THE LIBRARY 
 
 OF 
 
 THE UNIVERSITY 
 
 OF CALIFORNIA 
 
 RIVERSIDE 
 
 
 
 

 
 i£.v '7^l-*K<:''- 
 
 '^-^^^r^r 
 
 
 

 
 Xibrar^ of pbiloeoph^* 
 
 EDITED BY J. H. MUIRHEAD, M.A.
 
 THR [.IBRARY OF PHILOSOPHY. 
 
 riiL LIBRARY OF PHILOSOPHY is in the first in- 
 stance a contribution to the History of Thought. While 
 much has been done in England in tracing the course of evolu- 
 tion in nature, history, religion, and morality, comparatively 
 little has been done in tracing the development of Thought 
 ui)on these and kindred subjects, and yet " the evolution of 
 opinion is part of the whole evolution." 
 
 This Library will deal mainly with Modern Philosophy, 
 j)artly because Ancient Philosophy has already had a fair 
 share of attention in this country through the labours of Grote, 
 Ferrier, and others, and more recently through translations 
 from Zeller ; partly because the Library does not profess to 
 give a complete history of thought. 
 
 By the co-operation of different writers in carrying out this 
 jjlan, it is hoped that a completeness and thoroughness of treat- 
 ment otherwise unattainable will be secured. It is believed, 
 ;ilso, that from writers mainly English and American fuller 
 consideration of English Philosophy than it has hitherto re- 
 ceived from the great German Histories of Philosophy may 
 be looked for. In the departments of Ethics, Economics, and 
 Politics, for instance, the contributions of Encrlish writers to 
 the common stock of theoretic discussion have been especially 
 valuable, and these subjects will accordingly have special pro- 
 minence in this undertaking. 
 
 Another feature in the plan of the Library is its arrange- 
 ment according to subjects rather than authors and dates, 
 enabling the writers to follow out and exhibit in a way 
 hitherto unattempted the results of the logical development of 
 particular lines of thought. 
 
 The historical portion of the Library is divided into two 
 sections, of which the first contains works upon the develop- 
 ment of particular schools of Philosophy, while the second ex- 
 hibits the history of theory in particular departments. The 
 tiiird series contains original contributions to Philosophy, and 
 ihe fourth translations of valuable foreign works. 
 
 To these has been added, by way of Introduction to the 
 whole Library, an English translation of Erdmann's " History 
 of Philosophy," long since recognised in Germany as the 
 best. 
 
 J. H. MUIRHEAD, 
 
 ii General Editor.
 
 ALREADY PUBLISHED. 
 
 The History of Philosophy. By Dr. Johan'x Eduard Erdmank. 
 
 English Translation. Edited by Willistov S. Hough, M.Ph., Professor of 
 Mental and Moral Philosophy and Logic in the University of Minnesota. 
 In 3 vols., medium 8vo, cloth. 
 Vol. I. Ancient and Mediaeval Philosophy, 155. . . . Third Edition. 
 
 Vol. H. Modern Philosophy, 15? Third Edition. 
 
 Vol. in. Modern Philosophy since Hegel, 1 2.f. . . . Third Edition. 
 
 The History of .Esthetic. By Bernard Bosanquet, M.A., LL.D., late Fellow of 
 
 University College, Oxford. [Second Series. 
 
 The Development of Rational Theology since Kant. By Professor Otpo 
 
 Pfleiderer, of Berlin. [Second Series. Second Edition. 
 
 Philosophy and Political Economy in some of their Historical Relations. 
 
 By James Bonar, M.A., LL.D. [Second Series. 
 
 Appearance and Reality. By F. H. Bradley, M.A., Fellow of Merton College, 
 
 Oxford. 
 Natural Rights. By David G. Ritchie, Professor of Logic and Metaphysics in the 
 
 University of St. Andrews. [Third Series. 
 
 SiGWAJix's Logic. Translated by Helen Dendy. 2 vols. [Fourth Series. 
 
 LIST OF WORKS IN PREPARATION. 
 
 FIRST SERIES. 
 
 Early Idealism: Descartes to Leibnitz. By W. L. Courtney, M.A., LL.D. (St. 
 
 Andrews), Fellow of New College, Oxford. 
 German Idealists: Kant to Hegel. By Wm. Wallace, M.A., Whyte Professor of 
 
 Moral Philosophy, University of Oxford. 
 MoDKRN Realists: Leibnitz, Herbart, Lotze. By Andrew Seth, M.A., Professor of 
 
 Logic and English Literature, University of Edinburgh. 
 Sensationalists: Locke to Mill. By W. S. Hough, M.Ph., Professor of Mental and 
 
 Moral Philosophy, University of Minnesota. U.S.A. 
 The Utilitarians : Hume to Contemporary Writers. By W. R. Sorley, M. A., Fellow 
 
 of Trinity College, Cambridge, and Professor of Philo.sophy in University College, Cardiff. 
 Principle of Evolution in its Scientific and Philosophical Aspects. liy John 
 
 Watson, LL.D., Professor of Moral Philosophy, University of Queen's College, 
 
 Kingston, Canada. 
 
 SECOND SERIES. 
 
 The History of Psychology : Empirical and Rational. By Robert Adamson, M.A., 
 
 LL.D., Professor of Logic, University of Aberdeen. 
 The History of Political Philosophy. By D. G. Ritchie, M.A., Professor of 
 
 Logic and Metaphysics in the University of St. Andrews, and J. H. Muirhead, 
 
 M. A., Lecturer in Philosophy, Royal Holloway College, Egham, and Bedford College, 
 
 London. 
 The History of the Philosophical Tendencies of the Nineteenth Century. 
 
 By Josiah Royce, Professor of Philo.sophy, Harvard University. 
 
 THIRD SERIES. 
 
 First Principles of Philosophy. By John Stuari' Mackenzie, M..\., Fellow of 
 Trinity College. Cambridge. 
 
 The Theory of Ethics. By Edward Caird, LL.D., Master of Balliol College, 
 Oxford. 
 
 Epistemology ; or, The Theory of Knowi.edc;e. By James Ward, D.Sc, LL.D., 
 Fellow and Lecturer of Trinity College, Cambridge. 
 
 Principles of Psychology. By G. F. Stout, M.A., Fellow of St. John's College, 
 Cambridge. [Shortly. 
 
 Principles of In.strumental Logic. By John Dewey, Ph.D., Professor of Philo- 
 sophy, University of Michigan. 
 
 SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & Co., LONDON. 
 MACMILLAN & Co., NEW YORK.
 
 NATURAL RIGHTS 
 
 A CRITICISM OF SOME POLITICAL AND 
 ETHICAL CONCEPTIONS 
 
 DAVID G. RITCHIE M.A. 
 
 Professor of Logic and Metaphysics in the University of St. Andrcivs 
 Late Fellow and Tutor of Jesus College, Oxford; Author of " Darwin and Hegel," etc 
 
 3LonlJon 
 
 SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO 
 
 NEW YORK: MACMILLAN & CO 
 
 1895
 
 Q.C57' 
 
 BCIXER & Tanneb, 
 
 The Selwood Printing Works, 
 
 Frome, and London.
 
 go 
 E. S. H. R.
 
 PREFACE 
 
 When I began, some three years ago, to write a paper on " Natural 
 Rights," which has grown by degrees into the present volume, I 
 had a certain fear that in criticising that famous theory I might 
 be occupied in slaying the already slain. Recent experience has, 
 however, convinced me that the theory is still, in a sense, alive, or 
 at least capable of mischief. Though disclaimed by almost all our 
 more careful writers on politics and ethics, it yet remains a common- 
 place of the newspaper and the platform, not only in the United 
 States of America, where the theory may be said to form part of the 
 national creed, but in this country, where it was assailed a century 
 ago by both Burke and Bentham. If it be suggested that an ex- 
 posure of fallacies, which have survived the attack of two critics so 
 great and of such diverse genius, is either futile or superfluous, I 
 should answer that I hope I have approached the theory in a spirit 
 more appreciative and sympathetic than was possible to the eloquent 
 passion of Burke, or to the keen, cold, abstractly logical analysis of 
 Bentham. At least, I have endeavoured to regard the theorj'- in the 
 light of its historical significance ; for it is never sufficient to argue 
 that a widely held opinion is erroneous without trying to show how 
 and why it came to be widely held. What I have attempted is 
 simply a contribution to an historical and critical analysis of a set 
 of conceptions which have had, for good and evil, an enormous 
 influence in the region of practical politics and legislation. The 
 study is but a fragment of political philosophy ; and even in itself 
 it is inevitably incomplete. Illustrations and applications might 
 have been multiplied indefinitely ; and any selection must always 
 seem arbitrary to some readers. The subject of " liberty of thought " 
 has been discussed at what may seem disproportionate length ; but 
 it appeared to me one of the most suitable for the sake of illustration, 
 and the treatment accorded to it is, after all, not very lengthy. 
 Chapter VIII. will serve its purpose best, if it should help to provoke 
 some competent historical student to undertake an history of the 
 practice and of the idea of toleration, on which I have only given a 
 few jottings. 
 
 In writing on any political subject, however scientific and academic
 
 PREFACE 
 
 When I began, some three years ago, to write a paper on "Natural 
 Rights," which has grown by degrees into the present volume, I 
 had a certain fear that in criticising that famous theory I might 
 be occupied in slaying the already slain. Recent experience has, 
 however, convinced me that the theory is still, in a sense, alive, or 
 at least capable of mischief. Though disclaimed by almost all our 
 more careful writers on politics and ethics, it yet remains a common- 
 place of the newspaper and the platform, not only in the United 
 States of America, where the theory may be said to form part of the 
 national creed, but in this country, where it was assailed a centmy 
 ago by both Burke and Bentham. If it be suggested that an ex- 
 posure of fallacies, which have survived the attack of two critics so 
 great and of such diverse genius, is either futile or superfluous, I 
 should answer that I hope I have approached the theory in a spirit 
 more appreciative and sympathetic than was possible to the eloquent 
 passion of Burke, or to the keen, cold, abstractly logical analysis of 
 Bentham. At least, I have endeavoured to regard the theorj'- in the 
 light of its historical significance ; for it is never sufficient to argue 
 that a Avidely held opinion is erroneous withoiit trying to show how 
 and why it came to be widely held. What I have attempted is 
 simply a contribution to an historical and critical analysis of a set 
 of conceptions which have had, for good and evil, an enormous 
 influence in the region of practical politics and legislation. The 
 study is but a fi-agment of political philosophy ; and even in itself 
 it is inevitably incomplete. Illustrations and applications might 
 have been multiplied indefinitely ; and any selection must always 
 seem arbitrary to some readers. The subject of " liberty of thought " 
 has been discussed at what may seem disproportionate length ; but 
 it appeared to me one of the most suitable for the sake of illustration, 
 and the treatment accorded to it is, after all, not very lengthy. 
 Chapter VIII. will serve its purpose best, if it should help to provoke 
 some competent historical student to undertake an history of the 
 practice and of the idea of toleration, on which I have only given a 
 few jottings. 
 
 In writing on any political subject, however scientific and academic
 
 X FRF. FACE 
 
 oue may seek to be, it is impossible to avoid matters of practical 
 controversy or to escape all suspicion of partisanship. I would only 
 ask fair-minded readers to take no one passage as conveying my 
 opinions apart from qualifications expressed or implied in what is 
 said elsewhere in the volume. Conservative, Liberal, Radical, 
 Socialist, may each, amid much to dissent from, find something 
 with which he may agree; and I think this ought to be so, for 
 each of them represents some aspect of political truth neglected by 
 the others. The only political theorists whom I expect to dissent 
 from everything I have written are Anarchists, whether calling 
 themselves such, or by one of the other four names. Anarchism is 
 the creed of unreason in politics, and is a political philosophy only in 
 the sense in which absolute scepticism may be called a metaphysical 
 system. 
 
 For much of the historical material that I have used in this book 
 I am indebted, directly or indirectly, to the kind help of special 
 students of history, whom I have the good fortune to count among 
 my friends. Of these I ought particularly to name Mr. Charles H. 
 Firth. For many valuable suggestions I have to thank my friend 
 Mr. J. H. Muirhead, who, as editor of this Series, has read the book 
 through, both in MS. and in proof. And in every stage of the work 
 I owe more than I can fittingly express here to the advice, encourage- 
 ment and criticisms of ray wife. Bat for all errors and shortcomings 
 I must myself accept the full responsibility. The book has been 
 written at intervals, and amid many interruptions and much pressure 
 of other work. Yet I trust that it may be of some interest to the 
 general reader, as well as of some use to the special student of ethica 
 and politics. None of it has appeared in print before, except the 
 short chapter on " The Rights of Property," which was published, 
 in an Italian translation, in ha Riforma Sociale of May, 1894. 
 The appendix is given for the convenience of the student. It con- 
 tains the two oldest of the American Declarations of Natural Rights, 
 and all the French Declarations, as the latter are not very easily 
 accessible in this country. The translation of the Declaration of 
 1789, which appears in Paine's Rights of Man ^ is inserted, as possess- 
 ing an historical interest on its own account. 
 
 St. Andrews, 
 
 Octobtr, 1894.
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 Part I. — The Theory of Natural Eights. 
 
 IPTEB PAGES 
 
 f. The Principles of "89 :5-19 
 
 The " Rights of Man " not first proclaimed in the 
 French Declarations, 3; already formvilated in America, 
 4; the Virginia "Bill of Rights," 4, 5; these principles 
 derived from Locke, 6; implicit in Protestantism,?; 
 Wycliffe and John Ball, 8 ; the " Levellers," 8, 9. Transi- 
 tion from historical to " natural " rights among English 
 Puritans, 10; among American colonists, 10, 11 ; natural 
 rights pictured as quasi-historical, 11-13. 
 
 The appeal to Nature is (1) an appeal against external 
 authority, 13 ; and (2) an appeal to the judgment of 
 the individual, 14. The theory of natural rights maj- 
 become the creed of the Anarchist, but also of the Con- 
 servative individualist, 14-16 ; how revolutionary creeds 
 become conservative— the dialectic movement of history, 
 16-18; illustration from Calvinism, 18, 19. Plan of 
 following chapters, 19. 
 II. On the History of the Idea of " Nature " in Law and 
 
 Politics 20-47 
 
 Ambiguity of the word "natural," 20. The Greek 
 Sophists the forerunners of the eighteenth century 
 Rationalists, 21-25; the antithesis of "nature" and 
 " convention," 24-27. Aristotle's conception of nature, 
 27 ; his different uses of the term, 28 ; examination of 
 passages that seem to contain the idea of a " law of 
 nature," 29-32. The Cynics, and their " return to 
 nature," 32, 33. The Stoic conception of nature, 33-35. 
 Cicero, 85, 36. Roman Law, 36, 37 ; jus naf urate and 
 jvs gentium, 38. Influence of Roman legal ideas on 
 Western thought, 38,39; Thomas Aquinas, 39, 40 ; the 
 Roman conception of jus naturale favourable to legal 
 reform, 40, 41 ; its influence on International Law, 41 ; 
 OIL, politics and .ethics, 41. The "State of Nature" 
 in'/Hobbes-^Loc'ke, Pope, Rousseau, 42-44. "Natural 
 Theology " (in Adam Smith, etc.), 44, 45. Influence of 
 Natural Science on Mr. Herbert Spencer, who defends 
 "natural rights," 45, 46. " Biological rights," 46, 47.
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 CHAPTKK 
 
 PAGES 
 
 III. Rousseau and Rousseauism 48-70 
 
 Rousseau's opinion of civilisation iu his Contrat Social 
 contrasted with that in his earlier writings, 48-51. 
 '" Rousseauism "—the " return to nature," etc.— derived 
 from these earlier writings, 51 ; not properly " Socialist," 
 but individualist or anarchist, 52. Civilisation, its 
 elements, 53-56; city life and the love of nature, 56-59. 
 Truth and falsehood in the revolt against civilisation, 59. 
 The cult of the savage, 60-62. The burden of civilised 
 life, 63, 64. Types of Anarchists, 65, 66. Abstract think- 
 ing, 66-68. Antithesis between nature and man, 68-70 ; 
 its falsehood, 70. 
 
 IV. De DivisioxE Natur.k 71-77 
 
 I. Nature as the totality of what exists ; (a) Natura 
 naturans, (b) Natura naturata, 71-74. II. The " natural" 
 as opposed to the human or artificial, 74. III. The 
 " natural " as the original, 74, 75. IV. The " natural " as 
 the normal or the ideal, 75. Confusion between these 
 meanings, 75, 76. Another grouping of meanings sug- 
 gested, 77. 
 \. What Determines Rights'? 78-ll(; 
 
 Definition of a legal right, 78 ; of a moral right, 78-80. 
 Natural rights not identical with moral rights ; they are 
 the more fundamental rights which would be guaranteed 
 by a society which was as it ought to be, 80, 81. What 
 determines this "ought"? (1) Authority? 82-85; (2) 
 Nature, i.e. individual conscience or sentiment ? 85-87 ; 
 (3) Utility or Reason ? 87. 
 
 Conflicting interpretations of " the law of nature " 
 illustrated from opinions about polygamy: Father 
 Rickaby, 88-90; Grotius, 90; Locke, 90-92; Lorimer, 
 92, 93 ; Shelley, 93. Is Utility an equally uncertain 
 guide? 94; defects of Bentliamist Utilitarianism, 94-9(). 
 Tliese defects disappear, if, instead of feelings of pleasure 
 and pain taken abstractly, the Universal Ego or Reason 
 be made the metaph3'sical basis of ethics, 96, 97. Transi- 
 tion from Individualist to Evolutionist Utilitarianism, 
 97 101. Rights dependent on Society, 101-103. The 
 evolutionist manner of judging institutions, e.cj. slavery, 
 103, 104 ; industrial competition, 104, 105. Advantage of 
 appealing to reason and experience, rather than to 
 '■ Nature," 105, 106. 
 
 Some questions connected with the foregoing : Have 
 the lower animals rights ? 107-111. The notion of 
 progress, 111-114. The place of individual rights (1) in 
 political theory ; (2) in constitutional law, 115, 116.
 
 CONTENTS xiii 
 
 Pakt II. — Particular Natural Rights. 
 
 CHAPTER PiGES 
 
 VI. The Right of Life 119-134 
 
 (a) The instinct of self-preservation, 110, 120. Does 
 this give rise to a natural right in the individual against 
 society ? 120-122 ; or in the societj-, as a whole, against 
 other societies ? 122-121. 
 
 (&) Does the right to preserve imply the right to end 
 life? Opinions on suicide, 124-126. 
 
 (c) The right of " enjoying " life, 127. 
 
 {d) Is there a right to be well-born ? The rights of the 
 unborn, 127-134. 
 VII. The Right of Liberty : Liberty of Thought . . 135-156 
 
 The terms " liberty " and " freedom," their ambiguitj^, 
 135-138. Difference between negative and positive 
 liberty, 138, 139. Positive liberty cannot exist apart 
 from the State, 139, 140. The formula of " equal liberty," 
 141, 142 ; difficulty in applying it as the principle of 
 justice, 143-145. Limitation of individual liberty in the 
 French Declarations of Rights, 145, 146. The limitation 
 must be other than the equal liberty of other individuals, 
 146, 147. 
 
 Liberty of thought, in its literal sense, 147, 148 ; in the 
 positive sense of intellectual freedom it implies the exist- 
 ence of a strong government, 148, 149. Religious and 
 civil liberty not always found together, 149, 150. Liberty 
 of the press in the French Constitutions, 150, 151 ; in 
 England dependent solely on the abolition of the censor- 
 ship and on trial by jury, 151-155. Moral value of a 
 formal declaration of the right, 156. 
 VIII. Toleration 157-209 
 
 The term "Toleration" defended, 157-159. What is 
 "persecution"? 159, 160. Some limits to libertj^ of 
 speech and writing, as well as of action, required every- 
 where, 161. The teaching of Thomas Aquinas and his 
 followers on the repression of heresy, 161-164; Father 
 Eickaby on " liberty of opinion," 164-167. 
 
 The grounds of persecution : (1) tribal, 168 ; (2) 
 political, 168, 169 ; (3) theological — to defend the truth : 
 Christianity and persecution, 169-173. Locke's Letters 
 on Toleration do not meet the real principles of con- 
 scientious persecutors, 173-175 ; Locke's limits to tolera- 
 tion, 175, 176; compared with Rousseau's "Civil 
 religion," 176. Political character of persecution in 
 the early Roman Empire and in Elizabethan England, 
 176-178. Comparison of the Swiss and American con- 
 stitutional guarantees of religious liberty, 178-180. Ex- 
 tent of practical liberty in Great Britain, 180, 181. (4) 
 Social grounds of persecution hardly separable from the 
 others, 181, 182.
 
 (iv CONTENTS 
 
 Need of an historical spirit in judging of the past, 
 182. Growth of the practice of toleration, 183. The 
 principle of toleration implies a change of opinion as to 
 what is socially expedient or as to what is essential in 
 religion, 184, 185. Principles of intolerance may coexist 
 with mildness in practice, 185. 
 
 Ought the intolerant to be tolerated? — Opinions of 
 Locke, Rousseau, Renan, 185-188. Limits of toleration, 
 188. 
 
 Toleration in matters affecting morality, 189-198. 
 Difference between religious belief and morality, 189 ; 
 difficulty of estimating moral superiority, 190; the test 
 of seriousness in literature and art, 191-193; new ideas 
 must struggle, 193; what minorities may fairly claim, 
 194, 195. The duty of private judgment, 196. The claims 
 of Authority, 197. 
 Note A. — Religious Persecution and Toleration : Some 
 
 Historical Illustrations 198-202 
 
 Hallaiii on the persecutions of Elizabeth's reign, 198; 
 Burleigh's defence of his ti-eatment of Roman Catholics, 
 198,199; Hallam's five degrees of religious persecution, 
 200. The Declaration of Breda, 200. The " Instrument of 
 Government," 200. Roger Williams, the champion of 
 " soul-liberty" in principle and practice, 201, 202. 
 Note B.— Measures for Suppressing Mormonism in the 
 
 United States 202-209 
 
 Reasons for treating of the question, 202, 203. Legisla- 
 tion against polygamy, 204-207. Test-oath imposed on 
 voters, 207-209. 
 
 IX. The Rights of Public Meeting and Association . 210-226 
 The right of public meeting in France, 210, 211 ; in 
 Belgium, 211. The attitude of English law to public 
 meetings, 211-214. Voluntary associations, how different 
 from the State, 214-217. The family, 217; the Church 
 (the " liberty of the Church," " free Churches "), 218-221 ; 
 trading corporations, 221 ; Trade-Unions, 221-225. Prob- 
 lems for a Socialistic State, 224-226. 
 
 X. Freedom of Contract, National Freedom, etc. . 227-237 
 No absolute right of contract, 227. Must the State 
 
 enforce all the contracts it has permitted? 228. The 
 
 United States constitution prohibits the States from 
 
 impairing contract-obligations, 229. 
 The droit du travail, 229, 230 ; the droit au travail, 
 
 230, 231. 
 
 National freedom or independence, 232. Is there a 
 
 right of aggression? 233, 234, " International burglaries," 
 
 234. No general principle of non-intervention, 235. The 
 
 right to restrict immigration, 236, 237.
 
 CONTENTS XV 
 
 CUAPTBB PIRKS 
 
 XI. Resistance to Oppression 238-243 
 
 The right of resistance in the French and American 
 Declarations, 238, 239. A constitutional right of re- 
 bellion belongs to a verj^ primitive type of political 
 existence, 239, 240. The Pope as judge of tyrants, 240. 
 Constitutions regarded as compacts, 241 ; the South 
 Carolina Declaration of Independence, 241, 242. The 
 ethics of rebellion, 248. 
 
 XII. Equality 244-2G2 
 
 Natural right of equality in French and American 
 Declai-ations, 244. The natural equality of man accord- 
 ing to Hobbes, 245 ; and Locke, 246. The natural in- 
 equality of man not alwa.ys an argument for political 
 inequality, 246-248. The idea of equality aristocratic 
 in origin, 248. Bentham assumes equality, 249. Hedonist 
 Utilitarianism in its strict form might justify inequality 
 in some cases, equality in others, 249-251. Ethics based 
 on human rationality, can regard men, qua men, as all 
 potentially sharers in the same ideals, 251, 252. Kant's 
 formula for the moral law, 252, 253. Every human 
 being a " person," if humanity is regarded as a possible 
 society, 253, 254. The ideal of equality, how far due to 
 Christianity, 254. 
 
 Equality before the law, 255. Equality in political 
 rights, 255. Property qualifications for the suffrage, 
 255, 256 ; educational qualifications, 256, 257. The 
 suffrage as a duty : compulsory voting, 257, 258. 
 
 Negative equality, ?'.e. free competition, accentuates 
 inequality of social condition, 258. Equality of social 
 condition would require State-interference with the 
 familj', 259, 260 ; still more would equality of the sexes, 
 if it included the economic independence of women, 260, 
 261. Plato's ideal — the State as one family, 262. 
 
 XIII. The Right of Property 263-271 
 
 Ambiguity in the phrase " right of property." What 
 does Property imply ? 263, 264. The definitions and 
 limitations of property rights in the rival constitutions 
 of Kansas (1857-58), 264; in the French Declarations, 
 265 ; in the United States Constitution, 265. 
 
 The theory basing property on occupation, 266-268. 
 Locke's theory, basing property on labour, 268-271 ; Mr. 
 Henry George versus the Pope, 270, 271. 
 XIV. The Right of Pursuing and Obtaining Happiness 272-286 
 
 "Pursuing" and "obtaining" distinguished; Happi- 
 ness as the end of government, 272-275. 
 
 Conclusion : Aim not directly practical, but scientific 
 or philosophical, i.e. critical, 275, 276. The Socialistic 
 tendencies of our age, 276, 277. Progress must be 
 gradual, 277-282; "bourgeois" interest in civilisation,
 
 xvi CONTENTS 
 
 FAGK8 
 
 278 ; need of international solidaritj^, 279 ; fallacious 
 remedies, 280; continued importance of political qties- 
 tions, 280, 281 ; moral proj?ress must accompany political, 
 281, 282 ; delusion of finality, 282. Objection of the 
 pessimist, 282-284. Faith in the rationality of the 
 world is implied in social effort, 284, 285 ; and should 
 exclude contempt for the past and present, 285, 286. 
 
 APPENDIX. 
 
 The Virginian Declaration of Eights — June 12, 1776. 287 
 Extract from the Declaration of Independence— 
 
 July 4, 1776 289 
 
 French Declaration of Eights of 1789 (Constitution 
 
 of 1791), WITH Painb's Translation .... 290 
 
 French Declaration of Eights of 1793 . . . 294 
 
 French Declaration of Eights and Duties of 1795 . 297 
 
 Preamble to French Constitution of 1848 . . . 299 
 
 Index 301
 
 PART I 
 THE THEORY OF NATURAL RIGHTS
 
 CHAPTER I 
 
 THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 
 
 " The principles of 1789 " were embodied in the Declaration 
 of the Rights of Man, which was prefixed to the Constitution 
 promulgated in 1791. They are often spoken of, b}^ those 
 who admire and by those who reject them, as if they were 
 the distinctive and peculiar creed of the French Revolution. 
 But France deserves neither the credit nor the blame of 
 endeavouring to express for the first time, and for all time, 
 in a few abstract phrases the political and social faith on 
 which her institutions were to be founded and built up, 
 France has suffered more than any nation because of this creed 
 of liberty and equality that she proclaimed in the face of the 
 world ; but her critics, among whom may now be found many 
 Frenchmen as well as Englishmen and Germans, are guilty 
 of historical inaccuracy, if, on the evidence of this creed, they 
 contrast the foolish abstractions of the Gallic spirit with the 
 prudent positivism of those whom they are pleased to call 
 "Anglo-Saxons." If the French may be blamed at all in the 
 matter, there is more ground for alleging that they simply 
 plagiarised " Anglo-Saxon " formulas. Every article in the 
 French revolutionary creed had been already formulated — and 
 often (as will be shown in detail) in less carefully guarded 
 phraseology — by the emancipated "Anglo-Saxons " on the other 
 side of the Atlantic. When Lafa3^ette sent the key of the 
 destroyed Bastille by Thomas Paine to George Washington, he 
 was, in a picturesque symbol, confessing the debt of France to 
 America.^ It is true that neither the " Articles of Confedera- 
 tion " of 1777, nor the " Constitution of the United States," as 
 originally proposed (1787j and ratified, contained any "Bill," or 
 "Declaration of Rights"; it is true, also, that the first ten 
 "Amendments," which were added in 1789, were regarded by 
 Jefferson as a somewhat inadequate substitute for the Declara- 
 tion of Rights which he desired.^ But it should not be for- 
 
 ^ See Moncnre Conway, Life of Thomas I'aine, I. pp. 272-275. 
 ^ See his letters to Madison quoted by Janet, Hist, dc la Science 
 Politique (Ed. 3), 1., Introd., i)p. xxi.x.-xxxi.
 
 4 THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 [ch. i 
 
 gotten, /?r.«f, that the Declaration of Independence (1776) had 
 already named the natural and "unalienable rights," in virtue 
 of which the American colonists justified their rebellion 
 ao-ainst the British Government and their existence as a 
 group of leagued but independent States : and second^ that 
 the Constitution of the United States— even that of 1787— was 
 reo-arded as only drawing closer the bonds of alliance between 
 States which were still supposed to retain, in many respects, 
 their sovereign rights. The Constitution of the Union only 
 contains the terms of the federal compact.^ It declares the 
 rights of the States as against the Federal Government. The 
 appropriate place for the declaration of the rights of the indi- 
 vidual citizen is not in the federal constitution, but in the consti- 
 tutions of the several States.- And in most of the Constitutions 
 which originated after 1776 (some of the States retaining for 
 a considerable period — Rhode Island as late as 1842 — their old 
 colonial charters), there is a Declaration, or Bill of Eights, 
 exactly analogous to the French declaration. The " Bill of 
 Rights " of Virginia (June 12th, 1776) may be taken as 
 typical : it has served as the model for many similar declara- 
 tions, adopted after American independence had been secured. 
 " Other colonies," says Bancroft, " had framed bills of rights 
 in reference to their relations with Britain: Virginia moved 
 from charters and customs to primal principles; from a narrow 
 altercation about facts to the contemplation of immutable 
 truth. She summoned the eternal laws of man's being to pro- 
 test against all tyranny." ^ These words are worth pondering, 
 and also the words of the " Bill of Rights " itself. They may 
 serve as a wholesome warning against the habit of explaining 
 political institutions and political ideas by facile theories of 
 race-difference. 
 
 As M. Paul Janet has well said, " If the French Revolution 
 has lasted longer and been more violent than the English 
 
 ' See below, pp. 241, 242. 
 
 '•* Franklin had the American State Constitutions translated into 
 French, and presented them to Louis XVI. Cf. Moncure Conwaj', Life 
 of Paine, I. p. 290. 
 
 » Ilistorrj of the United States (ed. 5), YIII. p. 383. In M. Paul Janet's 
 " Introduction" to the 3rd edition of his Histoiie de la Science Politique, 
 the contrast drawn by M. Boutmy between the French and American 
 Constitutions in this matter of natural rights, seems to me verj- .fifectively 
 criticised.
 
 CH. i] THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 5 
 
 Revolution, it is because it has taken place a century later." ^ 
 The English parliamentarian was able to appeal, with more 
 or less accuracy, to " historical rights " — not in a forgotten, . 
 but in a recent past. The advocate of constitutional govern- 
 ment in the France of 1789 could not appeal to any " historical 
 rights " that were known to any one but antiquarians. Apart 
 from the longer postponement of the crisis, the remed}' was 
 more difficult to find in France than in England, secured 
 against continental complications by her insular position, or 
 than in America, separated by the ocean from the government 
 she was shaking off, and either receiving the sympathy, or 
 free from the interference of distant European powers. TJie 
 principles of the French Revolution were phrased in " meta- 
 physical" language. This was not due to a special defect in 
 the French mind, but to the spirit of the eighteenth century. 
 The English revolutionists of 1640 to 1660 spoke in theological 
 language ; it was the fashion of their time. The inheritors 
 of English traditions in America talk the same " metaphysical 
 jargon " which the French were to repeat in the next decade. 
 The Virginians declare — 
 
 " That all men are by nature equally free and independent, and have 
 certain inherent rights, of which, when they enter into a state of society, 
 they cannot by any compact deprive or divest their posteritj^ ; namely, 
 the enjoj'ment of life and libert3^, with the means of acquiring and pos- 
 sessing property, and pursuing and obtaining happiness and safety. 
 
 " That all power is vested in, and consequently derived from, the 
 people ; that magistrates are their trustees and servants, and at all times 
 amenable to them. 
 
 " That government is, or ought to he, instituted for the common 
 benefit, protection and security of the people, nation or community ; of 
 all the various modes and forms of government, that is best which is cap- 
 able of producing the greatest degree of happiness and safetj?-, and is.most 
 effectually secured against the danger of maladministration ; and that 
 when a government shall be found inadequate or contrary' to these pur- 
 poses, a majority of the community hath an indubitable, unalienable and 
 indefeasible right to reform, alter or abolish it, in such manner as shall 
 he judged most conducive to the public weal." 
 
 Is there anything more extreme in the French declarations 
 of 1791 and 1793? And is there one word of Burke's eloquent 
 denunciation of " metaphysic rights " which would not be 
 equally applicable to this Virginian declaration of 1776 ? And 
 the Americans should, in his eyes, have had the less excuse 
 
 ^ Hht, de la fSc. Pol. (od. 3), p. Ixi.
 
 6 THE nUNCIPLES OF 'S9 [ch. i 
 
 for their metaphysics, because they might have continued to 
 appeal, as they already liad appealed, to the inheritance of 
 .English liberties. 
 
 We must not suppose that this appeal to natural rights was 
 due solely to the influence of Rousseau, or that save for French 
 " metaphysics " such ideas would never have found a home in 
 the minds of men of English race and English speech. "Men 
 being by nature all free, equal and independent, no one can 
 be put out of this estate and subjected to the political power 
 of another without his own consent." These are the words 
 of the sober Englishman, John Locke ; ^ and in his Treatise of 
 Civil Government^ the great intellectual vindication of the prin- 
 ciples of the "Whig revolution of 1688,^ will be found every 
 one of the three principles which Burke condemns, and which 
 he doubtless did not find expressly formulated in the Act of 
 the 1st of William and Mary, sess. 2, ch. 2, which is known 
 as the "Declaration of Right." The principles of the revo-« 
 lution of 1688, according to Dr. Richard Price, were these : — 
 that we have a right (1) " To choose our own governors ; " 
 {2j " To cashier them for misconduct ; " (3) " To frame a 
 government for ourselves." ^ The doctrines of the American 
 Declaration of Independence resemble far more closely the 
 views of Locke than those of Rousseau. None at least of those 
 theories in respect of which Rousseau differs from Locke are 
 to Ije found in the American Declaration. And one passage 
 in the American Declaration echoes not merely the ideas, but 
 the very phraseology of Locke's Treatise.'^ 
 
 But the theory of natural rights was not Locke's invention. 
 Neither he nor Jean Jacques can claim the credit of having 
 " discovered the lost title-deeds of the human race." The 
 theory of natural rights is simply the logical outgrowth of the 
 Protestant revolt against the authority of tradition, the logi- 
 cal outgrowth of the Protestant appeal to private judgment, 
 i.e. to the reason and conscience of the individual. Speaking 
 
 * Treatise of Civil Government., II. § 95. 
 
 - It was published in 1000, though the greater part of it maj- have been 
 written before 1688. See Fox Bourne, Life of Locke, II. pp. 165, 166. 
 
 ^ Discourse on the Love of our Country, delivered on Nov. Uh, 1789. 
 Cf. Burke, Reflections on the lievolution in France, near the beginning. 
 
 ■• Compare with the Declaration (see Appendix) Locke's Treatise of 
 Civil Government, II. § 225, especially the words, "But if a long train 
 of abuses," etc.
 
 CH. i] THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 7 
 
 generall}'-, we may say that throughout all the struggles of 
 the Middle Ages, it was not " liberty" for which men fought, 
 but " liberties," Privileges were claimed because of some 
 real or fancied authority in the past. A town, a district, a 
 corporation, or a social class alleged on its own behalf im- 
 memorial custom or some definite royal, imperial, or papal 
 grant or charter. The political theories of the Middle Ages 
 were mostly the theories of men living in the cloister, or 
 trained under monastic influences. They implied the accep- 
 tance of three great authorities, which might be interpreted 
 or applied, but were not to be questioned — the authority of 
 the Bible, of Aristotle, and of Justinian. Now, as we shall 
 see, each of these authorities contributed something (Aristotle 
 least of all) to that idea of a Law of Nature which, in the 
 eighteenth century, became the basis of the revolutionary 
 creed. But, while the intellect of Europe still lived under the 
 abiding shadow of the Holy Roman Empire and the Holy 
 Roman Church, man did not think of himself except as the 
 paember of a particular nation, and, still more even, as the mem- 
 ber of a definite social class or caste. The Aristotelian doctrine 
 that " man is by nature a political animal " had acquired the 
 sanctity of a dogma, and kept the mediaeval thinker from 
 imagining man's rights in abstraction from any particular 
 political society. Still, even in the Middle Ages among the 
 unlettered multitudes, with whom Aristotle and Justinian 
 counted for nothing, but the dimly known Hebrew Scriptures 
 for a great deal, we find the first germs of an appeal to some- 
 thing beyond all charters and all customs and usages of 
 which lawyers knew. WyclifFe's startling thesis that " every 
 one in a state of grace has real lordship over the whole uni- 
 verse," ^ from which he deduces his ideal of community of 
 property, can hardly be cited as a mediaeval example of the 
 natural rights theory, because it is not man as man, but 
 only the saints that are in this fashion to inherit the earth. 
 Th-e man who is in mortal sin cannot hold dominion or lord- 
 ship at all. Nevertheless, it is easy to see what might become 
 of such interpretations of the Bible when they made their 
 way into the minds of the poor parish priests, or of oppressed 
 
 * See WyclifFe, De Civili Dominio, edited by R. L. Poole. Pref., pp. 
 xxii.-xxiv.
 
 8 THE rRINCITLES OF '89 [ch. i 
 
 peasants, who found in some scriptural phrase a voice for 
 their sufferings and for their claims. 
 
 " When Adam dalf and Eve span, 
 Who was then the gentleman ? " 
 
 In these words, which fixed in the popular mind the teach- 
 ings of the "mad" Wycliffite, John Ball, we have a genuine 
 appeal to the natural equality of mankind. The Bible, which 
 "VVycliife had tried to open to his countrymen, admitted, in- 
 deed, of diverse interpretations. Adam's dominion over the 
 creatures was appealed to by Sir Robert Filmer ^ in the seven- 
 teenth century as a ground for the divine right of kings to 
 rule despotically ; but an English peasant of the fourteenth 
 century, or of the seventeenth, was likely to find a different 
 lesson in the story of the "grand old gardener and his wife." 
 If all mankind were the sons of Adam, and if all might be- 
 come by adoption the sons of God, distinctions of birth, and 
 wealth, and power seemed a mere human invention, a conse- 
 quence (but why an inevitable consequence ?) of sin and the 
 corruption of human nature. Under the reign of the saints 
 might we not get rid of these inequalities ? The doctrine of 
 the " Levellers " may not be the doctrine of the most learned, 
 nor of the most orthodox, theologians, but it represents the 
 ideal which the exercise of private judgment in the study of 
 the Bible had kindled in the minds of the disinherited and 
 the oppressed. 
 
 I have already referred incidentally to the historical or 
 quasi-historical character of the rights claimed by the English 
 parliamentarians in the seventeenth century. The more 
 advanced sections of the anti-royalist party find themselves 
 driven farther and farther back in their claims. " To recover 
 our birthrights and privileges as Englishmen," " to purchase 
 our inheritances which have been lost," are alleged by some 
 of Cromwell's soldiers as the reason why they had taken up 
 arms.^ They are not content with Lancastrian precedents : 
 they profess to seek to undo the mischief of "Normanism." 
 The times before the Norman Conquest are imagined as a 
 golden age when Englishmen had their rights. According to 
 
 ' In his Pafriarcha, published 1G80 (Filmer died 1653). It is against 
 this book that Locke wrote his first Treatise of Civil Government. 
 
 * See The Clarke Papers [debates in the Parliamentary army, 1647], 
 edited by C. H. Firth, Vol. I. pp. 235, 322.
 
 CH. i] THE PRINCIPLES OE 'Z() 9 
 
 some of the "Levellers," the law and the constitution alike 
 were part of the Norman yoke.^ " The greatest mischief of 
 all, and the oppressing bondage of England ever since the 
 Norman yoke," says Lilburn, " is a law called the common 
 law. . . . The laws of this nation are unworthy a free 
 people, and deserve from first to last to be considered and 
 seriously debated, and reduced to an agreement with com- 
 mon equity and right reason, which ought to be the form 
 and life of every government. Magna Charta itself, being 
 but a beggarly thing, containing many marks of intolerable 
 bondage, and the laws that have been made since by Parlia- 
 ments have in very many particulars made our government 
 much more oppressive and intolerable."^ 
 
 Thomas Edwards, the "shallow Edwards" of Milton's 
 sonnet, a Presbyterian and constitutionalist, complains of the 
 "sectaries" in his Gangrcena: — "As they do in matters of 
 religion and conscience fly from the Scriptures, and from 
 supernatural truths revealed there, that a man may not be 
 questioned for going against them, but only for errors against 
 the light of nature and right reason ; so they do also in civil 
 government and things of this world, they go from the laws 
 and constitution of kingdoms, and will be governed by rules 
 according to nature and right reason ; and though the laws 
 and customs of a kingdom be never so plain and clear against 
 their ways, yet they will not submit, but cry out for natural 
 rights derived from Adam and right reason," ^ 
 
 Elsewhere the same writer e'xplains what these sectaries 
 meant by natural rights. " All men [according to them] are by 
 nature the sons of Adam, and from him have legitimately 
 derived a natural propriety [i.e. property], right and freedom. 
 . . . By natural birth all men are equally and alike born 
 to like propriety, liberty, and freedom ; and as we are delivered 
 of God by the hand of nature into this world, every one Avith 
 a natural innate freedom and propriety, even so we are to live, 
 ever}^ one equally and alike, to enjoy his birthright and 
 privilege."* 
 
 ^ The Clarke Papers, Pref., p. Ixi. 
 
 ^ Quoted from Lilburn's Jusf. i} fan's Justification, pp. 11-15, bj- Mr. C. 
 H. Firth, in his Pref. to the Clarke Papers, I. p. Ixi. 
 
 3 GaiKjrcena, pt. iii. p. 20, quoted likewise by Mr. Firth, p. Ix. (1 have 
 modernised the spelling.) 
 
 * lb., pt. iii. p. 16, quoted by Mr. Firth, p. Ixii.
 
 lo THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 [ch. i 
 
 Thus already in the Puritan revolution of the seventeenth 
 century the appeal to historic right was replaced by an appeal 
 to natural rights. The struggle for parliamentary liberties led 
 some men to go behind parliaments and charters, just as the 
 independent study of the Bible led some men to go behind the 
 authority of Bible and to rely on the authority of " the inner 
 light " alone. This is the logical outcome of Protestantism, 
 however unacceptable to the majority of those calling them- 
 selves Protestants, however unsatisfactory and dangerous in 
 the eyes of those who were more influenced by the historic 
 spirit and who realised in more or less intelligent fashion the 
 necessity of social cohesion and continuity. When compared 
 with the " Levellers" — those Puritan precursors of Robespierre 
 and St. Just — Cromwell and Ireton show their intellectual 
 affinity with Burke, or even with Dr. Johnson. " We are very 
 apt, all of us, to call that faith which perhaps may be but 
 carnal imagination." ^ In these words Cromwell pours cold 
 water on the fire of the mystical enthusiasts, who abounded in 
 the parliamentary army. Cromwell objects to the " Agreement 
 of the People " that it contained too great alterations in the 
 government of the country,^ Ireton abhors arguments about 
 abstract justice, and scents danger in the appeal to natural 
 rights. " When I do hear men speak of laying aside all en- 
 gagements to consider only that wild or vast notion of what 
 in every man's conception is just or unjust, I am afraid and 
 do tremble at the boundless and endless consequences of it. . . . 
 If 3^ou do paramount to all constitutions hold up this law 
 of nature, I would fain have any man shew me where you will 
 end." » 
 
 Puritan England had produced the theory of natural rights ; 
 but the conditions were not yet favourable for its abundant 
 growth. The American colonists a century later appealed at 
 first to the customary and traditional rights of all British sub- 
 jects. The Convention at New York, in October, 1765, while 
 protesting loyalty to His Majesty King George, declared 
 " That it is inseparably essential to the freedom of a people, 
 and the undoubted right of Englishmen, that no taxes be 
 imposed on them but with their own consent, given person- 
 
 > Clarice Papers, I. p. 238. 
 
 -' Ibid., p. 23G. 
 
 2 Ibid., i^^. Ixix., 2G4, 307.
 
 CH. I] THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 11 
 
 ally or by their representatives. . . . That trial by jury 
 is the inherent and invaluable right of every British subject 
 in these colonies," and so on, entirely in the spirit of the 
 English Bill of Rights of 1G89. But in the Declaration of 
 Rights of the Philadelphia Congress of 1774 appeal is made 
 not only to " the principles of the English constitntion 
 and the several charters or compacts," but to " the immu- 
 table laws of nature " ; and first among the rights claimed 
 comes the right '' to life, liberty, and property." ^ In the 
 Declaration of Independence of July 4th, 1776, no more is 
 said about the rights of British subjects. The thirteen united 
 States of America base their claim to independence on " cer- 
 tain unalienable rig^hts," which come to man direct from his 
 Creator. The French Declarations of 1791 and 1793 are pro- 
 claimed " in the presence of the Supreme Being," but the 
 " imprescriptible rights " are said to come to man simply by 
 nature or by birth. Thus the theory of natural rights appears 
 full grown, detached from history, and freed from the Biblical 
 or theological wrappings which at first in part concealed its 
 metaphysical nakedness. 
 
 The tendency is, however, always strong to translate logical 
 or metaphysical theories into the easier language of imagined 
 history. The ordinary mind thinks in pictures : and even 
 those who are counted among philosophers fall a prey to the 
 habit. Thus, while Hobbes does not seem to ascribe any his- 
 torical character to the social contract, which is at the basis 
 of all political society, and while Rousseau expressly disclaims 
 the attempt to offer an historical explanation " of how govern- 
 ments came into existence, Locke seeks to give historical 
 proofs of the origin of political society by means of contract, 
 referring to the cases of Rome and A^enice,'^ and speaks of 
 the state of nature as a golden age in the past. 
 
 ^ These declarations will be found in Documents Illustrative of Ameri- 
 can History icith Introductions and References, edited by Howard W. 
 Preston. 2nd edit. New York, 1891. 
 
 '' Cf. Contrat Social, I. c. i. : " L'homme est ne libra, et partout il est 
 dans les fers. . . Comment ce changement s'est-il fait ? Je I'ignore. 
 Qu'est-ce qui pent la rendre legitime? Je cx-ois pouvoir resoudre cette 
 question." It is thus no refutation of Rousseau to say tliat Joan 
 Jacques has not fixed the date of the social contract. 
 
 ^ Treatise of Civil Government, II. % 102. In anearlyessaj', "Reflections 
 upon the Roman Commonwealth," written probably about IGGO, parts of
 
 12 THE PRIXCIPLES OF '89 [ci-r. i 
 
 Similarly we find that Thomas Paine, in the passionate 
 rhetoric of his re23ly to Burke, defends the doctrine of the 
 rights of man, not as one might expect, by turning away from 
 the dust of parchments to the eternal laws of nature, but by 
 appealing from antiquity to an antiquity still more venerable. 
 " The error of those who reason by precedents drawn from 
 antiquit}^, respecting the rights of man, is that they do not 
 go far enough into antiquity. . . . Portions of antiquity, 
 by proving everything, establish nothing. It is authority 
 against authority all the way, till we come to the divine 
 origin of the rights of man at the creation. Here our enquiries 
 find a resting place and our reason finds a home." ^ 
 
 As a rhetorical argument, this of course is quite justifiable.^ 
 When charters, precedents, and title-deeds are quoted to stop 
 the mouth of the reformer, it is quite legitimate in the court 
 of public opinion, though not in the law-courts, to appeal to 
 the title-deeds of the human race ; and against opponents who 
 have tried to silence one by the authority of Scripture to 
 appeal to our common descent from Adam. At all times it 
 has been customary'' to represent reform as the return to 
 some earlier and better condition of affairs. The very word 
 " reform " suggests this. The " Levellers," and the champions 
 of the natural rights of man, might very well think of them- 
 selves as only extending farther the principle of appealing 
 to the past, which more moderate or more timid reformers, 
 ecclesiastical and political, expressly adopted. It was espe- 
 cially easy to do this in an age when, even among professed 
 historians, the sense of historical perspective was very weak, 
 when the theory of evolution had not yet been proclaimed 
 from the house-tops, when people were still influenced in 
 their practical thinking by the classical dream of a golden 
 
 which are printed in Mr. Fox Bourne's Life, I. pp. 148 seq., Locke speaks 
 of the " colony" which founded Rome as being "in the original state of 
 nature, free, and independent of any dominion whatsoever," and at liberty 
 to choose their own form of government. 
 
 ^ RhjhtH of Man, p. 18. (Freethought Publishing Company's edition. 
 London, 1883.) 
 
 ^ It sliould be noted, moreover, that Paine expressly avoids the appear- 
 ance of appealing merely to the origin of mankind. " Every child," he 
 saj-s, " born into the world must be considei-ed as deriving its existence 
 from God. The world is as new to him as it was to the first man that 
 existed, and his natural right in it is of the same kind." Generation is 
 regarded as the mode by which creation is continually repeated.
 
 CH. i] THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 13 
 
 age, and by the Hebrew legend of Paradise ; and when it 
 was possible, before the birth of anthropological science, 
 and at a safe distance from savage races, to idealise the 
 noble inhabitant of the woods. Even now, as I shall have 
 occasion to point out later on — even now, with the phraseology 
 of evolution in everybody's mouth, it is remarkable how per- 
 sistent is the belief in those ever-receding " good old days " ; 
 and stray attempts are sometimes made, where we should least 
 expect them, to rehabilitate the Golden Age. 
 
 The real significance of the theory of natural rights is, how- 
 ever, entirely independent of any historical, or quasi-historical, 
 setting that may be given to it. The real significance of the 
 theory is not to be determined by reference to remote ages, or 
 to rude peoples ; as with all political theories, and as with all 
 philosophical theories which are a genuine expression of the 
 thought and feeling of the period in which they prevail, its 
 meaning is only understood aright if we consider it in relation 
 to the circumstances of the very time in which it was main- 
 tained. The real significance of the appeal to nature is, in the 
 first place, the negative element in the appeal ; it is an appeal 
 against authorities that had lost their sacredness, against insti- 
 tutions that had outlived their usefulness ; against artificiality 
 in art, in literature, in manners, in dress — against wigs and 
 hair-powder. 
 
 Secondly, as we have already seen, the theory of natural 
 rights is Protestantism transferred to the region of worldly 
 affairs, and stripped of the traditionalism against which at 
 first it did not " protest " — the paramount authority of a book, 
 accepted on the guarantee of the "Church" whose authority 
 was rejected, and interpreted on certain traditional assump- 
 tions. Mediaeval doctors accepted the authority of the Church, 
 of the Bible, and of the Law of Nature interpreted by reason, 
 but under a general guidance from the other two authorities. 
 The earlier Protestants, protesting against the corruptions in 
 the Church, were not careful to lay down the precise relation- 
 ship between the other two authorities. When Protestantism 
 had in its turn crystallised into a traditional system, the intel- 
 lectual descendants of the first Protestants appeared as the 
 Deists and Rationalists of the eighteenth century. Calvin's 
 G-eneva in due time brought forth Rousseau ; and English 
 Puritanism on American soil produced the Declaration of
 
 14 THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 [ch. i 
 
 Independence.^ All other authorities are thrown aside or are 
 ranked as subordinate. Nature interpreted by Reason, and 
 by Reason not embodied in any society, but existing in the 
 individual mind, becomes the ultimate court of appeal. That 
 is to say, the assertion of natural rights implies not merely a 
 protest against the authority of customs and institutions, but 
 an appeal from this authority to the judgment of every indi- 
 vidual simply as such. The individualism of the theory may 
 indeed not seem as conspicuous as its negative character, be- 
 cause in appealing to Reason people have generally assumed 
 that Reason will give the same judgments in different minds. 
 The appeal to common sense (alike in the colloquial and in 
 the more philosophical use of that term) involves an assump- 
 tion of an objective or universal aspect of human reason, an 
 assumption which has restrained the theory of natural rights 
 within what have seemed "reasonable" limits, but only at 
 the cost of inconsistency with the assumed antagonism be- 
 tween reason and convention. But to this logical defect in 
 the theory I shall have to return later on. The ambiguities 
 in its application can be shown at once by an illustration. 
 " Negativity " and "individualism" both un^ly ahstractness^ 
 i.e. want of close relationship or organic connection with the 
 concrete facts of social life and history. And all abstract 
 theories about human society admit of divergent and conflict- 
 ing application. Thus the theory of social contract is used 
 by Hobbes to condemn rebellion, and by Locke to justify it. 
 The conception of social organism is used by Plato to justify 
 the extremest interference with individual liberty, and b}' Mr. 
 Herbert Spencer to condemn a very moderate amount of State 
 control. And so the theory of natural rights is used b}^ Anar- 
 chists to condemn the existing inequalities of social conditions, 
 and by Conservatives to check attempts on the part of govern- 
 
 " Jolm "Wyse published in 1717, "A Vindication of the Government of 
 New Enixland Churchog, Drawn from Antiquity, the Light of Nature, 
 Holy Scripture, its Noble Nature, and from the Dignity Divine Provi- 
 dence has put upon it," 1717. It was twice reprinted in 1772. Some sen- 
 tences quoted from this book by Mr. Charles Borgeaud in his Etdblissement 
 et lievision des Constitutions en Ameriqne et en Europe, p. 17, express 
 the social contract theory in the form in which it is held bj' Locke and 
 by Rousseau. (There is no copy of the book in the Bodleian Library.) 
 Wyse may be regarded as helping the transition from the seventeenth- 
 century Puritan to the eighteenth-century revolutionist.
 
 CH. i] THE PRINCIPLES OF '^ 15 
 
 ments to remedy these inequalities. The first of these modes 
 of application may seem indeed the more logical outcome of a 
 theory whose essence lies in protest and negation ; but the 
 second is, at the present daj^, quite as common. Protestant- 
 isms crystallise into dogmatisms ; and the theory of the revolu- 
 tionist becomes the watchword of the Conservative and of the 
 reactionary. The English revolution of 1688 and the Ameri- 
 can revolution of 1776 were carried out in defence of the 
 rights of "liberty and property."^ The "Liberty and Pro- 
 perty Defence League " of our own days regards itself as 
 a bulwark against revolutionary legislation. Mr. Herbert 
 Spencer, in sad isolation, defends " natural rights " against the 
 logical consequences of the evolutionist philosophy with 
 which he has familiarised his contemporaries.^ It is difficult 
 to know whether Mr. Auberon Herbert is to be classed among 
 the Anarchists or among the reactionaries. Perhaps his case 
 proves that there is more affinity between these apparent 
 extremes than appears at first sight. People are in the habit 
 of building the sepulchres of the prophets their fathers stoned, 
 and although, so far as I know, Tom Paine has not yet been 
 made a saint by the Knights and Dames of the Primrose 
 League, the spirit of the " rebellious stay-maker," if it ever 
 frequents the meetings of that highly respectable organisa- 
 tion, may have felt a grim delight in hearing the " Rights of 
 man " preached by a Tory Lord Chancellor. At a Primrose 
 League meeting in the town of Dingwall, August, 1891 (I 
 quote from a newspaper report ),^ Lord Halsbury, in opposition 
 to the subversive proposals of Radicals, declared that " one of 
 the things which the British people most cherished was their 
 own freedom of action, the right to do as they willed with 
 their own, whether it was their labour, their property, or their 
 skill." These are just the rights which figure in the Ameri- 
 can and the French Declarations. Paine or Robespierre would 
 
 ' Janet, in his Hist, de la Science Politique (ed. 3), 11. p. 202, quotes 
 Voltaire as saying : '■^Liberty and pi'opriety voila la devise des Anglais ; 
 elle vaut bien: Mont.joye et Saint Denis." In saying "propriety," it 
 should perhaps be noted, Voltaire has not the British matron in his 
 minds eye. 
 
 ■•* See The Man versus the State, pp. 87, seq. The conception of society 
 as essentially organic or super-organic, if it bo once really accepted, is 
 incompatible with the individualism of the " natural rights " theory\ 
 
 3 Bradford Observer, Aug. I'Jth, 1891.
 
 1 6 THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 [ch. 1 
 
 doubtless have asked for some definition of the right of 
 property ; but as to the right of labour it was only the droit du 
 tracail and not yet the droit an traoail (" the right to do work" 
 — not " the right to get work ") which formed one of the 
 principles of 1789. 
 
 The change which has taken place in English political 
 thought with regard to the American constitution is another 
 illustration of the way in which the Conservatives of one 
 generation may take up the ideas of a past generation of 
 Radicals. The supremacy of parliament and its competency 
 to reform itself were attacked by Paine as aristocratic and 
 despotic elements in the British Constitution. Now the 
 demand for a rigid Constitution on the American plan, ex- 
 empting certain rights from the control of the legislature, 
 comes not from the Radical but from the Conservative side. 
 " Americanise our institutions," is a cry which has passed from 
 the mouth of Paine to the mouth of Maine.^ 
 
 It argues an imperfect knowledge of the history of human 
 thought if we are astonished at this apparent shifting of sides 
 in the controversy. The very fact that some formula served 
 to express the special needs of a particular age might lead us 
 to expect that it would not adequately express the special 
 needs of a later age, in which the course of events had 
 brought new problems to the surface. And thus the very 
 watchwords of the reformer of one generation may be re- 
 peated most fervently by the opponents of reform in another. 
 This need not make us sceptical about the possibility of man- 
 kind knowing anything that is true, or holding any belief 
 tliat is worth holding ; the very reverse, if we read the facts 
 rightly. If we would avoid such scepticism about humanity 
 as would paralyse all serious effort, and make us hesitate to 
 call anything right or wrong, we must admit the fundamental 
 rationality of all institutions or practical beliefs that have 
 been able to hold their ground for some considerable time, and 
 to afford shelter and supply cohesion to considerable numbers 
 of human beings. They must in some way have been advan- 
 tageous to the society in which they prevailed, else — on the 
 principle of natural selection — they could not have prevailed ; 
 they would have been crushed out along with a society 
 which fed on poisonous stuff. The evolution theory compels 
 ' See liis Popular Government, Essay IV. (orig. publ. in Quarterly lievlett).
 
 CH. i] THE PRINCirLES OF '89 17 
 
 those who accept it to regard social cohesion and durability 
 as the proof of some degree at least of ethical value and truth. 
 It is a shallow wisdom which can see nothing but falsehood 
 and nothing but evil in widely diffused creeds and long en- 
 during institutions ; and the dogmatic despiser of the past does 
 not observe that, while he is challenging the bitter antagonism 
 of those who, by blind sentiment or reasonable conviction, cling 
 to whatever they find of seeming stability around them, he is 
 losing the argumentative advantage which comes from an 
 appeal to the spirit of the initiators of bygone days against 
 the mere repetition of the letter of their teaching by those who 
 profess to be their followers. Paine makes a most effective 
 point against Burke, when he shows the inconsistency of 
 accepting the results of the revolution of 1688 as necessarily 
 and for ever prohibiting any further change in the constitution. 
 The example of the. men of 1688 is more significant than their 
 illogical and impossible attempt to bind all future generations. 
 Let us admit that in practical affairs, in the complex material 
 of human society, we never get complete truth or perfect 
 institutions. Progress is only from one partial and one-sided 
 expression of the whole truth which hovers before us as an 
 ideal to another expression of it which may be equally, and 
 sometimes even more, partial and one-sided, and which at the 
 best is only less inadequate than that which it replaces. In 
 this long controversy, this dialectic of the human spirit, the 
 earlier and cruder stages are certainly more apt to take thp 
 form of mere antagonism and mutual negation ; in the higher 
 stages only does the new conception appear as simply the fuller 
 development of that which it replaces. In political contro- 
 versy, however, this " higher stage " is, as yet, more an ideal 
 possibility than a fact. 
 
 But, while admitting that durable institutions and widely 
 diffused practical beliefs must have had in them some element 
 of truth and value for the very reason that they flourished, we 
 are the more justified in considering wliether they still retain 
 a greater element of truth and value for our age than others 
 which have risen to compete with them. Institutions and 
 beliefs are apt to outlive their utility, and to prove in the long 
 run destructive to the well-being, if not to the very existence, 
 of the society which clings to them amid changed surroundings. 
 The reformer who proposes a change is not contradicting the 
 
 N.R. c
 
 1 8 THE PRINCIPLES OF '89 [ch. i 
 
 teachings of evolutionary science : he is obeying them, by 
 seeking to save his society from suffering unnecessarily through 
 the operation of natural selection. 
 
 Looking back calml}' at the histor}' of Europe from mediseval 
 times clown to the French Revolution, we can see certain 
 obvious merits in the structure of mediaeval society which it 
 was impossible for the representative spirits of the Reformation 
 period or of eighteenth-century Rationalism to appreciate 
 aright. We can see that the principle of Authority, the 
 principle that the life and thought of the individual man are 
 dependent on something greater and wider and more enduring 
 than himself, — we can see that this principle was true, although 
 mediaeval institutions realised it only in an external fashion, 
 in the Church as a visible, outward organisation, and in the 
 fixed castes of civil society. The revolt of the individual 
 against this external organisation was inevitable and necessary, 
 if mankind was to advance to new conquests over nature and 
 over itself; andj-et this revolt, when carried out logically, took 
 the form of making one man's private judgment (however 
 foolish and however prejudiced, i.e. however little it might in 
 reality be either "judgment" or " private ") count for as much 
 as another's, and of substituting the mere temporary " cash- 
 nexus " between individual and individual for the older bond 
 of permanent mutual obligation. And so this principle of 
 individualism tends in its turn, because only a partial truth 
 (true as against what the old society had come to be), to prove 
 itself false and mischievous. Those, therefore, who repeat the 
 formulas of the individualist negation and revolt, where and so 
 far as the circumstances which gave them a meaning have 
 passed away, are repeating what once was truth, but has now 
 become false, because meaningless. 
 
 An illustration from a different but kindred case may make 
 my argument clearer. People have sometimes wondered how 
 the Calvinistic doctrine of Election, which, looked at logically, 
 seemH much the same as Fatalism,^ could have been held bj' 
 men of the most vigorous character, and should have been the 
 
 ' The notion of Predestination only seems identical with Fatalism, 
 because people are apt to think " abstractly," i.e. to take some one part 
 of the whole process and isolate it from the series to which it belongs. 
 The eternal decrees of God ai-e pictured as if they were arbitrary intru- 
 sions into a process of cause and effect, which, apart from such intrusions, 
 goes on of itself.
 
 CH. I] THE PRINCIPLES OF 'Z<) 19 
 
 religious stimulus and education of the very nations which 
 struggled most stubbornly and most successfully for civil 
 liberty. Consider to what the doctrine was opposed, and the 
 mystery is explained ; the salvation of the individual depends 
 solely on the eternal and unalterable decree of God — that is 
 to say, it depends not at all on the will or act of any ecclesias- 
 tical authority, of any human authority whatever. The 
 doctrine of Election robs the priest of his power ; it is the 
 appeal from man to Grod. And thus, in its negative aspect, it 
 was a liberating creed, training up stern, independent men 
 who feared God and feared none beside. The creed becomes 
 something very different when it stiffens into a traditional 
 dogma, isolated from any relation to the opinions to which it 
 was opposed, and pictured with all the crude materialism of 
 popular thought. It tends to become a dreary, other-worldly 
 individualism. Having helped men to shake off tyrants, it 
 turns a too abstract conception of God into a frightful picture 
 of a tyrant worse than any of them. It is the same with this 
 theory of natural rights. At first it represents the revolt 
 against external authority, against the traditional mainten- 
 ance of the status quo. When in its turn it is handed down as 
 a traditional dogma out of relation to the particular circum- 
 stances which gave it its value, it comes to be used as a 
 support of what is now the established economic and social 
 order, save where some of its phraseology passes into the 
 mouths of fanatical Anarchists, who carry out the principles 
 of individualism to their logical conclusion — the destruction 
 of all orderly society whatever. 
 
 It is my purpose in the following chapters to examine the 
 conception of natural rights, the history of which has been 
 here briefly sketched. I shall first take the idea of '■'■Nature,'''' 
 considering it from the point of view both of history and of 
 philosophical analj^sis. I shall then consider the conception of 
 ^'■rights'''' generally, and shall afterwards take the most con- 
 spicuous of the alleged "natural rights" in detail. I trust 
 that I shall be found, consistently with what has just been 
 said, while exposing ambiguities and criticising what seem to 
 me false applications of the conception, to do full justice to its 
 relative truth and its historic value.
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 ox THE HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF '' NATURE " IN LAW AND 
 POLITICS ^ 
 
 The words " nature " and " natural " are constantly bandied 
 about in controversy as if they settled quarrels, whereas they 
 only provoke them by their ambiguity. Slavery has been 
 condemned as an " unnatural " institution ; and has been 
 defended on the ground of the "natural " inferiority of some 
 races to others. The equality of the sexes is asserted and 
 denied on the ground of " nature." The " natural " goodness 
 and the "natural" badness of mankind have been maintained 
 with like earnestness and sincerity. " To live according to 
 Nature " was the Stoic formula for the good life ; those Chris- 
 tian theologians, who have in some ways most intellectual 
 and moral affinity with the Stoics, have been those who have 
 spoken most strongly about the corruption of " the natural 
 man." "Natural religion" means something very different 
 from " Nature-worship." " A natural child " means a child 
 born out of wedlock ; but " an unnatural child " is not 
 necessarily legitimate, " A state of nature " may mean the 
 absence of clothing; but such absence is not considered 
 essential to the possession of " a natural manner " in society. 
 To the sentiment that " Nature is a holy thing " may always 
 be opposed the proposition that " Nature is a rum 'un," and, 
 in view of the ambiguity of the term, the theory of Mr. 
 Squeers is perhaps the more easily defensible of the two. 
 
 In no case can we understand what is meant by " Nature " 
 or " natural " unless we know to what the speaker is opposing 
 the term. As has already been pointed out. the special 
 characteristic of the appeal to Nature is negation, antagonism ; 
 it is an appeal from what exists or from what is proposed, 
 
 » It is a pity that the English language does not allow one any short 
 equivalent for the convenient German phrase " Zur Geschichte, etc." 
 *' Contributions to," is cumbrous. 
 
 20
 
 CH. ii] IN LAW AND POLITICS 21 
 
 and has therefore at all times been a convenient form of 
 criticism, rather than a good basis for construction. 
 
 We have seen that, though not originating in the eighteenth 
 century, it is specially characteristic of that period — a period 
 of criticism and individualism, a period of awakening and 
 enlightenment. If we go back to an older period, which in 
 many ways presents similar characteristics, we shall find this 
 use of " nature " as the antithesis to convention and definite 
 institutions anticipated in the ancient world. The age of the 
 Sophists is the ancient equivalent of the age of the Ency- 
 clopaedists ; in the phraseology of German historians of philo- 
 sophy, it is the Greek " Illumination " {Aufklcinmg). Both 
 periods represent a rationalistic revolt against traditional 
 beliefs ; both prepare the way for a profounder philosophical 
 study, especially of social institutions, than would have been 
 possible without the intellectual revolution produced by the 
 exercise of critical and sceptical reflection. In speaking of the 
 Sophists, we must of course clear our minds completely of the 
 misleading associations which have accumulated round that 
 word. "We must remember that our ideas of them are derived 
 mostly from the caricatures of Aristophanes and from the 
 adverse criticisms of Plato. What fair-minded historian, with 
 a sense of humour, would be content to take history from the 
 cartoons of a partisan comic paper, or to accept as true what- 
 ever an orthodox writer has said about the opinions of a 
 heretic ? Besides, even Aristophanes and Plato may be sum- 
 moned as witnesses against German or English writers who 
 have libelled the Sophists as the corrupters of Hellas. Aristo- 
 phanes hated the Sophists as an old Tory (or an old Whig — 
 for that matter) hated the French Revolution and Tom Paine : 
 but Aristophanes selects Socrates as the typical example of 
 the class. Plato is respectful to Protagoras and Gorgias ; and 
 Plato has expressly answered the charge of corruption, " It is 
 not the individual Sophists, but that great Sophist, the public, 
 that has a bad effect on our young men." ^ 
 
 Grote has conclusively proved — strange, that proof should 
 have been needed — that " Sophist " is not the name of a sect, 
 but the name of a profession, a profession called into existence 
 by the demand for " higher education."' There was a mental 
 exhilaration produced in the Hellenic world, and especiallj' in 
 ' Plato, Bepublic, VI. 492.
 
 2 2 JII STORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ir 
 
 Athens, by the defeat of the Persian invasions ' — the most 
 striking, and in its consequences the most significant of the 
 many examples in history of the intellectual stimulus which 
 follows the shock of a successful war of liberation. This 
 mental exhilaration and the growth of democracy, itself in 
 part due to the same cause, created a demand among the 
 ambitious youth for something more than the old education of 
 reading, writing, music, and reciting passages from the great 
 poets, who took the place of a " Bible " to the Greeks — an 
 education like that given in Mohammedan countries at the 
 present day, or, in its essential elements and defects, like that 
 which till lately was among ourselves the usual education of 
 young women of the middle and upper classes — an education 
 which gave no scope whatever to the reasoning and critical 
 faculties, but which produced, and was defended as producing, 
 a contented acquiescence in traditional beliefs. The young 
 Athenian of the new generation that grew up after Salamis 
 wished for something more ; and the class of Sophists — pro- 
 fessed " wise men ^' — arose to supply the demand. They were, 
 in fact, an itinerant University — University Extension lec- 
 turers, before the days of settled and endowed institutions for 
 the promotion of learning and the higher education. They 
 came from various parts of the Hellenic world, they had them- 
 selves been trained in various schools of the older philosophers, 
 who had speculated about nature, but had, on the whole, left 
 ethics and politics alone. They taught with a directly 
 practical object, to fit men for a successful career in public 
 life ; they taught their pupils }iow to speak, and were the first 
 of a long line of teachers of rhetoric (" the art of persuasion") ; 
 they taught, or professed to teach, also what to speak about — 
 the subject-matter of ethics and politics, "What is justice? 
 What are laws ? What is the State ? The man who speaks 
 in the law-courts or political assemblies speaks as if he 
 knew what these terms meant. The Sophists made him think 
 whether the terms as ordinarily used had any definite mean- 
 ing at all. 
 
 • Cf. Arist. PoZ. YIII. 6, § 11 : "When their wealth gave them greater 
 leisure, and they had loftier notions of excellence, being also elated 
 (<j)povr]fxaTi(r6evTfi) with their success both before and after the Persian 
 war, with more zeal than discernment they pursued every kind of 
 knowledge." Cf. also II. 12, § 5.
 
 CH. ii] IN LA IV AND POLITICS 23 
 
 Such questions may well have seemed scandalous to old- 
 fashioned people who had never reflected about the basis of 
 social life and conduct; and doubtless, then as now, such 
 questions were often rudely asked and crudely answered. The 
 clever lad has always felt a certain pleasure in shocking his 
 elderly relatives. The shock, as a rule, does no good to the 
 elderly relatives ; and when the youth is a little more mature 
 in mind, he may think with hardly less audacity, but with 
 a juster sense of the proportion of things. These popular 
 teachers of public speaking, of the art of reasoning, of mis- 
 cellaneous useful knowledge, of literary criticism, of the way 
 to succeed in private or political life, were the beginners of all 
 humanist studies — I mean, of all studies which concern not 
 the nature of the material universe, and the problems it sug- 
 gests, but the work of the spirit of man himself in his efforts 
 to know himself, his relations to nature and to the social world 
 into which he is born. Religion, art, laws, institutions, were 
 now claimed as proper subjects for thought and science. The 
 first effort to think out anything implies a certain antagonism 
 to the subject thought about. We must get out from among 
 the trees to look at the wood, we must stand at some distance 
 from a building to get a full view of it. And so the first 
 attempts at a philosophical understanding of religion, of 
 morality, of art, seem to take the form of revolts against 
 religion, morality, and art ; and very often they are in reality 
 revolts. It was inevitable, therefore, that the Sophists should 
 give offence to those who remained too completely under the 
 shelter of old institutions to allow that their value might be 
 questioned and disputed. It was inevitable also that this first 
 attempt at reflection on what had previously been accepted 
 on authority should seem crude and one-sided to those who, 
 having been themselves trained in the new learning, were 
 able in their turn to see the defects of it. Grote is right in 
 denying that there is any common " Sophistic '' doctrine ; but 
 he fails to recognise that the Sophists represent a common 
 tendency — a tendency not, of course, limited to these pro- 
 fessional teachers for pay. Xenophanes in his attacks on the 
 anthropomorphic polytheism of the traditional Greek religion, 
 and Plato in his attacks on both religion and art, are in the 
 same stage of thought as the Sophists, who seemed to be 
 attacking the foundations of society by their revolutionary
 
 24 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 theories — theories not more revolutionary, however, in some 
 respects than those of Plato himself. Aristotle, coming after 
 all this ferment of speculation, is able to think more calmly 
 and more objectivel}^ to avoid a quarrel with the popular 
 religion, while putting his own metaphysical interpretation 
 on religious phraseolog}', to construct a philosophical defence 
 of poetry, to see the rationality, not merely of an ideal state, 
 but of ordinary Hellenic society, and to appreciate the ethical 
 significance of institutions, such as the family and private 
 property, which Plato had attacked. 
 
 Now one main characteristic of the " Sophistic " waj"- of 
 thinking — and it is a characteristic that always repeats itself 
 in similar stages of thought, whether in the develoj)ment of 
 the individual mind or in the development of the general 
 intelligence of the community — is the habit of falling into 
 Antithesis. To split the confused intricate mass of the 
 universe, or whatever part of it one is studying, into two 
 sharply divided sections, by the use of an " either . , . or," 
 seems always an immense gain in the early stages of re- 
 flection. Only get hold of some fundamental conception, and 
 with the help of a sufficiently crude and narrow logic, you can 
 easily construct a philosophy of everything. Divide all human 
 instincts into egoistic and altruistic, distinguish all human 
 co-operation as voluntarj^ and compulsory, recognise two types 
 of society, the militant and the industrial, above all dis- 
 tinguish the natural from the artificial, and you are able to 
 make the most striking generalisations, and to reduce all the 
 complex " facts " into neat bundles — except that the facts, even 
 when they have been picked out in the light of the theory, 
 are apt to prove a little awkward now and then. You never 
 need to move out of the easy category of quantity. " More " 
 or "less" will represent the finest shades of distinction you need 
 to recognise. If government is gaining in power, the indi- 
 vidual must be losing in liberty ; if more laws are passed by 
 parliament, we are reverting to the militant stage ; and so on, 
 and so on. In alluding to Mr. Spencer's political writings as 
 examples of " Sophistic,'" I am, of course, not using the word 
 in any except a technical sense ; and I ought to add that Mr, 
 Spencer himself, by preaching and advertising " Evolution," 
 has done more than any other English philosopher to get 
 people beyond the Sophistic stage of thought. Hobbes, Locke?
 
 CH. ii] /A ZAJJ' AND POLITICS 25 
 
 and Rousseau are modern representatives of the Sophistic- 
 stage, and the greatness of these names maj' help to make us 
 appreciate the intellectual debt that we owe to the much- 
 abused Sophists of Greece. Glaucon, in the second book of 
 Plato's EepuhJic, propounds a theory of social contract which 
 is clearly due to some Sophist's speculation ; and this theorj- 
 is identical with that of Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau.^ " Jus- 
 tice," he says, " is a contract neither to do nor to suifer 
 wrong." Thrasymachus, the rhetorical Sophist, in the first 
 book of the Republic^ propounds a theory of justice, which is a 
 crude version of Hobbes' doctrine of law and sovereignty — the 
 theory which Hobbes handed on to Bentham and Austin, and 
 which is still prevalent among English jurists. " Right is that 
 which the government, being the stronger part of the political 
 society, commands." Lj'cophron the Sophist is quoted bj" 
 Aristotle- as maintaining that law depends upon a contract, 
 and that the end of law is the security of individual rights, 
 and that the State has no moral function — the \evy theory, 
 familiar to us in many modern writers, which Professor 
 Huxley has named "Administrative Nihilism." This same 
 Lycophron is said to have held that the difference between 
 noble and base-born was a difference in men's opinions merelj' 
 and not in reality.^ There can be little doubt that the attack 
 on the rightness of slavery, with which Aristotle deals in his 
 Politics,'^ was made by some Sophist, A certain rhetorician, 
 Alcidamas, is reported to have said, " God made all men free ; 
 nature made none a slave." ■'' Aristotle's argument is directed 
 alike against those who justified all slavery simply because it 
 was an existing fact, or because it was due to the right of the 
 stronger, and against those who condemned all slaverj- as 
 dependent merely on human institution and not on nature. 
 
 These illustrations may sufEce to show the similarity in 
 manner of thinking between the Greek Sophists — it might be 
 safer to say, between mine Greek Sophists of the fifth century 
 B.C. — and the advocates of liberal ideas in the seventeenth and 
 eighteenth centuries. In the eyes of the modern student the 
 
 ' I only refer to the element which is common to the three. 
 ' Pol, III. 9, § 8. 
 
 ' Quoted by Stobseus, Flor. SG, 24 (Meineke's edit., Vol. III. p. 158), 
 from Aristotle's dialogue, " On Nobility of Birth" (Arist., Frafjm. 82). 
 ' I. c. 4-7. 
 * Scholiast on Arist. Rhef., I., 13.
 
 26 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 attack ou slavery alone should serve to clear up the nature of 
 much of their teaching, which found its way into literature 
 through " Euripides the human," through the poets of the New 
 Comedy, and, in naive combination with pious credulity, in 
 the History of Herodotus. At the same time an attack on the 
 very basis of ancient society helps one to understand the un- 
 popularity of these old-world freethinkers. They seem to have 
 maintained a good many social heresies which have succeeded 
 better in our time than in theirs; but there is no evidence 
 that they based any of their theories or their paradoxes on 
 anything but a somewhat superficial reasoning. " Fire burns 
 both in Hellas and in Persia ; but men's ideas of right and 
 wrong vary from place to place." ^ The enlightened man who 
 has travelled about and shaken off local prejudices soon notes 
 this, and with his good-humoured scepticism cannot under- 
 stand why a Persian king should despise the Egyptian animal- 
 worship. " Custom is lord of all." ^ This disinterested attitude 
 towards human conduct and beliefs is a necessary step towards 
 a true understanding of them. But it is only the first step. 
 When we have once contrasted the uniformity of "natural" 
 processes with the diversity of human observance, we are only 
 then face to face with the problems of ethics and politics. 
 " Every one according to his taste" is a shallow maxim in art- 
 criticism ; but such "impressionism" is still less in place in 
 
 ' Arist., Eth. Nic, V. 7, § 2. 
 
 It does not affect my argument, if it could be proved that Aristotle is 
 here alluding, not to the Sophists, or to any Sophists, but to the Cynics. 
 The contrast between nature and convention is a typical example of that 
 " reflection " which is characteristic of the whole stage of mental develop- 
 ment that produced the Sophists and the one-sided Socratics and the 
 cynical worldly wisdom of a Callicles. Just so in inodern times, one 
 may find the same type of thinking in Locke, in Pope, in Voltaire, in 
 Rousseau, despite their enormous differences from one another. 
 
 The antithesis between nature and convention has been sometimes 
 associated with the Democritean physics, according to which in reality 
 there exist only atoms and the void, everything else — all the world that 
 appears to the senses — being due simply to arrangements among the 
 atoms. Democritus was probably twenty years younger than his fellow- 
 townsman Protagoras, and can hardly therefore have been his teacher 
 (see Zeller, Pre-Socratic Philosophy [tr.], II. pp. 210, 411, 412). But the 
 atomist philosophy probably contributed to the popularity of tlie anti- 
 thesis between convention and nature, appearance and reality. 
 
 - Herodotus, III. 27-38 : the story of how the " mad " Cambyses killed 
 the calf-god. and the reflections of Herodotus thereon.
 
 CH. ii] IN LAW AND POLITICS 27 
 
 regard to matters of right and wrong. If applied in practice 
 it means anarchy, or, quite as often, a cynical acquiescence in 
 successful tyranny or in irrational and indefensible custom. 
 In practice these extremes are always near to one another. 
 The Greek Sophists were not the cause, but were only a 
 symptom of the dissolution of the fabric of Greek society into 
 selfish individualism ; and we know that some of them were 
 expressly accused of being the apologists of tyranny. A 
 general irreverence towards constitutions and towards institu- 
 tions paves the way for some "people's friend" who will make 
 himself tyrant, and, everything else being open to doubt, will 
 fall back on the two undeniable facts of superior force and 
 superior fraud. Rationalism, scepticism, pessimism, blind sub- 
 mission, is a too familiar cycle in the history of political and 
 of religious beliefs. Is there any escape from it ? Only by 
 a rationalism which is true to itself, and which is prepared to 
 find reason not merely in the mind of the individual, but in 
 the concrete works of the human spirit, in the very institu- 
 tions, ethical, political, religious, which rationalism began 
 by classifying as "not natural." They are not "natural" 
 in the sense in which " nature " means the blind forces of 
 nature, working only in one direction ; but they are the out- 
 come of the highest things we know in " nature" as the whole 
 universe, namely, the thought and will of man. The very fact 
 that they are not according to mere nature proves them higher 
 in kind ; the very errors in human beliefs and institutions are 
 evidence of the reason which is struggling for expression in 
 them. We must set rid of the mere antithesis between 
 " nature " and " convention," of the illogical combination of 
 too great trust in the reason that criticises and condemns in- 
 stitutions as bad, with too little faith in the reason that once 
 created these institutions themselves and embodied itself in 
 them, however imperfectly. 
 
 Aristotle's famous sentence, " Man is by nature a political 
 animal," shows the gap between his view of "nature" and 
 that of the Sophists. This sentence is often quoted as if 
 Aristotle only meant that man was a gregarious animal. He 
 meant very much more. At the lowest man is gregarious — 
 that ho has in common with many, other animals. But man 
 does not attain to the possibilities open to him, save as the 
 member of a city-state. The true " nature " of a thing is to
 
 28 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 be found not in its rudest, lowest, or most elementary stage, 
 but in the very highest development of it; and to Aristotle 
 the Grreek city, with its vigorous political life, its opportunities 
 for friendly intercotirse, its art, its philosophy, was the highest 
 social organisation. Thus, if it be asked whether there is 
 anj^thing right by nature, Aristotle's answer is : that is right 
 by nature which is right, not apart from political institutions 
 (for that has no meaning to him), but according to the institu- 
 tions of the best or ideal state. As with Plato, to find what 
 justice really is, we look to an ideal society, which is justice 
 " writ large." 
 
 Aristotle's use of the term " nature " does indeed vary, but 
 the sense of the term which pervades his ethical and political 
 philosophy is that just noticed. Nature means to him also the 
 whole universe, organic and inorganic ; ^ but, by preference, he 
 uses it for the organic, in which " necessity " does not rule, 
 but freedom or rationalit}^ (the potentiality' of opposites), show- 
 ing itself most clearly in man. There is never any real 
 ambiguity in his application of the conception in ethics or 
 politics. There are only two important uses of the term 
 " Nature " in his ethical and political writings : (1) that in 
 which he uses "natural " for "original," e.g. when he speaks 
 of man having certain natural {I.e. innate, inherited) impulses 
 prior to training ; and (2) that in which, he uses " nature " for 
 the ideal. In the former sense he says that the family is " by 
 nature " prior to the state [Etli. Kic, VIII. 12, § 7), in the 
 latter that the state is " by nature " prior to the family and to 
 the individual [Pol..^ I. 2, § 12). As a rule these two senses are 
 sharply and clearly distinguished. But even Aristotle seems 
 to be led away by the fatal and ever- recurring confusion 
 between the two senses, when (in Pol.., I. cc. 8-11) h.e condemns 
 those forms of the art of wealth, which he has proved to be less 
 " natural " only in the sense that thej^ belong to a more com- 
 plicated stage of human society ; though, in judging of his 
 opinions on economic matters, one must remember that he has in 
 his mind an ideal of what the life of the citizen of the good state 
 ought to be — an ideal which excludes the money-making life.^ 
 
 ' For Aristotle's distinction between the Nature which works '' by 
 necessity" (= the inorganic), and the Nature which works towards an 
 end (= the organic), see Mr. Stewart's Notes on Nic. Eth., I. pp. 256-258. 
 
 ^ On the subject of Aristotle's economic ideas I ma}- refer to Mr.
 
 CH. ii] IN LA W AND POLITICS 29 
 
 There are indeed two phrases in Aristotle's writings, in both 
 of which he seems to be referring to older theories ; both of 
 which have, however, led to the belief that Aristotle held a 
 conception of the Law of Nature, substantially identical with 
 that of later times. These two phrases are : (1) the " natural 
 justice " (to ^vaiKov SiKatov) of the fifth book of the Ethics ; 
 and (2) the "universal law" (6 Koivb<; ^6/ao?) of the Rhetoric. 
 (1) In discussing Justice, Aristotle has before him the " Soph- 
 istic " ^ assertion that there is no natural justice, because the 
 natural must be everywhere the same, whereas men's ideas 
 about what is just and right vary in different places.- Accept- 
 ing the fact of the actual diversity of moral ideas, he still 
 contends that there is an element of unity underlying all this 
 diversity. The existence of left-handed persons does not pre- 
 vent our saying that " by nature " the right hand is better 
 than the left ; it is so on the whole, as a rule. Natural justice 
 is an ideal towards which human justice tends. Natural justice 
 may be found " among the gods " ^ — a phrase that must not be 
 taken literally, for in Eth. Nic, X. 8, § 7, Aristotle ridicules the 
 ascription of justice or any moral excellence to the divine 
 -being, which consists in pure intelligence, unmixed with the 
 element of desire from which action springs. " Among the 
 gods " is only a way of saying that perfect justice is for men 
 an ideal only.'^ 
 
 In the Sophistici Elenchi{c. 12, 173, r/. 7) Aristotle refers to the 
 antithesis between nature and convention as simply a sophistic 
 method, employed e.g. by Callicles in Plato's Gorgia.s^ as a way 
 of reducing an opponent to silence.^ The essence of the Soph- 
 istic argument lies in the antithesis being absolute. Aristotle 
 
 Bonar's Philosophy and Political Economy^ Bk. I. cli. ii., and to a short 
 article on " Aristotle " contributed by me to Mr. Inglis Palf>rave's 
 Dictionary of Political Economy. Those who are not interested in 
 Aristotelian questions may be recommended to omit the next 4 pages. 
 The habitual appeal to Aristotle as sanctioning the idea of a Law of 
 Nature is my reason for entering on the discussion here. 
 
 ' See above, p. 2ti, note 1. - Eth. Nic, V. 7, §§ 1, 2. •' Ibid, § 8. 
 
 ^ In Eth. Nic, V. 9, § 12, t6 npioTou BUaiov is equivalent to to (fiva-iKov 
 bUaiov. So in Pol., IV. 8, § *J, 17 dXrjdivrj Kal Tvp<s)TT) (ipiaTOKpiiTui means the 
 ideal state. t6 ^vo-ikoi/ dUaiov would be more correctly translated "Jus 
 naturale." 
 
