fe^^l Digitized by the Internet Arciiive iji 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/dramaitslawsitstOOmorrrich THE DRAMA ITS LAW AND ITS TECHNIQUE ' BY ELISABETH WOODBRIDGE, Ph.D. M / ALLYN AND BACON Copyright, 1898, By Lamson, WolfFe and Company. All rights reserved. FAN Nortuood Press J. S. Gushing & Co. — Berwick & Smith Norwood f Mass.f U.S.A. Mu PREFACE FREYTAG'S Technik des Dramas, written thirty-five years ago, remains up to this time the best work of its kind. Yet its defects of man- ner and of arrangement are apparent even to the casual reader, and they become yet more evident when the book is subjected to the test of the college class-room. Such a test — one for which the book was never intended — obscures its merits, which are many, and emphasizes its defects, which might appear few and superficial, but which are peculiarly irritating to both teacher and student. Yet the need of such a book is indicated by the number of treatises on the drama which have appeared since Freytag wrote. All of these that I have seen, however, are either too exclusively philosophical, and in their theorizing about the art ignore the practical details of the craft, or they are not philo- sophical enough, and in their preoccupation with the craft lose sight of the fundamental principles, the absolute standards, of the art. In this, as in all other essentials, Freytag was sound ; his proportionate emphasis is right, and when I first began to realize the defects of the V 4 :> ] Vi PREFACE book, I thought that by making some changes it could be rendered more practically available while no less suggestive. I soon discovered, however, that it was not possible to fit Freytag's discussion into the Procrustean framework of my own plan. His book lacks system, but it does possess the unity that must always characterize the utterances, how- ever careless, of an honest and conscientious thinker. My book, I saw, might rectify some of the faults of the original, but would fall short of its merits. So I laid Freytag quite aside, and wrote the following chapters with as little regard as possi- ble to the discussions in the Technik. " As little as possible," — for to make any claim to entire independence would be preposterous. No one can read the utterances of a thoughtful critic and veteran in stage-craft like Freytag without being influenced by them. Even if one has arrived inde- pendently at the theories and the judgments therein contained, the formulation and illustration of these theories and judgments by another mind must affect him, if not by altering his thought, at least by enriching its subject-matter. I wish, therefore, to make a comprehensive acknowledgment of my indebtedness to the Technik. Comprehensive and general it must be, for just because his book, despite its diffuseness and its desultorines?, is vital and fundamental, it is impossible to lay a finger on the exact places where I am in its debt. One of the chief merits of Freytag's work is its mass of illustrative comments on ancient and PREFACE VU modern dramas. More especially was his use of the Greek dramatists valuable and suggestive, and I hesitated before determining to omit from this treatment any such detailed discussion. Without a sympathetic famiharity with ^schylus, Sophocles, and Euripides for tragedy, and with Aristophanes for comedy, no one can claim the right to "judge righteous judgment " in things dramaturgic. When Freytag wrote, such a familiarity was scarcely to be gained without years of toil ; since his time, modem classical scholarship has experienced a wonderful growth, bearing fruit in a number of critical treatises whose profound learning is informed by philo- sophic insight and delicate taste, is directed by a sense for historic proportion, is dominated by just aesthetic standards. With such works at hand as , the treatises of Jebb, of Butcher, of Haigh, any j ^ detailed treatment of the ancient drama would be ' presumptuous, not to say superfluous, and its place is more fittingly taken by the bibliography at the end of the volume, which points out to the student some of the guides to whom he will commit himself when he shall explore this part of the field. Of Freytag's illustrations from modern drama, many are based on German plays, and are thus less illuminating to the average American reader — even the college student — than to the German audience for whom they were intended ; hence they greatly increase the bulk of the book without adding pro- portionately to its effectiveness. I have confined my illustrations more strictly to English Uterature, Vm PREFACE using the drama of other nations only where it is needed for comparison. Such a method is theo- retically lawful as well as practically expedient, since English drama was in its formative period — that is, up to Dryden — scarcely at all influenced by any other drama save the Roman and, chiefly indirectly, the Greek. With our own contemporary drama it is different. It is not possible to set up a language -barrier when our Enghsh and American stages are occupied with the plays of Italian, French, German, and Scandinavian writers. Of contemporary drama Freytag's book takes almost no account. Indeed, when he wrote, the renaissance, if we may venture to call it so, of drama had only just set in. Ibsen had been writ- ing plays only a few years, and his greatest were yet to come ; Sudermann was six years old; Hauptmann was an infant; Fulda was not yet born, nor was Maeterlinck, nor Rostand, the brill- iant actor-dramatist who is now hailed by some of his countrymen as their young Shakespeare ; in England a few critic s were hopelessly hoping that -'^dhe'^ama was not really so dead as it seemed. Small wonder that Freytag's mention of modern work had rather the character of an exhortation and a warning than of a critical judgment. But in the last thirty years many good plays, many brill- iant ones, some great ones, have been written, and it is well not to ignore them. In the ordinary college courses it is, indeed, scarcely possible to lay much emphasis on these, yet it is unfortunate FREFACS IX to treat the drama as though it came to an end, for England in 1616, and for Germany in 1832. Such an attitude lends color of truth to the assertion that the drama is no longer a living art form. One of the signs of its life is that it is changing ; and we must not be deceived by the frequent presentations of Shakespeare's plays into thinking that our stage is like the EHzabethan, or that our Shakespeare is the Shakespeare of Elizabeth and of James. In the study of drama Shakespeare must be our centre, but just as we cannot arrive at the truest judgment if we leave out the Greeks, so too we cannot if we ignore our own contemporaries. >1 Finally, there is one great section of the drama which Freytag left untouched, — comedy. Yet it is present as an element in every one of Shake- speare's plays, it is the predominant element in many of them, and a discussion of the drama which ignores this is, not Hamlet with Hamlet left out, but something more preposterous — Henry IV with Falstaff left out. For an exhaustive, or even a fairly satisfactory, discussion of dramatic comedy an entire volume is needed ; such a volume ought to be written. In the three chapters here devoted to the subject I have tried merely to make a survey of the field, to suggest points of view whence it may be studied, to point out lines along which it may be explored. So little has it been investigated that I cannot offer the student even the nucleus for a bibliog- raphy. My hope is that others may come to X PREFACE realize the fascination of this branch of dramatic theory, and that more may be done to illuminate this, at present the most complex and the least adequately treated subject in the realm of literary criticism. CONTENTS PART I. — LAW PAGB INTRODUCTION xiii I. Poetic Truth i IL/^ Dramatic Unity lo IJU. Seriousness — SIIQYAH ... 22 IM. The Nature and Sources of Tragic Effect 36 't-V^ The Nature and Sources of Comic Effect 51 PART II. — TECHNIQUE ^I. The Two Types of Drama ... 68 ^11. The Logical Divisions of the Action 76 ^ III. The Mechanical Divisions of the Drama 93 ''IV. Character-treatment . . . .116 <- V. Plot in Comedy 137 ^VI. Character-treatment in Comedy . 162 Bibliographies 175 Index 179 xi INTRODUCTION A DRAMA is a pr esentation of an action, or closely interlinked series of actions, ex- '" pressed directly Byiiiearrs~of' speech' and gesture. It is, however, distinguished from other literary species, not only by its form, but by its subject- X matter and its point of view. Its subject-m atter is the action and re action of human will, a nd it is treated withTv iew. not to the sequen ce of events, pt^r-*-^ but to their essential relations as causes and effects. jiJtA/f^ Nj^The drama is like the epTt: in that it deals with / events of human life ; it differs from it by empha- sizing more strongly the volitio nal an d subjective rather than the incidental and objective elements in such events: iit is like the lyric in that it is concerned with emotional, or, more broadly, with spiritual states~~it differs from it by emphasizing, not the emotional or spiritual state considered in itself, but this considered as issuing from or de- veloping into volition. Thus, though it has a closer connection with the inner life than has the epic, and a closer connection with the outer life than has the lyric, it trenches upon the realm of both epic and lyric, and every great drama has in XIV INTRODUCTION it each of these elements, though their relative proportions may vary. Vary, indeed, they do. The Greek drama, de- veloping out of the choral ode, always kept a strongly lyric cast; the Teutonic drama is as strongly epic in character. The Greek type, as we get it in Seneca, degenerates into the rhetorical monologue, from which the French classical drama never wholly freed itself; the Teutonic type easily lapses into the presentation of a series of events without inner unity, as in some of Shake- speare's historical plays which are little more than chronicles thrown into dramatic form. Within the limits of art, however, there is possibility of wide divergence in the proportionate values of the two elements, and the (Edipus Tyrannus does not ex- clude Macbeth from the number of great dramas. In the following discussion it has been assumed that, beneath the differences of form that distin- guish the ancient drama from the modern, there is enough identity in their informing spirit and underlying motive to justify a treatment of them as one. Differences there are, nor are they merely those of form, and Freytag states one side of the truth when he says: "Since Aristotle formulated some of the chief laws of dramatic effect, the cult- ure of the human race has grown older by more than two thousand years. It is not merely the artistic forms — the stage and the manner of pres- entation — which have altered, but, what is more important, the spiritual and moral nature of man, INTRODUCTION XV the relation of the individual to the race and to the highest forces of life, the idea of freedom, and the conception of the divine being, all these have undergone great changes." This is true, yet the more familiar one grows with the Greek drama the more one comes to realize that in the fundamental constitution of human nature there has been~TTttle change, and that in proportion as the drama is great it is the same for all ages. Or, if there are in this respect great essential differ- ences, — as there are certainly great superficial ones, — we English are closer to the Greeks in sympathy than we are to some peoples of more recent times, for example, the French of the seventeenth century, and are more at one with the writer of (Edipus Tyrannus than with the writer of Athalie, The two elements that are emphasized in dra- ^ matic treatment of human nature are, broadly speaking, free will and causality. It is a com- monplace of criticism to say that the Greek drama presented the latter, the modern drama the former, and indeed the Greek and the modern use of these two elements is different. But the doctrine of the freedom of the individual is not new, it is as old as the words, "The soul that sinneth, it shall die." The doctrine which sees the individual borne re- morselessly forward to his fate by forces which he did not initiate is not confined to Greece, it is as old as the first commandment in the Decalogue, or the words, "The fathers have eaten sour grapes, /^ XVI INTRODUCTION and the children's teeth are set on edge"; but it is also as modern as Ibsen. The ancient world laid greater stress on the second of these two truths, the modern world on the first, but it is only the proportionate emphasis that has changed : nothing old has been wholly lost, nothing really new has been added. In discussing any art it is possible to treat it in two ways, according as one considers the princi- ples or laws that underly it as an art, or the rules of technique that govern it as a craft. In the first aspect it is brought into more or less close relation with all art; in the second aspect it needs a narrower and more detailed treatment of those things which mark it off from the other arts. The following discussion has attempted to open up the subject first in the more general aspect, and then in the more specific. ^ iJ'f Y v/- Like all art, the drama, to be' of value at all, mus ^ have truth ; to be coherent and effective, it must have unity; to command^ our veneration, it , niust have that quality which the Greeks called ^oTovS?, and which we call greatness, seriousness, nobility. In one sense, any one of these qualities, deeply interpreted, includes the others, but it is possible also to separate them in thought. It has seemed best to take them thus separately and then to try to follow up the two main lines, the tragic and the comic, along which dramatic art has developed. The Drama t PART I — LAW CHAPTER I POETIC TRUTH ALL art, said Aristotle, is imitation. That he did not mean by this the mere copying or mirroring of facts is sufficiently clear from his re- marks about the ideal and philosophic character of poetry: "Tragedy represents men as better than they are,"^ "It should preserve the type and yet ennoble it.'"^ In the light of such passages, the word "imitation" takes on another significance from that we might at first be inclined to give it, but it is still misleading, and it seems better to substitute the broader term, "poetic truth." What does this mean, and what does it imply? - All art, and hence_ all _great^^drania*__i& in_ Jj;s I ( nature both universal and,personal,b^>th_general J and selective. . The painter cannot, for example, (^ paint every leaf of a tree, and if he did so his painting would certainly be more unsatisfactory to us than if he had worked with less minuteness. His art lies in determining which of the impres- 1 Poetics, II. 2 /^., XV. B I 2 LAW sions into which the infinitely complex total which we call "tree" may be resolved — which of these is to be preserved as essential, which may be re- jected. No two artists would ever make quite the same choice, yet each might be, artistically, true to the subject. Each would, if he were a great artist, give us something better than the landscape itself, he would interpret it to us — make it mean more than it had before. Millet once said, in effect, " A flock of sheep must be regarded by the painter, not as a collection of animals, but as one single huge animal, moving on many feet, and it must be so painted." And it is because Millet himself painted sheep in this way that his work is really art. \ To take another illustration, there is a certain living artist who has wonderful power in drawing the urchins of London's streets, convey- ing, with a few seemingly careless strokes, the . very life and movement of the boys. It is said that he first makes a rather detailed drawing of his subject, then goes over his work, eliminating line after line, until he has reduced it, as it were, to its lowest terms, and there_£emains no line not ai)-t^ sgl utely necessary^ The finished product, with its appearance of carelessness, is really the result of the most careful selection. It is conceivable that such a process should all have been mental, and nothing have appeared on paper but the final re- sult; conceivable, too, that it might be partly or wholly unconscious on the part of the artist; but the process, or something like it, is characteristic POETIC TRUTH 3 of all art, and in proportion as the artis t is great will his selective power be true and unerring, ' never rejecting the significant and retaining the unessential. To this end, however, he needs large and deep knowledge of his subject. Wordsworth said that a simple recital of the facts of a given phenomenon might be at once formally accurate and essentially untrue because it had been made either mechanically or ignorantly, noting the un- essential and the significant without discriminating between them. Such discrimination comes with knowledge, which enables us to check our observa- tion of particular instances by a knowledge of the universal, gained through observation of other particular instances. It will now be evident what was meant by saying . that art is in its nature both universal and personal or selective. It becomes the one by means of the other, for the selection will reject the accidental and temporary and retain the essential and perma- nent. In this selective process the personality of the artist is tested; upon his personality depends the value of his work to others. If it is deep enough and big enough to be in unison with the individualitjr(Tf~the~ "expression is legitimate) of humanity, he will see in his subject, be it land- scape or human soul, the things that all humanity must see when it looks deeply enough, though it may need his quickened vision to point them out. Thus the artist must be at once different from his fellow-man, and like him. " Once in a while an 4 LAW individual Ideal, when expressed, enlightens the world of art, and then we have the artistic genius; he is the prophet who shows to others an ideal field which they ^t once recognize as effective for them- selves, although but for him it would have been unknown to them. To e xpress his own id eal must be the artist' s work." ^ Of the ideal in this sense Amiel's remark is true; "The ideal, after all, is truer than the real; for the ideal is the eternal ele- ment in perishable things: it is their type, their sum, their raison d^etre^ their formula in the book pf the Creator, and therefore at once the most ex- act and the most condensed expression of them."* The danger in this selective art-process is evi dent, especially if we note some phases of it in painting. The extremists of the so-called "im- pressionist " school are simply carrying this process to its farthest issue. They reproduce of a land- scape only a single aspect. All its possibilities of suggestion, its complexity and shading, are swept away to make room for the artist's single impres- sion. The result is rather remarkable. If one happens to approach such a picture from the right direction, with exactly the right light, and in a peculiarly receptive mood, one may receive from it an impression startlingly vivid. If, on the other hand, these conditions are not fulfilled, the pictu^ may be absolutely meaningless to us. The reason is plain enough. The artist has so narrowed his 1 H. R. Marshall, /Esthetic Principles, p. 97. * Amiel, Journal, p. 105; POETIC TRUTH 5 presentation of impressions that it appeals to but few besides himself — it has become personal past the point of contact with others. The same thing occurs in literature, though it is not so easily demonstrable. Schopenhauer is a case of the too narrowly selective, the viciously . personal. He attempts satire, let us say; what results? Often enough, it is not satire, but in- vective, more or less hysterical. He is giving us things as they appear to him, but they appear to him as they do not appear to a sane man, and his work becomes interesting, not as art, but as pa- thology. If one would see the difference between satire and anger, that is, between legitimate and illegitimate personality, compare him with Juvenal or Swift at their best, or compare the fourth part of Gulliver's Travels with the first three parts, fi t is in finding the mean b etween this personal narrowness^ that is too selective, and the photo- graphic impersonality that is not selective aPall, that the individuality of the artist, his training and his ideals, are tested. It is t his that determi nes . how much his work shall possess pf what w e may^ I call poetic, or artis tic, tru th. The difference be- tween such truth and the truth of philosophy is not so much in the final result as in the means employed to reach it. The philosopher seeks to discover the essential and universal," and to state it in terms of the universal. The artist seeks to state it in terms of the particular.^ If he wishes to pre- sent the contrast between the misguided human "6 LAW heart, preoccupied with its gloomy or ghastly criminal purposes, and the sane and kindly stand- ards of the world of freer men, the philosopher will state this in terms of universal application; the poet may symbolize it by the rough and sud- den knocking at a castle gate, and the drowsy murmurs of a sleepy porter. L^Such a selective process is forced upon the dramatist, also, by the practical conditions of his problem. A play must, when acted, not exceed three hours, but this is an extreme estimate, and includes the time for scene-shifting and other waits ; the business of the play itself ought not to use more than two-thirds of this time. He has, then, two hours in which to present his action, with its causes and results. Obviously, there are in real life few cases where such an action occu- pies so short a time;t it is more apt to stretch over months or years, and its links are "the HttFe; nameless, . unremem befed acts^ of o«t daily life. The artist cannot possibly reproduce all these, and he must, therefore, be in a sense "untrue" to his model.^3' Yet, if he could reproduce them, he would not. For life, nature, in itself, as distinguished from nature as seen by us, is unemphatic. Its so- called contrasts, its humor, its varying emphasis, its "meaning," have their existence, not in the things themselves, but in the mind of the observer. It is, therefore, the artist's part to supply these, to mould his material, impressing upon it the stamp 1 Cf. infra, pp. 14-16. POETIC TRUTH f of his mind, and thus giving it emphasis, propor- tion, perspective, — which brings us back again to the selective process. (Out of the infinite series of occurrences he chooses such links as seem to him most important, or such as may be made to symbolize more than themselves!] These critical moments he emphasizes, the rest he lets go, trust- ing that from what we see we will infer what we do not see.^ Take Macbeth, The dramatist must present to us the rnor al ruin , — the sp«^itual disintegration of a man, with its inner causes. What does he do? He selects his moments, presents these, and lets them stand for all that goes between. We first hear of our hero as a high-minded and courageous soldier. Then we see him, fresh from victory, re- ceive the first suggestion of greater honors to be won; we see how the idea takes hold of him, and we suspect that one so easily touched must have been less sound at heart than we and others had supposed. What goes on in his mind immediately after this we are not told, but after the scenes with Lady Macbeth, we can look back and imagine. That is, we find ourselves responding to the poet's demand, we are become co-workers with him. After the murder, again, we get no insight into Macbeth' s inner life until after he has been made king. Then comes the banquet-scene, which, brief as it is, throws a blaze of light backward over the 1 Cf. the discussion of " the unities " in the following chapter, especially pp. 14-19. LAW interval. We recognize with perfect certitude the disintegration that has been going on in a spirit that we now see to have been never really strong, either for good or evil. And now our mind can go forward without teaching, we shall expect from the harassed king no firmness of touch, we know his spirit is fevered, that he is the slave of his past. For Lady Macbeth we are given no clews through the course of the play until, at the end, we are allowed, for one brief glimpse, to see her off her ^ guard, when her will of steel is relaxed in delirious E sleep. But those few lurid moments reveal to us - ^ whole life-history, and it is enough. ■ ^ ^ ' i If one would realize the tremendous compres- ^ sion of the play, and get the full significance of its method, let him note how another artist has treated a similar theme. Dostoiefsky, in Crime and Punishmenty gives us the history of a few days in a young man's life, during which he commits a crime, and afterwards, hovering on the verge of madness, undergoes spiritual tortures of the most exquisite kind. His mental processes are given almost from minute to minute, not an hour is un- accounted for. The effect of the whole is, it is true, tremendous; but it is not the kind of effect that art ought to produce, it is not the purified "pity and fear" which makes a subject beautiful in art which is merely terrible in nature. The writer certainly possessed such knowledge of the human soul as is given to few; had he possessed also the power to wield this knowledge, his book POETIC TRUTH 9 would have been one of the grandest art-produc- tions to which a man ever gave being. But o^ .e feels that he is not master gf his in s piration^ he is mastered by it,_ an(l the book has upon it the taint ' of madness from which the author, if we may trust report, was not wholly free. And thus it happens, that while Shakespeare had probably a less pro- found understanding than Dostoiefsky of the inner life of a sin-darkened soul, we feel that his drama is a great artistic creation, whereas of Dostoiefsky's story we feel that it might have been this, but is not. The discussion has led us to the verge of that Clever-dying controversy concerning the merits of the realistic and the idealistic in arj Z]' To enter "upon it would carry us beyond the limits of our subject. Be it suggested, however, thatJthe antithe- sis between the two terms is not absolute and fixed, for all true art is, as we have^seen^ideal, and all true art is based ^in reality. The difference between"~the two scEooTs is quantitative, it is a difference in the proportionate emphasis they lay upon these two aspects of arF,^ and their divergence should never be so great as to lead them, the one beyond the limits of art into the photographic, the other beyond the limits of art into the over narrowly personal. 