W^i '^■K C'VAS /ffk-. v^ '<' *.' V/fe' IT. mm $^ ci^ /^Zcc^j J'T^Cr -so T UN IVERSITY Received Accessions REESE LIBRARY OP THE OF CALIFORN lA. ■8f/ ^.^}/:J./ Shelf No. ^ *v> Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/beliefofjewishpeOOmlllrich THE BELIEF OF THE JEWISH PEOPLE AND OF THE MOST EMINENT GENTILE PHILOSOPHERS, MORE ESPECIALLY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE, IN A FUTURE STATE, BRIEFLY CONSIDERED. THE BELIEF OF THE JEWISH PEOPLE AND OF THE MOST EMINENT GENTILE PHILOSOPHERS, MORE ESPECIALLY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE, IN A FUTURE STATE, BRIEFLY CONSIDERED ; INCLUDING AN EXAMINATION INTO SOME OP THE LEADING PRINCIPLES CONTAINED IN BISHOP WARBURTON's DIVINE LEGATION OF MOSES ; IN A DISCOURSE PREACHED BEFORE THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD AT ST. MARY'S, March 30, 1828. WITH NOTES AND AN APPENDIX. BY W. MILLS, B. D. FELLOW OP MAGDALEN COLLEGE. rvftvei(ftev rtis 4"'X^i '^ AN0PXiniNH SOOIA riXos Se 'H 0EIA. Origenes. OXFORD: AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS FOR THE AUTHOR, AND SOLD BY J. PARKER ; AND BY C AND J. RIVINGTON, LONDON. MDCCCXXVIII. X^^ OF THE ^ UNIVERSITY 4^ 4^ J'^ y TO JOHN THOMAS HOPE, ESQ. THE FOLLOWING DISCOURSE IS INSCRIBED WITH THE SINCEREST FRIENDSHIP AND REGARD. I'V # PREFACE. XHE following Discourse, delivered up- wards of six months since, was not origi- nally intended for publication. It is com- mitted to the press with the sanction of a learned friend, whose opinion the author considers of great value. It was thought that a brief statement of an important question might not be without advantage to others engaged in the same inquiries. The controversies that arose when the Divine Legation of Warbu7'ton was first published have long since died away, nor is it necessary to awaken them again, ex- cept as far as the chief subject of dispute is connected with the acquisition of reli- gious truth itself An examination into the belief of Jew or Gentile in the soul's immortality before the coming of our Sa- viour, can never cease to be an interesting question to the Christian philosopher. Nor viii PREFACE. will the investigation be without profit to him who pursues it candidly, as a source of moral improvement. He may learn to be thankful on the ground of revelation for the advantages which he enjoys over the most favoured Israelite in the superior blessings and prospects of the new, com- pared with the old dispensation ; and on the ground of his natural faculties, he will be sensible of the benefits which reason itself has derived from the word of Scrip- ture, as well in directing as in limiting its exercise. He has seen the day clearly which the inspired patriarchs of old, with the prophetic eye of faith, at a distance, rejoiced to see; and he has received that light of imparted knowledge from Heaven, which the wisest of the heathens felt neces- sary to clear up the doubts of the specu- lative mind, and would have hailed with gratitude and reverence. IJKIVBBSITY 2 TIMOTHY 1. 10. — who hath abolished death, and brought life and immortality to light through the gospel, xHESE words form part of an Epistle written by the great apostle of the Gentiles, at a time when he stood in need of all the consolations to be derived from the doc- trine which they convey ; when he was suffering from imprisonment and persecu- tion, and he perceived that the hour of his martyrdom was approaching. Rejoicing in the hopes which they inspired, he declared that he was afflicted, and yet was not ashamed ; and looking forward to his re- ward, he exclaims in a subsequent part of the Epistle, / have fought a good fight, I have finished my course, I have kept the faith : henceforth there is laid up for me a crown of righteousness, which the Lord, the inghteous judge, shall give me. Language so full of confidence in his reward and in the grounds of it, so full of trust in the righteous Judge who was to confer it, as plainly to prove that the power of death B 9 was indeed abolished, and that life and im- mortality were brought to light. Yet these expressions of my text, ^coTia-ctv- Tff ^i*)y}v Ku) (A(j)6ccp(rioLv, however strong they may appear, are not to be considered as implying that the expectation of a future life had never been heard of till the coming of the Messiah. In its literal acceptation the word (pmZei signifies rather to make clear what is obscure, than to bring to light what is entirely unknown : thus ^oorZetv A^t]6siciv, to make the truth manifest, and not to shew forth a truth of which no glim- mering had previously been perceived. The heathen looked forward to a future state, though he had no certain evidence for his belief, neither comprehending clearly the immortality of the soul, nor having any notion of the resurrection of the body*. And the Jew was instructed by revelation, that the life forfeited by the transgression of Adam w^as to be restored through the mediation of some future deliverer, though all the circumstances connected with the a The word a^Qup(rlav, incorruption^ probably conveys this meaning. Macknight and Benson. 8 mystery of redemption were not to be fully revealed, till our Saviour's appearance and ministry upon earth dispelled every doubt and difficulty in which the doctrine was in- volved, enlightening what was before ob- scure, and completing what was before imperfect. It will be my object in the present dis- course, to compare the knowledge both of the Gentiles and the Jewish people, re- specting a future life, with the clearer reve- lations which Christians enjoy on this mo- mentous subject. That the idea of another state of exist- ence after the termination of the present universally prevailed among mankind, the records of history unequivocally prove : there is no nation, whether savage or civil- ized, amongst whom some traces of it may not be found. It made a part of the po- pular belief in the early stages of society, before mythology was formed into a sys- tem ; it was strongly impressed upon the mind before political codes gave a particu- lar direction to it by ceremonies and modes of worship, and before philosophy exhibited B 2 alike the power and the weakness of hu- man reason, by the subtlety of its specu- lations on a subject of such overpowering interest. This conviction cannot be ascribed to the policy of the legislator, which was itself the foundation on which his religious enactments were erected, nor yet to the wisdom of the philosopher, which prevailed for ages before philosophy took its rise among mankind. It was probably a rem- nant of that early revelation given to our first parents, and which, amid all the changes and distractions of civil society, and all the emigrations of tribes and na- tions, had never been utterly obscured^. But in process of time, when civilization had advanced, men's ideas respecting both the nature of the Deity and the doctrine of a future state had been corrupted; gods were multiplied without number "^j the li- b The notion of a future existence must be either a deduction of reason, or be derived from revelation, or an impression of instinctive consciousness. c The treatise, Tlepj xoV/xou, ascribed to Aristotle, speaks of the Deity as one, and derives the different names of God from the different parts of nature which he regu- lates. Aristot. lUp\ }i6a-(XQv, cap. 7. centious passions of the most licentious men'were ascribed to them, and the belief of a future existence was intermingled with the wildest creations of the fancy. All these notions were at length combined into order by the poet, and sanctioned by the legislator"^; vices of the most atrocious kind were countenanced by the example of the divinities, and the authority of the laws, and the obligations of mistaken piety and public duty, lent in some cases additional stimulus to the depraved appetites of our nature ^ Yet notwithstanding this perni- Hesiod and Homer reduced to system the mythology of the Grecian gods. Vid. Herod, lib. ii. c. 53. Brucker, Hist. Crit. Phil, pars ii. lib. i. cap. 1. sect. 26. 31. pp. 407. 423. In process of time, not only all the operations of exter- nal nature were explored for deities, but the most trifling acts of man himself were each under the superintendance of a particular god. Vide a singular chapter, Augustin. Civ. Dei, lib. iv. c. 11. d It is because the weakness and licentiousness of Jove and the other deities, as described by Homer, furnished a bad example to mankind, that Plato wished to banish poets from his republic. Plato de Repub. lib. iii. Bekker, pars iii. vol. i. p. 107 — 117. ^ The worship of Mylitta, the Babylonian* goddess, is frequently cited as a preeminent instance of pagan im- B 3 6 cious influence, derived from the corrup- tions of the doctrine, society must have been on the whole improved by it; for un- less the belief had acted powerfully as a check upon the unruly desires, we cannot conceive why legislators should have taken so much pains to preserve it^. When philosophy, at a comparatively late period, arose, it made no claim to the invention of the notion, or to have derived it from the deductions of natural reason. Not only Plato makes continual and direct allusions purity ; yet the ordinary homage paid to the divinities in Greece and Rome at the sacred festivals, was far more pernicious in its effect upon public morals than the singu- lar institution above alluded to. Vid. Augustin. Civ. Dei, lib. ii. cap. 4, 5. Herodot. lib. i. cap. 200. ^ Thales, the founder of the Ionic school, flourished about six hundred years before Christ, and no regular course of reasoning was brought forward for the soul's immortality, till the time of Plato, two centuries after : Thales taught that water was the first principle, which Aristotle seems to consider as the most ancient philoso- phical notion, Metaph. lib. i. c. 3. and that God, or Mind, made all things out of water. As he was a native of Phoenicia, Cud worth supposes that he received his two principles from thence, " water, and the Divine Spirit " moving on the face of it."" Cudworth, Intellect, Syst, book i. cap. i. sect. 22. to tradition as the origin of his knowledge^, but earlier writers were avowedly indebted to the same source; all that philosophy did pretend to was, to demonstrate that belief by arguments which was before grounded, we know not how, in the com- mon fears and hopes of mankind. And let those who form an exalted estimate of the intellectual powers, in deciding upon such mysterious subjects, judge with what suc- cess the attempt was made, by the jarring and contradictory opinions of the different schools of antiquity. Let those who imagine that the immortality of the soul (I speak not of the resurrection of the body) is dis- coverable by human sagacity ^ examine the strong reasons of that unrivalled genius, who has the merit of having taught suc- ceeding disputers to set their arguments in order on the subject. Almost all the dis- quisitions of Plato are grounded upon the hypothesis of the soul's preexistence K Be- s Vide Appendix, note A. h Phaedo passim. i The two principal arguments in the Phaedo, the one derived from the notions of the ancients respecting yevsa-tg, B 4 8 sides confusing himself and his readers with the mazes of verbal sophistry, in which, notwithstanding all its excellencies, Greek philosophy so much abounds, he derives his fancied demonstrations from abstruse theo- ries on the properties of generation and cor- ruption, and the essential and eternal ar- chetypes of things ; and even the most plausible and specious are so obscured by r the other from his own philosophical belief concerning the archetypes of things, rest entirely upon such a supposi- tion. As the term generation was relative, and implied its contrary corruption^ he infers that the act of being born involves the destruction of a previous existence, from which this present coming to life is a transition. '0^q\o- ysiTui apex, r){uv tea) tuvty} Tovg ^oovras sk rcav tsQvscotwv ysyo- vivai. Phaedo, Bekker, p. 30 — 34. 2dly. His theory of eternal essences, or ideas, suggests the argument that the notions which the soul has of perfect equality, perfect good, &c. which are never found in sensible objects, prove that it must have existed in a previous state, its present knowledge being nothing more than remlmscence. The discussion derives an incidental value, from shewing that Plato had a considerable acquaintance with the law of as- sociation. Plato, Bekker, pars ii. vol. iii. pp. 35 — 44. Not one of the ancient philosophers before Christianity held the soul's immortality, without holding the preexist- ence of souls. They believed also the immortahty and preexistence of brutes. Cudworth, Intellect. Syst. book i. cap. 1. sect. 31, 32. 9 the subtlety of his language \ as to be ab- solutely unintelligible, except to a mind long versed in the refinements of metaphysics. Such theories as those in the Phaedo could never have convinced any one of the soul's immortality, unless he had been previously prepared to believe it ; nor coming, as they are supposed to have done, from the lips of Socrates in his dying hour, could they have k As a specimen of unmeaning subtlety, it may be suj^ ficient to point out that exquisite verbal trifling towards the end of the -treatise, respecting the archetype of even and odd, and its application to tne question of the soul's immortality, a-xoitsi l\ irsg) rr^^ Tf^nxdoc, p. 99. The reader is absolutely bewildered for some time, till at length he is conducted to the conclusion — that as the essence of even does not partake of the contrary essence odd, so the soul which brings life cannot partake of the contrary essence death, and must consequently be immortal. If we had not known the treatise to be a serious inquiry upon a se- rious occasion, we might have been tempted to think, from the winding up of the dialogue, that the writer intended to ridicule such absurdities ; T/ ouv ; to ja^ h^of^^vov ty}v tou 'apTiQV iSeav t/ vvv drj oovo(/,ott^O[ji,sv ; 'Avapriov, e(pr). To 8g S/- xotiov fjL^ Se^OjOtevov xa» av [LOUdDtov fjt,vj U^rjTcn ; "Afx.ovaoVy g(p>), TO §£ aSjxov. Elev* o 8' av Qolvchtov (/,r) Ssp^ijra/, t/ xaXoO- ■ju^sv; 'AQuvuTOv, eipri. Oukoov y} ^v^yj ov he^sToti SotvctTOv ; Ou. 'Afiavarov apot ^ ^tJX^' *AdavaTOv. Klsv, e(p>)* touto [xh dt] AnOAEAEIX0AI <pciJ/Asv ; p. 103. Vide the whole argu- ment, from p. 90 — 105. 10 been his only consolation. If the argu- ment, grounded upon the compound nature of man ^, and the immateriality of the soul, be brought forward in opposition to such a view of the subject, it may be asked, was the phi- losopher so well acquainted, or are we our- selves, with all our additional knowledge, so well acquainted with the laws and properties of matter, as to be able to pronounce that the Being who ("' even according to Plato's creed) made the universe out of nothing, is limited in power, and that he could not, if he would, impart thought and intelligence to a material substance? Or have we so clear a notion of spirit^ or so perfect an in- sight into the essential qualities of spirit^ as to be satisfied, that leaving the revealed will of the Deity out of the consideration, it is in itself incapable of annihilation ? Yet, however unsatisfactory such argu- ments may be, (as arguments of natural rea- ^ The soul is divine, immortal, intelligent, uncom- pounded, indissoluble : the body human, mortal, without intelligence, concrete, dissoluble. Plato, Phaedo, p. 50. ^ Appendix, note B. 11 son on the subject ever must be ",) shall we assent at once to the opinion of bishop War- burton, that neither Plato nor any one of the philosophers (Socrates alone excepted) who inculcated the notion of a future state them- selves believed in it? By what process are we to separate his real belief from his constant and positive assertions? Those declarations of his on which so much stress has been laid, that it was lawful to deceive for the public good, were evidently intended to be ^ Warburton's Divine Legation, book iii. sect. 2. vol. ii. edit. 1788. p. 11, 26. The observations of Warburton respecting the doctrines of the ancient philosophers, vary- ing with the subject matter which they embraced, whether legislation or philosophy, are refined and ingenious ; but they are neither universally true, nor are the conclusions he would deduce from them to be trusted. " I have ob- " served," says he, " that those sects which joined legis- " lation to philosophy, as the Pythagoreans, Platonists, "Peripatetics, and Stoics, always professed the belief of " a future state of rewards and punishments ; while those " who simply philosophized, as the Cyrenaic, the Cynic, " &c, publicly professed the contrary." Aristotle was full as much a legislative philosopher as Plato, and far more practical ; and yet there is no one passage in the whole of his works in which he directly proposes the re- compense of a future state as the motive of morality; on the contrary, among the voluminous writings of Plato, there is scarcely a single treatise in which it is omitted. 12 understood in a limited sense only**, and not as the basis of a philosophy, which above all others professed to have truth for its one and only object. It is not merely in his more plain and practical works that we find his recorded opinions respecting the existence of a future state ; they are to be found in all his writings, whether moral, political, or physical p : they intermingle with the most subtle discussions in works which never could have been intended for popular instruction : and it is difficult to understand by what application of the well- known division of ancient philosophy into exoteric and esoteric % or by what theory of ^ Appendix, note C. P Vide Plato, edit. Bekker. Phaedo, pars ii. vol. iii. p. 106. Apologia, pars i. vol. ii. p. 138. Crito, pars i. vol. ii. p. 167. Epist. 7. pars iii. vol. iii. p. 448. Epist. 2. pars iii. vol. iii. p. 400. Timaeus, pars iii. vol. ii. p. 45. Republic, pars iii. vol. i. pp. 502 — 516. Gorgias, pars ii. vol. i. pp. 163. 164. 165. De Legibus, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 219. Epinomis, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 374. ^ Appendix, note D. IS a double sense, devised after Plato's own time, the same treatise, and the same por- tion of a treatise, could be adapted at once to instruct the philosopher and to delude the vulgar. "^ If there were certain unwrit- ten doctrines, which were a key to his real sentiments, they have not come down to us, and we have no means of estimating their value ; and it is evident that we can- not decide against the actual import of what we know, on the supposed testimony of what is altogether unknown. But it will be said, the notion of a future state ' is r Vid Brucker, vol.i. p. 660. Tennemann'*s Geschichte der Philosophie von Wendt. art. Plato, p. 98. Warburton, acute as he is acknowledged to be, seems to write at times as if he confounded the three distinct ideas of esoteric treatises, unwritten doctrines, and a double sense to what is written. s Warburton, book iii. sect. 3. Whately's Essays on the Peculiarities of Christianity, p. 30. Lancaster's Har- mony of the Law and Gospel, p. 126. 141. The doctrine of the absorption of the human soul is frequently imputed to Plato ; but it does not appear from his own writings that he entertained the notion, nor in- deed that of the Anima Mundi in the sense generally un- derstood. He never confounds the soul of the universe with the one first Cause, Creator, and Father of all things, Plato's names for the supreme Deity are, 6 Arif^iovpyos, 6 14 inconsistent with his philosophical theory of the reunion of the soul after death, to the one divine and universal Mind, from whence it originally emanated*. Now al- lowing, for the sake of argument, this to be Plato's opinion, which is found in the sys- tems of other philosophers rather than in his own, is it so very easy for the under- standing to realize to itself this notion of absorption into the universal spirit, in which all idea of personal consciousness is to be excluded, that we are at once to discard 0SO5, 6 IIoiviT^g, xu) TIuTvjp Tou 6\ou, 6 us) Osog. AYifj^iovgyov- ffoL Air /a, ysviasoog xa) ova lug uhiu, ^povou [x^ fisTB^oua-u, ou8* Iv %f'ova> TO 'KapUTtoLV ov(roi, 0gof uWiMTUTOg, 6 TrgooTog Qsog, 6 f/iiyio-Tog Qsog. The soul of the world, and other second causes, are, OsoO ysw^f^uTu xai spyu, Avifji,ioupyov wryipsroit, Seoi dscwv, who derive all their power from the first Creator. Vid. Timasus, and his other philosophical works, pas- sim. Plotinus, Numenius, and the Platonists of the Alex- andrian school, give a very different account : with them the supreme Deity is the father of the A>;jxioupyoj, the se- cond Deity, and the Anima Mundi is the third. Eusebius, Praep. Evang. lib. xi. c. 17, 18. edit. Vigeri, Paris, 1628. In the wild and blasphemous speculations of Cerintlius and other early heretics, the supreme Deity is also dis- tinguished from the A>jju,ioy^yo^, or Creator. Irena?us adv. Haereses, hb. i. cap. 1. 13. 16. 19. 25. 