ Hiller. The rerpaKHs used in the 
 Timaeus is the second described by Theon {Exp. p. 94, 10 sqq. 
 
 d 
 
I SCIENCE AND RELIGION 103 
 
 I It showed at a glance, that i +2 +3 +4=10. Speusippos 
 I tells us of several properties which the Pythagoreans dis- 
 ^6vered in the dekad/ It is, for instance, the first number 
 that has in it an equal number of prime and composite 
 numbers. How much of this goes back to Pythagoras 
 himself, we cannot tell ; but we are probably justified in 
 referring to him the conclusion that it is " according to 
 nature " that all Hellenes and barbarians count up to ten 
 and then begin over again. 
 
 It is obvious that the tetraktys may be indefinitely 
 extended so as to exhibit the sums of the series of successive 
 integers in a graphic form, and these sums are accordingly 
 called " triangular numbers." 
 
 For similar reasons, the sums of the series of successive 
 odd numbers are called '* square numbers," and those of 
 successive even numbers " oblong." If odd numbers are 
 added in the form of gnomons,^ the result is always a similar 
 figure, namely a square, while, if even numbers are added, 
 we get a series of rectangles,^ as shown by the figure : 
 
 Square Numbers. Oblong Numbers. 
 
 
 • • • 
 
 1 In accordance with analogy (p. 21, n. i), the" original meaning of 
 the word yvwixwv must have been that of the carpenter's square. From 
 that are derived its use (i) for the instrument ; (2) for the figure added 
 to a square or rectangle to form another square or rectangle. In Euclid 
 (ii. def. 2) this is extended to all parallelograms, and finally the ypco/xuv is 
 defined by Heron (ed. Heiberg, vol. iv, def. 58) thus : Kad6\ov 8k yvdofiiav 
 iarlv irav, 8 trpoaXa^bv otlouv, dpid/xbs rj axrj/J-O', Trote? to 6\ov 8/jloiov ip irpoael- 
 \-q(pev. These, however, are later developments ; for the use of yvdjficou 
 in the sense of "perpendicular" by Oinopides of Chios shows that, in 
 the fifth century B.C., it only applied to rectangular figures. 
 
 2 Cf. Milhaud, Philosophes gSometres, pp. 1155^^. Aristotle puts the 
 matter thus {Phys. V, 4. 203 a 13) : irepLnde/xipiov yap rdv yvwfibvwv -rrepl 
 rb iu Kal X'^P'J or^ jmeu dWo del ylyveadat to elSoj, ot^ bk 'iv. This is more 
 clearly stated by Ps.-Plut. (Stob. i. p. 22, 16), ert 5^ t^ ixovabt tQv icpe^r/S 
 ireptaaCJu TrepiTtde/x^vcAjv 6 ytv6/ji€vos del TeTpdyuivos icm ' tCjv dk dpriuv bfioius 
 
104 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 It is clear, then, that we are entitled to refer the study of 
 sums of series to Pythagoras himself ; but whether he went 
 beyond the oblong, and studied pyramidal or cubic numbers, 
 we cannot say.^ 
 Geometry 49. It is casy to 866 how this way of representing numbers 
 harmonics, would suggcst problems of a geometrical nature. The dots 
 which stand for the pebbles are regularly called " boundary- 
 stones " (opoL, termini, " terms "), and the area they mark 
 out is the " field " (xcopa).^ This is evidently an early 
 way of speaking, and may be referred to Pythagoras himself. 
 Now it must have struck him that " fields " could be com- 
 pared as well as numbers,^ and it is likely that he knew the 
 rough methods of doing this traditional in Egypt, though 
 certainly these would fail to satisfy him. Once more the 
 tradition is helpful in suggesting the direction his thoughts 
 must have taken. He knew, of course, the use of the 
 triangle 3, 4, 5 in constructing right angles. We have seen 
 (p. 20) that it was familiar in the East from a very early 
 date, and that Thales introduced it to the Hellenes, if they 
 did not know it already. In later writers it is actually 
 called the " Pythagorean triangle." Now the Pythagorean 
 proposition par excellence is just that, in a right-angled 
 
 irepiTideixhojv eTepofj.rjKeis Kal Avlctol Trdvres aTro^aivovaiv, tcrojs S^ ladKis ov8ds. 
 It will be observed that Aristotle here uses elSos in the sense of "figure." 
 The words /cat x^p's apparently mean x't'pis toO ivos, i.e. starting from 2, 
 not from i. 
 
 1 Speusippos (cf. p. 102, n. 2) speaks of four as the first pyramidal 
 number ; but this is taken from Philolaos, so we cannot safely ascribe it 
 to Pythagoras. 
 
 2 Proclus, in Eucl. I. p. 136, 8, ^ari 8^ rb 6vofxa (sc. 6pos) oUeTou ry i^ 
 dpxv^ yeu}/uL€Tpiq., Kad' ^v to, x^P^^ ejxiTpovv Kal tovs 8povs avrdv icpiuXarrov 
 da-vyxvTovs. We have 8poi of a series {^Kdeais), then of a proportion, 
 and in later times of a syllogism. The signs :, ::, and .-. seem to be 
 derived from this. The term xoipa is often used by the later Pytha- 
 goreans, though Attic usage required x^P'-o'^ for a rectangle. The spaces 
 between the ypa/xixai of the abacus and the chess-board were also called 
 
 * In his commentary on Euclid i. 44, Proclus tells us on the authority 
 of Eudemos that the irapa^oXif}, ^XXeti^tr, and vwep^oK-q of x^P^^ werc^ 
 Pythagorean inventions. For these and the later application of th^ 
 terms in Conic Sections, see Milhaud, Philosophes geometres, pp. 81 sqq. 
 
 I 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 105 
 
 triangle, the square on the hypotenuse is equal to the 
 squares on the other two sides, and the so-called Pythagorean 
 triangle is the application of its converse to a particular 
 case. The very name " hypotenuse " (viroreLvovaa) affords 
 strong confirmation of the intimate connexion between the 
 two things. It means literally " the cord stretching over 
 against," and this is surely just the rope of the " arpe- 
 donapt." It is, therefore, quite possible that this proposi- 
 tion was really discovered by Pythagoras, though we cannot 
 be sure of that, and though the demonstration of it which 
 Euclid gives is certainly not his.^ 
 
 50. One great disappointment, however, awaited him. incom- 
 
 . . mensur- 
 
 It follows at once from the Pythagorean proposition that ability, 
 the square on the diagonal of a square is double the square 
 on its side, and this ought surety to be capable of arithmetical 
 expression. As a matter of fact, however, there is no square 
 number which can be divided into two equal square numbers, 
 and so the problem cannot be solved. In this sense, it may 
 be true that Pythagoras discovered the incommensurability ^ 
 of the diagonal and the side of a square, and the proof 
 mentioned by Aristotle, namely, that, if they were commen- 
 surable, we should have to say that an even number was 
 equal to an odd number, is distinctly Pythagorean in 
 character.^ However that may be, it is certain that Pytha- 
 goras did not care to pursue the subject any further. He 
 may have stumbled on the fact that the square root of two 
 is a surd, but we know that it was left for Plato's friends, 
 Theodoros of Kyrene and Theaitetos, to give a complete 
 Uheory of irrationals.^ For the present, the incommensura- 
 |bility of the diagonal and the square remained, as has been 
 
 ;^aid, a " scandalous exception." Our tradition says that 
 
 \ 
 
 ^ See Proclus's commentary on Euclid i. 47. 
 
 2 Arist. An, Pr. A, 23. 41 a 26, 8tl davjufierpos rj bLajxerpo^ 8ia rb 
 yiyveadai to, irepLTTa taa tocs dprioLS crvfipi^Tpov redei<X'rfS. The proofs given 
 at the end of EucHd's Tenth Book (vol. iii. pp. 408 sqq., Heiberg) turn 
 on this very point. They are not Euclidean, and may be substantially 
 Pythagorean. Cf. Milhaud, Philosophes geometres, p. 94. 
 
 3 Plato, Theaet. 147 d 3 sqq. \ 
 
io6 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Hippasos of Metapontion was drowned at sea for revealing 
 this skeleton in the cupboard.^ 
 Proportion 51. These last considerations show that, while it is 
 harmony, quite Safe to attribute the substance of the early books 
 of EucHd to the early Pythagoreans, his arithmetical 
 method is certainly not theirs. It operates with lines 
 instead of with units, and it can therefore be applied 
 to relations which are not capable of being expressed as 
 equations between rational numbers. That is doubtless 
 why arithmetic is not treated in EucHd till after plane 
 geometry, a complete inversion of the original order. 
 For the same reason, the doctrine of proportion which we 
 find in Euclid cannot be Pythagorean, and is indeed 
 the work of Eudoxos. Yet it is clear that the early 
 Pythagoreans, and probably Pythagoras himself, studied 
 proportion in their own way, and that the three " medieties '* 
 (fjb€o-6T7]T€^) in particular go back to the founder, especially 
 as the most complicated of them, the " harmonic," stands 
 in close relation to his discovery of the octave. If we take 
 the harmonic proportion 12 : 8 : 6,^ we find that 12 : 6 is 
 the octave, 12 : 8 the fifth, and 8 : 6 the fourth, and it can 
 hardly be doubted that Pythagoras himself discovered these 
 intervals. The stories about his observing the harmonic 
 intervals in a smithy, and then weighing the hammers that 
 produced them, or suspending weights corresponding to those 
 of the hammxcrs to equal strings, are, indeed, impossible and 
 absurd ; but it is sheer waste of time to rationaUse them.^ 
 
 1 This version of the tradition is mentioned in lamblichos, V. Pyth. 
 247, and looks older than the other, which we shall come to later (§ 148). 
 The excommunicated Hippasos is the enfant terrible of Pythagoreanism, 
 and the traditions about him are full of instruction. See p. 94, n. 2. 
 
 2 The harmonic mean is thus defined by Archytas (fr, 2, Diels) d d^ 
 virevavrla {fieadTas), &.v KaXovfiep apfioucKdv, 6KKa icovri <Toiot (sc. oi 6poi) ' v> 
 6 irpQros Spos UTrep^xei rod devripov avravrov fi^pei, rwdrcp 6 jx^cros rod rplrov 
 virep^X^L rod Tpirov fx^pei. Cf. Plato, Tim. 36 a 3, rrjv . . . ravrip fx^pcL tQv 
 &Kp(j}v avrCou vTrep^x^^'^^" 'f'*^ inrepexofiivTjv. The harmonic mean of 12 and 6 
 is, therefore, 8 ; for 8 = 12 -V- =6 + f. 
 
 s The smith's hammers belong to the region of Mdrchen, and it is not 
 true that the notes would correspond to the weight of the hammers, or 
 
 I 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 107 
 
 For our purpose their absurdity is their chief merit. They 
 are not stories which any Greek mathematician could pos- 
 sibly have invented, but popular tales bearing witness to 
 the existence of a real tradition that Pythagoras was the 
 author of this momentous discovery. On the other hand, 
 the statement that he discovered the " consonances *' by 
 measuring the lengths corresponding to them on the mono- 
 chord is quite credible and involves no error in acoustics. 
 
 ./'^2. It was this, no doubt, that led Pythagoras to say all ^i^i^gs ar 
 pings were numbers. We shall see that, at a later date, the numbers, 
 rythagoreans identified these numbers with geometrical 
 figures ; but the mere fact that they called them " numbers,'* 
 taken in connexion with what we are told about the method 
 of Eurytos, is sufficient to show this was not th^? original 
 sense of the doctrine. It is enough to suppose thA Pytha- 
 goras reasoned somewhat as follows. |If musical sclinds can 
 be reduced to numbers, why not everything else! There 
 are many Hkenesses to number in things, and it may well 
 be that a lucky experiment, Uke that by which the octave 
 was discovered, will reveal their true numerical nature. 
 The Neopythagorean writers, going back in this as in other 
 matters to the earUest tradition of the school, indulge their 
 fancy in tracing out analogies between things and numbers 
 in endless variety ; but we are fortunately dispensed from 
 following them in these vagaries. Aristotle tells us dis- 
 tinctly that the Pythagoreans explained only a few things 
 by means of numbers,^ which means that Pythagoras him- 
 self left no developed doctrine on the subject, while the 
 Pythagoreans of the fifth century did not care to add any- 
 thing of the sort to the tradition. Aristotle does imply, 
 however, that according to them the '* right time " (/catpo?) 
 
 that, if they did, the weights hung to equal strings would produce the 
 notes. The number of vibrations really varies with the square root of 
 the weights. These inaccuracies were pointed out by Montucla (Martin, 
 Etudes sur le Timee, i. p. 391). 
 
 1 Arist. Met. M, 4. 1078 b 21 (R. P. 78). The Theologumena Arithmetica 
 is full of such fancies (R. P. 78 a). Alexander, in Met. p. 38, 8, gives a 
 few definitions which may be old (R. P. 78 c). 
 
ro8 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 was seven, justice was four, and marriage three J These 
 identifications, with a few others hke them, we miy safely 
 refer to Pythagoras or his immediate successors/ but we 
 
 1; must not attach too much importance to them. We 
 must start, not from them, but from any statements we 
 can find that present points of contact with the teaching of 
 the Milesian school. These, we may, fairly infer, belong to 
 the system in its most primitive form. 
 Cosmology. 53. Now the most striking statement of this kind is 
 one of Aristotle's. The Pythagoreai^ held, he tells us, 
 that there was " boundless breath "/Outside the heavens, 
 and that it was inhateti^^''ti!e^orld.^ In substance, that 
 is the doctrine of Anaximenes, and it becomes practically 
 certain that it was taught by Pythagoras, when we find 
 that Xenophanes denied it.^ We may infer that the further 
 development of the idea is also due to Pythagoras. We 
 are told that, after the first unit had been formed — however 
 that may have taken place — the nearest part of the Bound- 
 less was first draw^n in and limited ; ^ and that it is the 
 
 J Boundless thus inhaled that keeps the units separate from 
 
 I each other.* It represents the interval between them. 
 
 I This is a primitive way of describing discrete quantity. 
 
 ..,-,-i-Arist. Phys. A, 6. 213 b 22 (R. P. 75). 
 
 2 Diog. ix. 19 (R. P. 103 c), Hikov 5' bpav /cat 6\ov aKo^eiv, fir] /ul^ptol 
 Avairveiv {(prja-t. fi:,evo(pdpr]s). So in [Plut.] Strom, fr. 4 we read that 
 Xenophanes held fiij Kara ttolv fxipos irepi^x^'^^^'- ^'^^ d4pos [ttjv yrjv). We 
 may therefore ascribe the statement to Theophrastos without hesitation, 
 in spite of the fact that Diogenes is here drawing on an inferior (bio- 
 graphical) source, as shown by Diels {Dox. p. 168). Cf. also Hipp. Ref. 
 i, 14, 2, T7)v 5^ yT]u dTreipop elvai Kal fii^re vv' d^pos fxi^TC xiirb rod oipavov irepii- 
 Xeadat {'fi!,€vo(f>dvT]s \eyei). 
 
 3 Arist. Mei. N, 3. 1091 a 13 (R. P. 74). 
 
 4 Arist. Phys. A, 6. 213 b 23 (R. P. 75 a). The words diopi^ei rds 
 (pvaeis have caused unnecessary difficulty, because they have been supposed 
 to attribute the function of limiting to the dveipov. Aristotle makes it 
 quite clear that his meaning is that stated in the text. Cf. especially 
 the words x^P'-^P-^^ nvos tQu e<pe^ri$ /cat diopiaews. The term dioopia-pLipop, 
 " discrete," is the proper antithesis to avpex^s, " continuous." In his 
 work on the Pythagorean philosophy, Aristotle used instead the phrase 
 diopi^cL rds xwpas (Stob. i. p. 1 56, 8 ; R. P. 75), which is also quite in- 
 telligible if we remember what the Pythagoreans meant by x'^'P^ (cf- P- 
 104, n. 2). 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 
 
 109 
 
 In these passages of Aristotle, the " breath " is also 
 spoken of as the void or empty. This is a confusion we 
 have already met with in Anaximenes, and it need not 
 surprise us to find it here.^ We find also clear traces of the 
 other confusion, that of air and vapour. It seems certain, 
 in fact, that Pythagoras identified the Limit with fire, and 
 the Boundless with darkness. We are told by Aristotle 
 that Hippasos made Fire the first principle,^ and we shall 
 see that Parmenides, in discussing the opinions of his con- 
 temporaries, attributes to them the view that there were 
 two primary " forms,*' Fire and Night. ^ We also find that 
 Light and Darkness appear in the Pythagorean table of 
 opposites under the heads of the Limit and the Unlimited 
 respectively.* The identification of breath with darkness 
 Jiere implied is a strong proof of the primitive character of 
 I'the doctrine ; for in the sixth century darkness was supposed 
 ^. to be a sort of vapour, while in the fifth its-..t£ue..uature was 
 I known. Plato, with his usual historical tact, makes the 
 * Pythagorean Timaios describe mist and darkness as con- 
 densed air.^ We must think, then, of a " field " of darkness 
 or breath marked out by luminous units, an imagination 
 the starry heavens would naturally suggest. It is even 
 probable that we should ascribe to Pythagoras the Milesian 
 view of a pluraHty of worlds, though it would not have been 
 natural for him to speak of an infinite number. We know, 
 at least, that P^on, one of the early Pythagoreans, said 
 
 there were just a huMred and eighty-three worlds arranged 
 in a triangle.^ 1 
 
 ^ Cf. Arist. Phys. A, 6. 213 a 27, ol 5' ApOpooiroi . . . <paatv iv cp 5Xws 
 fji.r)d4v iaTi, tovt^ elvai Kevdv, 5i6 t6 xX^pes dipos Kevbv elvat ', De part. an. B, 
 10. 656 b 15, t6 ybip Kevbv Kokodfievov d^pos irXripis iari ; De an. B, lo. 419 
 b 34, doKeX yap etvai Kevbv 6 drip. 
 
 2 Arist. Mei. A, 3. 984 a 7 (R. P. 56 c). 3 See Chap. IV. § 91. 
 
 4 Arist. Met. A, 5. 986 a 25 (R. P. 66). & Plato, Tim. 58 d 2. 
 
 * This is quoted by Plutarch, De def. orac. 422 b, d, from Phanias of 
 Eresos, who gave it on the authority of Hippys of Rhegion. If we may 
 follow Wilamowitz {Hermes, xix. p. 444) in supposing that this really 
 means Hippasos of Metapontion (and it was in Rhegion that the Pytha- 
 goreans took refuge), this is a very valuable piece of evidence. 
 
no EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The 54. Anaximander had regarded the heavenly bodies as 
 
 bodii^^ wheels of "air" filled with fire which escapes through 
 certain orifices (§ 21), and there is evidence that Pythagoras 
 adopted the same view.^ We have seen that Anaximander 
 only assumed the existence of three such wheels, and it is 
 extremely probable that Pythagoras identified the intervals 
 between these with the three musicalr intervals he had dis- 
 covered, the fourth, the fifth, and the octave. That w^ould be 
 the most natural beginning for the doctrine of the " harmony 
 of the spheres," though the expression would be doubly 
 misleading if applied to any theory we can properly 
 ascribe to Pythagoras himself. The word dp/jbovla does 
 not mean harmony, but octave, and the " spheres " are an 
 anachronism. We are still at the stage when wheels or rings 
 were considered sufficient to account for the heavenly 
 bodies. 
 
 The distinction between the diurnal revolution of the 
 heavens from east to west, and the slower revolutions of the 
 sun, moon, and planets from west to east, may also be 
 referred to the early days of the school, and probably to 
 Pythagoras himself. ^ It obviously involves a complete 
 break with the theory of a vortex, and suggests that the 
 heavens are spherical. That, however, was the only way 
 to get out of the difficulties of Anaximander' s system. If 
 it is to be taken seriously, we must suppose that the motions 
 of the sun, moon, and planets are composite. On the one 
 
 1 This will be found in Chap. IV. § 93. 
 
 2 I formerly doubted this on the ground that Plato appeared to 
 represent the theory as a novelty in Laws, 822 a, but Professor Taylor 
 has convinced me that I was wrong. What Plato is denying in that 
 passage is this very doctrine, and the theory he is commending must be 
 that of a simple motion in a new form. This was a discovery of Plato's 
 old age ; in the Myth of Er in the Republic and in the Timaeus we still 
 have the Pythagorean theory of a composite motion. It is true that no 
 writer earlier than Theon of Smyrna (p. 150, 12) expressly ascribes this 
 theory to Pythagoras, but Actios (ii. 16, 2) says that Alkmaion, a younger 
 contemporary of Pythagoras, agreed with the mathematicians in holding 
 that the planets had an opposite motion to the fixed stars. His other 
 astronomical views were so crude (§ 96) that he can hardly have invented 
 this. 
 
 Jk 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION iii 
 
 hand, they have their own revolutions with varying angular 
 velocities from west to east, but they are also carried along 
 by the diurnal revolution from east to west. Apparently 
 this was expressed by saying that the motions of the 
 planetary orbits, which are oblique to the celestial equator, 
 are mastered {Kparelrai) by the diurnal revolution. The 
 lonians, down to the Demokritos, never accepted this view. 
 They clung to the theory of the vortex, which made it 
 necessary to hold that all the heavenly bodies revolved in 
 the same direction, so that those which, on the P^^thagorean 
 system, have the greatest angular velocity have the least 
 on theirs. On the Pythagorean view, Saturn, for instance, 
 takes about thirty years to complete its revolution ; on the 
 Ionian view it is '* left behind " far less than any other 
 planet, that is, it more nearly keeps pace with the signs of 
 the Zodiac.^ 
 
 For reasons which will appear later, we may confi- 
 dently attribute to Pythagoras himself the discovery of 
 the sphericity of the earth, which the lonians, even 
 Anaxagoras and Demokritos, refused to accept. It is 
 probable, however, that he still adhered to the geocentric 
 system, and that the discovery that the earth was a planet 
 belongs to a later generation (§ 150). 
 
 The account just given of the views of Pythagoras is, 
 no doubt, conjectural and incomplete. We have simply 
 assigned to him those portions of the Pythagorean system 
 which appear to be the oldest, and it has not even been 
 possible at this stage to cite fully the evidence on which 
 our discussion is based. It will only appear in its true light 
 when we have examined the second part of the poem of 
 Parmenides and the system of the later Pythagoreans. ^ 
 
 ^ See the account of the theory of Demokritos in Lucretius, v. 621 sqq., 
 and cf. above, p. 70. The technical term is u7r6Xeti/'ts. Strictly speaking, 
 the Ionian view is only another way of describing the same phenomena, 
 but it does not lend itself so easily to a consistent theory of the real 
 planetary motions. 
 
 2 See Chap. IV. §§ 92-93. and Chap. VII. §§ 150-152. 
 
112 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 It is clear at any rate that the great contribution of Pytha- 
 goras to science was his discovery that the concordant 
 intervals could be expressed by simple numerical ratios. 
 In principle, at least, that suggests an entirely new view of 
 the relation between the traditional " opposites." If a 
 perfect attunement [apixovia) of the high and the low can 
 be attained by observing these ration, it is clear that other 
 opposites may be similarly harmonised. The hot and the 
 cold, the wet and the dry, may be united in a just blend 
 {Kpaa-i^), an idea to which our word " temperature " still 
 bears witness. ^ The medical doctrine of the " tempera- 
 ments " is derived from the same source. Moreover, the 
 famous doctrine of the Mean is only an apphcation of 
 the same idea to the problem of conduct. ^ It is not too 
 much to say that Greek philosophy was henceforward to be 
 dominated by the notion of the perfectly tuned string. 
 
 II. Xenoppianes of Kolophon 
 
 Life. 55. We have seen how Pythagoras gave a deeper 
 
 meaning to the reUgious movement of his time ; we have 
 now to consider a very different manifestation of the reaction 
 against the view of the gods which the poets had made 
 famiUar. Xenophanes denied the anthropomorphic gods 
 altogether, but was quite unaffected by the revival of 
 reUgion going on all round him. We still have a fragment 
 of an elegy in which he ridiculed Pythagoras and the doctrine 
 of transmigration.^ We are also told that he opposed the 
 views of Thales and Pythagoras, and attacked Epimenides, 
 
 1 It is impossible not to be struck by the resemblance between this 
 doctrine and Dalton's theory of chemical combination. A formula like 
 HgO is a beautiful example of a fiea&rrfs. The diagrams of modern stereo- 
 chemistry have also a curiously Pythagorean appearance. We sometimes 
 feel tempted to say that Pythagoras had really hit upon the secret of 
 the world when he said, " Things are numbers." 
 
 2 Aristotle derived his doctrine of the Mean from Plato's Philebus, 
 where it is clearly expounded as a Pythagorean doctrine. 
 
 3 See fr. 7, below. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 113 
 
 which is hkely enough, though no fragments of the kind 
 have come down to us.^ 
 
 It is not easy to determine the date of Xenophanes. 
 Timaios, whose testimony in such matters carries weight, 
 said he was a contemporary of Hieron and Epicharmos, 
 and he certainly seems to have played a part in the anec- 
 dotical romance of Hieron's court which amused the Greeks 
 of the fourth century as that of Croesus and the Seven Wise 
 Men amused those of the fifth. ^ As Hieron reigned from 
 478 to 467 B.C., that would make it impossible to date the 
 birth of Xenophanes earlier than 570 B.C., even if we suppose 
 him to have Hved till the age of a hundred. On the other 
 hand, Clement says that Apollodoros gave 01. XL. (620- 
 616 B.c ) as the date of his birth, and adds that his days 
 were prolonged till the time of Dareios and Cyrus.^ Again, 
 Diogenes, whose information on such matters mostly comes 
 from Apollodoros, says he flourished in 01. LX. (540-537 B.C.), 
 and Diels holds that Apollodoros really said so.* However 
 that may be, it is evident that the date 540 B.C. is based 
 on the assumption that he went to Elea in the year of its 
 foundation, and is, therefore, a mere combination, which 
 need not be taken into account.^ 
 
 1 Diog. ix. 18 (R. P. 97). We know that Xenophanes referred to the 
 prediction of an edipse by Thales (Chap. I. p. 42, n. i). 
 
 2 Timaios ap. Clem. Strom, i. p. 353 (R. P. 95)- There is only one 
 anecdote which actually represents Xenophanes in conversation with 
 Hieron (Plut. Reg. apophth. 175 e), but it is natural to understand Arist. 
 Met. V. 5. 1 010 a 4 as an allusion to a remark made by Epicharmos to 
 him. Aristotle's anecdotes about Xenophanes probably come from the 
 romance of which Xenophon's Hieron is also an echo. 
 
 3 Clem, lac cit. The mention of Cyrus is confirmed by Hipp. Ref. i. 
 94. Diels thinks Dareios was mentioned first for metrical reasons ; but 
 no one has satisfactorily explained why Cyrus should be mentioned at 
 all, unless the early date was intended. On the whole subject, see Jacoby, 
 pp. 204 sqq., who is certainly wrong in supposing that &xpi- t^^ Aapeiov Kal 
 Kijpov xpovcov can mean " during the times of Dareios and Cyrus." 
 
 4 Rh. Mus. xxxi. p. 22. He adopts the suggestion of Ritter to read 
 TrevTrjKdaTTiv for TeaaapaKdarrjv in Clem. loc. cit. (N for M). But Apollodoros 
 gave Athenian archons, not Olympiads. 
 
 6 As Elea was founded by the Phokaians six years after they left 
 Phokaia_ (Herod, i. 164 sqq.) its date is just 540-39 B.C. Cf. the way in 
 which Apollodoros dated Empedokles by the era of Thourioi (§ 98). 
 
 8 
 
114 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 What we do know for certain is that Xenophanes had 
 led a wandering hfe from the age of twenty-five, and that 
 he was still alive and making poetry at the age of ninety-two. 
 He says himself (fr. 8 = 24 Karst. ; R. P. 97) : 
 
 There are by this time threescore years and seven that have 
 tossed my careworn soul ^ up and down the land of Hellas ; and 
 there were then five-and-twenty years from my birth, if I can 
 say aught truly about these matters. 
 
 It is tempting to suppose that in this passage Xenophanes 
 was referring to the conquest of Ionia by Harpagos, and 
 that he is, in fact, answering the question asked in another 
 poem 2 (fr. 22 = 17 Karst. ; R. P. 95 a) : 
 
 This is the sort of thing we should say by the fireside in the 
 winter-time, as we lie on soft couches after a good meal, drinking 
 sweet wine and crunching chickpeas : " Of what country are you, 
 and how old are you, good sir ? And how old were you When 
 the Mede appeared ? " 
 
 In that case, his birth would fall in 565 B.C., and his 
 connexion with Hieron would be quite credible. We note 
 also that he referred to Pythagoras in the past tense, and 
 is in turn so referred to by Herakleitos.^ 
 
 Theophrastos said that Xenophanes had " heard " 
 Anaximander,* and we shall see that he was acquainted 
 with the Ionian cosmology. When driven from his native 
 city, he Uved in Sicily, chiefly, we are told, at Zankle and 
 Katana.^ Like Archilochos before him, he unburdened his 
 soul in elegies and satires, which he recited at the banquets 
 where, we may suppose, the refugees tried to keep up the 
 
 1 Bergk {Litter aturgesch. ii. p. 418, n. 23) took cppovris here to mean 
 the literary work of Xenophanes, but it is surely an anachronism to 
 suppose that at this date it could be used like the Latin cura. 
 
 2 It was certainly another poem ; for it is in hexameters, while the 
 preceding fragment is in elegiacs. 
 
 3 Xenophanes, fr. 7 ; Herakleitos, frs. 16, 17. 
 
 4 Diog. ix. 21 (R. P. 96 a). 
 
 5 Diog. ix. 18 (R. P. 96). The use of the old name Zankle, instead of 
 the later Messene, points to an early source for this statement — probably 
 the elegies of Xenophanes himself. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 115 
 
 usages of good Ionian society. The statement that he was 
 a rhapsode has no foundation at all.^ The singer of elegies 
 was no professional Uke the rhapsode, but the social equal 
 of his listeners. In his ninety-second year he was still, we 
 have seen, leading a wandering Ufe, which is hardly consist- 
 ent with the statement that he settled at Elea and founded 
 a school there, especially if we are to think of him as 
 spending his last days at Hieron's court. ^ It is very 
 remarkable that no ancient writer expressly says he ever 
 was at Elea,^ and all the evidence we have seems inconsistent 
 with his having settled there at all. 
 
 56. According to Diogenes, Xenophanes wrote in hexa- Poems, 
 meters and also composed elegies and iambics against 
 Homer and Hesiod.* No good authority says anything 
 of his having written a philosophical poem.^ SimpHcius 
 tells us he had never met with the verses about the earth 
 
 1 Diog. ix. 18 (R. P. 97) says avrbs ippaxpifiSeL ra iavroO, which is a very 
 different thing. Nothing is said anywhere of his reciting Homer. Gom- 
 perz's imaginative picture (Greek Thinkers, vol. i. p. 155) has no further 
 support than this single word. 
 
 2 Diog. ix. 20 (R. P. 97) says he wrote a poem in 2000 hexameters 
 on the colonisation of Elea. Even if true, this would not prove he 
 lived there ; for the foundation of Elea would be a subject of interest 
 to all the Ionian emigres. Moreover, the statement is very suspicious. 
 The stichometric notices of the Seven Wise Men, Epimenides, etc., in 
 Diogenes come from the forger Lobon, and this seems to be from the 
 same source. 
 
 ' The only passage which brings him into connexion with Elea is 
 Aristotle's anecdote about the answer he gave the Eleates when they 
 asked him whether they should sacrifice to Leukothea. " If you think 
 her a goddess," he said, " do not lament her ; if you do not, do not 
 sacrifice to her " (RheL B, 26. 1400 b 5 ; R. P. 98 a). Even this does 
 not necessarily imply that he settled at Elea, and in any case such 
 anecdotes are really anonymous. Plutarch tells the story more than 
 once, but he makes it a remark of Xenophanes to the Egyptians {Diels, 
 Vors. II A 13), while others tell it of Herakleitos. 
 
 4 Diog. ix. 18 (R. P. 97). The word iiriKdxTcav is a reminiscence of 
 Timon, fr. 60 (Diels), 'S!iei.uo(pdvT]S VTrdTV<pos 'OfirjpaTrdTrjs iirLKOTTTris. 
 
 5 The oldest reference to a poem Ilepl cpvaeus is in the Geneva scholium 
 on //. xxi. 196 (quoting fr. 30), and this goes back to Krates of Mallos. 
 We must remember that such titles are of later date, and Xenophanes 
 had been given a place among philosophers long before the time of Krates. 
 All we can say, therefore, is that the Pergamene librarians gave the title 
 Uepl (pvaews to some poem of Xenophanes. 
 
ii6 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 stretching infinitely downwards (fr. 28),^ and this means that 
 the Academy possessed no copy of such a poem, which would 
 be very strange if it had ever existed. Simplicius was able 
 to find the complete works of much smaller men. Nor does 
 internal evidence lend any support to the view that Xeno- 
 phanes wrote a philosophical poem. Diels refers about 
 twenty-eight lines to it, but they would all come in quite 
 as naturally in his attacks on Homer and Hesiod, as I have 
 endeavoured to show. It is also significant that a number 
 of them are derived from commentators on Homer.^ It 
 is more probable, then, that Xenophanes expressed such 
 scientific opinions as he had incidentally in his satires. That 
 would be in the manner of the time, as we can see from the 
 remains of Epicharmos. 
 
 The satires are called Silloi by late writers, and this 
 name may go back to Xenophanes himself. It may, how- 
 ever, originate in the fact that Timon of Phleious, the 
 ' sillographer " (c. 259 B.C.), put much of his satire upon 
 philosophers into the mouth of Xenophanes. Only one 
 iambic Une has been preserved, and that is immediately 
 followed by a hexameter (fr. 14). This suggests that Xeno- 
 phanes inserted iambic hues among his hexameters in the 
 manner of the Margites. 
 The 57. I give the fragments according to the text and 
 
 arrangement of Diels. 
 
 Elegies 
 
 (I) 
 Now is the floor clean, and the hands and cups of all ; one 
 sets twisted garlands on our heads, another hands us fragrant 
 ointment on a salver. The mixing bowl stands ready, full of 
 
 1 Simpl. De caelo, p. 522, 7 (R. P. 97 b). It is true that two of our 
 fragments (25 and 26) are preserved by Simplicius, but he got them from 
 Alexander. Probably they were quoted by Theophrastos ; for it is plain 
 that Alexander had no first-hand knowledge of Xenophanes, or he would 
 not have been taken in by M.X.G. (See p. 126.) 
 
 2 Three fragments (27, 31, 33) come from the Homeric Allegories, two 
 (30. 32) are from Homeric scholia. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 117 
 
 gladness, and there is more wine at hand that promises never to 
 leave us in the lurch, soft and smelling of flowers in the jars. In 
 the midst the frankincense sends up its holy scent, and there is 
 cold water, sweet and clean. Brown loaves are set before us 
 and a lordly table laden with cheese and rich honey. The altar 
 in the midst is clustered round with flowers ; song and revel fill 
 the halls. 
 
 But first it is meet that men should hymn the god with joy, 
 with holy tales and pure words ; then after Ubation and prayer 
 made that we may have strength to do right — for that is in truth 
 the first thing to do — no sin is it to drink as much as a man can 
 take and get home without an attendant, so he be not stricken 
 in years. And of all men is he to be praised who after drinking 
 gives goodly proof of himself in the trial of skill, ^ as memory and 
 strength will serve him. Let him not sing of Titans and Giants 
 — those fictions of the men of old — nor of turbulent civil broils 
 in which is no good thing at all ; but to give heedful reverence 
 to the gods is ever good. 
 
 (2) 
 
 What if a man win victory in swiftness of foot, or in the 
 pentathlon, at Olympia, where is the precinct of Zeus by Pisa's 
 springs, or in wresthng, — what if by cruel boxing or that fearful 
 sport men call pankration he become more glorious in the citizens' 
 eyes, and win a place of honour in the sight of aU at the games, 
 his food at the pubUc cost from the State, and a gift to be an heir- 
 loom for him, — what if he conquer in the chariot-race, — ^he will 
 not deserve all this for his portion so much as I do. Far better 
 is our art than the strength of men and of horses ! These are 
 but thoughtless judgements, nor is it fitting to set strength before 
 goodly art.2 Even if there arise a mighty boxer among a people, 
 or one great in the pentathlon or at wrestling, or one excelling in 
 swiftness of foot — and that stands in honour before all tasks of 
 men at the games — the city would be none the better governed 
 for that. It is but Httle joy a city gets of it if a man conquer 
 at the games by Pisa's banks ; it is not this that makes fat the 
 store-houses of a city. 
 
 1 So I understand afx4> dpeTrjs. The rofos is " strength of lungs." 
 The next verses are directed against Hesiod and Alkaios (Diels). 
 
 2 At this date " art " is the natural translation of <xo(plT] in such a writer 
 as Xenophanes. 
 
ii8 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (3) 
 
 They learnt dainty and unprofitable ways from the Lydians, 
 so long as they were free from hateful tyranny ; they went to the 
 market-place with cloaks of purple dye, not less than a thousand 
 of them all told, vainglorious and proud of their comely tresses, 
 reeking with fragrance from cunning. salves. 
 
 (4) 
 Nor would a man mix wine in a cup by pouring out the wine 
 first, but water first and wine on the top of it. 
 
 (5) 
 Thou didst send the thigh-bone of a kid and get for it the fat 
 leg of a fatted bull, a worthy guerdon for a man to get, whose 
 glory is to reach every part of Hellas and never to pass away, so 
 long as Greek songs last.^ 
 
 (7) 
 
 And now I will turn to another tale and point the way. . . . 
 Once they say that he (Pythagoras) was passing by when a dog 
 was being beaten and spoke this word : " Stop ! don't beat it ! 
 For it is the soul of a friend that I recognised when I heard its 
 voice." 2 
 
 (8) 
 
 See p. 114. 
 
 (9) 
 
 Much weaker than an aged man. 
 
 Satires 
 
 (10) 
 
 Since all at first have learnt according to Homer. 
 
 n 
 
 1 Diels suggests that this is an attack on a poet like Simonides, whose 
 greed was proverbial. 
 
 2 The name of Pythagoras does not occur in the lines that have been 
 preserved ; but the source of Diogenes viii. 36 must have had the complete 
 elegy before him ; for he said the verses occurred iv iXeyeli^., ^s dpxv Nuv 
 adr dXXov ^ireiiu \6yov kt\. 
 
 dk 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 119 
 
 (II) 
 Homer and Hesiod have ascribed to the gods all things 
 that are a shame and a disgrace among mortals, stealings and 
 adulteries and deceivings of one another. R. P. 99. 
 
 (12) 
 
 Since they have uttered many lawless deeds of the gods, 
 steahngs and adulteries and deceivings of one another. R. P. ih. 
 
 (14) 
 
 But mortals deem that the gods are begotten as they are, 
 and have clothes Uke theirs, and voice and form. R. P. 100. 
 
 (15) 
 
 Yes, and if oxen and horses or Uons had hands, and could 
 paint with their hands, and produce works of art as men do, 
 horses would paint the forms of the gods like horses, and oxen 
 Uke oxen, and make their bodies in the image of their several 
 kinds. R. P. ih. 
 
 (16) 
 
 The Ethiopians make their gods black and snub-nosed ; the 
 Thracians say theirs have blue eyes and red hair. R. P. 100 b. 
 
 (18) 
 
 The gods have not revealed all things to men from the begin- 
 ning, but by seeking they find in time what is better. R. P. 
 104 b. 
 
 (23) 
 
 One god, the greatest among gods and men, neither in form 
 Uke unto mortals nor in thought. . . . R. P. 100. 
 
 (24) 
 
 He sees all over, thinks aU over, and hears all over. R. P. 
 102. 
 
 (25) 
 
 I But without toil he swayeth aU things by the thought of his 
 mind. R. P. 108 b. 
 
120 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (26) 
 
 And he abideth ever in the selfsame place, moving not at 
 all ; nor doth it befit him to go about now hither now thither. 
 R. P. no a. 
 
 (27) . 
 All things come from the earth, and in earth all things end. 
 R. P. 103 a. 
 
 (28) 
 
 This Umit of the earth above is seen at our feet in contact with 
 the air ; ^ below it reaches down without a limit. R. P. 103. 
 
 (29) 
 
 All things are earth and water that come into being and grow. 
 R. P. 103. 
 
 (30) 
 
 The sea is the source of water and the source of wind ; for 
 neither in the clouds (would there be any blasts of wind blowing 
 forth) from within without the mighty sea, nor rivers' streams 
 nor rain-water from the sky. The mighty sea is father of clouds 
 and of winds and of rivers. ^ R. P. 103. 
 
 (31) 
 
 The sun swinging over ^ the earth and warming it. . . . 
 
 (32) 
 
 She that fhey call Iris is a cloud likewise, purple, scarlet and 
 green to behold. R. P. 103. 
 
 (33) 
 
 For we all are born of earth and water. R. P. ib. 
 
 jt 
 
 1 Reading rj^pi for Kai pel with Diels. 
 
 2 This fragment has been recovered from the Geneva scholia on Homer 
 (see Arch. iv. p. 652). The words in brackets are added by Diels. 
 
 3 The word is iVepi^/zej/os. This is quoted from the Allegories as an 
 explanation of the name Hyperion, and doubtless Xenophanes so meant it. 
 
 Jl 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 121 
 
 (34) 
 
 There never was nor will be a man who has certain knowledge 
 about the gods and about all the things I speak of. Even if he 
 should chance to say the complete truth, yet he himself knows 
 not that it is so. But all may have their fancy.^ R. P. 104. 
 
 (35) 
 
 Let these be taken as fancies ^ something like the truth. 
 R. P. 104 a. 
 
 (36) 
 All of them ^ that are visible for mortals to behold. 
 
 (37) 
 
 And in some caves water drips. ... 
 
 (38) 
 
 If god had not made brown honey, men would think figs far 
 sweeter than they do. 
 
 ^S. Most of these fragments are not in any way philo- The 
 sophical, and those that appear to be so are easily accounted bodies! ^ 
 for otherwise. The intention of one of them (fr. 32) is clear. 
 " Iris too " is a cloud, and we may infer that the same thing 
 had been said of the sun, moon, and stars ; for the doxo- 
 graphers tell us that these were all explained as " clouds 
 ignited by motion." * To the same context clearly belongs 
 the explanation of the St. Elmo's fire which Actios has 
 preserved. " The things like stars that appear on ships," we 
 
 ^ It is more natural to take iraai as masculine than as neuter, and 
 iirl iracn can mean " in the power of all." 
 
 2 Reading SeSo^dadcj with Wilamowitz. 
 
 3 As Diels suggests, this probably refers to the stars, which Xenophanes 
 held to be clouds. 
 
 4 Cf. Diels ad loc. {P. Ph. Fr. p. 44), " ut Sol et cetera astra, quae 
 cum in nebulas evanescerent, deorum simul opinio casura erat." 
 
 \ 
 \ 
 
122 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 are told, "which some call the Dioskouroi, are Uttle clouds 
 made luminous by motion." ^ In the doxographers the 
 same explanation is repeated with trifling variations 
 under the head of moon, stars, comets, lightning, 
 shooting stars, and so forth, which gives the appearance 
 of a systematic cosmology. ^ But the system is due to 
 the arrangement of the work of Theophrastos, and not 
 to Xenophanes ; for it is obvious that a very few 
 additional hexameters would amply account for the whole 
 doxography. 
 
 What we hear of the sun presents some difficulties. 
 
 ^We are told that it is an ignited cloud ; but this is not 
 very consistent with the statement that the evaporation 
 
 ^of the sea from which clouds arise is due to the sun's 
 heat. Theophrastos stated that the sun, according to 
 Xenophanes, was a collection of sparks from the moist 
 exhalation ; but even this leaves the exhalation itself 
 unexplained.^ That, however, matters Httle, if the chief 
 aim of Xenophanes was to discredit the anthropo- 
 morphic gods, rather than to give a scientific theory of 
 the heavenly bodies. The important thing is that Helios 
 too is a temporary phenomenon. The sun does not go 
 round the earth, as Anaximander taught, but straight 
 on, and the appearance of a circular path is solely due to 
 its increasing distance. So it is not the same sun that 
 rises next morning, but a new one altogether ; while 
 eclipses occur because the sun " tumbles into a hole " 
 when it comes to certain uninhabited regions of the earth. 
 An echpse may last a month. Besides that, there are 
 
 ^ Aet. ii. 1 8, I {Dox. p. 347) > ^ePO(pdvr}i Toi)% iiri tCov ttXoiwv (paivo/xhovs 
 olov daripas, ods Kol AioaKOvpovs KaXoval Tcves, v€(p^\ia ehaL Kara ry]v ttololv ^ 
 KLvrjcrLv TrapaXdfMTTOVTa. 
 
 2 The passages from Actios are collected in Diels, Vors. ii a 38 sqq. 
 
 3 Aet. ii. 20, 3 {Dox. p. 348), 'iEi.epocpdvrjs €k vetpwv ireirvpwixivwv etvai 
 rbv ■¥j\lov. QedippacTTOs iv roh ^vffiKois y4ypa<p€v iK Trvpibioiv fxkv twv 
 <Tvva6poi^oixivo}v iK TT]s vypds dvadv/iiidaecos, avvadpoL^bvrwv 5k rbv ijXioy. 
 It seems likely from these words that Theophrastos pointed out the co: 
 tradiction, as his manner was. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 123 
 
 many suns and moons, one of each for every region of the 
 earth.i 
 
 The vigorous expression " tumbHng into a hole " ^ seems 
 clearly to come from the verses of Xenophanes himself, 
 and there are others of a similar kind, which we must' 
 suppose were quoted by Theophrastos. The stars go out 
 in the daytime, but glow again at night " like charcoal 
 embers." ^ The sun is of some use in producing the world 
 and the Uving creatures in it, but the moon " does no work 
 in the boat." * Such expressions can only be meant to 
 make the heavenly bodies appear ridiculous, and it will 
 therefore be well to ask whether the other supposed cosmo- 
 logical fragments can be interpreted on the same principle. 
 
 59. In fr. 29 Xenophanes says that " all things are earth Earth and 
 and water," and Hippolytos has preserved the account 
 given by Theophrastos of the context in which this occurred. 
 It was as follows : 
 
 Xenophanes said that a mixture of the earth with the sea is 
 taking place, and that it is being gradually dissolved by the 
 moisture. He says that he has the following proofs of this. 
 Shells are found in midland districts and on hills, and he says 
 that in the quarries at Syracuse has been found the imprint of 
 a fish and of seaweed, at Paros the form of a bayleaf in the depth 
 of the stone, and at Malta flat impressions of all marine animals. 
 These, he says, were produced when all things were formerly 
 mud, and the outlines were dried in the mud. All human beings 
 
 1 Aet. ii. 24, 9 {Dox. p. 355), ttoWovs elvat ijXiovs Kal o-eXiyi/as Karci 
 KXi/xara rijs 777s Kal dTroroyttds /cai fwi'as, Kara 84 riva Kaiphv ifMiriirreiv rbv 
 8l(tkov ets Tiva airoTOfiriv Trjs yrjs ovk oiKovfxhr]P v(f> TifxCov Kal ovtcjs (acirep Kevefi- 
 ^arovvra ^KXei^j/iv virocpalveiv ' 6 5' airbs t6v ijXiov els Aireipop fikv irpoUvai, doKetv 
 5^ KVKXeiadaL dia t7)u airixTraaLv. 
 
 2 That this is the meaning of Keve/x^ar^u} appears sufficiently from 
 the passages referred to in Liddell and Scott, and it describes a total 
 eclipse very well. 
 
 ^ Aet. ii. 13, 14 {Dox. p. 343), dva^wirvpe^v viKTiap Kaddirep roiis EvdpaKas. 
 
 * Aet. ii. 30, 8 {Dox. p. 362), rbv fih tjXlov xP'h'^'-l^^^ ^^'"^' "^P^^ "^^^ 
 rod Kbafiov Kal t^v tQv iv avT(^ (^'(fojv y^vealv re Kal di.oiKT](nv, ttjv 8^ aeXijpyjv 
 TrapeXKCLv. The verb 7ra/)A«:eti' means "to cork." (Cf. Aristophanes, 
 Pax, 1306.) In Hellenistic Greek the metaphor is no longer felt, and 
 wapiXKei means " is redundant," " is superfluous." 
 
124 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 are destroyed when the earth has been carried down into the 
 sea and turned to mud. This change takes place for all the 
 worlds. — Hipp. Ref. i. 14 (R. P. 103 a). 
 
 This is, of course, the theory of Anaximander, and we 
 may perhaps credit him rather than Xenophanes with the 
 observations of fossils.^ Most remarkable of all, however, 
 is the statement that this change appHes to " all the worlds." 
 
 ^^It seems impossible to doubt that Theophrastos attributed 
 a beUef in " innumerable worlds " to Xenophanes., As we 
 have seen, Actios includes him in his list of those who held 
 this doctrine, and Diogenes ascribes it to him also,^ while 
 Hippolytos seems to take it for granted. We shall find, 
 however, that in another connexion he said the World 
 or God was one. If our interpretation of him is correct, 
 there is no great difficulty here. The point is that, so far 
 from being " a sure seat for all things ever," Gaia too is a 
 passing appearance. That belongs to the attack on Hesiod, 
 and if in this connexion Xenophanes spoke, with Anaxi- 
 mander, of " innumerable worlds," while elsewhere he said 
 that God or the World was one, that may be connected with 
 a still better attested contradiction which we have now to 
 examine. 
 
 >r 60. Aristotle tried without success to discover from the 
 
 poems of Xenophanes whether he regarded the world as 
 finite or infinite. " He made no clear pronouncement on 
 the subject," he tells us.^ Theophrastos, on tlie other hand, 
 
 1 There is an interesting note on these in Gomperz's Ch'eek Thinkers 
 (Eng. trans, i. p. 551). I have translated his conjecture cf>vKQ}v instead of 
 the MS. (j)(i}kCov, as this is said to involve a palaeontological impossibiUty, 
 and impressions of fucoids are found, not indeed in the quarries of Syracuse, 
 but near them. It is said also that there are no marine fossils in Paros, 
 so the MS. reading 8d(pv7js need not be changed to ac/iijrjs with Gronovius. 
 The fact that the fossil was in the depth of the stone seemed to show that 
 Parian marble was once mud. It was no doubt imaginary. 
 
 2 Aet. ii. I, 2 {Dox. p. 327) ; Diog. ix. 19 (R. P. 103 c). It is true 
 that this passage of Diogenes comes from the biographical compendium 
 {Dox. p. 168) ; but it is difficult to doubt the Theophrastean origin of a 
 statement found in Actios, Hippolytos, and Diogenes. 
 
 3 Arist. Met. A, 5. 986 b 23 (R. P. loi), ovdh di€aa(p'rii'ia€P. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 125 
 
 decided that he regarded it as spherical and finite, because 
 he said it was *' equal every way." ^ It really appears that 
 Xenophanes did not feel the contradiction involved in calHng 
 the world " equal every way " and infinite. We have seen 
 that he said the sim went right on to infinity, and that agrees 
 with his view of the earth as an infinitely extended plain. 
 He also held (fr. 28) that, while the earth has an upper limit 
 which we see, it has no limit below. This is attested by 
 Aristotle, who speaks of the earth being " infinitely rooted," 
 and adds that Empedokles criticised Xenophanes for holding 
 this view. 2 It further appears from the fragment of Empe- 
 dokles quoted by Aristotle that Xenophanes said the vast 
 Air extended infinitely upwards.^ We are therefore bound 
 to try to find room for an infinite earth and an infinite air 
 in a spherical finite world ! That comes of trying to find 
 science in satire. If, on the other hand, we regard these 
 statements from the same point of view as those about the 
 heavenly bodies, we shall see what they probably mean. 
 The story of Ouranos and Gaia was always the chief scandal 
 of the Theogony, and the infinite air gets rid of Ouranos 
 altogether. As to the earth stretching infinitely downwards, 
 that gets rid of Tartaros, which Homer described as situated 
 at the bottommost Umit of earth and sea, as far beneath 
 Hades as heaven is above the earth.* This is pure con- 
 jecture, of course ; but, if it is even possible, we are 
 entitled to disbeUeve that it was in a cosmological poem 
 such startUng contradictions occurred. 
 
 1 This is given as an inference by Simpl. Phys. p. 23, 18 (R. P. 108 b), 
 dicL rb Travrax^dev bfxoLov. It does not merely come from M.X.G. 
 (R. P. 108), TrdvTy 5' bfioiov tpra (x<paipo€L8r] eivai. Hippolytos has it too 
 {Ref. i. 14 ; R. P. 102 a), so it goes back to Theophrastos. Timon 
 of Phleious understood Xenophanes in the same way ; for he makes him 
 call the One laov airavr-y (fr. 60, Diels ; R. P. 102 a). 
 
 2 Arist. De caelo, B, 13. 294 a 21 (R. P. 103 b). 
 
 3 I take daxffiXds as an attribute and airelpova as predicate to both 
 subjects. 
 
 * //. viii. 13-16, 478-481, especially the words ovB' et k€ to, veiara ireipad' 
 U-nac I yairji Kal irbvTOLo kt\. Iliad viii. must have seemed a particularly 
 bad book to Xenophanes. 
 
126 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 A more subtle explanation of the difficulty commended 
 itself to the late Peripatetic who wrote an account of the 
 Eleatic school, part of which is still extant in the AristoteHan 
 corpus, and is generally known now as the treatise on 
 Melissos, Xenophanes, and Gorgias.^ He said that Xeno- 
 phanes declared the world to be neither finite nor infinite, 
 and composed a series of arguments in support of this thesis, 
 to which he added another like it, namely, that the world 
 is neither in motion nor at rest. This has introduced endless 
 confusion into our sources. Alexander used this treatise 
 as well as the work of Theophrastos, and Simphcius supposed 
 the quotations from it to be from Theophrastos too. Having 
 no copy of the poems he was completely baffled, and until 
 recently all accounts of Xenophanes were vitiated by the 
 same confusion. It may be suggested that, but for this, we 
 should never have heard of the " philosophy of Xenophanes," 
 a way of speaking which is really a survival from the days 
 before this scholastic exercise was recognised as having no 
 authority. ■ 
 
 God and 6i. In the passage of the Metaphysics just referred to, ^ 
 
 Aristotle speaks of Xenophanes as ''the first partisan of. 
 the One," ^ and the context shows he means to suggest he I 
 was the first of the Eleatics. We have seen already that] 
 
 1 In Bekker's edition this treatise bears the title Ilepi fi!,evo(pdvovs, 
 trtpl Ti-^vcopos, irepl Topyiov, but the best MS. gives as the titles of its 
 three sections : (i) TJepl Z-Zipuvos, (2) Ilepl '^evocpavovs, (3) VLepl Topyiov. 
 The first section, however, plainly refers to Melissos, so the whole treatise 
 is now entitled De Melisso, Xenophane, Gorgia {M.X.G.). It has been 
 edited by Apelt in the Teubner Series, and more recently by Diels {Abh. 
 der k. Preuss. Akad. 1900), who has also given the section dealing with 
 Xenophanes in Vors. 11 a 28. He has now withdrawn the view main- 
 tained in Dox. p. 108 that the work belongs to the third century B.C., 
 and holds that it was a Peripatetico eclectico (i.e. sceptica, platonica, sioica , 
 admiscente) circa Christi natalem conscriptum. The writer would have no; 
 first-hand knowledge of his poems, and the order in which the philosophers 
 are discussed is that of the passage in the Metaphysics which suggested 
 the whole thing. It is possible that a section on Parmenides preceded 
 what we now have. 
 
 2 Met. A, 5. 986 b 21 (R. P. 1 01), TrpwTos tovtwv €vLaa$. The verb evL^eiv 
 occurs nowhere else, but is plainly formed on the analogy of ixriU^eiv, 
 (f>L\Linri^etv, and the like. 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 127 
 
 the certain facts of his life make it very unhkely that he 
 settled at Elea and founded a school there, and it is probable 
 that, as usual in such cases, Aristotle is simply reproducing 
 certain statements of Plato. At any rate, Plato had spoken 
 of the Eleatics as the " partisans of the Whole," ^ and he 
 had also spoken of the school as " starting with Xenophanes 
 and even earher." ^ xhe last words, however, show clearly 
 what he meant. Just as he called the Her akleit cans 
 " followers of Homer and still more ancient teachers," ^ 
 so he attached the Eleatics to Xenophanes and still earlier 
 authorities. We have seen before how these playful and 
 ironical remarks of Plato were taken seriously by his suc- 
 cessors, and we must not make too much of this fresh 
 instance of Aristotehan Hteralness. 
 
 Aristotle goes on to tell us that Xenophanes, " referring 
 to the whole world,* said the One was god." This 
 clearly alludes to frs. 23-26, where all human attributes 
 are denied of a god who is said to be one and " the 
 greatest among gods and men." It may be added that 
 these verses gain much in point if we think of them 
 as closely connected with frs. 11-16, instead of referring 
 the one set of verses to the Satires and the other to a 
 
 ^ Theaet. i8i a 6, rod okov araaiuTai. The noun a-Taanbrrjs has no other 
 meaning than " partisan," and the context shows that this is what it 
 means here. The derivation aracnuyras . . . dyrb Tijs ardaeus appears first 
 in Sext. Math. x. 46, where the term (rraa-twTat is incorrectly ascribed to 
 Aristotle and supposed to mean those who made the universe stationary, 
 an impossible interpretation. 
 
 2 Soph. 242 d 5 (R. P. loi b). If the passage implies that Xenophanes 
 settled at Elea, it equally implies this of his imaginary predecessors. But 
 Elea was not founded till Xenophanes was in the prime of life. 
 
 ^ Theaet. 179 e 3, tQu 'Hpa/cXetretwj/ ij, wawep aii X^yeis, 'Ofirjpeicov Kai ?ti 
 TToXaLOTepuv. Here Homer stands to the Herakleiteans in just the same 
 relation as Xenophanes does to the Eleatics in the Sophist. In just the 
 same spirit, Epicharmos, the contemporary of Xenophanes, is mentioned, 
 along with Homer, as a predecessor of the p^ovres [Theaet. 152 e). 
 
 * Met. 986 b 24. The words cannot mean " gazing up at the whole 
 heavens," or anything of that sort. They are taken as I take them by 
 Bonitz {im Hinhlicke auf den ganzen Himmel) and Zeller [im Hinblick auf 
 das Weltganze). The word diro^XiireLv had become too colourless to mean 
 more, and ovpavbs means what was later called K6<r/j.oi. 
 
128 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Mono- 
 theism or 
 poly- 
 theism. 
 
 cosmological poem. It was probably in the same context 
 that Xenophanes called the world or god " equal every 
 way " ^ and denied that it breathed. ^ The statement 
 that there is no mastership among the gods ^ also goes 
 very well with fr. 26. A god has no wants, nor is it 
 fitting for one god to be the servant of others, like Iris 
 and Hermes in Homer. 
 
 62. That this " god " is just the world, Aristotle tells 
 us, and the use of the word ^eo? is quite in accordance 
 with Ionian usage. Xenophanes regarded it as sentient, 
 though without any special organs of sense, and it 
 sways all things by the thought of its mind. He 
 also calls it " one god," and, if that is monotheism, 
 then Xenophanes was a monotheist, though this is 
 surely not how the word is generally understood. The 
 fact is that the expression ** one god " wakens all sorts 
 of associations in our mind which did not exist for the 
 ^Greeks of this time. What Xenophanes is really con- 
 I cerned to deny is the existence of any gods in the proper 
 / sense, and the words " One god " mean '' No god but the 
 world." * 
 
 It is certainly wrong, then, to say with Freudenthal 
 that Xenophanes was in any sense a polytheist.^ That he 
 should use the language of polytheism in his elegies is only 
 what we should expect, and the other references to " gods *' 
 can be best explained as incidental to his attack on the 
 anthropomorphic gods of Homer and Hesiod. In one case, 
 Freudenthal has pressed a proverbial way of speaking too 
 
 
 1 See above, p. 125, n. i. 
 
 2 Diog. ix. 19 (R. P. 103 c), 8\ov 8' opav Kal 6\ov aKOveiv, fxrj fxivroi dvairpetv. 
 See above, p. io8, n. 2. 
 
 ^ [Plut.] Strom, fr. 4, airocpalveTat 5k koI irepl deQjv ws ovdefiias TT/e/xovlas 
 iv aiiToXs oii<xr]s ' ov yap oaiov decnrS^eadal rcva tCcv 6eQv, iTideLadai re 
 /j,r]5€vbs avrdv [x-qMva firjd' 6Xu}$, 6.Koveiu dk Kal opau KadbXov Kal fii] Kara /xipos. 
 
 4 The fact that he speaks of the world as living and sentient makes 
 no difference. No Greek ever doubted that the world was in some sense 
 a ^cpov. 
 
 6 Freudenthal, Die Theologie des Xenophanes (Breslau, 1886). 
 
 i 
 
SCIENCE AND RELIGION 129 
 
 hard.^ Least of all can we admit that Xenophanes allowed 
 the existence of subordinate or departmental gods ; for it 
 was just the existence of such that he was chiefly concerned 
 to deny. At the same time, I cannot help thinking that 
 Freudenthal was more nearly right than Wilamowitz, who 
 says that Xenophanes " upheld the only real monotheism 
 that has ever existed upon earth." ^ Diels, I fancy, comes 
 nearer the mark when he calls it a '* somewhat narrow 
 pantheism." ^ But all these views would have surprised 
 Xenophanes himself about equally. He was really Goethe's 
 Weltkind, with prophets to right and left of him, and he 
 would have smiled if he had known that one day he was 
 to be regarded as a theologian. 
 
 ^ Xenophanes calls his god " greatest among gods and men," but this 
 is simply a case of " polar expression," to which parallels will be found in 
 Wilamowitz's note to Euripides' Herakles, v. 1106. Cf. especially the 
 statement of Herakleitos (fr. 20) that "no one of gods or men " made 
 the world, 
 
 2 Griechische Liter atur, p. 38. 
 
 3 Parmenides Lehrgedicht, p. 9. 
 
CHAPTER III 
 
 HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 
 
 Life of 63. Herakleitos of Ephesos, son of Bloson, is said to 
 
 Hera.- 
 
 kieitos. have " flourished " in 01. LXIX. (504/3-501/0 B.C.) ; ^ that 
 is to say, just in the middle of the reign of Dareios, with 
 whom several traditions connected him.^ It is more 
 important, however, for our purpose to notice that, while 
 Herakleitos refers to Pythagoras and Xenophanes by name 
 and in the past tense (fr. 16), he is in turn alluded to by 
 Parmenides (fr. 6). These references mark his place in the 
 history of philosophy. Zeller held, indeed, that he could 
 not have pubHshed his work till after 478 B.C., on the ground 
 that the expulsion of Hermodoros, alluded to in fr. 114, 
 could not have taken place before the downfall of Persian 
 rule. If that were so, it might be hard to see how Par- 
 menides could have known the views of Herakleitos at 
 the time he wrote his poem ; ^ but there is no difficulty 
 in supposing that the Ephesians may have sent one 
 of their citizens into banishment when they were still 
 paying tribute to the Great King. The spurious Letters 
 of Herakleitos show that the expulsion of Hermodoros 
 was believed to have taken place during the reign of 
 
 1 Diog. ix. I (R. P. 29), no doubt from Apollodoros through some 
 intermediate authority. The name Bloson is better attested than Blyson 
 (see Diels, Vors. 12 a i, n.), and is known from inscriptions as an Ionic 
 name. 
 
 2 Bernays, Die heraklitischen Brief e, pp. 13 sqq. 
 
 3 For the date of Parmenides, see p. 169. 
 
 130 
 
 i 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 131 
 
 Dareios/ and it seems probable that the party led by 
 him had enjoyed the confidence of the Persian govern- 
 ment. His expulsion would mark the beginnings of the 
 movement against Persian rule, rather than its successful 
 issue. 
 
 Sotion quotes a statement that Herakleitos was a disciple 
 of Xenophanes,2 which is not probable ; for Xenophanes 
 left Ionia before Herakleitos was born. More Hkely he^ 
 was not a disciple of any one„ ; but it is clear tnat newas 
 acquainted both with the Milesian cosmology and with the 
 poems of Xenophanes. He also knew something of the 
 theories taught by Pythagoras (fr. 17). Of his hfe we really 
 know nothing, except, perhaps, that he belonged to the 
 ancient royal house and resigned the nominal position of 
 Basileus in favour of his brother.^ The origin of the other 
 statements bearing on it is quite transparent.* 
 
 64. We do not know the title of the work of Herakleitos ^ His book, 
 ^-if, indeed, it had one — and it is not easy to form a clear 
 idea of its contents. We are told that it was divided into 
 three discourses : one dealing with the universe, one poHtical, 
 
 ^ Bernays, op. cit. pp. 20 sqq. This is quite consistent with the Roman 
 tradition that Hermodoros took part later in the legislation of the Twelve 
 Tables at Rome {Dig. i, 2, 2, 4 ; Strabo, xiv. p. 642). There was a statue 
 of him in the Comitium (Pliny, H.N. xxxiv. 21). The Romans were well 
 aware that the Twelve Tables were framed on a Greek model; and, as 
 Bernays said {op. cit. p. 85), the fact is attested as few things are in the 
 early history of Rome. 
 
 2 Sotion ap. Diog. ix. 5 (R. P. 29 c). 
 
 3 Diog. ix. 6 (R. P. 31). 
 
 * Herakleitos said (fr. 68) that it was death to souls to become water ; 
 and we are told accordingly that he died of dropsy. He said (fr. 114) 
 that the Ephesians should leave their city to their children, and (fr. 79) 
 that Time was a child playing draughts. We are therefore told that he 
 refused to take any part in public life, and went to play with the children 
 in the temple of Artemis. He said (fr. 85) that corpses were more fit to 
 be cast out than dung ; and we are told that he covered himself with 
 dung when attacked with dropsy. Lastly, he is said to have argued at 
 great length with his doctors because of fr. 58. For these tales see Diog. 
 
 ix. 3-5- 
 
 * The variety of titles enumerated in Diog. ix. 12 (R. P. 30 b) seems to 
 show that none was authentically known. That of " Muses " comes from 
 Plato, Soph. 242 d 7. The others are mere " mottoes " (Schuster) prefixed 
 by Stoic editors (Diog. ix. 15 ; R. P. 30 c). 
 
132 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 and one theological.^ It is not to be supposed that this 
 division is due to Herakleitos himself ; all we can infer is 
 that the work fell naturally into ;these three parts when the 
 Stoic commentators took their editions of it in hand. 
 
 The style of Herakleitos is proverbially obscure, and, at 
 a later date, got him the nickname of " the Dark." ^ Now 
 the fragments about the Delphic god and the Sibyl (frs. ii 
 and 12) seem to show that he was conscious of writing an 
 oracular style, and we have to ask why he did so. In the 
 first place, it was the manner of the time.^ The stirring 
 events of the age, and the influence of the rehgious revival, 
 gave something of a prophetic tone to all the leaders of 
 thought. Pindar and Aischylos have it too. It was also 
 an age of great individualities, and these are apt to be 
 solitary and disdainful. Herakleitos at least was so. If 
 men cared to dig for the gold they might find it (fr. 8) ; if 
 not, they must be content with straw (fr. 51). This seems 
 to have been the view taken by Theophrastos, who said the 
 headstrong temperament of Herakleitos sometimes led him 
 into incompleteness and inconsistencies of statement.* 
 
 The ^ 65. I give a version of the fragments according to the 
 
 arrangement of By water's exemplary edition : ^ 
 
 (i) It is wise to hearken, not to me, but to my Word, and to 
 confess that all things are one.^ R. P. 40. 
 
 1 Diog. ix. 5 (R. p. 30). By water followed this hint in his arrangement 
 . of the fragments. The three sections are 1-90, 91-97, 98-130. 
 
 2 R. P. 30 a. The epithet 6 <rK0Teiv6s is of later date, but Timon of 
 Phleious already called him alviKTrjs (fr. 43, Diels). 
 
 3 See the valuable observations of Diels in the Introduction to his 
 Herakleitos von Ephesos, pp. iv. sqq. 
 
 4 Cf. Diog. ix. 6 (R. P. 31). 
 6 In his edition, Diels has given up all attempt to arrange the fragments 
 
 according to subject, and this makes his text unsuitable for our purpose. 
 I think, too, that he overestimates the difficulty of an approximate arrange- 
 ment, and makes too much of the view that the style of Herakleitos was 
 " aphoristic." That it was so, is an important and valuable remark ; but 
 it does not follow that Herakleitos wrote like Nietzsche. For a Greek, 
 however prophetic in his tone, there must always be a distinction between 
 an aphoristic and an incoherent style. 
 
 8 Both Bywater and Diels accept Bergk's \6yov for dSyfiaros and 
 Miller's ehai for dbhai. Cf. Philo, Leg. all. iii. c 3, quoted in Bywater's note. 
 
 fragments. 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 133 
 
 (2) Though this Word ^ is true evermore, yet men are as 
 unable to understand it when they hear it for the first time as 
 before they have heard it at all. \Fov, though all things come to 
 pass in accordance with this Word, men seem as if they had no 
 experience of them, when they make trial of words and deeds 
 such as I set forth, dividing each thing according to its kind and 
 showing how it truly is. But other men know not what they 
 are doing when awake, even as they forget what they do in sleep7\ 
 R. P. 32. 
 
 (3) Fools when they do he^r are like the deaf : of them does 
 the sa5dng bear witness that they are absent when present. 
 R. P. 31 a. 
 
 r (4) Eyes and ears are bad witnesses to men if they have souls 
 that understand not their language.\ R. P. 42. 
 
 (5) The many do not take heed of such things as those they 
 meet with, nor do they mark them when they are taught, though 
 they think they do. 
 
 (6) Knowing not how to listen nor how to speak. 
 
 (7) If you do not expect the unexpected, you will not find it ; 
 for it is hard to be sought out and difficult. ^ 
 
 (8) Those who seek for gold -dig up much earth and find a 
 little. R. P. 44 b. 
 
 (10) Nature loves to hide. R. P. 34 f. 
 
 (11) The lord whose is the oracle at Delphoi neither utters 
 nor hides his meaning, but shows it by a sign. R. P. 30 a. 
 
 (12) And the Sibyl, with raving Ups uttering things mirthless, 
 
 1 The X670S is primarily the discourse of Herakleitos himself ; though, 
 as he is a prophet, we may call it his " Word." It can neither mean a 
 discourse addressed to Herakleitos nor yet " reason." (Cf. Zeller, p. 630, 
 w. I ; Eng. trans, ii. p. 7, n. 2.) A difficulty has been raised about the 
 words eovTos aid. How could Herakleitos say that his discourse had 
 always existed ? The answer is that in Ionic iiiiv means " true " when 
 coupled with words like X670S. Cf. Herod, i. 30, rip idvri xpV(^°-l^^'^os 
 X^7et ; and even Aristoph. Frogs, 1052, ovk 6vra \6yov. It is only by taking 
 the words in this way that we can understand Aristotle's hesitation as to 
 the proper punctuation {Rhet. F, 5. 1407 b 15 ; R, P. 30 a). The Stoic 
 interpretation given by Marcus Aurelius, iv. 46 (R. P. 32 b), must be 
 rejected. In any case, the Johannine doctrine of the X670S has nothing 
 to do with Herakleitos or with anything at all in Greek philosophy, but 
 comes from the Hebrew Wisdom literature. See Rendel Harris, " The 
 Origin of the Prologue to St. John's Gospel," in The Expositor, 1916, 
 pp. 147 sqq. 
 
 2 I have departed from the punctuation of Bywater here, and supplied 
 a fresh object to the verb as suggested by Gomperz {Arch. i. 100). 
 
134 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 unbedizened, and unperfumed, reaches over a thousand years 
 with her voice, thanks to the god in her. R. P. 30 a. 
 ; f (13) The things that can be seen, heard, and learned are 
 what I prize the most."^ R. P. 42. 
 
 (14) . . . bringing untrustworthy witnesses in support of 
 disputed points. 
 
 (15) The eyes are more exact witnesses than the ears.^ 
 R. P. 42 c. 
 
 (16) The learning of many things teacheth not understanding, 
 else would it have taught Hesiod and Pythagoras, and again 
 Xenophanes and Hekataios. R. P. 31. 
 
 (17) Pythagoras, son of Mnesarchos, practised scientific 
 inquiry beyond all other men, and making a selection of these 
 writings, claimed for his own wisdom what was but a knowledgeg^ 
 of many things and an imposture. 2 R. P. 31 a. ^P 
 
 (18) Of all whose discourses I have heard, there is not one 
 who attains to understanding that wisdom is apart from all. 
 R. P. 32 b. 
 
 (19) Wisdom is one thing. It , is to know the thought 
 by which all things are steered through aU things. R. P. 
 40. 
 
 (20) This world, 3 which is the same for all, no one of gods or 
 men has made ; but it was ever, is now, and ever shall be an 
 ever-Kving Fire, with measures of it kindling, and measures 
 going out. R. P. 35.4 
 
 1 Cf. Herod, i, 8. 
 
 ^ The best attested reading is iiroL-qaaTo, not eToirjaev, and iiroi-qaaTo 
 eavTov means " claimed as his own." The words iKXe^dfievos rairas ras 
 (rvyypa(f>ds have deen doubted since the time of Schleiermacher, and Diels 
 now regards the whole fragment as spurious. This is because it was used 
 to prove that Pythagoras wrote books (cf. Diels, Arch. iii. p. 451). As 
 Bywater pointed out, however, the fragment itself only says that he read 
 books. I would further suggest that the old-fashioned avyypa<pds is too 
 good for a forger, and that the omission of the very thing to be proved 
 would be remarkable. The last suggestion of a book by Pythagoras 
 disappears with the reading iiroL-qaaro for iiroi-qaev. For the rendering given 
 for KaKorexviv, compare its legal sense of " falsified evidence." 
 
 3 The word Koafj-os must mean " world " here, not merely " order " ; 
 for only the world could be identified with fire. This use of the word is 
 Pythagorean, and Herakleitos may quite well have known it. 
 
 * It is important to notice that fi^rpa is internal accusative with 
 airrdfjLepov, " with its measures kindhng and its measures going out." 
 This interpretation, which I gave in the first edition, is now adopted 
 Diels {Vors.^ 12 b 30 n.). 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 135 
 
 (21) The transformations of Fire are, first of all, sea ; and 
 half of the sea is earth, half whirlwind.^ ... R. P. 35 b. 
 
 (22) All things are an exchange for Fire, and Fire for all things, 
 even as wares for gold and gold for wares. R. P. 35. 
 
 (23) It becomes liquid sea, and is measured by the same tale 
 as before it became earth. ^ R. P. 39. 
 
 (24) Fire is want and surfeit. R. P. 36 a. 
 
 (25) Fire lives the death of air,^ and air lives the death of 
 fire ; water lives the death of earth, earth that of water. R. P. 37. 
 
 (26) Fire in its advance will judge and convict * all things. 
 R, P. 36 a. 
 
 {27) How can one hide from that which never sets ? 
 
 (28) It is the thunderbolt that steers the course of all things. 
 R. P. 35 b. 
 
 (29) The sun will not overstep his measures ; if he does, the 
 Erinyes, the handmaids of Justice, will find him out. R. P. 39. 
 
 {30) The limit of dawn and evening is the Bear ; and opposite 
 the Bear is the boundary of bright Zeus.^ 
 
 (31) If there were no sun it would be night, for all the other 
 stars could do.^ 
 
 (32) The sun is new every day. 
 
 1 On the word irprjaTrip, see below, p. 149, n. i. 
 
 2 The subject of fr. 23 is yrj, as we see from Diog. ix. 9 (R. P. 36), 
 TrdXtJ/ re aC Trjv yrjv x"0'^at .' and Aet. i. 3, II {Dox. p. 284 a I ; b 5), 
 ^Tretra dvaxaXw/i^i'T;?' tt]v yrjv virb tov irvpbs x^^^^ (Diibner : <p6a€i, libri) 
 ijScjp oLTTOTeXeicrdai. Herakleitos may have said 777 daXaaaa Siax^erat, and 
 Clement (Strom, v. p. 712) seems to imply this. The phrase fierpierai 
 eh rbv avTov \6yov can only mean that the proportion of the measures 
 remains constant. So Zeller (p. 690, n. i), zu derselben Grosse. Diels 
 (Vors. 12 B 31 n.) renders " nach demselben Wort [Gesetz)," but refers to 
 Lucr. V. 257, which supports the other interpretation {pro parte sua). 
 
 3 It is doubtful whether this fragment is quoted textually. It seems 
 to imply the four elements of Empedokles. 
 
 * I understand iireKdbv of the irvpbs ^<f>odos, for which see p. 151, n. i. 
 Diels has pointed out that KaraXa/ipdvetp is the old word for " to convict." 
 
 5 Here it is clear that odpos=T4pfiaTa, and therefore means "boundary," 
 not "hill." Strabo, who quotes the fragment (i. 6, p. 3), is probably 
 right in taking rjovs Kal iair^pas as equivalent to dvaroXiis /cat Stycreos and 
 making the words refer to the " arctic " circle. As aWpios Zei^s means 
 the bright blue sky, it is impossible for its odpos to be the South Pole, as 
 Diels suggests. It is more likely the horizon. I take the fragment as 
 a protest against the Pythagorean theory of a southern hemisphere. 
 
 6 We learn from Diog. ix. 10 (quoted below, p. 147) that Herakleitos 
 explained why the sun was warmer and brighter than the moon, and this 
 is. doubtless a fragment of that passage. 
 
136 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (33) (Thales foretold an eclipse.) 
 
 (34) . . . the seasons that bring all things. 
 
 (35) Hesiod is most men's teacher. Men are sure he knew 
 very many things, a man who did not know day or night ! They 
 are one.^ R. P. 39 b. 
 
 (36) God is day and night, winter and summer, war and 
 peace, surfeit and hunger ; but he takes various shapes, just as 
 fire, 2 when it is mingled with spices, is named according to the 
 savour of each. R. P. 39 b. 
 
 (37) If all things were turned to smoke, the nostrils would 
 distinguish them. 
 
 (38) Souls smell in Hades. R. P. 46 d. 
 
 ((39) Cold things become warm, and what is warm cools ; 
 what is wet dries, and the parched is moistened. 
 
 (40) It scatters and it gathers ; it advances and retires. 
 (41, 42) You cannot step twice into the same rivers ; for 
 fresh waters are ever flowing in upon you. R. P. 33. 
 
 (43) Homer was wrong in saying : " Would that strife might 
 perish from among gods and men ! " He did not see that 
 he was praying for the destruction of the universe ; for, if 
 his prayer were heard, all things would pass away.^ . . . 
 R. P. 34 d. . 
 
 (44) War is the father of all and the king of all ; and some 
 he has made gods and some men, some bond and some free. 
 
 R.P.34- . 
 
 (45) Men do not know how what is at variance agrees with 
 itself. It is an attunement of opposite tensions,* like that of 
 the bow and the lyre. R. P. 34. 
 
 (46) It is the opposite which is good for us.^ 
 
 .. (47) The hidden attunement is better than the open. R. P. 34. 
 1^ (48) Let us not conjecture at random about the greatest 
 things. 
 
 * Hesiod said Day was the child of Night {Theog. 124). 
 
 2 Reading SKcoa-Trep irvp for bKoja-rrep with Diels. 
 
 3 //. xviii. 107. I add oixna^crdaL yAp irdvTa from Simpl. in Cat. 
 412, 26. It must represent something that was in the original. 
 
 * I cannot believe Herakleitos said both iraXLuTouos and iraXipTpoiros. 
 apfioAT], and I prefer Plutarch's iraXivrovos (R. P. 34 b) to the TraXlvrpoiros oi 
 Hippolytos. Diels thinks that the polemic of Parmenides favours xaXlv 
 Tpoiros, but see below, p. 164, n. i, and Chap. IV. p. 174, n. 3. 
 
 6 This refers to the medical rule al 8' larpeiat Std ruv ivavrliav, e.g. 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 137 
 
 (49) Men that love wisdom must be acquainted with very 
 many things indeed. 
 
 (50) The straight and the crooked path of the fuller's comb 
 is one and the same. 
 
 (51) Asses would rather have straw than gold. R. P. 31 a. 
 (5i«) 1 Oxen are happy when they find bitter vetches to eat. 
 
 R. P. 48 b. 
 
 (52) The sea is the purest and the impurest water. Fish can 
 drink it, and it is good for them ; to men it is undrinkable and 
 destructive. R. P. 47 c. 
 
 (53) Swine wash in the mire, and barnyard fowls in dust. 
 
 (54) ... to delight in the mire. 
 
 (55) Every beast is driven to pasture with blows. ^ 
 
 (56) Same as 45. 
 
 (57) Good and ill are one. R. P. 47 c. ) 
 
 (58) Physicians who cut, burn, stab, and rack the sick, 
 demand a fee for it which they do not deserve to get. R. P. 
 47C.3 
 
 (59) Couples are things whole and things not whole, what 
 is drawn together and what is drawn asunder, the harmonious 
 and the discordant. The one is made up of all things, and all 
 things issue from the one.^ 
 
 (60) Men would not have known the name of justice if these 
 things were not.^ 
 
 (61) To God all things are fair and good and right, but men 
 hold some things wrong and some right. R. P. 45. 
 
 (62) We must know that war is common to all and strife is 
 justice, and that all things come into being and pass away (?) 
 through strife. 
 
 (64) All the things we see when awake are death, even as all 
 we see in slumber are sleep. R. P. 42 c.^ 
 
 1 See Bywater in Journ. Phil. ix. p. 230. 
 
 2 On fr. 55 see Diels in Berl. Sitzh., 1901, p. 188. 
 
 3 I now read eiraiT^ovrai with Bernays and Diels, 
 
 ^ On fr. 59 see Diels in Berl. Sitzb., 1901, p. 188. The reading 
 (xvv6.\pie$ seems to be well attested and gives an excellent sense. The 
 alternative reading a-vWdrj/ies is preferred by HofiEmann, Gr. Dial. iii. 
 240. 
 
 6 By " these things " he probably meant all kinds of injustice. 
 
 8 Diels supposes that fr. 64 went on oKSa-a 5^ redvTjKdres ^wt}. " Life, 
 Sleep, Death is the threefold ladder in psychology, as in physics Fire, 
 Water, Earth." 
 
138 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (65) The wise is one only. It is unwilling and willing to be 
 called by the name of Zeus. R. P. 40. 
 
 (66) The bow (/5ios) is called life (/Slos), but its work is death. 
 R. P. 49 a. 
 
 (67) Mortals are immortals and immortals are mortals, the 
 one living the others' death and dying the others' Hfe. R. P. 46. 
 
 (68) For it is death to souls to become water, and death to 
 water to become earth. But water comes from earth ; and from 
 water, soul. R. P. 38. 
 
 (69) The way up and the way down is one and the same. 
 R. P. 36 d. 
 
 (70) In the circumference of a circle the beginning and end 
 are common. 
 
 (71) You will not find the boundaries of soul by travelling in 
 any direction, so deep is the measure of it.^ R. P. 41 d. 
 
 (72) It is pleasure to souls to become moist. R. P. 46 c. 
 
 (73) A man, when he gets drunk, is led by a beardless lad, 
 tripping, knowing not where he steps, having his soul moist. 
 R. P. 42. 
 
 (74-76) The dry soul is the wisest and best.^ R. P. 42. 
 
 (77) Man kindles a light for himself in the night-time, when 
 he has died but is alive. The sleeper, whose vision has been put 
 out, lights up from the dead ; he that is awake lights up from 
 the sleeping.^ 
 
 1 The words ovtco ^adiiv \6yov ix^i present no difficulty if we remember 
 that \6yos means " measurement," as in fr. 23. 
 
 ^ This fragment is interesting because of the antiquity of the corrup- 
 tions it has suffered. According to Stephanus, who is followed by By water, 
 we should read : AUr) rj/vxv aocpwrdrTj koI dpiaTrj, ^rjpri being a mere gloss 
 upon adr]. When once ^rjpr} got into the text, aifrj became avyn, and we 
 get the sentence, " the dry light is the wisest soul," whence the siccum 
 lumen of Bacon. Now this reading is as old as Plutarch, who, in his 
 Life of Romulus (c. 28), takes avy-f} to mean lightning, as it sometimes^ 
 does, and supposes the idea to be that the wise soul bursts through the^ 
 prison of the body like dry lightning (whatever that may be) through a^ 
 cloud. (It should be added that Diels now holds that avyy) ^rjpT] x/yvx^ 
 <T0(p(x)TdT7] Kal dpia-TTj is the genuine reading.) Lastly, though Plutarch must 
 have written au7?7, the MSS. vary between aiirr] and avrri (cf. De def. or. 
 432 f. dvTT} yap ^Tjpd \pvxri in the MSS.). The next stage is the corruption of 
 the avyi^ into o5 7^. This yields the sentiment that " where the earth is 
 dry, the soul is wisest," and is as old as Philo (see By water's notes). 
 