1 CHAPTER II DRAMATIC UNITY FEW sayings have been the occasion of such bitter and long-continued controversy as Aris- totle's remarks on the unity of the drama. For this reason, and because they furnish a convenient point of departure, it may be well to quote his own words : '* Tragedy is an imitation of an action, that is complete, and whole, and of a certain magnitude. V\. . A whole is that which has beginning, middle, and end. A beginning is that which does not itself follow anything by causal necessity, but after which something naturally is or comes to be. An end, on the contrary, is that which itself naturally follows some other thing, either by necessity, or in the regular course of events, but has nothing following it. A middle is that which follows something as some other thing follows it. A well-constructed plot, therefore, must neither begin nor end at haphazard, but conform to the type here described," ^ '* Unity of plot does not, as some persons think, consist in the unity of the hero. ' For infinitely various are the incidents in one mari'Js life, which cannot be reduced to unity; and so, too, there are many actions of one man out of which we can- not make one action. ... As therefore, in the other imita- tive arts, the imitation is one, when the object imitated is one, so the plot, being an imitation of an action, must imitate 1 Aristotle, Poetics, VII. lo DRAMATIC UNITY If one action and that a whole, the structural union of the parts being such that, if any one of them is displaced or removed, the whole will be disjointed and disturbed." ^ " Epic poetry agrees with Tragedy in so far as it is an imita-'^/ tion in verse of characters of a higher type. . . . They differ, I again, in length : for Tragedy endeavors, as far as possible, J to confine itself to a single revolution of the sun, or but V slightly to exceed this limit; whereas the Epic action has no-^ limits of time." ^ ' / / ^ ■ The first two passages quoted, emphasizing the ^ \^ peed for what is technically known as " unity of agtion^^w ill be seen to have permanent and es- j sentiaTl^alidity. The last passage is evidently d//i passing generalization made from the usage of Aristotle's contemporaries. \ It was^ how e v er, taken up by the French of the early sixteenth century and, under the title " unity of time," exalted to the position of a chief canon in dramatic art. A_third requirement, that of " unity of place," though not even suggested by Aristotle, was taken for granted, partly as a corollary of the uijity of time^ partly in imitation of Greek and Senecan usage. These three canons, supported by the authority of the French Academy, and, after some resistance, ac- cepted and defended by Corneille, determined the form of French drama until the beginning of this century, when Victor Hugo, in Hernani, broke bounds, and the " Romantic " reaction became powerful. In Germany the drama for a time slavishly followed French models, but the break 1 Aristotle, Poetics, VIII. « lb., V. 12 LAW with the unities came somewhat earlier than in France, and may be taken as dating from Lessing's notes on dramatic writing, published between 1767 and 1769. In England the period of great drama fell so much earlier than in France or in Germany, that it escaped almost altogether the tyranny of " classic " tradition. To Shakespeare, Aristotle can have been Httle more than a name, and though Seneca's tragedies were translated in his Hfetime, their influence was only one of the factors which determined the form of the national drama.^ Yet, relatively small as was their influence in our own literature, the " unities " have been too im- portant elsewhere to be passed over in a discussion of the drama. Moreover, the very absurdities into which they led their adherents are ipstructive as to the true basis of dramatic theory. Nothing, for ex- ample, could be more suggestive than the treatise in which Corneille ^ defends The Three Unities , of Action, of Timey and of Place, A few extracts will indicate his position. " The fiiie regarding the unity of time is based ugo n this remark of Aristotle, * that the tragedy ought to confine the duration of its action within one revolution of the sun, or to try to exceed this but slightly.'^^These words have given occasion to this famous controversy, whether they ought to ^ For the blending of the Senecan and the national tradition, of. R. Fischer, Zur Kunstentwicklung der Englischen Tragodie. 2 P. Corneille, Discours III, J^es Trois lMtis. » Note Corneille's mistranslation of Aristotle, which really begs the whole question. Compare Butcher's translation, quoted above, p. zx. DRAMATIC UNITY 1$ be understood to mean a natural day of twenty-four hours^ or an artificial day of twelve. . . . For my part, I find that there are subjects which it is so inconvenient to reduce within so brief a time, that not only would I grant them the entire twenty-four hours, but I would even avail myself of the license allowed by the philosopher to exceed this number a little, and would without scruple extend it to thirty." Jn support of the rule he argues thus : " The dramatic poem is an imitation, or, better, a portrait of the actions of men; and there is no doubt that portraits are the more excellent in proportion as they the more closely ^V/ resemble their original. The representation [of a drama on pJ&i^ stage] lasts two hours, and the verisimilitude would be Qj/ perfect if the action which it presented did not demand Y^ more for its actual occurrence. Let us not, then, fix upon either twelve hours or twenty-four, but let us compress the action of the poem into as brief a space as we possibly can, in order that its representation have the greater verisimilitude and be the more perfect." I As to unity of place, he admits that the rule is] not found either in Horace or in Aristotle, but he nevertheless holds it binding, and characterizes as " un peu licencieuse "/the interpretation of it which would allow a single drama to represent such places as a man could go to and return from in a day. He goes on : ** " I could wish, in order not to offend the spectator in any way, that what we represent before him in two hours could actually take place in two hours, and that what we make him see, on a stage that is immovable, could confine itself to one roiom, or one hall, according to choice ; but often this is so inconvenient, not to say impossible, that it is necessary, for place as for time, to admit some enlargement of the limits." 14 LAW He concludes that in cases of absolute necessity it is sufficient that the action be confined within the walls of a single city. At the close of his treatise, however, the common sense of the practical play- wright overcomes for a moment the conventionality — never quite genuine — of the Academician, and asserts itself in the impatient remark : " It is easy for the theorists to be rigid; but if they were to give to the public six or a dozen poems of this sort, they would perhaps widen their rules even more than I have done, when they had seen by experience what restraint their pre- cision causes, and how many beautiful things it banishes from our stage." Evidently the trouble here arises from a misuse of the word " imitation^" and a misconception of what "truth to nature" really is. (Art does not copy nature, it follows and interprets it, and Cor- neille's first proposition, about which he says " there is no doubt " — namely, that the more closely the stage presentation copies the actual events the more perfect is the drama — this proposition is false and subversive of good art ; /f he had followed it consistently, he would not have been the great artist he was. ^ On the other hand, the practice of "following these rules at a distance " has something to be said for it. Shakespeare's dramas would have been better if they had not taken quite so much license. The structure of Lear is marred by the too fre- quent changes of scene, not because these destroy the illusion, but because every such change demands DRAMATIC UNITY 1 5 a fresh adjustment of the reader's mind to the new conditions^ and such use of his energies is waste of his energies unless there is some compensating gain. S jh Antony and Cleopatra we have a n ilhig - trati on of the way in which bad artistic form may "al most nullify the effectiveness of the artist's rgal perceptions ; for the noble scenes scattered th rough the play do not wholly atone for the^sprawling, helter-skelter character of the treatment. In modem plays the elaborateness of the scenery has taken the place of the "classic " tradition as a check on frequent changes of scene, and, except in plays that are chiefly spectacular, the tendency is to cut down scene-shifting, especially within the act. yhe greate j- p.mphfl< ;i< ^, to n, on the inner rathepj falin^e outer aspects tjf th e dramatic situa- tion^jnayji ave had some thi ng, to do with the sim- plificati on of setting and com pactness of treatment that mark§jthe- work of at least some groups of modern dramatists. It may be noted in the plays of the young German writers, Sudermann, Haupt- mann, Fulda; it is yet more striking in the dramas of Ibsen, some of which preserve the same scene throughout, while two. Ghosts and John Gabriel Borkman^ r>^g^fnrA tK^ iir>i»y ^f time i" olmr>g» Corneille's strictest mterpretatioiii. The same is true of Sudermann 'sZ>/., XV, > 44 LAW That is to say, the opposing force must derive its power, n ot only really but evidently, from what has gone before. Aristotle even goes so far as to say that if the event be not really probable, it should at least, by a kind of sleight of hand, be made to seem so.^ But, if such jugglery is neces- sary, it means weakness. The drama should be the place where we may see, more easily recognizable than in actual life, the universal operation and validity of irresistible law. Othello is not a great tragedy because a husband mistakenly kills his wife, but because he is seen to be, in so doing, the victim and the agent of absolute and remorse- less law. Wallenstein is not a great tragedy because the general is assassinated, or even because he is a traitor, but because these things are seen to be the inevitable conclusion of the given series of events. The thing which we must be made to feel is, in Amiel's phrase, "The fatality of the consequences which follow upon every human act, — the leading idea of dramatic art and the most I tragic element of life." ^ To take an opposite instance, the following is a true story of our Civil War : A young Confederate soldier had, after months of service, obtained leave to go home for a few weeks. His companions crowded around him, giving him messages to friends, and letters to be sent when he rt ched a safe district. As he was ready to start he turned back, with the words, "Guess I'll have one more 1 Poetics, XXIV. 2 Journal, 6th April, 185 1. SOURCES OF TRAGIC EFFECT ' 45 look at the Yanks," and went out again to the in- trenchments. He leaned forward on the ridge, raised his head above it, and a bullet from the Union ranks struck him. He fell forward, dead. Such an event appeals to us with more than common force, by virtue of its grim irony. It is one of those accidents which Aristotle would have said have an air of design, but it i s not available for tragedy — at least, not for the chief event of tragedy — because it is, after all y accident. At may, indeed, be said that nothing is accidental, everything is the result of unvarying law, and this is certainly true.) But not all events bear upon them the recognizable stamp of this causality, and there are therefore in our experience a vast num- ber of occurrences which go by the name of acci- dents. The dramatist may be able by his insight and power of presentation to take some of these occurrences out of this category. If he can, they are his to use. If he cannot, they are not fit mate- rial for tragedy; their appearance in drama is a sign of_deca)r, it is one of the d^stmguTshing char- acteristics of the "melodramatic." If examples of this kind of abuse are wanted, they may be found in almost any of the plays of Beaumont and Fletcher. Sucl].^n incident as that just given, if not strictly speaki.:^ tragic, is certainly pathetic, and we are now ready to return to the distinction, suggested at the beginning of the chapter, between these two classes of effects. That is pathetic which involves 46 LAW suffering, unmerited, or out of proportion to guilt, or at least considered without reference to the guilt of the sufferer. It implies a certain passivity on his part, or a resistance so manifestly inadequate as to amount to the same thing. Thus, the suffer- ings of animals under abuse are pathetic, the suffer- ings of sick people are so, so is much spiritual suffering which is recognized as inevitable and en- dured as such. Thus, Ophelia and Desdemona may be called pathetic, while Hamlet and Othello are tragic, and we might multiply examples indefi- nitely. This is perhaps the reason why children have never been used as tragic heroes. To them- selves, their world is great and their emotions in- tense, and, suffering being a wholly subjective matter, their actual sufferings are doubtless often as great as those of adults. But the dramatist is con- cerned wi th act as well as feeling, with struggle as well as pain, and the child has not the command of himselFand of the world to meet these require- ments. Occasionally the treatment of children in literature, by some singular combination of good fortune and skill and sympathy, does approximate the tragic j it does this in Kipling's remarkable story. The Drums of the Fore and A/L But the means by which the author has attained this result, so far as they are discoverable, only go to prove the truth of the general rule. An interesting in- stance of its validity may be found in the three Theban plays of Sophocles. In the (Edipus Rex Antigone and Ismene are simply pathetic figures, SOURCES OF TRAGIC EFFECT 47 used to enhance the effect of their father*s fall. In the CEdipus Coloneus Antigone is rising out of this passivity, but she is still in the main pathetic in this sense. In the Antigone she has become truly tragic, though retaining a certain pathetic tone, by virtue of the quietness of her resistance.^ It is, then, n ot enough that an incident be pa- thet ic — that the recit al of it saddens us. It must not be merely " a tale of things Done long ago, and ill done,*' but must i nvolve action and reaction, blow and counterblow, the conflict of forces . It has become a commonplace of dramatic criti- cism to say that the Greek tragic differs from ours in that their tragic force was a resistless fate, while with us it springs from recognized antecedents, usually to be found in the voluntary acts of the hero himself. Thus Freytag says : "The dramatic ideas and the dramatic actions of the Greeks dispensed with a rational world-order, dispensed, that is, with an interlinking of events that is completely accounted for by the conditions and the onesidedness of the characters represented. We are become freer men, we recognize on the stage no other fate than such as arises out of the essential nature of the hero himself." * 1 It is not meant to imply that the three plays were written in sequence or regarded as a trilogy. They were written at long intervals, and probably not in the order of the story, and were not performed together. Cf. Jebb's introduction to his translation oi Antigone, §§ 22, 23. 2 Die Technik des Dramas^ p. 81. And cf. pp. Iig-ao. I 48 LAW Such phrases are, however, apt to be misleading. Whatever be the difference in the form of state- ment, the underlying tragic motive in CEdipuSy and in Lear or Hamlet or Othello^ is really the same, namely, "the fatality of the consequences which follow upon every human act." It has been assumed that much of Ibsen's work is in this respect Greek rather than modern. But even in Ghosts^ where the idea of an overpower- ing fate is most prominent, this idea affords the tragic material only, and neither in Ibsen nor in Sophocles is the victim of this "fate" regarded, per set as the tragic hero. In Ghosts the victim, Oswald, is not the hero at all — he is a passive sufferer under what the dramatist, mistakenly or not, represents as unalterable law. The real pro- tagonist is Oswald's mother, and the tragic effect is found in the spectacle of her heroic struggle against a power that she finally discovers to be unconquerable. There is, as has been suggested, a type of tragedy which does not entirely conform to the principles we have been deducing. We have examples of it in Shakespeare's Richard III, in Jonson's Catiline and Sejanus, in Massinger's The Roman Actor. In these cases the hero is an absolutely vicious character who holds his place as hero at all only by reason of high intellectual_p,pwers, The tra^fe^y presents to us the spectacle of his downfall, it presents the ven- geance taken by society upon one \vho has done violence to all its laws. It does i^bt portray an SOURCES OF TRAGIC EFFECT 49 inner struggle, it does not present a spiritual prob- lem ; it shows the means by which a moral monster is prevented from permanent enjoyment of the fruits of his vices and his crimes. Such a theme can, it is evident, never be treated so as to attain the highest tragic effect. It may contain much pathos in the subordinate characters — it usually does contain this. When it is great at all its gre atness is intellectual so lely. It might be better to call this g roup s atiric tragedies, with emphasis on the " satiric," for it possesses the grim irony of satire and its judicial attitude, and thus affiliates with one group of satiric comedy. The differences between Richard IIIzxA Sejanus on the one hand, which are called tragedy, and Volpone on the other, which is called comedy, aire superficial ; their kinship is essential. Thus far we have been considering the elements of the tragic in themselves, and, so far as is pos- sible, apart from their effect on the spectator. Aristotle chose the other point of view and defined the tragic solely in terms of its effect.^ The two elements of this effect he made pity and fear, with a third element which may'be here disregarded because, despite the efforts of philosophers and commentators, it is still not quite clear what he meant, nor are we sure that his statement, if we do understand it, is true for us moderns. But pity and fear will be found to be readily convertible into the terms we have used. " Pi ty" corresponds 1 Poetics, VI. 50 LAW to the suffering and the struggle, "fear" corre- sponds to the causality. For Aristotle elsewhere distinguishes pity from fear by saying that pity 1^ is caused by the perception of suffering which we 1 do not think of as affecting ourselves; ^ear is caused by the perception of suffering which we realize may be ours. Now this last element is exactly what is involved in causality, it is the element of universal law, whose universality in- volves us in its sweep, and the perception of which produces, according to our mood, either an en- largement of spirit or a sense of oppression which is probably another name for Aristotle's fear. ^^^- Thus we may sum up the elements of tragic V \ effect in three words : suffering, struggle, causality, j Suffering alone is pathetic merely7~struggle alone ■may be heroic merely (note the Heracles of Euripi- des* Alkestis) ; causality alone gives us the rational i merely : the union of the three produces the tragic. CHAPTER V THE NATURE AND SOURCES OF COMIC EFFECT PERHAPS nothing in the province of literary forms is so baffling as comedy. Considered objectively, as an art-product, it trenches on the realm of the grotesque, confessedly one of the most difficult problems of aesthetics, while in its subjec- tive aspect it requires an analysis of our intellectual processes which has not yet been satisfactorily given us by psychologists. Moreover, in consid- ering concrete literary examples of comedy we are constantly checked by the conviction that the perception of what is comic is something very un- stable, subject t o change with process of time , and showing wide divergence among different classes of society living at the same time. This is, of course, partly true also of our perception of the tragic, but by no means to the same extent. For tragedy, as we have seen, deals with phases of human nature which are relatively eternal and un- changing. We cannot, of course, affirm that our perception of the tragic in the (Edipus is exactly the same as was that of Sophocles' contemporaries; but certainly time has made far less difference here than it has in the understanding and appreciation 52 LAW of Aristophanes, and this quite aside from the in- evitable obscurity of the comic poet's political al- lusions. Apparently, the feelings to which tragedy appeals attained a high degree of development at an earlier time than did those to which comedy appeals, and they have therefore undergone less change. Especially in the last few centuries has the comic sense been undergoing a modification intimately connected with the development of that group of feelings which may be roughly classed as the phil- anthropic. At the end of the sixteenth century, the sweetest-natured gentleman of his age could, without argument, class physical deformity among the legitimate sources of laughter.^ To-day such ia sentiment would at once stamp the holder of it as lacking in fine feeling and sympathetic instincts. It has only recently occurred to Shakespeare stu- dents that many of his scenes which to us are tragic or pathetic were perhaps comic or partly comic to his audience, and, right or wrong in the given instances, the suggestion is extremely interesting as a recognition of the instability, of the comic seiiscj, and as a step toward the study of its evo- lution.^ Such a study is here inadmissible; all we can do is to recognize that the problem exists, and admit that what is to be said in this chapter must 1 Sidney, Defense of Poesy, ed. Cook, p. 51. 2 Cf. John Corbin, The Elizabethan Hamlet, and Barrett Wendell, William Shakespeare. SOURCES OF COMIC EFFECT 53 necessarily be subject to modification when subject^shalljiaye been wo rked outJ urtIi£r^ It is generally agr.ee dTHat the sense of the comi c ^» arisesfrom a perception of incongruity. The in- congruity may be physical or spiritual, or both; it may be perceptual or conceptual, or both; it may exist in space or in time, or in both; and, according as it is one or another of these, there results one or another variety of comic effect. It may be helpful to make a rough scheme of these classes of comic effects, always remembering that any such scheme can only approximate complete- ness and only suggest truth. A. The incongruity is purely conceptual, as in the various forms of wit. Here we may class puns, double meanings, irony, hyperbole, etc. An ex- ample is the well-known question, addressed to a servant carrying a roasted hare, " Is that your own hare or a wig?" B. The incongruity is perceptual as well as conceptual. I. It is based on a perception of successive evejils*__Ih£ source of the comic effect may be stated in general terms as the contrast between expjectation_ and fulfilment. A simple example of this is the case of a man who goes to sit down in a chair, the chair is drawn away, he ^ on tlje floor. Such an occurrence is almost certain to raise a laugh, and the comic in our modern variety show is largely of this character. In comedy of a higher Jvpe, the cases are lesg f 54 LAW simple , but the p r inciple is the same^ The oc- currences are partly or wholly in the realm of the intellectual or social, rather than the physical life. Examples of this are the relations between Rosa- lind and Orlando in As You Like It^ and the devel- opment of the main plots of any of Plautus' or Terence's comedies.