 ' Callicles's " natural justice," or rather " natural right" {t6 ttjs (/jwrfwy 
 bUaiov) is might, as opposed to the conventions that the weak set up for 
 their protection (Gory., 484).
 
 30 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 does not hold that there is anj' absohite antithesis between 
 nature and convention. This is clear from his discussion of 
 slavery in the first book of the Politics. Nature and conven- 
 tion (positive institutions) do not always coincide — unfortu- 
 nately ; but there is no necessarj^ inconsistency between them. 
 And similarly, in the fifth book of the Ethics, political justice, 
 or, moro correctly, jus civile (to ttoXitikov SiKatov) is said to be 
 in part natural and in part conventional (V. 7, § 1), i.e. in part 
 merely conventional. There are some things which before 
 they are definitely instituted are not obligatory, but become 
 so by being instituted. I think Aristotle's meaning would be 
 correctly expressed in the following illustration : it is a 
 general political dut}'' ever}- where for the citizen to pay legally 
 imposed taxes ; but whether it is his duty to pay sixpence or 
 eightpence in the pound Income-tax depends on the Budget of 
 the year. 
 
 (2) In the Rhetoric Aristotle onl}' treats of ethical questions 
 on the level of ordinar}^ Grreek thought, so that wheu he refers 
 to the universal law, the unwritten law which is admitted 
 by all mankind {Rhet., I. 10, 1368, b. 7), nay even when he 
 identifies this universal law with the law according to nature 
 (13, 1373, b. 6), he must not be understood as necessarily accept- 
 ing the theory in the form in which people in general accepted 
 it. He is referring to a commonplace of orators.^ His attitude 
 towards this commonplace may be learnt from a subsequent 
 passage, where he gives advice about the use that can be made 
 of it. " "When you have no case according to the law of the 
 land, appeal to the law of nature and quote the Antigone of 
 Sophocles.^ Argue that an unjust law is not a law, etc." (15, 
 
 ' Demosthenes (adv. Aristocr., p. 639, 22. Eeiske) speaks of the " uni- 
 versal law of all mankind " as something over and above the " written 
 law." It may be noted that Aristotle, in Rhef., I. 13, 1373, b. 18, quotes 
 Alcidamas, as well as Sophocles and Empedocles, as evidence of the general 
 belief in this universal law of nature. Now what Alcidamas said was, 
 if the Scholiast maj- be believed, that "God made all men free ; Nature 
 has made none a slave" (cf. p. 25 above, note 5) — an opinion which Aris- 
 totle certainly did not hold (see Pol., I. 4-7). Thus his language in this 
 passage of the Rlietorie is no evidence of his own opinion as a philo- 
 sopher, but only of a current opinion among his contemporaries. 
 
 * This stock quotation {Ant., 45G) of writers about the law of nature 
 really means that Antigone is more moved by custom and traditional 
 religious belief about the duty of burying relatives than by fear of a 
 tyrant's prohibition. It is no appeal away from all institutions.
 
 CH. ii] IN LAW AND POLITICS 31 
 
 1375, a. 27 .^e^.)- Athenian courts, it should be noted, had no 
 trained professional judges to check rhetorical vagaries. But 
 if the written law is in your favour, Aristotle is equally ready 
 with suggestions. You must warn the jury against the danger 
 of trying to be wiser than the law : a professional physician 
 may make mistakes, but it does not pay to be cleverer than 
 the doctor : all the best codes forbid the attempt to go be- 
 hind the law, etc. (1375, &. 16 i<eq.). In the Ethics and Politics 
 Aristotle never makes anj^ reference to this " universal law " 
 of the Rhetoric ; and his feeling about the scientific value of 
 the conception may be fairly inferred from the discussion in 
 the Politics (III. 16) of the question whether it is better that 
 an individual or the law should be supreme. He decides, 
 unless under quite exceptional circumstances, in favour of the 
 rule of law, which is "reason without passion." Under law 
 Aristotle explains that he understands customary {Kara ra eOrj) 
 as well as written law ; ^ but customary law is law which 
 admits of proof by means of precedents ; it is not a law of 
 nature to be interpreted only by the arbitrary decisions of an 
 absolute monarch. And, when one turns from this discussion 
 to the passage in the Rhetoric^ one might almost imagine 
 Aristotle looking forward with prophetic vision on the vast 
 turgid river of rhetoric flowing through long ages from its 
 source in the upspringing protest against the rocky barrier of 
 mere external authority — a river destined to sweep away in its 
 course some things that were evil and some things that were 
 good. But Aristotle treats the whole question with scientific 
 impartiality, just as in the Politics he sees no inconsistency 
 between sketching an ideal state on the one hand and on the 
 other laying down prescriptions for preserving a tyrann}' 
 with a cold-blooded calmness which anticipates and explains 
 Machiavelli.- " No case : talk about the law of nature," is 
 a more lofty suggestion than " No case : abuse plaintiff's 
 attorney," but is equally a rhetorical device. Such a sugges- 
 tion is hardly sufficient evidence that Aristotle believed in 
 
 ' In Rhet., I. 13, 1373, h. 5, the I'Stos vo^ios (jus cirile) is divided into 
 written and unwritten. All unwritten law is not kolvos vofios (jus goii- 
 tiu7n.^), as might seem to be suggested by 10, 13G8, b. 8 standing alone. 
 
 - Pol., V. c. 11, which should be compared with The Prince. The Princo 
 has too often been read apart from the Discourses on Livy, and lias been 
 misunderstood as Aristotle has never been in this matter. Cannot peojile 
 see that even in the worst state there is a better and worse?
 
 32 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 the law of nature in the sense in which its modern advocates 
 have appealed to it as settling what is right and wrong, apart 
 from any reference to either statutory or customary law. 
 Throughout the whole of his Ethk>i and Politics^ he seems to 
 hold that in practical matters we can be more certain of 
 particular judgments as to right and wrong than of general 
 principles. General principles we must have for the sake of 
 legislation ; but they can only be valid " for the most part," and 
 may need correction on the grounds of equity by an adminis- 
 trator, who from his experience has acquired an " eye " {Eth. 
 Nic, VI. 11, § 6) that will enable him to see rightly in par- 
 ticulars. He does not speak of equity — " the correction of 
 legal right " (ihid., V. 10, § 3), as the introduction of the law 
 of nature to correct human law, but as a correction in some 
 particular instance " of such a kind as the legislator himself 
 would make, were he present " {ibid., § 5). 
 
 If further proof were needed of Aristotle's attitude to the 
 idea of the law of nature, I might refer to an example which 
 he gives in the Topics (VI. 2, 140, a. 6) of a bad definition : 
 '' Law is the measure or image of natural rights " (6 vofioq 
 ixerpov^ rj etKonv rwv ^vaei Sikcucov). "Such phrases," he says, 
 " are worse than metaphors : an image arises through imita- 
 tion, and this is not the case with law." Now to call law an 
 image is, so far as I can see, very like the notion of positive 
 human law being a copy or reflection of the Law of Nature. 
 But we must leave Aristotle for less exact thinkers, on whose 
 minds these rhetorical phrases took a stronger and firmer hold, 
 and whom modern defenders of Natural Rights can quote as 
 authorities with better justification than that with which 
 they can appeal to " the philosopher." 
 
 A set of men, more grimly in earnest with life than the 
 majority at least of the fashionable Sophists, took this anti- 
 thesis of nature and convention, not merely as a weapon for 
 attacking existing institutions with clever dialectic, but as a 
 guide in conduct. One of the Socratic circle was Antisthenes, 
 who is said to have previously been a pupil of the Sophist 
 Gorgias. Antisthenes taught " that the wise man is self- 
 
 ' What is meant by this is left obscure — Aristotle does not discuss this 
 alternative — probably that law determines what is otherwise vague, just 
 as in Aristotle's own theory of exchange {Eth. JV^iC, V. 5) money " mea- 
 sures" values.
 
 CH. ii] IN LA W AND POLITICS n 
 
 sufficient ; and that virtue does not need learning nor argu- 
 ments, but deeds only. Tlie wise man will live not according 
 to the established laws, but according to the law of virtue." 
 The pupil of Antisthenes, Diogenes, is better known than his 
 master, because of the gossip about him which has come down 
 to ITS through that editor of philosophical " Tit Bits," his 
 namesake, Diogenes Laertius.^ Diogenes became the typical 
 cynic. He represents a revolt against convention, not in 
 words only, but in life. He disowns the state ; he is a " citizen 
 of the world." He scoffs at Plato's philosophy ; he appeals 
 from fine arguments to the coarser evidence of his senses. " I 
 see a table and a cup ; but I see no tableness or cupness." He 
 scoffs at Plato's elegant carpet, trampling on it, as on Plato's 
 pride, " with pride of his own," as Plato retorted. He lives in 
 a tub instead of in a house. He sees a child drinking out of his 
 hands, and thereupon throws away his drinking cup, saying, 
 " The child has beaten me in the simplification of life." In all 
 things he will follow nature rather than convention. He pre- 
 fers liberty before everything. There is to be no property. 
 He argues (in a way that anticipates Wycliffe, mutatis mutan- 
 dis) that as everything belongs to the gods, and the gods are 
 the friends of the wise, therefore everything belongs to the wise. 
 There should be no marriage ; women and children should be in 
 common. There is no impiety even in tasting human flesh. It 
 is said that once he attempted to eat raw meat, but could not 
 digest it. Of the Cynics generally we are told that they wished 
 to abolish the whole system of logic and natural philosophy, and 
 to give up literature, science, and art. They taught that men 
 should live very simply, using only just as much food as is 
 sufficient, and wearing only one garment, despising riches and 
 glory and nobleness of birth. Some of them fed on nothing but 
 herbs and drank only cold water, living in any chance shelter 
 they could find. Diogenes used to say that the gods are in 
 want of nothing, and that therefore, when a man wished for 
 nothing, he was likest to the gods.-^ 
 
 Here we have the " return to nature," the protest against 
 convention, in its most extreme form. It is a protest which finds 
 many echoes at various periods, and even in our own day. It 
 
 ' "A learned man, in tlie worst sense of the term," as the late Pro- 
 fessor Jowett once described him. 
 ^ See Dio^^enes Laertins, Lib. VI., esp. §§ 103-105. 
 N. R. D
 
 34 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 is the Hellenic anticipation of Rousseauism. In the history of 
 thought it is most significant as the starting-point of Stoicism, 
 In Stoicism the Cynic maxims are toned down so as to make 
 them compatible with a fulfilment of the ordinary duties of an 
 honest citizen's life. The self-sufiftcingness of the Cynic is still 
 professedly held up as an ideal ; but his savage individualism 
 gives waj^ before a more social creed, and " Nature " means 
 something more than a mere absence of all that separates man 
 from tlie beasts. It seems that in the Stoic maxim "to live 
 in harmony with Nature," the words "with Nature " are an 
 addition to the original formula, which meant therefore " to 
 live in a way that is self-consistent," ^ Absence of contra- 
 diction in the maxim of conduct rem.inds one at once of Kant, 
 whose affinity with the Stoics has been frequentl}' noted. Thus 
 reason is the ultimate judge of right conduct ; but reason to the 
 Stoic is not the mere arbitrary whim of the individual. It is 
 something whose decisions admit of argument and discussion. 
 The Stoics, far from despising logic, cultivated it more than 
 any other post- Aristotelian sect. But all theoretical philosophy 
 was in their view subordinate to the practical guidance of life. 
 " Nature " to the Stoics is not the mere chaos of sensible 
 things minus whatever results from man's rational efforts. 
 It is objective reason ; it is, as with Aristotle, the divine 
 element in the Universe, The reason of the individual man 
 is only a partial manifestation of it : his reason is a divine 
 element in him, and it. is in virtue of this divine element in him 
 that man can understand the reason that is in the Universe 
 and can live the life according to Nature. Thus reason is not 
 something that separates the judgment of one man from that 
 of another. The appeal to reason is an appeal to the common 
 reason of mankind. Human laws and institutions, therefore, 
 are no longer despised as merely conventional. They are a 
 realisation, however imperfect, of the law of Nature which is 
 behind and above them. Even the popular religion is not to be 
 despised as merely false ; it is an imperfect recognition of the 
 deity that pervades the Universe, And the Stoic philosopher 
 may with a good conscience take part in the national worship. 
 Thus Stoicism touches the practical spirit of the legally-minded 
 and conservative Roman on one side, whilst it passes over into 
 Eastern or Neo-Platonic mysticism on the other. Stoicism, 
 ' Stobseus, EcL, II. c. 6, § 6 (182).
 
 CH. ii] IN LAW AND POLITICS 35 
 
 developed among the Greeks when the decaying Greek city- 
 state could no longer provide a basis for the moral life of the 
 individual, developed possibly under Semitic influence, found 
 its truest disciples among the Romans.^ To some of the 
 noblest souls of the ancient world it became a religion. And 
 it was a religion before which outward distinctions counted 
 for nothing ; it was equally the creed of the lame slave 
 Epictetus and of the Emperor Marcus Aurelius. 
 
 Cynicism had merely offered a protest against a civilisation 
 in which luxury was beginning to sap the vigour of the race. 
 Stoicism was likewise a creed of political despair ; it had no 
 belief in social progress. Nevertheless, by placing its practical 
 ideal, not in the isolation of the individual human being, but 
 in his union with the great whole of nature and humanity — 
 an abstract universal, instead of an abstract particular — it 
 favoured the very social progress which it seemed to deny. It 
 was the fitting creed of the best citizens of a universal empire; 
 it gave an intellectual justification for the breaking down 
 of the barriers of race and caste. Earlier than Christianity 
 it proclaimed that all men were brothers, and that all might be 
 by adoption the sons of God. In its contempt for " things 
 external " as things indifferent, like Christianity, it escaped 
 the need of directly facing many social problems ; but it intro- 
 duced a cosmopolitan and humanising spirit into the minds of 
 practical citizens, who were engaged in the work of adminis- 
 tering and interpreting the law of the Roman world. 
 
 Cicero is not now considered a great name in the history of 
 philosophy ; but he is a very important person in the history 
 of human thought in general. He had no genuine speculative 
 interest in philosophical problems ; he is mildly sceptical of all 
 solutions, but kindly disposed to all Schools. Yet in ethics he 
 can be dogmatic enough, and has most affinity with the Stoics, 
 tempering the harshness of their doctrines with elements 
 borrowed from Plato and Aristotle and with the sane, practical 
 judgment of the Roman spirit softened by Greek culture. For 
 the very reasons which make his writings unsatisfactory to the 
 special student of philosophy, they were admirably fitted to 
 
 ^ It must not indeed be forgotten that the practical character of later 
 Stoicism and its fitness to influence legal reformers was greatly due to 
 the fact of its being adopted by practical and politically-minded Eomans. 
 Cf. Zeller, Eclecticism (tr.), pp. 14-16.
 
 36 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 influence the average educated man. And it is tlirougli 
 Cicero's graceful Latin, more than through any other single 
 channel, that so large a portion of Greek, and above all of 
 Stoic ethics, has become the common heritage of the civilised 
 world. 
 
 The customary appeal, away from the disputes of the philo- 
 sophers, to the feelings implanted by God and Nature in the 
 heart of every man, to the common sense or the universal 
 opinion of mankind — this commonplace of popular philosophy 
 is the very essence of Cicero's ethical teaching. And here we 
 find the first distinct formulation of the idea of the law of 
 nature, in that very form of it which survives in modern 
 thought. " In every matter the consent of all peoples is to be 
 considered as the law of nature." " Universal consent is the 
 voice of nature." ^ Not only the fundamental principles of 
 morality, but the existence of God and the immortality of the 
 soul are revealed to us by " that voice of nature " which speaks 
 through the general consent of mankind. This innate con- 
 sciousness of what is right and true may indeed be obscured 
 and depraved by evil habits, but it is there nevertheless, and 
 it appears clearly in the opinions of the best men, and in the 
 uncorrupted minds of the young, " in whom as in a mirror 
 nature is seen." ^ Is not this just the "Common Sense" or 
 " Intuitionist " philosophy to which so many moderns have 
 resorted as the safest, and undoubtedly the easiest, defence 
 against Scepticism ? 
 
 It is in this Ciceronian and popular form that Stoic philo- 
 sophy found its way into Roman law. I do not mean to 
 suggest that the later jurists were conscious of borrowing the 
 idea of the law of nature directly from Cicero, or from any 
 Greek or Roman Stoic philosopher ; but that Cicero's use and 
 interpretation of the idea of nature sufficiently explains the 
 introduction of that idea as an equivalent or as a basis for the 
 J26s (jentium. The phrase j«.§ gentium was, in the seventeenth 
 century, by a mistranslation taken to mean " the law of 
 nations," what we now call " international law." The mis- 
 
 ' -'Omni autem in re consensio omnium gentium lex naturae putanda 
 est" (Ti/i'C, I. 13, § 30). "Omnium consensus naturae vox est" {Ibid., 
 15, § 35). 
 
 "^ De Fin., II. 14, § 45 ; V. 22, § 61. " Indicant pueri, in quibus ut in 
 speculis natura cernitur."
 
 CH. ii] IN LAW AND POLITICS 37 
 
 translation was a fortunate one, because it allowed Grotius, and 
 others, to introduce the humane conceptions of the Roman 
 " law of nature " into the theory of the right relations between 
 independent political societies. Nevertheless, it was a mis- 
 translation. JuH gentium was the term used to describe those 
 principles on which Roman magistrates decided cases in which 
 the parties were not both Roman citizens, and in which, 
 therefore, the jus civile was regarded as inapplicable. Jus 
 gentium meant simply " the principles generally accepted 
 among mankind," the common law of the world. ^ In practice 
 this meant the generally recognised principles of right among 
 those peoples with whom the Romans came most in contact, 
 primarily, of course, the other Italian races who were more or 
 less akin to the Romans in blood, in language, and in social 
 usages. This jus gentium, however, could never be anything 
 so fixed and definite as the jus civile of any particular State. 
 Hence it left much more scope for the exercise of his own 
 judgment of what was right or wrong on the part of the 
 pr(Etor, tempered by that respect for precedent in which the 
 Romans resemble the English — a respect for precedent which 
 has contributed so largely to the stability and quiet growth 
 of legal and social institutions among both peoples. It is 
 obvious how easily this idea of jus gentium or " equity " would 
 coalesce with that of the law of nature, when the latter con- 
 ception found its way from Greek philosophy into the minds 
 of Roman jurists. The law of nature was regarded as some- 
 thing permanently existing behind the particular law of this 
 or that State ; and it came to serve as an ideal of excellence 
 towards which the civil law should, when possible, be made to 
 approximate. It served as a standard of simplicity and of 
 perfection, and, as Sir Henry Maine has suggested, is probably 
 the chief reason for the progressive character of Roman legal 
 conceptions.- 
 
 ^ See art. on Jus Gentium, by the late Prof. Henry Nettleship in 
 Journal of PliUology. Vol. XIII. p. IG!) seq. 
 
 * Ancient Law, p. 78. Muirhead {Roman Law, p. 301) quotes a remark 
 of Voigt's " that the risk which arose from the setting up of the precepts 
 of a speculative jM*' nafiirale, as derogating from the rules of the jus 
 civile, was greatly diminished through tlie position held by tlie jurists 
 of the early empire. Theiv jus responchndi made them legislative organs 
 of the State; so that in introducing principles of the jus naturale or of 
 cequum et bonum, they at the same moment positivised them, and gave
 
 38 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 One great jurist, Ulpian, drew a peculiar distinction between 
 tlie jw.§ »rti?<r«/e and the J2<s gentium; according to his view, 
 which is embodied in Justinian's Institutes^ I. Tit. 2, the law of 
 nature applies not only to men, but to all animals. "It is 
 that which nature has taught to all animals." The union of 
 male and female, which we call marriage, and the rearing of 
 children are in this sense said to belong to the law of nature. 
 Ulpian apparently did not know, or did not take account of 
 the fact, that among some of the lower animals reproduction 
 may occur without sex, and that, except among the higher 
 animals, the young are left to shift for themselves. This 
 distinction, however, allows Ulpian to utter a sentence wliich 
 was to awaken far-reaching echoes when, after long centuries, 
 it passed out of the region of theoretical jurisprudence into 
 the region of practical politics. Slavery exists jure gejitium, 
 undoubtedly ; i.e. all civilised peoples known to the Romans 
 recognised this institution : ancient political society was 
 based on it. But " by the law of nature all men at the 
 first were born free." The appeal to the common usage of all 
 animals would hardly have served Ulpian here, had he known 
 of the slave-holding communities of ants. In using these 
 words, he probably only meant that apart from definite 
 human institution the status of slave did not exist. It might 
 be added, neither did that of the free citizen — the free man in 
 the full sense of the term. 
 
 As Maine has pointed out,^ the chief intellectual discipline 
 of the Western mind, of all that part of the empu^e whose 
 culture came to it in the Latin and not in the Greek tongue, 
 for nearly three centuries was the study of Roman law.^ 
 When the first revival of learning began in the twelfth 
 century, it was Roman law which divided with Aristotle the 
 
 them the force of law " (Voigt, Das Jus Naturale, etc., der Bomer, Vol. I. 
 p. 341.) 
 
 ' Ancient Law, ch. ix. 
 
 - It was undoubtedly from the Roman law^'ers that '• the natural 
 freedom of all mankind " found its way into the Ordinance of Louis X. 
 (Louis Hutin) of France (1315), which was intended to induce serfs to 
 purchase their freedom (as a means of bringing money into the roj-al 
 treasury). " Comme selon le droit de nature chacun doit naistre 
 franc " is the preamble of the ordinance. The attempt to raise money, 
 says Michelet, was ineffectual ; but a king's proclamation of the natural 
 liberty of mankind was not forgotten. {Ilistoire de France, III. p. 198.)
 
 CH. ii] JN LA W AND POLITICS 39 
 
 interests of students. And, finally, wlien the Reformation 
 displaced scholastic Aristotelianism or weakened its authority 
 in Protestant Universities, it was once again Roman law and 
 that Angustinian theology, which was based so largely on 
 legal conceptions, that dominated the thought of most of the 
 nations of Northern Europe. The famous treatise of Grotius, 
 De Jure Belli et Pads, was a principal medium through which 
 the Roman conception of a law of nature came to influence 
 ethical and political speculation. The idea of a law of nature, 
 which forms the background of Locke's political theories, and 
 which from Locke passed on to Rousseau, and to the fathers 
 of the American Republic, comes to Locke mainly from 
 Grotius and from Pufendorf. The other writer who in- 
 fluences Locke, and the writer whom he mostly quotes, is 
 Hooker ; and Hooker is the medium through whom the 
 ethical and political philosophy of Thomas Aquinas finds its 
 way into English popular thought. Now the conception of 
 Nature in Thomas Aquinas is derived from Aristotle ; but he 
 adds to it the Ciceronian conception of a law of nature, and 
 the law of nature he ujdderstands in a far more definite 
 manner as a code of rules which can be ascertained and fully 
 formulated by the use of reason. The ancient conception is 
 generally that of jus naturale, though, as we have seen, Cicero 
 alread}'' speaks of lex naturce. But in the middle ages the 
 influence of the Hebrew idea of a divinely given code, and the 
 influence of Roman law, no longer as something living and 
 growing, but as finally summed up in a venerable code, tend 
 to give a quasi-legal character to ethics, which has left deep 
 traces on modern thought and made it difficult for us to 
 appreciate the Greek point of view.^ " Moral law " is the 
 most familiar of modern ethical terms ; it is not to be found 
 in Aristotle at all.^ 
 
 Thomas Aquinas makes a very important distinction among 
 the precepts of the law of nature. " First of all there is in 
 man an inclination to that natural good which he shares 
 ^long with all suhstances, inasmuch as every substance seeks 
 the preservation of its own being, according to its nature. In 
 virtue of this inclination there belongs to the natural law the 
 taking of those means whereby the life of man is preserved, 
 
 1 Cf. Sid^'wick, lUstory of Ethics, pp. 108-110, 142. 
 
 - As to the KOLvos vofioi of the lihetoric, see above, pp. 30-32.
 
 40 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 and things contrary thereto are kept off. Secondly, there is 
 in man an inchnation to things more specially belonging to 
 him, in virtue of the nature which he shares with other 
 animals. In this respect those things are said to be of the 
 natural law, which nature has taught to all animals, as the 
 intercourse of the sexes, the education of offspring, and the 
 like. [With this compare Ulpian, quoted above.] In a third 
 way there is in man an inclination to good, according to the 
 rational nature which is proper to him ; as man has a natural 
 inclination to know the truth about God, and to live in society. 
 In this respect there belong to natural law such natural in- 
 clinations as to avoid ignorance, to shun offending other men. 
 and the like." [Summa^ la 2ae, qu. 94, art. '2. I quote from 
 Father Rickaby's very convenient translation, Aquinas Ethi- 
 cus, I. p. 282.] Here we have a careful distinction between 
 natural tendencies and the precepts of reason, which it would . 
 be well if all those who have talked about nature and the 
 law of nature had always observed. In discussing particular 
 natural rights, I shall have again to refer to some of the 
 opinions of the Angelic Doctor and of his followers. 
 
 The general conception of natural law in Aquinas corre- 
 sponds with that of the Stoics : " Natural law is nothing else 
 than the participation in the eternal law of the mind of a 
 rational creature " (la 2ae, qu. 91, art. 2), i.e. man partaking 
 partly in the divine reason can thereby know in some reflection 
 of it the eternal law, which can be fully known by none save 
 God Himself and the blessed who see God in His essence (la 
 2ae, qu. 93, art. 2). Human law, i.e. the positive laws of par- 
 ticular states, is derived from the law of nature, and is only 
 true so far as it partakes of the law of nature, or is not in con- 
 flict with it. By positive divine law Aquinas means the 
 eternal law as expressly revealed. That of course has no 
 connection with Greek or Roman ideas, and does not here 
 concern us. 
 
 Now it is to be noted that the Roman conception of a law of 
 nature, although it did good service in leading to the progres- 
 sive reform and humanisation of the civil law, did not imply 
 any direct conflict with positive human law : it was, except on 
 Ulpian's theory, nearly, if not altogether, identical with the 
 common element in the customary law of various communities.' 
 
 ^ According to the late Professor Muirhead {Roman Laic, pp. 298, 299),
 
 CH. ii] IN LA W AND POLITICS 41 
 
 And Ulpian's law of nature only differed by including the 
 lower animals. But when the codification of Roman law by 
 Justinian — which we might call in a certain sense the last act 
 of the ancient world — had given it a character of finalitj^, the 
 conception of the law of nature was received by the mediseval 
 world as the conception of something not merely more perfect 
 than any positive human laws, but as something distinct 
 from them. It came to be thought of as an ideal code, not 
 merely as the common or universal element amid the varieties 
 of human usage, but distinct from positive human laws, 
 which might very often conflict with this code. This rever- 
 ence for the law of nature did good service in helping to 
 bring some degree of order and system into the chaos of 
 French law. As Maine says, " the admission of its dignity 
 and claims was the one tenet which all French practitioners 
 (whether of the 'pmjs de droit ecrif^ or of the jj«?/.s- de droit 
 coutinnier) alike subscribed to.'' ' 
 
 To the service rendered by the idea of a law of nature in the 
 formation of the modern conception of a law of nations I have 
 already referred. But the influence of the idea on the simpli- 
 fication of French law, and its utility in supplying a set of 
 legal conceptions for the relations of independent political 
 societies, were both only extensions of that power which it had 
 already exercised among the later Roman jurists. In the appli- 
 cation of the idea by Thomas Aquinas and his followers we 
 have the germ of something new,^ of the use of nature as a 
 court of appeal by those whose consciences or whose political 
 aspirations were offended by the positive law of their country. 
 
 the notion of a j?a.s- naturale as distinct from the jus gentium was not 
 peculiar to Ulpian. A ju.s naturos common to man and the lower 
 animals is indeed a law of nature of which we find no other jurist tak- 
 ing account. " But many of them refer again and again to the jus 
 naturale] and Gaius is the only one' (Justinian following him) that 
 occasionally makes it synonymous with the jus (jentiumy This is a 
 controversy which I must leave to competent students of the Civil Law. 
 The opinion of Muirhead and of Voigt, whom he follows in this matter, 
 brings the Roman ji<,s' naturale a little nearer to themediteval conception 
 of it than the opinion of those {e.g. Dr. Moyle in his edition of .Justinian's 
 Institutes, Vol. I. p. 92), who say that Ulpian is the only leading jurist 
 who makes anything of the distinction, 
 
 ^ Ancient Law, p. 85. 
 
 - Though, from another jioint of view, only a return to the idea of the 
 Greek Sophists and Cjuiics.
 
 42 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 Lex injusta non est lex., says Snarez {De Legibus, III. c, 19): not 
 merely is an unjust law not to be obeyed, but it is not to be 
 regarded as a law at all. AVas it the assurance of a Divine 
 revelation and of an infallible guide in the authority of the 
 Church which made Scholastic ethics so ready to sanction the 
 rejection of the authority of human law ? When the authority 
 of the Church was shaken, the way was cleared for revolution 
 in the name of Nature. 
 
 But in the writers of the seventeenth century we hear not 
 only of the law, but of the state of nature. For Hobbes the 
 state of nature is simply what would remain if all human 
 institutions were taken away ; and this state of nature, he 
 holds, would be a state of war of all against all. In modern 
 phrase we should call it " the struggle for existence," unmiti- 
 gated by any associations — not even by that of the family; for 
 Hobbes does not appear to take note of the fact that even 
 among the animals, who have never entered into a social con- 
 tract, there is in some cases a certain limit, temporary at 
 least, imposed on the state of war by the relation subsisting 
 between mates, and still more by that between parent and 
 offspring. Hobbes's argument is that rebellion against the 
 existing government means a return to the " state of nature." 
 Locke, who wishes to justify revolution in certain cases, is 
 therefore concerned to maintain that this state of nature is not 
 a state of mere anarchy, but has a law to govern it; and where- 
 as Hobbes makes the laws of nature all simply consequences of 
 the natural instinct of self-preservation, Locke, thinking of his 
 state of nature as a social state, although not yet a political 
 state, includes in his conception of law of nature very much 
 what Thomas Aquinas includes in it. Locke's " state of 
 nature " is thought of by him as a fairly happy condition, the 
 only drawback to which was that every one had to be judge 
 in his own cause, Locke, moreover, has an idea of " a golden 
 age" existing even after government has come into existence 
 — a time when people did not need " to examine the original 
 and rights of government." * A little confusion on the part of 
 his readers (perhaps in his own mind) makes it possible to 
 regard the state of nature as itself the golden age, and the 
 way is prepared for the favourite theory of the eighteenth 
 century : — 
 
 ' Civil Government, II. § 111-
 
 CH. ii] IN LAW AND POLITICS 43 
 
 " Nor think in nature's state they hlindly trod ; 
 The state of nature was the reign of God : 
 Self-love and social at her birth began, 
 Union the bond of all things and of man. 
 Pride then was not, nor arts that pride to aid ; 
 Man walk'd with beast, joint tenant of the shade ; 
 The same his table, and the same his bed ; 
 No murder cloath'd him, and no murder fed." ' 
 
 In these lines of Pope's the state of nature is identified with 
 the golden age of the Greek and Latin poets ; and " the reign 
 of Grod " is an equivalent for Locke's words " has a law of 
 nature to govern it." ^ 
 
 Now to think of the law of nature not simply as an ideal 
 which the reason of man may discover behind or above all 
 actual positive laws, but as a law which has in some past age, 
 however dimly conceived, really prevailed, makes a very con- 
 siderable dijBference in the way in which the idea of that law 
 affects the conduct of mankind. It becomes something more 
 vivid for the imagination, and the feeling is pretty sure to 
 suggest itself that what once has been may be restored again, 
 if only we can get rid of the evil institutions that have inter- 
 fered with this blessed state of nature. It is a small step from 
 these lines of Pope's to the passionate invective of Rousseau 
 against civilisation. To the Thomist the law of nature is an 
 ideal for human law ; to the Rousseauist it is an ideal to be 
 reached by getting rid of human law altogether. 
 
 In explaining the rise of this new conception of the law of 
 nature as the law of a pre-political stage, we must take into 
 account firstly the diminished respect for Aristotle, due to the 
 Reformation and to the Renaissance — to the revolt against the 
 Church, and to the revolt against Scholasticism ; and secondly, 
 the diminished respect for theology and for the authority of 
 the Bible. The Protestantism of the sixteenth century has 
 passed into the rationalistic Deism of the eighteenth. Thus 
 the Scriptural story of Adam in Paradise fades away into the 
 Greek myth of a Golden Age. We must remember, too, that 
 although the Aristotelianism of Thomas Aquinas leads him to 
 regard political institutions as natural to man,^ yet many 
 Christian theologians had held that government had only 
 come into existence as a consequence of sin. Cain and Nim- 
 
 ' Essay on Man, III. 147 seq. ^ Civil Government, II. § 6. 
 ^ De lieg, I'rinc, I. 1,
 
 44 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [cH. ii 
 
 rod ^ were its founders. This is the theological equivalent ot 
 William Godwin's view that " Law is an institution of the 
 most pernicious tendency." Suarez has to introduce a dis- 
 tinction between the "directive" and "coercive" powers of 
 government in order to conceal the discrepancy between the 
 views of St. Thomas and St. Gregory ; even if man had not 
 fallen from the state of innocence, Suarez holds it " probable " 
 that the directive power of government would have been 
 necessary, " for even among the angels there is order and lord- 
 ship [prdo et principatus).^^ The coercive power of government 
 presupposes some deterioration, so that in respect of it govern- 
 ment may be said to have been introduced because of sin.^ 
 Thus the heresy of Rousseauism might in this matter claim a 
 certain degree of ecclesiastical sanction. 
 
 The mention of Rousseau suggests another element in the 
 conception of nature, which came into prominence in the 
 eighteenth century, and towards the close of it effected the 
 great revolution in literature and art and manners of which 
 Rousseati was the earliest conspicuous prophet. The love of 
 natural scenery, the interest in country life, the preference for 
 what appeals directly to sentiment over what appeals to the 
 intellect, form part of the new reverence for Nature as opposed 
 to human institutions. Rousseau's attack upon literature and 
 art ended by giving an enormous stimulus to the production 
 of new forms of them. Pope was little conscious that in those 
 lines I have quoted he was preparing the way for a reaction 
 against the whole style of literature and of thought, of which 
 he was one of the most famous representatives. It is Classi- 
 cism itself preparing the way for Romanticism and " Natu- 
 ralism." But the significance of Rousseau in respect of this 
 idea of Nature is so important, and has been so often misre- 
 presented, that I must reserve it for separate discussion. 
 
 The rationalistic Deism of the eighteenth century affects 
 the conception of Nature in a further way. " Natural 
 Theology " gains in importance with the decay of general 
 belief in ecclesiastical or scriptural authority : when first the 
 
 ' Cf. Milton, Paradise Lost, XTT. 24, for the idea that Nimrod invented 
 the dominion of man over man, which is contrary to the law of nature. 
 On the words in Gen. x. 9, "a mightj' hunter before the Lord," Milton 
 gives the gloss, " Hunting (and men, not beasts, shall be his game)," etc. 
 
 2 De Legibus, III. 1.
 
 CH. iij IN LA W AND POLITICS 45 
 
 Clmrcli and then the Bible begin to be doubted, there remains 
 Reason, and Natural Theology is common ground to the 
 theologian who acknowledges " Reason, unaided by Revela- 
 tion " as one of the sources of knowledge about the ultimate 
 meaning of the universe, and to the " Deist," who considers it 
 the only source.' Adam Smith's course of lectures on moral 
 philosophy, out of part of which grew his Wealth of N^ations-, 
 began with Natural Theology.^ In the conception of nature 
 which is implied in his advocacy of " the system of natural 
 liberty," is presupposed the idea of "that great, benevolent, 
 and all-wise Being, who directs all the movements of nature, 
 and who is determined to maintain in it at all times the 
 greatest possible quantity of happiness." This optimistic 
 Deism, which is common to Pope and Bolingbroke, to Jefferson 
 and Robespierre, is presupposed alike in the theory of natural 
 rights of the American declarations and in the theory of 
 natural liberty of the laissez faire economists, though in both 
 cases doubtless the idea of Nature would not have been applied 
 in this special way, had it not been for the recognition of evils 
 caused by oppressive or foolish governments. The theory of 
 the "Physiocrats,"^ that man ought to study natural law and 
 not to disturb its action, assumes that nature is operating in 
 a way that is beneficial to man. 
 
 Finally we must take into account the idea of natural laws 
 as that is held by the students of natural science, for it affects 
 not only the conception of economic laws but also the theory 
 of natural rights as maintained in our own time by Mr. 
 Herbert Spencer. When the phenomena of human society 
 come to be brought under conceptions and studied by methods 
 similar to those used in thS study of the phenomena of 
 vegetable and animal life, the notion of causality is introduced 
 into ethics and politics and economics which now become 
 branches of sociology. " Laws of nature " in this sense have, 
 however, no direct connection with the Law of Nature [jus 
 naturale) of Roman jurists, mediaeval theologians and intui- 
 
 ' The optimism of the Deists is, in one aspect of it, a reaction and a 
 protest aj^ainst the gloom of the popular theology. 
 
 ' Cf. T. E. Cliffe Leslie, Essays in PoliticaL and Moral I'hilosop/nj, 
 p. 150; Bonar, Philosophy and Political Economy, p. 148. 
 
 ^ Mr. Bonar in his Philosophy and Political Economy, p. 90, points 
 out how the idea of the law of nature had carried Locke in the direction 
 of what was afterwards known as Physiocracy,
 
 46 HISTORY OF THE IDEA OF NATURE [ch. ii 
 
 tional moralists. Only in the lex ceterna of Aquinas and his 
 followers do we find any meeting-point between them ; but 
 there is this important difference, that whereas natural laws 
 in the sense of causal sequences or uniformities among 
 phenomena are, if correctly stated, incapable of being broken 
 by man (I say nothing of the controversy about the relation 
 of God to the lex cetenia, as it is irrelevant here), laws of 
 nature in the ethical sense, Uke political laws, are statements 
 of what man " ought " to do and are therefore capable of being 
 broken. When we speak of violating a law of physiology, we 
 are using inaccurate language ; we mean violating a maxim 
 of health based on, or supposed to be based on, a knowledge of 
 physiology. So far as economic laws are statements of what 
 under certain conditions does happen, they are " natural laws " 
 and cannot be violated. Mr, Herbert Spencer is making use 
 of a mere ambiguity of language when he speaks of the folly 
 of our legislators in trying " to repeal by Act of Parliament a 
 law of Nature." ^ No Act of Parliament can affect what is 
 really a law of nature ; and Mr. Spencer need not be afraid of 
 the folly of our legislators, if it only leads them to attempt the 
 genuinely impossible, Mr, Spencer has drawn his own practi- 
 cal maxims from his own conclusions about nature ; and some 
 Acts of Parliament run counter to these — that is all, 
 
 Mr. Spencer seeks to justify his defence of natural rights 
 by appealing to the actual customs of various savage and 
 barbarian peoples.- This may seem to be the appeal to the 
 consensus liumani generis^ except that savages seem to be 
 preferred to civilised races in the appeal, so that we have here 
 rather the Rousseauist than the Roman or Thomist conception 
 of nature ; but there are, I think, also present certain associa- 
 tions derived from the modern scientific conception of nature, 
 in the sense of the system of permanent relations subsisting 
 between phenomena. Sociological facts are brought forward 
 to settle what is really a practical controversy about what 
 ought to be done. 
 
 Natural rights have been explained as " biological rights," 
 l)y which, I understand, is meant that there are certain natural 
 instincts or tendencies in human nature which must be re- 
 
 FJliics Part III.), p. 546. 
 Man versus State, pp. 90 seq.
 
 CH. ii] IN LA W AND POLITICS 47 
 
 specter! \>y legislation. This is obviously very much less than 
 is meant by " rights " under the law of nature in its old sense. 
 It is simply an appeal to fact ; and I do not see that it settles 
 for us which instincts deserve our respect and which do not, 
 and that is just the important matter in practice. To this 
 subject I must return.
 
 CHAPTER III 
 
 ROUSSEAU AND EOUSSEAUISJI 
 
 " This transition from the state of nature to the civil state 
 produces a very remarkable change in man, by substituting in 
 liis conduct justice for instinct and giving to his actions the 
 morality which they previously lacked. It is then alone that, 
 the voice of duty taking the place of physical impulse, and 
 right taking the place of appetite, man, who hitherto has 
 considered no one but himself, sees himself forced to act on 
 different principles and to consult his reason before listening 
 to his inclinations. Although he deprives himself in the 
 civil state of several advantages which nature gives him, he 
 gains such great advantages in their stead, his capacities are 
 exercised and developed, his ideas are enlarged, his sentiments 
 are ennobled, his whole soul is elevated to such a degree that 
 if the abuses of this new condition did not degrade him often 
 below the level of that from which he has come, he ought to 
 bless without ceasing the happy instant which took him from 
 it for ever, and which of an animal stupid and limited made 
 him an intelligent being and a man." 
 
 This passage from Rousseau's Contrat Social (I. c. 8) might 
 almost serve as a commentary on Aristotle's doctrine that " man 
 is by nature a political animal," save that Rousseau uses the 
 term " nature " only in a negative sense, for the non-civil 
 state. The qualification which is added to the praise of the 
 civil state also finds its counterpart in Aristotle : — 
 
 " A social instinct is implanted in all men by nature, and 
 yet he who first founded the state was the greatest of benefac- 
 tors. For man when perfected is the best of animals, but 
 when separated from law and justice he is the worst of all ; 
 since armed injustice is the more dangerous, and he is equipped 
 at birth with the arms of intelligence and with moral qualities 
 which he may use for the worst ends.^ Wherefore, if he have 
 
 ' Mr. Welldon translates, " Nature has endowed man with arms which 
 
 •»8
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISAf 49 
 
 not virtue, lie is the most unholy and the most savage of 
 animals, and the most full of lust and o-lnttony.'" ^ 
 
 The civilised man can sink himself lower, but he can also 
 rise higher than the beast or the savage. The savage is in- 
 capable of some civilised vices, but he is also incapable of most 
 civilised virtues. 
 
 The passage I have quoted from Rousseau does not contaiu 
 what is usually supposed to be Rousseau's view of civilised 
 society. The evils incident to the civil state are admitted, 
 but that only in the civil state can man rise above the animal 
 is recognised by Rousseau as fully as by Aristotle. No great 
 writer perhaps has suffered more than Rousseau from having 
 his views judged by his weakest writings. The Confrat 
 Social is a book much more talked about than read, and the 
 prevalent opinion about Rousseau's social theories is derived 
 from the paradoxes of his early prize essays, the Discourse on 
 the Sciences and Arts (1750), which gained a prize, and the 
 Discourse on the Origin of Inequality among Men (1753, publ. 
 1764), which did not. It is there he maintains that " our souls 
 have been corrupted in the proportion in which our sciences 
 and arts have advanced to perfection"; that "the man who 
 thinks is an animal spoilt " ; that '' iron and corn have civilised 
 men and have destroyed the human race." But even in the 
 Discourse on Ineqacditij he recognises that the state of nature 
 "has perhaps never existed, and probably will never exist," and 
 that when he speaks of it he is using a hypothetical argument 
 and not attempting to describe the actual, original state of 
 mankind. Though in the sequel he does refer to a primitive 
 state, he does not make that his ideal, but considers the 
 happiest period of human existence to be " that of the develop- 
 ment of the human faculties, occupying a golden mean be- 
 tween the indolence of the primitive state and the petulant 
 activity of our self-love." Savages, he holds, are mostly in 
 this stage, " the true youth of the world " ; and all further 
 progress has b(>en, in appearance, so many steps towards the 
 perfection of the individual, and, in effect, towards the de- 
 are intended to subserve tlie purposes of jn-udonco and virtue, but are 
 capable of being wliolly turned to contrary ends." Tliis gives a niucli 
 better sense, but it seems to require a conjectural emendation of the text, 
 such as that wliicli Mr. Welldon adopts. 
 
 ^ Arist., FoL, I. 2, §§ 15, IG (Jowett's Translation). 
 
 N. E. E
 
 50 JWUSSEAU AND ROUSSllAUISM [ch. hi 
 
 crepitude of the species." Nevertheless, in spite of tliis 
 glorification of the savage, he acknowledges that along with 
 a multitude of bad things in civilisation there are a small 
 number of good.^ 
 
 In tho Contrat Social, as we have seen, the proportions of 
 good and evil are reversed. Tho whole treatise is singularlj'- 
 free from the faults that are usually ascribed to Rousseau. 
 The most conspicuous defect in it is that he does not properly 
 appreciate representative government (III. 15) — a defect 
 which he shares with many persons at the present day who 
 have not his excuse. He had not, like Montesquieu, seen the 
 English government from a favourable (perhaps too favourable) 
 point of view. His political ideas had been formed by the 
 reading of Greek and Latin authors, whose only notion of free 
 government was that of small city states ; and he himself was 
 born a citizen of Geneva, a republic in many ways analogous 
 to one of these ancient states, owing its political independence 
 and its special character in a great degree to its Lycurgus, Cal- 
 vin.- The neighbouring Swiss cantons, with which Geneva 
 was allied, were direct democracies of the antique type, or 
 else close oligarchies. Was it strange, then, that Rousseau 
 should accept the generalisation that only small states were 
 fitted for democracy, that moderate-sized states might be aris- 
 tocracies, but that large states (unless by the device of con- 
 federation^) mast be monarchies? But this very opinion of 
 his should save him from the abuse commonly bestowed on 
 him, as if he had been a doctrinaire democrat, and were per- 
 sonally responsible for all the errors of the French Eevolntion. 
 He fully appreciated the "relativity of politics "; he predicted, 
 we may almost say, the part which federal government was to 
 ])lay in the solution of political problems, and of complete 
 democracy ho expressly says, " A government so perfect is not 
 suited to men." ■* His views about the sovereignty of the 
 people and about the justification of revolution are identical 
 
 ' In the Left re a .V. PhilopoUs lie says, " According to me, society is 
 natural to tlic luiman species as decrepitude to the individual ; arts, laws, 
 governments are necessary for peoples, as crutches are for old men." 
 
 - Cf. Contr. Soc, II. 7 (" Of the Legislator "). In a note lie says : " Those 
 Avho only think of Calvin as a theologian know little of the extent of his 
 genius." 
 
 =* Contr. Soc, III. 13. 
 
 ■• lb., III. 4.
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM 51 
 
 ■with those of Locke, expressed indeed in more telling language, 
 and addressed to an audience that was suffering graver and 
 older evils than those which had induced the English Whigs 
 of 1688 to change the government of their country. Rous- 
 seau's distinction of " the general will " from " the will of all," 
 and his seemingly mystical idea of the common self i^moi codi- 
 7)11171), are anticipations of the political theories of the great 
 German idealists. Kant, Fichte, and Hegel are disciples of 
 Rousseau in a truer sense than those Jacobin Puritans, Rol^es- 
 pierre and St. Just, by whom Rousseau has too frequently been 
 judged.^ 
 
 I do not mean to deny the large part which the idea of 
 " Nature " as the antithesis of civilisation, occupies in Rous- 
 seau's thinking. I only wish to insist that it cannot be said 
 to have vitiated the great political treatise of his most mature 
 and soundest period any more than it vitiated the political 
 theories of Locke. That period, however, produced also Emile 
 and La Nouvelle Helo'ise ; and it is with good ground that the 
 cry. "Return to Nature," and the exaltation of sentiment 
 above reason are associated in a special manner with Rousseau, 
 and may be described as " Rousseauism." Rousseau sent his 
 children to the foundling hospital, and could not afterwards 
 trace them. His spiritual children can be found more easily. 
 If one considers the most characteristic features of a great part 
 of European thought since Rousseau's time — the literature of 
 sentiment, the genuine or affected love for natural scenery, the 
 reaction against rationalism and against classicism, even the 
 pessimism of the nineteenth century, along with its deeper 
 sense of sympathy (often more sentimental than rational) with 
 the poor, one might say that, in some degree, we are all Rous- 
 seau's children, — at least there are a good many of them at 
 the present time who do not know their spiritual father. 
 
 If words always meant what their etymology would suggest, 
 if terms of controversy were always selected on strictly logical 
 principles, the opposition between Socialism and Individualism 
 would not lead one to expect that assertors of "natural rights '" 
 
 ' On Rousseau's influence on German thouglit, cf. R. Fester, Rousseau 
 xind die deutsche Geschichtsi^hilosoph/e (Stuttgart, 1890). On thedifl'er- 
 ence between Rousseau's tliouglit at diflcrcnt periods of liis life, cf. Charles 
 Borgeaud, J.-J. liOtisseau''ii lidlgionsphllosoi^hle (Geneva and Leipzig, 
 1883), csp. pp. 11 seq.
 
 52 ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM [ch. hi 
 
 and worshippers of Xature — as the " not duo to human reason " 
 — were to be found among those calKng themselves Socialists. 
 But the fact is, that a great many of those who most loudly 
 profess themselves Socialists are amongst those who have shown 
 least faith in the rationality of human society. To the great 
 confusion of logical terminology, a great many professing 
 "Socialists" are at heart " Individualists " and " Anarchists." 
 In defiance of scientific anthropological science and of history, 
 they seem to believe that individual freedom has decreased 
 with the growth of civilisation/ and that the return to a state 
 of nature is the ideal of human progress. The name " Social- 
 ist" may indeed reasonably l)e assumed by those who are 
 appealing from existing social arrangements to what they 
 conceive to be better social arrangements, not yet anywhere 
 realised, who are dissatisfied with existing society because it 
 is still so largely untrue to its ideal, so largely not social, not 
 organised, but inorganic and anarchical. But this dissatisfac- 
 tion frequently takes the form of a repudiation not merely of 
 this or that form of political organisation, but of all institutions 
 as such, with the exception, perhaps, of the institution of " the 
 dear love of comrades " - — an exception which is no exception ; 
 for love or comradeship is a personal relationship springing up 
 spontaneously between two or more human beings. It may and 
 does give rise to institutions; in fact, all institutions maybe 
 said to have grown out of it. But of itself it is no institution, 
 
 ' Cf. Eous.'eau, who says in the Discourse on Inequality that "the 
 savage lives in himself ; whilst a man in the social state is ahva3's out- 
 side himself, and can only live in the opinion of others." 
 
 - Walt Whitman, wiiosc phrase is here quoted, defie? classification and 
 argument as much as he defies everything else. He is the absolute ex- 
 treme of Protestant individualism, an incarnate " natural rights of man " ; 
 in him infinite self-assertion is combined with infinite recognition of the 
 equal rights of others, and both liberty and equality are merged in a 
 fraternity so wide and all-inclusive that all distinctions of good and bad, 
 right and wrong, are lost in a general blaze and blare of democratic en- 
 thusiasm. With a noble personality and the capacitj' of a certain poetic 
 grandeur, he has become a prophet and teacher in the eyes of a good 
 many in England who arc dissatisfied with the existing chaos and un- 
 reality of our social structure. But it is awkward to use Walt Whitman 
 as a guide of conscience. His appreciations are so universal. If he can 
 liardly bo likened to " the darkness in Avhich all cows are black," he might 
 be described as a blaze of exuberant shadowless sunlight, in which all 
 geese are swans. On Walt Whitman one English author at least has 
 been able to write with judgment and sobriety— Mr. William Clarke.
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND KOUSSEAUISM 53 
 
 such as can form a relatively permanent clothing or shelter 
 which will outlast the individuals who wear or inhabit it ; it 
 is no institution which can take new members into itself to 
 supplement the living or replace the dead, and which remains 
 as a social inheritance for those who are not yet born. 
 
 It is this creation of institutions round him which most of 
 all distinguishes man from the lower animals : the more highly 
 developed forms of it are summed up in the word "civilisa- 
 tion." The higher animals below man have already the germ 
 of social inheritance. Thus, while the insect owes everything, 
 or nearly everything, to inherited instincts, the bird learns by 
 imitation how to build its nest and how to rear its young. 
 Pigeons, unless th(\y have an experienced couple among them, 
 will generally fail to bring up a family. But even the most 
 intelligent of birds or mammalia have only the rudiments of 
 such social inheritance when compared with man; and for this 
 reason they remain stationary, while man progresses. " The 
 owl," says Edgar Quinet, "has outlived Pallas Athene; the 
 eagle has outlived Jupiter ; they have not lost a feather in 
 the fall of the gods." ^ " They have not lost a feather " ; but 
 neither have they learnt a note of music, nor improved their 
 style of domestic architecture. 
 
 Civilisation is a vague term, and to different persons it sug- 
 gests different ideas. To some people it suggests railways and 
 telegraphs ; to some it suggests bustling streets, showy shop- 
 windows, boulevards, cafes, theatres ; to some it suggests 
 chimney-pot hats and black coats ; to some it means Christian 
 churches, parliaments and policemen ; - to some it means 
 mainly art, science, and literature ; to our modern Cynics 
 or "Rousseauists, to those whose prophets are Thoreau and AValt 
 Whitman, it is a disease which needs to be cured by " a return 
 to nature." ^ 
 
 To analyse civilisation adequately would mean to write a 
 
 ' V Esprit Noiiveaic, p. 25. 
 
 - There is a well-kno\v}i story of an Irishman, shipwrecked in an un- 
 knowji h^iid : ^vhen lie saw a man lianging on a gallows, he exclaimed, 
 " Arrali, but this is a civilised country ! " When, soon after, he saw a 
 man lying drunk in a ditch, he cried out in grateful recognition, " Be- 
 gorrah, but this is a Christian country ! " 
 
 ^ At the close of his eloquent essay, which bears the signiiicant title, 
 Ciinlisation: its Cause and its Cicre, Mr. Edward Carpenter says: — 
 
 " The present competitive society is more and more rajjidly becoming
 
 54 ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM [cii. iii 
 
 complete treatise on sociology. At present let me attempt to 
 distingiiisli its principal elements or constituents, using the 
 term to mean what distinguishes man from the animals and 
 what (to adopt a phrase I have suggested elsewhere ^) enables 
 mankind to progress independently of heredity and of mere 
 natural selection. 
 
 (1) First of all, civilisation implies control over the forces of 
 nature ; and greater civilisation implies that such control is 
 greater. Prom the discovery of how to make fire by rubbing 
 sticks together on to the inventions of the telegraph and the 
 telephone, man has been learning how to use nature as his 
 servant. Man, it has been suggested, might be defined as a 
 tool-making animal. (2) Secondly, language makes it possible 
 to transmit experience ; and when to language are added the 
 inventions of writing and printing, this power of bequeathing 
 ideas is immensely increased. A greater power of expressing 
 and of diffusing ideas is thus one mark of a higher degree of 
 civilisation. Man is a speaking animal ; and because a speaking- 
 animal, he is also a rational or thinking animal, for language 
 makes possible the psychological advance from particular images 
 or representations to general concepts or ideas. Reflection, 
 moreover, though it may among the great mass of human 
 beings be mainly occupied with matters of direct practical 
 necessity, can be employed also about everything in the 
 universe, and about man himself, though such reflection may 
 have only an indirect practical value or apparently none at all. 
 Thus science, philosophy, history are among the marks which 
 distinguish a civilised from an uncivilised people. The tales 
 and myths of primitive races are the germs from which they 
 spring. (3) Tliinli}', man has a delight in doing or making- 
 things which are of no practical utility, for the sheer delight of 
 doing or making them. This " play," or free purposeless use of 
 
 a mere dead formula and husk, within which tlio outlines of the new and 
 human society are already discernible. Simultaneously, and as if to 
 match this growth, a move towards Nature and Savagery is for the first 
 time taking place from within, instead of being forced upon society from 
 Avitliout." The words " for the first time " show a curious oblivion of 
 Itousseau, and of the Cynics. 
 
 * Darwinism and Politics. Ed. 2, p. 101. Cf. Weismann Essays upon 
 Ikrcditij (Engl, tr.), Vol. II. p. 51, where the editor of the translation, 
 Prof. E. B. Poulton, cites my definition, of which he approved when I 
 first hit upon it.
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM 55 
 
 control over the body and over surrounding object.'^, exists in 
 germ among the lower animals, though with them, except among 
 the very j^oung, it is mostly connected with sexual selection. 
 Among human beings it is the source of art. From the wild 
 dances and songs of the savage grow up music, poetry, the 
 drama ; from his attempts to adorn his person, his weapons, his 
 hut, or to represent the beasts he has seen or the gods he 
 believes in, are developed architecture, sculpture, painting. 
 Man is more than a mere imitative animal ; he is a creator, so 
 far as he is able. Art, then, is another mark of civilisation. 
 (4) Fourthly, men come to use their thinking and their making- 
 powers to regulate their relations with one another ; i.e. their 
 social structure comes to depend not merely on natural selection 
 operating among competing tribes or communities, but to 
 result in part from conscious attempts at organisation. In other 
 words, civilised man formulates definitely and becomes fully 
 conscious of the laws and institutions which have grown up in 
 his community, and thereby on the one hand deliberately 
 adopts habits of reverence for law, and on the other hand be- 
 comes capable of carrjdng out political, social, ethical, religious 
 reforms (or, at least, changes) in a way impossible to him at a 
 ruder stage of existence. Man is a political animal ; and the 
 use of written laws, which all may (potentially) come to know, 
 and the possibility of carrying out peacefully constitutional 
 changes, are marks of civilisation. The habit of " free govern- 
 ment,'' i.e. of living under institutions which are not looked on 
 as some alien authority imposed from without, or existing 
 merely because they have existed in the past, but which in 
 some considerable degree correspond to the saner and soberer 
 sentiments of the more socially minded and orderly members 
 of the community, is a mark of civilisation, not perhaps the 
 most obvious ; for people governing themselves have often been 
 behind those more despotically governed in some, if not all, of 
 the other characteristics of civilisation : but it is a mark which 
 is directly connected with the original meaning of the term. 
 To be a dvis is to be the citizen of a self-governing political 
 society, the highest form of which known to the ancients was 
 the city republic of the Hellenic world. Starting from a 
 similar self-governing town, the Romans first conquered and 
 then Romanised and civilised the less advanced races of the 
 Mediterranean w^orld, whilst they themselves assimilated a
 
 56 ROUSSEAU AND JiOUSSEAUISM [ch. hi 
 
 great part of that Hellenic culture which had originated in the 
 cities of Ionia, and liad reached its perfection in the city of 
 Athens, and which was kept alive and spread to east and Avest 
 from the cosmopolitan city of Alexandria. And when the in- 
 cursion of the northern barbarians broke down the fabric of 
 ancient civilisation, it was in Roman cities above all that some 
 fragments of it were sheltered, and it was in the self-governing 
 city republics of Italy and in the " free towns " of the German 
 empire, that art and the peaceful pursuits of secular life first 
 revived and flourished. Even the Church, which through 
 man}^ dark centuries represented the only force in "Western 
 Europe making for peace and order and the intellectual goods 
 of mankind, was the Roman Church, carrying on in a new 
 form the discipline and the organisation which had originated 
 in the Imperial City. Rousseau himself dedicates his second 
 indictment of civilisation — The Discourse on Inequality — ^to the 
 Republic of Geneva, of which he Avas proud to count himself 
 a citizen. Even Walt Whitman, with his love of fresh air 
 and with all the prairies of America before him, seems to turn 
 affectionately to the " populous pavements " of the close-packed 
 city that covers the island of Manhattan. 
 
 It is this connection of civilisation with city life that more 
 than anything else has caused the revolt against it. The 
 massing together of human beings makes some good things 
 possible, but makes the evils of human society more con- 
 spicuous.^ It has been noticed, moreover, by several students 
 of art and literature, that the love of the sights and sounds, 
 the quiet and peace of the country, does not enter prominently 
 into poetry and painting except after the rise of great cities. 
 Still more is this true with regard to the sentiment for the 
 wilder and more terrible aspects of nature. " The love of 
 Nature," it has been said by a subtle critic of Roman literature, • 
 '• is not, as wo might naturally expect it to be, a feeling much 
 experienced by those wlio live in constant contact and conflict 
 with its sterner forces, as by husbandmen, herdsmen, and 
 hunters ; nor is it developed consciously in primitive times or 
 unsophisticated races ; but it is the accompaniment of leisure, 
 
 ^ Cf. Plato, L(7w.s-, 111.078: '•How can we possibly suppose that those 
 who know nothing of all the good and. evil of cities could have attained 
 their full development, whothcx- of virtue or of vice ? "
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM 57 
 
 culture, and refinement of life.'' ^ Like many strong feelings, 
 it is due to reaction. 
 
 Undoubted!}' some races are more susceptible to the beauty 
 or impressiveness of natural scenery tlian others, the Celts 
 perhaps more than the Saxons, the Italians more than the 
 Greeks. Occupation, however, has probabl}^ in all cases more 
 to do with the matter than race : a people of herdsmen or 
 hunters are more likely to develop some taste for scenery 
 than a people engaged in agriculture. But the cultured 
 lover of nature is verj'' apt to mistake the home-sickness of 
 the mountaineer or of the fisherman, for a purely esthetic 
 appreciation of mountain and sea. Custom strongly affects 
 the feelings even of the most reflective and the most logical 
 minds : with simple and unsophisticated persons who have 
 gone through few changes in their surroundings, custom is 
 all-powerful.- It is said that a Shetlander, finding himself for 
 the first time in a boantiful woodland district, was filled with a 
 feeling of terrified oppression : he seemed unable to breathe, 
 and was afraid the trees would fall on him. His longing for the 
 sea and for his bare rocky islands was of the same kind as the 
 longing of many a city-bred person for the smooth pavement 
 and the smell of asphalt. There is probably also in most cases a 
 physical basis in the longing for sea and mountain — a longing 
 which many even of those who have lived chiefly in midland 
 plains can understand. Lungs accustomed to a fresher air 
 seem stifled amid leafy lanes and green meadows as well as 
 amid brick walls. When such ph3''sical feelings and the 
 associations derived from habit are left out of account, it will 
 be found that the genuinely assthetic love of the country is in 
 the main a product of city life. 
 
 All the fine arts, indeed, require the existence of city lift' for 
 their rise and growth. The landscape painter, when landscape 
 painting has once become an established form of art, may work 
 in the country, and may work best in the country, but his 
 pictures are painted for the town : and it is to the landscape 
 painter that we owe a great deal of our admiration of natural 
 scenery.- Prof. Weismann has pointed out that " nearly all 
 
 * Sellar, Vinjil, p. 47. On p. 4G, note, Mr. Sellar refers to two C-ennaii 
 writers, Woermann and Helbig. 
 
 " "Even such an analysis of natural beauty in tlie liicht of ])hysical 
 fact as has been attempted by lluskin in the J\Ioderii J'aiiitera is cliielly
 
 S8 ROUSSEAU AXD ROUSSEAUISM [ch. hi 
 
 tlie renowned (musical) composers and singers of the present 
 century have come from large towns." ^ Great buildings, 
 adorned with paintings and sculpture, may indeed be erected 
 in the country ; but it is only in large towns that there is 
 a sufficiently continuous demand for architecture and the 
 imitative arts, or sufficient opportunity for studying them. By 
 an extensive use of all modern inventions which diminish the 
 inconvenience of distance, future generations may be able to 
 combine, in a way we can only dream of, the advantages of 
 both town and country ; but those who wish to begin their 
 social revolution b}^ abolishing everything that did not exist in 
 the tw^elfth century, or in ancient Hellas, or in unsophisticated 
 Japan, or in the Grarden of Eden, or wherever and whenever 
 they place their golden age, are under a strange delusion if 
 they hope to live in a primeval forest with no governments, no 
 .schools, no institutions of any kind, and yet to hear the music 
 of Beethoven, or have their walls adorned with frescoes worthy 
 of the best age of Florence. Rousseau is more consistent than 
 Mr. William Morris or Mr. Edward Ccxrpenter : art must be 
 expelled from the ideal state of nature, along with science, 
 and along with government. 
 
 No element of civilisation is possible without the city. But 
 need the city be for ever wdiat the Avord is too apt to suggest 
 to us ? — a grimy wilderness of monotonous rows of sombre and 
 often bad brick, every chimney-pot contributing its pollution 
 to the atmosphere, the eyes met on all sides by flaring adver- 
 tisements of soap and pills and mustard, the ears stunned by 
 ceaseless discordant cries of the latest newspaper with the 
 latest murder, a pervading odour of horse-dung and of the filth 
 of ill-cared-for, overcrowded human beings, whilst the more 
 prosperous are arrayed in coats and hats and trousers that 
 make sculpture impossible or ludicrous; and beyond all the 
 dreary noises, beyond everything that offends the senses or 
 the taste, the ever-present picture of the ceaseless struggle for 
 existence. May we not rather call up a vision of a city, sug- 
 gested to us partially even now by some ancient towns, and by 
 
 directed to sliowing Low great artists have extended the boundaries of 
 so-called natural beautj^, by their superior insight into tlie expressive 
 capabilities of natural scenes and objects." — Bosauquet, History of 
 yEsthetic, p. 4. 
 
 ' Kssays upoa Heredity (Engl, trans.), Vol. II. p. 48.
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM 59 
 
 some parts of some modern towns— a city not too large, bnt of 
 sucli size that from the upper Avindows of the Town-hall the 
 fresh fields can he seen — a city Avith a smokeless sky and 
 clean streets, no shops, and above all no advertisements, but a 
 large central market for needful exchange, no one interested in 
 making any one buy what he or she does not want, handsome 
 buildings and large leafy spaces, all the inventions of science 
 used to diminish irksome labour, and all the wealth of art lavished 
 not on the gratification of private luxury, but on the adornment 
 of the property of the commonwealth ? But it is an odd way of 
 preparing such a commonwealth, to condemn civilisation as a 
 disease, to exalt ignorance above science, and the savage above 
 '■' the heir of all the ages." Every one of the elements or 
 materials of civilisation may be turned to a bad purpose : is 
 that a reason for wishing them destroyed ? On the same 
 principle we might well wish that Prometheus had kept his 
 <liscovery to himself. There is quite as good reason for 
 blaming him as for blaming James Watt or George Stephen- 
 son. 
 
 In this revolt against civilisation there are, however, un- 
 doubtedly important elements of truth. Civilisation, as it has 
 just been defined and analysed, consists of certain means or 
 instruments (material and intellectual) for human well-being; 
 and these means or instruments are capable of being inherited 
 in the legal or social, not in the biological sense of inheritance. 
 But what is properly an instrument may come to be regarded 
 as if it were an end in itself. Tools and ornaments and insti- 
 tutions were made for man, and not man for tools and orna- 
 ments and institutions ; and yet the individual may become 
 the slave of the things he has created or, more likely, of 
 the things he has inherited. The miser who accumulates coin 
 is an abnormal product of half-civilisation, and is recognised 
 as such by every one except himself: what is not so generally 
 recognised is the slavery of the ordinary civilised man and 
 woman to clothes, which have to be varied when there is no 
 need, and to customs which change or do not change quite 
 irrespective of use or convenience — all this implying wasteful 
 expenditure and unnecessary fatigue on the part of those who 
 are supposed to enjoy the full benefits of civilisation, and 
 excessive toil on the part of those who do not. Civilisation is 
 not evil in itself, but because its products are so unequally
 
 6o ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM [ch. hi 
 
 distributed and so irrationally nsed. Ai2,'ain, the mere fact of 
 social inheritance, whilst aiding- enormously the advance of 
 humanity, contains in it the possibility of danger. It implies 
 to a ver}^ great extent a cessation of natural selection. Thus, 
 what is in many respects a highly civilised race, may be- 
 come more and more phj^sically enfeebled, till it falls a prey 
 to internal degeneration, and to the attack of some rudely 
 equipped, but vigorous barbarian invaders. 
 
 This is the too familiar history of the great empires of the 
 old woild. But the success of the barbarian does not prove 
 the absolute superiority of barbarism over civilisation. The 
 healthiness and strength of the barbarian, as of the wild 
 beast, are due simply to the ruthless action of natural selection. 
 The savage (if the paradox may be excused) is free from 
 disease, just because he so readily falls a victim to it. Epi- 
 demics which are comparatively mild among civilised peoples 
 rage with frightful virulence among people living under 
 more primitive conditions. Tribes engaged in constant war- 
 fare are exposed to a double process of natural selection : the 
 tribe possessed of the greatest strength, endurance, and 
 courage succeeds best, and kills off the others ; and within a 
 warlike tribe the more successful warrior is the more success- 
 ful man. Peace is generally accounted a blessing, and is 
 usual!}' lauded by those who preach the return to nature ; but 
 peace means a cessation of natural selection, and consequent 
 decay in the average physique. AVar and hunting are the 
 only honourable pursuits among the finer savage races, and 
 both pursuits ensure a high standard of physical excellence ; 
 but the killing of men, the capture of women, and the chasing 
 of beasts are not occupations admired by our humanitarian 
 neo-savages. Infanticide and the habit of killing off the aged 
 are primitive modes of artificial selection. But these methods 
 of social salvation also would probably be reprobated by the 
 higher barbarism of the present day. Even the physical 
 vigour of savage, compared with civilised, races is frequently 
 over-estimated, and for the power of triumphing over natural 
 difficulties more than physical vigour is needed. An autho- 
 rity, quoted by Mr. Edward Carpenter himself, in an appendix 
 to his indictment of civilisation, admits as much: ^'•\\\ 
 endurance the African savage beats us hollow (except trained 
 athletes). , . . But for sudden emergencies they are no-
 
 cir. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUIS.U 6i 
 
 where." ^ And even for tliose forms of endurance which 
 require "pluck" as well as vigour, it may be questioned 
 whether the civilised man is not as a rule superior. To im- 
 prove the average physical well-being of modern humanit}^, 
 it is a violent remedy to strip off our clothes, pull down our 
 houses and expose ourselves to the sunshine, which, in this 
 region of the world, " Nature " so often fails to provide. A 
 diet exclusively of fruit and grains, no government, no medical 
 science, are hardly the proper prescriptions for the sufferings of 
 our age.^ The Greeks, for whose art Mr. Carpenter expresses 
 admiration, were certainly not destitute either of government 
 or of science, and, although living in a milder climate than 
 ours, they did not restrict themselves to fruit and grains. The 
 Athenians of the great artistic age are the very type for all 
 time of a civilised people ; and their civilisation assuredly did 
 
 ' Quoted from Mr. H. B. Cotterill in Civilisation, its Canse and its 
 Cure. p. 50. 
 
 - " It raa\^ be noted," says Mr. Carpenter {Civilisation, etc., p. 38), '• tliat 
 foods of the seed kind — by which I mean all manner of fruits, nuts, 
 tubers, grains, eggs, etc. (and I may include milk in its various forms of 
 butter, cheese, curds, and so forth), not only contain by their nature the 
 elements of life in their most condensed forms, but have the additional 
 advantage that the^' can be appropriated without injury to any living 
 creature — for even the cabbage may inaudibly scream when torn up by 
 the roots and boiled, but the strawberry «.s7r.s* us to take of its fruit, and 
 paints it red expressly that we may see and devour it! Both of which 
 considerations must convince us that this kind of food is most fitted to 
 develop the kernel of man's life." "Man's life," I suppose, is a nut to 
 crack ; but I doubt if Mr. Carpenter lias done it successfully. One is glad 
 to see, however, that eggs have a better claim to be eaten than cabbages. 
 This is a mitigated vegetarianism. But are" milk, butter, cheese, curds, 
 etc.," " seeds " ? And what if there be mites on the cheese ? And if eggs 
 oi fowls may bo taken without sin against Nature, why not the roe of 
 fishes, when it can be removed without injuring the developed fish (for 
 it is apparently only the fully developed animal tliatthis reformed science 
 holds to be " living ") ? These are some interesting problems in casuistry 
 for those who would conscientiously apply the Law of Nature. As to 
 .strawberries vefsns cabbages, it is not for us that the strawberry paints 
 itself red, but for the bird who will help to spread its seeds. And the 
 market gardener who cultivates fruits to such perfection that the seeds arc 
 almost absent is surely violating Nature's holy plan. 
 
 Tlie late Professor Lorimer, in his interesting development of the idea 
 of Xatiirrecht, speaks of the " rights" of the "last rose of summer" not 
 to b3 plucked {Institutes of Laic, p. 82G;. What becomes of the riglits of 
 the ugly weeds in a garden ? Still, Professor Lorimor's conception of the 
 Law of Nature at least does not dethrone man from his dominion over 
 the creatures.
 
 62 ROUSSEAU AND EOUSSEAUIS.U [en. m 
 
 not lack its dark side any more than ours. He who would 
 reall}' lead us towards the promised land of an ideal domocracy, 
 must not merely lead us out from among the flesh-pots of 
 Egyptian bondage, and leave us without a guide and without 
 the tables of the law in the wilderness of savager}' — a sure 
 prey to the strongest and least scrupulous amongst ourselves 
 or our neighbours. 
 
 The problem is a harder one : can a general equality of social 
 conditions be attained without the loss of any of those instru- 
 ments of human well-being which we wish to be enjoyed by 
 all, instead of half-enjoyed or abused by the few ? In other 
 Avords, is civilisation possible without a slave class, and without 
 " free " competition ? If it is not possible, there are a good 
 many who will think democracy is a barbarian invasion, worse 
 than that of the Goths and Vandals. Some of us, however, 
 do believe and hope that, as in that older invasion the bar- 
 barian was gradually conquered by the civilitas he at first 
 despised and hated, ^ so in the new society which will grow up, 
 as the barriers of caste are broken through by the peaceful 
 Aveapons of education and legislation, the new inheritors of an 
 old civilisation will glory in the citizenship to which they are 
 admitted, and in treasures of thought and knowledge and 
 art to which all who choose may have access, along with 
 sufficient leisure in which to use their opportunities ; nor will 
 the aristocrat and the hourgeois go without their due meed of 
 praise for having attained and kept alive among themselves 
 ideals of culture, and for supplying from among their own 
 
 ' Cf. the passage fromOrosias, Ht'st., YII. 43, quoted by Mr. Hodgkin in 
 his Theodoi'ic,-p. 4. Orosins tells how Ataulfus, brother-in-law and suc- 
 cessor of Alaric, the first capturer of Rome, " was intimate with a certain 
 citizen of Narbonne, a grave, wise, and religious person, who had served 
 with distinction imder Theodosins, and often remarked to him that in 
 the first ardour of his youth he had longed to obliterate the Roman name 
 and turn all the Roman lands into an Empire which should be, and 
 siiould be called, the Empire of the Goths, so that what used to be known 
 as Romania should now be Gothia, and that he, Ataulfus, should be in 
 the world what Cresar Augustus had been. But now that he had proved 
 by long experience that the Goths, on account of their unbridled barbai-- 
 ism, could not bo induced to obey the laws, and yet that, on the other 
 hand, there must be laws, since without them the Commonwealth would 
 cease to be a Commonwealth, he had chosen, for his part at any rate, 
 that he would seek the glory of renewing and increasing the Roman 
 name by the arms of his Gothic followers, and would be remembered by 
 posterity as the restorer of Rome, since he could not be its changer."
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM (st, 
 
 members the very leaders and spokesmen of democracy in its 
 attack on a civilisation wliicli seems evil, not because there is 
 too much of it, but because it is accessible to too small a portion 
 of mankind. 
 
 As to the burden of civilised life on those Avho do now share 
 its advantages, is not that largely due to the barbaric or patri- 
 archal fashion in which we still manage things ? We are 
 only " citizens " in a small fraction of ourselves ; for the rest, 
 we try, if we can, in our separate households to keep up a 
 museum or an art gallery of an inferior kind. What bar- 
 barians we may seem some day — every household doing its 
 own cookery ! Older generations of housewives would have 
 been as much horrified at sending their clothes to a public 
 laundry, or at getting their bread from a baker, as their suc- 
 cessors are at the idea of public kitchens. Those who boast 
 themselves most sturdily "individualists " are generally those 
 whose social ideal is most completely of the patriarchal tj'pe. 
 ''The Englishman's house is his castle" — an ideal borrowed 
 from the barbaric isolation of the household of the robber 
 baron. The tent of the Arab sheikh, the cave of the Cyclops, 
 the den of the wild beast with its mate and its cubs — these 
 are the ideals that are preferred to the life of the Athenian 
 citizen.^ If the householder has to be king, high priest, 
 finance minister, foreign secretary, minister of war, besides 
 earning his income, i.e. being his own general, waging war 
 on rival potentates, while his consort is at the same time 
 queen, minister of the interior, diplomatist, master of the 
 ceremonies, minister of fine art, minister of education, be- 
 sides being mother of some of her subjects, nurse of some of 
 them, and foreman in a domestic factory, no wonder that 
 little time and energy remain over for them to " possess their 
 souls before they die." Yet does not such a description answer 
 fairly well to the model British well-to-do professional or 
 business man, and the model British matron ? To shake off 
 the burden of things upon us, we may, of course, lower our 
 standard of living in the intellectual,- and not merely in the 
 economic sense ; but a more systematic division of labour and 
 
 ' Le Plaj' consciously and deliberately finds his ideal society among 
 some of tlie pastoral peoples of Central Asia. {VEcole de la palx Sociale, 
 pp. 20 .seq.) 
 
 '^ We need a word to correspond to the German gei'itig.
 
 64 ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAU ISM [ch. hi 
 
 a more complete organisation Avould be a solution tliat would 
 involve less sacrifice of the higher goods of life. 
 
 True, the physical basis is primary. More and more we 
 discover, often too late, how much happiness and usefulness 
 depend on health and vigour. Man must not be content to be 
 a fine animal alone ; but of all tools a well-equipped body is 
 the least dispensable. So far, all moralists and social reformers 
 would nowadays agree with the cult of " the friendly and 
 flowing savage " (^I do not the least know what that second 
 epithet means : I wonder if Walt Whitman knew). We have 
 shaken off," in words at least, that contempt for the vile body 
 which has been the worst legacy of Oriental and ecclesiastical 
 asceticism. But for that deterioration which is due to the 
 shelter of civilisation and the consequent partial cessation of 
 natural selection, is the only remedy to be found in a return to 
 the savage state, i.e. to the unchecked play of the coarse and 
 cruel action of the struggle for existence ? Of course, nothing 
 is to be said against, and everything for, an occasional plajdng 
 at savages by way of a good holiday — weather permitting. 
 The passion for hunting among our well-to-do "barbarians," as 
 Matthew Arnold called them, is a perverted form of a healthy 
 instinct. The serious direct struggle of the savage with 
 nature is imitated in play as the relaxation of civilised life. 
 By all means let us have a crusade against unhealthy, incon- 
 venient, and ugly clothing, let us prohibit starch (physical 
 and social), let us set up a guillotine, not for heads, but for top- 
 hats ; but let our revolutionary tribunal be occupied, not by a 
 carelessly modelled figure of Nature, but by those products of 
 civilisation, men of science and artists. Instead of dccr3ung 
 the modern science of medicine, would it not be wiser to turn 
 its practitioners into an " established church " with the primary 
 duty of preventuig illness, with compulsory sanitary laws to 
 back them up, and with power to prohibit the parentage of the 
 unfit ? Either natural or rational artificial selection must be 
 at Avork — at present there is a great deal of irrational artificial 
 selection — or else a race must deteriorate under civilisation. It 
 is well that people should be compelled to face these alterna- 
 tives ; and the assailants of civilisation deserve our gratitude 
 for forcing the problem on reluctant minds. But when these 
 " advanced thinkers " devote so much of their energy to abus- 
 ing the very sciences to which we must look for aid, when in
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM 65 
 
 the name of Nature they vilify the patient researches of the 
 bacteriologist, and, as anti-vivisectionists, anti-vaccinationists 
 and anti-everything-that-is-scientific, give literary counte- 
 nance to the suspicion with which the superstitious and the 
 ignorant have always regarded science, they make one dread 
 that the remedy is still far off, and that Plato for a long time 
 to come will be called a foolish dreamer for thinking that the 
 wise should rule. 
 
 Anarchists are of three kinds. First of all, there is the old- 
 fashioned Radical who repeats the revolutionary creed of 1789 
 in changed times, to whom an association called a government 
 is an object of suspicion, whilst an association called a joint- 
 stock company is an object of admiration. This old-fashioned 
 Radical does not think himself a survival, but imagines that 
 he has the verdict of the newest science on his side. He 
 would abolish legislation, but would leave the judicial func- 
 tions of government to enforce what he calls natural rights, 
 but what are really the legal and customary rights resulting 
 from ancient legislation or want of legislation. He professes 
 to give every one a fair start, but does not notice that the 
 runners are unequally weighted. He calls himself an indi- 
 vidualist, and is only a half-hearted Anarchist. His anarchy is 
 anarchy based on the existing economic structure of society. 
 He believes in Nature, but forgets that it is a Nature that has 
 been operating for ages among human beings. Nature to him 
 really means human society under a completely triumphant 
 " Manchester School." He would contribute to the ameliora- 
 tion of the species by abolishing all sanitary legislation, but 
 would perhaps lend the tender-hearted private philanthropist 
 a free hand in encouraging the propagation of beggars in order 
 to give scope to his altruistic sentiments. 
 
 Secondly, there is the thorough-going Anarchist, who does not 
 consider government a necexi^anj evil, but an evil altogether. 
 He is produced, as might be expected, most easily in Russia. 
 Outside Russia he is a much more amiable person than those 
 who belong to the first species ; he has an intense belief in the 
 natural goodness of man, combined with an equally intense 
 belief in the badness of all the institutions that man has ever 
 produced. He often calls himself a Socialist. He is a Cynic 
 without cynicism. While the first type has very little rever- 
 ence for the past, this milder type has a great love for some 
 
 N. R. F
 
 66 ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM [ch. hi 
 
 past age, provided it be sufficiently remote ; and while in his 
 own age he can only see darkness, he ignores everything but 
 the bright side in his chosen period. He would make us all 
 healthy, happy, and wise, by reverting to the life of savages, 
 forgetful that the old cycle would be sure to repeat itself, and 
 that our own evil " civilisation period " would either be for- 
 gotten altogether, or would only be remembered in an idealised 
 form, just as he thinks of the Iroquois, or the Athenian, or the 
 mediaeval Englishman, without recalling the dark shadows in 
 the picture. 
 
 Lastly, there is a species of criminal, either a reversion to 
 the savage type, or produced by the cruelty of half-civilisa- 
 tion acting on a sensitive or unbalanced nature. He borrows 
 the language of the previous tj^pe, with whom he is apt to be 
 confused by the careless. To one branch of science only he 
 is not hostile, and that is the chemistry of explosives. He 
 makes war on society by killing and maiming at random. He 
 is perhaps able to die like a martyr, or a hero of melodrama, 
 but is probably half insane. Such unfortunate and dangerous 
 beings have existed at all times. In some communities and in 
 some periods they would be religious fanatics. In modern 
 Europe and North America they call themselves Anarchists, 
 and sometimes obtain mistaken sympathy from Anarchists 
 of the harmless sort, and from other sentimental persons. 
 Assassins who risk their own lives to kill a tyrant, or a 
 strongly guarded person whom they sincerely believe to be a 
 tyrant, and therefore a noxious kind of beast, may occasionally 
 command our respect, and in some extreme cases our admira- 
 tion ; but the dynamiter deserves nothing but a fair trial and 
 a quick death, or permanent detention in a lunatic asylum. 
 
 In all its forms Anarchism is an example of what Hegel calls 
 " abstract thinking," that is to say, the habit necessary in 
 ordinary conversation, and encouraged by the unavoidable 
 limitations of language, of regarding one aspect of a subject to 
 the exclusion of all the others, the habit of taking up a formula 
 which may be true enough in its context, isolating it from the 
 surroundings which made it valuable, and carrying it out re- 
 gardless of consequences. In its extremest shape " abstract 
 thinking " is monomania, which may often take a criminal 
 form. In its more familiar aspects, it is that narrow, one-sided 
 logic which produces religious or social bigotr}^ — a character-
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM 67 
 
 istic which the most wildly heterodox may share with the most 
 rigidl}^ conventional. " Faddists " are abstract thinkers, and 
 so are all those whose acceptance of formulas is not tempered 
 by a genial disposition or by a sense of humour — the only safe 
 substitute for a sound system of metaphysics. Shelley's 
 " Notes " to Queen Mah are an exposition, in very temperate 
 language on the whole, of Anarchism of the kind which I 
 placed second. They preach " the return to Nature " precisely 
 in the Anarchist sense. Abstract thinking is apt to extend 
 itself from one matter into another. In a disciple of Shelley's 
 "principles" may be found another very good example of 
 " abstract thinking." Mr. H. S. Salt^ thinks that to admire 
 Shelley's poetry, while apologising for his " social heresies," 
 is an untenable position. This is a terrible doctrine : may we 
 not eat flesh and yet admire the " Ode to the Skylark," or the 
 " Ode to the West Wind," or " Adonais " ? A small portion of 
 "Queen Mab" is perhaps the only part of Shelley's verse that for 
 its thorough appreciation needs an acceptance of the " central 
 underlying convictions " of the poet respecting the necessity 
 of abstinence from animal food, etc. Certainly a person who 
 abhors the mere suggestion of any alteration in the structure 
 of society will find a good deal to offend him in Shelle}^, and 
 may prefer a " safer " poet ; but how little of what is best and 
 grandest in literary art depends for our enjoyment of it on the 
 social theories of the writer ? - Why, even if we turn to works 
 professedly controversial (which the best poetry never is), ma}'' 
 only Anglicans admire Hooker and Jeremy Taylor, may onh'' 
 Roman Catholics admire Pascal and Bossuet — and not both 
 together, may only Baptists admire Bunyan ? Must we accept 
 "the central underlying convictions " of Newman or of Carlj-le 
 
 ' Shelley\s Principles, p. 14. 
 
 ^ The principle, or " cant," of " art for art's sake " is likewise a result 
 of " abstract thinking" : it involves an abstract use of the distinction be- 
 tween style and matter, between treatment and subject. But we must 
 not ignore the vinequal development of even the greatest of mortals. An 
 exquisite stylist may be a somewhat superficial thinker — at least on some 
 matters, and a master of psychological analysis, or a teacher of most ex- 
 cellent and necessarj^ doctrine, may fall into terrible dulness, obscurity, or 
 cacophony. It is said that Tennyson once said of Browning : " He is a 
 great poet, but he does not understand the glory of words,"— a consider- 
 able qualification in speaking of a poet. Shelley did understand " the 
 glory of words " ; but that is not in itself a sufficient ground for setting 
 him up as an infallible authority in ethics or politics.
 
 68 ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM [ch. hi 
 
 to take delight in them as writers '? Thank the Muses, in the 
 Catholic temple of Art the voice of controversy is hushed, and 
 the disputants stand side by side in their niches, as their books 
 may stand side by side on our shelves, and as their dust may 
 rest reconciled in the peace of the grave. 
 
 But to return to " nature '' — I mean to the uses of the term — 
 — the Rousseauist antithesis between nature and man is a 
 typical example of " abstract thinking." "When Cowper says, 
 *' God made the country and man made the town " ^ (substitut- 
 ing " God " for Nature, in deference to his own orthodoxy), he 
 utters what quite represents the usual frame of mind of those 
 who preach the "return to nature," but what contains at once 
 very curious theology and very curious history. If man made 
 the town, who then made man ? Man, acting under the 
 stimulus of wants and impulses implanted in him by " nature," 
 has manipulated some of the material with which " nature " has 
 supplied him, and a town hideous or beautiful, healthy or un- 
 healthy, is the result. And what of the country ? Man, it is true, 
 has written no furrows on the ocean's brow, he has left no foot- 
 prints on the eternal snows ; but what else in "nature" has man 
 not affected, directly or indirectly ? What was " the country " 
 of which Cowper thought? English hedgerows, pollard willows, 
 waving corn-fields. Has not man made these in almost the same 
 sense as that in which he makes a great cathedral, when he 
 lifts " out of the populous city, grey cliffs of lonely stone into 
 the midst of sailing birds and silent air " ? ~ The difference is 
 one of degree only. These " English elms " own their Italian 
 origin — was it the Romans who brought them first ? — by their 
 seeds seldom ripening under our colder skies. Not onlj^ the 
 fauna and flora, but the very climate of a country is affected by 
 the action of man ; the rainfall is increased or diminished by 
 planting or by cutting down forests. Mr. Carpenter recognises 
 this in order to take a fresh opportunity of blaming man. "Our 
 climate is greatly of our own creation. . . . It is we who 
 have covered the lands with a pall of smoke, and are walking 
 to our own funerals under it ! " ^ Yet the climate of Britain was 
 probably damper even than now, before marshes were drained 
 and forests cut down. Tacitus tells us that " the sky is filthy 
 
 ' The. Task near the end of " The Sofa." 
 