 ' I adopt the fuller text of Diels here. It is clear that Death, Sleep, 
 Waking correspond to Earth, Water, Air in Herakleitos (cf. fr. 68). 1 
 think, however, that we must take dirrerai in the same sense aU through 
 the fragment, so I do not translate "is in contact with," as Diels does. 
 
 d 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 139 
 
 (yS) And it is the same thing in us that is quick and dead, 
 awake and asleep, young and old ; the former are shifted ^ and 
 become the latter, and the latter in turn are shifted and become 
 the former. R. P. 47. 
 
 (79) Time is a child playing draughts, the kingly power is a 
 child's. R. P. 40 a. 
 
 (80) I have sought for myself. R. P. 48. 
 
 (81) We step and do not step into the same rivers ; we are 
 and are not. R. P. 33 a. 
 
 (82) It is a weariness to labour for the same masters and be 
 ruled by them. 
 
 (83) It rests by changing. 
 
 (84) Even the posset separates if it is not stirred. 
 
 (85) Corpses are more fit to be cast out than dung. 
 
 (86) When they are born, they wish to live and to meet with 
 their dooms — or rather to rest — and they leave children behind 
 them to meet with their dooms iji turn. 
 
 (87-89) A man may be a grandfather in thirty years. 
 
 (90) Those who are asleep are fellow-workers (in what goes 
 on in the world). 
 
 (91^) Thought is common to all. 
 
 (gib) Those who speak with understanding must hold fast 
 to what is common to aU as a city holds fast to its law, and even 
 more strongly. For all human laws are fed by the one divine 
 law. It prevails as much as it will, and suffices for all things with 
 something to spare. R. P. 43. 
 
 (92) So we must foUow the common,^ yet though my Word is 
 common, the many live as if they had a wisdom of their own. 
 R. P. 44. 
 
 (93) They are estranged from that with which they have 
 most constant intercourse.^ R. P. 32 b. 
 
 (94) It is not meet to act and speak Hke men asleep. 
 
 * I understand /ieTa7re(r6j'Ta here as meaning "moved" from one 7/30/^/^77 
 or division of the draught-board to another. 
 
 2 Sext. Math. vii. 133, dib del Headai tQ kolu(^ (so the MSS. : ^vv(^ 
 Schleiermacher), ^wbs y^p 6 kolv6s. Bywater omits the words, but I 
 think they must belong to Herakleitos, Diels adopts Bekker's suggestion 
 to read 8l6 del 'iirecrdai rtp <^vv(^, TovT^art r<p> koivc^. I now think also that, 
 if we understand the term \6yos in the sense explained above (p. 133, n. i), 
 there is no reason to doubt the words which follow. 
 
 8 The words \6y<^ ry rd S\a Sioikovvti belong to Marcus AureHus and 
 not to Herakleitos. 
 
140 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (95) The waking have one common world, but the sleeping 
 turn aside each into a world of his own. 
 
 (96) The way of man has no wisdom, but that of God has. 
 
 R. P. 45. 
 
 (97) Man is called a baby by God, even as a child by a man. 
 
 R. P. 45. 
 
 (98, 99) The wisest man is an ape compared to God, just as 
 the most beautiful ape is ugly compared to man. 
 
 (lOo) The people must fight for its law as for its walls. 
 R. P. 43 b. 
 
 (loi) Greater deaths win greater portions. R. P. 49 a. 
 
 (102) Gods and men honour those who are slain in battle. 
 R. P. 49 a. 
 
 (103) Wantonness needs putting out, even more than a house 
 on fire. R. P. 49 a. 
 
 (104) It is not good for men to get all they wish to get. It 
 is sickness that makes health pleasant ; evil,^ good ; hunger, 
 plenty ; weariness, rest. R. P. 48 b. 
 
 {105-107) It is hard to fight with one's heart's desire. ^ 
 Whatever it wishes to get, it purchases at the cost of soul. 
 R. P. 49 a. 
 
 (108, 109) It is best to hide folly ; but it is hard in times of 
 relaxation, over our cups. 
 
 (no) And it is law, too, to obey the counsel of one. R. P. 49 a. 
 
 (in) For what thought or wisdom have they ? They follow 
 the poets and take the crowd as their teacher, knowing not that 
 there are many bad and few good. For even the best of them 
 choose one thing above all others, immortal glory among mortals, 
 while most of them are glutted like beasts.^ R. P. 31 a. 
 
 (112) In Priene lived Bias, son of Teutamas, who is 
 of more account than the rest. (He said, " Most men are 
 bad.") 
 
 (113) One is ten thousand to me, if he be the best. R. P. 31 a. 
 
 (114) The Ephesians would do well to hang themselves, 
 every grown man of them, and leave the city to beardless lads ; 
 for they have cast out Hermodoros, the best man among them, 
 
 1 Adopting Heitz's KaKbv for kuI with Diels, 
 
 2 The word 6vijl6s has its Homeric sense. The gratification of desire 
 impUes the exchange of dry soul-fire (fr, 74) for moisture (fr. 72). Aristotle 
 misunderstood 9vfjt,6s here as anger {Eth. Nic. B, 2. 1105 a 8). 
 
 * This seems to refer to the " three Uves," Chap. II. § 45, p. 98. 
 
 d 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 141 
 
 sa5dng, " We will have none who is best among us ; if there be 
 any such, let him be so elsewhere and among others." ^ R. P. 29 b. 
 
 (115) Dogs bark at every one they do not know. R. P. 
 31 a. 
 
 (116) . . . (The wise man) is not known because of men's 
 want of belief. 
 
 (117) The fool is fluttered at every word. R. P. 44 b. 
 
 (118) The most esteemed of them knows but fancies,^ and 
 holds fast to them, yet of a truth justice shall overtake the 
 artificers of lies and the false witnesses. 
 
 (119) Homer should be turned out of the lists and whipped, 
 and Archilochos Hkewise. R. P. 31. 
 
 (120) One day is like any other. -^ 
 (ji2i) Man's character is his fate.^^f 
 
 (122) There awaits men when they die such things as they 
 look not for nor dream of. R. P. 46 d. 
 
 (123) . . . *that they rise up and become the wakeful 
 guardians of the quick and dead. R. P. 46 d. 
 
 (124) Night-walkers, Magians, Bakchoi, Lenai, and the 
 initiated . . . 
 
 (125) The mysteries practised among men are unholy 
 mysteries. R. P. 48. 
 
 (126) And they pray to these images, as if one were to talk 
 with a man's house, knowing not what gods or heroes are. 
 R. P. 49 a. 
 
 (127) For if it were not to Dionysos that they made a proces- 
 sion and sang the shameful phallic hymn, they would be acting 
 most shamelessly. But Hades is the same as Dionysos in whose 
 honour they go mad and rave. R. P. 49. 
 
 (129, 130) They vainly purify themselves by defiling them- 
 selves with blood, just as if one who had stepped into the mud 
 were to wash his feet in mud. Any man who marked him doing 
 thus, would deem him mad. R. P. 49 a. 
 
 1 He went to Italy and took part in framing the Twelve Tables at 
 Rome. See p. 131, w. i. 
 
 2 Reading boKiovra with Schleiermacher (or Sok^ovt S)v with Diels). 
 I also read yLvda-Ket, (pvXdaa-et with Diels, who quotes the combination 
 (pvXdacrovai Kal yiudocrKovaL from Hippokrates. 
 
 * On the meaning of dalfiuv here, see my edition of Aristotle's Ethics, 
 pp. I sq. 
 
 * I have not ventured to include the words ivda 5' idvri at the beginning, 
 as the text seems to me too uncertain. See, however, Diels's note. 
 
142 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Thedoxo- 66. Some of these fragments are far from clear, and 
 tradition, there are probably not a few of which the meaning will 
 never be recovered. We turn, then, to the doxographers 
 for a clue ; but unfortunately they are less instructive with 
 regard to Herakleitos than we have found them in other 
 cases. Hippolytos, on whom we can generally rely for a 
 fairly accurate accoimt of what Theophrastos said, derived 
 the material for his first four chapters, which treat of Thales, 
 Pythagoras, Herakleitos, and Empedokles, not from the 
 excellent epitome he afterwards used, but from a bio- 
 graphical compendium, 1 mostly consisting of apocryphal 
 anecdotes and apophthegms. It was based, further, on 
 some writer of Successions who regarded Herakleitos as a 
 Pythagorean. The Hnk between him and the Pythagoreans 
 was Hippasos, in whose system fire played an important 
 part. Theophrastos, following Aristotle, had spoken of the 
 two in the same sentence, and that was enough for the 
 writers of Successions.^ We are forced, then, to look to the 
 more detailed of the two accoimts of the opinions of Hera- 
 kleitos given in Diogenes,^ which goes back to the Vetusta 
 Placita, and is, fortunately, pretty full and accurate. 
 
 Another difficulty we have to face is that most of the 
 commentators on Herakleitos mentioned in Diogenes were 
 Stoics.* Now, the Stoics held the Ephesian in peculiar 
 veneration, and sought to interpret him as far as possible 
 in accordance with their own system. Further, they were 
 fond of " accommodating " ^ the views of earlier thinkers! 
 to their own, and this has had serious consequences. In 
 
 1 See Diels, Dox. p, 145. We must distinguish Ref. i. and Ref. ix, 
 as sources of information about Herakleitos. The latter book is ai 
 attempt to show that the Monarchian heresy of Noetos was derived fron 
 Heraldeitos, and is a rich mine of Herakleitean fragments. 
 
 2 Arist. Met. A, 3. 984 a 7 (R. P. 56 c) ; Theophr. ap. Simpl. Phys. 23 
 33 (R. P. 36 c). 
 
 8 For these double accounts see Note on Sources, § 15. 
 
 * Diog. ix. 15 (R. P. 30 c). Schleiermacher rightly insisted upon this 
 
 5 The word awoLKeLovv is used of the Stoic method of interpretation b] 
 
 Philodemos (cf. Dox. 547 b, n.), and Cicero {N.D. i. 41) renders it b] 
 
 accommodare. 
 
 I 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 143 
 
 particular, the Stoic theories of the \0709 and the eKirvpaxTtf; 
 are cc»nstantly ascribed to Herakleitos, and the very frag- 
 ments, are adulterated with scraps of Stoic terminology. 
 
 67) Herakleitos looks down not only on the mass of men, The 
 but on all previous inquirers into nature. This must mean oJ^^Jra^ 
 t|nat he believed himself to have attained insight into some kieitos. 
 truth not hitherto recognised, though it was staring men in 
 the face (fr. 93). To get at the central thing in his teaching, 
 we must try then to find out what he was thinking of when 
 he launched into those denunciations of human dulness and 
 ignorance. The answer seems to be given in two fragments, - — - 
 18 and 45. From them we gather that the truth hitherto 
 ignored is that the many apparently independent and con- 
 flicting things we know are really one, and that, on the other 
 hand, this one is also many. The " strife of opposites '* is 
 really an " attunement " (dpfiovLo). From this it follows 
 that wisdom is not a knowledge of many things, but the 
 perception of the underlying unity of the warring opposites. 
 That this really was the fundamental thought of Herakleitos 
 is stated by Philo. He says : " For that which is made up 
 of both the opposites is one ; and, when the one is divided, 
 the opposites are disclosed. Is not this just what the Greeks 
 say their great and much belauded Herakleitos put in the 
 forefront of his philosophy as summing it all up, and boasted 
 of as a new discovery ? " ^ 
 
 68. Anaximander had taught that the opposites were The one 
 separated out from the Boundless, but passed away into it ^^y^^ 
 once more, so paying the penalty to one another for their 
 unjust encroachments. It is here implied that there is 
 something wrong in the war of opposites, and that the 
 existence of the opposites is a breach in the unity of the One. 
 The truth Herakleitos proclaimed was that the world is at 
 once one and many, and that it is just the " opposite tension *' 
 of the opposites that constitutes the unity of the One. It 
 is the same conclusion as that of Pythagoras, though it is 
 
 1 Philo, Rer. div. her. 43 (R. P. 34 e). 
 
144 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 put in another way. The use of the word dpfioviTj su^ggests 
 that Herakleitos had come under the influence of hisij older 
 contemporary to some extent. ^ 
 
 Plato clearly states that this was the central th^ought 
 of Herakleitos. In the Sophist (242 d), the Eleatic stri. 7ger, 
 after explaining how the Eleatics maintained that what vv^^e 
 call many is really one, proceeds : 
 
 But certain Ionian and (at a later date) certain Sicilian 
 Muses remarked that it was safest to unite these two things, and 
 to say that reality is both many and one, and is kept together by 
 Hate and Love. " For," say the more severe Muses, " in its 
 division it is always being brought together " (cf. fr. 59) ; while 
 the softer Muses relaxed the requirement that this should always 
 be so, and said that the All was alternately one and at peace 
 through the power of Aphrodite, and many and at war with itself 
 because of something they called Strife. 
 
 
 
 In this passage the Ionian Muses stand, of course, for 
 Herakleitos, and the Sicilian for Empedokles. According 
 to Plato, then, Herakleitos taught that reality was at once 
 many and one. This was not meant as a logical principle.^ 
 The identity which Herakleitos explains as consisting in 
 difference is just that of the primary substance in all its 
 manifestations. This identity had been realised already 
 by the Milesians, but they had found a difficulty in the 
 difference. Anaximander had treated the strife of opposites 
 as an '* injustice," and what Herakleitos set himself to 
 
 1 This was the mistake of Lassalle's book. The source of his error 
 was Hegel's statement that there was no proposition of Herakleitos that 
 he had not taken up into his own logic {Gesch. d. Phil. i. 328). The 
 example which he cites is the statement that Being does not exist any 
 more than not-Being, for which he refers to Arist. Met. A, 4. This, how- 
 ever, is not there ascribed to Herakleitos, but to Leukippos or Demo- 
 kritos, with whom it meant that space was as real as body {§ 175)- 
 Aristotle does, indeed, tell us in the Metaphysics that " some " think 
 Herakleitos says that the same thing can be and not be ; but he adds 
 that it does not follow that a man thinks what he says [Met. V, 3. 1005 b 24). 
 This is explained by K, 5. 1062 a 31, where we are told that by being 
 questioned in a certain manner Herakleitos could be made to admit the 
 principle of contradiction ; as it was, he did not understand what he said. 
 In other words, he was unconscious of its logical bearing. 
 
 # 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 145 
 
 show was that, on the contrary, it was the highest justice 
 (fr. 62).l 
 
 69. All this made it necessary for him to seek out a new Fire, 
 primary substance. He wanted not merely something 
 from which opposites could be " separated out," but some- 
 thing which of its own nature would pass into everything 
 else, while everything else would pass in turn into it. This 
 
 he found in Fire, and it is easy to see why, if we consider 
 the phenomenon of combustion. The quantity of fire in a 
 flame burning steadily appears to remain the same, the 
 flame seems to be what we call a " thing." And yet the 
 substance of it is continually changing. It is always passing 
 away in smoke, and its place is always being taken by fresh 
 matter from the fuel that feeds it. This is just what we 
 want. If we regard the world as an " ever-living fire " 
 (fr. 20), we can understand how it is always becoming all ' ' 
 things, while all things are always returning to it.^ 
 
 70. This necessarily brings with it a certain way of Flux. 
 looking at the change and movement of the world. Fire 
 burns continuously and without interruption. It is always 
 consuming fuel and always liberating smoke. Everything is 
 either mounting upwards to serve as fuel, or sinking down- 
 
 1 That the Fire of Herakleitos was something on the same level as the 
 " Air " of Anaximenes is clearly implied in such passages as Arist. Met. 
 A, 3. 984 a 5. In support of the view that something different from 
 literal fire is meant, Plato, Crat. 413 b, is sometimes quoted ; but the con- 
 text shows the passage will not bear this interpretation. Sokrates is dis- 
 cussing the derivation of St'/caiov from dta-Ldv, and certainly diKrj was a 
 prominent Herakleitean conception, and a good deal that is here said 
 may be the authentic doctrine of the school. He goes on to complain 
 that when he asks what this is which " goes through " everything, he gets 
 inconsistent answers. One says it is the sun. Another asks if there is 
 no justice after sunset, and says it is simply fire. A third says it is not 
 fire itself, but the heat which is in fire. A fourth identifies it with Mind. 
 Now all we are entitled to infer from this is that different accounts were 
 given in the Herakleitean school at a later date. The view that it was 
 not fire itself, but Heat, which "passed through" all things, is related to 
 the theory of Herakleitos as Hippo's Moisture is to the Water of Thales. 
 It is quite likely, too, that some Herakleiteans attempted to fuse the 
 system of Anaxagoras with their own, just as Diogenes of Apollonia tried 
 to fuse it with that of Anaximenes. We shall see, indeed, that we still 
 have a work in which this attempt is made (p. 150, n. 2). 
 
 10 
 
146 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 wards after having nourished the flame. It foUows that 
 the whole of reahty is like an ever-flowing stream, and that 
 nothing is ever at rest for a moment. The substance of the 
 things we see is in constant change. Even as we look at 
 them, some of the stuff of which they are composed has 
 already passed into something else, while fresh stuff has 
 come into them from another source. This is usually 
 summed up, appropriately enough, in the phrase *'A11 
 things are flowing" {irdvra pel), though this does not seem 
 to be a quotation from Herakleitos. Plato, however, 
 expresses the idea quite clearly. *' Nothing ever is, every- 
 thing is becoming " ; " All things are in motion like 
 streams " ; " All things are passing, and nothing abides " ; 
 " Herakleitos says somewhere that all things pass and 
 naught abides ; and, comparing things to the current of a 
 river, he says you cannot step twice into the same stream '* 
 (cf. fr. 41) — these are the terms in which he describes the 
 system. And Aristotle says the same thing, " All things are 
 in motion," " nothing steadfastly is." ^ Herakleitos held, in 
 fact, that any given thing, however stable in appearance, was 
 merely a section in the stream, and that the stuff composing 
 it was never the same in any two consecutive moments. We 
 shall see presently how he conceived the process to operate ; 
 meanwhile we remark that this is not the most original 
 feature of the system. The Milesians had held a similar view. 
 The up- 71. Herakleitos appears to have worked out the details 
 
 Down- with reference to the theories of Anaximenes. 2 Itisunhkely, 
 path. however, that he explained the transformations of matter 
 by means of rarefaction and condensation.^ Theophrastos, 
 it appears, suggested that he did ; but he allowed it was by 
 no means clear. The passage from Diogenes we are about 
 to quote has faithfully preserved this touch.* In the 
 
 1 Plato, Theaet. 152 e i ; Crat. 401 d 5, 402 a 8 ; Arist. Top. A, 11. 104 
 b 22 ; De caelo, V, i. 298 b 30 ; Phys. 0, 3. 253 b 2. 
 
 2 See above, Chap. I. § 29. 
 
 3 See, however, the remark of Diels {Dox. p. 165) quoted R. P. 36, 
 * Diog. ix. 8, (xacpQs 5' oi)$iv iKriderac. 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 147 
 
 fragments we find nothing about rarefaction and condensa- 
 tion. The expression used is " exchange " (fr. 22), a very 
 good name for what happens when fire gives out smoke and 
 takes in fuel instead. 
 ^ It has been pointed out that, in default of Hippolytos, 
 our best account of the Theophrastean doxography of 
 Herakleitos is the fuller of the two accounts given in Laertios 
 Diogenes. It is as follows : 
 
 His opinions on particular points are these : 
 
 He held that Fire was the element, and that all things were 
 an exchange for fire, produced by condensation and rarefaction. 
 But he explains nothing clearly. All things were produced in 
 opposition, and all things were in flux like a river. 
 
 The aU is finite and the world is one. It arises from fire, and is 
 consumed again by fire alternately through all eternity in certain 
 cycles. This happens according to fate. Of the opposites, that 
 which leads to the becoming of the world is called War and Strife ; 
 that which leads to the final conflagration is Concord and Peace. 
 
 He called change the upward and the downward path, and 
 held that the world comes into being in virtue of this. When 
 fire is condensed it becomes moist, and when compressed it turns 
 to water ; water being congealed turns to earth, and this he calls 
 the downward path. And, again, the earth is in turn liquefied, 
 and from it water arises, and from that everything else ; for 
 he refers almost everything to the evaporation from the sea. 
 This is the path upwards. R. P. 36. 
 
 He held, too, that exhalations arose both from the sea and 
 the land ; some bright and pure, others dark. Fire was nourished 
 by the bright ones, and moisture by the others. 
 
 He does not make it clear what is the nature of that which 
 surrounds the world. He held, however, that there were bowls 
 in it with the concave sides turned towards us, in which the 
 bright exhalations were collected and produced flames. These 
 were the heavenly bodies. 
 
 The flame of the sun was the brightest and warmest ; for 
 the other heavenly bodies were more distant from the earth ; 
 and for that reason gave less fight and heat. The moon, on the 
 other hand, was nearer the earth ; but it moved through an 
 impure region. The sun moved in a bright and unmixed region 
 
148 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 and at the same time was at just the right distance from us. 
 That is why it gives more heat and Hght. The ecUpses of the 
 sun and moon were due to the turning of the bowls upwards, 
 while the monthly phases of the moon were produced by a 
 gradual turning of its bowl. 
 
 Day and night, months and seasons and years, rains and 
 winds, and things like these, were due to the different exhalations. 
 The bright exhalation, when ignited in the circle of the sun, 
 produced day, and the preponderance of the opposite exhalations 
 produced night. The increase of warmth proceeding from the 
 bright exhalation produced summer, and the preponderance of 
 moisture from the dark exhalation produced winter. He assigns 
 the causes of other things in conformity with this. 
 
 As to the earth, he makes no clear statement about its nature, 
 any more than he does about that of the bowls. 
 
 These, then, were his opinions. R. P. 39 b. 
 
 Now, if we can trust this passage, it is of the greatest 
 value ; and that, upon the whole, we can trust it is shown 
 by the fact that it follows the exact order of topics to which 
 all the doxographies derived from the work of Theophrastos 
 adhere. First we have the primarj^ substance, then the world, 
 then the heavenly bodies, and lastly, meteorological pheno- 
 mena. We conclude, then, that it may be accepted with the 
 exceptions, firstly, of the probably erroneous conjecture of 
 Theophrastos as to rarefaction and condensation ; and 
 secondly, of some pieces of Stoical interpretation which come 
 from the Vetusta Placita. 
 
 Let us look at the details. The pure fire, we are told, is 
 to be found chiefly in the sun. This, like the other heavenly 
 bodies, is a trough or bowl, with the concave side turned 
 towards us, in which the bright exhalations from the sea 
 collect and burn. How does the fire of the sun pass into 
 other forms ? If we look at the fragments which deal with 
 the downward path, we find that the first transformation it 
 undergoes is into sea, and we are further told that half of 
 the sea is earth and half of it Trprja-rrjp (fr. 21). What is 
 this '7rp7i<TTi]p ? So far as I know, no one has yet proposed 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 149 
 
 to take the word in the sense it usually bears elsewhere, 
 that, namely, of hurricane accompanied by a fiery water- 
 spout.^ Yet surely this is just what is wanted. It is amply 
 /attested that Herakleitos explained the rise of the sea to 
 Mire by means of the bright evaporations ; and we want a 
 similar meteorological explanation of the passing of fire 
 back into sea. We want, in fact, something which will 
 stand equally for the smoke produced by the burning of the 
 sun and for the immediate stage between fire and water. 
 What could serve the turn better than a fiery waterspout ? 
 It sufficiently resembles smoke to be accounted for as the 
 product of the sun's combustion, and it certainly comes 
 down in the form of water. And this interpretation becomes 
 practically certain when taken in connexion v^ith the report 
 of Actios as to the Herakleitean theory of irprja-Trjpef;. They 
 were due, w^e are told, " to the kindUng and extinction of 
 clouds." 2 In other words, the bright vapour, after kindhng 
 in the bowl of the sun and going out again, reappears as 
 the dark fiery storm-cloud, and so passes once more into sea. 
 At the next stage we find water continually passing into 
 earth. We are already familiar with this idea (§ 10). 
 Turning to the " upward path,'* we find that the earth is 
 Hquefied in the same proportion as the sea becomes earth, 
 so that the sea is still " measured by the same tale " (fr. 23). 
 Half of it is earth and half of it is TrpTjarijp (fr. 21). This 
 must mean that, at any given moment, half of the sea is 
 taking the downward path, and has just been fiery storm- 
 cloud, while half of it is going up, and has just been earth. 
 In proportion as the sea is increased by rain, water passes 
 
 1 This was written in 1890. In his Herakleitos von Ephesos {1901) 
 Diels takes it as I did, rendering Glutwind. Cf. Herod, vii, 42, and 
 Lucretius vi. 424. Seneca {Q.N. ii. 56) calls it igneus turbo. The opinions 
 of early philosophers on these phenomena are collected in Actios iii. 3. 
 The irprjaTTip of Anaximander (Chap. I. p. 68, w. 2) is a different thing. 
 Greek sailors probably named the meteorological phenomena after the 
 familiar bellows of the smith. 
 
 2 Aet. iii, 3. 9, irprja-Tijpas dk /caret vecpQv i/xirpiq<reis Kal (r^^aeis (sc. 
 'Hpa/cXetros diro(palv€Tai ylyveadat). 
 
150 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 into earth ; in proportion as the sea is diminished by 
 evaporation, it is fed by the earth. Lastly, the ignition of 
 the bright vapour from the sea in the bowl of the sun 
 completes the circle of the " upward and downward path.'* 
 Measure 7^. How is it that, in spite of this constant flux, things 
 
 measure ^-PP^ar relatively stable ? The answer of Herakleitos was 
 that it is owing to the observance of the " measures," in 
 virtue of which the aggregate bulk of each form of matter 
 in the long run remains the same, though its substance 
 is constantly changing. Certain " measures ** of the 
 " ever-Hving fire " are always being kindled, while hke 
 "measures" are always going out (fr. 20). All things 
 are " exchanged " for fire and fire for all things (fr. 22), 
 and this impUes that for everything it takes, fire will give 
 as much. "The sun will not exceed his measures" (fr. 29). 
 x\nd yet the " measures " are not absolutely fixed. We 
 gather from the passage of Diogenes quoted above that 
 Theophrastos spoke of an alternate preponderance of the 
 bright and dark exhalations, and Aristotle speaks of Hera- 
 kleitos as explaining all things by evaporation.^ In parti- 
 cular, the alternation of day and night, summer and winter, 
 were accounted for in this way. Now, in a passage of the 
 pseudo-Hippokratean treatise He pi BcalTTj^ which is almost 
 certainly of Herakleitean origin,^ we read of an " advance of 
 
 ^ Arist. De an. B, 2. 405 a 26, ttjp avadvjxiaaiv i^ ijs rSXAa (rvvlaTrjatv. 
 
 2 The presence of Herakleitean matter in this treatise was pointed out 
 by Gesner, but Bernays was the first to make any considerable use of it in 
 reconstructing the system. The older literature of the subject has been in 
 the main superseded by Carl Fredrichs' Hippokratische Untersuchungen 
 (1899). He shows that (as I said already in the first edition) the work 
 belongs to the period of eclecticism and reaction briefly characterised in 
 § 184, and he points out that c 3, which was formerly supposed to be 
 mainly Herakleitean, is strongly influenced by Empedokles and Anaxa- 
 goras. I think, however, that he goes wrong in attributing the section to 
 a nameless " Physiker " of the school of Archelaos, or even to Archelaos 
 himself ; it is far more like what we should expect from the eclectic 
 Herakleiteans described by Plato in Crat. 413 c (see p. 145, n. i). He is 
 certainly wrong in holding the doctrine of the balance of fire and water 
 not to be Herakleitean, and there is no justification for separating the 
 remark quoted in the text from its context because it happens to agree 
 almost verbally with the beginning of c 3, 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 151 
 
 fire and water " in connexion with day and night and the 
 courses of the sun and moon.^ In fr. 26, again, we read of 
 fire " advancing," and all these things seem to be closely 
 connected. We must therefore try to see whether there is 
 anything in the remaining fragments that bears on the 
 subject. 
 
 73. In studjdng this alternate advance of fire and water, Man. 
 it will be convenient to start with the microcosm. We have 
 more definite information about the two exhalations in 
 man than about the analogous processes in the -world at 
 large, and it would seem that Herakleitos himself explained 
 the world by man rather than man by the world. Aristotle 
 imphes that soul is identical with the dry exhalation, ^ and 
 this is confirmed by the fragments. Man is made up of 
 three things, fire, water, and earth. But, just as in the 
 macrocosm fire is identified with the one wisdom, so in the 
 microcosm the fire alone is conscious. When it has left the 
 body, the remainder, the mere earth and water, is altogether 
 worthless (fr. 85). Of course, the fire which animates man 
 is subject to the " upward and downward path," just as 
 much as the fire of the world. The Hepl hiairrj^; has pre- 
 served the obviously Herakleitean sentence : " All things 
 are passing, both human and divine, upwards and down- 
 wards by exchanges." ^ We are just as much in perpetual 
 flux as anjrthing else in the world. We are and are not the 
 same for two consecutive instants (fr. 81). The fire in us is 
 perpetually becoming water, and the water earth ; but, as 
 
 ■•• Ylepl dialTTjs, i. 5- ■'■ read thus : ij/J^prj Kal e{><pp6vr) eirl rb fi'^Kiarov Kal 
 ^\(i.X'-<^T^v ' ff^'os, ffeXrivT) iirl t6 fi-qKiarov Kal i\dxt(rTov ' wpbs ^0o5os Kal 
 uSaros. In any case, the sentence occurs between x^^P^"^ ^^ vdvra Kal de?d 
 Kal avBpdinva &vu3 Kal Karu) dfiei^dfieva and irdvTa raird Kal oi) rd avrd, 
 which are surely Herakleitean utterances. 
 
 2 Arist. De an. A, 2. 405 a 25 (R. P. 38). Diels attributes to Herakleitos 
 himself the words Kal ^vxo-1 5^ dirb tQv vypQy dvadvfiiQpTai, which are 
 found in Areios Didymos after fr. 42, I can hardly beheve, however, 
 that the word dvadv/jilaaLS is Herakleitean. He seems rather to have 
 called the two exhalations Kairvds and d^p (cf. fr. 37). 
 
 ' Hepl diaLTrjs i. 5, X^^P" ^^ Trdvra Kal [^deia Kal dpOpdiriva dvia Kal Kdrcj 
 dfiei^dfjieva. 
 
152 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the opposite process goes on simultaneously, we appear to 
 
 remain the same.^ 
 (a) Sleep- 74. This, however, is not all. Man is subject to a certain 
 
 waking. osciUation in his " measures " of fire and water, which gives 
 
 rise to the alternations of sleeping and waking, Ufe and death. 
 
 The locus classiciis on this is a passage of Sextus Empiricus, 
 
 which reproduces the account given by Ainesidemos.^ It is 
 
 as follows (R. P. 41) : 
 
 The natural philosopher is of opinion that what surrounds 
 us 3 is rational and endowed with consciousness. According to 
 Herakleitos, when we draw in this divine reason by means of 
 respiration, we become rational. In sleep we forget, but at our 
 waking we become conscious once more. For in sleep, when the 
 openings of the senses close, the mind which is in us is cut off 
 from contact with that which surrounds us, and only our con- 
 nexion with it by means of respiration is preserved as a sort of 
 root (from which the rest may spring again) ; and, when it is thus 
 separated, it loses the power of memory that it had before. 
 When we awake again, however, it looks out through the openings 
 of the senses, as if through windows, and coming together with 
 the surrounding mind, it assumes the power of reason. Just, 
 then, as embers, when they are brought near the fire, change 
 and become red-hot, and go out when they are taken away from 
 it again, so does the portion of the surrounding mind which 
 sojourns in our body become irrational when it is cut off, and so 
 does it become of like nature to the whole when contact is estab- 
 lished through the greatest number of openings. 
 
 ^ We seem to have a reference to this in Epicharmos, fr. 2, Diels 
 (170 b, Kaibel) : " Look now at men too. One grows and another passes 
 away, and all are in change always. What changes in its substance (/car A 
 <p{)aLv) and never abides in the same spot, will already be something different 
 from what has passed away. So thou and I were different yesterday, and. 
 are now quite other people, and again we shall become others and evert' 
 the same again, and so on in the same way." This is said by a debtor^ 
 who does not wish to pay. 
 
 2 Sextus quotes " Ainesidemos according to Herakleitos." Natoi 
 holds {Forschungen, p. 78) that Ainesidemos really did combine Heraklei- 
 teanism with Skepticism. Diels {Dox. pp. 210, 211), insists that he onl] 
 gave an account of the theories of Herakleitos. This controversy does 
 not affect the use we make of the passage. 
 
 2 T6 wepiixov w^^> opposed to but parallel with to irepUxov rbv Kdcrfxov. 
 
 ov. j 
 
 d 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 153 
 
 In this passage there is clearly a large admixture of later 
 ideas. In particular, the identification of '* that which 
 surrounds us " with the air cannot be Herakleitean ; for 
 Herakleitos knew nothing of air except as a form of water 
 (§ 27). The reference to the pores or openings of the senses 
 is probably foreign to him also ; for the theory of pores is 
 due to Alkmaion (§ 96). Lastly, the distinction between 
 mind and body is far too sharply drawn. On the other 
 hand, the important role assigned to respiration may very 
 well be Herakleitean ; for we have met with it already in 
 Anaximenes. And we can hardly doubt that the striking 
 simile of the embers which glow when brought near the fire 
 is genuine (cf. fr. 77). The true doctrine doubtless was, that 
 sleep was produced by the encroachment of moist, dark 
 exhalations from the water in the body, which cause the fire 
 to burn low. In sleep, we lose contact with the fire in the 
 world which is common to all, and retire to a world of 
 our own (fr. 95). In a soul where the fire and water 
 are evenly balanced, the equiUbrium is restored in the 
 morning by an equal advance of the bright exhalation. 
 
 75. But in no soul are the fire and water thus evenly (^^ Ljfe 
 balanced for long. One or the other acquires predominance, ^^^ 
 and the result in either case is death. Let us take each of 
 these cases in turn. It is death, we know, to souls to become 
 water (fr. 68) ; but that is what happens to souls which 
 seek after pleasure. For pleasure is a moistening of the 
 soul (fr. 72), as may be seen in the case of the drunken man, 
 who has so moistened his soul that he does not know where 
 he is going (fr. 73). Even in gentle relaxation over our 
 cups, it is more difficult to hide folly than at other times 
 (fr. 108). That is why we must quench wantonness (fr. 103) ; 
 for whatever our heart's desire insists on it purchases at 
 the price of hfe, that is, of the fire within us (fr. 105). Take 
 now the other case. The dry soul, that which has least 
 moisture, is the best (fr. 74) ; but the preponderance of fire 
 causes death as much as that of water. It is a very different 
 
154 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 death, however, and wins ** greater portions " for those 
 who die it (fr. loi). 
 
 Further, just as summer and winter are one, and neces- 
 sarily reproduce one another by their " opposite tension," 
 so do Hfe and death. They, too, are one, we are told ; and 
 so are youth and age (fr. 78). It follows that the soul will 
 be now Uving and now dead ; that it will only turn to fire 
 or water, as the case may be, to recommence once more its 
 unceasing upward and downward path. The soul that has 
 died from excess of moisture sinks down to earth ; but from 
 the earth comes water, and from water is once more exhaled 
 a soul (fr. 68). So, too, we are told (fr. 67) that gods and 
 men are really one. They Hve each others' Hfe, and die 
 each others' death. Those mortals that die the fiery death 
 become immortal,^ they become the guardians of the quick 
 and the dead (fr. 123) ; ^ and those immortals become 
 mortal in their turn. Everything is the death of something 
 else (fr. 64). The Hving and the dead are always changing 
 places (fr. 78), like the pieces on a child's draught-board 
 (fr. 79), and this appUes not only to the souls that have 
 become water, but to those that have become fire and are 
 now guardian spirits. The real weariness is continuance in 
 the same state (fr. 82), and the real rest is change (fr. 83). 
 Rest in any other sense is tantamount to dissolution (fr. 84),^ 
 So they too are born once more. Herakleitos estimated 
 the duration of the cycle which preserves the balance of Hfe 
 
 1 The word is used for its paradoxical effect. Strictly speaking, they] 
 are all mortal from one point of view and immortal from another. 
 
 2 Those who fall in battle apparently share the same lot (fr. io2).1 
 Rohde, Psyche (II. 2 pp. 148 sqq.), refused to admit that Herakleitos believedj 
 the soul survived death. Strictly speaking, it is no doubt an incon- 
 sistency ; but I believe, with Zeller and Diels, that it is one of a kind weJ 
 may well admit. The first argument which Plato uses to establish the] 
 doctrine of immortality in the Phaedo is just the Herakleitean paraUelisi 
 of life and death with sleeping and waking. 
 
 3 These fragments are quoted by Plotinos, lamblichos, and NoumeniosI 
 in this connexion (R. P. 46 c), and it does not seem possible to hold, withj 
 Rohde, that they had no grounds for so interpreting them. They knewj 
 the context and we do not. 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 155 
 
 and death as thirty years, the shortest time in which a man 
 may become a grandfather (frs. 87-89). ^ 
 
 76. Let us turn now to the world. Diogenes tells us The day 
 that fire was kept up by the bright vapours from land and year!^^ 
 sea, and moisture by the dark.^ What are these " dark " 
 vapours which increase the moist element ? If we remember 
 the " Air " of Anaximenes, we shall be inclined to regard 
 them as darkness itself. We know that the idea of darkness 
 as privation of Ught is not primitive. (l suppose, then, that 
 Herakleitos beUeved night and winter to be produced by the 
 rise of darkness from earth and sea — he saw^ of course, that 
 the valleys were dark before the hill-tops — and that this 
 darkness, being moist, so increased the watery element as 
 to put out the sun's hghtT] This, however, destroys the 
 power of darkness itself. It can no longer rise upwards 
 unless the sun gives it motion, and so it becomes possible 
 for a fresh sun (fr. 32) to be kindled, and to nourish itself at 
 the expense of the moist element for a time. But it can 
 only be for a time. The sun, by burning up the bright 
 vapour, deprives himself of nourishment, and the dark 
 vapour once more gets the upper hand. It is in this sense 
 that " day and night are one " (fr. 35). Each impHes the 
 other ; they are merely two sides of one process, in which 
 alone their true ground of explanation is to be found (fr. 36). 
 
 Summer and winter were to be explained in the same 
 way. We know that the "turnings back'* of the sun were a 
 subject of interest in those da3^s, and it was natural for 
 Herakleitos to see in its retreat to the south the advance of 
 the moist element, caused by the heat of the sun itself. 
 
 ^ Plut. Def. orac. 415 d, ^rrj rpidKOPra iroioOcri rrju yeveav Kad' 'KpdKXecTov, 
 iv ip XP^^V y^vvdvTa Trap^xet rbv i^ avrov yeyevvrifiivov 6 yevv/jo-ai. Philo, 
 fr. Harris, p. 20, dvparbv iu rpiaKoari^ ^rei aS t6v EvOpwirov irainrov 
 yevia-dai ktX. Censorinus, De die nat. 17. 2, " hoc enim tempus (triaginta 
 annos) genean vocari Heraclitus auctor est, quia orhis aetaiis in eo sit spatio : 
 orbem autem vocat aetatis, dum natura ab sementi humana ad sementim 
 revertitur." The words orbis aetaiis seem to mean ai'tDvos k^kXos, " the circle \ 
 
 of life." If so, we may compare the Orphic /ci//cXos yevicreus. 
 
 2 Diog. ix. 9 (R. P. 39 b). 
 
156 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 This, however, diminishes the power of the sun to cause 
 evaporation, and so it must return to the north that it may 
 supply itself with nourishment. Such was, at any rate, the 
 Stoic doctrine,^ and that it comes from Herakleitos seems to 
 be proved by its occurrence in the IJepl hiair'n^. The follow- 
 ing passage is clearly Herakleitean : 
 
 And in turn each (fire and water) prevails and is prevailed 
 over to the greatest and least degree that is possible. For 
 neither can prevail altogether for the following reasons. If fire 
 advances towards the utmost limit of the water, its nourishment 
 fails it. It retires, then, to a place where it can get nourishment. 
 And if water advances towards the utmost limit of the fire, move- 
 ment fails it. At that point, then, it stands still ; and, when it 
 has come to a stand, it has no longer power to resist, but is con- 
 sumed as nourishment for the fire that falls upon it. For these 
 reasons neither can prevail altogether. But if at any time 
 either should be in any way overcome, then none of the things 
 that exist would be as they are now. So long as things are as 
 they are, fire and water will always be too, and neither will 
 ever fail.^ 
 
 The jy. Herakleitos spoke also of a longer period, which is 
 
 Ye^. identified with the " Great Year," and is variously described 
 
 as lasting 18,000 and 10,800 years.^ We have no definite 
 
 statement, however, of what process Herakleitos supposed 
 
 1 Cf. Cic, N.D. iii. 37 : " Quid enim ? non eisdem vobis placet omnem 
 ignem pastus indigere nee permanere uUo modo posse, nisi alitur : ali 
 autem solem, lunam, reliqua astra aquis, alia dulcibus (from the earth), 
 alia marinis ? eamque causam Cleanthes (fr. 29 Pearson; I. 501 v. Arnim) 
 adfert cur se sol referat nee longius progrediatur solstitiali orbi itemque 
 brumali, ne longius discedat a cibo." 
 
 2 For the Greek text see below, p. 162, n. 3. Fredrichs allows that 
 it is from the same source as that quoted above (p. 151, n. i), and, as that 
 comes from Ilept dLairrjs, i. 3, he denies the Herakleitean origin of this 
 passage too. He has not taken account of the fact that it gives the Stoic 
 doctrine, which raises a presumption in favour of its being Herakleitean. 
 If I could agree with Fredrichs' theory, I should still say that the present 
 passage was a Herakleitean interpolation in the Physiker rather than that 
 the other was an interpolation from the Physiker in the Herakleitean 
 section. See p. 150, n. 2. 
 
 3 Aet. ii. 32. 3. 'Hp(i/cXeiTOS ^k /xvpiojv d/craKto-xiX^wv ivLavrCbv ifKiaKCiv 
 {t6p fxiyav iviavrbu elvai). Censorinus, De die nat. 11, Heraclitus et Linus, 
 Xdccc. 
 
 i 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 157 
 
 to take place in the Great Year. The period of 36,000 years 
 was Babylonian, and 18,000 years is just half that period, a 
 fact which may be connected with Herakleitos's way of 
 dividing all cycles into an *' upward and downward path." 
 The Stoics, or some of them, held that the Great Year was 
 the period between one world-conflagration and the next. 
 They were careful, however, to make it a good deal longer 
 than Herakleitos did, and, in any case, we are not entitled 
 without more ado to credit him with the theory of a general 
 conflagration.^ We must try first to interpret the Great 
 Year on the analogy of the shorter periods discussed already. 
 Now we have seen that a generation is the shortest time 
 in which a man can become a grandfather, it is the period of 
 the upward or downward path of the soul, and the most 
 natural interpretation of the longer period would surely be 
 that it represents the time taken by a " measure " of the 
 fire in the world to travel on the downward path to earth or 
 return to fire once more by the upward path. Plato imphes 
 that such a paralleUsm between the periods of man and the 
 world was recognised, ^ and this receives a curious confirma- 
 tion from a passage in Aristotle, which is usually supposed 
 to refer to the doctrine of a periodic conflagration. He is 
 discussing the question whether the " heavens," that is to 
 say, what he calls the " first heaven," is eternal or not, and 
 naturally enough, from his own point of view, he identifies 
 this with the Fire of Herakleitos. He quotes him along 
 with Empedokles as holding that the " heavens " are alter- 
 nately as they are now and in some other state, one of 
 passing away ; and he goes on to point out that this is not 
 
 1 For the Stoic doctrine, cf. Nemesios, De nat. horn. 38 (R. P. 503). 
 Adam {Republic, vol. ii. p. 303) allowed that no destruction of the world 
 or conflagration marked the end of Plato's year, but he declined to draw 
 what seems to me the natural inference that the connexion between the 
 two things belongs to a later age, and should not, therefore, be ascribed 
 to Herakleitos in the absence of any evidence that he did so connect them. 
 
 2 This is certainly the general sense of the parallelism between the 
 periods of the avdpuiTruov and the deiov yevviyrdv, however we may under- 
 stand the details. See Adam, Republic, vol. ii. pp. 288 sqq. 
 
158 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Did Hera- 
 kleitos 
 teach a 
 general 
 conflagra- 
 tion ? 
 
 really to say they pass away, any more than it would be 
 to say that a man ceases to be, if we said that he turned 
 from boy to man and then from man to boy again. ^ It is 
 surely clear that this is a reference to the parallel between 
 the generation and the Great Year, and, if so, the ordinary 
 interpretation of the passage must be wrong. It is not, 
 indeed, quite consistent with the theory to suppose that a 
 ** measure " of Fire could preserve its identity throughout 
 the whole of its upward and downward path ; but that is 
 exactly the inconsistency we have felt bound to recognise 
 with regard to the continuance of individual souls. Now, 
 it will be noted that, while 18,000 is half 36,000, 10,800 is 
 360 X 30, which would make each generation a day in the 
 Great Year, and this is in favour of the higher number. ^ 
 
 78. Most writers ascribe to Herakleitos the doctrine of 
 a periodical conflagration or eKirvpcoai^, to use the Stoic 
 term.^ That this is inconsistent with his general view is 
 obvious, and is indeed admitted by Zeller, who adds to his? 
 paraphrase of the statement of Plato quoted above (p. 144)! 
 the words : *' Herakleitos did not intend to retract thisi 
 principle in the doctrine of a periodic change in the constitu- 
 tion of the world ; if the two doctrines are not compatible 
 it is a contradiction which he has not observed." Now, it] 
 is quite Hkely that there were contradictions in the discourse 
 of Herakleitos, but it is very unhkely that there was this 
 particular contradiction. In the first place, it is inconsistent 
 with the central idea of his system, the thought that pos- 
 
 1 Arist. De caelo. A, 10. 279 b 14, oi d' ivaWa^ 6t^ fih ourws ot^ 
 8k AXXws ^x^iv <pdeip6/xevop, . . . &<nrep 'E/niredoKXrjs 6 'AKpayavriuos Kat 
 'KpdKXeiTos 6 'E0^o-tos. Aristotle points out that this really amounts only 
 to saying that it is eternal and changes its form, ibairep el ns ck iruLdbs 
 dvdpa yLyydfievoP koX i^ dvdpbs 7ra?5a ork jxkv (f)d€ipe<x6aL, ork 5' elvai oIolto (280 a 
 14). The point of the reference to Empedokles will appear from De Gen. 
 Corr. B, 6. 334 a i sqq. What Aristotle finds fault with in both theories is 
 that they do not regard the substance of the heavens as something outside^ 
 the upward and downward motion of the elements. 
 
 2 Cf. Tannery, Science Hellene, p. 168. Diels, accordingly, now reads 
 [ivpiwv dKTaKoaiup in Actios (Vors. 12 a 13). 
 
 3 Schleiermacher and Lassalle are notable exceptions. Zeller, Diels, 
 and Gomperz are all positive that Herakleitos beUeved in the iKirOpwais. 
 
 _ 4 
 
 .1 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 159 
 
 sessed his whole mind (§ 67), and we can only admit the 
 possibiUty of that, if the evidence for it should prove 
 irresistible. In the second place, such an interpretation 
 (destroys the whole point of Plato's contrast between Hera- 
 kleitos and Empedokles (§ 68), which is just that, while 
 Herakleitos said the One was always many, and the Many 
 always one, Empedokles said the All was many and one by 
 turnsTl Zeller's interpretation obhges us, then, to suppose 
 that Tlerakleitos flatly contradicted his own discovery 
 without noticing it, and that Plato, in discussing this very 
 discovery, was also blind to the contradiction. ^ 
 
 Nor is there anything in Aristotle to set against Plato's 
 statement. We have seen that the passage in which he 
 speaks of him along with Empedokles as holding that the 
 heavens were alternately in one condition and in another 
 refers not to the world, but to fire, which Aristotle identified 
 with the substance of his own ** first heaven." ^ it is also 
 quite consistent with our interpretation when he says that 
 all things at one time or another become fire. This need 
 not mean that they all become fire at the same time, but 
 may be merely a statement of the undoubted Herakleitean 
 doctrine of the upward and downward path.^ 
 
 The earUest statements to the effect that Herakleitos 
 
 1 In his fifth edition (p. 699) Zeller seems to have felt this last diffi- 
 culty ; for he said there : " It is a contradiction which he, and which 
 probably Plato too {und den wahrscheinlich auch Plato) has not observed." 
 This seems to me still less arguable. Plato may or may not be mistaken ; 
 but he makes the perfectly definite statement that Herakleitos says del, 
 while Empedokles says iv fxipei. The Ionian Muses are called a-vpTovuTepai 
 and the Sicilian ^uaXa/ccirepai just because the latter " lowered the pitch " 
 {ixdXaa-af) of the doctrine that this is always so (t6 del ravra oijTios ^x^iv). 
 
 2 See above, p. 158, n. i. 
 
 3 Phys. r 5, 205 a 3 {Met. K, 10. 1067 a 4), &<nrep "H.pdK\eir6s (prjatv 
 diravTa ylvecrdal irore irvp. Zeller translates this as werde alles dereinst zu 
 Feuer warden ; but that would require yevqaeadat. Nor is there anything 
 in his suggestion that dirayra {" not merely irdvTa ") impHes that all things 
 become fire at once. In Aristotle's day, there was no distinction of 
 meaning between ras and c^Tras. Of course, as Diels says, the present 
 tense might be used of a " constant alternation of epochs " {Vors. 12 A 
 10 «.) ; but, for the purpose of Zeller's argument, we want something 
 which not only may but must mean that. 
 
i6o EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 taught the doctrine of a general conflagration are found in 
 Stoic writers. The Christian apologists too were interested 
 in the idea of a final conflagration, and reproduce the Stoic 
 view. The curious thing, however, is that there was a 
 difference of opinion on the subject even among the Stoics. 
 In one place, Marcus AureHus says : *' So that all these 
 things are taken up into the Reason of the universe, whether 
 by a periodical conflagration or a renovation effected by 
 eternal exchanges." ^ Indeed, there were some who said 
 there was no general conflagration at all in Herakleitos. 
 " I hear all that," Plutarch makes one of his personages say, 
 " from many people, and I see the Stoic conflagration 
 spreading over the poems of Hesiod, just as it does over the 
 writings of Herakleitos and the verses of Orpheus." ^ We 
 see from this that the question was debated, and we should 
 therefore expect any statement of Herakleitos which could 
 settle it to be quoted over and over again. It is highly 
 significant that not a single quotation of the kind can be 
 produced.^ 
 
 On the contrary, the absence of anything to show that 
 Herakleitos spoke of a general conflagration only becomes 
 more patent when we turn to the few fragments which are 
 supposed to prove it. The favourite is fr. 24, where we are 
 
 ^ Marcus Aurelius, X. 7, ibcre koI ravra di'a\7}(f>dr}vai els rbv toO 6\ov 
 \6yov, etre Kara irepiodov iKirvpovfxivov, elre didiois dfioi^ais dvaveovfiipov. The 
 dfjiOL^ai are specifically Herakleitean, and the statement is the more 
 remarkable as Marcus elsewhere follows the usual Stoic interpretation. 
 
 2 Plut. De def. orac. 415 f., koI KXed/x^poros, 'AkoOcj rauT, ^(prj, iroWuv 
 Kal bpQ} TT]v liToiLKTjv iKTnjpuaiv Cbcnrep rd 'HpaKXeirov Kal 'Optpiois iirivefxofihrjv ^irr} 
 ovTU Kal rd 'B.cri68ov Kal cvve^aTTTovaav. As Zeller admits (p. 693 w.), this , 
 proves that some opponents of the Stoic iKirvpcacns tried to withdraw the' 
 support of Herakleitos from it. 
 
 3 This has been called a mere argumentum ex silentio ; but, in such 
 cases, the argumentum ex silentio is stronger than any other. Positive 
 statements may be misinterpreted ; but, when we know that a subject 
 was keenly debated, and when we find that neither party can produce an 
 unambiguous text in support of its view, the conclusion that none such 
 existed becomes irresistible. The same remark appHes to modern pro- 
 nouncements on the subject. Diels briefly says that my view " is wrong " 
 {ist irrig), but he does not adduce any fresh reason for saying so. The 
 conclusion is that he knows of none. 
 
 i 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS i6i 
 
 told that Herakleitos said Fire was Want and Surfeit. 
 That is just in his manner, and it has a perfectly intelligible 
 meaning on our interpretation, which is further confirmed 
 by fr. 36. The next is fr. 26, where we read that fire in its 
 advance will judge and convict all things. There is nothing 
 in this, however, to suggest that fire will judge all things 
 at once rather than in turn, and, indeed, the phraseology 
 reminds us of the advance of fire and water which we have 
 seen reason for attributing to Herakleitos, but which is 
 expressly said to be Hmited to a certain maximum.^ These 
 appear to be the only passages which the Stoics and the 
 Christian apologists could discover, and, whether our inter- 
 pretation of them is right or wrong, it is surely clear that 
 they cannot bear the weight of their conclusion, and that 
 there was nothing more definite to be found. 
 
 It is much easier to find fragments which are incon- 
 sistent with a general conflagration. The " measures " of 
 fr. 20 and fr. 29 must be the same thing, and they must 
 be interpreted in the light of fr. 23. If this be so, fr. 20, 
 and more especially fr. 29, directly contradict the idea 
 of a general conflagration. " The sun will not overstep 
 his measures." ^ Secondly, the metaphor of " exchange," 
 which is appUed to the transformations of fire in fr. 22, 
 points in the same direction. When gold is given in 
 exchange for wares and wares for gold, the sum or " measure " 
 of each remains constant, though they change owners. All 
 the wares and gold do not come into the same hands. In 
 the same way, when anything becomes fire, something of 
 equal amount must cease to be fire, if the " exchange " is 
 to be a just one ; and that it will be just, we are assured by 
 the watchfulness of the Erinyes (fr. 29), who sees to it that 
 the sun does not take more than he gives. Of course there 
 is a certain variation, as we saw ; but it is strictly confined 
 
 ^ Ilepl diairri^, i. 3, iy fiipei 5^ eKarepov Kparei Kal Kpare'cTaL is rb fx-qKLCTOV 
 Kol iXdxi-O^TOv ws avvcrrov. 
 
 2 If any one doubts that this is really the meaning of the " measures," 
 let him compare the use of the word by Diogenes of ApoUonia, fr. 3. 
 
 II 
 
i62 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 within limits, and is compensated in the long run by a 
 variation in the other direction. Thirdly, fr. 43, in which 
 Herakleitos blames Homer for desiring the cessation of 
 strife, is very conclusive. The cessation of strife would 
 mean that all things should take the upward or downward 
 path at the same time, and cease to " run in opposite 
 directions." If they all took the upward path, we should 
 have a general conflagration. Now, if Herakleitos had 
 himself held this to be the appointment of fate, would he 
 have been Hkely to upbraid Homer for desiring so necessary 
 a consummation ? ^ Fourthly, we note that in fr. 20 it is 
 this world,^ and not merely the " ever-living fire," which is 
 said to be eternal ; and it appears also that its eternity 
 depends on the fact that it is always kindhng and always 
 going out in the same " measures," or that an encroachment 
 in one direction is compensated by a subsequent encroach- 
 ment in the other. Lastly, Lassalle^s argument from the 
 concluding sentence of the passage from the TiepX 8ca[rr]<;, 
 quoted above, is really untouched by Zeller's objection, that 
 it cannot be Herakleitean because it implies that all things 
 are fire and water. It does not imply this, but only that 
 man, like the heavenly bodies, oscillates between fire and 
 water ; and that is just what Herakleitos taught. Now, 
 in this passage we read that neither fire nor water can prevail 
 completely, and a very good reason is given for this, a reason 
 too which is in striking agreement with the other views of 
 Herakleitos.^ And, indeed, it is not easy to see how, in 
 
 ^ This is just the argument which Plato uses in the Phaedo (72 c) to 
 prove the necessity of avTairbSoais, and the whole series of arguments in 
 that passage is distinctly Herakleitean in character. 
 
 2 However we understand Kocrfios here, the meaning is the same. 
 Indeed, if we suppose with Bernays that it means " order," the argument 
 will be all the stronger. In no sense of the word could a KoafMos survive 
 the eKirvpwa-Ls, and the Stoics accordingly said the Koa/Mos was (pdaprds, 
 though Herakleitos had declared it to be everlasting. 
 
 3 Uepl 8iaLT7)s, i. 3 (see above, p. 150, n. 2), ovS^repov ykp Kparijaai 
 TravreXQs d^parai 8lcl rdde ' t6 <Te> irvp eire^Lov iirl rb ^ax^'^'^^ "^o^ vdaros ^TrtXetTrei 
 7} rpo(f)-f) ' airoTpeireTai odv 6dev fxiWei rpitpeadai " to vdup re iire^ibv rod irvpbs 
 iirl rb ea-xo-TOv, tTrtXetTrei i} KLvr)ai% ' i<rrarat ody iv totliti^, Srav 8^ ar^, ovKiri 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 163 
 
 accordance with these views, the world could ever recover 
 from a general conflagration if such a thing were to take 
 place. The whole process depends on the fact that Surfeit 
 is also Want, or, in other words, that an advance of fire 
 increases the moist exhalation, while an advance of water 
 deprives the fire of its power to cause evaporation. The 
 conflagration, though it lasted but for a moment,^ would 
 destroy the opposite tension on which the rise of a new 
 world depends, and then motion would become impossible. 
 
 79. We are now in a position to understand more clearly strife and 
 the law of strife or opposition which manifests itself in the mony." 
 " upward and downward path." a At any given moment, 
 each of the three aggregates, Fire, Water, and Earth, is 
 made up of two equal portions — subject, of course, to the 
 oscillation described above — one of which is taking the 
 upward and the other the downward path. Now, it is just 
 the fact that the two halves of everything are being " drawn . 
 in opposite directions," this " opposite tension," that 
 " keeps things together," and maintains them in an equiU- 
 brium which can only be disturbed temporarily and within 
 certain limits. It thus forms the " hidden attunement " 
 of the universe (fr. 47), though, in another aspect of it, it is 
 Strife.^ As to the " bow and the lyre " (fr. 45), I think that 
 Campbell gave the best explanation of the simile. " As 
 the arrow leaves the string," he said, " the hands are pulling 
 opposite ways to each other, and to the different parts of 
 the bow (cf. Plato, Rep. iv. 439) ; and the sweet note of the 
 lyre is due to a similar tension and retention. The secret of 
 
 iyKparis iariv, dW -^St/ t{^ ifiiriirroPTi wvpl 4s t^v Tpo(f>T]u KaravaKiaKeTai. ' 
 ovd^repov 8^ 5ioL ravra d^parai KparTJaaL TraureKws, el 34 irore KpaTrjdelrj Kal 
 btroTepoVy ovbkv hv et-q tQsv vvv ebvTwv ibcnrep Ixet vvp ' oijTb} 34 ixbvTUV del 
 icrrai ra avra Kal ov84T€pov ovda/x^ ^TriXei^et. 
 
 ^ In his note on fr, 66 (=26 Byw.) Diels seeks to minimise the diffi- 
 culty of the iKirvpwffis by saying that it is only a Uttle one, and can last 
 but a moment ; but the contradiction remains. Diels holds that Hera- 
 kleitos was " dark only in form," and that " he himself was perfectly 
 clear as to the sense and scope of his ideas " {Herakleitos, p. i.). To 
 which I would add that he was probably called " the Dark " just because 
 the Stoics sometimes found it hard to read their own ideas into his words. 
 
i64 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the universe is the same." ^ War, then, is the father and 
 king of all things, in the world as in human society (fr. 44) ; 
 and Homer's wish that strife might cease was really a prayer 
 for the destruction of the world (fr. 43). 
 
 We know from Philo that Herakleitos supported his 
 theory by a multitude of examples ; and sonle of these can 
 still be recovered. There is a remarkable agreement between 
 a passage of this kind in the pseudo-AristoteHan TLepl Koa-fxov 
 and the Hippokratean Hepl hiairr}^. That the authors of 
 both drew from the same source, namely, Herakleitos, is 
 made practically certain by the fact that this agreement 
 extends in part to the Letters of Herakleitos, which, though 
 spurious, were certainly composed by some one who had 
 access to the original work. The argument was that men 
 themselves act just in the same way as Nature, and it is 
 therefore surprising that they do not recognise the laws by 
 which she works. The painter produces his harmonious 
 effects by the contrast of colours, the musician by that of 
 high and low notes. " If one were to make all things aUke, 
 there would be no deUght in them." There are many 
 similar examples, some of which must certainly come from 
 Herakleitos ; but it is not easy to separate them from the 
 later additions. ^ 
 
 1 Campbell's Theaetetus (2nd ed.), p. 244. Bernays explained the 
 phrase as referring to the shape of the bow and lyre, but this is much 
 less likely. Wilamowitz's interpretation is based on Campbell's. " Es ist 
 mit der Welt wie mit dem Bogen, den man auseinanderzieht, damit 
 er zusammenschnellt, wie mit der Saite, die man ihrer Spannung entgegen- 
 ziehen muss, damit sie klingt" (Lesebuch, ii, p. 129). Here we seem to feel 
 the influence of the Pythagorean " tuned string." 
 
 2 The sentence {Uepi dtalTTjs, i. 5), Kal ra fikv irp-qaaovcnv ovk oidaaiv, &, 
 8^ ov Trp'fi(xaov(TL doK^ova-ip eldivai ' Kal tcl ^fikv opiovaiv oi yLvtbaKovaiv, dW 
 6/xws avToTai irdura yiverai . . . Kal A ^o6\ovTat. Kal A /atj ^o^XovTai, has 
 the true Herakleitean ring. This, too, can hardly have had another 
 author : " They trust to their eyes rather than to their understanding, 
 though their eyes are not fit to judge even of the things that are seen. 
 But I speak these things from understanding." These words are gro- 
 tesque in the mouth of the medical compiler ; but we are accustomed to 
 hear such things from the Ephesian. Other examples which may be 
 Herakleitean are the image of the two men sawing wood — " one pushes, 
 the other pulls " — and the illustration from the art of writing. 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 165 
 
 80. There are several Herakleitean fragments which correia- 
 form a class by themselves, and are among the most striking oppog^es. 
 of the utterances that have come down to us. These assert 
 in the most downright way the identity of various things 
 usually regarded as opposites. The clue to their meaning 
 is to be found in the account already given of the assertion 
 that day and night are one. We have seen that Herakleitos 
 meant, not that day was night or night was day, but that 
 they were two sides of the. same process, namely, the oscilla- 
 tion of the " measures " of fire and water, and that neither 
 would be possible without the other. Any Explanation 
 that can be given of night will also be an explanation of 
 day, and vice versa ; for it will be an account of what is 
 common to both, and manifests itself now as one and now 
 as the other. Now this is only a particular application of 
 the principle that the primary fire is one even in its division. 
 It itself is, even in its unity, both surfeit and want, war and 
 peace (fr. 36). In other words, the " satiety " which makes 
 fire pass into other forms, which makes it seek " rest 
 in change " (fr. 83), and " hide itself " (fr. 10) in the 
 " hidden attunement '* of opposition, is only one side of the 
 process. The other is the " want " which leads it to con- 
 sume the bright vapour as fuel. The upward path is nothing 
 without the downward (fr. 69). If either were to cease, the 
 other would cease too, and the world would disappear ; 
 for it takes both to make an apparently stable reahty.^ 
 
 All other utterances of the kind are to be explained in 
 the same way. If there were no cold, there would be no 
 heat ; for a thing can only grow warm if, and in so far as, 
 it is already cold. And the same thing apphes to the opposi- 
 tion of wet and dry (fr. 39). These, it will be observed, are 
 just the two primary oppositions of Anaximander, and 
 Herakleitos is showing that the war between them is really 
 peace, for it is the common element in them (fr. 62) which 
 appears as strife, and that very strife is justice, and not, as 
 Anaximander had taught, an injustice which they commit 
 
i66 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 one against the other, and which must be expiated by a 
 reabsorption of both in their common ground.^ 
 
 The most startHng of these sayings is that which affirms 
 \y that good and evil are the same (fr. 57). This does not 
 mean that good is evil or that evil is good, but simply that 
 t]iey_9xe fl'^^^t}^- int;ppar ah1fi ha]ve? ^ 9f_9"^ 3.nd the same 
 thing. A thing can become good only in so far as it is already 
 evil, and evil only in so far as it is already good, and every- 
 thing depends on the contrast. The illustration given in 
 fr. 58 shows this clearly. Torture, one would say, was an 
 evil, and yet it is made a good by the presence of another 
 evil, namely, disease ; as is shown by the fact that surgeons 
 expect a fee for inflicting it on their patients. Justice, on 
 the other hand, which is a good, would be unknown were it 
 not for injustice, which is an evil (fr. 60). And that is why 
 it is not good for men to get everything they wish (fr. 104). 
 Tjust as the cessation of strife in the world would mean its 
 destruction, so the disappearance of hunger, disease, and 
 weariness would mean the disappearance of satisfaction, 
 health, and restA 
 
 This leads to a theory of relativity which prepares the 
 way for the doctrine of Protagoras, that " Man is the 
 measure of all things." ^ Sea- water is good for fish and bad 
 for men (fr. 52), and so with many other things. At the 
 same time,' Herakleitos is not a believer in absolute relativity. ■ 
 The process of the world is not merely a circle, but an 
 " upward and downward path." At the upper end, where 
 the two paths meet, we have the pure fire, in which, as there 
 is no separation, there is no relativity. We are told that, 
 while to man some things are evil and some things are good, 
 all things are good to God (fr. ^i). (Now by God, or the 
 
 1 Chap. I. § 16. 
 
 * Plato's exposition of tlie relativity of knowledge in the Theaetetus 
 (152 d sqq.) can hardly go back to Herakleitos himself, but is meant to 
 show how Herakleiteanism might give rise to such a doctrine. If the * 
 soul is a stream and things are a stream, then of course knowledge is = 
 relative. Perhaps the later Herakleiteans had worked out the theory in i 
 
 this direction. 
 
 i 
 
HERAKLEITOS OF EPHESOS 167 
 
 *' one wise/* there is no doubt Herakleitos meant Fire.y 
 There can hardly be any question that what he meant to 
 say was that in it the opposition and relativity universal in 
 the world disappear. It is doubtless to this that frs. 96, 97, 
 and 98 refer. 
 
 81. Herakleitos speaks of " wisdom " or the *' wise " in The wise, 
 two senses. We have seen already that he said wisdom was 
 " something apart from everything else " (fr. 18), meaning 
 by it the perception of the unity of the many ; and he also 
 appHes the term to that unity itself regarded as the " thought 
 that directs the course of all things." This is synonymous 
 with the pure fire which is not differentiated into two parts, 
 one taking the upward and the other the downward path. 
 That alone has wisdom ; the partial things we see have 
 not. We ourselves are only wise in so far as we are fiery 
 
 (fr. 74)- 
 
 ^2. With certain reservations, Herakleitos was prepared Theology, 
 to call the one Wisdom by the name of Zeus. Such, at 
 least, appears to be the meaning of fr. 65. What these 
 reservations were, it is easy to guess, lit is not, of course, 
 to be pictured in the form of a man. In saying this, Hera- 
 kleitos would only have been repeating what had already 
 been said by Xenophanes. He agrees further with Xeno- 
 phanes in holding that this " god," if it is to be called so, 
 is one ; but his polemic against popular rehgion was directed 
 rather against the rites and ceremonies themselves than 
 their mythological outgrowth. He gives a list (fr. 124) of 
 some of the rehgious figures of his time, and the context in 
 which the fragment is quoted shows that he in some way 
 threatened them with the wrath to come. He comments 
 on the absurdity of praying to images (fr. 126), and the 
 strange idea that blood-guiltiness can be washed out by 
 the shedding of blood (fr. 130). He seems also to have said 
 that it was absurd to celebrate the worship of Dionysos 
 by cheerful and hcentious ceremonies, while Hades was pro- 
 pitiated by gloomy rites (fr. 127). According to the mystic 
 
i68 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 doctrine itself, the two were really one ; and the one Wisdom 
 ought to be worshipped in its integrity. 
 Ethics of (83? The moral teaching of Herakleitos is summed up in 
 kieitos. the rule " Follow the common." The " common " upon 
 which Herakleitos insists is, nevertheless, something very 
 different from common sense, for which, indeed, he had the 
 greatest possible contempt (fr. iii). It is, in fact, his 
 strongest objection to " the many,'' that they Hve each in 
 his own world (fr. 95), as if they had a private wisdom of 
 their own (fr. 92) ; and pubHc opinion is therefore just the 
 opposite of " the common." The rule is really to be inter- 
 preted as a corollary of his anthropological and cosmological 
 views. The first requirement is that we keep our souls dry, 
 and thus assimilate them to the one Wisdom, which is fire. 
 That is what is really " common," and the greatest fault is 
 to act like men asleep (fr. 94), that is, by letting our souls 
 grow moist, to cut ourselves off from the fire in the world. 
 
 Herakleitos prepared the way for the Stoic world-state 
 by comparing ** the common " to the laws of a city. And 
 these are even more than a type of the divine law : they ? 
 are imperfect embodiments of it. They cannot, however, 
 exhaust it altogether ; for in all human affairs there is an 
 element of relativity (fr. 91). " Man is a baby compared to ] 
 God " (fr. 97). Such as they are, however, the city must 
 fight for them as for its walls ; and, if it has the good 
 fortune to possess a citizen with a dry soul, he is worth ten 
 thousand (fr. 113) ; for in him alone is *' the common " 
 embodied. 
 
CHAPTER IV 
 
 PARMENIDES OF ELEA 
 
 84. Parmenides, son of Pyres, was a citizen of Hyele, Elea, or Life. 
 Velia, a colony founded in Oinotria by refugees from Phokaia 
 in 540-39 B.c.i Diogenes tells us that he " flourished " in 
 01. LXIX. (504-500 B.C.), and this was doubtless the date 
 given by Apollodoros.^ On the other hand, Plato says that 
 Parmenides came to Athens in his sixty-fifth year, accom- 
 panied by Zeno, and conversed with Sokrates, who was then 
 quite young. Now Sokrates was just over seventy when 
 he was put to death in 399 B.C. ; and therefore, if we suppose 
 him to have been an ephehos, that is, from eighteen to twenty 
 years old, at the time of his interview with Parmenides, we 
 get 451-449 B.C. as the date of that event. It is quite 
 uncritical to prefer the estimate of ApoUodoros to Plato's 
 express statement,^ especially as Parmenides himself speaks 
 of visiting " all towns," * and we have independent evidence 
 of the visit of Zeno to Athens, where Perikles is said to have 
 
 1 Diog. ix. 21 (R. P. III). For the foundation of Elea, see Herod, i. 
 165 sqq. It was on the coast of Lucania, south of Poseidonia (Paestum). 
 
 2 Diog. ix. 23 (R. P. III). Of. Diels, Rhein. Mus. xxxi. p. 34; and 
 Jacoby, pp. 231 sqq. 
 
 '* Plato, Parm, 127 b (R. P. iii d). Wilamowitz once said that there 
 were no anachronisms in Plato, though he now {Platon, vol. i. p. 507) regards 
 this statement as an "invention." I cannot agree. In the first place, we 
 have exact figures as to the ages of Parmenides and Zeno, which imply- 
 that the latter was twenty-five years younger than the former, not forty 
 as ApoUodoros said. In the second place, Plato refers to this meeting in 
 two other places {Theaet. 183 e 7 and Soph. 217 c 5), which do not seem 
 to be mere references to the dialogue entitled Parmenides. 
 
 * Cf. p. 172, n. I. 
 
 169 
 
170 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 '' heard " him.^ The date given by ApoUodoros depends 
 solely on that of the foundation of Elea (540 B.C.), which 
 he had adopted as the floruit of Xenophanes. Parmenides 
 is born in that year, just as Zeno is born in the year 
 when Parmenides " flourished." I do not understand how 
 any one can attach importance to such combinations. 
 
 We have seen (§ 55) that Aristotle mentions a statement 
 which made Parmenides a disciple of Xenophanes ; but it is 
 practically certain that the statement referred to is only 
 Plato's humorous remark in the Sophist, which we have 
 dealt with already. ^ Xenophanes tells us himself that, in 
 his ninety-second year, he was still wandering up and down 
 (fr. 8). At that time Parmenides would be well advanced 
 in life. And we must not overlook the statement of Sotion, 
 preserved by Diogenes, that, though Parmenides " heard " 
 Xenophanes, he did not " follow " him. He was really 
 the " associate " of a Pythagorean, Ameinias, son of Dio- 
 chaitas, " a poor but noble man to whom he afterwards 
 built a shrine as to a hero." It was Ameinias and not 
 Xenophanes that " converted " Parmenides to the philo- 
 sophic Hfe.^ This does not read hke an invention. The 
 shrine erected by Parmenides would still be there in later 
 days, Hke the grave of Pythagoras at Metapontion, and 
 would have a dedicatory inscription. It should also be 
 mentioned that Strabo describes Parmenides and Zeno as 
 Pythagoreans, and that Kebes talks of a " Parmenidean and 
 Pythagorean w^ay of life." ^ It is certain, moreover, that 
 
 ^ Plut. Per. 4, 3. See below, p. 311, n. i. 
 
 ' See above, Chap. II. p. 127, n. 2. 
 
 ' Diog. ix. 21 (R. P. Ill), reading 'A/ietj't^ ALoxalra with Diels {Hermes, 
 XXXV. p. 197). SotioD, in his Successions, separated Parmenides from 
 Xenophanes and associated him with the Pythagoreans {Dox. pp. 146, 
 148, 166). So Proclus in Parm. iv. 5 (Cousin), 'EXearat d' dfxcpu} (Parmenides 
 and Zeno) Kal oi toOto fibvov, dXXd Kal tov livdayopLKOv StSacr/caXeton fxera- 
 \a^6vT€, Kaddirep irov Kal NiKd/xaxos la-Tdpyjaev. Presumably this comes from 
 Timaios. 
 
 * Strabo, vi, i, p, 252 (p. 171, n. 2) ; Ceb, Tab. 2 (R. P. iii c). The 
 statements of Strabo are of the greatest value ; for they are based upon 
 historians (especially Timaios) now lost. 
 
 i 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 171 
 
 the opening of the poem of Parmenides is an allegorical 
 description of his conversion from some form of error to 
 what he held to be the truth, and that it is thrown into the 
 form of an Orphic apocalypse.^ That would be quite natural 
 if he had been a Pythagorean in his early days, so we need 
 not hesitate to accept the tradition that he had. As regards 
 the relation of Parmenides to the Pythagorean system, we 
 shall have something to say later. At present we need 
 only note that, hke most of the older philosophers, he took 
 part in poHtics ; and Speusippos recorded that he legislated 
 for his native city. Others add that the magistrates of 
 Elea made the citizens swear every year to abide by the 
 laws Parmenides had given them.^ 
 
 85. Parmenides was the first philosopher to expound The poem. 
 his system in metrical language. His predecessors, Anaxi- 
 mander, Anaximenes, and Herakleitos, wrote in prose, and 
 the only Greeks who ever wrote philosophy in verse at 
 all were just these two, Parmenides and Empedokles ; for 
 Xenophanes was not a philosopher any more than Epi- 
 charmos. Empedokles copied Parmenides ; and he, no 
 doubt, was influenced by the Orphics. But the thing 
 was an innovation, and one that did not maintain itself. 
 
 The fragments of Parmenides are preserved for the most 
 part by Simplicius, who fortunately inserted them in his- 
 commentary, because in his time the original work was 
 already rare.^ I follow the arrangement of Diels. 
 
 ^ We know too little of the apocalyptic poems of the sixth century 
 B.C. to be sure of the details. All we can say is that Parmenides has 
 taken the form of his poem from some such source. See Diels, " tJber 
 die poetischen Vorbilder des Parmenides " {Berl. Sitzh. 1896), and the 
 Introduction to his Parmenides Lehrgedichi, pp. 9 sqq. 
 
 2 Diog, ix. 23 (R. P. III). Plut. Adv. Col. 1226 a, Uap/JLepid-ns 5^ Tr}v 
 eavTov irarplda 5ie/f6(r/x77(r€ p6fiocs dpiaTOii^ (bare ras dpxas Kad' ^Kaarov ivLavrbv 
 i^opKovv Toi/s iroXiTas ^ixfieveiv tois Uapfxevldov vbfjLOLS. Strabo, vi. I, p. 
 252, ('EX^ai') ^^ •^s Hap/xevidTji Kal Zrjvcju iy^rouro dvdpes Hvdaydpeioi. 8oK€t 8i 
 fjLot Kal 81 eKeipovs Kal ^tl TrpSrepop evpo/xrjdrjpai. We can hardly doubt that • 
 this too comes from Timaios. 
 
 ' Simpl. Phys. 144, 25 (R. P. 117). SimpUcius, of course, had the 
 library of the Academy at his command. Diels estimates that we have 
 about nine-tenths of the 'AXrjdeia and about one-tenth of the A6^a. 
 
172 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (I) 
 
 The car that bears me carried me as far as ever my heart 
 desired, when it had brought me and set me on the renowned way 
 of the goddess, which leads the man who knows through all the 
 towns. 1 On that way was I borne along ; for on it did the wise 
 5 steeds carry me, drawing my car, and maidens showed the way. 
 And the axle, glowing in the socket — for it was urged round by 
 the whirling wheels at each end — gave forth a sound as of a pipe, 
 when the daughters of the Sun, hasting to convey me into the 
 light, threw back their veils from off their faces and left the 
 
 lo abode of Night. 
 
 There are the gates of the ways of Night and Day,^ fitted 
 above with a lintel and below with a threshold of stone. They 
 themselves, high in the air, are closed by mighty doors, and 
 Avenging Justice keeps the keys that fit them. Her did the 
 
 15 maidens entreat with gentle words and cunningly persuade to 
 unfasten without demur the bolted bars from the gates. Then, 
 when the doors were thrown back, they disclosed a wide opening, 
 when their brazen posts fitted with rivets and nails swung back 
 one after the other. Straight through them, on the broad way, 
 
 ^^ did the maidens guide the horses and the car, and the goddess 
 
 greeted me kindly, and took my right hand in hers, and spake 
 
 to me these words : 
 
 Welcome, O youth, that comest to my abode on the car that 
 
 bears thee tended by immortal charioteers ! It is no ill chance, 
 
 but right and justice that has sent thee forth to travel on this 
 
 way. Far, indeed, does it lie from the beaten track of men ! 
 
 Meet it is that thou shouldst learn all things, as well the unshaken 
 
 heart of well-rounded truth, as the opinions of mortals in which 
 
 is no true behef at all. Yet none the less shalt thou learn these 
 30 
 
 things also, — how passing right through all things one should 
 judge the things that seem to be.^ 
 
 1 The best MS. of Sextus, who quotes this passage, reads /caret Trdvr 
 iarri. Parmenides, then, was srn itinerant philosopher, like the sophists 
 of the next generation, and this makes his visit to the Athens of Perikles 
 all the more natural. 
 
 * For these see Hesiod, Theog. 748. 
 
 3 I read SoKifxCja {i.e. SoKi/xuxrat) with Diels. I have left it ambiguous | 
 in my rendering whether elvai is to be taken with doKL/mCoffai or doKovvra. 
 
 i 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 173 
 
 But do thou restrain thy thought from this way of inquiry, 
 nor let habit by its much experience force thee to cast upon this 
 way a wandering eye or sounding ear or tongue ; but judge by 35 
 argument ^ the much disputed proof uttered by me. There is 
 only one way left that can be spoken of. ... R. P. 113. 
 
 k 
 
 The Way of Truth 
 
 (2) 
 
 Look steadfastly with thy mind at things though afar as if 
 they were at hand. Thou canst not cut off what is from holding 
 fast to what is, neither scattering itself abroad in order nor 
 coming together. R. P. 118 a. 
 
 (3) 
 
 It is all one to me where I begin ; for I shall come back 
 again there. 
 
 (4.5) 
 
 Come now, I will tell thee — and do thou hearken to my 
 saying and carry it away — the only two ways of search that 
 can be thought of. The first, namely, that It is, and that it is 
 impossible for it not to be, is the way of belief, for truth is its 
 companion. The other, namely, that It is not, and that it must 
 needs not be, — that, I tell thee, is a path that none can learn 
 of at all. For thou canst not know what is not — that is im- 
 possible — nor utter it ; for it is the same thing that can be 
 thought and that can be.^ R. P. 114. 
 
 1 This is the earliest instance of X670S in the sense of (dialectical) 
 argument which Sokrates made familiar. He got it, of course, from the 
 Eleatics. The Herakleitean use is quite different. (See p. 133, n. i.) 
 
 2 I still beUeve that ZeUer's is the only possible interpretation of rb 
 yap avrd voetv ^cftlv re Kal elvac {denn dasselhe kann gedacht warden und 
 sein, p. 558, n. i : Eng. trans, p. 584, «. i). It is impossible to separate 
 voeip i(TTLv here from fr. 4, el<yl vorjcrai, "can be thought." No rendering is 
 admissible which makes voeiu the subject of the sentence ; for a bare 
 infinitive is never so used. (Some grammars make Troielv the subject in 
 a sentence Uke dUaibv eo-ri tovto Troidv, but this is shown to be wrong by 
 5kat6s eiixL tovto iroieiv.) The use of the infinitive as a subject only 
 became possible when the articular infinitive was developed (cf. Monro, 
 H. Gr. §§ 233, 234, 242). The original dative meaning of the infinitive at 
 once explains the usage {yoctv €<ttiv, " is for thinking,'^ ^' Q^p, Ij^ tl\ought," 
 Uti.v dvai, " is for being," " can be "). 
 
174 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (6) 
 
 It needs must be that what can be spoken and thought is ; 
 for it is possible for it to be, and it is not possible for what is 
 nothing to be.^ This is what I bid thee ponder. I hold thee 
 back from this first way of inquiry, and from this other also, 
 5 upon which mortals knowing naught wander two-faced ; for help- 
 lessness guides the wandering thought in their breasts, so that 
 they are borne along stupefied like men deaf and blind. Undis- 
 cerning crowds, who hold that it is and is not the same and not 
 the same,2 and all things travel in opposite directions ! ^ R. P. 115. 
 
 (7) 
 
 >>w For this shall never be proved, that the things that are not 
 are ; and do thou restrain thy thought from this way of inquiry. 
 R. P. 116. 
 
 (8) 
 
 One path only is left for us to speak of, namely, that It is. In 
 this path are very many tokens that what is is uncreated and inde- 
 structible ; for it is complete,^ immovable, and without end. Nor 
 5 was it ever, nor wiU it be ; for now it is, all at once, a continuous 
 
 1 The construction here is the same as that explained in the last note. 
 The words rb X^yeLv re voeiv r i6v mean " that which it is possible 
 to speak of and think," and are correctly paraphrased by Simplicius 
 {Phys. p. 86, 29, Diels), el oZu Sirep &v rts t) etirrj ^ vorja-Q rb 6v taTL. Then 
 i<TTL yhp elvaL means " it can be," and the last phrase should be con- 
 strued ovk i<xTL firjdev (elvai), " there is no room for nothing to be." 
 
 ^ I construe oh vevbixiaTaL rb iriXeiv re Koi oiiK elvaL raiurbv Kai ov 
 rairrbv. The subject of the infinitives TrAeiv koL ovk elvat is the it, which 
 has to be supphed also with ^ariv and ovk e^TLv. This way of taking the 
 words makes it unnecessary to believe that Parmenides said [to) ovk elvai 
 instead of (r6) fir} elvat for " not-being." There is no difference between 
 TT^Xecv and elvai except in rhythmical value. 
 
 3 I take TrdvTuv as neuter and understand irakivrpoiros KeXevdos as 
 equivalent to the bSbs dvai Kdrto of Herakleitos. I do not think it has 
 anything to do with the iraXivrovos (or TraXivrpoiros) dpfxoviij. See Chap. 
 III. p. 136, n. 4. 
 