^ These last, however, con- tain much of the simpler comic, of the variety- show type; so also does Shakespeare's Comedy of Errors, The case in As You Like It^ on the other hand, affiliates with the next group. Indeed, nearly all ' comedy of intrigue, though .its main plot may be reduced to this type, involves some character-treatment, and must therefore be referred in part to the following group. II. The incongr uity is based on a perception of appearances, simultaneous rather than succes- sive7~"An example is the effect produced by the juxtaposition of a very tall and a very short man, or a very fat and a very thin man. The case is a good one to take, because it is so easily analyz- / able. The two members of the comparison are here supplied to perception, while a third element — the conception of the normal man — exists in the mind of the percipient as the standard from which both deviate. That this conceptual norm must exist, and must be a norm common to both members of the comparison presented, is shown by the fact that the contrast between a tall man and a child is usually not funny to us, because we 1 Cf. infra, pp. 139 flf. SOURCES OF COMIC EFFECT $5 apply different standards to the two; whereas, if the child attempts to take on a man's ways, he brings upon himself the application of the man's standard, and gets laughed at. Similarly, we laugh when a man adopts a child's manner. Again, the sight of a big tree and a small one side by side is not usually funny, because we have no definitely established standard of size for trees in general. The examples might be multiplied indefinitely, showing th e necessity for a common standard, and a definite one. btarting from these simple cases, we find comic effects ranging all the way up to those of very great complexity. The cases of actual physical deformity, of drunkenness, of the milder forms of insanity, all of which have ceased to be funny to many people, still are highly comic to many, and must be classed here; also instances like the use made of Falstaff's huge size, in King Henry /F, or of Ursula's in Bartholomew Fair. Our modern comic stage has much of this sort of thing. More complex, but essentially akin, are the cases where the emphasis is laid upon eccentricities of char- acter. The standard applied may be a moral one, as often in Jonson, or an intellectual one, as per- ' haps in the case of Osric or Polonius in Hamlet, or a social one, as in many of Molifere's plays. Here we must class all the so-called " Comedy of Humors." Here belong all the effects to which Meredith has exclusively applied the term " Com- edy," his standard of reference being the standard 56 LAW of common sense of the well-trained social man considered primarily as in society.^ C. There appears to be yet another source of comic e ffect, w hich is, howeverT^oftunately grow- ing less and less important. That, namely, which ar ises from the mere sight of pain, esp ecially pain involving violent movement. To take, as usual, a simple instance, the sight of a man getting a l] ^ating is apt to appear funny to somepeople,' even to-day, and any one who reads Aristophanes and Plautus and Terence, or even the Elizabethan and pre-Elizabethan drama, is almost forced to con- clude that beatings were esteemed iMnny per se. Of course the comic effect in these cases may often be interpreted as lying not in the beating qua beating, but in the beating qua surprise, as, for instance, in the Comedy of Errors , IV, 4, where Dromio enters, with the rope's end his master had sent him for, and, instead of thanks, gets a taste of it himself. But, placing the most charitable con- struction on such instances, we are still forced to suspect that, in the comic incident as in case of roast pig, the beating may have helped to "im- part a gusto." And this suspicion is strengthened if we note that in all comic surprise the surprise is almost always somewhat disagreeable for the person at whom we laugh, which only means that such comic denouements are, so to speak, beatings in disguise. Perhaps, then, Hobbes was right, at least in his estimate of the natural man, when he 1 Cf. George Meredith, An Essay on Comedy. / SOURCES OF COMIC EFFECT 5/ calls the comic sense "a sudden glory arising from some sudden conception of some eminency in our- selves by comparison with the inferiority of others, or with our own formerly." Leaving out of account this last group, which is partly provided for in group B^ we have two main classes of comic effects, of which the second falls into two parts, according as the contrasts occur simultaneously or successively, and so have to do respectively with plot and with character. But of course, though these groups are separable in thought, they are not so in experience, and the] scheme just given makes, we must repeat, no claii to subtlety of discrimination. For in dealing with anything so shifting and elusive as the comic sense, any schematic statement imposing, as it does, hard and fast limits where no such really exist, must of necessity be inadequate and partly false. But it is nevertheless useful if it be taken as merely indi- cating the main lines of comic effect. It will be found that most literary comedy can be easily put in one or another or in several of the above categories. The first division. Ay may be disregarded in this discussion, since it is only incidental in the drama. Group By I and II are essential, as they concern the treatment of life in its two aspects : character (physical or spiritual) and plot. For it is with these that the drama essentially deals. I^s evident that all the cases suggested in the sclwme just given have certain things in common ; 58 LAW t^ey imply a certain attitude on the part of the per- cipient quite different from the serious or tragic ittitudcv Every case makes an a ppeal to the [Qte llect primar ily, and to the emotions only sec- mdaril y^ if at all. The very word " incongruity " [implies a process of co mparison, w hich implies the reference to some standard or norm. A fat man is funny, not in virtue of his fatness per se^ but because most men- are not fat. One may ask, " But why is that funny?" which is merely to ask why any incongruity is comic. There is as yet no answer, any more than there is to the question why laughter rather than any other bodily contortion should be the physical expression of amusement. We must take these as ultimate facts, and leave their further explanation to the physiological psychologists. ; i To return, the whole matter is seen to be de- jpendent on perception of relations and the as- 'sumption of a standard of reference. But further, the incongruity^will_be_p£rceiyed as comic only if the attention be held closely to the particular contrast to be made. If it is allowed to wander, to take into consideration other aspects of the subject presented, the sense of the comic may give place to some other feeling. The ap- peal has thus far been to the intellect rtierely, and to the intellect working along a narrow and defi- nitely prescribed line. But if the emotions are called in, or if the mind breaks over the prescribed limits of the treatment, the comic incongruity may SOURCES OF COMIC EFFECT 59 be forgotten in more serious thoughts. If, for in- stance, after smiling at the sight of our very tall man walking beside our very short one, we ap- proach them, and suddenly perceive that the short man is a cripple and deformed, the smile vanishes. Why ? Because a whole set of feelings are called into activity of such a nature and strength as quite to overwhelm the intellectual perception of con-' trast. We perceive the contrast, indeed, all the more vividly, but our thought dwells not on the contrast per se, intellectually considered, but on what it involves to the cripple himself. Our emo- tions are aroused, our sympathy is evoked. i Thus it may be said that the perception of the^ comic has in it something arbitrary and limited.^' It requires"a point of view which shall cut off fronj the mental visipn the real issues of life and its vital substance, — the emotions and susceptibilities that make it subject to pleasure or pain. If the view be changed, so as to include these, the comic usually vanishes.^ The distinction is one of treat- \ ment, of attitude, not of original material, and this ; is why the same material may be either comic or tragic according to its treatment"^ wEy "even the same treatment may appear to us comic or tragic according as we fix our attention upon one or another aspect of it; for this reason two people may watch the same occurrence, and one may smile and the other be saddened by it. 1 But cf. injra, p. 65-66. 60 LAW Take as further illustration an instance from life and one from literature : A boy stands convulsed with laughter as he watches the wild contortions of two cats whose tails have been wired together; another boy, too small to interfere, may be suffering actual pain at the same sight. What is the difference? In a sense, both boys are right, for, though they are looking at the same occurrence, what they see is not the same : the thing the big boy sees is funny; the thing the little boy sees is painful. The little boy feels the pain of the tightly wound wire as it cuts into the animals' flesh, he feels the frenzy of the help- less creatures, he resents the brute strength that can willingly cause such tortures. The big boy, on the other hand, simply does not see or feel anything of all this : he sees merely the contortions of the animals, their total failure to comprehend the real cause of their difficulty, and the inade- quacy of the means they take to meet it. At the present time society, on the whole, stands with the small boy and condemns the big one; three centuries ago it would have done precisely the reverse; and each position is intellectually ex- plicable though to us only one seems morally justifiable. Take now an instance from literature : In Lear the subject-matter is the treatment of an old, helpless father by his daughters, and it ii so handled as to be one of the most terrible trage- dies ever written. But is this the only possible 1 SOURCES OF COMIC EFFECT 6l treatment? Turn to Aristophanes, and find in Tlie Clouds precisely the same theme made the basis of a comedy — of comedy, indeed, to appreciate which we must divest ourselves of some modern preconceptions, but genuine comedy nevertheless, and not cruel, simply because it is out of the realm of the emotions entirely. ^i There is, then, this f undamental ^ difference between tragedy and come dy: a difference in point of view — a difference not in the thing as pefceiveS^'ByTKe eye, but in the thing as conceived by the mind. We may say that tragedy interprets life by emphasizing its vital realities; comedy re- constructs it by emphasizing certain aspects of it^ selected so as to make good cor^trasts, striking in- congruities. Each is eminently selective, but the prmciple of selection is different. — ATrd~the^ comic standpoint may be assumed toward almost any sub- ject: it may be momentary, and we have its light playing over the situation for an instant and then going out, as when Hamlet rouses himself from his bitter melancholy to i^ake sport of Polonius or Osric; or it may be pervasive, affecting the entire conception of life as represented by the artist,' as in Shakespeare's early comedies {^Love's Labour's Lost, Comedy of Errors^ and Jonson's typical ones; or it may^^single out certain characters for comic treatment in the midst of an otherwise serious presentation of a subject, as in Shakespeare's later comedies. And according as it is more or less pervasive do we get all the gradations between un- r7 \ 62 LAW mixed comedy or pure farce at the one extreme and the tragedy with comic lights at the other. To return now to our classification of comic effects. It has thus far be en based on differences in subject-matter, and we have distinguished the come3y whose main point lies in the incongruities ^ men's character, from the comedy which em- phasizes mainly the incongruities in the things that happen to men. And if The Comedy of Errors is a purer example of the second class than King Henry IV is of the first, this is because, dramatically, character can scarcely be presented save through action, and Aristotle's assertion — difficult to explain as it stands^ — is unquestionably true if we change its application and read : " With- out action there cannot be a comedy; there may be without character."^ ^ But in the group of character comedies there is another basis of distinction. For incongruity of character implies — it springs from — imperfection of character. If a man's character were in per- fect poise, if it were absolutely symmetrical, it would not be comic. Co medy, then, is really based on imperfections in character, but consid- ered from the comic, not the tragic standpoint. Now it is evident that one may view these im- perfections in one of several ways: one may simply enjoy them as such, without forming a judgment of the moral or intellectual level of the 1 Cf. Poetics, VI, " Without action there cannot be a tragedy; there may be without character." SOURCES OF COMIC EFFECT 6$ person in whom they are manifested. Or one may, without losing sight of the comic, regard the person with sympathy, or even love. Or one may, consciously or unconsciously, make a judgment, and there is added to our perception of the comic, and modifying this perception, a feeling of su- periority, moral or intellectual or both, while we may express this judgment in terms varying from the gentlest irony to the severest condemnation, according to our mood and the nature of the sub- ject. This was the sort of comedy of which Sid- ney was speaking when he said, " The comedy is an imitation of the common errors of our life, which he representeth in the most ridiculous and scornful sort that may be, so as it is impossible that any beholder can be content to be such a one." ^ The significant thing here is the use of the two words " scornful " and " ridiculous. " " Ridic- ulous " carries with it a notion of superiority on the part of the percipient which is not so palpably implied in other words for the comic; "scornful" still further emphasizes this, leaving out the notion of the comic altogether ; and the conclud- ing phrase of the passage makes the writer's standpoint yet clearer. Such a passage, especially coming from Sidney, is highly significant. What he would have said if he had lived to see the Shakespearean comedy we can only surmise. Pe-haps he might then have seen the possibility of an ♦^her kind of comic per- 1 Tk£ Defense of Poesy, p. 28. \ \ % \ 64 LAW ception, wherein we laugh at the folly and love the fool. But, as it stands, the passage fairly repre- sents the type of comedy we have termed judicial. Jonson's is a stronger statement of the same view: " But, with an armed, and resolved hand, I'll strip the ragged follies of the time Naked as at their birth. . . . ... and with a whip of steel, Print wounding lashes in their iron ribs. "... Well, I will scourge those apes. And to these courteous eyes oppose a mirror, As large as is the stage whereon we act; Where they shall see the time's deformity Anatomized in every nerve and sinew. ... my strict hand Was made to seize on vice. . . . ^ And Meredith's description of Moli^re's comedy gives us only another aspect of this kind of comedy : " Never did man wield so shrieking a scourge upon vice, but his consummate self-mastery is not shaken while administering it. Tartuffe and Har- pagon, in fact, are each made to whip himself and his class, the false pietists, and the insanely covet- ous. Moliere has only set them in motion. He strips Folly to the skin, displays the imposture of the creature, and is content to offer her better clothing. . . . The source of his wit is clear reason: it is a fountain of that soil; and it springs 1 Every Man out of His Humour, Induction. SOURCES OF COMIC EFFECT 6$ to vindicate reason, common sense, Tightness and justice."^ These two attitudes, the non- judicial and the judicial, though of course neither one is ever adopted witli perfect consistency by any given writer, make a convenient basis for distinguishing - the t wo main tendencies of comedy. If we seek for literary types, we shall find the one predomi- nating in Shakespeare, Dickens, George Eliot; the other predominating in Jonson, Moli^re, Thack- eray, Meredith; while Addison and Goldsmith are on the border line between. We have called the second sorj^atjriccomedj;, because its tendency is toward satire. This will be apparent if we make a mental survey of the two fields of comedy and satire, and see how difficult it is at some points to distinguish them. Making Shakespeare one end of the scale, and Juvenal the other, we find next Shakespeare, but with satiric qualities, Addison and Thackeray; close to Juve- nal, but with comic qualities, Swift, with Pope and Dryden as subordinate types; between these would come Jonson and Moliere, while Aristophanes verges rather on satire, and Rabelais rather on comedy, though a rigid classification of either of these last is beyond possibility. On the other hand, the pure comedy shades off into other forms. It is, we have said, non-judicial, but one of the reasons why it is non-judicial is because it is sympathetic. Now we have seen 1 Meredith : An Essay on Comedy, pp. 27, 28, F v^ 66 LAW that keen^ sjnmpathy is usually incompatible with comic^ perception. That it was inevitably and invariably incompatible we expressly did not affirm. For here, as in the case of satiric comedy, there is no hard and fast line drawn, but the two things may shade off the one into the other. We may have the purely comic, where the sympathies, in this sense, are not invoked, as in the Launce episodes of The Two Gentlemen of Verona; or as in Sir John Falstaff, — the pure comic prepon- derating, but enough sympathy so that transition to the pathetic is possible, as hinted in the scene of Falstaff' s rebuff at the hands of the young king, and the account of his death. ^ Accentuate the sympathy farther, retaining the comic, and you get Cervantes' comedy; accentuate it still farther ind you get the Fool in Lear. Thus we find that the comic sense tends to vary in one of these two directions, — toward the pathetic or even the tragic on the one hand, and toward the satiric on the other. And it is evident that in the case of comedians like Jonson and Moliere, who stand part way on the road toward satire, any discussion which does not take into account the satiric as well as the comic aspect must necessarily be inadequate. One more quality of comedy must be mentioned here, though its purport will be more fully shown '^King Henry IV, Part II. Act V, Scene 5, King Henry V, Act II, Scenes 2 and 3, Probably the first of these Scenes was intended by Shakespeare to be comic. SOURCES OF COMIC EFFECT 6/ in the chapter on comic plot-structure. It is this : tion of its view, leaves out much of life; raore- over, tfieltHmgs it leaves out are those things that we are accustomed to call the serious realities of life, — the realities of pain and death, and the in- exorable sway of law. He nce, comedy is not bouujd, as is tragedy, to base itself on law; it may make a much freer use of what we call chance; the events and people with which it deals may, if we may use a figure, all be largely external. As an actual fact, comedy does do this, and compared with tragedy, the emphasis on causality, on law, is slight. Summing up: we have seen that comic effects have a rommon basis in incongruity^ contrast; that the incongruity may lie principally in the realm of events, and we have comic intrigue, or in the realm of appearances, and we have comic char- acter j^ while usually both these are found in con- junction, but with preponderating emphasis on one or the other, which gives us farce or intrigue co medy on the one hand and character comedy on the other. We have seen, too, that comedy differs from tragedy not so much in subject-matter as iiT point of view and treatment. Finally, we have noted that comedy itself varies"' according to the attitude of the author or the percipient, tending, where it becomes judicial, toward satire; where it becomes sympathetic, toward pathos and tragedy. PART II — TECHNIQUE CHAPTER I THE TWO TYPES OF DRAMA THUS far we have been considering the drama with reference to the general principles which govern it. We have distinguished drama from other literary forms; have considered those qualities which have always been deemed indis- pensable for good dramatic effect, namel y, truth, unity, proportion, seriojisnessj^andjha ye ^ eter- mined, at least in part, what are the essential ele- ments of tragedy and comedy. Turning now from these fundamental principles, which apply with more or less exactness to other forms of art than the drama, we come to consider in detail the way in which the dramatic form works itself out, — the rules of its technique. But here, too, before proceeding to those more mechanical regulations which are a part of the craft and are somewhat variable, we ought first to emphasize such laws as are a part of the art and are basic, and therefore permanent. The serious drama, as we have seen, presents a 68 THE TWO TYPES OF DRAMA 69 Struggle between two forces. Like any struggle, it proceeds from the first repose to the first grap- pling, then follows the tug and strain of the wrestle, until a moment comes when the advantage begins to go with one side or the other. From that moment on, the struggle moves inevitably, though perhaps not in a direct line, on to the final overthrow of one of the contestants. Such ist the course of every drama. The character of the ! contest may be of various kinds; it may be single combat, — man against fellow-man ; or man against society and social law ; or man against ' himself; while the sphere of the contest may be in the physical or the spiritual world, or in.both. In any case, the play Jalls_J.ogicallX ijUo two parts, called the r ising and the falling ac tion. whose point of junction and division is this de- cisive moment just spoken of, called in dramatic terms the clim|fx or turning-point. In these two parts are set forth respectively the actioasof the two contestants, the rising action being devoted predominantly to the one that is the aggressor, the falling action to the other. There are evidently two possibilities: (i) the hero takes the initia - tive^ is the ag gressor, or (2) he is in the beg in- n ings relatively passive and acts only when he is d rawn or driven into action bv the attack of the opposing force. In the first case, the hero is most prominent in the rising action, in the second, he does not come to his fullest expression until the falling action. Of the first sort, we may take as 70 TECHNIQUE examples Macbeth, Romeo and Juliet, Richard III, Antigone. Of the second, Othello, more doubtfully, Lear. Thus in Macbeth: in Act I, Scene 3 suggests his aggressive attitude toward his king, and hence toward the political and social law; Scene 4 further emphasizes this; Scenes 5 and 7 clinch his definite determination to kill the king, a determination in which Lady Macbeth is even more prominent than Macbeth himself. In Act II we have the murder of Duncan; in Act III the murder of Banquo. But in Scene 4 of this act, i.e. almost the exact mechanical middle of the play, occurs the banquet- scene, which presents the beginning of the reaction in Macbeth' s own spirit; in Scene 5 Hecate dooms him with the authority of her magic power; in Scene 6 we have the beginning of the political re- action. (Note the beautiful completeness of this scene-group, wherein the triple reaction — the spiritual, the supernatural, the political — is fore- shadowed.)^ After the banquet- scene Macbeth ceases to have prominence. In Act IV his activity does overlap a little in the murder of Macduff's children, but it is significant that Macbeth himself t. ^s not appear here, and the bulk of the act is taken up with the opposition, — hence the elaboration of the scene in Macduff's castle and in the English court between Malcolm and Macduff. In Act V we have a simple work- ing out of the double catastrophe, for Macbeth 1 Cf. infra, p. 83. THE TWO TYPES OF DRAMA 7 1 and Lady Macbeth, and except for the sleep- walking scene, the act oscillates between Macbeth and the insurgent army.^ Thus, resuming, we have the first two acts and half of the third devoted to exposition of the double hero's activity; the last half of the third act and all of the fourth and fifth to exposition of the reaction of this activity. The play illustrates, with diagrammatic clearness, the essential charac- ter of this type of drama. Compare with this Othello, In the first scene we have the arch enemy, lago, with his fellow- conspirator and tool, Roderigo. Their opposition is stated, and its activity begun. In Scene 2 lago is still the central figure, in Scene 3 comes Othello's great speech before the council, but the scene ends again with lago and Roderigo, concerting their villany : " I have't, it is engender'd. Hell and night, Must bring this monstrous birth to the world's light" In Act II, Scene i, Desdemona and Othello ap- pear, but are quiet, almost colorless. The illu- mination is still focussed brilliantly upon lago, and the scene closes with his elaboration of his plan of revenge. Scene 3 wi' ^f^sses his first deci- sive move, in working out that part of his scheme that concerns Cassio. In the first half of Act III lago strikes directly at Othello, and the end of this scene leaves him now in his turn thoroughly 1 Cf. infra, p. 73. 