 ^ Ruskin, Seven Lamps of Architechire (" The Lamp of Power"). 
 
 2 Civilisation, its Cause and its Cure, p. 37.
 
 CH. Ill] ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM 69 
 
 with frequent showers and fogs." ^ Birmingham and Man- 
 cliester can hardly be blamed for that. Adapting Cowper's 
 lines, we should have to say, " God made the fog, man diminished 
 it, and then made what was left dirty and deadly." But wh}-, 
 it may be asked, in this apportioning of blame, did not Nature 
 provide us with only smokeless coal ? Why should New York 
 be blessed above Liverpool '? 
 
 When people appeal to " Nature," they appeal arbitrarily to 
 what they happen to like or approve. Shelley, quoted by Mr. 
 Salt, admonishes us to live " like the beasts of the forest, and the 
 birds of the air " ; ^ but loJiich beasts and birds ? We should 
 hardly become mild vegetarians by imitating lions and eagles. 
 As a rule, animal-lovers take their notions of animals largely 
 from dogs ; but the dog, as he exists among us now, is almost 
 entirely an artificial animal. He has been selected for countless 
 generations for the sake of diverse qualities which happened to 
 be useful or agreeable to man. He is a parasite of human 
 society. The cat is less popular simply because she is still to a 
 great extent in " a state of nature " ; she is a truer disciple of 
 Jean Jacques. 
 
 How many of the plants on which the advocate of natural 
 diet would have us subsist in this chilly climate are them- 
 selves " natural " ? Wheat, barley, oats, cabbage, turnips, 
 peas, beans, apples and pears (except the little-eaten wild 
 apple) — I need not prolong the list — are any of these in their 
 "natural " condition ? All are due to artificial selection ; they 
 have been tampered with by man for his own convenience. If 
 we " return to nature," how can we permit such violations of 
 nature as grafting, as pruning, and the transference of plants 
 out of their " natural " habitat ? 
 
 When Nature is contrasted with man, it is not fair to single 
 out all that we happen to like on the one side and all that we 
 happen to dislike on the other. Man's action on nature has 
 been twofold. If he has created the horrors of the " black 
 country," he must also get the credit of having turned wilder- 
 nesses into gardens, and pestilential marshes into fertile fields 
 on other parts of the earth's surface. The remedy for the evils 
 of our civilisation is not a return to nature, but to use all our 
 power over nature and all our power over human nature to 
 
 ^ A(/)'icola, c. 12 : " Cuelum crebris itubribus et nebulis fujduin." 
 - Shelley's Principles, p. 52.
 
 70 ROUSSEAU AND ROUSSEAUISM [ch. hi 
 
 make the world a better place to live in than we have found it. 
 The Republic needs not chemists only, but all the sciences and 
 all the arts and much more of them than have yet existed. 
 
 There is no absolute gap between Nature and man. What 
 is dumb and blind in the struggle of plant and animal gains a 
 consciousness of its meaning and a voice to express its needs in 
 human society. And if we look for traces of Divine benevo- 
 lence in the world, we shall find them less obscurely written in 
 the records of human society than in the ceaseless warfare 
 which has moulded the forms and the habits of organisms lower 
 than man.^ The outlook would indeed be very hopeless for 
 us, if the history of civilisation were all a movement away from 
 the best life of which we are capable. It is certainly easiest to 
 see the defects in what is nearest us ; but it is a very elemen- 
 tary and childish form of criticism which sees only the defects.^ 
 The good and sound elements are our only starting-point for 
 further progress. 
 
 1 To a friend who preferred the beauty of nature to the insides of 
 churches, a pious monitor is said to have remarked : " The fields and 
 the trees may tell you about the power of the Creator; but what can they 
 tell you of redeeming love ? " There is an element of philosophical truth 
 in this " evangelical " objection to the worship of mere nature, as if that 
 were the only revelation of Deity. 
 
 The philosopher-king, Fi'ederick the Great of Prussia, has expressed 
 this philosophical truth very well. " Man," he says in answer to 
 Holbach's atheism, " is a reasonable being produced by nature. Nature 
 [including man, of course], then, must be infinitely more intelligent than 
 he." Similarly his friend Voltaire : '' To produce without intelligence 
 entities which possess it ! Is that conceivable ? " (quoted by Mr. F. 
 Espinasse in his Life of Voltaire, London, 1892, p. 172). The argument, 
 however, becomes much stronger if we take account of all man's 
 *' spiritual nature," as well as his intelligence. I may refer to what I 
 have said in Darwin and Ileyel, p. 173. 
 
 2 Cf. Hegel, Werke, VIII. p. 323 {Fhilosophie des Bechts, § 268). "Fault, 
 finding is eas^' ; what is hard is to recognise the good and the inner 
 necessity in a thing. ' A little learning ' always begins with fault-find- 
 ing : completed culture sees in everything the positive (really valid) 
 element." I have paraphrased, rather than translated literally.
 
 CHAPTER lY 
 
 DE DIVISIONE NATUE^ 
 
 In this chapter I do not propose to attempt to construct a 
 philosophical system, as the title might suggest, borrowed as it 
 is from the great work of the light of the dark ages, Joannes 
 Scotus or Erigena — John the Irish Scot. M. Littre in his 
 dictionary arranges the meanings of the French word Nature 
 under twenty-nine heads. ^ I shall only try to group together 
 for convenience the principal usages of the word which concern 
 us in political science. What is said here will therefore be 
 to some extent recapitulation of some parts of the preceding 
 chapters. 
 
 I. First of all, there is that use of the term "Nature" in which 
 it stands for the totality of what exists, for the whole universe. 
 "Within this general meaning there are distinctions of funda- 
 mental importance for philosophy and theology ; but with 
 most of these we are not here directly concerned. Thus we 
 may distinguish between {a) Nature as a principle underlying 
 and explaining (if or so far as it is possible for us to know it) all 
 the particular phenomena of space and time, and (h) Nature as 
 meaning simply the sum or series of these particular phenomena. 
 This is the distinction which in scholastic phraseology is known 
 as that between (a) Natura naturans and (6) Natura naturata 
 We may indeed speak of " Nature doing this or that," per- 
 sonifying and unifying the forces of the universe, without 
 intending to commit ourselves to any definite theory as to the 
 ultimate explanation of things ; but whenever we speak of 
 Nature in such a way, we are more or less consciously speaking 
 of Natura naturam^ of Nature as dynamic, as operating and 
 operating for definite purposes, however much we may qualify 
 our personification by warning others and ourselves that our 
 language is metaphorical. When we speak of Nature as simply 
 
 ' It sliould be noted, however, that such uses as Cotellette nature are 
 counted separately. 
 
 71
 
 72 DE DIVISIONE NATURE [ch. iv 
 
 a collection of objects, in whose presence we find ourselves and 
 which form the materials for scientific inquiry as to how they 
 stand related to one another, we are speaking of Katura 
 natiirata. 
 
 Xatura naturans maj' be identified, as in Spinoza's philosophy, 
 with God ; or God may be conceived of as transcendent, but 
 not immanent, i.e. as distinct from Natura naturans (the con- 
 ception of much popular theism), or as both immanent and 
 transcendent, i.e. identical with Xatura nafurani^^ and yet 
 having a kind of existence over and above what can be ex- 
 pressed and understood b}^ such identification (a conception at 
 once more philosophical, and more orthodox) ; or the term God 
 may be expressly avoided, because of its associations with 
 particular religions and dogmatic theologies, and Xatura natu- 
 rans may be called the Unknown, or even (dogmatically) the 
 Unknowable, and otherwise allowed only as a sometimes 
 convenient metaphor.^ 
 
 When we speak of the " laws of nature," we are thinking of 
 Xatura naturata as produced by Xatura naturans. However care- 
 ful a scientific man may be to explain that by "laws of Nature " 
 
 ' " Nature is divided bj' Scotus Erigena into four kinds : — (1) The 
 Natui-e creating and not created, viz. God as tlie source of all being; (2) 
 that creating and created, viz. the primordial causes or Platonic Ideas, 
 constituting the intelligible world ; (3) that created and not creating, 
 viz. the effects of these causes, constituting the sensible world of be- 
 coming, time and space ; (4) that neither creating nor created, viz. God 
 considered as the supreme and unchangeable unity into which all things 
 return." I quote this abstract of De Divisione Naturce, i. or ii. 1, from 
 a very lucid and interesting paper on that little-known book by Mr. 
 Clement C. J. Webb, in the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. 
 II. No. 1, Pt. ii. p. 125. Obviously (3) in this list is identical with Natura 
 naturata, as just explained. (1) and (2) are identical with Natura 
 naturans, though they make a distinction, which is very commonly 
 recognised, between God as the ultimate " first cause " and the '" laws 
 of nature " (or " thoughts of God," as Kepler called them) by which He 
 works. In (4) the conception is one not so familiar to popular Christian 
 theology ; it is the Aristotelian conception of God as the " final cause " 
 of the process of the universe, form apart from all matter, which "moves 
 all things not as an efficient cause, but as the object of desire." Erigena, 
 in Neo-Platonic fashion, represents God in this sense {i.e. not as the 
 Creator, but as God the Father, i.e. God as He is in His own essence) as 
 " the One " of which we can as truly denj" as assert any predicate. Here 
 is a meeting-point, which may to some be unexpected, between mediaeval 
 mysticism and that Kantian criticism from which latter-day " agnosti- 
 cism " is descended without always being aware of its parentage.
 
 CH. iv] DE DIVISIONE NATURE 73 
 
 lie means onl}' "generalisations as to what does as a matter of 
 fact happen " (or, more properly, " statements of what, under 
 certain conditions, would happen " ; for mere generalisations as 
 to what does happen are " empirical laws " in distinction from 
 "laws of nature " in which some causation, i.e. necessary or in- 
 varirt6/e connection, is asserted)— however careful a scientific 
 man may be to de-personalise his conception, he is very apt, 
 and his hearers and echoes are certain, to think of "laws" as if 
 they were commands issued by a superior to an obedient set of 
 subjects. Hence people see no inherent absurdity in talking 
 about " interferences with the laws of nature " — whether they 
 picture the sovereign of the universe, on grave emergencies, 
 issuing special "orders," dispensing some portion of his sub- 
 jects from their habitual obedience, or whether they imagine 
 human beings acting in such a wa}^ as to violate the commands 
 which Nature has imposed on them. That is to say, in ordi- 
 nary metaphorical or picture-thinking, the laws of nature may 
 be imaged, either as general commands imposed on natiina 
 naturafa, or as general commands imposed by natura naturans. 
 I need not here enter into the question of the proper definition 
 of "law "in its political or legal sense. Admitting that the 
 primary and historically essential element in " law " is not 
 command but custom, it still remains true that all human laws 
 may be regarded as commands of a political superior (in the 
 fashion which almost all English jurists have adopted from 
 Bentham and Austin), and that even as generally observed 
 customs they differ essentially from laws of nature. A human 
 law states what is expected to be done, or what is usually 
 done ; but the expectation may not be realised, the custom may 
 be broken through. Laws of nature are, in the strictest sense, 
 inviolable, i.e. there is no meaning in talking of violating them. 
 When a law of nature appears to be violated, this only shows 
 that it has not been correctly stated. If the conditions are 
 altered, the effect juusf be different. "When people speak of 
 breaking laws of nature, they mean breaking some maxim of 
 health, prudence, etc., based upon, or supposed to be based 
 upon, a knowledge of the way in which nature works. To the 
 mischief caused by this confusion between laws of nature and 
 human laws, I have already referred. The phrase " economic 
 laws," when used strictly, implies that economic facts are being- 
 studied by the help of the conceptions applicable to all phe-
 
 74 DE DIVISIONE NATUR.E [ch. iv 
 
 nomena in space and time ; the phrase " economic laws " im- 
 plies the assumption, necessary in all the sciences, that, given 
 the like cause, the like effect mind follow (does invariaft??/ 
 follow^ — they come to the same thing ; the word '' invariable" 
 is only a device by which the empiricist conceals from himself 
 the element of necessity involved in causal connection). But 
 because the subject-matter of economic science is human 
 society regarded in certain aspects, the confusion is fatally 
 easy which permits even careful writers to speak of " vio- 
 lating economic laws," " attempting to over-ride laws of 
 Nature by acts of Parliament," etc. 
 
 II. Secondly, within " Nature," in this widest sense, which 
 includes all human life and conduct, and all the works of man, 
 we are very commonly accustomed to make the distinction 
 between (1) what man does and (2) what exists, or is thought 
 to exist (for here the difference is not always recognised) in- 
 dependently of, and apart from, what man does. We call the 
 former set of phenomena " human," " social," or " artificial," 
 and the latter alone, in antithesis to them, " natural." 
 
 III, Thirdly, closely connected with this last use of " Nature " 
 is a use of it which extends into the human sphere. By the 
 " natural " may be meant what is " original " as opposed to 
 what is " acquired " afterwards, as the result either of agencies, 
 conscious or unconscious, external to the organism or thing 
 affected, or of some effort made voluntarily or spontaneously 
 by the organism itself. Thus we distinguish a man's 
 " natural " from his " acquired " powers ; his " natural " ten- 
 dencies from the character he has acquired owing to his own 
 conduct and the environment in which he has been placed. 
 When, however, we speak of a " natural " manner as op- 
 posed to an affected manner, the meaning of natural is a little 
 different; for human beings can hardly be said to start with or 
 to inherit manners, though they may inherit tendencies, such 
 as a self-assertive or a yielding temperament, a capacity or in- 
 capacity for imitation, etc., which may make certain manners 
 more easily acquired than others. By natural manners we 
 mean manners which do not suggest effort or self-conscious- 
 ness, so that in such a phrase there is more of the contrast 
 between natural and artificial (the second sense of Nature) 
 than of the contrast between original and acquired ; but the 
 notions of artificiality and acquisition run into one another,
 
 CH. iv] DE D I VISION E NATUR.E 75 
 
 and so also do the two meanings of " natural." Such a phrase, 
 however, as "natural manners" suggests, further, the idea of 
 Tightness or fitness. They are what the person using the 
 phrase considers the proper kind of manners to have ; and on 
 the question of what exact degree of artificiality is allowable 
 and right, and what exactly is artificiality, people would differ 
 very much. So here we get an element, at least, of what I 
 should distinguish as a fourth sense of the term " Nature "^ 
 (IV.) the sense in which "Nature" represents our ifleal of 
 what ought to be, whether it actually exists as a fact or not. 
 •■ Natural " is often equivalent to " normal " ; and normal 
 contains both the notion of generally happening, though not 
 necessarily happening, and the notion of a standard or rule 
 by which things are judged ^ in respect of quality or merit. 
 In the previous three senses, Nature always means something 
 that u ; in this sense it means what ougTit to &e, but does not 
 necessarily exist anywhere. Now it is in this fourth sense 
 that Nature is properly and intelligibly used when a Law ot 
 Nature {Jus NaturaJe or Lex Naturalis) and Natural Rights are 
 spoken of. And here, also, in the use of the term " law " we 
 have passed from the scientific sense of generalisation, formula, 
 statement of causal connection, etc., to the legal and ethical 
 sense of the term, as command or expectation of some obser- 
 vance. If the term "natural rights" were always confessedly 
 used in this sense, and in this sense only, no objection could 
 be taken to it, except that it was an ambiguous way of 
 saying what might be less ambiguously expressed by a direct 
 use of the term " ought." But unfortunately the term 
 " natural rights " is constantly used with a mixed connotation, 
 derived partly in varying degrees from some one or more of 
 the other senses of the term " Nature." As we have seen, 
 people are always apt to make a picture of their ideal as some 
 golden age in the past, to think of a reform as renewing some 
 old right ; - and so the meaning of " natural " as ideal is mixed 
 up with its meaning as " original." Two fallacies may thus 
 
 ' The English word "judgment " is ambiguous; it may mean dncKpavcns, 
 enunciatio, or Kpla-is, judicium. Generally, except in logic, it means the 
 latter («.e. not simply assertion, bat estimate of merit or value according 
 to a standard) ; for this meaning its legal associations fit it. 
 
 ^ " Erneut das alte Recht," says Heine, speaking of the Holy Spirit, in 
 the famous poem on the Trinity in his Harzreise.
 
 76 DE DIVISIONE NATURAE [ch. iv 
 
 arise. Either our historical notion of some period in the past 
 is vitiated by idealisation of the facts, or the actual facts of 
 the past are taken as of themselves determining what ought 
 to be done now. Further, the notion of " original " overlaps 
 with the notion of the not-human, i.e. that which is not, or 
 is not thought of as being, due to human action. Thus we get 
 Ulpian basing the conception of j».s- vaturale on the conduct 
 of all animals. In the way of thinking which I have called 
 Rousseauism, we have a combination of the .^eco7id and third 
 meanings as determining the fourth. Finally, the use of 
 Nature as equivalent to God (La) gives an apparent sanctit}' 
 to whatever can be described as " according to nature." The 
 " natural " as the ideal may quite reasonablj^ be represented 
 as that which is in accordance with a divine purpose, natural 
 rights described as bestowed on man by the Creator, and the 
 law of nature either identified with the Divine will, or re- 
 garded as some more or less complete manifestation of it. But 
 the second and third senses of Nature are apt to gain an 
 association of sanctity to which they have no necessary claim. 
 The original, which may be the imperfect, or the sub-human, 
 which, at the best, is only the incomplete manifestation of the 
 Divine meaning, is apt to be appealed to as determining 
 what ought to be. 
 
 The meaning of Nature as the totality of phenomena in the 
 universe, apart from any underlying principle or ultimate 
 purpose, is less apt to cause ambiguity. Yet the mere appeal 
 to fact as of itself settling a question of right may be regarded 
 as a confusion of the meanings which I have marked 16 and IV 
 respectively. The optimism which asserts the principle that 
 " whatever is, is right " may be described as such a confusion. 
 It assumes that we are able to estimate the worth of isolated 
 phenomena without regard to their relation to the underlying 
 principle or immanent reason of the universe, if we believe 
 that there is such an immanent reason in things, as all except 
 thoroughgoing pessimists or sceptics practically do, whatever 
 theories they may profess, whatever speculative doubts and 
 difficulties they may feel. " Whatever is, is right " is the 
 false way of putting the principle that "the real is the 
 rational." The " real " is not any and every particular phe- 
 nomena ; man}' phenomena turn out not to be realities {i.e. 
 not to have worth), but to be "shams."
 
 CH. ivj DE D I VIS I ONE NATUR.E 77 
 
 Perhaps the four (or five) meanings of Nature that I have 
 distinguished may be grouped more logically and symmetri- 
 cally as follows : Nature may be regarded either (A) " stati- 
 cally," or (B) " dynamically " (I use these terms metaphorically, 
 not, of course, in their strict sense in physics). We may look 
 on it, that is to say, either as existing (without taking time or 
 process into account) or as in process, moving to an end or 
 purpose (assuming that there is a purpose). Under each 
 division we may further mean either (a) the whole of Nature, 
 or (/3) a part of it. " Dynamically," the completed purpose 
 will correspond to what statically is the whole (if the whole be 
 looked at not merely as a collection of phenomena, but as the 
 manifestation of one underlying principle). Thus we should 
 distinguish : — 
 
 A a. Nature as the whole universe. 
 
 A /3. The non-human part of it. 
 
 B a. The ideal (or completed purpose). 
 
 B /S, The original (the incomplete). 
 
 These divisions will correspond to the previous divisions as 
 follows : — 
 
 A a = I. a and 6. 
 A/S = II. 
 B a = IV. 
 B/3 = IIL 
 The original division seems to me to be more convenient, 
 and I shall therefore retain it for purposes of reference. 
 
 The shortness of this chapter will, I hope, be a compensation 
 for its somewhat scholastic character. It will be obvious 
 that the word "ought," to which I have reduced the fourth 
 sense of " natural," stands very much in need of explanation. 
 To this I must proceed through an analysis of the meaning of 
 the term " a right."
 
 CHAPTEE V 
 
 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS ? 
 
 In considering the meaning of the term " right," it is best to 
 begin with the definition of right in its Jegal sense. A right 
 generally is defined b}' Professor Holland as " one man's capa- 
 city of influencing the acts of another, by means, not of his own 
 strength, but of the opinion or the force of society." A "■ legal 
 right," in the strictest sense, is " a capacity residing in one 
 man of controlling with the assent and assistance of the 
 State, the actions of others." ^ More briefly, though with 
 somewhat less precision, we might say that a legal right is the 
 claim of an individual upon others, recognised by the State. 
 A legal right need not necessarily have been created by the 
 State {e.g. by statute) ; but it must be such that the law courts 
 will recognise it, and, in all orderly communities, the force of 
 the State is at the back of all legal decisions. It is obvious 
 that there is no meaning in an individual's right unless there 
 are corresponding duties imposed on other individuals. On the 
 other hand, the State itself cannot be said, in the strict sense, 
 to have legal duties, but onl}" to have legal rights : there can- 
 not be a law court before which the State in itx sovereign capacity 
 (the qualification is essential) can be summoned for redress. A 
 " government" whose proceedings can come before the courts is 
 thereby proved not to be the legal sovereign in that commu- 
 nity. By " legal sovereign " I mean the body behind which 
 the lawyer qua lawyer does not go.'-^ 
 
 On the analogy of the definition of legal right, a moral right 
 might be defined as " a capacity residing in one man of con- 
 trolling the acts of another with the assent and assistance, or 
 at least without the opposition, of public opinion," or as "the 
 claim of an individual upon others recognised by society, 
 
 ' Juri.sprudou-e (Ed. II.), pp. (jl, 62. 
 
 - I may refer to an essay on " Sovereign tj'," included in the volume 
 called Darivin and Hegel, tvith other Philosophical Studies. 
 
 78
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? 79 
 
 irrespective of its recognition by the State." The onlj- sanc- 
 tion of a moral right as such is the approbation and disappro- 
 bation of private persons. In some cases such sanctions ma}' 
 be more binding and more dreaded than many legal penalties. 
 The religious sanction forms, in the great majority of cases, 
 one of the strongest elements in the sanction of a moral right : 
 but it is a sanction which, if not at the same time political 
 or social, must be applied by the individual to himself. The 
 difference between legal and moral rights makes it obvious that 
 moral rights cannot be so precisely determined as legal rights. 
 Different sections of the society to which a person belongs and 
 for whose opinion he cares may hold different views as to 
 various duties, and consequently as to various rights. Conflict 
 is therefore possible about moral as well as about legal rights ; 
 but in the matter of moral rights there is no law court to 
 which appeal can be made to pronounce a binding decision. 
 In homogeneous societies (and that means, as a rule, in compara- 
 tively primitive and simple societies) there will generally be 
 very little difference of opinion about moral rights. Such 
 homogeneous societies are the types of all primitive society, in 
 which there is no distinction between custom and law, between 
 moral and legal right. In societies which are held together hj 
 a common religious belief, there is generally a court of appeal 
 in matters of disputed moral rights and duties. Roman Catho- 
 lics, above all, are able to " consult approved theologians," and 
 although " doctors differ," they are able to get more cut-and- 
 dried and legal-looking answers on moral questions than an}' 
 body of Protestants who profess to submit their authority, 
 the Bible, to private interpretation. Still, any given sect of 
 Protestants will as a rule be found to hold ver}' much the same 
 opinion on most questions of moral obligation. Whenever we 
 have a very mixed and heterogeneous society, consisting of 
 persons of different religious beliefs, of different stages of 
 religious disbelief, and at very different grades of intellec- 
 tual development, questions of moral obligation become more 
 difficult to decide ; a greater responsibility is thrown on the 
 individuals immediately affected. Is there a moral right to 
 " boycott " non-unionists ? Have workmen on strike a moral 
 right to use intimidation towards " black-legs " ? Has a man 
 a moral right to marry a deceased wife's sister, if he be the 
 subject of a country where such a marriage is not yet recog-
 
 8o WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS 1 [ch. v 
 
 nised by the law ? In what cases and to what extent has an 
 individual a moral right, not merely to do what the law of the 
 land does not recognise, but to do what it positively forbids ? 
 Public opinion may not only consist of varying elements, but 
 it may undergo change. A change in public opinion is not 
 something formal and explicit, like a change in the law of the 
 land, and hence we have a further difficulty in determining 
 what are moral rights. 
 
 To escape such difficulties people have appealed to the Law 
 of Nature. If we knew clearly the natural rights of the indi- 
 vidual, we could deduce from them what are his moral rights, 
 and what in a well-regulated community should be his legal 
 rights : we should have a satisfactory system of practical ethics 
 and a satisfactory theory of legislation. Natural rights are 
 not identical with moral rights, because in many cases people 
 have claimed that they had a natural right to do things that 
 were not recognised either by the law of the land or by the 
 prevalent public opinion or by the conscience of the average 
 individual.^ Natural rights, when alleged by the would-be 
 reformer, mean those rights which in his opinion would be 
 recognised by the public opinion of such a society as he ad- 
 mires, and would either be supported or at least would not 
 be interfered with by its laws, if it had any laws ; they are 
 the rights which he thinks ought to be recognised, i.e. they 
 are the rights sanctioned by his ideal society, whatever that 
 may be. Not all rights, however, of our ideal society are, in 
 the strict sense, natural rights. The term " natural rights " is 
 generally restricted to those of them which are conceived of 
 as more fundamental than others, from which the others may 
 be deduced, or to which the others are only auxiliary. Thus, 
 most of those who have held the theory of natural rights have 
 not counted among them various political and civil rights, e.g. 
 the right to have a vote for representatives in the Legislature 
 (though this has frequently been claimed as a natural right), the 
 right to be elected, the right to sue in the courts, the right to 
 
 ^ Alleged natural rights may even be guaranteed by the State when 
 they are refused by the prevalent public opinion of society or of large 
 sections of it. Thus liberty of opinion in the matter of religion is one of 
 the most generally recognised " natural rights " ; but the history of per- 
 secution from the times of Jesus and Paul to the present day shows 
 how public opinion has often been more intolerant of religious freedom 
 than the State.
 
 CH. v] JVJIAT DETERMINES RIGHTS 1 8r 
 
 a speedy trial if accused, the right to be tried by a jury of one's 
 peers, etc. All these would generally be regarded as merely 
 means, and not necessarily the sole means, towards the attain- 
 ment of the fundamental natural rights of liberty and security. 
 It would generally be allowed that some degree of diversity of 
 opinion might quite well exist as to the particular form which 
 these secondary and derivative rights should take. With re- 
 gard to certain rights, notably the right of property, there is a 
 marked divergency among different believers in natural rights, 
 some giving it a prominent place in their list of natural rights, 
 others denying that it is a natural right at all, or limiting the 
 objects to which such right can apply, or restricting it in 
 various ways, excluding at least some property rights from 
 their law of nature. All such limitations of the meaning of 
 natural rights are clearly connected with that tendency, of 
 which I have already spoken, to regard the law of nature as 
 something that has already prevailed in some primitive state 
 of nature (to identify the natural with the original), and to 
 oppose the " natural " to that which is clearly due to human 
 institution (according to the distinctions laid down in last 
 chapter, meaning IV. of " nature " is confused with meanings 
 III. and II.). A primitive state of nature seems incompatible 
 with an elaborate set of political institutions, and with compli- 
 cated laws and customs regarding inheritance, freedom of be- 
 quest, etc. The law of nature, moreover (as with the Roman 
 jurists), is something behind and independent of the variations 
 of local usage: it is a universal code. Different communities 
 may adopt different kinds of political, legal, and social 
 machinery to give effect to it. Absolute uniformity is not 
 required except in essentials. But what are these essentials ? 
 There may be as much difficulty in getting the wished-for 
 agreement among the doctors of the Law of Nature as among 
 the doctors of the Church : and who shall decide as to who 
 are the politically and socially orthodox ? What rights oiKjht 
 every society at the very least to guarantee to its members ? 
 These, if we can agree upon them, will be our "natural 
 rights." 
 
 Now what determines this " ought " ? To this question 
 three types of answers have been and still are given. They 
 may be denoted by the words Auilwrity^ Nature, Utility. By 
 " Authority •' I mean here authority external to the mind of 
 
 N. E. a
 
 82 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 the individual. Nature, as we have already seen/ is tliouglit of 
 as something known by an inner voice, an internal authority. 
 Utility is known by Reason and Experience. 
 
 (1) To base natural or fundamental rights on external autho- 
 rity of any kind may seem to involve an obvious contradiction, 
 because these natural rights are supposed to be the very cri- 
 terion by which the worth of the external authority itself can 
 be judged. If the end of government be the preservation of 
 certain natural rights, we cannot let government itself deter- 
 mine what these rights are. This was clear enough to the 
 reflective framers of the American and French Declarations. 
 But if we go back to the ordinary unreflecting opinion of 
 mankind in comparatively primitive conditions, we shall find 
 that those rights which people think they ought to have are 
 just those rights which they have been accustomed to have, or 
 which they have a tradition (whether true or false) of having 
 once possessed. Rights are claimed because sanctioned in the 
 present or in the past by the authority of social recognition. 
 Custom is primitive law, and custom determines primitive 
 notions of obligation. But even in a reflective age, the think- 
 ing of the majority of persons remains of a primitive type ; and 
 even people who have become sophisticated enough to distin- 
 guish certain things as " natural " from certain others which 
 are merely " conventional," will be found very often to mean 
 by " natural " whatever has the sanction of the longest and 
 the least broken custom, while what is well known to be of 
 quite recent growth or is not very widely adopted can more 
 easily be regarded as "conventional." Thus to the average 
 Greek slavery undoubtedly seemed a "natural " institution ; it 
 was familiar to him, and he did not know of any civilised society 
 without it. Similarly the average person in every country at 
 the present day thinks the " natural " position of women to be 
 the position which is assigned to them by the customs of the 
 particular society to which he belongs. A Turk, a German, 
 an American, would give somewhat different accounts of this 
 natural status. The " natural " in each case may perhaps be 
 pitched a little above the average usage of the society in ques- 
 tion ; it represents the expectations of the society, of which 
 expectations fulfilment may indeed fall short. 
 
 Where the customs or laws of a society are ascribed to the 
 » Cf. above, Chap. II. pp. 3G, 41, 42.
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? B,z 
 
 revealed will of the gods, these rights are expressly based on a 
 definite authority ; and, if the revelation is supposed to be 
 through oracles, through sacred writings, or through a parti- 
 cular caste or class of society, the authority is an external autho- 
 rity. " Natural law " is, however, generally distinguished from 
 the revealed will of God ; ^ yet the revealed will of God is some- 
 times used as an argument to prove that something must be in 
 accordance with or not contrary to natural law, and, on the 
 other hand, natural law is sometimes appealed to as confirming 
 the validity of an alleged revelation. According to those theo- 
 logians and moralists who hold that right and wrong are de- 
 pendent upon the arbitrary will of the Deity, so that, if he had 
 so willed it, what is now right might have been wrong, and 
 vice versd^ there can be no meaning in natural law as distin- 
 guished from the revealed will of God. This combination of 
 " philosophic doubt," with a passive acceptance of Scriptural 
 or ecclesiastical authority, is a type of thinking very congenial 
 to a certain order of mind : it gratifies simultaneously the com- 
 pletest scepticism in the powers of the human reason and the 
 craving for absolute certainty. To this type of thinking the 
 theory of Hobbes presents considerable analogy, save that for 
 the Church he substitutes the de facto government. B}^ 
 "natural rights" Hobbes means simply those powers which 
 an individual has apart from all human institutions : so that 
 natural rights are equivalent to natural mights." In the state 
 of nature, i.e. apart from the laws and customs of a definite 
 political society, every one has a right to everything. The only 
 sanction of such natural rights is force. Political society has 
 its justification in the fact that it, and it alone, saves mankind 
 from the miseries of a condition in which there is no security 
 or peace : that is the meaning of Hobbes's version of the social 
 contract theory. With the exception of the natural right of 
 every individual to preserve his own life, to retain which man- 
 kind surrender all their other natural rights, all rights that a 
 man has in the civil state depend simply on the will of the 
 sovereign person or persons to whom he has handed over his 
 natural rights. The exception made by Hobbes in favour of 
 
 ' The Jwi' divinum voluntarium of Grotius and otliers. 
 
 ' "Natural" is thus used for what exists as a matter of fact apart from 
 the interference of human society. This is the sense of " nature " 1 have 
 marked (11.) in Chap. IV.
 
 84 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTSl [ch. v 
 
 the right of self-preservation seems inconsistent. " Skin for 
 skin, yea, all that a man hath will he give for his life." True ; 
 but many Englishmen of Hobbes's own time would have 
 argued, and did practically argue : " You take my life when 
 you do take the means whereby I live " ; and others thought 
 even life itself not worth having at the cost of depending on 
 the arbitrary will of any human being for the right to worship 
 God according to their consciences. What absolute priority, 
 it might reasonably be asked, has the right of preserving one's 
 life over the right of protecting one's property and the right 
 of following one's conscience in matters of religion ? Hobbes, 
 I fancy, means that the right of preserving one's life is pri- 
 mary, because without life everything else would be of no ac- 
 count. But does it not depend largely on individual tempera- 
 ment whether mere life at any cost is to be preferred to all the 
 things that seem to make life worth living ? If this natural 
 right is to remain intact in the civil state, why not others 
 which are necessarily involved in it ? If these others are ex- 
 cluded, why not this also ? It would be a more logical theory 
 to make even the right of preserving one's life dependent on 
 the will of the sovereign. As a matter of fact, it is so depen- 
 dent, as much as any other right. What difference is there 
 in principle between struggling with the executioner on the 
 scaffold and struggling with the officer who at the first arrests 
 me by order of the king ? And, on the other hand, what right 
 on Hobbes's theory has the government to do anything except 
 such right as depends upon its force to do it, so that if any 
 body of persons can succeed in obtaining the mastery, they 
 have the same right to issue orders and make laws which the 
 dispossessed government had, but no longer has ? All rights 
 must depend on the will of the de facto government, and 
 natural right means nothing except force. Spinoza eliminates 
 the inconsistency from Hobbes's theory, and preserves natural 
 right " safe and sound " in the civil state. ^ To the question of 
 the relation between might and right I must return later on. 
 
 Bentham, Austin, and most English jurists have accepted 
 Hobbes's account of rights in the civil state (" natural " rights 
 being discarded altogether) as perfectly true of legal rights. 
 But Hobbes himself (like his precursor, the sophist Thrasyma- 
 
 ' Epiiitolu, 50 (in the arrangement of Van Vloten and Land, as well as 
 in that of Bruder).
 
 CH. vj WHAT DETERMINES EIGHTS? 85 
 
 chus ^) made 110 distinction between legal and moral rights ; 
 and therefore remains as the most remarkable example of 
 a philosopher basing obligation simply upon the external 
 authority of the State. In this " sophistic " theory, custom 
 or usage becomes explicit as the mere arbitrary will of the 
 sovereign. 
 
 (2) When traditional custom or constituted authority comes 
 to be unsatisfactory to certain more reflective minds, there 
 arises a discrepancy between it and what seem to be the 
 natural instincts or feelings of the individual, a discrepancy 
 between law and conscience ; and so, as we have seen, reformers 
 try to go back to an authority more venerable than parHa- 
 ments and kings ; more venerable even than immemorial 
 usage :* they " appeal from tyranny to God," from the mere 
 custom of the multitude to the feelings that Nature has im- 
 planted in the breast of each of us. The unfortunate thing is 
 that these instinctive feelings differ so much in different per- 
 sons. A little reflection may show a discrepancy between out- 
 ward law and inward sentiment ; but a little more reflection 
 will show divergence between the sentiments of different per- 
 sons, or at least between the sentiments of different classes of 
 persons. The individual's conscience is apt to be the mirror 
 of the particular environment in which he has grown up ; and 
 even his revolt against existing institutions bears traces of 
 its unavoidable influence. We may strive to be as individual, 
 as original, as "singular" in our judgments as possible; 
 but we cannot escape much more easily from the network of 
 our social inheritance than we can escape from the inherit- 
 ance of a particular physical and mental constitution. Plato's 
 ideal state is the Hellenic state he knew — idealised. Some 
 of the materials are re-arranged, some latent principles are 
 clearly seen and carried out to their logical consequences. 
 " Conscience," says Professor Bain, " is an imitation within us 
 of the government without us." Hence it is no wonder that 
 Conscience should be spoken of, as it is by Butler, as if it were 
 a king, with definite prerogatives secured by the constitution. ^ 
 
 ' In Plato's liepublic, I. 
 
 ' Cf. Sermon II. "This prerogative, this natural sujrremacTj of the 
 faculty which surveys, approves, or disapproves of tlie several affections 
 of our minds, etc." " To preside and govern, from the very economy and 
 constitution of man, belongs to it." It is the legal theory of the English
 
 86 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 Yet there is this all-important difiference between tlie appeal to 
 law and cnstom and the appeal to conscience or natural feelings, 
 that in the latter case the authority appealed to is an internal, 
 not an external authority. The existing and the customar}^ 
 are being reflected upon and criticised, from the point of view 
 of an ideal which has grown up or been created out of them. 
 And the voice of God and Nature in the heart of every mortal 
 is thought of as a universal revelation : it professes to mean, 
 not what any chance person happens to feel, but what approves 
 itself to calm, reflective reason, and what can be shown to be 
 in accordance with the essential nature of things. The indi- 
 vidual conscience, according to the straitest sect of the In- 
 tuitionists, should be an infallible Pope in every man's 0"wni 
 breast ; but this infallible Pope is not in practice treated as 
 infallible, any more than is the other, by those to whom his 
 dogmas or decisions do not approve themselves. Even Catholic 
 theologians are not always agreed, in practice, as to the exact 
 point at which the infallibility comes in ; and with " every 
 man his own Pope," the distinctions between certainty and 
 error are even more difficult to draw. Practically we trust, 
 not to every man's conscience, but to the good man's con- 
 science — as Aristotle does,^ escaping thus the subjectivity of 
 Homo mensura. But who is the good man ? We have only 
 put the difficulty a stage farther back. What, then, is meant 
 by this further test of conformity to the essential nature of 
 things ? Is not this appeal the self-refutation of Intuitionalist 
 theories, and of all individualist or " idio-psychological " (to use 
 Dr. Martineau's phrase) theories of ethics ? It is an admission 
 that we must determine right and wrong by reference to ex- 
 perience, and not by the simple irresponsible dicta of an inner 
 light, which every man may claim to possess as well as every 
 other man. Natural rights, then, will not be what any chance 
 person may happen to claim as suiting his private notions of 
 what he ought to have. If the thief justifies himself on the 
 ground that " One must live," it is always possible for anyone, 
 who is backed by sufficient physical force, to answer, "I do not 
 see the necessity." Now such a retort is not the appeal from 
 one egotism to another : it is the appeal from individual self- 
 Constitution — rather than the political facts as they were coming to be — 
 to which Butler's theory of Conscience corresponds. 
 ' Eth. Nic, III. 4, § 5. Cf. VI. 11, § 6; 13, § 6.
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? 87 
 
 assertion to tlie self-assertion of a society of individuals. And, 
 be it observed, the genuine antique type of brigand or pirate, 
 as distinct from his survivals — his burglars and pick-pockets 
 of a civilised society — has such a social sanction to fall back 
 upon. 
 
 In the chaos of conflicting individual impulses, instincts, 
 desires, and interests, we can find no stable criterion. We must 
 go beyond them to the essential nature of things. But what 
 part of the nature of things is here relevant ? Is it not simply 
 — human society ? If there are certain mutual claims which 
 cannot be ignored without detriment to the well-being and, 
 in the last resort, to the very being of a community, these 
 claims may in an intelligible sense be called fundamental or 
 natural rights. They represent the minimum of security and 
 advantage which a community must guarantee to its members 
 at the risk of going to pieces, if it does not with some degree 
 of efficiency maintain them. 
 
 But in this interpretation of Nature we are appealing from 
 mere feelings to reason : conflicting claims can (in theory, at 
 least) come before a court in which their validity can be 
 judicially and impartially examined by the standard of the 
 general welfare. So that the details of a professedly Intui- 
 tionalist ethical code are filled up on Utilitarian principles. 
 
 The principle of Utility was expressly advocated by Bentham 
 and Mill in opposition both (1) to the mere following of custom 
 or external authority, and (2) to the arbitrary appeal to the 
 voice of nature speaking in the human breast — an appeal 
 which can be made in support of abuses, as well as in support 
 of the revolt against them. In opposition to both Authority 
 and the Law of Nature, Bentham, following Beccaria, sets up 
 " the greatest happiness of the greatest number," as our 
 criterion by which to judge of what ought to be. But the 
 Utilitarian theory is apt to provoke antagonism and revolt 
 almost more than the principle of external authority, for it has 
 not in the same way rooted itself in unreflective sentiment, 
 and feelings Avill outlive the reasonings that are supposed to 
 have killed them. And thus from Rousseau's time down- 
 wards the appeal to Nature is made as much against the 
 Utilitarian Rationalist as it is made against the advocates of 
 authoritative law and dogma.^ The duel becomes triangular : 
 
 ' A certain person, resisting the pressure of a bibulous friend wlio was
 
 83 WHA2' DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 Dogmatist (or Legalist), Sentimentalist and Rationalist do not 
 belong in life to separate epochs, as they might in the pages 
 of a history of thought ; all three are living and contending 
 among ourselves. Between them who is to decide ? 
 
 The Law of Nature, if it reall}^ represented " the consent of 
 the human race," would serve to settle controversies ; on the 
 whole it has helped to promote them. An illustration of the 
 difificulty in interpreting the voice of nature, and of the way 
 in which the case comes to be transferred from the court of 
 nature to some other court, may conveniently be taken from 
 the opinions about marriage which have been held by different 
 schools of believers in natural law. The Roman jurist, Ulpian, 
 as we saw, took this very matter of the union of the sexes as 
 one of his illustrations of jufi naturale^ so that we might 
 reasonably expect a fair consensus of opinion on the natural 
 rights involved. If, however, following Ulpian's guidance, we 
 were to refer to the usages of all animals, I fear we should 
 find a very conflicting set of precedents for man to follow. 
 Both monogamy and polygamy are sanctioned by the usages 
 of mammals and birds, though perhaps the consensus avium 
 may be allowed to condemn the polyandric practices of the 
 wicked cuckoo. But even when we may use the term " mono- 
 gamy " of animals, it must be remembered that most unions 
 of animals are temporary, and, as a rule, terminate at the 
 latest when the young are independent of their parents' 
 care. 
 
 As representing scholastic theology on the subject, I shall 
 take the opinion of the Jesuit Father Rickaby, an able modern 
 exponent of Thomas Aquinas. In his exposition of Natural 
 Law, he lays down that " by nature " polyandry is excluded 
 altogether, because (1) the absence of definite fatherhood inter- 
 feres with the good rearing of the offspring, and (2) if the 
 mother has as many " heads " over her as husbands, there will 
 be confusion; if she is head, there is "a perversion of the 
 natural order of predominance between the sexes." "Against 
 polygamy," he continues, " the case in natural law is not quite 
 so strong as against polyandry. Still, it is a strong case 
 enough in the interest of the wife." The relation between the 
 
 urging another glass upon him, was met by the argument, " You're 
 letting your judgment get the better of you." This is the appeal from 
 Eeason to instinct, from Utilitarianism to emotional Intuitionalism.
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES EIGHTS? 89 
 
 sexes should be a relation of equality, so far as mutual faith 
 is concerned. This limits the natural pre-eminence of the 
 husband.^ The polygamy of the Old Testament saints is, 
 however, an obvious difficulty to a Catholic moralist. The 
 view " that polygamy is not against the natural law, but only 
 against the positive divine law, which was derogated from in 
 this instance," is rejected by Father Rickaby, as is also a 
 second theory, that God gave the patriarchs a dispensation, 
 strictly so called, from this point of natural law. " A third 
 explanation would be founded on the words of St. Paul to the 
 Athenians (Acts xvii. 30) about ' God overlooking the times 
 of this ignorance.' This would suppose that mankind, begin- 
 ning in monogamy [Adam had not much opportunity of 
 beginning with anything else], from passion and ignorance, 
 lapsed quickly into polygamy ; that the patriarchs in good 
 faith conformed to the practice of their time, and that God, in 
 their case, as with the rest of mankind, awaited His own 
 destined hour for the light of better knowledge to break upon 
 the earth. Whether, meanwhile, by some darkly intelligible 
 stretch of His power He legitimised their unions, who can tell ? 
 A fourth explanation suggests a mode by which this legitimi- 
 sation may have taken place. God, by His supreme dominion, 
 can dissolve any marriage. By the same dominative power He 
 can infringe and partially make void any marriage contract, 
 without entirely undoing it. The marriage contract, existing 
 in its fulness and integrity, is a bar to any second similar 
 contract, as we have proved. But what, in this theory, the 
 Lord God did with the niarriages of the patriarchs was this : 
 He partially unravelled and undid the contract, so as to leave 
 room for a second contract and a third [and a seven hundredth, 
 in the case of Solomon ?], each having the bare essentials of a 
 marriage, but none of them the full integrity. This explana- 
 tion, and the one preceding, will stand with our philosophy. 
 As to which of them is to be preferred [I thought the fourt li 
 was only supplementary to the third], we answer in the style 
 of the Roman Court, Consult approved theologians^ - 
 
 I have quoted this passage in exfenso with my own interpo- 
 lations in square brackets, lest any account of its contents in 
 
 ' Moral Philosophy, or Ethics and Natural Law, 2iid Edition, pp. 
 270, 271. 
 
 * Ibid., pp. 273, 274.
 
 90 WHAT DETER.VINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 my own words might bs suspected of caricaturing the opinions 
 of a very able writer. Father E-ickaby's problem is indeed a 
 hard one — to reconcile a due respect for the much-married 
 heroes of Hebrew history with a belief in the absolute pro- 
 hibition of polygamy by the law of nature ; and he deserves 
 the credit of having taken his conception of natural law much 
 more seriously than many modern sentimentalists, who appeal 
 to nature simply as a means of giving a formal justification of 
 their private likes or dislikes, and then shirk the trouble of 
 argument. 
 
 Protestantism, in depressing the authority of the Church, 
 raised in relative importance the authority of the whole Bible ; 
 and the case of the Hebrew patriarchs, combined with a wider 
 knowledge derived from classical sources of the varying 
 practices of different peoples, leads Grotius to find no prohibi- 
 tion of polygamy in the law of nature.^ " Marriage by natural 
 law we conceive to be such a cohabitation of the male and 
 female as places the female under the protection and custody 
 of the male ; for such a union we see in some cases in mute 
 animals. But in man, as being a rational creature, to this is 
 added a vow of fidelity, by which the woman binds herself to 
 the man." ^ 
 
 Locke, in his Treatise of Civil Government^ seems to think 
 that, apart from the positive law of any particular political 
 society, the mutual obligation of husband and wife depends, 
 as with the animals, only on the necessity of rearing the 
 young. Since the young of those viviparous animals that feed 
 on grass can be nourished by their dams till they are able to 
 feed themselves, " the male only begets, but concerns not 
 himself for the female or young to whose sustenance he can 
 contribute nothing.^ But in beasts of prey the conjunction 
 lasts longer. . . . The assistance of the male is necessary 
 to the maintenance of their common family, which cannot 
 subsist till they are able to prey for themselves but by the 
 
 ' De Jure Belli et Pads, II. 5, § 9. Luther's sanctioning the bigamy 
 of the Landgrave Philip of Hesse was probably more due to strong 
 pressure from a defender of Protestantism, than to an unbiassed con- 
 viction following from a study of the Bible. 
 
 '' Ibid., II. 5, § 8 (Whewell's trans.). 
 
 ^ This fact might have been appealed to by Shelley and his disciples to 
 support a connection between vegetarianism and their theories about 
 marriage.
 
 CH. v] IVffAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? 91 
 
 joint care of male and female. . . . And herein, I think, lies 
 the chief, if not the only reason why the male and female in 
 mankind are tied to a longer conjunction than other creatures, 
 viz. because the female is capable of conceiving, and de facfo 
 is commonly with child again, and brings forth, too, a new 
 birth, long before the former is out of dependency for support 
 on his parents' help, and able to shift for himself, and has all 
 the assistance which is due to him from his parents ; whereby 
 the father, who is bound to take care of those he hath begot, 
 is under an obligation to continue in conjugal society with the 
 same woman longer than other creatures, whose young, being 
 able to subsist of themselves before the time of procreation 
 returns again, the conjugal bond dissolves of itself, and they 
 are at liberty till Hymen at his usual anniversary season 
 summons them again to choose new mates. AVherein one 
 cannot but admire the wisdom of the great Creator, who, 
 having given to man foresight and an ability to lay up for the 
 future, as well as to supply the present necessity, hath made 
 it necessary that society of man and wife should be more 
 lasting than of male and female amongst other creatures, that 
 so their industry might be encouraged, and their interest 
 better united to make provision and lay up goods for their 
 common issue, which uncertain mixture or easy and frequent 
 solutions of conjugal society would mightily disturb." ^ 
 
 Locke's object in dealing with the subject of marriage is 
 simply to show, in opposition to Filmer, that the paternal re- 
 lation does not determine the nature of political obligation ; but 
 that, on the contrary, a great deal of what is commonly sup- 
 posed to be involved in the family depends upon the enact- 
 ment of the civil magistrate and not upon the law of nature. 
 Although his opinion is expressed in a somewhat doubtful 
 way (" the chief, if not the only reason"), it would seem to 
 follow that, in Locke's view, a childless couple, or a couple whose 
 children were independent of them, might, according to the 
 law of nature alone, i.e. apart from special positive laws and 
 apart from any specially revealed divine law, separate from one 
 another and contract new conjugal ties.^ In another place 
 
 * Treatise of Civil Government, II. c. vii., §§ 79, 80. 
 
 ^ That polygamy is not contrary to the law of nature is also main- 
 tained by Locke in his unpublished Essay concerning Toleration (16()7), 
 printed in Mr. Fox Bourne's Life of Locke, Vol. I. See esp. pp. 178, 186. 
 Cf. also a passage in a paper of 1661 (y), ibid. p. 163.
 
 92 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 (c. vi. § 65), lie refers to polyandry without any suggestion that 
 such a form of the family is contrary to the law of nature ; he 
 uses the institution of polyandry as an argument against 
 Filmer : " What will become of this paternal power in that 
 part of the world where one woman hath more than one 
 husband at a time ? " Locke, of course, must not be understood 
 to imply that all the various systems of relations between the 
 sexes which may not be contrary to the law of nature are 
 therefore equally good : throughout his whole treatise, though 
 the law of nature and the state of nature are frequently 
 appealed to, Locke decides all important points on what we 
 should call " utilitarian considerations." The modern student 
 of sociology may note that, in his reference to the relation 
 between man and the animals, Locke has seen, in one respect 
 at least, the immense significance for social evolution of the 
 prolongation of infancy.^ 
 
 I shall now take the opinion of the late Professor Lorimer, 
 whose Institutes of Law bears as its second title the words, A 
 treatise of the Principles of Jurisprudence as determined by 
 Nature. This work is probably the best English exposition 
 of the idea of a Law of Nature in the special form which that 
 idea has received at the hands of German jurists and moralists 
 who have adopted the principle of Naturrecht as the basis of 
 their systems. Having decided that monogamy is the system 
 approved by the law of nature, because, among other reasons, 
 the sexes are on the whole equal in numbers, Professor Lorimer 
 sees possible difficulties which he discusses by putting a 
 hypothetical case of conscience. Suppose that one man and 
 twenty women find themselves on a desert island without hope 
 of ever being restored to society. There are three courses open 
 to them with respect to the regulation of marriage. First, they 
 may adhere to monogamy (and, it is implied, to all the other 
 restrictions on marriage usual among civilised nations) and allow 
 the race to become extinct after the first generation. [We 
 must assume apparently that the women at starting are all 
 
 ' Di'. E. Westermarck's formula tliat " max-riage is rooted in family 
 rather than family in marriage " (see his History of Human Marriage) 
 might almost serve as a summary of the passage I have quoted from 
 Locke. Dr. Westermarck told me that he was quite unaware of Locke's 
 treatment of the subject, till I pointed out to him the striking anticipation 
 of his own view, contained in the passage I have quoted.
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? 93 
 
 approaching middle life, else the difficulty might be got over 
 by a son of the sole married couple marrying at the earliest 
 possible age any woman still capable of bearing children ; but 
 this would spoil the puzzle.] Secondly^ they may adhere to 
 monogamy and allow brothers and sisters of full blood to 
 marry ; or thirdly^ they may resort to polygamy and avoid any 
 nearer connection than between brothers and sisters of half- 
 blood for one generation : afterwards re-establish monogamy 
 and the ordinary rules as to forbidden degrees. '' The first 
 course is that which they probably ought to adopt ; but, inas- 
 much as polygamy is less revolting than incest, the third course 
 would be clearly preferable to the second ; and in so far as the 
 teaching of nature goes, a good deal might be said for it even 
 as opposed to the first." ^ 
 
 Now it is difficult to see how the final suggestion diffei's 
 from that which would commend itself to a Utilitarian : and 
 the first course, it might very well be argued, conflicts with the 
 law of nature ; for how can nature command the extinction of 
 the species '? But the curious thing about the whole statement 
 and solution of the problem is the transference to a chance 
 group of human beings of the ideas and sentiments of particular 
 civilised societies. What human beings so situated icoidd 
 actually do, and how far they would consider what they were 
 doing to be right, would depend entirely on who these human 
 beings were, how they had been brought up, and what their 
 feelings towards one another came to be when they were thus 
 thrown together. It is possible the one man might become a 
 Mormon, it is possible he might become a monk — to pick out 
 one wife might be a dangerous experiment. The problem 
 may be commended to the notice of the psychological novelist. 
 
 Lastly, by way of change from this casuistical atmosphere, 
 let us consult Shelley, who finds in the law of nature an easy 
 solution of all problems. " Free love " would be his answer to 
 all questions about the natui-al relations of the sexes ; ^ and if 
 by " Nature " be meant what would happen in the absence of 
 all institutions, it is obviously the only true answer (save that 
 " free capture " would probably be the more accurate exprps- 
 sion). To Shelley Nature means this ; but it also means the 
 ideal. Shelley and his followers are very anxious to make out 
 
 1 Institutes of Law (1st edit. 1872), p. 433. 
 * Queen Mob, note on Canto V.
 
 94 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 that free love and promiscuity are not the same thing. But 
 " promiscuity " is simply a dyslogistic term for what is eulogisti- 
 cally called " free love " : a name for the relationships existing 
 between the sexes where, if anywhere, there are no definite 
 prohibitions recognised by law or custom. As soon as certain 
 things come to be approved and other things disapproved, we 
 have a custom and the elementary stage of a law : therefore, if 
 in a " natural " society any conduct was liable to be disapproved 
 of, there could not be absolute freedom. Opinions like those 
 of J. S. Mill and others, that positive law ought not to inter- 
 fere with the relations of the sexes, except so far as the 
 welfare of children is concerned, are entirely and confessedly 
 of a Utilitarian character — the appeal is to what experience 
 would show to be best : they admit of argument pro and con. 
 A simple appeal to Nature stops the mouth of the person who 
 wishes to argue from experience. 
 
 Now a Roman Catholic moralist, who is able to " consult 
 approved theologians," would not trouble himself with such 
 heretical and atheistical vagaries as he would undoubtedl}^ 
 consider the opinions of Grotius, Locke, and Shelley. (Pro- 
 fessor Lorimer might, perhaps, escape condemnation.) But he 
 only avoids the difficulties of knowing what the law of nature 
 is because he has an external authority to fall back upon. 
 The person who discards such authority, and appeals to Nature, 
 finds that her doctors disagree : and between them who shall 
 decide ? The moment the question comes to be really dis- 
 cussed, considerations of titility must come in. "Would it not 
 be better to leave Nature alone and bring in Utilitarian con- 
 siderations from the outset ? 
 
 But it may be, and has been objected, that people are no 
 more agreed as to what is " useful," than they are as to what 
 is right or just according to the law of nature. It is true, 
 the " useful," taken by itself, is quite as ambiguous as the just. 
 But the useful does not profess to be something incapable of 
 further analysis. It is confessedly a relative term, useful for 
 something. Useful for zvhat ? It is here that the Utilitarian 
 theory stands most in need of revision and correction. While 
 rejecting in words the theory of natural rights, Benthamism 
 retains the abstract individualism which forms an essential 
 part of that theory. Human beings are treated by the old- 
 fashioned Utilitarian as moral atoms, all similar in kind, so
 
 CH. v] irHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? 95 
 
 that one man's feelings can be quantitatively estimated and 
 dealt with as if they were identical with another man's feeHngs. 
 It is assumed that " lots " of pleasures can be distributed among 
 these individuals — an idea which justifies, so far, Carlyle's 
 caricature of the Utilitarian " happiness " as so much attainable 
 pig's wash to be divided among a given multitude of pigs.^ 
 Benthamism is an excellent theory for purposes of attack, since 
 it demands that institutions and laws shall justify themselves 
 as being conducive to the general happiness. But it is itself 
 open to many of the objections that can be made to the theory 
 of natural rights ; and in fact it involves an assumption of the 
 equality and similarity of all mankind in all times and places, 
 which is just a part of the theory of natural rights in its crudest 
 form. We have seen that the appeal to nature combines the 
 abstract individualism of an appeal to each isolated irresponsible 
 instinct with an appeal to that abstract universal, the " consent of 
 all mankind." Similarly, Benthamist Utilitarianism combines 
 the abstract individualism of treating every human being as 
 an isolated unit with the view of happiness as an abstract uni- 
 versal which is thought of as if it had a sort of existence apart 
 from the concrete individuals who alone are capable of feeling 
 it. That " every one should count for one and nobody for 
 more than one " can indeed be defended on utilitarian grounds 
 as the only way, or the easiest way, of escaping the difficulty 
 of distinguishing exactly between the needs and merits of 
 individuals, and of avoiding the discontent that arises from a 
 suspicion of injustice. But old-fashioned Utilitarianism goes 
 farther, and di'&^w.m.e'S, practically that men have, a priori^ equal 
 rights.^ Otherwise, according to Bentham's formula, and assum- 
 ing Bentham's calculus of pleasures to be possible, if in any 
 case it could be made out that the greater happiness of a few 
 
 ' Latter Day PamjMets, " Jesuitism." 
 
 ^ Cf. Maine, Early History of Institutions, p. 899. " The most conclu- 
 sive objection to the doctrine would consist in denying this equality ; and 
 I have myself heard an Indian Brahmin dispute it on the ground that, 
 according to the clear teaching of his religion, a Brahmin was entitled to 
 twenty times as much happiness as anybody else." The Brahmin has the 
 advantage of being able to appeal to an authoritative estimate of his 
 claims to happiness. But without such precise moral arithmetic, might 
 not a vigorous person of all-round interests, and with a gi-oat capacity for 
 enjoyment, reasonably, on Benthamist principles, demand a fuller share of 
 happiness than the timid, narrow soul on whom an equal " lot " would 
 be thrown away ?
 
 96 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS 1 [ch. v 
 
 could be obtained by the less happiness of a majority, and that 
 the total happiness thus obtained would be greater than if 
 happiness were distributed equally through the whole multi- 
 tude, and if\ further (this qualification is necessarily implied), 
 the majority being ignorant and apathetic were not discon- 
 tented or could be easily controlled, I cannot see how, on the 
 " greatest happiness" principle, we ought not to prefer such an 
 organisation of society to one based on equality. We know 
 that many defenders of aristocratic and caste privileges do 
 argue more or less explicitly in this way ; and if the end of life 
 were simply the attainment of the greatest sum of pleasures on 
 the whole (intensity being reckoned as much as extensiveness), 
 irrespective of the "rights" of the individuals who enjoy 
 them, then so long as the merry ruling caste are sufficiently 
 callous, and the depressed subject caste are sufficiently stupid, 
 I do not see how this aristocratic argument can be refuted. 
 But we know that the great Utilitarian reformers to whom 
 England owes so much had the passion for equality, and John 
 Stuart Mill, illogically it may be, preferred Socrates dissatisfied 
 to the pig satisfied : so that, practically, they did not accept 
 the greatest sum of pleasures as the end of life. 
 
 This objection of inconsistency only applies to Utilitarianism, 
 if the feelings of pleasure and pain be made the starting-point 
 of our ethical thinking. It would not apply at all to an ethi- 
 cal theory which starts from a conception of the self as rational 
 and universal (a theory of which the doctrine of a law of nature, 
 at least in its Roman and in its scholastic form, seems a rudi- 
 mentary and unsatisfactory foreshadowing). If our claims are 
 based not on our isolated instincts but on the fact, which 
 seems to be a necessary conclusion from the conditions of 
 knowledge, that our particular self or ego is only the imperfect 
 realisation of a universal reason, one and indivisible through- 
 out the universe, though manifested in countless forms and 
 revealed most clearly to us, not in the movements of the stars, 
 nor in the record of the rocks, nor even in the upward striving 
 life of plant and animal, but in the work of the human spirit, 
 that is to say in social institutions, in art, in religion, and 
 where thought seeks to be at home with itself — in the medita- 
 tions of the philosopher,^ — if this be so, every human being may 
 claim a right to be considered as such, because he potentially 
 ' See above, p. 70.
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETER. }rrNES RIGHTS 1 97 
 
 shares in this consciousness of the universal reason ; he may 
 claim the opportunity of developing this potentiality as far as 
 possible. Each can claim to be an end-in-himself without incon- 
 sistenc}'' or necessity of conflict, only because none is an end-in- 
 himself, except as partaking of the one " Reason " or " Nature " 
 which is what all the higher religions have meant by God. 
 Such a metaphysical conception of the self will not indeed 
 justify an abstract claim to equality in anything and every- 
 thing, but only to such equality as is required for. and is com- 
 patible with, the highest conceivable form of social existence. 
 And here we come in sight of a means of explaining the nature 
 of rights and a means of reforming Utilitarianism, which can 
 be adopted without the use of what many persons will put 
 aside as unintelligible mysticism. The metaphysics seem to 
 me, indeed, necessary for a complete account of the basis of 
 ethics and politics ; but having said that, I shall now pass 
 to an easier way of putting the case. 
 
 The difficulties which may be raised about the Hedonist 
 basis of Benthamist Utilitarianism do not here directly con- 
 cern us ; the difficulties suggested by the individualism of the 
 theory are sufficient. It is worth particular note that Pro- 
 fessor Sidgwick, who in his Elements of J^olitics applies the 
 Utilitarian principle throughout in its individualist form, yet 
 extends his consideration from the happiness of the existing 
 sum of individuals to include that of the future members of the 
 society. We must, he says, " take into account not only the 
 human beings who are actually living, but those who are to 
 live hereafter." ^ " Whatever force there is," he adds, " in the 
 argument urged against the view that the end of government 
 is the happiness of the individuals governed, depends on the 
 conception of these individuals as present, actually existing, 
 members of the particular com.munity in question. I fully 
 concede that there are crises of national life in which it is the 
 duty of the present generation of citizens, the actually living 
 human beings who compose any political community, to make 
 important sacrifices of personal happiness for the ' good or 
 welfare of their country,' and that this good or welfare cannot 
 be completely analysed into private happiness of the in- 
 dividuals who make the sacrifices. I should add that there 
 are cases in which it is the duty of the members of one 
 
 ' P. 34. 
 
 N. R. H
 
 98 WHAT DEI EN MINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 political society to make sacrifices for the good or welfare of 
 otlier sections of the human race. But I hold that if this 
 good is not chimerical and illusory, it must mean the happi- 
 ness of some individual human beings ; if not of those living 
 now, at any rate of those who are to live hereafter. And I 
 have tried in vain to obtain from any writer who rejects this 
 view, any other definite conception of the ' good of the 
 state.' " 1 
 
 This is a very important passage, because, although Pro- 
 fessor Sidgwick still prefers the old-fashioned Utilitarian 
 phraseology and will not talk about the " social organism," he 
 practically adopts the important element of truth in that 
 often misapplied conception, and thinks of society as organic, 
 i.e. as having a continuous life, within which its individual 
 members arise and perish, a life which has to be cared for 
 over and above the sum of individuals at any given time 
 existing. Professor Sidgwick complains that writers, such as 
 Bluntschli, to whom he specially refers, give no definite con- 
 ception of the " good of the state," beyond what a Utilitarian 
 can give. But how if the end of human life, individual and 
 social, does not admit of a definite conception ? It is only with 
 the progress of time that we discover the natural gifts and 
 capacities of an individual or of a society ; if we say that in 
 the end of the state should be included the development of a 
 people's natural gifts, the very word "development" would 
 suggest growth and progress. A fundamental defect of the 
 old Utilitarianism was the assumption of the identity of 
 human nature in spite of difference of time and place and 
 stage of growth ; it is the characteristic of a crude rationalism 
 to judge all social stages by similar canons. The conception 
 of evolution or, more precisely, the theory of natural selection 
 has at once corrected the errors and vindicated the truth of 
 Utilitarian ethics and politics. That is " good " for any par- 
 ticular society which furthers its success in the struggle for 
 existence with nature and with other societies ; that is " evil " 
 which hinders such success. Those societies have succeeded 
 best which have been most coherent and most vigorous ; and 
 so courage and fidelity to those of the same society have 
 been "selected" as good qualities; they are the primitive 
 virtues. With the growth of reflection and a wider outlook, 
 ^ Elements of Politics, p. 35.
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS} 99 
 
 i^ese good qualiries and others car. . 
 
 -:riier spKeres : and the -- -— - 
 
 ^hat is right mav come * . _ 
 
 its character. The individiLr ely 
 
 strives after happine^. ia ~ : 
 
 necessarily what a TTtili" : _. . 
 
 to pursue: but th- — re- 
 
 determines -' - ':: -. r - _ " J. •- iiipp.- 
 
 ness. " as i^r . -r r. : - :- - := in-:- 
 
 the end of right a : V -^ — - 
 
 manity, exc-ept in 5.:, la: - . .: 
 
 liiat is to say. it is rig_:-v - .t : i_ 
 
 ^zL" This inverts the _ . : I . , -— . 
 
 "vjii^r Tr : T-i- ---_■ " -it ascecic tneones _ " - -_ - ' l- 
 
 Happy citizens — .._ :_.: 'jz. tl^ -^ -^ - 
 
 citizens, healthy in znni. body. ^e — :=-_ prove the 
 
 most useful citizens. 'Jliniri's — . ~ _ _ " .^' --/. - - 
 
 to the objecdon laa- r^r r :. ;: 1 
 
 li it had an existence ii- : : _ T ''-- 
 
 tie individuals, wi' - i^ 
 
 jiKJ^rng «tf \rhar is : . ^ : 
 
 of a :-ity is itseii i: -^.-.z. tne ^:':": 
 
 meniC'*r-> ^^ ne^j.tn.'v v?»^*^v .^^ . . 
 
 ochers. 1 - :.isy serve to iHnstrare the 
 
 cetwr _ 
 
 The g 
 
 though the o: . .v in.ay be tl: _ - t evenly eisy 
 
 not rtealised aiivwiiere : ~ 15 
 
 ---^-^ -— - •• - '- -ime , .^ - "^ 
 
 society ^ ^
 
 loo WHAT DETERMINES FIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 moral judgment, that progress takes place. Every extension 
 of the range of persons who are taken account of, when we 
 think of the common good, effects changes in our moral judg- 
 ments. Moral judgments vary because societies vary in 
 character : conflict of duties and conflict of moral judgments 
 are possible just because each individual in all highly de- 
 veloped societies belongs to many communities, overlapping 
 one another. Professor Sidgwick, in the passage I quoted, 
 recognises that other sections of the human race than our 
 own section may have to be taken into account ; and it is 
 conceivable that duty towards a higher and better society 
 might lead people to think it right to destroy a society whose 
 welfare had previously formed the standard of their moral 
 judgments. Among conscious and reflective human beings, 
 natural selection passes into rational selection ; and a social 
 organism may die, while its individual members become ab- 
 sorbed in an organism of a higher type. 
 
 " 'Ere's a stranger ; let's 'eave 'arf a brick at him."^ That 
 is primitive morality — " natural " morality, if natural means 
 "original." The duty of kindness is only supposed to apply 
 to members of the same tribe, class, caste, trade-union, or 
 whatever the group may be. The brotherhood of mankind is 
 the ideal at the other end of the ethical scale. 
 
 There are indeed some sturdy individualists among us 
 who, whether in the name of " natural rights "or in the 
 name of " the greatest happiness of the greatest number," 
 protest equally against any appreciative reference to the past 
 and against any consideration of posterity in our ethical and 
 political judgments. This is a frame of mind against which 
 argument is difficult, as it implies a non-acceptance of that 
 continuity of the species which one would have thought was 
 a patent fact. The human race or, let me say, the inhabitants 
 of Great Britain do not consist of a certain number of adult 
 males, or adult males and females, assembled together in a 
 sort of cross between a debating society and a joint-stock 
 company, and entitled by the law of nature to divide all the 
 good things of life among themselves. An assembly or 
 national convention of all the adults of a community would be 
 only the trustees inheriting every moment from the old who 
 
 ^ Cf. /iosi«s = (l) stranger; (2) enemy. ^^ Hostis apud majores nostros 
 is dicebatur quern nwnc peregrininn dicimus." (Cic..Z>e Olf.. I. 12, 37.)
 
 CH. v] IVBAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? loi 
 
 are dying and obliged to take into account tlie interests of 
 those who are being born. Human beings would have to be 
 artificially cut off from all links of human kinship — to become 
 like a band of outlaws or pirates — before they could consider 
 the question of right and wrong without regard to the past 
 that had produced them and without regard to the future that 
 was even now amongst them. And with \^hat show of reason 
 can any one sit in judgment on the past and blame men in old 
 times for the inheritance of evil their actions or their negli- 
 gences have left to us, while calmly proposing to decide the 
 rights of living persons without any " superstition about the 
 effect on posterity " ? ^ 
 
 The transition from Individualist to Evolutionist Utilitarian- 
 ism — a transition which is being accepted by the great 
 majority of writers on scientific ethics, from whatever point 
 of view they set out — makes what one may call a "Copernican" 
 change in our way of considering the question of rights. The 
 eighteenth century thinkers looked on society as made by 
 individuals joining together, in order to secure their pre- 
 existing natural rights. We, unless we remain uninfluenced 
 by the more scientific conceptions of human society now 
 possible to us — we see that "natural rights," those rights 
 which ought to he recognised, must be judged entirely from the 
 point of view of society. We must return to the method of 
 Plato : in order to know what is really just, we must call up 
 a vision of an ideal society. That is the true value of " Uto- 
 pias " : they are rough attempts to see how our ideas of justice 
 look when writ large in a picture of a reconstructed society. 
 Society, as we are always being reminded, has indeed no 
 existence except as a society of individuals ; but individuals 
 as human beings with rights and duties, and not as mere 
 animals, can only be understood in reference to a society. 
 " Nature," we might say, falling back on the antithesis, made 
 man an animal ; society has made him a rational animal — a 
 thinking, intelligent being, capable of moral action. The 
 person with rights and duties is the product of a society, and 
 the rights of the individual must therefore be juflged from the 
 point of view of a society as a whole, and not the society from 
 
 ^ The phrase is used by Mr. J. M. Robertson in an article in tlio 
 National lieformer for Dec. 6, 1891, in which he criticises a lecture of 
 mine on the subject of " Natural Rights." 
 
 Mrji\/PR<^>TY Cr CALlFORNiA
 
 I02 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 the point of view of the indivicluah As against the Hedonist 
 Utilitarians, Intuitionalists are quite right in urging that moral- 
 ity is based on personality, and not on a mere summation of 
 pleasurable feelings, treated as if these feelings liad an existence 
 per se; but the Intuitionalist is apt to treat "personality" as if 
 that term were the solution, and not the statement of a problem. 
 Metaphysically^ personality can only be explained by a specu- 
 lative hypothesis about the ultimate nature of the universe — in 
 more familiar language, about the relations between God, nature, 
 and man; but for the purposes oi practical ethics and politics^ 
 it is sufficient to recognise that personality is a conception 
 meaningless apart from society. We have got the word 
 " person " in its ethical sense from the Roman jurists, and we 
 should acknowledge our debt by recognising the social — nay, 
 the civic — character of the conception. Wherever, as in those 
 famous theories of " social contract " and " natural rights," a 
 society seems to be reasonably and legitimately judged from 
 the point of view of the individual, such theories simply 
 represent an inaccurate, but possibly convenient way of judg- 
 ing any given society from the point of view of a supposed 
 wider or higher society. The rebel against society, whether 
 he appeals to nature or not, may be of two kinds. He may be 
 the precursor of some new and better society, in the name of 
 which he condemns an existing, but corrupt and decaying, set 
 of institutions ; or he may be the survival of a ruder and lower 
 stage of existence. The pirate and the brigand were once 
 very respectable people, but in a social condition which has 
 passed the stage to which they belong, they are rightly treated 
 as dangerous criminals. Society, indeed, consisting only of 
 fallible and imperfect beings, is apt to make mistakes, and it 
 may now and then confuse the two kinds of rebels, and 
 crucify a true prophet between two ordinary criminals ; 
 though the ratio of true prophets to ordinary criminals is not 
 as a rule so high. 
 
 Whether we say that rights are in all cases created by the 
 State or not, is very much a matter of language. There are 
 many primitive societies, which have too little definite organ- 
 isation to be conveniently called States, except proleptically ; 
 it is usual to reserve the term State for those societies which 
 have a fairly definite system of government. Moreover, within 
 the shelter of the State there may grow up various societies or
 
 c:h. v] what determines RIGHTS? 103 
 
 associations, of a more or less volantary character — voluntary 
 in appearance at least — and there may be surviving associations 
 of an older kind, families, clans, village communities, etc., all 
 of which may confer rights on their members, apart from the 
 rights expressly conferred by the State : and some of these 
 associations may be of an international character. The State 
 may recognise some of these rights as legally binding ; others 
 it may tolerate, without giving them any legal sanction ; others 
 it may expressly forbid, as injurious to the security of the 
 commonwealth, as allowing scope for foreign interference, or 
 as infringing what have come to be regarded as the proper 
 rights of individuals. This last form of State-action forms 
 a principal element in the guaranteeing of " natural rights " ; 
 it is interference on the part of an organised State to protect 
 individuals from what has come to be thought undue pressure 
 on the part of other societies, e.g. the family, the Church, 
 guilds or corporations of various kinds, old and new. 
 
 The appeal to natural rights, which has filled a noble place 
 in history, is only a safe form of appeal if it be interpreted, as 
 just explained, as an appeal to what is socially useful, account 
 being taken not only of immediate convenience to the existing 
 members of a particular society, but of the future welfare of 
 the society in relation, so far as possible, to the whole of 
 humanity. If it is argued that such an appeal is at least as 
 ambiguous as a mere reference to natural rights, I answer, No ; 
 for in appealing to social utility, we are appealing to something 
 that can be tested, not merely by the intuitions of an individual 
 mind, but by experience. History is the laborator^^ of politics. 
 Past experience is indeed a poor substitute for crucial experi- 
 ments ; but Ave are neglecting our only guide if we do not use 
 it. This means no slavish copying of antique models, but 
 trying to discover, from consequences which followed under 
 past conditions, what consequences are likely to follow under 
 similar or under dissimilar conditions now. 
 
 The introduction of the conception of evolution into the 
 study of institutions, if that conception be applied with due 
 care, gives us in one respect a much more hopeful outlook 
 than if we felt bound to apply to every age the same un- 
 varying " natural " code of right and wrong. As an illus- 
 tration, let me take the institution of slavery. To the 
 scientific student of human history it seems almost certain
 
 I04 WHAT DETERMINES KIGHTSl [ch. v 
 
 that slavery was a necessary step in the progress of hnmanit}-. 
 It mitigated the horrors of primitive warfare/ and thns gave 
 some scope for the growth, however feeble, of kindlier senti- 
 ments towards the alien and the weak. It gave to the free 
 population sufficient leisure for the pursuit of science and art, 
 and, above all, for the development of political liberty ; and 
 in this way slavery may be said to have produced the idea 
 of self-government. By contrast with the slave the freeman 
 discovered the worth of freedom. Thus slavery made possible 
 the growth of the very ideas which in course of, time came to 
 make slavery appear wrong. Slavery seems to us horrible : 
 it is contrary to nature, it violates the feelings that God and 
 Nature have implanted in our breasts, and so on. It used not 
 to seem horrible or contrary to nature, even to many people who 
 talked loudly about the inalienable right of liberty. There 
 are probably many things existing now, which will seem 
 "horrible" some day, but which now seem quite "natural " 
 to most persons. Science must have no prejudices, and there- 
 fore we must admit that there was a stage in human develop- 
 ment when slavery, being useful to the progress of mankind, 
 was not contrary to what could then have been considered 
 "Natural rights," although when slavery is no longer an insti- 
 tution of progressive societies, it becomes contrary to what 
 people now consider " Natural rights." It is no use to con- 
 struct hypothetical histories and imagine the civilisation, whose 
 benefits we reap, and among whose benefits are those ideas 
 that have abolished slavery, arising among some savage tribe 
 which had never hit upon this device for securing leisure to 
 themselves, in which to fight, to govern, to think. But an 
 hJMorical justification of an institution is no justification for 
 the continuance or revival of an institution, when it is no 
 longer socially beneficial, or when the purpose it once served 
 can be otherwise provided for. 
 
 The present competitive industrial system has done marvels 
 in the way of opening up the material resources of the earth ; 
 those who have grown up in the shadow of it are apt to 
 
 ^ That the introduction of the practice of making- slaves of captives 
 diminished the ferocity of war is generally admitted. What is less 
 generalljr noted is that, as Sir Henry Maine points out {International 
 Law, p. 1B4), " One consequence of the decay and abolition of slavery 
 was an increase of bloodshed."
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTSl 105 
 
 imagine that it is indispensable. Those who have studied the 
 history of slavery are not bound to any such belief. This 
 very epoch of competitive capitalism has produced ideas which 
 make it possible to believe in a better type of organisation in 
 which the captains of industry shall become essentially, and 
 not merely accidentally, the public servants of the whole com- 
 munity. The growth of joint-stock enterprise, under a system 
 of " free association," suggests the idea of common-ownership 
 on a gigantic scale. The " labour-saving " machinery, which 
 has caused the industrial revolution and brought about an 
 unsettlement of old, comparatively stationary societies, suggests 
 a utilisation of machinery, which shall in very truth be labour- 
 saving and not merely labour-displacing, and which shall pro- 
 vide the leisure that ancient communities could only secure to 
 their citizens by slavery.^ These visions of a better society are 
 not suggested by vague, irresponsible oracles of Nature ; they 
 are inferences from experience, which may be true or false, 
 but which admit of being profitably discussed. And this is the 
 advantage which the appeal to reason and experience has over 
 all appeals to irresponsible instincts, impulses, and claims, 
 whether called natural rights or not. If you appeal to Nature, 
 we may not be able to prove you wrong in your own court of 
 appeal ; but neither can you prove yourself right. The oracles 
 of Nature are dumb, save to those who will compel her to 
 speak by torture, i.e. by experiment ; and, where experiment is 
 inapplicable, by rational interpretation of experience. 
 
 Whether we are attacking or defending any institution, it is 
 always well to be very sure that we are doing so on grounds 
 which admit of reasonable discussion. If it could be shown 
 that democratic republics would always fall a prey to military 
 despotism, either from within or from without, then we should 
 have to conclude that democratic republics were incompatible 
 with human well-being, and that monarchical or aristocratical 
 institutions were more in accordance with the "law of nature" 
 than democracy. 
 
 If it were certain that the nations of Western Europe or of 
 America, by checking industrial competition and by getting 
 rid of their armies, would fall a prey to a Chinese invasion, just 
 as the peaceful and Christianised Roman Empire succumbed 
 
 * As far as possible we must use machinery as a substitute for "living 
 tools" — the phrase by which Aristotle describes slaves, {l^ol.^ I. ■!.)
 
 To6 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 before the incursion of the northern barbarians, then it would 
 be right to do all in our power to keep up the military and 
 industrial pugnacity of the Western peoples, and all socialistic 
 and peaceful projects would be contrary to the " law of 
 nature." If it were certain that an equal or nearly equal dis- 
 tribution of the products of industry would lead to the decay < 
 and gradual disappearance of science, of art, and of all intel- 
 lectual pursuits generally, and a consequent return to savagery, 
 then any such levelling project would be contrary to the " law 
 of nature." If it were argued that the " Republic has no need 
 of chemists," we may be certain that it would be so much 
 worse for that republic in the long run ; it would go to pieces 
 before nations that did honour chemists, even if those nations 
 were ruled by despots. The reformer of society who would 
 convince those who hesitate to join him, from a fear not of 
 personal loss but of social retrogression, is bound to prove that 
 what he advocates is compatible with the welfare of society 
 and with its progress in the future. The only "law of nature" 
 to which we can listen must be such as will commend itself to 
 our reason as a statement of the principles of a coherent and 
 orderly society which will not throw away the hard-won 
 achievements of man in his struggle with nature and with 
 barbarism, and which will at the same time be progressive, 
 in the sense of being capable of correcting its own faults. Any 
 " natural rights " which are incompatible Avith such a society 
 are only another name for anarchy. "Nonsense upon stilts" 
 Bentham called them in his Anarchical Fallacies. Fiat 
 JHsfifia, mat caelum^ it may be said. But what does that 
 famous maxim of heroic virtue mean ? " Let justice be done, 
 though the heavens fall "—a maxim admirable as an answer 
 to those pessimists who would deter mankind from any at- 
 tempt to better its social organisation on the ground that this 
 planet cannot for ever support living beings. But whoever 
 says, " Fiat jmtitia^ mat respuhlica^^^ whoever appeals to an 
 abstract justice that is incompatible with the continuance of 
 orderly social organisation is, wittingly or unwittingly, talking 
 nonsense — and mischievous nonsense, too, " Justice " may be 
 incompatible with some particular form or phase of society : 
 that is likely enough. When people seriously appeal to justice 
 against society, what they really mean is that a higher form 
 of society should supersede a lower. But it would be much
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? 107 
 
 better to sa}^ so directly, and not to talk about natural rights 
 or abstract justice at all. A good cause is never benefited by 
 bad arguments.^ 
 
 If rights are determined solely by reference to human 
 society'', it follows that the lower animals, not being members 
 of human society, cannot have rights. This conclusion is 
 resented by many modern humanitarians who, feeling that in 
 some sense or other we may be said to have duties towards 
 the lower animals, or at least duties in respect of our conduct 
 towards them, conclude that the animals in their turn must 
 have rights against us. If a utilitarian theory be based on a 
 consideration of the pleasures of all sentient existence, then, 
 whether or not the phraseology of natural rights be used, all 
 animals must be taken into account in our judgments of 
 right and wrong. Very difficult questions of casuistry will, 
 indeed, arise because of the difference in grades of sentience ; 
 and the undoubted difference in degree of acuteness of feeling 
 among human beings ought most assuredly to be taken account 
 of also. If the recognition of Animal Rights is compatible with 
 the kindly use of a horse as a beast of burden, would not a 
 kindly negro-slavery be also perfectly compatible with the 
 recognition of Natural Rights generally ? And if we dis- 
 criminate between what may be rightly done to the mollusc 
 from what may be rightly done to the mammal, on grounds of 
 different grades of sentience, should we not also — if sentience 
 be our sole guiding principle — discriminate between what may 
 be rightly done to lower and higher races among mankind — 
 the lower and less civilised being undoubtedly less capable of 
 
 ' In his excellent little book, First Steps in Philosophy, witli the 
 " physical " part of which I entirely agree, Mr. W. M. Salter says : '' It 
 miglit be better that there should be no animal or human life than that 
 it should maintain itself by violating ethical requirements" (p. 107). 
 Unless for those who believe ethical requirements to be determined by 
 arbitrary and irrational volitions of Deity, I can see no meaning in Mr. 
 Salter's proposition. Morality may include more than can properly be 
 expressed as "social duty," e.g. the " intellectual virtues" and the duties 
 of cultivating science and art and learning may not be capable of 
 analysis into social virtues and duties (I cannot discuss that question 
 here) ; but morality that would lead to the destruction of ail human life 
 seems to me a very immoral kind of morality, though a kind of morality 
 of which we have* had a good deal too much in the ])ast. As to the 
 animals — I discuss that question. Is it the tiger's ethical standard or 
 ours, which is to decide?
 
 io8 irHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 acute feeling ? An ethical theory which is based on the social 
 nature of man is not directly troubled by these difficulties, 
 though in the details of practical conduct these grades of 
 sentience do enter in as one of the factors determining our 
 moral judgments. 
 
 The most recent English book of which I know on the sub- 
 ject of Animals' Rights is that of Mr. H. S. Salt. "Have the 
 lower animals 'rights'?" he asks, and answers his question, 
 " Undoubtedly — if men have." But the question whether and 
 in what sense men have rights, Mr. Salt refuses to discuss. 
 He takes for granted that in some sense they have rights, 
 and treats the controversy about rights as " little else than an 
 academic battle over words, which leads to no practical con- 
 clusion." The term "academic" is apparently used as a term 
 of dispraise. For this, unfortunately, the past traditions of 
 learned societies may be to blame ; or is a disparagement of 
 logic and of all careful use of language merely one of the notes 
 of the higher barbarism of the new school of Rousseauists ? I 
 have tried to show that there is a sense in which the term 
 '■natural rights" may be harmlessly used, but it is a sense 
 which needs caution ; and therefore, if the term be used at 
 all, it should not be used except in " academic " discussions. 
 Otherwise its use can only be regarded as a rhetorical device 
 for gaining a point without the trouble of proving it — a device 
 which may be left to the stump-orator or party-journalist, but 
 which should be discredited in all serious writing. Mr. Salt's 
 justification for his assertion, that animals have rights if men 
 have, must be discovered incidentally. First of all, I note that 
 he appeals to the actual state of the law in England. "It is 
 scarcely possible, in the face of this legislation [for the preven- 
 tion of cruelty to animals], to maintain that ' rights ' are a 
 privilege with which none but human beings can be invested ; 
 for if some animals are already included within the pale of 
 protection, why should not more and more be so included 
 in the future?"^ Because a work of art or some ancient 
 monument is protected by law from injury, do we speak 
 of the "rights" of pictures or stones? Further, are animals 
 capable of being parties to a lawsuit ? It might be answered, 
 they are on the same footing permanently on which human 
 " infants " are temporarily {i.e. until they attain full age). But 
 ^ Auirnals' liiyhts, p. 8.
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTSl 109 
 
 if there are rights, there are correlative duties. And whereas 
 infants may be tried on a criminal charge, I do not know, 
 apart from a cause celebre in Aristoj)hanes, of any such trial 
 of animals in any advanced legal system. Thus it will hardly 
 do to appeal to existing law in proof that animals have rights 
 in any legal sense. Again, I note that Mr. Salt quotes with 
 approbation the maxim of the "Buddhist and Pythagorean 
 canons " ^ — " Not to kill or injure any innocent animal," and 
 the words of Bentham : " We have begun hy attending to the 
 condition of slaves ; we shall finish by softening that of all the 
 animals which assist our labours or supply our wants." '^ Why 
 these limitations of the jus animalium? If the animal as such 
 has rights, who are we to pronounce judgment, according to our 
 own human convenience, on his " innocence " ? What is the 
 "guilt " from the tiger's point of view of her raid on a human 
 village ? Why do we commend a cat that kills mice and punish 
 her if she attacks a tame bird ? If the animals were consulted, 
 they would choose to be tried by a jury of their peers, before 
 the question of guilt or innocence were decided. The most 
 despotic kings have always been quite willing to leave in 
 peace those of their subjects who contributed to their conveni- 
 ence, or whom they regarded as harmless. The Czar of Russia 
 does not oppress any one whom he regards as " innocent." 
 The claim of natural rights among men has meant something 
 very much more than a claim that the innocent should be 
 kindly treated, the arbitrary government against which they 
 protested being free to decide the question of innocence. 
 