33. lib. v. cap. 4. ^ Vid. Appendix, note E. 15 every declaration of belief as insincere, which is at variance with the inference de- ducible from such a theory? Are all those expressions, in which the feelings of the man triumph over the abstractions of the philosopher, to be set aside in favour of a principle which none of those who held it either comprehended or consistently ex- plained ? The best evidences of a man's real conviction are not his speculative views, but those natural sentiments to which he gives utterance more in unison with the or- dinary tendencies of the human mind. On the lofty heights of metaphysical specula- tion ", clouds and darkness hover, which it ^ The speculatist may declare, if he will, that the law of causation cannot be proved^ and that the free-agency of man is disproved ; yet from the very next moment to the last hour of his life, the natural course of his thoughts, words, and actions, will be in direct contradiction to his theories. If he argue that the immortality of the soul cannot be demonstrated on the principles of pure reason, the desire of the heart, the " longing after immortality," will still remain ; and this (omitting revelation) is of itself the best evidence of its truth, AI yap /SeATio-rat ^rjx^i MANTETONTAI rawra ootcoj iX^iv. Plato, 2 Epist. ad Dionys. Bekker, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 400. Warburton 16 is not permitted to the limited powers of the most exalted intellect to disperse. ""The difficulties multiply in proportion as we ascend, and if we imagine that we have ar- rived at certainty, and venture to give defi- nite form and shape to our abstractions, we shall soon learn the mortifying lesson, how little our system will influence the prac- tical belief of others, or even our own, when opposed to the more common motives and instinctive impressions of our nature. Those who have reflected most on such subjects will perhaps assent to the opinion, that if we would discover truth, we must pursue it in some lower region, in which the light of our moral feelings and faculties may be allowed to cheer and direct our path. These reflections, while they teach humi- lity to ourselves, may assist us to form a Warburton speaks with contempt of such inferences, as proper only to poetical metaphysicians and metaphysi- cal poets; yet Aristotle, at least as sober a reasoner as himself, attributes to no argument more weight than to one grounded on our natural desires. Divine Legation, vol. iii. p. 6S2. Aristot. Ethic, book i. chap. 2. Rhet. book ii. chap. 19. X Appendix, note F. 17 right estimate as to the actual belief of the ancient philosophers on the subject of a future existence. - It is not because they give way to doubts and misgivings; (on such a subject how could it be otherwise ?) it is not because we meet with unintelligible theories ; this has been the history of meta- physics in all ages and under all religions : it is not because these theories might lead to consequences inconsistent with their po- sitive declarations, that we are to come at once to the conclusion that they had no belief in what they asserted, and that So- crates and Plato ^ (for we have no certain y If the misgivings of Socrates at one time are brought forward, let us remember the strength and confidence of his assertions at others. Vid. Phaedo, p. 120. Sequitur ex liis nobile Socraticae scholse dogma ; ani- mum esse immortalem et habere post mortem pryemia virtutis: quod morte sua obsignavit et confirmavit So- crates. Videtur non tam de animorum post banc vitam felicitate dubitasse quam de ejus conditione et loco, quo referenda sunt, si vere sunt Socratis quae apud Antonium et Maximum ei tribuuntur, interrogatum quaenam in al- tero mundo sint obvia, respondisse, se neque ipsum ibi unquam fuisse neque cum ullo eorum qui inde rediissent colloquutum esse. Hist. Crit. Phil. Brucker, vol. i. pp. 563, 564i, 2 W^arburton and others attempt to separate the opin- C 18 criterion by which we can separate the opinions of the one from those of the other,) made it the sole business of their lives to deceive those whom they pretended to teach. The general tone and temper per- vading their discussions is at variance with such an opinion. ""It is a striking feature in the character of Socrates, and which well entitles him to the admiration even of Christians, that, surrounded with mysteries which he could not explain, and in the midst of darkness which he could not pene- ions of Socrates from those of Plato- Whether the fact be so or not, we have no means of distinguishing between them. As far as Plato's own evidence is available, the contrary is the case. Ata tuutu ov^h TTMnoT eyu) Trepi tou- %(TTai, Tu di vvv Xcyo>5va l^UKPATOTS sari. Plat. 2 Epist. ad Dionys. p. 406. I do not wish to insist on the positive testimony of this passage, on account of the obvious advantage it must have been to the philosopher to convey his instructions freely to his friend, through the medium of another's name; I am speaking of course of their opinions on moral subjects. It is well known that Plato discussed physical questions, which Socrates did not ; Scoxparouj Ss Treg) fLsv ru rjQixoi Trpayfi^uTsvoiJLSvou TTsp) Se t^j oXjjj <pua"£coj ovlsv. Aristot. Metaphys. lib. i. cap. 6. a Appendix, note G. 19 trate, he seems to have reposed implicit confidence in the benevolence of the Deity even unto death ^ and to have believed in b Socrates is full of expressions indicating that implicit confidence in the justice and benevolence of the Deity, which is the root and foundation of all religious faith. In the Theaetetus, 0eos ou8a/A>) ouSaftoJj oBixoc, oiW* cog olov TS SixaioVarof, jca) oux. scttiv avTcu ofioioTspov ov^sv r} og ocv Y}fjt,u)V ecu yevY^ron oti ^maiOTUTog. Kekker, pars ii. "vol. i. p. 247. In the Gorgias, M^ yup tovto [j^h, to ^f,v 6^J^oa■ov^ Xpovov, Tov ys cog a\Y}^cog avlpct euxreov h(TTi kolI ov ^<Ao\J/y^»3- T£ov, aXX' BTtiTpe^oivra irsp) toutoov too Qsco. Bekker, pars ii. vol. i. p. 142. Again, in the same treatise, speaking of the unjust and intemperate man, Our= yup oiv aWco uvQpaiTrco 'Kqo(T(^iKYig oiv siri 6 ToiouTog outs Seco. Bekker, pars ii. vol. i. p. 133. In the Theages, a treatise ascribed to Plato, 'E«v fJLSV too QsCti CplXOV ]5, TTOtVU TtOKu STTldaXTSig XU) TU^Vj el 8g jM,^, ou. Bekker, pars ii. vol. iii. p. 280. In the Apologia, Ou8e a[j(,£\slTcn VTTO 0ea)v tol toutov Trpayjxara. Bekker, pars i. vol. ii. p. 139. Vide also Alcibiades I. if this dialogue was really written by Plato, which admits of some doubt. SOC. Ou xoiXcag Xeysig, '12 'AXxi|3<aS)j. ALC. *AAAa TTcug ^pv) Ksysiv ; SOC/'Ori Euv Qaog s^sXyi, p. 373. SOC. 'O eTriTgoTTog 6 k[Aog ^sXrioov etTT* xu) (ro(pcjtiTspog jj Tlepixkrig 6 crog, ALC. Tig ouTog, CO "^wxpxTsg; SOC. 0£ogy M 'AXx</3»aS)j, X. t. X. Bekker, pars ii. vol. iii. p. 345. It may be worth mentioning also, that SocrateS con- sidered suicide a criminal act of disobedience to the Deity : because we are here at our post assigned us by the gods, C 2 20 him as a rewarder of them that diligently seek him, in spite of all the doubts that confounded his understanding, and the wrongs and oppressions which he endured. Whatever were his views on the abstract question of the universal soul, he is uni- form in teaching that no happiness in this life was perfect, and that our happiness in another would depend upon our conduct during our present existence. He reasoned as Hooker reasoned, that no sensible, no moral and civil perfection, was sufficient to satisfy the desires which nature had im- planted "". ^ He exhorted men to aspire (to and may not leave without their permission. ToSe ye [jt,oi ^OKsl, CO Ks(2ifjc, sv XsyecrQai, to 0sovg shon r}[ji,(ov Tovg sTrifjt^zXQ' lji,evoug. Phaedo, p. 13. c In the Convivium of Plato, Socrates is represented as making celestial love the source of every duty towards gods and men ; and admonishing his hearers, that all the labours and desires of the soul ought to aim at that supreme archetype of beauty and truth, which is perfect in itself, uniform and unchangeable, and in the possession of which alone complete happiness can be found. Convi- vium, pars ii. vol. ii. Plato, Bekker, p. 444, &c. Sentences like these remind us of bishop Butler's ser- mon on the Love of God ; and some of the most beauti- ful passages in the earlier parts of Hooker's Ecclesiastical 21 use the words of Hooker) to "something " spiritual and divine ; that which exceed- " eth the reach of sense, yea somewhat " above the capacity of reason, which with " hidden exaltation it rather surmiseth than " conceiveth^" This divine felicity in a future state was to consist in the contem- plation of truth in its substantial beauty and perfection, of which we only see the shadow here below, through the dark me- dium of the senses and imagination^ Hence Polity, vid. p. 260. vol. i. 8vo. edit. Leigh ton's 4th and 5th Lectures are also written very much in the spirit of Plato's exhortations ; Leighton's Works, vol. iv. d Appendix, notes H and I. e Cedant igitur hi oranes (says Augustin, speaking of other sects) illis philosophis qui non dixerunt boatum esse hominem, fruentem corpore, vel fruentem animo, sed fruentem Deo. August. Civ. Dei, lib. viii. c. 8. It is very true, that some of St. Augustin's observations respecting the similarity of Plato's sentiments to the pre- cepts of Christianity, are applicable only to the refine- ments introduced by the later Platonists : yet Plato him- self certainly inculcated the notion to which the words above cited allude. f Vide that beautiful passage in the Phaedo, unequalled perhaps for the flowing harmony of its language in the whole compass of Greek literature; in which he de- scribes the effect of the passions in darkening the under- c3 S2 his continual exhortations to die daily, (they are almost the words of Plato ^ ;) to subdue, even to their utter extinction, those cor- rupt affections which alike darken the un- derstanding, and are the cause of all moral evil. He asserts, in the language of holy writ, that the wars and fightings which exist among mankind, proceed from the unruly passions that tear in their members^y and that it was only by overcoming these, and practising virtue, which was an imita- tion of the Deity, that we could hope to enjoy the happiness of the Deity hereafter L standing, and the power of philosophy in emancipating the soul from their tyranny. Plato, Bekker, pars ii. vol. iii. pp. K>^ — 58. S True philosophers, ouSsv aXka atJroi 67r<T>j8suoy(riv \ olt^o- ^vy](Tx.siv Ts xai rs^vava/. Phasdo, Bekker, p. 16. h Kal yoip TTOksixoug xa) aroKTsig xa) (J^oi.^ct§ ouSev a.X>^o 'TTotg- ^X^i Yi TO a-cofjia xci) al toutou sttiQuixIoii. Phaedo, page 21. compare St. James iv. 1. * Aio xu) TTBipoLd^cti ^pr) IvdevBg exsl<rs <ps6yuv on Tu^liTToc. (Pvyrj ds 'OMOmSl^ 0E12I xcctu to dvvctTov. 'OMOmSlS ts tixaiov xa.) ocriov (j^sto. (ppovYiasoog ysveVQa*. Theastetus, Bek- ker, pars ii. vol. i. p. 347. It was the saying of the Py- thagorean philosophers, from whom Plato probahly bor- rowed the sentiment: tsKos avQpMTrov oiioicocris Qeoo, Eusebius asserts that this idea, of its being the perfection of man to imitate the Deity, was taken from the Hebrew scriptures. 2S In the spirit of the precept, which teaches that obedience is better than sacrifice, he declares that God is not propitiated by of- ferings and victims, but by the virtues of the soul, by piety, justice, and truth ^. He cautions his hearers against pride and high- mindedness, by admonishing them that the man who adhered to what was just, with a humble and well-regulated temper, would enjoy happiness and the favour of the Deity, while he who indulged an insolent spirit, swelling with pride and ambition, would be left deserted by God. In listening to such sentiments, who does not recollect the lan- guage of inspiration, which declares that God resisteth the proud, and giveth grace to the humble^? He teaches, that not only evil ev Tco *AXx<|8<a5>j (fr)o-/v. x.. t. \. Eusebius, Prasp. Evangel, lib. xi. cap. 27. Vigeri edit. Paris. 1628. Plato, Alcibiad. Bekker, pars ii. vol. iii. p. S68. ^ Kot) yocp OLV tmov sir], s] nzpog roi ^topot xoci roi$ Qucrloii a-no^ /3Xs7rou<nv ^jxcov o\ figol, aWa fxv) Trpog tvjv ^v^yjv, ccv Tig o<rioc noii S/xaiOf Mv Tuy^uvYi. Alcibiades II. Bekker, pars i. vol. ii. p. 295. ^ Vid. Plato de Legibus, lib. iv. Bekker, pars iii. vol. ii. p. 355. Eusebius, Praep. Evangel, lib. xi. cap. 13. St. James, iv^^G. c 4 24 actions are to be avoided, but that light and idle words are to be shunned : for an aveng- ing Nemesis was appointed to take account of, and severely to punish, even these'". That this vengeance of the gods, the wicked man could by no efforts either elude or escape ; if he could take wings and fly up to heaven, or could penetrate into the very depths of the earth, it would still pursue and search him out, either here or here- after ". Such maxims are certainly admir- able, and inferior only to that perfect wisdom which came from the lips of Him who spake as never man spake ^ and who proposed to the imitation of his followers no imaginary pattern, removed alike from their sight and their comprehension, but descended upon m AioTi KOT<l>12N xai nTHNX2N AOFON /3a/5ur«T)j ^>3ju-/a* TraiXi yotp STrKrxowos rolg Trsp) tu toiuvto, eroLp^Qri Alxris Ngjxecris ocyysXog, De Legibus, lib. iv. p. 357. " Oux ovTM a-[Jiixpos MV dvasi xaru to t% y^j /3a5oj, ou8* V^l/YlXO$ ySVOfJ^SVOS s\$ rOV OVpotVOV (XVUTTTYjO'Si, t'kTSIS 8g aVTMVf T^V rfrpocTYiKOva-av TifJicopluv s'It IvOaSs ju-evcov she xoi) Iv "Aidov ^iutto- psMg. De Legibus, lib. x. p. 219. o Mirantur quidam nobis in gratia Christi sociati cum audiunt vel legunt Platonem de Deo ista sensisse quae multum congruere veritati religionis nostras agnoscunt. Augustin, Civ. Dei, lib. viii, c. 11. 25 earth, and went about doing good, the visi- ble and embodied model and archetype of truth. Whether these precepts are called morality or philosophical purification, which necessarily included within it the idea of morality, their natural tendency, unless counteracted by other causes, must have been beneficial p; for those only who trained themselves by them were to be admitted to the future happiness -^ those who did not, were to be excluded from it ; whether the participation or exclusion were derived from some law of physical necessity inherent in the soul, or depended on the decision of a supreme Judge \ For allusions to a future judgment, including as it does the idea of retribution in its more strict and proper sense, are by no means wanting. In the same treatise, in which we find him declar- ing before the tribunal of his country, that there was a divine voice within him which P Apologia Socratis, Plato, Bekker, pars i. vol. ii. p. 118. Hist. Crit. Phil. Brucker, vol. i. p. 564. q Phaedo, Bekker, pars ii. vol, iii. p. 107. Epist. 7. Bekker, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 448. Gorgias, Bekker, pars ii. vol. i. p. 167. 26 commanded him to obey God rather than man \ he is represented as deriving consola- tion from the reflection that there would be a more just judgment hereafter. And after his condemnation, when his friends had made all things ready for his escape from prison, and urged him to fly from his im- pending fate, he refuses at once, alleging as the grounds of his refusal the duty of sub- mission to the laws : when they persist in their solicitations, urging that the injustice of the law, in condemning him though inno- cent, would warrant his disobedience ; he answers them with the Christian maxim, that it is our duty to return good for evil^; ^ nElSOMAI AE MA AAON Till 0EX2T H 'TMIN. Apo- logia, Bekker, pars i. vol. ii. p. 115. eOprjcrsi Toug cog 'AAH- 0f2^ AIKA^TA^, o'{ TTsg xa) XsyovroLi kxel Zixa^siv. Apo- logia, p. 138. The practical effects of his belief in a fu- ture judgment are stated also in the Gorgias : 'Ttto tovtoov TMV \6yoov fri'7rsi<rfx,ui, xa) (rxoitw 07ru)g uTro<pavoo[ji,oti too xpirfi cog vyisaTixTrjV tvjv ^v^^v, ^aigsiv ovv euaag rag Tiixoig rug tcjov ttoAAcuv oivSgMTtoov, Ttjv uKrjQsiuv axOTtcav, irsipccdOi^oLi tm ovri cog av Suvco- fjiui (^iXTKTTog coy xui ^^v x«i hzei^uv aTrofivijo-xco a7ro9vi^crxEiV, riapotxoiXco ds xu) Tovg aWovg Travrag uv&pooTroug. Gorgias, Plato, Bekker, pars ii. vol. i. p. 170. s The passage is very strong in the original : Socrates denies that we have the right, under any circumstances, 9.7 assigning at the same time as the motive of his conduct, that he may be able to give a good account to the gods who reign in Hades*. Thus the very same man whose arguments for the soul's immortality are unsatisfactory or unintelligible, teaches in plain and simple language the right source of moral obligation ", the most perfect moral precept, and the strongest motive and encouragement for the practice of it of returning evil for evil : Outs apx 'ANTAAIKEIN hi outs KAK12S nOIEIN ovUvu avQ^coTrcov, OTA' *AN 'OTIOTN nA:SXHI 'rn* ATTI2N. Crito, Uekker, pars i. vol. ii. p. 157. In the Gorgias also he declares that it is better to suffer injustice than to commit it : Su upu ^ov\oio av oSixsla-Qon fj,uK\ov r} a^ixfiv ; (Soc.) BouAo<jU.>3V jxsv av syaoys oodiTsgct' el 8' ocvayxoiiov enj u^ixslv 15 a5ixs7o"5a<, kXolfXYjv av {xoiXXov u^ixsi- a-QonYj oidiKslv. Gorgias, Bekker, pars ii. vol. i. p. 49. ^ M.YJTS 7ra7§aj TTSp) trKslovog ttoiov fj^rjTS to K,f,v ju-^ts «X>.o jOtyjSsv •ffpo Tov diKCilov, 'iva s\g"hi^ov sXflcov eyr^g twjto. "KcaTo. ccKOXoyy]- aotcrQcn To1g Ixsi oip^ouG-iv, Crit. p. 167. u The statement here given by no means coincides with the following assertions of Warburton : " The ancients " neither knew the origin of obligation nor the conse- " quence of obedience. Revelation hath discovered these " principles; and we now wonder that such prodigies of " parts and knowledge could commit the gross absurdities " which are to be found in their best discourses on mo- " rality.'"* Divine Legation, lib. iii. s. 5. vol. iii. p. 144. 28 in the expectation of future retribution. It is not my intention to pursue the sub- ject at length through the different schools of antiquity; through the scepticism of some, the atheism of others, or the sys- tems of those who allowed the existence, yet denied the providence of God; nor to examine how far their principles are consistent with their ordinary precepts, and the comparative credit due to either in de- ciding upon their own belief But it may be a matter of interesting inquiry to in- vestigate the opinions of one distinguished teacher respecting a future state, who more than divided with Plato the empire of phi- losophy. It is however by no means easy to ascertain the sentiments of Aristotle on the subject : as he taught that happiness would be the reward of virtue in this life, he makes few allusions in his practical works to the destinies of the soul in an- other state of being. He never directly proposes the doctrine of a future retribution as the motive of our morality : and though he certainly held the soul's immortality, it is doubted by some if he believed its exist- 29 ence after death in a state of personal iden- tity. In that important question, whether the abstract principles of reason or the com- mon opinions of mankind are the best evi- dence of truth, he uniformly gives the pre- ference to the latter''. And if this be adopt- ed as the test of his own notions in the present case, he believed in the separate existence of the soul, for he represents it as affected after death by the fortunes of its living friends ^i but at other times his language appears to be of a different ten- dency ; and in his metaphysical works, if amid many perplexed and obscure state- ments his meaning be rightly understood ^ X Hence his continual appeal in his Ethics to the lan- guage of men as an evidence of truth : and in the 10th book, chap. 8, he observes, that the arguments of philo- sophers have weight when they agree with experience, but when they disagree they must be rejected. y Aristot. Ethics, lib. i. cap. 11. z Vid. Aristot. de Anima, book ii ; also more particu- larly book iii. chap. 5, 6. Tennemann's Geschichte der Philosophie, art. Aristotle, p. 109. Cudworth**s Intellect. Syst. booki. §. 45. Warburton's Divine Legation, book 3. sect. 4. vol. iv. p. 112. No writer but Warburton pro- fesses to think Aristot. de Anima, book iii. chap. 5,Q, clear and intelligible. His theory of the TO 'EN intro- 30 he denies to that part, or rather power of the soul which he invests with immortahty, the possession of memory, and consequently, by a possible though not necessary infer- ence, of individual consciousness ^ The failure of the two most distinguished among the philosophers of antiquity may teach us how little the force of natural reason could effect in clearing up the most important of all subjects. Whatever they believed themselves, or their followers be- lieved, respecting, a future state, could not have been altogether in consequence of their arguments. As moralists they speak with the tongue of men and of angels, and prescribe a code of moral discipline beyond the capacity of man to practise, but their reasonings for the soul's immortality, with some few exceptions, began and ended in speculations alike inconceivable and unpro- fitable, and left the common expectations of mankind, loaded as they were with ab- surdity, a better guide even to themselves duced to explain the difficulty is an assumption, not an argument. a Appendix, note K. 31 than all the abstractions of philosophy How often must Plato have felt, when baffled and perplexed by the subtlety of his own reasonings, the wish which he once so strongly expressed ^ that the Deity would ^ The words «vayxa7ov ovv e^t) Trspifj^emv soog olv rig [i.ol^ cug hi Trgog Ssouj xai Trpoj uvQ^ctinovc ZiuxsiaSui. Alcib. Xlore ovv TTupscrcii 6 •^povog ovTO(;y oo l^ooKpotrsg; xu) rig 6 TruiBsvo'ctiv ', ij^i- ara yup av jxoi Soxw *8e7v rovrov rov uvSpooTTOv rig s<mvj have been frequently cited by theologians as a proof that So- crates expected some divine Teacher to appear upon earth ; and it was with this impression that the remarks were make in the text. If however the passage be fully examined in connection with the dialogue that follows to the end of the treatise, it will appear very dubious whe- ther they have any such meaning. The more probable import seems to be, that Socrates is speaking of himself, as the teacher who watched over the interests of Alci- biades, but he was aware that his disciple would not re- ceive his instructions till his mind at some future period should be less clouded by passion, and become better prepared to distinguish" between good and evil. Alci- biades II. Bekker, pars i. vol. ii. pp. 296 — 298. Nor will the passage in the Republic, (ourco ^lUKslpLsvog 6 hUceiog .... oiVix(r)(^iv^u\suQYj(rerui, Bekker, p. 66.) which is referred to by Black wall and many other learned men, as a prophetic description of our Saviour's crucifixion, appear to admit any application of the kind, if the whole discussion con- cerning justice and injustice be calmly considered from the commencement of the book to the words alluded to. Repub. lib. ii. Bekker, pp. 57 — 66. 