72 TECHNIQUE roused, with all his untamable passions inflamed. From this point on Othello receives greater and greater emphasis, though lago is not allowed to fall into the background. In Scene 4 occurs the first encounter between Othello and Desdemona, which involves the question of the handkerchief. In Act IV, Scene i, lago still works up his evi- dence; Scene 2 has the second interview of Othello with Desdemona, and ends with the plan of lago and Roderigo for Cassio's death; Scene 3 gives Desdemona her needed prominence. Act V, Scene i, has the murder of Cassio by Roderigo, which means the perfecting of lago's plans, but which also ultimately involves his own ruin. Scene 2 has the catastrophe. Thus it will be seen that, in contrast to Mac- betfiy this play begins by presenting its hero at poise, in a state of repose from which he is not roused until the third act, while from the third act on his passionate activity moves forward in a continuous and tremendous crescendo. Any one who remembers the part as acted by the elder Sal- vini will remember the overwhelming effect of this crescendo as brought out by the almost brutally titanic power of the actor. The two types of drama possess each its peculiar advantages and drawbacks, and each makes its different and characteristic impression. In the first, the interest of the audience is more imme- diately enlisted for the hero, who appears as ag- gressive and defiant. But the last half of the play THE TWO TYPES OF DRAMA 73 is harder to make effective, because the opposing force is apt to be less concentrated and less able to focus the attention. It is, in_general^less inter- esting to see the hero^acted_upQnj^ than to s^e h im ac ting. In Macbeth we must all feel the weakness of the second half compared with the first, the immediate falling off in effectiveness after the ban- quet-scene. Yet it was necessary, as we have seen, to set forth the activity of the opposition, and Shake- speare was forced to do this in a series of scenes which tend to scatter the attention and dissipate the interest of the audience. In Othello^ on the other hand, the interest constantly rises throughout the play, beginning on a low and unemphatic note, and rising through scene after scene to the final clashing chords of the catastrophe. The play can scarcely even be said to have its climax in the third act.^ It is rather a steady ascent through a series of scenes, each more intense and decisive than the preceding. Possibly, however, it may be said that the contrast with Macbeth is not quite fair, because in Othello the opposing force is also concentrated in one person, — is embodied in the genius of lago, — so that it is as if the play had two heroes, one for each half of the action. On this basis the drama might after all be classed with Macbeth, because lago is in one sense the hero, and his activity begins at once. This may be so, but per- haps it only shows that a drama of the highest power will have the strength of each type and 1 CC infra, pp. 77-78, and p. 84. 74 TECHNIQUE avoid the weakness of each. But, on the whole, the Macbeth type has been the one o ftenest adopted by the great dramatists. Shakespeare's plays almost" atr conform to it, and this is one of the reasons why his plays are so often weak in their working out, why the second half often fails to fulfil the promise of the first. It is significant that two of his plays of which this is not true, Othello and Lear^ are of the other type. In the Greek drama we find both types. To begin with, however, we must remember that the Greek tragedy often leaves out what would be our rising action, and begins somewhere about our turning-point, or even beyond that, in the falling action, at the fourth or fifth act. Thus, when Freytag places the CEdipus Tyrannus in the second class with Lear and Othello^ he is using an inap- plicable standard. For, to the Greek mind, what went before the written play was also a part of it. Thus, the real plot of the CEdipus may be stated, for our purposes, as follows : A young man slays his father and marries his mother, and by this double crime, committed in ignorance, gains pos- session of a throne. As a result, misfortune de- scends upon his people, ruin upon him. That is to say, he first acts, boldly and decisively; then he suffers the results of his acts. The parallel with Macbeth is apparent, though disguised by the circumstance that whereas the Englishman took his hero at the beginning of his crime and followed him through to the end, the Greek began near the THE TWO TYPES OF DRAMA 75 end, presupposing the earlier acts. The CEdipus Tyrannus may be considered as beginning at a point corresponding to the banquet-scene in Mac- beth ; that proviso made, the correspondences become clear, and the play is seen to be one of the first type. To class it with Othello is to miss its significance. The Philoctetes and the Ajax may, however, properly be so classed ; probably, also, the Electra, In each of these the hero appears as reacting against forces that have been in long-continued opposition to him. On the other hand, Antigone is plainly of the first type, like Macbeth and (Edi- pusy only here there is no difficulty, because the play includes within itself, formally, and not by implication merely, both the deed and the result. CHAPTER II LOGICAL DIVISIONS OF THE ACTION WHATEVER be the disposition of the con- testing forces, certain things in the work- ing out are unvarying. There is always a rising action, there is ahvays a falling action, no matter to which of these the chief activity of the hero is relegated; there is always a turning-point and a catastrophe; there are certain other minor but essential elements. It is well to consider these before we take up the more mechanical divisions of acts and scenes, and they will be discussed under the heads : Introduction, Rising Action, Climax, Falling Action, Catastrophe. And, first, it will be well to look for a moment at the diagram which has, since Freytag presented it, become stock property in dramatic exposition. The play is represented as a pyramid, rising to its turning-point or climax and falling to its catas- trophe. The metaphor will be found to be a helpful one. When the climax occurs at about the mechanical middle of the play, the diagram may be made thus (in the diagrams, A = introduction, 76 LOGICAL DIVISIONS OF THE ACTION 7/ B = rising action, C = turning-point, D = falling action, E = catastrophe) : while, according as it falls before or after this point, we may modify the figure thus: or thus indicating in the one case a rapid rising action and a slow descent, and in the other the reverse. Othello is, in one interpretation, an example of the last, if we make the steps of the rising action the successive scenes in which lago arouses and fixes the jealous suspicion of Othello. According to this. Scene 3 of Act III is only one member of the yS TECHNIQUE ascent, which rises further in Scene 4 of the same act, and culminates in Act IV, Scene i . The fall- ing action may be said to begin in the same scene, where Othello, deeming his fears confirmed, first strikes Desdemona. This places the turning-point appreciably beyond the middle of the play, and gives a relatively short and abrupt descent.^ [i] Intro due tio7i. The introduction, whose pur- pose is to prepare the listener for the play, used often to be set apart from the play itself as a pro- logue, or given by one of the actors in a set speech. It is by Shakespeare incorporated into the tissue of the play, and forms the first scene, or occasionally a scene-groupj There are cer- tain things .which it must do, and others which it may do. ut must, quickly and deftly, put the hearer in possession of enough facts to make him intelligent in following the playj It must tell him who the speakers are and prepare him for those who are soon to enter; ^ must at least hint to him the place and time of the action, although this duty is much lightened by the extensive use of scenery on our modern stage. Besides this, it may set the tone of the piece, indicate its " stim- mung," thus throwing the sensitive listener into the right mood, much in the same way that the "vorspiel " to some operas does (instance that to Lohengrin and to Parsifal). But not all dramatic introductions are thus successful. As instances where they are so, may be mentioned the witch 1 Cf. supra, p. 73, and infra, p. 84. LOGICAL DIVISIONS OF THE ACTION 79 scene in Macbethy the scene of the mob Xn Julius Ccdsar^ of the night watch on the battlements in Hamlety of the street brawl in Romeo and Juliet, It is evident that the management of the intro- duction is a severe test of the author's skill. He must tell his audience a great deal without seeming to tell them anything. To this end various de- vices have been employed. We are familiar, on our modern stage, with the chambermaid who vi- vaciously chronicles the family history as she dusts the family apartment; another resource, often used by the Elizabethans, who had not discovered the chambermaid, is that of the friend just returned from abroad, who must be told all the news. Some such expedient the author is almost forced to employ, even at the risk of seeming "stagey," and few indeed are the plays whose beginnings have not some trace of effort and artificiality; for there is one thing more fatal to a play than artificiality, an d that is obscurit y. The audience ^ must at any price be made to understand what they are witnessing, and be made to do it with the least possible effort on their part, so that even the boy in the gallery is quite clear in his mind. Under the most favorable conditions, it will always be a rather trying interval, this process of comprehen- sion, and the habitual reader of plays is often con- scious of a sinking of the heart as he is confronted with a new set of "dramatis personae." Many of Shakespeare's beginnings are not wholly successful : instance the first scene of Hamlety whose perfec- 80 TECHNIQUE tion is destroyed by Horatio's tedious account to Marcellus of the political relations of Denmark. Good beginnings are those of Macbeth, I, 2; Othello y I, I ; the first part of the opening scene in Coriolanus} the whole of the first scene of Romeo and Juliety and of Julius Casar, It is an inter- esting study to go over some of these scenes and see just how much information we have been given, which is absolutely, needed to understand the play, and how deftly and without effort this has been accomplished. It is almost a rule of the stag e that the introduc- tion shall prepare the audience to receive t he hero, but that the Jifirp Mmsj^^ldLaQt.appear. Where the scene is a lQng_Qne^ this is not so necessarily the case, and the hero often enters toward its close (see the opening scene or scenes of Julius CaTdr\' Macbeth, Hamlet, Othello, Romeo and Juliet, Coriolanus). On the other hand. King Lear plunges at once into the action — for the few preliminary speeches of Gloucester can scarcely be counted — since, by good fortune of the plot and the author's skill in taking advan- tage of it, there was no need of a preliminary exposition. In a few cases, moreover, the hero appears at once, and the reason for this is easily apparent. Thus, in Richard III, the first monologue of the king is typical of the way in which his personality dominates the whole drama. lago's part in the first scene of Othello may be similarly interpreted. LOGICAL DIVISIONS OF THE ACTION 8 1 if we take the play as having a double hero, and the difference in their respective activities will account for the introduction of lago and not Othello into the first scene. Compare, too, the different effect of Marlowe's Jew of Malta j where the Jew himself is at once introduced to us, and Shake- speare's Merchant of Venice, where he does not enter until the second scene. There is a corre- sponding difference, which it is hard to think acci- dental, between the parts played by the two men in the respective plays, and the attitude of the two authors toward them. [ 2] Rising Action. After the introduction comes the action proper of the play. It begins with what is called the "exciting force," that is, the force which is to change things from their condit ion o f bal ance or repose , and precipitate the dramatic conflict^^ From the moment of the exciting force to the moment of the turning-point, the activity thus begun, be it that of the hero or of the opposition, must show a continual, though not necessarily an evert'-paced, gain in power and reachj We have noted how this continual rise is illustrated by Mac- beth: the first two scenes form the introduc- tion, and the third scene, Macbeth' s meeting with the witches, furnishes the exciting force. Here first is suggested to him the thought that afterwards develops into act, in the murders of Duncan and Banquo, while the fulfilment of the first two of the witches' prophecies, at the end of the same scene, serves to emphasize their authority. From this G . 82 TECHNIQUE point through to the turning-point we have a series of scenes, each of which advances the action somewhat, each carries Macbeth and his wife more and more irretrievably forward along the path they have chosen. The only exception is Act II, Scene 4, which is, also, the only one which does not bring forward one or both the pro- tagonists. The scene is perhaps introduced to suggest the beginning of the return action, and, rather curiously, it is balanced by Act IV, Scene I, where Macbeth* s baleful activity overlaps into the return action. This is only another instance of the singularly symmetrical structure of the play.' \ CBut the r ijing action ought also to introduce t he oppos ing forces and make the audience familiar with . ^he characters in which they are em bodied, although it is left for the second part of the play to gi ve them greater prominence^ i Thus, the flight of Malcolm to safety in England hints at a future opponent to Macbeth; Macduff's refusal to go to the coronation of Macbeth at Scone is significant; the failure to kill Fleance suggests the possibility of further checks; the refusal of Macduff to come to court emphasizes his hostility already shadowed. By this means we are prepared for the return actioii even before it has actually set in ; we are constantly reminded that this seeming success is perhaps only strengthening the hand of avenging fate, that "God is not mocked"; and we are thus, in the 1 Cf. supra, p. 70. LOGICAL DIVISIONS OF THE ACTION I3 first part, kept from forgetting what in the second part is to be borne in upon us with tremendous force, namely, the universality and inviolability of law. [ 3] Turning-point or Climax, At a certain point in the rising action a moment comes when the activity of the aggressive force is com - pleted ; a moment after which the reversal be- gins, and there looms into view the force that is to dominate the last half of the action. This point is tfie'ciimax, or, beUer, tHe turning-point of the play.^ It is, of course, possible intellect- ually to separate this climactic point of the rise from the initial point of the fall, but actu- ally the two moments are often found organi- cally united in the same scene or scene-group. If the play is of the first type, the turning-point will be the moment when the hero completes the accomplishment of his purposes and feels the check of opposition. Thus in Macbeth the ban- quet-scene begins with the news of Banquo*s death, which assures the usurper that his most dreaded rival is removed. But with the news comes the first check, "Fleance is scaped," and this is followed up by the appearance of Banquo's ghost, foreboding the retribution to come. The two following scenes may be considered as com- plementary to this, but they are, very properly, less elaborated, and are transitional to the return action.^ 1 Cf. supra, p. 70. 84 TECHNIQUE In the second type of play, the turning-point shows the converse of this, and represents the hero as passing from a state of relative quiescence to a state of activity. Thus in Othello the great scene, III, 3, between lago and Othello makes the be- ginning of the turn, though here again we ought perhaps to make a two-membered climax, consist- ing of this scene plus the first scene of Act IV to the word "Devil!" spoken by Othello to Desde- mona, and the blow that goes with it. In a play where the struggle is subjective, and both the con- tending forces are lodged within the hero himself, the turning-point should be the moment when that force which is ultimately to conquer first gains its decided supremacy. Of this type is Shakespeare's Antony and Cleopatra, a play which, however, illustrates dramatic principles as much by their breach as by their observance. Its theme is the struggle between passion and honor, but in the actual working out this theme is obscured by the crowd of unessential details. Its turning-point should come at the point where passion conquers. There are two places where this point might be said to be: first, in Athens, when, after the de- parture of Octavia as mediator to Caesar, Antony returns to Egypt and Cleopatra; second, at Actium, when Antony flies, following the galleys of Cleo- patra. In Shakespeare's play the first of these two points has been wholly ignored, the second has been very inadequately treated* The battle itself is given to a messenger to describe, and the fol- LOGICAL DIVISIONS OF THE ACTION 8$ lowing scene, III, 2, supremely impressive as its first part is, is not enough. It would have been right if set in a larger scene-group, like some of the scene-groups in Hamlet or in Julius Ccesar; but, taken as a single one out of the thirteen scenes of which this act is composed, it is artistically in- adequate, out of proportion. It is, of course, not necessary that the climax be a scdn^ToFgrear out- ward magnificence, though, in fact, it often is so (cf. Macbeth f Julius Ccesar) y yet a c ertain outwar c impressivene ss is, after all, requ isite, simply be- cause, as we have seen earlier, the drama deals solely with the phenomenal. It cannot, as do Ibsen and Maeterlinck in some of their later and more extreme works, deal apparently in common- places and expect us to read into these the most supreme spiritual verities. It cannot, as does Shakespeare in this play, scatter half a dozen superb scenes through a play that has a total of forty-two, and leave the hearer to choose these half dozen to remember. The dramatist should expect much of his audience, but not so much as this. He should do his own selecting, his own emphasizing, for herein lies the difference be- tween the raw material and the art-product. On the other hand,|the ' turning-point or climax^/v^ must be spiritually emphatic asj^en^as_oii£^axdly imposin'g^^fKe^HTmax Ui Macbeth is not the climax in virtue of presenting a royal banquet with rich, massive effects; that in Julius Ccesar is not so in virtue of its impressive massing of S6 TECHNIQUE senators assembled in the capitol of the world. There must be inner significance as well, as in these cases there is. So, too, the cli max need not be the mechanical middle of the play; it must be its spiritual centre, the point toward which it makes from the beginning, and from which it passes downward to the end. [^]L7^<2///«i;' Action. What the exciting force is to the rising action, that the tragic force is to the falling action. It is, as we have seen, often closely united to the climax; sometimes they are, in a sense, one and the same, as in the (Edipus Tyrannusy where the very announcement that seems to make him perfectly secure really precipi- tates the discoveries that end in the catastrophe. However this may be, the tragi c force is the ini- tiation of the counter activity that is to govern the second half of the play and bring about the catastrophe. In Macbeth^ as we have seen, it is tripartite;^ in Romeo and Juliet it is dual, being embodied in the authority of the state and of Juliet's parents; note that here one of these two — that of the state — is emphasized before the cli- max, the other follows immediately upon the cli- max, being incorporated in the same scene with it. These two forces are the occasion of the lovers* ruin — the occasion rather than the cause, for the causal connection is, after all, indirect, and if the falling action in the play has a weak- ness, it is in this fact, — the fact, namely, that the iCf.p.70.*' LOGICAL DIVISIONS OF THE ACTION 8; forces of the falling action are not the forces that bring about the catastrophe.^ If, as is commonly the case, the play is of the first type, and the hero has been prominent in the first half of the play, the falling action will bring forward the characters of the opposition, and the hero will either be in the background, as in Mac- bethy or, if this is not the case, his treatment will be different, as in Romeo and Juliet, I The management of the falling action offers \U peculiar difficulties. Up to the climax there has ^ \r^ been growing suspense. After the tragic force V, appears, and the development of the opposition has begun, the listener begins to foresee what is to come, his mind naturally plunges forward, and he is impatient if the dramatist's exposition be slower than his own thought-processes. It is like being forced to await the completion of a slowly spoken sentence, whose point we have already anticipated. Perhaps this is the reason why the turning-point and tragic force are often put late in t he ^pl aV. making the actual duration of the return action less than that of the rise. But there is another device for breaking through this over- confident expectancy of the listener. It is the insertion, in the midst of the falling action, of an event which for a moment breaks its advance, seems even to turn it back; there is shown a way of escape for the victim, or at least a jutting crag by which he may delan^i^fall. This is called the el^^j^f 145. 88 TECHNIQUE *^ final suspense." Ins tances of it are: the vic- tory of Antony in Antony and Cleopatra, IV, 7; the successful carrying out by Romeo and Juliet of all the first part of their scheme; the remorse of Edmund in Lear, V, 3, which moves him to revoke his order to kilf Lear and Cordelia; the news brought to King Richard in Richard ///, IV, 4, that the army and navy of his opponents are both scattered; in Julius Ccesar, taking the first part as a whole in itself, Caesar's determina- ■ tion not to go to the senate house that particular day. Thus the dramatist, having throughout labored to impress upon us the inevitableness of fate, now '^ for a moment reverses his methods and tries to undo all this. But only for a moment; the check' has done its duty by keying up the slackened at- tention, and this done, the action swings back to its true movement and plunges forward to the catastrophe. [5]^ Catastrophe. We h ave traced the dramatic struggle through its rise, turning-point, and fall. We now come to its termination. In our ordi- nary thought, the catastrophe is taken as almost synonymous with death, and this is based on a true conception. For the drama deals with hunian life, and death is, for the dramatist, the end. It is the fitting conclusion for the tragedy because \t really concludes — it is final, precluding possi- bility of amendment or Evidently, however, ^^^^^haracter depends, W LOGICAL DIVISIONS OF THE ACTION 89 not on itself, but upon the nature of the action which it concludes. Death is in itself always solemn, it often moves to pity, sometimes to horror; but it is tragic only when it comes asjhe / natural, the inevitable conclusion of a tragic struggled And in such cases the death itself will ofibn actually seem a relief, just because it does terminate the struggle, just because it has been felt to be inevitable and so its occurrence relaxes the strain of expectation. This is the case in Macbeth. After the horror of the hero's life, its baleful activity without, its moral disintegration within, the physical conflict at the end comes as a return to health. Macbeth himself feels it. After the first sinking of heart that comes with the loss of his last support, there follows the rebound, the natural, if desperate joy in a fair fight, and there is a ring of freedom in his last defiance : " Lay on, Macduff, And damn'd be he that first cries, Hold, enough ! " Similarly, Brutus certainly feels death to be a release as he says : " Caesar, now be still : I killed not thee with half so good a will." In King Lear the consummation of the tragedy is, it is true, in a death; not, however, Lear's death, but Cordelia's, and this is tragic, not as it concerns Cordelia, but as it touches Lear himself. The climax of " pity and fear " is in the sight of the mad old man, with the strength of go TECHNIQUE despair, carrying in his dead daughter to show to all men, — the sight of him as he holds the feather to her lips to reveal her breathing, and, dim-eyed in the flesh, sees, with the vision of fevered desire, faint tokens of life. The tension breaks, and he dies, but his death is not tragic. It completes the tragedy of his life, and is fit, right, necessary; but for him it is a release. Kent's feeling is ours: " Vex not his ghost : O, let him pass ! he hates him much That would upon the rack of this tough world Stretch him out longer." But death is often, too, the consummation of the tragedy in another way. In Antigone^ the young girl's death is the tragedy, because it marks the completeness of her subjugation to crushing human law; whereas the deaths of Haemon and of Eurydice, in so far as they are tragic at all, are sp not in themselves, but in their effect on Creon. In Romeo and Juliet the deaths of the two lovers constitute the tragedy because only thus is forever shut off the possibility of recovered happiness. What the catastrophe must bring about is not prima rily death, but finality.