 It may be admitted, however, that towards the lower animals 
 we must always stand in the relation of despots ; but it may be 
 urged that our despotism ought to be guided by a recognition 
 of their rights. Well, then, in our exercise of our power and 
 in our guardianship of the rights of animals, must we not pro- 
 tect the weak among them against the strong? Must we not 
 put to death blackbirds and thrushes because they feed on 
 worms, or (if capital punishment offends our humanitarianism) 
 starve them slowly by permanent captivity and vegetarian diet? 
 What becomes of the " return to nature " if wo must prevent 
 the cat's nocturnal wanderings, lest she should wickedly slay a 
 mouse ? Are we not to vindicate the rights of the persecuted 
 prey of the stronger? or is our declaration of the rights of 
 ' Animals'' Rights, p. 3. ^ Ibid., p. G.
 
 no WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 every creeping thing to remain a mere hypocritical formula to 
 gratify jnig-loving sentimentaUsts, who prate about a nature 
 they will not take the trouble to understand — a nature whose 
 genuine students they are ready to persecute '? Mr. Salt 
 injures a needed protest against certain barbarities of " sport," 
 and against the habitual callousness of the ignorant in their 
 treatment of animals, by his attacks on men of science and his 
 opposition to the use of animal food. If all the world were 
 Jews, it has been well said, there would be no pigs in existence; 
 and if all the world were vegetarians, would there be any sheep 
 or cattle, well cared for and guarded against starvation ? Per- 
 haps a stray specimen in a zoological garden : turnips being 
 all needed for human food. Cruelty to animals is rightly sup- 
 posed to be an offence against humanitarian feeling. Our duty 
 to the animals is a duty to human society. It is an offence 
 against civilised life to cause any unnecessary suffering, or to 
 do any unnecessary damage — " unnecessary " meaning, as it 
 means even in Mr. Salt's theory, unnecessary for human well- 
 being. This consideration will explain also why we regard 
 cruelty to domestic animals, especially to pets, with more 
 horror than cruelty to wild animals — especially to dangerous 
 or injurious wild animals. We have admitted certain animals 
 to a sort of honorary membership of our society ; and we come 
 to think of them as standing in a quasi-human relation to our- 
 selves, especially when we give them names of their own, as if 
 they were persons. Of Schopenhauer, that poodle-loving hater 
 of man, it might almost be said that he and his dog (the reign- 
 ing sovereign for the time) formed a society by themselves. In 
 a metaphorical sense we may be said to have duties towards 
 these honorary human beings.^ 
 
 Pain is in itself an evil, not in the special moral sense of the 
 term " evil," but in the sense that it is an impediment to the 
 maintenance and development of life : it is an impediment 
 which every normal sentient being "naturally," i.e. by mere 
 instinct, strives to escape, and this instinct is kept alert by 
 natural selection. The growth of sympathy and of imagina- 
 tion makes it possible for human beings to feel mental pain at 
 the sufferings of other human beings, even of those not speci- 
 ally connected with them, and of other animals, in a manner 
 
 * Comte holds that the animals that help mankind form a part of 
 hnmanitj-. Positive Polity (Eng. trans.), IV. pp. 33, 312.
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? m 
 
 and to an extent impossible in a more primitive stage of exist- 
 ence. (The real savage and our sentimental neo-savage are 
 very different persons in this respect.) And thus the avoid- 
 ance of pain for other beings capable of feeling it, as well as 
 for oneself, comes to be thought of as a duty, except when the 
 infliction of such pain is necessary and unavoidable in the 
 interests of human society and human progress. Thus we 
 may be said to have duties of T^mdnesH towards the animals ; 
 but it is incorrect to represent these as strictly duties towards 
 the animals themselves, as if they had rights against us. If 
 the animals had in any proper sense rights, we should no more 
 be entitled to put them to death without a fair trial, unless in 
 strict self-defence, than to torture them for our amusement. 
 It is our duty to put animals to death as painlessly as possible, 
 when we wish their death for any human end ; and similarly, 
 in experiments on living animals for scientific purposes, it is 
 right to prefer the less highly organised animal to the more 
 highly organised, wherever the lower type is clearly sufficient 
 for the purposes of the experiment. It is a duty also not to 
 cause any suffering which is unnecessary for the properly 
 scientific purpose of the experiment. The evil of pain is the 
 element of permanent truth in the Hedonist protest against 
 Asceticism ; but to make the mere fact of sentience the deter- 
 mining principle of right and wrong in ethics is the abstrac- 
 tion that renders Hedonism, even in its universalistic form, an 
 inadequate ethical theory. I have already suggested the diffi- 
 culties which would be involved in any consistent attempt to 
 recognise in animals equal rights with human beings: on the 
 other hand, to fix a scale of unequal rights solely from the 
 point of view of human convenience is practically to give up 
 basing ethics on the mere fact of sentience, and implicitly to 
 recognise the interests of human society as our ultimate 
 criterion of right and wrong. 
 
 In the foregoing discussion of the ethical end I have included 
 the notion of the progress, as well as that of the maintenance, 
 of human society. And on this difficult conception uf " pro- 
 gress " I must therefore say a few words. In the first place, 
 it must be pointed out that progress is not identical with 
 evolution, as that term is used by biologists.^ Natural selec- 
 
 ' A confusion on this subject runs througli tlic whole of Mr. Benjuniiu 
 Kidd's book on Social Evolution.
 
 112 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? [ch. v 
 
 tion produces degeneration of organisms as well as advance. 
 In the struggle for existence, success may be obtained by 
 assimilation to a simpler type. Success does not necessaril}'- 
 imply increasing complexity and differentiation of structure. 
 And so it is with human beings regarded from a purely bio- 
 logical point of view. The highly cultured European, who 
 would adapt himself to the environment of the Esquimaux, 
 must discard those habits of life which raise him above the 
 Esquimaux from the point of view of sociology. A man may 
 succeed in the competition of the commercial world by greater 
 skill and efficiency in the management of his business, by 
 stricter honesty, by turning out better goods, by employing 
 more highly paid and capable workmen than his rivals. He 
 may succeed by these means, under sufficiently favourable 
 conditions, in the long run — if he gets a sufficiently long run. 
 But under other conditions he may succeed, and may more 
 easily obtain a rapid success, by skilful unscrupulousness, by 
 extensive advertising, by judicious underselling and driving 
 his rivals out of the field, etc. An old business man is said to 
 have enforced the maxim, " Honesty is the best policy," by 
 adding, " I've tried both " ; but there is a good deal of evidence 
 to support the inference that " to get honest " is only the best 
 policy for those who have already managed " to get on." The 
 big, successful business can be conducted on better principles 
 than the struggling one. 
 
 When by reflection we have once reached an ethical stan- 
 dard, when we judge human conduct from the point of view 
 of an ideal society, we become very fully conscious of the 
 discrepancy between "adaptation to environment," which 
 means pleasure and the absence of pain, and advance towards 
 ideal excellence ; and the pessimist is at hand to declare that 
 all intellectual and aesthetic and ethical advance means only 
 an increase of sorrow. Increasing complexity of structure 
 makes adaptation to environment more difficult, except in so 
 far as the euvironment can itself he controlled and altered. But 
 this control and alteration of the environment is just what the 
 intellectual conquests of mankind make possible. As we 
 understand nature better, and as we understand human nature 
 better, we can secure adaptation and adjustment by bending 
 nature in many ways to ourselves instead of bending ourselves 
 in every respect to nature. The torrent that sweeps awa3^
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? 113 
 
 the rude hut of the savage, if confined within barriers and 
 regulated by sluices, will grind corn and supply electricity for 
 the service of civilised man. The energy and desire to excel 
 which makes the Indian scalp his enemies is identical with 
 that " last infirmity of noble mind " which may stimulate the 
 researches of the savant, lighten the labours of the legislator, 
 and even add inspiration to the imaginative work of the crea- 
 tive artist, as it undoubtedly does to the performance of the 
 actor or of the musician. "We change the channels in Avhich 
 competition runs, and it becomes beneficial instead of hurtful. 
 May we then attempt a definition of Progress, in the only 
 sense in which Progress can be an end of action, as such in- 
 creasing complexity of structure as is compatible not only with 
 increasing "integration" but with increasing, or at least un- 
 diminished adaptation to environment ? This definition, it 
 may be objected, is only the old commonplace about " Order 
 and Progress " disguised in a new form of Spencerian phrase- 
 ology. Well, in a sense it is, but it is the old commonplace 
 divested of the fallacy which, by separating progress from 
 order, identifies progress with mere change — with mere insta- 
 bility. The old practical difficulties still remain, of course. 
 Change, variation, increasing complexity necessarily unsettle 
 the existing adjustments, which, however, are apt to seem 
 more settled and stable than they really are. But the merit 
 of the suggested definition of progress is this : that, while the 
 preference is given to the more highly developed structure, the 
 need of adaptation to environment is not ignored, and the 
 practical importance is indicated of adapting the environment, 
 so far as possible, to the higher structure. The mere fact of 
 adaptation to environment, i.e. the mere fact of contentment, 
 pleasure, absence of pain, absence of effort, is of itself no proof 
 of excellence. The more complex structure, it must be noted, 
 is not per se the higher, unless there is greater "integration," 
 as well as greater differentiation.^ If the complexity be such 
 
 ' Complexity in any case is not the same thing as mere complication. 
 When " simplification " is accepted as an ideal, it must be clearly under- 
 stood that simplification does not mean loss of organs. " Simplification " 
 is really an ambiguous way of expressing " greater integration " as an 
 ideal, because it may also mean degeneration. A concrete illustration 
 may help us to see more clearly the true relation of complexity to pro- 
 gress. A man who can talk several languages with ease, who is well 
 acquainted with history and literature, who has some knowledge of 
 N. K. I
 
 114 IVHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS'! [ch. v 
 
 that in no conceivable conditions could the organism work 
 well, the more complex is not higher than the simpler. But 
 tiie more complex structure which is capable of working better 
 in suitable surroundings than the less complex may work 
 worse in inferior surroundings ; and yet we should not be jus- 
 tified in calling it ethically inferior, simply because of that 
 want of adaptation. This is one way in which the defect of 
 the strict Hedonist ethics becomes apparent. To the Hedonist 
 the mere fact of contentment should be enough. Socrates dis- 
 satisfied, however, is better, as J. S. Mill says, than the pig 
 satisfied ; but Socrates dissatisfied is not the ideal. The want 
 of adaptation and the consequent pain is a proof of imperfec- 
 tion. The higher natures have always to suffer just because 
 they are in advance of their surroundings.^ But for the future 
 well-being and better-being of society, even this suffering is to 
 be preferred to an adaptation attained by the sacrifice of any 
 form of realisation of human faculty which is not incompatible 
 with the general well-being of an improved society. Even a 
 sufficient dole of bread all round would be dearly purchased at 
 the cost of stopping the work of the savant and the artist. 
 Those who trj^ to live by bread alone will soon have to live on 
 an inferior kind of bread. As I have tried to show in a pre- 
 vious chapter, the only consistent assailants of civilisation are 
 those who, like the Cjaiics, are deliberatel}^ prepared to go back 
 to savagery ; and if they trj^ to put their precepts into prac- 
 tice, whether by using dynamite, or by refusing to submit to 
 sanitary laws, civilised society must take the necessary mea- 
 sures against them. 
 
 several natural sciences, wlio can climb mountains, and ride, and row, 
 who can keep liis health and vigour either in town or country — " an all- 
 rouud man," in fact — is a more efficient person in everj- way than one 
 ■who can onl^' get on in a particular groove. But he who can get on in a 
 particular groove, though only in one, is more efficient than the person 
 who knows several languages, but cannot express himself intelligibly or 
 easily in an.y one of them, who can do many things, but does them all 
 badly, etc. Dr. Johnson's warning is always useful : " A man may be so 
 much of everything, that he is nothing of anything." (Hence the sound- 
 ness of the precept in learning — to aim at knowing everything about 
 something, and something about everything.) When we ask, not which 
 individual stands " higher," but which society, the problem is necessarily 
 much more complicated. 
 
 ' Of course, the lower natui-es in a superior environment suffer also. 
 Punishment is one form of that suffering.
 
 CH. v] WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS? 115 
 
 In conclusion, there are two questions about " natural rights" 
 which might claim to be noticed. The first concerns a matter 
 of scientific or theoretical convenience ; the second concerns a 
 matter of practical or political convenience. (1) Ought a 
 treatise on politics to begin with a statement of individual 
 rights ? (2) Ought the constitution of a countrj' to guarantee 
 certain rights to its citizens, and to protect them from legisla- 
 tive interference '? 
 
 With regard to the first of these questions, I should only say 
 that such a treatment presents some apparent logical advan- 
 tages, but has the drawback of being chieffj^ associated with 
 theories of Natura,l Law, which assume that we can formulate 
 natural rights irrespective of, and prior to, any consideration of 
 society. 
 
 The second question is practically the question whether a 
 rigid constitution, like the American, or a fluid constitution like 
 our own, is preferable. Now that is a question which hardly 
 admits of a general or abstract answer. In some cases a writ- 
 ten constitution is an inevitable necessity. The stability of 
 the Federal constitution of the United States has been of an 
 undoubted advantage to that country ; in the reverence for its 
 written constitution its citizens have found a safeguard against 
 the instabihty that might have been expected to arise among 
 a people whose independent history began in the violence of a 
 revolutionary war and in a professed breach with the traditions 
 of the past, and whose numbers are constantly being recruited 
 by the fragments and separated atoms of alien societies. On 
 the other hand, the rigidity of the constitution made a war 
 necessary in order to get rid of the institution of slavery, and 
 of the idea that there was a " right " of secession. And it is 
 possible that other questions ma}' arise in which a conflict 
 between modern needs and the theories of the eighteenth 
 century about individual rights may prove harsher and more 
 terrible because of the barriers placed in the way of change. 
 With regard to the Staie constitutions in America, the jealousy 
 of legislatures leads to the citizens every now and then 
 making the attempt to legislate for themselves on minute 
 points, the result being called a " constitution." This can only 
 be regarded as a very clumsy method of legislation. A far 
 better and safer way of guarding against the recklessness or 
 corruption of legislators is the Swiss device of the ReferenrfiDii
 
 ii6 WHAT DETERMINES RIGHTS! [ch. v 
 
 — to let the legislators do their work, and then subject it as 
 a whole to the approval of the electorate.^ 
 
 In regard to some particular rights, as we shall see in the 
 following chapters, something may be said for permanent and 
 express guarantees such as we have not yet been accustomed 
 to feel the need of in this country. 
 
 ' The case for written constitutions and for the referendum is very 
 lucidly and ably argued in Dr. Charles Borgeaud's work, £tablessement 
 et Revisions des Constitutions en Amerique et en Europe (Paris, 1893). 
 Many of those, Avho in this country are most willing to adopt political in- 
 novations, feel that the time has hardly yet come when it would be safe 
 to crj'stallise our fluid constitution ; and even the referendum might, if 
 pirematurely introduced, impede some salutary changes. The arguments 
 for and against the referendum do not, however, belong to my present 
 svibject.
 
 PART II 
 PARTICULAR NATURAL RIGHTS 
 
 117
 
 CHAPTER VI 
 
 THE RIGHT OF LIFE 
 
 I PROPOSE, ill this and the following chapters, applying the 
 results now reached, to examine in detail the most prominent 
 of those " natural rights " which have been claimed in the 
 American and French declarations. In several of the Ameri- 
 can State-constitutions are specially enumerated those " of 
 enjoying and defending life and liberty, acquiring, possess- 
 ing, and protecting property, and pursuing and obtaining 
 safety and happiness." 
 
 The right of life or the right to life may reasonably be 
 considered first. Now, what does this mean ? («) There is 
 the animal instinct of self-preservation, which undoubtedly is 
 "natural." It represents a tendency which we may trace 
 farther back even than the animal world, and may identify 
 with the vis inertice of the physicist, with what Thomas 
 Aquinas calls the tendency of every substance to seek the 
 preservation of its own being,^ with what Spinoza calls the 
 conatus sese con.se rccmdi.^ But what sense is there in calling 
 this natural instinct a " right " ? If by natural rights be meant 
 those rights which a well-constituted society ought to guar- 
 antee to its members, then whether preservation of life is to 
 be guaranteed or not must surely depend on whether the life is 
 valuable to the society or injurious to it, or on whether, though 
 not valuable, or even to some extent injurious, other considera- 
 tions of general security, etc., make it expedient to give the 
 preservation of such life the support of the organised force of 
 the community. The natural instinct to preserve life is an 
 instinct which may be furthered by reflection, and it may 
 come to be thought a duty to preserve one's life. But, on 
 the other hand, the natural instinct may be overcome by 
 reflection, and it may come to be thought a duty not to pre- 
 serve life, or only a secondary duty, subordinate to others, 
 
 ' fSunwia, la 2ae, qu. 94, art. 2. ^ Ethica, III., Prop. 7. 
 
 iia
 
 I20 THE RIGHT OF LIFE [ch. vi 
 
 Even apart from reflection the instinct to preserve life often 
 gives way before other instincts, e.g. the desire to preserve off- 
 spring, or even the desire to gratify passion. 
 
 The principle that there is an inalienable and imprescriptible 
 right in all men to preserve their lives, however much social 
 utility may demand the sacrifice of some lives — still more the 
 principle that all sentient beings (for where among them are 
 we to draw the line, if we once pass beyond the circle of 
 human society ?) possess such a right — would bring all regu- 
 lated action to a standstill, and would lead to a rapid disap- 
 pearance of the civilised men who adopted such a principle 
 before barbarians who did not, or, if all mankind adopted it, to 
 a disappearance of human beings before wild beasts. Re- 
 stricted to human beings, the idea of such an inalienable 
 natural right undoubtedl}' lies at the back of the objection to 
 capital punishment, although the plea for its abolition is usually 
 supported by utilitarian arguments, such as, that a convicted 
 person may afterwards be discovered to be innocent and that 
 therefore no penalty should be incapable of being reversed, etc. 
 Now, if the right to preserve life has any meaning, it must 
 include the right to defend life, and that may involve as a 
 matter of necessity the right to take the life of others (men or 
 beasts). It is easy for the theoretical moralist to say that 
 self-defence is justifiable, but that under no circumstances is 
 aggression justifiable ; as a matter of fact, those who justify 
 aggression among civilised communities justify it, as a rule, 
 on the ground that what appears aggression is really, directly 
 or indirectly, self-defence. All preventive measures may be 
 classed, by an unsympathetic onlooker, under the term 
 " aggression." To be able to call a measure " a measure of 
 self-defence " does not of itself prove that measure to be justifi- 
 able, nor does calling it "a measure of aggression" of itself 
 prove it unjustifiable. We must know wliat is being defended, 
 and on wliat aggression is being made, before we can know 
 whether the defence or the aggression is justifiable in the 
 interests of some particular society, or of humanity as a whole, 
 or of some important part of it. 
 
 Now on the same general principle on which the man who 
 is attacked may, with the conscience of the world approving 
 him, kill his assailant, if he has reasonable grounds for be- 
 lieving that so strong a measure is necessary for preserving
 
 CH. VI ] THE RIGHT OF LIFE 121 
 
 his own life — on tlie same principle an organised society- 
 may use the necessary force (which may include destruction of 
 life) in order to secure its members against loss of their 
 various guaranteed rights of life, liberty, securit}^, etc. This 
 will justify at least some wars, and the use of such penalties 
 for the punishment of offenders as will save the communit}- 
 from danger. If possible, punishment should aim at the 
 restoration of the offender to the character of a good citizen ; 
 but whether in any case that is possible or not, punishment 
 must at lea^t serve as a deterrent to other possible offenders, 
 and it must keep the more dangerous criminal from doing 
 further injur3\ Whether the punishment of death is necessarj- 
 or not, and to what offences it should be limited, is thus a 
 question of social expediency ; and among the elements that 
 must be taken account of in determining this social expedi- 
 enc}^, the prevalent opinion on the subject is an important 
 factor which it is alwa3^s unsafe to neglect. If there is a 
 widespread horror of the infliction of the punishment of death 
 for some offences or for all, the legal enactment of the 
 punishment may do more harm than good. When juries are 
 induced to bring in a verdict of "not guilty " because, con- 
 trary to their sentiment, death is the penalty for the offence 
 of which they really believe the accused to be guilty, societ}' 
 suffers by having a criminal let loose upon it, and by a 
 weakening of the sense of responsibility on the part of those 
 called to discharge a public duty. On the other hand, whereas 
 to many sensitive and cultured natures a long term of im- 
 prisonment may seem a much more terrible penalt}^ than a 
 quick and probably almost painless death, the popular senti- 
 ment about death may make it expedient to retain the penalt}' 
 for the gravest crimes, experience seeming to show that, if 
 really enforced, it serves the purpose of a deterrent better than 
 any other penalty. The growing attention paid to the element 
 of heredity in the production of crime leads many persons to 
 recognise that hereditary criminals should, if possible, be kept 
 from propagating their undesirable qualities. This in some 
 cases may reinforce the argument for the death-penalty, es- 
 pecially as life-long imprisonment is not only very cruel to 
 the individual, but very costly to the community, it 1)eing 
 impossible to make the labour of convicts profitable without 
 competing in the labour market to tlie disadvantage of the
 
 122 THE RIG FIT OF LIFE [ch. vi 
 
 non-criminal population. On the other hand the sense of the 
 value of all life is on the whole a useful moral factor in 
 societ}^ and, wherever it seems safe to do so, the penalty of 
 death may with soine advantage be abolished. To put a 
 human being to death means to give up the problem of 
 making anything of him. Some criminals who have not com- 
 mitted murder may be more dangerous than some who have, 
 but the popular feeling about a fitness between penalty and 
 offence may render it desirable to restrict the death-penalty to 
 such cases, unless and until the popular sentiment can be 
 altered. The murderer, provided that he be not an insane 
 person afflicted with homicidal mania, is indeed less likely, if 
 let loose on society, to repeat his offence than the thief, the 
 forger, the person guilty of cruelty to children or of assaults on 
 women ; and if the protection of society from those who have 
 already committed crimes against it were the only matter to 
 be considered, the penalty of death might seem quite un- 
 reasonable as applied to the murderer alone. But the effect of 
 the penalty as a deterrent to others is the more important 
 matter, and the average sentiment on the subject is therefore 
 of essential moment. As has frequently been pointed out, the 
 chief or sole reason for visiting murder with a severer penalty 
 than any other crime, is to remove the inducement which the 
 person committing any other offence (such as robbery or rape) 
 might otherwise have to add murder to the crime already 
 committed. If you hang for everything that moves j'our in- 
 dignation strongly, the criminal is tempted to get full value 
 for the price he may have to pay, especially as murdered persons 
 cannot appear as witnesses in court. The growth of a senti- 
 ment against any use of the punishment of death was chiefly 
 due to the reckless use of the penalty for offences of very 
 different kinds. 
 
 The individual has no inalienable right of preserving his 
 life against the society which secures him from aggression. 
 This is admitted, I believe, by all the theorists of natural 
 right except anarchists. Continued obedience, including the 
 acceptance of laws which in certain cases impose the penalty of 
 death, is indeed made conditional on the general security and 
 protection afforded by these laws. But what rights of self-pre- 
 servation has the society itself ? The necessity of a society's 
 preserving itself is, on the principles of evolutionist utilitari- 
 
 ^
 
 CH. vi] THE RIGHT OF LIFE 123 
 
 anism, made the basis for those rights which the society as a 
 whole has against its members — rights which might be called 
 "natural " in the sense of being necessary to the existence of 
 the society, but which are not usually called "natural," be- 
 cause the theory of natural rights belongs to an individualistic 
 type of thinking. On the other hand the right of the society 
 as a whole to maintain its existence against rebels within it, or 
 against the hostility of other societies, may be called "natural,"' 
 in the sense of not depending upon any human institution. 
 Such " natural right," however, as we have seen, is identical 
 with might or force. Even civilised nations are still to one 
 another in Hobbes's " state of nature " — a state of war miti- 
 gated only b}^ the growth of a certain international moral 
 sentiment and the consequent observance of a certain code of 
 honour, as it might be called, which, having a quasi-legal 
 character, is termed International Law. The idea, however 
 vague and ill-defined, of a community of civilised nations, and 
 the still vaguer and less-defined idea of a possible community 
 of all mankind, do give a certain rudimentary social meaning 
 to the " rights " of political societies ; and it is a convention of 
 International Law to treat each society w^hich can manage to 
 assert and maintain its independence as a unit which has a 
 certain right of self-preservation. The point at which a group 
 of rebels becomes a separate and independent State, or the point 
 at which a revolutionary party becomes the de facto government, 
 are matters on which other nations may decide differently with- 
 out necessarily contravening any principle of international law 
 or morality. The existence of any particular social organism 
 (either a political society or any other), not being of an abso- 
 lute value, but simply a means towards the well-being of 
 individuals,^ there can be no absolute moral right of self- 
 preservation in a society against some higher or better type of 
 society in which these individuals may be absorbed, or against 
 the formation of more closely coherent and better societies out 
 of an ill-compacted unity. Thus we do not consider that 
 humanity lost, but the reverse, by the absorption of Tuscany 
 in Italy, or by the separation of Belgium from Holland. The 
 right of self-preservation in a society is only valid against 
 individuals who would break it up into mere chaos, not against 
 
 ' I emphasise the word " particular," because the existence of a social 
 organism of some kind is essential to the well-being of individuals.
 
 124 THE RIGHT OF LIFE [ch. vi 
 
 au}' better form of society (whether previously existing, or in 
 process of formation) which ma}' take its place. "Where 
 societies are in a process of transition, it may indeed be very 
 difficult for individuals to decide where their strongest duty of 
 allegiance lies ; and in our historical judgments we are fre- 
 quently compelled to give our warmest praise to some of those 
 who from unselfish motives have been loj'al to lost causes or to 
 causes successful at the time, which we have come to consider 
 mistaken. In judging about the value for mankind of revolu- 
 tions, of secessions, of unifications, of annexations, we gain 
 nothing in clearness of thinking, but the very reverse, by talk- 
 ing about all nations or tribes as if their unity was of an abso- 
 lute character, and a> if the rights of such tmits as against one 
 another had any existence except in the opinions of human 
 beings, which opinions may change, although in regard to such 
 matters historical prescription is one of the most important 
 factors in keeping opinions uniform. Past history*, or past 
 tradition belief is more important than fact in influencing 
 popular sentiment), determines to a great extent what societies 
 seem '• natural " units with rio-hts worth struo-glino; for, and 
 what societies do not.^ 
 
 (6) Does the right to preserve one's life imply the right to 
 put an end to it ? If the right possessed bj' an individual over 
 his own life is analogous to the right possessed by him over pro- 
 perty, it might be argued that the right to retain implied the 
 corresponding right to destroy. On the other side it might be 
 urged that the destruction of life, bj* putting an end to all 
 rights, contradicted the very idea of individual rights (which 
 are all based on the primary right to preserve life), and there- 
 fore could not be one of them. Between these two abstract 
 arguments I shall not attempt to decide. If, on the other 
 
 ^ In. dealing with the question of the right of self-preserration. I have 
 unavoidably been. led to refer also to the right of liberty or independence. 
 It is one of the proofs of the abstractness of the theorj- of natural rights, 
 that it obliges us to separate elements that are inseparable in fact. This 
 is an objection which applies, indeed, to every attempt to arrange human 
 relationships under distinctive categories, though it applies much less to 
 the grouping of them according to institutions, e.g. the family (or if that 
 seems to assume a definite type of organisation, say the relations of the 
 sexes and the relation of parent and child), industrial relations, etc., than 
 to the grouping of thera according to the recognised or alleged rights 
 of individuals.
 
 CH. vi] THE RIGHT OF LIFE 125 
 
 hand, self-preservation be regarded as a social duiij^ the ques- 
 tion will still arise whether a life that is no longer of any- 
 utility to the community may not rightly be taken ; and if so, 
 whether we may not say that the individual in question has a 
 right to take it. It is clear, however, that, when we look at 
 the matter from the social point of view, it must be the society 
 and not the individual that ought to judge. Individuals who 
 may feel their life a burden to themselves may still be capable 
 of some social service ; and, if they were occupied in doing 
 such service, would most probably feel their life less of a 
 burden : while those who are of no social utility, and are, in 
 fact, a burden to others, may not be inclined to remove them- 
 selves. Very different views have been held respecting 
 suicide at different times ; and the tendency to seek refuge in 
 death varies greatly among different races. The Christian 
 Churches have universally condemned it in all circumstances ; 
 but popular sentiment among Christian nations has been ready 
 to find excuses for it in certain cases. The conflict between 
 law and sentiment in our own country leads to the customary 
 verdict of " temporary insanity " wherever a plausible pretext 
 can be found, and sometimes where it cannot. At the most, 
 however, suicide is excused, but not approved. When a de- 
 tected scoundrel takes his life in order to escape his trial or his 
 punishment, people may agree with Aristotle ^ in calling the 
 act the act of a coward, rather than of a brave man ; and j^et 
 there is often a feeling of relief at his disappearance, and 
 sometimes even a qualified admiration for the relative courage 
 of the act. The unsuccessful patriot, who kills himself to 
 avoid dragging out a dishonoured existence, or in despair at 
 the failure of the cause to which he had devoted his life, is 
 looked on with admiration, in spite of the effect of Christian 
 teaching, Philip Strozzi, who killed himself through fear that 
 torture might extract from him revelations injurious to his 
 friends, is said to have prayed that, if he must be damned, he 
 might occupy the same part of hell with Cato."- In the case of 
 some suicides, we blame social conditions rather than the indi- 
 vidual ; a poem like Hood's Bridge of SigJi>i represents a ver}' 
 widely diffused sentiment. 
 
 Thomas Aquinas (Summa, 2a, 28e, qu. 6-i, art. 6) lays down 
 
 ' Eth. Nic, III. 7, § 13. 
 
 - Leckj", European Mo)'als (ed. 3.), H. p. 56.
 
 126 THE RIGHT OF LIFE [ch. vi 
 
 unequivocally that "to kill oneself is altogether unlawful, for 
 three reasons. First, because naturally everything loves itself, 
 and consequently everything naturally preserves itself in 
 being, and resists destroying agencies as much as it can. And 
 therefore for any one to kill himself is against a natural incli- 
 nation, and against the charitj^ wherewith he ought to love 
 himself. And, therefore, the killing of oneself is always a 
 mortal sin, as being against natural law and against charity. 
 Secondly, because all that any part is, is of the whole. But 
 every man is of the community ; and so what he is, is of the 
 community ; hence, in killing himself he does an injury to the 
 community. Thirdly, because life is a gift divinely bestowed 
 on man, and subject to His power ' who killeth and maketh 
 alive.' And therefore he who takes his own life sins against 
 God." 
 
 The last of these arguments is identical with that used by 
 Socrates in Plato's Phcedo (62). The second is that of Aristotle 
 m the fifth book of the Ethics} The first, which Father Rickaby 
 (from whose translation I have quoted) considers " perhaps the 
 best of the three," is the only one that turns on the idea of a 
 Law of Nature. If there is any force in the argument, it seems 
 equally applicable to all actions contrary to natural inclination, 
 and certainly to many ascetic practices and abstinences, which 
 may be regarded as slow suicide, and which, so far from being 
 condemned by Catholic theologians, ma}^ even constitute a 
 claim to saintship. 
 
 Sir Thomas More, who died for his constancy to the Roman 
 Catholic faith, suggests in his Utopia the expediency, not 
 merely of permitting, but of recommending suicide to those 
 suffering from incurable diseases ; no suicides, however, are to 
 receive honourable burial who have not received public 
 authority for the act. Something like this suggestion of the 
 Utopia was actuallj'- the custom in the Greek colon}^ of Massilia 
 (Marseilles). If a man wished to die, he must apply to the Six 
 Hundred ; and if he made out a good case, he was allowed a dose 
 of poison.- Not a few physicians have felt the terrible cruelty 
 of a moral code which makes it a positive duty on their part 
 to prolong hopeless suffering. Yet it is clearly a matter that 
 cannot be left to individual responsibility. Would a license 
 to die necessarily be a more injurious institution than "that 
 ' Kill. Nic, V. 11, § 3. - Valerius Maximus. II. 6.
 
 CH. vi] THE RIGHT OF LIFE 127 
 
 charitable perjury of juries" (as Mr. Leckj' calls it) to which 
 we are accustomed ? 
 
 (c) The subject last discussed ma}^ suggest the question 
 whether the right to life does not mean something more than 
 the mere right to maintain life under certain conditions — a right 
 which is fully secured to all inhabitants of the United King- 
 dom by our Poor Laws. The American declarations speak of 
 enjoying life ; and this implies an assertion of a natural right 
 to a life worth living. But this includes all the other natural 
 rights, and cannot, therefore, be discussed as a right by itself 
 apart from them. As a matter of history, the demand to 
 enjoy and defend life is simply part of the protest against 
 arbitrar}^ government ; it is the demand to belong to a com- 
 munity with responsible government. 
 
 {d) A very important, but often neglected question remains. 
 Does the right to life include the right to be well-born ? — that 
 is to say, the right to start with a hereditary equij)ment which 
 at the least shall not foredoom its possessor to hopeless misery ? 
 If this right is to be recognised, there must be a good deal of 
 interference with some other alleged natural rights. 
 
 When Robespierre put forward his " Declaration of the 
 Rights of Man " in the Jacobin club, it was opposed by one 
 member only, Boissel, who proposed in place of it another, 
 which began : Lefi droits natureJs des sanscidottes consistent dans 
 la facidte de se reproduiye, de sliahUJer, et de se nouriv. " The 
 natural rights of the unbreeched are to breed, to dress, and to 
 feed." This Declaration, we are told, was received with 
 general laughter, and no one supported it.^ The order in 
 which these " natural rights " are stated corresponds on the 
 whole to the order in which the " proletariat," true to the 
 etymology of the word, exercise these "natural rights." The 
 precept " to be fruitful and multiply " is observed with very 
 little regard to the possibilities of food and clothing. The in- 
 stinct of reproduction and the instinct to obtain food are the 
 primary " natural" instincts of all animals ; the desire for cloth- 
 ing among human animals, insufiftciently covered by Nature, 
 may be regarded as having developed out of the natural impulse 
 to seek shelter, except where, as in warm climates, it exists 
 under " natural " conditions simply as the desire for ornament or 
 
 ' Duvergier de Hauranne, Ilisfoire du gouvernement jiarlemenfa/re, I. 
 p. 277.
 
 [28 THE RIGHT OF LIFE [ch. vi 
 
 from , ideas about decency. In such a statement of natural 
 riglits there is certainly no " sacrifice of the natural rights of 
 living people to a superstition about the effect on posterity." ^ 
 Posterity is provided with life ; but there is no regard paid to 
 the quality of the life bestowed on those who have never been 
 consulted. Might it not be argued that, as children have no 
 voice in choosing their parents, those who are called into 
 existence without their own consent should have such a life 
 secured to them that they would have consented to accept it 
 had it been possible to consult them ? Such an argument 
 however strange it may seem, is of the very same kind with 
 the argument that a government, if it is to be obeyed, must 
 either have been consented to by the subjects, or be such as 
 they would have consented to. Both arguments, it may well 
 be said, refute themselves by being unworkable. Obedience 
 cannot depend merely on consent; else every government, and 
 the coherence of every political society, would be perpetually 
 at the mercy of every discontented or disorderly individual. 
 A liberiim veto in the hands of every citizen would produce 
 anarchy more surely even than did the liberum veto of the 
 Polish aristocracy. Similarly, no ameliorations of the evils of 
 human life, that we can conceive of in this world, will ever 
 prevent some of the children of men from uttering, in the 
 bitterness of their soul, the wish that they had never been born. 
 A society of sincere and consistent pessimists, if such persons 
 exist, and if a society of them could exist, might decide that 
 the gift of life was not worth handing on ; but such a society 
 would thereby rapidly become extinct. The inevitable work- 
 ing of natural selection determines that those who, blindly or 
 knowingly, believe in the worth of life must always supplant 
 those who, wisely or foolishly, disbelieve in it. The creed of 
 
 ' In his exposition of Natural Law, Prof. Lorimer lays down that 
 " the right to be involves the right to reproduce and multiply our being "; 
 but at the end of the paragraph which expounds this natural right, we 
 are told that " A man who cannot bestow a human education on his 
 children has no more natural right to marry than a man who cannot 
 beget ihem^'' {Institutes of Law, pp. 176, 177.) What is the good of 
 declaring rights one moment and revoking them the next ? But this is 
 what has to be constantly done by the theorists of natural rights, when 
 they are not anarchists. And when they are anarchists, the ungratitied 
 natural rights of every one land us very soon in the helium omnium 
 contra omnes.
 
 CH. vi] THE RIGHT OF LIFE 
 
 129 
 
 pessimism by its very nature cannot prevail ; it can never be 
 anything but a " bye-product " of growing reflectiveness. But 
 the growth of reflectiveness, and of imaginative sympathy, 
 must make one generation take thought for those who are 
 to come after. Yet those who denounce the wickedness of the 
 rulers of mankind in the past, and those who treat the question 
 of political obedience in the anarchical fashion to which I 
 have just referred, are often very ready in their turn to dis- 
 regard the interests of posterity, and even to proclaim such 
 disregard as a part of the natural rights of those now 
 living. 
 
 It may be objected that any attempt to establish the right 
 of the unborn is hopeless, because the very last thing to which 
 human beings will submit is interference in such a matter as 
 sexual relations. The objection is false as to fact. At the 
 present time the vast majority of people in every orderly 
 society do submit to a great number of " interferences " of 
 custom and of law. Even amongst savage tribes there are 
 some set prohibitions as to marriage, rigidly observed. Among 
 ourselves, and in kindred societies, over and above the legal 
 preference given to monogamy, the exclusion of marriages 
 within certain prohibited degrees, the penalties attached to 
 certain sexual acts, and, in addition to legal enactmep.ts, the 
 sentiments which are connected with what the law allows 
 and forbids, we have, especially among the upper and middle 
 classes, a whole series of interferences on the part of " society " 
 with the freedom of individuals — interferences expressly in- 
 tended to check the " natural " consequences of " natural " 
 instincts. The social prohibition of what are considered " un- 
 suitable " marriages is a very strong one, and interferes greatly 
 with the operation of natural and sexual selection. A great 
 deal of what is often blamed as the selfishness and worldly 
 ambition and money-grubbing of the middle class is the out- 
 come, not of direct individual selfishness at all, but of a 
 highly-developed feeling of responsibility towards offspring. 
 The pity of it is that so much of the suffering and sacrifice 
 of individual happiness, caused by the social or parental pro- 
 hibition of an imprudent or an unsuitable marriage, does 
 nothing to improve the character of the race, and is often 
 directly injurious. But the moral pressure exerted in behalf 
 of an imperfect or false idea is a sufficient proof of what a 
 
 N. K. K
 
 I30 THE RIGHT OF LIFE [ch. vi 
 
 more enliglitenecl public sentiment could do in the way of 
 direct or indirect control of parentage. Wherever the stan- 
 dard of living rises, and a greater security of economic 
 condition is attained, the " virtues " of the middle class are 
 assimilated ; the most improvident, as might be expected, are 
 those whose economic condition is the most uncertain. The 
 children of the slums marry, or at least produce offspring, too 
 early ; among the dwellers in villas marriage is frequently 
 postponed too long for the physical and moral well-being, both 
 of the persons directly concerned and of their offspring. In 
 this bourgeois prudence, considerations of health occupy a 
 very minor place. The practice of life-insurance serves, among 
 the men at least, to introduce a certain minimum standard of 
 fitness ; and business success is, of course, some test of a certain 
 degree of vigour — a test that again applies to the men only. 
 But natural selection in this matter operates under great 
 limitations : the value of " ability to marry " as a test of fit- 
 ness for parentage is vitiated by the inheritance of property, 
 and sexual selection, so far as it operates freely within the limits 
 of persons considered "eligible," only excludes some of the 
 extremer cases of physical unfitness. Now, is it quite vision- 
 ary to suppose that, at least among those persons who exercise 
 this aristocratic and bourgeois virtue of prudential forethought, 
 the meaning of mesalliance and of unsuitability might come to 
 be altered, and that cancer, insanity, consumption might be 
 substituted as impediments to marriage for a deficiency of 
 quarterings, a grandfather in retail trade, or (most usually 
 now) a grandfather who did not leave behind him a sufficient 
 sum of money, however acquired ? 
 
 But no alteration in the implications of parental prudence 
 will affect those whose economic condition is the worst. A 
 general improvement in economic conditions would, of course, 
 mean a higher standard of living. But until that is brought 
 about, the deterioration of the race goes on unchecked. The 
 famines and pestilences of ruder stages of society exercised a 
 severe natural selection by killing off those least fit for the 
 struggle. But sanitation and philanthropy have checked the 
 ravages of the most deadly of these pestilences, and, although 
 there maybe great want and suffering, deaths from starvation 
 are rare. It is true that natural selection still works with 
 cruel license among the children of the poor : so that in the
 
 CH. vi] THE RIGHT OF LIFE 131 
 
 lowest economic stratum there is more selection of children 
 than among the middle class, Avhile there is less check on the 
 instinct of propagation. If the children of the proletariat 
 were better cared for by the community, the check of natural 
 selection would cease ; and it has been very seriously argued 
 that free education, if supplemented by free food and free 
 medical attendance, would simply tend to increase the physical 
 deterioration of the race by removing natural selection, and 
 at the same time to increase population by removing such 
 prudential checks as may now operate to some extent among 
 those who are not in the very lowest depths of hopelessness. 
 This argument contains a certain element of fallacy : for any- 
 thing that helped to give the new generation a lift up in 
 respect of proper nourishment, intelligence, and standard of 
 comfort, might do more than counterbalance any weakening 
 of the almost non-existent sense of parental responsibility, 
 which, when it is roused, works so often at present in wrong 
 directions. But the argument contains this important truth, 
 which those who use it and those against whom it is used are 
 alike slow to recognise — that the assumption of responsibility 
 on the part of the community towards the children of the 
 community points logically to the assumption by the com- 
 munity of some control over the existence of these children. 
 Those who may become parents cannot be indefinitely relieved 
 of responsibility ; if they are relieved of it in one direction, 
 they must be made to feel it in another. If the State (i.e. the 
 community) should ever come to guarantee to every citizen, 
 not a bare minimum of subsistence, but a fairly comfortable 
 subsistence, requiring the necessary amount of work from 
 every one capable of it, the State must take precautions to 
 ensure that the number of incapables shall be as small as 
 possible; in other words, if the State becomes a general 
 employment agency and insurance company, it must exercise 
 the same kind of prudence which such societies have to 
 exercise at present. If it does not, the quality of its citizens 
 must deteriorate, and the conditions of work for those who can 
 work will become more unpleasant, or else there must be a 
 continual degeneration towards a lower and lower scale ot 
 existence, till the society sinks into barbarism, or falls a prey 
 to some stronger community, which, either through remaining 
 more under the sway of natural selection, or through having
 
 13 2 THE RIGHT OF LIFE [ch. vi 
 
 adopted some system of rational selection, has not entered on 
 the campaign with an army of hereditary wastrels. 
 
 Many persons are ready to accept the idea of responsibility 
 towards the unborn, but not to accept the idea of State-inter- 
 ference in the matter. Such things, they sa}^, must be left to 
 the conscience of the individual ; the family is a sphere too 
 sacred for legal interference, Unfortunately for this argument, 
 the State has already interfered with a great many of the 
 institutions of the patriarchal family. The •paterfamilias can 
 no longer chastise his wife or even his children according to 
 his own irresponsible judicial decisions ; he can no longer 
 decide whether they shall have any education or none ; he can 
 no longer hold his house as a castle against the sanitar}' in- 
 spector. The law, as I have already pointed out, decides that 
 certain marriages are unlawful, and consequently that certain 
 children are illegitimate. How if the meaning of illegitimacy 
 were to be changed ? or, if that suggestion sounds too startling, 
 how if it were to be enlarged ? The fatal defect of trusting to 
 private prudence and conscientiousness is that it operates least 
 just where it is most wanted ; the prudent and conscientious 
 therefore increase in a smaller ratio than the imprudent and 
 careless. In a democratic community, or, indeed, in any 
 community, a large amount of public sentiment on the subject 
 would be necessary to carry a law enforcing a health-certificate 
 as a requisite for lawful parentage, or to make the law effective 
 if it were carried ; but that does not prove that the reform 
 could operate without the law. A law is the judgment of the 
 people when sober, and it serves as a check on what they 
 might do when drunk with passion. A law against bigamy 
 does not absolutely prevent bigamy, but it diminishes the 
 number of bigamists. 
 
 The view of criminality as to a great extent of the nature 
 of disease is a strong argument for certain punishments which 
 at first sight it might seem to condemn. The criminal who is 
 put to death, or who receives a very long sentence of imprison- 
 ment, is, at least, prevented from propagating his species.^ 
 
 ' The ferociovTS penalties enforced till lately under tlie criminal law 
 produced a reaction against all corporal punishment, a reaction which 
 some legal reformers feel has now gone too far. The making of eunuchs 
 for reasons of luxury, or jealousy, has caused the idea of sterilisation to 
 seem repulsive, so that a defender of /hiimaW Iiighti>,\i'kG Mr. Salt (p. 41),
 
 CH. vi] TFIE RIGHT OF LIFE 133 
 
 There is another aspect of this question of the right of the 
 unborn. As I have said, we cannot separate the discussion of 
 each "natural " right from the others. The question of the 
 equaUty of the sexes is very constantly treated as if it stood by 
 itself, and could be settled on its own merits. Supposing all 
 occupations opened to women, and women put on a footing of 
 equality with men so far as legal and political rights (and so 
 far as legal and political responsibilities — for that also would 
 follow) are concerned, a little thinking will show that the 
 average woman would always be at an economic disadvantage 
 in competition with the average man (I am not dealing with 
 cases of exceptional ability), because of the interruption 
 caused to her work by the bearing and rearing of children. 
 And in the interests of the children to be born, that interrup- 
 tion ought to be much greater than it is at present in the lives 
 of women who are wage-earners. The average man at present 
 works for such wages as will support himself, a wife and 
 children ; the average woman, for what will support herself 
 alone, and generally on a lower scale of expenditure than the 
 man. The man " without encumbrances " gets the economic 
 advantage of the standard set by the average man. The 
 woman with encumbrances gets the economic disadvantage of 
 the standard set by her unencumbered sisters, who are often 
 moreover partially supported by relatives or in other ways. 
 In addition to this we must add the fact, that in many pur- 
 suits the woman worker is apt to be less valuable than the 
 man, because marriage takes her away from her work just 
 when she has learnt it thoroughly, while marriage gives the 
 man a stronger inducement to continue and improve. Seeing 
 this, some women are far-sighted enough to urge that their 
 services as mothers should be taken into account by the 
 community, which could not continue to exist without such 
 services. If, however, maternity is to be regarded as a public 
 service, and rewarded as such, the community must, in its own 
 interests, take care that it receives a due equivalent for its 
 
 suggests that even the mutilation of domestic animals " could scarcely 
 survive the critical ordeal of thought." But when we consider the 
 numerous cases of semi-imbeciles wlio are found guilty of certain crimes, 
 is not the question worth asking whether (at least, for any repetition of 
 the offence) a surgical operation would not be a more benelicent and 
 more socially useful penalty than a very long sentence of imprison- 
 ment ?
 
 134 THE RIGHT OF LIFE [ch. vi 
 
 expenditure, AVhen tlie compulsory military service, wliicla 
 is normal in many countries, and may be required in all, is 
 urged as an argument for the political privileges of men in 
 distinction from women, the advocates of " women's rights " 
 ask, with considerable relevancy, " Where would your soldiers 
 be without mothers '? " The defect in this retort is that it over- 
 looks the fact that the State does not support any and every 
 male as a soldier ; a certain minimum of fitness is required. 
 The State must similarly reject those would-be mothers who 
 are physically or morally unfit. To burden the State with 
 paupers and imbeciles is the reverse of a public service, and 
 should certainly not be rewarded as such.
 
 CHAPTER YII 
 
 THE EIGHT OF LIBERTY : LIBERTY OF THOUGHT 
 
 Next to the right of life is generally named the right of 
 " liberty," and to many persons this seems the primary and 
 most essential right of all/ As many crimes have been done 
 in the name of Liberty (and a still greater amount of nonsense 
 talked in the name of Liberty), there are some who think they 
 gain a point or two by substituting the Saxon term " Free- 
 dom," Liberty, it is admitted, is something French, foolish 
 and frivolous. Freedom is English, solid and sensible, if just 
 a trifle dall. Any such distinction is mere playing with 
 words ; it matters not whether we choose to take the Romance 
 or the Teutonic term between which our conveniently compo- 
 site language offers us the alternative. John Locke writes 
 indifferently of " natural liberty " and of "freedom." I have 
 shown sufficiently in Chapter I. that we cannot shuffle off 
 upon French fanatics the sole responsibility of having pro- 
 claimed, even in the most extreme forms, the natural rights 
 of libert}'', etc. The same ambiguities lurk in the one term 
 and in the other. Whether any one demands the liberty to 
 do something, or asks to be left free to do something, he is 
 making the same sort of claim ; and if he supposes that for 
 liberty as .snchj or for freedom as such, there is any a priori 
 
 ' In a work entitled The Natural Iii(j/d to Freedom, by Mr. M. D. O'Brien 
 (recently published ; no date), I had hoped to find a reasoned statement 
 of the Individualist theory. But, save for some frat^ments of Stoic 
 moralising, I have found nothing except vituperation, misprints, and 
 bad grammar. Of the vituperation I am one of the objects ; but in tlie 
 distinguished, if somewhat oddly assorted, company of Professor Flint, 
 Sir J. F. Stephen, M. Zola, and Walt Whitman. To Mr. O'Brien's 
 vituperation of mj^self and my arguments I do not in tlie least object, 
 but I do object to having put in my mouth, and in that of Tacitus, such an 
 atrocious piece of individualist Latin as " Principis nwrtalis, repiiblicia 
 CB^erna " (p. 8i). Mi-. O'Brien would seem to claim a natural right to 
 freedom from the rules of grammar, as well as from the authority of 
 civilised society. 
 
 135
 
 136 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [ch. vii 
 
 justification as against the claims of " restraint " an such^ or 
 "interference" as stick, he has become a prey to the old 
 fallacy which consists in taking relative terms as absolute. 
 The modern reader of Plato's Eiithydemus is apt to dismiss the 
 captious puzzles of the old Sophists with a superior smile, 
 saying, " Such things belong to a very childish stage in 
 human thought." When Euthydemus argues that my father, 
 because he is a father, is also the father of all other men, and 
 also of all gudgeons and puppies and pigs ; and when Diony- 
 sodorus reverses the position, and argues that Ctesippus's dog, 
 because a father, is the father of Ctesippus himself,^ the 
 reasoning is so ridiculous, if one may say so, that it hardly 
 raises a laugh. But a great many arguments based upon the 
 appeal to " freedom " are arguments of the same kind, though 
 the fallacy is more deeply hid, since " freedom " is not on the 
 face of it a relative term in the same way that "father" is. 
 If I call a person " more learned," the question at once 
 suggests itself: "More learned than whom?" But when a 
 person is called "learned," or "prudent," or "sane," or 
 " honest," the question is not always asked : " By what 
 standard ? " Yet that is a very important question to ask. 
 A tall Esquimau would be a short Englishman ; and a learned 
 pig would be ignorant for a Justice of the Peace, The 
 relativity of the term "drunk" has frequently come before 
 the notice of the law courts. The definition of drunk as " not 
 capable of lying on the ground without holding on " would not 
 satisfy a "total abstainer." Now the term "free" is more 
 obviously relative than some of these terms. Not only, like 
 all adjectives of quality, does " free " imply some standard by 
 w'hich it can be measured — a free man, under the despotism 
 of Nero or Domitian, would hardly be accounted free by those 
 who looked back on the Republic — but the very word ought 
 to suggest the incompleteness of the description, till we know 
 from what a person is free, or what he possesses the liberty 
 to do. 
 
 The editor of Sir George Cornewall Lewis's excellent little 
 book on the Use and Abuse of roJitkal Terms — Sir R. K. Wil- 
 son^ — quotes from a speech, so far as he can remember, of Mr. 
 
 ^ Euthyd., 298. 
 
 ^ P. 151, note. I have not followed Sir R. K. Wilson's commentary on 
 the phrases in every respect, though I am greatly indebted to it.
 
 CH. vii] THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 137 
 
 Joseph Chamberlain, in which an "advanced" political pro- 
 gramme was put forward under the phrases " free land, free 
 labour, free religion, and free schools." If this coml)ination c;f 
 words was not actually used by the orator to whom it is as- 
 cribed, it is likely enough to have been used by somebody else 
 in the days when the creed of " Advanced Liberals " was manu- 
 factured at Birmingham. The adjective " free " in each of these 
 cases is meant to commend the policy advocated to the minds 
 of the party of " freedom." But what confusion of thought 
 that Httle word, conceals ! By " free land. " is meant appar- 
 ently any measures which would facilitate the legal transfer of 
 land ; and among such measures one of the most effectual 
 would be an interference with the " freedom " of bequest, and 
 with the " liberty " of landowners to tie up real property. 
 "Free labour" — well, what does that mean? In more recent 
 years it would probably mean the putting of restraint upon 
 trade-unions in their interference with the employment of non- 
 union men.^ In earlier times, in many lands, it would have 
 meant the abolition of slavery, or the removal of restrictions 
 which hindered the migration of workmen from one district to 
 another. Sir R. K. Wilson suggests that it may mean " the 
 repeal of all laws for punishing manual labourers as criminals 
 for mere breaches of contract," or " a shortening of the hours 
 of labour by means of legal restrictions on the freedom of con- 
 tract." I give up the problem of what it meant as originally 
 used. " Free religion " might mean freedom from legal and 
 political disabilities on the ground of religious opinion, and the 
 legal right of every citizen to worship God in his own fashion : 
 in the mouth of some ecclesiastics it would mean the liberty of 
 one Church to restrain all other forms of religion, and its ex- 
 emption from any responsibility to the civil courts, in all those 
 matters in which it did not choose to be responsible. As used 
 at Birmingham, however, the words would only mean the 
 disestablishment and disendowment of State Churches, i.e. an 
 extensive interference on the part of the State with the })ro- 
 perty of various corporations (sole and aggregate), and the 
 abolition of all legal provision of free, i.e. gratuitous, religious 
 teaching and worship. "Free schools " means the institution 
 of gratuitous teaching at the cost of the nation; so that the 
 
 ' Cf. the phrase about every man's riglit to do wliat he likes wiili his 
 labour, quoted p. 15 above.
 
 138 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [ch. vii 
 
 word '' free "' in these two last formulas lias exactly opposite 
 meanings. 
 
 It would be easy to multiply examples of the ambiguities of 
 the words " liberty" and "freedom." " A free monarchy" to 
 Bacon and to King James meant an absolute monarch}^, so 
 that " a free monarchy " is incompatible with what we call 
 " free government." The " liberties " of corporations, classes, 
 or individuals, mean their special privileges, and thus involve 
 considerable interference with the " liberty " of the non- 
 privileged. " Freedom of contract " maj'- result in a practical 
 bondage of one of the parties to the other. A " Free Church " 
 may allow less " liberty of thought " than Churches which are 
 not " liberated " from the State. ^ Where Bishop Burnet wrote, 
 " The Earl of Arg^de was free of all scandalous vices," Dean 
 Swift, in correction or malignit}^, wrote on the margin, " As a 
 man is free of a corporation, he means." The last example 
 suggests forcibly what is perhaps the most important of all the 
 ditierences in the signification of the term " liberty " — the 
 difference, namely, between negative iiwd positive liberty. Ne- 
 gative liberty means simply " being let alone." Whether that 
 is a good or a bad thing in itself is a perfectlj^ useless question to 
 discuss. It is (to adapt an illustration of Sir James Stephen's) 
 just like asking whether a hole is a good thing in itself.- All 
 depends on what the hole is made z'??, and on what you want to 
 put into the hole. A hole in my coat is useful, if it is a button- 
 hole or the place my arm has to go through ; but a hole in the 
 wrong place is not desirable. And so it is with liberty in the 
 merely negative sense of non-interference. We must know 
 who or what is being left alone, on what occasions, in what 
 places, and who it is that is leaving any one alone, before we 
 can profitably discuss the good or evil of freedom. To give a 
 baby its freedom on the verge of a precipice and to attempt to 
 supervise every act of grown men are both foolish and culp- 
 able proceedings. When people praise liberty, it may simply 
 be a way of expressing their strong detestation of some partic- 
 ular form of restraint ; but more often, there is implied also in 
 the praise the ideal of some positive ^^owers of doing something 
 which they consider worth doing.^ Positive or real liberty, as 
 
 ' Cf. below, p. 220. 
 
 * Cf. Liberty, Equality, Fraternity (Ed. 2), p. 197. 
 
 3 Cf. T. H. Green, Works, III. p. 371.
 
 CH. viil THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 
 
 139 
 
 we might call it, to distinguish it from the negative or merely 
 formal liberty of being let alone, means the opportnnitj'' or 
 capacity of doing something. Such liberty is, in its turn, 
 good or bad according as the things which can be done are 
 good or bad. That there is a natural right to liberty might be 
 understood to mean (in accordance with the sense of " natural " 
 explained above, p. 75) that every well-regulated society ought 
 to secure to all its members, so far as possible, the opportunity^ 
 of developing their various natural [i.e. inherited) gifts and 
 powers so far as they can without detriment to one another 
 or to the well-being of the society as a whole. 
 
 But this positive and qualified meaning of liberty has not 
 always been recognised as clearly distinguished from the mere 
 negative sense of being let alone ; nor is it always realised how 
 verj^ much any real positive liberty depends upon the existence 
 of elaborate social arrangements, and on a strong and stable 
 government. In this country no one is hindered by law from 
 reading all the works of Mr. Herbert Spencer. That is negative 
 liberty. But if a man cannot read at all, or if he can read but 
 has not any money to spare for the purpose of buying so many 
 volumes, or if he has no access to any public library, or if the 
 managers of any library to which he has access refuse to permit 
 such works on their shelves, or if, having access to them, he has 
 no leisure in which to read them, or if he has not had such an 
 education as enables him to understand what he reads, he cannot 
 be said to get much good out of the fact that the law of the land 
 does not prohibit him from reading Mr. Spencer's works. Thus, 
 in order that the great mass of the inhabitants of this countr3'' 
 should really enjoy the privilege of appreciating the philosophi- 
 cal basis on which Mr, Spencer founds his objections to State 
 education. State libraries, and all such forms of interference 
 with individual liberty, it is necessary that such forms of 
 State interference with individual liberty — and a good man}' 
 others — should be in active operation ; at least experience has 
 not yet shown us any instance in which opportunities of 
 culture have been accessible to all, or nearly all, the inhabi- 
 tants of densely populated countries without some such inter- 
 ference with the liberty of being ignorant, the liberty of 
 keeping children ignorant, the liberty of working for excessive 
 hours, and other individual liberties of that kind. 
 
 Thus, liberty in the sense of positive opportunity for self-
 
 I40 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [ch. vii 
 
 development, is the creation of law, and not sometliing that 
 could exist apart from the action of the State. It is, indeed, 
 conceivable that at least in small communities the pressure of 
 public opinion alone might suffice to keep up a strong sense of 
 parental responsibility in the matter of education, and a stan- 
 dard of living which would ensure among other things a fair 
 amount of leisure. But, where any approximation to such con- 
 ditions has existed, it will be found that a Church not tolerating 
 nonconformity has practically exercised effective compulsory 
 powers, backed by sanctions such as excommunication, for 
 which an equivalent can only be found in State-enforced penal- 
 ties when the Church ceases to be identical with the civil com- 
 munity, and when citizens may belong to other religious bodies, 
 or to none at all. Even in such cases of ecclesiastical, or, one 
 might say, theocratic compulsion, the sword of the civil magis- 
 trate has generally been at the service of the Church. Scot- 
 land and the New England colonies in the seventeenth and 
 early part of the eighteenth centuries might be cited as ex- 
 amples of countries where illiteracy was exceptional before 
 Compulsory Education Acts — in the modern sense — had been 
 passed ; but a powerful Puritan clergy enforced reading-lessons 
 on their flocks with the same stringency they would have used 
 to prohibit the teaching of such doctrines as those of Mr. 
 Spencer. The only alternative to the penalties enforced by the 
 law courts are the often more terrible penalties of religious 
 excommunication enforced by an exclusive and necessarily in- 
 tolerant Church, or of a " bo3^cott" enforced by some irrespon- 
 sible association, too much believed in or too much feared to 
 be lightly disobeyed. Most persons who care for liberty — in 
 the sense in which alone it is worth caring for, i.e. opportunities 
 of self-development — will prefer the compulsion enforced by a 
 State in which the whole community is in some way repre- 
 sented, and which is strong enough to secure toleration for 
 those who dissent from the prevailing religion or who dread 
 the arbitrary edicts of private associations or secret societies. 
 
 The American Declarations of Rights have contented them- 
 selves with claiming the natural right to liberty, but with more 
 prudence than respect for logic have abstained from giving 
 any definition of the term : • the attempt might possibly 
 
 * Here is a charming specimen of the casuistry to which the doctrine 
 of a natural right of liberty may lead. In a case arising out of the South
 
 CH. VI i] THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 141 
 
 have led to some awkward and premature differences between 
 the northern and the southern States. The French Declaration 
 of 1789 (prefixed to the Constitution of 179J ) seriously grapples 
 with the difficulty. " Liberty," according to its fourth article, 
 " consists in the power to do everything that does not injure 
 another ; thus the exercise of the natural rights of every man 
 has no limits except those which assure to the other members 
 of the society the enjoyment of these same rights." The cor- 
 responding article in the Declaration of 1793 has its first clause 
 almost identical with the words used in the Declaration of 
 1789: "Liberty is the power w^hich belongs to man of doing 
 everything that does not injure the rights of another." AVhat 
 follows is a somewhat rhetorical flourish : " Nature is its prin- 
 ciple, justice its rule, the law its safeguard : its moral limit is 
 to be found in the maxim. Do not do to another loliat thoti 
 icouldest not have done to thyself ^^ — the negative side of an 
 ancient and venerable moral precept. Mr. Herbert Spencer 
 enunciates the " formula of justice " in very similar terms : 
 "Everyman is free to do that which he wills, provided he 
 infringes not the equal freedom of any other man " {Justice^ p. 
 46). Mr. Spencer tells us that " for more than thirty years " 
 he supposed that he was " the first to recognise the law of 
 equal freedom as being that in which justice, as variously ex- 
 emplified in the concrete, is summed up in the abstract." At 
 length he has learned that Kant had said something similar. 
 In a translation of Kant's Fhilosophi/ of Law, he finds these 
 
 Carolina liquor law, which prohibits the sale of alcoholic drinks except 
 in State dispensaries, Judge J. H. Hudson, "the ablest of South Carolina's 
 eight judges " (I quote from the Boston Transcriiit of July 11, 1893), laid 
 down that the law was unconstitutional, because it deprived the people 
 of the right to pursue a lucrative branch of trade, and gave the State a 
 monopoly therein ; but that it would be lawful to j^rohibit the sale of in- 
 toxicating liquors altogether. Thus, apparently, the individual has a 
 natural right to sell drink, but no natural right to get it! It is only in 
 a very commercial community that the right of selling could seem more 
 primary and fundamental than the riglit of using the ai'ticle sold; but to 
 regard it as more " natural " is stranger still. As the South Carolina 
 liquor law has been enforced, i.e. has caused riots quite recently, I fancy 
 that Judge J. H. Hudson's decision must have been overruled, on equally 
 plausible grounds doubtless. 
 
 Since writing the foregoing note I see that the Suj^reme Court of South 
 Carolina has decided that the liquor law is vmconstitutional, whether on 
 Judge Hudson's grounds or not I do not know.
 
 142 THE RIGHl OF LIBERTY [ch. vii 
 
 words : " The universal Law of Right may be expressed thus : 
 ' Act externally in such a manner that the free exercise of thy 
 will may be able to co-exist with the freedom of all others, 
 according to a universal Law.' " ^ (See Mr. Spencer's Juatice^ 
 pp. 263, ''liyi.) Kant's BechtsleJwe, it may be observed, was first 
 published in 17'J7 (or, rather, in the latter part of 1796). Mr. 
 Spencer apparently has not yet heard of the still earlier anti- 
 cipation of his own formula in the French Declarations, nor of 
 the deduction from a more ancient maxim introduced in one of 
 them. " The Golden Rule," of course, in its j^os It ive form is a 
 maxim of Benevolence rather than a maxim of Justice, and it 
 is only the negative side of it which has any proper place in a 
 formula of Justice to be used as a principle of legislation. 
 
 All these formulas of Justice or definitions of liberty, it 
 should be noted, bring in the conception of equality as well as 
 that of liberty. As I have already pointed out, we cannot 
 keep the several alleged natural rights apart from one an- 
 other. At first sight, Mr. Spencer's phraseology may seem 
 the simplest and the most distinct. Liberty is taken to mean 
 " doing what one wills " ; but the right of doing what one 
 wills is limited by the equal freedom of everybody else. The 
 formula obviously implies a manner of thinking about human 
 action analogous to that which underlies a very common ver- 
 sion of the Social Contract theory. Every individual human 
 being (I assume that Mr. Spencer means " man " to be con- 
 strued as of common gender) is thought of as having in himself 
 a right to do anything he likes ; but as every one has the same 
 right, the various absolute rights conflict and make a war of 
 all against all, except for the Social Contract which sets limits 
 to the rights of each. The Social Contract theory may how- 
 ever be used, as it is by Hobbes, to solve the difficulty about 
 rights, by denying what are commonly called natural rights 
 (though not what Hobbes himself would call rights according 
 to the law of nature) altogether ; it may be used, as it is used 
 by Locke, to modify somewhat seriously some of the alleged 
 natural rights. According to Mr. Spencer's view of Justice, 
 this principle of equal liberty is an absolute principle which no 
 convention or law can rightly abolish or destroy, and which 
 can always be appealed to for the criticism of positive institu- 
 
 ^ Hastie's Kant's Fhilosophy of Law, i). AG; Kant, Werke (ed. Eosen- 
 kranz), IX. p. 33.
 
 CH. vii] THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 143 
 
 tions. We must think of the formula as a principle underlying 
 any possible social contract, and not as resulting from it. 
 Now let us see what it means, and what help we can get from 
 it, in settling practical difficulties. People will generally ad- 
 mit that they wish to do what is just ; but wliat is just in any 
 particular case is often the very thing in dispute. And it 
 would indeed be a great help if we had a formula applicable 
 to all cases. 
 
 At the first glance this formula of justice seems to offer me 
 a most charming license. I may do anything whatever that 
 I like — except — " Ay, there's the rub." I must leave " equal 
 freedom" to everybody else. Now, what is equal freedom? 
 Have I no right to stand up and speak at a meeting unless 
 everybody else may also stand up and speak at the same time? 
 If others are prevented, they are certainly deprived of their 
 equal freedom ; if they are not, it would be rather awkward 
 to be the chairman of that meeting — if, indeed, the formula 
 of justice allows any one to be chairman without everybody 
 being chairman. This last illustration will suggest the obvious 
 and reasonable solution. AVhy is any one allowed to stand up 
 and speak at a meeting at all ? AVhy is any one allowed to 
 sit in the chair and regulate the proceedings ? Is it in virtue 
 of any a priori principle of natural justice or equal freedom, 
 and not simply and solely because the persons attending the 
 meeting find it convenient to make or to follow certain con- 
 ventions as to the conduct of business ? Anybody's " right " 
 to do or say anything is derived entirely from the consent of 
 the society of persons forming the meeting ; there is no such 
 right in any one prior to, and independent of, the society in 
 question. A public meeting is indeed a very temporary type 
 of society ; and if it were not for the traditions and conven- 
 tions inherited by one meeting from others, or from the pro- 
 cedure of assemblies of a more permanent kind, public meet- 
 ings would always be more chaotic than they sometimes are. 
 
 It may be objected that I am quibbling with Mr. Spencer's 
 formula ; and that by equal freedom is meant, not necessarily 
 the right to do exactly the same thing at the same moment 
 in the same place, but only the right to do similar things 
 at the same moment in the same place, or to do the same 
 thing at different times and in different places. My right 
 to stand up and speak at a meeting depends on the right
 
 144 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [cH. vii 
 
 of other people to stand up and speak after me, and on 
 other people's rights to hold other meetings at different 
 places, and so on. But suppose I am speaking at the 
 most advantageous time and in the most convenient place, 
 the other people who only get the right of speaking at 
 the inferior times and places are deprived of their equal 
 freedom. And, even among the persons present at one meet- 
 ing, can it be said that no one has a right to speak at all, 
 unless every one has a right to speak afterwards ? Meetings 
 would be more terrible ordeals even than they are now, if 
 there was a natural and indefeasible right in everybody to 
 bore everybody else. Whether anybody is allowed to speak 
 at all, how long he may speak, and how many people may 
 speak — all depend ultimately on the willingness of the audience 
 to hear them. But, it will be said, can you not appeal to 
 the sense of justice in a meeting in order to get a hearing ? 
 Undoubtedly. But why ? It is because the persons are ac- 
 customed to certain modes of conducting meetings which have 
 gradually grown up under the shelter of firm government 
 and stable social order. These modes may vary, and one or 
 another be adopted according to the particular purpose for 
 which the meeting is held. People may have come together 
 simply to listen to a lecture : nobody but the chairman intro- 
 ducing the lecturer, the lecturer himself, and perhaps some 
 persons moving and seconding votes of thanks, may claim the 
 right to be heard at all. Or, again, questions may be invited 
 by the chairman, but any person taking advantage of the 
 right thus bestowed upon him may be strictly limited to the 
 asking of questions, and checked if he begins to wander off 
 into a little oration of his own. Or, again, the meeting may 
 be one in which " free discussion " is invited, but all persons 
 except the speaker or speakers who have opened the debate 
 may be restricted to ten. or to five minutes. In none of these 
 cases — all familiar enough — is there any absolute principle 
 of " equal freedom." There are, however, meetings — most 
 notably, the usual type of legislative assembly — in which 
 every one of a certain determinate number of persons con- 
 stituting the assembly is presumed by the constitution of the 
 assembly to have an equal right to speak, just as he may have 
 an equal right to vote. But I do not think there exists any 
 assembly of this kind anywhere, or that any such assembly
 
 CH. vii] THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 145 
 
 would be likely to exist long, in which an absolute and in- 
 defeasible right is conceded to every member, however fatuous 
 and however dull, to speak as frequently and as long as the 
 most eloquent, the most trusted, and the wisest statesman 
 present. Some venerable legislative bodies do occasionall}'' 
 seem to be approximating to such a condition ; but it is 
 generally regarded as a bad sign when an assembl}^, pro- 
 fessedly met together for the transaction of business, comes 
 to waste its time in a weak concession to the natural rights of 
 bores and buffoons. As a rule, the right of speech is dependent 
 on the goodwill of the audience ; and, though there maj'' be a 
 general willingness to give every one a hearing, that willing- 
 ness is usually and wisely limited by the conviction that, 
 unless a person has something to say that is worth listening 
 to, the less he is heard the better. Any assertion of an 
 absolute claim to equal freedom of speech would probably be 
 met by disapprobation and clamour ; and a continued as- 
 sertion of it would certainly lead to a general chaos and con- 
 fusion — the claim of " equality " destroying the " freedom " of 
 all by destroying the order that alone makes freedom possible. 
 
 To the connection between the idea of justice and the idea 
 of equality I shall have to return. Meanwhile, I think this 
 discussion of what is practically meant by the right of free 
 speech in meetings for special purposes illustrates sufficiently 
 well the source of such rights generally. The right of making 
 a speech is the creation of a society, and is limited by the 
 goodwill of the society as a whole, and, as a rule, is both pro- 
 tected and restricted by the authoritative decisions of some one 
 presiding person, to whom the society hands over its powers 
 in this matter for the time being, and who is aided and 
 supported by the accumulated traditions of the past. The 
 principle of justice should be a principle that holds a society 
 together ; but any absolute claim of equal freedom on the part 
 of every individual could only mean the break up of the 
 society, and cannot therefore be the principle of justice. 
 
 The French Declarations, however, do not leave the de- 
 finition of liberty open to any such anarchical interpretation. 
 The Declaration of 1789 makes the limit of individual liberty 
 depend upon the question whether any injury is done to other 
 persons or not; the Declaration of 1793 approaches more nearly 
 in appearance to the anarchical principle of Mr. Spencer's 
 
 N. R. L
 
 146 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [ch. vn 
 
 formula, since it substitutes for " injury to others," " injur^^ 
 to the rights of others." But injury to the rights of others is 
 in any case something very different from interference with 
 the equal freedom of others ; for among these rights are in- 
 cluded in the Declaration of 1793 the right of security and the 
 right of property. Without referring now to the difficult ques- 
 tions which are raised by an assertion of a natural right of pro- 
 perty, it is enough to point out that the recognition of a right 
 of security alone is incompatible with any absolute assertion of 
 a right to equal freedom under all circumstances. It implies, 
 however vaguely, the right to have order maintained by a 
 government of some sort. And the article on liberty in the 
 Declaration of 1793 goes on to say that "the law is the safe- 
 guard of liberty " — an expression much more ambiguous, 
 indeed, than the clear language of the Declaration of 1789, 
 which expressly la3^s down that the limits of liberty " can 
 only be determined by the law." Now, if this is once recog- 
 nised, it follows that the right of equal freedom, or the right 
 of any freedom, whether equal or not, is not prior to positive 
 law but dependent upon it. The French Declaration is a 
 protest against arbitrary government ; but it is a protest in 
 favour of the determination of rights by fixed and known laws. 
 It is conceived quite in the spirit of John Locke, who, in 
 spite of all his phrases about natural rights, says that "Where 
 there is no law there is no freedom." ^ 
 
 It might be shown in other ways that the right of any 
 individual to do what he wills must be limited by other con- 
 siderations than the right of other individuals to do the same 
 or similar acts. Most people now-a-days in this country 
 would, I fancy, agree that a person has not a right to spread 
 the infection, say, of scarlet fever or small-pox, provided only 
 that he concedes to all others a similar right. The others 
 might not consent to his liberty in return for his concession 
 of equal liberty to them. We have come to consider certain 
 things expedient in the interests of the general well-being, and 
 certain things injurious. And we have come to consider it 
 expedient to prohibit certain things simply because they are 
 injurious, quite apart from considerations of equal freedom. 
 We have indeed come to consider that restraints are in- 
 expedient, unless they are imposed upon all persons similarly 
 
 ' Treatise of Civil Government, II. § 57.
 
 CH. vii] THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 147 
 
 situated, so tliat in a certain sense we recognise a principle of 
 equal restraint ; i.e. we hold that the law should be impartial. 
 The reasons for this principle of equality I shall have to dis- 
 cuss later. Meanwhile, let me point out one obvious reason 
 for it. A law is more likely to be accepted under a democratic 
 constitution, and is more likely to be obeyed and to be enforced 
 if it seems to apply to all equally. But to recognise the need 
 of satisfying the demand for equality to some extent is a 
 very different thing from making equal freedom our guiding 
 principle. A few strong, well-armed men might be quite 
 willing that every one should have an equal right to kill and 
 plunder; but this willingness of the brigand to adopt the 
 formula of Mr. Herbert Spencer would not (in the judgment 
 of most persons) justify a settled modern society in going back 
 
 to 
 
 " the good old rule . . . the simple j^lan, 
 That they should take who liave the power, 
 And they should keep who can."' 
 
 The principle of equal freedom, if taken as the ultimate basis 
 on which the fabric of law and government is to be built up, 
 would either compel a complete abstinence from all action on 
 the part of every individual — that would be one way of every 
 one having an equal right to do everything, — or it would mean 
 the equal right of every one to do everything in the sense of 
 Hobbes, i.e. the war of all against all. The intermediate mean- 
 ings, which seem to make the principle of equal freedom a 
 plausible account of what justice is, all presuppose an orderly 
 fabric of society in which the rights of individuals are settled 
 for them by a fixed system of law. In the blank spaces left 
 unfilled by definite law or established custom, people do act 
 on a rough general principle of give and take. 
 
 Liberty in general is too ambiguous a term to permit us to 
 decide how far the right to liberty is a right which ought to 
 be recognised by a well-regulated society. The principle that 
 the liberty of every one should be limited only by the equal 
 liberty of every one else has been shown to be incapable of 
 any literal application as a fundamental principle of society ; 
 on the contrary, it is a principle which is either absurd or 
 
 ' Wordsworth, lloh lloy's Grave. According to the jioet, "in the 
 principles of things, He sought liis moral creed."
 
 148 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [ch. vii 
 
 anarchical, or both. I proceed now to examine some particular 
 kinds of liberty which have been claimed as natural rights. 
 In the life of man we very commonly distinguish three main 
 forms in which his natural powers can be exercised — thought, 
 speech, action. Action is a very wide term, and clearly re- 
 quires subdivision ; but we may take these three main forms 
 as distinguishing three spheres in which freedom may be 
 claimed. Freedom of thought in one sense, which may fairly 
 be regarded as the strictest sense of the words, every one has, 
 and nobody can restrict. The Holy Office may forbid a man 
 to utter any doctrine of which it does not approve, but no 
 power that priest or tyrant has ever wielded can limit the 
 freedom of a man's inmost soul. And, under oppression and 
 amid bigotry, the closed lips of the intellectual rebel have 
 often smiled bitterly but proudly, conscious of a freedom 
 which even stone walls and iron bars cannot limit or confine. 
 But to think what may not be uttered becomes a torture which 
 eats away the soul. And the intellect which is shut up in its 
 own dark chamber tends to pine away and perish, missing 
 alike the fresh air of controversy and the sunshine of human 
 sympathy. Indirectly, if not directly, even this sad privilege 
 of freedom of thought is destroyed by S3'stematic repression of 
 freedom of utterance. And in any sense of the words which 
 goes beyond the merely negative one — that what goes on in 
 one's mind cannot be directly ^ controlled by others — freedom 
 of thought cannot exist except in a stimulating intellectual 
 atmosphere. For freedom of thought, in the positive sense 
 of the development of intellectual capacity and the earnest 
 pursuit of truth, implies the existence of a good system of 
 education, of a high average of intellectual culture in at least 
 some class of the community, and of the possibility of a satis- 
 factory career for those who devote themselves specially to 
 intellectual pursuits. 
 
 The mere absence of laws interfering with intellectual 
 liberty will not of itself lead to the growth of a genuinely 
 scientific spirit in regard to matters of belief. The public 
 
 ^ A person hypnotised may be said to have his thoughts controlled by 
 another ; but the control is not exercised directly by mind over mind, 
 but through the medium of suggestion. Further, a hypnotised person 
 is not a specimen of a person " thinking," in the only sense of that term 
 we are here concerned with.
 
 CH. vii] THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 149 
 
 opinion of a society of uneducated or sliglitl}^ educated persons, 
 who are more or less under the sway of the same beliefs in 
 religious, political, or social matters, may be far more adverse 
 to the growth of any true positive intellectual liberty than 
 even the existence of considerable legal restrictions on the free 
 expression of opinion in popular discourses, provided that a 
 certain degree of license is permitted, or winked at, in the case 
 of those who address a limited audience of the learned. In 
 a democratically governed society there may, owing to the 
 strong pressure of popular prejudice, be less intellectual 
 liberty, negative or positive, than under certain kinds of 
 aristocratic and even of despotic governments. In the latter 
 cases freedom of thought may be the privilege only of the few, 
 and it may be a privilege dependent on the somewhat un- 
 certain caprice of those in power ; but in the former case it 
 may be practically non-existent. A strong government, even 
 of a despotic or arbitrary kind, is often necessary in order to 
 secure the person who holds some unpopular opinion against 
 the hatred of the bigoted multitude. Under the early Roman 
 Empire, Greek sceptics and Christian believers enjoyed an 
 amount of security and liberty which no champions of new 
 and unpopular opinions could possibly have enjo3"ed in a small 
 Swiss democracy or in Puritan Massachusetts, so long as such 
 communities remained homogeneous in their religious belief. 
 
 Freedom of thought is thus not necessarily connected with 
 the existence of what is called "free government." In spite 
 of what is sometimes alleged, religious and political liberty do 
 not always go together. The struggle for civil liberty, i.e. for 
 self-government, for institutions that are to some extent at 
 least democratic, still more the struggle for national liberty, 
 i.e. independence of alien rule, may even be directl}^ hostile to 
 religious liberty — as we understand it. The necessity of homo- 
 geneity, as we shall see, may compel or seem to compel a degree 
 of intolerance which is not necessary under a strong despotism. 
 In the long run, however, religious liberty is placed on surer 
 foundations if it is based upon a principle deliberately adopted 
 b}'^ a free people than if it rests solely on the caprice, or care- 
 lessness, or individual tolerance of a despot. On the other 
 hand, if libertj'' of thought is once granted, it is not likely to 
 be limited to religious questions : freedom of opinion respecting 
 the other world will lead to freedom of opinion respecting this.
 
 I50 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [ch. vii 
 
 And on this account the liberty of thought and speech is, as 
 Milton saw, the very foundation of all other liberties. A 
 democracy of uniform religious belief may stagnate throiigh 
 centuries ; an absolute monarchy which tolerates independence 
 of thought will prepare the way for something else than 
 absolute monarchy, though the transition may be violent. 
 
 "When people speak of freedom of thought, they generally 
 mean, not the mere freedom of thinking for yourself, but 
 the '' right to the free expression of opinion," ^ the freedom 
 of speech and the freedom of writing and circulating opinions. 
 The French Declaration of 1789 asserts that " the free com- 
 munication of thoughts and opinions is one of the most precious 
 rights of man. Every citizen therefore may speak, write, and 
 print freely, save that he must answer for the abuse of this 
 liberty in the cases determined by the law." In the first 
 section of the Constitution of 1791 (to which, as already said, 
 the Declaration of 1789 is prefixed) it is written: " The Consti- 
 tution guarantees as natural and civil rights . . . liberty 
 to every man to speak, write, print, and publish his thoughts, 
 without his writings being submitted to any censorship or 
 inspection before publication." The Declaration of 1793 
 asserts the right to free expression of opinion in less guarded 
 terms : " The right of manifesting one's thought and one's 
 opinions, whether by means of the press or in any other 
 manner . . . cannot be interdicted." This ambiguous 
 " cannot be," which provoked the wrath of Bentham," is 
 clearly meant to mean "ought not to be." Thought cannot, 
 as a matter of strict fact, be subjected to legal penalties : the 
 manifestation of thought may be so subjected. The Consti- 
 tution of 1793 " guarantees to all Frenchmen equality, libert}^ 
 security, property, the national debt,^ the free exercise of 
 religious worship, a system of public education, State relief 
 {des secours ^^(6//c8), the unlimited freedom of the press (Ja 
 liberfe indefinie de Ja pvesse)^ the right of petition, the right of 
 meeting in popular societies [we might interpret this — the 
 
 ^ Cf. Dicey, Law of the Constitution, Ed. 3, p. 224. 
 
 ^ See his Anarchical Fallacies, in Works, Vol. II. pp. 499, etc. 
 
 ^ Art. 122. "La dette publique." This means, I suppose, that the State 
 will not repudiate its debts. It sounds a little odd to name the national 
 debt among the privileges of citizenship ; though it does not need much 
 reflection to see, that the financial honesty of a State is a thing in which 
 its citizens are most deeply interested.
 
 CH. vii] THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 151 
 
 right of association and of public meeting], tlie enjo3'ment of 
 all the rights of man." The last clause makes a double guar- 
 antee of all the preceding rights ; but (alas for promises !) the 
 events which followed the promulgation of this Girondist 
 Constitution are an unfortunate commentary on its unrestricted 
 liberality. In the Declaration of Rights and Duties prefixed 
 to the Constitution of 1705, the right of free expression of 
 opinion is conspicuous by its absence. But it may be presumed 
 that the authors of that Declaration thought the right suffi- 
 ciently secured, though with the necessary restrictions, by the 
 definition of liberty which is adapted from the original Decla- 
 ration of 1789 : " Liberty consists in doing what does not 
 injure the rights of another." To the body of the Constitution 
 {Titve^w. § 353) is transferred the provision that "No one 
 can^ be hindered from saying, writing, printing and publishing 
 his thought. AVritings cannot [i.e. must not] be submitted to 
 any censorship before their publication. No one can be made 
 responsible for that which he has written or published, except 
 in the cases contemplated by the law." The Constitution of 
 1795 thus returns, so far as intention goes, to the position taken 
 up in the Constitution of 1791. Only the short-lived Consti- 
 tution of 1793 ventures to proclaim an absolute and unqualified 
 liberty of the press. The important feature of both the other 
 Constitutions is their acceptance of the principle, which had 
 been laid down in England by Lord Mansfield in these words : 
 " The liberty of the press consists in printing without an}'' 
 previous license, subject to the consequences of law," ^ — that is 
 to say, I am free to publish what I choose, but if I libel any 
 one, or if 1 infringe a copyright, I may have an action raised 
 against me ; and if there are on the statute-book laws against 
 treason, or against blasphemy, or against indecency, I may be 
 made responsible before the courts for any offence against 
 such laws. 
 
 In calling attention to this resemblance between these two 
 
 ' The "can" must be understood as meaning "shall by any law or execu- 
 tive order," since there is apparently no intention of coercing publisliers 
 and editors, who know various ways of hindering people from manifest- 
 ing their thought — not always entirely to the puljlic detriment. Even 
 the compositor can hinder a person froni jiuhli^hing his thought, by 
 misreading the author's ''copy." 
 
 * Quoted by Dicey, Law of the Constitution, Ed. 3, p. 232, from ll>-x 
 V. Dean of St. Amph, 3 T. R. 431 (note).
 
 152 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [ch. vii 
 
 revolutionary Constitutions and the principle of the English 
 law on the subject, I am not forgetting the difference, which 
 Professor Dicey points out so lucidly,^ between the usual Con- 
 tinental practice of dealing with press offences before special 
 tribunals and the English tradition of recognising no special 
 class of press offences. This difference is of great importance 
 to an}^ one who is tracing the history of the liberty of the press 
 in different countries. But I am here only concerned with the 
 general principle, that the liberty of free expression of opinion, 
 even when explicitly proclaimed in a Declaration of Rights, 
 must, if we are to avoid anarchj^, be subject to some restric- 
 tions. What these limits should be, and by what j)rocedure 
 they should be enforced, are very important questions of 
 practical legislation. But in the solution of them, is any help 
 to be got from the principle of natural rights ? It would be a 
 mere quibble to say that a preliminary censorship interferes 
 with a natural right, while a subsequent prosecution does not. 
 If there is a natural and indefeasible right inherent in every 
 individual to express his opinions freely, it is equally wrong to 
 punish him for having exercised that right, and to prevent 
 him exercising it. If the right to express opinions freely 
 is from the first regarded as necessarily checked and limited 
 by the need of avoiding "injury to others," such checks, so 
 far as the principle of natural rights goes, may seem to be 
 better applied before any injury is done than after the mischief 
 has actually taken place. Prevention is better than cure : and 
 that is exactl}^ the principle on which such institutions as a 
 literary censorship have been defended,^ It might even be 
 argued that the individual has a natural right to be protected 
 by government against the insults, indecencies, and profani- 
 ties of reckless scribblers, just as he expects to be protected 
 
 ' Law of the Constitution^ ch. vi. 
 
