W^i '^■K C'VAS /ffk-. v^ '<' *.' V/fe' IT. mm $^ ci^ /^Zcc^j J'T^Cr -so T UN IVERSITY Received Accessions REESE LIBRARY OP THE OF CALIFORN lA. ■8f/ ^.^}/:J./ Shelf No. ^ *v> Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/beliefofjewishpeOOmlllrich THE BELIEF OF THE JEWISH PEOPLE AND OF THE MOST EMINENT GENTILE PHILOSOPHERS, MORE ESPECIALLY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE, IN A FUTURE STATE, BRIEFLY CONSIDERED. THE BELIEF OF THE JEWISH PEOPLE AND OF THE MOST EMINENT GENTILE PHILOSOPHERS, MORE ESPECIALLY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE, IN A FUTURE STATE, BRIEFLY CONSIDERED ; INCLUDING AN EXAMINATION INTO SOME OP THE LEADING PRINCIPLES CONTAINED IN BISHOP WARBURTON's DIVINE LEGATION OF MOSES ; IN A DISCOURSE PREACHED BEFORE THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD AT ST. MARY'S, March 30, 1828. WITH NOTES AND AN APPENDIX. BY W. MILLS, B. D. FELLOW OP MAGDALEN COLLEGE. rvftvei(ftev rtis 4"'X^i '^ AN0PXiniNH SOOIA riXos Se 'H 0EIA. Origenes. OXFORD: AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS FOR THE AUTHOR, AND SOLD BY J. PARKER ; AND BY C AND J. RIVINGTON, LONDON. MDCCCXXVIII. X^^ OF THE ^ UNIVERSITY 4^ 4^ J'^ y TO JOHN THOMAS HOPE, ESQ. THE FOLLOWING DISCOURSE IS INSCRIBED WITH THE SINCEREST FRIENDSHIP AND REGARD. I'V # PREFACE. XHE following Discourse, delivered up- wards of six months since, was not origi- nally intended for publication. It is com- mitted to the press with the sanction of a learned friend, whose opinion the author considers of great value. It was thought that a brief statement of an important question might not be without advantage to others engaged in the same inquiries. The controversies that arose when the Divine Legation of Warbu7'ton was first published have long since died away, nor is it necessary to awaken them again, ex- cept as far as the chief subject of dispute is connected with the acquisition of reli- gious truth itself An examination into the belief of Jew or Gentile in the soul's immortality before the coming of our Sa- viour, can never cease to be an interesting question to the Christian philosopher. Nor viii PREFACE. will the investigation be without profit to him who pursues it candidly, as a source of moral improvement. He may learn to be thankful on the ground of revelation for the advantages which he enjoys over the most favoured Israelite in the superior blessings and prospects of the new, com- pared with the old dispensation ; and on the ground of his natural faculties, he will be sensible of the benefits which reason itself has derived from the word of Scrip- ture, as well in directing as in limiting its exercise. He has seen the day clearly which the inspired patriarchs of old, with the prophetic eye of faith, at a distance, rejoiced to see; and he has received that light of imparted knowledge from Heaven, which the wisest of the heathens felt neces- sary to clear up the doubts of the specu- lative mind, and would have hailed with gratitude and reverence. IJKIVBBSITY 2 TIMOTHY 1. 10. — who hath abolished death, and brought life and immortality to light through the gospel, xHESE words form part of an Epistle written by the great apostle of the Gentiles, at a time when he stood in need of all the consolations to be derived from the doc- trine which they convey ; when he was suffering from imprisonment and persecu- tion, and he perceived that the hour of his martyrdom was approaching. Rejoicing in the hopes which they inspired, he declared that he was afflicted, and yet was not ashamed ; and looking forward to his re- ward, he exclaims in a subsequent part of the Epistle, / have fought a good fight, I have finished my course, I have kept the faith : henceforth there is laid up for me a crown of righteousness, which the Lord, the inghteous judge, shall give me. Language so full of confidence in his reward and in the grounds of it, so full of trust in the righteous Judge who was to confer it, as plainly to prove that the power of death B 9 was indeed abolished, and that life and im- mortality were brought to light. Yet these expressions of my