— ^CTTequ ilibrium of forces which shall convince us of its permanence. It may be compared to the crash of the landslide by which the too precipitous cliff regains a natural slope. In Julius Ccesar there may be said to be two points of catastrophe : the first for Csesar, the second for the conspirators. In the first half oi LOGICAL DIVISIONS OF THE ACTION 9 1 the play, Caesar falls because he had risen too high ; Brutus and Cassius, representing the norm, pull him down. But then they in their turn rise too high, and the second half of the play shows how they are therefore in their turn overthrown. — In the management of the catastrophe, more than anywhere else, ther e should be con centration^ both of thought and expression. During the earlier part of the play, much elaboration is possible, much inc ident, much working-up ot character and episode; but as we near the close the lines should narrow. Earlier, many outcomes were possible; now nothing is possible except the single end to which everything has been tending. Upon this the rays must all converge, everything subsidiary must be eliminated. And if the drama has been well motived and well constructed, there will be no need for elaboration, or even for much empha- sis. The end is inevitable, all it requires is bare statement. To give more than this, to attempt explanation and commentary, implies carelessness on the part of the author, or a lack of faith in his work. Of carelessness, we have an illustration in the last lines of Julius Ccesary the conversation between Messala, Strato, and Octavius, concern- ing the promotion to favor of Brutus' servant. It is a petty detail, that spoils the simple greatness of the close. In another way, the concluding lines, given to Octavius, will, to some of us, seem another dissonance. The play naturally ends with Antony's words, "This was a man," and we would 92 TECHNIQUE fain rest here. Octavius' cold words point for- ward into a new realm of life, and at the moment . when we ought to feel that all is finished, we are V Krj l)»H [reminded of the political rearrangements to come, uJ^\ >A>*^ ■ the division of spoil — things which are histori- w* />y>€4, xvs Ically true enough, but which are here not fitting. ^ ^v« -K-r- jPerhaps it was Shakespeare's optimism that moved ^*^A f N"^ ^^ make this sort of mistake as often as he ^""^ .jdid, but if so it was optimism ill-timed. Summing up: we find that the action of the drama falls naturally into two parts, a rise and a fall; tha t the rising action has lour"p"arts : the introduc tory exposition, the exciting force , the wor king out, and the climax or t urning-point. The falling action has three parts : the tragic force, the working out, and the catastrophe, while often the final suspense makes a fourth part. Often, however, dramatic critics make a three- fold division instead of a twofold, namely, into the rising action, the climax, and the falling action. But i| the climax is organically devel- oped out of the rising action, as it ought to be, it is organically a part of it and should not be separated from it, even in thought. These, then, we have called the essential ele- ments of the drama, in distinction from those mechanical divisions, called acts and scenes, of which the dramatic structure is made up. CHAPTER III THE MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA (i) The Acts WE have called the division of the^ play into acts and scenes a mechanical one, in dis- tinction from the logical division which has just been discussed. The single fact that the five acts of a play are commonly of about equal length would make it antecedently improbable that they should correspond to the organic articulation of the action's parts. That they actually do not so correspond will be evident from the most super- ficial inspection of any play. For the first act does not cover the introduction alone; the second act does not suffice to contain the rising action, which begins in the first act and overlaps into the third; the third act almost always contains the climax, but it also includes the penultimate stages of the rising action and the initial stages of the falling action; the main part of the falling action is contained in the fourth act, but its last part runs over into the fifth act, which is therefore not exclusively devoted to the catastrophe. The relation between the mechanical and the 93 \ ^ TECHNIQUE logical divisions of the play may be thus dia- grammed ; Act III Rising JLct ^^y^y^ Action ^'"introduction It might seem, then, that the acts have no organ- ism in themselves — that they are merely marked off with a tape at equal distances in the course of the play. This is not altogether the case. The division into acts is indeed somewhat a matter of stage convenience : it gives the aud ience time to relax, and the actors time^fqr_rest or for change of costume, it furnishes opportunity for extensive scene-shifting. Moreover, from the author's point of view it is useful because it gives him a few points in the action wherein, the continuity being com- pletely broken, he may assume greater changes and longer lapses of time than is advisable between scenes. But each_a(^_ought..tQ ..be, to -some extent, a w hole in it self; it ought to have a "beginning, middle, and elid," a rise and fall somewhat like the rise and fall of the drama as a whole. In the Greek tragedy the sections of the action falling between the choruses formed such wholes, while in the Senecan tragedies, whence modern drama MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA 9$ took its formal five-act structure, each act is dis- tinctly complete in itself. In the Medea^ for ex- ample, the five acts present each a distinct stage of the action. Disregarding the choruses, they may be thus epitomized : Act I. Presents Medea's turbulent mood as she realizes that she is about to be deserted by her husband. Act II. Stirred by the bridal chorus, she medi- tates revenge, but does not yet determine on whom it shall fall. In order to perfect and carry out her yet immature plans, she obtains leave to remain in the palace one day longer. Act III. Her anger increases and hardens into cold resolve. In an interview with Jason she assures herself that he really loves the two children he has had by her. She therefore decides to kill them, as well as Creusa, his new bride. Act IV. She invokes the aid of magic to endow with destructive powers the rich gifts she purposes to send to Creusa. Her incantations finished, she sends the gifts by her sons. Act V. A messenger announces that Creusa and her father have died in agony, and that the city is in flames. Medea, rejoicing in this first fruit of her vengeance, proceeds to complete it. One of her sons she kills before his father arrives, the other she kills in Jason's presence. She herself departs in her magic chariot. 9^ TECHNIQUE It will be seen that each act makes one step in the course of the action, each is dominated by a distinct mood in Medea herself : in the first act, it is half -dazed surprise and anger; in the second, wild rage and fierce longing for vengeance; in the third, hard and deliberate resolve; in the fourth, the elation of conscious power; in the fifth, exul- tation in completed vengeance, alternating with horror at her own deeds. Each act, moreover, besides completing its sec- tion ot the action, points forward, at its close, to the action that is to follow. Thus at the end of Act I comes her dark prophecy that, as through crime she entered the house of Theseus, through crime she will leave it. At the end of Act II this is made more definite when she gains the day's reprieve in which to work out her vengeance. At the end of Act III she suggests the details of the plot she is to carry forward in the next act. At the end of Act IV she sends the fatal gifts, and we wait for Act V to learn the result. Turning now to the modern drama, we find that the structure of the classic French plays is closely ^ similar to their Senecan models. But with Shake- speare the case is different. Of no one of his plays can such an epitome as the one just given possibly be made. The acts have no such unity; instead of presenting a single step in the action, a single mood in the protagonist, they are a network of activities, a complex of moods. Yet in some cases a kind of unity is discover- MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA 97 able. This is especially true of Macbeth. Here, the first act shows Macbeth yielding to the evil promptings of ambition, while Duncan's visit gives him the opportunity to follow out his desires. The second act centres about the murder of Duncan. The third act presents the consummation of Mac- beth 's plots and the beginning of the reaction. The fourth and fifth acts, which are, as is usual with Shakespeare, not so well constructed, present the preliminary and the final stages of the reaction. Take now, in greater detail, the third act : Scene i. As a kind of introduction, Banquo sums up Macbeth' s course hitherto: " Thou hast it now : King, Cawdor, Glamis, all As the weird women promised; and, I fear, Thou play'dst most foully for 't— " Part i. Then his mind reverts to the part of the witches* oracle which has concerned himself. This second thought strikes the keynote of the act, since it is the memory of that prophecy which leads Macbeth to plan Banquo' s murder. Part 2. The court enters, and Macbeth en- joins Banquo to be back for the night's feast. His emphasis on Banquo's return — "fail not our feast," "Adieu, till you return at night" — points forward with double irony, first, to the measures Macbeth is about to take that Banquo may not "return at night," and, second, to the terrible manner in which the murdered man is, after all, to fulfil the king's injunction. 98 TECHNIQUE Part 3. Then follows the interview between the king and the murderers, really a scene in itself, with its own introduction (lines 73-85), rise (86-115), climax (i 16-126), and conclusion. Thus the scene falls into three parts, an intro- duction, a transitional part, and a last part form- ing the first link in the rising action of the act. Scene 2. This scene is chiefly of value as char- acter-exposition. It does not advance the story. The opening words again insist, like the repetition of a theme in music, upon the Banquo motive : ** Lady Macbeth. Is Banquo gone from court? Servant. Ay, Madam, but returns again to-night." Then follows the interview between Lord and Lady Macbeth, giving the necessary insight into their desperate moods. The phrases, "these terrible dreams that shake us nightly," "the torture of the mind," "life's fitful fever," "O, full of scorpions is my mind," are needed to give the spiritual at- mosphere of the act. The scene ends by revert- ing to the theme with which it began. Scene 3. The murder of Banquo. The escape of Fleance is the first check to Macbeth' s plans. Scene 4. The banquet-scene. It is in three parts : The brilliant introduction emphasizes the king's royal state. The few words with the murderer serve to set Macbeth' s mind at rest as to the success of his plot against Banquo. With the entrance of the ghost the change MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA 99 comes, and there follows the half-crazed agony of the king, and the hurried breaking up of the banqueters. The last few lines of the scene sketch the after- mood of the king, varying between remorse and a feverish and desperate resolution. This scene is, of course, the climax of the act, as of the play. It presents the consummation of the king's plans and the beginning of the reaction. If we seek a turning-point in a few lines, we might find it in these, where he seems dimly conscious of the nemesis to come : " the time has been. That, when the brains were out, the man would die, And there an end : but now they rise again, "With twenty mortal murders on their crowns, And push us from our stools." Scene 5. The witches and Hecate plan to draw on Macbeth "to his confusion." Scene 6. The two lords hint their suspicions with regard to Macbeth, and speak of the party Macduff is raising for resistance. Thus the act has a regular rise and fall. It rises to the murder of Banquo, the escape of Fleance suggests the turn, while the banquet-scene and the two following scenes develop the three- fold character of the reactionary forces, the forces, namely, of the moral order, of the supernatural realm, and of the political world. In Lear^ Act III, there is, considering the complicated nature of the double plot, a fairly ICX) TECHNIQUE Sc. I. Introductory. Heath. Storm. Sc. 2. Rise. Lear Enters, mad. Sc. 4. Climax. Hovel-Scene. Sc. 3. Introductory. Gloucester and Edmund. Sc.5. Rise. Edmund betrays Gloucester to Cornwall. Sc. 6. Secondary Climax and Fall. Trial-Scene: Lear Carried out for Dover. Sc. 7. Climax. Blinding of Gloucester. Wounding of Cornwall hints a return-action. MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA lOt compact structure. For the Lear-plot the act may be considered as extending from Scene i to Scene 6; for the Gloucester-plot, from Scene 3 to Scene 7. Making a double order, we may sketch it as in the accompanying diagram. It is to be noted that the treatment of the two plots is in this act different in kind : that of Lear is expository, that of Gloucester is narrative. The first has its expository climax in the hovel-scene, it falls away in the gentler tone of the farm- house scene, ending in the old king's exhausted sleep; the second has a steady rise through the three scenes, culminating in the blinding of Gloucester, and having an abrupt fall in the wounding of CornwalL. But such ceases of good act-structure are not to be taken as typical of Shakespeare. In Z^ar, for example, the other four acts are, in this respect, hopelessly inorganic. Macbeth is more evenly good, though the first three acts are the best. It is noteworthy, too, that where, as in Lear^ one act surpasses the others in structural- compactness, it is the third. Now the third act has for its nu- cleus the climax of the play as a whole, and it can thus hardly help having a well-marked rise and fall. However, an act may be well constructed and not have both rise and fall — everything depends on what is its position in the play. Take the first two acts of Macbeth; Act I may be thus summarized: r02 • TECHNIQUE Scene i . Witches. Introductory — suggests the " tone " of the play. Scene 2. Camp. Introductory exposition. Scene 3. Witches, Macbeth, and Banquo. Exciting force. Scene 4. Duncan, his generals, etc. Exciting force strengthened by partial fulfilment of the witches' prophecies, which increases Macbeth's confidence in them. Scene 5. Lady Macbeth resolves on the murder of Duncan. This initiates the rising action. Scene 6. Duncan received by Lady Macbeth. Scene 7. Lady Macbeth strengthens Macbeth's resolution. Here the first scene is merely preliminary — like the striking of chords in music; the second is introductory; the third and fourth present the exciting force; the fifth, sixth, and seventh pre- sent the first stages of the rise. The act is per- fectly compact and ends at exactly the righ^ moment. Compare now Apt 11,^ ^ Scene i. Expositional of Macbeth's highly wrought state. Scene 2. Contrasting sketch of Lady Macbeth's mood. Macbeth enters, having done the murder. The knocking on the gate. ^ Scene 3. The discovery of the murder. Flight of Malcolm and Donalbain. MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA IO3 Scene 4. Ross and Macduff discuss the murder. Macduff will not attend Macbeth 's coronation. The act, in contrast with the preceding, has a rise and fall : it works up to the murder and presents the beginning of the reaction from the deed as shown on Macbeth and on those about him. Taken in greater detail, it has two points of supreme ten- sion: the first in Scene 2, the second in Scene 3. The first part of Scene i, the talk between Banquo and Macbeth, is skilfully managed so as to be pregnant with suggestion. Banquo' s frank re- mark, "I dreamt last night of the three weird sisters," recalls the theme of the rising action, while Macbeth's quick, guilty answer, "I think not of them," is in marked contrast. There follows Macbeth's soliloquy — really a separate scene, and paralleled by the soliloquy of Lady Macbeth at the beginning of Scene 2. After Macbeth enters, having killed Duncan, the first point of tension is reached; when the knocking commences there is a sudden relaxing. The porter's entry makes a break, then the second rise begins, culminating in the discovery of the murder. From this point the tension relaxes again. Thus the movement of this act is seen to be quite different from that of the preceding one, and yet different from Act III. If they were to be symbolized in diagrams, they would be about as follows (the Roman numerals indicate acts; the Arabic, scenes): 104 TECHNIQUE One more point is to be noted. It was seen in the Medea of Seneca that each act had toward i-ts close some suggestion of the action that was to follow in the next. The sarafe thing maybe-ob- served at the end of alm,ost any of the acts in Shakespeare's plays. Of the .three acts just ana-, lyzed, the first closes with the criminal resolve oi Macbeth and his Lady; the second has the scene with Macduff, which is subtly suggestive of Jiis antagonism to Macbeth; the third blocks out the three main forces of the return action. One might multiply instances of such secondary, anticipatory rise. A notable exception is found in Romeo and Juliet^ in the position of the street brawl scene, wherein Tybalt is killed. We should expect it at the end of Act II instead of at the beginning of Act III. It would have given ex- actly the note of warning needed to intensify the scenes of the climax, yet would not have trenched so closely upon these scenes. The third act woul.d then have begun with the orchard scene, and would have gained the jewel-like unity that is the MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA IO5 concomitant of singleness of impression in com- plexity of material. In studying act-structure, however, Jt^ must oi course be remembered that the absence of a cur- tain made the divisions between the acts much less marked then than now. Yet the case of Macbeth shows that structural act-unity could be, though it seldom was attained by Shakespeare. The fact is, we must not expect from Shake- speare perfection of structure. In seeing and seiz- ing upon the essential dramatic moments in his theme he was almost unerring, but in the working out he was usually careless — possibly he was really indifferent, conscious that he possessed the "one thing needful." Certainly the attempt to deduce laws from his act-structure gives, in the main, only negative results, whereas a study of the dramatic moments — what we have called the logi- cal divisions — of his dramas is exhaustlessly fruitful. Our modern drama has a character intermediate between the French seventeenth century and the English Elizabethan and Stuart drama. Each act has greater complexity than had the French, greater compactness than the English. Ibsen, in so many respects affiliated with the Greek drama, usually preserves the unity of place and sometimes that of time, as in Ghosts^ and each act is in- dividual in its presentation of some phase of the theme. Sudermann's dramas are models in cleanness of construction, and they have the effec- I06 TECHNIQUE tiveness that comes of masterly technique. In Wildenbruch's Heinrich und Heinrich's Ge- schlechtf his latest and perhaps his strongest drama, the act-structure is remarkably compact. The play is built up about the humiliation of the emperor at Canossa and is in two "evenings," each forming a play by itself, of which the first is the more powerful. An analysis of its acts makes an interesting contrast with the Shake- spearean form. It has a prologue and four acts. Prologue. This shows Heinrich when a boy of ten. It serves to give an insight into his original, unperverted nature, and thus to invoke the sympathies of the audience. Act I. The State House in Worms. King Heinrich returns from a victorious campaign against the rebellious Saxons. Messengers from the Pope arrive, refusing to grant his request for the emperorship, and censuring him for his evil courses. He sends back a message of defiance couched in studiedly insulting terms. The act is chiefly expositional, presenting the two great factors in the struggle that is to ensue, namely, the king's intense love for his people and the radical antagonism between his nature and ideals and those of the Pope. Act II. There are two scenes, the first in Rome, the second in Worms. Scene i. Pope Gregory is giving judgment on the penitents brought before him. Heinrich's MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA lOj defiance reaches him. He wavers between the dictates of wordly ambition and those of the spir- itual vision. Scene 2. Heinrich is under the Pope's ban, but bitter and unyielding. The children of Worms come out with Christmas gifts for the little prince, his son. Softened by this evidence of their love, Heinrich resolves for their sakes to humble himself before Pope Gregory, and secure tranquillity for his people. Act III. Canossa. Scene i. An audience room in the castle. Gregory is beset by the Saxon faction, enemies of Heinrich, who offer to depose him and let the Pope create an emperor who shall be a tool of the church. As Gregory wavers before the temptation to grasp at temporal power, it is announced that King Heinrich has come to do penance. Scene 2. Another audience room. After three days of struggle with conflicting motives, Gregory admits the royal penitent and recalls his curse. Heinrich, at the height of spiritual exaltation, learns of the Pope's dealings with the Saxons, and the perception of this double dealing shatters his faith. His mood changes to one of hard cynicism, and he leaves the presence determined to gain the emperorship by force of arms. Act IV. Rome. A fortified tower where the Pope has taken refuge. Heinrich enters the city with his army. In disguise, he visits Gregory and asks him to crown him emperor. Gregory 108 TECHNIQUE refuses, and Heinrich goes, to set up a new pope who shall do his will. Gregory dies, while from below are heard the cries of the populace, " Em- peror Heinrich and Pope Vibert! " From this epitome it will be seen how each act presents one phase of the subject treated. The first suggests the factors in the problem ; the sec- ond presents the two great protagonists, Heinrich and Gregory, showing how each is torn by con- flicting impulses; the third brings the problem to its issue; the fourth presents the provisional solur tion, which the second part of the play is to bring in question, but which affords temporary stability. Among modern French work, an example of beautiful act-structure is Edmond Rostand's Cy- rano de BergeraCj which, though called a " heroiq comedy," has a partly tragic theme and the structure of serious drama. It has five acts, each located in a single place: the first, at the. Hotel de Bourgogne; the second, at Rageneau's bakery, a rendezvous for Bohemian Paris; the third, a street before a house; the fourth, a camp at the siege of Arras; the fifth, a convent garden. Each act is a wonder of construction, being highly complex in material, yet close-knit, with no ten- dency to straggle or fall apart. The first two acts have each a central climax, with a secondary rise toward the close, anticipatory of the following act. The third act has the central climax, but the secondary one is less marked. The fourth act is MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA IO9 constructed like a fifth act, with a central climax and a sudden fall to a catastrophe; but the curious double nature of the hero's activity makes this conclusion only partial, and the brief fifth act is needed for the final resolution. Summarizing; the division into acts has been called mechanical, in distinction from those logical divisions that are grounded in the development of