 * I prefer to read ^(xtl yap ovXofieXh with Plutarch {Adv. Col. 11 14 c). 
 Proklos {in Farm. 1152, 24) also read ovXofxeXes. Simplicius, who has 
 fiovvoyev^s here, calls the One of Parmenides bXofieX^s elsewhere {Phys. 
 p. 137, 15). The reading of [Plut.] Strom. 5, fiodvov ixowoyev^s, helps to 
 explain the confusion. We have only to suppose that the letters fx, v, y 
 were written above the line in the Academy copy of Parmenides by some 
 one who had Tim. 31 b 3 in mind. Parmenides could not call- what is 
 " only-begotten," though the Pythagoreans might call the world so. 
 
 dl 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 175 
 
 one. For what kind of origin for it wiK thou look for ? In what 
 way and from what source could it have drawn its increase ? . . . 
 I shall not let thee say nor think that it came from what is not ; 
 for it can neither be thought nor uttered that anything is not. 
 And, if it came from nothing, what need could have made it 10 
 arise later rather than sooner ? Therefore must it either be 
 altogether or be not at all. Nor will the force of truth suffer 
 aught to arise besides itself from that which is not. Wherefore, 
 Justice doth not loose her fetters and let anything come into 
 being or pass away, but holds it fast. Our judgment thereon 15 
 depends on this : "Is it or is it not ? " Surely it is adjudged, as 
 it needs must be, that we are to set aside the one way as unthink- 
 able and nameless (for it is no true way), and that the other path 
 is real and true. How, then, can what is be going to be in the 
 future ? Or how could it come into being ? If it came into 20 
 being, it is not ; nor is it if it is going to be in the future. Thus 
 is becoming extinguished and passing away not to be heard of. 
 R. P. 117. 
 
 Nor is it divisible, since it is all alike, and there is no more ^ of 
 it in one place than in another, to hinder it from holding together, 
 nor less of it, but everything is full of what is. Wherefore it is 23 
 wholly continuous ; for what is, is in contact with what is. 
 
 Moreover, it is immovable in the bonds of mighty chains, 
 without beginning and without end ; since coming into being 
 and passing away have been driven afar, and true belief has cast 
 them away. It is the same, and it rests in the self-same place, 
 abiding in itself. And thus it remaineth constant in its place ; 30 
 for hard necessity keeps it in the bonds of the limit that holds it 
 fast on every side. Wherefore it is not permitted to what is to 
 be infinite ; for it is in need of nothing ; while, if it were infinite, 
 * it would stand in need of everything.^ R. P. 118. 
 
 1 For the difi&culties which have been felt about fxaWov here, see Diels's 
 note. If the word is to be pressed, his interpretation is admissible ; but 
 it seems to me that this is simply an instance of " polar expression." It 
 is true that it is only the case of there being less of what is in one place 
 than another that is important for the divisibility of the One ; but if 
 there is less in one place, there is more in another than in that place. 
 In any case, the reference to the Pythagorean " air " or " void" which 
 makes reality discontinuous is plain. 
 
 2 Simplicius certainly read ixt) ibv 8' hv Travrbs iSeiro, which is metrically 
 impossible. I have followed Bergk in deleting fi-q, and have interpreted 
 with Zeller. So too Diels. 
 
176 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The thing that can be thought and that for the sake of which 
 
 35 the thought exists is the same ; ^ for you cannot find thought 
 
 without something that is, as to which it is uttered. ^ And there 
 
 is not, and never shall be, anything besides what is, since fate 
 
 has chained it so as to be whole and immovable. Wherefore all 
 
 these things are but names which mortals have given, beUeving 
 
 40 them to be true — coming into being and passing away, being 
 
 and not being, change of place and alteration of bright colour. 
 
 R. P. 119. 
 
 C Since, then, it has a furthest limit, it is complete on every 
 
 side, like the mass of a rounded sphere, equally poised from the 
 
 45 centre in every direction ; for it cannot be greater or smaller in 
 
 one place than in another. For there is no nothing that could 
 
 keep it from reaching out equally, nor can aught that is be more 
 
 here and less there than what is, since it is all inviolabJe. ^ For 
 
 the point from which it is equal in every direction tends equally 
 
 . to the limits. R. P. 120. 
 
 The Way of Belief 
 
 50 Here shall I close my trustworthy speech and thought about 
 
 the truth. Henceforward learn the beUefs of mortals, giving ear 
 
 to the deceptive ordering of my words. 
 
 Mortals have made up their minds to name two forms, one 
 
 of which they should not name, and that is where they go astray 
 55 from the truth. They have distinguished them as opposite in 
 
 form, and have assigned to them marks distinct from one another. 
 
 To the one they allot the fire of heaven, gentle, very Hght, in 
 
 every direction the same as itself, but not the same as the other. 
 
 The other is just the opposite to it, dark night, a compact and 
 60 heavy body. Of these I tell thee the whole arrangement as it 
 
 seems likely ; for so no thought of mortals will ever outstrip 
 
 thee. R. P. 121. 
 
 (9) 
 
 Now that all things have been named Ught and night, and 
 the names which belong to the power of each have been assigned 
 
 1 For the construction of ia-TL poelv, see above, p. 173, n. 2. 
 
 2 As Diels rightly points out, the Ionic (pari^eiv is equivalent to 
 dvofxai^eiv. The meaning, I think, is this. We may name things as we 
 choose, but there can be no thought corresponding to a name that is not 
 the name of something real. 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 177 
 
 to these things and to those, everything is full at once of light 
 and dark night, both equal, since neither has aught to do with 
 the other. 
 
 (10, II) 
 
 And thou shalt know the substance of the sky, and all tlie 
 signs in the sky, and the resplendent works of the glowing sun's 
 pure torch, and whence they arose. And thou shalt learn 
 likewise of the wandering deeds of the round-faced moon, and of 
 her substance. Thou shalt know, too, the heavens that surround 
 us, whence they arose, and how Necessity took them and bound 
 them to keep the Umits of the stars . . . how the earth, and 
 the sun, and the moon, and the sky that is common to all, and 
 the Milky Way, and the outermost Olympos, and the burning 
 might of the stars arose. R. P. 123, 124. 
 
 (12) 
 
 The narrower bands were filled with unmixed fire, and those 
 next them with night, and in the midst of these rushes their 
 portion of fire. In the midst of these is the divinity that directs 
 the course of all things ; for she is the beginner of all painful 
 birth and all begetting, driving the female to the embrace of the 
 male, and the male to that of the female. R. P. 125. 
 
 (13) ' 
 First of all the gods she contrived Eros. R. P. 125. 
 
 (14) 
 
 Shining by night with borrowed light,^ wandering round the 
 earth. 
 
 (15) 
 
 Always looking to the beams of the sun. 
 
 (16) 
 
 For just as thought stands at any time to the mixture of its 
 erring organs, so does it come to men ; for that which thinks 
 
 1 Note the curious echo of //. v. 214. Empedokles has it too (fr. 45), 
 It appears to be a joke, made in the spirit of Xenophanes, when it was 
 first discovered that the moon shone by reflected Hght. Anaxagoras may- 
 have introduced this view to the Athenians (§ 135), but these verses prove 
 it was not originated by him. 
 
 12 
 
178 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 is the same, namely, the substance of the limbs, in each and 
 every man ; for their thought is that of which there is more in 
 them.i R. P. 128. 
 
 (17) 
 On the right boys ; on the left girls.^ 
 
 (19) 
 
 Thus, according to men's opinions, did things come into 
 being, and thus they are now. In time they will grow up and 
 pass away. To each of these things men have assigned a fixed 
 name. R. P. 129 b. 
 
 « It is." 86. In the First Part of his poem, we find Parmenides 
 chiefly interested to prove that it is ; but it is not quite 
 obvious at first sight what it is precisely that is. He says 
 simply. What is, is. There can be no real doubt that this 
 is what we call body. It is certainly regarded as spatially 
 extended ; for it is quite seriously spoken of as a sphere 
 (fr. 8, 43). Moreover, Aristotle tells us that Parmenides 
 beheved in none but a sensible reaUty.^ Parmenides does 
 not say a word about "Being" anywhere,* and it is remark- 
 
 1 This fragment of the theory of knowledge which was expounded in 
 the .second part of the poem of Parmenides must be taken in connexion 
 with what we are told by Theophrastos in the " Fragment on Sensation " 
 {Dox. p. 499 ; cf. p. 193). It appears from this that he said the character 
 of men's thought depended upon the preponderance of the light or the 
 dark element in their bodies. They are wise when the hght element 
 predominates, and foolish when the dark gets the upper hand. 
 
 2 This is a fragment of Parmenides's embryology. Diels's fr. 18 is a re- 
 translation of the Latin hexameters of Caelius Aurelianus quoted R. P. 127 a. 
 
 3 Arist. De caelo, V, i. 298 b 21, iKeXvoi 5^ {ol irepl M^Xiaaov re Kal 
 IIapfX€vi87]v) Sia to fxrjd^v fx^v SlWo irapb. tt)v tQv aiadrjTQu oiicriav viroXafi^dveiy 
 eZvat kt\. So too Eudemos, in the first book of his Physics {ap. 
 Simpl. Phys. p. 133, 25), said of Parmenides : rb fih o^v Koivbv ovk Slv X^yoi. 
 oUre yap i^rjTeiTb ttw to, rotavra, aXK' iiarepov iK rQ>v \byu3v irporjXdeu, ovre iiri- 
 8ixoi-TO hv d T(p 5vTt iiriXiyei.. ttQs yap ^arai toOto '' fi^aaodev iaoTraXes" Kal 
 TO, TOiavra ; T<p be ovpavi^ (the world) ax^bbv Trdvres i<papnbaov<XLV ol tolovtol 
 Xbyoi. The Neoplatonists, of course, saw in the One the vorjTbi Kbafxos, 
 and Simplicius calls the sphere a " mythical figment." See especially 
 Baumker, " Die Einheit des Parmenideischen Seiendes " {Jahrb. f. kl. 
 Phil., 1886, pp. 541 sqq.), and Das Problem der Materia, pp. 50 sqq. 
 
 * We must not render rb ibv by "Being," das Sein or I'etre. It is 
 "what is," das Seiende, ce qui est. As to (rd) eli/ai it does not occur, and 
 hardly could occur at this date. 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 179 
 
 able that he avoids the term ** god," which was so freely 
 used by earlier and later thinkers. The assertion that it is 
 amounts just to this, that the universe is a plenum ; and 
 that there is no such thing as empty space, either inside 
 or outside the world. From this it follows that there can 
 be no such thing as motion. Instead of endowing the 
 One with an impulse to change, as Herakleitos had done, 
 and thus making it capable of explaining the world, Ppr- 
 menides dismissed change as an illusion. He showed once 
 
 for all thaf it you take the One seriously you are bound 
 to deny everything else. All previous solutions of the 
 question, therefore, had missed the point. Anaximenes, 
 who tfemight to save the unity of the primary substance 
 by his theory of rarefaction and condensation, did not 
 observe that, by assuming there was less of what is in 
 one place than another, he virtually affirmed the existence 
 of what is not (fr. 8, 45). ('The Pythagorean explanation 
 impHed that empty space or air exi^ted^outsi^^ 
 and that it en ter ed into it to separate the units ($ ^^) ?) 
 It, too, assumes the existence of what is not. Nor is the 
 theory of Herakleitos any more satisfactory ; for it is based 
 on the contradiction that fire both is and is not (fr. 6). 
 
 The allusion to Herakleitos in the verses last referred 
 to has been doubted, though upon insufficient grounds. 
 Zeller points out quite rightly that Herakleitos never says 
 Being and not-Being are the same (the old translation of 
 fr. 6, 8) ; and, were there nothing more than this, the refer- 
 ence might well seem doubtful. The statement, however, 
 that, according to the view in question, " all things travel in 
 opposite directions," can hardly be understood of anything 
 but the " upward and downward path " of Herakleitos 
 (§ 71). And, as we have seen, Parmenides does not attribute 
 the view that Being and not-Being are the same to the 
 philosopher whom he is attacking ; he only says that it is 
 and is not the same and not the same.^ That is the natural 
 
 ^ See above, fr. 6, n. 2. 
 
i8o EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 meaning of the words ; and it furnishes a very accurate 
 description of the theory of Herakleitos. 
 The 87. The great novelty in the poem of Parmenides is the 
 
 of Par- ' method of argument. He first asks what is the common 
 memdes. presuppositiou of all the views he has to deal with, and he 
 finds that this is the existence of what is not. The next 
 question is whether this can be thought, and the answer is 
 that it cannot. If you think at all, you must think of some- 
 thing. Therefore there is no nothing. Only that can be 
 which can be thought (fr. 5) ; for thought exists for the sake 
 of what is (fr. 8, 34). 
 
 This method Parmenides carries out with the utmost 
 rigour. He will not have us pretend that we think what 
 we must admit to be unthinkable. It is true that if we 
 resolve to allow nothing but what we can understand, we 
 come into direct conflict with our senses, which present us 
 with a world of change and decay. So much the worse 
 for the senses, says Parmenides. That is the inevitable 
 outcome of a corporeal monism, and this bold declaration! 
 of it ought to have destroyed that theory for ever, x If] 
 Parmenides had lacked courage to work out the prevaiUn^ 
 views of his time to their logical conclusion, and to accepi 
 that conclusion, however paradoxical it might appear, 
 men might have gone on in the endless circle of opposi- 
 tion, rarefaction, and condensation, one and many, for 
 ever. It was the thorough-going dialectic of Parmenides 
 that made progress possible. '^ Philosophy must now cease 
 to be monistic or cease to be corporealist. It could nol 
 cease to be corporeaHst ; for the incorporeal was still un- 
 known. It therefore, ceased to be monistic, and arrive( 
 ultimately at the atomic theory, which, so far as w( 
 know, is the last word of the view that the world is bodi 
 in motion.^ 
 
 ^ From the point of view we are now taking, it is doubtful if evei 
 Atomism can rightly be called Monism, since it impUes the real existence 
 of space. The most modern forms of Monism are not corporeahst, sine 
 they replace body by energy as the ultimate reahty. 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA i8i 
 
 I' 
 88. Parmenides goes on to develop all the consequences The 
 of the admission that it is. It must be uncreated and inde- ^^^" ^* 
 structible. It cannot have arisen out of nothing ; for there 
 is no such thing as nothing. Nor can it have arisen from 
 something ; for there is no room for anything but itself. 
 What is cannot have beside it any empty space in which 
 something else might arise ; for empty space is nothing, 
 nothing cannot be thought, and therefore cannot exist. 
 What is never came into being, nor is anything going to 
 come into being in the future. " Is it or is it not ? " If it 
 is, then it is now, all at once. 
 
 That this is a denial of the existence of empty space was 
 well known to Plato. He says Parmenides held " all things 
 were one, and that the one remains at rest in itself, having 
 no place in which to move.'* ^ Aristotle is no less clear. ^ 
 He lays down that Parmenides was driven to take up 
 the position that the One was immovable just because no 
 one had yet imagined there was any reality other than 
 the sensible. 2 
 
 That which is, is ; and it cannot be more or less. There 
 is, therefore, as much of it in one place as in another, and 
 the world is a continuous, indivisible plenum. From this 
 it follows at once that it must be immovable. If it moved, 
 it must move into an empty space, and there is no empty 
 space. It is hemmed in by what is, by the real, on every 
 side. For the same reason, it must be finite, and can have 
 nothing beyond it. It is complete in itself, and has no 
 need to stretch out indefinitely into an empty space that 
 does not exist. Hence, too, it is spherical. It is equally 
 real in every direction, and the sphere is the only form that 
 meets this condition. Any other would be in one direction 
 more than in another. 
 
 1 Plato, Theaet. i8o e 3, Aj ^j/ re trdvTa iarl koI ^(Ttt}K€v avrh iy ai/rcf 
 ovK ixov X^PO'^ ^v Tj Kiveirai. This is explicitly stated by Melissos (fr. 7, 
 p. 323), but Plato clearly meant to ascribe it to Parmenides as well. 
 
 * Arist. De caelo, V, i. 298 b 21, quoted above, p. 178, «. 3, and the 
 other passages there quoted. 
 
 r 
 
i82 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Par- 89. To sum Up. What is, is a finite, spherical, motion- 
 
 mem es 1^^^ corporeal plenum, and there is nothing beyond it. The 
 father of appearances of multipUcity and motion, empty space and 
 ism. time, are illusions. We see from this that the primary 
 
 substance of which the early cosmologists were in search 
 has now become a sort of " thing in itself." It never quite 
 lost this character again. What appears later as the 
 elements of Empedokles, the so-called " homoeomeries '* of 
 Anaxagoras and the atoms of Leukippos and Demokritos, 
 is just the Parmenidean " being." Parmenides is not, as 
 some have said, the " father of ideahsm " ; on the contrary, 
 all materialism depends on his view of reaUty. 
 
 90. It is commonly held that, in the Second Part of his 
 poem, Parmenides offered a duahstic theory of the origin of 
 things as his own conjectural explanation of the sensible 
 world, or that, as Gomperz says, " What he offered were the 
 Opinions of Mortals ; and this description did not merely 
 cover other people's opinions. It included his own as well, 
 as far as they were not confined to the unassailable ground 
 of an apparent philosophical necessity." ^ Now it is true 
 that in one place Aristotle appears to countenance a view of 
 this sort, but nevertheless it is an anachronism. ^ Nor is it 
 really Aristotle's view. He was well aware that Parmenides 
 did not admit the existence of '* not-being " in any degree 
 whatever ; but it was a natural way of speaking to call the 
 cosmology of the Second Part of the poem that of Parmenides. 
 His hearers would understand in what sense this was meant. 
 At any rate, the Peripatetic tradition was that Parmenides, 
 in the Second Part of the poem, meant to give the belief of 
 " the many." This is how Theophrastos put the matter, 
 
 ^ Greek Thinkers, vol. i. pp. 180 sqq. 
 
 2 Met. A, 5. 986 b 31 (R. P. 121 a). Aristotle's way of putting the 
 matter is due to his interpretation of fr. 8, 54, which -he took to mean 
 that one of the two " forms " was to be identified with to 6v and the other 
 with rb ixT) &v. Cf. De gen. corr. A, 3. 318 b 6, wairep Uap/xevid-qs \eyec 56o, 
 rb dy Kal to fir] du ehai (pda-Kojv. This last sentence shows clearly that 
 when Aristotle says Uapfj^vidrjs, he sometimes means what we should call 
 " Parmenides." 
 
 I 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 183 
 
 and Alexander seems to have spoken of the cosmology as 
 something which Parmenides himself regarded as wholly 
 false. ^ The other view comes from the Neoplatonists, and 
 especially SimpHcius, who regarded the Way of Truth as an 
 account of the intelligible world, and the Way of Opinion 
 as a description of the sensible. It need hardly be said 
 that this is almost as great an anachronism as the Kantian 
 paralleUsm suggested by Gomperz.^ Parmenides himself 
 tells us in the most unequivocal language that there is no 
 truth at all in the theory which he expounds, and that he 
 gives it merely as the belief of " mortals." It was this that 
 led Theophrastos to speak of it as the opinion of " the 
 many." 
 
 His explanation however, though preferable to that of 
 SimpHcius, is not convincing either. " The many " are as 
 far as possible from believing in an elaborate duaUsm such 
 as Parmenides expounded, and it is a highly artificial 
 hypothesis to assume that he wished to show how the popular 
 view of the world could best be systematised. " The many *' 
 would hardly be convinced of their error by having their 
 beUefs presented to them in a form they would certainly 
 fail to recognise them in. This, indeed, seems the most 
 incredible interpretation of all. It still, however, finds 
 adherents, so it is necessary to point out that the beliefs in 
 question are only called " the opinions of mortals " for the 
 very simple reason that the speaker is a goddess. Further, 
 we have to note that Parmenides forbids two ways of 
 research, and we have seen that the second of these, which is 
 also expressly ascribed to " mortals," must be the system 
 of Herakleitos. We should expect, then, to find that the 
 other way is also the system of some contemporary school, 
 
 1 Theophr. Phys. Op. fr. 6 {Dox. p. 482 ; R. P. 121 a), Kark 86^av 8^ rCoy 
 TToWdv els rb yiveaiv dTroSovvai tQv (paivoixevojv 8vo iroiQv rdr dpxds. For 
 Alexander, cf. Simpl. Phys. p. 38, 24, ei 8e ^evSels irivTrj Toi>% \6yovs 
 oierat iKeivovs {'AXi^ap8pos) kt\. 
 
 2 Simpl. Phys. p. 39, 10 (R. P. 121 b). Gomperz, Greek Thinkers, 
 vol. i. p. 180. 
 
i84 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 and it seems hard to discover any of sufficient importance 
 at this date except the Pythagorean. Now it is admitted 
 by every one that there are Pythagorean ideas in the Second 
 Part of the poem, and it is therefore to be presumed, in the 
 absence of evidence to the contrary, that the whole of its 
 cosmology comes from the same source. It does not appear 
 that Parmenides said any more about Herakleitos than the 
 words to which we have just referred, in which he forbids the 
 second way of inquiry. He impHes, indeed, that there are 
 really only two ways that can be thought of, and that the 
 attempt of Herakleitos to combine them was f utile. ^ In 
 any case, the Pythagoreans were far more serious opponents 
 at that date in Italy, and it is certainly to them that we 
 should expect Parmenides to define his attitude. 
 
 It is still not quite clear, however, why he should have 
 thought it worth while to put into hexameters a view he be- 
 lieved to be false. Here it becomes important to remember , 
 that he had been a Pythagorean himself, and that the 
 poem is a renunciation of his former beUefs. In the intro- 
 ductory verses, he tells us distinctly that he has passed from 
 darkness into the light. In such cases men commonly feel i 
 the necessity of showing where their old views were wrong. 1 
 The goddess tells him that he must learn of those beUefsj 
 also *' how one ought to pass right through all things and 
 judge the things that seem to be." We get a further hint 
 in another place. He is to learn these behefs, " and so no 
 opinion of mortals will ever get the better of him " (fr. 8, 6i). 
 If we remember that the Pythagorean system at this time 
 was handed down by oral tradition alone, we shall see what 
 this may mean. Parmenides was founding a dissident 
 school, and it was necessary for him to instruct his disciples 
 in the system they might be called upon to oppose. In 
 any case, they could not reject it intelhgently without 
 
 * Cf. frs. 4 and 6, especially the words alVep 65ot ixovvat 8i^7i<ti6s e/trtj 
 voTjcraL. The third way, that of Herakleitos, is only added as an after-] 
 thought — avrap iireLT dirh tT]$ kt\. 
 
 I 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 185 
 
 a knowledge of it, and this Parmenides had to supply 
 himself.^ 
 
 91. The view that the Second Part of the poem of The dual- 
 
 ist cos- 
 
 Parmenides was a sketch of contemporary Pythagorean moiogy. 
 cosmology is, doubtless, incapable of rigorous demonstration, 
 but it can be made extremely probable. The entire history 
 of Pythagoreanism up to the end of the fifth century B.C. is 
 certainly conjectural ; but, if we find in Parmenides ideas 
 wholly unconnected with his own view of the world, and if 
 we find precisely the same ideas in later Pythagoreanism, 
 the most natural inference will be that the later Pytha- 
 goreans derived these views from their predecessors, and 
 that they formed part of the original stock-in-trade of the 
 society. This will be confirmed if we find that they are 
 developments of certain features in the old Ionian cosmology. 
 Pythagoras came from Samos, and it was not, so far as we 
 can see, in his cosmological views that he chiefly displayed 
 originality. It has been pointed out (§ 53) that the idea of 
 the world breathing came from Anaximenes, and we need not 
 be surprised to find traces of Anaximander too. Now, if we 
 were confined to what Aristotle tells us on this subject, it 
 would be hard to make out a case ; but his statements 
 require, as usual, to be examined with care. He says, first 
 of all, that the two elements of Parmenides were the Warm 
 and the Cold.^ In this he is so far justified by the fragments 
 that, since the Fire of which Parmenides speaks is, of course, 
 warm, the other " form," which has all the opposite quahties, 
 must of necessity be cold. Here, then, we have the tradi- 
 tional " opposites " of the Milesians. Aristotle's identifica- 
 
 1 I read XPW SoKi-fiQa-' eXvai in fr. i, 32 with Diels. The view that 
 the opinions contained in the Second Part are those of others, 
 and are not given as true in any sense whatsoever, is shared by Diels. 
 The objections of Wilamowitz {Hermes, xxxiv. pp. 203 sqq.) do not 
 appear to me cogent. If we interpret him rightly, Parmenides never 
 says that " this hypothetical explanation is . . . better than that of any 
 one else." What he does say is that it is untrue altogether. 
 
 2 Met. A, 5. 986 b 34, depfibv Kal ypvxp(>v', Phys. A, 5. 188 a 20; De gen. 
 corr. A, 3. 318 b 6 ; B, 3. 330 b 14. 
 
i86 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 tion of these with Fire and Earth is, however, misleading, 
 though Theophrastos followed him in it.^ SimpHcius, who 
 had the poem before him (§ 85), after mentioning Fire and 
 Earth, at once adds " or rather Light and Darkness " ; ^ 
 and this is suggestive. Lastly, Aristotle's identification 
 of the dense element with " what is not," ^ the unreal of the 
 First Part of the poem, is not easy to reconcile with the view 
 that it is earth. On the other hand, if we suppose that the 
 second of the two '' forms," the one which should not have 
 been " named," is the Pythagorean Air or Void, we get a 
 very good explanation of Aristotle's identification of it 
 with " what is not." We seem, then, to be justified in 
 neglecting the identification of the dense element with earth 
 for the present. At a later stage, we shall be able to see 
 how it may have originated.* The further statement of 
 Theophrastos, that the Warm was the efficient cause and 
 the Cold the material or passive,^ is not, of course, to be 
 regarded as historical. 
 
 We have seen that SimpHcius, with the poem of Par- 
 menides before him, corrects Aristotle by substituting Light 
 and Darkness for Fire and Earth, and he is amply borne 
 out by the fragments he quotes. Parmenides himself calls 
 one " form " Light, Flame, and Fire, and the other Night, 
 and we have now to consider whether these can be identi- 
 fied with the Pythagorean Limit and Unhmited. We have 
 seen good reason to believe (§ 58) that the idea of the world 
 breathing belonged to the earhest form of Pythagoreanism, 
 and there can be no difiiculty in identifying this " boundless 
 breath " with Darkness, which stands very well for the 
 
 * Phys. A, 5- 188 a 21, raOra be {depixbv /cat ypvxpov) Trpocayope^iei wvp /cat 
 yrjv ; Met. A, 5. 986 b 34, olov irvp Kal yijv X^ycop. Cf. Theophr. Phys. 
 Op. fr. 6 {Dox. p. 482 ; R. P. 121 a). 
 
 2 Phys. p. 25, 15, ojs Ilapfjievidijs ev rots Trpos db^av irvp Koi yrjv (7) fiaXKov 
 (pus Kal <tk6tos). So already Plut. Adv. Col. 11 14 b, to Xafiwpbv Kal cTKOTeivdv. 
 
 ' Met. A, 5. 986 b 35, ToiT(j}v bk Kark fxh rb '6v rb depfibu rdrreL, ddrepoy 
 5i Kara rb /jlt] 6p. See above, p. 182, n. 2. 
 
 * See below. Chap. VII. § 147. 
 
 6 Theophr. Phys. Op. fr. 6 {Dox. p. 482 ; R. P. 121 a), followed by 
 the doxographers. 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 187 
 
 Unlimited. '* Air '* or mist was always regarded as the 
 dark element.^ And that which gives definiteness to the 
 vague darkness is certainly light or fire, and this may 
 account for the prominence given to that element by 
 Hippasos.2 We may probably conclude, then, that the 
 Pythagorean distinction between the Limit and the Un- 
 limited, which we shall have to consider later (Chap. VII.), 
 made its first appearance in this crude form. If, on the 
 other hand, we identify darkness with the Limit, and Ught 
 with the UnUmited, as many critics do, we get into insuper- 
 able difficulties. 
 
 92. We must now look at the general cosmical view The 
 expounded in the Second Part of the poem. The fragments bodl^? ^ 
 are scanty, and the doxographical tradition hard to in- 
 terpret ; but enough remains to show that here, too, we are 
 
 on Pythagorean ground. Actios says : 
 
 Parmenides held that there were bands crossing one another ^ 
 and encircling one another, formed of the rare and the dense 
 element respectively, and that between these there were other 
 mixed bands made up of light and darkness. That which 
 surrounds them all was solid like a wall, and under it is a fiery 
 band. That which is in the middle of all the bands is also solid, 
 and surrounded in turn by a fiery band. The central circle 
 of the mixed bands is the cause of movement and becoming to 
 all the rest. He calls it " the goddess who directs their course," 
 "the Holder of Lots," and "Necessity." — Aet. ii. 7. i (R. P. 126). 
 
 93. Now it is quite unjustifiable to regard these " bands " The 
 
 as spheres. The word arecpavaL can mean " rims " or '^'■^^"''"'• 
 
 1 Note the identification of the dense element with " air " in [Pint.] 
 Strom, fr. 5 {Dox. p. 581), \iyei 5^ tj]v 7^1' rod wvkvov Karappvivros dipos 
 yeyovivai. This is pure Anaximenes. For the identification of this 
 " air " with " mist and darkness," cf. Chap. I. § 27, and Chap. V. § 107. 
 It is to be observed further that Plato puts this last identification into 
 the mouth of a Pythagorean {Tim. 52 d). 
 
 * See above, p. 109. 
 
 ' It seems most likely that iiraWrjXovi here means " crossing one 
 another." as the Milky Way crosses the Zodiac. The term iwdWrjXos is 
 opposed to irapdXKrjXos. 
 
i88 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 " brims " or anything of that sort/ but it seems incredible 
 that it should be used of spheres. It does not appear, 
 either, that the solid circle which surrounds all the crowns is 
 to be regarded as spherical. The expression " Hke a wall " 
 would be highly inappropriate in that case.^ We seem, then, 
 to be face to face with something Hke the '* wheels " of 
 Anaximander, and it is highly probable that Pythagoras 
 adopted the theory from him. Nor is evidence lacking 
 that the Pythagoreans did regard the heavenly bodies in 
 this way. In Plato's Myth of Er, which is certainly Pytha- 
 gorean in its general character, we do not hear of spheres, 
 but of the " Ups " of concentric whorls fitted into one another 
 Hke a nest of boxes. ^ In the Timaeus there are no spheres 
 either, but bands or strips crossing each other at an angle.* 
 Lastly, in the Homeric Hymn to Ares, which seems to have 
 been composed under Pythagorean influence, the word 
 used for the orbit of the planet is avrv^, which must mean 
 '' rim.'' 5 
 
 The fact is, there is no evidence that any one ever adopted 
 the theory of celestial spheres, till Aristotle turned the 
 geometrical construction which Eudoxos had set up as a 
 hypothesis " to save appearances " {aw^eiv ra (^aLvofxeva) 
 
 ^ As Diels points out, crT€(f)dv7j in Homer is used of a golden band in 
 the hair (S 597) or the brim of a helmet (H 12). It may be added that it 
 was used technically of the figure contained between two concentric circles 
 (Proclus, in Eucl. I. p. 163, 12). It always means something annular. 
 
 2 It must be remembered that relxo^ is a city-wall or fortification, 
 and that Euripides uses <xTe<f>dvri for a city-waU [Hec. 910). Heath's 
 remark (p. 69) that " certainly Parmenides' All was spherical " is irrelevant. 
 We have nothing to do with his own views here. 
 
 ^ Rep. X. 616 d 5, Kaddirep ol KaSoi ol els dWi^Xovs apfidrrovTes ', e I, 
 k\jk\ovs dviadev rd X^'-^V (paivoPTas {(rcpovdvXovs). 
 
 * Tim. 36 b 6, Tavrrjv oVu ttjv (TTuaraaLV Trdaav dnrXrjv Kard fiiJKOs (7x/o-as, 
 fi^aTjv Trpbs fx^o-rjv cKaripav dW-^Xais dtov x^' (the letter X) irpoa^aXuiv 
 KariKa/xxl/ev eh Iv kiukX({). 
 
 ' Hymn to Ares, 6 : irvpavyia k^kXov^ eXlaawv 
 
 aWipot iirrairdpoLS eVi Telpeaiv, ^p6a ae TrtDXot 
 fa0Xc7^es TpirdTTjs vir^p dvTvyos aikv ^x^^'^'- 
 
 So, in allusion to an essentially Pythagorean view, Proclus says t~ 
 planet Venus (h. iv. 17) : 
 
 efre Koi eirrd kOkXuv virkp Hvrvyas aWipa valets. 
 
 i 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 189 
 
 into real things.^ At this date, spheres would not have 
 served to explain anything that could not be explained 
 more simply without them. 
 
 We are next told that these " bands " encircle one • 
 another or are folded over one another, and that they are 
 made of the rare and the dense element. We also learn 
 that between them are " mixed bands " made up of Hght 
 and darkness. Now it is to be observed, in the first place, 
 that light and darkness are exactly the same thing as the 
 rare and the dense, and it looks as if there was some con- 
 fusion here. It may be doubted whether these statements 
 are based on anything else than fr. 12, which might certainly 
 be interpreted to mean that between the bands of fire there 
 were bands of night with a portion of fire in them. That 
 may be right ; but I think it rather more natural to under- 
 stand the passage as saying that the narrower circles are 
 surrounded by wider circles of night, and that each has its 
 portion of fire rushing in the midst of it. These last words 
 would then be a simple repetition of the statement that the 
 narrower circles are filled with unmixed fire,^ and we should 
 have a fairly exact description of the " wheels " of Anaxi- 
 mander. 
 
 94. " In the middle of those," says Parmenides, " is the The 
 goddess who steers the course of all things." Actios ^° ^^ 
 explains this to mean in the middle of the " mixed bands," 
 while SimpHcius declares that it means in the middle of all 
 the bands, that is to say, in the centre of the world. ^ It is 
 not Hkely that either of them had anything better to go 
 upon than the words of Parmenides himself, and these are 
 ambiguous. Simphcius, as is clear from the language he 
 
 1 On the concentric spheres of Eudoxos, see Heath, pp. 193 sqq. 
 
 2 Such a repetition {Tra\i.v8poiJ.ia) is characteristic of all Greek style, but 
 the repetition at the end of the period generally adds a new touch to the 
 statement at the opening. The new touch is here given in the word 
 terat. I do not press this interpretation, but it seems to me much simpler 
 than that of Diels, who has to take "night" as equivalent to "earth," 
 since he identifies it with the (TTepeSv. 
 
 * Simpl. Phys. p. 34, 14 (R. P. 125 b). 
 
190 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 uses, identified this goddess with the Pythagorean Hestia 
 or central fire, while Theophrastos could not do that, because 
 he knew and stated that Parmenides described the earth as 
 round and in the centre of the world. ^ In this very passage 
 we are told that what is in the middle of all the bands is 
 sohd. The data furnished by Theophrastos, in fact, exclude 
 the identification of the goddess with the central fire alto- 
 gether. We cannot say that what is in the middle of all 
 the bands is solid, and that under it there is again a fiery 
 band. 2 Nor does it seem fitting to relegate a goddess to the 
 middle of a sohd spherical earth. 
 
 We are further told by Actios that this goddess was called 
 Ananke and the " Holder of Lots." ^ We know already 
 that she " steers the course of all things," that is, that she 
 regulates the motions of the celestial bands. Simplicius 
 adds, imfortunately without quoting the actual words, that 
 she sends souls at one time from the fight to the unseen 
 world, at another from the unseen world to the light .^ It 
 would be difficult to describe more exactly what the goddess 
 does in the Myth of Er, and so here once more we seem to 
 be on Pythagorean ground. It is to be noticed further that 
 in fr. 10 we read how Ananke took the heavens and com- 
 
 1 Diog. ix. 21, TrpCoTOS 5' ai/rbi rrjv yrji/ diricprjue acpaipoeidi] Kal iv 
 /A^o-y KeiadaL. Cf. viii. 48 (of Pythagoras), dXXa ij.t]v koL rbv oiipavbv 
 irpQ)Tov ovofida-at. Koaixov Kal t7]v yriv (XTpoyyvKrjv (cf. Plato, Phaed. 97 d), ws 
 dk QedcppaffTos, Uapfievidrfv. This appears to justify us in ascribing the 
 doctrine of a spherical earth to Pythagoras (cf. p. iii). 
 
 2 I do not discuss the interpretation of Trepl 8 irdXtv irvpthh-qs which 
 Diels gave in Parmenides Lehrgedicht, p. 104, and which is adopted in 
 R. P. 162 a, as it is now virtually retracted. In the later editions of his 
 Vorsokratiker (18 A 37) he reads koL t6 fxeaairaTov iracwv (sc. tQiv 0T€<pavQ)v) 
 arepebv, <,v<p' (^> TrdXt*' irvpibSrjs (sc. (XT€<pdvri). That is a fiat contradiction. 
 
 3 R. P, 126, where Fiilleborn's ingenious emendation kXtjSoOxov for 
 KK-qpovxov is tacitly adopted. This is based upon the view that Actios (or 
 Theophrastos) was thinking of the goddess that keeps the keys in the 
 Proem (fr. i, 14). I now think that the KkripoL of tjie Myth of Er give 
 the true explanation. 
 
 * Simpl. Phys. p. 39, 19, koI tAs ^vxds irifxireiv Trork fxkv iK tov ifxcpayovs 
 eli rb deibis {i.e. did^i), voH 3^ dvdTrakiv (f)r)(nv. We should probably 
 connect this with the statement of Diog. ix. 22 (R. P. 127) that men arose 
 from the sun (reading ijXiov with the MSS. for the conjecture tXi/os). 
 
 i 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 191 
 
 pelled them to hold fast the fixed courses of the stars, and 
 that in fr. 12 we are told that she is the beginner of all pairing 
 and birth. Lastly, in fr. 13 we hear that she created Eros 
 first of all the gods. So we shall find that in Empedokles it 
 is an ancient oracle or decree of Ananke that causes the gods 
 to fall and become incarnate in a cycle of births.^ 
 
 We should be more certain of the place this goddess 
 occupies in the universe if we could be sure where Ananke 
 is in the Myth of Er. Without, however, raising that 
 vexed question, we may lay down with some confidence 
 that, according to Theophrastos, she occupied a position 
 midway between the earth and the heavens. Whether we 
 beUeve in the " mixed bands " or not makes no difference in 
 this respect ; for the statement of Actios that she was in the 
 middle of the mixed bands undoubtedly impUes that she 
 was between earth and heaven. Now she is identified with 
 one of the bands in a somewhat confused passage of Cicero,^ 
 and the whole theory of wheels or bands was probably 
 suggested by the Milky Way. It seems to me, therefore, 
 that we must think of the Milky Way as a band intermediate 
 between those of the Sun and the Moon, and this agrees very 
 well with the prominent way in which it is mentioned in 
 fr. II. It is better not to be too positive about the other 
 details, though it is interesting to notice that according to 
 some it was Pythagoras, and according to others Parmenides, 
 who discovered the identity of the evening and morning star.^ 
 
 ^ Empedokles, fr. 115. 
 
 * Cicero, De nat. <i. i. 11, 28 : " Nam Parmenides quidem commenticium 
 quiddam coronae simile efficit {crTecpdvrjP appellat), continente ardore lucis 
 orbem, qui cingat caelum, quem appellat deum." We may connect with 
 this the statement of Aetios, ii. 20, 8, rbv ijXiov Kal ttjv cek-qv-riv iK toO 
 yaXa^iov kvkXov airoKpidrivai. 
 
 ^ Diog. ix. 23, Kol SoKeT {TLap/iei/Ldris) TrpQro^ ir€(l)b}paK^vai rhv avrbv 
 €lvai. "EffTrepop Kai ^i>3(T<p6pov, cos <pT]cn ^a^ojpiuos iv ir^ixtrTi^ 'AirofivrjfMovev- 
 fidruv ol 8k Uvdayopav. Cf. viii. 14 (of Pythagoras), irpQrrbv re "Eawepov 
 Kal ^wa(f>bpov rbv avrbv e'nretv, c&i (firjai HapixevLbrj^. So Diels now 
 reads with all the MSS. (the vulgate oi 8i 0a<rt UapfxeviS-nv is due to Casau- 
 bon). It is not necessary to suppose that Parmenides made this state- 
 ment exphcitly in his poem ; there may have been an unmistakable 
 allusion, as in Empedokles, fr. 129. In that case, we should have a 
 
192 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Besides all this, it is certain that Parmenides went on 
 to describe how the other gods were bom and how they fell, 
 an idea which we know to be Orphic, and which may well 
 have been Pythagorean. We shall come to it again in 
 Empedokles. In Plato's Symposium, Agathon couples 
 Parmenides with Hesiod as a narrator of ancient deeds 
 of violence committed by the gods.^ If Parmenides was 
 expounding the Pythagorean theology, this is just what we 
 should expect ; but it seems hopeless to explain it on any 
 of the other theories which have been advanced on the 
 purpose of the Way of Belief. ^ Such things belong to 
 theological speculation, and not to the beliefs of "the many." 
 Still less can we think it probable that Parmenides made up 
 these stories himself to show what the popular view of the 
 world really impHed if properly formulated. We must ask, 
 I think, that any theory shall account for what was evidently 
 no inconsiderable portion of the poem. 
 Physio- 95- In describing the views of his contemporaries, 
 ^°^* Parmenides was obliged, as we see from the fragments, to 
 say a good deal about physiological matters. Like every- 
 thing else, man was composed of the warm and the cold, 
 and death was caused by the removal of the warm. Some 
 curious views with regard to generation were also stated. 
 In the first place, males came from the right side and females 
 from the left. Women had more of the warm and men of 
 the cold, a view we shall find Empedokles contradicting.^ 
 It is the proportion of the warm and cold in men that deter- 
 
 remarkable confirmation of the view that the A6^a of Parmenides was 
 Pythagorean, If, as Achilles says, the poet Ibykos of Rhegion had 
 anticipated Parmenides in announcing this discovery, that is to be ex- 
 plained by the fact that Rhegion became for a time, as we shall see, the 
 chief seat of the Pythagorean school. 
 
 1 Plato, Symp. 195 c i. It is implied that these TraXata irpdyfiaTa were 
 troWk Koi ^iaia, including iKTo/xai and dea/xoL The ^ Epicurean criticism 
 of this is partially preserved in Philodemos, De pietate, p. 68, Gomperz ; 
 and Cicero, De nat. d. i. 28 [Dox. p. 534 ; R. P. 126 b). 
 
 * For these theories, see § 90. 
 
 « For all this, see R. P. 127 a, with Arist. De part. an. B, 2. 648 a 28 ; 
 De gen. an. A, i. 765 b 19. 
 
 i 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 193 
 
 r 
 
 mines the character of their thought, so that even corpses, 
 from which the warm has been removed, retain a perception 
 of what is cold and dark.^ These fragments of information 
 do not tell us much when taken by themselves ; but they 
 connect themselves in an interesting way with the history 
 of medicine, and point to the fact that one of its leading 
 schools stood in close relation with the Pythagorean Society. 
 Even before the days of Pythagoras, we know that Kroton 
 was famous for its doctors. ^ We also know the name of 
 a very distinguished medical writer who lived at Kroton 
 in the days between Pythagoras and Parmenides, and the 
 few facts we are told about him enable us to regard the 
 physiological views described by Parmenides not as isolated 
 curiosities, but as landmarks by which we can trace the 
 origin, and growth of one of the most influential of medical 
 theories, that which explains health as a balance of 
 opposites. 
 
 96. Aristotle tells us that Alkmaion of Kroton ^ was a Aikmaion 
 young man in the old age of Pythagoras. He does not 
 actually say, as later writers do, that he was a Pythagorean, 
 though he points out that he seems either to have derived 
 his theory of opposites from the Pythagoreans or they theirs 
 from him.^ In any case, he was intimately connected with 
 the society, as is proved by one of the scanty fragments of 
 his book. It began as follows : " Alkmaion of Kroton, son 
 of Peirithous, spoke these words to Brotinos and Leon and 
 Bathyllos. As to things invisible and things mortal, the 
 gods have certainty ; but, so far as men may infer . . ." ^ 
 
 1 Theophr. Be sens. 3, 4 (R. P. 129). * See p. 89, n. 2. 
 
 ' On Alkmaion, see especially Wachtler, De Alcmaeone Crotoniata 
 (Leipzig, 1896). 
 
 * Arist. Met. A, 5. 986 a 27 (R. P. 66). In a 30 Diels reads, with 
 great probability, iyeuero ttjv ifKLKlav <j'eos> eirl yipovn. Uvday Spq.. Cf. Iambi. 
 V. Pyth. 104, where Alkmaion is mentioned among the (xvyxpoviaavTe? Kal 
 fxadrjreOaavTes rip Uvdayopa rrpea^vTri vioi. 
 
 ^ 'AXK/xaitav KporoovirjTrjs rdde fKe^e TieLpidov vlbs BpOTLVip Kal A4ovtl Kal BadvXXcp- 
 Trepl tCjv dcpaviwv, irepl tCjv Ovt^tCHv, aacprjueiav ixkv deol exovri, ds 5k dvdpdnroLS 
 reK/xaipeadai Kal to. i^ijs (fr. I, Diels, Vors. 14 b i). The fact that this is not 
 written in conventional Doric is a strong proof of its genuineness. 
 
 13 
 
194 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The quotation unfortunately ends in this abrupt way, 
 but we learn two things from it. In the first place, 
 Alkmaion possessed that reserve which marks all the 
 best Greek medical writers ; and in the second place, 
 he dedicated his work to the heads of the Pythagorean 
 Society.^ 
 
 Alkmaion's importance really lies in the fact that he is 
 the founder of empirical psychology. ^ He regarded the 
 brain as the common sensorium, a view which Hippokrates 
 and Plato adopted from him, though Empedokles, Aristotle, 
 and the Stoics reverted to the more primitive view that the 
 heart is the central organ of sense. There is no reason to 
 doubt that he made this discovery by anatomical means. 
 We have authority for saying that he practised dissection, 
 and, though the nerves were not yet recognised as such, 
 it was known that there were certain " passages " {iropot) 
 which might be prevented from communicating sensations 
 to the brain by lesions.^ He also distinguished between 
 sensation and understanding, though we have no means of 
 knowing where he drew the line between them. His theories 
 of the special senses are of great interest. We find in him 
 already, what is characteristic of Greek theories of vision 
 as a whole, the attempt to combine the view of vision as 
 a radiation proceeding from the eye with that which attri- 
 butes it to an image reflected in the eye. He knew the 
 importance of air for the sense of hearing, though he 
 called it the void, a thoroughly Pythagorean touch. With 
 regard to the other senses, our information is more 
 
 1 Brotinos (or Brontinos) is variously described as the son-in-law or 
 father-in-law of Pythagoras. Leon is one of the Metapontines in the 
 catalogue of lamblichos (Diels, Vors. 45 a), and Bathyllos is presumably 
 the Poseidoniate Bathylaos also mentioned there. 
 
 2 Everything bearing on the early history of this subject is brought 
 together and discussed in Prof. Beare's Greek Theories of Elementary 
 Cognition, to which I must refer the reader for all details. 
 
 3 Theophr. De sens. 26 (Beare, p. 252, n. i). Our authority for the 
 dissections of Alkmaion is only Chalcidius, but he gets his information on 
 such matters from far older sources. The irbpoi and the inference from 
 lesions are vouched for by Theophrastos. 
 
PARMENIDES OF ELEA 195 
 
 scanty, but sufficient to show that he treated the subject 
 systematically.^ 
 
 His astronomy seems very crude for one who stood in 
 close relations with the Pythagoreans. We are told that he 
 adopted Anaximenes' theory of the sun and Herakleitos's 
 explanation of eclipses. ^ If, however, we were right in 
 holding that the Second Part of the poem of Parmenides 
 represents the view of Pythagoras, we see that he had not 
 gone very far beyond the Milesians in such matters. His 
 theory of the heavenly bodies was still "meteorological." 
 It is all the more remarkable that ^Alkmaion is credited with 
 the view that the planets have an orbital motion in the 
 opposite direction to the diurnal revolution of the heavens. 
 This view, which he may have learnt from Pythagoras, 
 would naturally be suggested by the difficulties we noted 
 in the system of Anaximander.^ It doubtless stood in close 
 connexion with his saying that soul was immortal because 
 it resembled immortal things, and was always in motion hke 
 the heavenly bodies.* He seems, in fact, to be the author 
 of the curious view Plato put into the mouth of the Pytha- 
 gorean Timaios, that the soul has circles in it revolving just 
 as the heavens and the planets do. This too seems to be 
 the explanation of his further statement that man dies 
 because he cannot join the beginning to the end.^ The 
 orbits of the heavenly bodies always come full circle, but 
 the circles in the human head may fail to complete them- 
 selves. 
 
 Alkmaion's theory of health as " isonomy " is at once 
 that which most clearly connects him with earher inquirers 
 
 ^ The details will be found in Beare, pp. ii sqq. (vision), pp. 93 sqq, 
 (hearing), pp. 131 sqq. (smell), pp. 180 sqq. (touch), pp. 160 sqq. (taste). 
 
 2 Aet. ii. 22, 4, TrXarvu elvat top ^\lov ', 29, 3, KaTa\TT]v tov^ aKa(pO€i8ovi 
 crTpo<pr]v Kal ras xepLKXlaeLS {iKXeiireiv ttjv aeKrjvrjv). 
 
 3 Aet. ii. 16, 2, {tQv /nadrjinaTLKCov rives) rods Tr\avf}Ta% tois airXdveaiv 
 airb bvcTfiCbv eir' dvaroXas avTi^epeaOat. rovTip 8^ avvofioXoyei /cai 'AX/c/xaiW. 
 For the difi&culties in Anaximander's system see p. 69 sq. 
 
 * Arist. De an. A, 2. 405 a 30 (R. P. 66 c). 
 
 ° Arist. Probl. 17, 3. 916 a 33, tov% dudpibwovs (prjcrly 'AXKfialuv Sid tovto 
 dirdWvcrdai, 6ti ov 86vavTailTrjp dpx^v Ti^^riXei Trpo(rd\(/ai. 
 
196 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 like Anaximander, and also that which had the greatest 
 influence on the subsequent development of philosophy. 
 He observed, to begin with, that " most things human were 
 two," and by this he meant that man was made up of the 
 hot and the cold, the moist and the dry, and the rest of the 
 opposites.i Disease was just the " monarchy " of any one 
 of these — the same thing that Anaximander had called 
 " injustice " — ^while health was the establishment in the 
 body of a free government with equal laws.^ This was the 
 leading doctrine of the SiciHan school of medicine, and we 
 shall have to consider in the sequel its influence on the 
 development of Pythagoreanism. Taken along with the 
 theory of " pores," it is of the greatest importance for later 
 science. 
 
 1 Arist. Met. A, 5. 986 a 27 (R. P. 66). 
 
 ^ Aet. V. 30, I, 'A\K/j.ai(i}v ttjs fxkv vyteias elvai (Tvv€ktik7)v ttjv l(Tovofxlav 
 Twv dvydfxewv, vypov, ^rjpoO, \pvxpov, depfioO, wiKpov, yXvK^os, Kal tCiv Xonrwp, 
 TT)v 5' iv avTols fiouapxidv vbaov iroLriTLK-qv • (pdopovoibif yap cKaripov fiovapx^o-v- 
 
CHAPTER V 
 
 EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 
 
 97. The belief that all things are one was common to the Pluralism, 
 early lonians ; but now Parmenides has shown that, if this 
 one thing really is, we must give up the idea that it can take 
 different forms. iThe senses, which present to us a world 
 of change and multiplicity, are deceitful. There seemed to 
 be no escape from his arguments, and so we find that from 
 this time onwards all the thinkers in whose hands philosophy 
 made progress abandoned the monistic hypothesis. Those 
 who still held by it adopted a critical attitude, and confined 
 themselves to a defence of the theory of Parmenides against 
 the new views. Others taught the doctrine of Herakleitos 
 in an exaggerated form ; some continued to expound the 
 systems of the early Milesians ; but the leading men are all 
 pluraUsts. The corporealist hypothesis had proved unable 
 to bear the weight of a monistic structure. 
 
 98. Empedokles was a citizen of Akragas in Sicily. He Date of 
 was the only native citizen of a Dorian state who plays an dokfel 
 important part in the history of philosophy. ^ His father's 
 name, according to the best accounts, was Meton.^ His 
 grandfather, also called Empedokles, had won a victory in 
 the horse-race at Olympia in 01. LXXI. (496-95 b.c.),^ and 
 
 ^ See, however, Introd. § II (p. 3). 
 
 2 Aet. i. 3, 20 (R. P. 164), ApoUodoros ap. Diog. viii. 52 (R. P. 162). 
 The details of the life of Empedokles are discussed, with a careful criticism 
 of the sources, by Bidez, La Biographie d'Empedocle (Gand, 1894). 
 
 3 p'or this we have the authority of ApoUodoros (Diog. viii. 51, 52; 
 R. P. 162), who follows the Olympic Victors of Eratosthenes, who followed 
 Aristotle. Herakleides, in his Jlepl voawv (see below, p. 200, n. 5), spoke of 
 
 197 
 
igS 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Empe- 
 dokles 
 as a 
 politician. 
 
 ApoUodoros fixed the floruit of Empedokles himself in 01. 
 LXXXIV. I (444-43 B.C.). That is the date of the foundation 
 of Thourioi ; and it appears from the quotation in Diogenes 
 that the fifth - century biographer, Glaukos of Rhegion/ 
 said Empedokles visited the new city shortly after its 
 foundation. But we are not bound to beUeve that he was 
 just forty years old at the time. That is the usual assump- 
 tion of ApoUodoros ; but there are reasons for thinking that 
 his date is considerably too late.^ It is more hkely that 
 Empedokles did not go to Thourioi till after his banishment 
 from Akragas, and he may well have been more than forty 
 years old when that happened. All, therefore, we can be said 
 to know is, that his grandfather was still aUve in 496 B.C. ; 
 that he himself was active at Akragas after 472, the date of 
 Theron's death ; and that he died later than 444. 
 
 99. Empedokles certainly played an important part in 
 the pohtical events which followed the death of Theron. 
 The Sicihan historian Timaios seems to have treated these 
 fully, and tells some stories which are obviously genuine 
 traditions picked up about a hundred and fifty years after- 
 
 the elder Empedokles as a " breeder of horses " (R. P. 162 a) ; and Timaios 
 mentioned him in his Fifteenth Book. Satyros confused him with his 
 grandson. 
 
 1 Glaukos wrote Ilept tCov dp%afaji' iroL-qTQv koI /xovo-lkCov, and is said to 
 have been contemporary with Demokritos (Diog. ix. 38). ApoUodoros adds 
 (R. P. 162) that, according to Aristotle and Herakleides, Empedokles died 
 at the age of sixty. It is to be observed, however, that the words ere 8' 
 'RpaK\ei5T]s are Sturz's conjecture, the MSS. having ctl d' 'Hpd/cXetroi/, and 
 Diogenes certainly said (ix. 3) that Herakleitos lived sixty years. On the 
 other hand, if the statement of Aristotle comes from the TLepl ttoltjtQu, it is 
 
 The 
 
 was one of the chief sources for the biography of Empedokles 
 names are often confused. 
 
 2 See Diels, " Empedokles und Gorgias," 2 {Berl. Sitzb., 1884). Theo- 
 phrastos said {Dox. p. 477, 17) that Empedokles was born " not long after 
 Anaxagoras," i.e. not long after 500 B.C. (see below, J 120). As he was 
 certainly later than Parmenides, this is a fresh ground for following Plato 
 in making Parmenides some fifteen years older than ApoUodoros does 
 (see above, § 84). In general it should be noted that the epoch of Thourioi 
 has misled ApoUodoros in many cases. Almost every one who had any- 
 thing to do with Thourioi [e.g. Herodotos, Protagoras) is said to have 
 been born in 484 b.c. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 199 
 
 wards. Like all popular traditions, however, they are a 
 little confused. The picturesque incidents are remembered, 
 but the essential parts of the story are dropped. Still, we 
 may be thankful that the " collector of old wives' tales," ^ as 
 his critics called him, has enabled us to measure the historical 
 importance of Empedokles for ourselves by showing us how 
 he was pictured by the great-grandchildren of his contem- 
 poraries. ^ All the tales are intended to show the strength 
 of his democratic convictions, and we are told, in particular, 
 that he broke up the assembly of the Thousand — perhaps 
 some oligarchical association or club.^ It may have been for 
 this that he was offered the kingship, which Aristotle tells us 
 he refused.* At any rate, we see that Empedokles was the 
 great democratic leader at Akragas in those days, though we 
 have no clear knowledge of what he did. 
 
 100. But there is another side to his public character Empe- 
 which Timaios found it hard to reconcile with his political ^s a^^ 
 views. He claimed to be a god, and to receive the homage religious 
 of his fellow -citizens in that capacity. The truth is, 
 Empedokles was not a mere statesman ; he had a good deal 
 of the " medicine-man " about him. According to Satyros,^ 
 
 1 He is called ypaoavWiKxpia in Souidas, s.v. 
 
 2 For instance Timaios {ap. Diog. viii. 64) said that once he was 
 invited to sup with one of the magistrates. Supper was well advanced, 
 but no wine was brought in. The rest of the company said nothing, 
 but Empedokles was indignant, and insisted on its being served. The 
 host, however, said he was waiting for the Sergeant of the Council. When 
 that official arrived, he was appointed ruler of the feast. The host, of 
 course, appointed him. Thereupon he began to give signs of an incipient 
 tyranny. He ordered the company either to drink or have the wine 
 poured over their heads. Empedokles said nothing, but next day he 
 brought both of them before the court and had them put to death — 
 both the man who asked him to supper and the ruler of the feast ! The 
 story reminds us of an accusation of incivisme under the Terror. 
 
 3 Diog. viii. 66, iiarepoif 8' 6 'EiuLire8oK\i]s Kal to tQv x'^^''"' AOpoifffia 
 Kar^Xvae (Tvv€<rTu)s iirl ^ttj Tpia.- The word dLdpoia/xa hardly suggests a 
 legal council, and ffwiaracrOaL suggests a conspiracy. 
 
 4 Diog. viii. 63. Aristotle probably mentioned this in his Sophist. 
 Cf. Diog. viii. 57. 
 
 6 Diog. viii. 59 (R. P. 162). Satyros probably followed Alkidamas. 
 Diels suggests {Emp. u. Gorg. p. 358) that the c()v<xiKbs of Alkidamas was 
 a dialogue in which Gorgias was the chief speaker. 
 
200 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Gorgias affirmed that he had been present when his 
 master was performing sorceries. We can see what this 
 means from the fragments of the Purifications. Empe- 
 dokles was a preacher of the new reUgion which sought 
 to secure release from the " wheel of birth " by purity 
 and abstinence. Orphicism seems to have been strong 
 at Akragas in the days of Theron, and there are even 
 some verbal coincidences between the poems of Empedokles 
 and the Orphicising Odes which Pindar addressed to that 
 prince. 1 \ On the other hand, there is no reason to doubt 
 the statement of Ammonios that fr. 134 refers to Apollo ; ^ 
 and, if that is so, it points to his having been an adherent 
 of the Ionic form of the mystic doctrine, as we have seen 
 (§ 39) Pythagoras was. Further, Timaios already knew 
 the story that Empedokles had been expelled from the 
 Pythagorean Order for " steaHng discourses," ^ and it is 
 probable on the whole that fr. 129 refers to Pythagoras.* 
 It seems most Hkely, then, that Empedokles preached a 
 form of Pythagoreanism which was not considered orthodox 
 by the heads of the Society. The actual marvels related 
 of him seem to be mere developments of hints in his 
 poems.^ 
 
 loi. Aristotle said that Empedokles was the inventor of 
 Rhetoric Rhctoric ; ^ and Galen made him the founder of the Italian 
 medicine, school of Medicine, which he puts on a level with those of 
 
 1 See Bidez, p. 115, n. i. 
 
 2 See below, note in loc. 
 
 3 Diog. viii. 54 (R. P. 162). * See below, note in loc. 
 5 Timaios told, for instance {ap. Diog. viii. 60), how he weakened the] 
 
 force of the etesian winds by hanging bags of asses' skins on the trees] 
 to catch them. In fr. iii he says that knowledge of science as taught] 
 by him will enable his disciples to control the winds. We are also tolc 
 how he brought back to life a woman who had been breathless anc 
 pulseless for thirty days. In fr. 11 1 he tells Pausanias that his teaching] 
 will enable him to bring the dead back from Hades.' The story of the] 
 dirvovs was given at length in the Hepl vbawv of Herakleides of Pontos» 
 and Diogenes says that it was related to Pausanias by Empedokles. Thai 
 gives us a hint of the way in which these stories were worked up. Cf. 
 the very similar anecdotes about Herakleitos, p. 131, w. 4. 
 « Diog. viii. 57 (R. P. 162 g). 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 201 
 
 Kos and Knidos.^ Both these statements must be considered 
 in connexion with his poHtical and scientific activity. It is 
 probable that Gorgias was his disciple, and also that the 
 speeches, of which he must have made many, were marked 
 by that euphuism which Gorgias introduced to Athens at a 
 later date, and which gave rise to the idea of an artistic 
 prose. 2 His influence on the development of medicine 
 was, however, far more important, as it affected not only 
 medicine itself, but, through it, the whole tendency of 
 scientific thinking. It has been said that Empedokles 
 had no successors,^ and the remark is true if we confine 
 ourselves strictly to philosophy ; but the medical school he 
 founded was still hving in the days of Plato, and had con- 
 siderable influence on him, and still more on Aristotle.* Its 
 fundamental doctrine was the identification of the four 
 elements with the hot and the cold, the moist and the dry. 
 It also held that we breathe through all the pores of the 
 body, and that the act of respiration is closely connected 
 with the motion of the blood. The heart, not the brain, 
 was regarded as the organ of consciousness. ^ A more 
 
 1 Galen, Meth. Med. i. i, ijpi^ov 5' airois (the schools of Kos and Knidos) 
 . . . Kal ol iK TTJs 'IraXias iarpoi, ^lXl(ttLci}v re Kal 'EfiiredoKXTJs Kal UavaauLai 
 Kal ol TovTUP eraipoi. Philistion was the contemporary and friend of Plato ; 
 Pausanias is the disciple to whom Empedokles addressed his poem. 
 
 2 See Diels, " Empedokles und Gorgias " {Berl. SiUb., 1884, pp. 
 343 sqq.). The oldest authority for saying that Gorgias was a disciple 
 of Empedokles is Satyros ap. Diog. viii. 58 (R. P. 162) ; but he seems to 
 have derived his information from Alkidamas, who was the disciple of 
 Gk)rgias himself. In Plato's Meno (76 c 4-8) the Empedoklean theory 
 of effluvia and pores is ascribed to Gorgias. 
 
 3 Diels {Berl. Sitzb., 1884, p. 343). 
 
 * See M. Wellmann, Fragmentsammlung der griechischen Artzte, vol. 
 i. (Berlin, 1901). According to Wellmann, both Plato (in the Timaeus) 
 and Diokles of Karystos depend upon Philistion. It is impossible to 
 understand the history of philosophy from this point onwards without 
 keeping the history of medicine constantly in view. 
 
 6 For the four elements, cf. Anon. Lond. xx. 25 (Menon's lairika), 
 ^iXccTLbJv 5' oterai 4k d' I'SecDv avvecTTdvat ijfMas, tout' ^(Xtiv e'/c 5' ffToix^luiV 
 irvpos, d^poi, CSaros, 7^s. elvai de Kal €Kd<jTOV dvvd/xeis, tov /jl^v Trvpbs rb 
 depfxbv, TOV 5^ d^pos Tb \pvxpbv, tov d^ vdaros Tb vypov, tt]S Sk yrjs t6 ^rjpbv. 
 For the theory of respiration, see Wellmann, pp. 82 sqq. ; and for the 
 heart as the seat of consciousness, ih. pp. 15 sqq. 
 
202 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Relation 
 to pre- 
 decessors. 
 
 Death. 
 
 external characteristic of the medicine taught by the fol- 
 lowers of Empedokles is that they still clung to ideas of 
 a magical nature. A protest against this by a member of 
 the Koan school has been preserved. He refers to them as 
 " magicians and purifiers and charlatans and quacks, who 
 profess to be very reUgious." ^ 
 
 102. In the biography of Empedokles, we hear nothing 
 of his theory of nature. The only hints we get are some 
 statements about his teachers. Alkidamas, who had good 
 opportunities of knowing, made him a fellow-student of 
 Zeno under Parmenides. Theophrastos too made him a 
 follower and imitator of Parmenides. But the further 
 statement that he had " heard " Pythagoras cannot be 
 right. No doubt Alkidamas said " Pythagoreans." 2 
 
 Some writers hold that certain parts of the system of 
 Empedokles, in particular the theory of pores and effluvia 
 (§ 118), were due to the influence of Leukippos.^ We know, 
 however, that Alkmaion (§ 96) spoke of " pores " in con- 
 nexion with sensation, and it was more probably from him 
 that Empedokles got the theory. Moreover, this is more 
 in accordance with the history of certain other physiological 
 views which are common to Alkmaion and the later Ionian 
 philosophers. We can generally see that those reached 
 Ionia through the medical school which Empedokles founded.^ 
 
 103. We are told that Empedokles leapt into the crater 
 of Etna that he might be deemed a god. This appears to 
 be a maUcious version ^ of a tale set on foot by his adherents 
 
 '^ Hippokr. Uepl ieprjs vbaov, c l, fxayoi re 
 aka^bves. The whole passage should be read. 
 
 Kol Kaddprac Kal dyijpTaL ko 
 Cf. Wellmann, p. 29 n. 
 
 2 Diog. viii. 54-56 (R. P. 162). 
 
 3 Diels, Verhandl. d. 35 Philologenversamml. pp. 104 sqq., Zeller, p. 767^ 
 It would be fatal to the main thesis of the next few chapters if it could b^ 
 proved that Empedokles was influenced by Leukippos. I hope to sho-st 
 that Leukippos was influenced by the later Pythagorean doctrine (Chad 
 IX. § 171), which was in turn affected by Empedokles (Chap. VII. § 147)11 
 
 * For irhpoL in Alkmaion, cf. Arist. De gen. an. B, 6. 744 a 8 ; Theophr] 
 De sens. 26; and for the way in which his embryological and other vi 
 were transmitted through Empedokles to the Ionian physicists, 
 Fredrich, Hippokratische Untersuchungen, pp. 126 sqq. 
 
 ^ R. P. 162 h. The story is always told with a hostile purpose. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 203 
 
 that he had been snatched up to heaven in the night. ^ 
 Both stories would easily get accepted ; for there was no 
 local tradition. Empedokles did not die in Sicily, but in 
 the Peloponnese, or, perhaps, at Thourioi. It is not at all 
 unUkely that he visited Athens. 2 Plato represents Sokrates 
 as famiUar with his views in early life, and the elder Kritias 
 adopted one of his characteristic theories.^ 
 
 104. Empedokles was the second philosopher to expound writings, 
 his system in verse, if we leave the satirist Xenophanes out 
 
 of account. He was also the last among the Greeks ; for 
 the forged Pythagorean poems may be neglected. Lucretius 
 imitates Empedokles in this, just as Empedokles imitated 
 Parmenides. Of course, the poetical imagery creates a 
 difficulty for the interpreter ; but it cannot be said that it is 
 harder to extract the philosophical kernel from the verses 
 of Empedokles than from the prose of Herakleitos. 
 
 105. We have more abundant remains of Empedokles The 
 than of any other early Greek philosopher. If we may 
 trust our manuscripts of Diogenes and of Souidas, the 
 librarians of Alexandria estimated the Poem on Nature and 
 the Purifications together as 5000 verses, of which about 
 
 1 R. p. ih. This was the story told by Herakleides of Pontos, at the 
 end of his romance about the Slttvovs. 
 
 2 Timaios refuted the common stories at some length (Diog. viii. 
 71 sqq. ; R. P. ih.). He was quite positive that Empedokles never returned 
 to Sicily after he went to Olympia to have his poem recited to the 
 Hellenes. The plan for the colonisation of Thourioi would, of course, be 
 discussed at Olympia, and we know that Greeks from the Peloponnese 
 and elsewhere joined it. He may very well have gone to Athens in 
 connexion with this. 
 
 3 See my edition of the Phaedo, 96 b 4 w., and, for Kritias, Arist. 
 De anima, 405 b 6. This is the Kritias who appears in Plato's Timaeus, 
 and he is certainly not the Kritias who was one of the Thirty, but his 
 grandfather. The Kritias of the Timaeus is a very old man, who re- 
 members the events of his boyhood quite well, but forgets what happened 
 the other day {Tim. 26 b). He also tells us that the poems of Solon were 
 a novelty when he was a boy {ib. 21 b). It is hard to understand how 
 he was ever supposed to be the oligarch, though Diels, Wilamowitz, and 
 E. Meyer seem to have felt no difficulty in the identification. It is clear 
 too that it must have been the grandfather who exchanged poetical com- 
 pliments with Anakreon (Diels, Vors.^ ii. p. 81 B i). Kritias of the Thirty 
 did not live to be an old man. 
 
204 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 2000 belonged to the former work.^ Diels gives about 
 350 verses and parts of verses from the cosmological poem, 
 or not a fifth of the whole. It is important to remember 
 that, even in this favourable instance, so much has been 
 lost. The other poems ascribed to Empedokles by the 
 Alexandrian scholars were probably not his.^ 
 
 I give the remains as they are arranged by Diels : 
 
 (I) 
 
 And do thou give ear, Pausanias, son of Anchitos the wise ! 
 
 For straitened are the powers that are spread over their 
 bodily parts, and many are the woes that burst in on them and 
 blunt the edge of their careful thoughts ! They behold but a 
 brief span of a life that is no life,^ and, doomed to swift death, 
 are borne up and fly off like smoke. Each is convinced of that 
 5 alone which he had dianced upon as he is hurried every way, 
 and idly boasts he has found the whole. So hardly can these 
 things be seen by the eyes or heard by the ears of men, so hardly 
 grasped by their mind ! Howbeit, thou, since thou hast found 
 thy way hither, shalt learn no more than mortal mind hath 
 power. R. P. 163. 
 
 (3) 
 
 ... to keep within thy dumb heart. 
 
 1 Diog. viii. 77 (R. P. 162) ; Souidas s.v. 'E/uLTredoKXijs- Kal iypaipe 5i' 
 eirdv Hepl ^tjo-ecos rdv 6vto3v ^L^Xia j3\ Kal ^cttlv ^rrr] u)5 SttrxtXta- It 
 hardly seems likely, however, that the KadapfioL extended to 3000 verses, 
 so Diels proposes to read irdvTa rpiaxl-Xta for Trevra/ctcrx^Xta, in Diogenes. 
 See Diels, " tjber die Gedichte des Empedokles " {Berl. Sitzh., 1898, pp. 
 396 sqq.). 
 
 2 Hieronymos of Rhodes declared (Diog. viii. 58) that he had met with 
 forty-three tragedies by Empedokles ; but see Stein, pp. 5 sqq. The poeni 
 on the Persian Wars, which he also refers to (Diog. viii. 57), seems tO 
 have arisen from a corruption in the text of Arist. Prohl. 929 b 16, wher^ 
 Bekker reads ev roh UepaLKois. The same passage, however, is said 
 occur ip Toh (pvcriKois, in Meteor. A> 4. 382 a i, though there too E hz 
 JlepaLKoh. 
 
 3 The MSS. of Sextus have ^ujrjaL ^iov. Diels reads ^urjs Idiov. I stij 
 prefer Scaliger's j^urjs &^iov. Cf. fr. 15, to 5t) §Lotov KoKiovai. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 205 
 
 (4) 
 
 But, O ye gods, turn aside from my tongue the madness of 
 those men. Hallow my Hps and make a pure stream flow from 
 them ! And thee, much-wooed, white-armed Virgin Muse, do 
 I beseech that I may hear what is lawful for the children of a 
 day ! Speed me on my way from the abode of Holiness and drive 5 
 my ^\illing car ! Thee shall no garlands of glory and honour at 
 the hands of mortals constrain to Uft them from the ground, on 
 condition of speaking in thy pride beyond that which is lawful 
 and right, and so to gain a seat upon the heights of wisdom. 
 
 Go to now, consider with all thy powers in what way each 
 thing is clear. Hold not thy sight in greater credit as compared lo 
 with thy hearing, nor value thy resounding ear above the clear 
 instructions of thy tongue ; ^ and do not withhold thy confidence 
 in any of thy other bodily parts by which there is an opening for 
 understanding, but consider everything in the way it is clear. 
 R. P. 163. 
 
 (5) 
 
 But it is all too much the way of low minds to disbelieve 
 their betters. Dp thou learn as the sure testimonies of my Muse 
 bid thee, when my words have been divided ^ in thy heart. 
 
 (6) 
 Hear first the four roots of all things : shining Zeus, life- 
 bringing Hera, Aidoneus and Nestis whose tear-drops are a 
 well-spring to mortals. R. P. 164.^ 
 
 (7) 
 
 . . . uncreated. 
 
 (8) 
 
 And I shall tell thee another thing. There is no substance * of 
 
 1 The sense of taste, not speech. 
 
 2 Clement's reading diaT/xTjeipros may perhaps stand if we take \6yoLo 
 as " discourse," " argument " (cf. diaipeiv). Diels conjectures 8ia(rcrr]0^vTos 
 and renders " when their speech has penetrated the sieve of thy mind." 
 
 3 The four " elements " are introduced under mythological names, for 
 which see below, p. 229, n. 2. 
 
 4 Plutarch {Adv. Col. 11 12 a) says that ^vaLs here means "birth," as is 
 shown b}'- its opposition to death, and all interpreters (including myself) 
 have hitherto followed him. On the other hand, the fragment clearly 
 deals with durjTd, and Empedokles cannot have said that there was no 
 death of mortal things. The dvrjrd are just perishable combinations of 
 
2o6 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 any of all the things that perish, nor any cessation for them of 
 baneful death. They are only a mingUng and interchange of 
 what has been mingled. Substance is but a name given to these 
 things by men. R. P. 165. 
 
 (9) 
 
 But they (hold ?) that when Light and Air (chance ?) to have 
 been mingled in the fashion of a man, or in the fashion of the 
 race of wild beasts or of plants or birds, that that is to be born, 
 and when these things have been separated once more, they call 
 it (wrongly ?) woeful death. I follow the custom and call it 
 so myself.^ 
 
 (10) 
 
 Avenging death. 
 
 the four elements (cf. fr. 35, 11), and the point is that they are constantly 
 coming into being and passing away. It is, therefore, impossible, as 
 pointed out by Prof. Lovejoy {Philosophical Review, xviii. 371 sqq.), to take 
 davdroLO reXevri^ as equivalent to Odvaros here, and it may equally well mean 
 "end of death." Now Aristotle, in a passage where he is carefully dis- 
 tinguishing the various senses of <p6(ns {Met. A, 4. 1015 a i), quotes this very 
 verse as an illustration of the meaning ^ tQv Byrcop ova-la (see further in 
 the Appendix) . I understand the words iirt roTaS' as equivalent to iTrl rots 
 Ov-qToh, and I take the meaning of the fragment to be that temporary 
 compounds or combinations like flesh, bone, etc., have no (f>v(ns of their 
 own. Only the four " immortal " elements have a 0i5(rts which does not 
 pass away. This interpretation is confirmed by the way Diogenes of 
 ApoUonia speaks in denying the ultimate reality of the "elements." He 
 says (fr. 2) el toijtuv tl ^v ^repov rod er^pov, '^repov di' t^ Idlq. (pvaei, i.e. he says 
 the elements are dvyyrd. 
 
 1 I understand this fragment to deal with the " elements," of which 
 0a)s and aidr^p (Fire and Air) are taken as examples. These are not 
 subject to birth and death, like the dv7]Td of fr. 8, and the application of 
 the terms to them is as much a matter of convention as the application 
 of the term 0i;<rts to the perishable combinations which are subject to 
 birth and death. The text is corrupt in Plutarch, and has two or three 
 lacunae, but the usual reconstructions depart too far from the tradition. 
 I suggest the following, which has at least the merit of not requiring the 
 alteration of a single letter : 
 
 06 5', 6're jxkv Kara (pQra fiiyev cpQis aWepi K^K^opa-gy^ 
 
 ^ Kard drjpQv dyporepuv yivos 7j Kara ddfivwv 
 
 rjk KOLT olwvCbVy t6t€ fikv rb v<.4/iovaO> yev^ffdai- 
 
 e5re 5' diroKpivdCJaL rdd' ad, dvadalfiova irbrfiov 
 
 Xi 64/ji.is <oi)> KoKeovai, vo/xcp 5' eiricf)r}ix(. Kal avrSs. 
 
 I understand rdde in the fourth verse as referring to the " elements " 
 
 {e.g. Fire and Air), which cannot properly be said to be born or to die 
 
 as their combinations do. I take it that Fire and Air are specially 
 
 mentioned because the life of animate creatures depends on them. The 
 
 earth and water would never of themselves produce a living being. 
 
 Jl 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 207 
 
 (II, 12) 
 
 Fools ! — for they have no far-reaching thoughts — who deem 
 that what before was not comes into being, br that aught can 
 perish and be utterly destroyed. For it cannot be that aught 
 can arise from what in no way is, and it is impossible and unheard 
 of that what is should perish ; for it will always be, wherever 
 one may keep putting it. R. P. 165 a. 
 
 (13) 
 
 And in the All there is naught empty and naught too fuU. 
 
 (14) 
 In the All there is naught empty. Whence, then, could 
 aught come to increase it ? 
 
 (15) 
 
 A man who is wise in such matters would never surmise in 
 his heart that as long as mortals Hve what they call their Ufe, so 
 long they are, and suffer good and ill ; while before they were 
 formed and after they have been dissolved they are just nothing 
 at all. R. P. 165 a. 
 
 (16) 
 
 For even as they (Strife and Love) were aforetime, so too 
 they shall be ; nor ever, methinks, will boundless time be 
 emptied of that pair. R. P. 166 c. 
 
 (17) 
 
 I shall tell thee a twofold tale. At one time it grew to be 
 one only out of many ; at another, it divided up to be many 
 instead of one. There is a double becoming of perishable things 
 and a double passing away. The coming together of all things 
 brings one generation into being and destroys it ; the other grows 
 up and is scattered as things become divided. And these things 
 never cease continually changing places, at one time all uniting 
 in one through Love, at another each borne in different directions 
 by the repulsion of Strife. Thus, as far as it is their nature to 
 grow into one out of many, and to become many once more 
 when the one is parted asunder, so far they come into being and 
 their life abides not. But, inasmuch as they never cease changing 
 
2o8 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 their places continually, so far they are ever immovable as they 
 
 go round the circle of existence. 
 
 ^. ....... . 
 
 w. But come, hearken to my words, for it is learning that 
 
 15 increaseth wisdom. As I said before, when I declared the heads 
 of my discourse, I shall tell thee a twofold tale. At one time it 
 grew together to be one only out of many, at another it parted 
 asunder so as to be many instead of one ; — Fire and Water and 
 Earth and the mighty height of Air ; dread Strife, too, apart 
 
 20 from these, of equal weight to each, and Love in their midst, 
 equal in length and breadth. Her do thou contemplate with thy 
 mind, nor sit with dazed eyes. . It is she that is known as being 
 implanted in the frame of mortals. It is she that makes them 
 have thoughts of love and work the works of peace. They call 
 
 25 her by the names of Joy and Aphrodite. Her has no mortal yet 
 marked moving round among them,i but do thou attend to the 
 undeceitful ordering of my discourse. 
 
 For all these are equal and alike in age, yet each has a different 
 prerogative and its own peculiar nature, but they gain the upper 
 
 30 hand in turn when the time comes round. And nothing comes 
 into being besides these, nor do they pass away ; for, if they had 
 been passing away continually, they would not be now^ and what 
 could increase this All and whence could it come ? How, too, 
 could it perish, since no place is empty of these things B There 
 
 35 are these alone ; but, running through one another, they become 
 now this, now that,^ and Uke things evermore. R. P. 166. 
 
 (18) 
 
 Love. ^ 
 
 (19) 
 
 CHnging Love. 
 
 (20) 
 
 This (the contest of Love and Strife) is manifest in the mass 
 
 of mortal limbs. At one time all the Hmbs that are the body's 
 
 portion are brought together by Love in blooming life's kigh 
 
 5 season ; at another, severed by cruel Strife, they wander each 
 
 alone by the breakers of Hfe's sea. It is the same with plants 
 
 1 Reading /Ltera roiaiv. I still think, however, that Knatz's palaeo- 
 graphically admirable conjuncture fiera deolaiv {i.e. among the elements) 
 deserves consideration. * Keeping dWore with Diels. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 209 
 
 and the fish that make their homes in the waters, with the beasts 
 that have their lairs on the hills and the seabirds that sail on 
 wings. R. P. 173 d. 
 
 (21) 
 
 Come now, look at the things that bear witness to my earlier 
 discourse, if so be that there was any shortcoming as to their 
 form in the earlier Hst. Behold the sun, everywhere bright and 
 warm, and all the immortal things that are bathed in heat and 
 bright radiance.^ Behold the rain, everywhere dark and cold ; 5 
 and from the earth issue forth things close-pressed and soUd. 
 When they are in strife all these are different in form and 
 separated ; but they come together in love, and are desired by 
 one another. 
 
 For out of these have sprung all things that were and are 
 and shall be — trees and men and women, beasts and birds and ^o 
 the fishes that dwell in the waters, yea, and the gods that live 
 long Uves and are exalted in honour. R. P. 166 i. 
 
 For there are these alone ; but, running through one another, 
 they take different shapes — so much does mixture change them. 
 R. P. 166 g. 
 
 (22) 
 
 For all of these^sun, earth, sky, and sea — are at one with 
 all their parts that are cast far and wide from them in mortal 
 things. And even so all things that are more adapted for 
 mixture are Uke to one another and united in love by Aphrodite. 5 
 Those things, again, that differ most in origin, mixture and the 
 forms imprinted on each, are most hostile, being altogether 
 unaccustomed to unite and very sorry by the bidding of Strife, 
 since it hath wrought their birth. 
 
 (23) 
 
 Just as when painters are elaborating temple-offerings, men 
 
 whom wisdom hath well taught their art, — they, when they 
 
 have taken pigments of many colours with their hands, mix 
 
 them in due proportion, more of some and less of others, and 
 
 1 Reading Afx^pora 5' 6(t<t tdei with Diels. For the word Uos, cf. frs. 
 62, 5 ; 73, 2. The reference is to the moon, etc., which are made of 
 soHdified Air, and receive their Hght from the fiery hemisphere. See 
 below, § 113. 
 
 14 
 
210 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 5 from them produce shapes like unto all things, making trees and 
 men and women, beasts and birds and fishes that dwell in the 
 waters, yea, and gods, that live long Uves, and are exalted in 
 honour,— so let not the error prevail over thy mind,^ that there 
 is any other source of all the perishable creatures that appear in 
 
 10 countless numbers. Know this for sure, for thou hast heard the 
 tale from a goddess.^ 
 
 (24) 
 
 Stepping from summit to summit, not to travel only one 
 path of words to the end. . . . 
 
 (25) 
 
 What is right may well be said even twice. 
 
 (26) 
 
 For they prevail in turn as the circle comes round, and pass 
 into one another, and grow great in their appointed turn. R. P. 
 l66c. 
 
 There are these alone ; but, running through one another, 
 they become men and the tribes of beasts. At one time they 
 5 are all brought together into one order by Love ; at another, 
 they are carried each in different directions by the repulsion of 
 Strife, till they grow once more into one and are wholly subdued. 
 Thus in so far as they are wont to grow into one out of many, 
 10 and again divided become more than one, so far they come 
 into being and their Ufe is not lasting ; but in so far as 
 they never cease changing continually, so far are they ever- 
 more, immovable in the circle. 
 
 (27) 
 
 There (in the sphere) are distinguished neither the swift limbs 
 of the sun, no, nor the shaggy earth in its might, nor the sea, 
 — so fast was the god bound in the close covering of Harmony, 
 spherical and round, rejoicing in his circular solitude.^ R. P. 167. 
 
 1 Reading with Blass (Jahrb. f. kl. Phil., 1883, p. 19) and Diels : 
 
 ovTii) /J.7) <r' diraTT} (ppha KatvijTuj kt\. 
 Cf . Hesychios : kulvilitu • vlk6.tw. This is practically what the MSS. of 
 Simplicius give, and Hesychios has many Empedoklean glosses. 
 