32 appoint some one to reveal his will to man, and enlighten his mind upon sub- jects too excellent for human intellect to attain to ! Let us turn from the speculations of pa- gan philosophy, to consider the belief of the Jewish people respecting a future state of retribution, possessing as they did the benefits of a divine revelation. *" The opinion has been maintained and supported with great learning and ability, that throughout the Old Testament, from Moses to the captivity, the Israelites had not the doctrine of a future state of re- wards and punishments ; and that so much as an intelligible hint of it is not found in the Mosaic law. That being omitted in the sanctions of the law, it was clearly never intended to be revealed to them. That in quality of historian as well as of legislator Moses is silent on the subject, and seems designedly to conceal the future immortality. c Warburton's Divine Legation of Moses, book v. sect. 5. vol. iii. pp. 131—134 edit. 1788. 33 "^That the extraordinary providence, which under the Jewish dispensation extended both to the state and the particular mem- bers of the state, would prevent any of that feeling arising from the unequal distribu- tion of things, which, under the ordinary course of God's providence, so naturally di- rects the hopes of men to the recompense of another life. These propositions are certainly at vari- ance with the general sentiments on the subject; and it may not be unprofitable briefly to examine as well into their truth or falsehood, as also into the nature of that foundation on which they are supposed to rest. "" Now it will readily be allowed by every d Book V. sect. 4. vol. iii. pp. 112 — 131. e Davison on Prophecy, p. 166. Maimonides and the most eminent Jewish doctors maintain that eternal life is to be found in the law, and that it is to be believed, not from other considerations, but because it is in the law. For the mode in which they support their interpretations vide Pearson on the Creed, edit. Oxford, 1797. 2d vol. p. 464. Warburton, Dedicat. to the Jews, 2d vol. p. 282. Warburton, book vi. sect. 3. vol. iii. p. 343. has cited the texts adduced by Manasseh Ben- Israel from the Pen- tateuch, in his tract de Resurrectione Mortuorum. For 34 candid inquirer, that, using the term Mo- saic law in its strict and limited sense, as the code delivered on mount Sinai, the doctrine of future retribution is not to be found in it. For the cabalistic interpre- tations and distortions of words and phrases, by which many of the Jewish rabbin at- tempt to establish a different opinion, are too absurd to require refutation ; and those solemn expressions of Moses, / call heaven and earth to record this day against you^ that I have set before you life and deaths blessing and cursing, therefore choose life, which some theologians understand of a future and eternal life, appear, when taken in connection with their context, to refer, in their simple and primary sense at least, the immortality, Exod. xix. 6. xxxiii. 20. Levit. vii. 25. Deut. xiv. 1, 2. xxii. 7. xxxii. 47. For the resurrection, Gen. iii. 19. xxxvii. 10. Exod. xv. 6. Levit. xxv. Numb. XV. 30. xviii. 28. Deut. iv. 4. xxxii. 39. xxxiii. 6. He has also given at length Rabbi Tanchum''s ridiculous Comment on 1 Sam. xxv. 29. Vide also Michaelis Argu- menta Immortalitatis, sect. 9. p. 96. Syntagma Comment. Goettingae 1759. who enumerates several texts from the Diatribe of Theodorus Dassovius, some of which are the same with those mentioned above, others different. 35 to the benefits of this life only^. And most certainly this promise of temporal good and evil on the part of the legislator, as the recompense of obedience or disobedience, when combined with the historical fact, that the fortunes of the Jewish people for ages are in exact accordance with it^, an agreement which no human wisdom could have foreseen, and no human power could have fulfilled, does prove that the legis- lator himself was an ambassador from hea- ven, and that he must have been appointed by that omniscient and omnipotent Being, who alone could make the contingent de- signs and contingent operations of free agents, whether acting individually or as nations, contribute to the accomplishment of his own certain and unchangeable pur- ^ Deut. XXX. 19. Mr. Peters contends that the Abra- hamic covenant was renewed in this chapter, and bishop Bull understood it in the same way. Vid. Critical Disser- tation on Book of Job, by Mr. Peters, part iii. sect. S. also bishop BulPs Harmon. Apostol. Dissert. Poster, cap. 11. This able divine argues very strongly through- out the chapter in favour of the hypothesis alluded to. g Vid. Joshua xxiii. 14. All are come to pass unto you, and not one thing hath Jailed thereof. D 2 36 poses. But to argue that, in consequence of this omission, it was intended by Moses, or rather by the Almighty, whose servant he was, that the Jews should be shut out from the knowledge of a future state, would** imply a far greater acquaintance with the counsels of divine wisdom than we may presume to lay claim to. The question, whether the Jews believed on such a doc- trine or not, would depend upon the means they might have of acquiring information from other sources besides their legp-l code; and whether the necessary effect of the Mosaic code would be to check or anni- hilate every other source of instruction. In order to understand the subject rightly it is necessary to keep in mind the object of that law, which was\ to preserve the h The law in its sanctions is only po,ntive, that God will do so much, not exclusive, that he will do nothing more. Davison on Prophecy, p. 175. Warburton's work was translated into German in 1751. J. D. Michaelis published a short Dissertation (if not written, corrected by him) against it, Argumenta Im- mortalitatis Animorum humanorum ex Mose collecta. Goettingae 1752. Vide Schrockh. viii. Theil. vol. xliii. p. 753. i Warburton, book v. sect. 2. vol. iii. p. QQ, 37 memory of the one God in an idolatrous world, till the coming of Christ. And it is difficult to conceive how this object could be effected by any other than temporal re- wards ; by any other than some signal and visible manifestations of the divine power, which might convince the heathen nations that the God of the Hebrews was indeed a God that doeth wonders, and might recall to the carnal-minded Jew himself, when tempted to forget his Benefactor, by the immediate vengeance attendant upon trans- gression, a sense at once of his obligations and his privileges:^ / will send my fear before thee, and will destroy all the people to whom thou shalt come, and I will make all thine enemies turn their backs unto thee. ^And five of you shall chase an hundred, and an hundred of you shall put ten thou- sand to flight, and your enemies shall fall before you by the sword. Such was the promised recompense of obedience ; but in case of disobedience the threat is denounced : ^ Exod. xxiii. 27. * lievit. xxvi. 8. d3 38 '" / will set my face against you, and ye shall be slain before you?* enemies. ""And I will scatter* you among the hea- then, and will draw out a sword after youy and your land shall be desolate and your cities waste. Nor does it appear that this promise of temporal good, as many of the opponents of Warburton° contended, was confined to the nation only: health and wealth, ferti- lity to the field and fruitfulness to the cattle, the blessing of the olive and the vine, the basket and the store, every kind of prosperity, was promised to the indivi- dual also ; yet as well to the individual as to the state, in reference to the main ob- ject, the preservation of both from idolatry, which would generally be best effected by the more striking example of national bless- ings and national punishments. Yet it is difficult to understand how such a condi- tion of things should destroy in the minds of the people either those natural expecta- "» Levit. xxvi. 17. " Levit. xxvi. 33. o Mr. Peters and other opponents of Warburton. 39 tions which the rest of mankind cherished in regard to a future state, or the authority of revelation, supposing the doctrine were contained in other inspired writings, which they acknowledged, besides the ordinances of their legal code. The extraordinary providence under which they lived could not justify the ways of God to man upon the ground of reason, as a rewarder of them that diligently seek him, for (it has been well remarked) though an extraordinary provi- denceP, it was not an equal providence, and under such a dispensation as the Mosaic (with reverence be it spoken) Omnipotence itself could not make it so. If the land suffered for its transgressions and became captive to its enemies, it is hardly possible to imagine that some innocent individuals should not have suffered with it. We read in the books of Moses, that when one par- ticular person had committed the offence, P Mr. Peters (p. 263.) observes, that an extraordinary providence does by no means include or infer an equal providence. Mr. Lancaster has very properly remarked on the egregious fallacy of Warburton in confounding the two ideas. Vide Mr. Lancaster's Harmony of the Law and the Gospel, p. 157. D 4 40 the whole army and nation was punished for his sin, though ignorant of it. In like manner, subjects were punished for the dis- obedience of the king. Again, when the father offended, his innocent children and family were cut off with him ; and, suppos- ing they escaped the legal penalty, the loss of the father would itself be an infliction of evil on his kindred. The author of the Divine Legation has called circumstances like these, inequalities of events, and neces- sarily arising from an equal providence % as if by a change of phrase he could get rid of the fact, that under such a dispensation the innocent suffered with the guilty ; and that it was even a necessary and appoint- ed part of it for the crimes of the fathers to be visited upon the children. Yet, amid such inequalities, have we any reason to ^ Warburton's Divine Legation, book v. sect. 4. vol. iii. p. 121. He attempts also most paradoxically to shew that the sacred writers, when they speak (more particularly in the Book of Psalms and Ecclesiastes) of the inequalities of Providence and the unfit distribution of things^ allude to a dispensation existing among their pagan neighbours, and not in Judaea. Book v. sect. 4. vol. iii. p. 120. 41 suppose that the peculiar people of God, favoured as they were acknowledged to be, should have been deprived of those hopes of future recompense, in which every other nation under heaven, when oppressed with calamity, could find consolation? And strong as the sanctions of their temporal code might be as a motive of moral con- duct, have we any probable grounds for supposing that the Almighty excluded from the breast of the Jew the fear of future re- tribution, which, in many secret offences to which the law cannot reach, provides a surer check than temporal evils or tempo- ral death, and which, even under such a reli- gion as paganism, had a powerful operation in deterring men from transgression : for we have the testimony of one of their own writers that it was the inordinate lusts and passions of men that made them atheists "" ? Nor is it necessary for us to explain why, if it were intended that the Jewish people should look forward to the good or evil of the future life, it was not made a part of ^ "Axgursla r|8ov«)v xai sTnQvixim. Plato de Legibus, lib. x. Bentley's First Sermon on the Folly of Atheism. 4£ the sanctions of their law. We cannot rea- son clearly on the purposes of the Almighty, who knows better than we do the compre- hensiveness of his own designs, and the best method and the best time of accom- • plishing them : The secret things belong unto the Lord, but those things which are revealed belong unto us and to our children for ever \ Yet if we reflect upon the me- thod which God had appointed, by which man was to be made partaker of eternal life, the propitiation of Christ and not his own merit or obedience, we may be led to understand why the promise of eternal life was not given in the law ^ Those who lived under such a system might in that case have supposed that the gift of eternal life was annexed as the deserved reward of obe- s Deut. xxix. 29. ' The apostle'*s answer will serve me ; For if there had been a law which could have given life, verily righteous- 7iess should have been by the law. Gal. iii. 21 . that is, if the genius of the law had produced such a dispensation as was proper to convey to mankind the free gift of life and immortality, this gift would have been conveyed by it. Warburton, vol. iii. book v. sect. 6. p. 163; vid. also p. 162. Mr. Lancaster's Harmony, preface, and p. 11. and 12. 43 dience to the law ; that the law was in it- self perfect, and sufficient for man's justifi- cation, and not the shadow of good things to come, and the preparation of a system founded upon better pi^omises. It is evi- dent from the Epistles of St. Paul, that it was their confidence in the allsufficiency of legal ordinances which wrought so strongly on the ancient Jews in their obstinate re- jection of the gospel; they believed that their scriptures held out the blessing of im- mortality as the destined portion of Israel ; and they were persuaded, that, if not di- rectly taught in the law, it was implied in it, and would be given to the faithful Is- raelite through the instrumentality of its sanctions alone. Supposing then eternal life had been the explicit promise of the Mosaic code, all these errors would have ac- quired tenfold strength ; their bitter aver- sion to the gospel would in some degree have been built upon reason, rather than upon blind prejudice; and some of the most powerful arguments, urged by the apostle to overcome the obstinacy of his country- men, would have lost much of their force 44 and propriety. And this reliance of their forefathers on the privileges of their law has been more than continued and con- firmed in the breasts of the modern Jews. The perverted " ingenuity of rabbinical in- terpreters since the dispersion of Israel, su- peradded to the ancient traditions, has in- spired them with the full conviction that eternal life is eoopressly revealed in the law; and to this, among other causes, may be ascribed the tenacious adherence with which the scattered remnant of the Jewish people still cling to the ancient dispensation "". If these reflections be well-founded, the no- tion of a double covenant and a twofold law proposed by Moses, as of positive enact- ment, the one his own national covenant with temporal promises, the other the Abra- hamic covenant with eternal life, a theory which some eminent divines have adopted with a view of reconciling difficulties, would be in itself an improbable hypothesis ; nor ^ More especially of Maimonides, who lived in the 12th century, X Vid. Mr. Lancaster's Supplementary Remarks, p. 873. 45 -^^^^ are the words upon which this idea is grounded sufficient to support the super- structure raised upon them. From this general view of the question, it is time to appeal to the word of God, and to examine how far the promises and prophe- cies relative to the future redemption con- tained in the inspired writings, previous to the captivity, together with those sentiments and turns of expression which meet our eyes almost in every page, are consistent with the opinion that the peculiar people of God were shut out from the knowledge of a fu- ture state. In making this examination, we should be cautious of attributing too much weight to the inferences we are now enabled to draw, by means of the full reve- lation we enjoy, from passages whether in the law of Moses or in other parts of the Old Testament ^. The words that convey to our minds clear notions of a future state might not have appeared in the same light to the understanding of the ancient Jews. y Vide some very just remarks in Dr. Whately's Essays on the peculiarities of Christianity, p. 49. on the passage cited by our Lord himself against the Sadducees. 46 But not to insist upon inferences more or less doubtful from particular texts, it would seem extraordinary, if, intrusted as they were with the oracles of God, in which the scheme of mercy and deliverance from the death denounced upon Adam and his pos- terity is the one great object, proceeding gradually to its accomplishment, from the fall to the birth of our Saviour, they could passively and without reflection have yielded themselves to the punishment of Adam, the bitter sting of death, without meditating upon the promises and blessings scattered through the same early records which re- lated the original transgression. In a nar- rative so concise as the history of the fall is, we cannot determine with what degree of clearness the revelation of redemption, and of future triumph over the tempter, was conveyed to the minds of our first parents in the curse pronounced upon the serpent, that his head should be bruised by the seed of the woman : but it is impossible (as War- burton himself allows) that the words could have been understood in the bare literal sense ; and without attempting to give any 47 undue extent to their signification, through the reflected light thrown upon them sub- sequently by the progressive developement of the Almighty's purposes, it is surely most probable, (because most consistent with that union of justice and mercy which pervade all the divine dispensations,) that at a time when the Father of mankind was bowed down under the weight of a penalty which condemned him to eat bread with the sweat of his brow, till he returned to the dust from whence he came, they were intended to convey to him the only hope of which he could be susceptible, the anticipation of final deliverance from his misery. What reflections would naturally suggest them- selves to the ancient Israelite, when, bearing this promise in mind, he was taught, as he proceeded in the sacred volume, that God looked with an eye of regard on the sacri- fice of Abel, and rejected the offering of Cain, and yet suffered the same righteous Abel to be murdered through envy excited by his righteousness ! He might read that the patriarchs of his race were the friends and favourites of God, and yet were Strang- 48 ers and pilgrims upon earth ; and while they rejoiced that their pilgrimage was drawing to a close, and they were about to be gathered to their fathers, would he be- lieve that this joy was excited by the termi- nation of their earthly labours in the in- sensibility of the grave ; and that being "^ga- thered to their fathers meant no more than that the same sepulchre which had covered the bones of their fathers should soon be the receptacle of their own ? We learn that Abraham looked for a city which hath foundations, and that he was commanded to train up his children and household in the way of the Lord""; and would the memory of these instructions be eradicated entirely from the breasts of the children of Abraham? ^Can we imagine that the z Warburton allows that the origin of this phrase must have been derived from the notion of a common recepta- cle for souls, vol. iii. book vi. sect. 3. p. 320. Michaelis observes, that the Hebrew word signifies non congregari^ solum sed et hospitio excipi, Argumenta immortalitatis sect. 17. TrpoasTs^Yf Ttpos tov Kuov uutqu. Sept. Interp. Genesis XXV. 8. 17. XXXV. 29. xlix. 33. Numbers xx. 24. 26. xxvii. 13. xxxi. 2. a Vid. Genesis xviii. 19. Hebrews xi. 10. 17, 18, 19. b « It appears that Enoch preached to the age in which 49 translation of Enoch would have awakened no reflections, intended as we may sup- " he lived, the doctrine of a future judgment ; his extra- " ordinary death would be a confirmation of its truth." Jude 14, 15. Davison on Prophecy, p. 122. Quoniam quidem Enoch placens Deo, in quo placuit corpore translatus est, translationem justorum prcemon- strans, &c. Irengeus adversus Haereses, lib. v. cap. 5. p. 439. edit. Paris. 