thejheme itself. In the Senecanjlranaa, how- ever, and in the classic French drama modelled thereon, each act has a lyric unity not found in the freer, more epic English drama. The best of the modern work combines the complexity and variety of the English manner with the more care- ful form of the French. (2) The Scenes The word "scene" has several meanings. It may denote merely the place in which the action occurs; it may refer to the entrances and exits of the persons; or it may mean such a section of the play as, in virtue of its significance, constitutes a unit in the treatment. According to French usage, any change in the number of persons on the stage, either by addition or diminution, makes a new scene. In common English usage, a new scene is indicated when the stage has been cleared and a new entrance occurs. The place of the action may or may not be changed. Thus, in Macbeth^ Act II, the first three scenes occur in the same place, a court of the castle. The first scene would, 1 10 TECHNIQUE according to French usage, be three scenes : one with Banquo and Fleance; one with Banquo, Fleance, and Macbeth; one with Macbeth alone. It is in our editions indicated as a single scene, because the entrances and exits overlap; but between Macbeth' s exit and the entrance of Lady Macbeth the stage is clear, hence a new scene is made. Either method of division has drawbacks. The French method often gives importance to an exit or an entrance — that of a servant, for instance — which does not make a real break in the action, and almost always there will be several, sometimes a dozen, of these little, mechanical scenes, going to make up what we may call the logical scene — that is, the scene which develops one phase of the subject. On the other hand, the English method sometimes leaves unemphasized an entrance or an exit that is of great importance, and we have really two logical scenes in one mechanical one. Thus in Macbeth^ Act III, Scene i, there are three distinct parts: (i) Ban- quo alone, (2) Banquo, Macbeth, and the court, (3) Macbeth and the murderers. When, therefore, we say that the scene should have in little what the act and the play has in large, — a compact, organic structure with a "beginning, middle, and end," — it is of the logical, not the mechanical scene that we are speaking. If Shakespeare is weak in act-management, he is strong in scene-management. Perhaps this is MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA 1 1 1 because the scene is small enough to be kept in view as a whole, even by the careless and rapid worker that Shakespeare often was; but, whatever be the reason, one may choose almost at random and find a scene exhibiting fine technique. As in the case of the act, so in the scene the rise and fall has not always the same form. Act II, Scene 3, of Macbeth has a central rise, but Scene i rises toward the close. Scene 2 falls toward the close, and the three scenes, following Frey- tag's method, might be thus diagrammed ; Scd Sc.2 sc:'s > and Scenes i and 2 ought, logically, to be taken either as four scenes or as one great scene in four parts, for Macbeth and his wife count here as one person, and their two soliloquies are comple- 112 TECHNIQUE mentary parts of the continuous rise to the murder itself. In some ways, the words "rise " and "fall " are not helpful, however, and it almost seems unfort- unate that Freytag imposed them on dramatic criticism. They are purely figurative, and figura- tive expressions are misleading when allowed to harden into formulas. As just used, they referred to the tension of the actors in the scenes, and hence of the audience as it follows the action. Thus Scene i begins quietly, with Banquo's words to Fleance, the conversation with Macbeth has more tension, and the soliloquy reaches a spiritual tumultuousness that goes over, on the same pitch, though with difference of tone, into the next scene, and increases on Macbeth' s reentry after the murder. The knocking on the gate acts like a dash of cold water: it breaks the continuity of mood and produces a sudden relaxation of tension. For another instance of good scene-structure, take Romeo and Juliet, Act III, Scene i : Introduction. Benvolio and Mercutio by their casual talk prepare us for what is to follow : " The day is hot, the Capulets abroad, And, if we meet, we shall not scape a brawl." Exciting Force. Tybalt and other Capulets enter ; a dispute arises between Tybalt and Mer- cutio. Rise. Romeo enters, bears Tybalt's insults, and tries to calm him. MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA II3 First Climax. Fight between Tybalt and Mercutio, Mercutio mortally wounded. The news of Mercutio's death overcomes Romeo's self-control. Second Climax. Reentry of Tybalt. Romeo defies him, they fight, Tybalt is killed. Return and Resolution. Entry of the popu- lace, with Montagues, Capulets, and the prince. The guilt of Romeo's action is argued, the prince decides against him and banishes him. The scene, with its two climaxes, might be thus diagrammed : Act ni Scene! In the above scene, the words " rise " and " fall " have regard not only to the inner excitement of the participants, but to the outer events that advance the story. In other cases the entire scene is broad expo* I 114 TECHNIQUE sition of spiritual states. Thus, in Lear^ Act III, Scene 4, we have an elaborate study of the old man's madness. The beginning is quiet, but by the end of his first long speech the king has worked himself up to an excitement whose char- acter he himself recognizes : "O, that way madness lies; let me shun that; No more of that." He becomes outwardly calm again, but the entry of Edgar feigning madness brings before his eyes the very madness he fears for himself, and perhaps draws him on toward it. At all events, his excite- ment grows again until it reaches the frenzy in which he cries, "Off, off, you lendings! come, unbutton here," and tears away his clothes. This is the point of greatest spiritual tension in the scene. Gloucester's entrance makes a break, and brings to the front Edgar, whose feigned ravings drop to the whimpered refrain, "Poor Tom's a-cold," "Tom's a-cold," while Lear's fury sub- sides to a dazed quietude. Here the words "rise " and " fall ' ' refer wholly to the spiritual intensity of the scene. Summing up: the play, as a whole, is like an organism : it is articulated into^cts, which are in turn artjculated into scenes. Each act and each scene has its own individual completeness — a completeness which is, however, subordinated to that of the whole of which it forms a part. The scenes fall naturally into larger or smaller groups, MECHANICAL DIVISIONS OF THE DRAMA II5 and cannot be considered out of their position without in some fashion having violence done them. Each scene, regarded as a unit in a greater whole, resembles not one brick in a straight wall, but one stone in an elaborate arch: the form of the stone will be determined by the point in the arch at which it is placed and the purpose — whether this be ornament or support — which it serves. CHAPTER IV ./■ I /' CHARACTER-TREATMENT IN the serious drama, it is impossible- to con- sider plot wholly apart from character or character apart from plot. At least, this ought to be so, for the plot being grounded in causality, not accident, its action is the inevitable outgrowth of the characters concerned in it. • Hence, in dealing with dramatic principle and with plot- structure, much has been already stated or assumed with regard to the tragic hero. In fact, all the essentials have been thus stated or assumed. He must, we have seen, have the freedom that both develops the positive, the "royal" character, and offers it opportunity for initiative; he must, we have assumed, possess strength of some sort, other- wise he will not hold his own for a moment in the tragic struggle — rather, no tragic struggle would be possible; but his nature will be one in which conflicting tendencies and impulses are present, for in these conflicting tendencies lies his weak- ness and the opportunity and occasion for the tragic conflict itself. Finally, all these require- ments usually imply that he will be a man of emi- nence, either by birth or fortune or training, and ^ y^' CHARACTER-TREATMENT II7 that he will have the power of self-expression, ena- bling us to understand the inner life that i^ not adequately represented in action. Thus much is evident with regard to the hero of the tragedy or the serious drama, and it is true of the other characters in proportion as their activity in the play resembles his. Aristotle laid it down as a general rule, that the hero should be neither wholly bad nor wholly good, because in the one case the spectacle of thg hero's suffering would not move our pity, in the other it woufd simply shock us.^ Yet the philosopher had before him the example, in Antigone^ of a fault- less heroine, in whose judgment of herself we con- cur : " I shall rest, a loved one with him whom I have loved, sinless in my crime." ^ Possibly Aris- totle did not admit this play as on a level with the CEdipus in tragic power; certainly it has no parallel. For Shelley's Beatrice, it is true, feels that her crime is the only right thing, but though her heart is the heart of Antigone, her choice is an Orestean one, from either of whose alternatives there is an instinctive recoil. Setting aside, for a moment, this single case, consider these requirements as to goodness and badness in the hero. There are reasons for them deeper than those given by Aristotle. We saw that the drama meant struggle, either with outer forces or, as in almost all the greatest 1 Poetics, XIII. 2 Antigone, trans. Jebb, p. 23. Il8 TECHNIQUE dramas, with inner forces. If the struggle is an inner one, it means a divided soul with a divided allegiance, conflicting impulses. Such is the case with Orestes, with Hamlet, with Lear, with Beatrice, with Brutus, with Wallenstein, with Faust, with Strafford. None of these has either, on the one hand, the steadfast poise and invulner- ability that we associate with perfect goodness, like that of Christ or th e mythical Socrate.& ; or, on 0t^ | the other hand, the assured firmness and security (j of another sort that we associate with absolute anwj^^jjp deliberate badness, like that of Richard III conceived by Shakespeare. But neither Christ nor Socrates would lend themselves to treatment » . , as a tragic hero, and Sudermann's latest drama, ^^i^*^ Johannes, which attempts a tragic treatment of John the Baptist, does not encourage efforts to use this type of character. Shakespeare's use of the opposite type, in Richard III, results in a play of tremendous power, but, as we have seen, the play is not tragedy at all in the sense in which we have been using the term. Similarly, in Jonson's Se- janus, the two central characters, Claudius and his great favorite, are both monsters of vice and wickedness, but here again the result is not true tragedy, for such characters leave no room for tragic struggle and tragic suffering, and this drama must be placed, with Richard III, in a class apart. With these belongs Massinger's The Roman Actor, though in this case the central character, Nero, has, for the purpose of tragic effect, been consider- CHARACTER-TREATMENT 1 1 9 ably softened by the dramatist : his passionate de- votion to his crime-won wife — a devotion which, so far as the limits of this drama are concerned, is single and absolute — carries him out of himself, and renders him vulnerable in a sense that is not true of Richard or of Sejanus. .Returning now to Antigone j it must, first of all, be said that this drama has in it a larger element of the pathetic than, for example, Hamlet^ or the tragedies dealing with Orestes, and that this is due to the fact that she is preeminently the victim of outer misfortune. Moreover, we feel the tragic element in her story in proportion as we realize that she also has been the battlefield of contending forces; that, calm though she appears, she has had a conflict, whose bitterness is hinted in her last outburst of longing for the life and joy she ha§ given up. But her case is different from that of Macbeth or of Hamlet, since the necessity of the conflict has been imposed upon her from without, instead of arising from within, — such was, until. Euripides, the phase of tragic conflict chiefly em- phasized in Greek drama. Evidently, the exceptional case of Antigone only helps to establish the rule that tragedy is to be found, not in suffering merely, BurTri'"HJffeilng accompanied by struggle. In so far as Antigone shows the suffering without the struggle it is not tragic but pathetic, as will appear yet more clearly if the play be compared with The Cenci and with the dramas whose subject is the story of Orestes. 120 TECHNIQUE We find, then, the plays Antigone and Richard III at the two ends of the scale, but each on the boundary line of typical tragedy, though not for the reason that Aristotle gives. For the question is not one of goodness or badness as such, and it is darkening counsel to bring these elements into the discussion. The dra ma deals with men, not devils or angels, and this not because devils are bad and angels good, but because both are fixed and out of the range of passion, outside of the life that is the dramatist's sphere. The drama shows men stj rred to the foundations of their being, open to influence^ capable of change, torn by desires, able to be aroused to the most intense activity, emotional, intellectual, volitional ; and such men have the souls neither of devils nor angels, but are a compound of elements from both. So much for the character of the tragic hero considered in itself. Consider it now with regard to the dramatist's presentation and the spectator's appreciation of it. Given a vital, positive character, given freedom to show his individuality in action, the thing that is above all necessary in the treatment is the arous- ing of the spectator's sympathy. He"lnust"Be made, noF me^fely"to see tHe acts, but to sympa- thize with their motiving. If the fact is a murder, we must ourselves feel the feelings that lead up to the deed, otherwise the presentation lacks spir- itual significance. Wordsworth, in his Letter CHARACTER-TREATMENT 121 to a Friend of Robert BurnSy speaking of the biography of the poet, says : "So much for facts and actions; and to what purpose relate them, even were they true, if the narrative cannot be heard without extreme pain; unless they are placed in such a light, and brought forward in such order, that they shall explain their own laws, and leave the reader in as little uncer- tainty as the mysteries of our nature will allow, respecting the spirit from which they derived their existence, and which governed the agent." And he quotes from Burns himself the lines : " One point must still be greatly dark, The moving why they do it." It is in the illuminating of this " greatly dark " point which should be the object of the dramatist's endeavor in his treatment of character. For, without attempting psychological subtleties, we may say that a man's life has two phases : its outer manifestation in deeds, and its inner in thoughts and feelings. The two phases are vitally con- nected, and the outer is not explicable save through the inner. ^ Now, the bridge, the middle ground, between inner and outer, is found in words and in gestures. Gesture is not available to the dramatist except through the meagre medium of stage directions, and he must here trust to his actor, or, if the drama be read, to the imagination of his reader. Words, then, are his to use, and in words and acts he finds his material. 122 TECHNIQUE 4 Self-expression through acts is the dramatist's special provi nceTTt is The Tone and sinew of his work, which is thereby distinguished from the epic. But no one is fully represented by his deeds alone; even in the man who is freest there will be a reserve of tendencies that are never realized, impulses that, so far as outer activity is concerned, nullify each other. These the drama- tist must consider, or his work will deteriorate into chronicle : — " Not on the vulgar mass Called * work/ must sentence pass, Things done, that took the eye and had the price; O'er which, from level stand, The low world laid its hand. Found straightway to its mind, could value in a trice; " But all, the world's coarse thumb And finger failed to plumb, So passed in making up the main accovint; All instincts immature. All purposes unsure. That weighed not as his work, yet swelled the man's amount. " Thoughts hardly to be packed Into a narrow act, Fancies that broke through language and escaped; All I could never be, All, men ignored in me. This, I was worth to God, whose wheel the pitcher shaped." y, We have seen what this fundamental principle usually involves as to the hero's position and cult- CHARACTER-TREATMENT 123 ure. In the technique of the drama it also has > certain corollaries. Two dramatic expedients ] have here their s ource, namely, the soliloquy and p*^ the c onfidant. .. Each is employed to meet a real need, and each is to some extent legitimate. The soliloquy, with its subspecie s, the stage "aside, " is, it is true, usually unnatural, but it is not there- fore to be wholly condemned. It is the conven- tional way of letting us know the inner state of the actor, which we cannot otherwise be made to understand. This is the purpose of the first soliloquy of Richard III, of the soliloquies of Macbeth and of Hamlet, of the exquisite orchard scene in Romeo and Juliet, of the lyric out- • burst of Antigone before she is carried off by the guards. The soliloquy has, indeed, been abused. Even Shakespeare does not always escape the Senecan faults of declamation and rhetoric for their own sake; but to counterbalance this we have the Ham- let reveries, and those two wonderfully effective variations of the species, the porter scene and the sleep-walking scene in Macbeth, The other expedient, that of the confidenUal friend, to whom the actor may lay bare his inmost soul, is as old as the Greek drama. It Hmelirto modern drama, like so many other dramatic fur- nishings, through Seneca, the nurse or companion in his tragedies being transferred bodily to the French and the English stage, there to undergo many superficial, but no essential modifications. 124 TECHNIQUE Both these stage expedients, however, have been the butt of much derision, some of it just enough, and modern playwrights usually try to avoid recourse to them. Where this can be done without sacrificing clearness, it is a distinct gain. Ibsen scarcely uses them at all, and though his plays are sometimes obscure, it is not for this reason. In the second part of Wildenbruch's Heinrich und Hehirich's Geschlecht^ however, the character of Prince Heinrich suffers, being in the highest degree subtle, complex, apparently contra- dictory, while we are given no key to its solution. On the other hand, it is instructive to note how, in Straffordy Browning has succeeded in portray- ing with masterly completeness the hero's inner nature, with very little use of soliloquy in the ordi- nary sense of the term, and with no confidant — for Lady Carlisle cannot be rightly so called. He has done this by carefully arranging the succession of the scenes so that, as Strafford confronts in turn the king, the court, Lady Carlisle, Pym, and the rest, the shiftings in his attitude make clear to us without further commentary that complex inner life which each of his fellows knows only in part and estimates untruly. The play Strafford is here and there marred by the obscurity that is Brown- ' ing's greatest fault, and that is due to a careless and incomplete expression of his thought, yet even as it stands it is worth close study as one of the most magnificent dramatic creations in our litera- ture. Its motto might have been the lines from CHARACTER-TREATMENT 12$ Ben Ezra quoted above, for the author has taken an historic person, the record of whose acts has seemed enigmatical if not despicable, and has restored or created the soul behind the acts — a soul whose sad grandeur is the more moving be- cause its fate has been to walk before men in the garb of meanness and treachery. Ther^-are other way s of arousing s ympathy besides' the direct "expression by the actor of his motives and feelings. Often the simple portrayal of other phases of his nature than those brought out in t he chief action will be the best possible means to this end, and many side-scenes in the great dramas are of this nature. Yn Julius Ccesar a comparison with the Plutarch version shows that the chief additions made by the dramatist were of this sort. Such are the elaboration of the quarrel scene, barely mentioned in Plutarch, the transfer- ence to this scene of the announcement of Cal- purnia's death, the exquisitely tender passage where Brutus is with his guards and with the boy Lucius. Addressing Lucius, he says : "What, thou speak'st drowsily? Poor knave, I blame thee not; thou art o'erwatch'd;" then, to Varro and Claudius : " I pray you, sirs, lie in my tent and sleep; , *♦♦♦♦*♦ Var. So please you, we will stand and watch your pleasure. 126 TECHNIQUE Bru. I will not have it so : lie down, good sirs; Look, Lucius, here's the book I sought for so; I put it in the pocket of my gown. Luc. I was sure your lordship did not give it me. Bru. Bear with me, good boy, I am much forgetful." These lines give us a glimpse of another phase of his character, which we should never have seen in the patriot who killed his friend because he deemed him a tyrant. And they make an appeal to our love, while the patriot might have moved only our admiration and respect. Such appeals seem to occur naturally in the great dramas, thus we find one in Lear, IV, 7, the scene between Lear and Cordelia, which is not needed for the action. Turning to the Greek drama, we may instance the little scene between (Edipus and his daughters, which, coming after the earlier scenes, brings out a side of his nature that was needed to counterbalance its harsher aspects. "Nay, let my fate go whither it will: but as touching my children, — I pray thee, Creon, take no care on thee for my sons; they are men. . . . But my two girls, poor hap- less ones, — who never knew my table spread apart, or lacked their father's presence, but ever in all things shared my daily bread, — I pray thee, care for them; and — if thou canst — suffer me to touch them with my hands, and to in- dulge my grief. Grant it, prince, grapt it, thou noble heart ! Ah, could I but once touch them with my hands, I should think that they were with me, even as when I had sight. . . . CHARACTER-TREATMENT 12/ [Creon's Attendants lead in the children Antigone and ISMENE.] Ha? O ye gods, can it be my loved ones that I hear sob- bing, — can Creon have taken pity on me and sent me my children — my darlings? Am I right?" etc.i In Antigong, too, the character of the heroine has throughout been sustained at a degree of tensity that is almost sternness, the other side must be brought out if our sympathies are to be touched; and the author's sure instinct meets the need in her last words, where she almost breaks down as her love of life and joy assert themselves. With this may be compared the closely similar scene in TTie Cenci, though here there is not quite the same need for it, since the little scenes between Beatrice and her mother, her little brother, and her lover have kept us conscious, throughout the play, of the tenderer, more lovable side of the girl's nature. In Hamlet ^t would be tempted to call the scene with Ophelia (III, i) another such; it certainly was given this value by Booth's rendering, but Shakespeare's own intention is not so certain. His purpose here, as elsewhere in the character, may have been a little blurred by the older tradi- tion, and it is not safe to build too much on his treatment.