 2 The " goddess " is, of course, the Muse, Cf. fr. 5. 
 
 » The word ixovl-y, if it is right, cannot mean " rest," but only solitude. 
 There is no reason for altering irepLrjyii, though Simplicius has Trepiyrjeet. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 211 
 
 (27 a) 
 There is no discord and no unseemly strife in his Hmbs. / 
 
 (28) 
 
 But he was equal on every side and quite without end, 
 spherical and round, rejoicing in his circular soUtude. 
 
 (29) 
 
 Two branches do not spring from his back, he has no feet, no 
 swift knees, no fruitful parts ; but he was spherical and equal 
 on every side. 
 
 (30, 31) 
 But when Strife was grown great in the limbs of the god and 
 sprang forth to claim his prerogatives, in the fulness of the 
 alternate time set for them by the mighty oath, ... for all 
 the Umbs of the god in turn quaked. R. P.' 167. 
 
 (32) 
 
 The joint binds two things. 
 
 (33) 
 
 Even as when fig juice rivets and binds white milk. . . . 
 
 (34) 
 Cementing ^ meal with water. . . . 
 
 (35, 36) . 
 But now I shall retrace my steps over the paths of song that 
 I have travelled before, drawing from my saying a new sa57ing. 
 When Strife was fallen to the lowest depth of the vortex, and Love 
 had reached to the centre of the whirl, in it do all things come 
 together so as to be one only ; not all at once, but coming together 5 
 at their will each from different quarters ; and, as they mingled, 
 strife began to pass out to the furthest limit. Yet many 
 things remained unmixed, alternating with the things that were 
 
 1 The masculine KoWriaas shows that the subject cannot have been 
 <i>iX6r775 ; and Karsten was doubtless right in believing that Empedokles 
 introduced the simile of a baker here. It is in his manner to take illus- 
 trations from human arts. 
 
212 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 being mixed, namely, all that Strife not fallen yet retained ; for 
 
 lo it had not yet altogether retired perfectly from them to the 
 
 . outermost boundaries of the circle. Some of it still remained 
 
 within, and some had passed out from the limbs of the All. But 
 
 in proportion as it kept rushing out, a soft, immortal stream of 
 
 blameless Love kept running in, and straightway those things 
 
 became mortal which had been immortal before, those things 
 
 15 were mixed that had before been unmixed, each changing its 
 
 path. And, as they mingled, countless tribes of mortal creatures 
 
 were scattered abroad endowed with all manner of forms, a 
 
 wonder to behold.^ R. P. 169. 
 
 (37) 
 
 Earth increases its own mass, and Air swells the bulk of Air. 
 
 (38) 
 
 Come, I shall now tell thee first of all the beginning of the 
 sun,2 and the sources from which have sprung all the things we 
 now behold, the earth and the billowy sea, the damp vapour 
 and the Titan air that binds his circle fast round all things. 
 R. P. 170 a. 
 
 (39) 
 If the depths of the earth and the vast air were infinite, a 
 foolish saying which has been vainly dropped from the lips of 
 many mortals, though they have seen but a Uttle of the All. . . .^ 
 R. P. 103 b. 
 
 (40) 
 The sharp-darting sun and the gentle moon. 
 
 (41) 
 But (the sunlight) is gathered together and circles round the 
 mighty heavens. 
 
 1 We see clearly from this fragment how the addvara (the elements) 
 are identified, with the " unmixed," and the dvrjTa (the perishable com- 
 binations) with the " mixed." 
 
 "^ The MSS. of Clement have rfKiov dpxw> ^^^ the reading ijXiov dpx^y 
 is a mere makeshift. Diels reads i^XiKd r' dpxw> " the first (elements) 
 equal in age." 
 
 * The lines are referred to Xenophanes by Aristotle, who quotes them 
 De caelo, B, 13. 294 a 21. See above. Chap. II. p. 125, n. 3. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 213 
 
 (42) 
 And she cuts off his rays as he goes above her, and casts a 
 shadow on as much of the earth as is the breadth of the pale-faced 
 moon.i 
 
 (43) 
 
 Even so the sunbeam, having struck the broad and mighty 
 circle of the moon, returns at once, running so as to reach the 
 sky. 
 
 (44) 
 
 It flashes back to Olympos with untroubled countenance. 
 R. P. 170 c. 
 
 (45, 46) 
 
 There circles round the earth a round borrowed Ught, as the 
 nave of the wheel circles round the furthest (goal).^ 
 
 (47) 
 
 For she gazes at the sacred circle of the lordly sun opposite. 
 
 (48) 
 It is the earth that makes night by coming before the Ughts. 
 
 (49) 
 ... of soUtary, bUnd-eyed night. 
 
 (50) 
 And Iris bringeth wind or mighty rain from the sea. 
 
 (51) 
 (Fire) swiftly rushing upwards . . . 
 
 (52) 
 And many fires burn beneath the earth. R. P. 171 a. 
 
 (53) 
 For so it (the air) chanced to be running at that time, though 
 often otherwise. R. P. 171 a. 
 
 1 I translate Diels's conjecture dTrea-Tiyaaev . . . iar Slv tri. 
 ' See p. 177, n. i. 
 
214 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (54) 
 But the air sank down upon the earth with its long roots. 
 R. P. 171 a. 
 
 (55) 
 Sea the sweat of the earth. R. P. 170 b. 
 
 (56) 
 Salt was solidified by the impact of the sun's beams. 
 
 (57) 
 On it (the earth) many heads sprung up without necks and 
 arms wandered bare and bereft of shoulders. Eyes strayed up 
 and down in want of foreheads. R. P. 173 a. 
 
 (58) 
 
 Solitary limbs wandered seeking for union. 
 
 ^ (59) 
 
 4. But, as divinity was mingled still further with divinity, these 
 things joined together as each might chance, and many other 
 things besides them continually arose.) 
 
 (60) 
 
 Shambling creatures with countless hands. 
 
 (61) 
 
 Many creatures with faces and breasts looking in different 
 
 directions were born ; some, offspring of oxen with faces of men, 
 
 while others, again, arose as offspring of men with the heads of 
 
 oxen, and creatures in whom the nature of women and men was 
 
 5 mingled, furnished with sterile ^ parts. R. P. 173 b. 
 
 (62) 
 
 Come now, hear how the Fire as it was separated caused the 
 night-bom shoots of men and tearful women to arise ; for my 
 tale is not off the point nor uninformed. Whole-natured forms 
 first arose from the earth, having a portion both of water and 
 
 1 Reading areipoLs with Diels. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 215 
 
 fire.i These did the fire, desirous of reaching its like, send up, 5 
 showing as yet neither the charming form of the limbs, nor yet 
 the voice and parts that are proper to men. R. P. 173 c. 
 
 (63) 
 
 . . . But the substance of (the child's) limbs is divided 
 between them, part of it in men's (and part in women's body). 
 
 (64) 
 
 And upon him came desire reminding him through sight. 
 
 (65) 
 . . . And it was poured out in the purified parts ; and when 
 it met with cold women arose from it. 
 
 (66) 
 The divided meadows of Aphrodite. 
 
 (67) 
 For in its warmer part the womb brings forth males, and 
 that is why men are dark and more manly and shaggy. 
 
 (68) 
 
 On the tenth day of the eighth month it turns to a white 
 putrefaction.^ 
 
 Double bearing.^ 
 Sheepskin.* 
 
 (69) 
 (70) 
 
 (71) 
 
 But if thy assurance of these things was in any way deficient 
 as to how, out of Water and Earth and Air and Fire mingled 
 
 1 Retaining efSeos {i.e. fSeos), which is read in the MSS. of Simplicius. 
 Cf. above, p. 209, n. i. 
 
 2 That Empedokles regarded milk as putrefied blood is stated by 
 Aristotle {De gen. an. A, 8. 777 a 7). The word irvov means pus. There 
 may be a pun on irv6s, " beestings," but that has its vowel long. 
 
 3 Said of women in reference to births in the seventh and ninth 
 months. 
 
 * Of the membrane round the foetus. 
 
2i6 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 together, arose the forms and colours of all those mortal things 
 that have been fitted together by Aphrodite, and so are now 
 come into being. . . . 
 
 (72) 
 
 How tall trees and the fishes in the sea . . . 
 
 (73) 
 
 And even as at that time Kypris, preparing warmth,^ after 
 she had moistened the Earth in water, gave it to swift fire to 
 harden it. . . . R. P. 171. 
 
 (74) 
 
 Leading the songless tribe of fertile fish. 
 
 (75) 
 All of those which are dense within and rare without, having 
 received a flaccidity of this kind at the hands of Kypris. . . . 
 
 (76) 
 
 This thou mayest see in the heavy-backed shell-fish that 
 dwell in the sea, in sea-snails and the stony-skinned turtles. In 
 them thou mayest see that the earthy part dwells on the upper- 
 most surface of the skin. 
 
 (77-78) 
 
 It is moisture ^ that makes evergreen trees flourish with 
 abundance of fruit the whole year round. 
 
 (79) 
 
 And so first of all tall olive trees bear eggs. . . . 
 
 cule:^" 
 
 (80) 
 Wherefore pomegranates are late-born and apples succule: 
 
 (81) 
 
 Wine is the water from the bark, putrefied in the wood. 
 
 1 Reading idea ironrvvovaa with Diels. 
 
 * This seems clearly to be the meaning of -f^-fip here. Cf. fr. 100, v. 13, 
 and p. 228, n. 2. 
 
 i 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 217 
 
 (82) 
 Hair and leaves, and thick feathers of birds, and the scales 
 that grow on mighty limbs, are the same thing. 
 
 (83) 
 But the hair of hedgehogs is sharp-pointed and bristles on 
 their backs. 
 
 (84) 
 
 L And even as when a man thinking to sally forth through a 
 stormy night, gets him ready a lantern, a flame of blazing fire, 
 fastening to it horn plates to keep out all manner of winds, and 
 they scatter the blast of the winds that blow, but the Hght leaping 
 out through them, shines across the threshold with unfaiUng 5 
 beams, as much of it as is finer ; ^ even so did she (Love) then 
 entrap the elemental fire, the round pupil, confined within 
 membranes and delicate tissues, which are pierced through and 
 through with wondrous passages. They keep out the deep 
 water that surrounds the pupil, but they let through the fire, as 10 
 much of it as is finer. R. P. 177 b.' 
 
 > 
 
 (85) 
 But the gentle flame (of the eye) has but a scanty portion 
 of earth. 
 
 (86) 
 Out of these divine Aphrodite fashioned unwearying eyes. 
 
 (87) ■ 
 
 Aphrodite fitting these together with rivets of love. 
 
 (88) 
 One vision is produced by both the eyes. 
 
 (89) 
 
 Know that effluences flow from all things that have come into 
 being. R. P. 166 h. 
 
 1 See Beare, p. 16, «. i, where Plato, Tim. 45 b 4 (toO ttv/j^s 6<tov to y^kv 
 Kaeiv ovK ^ax^v, rb 5^ irapix^tv (puts ij/x^pov), is aptly quoted. 
 
2i8 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (90) 
 So sweet lays hold of sweet, and bitter rushes to bitter ; 
 acid comes to acid, and warm couples with warm. 
 
 (91) 
 
 Water fits better into wine, but it will not (mingle) with oil. 
 R. P. 166 h. 
 
 (92) 
 Copper mixed with tin. 
 
 (93) 
 
 The bloom of scarlet dye mingles with the grey Hnen.^ 
 
 (94) 
 
 And the black colour at the bottom of a river arises from the 
 shadow. The same is seen in hollow caves. 
 
 (95) 
 
 Since they (the eyes) first grew together in the hands of 
 Kypris. 
 
 (96) 
 The kindly earth received in its broad funnels two parts of 
 gleaming Nestis out of the eight, and four of Hephaistos. So 
 arose white bones divinely fitted together by the cement of 
 proportion. R. P. 175. 
 
 (97) 
 
 The spine (was broken). 
 
 i 
 
 (98) 
 
 And the earth, anchoring in the perfect harbours of Aphrodite,] 
 meets with these in nearly equal proportions, with Hephaistos 
 and Water and gleaming Air — either a Uttle more of it, or less 
 
 ^ On this fragment see Clara E. Millard, On the Interpretation oj 
 Empedocles, p. 38, «. 3. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 219 
 
 of them and more of it. From these did blood arise and the 
 manifold forms of flesh. R. P. 175 c. 
 
 (99) 
 The bell ... the fleshy sprout (of the ear).i 
 
 (100) 
 
 Thus 2 do all things draw breath and breathe it out again. 
 All have bloodless tubes of flesh extended over the surface of 
 their bodies ; and at the mouths of these the outermost surface 
 of the sldn is perforated all over with pores closely packed 
 together, so as to keep in the blood while a free passage is cut 5 
 for the air to pass through. Then, when the thin blood recedes 
 from these, the bubbUng air rushes in with an impetuous surge ; 
 and when the blood runs back it is breathed out again. Just as 
 when a girl, playing with a water-clock of shining brass, puts the 10 
 orifice of the pipe upon her comely hand, and dips the water- 
 clock into the jdelding mass of silvery water — the stream does not 
 then flow into the vessel, but the bulk of the air ^ inside, pressing 
 upon the close-packed perforations, keeps it out till she uncovers 
 the compressed stream ; but then air escapes and an equal 15 
 volume of water runs in, — just in the same way, when water 
 occupies the depths of the brazen vessel and the opening and 
 passage is stopped up by the human hand, the air outside, striving 
 to get in, holds the water back at the gates of the ill-sounding 
 neck, pressing upon its surface, till she lets go with her hand. 20 
 Then, on the contrary, just in the opposite way to what happened 
 before, the wind rushes in and an equal volume of water runs out 
 
 ^ On fr. 99, see Beare, p. 96, n. i. 
 
 * This passage is quoted by Aristotle {De respir, 473 b 9), who makes 
 the curious mistake of taking pLvQv for the genitive of pLs instead of pivds. 
 The locus classicus on the klepsydra is Probl. 914 b 9 sqq.- (where read 
 aiXou for dXkov, b 12). It was a metal vessel with a narrow neck (au\6s) 
 at the top and with a sort of strainer {-qdfios) pierced with holes {rprifiaTa, 
 Tpvirrj/xaTo) at the bottom. The passage in the Problems just referred to 
 attributes this theory of the phenomenon to Anaxagoras, and we shall 
 see that he also made use of the experiment (§ 131). 
 
 3 The MSS. of Aristotle have d^pos here, though the air is called alO-^p 
 in four other verses of the fragment (vv, 5, 7, 18, 24), It is easier to 
 suppose that Aristotle made a shp in this one verse than that Empedokles 
 should use dr)p in a sense he elsewhere avoids (p. 228, n. 2), and this 
 suspicion is confirmed by the form d^pos instead of ij^pos. I think, 
 therefore, that Stein was right in reading aid^pos. 
 
220 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 to make room.^ Even so, when the thin blood that surges 
 through the limbs rushes backwards to the interior, straightway 
 25 the stream of air comes in with a rushing swell ; but when the 
 blood runs back the air breathes out again in equal quantity. 
 
 (lOl) 
 
 (The dog) with its nostrils tracking out the fragments of the 
 beast's limbs, and the breath from their feet that they leave in 
 the soft grass.2 
 
 (102) 
 
 Thus all things have their share of breath and smell. 
 
 ,^ (i03> 104) 
 
 \ Thus have all things thought by fortune's will. . . . And 
 inasmuch as the rarest things came together in their fall. 
 
 (105) 
 (The heart), dwelKng in the sea of blood that runs in opposite 
 directions, where chiefly is what men call thought ; for the 
 blood round the heart is the thought of men. R. P. 178 a. 
 
 (106) 
 
 For the wisdom of men grows according to what is before 
 them. R. P. 177. 
 
 (107) 
 
 For out of these are all things formed and fitted together, 
 and by these do men think and feel pleasure and pain. R. P. 178. 
 
 1 This seems to be the experiment described in Probl. 914 b 26, ihp 
 yap TLi aiiTTJs [rrjs K\e\}/6dpas) avTT]v tt}v Kcadiav ifi-rrX-qaas vdaros, iiriXa^wv 
 Toy a{>\6v^ KaTa(XTp^\}^ig iirl rbv aiXbv, ov (piperai rb v8ojp dioL rod aiXov iirl 
 arSfxa. dvoixdhro^ de rod ardfiaros, q-ukI evdiis iKpec Kara rbv ai>\6f, dXXA 
 fiiKpoT^p(^ iiarepov, wj ovk '6v iirl T<p crrbixari tov av\ov, dXX' varepov Sia to^tov 
 <f)ep6fi€vov dvoixdivros. The epithet dvcrrjx^os is best explained as a reference 
 to the ipvyfios or " belching " referred to at 915 a 7. Any one can 
 produce this effect with a water-bottle. If it were not for this epithet, 
 it would be tempting to read rjdfxoio for iad/xo7o, and that is actually the 
 reading of a few MSS. 
 
 2 On fr. loi, see Beare, p. 135, n. 2. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 221 
 
 (108) 
 
 And just so far as they grow to be different, so far do different 
 thoughts ever present themselves to their minds (in dreams).^ 
 R. P. 177 a. 
 
 (109) 
 
 For it is with earth that we see Earth, and Water with water ; \ 
 by air we see bright Air, by fire destroying Fire. By love do we 
 see Love, and Hate by grievous hate. R. P. 176. 
 
 (110) 
 
 For if, supported on thy steadfast mind, thou wilt contem- 
 plate these things with good intent and faultless care, then shalt 
 thou have all these things in abundance throughout thy Ufe, 
 and thou shalt gain many others from them. For these things 
 grow of themselves into thy heart, where is each man's true 5 
 nature. But if thou strivest after things of another kind, as it 
 is the way with men that ten thousand sorry matters blunt their 
 careful thoughts, soon will these things desert thee when the 
 time comes round ; for they long to return once more to their 
 own kind ; for know that all things have wisdom and a share of ^ 10 
 thought. 
 
 (Ill) 
 
 And thou shalt learn all the drugs that are a defence against 
 ills and old age ; since for thee alone will I accompUsh all this. 
 Thou shalt arrest the violence of the weariless winds that arise 
 to sweep the earth and waste the fields ; and again, when thou 
 so desirest, thou shalt bring back their blasts in return. Thou 5 
 shalt cause for men a seasonable drought after the dark rains, 
 and again thou shalt change the summer drought for streams 
 that feed the trees as they pour down from the sky. Thou shalt 
 bring back from Hades the Ufe of a dead man. 
 
 PURIFICATIONS 
 
 (112) 
 
 Friends, that inhabit the great town looking down on the 
 yellow rock of Akragas, up by the citadel, busy in goodly works, 
 harbours of honour for the stranger, men unskilled in meanness, 
 
 1 That this refers to dreams, we learn from Simpl. De an. p. 202, 30. 
 
222 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 all hail. I go about among you an immortal god, no mortal 
 5 now, honoured among aU as is meet, crowned with fillets and 
 flowery garlands. Straightway, whenever I enter with these in 
 my train, both men and» women, into the flourishing towns, is 
 reverence done me ; they go after me in countless throngs, 
 10 asking of me what is the way to gain ; some desiring oracles, 
 while some, who for many a weary day have been pierced by the 
 grievous pangs of aU manner of sickness, beg to hear from me 
 the word of heahng. R. P. 162 f. 
 
 (113) 
 
 But why do I harp on these things, as if it were any great 
 matter that I should surpass mortal, perishable men ? 
 
 (114) 
 
 Friends, I know indeed that truth is in the words I shall 
 utter, but it is hard for men, and jealous are they of the assault 
 of belief on their souls. 
 
 ("5) 
 
 There is an oracle of Necessity, an ancient ordinance of the 
 
 gods,^ eternal and sealed fast by broad oaths, that whenever one 
 
 of the daemons, whose portion is lengjin of days, has sinfully 
 
 polluted his hands with blood,^ or follo/wed strife and forsworn 
 
 5 himself, he must wander thrice ten ;tliousand seasons from the 
 
 abodes of the blessed, being born throughout the time in all 
 
 manners of mortal forms, changing one toilsome path of Hfe for 
 
 another. For the mighty Air drives him into the Sea, and the 
 
 10 Sea spews him forth on the dry Earth ; Earth tosses him into 
 
 the beams of the blazing Sun, and he flings him back to the eddies 
 
 of Air. One takes him from the other, and all reject him. One 
 
 of these I now am, an exile and a wanderer from the gods, for 
 
 that I put my trust in insensate strife. R. P. 181. 
 
 (116) 
 
 Charis loathes intolerable Necessity. 
 
 1 Necessity is an Orphic personage, and Gorgias, the disciple of 
 Empedokles, says dewv povXev/xaaiv /cat dydyKrjt xf/rjcfiia-fiaaiv {Hel. 6). 
 
 2 I retain ^oj/y in v. 3 (so too Diels). The first word of v. 4 has been 
 lost. Diels suggests IseUe'C, which may well be right, and takes dfiapT-rjaas 
 as equivalent to bixaprijcai. I have translated accordingly. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 223 
 
 ("7) 
 For I have been ere now a boy and a girl, a bush and a bird 
 and a dumb fish in the sea. R. P. 182. 
 
 (118) 
 
 1 wept and I wailed when I saw the unfamiUar land. R. P. 
 182. 
 
 (119) 
 From what honour, from what a height of bliss have I fallen 
 to go about among mortals here on earth. 
 
 (120) 
 We have come under this roofed-in cave.^ 
 
 (121) 
 
 . . . the joyless land, where are Death and Wrath and troops 
 of Dooms besides ; and parching Plagues and Rottennesses and 
 Floods roam in darkness over the meadow of Ate. 
 
 (122, 123) 
 
 There were ^ Chthonie and far - sighted HeHope, bloody 
 Discord and gentle -visaged Harmony, KalUsto and Aischre, 
 Speed and Tarrying, lovely Truth and dark-haired Uncertainty, 
 Birth and Decay, Sleep and Waking, Movement and Immobility, 
 crowned Majesty and Meanness, Silence and Voice. R. P. 182 a. 
 
 (124) 
 
 Alas, O wretched race of mortals, sore unblessed : such are 
 the strifes and groanings from which ye have been born ! 
 
 (125) 
 
 From Uving creatures he made them dead, changing their 
 )rms. 
 
 According to Porphyry {De antro Nymph. 8), these words were 
 spoken by the " powers " who conduct the soul into the world {\l/vxoTrofivol 
 dvvdfieis). The " cave " is not originally Platonic but Orphic. 
 
 2 This passage is closely modelled on the Catalogue of Nymphs in Iliad 
 tviii. 39 sqq. Chthonie is found already in Pherekydes (Diog. i. 119). 
 
224 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 (126) 
 
 (The goddess) clothing them with a strange garment of 
 flesh.i 
 
 (127) 
 
 Among beasts they ^ become lions that make their lair on the 
 hills and their couch on the ground ; and laurels among trees 
 with goodly foUage. R. P. 181 b. 
 
 (128) 
 
 Nor had they ^ any Ares for a god nor Kydoimos, no nor 
 King Zeus nor Kronos nor Poseidon, but Kypris the Queen. 
 . . . Her did they propitiate with holy gifts, with painted 
 figures * and perfumes of cunning fragrancy, with offerings of 
 5 pure mjnrh and sweet-smelling frankincense, casting on the 
 ground libations of brown honey. And the altar did not 
 reek with pure bull's blood, but this was held in the greatest 
 abomination among men, to eat the goodly limbs after tearing 
 out the Ufe. R. P. 184. 
 
 (129) 
 
 And there was among them a man of rare knowledge, most 
 
 skilled in all manner of wise works, a man who had won the 
 
 utmost wealth of wisdom ; for whensoever he strained with all 
 
 his mind, he easily saw everything of all the things that are, in 
 
 5 ten, yea, twenty hfetimes of men.^ 
 
 1 I have retained dWSyvioTL, though it is a Httle hard to interpret. 
 On the history of the Orphic chiton in gnostic imagery see Bernays, 
 Theophr. Schr. n. 9. It was identified with the coat of skins made by 
 God for Adam. Cf. also Shakespeare's " muddy vesture of decay." 
 
 2 This is the best fieroUTja-is (Ael. Nat. an. xii. 7). 
 ' The dwellers in the Golden Age. 
 
 * The MSS. of Porphyry have ypairroli re fwoio-t. The emendation 
 of Bernays (adopted in R. P.) does not convince me. I venture to 
 suggest fiaKToXs, on the strength of the story related by Favorinus 
 {ap. Diog. viii. 53) as to the bloodless sacrifice offered by Empedokles 
 at Olympia. 
 
 * These Hnes were already referred to Pythagoras by Timaios (Diog. 
 viii. 54), As we are told (Diog. ib.) that some referred the verses to 
 Parmenides, it is clear that no name was given. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 225 
 
 (130) 
 For all things were tame and gentle to man, both beasts and 
 birds, and friendly feelings were kindled ever5rwhere. R. P. 184 a. 
 
 (131) 
 If ever, as regards the things of a day, immortal Muse, thou 
 didst deign to take thought for my endeavour, then stand by 
 me once more as I pray to thee, O Kalliopeia, as I utter a pure 
 discourse concerning the blessed gods. R. P. 179. 
 
 (132) 
 Blessed is the man who has gained the riches of divine 
 wisdom ; wretched he who has a dim opinion of the gods in his 
 heart. R. P. 179. 
 
 (133) 
 It is not possible for us to set God before our eyes, or to 
 lay hold of him with our hands, which is the broadest way of 
 persuasion that leads into the heart of man. 
 
 (134) 
 
 For he is not furnished with a human head on his body, two 
 branches do not sprout from his shoulders, he has no feet, no 
 swift knees, nor hairy parts ; but he is only a sacred and unutter- 
 able mind flashing through the whole world with rapid thoughts. 
 R. P. 180. 
 
 ^35) 
 
 (This is not lawful for some and unlawful for others ;) but the 
 law for all extends everywhere, through the wide-ruling air and 
 the infinite Hght of heaven. R. P. 183. 
 
 (136) 
 WiU ye not cease from this ill-sounding slaughter ? See ye 
 not that ye are devouring one another in the thoughtlessness of 
 your hearts ? R. P. 184 b. 
 
 (137) 
 
 And the father lifts up his own son in a changed form and 
 slays him with a prayer. Infatuated fool ! And they run up to 
 the sacrificers, begging mercy, while he, deaf to their cries, 
 slaughters them in his halls and gets ready the evil feast. In 
 
 15 
 
226 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 5 like manner does the son seize his father, and children their 
 mother, tear out their Hfe and eat the kindred flesh. R. P. 184 b. 
 
 (138) 
 Draining their Ufe with bronze.^ 
 
 (139) 
 Ah, woe is me that the pitiless day of death did not destroy 
 me ere ever I wrought evil deeds of devouring with my Hps ! 
 R. P. 184 b. 
 
 (140) 
 
 Abstain wholly from laurel leaves. 
 
 (141) 
 Wretches, utter wretches, keep your hands from beans ! 
 
 (142) 
 Him will the roofed palace of aigis-bearing Zeus never rejoice, 
 nor yet the house of . . . 
 
 (143) 
 Wash your hands, cutting the water from the five springs in 
 the unyielding bronze. R. P. 184 c. 
 
 (144) 
 Fast from wickedness ! R. P. 184 c. 
 
 (145) 
 
 Therefore are ye distraught by grievous wickednesses, and 
 will not unburden your souls of wretched sorrows. 
 
 (146, 147) 
 
 But, at the last, they appear among mortal men as prophets, 
 
 song-writers, physicians, and princes ; and thence they rise up 
 
 as gods exalted in honour, sharing the hearth of the other gods 
 
 and the same table, free from human woes, safe from destiny, 
 
 5 and incapable of hurt. R. P. 181 c. 
 
 (148) 
 
 Earth that envelops the man. 
 
 I 
 
 * On frs. 138 and 143 see Vahlen on Arist. PoeU 21. 1457 b 13, and 
 Diels in Hermes, xv. p. 173. 
 
r 
 
 EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS \^227 
 
 1 06. At the very outset of his poem, Empedokles speaks Em- 
 angrily of those who professed to have found the whole and°pi^ 
 (fr. 2) ; he even calls this " madness " (fr. 4). No doubt ^enides. 
 he is thinking of Parmenides. -^His own position is not, 
 however, sceptical. ^ He only deprecates the attempt to 
 construct a theory of the universe off-hand instead of trying 
 to understand each thing we come across " in the way in 
 which it is clear" (fr. 4). And this means that we must 
 not, hke Parmenides, reject the assistance of the senses. 
 We soon discover, however, that Empedokles too sets up a 
 system which is to explain everything, though that system 
 is no longer a monistic one. 
 
 It is often said that this system was an attempt to 
 mediate between Parmenides and Herakleitos. It is not 
 easy, however, to find any trace of Herakleitean doctrine in 
 it, and it would be truer to say that it aimed at mediating 
 between Eleaticism and the senses. Empedokles repeats, 
 almost in the same words, the Eleatic argument for the sole 
 reaUty and indestructibiUty of " what is " (frs. 11-15) ; 
 and his idea of the " Sphere " seems to be derived from the 
 Parmenidean description of reaUty.^ Parmenides had held 
 that what underlies the illusory world of the senses was a 
 corporeal, spherical, continuous, eternal, and immovable 
 plenum, and it is from this Empedokles starts. Given the 
 sphere of Parmenides, he seems to have said, how are we 
 to get from it to the world we know ? How are we to 
 introduce motion into the immovable plenum ? Now Par- 
 menides need not have denied the possibiUty of motion 
 within the Sphere, though he was bound to deny all motion 
 of the Sphere itself ; but such an admission would not have 
 served to explain anything. If any part of the Sphere were 
 to move, the room of the displaced body must at once be 
 taken by other body, for there is no empty space. This, 
 however, would be of precisely the same kind as the body 
 it had displaced ; for all " that is " is one. The result of 
 
 1 Cf. Emp. frs. 27, 28, with Farm. fr. 8. 
 
228 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the motion would be precisely the same as that of rest ; 
 it could account for no change. But is this assumption of 
 perfect homogeneity in the Sphere really necessary ? Evi- 
 dently not ; it is simply the old unreasoned feeling that 
 existence must be one. Nevertheless, we cannot regard the 
 numberless forms of being the senses present us with as 
 ultimate reahties. They have no ^uo-i? of their own, and 
 are always passing away (fr. 8), so the only solution is to 
 assume a limited number of ultimate forms of reaUty. We 
 may then apply all that Parmenides says of What is to each 
 one of these, and the transitory forms of existence we know 
 may be explained by their minghng and separation. The 
 conception of " elements " (o-roLx^La), to use a later term,^ 
 was found, and the required formula follows at once. So 
 far as concerns particular things, it is true, as our senses tell 
 us, that they come into being and pass away ; but, if we 
 have regard to the ultimate elements of which they are 
 composed, we shall say with Parmenides that " what is " is 
 uncreated and indestructible (fr. 17). The elements are 
 immortal, just as the single <^uo-t9 of the Milesians was 
 " ageless and deathless." 
 The "four 107. The " four roots " of all things (fr. 6) which Empe- 
 roots." dokles assumed — Fire, Air, Earth, and Water — seem to 
 have been arrived at by making each of the traditional 
 " opposites " — hot and cold, wet and dry — into a thing 
 which is real in the full Parmenidean sense of the word. It 
 is to be noticed, however, that he does not caD Air a'^p, 
 but aWrjp,^ and this must be because he wished to avoid 
 
 ^ For the history of the term aToix^lov see Diels, Elementum. Eudemos 
 said [ap. Simpl. Phys. p. 7, 13) that Plato was the first to use it, but he 
 probably got it from the Pythagoreans. The original term was ixoptp-q or 
 IMa. 
 
 2 In fr. 17, V. 18 Diels reads ^^pos dirXerov ijypo^ with Sextus and 
 Simplicius. Plutarch, however, has aidipot, and it is obvious that this 
 was more likely to be corrupted into ^epos than vice versa in an enumera- 
 tion of the elements. In frag. 38, v. 3, which is not an enumeration of 
 elements, vypbs drjp [i.e. the misty lower air) is distinguished from Tlt^v 
 aid'f)p {i.e. the bright blue sky) in the traditional way. In fr. 78 the re- 
 ference is clearly to moisture. On fr. 100, 13, see p. 219, «. 3. These 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 229 
 
 confusion with what had hitherto been meant by the former 
 word. He had, in fact, nmde the discovery that atmospheric 
 air is a distinct corporeal siibstance, and is not to be identified 
 with empty space on the one hand or rarefied mist on the 
 other. Water is not Uquid air, but something quite dif- 
 ferent.^ This truth Empedokles demonstrated by means 
 of the klepsydra, and we still possess the verses in which he 
 apphed his discovery to the explanation of respiration and 
 the motion of the blood (fr. 100). Aristotle laughs at those 
 who try to show there is no empty space by shutting up 
 air in water-clocks and torturing wineskins. They only 
 prove, he says, that air is a thing. 2 That, however, is 
 exactly what Empedokles intended to prove, and it was 
 one of the most important discoveries in the history of 
 science. It will be convenient for us to translate the 
 aWrjp of Empedokles by " air " ; but we must be careful 
 in that case not to render the word arjp in the same way. 
 Anaxagoras seems to have been the first to use it of atmo- 
 spheric air. 
 
 Empedokles also called the " four roots " by the names 
 of certain divinities — '* shining Zeus, life-bringing Hera, 
 Aidoneus, and Nestis " (fr. 6) — though there is some doubt 
 as to how these names are to be apportioned among the 
 elements. Nestis is said to have been a Sicihan water- 
 goddess, and the description of her shows that she stands 
 for Water ; but there is a conflict of opinion as to the other 
 three. This, however, need not detain us.^ We are 
 
 are the only passages in which Empedokles seems to speak of drjp in the 
 sense of atmospheric air. ^ Cf. Chap, I. § 27. 
 
 2 Arist. Phys. A, 6, 213 a 22 (R. P. 159). Aristotle only mentions 
 Anaxagoras by name in this passage ; but he speaks in the plural, and we 
 know from fr. 100 that the klepsydra experiment was used by Empedokles. 
 
 3 In antiquity the Homeric Allegorists made Hera Earth and Aidoneus 
 Air, a view which has found its way into Actios from Poseidonios. It 
 arose as follows. The Homeric Allegorists were not interested in the 
 science of Empedokles, and did not see that his aiOrjp was quite a different 
 thing from Homer's drjp. Now this is the dark element, and night is a 
 form of it, so it would naturally be identified with Aidoneus. Again, 
 Empedokles calls Hera <pep^(Tj3ios, and that is an epithet of Earth in 
 
230 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 already prepared to find that Empedokles called the elements 
 gods ; for all the early thinkers had spoken in this way of 
 whatever they regarded as the primary substance. We 
 must only remember that the word is not used in its religious 
 sense. Empedokles did not pray or sacrifice to the elements. 
 Empedokles regarded the " roots of all things " as* 
 eternal. Nothing can come from nothing or pass away 
 into nothing (fr. 12) ; what is is, and there is no room for 
 coming into being and passing away (fr. 8). Further, 
 Aristotle tells us, he taught that they were unchangeable.^ 
 This Empedokles expressed by saying that *' they are 
 always aUke." Again, the four elements are all " equal," 
 a statement which seemed strange to Aristotle,^ but was 
 quite intelUgible in the days of Empedokles. Above all, 
 the four elements are ultimate. All other bodies might be 
 divided till you came to the elements ; but Empedokles 
 could give no further account of these without saying (as 
 he did not) that there is an element of which Fire and the 
 rest are in turn composed.^ 
 
 Hesiod and the Homeric Hymns. Another view identified Hera with Air, 
 which is the theory of Plato's Cratylus, and Aidoneus with Earth. The 
 Homeric AUegorists further identified Zeus with Fire, a view to which they 
 were doubtless led by the use of the word aid-qp. Now aid-qp certainly 
 means Fire in Anaxagoras, as we shall see, but there is no doubt that in 
 Empedokles it meant Air, It seems likely, then, that Knatz is right 
 (" Empedoclea " in Schedae Philologicae Hermanno Usenero ohlatae, 1891, 
 pp. I sqq.) in holding that the bright Air of Empedokles was Zeus. This 
 leaves Aidoneus to stand for Fire ; and nothing could have been more 
 natural for a Sicilian poet, with the volcanoes and hot springs of his 
 native island in mind, than this identification. He refers to the fires 
 that burn beneath the Earth himself (fr. 52). If that is so, we shall have 
 to agree with the Homeric AUegorists that Hera is Earth ; and surely 
 (pep^ff^ios "Upa can be none other than " Mother Earth." The epithet 
 seems only to be used of earth and corn. 
 
 ^ Arist. De gen. corr. B, i. 329 b i. * Ibid. B, 6. 333 a 16. 
 
 * Ibid. A, 8. 325 b 19 (R. P. 164 e). This was so completely mis- 
 understood by later writers that they attribute to Empedokles the doctrine 
 of crroix"ct -rrpb rCbv (XTovxeiwv (Aet. i. 13, i ; 17,' 3). The criticism of 
 the Pythagoreans and Plato had made the hypothesis of elements almost 
 unintelligible to Aristotle, and a fortiori to his successors. As Plato put 
 it (Tiw. 48 b 8), they were "not even syllables," let alone "letters" 
 {<noix<ua). That is why Aristotle calls them rd KoXo^iiMeva aroLx^ta (Diels, 
 Elementum, p. 25). 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 231 
 
 The " four roots '* are given as an exhaustive enumera- 
 tion of the elements (fr. 23 sub fin.) ; for they account for 
 all the quaUties presented by the world to the senses. When 
 we find, as we do, that the school of medicine which regarded 
 Empedokles as its founder identified the four elements with 
 the " opposites," the hot and the cold, the moist and the 
 dry, which formed the theoretical foundation of its system,^ 
 we see at once how the theory is related to previous views 
 of reaHty. We must remember that the conception of 
 quahty had not "yet been formed. Anaximander had no 
 doubt regarded his " opposites " as things ; though, before 
 the time of Parmenides, no one had fully reahsed how much 
 was implied in saying that anything is a thing. That is 
 the stage we have now reached. There is still no conception 
 of quality, but there is a clear apprehension of what is 
 involved in saying a thing is. 
 
 Aristotle twice ^ makes the statement .that, though 
 Empedokles assumes four elements, he treats them as two, 
 opposing Fire to all the rest. This, he says, we can see 
 for ourselves from his poem. So far as the general theory 
 goes, it is impossible to see anything of the sort ; but, when 
 we come to the origin of the world (§ 112), we shall find that 
 Fire plays a leading part, and this may be what Aristotle 
 meant. It is also true that in the biology (§§ 114-116) Fire 
 fulfils a unique function, while the other three act more or 
 less in the same way. But we must remember that it has 
 no pre-eminence over the rest : all are equal. 
 
 108. The Eleatic criticism had made it necessary to strife and 
 explain motion.^ Empedokles starts, we have seen, from 
 an original state of the " four roots," which only differs from 
 the Sphere of Parmenides in so far as it is a mixture, not a 
 homogeneous and continuous mass. It is this that makes 
 change and motion possible ; but, were there nothing outside 
 the Sphere which could enter in, like the Pjrthagorean " Air," 
 
 1 Philistion put the matter in this way. See p. 201, n. 5. 
 
 2 Arist. Met. A, 4. 985 a 31 ; Z)e gen. corr. B, 3. 330 b 19 (R- P- 164 e). 
 
 3 Cf. Introd. § VIII. 
 
232 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 to separate the elements, nothing could ever arise from it. 
 Empedokles accordingly assumed the existence of such a 
 substance, and he gave it the name of Strife. But the 
 effect of this would be to separate all the elements in the 
 Sphere completely, and then nothing more could possibly 
 happen ; something else was needed to bring the elements 
 together again. This Empedokles found in Love, which he 
 regarded as the same impulse to union that is implanted in 
 human bodies (fr. 17, 22 sqq.). He looks at it, in fact, from 
 a physiological point of view, as was natural for the founder 
 of a medical school. No mortal had yet marked, he says, 
 that the very same Love men know in their bodies had a 
 place among the elements. 
 
 The Love and Strife of Empedokles are no incorporeal 
 forces. They are active, indeed, but they are still corporeal. 
 At the time, this was inevitable ; nothing incorporeal had 
 yet been dreamt of. Naturally, Aristotle is puzzled by 
 this characteristic of what he regarded as efficient causes. 
 " The Love of Empedokles," he says,^ " is both an efficient 
 cause, for it brings things together, and a material cause, 
 for it is a part of the mixture." And Theophrastos expressed 
 the same idea by saying 2 that Empedokles sometimes gave 
 an efficient power to Love and Strife, and sometimes put 
 them on a level with the other four. The fragments leave 
 no room for doubt that they were thought of as spatial and 
 corporeal. All the six are called " equal." Love is said to 
 be " equal in length and breadth " to the others, and Strife 
 is described as equal to each of them in weight (fr. 17). 
 
 The function of Love is to produce union ; that of Strife, 
 to break it up again. Aristotle, however, rightly points 
 out that in another sense it is Love that divides and Strife 
 that unites. When the Sphere is broken up by Strife, the 
 result is that all the Fire, for instance, which was contained 
 in it comes together and becomes one ; and again, when the 
 
 1 Arist. Met. A, lo. 1075 b 3. 
 Theophr. Phys. Op. fr. 3 {Dox. p. 477; R. P. 166 b). 
 
 i 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 233 
 
 elements are brought together once more by Love, the mass 
 of each is divided. In another place, he says that, while 
 Strife is assumed as the cause of destruction, and does, in 
 fact, destroy the Sphere, it really gives birth to everything 
 else in so doing. ^ It follows that we must carefully distin- 
 guish between the Love of Empedokles and that " attraction 
 of like for Hke " to which he also attributed an important 
 part in the formation of the world. The latter is not an 
 element distinct from the others ; it depends on the proper 
 nature of each element, and is only able to take effect when 
 Strife divides the Sphere. Love, on the contrary, produces 
 V, an attraction of unlikes. 
 
 log. But, when Strife has separated the elements, what Mixture 
 determines the direction of their motion ? Empedokles separation, 
 seems to have given no further explanation than that each 
 was " running " in a certain direction (fr. 53). . Plato 
 severely condemns this in the Laws,^ on the ground that no 
 room is thus left for design. Aristotle also blames him for 
 giving no account of the Chance to which he ascribed so 
 much importance. Nor is the Necessity, of which he also 
 spoke, further explained.^ Strife enters into the Sphere at 
 a certain time in virtue of Necessity, or " the mighty oath " 
 (fr. 30) ; but we are told no more about.that. 
 
 The expression used by Empedokles to describe the 
 movement of the elements is that they " run through each 
 other" (fr. 17, 34). Aristotle tells us* that he explained 
 mixture in general by " the symmetry of pores." And 
 this is the true explanation of the " attraction of Uke for 
 Hke." The " pores " of Uke bodies are, of course, much the 
 same size, and these bodies can therefore mingle easily. 
 On the other hand, a finer body will " run through " a coarse 
 one without becoming mixed, and a coarse body will not be 
 
 1 Met. A, 4. 985 a 21 ; r, 4. 1000 a 24 ; b 9 (R. P. 166 i). 
 
 2 Plato, Laws, x. 889 b. The reference is not to Empedokles ex- 
 clusively, but the language shows that Plato is thinking mainly of him. 
 
 3 Arist. De gen. corr. B, 6. 334 a i ; Phys. O, i. 252 a 5 (R. P. 166 k). 
 * Arist. De gen. corr. A, 8. 324 b 34 (R. P. 166 h). 
 
234 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 able to enter the pores of a finer one at all. As Aristotle says, 
 this really implies something Hke the atomic theory ; but 
 there is no evidence that Empedokles himself was conscious 
 of that. Another question raised by Aristotle is even more 
 instructive. Are the pores, he asks, empty or full ? If 
 empty, what becomes of the denial of the void ? If full, 
 why need we assume pores at all ? ^ These questions 
 Empedokles would have found it hard to answer. 
 The four 1 10. It will be clear from what has been said that we must 
 
 perio s. distinguish four periods in the cycle. First we have the 
 Sphere, in which all the elements are mixed together by 
 Love. Secondly, there is the period when Love is passing 
 out and Strife coming in, when, therefore, the elements are 
 partially separated and partially combined. Thirdly comes 
 the complete separation of the elements, when Love is 
 outside the world, and Strife has given free play to the 
 attraction of Hke for like. Lastly, we have the period when 
 Love is bringing the elements together again, and Strife is 
 passing out. This brings us back to the Sphere, and the 
 cycle begins afresh. Now a world such as ours can exist 
 only in the second and fourth of these periods. It seems to 
 be generally supposed that we are in the fourth period ; ^ 
 I hope to show that we are in the second, that when Strife 
 is gaining the upper hand. 
 Our world III. That a world of perishable things [Ovtjto) arises both 
 of ^strife. ^^ ^^^ second and fourth period is distinctly stated by 
 Empedokles (fr. 17), and it is inconceivable that he had not 
 made up his mind which of these worlds is ours. Aristotle 
 is clearly of opinion that in our world Strife is increasing. 
 In one place, he says that Empedokles " holds that the 
 world is in a similar condition now in the period of Strife 
 
 1 Arist. De gen. corr. A, 8. 326 b 6. 
 
 2 This is the view of Zeller (pp. 785 sqg.), but he admits that the 
 external testimony, especially that of Aristotle, is wholly in favour of the 
 other. His difficulty is \vith the fragments, and if it can be shown thai 
 these can be interpreted in accordance with Aristotle's statements, th« 
 question is settled. 
 
 i 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 235 
 
 as formerly in that of Love." ^ In another, he tells us that 
 Empedokles omits the generation of things in the period of 
 Love, just because it is unnatural to represent this world, 
 in which the elements are separate, as arising from things 
 in a state of separation.^ This remark can only mean that 
 Empedokles assumed the increase of Strife, or, in other 
 words, that he represented the course of evolution as the 
 disintegration of the Sphere, not as the coming together of 
 things from a state of separation.^ That is what we should 
 expect, if we are right in supposing that the problem he set 
 himself to solve was the origin of this world from the Sphere 
 of Parmenides, and it is also in harmony with the tendency 
 of such speculations to represent the world as getting worse 
 rather than better. We have only to consider, then, whether 
 the details of the system bear out this general view. 
 
 112. To begin with the Sphere, in which the '* four roots Formation 
 of all things " are mixed together, we note that it is called a ^orldby 
 god in the fragments just as the elements are, and that Aris- ^t^i^^- 
 totle more than once refers to it in the same way.* We 
 
 ^ Arist. De gen. corr. B, 6. 334 a 6, rbv Kdafxov oyuo/ws ^xetv (firjalv iiri 
 re Tov veUovs vvv Kal irpbrepov iirl ttJs <pi\ias. Miss Millerd {Interpretation of 
 Empedocles, p. 45) adds Theophrastos, De sensu § 20, avfi^aivet 5^ Kal iwl rijs 
 ^iKtas SXws ^7; ehai atcrd7i<nv i) tjttov Slol rb avyKpiveadaL rbre Kal [xr] duroppeTv. 
 Here iirl rrjs ^iXias and t6t€ imply the antithesis iirl tov Nekous and vvv. 
 
 ^ Arist. De caelo, V, 2. 301 a 14, eV bieaTibruv 5k Kal kivovix^vuv qvk 
 eUXoyov iroietv tt]v yeveaiv. 8ib Kal 'EfiiredoKXrjs irapaXeiireL rr]v iirl rijs 
 <Pi\6n}Tos • oi yap B.v rjdOvaTO ffvaTTjaai rbv ovpavbv iK Kexf^pt^o^f^^vuiv fikv 
 KaracTKevd^wv, dyKpiaiv 8k iroiuiv did ttjj/ (piXSrrjTa' iK 8i.aK€Kpifj.4vu}v ydp 
 (TvvicTTrjKev 6 Kba/xos tQv (ttolx^Lwv (" our world consists of the elements 
 in a state of separation "), wo-r' dvayKalov yev^adai i^ ivbs Kal crvyKeKpifx^vov. 
 
 3 It need not mean that Empedokles said nothing about the world of 
 Love at all ; for he obviously says something of both worlds in fr. 17. It 
 is enough to suppose that, having described both in general terms, he 
 went on to treat the world of Strife in detail. 
 
 * Arist. De gen. corr. B, 6. 333 b 21 (R. P. 168 e) ; Met. B, 4. 1000 a 28 
 (R. P. 166 i). Cf. Simpl. Phys. p. 1124, i (R. P. 167 b). In other places 
 Aristotle speaks of it as " the One." Cf. De gen. corr. A, i. 315 a 7 (R. P. 
 168 e) ; Met. B. 4. 1000 a 29 (R. P. 166 i) ; A, 4. 985 a 28 (R. P. ib.). 
 This involves a slight Aristotelian " development." It is not the same 
 thing to say, as Empedokles does, that all things come together " into 
 one," and to say that they come together " into the One." The latter 
 expression suggests that they lose their identity in the Sphere, and thus 
 become something like Aristotle's " matter." As has been pointed out 
 
236 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 must remember that Love itself is a part of this mixture/ 
 while \^trife surrounds or encompasses it on every side 
 just as the Boundless encompasses the world in earlier 
 systems. Strife, however, is not boundless, but equal in 
 bulk to each of the four roots and to Love.^ 
 
 At the appointed time. Strife begins to enter into the 
 Sphere and Love to go out of it (frs. 30, 31). The fragments 
 by themselves throw little Hght on this ; but Actios and the 
 Plutarchean Stromateis have between them preserved a very 
 fair tradition of what Theophrastos said on the point. 
 
 Empedokles held that Air was first separated out and secondly 
 Fire. Next came Earth, from which, highly compressed as it 
 was by the impetus of its revolution, Water gushed forth. From 
 the water Mist was produced by evaporation. The heavens were 
 formed out of the Air and the sun out of the Fire, while terrestrial 
 things were condensed from the other elements. Aet. ii. 6. 3 
 {Dox. p. 334 ; R. P. 170). 
 
 Empedokles held that the Air when separated off from the 
 original mixture of the elements was spread round in a circle. 
 After the Air, Fire running outwards, and not finding any other 
 place, ran up under the solid that surrounded the Air.^ There 
 were two hemispheres, revolving round the earth, the one alto- 
 gether composed of fire, the other of a mixture of air and a little 
 fire. The latter he supposed to be the Night. The origin of 
 their motion he derived from the fact of fire preponderating in 
 one hemisphere owing to its accumulation there. Ps.-Plut. 
 Strom, fr. 10 {Dox. p. 582 ; R. P. 170 a). 
 
 (p. 230, n. 3), it is hard for Aristotle to grasp the conception of irreducible 
 elements ; but there can be no doubt that in the Sphere, as in their 
 separation, the elements remain " what they are " for Empedokles. As 
 Aristotle also knows quite well, the Sphere is a mixture. Compare the 
 difficulties about the " One " of Anaximander discussed in Chap. 1. § 15. 
 
 1 This accounts for Aristotle's statement, which he makes once posi- 
 tively {Met. B, I. 996 a 7) and once very doubtful!}' {Met. B, 4. looi a 12), 
 that Love was the substratum of the One in just the same sense as the 
 Fire of Herakleitos, the Air of Anaximenes, or the Water of Thales. He 
 thinks that all the elements become merged in Love, and so lose their 
 identity. In this case, it is in Love he recognises his own " matter." 
 
 2 For the phrase rov irepl rbv &4pa Trdyov cf. Ilepi 8ialT7]s, i. 10, i, 
 7rp6s Tov Trept^xoj'Ta irdyov. Et. M. s.V. firjXds . . . t6v dvorrdrii) irdyov Kal 
 
 i 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 237 
 
 The first of the elements to be separated out by Strife 
 then, was Air, which took the outermost position surround- 
 ing the world (cf. fr. 38). We must not, however, take the 
 statement that it surrounded the world " in a circle " too 
 strictly. It appears that Empedokles regarded the heavens 
 as shaped hke an egg.^ Here, probably, we have a trace of 
 Orphic ideas. At any rate, the outer circle of the Air became 
 soUdified or frozen, and we thus get a crystaUine vault as 
 the boundary of the world. We note that it was Fire which 
 soHdified the Air and turned it to ice. Fire in general had 
 a solidifying power. 2 
 
 In its upward rush Fire displaced a portion of the Air 
 in the upper half of the concave sphere formed by the 
 frozen sky. This air then sunk downwards, carrying with 
 it a small portion of the fire. In this way, two hemispheres 
 were produced : one, consisting entirely of fire, the diurnal 
 hemisphere ; the other, the nocturnal, consisting of air with 
 a Uttle fire. 
 
 The accumulation of Fire in the upper hemisphere 
 disturbs the equihbrium of the heavens and causes them to 
 revolve ; and this revolution not only produces the alterna- 
 tion of day and night, but by its rapidity keeps the heavens 
 and the earth in their places. This was illustrated, Aristotle 
 tells us, by the simile of a cup of water whirled round at the 
 end of a string.^ This experimental illustration is much in 
 the manner of Empedokles. It has nothing to do with 
 " centrifugal force," but is intended to show that rapid 
 motion juay counteract a tendency to fall. 
 
 113. It will be observed that day and night have been The sun, 
 explained without reference to the sun. Day is the Hght ^^s^'and 
 
 earth. 
 
 1 Act. ii. 31, 4 {Dox. p. 363). 2 Act. ii. ii, 2 (R. P. 170 c). 
 
 3 Arist. De caelo, B, i. 284 a 24 ; 13. 295 a 16 (R, P. 170 b). Plato, 
 Phaed. 99 b 6, 5i6 6 [xh tis divrju TrepiTidels ry yy virb tov ovpavoO fxiveiv 
 8r} TToiei Ti]v yijv. The experiment with rb iv rois Kvddots liSup which 
 KtjKKtf TOV Kvddov (pepofiivov iroWdKLS Kdru tov x^^'^oO yivd/xevov 8fJ,us ov 
 <f)4p€Tai KdTU), reminds us of that with the klepsydra in fr. 100, 
 The point is that the <f)6pa of the Uvt) overcomes the oiKeia. poir-f} by its 
 velocity. 
 
238 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 of the fiery diurnal hemisphere, while night is the shadow 
 thrown by the earth when the fiery hemisphere is on the 
 other side of it (fr. 48). What, then, is the sun ? The 
 Plutarchean Stromateis ^ again give us the answer : " The 
 sun is not fire in substance, but a reflexion of fire like 
 that which comes from water." Plutarch himself makes 
 one of his personages say : " You laugh at Empedokles for 
 saying that the sun is a product of the earth, arising from 
 the reflexion of the light of heaven, and once more ' flashes 
 back to Olympos with untroubled countenance/ " 2 Aetios 
 says : 3 " Empedokles held that there were two suns : one, 
 the archetype, the fire in one hemisphere of the world, filling 
 the whole hemisphere always stationed opposite its own 
 reflexion ; the other, the visible sun, its reflexion in the 
 other hemisphere, that which is filled with air mingled with 
 fire, produced by the reflexion of the earth, which is round, 
 on the crystalHne sun, and carried round by the motion of 
 the fiery hemisphere. Or, to sum it up shortly, the sun is 
 a reflexion of the terrestrial fire/' 
 
 These passages, and especially the last, are by no means 
 clear.* The reflexion we call the sun cannot be in the 
 hemisphere opposite the fiery one ; for that is the nocturnal 
 hemisphere. We must say rather that the light of the fiery 
 hemisphere is reflected by the earth on to the fiery hemisphere 
 itself in one concentrated flash. It follows that the appear- 
 ance which we call the sun is the same size as the earth. 
 We may perhaps explain the origin of this vi^ as follows. 
 
 1 [Plut.] Strom, fr. 10 {Dox. p. 582, 11 ; R. P. 170 c). 
 
 a Plut. De Pyth. or. 400 b (R. P. 170 c). I keep the MS. reading 
 ire pi yrjy with Diels. 
 
 8 Aet. ii. 20, 13 {Dox. p. 350), 'Efnre8oK\r}s dvo ijXiovs- rhv /j^v 
 dpx^TVTTOv, TTvp dv iv t4> iripcf} 'r]fiLa<paLpic{) tov KbajMov, ireirXrjpwKbs rb 7}jui.i<x(palpiov, 
 alet Kar avriKpb tt? avravyelg. iavrov Terayfiivou • rbv d^ tpaivb/jLcvov, dvra&yeiav 
 iv T(f> er^py i}/j,i.(r^acpl(fi t(^ tov dipos rod dep/xofiiyovs TreTrXTjpcofJi^vip, dirb KVKXorepovs 
 TT]i 777s Kar dvdKKacTLV yiyv ofiivrjv els rbv ijXiov rbv KpvaTaXXoeidij, (rvfnrepieX- 
 Kopiivrjv 5k ry KLvqaei tov irvplvov. ws 5k /S/oaxews elpTjadai (XwrefJibvTa, dpraOyeiap 
 etvai TOV Trepl ttjv yrjv wvpbi Tbv ■?jXiov. 
 
 * I strongly suspect that the confusion is due to a somewhat captious 
 criticism by Theophrastos (see below, p. 298, n. i). It would be like him 
 to point out that the theory implied " two suns." 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 
 
 239 
 
 It had just been discovered that the moon shone by reflected 
 Ught, and there is always a tendency to give any novel 
 theory a wider apphcation than it really admits of. In the 
 early part of the fifth century B.C., men saw reflected light 
 everywhere ; some of the Pythagoreans held a similar 
 view (§ 150). 
 
 It was probably in this connexion that Lpmpedokles 
 announced that Hght takes some time to travel, though its 
 speed is so great as to escape our p erceptio n.^] 
 
 " The moon was composed of air cut off by the fire ; it 
 was frozen just Hke hail, and had its hght from the sun." 
 It is, in other words, a disc of frozen air, of the same sub- 
 stance as the sohd sky which surrounds the heavens. 
 Diogenes says that Empedokles taught it was smaller than 
 the sun, and Actios tells us it was only half as distant from 
 the earth. 2 
 
 Empedokles did not explain the fixed stars by reflected 
 light, nor even the planets. They were made out of the 
 fire which the air carried with it when forced beneath the 
 earth by the upward rush of fire at the first separation. 
 The fixed stars were attached to the frozen air ; the planets 
 moved freely.^ 
 
 Empedokles was acquainted (fr. 42) with the true theory 
 of solar eclipses, which, along with that of the moon's Hght, 
 was the great discovery of this period. He also knew 
 (fr. 48) that night is the conical shadow of the earth, and not 
 a sort of exhalation. 
 
 Wind was explained from the opposite motions of the 
 fiery and airy hemispheres. Rain was caused by the com- 
 pression of the Air, which forced any water there might be 
 in it out of its pores in the form of drops. Lightning was 
 fire forced out from the clouds in much the same way.* 
 
 1 Arist, De sensu, 6. 446 a 28 ; De an. B, 7. 418 b 20. 
 
 2 [Plut.] Strom, fr. 10 {Dox. p. 582, 12 ; R. P. 170 c) ; Diog. viii. 77 ; 
 Aet. ii. 31, I (cf. Dox. p. 63). * Aet. ii. 13, 2 and 11 {Dox. pp. 341 sqq.). 
 
 * Aet. iii. 3, 7 ; Arist. Meteor. B, 9. 369 b 12, with Alexander's com- 
 mentary. 
 
240 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The earth was at first mixed with water, but the in- 
 creasing compression caused by the velocity of its revolu- 
 tion made the water gush forth, so that the sea is " the 
 sweat of the earth," a phrase to which ^jVristotle objects 
 as a mere poetical metaphor:^, The saltness of the sea was 
 explained by this analogy.^ It is taken for granted that the 
 earth shares in the rotation of the vortex [Uvrj). 
 Organic 114. Empcdoklcs wcut on to show how the four elements, 
 
 combina- 
 tions, mingled in different proportions, gave rise to perishable 
 
 things, such as bones, flesh, and the Hke. These, of course, 
 
 are the work of Love ; but this in no way contradicts the 
 
 view taken above as to the period to which this world 
 
 belongs. Love is by no means banished from the world 
 
 yet, though one day it wiU be. At present, it is still able to 
 
 form combinations of elements ; but, just because Strife is 
 
 ever increasing, they are all perishable. The important 
 
 part played by proportion (\0709) here is no doubt due to 
 
 i^Pythagorean influence. 
 
 The possibility of organic combinations depends on the 
 
 fact that there is still water in the earth, and even fire 
 
 (fr. 52). The warm springs of Sicily were a proof of this, 
 
 not to speak of Etna. These springs Empedokles appears 
 
 to have explained by one of his characteristic images, 
 
 drawn this time from the heating of warm baths. ^ His 
 
 similes are nearly all drawn from human inventions and 
 
 manufactures. 
 
 Plants. 115. Plants and animals were formed from the four 
 
 elements under the influence of Love and Strife. The 
 
 fragments which deal with trees and plants are 77-81 ; and 
 
 these, taken along with certain AristoteUan statements and 
 
 the doxographical tradition, enable us to make out pretty 
 
 1 Arist. Meteor. B, 3. 357 a 24 ; Aet. iii. 16, 3 (R. P. 170 b). Cf. the 
 clear reference in Arist. Meteor. B, i. 353 b 11. 
 
 2 Seneca, Q. Nat. iii. 24, " facere solemus dracones et miliaria et 
 complures formas in quibus aere tenui fistulas struimus per declive circum- 
 datas, ut saepe eundem ignem ambiens aqua per tantum fluat spatii 
 quantum efiiciendo calori sat est. frigida itaque intrat, efiEluit calida. 
 idem sub terra Empedocles existimat fieri." 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 241 
 
 fully what the theory was. The text of Actios is very 
 corrupt here ; but it may, perhaps, be rendered as follows : 
 
 Empedokles says trees were the first living creatures to grow 
 up out of the earth, before the sun was spread out, and before 
 day and night were distinguished ; from the symmetry of their 
 mixture, they contain the proportion of male and female ; they 
 grow, rising up owing to the heat which is in the earth, so that 
 they are parts of the earth just as embryos are parts of the uterus ; 
 fruits are excretions of the water and fire in plants, and those 
 which have a deficiency of moisture shed their leaves when that 
 is evaporated by the summer heat, while those which have more 
 moisture remain evergreen, as in the case of the laurel, the oHve, 
 and the palm ; the differences in taste are due to variations in 
 the particles contained in the earth and to the plants drawing 
 different particles from it, as in the case of vines ; for it is not 
 the difference of the vines that makes wine good, but that of the 
 soil which nourishes them. Aet. v. 26, 4 (R. P. 172). 
 
 fc 
 
 Lristotle finds fault with Empedokles for explaining 
 the double growth of plants, upwards and downwards, by 
 the opposite natural motions of the earth and fire contained 
 in them.^ For " natural motions " we must, of course, 
 substitute the attraction of Uke for like (§ 109). Theo- 
 phrastos says much the same thing. 2 The growth of plants, 
 then, is to be regarded as an incident in the separation of 
 the elements by Strife. Some of the fire still beneath the 
 earth (fr. 52) meeting in its upward course with earth, still 
 moist with water and " running " down so as to " reach its 
 own kind," unites with it, under the influence of the Love 
 still left in the world, to form a temporary combination, 
 which we call a tree or a plant. 
 
 At the beginning of the pseudo-AristoteHan Treatise on 
 Plants,^ we are told that Empedokles attributed desire, 
 sensation, and the capacity for pleasure and pain to plants, 
 and he rightly saw that the two sexes are combined in them. 
 
 (jArist. De an. B, 4. 415 b 28. 
 * Theophr. De causis planiarum, i. 12, 5. 
 3 [Arist.] De plantis, A, i. 8i5ai5. 
 
 16 
 
of animals. 
 
 242 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 This is mentioned by Aetios, and discussed in the pseudo- 
 AristoteHan treatise. If we may so far trust that Byzantine 
 translation from a Latin version of the Arabic/ we get a 
 hint as to the reason. Plants, we are there told, came into 
 being "in an imperfect state of the world," ^ in fact, at a 
 time when Strife had not so far prevailed as to differentiate 
 the sexes. We shaU see that the same thing appHes to the 
 original race of animals. It is strange that Empedokles 
 never observed the actual process of generation in plants, 
 but simply said they spontaneously " bore eggs " (fr. 79), 
 that is to say, fruit. 
 Evolution 116. The fragments which deal with the evolution of 
 animals (57-62) must be understood in the Hght of the 
 statement (fr. 17) that there is a double coming into being 
 and a double passing away of mortal things. The four 
 stages are accurately distinguished in a passage of Actios,^ 
 and we shall see that there is evidence for referring two of 
 them to the second period of the world's history and two to 
 the fourth. 
 
 The first stage is that in which the various parts of 
 animals arise separately. It is that of heads without necks, 
 arms without shoulders, and eyes without foreheads (fr. 57) . 
 It is clear that this must be the first stage in what we have 
 called the fourth period of the world's history, that in which 
 Love is coming in and Strife passing out. Aristotle distinctly 
 refers it to the period of Love, by which, as we have seen, 
 he means the period when Love is increasing.* It is in 
 accordance with this that he also says these scattered 
 members were subsequently put together by Love.^ 
 
 1 Alfred the Englishman translated the Arabic version into Latin in 
 the reign ojE Henry III. It was retranslated from this version into Greek 
 at the Renaissance by a Greek resident in Italy. 
 
 2 A, 2. 817 b 35, " mundo . . . diminuto et non perfecto in com- 
 plemento suo " (Alfred). » Aet. v. 19, 5 (R. P. 173). 
 
 * Arist. De caelo, T, 2. 300 b 29 (R. P. 173 a). Cf. De gen. an. A, 18. 
 722 b 19, where fr. 57 is introduced by the words Kaddwep 'E/xTredoKXrjs 
 yevvq, iirl ttJs ^iXdrrfTos: So Simplicius, De caelo, p. 587, 18, says fiovvo- 
 /leXr} ^Tt. rh yvia dirb rijs tov 'NcLkovs StuKpiaews 6vTa iirXavaTO. 
 
 6 Arist. De an. T, 6. 430 a 30 (R. P. 173 a). 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 243 
 
 The second stage is that in which the scattered limbs 
 are united. At first, they were combined in all possible 
 ways (fr. 59). There were oxen with human heads, 
 creatures with double faces and double breasts, and all 
 manner of monsters (fr. 61). Those of them that were 
 fitted to survive did so, while the rest perished. That is 
 how the evolution of animals took place in the period of 
 Love.^ 
 
 The third stage belongs to the period when the unity of 
 the Sphere is being destroyed by Strife. It is, therefore, 
 the first stage in the evolution of our world. It begins with 
 " whole-natured forms " in which there is not any distinc- 
 tion of sex or species. ^ They are composed of earth and 
 water, and are produced by the upward motion of fire 
 seeking to reach its Hke. 
 
 In the fourth stage, the sexes and species have been 
 separated, and new animals no longer arise from the elements, 
 but are produced by generation. 
 
 ^In both these processes of evolution, Empedokles was 
 guided by the idea of the survival of the fittest. Aristotle 
 severely criticises this. " We may suppose," he says, 
 *' that all things have fallen out accidentally just as 
 they would have done if they had been produced for some 
 end. Certain things have been preserved because they 
 had spontaneously acquired a fitting structure, while those 
 which were not so put together have perished and are 
 perishing, as Empedokles says of the oxen with human 
 faces." 3 ' This, according to Aristotle, leaves too much to 
 chance. One curious instance has been preserved. Verte- 
 bration was explained by saying that an early invertebrate 
 animal tried to turn round and broke its back in so 
 
 1 This is well put by Simplicius, De caelo, p. 587, 20, It is 5re rod 
 'NeiKOVs iweKparei Xoittoj' i] ^iXdTrjs . . . ^Tri r^s ^i\6t7]to$ o^v 6 'EyttTreSo/cX'^s 
 €K€iva elxev, ovx ws iiriKparo^arjs ijSr) rrjs ^iXdrrfTos, dXX' (is /4eXXoiv<r7/j 
 iTTiKpareTv. In Phys. p. 371, 33, he says the oxen with human heads 
 were Karh tt]v ttjs ^iKias apxfiv. 
 
 2 Cf. Plato, Symp. 189 e. 
 
 3 Arist. Phys. B, 8. 198 b 29 (R. P. 173 a). 
 
logy. 
 
 244 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 doing. This was a favourable variation and so survived. ^ 
 It should be noted that it clearly belongs to the period of 
 Strife, and not, hke the oxen with human heads, to that 
 of Love. The survival of the fittest was the law of 
 evolution in both periods^) 
 Physio 117. The distinction of the sexes was a result of the 
 differentiation brought about by Strife. Empedokles dif- 
 fered from the theory given by Parmenides in his Second 
 Part (§ 95) in holding that the warm element preponderated 
 in the male sex, and that males were conceived in the warmer 
 part of the uterus (fr. 65). The foetus was formed partly 
 from the male and partly from the female semen (fr. 63) : 
 and it was just the fact that the substance of a new being's 
 body was divided between the male and the female that 
 produced desire when the two were brought together by 
 sight (fr. 64). A certain S5nnmetry of the pores in the male 
 and female semen is necessary for procreation, and from 
 its absence Empedokles explained the sterility of mules. 
 The children resemble that parent who contributed most to 
 their formation. The influence of statues and pictures was 
 also noted, however, as modifying the appearance of the 
 offspring. Twins and triplets were due to a superabundance 
 and division of the semen. 2 
 
 Empedokles held that the foetus was enveloped in a 
 membrane, and that its formation began on the thirty-sixth 
 day and was complete on the forty-ninth. The heart was 
 formed first, the nails and such things last. Respiration 
 did not begin till the time of birth, when the fluids round 
 the foetus were withdrawn. Birth took place in the ninth 
 or seventh month, because the day had been originally nine 
 months long, and afterwards seven. Milk arises on the 
 tenth day of the eighth month (fr. 68). ^ 
 
 Death was the final separation by Strife of the fire and 
 
 1 Arist. De part. an. A, i. 640 a 19. 
 
 2 Aet. V. 10, I ; II, I ; 12, 2 ; 14, 2. Cf. Fredrich, Hippokratische 
 Untersuchungen, pp. 126 sqq. 
 
 8 Aet. V. 15, 3 ; 21, I {Dox. p. 190). 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 245 
 
 earth in the body, each of which had all along been striving 
 to '* reach its own kind." Sleep was a temporary separation 
 to a certain extent of the fiery element.^ At death the 
 animal is resolved into its elements, which either enter into 
 fresh combinations, or are permanently united with " their 
 own kind.** ^here can be no question here of an immortal 
 soul.3. 
 
 Even in life, we may see the attraction of like to Hke 
 operating in animals just as it did in the upward and down- 
 ward growth of plants. Hair is the same thing as foliage 
 (fr. 82) ; and, generally speaking, the fiery part of animals 
 tends upwards and the earthy downwards, though there 
 are exceptions, as may be seen in the case of certain shell- 
 fish (fr. 76), where the earthy part is above. These excep- 
 tions are only possible because there is still a great deal of 
 Love in the world. We also see the attraction of like for 
 like in the habits of different species of animals. Those 
 that have most fire in them fly up into the air ; those in 
 which earth preponderates take to the earth, as did the dog 
 which always sat upon a tile.^ Aquatic animals are those 
 in which water predominates. This does not, however, 
 apply to fishes, which are very fiery, and take to the water 
 to cool themselves.^ 
 
 Empedokles paid great attention to respiration, and his 
 explanation of it has been preserved in a continuous form 
 (fr. 100). We breathe, he held, through all the pores of the 
 skin, not merely through the organs of respiration. The 
 cause of the alternate inspiration and expiration of breath 
 was the movement of the blood from the heart to the surface 
 of the body and back again, which was explained by the 
 klepsydra. 
 
 The nutrition and growth of animals is, of course, to be 
 explained from the attraction of like to like. Each part 
 
 1 Aet. V. 25, 4 {Dox. p. 437). 
 
 » Aet. V. 19, 5 {Dox. p. 431). Cf. Eth. Eud. H, i. 1235 a 11. 
 
 3 Arist. De respir. 14. 477 a 32 ; Theophr. De causis plant, i. 21. 
 
tion. 
 
 246 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 of the body has pores into which the appropriate food will 
 fit. Pleasure and pain were derived from the absence or 
 presence of like elements, that is, of nourishment which 
 would fit the pores. Tears and sweat arose from a disturb- * 
 ance which curdled the blood ; they were, so to say, the 
 whey of the blood. ^ 
 Percep- 118. For the theory of perception held by Empedokles 
 we have the original words of Theophrastos : 
 
 Empedokles speaks in the same way of aU the senses, and 
 says that perception is due to the " effluences " fitting into the 
 passages of each sense. And that is why one cannot judge the 
 objects of another ; for the passages of some of themyire too 
 wide and those of others too narrow for the sensible p^'ect, so 
 that the latter either hold their course right through without 
 touching or cannot enter at aU. R. P. 177 b. 
 
 He tries, too, to explain the nature of sight. He says that the 
 interior of the eye consists of fire, while round about it is earth 
 and air,2 through which its rarity enab^ the fire to pass like the 
 light in lanterns (fr. 84). The passage?^ the fire and water are 
 arranged alternately ; through those of tne fire we perceive light 
 objects, through those of the water, dark ; each class of objects 
 fits into each class of passages, and the colours are carried to 
 the sight by effluence. R. P. ih. 
 
 But eyes are not aU composed in the same way ; some are 
 composed of like elements and some of opposite ; some have the 
 fire in the centre and some on the outside. That is why some 
 animals are keen-sighted by day and others by night. Those 
 which have less fire ^^keen-sighted in the daytime, for the fire 
 within is brought up -Hln equality by that without ; those which 
 have less of the opposite {i.e. water), by night, for then their 
 deficiency is supplemented. But, in the opposite case, each wiU 
 behave in the opposite manner. Those eyes in which fire pre- 
 dominates vy^iU be dazzled in the daytime, since the fire being 
 still further increased will stop up and occupy the pores of the 
 water. Those in which water predominates v^^U, he says, suffer; 
 
 1 Nutrition, Aet. v. 27, i ; pleasure and pain, Aet. iv. 9, 15 ; v. 28, i f 
 tears and sweat, v. 22, i. ^ 
 
 2 That is, watery vapour, not the elemental air or aid-qp (§ 107). It 
 identical with the " water" mentioned below. It is unnecessary, there^ 
 fore, to insert /cat ijbojp after irvp with Karsten and Diels. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 247 
 
 the same at night, for the fire will be obstructed by the water. 
 And this goes on till the water is separated off by the air, for in 
 each case it is the opposite which is a remedy. The best tempered 
 and the most excellent vision is one composed of both in 
 equal proportions. This is practically what he says about 
 sight. 
 
 Hearing, he holds, is produced by sound outside, when the 
 air moved by the voice sounds inside the ear ; for the sense of 
 hearing is a sort of bell sounding inside the ear, which he calls a 
 *' fleshy sprout.'* When the air is set in motion it strikes upon 
 the solid parts and produces a sound. ^ Smell, he holds, arises 
 from respiration, and that is why those smell most keenly whose 
 breath has the most violent motion, and why most smell comes 
 from sAtle and Hght bodies.^ As to touch and taste, he does 
 not lay Clown how nor by means of what they arise, except that 
 he gives us an explanation applicable to all, that sensation is 
 produced by adaptation to the pores. Pleasure is produced by 
 what is Uke in its elements and their mixture ; pain, by what is 
 opposite. R. P. ib. 
 
 And heaves a pi^sely similar account of thought and 
 ignorance. [Thought ^ses from what is like and ignorance from 
 what is unlike, thus implying that thought is the same, or nearly 
 the same, as perception?] For after enumerating how we know 
 each thing by means of itself, he adds, " for all things are 
 fashioned and fitted together out of these, and it is by these men 
 think and feel pleasure and pain " (fr. 107). And for this 
 reason we think chiefly with our blood, for in it of aU parts 
 of the body all the elements are most completely mingled. 
 R. P. 178. 
 
 All, then, in whom the mixture is eo^l or nearly so, and in 
 whom the elements are neither at too^eat intervals nor too 
 small or too large, are the wisest and have the most exact per- 
 ceptions ; and those who come next to them are wise in propor- 
 tion. Those who are in the opposite condition are the most 
 foolish. Those whose elements are separated by intervals and 
 rare are dull and laborious ; those in whom they are closely 
 packed and broken into minute particles are impulsive, they 
 attempt many things and finish few because of the rapidity with 
 which their blood moves. Those who have a well-proportioned 
 
 ^ Beare, p. 96, w. i. 2 Ibid. p. 133. 
 
248 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 mixture in some one part of their bodies will be clever in that 
 respect. That is why some are good orators and some good 
 artificers. The latter have a good mixture in their hands, 
 and the former in their tongues, and so with all other special 
 capacities. R. P. ih. 
 
 Perception, then, is due to the meeting of an element in 
 us with the same element outside. This takes place when 
 the pores of the organ of sense are neither too large nor too 
 small for the " effluences " which all things are constantly 
 giving off (fr. 89). Smell was explained by respiration. 
 The breath drew in along with it the small particles which 
 fit into the pores. Empedokles proved this by the example 
 of people with a cold in their head,^ who cannot smell, just 
 because they have a difficulty in breathing. We also see 
 from fr. loi that the scent of dogs was referred to in support 
 of the theory. Empedokles seems to have given no detailed 
 account of smell, and did not refer to touch at all. 2 Hearing 
 was explained by the motion of the air which struck upon the 
 cartilage inside the ear and made it swing and soimd like 
 a bell.3 
 
 The theory of vision * is more complicated ; and, as 
 Plato makes his Timaios adopt most of it, it is of great 
 importance in the history of philosophy. The eye was con- 
 ceived, as by Alkmaion (§ 96) ,5 to be composed of fire and 
 water. Just as in a lantern the flame is protected from the 
 wind by horn (fr. 84), so the fire in the iris is protected from 
 the water which surrounds it in the pupil by membranes 
 with very fine pores, so that, while the fire can pass out, 
 the water cannot get in. Sight is produced by the fire inside 
 the eye going forth to meet the object. J 
 
 Empedokles was aware, too, that " effluences," as he 
 called them, came from things to the eyes as well ; for he 
 defined colours as " effluences from forms (or ' things ') • 
 
 1 Aet. iv. 17, 2 [Dox. p. 407). Beare, p. 133. 
 
 2 Beare, pp. 161-3, 180-81. ^ md. pp. 95 sqq. 
 * Ibid. pp. 14 sqq. ^ Theophr. De sens. 26. 
 
EMPEDOKLES OF AKRAGAS 249 
 
 fitting into the pores and perceived." ^ It is not quite 
 clear how these two accounts of vision were reconciled, or 
 how far we are entitled to credit Empedokles with the 
 theory of Plato's Timaeus. The statements quoted seem 
 to imply something very like it. 2 
 
 Theophrastos tells us that Empedokles made no dis- 
 tinction between thought and perception, a remark already 
 made by Aristotle. ^ The chief seat of perception was the 
 blood, in which the four elements are most evenly mixed, 
 and especially the blood near the heart (fr. 105).* This 
 does not, however, exclude the idea that other parts of the 
 body may perceive also ; indeed, Empedokles held that all 
 things have their share of thought (fr. 103). But the blood 
 was specially sensitive because of its finer mixture.^ From 
 this it naturally follows that Empedokles adopted the view, 
 already maintained in the Second Part of the poem of Par- 
 menides (fr. 16), that our knowledge varies with the varjdng 
 constitution of our bodies (fr. 106). 
 
 119. The theoretical theology of Empedokles reminds Theology 
 us of Xenophanes, his practical religious teaching of Pytha- reUgion. 
 goras and the Orphics. ( We are told in the earlier part of 
 the poem that certain " gods " are composed of the ele- 
 ments ; and that therefore though they " Hve long lives " 
 they must pass away (fr. 21). The elements and the Sphere 
 are also called gods, but that is in quite another sense of the 
 word, and the elements do not pass away.i 
 
 If we turn to the religious teaching of the Purifications, 
 
 1 The definition is quoted from Gorgias in Plato, Men. 76 d 4. All 
 our MSS. have drroppoal o-x'»7/tiara}»', but Yen. T has in the margin yp. 
 XPV/^<^T<av, which may well be an old tradition. The Ionic for " things " 
 is xpiJ/^ciTa. See Diels, Empedokles und Gorgias^ p. 439. 
 
 2 See Beare, Elementary Cognition, p. 18. 
 
 3 Arist, De an. V, 3. 427 a 21. 
 
 * R, P. 178 a. This was the characteristic doctrine of the Sicilian 
 school, from whom it passed to Aristotle and the Stoics. Plato and 
 Hippokrates, on the other hand, adopted the view of Alkmaion (§ 97) 
 that the brain was. the seat of consciousness. At a later date, Philistion 
 of Syracuse, Plato's friend, substituted the xJ/vxi-Kdu wvevfia ("animal 
 spirits ") which circulated along with the blood. * Beare, p. 253. 
 
250 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 we find that everything turns on the doctrine of trans- 
 migration. On the general significance of this enough has 
 been said above (§ 42) ; the details given by Empedokles are 
 peculiar. According to a decree of Necessity, " daemons'* 
 who have sinned are forced to wander from their home in 
 heaven for three times ten thousand seasons (fr. 115). He 
 himself is such an exiled divinity, and has fallen from his 
 high estate because he put his trust in raving Strife. The 
 four elements toss him from one to the other with loathing ; 
 and so he has not only been a human being and a plant, 
 but even a fish. The only way to purify oneself from the 
 taint of original sin is by the cultivation of ceremonial 
 holiness, by purifications, and abstinence from animal 
 flesh. For the animals are our kinsmen (fr. 137), and it is 
 parricide to lay hands on them. ' In all this there are certain 
 points of contact with the cosmology. We have the 
 " mighty oath '* (fr. 115 ; cf. fr. 30), the four elements, 
 Hate as the source of original sin, and Kypris as queen in 
 the Golden Age (fr. 128). [But these points are not funda- 
 mental, and the cosmological system of Empedokles leaves 
 no room for an immortal soul, which is presupposed by the 
 Purifications. All through this period, there seems to have 
 been a gulf between men's religious beliefs, if they had any, 
 and their cosmological views. The few points of contact 
 we have mentioned may have been enough to hide this from 
 Empedokles himself. ~7 
 
CHAPTER VI 
 
 ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 
 
 120. All that Apollodoros tells us with regard to the date Date, 
 of Anaxagoras seems to rest on the authority of Demetrios 
 Phalereus, who said of him, in his Register o/Archons, that he 
 " began to be a philosopher " at Athens at the age of twenty, 
 in the archonship of KalHas or KalHades (480-79 B.c.).^ 
 This date was probably derived from a calculation based on 
 the philosopher's age at the time of his trial, which Demetrios 
 had every opportunity of learning from sources no longer 
 extant. Apollodoros inferred that Anaxagoras was bom 
 in 01. LXX. (500-496 B.C.), and he adds that he died at the 
 age of seventy-two in 01. LXXXVIII. i (428-27 B.c.).2 
 He doubtless thought it natural that he should not 
 survive Perikles, and that he should die the year Plato 
 was born.3 We have a further statement, of doubtful 
 origin, but probably due also to Demetrios, that Anaxagoras 
 lived at Athens for thirty years. If it is correct, we 
 get from about 480 to 450 B.C. as the time he lived there. 
 
 There can be no doubt that these dates are very nearly 
 ri^ht. Aristotle tells us * that Anaxagoras was older than 
 Empedokles, who was probably bom before 490 B.C. (§ 98) ; 
 
 ^ Diog. ii. 7 (R. P. 148). For the variation in the archon's name, see 
 Jacoby, p. 244, n. 1, and for the chronology generally, see A. E. Taylor 
 in Classical Quarterly, xi. 81 sqq,, whose arguments appear to me con- 
 vincing. 
 
 2 We must read dySorjKoaTrjs with Scahger to make the figures come 
 right. ^ On the statements of Apollodoros, see Jacoby, pp. 244 sqq, 
 
 * Arist. Met. A, 3. 984 a 11 (R. P. 150 a). 
 
 251 
 
 ^ 
 
252 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 and Theophrastos said ^ that Empedokles was born " not 
 long after Anaxagoras/' Demokritos, too, said that he 
 himself was a young man in the old age of Anaxagoras, and 
 he must have been born about 460 B.C. 2 
 Early life. 121. Anaxagoras was from Klazomenai, and Theophras- 
 tos tells us that his father's name was Hegesiboulos.^ The 
 tradition was that he neglected his possessions to follow 
 science.* It is certain, at any rate, that already in the 
 fourth century he was regarded as the type of the man who 
 leads the " theoretic life." ^ Of course the story of his 
 contempt for worldly goods was seized on later by the 
 historical noveHst and tricked out with the usual apoph- 
 thegms. These do not concern us here. 
 