1675. The ancient fathers do not enter into the question, ex- cept incidentally, as to the belief of the Jews in the im- mortality of the soul, and a future state of rewards and punishments ; for it does not appear in the early history of the church to have been much controverted, and the Christian apologists in general allude to it as if it were an acknowledged doctrine of the old dispensation, whether they are writing against Jews or against Gentile philoso- phers. Thus Eusebius, (Prsepar. Evangel, lib. x. xi.) in arguing (with what justice it matters not to the present question) that the Gentile sages borrowed all that is valu- able in their writings from the Hebrews, speaking of Plato, observes, " That he derived his notions of the " soul's immortality from Moses, and that there was no dif- " ference in their opinions on the subject ;""' xct) h rolg Tvsp) ^^X^^ aflavao-i'a^, ovUv Mooasoos 6 UkuTCtiv SieVryjxs Tr, So^r;, X. T. X. lib. xi. c. 27. Vigeri edit. Paris, 1628. It is scarce- ly necessary to remark that the assertion is beyond the truth, but it will at least serve to prove, with many other passages that might be adduced, that Eusebius did not agree with Warburton as to the doctrine either of Plato or the ancient Jews. The argument indeed throughout this treatise, as well as the Demonstratio Evangelica E 50 pose it to have been, since so many pa- triarchs and righteous men were suffered to die the common death of all men, not so much as a privilege to himself, as a les- son to his own age and succeeding genera- tions. And are all those expressions in the Old Testament, more especially in the Pro- phets and the Psalms, which appear to us clearly to point to a future life, satisfacto- rily explained by Warburton, who uniformly interprets the plain as relating to this life only, and the figurative as illustrative of some other truth, to be conveyed through the medium of a figure, which in itself was not intended to be considered as having any foundation in truth ^? Thus such expres- clearly evinces, that he did not suppose either the patri- archs or the people of Israel to have looked only to trans- itory promises. c Divine Legation, book vi. sect. 2. vol. iii. p. 312. Warburton, in combating Dr. Felton^s plain and simple principle, that all words used in a figurative sense must first be understood in a literal, adopts the same argument which the opponents of TertuUian made use of when they attempted to refute the doctrine of the resurrection. They asserted that the language of tlie prophets was to be understood figuratively, to which TertuUian replies, " Si omnia figurae, quid erit illud cujus figurae?"" In con- 51 sions as these, Thy dead men shall live, to- gether with my dead body shall they arise ^, might be used by the prophet without his conveying, or intending to convey, the no- tion that his dead body v^^ould arise. And that bold and sublime description of the prophet, in which the souls in Hades are represented as rising to meet the king of Babylon at his coming, according to this mode of interpretation, would be considered as intelligible, without the supposition that firmation, he appeals to the well-known passage in Eze- kiel, chap, xxxvii. which they declared to be figurative, and to convey no promise of a resurrection to the house of Israel, but the assurance of temporal prosperity, and the reunion of their scattered tribes ; his answer is, " Non '' posset de ossibus figura componi si non id ipsum ossi- " bus eventurum esset, nam etsi figmentum veritatis in " imagine est, imago ipsa in veritate est sui." Tertull. de Resurrect, Carnis cap. 29, 30, 31. Sculteti Syntagma, cap. 4. sect. 3. Vide Warburton's remarks on the chapter of Ezekiel alluded to, vol. iii. p. 314. book vi. sect. 2. Bishop of BristoPs Eccles. Hist. p. 282. *l Isaiah xxvi. 19. Few will agree with the observation of Warburton, that " there was no occasion for the doc- " trine of the resurrection to make the language intelli- " gible." Warburton, vol. iii. p. 313 ; still less, " that an '' image is of more force for its being ^inknownr p. 314. E 2 52 Hades existed as a receptacle for souls ^ Hell from beneath is moved to meet thee at thy coming ; it stirreth up the dead for thee^ even all the chief ones of the earth; it hath raised up from their thrones all the kings of the nations. All they shall speak and say unto thee^ Aj^t thou also become weak as we ? Art thou become like one of us? Not to mention many other passages, especially in the Prophets and the Psalms^, which are sufficient to shew that the idea was prevalent among the Jews, of Hades e Warburton, book vi. sect. 3. p. 337. Isaiah xiv. 9, 10. Warburton always translates Sheol the grave : but there are above sixty places in the Old Testament where the word occurs, and it is constantly rendered Hades by the Seventy, except in one or two places at most. Peters on the Book of Job, p. 322. ^^ Amongst all the ancients, whether heathens, Jews, or " Christians, the usual acceptation of hell was^ that it was *' the common lodge or habitation of separated souls both " good and bad, wherein each of them, according to their " deserts in this life, and their expectations of the future ^' judgment, remained either in joy or misery." Vide Cri- tical History of the Apostles'" Creed; a most able and learned work by an ancestor of the present lord King ; art. Descent into Hell, f Psalm Ixxxvi. 13. Prov. xv. 24. Psalm xvi. 10. Prov. ix. 18. Job xxvi. 6. 53 being the region of the departed, and that they divided this region, and assigned a dif- ferent habitation in it for the reception of the righteous and the wicked ^. Again, the more plain and direct expressions, which are generally understood as referring to a future state, are forced from their natural and obvious sense by the author of the Di- vine Legation, and restricted in their im- port to this life only : Thou wilt not leave my soul in hell, neither wilt thou suffer thine holy One to see corruption ^ might have signified to the Jews of old. Thou wilt not suffer me to fall immaturely ; The righteous hath hope in his death '\ The right- eous hath hope that he shall be delivered from the most imminent dangers. Nor does the expression, which have their portion in g Luke xvi. parable of the rich man and Lazarus. Mr. Peters on the Book of Job, sect. 8. ^ Psalm xvi. 10. An acquaintance with the opinions of Epiphanius, Athanasius, Origen, and other ancient fa- thers respecting this text, might have rendered Warbur- ton more cautious in hazarding an interpretation which has no merit but that of novelty to recommend it. ' Proverbs xiv. 3^. E 3 54 this life S mark, according to such principles of interpretation, any opposition between this life and another. It is needless to mul- tiply other passages of the same kind, which will readily suggest themselves to all who are conversant with the Old Testament, and which no acuteness and ingenuity can explain away. But that celebrated passage in the Book of Job \ which would seem de- cisive of the question, I have purposely omitted ; because, as many commentators of great knowledge and candour have doubted whether it referred to a future state or not, it would certainly be inadmissible as a proof in a controverted question, till, after a cri- tical examination of the original in con- nection with the context, its validity as a testimony were fully established* And theo- logians should ever bear in mind, that no greater injury can be done to the cause of k Psalm xvii. 14. ^ Job xix. 25. Amid the conflicting opinions of com- mentators, it is difficult for me to come to any conclusion on the subject. None indeed but a good Hebrew scholar is competent to the investigation : but while any doubt remains, it should not be received as a testimony in a matter of such importance. 55 truth, especially to that of religious truths than bringing forward with indiscreet zeal any questionable or doubtful evidence in support of a doctrine. The adversary might adduce it as a confession of weakness in a cause which had recourse to such assist- ance ; a presumption which can never be excited against an argument founded upon a comprehensive view of the general tenor and language of revelation. Nor has any appeal been made to the prophecy of Daniel, because it is allowed by all, that at the time when Daniel wrote the belief of a future state, from whatever cause, was generally prevalent among the Jewish people. Suffi- cient indications remain, without calling in the aid either of such specific declarations or more doubtful inferences, to convince every diligent and candid inquirer that the ancient fathers of the Jewish church did not look merely to transitory promises ; unless we are to believe, that, because they had a legal code with temporal advantages annexed for a particular purpose, they were to close their hearts against the natural re- flections which suggested themselves to all E 4 56 other men, and close their eyes against all the instruction to be derived from the reve- lation they possessed. Nor does the opinion, that both Jew and Gentile believed in a future state detract from the claims of the gospel as having brought life and immor- tality to light. The Gentiles assented to the truth, they knew not why, from the common apprehensions of nature ; but their expectations, though connected with the idea of responsibility and future judgment, were vague and uncertain ; and we have seen from the example of the philosophers, who went on for ever learning, yet never coming to a knowledge of the truth, how little they could give a reason of the hope that was in them. And the Jew, though taught by many a prophetic vision, or in- structive narrative, or consoling promise, or significant type, to cherish the hope of the immortal life, which the sin of Adam had forfeited, through the medium of a Deli- verer who was to be one of his descendants, had not, and could not have, that distinct and definite knowledge of the nature and method and benefits of redemption which 57 was reserved till the coming of Him in whom every type and prophecy and pro- mise were to receive their full accomplish- ment. The Israelite of old, in his journey through the wilderness of life, was strength- ened and cheered as he drank of the brook by the way, or of the fountain here and there gushing forth from the rock ; but the living well was wanting, whose constant and abundant waters are ever present to us, for the comfort and refreshing of our souls. He was conducted to his eternal inheritance by a light shinmg in a dark place, that pointed out dimly the glories of the future Redeemer, like that pillar of a cloud through which the glory of the Lord appeared, and which guided his foot- steps through the desert to the possession of his temporal Canaan. In the fulness of time the Sun of i'ighteousness arose with healing in his ivings, and all those clouds through which the light had shone dimly on the eye of the faithful were dispersed before him. God sent forth his Son pro- claiming peace on earth, and good-ivill to- wards men, revealed clearly in his offices of 58 Redeemer, Sanctifier, and Mediator, so ne- cessary to the wants, so encouraging to the hopes, so soothing to the apprehensions of man. We need no longer perplex our- selves with difficult questions respecting the soul's immortality : having died to re- deem us from iniquity, our Lord rose again from the dead, in order to assure us of eternal life, by teaching us the resurrection of the bodv ; a truth which alone could convey in a satisfactory manner to the understanding of man the doctrine of a future retribution. And if from a sense of our imperfection, we tremble at the ex- pectation of judgnnent to come, we may derive encouragement from the assurance that God hath committed all judgment to the Son, who himself partook of man's na- ture, and is touched with a feeling of hu- man infirmity. The speculative disputer may still object that there are many diffi- culties that perplex, and mysteries not fully explained, and to the finite under- standing of man they must ever remain so. There is a progressive order in the dispen- sations of Almighty Wisdom, which it is 59 possible may not yet be terminated. As the light which appeared to them of old time was only the dawning of that compa- rative fulness of light which we now enjoy, Christianity itself may be only the dawning of that perfect light which shall shine upon us in our glorified state ; when, in the lan- guage of St. Augustin, " the disposition of " them that thirst shall be changed into the " affection of them that taste and are re- " plenished ""." Instead of indulging in unprofitable speculations, we should place implicit confidence in the benevolence and wisdom of the Deity, and rest persuaded that he has fed us with spiritual food con- venient for us, and revealed all that was suitable to the capacities of our moral and intellectual improvement. And instead of giving way to distrust, because every diffi- culty is not cleared up, and which perhaps to beings constituted as we are, never could be, we should walk forward as men assured of our final inheritance, having our hope in heaven, our labour on earth, our reward in rn Hooker's Ecclesiastical Polity, vol. i. p. 259. 8vo. edit. 60 both : on earth, the inestimable peace of a conscience void of offence ; and in heaven, that peace with God, the author and finisher of our faith, which indeed passeth all un- derstanding ". ^ Dr. Whately, in his ingenious Essay on a Future State, has placed too much reliance on the bold assertions of Warburton ; who, with all his learning and dexterity in applying it, is by no means a safe guide. His learning is often superficial, and his reasoning sophistical. Had the author of the Essays on the Peculiarities of Christianity pursued the inquiry independently for himself, with no other aid than the resources of his own candid, vigorous, and argumentative mind, I am satisfied that his discussion on the subject would have been less liable to be mistaken. The words of Aristotle, when criticising the political dreams of his rival in philosophy, may justly be applied to characterize the Divine Legation of Warburton. To |u.£v DEPITTON e^oucri ttoivtss ol Koyoi, xai to KAINO- TOMON, xal to ZHTHTIKON* xaXwj Ss Travra hw^ xa^sTrov. Pol. Aristot. lib. ii. cap. 4. APPENDIX. APPENDIX. A. Orpheus, Pythagoras, ThaleSj Anaxagoras, all travelled into other countries, and from thence derived the greater part of their philosophical tenets. The ^Egyptian priest observes to Solon in the Timaeus % 'H SoXwv, SoAwv, ''EAA>yvef ael Trai^e^ €a-T€, yepoov ^V^EXXyjv ovk laztv, explaining his mean- ing at the same time by declaring that the Greeks had no ancient doctrine amongst them, no tradi- tion rendered venerable by age. The passages are innumerable in which Plato alludes to this kind of evidence ; and he always makes the appeal in the tone of a man who thought that it was en- titled to considerable weight. The only exception I recollect (and in this case the common remark is most true, that exceptio prohat regulam) is the passage in the Timaeus, in which, after mention- ing the traditions respecting Jupiter, Oceanus, Te- thys, &c. he observes, that we ought to assent to them, because they have been handed down from the heroic age ; and we must believe the sons of ^ Plato, Timjfius, pars iii. vol. ii. p. 12. Bekker. Eusebius, Prsep. Evangel, lib. x. cap. 4. 64 the gods^ though there are no probable or neces- sary proofs of their assertions. Warned by the fate of Socrates, he thought it prudent to enume- rate among his gods the deities of the popular mythology ; but at the same time, from his mode of expressing himself, we have no difficulty in col- lecting his real sentiments. The author however of the short compressed treatise in the ^ Doric dialect, of which Plato's work above cited is a kind of commentary, speaks of traditions respect- ing the punishments of a future life as false yet expedient. This must be considered as the sen- timent of the Locrian ; for it may be proved from his seventh Epistle that Plato's own opinion was very different. '^ In the treatise Ilefi Koa-fjiov, attri- buted to Aristotle, there is the same appeal made to the oL^xcdog Koyog ; nor is it important, in regard to the present subject, whether the work be ge- nuine or not. If not written by the Stagyrite, it is evidently a composition of great antiquity ^ : ^ 'Ahvvarov otv BeSv Tsaicriv airia-reiv Kal irep avev re elKorav ko,) avajKaiuv aitohl^eccv Xeyovariv. Plato, Timseus, Bekker, pars iii. vol. ii. p. 42. <= Bekker, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 391. *^ *Ap%aro5 jtA€V Qvv Tiq Xoyoq Koi waTpto? icrri iraa-iv avQpantOii; a<; Ik Biov roc iravra Ka) S»a deov viy.7> o-vvcVrvj/cev. Aristot. Hep) KoafMv^ cap. 6. ^ In his Metaphysics he speaks of the importance deservedly attributed to this kind of evidence : Ti/xtwraxoy yap to Ttpio-^vrot- Tov, lib. i. cap. 3. 65 and we have similar testimony in works undoubt- edly his own. The early fathers of the church, in their con- troversies with the Greek philosophers, always accuse themi of having borrowed their knowledge from foreign countries, principally from Egypt, and refer through this channel the wisdom of the ancients to divine revelation as its source ^. B. The assertion in the text, that Plato believed the Deity to have created matter out of nothing, has appeared to me, upon further examination* more than dubious. The younger Platonists, Cle- mens Alexandrinus, Ficinus, and Cudworth, main- Ila/jaSeSoTai vito tav 'APXAIHN Kcti TIAAAION ot< Qtol re il<r)v ovroi Ktxi TtepUx^i to 64kv rrji/ oX>jy (ftva-iv. Met. lib. xiv. C. 8. Vide also de Coelo. A^oVep, KaXSq tyjn avixTieidiTv eavrov rovq 'APXAI0T2 'AAH0EI2 elvai Xoyovq. Lib. ii. C. I. Diogenes Laertiiis, at the commencement of his work, cites a treatise of Aristotle in which philosophy was represented to have derived its origin from the Magi of Persia, the Chal- dcEans of Babylon, the Gymnosophists of India, and the Druids of Gaul. Diog. Laert. prooemium, p. i. Cicero also speaks of the same kind of testimony. Tusc. Qusest. lib. i. cap. 12, 13. 17. f Vide Mr. Lancaster's Supplementary Remarks, p. 422. and a learned Charge by Waterland in the 8th vol. of his Works ; Van Mildert's edit. Eusebius, Praep. Evangelica, lib. x. F 66 tain this opinion ; but their view of Plato's sen- timents is disproved by the statements of & Cicero and Aristotle; and the Timaeus alone appears sufficient to shew that he held the eternity of matter ; nor has Serranus been successful in la- bouring to prove that his assertions are to be con- sidered as applying only to the archetype of mat- ter, and not to matter visible and corporeal. It is also worthy of remark, that the fathers, in their refutation of the Pagans, almost uniformly object to them their ignorance of the creation of matter. Thus Athanasius'^ rebukes the Platonists for re- presenting the world to have been created out of preexisting matter. EpiphaniusS in his treatise against Hsereses, accuses Plato of holding contra- dictory language on the subject, sometimes speak- ing of matter as created, at others, as coeternal with the Deity. Eusebius'', in his Praeparatio Evangel., asserts the superiority of Hebrew theo- logy in its declaring that God had made^ all things, * Cic. Acadera. Qusest. lib. iv. 37. Avo yap apx^^i <p'70'* SoKcr itoieTv 6 UKctTuy, to //.ev vTroK€if/.(vov kou vAy^v Tvpoa-ocryopevuVf to Se u^ ai- Twv KOU Kivovv 6 deov KoKei kou vovv. Simplicius in Aristot. Phys. lib. i. p. 19. ed. Aldus, 1526. ^ "Akkoi Se €v 0I5 ia-ri kou {/.iyci^ itap "EXXijo-i XWa/raVy Ik Tcpwrca- K€i[Jt.evv}i KOU ayev^rov vX-t}^ iretroirjKiyat rov deov roc oXa hrjyovvrau. De Incarnatione, p. 48. edit. Benedict. Paris. 1698. ' Epiphanius adversus Hsereses, lib. i. cap. 6. » ^ Praeparatio Evangelica, lib. vii. cap. 18 — 22. 67 and also the matter put of which they were made. C. Warburton boldly asserts that all the ancient philosophers embraced the principle, that it was lawful and expedient to deceive for the public good ^ : and TuUy, on the authority of Plato, thinks it so clear, that he calls the doing other- wise nefas, " a horrid wickedness." As this state- ment appeared contrary to the whole tenor of Plato's writings, I was for some time at a loss to conceive what treatise of the philosopher could be alluded to. I have no doubt, however, that the assertion is grounded on a doubtful translation by Cicero of a passage in the Timseus™. Plato hav- ^ Divine Legation, book iii. sect. 2. vol. ii. p. 13. Warbur- ton gives no reference to the treatise in Tully where the sen- tence is to be found. "* Toy jM.ev oi/v iioiyjrvjv kou icarepa roUSe tov itavro^ evpelv re epyov Kai evpovra eU izavtaq AATNATON "kiyuv, Timaeus, p. 23. Bekker. Difficile est invenire Conditorem hujus mundi et inventum evulgare nefas. Ciceronianum Lexicon GrcBcolatinum, ab Hen. Stephano, 1557. Platonis Loci Interp. p. 13. Eusebius praises Plato for this reverence in speaking of the Deity, as teaching, like the Hebrew scriptures, afpt^rov etvan to 6€tov, Praep. Evangel, lib. xi. c. 12. In the same book, cap. 29, Eusebius cites the above passage from Plato ; and in the Latin translation by Vigerus the word nefas is used. The fact is, nefas is not an improper term ; but F 2 68 ing declared that it is very difficult to discover the Deity, and, when we have discovered him, that it is impossible to reveal him to all men, Ci- cero has rendered the word, not by impossible, but nefas. Yet upon this interpretation of Ci- cero's, or rather misconception on the part of Warburton of the proper meaning belonging to nefas^ in the passage, aided by an unwarrantable extension of a sentiment limited in its applica- tion into a general principle, Warburton has at- tempted to establish an hypothesis which would annihilate at once all that is excellent in Plato's philosophy. There is no author, ancient or mo- dern, who appears to devote himself with greater ardour to the pursuit of truth **. It is the conti- nual object of his aspirations. And there are very few occasions in which he allows of its being sa- crificed to expediency, and then only for a parti- cular purpose. Thus, in the third book of the Republic, he proposes to banish poets from his Warburton misunderstood its meaning. Eusebius, Vigeri edit. Paris. 1628. ° Vide the word aSuvaxov (Timaeus, p. 42.) in the passage cited in the Appendix, note A. ° OvK oktQcx,, "^v 8' iyoOi ort to ye ax; aX-^dut; i/^ci/So^, el oJov re tovtq elvely, vmt€<; Beol re Koi avBpuTioi (aktovo-iv ; De Repub. Bekker, p.103. "^evloq jtx^Se*? jttvjSev jtAijTe Xoyy, /xoyze CjSygj irpd^eie, Plato, quoted by Blackwall, Sacred Classics, vol. ii. p. 103. ed. 1731. 69 ideal commonwealth because they teach not truth, but the images of truth ; and he asserts that truth is always to be upheld as an object of great conse- quence : 'AAAa (JiYjv Kai oLKrfiua.v ye irepi iroKXov ttoi- ^reovP. He permits however the governors of the city to make use of deceit, either for the sake of the citizens, or on account of the enemies ; mean- ing probably for the good of the citizens,, more especially against the enemies of the state ^ : Toig ap'/ovdi '^vj TYjg itoKewg, ei irep tictiv akkotg, TrpoarJKei \pev- ^eaOai yj iroXefJ^iccv t] tto^itcov hveKa eir o^cpeXeia TYjg ttO' Xi(cg : but a private person is forbidden to practise it. Let us suppose then that Plato, while writ- ing his Republic, considered himself as enjoying the privileges of a magistrate ^ and entitled, at the very time he dismisses the poets for giving false representations of gods and men, to inculcate falsehoods respecting the rewards and punish- ments of another life, provided the tendency of his fictions was beneficial. How comes it, that not in the Republic and the Laws only, but in works strictly philosophical, he holds out the same prospect of retribution after death ? P De Repub. Bekker, pars iii. vol. i. p. 112. ^ De Repub. p. 112. ^ Yet this supposition, which is allowed for the sake of ar- gument, will not be entertained by any one who recollects the concluding pages in the second book of the Republic. F 3 70 Is he writing as a legislator in the Phaedo an account of the death of Socrates ? In the Crito, a narrative of his refusal to escape from prison ? In the Apologia, his defence before his judges ? In the Timaeus, a philosophical description of the creation of the world ? It! the Phaedrus, a discussion on the difference between the truly beautiful and the image of it ? In the Gorgias, a treatise on rhetoric ? D. It would appear from the writings of Plato himself, as well as from other testimonies, that there were secret and esoteric^ doctrines reserved for select disciples, which were intended to ex- plain more fully the obscurer parts of his philo- sophy. This seems to be the meaning of the pas- sage in the seventh Epistle, in which, apparently jealous that accounts of his instructions had been made public without his sanction, he declares (evincing at the same time, as may be perceived from the tone of his feelings, a desire to magnify the value of these hidden precepts) that there were some things which he never had written, and which he never would write ; and without « Brucker, vol. i. p. 660. Plato, Phaedrus, Epist. 