^ In Coriolanus such touches are almost wholly lacking, and we miss them, for it is especially in 1 CEdipus jyrannus, trans. Jebb, pp. 263 ff. * Ct supra, p. 30 and note. 128 TECHNIQUE those characters whose tendency is toward stern- ness that the dramatist must be careful to evoke sympathy. To turn to a modern drama, this was one of the problems that Wildenbruch had to face in treating the subject of Emperor Heinrich. He had to arouse us to keen sympathy with a man whose iron will and harsh exterior seemed singularly unpro- pitious. His solution is unique and masterly. He treats his main action in four acts, and in place of the other act inserts a prologue wherein he brings before us his hero as a boy of ten years, emotional, sensitive, generous, headstrong, in the first sense of the word, magnanimous. In the swiftly moving, highly condensed and suggestive scenes of this prologue we are made to feel the limitless possibilities for good and evil in the child's nature; we see, too, the kind of influences with which he is surrounded — violence and evil passion on the one hand, the coldness of a narrow and conventional, if not a merely superficial, piety on the other. When the play proper opens, and we see the little prince become a king, harsh, haughty, ruth- less, insolent toward God and man, we are not repelled, for we remember the royal nature of the boy, and we feel what must have been the grinding pain of the years that have turned his good to evil. Every bitter word of the king is so calculated as to remind us of the boy, and where the group around him see only a harsh tyrant, brutally mock- CHARACTER-TREATMENT 1 29 ing his conquered enemies and bitter even to his friends, we see in the very brutality and bitterness the perverted expression of a lovable nature. No drama, then, can represent merely the acts of the persons concerned; it must represent these acis in the light of the actors' motives, their moods, their ideals. But the proportionate emphasis on what we have roughly called the inner and the outer varies greatly in the work of different dramatic writers, or even in the different dramas of the same writer. If we compare, with this in mind, the dramas of Shakespeare and of Browning, wc see that in general Browning emphasizes the inner life, Shakespeare the outer. Shakespeare sees his characters primarily as acting men among men;' but because he sees them truly, not superficially, he sees also the man behind the activity, and, though valuing the outer, does not ignore the inner life. Browning proceeds conversely. Fol- lowing Ben Ezra's creed, he sees his characters as souls whose outer activity only partly represents them, and he fixes our attention, primarily, upon their inner activity. Shakespeare's emphasis is on the act first, and then on the spiritual state causing it or resulting from it; Browning's is on the spiritual state first, and only secondarily on the act into which it passes, or from which it arises. Shakespeare's treatment is, apparently, though not really, external: he prefers to set before us, in the vividest manner possible, the outer activity of the person, and let us from that K I30 TECHNIQUE infer the inner state. Thus Macbeth merely refers in passing to " these dreams that shake us nightly," and of Lady Macbeth' s spiritual experience we get scarcely a glimpse until the fifth act. Again, what Coriolanus undergoes we only guess at through stray hints and by inference from his deeds and the situations in which he is placed. We know that a soldier and a patriot does not go over to the enemy without war of spirit; we know that when a man whose pride has been unyielding gives way to his mother's prayers and reverses his action, it means an inner upheaval; we know that when he finds the enemy he has befriended turning again and rending him, the experience is bitter; but in each of these cases our knowledge is chiefly inferential. Compare with this Browning's treatment of what might have been a similar theme. We say " might have been," because in Luria as actually treated, the similarity of its original story to that of Corio- lanus is scarcely recognizable. The story in its bare outlines is this : A young Moor, with a genius for warfare, comes to Florence and devotes his talents to her service. He is given the command in the war against Pisa, and conducts affairs to the point where victory is certain and there is needed only the mechanical carrying out of his plans. The Florentine leaders, however, mistrust Luria' s single-mindedness, and fear that after the victory he will use his army to make himself master of the city. To prevent this, they enter against him accusations of treachery, and arrange for his secret CHARACTER-TREATMENT I3I trial and execution. The Pisan general, Tiburzio, chancing upon evidence of their double dealing, discloses it to Luria, and invites him to come over to the Pisans. Luria refuses, completes the orders for the final battle, then takes poison. As he is dying, the Florentine representatives seek him, having by Tiburzio's testimony been convinced of the injustice of their suspicions. But Luria dies. The likeness and the contrast in the two stories of Luria and Coriolanus need not be pointed out. For the present purpose what is interesting is the difference in method of treatment. First, the crowds and the large groups of men found in Coriolanus disappear, and instead we have a lit- tle group of seven persons, whose central figure, Luria, is brought and kept under the full blaze of light. Every thought, every feeling, every impulse is revealed from its birth to its fruition. And not this one figure alone, but the others as they come near him, as their activity affects him, are illumined; their motives, too, are searched, till one comes to feel that, after all, the act is nothing compared to the spiritual life behind the act. But it is not the dramatist's part to feel this; what he should feel is that the act is everything, when understood in the light of the spiritual life behind the act, and Browning's strength becomes his weakness, his seer's vision of the spiritual man makes him lose grip on those outer activities of 132 TECHNIQUE life which are indispensable parts of the drama- tist's material. Such phrases as " Thoughts hardly to be packed Into a narrow act," or, " the vulgar mass called * work ' " are significant of the tendency which sometimes mars his poetic work and lends a color of justice to the remark lately made, "Browning's plays are great poems — and they really ought to be drama- tized." In Strafford and A Blot in the ^Scutcheon, how- ever, the balance of emphasis is kept within the bounds of great dramatic art; in Luria^ Colombe's Birthday f A Soul's Tragedy^ it is, in varying de- gree, less perfect; while in Sordello and Paracel- susy where the inner quite overbalances the outer, the poet has judiciously abandoned the strictly dramatic form. The extreme of this tendency to portray the inner life at the expense of the outer is seen in the so-called dramas of Maeterlinck. The author boldly declares that his business is not with acts at all, but with the spiritual life which even words are almost powerless to reveal. His theory, like his work, shows a curious lack of the sense of proportion, and his dramas, where they are great, confute his theory. Shakespeare, however, though his treatment reverses Browning's emphasis, is not always the CHARACTER-TREATMENT 1 33 same. Between the balance of inner and outer activity in Coriolanus and that in Macbeth there is almost as much difference as between Shakespeare's general method and Browning's. There is cer- tainly more difference than there is between Mac- beth and A Blot in the 'Scutcheon. Coriolanus is the most external of the great tragedies, Macbeth the most consistently spiritual, though Hamletf in parts, goes further than anything else of Shake- speare's. This brings us to another question — the ques- tion of s o-called character-dev Qlopm^Tif, Tt has been maintained that much character-development is to be found in Shakespeare, and ten Brink, for example, finds in Romeo and Juliet a great change in Juliet between the Capulet's ball and the Capu- let's tomb. A change, certainly; but the question is, what is the nature of the change? is it true development of character or merely different mani- festations of the same character? r Evidently there is need for defining of terms. \ A person may be regarded as a complex of many I qualities, whose absolute intensities and relative proportions determine the person's "character." By the use and disuse of these qualities in daily life, these absolute intensities may be increased or diminished, and their relative proportions thereby permanently altered. This constitutes character- development as we ordinarily use the term in real life. In this sense, Tito, in George Eliot's Romolay exemplifies character-development, and L 134 TECHNIQUE Romola herself does so to a less extent. In Middlemarchy Lydgate, Rosamond, Dorothea, all show it; in The Mill on the Floss y Maggie TuUiver shows it; in Daniel Deronday Gwendolen Harleth shows it. In this same sense, we certainly get character- development in Macbeth, He himself recognizes this, when he says : " I have almost forgot the taste of fears : The time has been, my senses would have cool'd To hear a night-shriek ; and my fell of hair Would at a dismal treatise rouse and stir As life were in't : I have supped full with horrors; Direness, familiar to my slaughterous thoughts, Cannot once start me." ^ But it is a mistake to take this single play as typical of Shakespeare's work. In this respect, as in others, it is exceptional, and the change in character shown in its hero is different in kind from that shown in Othello or in Coriolanus or in Julius CcBsar, In Othello^ indeed, the difference between the well-poised, confident general who faces the Venetian council, and the frenzied, half- ' savage man of the final scene, — the difference here is apparently greater than between the Macbeth of Act I and of Act V, but the source of the differ- ence is not the same, and its significance is not the same. In Othello we see the gradual arousing of a passionate nature until it reaches a white heat that destroys itself and those nearest it; but this 1 Macbeth, V, S. CHARACTER-TREATMENT 1 35 IS not character-development, it is the temporary calling into play of one particular .set-fil^jassioiis already mature in the character, though at first in- active because not aroused. It is, of course, by the arousing of passions, by the giving of them free play, that they grow, and in this sense the action of Othello must be regarded as forming one link in the development of all the persons con- cerned. If Othello had lived, he could not after- ward have been quite the same man he was before, but this is not the aspect of the action that is em- phasized in the play. With the exception of Macbeth, Lear, and pos- sibly Hamlet, Shakespeare's plays do not show development in this sense. What they do show is the blazing up of powers and passions out of qui- escence mtcT activity, and if we call this develop- ment it is merely because every act that a person performs and every outbreak of passion may be said to be one link in the causal chain determin- ing as well as indicating character. If we turn to Browning, we find the case slightly different. A Soul's Tragedy certainly shows char- acter-development; not only shows it, but bases thereon the significance of the " tragedy." Ibsen's A DolVs House shows it; for, though the changes begin and culminate very rapidly, they are real and permanent, not merely the evincing of hitherto latent characteristics. Here, as in A SouPs Tragedy, the focus of attention is upon these permanent changes, only that, whereas in Brown- 136 TECHNIQUE ing the soul is lost, in Ibsen (from his standpoint at least) the soul finds itself and sets out to save itself. The same is true of Colombe's Birthday, Note, however, that in the case of Nora and of Colombe the limits of the dramatic form make possible only a suggestion of the development, and each play ends with an outlook into a future that we know will bring further changes along the lines of those already begun. X It is perhaps true that the drama can scarcely do more than thus suggesf development, and Shakespeare may have been right in not attempt- ing more. The life-history of Tito Melema or of Maggie TuUiver could not, in the five acts of a drama, have been treated effectively, and such themes may better be left to be handled in the less restricted literary form of the novel. What the drama primarily presents, is the critical moment of conflict, with the spiritual changes therein in- volved. It is this inner crisis, as worked out in the outer clash, the outer crisis as resulting from and reacting on the inner life, that it is the dram- atist's function to portray. -qHAgrlK-y PLOT IN COMEDY / IN many respects the laws of structure deter- mined for the serious drama are equally valid for comedy, but there are also important differ- ences between the two kinds of dramatic creation. First, it may be generally stated that in comedies the action of the plot is mtfch more independent of th,i5 characters than it is in the serious drama: it is, as we have already implied, even possible to create a comic plot which shall be really comic, while its persons are nothing more than puppets, the development of the plot being wholly extrane- ous to the characters. This is the case in The Comedy of Errors^ in much so-called farce, in much of the Spanish comedy. Again, the comic action is far less bound to emphasize^Iaw^inTits treatment of events; it can make free use of what we call accident and chance. Passing now to a more detailed consideration of its structure, we find that comedies fall into two main groups, according as their comie interest does or does not determine the main plot. Com- pare, for example. King Henry IV with Every Man in His Humour, In the former there is a -\ V 138 TECHNIQUE serious main plot, based on events in English his- tory wherein the fiercest passions were aroused and the largest interests involved, and wherein the actors were of heroic type. The comic interest is found in a number of interspersed scenes whose action is loosely connected with the serious main plot; cut out these scenes, and with few changes the play becomes a serious historical drama. In Jonson's play, on the other hand, the exact con- verse is the case. The serious interest — and there is very little — is subordinate. The comic interest is not merely developed in the main plot, it actually constitutes it; cut out this and you destroy the play. These two plays may be accepted as typical of two great classes of comedies. To those of the first type the name "romantic comedy "has been given, for reasons not wholly connected with its structure ; those of the second type have been vari- ously styled, according to considerations foreign to this discussion. To it belong all of Aris- tophanes, most of Plautus and Terence, most of Jonson and Moliere, the comedies of Massinger and Middleton and Congreve. With Henry IV are to be classed all of Shakespeare's comedies except Love's Labour's Lost^ The Comedy ofErrors^ The Merry Wives of Windsor ^ The Taming of the Shrew, Since the romantic comedy has as its basis a serioiis^main plot, and its comic interests are epi- sodic, it may be temporarily disregarded. It is PLOT IN COMEDY 1 39 in the second class of comedies that we shall find the typical comic structure. Reverting to our illustration of the primitive form of comic plot, — our case of the man who sits down on the floor, — let us start again from this. In actual life we know that this may occur for various reasons: (i) he may have miscalculated the position of the chair, and the fault is therefore his own; or (2) the chair may break, and the fault is no one's; or (3) some one with malice prepense may have pulled the chair from under him, or may have placed a weak chair where he was likely to sit. So in come dies. The action maxbe one where the mistakes, the^ cqmic^ dj^a^pmntments, _ arise . out of the weakn ess of the victim, and he. aloneJis_ to blame, or they may spring from circumstance, and no one is responsible, or they may be delib- erately planned by one of the play's persons, an arch-intriguer, assisted, perhaps, by lucky acci- dent, which he knows how to turn to account. An example of the first sort is seen, though not with perfect clearness, in Love's Labour's Lost^ through the fourth act. The four gentlemen have simply miscalculated their own powers and at- tempted something beyond them. Hence, all fail signally, and the great scene for which the play is planned, IV, 3, merely presents this failure. Each does in turn expose his fellow, in true "house- that-Jack-built fashion, ' ' but no one of them has planned the downfall of another. The second kind is exemplified with typical 140 TECHNIQUE clearness in The Comedy of Errors, Here the whole complication is the result of chance, no one guides its progress, and its conclusion is as much accident as any part of its course. The third sort is seen, as has just been said, in the last act of Love's Labour's Losiy but it is better to select an instance where the entire play is con- structed on this principle. Among the multitude of such, we may mention, as being, for one reason or another, unusually good instances, Jonson's Every Man in His Humour (Brainworm and Ed. Knowell are the intriguers); The Silent Woman (arch- intriguers, Dauphine, Clerimont, and Love- wit); Chapman's All Fools (intriguers, Rinaldo, for the main plot, Cornelio, for a subordinate counter-plot); Massinger's A New Way to Pay Old Debts (intriguers. Wellborn, for the main plot, Allworth and Lovell for the underplot); Moliere's V E cole des Maris (intriguers, Isabelle and Val^re). Among them, the simplest in structure is Moliere's, and next comes Massinger's, which we will take as a type because it is English. The argument is, briefly, as follows : Act I. Wellborn, a prodigal, has ruined him- self by his excesses, and his estate has passed into the hands of his uncle. Overreach, an unscrupulous old man who has amassed large wealth by sharp practice. In despair. Wellborn turns for help to Lady Allworth, a rich widow whose late husband he had once befriended in time of need. Out of PLOT IN COMEDY I4I gratitude for this, Lady AUworth consents to feign a betrothal to Wellborn. Acts II, III, and IV. On the strength of his expectations, Wellborn is instantly restored to credit. His uncle is anxious to facilitate the match, hoping ultimately to get hold of Lady All- worth's wealth as he already has got Wellborn' s. He therefore pays his nephew's debts and enter- tains him royally. Overreach has a daughter, Margaret, whom he longs to see married to a title, and he offers her in marriage to Lord Lovell. In the lord's service is young AUworth, stepson to Lady Allworth, who loves Margaret and is loved by her. Lord Lovell befriends his cause, and while feigning consent to the marriage for himself, helps young Allworth convey Margaret away and marry her. Meanwhile Marrall, an attorney and an unscru- pulous attach^ of Overreach, decides that it will be more profitable to serve Wellborn. Act V. Through Marrall 's agency it is dis- covered that the deed transferring Wellborn' s estates to his uncle is worthless, and the owner- ship, therefore, reverts to Wellborn. Next, Over- reach learns of the marriage of his daughter with young Allworth. At the double catastrophe he goes mad. Now, it will be seen that the entire structure of the plot depends on the deliberately planned schemes of Wellborn and Allworth to outwit Over- 142 TECHNIQUE reach. Does this differ from the plan of the serious drama? In a sense, we might adopt the phraseology of the tragedy, and call the action " a losing struggle, by an imperfect character, against the overpower- ing forces of life." We might say that there is found here, the three things essential to tragedy : suffering, struggle, causality: . In a sense, yes; but in a sense so different from the tragic that, though the words may be un- changed, the ideas can no longer be treated as the same. First: the character is indeed imperfect, but the imperfections are here regarded as material. for comic co ntrast, and subjects for ju dicial repre- hension, not fo^pity_and sympathy. This has already been discussed. Next, as to the struggle. The result of it in both cases is the overthrow of some one, but the process is different in^ principle and significance — as different as is our case where the malicious person pulls away the chair from the case where two men grapple- in a fair fight. In the serious drama, the hero is c ontending, i t may be against one man, it may be against a host, it may be against himself, it may be against the remorseless "course of things." We may even know from the beginning that the struggle must end in failure, as we do know in the (EdipuSy or in The Cenci; but our hero really fights, he has his chance, all his energies go into the struggle'liid are staked on ^ ch aracter of it s conflict, in its freedom from the necessity of emphasizing law and its consequent license in use of chance or accident, in the ab- sence of a true climax and a true falling action, and in the nature of its catastrophe. If the seri- ous drama is represented by the projected pyra- mid, the comedy, such as Massinger's, may be represented by two lines, an ascending one for the intriguer, a descending one for the victim. Applying these results to other comedies, it will be seen that they conform fairly well. In the comedies of Plautus the victim is usually a rich old man, the intriguer usually his son or nephew, always assisted by a slave, and often by some other young man. The differences between play and play are found in the differences in the method of attack and in the motives for it. In Jonson's comedies the plan is the same in principle, but the schemes are exceedingly complicated; there are usually several intriguers with plans somewhat opposed, and there results a number of separate 150 TECHNIQUE little puzzles, with separate solutions, but all finally brought together in the general solution of the denouement. Moli6re's plots, again, are more simple.^ Turning now from this large group of comedies, let us see how far its principles apply to the group loosely classed as "romantic." At the beginning of the chapter we turned away from these because the other, by virtue of its simplicity. and its clear- ness of definition, lent itself more readily to analysis. The results thus gained may help us in dealing with the more difficult and elusive "romantic" comedy, or, at least, may afford a firm base from which we may proceed to its in- vestigation. In the Jntrig ue comedy it was noted that^ in supplying the intriguer with a motive .Joi^Jiis. scheming, the love-interest was usually employed, and it was suggested that if the love-interest was sufficiently emphasized it might overbalance the comic interest, and the play might become more or less serious. In turning from the plays of Plautus to those of Terence one notices, in some cases, a tendency toward this very thing. Ter- ence's more delicate talent seems to have inclined him to lay a slightly greater emphasis on the seri- ous element of the plot, and there results a change in the proportionate values of the serious and the comic elements. It varies in different plays, but 1 For a fuller discussion of this type of comedy, cf. Wood- bridge, Studies in Jonson's Comedy. \S^ PLOT IN COMEDY I5I on the whole it seems fair to say that Terence treats the motive- interest, if we may so distinguish it from the intrigue-interest, with a tenderness of touch and gentle delicacy of sympathy that in a later age would have developed into the so-called . "romantic" plot. In the Heaut o ntimorutnen oSt *ft,K dl ^ the remorseful old father doing self-imposed pen- 6K^ ance for his harshness toward his son, the devotion of that son to his mistress, Antiphila, the little touches that sketch the character of the girl An- tiphila herself; in the Andria, the overwhelming love of iTomphiTu s and Glyceriui^, which seems to have in it something more than the passion we find depicted in Plautus; — these give us glimpses, though no more than glimpses, of a possible devel- opment into another sort of comedy. Such a development is found in full maturity in the work of Shakespeare; and though we may not take the plays of Terence as a link in an actual evolutionary chain, — for the evolution took place on other lines, — we may use them in our own thought as furnishing a transition phase between the two kinds of comedy.^ In dealing with Shakespeare we have, it must be remembered, only approximate dates, and cannot base too much on chronology, yet enough seems established to give us some rough notions of grouping and development. The comedies, fol- 1 In Italian comedy, however, there seems actually to have been some such evolution. Cf. Violet Paget's Studies 0/ the Eighteenth Century in Italy. 152 TECHNIQUE lowing the approximate chronology now agreed upon, may be arranged as follows : Love's Labour's Lost. The Comedy of Errors. The Two Gentlemen of Verona. A Midsummer Night's Dream. The Merchant of Venice. The Taming of the Shrew. King Henry IV, two parts. The Merry Wives of Windsor. Much Ado about Nothing. As You Like It. Twelfth Night. All's Well that Ends Well. Measure for Measure. Cymbeline. The Winter's Tale. The Tempest. Of the earliest group two, Love's Labour's Lost and The Comedy of Errors^ have been already accounted for. In both the comic interest deter- mines the main plot, which is in the one case developed out of the characters, in the other out of pure incident apart from character. Yet in the latter case it is significant that Shakespeare, using Plautus' plot, added to it here and there touches of seriousness not in his original, and the propor- tions of the two elements in the play are more nearly as in some of Terence's comedies. PLOT IN COMEDY 1 53 In The Two Gentlemen of Verona we have the roma ntic comedy proper : there is the comic epi- sode, which could be cut out without maiming the play's structure^ and the je^ double (as often in Terence) and following in its logical divisions the lines of the serious drama. Because it is so"~simple and typical, it is worth while to examine it somewhat in detail. Act I. Exposition : love of Proteus and Julia, friendship of Proteus and Valentine. Rising Action : Valentine leaves for Milan, Pro- teus also is to be sent thither. Act II. Exposition f continued : love of Valen- tine and Silvia. Rising Action^ continued: in development of Proteus' treachery toward Julia and toward Valen- tine. A possible opposition is hinted in Julia's resolution to go to seek Proteus. Act III. Climax : apparent success of Proteus* plans, and banishment of Valentine. Act IV. Return Action : turn of fortune for Valentine suggested in his being made king of the outlaws; for Proteus it is suggested by the ap- pearance of Julia in Milan; for both it is precipi- tated by Silvia's plan to run away. Act V. End of Return Action^ and Resolution : Silvia's flight accomplished, the pursuit of her brings about the solution. Here it will be seen that there is a true conflict of forces, a true rise, turning-point, and descent. 