text, ^coTia-ctv- Tff ^i*)y}v Ku) (A(j)6ccp(rioLv, however strong they may appear, are not to be considered as implying that the expectation of a future life had never been heard of till the coming of the Messiah. In its literal acceptation the word (pmZei signifies rather to make clear what is obscure, than to bring to light what is entirely unknown : thus ^oorZetv A^t]6siciv, to make the truth manifest, and not to shew forth a truth of which no glim- mering had previously been perceived. The heathen looked forward to a future state, though he had no certain evidence for his belief, neither comprehending clearly the immortality of the soul, nor having any notion of the resurrection of the body*. And the Jew was instructed by revelation, that the life forfeited by the transgression of Adam w^as to be restored through the mediation of some future deliverer, though all the circumstances connected with the a The word a^Qup(rlav, incorruption^ probably conveys this meaning. Macknight and Benson. 8 mystery of redemption were not to be fully revealed, till our Saviour's appearance and ministry upon earth dispelled every doubt and difficulty in which the doctrine was in- volved, enlightening what was before ob- scure, and completing what was before imperfect. It will be my object in the present dis- course, to compare the knowledge both of the Gentiles and the Jewish people, re- specting a future life, with the clearer reve- lations which Christians enjoy on this mo- mentous subject. That the idea of another state of exist- ence after the termination of the present universally prevailed among mankind, the records of history unequivocally prove : there is no nation, whether savage or civil- ized, amongst whom some traces of it may not be found. It made a part of the po- pular belief in the early stages of society, before mythology was formed into a sys- tem ; it was strongly impressed upon the mind before political codes gave a particu- lar direction to it by ceremonies and modes of worship, and before philosophy exhibited B 2 alike the power and the weakness of hu- man reason, by the subtlety of its specu- lations on a subject of such overpowering interest. This conviction cannot be ascribed to the policy of the legislator, which was itself the foundation on which his religious enactments were erected, nor yet to the wisdom of the philosopher, which prevailed for ages before philosophy took its rise among mankind. It was probably a rem- nant of that early revelation given to our first parents, and which, amid all the changes and distractions of civil society, and all the emigrations of tribes and na- tions, had never been utterly obscured^. But in process of time, when civilization had advanced, men's ideas respecting both the nature of the Deity and the doctrine of a future state had been corrupted; gods were multiplied without number "^j the li- b The notion of a future existence must be either a deduction of reason, or be derived from revelation, or an impression of instinctive consciousness. c The treatise, Tlepj xoV/xou, ascribed to Aristotle, speaks of the Deity as one, and derives the different names of God from the different parts of nature which he regu- lates. Aristot. lUp\ }i6a-(XQv, cap. 7. centious passions of the most licentious men'were ascribed to them, and the belief of a future existence was intermingled with the wildest creations of the fancy. All these notions were at length combined into order by the poet, and sanctioned by the legislator"^; vices of the most atrocious kind were countenanced by the example of the divinities, and the authority of the laws, and the obligations of mistaken piety and public duty, lent in some cases additional stimulus to the depraved appetites of our nature ^ Yet notwithstanding this perni- Hesiod and Homer reduced to system the mythology of the Grecian gods. Vid. Herod, lib. ii. c. 53. Brucker, Hist. Crit. Phil, pars ii. lib. i. cap. 1. sect. 26. 31. pp. 407. 