2. 7. 13. De Repub. lib. iv. Bekker, p. 1 79. 71 these, his common instructions could not in many points be clearly understood. It is easy to suppose him having in view those passages in his writings in which he makes vague and obscure allusions to some apparently sublime truth, and then hastens on, without dwelling far- ther on the subject, to sentences like that in the Phaedrus, where, after describing in a wild and mystical style the happiness belonging to different orders of spiritual beings, he hints at some more exalted and perfect felicity confined to the Deity alone, and which no poet ^ had ever yet described or could worthily describe. But there is no foun- dation for believing, that though his philosophical writings might sometimes admit of di fuller sense, they were therefore intended to bear a double «ense, and that the very same words were calcu- lated to convey to different classes of readers two meanings opposite to each other. Yet it is upon such a theory that we are to imagine Plato (ac- cording to Warburton's views) not merely keep- ing back something in his obscure representations, but absolutely disbelieving" his plain and positive * Tjy §€ vTiepovpdviov tottov ov re Tiq vfAv/ja-e iru tuv t^Bc troivjTY]^ ov re TToB' tiiAvriati Kocr a^iocv. Phaedrus, Bekker, pars i. vol. i. p. 42. " Cicero thought differently of Plato's belief on the subject. Ut enim rationem Plato nullam afferret (vide quid homini tri- buam) ipsa auctoritate me frangeret. Tot autem rationes attu- F 4 72 statements, and having no conviction of a future state of personal consciousness, though he never fails in every treatise to inculcate it. A species of literary Machiavellianism (as it has been called) so extravagant, if not impossible, as this, and so directly opposed to all the notions which a sober- minded man would imbibe from a general view of the tendency of Plato's writings, would require the strongest evidence for its support. And the supposition is at once disproved, as far as his be- lief of a future state is. concerned, by a reference to his Epistles ; those private Epistles, in which (as Warburton properly remarks) a man speaks his sentiments without disguise ; nay, to the very same Epistles which are appealed to for the theory of a double sense, and which, if they do contain it, prevent its application to the question of a fu- ture retribution, by their containing also other passages in which the philosopher decidedly ex- presses his conviction of individual consciousness after death''. In fact, nothing can be more la- lit, ut velle ceteris, sibi certe persuasisse videatur. Tusc. Quasi, lib. i. c. 21. ^ *0 ^vj Kca iyu TiKfji'/i^iov 'Koiovi/.at tri ecTTt Tt^ alo-^vjcr;^ ToTij T€$yeu<rt tSv ivOcile. at yap ^iXriffrai ypv^oii MANTETONTAI rcevra, o^tw? e;^€<y. at Se fAoyfifipoTai-ai ov (paa-i, Kvpiccrepa, 8e ra rwv Oeiav av^puv jxavnvixara ^ ra, tSv jea^. Epist. 2. ad Dionys. Bekker, p. 400. TlilQecrdat Se ovTuq au ^yj Tor^ ndkamq re Ka) UpoTq "klyoiq 0* 8^ lAT^viiovtriv yiiuv AOANATON ^i^TXHN EINAI AIKA2TA2 TE ISXEIN 73 boured and unsatisfactory than the bishop's argu- ments on the subject. The Epistles which he cites would by no means prove the truth of the general principle itself, omitting the question of its application, but only the partial adoption of such an expedient for a specific object y : and most of the other testimonies may be dismissed at once.- Such writers as Jamblichus and Synesius are of very little value in determining such a question. The latter was a Christian bishop of the fifth cen- tury ; and, as he refused to surrender his heretical notions respecting the soul to the testimony of the written word of God, it is very possible that his interpretations of philosophy might be equally at variance with the actual statements of Plato. And JambHchus, with all the Platonists of the Alexan- drian schools (though they by no means univer- sally support Warburton's views,) made it their object to misrepresent the doctrines of their Mas- ter. By the convenient theory of a double sense, of which they constituted themselves the inter- KAI TINEIN TA2 MEri2TA2 TIMnPIA2 OTAN T12 AnAAAAX0H TOT SnMATOS. Epist. 7. p. 448. y Warburton, book iii. sect. 2. 3. 4. ^ Plotinus, the most acute of themiill, never supposed that the unity of the universal Soul excluded the idea of separate consciousness after death, or of personal identity in the indivi- duals who were parts of it. 4th Ennead, Plotinus, 9th book, eh. I. 7th book, ch. 15. 74 preters, they were enabled to make any discoveries they pleased : hence it is, that while plain and in- telligible accounts were rejected, as intended for the vulgar only, the most obscure and indistinct conceptions were spiritualized into sublime truths; and the sacred mystery of the Trinity, and other doctrines of Christianity, were unfolded to the pro- phetic eye of Porphyry and Plotinus in the dis- cussions of the Academy ; till by these and similar methods the dark oracles of paganism were exalted into a perfect rule of truth and wisdom, to the dis- paragement of the clear revelations of Christianity. If we give the author of the Divine Legation the full benefit of ^Numenius's testimony, (of whose writings only a few fragments remain preserved in Origen and Eusebius, which do not sanction his opinions,) on the supposition, gratuitouly as- sumed, that the lost works of this Pythagorean and Platonist would have supported his view of * Numenius is mentioned by Origen contra Celsum, lib. v. pp. 258. 269. edit. Spencer. 16775 also Opiniones de Aniina, p. 629. edit. Paris. 1618. Eusebius, Prsep. Evang. lib. xi. con- tains Numenius's sentiments 3 ntp) rov Zevripov ahiov (cap. 18.); nep) rayadov (cap. 2 2.). This philosopher, as well as Plotinus, is fond of using the expressions " the Father" and *' the Son," (by the Son meaning the Avjpoypyo?,) to designate the first and second Deities of their own, not Plato's theological system. This was done wfth the view of making philosophy speak as much as possible the language of revealed truth. 75 the question ; it is impossible, in discussing a sub- ject of so much interest, to pass over without no- tice the observations which he makes on a passage quoted from Plato's Epinomis. The whole com- ment exhibits a singular instance of the blind par- tiality of a writer when advocating a favourite hypothesis. The elegant ambiguity of which War- burton speaks has no foundation, except in his own fancy : the words admit but of one meaning consistent with the general tenor of Plato's writ- ings and the rules of just interpretation. In pro- posing to render Ik voWav €ya^\ referring to the word atdSyjfjem, which occurs in the previous clause, that of many sensations he has only one left, the bishop has fully proved how much his acuteness and ingenuity surpassed his acquaintance with the ^ Divine Legation, book iii. sect. 3. vol. ii. p. 65. The passage alluded to is as follows ; ^Ov koI hiaxv^ii^oiAai itai'^av Koi <nTOvha<^uy ayLUj ore Oawdra) riq tuv Toiovrccv tv/j/ aviov uq7- pav ai/aTTA^tre/, o-%eSoi/ iuv ivep er arcoOavuv ^, [X'^re [AiOi^eiv er* tcoXXuv Tore KaQd trep vvv ouaB'ficreav^ [AiSi^ rt (/.olpaq fAer^iX'/icpota [/.ovov ko.) EK nOAAnN 'ENA TErONOTA €iJSa*>ova tc eaea-eai kou aocpararw a[f.a. Koi iJt.aKa,piov — here Warburton concludes : the sentence continues thus; ci^Te TI2 EN HnEIP0I2 EIT EN NH20I2 MA- KAPI02 ON ZHI, KaK€7vov [xeOe^civ r^q TOiavT-^q aei tvx*}^- Epinomis, Bekker, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 374. It is evident that the phrase eV ttoXXSv cW -ycyuvoTa alludes to the doctrine of Plato, that the soul was uniform and uncom- pounded, /-tovoeiS^?, as distinguished from the body which was compounded. Vid. Phsedo, Bekker, pars ii. vol. iii. p. 50. 76 elementary principles of grammar, a far more hum- ble, yet more necessary instrument in the investi- gation of ancient learning. And if he had pur- sued his inquiry to the end of the sentence, he would have observed that the words immediately following the part quoted could hardly fail to con- vey the notion of that personal consciousness for the denial of which he appeals to the passage as a testimony. It is perhaps unnecessary to dwell longer on this sentence ; for there is some reason to doubt whether the Epinomis was written by Plato. The Epistles appealed to in favour of a double sense are generally the 2d, the 7th, and the 13th. The meaning of the seventh has been before alluded to. The second contains a kind of cipher, expressive of the Deity, written with the view^ as Plato himself declares, that if the letter miscarried either by land or sea, the reader into whose hands it should chance to fall might not understand the import, a precaution not altogether unnecessary if we recollect the polytheism of the times, and the fate of Socrates his master: the words are these: ^^pacrreov ^^ aoi ^/ alviy^^av, iv av ri tj '^eXrog vj TTOVTOV Pj yvjg h irTv^oug TrdOvj, o avayvovg fjurj yvco. ^d^e yap ej^e/. Uepi tov wavTWv ^aaiXea iravr ecrri kou eKeivov eveKa iravTa, Kai €Keho aiTiov airoivTcov tZv KaXwv. ^evrepov ^ Bekker, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 403. 77 ^€ v€p) TO, '^evrepa, koi rplrov vep] ra rptra. This pas- sage is distinguished by a peculiarity of style which awakens strong suspicions against its being genuine. The founder of the Academy is mystical, but he seldom gives utterance to his mysticism in this kind of language. It will be observed also, that there is a difference of construction between the former part of the sentence irep). rov iravTm ^aai- Aea, and the two concluding clauses. In the first instance the Tre/?/ is made to refer to the person, in the latter to the thing. But to enter into any. in- vestigation as to the genuineness of the passage would involve a critical discussion on the general character of Plato's Epistles. And though the de- cision of the question might have some weight in determining the meaning we attach to the words before us, the theory of a double sense would not be in the least affected by such a considera- tion. For whether genuine or not, they were in- tended to convey obscurely one sense only; and to those who did not understand them they would have no signification at all. If we suppose the sentence spurious, it was probably interpolated by those who wished to represent Plato as teaching doctrines equivalent to the Christian revelation of the Trinity ; if really written by the philosopher, an interpretation must be sought accordant with the acknowledged principles conveyed in his works, 78 in which the Trinity is certainly not to be found ^. The account of creation, given in the Timseus, will furnish a probable explanation. The clause wepi Tov TrdvTuv (Saa-iXea may be considered as alluding to the chief Deity, Creator and Sovereign of all things : the second, who has secondary objects committed to his charge, may be referred to the universe : the third Intelligence, who has a third department allotted, was perhaps intended to de- signate man himself, whose formation and final destiny, as of a being distinguished for piety and wisdom, Plato describes with great pomp and dif- fuseness, and who, in the language of ancient phi- losophers, was often represented as a type of the world ^. It is true that Eusebius refers the whole passage to the blessed Trinity, and censures the interpretation of the Platonists^, who explain it by that favourite system which they invented for themselves of the Jirst God, the Father of all things ; the second Deity, the i^^rnxiovpyog ; and the *^ An account of the supposed Platonic Trinity will be found in Cudworth, lib. i. c. 4. p. 406. ® [AlKpOKOa-fAOq, f TavTot ol TOV TlKaTuiva ^tacracfyeTv ntdpuy.evot iir) tov irpuTov Seov avdyova-iVy ini re to ^evTepov oitiov, kou Tphov t^v tov Koa-fAov ypvxrjVf 0eev TpiTOV Ko.) avTrjv opC^o^cvoi elvai. ol Se ye 0e«o« Koyoi t^v ouylav kou fAdKupiav Tpidla.. k. t. X. Eusebius, Praeparat. Evangel, lib. xi. cap. 20. Vide also lib. xi. cap. 17. where the passage is again cited in an extract from Plotinus. 79 third, the soul of the world. But it must be re- membered that the bitter opposition of the one party to Christianity, and the injudicious argu- ments of the other in its favour, render the testi- mony of both on such a subject of little value. With regard to the sentence in the 13th Epistle, in which the writer professes to give a key to ex- pressions which he might make use of respecting the name of the Deity, rvjg fxh yap a-irovlaia^ 'Etho-to- \Yjg 0EOS «/?%€/, 0EOI ^6 ryjg ?Trov, it may be suffi- cient to observe, that the reason before alluded to, viz. the fear lest his letters should miscarry, would account for the adoption of such an expedient. These words, notwithstanding the testimony of Eusebius§^ in their favour, can furnish no proof either of a double sense in Plato's writings, or of his belief in the unity of the Godhead, for it is un- deniable that in his works the terms Seo^ and 0eoi are used indiscriminately ^. E. In considering the opinions of the ancient phi- losophers respecting the absorption of the soul after death into the one Spirit of the universe, it is important to keep in view the distinction of the g Praeparat. Evangel, lib. xi. cap. 13. '' Socrates uses the terms Godhead and the Gods without distinction in his works generally. Aristipps Briefti, Wieland, book i. p. 114. 80 several schools, and not to cite passages from M. Antoninus or Seneca as illustrative of the doctrines of all, but as confined in their application to that sect only of which the writers were members. The truth may briefly be stated thus: Plato, if the testimony of his own writings can be relied on, never entertained the notion that death brought with it the extinction of individual consciousness. Of Aristotle the opinions are more dubious ; yet there is nothing in his works which, if well considered, ought to destroy the positive testimony given in the Ethics of his belief that the dead are affected by the fortunes of their living friends *. Of Pythagoras^ there is no positive evidence by which we can absolutely determine his notions on the subject. The most distinguished philosophers among the Stoics differed from each other. Antoninus and Epictetus avowedly maintained the absorption of the human soul at its separation from the body into the Soul of the world, and the extinction of consciousness ; and it appears from some passages in the Epistles of Seneca ^ that he was of the same ' Ethics, lib. i. c. ii. ^ Tennemann Geschichte der Philosophic, s. 94. Brucker, Hist. Crit. Phil. p. 1039. ^ Brucker, pp. 951, 952, 953. Senecae Consolatio ad Mar- ciam, cap3i9. conf. cap. 25. Epist. 54. Mors est, non esse. Id quale sit, jam scio : hoc erit post me quod ante me fuit. 81 opinion; though at other times he dilates most admirably on the happiness to be enjoyed after death in the society of the gods. The prevailing doctrine of the sect seems to have been, that the souls of the virtuous and philosophical would be- come inhabitants of the stars, and exist till the periodical conflagration of the universe"^; but that those of the wicked would endure only for a cer- tain interval, and then be dispersed into the air. Cleanthes, however, and some others, maintained that all equally, the bad as well as the good, would survive till this revolution of things. The Epicureans disbelieved altogether that the soul survived the body. The middle and new Academy and the sceptics cannot be said to have had any belief, for they had no fixed opinions at all. At the risk of appearing tedious, I shall venture a few more observations on the different senses in which the doctrine of the Anima Mundi was held Quseris, quo jaceas post obitum loco Quo non nata jacent. Seneca tragicus. ^ T»|v Ze ■tpvx^v yeiyYjT^v re (p6aprv)v "kiyovciv' ovk evOvt; Se tov a-w- jtxaro? aTTCcXXayeTa-ay cf)d€lp€(r6ai, aXX' eitifJ-iv^iv rivaq ^povovq KaB' kav- Euseb. Praep. Evang. lib. xv. cap. 20. Cicero, Tusc. Quaest. lib. i. 32. Diog. Laertius,- lib. vii. p. 291. edit. 1570. G 82 by the different sects. The notion appears to have prevailed at an early period in Asia and Egypt, and it was from this latter country, pro- bably, that it was introduced into Greece, and be- came subject to various modifications as it passed through the several schools. " The opinions of Orpheus, before Greek phi- losophy was yet formed into a system, according to the most favourable supposition, were, that God was originally connected with matter,' but that he expelled it from him, and that what was before one nature was divided into two ; yet at the same time he does not appear to have altogether eman- cipated the Deity of his belief from the mass of matter which he pervaded and guided. ^ The no- tions of the Ionic school afterwards were probably not very different from this, till the time of Anax- agoras, who entertained nobler and more elevated views of the divine Mind than his predecessors p. " The opinions attributed to Orpheus seem to have been, that the world was an emanation from God ; and Brucker also thinks that he held this efflux of matter to be a part of God : this has however been disputed : " Deum ante mundi- " tum conditum cum chao infinite copulatum fuisse et ita con- *'junctum ut omnia continuerit. Expulisse vero Deum ex " sinu suo materiam." Brucker^ pars ii. lib. i. cap. i. p. 390. ° Brucker, pars ii. lib. i. pp. 470 — 490. Tennemann. Spe- culation der lonier. P Ka) TcpwTO^ iri vAji vovv iitiO'Trja'iy — itdvra %f'fiiAot.ia, rjv 6[a,qv eiTa 88 He taught that the essence of God had never been united with matter, and was now totally distinct from it; at the same time that he pervaded all things, and set them in order ; a belief not very far removed from the Christian doctrine of the omnipresence. According to Cudworth, Pythagoras held nearly the same sentiments as those above ascribed to Orpheus : but Brucker combats this opinion, and degrades his philosophy to pure atheism or Spino- zism ^. The fact is, that the treatises from which N0T2 iXOuv avra h€Ko<ry,r)(T€' irctpo koi vovq iireKX^Br}. Diog. Laert. in Anaxag. p. 51. edit. 1570. Idem, proosmiuni, p. 2. NOTN Kai 6(Qv Tiparot; e'Kay<xyo[/.€VO(; ttj KCffiioitmc/L. ThemJstiuS, quoted by Cudworth, p. 380. Noi/^ MEMIKTAI ovlein ^p'^ixart' aXka. (Aovoq avroq icf) iavrov eVr/v. Anaxagoras in Simplicio. Comment. Aristot. Phys. lib. i. p. 33. T7J<; 8e Kivrja-euq kou tvj? y^vea-iuq aiTiov iirea-Trja-c tov NOTN 6 'Ava- ^ayopacq. Simplicius, p. 1 2. *il^ apa N0T2 cVxiv 6 ^taK0<T[A.3]/ re koI ivdvruv aniot;. Socrates speaking of Anaxagoras, Plato, Phsedo, Bekker, p. 85. Aperta simplexque mens. Cicero de Natura Deorum lib. i. c. II. Academ. Quaestionum lib. iv. c. 37. Qua senlentia proxime ad Christlanorum dogma accesserit, qui Deum docent per res omnes commeare ut cum nulla tamen ullo modo misceatur. Brucker^ pars ii. lib. ii. cap. i. p. 507. ^ Qualis ille Deus Pythagoricus, nempe ignis mundi sub- tilissimus. Brucker, p. 1077. That he held an incorporeal Deity, distinct from the world, is a thing not questioned by any Cudworth, p. 21. Vide Aristot. de Anima, e^aadv xive? avrZv y^rv^qv uvai rd iv Ta depi ^vajAaTUy ol Se to ravra kivovv, lib. i. cap. 2. G 2 84 a knowledge of the Pythagorean principles is to be derived differ from each other. Timaeus the Locrian supports the view taken by Cudworth, but Ocellus Lucanus asserts that the world was neither created nor arranged ^ having had no ori- gin, and destined to have no end : and in another passage he seems to consider it as the Deity and the Cause of all things. The Eleatic school iden- tified God with the world. ^ Plato refined upon the doctrines of Pythagoras, and taught the more elevated philosophy of Anaxagoras, in separating the supreme Deity from matter : and though he makes a divinity of the law of nature, by assign- ing a divine Intelligence or Soul to the world, who guides and directs it to artificial ends, he ' AoK£7 yap (aoi to irav avaXeOpdJ/ eivai kcu ayivtirov aei re yap ^v Kou €<rrai. Ocellus Lucanus, Gale, Opusc. Mythol. cap. i. j). 506. edit. 1688. *0 Se ye K02M02, atrio^ i<m to?(J aKKoiq rov eivcci kcu rov crw^e- a-Bai, KOU Tov avroTeh^ elvoci. p. 5^0* Conf. p. 531. Taq hpi^€iq rnO TOT 0EOT 8iSo/A6va?— /cafi' eVacrToy, a.vaMki\pa<xev O 0EO2. Vide also Justin Martyr, Briicker, * Timaeus, passim. Alcinous, as interpreter of Plato's doctrines, gives the fol- lowing description of the Deity : nax^/j 8e cVti tS alnoii elvcxt itavruv KOU ko(T[a,€7v tov ovpoiviov vovv kou t^v x/'i^X^v tov Ko<Ty,ov itpoq iav- Tov KOU itpoq rotq iavrov vovjo-e*^. Kara yap t^v eavrov B0TAH2IN ifATt€irXiqK€ TfdvTa iavTov, rvjv ypv^^jy tou Koa-f^ov iireyeipaq Ka) elq iaviov iT[i(rrp€xl/aq rov vov ainviq atrioq iitdpxav. oq Koa-f/.'/jOelq vtio rov •narpoq haK0<rfx€7 avfAiraa-av ^vtriv iv r^Se r^ KOiTfjicc. Alcinous, cap. lO. 85 never confounds this secondary god with the one first Cause and Creator of all things. In the works of Aristotle, few as the indications are which they afford of his opinions on the sub- ject, it is not impossible to discover that he does not confound the Deity with the universe ^ In the Politics he clearly marks the distinction be- tween the two ideas, and in his metaphysical works, the same distinction may be traced. Among the followers of Plato in the Academy, no important deviation from his system is to be perceived^. The statements of Xenocrates and Polemo are far from being irreconcileable with the principles inculcated by the founder of the school. Into the doctrines of the middle and new Academy it is unnecessary to enter, because, as ' Aristot. Pol. lib. vii. cap. 3. 2%oX^ yap av O 0EO2 e%ot KaKuq Koi nA2 O K02M02 0*5 ovk tltrh i^anepiKOti irpd^eK; ntapa. Tccq ol- Kelaq Tccq avTuv. Vid. also Metaphys. lib. xiv. cap. 7. in which the Deity is said to be aiho^y axtvijTO?, Ki-xfiDpia-fA-ivoq rZv ala-OrjrZv, ufXeprjq Kou ahaipeToq, — De Coelo, lib. ii. cap. I. In which Ari- stotle argues, that if the Deity were confounded with the uni- verse, he would have the fate of Ixion. " Brucker, pp. 738. 