154 TECHNIQUE And if Proteus has some of the characteristics of the arch-intriguer, it is the serious, not the comic aspect of his activity that is emphasized, and its criminal nature. The broad comedy in the play is embodied in the episodes where Speed and Launce appear. They could be cut out, yet they are really related to the main-plot scenes. For, as the Greeks used to follow up their tragedies by a comic parody, so Shakespeare seems here to have intended a parody of his own serious situations. In II, 2, is pre- sented the parting of the two lovers; in the next scene Launce appears and sets forth, with the help of his slippers and his cane, his own farewell to his family : the tears of his parents, the wails of his cat, and the unnatural indifference of his "stony-hearted dog." Again, in III, i, immedi- ately following upon Valentine's desperate grief at the separation from Silvia, comes Speed with the announcement that he, too, is in love, and he proceeds to discuss the situation. The parallelism may be accidental, but it can scarcely be deemed so. A similar case occurs in Love's Labour's Lost, in the Armado-Costard-Jaquenetta episodes, while in As You Like It the parody is elaborated, in Touchstone and Awdry, past the point of mere parody, almost into an independent sub-interest. But, besides this burlesque treatment of the seri- ous issue, there is, in the presentation of the issue itself, the beginning of a kind of comedy peculiar to Shakespeare, namely, a touching of the serious PLOT IN COMEDY 1 55 with a slightly fnmir light^ — of the most tenderly delicate sort, it is true, but unmistakable comedy nevertheless. This is the case in the scenes in which Julia appears (note especially Act I, Scene 2). It is the first trace of the author's power to look at things in two ways at once, a first gleam of the genius that was later to look at the old Lear through the eyes of the "bitter fool," and utter his tragedy in a jest, "And yet I would not be thee, nuncle; thou hast pared thy wit o* both sides, and left nothing i' the middle " : (Goneril enters) "here comes one o' the parings." In A Midsummer Nighfs Dream, again, there are the two distinct lines : one the love- interest, — double again, and as usual with the lines inter- crossing until straightened out by Oberon, — and the other the comic interest in the tradesmen of Athens and their interlude. The third group, the fairies and Puck, brings in a semi-lyric element foreign to our present discussion. So far all is clear: the comic in the tradesmen's scenes is easily placed, and it does not affect the main plot. But once more, in this main plot, we find the note of comedy even stronger than in The Two Gentlemen of Verona, while in the entire treatment there is a tone of whimsicality that is perhaps a result of the midsummer night's witchery. The serious and the comic standpoints are represented for us in Oberon and Puck, as they look on at the confu- sion of the two pairs of lovers. Oberon, taking it earnestly, thinks of the consequences : 156 TECHNIQUE "What hast thou done? Thou hast mistaken quite And laid the love-juice on some true-love's sight : Of thy misprision must perforce ensue Some true love turned and not a false turned true." Puck, the mocker, enjoys the situation: " Captain of our fairy band, Helena is here at hand; And the youth, mistook by me, Pleading for a lover's fee. Shall we their fond pageant see? Lord, what fools these mortals be? Oberon. Stand aside : the noise they make Will cause Demetrius to awake. Puck. Then will two at once woo one; That must needs be sport alone; And those things do best please me That befall preposterously." And again, when Oberon reprimands the imp: " This is thy negligence : still thou mistakest. Or else committ'st thy knaveries wilfully." Puck answers, unabashed : " Believe me, king of shadows, I mistook, * * * * * * * And so far am I glad it did so sort As this their jangling I esteem a sport." ^ And evidently the poet himself was able to see at once with the eyes of Oberon and of Puck. In The Merchant of Venice a sterner note is struck. As always, there is the episodic comedy 1 A Midsummer NigMs Dream, III, 2. PLOT IN COMEDY 15/ and the love-plots, but there is also the Shylock- Bassanio interest. And here the query intrudes itself : did Shakespeare mean the Shylock plot to be comic or not? It has, indeed, even now a grim kind of comic effect, but we must suspect that the Elizabethan audience laughed where we do not. Possibly Shakespeare meant him to be comic, and without purposing to do so lapsed occasionally into a sympathetic treatment simply because he could not help doing this with any character that he handled long. This would account on the one hand for the hardness of tone in the Jessica plot, and on the other hand for the sympathetic insight in such passages as Shylock' s magnificent outburst in answer to Salarino ; " Salar. \Vhy, I am sure, if he forfeit, thou wilt not take his flesh: what's that good for? Shy. To bait fish withal : if it will feed nothing else, it will feed my revenge. ... I am a Jew. Hath not a Jew eyes? hath not a Jew hands. ... If you prick us, do we not bleed? if you tickle us, do we not laugh? if you poison us, do we not die? and if you wrong us, shall we not re- venge ? " etc.i According to this interpretation, we see in Shy- lock, despite such passages, our familiar comic victim, grown indeed more formidable, and re- quiring, not the justice but the injustice of the law courts to overcome him, but the comic victim nevertheless, whose downfall, as in typical comedy of intrigue, brings with it the happiness of the 1 The Merchant of Venice, III, i. 158 TECHNIQUE lovers. Shakespeare's mistake, then, was in making us sympathize too keenly with Shylock, though, as we have said, this may not have been the case for his own day. This brings us to Henry IVy whose structure we have already settled. For, though the charac- ter of Falstaff really overshadows the entire play, it does not affect its structure, and the comic scenes are episodic. In The Merry Wives of Windsor we have a unique case : the episodic comedy of the two preceding plays is, by a tour deforce^ made the main plot of this one, while a serious subplot is added. The victimizing is an end in itself, instead of being, as in the usual comic main plot, a means to some other end ; and Falstaff, from a unique comic hero, has deteriorated into a commonplace comid'butt. He has lost his peculiar wit, and — most impos- sible of all — he takes himself seriously, so that instead of laughing with him we are laug hing at, him. The character of the play bears out the tradition concerning its writing; it is evidently a piece of hack work, and though the hack work of genius cannot be ignored, the play may, in the present discussion, be set one side. The next three comedies form a closely related group, which need here scarcely be considered apart. All have serious love-plots and all have comic by-play, that in Twelfth iV/^>^/being curiously affiliated with the type found in Molibre and Jon- son, while in Rosalind we might, if we chose, see PLOT IN COMEDY 1 59 an arch- intriguer turned somewhat ethereal and exceeding moral, managing the others for their best good and her own innocent amusement. In all three the serious plot is occasionally given a comic tone, the comedy being also partly perceived even by the participants themselves. In these three plays we get the perfection of the Shake- spearean comedy, and we need not go on to the last two groups, for, though the bitter jests of AlVs Well that Ends Well and Measure for Measure and the idyllic temperateness of The Tempest show a tre- mendous range in tone and many interesting points of detail, there is nothing new in underly- ing structure. Pausing here, then, and looking over the range ^//^^ A of Shakespearean comedy, we find certain qualities y^y- ., pp. 83-85. 170 TECHNIQUE based will thus be made to stand out by themselves. If this goes far enough, the result will be personi- fication of the imperfection, which is now con- sidered as a positive quality — jealousy, vanity, boastfulness, choler, greed. When less pro- nounced, the result is at least an emphasis on the character considered as a type rather than as an individual. Jonson furnishes in all his plays, ex- cept perhaps The Alchemist and Bartholomew Fairy abundant illustration of this tendency to present the type, while in The Magnetic Lady and The Staple of News he actually passes over into personification, and the drama lapses, in parts, into allegory. Thus here, again, the author's weaker and less-balanced work shows what is its ultimate tendency. \ To the comedy which treats character in this way has been given the name "comedy of humors," from the use of the word "humor" by its repre- sentative, Jonson. He has himself well defined his use of the term : " As when some one peculiar quality Doth so possess a inaii that it doth draw All his effects, his spirits, and his powers, In their confluctions, all to run one way. This may be truly said to be a humor," ^ and these lines are a fair description of the extent to which he s elects and isolates characteristics, and exaggerates them somewhat for the purposes of his \ 1 Every Man Out of His Humour, Induction. CHARACTER-TREATMENT IN COMEDY I7I treatments Coleridge's description of Jonson's method is worth placing beside Jonson's own, if we do not allow ourselves to be misled by it : "Jonson's [characters] are either a man with a huge wen, having a circulation of its own, and which we might conceive amputated, and the patient thereby losing all his character; or they are mere wens themselves instead of men — wens per- sonified, or with eyes, nose, and mouth cut out, mandrake fashion." ^ Taken as censure, the above is true only of Jon- son's inferior work; taken as merely descriptive of a characteristic tendency, it is true of all his work except parts of Bartholomew Fair and The Alche- mist, But it is equally true of Moliere, and of Menander, so far as we know him through Terence. It is rather curious that the extreme tendencies of this kind of comedy should be things so diverse as personal invective and allegory. Their sources, however, are different, the one having its origin in temperamental conditions, the other in intel- lectual; for the morally judicial temper easily passes over into the personally scornful, while the perception of the faults that produce asymmetry and disproportion in character readily drifts into an excogitation of abstract qualities. Neither of these tendencies appears to be found in the non-judicial comedy. It is less analytic, and while emphasizing single aspects of individu- ality it keeps in view the individual. Instead of 1 Coleridge : Literary Remains, Vol. II, p. 379. 1/2 TECHNIQUE the diagrammatic definition of the type, it presents the definiteness of the concrete instance. The contrast between the two methods suggests the difference between the philosophic and the artistic habit, though the parallel cannot be pressed too far. This is the method of Shakespeare as contrasted with that of Jonson. M olfere is somewhere be- tween the two. That he, lik e Jonson^ tends to portra y the type is su ggested even by the titles of his plays, The Hypocrite^ The Miser, The Misan- thrope; but his work does not show the extremes that are found in Jonson, " He seized his charac- ters firmly for the central purpose of the play, stamped them in the idea, and by slightly raising and softening the object of study . . . general- ized upon it so as to make it permanently human." ^ It is to be noted that the tendency toward the _ judicial and the tendency toward the typical are found toget ner predomin ating in those dramatists in whose plays the comic interests constitute the main plot. This is, it would seem, not a mere coincidence. For there is probably a connection between the judicial attitude and the analytic, type-constructing habit of mind, and there is a connection between these and the kind of mind that constructs such plots. For the kind of mind that sees things in the form of schemes and dia- grams, that tends to transform character into char- 1 Meredith : An Essay on Comedy, p. 14. CHARACTER-TREATMENT IN COMEDY 1/3 acteristic, will find it natural to construct the sort of plot that suits such treatment. This may be one reason why Jonson invented most of his plots; it may also be a reason why comic authors of his type (Moli^re, Chapman) often borrowed their comic plots from Plautus and Terence. For these plots, or their Greek model, were originally con- structed to fit this sort of comic effect, which may account for the character of the plots, an ingenious complexity, a certain premeditated air and lack of spontaneity, for this is to be referred back to the temper of mind of the author. On the other hand , the comedy of sympathy is found b est in those writers who are also tragic, and often it occurs in the mids t of tragedy it$ g]ff as in Lear, And this, too, is intelligible, if we remem- ber how easily the sympathetic comedy passes into the pathetic and the tragic. Perhaps this is why the sudden transitions from tragedy or pathos to this kind of comedy does not shock us, but, accord- ing to its use, either relieves or heightens the tragic effect. Perhaps, too, it was from some such point of view that Plato suggested ^ that the genius of comedy was the same as that of tragedy. Both deal with contrasts, and given the presence of sym- pathy it is sometimes hard to say where comedy ceases and tragedy begins. It is, moreover, easy to understand why such comedy, being concrete and individual, does not demand a plot made 1 Plato : The Symposium, 324. 174 TECHNIQUE especially for it, but more naturally occurs as inci- dental to any and every plot-action. In general, an author does not produce both kinds of comedy. There are, however, instances where he wavers between the two; Shakespeare's early comedies seem to show such a wavering, while in Ben Jonson's case it is probable that his romantic comedy. The Case is Altered^ was in hand at about the same time as Every Man in His Humour, Conversely, Shakespeare's Malvolio "sick of self-love" is an instance of reversion to a method of treatment which his mature work had apparently long before abandoned, and the episode of Sir Andrew's duel, also in Twelfth Nighty was enough in Jonson's style to serve as model for an incident in The Silent Woman. Such instances — and they might be multiplied — only go to show that men's minds do not come in fixed moulds or move in fixed grooves. But, in general, it is ap- parent that the two ways of character-treatment, like the two kinds of plots, and the two attitudes toward character, are the outcome of two different types of mind. ^\ 6<-. K \^" .^ s^ O^^ \< \ > JT' .^^' ^*'N; ^< '^■^ \t' ^^^ BIBLIOGRAPHIES I. LIST OF BOOKS REFERRED TO IN THIS VOLUME Amiel, H. F. : Journal. London, 1889. Aristotle : Poetics. Ed. S. H. Butcher. London, 1895. Brandes, G. : William Shakespeare, A Critical Study. New York, 1898. Coleridge, S. T. : Literary Remains. Ed. H. N. Coleridge. London, 1836. Congreve, William : Comedies. Ed. W. E. Henley. Chicago and London, 1895. Corbin, John : The Elizabethan Hamlet. London and New York, 1895. Corneille, Pierre: CEuvres. Ed. Mary-Laveaux. Paris, 1862. Fischer, Rudolf: Zur Kunstentwicklung der Englischen Tragodie von ihren ersten Anfangen bis zu Shakespeare. Strasburg, 1893. Freytag, Gustav: Die Technik des Dramas. Leipzig, 1894. Marshall, H. R. : Pain, Pleasure, and Esthetics. New York, 1894. '^Meredith, George : An Essay on Comedy and the Uses of the Comic Spirit. New York, 1897. Paget, Violet (Vernon Lee) : Studies of the Eighteenth Century in Italy. London, 1887. Plato: The Dialogues. Trans. B. Jowett. New York and London, 1892. *75 iy6 BIBLIOGRAPHIES Sidney, Sir Philip : Defense of Poesy. Ed. Albert S. Cook, Boston, 1890. Shelley, P. B. : The Cenci. Sophocles: The Plays and Fragments, with critical notes, commentary, and translation in English prose. R. C. Jebb. Cambridge, 1894. Ulrici, H. : Shakespeare's Dramatic Art. Trans. L. D. Schmitz. London, 1876. Wendell, Barrett : William Shakespeare. Woodbridge, E. : Studies in Jonson's Comedy. Boston, 1898. II. LIST OF TREATISES DEALING WITH DRAMATIC THEORY AND CRITICISM 1 Archer, William : About the Theatre. Essays and Studies. London, 1886. , English Dramatists of To-day. London, 1882. Everett, C. C: Poetry, Comedy, and Duty. New York, 1890. Fitzgerald, Percy: Principles of Comedy and Dramatic Effect. London, 1870. NJFreytag, Gustav : The Technique of, the Drama. Trans. E. J. MacEwan. Chicago, 1895. Hazlitt, William : English Comic Writers. Lecture VIII. Hennequin, Alfred: The Art of Play writing. Boston, 1891. Hugo, Victor : Prefaces to Cromwell and Hernani (written 1827, 1830). j Hunt, Leigh: Dramatic Essays. Ed. William Archer and R. W. Lowe. London, 1896. Irving, Henry: The Drama. New York, 1892. Jones, Henry Arthur: The Renascence of the English Drama. London, 1895. 1 For references on English drama, cf. the excellent bibliog- raphy by K. L. Bates and L. B. Godfrey, Wellesley College, 1896. BIBLIOGRAPHIES I// Lamb, Charles : Dramatic Essays. Ed. Brander Matthews. New York, 1891. Morris, Mowbray : Essays in Theatrical Criticism. London, 1882. Meredith, George : An Essay on Comedy, and the Uses of the Comic Spirit. New York, 1897. Moulton, R. G. : Shakespeare as a Dramatic Artist. Oxford, 1889. Polti, Georges: Les Trente-six Situations Dramatiques. Paris, 1895. Prolss, R. : Katechismus der Dramaturgic. Leipzig, 1877. Shaw, G. B. : Articles on the drama in the Saturday Review up to 1898. Souriau, Maurice : De la Convention dans la Tragedie Clas- sique et dans le Drame Romantique. Paris, 1885. Thoma, A. : Das Drama. Gotha, 1891. Wagner, Wilhelm Richard: Oper und Drama. Leipzig, 1852. Walkley, A. B. : Playhouse Impressions. London, 1892. III. LIST OF WORKS THAT WILL BE OF VALUE IN THE STUDY OF CLASSICAL DRAMA 1 Butcher, S. H. : Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and Fine Art, with a critical text and a translation of the Poetics. London and New York, 1895; ^d ed., 1898. , Some Aspects of the Greek Genius. Campbell, Lewis: A Guide to Greek Tragedy for English Readers. New York and London, 1891. Collins, J. Churton: Menander. In Essays and Studies. London, 1895. 1 With two exceptions, this list does not include translations of the classical authors. Jebb's edition of Sophocles is men- tioned because of its invaluable introductions and notes, and the surpassing excellence of its translation ; the translations of Seneca — the first in English since those by Lodge — are noted because they are new and as yet little known. N 178 BIBLIOGRAPHIES Fischer, Rudolf: Zur Kunstentwicklung der Englischen Tra- godie von ihren ersten Anfangen bis zu Shakespeare. Strasburg, 1893. Freytag, Gustav: Technique of the Drama. Trans. E. J, MacEwan. Chicago, 1895. Haigh, A. E. : The Attic Theatre. Oxford, 1889. , The Tragic Drama of the Greeks. Oxford, 1896. Jebb, R. C. : The Growth and Influence of Classical Greek Poetry. Boston and New York, 1893. , Introductions, etc., accompanying translation of Soph- ocles. ^ Moulton, R. G. : The Ancient Classical Drama : A Study in Literary Evolution. Oxford, 1890. Seneca: Medea, and The Daughters of Troy. Metrical translation, Ella I. Harris. Boston, 1898. Sophocles: The Plays and Fragments. Prose translation, R. C. Jebb. Cambridge, 1883-96. Verrall, A. W. : The Student's Manual of Greek Tragedy. London and New York, i8qi. INDEX Addison, 65. ^schylus, vii. Amiel, 4, 44. Aristophanes, vii, 52, 56, 65, 138 ; The Clouds, 61. Aristotle, xiv, i, 10, 11, 12, 13, XT, 19, 20, 22, 24, 25, 29, 31, 38,43,44,45,49, so, 62, H7, 120. Arnold, 22. Beaumont, 45. Browning, 29, 35, 129 ; Blot in the Scutcheon, 132, 133 ; Co- lombe's Birthday, 132, 136; Luria, 130-132; Paracelsus, 132; Sordello, 132; SouVs Tragedy, 40, 132, 135 ; Straf- ford, oh-^rj, n8, 124-125, 132. Butcher, vii, 22. Byron, 35. Cervantes, 35, 66. Chapman, 173 ; All Fools, 140. Christ, 118. Coleridge, 171. Congreve, 138, 162, 167, 169. Corneille, 11, 12-14, 16, 29. Dante, 32, 33, 35. Dickens, 65. Donne, 22. Dostoiefsky, 8-9. Dryden, viii, 65. Eliot, 65 ; Daniel Deronda, 134 ; Middleinarch, 134; Mill on the Floss, 134, 136; Romola, 133. 136. Euripides, vii, 29, 119 ; Alkestis, 50. Fletcher, 45. Freytag, v-ix, xiv, 47, 76, ita, ^ Fulda, viii, 15. Gibbon, 17, 18. Goethe, Faust, 41-42, 118. Goldsmith, 65. viii, 15; Die Haigh, vii. Hauptmann, Weber, 31. Hegel, 39. Hobbes, 56. Horace, 13. Hugo, II. Ibsen, viii, xvi, 15, 48, 85, J05, 124 ; Doll 's House, 135-136 ; Ghosts, iq, 16, 48, 105 ; John Gabriel Borkman, 15. Jebb, vii. 179 i8o INDEX John the Baptist, cf. Suder- mann. Jonson, 6i, 64. 65, 66, 138, 149, 158, 161, 164, 167-169, 170, 171, 172; Alche7nist, 147, 166, 170, 171 ; Bartholomew Fair, 55, 170, 171; Case is Altered, 174; Catiline, 48, 166; Cyn- thia's Revels, 165-166 ; Every Man in His Humour, 137- 138, 140, 165, 174; Every Man out of His Hutnour, 165 ; Magnetic Lady, 170; Poet- aster, 165 ; Sejanus, 48, 49, 118-119, 166; Silent Woman, 140, 174; Staple of News, 170 ; Volpone, 49, 166. Juvenal, 5, 65. Keats, 35. Kipling, Drums of the Fore and Ap, 46. Lessing, 12. Maeterlinck, viii, 85, 132. Marlowe, yew of Malta, 81. Massinger, 138 ; New Way to Pay Old Debts, 140-142, 144, 146, 147, 148, 149; Ro7nan Actor, 48, 118, 166. Menander, 171. Meredith, 55, 64, 65, 168. Middleton, 138. Millet, 2. Milton, Paradise Lost, 22, 32, 33. 35- Moli^re, 55, 64, 65, 66, 138, 150, 158, 162, 164, 167-169, 171, 172, 173 ; L'Ecole des Maris, 140; Le Misanthrope, 148- 149, 167. Napoleon, 18. Orestes, 36, 38, 39, 40, 42, 117, 118, 119. Plato, Sy7nposium, 173. Plautus, 54, 56, 138, 14s, 149, 150, 152, 173. Plutarch, 125. Pope, 65. Rabelais, 35,65. Racine, Athalie, xv, 25-26. Rostand, viii ; Cyrano de Ber- gerac, 108-109. Schiller, 29; Wallenstem, 39. 43. 44, 118. Schopenhauer, 5, 19. Seneca, xiv, ii, 12, 109, 123; Medea, 95-96, 104. Shakespeare, ix, xiv, 9, 12, 14, 18, 20, 29, 33, 35, 52, 61, 65, 78,96, 105, 106, no, 123, 129, 132, 135. 136. 151. 154. 159- 161, 169, 172, 174 ; All's Well that Ends Well, 159 ; Antony and Cleopatra, 15, 84-85, 88 ; As You Like It, 54, 145, 154; Comedy of Errors, 54, 56, 61, 62, 137, 138, 140, 143, 152; Coriolanus, 80, 127-128, ^30, 131, 133, 134; Hamlet, ix, 30, 33> 38. 39. 42. 46, 48, 55. 6"i, . 79, 80, 85, 118, 119, 123, 127, 133. 13s; Henry IV, ix, 55, 62, 66, 137-138, 158 ; Henry V, 18,66; Henry VHI, 18 ; John, 18; Julius CcBsar, 18, 26-27, 79, 80, 85, 88, 90-92, 118, 125-126, 134 ; Lear, 14, 21, 23, 48, 60, 66, 74, 80, 88, 89- 90, 99-101, 114, 118, 126, 13s, 154. 173 ; Love's Labour's Lost, 61, 138, 139, 140, 152, 154, 163-164 ; Macbeth, xiv, 7, INDEX i8i 8, i6, i8, 36-37, 39, 40, 70, 72, 73. 74. 75. 79. 80, 81-83, 85, 86, 87, 89, 97-99, 101-104, 105, 109, 110, 111-112, 119, 123, 133, 134, 135 ; Measure for Measure, 159; Merchant of Venice, 81, 148 (note), 156-158; Merry Wives of Windsor, 138, 158; Mid- summer Night's Dream, 155- 156, 160: Othello, 23, 36, 37-38, 39, 43, 44, 46, 48, 71- 72, 1Z> 74. 75. n, 80, 84, 134- 135, 147-148; Richard III, 48, 49, 80, 88, 118-119. 120, 123; Romeo and Juliet, 39, 43. 79. 80, 86, 87, 88, 90, 104, I12-113, 123, 133, 145, 162; Taming of the Shrew, 138; Tempest, 159, 160; Twelfth Night, 158, 174 ; Two Gentle- men of Verona, 66, 153-155. Shelley, 18, 29, 32; Cenci, 18, 34, 117, 118, 119, 127, 142. Sidney, 52, 63. Socrates, 118. Sophocles, vii, 19. 29, 35, 48; j4jax, 75 ; Antigone, 19, 33, 39-41, 42, 47, 75, 90, 117. 119, 120, 123, 127; Electra, 75; CEdipus Coloneus, 47; CEdi- pus Tyrannus, xiv, xv, 19, 28, 46, 48, 51, 74-75, 86, 117, 126- 127, 142 ; Philoctetes, 75. Sudermann, viii, 15, 105 ; Die Heimath, 15 ; Johannes, 118. Swift, 5, 65. Swinburne, 29. Tennyson, 29, 35, Terence, 54, 56, 138, 145, 150- 151, 152, 153, 171, 173; An- dria, 151 ; HeautontimorU' menos, 151. Thackeray, 65. Virgil, /Eneid, 22. Wildenbruch, Heinrich und Heinrich's Geschlechi, 106- 108, 124, 128-129, Wordsworth, 3, 120-121. 14 DAY USE ^v^^ RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED ^Qf^y LOAN DEPT. This book is due on the last date stamped below, or oa the date to which renewed. Renewed books are subject to immediate recall. pueendo-^^' SToI^-™^ JUN0 9 1991 (fc.^ \-X^ c»Reo^ S^O*i OtP^ LD 2lA-60m-2,'G7 (H241slO)476B ^U^ General Library , University of California Berkeley U'C^} w ^n. '^tCPX^m