423. In process of time, not only all the operations of exter- nal nature were explored for deities, but the most trifling acts of man himself were each under the superintendance of a particular god. Vide a singular chapter, Augustin. Civ. Dei, lib. iv. c. 11. d It is because the weakness and licentiousness of Jove and the other deities, as described by Homer, furnished a bad example to mankind, that Plato wished to banish poets from his republic. Plato de Repub. lib. iii. Bekker, pars iii. vol. i. p. 107 — 117. ^ The worship of Mylitta, the Babylonian* goddess, is frequently cited as a preeminent instance of pagan im- B 3 6 cious influence, derived from the corrup- tions of the doctrine, society must have been on the whole improved by it; for un- less the belief had acted powerfully as a check upon the unruly desires, we cannot conceive why legislators should have taken so much pains to preserve it^. When philosophy, at a comparatively late period, arose, it made no claim to the invention of the notion, or to have derived it from the deductions of natural reason. Not only Plato makes continual and direct allusions purity ; yet the ordinary homage paid to the divinities in Greece and Rome at the sacred festivals, was far more pernicious in its effect upon public morals than the singu- lar institution above alluded to. Vid. Augustin. Civ. Dei, lib. ii. cap. 4, 5. Herodot. lib. i. cap. 200. ^ Thales, the founder of the Ionic school, flourished about six hundred years before Christ, and no regular course of reasoning was brought forward for the soul's immortality, till the time of Plato, two centuries after : Thales taught that water was the first principle, which Aristotle seems to consider as the most ancient philoso- phical notion, Metaph. lib. i. c. 3. and that God, or Mind, made all things out of water. As he was a native of Phoenicia, Cud worth supposes that he received his two principles from thence, " water, and the Divine Spirit " moving on the face of it."" Cudworth, Intellect, Syst, book i. cap. i. sect. 22. to tradition as the origin of his knowledge^, but earlier writers were avowedly indebted to the same source; all that philosophy did pretend to was, to demonstrate that belief by arguments which was before grounded, we know not how, in the com- mon fears and hopes of mankind. And let those who form an exalted estimate of the intellectual powers, in deciding upon such mysterious subjects, judge with what suc- cess the attempt was made, by the jarring and contradictory opinions of the different schools of antiquity. Let those who imagine that the immortality of the soul (I speak not of the resurrection of the body) is dis- coverable by human sagacity ^ examine the strong reasons of that unrivalled genius, who has the merit of having taught suc- ceeding disputers to set their arguments in order on the subject. Almost all the dis- quisitions of Plato are grounded upon the hypothesis of the soul's preexistence K Be- s Vide Appendix, note A. h Phaedo passim. i The two principal arguments in the Phaedo, the one derived from the notions of the ancients respecting yevsa-tg, B 4 8 sides confusing himself and his readers with the mazes of verbal sophistry, in which, notwithstanding all its excellencies, Greek philosophy so much abounds, he derives his fancied demonstrations from abstruse theo- ries on the properties of generation and cor- ruption, and the essential and eternal ar- chetypes of things ; and even the most plausible and specious are so obscured by r the other from his own philosophical belief concerning the archetypes of things, rest entirely upon such a supposi- tion. As the term generation was relative, and implied its contrary corruption^ he infers that the act of being born involves the destruction of a previous existence, from which this present coming to life is a transition. '0^q\o- ysiTui apex, r){uv tea) tuvty} Tovg ^oovras sk rcav tsQvscotwv ysyo- vivai. Phaedo, Bekker, p. 30 — 34. 