 ^ Cf. the argument of Dr. Johnson in his Life of Milton : " It seems not 
 more reasonable to leave the right of printing unrestrained, because 
 writers may be afterwards censured, than it would be to sleep with doors 
 unbolted, because by our laws we can hang a thief." Our laws do not, 
 howerer, oblige the policeman to find out wfhere every man is going 
 to, lest one or two should be thieves. Dr. Johnson was not likely to 
 sympathise with WAion'a Areojmgitica', but he seldom goes as strongly 
 against the current of his century, as when he says, "If every murmurer 
 at government may diffuse discontent, there can be no peace; and if every 
 sceptic in theology may teach his follies, there can be no religion." For 
 peace and piety now-a-days we should have to go to Russia.
 
 CH. vii] THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 153 
 
 against assaults upon his person. Both claims might be classed 
 under the general claim of a natural right of security. 
 
 If a distinction be drawn between injuries to the bod}' and 
 injuries to the mind or character, it is drawn on grounds of ex- 
 pediency and convenience. Injuries to the mind and character 
 may be worse than injuries to the body, but the}^ are injuries 
 respecting which the ordinary person has more difficulty in 
 deciding. No government — except under revolutionary or ex- 
 ceptional conditions — undertakes to arrest intending criminals : 
 the habitual arrest of persons on suspicion becomes itself an 
 evil as great as the occasional commission of crimes. An 
 author's manuscript is more easily inspected than the intentions 
 of a person of whom the police are suspicious ; so that a censor- 
 ship cannot be put aside simply on the grounds of impossibility. 
 On the other hand, a censor presumes to judge for a great mass 
 of human beings and for the future. It is a great and difficult 
 responsibility, "Who kills a man," says Milton, " kills a reason- 
 able creature, God's image; but he who destroys a good^ book 
 kills reason itself, kills the image of God, as it were in the eye," 
 "It cannot be denied," he says farther on in his immortal 
 Areojjagitica, " but that he who is made judge to sit upon the 
 birth or death of books, whether they may be wafted into this 
 world or not, had need to be a man above the common measure, 
 both studious, learned, and judicious," If the censor, he argues, 
 is such a person, how irksome a drudgery are we imposing on 
 him ; if he is not, how badly will the work be done. The 
 stupidity of censors, their venality, the wretched subterfuges 
 to which they drive authors — such subterfuges as those prac- 
 tised by Voltaire,^ and which help to make him so strange a 
 mixture of the knight-errant and the monkey — such things 
 are the best practical proof of the mischief of a censorship. 
 And it is well worth noting that it was the practical incon- 
 veniences of the licensing system which led to the abolition of 
 a censorship of the press in England, The House of Commons 
 discontinued (in 1695) the temporary Act which placed the 
 press under the control of licensers, and induced the Lords to 
 give way on the subject, not on any general grounds of a 
 
 ' " A Genevese worshipper would sometimes take up in church a book 
 lettered as, and looking like, the Psahns, only to find that it was a copj' 
 of the one-volume edition of the Dlctionnalre Fhilosophiquey—E>ip[ns.sse, 
 Life of Voltaire ["'Great Writers" Series], p. 151.
 
 154 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [ch. vii 
 
 natural right to free expression of opinion, nor even on the 
 grounds urged by Milton of the injury done to truth by im- 
 pediments put in the way of its pursuit, but " on account of 
 the petty grievances, the exactions, the jobs, the commercial 
 restrictions, the domiciliary visits which were incidental to " ^ 
 the enforcement of the Licensing Act, " Such were the argu- 
 ments," says Macaulay, "which did what Milton's ^reopa^i/ica 
 had failed to do." The reasons given by the Commons for dis- 
 senting with the Lords, when the latter proposed to continue 
 the Licensing Act, were supplied, it seems, by John Locke.^ 
 And it is specially to be noted that here Locke makes no use 
 of the doctrine of natural rights. Locke proposes exactly the 
 system now always accepted in this countr3^ " I know not," 
 he says, " why a man should not have liberty to print whatever 
 he would speak ; and to be answerable for the one, just as he 
 is for the other, if he transgresses the law in either. But 
 gagging a man, for fear he should talk heresy or sedition, has 
 no other ground than such as will make gyves necessary, for 
 fear a man should use violence if his hands were free, and must 
 at last end in the imprisonment of all who, you will suspect, 
 may be guilty of treason or misdemeanour. To prevent men 
 being undiscovered for what they print, you may prohibit any 
 book to be printed, j)ublished, or sold without the printer's or 
 bookseller's name, under great penalties, whatever be in it. 
 And then let the printer or bookseller whose name is to it be 
 answerable for whatever is against law in it, as if he were the 
 author, unless he can produce the person he had it from, which 
 is all the restraint ought to be upon printing."^ 
 
 Under this system, what we call the liberty of the press 
 and the freedom of thought have gradually, though not in an 
 untroubled course, progressed in this country. No such right 
 as the liberty of the press has ever been recognised by the law. 
 The " practical right " has come solely from the fact of re- 
 sponsibility to the ordinary law only. The laws about sedition 
 and about blasphemy might seem to make liberty of the press, 
 as we understand it, impossible, even after the censorship was 
 abolished. The uncertain security of the writer in the free 
 expression of his thought has lain only in the institution of 
 
 ' Macaulay, History of England, ch. xxi. 
 
 2 See Fox Bourne, Life of Locke, II. pp. 311-316. 
 
 '' Lord King's Life of Locke (Bohn's edition), pp. 202-208.
 
 CH. vii] THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY 155 
 
 trial by jur}'. We have had no special tribunals for the trial 
 of press offences. " Freedom of discussion," as Professor Dicey- 
 puts it, " is in England little else than the right to write or say 
 anything which a jury, consisting of twelve shopkeepers, think 
 it expedient should be said or written. Such ' liberty ' may 
 vary at different times and seasons from unrestricted license 
 to very severe restraint, and the experience of English history 
 during the last two centuries shows that under the law of 
 libel the amount of latitude conceded to the expression of 
 opinion has, in fact, differed greatly according to the condition 
 of popular sentiment." ^ The question is well worth raising : 
 whether a security, which has proved effectual when the 
 majority of the class from which jurymen are drawn had a 
 general tendency to give a verdict against the government, is 
 likely, when political and social conditions have changed, to 
 prove a sufHcient security for what many would consider legiti- 
 mate freedom of thought. An extended franchise and the re- 
 moval of the disabilities of Dissenters have made the sentiment 
 of the average juryman less sympathetic with some types of in- 
 tellectual rebellion than he was in the days of Pitt. Suppose a 
 still more extended suffrage and the Church disestablished, the 
 average juryman would be relatively still more " conservative," 
 and it is just conceivable that the free expression even of 
 political opinion might not be so well safeguarded as we think, 
 if an anti-revolutionary panic should overtake the country. 
 Suppose, further, that the qualification of jurymen were lowered 
 or abolished, it might still happen that in any community of 
 very homogeneous belief in religious matters and of very settled 
 social conditions, the author, whom we may regard as exer- 
 cising only a reasonable liberty of expressing his opinions 
 (whether we agree with his opinions or not), might find him- 
 self punished for offending against the religious or political 
 belief of the majority. Suppose Shelley to be tried before a jury 
 of Welsh Calvinistic Methodists, or Mr. Herbert Spencer before 
 a jury in a Collectivist community ; would either of them be 
 sure of getting a fair trial ? The absence of homogeneity in 
 religious beliefs, and the fact that so great a mass of the popu- 
 lation wish the liberty of airing different grievances and of 
 advocating different reforms, is a great security for the liberty 
 even of the more daring intellectual rebel. 
 
 ' Laic of the Constitution, Ed. 3, p. 231.
 
 156 THE RIGHT OF LIBERTY [ch. vii 
 
 A consideration of the degree of liberty or license allowed 
 under our system of dealing with, the press calls attention 
 forcibly to the dependence of such liberty on the prevailing 
 mood of public sentiment. No formal declaration of the liberty 
 of the press or of the freedom of opinion will of itself secure 
 the habitual exercise of such " rights," unless public opinion 
 continues to support the idea. But it may very well be ar- 
 gued that the existence of such a formal declaration, even if 
 it cannot, without risk of anarchy, be made constitutionally 
 or legally binding, has a very important moral effect in restrain- 
 ing the prejudices or the passions of the multitude. And that 
 is really the chief use which such Declarations serve.
 
 CHAPTER VIII 
 
 TOLERATION 
 
 I HAVE been assuming that a very wide, though undefined, 
 degree of toleration for diversity of opinion is a good thing. 
 It may reasonably be urged that, if the theory of natural 
 rights is rejected, such an assumption needs proof. In saying 
 a little about " toleration," it will be most convenient to go 
 beyond mere freedom of expressing opinion in speech and 
 writing, and to take account also of that form of freedom of 
 action which consists in the free exercise of religious worship 
 and the carrying out of religious principles into outward con- 
 duct. I have used the word " toleration " because it is the 
 name under which the struggle for liberty in matters of belief 
 has been generally fought out. In itself the word, on the 
 whole, has the advantage, rare in terms of controversy, of being 
 neutral. It does not ostentatiously claim to be a good thing ; 
 there was, at least, no absurdity of language in the denuncia- 
 tions of the wickedness of toleration, so common in the seven- 
 teenth century. It is still intelligible, and not uncommon, to 
 speak of the toleration of vice or of political corruption as being 
 a bad thing. It is true that in its original use the word implied 
 a certain set of opinions and beliefs and practices approved of 
 by the Church or by the State, while certain other opinions 
 or beliefs and practices, though not accepted nor indeed ap- 
 proved of by the powers that be, might 3'et be " tolerated." 
 In any case the word implies that the right is granted by the 
 community to individuals. It is this suggestion in the term 
 of a special favour or gracious condescension which provoked 
 the indignation of Paine. " Toleration," he says, "is not the 
 opposite of intolerance, but is the counterfeit of it. Both are 
 despotisms. The one assumes to itself the right of withholding 
 liberty of conscience, and the other of granting it. The one 
 is the pope armed with fire and faggot, the other is the pope 
 selling or granting indulgences."^ Paine urges it as a special 
 
 ' Itiijhts of Man, p. Bl (Ed. 18S3). 
 
 157
 
 158 TOLERATION. [ch. viii 
 
 merit of the Frencli Constitution that it "hath abolished or 
 renounced Toleration and Intolerance also, and hath estab- 
 lished Universal Right of Conscience." The Constitution to 
 Avhich Paine is here referring is the Constitution of 1791, not 
 that of 1793, in the framing of the original form of which he 
 had himself some part. In the Declaration of Rights of 1789 
 (Constitution of 1791), as we have already seen, the limits of 
 liberty are expressly said to be determinable only by the law, 
 and not therefore by the conscience of any one and every one. 
 The tenth article of the Declaration asserts that " No one ought 
 to be molested on account of his opinions, even on matters of 
 religion {'pour ses opinions^ meme rellgieuses)^ provided that bis 
 ' manifestation ' ^ of them does not disturb the public order 
 established by the law." In both articles the " law " is made 
 the arbiter of liberty, so that the very idea which Paine objects 
 to in the word "toleration" is introduced. The Declaration 
 of 1793 omits these qualifications, and may therefore be taken 
 as representing better Paine's own ideal. " The right of ex- 
 pressing one's thought and one's opinions . . . and the 
 free exercise of religious worship ((Ze.? cultes) cannot be pro- 
 hibited." If such "rights" are supposed to be incapable of 
 limitation, they will certainly come into conflict with the 
 principle of not injuring the rights of others, especially as 
 "security" and "property" are included among these rights. 
 Suppose an individual were to declare that his conscience or 
 an express revelation from Grod commanded him to offer up 
 his son in sacrifice as a part of his religious duty (the son con- 
 senting), Paine would have been more ready to denounce the 
 detestable superstition than to guarantee the free exercise of 
 this piece of religious worship, and he would not have shown 
 much respect to any kind of government that did not endeavour 
 strictly to prohibit any such "free exercise." The assertion 
 of a " Universal Right of Conscience " in any absolute and 
 indefeasible sense would oblige a government to take the word 
 of every individual for his own sincerity in saying what his 
 conscience ordained. If we refuse to allow the individual to 
 judge in his own case (as every well-regulated society must 
 in a great many instances refuse to do), we give up any absolute 
 
 ' The word is manifestation. Paine's translation "avowal" is not quite 
 enough. We might paraphrase " w&y of expressing them." The word 
 "even" (historically interesting) must have jarred on Paine.
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 159 
 
 right of the individual conscience and fall back upon the 
 authority of the legislature and the law-courts, which decide 
 to " tolerate " certain kinds of acts and utterances within 
 limits determined by the law, and not to tolerate other kinds 
 of acts and utterances, i.e. to punish those who are convicted 
 of them. We may very well rest content with the word 
 " toleration," which correctly expresses the nature of the liberty 
 allowed, and suggests the source of that liberty, and has, more- 
 over, received a sufficiently honourable consecration from the 
 use of it in the long struggle against ecclesiastical intolerance. 
 This matter of toleration is very apt to be thought much 
 simpler than it really is. We flatter ourselves that we no 
 longer persecute people for their religious or other opinions, 
 and we condemn the persecutions inflicted in past time by 
 Church and State. We seem to have a difficulty in understand- 
 ing how Christian people came to persecute ; for persecution is 
 supposed to be inconsistent with the religion they professed, and 
 inconsistent also with the true purposes of government, which 
 seem to us necessarily to include the safeguarding of liberty of 
 conscience. Now, in the first place, it must be pointed out that 
 " persecution " is a question-begging term. It means " repres- 
 sion," or " compulsion," of which the person using the term "per- 
 secution " disapproves. Public opinion has undergone great 
 changes as to the kind of actions which ought to be legally 
 repressed, or may be legally repressed without attendant evils, 
 that are too great to be risked. At all times people have been 
 ready to tolerate certain kinds of acts and utterances, but have 
 regarded it as a duty to suppress other kinds, if possible. The 
 line between what might be tolerated and what might not 
 has, however, been very differently drawn at different times, 
 and the methods of repression adopted have also differed very 
 greatly. Nowadays we blackball our heretics at a club, or 
 we try to subject them to what is called (in journalistic ignor- 
 ance of a Greek institution) " social ostracism," where our 
 ancestors would have used for their heretics the coarser methods 
 of the pillory and the stake. The "heresies" differ; the 
 methods of punishment differ. The spirit which leads to 
 l)ersecution remains, and it is a spirit which, in some forin, 
 is necessary to the cohesion and existence of any snciet}'. A 
 universal and absolute toleration of everything and everybody 
 would lead to a general chaos as certainly as a universal and
 
 i6o TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 absolute intolerance. We are all " dogmatists " on some ques- 
 tions, while prepared to treat others as relatively matters of 
 indifference on which we can tolerate diversity of opinion. 
 We are all ready to " persecute," i.e. to use the force of govern- 
 ment and the pressure of popular sentiment, in support of our 
 dogmas where it is otherwise expedient and safe to do so, some- 
 times even where it is not. We persecute "conscientious" 
 persons in support of the " dogma" of vaccination; we " per- 
 secute" the Peculiar People who quote Scripture to sanction 
 their neglect of getting medical attendance for their dying 
 children ; some people would like to " persecute " scientific 
 men, who have by their experiments defied the " dogma " of 
 anti-vivisection and violated the natural rights of frogs and — 
 microbes. Those who hold the " dogma " of monogamy, still 
 more those who hold the " dogma " of the equality of the sexes, 
 persecute the polygamist, who is, at a humble distance, follow- 
 ing the example of those saints of the Old Testament, whose 
 lives have edified many generations of Christian people. The 
 " persecution " of Mormonism in a land of professed " religious 
 liberty " like the United States is an instructive comment on 
 the notion that Declarations of natural rights will protect in- 
 dividuals who do what is unpopular. To the onlooker it is 
 even a little grotesque that in a society which permits such 
 varied " experiments in living " as the easy-going divorce laws 
 of some States allow, there should be so little toleration for an 
 experiment in restoring a primitive and venerable type of the 
 family ^ — the only form of it which, in old countries with an 
 excessive female population, could give a fair chance of becom- 
 ing "a wife and mother" to every woman; and, according to the 
 view many persons profess to hold about the " natural sphere " 
 of woman, such a fair chance might be reasonably considered 
 every woman's "natural right." 
 
 Of course the objection is ready to hand, that I am here con- 
 fusing the repression of acts which are obviously injurious to 
 society with persecution because of belief in theological doc- 
 trines, that I am confusing martyrs for religious faith with 
 criminal and vicious persons. " Criminals," it may be as well 
 
 ' Cf. J. G. Schurman, The Ethical Import of Darivinism,^. 263. "Blind 
 to the havoc which divorce is making in the old family system, we atone 
 for our manners by embodying the principles of our fathers in denuncia- 
 tion of the Mormons." See note B at end of this chapter.
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION i6i 
 
 to point out, means simply — those who have done actions which 
 the law of the land classes as " crimes." If the law of the 
 land makes heres}^ of any particular form a "crime," the here- 
 tic is a criminal. Put yourself for a moment in the place of 
 the persecutor of old days, and you will see that he looked at 
 religious persecution (as ice call it) exactly in the same manner 
 in which you look upon the repression of polygamy, or of vivi- 
 section, or of indecent literature, or of the liquor traffic, or 
 whatever may happen to be 3'our special aversion among what 
 you regard as the evils of the time. Opinion has changed as 
 to the things which ought to be forcibly repressed, as to the 
 things which can safely be repressed, and as to the methods of 
 repression which it is right or expedient to use. AVe are all 
 (except Count Tolstoi and a few benevolent anarchists) agreed 
 that some kinds of conduct ought to be repressed by force, if it 
 is possible and safe to do so : we differ as to what kinds of 
 conduct these are. It cannot even be said that we have limited 
 ourselves to the repression of acU of which we disapprove, and 
 that we leave people to express their opinions quite freely in 
 speech or writing, however much we disapprove of these 
 opinions and however mischievous we think them : a speech 
 which contains incitement to murder or violence is punishable 
 by law, and certain kinds of literature are liable to suppression 
 on the grounds of indecency, even where the conduct to 
 which they may be supposed to incite is not made " criminal " 
 by the law of the land, though condemned as "vicious" by 
 prevalent popular opinion. That is to say, lijnits are in all 
 civilised countries, however "tolerant," imposed on the liberty 
 of speech and writing as well as on the liberty of action. 
 
 We consider that to circulate false coins is rightly made a 
 crime and punished very severelj^ by the law of the land. 8t. 
 Thomas Aquinas considers that heretics are much more mis- 
 chievous persons than the utterers of false coins. " For it is a 
 much heavier offence to corrupt the faith, whereby the life of 
 the soul is sustained, than to tamper with the coinage, which 
 is an aid to temporal life. Hence if coiners or other malefac- 
 tors are at once handed over by secular princes to a just death, 
 much more may heretics, immediately they are convicted of 
 heresy, be not only excommunicated, but also justly done to 
 die." But although such immediate capital punishment of 
 heretics is just, the Church is merciful. " On the part of the 
 
 N. u. M
 
 1 62 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 Church is mercy in view of the conversion of them that err ; 
 and therefore she does not condemn at once, but ' after the 
 first and second admonition,' as the Apostle teaches {Titus iii. 
 10) : After that, however, if the man is still found pertinacious, 
 the Church, having no hope of his conversion, provides for the 
 safety of others, cutting him off from the Church by the sen- 
 tence of excommunication ; and further, she leaves him to the 
 secular tribunal to be exterminated from the world by death." ^ 
 It is worth observing that St, Thomas Aquinas here assigns 
 as the reason for the punishment of the heretic, not simply a 
 desire to vindicate the honour of God, a desire which we might 
 say modern legislation had found it right or expedient to leave 
 unsatisfied, but " the safety of others." 
 
 There should really be nothing startling in this passage 
 of Aquinas : it is difficult to see how a theologian, sincerely 
 believing that the Church is in possession of absolutely cer- 
 tain knowledge (so far as God has been pleased to reveal it) 
 respecting the destiny of the human soul and the principles 
 of right and wrong, can hold any different view about the 
 treatment of heretics, where the Church has sufficient power 
 to keep itself free from the taint of corruption. He may, in- 
 deed, hold that burning was too cruel a punishment, though 
 the blame for that rests with the temporal powers, the Church 
 handing over heretics with the merciful request that they 
 were to be put to death " without the shedding of blood"! 
 he may hold that imprisonment or even exclusion from the 
 privileges of citizenship would be a sufficient penalty and 
 bring less discredit on the Church from its unsympathetic 
 enemies. But he cannot consistently admit the claims of the 
 Roman Catholic Church to universal dominion over the souls 
 of men and to the possession of absolute truth, and yet hold 
 that the heretic ought to be left quite free, and should even 
 be defended by the arm of the law, in propagating his soul- 
 destroying opinions. The modern Roman Catholic theologian 
 may admit that manners have become milder, even among 
 
 ' '2a 286, qu. 11, art. 3. I quote from Father Rickaby's translation, 
 which puts quotation marks before the words " After that, etc.," but has 
 no indication of where the quotation ends. They ought to come at latest at 
 the word " excommunication." The passage in Titus cannot possibly be 
 stretched to mean more than that. As I understand St. Thomas, the 
 words " ut Apostolus docet " are meant to apply directly to the immedi- 
 atel}- preceding phrase alone. 
 
 I
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 163 
 
 theologians, and that the Church's claws are cut and her jaws 
 muzzled : he cannot admit that she ought never under 
 favourable conditions to use her teeth or to get the civil power 
 to scratch and bite for her. Let me quote Father Rickaby's 
 commentary on the passage just cited from the Angelic Doc- 
 tor : — 
 
 ''Are heretics to he tolerated f A question to ask in the nineteenth 
 century ! The changes of the last six hundred years may be reduced to 
 three heads. 
 
 1. The formation of heretical bodies of long standing, the individual 
 members of which, never having professed the Catholic faith, and bein>^ 
 ignorant of it, and from infancy prejudiced against it, cannot without 
 distinction be called heretics. ^ 
 
 2. The fallen estate of the Church as a political power.^ 
 
 1 This is a point very often ignored by, or unknown to, the Protestant 
 controversialist who is stirring up intolerance against Roman Catholics. 
 
 ^ I assume that Father Eickaby in these words is referring generally 
 to the diminished inflvience of the Church in j^olitical affairs : but his 
 words would include a reference to the loss of the temporal pow-er in a 
 portion of Italy. On this matter of the temporal power I think it worth 
 while to quote a passage from the Catholic Dictionary of Addis and 
 Arnold. (I purposely take my quotations from representatives of a very 
 tolerant and very enlightened Catholicism. Mr. Addis is no longer a 
 Catholic.) The passage may serve as a further illustration of the way 
 in which earnest modern Catholics feel obliged to look at the subject of 
 toleration. In the article on the " States of the Church " we are told 
 that "Protestants themselves, or the more reasonable and enlightened 
 among them, view w^ith grief and scorn the process by which Rome is 
 being reduced to the level of an English or American town. They would 
 prefer that at least one place should be left on earth where Catholic 
 principles of government and maxims of life might be applied without 
 disturbance. They would wish to see the Sacred Congregations again 
 discharging their critical and judicial functions. It might be said tliat 
 the discipline so set up must be inelifectual ; a Roman could obtain the 
 works of Renan or Paul de Kock at Florence, if the sale were forbidden 
 at Rome; he could turn Methodist and rant in public at Naples, if this 
 luxury were denied to him at home. But what then ? Is it nothing 
 that an example of right practice should be given, towards which 
 European society, dislocated as it now is, might gradually tend?" The 
 tourist in search of the picturesque, who complains that Rome (which 
 never was a t3'pical mediaeval city) is losing some of its mediaeval 
 quaintness, is dragged in as a witness on behalf of the claim of the Pope 
 to " mismanage the drains of a third-rate European city." He, or she, 
 would like to have a good specimen of a kind of spectacle that has become 
 obsolete. It w-ould be so interesting to see the Sacred Congregations 
 at work: to see a Giordano Bruno, for instance, being roasted. But per- 
 haps another class of tourist might think it equally interesting to see 
 the spectacle of an older Rome, to witness a gladiatorial contest in the
 
 1 64 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 3. The irritation set up in modern minds at the sight of men punished 
 for opinions, whether political or religious : a fact that the Church would 
 have to reckon with, even if she had might on her side, and consider 
 whether it would be prudent in her nowadays to visit heresy with 
 all the ancient penalties. For the Church's punishments are medicinal ; ' 
 and the same medicine does not suit every age and constitution of 
 society. The Church, however, still insists on her right to punish by 
 corporal intlictions. Pius IX, condemned this proposition (Syllabus, 24) : 
 ' The Church has no authority to use force.' " 
 
 In his manual of Moral Philosophy Father Rickaby discusses 
 the right of the State to control the expression of opinion. At 
 the end of his section on " Liberty of Opinion," he says : 
 " Penalties for the expression of opinion are available only so 
 far as they tally with the common feeling of the country. 
 When public opinion ceases to bear them out, it is better not 
 to enforce them : for that were but to provoke resentment and 
 make martyrs " — a most valuable lesson from the experience 
 of history. No regulation can be maintained except in a 
 congenial atmosphere. " Allowance, too, must be made for the 
 danger of driving the evil to burrow underground " (p. 370)— a 
 most important matter to be considered in all schemes for en- 
 forcing a uniform type of opinion or conduct. As to the duty 
 of the State to prevent the spread of what he considers per- 
 nicious opinions. Father Rickaby has- not the least doubt 
 "where the atmosphere is congenial," i.e. where the State can 
 carry on an effective persecution of heresy. " Silencing dis- 
 cussion," he says, " is an assumption, not of infallibility, but of 
 certainty " (p. 366); so that, even on matters where infallibility 
 is not claimed, the State may silence discussion. A great and, 
 on the whole, reasonable distinction is drawn between " free 
 discussion among competent persons " and " free discussion 
 among the incompetent and incapable." ^ 
 
 Coliseum, or to see the Christians as living torches lighting up Nero's 
 gardens. The tourist in search of strange and vivid sensations, who looks 
 on the whole of Italy as if it were a spectacular exhibition in an American 
 circus got up for his amusement, might even find the more ancient spec- 
 tacle the more attractive and exciting performance of the two. As to 
 " reasonable and enlightened " persons, Protestant or not, a little know- 
 ledge of how the Popes used to govern, and a little imagination as to 
 how "the example of right practice" would w^ork out if gradually fol- 
 lowed by all European countries, would probably be sufficient to deter 
 them from doing anything to revive the experiment of putting the sword 
 of the civil magistrate into the hands of the priest. 
 
 1 Very nasty physic sometimes. 
 
 ^ This distinction was made by Laud in England. He was tolerant
 
 CH. vm] TOLERATION 165 
 
 In answer to the objection " that it is immoral to interfere 
 with conscience and to attempt to stifle sincere convictions," 
 Father Rickaby writes : " The State has nothing to do with 
 convictions as such, nor with the inward convictions of anj'' 
 man. But if the State is sincerely convinced that the convic- 
 tions openl}^ professed and propagated by some of its subjects 
 are subversive of social order and public morality, whose sin- 
 cere conviction is it that must carry the day in practice ? It 
 is of the essence of government that the convictions, sincere or 
 otherwise, of the governed shall on certain practical issues be 
 waived in the external observance in favour of the convictions 
 of the ruling power. After all, this talk of conscience and 
 sincere convictions is but the canting phrase of the day, ac- 
 cording to which conscience means mere wild humour and 
 headstrong self-will.^ Such teachings as those which we would 
 have the State to suppress, e.g. An oath is a folly ; ~ There is 
 no law of purity ; There is no harm in doing anything that does 
 not annoy your neighbour : are not the teachings of men sin- 
 cerely convinced : they deserve no respect, consideration or 
 tenderness on that score. , . , When a man proclaims 
 some blatant and atrocious error in a matter bearing directly 
 upon public morals — and it is for the restraint of these errors 
 alone that we are arguing^ — there is a decided jjrcesumptlo juris, 
 that the error in him, however doggedly he maintains it, is 
 not a sincere, candid, and innocently formed conviction." 
 " Sincere conviction " is to be respected ; but we are the judges 
 of who is sincere, and we decide that every one who maintains 
 any opinion about public morals which is contrary to what we 
 believe (since it has been revealed to us by the Law of God or 
 the Law of Nature) is insincere, and therefore is not to be 
 respected ! I think it a pity that Father Rickaby did not 
 
 of learned discussion in big folios, but not of theological arguments and 
 political conclusions in sermons before the ordinarj'- laity. Cf. Gardiner, 
 History of Englnnd, 1603-1642, Vol. VII. p. 124. Pitt is said to have given 
 as his reason for not prosecuting Godwin for his Political Justice that 
 "a three-guinea book could never do much harm among those who had 
 not three shillings to spare" — toleration for high-priced heresy only. 
 
 ' How precisely all this expresses what the average Roman magistrate 
 must have felt in dealing with obstinate Christians, who refused to offi'r 
 incense to the Emperor's statue. 
 
 ^ What about the teaching that an oath is a sin, because forbidden by 
 Jesus Christ ? 
 
 ^ " In this particular book or place," I assume, ho means.
 
 1 66 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 avoid suggesting this time-honoured way of dealing with dis- 
 senters, religious or social — to deny the sincerity and to assail 
 the character of those who differ from you even on questions 
 of morality.^ He is on safer and surer ground when he says 
 that "the convictions, sincere or otherwise," of some persons 
 may have to be overridden in the interests, or what are sup- 
 posed to be the interests, of the well-being of the community 
 as a whole. So far as this general statement goes, we all — 
 except a few amiable anarchists — agree with Father Rickaby. 
 We may not like to admit the principle in words ; we adopt it 
 in practice, and it is well that we should realise clearly that 
 we do so, because we shall then be more fully alive to the re- 
 sponsibility we undertake in all legislation which is intended 
 to protect individuals, especially the young, against what we 
 consider indecent literature, pictures, etc. If a person accused 
 of disseminating indecent hterature pleads that he sincerely 
 believes the incriminated works to be of real artistic value, or 
 to contain sound doctrine wholesome and necessary for these 
 times, the plea is not likely to weigh with a jury who sincerely 
 believe the works in question to be detestable and pernicious 
 rubbish. Wiser persons and a later generation may differ 
 from the jury in their estimate : the typical juryman is not 
 exactly the person whom the lovers of art and literature would 
 like to entrust with the power of drawing up an Index Ex- 
 piwgatorius. Still, if the law prohibits indecency, as most 
 persons probably think it should, it seems safest to leave the 
 interpretation of "indecency" to fair representatives of the 
 community as a whole. Otherwise, who is to judge? AVe 
 have given up the plan of a censorship, except in the case of 
 stage plays : and the licensing functions of the Lord Chamber- 
 lain are often severely criticised. 
 
 ' In liis attitude to those whom he regards as in error as to matters of 
 morals, Father Rickaby seems to me to come short of the principle of St. 
 Thomas Aquinas, Avho holds (la 2ie, qu. 19, art. 5) that " when an errone- 
 ous reason proposes something as the precept of God, then it is the same 
 thing- to despise the dictate of reason as to despise the precept of God," 
 which seems to imply that a person may sincerely have opinions about 
 matters of morals and doctrine which St. Thomas Aquinas regards as very 
 grave errors, e.g. that to abstain from fornication is evil, or that to believe 
 in Christ is evil. These are Aquinas's own illustrations, and they are 
 evidently chosen by him as opinions the most hateful to a mediaeval 
 theologian.
 
 CH. VII i] TOLERATION 167 
 
 But while Father Rickab3^'s statement in its general form 
 expresses the principle which is accepted with the consent of 
 the majority in our legislation and in the administration of the 
 law, there would be great difference of opinion as to the par- 
 ticular " teachings " which we would have the State suppress. 
 Aiid I doubt if any British legislature, or any British jury, 
 would be likely to regard as an incitement to immorality the 
 doctrine that there is no harm in doing anything that does tiot 
 annoy your neighbour, which is just the definition that the 
 French Declarations give of " liberty." I do not think the 
 officials of the Post Office would consider a copy of The 
 Rights of Man to be an obscene publication, or that any 
 one is likely to be successfully prosecuted by a Vigilance 
 Committee for selling a copy of Mill's Liberty ; and yet both 
 of these works preach this " blatant and atrocious error " 
 which Father Rickaby thinks that no one can sincerely 
 maintain. The doctrine seems to me, indeed, so extremely 
 vague and ambiguous that it is useless as a general principle 
 or law of nature from which to deduce safe maxims of morals 
 or legislation. It is a formula which implies the fallacious 
 theory, as it seems to me, that there exist purely self-referrent 
 actions, and that these can always be easily distinguished from 
 those that affect others. The word " annoy " and the word 
 '' neighbour " stand also in need of definition. On the other 
 hand, the formula does express in a very crude and rough way 
 the great ethical principle which is coming more and more to 
 supplant both the old theory of the Law of Nature and the 
 appeal to external authority — the principle, namely, that right 
 and wrong are to be judged by the standard of social well- 
 being. The principle is expressed in a way open to misinter- 
 pretation, because it implies the conception of society as con- 
 sisting merely of mutually exclusive and repellent atoms. It 
 is the Utilitarian principle, still hampered by the individual- 
 istic basis which belongs to the theory of natural rights. It is 
 by this very principle of social well-being that we must judge 
 what limits are to be assigned to free speech and free action. 
 And it is because the conception of the ethical end has itself 
 undergone such great changes, and because the structure and 
 environment of different societies have varied so much, that we 
 can explain the extraordinary differences between different 
 ages and countries in the matter of toleration.
 
 1 68 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 Sir Frederick Pollock, in an essay on " The Theory of Per- 
 secution," ^ has distinguished the grounds of persecution as 
 (1) tribal, (2) political, (3) theological, and (4) social. 
 
 (1) The Jewish persecution of Jews who became Christians 
 will serve as an illustration of the first kind. In all societies 
 of the more primitive type — I mean societies held together by 
 the bond of real or fictitious kinship — the god or gods wor- 
 shipped are the gods of the tribe, and to desert the worship of 
 these gods, or worship them in a way not approved by tradi- 
 tion, is to be disloyal to one's own family, one's own kith 
 and kin. Persecution of this kind, though we should certainly 
 call it "religious persecution," is best understood by us, if we 
 think of the feelings of parents towards undutiful and re- 
 bellious children, who have been led away by evil example. 
 Persecution of this kind is not exercised towards aliens, so long 
 as they do not interfere with the religion of the tribe ; but any 
 wrong done or insult offered to the tribal god will readily pro- 
 voke persecution. The popular hatred of the Christians which 
 was apt to break out in various places throughout the Roman 
 Empire is to be explained in this way. The Ephesians would 
 not have molested the Apostle Paul if they had not thought 
 their special goddess was being injured, — commercial interests, 
 as often happens, supporting the prevalent religion. 
 
 (2) The poUfical reasons for persecution are closely connected 
 with the preceding, and grow out of them. A sharp line can- 
 not, I think, be drawn between these two divisions. When 
 the Athenians put Socrates to death for impiety, it was not, as 
 has been well said, because he introduced false gods, but be- 
 cause he introduced new gods. The religion of a Greek city- 
 state was an inseparable part of its political and social life. 
 The Sophists and Philosophers were exposed to attack on the 
 grounds of introducing dangerous innovations into the State. 
 With the establishment of the Roman Empire we see clearly 
 the predominance of political over tribal grounds of persecu- 
 tion. Under the Roman rule, local cults were not interfered 
 with. The Romans tolerated every kind of religion, except 
 (a) those whose rites seemed to conflict with public morals 
 and public order— like the orgiastic worship of Bacchus — and 
 (6) those which seemed to threaten the stability of the Empire. 
 
 * Essays in Jurisprudence and Ethics, pp. 144 seq. I have followed 
 out in my own way some of the ideas suggested in this admirable essa}'.
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 169 
 
 Druidism and Judaism both suffered at the hands of the 
 Romans, because and in so far as they stirred up political re- 
 bellion ; but the Jewish religion was treated with great tolera- 
 tion on the whole. So far as the Christians suffered molestation 
 or punishment from Roman magistrates, it was because their 
 missionary spirit disturbed the peace of families and of towns, 
 their secret meetings roused suspicion of social danger, their 
 attitude to existing institutions seemed to be anarchical, and 
 their refusal to offer incense to the Emperor's statue appeared 
 a clear proof of disloyalty. They were punished, not on the 
 ground of their beliefs, unless we except their belief in the 
 speedy destruction of the world — not, however, on the ground 
 of any of those beliefs which have remained a permanent part 
 of Christian theology^ but on the same sort of grounds as those 
 on which Social Democrats have been punished in Germany, 
 and Nihilists in Russia. So far as religion goes, the Roman 
 Empire was perhaps the least persecuting government that 
 ever existed on a great scale before the present century, and 
 under no condition of affairs that had previously been known in 
 the world had a missionary religion greater opportunities for 
 spreading itself. The general attitude of the Roman official to 
 the Christian apostle was to protect him from the fanatical 
 vengeance of the offended " tribal " religion of the Jews, His 
 enemies accused Jesus of blasphemy before the Jewish high 
 priest, but before Pilate they accused him of treason against 
 CaBsar. Pagan Rome tolerated all religious doctrines, and tried 
 to keep the peace between rival religions in the same way that 
 the British magistrate does in India.' We have prohibited 
 widows from burning themselves, and we endeavour to prevent 
 disorder. But the model civil servant is as "indifferent" to a 
 theological quarrel between two sects of Mohammedans as was 
 Gallio to what seemed to him a mere squabble between two 
 sects of Jews. 
 
 (3) Persecution, in the sense of repression for the purpose of 
 maintaining true doctrine, is the outcome of Christianity. 
 
 ^ In what I have said about the treatment of the Christians under the 
 Roman Empire, I do not think I have said anything? inconsistent witli 
 the views either of Prof. W. M. Ramsay in his book on The Church in 
 the Roman Empire, or of Mr. E, G. Hardy in his Christianity and the. 
 lloman Government. My statement is a rough, general one, taking no 
 special account of variations of time and place ; but I think it is true on 
 the whole, and certainlj- true of the earlier historj- of the Church.
 
 ijo TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 Such an assertion may seem a malignant slander, inexcusable 
 in any one who remembers the words ascribed to Jesus in the 
 Gospels "Forbid him not," spoken of one who followed not 
 with the disciples, and yet used the name of their Master to 
 cast out devils ; ^ or the rebuke addressed to James and John, 
 when they wished to call down fire from heaven on the 
 Samaritans who would not receive their Master ; '^ or the 
 lesson taught, but so often overlooked, in the parable of the 
 Good Samaritan,^ where the alien and heretic is held up as a 
 model to be imitated, because of a kind action, rather than the 
 priest and Levite of orthodox Judaism ; or the passages in 
 which, in the spirit of the greatest of the old prophets, deeds of 
 justice and mercy done in the service of humanity are made 
 the passport to the kingdom of God, and not the profession of 
 sound belief;'^ or the parable of the tares and the wheat, 
 where the lesson of tolerance seems very explicitly taught.^ 
 Still more strongly might persecution seem to be excluded by 
 the precepts of non-resistance ^ (which most Christians have, 
 however, decided to be impracticable in their literal form), and 
 by the prayer of divine pity on the cross : " Father, forgive 
 them, for they know not what they do."'' The words " Com- 
 pel them to come in " ^ have, we know, been used to sanction 
 the attempt to save souls from everlasting fire by penalties of 
 terrestrial burning; but such a use of the words is just one of 
 the many mischievous absurdities which result when any book 
 whatever is taken as a series of " texts " to be quoted, without 
 reference to time and occasion, as absolute and final authorities 
 
 ' Mark ix. 39 ; Luke ix. 50. ^ Luke ix. 54, 55. 
 
 » Luke X. 25-37. * Matt. vii. 21-23 ; xxv. 31-46. 
 
 * Matt. xiii. 24-30. This parable is referred to by St. Thomas 
 Aquinas, 2a 2ae, qu. 11, art. 3, as an argument that might be used for the 
 toleration of heretics. On the same side he mentions also (1) 2 Timothy 
 ii. (24-26) : *'The Lord's servant must not strive, but be gentle towards 
 all, apt to teach, forbearing, in meekness correcting them that oppose 
 themselves, if peradventure God may give them repentance unto the 
 knowledge of the truth," etc. ; for, as Aquinas says, if heretics are not 
 tolerated, bvxt put to death, the power of repentance is taken away from 
 them. And (2) 1 Cor. xi. (19), " There must also be {oportet esse) heresies 
 among you, that they which are approved may be made manifest among 
 you.'' Against toleration he quotes only the passage from the Epistle to 
 Titus, iii. 10, 11. Yet he sums up, as we have seen, against toleration. 
 The " Conclusio " only is given in Father Rickaby's translation. 
 
 ^ Matt. V. 38-42. ' Luke xxiii. 34. ^ Luke xiv. 23.
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 171 
 
 on matters of belief or practice. " I cume not to send peace, 
 but a sword," ^ is a prophecy, a warning of sufferings to come, 
 and most certainly not a precept of persecution. We have 
 already seen how the words of the Epistle to Titus, which imply 
 a much more definite religious organisation than any of these 
 sayings of the Gospels, are used by St. Thomas Aquinas to 
 justify persecution. But in the Epistle to Titus not one word 
 is said of anything beyond spiritual excommunication : " A 
 man that is heretical (or factious) after a first and second 
 admonition refuse (or avoid), knowing that such a one is per- 
 verted, and sinneth, being self-condemned."^ It is very easy, 
 however, to see how, when Christianity had become the pre- 
 vailing religion in any district or community, the avoidance 
 of intercourse with a heretic might come to be as effectual a 
 measure for repressing the utterance of opinions disapproved 
 of by the majority, or by those who controlled their conduct, 
 as the " boycott " has proved to be in more recent times. The 
 maintenance of uniformity of belief and practice and the exer- 
 cise of a strict censorship over doctrine and morals within any 
 Christian community thus prepared the way for the use of the 
 secular arm in the repression of heresy, when the Roman Avorld 
 became converted to Christianity. 
 
 When we speak of " Christianity " in any comparison be- 
 tween it and other religions, we mean, of course, the Chris- 
 tianity which has actually manifested itself in history'', and not 
 what any one may conceive to be the ideal of the religion as 
 originally taught. It is manifestly unfair to compare an ideal 
 of one religion with the actually prevalent precepts and 
 practices of another. Now, in the sense in which we say that 
 Christianity became the religion of the Roman world, in the 
 sense in which we say that Christianity is now the religion of 
 the most progressive and civilised part of the world, in the 
 sense in which we compare the numbers of Christians with 
 the numbers of Buddhists and Mohammedans, in that sense 
 Christianity has been a persecuting religion, and persecution 
 has been of the essence of it in a sense in which that could 
 not be said of any of the older tribal or political religions 
 which it supplanted. This is the historical sense of Chris- 
 tianity — the only sense which the term can bear in any 
 scientific discussion ; in any other sense its meaning will vary 
 ' Matt. X. 34. '' Epistle to Titus iii. 10, 11. Cf. above p. 1(;2.
 
 172 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 according to those passages of the Gospels^ or of the FauUne 
 Epistles^ or of the whole of the New Testament^ or those inter- 
 pretations of them which approve themselves to this or that 
 person.^ Christianity in this historical sense is a religion 
 which to elements derived from Jewish prophets has added 
 elements derived from Greek metaphysics, and elements 
 derived from Roman political administration : it is a religion 
 with definite theological doctrines and a definite system of 
 government and discipline ; and it was only as such that 
 Christianity could possibly have been the vehicle through 
 which the northern barbarians, who destroyed the old civilisa- 
 tion, could have received, as they did, an inheritance — maimed, 
 indeed, and mutilated — of Greek intellectual culture, and of 
 Roman legal and political institutions. 
 
 The importance assigned to the possession of truth — of the 
 truth — is one of the most fruitful ideas which Christianity has 
 diffused in the modern world. From it has grown up that 
 scientific spirit which is proving fatal to some traditional be- 
 liefs — a devotion to truth as such, which in the ancient world 
 
 ' Thus, if some one quotes the dicta of St. Paul as expressing the 
 Christian theory of the status of women, it is replied that the true Chris- 
 tian theory is not to be found in the Pauline Epistles, but in the teaching 
 and life of Jesus (who, however, though he had women among his 
 followers, is not recorded to have chosen a single woman among his 
 Apostles). The relation of Christianity to the status of women is a sub- 
 ject capable of, and deserving, historical study ; but we must take the 
 whole range of Christian thought and practice on the subject, and not a 
 few arbitrarily selected '"texts" interpreted for the occasion. There is an 
 interesting article on the sub ject of " The Position of Women among the 
 Early Christians" in the Contemporary Jieview for September, 1889 
 (vol. 56, p. 433 seq.), by Principal Donaldson; and this is what so 
 scholarly and impartial a writer feels obliged to say : "It is a prevalent 
 opinion that woman owes her present high position to Christianity and 
 the influences of the Teutonic mind. I used to believe tliis opinion, but 
 in the first three centuries I have not been able to see that Christianity 
 had any favourable effect on the position of women, but, on the contrary, 
 that it tended to lower their character and contract the range of their 
 activity." Like other writers {e.c/. Mr. Galton), Dr. Donaldson calls at- 
 tention to the mischief done to the race by the exaltation of virginity 
 above marriage, and the consequent survival of the morally and intel- 
 lectually unlittest. Yet, even on this, one must not exaggerate. How 
 much more have the celibate Latin clergy done for civilisation than the 
 married Greek clergy ! Even if all the celibate Christians of the first 
 three centuries had married and left offspring, this, so far as one can see, 
 would not have hindered the barbarian invasions.
 
 CH. viri] TOLERATION 173 
 
 was known only to a few philosophers.' But this very exalta- 
 tion of the importance of knowing the truth was the source of 
 " the persecuting spirit " when the truth was preached and 
 thought of, not as something to be sought for by patient 
 inquir}^, as something towards which the " Spirit of truth " - 
 would gradually guide mankind, but as a precious treasure, or 
 " deposit of doctrine," already possessed and enjoyed by the duly 
 accredited teachers of the Church. Such a treasure might 
 well seem fit to be defended and protected from everything 
 that would diminish its size or impair its beauty. Among 
 the rude barbarians out of whom the Church has moulded the 
 nations of modern Europe, this was the only way in which 
 " the truth " was likely to be thought of. Add to this manner 
 of conceiving truth the necessity of enforcing a rigid discipline, 
 especially whilst the State was in so many ways a weaker 
 power than the Church, and the claim of the Church to be the 
 one universal religion of the whole world, and it is difficult to 
 see how an orthodox theologian of the thirteenth century, or 
 any of those who derive their ideas from him, can escape from 
 believing in the duty of repressing false doctrine where it is 
 possible to do so, and by such means as experience has shown 
 to be best for the purpose. The growth of large and powerful 
 communities of " heretics " has obviously made it inexpedient 
 or difficult to use the secular arm in direct defence of ortho- 
 doxy ; and certain forms of punishment have gone out of 
 fashion. 
 
 A large part of the arguments used by Locke in his Leiters 
 on Toleration are arguments which involve a complete ignoratio 
 elencM ; they are completely irrelevant, if supposed to be ad- 
 dressed to a Roman Catholic or to any one who holds, as the 
 early Puritans mostly did, that his religious body is in solo 
 possession of the one truth about the highest and most im- 
 portant of all subjects. Thus Locke assumes that ordinary 
 morality is more important than the unity of the Church in 
 faith and doctrine, an assumption which would not liave been 
 admitted by a great many Protestants of his own time. He 
 assumes that he can lay down precisely the functions of Church 
 and State respectively, and that " the care of souls cannot 
 
 ' This affiliation was suggested to me, I think, by a remark of 11. 
 Tarde's in one of his works, but I cannot at present Hud tlie passage. 
 ^ Cf. the words in John xvi. 13.
 
 174 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 belong to the civil magistrate," which he interprets to mean 
 " that the magistrate's power extends not to the establishing 
 of any articles of faith or forms of worship, by the force of his 
 laws " — a principle which Anglican High Churchmen of the 
 sevenfeenfh century type ^ would not have accepted, and which 
 Roman Catholics could hardly accept in its generality, because 
 the magistrate might be using his power under the guidance 
 of the Church. Locke defines the Church as " a voluntary 
 society of men, joining themselves together of their own accord 
 in order to the public worshipping of God in such manner as 
 they judge acceptable to Him and effectual to the salvation 
 of their souls " — a definition of the Church which Roman 
 Catholics, Anglicans, and Presbyterians (as they were in the 
 seventeenth century) would all have considered unsatisfactory. 
 He condemns persecution solely because he cannot find it in 
 the New Testament — an appeal to the sole authority of Scrip- 
 ture interpreted by mere private judgment, which a Catholic 
 theologian could not allow. ^ And we have already seen how 
 St. Thomas Aquinas deals with the argument from the New 
 Testament. When Locke says that '' every Church is orthodox 
 to itself; to others, erroneous or heretical," he makes what 
 many people would consider a very sensible remark, even if it 
 be somewhat of a truism ; but to an ardent theologian the 
 remark may seem " a blatant and atrocious error," or to savour 
 too much of flippancj^ to allow a belief in the writer's sincerity. 
 Locke draws the line between essentials and matters indifferent 
 in religion at a different point from that where Roman Catholic 
 or strict Anglican or Presbyterian would draw it. He lays 
 down that " there is absolutely no such thing under the gospel 
 as a Christian commonwealth," a proposition which very few 
 Protestants even would have accepted in the earlier part of the 
 
 1 Cf. Gardiner, Hist, of England, 1C03-1642, VII. p. 127. 
 
 ^ In lieligion^s Peace: or, A Plea for Liberty of Conscience (1614), hy 
 Leonard Busher — a work which is claimed by the Baptists as one of " the 
 first articulations of infant libert3' " — the plan of toleration proposed in- 
 cludes this provision : " that it be lawful for every person or persons, yea, 
 Jews and Papists, to write, dispute, confer and i-eason, print and publish 
 any matter touching religion, either for or against whomsoever, alirays 
 provided they allege no Fattiers for proof of any point of religion, but 
 only tlie Holy Scriptures^' {Tracts on Liberty of Conscience, 1614-1661, 
 published by the Hanserd Knollys Society, 1846, p. 51). Such limited 
 " liberty of conscience " would certainly have told hardly against many 
 of the more learned controversialists of the seventeenth century.
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 175 
 
 seventeenth century, and which many even of those opposed 
 to State churches would hesitate to accept now. He holds that 
 " the care of each man's salvation belongs only to himself" — a 
 doctrine of extreme individualism in religion which would be 
 rejected by the great majority even of Protestants. Locke, 
 that is to say, argues throughout from the point of view of a 
 " Liberal Christian " of very rationalistic tendencies, and his 
 arguments could only appeal to those who had gone a very 
 long way in his direction, and could not be accepted even by 
 the most liberal of Catholics without very important qualifica- 
 tions. 
 
 A change in the notion of what constitutes a Church, and 
 a change in opinion as to what is essential in religious be- 
 lief and what is not, and furthermore, a diminished sense of 
 the importance of correct intellectual conceptions about the 
 nature of God and the Divine plan of the universe, with, per- 
 haps, some scepticism as to the possibility of attaining com- 
 plete certainty in such deep matters — these are the necessary 
 preliminaries to an acceptance of Locke's views on toleration. 
 Contrast Locke's position with that of St. Thomas Aquinas or 
 Father Rickaby, and we have a very excellent measure of the 
 gap between the premises from which persecution (where 
 convenient) is a necessary deduction, and the premises which 
 exclude persecution, with some exceptions. For Locke's 
 limitations are worth taking note of. Milton, in his Areo]^a- 
 gitica^ excludes from the toleration he advocates " Popery and 
 open superstition." Locke has no objection to tolerate what 
 he would consider " superstition." " It may be said, what if a 
 Church be idolatrous " — what most Protestants said of Roman 
 Catholicism, what most Puritans said of the Church of Eng- 
 land — "is that also to be tolerated by the magistrate? I 
 answer, what power can be given to the magistrate for the 
 suppression of an idolatrous Church which may not in time 
 and place be made use of to the ruin of an orthodox one ? " — 
 a good diplomatic argument. But Locko holds (1) that those 
 ought not to be tolerated " who will not own and teach the 
 duty of tolerating all men in matters of mere religion," and 
 (2) that " that Church can have no right to be tolerated by 
 the magistrate which is constituted upon such a bottom that 
 all those who enter into it do thereby ipso facto deliver them- 
 selves up to the protection and service of another prince."
 
 176 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 Under either of these heads it would be easy to refuse tolera- 
 tion to Roman Catholics. The important thing to note is, that 
 in both cases Locke's reasons for excluding these two classes 
 from toleration are not theological or religious, but purely 
 political^ and the same remark applies to his reasons for exclud- 
 ing Atheists. "Promises, covenants, and oaths, which are the 
 bond of human society, can have no hold upon an Atheist." A 
 Roman magistrate in the same way might have argued that a 
 person who would not burn incense to the emperor's statue 
 could not possibly be a safe subject. 
 
 Locke's minimum of belief requisite in those who are to 
 be tolerated comes to very much the same as Rousseau's 
 " dogmas of the religion of the citizen as such " (if so we 
 may paraphrase " la religion civile "), which are as follows : " the 
 existence of a God whose attributes are power, intelligence, 
 beneficence, foreknowledge, and providential care ; a future life 
 with rewards and punishments, the sanctity of the social con- 
 tract and the laws — these are positive dogmas. As to negative 
 dogmas, I limit them to one only — intolerance. . . . One 
 should tolerate all those who tolerate others, so far as their 
 dogmas contain nothing contrary to the duties of the citizen. 
 But whosoever dares to say. Out of the Church no salvation, 
 should be driven from the State." " It is impossible," Rous- 
 seau says, " to live in peace with those whom one believes 
 damned," so that theological intolerance by itself excludes 
 from citizenship on political grounds.^ Rousseau's dogmas 
 seem, indeed, rather more numerous than those of Locke ; and 
 the citizen of Calvin's Geneva anathematises in a sterner tone 
 than the countryman and admirer of the mild and judicious 
 Hooker. But Locke and Rousseau alike base the " persecu- 
 tion " they justify on purely political grounds. 
 
 Very many persecutions, which have been regarded by those 
 who suffered from them, and even by critical historians, as 
 " religious persecutions," i.e. forcible interferences on the part 
 of the State with liberty of expressing opinion on theological 
 matters and with liberty of worship, are much more properly 
 classed as " persecutions" in the interests of political security- 
 and social peace and order. The persecutions of the Christians 
 under the Roman Empire, certainly those under the early 
 Empire, were acts of repression in the interests of political 
 1 Contrat Social, IV. cli. viii., "De la religion civile."
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 177 
 
 stability. Tlie Roman magistrate, as I have already pointed 
 out, did not punish the Christians for preaching the theological 
 doctrines distinctive of their faith, as magistrates in Catholic 
 countries afterwards punished Protestants, or as magistrates in 
 Catholic and Protestant countries have often punished Socin- 
 ians and Atheists ; to the Roman magistrate it was a matter 
 of comparative indifference whether the Christians worshipped 
 as a God one whom the Jews declared to be a man guilty 
 of blasphemy, and whom a Roman magistrate had, foolishly 
 perhaps, put to death as a rebel against Caesar; but to the 
 Roman magistrate and to the Roman Emperor it did seem 
 important to discourage secret assemblies and movements 
 likely to cause a breach of the peace, and to ensure the poli- 
 tical loyalty of the subjects and citizens of Rome. Now the 
 persecution of Roman Catholics, and specially of the Jesuits in 
 England in the days of Queen Elizabeth, was a persecution, 
 in the main, for political reasons, — certainly after the Pope, 
 Pius v., had issued a bull of excommunication against the 
 queen. After that, how could any one believe that a conscien- 
 tious Roman Catholic could be a loyal subject ? ^ The writ- 
 ings of some Jesuits — whether disapproved or not at Rome 
 — had, moreover, undoubtedly justified the assassination of 
 heretical princes who persecuted the true religion ; and every 
 Jesuit was therefore — presumptively — an instigator of treason. 
 The methods of enforcing uniformity of religious worship 
 adopted in Elizabeth's reign are, indeed, uncongenial to the 
 modern mind ; and it may very well be argued that the perse- 
 cution of the Puritans was the beginning of a fatal policy which 
 led to the civil dissensions of the following century, and was 
 thus a most mistaken piece of statecraft. But with regard to 
 the repression of Roman Catholicism, the case is somewhat 
 different ; and it is quite possible for the historian, who regrets 
 
 ' The Earl of Southampton asked Mary's (the Queen of Scots) ambassa- 
 dor, Bishop Lesley, whether, after the Bull, he could in conscience obey 
 Elizabeth. Lesley answered that, as long as she was the stronger, he 
 ought to obey her. (The story is referred to by Hallam, Const. Hint, ch. 
 iii. [" World Library " edit., p. 115 note].) If that was a widespread sen- 
 timent, Elizabeth's supporters had strong motives for keeping her the 
 stronger : the rest was a question of means. And it may be very well 
 argued that a toleration such as commends itself to us might have been 
 fatal to the maintenance of Protestantism in England in the time of 
 Elizabeth. 
 
 N. K. N
 
 1 78 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 that Catholic emancipation was so long delayed in this century, 
 to recognise that to statesmen of Elizabeth's day stringent 
 measures may have seemed necessary purely on political 
 grounds. "Was her government sufficiently stable to afford to 
 tolerate those whose interest it undoubtedly was to upset her 
 government if possible ? The rigid uniformity of belief en- 
 forced in Geneva or in Massachusetts was enforced, partly at 
 least, on political grounds — to ensure a sufficient amount of 
 cohesion in small communities struggling for their liberty. 
 Such communities cannot afford to tolerate those who only ask 
 for toleration, till they are strong enough to seize the govern- 
 ment and refuse toleration to others.^ 
 
 The Federal Constitution of Switzerland may be regarded 
 as very fairly representing the attitude of a democratic but 
 prudent people, experienced in the working of institutions, 
 towards the alleged right of religious liberty. The Swiss Con- 
 stitution embodies elements derived from the experience (under 
 which I include the mistakes) of French and American Con- 
 stitutions ; and the Swiss Federal Constitution guarantees 
 religious liberty in a fuller sense than is done by the Constitu- 
 tion of the United States of America. The American Federal 
 Congress is forbidden (by the first Amendment to the Constitu- 
 tion) "to make any law respecting an establishment of religion, 
 or to prohibit the free exercise thereof, or to abridge the free- 
 dom of speech, or of the press " ; but the several States are left 
 " free " to restrict the freedom of individuals on these matters. 
 As a matter of fact, all the State Constitutions do now provide 
 for religious freedom, and for the equality before the law of 
 all religious denominations and their members ; but several 
 States, especially in the South, make any one who denies the 
 existence of God ineligible for office (Arkansas, Maryland, Mis- 
 sissippi, North Carolina, South Carolina, Texas) ; in two States, 
 Pennsylvania and Tennessee, another dogma of the " civil re- 
 ligion " is required — the belief in future rewards and punish- 
 ments. In Arkansas and Maryland a person who does not 
 accept this belief is incompetent as a witness or juror,- "Ne- 
 vada," we are told, " has recently disfranchised all Mormons 
 resident within her bounds."^ Many of the States, especially 
 
 > See Note A at the end of this chapter. 
 
 ^ Bryce, American Commonwealth, II. pp. 36, 37. 
 
 3 Ihid., III. p. 467 note. If it be said that the Mormons are not dis-
 
 CH. VI 1 1] TOLERATION 179 
 
 in the North, had what were virtually State Churches till some 
 time after the beginning of this century.^ But " religious 
 equality," as it is called, which simply means the absence of an 
 Established Church, has nothing directly to do with the ques- 
 tion I am at present considering, viz., the amount of liberty 
 of expressing opinions on matters of religion, and the amount 
 of liberty in following the precepts of this or that religion 
 guaranteed to the individual. Although in Switzerland every 
 canton has an Established Church or several Established 
 Churches (the Swiss mode of recognising the equality of re- 
 ligious bodies), the Federal Constitution of 1874 lays down 
 (Art. 49) that " freedom of conscience and belief is inviolable," 
 that "no person can be constrained to take part in a religious 
 society, to attend religious instruction, to perform a religious 
 rite, or to incur penalties of any kind whatever on account of 
 religious opinion." Furthermore, " the exercise of civil or 
 political rights shall not be abridged by any provisions or con- 
 ditions whatever of an ecclesiastical or religious kind." These 
 are provisions which restrict the power of the several cantons 
 as well as of the Federal Government to limit individual 
 liberty, and not, like the provision I have quoted from the 
 American Constitution, restrictions on the action of the Federal 
 Legislature only. But the Swiss Constitution, though thus 
 more favourable than the American to the liberty of the indi- 
 vidual in matters of religion,^ sets very distinct limits to that 
 
 franchisee! on religious grounds, this onlj^ furnishes another illustration 
 of what I am urging about a great deal of what is called " religious 
 persecution " — that it is professedly political or social. 
 
 1 Article 3 of the " Declaration of Rights " of Massachusetts, 1780, ex- 
 pressly asserts the right of the people to invest their legislature with 
 the power to require the several towns and parishes " to make suitable 
 provision, at their own expense, for the public worship of God, and for 
 the support and maintenance of public Protestant teachers of pietj^, re- 
 ligion and morality in all cases where such provision shall not be made 
 voluntarily." This article remained unaltered till 1833. 
 
 2 Professor Vincent, in his admirable w^ork on 8tat(t and Federal 
 Government in Switzerland, thinks that "so long as the cantons main- 
 tain established religions, or even attempt to support the ministry of all 
 the chief sects alike, there will bo limitations to religious liberty not 
 known in the United States. ... So far as private belief is con- 
 cerned, no limitations are set ; but as to taxation for religious purposes, 
 complete freedom is yet to be obtained " (p. 98). This passage seems to 
 me to show some confusion between the " liberty " of {i.e. the absence of
 
 I So TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 liberty. In the same Article, 49, it is provided that " No person 
 shall, on account of a religious belief, release himself from the 
 accomplishment of a civil duty," which means among other 
 things that a Quaker's conscientious objection to bear arms 
 would not be respected by the law. The 5()th Article provides 
 that "the free exercise of religious worship is guaranteed within 
 the limits compatible with public order and good morals " ; and 
 on grounds of public order noisy processions have been pro- 
 hibited, although they constituted the mode of worship of a 
 religious body. Article 51 prohibits the reception of the order 
 of the Jesuits, and of societies affiliated with them, in any part 
 of Switzerland. Now the Quaker, the member of the Salvation 
 Army, and the Jesuit may all declare that they have undergone 
 " religious persecution " in Switzerland ; but in all cases the 
 ground of action on the part of the Swiss authorities is 
 political and social, not theological. 
 
 In this country, so far as the law of the land is concerned, 
 freedom of discussion on religious matters is not recognised. 
 It is still possible to prosecute any one who has been educated 
 in Christianity for denying the authority of the Scriptures. 
 Practically we know that an anti-orthodox lecturer or writer 
 is not Hkely (that is all. we can say) to be found guilty by a 
 jury, if he does not grossly offend the average sentiment of 
 the community by coarse and offensive attacks on prevalent 
 beliefs. The punishment, when nowadays inflicted, is a 
 punishment for a breach of good manners and decency in 
 
 State control over) religious hodies, and the liberty of the individual in 
 matters of religious belief {i.e. absence of civil or political disabilities 
 arising from the opinions of the individual). Even on the matter of 
 " taxation for religious purposes," the Swiss Federal Constitution lays 
 down that "No person is bound to pay taxes of which the proceeds are 
 specifically appropriated to the actual expenses of the worship of a re- 
 ligious body to which he does not belong. The details of the carrying 
 out of this principle ai-e reserved for federal legislation " (Art. 49). But 
 let us grant that, through imperfection in such legislation, a small fraction 
 of the taxes paid by a conscientious " free thinker," who doubts a future 
 life, is divided among the four established churches of Neuchatel (where 
 " the liberty of the conscience of the ecclesiastic " in the Protestant 
 Church is declared inviolable — no test being permissible), has he less 
 " religious liberty " than he would have in the State of Arkansas, where 
 his evidence would not be received in a law-court maintained out of 
 taxes that he cannot escape pajdng ? To the probable pressure of public 
 opinion in the way of restricting liberty of thought under the latter 
 condition. 1 am not here referring.
 
 CH. VI 1 1] TOLERATION iSi 
 
 controvers}'' rather than a punishment for heresy. And it 
 would be more in accordance with national honesty, as well as 
 a necessary security against the possibility of purely " theo- 
 logical " persecution in some time of panic, if legislation 
 expressly determined the limits of free discussion by consider- 
 ations of decency alone, and not by any considerations of 
 doctrine.^ In all countries, indeed, even in those which guar- 
 antee a natural right of liberty to their citizens, the liberty 
 practically conceded depends on the prevailing sentiment of 
 the community more than on anything else. The standard of 
 what is permissible in controversy is in the last resort deter- 
 mined by the prevailing sentiment of the community, and at 
 the present moment there is probably in this country, at least 
 in large towns, a greater practical liberty, or license, in the 
 matter of religious or irreligious eccentricity than is enjoyed, 
 or dreaded, by the citizens of most of the American States. 
 
 At the same time it must be allowed that the existence of 
 an express declaration in favour of liberty of any kind — how- 
 ever little it is actually guaranteed by the existing laws — has 
 a certain moral effect in influencing the sentiment of the com- 
 munity, and it may at least supply any one who is struggling 
 for greater liberty than exists with. a convenient rhetorical 
 premise. On these grounds, as already suggested,^ Declarations 
 of Rights have their practical advantages. 
 
 I have not attempted to distinguish (4) " social " ^ from 
 " political " reasons for limiting libertj'- of expressing opinions, 
 or of performing what may be considered religious acts. As 
 
 * The Anglo-Indian Penal Code may be taken as representing admirably 
 the principle on which alone most thoughtful persons in this country 
 would nowadays think it right to limit "liberty " in matters of religion. 
 Thus chapter xv. sec. 298 makes insult^ with deliberate intention, to any 
 religion, penal. The preceding sections forbid injuring or defiling places 
 of worship with intent, disturbing religious assemblies, trespassing on 
 burial places, etc. In chapter xiv. sec. 292, under the clause making penal 
 the printing or exhibiting, etc., of obscene books, paintings, etc., an excep- 
 tion is made in favour of " representations, sculptured, engraved, painted, 
 or otherwise represented, on or in any temple or on any car used for the 
 conveyance of idols, or kept or used for any I'eligious purpose." Aristotle 
 even in his ideal state is similarly complaisant to existing religious pre- 
 judices. " Let the rulers take care that there be no image or picture 
 representing unseemly actions, except in the temples of those gods at 
 whose festivals the law [i.e. custom] permits even ribaldry." — Pol., VII. 
 17, § 10. 
 
 * Cf. above, p. 156. ' Cf. above, p. 168.
 
 iS2 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 already suggested, I do not think the Tribal, Political and 
 Social Reasons can be clearly distinguished from one another. 
 All are different stages of the same principle, and all together 
 can be distinguished from the " theological " reasons. It might 
 indeed be said that in the tribal stage of society the political 
 and theological reasons were simply not yet differentiated. 
 The cohesion of the tribe and the worship of the tribal god 
 fwho is perhaps thought of as the ancestor of the tribe) were 
 bound up together. An insult to the god was an insult to the 
 tribe. In the clearly political stage of thought on the subject, 
 it is possible to recognise the principle Deorum injurice dis curce, 
 interfering with religion only for reasons of State, for the re- 
 pression of treason or the maintenance of peace and order. 
 In the distinctly theological stage, on the other hand, the 
 purity of doctrine is something to be maintained, even at the 
 risk of temporal loss and injury to the nation ; purely theo- 
 logical persecution has therefore usually been more an eccle- 
 siastical ideal than a historical fact. In practice, elements of 
 tribal sentiment or supposed political and social expediency 
 have generally been among the motives which have induced 
 the secular magistrate to put his sword at the disposal of the 
 spiritual power. 
 
 We judge past ages very unfairly if we suppose that people 
 could have been actuated by the same motives which are 
 predominant now, still more if we suppose that the circum- 
 stances in which they had to decide on a course of action pre- 
 sented themselves to their minds as they do to ours now in the 
 light of subsequent events ; and most of all do we judge un- 
 fairly, if we neglect the difference between their circumstances 
 (as they saw them) and the circumstances with which we are 
 familiar. In primitive conditions of society — I am using the 
 term " primitive " in a very wide sense — in a tribal society or 
 a small Greek city-state living in perpetual fear of attack from 
 without, a very rigid cohesion is the primary essential of ex- 
 istence, and therefore the most important factor in all moral 
 judgments. A society of this sort which did not repress dis- 
 senters from the worship that held the community together 
 would have little chance of holding its own in the struggle 
 for existence. Even the powerful and intelligent city of 
 Athens suffered, not perhaps from the corruption introduced 
 by the Sophists, but from the decay of social cohesion and the
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 183 
 
 growth of individualism, of which the appearance and popu- 
 larity of the Sophists was only one symptom. We should not 
 blame the average Athenian too severely if he thought the 
 teachings of Socrates socially and politically dangerous ; we 
 may be grateful to Athens that the degree of toleration she did 
 allow made the teaching of Socrates possible through so many 
 years. The great empires like the Persian, the Macedonian, 
 the Roman, contained within their limits many tribal religions 
 and many city-state religions, and it is in the co-existence of 
 these differences under the shadow of one ruling power that 
 we get the first form of toleration as a recognised principle. 
 
 In the Middle Ages it must be remembered that it was the 
 Church rather than the Holy Roman Empire which really in- 
 herited the sovereignty of Rome ; and the persecutions of 
 heretics at the suggestion of the Church may be regarded as 
 the endeavour of the Church to maintain its own cohesion — an 
 endeavour greatly checked by the mutual jealousy of the differ- 
 ent parts of Christendom. The Reformers certainly did not 
 think of themselves as setting up new Churches alongside of 
 the existing Church. For them also there was only one Uni- 
 versal Church, though there might be considerable permissible 
 differences between its forms in one nation and in another. 
 But the growing varieties of Protestantism and the success of 
 the Catholic reaction made the theory, and even the ideal, of 
 one Universal Church seem, to statesmen at least, more and 
 more impossible ; and people became accustomed to the idea 
 of different political societies living alongside of one another, 
 and yet adhering to different religions. Cujus reglo^ ejus religio 
 — that the religion of the people must follow the religion of the 
 prince — seems to us the very reverse of a principle of religious 
 liberty ; but there is no doubt that its acceptance as a political 
 necessity marked an important advance in the direction of 
 toleration. It put aside the idea of a crusade for the universal 
 destruction of heresy. That different religious communities 
 might safely be permitted to co-exist within the same political 
 community was an idea that took a much longer time to pre- 
 vail. In Switzerland, as a whole, it was not recognised till 1848. 
 The efforts of minorities to gain toleration for themselves in the 
 hope of finally prevailing prepared the way for acquiescence in 
 mutual toleration without the hope of uniformity. No re- 
 ligious body as such can claim the merit of having adopted
 
 1 84 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 toleration as its principle, till a certain amount of toleration 
 had already been forced on them by the practical necessities of 
 the statesman. Roman Catholic, Anglican, Presbyterian, In- 
 dependent have all been persecuted, and have all persecuted 
 when they had the opportunity. If the Baptists have never 
 persecuted, it must be borne in mind that they never had the 
 opportunity. The Quakers indeed may claim the honourable 
 distinction of having been often the victims but never the 
 agents of religious persecution ; but a nation of Quakers could 
 never have existed without deserting the principle of non-resist- 
 ance. They would have been the easy prey of any enterprising 
 neighbour.^ They could only become a nation by converting 
 the whole world, and if they did so they would probably 
 undergo a change like that which makes the difference between 
 the Christians of the first and those of the fourth century — 
 between the apostles and the Emperor Constantine. 
 
 Apart from a strict application of the principle of non- 
 resistance, the adoption of toleration as a principle implies 
 either a statesman's view of religious differences as compatible 
 with political cohesion — a view only possible when a consider- 
 able degree of political and social stability has been attained ; 
 or it implies the adoption of an attenuated religious creed, so 
 that the number of non-essential articles increases, while that 
 of essentials diminishes. Locke could tolerate diversity of 
 opinion about the sacraments or about the Trinity : these 
 seemed non-essential to him. But, as I have shown, his argu- 
 ments have no force against those who really think a right 
 belief about the Trinity, or a due observance of the sacra- 
 ments, essential to salvation, as Locke thought the belief in a 
 God essential to social and political stability. The growth 
 of charity is greatly due to the decay of faith, if " faith" is to 
 be measured by the number of doctrines in which people 
 
 ' Pennsylvania may seem to be a refutation of this statement; but the 
 Indians with whom the Quaker settlers in Pennsylvania had to do were 
 only the Delaware?, who were in subjection to the powerful Iroquois, who 
 were the firm allies of the English against the French (see Fiske, The 
 Beginnings of Netv England, p. 206). The Quakers profited here, as else- 
 where, by the fighting habits of other people. In the earlier half of the 
 eighteenth century, during the struggles between the English and the 
 French in America, Pennsylvania suffered much from Indian raids, her 
 Quaker inhabitants not defending the frontiers (Thwaites, The Colonies 
 [in " Epochs of American History "], p. 277).
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 185 
 
 profess to believe. On the other hand, if faith be taken to 
 mean faith in human nature and in the rationality of the pro- 
 cess of evolution, it is only such faith that makes toleration 
 possible ; for to such faith the various beliefs about which 
 men have fought so fiercely are " but broken lights," or par- 
 tial truths, which are false if taken to be the whole truth. 
 That there should be diversity of belief may even be thought 
 of as an advantage : there is more variety for natural selection 
 to work upon. There is a security against stagnation. There 
 is an educative influence in the substitution of peaceable dis- 
 cussion for forcible repression. 
 
 To many, such an attitude towards religious questions may 
 seem incompatible with what they regard as the necessarily 
 dogmatic character of religion. Believing that they possess 
 absolute certainty on some matters at least, they may yet 
 allege that they do not wish to persecute, but only to persuade. 
 Probably nowadays the most bigoted religionist does not 
 really wish to hum the worst of heretics, even if he had the 
 power, and was not in fear of reprisals. But suppose him to 
 have the power to control the educational system in a country, 
 and to check the diffusion of what he considers blasphemous 
 and immoral literature ; if a scholar or a scientific man in such 
 a country is prohibited from teaching, and finds that the works 
 of Renan and Strauss, of Darwin and Spencer, which he has 
 ordered from abroad, are seized and destroyed on the frontier, 
 is it wrong to say that he is " persecuted," merely because he 
 is not burned along with the heretical volumes ? Undoubtedly 
 a milder tone has spread into the words even of those whose 
 principles lead logically to intolerance. Just as Protestantism 
 has influenced the Catholicism which rejected it, so that toler- 
 ant and reverent Rationalism, of which Locke was one of the 
 great initiators, has influenced Protestant and Catholic alike : 
 and the duty of repressing heretics by the secular arm, where 
 it is possible and expedient, is a principle that is kept in the 
 background, from a sort of politeness, or is only treated as an 
 ancient weapon, to be laid up in the museum rather than in 
 the armoury, and to be referred to with a sort of pious regret, 
 like the sigh for the godly discipline of old days at the be- 
 ginning of the Anglican Commination Service. 
 
 Ought we to tolerate those who are bound by their professed
 
 i86 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 principles not to tolerate us ? On this question of casuistry, the 
 doctors of "Liberalism" have answered differently ; " No " (as 
 we have seen) is the answer of Locke and E-ousseau ; " Yes " 
 is the answer of Renau, in a passage in his Lectures on Rome 
 and Christianity. " I have no right to prevent any one from 
 expressing his opinion, but no one has the right to prevent 
 me from expressing mine. That is a theory which will 
 appear very humble to the transcendental doctors who believe 
 themselves in possession of absolute truth. We have a great 
 advantage over them. They are obliged in consistency to be 
 persecutors ; as for us, we can be tolerant, tolerant even 
 towards those who, if they had the powxr, would not be 
 tolerant towards us. Yes, let us go as far as this paradox : — 
 Liberty is the best weapon against the enemies of liberty. 
 Certain fanatics say to us with sincerity, ' AVe take the liberty 
 3'ou give us, because you owe it to us on your principles ; but 
 you should not receive it from us, because we do not owe it to 
 you.' Very w^ell, let us give them liberty all the same, and 
 do not let us imagine we shall be cheated in the bargain. No ; 
 liberty is the great solvent of all fanaticisms. In demanding 
 liberty for my enemy, for him who would suppress me if he 
 had the power to do so, I give him in reality the worst gift 
 he could receive. I compel him to drink a strong beverage, 
 which will turn his head, whilst I shall keep mine steady. 
 Science can endure the virile rule of liberty : fanaticism and 
 superstition cannot endure it. . . . The essential thing 
 is not to silence a dangerous doctrine, to quench a discordant 
 voice ; the essential thing is to put the human intellect in a 
 condition in which the mass may see the uselessness of these 
 outbursts of anger. AVhen such a spirit becomes the atmo- 
 sphere of society, the fanatic cannot find anything more to live 
 on. He is himself vanquished by the prevailing gentleness." ^ 
 Now, this characteristic passage of the great French writer 
 contains a profound truth, which rests on facts of ordinary 
 human nature, and on a large experience of history. But the 
 principle of tolerating even the intolerant is asserted in too 
 general terms. When we believe that the principle of intoler- 
 ance has become a mere pious opinion, a mere " counsel of per- 
 fection " for a commonwealth that is not likely to be realised, 
 it is easy enough to give to those who hold the principle and 
 ^ Conferences cFAiigleterre, pp. 205-207 (Hibbert Lectures, 1880).
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 1S7 
 
 proclaim it the toleration of an easy-going contempt. But when 
 some new belief is still struggling for existence amid hostile 
 surroundings, as was the case with Pi-otestantism in the six- 
 teenth century, a general toleration on the part of those hold- 
 ing the new belief is more doubtful policy, and is certainly less 
 likely to be thought of. Direct persecution has indeed almost 
 always proved a clumsy and inefficient measure of securing 
 uniformity, unless, as was the case in Spain, it is made so 
 thoroughgoing as to sap the whole intellectual vigour of a 
 people. But few persons have the opportunities or the special 
 gifts required to make the perfectly unflinching persecutor; 
 and any inconsistent clemency allows some seeds to survive 
 that will spring up again, watered by the tears, if not b}' the 
 blood, of martyrs. On the other hand, an absolutely universal 
 toleration is inconsistent with any social cohesion whatever. It 
 is only on the basis of a firmly established foundation of political 
 and social stability that what are generally understood by 
 liberty of religion, liberty of the press — liberty in the propa- 
 gation of opinions generally — can be granted or are likely to 
 be granted. Only those who feel themselves secure can aftbrd 
 to tolerate attacks upon themselves ; and toleration is then their 
 wisest policy. 
 
 The last sentences in the passage I have quoted from Renan 
 suggest that he is assuming what in the eyes of some of the 
 " enemies " he tolerates would seem a very important restric- 
 tion on liberty. Who is to control education? Even Lord 
 Burleigh was prepared to tolerate Papists, provided that he 
 might bring up their children as Protestants.^ Suppose a 
 country in which complete liberty of the press, complete 
 liberty of religion (and of irreligion), complete liberty of 
 association were all guaranteed by the law, or, if you like, by 
 the absence of all laws on the subject ; suppose, moreover, 
 that in such a country the Government rigidly abstained, in the 
 interests of complete liberty of thought, from instituting any 
 system of public education whatever. Suppose, in fact, that 
 we had the ideal state of Mr. Auberon Herbert, or at least that 
 of Mr. Herbert Spencer. But suppose, further, that the best 
 schools in the country were those managed by the Society of 
 Jesus, and that the members of this Society, constantly re- 
 cruited by picked men from other countries as well as from 
 ' See note A at the end of this clicapter.
 
 i88 TOLERATIOy [ch. viii 
 
 that "we are considering, gradually obtained, througli their 
 influence as educators, a complete ascendancy over the majo- 
 rity of the population ; is it difficult to foresee that ecclesi- 
 astical denunciations and excommunications would come to be 
 more deterrent than any laws in checking the growth of 
 heresy or free-thought ? And it would be only a step farther 
 to suppose the whole population, with hardly a protest, abolish- 
 ing the unchristian '' Liberalism "' of the old constitution (or 
 we should rather say, of the old Anarchy), and agreeing to 
 the establishment of a " Christian Commonwealth," which 
 would bum every copy of Eenan"s works on the frontier. 
 With a general system of education in the hands of the 
 Government, with Universities free from clerical control, or 
 affected by very diverse theological influences, and with cleri- 
 cal influence largely neutralised by ecclesiastical dissensions, 
 with the consequent intermingling and intercourse of those 
 brought up in different religious beliefs : it is possible to toler- 
 ate the advocates of a hypothetical intolerance — possible even 
 to tolerate the Jesuits, when they are not too numerous, and 
 when there is a traditional hostility to them well diffused 
 throughout the community. But it is all a question of time 
 and place ; and, in the interests of toleration, it would be un- 
 wise to adopt any such extreme principles as would be likely 
 to endanger toleration itself. As to education, that cannot 
 safely be left alone by the State ; for education left alone 
 by the State means either a very illiterate and ignorant popu- 
 lation, or a population educated by voluntary associations — 
 that is, mainly, by religious sects. In neither case is there 
 much likelihood of any considerable amount of freedom of 
 thought being practically granted. 
 
 Many persons sincerely hold that a purely " secular " edu- 
 cation, such as the State can ensure, contains grave moral 
 dangers : and that some amount of religious teaching must be 
 given — perhaps some minimum, stich as "the Bible." The 
 policy may be a wise one, but those who advocate it have no 
 right to allege that they are supporters of complete religious 
 liberty. If we use language carefully, no one (except Anar- 
 chists) does beheve in unlimited liberty of thought ; and, on 
 the other hand, no one allows no liberty of thought whatever. 
 Even the strictest of sects have drawn their own distinctions 
 between things essential and things indifferent. Even the
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 189 
 
 most tolerant of persons would impose some check on tlie in- 
 dulgence in personal abuse under the guise of freedom of 
 opinion. It is easy to tolerate differences of opinion and of 
 practice in matters which we regard as more or less " indif- 
 ferent " ; it is very difficult to tolerate differences in what we 
 regard as essentials, and, to some, it may seem questionable 
 how far it is morally right to do so. 
 
 People tolerate differences in matters of religion, but they 
 are not so willing to tolerate differences of opinion in matters 
 of moralit}^, except within somewhat narrow limits. A strong 
 point with the advocates of very strict limits to toleration in 
 matters of religion has always been that freedom of thought 
 and expression in religious matters is certain to lead to free- 
 dom of thought, and ultimately to license of conduct, in mat- 
 ters of morality. To the average educated person in most 
 civilised countries, it seems easy enough to differentiate re- 
 ligious from moral questions, and especially easy to differenti- 
 ate theological from moral questions, and consequently to 
 allow a very wide liberty with regard to the former; while re- 
 stricting by the pressure of public opinion, and sometimes by 
 the agency of law, any similar Hberty with regard to the 
 latter. There is indeed one obvious and important difference 
 between religious and moral tenets : that the truth or falsehood 
 of religious beliefs cannot be verified by reference to experi- 
 ence ; whereas the effect of moral principles on conduct and 
 the effect of conduct on social well-being seem to admit of such 
 verification in experience. The effect of religious beliefs or dis- 
 beliefs on the destiny of individuals in a future Hfe admits of 
 no test which the ordinary understanding can be expected to 
 apply ; their effect on the well-being of a society in the pre- 
 sent world does admit of such a test, though it is a test which 
 many ecclesiastics would not regard as satisfactory — they would 
 refuse to consider material well-being, or even intellectual pro- 
 gress, a proper measure of the value of religion. While willing 
 to put down to the credit of Christianity the higher civili- 
 sation and worldly success of the Christian nations, and while 
 ready to put down " the horrors of the French Revolution " to 
 the discredit of eighteenth century Rationalism, Catholic 
 controversialists would not allow the greater material pros- 
 perity and intellectual progress of Protestant countries to be 
 considered an argument in favour of Protestantism.^ 
 
 ^ '• The Church," according to Cardiual Newman, " pronounces the
 
 I90 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 When appeal is made, however, to moral superiority or 
 moral progress, it is supposed that the appeal is made to 
 something on which we are all agreed. Yet is the appeal as 
 decisive as it might seem at first ? There are people who 
 would measure the morality of a country solely by the paucity 
 of illegitimate births ; yet a neighbouring people, with a less 
 complete recognition of the virtues that keep the family 
 together, may be superior in industry and in honesty. Take 
 the number of suicides, the number of divorces, the number of 
 convictions for murder, for assaults, for attacks on property'', 
 the prevalence of drunkenness — any of the departments of 
 conduct that admit of statistical enumeration — and we should 
 find very conflicting results as to the moral condition of differ- 
 ent countries. Moreover, it is useless to take any of these 
 numbers and consider merely the percentage to population, 
 without taking account of race, climate, industrial conditions, 
 the laws of the country at the time, and the success with 
 which they are enforced. Thus, e.//., in a country where divorce 
 
 momentary wish, if conscious and deliberate, that another should be 
 sti-uck down dead, or suffer any other grievous misfortune, as a blacker 
 sin than a passionate, unpremeditated attempt on the life of the 
 Sovereign. She considei's direct unequivocal consent, though as quick as 
 thought, to a single unchaste desii-e, as indefinitely more heinous than 
 any lie which can possiblj- be fancied; that is, when that lie is viewed, of 
 course, in itself, and apart from its causes, motives, and consequences. 
 [How a lie can be viewed " in itself," and yet ethically, is not explained.] 
 Take a mere beggar-woman, lazj^ ragged, and filthj', and not over-scrupu- 
 lous of truth— (I do not say she had arrived at perfection)— but if she is 
 chaste and sober and cheerful, and goes to her religious duties (and I am 
 supposing not at all an impossible case), she will, in the eyes of the 
 Church, have a prospect of heaven which is quite closed and refused to 
 the State's pattern man, the just, the upright, the generous, the honour- 
 able, the conscientious, if he be all this, not from a supernatural power 
 (I do not determine whether this is likely to be the fact, but I am con- 
 trasting views and principles), — not from a supernatural power, but from 
 mere natural virtue " {Anglican Difficulties, p. 206 seq., quoted by 
 Mr. W. S.Lilly, in his Characteristics from the Writings of J.H.N.) . 
 From the point of view of "the Church," as here explained, social pro- 
 gress would be estimated by a standard incommensurable with that which 
 the statesman is bound to applj-. The forms of Protestantism which 
 incline to Antinomian views of pietj- would supply still more startling 
 differences from the statesman's standard. A Highlander, who con- 
 sidered himself a devout Christian, is reported to have said of an ac- 
 quaintance: "Donald's a rogue, and a cheat, and a villain, and a liar; 
 but he's a good, pious man." Probably Donald " kept the Sabbath — and 
 everything else he could laj- his hands on."
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 
 
 191 
 
 is permitted on many grounds, there will be more divorces, but 
 not necessarily more frequent violations of the duties of the 
 family, than in countries where divorce is more difficult or 
 impossible to obtain. 
 