742. Cudworth, Intellect. Syst. cap. 4. sect. 24. p. 418. Speusippus autem et Xenocrates qui prirai Platonis rationem auctoritatemque susceperant et post hos Po- lemo, et Crates unaque Grantor in Academia congregati dili- genter ea quae a superioribus acceperant, tuebantur. Cicero, Academ. Qucest. lib. i. cap. 9. G 3 86 was before remarked, they virtually made it their principle to have no established system ^, and they are therefore justly classed by Warburton with professed Pyrrhonists. The Peripatetics by no means uniformly ad- hered to the tenets of their master, and one of them, Strato Lampsacenus y, is distinguished for having plunged into a depth of atheism beyond that of any other philosophical teacher, and to have inculcated more degrading notions respecting the Deity than those of the Stoics ; for he main- tained that there was no other God than a kind of plastic life in nature,' without sense or con- sciousness. The Stoics, like Strato, considered God and matter to form one nature inseparably united, but they maintained the existence (if such a dif- ference between these two forms of atheism can clearly be conceived) of a kind of divine reason, ^ Opinabor was their professed principle: Qusero enim, quid sit, quod comprehendi possit — Incognito nimirum assen- tiar, id est, opinabor, Cic. Academ. Qucest. lib. iv. 35. y A short account of Strato's life, but not of his doctrines, is given in Diog. Laert. and his works also are enumerated : he succeeded Theophrastus in his school, and had been preceptor to Ptolemy Philadelphus, Diog. Laert. p. 186. He is described by St. Augustine as something between an atheist and a theist. For his opinions, vide Cudworth, lib. i. cap. 3. sect. 4. p. 107. Brucker, pars ii. lib. ii. cap. 7. pp. 845 — 847. Cicero de Na- tura Deorum, lib. i. cap. 13. Academ. Qusest. lib. i. cap. 9. lib. iv. cap. 38. ,87 divina ratio toti mundo insita ^, while their rivals above alluded to allowed the divinity of plastic force only. The distinction must be considered more verbal than real % if we remember that the god of the Stoics, notwithstanding the magnificent language in which they sometimes extol him, was corporeal made up of fire and liquid ether, finite, inseparably united to matter, and subject to its control, without free-will, and apparently without personality. They taught that the soul of man was a part of the divine essence, a Trvevfxa evBepixov ^, that it partook of the same qualities, was an ema- nation from it, and, after the destined period, would be resolved into it ^, when the eternal law of fate. ^ Zeno autem naturalem legem divinam esse censet. Aliis autem libris rationem quandani, per omnem naturam rerum pertinentem ut divinam esse affectam (divina vi affectam) putat. Cicero, de Nafura Deorum, lib. i. cap. 14. ratione mun- dus utitur. Animans est mundus composque rationis. lib. ii. cap. 8. ^ Brucker, parsii. lib. ii. cap. 9. p. 937. Tennemann, Stoiker, s. 121. Diog. Laert. lib. vii. De Natura Deorum, Cicero, lib. i. lib. ii. cap. 14, 15. Academ. Qusest. lib. iv. cap. 41. Cudworth, lib. i. cap. 4. p. 419. Eusebius, Praeparat. Evangel, lib. xv. cap. 15, 16. S. Epiphanii Responsio ad Epist. Acacii etPauli, p. 7. Adv. Haereses. lib. i. 5. ^ Diog. Laert. lib. vii. p. 291. ^ 'ApcV/cet Se ro7<; upca^vraToTq rav ocno Trjq atpea-euq rocvTi^q isaepov- (xBat TcavTo. kccto. •mpiotovq tivaq raq fJt.iyKrraq ilq itvp aWepShcq avaXvo- lA,ivuv •ttdvTm. Eusebius, Prsep. Evangel, lib. xv. cap. 18. Idem rx4 88 from similar principles, would again produce simi- lar combinations ; a new universe would arise from its efementary fire, destined to become in the de- velopement of all its successive phenomena, phy- sical and moral, whether trifling or important, the exact counterpart of the old : from the eruption of volcanoes, or the convulsion of empires, to the smallest blade of grass, and the most minute acci- dent in the character and fortunes of every indi- vidual that before existed. ^ The opinions of Epicurus are too well known to require examination. The Romans were copy- ists of the Greek philosophers, rather than in- ventors of independent systems, and in the inter- pretation of their sentiments they are frequently superficial, and not always to be relied on. In the time of Cicero the philosophy of Epicurus, of the Stoics, and of the old and new Academy, was most studied. Cicero himself, next to the works of the new Academy, his own sect, was most conversant in the writings of the Stoics. In speaking of Aristotle he observes, that his philosophy was little read even by the learned ^. It appears that those cap. 19. Diog. Laert. lib. vii. p. 284. edit. 1570. Warburton, book iii. sect. 3. vol. ii. p. 72. Vide also Origen contra Cel- sum, lib. V. p. 244, 245. edit. Spencer. 1677. Even Socrates's worn out clothes were to appear again in this regeneration. ^ Cicero de Natiira Deorum lib. i. ^ Rhetor autem ille magnus haec Aristotelica se ignorare re- 89 Romans in general who believed in a supreme Deity identified him with the Soul of the universe. ^ Varro undoubtedly had no other notion of Ju- piter, and he may be considered as representing the principles prevalent in his time. The later Platonists of the school of Ammonius were lost in the dreams of oriental speculation. Plotinus, like Spinoza, afterwards seems to have maintained that God was no existence himself, but the cause of all existence ^, and that matter, soul, and God were inseparable, and had been so from all eternity. It might be a subject of curious investigation to fol- spondit. Quod quidem minime sum admiratus eum philoso- phum rhetori non esse cognituni, qui ab ipsis philosophis, prae- ler admodum paucos, ignoraretur. Topica, cap. i . f Dicit ergo Varro adhuc de natural! theologia praeloquens, Deum se arbitrari esse Animam Mundi quam Graeci vocant KoV/xoi/ et hunc ipsuin mundum esse Deum. Augustin, Civ. Dei, lib. vii. cap. 6. A very interesting account of the theology of Varro is given in Dr. Ireland's learned treatise on Paganism and Christianity compared, chap. 5. e Plotinus's notion in lib. ix. Ennead. 6. so far as an ordi- nary mind may be permitted to approach such sublime ab- stractions, appears to be, that the first original principle is No- thing, yet the cause of all things ; having neither quantity nor quality ; neither soul nor reason ; is neither in motion nor in tranquillity ; is neither unity nor number ; neither in space nor in time ; without thought or will ; yet the act of thinking, and the cause of all thought ; the smallest, yet the largest j the good, the perfect. 90 low up the question through the philosophical sects of more modern times, to examine how far the system of Spinoza accords with the doctrine taught in some of the ancient schools, and to pursue the inquiry even to our own day, through the most recent philosophical systems, and ascertain to what extent the charge of pantheism is justly to be im- puted to them ^. But a superficial view of such subjects seldom fails to produce or strengthen er- roneous opinions, and an accurate research would require the labours of a life. It appears then, that, of the different schools of antiquity, some held the soul of the world to be the chief God, some a secondary Deity; of the former, some believed the universal Soul to pass through matter unmixed, some to be united and form only one nature with it ; and of these again, some considered the corporeal Deity to be a kind of divine reason without personality, others a spe- cies of vegetative life, called the plastic force of nature. Is it too much to infer, from an examina- tion of such unintelligible theories ', that the in- ventors and supporters had no clear conceptions of their own meaning, and that principles like these ^ Die neueste philosophie nahert sich dem system des Spi- uoza von mehreren Seiten an. Tennemann, art. Spinoza. ' Exposui fere non philosophorum judicia sed delirantium sorania. Cicero de Natura Deorum lib. i. cap. i6. 91 had very little influence on the practical belief of mankind ? And degrading as the picture is which such systems exhibit of the weakness of human reason, it is at least a subject of satisfaction to per- ceive, that the two great master minds of anti- quity, Aristotle and Plato, never cherished those low and debasing views of the Divinity which in- ferior teachers ventured to inculcate. With that humility which never fails to accompany talent of the highest order, they both express themselves unable to penetrate the darkness and difficulty which involves such questions as those respecting the divinre essence and the nature of the soul ; and Plato more than once recommends prayer to the Deity, that the understanding may be strength- ened and enlightened ^, G. This must be the feeling of every man con- versant with metaphysical systems. If we trace the history of philosophical speculation from its commencement to the present hour ^5 we shall ^ Plato, Timaeus, p. 22. Aristot. de Anima, lib. i. ' ^iXo<TO(pia ydip roi eVriv, u XuKpoirei;, xctfUv, a.v riq avrov fAerpiuq oc'tpvjrcn iv T^ ^XtKt^t" idv Se Tcepanepci} tov Seovro^ ivhiccrpt-ipyj, ^laipOopa ruv av6puituv. Gorgias, Bekker, pars ii. vol. i. p. 83. These words, originally used by Plato with a diiferent object in view, will apply to the present question. 92 observe the same forms of atheism and pantheism reviving in different ages, and supported and com- bated by nearly the same arguments. It would seem as if speculation on its wildest wing was still condemned to soar within prescribed limits, and to pursue the same circling flight. The most subtle and profound thinkers have arrived at little certainty upon subjects of abstract reasoning. Nor are the wild and dangerous theories that have sometimes been adopted, to be attributed to pure malice and malignity, at enmity with the good of mankind, but to a restless desire of know- ledge upon questions in which knowledge in our present state can never be attained, and to a spirit of intellectual ambition which allows of no limita- tion to the exercise of human thought. Hence it is that ancients and moderns, deists, atheists, and Christians, men of immoral and moral life, of pious and impious feelings, have built up philo- sophical systems equally unintelligible. And some of these have been established upon principles of which it would be very difficult to shew the fal- lacy, yet upon which no man, not even the in- ventor of the system, would or could act for a single moment. In seeking to become more, we pay the penalty of our folly, and become less than man. Hume declared that he was afraid to think, on account of the conclusions to which he might 93 come, and the barriers of separation he might create between himself and the rest of mankind. This feeling should have taught him that the pur- suit of truth, properly conducted, could never lead to such a separation, and that there was other and stronger evidence than abstract reasoning alone "\ Reid was unable to refute Berkeley's principles, till he appealed to the common belief and conduct of mankind. And as a rule for our own decision in judging of the conviction of a writer, when his philosophy is opposed to his common feelings and language ", it will be much safer to depend upon the latter, than upon in- ferences from his metaphysical creed ^. Anaxa- goras is said to have maintained that snow was black, in order to preserve his consistency as a "^ Qui nondum ea, quae multis post annis tractari coepissent, physica didicissent, tantum sibi persuaserant quantum natura admonente cognoverant. Haec ita sentimus natura duce, nulla ratione nullaque doctrina. Cic. Tusc. Qucest. lib. i. cap. 13. nSv yap OTtep \ay.€v Kpemov vj kut'' airohel^iv tovto kocto, koiv^v tvvoiav iV/Acv. Origen de Aniina, p. 618. ed. Paris. 161 8. La Nature confond les Pyrrhoniens, et la raison confond les dogmatistes. Pensees de Pascal, art. I. " I do not wish by this statement to set up feeling in religion above reason, but above metaphysical and abstract reasoning. In an argument of reason our natural feelings and desires, to- gether with conscience, should form a part of it. " Anaxagoras nivem nigram dixit esse; ferres me si ego idem dicerem ? Cicero Academ. Qucest. lib. iv. cap. 23. 94 reasoner ; but who will imagine that he was sin- cere ? The following brief sketch of the moral sys- tems supported by Aristotle and Plato may be of service in determining the question whether the ancients generally believed that truth and utility did not coincide. Notwithstanding the subtlety of their speculative discussions, in which the distinctions and divisions are often merely verbal, it was evidently the object of both phi- losophers to elevate, and as far as possible perfect, the mind and faculties of man. They both main- tained that the happiness which nature had taught the desires of the soul to aim at, as its ultimate end and object^ would consist in the perception of truth. Plato considered this truth to be altogether intellectual and speculative. Hence it is that he enjoins the purest moral precepts ; the entire sub- jugation, or rather annihilation of the passions?, not because moral virtue was a direct means to happiness, but because the purification of the soul was necessary to the perception of intellectual truth, in which alone human felicity would be found. For the same reason he commands the extinction of imagination also ^ ; it is a faculty which cheats and deludes us with the image of P Vid. Phaedo, passim. 'i Republic, book iii. x. 1 95 truth instead of the reality. Poetry and painting and all the fine arts are to be banished, as obscur- ing and impeding the exercise of reason in aspir- ing after its substantial good. But though our nature while on earthy by thus endeavouring to destroy passion and imagination, might make gradual progress towards the enjoyment of happi- ness and the perception of truth, their full per- fection could never be attained till the soul was emancipated from the body, when the shadow of knowledge would be changed into the substance, and we should see essential truth as it really is, uniform, unchangeable, and eternal. Aristotle, on the contrary, does not consider intellectual truth alone as the only knowledge to which the human faculties are to be trained and directed. Regarding man as a being possessed of passion, imagination, and reason, he provides for the due exercise and perfection of them all. Truth with him is not one and indivisible, but distinguished into truth in morals, truth in the fine arts, and truth in questions of science and wisdom, purely abstract and speculative. These different kinds of knowledge are not inseparably united and confounded^. He who possesses that moral perfection which teaches him to think, feel, and act on all occasions as becomes a virtuous •^ Aristot. Ethics, lib. iii. iv. v. vi. 96 man, a good citizen, or a friend in the ordinary intercourse of society; he who habitually sees with the intuitive eye of taste the beautiful and the true in architecture, sculpture, and painting, may yet want that intellectual excellence em- ployed in perceiving abstract truth. Refined and masterly as this theory unquestionably is, and more just and better adapted than Plato's to the wants and capacities of man, it is still inferior to that of the rival system in one striking and im- portant feature. Aristotle (whatever were his sentiments respecting a future state) seems to propose the truth, which he teaches us to pursue, as belonging in its perfection to our present con- dition, as if the powers of the soul could here be fully developed; whereas Plato uniformly repre- sents it as a foretaste of knowledge, whose fulness was yet to come ; a system to be commenced on earth, but to be perfected in heaven ^. While speaking on the doctrines of these philo- sophers, it may perhaps be allowable to make an observation on a difficult passage in another part of Aristotle's works, not entirely unconnected with the subject, the meaning of which is still dis- puted among critics. I allude to the definition * Or rather in some better part of the earth, (7^.) This pre- sent habitation of ours, according to Plato, being only one out of many divisions of it. Vid. Phsedo, ad fin. 97 of tragedy in the Poetics, in which he insists upon its moral tendency. Plato had banished poets from the republic, because he considered the images which they presented as calculated to strengthen the passions of pity and fear, and thus oppose that perfect KaBapatgy or purification of the soul, which he believed to constitute the excel- lence of our nature. Aristotle, it is probable, had this theory in his eye when he declared that the pity and fear excited by the scenic representations, so far from strengthening the passions, would have a tendency to weaken them, and purify the soul from their more powerful and pernicious effects. Plato teaches that the pleasure resulting from tragedy would be injurious to our moral consti- tution. Aristotle therefore felt it necessary to declare that this pleasure would have a directly contrary effect, and become an instrument of vir- tue : and thus he has gone a little out of his way in adding the moral effects of tragedy to a defini- tion already sufficiently complete. Many authors have done themselves little cre- dit in the attempt to degrade the character of Socrates by bringing together calumnies founded upon the representation of later writers, in whom little confidence is to be placed. Those who have H 98 examined his opinions, as recorded by his own disciples, will understand the bold expressions of an illustrious modern scholar, "Sancte Socrates, " ora pro nobis." The vices attributed to him are disproved by the testimony of Alcibiades in the very treatise, the Convivium of Plato, most fre- quently cited to establish the contrary opinion: and it should be recollected, that the immoral sentiments contained in this treatise are put into the mouth of Aristophanes, and are censured by Socrates himself as evidences of a debased mind. In other parts of Plato's writings the same vices are reprobated : thus in the first book of the Laws the TO Tta^a. (pva-iv To\{xy}[j.a is an expression in which Socrates strongly marks the infamy of the crime. The latter part of the Convivium may be con- sulted, from which the following sentences are selected: Alcibiades, describing his reverence for his master, observes, UeTrovSa ^e Trpo^ tovtov [/.ovov av- BpooTTCCv^, ovK av Tig oioiTO ev e/xoi evehai^ to aiayyveaBai OVTIVOVV. Oiog yap 'A^^AXevf eyivero, anuKaaeiev av Tig Kai Bpaa-i^av koi aXXovg, Ka) oiog av UepiKX^g, Kai NeaTopa Ka) ^ AvTYivopa'^^ eia) &e Ka) eTepoi' oiog ^e ovToai yeyove T^v aTOTTiav avSpoi)7rog, Ka) avTog Kai ot Xoryoi avTOv, ovo eyyvg iv evpoi Tig JV^tcov, ovTe tSov vvv ovt€ t»v 7raXai(av, Ov^h 'TTepiTTOTcpov KaTa^e^apdvjKCcg avea-TVjv f/,€Ta S«- * Convivium, Bekker, p. 454. " Bekker, p. 465. 99 Kparovg ^ vj el fxerd iraTpog Kadvjv^ov rj a^e\(f>ov Trpea-jSyri" pov. Vide also Xenophon's Memorabilia, lib. iv. " Sunt quidem inter veteres qui ei objecerunt " pulchritudine Alcibiadis inferior em et juvenum " corruptorem fuisse, qua de causa Aspasia quoque " eum versibus suis traduxit. Sed impudentissi- *' mam banc esse calumniam non solum tota vitae " Socratis ratio loquitur, sed et Aristophanis silen- " tium probat." JSrucker, pars ii. lib. ii. cap. 2t. p. 539. The opinion of Wieland, a man extremely well read in the philosophers of antiquity, is of some value on such a subject : " Socrates was a vir- " tuous man in the highest and completest sense " of the word ; in every relation of life he was a " model for all men." Wielancfs Aristippus, p. 75. vol. i. H. The figurative representations in the Phsedrus will be read with different feelings by different minds ; images that are ridiculous and absurd in the eyes of some, will appear to others pregnant with beauty and truth, in the same manner as honey and poison may be extracted from the same flowers. It should be remembered that Plato him- " Bekker, p. 461. H 2 100 self does not propose his allegories of the souly to be understood in a literal sense, but as serving to convey, through the medium of sensible images dnd similitudes, some notion of that spiritual es- sence whose real nature is unintelligible ; and he has evidently attempted to explain the imperfec- tions of the soul, in its present union with body, by a narrative of its fortunes in an earlier and un- compounded state. It is not easy to follow him in his lofty speculations, nor to overtake " the " winged chariots of the gods," which he so fan- cifully describes ; but the general impression that remains upon the reader's mind is nearly to the following effect : ^The soul at its first creation was perfect, and winged, and sublime in its contemplations ; but, unable to preserve so high a flight, it descended to earth, and its wings fell off, and perished through the evil with which it had become connected. The desire of man upon earth should be to recover these lost wings by meditations on the good^ the true, and the celestial^. y Hep* Se T^5 )^ka^ aiJiTj? wSe X^Kreov, olov [mv e<rT<, TravTij itavTccq Plato, Phaedrus, p. 39. Bekker, pars i. vol. i. ^ Phaedrus, Bekker, pp. 39. 