2dly. His theory of eternal essences, or ideas, suggests the argument that the notions which the soul has of perfect equality, perfect good, &c. which are never found in sensible objects, prove that it must have existed in a previous state, its present knowledge being nothing more than remlmscence. The discussion derives an incidental value, from shewing that Plato had a considerable acquaintance with the law of as- sociation. Plato, Bekker, pars ii. vol. iii. pp. 35 — 44. Not one of the ancient philosophers before Christianity held the soul's immortality, without holding the preexist- ence of souls. They believed also the immortahty and preexistence of brutes. Cudworth, Intellect. Syst. book i. cap. 1. sect. 31, 32. 9 the subtlety of his language \ as to be ab- solutely unintelligible, except to a mind long versed in the refinements of metaphysics. Such theories as those in the Phaedo could never have convinced any one of the soul's immortality, unless he had been previously prepared to believe it ; nor coming, as they are supposed to have done, from the lips of Socrates in his dying hour, could they have k As a specimen of unmeaning subtlety, it may be suj^ ficient to point out that exquisite verbal trifling towards the end of the -treatise, respecting the archetype of even and odd, and its application to tne question of the soul's immortality, a-xoitsi l\ irsg) rr^^ Tf^nxdoc, p. 99. The reader is absolutely bewildered for some time, till at length he is conducted to the conclusion — that as the essence of even does not partake of the contrary essence odd, so the soul which brings life cannot partake of the contrary essence death, and must consequently be immortal. If we had not known the treatise to be a serious inquiry upon a se- rious occasion, we might have been tempted to think, from the winding up of the dialogue, that the writer intended to ridicule such absurdities ; T/ ouv ; to ja^ h^of^^vov ty}v tou 'apTiQV iSeav t/ vvv drj oovo(/,ott^O[ji,sv ; 'Avapriov, e(pr). To 8g S/- xotiov fjL^ Se^OjOtevov xa» av [LOUdDtov fjt,vj U^rjTcn ; "Afx.ovaoVy g(p>), TO §£ aSjxov. Elev* o 8' av Qolvchtov (/,r) Ssp^ijra/, t/ xaXoO- ■ju^sv; 'AQuvuTOv, eipri. Oukoov y} ^v^yj ov he^sToti SotvctTOv ; Ou. 'Afiavarov apot ^ ^tJX^' *AdavaTOv. Klsv, e(p>)* touto [xh dt] AnOAEAEIX0AI TO 'KapUTtoLV ov(roi, 0gof uWiMTUTOg, 6 TrgooTog Qsog, 6 f/iiyio-Tog Qsog. The soul of the world, and other second causes, are, OsoO ysw^f^uTu xai spyu, Avifji,ioupyov wryipsroit, Seoi dscwv, who derive all their power from the first Creator. Vid. Timasus, and his other philosophical works, pas- sim. Plotinus, Numenius, and the Platonists of the Alex- andrian school, give a very different account : with them the supreme Deity is the father of the A>;jxioupyoj, the se- cond Deity, and the Anima Mundi is the third. Eusebius, Praep. Evang. lib. xi. c. 17, 18. edit. Vigeri, Paris, 1628. In the wild and blasphemous speculations of Cerintlius and other early heretics, the supreme Deity is also dis- tinguished from the A>jju,ioy^yo^, or Creator. Irena?us adv. Haereses, hb. i. cap. 1. 13. 16. 19. 25. 33. lib. v. cap. 4. ^ Vid. Appendix, note E. 15 every declaration of belief as insincere, which is at variance with the inference de- ducible from such a theory? Are all those expressions, in which the feelings of the man triumph over the abstractions of the philosopher, to be set aside in favour of a principle which none of those who held it either comprehended or consistently ex- plained ? The best evidences of a man's real conviction are not his speculative views, but those natural sentiments to which he gives utterance more in unison with the or- dinary tendencies of the human mind. On the lofty heights of metaphysical specula- tion ", clouds and darkness hover, which it ^ The speculatist may declare, if he will, that the law of causation cannot be proved^ and that the free-agency of man is disproved ; yet from the very next moment to the last hour of his life, the natural course of his thoughts, words, and actions, will be in direct contradiction to his theories. If he argue that the immortality of the soul cannot be demonstrated on the principles of pure reason, the desire of the heart, the " longing after immortality," will still remain ; and this (omitting revelation) is of itself the best evidence of its truth, AI yap /SeATio-rat ^rjx^i MANTETONTAI rawra ootcoj iX^iv. Plato, 2 Epist. ad Dionys. Bekker, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 