 Still, in spite of the dispute which may arise about certain 
 parts of morality, there does seem to be a sufficient consensus 
 of opinion as to right and wrong, which contrasts markedly 
 with the differences of opinion as to matters of religion. 
 People who would differ from one another in their views as to 
 the nature of God, as to the possibility of miracles, as to the au- 
 thority of Scripture, as to the definition of a Church, the value 
 of the Sacraments, etc., would recognise a common standard 
 on the leading principles of morality — so far as general state- 
 ments go. As to the indispensability for human life of certain 
 fundamental virtues, such as justice, fidelity, self-control, 
 there would be no dispute. The differences would show them- 
 selves, however, the moment it came to be considered what 
 kind of acts were just ; under what conditions promises were and 
 were not binding, and what degree of self-control was neces- 
 sary in the different departments of life. As to what people 
 will tolerate in the way of discussion on moral matters, I 
 think we may say that they are generally ready to allow dis- 
 cussion of a serious kind, provided any novel proposals do not 
 go very far beyond what they are accustomed to, or else go so 
 very far that they do not seem likely to bear practical fruit. 
 Thus people who disapprove of all divorce may allow discussion 
 on the subject of divorce, but would certainly disapprove, and 
 might even be inclined to punish an attack on the institution 
 of the family as they understand it. But an advocacy of com- 
 plete community of wives and children, as in Plato's Republic, 
 would seem too alien from their accustomed world to be likely 
 to be of any practical danger to morality. There is, however, 
 a growing feeling that discussion of moral principles is to be 
 tolerated or not very much according to the seriousness of 
 tone with which it is carried on, and the absence of appeals to 
 individual passion or selfishness. This, we may say, is the 
 modern form of the distinction which used to be made be- 
 tween serious discussions among the learned and the dissemina- 
 tion of dangerous and unsettling opinions among the ignorant 
 multitude who are ruled by custom and authority and not by 
 reason. When all are supposed by a convention of demo-
 
 192 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 cratic sentiment to be reasonable, and when private judgment 
 is claimed as a right, or recognised as a duty, the distinction 
 comes to be drawn differently, the mode of speech being- 
 accounted more important than the class of persons addressed. 
 The same standard is therefore applied to controversy about 
 moral, as about religious questions — a standard of decency 
 rather than a standard of orthodoxy. It should not be for- 
 gotten, however, how relative such a standard is ; and the wise 
 maxim is therefore, in doubtful cases, to give the person ac- 
 cused of "indecency," in speech or writing or act, the benefit 
 of the doubt. Any repression that seems to any considerable 
 number of serious-minded persons to err in the direction of in- 
 tolerance is certain to be accompanied by clandestine attempts 
 to evade the law, of which attempts there will not be suffici- 
 ently general disapproval. 
 
 To those who approach ethical questions with the idea that 
 everything must have an indisputable and dogmatic basis, 
 such a position may seem dangerous and unstable. How, it 
 may be asked, are we to avoid complete moral anarchy if 
 everything may be questioned, provided the assailant of ac- 
 cepted principles says with any plausibility that he is a serious- 
 minded person ? Such an objection ignores the principle on 
 which scientific ethics rest — the principle of consistency or 
 coherence — the principle which the Kantian ethics express 
 in the form of universality. In moral matters, because of the 
 necessities of education — if for no other reason — the burden of 
 proof must be laid on the assailant of accepted beliefs. Any 
 one who simply attacks and insults accepted beliefs about right 
 or wrong may fairly be regarded as not a serious-minded inno- 
 vator. He may fairly be asked to show that the principles he 
 advocates would work out better than the accepted principles. 
 The thief implies the existence of private property, and 
 profits by it : his conduct does not belong to a system under 
 which a society could exist at all. No society could exist 
 hy every one stealing from everybody else. On the other 
 hand, the advocate of communism may be wise or foolish ; 
 but he is advocating a social system, and attacks existing 
 institutions from the standpoint of an alleged better society. 
 Similarly, the adulterer presupposes the existence of the 
 family, and uses it to his own advantage : whereas the advo- 
 cate of complete promiscuity may be foolish, but he is argu-
 
 CH. VI 1 1] TOLERATION 193 
 
 ing from the point of view of an alleged better society, not 
 from the point of view of the mere selfish violator of existing 
 institutions. 
 
 When we have to deal with works of art, it is more difficult 
 to apply this test of sincerity — the possession of an ideal sys- 
 tem ; for the artist as such does not work in a medium of 
 general conceptions, nor has his work any direct social aim. 
 Where a work of art (a book or picture) seems to the average 
 person grossly indecent, the artist is bound to prove that his 
 work involves real, thorough, earnest labour. The test of ear- 
 nest, hard work may be suggested as a help towards distin- 
 guishing the serious artist from the manufacturer of mere 
 indecencies ; it is one form of the general ethical test of co- 
 herence. The virtue of industry, of honest work, may go 
 along with many defects, but cannot go along with mere reck- 
 lessness and absence of all sense of responsibility. 
 
 We may lay down general precepts which seem to us per- 
 fectly unexceptionable, and we may expect to escape the mis- 
 takes of our predecessors and not to be found persecuting those 
 whom a later age will venerate or at least excuse : neverthe- 
 less, we may be certain that similar mistakes will be made 
 again and again. Every new idea with regard to matters of 
 religion, or matters of morality, must offend a great mass of 
 prevalent opinion, and must struggle for existence among the 
 ideas already in possession of the ground. This is inevitable ; 
 and it need not be a matter of regret. A great many new ideas 
 are not true or valuable, and it is well that they should not 
 survive. A general willingness to take up every idea, simply 
 because it is new, is not a healthy sign either of a society or of 
 an individual mind. On the other hand, the society which re- 
 jects every new idea condemns itself to stagnation and decay. 
 The safest principle is that the fight between ideas should be 
 carried on as fairly, and with as much courtesy as possible. 
 To silence an opponent by burning him, or even by burning his 
 books, is a brutal kind of argument ; but if you really think 
 his ideas nonsense, and mischievous nonsense, there is no 
 reason for hesitating to say so. To go on, however, to suggest 
 that he is an immoral person, or that his motives (about which 
 you know nothiugj in ])ublishing his opinions are bad motives, 
 is to overstep the limits of decent controversy. On the other 
 hand, ridicule is a fair weapon on the whole, and is a great 
 improvement on the Inquisition or the censorship. 
 
 N. R. O
 
 194 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 There is, too, an obvious difference — analogous to that 
 ah'eady referred to — between tolerating the publication of 
 books which you (whoever the " you " may be) may think 
 injurious to religion and morality, and tolerating the thrusting 
 of these books in a cheap f^rm under the notice of j^oung and 
 inexperienced persons. If a firm of booksellers or the mana- 
 gers of a circulating library " boj^cott " a certain class of 
 books, it is perfectly legitimate to ridicule their conduct, 
 and try to show the inconsistency of countenancing the 
 works of X, while refusing to supply the works of Y and Z ; 
 but the only way to make the purveyors of innocuous litera- 
 ture alter their conduct is to alter the opinions of the great 
 reading public ; and then the amateur censorship of the press, 
 exercised by Messrs. Blank and Company, will be sure to 
 alter its character. If we ask the great reading public, who 
 are the clients of Messrs. Blank and Company, to abstain from 
 prohibiting our books altogether, we must not complain if the 
 private and unofficial " boycott " is substituted for the public 
 censorship. "We must tolerate, in our turn, what we think the 
 pig-headedness of the great reading public. The case is 
 different Avhen books are bought, as in a rate-supported 
 library, out of money to which the whole community contri- 
 butes ; it is then fair to demand that any book likely to be 
 desired by a sufficient number of readers shall be supplied. 
 But here, in disputed cases, the only fair resort is to a. poll, 
 and the decision of the majority must be accepted as final — 
 " until the times do alter." No one, not even if he considers 
 himself sent direct from heaven to preach a new gospel, can 
 claim any political or social right to thrust his notions upon 
 people against their wish — he may consider it a moral duty 
 to do so, but he must be prepared to face the odium of society. 
 It would be unreasonable to demand a law compelling Mrs. 
 Grundy to leave her card on every apostle of every "new spirit" : 
 and the apostle would probably not benefit by such a law in 
 the long run. The initiator must be prepared to fight his way 
 to recognition ; his ideas may be destructive to the society he 
 addresses, and need he be astonished if that society is reluc- 
 tant to hear him ? Leave him alone, according to Gamaliel's 
 wise precept of tolerance ; neither give the foolish fanatic 
 the undeserved honour of martyrdom, nor raise dangerous 
 obstacles to the peaceable transition of society from one stage 
 
 A
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 195 
 
 to another. Such tolerance implies a belief in the ultimate 
 rationality of that struggle between institutions and ideas 
 which makes the most interesting part of the world's histor}' ; 
 but, as I have already pointed out, it is a tolerance only likely 
 to be felt and allowed by those who consider themselves fairly 
 secure in their position, and who do not fear a violent over- 
 throw. One of the lessons of experience is that toleration 
 itself offers a safety-valve, and prevents explosions. There 
 must be variety of ideas for the selecting process to work 
 upon ; but in the evolution of ideas and institutions, the less 
 the lives and welfare of individual human beings are sacrificed, 
 the higher is the type of evolution.^ 
 
 ^ Since writing the above, I see that, in the International Journal of 
 Ethics for April, 1894, Mr. J. C. Smith, criticising an essay of mine on 
 " The Eights of Minorities " (republished in Darivin and Hegel, etc.), so 
 completely misunderstands my position as to say that I have been 
 "exactly anticipated by that arch-Tory, Dr. Johnson: 'In short, sir, I 
 have got no farther than this; every man has aright to utter what he 
 thinks truth, and every other man has a right to knock him down for it. 
 Martyrdom is the test.' " Now, if natural rights mean merely tliose 
 "rights "that exist independently of and prior to organised society, it 
 is quite true that such a mere struggle for existence is all that we should 
 find. But if, as I have been urging throughout, natural rights mean, as 
 thej- have always practically meant to political and social reformers 
 (amid whatever confusions of thought and language), those rights 
 which a well-regulated State ought to secure to its citizens, then what I 
 contend is, that every man ought to have a right secured to him to utter 
 what he thinks truth, provided that he do so with sutficient decency of 
 language, and in a manner not calculated to provoke a breach of the 
 peace ; and that, whether he observes these conditions or not, no other 
 man shall be permitted to knock him down for it. If he is punished for 
 indecency or for inciting to violence, it must be hy duly constituted 
 authority. P^ven the Anarchist, caught in the act of depositing his 
 infernal machine, must in a well-regulated State be protected by the police 
 against lyncliing on his way to prison or the scaifold. ''The all-important 
 right of minorities," I have said more than once, " is the right to turn 
 themselves into majorities if they can." This principle has been thought 
 to savour of intolerance, simply because my critics have not realised how 
 very miich that right implies. It means, at least, "freedom of the press, 
 freedom of associations, freedom of public meeting." Mr. Smith thinks 
 these things are given "wherever there is a fairly representative govern- 
 ment and a sound public opinion." AVell, I do not know how much he is 
 prepared to understand by "a sound public opinion"; there must be a 
 public o\-)\mon faiiourable to tolerance. Representative government, re- 
 publican institutions, nay, even accumulated Declarations of the IMghts 
 of Man and constitutional guarantees of liberty, are not always sullicicnt 
 to secure this so modest right of a minority that 1 plead for. As I show
 
 196 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 When we turn from the more specially political to the 
 more specially ethical aspects of toleration, the matter to be 
 considered is not the right of freedom of thought, but the 
 duty of exercising private judgment. The most important 
 question that can be discussed in connection with this duty 
 is the proper attitude of the individual to authority. It is 
 often absurdly alleged that authority in matters of opinion is 
 an antiquated principle, for which the modern democratic 
 spirit can have no further reverence. The man who claims to 
 discard all authority, and to judge everything for himself, if 
 he is quite in earnest, must avoid receiving any education, 
 must avoid even learning a language ; and such an one will 
 not be likely to express, or even to form, any opinion of his 
 own whatever. The rejection of authority should, to a 
 reasonable being, who is a social being, mean nothing more 
 than the rejection of authority which refuses to submit to anj'' 
 tests that carefully trained human reason can apply. That 
 the person who accepts any one's authority on any subject 
 should himself be able to test the worth of the authority is a 
 perfectly unreasonable demand. I maj^ accept as accurate the 
 result of a chemical analysis, without myself knowing any- 
 thing about chemistry ; but I may be reasonably suspicious of 
 a person's statement of the value of a food or a medicine, if 
 the person who recommends it refuses to submit it to the 
 analysis of experts at all. I may use a table of logarithms 
 for purposes of calculation without thinking it necessary to 
 test the accuracy with which it has been constructed, but I 
 should have my suspicions of its value aroused, if it were 
 made a penal offence to say anything disrespectful about the 
 manner in which the book had been compiled. 
 
 in Note, B at the end of this chapter, the United States refuse this 
 right to the Mormon community. Whether their action is justifiable or 
 not, on grounds of urgent public safety, I am not prepared to discuss 
 fully : I am not sufficiently acquainted with the particular facts. But 
 their action is certainly inconsistent with this right of minorities, and 
 with the loudly proclaimed right of religious liberty. 
 
 What I do strongly hold, however, is that minorities have no "natural 
 right," I mean no reasonable claim, to have their views enforced on other 
 people, and their actions in violation of the law of the land (in countries 
 with a fair representative system) safeguarded against legal penalties. 
 But just because of these necessities of public order, the right of striving 
 by peaceable means of persuasion to get the law altered must be the more 
 carefully protected. 
 
 m
 
 CH. VI 1 1] TOLERATION 197 
 
 Authority in matters of conduct depends on rather more 
 complex considerations than in either of these cases. The 
 cohesion of a society requires in many cases an implicit 
 obedience to commands, though it may no longer require an 
 implicit acceptance of statements about matters of fact. I 
 cannot be allowed, if anarchy is to be avoided, the same license 
 in deciding whether I shall obey a law or not, that I am 
 allowed in expressing an opinion about its justice or expediency. 
 If I am seriously convinced that it is wrong for me to obey 
 the law, it may become my duty to rebel — but it is then also 
 my duty to take the consequences. But this raises a question 
 to which I have to come later — the alleged natural right of 
 resistance. In the meantime it is enough to point out the 
 serious responsibility undertaken by any one who denies the 
 generally accepted principles of right and wrong ; he is 
 morally bound to show that the principles he proposes to sub- 
 stitute are workable and compatible with human well-being. 
 But it is a fair demand that the accepted principles shall be 
 capable of justification on some other grounds except their 
 antiquity. The individual may not say : " I have a right to 
 disobey every law and maxim of conduct of whose worth I 
 am not personally convinced " — that is anarchy, which is the 
 reductio ad absurdum of any principle of conduct. He may 
 say : " I have a right to discuss in a serious manner, and be- 
 fore an audience that will not be excited to violence by what 
 I say, the justice of this law or this maxim of conduct." That 
 is the toleration which every sufficiently stable and yet pro- 
 gressive society ought to grant. And such toleration imposes 
 on the critic a greater responsibility than can reasonably be 
 demanded of the hunted victim of despotic power. We ex- 
 pect an Englishman to be more sober in his attacks on the 
 institutions of his country than we can expect a Russian exile 
 to be in criticising the authority of the Czar. We excuse a 
 great deal in Voltaire which we should not excuse in a modern 
 free-thinker. We should not be astonished if the man whose 
 soberest criticisms are met by imprisonment or banishment 
 becomes bitter, and turns savagely on his enemies. But 
 neither should we be astonished that any society is apt to be 
 provoked into anger by abusive criticisms of its most cherished 
 institutions. The assailants of time-honoured usages are apt 
 to say of society : —
 
 19S TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 " Get animal est tres mechant, 
 Quand on I'attaque, il se defend," 
 
 wliicli may be Englished roughly thus : — 
 
 "This animal is very wicked, 
 It turns and figlits when it is kicked." 
 
 Struggle is inevitable ; it rests with us whether it is a brutal 
 or a civilised warfare — a contest of reason on both sides, or a 
 contest of rant on the one side and of cruelty and cant on 
 the other, 
 
 NOTE A. 
 
 RELIGIOUS PERSECUTION AND TOLERATION: SOME HISTORICAL 
 ILLUSTRATIONS. 
 
 Hallam, in liis Constitutional History^ is justly indignant with such 
 a passage as this of Southey's (from the Book of the Churchy II 
 p. 285): "That Church [viz., the Church of England] and the queen 
 [Elizabeth], its re-founder, are clear of persecution as regarding the 
 Catholics. No church, no sect, no individual even, had yet professed 
 the principle of toleration." Hallam points out that the second of 
 these sentences certainly does not help to prove the first of them ; 
 and that, as regards individuals, the statement is false. Sir Thomas 
 More, in his Utopia, professed a principle of toleration wider even 
 than that of Locke. The dogmas of the " civil religion " of Utopia 
 are only two — a Divine providence and the immortality of the soul, 
 with future rewards and punishments ; but those who deny these 
 doctrines, though excluded from all public offices (as at the present 
 day in the law-abiding State of Arkansas), are put to no punishment, 
 and are not banished, as they wonld be according to Rousseau's " civil 
 religion." In his views on religion, as in several other matters, this 
 Roman Catholic martyr for conscience' sake goes far beyond what 
 many of the champions of religious liberty have dared to dream of. 
 
 While Hallam is right in saying that we cannot acquit Elizabeth's 
 governm^ent of persecution, I think he does not do full justice to the 
 significance of the contention made by Burleigh: that no one had 
 been put to death in Elizabeth's reign for religion, but only for 
 treason. Admit that the interpretation given to treason makes this 
 defence a hypocritical one, is it not significant of a change of sentiment 
 that Burleigh adopts it ? It is the homage paid to a new principle. 
 The pamphlet called The Executive of Justice in England for 
 Maintenance of Public and Christian Peace, published in 1583, and 
 ascribed, with every probability, to Lord Burleigh, is included in 
 The Soniers Tracts (ed. Scott, I. p. 189 scq.). The giving up of the 
 punishment of death for heresy as such is indeed only a small step 
 in the direction of religious toleration. In another pamphlet of
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 199 
 
 1583, .4 Declaration of the favourable dealing of her Majesty's Com- 
 missioners aj^pointed for the Examination of certain Traitors, and 
 for the Tortures unjustly reported to he done upon them for matters 
 of Religion {Somers Tracts, I, p, 209 seq.), Burleigh asserts that 
 those who applied the rack were specially charged to use it " in so 
 charitable a manner as such a thing might be." It is remarkable, 
 as Hallain points out, that in this same year Burleigh addressed a 
 memorial to the Queen in favour of a lax enforcement of the oath 
 of supremacy on Papists. To pass very stringent laws in order to 
 satisfy the fanatics, and then to allow them to be administered laxly, 
 was a favourite device of statesmen in those days, and is not quite 
 unknown in ours. I have heard an American citizen saying with 
 reference to Prohibitory Liquor Laws (with what amount of exaggera- 
 tion I cannot judge), " In this country we make laws, but we don't 
 keep them. We pass a strict law about the sale of liquor — that 
 pleases the Prohibitionists ; but you can always get a drink, if you 
 know how." ^ It seems to have been much the same with laws 
 against the Papists : it was one thing to pass a stringent law to 
 satisfy the more vehement Protestants, it was another to enforce it 
 rigidly against loyal country gentlemen in the northern counties, 
 where, out of a scanty population, a large proportion were Catholic 
 in sympathies. As to priests, and especially Jesuits — that was 
 another thing. 
 
 In this Memorial of Burleigh's {So7ners Tracts, I. p. 164 seq.), it 
 is noticeable how he argues the inefficacy of persecution from 
 experience. " Putting to death," he says, " doth no ways lessen 
 them, since we find by experience that it worketh no such effect, 
 but like Hydra's heads, upon cutting off one, seven grow wp, persecu- 
 tion being accounted as the badge of the Church ; and therefore they 
 should never have the honour to take any pretence of martyrdom in 
 England, where the fulness of blood and greatness of heart is such, 
 that they will even for shameful things go bravely to death — much 
 more when they think themselves to climb heaven ; and this vice 
 of obstinacy seems to the common people a Divine constancy : so 
 that, for my part, I wish no lessening of their number, but by 
 preaching and by education of the younger, under good school- 
 masters " — i.e., he proposes to deprive Papists of the control of the 
 education of their children, these children to serve as hostages for 
 their parents' fidelity. In the same Memorial, he advises also against 
 driving out of the Church " the preciser sort " {i.e. the Puritans), 
 with whom he had no particular sympathy. 
 
 Hallam distinguishes five stages or degrees in resti-aint on religious 
 liberty. Here is the persecutor's ladder, as one might call it: — 
 
 ^ Tlie statement seems, on the whole, to be borne out by Mr. Fansliawe 
 ill his Report (for Mr. Eathbone) on Liquor Legislation in the United 
 States and Canada (Cassell & Co. 1893).
 
 200 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 (1) The requisition of a test of conformity to the established religion 
 as a condition of exercising offices of civil trust. (2) Restraint of the 
 free promulgation of opinions, especially through the press. (3) Pro- 
 hibition of the open exercise of religious worship. (4) Prohibition of 
 even private acts of devotion or private expression of opinion. (5) 
 Enforcement by legal penalties of conformity to the Established 
 Church, or an abjuration of heterodox tenets. " The statutes of 
 Elizabeth's reign," he adds, " comprehend every one of these pro- 
 gressive stages of restraint and persecution." 
 
 In the "Declaration of Breda" (1(360), Charles II. declares "a 
 liberty to tender consciences, and that no man shall be disquieted or 
 called in question for differences of opinion in matter of religion, 
 tchich do not disturb the })cace of the kingdom ; and that we shall 
 be ready to consent to such an Act of Parliament, as upon mature 
 deliberation shall be offered to us, for the full granting that in- 
 dulgence " (Gardiner, Const. Doc, p. 352;. We have here the express 
 recognition, in words at least, of what may be called the non- 
 mediseval principle of interfering with religious liberty solely on 
 political or social grounds. The Parliaments of Charles 11. were 
 sufficiently intolerant, but then the words "disturb the peace of the 
 kingdom " may be interpreted in such a way as to justify severe 
 restraints on dissenters. 
 
 The Instrument of Government (1G53) limits the toleration it con- 
 cedes to " such as profess faith in God by Jesus Christ," and not 
 only by consideration of the public peace ; it also expressly excludes 
 Popery and Prelacy, so that although it implies the giving up of the 
 attem^Dt to enforce uniformity of doctrine and worship, it still main- 
 tains the duty of excluding certain kinds of religion, as such. On 
 this matter the Instrument of Government, in the main, carries out 
 the provisions of the Agreement of the People (originally drawn up 
 by the army in 1647-8), except that the latter leaves the toleration 
 of Popery and Prelacy so far an open question, i.e. a question for 
 Parliament to deal with. " It is not intended to be hereby provided 
 that this liberty shall necessarily' extend to Popery or Prelacy." 
 The constitutional Bill of the first Parliament of the Protectorate 
 (Gardiner, p. 353 seq.) only provides " that without the consent of 
 the Lord Protector and Parliament, no law or statute be made for 
 the restraining of such tender consciences as shall differ in doctrine, 
 worship, or discipline from the public profession aforesaid, and shall 
 not abuse their liberty to the civil injury of others or the disturbance 
 of the public peace." Bills, however, were without the Protector's 
 consent to become law which restrained "damnable heresies." What 
 are damnable heresies, however, was to be agi'eed on by Protector 
 and Parliament. This scheme is obviously very far away from what 
 we generally understand by the principle of religious liberty.
 
 CH. VI 1 1] TOLERATION 201 
 
 If Sir Thomas More in his Utopia deserves to be accorinted the 
 first theoretical advocate of religions toleration, Roger Williams, the 
 founder of Providence (afterwards incorporated in Rhode Island), is 
 the first person in modern times who actually succeeded in establish- 
 ing a community on a basis of liberty of conscience (1(J3G) ; and for 
 a long time the colony seemed to its more orderly but intolerant 
 neighbours, Massachusetts and Connecticut, to be a shocking example 
 of anarchy and confusion. But time justified the bold experiment, 
 and Charles II. in 1G63 granted a charter to Rhode Island, which 
 remained its written constitution until 1842, and which conceded 
 a religious liberty such as few could have dared to ask for or to grant 
 in Grreat Britain in the seventeenth century. This religious liberty 
 was granted expressly on the ground that Rhode Island was too 
 remote to make any breach of " the unity and uniformity established 
 in this nation." 
 
 Mary Pisher, the Quakeress, who was imprisoned in Boston and 
 half-starved for preaching blasphemous and devilish doctrines, five 
 years afterwards " went to Adrianople and tried to convert tlie Grrand 
 Turk, who ti^eated her with grave courtesy and allowed her to 
 prophesy unmolested. [Did he understand her?] This is one of the 
 numerous incidents that, on a superficial view of history, might be 
 cited in support of the opinion that there has been on the whole more 
 tolerance in the Mussulman thaii in the Christian world. Rightly 
 interpreted, however, the fact has no such implication. In Massa- 
 chusetts the preaching of Quaker doctrines might (and did) lead to a 
 revolution ; in Turkey it was as harmless as the barking of dogs. 
 Grovernor Endicott was afraid of Mary Fisher ; Mahomet III. was 
 not" (Fiske, The Beginnings of New England^ pp. 183, 184). 
 
 Roger Williams, in tolerating the Quakers, proved that he adopted 
 toleration — " soul liberty " — as a principle and not merely as a 
 policy : for he never concealed his antipathy to their doctrines. He 
 wrote not only The Bloody Tenent, but George Fox digged out of 
 his Burroios. It may be noted that Williams's saying that " A soul 
 or spiritual rape is more abominable in Grod's eye than to force and 
 ravish the bodies of all the women in the world " {Bloody Tenent, 
 1644, p. 94) had been anticipated by the Baptist Busher {/icligion''s 
 Peace, 1614): "Persecution for religion is to force the conscience. 
 . . . And herein the bishops commit a greater sin than if they 
 force the bodies of women and maids against their wills " (Hanserd 
 Knollys Society's Tracts on Liberty of Conscience, 1614-1661, p. 34). 
 But Williams had to put his principles to the test iu the difficult task 
 of organising a turbulent community. It is true he believed that 
 toleration would lead the sect of Quakers to dwindle. " They are 
 likely to gain more followers by the conceit of their patient suiforings 
 than by consent to their pernicious sayings." 
 
 Roger Williams's famous book is entitled. The Bloudy Tencnt of
 
 202 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 Persecution for cause of Conscience, discussed in a Conference 
 beticeene Truth and Peace, icho, in all tender Affection, jjresent to the 
 High Court of Parliament (as the residt of their Discourse) these 
 (amongst other Passages) of highest consideration (London: 1644). 
 A reply to Williams's book was made in The Bloudy Tenent icashed 
 and made white in the blond of the Lanibe : being discussed and dis- 
 charged of bloud-guiltiness by just Defence, etc. Whereunto is added 
 a Reply to Mr. Williams^s Answer to Mr. Cotton's Letter. By John 
 Cotton, Batcheloi- in Divinity, and Teacher of the Church of Christ 
 at Boston in New-England (London: 1647). To this a rejoinder 
 was published by Williams : The Bloody Tenent yet more Bloody by 
 Mr. Cotton''s endevour to wash it ichite in the Blood of the Lambe ; 
 of ^chose j^i'ccious Blood, spilt in the Blood of his Servants, and of 
 the Blood of Millions spilt in former and later Wars for Conscience 
 sake, that most Bloody Tenent of Persecution for cause of Con- 
 science upon a second Tryal is found now more apparently and 
 more notoriously guilty. By R. Williams of Providence in New- 
 England (London : 1652). 
 
 From this last work it is worth quoting, in explanation of this 
 quaint title, and for its own sake, the eloqiient concluding passage. 
 It comes at the end of "An Appendix" addressed "to the clergy 
 of the fo;ir great parties, professing the name of Christ Jesus, in 
 England [the head-line inserts " Old and New " before England], 
 Scotland, and Ireland, viz., the Popish, Prelatical, Presbyterian, and 
 Independent": — "You know it is the Spirit of Love from Christ 
 Jesus, that turns our feet from the traditions of Fathers, etc., that 
 sets the heart and tongue and pen and hands too (as Paul's) day and 
 night to work rather than the progress and puritj' and simplicity of 
 the crown of Christ Jesus should be debased or hindered. This Spirit 
 will cause you leave (with joy) benefices and bishoprics, worlds and 
 lives, for His sake, the heights and depths, lengths and breadths of 
 whose love you know doth infinitely pass your most knowing com- 
 prehensions and imaginations. There is but little of this Spirit 
 extant — I fear will not be until we see Christ Jesus slain in the 
 slaughter of the witnesses : then Joseph will go boldly unto Pilate 
 for the slaughtered body of most precious Saviour, and Nicodemus 
 will go by day to buy and bestow his sweetest spices on his infinitely 
 sweeter soul's beloved." 
 
 NOTE B. 
 
 MEASURES FOR SUPPRESSING MORMONISM IN THE UNITED S'^ATES, 
 
 It is worth while, in connection with this subject of religious 
 liberty and liberty of opinion, to call attention to the treatment of 
 the Mormons by the Grovernment of the United States, for two reasons 
 especially. In the first place, this is a test case of the extent to
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 203 
 
 which "religious liberty" is really secured to individuals in a 
 country whose constitution is supposed to be strictly limited by the 
 recognition of certain indefeasible natural rights, which Government 
 should protect, but with which it should not interfere. ^ The amount 
 of sympathy, with which the action of the United States Government 
 in its endeavour to suppress Mormonism is regarded in America and 
 in Europe, serves also as a measure of the extent to which people 
 really believe in " religious liberty." Secondly, the action of the 
 United States Government, and the sympathy with which it has been 
 regarded in this matter, help one to realise more accurately the spirit 
 m which Catholics have persecuted Protestants, and Protestants 
 Catholics. Some study of the Mormon question is an important 
 discipline and training for the exercise of the historical spirit in our 
 judgments about the past. You abhor polygamy, you think it a 
 degrading and detestable institution, and the religion of the "Latter 
 Day Saints " which supports it (or did support it) 3'ou look on as a 
 tissue of delusions and lies. Transfer these sentiments of yours to 
 the mind of a sincere Protestant of the sixteenth or seventeenth 
 centuries, and you will understand the way in which he regarded 
 toleration of " the idolatrous sacrifice of the mass." You, the en- 
 lightened, tolerant, modern Protestant, cannot understand, perhaps, 
 the attitude of the Roman Catholic clergy of the present day to the 
 question of divorce, or the attitude of the bulk of the Anglican 
 clergy to the " Deceased Wife's Sister Bill." On what general 
 grounds of respect for individual liberty is there any difference 
 between your attitude and theirs? They abhor and, if they could, 
 would prevent what injures the institution of the family, as they 
 understand the family, and what violates the principles of religion, 
 as they understand religion. You understand the institution of the 
 family and the principles of religion differently from them, and 
 differently from the " Latter Day Saints." The difference is a 
 difference in private judgment ; and yet in virtue of an opinion not 
 supported by any infallible court of appeal you interfere with the 
 religious liberty of others; for if " religious liberty " has any mean- 
 ing, the "religion" must depend on the judgment of the person 
 claiming the liberty, and not on that of the person conceding it. 
 People may glory in not allowing their Government to interfere in 
 matters of religion; but, however much they may disestablish all 
 Churches, they must either concede to their Government the right of 
 
 ' As I have pointed out, the Declarations of Rights ajipcar in State 
 Constitutions, but the first amendment to the U.S. Constitution lays down 
 that " Congress sliall make no law respecting an establisliment of re- 
 ligion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof ; or abridging the freedom 
 of speecli, or of the press, etc." This is the constitutional guarantee of 
 tiie liberties of citizens of the U.S. living in Territories, and is generally 
 understood as a guarantee of " religious liberty."
 
 204 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 deciding what arc matters of religion, or they must bow to the de- 
 cision of some Chnrch or combination of Churches. By no possible 
 declaration of rights, or constitutional safeguards, can you absolutely 
 distinguish Church and State, the spiritual and the temporal power, 
 for in the last resort cither Church or State must determine the pro- 
 vinces of each. 
 
 Now let us admit, not merely that polygamy is a morally defective 
 form of the family, but that its suppression by law is a desirable end, 
 and that the fact of polygamy being practised under the sanction of 
 religion, so far from making it advisable to leave polygamy alone, 
 makes it all the more important to suppress an institution which is 
 more likely to endure and to spread because supported by belief in a 
 religion — however absurd that religion may seem to the majority of 
 persons in the country. How can such suppression of polygamy be 
 reconciled with the maintenance of religious liberty ? I think no 
 objection can be taken to the decision of the Supreme Court of the 
 United States in the case of Eeynolds v. U. S., that " Congress was 
 deprived by the Constitution of all legislative power over mere 
 opinion, but was left free to reach actions which were in violation of 
 social duties and subversive of good order." Who decides, however, 
 what "actions are in violation of social duties and subversive of good 
 order " ? The legislature itself, — which means in the last resort the 
 average public opinion of the community, or rather the opinion of 
 those persons who manage to make their will effective at election 
 time. Suppose a strongly Protestant majority united in political 
 sentiment, living alongside of a Roman Catholic minority, whose 
 votes are not an object of importance, as they would be were the 
 majority divided amongst themselves ; suppose a great antagonism to 
 the Confessional among the Protestant majority and among a con- 
 siderable number of husbands of Roman Catholic wives, might not 
 the Confessional be prohibited on the ground that it was " in violation 
 of social duties and subversive of good order"? Would such a law 
 be an infringement of the right of religious liberty ? Undoubtedly 
 penitents and priests would have to choose between risking their 
 eternal welfare (as they believe) and breaking the law of the land. 
 Yet, from the point of view of many a legislator, the practice of 
 confession might be regarded as interfering with the duties of 
 family life (as he understands them) in the same sort of way that 
 polygamy seems to do from the point of view of other legislators. 
 
 A series of laws passed by Congress between 1862 and 1887 have, 
 with continually increasing severity, sought to stamp out polygamy 
 in the Territories. Lest an ordinary law against bigamy should be 
 insufficient, the Edmunds Law of 1882 makes " cohabitation with 
 more than one woman " a crime. To the European who believes in 
 religious liberty, or in what is otherwise described as the secularisa- 
 tion of politics, it must seem astonishing that, in its endeavours to
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 205 
 
 discourage polygamy, Congress should commit such a direct infringe- 
 ment of religious liberty as is implied in this revival of Puritan 
 methods of dealing with the voluntar}'- relations of the sexes among 
 adults, punishing " sins " as "crimes." If in any American State 
 the Roman Catholic population obtained the control of the legislature, 
 they might punish as " criminals " persons legally divorced (in other 
 States) who had married again, or persons who had contracted mixed 
 marriages, with no more disrespect to the natural rights of liberty, 
 etc., than that with which the United States Government has made 
 adultery a crime in Utah. Congress has chosen to proceed on what 
 may be called mediaeval principles of legislation, eriforcing by penal 
 laws certain prohibitions of the Christian Church (though not others). 
 The Supreme Court, in defending a piece of legislation of which I 
 have still to speak, lays down that " the primitive power of Govern- 
 ment for acts recognised by the general consent of the Christian world 
 in modern times as proper matters for prohibitory legislation, cannot 
 be suspended in order that the tenets of a religious sect encouraging 
 crime may be carried out without hindrance." It is to be noticed 
 that the appeal is not made, as by the fathers of the Constitution, to 
 the law of nature or the consent of the human race, but, as it might 
 have been made by any of the " persecuting " governments of earlier 
 days, to " the consent of the Christian world in modern times " {I.e. at 
 present). The Christian world, certainly up to the end of the seven- 
 teenth century, with trivial exceptions, agreed that " heresy " ought 
 to be suppressed or at least discouraged by law, though different 
 parts of the Christian world had (fortunately for the cause of liberty) 
 different definitions of heresy. The American Supreme Court are 
 using the very arguments which Lord Burleigh or Archbishop Laud 
 might have used. You make saying mass a crime, or you make 
 attending a "conventicle" a crime, and then you say, "No one's 
 religion shall excuse him from committing a crime against the law 
 of the land." The method is simple ; but is this " religious liberty " ? 
 "But," it will be answered, "the Supremo Court refers only to 
 the general consent of the Christian world in modern times. The 
 Christian world has come to the opinion that it is wrong to punish 
 for error in doctrine [Strict Roman Catholics have not come to that 
 opinion, but only to the opinion that it is sometimes impossible and 
 sometimes unsafe or inexpedient to do so]. We differ too much about 
 doctrines, but about morality all Christians are agreed." Are they ? 
 How about divorce ? What is the standard of " Christian " ethics ? 
 Is it the opinion of a Church which claims infallibility, or is it 
 " the Scriptures " to which Protestants appeal ? If the former, how 
 can you sanction divorce ? If Christian ethics are to be decided by 
 the Bible, and the Bible only, it seems specially unreasonable to pro- 
 hibit polygamy, which is sanctioned by the example of men after 
 God's own heart in the Old Testament, and is nowhere forbidden in
 
 2o6 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 the New Testament, except in the case of Bishops. ^ But " the 
 general consent of the Christian world in modern times," it will be 
 explained, *' means the opinion of Catholics and Protestants on those 
 matters of morality on which they are agreed; the appeal is made 
 to the actual practice of countries in which Christianity is the pre- 
 dominant religion, though in matters of legislation compromises 
 between Catholics and Protestants are adopted." Do Great Britain, 
 France, Germany, Austria, Italy, in all of which Christian Churches 
 are "established," form a pnrt of the Christian world as well as the 
 United States of America, in which, professedly in the interests of 
 " religious liberty," there is no established Church ? In none of these 
 countries is adultery nowadays punished as a crime ^ in the strict 
 sense of the term — a wrong against the State, to be detected and 
 punished like theft or murder, quite apart from any initiative of 
 aggrieved individuals. The tendency of " modern " legislation has 
 been to give up the attempt to enforce by penal sanctions (I am 
 r.ot referring to civil remedies) the code of Christian ethics in regard 
 to sexual morality on adult persons acting voluntarily, and not " con- 
 trary to nature." It is a new thing that the United States of America 
 should be ambitious of being more mediaeval than the benighted coun- 
 tries of the old world. Are modern legislators, who profess a belief 
 in natural rights, and who accept the standard of general happiness 
 as the test of good legislation, prepared at the bidding of a union 
 of sects to enact laws which cannot really be enforced without the 
 introduction of a spy-system that would be far more injurious to the 
 morality of social life than the laxity such Puritanical laws are 
 intended to cure ? Such laws, one is inclined to suspect, are not 
 intended to be generally enforced, but are passed (like some liquor 
 laws) to catch a certain number of votes, and to be used as a weapon 
 of attack against obnoxious groups, when convenient. 
 
 Now, what seems to take away excuse from the Congress and the 
 Supreme Court of the United States is, that it would have been quite 
 possible to fight polygamy on the principles which regulate " modern " 
 legislation in most Eui'opean countries. The following programme 
 is what would probably suggest itself to the secularised politicians of 
 those European countries which have accepted the principles of '89 : 
 First^ to recognise no marriage as legally binding except a civil 
 marriage. Secondly, to prohibit bigamous or polygamous civil mar- 
 
 ' 1 Tim. iii. 2. If the prohibition be of second marriages, this prohi- 
 bition, binding on jn'ieats of the '' Orthodox " Church, has not been 
 enforced on the laity by the legislature in anj' Christian country. 
 Theologians quote various texts from which they infer a prohibition of 
 poh-gamy ; and some theologians have great powers of inference. They 
 could more easily find texts deterring from marriage altogether than 
 from polygamous marriage. Monogamy has come to us as a Eoman, not 
 as a distinctively Christian, institution.
 
 CH. viii] TOLERATION 207 
 
 riages — with proper exceptions, of course, for persons legally divorced. 
 Thirdly^ to make adultery a ground for divorce, in the case of both 
 sexes equally, Fourthly^ in order to meet the special case of the 
 Mormons, who do not allow a second " marriage " unless the first 
 wife consents, it might be necessary to set a limit to the period of 
 time during which '' condonation " or " connivance " is a bar to di- 
 vorce, so as to allow the legal wife, who repents of a consent, given 
 perhaps under the influence of religious enthusiasm or religious ter- 
 rorism, full means of escaping from a polygamous husband if she 
 wishes. Lastly^ instead oiabolishiny female suffrage in the Territory 
 of Utah, as was done by the Edmunds-Tucker Law of 1887,^ it would 
 have seemed more in accordance with a sincere belief that pol3'gamy 
 was a system of slavery in which women were kept against their will, 
 to have retained female suffrage while ensuring by stringent enact- 
 ments the inviolable secrecy of the ballot. 
 
 Such a series of measures would probably have been very unac- 
 ceptable to the Mormon community ; but they would have been 
 measures for crushing out polygamy without violating, as the existing 
 measures seem to do to the observer from outside, the principle of 
 religious liberty, so loudly pi'ofessed by the United States. If the 
 devout Mormon were to choose, with the consent of his legal wife, to 
 bind himself by religious ceremonies to support a number of other 
 women for the term of their natural lives, and to put their children on 
 the same footing as to inheritance with his lawful issue, that would 
 doiibtless be an unusual manner of violating the duties of the family, 
 and would present a remarkable contrast to the way in which men 
 have been known to treat their wives and their mistresses in other 
 parts of the world — and even of the United States — but it seems 
 hardly so terrible a state of affairs as to call for criminal proceedings 
 on the part of a strong government in a country the vast majority of 
 whose inhabitants are not likely to become converts to the singular 
 revelations of Saint Joseph Smith. The United States Grovernment 
 has not even the excuse of reasonable fear, which may be pleaded for 
 the persecution of Elizabeth's reign. Have the legislators of Congress 
 so little faith in the superiority of monogamy that they can only fight 
 polygamy by the methods which the Puritans used in New England 
 against Catholics and Quakers ? 
 
 But even supposing it were conceded that there is nothing incon- 
 sistent with " religious liberty " in treating as criminal the plural or 
 " celestial " marriages recognised as binding by a religious sect, the 
 " persecution " of the Mormons does not end in the punishment of 
 overt acts which are, or have for the special purpose been made, crimes 
 by the law of the land. The Supreme Court of the United States 
 has decided that it is not unconstitutional to impose on voters a test 
 or abjuration oath, in which they have to swear that they do not 
 ' Of. Bryce, American CommoniccaWi, III. p. 294.
 
 2o8 TOLERATION [ch. viii 
 
 belong to an assocktion which teaches polygamy as a religious duty.^ 
 Such a test oath is imposed by the statutes of Idaho Territory ; that 
 is to say, a person can be deprived of his political rights simply for 
 belonging to a religious body which believes in the Tightness of 
 certain conduct which the law of the land has made criminal. Lord 
 Bui-leigh has been condemned as hypocritical because, while requir- 
 ing an abjuration oath from Roman Catholics (which they could not 
 conscientiously take) denying the papal supremacy in England, he 
 yet declared that this was not religious persecution. And yet every 
 Roman Catholic might reasonably be alleged to be a traitor so long 
 as he acknowledged the power of the Pope to dispense Englishmen 
 from their allegiance to Queen Elizabeth, and every Jesuit, during a 
 cousidex-able period, might be reasonably alleged to belong to an 
 association which taught the rightness and the duty even of assassi- 
 nating " tyrants " who had been recognised as such by the Pope. 
 Now no one can argue that polygamy, however detestable, is a 
 political or social danger of the same kind as rebellion and assassina- 
 tion ; and yet the merely belonging to an association that teaches or 
 encourages the practice of polygamy as a religious duty renders a 
 citizen of the United States in this Territory of Idaho liable to a loss 
 of political rights. This kind of " persecution '' is indeed but the 
 first step in the persecutors' ladder, which Hallam has described ; 
 but, as I do not believe that even the Supreme Court of the United 
 States is infallible, I cannot see how such a test oath is to be recon- 
 ciled with the decision that " Congress was deprived by the Consti- 
 tution of all legislative power over mere opinion" (Reynolds v. U.S.). 
 I have said elsewhere that the most valuable right of a minority is 
 the right to turn itself into a majority if it can : and I have found 
 myself criticised on the ground that this concedes too much power to 
 majorities. But the right of a minority to turn itself into a majority 
 implies the right to free expression of opinion (within the limits of 
 decency) and the right of association for the purpose of propagating 
 opinion (limited by respect for the rights of others). So far as I under- 
 stand the matter, compulsory vaccination is a most valuable measure, 
 and it seems to me quite right that those who fail to have their children 
 vaccinated should be subject to penalties : but that Anti-vaccinators 
 should be deprived of their votes simply because they belong to an 
 association which teaches and encourages its members to break the 
 law of the land would be an excessive interference with the right 
 of a minority to agitate in a constitutional way. I admit that the 
 teaching or encouraging of such crimes as murder may be very 
 properly punished, if it can be done ; but the punishment should be 
 
 ' Davis V. Beason. Observe the individual himself need not have 
 taught or encouraged the practice of polygamy. The Test is clearly in- 
 tended to exclude the whole sect of Mormons an such.
 
 CH. VI if] toleration 209 
 
 a direct punishment of every individual teaching or encouraging the 
 crime, and not the roundabout method of depriving every one of his 
 vote who does not abjure the membership of Anarchist societies. 
 Such test oaths, though the mildest, are one of the least expedient 
 forms of persecution : they cause irritation without being effectual 
 in doing anything else than making constitutional agitation difficult. 
 They provoke hypocrisy and encourage perjury. It is possible, how- 
 ever, that such legislation as the Edmunds-Tucker Law and the Idaho 
 Test Oath may seem to be effectual (with the help of the Pacific 
 railroad) in destroying those parts of Mormonism to which the majority 
 of people in America object. But to the observer from without it 
 does seem that the institutions objected to might have been attacked 
 in a manner more compatible with the constitutional guarantee of 
 religious liberty. Religious liberty may be thought a good thing or a 
 bad thing; but it is a hypocritical pretence to say you concede religious 
 liberty and yet insist that what ?/o?«. do not call "religion" is not 
 religion, or that people who approve of what you disapprove of can- 
 not possibly be sincere and conscientious. Religious liberty, whether 
 a good thing or a bad thing, means something very different from a 
 general disestablishment of Churches. 
 
 N. R.
 
 CHAPTER IX 
 
 THE RIGHTS OF PUBLIC MEETING AND ASSOCIATION 
 
 I HAVE treated the subject of toleration and liberty of opinion 
 at considerable length, as a convenient method of getting at 
 some of the principles by which the rights of individuals must 
 be determined. Other aspects of the alleged natural right of 
 liberty may be treated more briefly. A general and unquali- 
 fied liberty of action has never been claimed by any sane or 
 reasonable person. The mere possibility of social existence in- 
 volves some check upon the liberty of each individual ; and, 
 although amiable anarchists may dream of a society in which 
 every one would respect the claims of every one else, without 
 any force, even in the remotest background, to guarantee those 
 claims, and without any body of pei'sons expressly empowered 
 to decide on the merits of rival claims and having the regulated 
 force of the society to back up its decisions, it is clear to all 
 those who have learnt anything from a study of history, or 
 even from a slight reflection on human nature, that without 
 some such available compulsion in the last resort no society 
 can permanently hold together. The less that force needs to 
 be used to compel order, the better on the whole is the condi- 
 tion of the society ; but force is not useless in social matters 
 simply because it does not always need to be used. 
 
 There are certain particular liberties of action, which are 
 often enumerated as distinct " rights " in popular language 
 and in formal " Declarations." One of these is what we are 
 accustomed to call " the right of public meeting." In the 
 Declaration of Rights of 1793, " the right of assembling peace- 
 ably " is mentioned along with the right of free expression 
 of opinion. This right of assembling is not expressly named 
 in the Declaration of 1789, but in the Constitution of 1791, 
 Titre i., among the " natural and civil rights," the Constitution 
 guarantees to the citizens " the liberty of assembling themselves 
 peaceably and without arms, provided that they satisfy the
 
 CH. ixj PUBLIC MEETING AND ASSOCIATION 211 
 
 police laws " — limitations obviously capable of a very stringent 
 interpretation. The Constitution for the year III. (1795) is, as 
 might be expected, less favourable to the right of public meet- 
 ing than that of 1793. In Titt'e xiv. § 365, it is laid down 
 that " every armed mob {attroupement) is an attack on the con- 
 stitution and ought to be immediately dispersed by force " ; 
 while the following section provides " that every mob without 
 arms should be equally dispersed, at first by w^ay of verbal 
 command, and, if it is necessary, by the use (developpement) of 
 armed force." I assume that the executive under this consti- 
 tution reserves to itself the definition of what constitutes an 
 " attroupementy 
 
 The Belgian Constitution may be taken as a fair specimen 
 of a more modern constitution, which expressly guarantees a 
 right of public meeting under certain restrictions. Its nine- 
 teenth article is as follows : " The Belgians have the right of 
 assembling peaceably and without arms, on condition of con- 
 forming to the laws which may regulate the exercise of this 
 right, but without having to obtain previous permission. This 
 rule does not apply to meetings in the open air, which remain 
 entirely subjected to the police laws." ^ 
 
 This provision in the Belgian Constitution was probablj' 
 intended, as Professor Dicey suggests, to secure in the main 
 the same liberty of public meeting, which by 1831 at least 
 might be regarded as being recognised in this country. Perhaps 
 we should rather say — which had come de facto to establish 
 itself in this country ; for, while on the one hand our law 
 makes no distinction between meetings indoors and meetings 
 out of doors, there exists, by the law of the land, no such thing 
 as a right of public meeting at all. "No better instance,"' 
 says Professor Dicey, " can indeed be found of the way in 
 which in England the constitution is built up upon individual 
 rights than our rules as to public assemblies. The right 
 of assembling is nothing more than the result of the view 
 taken by the Courts as to individual liberty of person and in- 
 
 ^ " Les Belyes ont le droit de s'asHembler jKiisiblement et sans annes, 
 en se conformant aiix lois qui peuvent re(jler Vexercice de ce droit, sa)is 
 neanvioins le soumettre a une autorisation prealable. Cette disposition 
 ne s'applique point aux rassemblements en plei7i air, qui restent entierc- 
 ment soumis aux lois de police." (Quoted by Dice}', Law of the Constitu- 
 tion, Ed. 3, p. 254.)
 
 212 
 
 THE RIGHTS OF [ch. ix 
 
 dividual liberty of speech. There is no special law allowing 
 A, B and C to meet together either in the open air or else- 
 where for a lawful purpose, but the right of A to go where he 
 pleases so that he does not commit a trespass, and to say what 
 he likes to B, so that his talk is not libellous or seditious, the 
 right of B to do the like, and the existence of the same rights 
 of C, D, E and F, and so on ad infinitimi^ leads to the con- 
 sequence that A, B, C, D and a thousand or ten thousand other 
 persons may (as a general rule) meet together in any place 
 where otherwise they each have a right to be for a lawful pur- 
 pose and in a lawful manner." ^ 
 
 Now to ordinary common sense a meeting of a thousand, 
 or of two or three thousand, persons for a definite and common 
 purpose is a different fact from an accidental walking and 
 accidental talking of A, B, C, D, etc., as separate individuals. 
 The individualist logic, which is taken for granted in our 
 popular philosophy, may indeed look on even permanent 
 societies as mere aggregates of the individuals who compose 
 them, and think that the properties of the society can be arrived 
 at by a summation of the properties of the individuals. But 
 ordinary common sense, unsophisticated by popular philosophy 
 (which is a xery different thing from ordinary common sense), 
 can easily see the difference between even a temporary " meet- 
 ing " and a mere addition of units. If any one were to say that 
 he happened to be taking a walk in Hj'de Park one day, and 
 that several hundreds of people all happened to be taking a 
 walk four-abreast in the same direction, and that when they 
 came to a certain spot, where there happened to be a platform, 
 first one person, then another, and then more stood up on the 
 platform, and they all happened to make some remarks, in 
 rather a loud voice, to the other people, and they all happened 
 to make remarks of much the same kind and about much the 
 same subject — we should probably regard such a narrative as a 
 feeble attempt at humour.^ But this abstract view of the 
 facts has sufficed hitherto for English lawyers. 
 
 No doubt in this, as in other matters, it has been advanta- 
 geous for the growth of democracy in England, that the 
 
 ' Law of the Constitution, Ed. 3, p. 255. 
 
 " A great deal of humour, especially the humour of the professional 
 humourist, consists in abstracting certain aspects of events from their 
 context, just as caricature in drawing consists in taking certain features
 
 CH. ix] PUBLIC MEETING AND ASSOCIATION 213 
 
 rights of citizens as sucli were not laid down at too early a 
 date ; but it may perhaps be questioned whether the interests 
 of orderly progress are at present best served by this legal 
 ignoring of political facts. On the one hand this habit of 
 regarding a multitude as simply a sum of individuals helps 
 to give countenance to the rather widely spread notion that 
 there is a sort of unlimited right of making processions and hold- 
 ing meetings. A may walk down this street as well as anybody 
 else ; B may walk down this street as well as anybody else ; 
 and so of C, D, E, etc. Therefore A + B + C + D + etc., may go 
 in procession down this street, when it comes into their joint 
 heads to do so, and the authorities who prevent the procession 
 are interfering with a just and indefeasible right of free Eng- 
 lishmen. In practice the organisers of processions generally 
 recognise a reasonable limitation of their rights by giving suffi- 
 cient notice of their intention to the police, and consulting with 
 them about the route least likely to cause inconvenience to the 
 rest of the community. But would there not be some gain in 
 making the organisers of processions or meetings more definitely 
 and legally responsible for their orderliness ? There would then 
 be better security taken against the presence of those disorderly 
 aud ruffianly followers, who have so often brought reasonable 
 and peaceable "agitation" into undeserved discredit. There 
 can obviously be no general right of going in processions or 
 holding meetings at all times and in all places, even if proces- 
 sion and meeting be quite orderly. Even those persons who do 
 not want to make processions or to go to meetings have some 
 " rights " in the public streets and open spaces. On the other 
 hand, the great value of public meetings as expressions, though 
 of a very vague and unsatisfactory kind, of the opinions of 
 certain sections of the community, and still more their great 
 value as safety-valves of feeling which becomes dangerous 
 when pent up, make it very important that no unnecessary 
 obstacles should be thrown in their way, and that no pretext 
 should be given for the supposition that one set of opinions 
 is favoured by the police authorities, while another set is 
 
 and exaggerating tliem to the neglect of the otlicrs. Tliis " abstraction " 
 might be illustrated b3^ the story of a man wlio was asked Iiow his father 
 died, and answered, " He was engaged in serious conversation with a 
 clergj'inan, when some boards in a platform gave wa^-, and he broke his 
 jieck while falling through."
 
 2 14 THE RIGHTS OF [ch. ix 
 
 frowned on. Provided that incitements to violence are avoided 
 and a certain decency of language observed, it is generally 
 wise to allow any kind of views to be promulgated, and it 
 would be well if every town and village had its public hall or, 
 failing that, its open space, where all sorts of meetings might 
 be held, provided of course that no one party be allowed to 
 monopolise the use of public property. It is moreover a 
 useful part of a citizen's education to be able to hear the most 
 divergent opinions propounded without a breaking of heads, 
 either by the mutual efforts of the audience or by the guard- 
 ians of the public peace. 
 
 The liberty of association may be regarded as a mere 
 application of the right of public meeting ; an association of 
 individuals for any special purpose may be thought of as a 
 public meeting, which is never dissolved, but only adjourned. 
 But an association means more than that ; for the body as a 
 whole, by its constitution, comes to acquire definite " rights " 
 over the individuals composing it, in a way to which a public 
 meeting only approximates. An individual who attends a 
 public meeting does indeed thereby become, to some extent, sub- 
 ject to the control of the assemblage as a whole, or of its effective 
 majority, or of those who can control the majority. His right 
 of absolute freedom of speech and action is, for instance, limited 
 far more than it would be were he not present at the meeting. 
 If he makes certain remarks which he might, perhaps, have 
 been allowed to make at his own fireside, or even while walk- 
 ing along a public street, he may incur the risk of being put 
 out of the meeting with necessary or superfluous force, every 
 one recognising the " natural right " of public meetings to 
 maintain such order and harmony as may be necessary for 
 their existence as meetings for hearing speeches or discussions. 
 But the control which an association exercises over the indi- 
 viduals belonging to it is of a wider kind, and of a much more 
 definite kind. As a rule, an individual in joining a more or 
 less permanent association is told something, at least, of the 
 laws and regulations of the association to which he thus be- 
 comes subject ; membership of other associations than the 
 State is generally supposed to be, and is certainly spoken of 
 as if it were, " voluntary," whereas membership of the State 
 is supposed to be " compulsory." The distinction, however, is
 
 CH. ix] PUBLIC MEETING AND ASSOCIATION 215 
 
 not quite so clear and rigid as is often thought. The obvious 
 difference between the State and what is called a voluntary 
 association is, that the State can exercise regulated force in 
 inflicting penalties for disobedience to its commands, whereas 
 a voluntary association is either restricted to the exercise of 
 " moral compulsion," or can only enforce its penalties by mak- 
 ing use of the legal machinery which the State itself provides. 
 The distinction, as thus formulated, does on the whole exist 
 between the modern State in all orderly societies, and the 
 greater number of what are called voluntary associations. But 
 the weak States of the middle ages had frequently very much 
 less power of enforcing their commands than was possessed by 
 the Church (which would now-a-days be called a " voluntary 
 association," because it is not the State) in those daj^s when the 
 supernatural and other-worldly penalties of the Church exer- 
 cised a stronger influence over the mass of people, homogeneous 
 in their beliefs, than the irregularly enforced penalties of the 
 temporal power. At different times and in different places 
 there has been a difference in value between hanging and damn- 
 ing as penalties for the violation of commands or precepts ; 
 though, as a rule, the Church, when exercising an effective 
 control over consciences, has also been able and willing to use 
 the secular arm to back up the ghostly terrors which are her 
 own proper weapon. Even if we consider only those times in 
 which the State is strong and can ensure the systematic enforce- 
 ment of the penalties it threatens, it should be recognised that 
 there is no absolute difference, so far as concerns the effect on 
 the individual's motives, between the pressure of the State 
 and the pressure of other associations. If disobedience to the 
 commands of some powerful association means an effective ex- 
 communication, or "boycott," or practical deprivation of the 
 means of obtaining a living, the individual's free choice may 
 be as much limited as by the knowledge that disobedience to 
 the commands of the State will involve death or imprisonment. 
 The fear of starvation for oneself and those dependent on one 
 may be as strong a motive as the fear of the law of the land. 
 Moreover, the belonging, or ceasing to belong, to a "voluntary" 
 association may be as little voluntary as the belonging, or 
 ceasing to belong, to a particular State. In the societies of the 
 ancient world, it is true, citizenship came mostly by birth, and 
 could only be obtained exceptionally, and as a special favour,
 
 2i6 THE RIGHTS OF [ch. ix 
 
 by an outsider. But in the modern world, to a considerable 
 extent, citizenship depends on the will of the individual. 
 Thus it is more easy for an able-bodied person, or a person 
 with sutlicient personal property, to exchange a country and a 
 nationality, that he finds disagreeable, for one more to his 
 liking, than it is for a barrister or a doctor, who is dependent 
 on his earnings, to violate the etiquette of his profession. 
 Again, a great many persons are born into, or brought up 
 into (if we may say so), a " voluntary " association, or are 
 made to feel it necessary to join one. Most persons are " born " 
 in this or that religious body, quite as much as they are born 
 of this or that nationality. To belong to a trade-union may 
 be an almost indispensable condition of obtaining a living by 
 the occupation to which one has been brought up. It may 
 need a strength of will and power of defying the opinion of 
 one's neighbour, very much above the average, to refuse to 
 pay certain " voluntary " subscriptions. 
 
 This ultimate similarity between the State and other as- 
 sociations is overlooked in that very naive proposal of certain 
 " Individualists " to make taxation voluntary. I shall not 
 discuss the spectacle of a First Lord of the Admiralty sending 
 the hat round (a cocked hat, I suppose it would be — very 
 soon, if not at the outset), with a polite request : " Your con- 
 tributions are respectfully solicited for the maintenance of the 
 British Navy." Of course such an idea is not necessarily 
 absurd, though it belongs to a stage of society which in some 
 matters has become unfamiliar to us. It is only custom that 
 makes us see no incongruity in keeping up lighthouses at the 
 public expense, while lifeboats are dependent on private sub- 
 scriptions, or in keeping up poorhouses out of the rates, while 
 hospitals are private charities ; in many such matters we pro- 
 gress only by degrees from the voluntary, i.e. the haphazard, 
 to the political, i.e. the more systematic method of meet- 
 ing general needs. But let me leave the question of external 
 defences out of sight. Suppose a model town on the voluntary 
 system. Instead of a police force maintained out of the rates, 
 we should have a private association maintained by voluntary 
 subscriptions for the defence of person and property. Possibly 
 some of the wealthier inhabitants might not care to join, but 
 would provide their own staff of guards, and protect their 
 houses or factories or shops in the good old fashion of the
 
 CH. ix] PUBLIC MEETING AND ASS0CL4TI0N 217 
 
 mediasval baron. Humbler persons would have to combine, 
 as they could each only afford the expense of a fraction of a 
 six-foot policeman. Now suppose that a certain citizen, in the 
 full exercise of the freedom he enjoys under this reign of 
 libert}^, refuses to subscribe to the defence-fund, his name 
 would be conspicuously absent from the subscription list, and 
 of this absence the burgling profession would keep itself in- 
 formed. To most people subscriptions of this sort would only 
 differ in name from rates and taxes, and might be even more 
 troublesome and vexatious. The tax-gatherer is an unpopular 
 person ; but the blackmailer would be a greater nuisance. 
 
 The State differs from other associations in having the 
 common good professedly as its end, and therefore — (1) in not 
 being limited a priori to certain particular aspects of life,^ and 
 (2) in including all the inhabitants (except resident aliens) of 
 the national territory, in some sense or other, in its member- 
 ship. If we hold that the liberty of individuals in any real 
 and positive sense ^ is one of the principal objects which the 
 State ought to secure, then it is indispensable that the State 
 should claim the right of interfering, where necessary, with 
 the actions of voluntary associations. To concede a general 
 " liberty of association " is to turn the liberty of the individual 
 into a mere empty and meaningless form. The progress of 
 individual liberty, in any real and positive sense, has meant to 
 a great extent the emancipation of the individual from the 
 absolute control of various associations, natural and artificial, 
 against which the individual in many cases needs to be pro- 
 tected by the State. The family, the Church, the joint-stock 
 company, the trade-union, the political club are all " associa- 
 tions," whose " liberties " often conflict with those of one 
 another, and with the liberty of individuals who are and who 
 are not their members. The abolition of slavery, and the 
 legislative protection of children and of wives, are interferences 
 with " the family " as that used to be understood. If heads 
 of households are no longer allowed the same control over other 
 members of the household which they exercised when the 
 
 * My meaning is that, prior to discussion and to an investigation of 
 the teachings of experience, we must not assume (a) that the State ought 
 only to concern itself with certain matters, nor (6) that it ought to concern 
 itself with all ; for experience may show that some matters cannot con- 
 veniently be dealt with by any State, or by this or that particular State. 
 
 - See above, pp. 138, 139.
 
 2i8 THE RIGHTS OF [ch. ix 
 
 family was itself a little State — a State in germ — tlie in- 
 dependence of the family has certainly been diminished, but 
 in the interest of the liberty of individuals. Compulsory 
 education, compulsory vaccination, compulsory notification of 
 infectious diseases, etc., are infringements of the independence 
 of the family, but in the interest of the liberty — the real, 
 positive liberty — of the individuals who belong to the family, 
 and of others. If an individual has a certain minimum of 
 education and of protection from gross neglect and from 
 infectious disease secured to him, he is to that extent more 
 "free" to make what he can of his natural powers and of his 
 opportunities, than if he is entirely at the mercy of ignorant 
 parents, and of dirty, diseased, or fanatical neighbours. 
 
 The " liberty of the Church " has in past times meant that 
 churches, i.e. those in authority in them, have had a free hand 
 to rule over individuals as they chose. Such liberties restrict the 
 freedom of individuals in many ways, notably in respect of the 
 free expression of opinion, and in respect of such matters as 
 marriage and divorce. There is, however, an obvious differ- 
 ence between " the liberty of the Church," i.e. the power of 
 one great international organisation, whose system of ecclesias- 
 tical discipline is supported here and there by the organised 
 force of States, and the tolerated existence of what are called 
 different denominations, i.e. religious associations which do not 
 claim, or have been practically obliged to give up the claim, to 
 dictate directly the policy of the State in any matter. Such 
 associations may, of course, influence their own members and 
 others to use their rights as citizens in such a way as to further 
 the religious interests and the opinions of a particular sect in 
 matters of education, of prohibition of work and amusement 
 on certain days, and of various other legislative interferences 
 with the liberties of individuals in the interests, or supposed 
 interests, of morality ;^ but such political influence of religious 
 
 * Those who argue against establislied cliurches on the ground that 
 the Christian religion should never be supported bj^ the force of the 
 State are guilty of inconsistency, if they support the prohibition, e.g. of 
 trade or of theatrical performances on Sundays. Such prohibitions do 
 mean the State-establishment of Puritanic Christianit}^, and are an 
 infringement of the religious liberty of Jews, wlio observe their Sabbath 
 without State-help, and likewise of all non-Sabbatarians, whether 
 Christians or not. To provide by law that every one should have one 
 lioliday in every seven, or any other number of, days, without specifying 
 
 SA
 
 CH. ix] PUBLIC MEETING AND ASSOCIATION 219 
 
 bodies is of the same kind with the political influence of pro- 
 fessedly political clubs, and of other associations for organising 
 and controlling the votes of electors. I do not think it can be 
 laid down absolutely that the State ought never in any way to 
 interfere with " free churches," any more than that it ought 
 never to interfere with political clubs or humanitarian societies. 
 A charitable institution, for instance, might conceivably fill a 
 district with semi-criminal, semi-lunatic paupers, to the injury 
 of the community as a whole ; a so-called political club might 
 become a gang of conspirators to promote assassination ; and a 
 church might use an assumed power of inflicting supernatural 
 penalties in such a way as dangerously to control the political 
 and civil liberty of its members.^ No political society can 
 safely recognise any absolute right of private association among 
 its members ; for such private associations may conceivably 
 grow into what are practically separate States waging war, 
 from a vantage-ground, against the national existence. It is 
 in this as in the general question of toleration : time, and 
 place, and experience of the past must decide what is best to 
 be done. "What will actually in any case be done will depend 
 mainly on the extent to which those, who happen to exercise 
 effective sovereignty, fear disturbance, or feel strong enough to 
 concede the toleration of contempt, or confident enough in the 
 general reasonableness of their fellow-citizens to recognise the 
 edi>cative value of diverse associations for the promotion of 
 different and conflicting kinds of restraints on individual 
 liberty. 
 
 The name " Free Church," as already indicated," is an inter- 
 esting example of the ambiguities and contradictory suggestions 
 
 the day, would be a different matter, and would be the onl3^ consistent 
 course for those persons (probably very few in number) who really dis- 
 approve of all State-establishment and State-enforcement of any religion 
 whatever. The endowmeiit of churches is a separate question from tlie 
 establishment of religion. But those who would take ancient endow- 
 ments from churches, and use them for the support of schools, in which 
 religious doctrines of any kind are taught, are using the power of the 
 State to endow a certain kind of religion. 
 
 ' To refuse to give legal recognition to religious vows {French Consti- 
 tution of 1791) is to interfere with complete liberty of association, as well 
 as indirectly with complete freedom of contract ; monks or nuns who 
 repent of their vows will be protected against the associations to which 
 they have bound themselves. 
 
 ^ See above, p. 138.
 
 2 20 THE RIGHTS OF [ch. ix 
 
 ill the word "free." In its most famous liistorical use, as the 
 official designation of the vigorous, militant, and in many ways 
 heroic religious body which originated in the Scottish Ecclesi- 
 astical Disruption of 1843, it represented a renewal of the same 
 claim which is asserted in the phrase " liberty of the Church," 
 — a claim to be supported by the State, without recognising 
 any mutual obligation on the part of the ecclesiastical power 
 to obey the State, except in those matters which the ecclesias- 
 tical power itself decides to be the concern of the civil power. 
 It represented a renewal of the claim of the older Puritans, 
 not to be " tolerated," but to dictate directly to the State as 
 to what might be tolerated, and what might not.^ Such 
 proud assertions tend to become meaningless when they are 
 made by a body which finds itself a minority of the population, 
 and by a body, however important, of dissenters, dissenting 
 from other dissenters. And so in course of time " free church," 
 and even " Free " with a capital, may come to connote nothing 
 more than absence of direct connection with the State. In 
 French-speaking Protestant Switzerland, where there is a 
 tendency to that multiplication of sects which is often sup- 
 posed to be a special characteristic of the English-speaking 
 peoples, there is a considerable religious body known as the 
 "Free" Church. It "sprang," says Mr, Vincent, in his 
 valuable work on i^tate and Federal Government in Switzer- 
 land^ " from an endeavour to gain freedom from State inter- 
 ference, and at the same time to maintain a stricter confession 
 of faith. It was, in reality, a protest within the Protestant 
 Church, and in Geneva and Vaud goes back to the time of the 
 abolition of the Helvetic Confession. In Neuchatel it was a re- 
 sult of the ecclesiastical law of 1873, which made every citizen, 
 ipso facto^ a member of the Church, and abolished all theological 
 tests for ministers." - In Neuchatel and Geneva the liberty 
 of the conscience of the minister is declared inviolable by the 
 constitution,^ and against this liberty the " Free " Church is a 
 
 * HnW&m, Const. Hist. ^. 142 (" World Library " edition), has pointed 
 out the striking resemblance between the demand of Cartwright, that the 
 civil magistrate should, "as the prophet speaketh, lick the dust of the feet 
 of the cliurch," and the ecclesiastical theory of Pope Gregory' \ll. The 
 original position of the Scotch "Free Church" has been similaidy de- 
 scribed by its critics as that of Protestant Ultramontanism (with an in- 
 teresting oblivion of the original sense of the latter word). 
 ^ 2 ii)ia.^ p. 176. 3 iii^i^ p_ 130.
 
 CH. ix] PUBLIC MEETING AND ASSOCIATION 221 
 
 protest. A similar dislike to the liberty of the conscience of 
 the minister may, occasionally, be found as a motive in the 
 making and continuance of " free " churches elsewhere than in 
 Switzerland. 
 
 Commercial companies have generally grown up to some 
 extent under the protection of the State. Great trading or 
 industrial enterprises, as a rule, require the interference of the 
 State on their behalf, e.g. in order to enforce contracts, to 
 secure protection in foreign countries, to obtain compulsory 
 power of purchase of land, etc. ; and the State has thus an 
 easy means of restricting the liberty of companies, in return 
 for the advantages it confers on them. As has been generally 
 recognised, there is a much stronger case for the State to inter- 
 fere on behalf of employees with the " liberty " of companies 
 on which it has conferred special privileges, than with the 
 " liberty " of private individuals whose commercial or indus- 
 trial enterprises are not aided by the State in any special way. 
 The right of the State to regulate the hours of railway servants 
 — apart from reasons of public safety — has been recognised by 
 those who still feel doubtful about the expediency or justice of 
 any general attempt to fix a maximum working-day by law. 
 In protecting shareholders against fraud or culpable neglect on 
 the part of directors and promoters, in protecting the general 
 public against the tyranny of companies which have, whether 
 by law or by the operation of economic causes, a monopoly in 
 the supply of any particular commodity or service, and in 
 bringing under more direct State-control, or even under 
 immediate State management (I include administration by 
 municipalities or other local bodies invested with power by 
 the Central Government), enterprises which it has become 
 sufficiently convenient for the State to undertake — in such ex- 
 tensions of State control over joint-enterprises, for the sake of 
 individual liberty, and in the interests of the general well- 
 being, lies much work for political energy in the immediate 
 future. 
 
 Trade-Unions have fought their way through persecution 
 to toleration. From an evil to be suppressed, they have 
 become, in the eyes of politicians, a necessary evil, or even a 
 beneficial institution. As benefit societies, as teachers of a 
 spirit of co-operation, however limited and narrow, their value is 
 generally admitted. Even as instruments of industrial war-
 
 22 2 THE RIGHTS OF [ch. ix 
 
 fare, their advantages are widely acknowledged; it is always 
 easier to deal with an organised body of men than with an 
 unorganised mass. Trade-unionism, still, means warfare ; but 
 it is the civilised warfare of disciplined armies, not of irregulars, 
 banditti, or savages. But what of the attitude of the militant 
 Unionist towards the " free labourer " ? The State has the 
 obvious duty of protecting even those whom the Unionist calls 
 " blacklegs " against anything like physical compulsion on the 
 part of the Unionist — by the use of military force where neces- 
 sary. Unless or until Trade-Unions have become absorbed by 
 government departments (in which case a strike would be 
 punishable as a mutiny by military law), the Trade-Unionist 
 can make no legitimate claim to use any weapon but persuasion 
 against the non-Unionist ; and if it is in the public interest 
 that some particular industry should be carried on, the State 
 has the duty imposed upon it of protecting by all the necessary 
 force those engaged in carrying on that industry against the 
 interference of Unionist strikers. If the State cannot success- 
 fully protect individuals against any Union or combination of 
 Unions, regular government has broken down, and the country 
 is at the mercy of a revolutionary usurpation, ruling by 
 terrorism. In any given case, one may sympathise with the 
 Unionist striker, or with the " blackleg " ; but, as I have said, 
 so long as the Unions are not directly responsible to national 
 control, the State as such is bound to be impartial. The as- 
 sumption, too readily sanctioned even by some responsible 
 statesmen, that military force is not justifiably used in repress- 
 ino; cUsordei' is an unfortunate inheritance from the time when 
 military force was freely used by despotical governments to 
 prevent the free expression of opinion. 
 
 Some Trade-Unionists seem to take for granted that because 
 Trade-Unions have undoubtedly improved the conditions of 
 life, and raised the standard of living among a large portion of 
 the population, an extension of Unionism, and a greater sup- 
 port of Unions in case of strikes by public opinion, constitute 
 the true or, at least, the chief solution of our economic and social 
 difficulties. There is this fatal objection to such an idea: — 
 A Trade-Union must either include all the workers of a given 
 trade, or only some ; and all the Trade-Unions of the country 
 must either include all the workers or only some. At present
 
 CH. ix] PUBLIC MEETING AND ASSOCIATION 223 
 
 the unions exclude a great number of the workers/ and it is 
 against these excluded workmen far more than against the em- 
 ployers that the struggle in a strike or lock-out is really carried 
 on. By using persuasion (accompanied or not by threats of 
 violence) towards non-unionists, or by refusing to work along 
 with them, unionists seek to compel employers to accept their 
 terms, i.e. they artificially produce the same effect as would be 
 produced by the death or emigration of the workmen competing 
 with them for employment. It is true that in such struggles 
 it is " the fittest " (in the biologist's sense) who survive, and in 
 this case " the fittest " generally means those who have most 
 skill and most steadiness of character, though not necessarily 
 so in every instance. The effect of a successful strike for 
 higher and steadier wages is often to supplant a larger body 
 of irregularly employed and unorganised workmen by a smaller 
 body, more regularly employed. The diminution of casual 
 employment is undoubtedly a gain in many ways, but it in- 
 creases the number of the unemployed. Suppose, on the other 
 hand, that the unions include all the workers in all the indus- 
 tries of a country — I pass over the obvious difficulty of un- 
 employed and casual labourers paying their subscriptions 
 regularly — and that the unions are federated together into one 
 vast industrial association, it will follow that, for many pur- 
 poses, such an industrial association will have become practically 
 the State itself. But this association will acquire the responsi- 
 bilities along with the advantages of the State. Is every one 
 born in the country (even if foreign immigrants are rigorously 
 excluded) to be, by the mere fact of his existence, entitled to 
 have work and subsistence found for him, however incapable 
 he may be ? A continually increasing population does increase 
 to some extent the demand for commodities, but will, in course 
 of time, press more heavily on the resources of the country. 
 And if immigrants are excluded, other countries will probably 
 
 ^ According to the best calculations, the Trade-Unionists of England 
 and Wales number only 20 per cent, of the adult male manual-working 
 population, only 4 per cent, of the total population. Even in the excep- 
 tional counties of Nortlunnberland and Durham, where Trade-Unionism 
 flourishes most, the Trade-Unionists number only 11-2;) and 11-21 percent, 
 of the population, whereas adult male manual-workers are reckoned at 
 18 per cent, of the population: so that even there more than one-third 
 of the working men are non-unionists (see Mr. and Mrs. Sidney Webb's 
 History of Trade- Unionism, pp. 409-413).
 
 2 24 THE RIGHTS OF [ch. ix 
 
 retaliate and prevent the relief hitherto obtained by emigra- 
 tion. The Industrial Federation of united unions will thus be 
 face to face with the population difficulty, but such an Indus- 
 trial Federation will not be able to deal with that difficulty, 
 nor with any of the problems of production and distribution 
 that will arise, unless it ceases to be a mere congeries of " volun- 
 tary " associations, and becomes openly a State able to enforce 
 and maintain a rigid discij)line and a sacrifice of individual 
 aims and likings, such as hitherto has only existed in the army 
 and the navy, and in some of the strictest of monastic orders. 
 
 Very many Trade-Unionists do not yet sufficiently recognise 
 that the ultimate outcome of their policy is a Socialistic State ; 
 and I doubt if any of them recognise at all the absolute neces- 
 sity for a very severe discipline in the industrial armies of the 
 future. Such a transformation of Trade-Unions from associa- 
 tions of particular groups of producers into a highly organised 
 State is, however, not likely to take place by a one-sided develop- 
 ment. If on the one side Trade-Unions approximate more to the 
 conditions of political organisations, with responsibilities to the 
 common good of all, on the other side the State will probably 
 meet them half-way. If a social re-organisation is to take 
 place without violence, and in such a way as to be fairly 
 stable, it must come about gradually ; a sudden change would 
 probably mean gross mismanagement, corruption, disorder — 
 possibly civil war, and a terrible reaction. The State which is 
 to undertake responsibilities such as no State has yet attempted 
 to undertake, must be free from jobbery or the suspicion of 
 jobbery, and its citizens must possess sufficient enlightenment 
 and a sufficient spirit of obedience for the sake of the common 
 good to subordinate personal or sectional ambitions and pre- 
 ferences to the decision of experts — responsible indeed to the 
 community, but allowed a tolerably free hand, like generals 
 in command of an army in the field. Trade-Unionism, with 
 all its defects, its narrowness of outlook and disregard for 
 interests outside the material well-being of special sections of 
 producers as such, does supply part, though a small part, of 
 the necessary training in obedience and discipline which alone 
 can make anything like a Socialistic State possible. 
 
 It is a delusion to suppose that shorter hours, whether ob- 
 tained by the efforts of Trade-Unions, or by legislation, or by 
 a combination of both means, will lead to a solution of the diffi-
 
 CH. ix] PUBLIC MEETING AND ASSOCIATION 225 
 
 culty of the unemployed. Higher wages and shorter hours — 
 if the wages are to be reaUy higher, i.e. capable of purchasing 
 more commodities — will lead to the use of more machinery, 
 and not, directly at least, to the employment of more men ; 
 and a greater demand for machinery can only to a small ex- 
 tent, if at all, increase the demand for labour. The present 
 system of Trade-Unions supplemented by legislative restric- 
 tion of hours of labour cannot do away with the difficulty of 
 obtaining employment, but may even increase it. But though 
 not solving the problem, Trade-Unionism may help to put it 
 in a form more capable of solution. Anything that diminishes 
 casual and irregular employment makes the class of the unem- 
 ployed a more definite body, with which the State may more 
 easily hope to deal ; and the more sharply defined line between 
 the more capable and the more incapable portion of the popu- 
 lation may prepare public opinion for those stringent, though 
 beneficent, measures by which alone the pauper class can be 
 prevented from injuring the more vigorous section of the race. 
 If subsistence is to be guaranteed by the State to all its 
 members, the unemployed must, if capable of it, be set to work ; 
 but this work must not compete in the labour market with 
 that of those already in employment, else the suffering is only 
 shifted from one set of individuals to another. The unem- 
 ployed, if cared for by the State, must be treated as, for indus- 
 trial purposes, a separate and isolated community, whose more 
 capable members may, when occasion arises, be drafted into 
 the ranks of the regular and organised workers : ^ and, as 
 already argued, there must be some check on the increase of 
 the population by State-pensioners. If sach powers of control 
 are refused to the State by the moral sentiments or prejudices 
 of the community, the State may reasonably refuse to deal with 
 these economic difficulties. 
 
 I have ventured to refer thus briefly to one of the most 
 difficult of social questions — what is very often called the social 
 
 Cf. Charles Booth, Life and Labour of the Peoj^le, Ed. 2, Vol. I. pp. 
 1G5-1G8. Mr. Booth does not shrink from uslnp; the word " State slavery" 
 as a name for the only forai in which the problem can be dealt with. 
 One thinks of Fletcher of Saltoun's proposal to dispose of paupers as 
 slaves in the " plantations and at home." See his Second Discourse on 
 the Affaira of Scotland {Works, p. 146-149, Ed. of 1737). The moral 
 objections to slavery, where slaves were private property, are not applic- 
 able to State-slavery in Mr. Booth's sense. 
 
 N. R. Q
 
 226 RIGHTS OF PUBLIC MEETING, ETC [ch. ix 
 
 question — in order to illustrate the impossibility of dealing 
 \yith " the rights of associations " without considering the 
 general question of the relation of the State to individuals ; 
 and to show how an unlimited liberty of association is incom- 
 patible with the very existence of the State. The State itself 
 is the only association whose liberty cannot be limited by the 
 State. 
 
 :iS
 
 CHAPTER X 
 
 FREEDOM OF CONTRACT ; NATIONAL FREEDOM, ETC 
 
 One of the most important rights of individuals is generally 
 supposed to be the right to enter into contracts with other 
 individuals, and the most important function of the State, 
 according to the theories of those who most seek to minimise 
 its functions, is supposed to be the enforcement by law courts 
 of obligations arising out of contract. The famous theory 
 which explains political obligation as dependent on the social 
 contract is, in one aspect of it, an illogical generalisation of this 
 notion about the functions of government — illogical, because 
 contracts are the product of political society, which cannot 
 therefore be based upon a contract. To try to escape this 
 argument by substituting the term social pact, or compact, for 
 the legal term contract, is a mere evasion ; for the social pact 
 is assumed to be as binding as if it were a contract that could 
 be enforced, or rather it is assumed to be much more binding 
 than any particular contract depending on it. An alleged 
 natural right of freedom of contract is meaningless, if it be im- 
 plied that a State ought to recognise a right in its members to 
 enter into contracts of every possible kind, and should undertake 
 to enforce these contracts. Such an absolute right to freedom of 
 contract would require the State to enforce an obligation to 
 commit crimes and to rebel against itself; but this is anarchical 
 and absurd. It is generally recognised, even by the staunchcst 
 upholders of the sanctity of contracts, that the State may pro- 
 hibit or refuse to recognise contracts of certain kinds. Such 
 an admission implies of course that the State exists for other 
 purposes than simply for the enforcement of contracts; it 
 implies that the State has the right of restricting individual 
 liberty in various ways, even where no contract has been 
 broken, and of discouraging certain kinds of contract by the 
 refusal of legal remedies. If the State may prohibit or dis- 
 
 227
 
 2 28 FREEDOM OF CONTRACT; [ch. x 
 
 courage certain kinds of contracts, it is admitted (though it 
 may be unconsciously) that the State has a moral function, 
 and may rightly endeavour to bias its members in favour of 
 certain kinds of conduct and against others, which is, after all, 
 the only way in which the State ever can be said to try " to 
 make people moral." 
 
 But if a State has not prohibited a contract of a certain 
 kind, may the State never by any legislative or judicial or 
 executive proceedings interfere with and impair the obligations 
 to which that contract has given rise ? If it may not, great 
 hardships may undoubtedly be inflicted on individuals, and 
 the disastrous result follows that courts of justice will be 
 obliged to enforce what public sentiment may consider to be 
 injustice ; law may come into conflict with what is approved 
 of by the average conscience of the community, and the habit 
 of respect for law and of obedience to it may be seriously 
 weakened. If, on the other hand, the State may interfere with 
 the enforcement of contract-obligations, which the State itself 
 has sanctioned, is not the feeling of security which is one of the 
 primary benefits derived from good government, and which we 
 are told is one of the natural rights of man, very seriously im- 
 paired, and a bad example of dishonesty set to the community ? 
 Now, it is obvious that to interfere with the obligation arising 
 out of a contract already made under public sanction is, on these 
 grounds of honesty and general security, a much more disput- 
 able policy than the prohibition of certain kinds of contract. 
 But an absolute respect for all contracts, not previously pro- 
 hibited, may be a sacrifice of public well-being, and even of 
 the very existence of the community, to the letter of formal 
 legality. Circumstances may have changed so that the en- 
 forcement of a contract undertaken with full deliberation and 
 on equal terms becomes a practical injustice ; or it may come 
 to be recognised that the contract, though in appearance a 
 contract freely entered into, was practically a compulsory 
 submission of the weaker to the stronger, and that its strict 
 enforcement would do more harm, not merely because of the 
 material suffering it may cause, but because of the detestation 
 of law and order which it may excite, than a departure from 
 the general rule of holding people to their legal obligations. 
 No cut and dried rule can be laid down : time, place, and cir- 
 cumstances must determine the manner and degree in which
 
 CH. x] NATIONAL FREEDOM, ETC 229 
 
 the State may wisel}'- and safely impair tlie obligation of 
 contracts. 
 
 The Constitution of the United States of America is often 
 held up as an example in contrast to recent legislation in this 
 country, because of the greater sanctity which it recognises in 
 contract obligations. Our critics, especially our American 
 critics, are perhaps apt to forget the difference of circum- 
 stances between an old country, with a very complex society 
 and a very chaos of ancient customs and institutions, on the 
 one hand, and a new country, with, until recently, free space 
 for individual enterprise — a country which made a fresh start 
 after a revolution only a little over a hundred years ago. The 
 time may come when social needs and changing ideals may 
 compel the people of the United States to impair some 
 contract obligations, which are enforced at present. And to do 
 this, they need not delete the section (Art. I. § 10) which pro- 
 hibits laws impairing the obligation of contracts : for that 
 prohibition only applies to the States. The Federal Congress 
 is not prohibited from infringing vested interests or violating 
 the obligation of contracts in regard to any of those matters 
 in which the constitution empowers it to legislate ; e.g. the 
 Federal Congress may make laws releasing debtors from their 
 obligations, whereas the States are (wisely perhaps) prohibited 
 from doing so.^ If equity or public security seemed to require 
 an infringement of legal obligation in some matter over which 
 Congress has not control {e.g. the land laws of a State), it might 
 be safer to extend the powers of Congress by an amendment to 
 the constitution in that respect, than to give State legislatures 
 too free a hand. The difficulty of amending the Federal 
 Constitution at all may, indeed, put serious delays in the way 
 of necessary legislation. 
 
 The "free labourer," who is the object of dislike to the mili- 
 tant Trade-Unionist, may be regarded as a person who asserts 
 the natural right to dispose of his labour as he chooses, i.e. 
 who demands the protection of the State in order that he may 
 have this freedom. This right of freedom in the disposal of 
 labour is expressly asserted in the French Declaration of 1793. 
 In article 18 it is provided that " Every man may engage his 
 services and his time, but he cannot sell himself, or be sold ; 
 his person is not an alienable property. The law does not 
 ^ Desty's Federal Constitution, p. 84.
 