 One incident belonging to the early manhood of Anaxa- 
 goras is recorded, namely, the fall of a huge meteoric stone 
 into the Aigospotamos in 468-67 b.c.^ Our authorities tell 
 us he predicted this phenomenon, which is plainly absurd. 
 But we shall see reason to believe that it may have occa- 
 sioned one of his most striking departures from the earlier 
 cosmology, and led to his adoption of the very view for 
 which he was condemned at Athens. At all events, the fall 
 of the stone made a profound impression at the time, and 
 it was still shown to tourists in the days of Pliny and 
 Plutarch-7 
 
 1 Phys. Op. fr. 3 {Dox. p. 477), ap. Simpl. Phys. p. 25, 19 (R. P. 162 e). 
 
 2 Diog. ix. 41 (R. P. 187). On the date of Demokritos, see Chap. IX. 
 
 § 171- 
 
 3 Phys. Op. fr. 4 {Dox. p. 478), repeated by the doxographers. 
 
 * Plato, Hipp. ma. 283 a, rovvavrlov yhp 'Ava^aydpg. (paa-l (ru/xjS^vai 
 ■^ Vfuv KaTa\ei(f)d^PTi>)v yhp aur^J iroWQu XPVI^<^'''<^'^ KarafxeXTja-aL Kal diroX^aai 
 iravra' ovto}S airrbv dvbrjTa <T0(p[^ecr6ai. Cf. Plut. Per. i6. 
 
 6 Arist. Eth. Nic. K, 9. 1179 a 13. Cf, Eth. Eud^ A, 4. 1215 b 6 and 
 15, 1216 a 10. 
 
 « Diog. ii. 10 (R. P. 149 a). Pliny, N.H. ii. 149, gives the date as Ol. 
 LXXVIII. 2 ; and Eusebios gives it under 01. LXXVIII. 3. But cf, 
 Marm. Par. 57, d0' o5 iv Aiybs iroTa/noTs 6 Xidos iireae . . . h-rj HHII, 
 &PXOVTOS 'AdrjVTjcri Qeayeyldov, which is 468-67 B.C. The text of Diog 
 ii. II is corrupt. For suggested restorations, see Jacoby, p. 244, n. 2; 
 and Diels, Vors. 46 a i, 
 
 ' Pliny, loc. cit., " qui lapis etiam nunc ostenditur magnitudine vehi|| 
 colore adusto," Cf. Plut. Lys. 12, koX deUvvrai . . . ^rt vvv. 
 
 m 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 253 
 
 122. The doxographers speak of Anaxagoras as the pupil Relation 
 of Anaximenes.i This can hardly be correct ; Anaximenes *°^^® 
 most probably died before Anaxagoras was born. But it is school. 
 not enough to say that the statement arose from the fact 
 that the name of Anaxagoras followed that of Anaximenes 
 in the Successions. We have its original source in a fragment 
 of Theophrastos himself, which states that Anaxagoras had 
 been "an associate of the philosophy of Anaximenes." ^ 
 Now this expression has a very distinct meaning if we accept 
 the view as to " schools " of science set forth in the Intro- 
 duction (§ XIV.). It means that the old Ionic school sur- 
 vived the destruction of Miletos in 494 B.C., and continued 
 to flourish in the other cities of Asia. It means, further, 
 that it produced no man of distinction after its third great 
 representative, and that " the philosophy of Anaximenes " 
 was still taught by whoever was now at the head of the 
 society. 
 
 At this point, then, it may be well to indicate briefly the 
 conclusions we shall come to in the next few chapters with 
 regard to the development of philosophy during the first 
 half of the fifth century B.C. We shall find that, while the 
 old Ionic school was still capable of training great men, it 
 was now powerless to keep them. Anaxagoras went his own 
 way ; Melissos and Leukippos, though they still retained 
 enough of the old views to bear witness to the source of their 
 inspiration, were too strongly influenced by the Eleatic 
 dialectic to remain content with the theories of Anaximenes. 
 It was left to second-rate minds hke Diogenes to champion 
 the orthodox system, while third-rate minds like Hippon 
 
 ^ Cicero, De nat. d. i. 26 (after Philodemos), " Anaxagoras qui accepit 
 ab Anaximene disciplinam {i.e. di'/jKovae) ; Diog, i, 13 (R. P. 4) and ii. 6; 
 Strabo, xiv. p. 645, KXa^o/n^uios 8' ^v avT)p iin<pavr]i 'Ava^ayopas 6 <pv<rcK6s, 
 'Ava^i/x^vovs o/iiXTjTT^s ; Euseb. P.E. p. 504 ; [Galen] Hist. Phil. 3 ; 
 Augustine, De civ. Dei, viii. 2. 
 
 2 Phys. Op. fr. 4 [Dox. p. 478), 'Ava^ayopas /nh ykp "B.yri<n^oi\ov 
 KXaJi'ofjLivios Koipuvrjaas ttjs 'Ava^ifx^vovs (pikoa-ocplas ktX. In his fifth edition 
 (p- 973. w. 2) Zeller adopts the view given in the text, and confirms it 
 by comparing the very similar statement as to Leukippos, Koii/uv/ja-as 
 UapfievLdri ttjs <pL\oao<f>las. See below. Chap. IX. § 172. 
 
254 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 of Samos went back to the cruder theory of Thales. The 
 details of this anticipatory sketch will become clearer as we 
 go on ; for the present, it is only necessary to call the 
 reader's attention to the fact that the old Ionic Philosophy 
 now forms a sort of background to our story, just as Orphic 
 and Pythagorean religious ideas have done in the preceding 
 chapters. 
 Anaxa- 123. Auaxagoras was the first philosopher to take up 
 
 Ath?ns* ^^s abode at Athens. We are not informed what brought 
 him there in the year of Salamis. He was, however, a 
 Persian subject ; for Klazomenai had been reduced after 
 the suppression of the Ionian Revolt, and it seems likely 
 enough that he was in the Persian army.^ 
 
 Anaxagoras is said to have been the teacher of Perikles, 
 and the fact is placed beyond the reach of doubt by the 
 testimony of Plato. In the Phaedrus 2 he makes Sokrates 
 say : " For all arts that are great, there is need of talk and 
 discussion on the parts of natural science that deal with 
 things on high ; for that seems to be the source which in- 
 spires high-mindedness and effectiveness in every direction. 
 Perikles added this very acquirement to his original gifts. 
 He fell in, it seems, with Anaxagoras, who was a scientific 
 man ; and, satiating himself with the theory of things on 
 high, and having attained to a knowledge of the true nature 
 of mind and intellect, which was just what the discourses 
 of Anaxagoras were mainly about, he drew from that source 
 whatever was of a nature to further him in the art of speech.*' 
 This clearly means that Perikles associated with Anaxagoras 
 before he became a prominent poHtician. So too Isokrates 
 says that Perikles was the pupil of two ** sophists," Anaxa- 
 
 1 That might explain the charge of " Medism " which was perhaps 
 brought against him at his trial (§ 124). It is also, perhaps, significant 
 that Apollodoros (and probably Demetrios of Phaleron) spoke of him as 
 twenty years old Kara tt]v S^/j^ou did^aacv, which means, of course, the 
 crossing of the Hellespont, and would hardly be relevant if Anaxagoras 
 had not been with Xerxes then. It is certainly difficult to see what else 
 could bring a young Klazomenian to Athens at that date. 
 
 2 270 a (R. P. 148 c). 
 
 i 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 255 
 
 goras and Damon. ^ There can be no doubt that the teaching 
 of Damon belongs to the youth of Perikles,^ and it is to be 
 inferred that the same is true of that of Anaxagoras. 
 
 A more difficult question is the alleged relation of 
 Euripides to Anaxagoras. The oldest authority for it is 
 Alexander of Aitolia, poet and hbrarian, who Hved at the 
 court of Ptolemy Philadelphos [c. 280 B.C.). He referred to 
 Euripides as the " nursling of brave Anaxagoras." ^ The 
 famous fragment on the blessedness of the scientific life 
 might just as well refer to any other cosmologist as to Anaxa- 
 goras, and indeed suggests more naturally a thinker of a 
 more primitive type.* On the other hand, it is likely enough 
 that Anaxagoras did not develop his system all at once, 
 and he doubtless began by teaching that of Anaximenes. 
 Besides there is one fragment which distinctly expounds the 
 central thought of Anaxagoras, and could hardly be referred 
 to any one else.^ 
 
 124. It is clear that, if we adopt the chronology of The trial. 
 Demetrios of Phaleron, the trial of Anaxagoras must be 
 placed early in the political career of Perikles.^ That is 
 the tradition preserved by Satyros, who says that the 
 
 * Isokrates, Hepl avriddaeios, 235, UepiKXijs 8^ dvoiu {aocpiaraiu) iyhero 
 fiadrjT'/jS, ' Ava^ayopov re toD KXa^o/xeulov Kal Adfiuvos. 
 
 2 Damon (or Damonides) must have been politically active about 
 460 B.C. (Meyer, Gesch. des Altert. iii. 567 ; Wilamowitz, Aristoteles und 
 Athen, i. 134), so that he must have been born about 500 B.C. He was 
 ostracised before 443 B.C. according to Meyer, and an ostrakon with 
 the name of Damon son of Damonides has been found (Bruckner, Arch. 
 Anz., 191 4, p. 95). If we suppose that he was ostracised in 445 and re- 
 turned in 435, his subsequent relations with Sokrates are quite natural. 
 Plato can hardly have known him personally. On the whole subject, 
 see Rosenberg in Neue Jahrb. xxxv. p. 205 sqq. 
 
 3 Gell. XV. 20, " Alexander autem Aetolus hos de Euripide versus 
 composuit " ; 6 5' ' Ava^ay 6pov Tpb(f>L^os Xtt'oO (so Valckenaer for apxO'^ov) 
 kt\. * See Introd, p. 10, n. 3. 6 r. p. j^q b. 
 
 6 The trial of Anaxagoras is generally referred to the period just before 
 the Peloponnesian War. That is how it was represented by Ephoros 
 (reproduced by Diod. xii. 38), and the same account is followed by 
 Plutarch (F. Per. 32). The pragmatic character of the chronology of 
 Ephoros is, however, sufficiently estabUshed, and we cannot infer any- 
 thing from it. Sotion, who made Kleon the accuser, must also have 
 assumed a late date for the trial. 
 
256 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 accuser was Thoukydides, son of Melesias, and that the 
 charge was impiety and Medism.^ As Thoukydides was 
 ostracised in 443 B.C., that would make it probable that the 
 trial of Anaxagoras took place about 450 B.C., and would 
 bring it into connexion with the ostracism of the other 
 teacher of Perikles, Damon. 2 If that is so, we understand 
 at once why Plato never makes Sokrates meet with 
 Anaxagoras. He^ had handed his school over to Archelaos 
 before Sokrates was old enough to take an interest in 
 scientific theories. ^ We do learn from Plato, however, 
 what the charge of impiety was based on. It was that 
 Anaxagoras taught the sun was a red-hot stone, and 
 the moon earth,* and we shall see that he certainly did 
 hold these views (§ 133). For the rest, the most Hkely 
 account is that he was got out of prison and sent away 
 by Perikles. 5 We know that such things were possible at 
 Athens. 
 
 Driven from his adopted home, Anaxagoras naturally 
 went back to Ionia, where at least he would be free to teach 
 what he pleased. He settled at Lampsakos, a colony of 
 Miletos, and we shall see reason to believe that he founded 
 a school there. If so, he must have lived at Lampsakos for 
 some time before his death. ^ The Lampsakenes erected an 
 altar to his memory in their market-place, dedicated to 
 
 ^ Diog. ii. 12, SdiTvpoj 5' iu tols "BIols virb QovKvdidov tprjalv ela-axdTJpaL ttjp 
 8lKr]Vy ayTiTToXirevofiivov ry Ile/Dt/cXet' Kai oif jxbvov da-e^eias dWd Kai firidiafiov' 
 KoX dirSpTa KaTadLKaadrjvai davdrip. 
 
 2 This would be in complete agreement with the statement that 
 Anaxagoras lived thirty years at Athens (p. 251). For the ostracism of 
 Damon, see p. 255, n. 2. 
 
 5 The well-known passage of the Phaedo (97 b 8 sqq.) distinctly 
 implies that Anaxagoras had left Athens when Sokrates was still quite 
 young. He hears of his doctrine only at second-hand (from Archelaos ?) 
 and he at once procures the book of Anaxagoras and reads it. If Anaxa- 
 goras had still been at Athens, it would have been a simple matter for 
 Sokrates to seek him out and question him, and it would have made an 
 excellent subject for a Platonic dialogue. The fact that Plato does make 
 Sokrates meet Parmenides and Zeno and does not make him meet Anaxa- 
 goras is clearly significant. * Apol. 26 d. 
 
 6 Plut. Nic. 23 (R. P. 148 c). Cf. Per. 32 (R. P. 148). 
 « See the account of Archelaos in Chap. X. § 191. 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 257 
 
 Mind and Truth ; and the anniversary of his death was long 
 kept as a hoHday for school-children, it was said at his own 
 request. 1 
 
 125. Diogenes includes Anaxagoras in his Hst of philo- writings. 
 sophers who left only a single book, and he has also preserved 
 the accepted criticism of it, namely, that it was written " in 
 a lofty and agreeable style.'* 2 There is no evidence of any 
 weight to set against this testimony, which comes ultimately 
 from the librarians of Alexandria.^ The story that Anaxa- 
 goras wrote a treatise on perspective as applied to scene- 
 painting is most improbable ; * and the statement that he 
 composed a work dealing with the quadrature of the circle 
 is a misunderstanding of an expression in Plutarch.^ We 
 learn from the passage in the Apology, referred to above, 
 that the works of Anaxagoras could be bought at Athens 
 for a drachma ; and that the book was of some length may 
 be gathered from the way in which Plato makes Sokrates 
 go on to speak of it.^ In the sixth century a.d. Simplicius 
 had access to a copy, doubtless in the library of the Academy; 
 and it is to him we owe the preservation of all our fragments, 
 with one or two very doubtful exceptions. Unfortunately 
 his quotations seem to be confined to the First Book, that 
 dealing with general principles, so that we are left somewhat 
 in the dark as to the treatment of details. 
 
 1 The oldest authority for the honours paid to Anaxagoras is Alkidamas, 
 the pupil of Gorgias, who said these were still kept up in his own time. 
 Arist. Rhet. B, 23. 1398 b 15. 
 
 2 Diog. i. 16; ii. 6 (R. P. 5; 153). 
 
 * Schaubach {An. Claz. Fragm. p. 57) fabricated a work entitled rh 
 irpbs Kexi-veov out of the pseudo- Aristotelian De plantis, 817 a 27. But the 
 Latin version of Alfred, which is the original of the Greek, has simply et 
 ideo dicit lechineon ; and this seems to be due to failure to make out the 
 Arabic text from which the Latin was derived. Cf. Meyer, Gesch. d. 
 Bot. i. 60. 
 
 * Vitruvius, vii. pr. 11. A forger, seeking to decorate his production 
 with a great name, would think at once of the philosopher who was said 
 to have taught Euripides. 
 
 6 Plut. De exilio, 607 f. The words merely mean that he used to 
 draw figures relating to the quadrature of the circle on the prison floor. 
 
 6 Apol. 26 d-e. The expression ^i^Xia perhaps implies that it filled 
 more than one roll. 
 
 17 
 
258 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The Frag- 1 26. I givc the fragments according to the text and 
 
 ments. . r t\' ^ 
 
 arrangement of Diels : 
 
 (i) All things were together, infinite both in number and in 
 smallness ; for the small too was infinite. And, when all things 
 were together, none of them could be distinguished for their 
 smallness. For air and aether prevailed over all things, being 
 both of them infinite ; for amongst all things these are the greatest 
 both in quantity and size.^ R. P. 151. 
 
 (2) For air and aether are separated off from the mass that 
 surrounds the world, and the surrounding mass is infinite in 
 quantity. R. P. ib. 
 
 (3) Nor is there a least of what is small, but there is always a 
 smaller ; for it cannot be that what is should cease to be by being 
 cut. 2 But there is also always something greater than what is 
 great, and it is equal to the small in amount, and, compared with 
 itself, each thing is both great and small. R. P. 159 a. 
 
 (4) And since these things are so, we must suppose that there 
 are contained many things and of all sorts in the things that are 
 uniting, seeds of all things, with all sorts of shapes and colours 
 and savours (R. P. ib.), and that men have been formed in them, 
 and the other animals that have hfe, and that these men have 
 inhabited cities and cultivated fields as with us ; and that they 
 have a sun and a moon and the rest as with us ; and that their 
 earth brings forth for them many things of all kinds of which 
 they gather the best together into their dwellings, and use them 
 (R. P. 160 b). Thus much have I said with regard to separating 
 off, to show that it will not be only with us that things are 
 separated off, but elsewhere too. 
 
 But before they were separated off, when all things were 
 together, not even was any colour distinguishable ; for the 
 mixture of all things prevented it — of the moist and the dry, 
 and the warm and the cold, and the fight and the dark, and of 
 much earth that was in it, and of a multitude of innumerable 
 seeds in no way Hke each other. For none of the other things 
 
 ^ Simplicius tells us this was at the beginning of Book I. The 
 sentence quoted by Diog. ii. 6 (R. P. 153) is not a fragment of Anaxagoras, 
 but a summary, like the TrdpTa pel ascribed to Herakleitos (Chap. III. 
 p. 146). 
 
 * Zeller's topl^ still seems to me a convincing correction of the 
 rd ii-q, which Diels retains. 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 259 
 
 either is like any other. And these things being so, we must 
 hold that all things are in the whole. R. P. 151.^ 
 
 (5) And those things having been thus decided, we must 
 know that all of them are neither more nor less ; for it is not 
 possible for them to be more than all, and all are always equal. 
 R. P. 151. 
 
 (6) And since the portions of the great and of the small are 
 equal in amount, for this reason, too, all things will be in every- 
 thing ; nor is it possible for them to be apart, but all things have 
 a portion of everything. Since it is impossible for there to be a 
 least thing, they cannot be separated, nor come to be by them- 
 selves ; but they must be now, just as they were in the beginning, 
 ail together. And in all things many things are contained, and 
 an equal number both in the greater and in the smaller of the 
 things that are separated off. 
 
 (7) . . . So that we cannot know the number of the things 
 that are separated off, either in word or deed. 
 
 (8) The things that are in one world are not divided nor cut 
 off from one another with a hatchet, neither the warm from the 
 cold nor the cold from the warm. R. P. 155 e. 
 
 (9) . . . as these things revolve and are separated off by 
 the force and swiftness. And the swiftness makes the force. 
 Their swiftness is not Hke the swiftness of any of the things that 
 are now among men, but in every way many times as swift. 
 
 (10) How can hair come from what is not hair, or flesh from 
 what is not flesh ? R. P. 155, f, n. i. 
 
 (11) In everything there is a portion of everything except 
 Nous, and there are some things in which there is Nous also. 
 R. P. 160 b. 
 
 (12) All other things partake in a portion of everything, 
 while Nous is infinite and self-ruled, and is mixed with nothing, 
 but is alone, itself by itself. For if it were not by itself, but were 
 mixed with anything else, it would partake in all things if it were 
 mixed with any ; for in everything there is a portion of every- 
 thing, as has been said by me in what goes before, and the things 
 mixed with it would hinder it, so that it would have power over 
 nothing in the same way that it has now being alone by itself. 
 For it is the thinnest of all things and the purest, and it has all 
 
 1 I had already pointed out in the first edition that Simplicius quotes 
 this three times as a continuous fragment, and that we are not entitled 
 to break it up. Diels now prints it as a single passage. 
 
26o EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 knowledge about everything and the greatest strength ; and 
 Nous has power over all things, both greater and smaller, that 
 have life. And Nous had power over the whole revolution, so 
 that it began to revolve in the beginning. And it began to 
 revolve first from a small beginning ; but the revolution now 
 extends over a larger space, and will extend over a larger still. 
 And all the things that are mingled together and separated off 
 and distinguished are all known by Nous. And Nous set in 
 order all things that were to be, and all things that were and are 
 not now and that are, and this revolution in which now revolve 
 the stars and the sun and the moon, and the air and the aether 
 that are separated off. And this revolution caused the separat- 
 ing off, and the rare is separated off from the dense, the warm 
 from the cold, the light from the dark, and the dry from the 
 moist. And there are many portions in many things. But no 
 thing is altogether separated off nor distinguished from anything 
 else except Nous. And all Nous is alike, both the greater and 
 the smaller ; while nothing else is Hke anything else, but each 
 single thing is and was most manifestly those things of which it 
 has most in it. R. P. 155. 
 
 (13) And when Nous began to move things, separating off 
 took place from all that was moved, and so much as Nous set in 
 motion was all separated. And as things were set in motion and 
 separated, the revolution caused them to be separated much more. 
 
 (14) And Nous, which ever is, is certainly there, where every- 
 thing else is, in the surrounding mass, and in what has been 
 united with it and separated off from it.^ 
 
 (15) The dense and the moist and the cold and the dark came 
 together where the earth is now, while the rare and the warm 
 and the dry (and the bright) went out towards the further part 
 of the aether.2 R. P. 156. 
 
 (16) From these as they are separated off earth is soUdified ; 
 for from mists water is separated off, and from water earth. 
 From the earth stones are solidified by the cold, and these rush 
 outwards more than water. R. P. 156. 
 
 (17) The Hellenes follow a wrong usage in speaking of coming 
 
 1 Simplicius gives fr. 14 thus (p. 157, 5) : 6 8^ povs 6<xa iarl re Kapra 
 Kai vvv iariv. Diels now reads 6 8k vovs, 8s d<e^> eaTL, rb Kdpra Kal vvv eariv. 
 The correspondence of ael . . . /cat vvv is strongly in favour of this. 
 
 2 On the text of fr. 15, see R. P. 156 a. I have followed Schorn in 
 adding /cat to Xafiirpov from Hippolytos. 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 261 
 
 into being and passing away ; for nothing comes into being or 
 passes away, but there is mingHng and separation of things 
 that are. So they would be right to call coming into being 
 mixture, and passing away separation. R. P. 150. 
 
 (18) It is the sun that puts brightness into the moon. 
 
 (19) We caU rainbow the reflexion of the sun in the clouds. 
 Now it is a sign of storm ; for the water that flows round the 
 cloud causes wind or pours down in rain. 
 
 (20) With the rise of the Dogstar (?) men begin the harvest ; 
 with its setting they begin to till the fields. It is hidden for 
 forty days and nights. 
 
 (21) From the weakness of our senses we are not able to judge 
 the truth. 
 
 {21a) What appears is a vision of the unseen. 
 (216) (We can make use of the lower animals) because we 
 use our own experience and memory and wisdom and art. 
 
 (22) What is called " birds' milk " is the white of the egg. 
 
 127. The system of Anaxagoras, like that of Empedokles, Anaxa- 
 aimed at reconciling the Eleatic doctrine that corporeal his^p^r^^ 
 substance is unchangeable with the existence of a world ^^cessors. 
 which everywhere presents the appearance of coming into 
 being and passing away. The conclusions of Parmenides 
 are frankly accepted and restated. Nothing can be added 
 to all things ; for there cannot be more than all, and all is 
 always equal (fr. 5). Nor can anything pass away. What 
 men commonly call coming into being and passing away 
 is really mixture and separation (fr. 17). 
 
 It is in every way probable that Anaxagoras derived his 
 theory of mixture from his younger contemporary, whose 
 poem may have been published before his own treatise.^ 
 In any case, we have seen that the opinions of the latter 
 were known at Athens before the middle of the fifth century. 
 We have seen how Empedokles sought to save the world of 
 
 1 I do not now think, however, that this is the meaning of the words 
 TOis ^pyois varepos in Arist. Met. A, 3. 984 a 12 (R. P. 150 a). At any 
 rate Theophrastos did not take them so ; for he imitates the passage in 
 speaking of Plato {Dox. 484, 19), of whom he says Toi^rots iTnyevbixevos JIXAtwv 
 TTj fx^v do^y Kal Ty dvpdfxet irporepos, rots 8k xP^^ols vcrrepos. It seems that he 
 understood the Aristotehan formula as "inferior in his achievements." 
 
262 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 appearance by maintaining that the opposites — hot and 
 cold, moist and dry — were things, each one of which was 
 real in the Parmenidean sense. Anaxagoras regarded this 
 as inadequate. Everything changes into everything else,^ 
 the things of which the world is made are not " cut off with 
 a hatchet " (fr. 8) in this way. On the contrary, the true 
 formula must be : There is a portion of everything in every- 
 thing (fr. ii). 
 "Every- 128. A part of the argument by which Anaxagoras 
 
 in^every- sought to provc this poiut has been preserved in a corrupt 
 thing." iorm by x\etios, and Diels has recovered some of the original 
 words from the schoUast on St. Gregory Nazianzene. " We 
 use a simple nourishment," he said, " when we eat the fruit 
 of Demeter or drink water. But how can hair be made of 
 what is not hair, or flesh of what is not flesh ? " (fr. lo).^ 
 That is just the sort of question the early Milesians must 
 have asked, only the physiological interest has now definitely 
 replaced the meteorological. We shall find a similar train 
 of reasoning in Diogenes of ApoUonia (f r. 2) . 
 
 The statement that there is a portion of everything in 
 everything, is not to be understood as referring simply to 
 the original mixture of things before the formation of the 
 worlds (fr. i). On the contrary, even now " all things are 
 together," and everything, however small and however 
 great, has an equal number of " portions " (fr. 6). A 
 smaller particle of matter could only contain a smaller 
 number of portions, if one of those portions ceased to be ; 
 but if anything is, in the full Parmenidean sense, it is 
 impossible that mere division should make it cease to be 
 (fr. 3). Matter is infinitely divisible ; for there is no least 
 thing, any more than there is a greatest. But however 
 great or small a body may be, it contains just the same 
 number of '* portions," that is, a portion of everything. 
 129. What are these " things " of which everything 
 
 1 Arist. Phys. A, 4. 187 b i (R. P. 155 a). 
 
 2 Aet, i. 3, 5 {Dox. p. 279). See R. P. 155 f and «. i. I read Kapirbv 
 with Usener. 
 
 The 
 portions. 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 263 
 
 contains a portion ? It once was usual to represent the 
 theory of Anaxagoras as if he had said that wheat, for 
 instance, contained small particles of flesh, blood, bones, 
 and the like ; but we have just seen that matter is infinitely 
 divisible (fr. 3), and that there are as many " portions " in 
 the smallest particle as in the greatest (fr. 6). That is fatal 
 to the old view. However far we carry division, we can 
 never reach anything " unmixed," so there can be no such 
 thing as a particle of simple nature, however minute. 
 
 This difficulty can only be solved in one way.^ In fr. 8 
 the examples given of things which are not " cut off from 
 one another with a hatchet '* are the hot and the cold ; and 
 elsewhere (frs. 4, 15), mention is made of the other traditional 
 " opposites." Aristotle says that, if we suppose the first 
 principles to be infinite, they may either be one in kind, as 
 with Demokritos, or opposite. 2 Simplicius, following Por- 
 phyry and Themistios, refers the latter view to Anaxagoras ; ^ 
 and Aristotle himself implies that the opposites of Anaxa- 
 goras had as much right to be called first principles as the 
 " homoeomeries." * 
 
 It is of those opposites, then, and not of the different 
 forms of matter, that everything contains a portion. Every 
 
 ^ See Tannery, Science hellene, pp. 283 sqq. I still think that Tannery's 
 interpretation is substantially right, though his statement of it requires 
 some modification. It is, no doubt, difficult for us to think of the hot 
 and cold, dry and wet as " things " (xpT^/xara) ; but we must remember 
 that, even when the notion of quahty (7rot6Tijs) had been defined, this 
 way of thinking survived. Galen {De nat. Jac. i. 2, 4) is still quite clear 
 on the point that it is the qualities which are eternal. He says ol 8^ 
 Tives elv0,L fikv iv ai/ry {ry VTroKeLfiivri ovaig) ^ovKovrai ret? iroLbrriTas, 
 d/J.€Ta^\7)T0Vi 8^ Kal arpiirTovi i^ aluivos, kuI ras (paivofi^vas ravras dXXotwtreis tt/ 
 SiaKpLcrei re Kal crvyKpiaeL yiyveadai (paaiu ws 'Ava^ayopas. 
 
 2 Arist. Phys. A, 2. 184 b 21, ij oihus Ibairep Atj/xSkpltos, t6 yho% ev, 
 crx'>?/^aTt 5^ ij e'tdei 8ia(p€po}jcra$, fj Kal ivaprlas. 
 
 3 Phys. p. 44, I. He goes on to refer to depfjtdTrrras . . . Kal 
 \pvxpOTT)Tas ^TjpdTTjTOLS T€ Kal vypoTrjTOLS fMaudrriTds re Kal TrvKvSrTjTas Kal tols 
 dXXas Kara TrocoTTjTa ipauTiorrjTas. He observes, however, that Alexander 
 rejected this interpretation and took SLa<pepo6<ras ^ Kal evavHas closely 
 together as both referring to Demokritos. 
 
 * Phys. A, 4. 187 a 25, rbv ixh {' kva^aybpav) direcpa iroieLV to, re o/xoLOfiepij 
 Kal rdvavTia. Aristotle's own theory only differs from this in so far as 
 he makes vXt) prior to the evavrla. 
 
264 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 particle, however large or however small, contains every 
 one of those opposite qualities. That which is hot is also 
 to a certain extent cold. Even snow, Anaxagoras affirmed, 
 was black ; ^ that is, even the white contains a certain 
 portion of the opposite quality. It is enough to indicate 
 the connexion of this with the views of Herakleitos (§ 80). 2 
 Seeds. 130. The difference, then, between the theory of Anaxa- 
 
 goras and that of Empedokles is this. Empedokles had 
 taught that, if you divide the various things which make up 
 this world, and in particular the parts of the body, such as 
 flesh, bones, and the hke, far enough, you come to the four 
 '* roots " or elements, which are, accordingly, the ultimate 
 reahty. Anaxagoras held that, however far you may divide 
 any of these things — and they are infinitely divisible — you 
 never come to a part so small that it does not contain 
 portions of all the opposites. On the other hand, everything 
 can pass into everything else just because the " seeds," as 
 he called them, of each form of matter contain a portion of 
 everything, that is, of all the opposites, though in different 
 proportions. If we are to use the word " element " at all 
 it is these seeds that are the elements in the system of 
 Anaxagoras. 
 
 Aristotle expresses this by saying that Anaxagoras 
 regards the ofjuoLo/jueprj as o-roLx^la.^ We have seen that 
 the term arroi'xelov is of later date than Anaxagoras, and it 
 
 1 Sext. Pyrrh. i. 33 (R. P. 161 b). 
 
 2 The connexion was already noted by the eclectic Herakleitean to 
 whom I attribute Hepl dLairris, i. 3-4 (see above. Chap. III. p. 150, «. 2). 
 Cf. the words e'x^t 5^ dir' a,\\'r}Xo}v to ixkv irvp dirb tov {/Saros t6 vyp6f ^vi 
 yap iv irvpl vypdrrjs ' rb 5e iiSwp (Xtto tov irvpos to ^rjpou ' ivi yap Kal 
 iidaTL ^Tjpov. 
 
 « Arist. De gen. corr. A, x, 314 a 18, 6 ij^v yhp (Anaxagoras) tH 
 OfJLOLOixeprj <rroiXf'a Ti6r}(nv, olov Scttovp Kal adpKa /cat fx-veXSv, Kal tQv &\\wv <5lf 
 ^Kao-Tip avvfbvvfxov Tb /xepos i<xTip. This was, of course, repeated by 
 Theophrastos and the doxographers ; but it is to be noted that Aetios^ 
 supposing as he does that Anaxagoras himself used the term, gives it ai^ 
 entirely wrong meaning. He says that the dfioiofiepeiaL were so called 
 from the likeness of the particles of the Tpo<f)ri to those of the body {Dox\ 
 279 a 21 ; R. P. 155 f). Lucretius, i. 830 sqq. (R. P. 150 a) has a similai^ 
 account of the matter, derived from Epicurean sources. Obviously, it 
 cannot be reconciled with what Aristotle says. 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 265 
 
 is natural to suppose that the word o/jLoto/jueprj is also only 
 Aristotle's name for the " seeds." In his own system, the 
 oixoiofieprj are intermediate between the elements [a-roix^la), 
 of which they are composed, and the organs {opyava), which 
 are composed of them. The heart cannot be divided into 
 hearts, but the parts of flesh are flesh. That being so, 
 Aristotle's statement is quite intelligible from his own point 
 of view, but there is no reason for supposing that Anaxa- 
 goras expressed himself in that particular way. All we 
 are entitled to infer is that he said the " seeds," which he 
 substituted for the " roots " of Empedokles, were not the 
 opposites in a state of separation, but each contained a 
 portion of them all. If Anaxagoras had used the term 
 " homoeomeries " himself, it would be very strange that 
 SimpUcius should quote no fragment containing it. 
 
 The difference between the two systems may also be 
 regarded from another point of view. Anaxagoras was not 
 obliged by his theory to regard the elements of Empedokles 
 as primary, a view to which there were obvious objections, 
 especiaUy in the case of earth. He explained them in quite 
 another way. Though everything has a portion of every- 
 thing in it, things appear to be that of which there is most 
 in them (fr. 12 sub fin.). We may say, then, that Air is 
 that in which there is most cold. Fire that in which there is 
 most heat, and so on, without giving up the view that there 
 is a portion of cold in the fire and a portion of heat in the 
 air.i The great masses which Empedokles had taken for 
 elements are really vast collections of all manner of " seeds." 
 Each of them is, in fact, a irava-irepfiia.'^ 
 
 1 Cf. above, p. 263. 
 
 2 Arist. De gen. corr. A, i. 314 a 29. The word iravinrepfjt.ia was used 
 by Demokritos (Arist. De an. A, 2. 404 a 8 ; R. P. 200), and it occurs in the 
 Uepi diair-qs [loc. cit.). It seems natural to suppose that it was used by 
 Anaxagoras himself, as he used the term (nr^pfiara. Much difdculty has 
 been caused by the apparent inclusion of Water and Fire among the 
 ofioiofxepi] in Arist. Met. A, 3. 984 a 11 (R. P. 150 a). Bonitz under- 
 stands the words Kaddirep vdwp ^ irvp to mean " as we have just seen that 
 Fire and Water do in the system of Empedokles." In any case, Kaddirep 
 goes closely with ovtcj, and the general sense is that Anaxagoras appHes 
 
266 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 "AU 131. From all this it follows that, when " all things 
 
 together." Were together/' and when the different seeds of things were 
 mixed together in infinitely small particles (fr. i), the 
 appearance presented would be that of one of what had 
 hitherto been regarded as the primary substances. As a 
 matter of fact, they did present the appearance of " air and 
 aether " ; for the quahties (things) which belong to these 
 — i.e. the hot and the cold, prevail in quantity over all other 
 things in the universe, and everything is most obviously 
 that of which it has most in it (fr. 12 suh fin.). Here, then, 
 Anaxagoras attaches himself to Anaximenes. The primary 
 condition of things, before the formation of the worlds, is 
 much the same in both ; only, with Anaxagoras, the original 
 mass is no longer the primary substance, but a mixture of 
 innumerable seeds divided into infinitely small parts. 
 
 This mass is infinite, like the air of Anaximenes, and it 
 supports itself, since there is nothing surrounding it.^ 
 Further, the " seeds " of all things which it contains are 
 infinite in number (fr. i). But, as the innumerable seeds 
 may be divided into those in which the portions of cold, 
 moist, dense, and dark prevail, and those which have most 
 of the warm, dry, rare, and light in them, we may say 
 that the original mass was a mixture of infinite Air and 
 of infinite Fire. The seeds of Air, of course, contain 
 " portions " of the " things " that predominate in Fire, and 
 vice versa ; but we regard everything as being that of which 
 it has most in it. Lastly, there is no void in this mixture, 
 an addition to the theory made necessary by the arguments 
 of Parmenides. It is, however, worthy of note that Anaxa- 
 goras added an experimental proof of this to the purely 
 dialectical one of the Eleatics. He used the klepsydra 
 
 to the o/jLoiofxeprj what is really true of the a-roixeia. It would be better to 
 delete the comma after irvp and add one after ^rjai, for (TvyKpLa-ei Kal 8iaKpi<x€i 
 jxbvov is explanatory of oiirw . . . Kaddwep. In the next sentence, I read 
 dTrXcDs for dWus with Zeller {Arch. ii. 261). See also Arist. De caelo, 
 r, 3. 302 b I (R. P. 150 a), where the matter is very clearly put. 
 1 Arist. Phys. T, 5- 205 b i (R. P. 154 a). 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 267 
 
 experiment as Empedokles had done (fr. 100), and also 
 showed the corporeal nature of air by means of inflated 
 skins. 1 
 
 132. Like Empedokles, Anaxagoras required some Nous, 
 external cause to produce motion in the mixture. Body, 
 Parmenides had shown, would never move itself, as the 
 Milesians had assumed. Anaxagoras called the cause of 
 motion by the name of Nous. It was this which made 
 Aristotle say that he " stood out like a sober man from the 
 random talkers that had preceded him," 2 and he has often 
 been credited with the introduction of the spiritual into 
 philosophy. The disappointment expressed by Sokrates 
 in the Phaedo as to the way in which Anaxagoras worked out 
 the theory should, however, make us pause to reflect before 
 accepting too exalted a view of it. Plato ^ makes Sokrates 
 say : "I once heard a man reading a book, as he said, of 
 Anaxagoras, and sajdng it was Mind that ordered the world 
 and was the cause of all things. I was delighted to hear 
 of this cause, and I thought he really was right. . . . But 
 my extravagant expectations were all dashed to the ground 
 when I went on and found that the man made no use of 
 Mind at all. He ascribed no causal power whatever to it 
 in the ordering of things, but to airs, and aethers, and waters, 
 and a host of other strange things.*' Aristotle, of course 
 with this passage in mind, says : * " Anaxagoras uses Mind 
 as a deus ex machina to account for the formation of the 
 world ; and whenever he is at a loss to explain why anything 
 necessarily is, he drags it in. But in other cases he makes 
 anything rather than Mind the cause." These utterances 
 may well suggest that the Nous of Anaxagoras was some- 
 thing on the same level as the Love and Strife of Empedokles, 
 
 ^ Phys. Z, 6. 213 a 22 (R. P. 159). We have a full discussion of the 
 experiments with the klepsydra in Prohl. 914 b 9 sqq., a passage which 
 we have already used to illustrate Empedokles, fr. 100. See above, 
 p. 219, n. 2. 
 
 2 Arist. Met. A, 3. 984 b 15 (R. P. 152). 
 
 3 Plato, Phaed. 97 b 8 (R. P. 155 d). 
 
 4 Arist. Met. A, 4. 985 a 18 (R. P. 155 d). 
 
268 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 and this will be confirmed when we look at what he has to 
 say about it. 
 
 In the first place, Nous is unmixed (fr. 12), and does not, 
 like other things, contain a portion of everything. This 
 would hardly be worth saying of an immaterial mind ; no 
 one would suppose that to be hot or cold. The result of 
 its being unmixed is that it " has power over " everything, 
 that is to say, in the language of Anaxagoras, it causes things 
 to move.i Herakleitos had said as much of Fire, and Empe- 
 dokles of Strife. Further, it is the " thinnest " of all things, 
 so that it can penetrate everywhere, and it would be mean- 
 ingless to say that the immaterial is " thinner " than the 
 material. It is true that Nous also " knows all things " ; 
 but so, perhaps, did the Fire of Herakleitos, 2 and certainly 
 the Air of Diogenes. ^ Zeller holds, indeed, that Anaxagoras 
 meant to speak of something incorporeal ; but he admits 
 that he did not succeed in doing so,* and that is historically 
 the important point. Nous is certainly imagined as occupy- 
 ing space ; for we hear of greater and smaller parts of it 
 (fr. 12). 
 
 The truth probably is that Anaxagoras substituted Nous 
 for the Love and Strife of Empedokles, because he wished 
 to retain the old Ionic doctrine of a substance that " knows " 
 all things, and to identify that with the new theory of a 
 substance that " moves " all things. Perhaps, too, it was 
 his increased interest in physiological as distinguished from 
 purely cosmological matters that led him to speak of Mind 
 rather than Soul. The former word certainly suggests to 
 the Greek an intimate connexion with the living body which 
 
 1 Arist. Phys. 6, 5. 256 b 24, did /cat 'Ava^ayopas opdws X^yeL, rbv vovv 
 airady] (pdaKoov /cat d/j-Lyrj elvai, eireidrfTrep Kiw^aeojs dpxw o-vrhv iroiet etvat * ovtoi} 
 yap Slu fxbvios Kivoirj aKivr}Tos Cbv /cai KparoLr} d/ucLyrjs il)v. This is only quoted for 
 the meaning of Kparelv. Of course, the words dKivrjTos Cbv are not meant 
 to be historical, and still less is the interpretation in De an. T, 4. 429 a 
 18. Diogenes of Apollonia (fr. 5) couples virb tovtov iravra Kv^epvdadai 
 (the old Milesian word) vdth irdvrwv Kparelv. 
 
 2 If we retain the MS. elbivai in fr. i. In any case, the name rb ao^ou 
 imphes as much. ' See fr. 3, 5. * Zeller, p. 993. 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 269 
 
 the latter does not. But, in any case, the originality of 
 Anaxagoras lies far more in the theory of substance than in 
 that of Nous. 
 
 133. The formation of a world starts with a rotatory Formation 
 motion which Nous imparts to a portion of the mixed mass worlds. 
 in which " all things are together " (fr. 13), and this rotatory 
 motion gradually extends over a wider and wider space. 
 
 Its rapidity (fr. 9) produced a separation of the rare and the 
 dense, the cold and the hot, the dark and the light, the 
 moist and the dry (fr. 15). This separation produces two 
 great masses, the one consisting mostly of the rare, hot, 
 light, and dry, called the " Aether *' ; the other, in which 
 the opposite qualities predominate, called ** Air " (fr. i). 
 Of these the Aether or Fire ^ took the outside while the Air 
 occupied the centre (fr. 15). 
 
 The next stage is the separation of the air into clouds, 
 water, earth, and stones (fr. 16). In this Anaxagoras follows 
 Anaximenes closely. In his account of the origin of the 
 heavenly bodies, however, he showed himself more original. 
 We read at the end of fr. 16 that stones '* rush outwards 
 more than water," and we learn from the doxographers that 
 the heavenly bodies were explained as stones torn from the 
 earth by the rapidity of its rotation and made red-hot by 
 the speed of their own motion. 2 Perhaps the fall of the 
 meteoric stone at Aigospotamoi had something to do with 
 the origin of this theory. It will also be observed that it 
 necessarily implies the rotation of the flat earth along with 
 the "eddy" [Uvn). 
 
 134. That Anaxagoras adopted the ordinary Ionian innumer- 
 theory of innumerable worlds is clear from fr. 4, which we worlds. 
 have no right to regard as other than continuous.^ The 
 
 ^ Note that Anaxagoras says " air " where Empedokles said " aether," 
 and that " aether " is with him equivalent to fire. Cf. Arist. De caelo, V, 3. 
 302 b 4, t6 ykp TTvp Kal tov alOepa irpocrayopeveL ravTo and ib. A, 3. 270 b 24, 
 'Aua^ay6pa$ 5^ /caraxp^rai t^) 6p6/xaTL TO}jT(f ov /caXws" dvo/xd^ei yap aldipa dvrl 
 
 TTVpOS. 
 
 2 Aet. ii. 13, 3 {Dox. p. 341 ; R. P. 157 c). 
 
 3 See above, p. 259, n. i. 
 
270 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 words " that it was not only with us that things were 
 separated off, but elsewhere too " can only mean that Nous 
 has caused a rotatory movement in more parts of the bound- 
 less mixture than one . Actios certainly includes Anaxagor as 
 among those who held there was only one world ^ ; but this 
 testimony cannot be considered of the same weight as that 
 of the fragments. Zeller's reference of the words to the 
 moon is very improbable. Is it likely that any one would 
 say that the inhabitants of the moon *' have a sun and 
 moon as with us " ? 2 
 Cos- 13^. Xhe cosmology of Anaxagoras is clearly based upon 
 
 that of Anaximenes, as will be seen from a comparison of 
 the following passage of Hippolytos ^ with the quotations 
 given in Chap. I. (§ 29) : 
 
 (3) The earth is flat in shape, and remains suspended because 
 of its size and because there is no vacuum.'* For this reason the 
 air is very strong, and supports the earth which is borne up by it. 
 
 (4) Of the moisture on the surface of the earth, the sea arose 
 from the waters in the earth (for when these were evaporated the 
 remainder turned salt),^ and from the rivers which flow into it. 
 
 (5) Rivers take their being both from the rains and from the 
 waters in the earth ; for the earth is hollow and has waters in 
 its cavities. And the Nile rises in summer owing to the water 
 that comes down from the snows in Ethiopia.^ 
 
 1 Aet. ii. 1,3 {Dox. p. 327). 
 
 2 Further, it can be proved that this passage (fr. 4) occurred quite near 
 the beginning of the work. Cf. Simpl. Phys. p. 34, 28 ij^er dXiya t^j 
 dpxv^ ToO irpd)Tov Uepl (j>v(xi(jis, p. 1 56, I, /cat [xeT 6\iya (after fr. 2), 
 which itself occurred, fier oKiyov (after fr. i), which was the beginning of 
 the book. A reference to other " worlds " would be quite in place here, 
 but not a reference to the moon. 
 
 3 Ref. i. 8, 3 {Dox. p. 562). 
 
 * This is an addition to the older view occasioned by the Eleatic denial 
 of the void. 
 
 5 The text is corrupt here, but the general sense can be got from 
 Aet. iii. 16. 2. 
 
 « The MS. reading is iv rots &pktols, for which Diels adopts Fredrichs' 
 iv TOLs dvTapnTLKots. I have thought it safer to translate the ev rri AldLOTrig. 
 of Actios (iv. I, 3). This view is mentioned by Herodotos (ii. 22). 
 Seneca {N.Q. iv. 2, 17) points out that it was adopted by Aischylos {Suppl. 
 559, fr. 300, Nauck), Sophokles (fr. 797), and Euripides {Hel. 3, fr. 228), 
 who would naturally take their opinions from Anaxagoras. 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 271 
 
 (6) The sun and the moon and all the stars are fiery stones 
 carried round by the rotation of the aether. Under the stars 
 are the sun and moon, and also certain bodies which revolve 
 with them, but are invisible to us. 
 
 (7) We do not feel the beat of the stars because of the great- 
 ness of their distance from the earth ; and, further, they are not 
 so warm as the sun, because they occupy a colder region. The 
 moon is below the sun, and nearer us. 
 
 (8) The sun surpasses the Peloponnesos in size. The moon 
 has not a light of her own, but gets it from the sun. The course 
 of the stars goes under the earth. 
 
 (9) The moon is eclipsed by the earth screening the sun's 
 light from it, and sometimes, too, by the bodies below the moon 
 coming before it. The sun is ecUpsed at the new moon, when the 
 moon screens it from us. Both the sun and the moon turn back 
 in their courses owing to the repulsion of the air. The 
 moon turns back frequently, because it cannot prevail over 
 the cold. 
 
 (10) Anaxagoras was the first to determine what concerns 
 the ecUpses and the illumination of the sun and moon. And he 
 said the moon was of earth, and had plains and ravines in it. 
 The Milky Way was the reflexion of the Hght of the stars that 
 were not illuminated by the sun. Shooting stars were sparks, as 
 it were, which leapt out owing to the motion of the heavenly 
 vault. 
 
 (11) Winds arose when the air was rarefied by the sun, and 
 when things were burned and made their way to the vault of 
 heaven and were carried off. Thunder and lightning were pro- 
 duced by heat strildng upon clouds. 
 
 (12) Earthquakes were caused by the air above striking on 
 that beneath the earth ; for the movement of the latter caused 
 the earth which floats on it to rock. 
 
 All this confirms the statement of Theophrastos, 
 that Anaxagoras had belonged to the school of An- 
 aximenes. The flat earth floating on the air, the 
 dark bodies below the moon, the explanation of the 
 solstices and the " turnings back " of the moon by 
 the resistance of air, the explanations of wind and of 
 thunder and lightning, are all derived from the Milesian. 
 
272 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 As to the moon's light and the cause of eclipses, it 
 was natural that Anaxagoras should be credited at Athens 
 with these discoveries. On the other hand, it seems 
 very unlikely that they were made by a believer in a 
 flat earth, and there is sufficient evidence that they are 
 really Pythagorean. ^ 
 Biology. 136. " There is a portion of everything in everything 
 
 except Nous, and there are some things in which there is 
 Nous also '' (fr. 11). In these words Anaxagoras laid down 
 the distinction between animate and inanimate things. He 
 tells us that it is the same Nous that *' has power over," 
 that is, sets in motion, aU things that have life, both the 
 greater and the smaller (f r. 12) . The Nous in living creatures 
 is the same in all (fr. 12), and from this it followed that the 
 different grades of intelligence we observe in the animal and 
 vegetable worlds depend entirely on the stmcture of the 
 body. The Nous was the same, but it had more oppor- 
 tunities in one body than another. Man was the wisest of 
 animals, not because he had a better sort of Nous, but 
 because he had hands. ^ This is in accordance with the 
 previous development of thought upon the subject. Par- 
 menides, in his Second Part (fr. 16), had already made 
 the thought of men depend on the constitution of their 
 limbs. 
 
 As aU Nous is the same, we are not surprised to find that 
 plants were regarded as living creatures. If we may trust 
 the pseudo- Aristotelian Treatise on Plants ^ so far, Anaxa- 
 goras argued that they must feel pleasure and pain in 
 connexion with their growth and with the fall of their leaves. 
 Plutarch says * that he caUed plants " animals fixed in the 
 earth." 
 
 Both plants and animals originated in the first instancers 
 from the iravairepixia. Plants arose when the seeds of 
 
 1 See p. 177, n. i. 
 
 2 Arist. De part. an. A, 10. 687 a 7 (R. P. 160 b). 
 
 3 [Arist.] De plant. A, i. 815 a 15 (R. P. 160). 
 
 4 Plut. Q.N. I (R. P. 160), ^(^ou . . . eyyeiov. 
 
 1 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 273 
 
 them which the air contained were brought down by 
 the rain-water,^ and animals originated in a similar way. 2 
 Like Anaximander, Anaxagoras held that animals first arose 
 in the moist element.^ 
 
 137. In these scanty notices we seem to see traces of a Percep- 
 polemical attitude towards Empedokles, and the same may *^°^* 
 be observed in what we are told of the theory of perception 
 adopted by Anaxagoras, especially in the view that percep- 
 tion is of contraries.* The account which Theophrastos 
 gives of this ^ is as follows : 
 
 But Anaxagoras says that perception is produced by opposites ; 
 for like things cannot be effected by like. He attempts to give a 
 detailed enumeration of the particular senses. We see by means 
 of the image in the pupil ; but no image is cast upon what is of 
 the same colour, but only on what is different. With most living 
 creatures things are of a different colour to the pupil by day, 
 though with some this is so by night, and these are accordingly 
 keen-sighted at that time. Speaking generally, however, night 
 is more of the same colour with the eyes than day. And an 
 image is cast on the pupil by day, because light is a concomitant 
 cause of the image, and because the prevailing colour casts an 
 image more readily upon its opposite.^ 
 
 It is in the same way that touch and taste discern their 
 objects. That which is just as warm or just as cold as we are 
 neither warms us nor cools us by its contact ; and, in the same 
 way, we do not apprehend the sweet and the sour by means of 
 themselves. We know cold by warm, fresh by salt, and sweet 
 by sour, in virtue of our deficiency in each ; for aU these are in 
 us to begin with. And we smell and hear in the same manner ; 
 the former by means of the accompan5dng respiration, the latter 
 by the sound penetrating to the brain, for the bone which sur- 
 rounds this is hollow, and it is upon it that the sound falls.' 
 
 And all sensation implies pain, a view which would seem to 
 be the consequence of the first assumption', for all unlike things 
 
 1 Theophr. Hist. Plant, iii. i, 4 (R. P. 160). 
 
 2 Irenaeus, Adv. Haer. ii. 14, 2 (R. P. 160 a). 
 
 3 Hipp. Ref. i. 8, 12 {Dox. p. 563). 
 
 * Beare, p. 37. ^ Theophr. De sensu, 27 sqq. {Dox. p. 507). 
 
 6 Beare, p. 38. ' Beare, p. 208, 
 
274 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 produce pain by their contact. And this pain is made percept- 
 ible by the long continuance or by the excess of a sensation. 
 Brilliant colours and excessive noises produce pain, and we cannot 
 dwell long on the same things. The larger animals are the more 
 sensitive, and, generally, sensation is proportionate to the size 
 of the organs of sense. Those animals which have large, pure, 
 and bright eyes, see large objects and from a great distance, and 
 contrariwise.^ 
 
 And it is the same with hearing. Large animals can hear 
 great and distant sounds, while less sounds pass unperceived ; 
 small animals perceive small sounds and those near at hand.^ 
 It is the same too with smell. Rarefied air has more smell ; 
 for, when air is heated and rarefied, it smells. A large animal 
 when it breathes draws in the condensed air along with the 
 rarefied, while a small one draws in the rarefied by itself ; so 
 the large one perceives more. For smeU is better perceived when 
 it is near than when it is far by reason of its being more con- 
 densed, while when dispersed it is weak. But, roughly speaking, 
 large animals do not perceive a rarefied smell, nor small animals 
 a condensed one.^ 
 
 This theory marks in some respects an advance on that 
 of Empedokles. It was a happy thought of Anaxagoras to 
 make sensation depend upon irritation by opposites, and to 
 connect it with pain. Many modern theories are based upon 
 a similar idea. 
 
 That Anaxagoras regarded the senses as incapable of 
 reaching the truth of things is shown by the fragments 
 preserved by Sextus. But we must not, for all that, turn 
 him into a sceptic. The saying preserved by Aristotle * 
 that " things are as we suppose them to he," has no value 
 at all as evidence. It comes from some collection of apoph- 
 thegms, not from the treatise of Anaxagoras himself ; and 
 it had, as likely as not, a moral application. He did say 
 (fr. 2i) that " the weakness of our senses prevents our 
 discerning the truth,*' but this meant simply that we do 
 not see the " portions " of everything which are in every- 
 
 1 Beare, p. 209. ^ Ibid. p. 103. 
 
 8 Ibid. p. 137. * Met. A, 5. 1009 b 25 (R. P. 161 a). 
 
 dl 
 
ANAXAGORAS OF KLAZOMENAI 
 
 '2^1^ 
 
 thing ; for instance, the portions of black which are in the 
 white. Our senses simply show us the portions that prevail. 
 He also said that the things which are seen give us the 
 power of seeing the invisible, which is the very opposite 
 of scepticism (fr. 21a). 
 
CHAPTER VII 
 
 THE PYTHAGOREANS 
 
 The 138. After losing their supremacy in the Achaian cities, 
 
 Pytha- 
 gorean the Pythagoreans concentrated themselves at Rhegion ; but 
 
 ^ ^ ' the school founded there did not maintain itself for long, 
 and only Archytas stayed behind in Italy. Philolaos and 
 Lysis, the latter of whom had escaped as a young man from 
 the massacre of Kroton, had already found their way to 
 Thebes.^ We know from Plato that Philolaos was there 
 towards the close of the fifth century, and Lysis was after- 
 wards the teacher of Epameinondas.^ Some of the Pytha- 
 goreans, however, were able to return to Italy later. Philo- 
 laos certainly did so, and Plato implies that he had left 
 Thebes some time before 399 B.C., the year Sokrates was put 
 to death. In the fourth century, the chief seat of the school 
 is the Dorian city of Taras, and we find the Pythagoreans 
 heading the opposition to Dionysios of Syracuse. It is to 
 this period that the activity of Archytas belongs. He was 
 the friend of Plato, and almost realised the ideal of the 
 philosopher king. He ruled Taras for years, and Aristoxenos 
 tells us that he was never defeated in the field of battle.^ 
 
 ^ Iambi. V. Pyth. 251. The ultimate authority for all this is Timaios. 
 There is no need to alter the MS. reading 'Kpxvrov to 'ApxtTrirov (as Diels 
 does after Beckmann). W^e are dealing with a later generation, and the 
 sentence opens with ol 5^ \onroi tCov Uvd ay opeioov, i.e. those other than 
 Archippos and Lysis, who have been dealt with in the preceding section. 
 
 2 For Philolaos, see Plato, Phaed. 6i d 7 ; e 7 ; and for Lysis, Aristo- 
 xenos in Iambi. V. Pyth. 250 (R. P. 59 b). 
 
 3 Diog. viii. 79-83 (R. P. 61). Aristoxenos himself came from Taras. 
 The story of Damon and Phintias (told by Aristoxenos) belongs to this 
 time. 
 
 276 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 277 
 
 He was also the inventor of mathematical mechanics. At 
 the same time, Pythagoreanism had taken root in the East. 
 Lysis remained at Thebes, where Simmias and Kebes had 
 heard Philolaos, while the remnant of the Pythagorean school 
 of Rhegion settled at Phleious. Aristoxenos was personally 
 acquainted with the last generation of this school, and 
 mentioned by name Xenophilos the Chalkidian from Thrace, 
 with Phanton, Echekrates, Diokles, and Polymnastos of 
 Phleious. They were all, he said, disciples of Philolaos and 
 Eurytos,^ and we learn from Plato that Simmias and Kebes 
 of Thebes and Echekrates of Phleious were also associates of 
 Sokrates.2 Xenophilos was the teacher of Aristoxenos, and 
 lived in perfect health at Athens to the age of a hundred 
 and five. 3 
 
 139. This generation of the school really belongs, how- pmc 
 ever, to a later period ; it is with Philolaos we have now to 
 deal. The facts we know about his teaching from external 
 sources are few in number. The doxographers, indeed, 
 ascribe to him an elaborate theory of the planetary system, 
 but Aristotle never mentions his name in connexion with 
 that. He gives it as the theory of " the Pythagoreans " or 
 of " some Pythagoreans." * It seems natural to suppose, 
 however, that the Pjrthagorean elements of Plato's Phaedo 
 and Gorgias come mainly from Philolaos. Plato makes 
 Sokrates express surprise that Simmias and Kebes had not 
 learnt from him why it is unlawful for a man to take his 
 life,^ and it seems to be implied that the Pythagoreans at 
 Thebes used the word " philosopher " in the special sense of 
 
 1 Diog. viii. 46 (R. P. 62). 
 
 2 The whole mise en scene of the Phaedo presupposes this, and it is 
 quite incredible that Plato should have misrepresented the matter. 
 Simmias and Kebes were a little younger than Plato and he could hardly 
 have ventured to introduce them as disciples of Sokrates if they had not 
 in fact been so. Xenophon too {Mem. i, 2. 48) includes Simmias and Kebes 
 in his list of genuine disciples of Sokrates, and in another place (iii. n, 7) 
 he tells us that they had been attracted from Thebes by Sokrates and 
 never left his side. 
 
 3 See Aristoxenos ap. Val. Max. viii. 13, ext. 3 ; and Souidas s.v. 
 * See below, §§ 150-152. s piato, Phaed. 61 d 6. 
 
278 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 a man who is seeking to find a way of release from the burden 
 of this life.i It is probable that Philolaos spoke of the body 
 (o-cofjia) as the tomb {o-tj/jlo) of the soul. 2 We seem to be 
 justified, then, in holding that he taught the old Pytha- 
 gorean religious doctrine in some form, and that he laid 
 special stress on knowledge as a means of release. That 
 is the impression we get from Plato, who is far the best 
 authority we have. 
 
 We know further that Philolaos wrote on " numbers " ; 
 for Speusippos followed him in the account he gave of the 
 Pythagorean theories on that subject. ^ It is probable 
 that he busied himself mainly with arithmetic, and we can 
 hardly doubt that his geometry was of the primitive type 
 described in an earher chapter. Eurytos was his disciple, 
 and we have seen (§ 47) that his views were still very crude. 
 
 We also know now that Philolaos wrote on medicine,* 
 and that, while apparently influenced by the theories of the 
 Sicihan school, he opposed them from the Pythagorean 
 standpoint. In particular, he said that our bodies were 
 composed only of the warm, and did not participate in the 
 
 1 This appears to follow from the remark of Simmias in Phaed. 64 b. 
 The whole passage would be pointless if the words <pL\6(TO(f)os, 4)iXo(xo^€cv, 
 (f)i\oao(pia had not in some way become familiar to the ordinary Theban 
 of the fifth century. Now Herakleides Pontikos made Pythagoras invent 
 the word, and expound it in a conversation with Leon, tyrant of Sikyon 
 or Phleious. Cf. Diog. i. 12 (R. P. 3), viii. 8 ; Cic. Tusc. v. 3. 8. Cf. also 
 the remark of Alkidamas quoted by Arist. Rhet. B, 23, 1398 b 18, Q-q^-rja-tv 
 dfia ol TT/Jocrrdrat (pi,\6ao(pot iy^vovro koI evdaifidvrjaev 17 7r6Xis. 
 
 2 For reasons which will appear, I do not attach importance in this 
 connexion to Philolaos, fr. 14 Diels=23 Mullach (R. P. 89), but it does 
 seem Ukely that the fj,vdo\oyC^ KOfixj/bs dvrjp of Gorg. 493 a 5 (R. P. 89 b) 
 is responsible for the whole theory there given. He is certainly, in any 
 case, the author of the rerp-qixhos ttLOos, which impHes the same general 
 view. Now he is called taojs StKcX6s ns fj 'ItoXikSs, which means he was 
 an Italian ; for the St/ceX6s ns is merely an allusion to the 2t/feX6s Koixxj/hs 
 av7]p -jtotI tclv /xar^p' ^<pa of Timokreon. We do not know of any Italian 
 from whom Sokrates could have learnt these views except Philolaos or one 
 of his associates. 
 
 ^ See above. Chap. II. p. 102, w. 2. 
 
 * It is a good illustration of the defective character of our tradition 
 (Introd. p. 26) that this was quite unknown till the publication of the 
 extracts from Menon's latrika contained in the Anonymus Londinensis. 
 See Diels in Hermes, xxviii. pp. 417 sqq. 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 279 
 
 cold. It was only after birth that the cold was introduced 
 by respiration. The connexion of this with the old Pytha- 
 gorean theory is clear. Just as the Fire in the macrocosm 
 draws in and Hmits the cold dark breath which surrounds 
 the world (§ 53), so do our bodies inhale cold breath from 
 outside. Philolaos made bile, blood, and phlegm the causes 
 of disease ; and, in accordance with this theory, he had to 
 deny that the phlegm was cold, as the Sicilian school held. 
 Its etymology proved it to be warm. We shall see that it 
 was probably this preoccupation with the medicine of the 
 SiciUan school that gave rise to some of the most striking 
 developments of later Pythagoreanism. 
 
 140. Such, so far as I can judge, was the historical Plato 
 Philolaos, though he is usually represented in a very different pytha- 
 light and has even been called a predecessor of Copernicus. 8°^®^°^* 
 To understand this, we must turn our attention to the story 
 of a literary conspiracy. 
 
 We have seen that there are one or two references to 
 Philolaos in Plato, ^ but these hardly suggest that he played 
 an important part in the development of Pythagorean 
 science. The most elaborate account we have of this is put 
 by Plato into the mouth of Timaios the Lokrian, of whom 
 we know no more than he has chosen to tell us. It is clear 
 at least that he is supposed to have visited Athens when 
 Sokrates was still in the prime of life, 2 and that he must 
 have been practically a contemporary of Philolaos. It 
 hardly seems likely that Plato should have given him the 
 credit of discoveries which were really due to his better- 
 known contemporary. However, Plato had many enemies 
 and detractors, and Aristoxenos was one of them. We know 
 he made the extraordinary statement that most of the 
 Republic was to be found in a work by Protagoras,^ and he 
 
 1 See p. 276, n. 2, and p. 278, n. 2. 
 
 2 This follows at once from the fact that he is represented as conversing 
 with the elder Kritias (p. 203, n. 3), who is very aged, and with Hermokrates, 
 who is quite young. 
 
 8 Diog. iii. 37. For similar charges, cf. Zeller, Plato, p, 429, n. 7. 
 
28o EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 seems also to be the original source of the story that Plato 
 bought " three Pythagorean books " from Philolaos and 
 copied the Timaeus out of them. According to this, the 
 *' three books " had come into the possession of Philolaos ; 
 and, as he had fallen into great poverty, Dion was able to 
 buy them from him, or from his relatives, at Plato's request, 
 for a hundred minae.^ It is certain, at any rate, that this 
 story was already current in the third century ; for the 
 sillographer Timon of Phleious addresses Plato thus : " And 
 of thee too, Plato, did the desire of discipleship lay hold. 
 For many pieces of silver thou didst get in exchange a small 
 book, and starting from it didst learn to write Timaeus.'' ^ 
 Hermippos, the pupil of Kallimachos, said that '' some 
 writer " said Plato himself bought the books from the 
 relatives of Philolaos for forty Alexandrian minae and 
 copied the Timaeus out of it ; while Satyros, the Arist- 
 archean, says he got it through Dion for a hundred minae.^ 
 There is no suggestion in any of these accounts that the book 
 was by Philolaos himself ; they imply rather that what 
 Plato bought was either a book by Pythagoras, or at any 
 rate authentic notes of his teaching, which had come into 
 the hands of Philolaos. In later times, it was generally 
 supposed that the forgery entitled The Soul of the World, 
 which goes by the name of Timaios the Lokrian, was meant ; * 
 but it has now been proved that this cannot have existed 
 earlier than the first century a.d. Moreover, it is plain that 
 it is based on Plato's Timaeus itself, and that it was written 
 in order to bolster up the story of Plato's plagiarism. It 
 does not, however, fulfil the most important requirement, 
 that of being in three books, which is always an essential 
 feature of that story.^ 
 
 1 Iambi. V. Pyth. 199. Diels is clearly right in ascribing the story to 
 Aristoxenos {Arch. iii. p. 461, n. 26). 
 
 2 Timon, fr. 54 (Diels), ap. Gell. iii. 17 (R. P. 60 a). 
 
 3 For Hermippos and Satyros, see Diog. iii. o ; viii. 84, 85. 
 
 * So Iambi, in Nicom. p. 105, 11 ; Proclus, in Tim. p. i, Diehl. 
 5 They are tcl 6pv\ovixeva Tpia" jSi^Xia (Iambi. V. Pyth. 199), to, dLap6r)Tc. 
 rpla j8i/3\fa (Diog. viii. 15). 
 
 i 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 281 
 
 Not one of the writers just mentioned professes to have 
 seen these famous " three books " ;^ but at a later date 
 there were at least two works which claimed to represent 
 them. Diels has shown how a treatise in three sections, 
 entitled HaiBevrcKov, itoXltikov, (^vo-lkov, was composed in 
 the Ionic dialect and attributed to Pythagoras. It was 
 largely based on the UvOayopiKoi a7ro(j)do-6i<; of Aristoxenos, 
 but its date is uncertain.^ In the first century B.C., 
 Demetrios Magnes professes to quote the opening words 
 of the work published by Philolaos.^ These, however, 
 are in Doric. Demetrios does not actually say this 
 work was written by Philolaos himself, though it is 
 no doubt the same from which a number of extracts 
 are preserved under his name in Stobaios and later 
 writers. If it professed to be by Philolaos, that was 
 not quite in accordance with the original story ; but it 
 is easy to see how his name may have become attached 
 to it. We are told that the other book which passed under 
 the name of Pythagoras was really by Lysis.* Boeckh has 
 shown that the work ascribed to Philolaos probably con- 
 sisted of three books also, and Proclus referred to it as the 
 Bakchai,^ a fanciful Alexandrian title which recalls the 
 ** Muses " of Herodotos. Two of the extracts in Stobaios 
 bear it. It must surely be confessed that the whole story 
 is very suspicious. 
 
 141. Boeckh argued that all the fragments preserved The 
 under the name of Philolaos were genuine ; but no one will mentfof 
 now go so far as that. The lengthy extract on the soul is P^i^Qi^os.' 
 given up even by those who maintain the genuineness of the 
 
 1 As Bywater said (/. Phil. i. p. 29), the history of this work "reads 
 Hke the history, not so much of a book, as of a Hterary ignis fatuus floating 
 before the minds of imaginative writers." 
 
 2 Diels, " Ein gefalschtes Pythagorasbuch " {Arch, iii. pp. 451 sqq.). 
 
 3 Diog. viii. 85 (R. P. 63 b). Diels^ reads irpCorov} iKdovvai tQv Uvda- 
 yopiKUiv 0L^\ia Kai iirLypdypat Uepi^^oaeus. 
 
 * Diog. viii. 7. 
 
 6 Proclus, in Eucl. p. 22, i55(Friedlein). Cf. Boeckh, Philolaos, pp. 
 36 sqq. Boeckh refers to a sculptured group of three Bakchai, whom he 
 supposes to be Ino, Agaue, and Autonoe. 
 
282 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 rest.i It cannot be said that this position is plausible. 
 Boeckh saw there was no ground for supposing that there 
 ever was more than a single work, and he drew the conclu- 
 sion that we must accept all the remains as genuine or 
 reject all as spurious. 2 As, however, many scholars 
 still maintain the genuineness of most of the fragments, 
 we cannot ignore them altogether. Arguments based on 
 their doctrine would, it is true, present the appearance 
 of a vicious circle at this stage, but there are two serious 
 objections to the fragments, which may be mentioned at 
 once. 
 
 In the first place, we must ask whether it is likely that 
 Philolaos should have written in Doric ? Ionic was the 
 dialect of science and philosophy till the time of the Pelo- 
 ponnesian War, and there is no reason to suppose the early 
 Pythagoreans used any other.^ Pythagoras was himself an 
 Ionian, and it is not likely that in his time the Achaian 
 states in which he founded his Order had adopted the Dorian 
 dialect.* Alkmaion of Kroton seems to have written in 
 Ionic.5 Diels says that Philolaos and then Archytas were 
 the first Pythagoreans to use the dialect of their homes ; ^ 
 but Philolaos can hardly be said to have had a home, and it 
 is hard to see why an Achaian refugee at Thebes should 
 
 1 The passage is given in R. P. 68. For a full discussion of this and 
 the other fragments, see Bywater, " On the Fragments attributed to 
 Philolaus the Pythagorean " (/. Phil, i, pp. 21 sqq.). 
 
 2 Boeckh, Philolaos, p. 38. Diels {Vors. p. 246) distinguishes the 
 Bakchai from the three books Uepl (pvatos {ib. p. 239). As, however, he 
 identifies the latter with the " three books " bought from Philolaos, and 
 regards it as genuine, this does not seriously affect the argument. 
 
 3 See Diels in Arch. iii. pp. 460 sgq. 
 
 * On the Achaian dialect, see O. Hoffmann in CoUitz and Bechtel, Didlekt- 
 Inschriften, vol. ii. p. 15 1 . How slowly Doric penetrated into the Chalkidian 
 states may be seen from the mixed dialect of the inscription of Mikythos 
 of Rhegion (Dial.-Inschr. iii, 2, p. 498), which is later than 468-67 B.C. 
 There is no reason to suppose that the Achaian dialect of Kroton was less 
 tenacious of life. We can see from Herodotos that there was a strong 
 prejudice against the Dorians there. 
 
 * The scanty fragments contain one Doric (or Achaian ?) form, ^x'"'^' 
 (fr. i), but Alkmaion calls himself KpoTuvirjTrjs, which is very significant; for 
 KpoTOJuidras is the Achaian as well as the Doric form. ^ Arch. iii. p. 460. 
 
 dl 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 283 
 
 write in Doric. ^ Nor did Archytas write in the Laconian 
 dialect of Taras, but in what may be called " common 
 Doric/' and he is a generation later than Philolaos, which 
 makes a great difference. In the time of Philolaos and 
 later, Ionic was still used even by the citizens of Dorian 
 states for scientific purposes. The Syracusan historian 
 Antiochos wrote in Ionic, and so did the medical writers of 
 Dorian Kos and Knidos. The forged work of Pythagoras, 
 which some ascribed to Lysis, was in Ionic ; and so was 
 the book on the Akousmata attributed to Androkydes,^ 
 which shows that, even in Alexandrian times, it was 
 beheved that Ionic was the proper dialect for Pythagorean 
 writings. 
 
 In the second place, there can be no doubt that one of 
 the fragments refers to the five regular solids, four of which 
 are identified with the elements of Empedokles.^ Now 
 Plato tells us in the Republic that stereometry had not been 
 adequately investigated at the time that dialogue is supposed 
 to take place,* and we have express testimony that the five 
 *' Platonic figures," as they were called, were discovered in 
 the Academy. In the Scholia to EucHd we read that the 
 Pythagoreans only knew the cube, the pyramid (tetra- 
 hedron), and the dodecahedron, while the octahedron and 
 
 1 He is distinctly called a Krotoniate in the extracts from Menon's 
 'larpLKo. (cf. Diog. viii. 84). It id true that Aristoxenos called him and 
 Eurytos Tarentines (Diog. viii. 46), but this only means that he settled at 
 Taras after leaving Thebes. These variations are common in the case of 
 migratory philosophers. Eurytos is also called a Krotoniate and a Meta- 
 pontine (Iambi. V. Pyth. 148, 266). Cf. also p. 330, n. i on Leukippos, 
 and p. 351, w. I on Hippon. 
 
 2 For Androkydes, see Diels, Vors. p. 281. As Diels points out {Arch. 
 iii. p. 461), even Lucian has sufficient sense of style to make Pythagoras 
 speak Ionic. 
 
 3 Cf. fr. 12=20 M. (R. P. 79), which I read as it stands in the MS. of 
 Stobaios, but bracketing an obvious adscript or dittography, koI to. eV 
 rq, (Tcpaipq. adofxara irivre ivH \tcl ev rq. <y(f)aipg.'], irvp, vdcjp /cat 7a Kal drjp, 
 Kal 6 ras a<palpas oXkcls irefiirTdv. In any case, we are not justified in 
 reading tA fi^v ras acpaipas cuj/xara with Diels. For the identification of 
 the four elements with four of the regular soHds, cf. § 147, and for the 
 description of the fifth, the dodecahedron, cf. § 148. 
 
 * Plato. Rep. 528 b. 
 
284 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the icosahedron were discovered by Theaitetos.i This suffi- 
 ciently justifies us in regarding the " fragments of Philolaos " 
 with suspicion, and all the more so as Aristotle does not 
 appear to have seen the work from which these fragments 
 come. 2 
 
 The 142. We must look, then, for other evidence. From 
 
 what has been said, it will be clear that it is above all from 
 Plato we can learn to regard Pythagoreanism sympatheti- 
 cally. Aristotle was out of sympathy with Pythagorean 
 ways of thinking, but he took great pains to understand 
 them. This was because they played so great a part in the 
 philosophy of Plato and his successors, and he had to make 
 the relation of the two doctrines as clear as he could to 
 himself and his disciples. What we have to do, then, is 
 to interpret what Aristotle tells us in the spirit of Plato, 
 and then to consider how the doctrine we thus arrive at is 
 related to the systems which preceded it. It is a delicate 
 operation, no doubt, but it has been made much safer by 
 recent discoveries in the early history of mathematics and 
 medicine. 
 
 1 Heiberg's Euclid, vol. v. p. 654, i, ^v To&riiJ t(? ^L^Xlcp, Tovr^ari 
 T(^ ly', ypdcperaL to, \eybfieva HXdrwj'os ? (rxi^Atara, A a^roO fih ovk ^<jtlv^ 
 rpla d^ tCov irpoeiprj/j.&coj/ e o-XT/iudro;?' tQv llvdayopelwv iarlv, 8 re kij^os 
 Kal i] irvpafils kuI t6 doiSeKdeSpou, Qeair-qrov 5k rb re dKrdedpov /cat rb 
 elKoadeSpov. It is no objection to this that, as Newbold points out (Arch. 
 xix. p. 204), the inscription of the dodecahedron is more difficult than that 
 of the octahedron and icosahedron. We have no right to reject the definite 
 testimony quoted above (no doubt from Eudemos) on grounds of a priori 
 probabiUty. As a matter of fact, there are Celtic and Etruscan dodeca- 
 hedra of considerable antiquity in the Louvre and elsewhere (G. Loria, 
 Scienze esatte, p. 39), and the fact is significant in view of the connexion 
 between Pythagoreanism and the North which has been suggested. 
 
 2 Philolaos is quoted only once in the Aristotelian corpus, in Eth. End, 
 B, 8. 1225 a 33 dXX' (ba-irep $tX6Xaos ecpri elvai TLvas Xbyovs KpeLrTovs i^fiCbv, 
 which looks like an apophthegm. His name is not even mentioned any- 
 where else, and this would be inconceivable if Aristotle had ever seen 
 a work of his which expounded the Pythagorean system. He must have 
 known the importance of Philolaos from Plato's Phaedo, and would certainly 
 have got hold of his book if it had existed. It should be added that 
 Tannery held the musical theory of our fragments to be too advanced for 
 Philolaos. It must, he argued, be later than Plato and Archytas {Rev. de 
 Phil, xxviii. pp. 233 sqq.). His opinion on such a point is naturally of 
 the greatest weight. 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 285 
 
 Zeller has cleared the ground by eHminating the Platonic 
 elements which have crept into later accounts of the system. 
 These are of two kinds. First of all, we have genuine 
 Academic formulae, such as the identification of the Limit 
 and the UnUmited with the One and the Indeterminate 
 Dyad ; ^ and secondly, there is the Neoplatonic doctrine 
 which represents the opposition between them as one 
 between God and Matter. 2 It is not necessary to repeat 
 Zeller 's arguments here, as no one will now attribute the 
 doctrine in that form to the Pythagoreans. 
 
 This simplifies the problem, but it is still very difficult. 
 According to Aristotle, the Pythagoreans said Things 
 are numbers, though that is not the doctrine of the 
 fragments of '* Philolaos." According to them, things 
 have number, which makes them knowable, while their 
 real essence is something unknowable.^ We have seen 
 reason for believing that Pythagoras himself said Things 
 are numbers (§ 52), and there is no doubt as to what 
 his followers meant by the formula ; for Aristotle says 
 they used it in . a cosmological sense. The world, accord- 
 ing to them, was made of numbers in the same sense 
 as others had said it was made of " four roots " or 
 " innumerable seeds." It will not do to dismiss this 
 as mysticism. The Pythagoreans of the fifth century 
 were scientific men, and must have meant something quite 
 definite. We shall, no doubt, have to say that they 
 used the words Things are numbers in a somewhat non- 
 natural sense, but there is no difficulty in that. The 
 Pythagoreans had a great veneration for the actual words 
 of the Master {avro<; €<j>a) ; but such veneration is often 
 
 ^ Aristotle says distinctly {Met. A, 6. 987 b 25) that " to set up a dyad 
 instead of the unlimited regarded as one, and to make the unlimited consist 
 of the great and small, is distinctive of Plato." 
 
 2 Zeller, p. 369 sqq. (Eng. trans, p. 397 sqq.). 
 
 3 For the doctrine of " Philolaos," cf. fr. i (R. P. 64) ; and for the un- 
 knowable iarw tCov irpayixaTo^v, see fr. 3 (R. P. 67). It has a suspicious 
 resemblance to the later uX?;, which Aristotle would hardly have failed to 
 note. He is always on the look-out for anticipations of vXtj. 
 
286 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 accompanied by a singular licence of interpretation. We 
 shall start, then, from what Aristotle tells us about the 
 numbers. 
 Aristotle 143- In the first place, Aristotle is quite clear that 
 
 Numbers. Pythagoreanism was intended to be a cosmological system 
 like the others. " Though the Pythagoreans," he tells us, 
 " made use of less obvious first principles and elements than 
 the rest, seeing that they did not derive them from sensible 
 objects, yet all their discussions and studies had reference to 
 nature alone. They describe the origin of the heavens, 
 and they observe the phenomena of its parts, all that happens 
 to it and all it does." ^ They apply their first principles 
 entirely to these things, " agreeing apparently with the 
 other natural philosophers in holding that reality was just 
 what could be perceived by the senses, and is contained 
 within the compass of the heavens," ^ though " the 
 first principles and causes they made use of were really 
 adequate to explain reahties of a higher order than the 
 sensible." ^ 
 
 The doctrine is more precisely stated by Aristotle to be 
 
 that the elements of numbers are the elements of things, 
 
 ^ and that therefore things are numbers.* He is equally 
 
 ' positive that these " things " are sensible things,^ and indeed 
 
 that they are bodies,^* the bodies of which the world is con- 
 
 1 Arist. Met. A, 8. 989 b 29 (R. P. 92 a). 
 
 2 Arist. Met. A, 8. 990 a 3, bfxoKoyovvTes rots AXXois <pvaio\6yois 6tl t6 
 -7' ov TOVT ecTTiu offov alffdrjTou icrri /cat ir€piei\r](f)€V 6 KaXodfiepos ovpavds. 
 
 * Met. ib. 990 a 5, ras 5' airias kul tcls dpxds, (bairep elirofxev, iKavas 
 Xiyovaiv eTrava^ijvai Kal iirl to. dvojTepu) tGjv 6vtu}v, /cat ixdWov 9) rots wepl 
 ^uaeoiis \6yoLS dp/xoTTOiJcras. 
 
 * Met. A, 5. 986 a I, rd. tCjv dpidfiQiv (rrotxeia tQp 6vt(j)v (rrotxeia irdvTiOv 
 uwiXa^op elvai ', N, 3. IO90 a 22, elvai fxev dpidfioiis iirolTjaav to. tvra, ov 
 Xt^pi'O'Toiis 8i, dXX' e^ dpid/xQv rd 6vTa. 
 
 ^ Met. M, 6. 1080 b 2, COS e/c rwu dpidfxQv ewirapxovTwv 6vTa rd ahdrp-d ; 
 ib. 1080 b 17, €K TovTov {tov fiadrjfiaTCKov dpLdfjLov) rds aiadrjrds ovcias crvuecrTdvai 
 (pao-iv. 
 
 * Met. M, 8. 1083 b II, rd (ribfiara i^ dpidfiQv elvai avyKcifJieva ; ib. b 17, 
 iKctvoL d^ Tov dpidjxbv rd 6vTa Xiyovaiv rd yovv dewp-qixara irpoadTTTOvaL rots 
 crt6/xacrtj' cos e^ eKeivcjv 6vtu3V tQu dpcdfxCov ; N, 3. 1090 a 32, /caret, fxhroi rb 
 TTOielv i^ dpidfxuiv rd (pvaiKd (ru)fj.aTa, iK fXT] exbvroiv ^dpos /jLrjde K0V(/)6Tr)Ta ^xoj'ra 
 KOV(f)6r7)Ta /cat ^dpos. 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 287 
 
 structed.^ This construction of the world out of numbers 
 was a real process in time, which the Pythagoreans described 
 in detail. 2 
 
 Further, the numbers were intended to be mathematical 
 numbers, though they were not separated from the things 
 of sense.^ On the other hand, they were not mere predicates 
 of something else, but had an independent reality of their 
 own. " They did not hold that the limited and the un- 
 limited and the one were certain other substances, such as 
 lire, water, or anything else of that sort ; but that the 
 unlimited itself and the one itself were the reality of the 
 things of which they are predicated, and that is why they 
 said that number was the reality of everything." * Accord- 
 ingly the numbers are, in Aristotle's own language, not 
 only the formal, but also the material, cause of things.^ 
 
 Lastly, Aristotle notes that the point in which the 
 Pythagoreans agreed with Plato was in giving numbers an 
 independent reahty of their own ; while Plato differed from 
 the Pythagoreans in holding that this reality was distin- 
 guishable from that of sensible things.^ Let us consider 
 these statements in detail. 
 