400. Warburton 16 is not permitted to the limited powers of the most exalted intellect to disperse. ""The difficulties multiply in proportion as we ascend, and if we imagine that we have ar- rived at certainty, and venture to give defi- nite form and shape to our abstractions, we shall soon learn the mortifying lesson, how little our system will influence the prac- tical belief of others, or even our own, when opposed to the more common motives and instinctive impressions of our nature. Those who have reflected most on such subjects will perhaps assent to the opinion, that if we would discover truth, we must pursue it in some lower region, in which the light of our moral feelings and faculties may be allowed to cheer and direct our path. These reflections, while they teach humi- lity to ourselves, may assist us to form a Warburton speaks with contempt of such inferences, as proper only to poetical metaphysicians and metaphysi- cal poets; yet Aristotle, at least as sober a reasoner as himself, attributes to no argument more weight than to one grounded on our natural desires. Divine Legation, vol. iii. p. 6S2. Aristot. Ethic, book i. chap. 2. Rhet. book ii. chap. 19. X Appendix, note F. 17 right estimate as to the actual belief of the ancient philosophers on the subject of a future existence. - It is not because they give way to doubts and misgivings; (on such a subject how could it be otherwise ?) it is not because we meet with unintelligible theories ; this has been the history of meta- physics in all ages and under all religions : it is not because these theories might lead to consequences inconsistent with their po- sitive declarations, that we are to come at once to the conclusion that they had no belief in what they asserted, and that So- crates and Plato ^ (for we have no certain y If the misgivings of Socrates at one time are brought forward, let us remember the strength and confidence of his assertions at others. Vid. Phaedo, p. 120. Sequitur ex liis nobile Socraticae scholse dogma ; ani- mum esse immortalem et habere post mortem pryemia virtutis: quod morte sua obsignavit et confirmavit So- crates. Videtur non tam de animorum post banc vitam felicitate dubitasse quam de ejus conditione et loco, quo referenda sunt, si vere sunt Socratis quae apud Antonium et Maximum ei tribuuntur, interrogatum quaenam in al- tero mundo sint obvia, respondisse, se neque ipsum ibi unquam fuisse neque cum ullo eorum qui inde rediissent colloquutum esse. Hist. Crit. Phil. Brucker, vol. i. pp. 563, 564i, 2 W^arburton and others attempt to separate the opin- C 18 criterion by which we can separate the opinions of the one from those of the other,) made it the sole business of their lives to deceive those whom they pretended to teach. The general tone and temper per- vading their discussions is at variance with such an opinion. ""It is a striking feature in the character of Socrates, and which well entitles him to the admiration even of Christians, that, surrounded with mysteries which he could not explain, and in the midst of darkness which he could not pene- ions of Socrates from those of Plato- Whether the fact be so or not, we have no means of distinguishing between them. As far as Plato's own evidence is available, the contrary is the case. Ata tuutu ov^h TTMnoT eyu) Trepi tou- %(TTai, Tu di vvv Xcyo>5va l^UKPATOTS sari. Plat. 2 Epist. ad Dionys. p. 406. I do not wish to insist on the positive testimony of this passage, on account of the obvious advantage it must have been to the philosopher to convey his instructions freely to his friend, through the medium of another's name; I am speaking of course of their opinions on moral subjects. It is well known that Plato discussed physical questions, which Socrates did not ; Scoxparouj Ss Treg) fLsv ru rjQixoi Trpayfi^uTsvoiJLSvou TTsp) Se t^j oXjjj ) ouSaftoJj oBixoc, oiW* cog olov TS SixaioVarof, jca) oux. scttiv avTcu ofioioTspov ov^sv r} og ocv Y}fjt,u)V ecu yevY^ron oti ^maiOTUTog. Kekker, pars ii. "vol. i. p. 247. In the Gorgias, M^ yup tovto [j^h, to ^f,v 6^J^oa■ov^ Xpovov, Tov ys cog a\Y}^cog avlpct euxreov h(TTi kolI ov ^