43. pars i. vol. i. ^ One of the fathers of the church has the same kind of ex- pression, teaching us that it is the business of man, " to give 101 The soul is like a winged chariot, borne along^ by two steeds, and guided by a charioteer. The steeds of the celestial intelligences, deities of a higher nature than man, are both good, and di- rected by the supreme Charioteer, who arranges the order and beauty of all things ; the car passes lightly forward in its course. Each intelligence performs its appointed work, enjoys the contem- plation of truth, and visits regions of happiness. But the steeds in the winged chariot, destined to become man's soul, are one good, the other bad ; they urge it forward (like our desires now^) in different directions, the one elevating it to heaven, the other depressing it to earth, and often refuse the guidance of the Charioteer. I. The poetic colouring with which Plato adorns his sentiments is frequently considered a proof of his insincerity. No one can deny that his mind was essentially poetical, that in the highest sense of the word he was a poet ; for his constant aspi- ration is after some nobler and purer life than any . this earth can supply. The warmth of his genius pervades and elevates every subject which he " wings to the soul," koI apiraaai Kocy^AOV ku) twvai 0€a. Vid. Leighton's Works, vol. iv. p. 205. ^ like our desires now'] This application is not made by Plato. H 3 102 touches, and imparts an energy and beauty to his descriptions which no poet ever surpassed. But is the sentiment less true because it is strongly coloured? The ornament may be fiction, but the feeling itself, and the foundation of the feeling, is truth ^ ; and the voice of nature speaks more com- monly its real belief in metaphor and allusion, than in measured and artificial language. Those elevated descriptions of the future world, the ra- diant visions w^hich he creates in order to embody his glowing anticipations of happiness to come, prove only the intenseness of the feelings with which he cherished this hope of immortality. Hence his imaginary paradise, with its purple and golden atmosphere of inconceivable brilliancy and clearness, in which all the rocks are of jasper and emerald "^ ; and his assertions, that the trees and flowers, which nature pours forth in such profu- *^ Aristotle observes, in his Rhetoric, lib. iii. 7, that poetical expressions are natural to men under the influence of emotion, dpixoTTii Xcyovri iraOvjriKai;. If the truth of this precept had been kept in mind, Shakspeare would not have been so often cen- sured for putting metaphors and images into the mouths of his characters when strongly excited. ^ Vid. Phsedo, pp. 112 — 120; also Republic, book x. pp. 502 — 516. The prophet Isaiah predicts the future glory of Jerusalem in images equally bold : Behold, I will lay thy stones with fair colours^ and lay thy foundations with sapphires. And I will make thy windows of agates, and thy gates of car- buncles. Isaiah liv. 11, 12. 108 sion for man's gratification on earth, are but faint shadows of those trees and flowers and unfading archetypes of beauty, which yield fruit and fra- grance in some better part of the universe. If he declare that in a retreat like this the souls of the virtuous will enjoy in another state of being, not the sensuality of Mahomet's paradise, but that per- fect felicity which will result from the perception of substantial truth ; is he to be considered at once as a man who disbelieved entirely in personal con- sciousness after death, and consequently in all re- compense of the good ? If, again, he describe the dark and tumultuous waves of Cocytus as destined to bear the wicked in their bosom round the vast circle of the universe, rolling on and tossing them unceasingly, and resounding in their ears through all the ages of eternity ; is he to be regarded as one who in his heart believed that the retribution of the wicked in every sense of the word was a fable, an ingenious contrivance of the legislator to curb the passions of mankind ? His conceptions of paradise were probably derived from traditions re- specting the garden of Eden, from which our first parents were excluded, and which, in the oriental imagery of the book of Job^ appears to be alluded to as the place whose stones are sapphires, and *= Job xxviii. 5. 6. Mr. Peters on the book of Job, p. 397. Eusebius Praep. Evangel, lib. xi, c. 36. 37. 38. H 4 104 whose dust is gold : and his representations of the punishment reserved for the incurably wicked might have arisen from traditions^ respecting that universal deluge in which the whole guilty race of man once perished. K. Aristotle's treatise de Anima is extremely per- plexed and obscure ^. It is not so much a meta- physical, as a physical work, the discussions con- cerning mind are principally confined to its opera- tions while in connection with body; and those who expect to find in it any opinions stated posi- tively as to the destination of the human soul in another life will be entirely disappointed ^\ Aware himself of the nature of the subject, the philoso- pher observes, at the very commencement, that it is of all things most difficult to obtain clear and satisfactory evidence \ In defining soul in general to be a habit consti- tuting the essential perfection of a natural body^, f Mr. Peters, pp. 359. 360. 371. 372. S OvT€ (f>va-iK7} aTTA&J? oIt€ f/.€Ta ra (f)V(rtKa, >j ncp) ypv^^q Oeapia. Simplicii Prooemium de Anima Aristot. p. i . ^ OCSeva (paiverat irepi t^^ rZv ovpaviav 4'^X^i iroiovfAevoq Xoyov. Idem, p. I. Prooemium. ' Hdvrv} Be Ka\ ntavru^ icrr) iwv ')(jx'kmci)ra/T(jt}v Xa^eiv T<va iclaTtv itipi avT^<;.- De Anima, lib. i. cap. i. ^ 'EyT€Xe%eta ttpur'/} o-cy/xaxo? (pvaiKOV. Lib. ii. Cap. I. The WOrd ENTEAEXEIA is translated by Cicero, Tusc. Qusest. lib. i. c. 10. 105 it would appear at first sight that he considered its existence as inseparable from that of the body which it animates. But in the third book, in which the vovg^ or intelligence of the soul is discussed, and which is divided into active and passive^ the power of actively exercising its functions by think- ing and reasoning, and the capacity of receiving ideas, Aristotle assigns immortality to this intelli^ gence, but denies it memory. It has been dis- puted whether he meant the whole of intelligence to be immortal, or merely the active power. The latter opinion is maintained by Warburton, by Tennemann in his History of Philosophy ^ and has continuata motio : it is frequently used in the sense of actus as opposed to iv hwuixei: the translation I have given will com- prehend the other senses : "Ea-n Se vj [acv vKv] S^va/A^, to Se EIA02 €VTcAe%€ia: it is what constitutes the form or essence of a thing. Vid. Origen. Celebres Opiniones de Anima, p. 628. ed. 161 8. Simplicii Prooemium, p. 2. Towards the end of the first chap-: ter it is observed, that some of the functions of soul may be se- parated from the body because they are not operations essen- tially perfecting any parts of the body : O^ [a.v}v a>X evici ye ovOh KooXvei hoc TO jwyj^eve? elvai aafj^enrog evrcAc^e/a? : thus, though the sight of the eye cannot be separated from the bodily eye, the speculative energy of the soul may be separated from body: irep) he rov vov koI t^<; BeupvjTiK^t; hwdfAeut; ovHeita ^txvepov, aXX' €0iK€ ^pv^yji; yevo^ (tepcv elvoci kou tovto y.ovov ivhexerai XnPIZE20AI KaOd •nep TO aihcv rov (p$aprov. Aristot. de Anima, lib. ii. cap. 2. ^ Tennemann's Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophic, art. Aristotle. Lancaster's Harmony of the Law and the Gos- » pel, p. 431. ' ■ 106 been recently adopted by Mr. Lancaster. It ap- pears that the question, after all, depends upon the signification we attach to the term passive intelli- gence. If Aristotle meant the power which the mind has of receiving ideas through ^avracr/a, which depends upon bodily sensation, it is obvious that this sensation and (pavraaia being destroyed at death, there can be no longer any capacity of receiving ideas through the medium of the same instruments : but, if we understand by the phrase the power of receiving ideas without reference to the mode in which they are conveyed, there is no reason why the passive intelligence should not exist after death "^. Such an interpretation of the fifth and sixth chapters would appear perfectly consistent with the assertion that vov^, or intelli- gence, is immortal, and also with the declaration that the manner of its apprehending while in connection with the body is not so. It may ex- *" Aristotle does not divide the vov<;, or intelligence^ into ac- tive and passive with the precision of his Latin translators, but describes it as operating actively and passively, and he cer- tainly appears to consider these two kinds of operation as im- plied in our very notion of intelligence. The term ita9ririKoq 1/01)5, which we meet with in the sixth chapter, is not used in the fifth, where the functions of intelligence are described, and if it be synonymous with (pavrotaluy is not to be confounded with passive intelligence, as will readily be seen by a comparison of the preceding chapter on <payra<Tia. Aristot. de Anima, lib. iii. cap. 3—6. 107 ercise its active powers of thinking and reasoning, though more quickly and perfectly after death, in the same manner as now; but it cannot apprehend ideas in the same way, viz. through the medium of (pavraa-ia, which depends upon bodily sensation. It does not follow then, because Aristotle denies that the instruments by which the soul energizes while in connection with the body will remain after death, that the soul is to discontinue its energies — that because it is no longer to receive ideas through sensation ", it is to have no ideas at all. For my own part, I do not understand what is meant by the existence of active intelligence after death ", without supposing that its activity is to continue. Active intelligence, inert and with- out consciousness, is a contradiction in terms ; and so far from Aristotle denying consciousness to the soul when separated from the body, as Tenne- mann and others represent him to have done, he speaks in the preceding chapter of its ability in " Origen observes that even many notions which the soul has in its present state, its ideas of the Deity for example, are independent of body; iraivrvj Kcxc^pia-Toci a-wixarot; yj loiavr'^ ivepyeiat Ku) ATTH2 AE TH2 ^^ANTASIAS. Origen, de Anima, p. 640. Does not Aristotle mean that it may receive ideas in another way, when, speaking of the intellect, he observes, AnA0E2 apa Ser Jvai, AEKTIKON AE TOT EIAOTD ? De Anima, lib. iii. c. 5. ° OuTo? vovi; %ft>|5iO-T05, Ka) u(jt.iyy}(;, ku) airaBrj^y THI OT2IAI ON ENEPFEIA. Again, Ov^ ore fAiv vou ore hi ov vo€7. Aristot. dc Anima, lib. iii. cap. 6. 108 this state to speculate upon itself^. It is true, he might mean this consciousness not to be separate and individual, but a part of and absorbed in the consciousness of the one universal Mind; but he has never told us that this was his opinion, (ac- cording to Warburton's gratuitous assumption,) nor P Ka* avTO^ Se avroif Tore ^wdrai voeTv. Aristot. de Anima, lib. iii. cap. 5. Origen. Opiniones de Anima, p. 677. As far as I can understand Aristotle's notion, it appears to be this ; the soul of map is like an unwritten tablet; ypafjLfAarelov a jixvjSfv lit- dpx'^i, lib. iii. cap. 5. The senses exercised upon external ob- jects communicate impressions to phantasia -which retains them, and the intellect speculates and reasons upon the ideas so ob-^ tained. De Anima, lib. iii. c. 3. et 4. At death the senses and the phantasia perish, but the intellect, having no necessary connection with the two former, survives and is immortal. Origen confirms this view of the subject : ^ (aIv cpavraaia tZv irej/re alarQ-^aeuv Several rov(; rintovq. Opiniones de Anima, p. 620. ^avTCtaloc ydf icrriv tj rwv (pavBivrccv (Ttdariq. ta'TVj<n yap iy ainrj ra e^a (pavivra, p. 6 1 9. Again, p. 66 1. Aristotle (he observes) likens the soul to an unwritten tablet, Plato to a written tablet. ^nd in other passages he mentions that Aristotle was aware of the rational soul being separable from body and immortal, and of its capacity in this state for receiving the images of intel- lectual things. Conf pp. 660. 631. It is surely a most un- warrantable inference to argue, because a metaphysical writer declares that the faculties which receive and retain impressions from sensible and external objects perish at death, that he be- lieved the soul in a separate and disembodied state no longer to possess individual consciousness, and to be incapable of having any power of thought whatever apart from the universal Mind. It would appear from the comparison of the unwritten tablet that Locke's theory is not altogether novel. 109 does such a consequence necessarily follow from any assertion in any part of his works. He denies indeed the continuance of memory after death, which he observes is the result of cpavTaa-ia, and, if memory be absent, it may be asked, how can the consciousness of personal identity exist, the loss of which would be fatal to the expectation of future recompense ? But with regard to this conclusion I would venture to remark, that, though memory be excluded, it does not necessarily follow that the knowledge which man obtains or preserves by means of memory, while mind and body are unit- ed, is to cease when they are separated. Aristotle assigns to the Deity consciousness of happiness, apprehension of ideas, and an interest in the con- duct and fortunes of mankind ; and yet, by deny- ing him *^ bodily sensation, virtually denies him me- mory. He has defined memory to be a faint per- ception of past reality : the perception of this re- ality may be conveyed in another way, and more vividly, after death ^ In the Ethics the dead are said to be affected by the fortune of their living friends, yet not affected so far as to have their condition changed by this sympathy, whether they ^ The Epicurean in Cicero accuses Aristotle of depriving the Deity of thought, because he deprived him of body. De Na- tura Deorum lib. i. cap. 13. •■ Aristotle's Ethics, book i. chap. 1 1. 110 are happy or otherwise. It is clear from this pas- sage that the dead are supposed to be conscious of personal identity, and to be sensible of pleasure and pain, and that they are divided into classes, some being happy and others not so ^ But if the happiness of man in this life is not in Aristotle's opinion a capricious gift of the gods, but the re- ward of virtuous actions \ it is not easy to imagine any other circumstances or conditions on which the fortunes of the soul after death could be made to depend. And this consideration would lead us back to the necessity of some sort of future re- tribution which the metaphysical theory we have just examined apparently tended to annihilate. It is surprising, that while almost every other branch of human knowledge has been investigated by Aristotle, how little consideration he has be- stowed upon the question of the soul's immor- tality. It is impossible to speak positively as to his opinions on the subject ; for throughout his vo- luminous works, metaphysical, physical, and moral, we find no sufficient data from which to deduce * This positive opinion can hardly be overthrown by the as- sertion in the third book, that death is most terrible because it is an end, and there appears to be neither good nor evil be- yond. Aristotle's Ethics, book iii. chap. 6. He might speak thus of death, and the fear of death, in the mind of man with- out intending thereby to deny a future state. * Aristotle's Ethics, book i. chap. 9. book x. chap. 8. Ill any certain conclusion. It is probable, from the practical character of his mind, that he was un- willing to indulge in speculations on a question from the discussion of which he could arrive at no clear and accurate knowledge. It is not often that we meet with a more complete example of what the logicians call the petitio principii than the assertions of Warburton respecting the chap- ter we have attempted to discuss. Cudworth had declared it to be obscure, but, says the author of the Legation, " " had that excellent person re- ^' fleeted on the general doctrine of the TO 'EN he " would have found the passage plain and easy." And he sums up his observations in that conve- nient form of words recommended by the ancient sophists and rhetoricians, to silence opposition by alarming the adversary into an idea that his dis- sent will be interpreted as a proof of ignorance : " The learned well know that the Intellectus «^ Agens of Aristotle was the very same with the " Anima Mundi of Plato and Pythagoras." Now, omitting all further inquiry into the correctness of Warburton's representations respecting Plato's creed, it may be sufficient to observe at present, that if the learned have acquired such satisfactory knowledge of the opinions entertained by the Sta- " Divine Legation, lib. iii. sect. 4. vol. ii. p. 112. 112 gyrite on the same subject, it must have been from other sources than his own writings. That Aristotle believed in a ^ Supreme Beings the original Mover of all things, enjoying perfect felicity, and the source of all good, may be abun- dantly proved ; that, besides the Supreme Being, he maintained the existence also of y 07ie intelli- gent Principle (notwithstanding his notion that all the spheres were animated essences) pervading the universe, may be inferred from some expres- sions in his metaphysical works, and from a direct assertion in his Politics. In addition to these, he appears to have considered ^Nature as a third and distinct cause, performing its functions sub- ordinate to and dependent on the two former ; ^ ^a/>tev §e rov Beov elvcci ^£ov ai^iov apia-rov, ua-re ^covj koc) alwv (Tvv- €Xr!? /ca* athot; viidpx^i rS Be^. Metaph. lib. xiv. cap. 7. *H ocpx/j Kot TO TipaTov Tuv ovTcov aKiv^iov K(Xi KO.G' aino. Ibid, cap. 8. Ei [Ml €<rrai izapa. to, al<rdr)Ta aXka, ovk earrcci ap'^fj, ko,) rd^iq, kou y€vi(rtq. Ibid. cap. 10. *0 6eo<f ^0K€7 ro a'lriov Tracrij/ elvai kou dp^"^ riq. Ibid. lib. i. C. 2. TluvTcc l^et rdyaOd Oecx; Kai i<TTiv avTdpKVji;. Magna Moralia, lib. ii. cap. 15. y 2%0A^ yap av o Oeo^ e^Oi KoXaq kou TIAS O K02M02, of? ovk etViv i^uTepiKou Trpale*^ Trapa Tocq o</ce/a^ rdq avTuv. Aristot. Politic, lib. vii. cap. 3. Vide also Metaph. lib. xiv. cap. 8. de Ccelo, lib. ii. cap. 3. Idem, lib. i. cap. 9. ^ *Y.K roioivrv}(; dpoc, dpx^i ijpTvjTa* ovpavot; kou tj ^T2I2. Metaph. lib. xiv. cap. 7. Vide also Phys, lib. ii. cap. i. 113 but he has by no means clearly or consistently explained the peculiar province of each, nor the relation which they bear to the human soul. Ah though therefore it may be allowed that he held the doctrine of the Anima Mundi, he does not seem to have taught it in the fulness of Plato's sense, who confounds it with the law of Nature, and gives a diffuse account of its creation, attri- butes, and operations. This view of his opinions is supported by the authority of ^Eusebius and other fathers of the church, who triumphantly mention the discordance of these great teachers on the subject, as contrasted with the harmony of the inspired writers. It is well known also that the two philosophers were opposed to each other respecting the origin of the world itself: Plato believed that matter in disorder^ was eternal, Aristotle, that matter arranged, or the world, was eternal ; a doctrine which he probably borrowed ^ In Eusebius, Praeparat. Evangel, lib. xv. cap. 12. where an ^extract is given from Porphyry containing an account of Plato's Anima Mundi, the following words occur : Il/jo^ uvhh rovruv ^fMV * Apia-roTikviq ofMXoyitf od yap eivai rrjv <pv<riv i^y^V 'fcei ra irept y^v in:o [Aia(; (pva-ea^ hoiKeia-Oaif &C. ^ De Coelo, lib. i. cap. 10. Idem, lib. ii. cap. i. Cicero, Tusc. Quaest. lib. i. cap. 29. Eusebius, Praeparat. Evangel, lib. xv. cap. 6, &c. It should be observed, in consulting Aristotle de Ccelo, that ovpavot; is frequently used by him to signify the world : it has the same sense also in Plato's Timaeus. I 114 from Ocellus Lucanus ^ who in this instance de- serted the principles of his master Pythagoras, and almost all the more ancient writers. TlMJSUS. It has been asserted that Plato never confounds the Soul of the universe with the one First Cause and Creator of all things. In illustration of this assertion it may not be uninteresting, however ex- travagant and little intelligible such a " rhapsody " rather than a philosophy" may be in itself, to give a short abstract of the creation of the world compressed from the Timaeus. Having observed that it is difficult to discover the Maker and Fa- ther of all things, and when we have discovered him it is impossible to reveal him to all men ; hav- ing laid down a necessary distinction ^between what is created and uncreated, and declared that the one is discerned by reason and intelligence, (voy](Ti^,) the other by sensible perception, (aiaOy^cng,) the author proceeds to give an account of creation in terms which he premises will be akin to the nature of the subjects treated of, where proba- <= Vide an extract from Philo Judseus in Gale's Opusc. My- tholog. p. 501. ed. 1688. ^ "Eariv ovv 8^ koct ifArjV ho^av irpurov ^lactper^ov raSe. t/ to ov ae), yivea-iv Se ovk e%oy, ko,) il to yiyvQ^A.evov (/.ly ail, ov he ovhinore j Bek- ker, pars iii. vol. ii. Timaeus, p. 22. 115 bility not certainty is to be expected. In that flowing and beautiful language which is peculiar to him, as different from the compressed and sim- ple style of the short composition by Timaeus the Locrian as the ornamented Corinthian column from its Doric original, he explains in detail how the supreme Deity, influenced by the desire of diffusing his own ^goodness, out of disorder re- duced to ^ order the fluctuating mass of matter, gave intelligence to the soul, united soul with body, till the whole material world arose into ex- istence, an ^ animal endowed with life and intelli- gence through the providence of God. In the formation of this visible fabric after the model of the invisible archetype which was eternal in the divine Mind, the Creator first took fire and earth, and made the union of these two substances com- plete by the addition of a third called Analogia^, or ^ *Aya6o(; ijv, ayacQa Se oiJSei^ irepl o^Sevo? o^ScTroTe iyyiyverai (l)6ovoi* Tovrov 8' €Kro(; av irdvra on [AtzXia-ra, yevetrOai i^ovX-^dvj irupanA'^<Tia eavTw. Timaeus, p. 25. f EU Tafiv avTo ^ya.yf.v Ik t^^ arouiia^. Timaeus, ibid. g Zwoi/ ejiAi|/yp^ov ^vvavv re t^ aXvjfie/jt 5<a t^v rov Beov yevea-Qai Trpo- votav. Timaeus, p. 26. '^ This Analogia appears to be the law of nature, like the apxh ^ApjMiyiccq, the law of harmonious arrangement ; (Aristot. Polit. lib. i. cap. 35) or that law so beautifully described by Hooker, to which all things in heaven and earth do homage : ^evf/i.uv 8e KoKkKTroq 0^ av avTov KOii ra ^vv^ov[/.