 144. Aristotle speaks of certain *' elements " {aroux'^la) The 
 of numbers, which were also the elements of things. That ^^^®°^®^*^ 
 is clearly the key to the problem, if we can discover what it numbers, 
 means. Primarily, the " elements of number " are the Odd 
 and the Even, but that does not seem to help us much. We 
 find, however, that the Odd and Even were identified with 
 the Limit and the Unlimited, which we have seen reason to 
 regard as the original principles of the Pythagorean cosmo- 
 
 ^ Met. A, 5. 986 a 2, rbv 8\ou ovpavbv ap/xovlav elvai Kai dpLd/nbp ', A, 8. 
 990 a 21, t6u apidfibv tovtov e^ o5 (XvviarrjKev 6 Koafios; M, 6. 1080 b 18, rbv 
 yap 8X0P oi)p(xvbv KaraaKevd^ovaiv i^ dpidfiQu; De caelo, V, I. 300 a 15, roh i^ 
 dpidfxQ}v (rvuL(TTacn rbv oipavbv ' ^vtoi yap Tr)v (pvaiv i^ dpLd[xG)v a-vuLaraaiP, 
 ibairep r(hv Ilvdayopelup TLves. 
 
 2 Met. N, 3. 1 09 1 a 18, Koa/xoTroiovcri Kal (pvaiKCos ^oOXovrai \iyeiv. 
 
 ' Met. M, 6. 1080 b 16 ; N, 3. 1090 a 20. 
 
 * Arist. Met. A, 5. 987 a 15. 6 Met. ib. 986 a 15 (R. P. 66). 
 
 • Met. A, 6. 987 b 27, 6 ixkv (nXdroji/) tov% dpLd/xods irapd rd aiadTjTd, 
 oi 5' (ot ILvdayupeiot) dpidp-ovs elvai (paaiv avrd rd aladrfTd. 
 
288 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 logy (§ 53). Aristotle tells us that it is the Even which gives 
 things their unlimited character when it is contained in 
 them and limited by the Odd,^ and the commentators are 
 at one in understanding this to mean that the Even is in 
 some way the cause of infinite divisibility. They get into 
 difficulties, however, when they try to show how this can 
 be. Simplicius has preserved an explanation, in all proba- 
 bility Alexander's, to the effect that they called the even 
 number unhmited " because every even is divided into 
 equal parts, and what is divided into equal parts is unlimited 
 in respect of bipartition ; for division into equals and halves 
 goes on ad infinitum. But, when the odd is added, it limits 
 it ; for it prevents its division into equal parts." ^ Now it 
 is plain that we must not impute to the Pythagoreans the 
 view that even numbers can be halved indefinitely. They 
 must have known that the even numbers 6 and 10 can only 
 be halved once. The explanation is rather to be found in a 
 fragment of Aristoxenos, where we read that " even numbers 
 are those which are divided into equal parts, while odd 
 numbers are divided into unequal parts and have a middle 
 term.'* ^ This is still further elucidated by a passage which is 
 quoted in Stobaios and ultimately goes back to Poseidonios. 
 It runs : " When the odd is divided into two equal parts, 
 a unit is left over in the middle ; but when the even is so 
 divided, an empty field is left, without a master and without 
 a number, showing that it is defective and incomplete." * 
 
 1 Met. A, 5. 986 a 17 (R. P. 66) ; Phys. V, 4. 203 a 10 (R. P. 66 a). 
 
 2 Simpl. Phys. p. 455, 20 (R. P. 66 a), I owe the passages which I 
 have used in illustration of this subject to W. A. Heidel, " Il^pas and A-n-eipov 
 in the Pythagorean Philosophy" (Arch. xiv. pp. 384 sqq.). The general 
 principle of my interpretation is the same as his, though I think that, 
 by bringing the passage into connexion with the numerical figures, I have 
 avoided the necessity of regarding the words 17 70,^ els iaa Kai rjfiiixrj diaipetns 
 itr direipov as " an attempted elucidation added by Simplicius." 
 
 8 Aristoxenos, fr. 81, ap. Stob. i. p. 20, i, iK tCjv Wpiaro^hov IlepL 
 dptd/xrjTLKTjs. . . tQv 5^ dpLdfiQu dpTioL fxiv elacv ol els taa diaipovjj.€VOL, wepLcro-ol 
 8^ oi els dvLaa /cat /miaov ^xoi/Tes. 
 
 * [Plut.] ap. Stob. i. p. 22, 19, Kal /x^v els 5vo bLaipovixivuiv tcra tov fxkv 
 Trepiaaov fiovds iv fi^acp irepiicrTi, tov 8k dpriov Kev^ XetTrerat xwpa koL a.8iairoros 
 Kai dvdpi6/xos, ws dv ipSeovs Kai dreXovs 6vtos. 
 
 m 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 289 
 
 Again, Plutarch says : "In the division of numbers, the 
 even, when parted in any direction, leaves as it were 
 within itself ... a field ; but, when the same thing is 
 done to the odd, there is always a middle left over from 
 the division." ^ It is clear that all these passages refer 
 to the same thing, and that can hardly be anything else 
 than the " terms " or dots with which we are already 
 familiar (§ 47). The division must fall between these; 
 for, if it meets with an indivisible unit, it is at once 
 arrested. 
 
 145. Now there can be no doubt that by his Unlimited The 
 Pythagoras meant something spatially extended ; for he spatial^ 
 identified it with air, night, or the void. We are prepared, 
 then, to find that his followers also thought of the Unlimited 
 as extended. Aristotle certainly regarded it so. He argues 
 that, if the Unhmited is itself a reaUty, and not merely the 
 predicate of some other reality, then every part of it must 
 be unlimited too, just as every part of air is air.^ The same 
 thing is implied in his statement that the Pythagorean 
 Unlimited was outside the heavens.^ Further than this, it 
 is not safe to go. Philolaos and his followers cannot have 
 regarded the Unlimited as Air ; for, as we shall see, they 
 adopted the theory of Empedokles as to that " element,'' 
 and accounted for it otherwise. One of them, Xouthos, 
 argued that rarefaction and condensation implied the void ; 
 without it the universe would overflow.* We do not know, 
 however, whether he was earlier than the Atomists or not. 
 
 ^ Plut. De E apud Delphos, 388 a, rats yap els taa rofxais tQv dpLOfiwv, 
 6 iJjkv dprios TTCLvrri bCCardixevos iTroXeiirei riva BeKTiKTjv dpx^v olov iv iavrip 
 Kal x'^P^^y ^^ ^^ '''V irepiTTCp ravrb iradbvTL (xicrov del veplecTTi rrjs vefii^aeus 
 ySvLfMOP. The words which I have omitted, in translating refer to the 
 further identification of Odd and Even with Male and Female. The 
 passages quoted by Heidel might be added to. Cf., for instance, what 
 Nikomachos says (p. 13, 10, Hoche), ^an 8^ dpnov fxkv t oUv re ds 5{io 
 taa diaipedTJvaL fiovdSos p.i<Tov /xt] irapeixirnrTovar^s, irepiTTOv bk t6 /jlt) dxivd/xevov 
 ei's 5i5o i'ca ixeptadrivai 5ia rrfv Trpoeiprjfj^^vrju ttjs /xovddos fieaiTelav. He significantly 
 adds that this definition is iK ttjs drj/xdidovs uttoXtJ^cws. 
 
 2 Arist. Phys. T, 4. 204 a 20 sgq., especially a 26, dWd firjv (bairep dipos 
 drjp ix4pos, ovTU Kal Eireipov drrelpov, e'i ye ovaia earl Kal dpx'h- 
 
 3 See Chap. II. § 53. * Ar. Phys. A, 9- 216 b 25, Kvixavelrb 6\ov. 
 
 19 
 
290 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 It is enough to say that the Pythagoreans meant by the 
 UnUmited the res extensa. 
 
 As the UnUmited is spatial, the Limit must be spatial 
 too, and we should expect to find that the point, the Hne, 
 and the surface were regarded as forms of the Limit. That 
 was the later doctrine ; but the characteristic feature of 
 Pythagoreanism is just that the point was not regarded as 
 a limit, but as the first product of the Limit and the Un- 
 limited, and was identified with the arithmetical unit 
 instead of with zero. According to this view, then, the 
 point has one dimension, the Hne two, the surface three, and 
 the solid four.^ In other words, the Pythagorean points 
 have magnitude, their lines breadth, and their surfaces 
 thickness. The whole theory, in short, turns on the defini- 
 tion of the point as a unit " having position " (/Aom? deatv 
 exovaa).^ It was out of such elements that it seemed possible 
 to construct a world. 
 The 146. This way of regarding the point, the line, and the 
 
 as magni- surf acc is closely bound up with the practice of representing 
 tudes. numbers by dots arranged in symmetrical patterns, which 
 we have seen reason for attributing to the Pythagoreans 
 (§ 47) . Geometry had already made considerable advances, 
 but the old view of quantity as a sum of units had not been 
 revised, and so the point was identified with i instead of 
 with 0. That is the answer to Zeller's contention that to 
 regard the Pythagorean numbers as spatial is to ignore the 
 fact that the doctrine was originally arithmetical rather than 
 geometrical. Our interpretation takes full account of that 
 
 1 Cf. Speusippos in the extract preserved in the Theologumena arith- 
 metica, p. 61 (Diels, Vors. 32 a 13), t6 fi7)v yap d cTLyix'T), tcl 5^ /3 ypa/xm^, to, 8^ 
 y rplyiavov, to. 5k 8 wvpafiis. We know that Speusippos is following 
 Philolaos here. Arist. Met. Z, 11. 1036 b 12, Kal dvdyovcrt irdvra els 
 Tovs dpLdfioiJi, Kal ypa/xfiTJs t6v \6yov rbv rCJv Svo dvai (paaiv. The matter is 
 clearly put by Proclus in Eucl. I. p. 97, 19, rb fiku ffrifieiov dvd\oyov TidevTai 
 fiovd8t, T^v 8k ypa/xfXT]v 8vd8t, tt]v 8k ^TncpdveLav rri Tpid8i Kal rb crepebv tt? 
 TeTpd8i. Kairoi ye a?s 8La(jTaTd Xafi^dvovres fiova8iK7}v jxkv evp-f^aoixev tt]v ypap.fx'qv, 
 8va8LKT}v 8k T7]v kirKpaveiav, rpiaSiKOV 8k rb arepebv. 
 
 2 The identification of the point with the unit is referred to by Aristotle, 
 Phys. E, 3. 227 a 27. 
 
 ■ 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 291 
 
 fact, and indeed makes the peculiarities of the whole system 
 
 depend on it. Aristotle is very decided as to the Pythagorean 
 
 points having magnitude. " They construct the whole world 
 
 out of numbers/' he tells us, " but they suppose the units 
 
 have magnitude. As to how the first unit with magnitude 
 
 arose, they appear to be at a loss." ^ Zeller holds that this 
 
 is only an inference of Aristotle's, 2 and he is probably right 
 
 in this sense, that the Pythagoreans never felt the need of 
 
 sajdng in so many words that points had magnitude. It 
 
 does seem probable, however, that they called them 
 " 3 
 
 QfyKOi. 
 
 Zeller, moreover, allows, and indeed insists, that in the 
 Pythagorean cosmology the numbers were spatial, but he 
 raises difficulties about the other parts of the system. There 
 are other things, such as the Soul and Justice and Oppor- 
 tunity, which are said to be numbers, and which cannot be 
 regarded as constructed of points, lines, and surfaces.* 
 Now it appears to me that this is just the meaning of a pas- 
 sage in which Aristotle criticises the Pythagoreans. They 
 held, he says, that in one part of the world Opinion prevailed, 
 while a little above it or below it were to be found Injustice 
 or Separation or Mixture, each of which was, according to 
 them, a number. But in the very same regions of the 
 heavens were to be found things having magnitude which 
 were also numbers. How can this be, since Justice has no 
 magnitude ? ^ This means surely that the Pythagoreans 
 
 1 Arist. Met. M, 6. 1080 b 18 sqq., 1083 b 8 sqq. ; De caelo, V, i. 300 a 16 
 (R. P. 76 a). 2 Zeller, p. 381. 
 
 3 Zeno in his fourth argument about motion, which, we shall see (§ 163), 
 was directed against the Pythagoreans, used i-yKoi for points. Actios, i. 3, 
 19 (R. P. 76 b), says that Ekphantos of Syracuse was the first of the 
 Pythagoreans to say that their units were corporeal. Cf. also the use of 
 t^KOL in Plato, Parm. 164 d, and Galen, Hist. Phil. 18 {Dox. p. 610), 'Hpa- 
 KXeLSijs d^ 6 U.ovti.k6s Kai ' AaK\7]Trcddr]s 6 Bi.dvv6s dvap/JLOvs 6yKovs ras apxas viro- 
 TcdevTaL tQ}v 6\u3v. * Zeller, p. 381. 
 
 5 Arist. Met. A, 8. 990 a 22 (R. P, 81 e). I read and interpret thus : 
 " For, seeing that, according to them, Opinion and Opportunity are in 
 a given part of the world, and a little above or below them Injustice and 
 Separation and Mixture, — in proof of which they allege that each of these 
 is a number, — and seeing that it is also the case (reading av/x^alprj with 
 
292 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 had failed to give any clear account of the relation between 
 these more or less fanciful analogies and their geometrical 
 construction of the universe. 
 The 147. We seem to see further that what distinguished 
 
 and^hf the Pythagoreauism of this period from its earlier form was 
 elements, ^j^^^ ^^ sought to adapt it Self to the new theory of ' ' elements. ' ' 
 This is what makes it necessary to take up the consideration 
 of the system once more in connexion with the pluraUsts. 
 When the Pythagoreans returned to Southern Italy, they 
 would find views prevalent there which demanded a partial 
 reconstruction of their own system. We do not know that 
 Empedokles founded a philosophical society, but there can 
 be no doubt of his influence on the medical school of these 
 regions ; and we also know now that Philolaos played a part 
 in the history of medicine. ^ This gives us the clue to what 
 formerly seemed obscure. The tradition is that the Pytha- 
 goreans explained the elements as built up of geometrical 
 figures, a theory we can study for ourselves in the more 
 developed form it attained in Plato's Timaeus} If they 
 were to retain their position as the leaders of medical 
 study in Italy, they were bound to account for the 
 elements. 
 
 Bonitz) that there is already in that part of the world a number of com- 
 posite magnitudes {i.e. composed of the Limit and the Unlimited), because 
 those affections (of number) are attached to their respective regions ; — 
 (seeing that they hold these two things), the question arises whether the 
 number which we are to understand each of these things (Opinion, etc.) to 
 be is the same as the number in the world {i.e. the cosmological number) 
 or a different one." I cannot doubt that these are the extended numbers 
 which are composed {o-wiaTaTai) of the elements of number, the limited 
 and the unhmited, or, as Aristotle here says, the " affections of number," 
 the odd and the even. Zeller's view that " celestial bodies " are meant 
 comes near this, but the application is too narrow. Nor is it the number 
 (7r\?7^os) of those bodies that is in question, but their magnitude {fjjyedos). 
 For other views of the passage see Zeller, p. 391, w. i. 
 
 ^ All this has been put in its true light by the publication of the extract 
 from Menon's 'larpt/cd, on which see p. 278, n. 4. 
 
 2 In Aet. ii. 6, 5 (R. P. 80) the theory is ascribed to Pythagoras, which 
 is an anachronism, as the mention of " elements " shows it must be later 
 than Empedokles. In his extract from the same source, Achilles says 
 ol Uvdaydpem, which doubtless represents Theophrastos better. 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 293 
 
 We must not take it for granted, however, that the 
 Pythagorean construction of the elements was exactly 
 the same as that we find in Plato's Timaeus. As we 
 have seen, there is good reason for believing they 
 only knew three of the regular solids, the cube, the 
 pyramid (tetrahedron), and the dodecahedron.^ Now 
 Plato makes Timaios start from fire and earth,^ and 
 in the construction of the elements he proceeds in 
 such a way that the octahedron and the icosahedron 
 can easily be transformed into pyramids, while the cube 
 and the dodecahedron cannot. From this it follows 
 that, while air and water pass readily into fire, earth 
 cannot do so,^ and the dodecahedron is reserved for another 
 purpose, which we shall consider presently. This would 
 exactly suit the Pythagorean system ; for it would leave 
 room for a dualism of the kind outlined in the Second Part 
 of the poem of Parmenides. We know that Hippasos made 
 Fire the first principle, and we see from the Timaeus how 
 it would be possible to represent air and water as forms of 
 fire. The other element is, however, earth, not air, as we 
 have seen reason to believe that it was in early Pytha- 
 goreanism. That would be a natural result of the discovery 
 of atmospheric air by Empedokles and of his general theory 
 of the elements. It would also explain the puzzling fact, 
 which we had to leave unexplained above, that Aristotle 
 identifies the two " forms " spoken of by Parmenides with 
 Fire and Earth.* 
 
 148. The most interesting point in the theory is, however. The 
 the use made of the dodecahedron. It was identified, we hedron' 
 are told, with the " sphere of the universe," or, as it is put 
 
 1 See above, p. 283. 2 piato, Tim. 31 b 5. 
 
 3 Plato, Tim. 54 c 4. It is to be observed that in Tim. 48 b 5 Plato 
 says of the construction of the elements ovdeis ttw yiveaiv avrQu fjie/xrjvvKeu, 
 which implies that there is some novelty in the theory as Timaios states it. 
 If we read the passage in the light of what has been said in § 141, we shall 
 be inclined to believe that Plato is making Timaios work out the Pytha- 
 gorean doctrine on the lines of the discovery of Theaitetos. 
 
 * See above, Chap. lY. p. i86. 
 
294 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 in the Philolaic fragment, with the " hull of the sphere/* ^ 
 Whatever we may think of the authenticity of the fragments, 
 there is no reason to doubt that this is a genuine Pythagorean 
 expression, and it must be taken in close connexion with 
 the word " keel " applied to the central fire.^ The structure 
 of the world was compared to the building of a ship, an idea 
 of which there are other traces.^ The key to what we are 
 told of the dodecahedron is also given by Plato. In the 
 Phaedo, which must have been written before the doctrine 
 of the regular solids was fully established, we read that the 
 " true earth," if looked at from above, is " many-coloured 
 like the balls that are made of twelve pieces of leather." ^ 
 In the Timaeus the same thing is referred to in these words : 
 " Further, as there is still one construction left, the fifth, 
 God made use of it for the universe when he painted it." ^ 
 The point is that the dodecahedron approaches more nearly 
 to the sphere than any other of the regular solids. The 
 twelve pieces of leather used to make a ball would all be 
 regular pentagons ; and, if the material were not flexible 
 
 1 Aet. ii. 6, 5 (R. P. 80) ; " Philolaos," fr. 12 (=20 M. ; R. P. 79). On 
 the oX/cds, see Gundermann in Rhein. Mus. 1904, pp. 145 sqq. In the 
 Pythagorean myth of Plato's Politicus, the world is regarded as a ship, of 
 which God is the Kv^epv'r)T7}s (272 e sqq.). The ttovtos ttjs dvofioLdrrp-os (273 d) 
 is just the dTreipof. 
 
 ^ Aet. ii. 4, 15, Sirep rpd-n-eus biKrjv Trpovire^dXeTO ry rod ttuvtos <^a(paipq.y 
 6 drjfjiiovpybs deds. 
 
 ^ Cf. the uTTo^w/iara of Plato. Rep. 616 c 3. As vXr) generally means 
 " timber " for shipbuilding (when it does not mean firewood), I suggest 
 that we should look in this direction for an explanation of the technical use 
 of the word in later philosophy. Cf. Plato, Phileb. 54 c i, yeviaem . . . 
 eveKa . . . irdaav vX-qv TraparWeadai irdaiv, which is part of the answer to the 
 question Trbrepa irXolwv vav7rr]yiap eVeKa 07^5 yiypeaOaL fxdXXop ■^ TrXoia evena 
 vavirrjylas ; [ib. b 2) ; Tim. 69 a 6, ola riKToaiv ijfuv vXt) irapaKeiTai. 
 
 * Plato, Phaed. no b 6, doarrep ol doideKdaKVToi acjiaipai, the meaning 
 of which phrase is quite correctly explained by Plutarch, Plat. q. 1003 b, 
 Koi yap fidXicTTa t(^ -rrX-qdei tuiv aroLxeioju dfi^X^TrjTL 8^ tQv yuuiQu tt]v 
 €vdvTT]Ta biacpvybv evKajxirh icrri [rd SuBeKdedpov'], Kal ry Trepirdaei (bcnrep ai 
 dudeKdcTKVTOt cr<pa7pai KVKXorepks yiyverai Kal TrepiXrjirTiKdv. 
 
 5 Plato, Tim. 55 c 4. Neither this passage nor the last can refer to the 
 Zodiac, which would be described by a dodecagon, not a dodecahedron. 
 What is implied is the division of the heavens into twelve pentagonal fields, 
 in which the constellations were placed. For the history of such methods 
 see Newbold in Arch. xix. pp. 198 sqq. 
 
 m 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 295 
 
 like leather, we should have a dodecahedron instead of a 
 sphere. That proves that the dodecahedron was well 
 known before Theaitetos, and we may infer that it was 
 regarded as forming the " timbers " on which the spherical 
 hulk of the heavens was built. 
 
 The tradition confirms in an interesting way the import- 
 ance of the dodecahedron in the Pythagorean system. 
 According to one account, Hippasos was drowned at sea for 
 reveaUng " the sphere formed out of the twelve pentagons." ^ 
 The Pythagorean construction of the dodecahedron we 
 may partially infer from the fact that they adopted the 
 pentagram or pentalpha as their symbol. The use of this 
 figure in later magic is well known ; and Paracelsus still 
 employed it as a symbol of health, which is exactly what the 
 Pythagoreans called it.^ 
 
 149. The view that the soul is a " harmony," or rather TheSoui 
 an attunement, is intimately connected with the theory of mony." 
 the four elements. It cannot have belonged to the earliest 
 form of Pythagoreanism ; for, as shown in Plato's Phaedo, 
 it is quite inconsistent with the idea that the soul can exist 
 independently of the body. It is the very opposite of the 
 belief that " any soul can enter any body." ^ On the other 
 hand, we are told in the Phaedo that it was accepted by 
 Simmias and Kebes, who had heard Philolaos at Thebes, and 
 by Echekrates of Phleious, who was the disciple of Philolaos 
 and Eurytos.* The account of the doctrine given by Plato 
 is quite in accordance with the view that it was of medical 
 origin. Simmias says : " Our body being, as it were, strung 
 and held together by the warm and the cold, the dry and the 
 
 1 Iambi. V. Pyth. 247. Cf. above, Chap. II. p. 106, n. i. 
 
 2 See Gow, Short History of Greek Mathematics, p. 151, and the 
 passages there referred to, adding Schol. Luc. p. 234, 21, Rabe, rb 
 irevTdypafMfj.ov'] fin rb iv ttj avvTfdelc}. Xeybfxevov xeurdXipa aO/x^o\ov ?ju wpbs dWriXovs 
 Ilvdayopeitov duayvupLarLKbv Kal tovtus iv rats iirKXToXaci ixp^vTO. The 
 Pythagoreans may quite well have known the method given by Euclid 
 iv. II of dividing a line in extreme and mean ratio, the so-called "golden 
 section." 
 
 3 Arist. De an. A, 3. 407 b 20 (R. P. 86 c). 
 
 * Plato, Phaed. 85 e sqq. ; and for Echekrates, ib. 88 d. 
 
296 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 moist, and things of that sort, our soul is a sort of tempera- 
 ment and attunement of these, when they are mingled with 
 one another well and in due proportion. If, then, our soul 
 is an attunement, it is clear that, when the body has been 
 relaxed or strung up out of measure by diseases and other 
 ills, the soul must necessarily perish at once." ^ This is 
 clearly an application of the theory of Alkmaion (§ 96), and 
 is in accordance with the views of the Sicihan school. It 
 completes the evidence that the Pythagoreanism of the 
 end of the fifth century was an adaptation of the old doctrine 
 to the new principles introduced by Empedokles. 
 
 It is further to be observed that, if the soul is regarded 
 as an attunement in the Pythagorean sense, we should expect 
 it to contain the three intervals then recognised, the fourth, 
 the fifth and the octave, and this makes it extremely 
 probable that Poseidonios was right in saying that the 
 doctrine of the tripartite soul, as we know^ it from the 
 Republic of Plato, was really Pythagorean. It is quite 
 inconsistent with Plato's own view of the soul, but agrees 
 admirably with that just explained.^ 
 The 150- The planetary system which Aristotle attributes to 
 
 " the Pythagoreans " and Actios to Philolaos is sufficiently 
 remarkable.3 The earth is no longer in the middle of the 
 world ; its place is taken by a central fire, which is not to 
 
 1 Plato, Phaed. 86 b 7-c 5. 
 
 2 See J. L. Stocks, Plato and the Tripartite Soul {Mind N.S., No. 94, 
 I9i5» PP- 207 sqq.). Plato himself points to the connexion in Rep. 
 443 <i» 5 (Tvuapixba avra rpLa 6vTa, uxnrep 6povs rpeis ap/jLOuias arexvC^s, pedrrji 
 T€ Kai virdTr)s /cat fxiai^s, Kai ei &X\a Erra fiera^ii Tvyx'^^^'' ^vtol {i.e. the 
 movable notes). Now there is good ground for believing that the state- 
 ment of Aristides Quintihanus (ii. 2) that the dvfuKov is intermediate 
 between the \oyiKbv and the dXoyou comes from the musician Damon (Deiters, 
 De Aristidis Quint, fontibus, 1870), the teacher of Perikles (p. 255, n. 2), to 
 whom the Platonic Sokrates refers as his authority on musical matters, but 
 who must have died when Plato was quite young. Moreover, Poseidonios 
 (ap. Galen, De Hipp, et Plat. pp. 425 and 478) attributed the doctrine of the 
 tripartite soul to Pythagoras, avTov fi^v toO llvdayopov avyypd/j.fMaTos oidepds 
 ei's ■fjfji.ds diaa ({j^ofM^uov, TtKfiatpbfievos de e^ S)v 'ivioi tCov fiadrjTwv avTov yey pd(pa<Ti.v. 
 
 3 For the authorities see R. P. 81-83. The attribution of the theory 
 to Philolaos is perhaps due to Poseidonios. The " three books " were 
 doubtless in existence by his time. 
 
 central 
 fire. 
 
I 
 
 THE PYTHAGOREAISS 297 
 
 be identified with the sun. Round this fire revolve ten 
 bodies. First comes the Antichthon or Counter-earth, and 
 next the earth, which thus becomes one of the planets. After 
 the earth comes the moon, then the sun, the planets, and 
 the heaven of the fixed stars. We do not see the central 
 fire and the antichthon because the side of the earth on 
 which we five is always turned away from them. This is to 
 be explained by the analogy of the moon, which always 
 presents the same face to us, so that men hving on the other 
 side of it would never see the earth. This impHes, of course, 
 from our point of view, that these bodies rotate on their 
 axes in the same time as they revolve round the central 
 fire,i and that the antichthon revolves round the central fire 
 in the same time as the earth, so that it is always in opposi- 
 tion to it.^ 
 
 It is not easy to accept the statement of Actios that this 
 system was taught by Philolaos. Aristotle nowhere men- 
 tions him in connexion with it, and in the Phaedo Sokrates 
 gives a description of the earth and its position in the world 
 which is entirely opposed to it, but is accepted without demur 
 by Simmias the disciple of Philolaos.^ It is undoubtedly 
 a Pythagorean theory, however, and marks a noticeable 
 advance on the Ionian views current at Athens. It is clear 
 too that Sokrates states it as something of a novelty that the 
 earth does not require the support of air or anything of the 
 sort to keep it in its place. Even Anaxagoras had not been 
 able to shake himself free of that idea, and Demokritos still 
 
 ^ Piato makes Timaios attribute an axial rotation to the heavenly bodies, 
 which must be of this kind {Tim. 40 a 7). The rotation of the moon upon 
 its axis takes the same time as its revolution round the earth ; but it comes 
 to the same thing if we say that it does not rotate at all relatively to its 
 orbit, and that is how the Greeks put it. It would be quite natural for 
 the Pythagoreans to extend this to all the heavenly bodies. This led 
 ultimately to Aristotle's view that they were all fixed {ivbebefiiva) in 
 corporeal spheres. 
 
 2 This seems more natural than to suppose the earth and counter- 
 earth to be always in conjunction. Cf. Aet. iii. 11, 3, tt]v oiKoufiivrju yrjv 
 i^ ivavrias Kei-^ihi^v /cat irepKpepofievrju ry duTLxdovi. 
 
 ' Plato, Phaed. 108 e 4 sqq. Simmias assents to the geocentric theory 
 in the emphatic words xai 6pd(as ye. 
 
298 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 held it along with the theory of a flat earth. The natural 
 inference from the Phaedo would certainly be that the theory 
 of a spherical earth, kept in the middle of the world by 
 its equilibrium, was that of Philolaos himself. If so, the 
 doctrine of the central fire would belong to a later generation. 
 
 It seems probable that the theory of the earth's revolu- 
 tion round the central fire really originated in the account 
 of the sun's light given by Empedokles. The two things 
 are brought into close connexion by Actios, who says that 
 Empedokles beUeved in two suns, while '' Philolaos " believed 
 in two or even in three. His words are obscure, but they 
 seem to justify us in holding that Theophrastos regarded the 
 theories as akin.i We saw that Empedokles gave two 
 inconsistent explanations of the alternation of day and 
 night (§ 113), and it may well have seemed that the solution 
 of the difficulty was to make the sun shine by reflected light 
 from a central fire. Such a theory would, in fact, be the 
 natural issue of recent discoveries as to the moon's light 
 and the cause of its ecUpses, if these were extended to the 
 sun, as they would almost inevitably be. 
 
 The central fire received a number of mythological 
 names, such as the " hearth of the world," the " house," or 
 '* watch-tower " of Zeus, and " the mother of the gods." ^ 
 That was in the manner of the school, but it must not blind 
 
 1 Aet. ii. 20, 13 (Chap. VI. p. 238, n. 3) compared with ib. 12 
 #iX6Xaos d IlvdaybpeLos vaXoeidrj rbv -fjXiov, Sexofievov fxkv rod iv T(^ K6<Tfi(fi 
 irvpbs Tr]v dvra&yeLav, dnjdovvra 8^ irpbs ^/tas rb 0ws, ibiXTe rpbirov tlvcl 
 diTToiis ijXiovs ylyveadai, t6 re iv ry ovpavi^ TrvpQdh /cat rb dw' avrov 
 irvpoeid^s Hard, rb ia-owTpoeidis' el fi-q tls kuI Tplrov \4^ei rrjv dirb toO 
 ivoTTTpov KUT dvdKXaffip btaa-Trei.pofjt.^vTiv Trpbs i]/iias aiyqv. This is not, of 
 course, a statement of any doctrine held by " Philolaos," but a rather 
 captious criticism such as we often find in Theophrastos. Moreover, 
 it is pretty clear that it is inaccurately reported. The phrase t6 iv ry 
 Kbapoj} irvp, if used by Theophrastos, must surely mean the central 
 fire, and rb iv ry ovpavip irvpQSes must be the same thing, as it very 
 well may, seeing that Actios tells us himself (ii. 7. 7, R. P. 81) that 
 " Philolaos " used the term ovpavos of the sublunary region. It is true that 
 Achilles says rb irvpQdes Kal Stairy^s Xafi^dvovra &vu6ev dirb tov depiov 
 irvpbs, but his authority is not sufiiciently great to outweigh the other 
 considerations. 
 
 2 Aet. i. 7, 7 (R. P. 81). Proclus in Tim. p. 106, 22 (R. P. 83 e). 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 299 
 
 us to the fact that we are deaUng with a scientific hypothesis. 
 It was a great thing to see that the phenomena could best 
 be " saved " by a central luminary, and that the earth must 
 therefore be a revolving sphere like the other planets. ^ 
 Indeed, we are tempted to say that the identification of the 
 central fire with the sun was a detail in comparison. It is 
 probable, at any rate, that this theory started the train of 
 thought which made it possible for Aristarchos of Samos to 
 reach the heliocentric hypothesis,^ and it was certainly 
 Aristotle's successful reassertion of the geocentric theory 
 which made it necessary for Copernicus to discover the truth 
 afresh. We have his own word for it that he started from 
 what he had read about the Pythagoreans. ^ 
 
 In the form in which it was now stated, however, the 
 theory raised almost as many difficulties as it solved, and it 
 did not maintain itself for long. It is clear from Aristotle 
 that its critics raised the objection that it failed to " save the 
 phenomena " inasmuch as the assumed revolution of the 
 earth would produce parallaxes too great to be negligible, 
 and that the Pythagoreans gave some reason for the belief 
 that they were negligible. Aristotle has no clear account 
 of the arguments on either side, but it may be pointed out 
 that the earth was probably supposed to be far smaller than 
 it is, and there is no reason why its orbit should have been 
 thought to have an appreciably greater diameter than we 
 now know the earth itself to have.* 
 
 1 Aristotle expresses this by saying that the Pythagoreans held ttju . . . 
 yiju iv tG}v darpcov odaav kvkXij} (pepofM^vrjv irepi rb ixi<xov vvKra re Kal 7]fiipav iroieiv 
 {De caelo, B, 13. 293 a 23). 
 
 2 I do not discuss here the claims of Herakleides to be the real author 
 of the heliocentric hypothesis. 
 
 3 In a letter to Pope Paul III., Copernicus quotes Plut. Plac. iii. 13, 2-3 
 (R. P. 83 a) and adds Inde igitur occasionem.nactus, coepi et ego de tevvae 
 mobilitate cogitare. 
 
 * Cf. Ar. De caelo, B, 13. 293 b 25 iirel yap ovk ^anv ij 777 Kivrpov, dW 
 dTT^X^' T"^ rmtcrcpaipLov avTrji 6\ov, ovdh KwXieiv otourai rk ^aivS/JLeva crvfx^alveiv 
 6/j.oio}s fXT} KUTOiKovaiu i]/xli/ iirl rod K^vrpov, wcrirep kB,v el iirl rod fi^crov ^v ij yi]' 
 ovdev yap oidk vvv iroielv eTrlSrjXov ttjv rjfjLiaeiav air^x^^'^^^ rjfids 8td/j.eTpov. 
 (Of course the words rb ij/xKTipaipiou avrrjs 6Xov refer to Aristotle's own 
 theory of celestial spheres ; he really means the radius of its orbit.) 
 
300 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 A truer view of the earth's dimensions would naturally 
 suggest that the alternation of night and day was due to 
 the earth's rotation on its own axis, and in that case the 
 earth could once more be regarded as in the centre. It does 
 not appear that Aristotle knew of any one who had held this 
 view, but Theophrastos seems to have attributed it to 
 Hiketas and Ekphantos of Syracuse, of whom we know 
 very little otherwise.^ Apparently they regarded the 
 heaven of the fixed stars as stationary, a thing Aristotle 
 would almost have been bound to mention if he had ever 
 heard of it, since his own system turns entirely on the diurnal 
 revolution. 
 
 Both theories, that of the earth's revolution round a 
 central fire and that of its rotation on its own ajcis, had the 
 effect of making the revolution of the fixed stars, to which 
 the Pythagoreans certainly adhered, very difficult to 
 account for. They must either be stationary or their 
 motion must be something quite different from the diurnal 
 
 Now it is inconceivable that any one should have argued that, since 
 the geocentric parallax is negligible, parallax in general is negUgible. 
 On the other hand, the geocentric Pythagorean (the real Philolaos ?), whose 
 views are expounded by Sokrates in the Phaedo, appears to have made a 
 special point of saying that the earth was Trdfifjieya (109 a 9), and that would 
 make the theory of the central fire very difficult to defend. If Philolaos 
 was one of the Pythagoreans who held that the radius of the moon's orbit 
 is only three times that of the earth's (Plut. De an. procr. 1028 b), he cannot 
 have used the argument quoted by Aristotle. 
 
 ^ Aet. iii. 13, 3 'Hpa/cXeiSTys 6 Hoptlkos Kai "Ex^avros 6 ni;^a76/3eios Kivovai 
 fxh T71V yrjv ov fi-Zju ye fiera^aTLKuis, dWa TpeirTLKQs [1. o-rpeTrri/cws] rpoxov diKTjv 
 iyr)^ovL(T/x€Pr)i^, dirb bvajxCiv eV dvaroKdi irepl t6 Idiov avTTJs KivTpov. Cicero 
 attributes the same doctrine to Hiketas {Acad. pr. ii. 39), but makes nonsense 
 of it by saying that he made the sun and moon stationary as well as the 
 fixed stars. Tannery regarded Hiketas and Ekphantos as fictitious person- 
 ages from a dialogue of Herakleides, but it seems clear that Theophrastos 
 recognised their existence. It may be added that the idea of the earth's 
 rotation was no novelty. The Milesians probably (§21) and Anaxagoras 
 certainly (p. 269) held this view of their flat earth. All that was new was 
 the appHcation of it to a sphere. If we could be sure that the geocentric 
 Pythagoreans who made the earth rotate placed the central fire in the 
 interior of the earth, that would prove them to be later in date than the 
 system of " Philolaos." Simplicius appears to say this {De caelo, p. 512 
 9 sqq.)t and he may be quoting from Aristotle's lost work on the Pytha- 
 goreans. The point, however, is doubtful. 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 301 
 
 revolution. 1 It was probably this that led to the abandon- 
 ment of the theory. 
 
 In discussing the views of those who hold the earth to 
 be in motion, Aristotle only mentions one theory as alternative 
 to that of its revolution round the central fire, and he says 
 that it is that of the Timaeus. According to this the earth 
 is not one of the planets but " at the centre,** while at the 
 same time it has some kind of motion relatively to the axis 
 of the universe.^ Now this motion can hardly be an axial 
 rotation, as was held by Grote ; ^ for the whole cosmology 
 of the Timaeus implies that the alternation of day and night 
 is due to the diurnal revolution of the heavens.* The fact 
 that the earth is referred to a little later as "the guardian and 
 artificer of night and day " ^ proves nothing to the contrary, 
 since night is in any case the conical shadow of the earth, 
 which is thus the cause of the alternation of day and night. 
 So far, Boeckh and his followers appear to be in the right. 
 
 1 The various possibilities are enumerated by Sir T. L. Heath (Arist- 
 archus, p. 103). Only two are worth noting. The universe as a whole 
 might share in the rotation of the dirXapis, while the sun, moon and planets 
 had independent revolutions in addition to that of the universe. Or the 
 rotation of the dirXap^s might be so slow as to be imperceptible, in which 
 case its motion, " though it is not the precession of the equinoxes, is some- 
 thing very like it" (Heath, loc. cit.). 
 
 2 Arist. De caelo, B, 13. 293 b 5, ^vioi 8k Kal Kctfiivrjv iirl rod Kivrpov \tt)v 
 77}!'] (paalu avT7)v iWecdaL /cat Kiveiadai irepl rbv 8ia iravrbs rerafiivov irdXov, 
 &cnrep iv t<^ Ttfiaiip yiypairrai. The text and interpretation of this 
 passage are guaranteed by the reference in the next chapter (296 a 25) 
 61 S' iirl Tov pAaov d^vres tWeadai Kal Kiveiadai (pacri irepl rbv irdXov jjAaov. 
 All attempts to show that this refers to something else are futile. 
 We cannot, therefore, with Alexander, regard Kal KLPeiadat as an inter- 
 polation in the first passage, even though it is omitted in some MSS. 
 there. The omission is probably due to Alexander's authority. More- 
 over, when read in its context, it is quite clear that the passage gives 
 one of two alternative theories of the earth's motion, and that this 
 motion, like the revolution round the central fire, is a motion of 
 translation {(f)opd), and not an axial rotation. 
 
 3 Plato's Doctrine respecting the Rotation of the Earth (i860). 
 
 * Plato, Tim. 39 c I, vii^ fiev oDp Tjfxipa re y^yovev oIjtus Kal dih 
 ravra, 17 rrjs fxids Kal (ppovifioiTdrTjs KVKXifjaeoos Trepiodos. This refers to 
 the revolution of the " circle of the Same," i.e. the equatorial circle, arid is 
 quite unambiguous. 
 
 5 Plato, Tim. 40 c l [yrjul (f>ij\aKa Kal Srjinovp'ybv vvktSs re Kal i]/x4pas 
 ip.7)X^vT](raTo. On this cf. Heath, Aristarchus, p. 178. 
 
302 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 When, however, Boeckh goes on to argue that the word 
 tXkofiev7)v in the Timaeus does not refer to motion at all, 
 but that it means " globed '* or " packed " round, it is quite 
 impossible for me to follow him. Apart from all philo- 
 logical considerations, this interpretation makes nonsense of 
 Aristotle's line of argument. He says ^ that, if the earth 
 is in motion, whether " outside the centre " or " at the 
 centre," that cannot be a " natural motion " ; for, if it 
 were, it would be shared by every particle of earth, and we 
 see that the natural motion of every clod of earth is " down," 
 i.e. towards the centre. He also says that, if the earth is 
 in motion, whether " outside the centre " or " at the centre,'* 
 it must have two motions hke everything else but the 
 " first sphere," and therefore there would be excursions in 
 latitude (TrdpoBot) and " turnings back " {rpoirai) of the 
 fixed stars, which there are not. It is clear, then, that 
 Aristotle regarded the second theory of the earth's move- 
 ment as involving a motion of translation equally with the 
 first, and that he supposed it to be the theory of Plato's 
 Timaeus. It is impossible to believe that he can have 
 been mistaken on such a point. ^ 
 
 When we turn to the passage in the Timaeus itself, we 
 find that, when the text is correctly established, it completely 
 corroborates Aristotle's statement that a motion of transla- 
 tion is involved,^ and that Boeckh's rendering is inadmissible 
 
 1 Arist. De caelo, B, 14. 296 a 29 sqq. The use of the word viroXenrbfxeva 
 of the apparent motion of the planets from west to east is an interesting 
 survival of the old Ionian view (p. 70), The idea that the earth must have 
 two motions, if it has any, is based on nothing more than the analogy of 
 the planets (Heath, Aristarchus, p. 241). 
 
 2 Aristotle must have been a member of the Academy when the 
 Timaeus was published, and we know that the interpretation of that dia- 
 logue was one of the chief occupations of the Academy after Plato's death. 
 If he had misrepresented the doctrine by introducing a motion of transla- 
 tion, Alexander and Simplicius would surely have been able to appeal to 
 an authoritative protest by Krantor or another. The view which Boeckh 
 finds in the Timaeus is precisely Aristotle's own, and it is impossible to 
 believe that he could have failed to recognise the fact or that he should 
 have misrepresented it deliberately. 
 
 « The best attested reading in Tim. is yrju 8^ rpo^bv fikv rnxeripav, 
 IWofihr^v 5^ TT]v irepl tov 5ia Travrbs irbXov TeTa/uihov. The article ttjv 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 303 
 
 on grammatical and lexicological grounds. ^ We have there- 
 fore to ask what motion of translation is compatible with the 
 statement that the earth is " at the centre," and there seems 
 to be nothing left but a motion up and down (to speak loosely) 
 on the axis of the universe itself. Now the only clearly 
 attested meaning of the rare word tWofiat is just that of 
 motion to and fro, backwards and forwards.^ It may be 
 added that a motion of this kind was familiar to the Pytha- 
 goreans, if we may judge from the description of the waters 
 in the earth given by Sokrates in the Phaedo on the authority 
 of some unnamed cosmologist.^ 
 
 What was this motion intended to explain ? It is 
 impossible to be certain, but it is clear that the motions of 
 the circles of the Same and the Other, i.e. the equator and 
 the ecliptic, are inadequate to " save the appearances." So 
 far as they go, all the planets should either move in the 
 
 is in Par. A and also in the Palatine excerpts, and it is difficult to suppose 
 that any one would interpolate it. On the other hand, it might easily be 
 dropped, as its meaning is not at once obvious. It is to be explained, of 
 course, like tt^v iwl ddvaTov or Xenophon's irpoekrfKvdbTo^ . . . ttjv irpbs to, 
 (ppovpia, and imphes a path of some kind, and therefore a movement of 
 translation. 
 
 1 In the first place, the meaning globatam, " packed," " massed " would 
 have to be expressed by a perfect participle and not a present, and we 
 find accordingly that Simplicius is obliged to paraphrase it by the 
 perfect participle, dedefi^vrj or dedea-fjiTj/uiivr). Sir T. L. Heath's " wound " 
 {Aristarchus, p. 177) ought also to be " winding." In the second place, 
 though Par. A has elWofiivrjv, the weight of authority distinctly favours 
 IWofjt^vTjv, the reading of Aristotle, Proclus and others. The verbs e'iXXw 
 {etXXu}), eiXQ and I'XXw are constantly confused in MSS. It is not, I think, 
 possible to regard I'XXw as etymologically connected with the other verbs. 
 It seems rather to go with iXX6s and IWaivu), which are both used in 
 Hippokrates. For its meaning, see below, n. 2. 
 
 2 Cf. Soph. Ant. 340 IWojxivwv apbrpojv ^tos els '4tos^ clearly of the 
 ploughs going backwards and forwards in the furrows, Simplicius 
 makes a point of the fact that ApoUonios Rhodios used iWdfievos in the 
 sense of "shut in," "bound," elpyo/xevos (cf. Heath, Aristarchus, p. 175, 
 n.6). That, however, cannot weigh against the probability that the scribes, 
 or even ApoUonios himself, merely fell into the common confusion. Unless 
 we can get rid of the article ttjv and the testimony of Aristotle, we must 
 have a verb of motion. 
 
 3 Cf . Plato, Phaed. 1 1 1 64, where we are told that there is an alibpa in 
 the earth, which causes the waters to move up and down in Tartaros, 
 which is a chasm extending from pole to pole. See my notes in loc. 
 
304 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ecliptic or remain at an invariable distance from it, and this 
 is far from being the case. Some explanation is required of 
 their excursions in latitude, i.e, their alternate approaches 
 to the ecliptic and departures from it. We have seen (p. 63) 
 that Anaximander already busied himself with the " turnings 
 back " of the moon. Moreover, the direct and retrograde 
 movements of the planets are clearly referred to in the 
 Timaeus a few lines below. ^ We are not bound to show in 
 detail that a motion of the kind suggested would account for 
 these apparent irregularities ; it is enough if it can be made 
 probable that the fifth -century Pythagoreans thought it 
 could. It may have seemed worth while to them to explain 
 the phenomena by a regular motion of the earth rather than 
 by any waywardness in the planets ; and, if so, they were at 
 least on the right track. 
 
 To avoid misunderstanding, I would add that I do not 
 suppose Plato himself was satisfied with the theory which 
 he thought it appropriate for a Pythagorean of an earlier 
 generation to propound. The idea that Plato expounded his 
 own personal views in a dialogue obviously supposed to take 
 place before he was born, is one which, to me at least, is quite 
 incredible. We know, moreover, from the unimpeachable 
 authority of Theophrastos, who was a member of the Academy 
 in Plato's later years, that he had then abandoned the 
 geocentric hypothesis, though we have no information as to 
 
 1 Proclus, in his commentary, explains the Trpoxw^ceis and iirava- 
 Ku/cXiJcrets of Tim. 20 c as equivalent to trpoirobLcrfiol and viroTrodtafioL 
 In a corrigendum prefixed to his Aristarchus, Sir T. L. Heath disputes this 
 interpretation, and compares the application of the term ^wavaKVKKovixevov 
 to the planet Mars in Rep. 617 b, which he understands to refer merely to 
 its " circular revolution in a sense contrary to that of the fixed stars." It 
 is to be observed, however, that Theon of Smyrna in quoting this passage 
 has the words /idXtcrra tCov EWiov after iTravaKVKKodixevov, which gives 
 excellent sense if retrogradation is meant. In fact Mars has a greater arc 
 of retrogradation than the other planets (Duhem, Systeme du monde, vol. i. 
 p. 61). As I failed to note this in my text of the Republic, I should like 
 to make amends by giving two reasons for believing that Theon has pre- 
 served Plato's own words. In the first place he is apparently quoting from 
 DerkyUides, who first estabUshed the text of Plato from which ours is 
 derived. In the second place fidXiara tQv dWoov is exactly fifteen letters, 
 the normal length of omissions in the Platonic text. 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 305 
 
 what he supposed to be in the centre of our system. ^ It 
 seems clear too from the Laws that he must have attributed 
 an axial rotation to the earth.^ 
 
 151. The existence of the antichthon was also a hypothesis The 
 intended to account for the phenomena of eclipses. In one 
 place, indeed, Aristotle says the Pythagoreans invented it in 
 order to bring the number of revolving bodies up to ten ; ^ 
 but that is a mere sally, and Aristotle really knew better. 
 In his work on the Pythagoreans, he said that eclipses of the 
 moon were caused sometimes by the intervention of the earth 
 and sometimes by that of the antichthon ; and the same 
 statement was made by Phihp of Opous, a very competent 
 authority on the matter.* Indeed, Aristotle shows in another 
 passage how the theory originated. He tells us that some 
 thought there might be a considerable number of bodies 
 revolving round the centre, though invisible to us because of 
 the intervention of the earth, and that they accounted in 
 this way for there being more eclipses of the moon than of 
 the sun. 5 This is mentioned in close connexion with the 
 antichthon, so Aristotle clearly regarded the two hypotheses 
 as of the same nature. The history of the theory seems to 
 be this. Anaximenes had assumed the existence of dark 
 
 1 Plut. Plat, quaest, 1006 c (cf. V. Numae, c. 11). It is important to 
 remember that Theophrastos was a member of the Academy in Plato's 
 last years. 
 
 2 In the passage referred to (822 a 4 sqq.) he maintains that the planets 
 have a simple circular motion, and says that this is a view which he had not 
 heard in his youth nor long before. That must imply the rotation of the 
 earth on its axis in twenty-four hours, since it is a denial of the Pythagorean 
 theory that the planetary motions are composite. It does not follow that 
 we must find this view in the Timaeus, which only professes to give the 
 opinions of a fifth-century Pythagorean. 
 
 3 Arist. Met. A, 5. 986 a 3 (R. P. 83 b). 
 
 * Aet. ii. 29, 4, tQv Hvdayopeidjv tlv^s KarcL Tr)u ' ApLaroriXeLov laToplav 
 Kctl T7]v ^iXIttttov toO 'OttowtLov oltt 6({>acr lv dPTavyeiq, Kal dvTi.(ppd^ei Tork 
 fj.h TTjs 777s, TOT^ d^ TTJs duTixOouos {eKXeLTTetv TTju (xeXrjvrjv). 
 
 ^ Arist. De caelo, B, 13. 293 b 21, ivioLs 5k 5ok€i Kal irXeico aibixara 
 Toiavra evbix^adai (p^peadat irepl rb fi^crov rjfuu dd-qXa 8id rrju iirnrpdadijaiv 
 TTJS 777s. dib Kal ras ttjs aeXrjPtjs ^KXeixpeis TrXeiovs i) rds tov ijXiov ylyveadai 
 <pa<TLV ■ tCjv yap cj>€po(JL4vMU 'iKaarov dvTKppaTTetv avT'/jv, dXX' ov fidpov ttjv 
 
 20 
 
 I 
 
3o6 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 planets to account for lunar eclipses (§ 29), and Anaxagoras 
 had revived that view (§ 135). Certain Pythagoreans ^ had 
 placed these dark planets between the earth and the central 
 fire in order to account for their invisibility, and the next 
 stage was to reduce them to a single body. Here again we 
 see how the Pythagoreans tried to simplify the hypotheses of 
 their predecessors. 
 
 152. We have seen (§ 54) that the doctrine commonly, 
 but incorrectly, known as the " harmony of the spheres " 
 may have originated with Pythagoras, but its elaboration 
 must belong to a later generation; and the extraordinary 
 variations in our accounts of it must be due to the conflicting 
 theories of the planetary motions which were rife at the end 
 of the fifth and the beginning of the fourth centuries B.C. 
 We have the express testimony of Aristotle that the Pytha- 
 goreans whose doctrine he knew believed that the heavenly 
 bodies produced musical notes in their courses. Further, 
 the pitch of the notes was determined by the velocities of 
 these bodies, and these in turn by their distances, which were 
 in the same ratios as the consonant intervals of the octave. 
 Aristotle distinctly implies that the heaven of the fixed stars 
 takes part in the celestial symphony ; for he mentions " the 
 sun, the moon, and the stars, so great in magnitude and in 
 number as they are/' a phrase which cannot refer solely or 
 chiefly to the five planets.^ We are also told that the slower 
 bodies give out a deep note and the swifter a high note, and 
 the prevailing tradition gives the high note of the octave to 
 
 1 It is not expressly stated that they were Pythagoreans, but it is natural 
 to suppose so. So, at least, Alexander thought (Simpl. De caelo, p. 515 
 
 25). 
 
 2 Arist. De caelo, B, 9. 290 b, 12 sqq. (R. P. 82). Cf. Alexander, In met. 
 p. 39, 24 (from Aristotle's work on the Pythagoreans) tuv yap awfidruv 
 rdv irepl to fxiaov (pepofi&wu iv avakoylq, ras dwoaTdaeLS ^x6j'rw»' . . . 
 iroioiJVTCov d^ Kal \f/6(pov iv ry Ktvecadai tCjv fih ^padvripiov ^apjjv, rOiv d^ 
 raxvripojv 6^17. There are all sorts of difficulties in detail. We can 
 hardly attribute the identification of the seven planets (including sun 
 and moon) with the strings of the heptachord to the Pythagoreans of this 
 date ; for Mercury and Venus have the same mean angular velocity as the 
 Sun, and we must take in the heaven of the fixed stars. 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 307 
 
 the heaven of the fixed stars, which revolves in twenty-four 
 hours. Saturn, of course, comes next ; for, though it has a 
 slow motion of its own in a contrary direction, that is 
 " mastered " (KpareiraL) by the diurnal revolution. The 
 other view, which gives the highest note to the Moon and 
 the lowest to the fixed stars, is probably due to the theory 
 which substituted an axial rotation of the earth for the 
 diurnal revolution of the heavens.^ 
 
 153. We have still to consider a view, which Aristotle Things 
 sometimes attributes to the Pythagoreans, that things were Jf ^^^^^^^ 
 " like numbers." He does not appear to regard this as numbers, 
 inconsistent with the doctrine that things are numbers, 
 though it is hard to see how he could reconcile the two.^ 
 There is no doubt, however, that Aristoxenos represented 
 the Pythagoreans as teaching that things were like numbers,^ 
 and there are other traces of an attempt to make out that 
 this was the original doctrine. A letter was produced, 
 
 1 For the various systems, see Boeckh, Kleine Schriften, vol. iii. pp. 
 169 sqq., and Cari v. Jan, " Die Harmonic der Spharen " {Philol. 1893, 
 pp. 13 sqq.). There is a sufficient account of them in Heath's Aristarchus, 
 pp. 107 sqq., where the distinction between absolute and relative velocity 
 is clearly stated, a distinction which is not appreciated in Adam's note 
 on Rep. 617 b (vol. ii. p. 452), with the result that, while the heaven of 
 the fixed stars is rightly regarded as the utjtt] (the highest note), the Moon 
 comes next instead of Saturn — an impossible arrangement. The later 
 view is represented by the " bass of Heaven's deep Organ " in the " ninefold 
 harmony " of Milton's Hymn on the Nativity (xiii.). At the beginning of 
 the Fifth Act of the Merchant of Venice, Shakespeare makes Lorenzo ex- 
 pound the doctrine in a truly Pythagorean fashion. According to him, 
 the " harmony " in the soul ought to correspond with that of the heavenly 
 bodies {"such harmony is in immortal souls"), but the "muddy vesture 
 of decay " prevents their complete correspondence. The Timaeus states 
 a similar view, and in the Book of Homage to Shakespeare (pp. 58 sqq.) I 
 have tried to show how the theories of the Timaeus may have reached 
 Shakespeare. There is no force in Martin's observation that the sounding 
 of all the notes of an octave at once would not produce a harmony. There 
 is no question of harmony in the modern sense, but only of attunement 
 {apfiovia) to a perfect scale. 
 
 2 Cf. especially Met. A, 6. 787, b 10 (R. P. 65 d). It is not quite the 
 same thing when he says, as in A, 5. 985 b 23 sqq. (R. P. ib.), that they 
 perceived many hkenesses in things to numbers. That refers to the 
 numerical analogies of Justice, Opportunity, etc. 
 
 3 Aristoxenos ap. Stob. i. pr, 6 (p. 20), Uvdayopas . . . irdura to. 
 irpdyiJ.aTa drreLKa^uv rots dpid/nols. 
 
 I 
 
3o8 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 purporting to be by Theano, the wife of Pythagoras, in 
 which she says that she hears many of the Hellenes think 
 Pythagoras said things were made of number, whereas he 
 really said they were made according to number. ^ 
 
 When this view is uppermost in his mind, Aristotle seems 
 to find only a verbal difference between Plato and the 
 Pythagoreans. The metaphor of " participation " was 
 merely substituted for that of " imitation." This is not 
 the place to discuss the meaning of the so-called *' theory of 
 ideas " ; but it must be pointed out that Aristotle's ascrip- 
 tion of the doctrine of " imitation " to the Pythagoreans is 
 abundantly justified by the Phaedo. When Simmias is asked 
 whether he accepts the doctrine, he asks for no explanation 
 of it, but replies at once and emphatically that he does. The 
 view that the equal itself is alone real, and that what we call 
 equal things are imperfect imitations of it, is quite familiar 
 to him,^ and he is finally convinced of the immortality of the 
 soul just because Sokrates makes him see that the theory of 
 forms implies it. 
 
 It is also to be observed that Sokrates does not introduce 
 the theory as a novelty. The reality of the " ideas " is the 
 sort of reahty " we are always talking about,*' and they are 
 explained in a peculiar vocabulary which is represented as 
 that of a school. The technical terms are introduced by such 
 formulas as " we say." ^ Whose theory is it ? It is usually 
 supposed to be Plato's own, though some call it his ** early 
 theory of ideas," and say that he modified it profoundly in 
 later Hfe. But there are serious difficulties in this view. 
 
 1 Stob. Ed. i. p. 125, 19 (R. P. 65 d). 
 
 2 Plato, Phaed. 74 a sqq. 
 
 3 Cf. especially the words 8 dpvKoviiev del (76 d 8). The phrases airb 8 
 ia-Tiv, a-uTo Kad' avrb, and the like are assumed to be familiar. " We " 
 define reality by means of question and answer, in the course of which "we " 
 give an account of its being {^s \6yov dido/xev rod elvai, 78 d I, where 
 \6yop . . . Tov elvai is equivalent to \6yov ttjs oiiaias) . When we have done 
 this, " we " set the seal or stamp of avrb 8 ^anv upon it (75 d 2). Tech- 
 nical terminology impUes a school. As Diels puts it {Elementum, p. 20), 
 it is in a school that " the simile concentrates into a metaphor, and the 
 metaphor condenses into a term." 
 
 ■ 
 
THE PYTHAGOREANS 
 
 309 
 
 Plato is very careful to tell us that he was not present at the 
 conversation recorded in the Phaedo. Did any philosopher 
 ever propound a new theory of his own by representing it as 
 already familiar to a number of distinguished living con- 
 temporaries ? ^ It is not easy to believe that. It would be 
 rash, on the other hand, to ascribe the origin of the theory 
 to Sokrates, and there seems nothing for it but to suppose 
 that the doctrine of " forms " (etSrj, ISeat) originally took 
 shape in Pythagorean circles, though it was further developed 
 by Sokrates. There is nothing startling in this. It is a 
 historical fact that Simmias and Kebes were not only Pytha- 
 goreans but disciples of Sokrates, and there were, no doubt, 
 more " friends of the ideas " ^ than we generally recognise. 
 It is certain, in any case, that the use of the words clBt} and 
 IBeao to express ultimate realities is pre-Platonic, and it 
 seems most natural to regard it as of Pythagorean origin. 
 
 We have really exceeded the limits of this work by tracing 
 the history of Pythagoreanism down to a point where it 
 becomes practically indistinguishable from the theories which 
 Plato puts into the mouth of Sokrates ; but it was necessary 
 to do so in order to put the statements of our authorities in 
 their true light. Aristoxenos is not likely to have been 
 mistaken with regard to the opinions of the men he had 
 known personally, and Aristotle's statements must have had 
 some foundation. 
 
 ^ In the Parmenides Plato makes Sokrates expound the theory at a date 
 which is carefully marked as at least twenty years before his own birth. 
 
 2 Plato, Soph. 248 a 4. Proclus says {In Parm. iv. p. 149, Cousin) 
 ^u fxeu yap Kal rrapa Toiis Ylvdayopelois ij irepl tQv eiSQu deupla, Kai drjXoi 
 Kol avrbs iv XocpiaT-Q tQu eldQv cpiXovs irpoaayopeiLxau toi>s iv ^iToklq. (ro(f)o6s, 
 dW 8 ye fxaKicrTa irpecr^eicras Kal Siappr)5r)v vwodifievos ra etdrj 'ZcaKpa.Trjs 
 ia-riv. This is not in itself authoritative ; but it is the only statement 
 on the subject that has come down to us, and Proclus (who had the tradition 
 of the Academy at his command) does not appear to have heard of any 
 other interpretation of the phrase. In a later passage (v. p. 4, Cousin) he 
 says it was natural for Parmenides to ask Sokrates whether he had thought 
 of the theory for himself, since he might have heard a report of it. 
 
CHAPTER VIII 
 
 THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 
 
 Relation 154. The systems we have just been studying were all funda- 
 decessors. mentally pluralist, and they were so because Parmenides had 
 shown that, if we take a corporeal monism seriously, we must 
 ascribe to reality a number of predicates inconsistent with 
 our experience of a world which everywhere displays multi- 
 pHcity, motion, and change (§97). The four "roots" of 
 Empedokles and the innumerable " seeds " of Anaxagoras 
 were both of them conscious attempts to solve the problem 
 Parmenides had raised (§§ 106, 127). There is no evidence, 
 indeed, that the Pythagoreans were directly influenced by 
 Parmenides, but it has been shown (§ 147) how the later form 
 of their system was based on the theory of Empedokles. 
 Now it was just this prevailing pluralism that Zeno criticised 
 from the Eleatic standpoint ; and his arguments were 
 especially directed against Pythagoreanism. Melissos, too, 
 criticises Pythagoreanism ; but he tries to find a common 
 ground with his adversaries by maintaining the old Ionian 
 thesis that reahty is infinite. 
 
 I. Zeno of Elea 
 
 Life. 155. According to Apollodoros,i Zeno flourished in 
 
 01. LXXIX. (464-460 B.C.). This date is arrived at by 
 making him forty years younger than Parmenides, which is 
 
 ^ Diog, ix. 29 (R. P. 130 a), ApoUodoros is not expressly referred to 
 for Zeno's date ; but, as he is quoted for his father's name (ix. 25 ; R. P. 
 130), there can be no doubt that he is also the source of the floruit. 
 
 310 
 
I 
 
 THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 311 
 
 in direct conflict with the testimony of Plato. We have 
 seen already (§ 84) that the meeting of Parmenides and Zeno 
 with the young Sokrates cannot well have occurred before 
 449 B.C., and Plato tells us that Zeno was at that time 
 '* nearly forty years old.'' ^ He must, then, have been bom 
 about 489 B.C., some twenty-five years after Parmenides. 
 He was the son of Teleutagoras, and the statement of 
 ApoUodoros that he had been adopted by Parmenides is 
 only a misunderstanding of an expression of Plato's Sophist.^ 
 He was, Plato further tells us,^ tall and of a graceful 
 appearance. 
 
 Like Parmenides, Zeno played a part in the politics of 
 his native city. Strabo, no doubt on the authority of 
 Timaios, ascribes to him some share of the credit for the 
 good government of Elea, and says that he was a Pytha- 
 gorean.* This statement can easily be explained. Par- 
 menides, we have seen, was originally a Pythagorean, and 
 the school of Elea was naturally regarded as a mere branch 
 of the larger society. We hear also that Zeno conspired 
 against a tyrant, whose name is differently given, and the 
 story of his courage under torture is often repeated, though 
 with varying details.^ 
 
 156. Diogenes speaks of Zeno's " books," and Souidas writings, 
 gives some titles which probably come from the Alexandrian 
 librarians through Hesychios of Miletos.^ In the Parmenides 
 Plato makes Zeno say that the work by which he is best 
 known was written in his youth and pubhshed against his 
 will.' As he is supposed to be forty years old at the time of 
 
 1 Plato, Parm. 127 b (R. P. 11 1 d). The visit of Zeno to Athens is 
 confirmed by Plut. Per. 4 (R. P. 130 e), where we are told that Perikles 
 " heard " him as well as Anaxagoras. It is also alluded to in Ale. I. 119 a, 
 where we are told that Pythodoros, son of Isolochos, and Kallias, son of 
 Kalliades, each paid him 100 minae for instruction. 
 
 2 Plato, Soph. 241 d (R. P. 130 a). 
 
 3 Plato, Parm., loc. cit. * Strabo, vi. p. 252 (R. P. iii c), 
 
 5 Diog. ix. 26, 27, and the other passages referred to in R. P. 130 c. 
 The original of the account given in the tenth book of Diodoros is doubtless 
 Timaios. ^ Diog, ix. 26 (R. P. 130) ; Souidas s.v. (R. P. 130 d). 
 
 7 Plato, Parm. 128 d 6 (R. P. 130 d). 
 
312 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the dialogue, this must mean that the book was written 
 before 460 B.C., and it is very possible that he wrote others 
 after it.^ If he wrote a work against the " philosophers," as 
 Souidas says, that must mean the Pythagoreans, who, as we 
 have seen, made use of the term in a sense of their own.^ 
 The Disputations ('EptBes;) and the Treatise on Nature may, 
 or may not, be the same as the book described in Plato's 
 Parmenides. 
 
 It is not likely that Zeno wrote dialogues, though certain 
 references in Aristotle have been supposed to imply this. In 
 the Physics ^ we hear of an argument of Zeno's, that any 
 part of a heap of millet makes a sound, and Simplicius illus- 
 trates this by quoting a passage from a dialogue between 
 Zeno and Protagoras.* If our chronology is right, it is quite 
 possible that they may have met ; but it is most unlikely 
 that Zeno should have made himself a personage in a dialogue 
 of his own. That was a later fashion. In another place 
 Aristotle refers to a passage where " the answerer and Zeno 
 the questioner " occurred,^ a reference which is most easily 
 to be understood in the same way. Alkidamas seems to have 
 written a dialogue in which Gorgias figured,^ and the exposi- 
 tion of Zeno's arguments in dialogue form must always have 
 been a tempting exercise. 
 
 Plato gives us a clear idea of what Zeno's youthful work 
 I was like. It contained more than one " discourse," and 
 
 ^ The most remarkable title given by Souidas is 'E^i^yria-ts rCjv 'E/xve- 
 doK\^ovs. Of course Zeno did not write a commentary on Empedokles, 
 but Diels points out {Berl. Sitzh., 1884, p. 359) that polemics against philo- 
 sophers were sometimes called i^-qyTjaeis. Cf. the 'RpaKXeirov i^riyrjaets of 
 Herakleides Pontikos and especially his TIpbs rbv ArjfidKpLTOp i^Tjynaeis (Diog. 
 V. 88). 
 
 2 See above, p. 278, n. i. It hardly seems likely that a later writer 
 would make Zeno argue 7rp6s rovs <pi\o<r6<povs, and the title given to the 
 book at Alexandria must be based on something contained in it. 
 
 3 Arist. Phys. H, 5. 250 a 20 (R. P. 131 a). 
 
 * Simpl. Phys. p. 1108, 18 (R. P. 131). If this is what Aristotle refers 
 to, it is hardly safe to attribute the Keyxplr-qs \6yos to Zeno himself. 
 The existence of this dialogue is another indication of Zeno's visit to Athens 
 at an age when he could converse with Protagoras, which agrees very well 
 with Plato's representation of the matter, 
 
 5 Arist. Soph. El. 170 b 22 (R. P. 130 b). « Chap. V. p. 199, n. 5. 
 
 dl 
 
THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 313 
 
 these discourses were subdivided into sections, each dealing 
 with some one j)resu£position of his adversaries.^ We owe 
 the preservation of Zeno's arguments on the one and many 
 to SimpHcius.^ Those relating to motion have been pre- 
 served by Aristotle ; ^ but he has restated them in his own 
 language. ^^ 
 
 157. Aristotle in his Sophist * called Zeno the inventor Dialectic, 
 of dialectic, and that, no doubt, is substantially true, though 
 the beginnings at least of this method of arguing were con- 
 temporary with the foundation of the Eleatic school. Plato ^ 
 gives us a spirited account of the style and purpose of Zeno's 
 book, which he puts into his own mouth : 
 
 In reality, this writing is a sort of reinforcement for the 
 argument of Parmenides against those who try to turn it into 
 ridicule on the ground that, if reality is one, the argument be- 
 comes involved in many absurdities and contradictions. This 
 writing argues against those who uphold a Many, and gives them 
 back as good and better than they gave ; its aim is to show that 
 their assumption of multiplicity will be involved in still more 
 absurdities than the assumption of unity, if it is sufficiently 
 worked out. 
 
 The method of Zeno was, in fact, to take one of his 
 adversaries' fundamental postulates and deduce from it two L.-^ 
 contradictory conclusions. ^ This is what Aristotle meant 
 
 1 Plato, Farm. 127 d. Plato speaks of the first virSdeais of the first 
 \670s, which shows that the book was really divided into separate sections. 
 Proclus {in loc.) says there were forty of these \6yoL altogether. 
 
 2 Simplicius expressly says in one place (p. 140, 30 ; R. P. 133) 
 that he is quoting Kar^ X^^iv. I see no reason to doubt this, as the 
 Academy would certainly have a copy of the work. In that case, the use 
 of the Attic dialect by Zeno is significant. 
 
 3 Arist. Phys. Z, 9. 239 b 9 sqg. * Cf. Diog. ix. 25 (R. P. 130). 
 
 5 Plato, Farm. 128 c (R. P. 130 d). If historians of philosophy had 
 started from this careful statement of Plato's, instead of from Aristotle's 
 loose references, they would not have failed to understand his arguments, 
 as they all did before Tannery. 
 
 ^ The technical terms used in Plato's Farmenides seem to be as old as 
 Zeno himself. The vTrodeais is the provisional assumption of the truth of 
 a certain statement, and takes the form el ttoXM 4<ttl or the like. The 
 word does not mean the assumption of something as a foundation, but the 
 setting before one's self of a statement as a problem to be solved (Ionic 
 
314 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 by calling him the inventor of dialectic, which is just the 
 art of arguing, not from true premisses, but from premisses 
 admitted by the other side. The theory of Parmenides had 
 led to conclusions which contradicted the evidence of the 
 senses, and Zeno's object was not to bring fresh proofs of 
 the theory itself, but simply to show that his opponents' view 
 led to contradictions of a precisely similar nature. 
 Zenoand 158. That Zeuo's dialectic was mainly directed against 
 
 goreanism. the Pythagoreans is certainly suggested by Plato's statement, 
 that it was addressed to the adversaries of Parmenides, who 
 held that things were " a many." ^ Zeller holds, indeed, 
 that it was merely the popular form of the behef that things 
 are many that Zeno set himself to confute ; ^ but it is surely 
 not true that ordinary people beUeve things to be " a many " 
 in the sense required. Plato tells us that the premisses of 
 Zeno's arguments were the behef s of the adversaries of 
 Parmenides, and the postulate from which all his contra- 
 dictions are derived is the view that space, and therefore 
 body, is made up of a number of discrete units, which is just 
 the Pythagorean doctrine. We know from Plato that Zeno's 
 book was the work of his youth.^ It follows that he must 
 have written it in Italy, and the Pythagoreans are the only 
 people who can have criticised the views of Parmenides there 
 and at that date.* 
 
 It will be noted how much clearer the historical position 
 of Zeno becomes if we follow Plato in assigning him to a later 
 date than is usual. UVe^Jiave first Parmenides, then the 
 
 virodiadaL, Attic vpodiadat). If the conclusions (rd avfi^alvovra) which 
 necessarily follow from the virbdeais are impossible, the vwddeats is 
 "destroyed" (cf. Plato, Rep. 533 c 8, rds vvod^a-eLs dvaipouaa). The 
 author of the Ilepi dpxaiTjs larpLKijs (c i) knows the word virbdeai^ in a 
 similar sense. 
 
 ^ The view that Zeno's arguments were directed against Pythagoreanism 
 has been maintained in recent times by Tannery {Science hellene, pp. 249 sqq.), 
 and Baumker {Das Problem der Materie, pp. 60 sqq.). 
 
 2 Zeller, p. 589 (Eng. trans, p. 612). 3 Parm., loc. cit. 
 
 * Empedokles has been suggested. He was about the same age as Zeno, 
 indeed (§ 98), and he seems to criticise Parmenides (§ 106), but the argu- 
 ments of Zeno have no special applicability to his theories. Anaxagoras 
 is still less likely. 
 
THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 315 
 
 pluralists, and then the criticism of Zen(i; This, at any rate, 
 seems to have been the view Aristotle took of the historical 
 development.^ 
 
 159. The polemic of Zeno is clearly directed in the first what is 
 instance against a certain view of the unit. Eudemos, in his *^^ ^"^* ' 
 Physics,^ quoted from him the sa5dng that '* if any one could 
 
 tell him what the unit was, he would be able to say what 
 things are." The commentary of Alexander on this, pre- 
 served by Simplicius, is quite satisfactory. " As Eudemos 
 relates," he says, " Zeno the disciple of Parmenides tried to 
 show that it was impossible that things could be a many, - 
 seeing that there was no unit in things, whereas ' many ' 
 
 means a number of units." ^ Here we have a clear reference 
 
 to_ the Pythagorean view that everything may be reduced to 
 a sum of units, which is what Zeno denied. 
 
 160. The fragments of Zeno himself also show that this The 
 was his line of argument. I give them according to the ^^^^^g^ 
 arrangement of Diels. 
 
 (I) . 
 
 If what is had no magnitude, it would not even be. . . . 
 But, if it is, each one must have a certain magnitude and a certain 
 thickness, and must be at a certain distance from another, and the 
 same may be said of what is in front of it ; for it, too, will have 
 magnitude, and something will be in front of it.* It is all the 
 same to say this once and to say it always ; for no such part of it 
 
 1 Arist. Phys. A, 3. 187 a i (R. P. 134 b). See below, § 173. 
 
 2 Simpl. Phys. p. 138, 32 (R. P. 134 a). 
 
 3 Simpl. Phys. p. 99, 13, ws yap iaropei, (prjo-iv {'AX^^avSpos), Eiidrjimos, 
 Z-qvtjiv b Hapixevlbov yv(hpi.[xos iTreiparo deiKv{ivat 8ti fir) oXbv re to. 6vTa TroXXd 
 elvai Tip fjL7)8^p dvai iv rots odaiv 'iv, to, 8k TroXXot TrXijdoi elpai ivdSuv. 
 This is the meaning of the statement that Zeno dvypei t6 ^v which 
 is not Alexander's (as implied in R. P. 134 a), but goes back to 
 no less an authority than Eudemos. It must be read in connexion 
 with the words rV yap arLyfiriv ws t6 ^v Xe'7et (Simpl. Phys. p. 99, ii). 
 
 * I formerly rendered " the same may be said of what surpasses it in 
 smallness ; for it too will have magnitude, and something will surpass it in 
 smallness." This is Tannery's rendering, but I now agree with Diels in 
 thinking that d^x"" refers to fi^yedos and irpoix^iv to irdxos. Zeno is 
 showing that the Pythagorean point must have three dimensions. 
 
3i6 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 will be the last, nor will one thing not be as compared with 
 another. 1 So, if things are a many, they must be both small 
 and great, so small as not to have any magnitude at all, and so 
 great as to be infinite. R. P. 134. 
 
 (2) 
 
 For if it were added to any other thing it would not make it 
 any larger ; for nothing can gain in magnitude by the addition 
 of what has no magnitude, and thus it follows at once that what 
 was added was nothing.^ But if, when this is taken away from 
 another thing, that thing is no less ; and again, if, when it is 
 added to another thing, that does not increase, it is plain that 
 what was added was nothing, and what was taken away was 
 nothing. R. P. 132. 
 
 (3) 
 
 If things are a many, they must be just as many as they are, 
 and neither more nor less. Now, if they are as many as they 
 are, they will be finite in number. 
 
 If things are a many, they will be infinite in number ; 
 for there will always be other things between them, and others 
 again between these. And so things are infinite in number. 
 R. P. 133.' 
 
 The unit. i6i. If WO hold that the unit has no magnitude — and 
 this is required by what Aristotle calls the argument from 
 dichotomy,* — then everything must be infinitely small. 
 Nothing made up of units without magnitude can itself have 
 any magnitude. On the other hand, if we insist that the 
 units of which things are built up are something and not 
 nothing, we must hold that everything is infinitely great. 
 
 1 Reading, with Diels and the MSS., oijre 'irepov irpbs ^repop oiiK ^trrat. 
 Gomperz's conjecture (adopted in R. P.) seems to me arbitrary. 
 
 2 Zeller marks a lacuna here. Zeno must certainly have shown that 
 the subtraction of a point does not make a thing less ; but he may have 
 done so before the beginning of our present fragment. 
 
 3 This is what Aristotle calls " the argument from dichotomy " (Phys. 
 A, 3. 187 a I ; R, P. 134 b). If a line is made up of points, we ought to 
 be able to answer the question, " How many points are there in a given 
 line ? " On the other hand, you can always divide a line or any part of it 
 into two halves ; so that, if a line is made up of points, there will always 
 be more of them than any number you assign. ' * * See last note. 
 
THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 317 
 
 The line is infinitely divisible ; and, according to this view, 
 it will be made up of an infinite number of units, each of 
 which has some magnitude. 
 
 That this argument refers to points is proved by an 
 instructive passage from Aristotle's Metaphysics.'^ We read 
 there — 
 
 If the unit is indivisible, it will, according to the proposition 
 of Zeno, be nothing. That which neither makes anything larger 
 by its addition to it, nor smaller by its subtraction from it, is not, 
 he says, a real thing at all ; for clearly what is real must be a 
 magnitude. And, if it is a magnitude, it is corporeal ; for that 
 is corporeal which is in every dimension. The other things, 
 i.e. the plane and the line, if added in one way will make things 
 larger, added in another they will produce no effect ; but the 
 point and the unit cannot make things larger in any way. 
 
 From all this it seems impossible to draw any other 
 conclusion than that the " one " against which Zeno argued 
 was the " one " of which a number constitute a " many," 
 and that is just the Pythagorean unit. 
 
 162. Aristotle refers to an argument which seems to be Spacp. 
 directed against the Pythagorean doctrine of space, ^ and 
 SimpUcius quotes it in this form : ^ 
 
 If there is space, it will be in something ; for all that is is in 
 something, and what is in something is in space. So space will 
 be in space, and this goes on ad infinitum, therefore there is no 
 space. R. P. 135. 
 
 What Zeno is really arguing against here is the attempt 
 to distinguish space from the body that occupies it. If we 
 insist that body must be in space, then we must go on to ask 
 what space itself is in. This is a " reinforcement " of the 
 Parmenidean denial of the void. Possibly the argument that 
 
 1 Arist. Met. B, 4. looi b 7. 
 
 2 Arist. Phys. A, i. 209 a 23 ; 3. 210 b 22 (R. P. 135 a). 
 
 3 Simpl. Phys. p. 562, 3 (R. P. 135). The version of Eudemos is 
 given in Simpl. Phys. p. 563, 26, a^Lot yap wav rb dv ttoO elvai • ei S^ 6 
 tSttos tCov 6vt(i}v, ttoO Av elrj ; oiKovp iu AXXy rdircf KUKeivos dij iv dXXy /cai 
 oCrwj els t6 irp6<xu}. 
 
3i8 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 everything must be " in " something, or must have something 
 beyond it, had been used against the Parmenidean theory of 
 a finite sphere with nothing outside it. 
 Motion. 163. Zeno's arguments on the subject of motion have 
 
 been preserved by Aristotle himself. The system of Par- 
 menides made all motion impossible, and his successors had 
 been driven to abandon the monistic hypothesis in order to 
 avoid this very consequence. Zeno does not bring any fresh 
 proofs of the impossibility of motion ; all he does is to show 
 that a pluralist theory, such as the Pythagorean, is just as 
 unable to explain it as was that of Parmenides. Looked at 
 in this way, Zeno's arguments are no mere quibbles, but mark 
 a great advance in the conception of quantity. They are as 
 follows : 
 
 (i) You cannot cross a race-course. ^ You cannot traverse 
 an infinite number of points in a finite time. You must traverse 
 the half of any given distance before you traverse the whole, and 
 the half of that again before you can traverse it. This goes on 
 ad infinitum, so that there are an infinite number of points in 
 any given space, and you cannot touch an infinite number one by 
 one in a finite time.^ 
 
 (2) Achilles will never overtake the tortoise. He must first 
 reach the place from which the tortoise started. By that time 
 the tortoise will have got some way ahead. Achilles must then 
 make up that, and again the tortoise will be ahead. He is 
 always coming nearer, but he never makes up to it.^ 
 
 The " hypothesis '* of the second argument is the same 
 as that of the first, namely, that the line is a series of points ; 
 but the reasoning is compHcated by the introduction of 
 another moving object. The difference, accordingly, is not 
 a half every time, but diminishes in a constant ratio. Again, 
 the first argument shows that, on this hypothesis, no moving 
 object can ever traverse any distance at all, however fast it 
 
 ^ Arist. Top. 0, 8. 160 b 8, Ti-qvoyvo^ (\670s), 6tl ovk ivd^x^T'^'- KiveiadaL 
 ovbk TO (rrddiov dLcXdeXv. 
 
 2 Arist. Phys. Z, g, 239 b 11 (R. P. 136). Cf. Z, 2. 233 an; a 21 
 (R. P. 136 a). 
 
 3 Arist. Phys. Z, 9- 239 b 14 (R. P. 137). 
 
THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 319 
 
 may move ; the second emphasises the fact that, however 
 slowly it moves, it will traverse an infinite distance. ^ 
 
 (3) The arrow in flight is at rest. For, if everything is at 
 rest when it occupies a space equal to itself, and what is in flight 
 at any given moment always occupies a space equal to itself, it 
 cannot move.^ 
 
 Here a further complication is introduced. The moving 
 object itself has length, and its successive positions are not 
 points but lines. The first two arguments are intended to 
 destroy the hypothesis that a line consists of an infinite 
 number of indivisibles ; this argument and the next deal 
 with the hypothesis that it consists of a finite ^ number of 
 indivisibles. 
 
 (4) Half the time may be equal to double the time. Let 
 us suppose three rows of bodies,* one of which (A) is at 
 rest while the other two (B, C) are moving with equal 
 velocity in opposite directions (Fig. i). By the time they 
 are all in the same part of the course, B will have passed 
 twice as many of the bodies in C as in A (Fig. 2). 
 
 FIG. I. FIG. 2. 
 
 • ••• A«««« 
 
 &••••-> B 9 m 9 • 
 
 ^KC ■<- •••• C % m 9 9 
 
 ^^ Therefore the time which it takes to pass C is twice as long as 
 the time it takes to pass A. But the time which B and C take 
 
 1 As Mr. Jourdain puts it {Mind, 1916, p. 42), " the first argument 
 shows that motion can never begin ; the second argument shows that the 
 slower moves as fast as the faster," on the hypothesis that a line is infinitely 
 divisible into its constituent points. 
 
 2 Phys. Z, 9, 239 b 30 (R. P. 138) ; ib. 239 b 5 (R. P. 138 a). The 
 latter passage is corrupt, though the meaning is plain. I have translated 
 Zeller's version of it : e^ ydp, (p-qaiv, ripeixei ttSj' brau ri Kark rb laov, iari 5' 
 ael t6 (l)€p6fJt.epov iv ry vvv Kara t6 taov, aKivrjTOP k.t.X. Of course del 
 means " at any time," not " always," and Kara rb iaov is, literally, " on 
 a level with a space equal (to itself)." For other readings, see Zeller, 
 p. 598, n. 3 ; and Diels, Vors. 19 a 27. 
 
 3 See Jourdain {loc. cit.). 
 
 4 The word is 67/fot ; cl Chap. VII. p. 291, n. 3. The name is very 
 appropriate for the Pythagorean units, which Zeno had shown to have 
 
320 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 to reach the position of A is the same. Therefore double the 
 time is equal to the half.^ 
 
 According to Aristotle, the paralogism here depends on 
 the assumption that an equal magnitude moving with equal 
 velocity must move for an equal time, whether the magni- 
 \tude with which it is equal is at rest or in motion. That is 
 certainly so, but we are not to suppose that this assumption 
 is Zeno's own. The fourth argument is, in fact, related to 
 the third just as the second is to the first. The Achilles adds 
 a second moving point to the single moving point of the first 
 argument ; this argument adds a second moving hne to the 
 single moving line of the arrow in flight. The lines, however, 
 are represented as a series of units, which is just how the 
 Pythagoreans represented them ; and it is quite true that, if 
 Hues are a sum of discrete units, and time is similarly a series 
 of discrete moments, there is no other measure of motion 
 possible than the number of units which each unit passes. 
 