 230 FREEDOM OF CONTRACT; [ch. x 
 
 recognise the condition of servitude {domesticife) '\: ^ while 
 personal bondage is excluded, the right of perfectly free con- 
 tract between employer and emplo^'^ed is recognised. Such a 
 principle, if strictly carried out, would of course prevent any 
 legislative interference with the hours or the conditions of 
 labour, and would certainly require the State to put a con- 
 siderable check on the freedom of Trade-Unions in boycotting 
 blacklegs, or in doing anything beyond endeavouring to per- 
 suade free labourers, by logical or rhetorical arguments, not to 
 undertake work on conditions unfavourable to themselves or to 
 other workers in the same trade. The evident purpose of this 
 and some other articles in the French Declaration was to get 
 rid of restrictions, whether due to legislation or to the custom- 
 ary privileges of guilds, etc., on the free movement of labour. 
 The ideal was " a career open to talents " — complete negative 
 liberty. This is the droit da travail; the droit au travail is 
 the positive right to get work found for one. 
 
 A subsequent article (21) in the same Declaration recognises 
 the right of citizens to subsistence in the following form : 
 "Public relief {les secours publics) i& a sacred debt. Society 
 owes subsistence to unfortunate citizens, either by procuring 
 work for them, or by assuring the means of existence to those 
 who are not capable of working." In the Jacobin draft this 
 principle is expressed in somewhat stronger language : " Society 
 is obliged to provide for the subsistence of all its members, 
 either by procuring work for them, or etc." — as before. The 
 form adopted was apparently a compromise between the Jaco- 
 bin form and the draft of Condorcet, which says nothing about 
 the procuring of work, though recognising that " Public relief 
 is a sacred debt." 
 
 In the Declaration of 1848, it is asserted (art. 8) that the 
 Republic " ought by fraternal help to assure the existence of 
 necessitous citizens, either by procuring work for them, within 
 the limits of its resources, or by giving, where the family cannot 
 (or does not?) do so [the words are a defaut de la famille\ 
 assistance to those who are incapable of working." The 
 wording is somewhat vague. What is to be done with those 
 who will not work, though able to do so ? And what is to 
 limit the power of the government to find work for the unem- 
 
 ^ Practically identical in Condorcet's draft. Cf. Lord Halsburj^'s words 
 quoted in Chai^. I. p. 15.
 
 CH. x] NATIONAL FREEDOM, ETC 231 
 
 ployed? May it increase taxation, for instance, in order to 
 provide nnremunerative work, or does " the limits of its re- 
 sources " imply that taxation should not be increased for this 
 reason alone, and that the work ought to be remunerative? 
 If the work is to be remunerative, how is competition to be 
 avoided in a market which is proved to be already overcrowded 
 by the mere existence of unemployed labourers ? 
 
 It may be necessary to repeat what has often been pointed 
 out, but is still generally ignored, that the experiment of 
 national workshops in 1848 was an experiment tried under 
 most unfair conditions and managed by persons who did not 
 wish it to succeed : the failure of this experiment is of itself 
 no argument against the State undertaking the responsibility 
 of providing work. But a careful consideration of those 
 questions, which are suggested by the cautious but ambiguous 
 wording of the Declaration, calls attention to some of the 
 difficulties involved. In the long run, we always come face to 
 face with the ultimate problem : Can a State, without the cer- 
 tain prosj^jcct of ultimate disaster, undertake to provide work 
 and a satisfactory subsistence (judged by the average standard 
 of living at present) for all its members, without taking some 
 security against an indefinite increase of population, and against 
 a disproportionate increase of the less capable part of the popu- 
 lation ? ^ 
 
 ' Charles Mackay sings : — 
 
 " There's a good time coming, boys, 
 
 A good time coming; 
 And a poor man's family 
 Shall not be his miser3^ 
 
 In the good time coming. 
 Every child shall be a help, 
 
 To make his right arm stronger ; 
 The hap2)ier he the more he has ; — 
 
 Wait a little longer." 
 
 Such a sentiment is meaningless and foolish except under the con- 
 ditions of a new and thinly peopled country. If the resource of emigra- 
 tion be largely diminished, through the filling up of new countries, and 
 through the policy dictated by the wage-receivers there, and if the right 
 of every one to subsistence and, if he can work, and will work, or has 
 worked as long as he could, to a comfortable subsistence, be legally 
 conceded, — a continuous increase in population must mean a continuous, 
 not necessarily an exactly proportionate, lowering of the standard of 
 comfort.
 
 232 FREEDOM OF CONTRACT; [ch. x 
 
 A " free coiintr}'," or a " free people," may mean that the 
 government is of a more or less democratic kind, but it may 
 only mean that the country is not under the rule of any 
 foreign power. AVordsworth lamented the extinction of the 
 Venetian Republic and the conquest of Switzerland by the 
 French ; but the Venetian Republic was a close and tyrannical 
 oligarchy, and the establishment of the Helvetian Republic by 
 the help of French arms was a liberation of the people of 
 Vaud and Ticino from the oppression of the German cantons. 
 Those Poles who have come under the sway of Russia have 
 gained nothing and lost a great deal ; but the liberty of 
 Poland meant the liberties of an aristocratic caste who showed 
 particularly little capacity for governing — to say nothing 
 about governing well. A people may often prefer to be 
 ill-governed by rulers of their own race, to whom they are 
 accustomed, rather than to be governed much better by aliens. 
 The resistance of Spain to Napoleon is a typical example. 
 And in the long run it is generally best that a people who 
 have too strong sentiments of nationality to be readily assimi- 
 lated even by a higher form of civilisation, should work out 
 their political and social problems for themselves. Progress 
 may be very much slower, but it is likely to be more steady 
 and more secure. 
 
 The question, however, arises : In what sense has a nation, 
 a country — that is to say, a particular group of people — a 
 right to freedom, in the sense of independence ? In other 
 words, how far can we suppose that other nations are morally 
 bound (of any other obligation it is superfluous to speak) to 
 respect the independence of a particular nation ? Suppose 
 this nation is in a chronic state of disorder, that laws are not 
 enforced, or that there is so much oppression that discon- 
 tented and persecuted persons are always endeavouring to 
 cross the frontier, may not neighbouring nations have " a 
 right " to interfere — even on behalf of the inhabitants of the 
 country itself ? Or suppose that the territory possessed by a 
 particular race or nation is fertile and full of natural resources, 
 but that owing to misgovernment or backwardness in civilisa- 
 tion these natural resources are left undeveloped ; may not 
 neighbouring nations with an overflowing population capable 
 of utilising these natural resources be thought to have a right 
 to seize such of this territory as is convenient for them ?
 
 CH. x] NATIONAL FREEDOM, ETC 233 
 
 I do not think there is much profit in discussing the morality 
 of aggression without taking account of the fact that, under 
 such circumstances as I have supposed, neighbouring nations 
 are certain to avail themselves of convenient opportunities for 
 enlarging their territory and increasing the advantages of their 
 members. And where aggression is undertaken because of 
 disorderliness or great misgovernment, which makes a neigh- 
 bouriug country a breeding ground of criminals haunting the 
 frontier, or a breeding ground of pestilences, aggression maj^ 
 very reasonably be held to be a kind of police-measure and a 
 legitimate form of self-defence. 
 
 Professor Lorimer, in his interpretation of the Law of 
 Nature, speaks of a "natural right of aggression." "Aggres- 
 sion," he says, " is a Natural Right, the extent of which is 
 measured by the power which God has bestowed on the 
 aggressor or permitted him to develop." ^ This seems to me a 
 very much more logical and consistent application of the idea 
 of nature, than is to be found in most theories of natural rights. 
 Natural right is here determined simply by might or power, as 
 in the theory of Spinoza. It should of course be carefully 
 noted that " power " does not mean simply what is called 
 "brute force," but all those intellectual and moral qualities 
 which are implied in greater strategic skill, greater discipline, 
 and, above all, in the power of keeping possession of territory 
 seized by war and of turning a conquered population into 
 orderly and peaceable subjects or fellow-citizens. Such a re- 
 cognition of a natural right of aggression is often strongly 
 objected to by those who see nothing wrong in a trade-union 
 striking to secure better terms for its own members, when a 
 favourable opportunity occurs, even though a strike necessarily 
 involves much suffering to many individuals other than the 
 strikers themselves. But the principle in either case is the 
 same — the action, so far as it is justified, can be justified 
 only on the grounds of its success and on the better condition 
 of some very considerable number of human beings which 
 results from that success. 
 
 It is important to note that such a right of aggression 
 depends on the superiority in civilisation of the conquering 
 power — that is to say, it is assumed that the nations concerned 
 are not treated as equals. Where it has become convenient 
 
 1 ListUuteii of Law. I quote from the "Coutonts " of Book II., chap. 5.
 
 234 FREEDOM OF CONTRACT; [ch. x 
 
 and customary, as it lias among the civilised powers of 
 Christendom, to assume the diplomatic equality of powers 
 ■whose military and other resources are very unequal, there is 
 also the feeling that aggression as such is not justifiable, and 
 that war is only justifiable if entered upon for what may 
 plausibly be considered the purpose of self-defence. But it is 
 of coursa very easy to give " defence " a wide interpretation. 
 For a nation under all circumstances to wait until it is attacked 
 may mean to give such an advantage in carrying on war to 
 the assailant, that the nation may lose its independence, or that 
 some portion of it may be annexed by a less scrupulous neigh- 
 bour.^ 
 
 As to instances of the use of force by civilised over barbarous 
 or savage peoples, it is cheap virtue to call them " interna- 
 tional burglaries," and a very misleading use of language. 
 The word burglary can only be used metaphorically in cases 
 where there is no common criminal law to which both parties 
 are subject ; and the use of the term involves a naive accept- 
 ance of the status quo, analogous to what is implied in calling 
 any legislative interference with ancient rights of property 
 " confiscation " or " theft." People who are ready to advocate 
 the disendowment of an Established Church have very little 
 right to call the conquest of India or the invasion of Egypt 
 acts of burglary. They ought to leave that language to those 
 who call any readjustment of the ancient endowments of cor- 
 porations a " robbery of God." A savage or barbarous people, 
 misgoverned by some ferocious or incapable tyrant, cannot be 
 regarded, except conventionally, for some special purpose of 
 international convenience, as an independent nation in the 
 same sense as one of the great powers of Europe. In the 
 interests of humanity we can recognise no absolute right in 
 all governments, however bad, never to be interfered with. 
 We laugh at the Divine Right of Kings, claimed by Stuarts 
 
 Did tlie French Republic, in 1792, enter on a war of aggression, or 
 of self-defence? Did Prussia, in 1870, enter on a war of aggression, or of 
 self-defence ? Even tlie peace-loving Mr. Herbert Spencer speaks of 
 territories taken from the French "in punishment for their aggressive- 
 ness " (Principles of Ethics, Vol. I. p. 318). He assumes apparently 
 tliat nothing can be said against the view that Germany in taking Alsace 
 and Lorraine was simply recovering stolen goods. How far a province 
 may have been assimilated by a conqueror is a matter your abstract 
 thinker does not dream of considering.
 
 CH. x] NATIONAL FREEDOM, ETC 235 
 
 or Bourbons ; but the natural riglit of a king of Dahome}', or of 
 every robber chief or murderous pasha, to be left undisturbed 
 by all civilised nations, is at least quite as absurd. There 
 would be more reason for arguing that there is a natural right 
 inherent in all men to be governed well — an idea suggested 
 by the language of the French Declarations, which are 
 Declarations of the rights of men as well as of citizens. And 
 it is good government that alone legitimises conquest ; but it 
 does legitimise it in the minds of those who are prepared to 
 think out questions of right and wrong in the light of actual 
 human experience and not of arbitrary and a j)Viori principles 
 or prejudices. 
 
 I do not mean to suggest that the dealings of civilised 
 nations with uncivilised or less civilised races present no 
 difficult moral problems. All that I mean to insist on is, that 
 a general principle of non-intervention, based on an assumed 
 inalienable natural right of every group of human beings 
 that may call itself an independent tribe or people, is of no 
 use whatever for practical guidance. It is an unworkable 
 principle, and it is a wrong principle. A nation acts unwisely, 
 and therefore wrongly, if it undertakes responsibilities which 
 it cannot properly fulfil and which it could have avoided. 
 It is wrong to interfere, if we cannot reasonably hope to leave 
 things in a better condition than that in which we found 
 them — a better condition for the ind'widuals whose national or 
 tribal independence has been interfered with. But it is absurd 
 and misleading to class all interferences under the same 
 general condemnation ; it is a transference to foreign affairs 
 of the abstract belief in laissez faire. The contact of higher 
 and lower races, especially where the gap between them is 
 great, often forms one of the most unpleasant and saddest 
 parts of history ; but the contact is likely to be more disastrous 
 in its consequences where it comes simply through the irre- 
 sponsible action of private adventurers, than where a certain 
 measure of order and security and systematic administration 
 of justice is bestowed on a people in lieu of the right of being 
 left a prey to native despots and slave-raiders. Lovers of 
 peace ought to show due gratitude to the _i)ax Roninna,^ wJiich 
 
 * '• Throughout civilisation," says Mr. Herbert Spencer {Principles of 
 Ethics, Vol. I., p. 374), " the relations of citizens have become relatively 
 equitable only as fast as militancy has become less predominant; and
 
 2 36 FREEDOM OF CONTRACT; [ch. x 
 
 gave Europe a time of quiet such as it lias never enjoyed 
 since the Empire fell to pieces, and to the -pax Britamiica^ 
 which would come to a speedy end were India left to the 
 Indians. " India for the Indians," indeed, may serve as a 
 good specimen of those cant phrases which are used so freely 
 as rhetorical substitutes for argument. There may be an 
 Indian nationality some day ; if there is, its existence will be 
 due to British rule and its language will, in all probability, 
 be the English tongue. 
 
 Closely connected with this subject of national or tribal 
 independence or liberty is the " right " by which a State may 
 claim to reserve the territory it possesses for the exclusive 
 use of the present inhabitants and their descendants — the 
 right to prevent or restrict immigration. It is clear that 
 there is no sense in talking about a general natural right 
 on the part of every human being to go and settle in any 
 part of the world he chooses ; the right will depend on whether 
 other nations wish to have him or, if they do not, on whether 
 they can manage to keep him out. In the past, when facilities 
 for movement were much less than they are now, countries 
 which served as an asylum for the persecuted have generally 
 profited greatly by the folly of their neighbours in weeding 
 out many of the most vigorous minds and characters in the 
 nation. When a country, however, is fairly well filled and 
 has a sufficiently mixed stock already, it may reasonably 
 refuse to help to solve the problem of pauperism for other 
 lands. ^ The country which excludes desirable immigrants, on 
 the other hand, will suffer for it in the long run. And the 
 need of an outlet for a vigorous and overflowing population 
 may become so urgent as to break down barriers against 
 immigration defended by too scanty hands. 
 
 Here indeed we come upon the other side of the population 
 
 onh' .along with this change has the sentiment of justice become more 
 pronounced." A fighting people is not necessarily a legislating people; 
 but docs Mr. Spencer know of any great governing people which has not 
 shown its capacity for conquest and for retaining its conquests f 
 
 ' The United States of America have already given up their right to 
 the once famous boast that their — 
 
 " Free latch-string never was drawed in 
 Against the poorest child of Adam's kin." 
 The rights of the existing citizens are now asserted against any general 
 rights of man.
 
 CH. x] NATIONAL FREEDOM, ETC 237 
 
 question. It may be argued that, if the more civilised races 
 were to become stationary in numbers, the world might be 
 overrun by the lower races. Those who use this argument 
 are apt to forget two things— first, that the quality of a race 
 is more important than mere numbers. A swarming popula- 
 tion of hereditary paupers is no gain to the countr}' that is 
 burdened with their support. Secondly, a race may even 
 dwindle, and yet its type of civilisation may be successfully 
 imposed on immigrants of other races, so that the nation 
 increases. France attracts numerous immigrants from neigh- 
 bouring countries, but the Frenchman need not be despondent 
 about the future of his country so long as he turns them all 
 into Frenchmen, as he has hitherto always succeeded in doing. 
 Exclusion of immigrants, if allowed to be in some cases a 
 justifiable policy, is, it should be clearly recognised, quite 
 inconsistent with any sincere admission of the equality of all 
 human beings, or with any natural right of all to share in the 
 gifts of nature. It is inconsistent also when those, who object 
 to the immigration of labourers who will lower the standard 
 of living, object to the endeavour of trade-unions to exclude 
 from employment free labourers of their own country who will 
 lower the standard in a similar way. There is indeed this 
 difference in favour of the former policy over the latter, that 
 a nation may, with an honest government, decide the question 
 at least in the light of the whole nation, taking into account 
 the probable effects of its policy on the treatment of its own 
 citizens in foreign countries affected by this policy, while a 
 trade-union is very unlikely to consider anything except the 
 obvious and apparent interests of its own members, and may 
 even leave out of sight the effects of its policy on the price of 
 commodities and consequently on the ultimate real wage even 
 of its own members. Both endeavours, however, that of a 
 nation and that of a trade-union, to keep up the standard of 
 living are irreconcilable with any doctrine of natural rights, 
 except such as frankly recognises the connection between 
 natural right and the power of getting one's own way.
 
 CHAPTER XI 
 
 EESISTANCE TO OPPRESSION 
 
 The French Declaration of 1789 names among " the natural 
 and imprescriptible rights of man," whose maintenance is 
 the end of all political society, not only the rights of liberty, 
 of property, of security, but the right of resistance to op- 
 pression. The Declaration of 1793 asserts that " Resistance 
 to oppression is the consequence of the other rights of man " 
 (art. 33). The following article gives what appears to be 
 intended for a definition of " oppression," but it is somewhat 
 more epigrammatic than lucid. " There is oppression of the 
 social body when any single member of it is oppressed : there 
 is oppression of every member when the social body is op- 
 pressed." This statement really implies a theory of the relations 
 of society to the individual that is fundamentally inconsistent 
 with the individualistic view of society implied in the whole 
 doctrine of natural rights. The 35th and last article of the 
 Declaration is as follows : " When the government violates 
 the rights of the people, insurrection is for the people and for 
 every portion of the people the most sacred of rights and the 
 most indispensable of duties." " Resistance to oppression " 
 might indeed be used to mean simply legal remedies against 
 illegal or arbitrary action on the part of officials ; and doubt- 
 less that was part of what the framers of these Declarations 
 were thinking of. And it is a reasonable demand that a 
 Constitution should provide individuals with legal means of 
 defending those rights which the Constitution professes to . 
 guarantee to them. But the last article of the Declaration 
 of 1793 gives a wider meaning to the term "resistance." That 
 a Constitution should provide means for its own amendment is 
 essential, if it is not by claiming eternity to provoke revolu- 
 tion ; and it is expedient that the delays and difficulties of the 
 amending process should not be such as to make amendment 
 seem practically impossible. Some of the American Declara-
 
 CH. xi] JiESISTAXCE TO OPPRESSION 
 
 239 
 
 tions indeed assert that the people " have at all times an 
 inalienable and indefeasible right to alter, reform, or abolish 
 [Query, without substituting anything in its place?] their 
 form of government in such manner as they may think 
 expedient." ^ Between " at all times " and " never," or " at 
 very long intervals," a mean is often deemed expedient. But 
 such a right of constitutional amendment by constitutional 
 means is a very different thing from a constitutional guarantee 
 of the right of overthrowing the government by the use of 
 force. Such a constitutional right of insurrection is the most 
 anarchical and contradictory notion that it ever entered into 
 the heart of man to conceive. Even the vaguer right of 
 resistance to oppression is left out of the Declaration of 1795, 
 for obvious reasons of historical experience. As Bentham 
 remarks, " Between 1791 and 1795 Citizen Resistance-against- 
 Oppression had been playing strange tricks." ^ 
 
 It would be very unjust, however, to suppose, as is frequently 
 done, that this notion of a right of resistance was the outcome 
 merely of French political inexperience. As asserted in the 
 Declaration of 1789, it may be regarded as only a repetition 
 of the right which is asserted in the American Declaration of 
 Independence, and the right there claimed is nothing more 
 -than had been recognised and defended by Locke in his Treatise 
 of Civil Govenimeyit — the theoretical defence of the English 
 Revolution of 1688. The American Declaration of Indepen- 
 dence is, however, a Declaration of war, and is hardly therefore 
 the best model for a Declaration of those Rights which are to 
 be guaranteed by a Constitution. To find a genuine parallel 
 to the constitutional recognition of a right of resistance we 
 must go back to times when the idea of the State was in a 
 very rudimentary stage — to such documents as the " Golden 
 Bull" of King Andrew (a.d. 1222), which concedes, while like 
 Magna Cliarta only professing to confirm, the special privi- 
 leges of the Hungarian nobility. " Should we," it is written, 
 "or any of our successors, at any time be disposed to infringe 
 upon any of these our orders, the bishops, as well as the other 
 lords and the nobles of the realm, shall be at liberty, jointly or 
 singly, by virtue of this letter, to oppose and contradict us 
 and our successors, for ever, without incurring the penalty of 
 
 1 "Declaration of Rights," in Constitution of Alabama, 1809. 
 ^ Anarchical Fallacies, in Works (18i3), II. p. 525.
 
 240 RESISTANCE TO OPPRESSION [ch. xi 
 
 treason." ' Such a method of imposmg a check on oppression 
 is only a degree less primitive than the letter of King Ahasu- 
 erus, in which he permits the Jews to massacre those whom he 
 had previously permitted to massacre them - — violence checked 
 by counter-violence. In a written constitution of the modern 
 type, it is, however, an anomaly and an absurdity to recognise 
 a right which, strictly interpreted, would make government 
 impossible, a right which contradicts the fundamental notion 
 of sovereignty. Rousseau's teaching about the sovereignty of 
 the people is often made responsible for the anarchical theories 
 of some of the French revolutionary leaders, but those who 
 thought they derived a right of insurrection from Rousseau 
 proved themselves unintelligent disciples ; for on Rousseau's 
 theory there is no sense in claiming the right of insurrection. 
 If a peo|)le throw off a tyrannical government it is an act of 
 sovereignty ; and to call it an " insurrection " involves the 
 assumption that the government is the sovereign, which it 
 never can be, on Rousseau's theory, except by usurpation. 
 Such a usurping government should be called a " rebel," and 
 punished as such. This theory may seem strange ; but at least 
 it is logical, which the guarantee of a right of insurrection is 
 not. It is, indeed, only a Constitution like the present Federal 
 Constitution of Switzerland, with its referendum on all consti- 
 tutional changes, and potentially on all laws, that gives any 
 security for the smooth and quiet working of a legal sovereignty 
 of the people.'^ 
 
 Those, indeed, avIio accepted what may be called the Hilde- 
 brandine theory of the Papal power, may be said to have made 
 the Church, i.e., for convenience, or in explicit theory, the 
 Pope, the only true sovereign over all Christian peoples. The 
 justification of resistance to tyrants (even of assassination of 
 tyrants, when necessary) by many mediseval theologians and 
 by some Jesuit casuists (in reference to Protestant rulers, of 
 course) always rests on the assumption that the Pope can decide 
 who is and who is not a "tyrant." When allegiance to the 
 Pope is thrown off, every one is left to decide for himself what 
 constitutes the "tyranny" or "oppression" that justifies resist- 
 
 ^ Yambery, Huntjary ("Story of the Nations" Series), p. 130, 
 ^ See The Book of Esther. 
 
 ^ On this subject I may be allowed to refer to an Essay on " Tlie Con- 
 ception of Sovereignty," in my Daricin and Hegel, etc.
 
 CH. xi] RESISTANCE TO OPPRESSION 241 
 
 auce, and thus, although morally resistance may seem perfectly 
 justifiable and necessary, the appearance of legality, that might 
 seem to cling to it in the minds of those who accepted the 
 Pope's deposing power, has altogether disappeared. 
 
 If indeed a Constitution be thought of as a Compact, there 
 is considerable plausibility in regarding the "insurrection" of 
 one of the parties to the compact as constitutionally justified 
 by the failure of the other party to perform his (or its) part of 
 the compact — the party that considers itself aggrieved claiming 
 the right to judge when the compact is broken. It was by 
 appealing to this notion of a contract between King and 
 People that the English Convention Parliament justified the 
 Revolution of 1688.^ The idea of a contract between King 
 and People was very widely held in the middle ages, and 
 frequently received a sort of express recognition in the form of 
 the coronation oath. The theory, like many other illogical 
 theories, has been practically very useful in helping the cause 
 of political libert}^ ; but the very fact that it gives a quasi- 
 constitutional sanction to rebellion is a refutation of its claims 
 to represent the true legal theory of a Constitution. 
 
 There is no doubt that the theory of the United States Con- 
 stitution of 1787 as a Compact between Sovereign States was 
 widely held at the time the Constitution was framed ; and if 
 it had not been a plausible interpretation of the Constitution, 
 several of the States might have been more reluctant than they 
 were to give up the more independent position which they held 
 under the original Confederation. And I think it must be 
 granted that there is a greater appearance of constitutional 
 legality in the South Carolina Declaration of Independence of 
 1860 than there is in the Declaration of Independence of the 
 Thirteen Colonies in 1776. The Thirteen Colonies could only 
 appeal to natural rights and to abstract principles, inherited 
 from the theories of Locke and others: South Carolina ap- 
 pealed, in addition, to a definite written agreement actually 
 formed between sovereign States — the terms of which agree- 
 
 ^ Even Grotius, wlio rejects the idea that there is auy general natural 
 right of resistance, allows a right of resistance when a i)riuce has abdi- 
 cated, or when he is manifestly bearing himself as the enemy of his 
 whole people. — De Jure, Belli et Facia, I., c. iv. §§ 8 seq. Tiie English 
 Revolution of 1688 might fairly be brought under the sanction of his 
 principles. 
 
 N. R. K
 
 242 RESISTANCE TO OPPRESSION [ch. xi 
 
 ment liad, it was alleged, been broken.^ Furthermore, whereas 
 the majority of the Colonies, when they renounced their alle- 
 giance to the British Crown, had to frame for themselves new 
 Constitutions and all of them had to make themselves from 
 dependencies into States which previously had no legal exist- 
 ence as such, South Carolina, in seceding, was simply retain- 
 ing her existing constitution and resuming the position she 
 actually had occupied in 1787. The better legal theory of the 
 United States Constitution undoubtedly rejects the view that 
 it is a Compact: it is not made by the "United States," but 
 by "the People of the United States" — a sovereign body that 
 had no existence in the Confederation of 1777. The fortune of 
 war confirmed the interpretation adopted by the Supreme 
 Court .; and events revealed that an American Nation had 
 grown up in a sense which the particularism of the South had 
 not realised. But, still, there was a very plausible case for 
 the constitutional right of secession — more plausible than could 
 be alleged for many rebellions where the moral duty of re- 
 bellion seems clear and where the appeal court of history has 
 condoned the want of legal right. For legality and moralit}", 
 legal rights and political or historical facts, are often very 
 different things. And the gravest objection to the whole 
 theory of natural rights is, that it is always tending to confuse 
 the two sets of notions, by representing what may on occasion 
 be moral duties as legal or quasi-legal rights, and hy concealing 
 under such ambiguous terms as " can " and " cannot " the 
 difference between "ought" and "is," or between "wish" and 
 
 ^ The South Carolina Declaration of Independence, after referring to 
 the Declaration of Independence of the Colonies, which asserted their 
 existence as sovereign and independent States, to the recognition of the 
 United States as sovereign and independent States by Great Britain in 
 1783, and to the formation of the Constitution of 1787 by the sovereign 
 States, proceeds as follows: "We hold that the government thus estab- 
 lished is subject to the two great principles asserted in the Declaration of 
 Independence [viz. the right of a State to govern itself and the right of a 
 people to abolish a government when it becomes destructive of the ends 
 for which it was instituted], and we hold further that the mode of its 
 formation subjects it to a third fundamental principle, namely, the law 
 of compact. We maintain that in every compact between two or more 
 parties the obligation is mutual — that the failure of one of the contract- 
 ing parties to perform a material part of the agreement entirelj^ releases 
 the obligation of the other, and that, where no arbiter is appointed, each 
 party is remitted to its own judgment to determine the fact of failure 
 with all its consequences."
 
 CH. xi] RESISTANCE TO OPPRESSION 243 
 
 " power." ^ Much is lost in logical clearness, and notliing is 
 gained in practical politics, by endeavours to shirk the neces- 
 sarily unlimited character of sovereignty — the legal despotism 
 of the legal sovereign. Disobedience to the law of the land — ■ 
 if it is the law of the land — can never be a legal or consti- 
 tutional right ; it may be morally excused, or it may be a 
 moral duty. If there is this conflict between ]aw and morals, 
 that is a reason for changing the law if possible — peaceably 
 and constitutionally if possible ; but it is no reason for pre- 
 tending that the law is what we think it ought to be, or that 
 what we think ought to be is law. 
 
 When people think about a " right of resistance " they are 
 really concerned with a moral, not a constitutional, question. 
 When, if ever, is it right to use force against a de facto govern- 
 ment? This is an important question of political casuistry. 
 It is said that a bishop, in a country that I need not specify, 
 was once consulted as to whether a rebellion of a certain kind 
 would be justifiable : he answered, " There are reasons on both 
 sides. For the negative there is, /?r.S'^, that you have no 
 cannon "" It v/as unnecessary to proceed with the argu- 
 ment. The worthy ecclesiastic laid stress on a very important 
 element in determining the rightness of resistance — a reason- 
 able chance of success. But success ought to be taken to 
 mean, not merely overthrowing and destroying the existing 
 government or constitution, but substituting something better 
 that is Ukely to last fairly well. Another most important 
 consideration is this : Have all peaceable and constitutional 
 means of reform been tried in vain, or does the government 
 make it impossible to have recourse to them? And the last 
 question, the question which should really be asked first, is 
 this : Are the evils under which we are suffering such that 
 they are worse than the risk of disorder and bloodshed?^ 
 This last question is likely to be answered very dilferently by 
 persons and races of different temperament. 
 
 » Cf. Bentham, Anarchical Fallacies, Works, II. pp. 494, 495, 499, 500, 
 etc. 
 
 ^ Cf. the story of the answer of Bisliop Lesley to the E;irl of South- 
 ampton, p. 177, note. 
 
 3 On the ethics of resistance see T. H. Green, Philosophical Works, II. 
 pp. 455 seq.
 
 CHAPTER XII 
 
 EQUALITY ^ 
 
 Amonq the natural rights of man which a Constitution ought 
 to guarantee, equality is not named in the French Declaration 
 of 1789, although in article 6 the equality of citizens before 
 the law is expressly asserted. " The law should be the same 
 for all, both in protecting and in punishing. All citizens being 
 equal in the eye of the law, are equally admissible to all 
 dignities and public places and employments, according to 
 their capacity, and without other distinction than that of their 
 virtues and their talents." In the Declaration of 1793, 
 " equality " is named along with liberty, security, and pro- 
 perty, as one of the natural and imprescriptible rights to 
 guarantee which government has been instituted (arts. 1 and 
 2). A separate article asserts that " all men are equal by 
 nature and before the law." This more extreme position of 
 the Declaration of 1793 comes nearer to the words of the 
 American Declaration of Independence. In the Declaration 
 of Independence it is said, " We hold those truths to be self- 
 evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed 
 by the Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among 
 these are Life, Liberty, and the pursuit of Happiness." The 
 equality of mankind is asserted to be a self-evident truth, and 
 equality is not regarded as the creation of the law, but as 
 something which exists independently of any human law. 
 Some of the State Constitutions contain similar assertions in 
 their Declarations of Rights. Thus in the Connecticut Declara- 
 tion (1818) we read, " That all men, when they form a social 
 compact, are equal in rights, and that no man or set of men 
 are entitled to exclusive public emoluments or privileges from 
 
 ^ A short article of mine on this subject appeared in the Contemporary 
 lieview for October, 1892. The present chapter, though written from 
 quite the same point of view, is an independent treatment of the question. 
 
 2U
 
 CH. xii] EQUALITY 245 
 
 the community." It is instructive to put alongside of this the 
 parallel passage in two Southern Constitutions formed about 
 the same time. In the Mississippi Declaration of Rights of 
 1817 and in the Alabama Declaration of 1819, it is declared 
 " that all freemen^ when they form a social compact, are equal 
 in rights," etc. — a significant amendment of the phraseology 
 that was common at the time of the War of Independence. 
 
 Now, what is meant by the natural equality of men? The 
 meaning may be only this : that distinctions in rank, in wealth, 
 in political and social status, etc., are due entirely to social 
 arrangements, and apart from society would not exist. This 
 is a principle which may be accepted, not perhaps as self- 
 evident, but as a consequence of a process of abstraction, by 
 which we eliminate all that history and experience prove to be 
 due to human institution, deliberate or unconscious. In this 
 sense the natural equality of mankind means the same sort of 
 thing as the freedom of mankind by the jus vafurale Avhich 
 Ulpian recognises. In this sense the equality of mankind is 
 accepted equally by Hobbes and Locke. Hobbes, indeed, goes 
 farther than this, and makes the natural equality of men mean, 
 not merely the absence of those inequalities which are due to 
 institutions and conventions, but an approximate positive 
 equality in faculties of mind and bod5^ " Nature," he says 
 {Leviathan, ch. xiii,), " hath made men so equal in the faculties 
 of body and mind, as that, though there be found one man 
 sometimes manifestly stronger in body, or of quicker mind 
 than another, yet when all is reckoned together the difference 
 between man and man is not so considerable, as that one man 
 can thereupon claim to himself any benefit to which another 
 may not pretend as well as he. For as to the strength of body, 
 the weakest has strength enough to kill the strongest, either 
 by secret machination, or by confederacy with others that 
 are in the same danger with himself. [The need of secret 
 machination and of confederacy with others is an odd reason 
 to give for equality !] And as to the faculties of mind . . . 
 I find a yet greater equality amongst men than that of 
 strength. For Prudence is but Experience, which equal time 
 equally bestows on all men in those things they equally apply 
 themselves unto. That which may, perhaps, make such 
 equality incredible, is but a vain conceit of one's own wisdom, 
 which almost all men think they have in a greater degree
 
 246 EQUALITY [ch. xii 
 
 than the vulgar; that is, than all men but themselves, and a 
 few others, whom, by fame or for concurring with themselves, 
 they approve." Hobbes seems to adopt an unnecessarily wide 
 premise for taking down the pride of those who think them- 
 selves superior persons. Locke, who cites " the judicious 
 Hooker" in support of the self-evident character of the equality 
 of men by nature,^ does not venture to assert the actual positive 
 equality of men in the same way as Hobbes does. Children, 
 he confesses, are not born in this full state of equality, though 
 they are born to it,- a distinction which implies a recognition, 
 however slight, of difference between nature as the original 
 condition, and nature as an ideal of what ought to be. And 
 in speaking of the " State of Nature," he argues that the state 
 is one of equality, " there being nothing more evident than 
 that creatures of the same species and rank, promiscuously 
 born to all the same advantages of Nature and the use of the 
 same faculties, should also be equal one amongst another, 
 without subordination or subjection, unless the Lord and 
 Master of them all should, by any manifest declaration of His 
 will, set one above another, and confer on him, by an evident 
 and clear appointment, an undoubted right to dominion and 
 sovereignty " ^ — a passage which suggests that it cannot be self- 
 evident that the Creator has made all men equal, if the Creator 
 could, without contradicting Himself, make some superior : the 
 positive Divine law is usually supposed to be limited by the 
 law of nature. Locke makes equality consist in the being 
 born to the same advantages of Nature, as if it were not 
 self-evident that all were born witli the same advantages. 
 Furthermore, he limits equality to those of " the same species 
 and rank." But what determines sameness of ranli (it must 
 be natural rank, of course) ? and what if it were held that 
 different human races were naturally different in rank ? 
 
 The natural equality of all mankind in the sense of a 
 positive equality of inlierited bodily and mental powers 
 (acquired powers being obviously due to institutions) is not so 
 likely to be dogmatically asserted now-a-days as it was in the 
 days when biology did not exist as a science, and when it was 
 still possible for the inhabitants of civilised countries to idealise 
 the noble savage. Let it be admitted as fully as possible that 
 
 * Treatise of Civil Government, II. § 5. 
 2 Ibid., § 55. » Ibid., § 4.
 
 CH. xiij EQUALITY 247 
 
 the natural gulf which separates the lowest savage from the 
 highest extant ape is greater than that which separates the 
 lowest savage from the highest civilised race ; that is to say, 
 let it be admitted that the brain of the savage differs more 
 from the brain of the ape than it does from the brain of the 
 civilised man, while the actual mental furniture of the savage 
 is nearer to that of the ape than to that of the civilised man, 
 this proves indeed the enormous extent to which inequalities 
 are due to differences in training and in social environment — 
 i.e, to human institutions ; but no careful or thoughtful person 
 can now-a-days deny the very great differences in mental and 
 moral capacities, even among persons of the same race, nay, 
 even of the same family, and with equal opportunities of cul- 
 tivatiug their natural powers. Differences in bodily health, 
 strength, etc, (prior to training), are too obvious to need remark; 
 some persons inherit better constitutions and more capacity for 
 ph3^sical development than others. It is perfectly unscientific, 
 and, therefore, perfectly useless, now-a-days to discuss the 
 political and social aspects of equality, except on the basis of 
 admitting the great natural inequalities among human beings. 
 But supj)ose these admitted ; it does not follow that in respect 
 of legal and political rights persons who may be naturally un- 
 equal ought in no case to be treated as legally and politically 
 equal. In the first place, natural inequalities, especially mental 
 and moral inequalities, are not always easy to discover ; they 
 take time to show themselves. Even Aristotle, while basing 
 his defence of slavery on the natural inequalities of human 
 beings, admits that it is not always easy to tell who is by 
 nature a slave, and who is by nature fit for freedom, and con- 
 tents himself with the rough practical rule that the Greek 
 race is superior to barbarians, and that therefore Greeks 
 ought not to be enslaved.^ Thus laws and institutions may 
 often treat unequals as equals, simply because of the difficulty 
 of deciding degrees of inequality by any sufftciently certain 
 standard. Secondly, because Nature has made human beings 
 unequal, it does not follow that human laws and institutions 
 should attempt to follow Nature in this matter, even if it 
 were possible to do so. It may often be considered best to en- 
 deavour to remedy the inequalities which Nature has inllicted 
 on her children. " It is precisely," says Rousseau, " because 
 
 ' Pol, I. 4-6.
 
 248 EQUALITY [cH. xii 
 
 the force of circumstances tends always to destroy equality, 
 that the force of legislation ought always to tend to maintain 
 it." ^ There are, of course, obvious limits to the extent to 
 which this ought to be done ; e.g. it would not be safe to make 
 every citizen in turn commander of the navy or the army on 
 grounds of equality. Even in Athens, where the lot was used 
 in order to secure a rotation of official experience among the 
 citizens (the dominant caste of free men — be it understood), 
 the principle was not ajiplied in electing generals. How far 
 equality should practically be applied in determining the rights 
 of citizens is a matter that cannot be decided a jyviori by any 
 reference to Nature, but must be settled in every case by some 
 compromise, based on a consideration of what is safe, when 
 the maintenance of security against external enemies and the 
 avoidance of discontent at home are both considered. The 
 existence of the ideal of equality in the minds of a people is, 
 of course, an important factor in determining what can be 
 done, what ought to be done, and what is likely to be done. 
 
 This ideal of equality is an inheritance from the inequalities 
 of ancient societies ; it is the idea of a peerage — an order or 
 caste of nobles who recognise each other as in some respects 
 and for some purposes equals, while asserting their superiority 
 to the rest of the nation or the rest of the human race.^ The 
 idea of equality has grown out of the idea of privilege ; the 
 same is the case with the idea of freedom. Both ideas are the 
 outgrowth of aristocratic and slave-holding communities. It 
 was in contrast with the subject and the slave that men first 
 felt themselves equal and free. The ancient democracies were 
 slave-holding aristocracies ; but the ideas of liberty and equality 
 once started go farther. Even in the modern democratic ideal, 
 there is no doubt that the equality of mankind is connected 
 with the superiority of man as such to all the lower animals. 
 Those who would assert the equality of all sentient beings 
 would put an end to the equality of mankind as such. For 
 it is the recognition that there is something in man which 
 distinguishes him as such from all other animals that alone 
 justifies one in speaking of the equality of men as men. 
 
 ' Contr. Soc, II. c. xi. 
 
 ^ Cf. G. Tarde, Les Lois de V Imitation, p. 257 : " Le veritable travail 
 preparatoire de Fegalitarisme actuel a ete execute dans le passe par la 
 noblesse et non par la bourgeoisie ; " and ideas spread downwards.
 
 CH. xii] EQUALITY 249 
 
 When Beiitliam uttered his dictum, " Everybody to count 
 for one, nobody for more than one," ' and assumed it as a 
 principle by which to interpret his formula of Greatest Happi- 
 ness as the ethical end, he uttered a dictum which has been 
 extremely serviceable in aiding legislative reform by putting 
 a check on arbitrary appeals to the law of Nature ; but it is 
 a dictum which itself involves the assumption of that natural 
 right of equality, against which he himself protests. ^ We 
 are not entitled to assume the equal claims of all men to 
 happiness if our ethical principle is based solely on the fact 
 that all sentient beings naturally pursue pleasure. If the 
 greater sum of pleasures be always to be preferred, and be our 
 sole ultimate criterion of right and wrong, it is quite illegiti- 
 mate to prefer a smaller sum of pleasures distributed among 
 a larger number of persons to a larger sum of pleasures though 
 shared among a smaller number of persons. For the purpose 
 of this moral arithmetic we must, of course, assume that pains 
 may be simply reckoned as a set-off against pleasures, so that 
 m units of pleasure would be exactly cancelled by m units of 
 pain. We must also assume that our hedometer (a desirable 
 instrument that no Grreatest Happiness moralist has yet 
 invented) will enable us to measure intensity against dura- 
 tion. We miust make these assumptions, strange or ridiculous 
 as they may seem, if the hedonist ethical standard is to be 
 saved from the caprice of every individual, and to be put on 
 an objective and ''scientific" basis by the introduction of 
 quantitative measurement. 
 
 J. S. Mill, although he quotes the dictum about everybody 
 and nobody to which I have just referred, denies the quite 
 sound criticism of Mr. H. Spencer, that " the principle of utility 
 [in Bentham's sense] presupposes the anterior principle, that 
 everybody has an equal right to happiness." According to 
 Mill, Bentham's principle only supposes " that equal amounts 
 of happiness are equally desirable, ?o/<e^/i<?r /e/f hy the same ov 
 by different persons^'' and, he adds, " if there is any anterior 
 principle implied, it can be no other than this, that the truths 
 of arithmetic are applicable to the valuation of happiness, as of 
 
 ^ Quoted by J. S. Mill, Utilitariam.svi, p. 93. This maxim seems to 
 belong to the unwritten doctrine of the Utilitarian master. Cf. Bonar^ 
 Fhilosophy and J'olificcd Economy^ p. 234, note. 
 
 ^ Anarchical Fallacies, in Works, II. pp. 498, 499.
 
 250 EQUALITY [ch. xii 
 
 all other measurable quantities."^ If this be so, there must be 
 many cases where Bentham's dictum about equality of persons 
 cannot possibly apply. Suppose that some one presents a dish 
 of olives to five persons, of whom two are passionately fond of 
 olives, while three detest them, the greatest happiness of the 
 company will obviously be attained by dividing the olives 
 among the two who like them, and giving none to the others. 
 Suppose that there are only two concert tickets available for 
 five persons, and the two who enjoy music most get hold of 
 them and deprive their less musical friends of what to them 
 would be a very inferior pleasure, or even a positive pain, is not 
 this the plan which produces the greatest sum of happiness, 
 although equality is quite neglected ? Now, suppose that in 
 a political community there is a small, but able and powerful 
 and wealthy and well-armed ruling caste, with a subject 
 population of greatly inferior intellectual type, placid, ac- 
 quiescent and careless of liberty and equality, so long as they 
 are sufficiently well-fed, and not treated "with positive cruelty, 
 will not the greatest sum of happiness be attained by the 
 ruling caste keeping to themselves the pleasures and excite- 
 ments of a splendid life of political activity and intellectual 
 and sesthetic enjoyment, unfettered by the drudgery of manual 
 toil, and subsisting on the labour of their slaves and depend- 
 ants ? To introduce equality into such a community means a 
 curtailment of the pleasures of the higher caste with no com- 
 mensurate increase of the pleasures of the lower, who will 
 undoubtedly be made more discontented, and therefore more 
 miserable, by having new ideals of life put before their minds, 
 and new wants created. The ideal of a m-odern democracy is 
 an ideal far more difficult of attainment than the ideal of what 
 the Greeks understood by democracy ; and for that very rea- 
 son it seems true, that the Greatest Happiness moralist ought, 
 if he is consistent, to prefer the Greek ideal wherever and so 
 long as it is possible. We know that Bentham and John 
 Stuart Mill would not prefer it ; but that is just because the 
 one introduces a j)rinciple of equality, and the other a dis- 
 tinction of qualities of pleasure — criteria of right and wrong 
 which are fatal to the purely quantitative and objective 
 weighing of lots of pleasure against one another — the arith- 
 metical method by which it was proposed to bring ethics under 
 ^ Utilitarianism, p. 93, note.
 
 en. xii] EQUALITY 251 
 
 the exact sciences. Undoubtedly there are man}'- cases in which 
 a Benthamite might quite consistently come to the practical 
 conclusion that it is best to treat people as equal ; he may 
 do so simply because the problem of adjusting things to 
 persons in such a way as to promote the really greatest sum 
 of happiness is too difficult of solution ; and so, giving up the 
 problem, he may settle the matter by bestowing equal shares 
 on persons with admittedly unequal capacities of enjoyment — 
 that is the same sort of thing as settling a difficulty by 
 "tossing up," which is, of course, not to decide rationally, but to 
 leave the decision to chance. Further, if the ideal of equality 
 (however absurd such an ideal might seem to a thoroughly 
 scientific quantitative hedonist with a well-constructed 
 hedometer) has once got possession of a large number of 
 persons, it may be dangerous to attempt anything but such a 
 rough-and-ready way of solving ethical and political problems; 
 and the pains of discontent may, to some extent, be allayed 
 (though probably new pains of discontent will be created) by 
 professing to reckon everybody as one, and nobody as more 
 than one. But in all such cases equality must be adopted as 
 a conclusion from considerations of what is socially expedient, 
 and not taken for granted as a premise.^ 
 
 With regard to equality, an ethical system which starts 
 from the fact of man's rationality is on a somewhat different 
 footing from a system which starts from the fact of man's 
 sentience. Man's rationality is what separates him from the 
 lower animals, and connects him with his fellow-men. His 
 sentience connects him with all other animals, but, as such, 
 gives him no special link (apart from his rationality) with his 
 fellow-men. It is not necessary to the assertion that man is 
 rational to assume that the gap between him and the animals 
 is absolute : it is enough to recognise that the barrier of com- 
 munication and interchange of ideas is less between any 
 human beings, however far separated in degree of civilisation, 
 than between man and the lower animals. We must not be 
 misled by such facts as the amount of sympathy a man feels 
 with his dog. The dog, as I have already pointed out, is an 
 
 ^ In the foregoing passage, and some of wliat follows, I have found 
 myself unable to avoid some repetition of wliat has already been said in 
 Chapter V. (pp. 95, 90). To repeat has seemed to me in this case a less evil 
 than merely to refer the reader to what was said in a diliierent context.
 
 252 EQUALITY [ch. xii 
 
 artificial animal — a parasite that man, by artificial selection 
 through long generations, has adapted to his own convenience 
 or fancies. Even the most fanatical dog-lover, in his saner 
 moments, will admit that he could carry on a more elaborate, 
 even if a less agreeable, conversation with a negro than with a 
 creature that can only bark and whine and wag its tail. In all 
 human beings we recognise, not merely the participation in the 
 same general physical structure as in ourselves, and conse- 
 quently in the same general life-history, but we recognise also 
 a participation in the same idea of self^ — a power of reflecting 
 on one's place in the universe which, however little developed, 
 is there in germ in every human being. What kind of con- 
 sciousness the lower animals have we can only guess, and we 
 can never verify our hypothesis in any direct manner. Our 
 belief in the consciousness of other human beings, and in the 
 likeness of their consciousness to ours, is a hypothesis also ; but 
 it is a hypothesis that we can verify by comparing our mental 
 experience with theirs. Thus human beings are not only 
 linked together as members of the same animal species, but as 
 the sharers in the same type of mental life, and therefore 
 potentially in the same ideals of conduct. "We find that each of 
 us — each human being — is a centre of a universe of his own, 
 from which, in one sense, each of us can never escape. 
 
 When Kant enunciates the moral law in the iorm. that " we 
 should so act as to treat humanity in ourselves and others in 
 every case as an end, never as a means only," he asserts a 
 certain equality of all men; but he does so with better logical 
 justification than Bentham, for he starts from the rationahty 
 and not from the sentience of human nature. Kant's ethical 
 thinking is, indeed, pervaded by the individualism which lies 
 at the basis of the whole theory of natural rights, and I think 
 it must be admitted that in this formula he is guilty of a one- 
 sided exaggeration in his way of expressing the idea of 
 humanity as an end-in-itself. That "we should never treat any 
 human being as a means only " cannot be a part of the moral 
 law, unless the moral law is by its very nature incapable of 
 being obeyed — so that we should have to say, "I ought, there- 
 fore I cannot," Is it necessarily wrong to climb up on another 
 person's shoulder for a lawful purpose, when there is no ladder 
 at hand, or to employ a human model instead of a lay-figure, 
 or to ask a policeman to show one the way? It is a curious
 
 CH. xii] EQUALITY 253 
 
 comment ou Kant's language about humanity being always an 
 end, that in his Philosophij of Law he allows the Tightness of 
 impressing men for military service.* Interpreted in a rigid 
 waj'', the idea of never using a human being as a means is 
 unworkable. What Kant really intends is, that no human 
 being should be regarded as being altogether onl}^ a means ; 
 that every human being, however much he may serve as a 
 means for the satisfaction of the needs of others, has still a life 
 of his own that ought to be respected. A human being ma}'' 
 be a "living tool," as Aristotle defines the slave, but in a well- 
 regulated society no one should be a '' living tool " only. Kant, 
 that is to say, has a social ideal which excludes such institu- 
 tions as slaver^^ ; but the fact that he is judging conduct from 
 the point of view of such a society only comes dimly to the 
 front, when, e.g., he speaks of human beings as being members 
 of " a kingdom of ends." 
 
 The " equality " of human beings as such, which alone is 
 necessarily implied in an idealist system of ethics, would be 
 
 1 Rechtslehre, § 55 (Werke, IX. pp. 197, 198, ed. Eosenkranz ; VII. 
 p. 163, ed. Hartenstein). Mr. Bonar, in his Philosophy and Political 
 Economy, p. 273, curiously misrepresents Kant's own view in saying 
 simply, " The right of the State to impress soldiers is deduced from its 
 creation of them." What Kant really says is, that the right of tlie State 
 to compel its subjects to fight for it appears to be easily deducible from 
 the principle that what one has substantially made for one's self is 
 one's own property, and that one may do what one will with one's own 
 property. Now population could not grow up without the protection of 
 government; therefore, etc. Such a principle may be accepted by the 
 mere jurist, " and may be supposed to float dimly before the mind of 
 monarchs ; but, though applicable to animals, it will not apply to man at 
 all, especially when he is viewed as a citizen, who must be regarded as a 
 member of the State with a share in legislation— y;.o^ merely as a means, 
 but at the same time as also an end-iv-himself. As such, he must give 
 his free consent, through his representatives, not only to the carr3'ing 
 on of war in general, but to every separate declaration of war; and it 
 is only under this limiting condition that the State has a right to require 
 of him such dangerous services. We must, therefore, perhaps deduce 
 this right from the duty of the sovereign to the people, not conversely 
 [from the duty of the i)eople to the sovereign, as on the theory first 
 suggested]. The people having the right of voting may be considered, 
 though passive, to be also active and to represent the Sovereign himself." 
 The passage is not very lucid ; but it avoids the exaggeration of Mr. 
 Bonar's interpretation, as well as of a too literal apjilication of the " end- 
 in-himself" notion. The necessity of the "consent "of the people to 
 every declaration of war would, however, if strictly taken (whicli Kant 
 does not seem to mean), prove an unworkable principle.
 
 254 EQUALITY [ch. xii 
 
 more correctly expressed as their potential membership of a 
 common society. It is only in so far as we can think of 
 humanity as a possible society that we can regard human 
 beings as equal moral units. They are persons potentially, be- 
 cause they are potentially members of a society. As a matter 
 of historical development, it is only in smaller societies that 
 the idea of moral personality has grown up. The idea of 
 humanity as a possible society has been of gradual growth, 
 and therefore also the idea of every human being as a person 
 — the idea, as it is sometimes phrased, of " the infinite worth 
 of every human soul." The idea of one God, as the God of all 
 races of mankind, is an essential element in this conception. 
 
 Such metaphysical notions may seem far away from practical 
 politics, but it is only in the light of them that we can put any 
 tenable meaning into the political dogma, or, let me rather say, 
 the political ideal of equality. The historical connection be- 
 tween religious and political ideas is easily seen, and it is 
 usually through religion that metaphysical ideas first grow up 
 or become popularised. "When a religion ceases to be the 
 affair of a particular race or a particular nation, we have the 
 first step in the proclamation of the right of equality. When 
 it is declared that God is no respecter of persons, but accepts 
 all, irrespective of race, sex, or outward condition, we are still 
 a long way from the democratic formula ; but the most 
 formidable barriers of caste, the religious barriers, have been 
 broken down. The hierarchical Church of the Middle Ages 
 may indeed seem far removed, not merely in its actual con- 
 dition but in its ideals, from the doctrine of equality. But in 
 its priesthood, which was no hereditary caste, but recruited 
 from all classes, even the lowest, it suggested the idea of " a 
 career open to talent" at a time when the whole structure of 
 secular society suggested rather a rigid system of caste, ^ 
 When Protestantism, especially in its extremer forms, revolted 
 against the monarchical and aristocratic character of the 
 Mediaeval Church, the way was prepared for the revolutionary 
 doctrine of equality. 
 
 ' Relatively to lay society the clerical order was a separate, and, in a 
 sense, a superior caste — a spiritual aristocracy. The idea of equality — 
 in the negative sense of an absence of permanent barriers, even to the 
 highest offices — spread down from this spiritual aristocracy to the lay 
 community. (Cf. above, p. 248, note 2.) Protestantism tended to recog- 
 nise the potential priesthood of all men, and their potential kingship also.
 
 CH. xii] EQUALITY 255 
 
 " Equality before the law " is the first and most essential 
 kind of equality. And tMs equality is transferred from the 
 Declaration of 1789 even into the Constitutional Charter of the 
 restored Bourbons, of which the first article runs : "Frenchmen 
 are equal before the law, whatever otherwise their titles and 
 ranks may be." The significance of this equality is to be 
 found by considering that it means the abolition of the special 
 privileges and immunities of the clergy and the nobility 
 — it means an increasing unification and integration in the 
 national life, the disappearance of various quasi-States before 
 the one State. As with the idea of equality in ethics and in 
 religion, equality before the law means the membership of a 
 great whole. 
 
 Equality in political rights — in the suffrage and in eligibility 
 to office — is a different matter. Many champions of the idea of 
 natural rights do not assert the natural right of every one to 
 have a vote. The suffrage, by all thoughtful persons at least, 
 is regarded as a means to the working of the constitution; and 
 the right of voting is obviously a right created by the law 
 (whether special constitutional law or ordinary law), and 
 cannot intelligibly be represented as a right prior to and in- 
 dependent of law. A constitution may be thought of as 
 existing in order that individuals may have security and 
 liberty ; but cannot logically be regarded as existing in order 
 that certain persons may have votes. On whom the suffrage 
 should be conferred is a matter not to be settled a priori, but 
 by reference to the particular circumstances of the country. 
 In this, as before, we have to consider what is safe, regard 
 being had both to external and internal dangers — the latter 
 including the discontent that is apt to arise from the refusal 
 of political rights that are enjoyed by others. 
 
 A high property qualification, or, at least, some property 
 qualification, is often urged as a necessary safeguard against 
 the political instability that is likely to follow from political 
 power passing into the hands of the more ignorant or the 
 more reckless part of the population. The revolutionary 
 Ireton,^ who appealed to the Law of Nature and of Nations 
 in justification of the right of resistance, thought it unwise 
 to give votes except to persons owning land ; ^ but tlien 
 
 1 Cf. Chap. I., p. 10. 
 
 * Mr. Firth {Clarke Papers, p. l.xx.) compares Iretoii's attitude to tlie
 
 256 EQUALITY [CH. xii 
 
 Ireton objected to the theory that a man had by " birthright " 
 any claim to a voice in the government of his country. To 
 him the claim of an equal right in all men to a vote seemed no 
 more reasonable than " an equal right in any goods he sees, 
 meat, drink, clothes, to take and use for his sustenance." 
 When, indeed, it is urged that representation should go along 
 with taxation, it is reasonable that no one should have a vote 
 who does not pay some taxes. In our local government a rate- 
 paying qualification is considered a reasonable limit. 
 
 But to make the voting power of different classes depend on 
 a ratio to the amount of direct taxes which they pay — as is 
 done in the Prussian " Three-Class System " — is open to the 
 objection that it conspicuously confers political privileges on the 
 wealthy, as such: it is thus a provocation of discontent. 
 Elaborate systems of " proportional representation " are open 
 to a similar objection ; they seem difficult to understand to the 
 ordinary person, and suggest an element of trickery, which 
 .<?ee?n.s' absent from an apparently simple phrase such as "one 
 man one vote." To introduce a property qualification where 
 there has been "universal suffrage," or to raise the property 
 qualification to one higher than before, are likewise dangerous 
 devices, because they would certainly create a sense of injustice. 
 On the other hand, the abolition of any provision for illiterate 
 voters, or the introduction of an educational test — after com- 
 pulsory and gratuitous education has been in operation for some 
 time — seems unobjectionable. To require "every voter to be 
 able to write his name, and to read any section of the Con- 
 stitution in the English language " — a proposition which has 
 been carried by popular vote in the State of California ^ — seems 
 a wise and reasonable method of checking the negro and foreign 
 
 proposals of the Levellers of 1G47 (see pp. B07, 308), with that of Lord 
 Braxfield to the Reformers of 1794. The latter, in his charge to the jury 
 in the trial of Thomas Muir, said : " A government in every country 
 should he just like a corporation, and in this country it is made up of 
 the landed interest, which alone has a right to be represented. As for the 
 rabble, who have nothing but personal property, what hold has the nation 
 of them? They may pack up their pi-operty on their backs and leave 
 the country in the twinkling of an eye, but landed property cannot be 
 removed." 
 
 ^ Oberholzer, The Referendum in America (Philadeljihia, 1898), p. 18. 
 This provision appeared in the Massachusetts Constitution of 1857, with 
 the qualification that it was not to apply to voters already on the register, 
 nor to persons over 60 years of age. 
 
 .^
 
 CH. xii] EQUALITY 257 
 
 vote. If with free education citizens do not qualify themselves 
 for a vote by learning a little of the language in which the 
 government of the country is carried on, it is their own fault, 
 and it might be possible even to require more than " reading a 
 section of the Constitution" from those who are called upon to 
 have a voice even indirectly in the government of their country, 
 without creating discontent, except among a portion of the 
 population who would be least likely to find supporters else- 
 where, save, indeed, from motives of faction. The partisan. 
 use which can always, unfortunately, be made of the grievance 
 of an excluded class, is indeed one argument for universal 
 suffrage. 
 
 When the suffrage is claimed for some hitherto excluded 
 class — e.g. for women — far too little is usually made of the 
 argument that the exercise of political rights has an educa- 
 tional value : there is too much appeal to the ambiguous claim 
 of " rights," and too little is said about the exercise of such 
 rights as the State bestows being the imposition of a public 
 duty on the individual citizen. To accentuate this aspect of 
 the suffrage, it would be very reasonable to impose a fine on 
 any elector who did not vote at an election, except for such 
 reasons as would be held to excuse a person liable to serve on 
 a jury absenting himself when summoned. Of course the 
 voter, coming to the poll under penalties, could not be pre- 
 vented from leaving his ballot-paper empty, or from filling it 
 up with opprobrious language ; but, even so, it would be very 
 important for the political statistician to find out what pro- 
 portion of the electors were unable to make up their minds, or 
 really despised and disliked their political rights. 
 
 Compulsory voting is not unknown in the history of 
 English-speaking communities. In the colony of Virginia, 
 it was enacted in 1646 that all freemen absent from an elec- 
 tion without lawful cause should be fined one hundreil pounds 
 of tobacco. " After 1662 the amount of the penalty was in- 
 creased to two hundred pounds of the same staple. The law 
 of compulsory voting was re-enacted in 1705, and again in 
 1763." ^ In the colony of Plymouth voting was also made 
 compulsory as early as 16a6. The arguments for compulsory 
 voting become especially strong where the electors have the 
 
 1 Corblandt F. Bishop, History of Elections in the American Colonies 
 (Columbia College Studies, Vol. III., No. 1), New York, 18!)i3, p. 191. 
 N. E. S
 
 258 EQUALITY [CH. xii 
 
 right and duty of voting directly on laws or on constitutional 
 amendments. Compulsion would be the best security against 
 the excessive preponderance of cliques, and against the very 
 fluctuating interest most people are apt to take in politics, and 
 would have the permanent merit of bringing before every 
 citizen his political responsibilities. 
 
 The claim of equality, in its widest sense, means the demand 
 for equal opportunity — the carriere ouverte mix talents. The 
 result of such eqnalit}^ of opportunity will clearly be the very 
 reverse of equality of social condition, if the law allows the 
 transmission of property from parent to child, or even the 
 accumulation of wealth by individuals. And thus, as has 
 often been pointed out, the effect of the nearly complete 
 triumph of the principles of 1789 — the abolition of legal re- 
 strictions on free competition — has been to accentuate the 
 difference between wealth and poverty. Equality in political 
 rights, along with great inequalities in social condition, has 
 laid bare " the social question " ; which is no longer concealed, 
 as it formerly was, behind the struggle for equality before the 
 law and for equality in political rights. As in the case of 
 liberty, our attention is called to the difference between 
 " formal " or " negative " and "real" or "positive" equality. 
 The abolition of legal restrictions on free competition allows 
 the natural inequalities of human beings, in vigour of body 
 and mind, to assert themselves. Even under a socialistic 
 regime, which fell short of a complete communism penetrating 
 to every detail of every individual's life, there would be in- 
 equalities of condition which, though they might seem slight 
 when looked at from the standpoint of all civilised societies 
 with which we are familiar, might prove extremely galling to 
 persons who were strongly possessed with the passion of level- 
 ling. That a society should have attained such stability of 
 economic conditions, and should be permeated by such a spirit 
 of discipline and of zeal for the common good that it was able 
 to provide work and comfortable subsistence for all its mem- 
 bers who were fit to work, with comfortable subsistence also 
 for all those physically unfit to work, and severe penalties, 
 rigidly carried out, for the idle and rebellious — such a society 
 may seem a satisfactory ideal to those who seek a remedy for 
 the most pressing of present discontents, and who believe that 
 the orderl}'' and sympathetic instincts of mankind are capable
 
 cii. xii] EQUALITY 259 
 
 of development ; but it would prove unsatisfactor}^ alike to the 
 enthusiast for individual liberty and to the dogmatic believer 
 in absolute equality. 
 
 Most of the advocates of the natural rights of liberty and 
 equality have not proposed to interfere legally with the insti- 
 tution of the family; some of them, indeed, have protested 
 against legislation which has diminished the customary rights 
 of parents over their children. But no real or positive equality 
 in social conditions can be secured so long as individuals are 
 looked at in any respect as members of families, and not in 
 every respect as members of the State alone. Suppose two 
 workmen receive equal wages, but the one has no children 
 and the other has six, all too young to earn anything, where 
 is the equality in the social condition of the individuals sup- 
 ported out of these equal wages ? Even under the system of 
 a compulsory minimum of education, has the child of incapable 
 or vicious parents — quite apart from his hereditary disadvan- 
 tages — an equal opportunit}^ given him, in any true sense, with 
 the child who has grown up in a careful and regular house- 
 hold '? For a great many purposes still, in spite of individual- 
 istic sentiment and socialistic legislation, the unit of society is 
 the family and not the individual. And we cannot think out 
 any social problem fairly without taking that fact into account. 
 Society is not yet at least, and possibly never will be, so 
 atomist as professed individualists and most of those who call 
 themselves Socialists imagine it to be. Even supposing very 
 great changes to take place in the character of the family 
 — changes of which the diminished control of husbands over 
 wives, of parents over children, may be taken as specimens — 
 the physical conditions of infancy and maternity will always 
 throw some difficulty in the way of the State regarding every 
 human being simply as an individual. The patriarchal famil}'', 
 in its literal sense, as the family in which the father rules over 
 his wife or wives and children — and possibly over household 
 slaves also — is the social unit, which, however late it may 
 come (according to some theories) in the social evolution of 
 the human race, is the chief bond of cohesion that we find 
 within the historical period, in all those peoples that have 
 developed a high civilisation. The growth of the power of 
 the State has everywhere tended to diiniiiish the })Ower of the 
 house-father over his subjects, and has made possible the social
 
 26o EQUALITY [ch. xii 
 
 existence of individuals owning no allegiance to any liouseliold 
 monarch. But the individualism, which asserts itself in the 
 reaction against the old social system, seems to be too chaotic 
 for humanity to rest in it ; and the State can only secure the 
 real well-being — I may add, the real liberty and equality (so far 
 as these are socially useful ends) — of its citizens, by taking over 
 the functions of which it deprives the family and performing 
 them in a higher and better way. Is any State that yet exists 
 anywhere prepared to do that, or fit to attempt it ? Yet all 
 modern States are consciously or unconsciously moving in that 
 direction. 
 
 The modern assertion of the equality of the sexes brings the 
 special difficulties of the problem more prominently before us 
 than anything else. The demand of women for equal political 
 rights with men is only a small part of the problem. It may 
 be noted, by the way, that this demand, though it had been 
 put forward by isolated thinkers, such as Thomas Paine, Con- 
 dorcet, and Mary AVollstonecraft, who applied the idea of 
 natural rights a little more logically than most of their con- 
 temporaries, did not become prominent in practical politics till 
 after the American civil war had put an end to the disabilities 
 of the blacks — in constitutional theory at least. The feeling 
 of racial superiority to the negro-voter was certainly an im- 
 portant factor in suggesting the absurdity of enfranchising 
 any black man while excluding every white woman. Simi- 
 larly, in this country, the enfranchisement of the agricultural 
 labourer has undoubtedly made the anomaly of the unen- 
 franchised woman taxpayer of the upper and middle classes 
 more conspicuous. Though the idea of female suffrage once 
 started may be more readily taken up among the women of 
 the poorer classes, the idea originated only among the men 
 and women of the middle classes.^ New ideas almost always 
 begin among the class that at the time is dominant, and work 
 downwards. As already said, the idea of equality seems pri- 
 
 ^ It is sometimes iirg;ed — as with other rights that are claimed — that 
 the right of women to the suffrage once existed, but has been put an end 
 to by the selfishness of men. Mr. Ostrogorski has shown that where 
 women in feudal times, as in Austria still, had an indirect right of voting, 
 the vote was really attached to property and not to persons. The first 
 effect of the modern democratic idea of the sufFi-age as a right belonging 
 to persons has been to abolish this apparent voting power of women. 
 See his Bights of Women.
 
 CH. xii] EQUALITY 261 
 
 maril}'- to be the outgrowth of an aristocratic sentiment ; it is 
 aristocracy passing over by a logical process to its own nega- 
 tion. 
 
 But the equality of the sexes implies much more than 
 equality in political rights and duties. As the opponents of 
 female suffrage and its more thoughtful advocates alike recog- 
 nise, the franchise would be chiefly valuable as a sj^mbol of social 
 equality. The economic independence of w^omen, even of those 
 who have become wives and mothers, is what the more logical 
 advocates of the equality of the sexes see to be necessary for 
 the real social equality of the woman with the man. This 
 leads many of them to object to all legislative interference 
 with the work of women. And yet, as things are, it is only 
 too clear that the competition of women in the labour-market 
 with men and with one another lowers the wages of men, so 
 that, as Mr. Charles Booth has shown, the characteristic of a 
 poorer class is the wage-earning of the women belonging to 
 it.^ The work of married women away from home is, moreover, 
 the source of great injury to their children : their work in 
 their homes is a principal cause of " sweating." But even if 
 the wage-earning of married women were entirely aboUshed, 
 in all old countries there are a vast number of unmarried 
 women and widows who are compelled to work for a living ; 
 and to them it is simple irony to say that women's proper 
 place is in the household, unless polygamy were made com- 
 pulsory on all men having more than a certain income. 
 Household industries, moreover, have disappeared, the word 
 '•spinster" has lost its meaning, and the male head of the 
 household, in losing his ancient privileges, can no longer be 
 expected to make himself responsible for all the women of the 
 family, when he is not able to marry them off by compulsion. 
 The modern widow cannot so easily adopt the methods of 
 Naomi and Ruth without reproach. Trade-unions among 
 women workers may help to raise some of them to a better 
 economic level ; but a large number must always be excluded, 
 and if married women who are mothers become to any great 
 extent economically independent of their husbands, this can 
 only lead to a general lowering of wages, diminution of com- 
 fort, and decay of physique. Women who are mothers can, as 
 a general rule, only attain economic independence by receiving 
 ' Life and Labour of the People (2nd edit.), Vol. I. p. 50.
 
 262 EQUALITY [ch. xii 
 
 State-support. But, as I have already pointed out/ the State 
 cannot safely undertake the legal responsibilities of the 
 husband without having a choice in its wives. 
 
 The Socialistic ideal of the State must still be Plato's ideal, 
 i.e. the State must be regarded as one family, in which all 
 shall work according to their capacity and receive according to 
 their needs — an ideal which requires a very high level of sym- 
 path}^, but which has no connection with any abstract principle 
 of equality. In saying this, I do not mean that the State need 
 make any regulations about the relations of the sexes in viola- 
 tion of the religious and moral sentiments of the community. 
 The Platonic ideal may be impossible of realisation, but a very 
 considerable legal limitation of the right of parentage would 
 be quite compatible with the continued recognition of mono- 
 gamy as a moral, though no longer as an economic, institution. 
 It might even be argued that only under such conditions would 
 monogamy as a moral institution be fairly tried. In the 
 absence of difficulties about property and about the proper 
 maintenance of children, the attachment of women as well as 
 of men to monogamy would be experimentally tested in a 
 manner at present impossible. Whether any such very great 
 economic change would not tend to alter many moral ideas 
 may very well be asked. Of this, however, we may be certain, 
 that no community can hold together for any length of time 
 unless its institutions and customs are in harmony with the 
 moral sentiments of its members and the ideas of religious 
 duty which they have come to hold, 
 
 1 Cf. above, pp. 129-134.
 
 CHAPTEE XIII 
 
 THE EIGHT OF PROPERTY 
 
 The confusions which permeate the theory of natural rights 
 come out most conspicuously of all in the case of the right of 
 property. With regard to property there are three questions 
 which should be carefully distinguished from one another : 
 (1) How does the right of property originate ? This is a 
 purely historical question, and does not directly and for its 
 own sake concern us here. In discussing rights which are 
 alleged to be natiu-al, we are dealing with a different ques- 
 tion, viz. — (2) What is the justification of the right of 
 property? But we cannot discuss that question fairly, 
 unless we consider also the question — (3) What does the 
 right of property at any given time and place imply ? This 
 question involves a whole series of different questions, such 
 as : — What objects may be held as property ? How far does 
 the right of property over these objects extend ? Does the 
 right of property imply only the right of using, or also the 
 right of using up (jus ahutendi) ? Does it involve the right 
 of destroying in the case of things that can be used with- 
 out being destroyed, as well as in the case of things that perish 
 in the using ? Does it include the right of alienating ? And 
 does the right of alienation include the right of bequest ? And, 
 if bequest, with or without limitation ? Further, in what sense 
 is there any right of individual property against the State ? 
 In the discussion of such questions we should be compelled to 
 consider the actual historical origin and development of pro- 
 perty, public and private, in its different forms {i.e. our first 
 question is really only a part of our third). Now, I cannot 
 attempt to write a history of property. That can only be 
 satisfactorily done by the combined labours of many anthropo- 
 logists, historians and lawyers. I onlj'' wish to point out that 
 " the right of property," which has been said to be a natural 
 right in many Declarations, is a very ambiguous phrase. 
 
 263
 
 264 THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY [ch. xiii 
 
 People are too ready to dispute about the good or evil of 
 property, or of " private property," as if every one was 
 agreed on what it means. 
 
 In the Constitution framed for the State of Kansas, and 
 adopted by the pro-slavery party in 1857, the 7th article 
 contains these words : " The right of property is before and 
 higher than any constitutional sanction [Locke's theory, it 
 will be noted, as distinct from Hobbes's], and the right of the 
 owner of a slave to such slave and its [.sic] increase is the same 
 and as inviolable as the right of the owner of any property 
 whatever." ^ This seems to most of us, probably, a very start- 
 ling claim, but I cannot see that there is any greater a priori 
 objection to it than to any other alleged natural right — so long 
 as we simply appeal to " Nature," and do not consider social 
 expediency. In the Bill of Rights which forms part of the 
 constitution which was adopted by the anti-slavery party in 
 Kansas, in 1858, it is declared that " All men are by nature 
 equally free and independent," etc., and then that " the right 
 of all men to the control of their persons exists prior to law, 
 and is inalienable." I assume that the framers of this phrase 
 did not really mean that the right is so inalienable that a con- 
 victed felon has a claim to the control of his own person ; but, 
 like their opponents, they were only constructing a major 
 premise from which to deduce a conclusion favourable to their 
 side in the controversy about negro slavery, and were not very 
 careful about its literal truth. 
 
 Now, here is " a very prett}'- quarrel " among the believers 
 in inalienable natural rights ; and it has needed a civil war to 
 settle the dispute. Most Americans think that in their declara- 
 tions of natural rights they have a security against those 
 socialistic interferences with liberty and property to which our 
 carelessness on the question of natural rights and our unlimited 
 sovereign legislature leave us exposed. But supposing that 
 public opinion, and it is to be hoped without a civil war, were 
 to be convinced that certain other forms of private property, 
 besides property in human beings, were incompatible with the 
 equal freedom and independence of all men, no amount of 
 declarations of natural rights could bar the way to a torrent of 
 socialistic legislation, nor could a multitude of constitutional 
 
 ' This clause is taken word for word from the Kentucky Constitution 
 of 1850, and was still there in 1890.
 
 CH. xiii] THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY 265 
 
 checks do an3''thing except render the conflict of old and new 
 ideas more dangerous to the public peace. Sooner or later the 
 constitutional lawyers would have to put a different interpreta- 
 tion on the word " property " from that which their predeces- 
 sors put upon it. A declaration of rights can never have more 
 than a moral force, and may come to lose that. 
 
 The French Declaration of Rights of 1791 {i.e. the Declara- 
 tion framed in 1789) lays down that " the right of property 
 being inviolable and sacred, no one ought to be deprived of it, 
 except in cases of evident public necessity, legally ascertained, 
 and on conditions of previous just indemnity." The Declara- 
 tion of 1793 lays down that " the right of property is that 
 which belongs to every citizen to enjoy and to dispose at his 
 will of his goods, his revenues, the fruit of his toil and 
 industry." This is the formula framed under Girondist influ- 
 ence. In the Declaration put forward by Robespierre and his 
 followers in the Jacobin Club, the corresponding clause is 
 worded in a manner that would, I think, commend itself better 
 to an English lawyer. " Property is the right which every 
 citizen has to enjoy and to dispose of that portion of his goods 
 which is guaranteed to him by the law." But even the Giron- 
 dist Declaration does not make the right of property absolute 
 as against the State ; for a subsequent clause recognises, in 
 almost the same phrases as are used in the Declaration of 1791, 
 the right of the State to take property from the individual, 
 under conditions. " No one can be deprived of the least por- 
 tion of his property without his consent, unless when public 
 necessity, legally ascertained, demands it, and under the con- 
 dition of a previous just indemnity." And the right of taxa- 
 tion for purposes of general utility, and under popular control, 
 is recognised in the following section. 
 
 The fifth Amendment to the Constitution of the United 
 States of America declares that private property shall not be 
 taken for public use "without just compensation." None of these 
 written constitutions define the term " just." None of them 
 are so rash as to attempt to answer the question of Socrates : 
 " What is Justice ? " So that what is " just compensation " 
 must ultimately depend on public opinion at the time when 
 the compensation comes to be given, as much as in Great 
 Britain, where there is no written constitution, and where we 
 have hitherto got on somehow without declaring our natural
 
 266 THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY [ch. xiii 
 
 rights. It may also be pointed out that " legally ascertained " 
 or " due process of law " is a phrase to which different ages 
 and countries would give a very different meaning. 
 
 The attempts to base the right of property on the Law of 
 Nature take two principal forms : in both of these we see the 
 influence of that sense of " nature " in which the natural means 
 what is least affected by human institutions. There is the 
 theory which bases property on occujpation, and there is the 
 theory which bases it on labour. 
 
 The theory which bases property on the occupation of what 
 is previously unoccupied represents the facts of the most 
 primitive condition of human society. "We may go lower even 
 than human society. When a cat catches a mouse, and there 
 is no stronger or cleverer animal about to dispute possession, 
 the mouse, in a very intelligible sense, becomes that cat's 
 property ; and of course the cat can make her title under the 
 Law of Nature quite secure bj^ depositing the mouse in the 
 internal safe with which Nature has provided her. Similarly, 
 when a bird has taken an unoccupied site for her nest, we may 
 consider that the bird has at least a temporary right of property 
 in that site. So it is with human beings in the hunting and 
 fishing stage. As a matter of fact, whoever can catch may 
 keep, unless a stronger deprives him of his prey. We may call 
 that the Law of Nature if we like. Possession, as we say, is 
 nine points of the law, and it is so even among the animals ; 
 because, unless food is scarce, as a rule it is less trouble to go 
 and find for one's self than to have the trouble and risk of fight- 
 ing. Only a very pugnacious sparrow will fight for another 
 sparrow's crumb instead of looking out for an unoccupied 
 crumb. 
 
 But when reflective human beings wish to find a good 
 reason for the right of the first occupier, they are not content 
 to base it simply on force and on the convenience to the 
 individual. They seek a social reason for it. And, obviously, 
 unless the right of the first occupier had some good utilitarian 
 justification, it would not in the long run have been recognised 
 by flourishing societies. The first occupier, it is said — by 
 Locke ^ for instance — has a right to keep and use, so long as 
 there is enough and as good left over for others. This, it may 
 ^ Treatise of Civil Government, II. ch. v. §§ 32, 33.
 
 CH. XI 1 1] THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY 267 
 
 be noted, is the principle of "equal liberty" in that modified 
 form in which " similar " is substituted for " same."^ But this 
 is a justification of the right of the first occupier which must 
 perpetually diminish with the growth of population. The best 
 land, not necessarily the most fertile, but the most conveni- 
 ently situated, will be first taken up, and the later comers as 
 a rule have to content themselves with what is inferior. Yet, 
 if they were to plead this law of nature — the law of equal 
 rights — they might all claim to get equally good land ; and 
 these natural rights would have to be decided by a vast amount 
 of natural litigation, i.e. fighting. As a matter of fact, people 
 take what they can get, and are content with the inferior, 
 unless they are very pugnacious, in which case they act like 
 the pugnacious sparrow aforementioned, but at a vastly greater 
 risk, because they have not merely other individuals against 
 them, but individuals who are holding together in some sort of 
 society.- If I go to borrow a book from a circulating library, 
 and the most desirable books are out already, I do not, if I am 
 a fairly reasonable person, make a row because according to 
 the law of nature no one has a right to any books unless equally 
 good books are left for all. I am content to abide by the rules 
 of the librar}', whatever they may be. If I do not like them, I 
 may try to get them altered. But the rights, in any case, are 
 determined by a society, and do not exist prior to the society. 
 Thus, so far as the right of the first occupier is still recognised 
 as a basis for the valid holding of property, it is because the 
 society in question recognises the rule as socially convenient, or 
 at least has not yet come to feel it specially inconvenient. It 
 is only " natural," either in the sense of being socially expedient, 
 or in the sense of being a survival of the primitive prevalence 
 of force, tempered by fear and by laziness. 
 
 In the dealings of nations with one another we have clear 
 survivals of this state of nature. International law recognises 
 the right of the first occupier : that is to say, nations generally 
 
 1 Cf. above, p. 143. 
 
 ' Cf. Prof. Huxley, Evolution and Ethics (Romanes Lecture), p. 10. 
 " Wolves could not hunt in packs except for the real, though unexpressed, 
 iinderstanding that they should not attack one another during the chase. 
 The most rudimentary polity is a pack of men living under the like tacit 
 or expressed convention, and having made the very important advance 
 upon wolf society, that they agree to use the force of the wliole body 
 against individuals who violate it, and in favour of those virho observe it."
 
 268 THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY [ch. xiii 
 
 acquiesce in the seizure of unoccupied territory by other 
 nations, because it is usually more convenient to seize for one's 
 self than to fight with other nations, unless a specially favour- 
 able opportunity arises. It need hardly be said that unoccupied 
 territory means practically, for this purpose, territory unoccupied 
 by other civilised or by other powerful nations, though the 
 formal consent or the supposed benefit of the natives may be 
 needed to satisfy the conqueror's conscience. ^ Reflection on 
 what is beneficial to humanity as a whole gradually — very 
 gradually — begins to mitigate the primitive law of nature, 
 which, as I have said, is simply the law of force tempered 
 by fear and by laziness. 
 
 The theory which bases the right of property upon labour 
 represents likewise what we find among animals and among 
 savages. A pair of birds build a nest, and the nest then 
 becomes the nest of these birds. The savage builds a hut for 
 himself and his mate, and it becomes his hut until a stronger 
 tribe comes and seizes or destroys it. He may be said to own 
 the materials and the site by the right of first occupation, and 
 the finished hut by the right of labour. Grotius, in criticising 
 the Eoman Jurist Paulus, who had already anticipated 
 Locke's theory and made labour a justification of property, 
 points out that, since nothing can be made except out of pre- 
 existing matter, acquisition by means of labour depends 
 ultimately on possession by means of occupation.^ So far as 
 any such rights, whether based on labour or on occupation, are 
 recognised in a more complicated society, this only means that 
 the society recognises them as advantageous to itself, or has 
 not yet come to feel them disadvantageous. In a complicated 
 society there is no such thing as individual labour, unless 
 a person were purposely to isolate himself and live like a 
 savage ; and even then it would only be by the recognised law 
 and custom of the society that he could maintain his isolation 
 
 ' The conversion of the Indians to Christianity was, no doubt quite 
 sincerely, alleged as a justification of the Spanish conquests in America. 
 The Puritans in New England, like the Dutch settlers at the Cape, were 
 sometimes influenced by the Scriptural example of the utter destruction 
 of the Canaanites. Now-a-days, the consent of the native community or 
 of their chiefs is generally thought necessary to a good title in Interna- 
 tional Law. See Maine, International Laiv, pp. 71 — 75. 
 
 ^ Grotius, De Jure Belli et Pads, II. iii. § 3.
 
 CH. xiii] THE BIGHT OF PROPERTY 269 
 
 unmolested. Mr. Edward Carpenter/ in his polemic against 
 civilisation, calls the policeman a " parasite." In a crowded 
 country the policeman is only a part of the orderly organisation 
 which makes it possible for the peaceable citizen to abuse 
 civilisation at his ease. Locke, in propounding his theory of 
 property, recognises fully that to the making of a loaf of bread 
 in a civilised community there go an immense number of 
 industries besides that of the baker; but he does not recognise, 
 as he should have done, that those who keep the peace within 
 the society, those who defend it from attack from without, and 
 those who in any way advance the orderliness and the intelli- 
 gence of the society and its power over nature, all contribute 
 their share to the making even of a loaf of bread. So that 
 when we come to consider fairly the question, " Whose is the 
 loaf ? " 2 not merely the miller, the farmer, the ironworker, the 
 miner may put in their claim for a portion, but the magistrate, 
 the policeman, the soldier, the man of science, the schoolmaster. 
 All labour in a civilised society is social and not individual 
 labour ; and therefore no law of nature helps us to determine 
 a priori how the produce of labour ought to be distributed. 
 
 To some persons, indeed, a great part of the highly paid work 
 of the world, the work of the lawyer or the merchant, for in- 
 stance, or the work of the general and of the of&cials of the AVar 
 Office, may seem useless or even mischievous work, while the 
 work of the " labouring man " seems honest in comparison. To 
 this it need only be answered that the mere fact of work being 
 manual does not make it socially beneficial. The enterprising 
 capitalist who puts adulterated or deleterious goods in the 
 market may be more morally blameworthy than the workmen 
 he employs to execute his nefarious plot upon the community ; 
 but it cannot be pretended that these workmen are conferring 
 any benefit upon society. And, if they deserve credit simply 
 because they are busy — no matter at what — the same plea 
 must serve for many of those whom the " labourer," or the 
 labourer's advocate, calls " parasites." What industries should 
 be permitted at all, and how the product of industry is to be 
 divided among the community, must in all cases be determined 
 by social arrangements which the State tolerates or brings into 
 being ; and every society in the long run seeks to discover what 
 
 ^ Civilisation — Its Cause and its Cure, p. 10, 
 
 * Not the loafer's !— unless society thinks it expedient to uuuntaiu him.
 
 2 70 THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY [ch. xiii 
 
 social arrangements are the best for its well-being as a whole. 
 We can only allow natural rights to be talked about in the 
 sense in which natural rights mean those legal or customary 
 rights which we have come to think or may come to think it 
 most advantageous to recognise. Of course, in this question of 
 what is advantageous, it is very important to consider how any 
 change, if a change is considered desirable, can be brought 
 about with the least amount of friction. Thus, if it has come 
 to be thought that any particular form of private property is 
 inexpedient, it would be disadvantageous to a society to take 
 away that right of private property without what the com- 
 munity at large would consider "just compensation," unless 
 the community at large, and not merely some fanatical section 
 of it, came to consider that form of property so immoral, i.e. so 
 socially inexpedient, that it held " just compensation " to mean 
 " no compensation at all," and the mere absence of a criminal 
 prosecution to be the extreme of charity. But, as has been 
 iterated throughout these pages, all such questions are best 
 discussed without dragging in those vague and rhetorical 
 appeals to the Law of Nature. 
 
 As a final example of the ambiguities in these theories of 
 natural rights, let me take the dispute between those two 
 scholastic theologians, Mr. Henry George and Pope Leo XIII. 
 Both of them adopt the theory which bases private property 
 on labour. The Pope justifies private ownership of land on 
 the same ground as Locke, that man has mixed his labour 
 with it {Encyclical of May, 1891), and also on the ground 
 that a man with his honestly-earned savings may buy land. 
 To the latter argument Mr. George very pertinently replies 
 that it would justify slavery, wherever savings had been 
 invested in human flesh. ^ To the former he might have 
 answered that the legitimate occupation of the land is pre- 
 supposed. Mr. George himself argues that the right of pro- 
 perty, since it originates in the right of the individual to him- 
 self, " attaches only to things produced by labour, but cannot 
 attach to things created by God." " Thus," he continues, "if 
 a man take a fish from the ocean he acquires a right of property 
 in that fish, which exclusive right he may transfer by sale or 
 gift. But he cannot obtain a similar right of property in the 
 ocean, so that he may sell it or give z7, or forbid others to use 
 ^ The Condition of Labour, p. 35.
 
 CH. xiii] THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY 271 
 
 y'^." Mr. George apparently thinks that man produces the fish 
 by his labour ; but surely much land in the world is more 
 man's product than any fishes in the open sea. How Mr. 
 George expects His Holiness the Pope to believe that God did 
 not create the fish, in the same sense as that in which He 
 created the land, I may leave as a problem to those persons 
 who care for that casuistry of natural rights, of which I have 
 given a quite sufficient number of specimens.^ 
 
 ^ I have discussed Locke's tlieorj^ of property somewhat more full^- in 
 an essay, under that title, included in Darwin and Hegel, etc.
 