€vci on lAokiara ev irojj. Timaeus, p. 28. The principles on which Analogia per- I 2 116 Proportion, which was to regulate the order and limits of their connection. The First Cause next took air and water, gave it in charge to Analogia to combine these with the former elements, and all with itself, till the one vast fabric was bound together in the ties of friendship indissoluble, ex- cept at the hands of him who first connected it. The supreme Creator then assigned motion to the whole, and placed a soul in the centre, that its energy might be extended from thence through- out the various parts. Thus did the eternal Deity create the universe as an inferior deity possessed of consciousness and enjoying happi- ness ; a second cause and servant of himself; {evdaifJLOva 6eov eyevv^aaro.) But this Soul of the forms its functions, Plato attempts to illustrate by a mystical application of the relations of numbers. Vide Timaeus the Locrian also Aristot. Metaph. lib. i. cap. 5. It should be re- membered, however, that when the ancients appear to speak so extravagantly of the power of numher^ they do not use the word exactly in our sense, but as conveying the idea that all things are subject to certain definite rules and proportions, which may be illustrated by the operation of numbers ; as if they had some obscure notions of those physical laws of com- bination which modern philosophers have demonstrated : 01 fA€V yap TlvOayoptioi MIMH2IN ra cvrd (fyaariv flvai ray api6fji.Zy^ Aristot. Metaph. lib. i. cap. 6. Thus when Aristotle in his Rhetoric observes, Uepaiverai Se apiBfjLu itdvia, " All things are " limited by number," he means, probably, all things are sub- ject to some definite law. 117 world, though mentioned last in the descrip- tion, was not contrived the last in order, but was prior both in production and in excel- lence. It was composed of three essences, the divisible and changeable, the indivisible and un- changeable, and of a third made up of the combi- nation of the other two. From these three sub- stances, the divinity formed one soul, and distri- buted it to the different members of the universe. But when the composition of the soul had been thus completed according to the intention of the Composer', the eternal Cause then contrived all the material mass within, and united it centre to centre^. The soul, diffusing itself from hence, 5 EHEI AE RATA NOTN TOl STNI2TANTI itaaa ^ t^ ^A^^ffi ^varouTiq iyiyevi^roy jwera rovro itav to (TftjjticaToeiSe? ivroq avt^^ ettKrai- v€To. Thus translated by Cicero : " Aninmm igitur quum ille " procreator mundi Deus ex sua mente et divinitate geniiisset." This can hardly be considered a translation of the words. If ex sua mente alone will bear the meaning, '* according to his ** intention," ex sua mente et divinitate together, can scarcely signify any thing else than, " out of his own divine essence," which Plato does not say. Ciceronianum Lexicon Grseco-La- tinum ab Henrico Stephano, edit. 1557. Platonis Loci a Ci- cerone Interpretati, p. 23. ^ The principles on which this distribution is made are de- scribed with all the useless and unintelligible mysticism in which Plato was so fond of indulging. The laws again by which the composition of the soul was regulated are explained by a fanciful combination of numbers. In this sense, the number of the soul in Timaeus the Locrian is declared to be I 3 118 pervaded the extremity of the heaven revolving upon itself around it, and established the com- mencement of a life unceasing and full of intel- lectual enjoyment. Formed by the most excellent Creator the most excellent of created things, it is endowed with a capacity of perceiving eternal truths. From its proportionate distribution and compound essence, and self-revolving power ^, when it approaches any divisible or indivisible substance, it is enabled to discern, by moving itself through its own entire nature, the identity and differences of things, to what class each belongs, the time and place and manner of its existence, the distinction 1 1 4695. Vide Timseus the Locrian. Bekker, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 382. Absurd as these speculations of Plato are, they are more than equalled by those of Darjes, a German writer, (and he was only one of a school,) not a century ago, who published a philoso- phical treatise to demonstrate the Trinity by algebraical formula. Tractatus philosophicus in quo Plurahtas Personarum in Deitate, &C.1735. Problems of the same kind are also to be found in Stap- fer, a divine of a different church, in a learned work, (Institu- tiones Theolog. tomi 5. Tiguri, 1743.) Vid. vol. iii. p. 481, 482, &c. And Dr. Hutchinson, in his inquiry into the origin of our ideas of beauty and virtue, has applied algebra to the question of "moral merit:" "The benevolence (moral merit) of an " agent is proportional to a fraction, having the moment of ** good for the numerator, and the ability of the agent for the •* denominator." Life and Writings of Dr. Held, in Dugald Stewart's edition of his works. ' Cicero de Natura Deorum lib. i. cap. 10. 119 between essences eternal and the same, and those created and changeable. But when the Father who had made this image of the eternal deities had seen it living and moving, he was well-pleased and rejoiced, and he determined to perfect his work, and to render it still more similar to the original archetype. He then applied himself to the creation of time ™, the sun, moon, and stars, and other divinities, who though parts of the one vast animal, are endowed with separate conscious- ness and personal happiness ". When the Father "" It is remarkable that Plato makes no distinction of time in the eternal archetype of the world as it existed in the divine mind ; AeyofMv yap tv} uq ^v tarn re ku) eo^a/, t^ he ro tan [/.ovov KUTo, Toy aXuj^ Xoyov 'rrpo(jr,K€i. Timaeus, p. 36. " This is certainly Plato's theory, Timaeus, p. 29. If then all the animals which are parts of the material universe possess separate consciousness, what reason is there for supposing that he believed the soul after death, when it became a part of uni- versal mind, would lose its personality. He uniformly repre^ sents it as possessed of individuality. Parts are used in a figu- rative sense : Plato himself tells us that the term body is ap- plied to the universe, not literally, but figuratively, (Timaeus, p. 30.) I am well aware that by subsequent writers the distinctions of the philosopher were not so accurately observed, and that the still greater absurdity of their notions respecting the Anima Mundi might justify the satire of the Epicurean in Cicero, or the keener ridicule of St. Augustine : though we can hardly imagine the creed of any to have extended so far as to embrace the belief, that all things were literally a part of Jupiter, and that the Deity in the torrid zone was parched with heat, and in the hyperborean regions was stiff with cold ; and that he actually I 4 of all things had created these principal parts of the universe, he afterwards assigned to them, as second causes and subject deities, their subordinate departments in the work of creation. To their care was committed the formation of other ani- mated essences inferior to themselves. They are charged in gratitude for the immortality which their Maker in his benevolence has given them, and to which they had no natural claim, to devote themselves diligently to the task: "^ Deities of dei- " ties, of whom I am Creator and Father, ye are " not immortal and indissoluble; what I have made " I can dissolve, yet ye shall not be dissolved, nor *' be subject to death, through the might of my *' will. Apply yourselves to the creation of ani- " mals, imitating my power exerted in your pro- " duction. , I will furnish you with the first prin- " ciples and eternal seeds for the formation of " those who are to resemble the immortal Gods, " but do ye, adding the mortal to the immortal " nature, mould and produce them into being, died in men, and was whipped in hoys : " Quid infelicius credi ** potest quam Jovis partem vapulare cum puervapulat," Cicero de Natura Deorum lib. i. cap. lo, ii. St. Augustin, Civ. Dei, lib. iv. cap. 13. Dr. Ireland, p. 184, 185. Vide also Comment. Marsil. Ficini, lib. iii. cap. 3. Plotini Ennead. 4. ° The spirit and beauty of the passage beginning ©eo* Oewv, &v ^ya IvKA.iovpyoi itaTfip re epyecv will be felt by every reader of Plato. Timseus, p. 43. Ul " nourish and multiply them, and receive back " their dissolved elements when they perish." Saying this, he turned to the cup in which he had tempered the soul of the universe, and mingled the materials in the same manner as before, but of inferior purity ; and having formed souls, he dis- tributed them to different stars, each to its own star, to be reserved for the production of an ani- mal distinguished for piety towards the Gods. When these souls should be introduced into bodies, and become subject to the influence of bodily passions, the Creator ordained that the man who lived his allotted time subduing his appetites should enjoy a life of future happiness, returning to that kindred star in which his spirit had been at first deposited. If he failed to conquer them, he was destined in his second formation to put on the nature of woman p, and unless corrected then, he was to pass into other animals, till the irrational part should be at length overcome, and his soul should approach to that excellency and purity in which it had at first been formed. The Creator having established these laws, in order that him- P In other works Plato seems to consider women on an equality with men. Vid. Republic, fifth book, in which he re- commends the same course of bodily and mental discipline, IMva-iK^i and yvfAvatrriKrj, to both. Aristotle considered women inferior. Aristot. Polit. book i. chap. 13. 122 self might be guiltless of the evil which should hereafter infect them, interspersed some souls in the moon, others in the sun, and others in the various stars. The inferior deities, having received these first principles of the immortal soul, proceed to the accomplishment of their work, and to form the body of man as well as that mortal soul which is the seat of the passions, and of pleasure and pain : of pleasure, the greatest allurement to evil ; of pain, that most strongly deters us from good ; of anger and fear, inconsiderate twin-counsellors ; of hope, that easily seduces by means of the irrational senses ; and of love, that dares every enterprise. Yet, fearing to mingle their work with that of the supreme Deity, they implant this irrational soul in the breast, whereas the immortal soul was placed in the head, in order that from this acropolis, or citadel, it might issue its com- mands with authority to the inferior faculties and passions. An apology is perhaps necessary for introducing such a wild and fanciful narrative to the notice of the reader, but it may possibly furnish some illus- tration of Plato's opinions, as well as of the poeti- cal colouring with which he adorned them, though we may be unable to determine the exact mea- sure of belief which he himself gave to the dif- ferent parts of such a theory. It is clear how- 123 ever, from the tenor of the whole account, that he never confounds the soul of the universe with the One First Cause ; nor can any inference be de- duced, either directly or indirectly, from it, that he believed the human soul after death would so become a part of the Anima mundi as to lose per- sonal consciousness. It will be no uninstructive lesson to compare this diffuse and tedious history, in which the acts of the Deity are so elaborately detailed, with the simple and sublime language of inspiration on the same subject. If such an argu- ment were wanting to establish the truth of the Mosaic history, the style itself would furnish strong evidence in its favour. No attempt is made to enchain the reader's attention, or satisfy unprofitable curiosity upon matters too exalted for human comprehension, by copious and high- wrought descriptions. The sacred writer repre- sents not the Creator mingling elements and sub- stances like an earthly workman^, and determining by calculated arrangements and multiplied com- binations the limits and proportions of their union, but as an Almighty Being, whose words and whose works are the same. The single sentence, '1 The disciple of Epicurus in Cicero makes this objection to Plato's narrative : " Quae molitio ? quas ferramenta ? qui vectes ? ** quae machinae? qui niinistri tanti operis fuerant?" De Natura Deormn lib. i. cap. 8. 124 Let there he light, and there was light, serves at once to repress curiosity, and fill the mind with a magnificent image of that infinite Power, who spake, and it was done ; who commanded, and it stoodfast. The work of Timaeus the Locrian^ in the Doric dialect, which has been before alluded to, and which is supposed to contain the principles of the Pythagoreans, differs in no important particulars from the more diffuse description of Plato. Two original principles are represented as existing from eternity, God or Mind, and Necessity; 0€Of or vovg, and avajKri, of which Matter and Form, vKfi and /^ea, are the offspring ^ And it is asserted in another passage, that before the heaven was pro- duced the Deity and Matter existed, and also the essential archetype or form of things ^ The Soul of the universe is described as the composition of the Deity with a degree of minuteness and mysti- cism that Plato himself has not surpassed. But there is nothing in the narrative to lead us to the inference that the writer imagined the First Cause to confound himself with the Soul of the universe, the work of his own creation, or that the soul of ■■ T//*aio$ AoVpo? TaSe e^a. is the commencement of the work. ^ Ilpiv uv ^pavov <yev€<TBct^ Xoy^ Tjcrnjv l^eot re ko,) vXa koI o 0€o< ZafAiovpyoq ta jScXr/ovo?. Bekker, pars iii. vol. iii. p. 380. The Deity is also called *Xpy^ rSv apia-ruv, p. 379. 125 man was absorbed in it after death. The neces- sity of the irrational part obeying the rational is insisted on, and it is declared, that the perception of truth will conduct the man who observes this law to a life of the greatest happiness ". But it is uncertain whether this relates to a future state of happiness or not. The idea of future punishment, and the menaces respecting it, are discarded, and such doctrines are permitted only as providing a check for those who refuse the admonitions of reason ^. Yet the last words of the treatise leave a doubt upon the mind whether the writer, re- jecting as he did the representation of the poets, and the fables of the metempsychosis, had not some belief in an avenging Nemesis to punish the guilty after death ; nor are they satisfactorily ex- plained by the distinction that Warburton makes between the physical and moral metempsychosis. " A*' ocKaOecrrdTav ho^oiv ayerai €7ri tov ti/taifAOviaTarov ^lov. Bek- ker, pars iii. vol. Hi. p. 391, * *n^ yap roc o-ufAara voa-a^ea-i ttoKo. vyia^ofAeq^ ou ko. [Arj cIktj to<V vyi6i- voTaTOig, ovru raq ypv^aq a,iT€ipyoi/.€q x^cfSeo-t Xoyoiq^ ei kcc fM] ay^tcti a\a- Bea-i. Timseus ad fin. Vide also the concluding sentence of the treatise. If Plato had left no works of his own behind him, this passage might have been admitted as affording evidence of his opinions ; but its authority is of little weight when opposed to the numerous treatises written by himself, in which contrary doctrines are inculcated. Vid. Warburton's Divine Legation, book iii. sect. 3. also sect. i. vol. ii. p. 2. 54, 55. U6 In conclusion it may be observed, that War- burton's knowledge of ancient philosophy was more extended, than sound and accurate y. He asserts, that Aristotle believed the care of Provi- dence not to extend to individuals; the Ethics alone might have convinced him of his error. He denies that the affection of love, joy, &c. were believed by Plato and Pythagoras to belong to the supreme Deity, but only to inferior divinities^; in the Timaeus the supreme Deity is represented as rejoicing when he had made the world. He ob- serves again, that in taking away human passions from God, they left him nothing but that kind of natural excellence which went not from his will, but his essence only. The assertion is not limited to the Stoics, but applied universally. Did the author of the Divine Legation ever read the pas- sage in the Timaeus before alluded to ? " Deities of " deities, ye are not immortal, and yet ye shall not " be dissolved, t^$- efxvj^ povX'^a-ecDg, k. t. A. through " the power of my will." * Upon a general re- y Book iii. sect. 4. p. 95, 96. vol. ii. Aristot. Ethics, lib. i. cap. 9. lib. X. cap. 8. E* ydp nq i'jrt(Ji.€K€ia tuv avBficimivuv vico Seav yiveTOci uairep So/fe?, Koci etvj oiv evKoyov xaipeiv re avrolq r^ (rvyyeve- a-Ta.1'^. and hence he deduces the inference, that he is the hap- piest man who is dearest to the gods. Cudworth, lib. i. cap. i. sect. 45. z Book iii. sect. 4. p. 97, 98. vol. ii. ^ Vide also Alcinous on the doctrines of Plato, cap. x. Cud- worth, Hb. i. cap. 4. p. 415. 127 view of the inquiry, we may, I think, venture to de- termine, that he has by no means proved his asser- tions against the philosophers of Greece : to quote the words of Mosheim^, " Non apertis et planis " testimoniis causam suam agit vir praeclarus, quod " in tanti momenti accusatione necessarium vide- " tur, sed conjecturis tantum, exemplis nonnullis, " denique consectariis ex institutis quibusdam et " dogmatibus philosophorum quibusdam ductis." Though the author of the Divine Legation has attempted to refute this charge, it will appear, upon an accurate examination, not only strictly true, but to fall short of the truth. In what man- ner, for example, are the opinions of Plato attempt- ed to be ascertained? Not by a comprehensive view of his own writings, but by an appeal to Jamblichus, Albinus, or Celsus. The sentiments of Aristotle are pronounced upon after an investi- gation equally partial and unsatisfactory. The most important passage in the Ethics that bears upon the subject is omitted, and the observations on the chapters in the treatise de Anima are made up partly of unwarranted assumption, partly of reasoning, alike superficial and unphilosophical. The statements of bishop Warburton, respecting the other philosophers of Greece, are often founded ^ De Rebus Christ, ante Constantinum Magnum, p.i8. quoted by Warburton, lib. iii. sect. 4. vol. ii. p. 138. 128 in the same manner upon scattered passages, ap- plied with wonderful dexterity and ingenuity, but not upon any general comparison of their writ- ings. Nor does he shew much critical acumen (and this is surprising in so acute a writer) in dis- tinguishing the relative value of the testimonies which he cites. He appears at times to argue in the spirit of a man who might think Plutarch, or even Porphyry, as good evidence for the doctrine of the Academy as Plato himself; and M. Antoni- nus or Apuleius sound authorities on the philoso- phy of Aristotle. In answer to the chancellor of Gottingen, he asserts, that the Greek philosophers are proved by him to have made use of a double doctrine — to have held it lawful to deceive, and to say one thing when they thought another — to have sometimes owned, and sometimes denied a future state of rewards and punishments — to have held that God could not be angry, nor hurt any one — that the soul was part of the substance of God — to have avowed that the consequence of these ideas of God and the soul was no future state of rewards and punishments. But how few of these propositions have been established upon any solid grounds. The author of the Divine Le- gation has not shewn, nor is it possible to shew, that Plato and Aristotle held the notion of a double sense distinct from the division of doctrines 129 into exoteric and esoteric : the assertion, that Plato held it lawful to deceive for the public good, is grounded chiefly on a translation of a sentence by Cicero, either wrong in itself, or misunderstood : that they sometimes owned and sometimes denied a future state, is not true of Plato, if it is meant that his expressions of denial, or rather of doubt, bear any proportion to those of belief and ac- knowledgment ; and in the case of other philoso- phers, occasional doubts upon such a subject would furnish no very decisive evidence against the ge- neral character of their belief. That they held God could not be angry, was an opinion of some sects of philosophy, not of all : the supposition that the soul*^ was part of the substance of God does not necessarily affect the argument respecting a future state of retribution ; for the Platonists did not imagine that being a part of universal mind ex- cluded the notion of personal consciousness : that they avowed the consequences of these ideas of God and the soul was no future state of rewards and punishments, is not true of the philosophers in general, but chiefly of the Stoics. Nor are the theories of bishop Warburton^ respecting the be- ^ Tertullian held that the soul was part of the substance of God. ^ In Schrockh's Ecclesiastical History there is this brief and just criticism on Warburton's theory : Sinnreich genugy aber K 130 lief of the ancient Jews supported by more solid arguments. History, prophecy, and precept, the common hopes and fears of mankind, are all made to bend to the supposed influence of a law, which, while it included within the range of its enact- ments temporal rewards as well as punishments, cannot be proved upon any sound principles to have excluded the expectation of future recom- pense. Our admiration of learning and ingenuity, however perverted and misapplied, will always en- sure to the works of Warburton a certain degree of popularity; but opinions like those developed in the Divine Legation of Moses will never ex- tensively prevail, till the love of novelty and inge- nuity gets the better alike of sober criticism and common sense. nur sinnreich! "Ingenious enough, but otily ingenious!" Schrockh viii. theil. vol. xliii. p. 753. THE END. '%,; THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW AN INITIAL FINE~OP 25 CENTS WILL INCREASE TO SO CENTS ON THE pour™ oOeROUE. "° ^^-^^ ^'^ -- SEVENT^ro'i;; NOV ^ '/ r 1935 MAY 5 1948 LD 21-l00m-7 '33 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA UBRARY ^I^^X^ : 3^^5*^- ^- ■ ^y ^. i-' / \ ^^' - y^-^ -. //^ \ ^ "■-- << ;^ '7 v^U • Kr\r<^K' ^':A k- ^^' <// iJ*: ^^■d ^ tx^4'> .■k\< •;> iC^-^ r-^ii /^^/^^ (f'^ fr^^^ m^