 This argument, like the others, is intended to bring out 
 the absurd conclusions which follow from the assumption 
 that all quantity is discrete, and what Zeno has really done 
 is to estabhsh the conception of continuous quantity by a 
 reductio ad absurdum of the other hypothesis. If we re- 
 member that Parmenides had asserted the one to be con- 
 tinuous (fr. 8, 25), we shall see how accurate is the account of 
 Zeno's method which Plato puts into the mouth of Sokrates. 
 
 II. Melissos of Samos 
 
 Life. 164. In his Life of Perikles, Plutarch teUs us, on the 
 authority of Aristotle, that the philosopher MeUssos, son of 
 Ithagenes, was the Samian general who defeated the Athenian 
 
 ^ Arist. Phys. Z, 9. 239 b 33 (R. P. 139). I have had to express the 
 argument in my own way, as it is not fully given by any of the authorities. 
 The figure is practically Alexander's (Simpl. Phys. p. 1016, 14), except 
 that he represents the 67/coi by letters instead of dots. The conclusion is 
 plainly stated by Aristotle {loc. cit.), avix^aiveLv oterai laov elvai XP^^^^ 
 ry dnrXaffiip rbv TJfjLiavv, and, however we explain the reasoning, it must 
 be so represented as to lead to the conclusion that, as Mr. Jourdain puts 
 it {loc. cit.), *' a body travels twice as fast as it does." 
 
ments. 
 
 THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 321 
 
 fleet in 441/0 B.C. ; ^ and it was no doubt for this reason that 
 ApoUodoros fixed his floruit in 01. LXXXIV. {444-41 B.C.). 2 
 Beyond this, we really know nothing about his life. He is 
 said to have been, like Zeno, a disciple of Parmenides ; ^ but, 
 as he was a Samian, it is possible that he was originally a 
 member of the Ionic school, and we shall see that certain 
 features of his doctrine tend to bear out this view. On 
 the other hand, he was certainly convinced by the Eleatic 
 dialectic, and renounced the Ionic doctrine in so far as it 
 was inconsistent with that. We note here the effect of 
 the increased facility of intercourse between East and 
 West, which was secured by the supremacy of Athens. 
 
 165. The fragments which we have come from Simplicius, TheFrag- 
 and are given, with the exception of the first, from the text 
 of Diels.4 
 
 {la) If nothing is, what can be said of it as of something 
 real ? ^ 
 
 (i) What was was ever, and ever shall be. For, if it had 
 come into being, it needs must have been nothing before it came 
 
 ^ Plut. Per. 26 (R. P. 141 b), from Aristotle's 'Laixlwv iroKiTeia. 
 
 2 Diog. ix. 24. (R. P. 141). It is possible, of course, that ApoUodoros 
 meant the first and not the fourth year of the Olympiad. That is his 
 usual era, the foundation of Thourioi. But, on the whole, it is more 
 likely that he meant the fourth ; for the date of the vavapxla would be 
 given with precision. See Jacoby, p. 270. 
 
 3 Diog. ix. 24 (R. P. 141). 
 * It is no longer necessary to discuss the passages which used to appear 
 
 as frs. 1-5 of Melissos, as it has been proved by A. Pabst that they are 
 merely a paraphrase of the genuine fragments {De Melissi Samii fragmentis, 
 Bonn, 1889). Almost simultaneously I had independently come to the 
 same conclusion (see the first edition, § 138). Zeller and Diels have both 
 accepted Pabst's demonstration, and the supposed fragments have been 
 relegated to the notes in the last edition of R. P. I still believe, however, 
 that the fragment which I have numbered la is genuine. See next 
 note. 
 
 5 This fragment is from the beginning of the paraphrase which was 
 so long mistaken for the words of Melissos (Simpl. Phys. p. 103, 18 ; R. P. 
 142 a), and Diels has removed it along with the rest. I beUeve it to 
 be genuine because Simplicius, who had access to the original, introduces 
 it by the words dpxeraL rod avyypdjj.fjLaTos ovtojs, and because it is thoroughly 
 Eleatic in character. It is quite natural that the first words of the book 
 should be prefixed to the paraphrase. , 
 
 21 
 
 I 
 
322 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 into being. Now, if it were nothing, in no wise could anything 
 have arisen out of nothing. R. P. 142. 
 
 (2) Since, then, it has not come into being, and since it is, 
 was ever, and ever shall be, it has no beginning or end, but is 
 without limit. For, if it had come into being, it would have had 
 a beginning (for it would have begun to come into being at 
 some time or other) and an end (for it would have ceased to 
 come into being at some time or other) ; but, if it neither began 
 nor ended, and ever was and ever shall be, it has no beginning 
 or end ; for it is not possible for anything to be ever without all 
 being. R. P. 143. 
 
 (3) Further, just as it ever is, so it must ever be infinite in 
 magnitude. R. P. 143. 
 
 (4) But nothing which has a beginning or end is either eternal 
 or infinite. R. P. 143. 
 
 (5) If it were not one, it would be bounded by something 
 else. R. P. 144 a. 
 
 (6) For if it is (infinite), it must be one ; for if it were two, it 
 could not be infinite ; for then they would be bounded by one 
 another. 1 R. P. 144. 
 
 {6a) (And, since it is one, it is ahke throughout ; for if it were 
 unlike, it would be many and not one.) ^ 
 
 (7) So then it is eternal and infinite and one and all alike. 
 And it cannot perish nor become greater, nor does it suffer pain 
 or grief. For, if any of these things happened to it, it would no 
 longer be one. For if it is altered, then the real must needs not be 
 aU alike, but what was before must pass away, and what was not 
 must come into being. Now, if it changed by so much as a single 
 hair in ten thousand years, it would all perish in the whole of 
 time. 
 
 Further, it is not possible either that its order should be 
 changed ; for the order which it had before does not perish, nor 
 does that which was not come into being. But, since nothing is 
 either added to it or passes away or is altered, how can any real 
 
 1 This fragment is quoted by Simpl. De caelo, p. 557, 16 (R. P. 144). 
 The insertion of the word " infinite " is justified by the paraphrase (R. P. 
 
 144 a) and by M.X.G. 974 a 11, ttS;/ 5k dwetpov dv <^j/> etvaL- el yap Si^o 
 ■^ TrXetoj ei'77, irepar b-v elvai raOra irpbs dWriXa. 
 
 2 I have ventured to insert this, though the actual words are nowhere 
 quoted, and it is not in Diels. It is represented in the paraphrase (R. P. 
 
 145 a) and in M.X.G. 974 a 13 (R. P. 144 a). 
 
 ■ 
 
THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 323 
 
 thing have had its order changed ? For if anything became 
 different, that would amount to a change in its order. 
 
 Nor does it suffer pain ; for a thing in pain could not all be. 
 For a thing in pain could not be ever, nor has it the same power 
 as what is whole. Nor would it be alike, if it were in pain ; for it 
 is only from the addition or subtraction of something that it 
 could feel pain, and then it would no longer be alike. Nor could 
 what is whole feel pain ; for then what was whole and what 
 was real would pass away, and what was not would come 
 into being. And the same argument applies to grief as to 
 pain. 
 
 Nor is anything empty. For what is empty is nothing. What 
 is nothing cannot be. 
 
 Nor does it move ; for it has nowhere to betake itself to, but 
 is full. For if there were aught empty, it would betake itself 
 to the empty. But, since there is naught empty, it has nowhere 
 to betake itself to. 
 
 And it cannot be dense and rare ; for it is not possible for 
 what is rare to be as full as what is dense, but what is rare is at 
 once emptier than what is dense. 
 
 This is the way in which we must distinguish between what 
 is full and what is not full. If a thing has room for anything 
 else, and takes it in, it is not full ; but if it has no room for any- 
 thing and does not take it in, it is full. 
 
 Now, it must needs be full if there is naught empty, and if it 
 is full, it does not move. R. P. 145. 
 
 (8) This argument, then, is the greatest proof that it is one 
 alone ; but the following are proofs of it also. If there were a 
 many, these would have to be of the same kind as I say that the 
 one is. For if there is earth and water, and air and iron, and gold 
 and fire, and if one thing is living and another dead, and if things 
 are black and white and all that men say they really are, — if that 
 is so, and if we see and hear aright, each one of these must be 
 such as we first decided, and they cannot be changed or altered, 
 but each must be just as it is. But, as it is, we say that we see 
 and hear and understand aright, and yet we believe that what is 
 warm becomes cold, and what is cold warm ; that what is hard 
 turns soft, and what is soft hard ; that what is living dies, and 
 that things are born from what lives not ; and that all those 
 things are changed, and that what they were and what they are 
 now are in no way alike. We think that iron, which is hard, is 
 
 I 
 
324 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 rubbed away by contact with the finger ; ^ and so with gold and 
 stone and everything which we fancy to be strong, and that 
 earth and stone are made out of water ; so that it turns out that 
 we neither see nor know reaUties. Now these things do not agree 
 with one another. We said that there were many things that 
 were eternal and had forms and strength of their own, and yet we 
 fancy that they all suffer alteration, and that they change from 
 what we see each time. It is clear, then, that we did not see 
 aright after aU, nor are we right in beHeving that all these things 
 are many. They would not change if they were real, but each 
 thing would be just what we believed it to be ; for nothing is 
 • stronger than true reality. But if it has changed, what was has 
 passed away, and what was not is come into being. So then, if 
 there were many things, they would have to be just of the same 
 nature as the one. R. P. 147. 
 
 (9) Now, if it were to exist, it must needs be one ; but if it 
 is one, it cannot have body ; for, if it had body it would have 
 parts, and would no longer be one. R. P. 146.^ 
 
 (10) If what is real is divided, it moves ; but if it moves, it 
 cannot be. R. P. 144 a.^ 
 
 Theory of i66. It has been pointed out that Melissos was not 
 reauty. perhaps originally a member of the Eleatic school ; but he 
 certainly adopted all the views of Parmenides as to the true 
 nature of reality with one remarkable exception. He appears 
 to have opened his treatise with a reassertion of the Par- 
 menidean " Nothing is not " (fr. id), and the arguments by 
 which he supported this view are those with which we are 
 already famihar (fr. i). ReaUty, as with Parmenides, is 
 eternal, a point which Melissos expressed in a way of his own. 
 He argued that since everything that has come into being 
 has a beginning and an end, everything that has not come 
 into being has no beginning or end. Aristotle is very hard 
 on him for this simple conversion of a universal affirmative 
 
 1 Reading d/xovp^ojy with Bergk. Diels keeps the MS. ofjiov p^cou ; Zeller 
 (p. 613, n. i) conjectures vtt' loO p^wv. 
 
 2 I read ei [xh odv et-q with E F for the ei [xh ov elrj of D. The ibv 
 which still stands in R. P. is a piece of local colour due to the editors. 
 Diels also now reads ovv. 
 
 3 Diels now reads dXXd with E for the d/xa of F, and attaches the word 
 to the next sentence. 
 
 ■ 
 
THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 325 
 
 proposition ; 1 but, of course, his belief was not founded on 
 
 that. His whole conception of reality made it necessary for 
 
 him to regard it as eternal. ^ It would be more serious if 
 
 Aristotle were right in believing, as he seems to have done, 
 
 that Melissos inferred that what is must be infinite in space, ^ 
 
 because it had neither beginning nor end in time.^ As, 
 
 however, we have the fragment which Aristotle interprets in 
 
 this way (fr. 2), we are quite entitled to understand it for 
 
 ourselves, and I cannot see anything to justify Aristotle's 
 
 assumption that the expression " without limit *' means 
 
 without Umit in space.* 
 
 167. Melissos did indeed differ from Parmenides in hold- Reality 
 ing that reahty was spatially as well as temporally infinite ; ^gnite.-^ 
 but he gave an excellent reason for this behef, and had no 
 need to support it by such an extraordinary argument. What 
 he said was that, if it were Umited, it would be Umited by 
 empty space. This we know from Aristotle himself,^ and 
 it marks a real advance upon Parmenides. He had thought 
 it possible to regard reahty as a finite sphere, but it would 
 have been difficult for him to work out this view in detail. 
 He would have had to say there was nothing outside the 
 sphere ; but no one knew better than he that there is no 
 
 1 Arist. Phys. A, 3. 1 86 a 7 (R. P. 143 a). The false conversion is also 
 mentioned in Soph. El. 168 b 35 (R. P. ih.). So Eudemos ap. Simpl. 
 Phys. p. 105, 24, oil ydp, el rb yevojmepov dpxvf ^X^h t^ M yevofxevou dpxy)v 
 ovK ex^L, fJ.dX\ou 5e to fxr] ^x°^ ^PXW ow iyiveTO. 
 
 2 The real reason is given in the paraphrase in Simpl. Phys. p. 103, 21 
 (R. P. 142 a), avyx'^P^^'^^-'- 7'^P >^°-^ tovto vtto tQiv (pvaLKihv, though Melissos 
 himself would not have put it in that way. He regarded hiniself as a 
 (pva-LKds like the rest ; but, from the time of Aristotle, it was a common- 
 place that the Eleatics were not (pvcnKoi, since they denied motion. 
 
 2 Cf. especially Soph. El. 168 b 39, ws dixcpcj ravrd 6vTa t^j dpxh^ ^X"''} '''^'^^ 
 yeyovbs kuI rb ireTrepaafi&ov. The same point is made in 167 b 13 and 181 a 27. 
 
 4 The words dX\' direipdv eari mean simply " but it is without limit," 
 and this is simply a repetition of the statement that it has no beginning or 
 end. The nature of the limit can only be determined by the context, and 
 accordingly, when Melissos does introduce the subject of spatial infinity, 
 he is careful to say Tb fxeyedos d-n-eipov (fr. 3). 
 
 5 Arist. Gen. Corr. A, 8. 325 a 14, iv Kai ddv-qTov rb trdv elvaL (paai Kal 
 diretpov iuLOL ' rb ydp iripas irepalveLV dv irpbs rb Kevbv. That this refers 
 
 [elissos has been shown by Zeller (p. 612, w. 2). 
 
326 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 such thing as nothing. Melissos saw that you cannot imagine 
 a finite sphere without regarding it as surrounded by an 
 infinite empty space ; ^ and as, in common with the rest of 
 the school, he denied the void (fr. 7), he was forced to say 
 reahty was spatially infinite (fr. 3). It is possible that he was 
 influenced in this by his association with the Ionic school. 
 
 From the infinity of reality, it follows that it must be 
 one ; for, if it were not one, it would be bounded by some- 
 thing else (fr. 5). And, being one, it must be homogeneous 
 throughout (fr. 6a), for that is what we mean by one. Reahty, 
 then, is a single, homogeneous, corporeal plenum, stretching 
 out to infinity in space, and going backwards and forwards 
 to infinity in time, 
 opposi- ^^^' Eleaticism was always critical, and we are not 
 tionto without indications of the attitude taken up by Melissos 
 
 lonians. ^ '' 
 
 towards contemporary systems. The flaw which he found 
 in the Ionian theories was that they all assumed some want 
 of homogeneity in the One, which was a real inconsistency. 
 Further, they all allowed the possibiUty of change ; but, if 
 all things are one, change must be a form of coming into 
 being and passing away. If you admit that a thing can 
 change, you cannot maintain that it is eternal. Nor can the 
 arrangement of the parts of reality alter, as Anaximander, 
 for instance, had held ; any such change necessarily involves 
 a coming into being and passing away. 
 
 The next point made by Melissos is somewhat peculiar. 
 ReaUty, he says, cannot feel sorrow or pain ; for that is 
 always due to the addition or subtraction of something, 
 which is impossible. It is not easy to be sure what this 
 refers to. Perhaps it is to the theory by which Anax- 
 agoras explained perception. 2 
 
 1 Note the disagreement with Zeno (§ 162). 
 
 2 See p. 273. It is clear that Anaxagoras made considerable use of 
 pain {jhvoi), and it is possible that his doctrine, summed up in the words 
 dei Trove? to ^cpov (Arist, Eth. Nic. H, 15. 1 1 54 b 7) had a wider application 
 than appears from his remains. Aristotle {De caelo, B, i. 284 a 15) makes 
 a point of the oiipav6s being dirovos. 
 
THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 327 
 
 Motion in general ^ and rarefaction and condensation 
 in particular are impossible ; for both imply the existence \ 
 of empty space. Divisibility is excluded for the same | 
 reason. These are the same arguments as Parmenides ' 
 employed. 
 
 169. In nearly all accounts of the system of Melissos, we opposi- 
 find it stated that he denied the corporeaUty of what is real, p°tha°- 
 — an opinion which is supported by a reference to fr. 9, which goreans. 
 is certainly quoted by Simplicius to prove this very point. ^ 
 If, however, our general view as to the character of early 
 Greek philosophy is correct, the statement must seem in- 
 credible. And it will seem even more surprising when we 
 find that in the Metaphysics Aristotle says that, while the 
 unity of Parmenides seemed to be ideal, that of Melissos was 
 material.3 Now the fragment, as it stands in the MSS. of 
 SimpHcius,* puts a purely hypothetical case, and would most 
 naturally be understood as a disproof of the existence of 
 something on the ground that, if it existed, it would have to 
 be both corporeal and one. This cannot refer to the Eleatic 
 One, in which MeHssos himself beUeved ; and, as the argu- 
 ment is almost verbally the same as one of Zeno's,^ it is 
 natural to suppose that it also was directed against the 
 Pythagorean assumption of ultimate units. The only 
 possible objection is that Simplicius, who twice quotes the 
 
 1 The view of Baumker that Melissos admitted dpTLirepla-Taan or motion 
 inpleno {Jahrb.f. kl. Phil, 1886, p. 541 ; Das Problem der Materie, p. 59) 
 depends upon some words of Simplicius {Phys. p. 104, 13), ovx Htl fxr] dwarbv 
 Sto. irXiQpovs Kivelffdai, (is iirl tQiv auimaTuv \4yofxev ktX. These words were 
 formerly turned into Ionic and passed off as a fragment of Melissos. They 
 are, however, part of Simplicius's own argument against Alexander, and 
 have nothing to do with Melissos at all. 
 
 2 See, however, Baumker, Das Problem der Materie, pp. 57 sqq., who 
 remarks that iSv (or 6v) in fr. 9 must be the predicate, as it has no article. 
 In his fifth edition (p. 611, n. 2) Zeller adopted the view here taken. 
 He rightly observes that the hypothetical form ei ixku bv dn) speaks for it, 
 and that the subject to et-q must be kKaarov tQp ttoXXcDv, as with Zeno. 
 
 3 Met. A, 5. 986 b 18 (R. P. loi). 
 
 * Brandis changed the ei-q to lorri, but there is no warrant for this. 
 5 Cf. Zeno, fr. i, especially the words ei 5^ ^o-tlv, dvdyKr) ^Kaarov 
 fjt.4y€d6s TL ^x^tv Kal Trdxos. 
 
328 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 fragment, certainly took it in the sense usually given to 
 it.i But it was very natural for him to make this mistake. 
 " The One " was an expression that had two senses in the 
 middle of the fifth century B.C. ; it meant either the whole 
 of reality or the point as a spatial unit. To maintain it in 
 the first sense, the Eleatics were obliged to disprove it in the 
 second ; and so it sometimes seemed that they were speaking 
 of their own " One " when they really meant the other. We 
 have seen that the very same difficulty was felt about Zeno's 
 denial of the " one.*' 2 
 opposi- 170. The most remarkable fragment of Mehssos is, 
 Anax- perhaps, the last (fr. 8). It seems to be directed against 
 agoras. Anaxagoras ; at least the language seems more applicable 
 to him than any one else. Anaxagoras had admitted 
 (§ 137, fin,) that, so far as our perceptions go, they do not 
 agree with his theory, though he held this was due solely 
 to their weakness. Mehssos, taking advantage of this 
 admission, urges that, if we give up the senses as the test 
 of reahty, we are not entitled to reject the Eleatic theory. 
 With wonderful penetration he points out that if we are to 
 say, with Anaxagoras, that things are a many, we are bound 
 also to say that each one of them is such as the Eleatics 
 declared the One to be. In other words, the only consistent 
 plurahsm is the atomic theory. 
 
 Mehssos has been unduly depreciated owing to the 
 criticisms of Aristotle ; but these, we have seen, are based 
 mainly on a somewhat pedantic objection to the false con- 
 version in the early part of the argument. Mehssos knew 
 nothing about the rules of conversion ; and he could easily 
 have made his reasoning formally correct without modifying 
 his system. His greatness consisted in this, that not only 
 was he the real systematiser of Eleaticism, but he was also 
 able to see, before the plurahsts saw it themselves, the only 
 way in which the theory that things are a many could 
 
 1 Simpl. Phys. pp. 87, 6, and no, i. 
 2 See above, § 159, p. 315, n. 3. 
 
THE YOUNGER ELEATICS 
 
 329 
 
 consistently worked out.^ It is significant that Polybos, the 
 nephew of Hippokrates, reproaches those " sophists " who 
 taught there was only one primary substance with " putting 
 the doctrine of Melissos on its feet." ^ 
 
 1 Baumker, op. cit. p. 58, m. 3 : " That Melissos was a weakling is 
 a fable convenue that people repeat after Aristotle, who was unable to 
 appreciate the Eleatics in general, and in particular misunderstood Melissos 
 not inconsiderably." 
 
 2 Ilepi tpijaLos dvOpdowov, c, I, dW e/xoiye doKiovaiv oi toioutol dvdpcoiroL 
 avTol eojvTods Kara^dWeiv iv toZclv dvofiacn tQiv Xdyuv avrCov inrb da-vveairjs, 
 Thp 5k '},U\l(xaov Xoyov opOovv. The metaphors are taken from wrestling, 
 and were current at this date (cf. the KarafidWovTes of Protagoras). Plato 
 implies a more generous appreciation of Melissos than Aristotle's. In 
 Theaet. 180 e 2, he refers to the Eleatics as MAttro-ot re Kal Hap/ievidai, 
 and in 183 e 4 he almost apologises for giving the pre-eminence to 
 Parmenides. 
 
CHAPTER IX 
 
 LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 
 
 Leukippos 171. We have seen (§§ 31, 122) that the school of Miletos 
 Demo- did not come to an end with Anaximenes, and it is a striking 
 ^^°^* fact that the man who gave the most complete answer to the 
 question first . sked by Thales was a Milesian. ^ It is trme 
 that the very existence of Leukippos has been called im 
 question. Epicurus is reported to have said there never was 
 such a philosopher, and the same thing has been maintained 
 in quite recent times. ^ On the other hand, Aristotle and 
 Theophrastos certainly made him the originator of the atomic 
 theory, and they can hardly have been mistaken on such a 
 point. Aristotle was specially interested in Demokritos, and 
 his native Stageiros is not very far from Abdera, the seat of 
 the Atomist school. 
 
 1 Theophrastos said he was an Eleate or a Milesian (R. P. 185), while 
 Diogenes (ix. 30) says he was an Eleate or, according to some, an Abderite. 
 These statements are just like the discrepancies about the native cities of 
 Pythagoreans already noted (Chap. VII. p. 283, n. i). Diogenes adds 
 that, according to others, Leukippos was a Melian, which is a common con- 
 fusion. Actios (i. 7. i) calls Diagoras of Melos a Milesian (cf. Dox. p. 14). 
 Demokritos was called by some a Milesian (Diog. ix. 34; R. P. 186) 
 for the same reason that Leukippos is called an Eleate. We may also 
 compare the doubt as to whether Herodotos called himself a Halikar- 
 nassian or a Thourian. 
 
 2 Diog. X. 13 (R. P. 185 b), d\V ovdk Ae^KLinrov riva yeyevrjadal (f>7)(Tt. 
 (f>CKb(TO(})ov o{}t€ avrbs (sc. 'EwiKovpos) oijTe"Epfj.apxos. This led E. Rohde to main- 
 tain that Leukippos never existed (Kl. Schr. i. 205), but this is to make 
 too much of a characteristic Epicurean sally. I suggest that Epicurus said 
 something Hke AeOKL-n-rrov ov8' el yiyoveu oWa, which would be idiomatic 
 Greek for "I (purposely) ignore him," "I dechne to discuss him." 
 (Cf. e.g. Dem. De cor. § 70 ZeppLou 5k Kal AopiaKov Kal ttjv Ueirapifidov 
 irbpdt)aLv . . . 0^5' et yiyovev oT5a.) That would be just like Epicurus. 
 
 330 
 
 di 
 
LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 331 
 
 The question is intimately bound up with that of the 
 date of Demokritos, who said that he himself was a young 
 man in the old age of Anaxagoras, a statement which makes 
 it unhkely that he founded his school at Abdera much before 
 420 B.C., the date given by ApoUodoros for his floruit.'^ Now 
 Theophrastos stated that Diogenes of Apollonia borrowed 
 some of his views from Anaxagoras and some fromLeukippos,^ 
 which must mean that there were traces of the atomic theory 
 in his work. Further, Diogenes is parodied in the Clouds of 
 Aristophanes, which was produced in 423 B.C., from which it 
 follows that the work of Leukippos must have become known 
 before that date. What that work was, Theophrastos also 
 tells us. It was the Great Diakosmos usually attributed to 
 Demokritos.3 This means further that what were known 
 later as the works of Demokritos were really the writings of 
 the school of Abdera, and included, as was natural, the works 
 of its founder. They formed, in fact, a corpus like that which 
 has come down to us under the name of Hippokrates, and 
 it was no more possible to distinguish the authors of the 
 different treatises in the one case than it is in the other. 
 
 Theophrastos found Leukippos described as an Eleate 
 in some authorities, and, if we may trust analogy, that means 
 he had settled at Elea.* It is possible that his emigration 
 
 ^ Diog. ix. 41 (R. P. 187). As Diels says, the statement suggests that 
 Anaxagoras was dead when Demokritos wrote. It is probable, too, that 
 this is what made ApoUodoros fix his floruit just forty years after that of 
 Anaxagoras (Jacoby, p. 290). We cannot make much of the statement 
 of Demokritos that he wrote the Mtfcpos biaKoaixo^ 750 years after the 
 fall of Troy ; for we cannot tell what era he used (Jacoby, p. 292). 
 
 2 Theophr. ap. Simpl. Phys. p. 25, i (R. P. 206 a). 
 
 3 This was stated by Thrasylos in his Ust of the tetralogies in which he 
 arranged the works of Demokritos, as he did those of Plato. He gives 
 Tetr. iii, thus : (i) M^7as StdtKocr/ios {tv oi ire pi QeStppaarou AevKiirirov 
 (paaiv elvaL) ] (2) MiKpds 5l6.ko(tixo$ ; {3) Kocr/JLoypacpLr} ', (4) Uepl rG>v 
 irKav7)TU}v. The two SidKoafioi would only be distinguished as fxiya^ and 
 ixLKpbs when they came to be included in the same corpus. A quotation 
 from the Hepl vov of Leukippos is preserved in Stob. i. 160. The phrase 
 iv Toh AevKlirirov KoXovfiivoLi \670ts in M.X.G. 980 a 8 seems to refer 
 to Arist. De gen. corr. A, 8. 325 a 24, AevKnnros 8' ix^iv (^rjdrj \6yovs kt\. 
 Cf. Chap. II. p. 126, n. i. 
 
 * See above, p. 330, n. i. 
 
332 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 was connected with the revolution at Miletos in 450-49 B.c.^ 
 In any case, Theophrastos says distinctly that he had been 
 a member of the school of Parmenides, and his words suggest 
 that the founder of that school was then still at its head. 2 
 He may quite well have been so, if we accept Plato's 
 chronology.^ Theophrastos also appears to have said that 
 Leukippos ** heard " Zeno, which is very credible. We shall 
 see, at any rate, that the influence of Zeno on his thinking is 
 unmistakable.^ 
 
 The relations of Leukippos to Empedokles and Anax- 
 agoras are more difficult to determine. It has become part 
 of the case for the historical reahty of Leukippos to say that 
 there are traces of atomism in the systems of these men ; 
 but the case is strong enough without that assmnption. The 
 chief argument for the view that Leukippos influenced 
 Empedokles is that drawn from the doctrine of " pores " ; 
 but we have seen that this originated with Alkmaion, and 
 it is therefore more probable that Leukippos derived it from 
 Empedokles.^ Nor is it at all probable that Anaxagoras 
 knew anything of the theory of Leukippos. It is true that 
 he denied the existence of the void ; but it does not follow 
 that any one had already maintained that doctrine in the 
 atomist sense. The early Pythagoreans had spoken of a 
 void too, though they had confused it with atmospheric air ; 
 and the experiments of Anaxagoras with the klepsydra and 
 the inflated skins would only have had any point if they were 
 directed against the Pythagorean theory.^ If he had really 
 
 1 Cf. [Xen.] 'A^. ttoX. 3, ii. The date is fixed by C.I. A. i. 22 a. 
 
 2 Theophr. ap. Simpl. Phys. p. 28, 4 (R. P. 185). Note the differ- 
 ence of case in KOiviov-qaas Uapfiepidr} r^s 0t\ocro0tas and Koivujvrjcras rijs 
 'Ava^iju^vovs (f)c\o<xo(pias, which is the phrase used by Theophrastos of 
 Anaxagoras (p. 253, n. 2). The dative seems to imply a personal relation- 
 ship. It is quite inadmissible to render " was familiar with the doctrine of 
 Parmenides," as is done in Gomperz, Greek Thinkers, vol. i. p. 345. 
 
 ' See § 84. 
 
 * Cf. Diog. ix. 30, odros iJKovae Zrjvwvos (R. P. 1 85 b) ; and Hipp. 
 Ref. i. 12, I, AevKLiriros . . . Z'/jvupos iraipos. 
 6 See above, Chap. V. p. 194, n. 3. 
 6 See above. Chap. VI. § 131 ; and Chap. VII. § 145. 
 
LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 333 
 
 wished to refute Leukippos, he would have had to use 
 arguments of a very different kind. 
 
 172. Theophrastos wrote of Leukippos as follows in the Theo- 
 First Book of his Opinions : onThe°^ 
 
 atomic 
 
 Leukippos of Elea or Miletos (for both accounts are given theory. 
 of him) had associated with Parmenides in philosophy. He did 
 not, however, foUow the same path in his explanation of things 
 as Parmenides and Xenophanes did, but, to all appearance, the 
 very opposite (R. P. 185). They made the All one, immovable, 
 uncreated, and finite, and did not even permit us to search for 
 what is not ; he assumed innumerable and ever-moving elements, 
 namely, the atoms. And he made their forms infinite in number, 
 since there was no reason why they should be of one kind rather 
 than another, and because he saw that there was unceasing 
 becoming and change in things. He held, further, that what is 
 is no more real than what is not, and that both are alike causes 
 of the things that come into being ; for he laid down that the 
 substance of the atoms was compact and fuU, and he called them 
 what is, while they moved in the void which he called what is not, 
 but affirmed to be just as real as what is. R. P. 194. 
 
 173. It will be observed that Theophrastos, while noting Leukippos 
 the affihation of Leukippos to the Eleatic school, points out Eieatics. 
 that his theory is, prima facie, '^ just the opposite of that 
 maintained by Parmenides. Some have been led by this to 
 
 deny the Eleaticism of Leukippos altogether ; but this denial 
 is really based on the view that the system of Parmenides 
 was " metaphysical," coupled with a great reluctance to 
 admit that so scientific a hypothesis as the atomic theory 
 can have had a " metaphysical " origin. This is merely a 
 prejudice, and we must not suppose Theophrastos himself 
 beheved the two theories to be so far apart as they 
 
 ^ The words ws SoKet do not imply assent to the view introduced by 
 them ; indeed they are constantly used in reference to beliefs which the 
 writer does not accept. The translation " methinks " in Gomperz, Greek 
 Thinkers, vol. i. p. 345, is therefore most misleading, and there is no 
 justification for Brieger's statement {Hermes, xxxvi. p. 165) that Theo- 
 phrastos dissents from Aristotle's view as given in the passage about to 
 be quoted. 
 
 I 
 
334 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 seem.i As this is really the most important point in the 
 history of early Greek philosophy, and as, rightly under- 
 stood, it furnishes the key to the whole development, 
 it is worth while to transcribe a passage of Aristotle ^ 
 which explains the historical connexion in a way that 
 leaves nothing to be desired. 
 
 ' Leukippos and Demokritos have decided about all things 
 practically by the same method and on the same theory, taking 
 as m^ starting-point what naturally comes first. Some of the 
 ancients had held that the real must necessarily be one and 
 immovable ; for, said they, empty space is not real, and motion 
 would be impossible without empty space separated from 
 matter ; nor, further, could reality be a many, if there were 
 nothing to separate things. And it makes no difference if any 
 one holds that the AH is not continuous, but discrete, with its 
 part in contact (the Pythagorean view), instead of holding that 
 reality is many, not one, and that there is empty space. For, 
 if it is divisible at every point there is no one, and therefore nO 
 many, and the Whole is empty (Z^wo); while, if we say it is 
 divisible in one place and not in another, this looks like an 
 arbitrary fiction ; for up to what point and for what reason will 
 part of the Whole be in this state and be full, while the rest is 
 discrete ? And, on the same grounds, they further say that 
 there can be no motion. In consequence of these reasonings, 
 then, going beyond perception and overlooking it in the belief 
 that we ought to follow the argument, they say that the All is 
 one and immovable (Parmenides), and some of them that it is 
 infinite (Melissos), for any limit would be bounded by empty 
 space. This, then, is the opinion they expressed about the truth, 
 and these are the reasons which led them to do so. Now, so far 
 as arguments go, this conclusion does seem to follow ; but, if 
 we appeal to facts, to hold such a view looks like madness. No 
 one who is mad is so far out of his senses that fire and ice appear 
 to him to be one ; it is only things that are right, and things that 
 
 1 This prejudice is apparent all through Gomperz's Greek Thinkers, and 
 seriously impairs the value of that fascinating, though somewhat imagina- 
 tive work. It is amusing to notice that Brieger, from the same point of 
 view, regards the custom of making Anaxagoras the last of the Presocratics 
 as due to theological prepossessions [Hermes, xxxvi. p. 185). 
 
 2 Arist. De gen. corr. A, 8. 324 b 35 (R. P. 193). 
 
LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 335 
 
 appear right from habit, in which madness makes some people 
 see no difference. 
 
 Leukippos, however, thought he had a theory which was in 
 harmony with sense, and did not do away with coming into being 
 and passing away, nor motion, nor the multiplicity of things. He 
 conceded this to experience, while he conceded, on the other 
 hand, to those who invented the One that motion was impossible 
 without the void, that the void was not real, and that nothing of 
 what was real was not real. " For," said he, " that which is 
 strictly speaking real is an absolute plenum ; but the pUnvpm is 
 not one. On the contrary, there are an infinite number of them, 
 and they are invisible owing to the smallness of their bulk. They 
 move in the void (for there is a void) ; and by their coming 
 together they effect coming into being ; by their separation, 
 passing away." 
 
 In this passage Zeno and Melissos are not named, but 
 the reference to them is unmistakable. The argument of 
 Zeno against the Pythagoreans is clearly given ; and Melissos 
 was the only Eleatic who made reahty infinite, a point which 
 is distinctly mentioned. We are therefore justified by 
 Aristotle's words in explaining the genesis of Atomism and 
 its relation to Eleaticism as follows. Zeno had shown that 
 all pluralist systems yet known, and especially Pytha- 
 goreanism, were unable to stand before the arguments from 
 infinite divisibihty which he adduced. MeHssos had used 
 the same argument against Anaxagoras, and had added, as 
 a reductio ad absurdum, that, if there were many things, each 
 one of them must be such as the Eleatics held the One to be. 
 To this Leukippos answers, " Why not ? " He admitted the 
 force of Zeno's arguments by setting a limit to divisibility, 
 and to each of the " atoms " which he thus arrived at he 
 ascribed all the predicates of the Eleatic One ; for Par- 
 menides had shown that if it is, it must have these predicates 
 somehow. The same view is implied in a passage of Aris- 
 totle's Physics.^ " Some," we are there told, " surrendered 
 both arguments, to the first, the argument that all things 
 
 1 Arist. Phys. A, 3. 187 a i (R. P. 134 b). 
 
336 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 are one, if the word is is used in one sense only (Parmenides), 
 by affirming the reaUty of what is not ; to the second, that 
 based on dichotomy (Zeno), by introducing indivisible magni- 
 tudes." Finally, it is only by regarding the matter in this 
 way that we can attach any meaning to another statement 
 of Aristotle's that Leukippos and Demokritos, as well as the 
 Pythagoreans, virtually make all things out of numbers. ^ 
 Leukippos, in fact, gave the Pythagorean monads the 
 character of the Parmenidean One. 
 Atoms. 174. We must observe that the atom is not mathe- 
 
 matically indivisible, for it has magnitude ; it is, however, 
 physically indivisible, because, Hke the One of Parmenides, 
 it contains no empty space. ^ Each atom has extension, and 
 all atoms are exactly ahke in substance.^ Therefore all 
 differences in things must be accounted for either by the 
 shape of the atoms or by their arrangement. It seems 
 probable that the three ways in which differences arise, 
 namely, shape, position, and arrangement, were already 
 distinguished by Leukippos ; for Aristotle mentions his name 
 in connexion with them.^ This explains, too, why the atoms 
 are called " forms " or " figures," a way of speaking which is 
 clearly of Pythagorean origin.^ That they are also called 
 
 ^ Arist. De caelo, V, 4. 303 a 8, Tpbirov yap riva Kal oSroi (AeijKiTnros 
 Kal ArjfidKpiTos) Travra ra 6uTa Troiou<nv dpid/JLoiis Kal e^ dpidfiwu. This also 
 serves to explain the statement of Herakleides attributing the theory 
 of corporeal 6yK0(. to the Pythagorean Ekphantos of Syracuse (above, 
 p. 291, n. 3). 
 
 2 The Epicureans misunderstood this point, or misrepresented it in 
 order to magnify their own originality (see Zeller, p. 857, n. 3). 
 
 ' Arist. De caelo, A, 7. 275 b 32, tt)]/ dk <f)v<riv eXvai <paaiu avrQp fxlav. 
 Here (p^ais can only have one meaning. Cf. Phys. T, 4. 203 a 34, avT(f 
 {ArjfioKpiTq)) TO Koivbv crQ/xa iravTuv earlv dpx^' 
 
 * Arist. Met. A, 4. 985 b 13 (R. P. 192) ; cf. De gen. corr. A, 2. 315 b 6. 
 As Diels suggests, the illustration from letters is probably due to Demo- 
 kritos. It shows, in any case, how the word cttoix^Tov came to be used for 
 " element." We must read, with Wilamowitz, to 8k Z tov H d^aet for 
 t6 5^ Z TOV N 64a€i, the older form of the letter Z being just an H laid 
 upon its side (Diels, Elementum, p. 13, n. 1). 
 
 5 Demokritos wrote a work, Ilept idedv (Sext. Math. vii. 137 ; R. P. 
 204), which Diels identifies with the ITept tCjv diacpepoPTwv pva/j-Qv of 
 Thrasylos, Tetr. v. 3. Theophrastos refers to Demokritos, iv tois trepl 
 Twv elduv [De sensibus, § 51). Plut. Adv. Col. mi a, elyai 8k rrdvTa rdi 
 
 i 
 
LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 337 
 
 <^u(7t9 ^ is quite intelligible if we remember what was said of 
 that word in the Introduction (§ VII.). The differences in 
 shape, order, and position just referred to account for the 
 " opposites,'* the *' elements " being regarded rather as 
 aggregates of these {Trava-irep/jbLac) , as by Anaxagoras.^ 
 
 175. Leukippos affirmed the existence both of the Full The void. 
 and the Empty, terms which he may have borrowed from 
 MeUssos.3 He had to assume empty space, which the 
 Eleatics had denied, in order to make his explanation of the 
 nature of body possible. Here again he is developing a 
 Pythagorean view. The Pythagoreans had spoken of the 
 
 void, which kept the units apart ; but they had not dis- 
 tinguished it from atmospheric air (§ 53), which Empedokles 
 had shown to be a corporeal substance (§ 107). Parmenides, 
 indeed, had formed a clearer conception of space, but only to 
 deny its reality Leukippos started from this. He admitted, 
 indeed, that space was not real, that is to say, corporeal ; 
 but he maintained that it existed all the same. He hardly, 
 it is true, had words to express his discovery in ; for the verb 
 "to be " had hitherto been used by philosophers only of 
 body. But he did his best to make his meaning clear by 
 saying that " what is not '* (in the old corporeaHst sense) 
 " is " (in another sense) just as much as " what is." The 
 void is as real as body. 
 
 176. It might seem a hopeless task to disentangle the Cosmo- 
 cosmology of Leukippos from that of Demokritos, with °^' 
 which it is generally identified ; but that very fact affords 
 
 a valuable chie. No one later than Theophrastos was able 
 to distinguish their doctrines, and it follows that all definite 
 
 drSfiovs, lS4as vt avrov KoXovfihas (so the MSS. : ISius, Wyttenbach ; <-^> 
 tS^as, Diels). Herodian has i8ia . . . rb eXax^arov adfia (Diels, VofS. 
 55 B 141). So Arist. Phys. V, 4. 203 a 21, (A7?/i6«-/)tTOs) e/c tt)s iravairepixlat 
 tQv axvi^^T^'^ [aireipa iroiei to. aroLxeTa). Cf. De gen. corr. A, 2. 315 b 7 
 (R. P. 196). 
 
 1 Arist. Phys. 9, 9. 265 b 25 ; Simpl. Phys. p. 13 18, 33, radra yap 
 {to. &TO/xa (TibfJ-aTa) iKeivoi (pijffiv iK&Xovv. 
 
 2 Simpl. Phys. p. 36, i (Diels, Vors. 54 a 14), and R. P. 196 a. 
 
 13 Arist. Met. A, 4. 985 b 4 (R. P. 192). Cf. Melissos, fr. 7 sub fin. 
 22 
 
338 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 statements about Leukippos in later writers must, in the long; 
 run, go back to him. If we follow this up, we shall be able 
 to give a fairly clear account of the system, and we shall even 
 come across some views which are peculiar to Leukippos and 
 were not adopted by Demokritos.i 
 
 The fuller of the doxographies in Diogenes, which comes 
 from an epitome of Theophrastos,^ is as follows : 
 
 He says that the All is infinite, and that it is part fuU, and 
 part empty. These (the full and the empty), he says, are the 
 elements. From them arise innumerable worlds and are resolved 
 into them. The worlds come into being thus. There were 
 borne along by " abscission from the infinite " many bodies of aU 
 sorts of figures " into a mighty void," and they being gathered 
 together produce a single vortex. In it, as they came into 
 collision with one another and were whirled round in aU manner 
 of ways, those which were alike were separated apart and came 
 to their likes. But, as they were no longer able to revolve in 
 equilibrium owing to their multitude, those of them that were 
 fine went out to the external void, as if passed through a sieve ; 
 the rest stayed together, and becoming entangled with one 
 another, ran down together, and made a first spherical structure. 
 This was in substance like a membrane or skin containing in 
 itself all kinds of bodies. And, as these bodies were borne round 
 in a vortex, in virtue of the resistance of the middle, the surround- 
 ing membrane became thin, as the contiguous bodies kept 
 flowing together from contact with the vortex. And in this way 
 the earth came into being, those things which had been borne 
 towards the middle abiding there. Moreover, the containing 
 membrane was increased by the further separating out of bodies 
 from outside ; and, being itself carried round in a vortex, it 
 further got possession of all with which it had come in contact. 
 Some of these becoming entangled, produce a structure, which 
 was at first moist and muddy ; but, when they had been dried 
 and were revolving along with the vortex of the whole, they were 
 then ignited and produced the substance of the heavenly bodies. 
 
 1 Cf. Zeller, " Zu Leukippos " {Arch, xv, p. 138). 
 
 2 Diog. ix, 31 sqq. (R. P. 197, 197 c). This passage deals expressly with 
 Leukippos, not with Demokritos or even " Leukippos and Demokritos." 
 For the distinction between the " summary " and " detailed " doxographies 
 in Diogenes, see Note on Sources, § 15. 
 
LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 339 
 
 Tke circle tf tke sun is tke •uterm^st, tkat •£ tke moon is nearest 
 to tke eartk, amd thtse of the •tkers are between these. And all 
 the keavemly bodies are ij^mited because of the swiftness of their 
 m«ti«m ; while the sun is als» ignited by the stars. But the 
 m##n tnly receives a small ptrtitn of fire. The sun and the 
 moon are ecUpsed . . . (And the obliquity of the zodiac is pro- 
 duced) by the earth being inclined towards the south ; and the 
 northern parts of it have constant snow and are cold and frozen. 
 And the sun is eclipsed rarely, and the moon continually, because 
 their circles are unequal. And just as there are comings into 
 being of the world, so there are growths and decays and passings 
 away in virtue of a certain necessity, of the nature of which he 
 gives no clear account. 
 
 As it comes substantially from Theophrastos, this passage 
 
 is good evidence for the cosmology of Leukippos, and it is 
 
 confirmed by certain Epicurean extracts from the Great Dia- 
 
 kosmos.^ These, however, give a specially Epicurean turn to 
 
 ' some of the doctrines, and must therefore be used with caution. 
 
 177. The general impression we get from the cosmology Relation 
 of Leukippos is that he either ignored or had never heard of cosmo-^ 
 the great advance in the general view of the world which was ^o^- 
 due to the later Pythagoreans. He is as reactionary in his 
 detailed cosmology as he was daring in his general physical 
 theory. We seem to be reading once more of the specula- 
 tions of Anaximenes or Anaximander, though there are traces 
 of Empedokles and Anaxagoras too. The explanation is not 
 hard to see. Leukippos would not learn a cosmology from 
 his Eleatic teachers ; and, even when he found it possible to 
 construct one without giving up the Parmenidean view of 
 reahty, he was thrown back upon the older systems of Ionia. 
 The result was unfortunate. The astronomy of Demokritos 
 was still of this childish character. He beheved the earth 
 was fiat and rested on the air. 
 
 This is what gives plausibihty to Gomperz's statement 
 that Atomism was "the ripe fruit on the tree of the old Ionic 
 
 1 See Aet. i. 4 {Dox p. 289 ; Vors. 54 a 24 ; Usener, Epicurea. fr. 308). 
 Epicurus himself in the second epistle (Diog. x. 88 : Usener, p. 37, 7) quotes 
 the phrase dTroro/xr^v '4xov(Ta dTo toO direipov. 
 
 I 
 
eternal 
 motion. 
 
 340 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 doctrine of matter which had been tended by the Ionian 
 physiologists/' ^ The detailed cosmology was certainly such 
 a fruit, and it was possibly over-ripe ; but the atomic theory 
 proper, in which the real greatness of Leukippos comes out, 
 was wholly Eleatic in its origin. Nevertheless, it will repay 
 us to examine the cosmology too ; for such an examination 
 will serve to bring out the true nature of the historical 
 development of which it was the outcome. 
 The 178. Leukippos represented the atoms as having been 
 
 always in motion. Aristotle puts this in his own way. The 
 atomists, he says, " indolently " left it unexplained what 
 was the source of motion, and did not say what sort of motion 
 it was. In other words, they did not decide whether it was 
 a " natural motion " or impressed on them " contrary to 
 their nature.'' ^ He even said that they made it " spon- 
 taneous," a remark which has given rise to the erroneous 
 view that they held it was due to chance.^ Aristotle does 
 not say that, however ; but only that the atomists did not 
 explain the motion of the atoms in any of the ways in which 
 he himself explained the motion of the elements. They 
 neither ascribed to them a natural motion like the circular 
 motion of the heavens and the rectihnear motion of the four 
 elements in the sublunary region, nor did they give them a 
 forced motion contrary to their own nature, like the upward 
 motion that may be given to the heavy elements and the 
 downward that may be given to the Hght. The only frag- 
 ment of Leukippos which has survived is an express denial 
 of chance. " Naught happens for nothing,^' he said, " but 
 everything from a ground and of necessity." * 
 
 1 Gomperz, Greek Thinkers, vol, i. p. 323. 
 
 2 Arist. Phys. G, i. 252 a 32 (R. P. 195 a) ;' De caelo, V, 2. 300 b 8 (R. P. 
 195) ; Met. A, 4. 985 b 19 (R- P- ib.). 
 
 3 Arist. Phys. B, 4. 196 a 24 (R. P. 195 d). Cicero, De nat. d. i. 66 
 (R. P. ib.). The latter passage is the source of the phrase " fortuitous 
 concourse " {concurrere=(rvvTpix^iv). 
 
 * Aet. i. 25, 4 {Dox. p. 321), AeiJKLTTTos irdvTa Kar dvdyKrjv, rrjv 5' avT7)v 
 iirdpx^iv eifMapfi^vrji'. X^7ei ydp iv t^j liepl vov • Ovbh XPW°- tJ^'i-Tflv yiyverac, 
 dXXa irdPTa iK \6yov re Kal vir dvdyKrjs. 
 
I 
 
 LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 341 
 
 Speaking historically, all this means that Leukippos did 
 not, like Empedokles and Anaxagoras, find it necessary to 
 assume a force to originate motion. He had no need of 
 Love and Strife or Mind, and the reason is clear. Though 
 Empedokles and Anaxagoras had tried to explain multi- 
 pKcity and motion, they had not broken so radically as 
 Leukippos with the Parmenidean One. Both started with 
 a condition of matter in which the " roots " or " seeds " 
 were mixed so as to be " all together," and they therefore 
 required something to break up this unity. Leukippos, 
 who started with an infinite number of Parmenidean " Ones," 
 so to speak, required no external agency to separate them. 
 What he had to do was just the opposite. He had to account 
 for their coming together, and there was nothing so far to 
 prevent his return to the old idea that motion does not 
 require any explanation at all.^ 
 
 This, then, is what seems to follow from the criticisms 
 of Aristotle and from the nature of the case ; but it is not 
 consistent with Zeller's opinion that the original motion of 
 the atoms is a fall through infinite space, as in the system of 
 Epicurus. This view depends, of course, on the further 
 belief that the atoms have weight, and that weight is 
 the tendency of bodies to fall, so we must now consider 
 whether and in what sense weight is a property of the 
 atoms. 
 
 179. As is well known, Epicurus held that the atoms The 
 were naturally heavy, and therefore fell continually in the ttS^atoms. 
 infinite void. The school tradition is, however, that the 
 " natural weight " of the atoms was an addition made by 
 Epicurus himself to the original atomic system. Demokritos, 
 we are told, assigned tyvo properties to atoms, magnitude and 
 form, to which Epicurus added a third, weight.^ On the 
 
 1 Introd. § VIII. 
 
 2 Aet. i. 3, 18 (of Epicurus), a-vfi^e^riKivai dk roT^ adfiaaL rpia ravra, 
 <rxvfj^, fJ^yedos, /3d/3os. ArjfidKpLTOs ixku ykp fKeye 5i5o, jiAyedbs re Kal 
 aX^a, 6 5^ 'EvlKovpos totjtols Kal rpirov ^apos -rrpocr^dTjKev • avdyK-q yap, (prjaL, 
 Kiveladai to. (rdbfiara ry rod ^dpovs irXrjy^ ' iird ("or else") ov Kivqd-qceTai', 
 
342 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 other hand, Aristotle distinctly says that Demokritos held 
 the atoms were heavier " in proportion to their excess," and 
 this seems to be explained by the statement of Theophrastos 
 that, according to him, weight depended on magnitude.^ 
 Even so, however, it is not represented as a primary property 
 of the atoms in the same sense as magnitude. 
 
 It is impossible to solve this apparent contradiction 
 without referring briefly to the history of Greek ideas about 
 weight. It is clear that Ughtness and weight would be among 
 the very first properties of body to be distinctly recognised 
 as such. The necessity of lifting burdens must very soon 
 have led men to distinguish them, though no doubt in a 
 crude form. Both weight and Ughtness would be thought 
 of as things that were in bodies. Now it is a remarkable 
 feature of early Greek philosophy that from the first it was 
 able to shake itself free from this idea. Weight is never 
 called a " thing " as, for instance, warmth and cold are ; 
 and, so far as we can see, not one of the thinkers we have 
 studied hitherto thought it necessary to give any explanation 
 of it at all, or even to say anything about it.^ The motions 
 and resistances which popular theory ascribes to weight are 
 
 ib. 12, 6, ArjfidKpLTOs tA, irpQTd (prjcn a-ibfiara, ravra 5' fiv ra vatxra, ^dpos 
 fxkv ovK ^x^"'> KLveiadai dk Kar' a.X\r]\oTVTriav iv T(p dirreipq}. Cic. De fato, 
 20, " vim motus habebant (atomi) a Democrito impulsionis quam 
 plagam ille appellat, a te. Epicure, graidtatis et ponderis." These 
 passages represent the Epicurean school tradition, which would hardly 
 misrepresent Demokritos on so important a point. His works were still 
 accessible. It is confirmed by the Academic tradition in De fin. i. 17 that 
 Demokritos taught the atoms moved " in infinito inani, in quo nihil nee 
 summum nee infimum nee medium nee extremum sit." This doctrine, 
 we are quite rightly told, was " depraved " by Epicurus. 
 
 ^ Arist. De gen. corr. A, 8. 326 a 9, Katroi ^apvrepbv ye Kara tt]v virepoxw 
 ^rjatv elvai Atj/jlokpltos 'iKaarov tQv ddLaip^rcav. I cannot beUeve this 
 means anything else than what Theophrastos says in his fragment on 
 sensation, § 61 (R. P. 199), jSapi) fi^u odv Kal Kov(f>ov t^ /xey^dei diaipei 
 
 AtJjJ.bKpiTOS. 
 
 2 In Aet. i. 12, where the placita regarding the heavy and light are 
 given, no philosopher earlier than Plato is referred to. Parmenides 
 (fr. 8, 59) speaks of the dark element as ep-lSptdes. Empedokles (fr. 17) 
 uses the word drdXavrou. I do not think that there is any other 
 place where weight is even mentioned in the |fragments of the early 
 philosophers. 
 
LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 343 
 
 al 1 explained in some other way. Aristotle distinctly declares 
 that none of his predecessors had said anything of absolute 
 weight and lightness. They had only treated of the relatively 
 light and heavy. ^ 
 
 This way of regarding the notions of weight and 
 lightness is clearly formulated for the first time in 
 Plato's Timaeus.^ There is no such thing in the world, 
 we are told there, as " up " or " down.'* The middle 
 of the world is not " down " but " just in the middle," 
 and there is no reason why any point in the circum- 
 ference should be said to be " above " or " below " 
 another. It is really the tendency of bodies towards their 
 kin that makes us call a falling body heavy and the 
 place to which it falls " below." Here Plato is really 
 giving the view taken more or less consciously by his pre- 
 decessors, and it is not till the time of Aristotle that it is 
 questioned.^ For reasons which do not concern us here, 
 Aristotle identified the circumference of the heavens with 
 " up " and the middle of the world with " down," and 
 equipped the elements with natural weight and lightness 
 that they might perform their rectihnear motions between 
 them. As, however, Aristotle beUeved there was only one 
 world, and did not ascribe weight to the heavens proper, the 
 effect of this reactionary theory on his cosmical system was 
 not great ; it was only when Epicurus tried to combine it 
 with the infinite void that its true character emerged. It 
 seems to me that the nightmare of Epicurean atomism can 
 only be explained on the assumption that an Aristotelian 
 doctrine was violently adapted to a theory which really 
 
 1 Arist. De caelo. A, i. 308 a 9, Trepl ^ikv odv tCjv dTrXws \eyoixiv(x}v {^apiwv 
 KOI Kov<p(i}v) ovdh etprp-aL -rrapa tQv irpbrepov. 
 
 2 Plato, Tim. 61 c 3 sqq. 
 
 3 Zeller says (p. 876) that in antiquity no one ever understood by weight 
 anything else than the property of bodies in virtue of which they move 
 downwards ; except that in such systems as represent all forms of matter 
 as contained in a sphere, " above " is identified with the circumference and 
 " below " with the centre. As to that, I can only say that no such theory 
 oi weight is to be found in the fragments of the early philosophers or is 
 anywhere ascribed to them, while Plato expressly denies it. 
 
344 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 excluded it.^ It is totally unlike anything we meet with in 
 earlier days. 
 
 This suggests at once that it is only in the vortex that 
 the atoms acquire weight and lightness, ^ which are, after all, 
 only popular names for facts which can be further analysed. 
 We are told that Leukippos held one effect of the vortex to 
 be that like atoms were brought together with their likes. ^ 
 Here we seem to see the influence of Empedokles, though the 
 *' likeness " is of another kind. It is the finer atoms that 
 are forced to the circumference, while the larger tend to the 
 centre. We may express that by saying that the larger are 
 heavy and the smaller light, and this will amply account for 
 everything Aristotle and Theophrastos say ; for there is no 
 passage where the atoms outside the vortex are distinctly 
 said to be heavy or light.* 
 
 There is a striking confirmation of this view in the 
 atomist cosmology quoted above. ^ We are told there that 
 the separation of the larger and smaller atoms was due to 
 the fact that they were '* no longer able to revolve in equi- 
 librium owing to their number," which implies that they had 
 previously been in a state of " equilibrium " or " equipoise.'' 
 Now the word laoppoiria has no necessary implication of 
 
 ^ The Aristotelian criticisms which may have affected Epicurus are such 
 as we find in De caelo, A, 7. 275 b 29 sqq. Aristotle there argues that, as 
 Leukippos and Demokritos made the (pvcns of the atoms one, they were 
 bound to give them a single motion. That is just what Epicurus did, but 
 Aristotle's argument implies that Leukippos and Demokritos did not. 
 Though he gave the atoms weight, even Epicurus could not accept Aris- 
 totle's view that some bodies are naturally light. The appearance of 
 lightness is due to tKd\L\f/Ls, the squeezing out of the smaller atoms by 
 the larger. 
 
 2 In dealing with Empedokles, Aristotle expressly makes this distinction. 
 Cf. De caelo, B, 13, especially 295 a 32 sqq., where he points out that 
 Empedokles does not account for the weight of bodies on the earth (ou yap 
 Tj ye diurj TrXrjaid^eL irpbs i]fj.ds), nor for the weight of bodies before the 
 vortex arose {irpiu yevicdaL rrjv divrjv). 
 
 3 Diog. loc. cit. (p. 338). 
 
 * This seems to be in the main the view of Dyroff, Demokritstudien 
 (1899), pp. 31 sqq., though I should not say that lightness and weight only 
 arose in connexion with the atoms of the earth (p. 35). If we substitute 
 " world " for " earth," we shall be nearer the truth. 
 
 ^ See above, p. 338. 
 
LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 345 
 
 weight in Greek. A poirrj is a mere leaning or inclination in 
 a certain direction, which is the cause rather than the effect 
 of weight. The state of iaoppoiria is therefore that in which 
 the tendency in one direction is exactly equal to the tendency 
 in any other, and such a state is more naturally described as 
 the absence of weight than as the presence of opposite weights 
 neutralising one another. 
 
 Now, if we no longer regard the "eternal motion" of the 
 premundane and extramundane atoms as due to their weight, 
 there is no reason for describing it as a fall. None of our 
 authorities do as a matter of fact so describe it, nor do they 
 tell us in any way what it was. It is safest to say that it is 
 simply a confused motion this way and that.^ It is possible 
 that the comparison of the motion of the atoms of the soul 
 to that of the motes in a sunbeam coming through a window, 
 which Aristotle attributes to Demokritos,^ is really intended 
 as an illustration of the original motion of the atoms still 
 surviving in the soul. The fact that it is also a Pythagorean 
 comparison ^ so far confirms this ; for we have seen that 
 there is a real connexion between the Pythagorean monads 
 and the atoms. It is also significant that the point of the 
 comparison appears to have been the fact that the motes in 
 the sunbeam move even when there is no wind, so that it 
 would be a very apt illustration indeed of the motion inherent 
 
 1 This view was independently advocated by Brieger [Die Urbewegung 
 der Atome und die Weltentstehung hei Leucipp und Demokrii, 1884) and 
 Liepmann {Die Mechanik der Leucipp-Demokritschen Atome, 1885), both 
 of whom unnecessarily weakened their position by admitting that weight 
 is an original property of the atoms. On the other hand, Brieger denies 
 that the weight of the atoms is the cause of their original motion, while 
 Liepmann says that before and outside the vortex there is only a latent 
 weight, a Pseudoschwere, which only comes into operation in the world. 
 It is surely simpler to say that this weight, since it produces no effect, does 
 not yet exist. Zeller rightly argues against Brieger and Liepmann that, 
 if the atoms have weight, they must fall ; but, so far as I can see, nothing 
 he says tells against their theory as I have restated it. Gomperz adopts 
 the Brieger- Liepmann explanation. See also Lortzing, Bursians Jahresber., 
 1903. PP- 136 sqq. 
 
 2 Arist. De an. A, 2. 403 b 28 sqq. (R. P. 200). 
 
 3 Ibid. A, 2, 404 a 17 (R. P. 86 a). 
 
346 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 in the atoms apart from the secondary motions produced by 
 impact and collision. 
 The i8o. But what are we to say of the vortex itself which 
 
 produces these effects ? Gomperz observes that they seem 
 to be " the precise contrary of what they should have been 
 by the laws of physics " ; for, " as every centrifugal machine 
 would show, it is the heaviest substances which are hurled 
 to the greatest distance." ^ Are we to suppose that Leu- 
 kippos was ignorant of this fact, which was known to Empe- 
 dokles and Anaxagoras ? ^ We know from Aristotle that all 
 those who accounted for the earth being in the centre of the 
 world by means of a vortex appealed to the analogy of eddies 
 in wind or water,^ and Gomperz supposes that the whole 
 theory was an erroneous generalisation of this observation. 
 If we look at the matter more closely, we can see, I think, 
 that there is no error at all. 
 
 We must remember that all the parts of the vortex are 
 in contact, and that it is just this contact (iTrlyfravo-Lf;) by 
 which the motion of the outermost parts is communicated 
 to those within them. The larger bodies are more able to 
 resist this communicated motion than the smaller, and in 
 this way they make their way to the centre where the motion 
 is least, and force the smaller bodies out. This resistance is 
 surely just the avrepeLo-L^ rod fieaov which is mentioned in 
 the doxography of Leukippos,* and it is quite in accord- 
 ance with this that, on the atomist theory, the nearer a 
 heavenly body is to the centre, the slower is its revolution.^ 
 That is just the point which, as we have seen,^ Anaxi- 
 mander would seem not to have observed. There is 
 
 ^ Gomperz, Greek Thinkers, i. p. 339. 
 
 2 For Empedokles, see Chap. V. p. 237 ; Anaxagoras, see Chap. VI. 
 p. 269. 
 
 * Arist. De caelo, B, 13. 295 a 10, raiJTrjv yap ttjj/ alrlav (sc. ttji^ 
 div7j(nv) iravTes \iyov<nv ^k tG)v iv rots vypois Kal irepl rbv d^pa avix^aivbvTwv ' 
 iv TOVTOLS ycLp del (p^peraL to, fiei^co Kal rd ^ap^repa irpbs to (x^aov ttj^ 5ivr}s. 
 
 * Diog. ix. 32. Cf. especially the phrases Cbu Kara rrjv toO /jl^ctov 
 avripeiaLV TrepiSivovfxivcov, av/xfjt.evdvTwi' del tQjv avvex^v Kar iirixpavcip t7]S blvrjs, 
 and (rvfj-fievoPTUv tQu ivexd^vTWV errl rb fi^crov. 
 
 ^ Cf. Lucr. V. 621 sqq, ^ See p. 69. 
 
LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 347 
 
 no question of " centrifugal force '' at all, and the analogy 
 of eddies in air and water is in reality quite satis- 
 factory. 
 
 181. When we come to details, the reactionary character The earth 
 of the atomist cosmology is very manifest. The earth was h^averdy 
 shaped Uke a tambourine, and floated on the air.^ It was ^o^^^s. 
 inclined towards the south because the heat of that region 
 
 made the air thinner, while the ice and cold of the north 
 made it denser and more able to support the earth. 2 This 
 accounts for the obhquity of the zodiac. Like Anaximander 
 (§ 19), Leukippos held that the sun was farther away than 
 the stars, though he also held that these were farther away 
 than the moon.^ By this time the occupation of the planets 
 by the moon must have been observed. There seems to 
 be no very clear distinction between the planets and 
 the fixed stars. Leukippos appears to have known the 
 theory of echpses as given by Anaxagoras.* Such other 
 pieces of information as have come down to us are mainly of 
 interest as showing that, in some important respects, the 
 doctrine of Leukippos was not the same as that taught 
 afterwards by Demokritos.^ 
 
 182. Actios expressly attributes to Leukippos the Percep- 
 doctrine that the objects of sense-perception exist ''by 
 
 law " and not by nature.^ This must come from Theo- 
 
 * Aet. iii. 3, 10, quoted above, p, 79, n. i. 
 
 ^ Aet. iii. 12, I, AeuKnnros TrapeKireaelp tt]v yrjv els rot fieaT^/x^piva ixiprj 
 dia TT]v iu ToTs fiearj/ji^pLvois dpaLOTTjra, are Stj TreTrrjyoTCJV tG)v ^opeiwv 8tcL t6 
 /carei/'Dx^ai rois Kpv/xois, tCov 5k dvTid^TUiv ireirvpiapL^vwv. 
 
 ' Diog. ix. 33, eXvaL 5k rbv tov ifKLov kOkXov e^dirarov, rbv 5k rrjs (reXrjprjs 
 irpoayeidTaTov, <Tot>s 5e> rQy dWcou /xera^v tovtuiv. 
 
 * From Diog. loc. cit. {supra, p. 339), it appears that he dealt with the 
 question of the greater frequency of lunar as compared with solar eclipses. 
 
 5 Diels pointed out that Leukippos's explanation of thunder 
 (7ri;p6s ipav-o\7}<fod4i'Tos p4<f>€<ri TraxvrdTots ^kittuo-lv laxvpcLV ^povTTjv diroTeXeiv 
 diro<palviTai., Aet. iii. 3, 10) is quite different from that of Demokritos 
 [PpovTT)v . . . iK avyKpifiaros dviofxdXov to TrepieiXrjcpos aiiTO v^(f)OS irpos tt)v 
 Kdru) (popdv iK^ia^o/j-epov, ib. ii). The explanation given by Leukippos 
 is derived from that of Anaximander, while Demokritos is influenced by 
 Anaxagoras. See Diels, 35 Philol.-Vers. 97, 7. 
 
 8 Aet. iv. 9, 8, ol fikp AXXoL (pv<reL rd alad-qra, KevKiiriros 5k ArmdKpiTOS 
 
 Aioyeprjs p6fjn{}. See Zeller, Arch. v. p. 444. 
 
348 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 phrastos ; for, as we have seen, all later writers quote 
 Demokritos only. A further proof of the correctness of the 
 statement is that we also find it attributed to Diogenes of 
 Apollonia, who, as Theophrastos tells us, derived some of 
 his views from Leukippos. There is nothing surprising in 
 this. Parmenides had already declared the senses to be 
 deceitful, and said that colour and the like were only 
 " names," ^ and Empedokles had also spoken of coming into 
 being and passing away as only a name.^ It is not hkely 
 that Leukippos went much further than this. It would 
 probably be wrong to credit him with Demokritos's clear 
 distinction between " true-born " and ** bastard " know- 
 ledge, or that between the primary and secondary qualities 
 of matter.3 These distinctions imply a definite theory of 
 knowledge, and all we are entitled to say is that the germs 
 of it were already to be found in the writings of Leukippos 
 and his predecessors. Of course, these do not make Leu- 
 kippos a sceptic any more than Empedokles or Anaxagoras, 
 whose remark on this subject (fr. 21a) Demokritos is said to 
 have quoted with approval.* 
 
 There appear to be sufficient grounds for ascribing the 
 theory of perception by means of simulacra or el'SwXa, which 
 played such a part in the systems of Demokritos and 
 Epicurus, to Leukippos.^ It is a natural development of 
 the Empedoklean theory of " effluences " (§ 118). It hardly 
 seems likely, however, that he went into detail on the subject, 
 and it is safer to credit Demokritos with the elaboration of 
 the theory. 
 
 ^ Chap. IV. p. 176. The remarkable parallel quoted by Gomperz 
 (p. 321) from Galileo, to the effect that tastes, smells, and colours non sieno 
 altro che puri nomi should, therefore, have been cited to illustrate Par- 
 menides rather than Demokritos. 
 
 2 See p. 206, fr. 9. » For these see Sext. Math. vii. 135 (R. P. 204). 
 
 * Sext. vii. 140, *' 6xl/LS yap dSriXoju ra (paivS/jLeva," &s (f>7](nv 'Ava^aydpas, 
 tv iirl TovTcp Arj/JLOKptTos eiraivet. 
 
 ^ See Zeller, " Zu Leukippos " {Arch. xv. p. 138). The doctrine is 
 attributed to him in Aet. iv. 13, i {Dox. p. 403) ; and Alexander, De sensu, 
 pp. 24, 14 and 56, 10, also mentions his name in connexion with it. This 
 must come from Theophrastos. 
 
 ■ 
 
LEUKIPPOS OF MILETOS 349 
 
 183. We have seen incidentally that there is a wide import- 
 divergence of opinion among recent writers as to the place Leukippos. 
 of Atomism in Greek thought. The question at issue is 
 really whether Leukippos reached his theory on what are 
 called " metaphysical grounds," that is, from a considera- 
 tion of the Eleatic theory of reality, or whether, on the 
 contrary, it was a pure development of Ionian science. The 
 foregoing exposition will suggest the true answer. So far 
 as his general theory of the physical constitution of the world 
 is concerned, it has been shown, I think, that it was derived 
 entirely from Eleatic and Pythagorean sources, while the 
 detailed cosmology was in the main a more or less successful 
 attempt to make the older Ionian behefs fit into this new 
 physical theory. In any case, his greatness consisted in his 
 having been the first to see how body must be regarded if 
 we take it to be ultimate reality. The old Milesian theory 
 had found its most adequate 'expression in the system of 
 Anaximenes (§ 31), but of course rarefaction and condensa- 
 tion cannot be clearly represented except on the hypothesis 
 of molecules or atoms coming closer together or going farther 
 apart in space. Parmenides had seen that very clearly 
 (fr. 2), and it was the Eleatic criticism which forced Leu- 
 kippos to formulate his system as he did. Even Anaxagoras 
 took account of Zeno's arguments about divisibiUty (§ 128), 
 but his system of quaUtatively different " seeds," though 
 in some respects it goes deeper, lacks that simplicity which 
 had always been the chief attraction of atomism. 
 
CHAPTER X 
 
 ECLECTICISM AND REACTION 
 
 science.' 
 
 The 184. With Leukippos our story should come to an end ; 
 
 t( bank- 
 
 ruptcy of for he had answered the question first asked by Thales. We 
 have seen, however, that, though his theory of matter was 
 of a most original and daring kind, he was not equally 
 successful in his attempt to construct a cosmology, and this 
 seems to have prevented the recognition of the atomic theory 
 for what it really was. We have noted the growing influence 
 of medicine, and the consequent substitution of an interest 
 in detailed investigation for the larger cosmological views of 
 an earlier time, and there are several treatises in the Hippo- 
 kratean corpus which give us a clear idea of the interest 
 which now prevailed. ^ Leukippos had shown that " the 
 doctrine of MeUssos," ^ which seemed to make all science 
 impossible, was not the only conclusion that could be drawn 
 from the Eleatic premisses, and he had gone on to give a 
 cosmology which was substantially of the old Ionic type. 
 The result at first was simply that all the old schools revived 
 and had a short period of renewed activity, while at the same 
 time some new schools arose which sought to accommodate 
 the older views to those of Leukippos, or to make them more 
 available for scientific purposes by combining them in an 
 eclectic fashion. None of these attempts had any lasting 
 importance or influence, and what we have to consider in 
 
 ^ Cf. what is said in Chap. IV. p. 150, n. 2, of the Ilepi ScaiTrjs. 
 The Ilept avOpihirov (pvatos and the Ilept dpxa.ir}s laTpLKrjs are invaluable 
 documents for the attitude of scientific men to cosmological theories at 
 this date. 2 cf_ chap. VIII. p. 329, n. 2. 
 
 350 
 
 ■ 
 
I 
 
 ECLECTICISM AND REACTION 351 
 
 this chapter is really one of the periodical " bankraptcies of 
 • science " which mark the close of one chapter in its history 
 and announce the beginning of a new one. 
 
 ^ 
 
 I. HippoN OF Samos 
 
 185. Hippon of Samos or Kroton or Rhegion belonged to 
 the Italian school of medicine.^ We know very little indeed 
 of him except that he was a contemporary of Perikles. From 
 a schoHast on Aristophanes ^ we learn that Kratinos satirised 
 him in his Panoptai ; and Aristotle mentions him in the 
 enumeration of early philosophers given in the First Book of 
 the Metaphysics,^ though only to say that the inferiority of 
 his intellect deprives him of all claim to be reckoned among 
 them. 
 
 With regard to his views, the most precise statement is Moisture. 
 that of Alexander, who doubtless follows Theophrastos. It 
 is to the effect that he held the primary substance to be 
 Moisture, without deciding whether it was Water or Air.* 
 We have the authority of Aristotle ^ and Theophrastos, 
 represented by Hippolytos,^ for saying that this theory was 
 supported by physiological arguments of the kind common 
 at the time, and the arguments tentatively ascribed to 
 Thales by Aristotle are of this kind (§ 10). His other 
 views belong to the history of Medicine. 
 fcTill quite recently no fragment of Hippon was known 
 ■exist, but a single one has now been recovered from the 
 
 ^ Aristoxenos said he was a Samian (R. P. 219 a). In Menon's latrika 
 le is called a Krotoniate, while others assign him to Rhegion (Hipp, Ref. i. 
 c6) or Metapontion (Censorinus, De die nat. 5, 2). This variation implies 
 iiat he belonged originally to the Pythagorean school. The evidence of 
 .\ristoxenos is, in that case, all the more valuable. Hippon is mentioned 
 along with Mehssos as a Samian in lambUchos's Catalogue of Pythagoreans 
 V. Pyth. 267). 
 
 2 Schol. on Clouds, 94 sqq. 
 
 3 Arist. Met. A, 3. 984 a 3 (R- P- 219 a). 
 * Alexander in Met. p. 26, 21 (R, P. 219). 
 6 Arist. De an. A, 2. 405 b 2 (R. P. 220). 
 « Hipp. Ref. i. 16 (R. P. 221). 
 
 I 
 
352 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Geneva Scholia on Homer. ^ It is directed against the old 
 assumption that the " waters under the earth " are an 
 independent source of moisture, and runs thus : 
 
 The waters we drink are all from the sea ; for if wells were 
 deeper than the sea, then it would not, doubtless, be from the 
 sea that we drink, for then the water would not be from the sea, 
 but from some other source. But as it is, the sea is deeper than 
 the waters, so all the waters that are above the sea come from 
 it. R. P. 219 b. 
 
 We observe here the universal assumption that water 
 tends to rise from the earth, not to sink into it. 
 
 Along with Hippon, Idaios of Himera may just be men- 
 tioned. We know nothing of him except from Sextus,^ who 
 says he held air to be the primary substance. The fact that 
 he was a SiciUan is, however, suggestive. 
 
 II. Diogenes of Apollonia^ 
 
 Date. 186. After discussing the three great representatives of 
 
 the Milesian school, Theophrastos went on to say : 
 
 And Diogenes of Apollonia, too, who was almost the latest 
 of those who gave themselves up to these studies, wrote most of 
 his work in an eclectic fashion, agreeing in some points with 
 Anaxagoras and in others with Leukippos. He, too, says that 
 the primary substance of the universe is Air infinite and eternal, 
 from which by condensation, rarefaction, and change of state, 
 the form of everything else arises. R. P. 206 a.* 
 
 ^ Schol. Genav. p. 197, 19. Cf. Diels in Arch. iv. p. 653. The extract 
 comes from the 'O/xripiKd of Krates of Mallos. 
 
 2 Sext. Adv. Math. ix. 360. 
 
 3 Stephanos of Byzantion s.v. 'ATroWcovLa says this was Apollonia in 
 Crete, but that seems improbable. Zeller doubted it on the ground that 
 Diogenes wrote in Ionic, but Ionic was the regular dialect for scientific 
 works, and we cannot found on that. On the other hand, it seems much 
 more likely in itself that he came from Apollonia on the Pontos, a Milesian 
 colony which regarded Anaximander as its founder (p. 52, n. i). Aelian 
 {V. H. ii. 31) calls him Aioyhrjs 6 ^pv^, which shows that he took this view. 
 
 * On this passage see Diels, " Leukippos und Diogenes von Apollonia " 
 (Rhein. Mus. xlii. pp. i sqq.). Natorp's view that the words are merely 
 those of Simplicius {ib. pp. 349 sqq.) can hardly be maintained. 
 
ECLECTICISM AND REACTION 353 
 
 This passage shows that the Apolloniate was somewhat 
 later in date than the statement in Laertios Diogenes ^ that 
 he was contemporary with Anaxagoras would lead us to 
 suppose, and the fact that his views are satirised in the Clouds 
 of Aristophanes points in the same direction. ^ 
 
 187. Simplicius affirms that Diogenes wrote several works, writings, 
 though he allows that only one survived till his own day, 
 namely, the liepl ^vo-eo)?.^ This statement is based upon 
 references in the surviving work itself, and is not to be Hghtly 
 rejected. In particular, it is very credible that he wrote a 
 
 tract Against the Sophists, that is to say, the pluralist cos- 
 mologists of the day.* That he wrote a Meteorology and a 
 book called The Nature of Man is also quite probable. This 
 would be a physiological or medical treatise, and perhaps the 
 famous fragment about the veins comes from it.^ 
 
 188. The work of Diogenes seems to have been preserved The 
 in the Academy ; practically all the fairly extensive frag- nS^s. 
 ments which we still have are derived from Simplicius. I 
 give them as they are arranged by Diels : 
 
 (i) In the beginning any discourse, it seems to me that one 
 should make one's starting-point something indisputable, and 
 one's expression simple and dignified. R. P. 207. 
 
 (2) My view is, to sum it all up, that all things are differentia- 
 tions of the same thing, and are the same thing. And this is 
 obvious ; for, if the things which are now in this world — earth, 
 and water, and air and fire, and the other things which we see 
 
 1 Diog. ix. 57 (R. P. 206). The statement of Antisthenes, the writer 
 of Successions, that he had " heard " Anaximenes is due to the usual 
 confusion. He was doubtless, like Anaxagoras, " an associate of the 
 philosophy of Anaximenes." Cf. Chap. VI, § 122. 
 
 2 Aristoph. Clouds, 227 sqq., where Sokrates speaks of " mixing his 
 subtle thought with the kindred air," and especially the words ^ 7^ 
 ^iq. I ^\k€l Trpbs avrrjv tt]v tK/uLada T975 (ppovridos. For the iKfxds, see Beare, 
 p. 259. 
 
 3 Simpl. Phys. p. 151, 24 (R. P. 207 a). 
 
 * Simplicius says Upbs ^vaio\6yovs, but he adds that Diogenes called 
 them (Totpiarai, which is the older word. This is, so far, in favour of the 
 genuineness of the work. 
 
 6 Diels gives this as fr. 6 {Vers. 51 b 6). I have omitted it, as it really 
 belongs to the history of Medicine. 
 
 23 
 
 I 
 
354 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 existing in this world — if any one of these things, I say, were 
 different from any other, different, that is, by having a substance 
 pecuhar to itself ; and if it were not the same thing that is often 
 changed and differentiated, then things could not in any way 
 mix with one another^ nor could they do one another good or 
 harm. Neither could a plant grow out of the earth, nor any 
 animal nor anything else come into being unless things were 
 composed in such a way as to be the same. But all these things 
 arise from the same thing ; they are differentiated and take 
 different forms at different times, and return again to the same 
 thing. R. P. 208. 
 
 (3) For it would not be possible for it without intelligence to 
 be so divided, as to keep the measures of all things, of winter 
 and summer, of day and night, of rains and winds and fair 
 weather. And any one who cares to reflect wiU find that every- 
 thing else is disposed in the best possible manner. R. P. 210. 
 
 (4) And, further, there are still the following great proofs. 
 Men and all other animals live upon air by breathing it, and this 
 is their soul and their intelligence, as will be clearly shown in this 
 work ; while, when this is taken away, they die, and their intelli- 
 gence fails. R. P. 210. 
 
 (5) And my view is, that that which has intelligence is what 
 men call air, and that all things have their course steered by it, 
 and that it has power over all things. For this very thing I hold 
 to be a god,i and to reach everywhere, and to dispose everything, 
 and to be in everything ; and there is not anything which does 
 not partake in it. Yet no single thing partakes in it just in the 
 same way as another ; but there are many modes both of air 
 and of intelligence. For it undergoes many transformations, 
 warmer and colder, drier and moister, more stable and in swifter 
 motion, and it has many other differentiations in it, and an 
 infinite number of colours and savours. And the soul of all 
 living things is the same, namely, air warmer than that outside 
 us and in which we are, but much colder than that near the sun. 
 And this warmth is not alike in any two kinds of living creatures, 
 
 ^ The MSS. of Simplicius have ^dos, not deds; but I adopt Usener's 
 certain correction. It is confirmed by the statement of Theophrastos that 
 Diogenes called the air within us " a small portion of the god " {de Sens. 
 42) ; and by Philodemos {Dox. p. 536), where we read that Diogenes praises 
 Homer, rbv aipa yap avrbv Ai'a vofii^etv (pyjaiy, iweidT) irav eiSivai. rov ALa X^7ei 
 (cf. Cic. Nat. D. i. 12, 29) 
 
ECLECTICISM AND REACTION 355 
 
 nor, for the matter of that, in any two men ; but it does not 
 differ much, only so far as is compatible with their being alike. 
 At the same time, it is not possible for any of the things which 
 are differentiated to be exactly like one another till they aU once 
 more become the same. 
 
 (6) Since, then, differentiation is multiform, living creatures 
 are multiform and many, and they are like one another neither 
 in appearance nor in intelUgence, because of the multitude of 
 differentiations. At the same time, they all live, and see, and 
 hear by the same thing, and they all have their intelligence from 
 the same source. R. P. 211. 
 
 (7) And this itself is an eternal and undying body, but of 
 those things ^ some come into being and some pass away. 
 
 (8) But this, too, appears to me to be obvious, that it is both 
 great, and mighty, and eternal, and undying, and of great 
 knowledge. R. P. 209. 
 
 That the chief interest of Diogenes was a physiological 
 one, is clear from his elaborate account of the veins, pre- 
 served by Aristotle. 2 It is noticeable, too, that one of his 
 arguments for the underlying unity of all substances is that 
 without this it would be impossible to understand how one 
 thing could do good or harm to another (fr. 2). In fact, the 
 writing of Diogenes is essentially of the same character as a 
 good deal of the pseudo-Hippokratean literature, and there 
 is much to be said for the view that the writers of these 
 curious tracts made use of him very much as they did of 
 Anaxagoras and Herakleitos.^ 
 
 189. Like Anaximenes, Diogenes regarded Air as the Cos- 
 primary substance ; but we see from his arguments that he 
 lived at a time when other views had become prevalent. 
 
 1 The MSS. of Simplicius have rep Si, but surely the Aldine tQv 84 is 
 right. 2 Arist. Hist. An. T, 2. 511 b 30. 
 
 3 See Weygoldt, " Zu Diogenes von Apollonia " {Arch. i. pp. 161 sqq.). 
 Hippokrates himself represented just the opposite tendency to that of those 
 writers. His great achievement was the separation of medicine from 
 philosophy, a separation most beneficial to both (Celsus, i. pr.). This is 
 why the Hippokratean corpus contains some works in which the " sophists " 
 are denounced and others in which their writings are pillaged. To the 
 latter class belong the Ilepl dLairrjs and the Uepl <pv(x(av ; to the former, 
 especially the ILepl apxaiv^ iaTf^iKTjs. 
 
 I 
 
356 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 He speaks clearly of the four Empedoklean elements (fr. 2), 
 and he is careful to attribute to Air the attributes of Nous 
 as taught by Anaxagoras (fr. 4). The doxographical tradi- 
 tion as to his cosmological views is fairly preserved : 
 
 Diogenes of Apollonia makes air the element, and holds that 
 all things are in motion, and that there are innumerable worlds. 
 And he describes the origin of the world thus. When the All 
 moves and becomes rare in one place and dense in another, where 
 the dense met together it formed a mass, and then the other 
 things arose in the same way, the lightest parts occupying the 
 highest position and producing the sun. [Plut.] Strom, fr. 12 
 (R. P. 215). 
 