 CHAPTER XIV 
 
 THE RIGHT OF PURSUING AND OBTAINING HAPPINESS 
 
 The right, not merely of pursuing but of obtaining happiness, 
 which is named as one of the natural rights of man in most 
 American State Constitutions, ma}'' seem, in this world of ours, 
 to be a very large order on the bank of Providence. The right 
 of pursuing happiness is clearly only a generalised form in 
 which is asserted the right of the individual to be left alone 
 in his conduct. The right to pursue happiness may be quite 
 compatible with the right to be left to suffer the effects of 
 one's own folly, though it might also suggest a right to be 
 protected against the folly, as well as against the wilful malice, 
 of other people. But a right to obtain happiness — if it means 
 anything more than the right to pursue happiness — when such 
 a right is guaranteed by the State to its citizens, involves a 
 recognition, however implicit and unconscious, that the func- 
 tion of the State is not merely the negative function of secur- 
 ing to the individual certain rights as against other individuals, 
 but the positive function of aiding him in the attainment of 
 his desires, so far as these are compatible with the general 
 well-being. If the guarantee of a right of obtaining happi- 
 ness has any definite and specific meaning, it means the same 
 thing as the assertion in the first Article of the French 
 Declaration of 1793, that " the end of society is the common 
 happiness {le honheuf commun).^^ No such Article occurs in 
 the Declaration of 1789, and many of those who have de- 
 fended "the principles of '89" have pointed to this article in 
 the forefront of the Constitution of 1793 as a proof of falling 
 away from the sane and sober doctrines of the earlier creed of 
 the E-evolution. 
 
 There is no doubt that the recognition of happiness as the 
 end of government — still more the recognition of the common 
 happiness as the end — involves a departure from the strict 
 individualism with which, as we have seen, the doctrine of
 
 CH. xiv] THE RIGHT OF PURSUING HAPPINESS 273 
 
 natural rights is most properly connected. It is true, also, 
 that the term "happiness" may be interpreted in such a way 
 that the making of it the direct end of government would 
 justify tyranny, and would logicall}^ lead to a refusal of those 
 other rights of liberty and of the jmrstdt of happiness which 
 were chiefly in the minds of those who began the American 
 and the French Revolutions. If happiness meant, as the 
 Hedonist Utilitarian professes to make it mean, simply a sum 
 of pleasures and absence of pains, then undoubtedly such 
 happiness might be best secured by a powerful and skilful 
 ruling caste keeping the mass of the people, if possible, in 
 comfortable and contented ignorance, taking care that they 
 were fed and amused, saved from the anxiety and misery of 
 the struggle for existence and of the struggle for intellectual 
 and moral progress. "We have seen already (in Chapters V, 
 and XII.) that this is not pr ad icaJJij what the great Utilitarian 
 reformers have meant by " happiness," whatever logical con- 
 sistency might have obliged them to admit. Nor is it what 
 the mass of mankind have commonly meant by happine.ss ; 
 for the contrast between " real and true ha])piness" on the one 
 side, and " pleasure" on the other, is a commonplace of popular 
 moralising. Still less can any such conception of " happiness '' 
 — as a sum of pleasures — be retained as a conception of the 
 ethical end by the Evolutionist Utilitarian. Since, on the 
 confession of John Stuart Mill himself, happiness is something 
 that can only be attained by not being pursued,^ — since, accord- 
 ing to Clifford, the individual's happiness is irrelevant to the 
 welfare of the social organism, except in so far as it makes 
 him a more efficient member,'- it would be better in ethics to 
 give up the use of the term altogether as a desigiiation of the 
 moral end, adopting some vaguer but less misleading term, 
 such as "welfare" or " well-being." "^ Such a term would 
 suggest the two elements both of which must enter into any 
 conception of the ethical end that avoids the onesidedness 
 alike of Asceticism and of Hedonism — the element of right 
 conduct, virtuous action, icell-doing^ and the element of favour- 
 
 ' Autobiography, p. 142. 
 
 2 Lectures and Essays, II. pp. 122, 173. Cf. above, p. 99. 
 
 ^ Suggested in Prof. Fowler's Progressive Morality (pp. 99, 100), as 
 corresponding best to Aristotle's (vbai^jiovia. Kant's use of tlie term 
 " Eudaemonism ". has led to much misunderstanding of Aristotle. 
 
 X. R. T
 
 2 74 1HE RIGHT OF PURSUING [ch. xiv 
 
 able environment, pleasure, or, as we can say in English, of doing 
 well in the sense of faring well. Furthermore, the idea of wel- 
 fare is more applicable to a community than the idea of happi- 
 ness. Nevertheless, popular usage allows us to speak of a nation 
 being "liapp}'," and popular usage may make it convenient and 
 permissible in politics to retain the term " happiness " as ex- 
 pressive of the end. For ethics happiness appears rather the 
 external and accidental element in the end — the word has 
 never entirely lost its association with " hap'' ; — it depends on 
 favourable circumstances^ whether right conduct is unimpeded' 
 or not. But since politics is concerned with the providing of 
 these favourable circumstances, and can only indirectly affect 
 the right conduct of the individual, happiness may be said to 
 be the end for politics. 
 
 With due qualifications as to the meaning of the term, nearly 
 every one, except the most rigid sticklers for the " principles 
 of '89 " in their most narrowly individualist form, would now-a- 
 days allow that the happiness of the citizens ought to be 
 included among the ends of government. How far this end 
 can be attained by leaving people alone, and how far it can be 
 attained by interference — on this the great practical differences 
 of opinion would begin. "Where some would lay more stress 
 on the need of directly removing obstacles to physical health, 
 to intellectual and moral development, others would lay more 
 stress on the need of " freedom,''— on the need of letting people 
 learn even by mistakes and failures, in order that their ultimate 
 progress maybe more secure. The desire to see "England free 
 rather than compulsorily sober " meant the fear that compulsory 
 abstinence from vice, and even from morally neutral actions, 
 might make virtue impossible. And so if anyone would rather 
 see his country free than happy, it is because he fears that hap- 
 piness obtained at the cost of freedom would mean a lower kind 
 of happiness, and an impediment to the pursuit of any higher 
 kind. On the other hand, those who argue for compulsion are 
 
 * Aristotle's tvTV)(la, to. €<t6s dyadd, 
 
 ^ Pleasure is iufpytia duefinodia-TOi, Eth. Nlc. VII. 12, § 3 ^^not, in any 
 way, inconsistent with X. 4, § 8). In Pol., IV. 11, § 3. and VII. 13, § 5, 
 the teaching of Eth. Nic, I. 7, §§ 14-16, is combined with the accounts of 
 Pleasure in Books VII. and X.: the chief good {evSaifiovia) is "the 
 unimpeded realisation of excellence." I do not think these Aristotelian 
 definitions have been superseded or surpassed. We are only getting 
 back to his sane and scientific way of regarding the ethical end.
 
 CH. xiv] AXD OBTAINING HAPPINESS -75 
 
 bound to show that it will do more than produce an immediate 
 absence of certain evils : they are bound to show that it will 
 set free energies tor good which are at present impeded : and 
 those who wish to make people '• happy '' by legislation must 
 prove that the happiness will help and not hinder their pro- 
 gress. You could make a great many people " happy " for a 
 short time I by making them drunk ; but the wise legislator 
 will prefer more roundabout methods, even methods such as 
 education and political liberty, which may make people more 
 acateh- sensible of their misery. The general aspects of such 
 discussions I have alreadj^ had to deal with in connection with 
 the alleged natural right of liberty : and it has been my chief 
 endeavour to show that particular practical solutions cannot 
 be given a priori, but must depend on time, place, and circum- 
 stances. 
 
 The reader may complain that after all these tedious and 
 intricate discussions on matters that closely concern political 
 practice, I give no practical help ; I do not tell him *' what to 
 do."' In answer, I might say, in the first place, that my object 
 has not been to preach, to exhort, to rouse to enthusiastic 
 action ; there are plenty of people engaged in doing that, more 
 or less efiectively, more or less wisely. However I may have 
 failed of my object, my object has been scientific, to expose 
 confusions, to set those people thinking who can be induced to 
 think. For science does not only consist in accumulating facts, 
 in arranging statistics ; it involves a criticism of terms, an 
 examination of phrases, which are apt to deceive, if, though 
 worthless or worn out, they are accepted as good sound coin. 
 '• We shall never think rightly in politics until we have cleared 
 our minds of delusions," Professor Huxley has admirably said ; ' 
 and this " clearing our minds " in regard to a certain set of 
 famous political phrases is all that I have set m3'self to do. 
 If any one thinks sach merely critical work to be unworthy 
 the name of Political Science, I shall not quarrel with him. 
 For m^-self I prefer to call it by the reall}- more modest, though 
 seemingly more high-sounding name of "philosophy" — not 
 wisdom or •' s^^stematic knowledge," but the eflbrt after know- 
 ledge. '■ Philosophy" has been well defined as *' a criticism of 
 categories," i.e. of fundamental conceptions. 
 
 ' Collected Essay<f. Vol. I., Method and Results, p. 424.
 
 2 76 THE RIGHT OF PURSUING [ch. xiv 
 
 Bat, tliougli my procedure has been professedly critical, I do 
 not think that the result is entirely negative. Any one who 
 chose could pick out of the foregoing pages considerable 
 fragments of a constructive creed : whether he would then 
 accept this creed is another matter. The demand, that if one 
 criticises, one must construct, is a just demand to this extent 
 only — that criticisms in order to be listened to, and to be intel- 
 ligible, must proceed from a fairly consistent standpoint : 
 but they do not need to be made on the basis of a completed 
 dogmatic system. It would not be legitimate criticism, for 
 instance, to use strictly individualist arguments in criticising 
 socialism, and then to use the assumptions of dogmatic socialism 
 in criticising individualism. But in order to see the weakness 
 in the logic of individualism one need not be a dogmatic and 
 uncompromising socialist : and in order to see the weakness in 
 the practical schemes supported by socialists one need not lie 
 an advocate of universal Jaissez-faive. It is possible to believe 
 that political and social develo^Dment is proceeding in a certain 
 direction and must proceed in that direction, if violent revolu- 
 tion is to be averted ; and yet to feel very uncertain as to the 
 precise form which society is likely to assume in fifty years' 
 time, or in the remote future, and to be rather sceptical about 
 the value of certain remedies which are commonly advocated 
 as if they were panaceas. 
 
 It seems to me perfectly certain that in all civilised coun- 
 tries there is an unconscious, as well as a conscious, tendency 
 in what can be most conveniently described as a socialistic or 
 "collectivist " direction. The economic tendency is, on the 
 whole, towards the concentration and depersonalisation of 
 capital : the company with salaried officials replaces the 
 " capitalist," of whom old-fashioned economists and popular 
 agitators continue to speak. The older questions of political 
 liberty and of national independence are settled, or approach 
 settlement, onl}^ to make way for the " social question." In 
 philosophy, in ethical theories, in religious movements, in 
 popular sentiment there is a tendency, more rapid and pro- 
 nounced in some quarters than in others, away from the 
 individualism which we have come to think of as characteristic 
 of the last century and not of this. The reaction against the 
 French Revolution, the Romantic movement in literature, with 
 its return to mediaeval ideals, the Catholic revival bringing
 
 CH. xiv] AND OBTAINING HAP PI NESS 277 
 
 back the religious value of the idea of an actual community or 
 corporate bod}^, the truer understanding of the Hellenic spirit 
 with its idealisation of the State, the biological conceptions 
 of evolution and organism supplanting in social theory the 
 older conceptions of a mechanical aggregate and of the merely 
 external relation of contract — all these movements and ten- 
 dencies in thought, some of them connected with one another, 
 others working separately and in seeming antagonism, have 
 contributed to produce a new wa}^ of dealing with practical 
 social problems, unlike that which commendied itself to the 
 political thinkers of the last centur}'', and of the earlier part 
 of this.^ The enormous growth of town populations, due to 
 " the industrial revolution," has made the suffering and the 
 uncertain conditions of life, if not always greater, certainly 
 more conspicuous than they were before. Social problems 
 stare every one in the face, and socialistic instead of individu- 
 alistic solutions are now the more frequently proposed. 
 But along with a great deal of socialistic talk there goes the 
 old individualist logic of the ethics of Bentham or even of 
 Hobbes, and theories of natural rights in their crudest forms 
 survive alongside of new political ideals, which appeal 
 to sentiment without having been fully thought out. The 
 phrases " social organism " and " evolution " are on every- 
 body's lips, but those who use them most frequently have 
 often grasped their significance the least. 
 
 Believing that a transformation of society'- is in process, 
 more far-reaching perhaps in its ultimate effects than the 
 break-up of mediaeval society which culminated in the great 
 French Revolution, I believe also that this transformation can- 
 not take place safely or without much loss and much suffering 
 in any country, unless there is a corresponding transformation 
 in ideas, in sentiments, in ideals of life — a transformation at 
 least as great as those changes which we call the Renaissance 
 and the Reformation combined. For this reason I do not 
 shrink from saying that I hope the transformation will not 
 take place rapidly. Those who have pictured their full-blown 
 Collectivist society are very apt to be impatient for its 
 
 ' Note, for instance, the dift'arence between the older religious "ri'vival- 
 ism " and the " Salvation Army," which is an organisation to begin with, 
 and which does not shrink from schemes of bettering the material con- 
 ditions of human souls.
 
 -^7S THE RIGHT OF PURSUING [ch. xiv 
 
 realisation, and, amid the social miseiy and dissatisfacticn of 
 which \ve have become acutely conscious, their impatience is 
 excusable. Those who venture to hint at doubts and diffi- 
 culties, and to point out that the existing structure of society 
 cannot be altogether evil if it really contains the germs out of 
 which a better society is to be evolved, are apt to be re- 
 proached with selfishness or to be scoffed at as hmirgeoia per- 
 sons — " bourgeois-^ having rather an ugly sound in the English 
 language, and having for the purposes of abuse the additional 
 and indisputable advantage of beginning with the letter b. 
 The reproach of possessing a "middle-class" mind may not 
 seem to every one a reproach: the so-called middle-class and 
 the upper-class have hitherto provided the leaders and cham- 
 pions of the " proletariat," and the severest attacks on the 
 middle-class are all of middle-class origin. Nor is this to be 
 wondered at ; for it is only those who have had the oppor- 
 tunities of contact with varied ideas who are likely to initiate 
 new movements, and it is decidedly to the credit of a class 
 that it can produce and tolerate hostile criticism. The term 
 bouyrjeais ought to carrj^ the opposite of reproach: it is the 
 burgher^ the citizen, who has kept up those institutions of 
 orderh' and responsible government, which only in modern 
 times have been extended to large numbers previously ex- 
 cluded. And our ideals for the future must, at the least, not 
 be placed lower in the scale of civilisation than the civic 
 institutions of the best sort in the past. If we look at human 
 history as a whole, we see how recent and how rare civilisa- 
 tion has been ; and, in striving after an extension of its benefits 
 to larger numbers, we must be ver}' careful that, if possible, 
 none of the hardly accumulated gains of humanity be lost in 
 the process To prevent such loss we must be content, we 
 must even be glad, if the transition to a new form of society 
 takes place more slowly than some enthusiasts desire. Any 
 attempt to transform institutions suddenly is certain to bring 
 disaster, to involve loss, and to provoke reaction. We may 
 envy the feelings of exhilaration with which the earlier stages 
 of the French Revolution were greeted by generous spirits in 
 other lands as well as in France ; but the bitter disillusions 
 and the dreary years of reaction and oppression which followed 
 remain as a salutary warning, if only we can learn by it. 
 
 Another reason why progress must be gradual is that no one
 
 CH. xiv] AND OBTAINING HAPPINESS 277 
 
 nation can solve social problems apart from other nations. 
 The solidarity of the interests of the working classes through- 
 out the world is recognised by socialists in -words; but in their 
 practical proposals there lurks the same confusion between the 
 rights of the citizen and the rights of man which Bentham 
 pointed out long ago in criticising the French Declarations of 
 Rights. What becomes of this solidarity of interests Vjetween 
 the workers of the world, when land nationalisation is taken to 
 imply the absolute right of the existing inhabitants of a 
 country, however they ma^^ originally have come there, to 
 shut the door in the face of all the rest of mankind ? On the 
 other hand, where is the consistency between approving the 
 trade-unionist's indignation at " blacklegs" and yet permitting 
 the immigration of aliens ? And if aliens are to be excluded 
 iDecause they may lower the rate of -^-ages, how does that 
 policy differ in principle from a policy of protective tariffs ? 
 (That it may differ very much in its actual effect on the 
 majority of the population there is not much doubt.j A work- 
 man who perhaps calls liimself a Socialist, and who may even 
 boast that he has outgrown patriotic prejudice, may be heard 
 complaining that the British consumer buys articles " made in 
 Germany " ; he does not reflect that he is living on wheat 
 grown in America or in Russia. Starvation or exile for a large 
 number would be the speedy consequence of protection all 
 round, whether enforced by law or by boycotting. We have 
 not yet got beyond the Nationalist stage of regarding our 
 social questions, and there is no use in talking as if patriotism, 
 even in its narrower and meaner aspects, was likely to be an 
 extinct sentiment for a long time to come. We must work up 
 from the good elements in patriotism towards a wider tie. 
 And we cannot get to a federation of the world all at once. 
 Our citizens cannot yet be citizens of the world ; we cannot 
 afford to sink the citizen in the man. The difference between 
 civilised and uncivilised races is a real barrier ; and to try to 
 ignore it, as Socialists and philanthropic Radicals almost 
 habitually do, is only to fall a prey to false and mischievous 
 abstractions. 
 
 Short cuts over unknown country are generally a mistaken 
 policy. And here we must give the Socialists every credit for 
 pointing out the errors of old-fashioned Radicals and of many 
 eager social reformers, who wish to strike at symptoms of
 
 28o THE RIGHT OF PURSUING [ch. xiv 
 
 disease without removing the causes. To increase the number 
 of small landowners, to pass Puritanical laws which cannot be 
 enforced without creating fresh evils, to disendow ancient cor- 
 porations which are serving professedly at least some social 
 function — measures of that sort which till lately formed the 
 most conspicuous part of every " advanced " programme — are 
 seen by the Socialist to be moves in a wrong direction or un- 
 important changes. But the Socialist himself is too apt to 
 overlook the problem of population — not merely of over-popu- 
 lation, of excessive quantity, but the less considered problem 
 of degeneration in quality — which at every point confronts the 
 reformer who in any way combats the cruelty of natural 
 selection. And, as 1 have had occasion to argue, the Socialist 
 is generally too oblivious of the need of discipline, of the virtues 
 of what he detests as " militarism," and too apt to be infected 
 by Anarchist views of society, which are logically" antithetic to 
 his own professed creed. 
 
 Eagerness for social legislation is apt to make the reformer 
 neglect the importance of political machinery. There is 
 noticeable in many quarters a growing impatience of repre- 
 sentative government, a dislike of discussion of what are con- 
 temptuously called " constitutional conundrums," a certain 
 craving even for the despot, the strong man, who will carry 
 out great schemes promptly and ruthlessly. All these symp- 
 toms contain elements of danger. It is something, indeed, 
 to recognise the secondary character of all merely political 
 changes ; it is something to see that what is called " free govern- 
 ment " is not everything ; it is something even to give the lie 
 explicitly to false notions of equality, and to feel the need of 
 superior skill and superior force. But while admitting that 
 machinery is only a means to an end, we must not suppose 
 that any means will do equally well. Great changes in 
 political institutions have probably yet to come : we are only 
 beginning to see the problems of the proper working of demo- 
 cratic government. The stability of parliamentary institu- 
 tions and their usefulness is threatened by the break-up of the 
 old system of two parties and two parties only. Those who 
 are fond of denouncing party-government seem to forget that, 
 so far as experience goes, there is something worse than party- 
 government, and that is the absence of definite and responsible 
 parties altogether, and the predominance in politics of hap-
 
 CH. xiv] AND OBTAINING HAPPINESS 281 
 
 hazard combinations of fluctuating groups. The supporters 
 of " independent " parties say, Why not introduce in Great 
 Britain the Second Ballot, which most European countries 
 already have ? It is a most desirable reform — in tlie interests 
 of political honesty ; but it would undoubtedly hasten the Ibr- 
 mation and the increase of independent groups and the conse- 
 quent diminution of parliamentary stability. 
 
 Possibly the Referendum, if worked as well or no worse than 
 it has been worked on the whole in Switzerland, might com- 
 pensate for many of the losses which the deca}^ of the old 
 party system would bring. We might, conceivably, get an 
 Executive, like the Swiss, not based on party at all, and ad- 
 ministering the business of the country on purely business 
 principles. But the advantages are not all on one side. And 
 the eager social reformer, if he is wise, must tolerate many 
 discussions on the Referendum, on Federation, on the relations 
 between Executive and Legislature, which may seem to him 
 uninteresting and purely academic. The academic study of 
 political questions is indeed sorely needed, and the academic 
 temper in dealing with them. 
 
 No change in political machinery and no change in social 
 institutions will lead to social stability and to the " obtaining 
 of happiness" on the part of the citizen, unless the moral feel- 
 ings of the community are adapted to the new institutions. 
 This is the most important reason of all why successful reforms 
 must be brought about gradually. Here we come upon the 
 antinomy which is always recurring in discussions on social 
 progress. On the one side, " No progress is possible without a 
 moral improvement in the individual ; " and so it is often in- 
 ferred that no external or material change is of any use. On 
 the other, " Change the circumstances which mould men's 
 characters, and the characters will change ;" and so it is often 
 inferred that external or material changes are the sole thing 
 needed. Each premise is true, but not the whole truth; and 
 therefore both inferences are fallacious. Human beings are 
 dependent on circumstances, but they have also natures of 
 their own, natures inherited from their ancestors, and modified 
 by reflection and sentiment ; so that for social progress there 
 must be harmony between character and circumstances. 
 Progress takes place through some individuals being in advance 
 of the average of their neighbours in their ideals and senti-
 
 282 THE RIGHT OF FURSUING [ch. xiv 
 
 ments ; a certain diffusion of these ideals and sentiments 
 amonc; others is necessary under any form of government, most 
 of all under a democratic, in order to bring about legislative 
 changes. A law or institution once established, if it is backed 
 by a fair amount of approving sentiment, fixes and makes 
 definite the ideals to which it corresponds. If it is not backed 
 by such approving sentiment, it remains more or less a dead- 
 letter, or it provokes active opposition : in either case it fails 
 to produce its proper effect, and no real progress has been 
 effected by its means. 
 
 Laws and institutions to be progressive must furthermore 
 be educative : they must be such as prepare people to go 
 beyond them, in quiet and orderly fashion. "When some evils 
 are specially prominent, the changes that promise a relief from 
 these evils are thought of as if the}"- were final changes, could 
 they only be obtained. Reformers are alwa3's apt to look 
 forward to " living happily ever afterwards " when once the 
 great crisis is over. But it is only in old-fashioned stories 
 that trouble ends with the wedding bells ; and it is a very 
 crude and inexperienced kind of political thinking which ex- 
 pects even the biggest of Collectivist schemes to leave no 
 social problems for the future. It is wiser, though a rare 
 wisdom, frankly to disclaim finality. It may destroy the 
 opportunity for much moving rhetoric, but it will save a good 
 deal of painful disillusion, A plan which offers opportunities 
 for alteration, even for moving back again if necessary, is 
 preferable to one which admits of no return, and leaves 
 amendment out of the question.* Too great completeness is not 
 a merit in a political or social programme. 
 
 Two different kinds of objections aie likely to be made to 
 such a political creed as is indicated in the foregoing words. 
 The first, to which I have already referred, is that of the 
 eager socialist, who is wearied with wandering in the 
 wilderness, and wishes to rush impetuously into the promised 
 land he has pictured to himself, who wants his millennium to 
 begin by act of parliament, or by plebiscite, on the first of 
 January next. The other objection is that put forward by the 
 pessimist, who is keenly alive to the vanity of human .wishes 
 and the weakness of human nature, and who is very sceptical 
 
 ^ The opportunity of experimental legislation is a strong argument for 
 decentralisation of power and centralisation of information.
 
 CH. XI v] AND OBTAINING HAPPINESS 283 
 
 about any amelioration in the intellects or the characters of 
 the mass of mankind, and who sees too clearly that every 
 advance in external comfort only brings new cravings 
 and new pains, more vividly realised than the old dumb, 
 hopeless suffering or apathy ; to such an one resignation is 
 the supreme virtue, and what is called political and social 
 progress a matter of indiiference. After all, is not a despotism 
 the best form of government for the Stoic or the Buddhist, or 
 other ascetic individualist, to live under, since his ideal life is a 
 life of protest and of withdrawal into the inward peace that 
 he can find only in the spiritual calm of his own passion- 
 freed soul ? At the best, supposing the dream of a perfected 
 society to be accomplished on this earth, the remedy would be 
 very transitory ; and all the results of long tedious effort 
 must perish, as our planet gradually becomes incapable of 
 supporting life. Such pessimism about the worth of human 
 society may go along with an intense belief in the certain 
 bliss of another world, in comparison with which every other 
 aim is empty; or it may exist in the more bitter form that 
 has no hope to outweigh its despair. 
 
 Let me take this second objection before returning to the 
 first. Suppose we admit the impossibility of any final or 
 complete happiness for beings such as we are in any future, 
 either here or elsewhere, it is surely a piece of " abstract 
 thinking" to ignore the difference between a worse and a 
 better — or, let us say, a less bad — condition in human affairs. 
 Before the pessimist obtains our votes as to the worthlessness 
 of all social effort, it is surely reasonable to try whether life 
 cannot be made more tolerable, more worth living, to the mass 
 of human beings than it has been hitherto. Moreover, as 
 already said, pessimism will always meet with a practical 
 refutation through the operation of natural selection. Those 
 who sincerely resign '• the will to live " must inevitably give 
 place to those who assert it. Pessimism never can be any- 
 thing else except a bye-product of the reflective consciousness, 
 relatively uselul if it quickens sympathy with suffering, and 
 thus stimulates the effort to relieve it. Pessimism then 
 becomes an element in that very striving after social pro- 
 gress which, if taken as a final creed, it seemed logically to 
 condemn. And to this practical self-refutation of pessimism 
 may be added the philosophical consideration, that t lu- mer.^
 
 284 THE RIGHT OF PURSUING [ch. xiv 
 
 judgment that human life or human society is evil implies an 
 ideal of goodness and perfection by which as standard the 
 existing world is judged. Such a contrast between the ideal 
 and the actual is explicitly recognised in the pessimism of 
 Christian ascetics. And the sense of the contrast leads the 
 more courageous spirits to seek to overcome it. The fanatical 
 hermits of the Thebaid were replaced by the Benedictine 
 monks, who became to barbarous races the missionaries of 
 ancient learning and civilisation, and by the Franciscan 
 friars, who, after their lights, fought with disease and want 
 and ignorance in crowded cities, and beginning without orna- 
 ments and without books, trained some of the boldest of medi- 
 aftval philosophers and kindled the fire of Italian art. In the 
 modern movement for diffusing the benefits of civilisation and 
 improving all the conditions of human life, amid all the errors 
 and absurdities and narrowness of outlook that inevitably 
 accompany any great movement, can we not still recognise 
 the same aspiration as is expressed in the one prayer in which 
 all sections of divided Christendom unite, — the aspiration 
 that the heavenly kingdom, the reign of peace and righteous- 
 ness and love, should not remain a far-off vision, but should be 
 realised here, in the actual human world : " Thy kingdom 
 come : Thy will be done in earth as it is in heaven " '? 
 
 However unconsciously, the effort for social amelioration 
 implies what we can only call a religious faith. In words the 
 social reformer may disclaim any religious beh'ef, and may 
 argue that one of the main causes of the growth of socialism 
 and kindred tendencies is that decay in religious belief 
 which is often said to be one of the prominent features of our 
 time ; in particular it is often said that the disappearance of 
 belief in the compensations of another life is one of the prin- 
 cipal sources of the eagerness with which immediate and 
 earthly justice- is demanded. But, in the first place, it is 
 important to recognise that, as Professor Wallace has ex- 
 pressed it, " The religion of a time is not its nominal creed, 
 but its dominant conviction of the meaning of reality, the 
 principle which animates all its being and all its striving, the 
 faith it has in the laws of nature and the purpose of life." ^ 
 In the second place, the diminished importance of " other- 
 worldly " considerations is only one as]3ect of a change which 
 ^ HegeVs Philosophy of 2Iaid, p. xxxvii.
 
 CH. xiv] AXD OBTAINING HAPPINESS 285 
 
 has been going on within, as well as without, the visible 
 Churches. Few moralists nowadays venture to stako the oV)li- 
 gation to morality upon the sanctions of future reward and 
 punishment. Like Plato in the Republic^ they would rather 
 put aside such sanctions altogether, aware of the demoralising 
 manner in which they have often been conceived, until the 
 superiority of justice to injustice has been shown through con- 
 siderations of social well-being ; and the hope of continued 
 existence is based mainly, if not solely, upon the independently 
 established facts of morality. Not only in Kant and those whom 
 he has influenced, but in the poets who have taught our age a 
 great deal of its theology — in Tennyson and Browning — we find 
 "the hope of immortality " based mainly on the inadequacy 
 between man's ideal and what he can accomplish in his short 
 span of earthly life. The hope of immortality has become one 
 aspect of the desire for progress. And those who believe and 
 those who doubt the persistence of the individual conscious- 
 ness after death alike agree that strenuous well-doing in this 
 life would be the best preparation for another. "Whatsoever 
 thy hand findeth to do, do it with thy might ; for there is no 
 work, nor device, nor knowledge, nor wisdom, in the grave 
 whither thou goest." ^ " Thou hast been faithful over a few 
 tilings; I will make thee ruler over many things."^ The im- 
 plied belief may seem to be different : the practical moral les- 
 son is the same. To neglect social duties in order to save one's 
 own soul is, happily, a dwindling type of religion. 
 
 Now what is implied in saying that effort for social pro- 
 gress implies a religious faith? It may be said by the pessi- 
 mist that such faith is entirely irrational. An irrational faith, 
 i.e. a blind instinct, may induce people to seek to preserve 
 their own lives and to continue their species. Such irrational 
 " egoism " and " altruism " cannot lead them to plan and think 
 out schemes of social reorganisation. To do so implies a belief 
 (however little recognised) that the evolution of the world is a 
 rational process ; else how could we ever hope b}^ our reasoning 
 to hit upon any scheme that would work in harmony with 
 the laws of nature and of human nature ? But when such a 
 
 ' Eccl. ix. 10. Is not this echoed in Jolin ix. 4: "I must work the 
 works of him that sent me, Vv^hile it is day : the night comctli, wlicrein 
 no man can worlc " ? 
 
 2 Matt. XXV. 21.
 
 286 THE RIGHT OF PURSUING HAPPINESS [ch. xiv 
 
 belief in the ultimate rationality of natiire, and especially of 
 human history'-, becomes explicit, it is no longer logically pos- 
 sible to turn our back upon all the past, and to disdain all 
 the present. Oar trust in the possibility of a better future 
 must be based on a belief in the rationality of past and present 
 also. And thus the impatience of the social reformer — intelli- 
 gible and excusable as it may be — is due to an imperfect 
 recognition of the rational basis of the faith which stimulates 
 his efforts. Even those who talk freely about '' development" 
 often show very little appreciation of what is meant by the 
 growth of institutions, and of the ideas which may lead to 
 their reconstruction; and the use of the phrase " social evo- 
 lution " may go along with a great disrespect for history. 
 
 The truth in the theory of Natural Eights— what gave the 
 theory its practical value — was the belief in " Nature " as an 
 ideal, the belief in a Divine purpose determining the ends 
 which man should set before him, and the belief that this 
 ideal, this Divine purpose, could be discovered by the use of 
 human reason. The defect of the theory lay, as we have seen, 
 in the tendency to set this ideal in abstract antithesis over 
 against the actual and the historical. In the light of the con- 
 ception of evolution applied to human society — i.e. using an 
 historical method in the study of institutions, and being influ- 
 enced by an historical spirit in dealing with all human 
 problems — we must think of this ideal, this Divine purpose, as 
 something not existing definitely formed in the mind of any 
 one man however inspired, of any set of legislators however 
 honest and however enthusiastic, but as something gradually'' 
 revealing itself in the education of the human race. In other 
 words, an adequate theory of rights and an adequate theory of 
 the State must rest upon a philosophy of history ; and steady 
 progress in political and social reform cannot be made unless 
 there is a willingness to learn the lessons of experience, and a 
 reasonable reverence for the long toil of the human spirit in 
 that past from which we inherit not only our problems, but 
 the hope and the means of their solution.
 
 APPENDIX. 
 
 The Virginian Declaration of Rights— June 12, 17TG. 
 
 A DECLARATION OF RIGHTS, 
 
 Made by the Representatives of the good People of Virginia, 
 assembled iu full and free Convention, which rights do pertain to 
 them and their posterity as the basis and foundation of govern- 
 ment. 
 
 I. That all men are by nature equally free and independent, and 
 have certain inherent rights, of which, when they enter into a state 
 of society, they cannot by any compact deprive or divest their 
 posterity; namely, the enjoyment of life and liberty, with the means 
 of acquiring and possessing proper t}^, and pursuing and obtaining 
 happiness and safety. 
 
 II. That all power is vested in, and consequent!}' derived from, the 
 people; that magistrates are their trustees and servants, and at all 
 times amenable to them. 
 
 III. That government is, or ought to be, instituted for the common 
 benefit, protection, and security of the people, nation or community ; 
 of all the various modes and forms of government, that is best which 
 is capable of producing the greatest degree of happiness and safety, 
 and is most effectually secured against the danger of maladministra- 
 tion ; and that, when a government shall be found inadequate or con- 
 trary to these purposes, a majority of the community hath an 
 indubitable, unalienable, and indefeasible right to reform, alter or 
 abolish it, in such manner as shall be judged most conducive to the 
 public weal. 
 
 IV. That no man, or set of men, are entitled to exclusive or separate 
 emoluments or privileges from the community but in consideration 
 of public services, which not being descendible, neither ought the 
 offices of magistrate, legislator or judge to be hereditary. 
 
 V. That the legislative, executive and judicial powers slumid be 
 separate and distinct ; and that the members thereof may be 
 restrained from oppression, by feeling and participating the burthens 
 of the people, they should, at fixed periods, be reduced to a private 
 station, return into that body from which they were originally taken, 
 and the vacancies be supplied by frequent, certain and regular 
 elections, in which all, or any part of the former members to be 
 again eligible or ineligible, as the laws shall direct.
 
 2 88 APPENDIX 
 
 VI. That all elections ought to be free, and that all men having 
 sufficient evidence of permanent common interest with, and attach- 
 ment to the community, have the right of suffrage, and cannot be 
 taxed, or deprived of their property for public uses, without their own 
 consent, or that of their representatives so elected, nor bound by anj^ 
 law to which they have not in like manner assented, for the public 
 good. 
 
 VII. That all power of suspending laws, or the execution of laws, by 
 any authority, without consent of the representatives of the people, 
 is injurious to their rights, and ought not to be exercised. 
 
 VIII. Tliat in all capital or criminal prosecutions a man hath a right 
 to demand the cause and nature of his accusation, to be confronted 
 with the accusers and witnesses, to call for evidence in his favour, 
 and to a speedy trial by an impartial jury of twelve men of his 
 vicinage, without whose unanimous consent he cannot be found 
 guilty ; nor can he be compelled to give evidence against himself ; 
 that no man be deprived of his liberty, except by the law of the land , 
 or the judgment of his peers. 
 
 IX. That exce.'^sive bail ought not to be required, nor excessive 
 fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted. 
 
 X. That general warrants, whereby an officer or messenger may 
 be commanded to search su.spected places without evidence of a fact 
 committed, or to seize any person or persons not named, or whose 
 offence is not particularly described and supported by evidence, are 
 grievous and oppressive, and ought not to be granted. 
 
 XI. That in controversies respecting property, and in suits between 
 man and man, the ancient trial by jury of twelve men is preferable 
 to any other, and ought to be held sacred. 
 
 XII. That the fi-eedom of the press is one of the great bulwarks of 
 liberty, and can never be restrained but by despotic governments. 
 
 XIII. That a well-regulated militia, composed of the body of the 
 people, trained to arms, is the proper, natural and safe defence of a 
 free State ; that standing armies in time of peace should be avoided 
 as dangerous to liberty ; and that in all cases the military should be 
 under strict subordination to, and governed by, the civil power. 
 
 XIV. That the people have a right to uniform government ; and 
 therefore that no government separate from or independent of the 
 government of Virginia ought to be erected or established within 
 the limits thereof. 
 
 XV. That no free government, or the blessing of liberty, can be 
 preserved to any people, but by a firm adherence to justice, modera- 
 tion, temperance, frugality and virtue, and by a frequent recurrence 
 to fundamental principles. 
 
 XVI. That religion, or the duty which w-e owe to our Creator, and 
 the manner of discharging it, can be directed only by reason and 
 conviction, not by force or violence ; and therefore all men are equally
 
 APPENDIX 2 89 
 
 entitled to the free exercise of religion, according to the dictates of 
 conscience ; and that it is the duty of all to practice Christian forbear- 
 ance, love and charity towards each other. 
 
 Extract from the Declaration of Indepexdexce of the 
 United States of America— July 4, 177G. 
 
 The unanimous Declaration of the tliirtecn united States of 
 
 America. 
 
 When in the Course of human events, it becomes necessary for one 
 people to dissolve the political bands which have connected them 
 with another, and to assume among the Powers of the earth, the 
 separate and equal station to which the Law^s of Nature and of 
 Nature's God entitle them, a decent respect to the opinions of man- 
 kind requires that they should declare the causes which impel them 
 to the separation. 
 
 We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created 
 equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalien- 
 able Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of 
 Happiness. That to secure these rights, Governments are instituted 
 among Men, deriving their just powei'S from the consent of the 
 governed. That whenever any Form of Government becomes destruc- 
 tive of these ends, it is the Right of the People to alter or to abolish 
 it, and to institvite new Government, laying its foundation on such 
 principles and organizing its powers in such form, as to tliem shall 
 seem most likely to effect their Safety and Happiness. Prudence, 
 indeed, will dictate that Governments long established should not be 
 changed for light and transient causes ; and accordingly all experience 
 hath shown, that mankind are more disposed to suffer, while evils 
 are sufferable, than to right themselves by abolishing the forms to 
 which they are accustomed. But when a long train of abuses and 
 usurpations, pursuing invariably the same Object, evinces a design to 
 reduce them under absolute Despotism, it is their right, it is their 
 duty, to throw off such Government, and to provide new Guards for 
 their future security. — Such has been the patient sufferance of those 
 Colonies ; and such is now the necessity which constrains them to 
 alter their former Systems of Government. The history of the present 
 King of Great Britain is a history of repeated injuries and usurpa- 
 tions, all having in direct object the establishment of an absolute 
 Tyranny over these States. To prove this, let facts be submitted to 
 a candid world. 
 
 [Then follow statements of paj-ticular grievances.] 
 
 N.R. U
 
 290 APPENDIX 
 
 In every stage of these Oppressions We have Petitioned for Redress 
 in the most humble terms : Our repeated Petitions have been 
 answered only by repeated injury. A Prince, whose character is thus 
 marked by every act which may define a Tyrant, is unfit to be the 
 ruler of a free People. 
 
 Nor have We been wanting in attention to our British brethren. 
 We have warned them from time to time of attempts by their legisla- 
 ture to extend an unwarrantable jurisdiction over us. We have 
 reminded them of the circumstances of our emigration and settlement 
 here. We have appealed to their native justice and magnanimity, 
 and we have conjured them by the ties of our common kindred to 
 disavow these usurpations, which would inevitably interrupt our 
 connections and correspondence. They too have been deaf to the 
 voice of justice and of consanguinity. We must, thei'efore, acquiesce 
 in the necessity which denounces our Separation, and hold them, as 
 we hold the rest of mankind. Enemies in War, in Peace Friends. 
 
 We, therefore, the Representatives of the united States of America, 
 in General Congress, Assembled, appealing to the Supreme Judge of 
 the world for the rectitude of our intentions, do, in the Name, and by 
 Authority of the good People of these Colonies, solemnly publish and 
 declare, That these United Colonies are, and of Right ought to be 
 Free and Independent States ;" that they are Absolved from all 
 Allegiance to the British Crown, and that all political connection 
 between them and the State of Great Britain, is and ought to be 
 totally dissolved ; and that as Free and Independent States, the}' 
 have full Power to levy War, conclude Peace, contract Alliances, 
 establish Commerce, and to do all other Acts and Things which 
 Independent States may of right do. And for the support of this 
 Declaration, with a firm reliance on the Protection of Divine Provi- 
 dence, we mutually pledge to each other our Lives, our Fortunes and 
 our sacred Honor. 
 
 Declaration des Droits Translation given in Thomas 
 
 DE L'HoMME ET DC CiTOYEN Paine\s ^^ Rights of Many 
 
 (1789). Declaration of the Rights of 
 
 (prefixed to constitution Man and of Citizens, 
 
 FRANQAISE DU 3-14 SePT., BY THE NATIONAL ASSEMBLY 
 
 1791). OF FRANCE. 
 
 Les representans du pen pie The representatives of the 
 
 franpais, constitues en assemblee people of France, formed into a 
 
 nationale, considerant que I'igno- National Assembly, considering 
 
 ranee I'oubli ou le mepris des that ignorance, neglect, or con-
 
 APPENDIX 
 
 291 
 
 droits de rhomme sont les seules 
 causes des malheurs publics et de 
 la corruption des gouvernemens, 
 ont resolu d'exposer, dans une 
 declaration solennelle, les droits 
 naturels, inalienables et sacres de 
 rhomme, alin que cette declaration, 
 constamment presente a tous les 
 membres du corps social, leur 
 rappelle sanscesse leurs droits et 
 leurs devoirs ; afin que les actes 
 du pouvoir legislatif et ceux du 
 pouvoir executif, pouvant etre a 
 chaque instant compares avec le 
 but de toute institution politique, 
 en soient plus respectes, afin que 
 les reclamations des citoyens, 
 fondees desormais sur des prin- 
 cipes simples et incontestables 
 tournent toujours aumaintien de 
 la constitution et au bonbeur de 
 tous. 
 
 En consequence, I'assemblee 
 nationale reconnait et declare en 
 presence et sous les auspices de 
 I'Etre supreme, les droits suivans 
 de I'homme et du citoyen. 
 
 Art. l*"". Les hommes naissent 
 et demeurent libres et egaux en 
 droits. Les distinctions sociales 
 ne peuvent etre fondees que sur 
 I'utilite commune. 
 
 2. Le but de toute association 
 pplitique est la conservation des 
 droits naturels et imprescriptibles 
 de I'homme. Ces droits sont la 
 liberte, la propriete, la surete et 
 la resistance a I'oppression. 
 
 3. Le principe de toute souve- 
 rainete reside essentiellement 
 dans la nation ; nul corps, nul 
 individu ne peut exercer d'au- 
 
 terapt of human rights, ai'e the 
 sole causes of public misfortunes 
 and corruptions of Government, 
 have resolved to set forth in a 
 solemn declaration, these natural, 
 imprescriptible, and inalienable 
 rights: that tliis declaration 
 being constantly present to the 
 minds of the members of the 
 body social, they may be for ever 
 kept attentive to their rights 
 and their duties ; that the acts 
 of the legislative and executive 
 powers of government, being 
 capable of being every moment 
 compared with the end of politi- 
 cal institutions, may be more 
 respected; and also, that the 
 future claims of the citizens, 
 being directed by simple and 
 incontestible principles, may 
 always tend to the maintenance 
 of the Constitution, and the 
 general happiness. 
 
 For these reasons, the National 
 Assembly doth recognise and 
 declare, in the presence of the 
 Supreme Being, and with the 
 hope of his blessing and favour, 
 the following mcred rights of 
 men and of citizens : 
 
 I. Men are born, and always 
 continue, free and equal in respect 
 of their rights. Civil distinc- 
 tions, therefore, can be founded 
 only on public utility. 
 
 II. The end of all political 
 associations, is the preservation 
 of the natural and imprescriptible 
 rights of man; and these rights 
 are liberty, property, security, 
 and resistance of oppression. 
 
 III. The nation is e.ssentially 
 the source of all sovereignty ; 
 nor can any individual, or any 
 body of men, be entitled to any
 
 292 
 
 APPENDIX 
 
 torite qui n'en emane expresse- 
 ineiit. 
 
 4. La liberte consiste apouvoir 
 faire tout ce qui ne nuit pas k 
 autrui : ainsi I'exercice des droits 
 naturels de chaque homme n'a de 
 bornes que celles qui assureut 
 aux autres membres de la 
 societe la jouissance de ces memes 
 droits. Ces bornes ne peuvent 
 etre determinees que par la loi. 
 
 5. La loi n'a le droit de de- 
 fendre que les actions nuisibles a 
 la societe. Tout ce qui n'est pas 
 def'endu par la loi ne peut etre 
 empeclie, et nul ne peut etre 
 contraint k faire ce qu'elle n'or- 
 donne pas. 
 
 6. La loi est I'expression de la 
 volonte generale. Tous les cito- 
 yens ont droit de concourir per- 
 sonnellement, ou par leui-s 
 representans, k sa formation. 
 Elle doit etre la meme pour tous, 
 soit qu'elle protege, soit qu'elle 
 punisse. Tous les citoyens etant 
 egaux ci ses yeux, sont egalement 
 admissibles a toutes dignites, 
 places et emplois publics, selon 
 leur capacite, et sans autre 
 distinction que celle de leurs 
 vertus et de leurs talens. 
 
 7. Nul homme ne peut etre 
 accuse, arrete ni detenu que dans 
 les cas determines par la loi, et 
 selon les formes qu'elle a pre- 
 scrites. Ceiix qui soUicitent, 
 expedient, executent ou font 
 executer des ordres arbitraires, 
 doivent etre punis : mais tout 
 citoyen appelle ou saisi en vertu 
 de la loi, doit obeir k I'instant ; 
 il se rend cotipable par la resist- 
 ance. 
 
 authority which is not expressly 
 derived from it. 
 
 IV. Political liberty consists 
 in the power of doing whatever 
 does not injure another. The 
 exercise of the natural rights of 
 every man, has no other limits 
 than those which are necessary 
 to secure to every otliev man the 
 free exercise of the same rights ; 
 and these limits are determinable 
 only by the law. 
 
 V. The law ought to prohibit 
 only actions hurtful to society. 
 What is not prohibited by the 
 law, should not be hindered ; 
 nor should any one be compelled 
 to that which the law does not 
 require. 
 
 VI. The law is an expression 
 of the will of the community. 
 All citizens have a right to concur, 
 either personally, or by their 
 representatives, in its formation. 
 It should be the same to all, 
 whether it protects or punishes ; 
 and all being equal in its sight, 
 are equally eligible to all honours, 
 places, and employments, accord- 
 ing to their different abilities, 
 without any other distinction 
 than that created by their virtues 
 and talents. 
 
 VII. No man should be ac- 
 cused, arrested, or held in con- 
 finement, except in cases deter- 
 mined by the law, and according 
 to the forms which it has pre- 
 scribed. All who promote, solicit, 
 execute, or canse to be executed, 
 arbitrary orders, ought to be 
 punished, and every citizen called 
 upon, or apprehended by virtue 
 of the law, ought immediately to 
 obey, and renders himself culp- 
 able by resistance.
 
 APPENDIX 
 
 293 
 
 8. La loi ne doit etablir que 
 des peines strictement et evidem- 
 ment necessaires, et nul ne pent 
 etre puni qu'en vertu d'une loi 
 etablie et promulguee anterieure- 
 ment au delit et legalement 
 appliquee. 
 
 9. Tout homme etant presume 
 innocent jusqu'a ce qu'il ait ete 
 declai-e coupable, s'il est juge 
 indispensable de I'arreter, toute 
 rigueur qui ne serait pas neces- 
 saire pour s'assurer de sa per- 
 sonne, doit eti^e severement 
 reprimee par la loi. 
 
 10. Nul ne doit etre inquiete 
 pour ses opinions, memes 
 religieuses, pourvu que leur 
 manifestation ne trouble pas 
 I'ordre public etabli par la loi. 
 
 11. La libre communication 
 des pensees et des opinions est 
 un des droits les plus precieux de 
 I'homme ; tout citoyen pent done 
 parler, ecrire, imprimer librement, 
 sauf a repondre de I'abus de cette 
 liberte dans les cas determines 
 par la loi. 
 
 12. La garantie des droits de 
 I'homme et du citoyen necessite 
 une force publique : cette force 
 est done instituee pour I'avantage 
 de tons, et non pour I'utilite 
 particuliere de ceux auxquels 
 elle est confiee. 
 
 13. Pour I'entretien de la 
 force publique, et pour les 
 depenses d'administration, une 
 contribution commune est indis- 
 pensable, elle doit etre egalement 
 repartie entre tons les citoyens 
 en raison de leurs facultes. 
 
 VIII. The law ought to im- 
 pose no other penalties but such 
 as are absolutely and evidently 
 necessary ; and no one ought to 
 be punished, but in virtue of 
 a law promulgated before the 
 offence, and legally applied. 
 
 IX. Everj'- man being pre- 
 sumed innocent till he has 
 been convicted, whenever his 
 detention becomes indispensable, 
 all rigour to him, more than is 
 necessary to secure his person, 
 ought to be provided against by 
 the law. 
 
 X. No man ought to be mo- 
 lested on account of his opin- 
 ions, not even on account of his 
 religious opinions, provided his 
 avowal of them does not disturb 
 the public order established by 
 the law. 
 
 XL The unrestrained com- 
 munication of thoughts and 
 opinions being one of the most 
 precious rights of man, every 
 citizen may speak, write, and 
 publish freely, provided he is 
 responsible for the abuse of this 
 liberty, in cases determined by 
 the law. 
 
 XII. A public force being 
 necessary to give security to the 
 rights of men and of citizens, 
 that force is instituted for the 
 benefit of the community and not 
 for the particular benefit of the 
 persons to whom it is intrusted. 
 
 XIII. A common contribution 
 being necessary for the support 
 of the public force, and for de- 
 fraying the other expenses of 
 government, it ought to be divi- 
 ded equally among the members 
 of the community, according to 
 their abilities.
 
 294 
 
 APPENDIX 
 
 14. Tons les citoyens ont le 
 droit (Je constater, par eux-memes 
 ou par leurs representans, la 
 necessite de la contribution 
 publique, de la consentir libre- 
 ment, d'en suivre I'emploi, et 
 d'en determiner la quotite, I'assi- 
 ette, le recouvrement et la duree. 
 
 15. La societe a le droit de 
 demander compte a tout agent 
 public de son administration. 
 
 16. Toute societe dans laquelle 
 la garantie des droits n'est pas 
 assuree, ni la separation des 
 pouvoirs determinee, n'a point de 
 constitution. 
 
 17. La propriete etant un droit 
 inviolable et sacre, nul ne pent 
 en etre prive, si ce n'est lorsque 
 la necessite publique, legalement 
 constatee, I'exige evidemment, et 
 sous la condition d'une juste et 
 prealable indemnite. 
 
 XIV. Every citizen has a 
 right, either by himself or his 
 representative, to a free voice in 
 determining the necessity of 
 public contributions, the appro- 
 priation of them, and their 
 amount, mode of assessment, and 
 duration. 
 
 XV. Every community has had 
 a right to demand of all its agents 
 an account of their conduct. 
 
 XVI Every community in 
 which a separation of powers 
 and a security of rights is not 
 provided for, wants a constitu- 
 tion. 
 
 XVII. The right to property 
 being inviolable and sacred, no 
 one ought to be deprived of it, 
 except in cases of evident public 
 necessity, legally ascertained, and 
 on condition of a previous just 
 indemnity. 
 
 Declaration Prefixed to Constitution of June 24, 1793. 
 
 Le Peuple fran^ais, convaincu que I'oubli et le mepris des droits 
 naturels de I'homme sont les seules causes des malheurs du monde, 
 a resolu d'exposer, dans une declaration solennelle, ces droits sacres 
 et inalienables, alin que tons les citoyens, pouvant comparer sans cesse 
 les actes du gouvernement avec le but de toute institution sociale, 
 ne se laissent jamais opprimer et avilir par la tyrannie ; afin que le 
 peuple ait toujoui's devaut les yeux les bases de sa liberte et de son 
 bonheur, le magistrat la regie de ses devoirs, le legislateur I'objet de 
 sa mission. 
 
 En consequence il proclame, en presence de I'Etre supreme, la 
 declaration suivante des droits de I'homme et du citoyen. 
 
 Art. l°^ Le but de la societe est le bonheur commun. Le gouverne- 
 ment est institue pour garantir ^ I'homme la jouissance de ces droits 
 naturels et imprescriptibles. 
 
 2. Ces droits sont I'egalite, la liberte, la s€irete, la propriete. 
 
 3. Tons les hommes sont egaux par la nature et devant la loi. 
 
 4. La loi est I'expression libre et solennelle de la volonte generale ;
 
 APPENDIX 295 
 
 elle est la meme pour tous, soit qu'elle protege, soit qu"elle punisse ; 
 elle ne pent ordonner que ce qui est juste et utile a, la societe ; elle 
 ne peut defend re que ce qui lui est nuisible. 
 
 5. Tous les citoyens sont egalement admissibles aux emplois 
 publics. Les peuples libres ne connaissent d'autres motifs de pre- 
 ference dans leurs elections que les vertus et les talens. 
 
 6. La liberte est le pouvoir qui appartient a rhomme de faire tout 
 ce qui ne nuit pas aux droits d'autrui : elle a pour principe la nature, 
 pour regie la justice, pour sauve-garde la loi ; sa limite morale est 
 dans cette maxinie : Ne fais pas a un autre ce que tu ne veux pas 
 qui te soit fait. 
 
 7. Le droit de manifester sa pensee et ses opinions, soit par la 
 voie de la presse, soit de toute autre maniere, le droit de s'assembler 
 paisiblement, le libre exercice des cultes, ne peuvent etre interdits. 
 La necessite d'enoucer ses droits suppose ou la presence ou le souvenir 
 recent du despotisme. 
 
 8. La surete consiste dans la protection accordee par la societe k 
 chacun des ses membres pour la conservation de sa personne, de ses 
 droits et de ses proprietes. 
 
 9. La loi doit proteger la liberte publique et individuelle centre 
 I'oppression de ceux qui gouvernent. 
 
 lU. Nul ne doit etre accuse, arrete ni detenu, que dans les cas 
 determines par la loi et selon les formes qu'elle a prescrites. Tout 
 citoyen appele ou saisi par I'autorite de la loi, doit obeir a I'instant; 
 il se rend coupable par la resistance. 
 
 IL Toute acte exerce centre un homme hors des cas et sans les 
 formes que le loi determine, est arbitraire et tyrannique ; celui contra 
 lequel on voudrait I'executer par la violence, a le droit de la repousser 
 par la force. 
 
 12. Ceux qui solliciteraient, expedieraient, signeraient, executer- 
 aient ou feraient executor des actes arbitraires, sout coupables, et 
 doivent etre punis. 
 
 13. Tout bomme etant presume innocent jusqu'i ce qu'il ait ^te 
 declare coupable, s'il est juge indispensable de I'arreter, toute rigueur 
 qui ne serait pas neceasaire pour s'assurer de sa personne, doit etre 
 severement reprimee par la loi. 
 
 14. Nul ne doit etre juge ou puni quapres avoir ete entendu on 
 legalement appele, et qu'en vertu d'une loi promulgee anterieurement 
 au delit. La loi qui punirait des delits commis avant qu'elle existat 
 serait une tyrannie ; I'effet retroactif donne ii la loi serait un crane. 
 
 15. La loi ne doit decerner que des peines strictemeut et evidem- 
 ment necessaires : les peines doivent etre proper tionuees au delit et 
 utiles a la societe. 
 
 16. Le droit de propriele est celui qui appartient 11 tout citoyen de 
 jouir et de disposer 11 son gre de ses biens, de ses reveuus, du Iruit 
 de son travail et de son Industrie.
 
 2 96 APPENDIX 
 
 17. Nul genre de travail, de culture, de commerce, ne peut etre 
 interdit a, I'industrie des citoyens. 
 
 18. Tout homme peut engager ses services, son terns ; mais il ne 
 peut se vendre ni etre vendu ; sa personne n'est pas une propriete 
 alienable. La loi ne connait point de domesticite ; il ne peut exister 
 qu'un engagement de soins et de reconnaissance entre I'homme qui 
 travaille et celui qui Temploie. 
 
 19. Nul ne peut etre prive de la moindre portion de sa propriete, 
 sans son consentement, si ce n'est lorsque la necessite publique 
 legalement constatee I'exige, et sous la condition d'une juste et pre- 
 alable indemnite. 
 
 20. Nulle contribution ne peut etre etablie que pour I'utilite 
 generale. Tons les citoyens ont droit de concourir a I'etablissement 
 des contributions, d'en surveiller I'emploi et de s'en faire rendre 
 conipte. 
 
 21. Les secours publics sont une dette sacree. La societe doit la 
 subsistance aux citoyens malheureux, soit en leur procurant du travail, 
 soit en assurant les moyens d'exister a ceux qui sont hors d'etat de 
 travailler. 
 
 22. L'instruction est le besoin de tons. La societe doit favoriser 
 de tout son pouvoir les progres de la raison publique, et mettre l'in- 
 struction a la portee de tons les citoyens. 
 
 23. La garantie sociale consiste dans Taction de tons pour assurer 
 a chacun la jouissance et la conservation de ses droits : cette garantie 
 repose sur la souverainete nationale. 
 
 24. EUe ne peut exister, si les limites des fonctions publiques ne 
 sont pas clairement determinees par la loi, et si la responsabilite de 
 tons les fonctionnaires n'est pas assuree. 
 
 25. La souverainete reside dans le peuple ; elle est une et indi- 
 visible, imprescriptible et inalienable. 
 
 26. Aucune portion du peuple ne peut exercer la puissance du 
 peuple en tier ; mais chaque section du souverain assemblee doit jouir 
 du droit d'exprimer sa volonte avec une entiere liberte. 
 
 27. Que tout individu qui usurperait la souverainete soit a I'instant 
 suis a mort par les hommes libres. 
 
 28. Un peuple a toujours le droit de revoir, de reformer et de 
 changer sa constitution. Une generation ne peut assujetir a ses lois 
 les generations futures. 
 
 29. Chaque citoyen a un droit egal de concourir a la formation de 
 la loi et a la nomination de ses mandataii-es ou de ses agens. 
 
 30. Les fonctions publiques sont essentiellement temporaires ; elles 
 ne peuvent etre considerees comme des distinctions ni comme des 
 recompenses, mais comme des devoirs. 
 
 31. Les delits des mandataires du peuple et de ses agens ne doivent 
 jamais etre impunis. Nul n'a le droit de se pretendre plus inviolable 
 que les autres citoyens.
 
 APPENDIX 297 
 
 32. Le droit de presenter des petitions aux depositaries de I'au- 
 torite publique ne peut, en ancun cas, eti'e intendit, suspendu ni 
 limite. 
 
 33. La resistance a roppression est la consequence des autres droits 
 de I'homme. 
 
 34. II y a oppression contre le corps social, lorsqu'un seul de ses 
 inembres est opprime : il y a oppression contre chaque inembre, 
 lorsque le corps social est opprime. 
 
 35. Quand le gonvernement viole les droits du peuple, I'insurrection 
 est pour le peuple et pour chaque portion du peuple, le plus sacre des 
 droits et le plus indispensable des devoirs. 
 
 .Declaration prefixed to the French Constitution of 5 Fructi- 
 DOK, An III. ( = Adg. 22, 1795): accepted by the People and 
 proclaimed Loi fondamentale 1^" Vendemiaire, An IV. 
 (Sept. 23, 1795). 
 
 Declaration des Droits et des Devoirs de V Homme et du Citoyen. 
 
 Le peuple fran9ais proclame, en presence de I'fitre supreme la 
 declaration suivante des droits et des devoirs de I'homme et du 
 citoyen. 
 
 Droits. 
 
 Art. l**". Les droits de I'homme en societe sont la liberte, I'egalite, 
 la siirete, la propriete. 
 
 2. La liberte consiste a pouvoir faire ce qui ne nuit pas aux 
 droits d'autrui. 
 
 3. L'egalite consiste, en ce que la loi est la meme pour tons, soit 
 qu'elle protege, soit qu'elle punisse. 
 
 L'egalite n'admet aucuue distinction de naissance, aucune 
 heredite de pouvoir. 
 
 4. La surete resulte du concours de tons pour assurer les droits de 
 chacun. 
 
 5. La propriete est le droit de jouir et de disposer de ses bicns, 
 de ses revenus, du fruit de son travail et de son Industrie. 
 
 6. La loi est la volonte generale, exprimee par la majorite 
 generale des citoyens ou de leurs representans. 
 
 7. Ce qui n'est pas defend u par la loi ne peut etre empeche. Niil 
 ne peut etre contraint a faire ce qu'elle n'ordonne pas. 
 
 8. Nul ne peut etre appeleen justice, accuse, arrete, ni detenu, quo 
 dans les cas determines par la loi, et selon les formes qu'elle a 
 prescrites.
 
 298 APPENDIX 
 
 9. Ceux qui sollicitent, expedient, signent, executant ou font 
 executer des actes arbitraires, sout coupables et doivent etre punis. 
 
 10. Toute rigueur qui ne serait pas necessaire pour s'assurer de la 
 personne d'un prevenu, doit etre severement reprimee par la loi. 
 
 11. Nul ne peut etre juge qu'apres avoir ete entendu ou legalement 
 appele. 
 
 12. La loi ne doit decerner que des peines strictement necessaires 
 et proportionuees au delit. 
 
 13. Tout traitement qui aggrave la peine determinee par la loi est 
 un crime. 
 
 14. Aucuue loi, ni criminelle, ni civile, ue peut avoir d'effet 
 retroactif. 
 
 15. Tout homine peut engager son terns et ses services, mais il ne 
 peut se veudre ni etre vendu ; sa personne n'est pas une propriete 
 alienable. 
 
 16. Toute contribution est etablie pour I'utilite g^uerale ; elle doit 
 etre repartie entre les contribuales eu raison de leurs facultes. 
 
 17. La souveraioete reside essentiellement dans Tuniversalite des 
 citoyens. 
 
 18. Nul individu, nulle reunion partielle de citoyens ne peut 
 s'attribuer la souverainete. 
 
 19. Nul ne peut, sans une delegation legale, exercer aucune 
 autorite, ni remplir aucune fonction publique. 
 
 20. Chaque citoyen a im droit egal de concourir, immediatement ou 
 mediatement a la formation de la loi, a la nomination des re- 
 presentans du peuple et des fonctionnaires publics. 
 
 21. Les fonctions publiques ne peuvent devenir la propriete de 
 ceux qui les exercent. 
 
 22. La garautie sociale ne peut exister si la division des pouvoirs 
 n'est pas etablie, si leurs limites ne sont pas fixees, et si la responsa- 
 bilite des fonctionnaires publics n'est pas assuree. 
 
 Devoirs. 
 Art. l^^ La declaration des droits contient les obligations des 
 legislateurs : le maintien de la societe demande que ceux qui la 
 component connaissent et remplissent egalement leurs devoirs. 
 
 2. Tous les devoirs de I'homme et du citoyen derivent de ces deux 
 principes, graves par la nature dans tous les coeurs : 
 
 Ne faites pas k autrui ce que vous ne voudriez pas qu'on vous 
 
 fit. 
 Faites constamment aux autres le bien que vous voudriez en 
 
 recevoir. 
 
 3. Les obligations de chacun envers la societe consistent a la 
 defendre, a la servir, a vivre soumis aux lois, et a respecter cevix qui 
 en sont les orgaues. 
 
 4. Nul n'est boa citoyen s'il n'est bon fils, bon frere, bon ami, bon 
 epoux.
 
 APPENDIX 299 
 
 5. Nul n'est homme de bien, s'il n'est franchement et religiense- 
 ment observateur des lois. 
 
 G. Celui qui viole ouvertement les lois, se declare en etat de guerre 
 avec la societe. 
 
 . 7. Celui qui, sans eufreindre les lois, les elude par ruse ou par 
 adresse, blesse les interets de tons ; il se rend iudigue de leur 
 bienveillance et de leur estime. 
 
 8. C'est sur le raaintien des proprietes que reposent la culture des 
 terres, toutes les productions, tout moyen de travail et tout I'ordre 
 social. 
 
 9. Tout citoyeu doit ses services a la patrie et au uiaintien de la 
 liberte, de Tegalite et de la propriete, toutes les fois que la loi 
 I'appelle a les defendre. 
 
 Constitution de la Republique FKANgAiSE du 4 Xov., 1848. 
 
 PR^AMBULE. 
 
 En presence de Dieu et au nom du peuple fran^ais, I'Asseniblee 
 nationale proclame : — 
 
 1. La France s'est constituee en Republique. En adoptant cette 
 forme definitive de gouvernement, elle s'est propose pour but de 
 marcher plus librement dans la voie du progres et de la civilisation, 
 d'assurer una repartition de plus en plus equitable des charges et des 
 avantages de la societe, d'augmenter I'aisance de chacun par la 
 reduction graduee des depenses publiques et des impots, et do 
 faire parvenir tons les citoyens, sans nouvelle commotion, par I'actiou 
 successive et constants des institutions et des lois, k un degre 
 toujours plus eleve de la moralite, de lumieres et de bien-etre. 
 
 2. La Republique francaise est democratique, una et indivisible. 
 
 3. Elle reconnaitdes droits et des devoirs anterieurs et superieurs 
 aux lois positives. 
 
 4. Elle a pour principe la Liberte, I'Egalite et la Fraternite. Kilo 
 a pour base la Familla, le Travail, la Propriete, I'Ordre public. 
 
 5. Elle respecte les nationalites etrangeres, comme elle entend 
 faire respecter la sienne ; n'entreprend aucuue guerre dans les vues 
 de conquete, et n'emploie jamais ses forces contre la liliHiti'- d'aucun 
 peuple. 
 
 6. Des devoirs reciproques obligent les citoyens euvers la 
 Republique, et la Republique euvers les citoyens. 
 
 7. Les citoyens doiveut aimer la patrie, servir la Republique, la 
 defendre au prix de leur vie, participer aux charges de TEtat en
 
 300 APPENDIX 
 
 proportion de leur fortune ; ils doivent s'assurer, par le travail, des 
 moyens d'existence, et par la prevoyance, des ressources pour 
 I'avenir ; ils doivent concourir au bien-etre commun en s'entr'aidant 
 fraternellement les uns las autres, et a I'ordre general en observant 
 les lois moi'ales et les lois ecrites qui regissent la societe, la famille et 
 I'individu. 
 
 8. La Republique doit proteger le citoyen dans sa personne, sa 
 famille, sa religion, sa propriete, son travail, et mettre a la portee de 
 cliacun I'instruction indispensable a tons les homines ; elle doit, par 
 une assistance fraternelle, assurer I'existence des citoyens necessiteux, 
 soit en leur procurant du travail dans les limites de ses ressources, 
 soit en donnant, a defaut de la famille, des secours a ceux qui sont 
 hors d'etat de travailler. 
 
 En vue de I'accomplissement de tous ces devoirs, et pour la garantie 
 de tous ces droits, I'Assemblee nationale, fidele aux traditions des 
 grandes assemblees qui ont inaugure la revolution fran^aise, decrete, 
 ainsi qu'il suit, la Constitution de la Republique.
 
 INDEX 
 
 This index is only intended to supplement the analytical table of contents. 
 n after the niimber of a page indicates that the reference is to a footnote. 
 
 Addis and Arnold, Catholic Dictio7iary, 
 Id'dn. 
 
 Ahasuerus, 240. 
 
 Alabama, 23H, 245. 
 
 Alcidamas, 25, 'dUn. 
 
 .Alexandria, 56. 
 
 Alsace, 2ii4«. 
 
 America, United States of : Civil War, 
 260, 264. Constitution, 3, 4, 16, 115, 
 203«, 229, 241, 242, 265. Declara- 
 tion of Independence, 4, 11, 45, 239, 
 289, 290. <S'ee names of separate 
 States and Territories. 
 
 Anarchists, 19, 52, 65-67. 
 
 Andrew, King (of Hungary), 239. 
 
 Anglicans, 174, 184, 198. 
 
 Anglo-Indian Code, 181«. 
 
 Antisthenes, 32, 33. 
 
 Aquinas, Thomas, 39, 40. 41, 42, 43, 
 46, 88, 119, 125, 161-163, 166n, 170«, 
 171. 
 
 Aristotle, 7, 22w, 25, 26, 27-32, 34, 35, 
 38, 39, 43, 4y, 49, 86, 105«, 125, 126, 
 181w, 247, 273«, 274«. 
 
 Aristophanes, 21, 109. 
 
 Arkansas, 178, 18Un, 198. 
 
 Arnold, Matthew, 64. 
 
 Ataulf us. The Goth, 62??. 
 
 Athens, 22, 31, 56, 89, 168, 182, 248. 
 
 Augustine, 39. 
 
 Aurelius, Marcus, 35. 
 
 Austin, John, 25, 73, 84. 
 
 Austria, 260//. 
 
 Bacon, F., 138. 
 
 Bain, Prof., 85. 
 
 Ball, .Jolin. 8. 
 
 Bancroft, History of United States, 4. 
 
 Baptists, 67, 174//, 184. 
 
 Bastille, Key of the, 3. 
 
 Beccaria, 87. 
 
 Beethoven, 58. 
 
 Belgium, 123, 211. 
 
 Bentham, 25, 73, 84, 87, 94, 95, 106. 
 
 109, 150, 239, 249, 277, 279. 
 Bible, The, 7, 10, 13, 79, 90, 174, 180, 
 
 188. 
 Birmingham, 137. 
 
 Bluntschli, 98. 
 
 Boissel, 127. 
 
 Bolingbroke, 45. 
 
 Bonar, James, 29n, 45//, 253//. 
 
 Booth, Charles, 225//, 261. 
 
 Bosanquet, B., 58//. 
 
 Bossuet, 67. 
 
 Boston, 201. 
 
 Borgeaud, Charles, 14//, 51//, 116//. 
 
 Boui'ne, Fox, 6//, 12//, 91//. 
 
 Boutmy, An. 
 
 Braxfield, Lord, 256//. 
 
 Breda, Declaration of, 200. 
 
 Britain, Great, 151-155, 180, ISl, 
 
 211-214. 
 British Constitution, 50, 115, 116, 281. 
 Browning, Robert, 67//, 285. 
 Bruno, Giordano, 163//. 
 Bunyan, 67. 
 
 Burke, Edmund, 5, 6, 10, 12, 17. 
 Burleigh, Lord, 187, 198, 199, 205. 
 Burnet, Bishop, 138. 
 Busher, Leonard, 174//, 201. 
 Butler, Bishop, 85, 86. 
 
 California, 256, 
 
 Callicles, 26, 29. 
 
 Calvin, John, 13, 50. 
 
 Calvinism, 18, 19. 
 
 Cambyses, 26//. 
 
 Carlyle, T., 67, 95. 
 
 Carpenter, Edward, 53//, 58, 60, 61, 68, 
 
 269. 
 Cartwright, 220//. 
 Catholic, nee Koniaii (!atlio]ic. 
 Catholic Dictionarij quoted. 163//. 
 Cato, 125. 
 Celts, 57. 
 
 CharlesIL, 2CX), 201. 
 Christianity, 35, 43, 53, 12.5, 169. 172. 
 
 173, 189, 254, 268//, 2S4. 
 Cicero, 35, 36, 39, 100//. 
 Clarke : The Clarke /'aper^t. S//. 
 Clarke, William, .52//. 
 Clifford, Prof., 99. 273. 
 Comte, Auguste. 110//. 
 Condorcet, 230, 260. 
 Connecticut, 201, 244.
 
 302 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Constantine, 184. 
 
 Copernicus, 101. 
 
 Cotterill, H. B., 61>«. 
 
 Cotton, John, 202. 
 
 Cowper, W., 68, 69. 
 
 Cromwell, Oliver, 8, 10, 200. 
 
 Cynics, 26/?, 34, 35, 41m, 53, 65, 114. 
 
 Deists, 13, 43, 44, 45. 
 
 Democritus, 26w. 
 
 Demosthenes, 30h. 
 
 Dicey, Prof., 152, 155, 211. 
 
 Dickens, Charles, Nicliolas XkJcelbi/ 
 
 quoted, 20. 
 Diogenes the Cynic, 33. 
 Diogenes Laertius, 33. 
 Donaldson, Principal, ll'In. 
 Druidism, 160. 
 Dutch, The, at the Cape, 268. 
 
 Edmunds-Tucker Law, 207, 209. 
 Edwards, Thomas, author of Gan- 
 
 qrcena, 9. 
 Egypt, -26, 231. 
 Elizabeth, Queen, 177, 198. 
 England, " Bill of Rights " of 1689, 
 
 6, 11. 
 England, Church of, see Anglican. 
 English Government, 50. 
 English Houses of Parliament, 153. 
 English Revolutions of 17th cent., 5, 
 
 17, 51, 241h. 
 Empedocles, 30«. 
 Epictetus, 35. 
 
 Erigena, Joannes Scotus, 71, 72k. 
 Espinasse, 70«, 1.53«. 
 Eui'ipides, 26. 
 
 Fatalism, 18. 
 
 Fester, R., bin. 
 
 Fichte, 51. 
 
 Filmer, Sir R., author of Patriarcha, 
 
 8, 91, 92. 
 Firth, C. H., 8», 9«, 2.55». 
 Fisher, Marv, 201. 
 Fiske, J., quoted, 184h, 201. 
 Fletcher of Saltoun, 225h. 
 Florence, 58. 
 Fowler, Prof. T., 273n. 
 Fox, George, 201. 
 France, 3, 5, 237. 
 Franklin, Benjamin, 4»«. 
 Frederick the Great, 70. 
 French, Declarations of Rights, 3, 141, 
 
 145, 146, 1.50, 1.51, 1.58, 210, 211, 229. 
 
 230, 238, 239, 244, 245, 265, 272. See 
 
 Appendix, 290-300. 
 French Law, 41. 
 
 Gallio,.169. 
 
 Galton, F., 172h. 
 
 Gamaliel, 194, 
 
 Geneva, .50, .56, 1.53», 178, 220. 
 
 George, Henry, 270, 271. 
 
 Girondists 266. 
 
 Godwin, William, 44, 165«. 
 
 Gorgias, 21, 32. 
 
 Gospels, The, 170, 171. 
 
 Goths, 62. 
 
 Gregory I., 44. 
 
 Gregory VII., 220«, 240. 
 
 Grote, George, 21, 23. 
 
 Grotius, 37, 39, 83«, 90, 94, 241«, 268. 
 
 Hallam, Henry, 198, 220h. 
 
 Halsbury, Lord, 15. 
 
 Hardy, E. G., 169. 
 
 Hastie, Translation of 'Kant's Philoso- 
 
 j)hii of Laic, 142. 
 Hedonism, 114. See Utilitarianism, 
 Hegel, 51, 66, 70«. 
 Heme, Heinricli, 75h. 
 Herbert, Auberon, 15, 187. 
 Herodotus, 26. 
 Hobbes. Thomas, 11, 14, 24, 25, 42, 83, 
 
 84, 123, 142, 245, 277. 
 Hodgkin, T., 62n. 
 Holland, 123. 
 Holland. Prof., 78. 
 Hood, Thomas, 125. 
 Hooker, Richard, 39, 67, 176, 246. 
 Hudson, Judge J. H., 141w. 
 Hungary, 239. 
 Huxley, Prof., 25, 267h, 275. 
 
 Idaho, 208, 209. 
 Independents, 184, 202. 
 India, 169, 181h, 234, 236. 
 International Law, 36, 123. 
 Intuitionists, 36, 86, 88«. 
 Ionia, 56. 
 
 Ireton, 10, 255, 2.56. 
 Italy, 57, 123, KUm. 
 
 .Jacobin Club, 51, 127, 230, 265. 
 
 James I., 138. 
 
 Janet, Paul, quoted, 4«, 15«. 
 
 Jefferson, Thoinas, 3, 45. 
 
 Jesuits, 177, 180, 187, 188, 199, 240. 
 
 Jews, 169, 218«, 240. 
 
 Johnson, Samuel, 10, 114«, 152«, 195«. 
 
 Jowett, Prof., 33/?, 49n. 
 
 Jus Gentium, 36, 37. 
 
 Jus Divinum VoiuntMrium, 83». 
 
 Jus Naturale, see especially Chapter 
 
 IL 
 Justinian, 7, 38, 41. 
 
 Kansas, 264. 
 
 Kant, 34, 51, 72«, 141, 112. 192, 2.52, 
 
 2.53, 273/?, 285. 
 Kentucky, 264w. 
 Kepler, 72/?. 
 Kidd, Benjamin, 111/?. 
 
 Lafayette, 3. 
 
 Laud, Abp., 164/?. 205. 
 
 Lecky, W. H., 125/?, 127. 
 
 Leo XIII., 270. 
 
 Le Play, 63/?.
 
 INDEX 
 
 303 
 
 Lesley, Bishop, \lln. 
 
 Leslie, T. E. Cliffe, 43«. 
 
 Levellei-s, The, 9, 12. 
 
 Lewis, Sir G. C, 136. 
 
 Lilburn, John, 9. 
 
 Littre, 71. 
 
 Locke, John, 6, 11, 14, 24. 25, 39, 42, 
 51, 90-92, 94, 135, 142, 146, 154, 173- 
 176. 184, 185, 186, 198, 239, 246, 266, 
 268-270. 
 
 Lorimer, Prof. J., 61w, 92, 94, 128w, 233. 
 
 Lorraine, 234>«. 
 
 Louis X. of France, 3S«. 
 
 Louis XVI., 4«. 
 
 Lowell, J. il., quoted, 236«. 
 
 Luther, 90h. 
 
 Lycophron, 25. 
 
 Macaulay, Lord, 154. 
 
 Machiavelli, 31. 
 
 Mackay, Charles, 23l«. 
 
 Maine, Sir H. S.,.16, 37, 38, 41, 95«, 
 
 104«, 268w. 
 Manchester School, 65. 
 Mansfield, Lord, 151. 
 Martineau, Dr., 86. 
 Maryland, 178. 
 Massachusetts, 149, 178, 179«, 201, 
 
 256«. 
 Massilia, 126. 
 Michelet, Jules, 38h. 
 Mill, J. S., 87, 94, 96, 114, 167, 249, 
 
 273. 
 Milton, J., 44«, 152?«, 153, 154, 175. 
 Mississippi, State of, 178, 24.5. 
 Mohammedans, 22, 201. 
 Montesquieu, 50. 
 More, Sir Thomas, 126, 198, 201. 
 Mormonism, 93, 160, 178, 196«, 202- 
 
 209. 
 Morris, William, .58. 
 Moyle, J. B., Editor of Justinian's 
 
 Imtifutes, 41??. 
 Muir, Thomas, Trial of, 256. 
 Muirhead, Prof., 37h, 40??,. 
 
 Natural Theology, 44, 45. 
 
 Napoleon, 232. 
 
 Neo-Platonism, 34, 72??. 
 
 Nero, 164»?. 
 
 Nettleship, Henrv, 37??. 
 
 Neuchatol, 180??, 220. 
 
 Nevada, 178. 
 
 Newman, John Henry, 67, 189??. 
 
 North Carolina, 178. 
 
 " Normanism," 8. 
 
 Nimrod, 43, 44??. 
 
 O'Brien, M. D., 135. 
 
 Orosiua, 62m. 
 
 Orthodox (Greek) Church, 206??. 
 
 Ostrogorski, Mights of Women, 260m. 
 
 Paine, Thomas, 3, 12, 15, 16, 17, 21, 
 157, 158, 260. 
 
 Party-government, 280. 
 
 Pascal, 67. 
 
 Patriotism, 279. 
 
 Paul, the Apostle, 80??, 89, 168, 172??. 
 
 Paulus, the Jurist, 268. 
 
 Pennsylvania, 178, 184??. 
 
 Persian War, 22. 
 
 Personality, 102. 
 
 Pessimism, 27, 128, 129, 282-284. 
 
 Philadelphia Congress, 11. 
 
 Philip of Hasse, 90??. 
 
 Physiocrats, 45. 
 
 Pitt, William, 165??. 
 
 Pius v., 177. . 
 
 Pius IX., 164. 
 
 Plato, 14, 21, 23, 24, 25, 28, 29, 33, 35 
 
 56??, 65, 85, 101, 126, 136, 191, 262, 
 
 265, 285. 
 Plymouth (New England), Colony of, 
 
 257. 
 Pollock, Sir F., 168. 
 Poland, 128, 232. 
 Pope, Alexander, 26??, 43, 44, 45. 
 Population question, 64, 127-134, 2-^5 
 
 231, 261, 262, 280. 
 Poulton, E. B., 54??. 
 Presbyterians, 174. 184, 202. 
 Preston, Howard W., 11??. 
 Price, Di-. Richard, 6. 
 Progress, 111-114, 281. 
 Protagoras, 21. 
 Protestantism, 10, 13, 39, 43, 79, 90, 
 
 185. 
 Providence, Colony of, 201, 202. 
 Prussia, 234, 256. 
 Pufendorf, 39. 
 Punishment, 120-122. 
 Puritans, The, 10, 13, 51, 177. 
 
 Quakers, The, 180, 184, 201. 
 Qainet, Edgar, 53. 
 
 Ramsay, Prof. W. M., 169??. 
 Rationalism, 13, 18, 27, 88, 185, 189. 
 Referendum. See Switzerland. 
 Reformation, Tte, 39, 43. 183, 277. 
 Renaissance, The, 43, 277. 
 Renan, E., 163??, 186. 
 Rhode Island (U.S.A.), 4, 201. 
 Rickaby, Father, 40, 88, 89, 90, 12t], 
 • 162??, 163-166. 
 Robertson, J. M., 101??. 
 Robespierre, 1.5, 45, 51, 127, 265. 
 Roman Catholics, 67, 79, 173-178. 181. 
 Roman Emiiire, 7, 62??, 105, 149, 16.S, 
 
 169, 170, 177, 183. 
 Roman Law, 36-39, 81. 
 Rome, 11, 12??, 62??, 163??. 
 Romans, The, 31, 35, 37, H'^, 39, 40, 41, 
 
 45. 
 Rousseau, .L .T., 6, 11, 1.3, 2.5, 34. 39, 
 
 43, 44, 46, 48-51, 53, .56, .58, 68, 76, 
 
 87, 99, 176, 186, 240, 2-17. 
 Rusk in, .Tolin, 57??, 68??. 
 Russia, 6.5.
 
 304 
 
 INDEX 
 
 St. Just, 51. 
 
 Salamis. 22. 
 
 Salt, H.'S., 67, 6'^, lOS, 109, 110, 132«. 
 
 Salter, W.M., 107«. 
 
 Salvation Army, 180, 277«. 
 
 Saxons, 57. 
 
 Scholasticism, 42, 43. 
 
 Schopenhauer, A., 1]0. 
 
 Schurman, J. G., 160«. 
 
 Scotland, 140 ; Free Church of, 220. 
 
 Scotus, Joannes (Erigena), 71, 72«. 
 
 Sellar, W. Y.. 57«. 
 
 Shellej'. P. B.' 67. 69, 90w, 93, 94. 
 
 Sidgwick. Henry, 89n, 97, 98, lOO. 
 
 Slavery, 38, 103, 104, 247. 
 
 Smith, Adam. 45. 
 
 Smith, J. C, 195«. 
 
 Smith, Joseph, 207. 
 
 Socrates, 21. 32, 96, 114, 168, 183, 265. 
 
 South Carolina, 141«. 178, 241, 242. 
 
 Southey, R., 198. 
 
 Sophists, The, 21-27, 29, 32, 41w, 182, 
 183. 
 
 Sophocles, Antigone, 30. 
 
 Spain, 187, 232. 
 
 Spanish Conquests in America, 268«. 
 
 Spencer, Herbert, 14, 15, 24, 45. 46, 
 113, 139. 141, 142, 187, 234«, 235«, 
 
 Spinoza, 72, 84. 119, 233. [249. 
 
 Stephen, Sir J.' F., 138. 
 
 Stephenson, George, 59. 
 
 Stewart, J. A., 28«. 
 
 Stobseus, 25w. 
 
 Stoics, The, 20, &4, 35, 36, 283. 
 
 Strozzi, Philip, 125. 
 
 Suarez, 42, 44. 
 
 Swift, Dean, 138. 
 
 Switzerland, 220. 232; Federal Con- 
 stitution of, 178-180, 183, 240; The 
 Referendum, 115, 116«, 281. See 
 names of Cantons. 
 
 Tacitus, 68, 135«. 
 Tarde, G., 173w, 248h. 
 Taylor, Jeremy, 67. 
 Tennessee. 178. 
 
 Tennyson. 67«, 285. 
 
 Texas, 178. 
 
 Thomas Aquinas, see Aquinas. 
 
 Thoreau, H., 53. 
 
 Thi-asymachus, 25. 
 
 Ticino, 232. 
 
 Timothy, Epistles to, 170w, 206». 
 
 Tit^is, Epistle to, 162, 170«, 171. 
 
 Tolstoi, Count, 161. 
 
 Tuscany, 123. 
 
 Ulpian, 88, 40, 41w, 76, 88, 245. 
 Utah, 205, 207. 
 
 Utilitarianism, 87, 93, 94-101, 249-251, 
 273. 
 
 Vaud, 220, 232. 
 
 Venice, 11 : Venetian Republic, 232. 
 
 Vincent, Prof., 179«, 220. 
 
 Virginia, 4, 5. 257 ; Declaration of 
 
 Rights, 287-289 (Appendix). 
 Voigt, Jus Naturale, etc., 37w, 41??. 
 Voltaire, 15«, 26w, 7'Oh, 153, 197. 
 
 Wallace, Prof. W., 284. 
 
 Washington, George, 3. 
 
 Watt, James, 59. 
 
 Webb, Clement C. J., 72w. 
 
 Webb, Mr. and Mrs. Sidney, 223h. 
 
 Welldon, Dr., Translation of Ari!>t. 
 
 FoL, 48». 
 Weismann, Prof., 57. 
 Westermarck, E., 92w. 
 Whitman, Walt, 52«, 53, 56. 64. 
 Williams, Roger. 201, 202. 
 Wilson, Sir R. K., 136, 137. 
 Wollstonecraft, Marv, 260. 
 Women's Rights, 133, 134, 207, 257, 
 
 259-262. 
 Wordsworth, W., 147. 232. 
 Wycliffe, John, 7, 33.' 
 Wyse, John, 14«. 
 
 Xenophanes, 23. 
 
 Zeller, 26«, 35«. 
 
 Butler & Tanner The Selwood Printing Works, Fromc, and London.
 
 ^
 
 :*?;.-r. 

 
 AA 001 129 803 
 
 Library Bureau Cat. No. 1137 
 
 
 ^i. V ■ 
 
 ■■ V A- -. ■; V, / ', .• : 
 
 
 
 
 HR*»^'' :'r. 
 
 .?■■"'' 
 
 ^H^'.-e^v^.. -^^ 
 
 
 ^^Bj<- ••^/>' 
 
 
 
 
 ^^H'*. i"^ 
 
 
 ^■I'Vi r. . 
 
 
 ^K>-,'-/^; - '- 
 
 
 
 
 ^^I^HE^ ' 
 
 
 ^■■Rr ' w . 
 
 
 mPijd>, * .rV 
 
 
 ^;|il''-»'-|l, . 
 
 
 Mv