 Nothing arises from what is not nor passes away into what 
 is not. The earth is round, poised in the middle, having received 
 its shape through the revolution proceeding from the warm and 
 its solidification from the cold. Diog. ix. 57 (R. P. 215). 
 
 The heavenly bodies were like pumice-stone. He thinks 
 they are the breathing-holes of the world, and that they are 
 red-hot. Aet. ii. 13, 5 = Stob. i. 508 (R. P. 215). 
 
 The sun was like pumice-stone, and into it the rays from the 
 aether fix themselves. Aet. ii. 20, 10. The moon was a pmnice- 
 Uke conflagration. lb. ii. 25, 10. 
 
 Along with the visible heavenly bodies revolve invisible 
 stones, which for that very reason are nameless ; but they often 
 fall and are extinguished on the earth Uke the stone star which 
 fell down flaming at Aigospotamos.^ lb. ii. 13, 9. 
 
 We have here nothing more than the old Ionian doctrine 
 with a few additions from more recent sources. Rarefaction 
 and condensation still hold their place in the explanation of 
 the opposites, warm and cold, dry and moist, stable and 
 mobile (fr. 5). The differentiations into opposites which Air 
 may undergo are, as Anaxagoras had taught, infinite in 
 number ; but all may be reduced to the primary opposition 
 of rare and dense. We may gather, too, from Censorinus 2 
 that Diogenes did not, like Anaximenes, speak of earth and 
 water as arising from Air by condensation, but rather of blood. 
 
 ^ See Chap. VI. p. 252, n. 6. 
 2 Censorinus, de die natali, 6, i {Dox. p. 190). 
 
 I 
 
ECLECTICISM AND REACTION 357 
 
 flesh, and bones. In this he followed Anaxagoras (§ 130), 
 as it was natural that he should. That portion of Air, on 
 the other hand, which was rarefied became fiery, and pro- 
 duced the sun and heavenly bodies. The circular motion of 
 the world is due to the intelligence of the Air, as is also the 
 division of all things into different forms of body and the 
 observance of the " measures " by these forms. ^ 
 
 Like Anaximander (§ 20), Diogenes regarded the sea as 
 the remainder of the original moist state, which had been 
 partially evaporated bj^ the sun, so as to separate out the 
 remaining earth. 2 The earth itself is round, that is to 
 say, it is a disc : for the language of the doxographers 
 does not point to the spherical form.^ Its solidification 
 by the cold is due to the fact that cold is a form of 
 condensation. 
 
 Diogenes did not hold with the earlier cosmologists that 
 the heavenly bodies were made of air or fire, nor yet with 
 Anaxagoras, that they were stones. They were, he said, 
 pumice-hke, a view in which we may trace the influence of 
 Leukippos. They were earthy, indeed, but not solid, and 
 the celestial fire permeated their pores. And this explains 
 why we do not see the dark bodies which, in common with 
 Anaxagoras, he held to revolve along with the stars. They 
 really are solid stones, and therefore cannot be penetrated 
 by the fire. It was one of these that fell into the Aigos- 
 potamos. Like Anaxagoras, Diogenes affirmed that the 
 incHnation of the earth happened subsequently to the rise 
 of animals.* 
 
 We are prepared to find that Diogenes held the doctrine 
 of innumerable worlds ; for it was the old Milesian behef, 
 and had just been revived by Anaxagoras and Leukippos. 
 He is mentioned with the rest in the Placita; and if SimpHcius 
 classes him and Anaximenes with Herakleitos as holding the 
 Stoic doctrine of successive formations and destructions of 
 
 ^ On the " measures " see Chap. III. § 72. 
 
 » Theophr. ap. Alex, in Meteor, p. 67, i {Dox. p. 494). 
 
 8 Diog. ix. 57 (R. P. 215). « Aet. ii. 8, i (R. P. 215). 
 
358 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 a single world, he has probably been misled by the 
 " accommodators/' ^ 
 Animals 190. Living creatures arose from the earth, doubtless 
 plants, under the influence of heat. Their souls, of course, were 
 air, and their differences were due to the various degrees 
 in which it was rarefied or condensed (fr. 5). No special 
 seat, such as the heart or the brain, was assigned to the soul ; 
 it was simply the warm air circulating with the blood in the 
 veins. 
 
 The views of Diogenes as to generation, respiration, and 
 the blood, belong to the history of Medicine ; ^ his theory of 
 sensation too, as it is described by Theophrastos,^ need only 
 be mentioned in passing. Briefly stated, it amounts to this, 
 that all sensation is due to the action of air upon the brain 
 and other organs, while pleasure is aeration of the blood. 
 But the details of the theory can only be studied properly in 
 connexion with the Hippokratean writings ; for Diogenes 
 does not really represent the old cosmological tradition, but 
 a fresh development of reactionary philosophical views 
 combined with an entirely new enthusiasm for detailed 
 investigation and accumulation of facts. 
 
 III. Archelaos of Athens 
 
 Anaxa- IQI- The last of the early cosmologists was Archelaos of 
 
 goreans. Athens, who was a disciple of Anaxagoras.* He is also said, 
 
 by Aristoxenos and Theophrastos, to have been the teacher 
 
 of Sokrates, and there is not the slightest reason for 
 
 doubting it.^ There is no reason either to doubt the tradition 
 
 1 Simpl. Phys. p. 1121, 12. See Chap. I. p. 59. 
 
 2 See Censorinus, quoted in Dox. -p. igi sq. 
 
 3 Theophr. de Sens. 39 sqq. (R. P. 213, 214). For a full account, see 
 Beare, pp. 41 sqq., 105, 140, 169, 209, 258. As Prof. Beare remarked, 
 Diogenes " is one of the most interesting of the pre-Platonic psychologists " 
 (p. 258). « Diog. ii. 16 (R. P. 216). 
 
 5 See Chiapelli in Arch. iv. pp. 369 sqq. Ion of Chios said that Sokrates 
 accompanied Archelaos to Samos (fr. 73 Kopke). If this refers to the siege 
 of Samos, it is interesting to think of the youthful Sokrates serving against 
 a force commanded by Melissos. 
 
ECLECTICISM AND REACTION 359 
 
 that Archelaos succeeded Anaxagoras in the school at Lamp- 
 sakos.i We certainly hear of Anaxagoreans,^ though their 
 fame was soon obscured by the rise of the Sophists, as we 
 call them. 
 
 102. On the cosmoloe:y of Archelaos, Hippolytos ^ Cos- 
 writes as follows : 
 
 Archelaos was by birth an Athenian, and the son of Apollo- 
 doros. He spoke of the mixture of matter in a similar way to 
 Anaxagoras, and of the first principles Ukewise. He held, 
 however, that there was a certain mixture immanent even in 
 Nous. And he held that there were two efficient causes which 
 were separated off from one another, namely, the warm and the 
 cold. The former was in motion, the latter at rest. When the 
 water was liquefied it flowed to the centre, and there being burnt 
 up it turned to earth and air, the latter of which was borne 
 upwards, while the former took up its position below. These, 
 then, are the reasons why the earth is at rest, and why it came 
 into being. It lies in the centre, being practically no appreciable 
 part of the universe. (But the air rules over all things),* being 
 produced by the burning of the fire, and from its original com- 
 bustion comes the substance of the heavenly bodies. Of these the 
 sun is the largest, and the moon second ; the rest are of various 
 sizes. He says that the heavens were inclined, and that then 
 the sun made light upon the earth, made the air transparent, 
 and the earth dry ; for it was originally a pond, being high at 
 the circumference and hoUow in the centre. He adduces as a 
 proof of this hoUowness that the sun does not rise and set at the 
 same time for aU peoples, as it ought to do if the earth were level. 
 As to animals, he says that when the earth was first being warmed 
 in the lower part where the warm and the cold were mingled 
 together, many living creatures appeared, and especially men, all 
 having the same manner of life, and deriving their sustenance 
 
 1 Euseb. P. E. p. 504, c 3, 6 5^ 'Apx^^aos iv Aafi\pdK(^ diedi^aro rV 
 (TXoM]v Tov 'Ava^aySpov. 
 
 2 'Ava^ayopeLOL are mentioned by Plato {Crat. 409 b 6), and in the Aitro-oi 
 \6yot (cf. p. 29, n. 3). It is also to be noted that Plato {Parm. 126 a, b) 
 represents certain <pt\6<xo(l)OL from Klazomenai as coming to Athens after 
 the death of Sokrates for the purpose of getting an accurate account of the 
 famous conversation between Parmenides and the young Sokrates (§ 84). 
 
 3 Hipp. Ref. i. 9 (R. P. 218). 
 
 * Inserting t6v 8' d4pa KpareXv tov iravrds, as suggested by Roeper. 
 
36o EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 from the slime ; they did not live long, and later on generation 
 from one another began. And men were distinguished from the 
 rest, and set up leaders, and laws, and arts, and cities, and so 
 forth. And he says that Nous is implanted in all animals alike ; 
 for each of the animals, as well as man, makes use of Nous, but 
 some quicker and some slower. 
 
 It is clear from this that, just as Diogenes had tried to 
 introduce certain Anaxagorean ideas into the philosophy of 
 Anaximenes, so Archelaos sought to bring Anaxagoreanism 
 nearer to the old Ionic views by supplementing it with the 
 opposition of warm and cold, rare and dense, and by stripping 
 Nous of that simplicity which had marked it off from the 
 other " things " in his master's system. It was probably 
 for this reason, too, that Nous was no longer regarded as 
 the maker of the world. ^ Leukippos had made such a force 
 unnecessary. It may be added that this twofold relation 
 of Archelaos to his predecessors makes it very credible that, 
 as Actios tells us,^ he believed in innumerable worlds ; both 
 Anaxagoras and the older lonians upheld that doctrine. 
 Con- 103. The cosmology of Archelaos, like that of Diogenes, 
 
 elusion. 
 
 has all the characteristics of the age to which it belonged — 
 an age of reaction, eclecticism, and investigation of detail.^ 
 Hippon of Samos and Idaios of Himera represent nothing 
 more than the feeUng that philosophy had run into a bUnd 
 alley, from which it could only escape by trying back. The 
 Herakleiteans at Ephesos, impenetrably wrapped up as they 
 were in their own system, did little but exaggerate its para- 
 doxes and develop its more fanciful side.* It was not enough 
 for Kratylos to say with Herakleitos (fr. 84) that you cannot 
 step twice into the same river ; you could not do so even 
 
 1 Aet. i. 7, i4=Stob. i. 56 (R. P. 217 a). 2 Aet. ii. i, 3. 
 
 3 Windelband, § 25. The period is well described by Fredrich, Hippo- 
 kratische Untersuchungen, pp. 130 sqq. It can only be treated fully in 
 connexion with the Sophists. 
 
 * For an amusing picture of the Herakleiteans see Plato, Theaet. 179 e. 
 The new interest in language, which the study of rhetoric had called into 
 life, took with them the form of fantastic and arbitrary etymologising, such 
 as is satirised in Plato's Cratylus. 
 
ECLECTICISM AND REACTION 361 
 
 once.i The fact is that philosophy, so long as it clung to 
 its old presuppositions, had nothing more to say ; for the 
 answer of Leukippos to the question of Thales was really 
 final. 
 
 It will be observed that aU these warring systems found 
 their way to Athens, and it was there, and there alone that 
 the divergent theories of Ionia and the West came into 
 contact. Such questions as whether the earth was round 
 or fiat, and whether "what we think with" was Air or Blood, 
 must have been hotly debated at Athens about the middle 
 of the fifth century B.C., when Sokrates was young. On any 
 view of him, it is surely incredible that he was not interested 
 in these controversies at the time, however remote they may 
 have seemed to him in later hfe. Now, in the Phaedo, Plato 
 has put into his mouth an autobiographical statement in 
 which he tells us that this was actually the case,^ and the 
 list of problems there given is one that can only have occupied 
 men's minds at Athens and at that date.^ All the scientific 
 schools end at Athens, and it was the Athenian Sokrates who 
 saw that the questions they had raised could only be met by 
 making a fresh start from another point of view. 
 
 ^ Arist. Met. r, 5. ioioai2. He refused even to speak, we are told, 
 and only moved his finger. 
 
 2 Plato, Phaedo, 96 a sqq. 
 
 3 I have tried to show this in detail in my notes on the passage in my 
 edition of the Phaedo (Oxford, 1910). It is a remarkable proof of Plato's 
 historical sense that he should have been able to give an account of the 
 state of scientific opinion at Athens some twenty-five years before his own 
 birth, without, so far as I can see, a single anachronism. 
 
^ 
 
APPENDIX 
 
 ON THE MEANING OF ^vac^; 
 
 The account which I have given (pp. lo s^^.) of the meaning of 
 the term c^wts in early Greek philosophy has been criticised by 
 Professor W. A. Heidel in a paper entitled Hepl <^vo-ea)s, A Study 
 of the Conception of Nature among the Pre-Socratics} It is an 
 exceedingly valuable paper, and I cannot find that it contains 
 anything inconsistent with my view, though the writer apparently 
 thinks it does. The only point at issue, so far as I can see, is 
 that Professor Heidel assumes that the original meaning of </)vo-ts 
 is "growth," which seems to me extremely doubtful. No doubt 
 the verb (fivofiai (i.e. ^vioixai) with a long vowel means " I grow," 
 but the simple root ^v is the equivalent of the Latin fu and the 
 English be, and need not necessarily have this derivative meaning. 
 
 There is an interesting article in support of my view by 
 Professor Lovejoy in the Philosophical Review, vol. xviii. pp. 369 
 sqq., and Mr. Beardslee has recently examined the use of the word 
 ^v<jLs in Greek writers of the fifth century B.C. in a Ph.D. disserta- 
 tion (University of Chicago Press, 19 18). Here again, while 
 acknowledging the value of the work, I can only say that I do not 
 find its results inconsistent with the account I have given. I have 
 never questioned the obvious fact that the word (^wts had a 
 history, and developed meanings quite different from that which 
 it may have had for an Ionian. 
 
 I should almost be willing to rest the case for this on the 
 fragment of Euripides quoted on p. 10, where the significant 
 epithet dOdvaros Kal dyrip(D<s is given to (f)V(TL?, but it may be well 
 to collect here some of the passages on which I also rely. 
 
 I. Plato, Laws 891 C l, KLvSwevec ydp 6 Aeywv ravTa irvp kol 
 vSoyp KOL yrjv kol dkpa irpQtTa rjyeia-Oai twv TravTWV eiVat, Kat rrjv 
 (f)V(TiV ovojU,a^€6v TavTa avrd. 892 c 2, ^vcrtv f^ovXovTat Aeyetv 
 yevecrtv rrjv Trepl to. rrpdra' et Se (^av/ycrerat ^VX"! ""pajTov, ov 
 TTvp ovSe d-qp, ^vx'>] S' ^v 7rpioToi<5 yeyevTjixhr], (rxe66v opOorara 
 XkyoLT dv etvai 8La(ji€p6vT(D<s ^Txret. 
 
 1 Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, vol. xlv. No. 4. 
 
 363 
 
364 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 In 891 c 7 the use of (f>v(rL<s here criticised is expressly said to 
 be that of ottoctol TrwTroTe riov Trepl <j)V(r€(x)s €(f)7J\l/avT0 ^rjTrjfjLOLTiov. 
 
 2. Ar. Phys, B, i. 193 a 9, hoK^l 8 y] (fivcns koI rj ovcria rdv 
 
 (fiV(T€L OVTOiV eVLOLS €tVat TO TTpoOTOV €VV7rdp)(0V eKOXTTO) dppvOfXL<TTOV 
 
 KaO eavTO, oTov kAiv^s (f)V(TLS to ^vXov, dvSpidvros 8' 6 x^^^'^^s. 
 crrjfietov 8e cf>7](TLv AvTLcfiioP oVt, et tls Karopv^ete kXlvtjv kol XdfSot 
 SvvafiLv 'q crrjTreSayv ^crre dveivai fSXacTTOv, ovk dv yevecrOat kXlvtjv 
 dXXd ^vXov. 
 
 Antiphon the Sophist was a contemporary of Sokrates. 
 
 3. Ar. Phys. A, 6. 18952, ot /^lav Ttvo, ^v<jiv etvai Xeyovres 
 rh Trav, otov v8(i)p t] irvp rj to fiera^v Tovrtuv. B, I. 193 a 21, ot 
 )U,ev TTvp, ol Se yrfv, 01 8 d^pa (ftaa-iv, ol 8e vSoyp, ot 8 eVta tovtidv, 
 ot 8k Trdvra ravra rrjv (jivcnv eivat rrjv riov ovtcov. P, 4. 203 a 16, 
 ot Se Trepl (f)V(T€ii)<s del TravTcs viroTiOeacnv krkpav nvd ^vcrw t(^ 
 dTrelpi^ rdv Xeyofxevoiv (rroL^eioiv, otov v8o)p rj dkpa r) to fiera^v 
 
 TOVT(i)V. 
 
 4. Ar. Afe^. A, 4. 1014 b 16, <^w"ts Xeyerai eva fiev rpoirov 'q 
 Twv (fiVOfjicviDV y€ve(TLS, otov €t Tts eTTCKTeivas Aeyot to v. 
 
 There is no doubt that this means that, to Aristotle, <^i;o-is did 
 not immediately suggest the verb <^voixai. That has a long v and 
 4iva-Ls has a short v. We need not discuss the question whether 
 Aristotle's difficulty is a real one or not. All that concerns us is 
 that he felt it. 
 
 5. Aristotle, II/aoTpeTrTtKos, fr. 52 Rose {ap. Iambi. Protr. p. 38. 
 22 Pistelli), o/xofcws 8\ kol twv Trepl <^i;o-€0>s (ea-rt Tts eTTLfieXeta kol 
 Te^vrj)' TToXv yap Trporepov dvayKaiov r(av aiTtwv Acai twi/ (TTOt^j^etwv 
 etvat (fipovrjCTLV rj twv vcrrepov. ov ydp ravra twv aKpaiv ov8 l/c 
 TovTWv TO, TT/awTa 7r€cf)VK€v, dXX e^ eK€LV(i)v KOi 81' eK€iv(DV rdXXa 
 ytyvcTat /cat o-vvia-TaTai (jiavepcos. eiVe ydp irvp clt drjp etr dptO/xhs 
 ctVe aAAat Ttves <^Txrets atTiat kol TrpOtrai twv aAAwv, d8vvarov twv 
 cLAAwv Tt ytyi/wo-Kctv e/ceii/as dyvoovvTas* ttws yap av ti? '^7 Aoyoi/ 
 yvoipl^OL a-vXXafSds dyvo(Ji)V, rj TavTas eTrtcrraiTO ixr]8€V tcov o^Tot^eiW 
 etSws ; 
 
 The importance of this passage. for our purpose is that it is 
 from a popular work, in which the phraseology is Academic (e.g. 
 the use of (^povrja-is for what Aristotle himself called aocfita). 
 
 The usage of Theophrastos is the same, but of course he simply 
 reproduces Aristotle. 
 
INDEXES 
 
 I. ENGLISH 
 
 Aahmes, iS sq., 46 
 
 Abaris, 81, go n. 2 
 
 Abdera, school of, 61, 330 sq. 
 
 Abstinence, Orphic and Pythagorean, 
 93> 95 ; Empedoklean, 250 
 
 Academy, 29 ; library of, 33, 116, 171 
 w- 3, 353 
 
 Accommodation {avvoiKeluais) , 32, 142, 
 358 
 
 Achaians, 2 n. i, 4, 81 ; of Pelo- 
 ponnesos, 92 ; dialect, 282 n. 4 
 
 Achilles and the tortoise, 318 
 
 Achilles, Elaayuyr], Sources § g (p. 34), 
 191 n. 3, 292 n. 2, 298 n. 1 
 
 Adrastos, 24 n. 2 
 
 Aegean civilisation, survivals of, 2, 3, 
 15, 21 n. 2, 39, 80 
 
 Aether. See aW-qp 
 
 Aetios, Sources § 10 (p. 35) 
 
 Ages of the world, 5 
 
 Aigospotamof, meteoric stone of, 252, 
 269, 357 
 
 Ainesidem /S, 152 
 
 Air, idencified with mist or vapour, 
 62, 64, 68, 74 sq., 109, no, 153, 
 187 n. I, 216 n. 2, 219 n. 3, 228 n. 2, 
 246 n. 2 ; identified with the void, 
 109, 186, 194, 229 ; atmospheric, 
 109, 229, 266 sq., 269, 289, 293, 337 
 
 Akousmata, 96, 98, 283 
 
 Akousmatics, 94, 96, 98 
 
 Akragas, 3, 197 sqq. 
 
 Alexander, writer of Successions, 
 Sources § 17 (p. 37) 
 
 Alexander Aetolus, 255 
 
 Alexander Aphrodisiensis, Sources § 7 
 (P- 33) \ oil Anaximander, 64 ; on 
 Xenophanes, 116 n. i, 126; on the 
 Pythagoreans, 107 n. i, 288, 306 
 nn. I and 2 ; on Parmenides, 183 ; on 
 Zeno, 320 n. I ; on Kippon, 351 
 
 Alkidamas, 86, 199 «. 5, 201 «. 2, 202, 
 257 n. I, 278 n. I, 312 
 
 I 
 
 Alkmaion of Kroton, 86, no n. 2, 153, 
 193-196, 202, 248, 282 n. 5, 296, 332 
 
 Allegorists, Homeric, 49 «. i, 116 », 2 
 
 Amasis, 40, 88 
 
 Amber, 48 n. i, 50 
 
 Ameinias, 170 
 
 Anakreon and Kritias, 203 n. 3 
 
 Anaxagoras, 251-275 ; and Euripides, 
 10, 255 ; and Sokrates, 256, 267 ; 
 and Per ikies, 254 sqq. ; and Zeno, 
 349 ; and Anaximenes, 253, 266, 
 269, 270, 271 ; and Herakleitos, 264, 
 268 ; and Empedokles, 261, 264, 265, 
 267, 268, 273 sq. ; and Leukippos, 
 331 ; relation to the Eleatics, 182, 
 261, 310 ; on the rise of the Nile, 
 45 ; on the moon's light, 177 n. i ; 
 on eclipses, 306 ; on irbvos, 326 n. 2 ; 
 primitive cosmology of, in, 297 
 
 Anaxagoreans, 29 n. 3, 359 n. 2 
 
 Anaximander, 50-71 ; as an observer 
 in marine biology, 26 ; and Xeno- 
 
 ^^ phanes, 114 
 
 i;^" Anaximenes, 72-79, i79 ; school of, 
 """ 79. 253, 305, 330, 353 w. I 
 
 Androkydes, 283 
 
 Andron of Ephesos, 87 
 
 Anecdotes, of Thales, 46 n. 4 ; of 
 Xenophanes, 113 n. 2, 115 n. 3 ; 
 of Herakleitos, 115 n. 3, 131 n. 4 ; 
 of Empedokles, 200 n. 5 
 
 Animals, Anaximander, 26, 70 sqq. ; 
 Empedokles, 242 sqq. ; Anaxagoras, 
 272 sq. ; Diogenes of Apollonia, 358 
 
 Antichthon, 297, 305 sq. 
 
 Antisthenes, writer of Successions, 
 Sources § 17 (p. 37) 
 
 Antonius Diogenes, 87 «. 2 
 
 Apollo, an Achaian god, 4 
 
 ApoUo Hyperboreios, 4, 81, 87 n. 3, 
 90, 200 
 
 ApoUodoros, Sources § 21 (p. 38) ; on 
 Thales, 44 «. 2 ; on Anaximander, 
 
 365 
 
366 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 51 ; on Anaximenes, 72 ; on Pytha- 
 goras, 88 n. 2 ; on Xenophanes, 
 113 ; on Herakleitos, 130 ; on 
 Parmenides, 169 ; on Empedokles, 
 197 nn. I and 2, 198 ; on Anaxagoras, 
 251, 254 ». I, 331 «. I ; on Zeno, 
 310 sq. ; on Melissos, 321 ; on 
 Leukippos, 331 ; on Demokritos, 
 331 w. I 
 Apollonia, 52, 352 n. 3 
 Apollonios of Tyana, 87 n. 2, 95 
 Apophthegms, of Thales, 50 w. 3 ; of 
 Herakleitos, 50 «. 3 ; of Anaxa- 
 goras, 252, 274 ; of Philolaos, 284 
 n. 2 
 Appearances, saving, 28, 188 
 Arcadian and Cypriote dialect, 4 n. 2 
 Archelaos, 256, 358-360 ; and Anaxa- 
 goras, 360 
 Archippos, 91, 276 w. i 
 Archytas, 276 ; on Eurytos, 100 n. 2 ; 
 definition of harmonic mean, 106 
 «. 2 
 Aristarchos of Samos, 299 
 Aristeas of Prokonnesos, 81, 90 n. 2 
 Aristophanes, on Thales, 47 w. i ; on 
 Alvos, 61 n. 3 ; on Diogenes of Apol- 
 lonia, 331, 353 
 Aristotle, Sources § 2 (p. 31) ; on the 
 rise of the Nile, 45 ; on Egyptian 
 mathematics, 15 n. 4, 19 ; on Baby- 
 lonian astronomy, 23 «. 2 ; on 
 " theologians," 7 ; on Ionian 
 monism, 9 «. 2 ; on Thales, 46 
 n. 4, 47-50 ; on Anaximander, 53, 
 55 sq., 57, 60 n. 4, 63 sq., 66 n. i ; 
 on Anaximenes (?), 77 ; on Pytha- 
 goras, 86, 87 «. 3, 90 ». 2, 97 
 n. 3 ; on Xenophanes, 113 n. 2, 
 115 n. 3, 124 sq., 126 sq. ; on 
 Hippasos, 109, 142 ; on Hera- 
 kleitos, 133 n. I, 140 n. 2, 142, 144 
 n. I, 146, 151, 157, 158, 159 ; on 
 Parmenides, 170, 178 n. 3, 181, 182, 
 185 sq. ; on Alkmaion, 193, 196 ; 
 on Empedokles, 158 n, i, 199, 200, 
 229, 230, 231, 232, 233, 234, 235, 
 236 n. 1, 237, 239 nn. 1 and 4, 240, 
 241, 242, 243, 244, 249 ; on Anaxa- 
 goras, 251, 252 n. 5, 257 n. I, 261 
 ». I, 262 n. I, 263, 264 n. 3, 265, 
 267, 268 n. I, 269 n. I ; on the 
 Pythagoreans, 92 n. 2, 107, 277, 
 284 sqq., 289, 290 n. i, 291 sqq., 
 305, 306, 307 ; on Eurytos, 100 
 «. 2 ; on Zeno, 312, 313, 317, 318 sqq. ; 
 on Melissos, 324 sq., 327, 328 ; on 
 Leukippos, 330, 334 sq., 335 sq., 
 336 ; on Hippon, 351 ; on Diogenes 
 of ApoUonia, 355 ; on Demokritos, 
 342 ; on gravity, 340, 343 ; on 
 eternal motion, 12 ; on the diurnal 
 
 revolution, 13 n. i ; on the celestial 
 spheres, 188 ; on the substance of 
 the heavens, 15 n. 1, 27 n. 1 ; on 
 the motion of the earth, 299 sqq. ; 
 on the galeus levis, 70 n. 2, 71 «. 2 ; 
 on the theoretic life, 83, 98 ; on the 
 mysteries, 84 m. 4 ; misunder- 
 standings of Platonic humour, 
 Sources § 2 (p. 32), 48 n. 2, 127, 170 ; 
 nporpeTTTiKds, 83 «. 2 ; on triangular, 
 square, and oblong numbers, 100 sq., 
 103 M. 2 ; on incommensurability, 
 105 n. 2 ; doctrine of the Mean, 
 112 n. 2 
 
 [Aristotle] de Mundo, 164 
 
 [Aristotle] de Plantis, 241, 242 «. i, 
 257 w. 3, 272 
 
 Aristoxenos, on Pythagoras, 86, 87 
 *»• 5, 89, 91, 93 nn. 4 and 5, 94 «. i, 
 99 n. I, 307 M. 3 ; on the Pytha- 
 goreans, 97 n. 4, 277, 288 n. 3, 309 ; 
 on Eurytos, 100 n. 1, 277 ; on 
 Archytas, 276 ; on Philolaos, 283 
 n. I ; YivdayopiKal diro(pd(r€LS, 92 
 n. 3, 96, 281 ; on Hippon, 351 n. i ; 
 on Plato, 279 sq. 
 
 Arithmetic, Egyptian, 19 ; Pytha- 
 gorean, 99 sqq. ; Euclidean, 106 
 
 Arnobius, Sources § 16 (p. 37) 
 
 Arpedonapts, 20, 105 
 
 Astrology, 24 n. 1 
 
 Astronomy, Babylonian and Greek, 
 21 sq. See Heavenly bodies, Sun, 
 Moon, Planets, Stars, Earth, 
 Eclipses, Geocentric and Helio- 
 centric hypotheses 
 
 Atheism, 50 
 
 Athenagoras, Sources § 9 (p. 34) 
 
 Athens, meeting-place of Ionian and 
 Italiote science, 321, 361 ; Par- 
 menides and Zeno at, 169, 311 n. 1 ; 
 Empedokles at, 203 ; Anaxagoras 
 at, 254 sqq. 
 
 Atomism, 180 n. i, 182, 336 sqq. See 
 Leukippos 
 
 Atoms, movement of, 13, 61, 340, 
 345 sq. ; weight of, 341 sq. 
 
 Augustine, Sources § 16 (p. 37) 
 
 Babylonian astronomy, 21 sqq., 157 ; 
 
 prediction of eclipses, 42 sq. 
 Beans, taboo on, 93 n. 5 
 Bias, 140 
 
 Biology. See Animals, Plants 
 Blood, Empedokles, 201, 229, 247 ; 
 
 Diogenes of ApoUonia, 355 ; Sicilian 
 
 school of medicine, 249 n. 4 
 Boundless. See d-jreipov 
 Brain, Alkmaion, 194 ; Empedokles, 
 
 201, 249 ; Plato and Hippokrates, 
 
 249 n. 4 
 Breath. See Respiration 
 
INDEX 
 
 367 
 
 Breath of the world, 75, 108, 128, 185 
 
 sq., 231 
 Brotinos, 194 
 
 Calendar, Babylonian, 22 ; Thales, 47 
 
 Cave, Orphic, 83 n. 3, 223 n. i 
 
 Centum and satetn languages, 2 «. i 
 
 Chaos, 7 ». I 
 
 Cicero, Sources § 12 (p. 35) ; on Stoic 
 " accommodation," 32 n. 1 ; on 
 Thales, 49 sq. ; on Anaximander, 60 ; 
 on Anaximenes, 78; on Pythagoras, 
 89 n. 3 ; on Parmenides, 191 «. 2, 
 192 «. I ; on Anaxagoras, 253 m. i ; 
 on Atomism, 341 n. 2 
 
 Clement of Alexandria, 16 
 
 Comic poets on Pythagoreans, 94 n. 3 
 
 Condensation. See Rarefaction 
 
 Conflagration. See iKTrvpojais. 
 
 Constellations, names of, 21 ». 2 
 
 Continuity, 320 x 
 
 Copernicus, 299 n. 3 
 
 Cosmogonies 7 sq. 
 
 Croesus, Solon and, 24, 113; Milesians 
 and, 39 sqq. 
 
 Cjnril, Sources § 9 (p. 34) 
 
 Damasias, 44 
 
 Damaskios, 7 w. 3 
 
 Damon, 255 n. 2, 256, 296 n. 2 
 
 Darkness, 74, 109, 155, 186, 187, 237, 
 
 239 
 
 Death, Herakleitos, 137 n. 6, 138, 
 153 sq. ; Parmenides, 193 ; Alk- 
 maion, 195 ; Empedokles, 244 sq. 
 
 Dekad, 102 
 
 Delos, 80, 81, 90 n. 2 
 
 Demetrios Magnus, on Philolaos, 281 
 
 Demetrios Phalereus, on Thales, 44 ; 
 on Anaxagoras, 251 
 
 Demokritos, not a " pre-Socratic," 
 I «. I ; date of, 252 n. 2, 331 ; 
 on Egyptian mathematics, 20 ; on 
 Anaxagoras, 252, 331, 348 ; and 
 Leukippos, 331 ; and Epicurus, 341 
 sq. ; primitive cosmology of, 79 n. i, 
 III, 297 sq., 339 
 
 Derkyllides, 42 n. i, 304 n. i 
 
 Diagonal and side of square, 105 
 
 Dialectic, Eleatic, 180, 313 sqq. 
 
 Diels, Doxographi graeci. Sources § 6 
 (p- 33) > on Apollodoros, Sources § 21 
 I (p. 38) 
 V Dikaiarchos, on Pythagoras, 86, 89 n. 4, 
 
 I 92 
 
 I Diodoros of Aspendos, 95 
 
 \ Diogenes of Apollonia, 352-358, 64, 79, 
 
 !• 145 n. I ; and Empedokles, 356 ; 
 
 and Anaxagoras, 356 sq. ; and 
 
 Leukippos, 357 
 Diogenes Laertios, Sources § 15 (p. 37), 
 
 § 20 (p. 38) ; on Herakleitos, 147 
 
 sq. 
 Dionysos, 81 
 Distances, measurement of inaccessible, 
 
 46 
 Divisibility, 262, 264, 316 sq., 327, 335, 
 
 349 
 Dodecahedron, 284 n. i, 293 sqq. 
 Dorians, 2 «. i, 89 5^. 
 Doric dialect, 281, 282 sq. 
 Doxographers, Sources § 6 (p. 33 
 
 sqq.) \ 
 
 Earth, shape of, 23 n. 3, 66, 79 n. i, 
 III, 190 n. 1, 298, 347; originally 
 moist, 26, 63 sqq., 65, 240 ; motion 
 of, 66 n. 3, 69, 299 sqq., 305, 307 ; 
 Thales, 47 ; Anaximander, 65 sq. ; 
 Anaximenes, 77 ; Pythagoras, 1 1 1 ; 
 Xenophanes, 125 ; Empedokles, 240 ; 
 Anaxagoras, 271 ; Pythagoreans, 
 300 sqq. ; Leukippos, 347 ; Dio- 
 genes of Apollonia, 357. See 
 Geocentric hypothesis 
 
 Echekrates, 85, 277, 295 
 
 Eclipses, 22 ; Babylonian predictions 
 of, 42 ; Thales, 41 sq., 113 n. i ; 
 Anaximander, 67 w. 2 ; Anaximenes, 
 78 ; Xenophanes, 122 ; Herakleitos, 
 67 n. 2, 148 ; Alkmaion, 195 ; 
 Empedokles, 239 ; Anaxagoras, 271, 
 272 ; Pythagoreans, 298, 305 ; Leu- 
 kippos, 347 
 
 Ecliptic. See Obliquity 
 
 Effluences. See airoppoal. 
 
 Egypt, 3, 15, 16 ; Thales and, 44 ; 
 Pythagoras and, 88 
 
 Egyptian mathematics, 15 ; arith- 
 metic, 18 ; geometry, 19 
 
 Ekphantos, 291 n. 3, 300 n. i, 336 n. i 
 
 Elea, 169 ; era of, 113, 170 ; Xeno- 
 phanes and, 113, 115, 127; 
 Parmenides and, 169 ; Zeno and, 
 
 311 
 Eleatics. See Parmenides, Zeno, " 
 Melissos ; Plato on, 29 n. 2, 127 ; 
 Leukippos and the, 331, 333 sqq.y 
 
 349 
 
 Elements, 12 n. 2, 53, 55 sq., 201 n. 5, 
 206 n. I, 228 sqq., 283, 292 sq. 
 See Roots, Seeds, eWos, I5ia, iJ.op<fyfi, 
 aroix^LOP 
 
 Embryology, Parmenides, 178 «. 2, 
 192 ; Empedokles, 244 
 
 Empedokles, 197-250 : was he a 
 Dorian ? 3 ; at Athens, 203 ; and 
 Orphicism, 200, 2495^. ; and medicine, 
 201 sq.; and Pythagoras, 200, 224 
 n. 5 ; and Xenophanes, 125, 212 
 n. 3 ; and Parmenides, 182, 202, 
 224 n. 5, 227 sqq., 249, 310; and 
 Zeno, 202 ; and Leukippos, 202, 
 
368 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 332 ; and Gorgias, 201, 249 n. i ; 
 on " air " and darkness, 237 
 
 Engineering, Ionian, 40 w. i 
 
 Ephesos, 130 sqq. 
 
 Ephoros, on Anaxagoras, 255 n. 6 
 
 Epicharmos, 113 n. 2, 116, 127 n. 3, 
 152 n. I 
 
 Epicureans, Sources § 12 (p. 36) 
 
 Epicurus, on innumerable worlds, 59 ; 
 on Leukippos, 330 n. 2, 339 ; atomic 
 theory of, 341 sq., 343 sq. 
 
 Epimenides, 7, 97, 112 ; evaporation, 
 49. See duadvfxlaacs 
 
 Equinoxes, 21, 42 ». i, 51, 301 n. i ; 
 precession of the, 22 n. i 
 
 Er, myth of, 188, 190, 191 
 
 Eratosthenes, Sources § 21 (p. 38) ; 
 on Anaximander's map, 51 ; on 
 Pythagoras, 88 w. i 
 
 Eros, in Hesiod, 7 ; in Parmenides, 191 
 
 Ethics, origin of, i 
 
 Euclid, arithmetic, 106 ; i. 47, 105 ; 
 iv. II, 295 n. 2 
 
 Eudemos of Rhodes, on Thales, 42 
 n. I, 44 n. 4, 45 nn. 4 and 5 ; on 
 Anaximander, 66 «. 3 ; on Pytha- 
 goras, 104 M. 3 ; on Parmenides, 178 
 n. 3 ; on Zeno, 315 m. 3 ; on Melissos, 
 325 n. I ; on the term aroix^Tov, 
 228 n. I 
 
 Eudoxos, spheres of, 62 n. i, 188 ; 
 theory of proportion, 106 
 
 Euripides, on (pijais, 10 ; and Anaxa- 
 goras, 255 
 
 Eurytos, 99 sq., 100 n. i, 107, 277, 
 278, 283 n. I 
 
 Eusebios, Sources § 9 (p. 34), § 14 
 (p. 36), § 16 (p. 37) ; on Mosaic 
 origin of Greek philosophy, 16 
 
 Euthjonenes of Massalia, 45 
 
 Evans, Sir Arthur, 2 «. i, 4 w. 2 
 
 Even and Odd, 287 sqq. 
 
 Evolution, Anaximander, 71 ; Empe- 
 dokles, 242 sqq. ; Anaxagoras, 272 sq. 
 
 Examyes, 41 
 
 Experiment, 27. See Klepsydra 
 
 Figures, numerical, 100 ; " Arabic," 
 
 100 n. 3 
 Fire, fed by moisture, 49, 64 m. i, 150, 
 
 156 n. I ; Hippasos, 109 ; Hera- 
 
 kleitos, 145 
 Fire, central, 190, 296 sqq. 
 Floruit. See aKfii) 
 Flux, Herakleitian, 145 sq. 
 Forgeries, Pythagorean, 92 n. 5, 
 
 280 sqq. 
 Fossils, Xenophanes on, 26, 123 sq. 
 
 Galen, Sources § 9 (p. 34)1 on 
 
 Empedokles, 200 
 Galeus levis, 70 n. 2, 71 n. 2 
 
 Geocentric hypothesis, 23, 27 sq., iii, 
 190, 297 n. 3, 299 sqq., 304 sq. 
 
 Geometry, Egyptian, 19 sq. ; of 
 Thales, 45 sq. ; of Pythagoras, 
 104 sq. 
 
 Glaukos of Rhegion, 198 n. i 
 
 Gnomon, the carpenter's tool, 21 w. i ; 
 the astronomical instrument, 26 n. i, 
 42 «. I, 51 n. 4 ; in geometry and 
 arithmetic, 21 n. i, 103 
 
 God, gods, in Homer, 4 ; in Hesiod, 
 5, 14 ; non-religious use of the word, 
 14, 80 ; fall of gods, 81 ; Thales, 
 48, 50 ; Anaximander, 60 ; 
 Anaximenes, 78 ; Xenophanes, 128 
 sq. ; Herakleitos, 167 ; Parmenides 
 (avoids the term), 179 ; Empedokles, 
 230, 235, 249 ; Diogenes of Apollonia, 
 354 n. I 
 
 Golden Section, 295 n. 2 
 
 Gorgias and Empedokles, 198 n. 2, 
 
 199 w. 5, 200, 201, 222 n. I, 249 n. I 
 Great Year, 156 sqq. 
 
 Greek, origin of the name, 2 m. i ; 
 Greek language, ib. 
 
 Harmonic mean, 106 n. 2 
 
 Harmonics, 98, 306 sq. 
 
 " Harmony of the Spheres," no, 306 
 ^9-> 307 n. I. See Soul and dp/xovia. 
 
 Hearing, sense of, Alkmaion, 195 «. i ; 
 Empedokles, 247, 248 ; Anaxagoras, 
 273 sq. 
 
 Heart, Alkmaion, 194 ; Empedokles, 
 201 
 
 Heavenly bodies, Anaximander, 62 
 sqq., 66 sqq. ; Anaximenes, 75 sqq. ; 
 Pythagoras, no sq. ; Xenophanes, 
 121 sqq. ; Herakleitos, 148 sqq. ; 
 Parmenides, 187 sq. ; Alkmaion, 
 195 ; Empedokles, 237 sqq. ; Anaxa- 
 goras, 271 sq. ; Leukippos, 347 ; 
 Diogenes of Apollonia, 357 
 
 Hekataios, in Egypt, 17 n. i ; on 
 Thales (?), 45, 50 ; and Anaxi- 
 mander's map, 51 ; Herakleitos on, 
 134 
 
 Heliocentric hypothesis, 23, 299 sqq. 
 
 Herakleides of Pontos, on Pythagoras, 
 95 nn. 2 and 3, 98 n. 3, 278 n. i ; on 
 Empedokles, 197 n. 2, 198 n. i, 
 
 200 n. 5, 203 n. I, 312 «. I ; on 
 Ekphantos, 336 ». i ; on the earth's 
 motion, 300 n. i 
 
 Herakleides Lembos, Sources § 17 
 
 (P- 37) 
 Herakleiteans, 29 n. i, 145 n. i, 166 
 
 n. 2, 360 n. 4 
 Herakleitos, 130-168 : on Homer, 136, 
 
 141, 162, 164; on Hesiod, 134, 136; 
 
 on Archilochos, 141 ; on Hekataios, 
 
 134 ; and Anaximenes, 146 ; on 
 
 I 
 
INDEX 
 
 369 
 
 Pythagoras, 85, 87 n. 5, 88, 97, 130, 
 131, 134, 135 «, 5 ; on Xenophanes, 
 114, 130, 134 ; and Protagoras, 166 ; 
 reference to the " three lives," 98 
 ». 3, 140 n. 3 ; apophthegms, 50 n. 3 
 
 Herakleitos, the Homeric Allegorist, 
 on Thales, 49 n. i 
 
 Hermippos, Sources § 18 (p. 37), 280 
 
 Hermodoros of Ephesos, 130, 131 n. i, 
 140 sq. 
 
 Hermokrates, 279 «. 2 
 
 Herodotos, on Homer and Hesiod, 
 6 ; on Egyptian influences, 15 ; 
 on Egyptian geometry, 19; on 
 the rise of the Nile, 44 ; on the 
 gnomon, 51 n. 4 ; on Orphicism, 88 ; 
 on the Hyperboreans, 81 ; on 
 Abaris and Aristeas, 81 ; on Solon 
 and Croesus, 24 ; on Lydian in- 
 fluences, 39 ; on Thales, 40-44, 46 ; 
 on Pythagoras, 85, 87 n. 5, 88 ; on 
 the foundation of Elea, 113 n. 5 ; 
 on Empedokles (?), 88 «. 5 ; on 
 Anaxagoras, 270 «. 6 
 
 Hesiod, 5 sq., 14. See Xenophanes 
 
 Hieron, 113 
 
 Hiketas, 300 n. i 
 
 Hippasos, 94 n. 2, 106 n. 1, 109 n. 6, 
 142, r87, 293, 295 
 
 Hippokrates of Kos, on Ionian 
 monism, 9 n. 2, 26 ; on Empedokles, 
 202 ; on the brain, 249 n. 4 ; liepi 
 d4p(av v86.t<j3v rbiruiv, 74 n. 2 ; Hepl 
 dpxal7}s iaTpiKrjs, 355 w. 3 
 
 [Hippokrates] wepi Sta^xTjj, 150 n. 
 2, 151, 156, 162, 164, 264 n. 2, 265 
 n. 2, 350 M. I, 355 «. 3 
 
 Hippolytos, Sources § 13 (p. 36) ; on 
 Anaximander, 51, 54 m. 2 ; on Anaxi- 
 menes, 78 ; on Herakleitos, 142 ; 
 on Anaxagoras, 270 sq. 
 
 Hipponof Samos, 35r-352 ; and Thales, 
 48 n. 3, 351 ; and the Pythagoreans, 
 351 n. I 
 
 Hippys of Rhegion, 109 n. 6 
 
 Homer, 4 sqq. ; on the soul, 81. See 
 Xenophanes, Herakleitos 
 
 Homeric allegorists, 49 «. i, 229 n. 3 
 
 Hylozoism, 12 «. 3 
 
 Hyperboreans, 81, 90 n. * 
 
 Hypotenuse, 105 
 
 lamblichos, Life of Pythagoras, 86 sq., 
 97 n. I, 100 M. I ; on numerical 
 symbolism, lor nn. i and 2 
 
 Ibykos, 191 n. 3 
 
 Idaios of Himera, 352 
 
 " Ideas," theory of, 308 sq. 
 
 Immortality, 84, r54, r95, 245, 250 
 
 Incommensurability, 105 
 
 Indian philosophy, 18, 82 n. 2. See 
 Transmigration 
 
 Infinity, Anaximander, 53 sqq. ; Xeno- 
 phanes, 124 sqq. ; Parmenides, 181 ; 
 Melissos, 325 sq. See Divisibility, 
 &Trei.pov 
 
 Injustice. See ddLKia, 
 
 Intermediate. See fiera^jj 
 
 Intervals, musical, 106 sq., 112. See 
 Octave 
 
 lonians, 3 ; pessimism of, 8 ; secu- 
 larism of, 13 5^., 80 ; as engineers, 
 40 M. I ; primitive cosmology of, 
 III 
 
 Ionic dialect, 72, 281, 282 sq., 352 n. 3 
 
 Irenaeus, Sources § 16 (p. 37) 
 
 Irrationals, loi, 105 
 
 Isokrates, (f)iXoao<pia in, 83 ; on 
 Pythagoras, 88, 95 n. 1 ; on 
 Anaxagoras and Damon, 254, 255 
 n. I 
 
 Italiote philosophy, 80 
 
 Justice. See 5iKrj 
 
 Kallimachos, on Thales, 41 «. 2 
 Kebes and Simmias, 277 n. 2, 295, 309 
 Kebes, Uiva^, on Pythagoras and 
 
 Parmenides, 170 
 Klepsydra, 27, 219 n. 2, 220 n. i, 229, 
 
 245, 267 n. I, 332 
 Korybantes, 97 sq. 
 Kratinos, 351 
 Kratylos, 360 sq. 
 
 Kritias the elder, 203 n. 3, 279 n. 2 
 Kritias of the Thirty, 203 n. 3 
 Kroton, 89, 193 
 Kylon, 90 M. I, 91 
 
 Laertios Diogenes. See Diogenes 
 Laertios 
 
 Lampsakos, school of, 256, 359 
 
 Leukippos, 330-349 ; and the lonians, 
 339 sg-> 349 ; and the Eleatics, 182^ 
 331 sq., 333 sqq., 337, 341, 349 ; and 
 Empedokles, 202, 332 ; and Anaxa- 
 goras, 332, 347 ; and the Pytha- 
 goreans, 337, 339, 345 ; and Diogenes 
 of ApoUonia, 348 ; and Demokritos, 
 337 sq., 347 n. 5, 348 
 
 Light, 186, 239. See Sun, Moon 
 
 Lightning and Thimder, Anaximander, 
 68 ; Anaximenes, 76 ; Empedokles, 
 239 
 
 Limit. See Hpas 
 
 Lives, the three, 98, 140 n. 3 
 
 Logic, origin of, i 
 
 Love, in Hesiod, 7 ; in Parmenides, 
 191 ; in Empedokles, 231 sqq. 
 
 Lucretius, on Empedokles, 203 ; on 
 Anaxagoras, 264 «. 3 ; on Demo- 
 kritos, III n, I 
 
 Lydia, 39 sq., 118 
 
 Lysis, 91, 276, 277» 281, 283 
 
 24 
 
370 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Magnet, Thales on the, 48, 50 
 
 Man, Anaximander, 70 sq. ; Hera- 
 kleitos, 151 sq. 
 
 Map, Anaximander's, 51 
 
 Marmor Parium, on Pythian era, 44 
 n. 3 ; on the meteoric stone of 
 Aigospotamos, 252 n. 6 
 
 Materialism, 182 
 
 Matter. See vXrj 
 
 Mean, Harmonic, 106 «. 2 ; Aristotle's 
 doctrine of the, 112 
 
 Measures, 134 n. 4, 135 n. 2, 150 sq., 
 161, 357 
 
 Medicine, Pythagorean, 97, 193 ; 
 Alkmaion, 193 sqq.; Empedokles, 
 200 sq., 231 ; Philolaos, 278 
 
 Melissos, 320 - 329 ; and Parmeni- 
 des, 181, 321, 324 ; and the lonians, 
 321, 326 ; and the Pythagoreans, 
 327 ; and Anaxagoras, 326 n. 2, 
 328, 335 
 
 Melissos, Xenophanes, and Gorgias, 
 126 n. I, 322 nn. i and 2 
 
 Menon, 'larpLKd, 48 n. 3, 201 n. 5, 
 278 n. 4, 283 n. I, 292 n. i, 351 ». i 
 
 Metapontion, 89, 90 n. 2, 91 
 
 Metempsychosis. See Transmigration 
 
 Meteorology, at first confused with 
 astronomy, 27, 49, i95 
 
 Milesian school, 39-79 
 
 Miletos, 39, 49, 52 n. 2, 330, 332 
 
 Milky Way, 191, 271 
 
 Milo of Kroton, 91 
 
 Milton, on " saving appearances," 28 
 n. 2 ; on " harmony of the spheres," 
 307 n. I 
 
 Mixture, Anaximander, 56 ; Empedo- 
 kles, 233 sq. 
 
 Mochos of Sidon, 16 «. 4 
 
 Monism, 9 n._ 2, 180, 1^ 7, 310 
 
 Monotheism, 128 sq. 
 
 Moon, Anaximander, 67 ; Anaximenes, 
 75 sq. ; Xenophanes, 123 ; Empedo- 
 kles, 239 ; Anaxagoras, 271 sq. ; 
 Leukippos, 347 ; liglit of the, 177 
 «. I, 239, 272, 298 ; rotation of the, 
 297 
 
 Motion, eternal, 12, 61 ; premundane, 
 61 ; denied by Parmenides, 179, 181 ; 
 explained by Empedokles, 227 sq. ; 
 and Anaxagoras, 267 ; criticised by 
 Zeno, 318 sqq. ; denied by Melissos, 
 327 ; reaffirmed by Leukippos, 
 340 sq. 
 
 Music, Pythagorean, 97 
 
 Mysteries, 84, 141 
 
 Nabonassar, era of, 22 
 Names, 176, 348 n. i 
 Navigation, Thales, 41, 47; Anaxi- 
 mander, 51 sq. 
 Necessity. See dvdyKr} 
 
 Neoplatonists, Sources § 5 (p. 32) ; 
 on Parmenides, 178 n. 3, 183 
 
 Neopythagoreans, 107 
 
 Nigidius Figulus, 95 
 
 Nikomachos of Gerasa, on Pythagoras, 
 87 «. 2 ; on numerical symbolism, 
 loi n. I, 289 n. I 
 
 Nile, rise of the, 44 sq., 270 n. 6 
 
 Nomnenios, 16 
 
 Nous, in Anaxagoras, 267 sqq. 
 
 Numljers, Pythagorean doctrine of, 
 107 sq., 278, 285 sqq., 307 sqq. ; 
 relation to Atomism, 336 ; triangu- 
 lar, square, and oblong, 102 sq. 
 
 Numerical symbolism, 100 sqq. 
 
 Obliquity of the ecliptic (zodiac), 
 
 Anaximander, 51 ; Anaximenes, 77 ; 
 
 Leukippos, 347 ; Diogenes of Apol- 
 
 lonia, 357 
 Oblong numbers. See Numbers 
 Observation, 26 
 Octave, 106, no, 296, 306 
 Odd and Even, 287 s^. 
 Oinopides of Chios, 26 n. 1, 103 n. i 
 Olympiodoros on the term [xeTsixxpi- 
 
 Xwats, 93 n. 2 
 Onomakritos, 97 
 Opposites (hot-cold, dry-wet), 8 sq., 
 
 53 sq., 57, 112, 143, 165, 185, 196, 
 
 201, 228, 231, 263, 356 
 Oriental influences, 15 sqq. 
 Origin, (piXoa-ocpoijfieva, Sources § 13 
 
 (p. 36) 
 Orphicism, 5 ». 2, 7 n. 3, 81 sqq., 192, 200 
 
 Pain, 273, 326 
 
 Parmenides, 169-193 ; and Xeno- 
 phanes, 170 ; and Anaximander, 
 189 ; and Herakleitos, 130, 179, 
 183 sq. ; and Pythagoreanism and 
 Empedokles, 109, 170, 179, 184 sqq., 
 192, 202, 293, 310 ; at Athens, 169, 
 172 «. I, 311 
 
 Pausanias, 201 n. i 
 
 Pentagram, 295 
 
 Pebbles. See xf/rjtpot 
 
 Perception, sense, Parmenides, 178 ; 
 Alkmaion, 194 ; Empedokles, 246 
 sqq. ; Anaxagoras, 273 sq. ; Leu- 
 kippos, 347 sq. ; Diogenes of 
 ApoUonia, 358 
 
 Perikles, and Zeno, 169, 311 n. i ; 
 and Anaxagoras, 251, 254 sqq. ; 
 and Melissos, 320 
 
 Petron, 60, 109 
 
 Phaidros, Sources § 12 (p. 36) 
 
 Pherekydes of Syros, 3, 7 n. 2, 80, 94 
 n. I, 97 
 
 Philip of Opous, 305 
 
 Philistion, 201 nn. 1 and 4, 231 «. i, 249 
 n. 4 
 
 Philo of Byblos, 16 w. 4 
 
 ■ 
 
INDEX 
 
 371 
 
 Philo Judaeus, 16 ; on Herakleitos, 
 143, 164 
 
 Philodemos, de pietate, Sources § 12 
 (p. 36) ; on " accommodation," 
 32 «. I ; on Anaximander, 60 ; on 
 Parmenides, 192 m. i 
 
 Philolaos, 85, 100, 276, 277 sqq., 292, 
 297 sq. ; Speusippos and, 102 n. 2 
 
 Philosophy. See (pL\oao4)ia 
 
 Phleious, Pythagorean society of, 83 
 «. I, 98 n. 3, 277 
 
 Phoenician influence, 41. See Mochos 
 
 Physiological interest, 48, 232, 262, 
 268, 350 
 
 Physiology, Parmenides, 192 sq. ; 
 Alkmaion, 194 ; Empedokles, 244 
 sqq. ; Diogenes of ApoUonia, 355 
 
 Pindar, on the Hyperboreans, 81 ; 
 Orphic odes, 200 
 
 Piremus, 19, 21 n. 1 
 
 Placita, 26 ; of Aetios, Sources § 10 
 (P- 35) ; Vetusta (Poseidonian), ih. § 
 II (P- 35) J pseudo- Plutarch, ib. § 9 
 (P- 34) 
 
 Planets, names of, 23 «. i ; motion of, 
 21, 70, no, 195, 239 ; Pythagorean 
 system of, 277, 296 sqq. 
 
 Plants, Empedokles, 240 sq. ; Anaxa- 
 goras, 272 sqq. 
 
 Plato, Sources § i (p. 31) ; on Egyptian 
 science, 15M. 3,i9».i; on oriental 
 astronomy, 23 m. 2, 24 ». 2 ; on 
 astrology, 24 ». i ; on Orphicism, 
 84 ; on Kddapais, 98 n. i ; on 
 schools of philosophy, 29 sq. ; on 
 Seven Wise Men, 44 w. 3 ; definition of 
 harmonic mean, xo6 «. 2 ; on 
 stereometry, 283 ; on planetary 
 motions, no n. 2, 195 ; on the 
 earth's motion, 301 sq., 305 ; on 
 gravity, 343 ; on the doctrine of 
 the Mean, 112 n. 2 ; on the Great 
 Year, 157 ; on avTairoSocns, 162 
 M. I ; on " air," 187 n. i ; and Empe- 
 dokles, 248, 249 ; and Philistion, 
 201 n. 4 ; and the Pythagoreans, 
 308 {see Er, myth of) ; on Thales, 
 46 n. 4, 47 M. I ; on Pythagoras, 85, 
 89 «. 4 ; on Xenophanes, 127, 170 ; 
 on Epicharmos, 127 w. 3 ; on 
 Herakleitos, 131 n. 5, 144, 146, 158, 
 159 ; on Herakleiteans, 29 n. i, 
 145 n. I, 150 n. 2, 166 «. 2 ; on 
 Parmenides, 169, 170, 181, 192, 198 
 w. 2, 311 ; on the Eleatics, 29 n. 2, 
 127 ; on Empedokles, 144, 201 n. 2, 
 233, 237 ». 3 ; on Anaxagoras, 252 n. 4, 
 254, 256 n. 3, 257, 267 ; on Anaxa- 
 goreans, 29 ». 3 ; on Philolaos, 276 ; 
 on Pythagoreans, 13, 61, 66 n. i, 
 83, 85, 89 n. 4, 98 nn. 2 and 3, 109, 
 277 M. 2, 279 sqq., 292 sqq., 301 sqq.. 
 
 304 sq. ; on Zeno, 169, 311, 312, 
 313, 314 ; on Melissos, 329 n. 2 ; on 
 Sokrates, 361 
 
 Pleasure and pain, Empedokles, 241, 
 246, 247 ; Anaxagoras, 274 ; Diogenes 
 of Apollonia, 358 
 
 Pliny, on Thales, 43, 44 n. 2 ; on 
 Anaximander, 51 ; on Anaximenes, 
 51 w. 4 ; on Hermodoros, 131 n. i ; 
 on the meteoric stone of Aigospota- 
 mos, 252 
 
 Pluralism, 197, 310 
 
 Plutarch, on Thales, 46 w. i ; on 
 Anaximenes, 75 ; on the Pytha- 
 goreans, 95 n. 2 ; on Herakleitos, 
 160 ; on Parmenides, 171 n. 2, 
 186 n. 2, 311 n. 1 ; on Zeno, 169 sq., 
 31 X n. I ; on Melissos, 320 sq. ; on 
 Anaxagoras, 255 n. 6, 256 n. 5, 257 
 «. 5 ; on Demokritos, 336 «. 5 ; on 
 Plato, 304 sq. ; on the meteoric 
 stone of Aigospotamos, 252 ; on 
 Odd and Even, 289 
 
 [Plutarch] Placita, Sources § 9 (p. 34) 
 
 [Plutarch] Stromateis, Sources § 14 
 (p. 36) ; on Parmenides, 187 n. i ; 
 on Empedokles, 236, 238 
 
 Points, lines, and surfaces, 290, 315 
 sqq. 
 
 Political activity of philosophers : 
 Thales, 46 ; Anaximander, 52 ; 
 Pythagoras, 90 sqq. ; Parmenides, 
 171 ; Empedokles, 198 sqq. ; Zeno, 
 311 
 
 Polybios, on Pythagoreans, 92 n, i 
 
 Polybos, on Melissos, 329 
 
 Polykrates, era of, 38, 88 
 
 Pores. See -wopoL 
 
 Porphyry, Life of Pythagoras, 87, 95 
 
 Poseidonios, and Mochos of Sidon, 16 
 n. 4 ; and astrology, 24 w. i ;' on the 
 tripartite soul, 296 n. 2. See Placita, 
 Vetusta 
 
 Precession. See Equinoxes 
 
 Primary substance, 9-11, 12 n. i 
 
 Proclus, Commentary on Euclid I., 26 
 n. I, 44 n. 4, 45 n. 4, 104 nn. 2 and 
 3, 188 n. I ; on Parmenides and 
 Zeno, 170 M. 3 ; on Philolaos, 281 ; 
 on Pythagoreans, 290 n. i, 309 n. 2 ; 
 on the " theory of ideas," 309 n. 2 
 
 Proportion, 106 
 
 Protagoras, and Herakleitos, 166 ; and 
 Zeno, 312 ; Kara^aXKovTes, 329 n. 2 
 
 Purification. See Kadapfioi, Kadaptris 
 
 Pyramids, height of, 46. See irvpafxLs 
 
 Pjrrrho, 82 n. 2 
 
 Pythagoras, 84-112 ; an Ionian, 3, 81 ; 
 Empedokles on, 200 
 
 Pythagoreans, 276-309 ; in the Aia-crol 
 X6701, 29 M, 3 ; on the premundane 
 motion, 61 ; on air or the void, 109, 
 24 A 
 
372 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 179, 181, 231 ; Plato on, 13, 61, 
 
 66 n. I, 83, 85, 89 «. 4 ; comic poets 
 
 on, 94 n. 3 
 " Pythagorean theorem " (Eucl. i. 47), 
 
 104 sq. 
 Pythian era, 44 
 Pythodoros, 311 n. i 
 
 Rarefaction and condensation, 73 sqg., 
 
 146, 179, 327, 356 
 Religion, Aegean, 3, 4, 80 ; Delian, 81. 
 
 See God, Monotheism, Orphicism, 
 
 Sacrifice 
 Respiration, 153, 201, 229, 245, 279 
 Rest. See Motion 
 
 Retrograde motion of planets, 21, 304 
 Revolution, diurnal, 13, 61, 110 
 Rhegion, 109 n. 4, 191 n. 3, 276 
 Rhetoric, Empedokles and, 200 
 Rhind papyrus, 18 sqq. 
 Rhodes, 3 
 Roots {=aTOLX€ia), Empedokles, 228 
 
 sqq. 
 
 Sacrifice, mystic, 95 ; bloodless, 93, 
 224 n. 4 
 
 Salmoxis, 85, 90 n. 2 
 
 Sanchuniathon, 16 «, 4 
 
 Sardeis, era of, 38, 44 n. 2, 51, 72. See 
 Lydia 
 
 Saros, 42 n. 2 
 
 Satjoros, Sources § 19 (p, 38) ; on 
 Empedokles, 199 n. 5, 201 «. 2 ; on 
 Anaxagoras,255 sq. ; on Philolaos, 280 
 
 Schools of philosophy, 28 sqq., 50 n. 
 4, 79 
 
 Sea, Anaximander, 64 sq. ; Herakleitos, 
 149 ; Empedokles, 240 ; Anaxagoras, 
 270 ; Diogenes of Apollonia, 357 
 
 Seeds, Anaxagoras, 264 sq. 
 
 Seqt, 19, 46 
 
 Seven Wise Men, 41, 44, 50, 113 
 
 Sextus Empiricus, Sources § 4 (p. 32) ; 
 on Herakleitos, 152 ; on Anaxa- 
 goras, 264 n. I 
 
 Shakespeare, on the " harmony of 
 the spheres," 307 n. i 
 
 Sight, Alkmaion, 194, 195 n. i ; 
 Empedokles, 246 sq., 248 ; Anaxa- 
 goras, 273 sq. 
 
 Silloi, 116 
 
 Simnias. See Kebes 
 
 Simplicius, Sources § 5 (p. 32) ; on 
 Thales, 48 ; on Anaximander, 54 
 n. 2 ; on innumerable worlds, 
 59; on Xenophanes, 115 sq., 116 n. 
 I, 126 ; on Parmenides, 171, 174 n. 
 I, 178 n. 3, 183, 186, 189 sq., 190 
 n. 4 ; on Empedokles, 243 n. i ; 
 on Anaxagoras, 257, 263 ; on 
 Pythagoreans, 288, 300 n. i ; on 
 Zeno, 313 ; on Melissos, 321, 327 
 
 ». I ; on Diogenes of Apollonia, 353, 
 357 
 
 Sleep, Herakleitos, 137 n. 6, 138 «. 3, 
 152 sq. ; Empedokles, 245 
 
 Smell, Alkmaion, 195 n. i ; Empe- 
 dokles, 247, 248 ; Anaxagoras, 273 
 sq. 
 
 Sokrates, on the soul, 84 ; meeting 
 with Parmenides and Zeno, 169, 
 256 n. 3, 311 ; and the Pythagoreans, 
 
 277, 278 w. 2 ; and Anaxagoras, 256, 
 267 ; and Archelaos, 358 sq.; and 
 Damon, 296 n. 2 ; " theory of 
 ideas," 308 sq. 
 
 Solids, regular, 283 sqq., 284 n. i, 
 
 293 sqq. 
 Solon and Croesus, 24 sq. 
 Solstices, 21, 42 n. i, 51. See Tpoiral 
 Sosikrates, writer of Successions, 
 
 Sources § 17 (p. 37) 
 Sotion, Sources § 17 (p. 37) ; on 
 
 Parmenides, 170 ; on Anaxagoras, 
 
 255 n. 6 
 Soul, of the world ; Thales, 49 ; 
 
 Anaximenes, 75 ; of man, Orphic, 
 
 81 s^. ; Anaximenes, 75 ; Alkmaion, 
 
 195 ; a " harmony," 295 sqq. ; 
 
 tripartite, 296 n. 2 ; Sokrates on 
 
 the, 84 
 Space, 317 
 Speusippos, on Parmenides, 171 ; on 
 
 Pythagorean numbers, 102 n. 3, 
 
 278, 290 n. I 
 
 Sphere, planetary spheres, 62 «. i ; 
 Parmenides, 181, 227, 231 ; Empe- 
 dokles, 227. See Earth, Eudoxos, 
 Harmony 
 
 Square numbers. See Nmnber 
 
 Stars, fixed, 77 n. 4, 239, 271, 347 
 
 Stobaios, Sources § 9 (p. 34) 
 
 Stoics, Sources § 3 (p. 32) ; and 
 astrology, 24 m. i ; as interpreters of 
 Herakleitos, 131 n. 5, 132, 133 n. i ; 
 142, 148, 160 sq. ; on the Great 
 Year, 157 
 
 Strabo, on Mochos, 16 w. 4 ; on 
 Pythagoreans, 90 w. i ; on Her- 
 modoros, 131 m. i ; on Parmenides 
 and Zeno, 170, 171 n. 2, 311 ; on 
 Anaxagoras, 253 n. 1 
 
 Strife. See Opposites, ^pis, veiKos 
 
 Sublunary region, 27 «. i 
 
 Successions, Sources § 17 (p. 37) 
 
 ^ulva-sUtras, 20 
 
 Sim, Thales, 49 ; Anaximander, 67 
 sq. ; Anaximenes, 76 sq. ; Xeno- 
 phanes, 122 ; Herakleitos, 148, 155 ; 
 Alkmaion, 195 ; Empedokles, 238 
 sq., 298 n. I ; Anaxagoras, 271 ; 
 Pythagoreans, 298 n. i ; Leukippos, 
 347 
 
 Sybaris, 89 n. 3, 91 
 
 ■ 
 
INDEX 
 
 373 
 
 Taras, 90 n. i, 276 
 
 Taste, Alkmaion, 195 «. i ; Empe- 
 dokles, 247 ; Anaxagoras, 273 sq. 
 
 Temperaments, 112 
 
 Temperature, 112 
 
 Tetraktys, 102 
 
 Thales, 39-50, 104 ; era of, 38 
 
 Theaitetos, 105, 284 
 
 Theano, 308 
 
 Thebes, <pi\6ao(poi at, 91, 278 n. i ; 
 Lysis at, 91, 276 sq. ; Philolaos at, 
 276 
 
 Theodoret, Sources § 10 (p. 35), § 16 
 (p. 37) 
 
 Theodoros of Kyrene, 105 
 
 Theogony, Kesiod, 6 sqq. ; Rhapsodic, 
 7 w. 3 
 
 Theologians, 7 5^. 
 
 Theologumena arithmetica, 102 n. 2, 
 107 n. I, 290 n. I 
 
 Theology. See God 
 
 Theon of Smyrna, on oriental astro- 
 nomy, 24 n. 2 ; on planetary 
 motions, 304 n. 1 
 
 Theophrastos, Sources § 7 (p. 33) ; on 
 abstinence, 95 m. 2 ; on astrology, 24 
 n. I ; on innmnerable worlds, 58 sqq.; 
 on schools of philosophy, 28 sq., 50 
 ». 4 ; on Prometheus, 40 n. 2 ; on 
 Thales, 40 m, 2 ; on Anaximander, 
 50 n. 4, 52 sqq., 54. n. 2 ; on Anaxi- 
 menes, 72 sqq. ; on Xenophanes, 
 114, 122, 123, 124; on Herakleitos, 
 132, 142, 146 ; on Parmenides, 178 
 n. I, 182 sq., 186, 190, 191 sq. ; 
 on Alkmaion, 194 ; on Empedokles, 
 198 n. 2, 202, 232, 235 n. I, 238 n. 4, 
 241, 246 sqq., 249 ; on Anaxagoras, 
 252, 253, 271, 273 sq. ; on " Philo- 
 laos," 298 M. I ; on Hiketas and 
 Ekphantos, 300 ; on Leukippos, 330, 
 332 n. 2, 333, 338 sqq. ; on Diogenes 
 of Apollonia, 352, 358 ; on Hippon 
 of Samos, 351 ; on Demokritos, 342 ; 
 on Plato, 304 sq. 
 
 Theoretic Hfe, 25 n. i, 98, 252 
 
 Thought, Parmenides, 178 ; Empe- 
 dokles, 247 
 
 Thourioi, era of, 38, 91, 198, 203 n. 2 
 
 Thracian influences, 81 
 
 Thymaridas, 10 1 n. 2 
 
 Timaeus Locrus, the, 280 
 
 Timaios the Lokrian, 85, 195, 279 
 
 Timaios of Tauromenion, on Pytha- 
 goras, 86, 89, 93 ; on Xenophanes, 
 1 1 3 ; on Parmenides and Zeno, 1 70 n. 3, 
 
 171 n. 2, 311 ; on Empedokles, 198, 
 199 n. 2, 200, 203 «. 2 ; on Pytha- 
 goreans, 276 n. I 
 
 Timon of Phleious, on Xenophanes, 
 115 n. 4, 116, 125 n. I ; on Hera- 
 kleitos, 132 w. 2 ; on Plato, 280 
 
 Touch, Alkmaion, 195 n. i ; Empe- 
 dokles, 247 ; Anaxagoras, 273 sq. 
 
 Transmigration, 82 n. 2, 85, 88, 93, 
 250 
 
 Triangle, Pythagorean (3, 4, 5), 20, 104 
 
 Triangular numbers. See Numbers 
 
 Unit, Pythagorean, 108, 316 sqq. 
 
 Void, Pythagorean, 109, 179, 186, 289 ; 
 
 Parmenides on the, 179, 186, 317 ; 
 
 Alkmaion, 194 ; Anaxagoras, 270 ; 
 
 Melissos, 326 ; Leukippos, 332, 337 
 Vortex. See 5Lvt] 
 
 Water, Thales, 47 
 
 Weight, 342 sq. 
 
 Wheel of birth, 97, 98 
 
 Wheels, Anaximander, 62 n. i,''68, no, 
 189; Pythagoras, no, 189; Par- 
 menides, 189 
 
 World. See ovpavds, Kdafios 
 
 Worlds, innumerable : Anaximander, 
 58 sqq., 69 ; Anaximenes, 78 ; 
 Pythagoras, 109 ; Xenophanes, 124 ; 
 Anaxagoras, 269 sq. ; Diogenes of 
 Apollonia, 357 ; Archelaos, 360 
 
 Xenophanes, 112-129; and Anaxi- 
 mander, 114; on Homer and 
 Hesiod, 115, 124, 125 ; on fossils, 26 ; 
 on Thales, 42, 112 ; on Pythagoras, 
 84, 108, 112, 114, 118 n. 2 ; and 
 Parmenides, 170 
 
 Xenophilos, 277 
 
 Xenophon on Sokrates and the Pytha- 
 goreans, 277 n. 2 
 
 Xouthos, 289 
 
 Year. See Great Year 
 
 Zamolxis. See Salmoxis 
 
 Zankle, 114 «. 5 
 
 Zeno, 310-320 ; at Athens, 169, 311 
 
 «. I, 312 w. 4 ; on Pythagoreans, 314 
 
 sqq. ; and Empedokles, 202, 312 
 
 ». I, 314 n. 4 
 Zero, 100 n. 3 
 Zodiac, Babylonian, 21 n. 2. See 
 
 Obliquity 
 
374 
 
 EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY 
 
 II. GREEK 
 
 dSiKla, 9, 54 n. i, 57, 65, 144, 165, 196 
 
 drip. See Air 
 
 dddvaTos Kot dyqpws, g n. i, zo n. 3, 
 
 52 
 aW-qp, 219 n. 3, 228 n. 2, 229, 269 n. i 
 dKfXT}, Sources § 21 (p. 38). See Apollo- 
 
 doros 
 dKo^a/nara, 96 
 dKova/naTLKol, 94 n. 2 
 dWdrpiou 0cDs, 177 «. i 
 'AvdyKT), 187, 190, 191, 222 «. I, 233, 
 
 250 
 dvadvfxiaaLS, 148 J^^. , 150 j^^., 151 «. 2, 
 
 155 j^^., 163 
 dvT^peiaLS, 346 
 dvTv^, 188 n. 5 
 direipov, TO, Anaximander, 54 «. 2, 57 
 
 j^$'. , 58 «. I ; Pythagorean, 109 
 dTTj'ous, 7), 200 /z. 5 
 dirdKpKTLS, 61 
 
 diroppoai, 202, 246, 248, 249 «. i, 348 
 diroTOix-q, 339 «. i 
 dpLdfiTjTiKr), dist. XoyiariK'Tj, 19 
 dpLcTTOKpaTia, 90 tz. I 
 dpixovla, no, 112, 143, 144, 163 
 dpiredovdiTTai, 20 
 d/)X'?7, Aristotelian term for the material 
 
 cause, II, 47 ;?. 6, 54 
 ai)Tb 5 ^(TTLv, 308 «. 3 
 auT6 /ca^' aL'r6, 308 n. 3 
 
 7aXeo/, 70 «. 2, 71 «. 2 
 
 yp(j!)/j.o)v, 21 «. I, 26 ;?. I, 103 «. I. 5e^ 
 
 Gnomon 
 y6rp-€s, 97 
 yvpds, 65 «. I 
 
 daifxoiVf dalfioves, 250 
 
 dLadoxat, Sources § 16 (p. 37) 
 
 SiaarijixaTa, 60 w. 3 
 
 a^K?;, 9, 54 n. I, 145, 165 
 
 Uvq, 13 «. 3, 61 sq., 66 «. 2, 69, no, 
 
 III, 237 n. 3, 240, 269, 344 sq., 
 
 346 sq. 
 diopL^u), 108 «. 4 
 5L(j}pi<Tix4vov, io8 ;z. 4 
 diodcKdaKVTOi cr^alpai, 294 «. 4 
 
 etSoj, of geometrical figures, 103 n. 2 ; 
 
 of atoms, 336 «. 5 
 eldQp (piXoL, 309 n. 2 
 efSwXa, 348 
 elj/at, t6 ^i**, 178 n. 4 ; ecjf, " true," 133 
 
 n. I 
 (KTr^pcoats, 143, 157, 158 J^^. 
 ^Ko-Taaii, 81 
 ^WeirpLS, 104 «. 3 
 ^j*, t6, 126 ; Pythagorean, 108, 316 sqq. 
 
 ivavrla,, havrLbr-qres. See Opposites 
 
 evl^w^ 126 «. 2 
 
 ^TrdXX 77X05, 187 n. 3 
 
 €TravaKVK\f]ffeL^, 304 ;«. i 
 
 iwLipava-LS, 346 
 
 ^pis, 143, 163 
 
 "E(77re/)os and 'Ea>o-06/3os, regarded as 
 different, 23 n. i, 69 ; identified by 
 Pythagoras or Parmenides, 23 «. i, 
 191 n. 3 
 
 earia, 190 
 
 icTw, 285 n. 3 
 
 eTepofx-qKeLS dpidfiol, 103 «. 2 
 
 €vyv(aixo(x{iVT}, Sources § 5 (p. 32) 
 
 ^Xe/ixv^ta, 95 «. I 
 
 iX^ppVf^Oixtrvr], 95 «. I 
 
 Beds. See God 
 deuprjTLKos ^ios, 25 «. i, 98 
 dewpla, 25, 98 
 dvfids, 140 «. 2 
 
 Z5^a ( = o-roixeiOJ'), 201 «. 5, 228 n. i ; 
 
 of atoms, 336 n. 5 
 Z5os, 209 n. I, 215 «. I, 216 n. i 
 t'XXoyU.at, 302 j^. 
 iaovo/iiia, 195, 196 ^z. 2 
 laoppoirla, 66 n. i, 344 J^, 
 IcTTopia, 10 «. 2, 25, 85, 97 ;^. I 
 
 Kadapfioi, Kddapats, 82, 97 n. 4, 98 «. i, 
 
 249 sq. 
 KaKorexvirj, 134 n. 2 
 Kara^dWo}, 329 ;^. 2 
 Keyxpi'Tr]^ X670S, 312 ;?. 4 
 Kevefi^aTeTv, 123 «. 2 
 KXeij/vdpa. See Klepsydra 
 KXrjpovxos 6e6s, 187, 190 «. 3 
 Kdafios, 9, 10 «. 3, 134 «. 3, 162 n. 2, 
 
 190 «. I 
 Kpdais, 112, 296 
 KpareXv, in, 268 w. i, 307 
 
 XoyiaTLKT), dist. dpidfirjriK'fi, 19 
 
 X670J, 133 «. I, 13s «. 2, 138 n. I 
 
 139 «. 3, 143, 173 n. 2, 240 
 X670J Tov eTvai, ttjs ovaias, 308 n. 3 
 
 /xadrj/xaTiKoi, 94 «. 2 
 
 lie<x6T7js, fieadrrjTes, 106, 112 « 
 
 fiera^ij, t6, Anaximander, 55 «. 4, 56 /?;?. 
 
 I and 2, 65 
 fX€T€ix\pTjx^(^'-^i 93 "• 2. "S"^^ Trans 
 
 migration 
 IJi€Tevcro}fidr(i}(ns, 93 «. 2 
 fieri (1} pa, rd, 27 
 fiereiapoXoyia, 27 «. i 
 ^^pa. -S^^ Measures 
 
 1 
 
INDEX 
 
 375 
 
 jxovas diffiv ^xoi'^'Oi 290 
 
 fiop^ ( = <rToi.xe?ov), 185, 228 n. i 
 
 veiKOSf Empedokles, 231 sgg'. 
 pdfMos, opp. (pOa-is, 347 
 
 6yK0i, 291 n. 3, 319 n. 4, 336 n. 1 
 oXKds, 294 n. I 
 oixQioixepri, 264 J^. 
 S/J-OLOS, 6/j.ol6t7]s, 66 «. I 
 3/57ai'a, 265 
 fipYia, 82, 97 
 5/)os, terjtiinus, 104 
 
 oypavos, ?.y. KdafjLos, 27, 56 w. i, 60 ;z. 2, 
 127 n. 4 
 
 7rd7os, 236 «. 2 
 
 7ra\i77ej'e(r/a, 93 «. 2. See Trans- 
 migration 
 
 TraXiuTOVos apfiovla, 136 n. 4, 174 ;«. 3 
 
 TraXiPTpoiros K^Xevdos, 174 n. 3, 179 
 
 Trava-rrep/Jt-ta, 265 «. 2, 337 
 
 trapa^oX-fj, 104 «. 3 
 
 TrapaTrriyfiara, 47 
 
 irdpodoL, 302 
 
 TT^pas, Pythagorean, 109, 2S7 sg. 
 
 irepLayoyy-f], 59 «. i 
 
 Trepi^X^) TfepUxof, 56 «. i, 58 «. i, 60, 
 152 «. 3 
 
 irepiffTaffLSy 59 /z. I 
 
 TrlXrja-cs, 73 «. 3 
 
 irvevfxa, Aireipov, 108 
 
 TTOLdrris, 263 «. i 
 
 irbpOL, 153, 194, 201, 202, 233 j^. , 246 
 j^., 248, 332 
 
 TT pTJCTT-qp, 68 «. 2, 148, 149 «. I 
 
 irpbfiXrjij.a (7rpo/3d\Xcu), 28 «. 2 
 TTporaaLi {vpoTelvu}), 28 n. 2 
 Trpoxwp'J^o'ets, 304 n. i 
 ni'^a7opio-Tai, dist. nu^a76petoi, 94 n. 2 
 TTvpafiis, etymology, 21 n. i 
 
 pai/'wSuj, 115 «. I 
 poTT??, 345 
 
 (TTJfia (Twfia, 98, 278 
 
 cro<f>ia, 117 «. 2 
 
 ao<piaTr}s, 85, 353 «. 4 
 
 (Trao-icDTat, 127 «. i 
 
 <TTi<pavaif 187 J^^. , 191 «. 2 
 
 (rrotx«oj', 12 «. 2, 52 ;z. 5, 201 n. 5, 
 
 228, 230 «. 3, 265, 336 n. 4 
 avvcx^s, 108 ;?. 4 
 crui'Oticeiu), accommodo , Sources § 3 (p. 
 
 32 n. i), 142 n. 5 
 a<p6v8vXoi, 188 «. 3 
 cXT^A^ara, 100 
 
 T€TpaKTTUS, 102 J^. 
 
 To^ei^s, sector, 21 n. i 
 
 Tpoirai, solstices, 62 «. 2, 63 «, 2, 
 
 64 n. I, 67 «. 2, 76 ft. 3, 15s j^. , 
 
 271, 302, 304 
 rpoTTis, 294 n. 2 
 rpbxoSf 62 «, 2, 77 n. 2 
 
 {jXt), 47 «. 6, 55, 294 «. 3 
 ■uirep^oXifi, 104 «, 3 
 virddecris, 28 «. 2, 313 «. 6 
 i/Tro^u)fj,aTa, 294 «. 3 
 VTr6X€i\f/i$, III «. I, 302 «. I 
 {firordvovaa, 105 
 
 <paip6/x€Pa, ffip^eiv rd, 28 «. 2 
 (piXoaocpia, 25, 83, 278 «. i 
 (f>iX6<TO(pos, 277, 278 «. I, 312 «, 2 
 (ppovris, 114 «. I 
 (f>(i(rLs, 9-1 1, 54, 205 ;?. 4, 228, 336 «. 3, 
 
 337 ; Ilepi (pOcreus, 115 n. 5 ; opp. 
 
 "6^05, 347 
 
 X^os, 7 n. I 
 Xi-T(Jov, 224 ;?. I 
 XpVf^O'Ta, 249 «. I, 263 «. I 
 X^PO; 104 ^- 2, 108 n. 4 
 Xidplov, 104. n. 2 
 
 \pri(pOL, 100, 102 
 \l/vxtKbv TTvevfia, 249 «. 4 
 
 THE END 
 
 Printed in Great Britain fry R. & R. Clark, Limited, Edinburgh. 
 
^^ii^ 
 
 14 DAY USE 
 
 TO DESK FROM WHICH BOR^ 
 
 SEP 
 
 HOLUONBUON 
 
YC 3192 
 
 1927 
 
 RETURN TO the circulation desk of any 
 University of California Library 
 
 or to the 
 
 NORTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 
 
 University of California 
 
 Richmond Field Station, BIdg. 400 
 
 1301 South 46th Street 
 
 Richmond, CA 94804-4698 
 
 ALL BOOKS MAY BE RECALLED AFTER 7 DAYS 
 
 To renew or recharge your library materials, you may 
 
 contact NRLF 4 days prior to due date at (510) 642-6233 
 
 DUE AS STAMPED BELOW 
 
 MAY 09 2008 
 
 DD20 12M 7-06